Skip to main content

Full text of "The principle of teleology in the critical philosophy of Kant"

See other formats


Qass_ 

Book  _JDa_/A_ii_ 


/  9- 


THE 


PRINCIPLE  OF  TELEOLOGY 


The  Critical  Philosophy  of  Kant 


DAVID  R.  MAJOR 

Formerly  Scholar  and  Fellow  in  the  Sage  School  of 
Philosophy,  Cornell  University 


Ithaca,  N.  Y. 

Andrus  &  Church 

1897 


CONTENTS 


PAGE 

PART  I.— Historic al. 

\  I.  Development  of  Kant's  doctrine  of  the  three-fold  na- 
ture of  mind, ....  i 

\  2.  Changes  in  the  form  and  problem  of  the  third  Critique,  16 

PART  II. — The  Critique  of  Judgment  as  a  mediation  of 
Kant's  theoretical  and  practical  Philosophy. 

\  I.  Formal  and  real  mediation  distinguished, 30 

\  2.  Relation  of  the  theoretical  and  practical  philosophy,  34 

\  3.  Kant's  theory  of  the  Beautiful, 49 

(a)  The  doctrine  of  harmony, 6r 

(b)  Distinction  between  beauty  and  perfection,  ...  68 
fc)  The  doctrine  of  ' '  purposiyeness  without  purpose, ' '  74 

(d)  Universality  and  necessity  of  aesthetic  judgments,  76 

(e)  The  beautiful  object  a  union  of  freedom  and  na- 

ture,    79 

\  4.  Design  in  organic  nature, 81 

\  5.  Relation  of  the  principle  of  Teleology  to  Kant's  ethical 

doctrines 8q 


PREFACE. 


This  Essay  consists  of  two  parts  :  the  first  being  his- 
torical ;  the  second,  expository  and  critical.  In  the  his- 
torical part,  an  effort  has  been  made  to  trace  the  influ- 
ences and  steps  which  led  to  the  displacement  of  Aris- 
totle's bipartite  division  of  the  fundamental  powers  of 
mind  by  the  present  generally  accepted  division  into 
Intellect,  Feeling,  and  Will.  It  is  also  shown  in  Part  I 
that  Kant's  original  plan  comprised  only  the  critiques  of 
pure  and  practical  philosophy,  and  that  the  third  Critique 
was  designed  at  a  later  time,  to  establish  a  priori  prin- 
ciples for  the  newly  discoved  faculty  of  Feeling.  Final- 
ly, it  is  maintained  that  Kant  combined  the  Critique  of 
Teleology  with  the  Critique  of  Taste,  and  issued  them 
under  a  common  title — the  Critique  of  Judgment — be- 
cause both  works  center  about  the  notion  of  purposive- 
ness,  or  design.  Part  II  is  devoted  to  a  consideration  of 
the  Critique  of  Judgment  as  a  mediating  link  between 
the  critiques  of  pure  and  practical  philosophy  ;  or,  if 
one  is  thinking  of  the  content — the  inner  nature  of 
three  Critiques — the  object  is  to  consider  the  principle 
of  teleology,  which  the  Critique  of  Judgment  illustrates, 
as  a  means  of  mediating  the  modes  of  thought  prevail- 
ing in  the  realms  of  freedom  and  nature. 

The  edition  of  Kant's  works  by  Rosenkranz  and 
Schubert  is  referred  to  as  R.,  and  Hartenstein's  second 
edition  is  indicated  by  the  letter  H.  In  the  same  way 
references  have  been  made  to  Max  Miiller's  translation 


vi  Preface. 

of  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason,  and  Bernard's  transla- 
tion of  the  Critique  of  fudgment  as  M.  and  B.,  res- 
pectively. 

I  am,  of  course,  indebted  to  many  authors  and  books 
for  help  and  suggestion  on  particular  points,  and  in 
most  cases  I  have  been  able  to  acknowledge  this  in- 
debtedness by  foot-notes.  My  obligations  to  Professor 
Caird's,  The  Critical  Philosophy  of  Immanuel  Kant,  are, 
however,  so  great  as  to  require  special  acknowledgement. 
I  am  also  glad  to  have  this  opportunity  of  expressing 
my  gratitude  to  all  the  professors  under  whom  I  studied 
while  a  member  of  the  graduate  department  of  Cornell 
University.  And,  in  particular,  I  wish  to  express  my  ob- 
ligations to  Professor  J.  E.  Creighton  for  encouragement 
and  direction  in  the  preparation  of  this  work. 

D..  Rr  M.. 

Ithaca,  N.  Y.,  August,  1897.- 


PART  I. 
HISTORICAL. 

§  I.    DEVELOPMENT   OF    KANT'S    DOCTRINE   OF   THE 
THREE-FOLD    NATURE    OF    MIND. 

The  division  of  the  Critical  Philosophy  into  three 
parts  rests  upon  Kant's  recognition  of  three  distinct 
mental  faculties — Intellect,  Feeling,  and  Will.  That 
Kant  was  aware  of  the  influence  of  his  psychology  in 
determining  the  main  lines  or  divisions  of  his  investiga- 
tions, is  clearly  shown  by  the  following  sentences  from 
a  letter  to  Reinhold,  1787  :  "  I  am  at  present  engaged  in 
a  Critique  of  Taste  and  have  in  this  way  been  led  to 
the  discovery  of  another  kind  of  a  priori  principles  than 
I  had  formerly  recognized.  For  the  faculties  of  the 
mind  are  three ;  the  faculty  of  knowledge,  the  feeling 
of  pleasure  and  pain,  and  the  will.  I  have  discovered 
a  priori  principles  for  the  first  of  these  in  the  Critique  of 
Pure  Reason,  and  for  the  third,  in  the  Critique  of  Prac- 
tical Reason  ;  but  my  search  for  similar  principles  for 
the  second  seemed  at  first  fruitless."1  Many  passages 
similar  to  the  extract  just  quoted  from  the  letter  to 
Reinhold  may  be  found  in  the  Critique  of  fudgment, 
and  also  in  the  treatise  Ueber  Philosophie  iiberhaupt, 
which  was  published  in  1794.  The  following  from  §  3 
of  the  Introduction  to  the  former  work  is  typical  :  "  All 
the  faculties  or  capacities  of  the  mind  can  be  reduced  to 
three,  which  cannot  be  any  further  derived  from  one 

1 R.  XI.   86.  H.  VIII.    739  f.  Caird,  Critical  Philosophy  of  Kant. 
II.  pp.  406  f. 


2  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

common  ground  :  The  faculty  of  knowledge,  the  feeling 
of  pleasure  and  pain,  and  the  faculty  of  desire.  For  the 
faculty  of  knowing  the  Understanding  is  alone  a  priori 
legislative  by  means  of  natural  concepts.  For  the  faculty 
of  desire  the  Reason  is  alone  a  priori  legislative.  We 
may  suppose,  therefore,  that  Judgment  which  stands 
midway  between  Understanding  and  Reason  may  con- 
tain a  priori  principles  for  feeling."  For  each  of  the 
three  faculties,  Intellect,  Feeling,  and  Will,  there  are, 
according  to  Kant's  final  statement,  a  priori  principles 
of  activity ;  it  is  the  province  of  the  three  Critiques  to 
exhibit  and  explain  those  principles.  In  its  completed 
form,  therefore,  the  Critical  Philosophy  comprised  three 
works  corresponding  to  the  three  mental  powers  enu- 
merated above. 

Although  it  is  true  that  the  division  of  the  Critical 
Philosophy  into  three  parts  rests  upon  the  three-fold  di- 
vision of  mind,  and  that  each  Critique  has  special  refer- 
ence to  one  particular  faculty,  it  would  be  quite  mistaken 
to  suppose  that  Kant  consciously  set  about  the  critical 
inquiry,  to  discover,  if  possible,  a  priori  principles  for 
each  of  the  three  mental  faculties.  We  know,  on  the 
contrary,  that  the  original  plan  comprised  only  a  Cri- 
tique of  theoretical  philosophy,  and  a  Critique  of  practical 
philosophy,  corresponding  to  the  faculties  of  cognition 
and  desire.  The  proof  of  this  is  derived  from  the  famous 
letter  to  Herz  of  1772.  Kant's  words  there  are:  "I 
am  planning  a  work  under  the  title,  The  limits  of  Sen- 
sibility and  Reason.  The  work  will  consist  of  two  parts, 
a  theoretical  and  a  practical.  The  first  falls  into  two 
sections :  first,  Phenomenology  in  general  ;  and  second, 
the  nature  and  methods  of  Metaphysics.  The  second, 
likewise,  falls  into  two  parts  :  first,  the  general  princi- 
ples of  feeling,  of  taste  and  of  sensuous  desires  ;  second, 


Development  of  Kanfs  Psychology.  3 

the  foundations  of  morality."1  It  is  here  distinctly 
stated  that  the  work  contemplated  is  to  consist  of  a 
theoretical  and  a  practical  part,  and  although  Kant's 
plans  were  greatly  changed  subsequently,  the  Critiques 
of  pure  and  practical  reason  are  clearly  foreshadowed  in 
the  passage  just  quoted.  But  it  was  not  until  Kant  came 
to  recognize  the  importance  of  the  feeling  life,  and  finally 
to  coordinate  Intellect,  Feeling,  and  Will,  that  he 
conceived  the  plan  of  writing  a  third  Critique  dealing 
specially  with  Feeling  as  the  completion  of  his  system. 
Only  after  a  vast  amount  of  investigation  and  reflection 
by  himself  and  his  contemporaries  upon  the  emotional  ex- 
perience did  Feeling  come  to  be  differentiated  from  In- 
tellect and  Will,  and  not  until  Feeling  had  been  thus 
marked  off  from  and  coordinated  with  those  faculties  did 
Kant  see  the  necessity  of  assigning  to  it  also  a  priori 
principles  of  activity.2  It  is  now  proposed  to  set  forth, 
briefly,  the  steps  and  influences  by  which  Kant  came  to 
accord  Feeling  a  place  beside  Intellect  and  Will. 

Before  the  middle  of  the  18th  century,  roughly  speak- 
ing, Psychologists  had  recognized  only  two  main  mental 
faculties — Cognition  and  Desire.  To  quote  Sir  William 
Hamilton  :  "  The  feelings  were  not  recognized  by  any 
philosophers  as  the  manifestation  of  any  fundamental 
power.  The  distinction  taken  in  the  Peripatetic  School 
by  which  the  mental  modifications  were  divided  into 
Cognitive  or  Appetent  and  the  consequent  reduction  of 

1  H.,  VIII,  688,  f. 

2  Another  proof  that  Kant's  plan  did  not,  at  first,  include  a  Critique 
of  Taste  is  found  in  a  note  to  page  21  of  the  first  edition  to  the  K.  d. 
r.  V.  In  this  note  Kant  discouraged  as  vain  all  endeavors  to  bring 
the  critical  judgment  of  the  beautiful  to  rational  principles.  At  that 
time  he  regarded  the  search  for  a  priori  principles  of  feeling  as  hope- 
less. In  the  second  edition  of  the  K.  d.  r.  V.,  the  note  is  changed  so 
as  to  read,  'Judgments  of  taste  are  in  their  principal  sources  empiri- 
cal. ' 


4  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

all  faculties  to  the  faatltas  cognoscendi  and  the  facie  lias 
appetendi  was  the  distinction  which  was  long  most  uni- 
versally prevalent."1  Feeling  was  regarded  either  as  a 
particular  kind  of  intellectual  consciousness,  a  lower 
kind  of  knowledge  ;  or  it  was  confounded  with  desire  or 
impulse.  But  during  the  half  century  immediately  fol- 
lowing 1740 — a  period  which  is  characterized  by  histor- 
ians as  one  of  great  psychological  ( activity  '  — Feeling 
came  to  be  regarded  as  an  independent  mental  function, 
and  was  assigned  a  place  along  side  Intellect  and  Will. 
The  activity  in  psychology  referred  to,  doubtless  was 
caused  by,  or  rather  was  a  part  of  the  wave  of  individ- 
ualism that  swept  over  Europe  in  the  latter  part  of  the 
1 8th  century.  The  same  individualistic  movement,  the 
same  subjectivism  that  revolted  against  custom  and  au- 
thority might  naturally  be  expected  to  revolt  against  met- 
aphysic.  Interest  in  theories  of  the  universe,  its  nature 
and  origin,  was  overshadowed  by  enthusiasm  for  man 
the  individual.  The  watchword  of  the  age  was,  "  the 
proper  study  of  mankind  is  man."  Man,  his  happiness, 
his  welfare  present  and  future,  his  virtues  and  vices, 
strength  and  foibles,  became  the  center  of  interest  for  the 
illuminationists.  It  is  not  surprising,  therefore,  that  a 
part  of  this  grand  movement  should  find  expression  in 
most  searching  analyses  of  individual  psychical  states. 
There  thus  sprang  up  a  luxuriant  growth  of  psychologi- 
cal literature.  One  need  only  mention  the  works  of  Men- 
delssohn, Sulzer  and  Tetens  in  Germany  ;  those  of  Bon- 
net, Condillac,  DeTracy,  Helvetius,  and  Cabanis  among 
French  writers  as  examples  of  a  literature  rich  in  observa- 
tions and  analyses  of  the  individual  psychical  states. 
It  was  during  this  period  of  great  psychological  interest 
that  Feeling  attained  a  rank  equal  with  Intellect  and 

1  Hamilton,  Lectures  on  Metaphysic,  Lecture  41. 


Development  of  Kanfs  Psychology.  5 

Will.     It  was  this  period  that  saw  the  displacement  of 
the  bipartite  division  of  mind  by  the  tripartite. 

Our  effort  to  trace  the  steps  which  led  to  this  change 
must  take  account  first  of  the  work  of  Leibnitz.  For  while 
there  is  no  disposition  on  the  part  of  that  philosopher  to 
break  with  the  old  division,  yet  the  investigations  which 
led  to  the  new  classification  of  the  mental  powers,  and 
especially  to  the  reflection  upon  the  feeling  of  beauty 
and  pleasure-pain  experience,  are  directly  traceable  to 
the  influence  of  his  doctrines.  To  understand  Leibnitz's 
influence  upon  subsequent  psychology  and  aesthetics  it 
is  necessary  to  recall  a  few  of  the  leading  doctrines  of 
his  philosophy.  In  the  first  place,  he  maintained  that 
the  world  is  composed  of  an  infinite  number  of  harmoni- 
ously related  parts  and  that  true  knowledge  consists  in 
accurately  mirroring  that  harmony.  In  the  second 
place,  we  may  recall  Leibnitz's  doctrine  that  there  are 
three  stages  of  clearness  with  which  the  mind  mirrors  the 
harmony  and  perfection  of  the  world.1  Corresponding  to 
the  first  stage  we  have  obscure  perceptions  as  in  a  dream- 
less sleep  or  in  a  swoon  ;  corresponding  to  the  second 
stage  we  have  confused  perceptions  as  "when  one  hears 
the  roar  of  the  sea  which  strikes  one  when  on  the  shore, 
but  does  not  perceive  that  the  roar  is  made  up  of  an  in- 
finite number  of  little  noises."2  We  also  perceive  con- 
fusedly when  we  are  unable  to  see  that  a  given  color  is 

1  The  reader  will  notice  that  this  account  leaves  out  of  view  Leib- 
nitz's doctrine  of  the  continuity  of  all  being,  the  theory  that  from  the 
lowest  monad  to  the  highest  there  is  a  gradual  increase  in  clearness  of 
perception.  It  would  be  misleading  to  say  that  Leibnitz  made  a  sharp 
line  of  division  between  the  perceptions  denominated  obscure,  con- 
fused, clear  and  distinct.  On  the  contrary,  each  class  shades  off  into 
those  near  it  as  dawn  into  daylight.  The  words  obscure,  clear,  etc., 
are  used  only  to  mark  prominent  stages  in  the  scale  of  perceptual  be- 
ing. 

2Gerhardt,  Leibnitz's  Schriften  v.  47.     Duncan's  Trans.,  p.  293. 


6  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

made  by  mixing  two  different  colors,  e.g.,  we  do  not  see 
that  green  is  caused  by  mixing  yellow  and  blue.  The 
highest  stage  of  perception  is  the  stage  of  knowledge,  or 
truth,  in  which  the  mind  faithfully  and  adequately  rep- 
resents the  external  world.  "  The  mind  beholds  ideas 
as  though  in  perspective.  The  nearer  a  picture  the 
clearer  the  lines  ;  the  further  away  the  less  clear  and  less 
distinct.  We  have  obscure  ideas  when  it  is  not  possible 
to  distinguish  them  from  ourselves  or  from  other  ideas  ; 
confused  ideas  when  the  elements  of  the  ideas  are  not 
distinguishable ;  distinct  ideas  when  it  is  possible  to  re- 
solve them  into  their  factors."  l  If  the  ideas  are  distinct 
the  mind  is  said  to  possess  true  knowledge,  and  to 
accurately  mirror  the  harmony  and  perfection  of  the 
world.  But  if  that  perfection  and  harmony  are  indis- 
tinctly perceived  the  mind  experiences  not  truth  but  the 
feeling  of  beauty.  The  pleasure  which  a  product  of  art 
causes  is  the  result  of  an  unconscious  recognition,  a  con- 
fused perception  of  the  perfection  and  harmony  in  the 
relation  of  its  parts.  "  Music  charms  us,  although  its 
beauty  only  consists  in  the  harmony  of  numbers  and  in 
the  reckoning  of  the  beats  or  vibrations  of  sounding 
bodies,  which  meet  at  intervals,  of  which  we  are  not 
conscious  and  which  the  soul  does  not  cease  to  make. 
The  pleasures  which  sight  finds  in  proportions  are  of 
the  same  nature."2  The  harmony,  or  perfection,  in  the 
relation  of  musical  vibrations,  if  confusedly  apprehended, 
arouses  the  feeling  of  Beauty.  If  that  perfection  is  dis- 
tinctly cognised  we  should  experience  not  beauty  but 
truth.  "  Beauty  and  Truth  differ  only  in  the  fact  that 
perfection  is  confusedly  apprehended  in  one  case,  dis- 
tinctly in  the  other.3     Iyeibnitz,  thus,  by  the  conception 

^Schmidt,  Leibnitz  and  Baumgarten,  p.  41. 

2  Prin.  d.  I.  Nat.,  17. 

3  Erdtnann,  History  of  Phil.,  \  288,  2,  3,  4,  5. 


Development  of  KanPs  Psychology.  7 

of  Beauty  as  the  confused  apprehension  of  perfection 
moulded  the  character  of  all  aesthetical  speculation  prior 
to  the  appearance  of  the  critical  philosophy.  The  men 
who  developed  that  branch  of  philosophy  merely  elabor- 
ated the  thought  of  the  master. 

Wolff,  upon  whom  the  mantle  of  L,eibnitz  fell,  is  im- 
portant for  our  purpose  mainly  because  of  things  he  did 
not  do,  but  handed  down  as  problems  to  his  pupil  Baum- 
garten.  Following  Leibnitz,  Wolff  distinguished  two 
main  forms  of  mental  activity — knowing,  (factiltas  cog- 
noscendi)  and  desiring  {facultas  appetendi).  He  also 
adopted  Leibnitz's  distinction  of  two  forms  or  stages  of 
cognition  :  (i)  a  higher  form  concerned  with  clear  and 
distinct  ideas  including  Attention,  Understanding  and 
Reason ;  and,  (2)  a  lower  form  concerned  with  confused 
ideas  and  comprising  Sensation,  Imagination,  and 
Memory.  Wolff  having  treated  only  the  higher  forms 
of  cognition  his  pupil,  Baumgarten,  took  up  the  investi- 
gation of  the  lower  forms  under  the  title  Aesthetics,  which 
he  defined  as  "  the  science  of  the  lower  forms  of  knowl- 
edge. ' ' l  Wolff,  in  his  logic,  had  established  the  science  of 
the  correct  use  of  the  higher  forms  of  mind  ;  Baumgarten 
wished  to  complement  the  logic  with  a  science  of  the 
proper  use  of  the  lower  forms  of  knowledge.  Inheriting 
the  Leibnitzian  psychology  through  Wolff,  he  also  in- 
herited the  fundamental  tenet  of  the  Leibnitzian  theory 

Note. — The  use  of  the  term  aesthetics  to  designate  both  the  theory 
of  the  beautiful  and  the  science  of  the  sensibility  will  be  understood 
if  it  is  remembered  that  the  experience  of  the  Beautiful  depends  upon 
the  activity  of  the  senses.  The  close  connection  between  their 
activity  and  the  beautiful  experience  justifies  the  double  use  of  the 
word  "Aesthetics."  Sense- perception  of  the  perfect  produces  the  ex- 
perience of  the  beautiful,  perfection-sensed  gives  pleasure.  The  fact 
also  that  both  are  for  Leibnitz  confused  knowledge  warrants  their  in- 
clusion under  a  common  title. 

1  Schmidt,  op.  cit.  p.  15. 


8  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

of  beauty,  viz.,  that  beauty  consists  in  a  confused  per- 
ception of  perfection.  So  far  as  aesthetics  is  concerned 
Baumgarten's  work  consisted  mainly  in  an  effort  to  de- 
termine the  subjective  and  objective  conditions  of  the 
beautiful,  and  thereby  contributed  towards  bringing  into 
prominence  the  feeling  life. 

It  seems  proper  at  this  point  to  consider  the  claim 
made  by  Gottsched,  and  quoted  with  approval  by 
Schmidt,  that  Baumgarten,  although  adopting  and  re- 
taining the  main  features  of  the  Iyeibnitzian  philosophy, 
clearly  anticipated  the  tripartite  division  of  mind 
established  by  Kant.1  In  support  of  their  claim  on  be- 
half of  Baumgarten  they  cite  the  fact  that  he  dis- 
tinguished clearly  the  faculty  of  cognizing  anything  ob- 
scurely and  confusedly,  or  indirectly  as  the  faculty  of 
lower  cognition  from  the  higher  faculty  of  knowledge 
which  possesses  logical  clearness  and  certainty.  He 
assumes,  therefore,  it  is  said,  for  the  sensuous  idea  a 
special  though  lower  faculty  as  an  independent  factor  of 
the  human  mind,  having  its  own  peculiar  nature,  laws 
and  perfection.  It  is  claimed,  moreover,  that  Baum- 
garten distinguishes  between  conceptual  truth  and 
material  perfection,  i.  <?.,  sensuous  truth — -Beauty — and 
so  between  logic  and  aesthetics  as  belonging  to  entirely 
different  spheres.  This,  it  is  said,  is  a  distinct  advance 
beyond  the  Wolffian  separation  of  empirical  and  rational 
disciplines.  In  Wolff's  scheme  the  lower  and  higher 
faculties  differed  only  in  degree,  while  Baumgarten 
originated  the  idea  of  two  separate  faculties.  It  is  very 
difficult  to  judge  of  the  merits  of  this  claim  made  on  be- 
half of  Baumgarten  because  of  the  uncertain  meaning 
that  attaches  to  the  word  'faculty.'  But  it  is  quite 
probable  that  Baumgarten  meant  by  '  faculty  of  lower 

1  Schmidt,  op.  cit.  p.  44,  f. 


Development  of  Kanfs  Psychology.  9 

cognition '  a  capacity  or  power  (not  very  different  from 
Wolff's  meaning)  of  having  knowledge  of  a  lower  order 
than  that  yielded  by  Reason  and  Understanding.  It  is 
not  probable  that  he  thought  of  making  Feeling  a 
faculty  distinct  from  and  coordinate  with  Intellect  and 
Will  as  was  done  by  Kant  and  the  contemporary 
psychologists.  If  this  view  of  the  matter  is  correct, 
Baumgarten  can  scarcely  be  said  to  have  advanced  in  his 
psychology  beyond  his  teacher,  Wolff. 

Baumgarten's  aesthetical  theories  were  developed  by 
Meier,  a  zealous  student  of  the  subject  who  adopted  the 
Wolffian  division  of  cognition  into  higher  and  lower 
(sensuous)  forms.  Like  Baumgarten,  Meier  regarded 
beauty  as  sensuously  perceived  perfection,  and  therefore, 
as  belonging  to  the  lower  form  of  knowledge.  "  Die 
Schonheit  ist  eine  Vollkommenheit,  insofern  sie  undeut- 
lich  oder  sinnlich  erkant  wird.  "  *  Meier  repeatedly  in- 
sisted that  the  schbne  Erkenntniss  must  be  indistinct, 
that  is,  sensuous.  An  act  of  the  Understanding,  he  main- 
tained, which  analyzes  a  perceived  object  into  its  parts 
destroys  the  sensation  of  beauty  ;  for  '  beauty  is  perfection 
confusedly  apprehended  ' .  It  is  thus  seen  that  Meier's 
contribution  to  the  science  of  Aesthetics  does  not  differ 
from,  or  carry  any  further,  the  work  of  Baumgarten ; 
his  influence  upon  the  psychology  of  his  time  consisted 
in  bringing  into  the  foreground  the  emotional  experience. 

The  next  noteworthy  name  in  this  connection  is  that 
of  Sulzer  who  insisted  that  the  Wolffian  division  of  mind 
into  Intellect  and  Will  implied  "  an  undue  disregard  of 
the  sensations  of  the  agreeable  and  disagreeable.  " 2  To 
Sulzer,  therefore,  belongs  the  credit  of  first  laying  special 
emphasis  upon  the  pleasure-pain  experience.     In  the 

1  Sommers,  Deutsche  Psychologie  unci  Aesthetic,  p.  28. 

2  Brdmann,  op.  cit.  \  294.  4. 


io  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

Allgemeine  Theorie  der  schbnen  Kiinste,  177T,  Sulzer 
coordinates  the  faculty  of  sensing,  i.  e.,  of  being  affected 
in  a  pleasant  or  unpleasant  manner,  with  the  faculty  of 
cognizing  the  characteristics  of  things. l  In  the  same 
work  he  places  the  aesthetic  sensibility  between  thought 
and  actioii.  In  explaining  methods  of  inspiring  men  to 
noble  conduct  he  points  out  that  one  must  not  only  ap- 
peal to  the  Intellect,  but  must  touch  the  feelings  as  well. 
"  The  Understanding  yields  nothing  but  knowledge  and 
in  this  there  is  no  power  of  acting.  If  the  truth  is  to  be 
effective  then  must  it  not  only  be  cognized  in  the  form 
of  the  Good,  but  must  also  be  sensed,  for  only  by  this 
means  is  the  active  power  excited.  "  2  Here  Sulzer  ap- 
proaches very  nearly  to  a  definite  statement  of  a  tripar- 
tite division,  and,  perhaps,  failed  to  do  so  only  because 
he  was  concerned  with  Aesthetics  and  not  with  Psychol- 
ogy- 

The  examination  of  the  pleasure-pain  experience 
which  Sulzer  was  the  first  to  treat  with  special  care  was 
more  thoroughly  and  exhaustively  carried  out  by  Men- 
delssohn in  Brief e  iiber  die  Empfindungen,  1755.  In 
the  Brief e,  Mendelssohn  contended  against  those  who 
would  acknowledge  only  Cognition  and  Will  as  funda- 
mental activities,  and  demanded  that  Sensibility  be  put 
along  side  those  faculties.  The  sensibility  here  referred 
to  is  the  power  of  sensing  the  beautiful.  In  the  Mor- 
genstunden,  Mendelssohn  describes  the  character  and  in- 
dicates the  place  of  the  faculty  of  sensing  the  Beautiful. 
His  language  is,  "  As  a  rule  one  ought  to  distinguish 
two  mental  faculties — the  cognitive  and  the  volitional — 
and  place  the  sensation  of  pleasure  and  pain  with  the 
faculty  of  desire.     .     .     .     But  it  seems  that  the  satis- 

1  Dessoir,  Geschichte,  d.  n.  Deutschen  Psychologie,  I,  p.  269. 
2Sommers,  op.  tit.,  p.  205. 


Development  of  KanPs  Psychology.  1 1 

faction  one  feels  in  the  beauty  of  Nature  and  Art  is 
wholly  free  from  inclination  or  desire  ;  it  can  be  contem- 
plated with  quiet  satisfaction.  I  shall  call  the  faculty  of 
beauty  the  Billigungsvermbgen,  and  thereby  distinguish 
it  from  cognition  of  the  truth  as  well  as  from  the  desire 
for  the  good.  " l  That  is,  Mendelssohn  proposes  as  a 
substitute  for  the  old  division  of  mind  into  cognition  and 
desire  a  division  that  would  include  also  a  faculty  of 
sensing  the  Beautiful.  The  new  faculty  is  made  to  stand 
between  the  other  two  and  unites  by  'the  smallest  grada- 
tions '  their  activity.  It  thus  appears  that  the  present 
commonly  accepted  division  of  the  mind  into  Intellect, 
Feeling,  and  Will  was  first  stated,  though  somewhat 
vaguely,  by  Mendelssohn. 

In  1776,  Tetens,  a  distinguished  psychologist  of  the 
period,  was  led  to  make  the  same  classification  of  the 
mental  faculties.  "I  discover,"  he  writes  in  the  Philo- 
sophische  Versuche  uber  die  menschliche  Natur  und  Hire 
Entwicklung,  i  three  fundamental  powers  of  mind ; 
Feeling,  Understanding,  and  Will.  Feeling  includes 
sensitiveness  as  well  as  the  mere  feeling  of  new  changes. 
The  power  of  ideating  and  the  power  of  thinking,  both 
belong  to  the  Understanding.  The  remaining  faculty 
which  is  coordinated  with  Feeling  and  Understanding, 
and  is  called  Will."2  Whatever  one  may  say  of  a  certain 
vagueness  in  the  statement  of  the  three-fold  division  of 
the  mental  faculties  by  Sulzer,  Mendelssohn,  and  Baum- 
garten,  if  that  merit  is  accredited  to  the  last  named,  there 
is  no  mistaking  Tetens'  language.  It  is  a  clear  and 
definite  statement  of  the  division  which  met  the  approval 
of  Kant  and  which  was  established  by  the  might  of  his 
authority. 

1  Mendelssohn,  Schriften,  Vol.  2,  pp.  294-5.    Morgenstunden,  VII. 

2  Tetens,  Versuche,  Vol.  I,  p.  625. 


12  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

The  result  of  the  foregoing  sketch  may  be  summed 
up  by  noting,  (i)  that  the  three-fold  division  of  mind 
owes  its  existence  directly  to  the  widespread  activity  in 
the  field  of  aesthetics  and  to  the  particular  trend,  or 
direction,  given  that  activity  by  the  doctrines  of  Leib- 
nitz and  Wolff,  more  especially  to  the  L,eibnitzian  con- 
ception that,  '  Beauty  is  perfection  confusedly  appre- 
hended.' After  the  work  of  the  writers  on  aesthetics 
had  brought  to  the  foreground  the  feeling  life,  it  was 
but  natural  that  the  power  or  faculty  of  Feeling  should 
attain  a  rank  coordinate  with  Intellect  and  Will. 

Contenting  ourselves  with  this  somewhat  fragmentary 
historical  outline,  we  have  now  to  inquire  (i)  when  Kant 
first  became  interested  in  the  question  of  the  division  of 
the  mental  faculties,  and  (2)  what  influence,  if  any,  each 
of  the  investigators  mentioned  above  had  upon  his  re- 
flections upon  the  subject.  The  following  passage  from 
a  work  entitled  Untersttchung  uber  die  deutlichkeit  der 
Grundsatze  der  natiirlichen  Theologie  tend  Moral,  pub- 
lished 1763,  shows  that  at  that  time  Kant  saw  the  need 
of  a  careful  examination  of  the  fundamental  mental 
faculties  :  "  Without  an  exact  knowledge  and  analysis 
of  the  many  feelings  of  the  mind,  the  feelings  of  the 
sublime,  the  beautiful,  disgust,  etc.,  the  motives  of  our 
nature  cannot  be  known.  Explanations  of  pleasure  and 
pain,  of  desire,  nausea  and  the  like  have  never  been  fur- 
nished because  adequate  analyses  were  lacking."1  In  the 
same  treatise  Kant  distinguished  between  cognition  as 
the  faculty  of  perceiving  the  truth  and  feeling  the 
faculty  of  sensing  the  goody2  It  is  evident  from  these 
expressions  that  at  that  time,  1763,  the  problem  of  the 

JR.  I.,  84,  f.  H.  II,  288.  The  passage  is  quoted  by  J.  B.  Meyer, 
KanVs  Psychologie,  p.  41. 

2  It  is  possible,  Meyer  thinks,  that  this  distinction  was  suggested  to 
Kant  by  Hutcheson's  Theory  of  the  moral  sense. 


Development  of  Kant's  Psychology.  13 

true  division  of  the  faculties  was  clearly  before  Kant. 
Further,  an  examination  of  the  correspondence  compiled 
by  Kant's  editors  shows  that  his  views  experienced 
numerous  changes  before  he  finally  settled  upon  the  divi- 
sion into  Intellect,  Feeling,  and  Will.  Setting  aside  the 
needless  task  of  enumerating  those  changes,  we  proceed 
to  the  second  question  :  What  influence  had  Kant's  con- 
temporaries or  predecessors  upon  his  reflection  on  the 
problem  of  the  proper  classification  of  the  fundamental 
mental  powers  ? 

First,  the  historians  agree  in  the  statement  that  Kant 
was  familiar  with  the  works  of  Baumgarten  and  Meier, 
and  used  them  as  his  guides  in  the  sphere  of  aesthetics. 
These  works,  it  is  said,1  were  always  before  him  in  pre- 
paring and  delivering  his  lectures  on  that  subject.  The 
influence  from  this  source  we  may  suppose,  therefore,  to 
have  been  considerable,  for  the  obvious  reason  that  fol- 
lowing the  lead  of  such  zealous  students  of  aesthetics 
naturally  would  lead  to  an  increased  knowledge  and 
sense  of  the  importance  of  the  feeling  life.  It  is  highly 
probable,  also,  that  Kant  knew  Sulzer's  essay  in  which 
he  had  coordinated  the  faculty  of  being  affected  in  a 
pleasant  or  unpleasant  manner  with  the  faculty  of  Ideas. 
There  is  no  ground  for  supposing,  however,  that  Kant 
could  have  received  more  than  an  impetus  to  his  own 
reflection  from  Sulzer's  work. 

The  two  men  who  seem  to  have  exerted  the  most  di- 
rect and  marked  influence  upon  Kant  are  Tetens  and 
Mendelssohn.  Krdmann  makes  the  positive,  but  proba- 
bly not  carefully  considered  statement,  that  Kant  based 
his  assumption  of  three  distinct  mental  faculties  upon 
the  authority  of  Tetens.  Meyer  questions  this  state- 
ment, and  maintains  with  good  ground  that,  while  Kant 

1  Erdmann,  op.  ciL,  \  290,  10,  11. 


14  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

doubtless  was  familiar  with  Tetens'  Versuche,  and  the 
three-fold  division  which  it  proposed,  he  received  from 
it  no  more  than  direction  and  guidance  in  his  own  in- 
vestigations. Kant  was  not  the  man  to  adopt  the  views 
of  other  writers  without  first  carefully  scrutinizing  their 
validity.  It  would  be  very  unlike  the  Copernican  phi- 
losopher to  adopt  a  view  or  theory  on  the  authority  of 
some  other  man  or  men. 

Mendelssohn,  in  the  opinion  of  Meyer,  influenced 
Kant's  reflections  upon  this  subject  much  more  than 
Tetens  ;  yet  there  is  ground  for  supposing  that  the  influ- 
ence was  mutual.  In  1776,  Mendelssohn  placed  the  fa- 
culty of  Sensation,  by  which  we  sense  anything  as 
pleasant  or  unpleasant,  good  or  bad,  etc.,  between  the 
faculties  of  cognition  and  desire.  This  view  clearly 
does  not  accord  with  Kant's  final  statement  of  the  tri- 
partite division ;  it  differs  from  it  especially  in  that  it 
confuses  the  aesthetical  and  the  ethical  elements  in  sen- 
sation. In  1785,  however,  Mendelssohn  made  a  sharp 
distinction  between  Sensation,  as  the  faculty  of  sensing 
the  pleasant  and  unpleasant,  and  the  desire  for  and  the 
sensation  of  the  Good.  This  view  approaches  that  ex- 
pressed by  Kant  in  the  letter  written  to  Reinhold  in 
1787.1  But  the  strongest  reason,  in  the  opinion  of 
Meyer,  for  believing  that  Mendelssohn  was  largely  influ- 
ential in  bringing  Kant  to  his  final  position  on  this  ques- 
tion, is  the  fact  that  Mendelssohn  visited  Konigsberg  in 
1777,  and,  while  there,  conversed  with  Kant  on  philosoph- 
ical subjects.  This  circumstance,  together  with  the  fact 
that  both  had  long  been  interested  in  the  problem  of  the 
distribution  of  the  mental  powers,  leads  Meyer  to  think  it 
highly  probable  that  they  exchanged  views  concerning 
it.     However,  as  Meyer  would  admit,  it  is  wholly  a  mat- 

1  Meyer,  Kant's  Psychologie,  p.  61  f. 


Development  of  Kant's  Psychology.  15 

ter  of  conjecture,  that  Kant  and  Mendelssohn  discussed 
the  point  referred  to ;  further,  it  is  a  matter  of  conject- 
ure what  the  result  of  such  a  discussion  would  be,  sup- 
posing it  to  have  occurred.  But  the  fact  that  Mendels- 
sohn was  deeply  interested  in  explorations  and  investi- 
gations regarding  the  feeling  experience  seemed  to 
Meyer  to  afford  ground  for  supposing  that  he  would  not 
neglect  the  opportunity  of  urging  upon  Kant  the  im- 
portance of  that  aspect  of  individual  consciousness.  We 
are  warranted  in  thinking,  therefore,  he  maintains,  that 
Kant  received  from  Mendelssohn  a  new  and  deeper  in- 
terest in  the  feeling  life,  especially  the  feeling  of  beauty, 
and  was  thus  led  to  assign  this  experience  to  a  separate 
faculty  of  the  mind. 

It  must  be  admitted,  however,  that  we  cannot  exactly 
determine  how  much  Kant  owes  to  Mendelssohn, 
or  to  any  other  thinker,  and  how  much  is  due  to 
his  own  independent  reflection  ;  we  cannot  measure 
exactly  the  influence  which  Kant's  contemporaries,  or 
any  one  of  them,  had  upon  his  investigations  regarding 
the  proper  division  of  the  mental  powers.  The  pro- 
posed innovation  in  the  division  of  the  fundamental 
powers  of  mind  was  only  one  of  the  many  psychological 
novelties  with  which  the  air  was  charged.  And  Kant, 
like  every  great  scientific  worker,  was  responsive  to  the 
influences  of  his  time,  and  in  turn  he  influenced  the 
world  of  thought  and  action  about  him.  So  with  refer- 
ence to  the  question  in  hand,  we  may  be  sure  that  Kant's 
displacement  of  the  bipartite  division  of  the  mental 
powers  by  the  tripartite  was  the  result  of  his  own  reflec- 
tion guided  and  stimulated  by  other  investigators. 

In  concluding  this  section  one  may  repeat  that  it  was 
not  until  Kant  came  to  recognise  Feeling  as  an  inde- 
pendent mental  faculty  that  the  plan  of  writing  a  third 


1 6  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

Critique  occurred  to  him.  The  Critique  of  Pure  Reason 
established  a  priori  principles  for  the  Understanding  ;  the 
Critique  of  Practical  Reason  exhibited  the  a  priori 
principles  of  Desire.  It  would  seem  then,  that  Feeling, 
as  an  independent  mental  faculty,  required  a  separate 
set  of  principles  to  regulate  its  activity.  This  demand 
was  fulfilled  in  the  Critique  of  Judgment,  the  work 
which  formally  completed  Kant's  critical  investigations. 

§  2.       CHANGES   IN   THE    FORM    AND    PROBLEM     OF    THE 
THIRD    CRITIQUE. 

We  have  traced  in  the  preceding  section  the  influences 
and  steps  by  which  Kant  came  to  design  a  third  Cri- 
tique. We  saw  how  the  activity  in  Aesthetics  brought 
to  the  foreground  the  emotional  life  ;  how  gradually  the 
feeling  experience  came  to  be  assigned  to  a  separate 
power  of  mind  ;  also  how  Kant  admitted  Feeling  to  a 
rank  coordinate  with  Intellect  and  Will ;  and,  finally, 
that  he  designed  the  third  Critique  to  establish  a  priori 
principles  of  activity  for  the  newly  discovered  faculty. 
We  have  seen,  also,  (p.  i.)  that  when  Kant  wrote  to 
Reinhold,  1787,  regarding  the  forthcoming  work,  he  in- 
tended to  confine  his  research  to  a  Critique  of  Taste — 
an  effort  to  discover  a  priori  principles  for  judgments  of 
the  beautiful.  It  is  easily  understood  how  this  phase 
rather  than  any  other  of  our  feeling  experience,  i.e.,  the 
feeling  of  beauty,  attracted  Kant's  attention  first  and  in- 
duced him  to  undertake  the  discovery  of  a  priori  prin- 
ciples for  the  activity  of  feeling — as  he  had  previously 
done  for  intellect  and  will — this  is  easily  understood 
when  we  remember  that  the  investigations  of  the  Wolff- 
ians— Baumgarten,  Meier,  and  L,ambert — and  the  111- 
uminationists — Mendelssohn,  Lessing,  and  Sulzer — were 
concerned  mainly  with  the  analysis  of  the  experience  of 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the  Third  Critique.     17 

the  beautiful  aud  the  effort  to  discover  its  objective  and 
subjective  conditions.  Their  labors  brought  judgments 
about  the  beautiful  into  such  clear  light  that  they  ap- 
peared to  Kant  to  need  "  rationalizing  "  ;  they  seemed 
important  enough  to  justify  the  attempt  to  find  a  priori 
principles  for  them.  In  its  inception,  therefore,  the 
third  Critique  was  to  deal  only  with  judgments  of  Taste, 
it  was  to  be  concerned  with  the  single  purpose  of  ration- 
alizing aesthetical  Judgments. 

But  when  the  third  Critique  appeared,  it  included  not 
only  a  Critique  of  Taste  (Critique  of  the  aesthetical 
Judgment),  but  also  the  Critique  of  teleological  Judg- 
ment dealing  with  the  problem  of  design  in  organic 
nature.  Kant's  reason  for  embodying  both  discussions 
in  the  same  work  may  be  inferred  from  certain  passages 
in  his  writings,  and  from  the  general  character  of  the 
two  Treatises.  Thus  in  section  8  of  the  Introduction  to 
the  Critique  of  Judgment  he  says  :  "  Purposiveness  may 
be  represented  in  an  object  given  in  experience  on  a 
merely  subjective  ground — or  it  may  be  represented  ob- 
jectively as  the  harmony  of  the  form  of  the  object  with 
the  possibility  of  the  thing  itself."  Again  in  the  same 
section  :  "  We  can  regard  natural  beauty  as  the  presenta- 
tion of  the  concept  of  the  formal  (merely  subjective) 
purposiveness,  and  natural  purposiveness  as  the  presenta- 
tion of  the  concept  of  real  (objective)  purposiveness. 
The  former  we  judge  by  the  faculty  of  Taste,  the  latter 
by  the  Understanding  and  Reason.  On  this  is  based  the 
division  of  the  Critique  of  Judgment  into  the  Critique 
of  the  aesthetical  and  the  Critique  of  teleological  Judg- 
ment." In  other  words,  Nature  is  subjectively  purpose 
ive  in  so  far  as  the  contemplation  of  its  various  forms 
arouses  the  emotion  of  Beauty ;  it  is  really  purposive  in 
so  far  as  the  objects  of  nature  conform  to  ideas,  or  con- 


1 8  Teleology  in  Kant^s    Critical  Philosophy. 

cepts.  Objects  judged  aesthetically  are  judged  with  re- 
ference to  their  adaptation  to  the  harmonious  function- 
ing of  our  cognitive  faculties.  Objects  are  judged  tel- 
eologically  when  their  possibility  is  inexplicable  except 
on  the  assumption  that  they  are  the  realization  of  a  plan 
or  idea.  The  beautiful  object  displays  a  certain  pur- 
posiveness  with  reference  to  the  faculties  of  knowledge 
and  their  accordant  activity ;  such  objects  are  subject- 
ively purposive.  Organisms  exhibit  what  Kant  calls 
objective  purposiveness ;  they  seem  to  actualize,  or  em- 
body a  concept,  or  plan.  Purposiveness,  therefore,  is  the 
principle,  is  fundamental  to,  is  the  guide  for  both 
aesthetical  and  teleological  Judgments.  Both  activities 
proceed  according  to  one  and  the  same  rule.  Caird's 
profound  observation  that  "  the  Critique  of  Judgment  is 
equivalent  to  a  discussion  of  the  validity  of  the  teleo- 
logical idea,"1  tersely  expresses  the  same  thought, 
that  the  central,  the  most  important  idea  in  the  Critique 
of  Judgment,  the  idea  about  which  the  discussions  cen- 
ter, is  that  of  design,  or  teleology. 

If  now  we  turn  to  the  faculty  which  acts  in  accordance 
with  this  principle,  we  find  that  both  functions  (the 
aesthetical  and  the  teleological)  are  referred  to  the  re- 
flective Judgment,  which  Kant  distinguished  from  the 
determinant  Judgment  by  the  fact  that  the  latter  sub- 
sumes the  particular  under  a  given  universal  (rule,  law, 
or  principle),  while  the  reflective  Judgment  endeavors  to 
find  a  universal  for  the  given  particular.  The  determin- 
ant Judgment  prescribes  laws  to  nature,  the  reflective 
gives  a  law  only  to  itself  and  not  to  nature.  Kant  dis- 
tinguishes the  two  forms  of  Judgment  in  the  Introduc- 
tion to  the  Critique  of  Judgment2  as  follows:  "If  the 

1  Caird,  Critical  Phil,  of  Kant,  II.,  p.  415. 
2R.,  IV,  17.     H.,V,  185.     B.,  16. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the  Third  Critique.     19 

universal  (the  rule,  the  principle,  the  law)  be  given,  the 
Judgment  which  subsumes  the  particular  under  it  is  de- 
terminant. But  if  only  the  particular  is  given  for  which 
the  universal  has  to  be  found,  the  Judgment  is  merely 
reflective."  The  determinant  Judgment  subsumes  under 
universals  furnished  by  the  understanding  ;  the  reflective 
Judgment  subsumes  under  a  universal  created  by  itself. 
The  former  brings  the  particular  under  the  universal, 
transcendental  laws  of  the  Understanding — the  schema- 
tised categories.  It  brings  an  infinitude  of  particulars 
under  the  universal  a  priori  rules  of  the  Understanding. 
Kant  refers  to  this  form  of  Judgment  in  the  Introduc- 
tion to  the  K.  d.  r.  V.  as  the  faculty  of  subsuming  under 
the  rules  of  the  Understanding,  i.  e.,  of  determining 
whether  anything  falls  under  a  given  rule  or  not.  The 
1  anything '  is  the  manifold  of  sense  synthesized  by 
Imagination.  The  distinguishing  mark,  then,  of  the 
activity  of  the  determinant  Judgment  is  that  the  general, 
the  universal,  under  which  it  subsumes  the  particular,  the 
manifold  of  Sense,  is  given.  Now  according  to  Kant 
the  activity  of  the  determinant  Judgment  is  all  that  is 
required  to  supply  us  with  a  knowledge  of  nature,  to 
furnish  us  with  an  experience  which  we  call  objective, 
to  enable  us  to  know  nature  as  an  object  of  possible  ex- 
perience. But  this  activity  alone  is  inadequate  to  give 
us  an  ordered  system  of  knowledge.  "  The  forms  of 
nature  are  so  manifold,  and  there  are  so  many  modifica- 
tions of  the  universal  transcendental  natural  concepts 
left  undetermined  by  the  laws  given  a  priori  by  the 
Understanding — because  these  only  concern  the  possi- 
bility of  nature — (as  an  object  of  Sense)  that  there  must 
be  laws  for  these  forms  also."  *  That  is,  the  determin- 
ant judgment  supplies  us  with  a  world  of  natural  objects, 

»R.,  IV,  17.     H.,  V,  186.      B.,  17. 


20         Teleology  in  Kaitfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

but  these  remain  disconnected  and  isolated  ;  order  and  sys- 
tem are  wanting.  Caird  thus  expresses  the  imperfection 
and  incompleteness  of  the  product  yielded  by  the  activity 
of  the  determinant  judgment :  "  An  endless  variation  of 
the  detail  of  experience  was  still  possible  consistently  with 
the  determination  of  its  objects  and  their  general  rela- 
tions by  the  laws  of  the  Understanding.  Nay,  the  ob- 
jects given  might  be  so  manifold,  and  their  similarity  so 
slight,  that  the  effort  to  subsume  them  under  these  laws 
might  altogether  fail.  In  supposing  that  knowledge  is 
possible,  therefore,  we  are  supposing,  not  only  that  ob- 
jects as  perceived  are  confined  to  the  general  conditions 
under  which  they  are  known  as  objects,  but  that,  in 
their  detail  they  are  not  infinitely  varied,  but  have  a 
certain  similarity  and  continuity  through  all  their  dif- 
ference, which  makes  it  possible  for  the  intellect  to  get 
a  hold  upon  them."  1  The  activity  of  the  determinant 
judgment  being  limited  to  the  subsumption  of  the 
synthesized  manifold  under  laws  of  the  Understanding,  it 
is  insufficient  to  yield  a  system  of  knowledge.  We  have 
an  objective  experience  but  it  lacks  order  and  unity. 
Hence  it  is  at  this  stage  that  the  demand  for  a  principle 
of  unity  arises ;  it  is  at  this  point  that  the  function  of 
the  reflective  Judgment  and  its  unifying  principle  be- 
comes important. 

We  have  seen  that  in  the  case  of  the  determinant 
Judgment  its  principle  of  unification,  its  universal  is  fur- 
nished by  the  Understanding  ;  in  the  case  of  the  reflective 
Judgment,  however,  its  principle  is  self-given  and  self- 
imposed.  The  nature  of  this  latter  principle  has  already 
been  anticipated,  the  principle,  viz.,  of  regarding  the  va- 
riety in  the  forms  and  laws  of  nature  as  capable  of  being 
reduced  to  an  order  and  unity  prearranged  by  a  design- 

1  Caird,  op.  tit.,  II,  p.  411. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the  Third   Critique.     21 

ing  Intelligence.  "  The  particular  empirical  laws  in  re- 
spect of  what  is  in  them  left  undetermined  by  the  uni- 
versal laws  of  the  Understanding,  must  be  considered  in 
accordance  with  such  unity  as  they  would  have  if  an 
Understanding  ( although  not  our  Understanding )  had 
furnished  them  to  our  cognitive  faculties  so  as  to  make 
possible  a  system  of  experience  according  to  particular 
laws  of  Nature.  "  l  We  must  regard  the  world  as  pur- 
posive, i.  e.%  it  must  be  represented  as  if  an  Understand- 
ing contained  the  ground  of  the  unity  of  its  manifold  of 
form  and  law.  Assuming  the  standpoint  of  the  reflec- 
tive Judgment,  we  must  think  the  world  as  an  ordered, 
intelligible  cosmos,  and  not  as  a  confused,  unintelligible 
chaos.  To  assert  that  the  world  is  purposive  is  to  assert 
its  intelligibility.  Hegel  thus  expresses  the  nature  and 
function  of  Kant's  reflective  Judgment :  "  The  reflective 
power  of  Judgment  is  invested  by  Kant  with  the  func- 
tion of  an  Intuitive  Understanding;  i.  e.,  whereas  the 
particulars  had  hitherto  appeared,  so  far  as  the  universal 
or  abstract  identity  was  concerned,  adventitious  and  in- 
capable of  being  deduced  from  it,  the  Intuitive  Under- 
standing apprehends  the  particulars  as  moulded  and 
formed  by  the  universal  itself.  "  2  We  proceed  in  our  re- 
flection upon  nature  according  to  the  principle  that  a 
supreme  intelligence  has  ordered  the  laws  and  phenom- 
ena of  nature  with  reference  to  a  given  end.  We  employ 
this  notion  of  design  ( 1 )  in  the  process  of  reducing  our 
knowledge  of  nature  to  an  ordered  system  of  knowledge, 
(  2  )  in  interpreting  organic  nature,  (  3  )  in  explaining 
the  Beautiful  in  Nature  and  Art.  The  reflective  Judg- 
ment as  thus  described,  is  the  faculty  which  employs  the 

■R.,  IV,  18.     H.,  V,  186.     B.  18. 

2  Hegel,  Werke,  VI,  p.  116.     Encyclopaedic,  $55.     Wallace,  Tra?is. 
of  Logic,  p.  112. 


22  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

idea  of  purposiveness  in  the  realm  of  the  beautiful  and 
in  organic  nature. 

In  conclusion,  one  may  repeat  in  answer  to  the  ques- 
tion, What  were  Kant's  reasons  for  putting  the  Critique 
of  aesthetical  Judgment  and  the  Critique  of  teleological 
Judgment  in  the  same  work  ?  first,  that  both  classes  of 
judgment  rest  upon  the  same  principle  : — purposiveness  ; 
secondly,  that  the  same  faculty,  the  reflective  judgment, 
is  operative  in  both.  The  following  quotation  from  the 
treatise  Uber  Philosophie  uberhaupt,  originally  designed 
to  form  the  Introduction  to  the  Critique  of  Judgment, 
confirms  this  view  :  "  It  is  demanded  that  the  Critique 
of  the  teleological  faculty  and  that  of  the  aesthetical  fa- 
culty be  united  as  resting  upon  the  same  principle. 1 
For  the  teleological  as  well  as  the  aesthetical  judgment 
belongs  to  the  reflective  judgment  and  not  the  determi- 
nant. "  2  This  passage,  the  clearest  I  have  found  on  the 
subject,  as  was  stated,  is  from  the  treatise  which  was 
originally  intended  to  form  the  Introduction  to  the  Cri- 
tique of  Judgment  and  fully  agrees  with  the  passage 
quoted  (p.  17)  from  the  Introduction  to  the  work  as  it 
now  stands. 

In  addition  to  the  reasons  already  advanced  in  ex- 
planation and  justification  of  the  connection  of  the  two 
works,  viz.,  that  both  center  about  the  principle  of  de- 
sign, and  that  both  come  under  the  dominion  of  the  re- 
flective Judgment,  one  may  suppose  that  another  con- 
sideration tended  to  commend  to  Kant  the  plan  of  com- 
bining the  two  treatises ;  the  fact,  namely,  that  in  the 
course  of  his  reflection  he  had  come  to  regard  the  prin- 
ciple of  purposiveness  as    a  mediating  link  between  the 

1  The  "  same  principle  "  referred  to,  is,  of  course,  the  principle  of 
purposiveness,  or  design. 

2  R.,  I,  614  f.     H.,  VI,  401. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the  Third  Critique.     23 

doctrines  of  the  critiques  of  pure  and  practical  Reason. 
Now  when  purposiveness  came  to  be  regarded  as  a  prin- 
ciple of  mediation  between  the  doctrines  of  the  former 
critiques,  every  discussion  and  every  illustration  of 
that  principle,  which,  as  Kant  believed,  would  harmon- 
ize the  results  of  the  earlier  critiques,  would  be  brought 
together  in  one  work.  Every  fact  and  every  argument 
that  would  contribute  toward  throwing  light  upon  the 
teleological  notion  naturally  would  be  gathered  under 
the  same  title.  Although  Kant  nowhere  intimates  that 
this  consideration  had  any  influence  whatever  in  causing 
him  to  combine  the  two  discussions,  it  cannot  be  wholly 
fanciful  to  suppose  that  after  he  recognized  in  the  notion 
of  design  the  key  to  the  unification  of  the  earlier  cri- 
tiques, he  naturally  would  see  the  propriety  of  combining 
a  discussion  of  the  design  manifest  in  the  beautiful  with 
that  of  the  design  thought  to  be  displayed  by  organic 
nature.  The  Critiqtce  of  Judgment  had  come  to  be  re- 
garded as  something  more  than  a  completion  of  the 
critical  system  as  a  number  of  mechanically  related 
parts ;  it  contained  the  discussion  of  a  principle  which 
would  unite  the  system  into  a  harmonious  whole.  We 
may  suppose,  therefore,  that  as  the  necessity  of  design- 
ing the  third  critique  with  reference  to  the  mediation  of 
the  former  critiques  became  more  urgent,  the  fitness  of 
uniting  the  two  discussions  of  teleology  in  the  same 
work  became  more  apparent.  And  while  it  is  true  that 
when  the  third  critique  was  originally  planned  its  prob- 
lem was  limited  to  a  determination  of  the  a  priori  prin- 
ciples of  Taste,  yet  the  fact  that  the  key  to  the  ex- 
perience of  the  beautiful  and  to  the  interpretation  of 
organic  nature  lies  in  the  notion  of  purposiveness,  and 
the  further  fact,  that  the  third  critique,  as  the  unfolding 
and   illustration   of   that    notion,  is   the   keystone,  the 


24         Teleology  in  Kanf  s    Critical  Philosophy. 

unifier  of  the  critical  system,  fully  justifies  the  inclusion 
of  the  critiques  of  the  aesthetical  and  teleological  judg- 
ment under  the  same  title. 

Even  if  the  above  is  accepted  as  an  explanation  and 
justification  for  the  union  of  the  two  treatises  under  the 
same  title,  it  is  still  maintained  by  Adamson, l  and,  I 
think  rightly,  that  the  Critique  of  aesthetical  Judgment 
forms  one  distinct  work  with  principles  of  its  own,  and 
is  the  peculiar  and  proper  subject  of  the  third  Critique. 
In  support  of  this  proposition,  the  following  quotation 
may  be  submitted  :  "  The  faculty  of  cognition  according 
to  concepts  has  its  a  priori  principles  in  the  pure  Un- 
derstanding ( the  concepts  of  Nature ),  the  Will  in  pure 
Reason  ( its  concepts  of  Freedom ).  There  yet  remains 
among  the  general  properties  of  the  mind  a  mediating 
faculty  or  sensibility,  viz.,  the  feeling  of  pleasure  and 
pain  ;  so  likewise  among  the  higher  cognitive  faculties 
there  remains  a  mediating  faculty,  the  Judgment.  Now 
what  is  more  natural  than  to  suppose  that  the  Judgment 
contains  a  priori  principles  for  Feeling.  "2  After  Kant 
adopted  the  three-fold  division  of  Mind  into  Intellect, 
Feeling,  and  Will,  and  after  the  first  two  Critiques  had 
established  a  priori  principles  for  the  Intellect  and  Will, 
the  idea  of  completeness  seemed  to  demand  that  the  dis- 
covery of  a  priori  principles  for  Feeling  be  undertaken. 
That  is,  the  investigation  of  the  feeling  experience,  the 
attempt  to  determine  a  priori  principles  for  judgments 
of  the  beautiful  would  complete  the  work  so  far  as  crit- 
icism was  concerned.  It  was  not  necessary,  it  was  even 
beside  the  task,  so  far  as  completeness  of  treatment  was 
concerned,  to  enter  upon  the  investigation  of  the  pur- 
posiveness  manifest  in  organic  products  which  forms  the 

1  The  Philosophy  of  Kanl,  p.  235. 

2R.,  I,  p.  587.     Quoted  by  Adamson.  op.  cit.  p.  235. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the  Third  Critique.     25 

second  part  of  the  third  Critique  as  issued.  The  follow- 
ing passage  affords  additional  proof  that  Kant  regarded 
the  Critique  of  aesthetical  Judgment  in  particular  to  be 
necessary  for  the  completion  of  his  system  :  "  The  Cri- 
tique of  Taste,  which  formerly  was  for  the  improvement 
of  Taste,  opened,  when  considered  from  the  transcenden- 
tal point  of  view,  in  that  it  filled  a  gap  in  the  system  of 
our  faculties  of  cognition,  a  remarkable,  and  it  seems  to 
me,  a  very  promising  outlook  towards  a  completed  sys- 
tem of  all  the  mind's  powers  so  far  as  they  are  related 
in  their  determination  not  only  to  the  sensuous  but  also 
to  the  supersensuous."  x 

Stadler,  who  agrees  with  Adamson  in  maintaining 
that  the  Critique  of  the  aesthetical  Judgment  is  all  that 
properly  belongs  to  the  third  Critique,  states  the  object  of 
the  investigation  in  his  work,  KanPs  Teleologie?  to  be 
"  to  show  that  the  Critique  of  the  teleological  judgment 
stands  in  a  close  and  important  relation  to  the  Critique 
of  pure  Reason.  "  That  is,  Stadler  proposes  to  show  that 
the  thought  elaborated  in  the  Critique  of  the  teleological 
Judgment,  viz.,  that  in  our  investigation  of  organic  na- 
ture we  must  proceed  upon  the  supposition  that  organ- 
isms are  the  result  of  design  is  merely  a  fuller  treatment 
of  the  doctrine  sketched  in  the  K.  d.  r.  V.  under  the  head- 
ing, Of  the  regulative  use  of  the  Ideas  of  pure  Reason. 3 
That  doctrine,  briefly  stated,  is  that  in  all  our  investiga- 
tions we  must  proceed  on  the  theory  that  the  world  has 
originated  in  the  design  of  a  supreme  Intelligence  ;  that 
purpose,  plan,  pervades  and  is  revealed  in  the  world  of 
nature.  Accordingly,  Stadler  argues  that  the  union  of  the 
two  treatises  in  the  same  volume,  under  the  same  title 
does  not  signify  their  absolute  coordination.     Two  pas- 

>R.,  1,  p.  615.     H.,  VI,  402. 

2  Stadler.     Kant's  Teleologie,  p.  27. 

3R.,  II,  499-     H.,  Ill,  435  ff.     M.,II,55iff. 


26  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

sages,  one  from  the  Preface,  another  from  the  Introduc- 
tion to  their,  d.  £/.,  seem  to  confirm  his  position.  From 
the  Preface  he  quotes,  "  The  confusion  on  account  of  a 
principle  exists  mainly  in  the  aesthetical  Judgment,  . 
.  .  .  the  most  important  part  of  a  Critique  of  the 
faculty  of  Judgment  is  the  critical  investigation  of 
Taste.  "  l  From  the  Introduction  he  cites,  "  the  aesthet- 
ical Judgment  is  a  particular  faculty  of  judging  things 
according  to  a  rule  but  not  according  to  concepts ;  the 
ideological  judgment  on  the  other  hand  is  no  particular 
faculty  but  only  the  reflective  Judgment  in  general.  " 2 
Again  in  stating  the  problem  of  the  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment, Kant  enumerated  three  things  which  he  proposed 
to  investigate:  (i)  " whether  Judgment,  the  mediating 
link  between  Understanding  and  Reason,  has  a  priori 
principles  5(2)  whether  these,  if  they  exist  at  all,  are 
constitutive  or  merely  regulative  5(3)  whether  they  give 
a  rule  a  priori  to  the  feeling  of  pleasure  and  pain  as  the 
mediating  link  between  the  cognitive  faculty  and  the 
faculty  of  desire  just  as  the  Understanding  prescribes 
laws  a  priori  to  the  first  and  Reason  to  the  second.  " 3 
If  this  passage  is  read  with  the  thought  in  mind  that 
Kant  was  aiming  in  the  third  Critique  to  complete  his 
critical  investigations,  one  can  hardly  resist  the  conclu- 
sion that  the  discussion  which  the  Critique  of  the  aes- 
thetical Judgment  contained  was  regarded  by  Kant  as 
more  important  than  the  Critique  of  the  teleological 
Judgment,  since  it  undertakes  to  determine  whether 
Judgment  prescribes  rules  for  Feeling  just  as  Under- 
standing does  for  Cognition,  and  Reason  for  the  faculty 
of  Desire.     It  would  seem,  therefore,   that  if  the  main 

'R.,  IV,  p.  4.    H.,  V,  175.    B.4. 
2  R.,  IV,  37.    H.,V,  200  f.    B.,37. 
3R.,  IV,  2.     H.,V,  174.     B.,  2. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the   Third  Critique.     27 

object  of  the  third  Critique  was  to  complete  the  critical 
investigation  by  finding  an  a  priori  rule  for  the  feeling 
of  pleasure,  that  that  task  was  completed  by  the  Cri- 
tique of  aesthetical  Judgment.  It  appears,  further,  that 
some  aim  other  than  that  of  merely  completing  his  sys- 
tem moved  Kant  to  issue  the  two  treatises  under  the 
same  cover. 

As  a  supplement  to  the  proposition  that  the  Critique 
of  aesthetical  Judgment  is  all  that  properly  belongs  to 
the  third  Critique,  so  far  as  the  demand  for  architectonic 
unity  is  concerned,  we  derive  the  corollary  that  origin- 
ally Kant  regarded  the  third  Critique  as  effecting  merely 
the  formal,  or  external,  connection  of  the  earlier  Cri- 
tiques as  distinguished  from  the  real  or  inner  mediation 
to  be  described  hereafter.  The  following  passage  from 
the  letter  written  to  Reinhold  in  1787,  supports  the  con- 
clusion that  the  thought  of  real  or  inner  mediation  had 
not  at  that  time  taken  definite  shape  in  Kant's  mind, 
and  that  the  problem  and  final  success  of  discovering  a 
priori  principles  for  all  the  faculties  of  mind  was  then 
of  most  importance  for  him.  "  I  now  recognize,"  he 
writes,  "three  parts  of  Philosophy,  each  of  which  has  its 
own  a  priori  principles.  We  can  now,  therefore,  se- 
curely determine  the  compass  of  knowledge,  which  is 
possible  in  this  way,  as  including  the  three  departments 
of  Theoretical  Philosophy,  Teleology,  and  Practical 
Philosophy."1  All  along  it  was  the  thought  of  establish- 
ing a  priori  principles  for  the  mental  functions  that  was 
of  paramount  importance.  Caird  thus  touches  the  secret 
of  the  delight  which  thrilled  Kant  at  the  discovery  of 
the  key  to  judgments  of  Taste:  "Kant  had  begun  the 
critical  inquiries  in  the  effort  to  separate  the  apparent 
from  the  real,  the  element  in  our  ideas  or  knowledge 

1H.,  VIII,  739,  f.     Caird,  op.  cit..  II,  p.  407. 


28  Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

which  is  peculiar  to  us  as  finite  subjects  whose  reason 
works  through  sense,  from  that  element  which  we  ap- 
prehend in  virtue  of  pure  reason  itself."     Now  the  dis- 
covery of  a  priori  principles  for  the  faculty  of  feeling,  as 
had  been  done  previously  for  knowledge  and  desire,  af- 
forded "  a  fresh  confirmation  of  the  truth  of  his  fundamen- 
tal principles  ".*     For  if  he  had  failed  to  find  the  a  priori 
element  in  the  feeling  of  the  beautiful,  it  would  have 
cast  a  shadow  of  doubt  over  the  soundness  of  the  whole 
critical  procedure  ;  but  since  a  priori  principles  have 
been  discovered  for  this  experience,  and  since  we  may 
now  securely  determine  the  compass  of  knowledge  ac- 
cording to  such  principles,  we  may  have  increased  con- 
fidence in  the  critical  procedure,  its  methods  and  results. 
Furthermore,  if  Kant  designed  the  Critique  of  Taste  to 
represent  a  method  of  uniting  the  different  parts  of  his 
philosophy  into  a  real  system,  or  if  any  such  purpose 
had  occurred  to  him  at  the  time  he  wrote  to  Reinhold 
respecting  the  forthcoming  work,  why  did  he  not  refer 
to  the  fact?     It  is  highly  improbable  that  he  would 
neglect  or  fail  to  mention  so  important  a  function  if  it 
had  then  occurred  to  him.     Still  another  thing   that 
seems  inexplicable  on  the  theory  that  the   Critique  of 
Judgment  was  written  expressly  to  mediate  the  opposing 
results  of  the  earlier  works  is  the  fact  that  nowhere  in 
the  discussion  of  the  aesthetical   and  teleological  judg- 
ments is  there  any  mention  of  '  mediation '.     It  seems 
incredible  that  Kant  should  have  planned  a  work  to 
unite  the  opposing  parts  of  his  system  and  still  make  no 
reference  to  his  purpose  in  the  course  of  the  discussion. 
One  naturally  would  expect  to  find  an  indication  of  the 
way  in  which  the  principle  illustrated  is  to  be  applied. 
The  more  probable  theory  is  that  it  was  after  Kant  de- 

1  Caird.,  op.  cit.,  II,  pp.  409,  406. 


Changes  in  the  Plan  of  the   Third  Critique.     29 

cided  to  unite  the  Critiques  of  aesthetical  and  teleological 
judgment  under  the  same  title,  because  both  center 
about  the  notion  of  purposiveness,  that  it  occurred  to 
him  that  the  third  Critique  would  harmonize  the  re- 
sults of  the  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical  Reason. 

It  is  proper  to  note  at  this  point  that  the  Stadler- 
Adamson  argument  for  regarding  the  Critique  of  aes- 
thetical Judgment  as  the  proper  work  of  the  third  Cri- 
tique lays  special  emphasis  upon  the  fact  that  Kant's 
leading  purpose  was  to  complete  the  system  by  rational- 
izing the  feeling  experience.  Starting  with  this 
assumption  the  conclusion  is  inevitable  that  the  connec- 
tion of  the  Critique  of  the  teleological  with  the  Critique 
of  the  aesthetical  Judgment  is  more  or  less  forced  and 
unnatural.  But  when  we  remember  that  Kant's  final 
and  broader  plan  included  not  only  the  formal  comple- 
tion of  the  critical  investigation,  but  also  proposed  to 
point  out  a  method  of  harmonizing  the  results  of  the 
former  Critiques,  the  reason  for  combining  both  treatises 
under  the  same  title  is  quite  apparent  and  entirely  ade- 
quate. 

The  conclusion  we  reach  from  the  foregoing  argu- 
ment is  that,  in  its  inception,  the  Critique  of  Taste  was 
designed  to  mediate  the  preceding  Critiques  in  so  far, 
and  only  in  so  far,  as  there  was  need  of  such  an  investi- 
gation to  complete  the  work  of  criticism  :  further,  that 
it  was  not  until  after  the  Critique  of  Taste  had  been 
finished,  and  probably  after  it  had  been  united  with  the 
Critique  of  Teleology  under  the  title,  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment, that  the  work  seemed  to  Kant  to  afford  a  principle 
of  real,  or  inner,  mediation  between  the  results  of  the 
former  Critiques. 


PART  II. 

THE    CRITIQUE    OF   JUDGMENT    AS    A    MEDIATING   LINK 
BETWEEN    KANT'S    THEORETICAL    AND   PRAC- 
TICAL  PHILOSOPHY. 

§   I.    FORMAL  AND   REAL  MEDIATION  DISTINGUISHED. 

In  the  Preface  and  Introduction  to  the  Critique  of 
Judgment  the  work  is  described  as  a  mediating  link,  or 
as  supplying  a  principle  of  mediation,  between  the  theo- 
retical and  practical  philosophy.  This  description, 
which  is  quite  brief  and  incomplete,  suggested  the  main 
problems  of  this  part  of  our  investigation  ;  namely,  what 
doctrines  of  the  theoretical  and  practical  philosphy  re- 
quire to  be  mediated  ?  and  what  meaning  can  we  attach 
to  the  expression  '  mediation '  when  applied  to  the  third 
Critique  and  the  place  it  occupies  in  the  critical  philoso- 
phy ? 

Preliminary  to  these  more  important  inquiries,  it  is 
necessary  to  distinguish  the  two  ways  in  which  the 
Critique  of  Judgment  may  be  said  to  mediate  the  Cri- 
tiques of  pure  and  practical  philosophy.  According  to  one 
mode  of  representation  the  mediation  which  the  third  Cri- 
tique affords  is  merely  external  and  formal ;  according 
to  another  it  is  inner  and  real.  It  will  be  necessary,  in 
the  first  place,  to  make  clear  the  distinction  between  for- 
mal, or  external  mediation  and  real,  or  inner  mediation. 
Kant  has  reference  to  formal  mediation  when  he  says 
that,  "  since  Judgment  stands  between  Understanding 
and  Reason  in  the  family  of  the  supreme  cognitive 
faculties,  and  since  the  two  latter  faculties  have  a 
priori    principles    of    legislation,   we    may    judge    by 


Formal  and  Real  Mediation  Distinguished.       31 

analogy  that  Judgment  also  has  a  special  a  priori  prin- 
ciple of  legislation."1  It  was  maintained  in  a  former  sec- 
tion that  the  primary  aim  of  the  third  Critique  (the 
Critique  of  Taste)  was  to  rationalize  judgments  about 
the  beautiful ;  incidentally,  Kant  intended  to  mediate 
the  work  of  the  earlier  Critiques  in  the  sense  that  has 
been  designated  above  as  formal.  Thus,  in  the  preface 
to  the  Critique  of  Judgment,  Kant  states  his  object  to  be 
"  to  determine  whether  Judgment  which  in  the  order  of 
our  cognitive  faculties  forms  a  mediating  link  between 
Understanding  and  Reason,  has  also  a  priori  principles 
for  itself,  and  whether  they  give  a  rule  a  priori  to  the 
feeling  of  pleasure  and  pain  as  the  *  mediating  link ' 
between  the  cognitive  faculty  and  the  faculty  of  desire 
(just  as  the  Understanding  prescribes  laws  a  priori  to 
the  first  and  Reason  to  the  second.")2  The  first  two  Cri- 
tiques had  established  a  priori  principles  for  the  Intel- 
lect and  Will,  and  the  idea  of  completeness  demanded 
that  a  similar  work  be  performed  for  the  faculty  of 
Feeling  which,  in  Kant's  table,  stands  between  Intellect 
and  Will.  That  is,  the  investigation  of  the  feeling  ex- 
perience, and  the  discovery  of  a  priori  principles  for 
judgments  about  the  beautiful  would  complete  the  work 
so  far  as  criticism  was  concerned.  One  more  passage 
may  be  quoted  to  illustrate  what  is  meant  by  formal 
mediation  :  "  Between  Understanding  and  Reason  stands 
Judgment,  of  which  we  have  cause  for  supposing  accord- 
ing to  analogy  that  it  may  contain  in  itself,  if  not  a 
special  legislation,  yet  a  special  principle  of  its  own  to 
be  sought  according  to  laws  though  merely  subjective 
a  priori.  .  .  .  For  the  faculty  of  Knowledge  the 
Understanding   is    alone    legislative     ...     for    the 

XR.  IV,  15.   H.  Ill,  183.   B.  14. 
2R.  IV,  2.    H.  Ill,   174.  B.  2. 


32  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

faculty  of  desire,  Reason  is  alone  a  priori  legislative. 
Now  between  the  faculties  of  knowledge  and  desire 
there  is  the  feeling  of  pleasure  just  as  the  Judgment 
mediates  between  Understanding  and  Reason.  We, 
therefore,  may  suppose  provisionally  that  Judgment  like- 
wise contains  in  itself  an  a  priori  principle."  l 

It  is  at  once  apparent  that  mediation,  as  described  in 
the  foregoing  paragraph,  is  merely  external,  or  formal ; 
that  is,  the  third  Critique  was  designed  to  mediate  be- 
tween the  first  two  Critiques  in  the  sense  that  it  attempts 
to  discover,  exhibit  and  illustrate  the  principle  or  prin- 
ciples underlying  the  activity  of  faculties  which,  in 
Kant's  scheme,  occupy  a  middle  ground.  Judgment 
standing  between  Understanding  and  Reason  supplies  a 
principle  for  feeling  which  is  intermediate  to  cognition 
and  desire.  In  this  sense,  the  third  Critique  fills  a  gap, 
and  by  so  doing  completes  the  task  of  discovering  a 
priori  principles  for  each  of  the  so-called  supreme  cog- 
nitive faculties. 

Reasons  have  already  been  given  for  believing  that 
when  the  third  Critique  was  first  planned,  '  mediation  ' 
meant  for  Kant  no  more  than  bridging  the  gap,  in  the 
manner  indicated  above,  left  by  the  Critiques  of  pure 
and  practical  Reason.  In  other  words,  the  dominating 
purpose  was  not  to  find  a  principle  which  would  unify 
and  harmonize  the  results  of  the  theoretical  and  prac- 
tical philosophy ;  but  it  was  to  discover  the  a  priori 
principle  for  the  faculty  of  Feeling  which  recently  had 
been  coordinated  with  Intellect  and  Will.  Kant  did  not 
consciously  set  about  to  unify,  to  mediate  the  opposing 
results  of  the  two  former  Critiques ;  it  was  rather 
his  task  to  rationalise  the  feeling  experience.  But  as 
the  work  progressed,  as  the  third  Critique  became  en- 

1  R.  IV,  15  f.     H.  Ill,  183  f.     B.  14  f. 


Formal  and  Real  Mediation  Distinguished.       2>Z 

larged  so  as  to  embrace  not  only  a  Critique  of  Taste,  but 
also  a  Critique  of  teleological  Judgment  under  the  title, 
Critique  of  Judgment,  mediation  came  to  have  a  real 
and  very  important  meaning  for  Kant.  He  began  to 
see  that  the  third  Critique  not  only  filled  a  gap  in  the 
critical  investigation,  but  that  it  also  revealed  a  method 
of  harmonising  the  apparently  contradictory  results  of 
the  earlier  Critiques.  It  still  remains  to  show — and  this 
is  the  main  purpose  of  this  investigation — what  is  in- 
volved in  the  notion  of  '  real  mediation,'  and  in  what 
sense  the  Critique  of  Judgment  supplies  such  a  principle. 

We  have  seen  that  Kant  has  reference  to  real  media- 
tion when  he  attributes  to  Judgment  the  function  of 
supplying  a  "principle  of  mediation  between  the  realm 
of  the  concept  of  nature  and  that  of  the  concept  of  free- 
dom." The  same  thought  is  elsewhere  stated  thus : 
"  The  concept  of  the  purposiveness  of  nature  is  fit  to  be 
a  mediating  link  between  the  realm  of  the  natural  con- 
cept and  that  of  the  concept  of  freedom."1  Still  another 
way  of  expressing  the  notion  of  real  mediation  is  as  fol- 
lows :  "Judgment  furnishes  a  concept  that  makes  pos- 
sible the  transition  from  conformity  to  law  in  accordance 
with  the  concept  of  nature  to  final  purpose  in  accordance 
with  the  concept  of  freedom."2 

Before  inquiring  at  length  what  real  mediation  means 
or  involves,  it  will  be  necessary  to  determine  what  mean- 
ings are  conveyed  by  the  somewhat  vague  and  indefinite 
expressions,  "realm  of  the  concept  of  nature",  and 
"  realm  of  the  concept  of  freedom  ".  For  casual  obser- 
vation shows  that  they  are  used  to  express  any  one  of  a 
number  of  things ;  that  their  meaning  varies  with  the 

XR.  IV,  39;  H.  Ill,  203;  B.  41. 
2  R.  IV,  38  ;  H.  Ill,  202  ;  B.  39. 
3 


34  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

context.  Thus  '  realm  of  nature  '  is  used  to  distinguish 
the  phenomenal  from  the  noumenal,  the  sensible  from 
the  supersensible,  the  object  known  from  the  knowing 
subject,  consciousness  of  objects  from  self-consciousness, 
the  world  of  nature  in  strict  conformity  to  physical  law 
from  the  world  of  spirit  under  the  dominion  of  freedom, 
Understanding  and  its  legislation  from  Reason  and  its 
legislation.  The  expression  '  realm  of  freedom  '  is  equiv- 
alent to  the  second  member  of  each  of  this  series  of 
pairs.  To  represent  completely  what  Kant  means  by 
each  of  these  expressions — '  realm  of  the  natural  concept ' 
and  '  realm  of  the  concept  of  freedom  ' — would  involve 
a  statement  of  the  main  doctrines  and  conclusions  of 
the  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical  Reason.  For  '  realm 
of  the  concept  of  nature  '  corresponds  to  the  domain  in 
which  the  principles  of  the  theoretical  philosophy  are 
regnant ;  '  realm  of  the  concept  of  freedom  '  corresponds 
to  the  sphere  in  which  practical  Reason  with  its  legisla- 
tion is  supreme.  It  will  be  necessary,  therefore,  to  state 
and  show  the  mutual  relations  of  the  leading  doctrines 
and  results  of  the  critiques  of  theoretical  and  practical 
philosophy.  For  this  purpose,  however,  it  will  be  suf- 
ficient to  give  a  very  general  outline  of  the  elaborate 
and  intricate  discussions  of  the  two  Critiques,  and  to 
indicate  the  fundamental  features  and  results  of  each 
work. 

§  2.      RELATION  OF  THE   THEORETICAL  AND  PRACTICAL 
PHILOSOPHY. 

It  is  now  proposed  to  represent  the  relation  of  the 
main  results  of  the  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical  Reason 
in  order  to  indicate  more  exactly  the  nature  of  the  op- 
position, or  disharmony,  which  the  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment is  supposed  to  overcome.     First,  with  reference  to 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  35 

the  results  of  the  Critique  of  pure  Reason,  it  will  suf- 
fice to  state  what  seem  to  be  its  main  purpose  and  re- 
sults when  considered  with  reference  to  the  main  con- 
clusions of  the  Critique  of  practical  Reason  and  the 
Critique  of  Judgment.  Viewing  Kant's  system  as  a 
whole,  it  may  be  said  that  the  Critique  of  pure  Reason 
contains  a  doctrine  of  knowledge,  the  Critique  of  prac- 
tical Reason  presents  a  theory  of  morals,  and  the  Cri- 
tique of  Judgment  a  doctrine  of  teleology.  The  main 
purpose  of  the  Critique  of  pure  Reason  is  an  examination 
of.  the  mind  as  an  organ  of  knowledge,  and  its  prob- 
lem is  to  indicate  the  factor  or  factors  which  the  mind 
supplies  in  the  complex  of  experience  called  the  objec- 
tive world  ;  it  is  "  a  determination  of  the  a  priori  prin- 
ciples of  the  faculty  of  cognition  with  reference  to 
their  conditions,  extent,  and  the  limits  of  their  use."  l 
Accordingly,  we  have  presented,  as  Kant  conceived  it, 
a  description  of  how  the  known  world  is  built  up  from 
sense  impressions,  the  forms  of  space  and  time,  and  the 
concepts  of  Understanding.  Kant  starts  with  the  fact  of 
experience,  and  exhibits  the  factors  and  conditions  by 
which  we  come  to  have  what  we  call  a  knowledge  of 
the  world.  Thus  regarded,  the  Critique  of  pure  Reason 
is  essentially  and  primarily  a  presentation  of  a  theory  of 
knowledge.  It  considers  man  as  a  cognitive  being,  and 
explains  the  origin,  presuppositions  and  limits  of  knowl- 
edge. 

But  this  seems  to  be  a  partial  and  inadequate  view  of 
man's  nature ;  it  disregards  an  important  side  or  factor 
of  his  life,  viz.,  the  volitional  side.  Man  is  a  being  that 
wills,  that  has  purposes,  and  ideals,  and  strives  to  realize 
them.     He  not  only  knows  but  wills.     Especially  is  it 

1  R.,  VIII,  115  ;  H.,  V,  11  f.     Abbott,  Kant's  Theory  0/ Ethics,  4th 
ed.,  p.  97. 


36  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

to  be  noted  that  a  philosophy  which  is  limited  to  man's 
cognitive  nature  leaves  out  of  account  the  fact  that  he  is 
a  moral  being  with  moral  ends  to  fulfill.  Not  only  is 
this  mode  of  representation  one-sided  and  incomplete,  but 
it  is  seen  that  if  the  principles,  rules,  and  axioms  which 
are  valid  in  the  phenomenal,  material  world,  are  ex- 
tended and  given  universal  application,  they  threaten  to 
undermine  the  foundations  of  the  moral  and  religious 
life.  This  danger  exists  particularly  with  reference  to 
the  unchecked  extension  of  the  principle  of  causality, 
according  to  which  every  event  must  have  another  pre- 
ceding event  as  its  cause.  The  law  of  causality  demands 
that  every  change  shall  result  from  or  depend  upon  an 
antecedent  change.  This  is  the  view  that  we  are  com- 
pelled to  take,  if  we  look  at  the  world  from  the  standpoint 
of  cognition  ;  we  are  bound  to  follow  the  category  of 
causality,  and,  therefore,  to  regard  every  phenomenon  as 
determined  by  a  preceding  phenomenon.  The  world 
then  presents  the  scene  of  an  endless  series  of  events 
each  of  which  is  caused  by  the  one  preceding  it.  The 
changes  which  man  is  thought  to  effect  in  the  world  are 
no  exception  to  this  rule.  Man,  as  a  member  of  the 
phenomenal  world,  is  subject  to  its  laws,  is  impelled  by 
its  forces,  is  carried  along  like  a  material  thing  by  the 
irresistible  course  of  events. 

Now  this  manner  of  extending  the  use  of  the  notion 
of  causality  seemed  to  Kant  to  exclude  all  moral  action 
and  to  render  moral  legislation  futile.  For,  as  will  be 
remembered,  according  to  Kant's  way  of  conceiving  the 
matter,  man's  actions,  so  far  as  they  are  incited  by  in- 
fluences from  the  phenomenal  world,  are  non-moral. 
Man's  conduct,  so  far  as  it  is  determined  by  sensuous 
motives  of  pleasure  and  pain,  has  no  moral  worth  what- 
ever.    Hence,  the  possibility  of  morality  is  dependent 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  37 

upon  the  possibility  of  establishing  a  ground  of  activity 
for  man's  will  free  from  all  sensuous  motives.  There 
thus  arises  the  necessity  of  inquiring  whether  there  is  a 
determination  of  Will  independent  of  influences  from  the 
sensible  world.  The  first  and  most  important  task  of 
practical  philosophy  is,  therefore,  "  to  determine  whether 
pure  reason  of  itself  alone  suffices  to  determine  the  Will, 
or  whether  it  can  be  a  ground  of  determination  only  on 
empirical  conditions."  x  The  Critique  of  Practical  Rea- 
son inquires  whether  man  has  the  power  of  free  self-deter- 
mination in  accordance  with  moral  maxims  which  are 
self-derived  and  self-imposed.  Kant  is  thus  seen  to  have  a 
double  purpose  in  view ;  viz.,  to  establish  freedom,  and 
also  to  displace  the  hedonistic  ethical  doctrines  of  his 
time.  "  To  this  Eudaemonism  which  was  destitute  of 
stability  and  consistency,  and  which  left  the  door  and 
gate  wide  open  for  every  whim  and  caprice,  Kant  op- 
posed the  Practical  Reason  and  thus  emphasized  the 
need  for  a  principle  of  Will  which  should  be  universal 
and  lay  the  same  obligation  on  all."  2  The  vindication 
of  freedom  involved  the  establishment  of  principles  of 
legislation  for  the  moral  activities  of  the  Will  inde- 
pendent of  all  reference  to  pleasure-pain  motives,  and 
the  proof  that  reason  legislates  a  priori  for  Will  is  at 
the  same  time  the  proof  of  freedom. 

XR.,  VIII,  119 ;  H.,  V.,  15.     Abbott,  op.  tit.,  101. 

2  Hegel,  Werke,  VI,  p.  115.     Wallace,  Trans,  of  Logic,  p.  111. 

Note. — Hegel's  use  of  the  word  '  Kudaemonismus '  to  indicate 
the  doctrines  against  which  Kant  '  opposed  the  practical  rea- 
son' is  not  altogether  happy.  The  word  '  hedonism  '  describes  more 
accurately  the  kind  of  ethical  teaching  against  which  Kant  was  pro- 
testing. For  the  word  evBatixovta  as  used  by  Plato,  Aristotle  and  the 
Stoics  included  not  only  the  well-being  of  the  sentient-self  (Hedon- 
ism), but  also  the  well-being  of  the  rational  self.  For  full  discussion 
of  the  distinction  between  Hedonism  and  Eudaemonism,  see  Professor 
J.  Seth's  Study  of  Ethical  Principles,  Part  I. 


38  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

We  shall  now  have  to  set  forth  Kant's  method  of 
establishing  the  postulate  of  freedom.  Briefly  put, 
the  ground  of  the  belief  in  freedom — the  ratio  cogno- 
scendi — is  the  consciousness  of  the  "ought",  the  feeling 
of  moral  obligation,  the  sense  of  duty  to  which  every 
one  feels  himself  subject.  The  fact  that  we  feel  that  we 
ought  to  do  certain  things  and  refrain  from  doing  others 
proves  that  we  can.  uThou  oughtst,  therefore,  thou 
canst."  Otherwise,  we  should  not  understand  the  sense 
of  duty  which  every  one  experiences ;  it  would  be  im- 
possible to  understand  the  force  and  absoluteness  of  the 
decrees  of  practical  Reason  without  supposing  that  man 
is  free  to  comply  with  them.  Since  conscience  issues 
unconditional  commands  for  the  performance  of  certain 
actions  and  forbids  the  performance  of  others,  we  must 
believe  that  man  is  free  to  obey  its  dictates.  Thus  free- 
dom, which  had  no  standing  in  the  theoretical  Phil- 
osophy, is  established  for  practical  Philosophy  by  the 
consciousness  of  duty. 

But  it  is  not  enough  to  show  that  the  Will  is  free  to 
act  according  to  the  dictates  of  self-derived  rules,  to  prove 
that  Reason  is  the  sole  determining  principle  of  the 
moral  will ;  it  must  be  possible  for  the  principles  of  Rea- 
son to  find  objecti vation.  u  Reason  first  becomes  practi- 
cal in  the  true  sense  of  the  word  when  it  insists  upon 
the  good  being  manifested  in  the  world  with  an  outward 
objectivity.  " l  That  is,  when  the  Will,,  which  recognizes 
the  obligation  of  the  moral  law,  seeks  to  give  that  law 
objective  realization.  Kant  was  not  content  to  confine 
the  legislation  of  Reason  to  a  mere  formal  determination 
of  the  Will  which  would  leave  it  unrelated  and  incapa- 
ble of  being  related  to  the  concrete  actions  of  man. 
Reason  must  have  an  object  to  realize — an  object  the 

1  Hegel,  Werke,  VI,  p.  115.     Wallace,   Trans,  of  Logic,  p.  no. 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.   39 

realization  of  which  forms  for  Kant  the  summum 
bonum}  And  while  Kant  would  not  admit  that  the 
need  of  realizing  the  highest  good  can  become  a  ground 
of  determination  for  the  Will — for  the  basis  of  that  obli- 
gation is  wholly  subjective — yet  the  chief  good  is  the 
necessary  object  of  a  Will  practically  determined. 

But  an  obstacle  to  the  attainment  of  the  summum  bo- 
num arises  from  the  fact  that  man's  conduct  is  not  wholly 
guided  by  the  law  of  reason ;  he  is  a  member  of  the  sen- 
sible world  and,  as  such,  is  ever  open  to  influences  from 
that  world  ;  and  so  long  as  his  actions  are  partially  em- 
pirically determined  he  is  ipso  facto  incapable  of  attain- 
ing the  fundamental  element  of  the  chief  good — holiness. 
"  The  perfect  accordance  of  the  Will  with  the  moral  law 
is  holiness,  a  perfection  of  which  no  rational  being  of  the 
sensible  world  is  capable  at  any  moment  of  his  exist- 
ence. "  2  Kant  gets  over  this  difficulty  by  the  thought 
of  a  progress  in  infinitum  in  which  there  is  an  increas- 
ing harmony  between  the  empirical  and  rational  deter- 
minations of  will.  "It  is  only  in  an  endless  progress 
that  we  can  attain  perfect  accordance  with  the  moral 
law.  "  3  An  endless  process  of  culture  and  discipline  is 
required  to  reach  a  state  of  holiness.  "  This  endless 
progress  is  possible  only  on  the  supposition  of  an  endless 
duration  of  the  existence  and  personality  of  the  same  ra- 

1  Note.  The  summum  bonum  in  Kant's  Ethics  is  the  union  of  per- 
fect virtue  and  perfect  happiness.  One  who  has  attained  a  state  of 
perfect  virtue  combined  with  perfect  happiness  has  achieved  the  high- 
est good.  Kant  did  not  dissociate  holiness  and  happiness  and  regard 
one  as  the  chief  good,  the  other  as  a  means  to  that  good,  as  had  been 
the  custom  of  moralists  from  the  beginning  of  speculation  upon  the 
subject  of  the  summum  bonum.  Neither  of  these  factors  is  the  cause 
or  ground  of  the  other,  for  the  notion  of  the  highest  good  includes 
both. 

*  R.,  VIII,  261  ;  H.,  V,  128.     Abbott,  op.  cit,  218. 

3  R.,  VIII,  p.  262  ;  H.,  V,  128.     Abbott,  op.  cit.,  219. 


4-0         Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

tional  being  ( which  is  called  immortality  of  the  soul ).  "  * 
Kant  thus  overcame  the  difficulty  resulting  from  an  an- 
tagonism between  the  sensuous  and  rational  motives  to 
action  by  supposing  that  in  an  infinite  series  of  steps  the 
two  kinds  of  motives  will  be  brought  into  accord.  The 
possibility  of  this  infinite  progress  depends  upon  the 
continued  existence  of  the  soul,  immortality. 

We  saw  above  ( note  p.  39)  that  the  moral  law  leads 
us  to  affirm  the  possibility  of  the  second  element  of  the 
siimmum  bonum,  viz.,  happiness  proportioned  to  virtue. 
Although  happiness  is  never  a  motive  to  virtuous  con- 
duct ( for  then  the  conduct  would  cease  to  be  moral  since 
the  sole  spring  of  moral  conduct  is  reverence  for  the  mo- 
ral law ),  it  must  be  conceived  as  always  attending  it. 
But  it  would  be  far  from  the  truth  to  assert  that  happi- 
ness does  in  all  cases  accompany  virtuous  acting  ;  on  the 
contrary,  we  observe  that  very  many  noble  deeds  are  in- 
evitably accompanied  by  suffering.  There  is  no  neces- 
sary connection  between  goodness  and  happiness  so  far 
as  we  can  see.  "  Good  and  evil  fortunes  fall  to  the  lot 
of  pious  and  impious  alike."  Happiness  is  defined 
as  "  the  condition  of  a  rational  being  in  the  world 
with  whom  everything  goes  according  to  his  wish  and 
will.  "  But  since  man  is  not  the  cause  of  the  world, 
and  is  not  able  to  bring  it  into  harmony  with  his  practi- 
cal principles,  we  must  postulate  the  existence  of  a  Be- 
ing who  will  bring  about  this  harmony.  To  insure  the 
realization  of  the  second  element  of  the  summum  bonum, 
happiness,  we  postulate  the  existence  of  a  Power  or  Be- 
ing great  enough  to  bring  into  accord  the  world  and 
man's  moral  character.  Not  only  must  such  a  Being 
have  sufficient  power,  but  he  must  also  have  the  disposi- 
tion to  effect  this  harmony.     "  The  summum  bonum  is 

1R.,  VIII,  262  ;  H.,  V,  128.     Abbott,  op.  cit.\  218. 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  41 

possible  in  the  world  only  on  the  supposition  of  a  Supreme 
Being  having  a  causality  corresponding  to  moral  charac- 
ter. "  1  We  assume  that  the  same  power  which  impels 
man  to  moral  conduct  is  the  same  power  which  lies  at  the 
basis  of  nature,  and  will  ultimately  bring  nature  into  ac- 
cord with  man's  reason  thus  insuring  his  happiness.  Such 
a  power  is  God.  To  sum  up  the  foregoing — the  con- 
sciousness of  the  "  ought  ",  the  consciousness  of  being  de- 
termined by  the  moral  law  leads  us  to  postulate  freedom 
as  the  first  condition  of  obedience  to  that  law ;  secondly, 
the  complete  fulfillment  of  the  moral  law,  the  attainment 
of  perfect  virtue  requires  an  eternity  of  existence,  immor- 
tality, for  the  same  rational  being.  In  the  third  place, 
the  demand  that  happiness  shall  be  proportionate 
to  goodness  leads  us  to  postulate  the  existence  of  a  "  Be- 
ing distinct  from  nature  itself  and  containing  the  prin- 
ciple of  connexion  between  happiness  and  goodness.  " 2 
Upon  these  three  Ideas — God,  Freedom,  and  Immortal- 
ity— Ideas,  which  in  the  Critique  of  theoretical  Reason 
had  been  declared  incapable  of  demonstration,  Kant  con- 
structed his  ethical  and  religious  systems. 

Although  the  opposition  between  the  Critiques  of 
theoretical  and  practical  philosophy  extends  to  all  of 
these  ideas,  it  arises  primarily  and  chiefly  with  reference 
to  the  concept  of  Freedom — '  the  fundamental  concept 
of  all  unconditioned  practical  laws ' — the  corner-stone  of 
Kant's  ethical  system.  Theoretical  Reason  declares  that 
every  event  in  the  world  is  connected  according  to  the 
law  of  cause  and  effect,  that  there  is  only  an  endless 
chain  of  physical  events  each  of  which  is  determined 
by  the  one  preceding  it.  Practical  Reason  claims  for 
man  exemption  from  this  mechanically  fixed  order  of 

1  R,  VIII,  264  ;  H.,  V.  130  f.     Abbott,  op.  cit.,  221  f. 

2  R.,  VIII,  264  ;  H.,  V,  130.     Abbott,  op.  cit.,  221. 


42  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

things,  and  endows  him  with  the  power  of  free,  spon- 
taneous origination,  independent  of  external,  physical 
influences.  Practical  Reason  is  impelled  and  guided  by 
an  '  ought '  which  theoretical  Reason  brushes  aside  as 
hollow  and  meaningless.  "  Our  Understanding  can 
know  nothing  of  a  natural  world  except  what  is)  what 
has  been,  or  what  will  be.  '  Ought '  has  no  meaning 
whatever  in  nature.  We  cannot  inquire  what  ought  to 
happen  in  nature,  any  more  than  we  can  inquire  what 
properties  a  circle  ought  to  have.  The  *  ought '  ex- 
presses a  possible  action,  the  ground  of  which  cannot  be 
anything  but  a  mere  concept ;  while  in  every  merely 
natural  action  the  ground  must  always  be  a  phenome- 
non."1 It  is  clear,  therefore,  that  the  opposition  between 
the  first  two  Critiques  centers  about  the  conflict  between 
the  principles  of  freedom  and  necessity  ;  viewed  broadly 
it  is  the  opposition  between  the  teleological  and  mechan- 
ical views  of  the  world.  In  its  narrower  form  the  ques- 
tion is,  can  there  be  a  causality  of  concepts, — in  the 
present  case  of  moral  concepts — or  must  all  causes 
be  conceived  as  material?  The  latter  view  domin- 
ated the  scientific  thought  of  Kant's  time,  as  it  does 
that  of  the  present.  The  principles  of  physical  science 
are  employed  not  only  in  determining  the  world 
of  matter,  but  are  extended  to  the  world  of  spirit  as  well. 
Physics  can  find  no  place  for  freedom,  and  declares  our 
experience  of  it  to  be  a  delusion.  The  scientific  position 
is  well  expressed  in  Spinoza's  famous  saying,  l  that  a 
stone  and  a  human  being  are  equally  determined  to 
exist  and  operate  in  a  fixed  and  determinate  manner,' 
the  only  difference  being  that  the  actions  of  man  are 
accompanied  by  consciousness.  "  But  that  Reason  has  a 
causality,  or  at  least  that  we  represent  it  as  having  such 
1 R.  II,  429 ;  H.  in,  379  ;  M.  11,  472. 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  43 

a  causality,  is  clear  from  the  imperatives  which  in  all 
our  practical  life  we  impose  as  rules  upon  our  executive 
powers.  The  ought  expresses  a  kind  of  necessity,  a  kind 
of  connection  of  actions  with  their  grounds  or  reasons 
such  as  is  to  be  found  nowhere  else  in  nature."  * 

The  relation  of  the  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical 
philosophy  with  reference  to  the  problem  of  freedom 
may  be  further  illustrated  by  considering  two  different 
relations  in  which  man  stands  to  the  physical  world. 
First,  he  may  be  thought  as  merely  one  object  among 
an  infinitude  of  other  objects,  as  one  atom  in  a  sea  of 
atoms.  As  such,  he  is  subject  to  the  same  influences,  is 
played  upon  and  controlled  by  the  same  forces  as  any 
other  object  in  nature.  All  the  laws  which  are  applica- 
ble to  the  physical  world  are  applicable  to  him  as  a 
member  of  that  world.  He  is  regarded,  like  other  ob- 
jects of  the  phenomenal  world,  according  to  the  laws  of 
nature  and  necessity.  All  his  states  and  changes  are 
determined  by  his  relation  to  other  objects.  Conceived 
as  merely  phenomenal,  man  is  only  a  link  in  an  endless 
chain  of  events  which  constitutes  the  physical  series. 

But  to  restrict  ourselves  to  this  one  relation  or  view 
would  be  partial  and  inadequate.  Reflection  suggests 
another  important  relation  in  which  man  stands  to  the 
world  of  objects.  In  addition  to  his  consciousness  of 
himself  as  a  phenomenon,  as  one  object  among  other 
objects,  man  is  also  conscious  of  himself  as  entirely 
separated  from  and  above  the  world  of  objects,  out  of  the 
natural  order  of  things,  a  supersensible  or  intelligible 
being,  a  noumenon.  He  feels  himself  to  be  free  and  in- 
dependent of  the  phenomenal  world,  acting  with  perfect 
spontaneity  according  to  laws  of  his  own  being.  Accord- 
ing to  this  latter  view,  man  is  independent  of  the  affec- 

1  R.  ii,  429 ;  H.  Ill,  379  ;  M.  II,  472. 


44  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

tions  of  sense,  and  apart  from  the  empirically  condi- 
tioned ;  he  is  a  purely  intelligible  being  and  so  in  virtue 
of  the  practical  Reason,  "  which  is  properly  and  pre- 
eminently distinct  from  all  empirically  conditioned 
powers  in  virtue  of  a  free  will  which  acts  from  motives 
entirely  self-derived,  not  on  motives  excited  by  external 
objects." 

We  have  seen  that  the  activities  of  man,  regarded  as 
a  phenomenon,  result  from  external  influences ;  but 
man  regarded  as  a  noumenon  is  under  no  influence  ex- 
cept the  demands  of  Reason,  or  the  moral  law  prescribed 
by  Reason.  He  finds  the  springs  of  his  activity  wholly 
within  his  rational  nature  unmixed  with  any  external 
motives  whatever.  All  his  actions  as  a  rational  being 
spring  from,  and  are  guided  by,  self-derived  and  self-im- 
posed laws  of  Reason.  This  manner  of  conceiving 
man's  relation  to  the  sensible  world  brings  into  promi- 
nence Kant's  distinction  between  the  noumenal  and  phe- 
nomenal world,  between  the  intelligible  and  empirical 
self.  As  a  member  of  the  phenomenal  world,  man's 
will  is  subject  to  natural  necessity ;  as  a  member  of  the 
noumenal  world,  his  will  is  under  the  law  of  freedom. 
Freedom  is  thus  saved  by  postulating  beyond  the  phe- 
nomenal world  a  noumenal  or  supersensible  world.  It  is 
impossible  to  determine  this  noumenal  world  in  any 
way  whatever,  but  so  long  as  we  are  compelled  to 
think  it,  so  long  as  we  believe  in  its  existence,  so 
long  are  we  justified  in  refusing  to  admit  the  uni- 
versal applicability  of  the  principles  of  physical 
science,  especially  may  we  justly  exclude  them  from  the 
province  of  the  supersensible.  Here  the  Reason  lays 
claim  to  absolute  dominion  ;  into  this  territory  it  retreats 
and  finds  security.  "  We  are  not  on  sufferance  in  our 
possession,  when,  though  our  own  title  may  not  be  suffi- 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  45 

cient,  it  is  nevertheless  quite  certain  that  no  one  can 
ever  prove  its  insufficiency."  !  Freedom  thus  protects 
herself  against  the  attacks  of  science  by  withdrawing 
from  the  phenomenal  plane  and  taking  refuge  in  a 
stronghold  where  science  cannot  follow.  The  importance 
of  this  defense  for  Kant  is  thus  stated  by  Caird  :  "  It 
protects  the  moral  and  religious  life  from  the  danger  of 
being  considered  illusory  on  one  special  ground,  viz., 
that  it  and  its  objects  cannot  be  brought  within  the  cir- 
cle of  ordinary  experience  and  ordinary  science,  or  de- 
termined by  the  categories  that  hold  good  there."  2 

But  this  method  of  protecting  freedom  seems  to  render 
it  utterly  useless.  The  conception  of  man  as  a  noume- 
non  seems  entirely  to  exclude  him  from  all  relation  to, 
or  connection  with  the  world  of  experience ;  it  places 
him  upon  an  entirely  different  plane  wholly  unrelated 
to  the  phenomenal.  But  if  man's  freedom  is  to  mean 
anything,  if  moral  purposes  are  to  be  more  than  idle 
dreams,  the  concepts  of  morality  must  be  capable  of  act- 
ualization in  the  phenomenal  world.  Freedom,  if  it  is 
worth  anything,  must  be  able  to  exert  an  influence  upon 
the  course  of  events,  it  must  be  a  cause  in  the  world  of 
nature,  it  must  be  able  to  mould  the  objects  of  nature 
with  reference  to  the  ends  of  freedom.  If  freedom  is  to 
be  saved  from  the  hollowness  which  threatens  it,  the 
world  must  be  determinable  in  conformity  to  the  laws 
of  practical  Reason. 

It  is  thus  seen  that  in  Kant's  ethics  there  is  a  constant 
struggle  between  the  necessity  of  preserving  the  purity 
of  the  determining  principles  of  moral  activity,  and  the 
demand  that  in  so  doing  the  moral  law  shall  not  be  de- 
graded into  a  barren,   abstract,  contentless  non-entity. 

1  R.,  II,  572  ;  H.,  Ill,  493  ;  M.,  II,  634. 

2  Caird,  Crit.  Phil,  of  Kant,  II,  p.  157. 


46  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

There  is  no  direct  evidence  that  Kant  was  fully  aware 
of  these  conflicting  tendencies  of  his  system  ;  but  when 
we  remember  the  prominent  place  which  the  summum 
bonum  occupies  in  his  system,  when  we  remember  "  that 
the  promotion  of  the  summum  bonum  is  a  priori  a 
necessary  object  of  our  will  and  inseparably  attached  to 
the  moral  law,"  we  are  led  to  think  that  Kant  realized 
the  absurdity  of  demanding  obedience  to  the  law  solely 
for  the  law's  sake.  Man,  as  a  rational  being,  cannot  act 
without  motives,  and  the  bare  law  in  itself  affords  no 
motive.  We  may  suppose,  therefore,  that  Kant  was 
alive  to  the  danger  of  depriving  the  notion  of  free- 
dom of  all  worth,  of  emptying  the  moral  law  of  all 
content.  Accordingly  he  made  partial  provision  against 
the  hollowness  and  abstractness  which  threatened  his 
conception  of  freedom  and  the  "  ought  "  by  reference  to 
the  notion  of  the  summum  bonum  as  "  the  necessary  ob- 
ject of  a  Will  determinable  by  the  moral  law."  Still, 
Kant  never  wavered  in  his  insistence  upon  the  doctrine 
that  the  summum  bonum  can  never  be  regarded  as  a  mo- 
tive to  virtuous  conduct ;  for  that  motive  is  always 
grounded  in  the  pure  reason.  And  although  Kant  urges 
us  to  think  the  summum  bonum  as  the  proper  object  of 
a  Will  acting  under  the  moral  law,  one  still  feels  that 
he  could  have  made  more  adequate  provision  against  the 
danger  of  abstractness  which  hampers  his  doctrine  by 
bringing  the  idea  of  the  summum  bonum  into  more  im- 
mediate relation  to  the  concrete  life  of  man. 

In  summing  up  the  results  of  the  present  section  it 
may  be  said  that  the  function  of  the  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason  is  to  explain  experience,  to  discover  and  confirm 
the  principles,  rules  and  presuppositions  of  physical 
science  ;  the  purpose  of  the  Critique  of  Practical  Rea- 
son is  to  exhibit  the  a  priori  rules  of  practical  Reason, 


Relation  of  Theoretical  and  Practical  Philosophy.  47 

to  discover  and  confirm  the  maxims  and  postulates  of 
morals  and  religion.  The  doctrines  enunciated  and  the 
principles  established  in  the  two  Critiques  if  not  an- 
tagonistic are  at  least  inconsistent,  or  rather  wholly  dis- 
parate and  incommensurable.  Kant's  own  statement 
brings  out  very  clearly  the  province  or  function  of  each 
Critique,  and,  at  the  same,  the  contradictory  character 
of  the  principles  which  they  elaborate  : — "  The  Under- 
standing legislates  a  priori  for  nature  as  an  object  of 
sense  :  Reason  legislates  a  priori  for  freedom  and  its 
peculiar  causality.  The  realm  of  the  natural  concept 
under  the  one  legislation,  and  that  of  the  concept  of  free- 
dom under  the  other  are  entirely  removed  from  all 
mutual  influence.  The  concept  of  freedom  determines 
nothing  in  respect  of  the  theoretical  cognition  of  nature  ; 
and  the  natural  concept  determines  nothing  in  respect 
of  the  practical  laws  of  freedom.  So  far  then  it  is  not 
possible  to  throw  a  bridge  from  the  one  realm  to  the 
other." l  Legislation  by  the  Understanding  is  valid 
only  for  cognition  ;  legislation  by  Reason  is  valid  only 
for  the  Will.  The  province  of  the  one  is  nature ;  the 
province  of  the  other  is  the  moral  and  religious  life. 
There  can  be  no  mutual  influence  between  the  two 
realms,  there  must  be  no  encroachment  by  either  upon 
the  domain  of  the  other.  On  the  one  side,  we  see 
physical  science  asserting,  in  accordance  with  the  prin- 
ciples of  the  understanding,  that  every  event  must  come 
under  the  inexorable  law  of  physical  causality,  that 
every  phenomenal  effect  can  have  only  a  physical  cause. 
Even  the  actions  of  man  are  no  exception  to  the  uni- 
versality and  necessity  of  the  law  of  causality.  On  the 
other  hand,  it  is  maintained  that  c  man  is  possessed  of  an 
active  and  spontaneously  energizing  faculty ',  that  he 

aR.,IV,  36,  f.^  H.,V,  201;  B.,    38. 


48  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

has  a  causality  which  is  free  and  independent  of  the 
physical  world.  "  Reason  frames  for  itself  with  perfect 
spontaneity  a  new  order  of  things  according  to  ideas.  '•' 
That  is,  man  conceives  and  realizes  moral  ideals  inde- 
pendently of  external  influences.  Kant  continues,  "  Now 
although  an  immeasurable  gulf  is  thus  placed  between  the 
realm  of  nature  and  the  realm  of  freedom  so  that  no  tran- 
sition from  the  first  to  the  second  is  possible,  yet  the  second 
is  meant  to  have  an  influence  upon  the  first.  The  concept 
of  freedom  is  meant  to  realize  in  the  world  of  sense  the 
purpose  proposed  by  its  laws,  and  consequently  nature 
must  be  so  thought  that  the  conformity  to  law  of  its 
form,  at  least  harmonizes  with  the  possibilities  of  the 
purposes  to  be  effected  in  it  according  to  the  laws  of 
freedom.  "  l  The  relation  of  the  notions  of  nature  and 
freedom,  and  so  of  the  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical 
Reason,  which  deal  respectively  with  those  ideas,  is  ad- 
mirably stated  by  Bosanquet  in  a  passage  which,  at  the 
same  time,  indicates  the  function  of  the  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment in  the  Critical  Philosophy  :  "In  his  life-long  labor 
for  the  reorganization  of  philosophy,  Kant  may  be  said  to 
have  aimed  at  three  cardinal  points.  First,  he  desired  to 
justify  the  conception  of  a  natural  order  ;  secondly,  the 
conception  of  a  moral  order ;  thirdly,  the  conception  of 
compatibility  between  the  natural  and  the  moral  order. 
The  first  of  these  problems  formed  the  substance  of  the 
Critique  of  pure  Reason  ;  the  second  was  treated  in  the 
Critique  of  practical  Reason  ;  the  third  necessarily  arose 
out  of  the  relation  between  the  other  two.  .  .  .  And 
although  the  formal  compatibility  of  nature  and  rea- 
son had  been  established  by  Kant,  as  he  believed,  in 
the  negative  demarcation  between  them  which  the  first 

1R,  IV,  14;  H.,  V,  182;  B.   12. 


Kanfs  Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  49 

two  Critiques  expounded,  it  was  inevitable  that  he  should 
subsequently  be  led  on  to  suggest  some  more  positive 
conciliation.  This  attempt  was  made  in  the  Critique  of 
the  Power  of  Judgment.  "  1  Kant  finds  the  key  to  the 
'  more  positive  conciliation '  between  the  law  and  order 
of  the  natural  world,  and  the  principles  dominating  the 
realm  of  morals,  in  the  thought  of  a  "  ground  of  unity  " 
underlying  both  nature  and  freedom.  His  words  are  : 
"  There  must  be  a  ground  of  the  unity  of  the  supersensi- 
ble which  lies  at  the  basis  of  nature  with  that  which  the 
concept  of  freedom  practically  contains.  " 2  The  same 
force  or  power  manifest  in  and  through  the  natural  or 
material  world  must  be  thought  as  having  the  same 
character,  the  same  ultimate  purpose,  as  that  force  which 
expresses  itself  in  the  will  of  man  acting  under  the  moral 
law.  The  law  and  necessity  prevailing  in  the  physical 
world  must  spring,  according  to  the  sentence  quoted, 
from  the  same  ground  which  underlies  the  determination 
of  the  Will  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of  freedom.  It 
now  remains  to  consider  the  evidence  for  the  existence 
of  this  '  ground  of  unity '  which  Kant  has  collected  in 
the  Critique  of  Judgment,  and,  also,  the  way  in  which 
this  principle  can  be  used  to  complete  the  results  of  the 
first  two  Critiques. 

§  3.  KANT'S  THEORY  OF  THE  BEAUTIFUL. 

In  Part  I,  reasons  were  assigned  for  believing  that 
when  Kant  began  the  investigation  of  judgments  con- 
cerning the  Beautiful  his  main  purpose  was  to  ration- 
alize those  judgments,  to  put  them  upon  a  firm,  reasoned 
foundation  by  exhibiting  the  a  priori  element  which 
underlies  them.     The  Critiques  of  pure  and  practical 

1  Bosanquet,  History  of  Aesthetics,  p.  256  f. 

2  R.,  IV,  14.     H.,  V,  182.     B.,12. 

4 


50  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

reason  had  established  a  priori  principles  for  cognition 
and  desire,  and  if  a  like  work  could  be  performed  for 
feeling,  which  stands  between  those  two  faculties, 
the  system  would  be  complete,  each  part  would  stand 
upon  a  fully  formulated  basis  of  a  priori  truth.  It  was 
also  explained  how  Kant  came  to  regard  purposiveness 
as  the  principle  underlying  the  activity  of  the  reflective 
Judgment ;  also  how,  in  the  course  of  his  reflections,  it 
occurred  to  him  that  the  principle  of  purposiveness, 
which  is  the  principle  of  the  reflective  Judgment,  afforded 
a  means  of  real  mediation  between  the  theoretical  and 
the  practical  philosophy.  But  there  is  no  attempt  to  ap- 
ply the  principle,  or  to  illustrate  what  is  meant  by  the 
statement  that  '  Judgment  supplies  a  mediating  principle 
between  the  concepts  of  freedom  and  nature.'  It  is  use- 
less to  conjecture  why  Kant  failed  to  perform  this  im- 
portant work,  why  he  failed  to  show  how  the  results  of 
the  Critique  of  Judgment  mediate  in  a  real  sense  the 
results  of  the  earlier  Critiques.  We  have  the  bare  state- 
ment that  purposiveness,  the  principle  which  the  re- 
flective Judgment  employs,  affords  a  means  of  transition 
from  freedom  to  nature,  and  with  that  statement  the 
matter  is  dismissed. 

Our  aim,  in  the  remaining  sections  of  this  essay, 
will  be  to  follow  out  Kant's  hint  by  showing  how 
the  Critique  of  Judgment,  with  its  fundamental  con- 
cept of  purposiveness,  mediates,  or  affords  a  principle 
of  mediation,  in  a  real  sense  between  the  Critiques  of 
theoretical  and  practical  philosophy.  It  will  be  re- 
membered that  the  Critique  of  theoretical  philoso- 
phy has  to  do  with  the  realm  of  nature,  while  the  Cri- 
tique of  practical  philosophy  has  to  do  with  the  realm  of 
freedom.  Purposiveness,  therefore,  is  conceived  as 
bridging  the  chasm  between  these  two  realms,  or  to  use 
less  metaphorical  language,  the  notion  of  design  brings 


KanPs   Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  51 

into  closer  relation  the  modes  of  thought  prevailing  in 
the  theoretical  and  practical  domains.  Broadly  speak- 
ing, the  consideration  of  the  third  Critique  as  a  means 
of  combining  the  results  of  the  earlier  Critiques  resolves 
itself  into  a  consideration  of  the  evidence  adduced  in 
that  Critique  in  support  of  the  theory  that  there  is  pur- 
pose in  nature.  But  it  must  not  be  inferred  from  this 
statement  that  Kant  started  with  the  hypothesis  that 
nature  is  purposive  and  went  in  search  of  facts  to  sup- 
port this  hypothesis.  For  his  method  was  quite  the  re- 
verse of  this.  Certain  phenomena  which  attracted  his 
attention  seemed  inexplicable  except  by  supposing  that 
they  were  the  result  of  design.  They  resisted  the 
ordinary  methods  of  explanation  and  called  for  a  new 
category  ;  that  category  Kant  called  purposiveness. 

It  may  be  well  at  this  point  to  anticipate  an  inquiry 
that  properly  belongs  in  a  later  connection,  and  ask 
what  is  involved  in  the  notion  of  purpose  ?  What  do  we 
mean  by  saying  that  a  thing  is  purposive,  and  what  does 
it  imply  ?  In  the  first  place,  the  notion  of  purpose  implies 
an  Intelligence  which  forms  plansv&nd  has  the  power  to 
execute  them.  It  implies  freedom,  a  '  thinking  Will.' 
Briefly  put,  therefore,  the  Critique  ofjttdgment  contains 
a  description  and  analysis  of  the  phenomena  which  com- 
pel us  to  believe  that  there  is  a  '  thinking  Will '  behind 
the  world.  And  this  point  of  view  is  forced  upon  us  when 
we  are  dealing  with  the  Beautiful  and  with  the  forms 
of  organic  nature.  Since  these  objects  require  us  to 
think  that  purpose  is  the  ground  of  their  existence,  they 
contain  in  themselves  a  union  of  freedom  and  nature ; 
the  purposiveness  which  they  exhibit,  or  suggest, 
implies  the  presence  of  a  force  acting  freely.  Beautiful 
objects  and  organic  products  as  members  of  the  realm  of 
nature  are  at  the  same   time   the  embodiments  of  con- 


52  Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

cepts  of  freedom.  In  them  we  find  examples  of  the  con- 
crete union,  or  blending,  of  the  notions  of  free- 
dom and  nature.  In  other  words,  the  Beautiful  and  the 
Organic  are  examples  of  '  concrete  Ideas ;'  they  are 
realized  ideals. 

Having  explained  briefly  what  is  implied  in  the  idea 
of  purpose,  let  us  return  to  the  consideration  of  the  no- 
tion of  purposiveness  as  a  means  of  uniting  the  parts  of 
the  Critical  Philosophy.  It  was  stated  in  the  preceding 
paragraph,  that  in  the  Critique  of  Judgment,  Kant  gives 
an  explanation  of  the  beautiful  and  the  organic,  and 
that  the  key  to  the  explanation  of  those  phenomena  is 
found  in  the  notion  of  purposiveness.  These  objects  are 
explained  by  the  idea  of  design  ;  at  the  same  time,  we 
get  an  insight  into  the  content  of  that  idea  by  examin- 
ing beautiful  objects  and  the  phenomena  of  organic 
nature.  It  will  be  necessary,  therefore,  in  order  to 
understand  how  the  idea  of  design,  or  purposiveness 
mediates  the  results  of  the  first  two  Critiques,  to  present 
Kant's  theory  of  the  Beautiful  and  the  Organic.  It 
will  be  most  convenient  to  set  forth  his  theory  of  each 
of  these  classes  of  phenomena  separately ;  also  to  con- 
sider them  separately  with  reference  to  the  doctrine  of 
mediation. 

( i )  The  theory  of  the  beautiful.  In  undertaking 
the  criticism  of  aesthetic  judgments,  Kant  had  first  to 
justify  his  subject-matter  by  calling  attention  to  the  fact 
that  objects  may  be  judged  not  only  logically,  but 
also  aesthetically.  Accordingly,  we  find  in  the  opening 
sentence  of  section  VII  of  the  Introduction  ( which  con- 
tains an  epitome  of  the  involved  and  elaborate  analysis 
presented  in  the  Critique  of  the  aesthetical  Judgment ) 
a  statement  of  the  difference  between  these  two  classes 
of  judgment.     "  Every  object  of  sense  may  be  judged 


Kanfs   Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  53 

both  aesthetically  and  logically,  i.  e.,  we  may  judge  it 
logically  with  reference  to  its  relation  to  other  objects  ; 
we  may  also  judge  it  aesthetically  with  reference  to  the 
pleasure  or  pain  experienced  by  the  person  apprehending 
it.  "  That  is,  accompanying  the  mere  cognition  of  every 
object,  there  is  an  affective  experience  which  may  be 
either  pleasurable  or  painful.  By  drawing  this  distinc- 
tion Kant  prepares  the  way  for  his  discussion  of  the  ex- 
perience of  the  beautiful.  His  purpose  is  to  call  to  mind 
a  class  of  judgments  which  are  distinctly  judgments 
about  the  aesthetic  character  of  objects.  If  we  leave 
out  of  account  the  experience  of  the  painful,  and  consider 
only  the  pleasurable,  in  this  case  the  beautiful  expe- 
rience, the  account  would  run  as  follows  :  There  is  bound 
up  with  the  cognition  of  certain  objects  of  nature  and  of 
art  a  pleasurable  feeling  which  cannot  be  an  element  of 
cognition.  In  addition  to  our  knowledge  of  these  objects, 
we  have  a  consciousness  of  the  harmony  of  their  repre- 
sentations with  the  conditions  of  knowledge  in  general, 
a  feeling  of  pleasure  in  the  more  lively  play  of  the  men- 
tal powers  which  the  idea  of  the  object  produces.  This 
pleasure  is  not  an  element,  but  a  mere  accompaniment 
of  the  cognition  of  such  objects.  To  apprehend  an  ob- 
ject is  quite  different  from  being  conscious  of  the  feeling 
of  pleasure  aroused  by  and  attendant  upon  that  appre- 
hension. This  pleasurable  feeling,  we  are  told,  is  the  re- 
sult of  the  mutual  subjective  harmony  of  the  cognitive 
faculties — Imagination  and  Understanding — in  the  cog- 
nition of  an  object.  It  is  a  feeling  occasioned  by  a  har- 
monious, or  accordant  activity  of  the  imagination  in  its 
freedom  with  the  understanding  in  its  conformity  to  law. 
Certain  objects  of  nature  or  of  art  produce  this  harmony 
of  the  cognitive  faculties  which  contains  the  ground  of 


54  Teleology  in  KanVs    Critical  Philosophy. 

this  pleasure. 1  The  representations  of  these  objects  are 
adapted  to  throw  the  faculties  of  imagination  and  under- 
standing into  accord — such  objects  are  said  to  be  Beauti- 
ful. 

So  far,  Kant's  analysis  of  judgments  of  beauty  does  not 
enable  us  to  distinguish  that  class  of  judgments  from  two 
other  classes,  viz.,  judgments  of  the  Pleasant  and  the 
Good.  Yet,  as  will  be  seen  later,  it  is  of  the  highest 
importance  for  Kant  that  he  should  keep  the  experience 
of  the  beautiful  entirely  distinct  and  separate  from  that 
of  the  pleasant  and  the  good.  The  first  step  in  making 
clear  this  distinction  is  to  refer  aesthetical  judgments  to 
a  special  faculty — the  faculty  of  Taste. 2  It  then  becomes 
necessary  to  analyze  judgments  of  taste  in  order  to  show 
what  is  required  to  warrant  us  in  calling  an  object  beau- 
tiful as  distinguished  from  the  pleasant  and  the  good. 
Kant  has  a  double  purpose  in  this  analysis :  first,  he 
wishes  to  indicate  the  characteristics  of  the  beautiful 
and  point  out  its  prominent  features ;  and  secondly,  he 
wished  at  the  same  time  to  show  how  it  differs  from 
these  other  forms  of  experience.  Accordingly,  we 
find  the  analysis  and  description  of  the  beautiful  running 
parallel  to  the  process  of  differentiating  the  beautiful  from 
the  good  and  the  pleasant. 

While  it  is  true  that  the  two  purposes  are  coordinate, 
it  seems  certain  that  Kant's  one  great  aim  was  to  re- 
move every  possibility  of  confusing  the  beautiful  with 
either  the  pleasant  or  the  good,  to  win  for  it  a  definite 
field  of  experience  of  which  it  is  the  sole  occupant.  One 
often  suspects  that  the  desire  to  make  rigid  this  dis- 
tinction was  paramount  to  the  desire  to  determine  the 
nature  of  the  Beautiful,  that  the  former  motive  deter- 

1R.,  IV,  39.     H.,  V,  203.     B.,  40,  64,  66,  67,  69. 
2 R.,  IV,  45.     H.,  V,  207.     B.,  45  note. 


Kanfs  Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  55 

mined  the  moments  or  characteristics  of  beauty  rather 
than  the  analysis  resulting  in  the  conviction  that  the 
beautiful  experience  has  a  peculiar  nature.  But  in  truth 
the  one  process  involves  the  other.  The  process  of 
analysis  involves  a  characterization  of  the  Beautiful 
which,  at  the  same  time,  marks  it  off  from  the  pleasant 
and  the  good.  The  work  of  distinguishing  the  aesthetic 
from  every  other  experience  involves  also  the  work  of 
indicating  its  peculiar  qualities. 

Keeping  in  mind  then  that  Kant  has  a  two-fold  pur- 
pose before  him,  let  us  proceed  to  a  statement  of  his 
execution  of  it.  Facility  of  presentation  will  be  gained 
by  adhering  somewhat  closely  to  Kant's  order  of  pro- 
cedure, artificial  though  it  is.1  His  analysis  may  be  fol- 
lowed with  advantage  though  it  is  violently  and  un- 
naturally made  to  conform  to  the  convenient  but  rigid, 
mechanical  framework  of  the  Categories  of  Quality, 
Quantity,  Relation,  and  Modality.  Under  each  of  these 
categories  one  finds  a  description  of  one  of  the  essential 
qualities  or  characteristics  of  aesthetic  judgment.  One 
finds  also  under  each  category  a  feature  pointed  out 
which  helps  to  distinguish  the  beautiful  from  the 
pleasant  and  the  good. 

(a)  Quality  of  aesthetic  Judgments,  It  was  seen  in  a 
preceding  paragraph  that  the  judgment  of  taste  is  an 
aesthetical,  and  not  a  logical  judgment,  because  it  has 
reference,  not  to  the  relations  of  objects  to  one  another, 
but  to  the  relations  of  the  object  to  the  subject's  feeling 

1  The  artificial  character  of  Kant's  divisions  is  perhaps  more  clearly 
seen  in  the  Critique  of  Judgment  than  in  any  of  his  other  works. 
He  seemed  to  feel  that  there  was  something  peculiarly  significant  in 
the  plan  of  the  first  Critique,  and  took  especial  pains  to  make  the 
Critiques  of  Practical  Reason  and  Judgment  correspond  in  every  way 
to  it.  The  influence  of  this  tendency  has  been  well  explained  and 
illustrated  by  B.  Adickes  :  KanVs  Systematic  als  system — bildender 
Factor. 


56         Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

of  pleasure  and  pain.  It  must  also  be  disinterested  to 
distinguish  it  from  the  pleasant  on  the  one  hand,  and 
from  the  good  on  the  other.  For  when  we  pronounce 
an  object  '  pleasant '  we  express  an  interest  in  its  exist- 
ence ;  we  desire  the  object,  or  that  it  shall  continue  to 
exist.  "  Hence  we  do  not  merely  say  of  the  pleasant,  it 
pleases,  but  it  gratifies.  We  give  to  it  no  mere  assent,  but 
inclination  is  aroused  by  it."  x  The  pleasant  has  a  refer- 
ence to  the  faculty  of  desire ;  the  satisfaction  it  brings  is 
sensuously  conditioned :  but  the  judgment  of  taste  is 
merely  contemplative  ;  it  is  a  judgment  which,  indiffer- 
ent as  regards  the  existence  of  the  object,  compares  its 
character  with  the  feeling  of  pleasure  and  pain. 2  The 
mere  representation  of  a  beautiful  object,  apart  altogether 
from  any  inclination  towards  it,  is  accompanied  by  a 
feeling  of  satisfaction. 

It  is  equally  necessary  to  distinguish  the  beautiful 
from  the  good.  The  good  is  whatever  pleases  us  by 
means  of  Reason  through  the  mere  concept.  It  pleases 
because  it  is  the  realization  of  an  idea  or  plan.  We 
must  always  know  what  sort  of  thing  the  object  ought 
to  be  before  we  can  determine  whether  or  not  it  is  good. 
But  this  implies  an  interest  in  the  existence  of  the  ob- 
ject, and  thus  conflicts  with  the  doctrine  that  judgments 
of  taste  are  wholly  disinterested.  An  aesthetic  judgment 
does  not  imply  any  interest  in  the  existence  of  the 
object,  but  is  based  solely  upon  its  fitness  to  produce  a 
pleasurable  feeling  by  its  mere  form.  Thus  it  is  seen 
that  judgments  of  the  pleasant  and  the  good  agree  in 
the  fact  that  both  are  always  bound  up  with  an  interest 
in  their  object.  Both  have  reference  to  the  faculty  of 
desire,  and  bring  with  them  a  satisfaction  which  is  de- 

1R.,  IV,  49.     H.,  V,  210     B.,  50. 
2R.,  IV,  53-     H.,V,  213.     B.,53- 


Kant's   Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  57 

termined  not  merely  by  the  representation  of  the  object, 
but  also  by  the  represented  connection  of  the  subject 
with  the  existence  of  the  object.1  The  feeling  of  beauty, 
on  the  other  hand,  leaves  the  mind  entirely  free  and  dis- 
interested as  regards  the  existence  of  the  object ;  no  in- 
terest either  of  sense,  or  of  reason,  impels  us  to  judge  a 
thing  beautiful.  The  mind  is  content  to  rest  in  a  state 
of  mere  contemplation. 

(b)  Quantity  of  aesthetic  judgments.  We  saw  in  the 
preceding  paragraphs  that  the  satisfaction  one  feels  in 
the  beautiful  object  is  wholly  disinterested ;  it  may  be 
supposed,  therefore,  to  be  grounded  on  conditions  com- 
mon to  all  men.  Since  the  subject,  in  judging  a  thing 
as  beautiful,  believes  himself  to  be  quite  free  as  regards 
the  satisfaction  which  he  attaches  to  the  object,  he  con- 
cludes that  his  satisfaction  is  not  based  on  conditions 
peculiar  to  himself.  He,  therefore,  regards  his  judgment 
as  grounded  on  what  he  can  presuppose  as  existing  in 
every  other  person's  mind.  Consequently,  he  assumes 
that  every  one  will  find  a  similar  satisfaction  in  the  ob- 
ject he  calls  beautiful.  He  ascribes  the  characteristic 
'  beauty  '  to  the  object  in  the  same  way  that  he  makes  a 
logical  judgment  concerning  it.  In  other  words,  we 
assume  that  the  relation  of  the  cognitive  faculties  suita- 
ble for  cognition  in  general  is  the  same  in  all  persons, 
and  that  if  we  find  that  the  apprehension  of  a  given  object 
throws  our  mind,  or  mental  powers,  into  a  harmonious 
state,  we  assume  that  the  same  object  will  produce  the 
same  effect  in  every  other  person's  mind. 

This  quality  of  universality  which  judgments  of  taste 
are  supposed  to  possess  affords  Kant  another  means  of 
distinguishing  those  judgments  from  judgments  of  the 
pleasant  and  the  good,  or  perfect.     It  is  said  with  refer- 

!R,  IV,  52.     H.,V,  213.     B.,  52,  f. 


58  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

ence  to  tlie  pleasant,  that  every  one  is  content  that  his 
judgment  should  be  merely  individual  ;  that  the  funda- 
mental proposition  as  regards  the  pleasant  is,  '  every  one 
has  his  own  taste  ' ;  whereas,  judgments  of  the  beautiful 
are  thought  to  have  universal  validity.  That  is,  when  a 
person  pronounces  an  object  beautiful,  he  assumes  that 
all  other  persons  will  give  their  assent  to  his  judgment. 
With  respect  to  judgments  of  perfection,  it  is  true  that 
they  claim  universality ;  "  but  these  judgments  are 
based  upon  concepts  of  objects  of  universal  satis- 
faction, and  thus  are  different  from  judgments  of 
the  beautiful  which  do  not  rest  upon  concepts  but 
upon  a  subjective  relation  of  the  cognitive  powers."  l 
•(c)  Relation  of  the  judgment  of  taste.  Under  the 
category  of  relation,  Kant  explains  the  doctrine  that  in 
the  aesthetic  judgment  there  is  implied  the  notion  of 
" purposiveness  zvithout  purpose"  We  think  purpose 
when  not  only  the  cognition  of  an  object,  but  the  ob- 
ject itself  (its  form  and  existence)  is  thought  as  an  effect 
possible  only  by  means  of  a  purpose.2  But  we  also  pre- 
suppose the  representation  of  purpose  when  the  possi- 
bility of  an  object,  or  state  of  mind  can  be  explained 
only  by  assuming  as  its  ground  a  causality  according  to 
purposes.  In  this  latter  case,  we  have  k  purposiveness 
without  purpose,'  so  far  as  we  do  not  refer  the  object  or 
state  of  mind  directly  to  a  Will,  although  we  can  make 
it  intelligible  only  by  driving  it  from  a  Will.3  Now  we 
have  seen  that  judgments  of  taste  cannot  be  based  upon 
concepts  of  purposes  either  internal  or  external.  They 
cannot  be  based  upon  the  adaptation  of  objects  to  excite 
a  feeling  of  pleasure,  because  in  that  case  the  judgment 

1  R.,  IV,  58.     H.,  V,  217.     B.,  58. 

2  R,  IV,  66.     H.,  V,  224.     B.,  67. 
SR.,  IV,  67.     H.,  V,  225.     B.,  68. 


Kanfs   Theory  of  the  Beautiful.  59 

would  carry  with  it  an  interest.  Nor  is  it  possible  to 
base  it  upon  the  concept  of  an  external  purpose,  for  we 
do  not  call  an  object  beautiful  because  it  realizes  a  plan. 
To  judge  an  object  beautiful  goes  no  further  than  to 
assert  its  fitness  to  produce  a  harmonious  working  of  the 
cognitive  faculties  in  apprehending  it.  The  judgment 
of  taste  expresses  a  relation  of  purposiveness  or  adapta- 
tion, but  it  does  not  regard  the  adaptation  as  the  result 
of  design.  We  require  the  idea  of  purpose  as  a  principle 
of  explanation,  but  there  is  no  trace  of  that  idea  in  the 
act  of  judging  an  object  aesthetically. 

Kant  employs  the  doctrine  that  aesthetic  judgments 
imply  '  purposiveness  without  purpose  '  to  give  further 
emphasis  to  the  distinction  already  drawn  between  aes- 
thetic and  logical  judgments.  The  importance  of  en- 
forcing this  distinction  at  every  stage  of  the  discussion 
will  be  explained  in  detail  in  a  subsequent  section.  It 
is  sufficient  to  note,  in  this  connection,  that  Kant  was 
contending  all  the  while  against  the  Wolffian  dictum 
that,  '  Beauty  is  merely  Perfection  confusedly  appre- 
hended. ) 

(  d  )  Modality  of  aesthetic  judgments.  Under  the  cat- 
egory of  modality,  Kant  sets  forth  the  grounds  for  as- 
cribing the  attribute  of  necessity  to  aesthetic  judgments. 
That  necessity,  he  explains,  is  of  a  peculiar  kind ;  for. 
while  we  can  compel  assent  to  logical  judgments,  judg- 
ments of  taste  are  only  '  exemplary' .  That  is,  in  the 
latter  case  we  can  only  say  that  "  every  one  ought  to 
give  his  approval  to  the  object  in  question  and  describe 
it  as  beautiful.  "  l  The  ground  of  this  belief  is  found  in 
the  Idea  of  a  common  sense  which  is  defined  as  "  the 
faculty  of  feeling  the  effect  resulting  from  the  free  play 

'R,  IV,  88f.     H.,V,  243.     B.,  92. 


60  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

of  the  cognitive  powers.  "  2  And  since  all  persons  have 
like  cognitive  faculties,  we  suppose  that  an  object  which 
arouses  the  feeling  of  beauty  in  one  person's  mind  will 
of  necessity  arouse  the  same  feeling  in  all  other  minds. 

We  have  seen  in  the  preceding  paragraphs  that  the 
analytic  of  the  aesthetic  Judgment  involves  a  considera- 
tion of  judgments  of  taste  from  four  points  of  view : 
quality,  quantity,  relation,  and  modality.  With  refer- 
ence to  the  first  aspect  or  characteristic  (  quality ),  aes- 
thetical  Judgments  were  said  to  be  entirely  disinterested. 
There  is  no  interest  in  the  existence  of  the  object.  With 
reference  to  the  second,  (  quantity )  they  are  universally 
valid  ;  all  persons  are  expected  to  agree  in  their  aesthet- 
ical  judgments  of  objects.  The  reason  for  ascribing  uni- 
versality to  judgments  of  taste  rests  upon  the  assumption 
that  all  persons  have  like  cognitive  faculties,  and,  also,  a 
common  sense,  or  faculty,  of  judging  respecting  the  re- 
lation of  those  faculties.  The  relation  expressed  by 
judgments  of  taste  is  one  of  adaptation,  or  purposiveness  ; 
but  this  adaptation  is  not  regarded  as  the  result  of  de- 
sign, i.  <?.,  it  expresses  a  relation  of  purposiveness  with- 
out purpose  ( Zweckmassigkeit  ohne  Zweck) .  Lastly, 
the  modality  of  judgments  of  taste  is  that  of  necessity, 
and  is  based,  like  the  characteristic  of  universality,  upon 
the  idea  of  a  sense  common  to  all  persons.  These 
marks — disinterestedness,  universality,  necessity,  and 
purposiveness  without  purpose — besides  describing  aes- 
thetical  judgments — serve  to  mark  them  off  from  judg- 
ments about  the  pleasant  and  the  good.  It  is  now  nec- 
essary to  examine  more  in  detail  some  of  the  main  fea- 
tures of  Kant's  theory  in  order  to  understand  its  signifi- 
cance in  his  philosophy  as  a  whole,  and  also  to  enable 
us  to  see  how,  in  the  beautiful  object,  there  is  a  media- 

2R.,  IV,  89.    H.,  V,  244.    B.,  93. 


The  Doctrine  of  Harmony.  61 

tion  of  freedom  and  nature.  The  concepts  which  seem 
to  require  further  elucidation  and  discussion  are : 
(  i )  the  doctrine  that  beauty  depends  upon  the  har- 
monious working  of  imagination  and  understanding, 
(  2  )  the  distinction  between  aesthetic  judgments  and 
judgments  of  perfection,  (  3 )  the  doctrine  that  judg- 
ments of  taste  imply  (  purposiveness  without  purpose,  ' 
(4)  the  universality  and  necessity  of  aesthetic  judgments. 
After  examining  these  four  phases  of  Kant's  theory 
an  attempt  will  be  made  to  show  how  the  design  implied 
in  judgments  of  taste  is,  at  the  same  time,  evidence  of 
mediation  between  nature  and  freedom.  That  is,  it  will 
be  shown  that  in  the  beautiful  object  that  mediation  is 
thought  to  be  effected. 

(  a )  The  doctrine  of  harmony.  The  most  prominent 
feature  in  Kant's  theory  of  the  beautiful  is  the  doctrine 
that  the  feeling  of  beauty  depends  upon  the  mutual  sub- 
jective harmony  of  the  cognitive  faculties — Imagination 
and  Understanding.  All  the  parts  of  the  theory  center 
about  the  idea  of  harmony.  In  order,  therefore,  to  a 
clearer  and  more  exact  understanding  of  Kant's  doctrine, 
it  becomes  of  highest  importance  to  determine,  if  possi- 
ble, exactly  what  is  meant  by  the  rather  formidable 
phrase,  ( mutual  subjective  harmony  of  the  cognitive 
faculties, '  and  also  what  are  the  implications  of  the 
thought  it  contains. 

In  this  investigation  it  will  be  necessary  to  inquire, 
first,  how  does  Kant  define  each  of  the  cognitive  facul- 
ties in  the  Critique  of  pure  Reason  ?  What  function 
does  he  assign  to  each,  and  what  are  the  relations  of  the 
different  faculties  to  each  other ;  and,  in  particular,  how 
are  Imagination  and  Understanding,  whose  mutual  har- 
mony is  at  the  basis  of  the  experience  of  the  beautiful, 
distinguished  in  the  first  Critique?     Kant  enumerates 


62  Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

three  steps  or  processes  in  the  cognition  of  objects :  re- 
ceptivity, synthesis,  and  recognition.  Corresponding  to 
these  three  steps  are  three  cognitive  faculties  :  sense, 
imagination,  and  understanding.  "  There  are  three  sub- 
jective sources  of  knowledge  on  which  the  possibility  of 
all  experience  and  all  knowledge  depends,  viz.,  sense, 
imagination,  and  understanding.  (Apperception)"1  In 
one  respect  the  cognitive  process  may  be  conceived  as 
beginning  with  Sense,  which  is  defined  as  the  faculty 
of  receiving  impressions  according  to  the  manner  in 
which  we  are  affected  by  objects.2  It  is  the  faculty  which 
contributes  the  raw  material,  the  scattered,  disconnected 
manifold  which  the  Understanding  works  up  into  knowl- 
edge. Kant  elsewhere  defines  sensibility  as  "  the  re- 
ceptivity of  our  soul,  or  its  power  of  receiving  impres- 
sions whenever  it  is  in  any  wise  affected."  3  But  if  one 
stops  with  the  work  of  sense  one  will  have  only  a  mani- 
fold of  single,  disconnected  sense  impressions ;  there 
will  be  no  order  or  unity  in  them  ;  they  will  pass  before 
the  mind  as  fleeting,  isolated  pictures  before  a  mirror. 
Moreover,  if  every  single  representation  stood  by  itself, 
as  if  isolated  and  separated  from  all  others,  nothing  like 
what  we  call  knowledge  could  ever  arise.  For  "knowl- 
edge forms  a  whole  of  representations  connected  and 
compared  with  each  other."4  The  elements  of  knowl- 
edge, the  manifold,  must  be  collected,  synthesized,  or 
unified,  as  Kant  variously  calls  the  next  stage  of  the 
process.  This  second  step  is  the  work  of  imagination, 
"  a  blind  but  indispensable  function  of  the  soul  without 
which  we  should    have    no   knowledge    whatsoever."5 

'R.,  II,  90,  105.  H.,  Ill,  112.  M.,  II,  pp.  84,  101. 
«R.,  II,  32  note.     H.,  Ill,  56.     M.,  II,  17. 
3R.,  II,  56.     H.,  Ill,  82.     M.,  II,  45. 
4R.,  II,  92.     H.,  Ill,  566.  M.,  II,  87. 
5R.,  II,  77.     H.,  Ill,  99.     M.,  II,  69. 


The  Doctrine  of  Harmony.  63 

The  single,  isolated,  disconnected  perceptions  must  have 
a  connection,  such  as  they  cannot  receive  from  mere 
sense,  before  they  can  be  referred  to  an  object  of  knowl- 
edge. "  There  exists  in  us,  therefore,  an  active  power 
for  the  synthesis  of  the  manifold  which  we  call  imag- 
ination, and  the  function  of  which,  as  applied  to  percep- 
tions, I  call  apprehension.  This  imagination  is  meant 
to  change  the  manifold  into  an  Image." l  But  this 
synthesis  of  the  manifold  by  imagination  does  not  yet 
produce  knowledge ;  there  is  still  required  the  work  of 
the  understanding,  "  the  faculty  of  thinking  an  object 
in  the  manifold  of  sense  by  means  of  the  categories."  2 
There  is  still  necessary  a  faculty  which  is  able  to  recog- 
nize and  bring  to  light  the  principle  of  unity  present  in 
the  manifold  synthesized  by  imagination.  Understand- 
ing recognizes  the  identity  of  the  representations  which 
are  synthesised  by  imagination  with  the  phenomena  by 
which  they  were  given;  i.  e.,  the  understanding  gives 
the  representations  an  objective  reference.  The  under- 
standing is  defined,  finally,  as  the  faculty  of  judging, 
i.  e.,  of  referring  the  perceptions  of  sense  to  a  concept. 
In  this  exercise  of  understanding,  there  is  a  conscious- 
ness of  a  unity  in  the  perceptions ;  whereas,  the  unity 
formed  by  imagination  is  unconscious.  Understanding 
recognizes  the  manner  or  means  by  which  the  raw 
material  of  sense  is  collected  by  the  imagination. 
Knowledge  or  experience,  therefore,  is  the  product  of 
the  combined  activities  of  these  three  powers :  Sense, 
the  faculty  of  receiving  impressions ;  Imagination,  the 
faculty  of  "  blindly  combining  these  impressions  into 
an  image  ;"  and  Understanding,  "  the  faculty  of  recog- 
nizing in  that  image  the  universality  of  the  rule  ac- 
cording to  which  the  synthesis  takes  place." 

■  R.,  II,  109.     H.,  579.     M.,  II,  105. 
2  R.,  II.  79.     H.,  Ill,  100  f.     M.,  II,  71. 


64  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

This  account  of  the  origin  of  knowledge,  or  experi- 
ence, taken  from  the  first  edition  of  the  Critique  of  Pure 
Reason  is  found,  on  comparison,  to  be  the  same  as  the 
doctrine  Kant  had  in  mind  when  the  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment was  written.  It  is  unnecessary  to  dwell  at  length 
upon  the  theory  of  knowledge  advanced  in  the  last  named 
Critique.  It  will  be  sufficient  to  say  that  in  the  Critique 
of  Judgment,  Sense  is  conceived  as  a  faculty  of  receiving 
impressions ;  Imagination,  as  the  faculty  of  combining 
those  impressions  into  an  image ;  Understanding,  as  the 
faculty  of  recognizing  in  the  image  a  unity  by  means  of 
concepts.  Sense  supplies  a  disconnected,  raw  material ; 
Imagination  reduces  that  discrete  matter  to  unity  ;  Un- 
derstanding reveals  the  principle  of  unity  by  means  of 
the  categories.1 

We  are  now  prepared  to  proceed  to  the  main  question 
of  this  section,  viz.,  what  does  Kant  mean  by  the 
1  harmony '  of  Imagination  and  Understanding  which  is 
the  immediate  occasion  of  the  experience  of  the  beauti- 
ful.2 Etymologically  the  word  'harmony'  suggests  a 
fitting  or  joining  together,  (apiioZetv).  The  word  was 
used  primarily  to  indicate  the  external  fitting  together 
of  the  parts  of  a  system  :  and,  indeed,  it  retains  much  of 
its  original  meaning.  The  prominent  element  in  the 
idea  is  still  that  of  a  complete  correspondence  of  part  to 
part.  A  perfect  joint  in  mechanics,  a  skilful  dovetail,  a 
pair  of  cogwheels  the  teeth  of  which  mesh  with  exact- 
ness yet  without  friction,  a  piece  of  music  whose  notes 
have  their  proper  places  with  reference  to  the  other 
notes  are  thought  of  as  instances  of  harmony,  or  adapta- 
tion.    Moreover,  the  system  which  Kant  discovered  or 

»R.,  IV,  90.    H.,  V,  244.    b.,  93. 

2 1  say  '  immediate  occasion  '  because  the  feeling  of  beauty  is  oc- 
casioned primarily  by  the  beautiful  object. 


The  Doctrine  of  Harmony.  65 

devised  in  the  Critique  of  Pure  Reason  which  produces 
Knowledge — the  framework  of  which  is  reproduced  in 
the  Critique  of  Judgment — justifies  a  more  or  less  me- 
chanical representation  of  the  idea  of  harmony.  For,  as 
we  have  seen,  the  Imagination  as  a  piece  of  that 
mechanism — the  faculty  of  collecting  and  converting 
into  an  image  the  manifold  supplied  by  Sense, — is 
separate  and  distinct  in  its  activity  from  the  Understand- 
ing and  its  activity.  A  beautiful  object  then,  a  harmony- 
producing-object  is  one  the  raw  material  of  which 
will  permit  an  accordant,  frictionless  movement  of  these 
faculties.  Beautiful  objects  are  those  whose  elements  or 
manifold  are  easily  prepared  by  Imagination  for  recog- 
nition by  the  Understanding.  They  are  objects  whose 
elements  are  not  stubborn  and  unruly,  but  plastic,  and 
willing  to  be  worked  up  into  knowledge.  Or  again,  at 
the  risk  of  making  Kant's  theory  of  knowledge  ridicu- 
lously mechanical,  one  may  conceive  the  work  of  Imag- 
ination to  consist  in  so  moulding  the  manifold  of  sense 
that  it  may  be  given  the  stamp  of  recognition  by  the 
Understanding.  If  this  manner  of  representing  Kant's 
notion  of  harmony  seems  too  concrete,  too  mechanical, 
we  may  take  the  more  abstract  statement  that  "harmony 
of  the  cognitive  faculties  means  a  state  most  favorable 
for  both  faculties  in  respect  of  cognition  in  general." 

But  whatever  method  we  employ  to  make  intelligible 
the  doctrine  of  harmony  between  imagination  and  un- 
derstanding as  the  ground  of  the  experience  of  the  beau- 
tiful, it  is  soon  felt  that  an  explanation  of  the  feeling  of 
beauty  by  reference  to  the  harmonious  play  of  the  cog- 
nitive faculties  is  wholly  incomplete  and  unsatisfactory. 
It  is  incomplete  because  it  fails  to  indicate  the  relation 
of  those  faculties  to  the  object  judged  beautiful.     It  fails 


66  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

to  point  out  the  relation  of  the  cognitive  faculties  to  the 
object  which  occasions  the  beautiful  experience.  It 
treats  the  activities  of  those  faculties  as  if  it  were  isolated 
and  unrelated  to  the  sense-world,  while  as  a  matter  of 
fact  the  fundamental  harmony  is  necessarily  between 
the  sense-product  on  the  one  hand  and  the  activity  of 
understanding  on  the  other,  i.  <?.,  the  harmony  is  funda- 
mentally, not  between  Imagination  and  Understanding, 
but  between  nature  on  the  one  hand  and  mind  on  the 
other.  The  harmony  of  imagination  and  understanding 
may  be  regarded  as  the  immediate  cause  of  the  feeling  of 
beauty,  but  the  ultimate  cause,  or  ground,  is  in  the  har- 
mony between  the  beautiful  object  and  the  cognitive 
faculties.  The  statement  that  an  object  excites  the 
imagination  and  understanding  to  harmonious  activity 
is  only  another  way  of  saying  that  the  object  is  adapted 
to,  or  is  in  harmony  with,  the  activity  of  the  faculty  of 
knowing.  The  harmony  of  imagination  and  understand- 
ing implies  a  high  degree  of  adaptation  in  certain  objects 
to  the  faculty  of  cognition  in  general ;  it  implies  that 
some  objects  are  purposive  with  reference  to  the  mutual 
agreement  of  sense-products  and  the  activity  of  the  un- 
derstanding. By  regarding  harmony  as  the  ground  of 
the  feeling  of  beauty,  Kant  has  reference  directly  to  the 
relation  of  imagination  and  understanding ;  indirectly, 
to  the  relation  between  the  sense  world  and  the  faculty 
of  cognition  in  general.  That  this  latter  is  the  real  and 
fundamental  harmony,  becomes  evident  when  we  con- 
sider the  section  containing  the  solution  of  the  antinomy 
which  arises  with  reference  to  judgments  of  taste. l 
The  following  passages  from  that  section  may  be  cited 
in  support  of  this  position :  "  the  judgment  of  taste  is 
based  upon  the  concept  of  the  general  ground  of  the  sub- 

1  R.,  IV,  214  ff.  H.,  V,  350  ff.  B.,  231  ff. 


The  Doctrine  of  Harmony.  67 

jective  purposiveness  of  nature  for  the  faculty  of  knowl- 
edge. "  l  In  another  connection,  the  idea  of  the  super- 
sensible substrate  is  referred  to  as  "  the  ground  of  the 
subjective  purposiveness  of  nature  for  our  cognitive 
faculty.  "  2  Here  we  have  an  explicit  statement  that  the 
relation  of  purposiveness  obtains  between  nature  and 
mind. 

Another  passage  which  gives  additional  strength  to 
the  view  that  the  harmony  of  imagination  and  under- 
standing rests  upon  the  deeper  harmony  between  nature 
and  reason,  or  mind,  may  be  quoted  from  the  section  on 
the  Idealism  of  purposiveness  ;  "  The  property  of  na- 
ture that  gives  us  occasion  to  perceive  the  inner  pur- 
posiveness hi  the  relation  of  our  mental  faculties  in 
judging  certain  of  its  products  cannot  be  a  natural  pur- 
pose, etc. "  That  is,  certain  features  of  nature  are 
specially  adapted  to  excite  the  pleasurable  activity  of  the 
mental  faculties.  But  it  is  unnecessary  to  seek  for  more 
explicit  statements  than  the  oft  recurring  one  that  the 
beautiful  object  is  one  adapted  to  produce  such  an  ac- 
cordant activity  of  imagination  and  understanding  as  is 
requisite  for  cognition  in  general.  Beautiful  objects  are 
also  sense  objects,  and  to  say  that  they  are  purposive  with 
reference  to  the  mental  powers  and  their  employment  is 
equivalent  to  saying  that  they  are  purposive  for  the  activ- 
ity of  mind,  or  reason.  The  conclusion  is,  therefore,  that 
the  free  play,  the  relation  of  harmony  between  the  cogni- 
tive faculties,  which  is  the  immediate  occasion  of  the  feel- 
ing of  beauty,  rests  upon  the  peculiar  adaptation  of  certain 
natural  objects  to  the  activity  of  mind  in  general.  Pri- 
marily, the  harmony  is  not  between  imagination  and  un- 
derstanding but  between  nature  on  the  one  hand  and  the 

'R,  IV,  216.  H.,  v,  351.  B.  233. 
?R.,  IV,  223.  H.:  V,  357.  B.,  241. 


68  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

knowing  mind  on  the  other,  or  between  percept  and  con- 
cept. We  are  thus  led  to  see  that,  and  how,  the  feeling 
of  beauty  is  a  revelation  of  the  fact  of  mediation  between 
freedom  and  nature. 

(b)  Distinction  between  Beauty  and  Perfection.  In 
the  exposition  of  the  theory  of  beauty  it  was  observed 
that  its  most  conspicuous  feature  is  the  emphasis  laid 
upon  the  difference  between  the  Beautiful  and  the  Good. 
It  was  noted  that  Kant's  great  and  constant  purpose  was 
to  remove  every  possibility  of  confounding  judgments  of 
taste  with  judgments  of  the  good,  or  perfect.  One  might 
go  further  and  say  that  the  whole  of  the  Critique  of  the 
aesthetical  Judgment  was  planned  and  executed  with  a 
view  to  enforcing  that  distinction  ;  that  every  argument 
was  framed  with  the  clear  purpose  of  driving  home  the 
doctrine  that  the  two  classes  of  judgments  are  radically 
different. 

Before  examining  those  arguments  and  their  implica- 
tions, it  will  be  convenient  to  digress  at  this  point  and 
seek  for  an  explanation  of  Kant's  vigilance  in  guarding 
the  peculiarity  and  distinctness  which  he  had  assigned 
to  aesthetic  judgments.  Why  was  he  so  anxious  to 
establish  the  individuality,  the  separateness,  of  judg- 
ments of  taste  ?  What  is  the  origin  of  his  interest  in 
marking  off  that  class  of  judgments  from  every  other? 
The  answer,  I  believe,  is  suggested  by  the  following 
considerations  :  Kant's  original  purpose,  according  to  the 
theory  advanced  in  Part  I  of  this  inquiry,  was  to  find  an 
a  priori  ground  for  the  faculty  of  Feeling  as  had  been 
done  for  Intellect  and  Will.  The  idea  of  completeness 
and  symmetry  demanded  that  the  feeling  experience 
should  be  rationalized  and  grounded  in  a  prio7ri  prin- 
ciples which  are  separate  and  distinct  from  the  princi- 
ples underlying  the  activity  of  cognition   and   desire. 


Distinction  between  Beauty  and  Perfection.       69 

Another  consideration  that  prompted  Kant  to  claim  for 
aesthetic  judgments  a  peculiar  nature,  was  the  fact  that 
since  Understanding  and  Reason  furnish  the  a  priori 
grounds  for  intellect  and  will,  it  may  be  supposed  that 
Judgment — the  third  of  the  supreme  cognitive  faculties 
— will  perform  a  similar  work  for  feeling.  But  if 
aesthetic  judgments  are  resolved  into  judgments  of 
perfection,  it  is  clear  that  their  guiding  principle  is  de- 
rived not  from  Judgment,  but  from  the  Understanding, 
i.  <?.,  that  they  are  based  upon  a  concept,  or  idea,  of  what 
the  thing  should  be.  The  doctrine  that  beauty  is  perfec- 
tion confusedly  apprehended,  clearly  leaves  no  place  for 
judgments  based  upon  a  peculiar  and  distinct  principle 
supplied  by  the  faculty  of  Judgment.  That  was  the 
view  Kant  took  of  the  matter.  He  had  a  sort  of  jealousy 
towards  the  Understanding  lest  it  should  encroach  upon 
a  territory  which  rightfully  belongs  to  Judgment.  If 
judgments  of  taste  can  be  based  upon  concepts  similar 
to  those  upon  which  judgments  of  the  good  rest,  then 
the  distinctness  of  the  aesthetic  judgment  is  lost,  or 
rather  it  has  no  need  of  additional  grounds  of  activity. 
Moreover,  Kant  saw  that  if  the  Wolffians  were  right  in 
maintaining  that  the  feeling  of  beauty  is  only  a  confused 
judgment  of  perfection,  then  the  search  for  an  a  priori 
principle  which  shall  serve  as  a  guide  for  the  activities 
of  a  faculty  which  has  no  special  and  distinguishing 
characteristic,  no  peculiar  employment,  is  clearly  useless 
and  absurd. 

We  shall  now  proceed  to  examine  the  arguments  ad- 
vanced by  Kant  to  enforce  the  distinction  between  judg- 
ments of  beauty  and  judgments  of  perfection.  The  prob- 
lem, as  it  framed  itself  in  Kant's  mind  was  :  Is  beauty  per- 
fection apprehended  through  the  senses  ?  Is  the  judgment 
that  an  object  is  beautiful  merely  the  forerunner   of  a 


jo  Teleology  in  KanVs    Critical  Philosophy. 

possible  judgment  that  the  object  is  an  instance  of  the 
perfect  blending  of  a  manifold  with  a  given  concept  ? 
May  the  same  object  be  judged  beautiful  from  one  stand- 
point and  perfect  from  another  ?  If  these  questions  are 
answered  in  the  affirmative  then  obviously  there  is  no 
difference  between  the  beautiful  object  of  Kant  and 
the  beautiful  object  of  the  Wolffians.  In  that  case, 
the  difference  between  the  two  theories,  upon  which 
Kant  lays  so  much  emphasis,  must  be  sought  elsewhere 
than  in  the  character  of  the  objects  pronounced  beauti- 
ful. It  must  be  found  in  the  nature  of  the  judgments, 
or  rather,  in  a  difference  in  attitude  on  the  part  of  the  sub- 
ject judging.  The  Wolffians  implied  in  the  judgment  that 
an  object  is  beautiful,  the  further  judgment  that  it  is  also 
perfect.  They  maintained  that  the  aesthetic  judgment 
implies  a  logical  judgment  respecting  the  nature  of  the 
object.  Kant,  on  the  other  hand,  insists  over  and  over 
again,  that  the  judgment  of  taste,  qua  judgment  of  taste, 
says  absolutely  nothing  respecting  the  nature  of  the  ob- 
ject except  that  it  is  adapted  to  excite  a  harmonious  in- 
teraction of  Imagination  and  Understanding.  The  Wolf- 
fians would  say,  '  I  apprehend  confusedly  by  Feeling  the 
perfect  union  of  the  raw  material  of  Sense  with  a  con- 
cept of  the  Understanding.'  Kant  would  say,  '  I  ap- 
prehend absolutely  nothing  regarding  the  character  of 
the  object,  nor  is  anything  further  implied  in  the  judg- 
ment of  taste  than  the  fitness  of  a  given  object  to  pro- 
duce a  free  play  of  Imagination  and  Understanding.' 
The  ground  of  that  fitness  is  not  known,  it  is  not  sought 
for.  The  judgment  of  beauty  is  limited  to  the  mere  as- 
sertion of  a  contemplative  delight  which  a  given  object 
produces. 

It  would  carry  us  far   beyond  our  present  purpose  to 
attempt  an  evaluation  of  Kant's  proposed  modification  of 


Distinction  between  Beauty  and  Perfection.       71 

aesthetical  theory.  Yet,  the  remark  may  be  ventured 
that  Kant  made  a  decided  improvement  upon  the  theory 
of  aesthetics  which  he  had  inherited  from  the  Wolffian 
school  by  his  strong  insistence  upon  the  distinction  be- 
tweeen  the  feeling  of  beauty  and  the  cognition  of  per- 
fection. The  Wolffian  doctrine  that  beauty  is  perfection 
indistinctly  or  confusedly  apprehended,  and  the  inherent 
implication  that  the  two  are  at  bottom  identical,  entirely 
neglects  the  emotional  element  in  the  experience  of 
beauty.  That  theory  is  purely  rationalistic,  and,  if  it  is 
consistent,  derives  beauty  entirely  from  rational  factors. 
But,  as  Kant  rightly  maintains,  experience  of  beauty 
is  not  a  recognition,  even  though  confused,  of  the  con- 
formity of  an  object  to  an  idea,  or  concept ;  and  his  in- 
sistence that  the  two  classes  of  judgments  should  rigor- 
ously be  kept  apart  is  fully  justified.  For  the  instant 
one  judges  an  object  according  to  a  plan,  the  moment 
one  asks  whether  the  object  realizes  a  purpose,  that  mo- 
ment one  ceases  to  regard  the  object  aesthetically.  In 
that  case  the  emotional  element,  which  constitutes  the 
beautiful  experience,  is  displaced  by  a  logical  judgment. 
But,  in  reality,  we  do  not  come  to  beautiful  objects  with 
an  ideal  standard  to  which  they  must  conform  ;  rather 
we  feel  or  experience  the  ideal  through  the  harmonious 
play  of  our  faculties.  Kant's  clear  recognition  of  this 
fact,  his  tendency  to  suppress  the  cognitive  and  empha- 
size the  emotional  element,  renders  his  theory  decidedly 
superior  to  that  of  his  immediate  predecessors. 

Admitting  the  correctness  and  value  of  the  contribu- 
tion which  Kant  made  to  the  theory  of  Aesthetics  in 
thus  freeing  judgments  of  taste  from  any  reference  to 
the  perfection  or  imperfection  of  an  object,  must  we  not 
say  after  all  that  the  beautiful  object  is  a  perfect  object 
in  that  it  is  an  embodiment  of  an  idea  or  concept  of  the 


72  Teleology  i7i  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

Understanding?  Must  we  not  say  that  although  the 
idea  of  perfection  does  not  enter  into  the  mere  judgment 
of  taste,  yet  the  perfect  harmony  of  a  manifold  with  a 
concept  is  at  the  basis  of  the  feeling  of  beauty  ?  Kant 
did  not  discuss  this  question.  He  nowhere  explicitly 
affirms  or  denies  that  a  beautiful  object  may  also  be  re- 
garded as  a  perfect  object.  The  single  point  upon 
which  he  insists  is,  that  at  the  time  beauty  is  experi- 
enced there  is  no  concept  or  purpose  present  to  the  mind 
of  the  person  judging.  Although  there  are  no  explicit 
statements  on  the  subject,  there  is  abundant  evidence 
available  to  support  the  theory  that  the  beautiful  object 
and  the  perfect  object  are  identical  in  character,  that 
both  are  actualizations  of  an  idea  or  concept.  The 
clearest  proof  of  this  is  derived  from  the  cardinal  doc- 
trine of  the  theory,  viz.,  that  the  beautiful  object  is  one 
whose  form  harmonizes  with  the  faculty  of  cognition  in 
general ;  that  the  pleasure  which  beauty  excites  is  the 
result  of  the  agreement  of  an  object  with  the  empirical 
use  of  the  judgment  in  general  which  consists  in  refer- 
ring intuitions  of  Imagination  to  concepts  of  the  Under- 
standing.1 Now  the  perfect  object  is  a  union  of  percept 
and  concept ;  that  the  same  description  will  apply  to  the 
beautiful  object  will  be  evident  when  it  is  remembered 
that  the  experience  of  the  beautiful  results  from  the  free 
play  between  Imagination  (the  faculty  of  percepts)  and 
Understanding  (the  faculty  of  concepts).  There  is  a 
union  of  percept  and  concept  in  both  beauty  and  perfec- 
tion. In  the  one,  notice  is  taken  merely  of  the  free  rela- 
tion^ the  harmonious  state  of  the  faculties  employed  in 
the  process,  and  because  of  that  harmonious  relation  the 
object  is  judged  beautiful.  In  judgments  of  perfection, 
attention  is  centered  upon  the  character  of  the  object ;  it 
'R.,  IV,  30  f.     H.,  V,  196.     B.,  31. 


Distinction  between  Beauty  and  Perfection.       73 

is  said  to  be  a  union  of  percept  and  concept,  and,  there- 
fore, is  perfect. 

The  same  doctrine  may  be  stated  in  a  slightly  different 
form  by  considering  Kant's  way  of  conceiving  the  rela- 
tions of  the  activities  and  products  of  Imagination  and 
Understanding.  The  work  of  imagination  consists  in  re- 
ferring a  combined  manifold  to  a  concept  of  the  under- 
standing. That  object  whose  manifold  is  most  easily  re- 
ducible to  a  concept  is  the  beautiful  object,  because  it  per- 
mits the  free  play  of  those  faculties.  Such  an  object  is 
also  perfect,  because  perfection  consists  in  the  agreement 
of  manifold  and  concept.  The  work  and  general  relation 
of  the  faculties  of  imagination  and  understanding  in  the 
apprehension  of  an  object  which  is  not  beautiful  are  the 
same  as  in  the  apprehension  of  an  object  which  is  beau- 
tiful. In  both  cases  there  is  a  reference  of  percepts  to 
concepts,  the  difference  being  entirely  in  the  purposive- 
ness  which  some  objects  display  to  put  those  faculties  in 
more  harmonious  relations.  In  the  case  of  the  beautiful 
object,  and  in  the  case  of  the  object  not  beautiful,  the  re- 
lation of  the  cognitive  powers  is  the  one  most  suitable 
for  the  cognition  of  the  particular  object.  But  the  rela- 
tion most  suitable  for  cognition  in  general  must  be  that 
in  which  the  employment  of  the  faculty  of  percepts  is  in 
perfect  accord  with  that  of  the  faculty  of  concepts. 
That  harmonious  relation  is  the  cause  of  the  feeling  of 
beauty.  The  conclusion,  therefore,  is  that  if  the  per- 
fect object  is  defined  as  one  in  which  there  is  a  perfect 
union  of  percept  and  concept,  of  matter  and  idea,  then 
the  beautiful  object  is  also  capable  of  being  regarded  as 
a  perfect  object.  But  the  fact  that  it  is  perfect,  that  it 
is  the  embodiment  of  an  idea,  the  fulfillment  of  a  con- 
cept, is  not  present  to  consciousness  when  one  experi- 
ences the  feeling  of  beauty. 


74  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

It  remains  to  indicate  the  relation  of  the  conclusion 
of  the  present  discussion,  viz.,  that  the  feeling  of  beauty 
is  grounded  primarily  upon  the  union  of  percept  and 
concept,  to  the  doctrine  that  the  accordance  of  Imagina- 
tion and  Understanding  is  based  upon  the  fundamental 
harmony  of  Mind  and  Nature.  The  two  conclusions 
are  in  accord  and  are  mutually  explanatory.  Since  the 
feeling  of  beauty  rests  upon  the  harmonious  relation  of 
Imagination  (the  faculty  of  percepts)  and  Understanding, 
(the  faculty  of  concepts)  and  since  the  one  contributes  to 
the  structure  of  knowledge  a  synthesized  manifold  derived 
from  the  sense-world  (nature),  and  the  other  contains 
the  principle  of  recognizing  the  unity  in  that  synthesis 
(a  mental  factor),  it  is  clear  that  the  expression  "  harmony 
of  nature  and  mind  "  is  identical  in  meaning  with  the 
expression  'harmony  of  percept  and  concept.' 

(c)  Purposiveness  without  purpose.  Complementary 
to  the  distinction  which  Kant  draws  between  the  judg- 
ment of  taste  and  the  judgment  of  perfection,  is  the 
doctrine  that  the  former  has  reference  to  a  purposiveness 
without  purpose,  while  the  latter  involves  a  purposive- 
ness with  purpose.  That  is,  in  judgments  of  taste  we 
think  purpose,  but  we  are  not  warranted  in  supposing 
that  the  object  judged  beautiful  is  the  result  of  purpose. 
When  it  is  said  that  the  beautiful  object  is  an  instance 
of  "  purposiveness  without  purpose,"  we  mean  that 
although  no  concept  is  needed  as  a  point  of  reference 
for  the  object  in  order  to  judge  it  beautiful — nay,  more, 
the  reference  to  a  concept  would  mar  the  purity  of  the 
judgment — yet  we  are  compelled  to  assume  as  a  prin- 
ciple of  explanation  the  existence  of  a  designing  intelli- 
gence as  the  ground  of  the  purposiveness  exhibited  by 
the  beautiful  in  nature  and  art.  "  Although  we  cannot 
place  the  cause  of  the  purposive  form  of  beautiful  objects 


Purposiveness   without  Purpose.  75 

in  a  Will,  we  can  only  make  the  explanation  of  its  pos- 
sibility intelligible  to  ourselves  by  deriving  it  from  a 
Will."1  We  must  think  the  beautiful  object  as  if  it 
owed  its  form  and  its  adaptation  to  our  cognitive  powers, 
to  the  work  of  a  designing  Intelligence. 

Kant  repeats  the  doctrine  of  "  purposiveness  without 
purpose  "  in  the  section  on  The  Idealism,  of  the  pur- 
posiveness of  both  Nature  and  Art,  etc.2  Those  who 
maintain  the  realism  of  the  purposiveness  of  nature  re- 
gard the  adaptation  of  natural  objects  to  our  cognitive 
faculties  as  designed.  This  view  seems  to  find  support 
in  "  the  beautiful  formations  in  the  kingdom  of  organ- 
ized nature,"  since  we  might  assume  that  behind  the 
production  of  those  formations  there  is  an  Idea  of  the 
beautiful  in  the  producing  cause,  viz.,  a  purpose  in  re- 
spect of  our  imagination."3  Those  who  maintain  the 
ideality  of  purposiveness  in  nature,  while  admitting  that 
there  is  just  such  an  agreement  as  there  would  be  if 
designed,  yet  point  out,  first,  that  nature  everywhere 
shows  in  its  free  formations  much  mechanical  ten- 
dency to  the  production  of  forms  which  seem  to  be 
made  for  the  aesthetical  exercise  of  our  Judgment, 
without  affording  the  least  ground  for  supposing  that 
there  is  need  of  anything  more  than  mechanism  for 
their  production."  i  For  example,  crystallization  in  all 
its  various  forms  often  presents  beautiful  shapes,  but  it 
apparently  takes  place  according  to  purely  mechanical 
laws  without  reference  to  any  design  whatever.  If  mere 
mechanism  is  sufficient  to  explain  beautiful  formations 
in  the  inorganic  world,  why  is  it  not  sufficient  to  ex- 
plain the  beautiful  in  organic  nature  ? 

1  R.,  IV,  67.  H.,  V,  225.    b.,  68. 

2R.,IV,  223.  H.,  V,  357.     B.,24if. 

4R„  IV,  225.  EL,  V,  359-     B.,  243. 

*R.,  IV,  225.  H.,  Ill,  357.     B.,  243. 


J  6  Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

But  there  is  another  and  stronger  reason  for  maintain- 
ing the  ideality  of  the  purposiveness  of  Nature  ;  the  fact, 
viz.,  that  in  "  judging  beauty  we  invariably  seek  its  gauge 
in  ourselves  a  priori."  2  In  aesthetical  judgments  we  do 
not  consider  what  nature  is  in  itself,  or  in  relation  to 
ourselves,  but  "  how  we  take  it."  We  do  not  judge  that 
nature  shows  us  favor — that  would  be  a  judgment  of  ob- 
jective purposiveness — but  that  we  receive  nature  with 
favor,  that  it  is  subjectively  purposive.  To  maintain  the 
reality  of  the  purposiveness  of  beautiful  objects  is  equiv- 
alent to  saying  that  they  were  produced  according  to 
some  design.  This,  however,  contradicts  an  essential 
feature  of  the  beautiful,  viz.,  that  its  purposiveness  is 
undesigned,  merely  subjective,  and  based  wholly  upon 
the  harmonious  relation  of  the  cognitive  faculties,  im- 
agination and  understanding.  The  purposiveness  which 
nature  displays  in  beautiful  objects  must  be  conceived 
as  undesigned  ;  it  is  a  "  purposiveness  without  purpose  ". 

Finally,  it  may  be  pointed  out  that  the  doctrine  of 
'  purposiveness  without  purpose '  is  merely  another 
aspect  or  statement  of  an  important  feature  of  Kant's 
theory  already  discussed  that  aesthetic  judgments  are 
entirely  free  from  any  reference  to  purpose  or  concept  of 
purpose,  except  the  concept,  or  Idea,  of  a  supersensible 
ground  of  purpose  to  be  considered  hereafter. 

(d)  Universality  and  necessity  of  aesthetic  Judgments. 
One  more  important  feature  of  Kant's  theory  remains  to 
be  considered,  namely,  the  ground  of  the  universality 
and  necessity  claimed  for  judgments  of  taste.  In  the 
Analytic,  Kant  bases  the  universality  and  necessity 
which  he  ascribes  to  aesthetic  judgments  upon  the  Idea 
of  a  universal  voice,  or  common  sense,  which  has  the 
power  of  perceiving  the  agreement  or  disagreement,  the 

2R.,IV,  228.     H.,  Ill,  361.     B.,  246. 


Universality  of  Aesthetic  Judgments.  jy 

harmony  or  disharmony  of  the  representative  faculties 
in  apprehending  objects  of  nature  or  art.  Having 
assumed  that  the  process  of  cognition  is  the  same  in  all 
persons,  Kant  held  that  nothing  more  is  needed  to  give 
a  universally  valid  estimate  of  the  aesthetic  character  of 
objects,  than  a  sense,  or  faculty  of  judging  aesthetically, 
common  to  all  persons. 

Kant  left  the  matter  in  this  somewhat  unsatisfactory 
form  in  the  Analytic,  but  doubtless  clearly  realized  the 
difficulty  of  attributing  universality  and  necessity  to 
aesthetic  judgments  without  admitting  at  the  same  time 
that  such  judgments  must  be  based  upon  concepts.  But 
he  could  not  make  this  admission  without  violating  the 
cardinal  principle  that  judgments  of  taste  are  wholly  in- 
dependent of  any  reference  to  concepts.  Accordingly, 
an  attempt  is  made  in  the  solution  of  the  antinomy  of 
taste  to  discover  a  different  ground  for  the  universality 
and  necessity  ascribed  to  aesthetic  judgments.  In  fact, 
the  antinomy  is  essentially  a  statement  of  the  difficulty, 
just  referred  to,  of  claiming  universality  and  necessity 
for  aesthetic  judgments  without  basing  them  upon  con- 
cepts. The  antinomy  is  stated  thus  :  "  Thesis — The 
judgment  of  taste  is  not  based  upon  concepts.  Anti- 
thesis— The  judgment  of  taste  is  based  upon  concepts." 
The  antinomy  is  solved  by  showing  that  the  '  concept ' 
to  which  we  refer  the  object  in  this  class  of  judgments 
is  not  taken  in  the  same  sense  in  both  thesis  and  anti- 
thesis,1 It  is  plain  that  the  object  cannot  be  referred  to 
a  concept  of  the  understanding,  for  in  that  case  it  would 
become  a  logical  and  not  an  aesthetical  judgment.  Still, 
the  judgment  of  taste  must  refer  to  some  concept ;  other- 
wise, we  could  not  ascribe  to  it  universality  and  neces- 
sity.    But  it  is  not  a  concept  that  affords  a  ground  of 

1 R.,  IV,  214  ff.    H.,  v,  350  f.    b.,  231. 


78  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

proof,  or  one  through  which  we  can  know  anything.  It 
is  "  the  mere  pure  rational  concept  of  the  supersensible 
which  underlies  the  object  (and  also  the  subject  judging 
it)  regarded  as  an  object  of  sense  and  thus  as  phe- 
nomenal." 1  That  is,  at  the  basis  of  judgments  of  taste 
is  the  concept,  or  idea,  of  a  supersensible  substrate  of 
both  object  and  subject. 

But  how,  the  reader  will  ask,  does  the  mere  idea  of  a 
ground  common  to  the  object  perceived  and  the  per- 
ceiving mind  afford  proof  that  aesthetic  judgments  are 
universally  valid  ?  Kant's  discussion  at  this  point  is  a 
hopeless  tangle  of  broken  sentences  and  obscure  phrases, 
and  one  can  do  no  more  than  guess  at  its  main  threads. 
In  the  first  place,  Kant  repeats,  in  slightly  altered  form, 
the  theory  that  beauty  depends  upon  the  free  play  of 
imagination  and  understanding.  According  to  his  modi- 
fied statement,  the  idea  of  a  supersensible  substrate  for 
imagination,  the  faculty  of  percepts,  and  understanding, 
the  faculty  of  concepts,  is  the  ground  of  their  mutual 
adaptation.  Now  it  is  far  from  clear  what  Kant  means 
by  (  supersensible  substrate,  etc.,'  but  it  is  probable  that  in 
these  words  we  have  another  expression  of  the  thought 
contained  in  the  well-known  passage  of  the  Introduction 
to  the  first  Critique  : — "  There  are  two  stems  of  human 
knowledge,  which  perhaps  may  spring  from  a  common 
root  unknown  to  us,  etc."  In  that  case,  the  adaptation 
of  the  cognitive  faculties  results  from  the  fact  of  identity 
of  ground,  or  origin.  The  activity  of  Sense  is  in  har- 
mony with  the  activity  of  Understanding,  because  both 
activities  spring  from  a  common  source.  They  are 
thought  as  merely  different  modes  in  which  the  super- 
sensible reality  expresses  itself. 

After  establishing  a  new  ground  for  the  adaptation  of 

]R,  IV,  216.     H.,  V,  351.     B.,233. 


The  Beautiful  a  Union  of  Freedom  and  Nature.   79 

the  cognitive  faculties,  the  next  step  in  the  argument  is 
to  explain  the  universality  and  necessity  of  aesthetic 
judgments  by  reference  to  "  the  concept  of  the  general 
ground  of  the  subjective  purposiveness  of  nature  for  the 
faculty  of  cognition  in  general."  Kant  assumes,  in  the 
first  place,  that  there  is  a  Reason  common  to  all  human 
beings  ;  and,  secondly,  that  nature  is  adapted  to  the  em- 
ployment of  that  Reason.  This  is  sufficient  to  account 
for  the  universal  validity  of  logical  judgments,  but  it  is 
not  so  clear  how  it  will  justify  one  in  attributing  that 
quality  to  judgments  of  taste.  Kant  maintains,  how- 
ever, that  the  idea  of  a  common  ground,  or  substrate,  of 
humanity,  taken  with  the  idea  of  a  ground,  or  substrate, 
of  both  nature  and  Reason  will  account  for  the  purposive- 
ness which  certain  objects  display  with  reference  to 
the  employment  of  our  faculties,  and,  also,  for  the 
universal  validity  of  the  aesthetic  judgments  we  make 
concerning  those  objects. 

(e)  The  beautiful  object  a  union  of  freedom  and  nature. 
It  remains  to  conclude  this  section  by  emphasizing  the 
thought  that  the  beautiful  object  affords  an  example  of 
a  reconciliation  between  the  realms  of  nature  and  free- 
dom, and  that  the  judgment  of  beauty  is  a  revelation,  or 
expression,  of  that  mediation.  It  will  be  helpful  to 
raise  anew  the  questions  :  What  is  meant  by  mediation 
of  nature  and  freedom,  and  what  would  constitute  such 
a  mediation  ?  We  have  already  seen  that  Kant  means 
by  '  realm  of  nature  '  the  realm  of  the  material,  sense- 
world  considered  as  a  system  of  phenomena  in  space  and 
time  strictly  subject  to  the  law  of  natural  necessity.  It 
has  also  been  shown  that  the  '  realm  of  freedom '  is  the 
realm  of  ideas,  or  purposes,  and  that  it  is  not  subject  to 
the  ordinary  laws  of  nature.  Now  a  reconciliation  or 
mediation  of   these  two  realms  would  be  effected  by 


8o  Teleology  in  KanVs    Critical  Philosophy. 

actualizing  an  idea,  or  purpose,  in  the  material  world. 
Freedom  is  the  principle,  or  power,  of  originating  ideals 
and  purposes,  and  when  we  find  evidence  of  the  work  of 
this  power  in  the  physical  world  we  have  an  example  of 
mediated  nature  and  freedom.  If  such  an  example  can 
be  found  we  may  say  the  ideal  has  become  real,  and  that 
it  has  taken  on  a  concrete  body  and  form.  This  thought 
may  be  illustrated  by  thinking  of  the  work  of  the 
sculptor  who  undertakes  to  delineate  in  a  rough  piece  of 
marble  his  idea  of  any  thing,  or  person,  real,  or  imagin- 
ary. As  the  chips  fall  before  the  mallet  and  chisel,  the 
idea  is  being  realized,  until,  finally,  when  the  last  stroke 
is  made,  the  idea  has  become  actualized,  it  has  sprung 
forth  a  reality.  With  this  understanding  of  mediation 
we  shall  now  examine  Kant's  statement  that  "  the 
beautiful  object,  or  the  purposiveness  which  it  displays, 
is  fit  to  be  a  mediating  link  between  the  realms  of  nature 
and  freedom."  First,  it  is  observed  that  Kant  attributes 
purposiveness  to  beautiful  objects  because  of  their  fitness 
to  arouse  a  pleasurable  employment  of  the  faculty  of 
cognition  in  general.  The  principle  upon  which  Kant 
bases  the  reference  of  purposiveness  to  the  beautiful  is, 
"  that  if  an  object  or  state  of  mind,  or  even  an  action  is 
inexplicable  except  by  reference  to  a  ground  of  causality 
acting  according  to  purpose,  then  we  must  think  pur- 
pose 'V  When  an  object  is  contingent  so  far  as  the 
ordinary  processes  of  nature  are  concerned  we  are  obliged 
to  employ  the  idea  of  design  as  a  principle  of  its  explan- 
ation. On  this  ground,  the  beautiful  object  is  thought 
to  require  the  employment  of  the  idea  of  design  as  the 
key  to  its  explanation.  One  cannot  penetrate  the 
secret  of  its  nature  without  regarding  it  as  the 
embodiment  of  an  idea,  or  purpose.  But,  as  we 
1R.,iV,  67.    H.,  v,  225.    B.,  68. 


Design  in   Organic  Nature.  81 

have  seen,  to  find  purpose  in  an  object  is  the  same  as 
to  find  in  it  a  union,  a  mediation  of  nature  and  freedom. 
Such  an  object  may  aptly  be  described  as  a  '  concrete 
idea ',  an  idea  which  has  taken  body  and  form,  which 
has  become  tangible.  The  beautiful  object  reveals  this 
union  of  freedom  and  nature  in  the  fact  that  it  con- 
tains a  manifold  of  sense  adapted  to  arouse  the  har- 
monious activity  of  Imagination  and  Understanding. 
If  one  goes  deeper  for  the  ground  of  the  harmony,  it  is 
found  in  the  fact  that  an  idea  is  immanent  in  the  beauti- 
ful object :  there  is  a  union  of  real  and  ideal.  To 
slightly  vary  Bosanquet's  language,  "  The  beautiful  ob- 
ject is  assigned  by  Kant  the  high  position  of  being  the 
representative  of  reason  in  the  world  of  sense,  and  of 
sense  in  the  world  of  reason  'V 

§  4.    EVIDENCE   OF   DESIGN    IN   ORGANIC   NATURE. 

It  must  constantly  be  borne  in  mind  that  the  principal 
aim  of  this  study  is  to  examine  the  Critique  of  Judg- 
ment as  a  means  of  combining  the  Critiques  of  pure  and 
practical  Reason  ;  or,  if  one  is  thinking  of  the  content — 
the  inner  nature  of  the  three  Critiques — the  object  is  to 
consider  the  principle  of  purposiveness,  which  the  Cri- 
tique of  Judgment  exhibits,  as  a  principle  of  mediation 
between  the  modes  of  thought  prevailing  in  the  realms 
of  nature  and  freedom.  Our  purpose  is  to  consider  the 
principle  of  teleology  as  a  means  of  harmonizing  the 
view  that  insists  unyieldingly  upon  the  universal  valid- 
ity and  applicability  of  the  principles  of  physical  science 
and  the  view  that  claims  for  freedom  a  causality  inde- 
pendently of  the  physical  series. 

In  the  first  two  Critiques,  Kant  tried  to  overcome  this 
opposition  by  conceiving  two  separate  worlds,  or  king- 
'Bosanquet,  op.  cit.,  p.  261. 


82  Teleology  in  Kant's    Critical  Philosophy. 

doms,  in  one  of  which  Science  and  its  principles  should 
have  undisputed  authority ;  in  the  other,  Freedom  and 
its  legislation  should  have  absolute  dominion.  This  is 
the  familiar  distinction  between  the  phenomenal  and 
noumenal  worlds,  by  which  the  principles  of  physical 
science  are  left  in  secure  possession  of  the  phenomenal 
world,  while  the  practical  Reason  is  relegated  to  the 
noumenal  world.  Kant's  critics,  however,  were  not  dis- 
posed to  allow  him  to  lay  the  unction  to  his  soul  that 
his  solution  of  the  difficulty  was  adequate ;  and,  al- 
though he  valiantly  came  to  its  defense,  he  soon  saw  the 
need  of  a  positive  and  real  harmonization  of  the  results 
of  the  earlier  Critiques.  That  is,  he  came  to  see  that 
the  purposes  of  freedom  must  be  thought  as  being  capa- 
ble of  realization  in  nature.  It  must  be  conceivable 
that  the  ideals  of  practical  Reason  are  able  to  find  ex- 
pression in  the  sense  world. 

We  have  seen  in  the  preceding  sections  of  this  Part, 
that  the  purposiveness  displayed  by  beautiful  objects  is 
thought  to  bridge  the  chasm  between  nature  and  free- 
dom. We  shall  now  have  to  consider  another  set  of 
purposive  phenomena  which  are  thought  to  unite 
these  two  realms.  Those  phenomena  are  organisms, 
and  they  form  the  subject  matter  of  the  second  part  of 
the  Critique  of  Judgment,  the  Critique  of  the  teleolog- 
ical  Judgment. 

It  is  now  proposed  to  consider  the  main  doctrines  of 
the  last  named  work,  omitting  everything  which  does 
not  contribute  directly  to  elucidate  the  thesis  that  or- 
ganisms are  inexplicable  to  us  unless  we  import  the  con- 
cept of  purpose  as  a  new  principle  of  explanation.  The 
general  problem  discussed  in  this  part  of  the  Critique 
of  Judgment  is,  "  to  what  extent  and  on  what  grounds 
can   we   apply  the  idea  of  objective  purposiveness  to 


Desig7i  in  Organic  Nature.  83 

nature?"  In  former  works,  Kant  had  considered  the 
grounds  for  regarding  nature  in  some  of  its  parts,  or  as 
a  whole,  as  either  subjectively  or  formally  purposive. 
He  had  shown  in  the  Critique  of  Aesthetic  Judgment 
that  we  have  good  ground  for  assuming  that  nature,  in 
many  of  its  products,  is  subjectively  purposive  wuth 
reference  to  the  nature  of  our  cognitive  faculties.  Many 
objects  appear  especially  fitted  for  our  Judgment,  and 
"serve  at  once  to  strengthen  and  sustain  the  mental 
powers  that  come  into  play  in  the  employment  of  this 
faculty."1  In  this  respect  nature  is  said  to  be  subject- 
ively purposive.  So,  also,  in  the  Dialectic  of  the  Cri- 
tique of  Pure  Reason,  and  in  the  Introduction  to  the 
Critique  of  Judgment,  Kant  already  had  vindicated  the 
use  of  the  concept  of  the  formal  purposiveness  of  nature 
as  an  aid  in  our  investigation  of  nature.  In  both  places 
he  maintained,  (1)  that  the  world  is  an  intelligible  sys- 
tem; (2)  that  it  is  intelligible  to  us;  (3)  that  we  are 
warranted  in  carrying  with  us  as  a  guide  and  impetus 
to  the  investigation  of  phenomena,  the  assumption  that 
the  world  is  designed  with  reference  to  the  nature  of  our 
cognitive  powers.  In  this  way  Kant  had  indicated  the 
grounds  for  attributing  both  subjective  and  formal  pur- 
posiveness to  nature.  The  Beautiful  leads  us  to  think 
subjective  purposiveness  ;  the  order  and  system  of  nature 
justifies  us  in  regarding  it  as  formally  purposive.  The 
question  now  is,  can  we  apply  the  idea  of  objective  pur- 
posiveness, to  nature  as  a  whole,  or  to  any  of  its  parts  ? 
In  other  words,  do  purposes  constitute  a  particular 
kind  of  causality  in  the  realm  of  organic  nature  ? 

According  to  his  usual  method,  Kant  divides  the  Cri- 
tique of  the  teleological  Judgment  into  an  Analytic  and 
Dialectic,    with    an    Appendix    on  Methodology.     The 

lR.?IV,  239.     H.,  V,  371.     B.,  259. 


84  Teleology  in  KanPs    Critical  Philosophy. 

particular  tasks  undertaken  in  the  Analytic  are,  (1)  to 
define  and  illustrate  the  different  kinds  of  objective  pur- 
posiveness ;  (2)  to  present  the  evidence  of  design  in 
nature ;  (3)  to  indicate  the  place  of  teleology  in  a  the- 
oretical natural  science. 

In  discussing  the  first  of  these  points,  Kant  dis- 
tinguishes formal  from  material,  objective  purposive- 
ness.  Certain  geometrical  figures,  e.  g.,  the  circle,  which 
'  display  a  manifold,  oft-admired  purposiveness  with  ref- 
erence to  their  usefulness  for  the  solution  of  several 
problems  by  a  single  principle,'  are  cited  as  examples  of 
formal  objective  purposiveness.1  They  are  formally, 
not  materially  purposive,  because  it  is  not  supposed  that 
the  figures  exist  in  order  to  fulfill  the  use  made  of  them. 
That  is,  purpose  is  not  thought  to  be  the  ground  or  basis 
of  their  existence.  The  definition  of  material  object- 
ive purposiveness  is  implicit  in  the  foregoing,  viz.,  a 
purpose  which  implies  that  the  purposiveness  is  de- 
signed, is  dependent  on  a  concept  of  purpose,  e.  g.,  when 
one  sees  the  plants  in  a  garden  distributed  with  order 
and  regularity,  one  is  led  to  suppose  that  the  order 
and  regularity  is  the  result  of  plan.  Here  we  have 
material  objective  purposiveness,  of  which  there  are  two 
kinds,  relative  and  inner.  Relative,  or  external,  pur- 
pose is  seen  in  those  objects  that  serve  as  means  to  other 
objects,  e.  g.,  grass  is  a  relative  purpose  with  reference 
to  the  needs  of  certain  herbivorous  animals.  It  is  pur- 
posive, not  in  itself,  but  with  relation  to  something  else. 
We  say,  on  the  contrary,  that  a  thing  displays  inner  pur- 
pose when  it  exists  as  an  end  in  itself.  One  does  not  need, 
that  is,  to  go  outside  of  it  to  make  its  nature  intelligible. 
It  is  a  whole  which  contains  its  own  explanation  :  it  has 
inner  purposiveness  (innere  Zweckmassigkeit). 
1  R.,  IV,  242.     H.,  v,  374.     B.,  262. 


Design  in   Organic  Nature.  85 

After  drawing  these  distinctions,  Kant  proceeds  to 
consider  a  particular  class  of  natural  products,  which,  at 
the  same  time,  are  natural  purposes.  These  objects 
have  three  distinguishing  marks.  In  the  first  place, 
they  must  be  both  cause  and  effect  of  themselves.  This 
paradox  is  exemplified  in  the  case  of  a  tree  that  pro- 
duces itself  generically.  Viewed  from  one  standpoint 
the  genus  tree  is  continually  self-produced  :  viewed  from 
another,  it  continually  produces  itself.  That  which  in 
one  sense  is  the  effect  may  also  be  regarded  as  the  cause 
of  the  effect.  Practical  life  affords  numerous  instances 
of  this  kind  of  causal  connection,  e.g.,  when  one  lights 
a  lamp  in  the  evening,  the  idea  of  a  possible  light  is  the 
cause  of  lighting  the  lamp ;  the  effect,  or  the  idea  of  the 
effect,  is  the  real  cause.  The  remaining  marks  of 
things  regarded  as  natural  purposes  are,  first,  that  their 
parts  shall  be  ordered  with  reference  to  the  character  of 
the  whole ;  that  the  idea  of  the  whole  shall  determine 
the  character  of  all  the  parts.  And  in  the  second 
place,  it  is  necessary  that  the  parts  should  so  combine 
in  the  unity  of  the  whole  as  to  be  reciprocally  cause  and 
effect  of  each  others  form  ;  that  "  every  part  should  exist 
not  only  by  means  of  the  other  parts,  but  be  thought  as 
existing  for  the  sake  of  the  others  and  the  whole."  l 
Thus  in  a  tree  the  various  parts  exist  by  means  of,  and 
for  the  sake  of,  the  other  parts,  as  well  as  for  the  tree  as  a 
whole.  "  A  natural  purpose  is,  therefore,  an  organized 
and  self-organizing  being."  2  The  purpose  is  not  referred 
to  a  being  outside  the  object,  as  in  a  work  of  art,  but  is 
thought  to  be  in  the  object  itself.  To  speak  strictly, 
then,  the  organization  of  nature  has  in  it  nothing 
analogous  to  any  causality  we  know.3     The  object  and 

»R.,  IV,  257.  H.,  V,  386.  B.,  277. 
ZR.,  IV,  257.  H.,V,  386.  B.,278. 
3R.,IV,  258.     H.,  V,  387.     B.,279. 


86         1  eleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

every  part  of  it  are  conceived  as  being  determined  by 
the  idea  of  the  object  as  a  whole.  It  follows,  therefore, 
that  we  have  no  reason  to  regard  the  form  of  such  a 
natural  product  as  partly  dependent  upon  mechanism 
and  partly  dependent  upon  purpose ;  i.  en  we  must  not 
mix  mechanism  and  teleology  in  judging  nature. 

We  are  thus  brought  to  the  third  important  discussion 
of  the  Analytic;  viz.,  the  place  of  teleology  in  theoretical 
natural  science.  Kant  holds  that  both  the  mechanical 
and  teleological  methods  are  required  to  interpret  nature. 
If  Reason  hopes  to  gain  an  insight  into  the  nature  of 
things,  it  must  not  abandon  the  mechanical  mode  of  ex- 
planation, but  it  is  just  as  necessary  that  the  purposive- 
ness  of  nature  should  not  be  overlooked.  In  the  first 
place,  Kant  maintains  that  every  investigator  proceeds  on 
the  assumption  that  the  world  is  adapted  to  the  use  of 
our  cognitive  faculties,  that  is,  that  it  is  intelligible.  It  is 
a  necessary  assumption  of  reason  that  order  and  system 
exist  amid  all  the  manifoldness  and  variety  of  nature,  or 
in  other  words,  that  nature  embodies  some  intelligible 
purpose.  "  The  conceived  harmony  of  nature  in  the 
variety  of  its  particular  laws  with  our  need  of  finding 
universality  of  principles  for  it,  must  be  judged  as  con- 
tingent in  respect  of  our  insight ;  but  yet  at  the  same  time 
as  indispensable  for  the  needs  of  our  understanding  ;  and, 
consequently,  as  a  purposiveness  by  which  nature  is  har- 
monized with  our  design,  which  has  only  knowledge  for 
its  aim."1  That  is,  it  is  assumed  that  we  shall  be  able 
to  unite  all  diverse  principles  under  one  all  embracing 
principle ;  that  nature  is  a  unity,  and  that  we  may  con- 
tinually approach  the  discovery  of  that  unity  in  the  ex- 
tension of  knowledge. 

A  special  application  of  the  general  principle  of  the 
]R.,  IV,  26.     H.,  V,  193.     B.,  26. 


Design  in   Organic  Nature,  87 

intelligibility  of  nature  is  made  by  the  scientist  in 
approaching  the  investigation  of  organic  phenomena. 
For  he  proceeds  upon  the  assumption  that  all  the  parts  of 
an  organism  have  a  meaning  with  reference  to  all  the 
other  parts  ;  "  that  nothing  in  such  a  creature  is  in  vain." 
He  supposes  that  such  objects  are  fashioned  according 
to  a  plan,  and  that  all  the  parts  bear  an  important  rela- 
tion to  that  plan.  This  use  of  design  may  be  illustrated 
by  taking  the  case  of  a  botanist  who  is  attracted  by  the 
curious  arrangement  of  the  parts  of  a  particular  flower. 
He  quite  naturally  will  ask,  what  is  it  for?  i.  e.,  what  is 
its  purpose  ?  Investigation  stimulated  and  guided  by 
the  desire  to  understand  the  purpose  or  design  of  the 
peculiar,  arrrangement  of  the  flower  parts,  results  in 
showing  that  it  is  a  device  to  prevent  close  and  secure 
cross-fertilization.  Numerous  examples  might  be  given 
to  show  that  some  of  the  richest  rewards  of  scientific  in- 
quiry are  gained  in  the  effort  to  explain  the  meaning, 
or  purpose,  of  something  which  appears  in  itself  to  be 
merely  unusual,  or  trivial,  both  in  the  inorganic  and 
organic  realms  ;  and  in  faithfully  following  the  teleologi- 
cal  maxim  that  everything  in  nature  has  a  meaning. 

In  addition  to  the  uses  of  design  as  a  regulative  prin- 
ciple indicated  by  Kant,  there  are  passages  in  which  he 
seems  to  say  that  we  cannot  fully  understand  a  thing 
until  we  gain  an  insight  into  its  purpose,  or  can  tell 
what  end  it  serves.  The  account  of  how  it  came  to  be 
as  it  is,  may  be  full  and  complete,  and  yet  we  may  have 
no  real  understanding  of  the  object.  The  mechanical 
explanation  must  be  supplemented  by  the  teleological.1 

1  Kant  has  no  thought,  however,  of  abandoning  the  scientific  mode 
of  explanation  in  favor  of  the  teleological.  His  employment  of  the 
notion  of  design  is  not  the  one  ridiculed  by  Spinoza  as  "the  retreat 
to  the  sanctuary  of  ignorance  "  when  it  is  impossible  to  find  scientific 
explanations  of  phenomena.     For,    it  will  be  remembered,  (1)  that 


88  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

Having  presented  in  the  foregoing  paragraphs  Kant's 
use  of  the  notion  of  design  in  investigating  organic 
nature,  it  remains  to  indicate  the  application  of  the 
doctrine  of  purposiveness  in  organisms  to  the  problem 
of  mediation.  We  have  seen  that  Kant  was  led  to  em- 
ploy the  idea  of  design  as  a  guiding  principle  in  the  in- 
vestigation of  organic  phenomena  because  the  mechan- 
ical rules  of  explanation  do  not  enable  us  to  render  a 
full  account  of  the  form  and  existence  of  those  phe- 
nomena. The  harmonious  relation  of  the  parts  cannot 
be  thought  except  as  the  result  of  design.  The  idea  of 
the  whole  is  thought  to  determine  the  form  and  com- 
bination of  the  various  parts  of  the  organism,  just  as  in  a 
work  of  art,  the  idea  of  the  work  as  a  whole  determines 
the  special  features  and  parts  of  the  production.  More- 
over in  the  organism,  an  Idea  is  taken  as  the  ground  of  the 
form  and  existence  of  the  object.  An  object  whose  parts 
stand  in  organic  relation  furnishes  an  instance  of  the 
union  of  purpose  and  sensuous  matter,  of  idea  and 
reality.  Now  since  the  realm  of  nature  is  also  the 
realm  of  the  material,  and  the  realm  of  freedom  corre- 
sponds to  the  realm  of  purposes,  we  are  enabled  to  see 
that  in  the  organism  we  have  a  union  of  freedom  and 
nature.  In  an  organism  we  have  an  example  of  purpo- 
siveness, or  freedom,  revealing  itself  in  the  material, 
sense-world. 

the  idea  of  design  which  Kant  employs  is  that  of  natural,  or  immanent 
purpose  in  the  organism  itself,  and  that  there  is  no  necessary  refer- 
ence to  an  external  will  ;  and  (2),  that  the  idea  of  purposiveness  in 
its  regulative  use  contributes  directly  towards  the  discovery  of  natural 
causes.  Furthermore,  (3)  one  may  say  that  this  idea  completes  the 
scientific  explanation  by  showing  the  real  unity  and  intelligibility 
of  the  facts  which  the  latter  presents.  It  is  both  the  author  and 
finisher  of  the  scientific  mode  of  explanation. 


Teleology  in  Kan?s  Ethics.  89 

§  5.    RELATION  OF  TELEOLOGY  TO  KANT'S  ETHICAL 
DOCTRINES. 

The  two  preceding  sections  were  concerned  chiefly  in 
developing  and  illustrating  the  thought  which  is 
implicit  in  Kant's  phrase  that,  c  purposiveness  is  fit  to 
be  a  mediating  link  between  the  realms  of  nature  and 
freedom.'  Preliminary  to  that  discussion,  a  section  was 
given  to  the  representation  of  the  nature  of  the  opposi- 
tion between  these  two  realms.  Before  we  could  under- 
stand what  mediation  meant,  and  what  it  involved,  it 
was  necessary  to  determine  the  nature  of  the  opposites 
which  were  to  be  mediated.  It  was  seen  that  the  an- 
tagonism is  between  the  mode  of  thought  which  regards 
every  event  in  the  order  of  nature  as  the  result  of  purely 
physical  forces,  and  the  mode  of  thought  which  claims 
for  Reason  a  causality  through  freedom. 

The  effort  to  harmonize,  or  reconcile,  these  opposing 
modes  of  thought  formed  an  important,  if  not  the  most 
important  part  of  the  Critical  philosophy.  Abundant 
evidence  could  be  adduced  to  support  the  thesis  that 
Kant's  paramount  purpose  throughout  the  entire  course 
of  his  reflection  was  to  reconcile  the  doctrines  of  freedom 
and  necessity,  to  harmonize  the  teleological  and  me- 
chanical conceptions  of  the  world.  One  may  distinguish 
three  steps,  or  stages,  in  Kant's  treatment  of  this  prob- 
lem. The  first  is  that  presented  in  the  solution  of  the 
third  Antinomy,  and  is  usually  referred  to  as  the  solu- 
tion by  the  doctrine  of  the  ideality  of  phenomena,  or  by 
the  distinction  of  phenomena  and  noumena.  Kant  in 
these  pages  reminds  us  that  the  transcendental  analytic 
of  pure  Reason  firmly  established  the  correctness  of  the 
doctrine,  that  all  events  in  the  phenomenal  world  have 
an   unbroken    connection    according    to   unchangeable 


90  Teleology  in  KanVs    Critical  Philosophy. 

laws  ;  that  therefore,  the  only  question  open  is  '  whether 
it  is  a  proper  disjunctive  proposition  to  say,  that  every 
effect  in  the  world  must  arise,  either  from  nature  or  from 
freedom,  or  whether  both  cannot  co-exist  in  the  same 
event  in  different  relations.1  Does  causality  by  nature 
exclude  the  possibility  of  causality  by  freedom  ?  May  not 
freedom  and  nature  unite  in  producing  the  same  effect  ? 
Kant's  answer  is  that  if  you  insist  upon  the  reality  of 
phenomena,  freedom  is  lost,  because,  in  the  world  of  phe- 
nomena, events  have  an  unbroken  connection  according 
to  the  unalterable  law  of  natural  necessity.  But  by 
ascribing  both  an  empirical  and  an  intelligible  character 
to  every  subject  of  the  sense-world,  one  may  think  free- 
dom though  it  cannot  thereby  be  established.  In  its 
empirical  character  every  subject,  as  a  phenomenon, 
would  stand  with  other  phenomena  in  an  unbroken  con- 
nection according  to  fixed  laws  of  nature,  and  all  its 
actions  would  be  determined  by  those  laws.  But  in  its 
intelligible  character  it  would  be  quite  free  from  every 
external  influence  and  would  have  a  causality  of  its  own. 
In  this  way  we  are  enabled  to  think  the  possibility  of 
both  nature  and  freedom  existing  together  in  the  same 
action.  Man,  like  every  object  in  the  sense-world,  can 
be  viewed  from  these  two  points  of  view.  In  his 
empirical  character  he  is  under  the  laws  of  physical 
necessity  ;  but  in  his  intelligible  character  he  is  free  and 
determines  himself  in  accordance  with  the  laws  of 
Reason.  Kant  concludes  that  the  laws  of  nature  and 
the  law  of  freedom  are  not  contradictory ;  but  he  does 
not  claim  to  have  established  the  reality,  or  even  the 
possibility  of  freedom,  but  merely  that  nature  regarded 
as  a  phenomenon  does  not  necessarily  contradict  or  ex- 
clude the  causality  of  freedom.2 

lR.,  II,  421.     H.,  Ill,  372  f.     M.,  II,  463- 
2R.,  II,  437-     H.,  Ill,  385.     M.,  II,48i. 


Teleology  in  Kanfs  Ethics.  91 

The  second  step  in  Kant's  solution  of  the  problem  of 
freedom  and  necessity  is  the  argument  for  freedom  based 
upon  the  consciousness  of  duty.  The  sense  of  obliga- 
tion imposed  by  the  moral  law  implies  the  power  to  ful- 
fill that  obligation ;  it  is  evidence  of  freedom.  We 
ought,  therefore,  we  can.  The  first  step  was  to  show  that 
freedom  is  not  incompatible  with  physical  law  ;  that  one 
can,  without  doing  violence  to  Reason,  think  a  union  of 
both  freedom  and  natural  necessity  in  the  same  action. 
The  second  step  was  to  affirm  the  fact  of  freedom  upon 
the  ground  of  duty.  But  both  of  these  modes  of  proof 
were  far  from  satisfactory,  since  they  give  us  no  assurance 
that  the  ideas  of  freedom  ever  become  realized  in  the 
world.  They  furnished  no  evidence  that  the  ideas  of 
freedom  ever  find  expression  or  realization  in  the  sense- 
world.  It  was  sufficient  to  satisfy  the  demand  of  the 
moral  law  if  one  was  conscious  of  willing  in  accordance 
with  that  law. 

Now  one  can  easily  understand  why  Kant  could  not 
rest  content  with  such  a  notion  of  freedom.  For  the  latter 
is  a  worthless  treasure,  if  its  purposes  are  incapable  of  real- 
ization in  the  phenomenal  world.  It  would  be  mockery 
to  endow  man  with  the  power  of  free  causality  and  yet 
confess  that  he  can  never  know  that  he  actually  does 
exert  an  influence  upon  the  course  of  events.  That  is, 
if  there  is  an  impassable  gulf  between  nature  and  free- 
dom so  that  the  latter  can  exert  no  influence  upon  the 
former — if  freedom  is  impotent  to  fulfill  its  ideals  — then 
it  is  useless  and  not  worth  the  labor  it  costs  to  defend  it. 
Accordingly,  in  the  last  Critique,  Kant  drops  a  hint  as 
to  the  way  in  which  the  idea  of  freedom  may  be  brought 
into  connection  with  the  doctrine  of  physical  necessity, 
viz.,  through  the  idea  of  purposiveness  which  the  Beauti- 
ful and   the  Organic  exhibit.     It  has  already  been  ex- 


92  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

plained  how  the  Beautiful  and  the  Organic,  through 
the  design  which  they  display,  may  be  regarded  as 
examples  of  a  blending  of  nature  and  freedom,  how  in 
each  of  those  classes  of  objects  there  is  both  a  sensuous, 
material  element,  and  also  a  spiritual  or  ideal  element. 
Kant  further  explains  that  the  Reflective  Judgment,  in 
pronouncing  certain  objects  purposive,  thereby  declares 
that  concepts  of  freedom  are  realized  in  the  realm  of 
nature  ;  and  this  declaration  is  made  irrespective  of  prac- 
tical considerations,  i.  e.,  without  reference  to  the  possi- 
bility of  realizing  the  purposes  of  the  practical  Reason. 
Yet,  as  will  be  shown  presently,  the  main  use  which 
Kant  sought  to  make  of  the  doctrine  of  purposiveness, 
and  the  evidences  of  purpose  which  he  discovered  in  na- 
ture, was  to  strengthen  the  foundations  of  his  ethical 
doctrines,  especially  the  doctrine  of  Freedom.  If  one 
raises  again  the  question  why  Kant  was  so  desirous  of 
bringing  into  closer  relation  the  leading  doctrines  of 
the  critiques  of  pure  and  practical  Reason,  why  he 
deemed  it  so  important  to  mediate  the  concepts  dominat- 
ing the  realms  of  nature  and  freedom,  the  answer  is,  as 
anticipated  above,  that  by  so  doing  he  hoped  to  strength- 
en the  ethical  doctrines  advanced  in  the  earlier  Critiques. 
For  as  every  student  of  the  critical  philosophy  soon  comes 
to  feel,  Kant  regarded  the  interests  of  the  practical  Rea- 
son as  of.  transcendent  importance.  The  one  thing  of 
absolute  worth  in  all  the  world  is  man  acting  under  the 
moral  law.  Kant's  scientific  spirit,  his  intense  love 
of  truth,  will  win  the  admiration  of  all  succeeding  ages  ; 
but  stronger  than  his  devotion  to  truth,  for  truth's  sake, 
was  his  devotion  to  the  interests  of  man  as  a  moral  be- 
ing. Accordingly,  when  the  question  of  the  final  pur- 
pose of  nature  is  raised,  when  it  is  asked,  What  meaning 
has  nature,  what  is  its  raison  d&tre  and  ultimate  pur- 


Teleology  in  Kanfs  Ethics.  93 

pose,  Kant  replies  that  it  is  only  with  reference  to 
man's  moral  nature  that  the  world  has  a  meaning.  It 
is  clear  that  this  is  in  accord  with  the  note  struck  in  the 
opening  sentence  of  the  Metaphysic  of  Morals  :  "  Noth- 
ing can  possibly  be  conceived  in  the  world,  or  even  out 
of  it  which  can  be  called  good  without  qualification,  ex- 
cept a  Good  Will ;"  l  and  by  '  good  will '  Kant  means  a 
Will  under  the  moral  law.  It  is  in  man  as  a  moral  be- 
ing, man  possessed  of  a  good  will,  then,  that  Kant  finds 
a  being  of  absolute  worth,  and  one  that  gives  meaning 
and  purpose  to  the  world.  "  Without  man  the  whole 
creation  would  be  a  mere  waste,  in  vain,  and  with- 
out final  purpose  ;  and  it  is  in  man's  good  will  that 
he  can  have  an  absolute  worth,  and  in  reference  to  which 
the  world  can  have  a  final  purpose."  2 

It  is  to  be  noted  further  that  the  world  is  conceived 
as  a  sort  of  training  place  for  man's  moral  nature  ;  a 
scene  of  probation  in  which  he  is  prepared  for  a  nobler 
and  more  blessed  state  hereafter.  The  hardships,  op- 
pression and  cruelty  which  man  suffers  from  the  world 
help  to  free  him  from  the  fetters  of  desire  and  prepare 
him  for  the  exercise  of  his  nobler  faculties.  It  is  as  a 
means  of  discipline  to  man's  moral  nature  that  the 
world  has  a  meaning.3 

1  Abbott,  op.  cit,  p.  9. 

2  R.,  IV,  342  f.     H.,  V,  455,  f.     B.,370,  f. 

3  It  is  interesting  to  notice  the  striking  similarity  between  the  views 
of  Kant  and  Fichte  concerning  nature  and  its  purpose  with  reference 
to  the  development  of  man's  moral  character.  Although  Fichte's 
thought  is  expressed  in  quite  different  language  and  is  not  so  explicit 
as  Kant's  statement,  yet  his  view  is  substantially  a  repetition  of  the 
doctrine  of  Kant,  that  the  world  has  its  final  explanation  in  serving 
as  a  means  of  culture  to  the  moral  side  of  man's  nature.  In  the 
theoretical  part  of  the  Science  of  Knowledge,  Fichte  showed  that  if  the 
Ego  is  to  be  intelligence,  part  of  its  infinitely  extending  activity  must 
be  canceled,  and  thus  posited  in  its  opposite,  the  non-ego.  In  the 
practical  part,  it  is  shown  that  if  the  Ego  is  to  be  Will,  if  it  is  to  have 


94  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

Now  when  we  remember  the  great  importance  which 
Kant  attached  to  the  moral  element  in  man's  nature,  we 
may  understand  why  he  was  so  much  concerned  to 
render  secure  the  interests  and  position  of  the  practical 
Reason.  Every  fact  and  every  argument  that  could  be 
used  to  strengthen  the  postulates  of  morals  would  be 
brought  into  seivice.  We  may  suppose,  therefore,  that 
it  was  Kant's  purpose  to  use  the  results  of  the  Critique  of 

a  causality,  it  must  encounter  resistance  and  opposition  in  the  non- 
ego.  As  practical,  the  Ego  yearns  to  change  the  order  of  the  world, 
to  make  it  conform  to  its  own  ideal  activity.  In  other  words — and 
this  is  the  point  with  which  we  are  here  concerned — the  purpose,  or 
function,  of  nature  with  reference  to  man's  moral  character,  is  to  offer 
resistance  to  the  infinite  activity  of  the  Ego  ;  first,  in  order  that  con- 
sciousness and  intelligence  may  be  aroused  ;  second,  in  order  that 
moral  ideals  may  be  conceived  as  a  result  of  the  check  put  upon  the 
Ego's  activity. 

It  is  of  interest  to  note,  also,  that  this  view  of  nature  and  its  purpose 
with  reference  to  the  conditions  of  realizing  the  summiim  bonum, 
differs  from  the  view  presented  in  the  corresponding  discussions  of 
the  earlier  critiques.  The  summum  bonum  for  Kant  consists  of  two 
factors,  perfect  holiness  and  perfect  happiness.  Now  perfect  happi- 
ness depends  upon  the  harmony  of  physical  nature  with  man's  moral 
activity.  Kant,  however,  maintained  in  the  first  two  critiques  that  this 
harmony  is  wanting,  that  nature  is  a  hindrance  to  the  realization  of 
happiness.  The  world,  thus  regarded,  is  a  bar  to  the  actualization  of 
one  factor  of  the  summum  bonum.  But  when  Kant  comes  to  search 
for  the  final  purpose  of  nature,  and  its  function  with  reference  to  that 
purpose,  he  is  led  to  regard  nature  as  an  indispensable  means  to  the 
culture  of  man's  moral  powers.  The  obstacles,  cruelties,  and  hard- 
ships which  oppress  man  upon  every  side  are  disguised  blessings,  but 
nevertheless  blessings,  because  they  help  him  to  free  himself  from 
the  tyranny  of  sense  and  enable  him  to  rise  to  the  clear  atmosphere 
of  pure  Reason.  According  to  the  one  view,  the  world  presents  an 
insuperable  obstacle  to  happiness  so  far  as  man's  power  is  concerned. 
According  to  the  other,  the  world  is  a  necessary  means  of  culture  to 
man's  moral  nature.  The  contradiction  inherent  in  the  two  views  is 
irreconcilable.  For  so  long  as  the  world  is  useful  as  a  means  of 
culture  to  man's  virtue,  it  is  an  obstacle  the  realization  of  his  happi- 
ness ;  and  when  it  is  brought  into  harmony  with  the  conditions  of 
happiness,  it  loses  its  value  as  a  means  of  moral  culture.  It  thus  ap- 
pears that  it  is  impossible  to  attain  both  happiness  and  holiness  at  the 
same  time.  The  conditions  favorable  to  the  realization  of  the  one  are 
unfavorable  to  the  realization  of  the  other. 


Teleology  hi  Kanfs  Ethics.  95 

Judgment  as  a  confirmation  of  the  postulates  of  practical 
Reason,  especially  the  postulates  of  God  and  freedom. 
We  shall  now  have  to  see  how  the  principles  established 
in  the  third  Critique  strengthen  Kant's  ethical  doctrines. 
First,  with  reference  to  the  notion  of  freedom,  it  is  clear 
that  if  there  is  evidence  that  some  causes,  or  forces, 
besides  physical  causes  are  at  work  or  have  been  at  work 
in  nature,  and  if  there  is  ground  for  supposing  that  those 
forces  are  analogous  to  our  human  reason,  we  are  war- 
ranted in  assuming  that  our  own  will  may  find  its  ideals 
realized  in  the  realm  of  nature.  It  has  been  explained 
already  that  to  regard  a  thing  as  purposive  is  the  same 
as  to  see  in  it  the  work  of  freedom.  Moreover,  when 
Kant  speaks  of  mediating  the  realms  of  nature  and  free- 
dom he  is  thinking  of  the  possibility  of  realizing  moral 
concepts  in  the  material  world.  This  does  not  mean 
merely  that  one  can  carry  out  the  rules  of  skill  and  art, 
that  we  can  fashion  the  material  world  according  to 
plans  :  the  mediation  of  nature  and  freedom  to  which  he 
refers  is  the  harmonization  of  nature  and  moral  pur- 
poses. When  Kant  speaks  of  mediating  nature  and 
that  which  the  concept  of  freedom  practically  contains, 
it  is  evident  that  he  has  in  mind  moral  freedom  and  its 
concepts.  All  doubt  as  to  whether  Kant  is  thinking  of 
moral  purposes  is  removed  when  we  recall  the  distinction 
drawn  between  technically  practical  and  morally  prac- 
tical principles  of  the  Will.  He  says,  "  the  Will  .  . 
.  .  is  one  of  the  many  natural  causes  in  the  world, 
viz.,  that  cause  which  acts  in  accordance  with  concepts. 
All  that  is  represented  as  possible  by  means  of  a  will  is 
called  practically  possible.  Now  if  the  concept  which 
determines  the  causality  of  the  Will  is  a  natural  con- 
cept, then  the  principles  are  technically  practical ;  but  if 
it  is  a  concept  of  freedom,  they  are  morally  practical. 


96  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

The  rules  of  skill  and  art  rest  upon  natural  concepts  ; 
but  the  rules  of  morals  are  based  upon  concepts  of  free- 
dom — the  moral  law."  1  Therefore,  when  Kant  speaks 
of  the  '  concepts  of  freedom,'  he  invariably  has  reference 
to  the  determination  of  the  Will  according  to  moral 
ideals,  and  when  he  speaks  of  mediating  nature  and 
freedom,  he  refers  to  the  realization  of  a  moral  idea  in 
nature.  Further,  he  expressly  states  that  "  purposes 
in  the  world  are  studied  in  order  to  confirm  incidentally 
the  Ideas  that  pure  practical  Reason  furnishes  ;  " 2  those 
Ideas,  I  take  it,  are  the  ideas  of  God  and  Freedom. 
Again,  when  Kant  states  in  the  Preface  to  the  Critique 
of  Judgment  that  the  a  priori  concept  of  purposiveness 
opens  out  prospects  which  are  advantageous  for  the 
practical  Reason,"  3  he  doubtless  refers  to  the  use  one 
can  make  of  that  notion  to  strengthen  the  grounds  of 
belief  in  God  and  Freedom.  In  a  word,  Kant  would  use 
the  evidence  of  purposiveness  exhibited  by  nature  as  a 
means  of  fortifying  the  conviction  that  other  forces  than 
physical  forces  exert  an  influence  upon  the  course  of  the 
world. 

Not  only  does  the  doctrine  of  purposiveness  in  nature 
lend  itself  to  the  service  of  Kant's  theory  of  Freedom, 
but  the  doctrine  of  the  summum  bonum  is  also  indirectly 
strengthened  thereby.  It  will  be  remembered  that  Kant 
postulated  an  eternity  of  existence  (immortality)  in 
which  to  attain  to  perfect  virtue,  the  first  and  funda- 
mental factor  of  summum  bonum.  Now  perfect  virtue 
must  be  accompanied  by  perfect  happiness,  which  is  de- 
fined as  "  the  state  of  a  rational  being  in  the  world  with 
whom  everything  goes  according  to  his  wish  and  will, 

1 R.,  IV,  9.    H.,  v,  178.    b.,  7. 

*R.,IV,345.     H.,  V,  358.     B.,  373- 

3R.,  IV,  6.     H..V,  176.     B.,  4. 


Teleology  in  Kanfs  Ethics.  97 

and  rests,  therefore,  upon  the  harmony  of  physical 
nature  with  his  whole  end  and  with  the  essential  deter- 
mining principles  of  his  will."1  But  since  man  is  not 
the  cause  of  nature,  and  therefore  is  not  able  to  make  it 
harmonize  with  his  practical  needs,  we  must  postulate 
the  existence  of  a  Power  great  enough  to  bring  the 
world  into  accord  with  man's  moral  nature.  We  assume 
the  existence  of  a  being  distinct  from  nature  itself  and 
containing  the  principle  of  connection  between  happi- 
ness and  goodness.2  That  Being  is  God,  and  any  evi- 
dence tending  to  prove  his  existence  will  indirectly  sup- 
port the  doctrine  of  the  summum  bonum.  For,  as  was 
just  stated,  it  is  only  upon  the  supposition  of  the  exist- 
ence of  God,  that  we  have  a  guarantee  of  that  due  pro- 
portion between  virtue  and  happiness  which  constitutes 
the  summum  bonum. 

Now  the  argument  for  the  existence  of  God  derived 
from  "  the  order,  variety,  fitness,  beauty,"  which  the 
world  presents,  is,  in  Kant's  language,  "  the  oldest,  the 
clearest  and  the  most  in  conformity  with  human  rea- 
son "  ;  and  although  he  maintained  throughout  all  his 
writings  that  "  the  moral  proof  is  the  only  one  that  pro- 
duces conviction,"  yet  the  physico-teleological  proof  has 
the  merit  of  leading  the  mind  in  its  consideration  of  the 
world  by  the  way  of  purposes  and  through  them  to  an 
intelligible  author  of  the  world.  The  physico-teleologi- 
cal proof  by  leading  the  mind  to  consider  the  wisdom 
and  beauty  of  the  world,  and,  so,  to  think  a  causality 
according  to  purposes,  makes  the  mind  more  susceptible 
to  the  moral  argument.  "  The  argument  from  design 
mingles  itself  with  the  moral  argument  and  serves  as  a 
desirable  confirmation  of  the  latter." 

1  Abbott,  op.  city  p.  221. 

2  R.,  VIII,  265.     H.,  V,  130  f.     Abbott,  op.  tit.,  p.  221  f. 


98  Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

The  present  section  may  be  summed  up  by  repeating 
that  the  notion  of  design  suggested  by  the  Beautiful 
and  the  Organic  points  to  and  is  evidence  of  a  force  or 
principle  in  nature  over  and  above  physical  forces. 
There  is  evidence  of  the  work  of  purpose  in  nature  ;  an 
idea  is  thought  to  be  immanent  in  certain  of  its  pro- 
ducts. Now  if  this  belief  is  well  grounded,  we  are  en- 
couraged to  hope  that  our  ideas,  or  purposes,  may  find 
expression  in  the  natural  world ;  in  short,  that  man 
through  freedom,  may  actualize  the  demands  of  the 
practical  Reason.  In  the  second  place,  the  evidence  of 
design  in  nature  helps  to  strengthen  the  argument  for 
the  existence  of  God — a  necessary  condition  of  the  real- 
ization of  the  summum  bonum. 

In  discussing  the  meaning  and  function  of  the  princi- 
ple of  teleology,  no  special  notice  has  been  taken  of  the 
fact  that  Kant  maintained  to  the  last  that  the  latter  has 
merely  subjective  validity,  and  is  valuable  only  as  a 
methodological  principle  of  investigation ;  that  he  never 
tires  of  warning  his  reader  against  the  dangers  involved 
in  the  attempt  to  give  that  principle  objective  applica- 
tions. Justification  for  this  mode  of  procedure  may,  I 
think,  be  found  in  the  fact  that  Kant  himself,  despite 
his  repeated  warnings,  applies  the  teleological  principle 
with  as  much  confidence,  apparently,  as  if  he  believed  it 
to  possess  objective  validity.  Moreover,  we  are  justified 
in  passing  over  lightly  Kant's  protests,  because  the  notion 
of  design,  if  reduced  to  a  merely  regulative  principle,  loses 
its  meaning  and  efficacy  as  a  means  of  mediating  the 
concepts  of  freedom  and  nature.  For,  if  we  conclude 
that  after  all  there  is  no  purpose,  no  design  in  nature, 
then  the  great  structure  built  up  in  the  Critique  of 
Judgment  on  the  unwarranted  assumption  of  purposive- 


Teleology  in  Kanfs  Ethics.  99 

ness  in  nature,  is  like  a  house  built  upon  the  sand.    It  has 
been  assumed,  throughout  this  thesis,  therefore,  that  Kant 
would  have  given  teleology  a  place  among  the  determi- 
nant concepts  of  the  understanding,  if  he  had  not  been 
bound  by  the  supposed  finality  and  completeness  of  the 
table  of  categories  drawn  up  in  the  first  Critique.     Kant, 
following  the  cue  he  had  taken  from  formal  logic,  sup- 
posed that  he  had  found  a  complete  list  of  the  possible 
ways  in  which  the  pure  understanding  manifests  itself 
in   the  complex  of  experience.      He  could  not  admit  a 
new  category  without  disturbing  the  table  already  estab- 
lished ;  and,  what  was  more  serious  than  the  mere  inter- 
ference with  the  formal  symmetry  of  his  scheme,  the  ad- 
mission of  a  new  category  would  have  necessitated  a  re- 
construction of  his  theory  of  knowledge.     It  is  more  than 
probable,  therefore,  that  Kant  would  have  clothed  teleol- 
ogy with  the  power  of  objective  determination  if  he  had 
not  been  limited  by  the  theory  of  knowledge  worked  out  in 
the  first  Critique.       For  its  objective  validity  can  appar- 
ently be  justified  by  appealing  to  the  principle  employed 
by  Kant  as  a  guide  in  the  deduction  of  the  categories. 
That  principle  is  that,  "it  is  really  a  sufficient  deduction 
of  the  categories  and  a  justification  of  their  objective  valid- 
ity, if  we  succeed  in  proving  that  by  them  alone,  an  object 
can  be  thought. nl   That  is,  a  category  is  a  necessary  postu- 
late of  knowledge,  its  validity  is  sufficiently  guaranteed, 
if  it  can  be  shown  that  it  is  required  and  presupposed  in 
our  actual  experience.     Now,  we  ask,  cannot  the  princi- 
ple of  purposiveness  be  given  a  place  among  the  catego- 
ries upon  this  ground  ?     If  it  is  true,  as  Kant  holds,  that 
the  mechanical  explanation  of  the  world  leaves  our  knowl- 
edge incomplete  ;   if  it  is  true  that  we  cannot  fully  under- 
stand nature  or  any  of  its  parts  until  we  have  an  insight 
JR.,  92      H.,566.     M,  II,  86. 

LOFC 


ioo        Teleology  in  Kanfs    Critical  Philosophy. 

into  its  meaning  and  purpose,  what  justification  can  be 
found  for  stopping  short  of  the  teleological  explanation 
of  the  world  ?  It  is  true  that  teleology  does  not  seem  as 
fundamental  to  the  very  existence  of  experience  as  some 
of  the  other  categories.  We  can  have  an  experience  of 
objects — an  experience  too  which  has  some  degree  of 
unity  and  coherence — without  the  notion  of  purpose. 
But  as  Kant  has  said,  our  experience  can  never  be  a  real 
unity  without  this  idea.  It  is  necessary  to  satisfy  our 
demand  for  complete  explanation,  and  to  make  the  world 
fully  intelligible.  And  this  being  so,  teleology  it  seems 
to  me  to  be  proved  or  justified  in  exactly  the  same  way  as 
the  principle  of  causality.  Moreover,  it  might  be  urged 
- — and  this  argument  would  have  much  weight  from 
Kant's  standpoint — that  the  validity  of  the  teleological 
view  of  the  world  is  a  necessary  requirement  of  morals  and 
religion.  The  conception  of  the  world  as  flowing  from 
and  guided  by  a  Divine  purpose  is  fundamental  to  the 
moral  and  religious  life.  u  That  is,  it  is  necessary  to 
assume  a  morally-legislating  Being  outside  the  world 
from  purely  moral  grounds  on  the  mere  recommendation 
of  a  purely  practical  Reason  legislating  by  itself  alone. 
.  .  .  We  must  assume  a  moral  World-Cause  in  order  to 
set  before  ourselves  a  final  purpose  consistently  with  the 
moral  law.n 


LEJL  D8 


THE 


PRINCIPLE  OF  TELEOLOGY 


*  The  Critical  Philosophy  of  Kant 


BY 


DAVID   R.  MAJOR,  B.S. 


A  Thesis  presented  to  the  Faculty  of  Cornell  University 

for  the  degree  of  Doctor  of  Philosophy, 

May,  1896 


Ithaca,  N.  Y. 

Andrus  &  Church 

1897 


Deacidified  using  the  Bookkeeper  process. 
Neutralizing  agent:  Magnesium  Oxide 
Treatment  Date:  Sept.  2004 

PreservationTechnologies 

A  WORLD  LEADER  IN  PAPER  PRESERVATION 

1 1 1  Thomson  Park  Drive 
Cranberry  Township.  PA  16066 
(724)779-2111