Skip to main content

Full text of "Projective Geometry Vol I"

See other formats


PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 



BY 

OSWALD VEBLEN 

MIOFMSSOR OV MATHKMATIOS, PUINOBTON UNIVERSITY 
AND 

JOHN WESLEY YOUNG 

I'UOl l.sMW HP MATUKMATICH, DAHTMOUTII COLLEGE 



VOLUME I 




GINN AND COMPANY 

BOSTON NKW YOUK CHICAGO * LONDON 
ATLANTA DALLAS COLUMBUS * SAN FRANCISCO 



5221 



ENTBttBO AT 

\ 

COJ'VHK.HT, Mil, MV 

OHWAU) VKIthHN ANI iKUIN Wl-fcM V 



N AH. UIUIITM ttl'HKWVKW 

PHINTBD IN TJtIC UNI't'Ktt Ht.Vi'KH Ol** AWJSttt*'* 
WK.1 



* \ 

! i Ilk ANY '* 
o 



PRIBTUK8 BUHTtJN 4 



PREFACE 



Geometry, which had boon for centuries the most perfect example 
of a deductive science, during the creative period of the nineteenth 
century outgrew its old logical forms. The most recent period has 
however brought a clearer understanding of the logical foundations 
of mathematics and thus has made it possible for the exposition of 
geometry to resume the purely deductive form. But the treatment 
in the books which have hitherto appeared makes the woj'k of lay- 
ing the foundations seem so formidable as either to require for itself 
a separate treatise, or to be passed over without attention to more 
than the outlines. This is partly due to the fact that m giving the 
complete foundation for ordinary real or complex geometry, it is 
necessary to make a study of linear order and continuity, a study 
which is not only extremely delicate, but whose methods are those 
of the theory of functions of a real variable rather than of elemeh- 
tary geometry. 

The present work, which is to consist of two volumes and is in- 
tended to be available as a text in courses offered in American uni- 
versities to upper-class and graduate students, seeks to avoid this 
dilnoulty by deferring the study of order and continuity to the sec- 
ond volume. The more elementary part of the subject rests on a 
very simple set of assumptions which characterize what may be 
called "general projectivo geometry." It will be found that the 
theorems selected on this basis of logical simplicity are also elemen- 
tary in the HGIUJO of being easily comprehended and often used. 

Even the limited space devoted in this volume to the foundations 
may seem a drawback from the pedagogical point of view of some 
mathematicians. To this we can only reply that, in our opinion, 
an adequate knowledge of geometry cannot be obtained without 
attention to the foundations. We believe, moreover, that the 
abstract treatment is peculiarly desirable in projective geometry, 
because it is through the latter that the other geometric disciplines 
are most readily coordinated* Since it is more natural to derive 

m 



iv PREFACE 

the geometrical disciplines associated with the names of Euclid, 
Descartes, Lobatchewsky, etc., from protective geometry than it 
is to derive projective geometry from one of them, it is natural to 
take the foundations of projoctive geometry as the foundations of 
all geometry. 

The deferring of linear order and continuity to the second vol- 
ume has necessitated the deferring of the discussion of the metric 
geometries characterized by certain subgroups of the general pro- 
jective group. Such elementary applications as the metric proper- 
ties of conies will therefore be found in the second volume. This 
will be a disadvantage if the present volume is to be used for a 
short course in which it is desired to include metric applications. 
But the arrangement of the material will make it possible, when 
the second volume is ready, to pass directly from Chapter VIII of 
the first volume to the study of order relations (which may them- 
selves be passed over without detailed discussion, if this is thought 
desirable), and thence to the development of Euclidean metric 
geometry. We think that much is to be gained pedagogically as 
well as scientifically by maintaining the sharp distinction between 
the projective and the metric. 

The introduction of analytic methods on a purely synthetic basis 
in Chapter VI brings clearly to light the generality of the set of 
assumptions used in this volume. What we call " general projective 
geometry " is, analytically, the geometry associated with a general 
number field. All the theorems of this volume are valid, not alone 
in the ordinary real and the ordinary complex projective spaces, but 
also in the ordinary rational space and in the finite spaces. The 
bearing of this general theory once fully comprehended by the 
student, it is hoped that he will gain a vivid conception of the 
organic unity of mathematics, which recent developments of postu- 
lational methods have so greatly emphasized. 

The form of exposition throughout the book has been, condi- 
tioned by the purpose of keeping to the fore such general ideas as 
group, configuration, linear dependence, the correspondence be 
tween. and the logical mterchangeability of analytic and synthetic 
methods, etc. Between two methods of treatment we have choser 
the more conventional in all cases where a new method did nol 
seem to have unquestionable advantages. We have tried also t< 



PBEFACE V 

avoid in general the introduction of new terminology. The use 
of the word on in connection with duality was suggested by Pro- 
fessor Frank Morley. 

We have included among the exercises many theorems which in 
a larger treatise would naturally have formed part of the text. 
The more important and difficult of these have been accompanied 
by references to other textbooks and to journals, which it is hoped 
will introduce the student to the literature in a natural way. There 
has boon no systematic effort, however, to trace theorems to their 
original sources, so that the book may be justly criticized for not 
always giving due credit to geometers whose results have been 
used. 

Our cordial thanks are due to several of our colleagues and stu- 
dents who have given us help and suggestions. Dr. H. H. Mitchell 
has made all the drawings. The proof sheets have been read in whole 
or in part by Professors Birkhoff, Eisenhart, and Wedderburn, of 
Princeton University, and by Dr. R. L. Borger of the University 
of Illinois. Finally, we desire to express to Ginn and Company our 
sincere appreciation of the courtesies extended to us. 

0. VEBLEIST 

J. W. YOUNG 
August, 1910 



In the second impression we have corrected a number of typo- 
graphical and other errors We have also added (p, 343) two 
pages of "Notes and Corrections" dealing with inaccuracies or 
obscurities which could not be readily dealt with in the text. We 
wish to express our cordial thanks to those readers who have kindly 

called our attention to errors and ambiguities. 

o.v. 

J.W.Y. 
August, 1016 



CONTENTS 



INTRODUCTION 

SffiOTION TAQB 

I Undefined elements and unproved propositions 1 

2. Consistency, categoricalness, independence. Example of a mathematical 

science 2 

3. Ideal elements in geometry . . .... 7 

4. Consistency of the notion of points, lines, and plane at infinity 9 

5. Protective and metric geometry . . 12 

CHAPTER I 
THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY 

6. The assumptions of alignment 15 

7. The plane ... 17 

8 The fiist assumption of extension .... 18 

{) The tlueo-space 20 

10. The remaining assumptions of extension for a space of three dimensions . 24 

11. The principle of duality 20 

12. The theorems of alignment for a space of n dimensions 29 

CHAPTER II 
PROJECTION, SECTION, PERSPEQTIVITY, ELEMENTARY CONFIGURATIONS 

IS, Projection, section, porspectivity 84 

14. The complete n-pomt, etc. . . SO 

15. OoniigmatioiiB , . . 88 

10. Tho DoHttrguos configuration 89 

17. Perspective tetrahedra 48 

18. Tho quadrangle-quadrilateral configuration 44. 

19. The fundamental theorem on quadrangular sets 47 

20. Additional remarks concerning the Desargues configuration 61 

CHAPTER III 

FKOJEOTIVITIES OB 1 THE PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS OF ONE, TWO, 
AND THREE DIMENSIONS 

21. The nine primitive geometric forms .55 

22. Perspectovity and projectivity . 66 

. The projectivity of one-dimensional primitive forms .,,.*.,... 59 

vii 



viii CONTENTS 

SECTION VAGI6 

24. General theory of coriespondence. Symbolic tieatment (54 

26. The notion of a group 00 

26. Groups of correspondences. Invariant elements and figures .... 07 

27. Gioup properties of projectivities (58 

28. Projective transformations of two-dimensional forms 71 

20 Projective collineations of three-dimensional forms 76 



CHAPTER IV 

HARMONIC CONSTRUCTIONS AND THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF 
PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 

80. The projoctivity of quadrangular sets 70 

81. Harmonic sets , 80 

- 32. Nets of rationality on a line 81 

* 88. Nets of rationality in the plane 8(5 

34 Nets of rationality in space 80 

35, The fundamental theorem of projectivity 1)3 

86. The configuration of Pappus Mutually inscribed and ciicumscribed tri- 
angles 08 

37. Construction of projectivitios on one-dimensional forms 100 

38. Involutions 102 

30. Axis and center of homology 103 

40. Types of collineations in the plane 10(5 

CHAPTER V 
CONIC SECTIONS 

41. Definitions, Pascal's and Brianchon'fl theorems 100 

42. Tangents. Points of contact . . . 112 

43. The tangents to a point conic form a line conic 110 

44. The polar system oJt a conic 120 

45. Degenerate conies 12(1 

46. Desargues'a theorem on comes 127 

47. Pencils and ranges of conies. Order of contact . . . , 128 

CHAPTER VI 
ALCiEBlU OF POINTS AND ONE-DIMENSIONAL COORDINATE SYSTEMS 

48. Addition of points 141 

40. Multiplication of points 144 

60. The commutative law for mulLiplication 148 

61. The inverse operations ,,..,,,, ,,,., 148 

62. The abstract concept of a number system. Isomorphism ....... 149 

68. 1 Nonhomogeneous coordinates 160 

64. The analytic expression for a projectivity in a one-dimensional primitive 

form ....... . * , . , , 162 

66. Von Staudt'iS algebra of throws , 167 



CONTENTS ix 

SECTION PAOK 

68 The cross ratio . 15$) 

57 Coordinates m a not of rationality on a line . 102 

68. Homogeneous; coordinates on a lino . . 103 

60. Protective correspondence between the points of two diffcient lines . , 100 



CHAPTER VII 

COORDINATE SYSTEMS IN TWO- AND THREE-DIMENSIONAL FORMS 

00. Nonhomogeneous coordinates in a plane . . . . ... .109 

01 Simultaneous point and line coordinates . ... . 171 

02. Condition that a point toe on a line . . . . . 172 

68. Homogeneous coordinates in the plane . ... ,174 

04. The lino on two points. The point on two lines 180 

06. Pencils of points and lines. Projoctivity . . . ... 181 

00. The equation of a conic ..... . . 185 

07. Linear transfoimations, in a plane ... . . . 187 

08. Collmeations between two different planes . . 100 

60. Nonhomogeneous coordinates m space . . . .... 190 

70 Homogeneous cooidmates in space ... . . ... 194 

71. Linear transformations in space . 199 

72. Finite spaces .... . . 201 

CHAPTER VIII 
PKOcIECTIVITlKS IN ONE- DIMENSIONAL FORMS 

73. Characteristic throw and cross ratio . J . . ... . . 205 

74. Protective piojeclwtiea .... ... 208 

75. Groups of projectivities on a lino . . 200 

70. Projectivo transformations between conies 212 

77. Projectivities on a conic 217 

78. Involutions . 221 

70, Involutions associated with a given projectivity 225 

80 Harmonic transformations 280 

81. Scale on a conic 281 

82. Parametric representation of a conic 284 

CHAPTER IX 

GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS. INVARIANTS 

88, The degree of a geometric problem 236 

84. The intersection of a given lino with a given conic 240 

86. Improper elements. Proposition Ka 241 

86. Problems of the second degree , . 245 

87. Invariants of linear and quadratic binary forms 251 

88. Proposition K n 254 

89. Taylor's theorem, Polar forms 255 



X CONTENTS 

SECTION TAGK 

' 00. Invariants and covanants of binaiy forms . 257 

' 91. Ternary and quaternary forms and their invariants . . . 258 

1 92. Pioof of Imposition K n 260 

CHAPTER X 
PEOJECTIVE TRANSFORMATIONS OP TWO-DIMENSIONAL FORMS 

93. Correlations between two-dimensional forms 262 

4 94. Analytic representation of a correlation between two planes , . . 260 

95 General piojoctive gioup. Representation by matrices . . . 268 

90. Double points and double lines of a collmeation in a plane . , 271 

97. Double pairs of a correlation 278 

98. Fundamental conic of a polarity in a plane 282 

99. Poles and polars with respect to a conic. Tangents 284 

100. Various definitions of conies . . . . . . 285 

101. Pairs of conies . . . 287 

102 Problems of the third and fourth degrees 294 

CHAPTER XI 
FAMILIES OF LINES 

103. The regains . . . .298 

104. Tho polar system of a regains 300 

105. Protective conies .... . . . 804 

106. Linear dependence of lines 311 

107. The linear congruence . 812 

108. The linear complex . . , . * 819 

109. The Plucker line coordinates . ... 827 

110. Linear families of lines 829 

111. Interpretation of line cobrdinates as point coordinates in SB 381 

INDEX 885 




PKOJEOTIVE GEOMETRY 



INTRODUCTION 

1. Undefined elements and unproved propositions. Geometry deals 
with the pioperties of figures in space. Every such figure is made up 
of various elements (points, lines, curves, planes, surfaces, etc), and 
these elements bear certain relations to each other (a point lies on a 
line, a line passes through a point, two planes intersect, etc). The 
propositions stating these properties are logically interdependent, and 
it is the object of geometry to discover such propositions and to 
exhibit their logical interdependence. 

Some of the elements and relations, by virtue of their greater 
simplicity, are chosen as fundamental, and all other elements and 
relations are defined in terms of them. Since any defined element or 
relation must be defined in terms of other elements and relations, 
it is necessary that one or more of the elements and one or more of 
the relations between them remain entirely undefined; otherwise a 
vicious circle is unavoidable. Likewise certain of the piopositions 
are regarded as fundamental, in the sense that all other propositions 
are derivable, as logical consequences, from these fundamental ones. 
But here again it is a logical necessity that one or more of the prop- 
ositions remain entirely unproved ; otherwise a vicious circle is again 
inevitable. 

The starting point of any strictly logical treatment of geometry 
(and indeed of any "branch of mathematics) must then "be a set of un- 
defined elements and relations) and a set of unproved propositions 
involving them ; and from these all other propositions (theorems} are 
to "be derived ly the methods of formal logic. Moreover, since we 
assumed the point of view of formal (i.e symbolic) logic, the unde- 
fined elements are to be regarded as mere symbols devoid of content, 
except as implied by the fundamental propositions. Since it is mani- 
festly absurd to speak of a proposition involving these symbols as 

1 



2 INTBODUCTIOtf 

self-evident, the unproved propositions referred to above must be re- 
garded as mere assumptions. It is customary to refer to these funda- 
mental propositions as axioms or postulates, but we prefer to retain the 
term assumption as more expressive of their real logical character. 

We understand the term a mathematical science to mean any net 
of propositions arranged according to a sequence of logical deduction. 
From the point of view developed above such a science is purely 
abstract If any concrete system of things may be regarded as sat- 
isfying the fundamental assumptions, this system is a concrete ap- 
plication or representation of the abstract science. The practical 
importance or triviality of such a science depends simply on the 
importance or triviality of its possible applications. These ideas will 
be illustrated and further discussed in the next section, whore it will 
appear that an abstract treatment has many advantages quite apart 
from that of logical rigor. 

2. Consistency, categoricalness, independence. Example of a math- 
ematical science. The notion of a class* of objects is fundamental 
in logic and therefore in any mathematical science. The objects 
which make up the class are called the elements of the class. The 
notion of a class, moreover, and the relation of "belonging to a class 
(being included in a class, being an element of a class, etc.) are primi- 
tive notions of logic, the meaning of which is not here called in 
question, f 

The developments of the preceding section may now be illustrated 
and other important conceptions introduced by considering a simple 
example of a mathematical science. To this end let S be a class, the 
elements of which we will denote by A,B,0, . . . Further, let there 
be certain undefined subclasses ^ of S, any one of which we will call 
an m-class Concerning the elements of S and the m-classes we now 
make the following 

ASSUMPTIONS : 

I. If A and B are distinct elements of S, there is at least one 
m-class containing loth A and B t 

* Synonyms for doss are s&t, aggregate, assemblage, totality; in German, Menge; 



, . 

t <?f. B.Jftutoll, The [Principles of Mathematics, Cambridge, 1008 j and L. Cou- 
turat, Lea prlncjpea des tnathe'inatiques, Paris, 1905, 

t A class S' is said to be a subclass of another class S, if every element of ' is 
an element of S. 



2] A MATHEMATICAL SCIENCE 3 

II. If A and 1> are distinct elements of S, there in not more, than 
one in-class containing both A and B. 

III. Any two m-dasses have at least one dement of S in, rownwn. 
IV There exists at least one m-dass 
V. Every m-dass contains at least three elements of S. 
VI. All the elements of S do not belong to the same in-class. 
VII. No m-dass contains more than three elements of S. 
The reader will observe that in this set of assumptions we have 
just two undefined terms, viz, element of S and m-dass, and one 
undefined relation, belonging to a class The undefined terms, more- 
over, are entirely devoid of content except such as is implied in the 
assumptions 

Now the first question to ask regarding a set of assumptions is : 
Are they logically consistent? In the example ahove, of a set of 
assumptions, the reader will find that the assumptions -are all true 
statements, if the class S is interpreted to mean the digits 0, 1, 2, 3, 
4, 5, 6 and the m-classes to mean the columns in the following table : 

0123456 

(1) 1234560 

3456012 

This interpretation is a concrete representation of our assumptions. 
Every proposition derived from, the assumptions must he true of this 
system of triples. Hence none of the assumptions can be logically 
inconsistent with the rest ; otherwise contradictory statements would 
be true of this system of triples. 

Thus, in general, a set of assumptions is said to be consistent if a 
single concrete representation of the assumptions ean le given.* 

Knowing our assumptions to be consistent, we may proceed to de- 
rive some of tn*e theorems of the mathematical science of which they 
are the basis : 

Any two distinct elements of S determine one and only one in-class 
containing loth these elements (Assumptions I, II). 

* It will be noted that this test for the consistency of a set of assumptions 
merely shifts the difficulty from one domain to another. It is, however, at present 
the only test known. On the question as to the possibility of an absolute test of 
consistency, cf , Hilbert, Grundlagen der Geometric, 2d ed., Leipzig (1903), p. 18, and 
Verhandlungen d. III. intern, math. Kongresses zu Heidelberg, Leipzig (1004), 
P. 174; Padoa, L'Enseignement mathe'matique, Vol. V (1903), p. 86, 



4 INTRODUCTION 

Tlie w-class containing the elements A and B may conveniently 
be denoted by the symbol AB 

Any two m-classcs have one and only one dement of S in common 
(Assumptions II, III). 

There exist three elements of S wliioJi are not all in the same 
m-class (Assumptions IV, V, VI). 

In accordance with, the last theorem, let A, B, G he three elements 
of S not in the same m-class. By Assumption V there must he a 
third element in each of the w-classes AB> BC, CA, and by Assump- 
tion II these elements must be distinct from each other and from 
A, B } and C Let the new elements be D, J&, G, so that each of 
the triples ABD, BG1S, OAG belongs to the same m-class. By 
Assumption III the m-classes AJS and BG, which are distinct from 
all the m-classes thus far obtained, have an element of S in common, 
which, by Assumption II, is distinct from those hitherto mentioned ; 
let it be denoted by F, so that each of the triples ASF and BFG 
belong to the same m-class. No use has as yet been made of As- 
sumption VII. We have, then, the theorem . 

Any class S subject to Assumptions I VI contains at least seven 
elements. 

Now, making use of Assumption VII, we find that the m-classes 
thus far obtained contain only the elements mentioned. The #i-classes 
GD and A1SF have an element in common (by Assumption III) 
which cannot be A or J8, and must therefore (by Assumption VII) 
be Jf. Similarly, AGO- and the m-class DE have the element G in 
common. The seven elements A, B, C, D, JS, J?, G have now been 
arranged into m-classes according to the table 

A B D JS F a 

(!') B D JS F G A 

X> JE F G A B C 

in which the columns denote m-classes The reader may note at once 
that this table is, except for the substitution of letters for digits, 
entirely equivalent to Table (1); indeed (I 1 ) is obtained from (l)by 
replacing by A, I by B t 2 by 0, etc. We can show, furthermore, 
that S can. contain no other elements than J, J9, G, , JB> 2?, G. For 
suppose there were another element, T. Then, by Assumption III, 



2] CATEGORICALNESS 5 

the m-classes TA and BFG would have an element in common. This 
element cannot be B, for then ABTD would belong to the same 
m-class ; it cannot be F, for then AFTJS would all belong to the same 
m-class , and it cannot be G, for then AGTC would all belong to the 
same m-class. These three possibilities all contradict Assumption VII. 
Hence the existence of T would imply the existence of four elements 
in the m,-class BFG, which is likewise contrary to Assumption VII. 

The properties of the class S and its m-classes may also be repre- 
sented vividly by the accompanying figure (fig. 1). Here we have 
represented the elements of S by 
points (or spots) in a plane, and 
have joined by a line every triple 
of these points which form an m- 
class. It is seen that the points 
may be so chosen that all but one 
of these lines is a straight line. 
This suggests at once a similarity 
to ordinary plane geometry. Sup- 
pose we interpret the elements of 
S to be the points of a plane, and interpret the m-classes to be the 
straight lines of the plane, and let us reread our assumptions with this 
interpretation Assumption VII is false, but all the others are true 
with the exception of Assumption III, which is also true except when 
the lines are parallel. How this exception can be removed we will 
discuss in the next section, so that we may also regard the ordinary 
plane geometry as a representation of Assumptions I-VI. 

Returning to our miniature mathematical science of triples, we are 
now in a position to answer another important question To what ex- 
tent do Assumptions I-VII characterize the class S and the m-classes ? 
We have just seen that any class S satisfying these assumptions may 
be represented by Table (!') merely by properly labeling the ele- 
ments of S. In other words, if S x and S 2 are two classes S subject 
to these assumptions, every element of S x may be made to correspond* 
to a -unique element of S 2 , in such a way that every element of S 2 
is the correspondent of a unique element of S 19 and that to every 
m-class of S x there corresponds an m-class of S 2 , The two classes are 

* The notion of correspondence is another primitive notion which we take over 
without discussion from the general logic of classes. 




6 INTRODUCTION 

then said to be in one-to-one reciprocal correspondence, or to be simply 
isomorphic* Two classes S are then abstractly equivalent ; i e there 
exists essentially only one class S satisfying Assumptions 1 VII 
This leads to the following fundamental notion : 

A set of assumptions is said to ~b& categorical, if there is essentially 
only one system for which the assumptions are vahd ; i e. if any two 
such systems may be made simply isomorphic. 

We have just seen that the set of Assumptions I- VII is categor- 
ical. If, however, Assumption VII be omitted, the remaining set of 
six assumptions is not categorical. We have already observed the 
possibility of satisfying Assumptions I- VI by ordinary plane geom- 
try. Since Assumption III, however, occupies as yet a doubtful posi- 
tion in this interpretation, we give another, which, by virtue of its 
simplicity, is peculiarly adapted to make clear the distinction between 
categorical and noncategorical. The reader will find, namely, that 
each of the first six assumptions is satisfied by interpreting the class S 
to consist of the digits 0, 1, 2, ,12, arranged according to the fol- 
lowing table of i-classes, every column constituting one m-class : 

1 2 3 4 5 6 -7 8 9 10 11 12 

123466789 10 11 12 

^3 4 5 6789 10 11 12 1 2 

9 10 11 12 012345678 

Hence Assumptions I VI are not sufficient to characterize completely 
the class S, for it is evident that Systems (1) and (2) cannot be made 
isomorphic. On the other hand, it should be noted that all theorems 
derivable from Assumptions I- VI are valid for both (1) and (2). 
These two systems are two essentially different concrete representa- 
tions of the same mathematical science. 

This brings us to a third question regarding our assumptions : Are 
they independent ? That is, can any one of them be derived as a log- 
ical consequence of the others ? Table (2) is an example which shows 
that Assumption VII is independent of the others, because it shows 
that they can all be true of a system in which Assumption VII is 
false. Again, if the class S is taken to mean the three letters A, B, Q, 

* The isomorphism of Systems (1) and (!') is clearly exhibited in fig. 1, where 
each point is labeled both with a digit and with a letter. This isomorphism may, 
moreover, be established in 7 6 4 different ways. 



2,3] IDEAL ELEMENTS 7 

and the m-olasses to consist of the pairs AJ3, BC, CA, then it is 
cleflx that Assumptions I, II, III, IV, VI, VII are true of this class 
S, and therefore that any logical consequence of them is true with 
this interpretation. Assumption V, however, is false for this class, 
and cannot, therefore, be a logical consequence of the other assump- 
tions. In like manner, other examples can be constructed to show 
that each of the Assumptions I-VII is independent of the remain- 
ing ones. 

3. Ideal elements in geometry. The miniature mathematical science 
which we have just been studying suggests what we must do on a 
larger scale in a geometry which describes our ordinary space. We 
must first choose a set of undefined elements and a set of funda- 
mental assumptions This choice is in no way prescribed a priori, 
but, on the contrary, is very arbitrary. It is necessary only that the 
undefined symbols be such that all other elements and relations that 
occur are definable in terms of them ; and the fundamental assump- 
tions must satisfy the prime requirement of logical consistency, and 
be such that all other propositions are derivable from them by formal 
logic. It is desirable, further, that the assumptions be independent* 
and that certain sets of assumptions be categorical. There is, further, 
the desideratum of utmost symmetry and generality in the whole 
body of theorems. The latter means that the applicability of a theo- 
rem shall be as wide as possible. This has relation to the arrange- 
ment of the assumptions, and can be attained by using in the proof 
of each theorem a minimum of assumptions.! 

Symmetry can frequently be obtained by a judicious choice of 
terminology. This is well illustrated by the concept of "points at 
infinity" which is fundamental in any treatment of projective geome- 
try. Let us note first the reciprocal character of the relation expressed 
by the two statements : 

A point lies on a line. A line passes through a point. 

To exhibit clearly this reciprocal character, we agree to use the phrases 

A point is on a line ; A line is on a point 

* This is obviously necessary for the precise distinction between an assumption 
and a theorem. 

t If the set of assumptions used in the proof of a theorem is not categorical, the 
applicability of the theorem is evidently wider than in the contrary case. Of. exam- 
ple of preceding section. 



8 INTRODUCTION 

to express this relation Let us now consider the following two 
propositions : 

1. Any two distinct points of 1' Any two distinct lines of a 
a plane are on one and only one plane are on one and only one 
line* point. 

Either of these propositions is obtained from the other by simply 
interchanging the words point and line. The first of these propositions 
we recognize as true without exception m the ordinary Euclidean 
geometry. The second, however, has an exception when, the two 
lines are parallel. In view of the symmetry of these two propositions 
it would clearly add much to the symmetry and generality of all 
propositions derivable from these two, if we could regard them, both 
as true without exception. This can be accomplished by attributing 
to two parallel lines a point of intersection. Such a point is not, 
of course, a point in the ordinary sense ; it is to be regarded as an 
ideal point, which we suppose two parallel Imes to have in, common. 
Its introduction amounts merely to a change in the ordinary termi- 
nology. Such an ideal point we call a point at infinity; and we 
suppose one such point to exist on every line f 

The use of this new term leads to a change in the statement, 
though not in the meaning, of many familiar propositions, and makes 
us modify the way in which we think of points, lines, etc. Two non- 
parallel lines cannot have in common a point at infinity without 
doing violence to propositions 1 and 1' ; and since each of them has a 
point at mfinity, there must be at least two such points Proposition 
1, then, requires that we attach a meaning to the notion of a line on 
two points at infinity. Such a line we call a line at infinity, and 
think of it as consisting of all the points at infinity in a plane. 
In like manner, if we do not confine ourselves to the pomts of a 
single plane, it is found desirable to introduce the notion of a plane 
through three points at infinity which are not all on the same line 
at infinity. Such a plane we call a plane at infinity,* and we think 

* By line throughout we mean straight line. 

f It should, he noted that (since we are taking the point of view of Euclid) we do 
not think of a line as containing more than one point at infinity ; for the supposi- 
tion that a line contains two such points would imply either that two parallels can 
be drawn through a given point to a given line, or that two distinct lines can have 
more-than one point in common. 



3,4] CONSISTENCY OF IDEAL ELEMENTS 9 

of it as consisting of all the points at infinity in space. Every ordi- 
nary plane is supposed to contain just one line at infinity , every sys- 
tem of parallel planes in space is supposed to have a line at infinity 
in common with the plane at infinity, etc 

The fact that we have difficulty in presenting to our imagination 
the notions of a point at infinity on a line, the line at infinity in a 
plane, and the plane at infinity in space, need not disturb us in this 
connection, provided we can satisfy ourselves that the new terminol- 
ogy is self-consistent and cannot lead to contradictions The latter 
condition amounts, in the treatment that follows, simply to the con- 
dition that the assumptions on which we build the subsequent theory 
be consistent. That they are consistent will be shown at the tune 
they are introduced. The use of the new terminology may, however, 
be justified on the basis of ordinary analytic geometry. This we 
do in the next section, the developments of which will, moreover, 
be used frequently in the sequel for proving the consistency of the 
assumptions there made. 

4. Consistency of the notion of points, lines, and plane at infinity. 
We will now reduce the question of the consistency of our new ter- 
minology to that of the consistency of an algebraic system For this 
purpose we presuppose a knowledge of the elements of analytic geom- 
etry of three dimensions.* In this geometry a point is equivalent 
to a set of three numbers (x, y, 2). The totality of all such sets of 
numbers constitute the analytic space of three dimensions. If the 
numbers are all real numbers, we are dealing with the ordinary "real" 
space ; if they are any complex numbers, we are dealing with the ordi- 
nary complex " space of three dimensions. The following discussion 
applies primarily to the real case 

A plane is the set of all points (number triads) which satisfy a 
single linear equation 

ax + ly + cz + d = 0. 

A line is the set of all points which satisfy two linear equations, 

.3 + ^ = 0, 



* Such knowledge is not presupposed elsewhere in this book, except m the case 
of consistency proofs. The elements of analytic geometry are indeed developed 
from the beginning (cf Chaps. VI, VII) 



10 INTRODUCTION [INTBOD. 

provided the relations 



do not hold * 

Now the points (x, y, z), with the exception of (0, 0, 0), may also be 
denoted by the direction cosines of the line joining the point to the 
origin of coordinates and the distance of the point from the origin ; 
say by 



i *Y* OJ % 

where d = v as 2 + y* + g 2 , and Z = -jm = ^>w = -- The origin itself 

add 

may be denoted by (0, 0, 0, Je), where 7c is arbitrary. Moreover, any 
four numbers (x v x s , ss a , x 4 ) (x *f* 0), proportional respectively to 

1\ 

I, m, n, ) i will serve equally well to represent the point (#, y, 3), 
d/ 

provided we agree that (x v x z , x s , x^ and (cx v cx^ cx 8 , cx 4 ) represent 
the same point for all values of c different from 0. For a point 
(x, y, z) determines 

ex , cy 

= cl, x z f y ==cm, 



CZ 



where c is arbitrary (c= 0), and (sc v x z , x a , x^ determuies 

/i \ "\ n "' 

(1) % = -*> y*=-*> = > 

w 4 a 4 . a 4 

provided a? 4 ^ 0. 

We have not assigned a meaning to (x v oc z , x a , x^ when x t = 0, but 

it is evident that if the point ( cl, cm, en, -. } moves away from the 

\ d l 

origin an unb'imted distance on the line whose direction cosines are 

I, m, n, its coordinates approach (cl, cm, en, 0). A little consideration 
will show that as a point moves on any other line with direction 



* It should be noted that we are not yet, m this section, supposing 
known regarding points, lines, etc., at infinity, but aye placing ott*selye|f on tftfc 
basis of elementary geometry. 



4] CONSISTENCY OF IDEAL ELEMENTS 11 

cosines I, m, n, so that its distance from the origin increases indefi- 
nitely, its coordinates also approach (cl, cm, en, 0) Furthermore, these 
values are approached, no matter in which of the two opposite direc- 
tions the point moves away from the origin. We now define (x 1} x z , 
x s , 0) as a point at infinity or an ideal point We have thus associ- 
ated with every set of four numbers (x v sc z , aj g , # 4 ) a point, ordinary 
or ideal, with the exception of the set (0, 0, 0, 0), which we exclude 
entirely from the discussion The ordinary points are those for which 
x^ is not zero ; their ordinary Cartesian coordinates are given by the 
equations (1). The ideal points are those for which # 4 = 0. The num- 
bers (x v x z , x s , ( 4 ) we call the homogeneous coordinates of the point. 
We now define a plane to be the set of all points (x v x & , # 8> o; 4 ) 
which satisfy a linear homogeneous equation . 



It is at once clear from the preceding discussion that as far as all 
ordinary points are concerned, this definition is equivalent to the one 
given at the beginning of this section. However, according to this 
definition all the ideal points constitute a plane 4 = 0. This plane 
we call the plane at infinity In like manner, we define a line to 
consist of all points (x v x z , x a> # 4 ) which satisfy two distinct linear 
homogeneous equations : 

a i aj i+ &A+ C A+ ^A= 
a z x v + Z> 2 # 2 H- c 2 x s + d.^= 0. 

Since these expressions are to be distinct, the corresponding coefficients 
throughout must not be proportional According to this definition 
the points common to any plane (not the plane at infinity) and the 
plane a; 4 = constitute a line Such a line we call a hne at infinity, 
and there is one such in every ordinary plane. Finally, the line de- 
fined above by two equations contains one and only one pomt with 
coordinates (x^ OJ 2 , # 8 , 0) ; that is, an ordinary line contains one and only 
one point at infinity. It is readily seen, moreover, that with the above 
definitions two parallel lines have their points at infinity in common. 
Our discussion has now led us to an analytic definition of what 
may be called, for the present, an analytic protective space of three 
dimensions. It may be defined, in a way which, allows it to be either 
real or complex, as consisting of ; 



12 INTRODUCTION 

Points : All sets of four numbers (x v x z , x s , x^) t except the set 
(0, 0, 0, 0), where (cx v cx z , cx z , cx^ is regarded as identical with 
(x v x z) x s , C 4 ), provided c is not zero. 

Planes: All sets of points satisfying one linear homogeneous 
equation. 

Lines: All sets of points satisfying two distinct; linear homoge- 
neous equations. 

Such a proactive space cannot involve contradictious unless our 
ordinary system of real or complex algebra is inconsistent. The defi- 
nitions here made of points, lines, and the plane at infinity are, 
however, precisely equivalent to the corresponding notions of the 
preceding section. We may therefore use these notions precisely in 
the same way that we consider ordinary points, lines, and planes. 
Indeed, the fact that no exceptional properties attach to our ideal 
elements follows at once from the symmetry of the analytic formu- 
lation; the coordinate x^ whose vanishing gives rise to the ideal 
points, occupies no exceptional position in the algebra of the homo- 
geneous equations. The ideal points, then, are not to "be regarded 
as different from the ordinary points. 

All the assumptions we shall make in our treatment of projective 
geometry will be found to be satisfied by the above analytic creation, 
which therefore constitutes a proof of the consistency of tile assump- 
tions in question This the reader will verify later. 

5. Projective and metric geometry. In projective geometry no 
distinction is made between ordinary points and points at infinity, 
and it is evident by a reference forward that our assumptions pro- 
vide for no such distinction. "We proceed to explain this a little 
more fully, and will at the same time indicate in a general way 
the difference between projective and the ordinary Euclidean metric 
geometry. 

Confining ourselves first to the plane, let in and m' be two distinct 
lines, and P a point not on either of the two lines, Then the points 
of m may be made to correspond to the points of m f as follows ; To 
every point A on m let correspond that point A 1 on <m/ in which m 1 
meets the line joining A to P (fig. 2). In this way every point on 
either line is assigned a unique corresponding point on. the other 
line. This type of correspondence is called perspective, and the points 
on one line are said to be transformed into the points of the other by 



4,5] PBOJECTIVB AISTD METEIC GEOMETRY 13 

a perspective transformation with center P If the points of a line m 
be transformed into the points of a line m 1 by a perspective transfor- 
mation with center P, and then the points of in' be transformed into the 
points of a third line m" by a perspective transformation with a new 
center Q ; and if tins be continued any finite number of times, ulti- 
mately the points of the line m will have been brought into corre- 
spondence with the points of a line m w , say, in such a way that every 
point of m corresponds to a unique point of m (n) . A correspondence 
obtained in this way is called projwtwe, and the points of m are said 




FIG 2 

to have been transformed into the points of m by a protective 
transformation. 

Similarly, in three-dimensional space, if lines are drawn joining 
every point of a plane figure to a fixed point P not in the plane TT 
of the figure, then the points in winch tins totality of lines meets 
another plane TT' will form a new figure, such that to every point of 
TT will correspond a unique point of IT', and to every line of ir will 
correspond a unique line of IT' We say that the figure in TT has been 
transformed into the figure in TT' by & perspective transformatwn with 
center P. If a plane figure be subjected to a succession of such per- 
spective transformations with different centers, the final figure will 
still be such that its points and lines correspond uniquely to the 
points and lines of the original figure. Such a transformation is again 
called a protective transformation. In projective geometry two figures 
that may be made to correspond to each other by means of a projee- 
tive transformation are not regarded as different. In other words, 



14 INTRODUCTION 

protective geometry is concerned twtli those properties of Jtryi^ r&s that 
are left unchanged when the figures fire subjected to ft >voje^ve 
transformation. 

It is evident that no properties that involve essentially th.e notion 
of measurement can have anyplace in projective geometry as such ;* 
hence the term projective, to distinguish it from the ordinary geom- 
etry, which is almost exclusively concerned with properties involving 
the idea of measurement. In case of a plane figure, a perspective 
transformation is clearly equivalent to the change brought about in 
the aspect of a figure by looking at it from a different angle, the 
observer's eye being the center of the perspective transformation 
The properties of the aspect of a figure that remain unaltered when 
the observer changes his position will then be properties with, which 
projective geometry concerns itself. For this reason von Staxidb called 
this science Q-eometrie der Zarje 

In regard to the points and lines at infinity, we can now see why 
they cannot be treated as in any way different from tlie ordinary 
points and lines of a figure. For, in the example given of a per- 
spective transformation between lines, it is clear that to the point at 
infinity on m corresponds in general an ordinary point on ra', and 
conversely. And m the example given of a perspective tx*ansforma- 
tion between planes we see that to the line at infinity in one plane 
corresponds in general an ordinary line in the other. In projective 
geometry, then, there can be no distinction between tlie ordinary 
and the ideal elements of space. 

* The theorems of metric geometry may however be regarded as special cases 
of projectire theoiems. 



CHAPTER I 

THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY 

6. The assumptions of alignment. In the following treatment of 
projective geometry we have chosen the point and the line as unde- 
fined elements We consider a class (of, 2, p. 2) the elements of 
which we call points, and certain undefined classes of points which 
we call hncs Here the words point and line are to be regarded 
as mere symbols devoid of all content except as implied in the as- 
sumptions (presently to be made) concerning them, and which may 
represent any elements for which the latter may be valid propositions. 
In other words, these elements are not to be considered as having 
properties in common with the points and lines of ordinary Euclidean 
geometry, except in so far as such properties are formal logical conse- 
quences of explicitly stated assumptions. 

We shall in the future generally use the capital letters of the 
alphabet, as A, B, C, P, etc., as names for points, and the small let- 
ters, as a, I, c, I, etc , as names for lines. If A and B denote the same 
point, this will be expressed by the relation A = JS, if they repre- 
sent distinct points, by the relation A = B If A = J3, it is sometimes 
said that A coincides with B, or that A is coincident with B. The 
same remarks apply to two lines, or indeed to any two elements of 
the same kind. 

All the relations used are defined in general logical terms, mainly 
by means of the relation of "belonging to a class and the notion of one- 
to-one correspondence. In case a point is an element of one of the 
classes of points which we call lines, we shall express this relation 
by any one of the phrases : the point is on or lies on or is a point of 
the line, or is united with the line ; the line passes through or con- 
tains or is united with the point. We shall often find it convenient 
to use also the phrase the line is on the point to express this relation. 
Indeed, all the assumptions and theorems in this chapter will be 
stated consistently in this way. The reader will quickly become ac- 
customed to this " on " language, which is introduced with the purpose 

15 



16 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP. I 

of exhibiting in its most elegant form one of tbo most far-reaching 
theorems of protective geometry (Theorem 11). Two lines which have 
a point in common are said to intersect in or to meet in that point, or 
to be on a common point. Also, if two distinct points lie on. the same 
line, the line is said to join the points. Points which are on the 
same line are said to be collinear ; points which are not on the same 
line are said to be noncollinear. Lines which are on the same point 
(i.e contain the same point) are said to be copunctal, or concurrent * 
Concerning points and lines we now make the following assump- 
tions : 

THE ASSUMPTIONS OF ALIGNMENT, A 

A 1. If A and B are distinct points, there is at least one line on 
loth A and B. 

A 2 If A and B are distinct points, there is not more than one 
line on both A and B. 

A3 If A, B, are points not all on the same line, and X> and 
E (D = -2?) are points such that B, 0, D are on a hne and 0, A, JS 

are on a line, there is a point F 
such that A, B, F are on a line 
and also Z>, JS t F are on a hne 
(fig 3).f 

F It should be noted that this set 
of assumptions is satisfied by the 
triple system (1), p 3, and also 
by the system of quadruples (2), 

p. 6, as well as by the points and lines of ordinary Euclidean geom- 
etry with the notion of "points at infinity" (cf. 3, p. 8), and by 

* The object of this paragraph is simply tn define the terms in common use in 
terms of the general logical notion of belonging to a class. In later portions of 
this book we may omit the explicit definition of such common terms when such 
definition is obvious. 

t The figures are to be regarded as a concrete representation of our science, in 
which the undefined "points" and "lines" of the science are represented by 
points anrl lines of ordinary Euclidean geometry (this requires the notion of ideal 
points , cf, 8, p, 8). Their function is not merely to exhibit one of the many 
possible concrete representations, but also to help keep an mind the various rela- 
tions in question. In using them, however, great care must be exercised not 
to use any properties of such figures that are not formal logical consequences 
of the assumptions ; in other words, care must be taken that all deductions are 
made formally from the assumptions and theorems previously derived from the 
assumptions. 




7] THE PLANE 17 

the " analytic projective space " described in 4. Any one of these 
representations shows that OUT set of Assumptions A is consistent.* 

The following three theorems are immediate consequences of the 
first two assumptions. 

THEOREM 1 Two distinct points are on one and only one hne. 
(Al,A2)t 

The line determined by the points A, B (A 3 s B) will often be 
denoted by the symbol or name AB. 

THEOREM 2 If C and D (C = D) are points on the line AB, A and 
B are points on the line CD. (Al, A 2) 

THEOREM 3. Two distinct lines cannot be on more than one common 
point. (A 2) 

Assumption A3 will be used in the derivation of the next theo- 
rem. It may be noted that under Assumptions A 1, A 2 it may be 
stated more conveniently as follows . If A, B, C are points not all on 
the same line, the line pining any point D on the line BO to any 
point JS (D = E) on the line CA meets the hne AB in a point F. 
This is the form in which this assumption is generally used in the 
sequel. 

7. The plane. DEFINITION. If P, Q, JS are three points not on 
the same line, and I is a line joining Q and R, the class S 2 of all 
points on the lines joining P to the points of I is called the plane 
determined by P and I, 

We shall use the small letters of the Greek alphabet, a, /3, 7, TT, etc , 
as names for planes. It follows at once from the definition that P and 
every point of I are points of the plane determined by P and L 

THEOREM 4 If A and B are points on a plane TT, then every point 
on the line AB is on TT. (A) 

Proof. Let the plane TT under consideration be determined by the 
point P and the line I 

* In the multiplicity of the possible concrete representations is seen one of the 
great advantages of the formal treatment quite aside from that of logical rigor. It 
is clear that there is a great gam m generality as long as the fundamental assump- 
tions are not categorical (of. p. 6). In the present treatment our assumptions are 
not made categorical until very late. 

t The symbols placed in parentheses after a theorem indicate the assumptions 
needed in its proof. The symbol A will be used to denote the whole set of Assump- 
tions A 1, A 2, A3, 




JPw. 4 



18 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP. I 

1 If both A and B are 011 I, or if the hue AJB contains P, the 
theorem is immediate. 

2. Suppose A is on I, B not on l t and AS does not contain _P (fig. 4). 
Since ^ is a point of TT, there is a point B' on Z colliuear with 13 and P. 

If C be any point on AB, the line 
joining C on .^J? to P on BB' 
will have a point T in common 
with AB' = l (A 3). Hence is a 
point of TT. 

3. Suppose neither 4 nor B is 
on 2 and that .4.2? does not con- 
tain P (fig 5) Since A and .S are 
points of TT, there exist two points 
A and 5' on I coUinear with A, P and B, P respectively. The line join- 
ing A on A'P to B on P' has a point Q in common with &'A f (A 3). 
Hence every point of the line AB = A Q 
is a point of TT, by the preceding case 
This completes the proof 
If all the points of a line are points 
of a plane, the line is said to be a line of 
the plane, or to lie in or to "be in or to 
he on the plane; the plane is said to 
pass through, or to contain the line, 
or wo may also say the plane is on the 
line. Further, a point of a plane is said 
to be in or to lie in the plane, and the 
plane is on the point. 

8. The first assumption of extension. The theorems of the pre- 
ceding section were stated and proved on the assumption (explicitly 
stated in each case) that the necessary points and lines exist. The 
assumptions of extension, E, insuring the existence of all the points 
which we consider, will be given presently. The first of these, how- 
ever, it is desirable to introduce at this point, 
AN ASSUMPTION OF EXTENSION : 
E 0. There are at least three points on every line, 
This assumption is needed in the proof of the following 
THEOREM 5. Any two lines on the same plane v are on a common 
point. (A, EO) 




. 6 



ASSUMPTION OF EXTENSION 



19 




EIG. C 



Proof, Let the plane TT be determined by the point P and the line I, 
and let a and & be two distinct lines of TT. 

1. Suppose a coincides with I (fig 6). If I contains P, any point 

B of & (E 0) is collinear with P and 
some point of l=a, winch proves the 
theorem when & contains P If 5 does 
not contain P, there exist on 5 two 
points A and B not on I (E 0), and 
since they are points of TT, they are 
collinear with P and two points A' 
and B f of I respectively. The line 
joining A on A'P to P on PP/ has a 
point R in common with .4'P/ (A 3) 
i.e. 1 = a and 5 have a point in common. Hence every line in the plane 
TT has a point in common with I. 
2 Let a and & both be distinct 
fromJ. (i) Let a contain P (fig. 7) 
The line joining P to any point 
B of 5 (E 0) has a point B' in com- 
mon with I (Case 1 of this proof) 
Also the lines a and & have points 
A' and ^ respectively in common 
with I (Case 1). Now the line 
A'P a contains the points A' of 
RB' and P of .B'P, and hence has a point A in common with BR &. 

Hence every line of IT has a, point 
in common with any line of TT 
through P. (u) Let neither a nor 
& contain P (fig. 8). As before, 
a and & meet I in two points (? 
and JR respectively. Let JB' be a 
point of Z distinct from Q and 12 
(E 0). The line PP/ then meets 
a and & in two points A and B 
respectively (Case 2, (i)). If 
A ~ B, the theorem is proved. If A ^ J5, the line & has the point 
R in common with QB 1 and the point B in common with B'A, and 
hence has a point in common with AQ *= a (A 3). 




Pio 7 





20 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP. I 

THEOREM 6 The plane a determined "by a line I and a point P is 
identical with the plane /3 determined ly a line m and a point Q, 
provided in and Q are on a (A, E 0) 

Proof. Any point JB of ft is coH.in.ear with Q and a point A of m 
(fig, 9) A and Q are both points of a, and hence every point of the 

line AQ is a point of <x (Theorem 4). 

1 Hence every point of /S is a point 

A Q of a. Conversely, let B be any point 

of of. The line B Q meets m in a 
point (Theorem 5). Hence every 
point of a is also a point of /3. 

COROLLARY. There is one and only 
one plane determined "by three non- 
collinear points, or by a line and a 
point not on the line, or "by two inter- 
Fm< 9 secting lines. (A, EO) 

The data of the corollary are all equivalent by virtue of E 0. We 
will denote by ABO the plane determined by the points A, J5, (7; 
by aA the plane determined by the line a and the point A, etc. 

THEOREM 7. Two distinct planes which are on two common points 
A, B (A 3 s B) are on all the points of the line A3, and on no other com- 
mon points. (A, E 0) 

Proof. By Theorem 4 the line AS lies in each of the two planes, 
which proves the first part of the proposition. Suppose 0, not on AB, 
were a point common to the two planes. Then the plane determined by 
At JB, would be identical with each of the given planes (Theorem 6), 
which contradicts the hypothesis that the planes are distinct. 

COROLLARY. Two distinct planes cannot "be on more than one com- 
mon line, (A, E 0) 

9. The three-space. DEFINITION. If P, Q, R, T are four points 
not i the same plane, and if TT is a plane containing Q, JK, and 3T, 
the class S 8 of all points on the lines joining P to the points of IT is 
called the space of three dimensions, or the three-space deteraiiaed 
by P and TT, 

If a point belongs to a three-space or is a point of a three-space, it 
is said to "be in or to lie in or to le on the three-space. If all the points 
of a Hue or plane are points of a three-space S# the line or plane is said 



] 



THE THREE-SPACE 



21 




FIG. 10 



to lie in or to l>e in or to le on the S 8 Also the three-space is said to 
le on, the point, line, or plane. It is clear from the definition that P and 
every point of TT are points of the three-space determined by P and IT. 

THEOREM 8 If A and B are didmct points on a three-space S 8 , 
every point on the line AB is on S a (A) 

Proof. Let S 3 Le determined by 
a plane TT and a point P. 

1. If A and B are both in ir t the 
theorem is an immediate conse- 
quence of Theorem 4. 

2 If the line AB contains P, 
the theorem is obvious, 

3 Suppose A is in TT, B not in 
TT, and AB does not contain P 
(fig. 10) There then exists a point 
B' (= A] of TT collmear with B 

and P (def ). The line joining any point M on AB to P on .SJS' has 
a point M' in common with BfA (A 3). But .M 7 is a point of TT, since 
it is a point of AB 1 . Hence If is a point of S 3 (def.). 

4. Let neither A nor B he in TT, and let AB not contain P (fig. 11). 
The lines PA and PB meet TT in 
two points A' and J3' respectively. 
But the line joining A on A'P to 
J5 on PB' has a point (7 in common 
with B'A 1 is a point of TT, which 
reduces the proof to Case 3 

It may be noted that in this 
proof no use has been made of E 0. 

In discussing Case 4 we have 
proved incidentally, m connection 
with E and Theorem 4, the fol- 
lowing corollary; m ' 

COROLLARY 1 If S 8 is a three-space determined "by a point P and a 
plane TT, then IT and any line on S a but not on IT are on one and only 
one common point. (A, E 0) 

COROLLARY 2 Every point on any plane determined ly three non- 
collinear points on a three-space S 8 is on S 8 . (A) 




22 THEOBEMS OP ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY LOHAP I 



Proof As before, let the three-space be determined by -TT and JP, 
and let the three noncollinear points be A, B, C. Every point of the 
line JBC is a, point of S 3 (Theorem 8), and every point of tho piano 
ABC* is collmear with A and some point of BC 

COROLLAEY 3 If a three-space S 8 is determined fry a point P and 
a, plane TT, then TT and any plane on S 3 distinct from ir arc, on one 
and only one common line (A, E 0) 

Proof. Any plane contains at least three lines not passing through 
the same point (del, A 1). Two of these lines must meet TT iu two 
distinct points, which are also 
points of the plane of the lines 
(Cor. 1). The result then follows 
from Theorem 7. 

THEOREM $ If a plane a and 
a Ime a not on a are on the same 
three-space S a , then a and a are 
on one and only one common point. 
(A,EO) 

Proof. Let S a be determined by 
die plane TT and the point P. 

1. If a coincides with TT, the theo- 
rem reduces to Cor. 1 of Theorem 8. 

2. If a is distinct from TT, it has 

a line I in common with IT (Theorem 8, Cor 3). Let A be any point 
on a not on I (EO) (fig. 12) The planed, determined by A and a, 
meets TT in a line m = I (Theorem 8, Cor. 3). The lines I, m have 
a point B in common (Theorem 5) The line AB in aA meets a in 
a point Q (Theorem 5), which is on a, since AB is on a. That a 
and a have no other point in common follows from Theorem 4 

COROLLARY 1. Any two distinct planes on a three-space are on one 
and only one common hne. (A, E 0) 

The proof is similar to that of Theorem 8, Cor. 3, and is left as an 
exercise. 

COEOLLARY 2 Conversely, if two planes are on a common line, there 
exists a three-space on loth. (A, E 0) 

, * Tfce proof can evidently fce so worded as not to imply Theorem 0, 




Pio. 12 



9] THE THREE-SPACE 23 

Proof If the planes a and ]3 are distinct and have a line / in 
common, any point P of fi not on I will determine with a a three- 
space containing I and P and hence containing ft (Theorem 8, Cor 2) 

COROLLARY 3. Three planes on a three-space which arc not on a 
common line are on one and only one common point (A, E 0) 

Proof. This follows without difficulty from the theorem and Cor. 1. 

Two planes are said to determine the line which they have in com- 
mon, and to intersect or meet in that line. Likewise if three planes 
have a point m common, they are said to intersect or meet in the point. 

COROLLARY 4. If a, ft, <y are three distinct planes on the same S 8 
but not on the same hne, and if a line I is on each of two planes p, v 
which are on the lines fty and <ya respectively, then it ^s on a plane \ 
which is on the hne a/3 (A, E 0) 

Proof. By Cor. 3 the planes a, 
fi, 7 have a point P in common, 
so that the lines /&y, rya, aj3 all 
contain P. The line I, being com- 
mon to planes through (3y and ya, 
must pass through P, and the 
lines I and aft therefore intersect 
in P and hence determine a plane 
X (Theorem 6, Cor,). 

THEOREM 10. Tlie, three-space 
c , , .77 7 7 FIG- 18 

S s determined oy a plane TT and 

a point P is identical with the three-space S determined "by a plane 
TT' and a point P 1 , provided IT' and P' are on S s , (A, E 0) 

Proof. Any point A of S^ (fig 13) is collinear with P' and some 
point A 1 of TT'; but P' and A' are both points of S 8 and hence A is a 
point of S 8 (Theorem 8). Hence every point of S' B is a point of S 8 . 
Conversely, if A is any point of S 3 , the line AP' meets TT' in a point 
(Theorem 9). Hence every point of S 8 is also a point of S^. 

COEOLLAEY. There is one and only one three-space on four given 
points not on the same plane, or a plane and a, point not on the plane t 
or two nonintersecting lines, (A, E 0) > 

The last part of the corollary follows from the fact that two 
nonintersecting lines are equivalent to four points not in the same 
plane (EO). 




24: THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP. I 

It is convenient to use the term coplanar to describe points in the 
same plane. And we shall use the term skew lines for lines that have 
no point in common. Four noncoplanar points or two skew lines 
are said to determine the three-space in which they lie. 

10. The remaining assumptions of extension for a space of three 
dimensions. In 8 we gave a first assumption of extension We will 
now add the assumptions which insure the existence of a space of 
three dimensions, and will exclude from our consideration spaces of 
higher dimensionality. 

ASSUMPTIONS OF EXTENSION, E : 

E 1. There exists at least one line. 

E2. All points are not on the same line 

E 3. All points are not on the same plane. 

E 3'. If S 3 is a three-space, every point is on S 8 . 

The last may be called an assumption of closure* 

The last assumption might be replaced by any one of several equiv- 
alent propositions, such as for example : 

Every set of five points lie on the same three-space ; or 

Any two distinct planes have a line in common (Of. Cor. 2, Theo- 
rem 9) 

There is no logical difficulty, moreover, in replacing the assumption 
(E3') of closure given above by an assumption that all the points 
are not on the same three-space, and then to define a " four-space " 
in a manner entirely analogous to the definitions of the plane and 
to the three-space already given. And indeed a meaning can be given 
to the words point and line such that this last assumption is satisfied 
as well as those that precede it (excepting E3' of course). We 
could thus proceed step by step to define the notion of a linear 
space of any number of dimensions and derive the fundamental 
properties of alignment for such a space. But that is aside from our 
present purpose. The derivation of these properties for a four-space 
will furnish an excellent exercise, however, in the formal reasoning 
here emphasized (of Ex. 4, p. 25). The treatment for the n-diinensional 
case will be found in 12, p. 29, 

* The terms extension and closure in this connection, were suggested by N. J, Lennes, 
It -will be observed that the notation has been so chosen that Ei insures the exist- 
ence of a space of i dimensions, the line and the plane being regarded as spaces of 
one and two dimensions respectively. 



10] ASSUMPTIONS OF EXTENSION 25 

The following corollaries of extension are readily derived from the 
assumptions just made The proofs are left as exercises 

COROLLARY 1 At least three coplanar hues are on every point. 
COROLLARY 2 At least three distinct planes are on every line. 
COROLLARY 3. All planes are not on the same line. 
COROLLARY 4 All planes are not on the same point. 
COROLLARY 5. If S s is a three-space, every plane is on jS z . 

EXERCISES 

1 Prove that through a given point P not on either of two skew lines I 
and I' there is one and only one line meeting both the lines I, I'. 

2 Prove that any two lines, each of which meets thiee given skew lines, 
are skew to each other. 

3 Our assumptions do not as yet determine whether the number of points 
on a line is finite or infinite Assuming that the number of points on one line 
is finite and equal to n + 1, prove that 

i. the number of points on every line is n + 1; 
ii. the number of points on every plane is n 2 + n + 1; 
iii. the number of points on eveiy three-space is n 8 + n 2 + n + 1; 
iv. the number of lines on a three-space is (n 2 + 1) (ra 2 + n + 1); 
v. the number of lines meeting any two skew lines on a three-space is 
(n + 1) 2 , 

vi the number of lines on a point or on a plane is n 2 + n + 1. 

4 Using the definition below, prove the following theorems of alignment for 
a four-space on the basis of Assumptions A and E . 

DEFINITION. If P, Q, R, S, T are five points not on the same three-space, 
and S 8 is a three-space on Q, R, S t T, the class S 4 of all points on the 
lines joining P to the points of S 8 is called the four-space determined by 
P and S 8 . 

i. If A and B are distinct points on a four-space, every point on the line A B 
is on the four-space. 

11. Every line on a four-space PQRST which is not on the three-space 
QHST has one and only one point in common with the three-space 

iii Every point on any plane determined by thiee noncollmear points on 
a four-space is on the four-space. 

iv. Eveiy point on a three-space determined by four noncoplanar points 
of a four-space is on the four-space. 

v. Every plane of a four-space determined by a point P and a three-space 
S 3 has one and only one line in common with S 8 , provided the plane is not on S 8 . 

vi. Every three-space on a four-space determined by a point P and a three- 
space S 8 has one and only one plane in common with S 8 , provided it does 
not coincide with S_ 



26 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [OKA..I 

vii If a three-space S 3 and a plane a not on S 3 aie on the same four-space, 
S 3 and a have one and only one line in common. 

' vm If a three-space S 3 and a line I not on S,, ai e on the same four-space, 
S 8 and I have one and only one point in common 

ix Two planes on the same foui -space but not on the same tluee-space 
have one and only one point in common 

x. Any two distinct three-spaces on the same four-space have one and only 
one plane in common 

xi If two three-spaces have a plane in common, they lie in the same four-space 

xh The four-space S 4 deteimined by a three-space S_j and a point P is 
identical with the four-space deteimined by a three-space 83 and a point P', 
provided B' 3 and P' aie on S 4 . 

5 On the assumption that a line contains n + 1 points, extend the icsults 
of Ex 3 to a fom -space. 

11. The principle of duality. It is in order to exhibit the theorem 
of duality as clearly as possible that we have introduced the sym- 
metrical, if not always elegant, terminology : 

A point is on a line. A line is on a point. 

A point is on a plane A plane is on a point. 

A line is on a plane. A plane is on a line. 

A point is on a three-space. A three-space is on a point. 

A line is on a three-space. A three-space is on a line. 

A plane is on a three-space. A three-space is on a plane. 

The theorem in question rests on the following observation: If any 
one of the preceding assumptions, theorems, or corollaries is expressed 
by means of this "on" terminology and then a new proposition is 
formed by simply interchanging the words point and plane, then 
this new proposition will be valid, i e will be a logical consequence 
of the Assumptions A and E. We give below, on the let, a complete 
list of the assumptions thus far made, expressed in the " on " termi- 
nology, and have placed on the right, opposite each, the corresponding 
proposition obtained by interchanging the words point and plane 
together with the reference to the place where the latter proposition 
occurs in the preceding sections : 

ASSUMPTIONS A 1, A 2. If A and THEOREM 9, COB, 1. I aand/3 
S are distinct points, there is one are distinct planes, there is one and 
and only one line on A and JB, only one line on a and ;&* 

* By virtue of Assumption E 8" it is not necessary to impose the condition that the 
elements to be considered are in the same three-space This observation should empha- 
size, howevei, that the assumption of closure is essential in the theorem to be proved, 



11] 



THE PRINCIPLE OF DUALITY 



ASSUMPTION A 3. If A, B, are 
points not all on the same line, and 
I) and E (D & E} are points such 
that B, C, D are on a line and C, 
A, E are on a line, then there is a 
point F such that A, B, F are on a 
line and also D, J2, F are on a line. 

ASSUMPTION EO. There are at 
least three points on every line 

ASSUMPTION El There exists 
at least one line. 

ASSUMPTION E 2 All points are 
not on the same line. 

ASSUMPTION E 3 All points are 
not on the same plane. 

ASSUMPTION E3'. If S s is a 
three-space, every point is on S 3 . 



THEOREM 9, COR. 4. If a, fi, y 
are planes not all on the same line, 
and /* and v(^^v) are planes such 
that ft, <y, p are on a line and y, a, v 
are on a line, then there is a plan e X 
such that a, ft, X are on a line and 
also ft, V) X are on a line. 

COR, 2, p. 25. There are at 
least three planes on every line. 

ASSUMPTION E 1. There exists 
at least one line. 

COR 3, p. 25. All planes are 
not on the same line 

COR. 4, p. 25. All planes are 
not on the same point. 

COR. 5, p. 25. If S 3 is a three- 



space, every plane is on S 3 

In all these propositions it is to be noted that a line is a class 
of points whose properties are determined by the assumptions, while 
a plane is a class of points specified by a definition This definition 
in the "on" language is given below on the left, together with a 
definition obtained from it by the interchange of point and plane. 
Two statements in this relation to one another are referred to as 
(space) duals of one another 



If P, Q, R are points not on 
the same line, and Hs a line on 
Q and JS, the class S 2 of all 
points such that every point of 
S a is on a line with P and some 
point on I is called the plane 
determined by P and I. 



If X, /*, v are planes not on the 
same line, and I is a line on p 
and v, the class B 2 of all planes 
such that every plane of B a is on 
a line with X and some plane on 
I is called the lunette determined 
by X and I. 



Now it is evident that, since X, /*, v and I all pass through a point 0, 
the bundle determined by X and I is simply the class of all planes on 
the point 0. In like manner, it is evident that the dual of the defini- 
tion of a three-space is simply a definition of the class of all planes on 
a three-space. Moreover, dual to the class of all planes on a line we 
have the class of all points on a line, ie. the line itself, and conversely. 



28 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP.I 

With the aid of these observations we are now ready to establish 
the so-called principle of duality . 

THEOREM 11 THE THEOREM OF DUALITY FOR A SPACE OF THREE 
DIMENSIONS. Any proposition deducible from Assumptions A and E 
concerning points, lines, and planes of a three-space remains valid, if 
stated in the "on" terminology, when the words "point" and "plane" 
are interchanged (A, E) 

Proof. Any proposition deducible from Assumptions A and E is 
obtained from the assumptions given above on the left by a certain 
sequence of formal logical inferences Clearly the same sequence of 
logical inferences may be applied to the corresponding propositions 
given above on the right. They will, of course, refer to the class of 
all planes on a line when the original argument refers to the class of 
all points on a line, i.e. to a line, and to a bundle of planes when the 
original argument refers to a plane. The steps of the original argu- 
ment lead to a conclusion necessarily stated in terms of some or all 
of the twelve types of " on " statements enumerated at the beginning 
of this section The derived argument leads in the same way to a 
conclusion which, whenever the original states that a point P is on a 
line I, says that a plane TT' is one of the class of planes on a line I', 
i.e. that TT' is on V , or which, whenever the original argument states 
that a plane TT is on a point P, says that a bundle of planes on a 
point P' contains a plane TT', i e that P' is on TT'. Applying similar 
considerations to each of the twelve types of "on" statements in 
succession, we see that to each statement in the conclusion arrived 
at by the original argument corresponds a statement arrived at by 
the derived argument in which the words point and plane in the 
original statement have been simply interchanged. 

Any proposition obtained in accordance with the principle of dual- 
ity just proved is called the space dual of the original proposition. 
The point and plane are said to be dual elements ; the line is self- 
dual We may derive from the above similar theorems on duality in 
a plane and at a point. For, consider a plane IT and a point P not on 
TT, together with all the lines joining P with every point of TT. Then 
to every point of TT will correspond a line through P, and to every 
line of TT will correspond a plane through P Hence every proposi- 
tion concerning the points and lines of TT is also valid for the corre- 
sponding lines and planes through -P. The space dual of the latter 



ii, 12] SPACE OF N DIMENSIONS '. 29 

proposition is a new proposition concerning lines and points on a 
plane, which could have been obtained directly by interchanging 
the words point and line in the original proposition, supposing the 
latter to be expressed m the " on " language. This gives 

THEOREM 12. THE THEOREM OF DUALITY IN A PLANE. Any prop- 
osition deducible from Assumptions A and E concerning the points 
and lines of a plane remains valid, if stated in the " on " terminology, 
when the words "point" and "line" are interchanged. (A, E) 

The space dual of this theorem then gives 

THEOREM 13. THE THEOREM OF DUALITY AT A POINT Any prop- 
osition deducible from Assumptions A and E concerning the planes 
and lines through a point remains valid, if stated in the " on " termi- 
nology, when the words "plane" and " line" are interchanged (A, E) 

The piinciple of duality was first stated explicitly by Gergonne (1826), but 
was led up to by the writings of Poncelet and others duimg the first quarter 
of the nineteenth century It should be noted that this principle was for 
several years after its publication the subject of much discussion and often 
acrimonious dispute, and the tieatment of this principle in many standard 
texts is far from convincing. The method of formal infeience from explicitly 
stated assumptions makes the theoiems appear almost self-evident This may 
well be regarded as one of the important advantages of this method 

It is highly desirable that the reader gain proficiency in foiming the duals 
of given propositions. It is therefore suggested as an exercise that he state 
the duals of each of the theorems and coiollanes in this chapter. Pie should 
in this case state both the original and the dual proposition in the ordinary 
terminology in order to gain facility in dualizing propositions without first 
stating them in the often cumbersome "on" language. It is also desirable 
that he dualize several of the proofs by writing out m order the duals of each 
proposition used in the pi oofs in question. 

EXERCISE 

Prove the theorem of duality for a space of four dimensions Any propo- 
sition derivable from the assumptions of alignment and extension and closure 
for a space of four dimensions concerning points, lines, planes, and three- 
spaces lemains valid when stated in the " on " terminology, if the words 
point and three-space and the words hne and plane be interchanged. 

* 12. The theorems of alignment for a space of n dimensions. We 
have already called attention to the fact that Assumption E3', 
whereby we limited ourselves to the consideration of a space of only 

"* Ibis section may be omitted on a first reading. 



522 ( 



30 THEOEEMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP, i 

three dimensions, is entirely arbitrary. This section is devoted to the 
discussion of the theorems of alignment, i e. theorems derivable from 
Assumptions A and EO, for a space of any number of dimensions. 
In this section, then, we make use of Assumptions A and E only. 

DEFINITION. If J, P i} P it - , P n are n + 1 points not on the same 
(n l)-space, and S n _ 1 is an (n l)-space on J?, -2^, . , J, the class 
S n of all points on the lines joining P to the points of S n _ x is called 
the n-space determined by % and S M _ r 

As a three-space has already been defined, this definition clearly 
determines the meaning of w-space" for every positive integral value 
of n. We shall use S n as a symbol for an u-space, calling a plane a 
2-space, a line a 1-space, and a point a 0-space, when tins is convenient. 
S is then a symbol for a point. 

DEFINITION. An S r is on an S, and an S 4 is on an S, (r < t), pro- 
vided that every point of S 7 is a point of S ( . 

DEFINITION. Is points arc said to be independent, if there is no S l _ 2 
which contains them all 

Corresponding to the theorems of 6-9 we shall now establish 
the propositions contained in the* following Theorems S n l, S, t 2, 
S B 3. As these propositions have all been proved for the case n 3, 
it is sufficient to prove them on the hypothesis that they have already 
been proved for the cases ^ = 3, 4, ,/ 1 ; i e we assume that the 
propositions contained in Theorem S n _ 1 l, a, b, c, d, c, f have been 
proved, and derive Theorem S n l, a, , / from them. By the prin- 
ciple of mathematical induction this establishes the theorem for any n. 

THEOREM S n l Let the n-space S n le defined "by the point R and the 
(n l)-space R H-1 . 

a There is an n-space on any n + 1 independent points. 

J. Any line on two points of S n has one point in common with R n _]_, 
and is on S n . 

c. Any S r (r< n} on r + 1 independent points of S B is on S n . 

d. Any S r (r < n} on r + 1 independent points of S n has an S r _ 1 in 
common with R f ,_ 1 , provided the r + 1 points are not all on R H _ r 

e. Any line I on two, points of S n has one point in common with 

an V S n-i on s *- 

/. If T a and T ll _ 1 (T not on T B _ 1 ) are any point and any 
(n T)-$pace respectively of the n-space determined by R and R B _i, 
the latter n'Space is the same as that determined by T and T n l r 



12] SPACE OF N DIMENSIONS 31 

Proof, a. Let the n + 1 independent points be P , P I} - , P n . Then 
the points P v P 2 > -, P n are independent; for, otherwise, there would 
exist an S n _ 2 containing them all (definition), and this S n _ 2 with J? 
would determine an S,^ containing all the points J%, J%, - > JE? t , con- 
trary to the hypothesis that they are independent. Hence, by Theorem 
S^l a, there is an S B _ 1 on the points J I, , J^; and this S n _ 1 
with J^ determines an n-space which is on the points JJ}, J%, P 2 , , Jf t . 

1. If the line I is on R or R B _ 1} the proposition is evident from the 
definition of S n . If I is not on R or R n _ v let A and jB be the given 
points of I which are 011 S B The lines R A and R B then meet R n-1 
in two points A' and ' respectively. The line I then meets the two 
lines JB'R , R A'; and hence, by Assumption A3, it must meet the 
line A'B' in a point P which is on R n-1 by Theorem S n _ l 1 5 To 
show that every point of I is on S B , consider the points A, A 1 , P. Any 
line joining an arbitrary point Q of I to R , meets the two lines PA 
and AA', and hence, by Assumption A3, meets the third line A'P. 
But every point of A'P is on R B-1 (Theorem S n _ 1 l 5), and hence Q 
is, by definition, a point of S B 

c. This may be proved by induction with respect to r. Tor r = 1 it 
reduces to Theorem S n l 5 If the proposition is true for r Jc 1, all 
the points of an S k on k + 1 independent points of S n are, by definition 
and Theorem S^l/, on lines joining one of these points to the points 
of the S i _ 1 determined by the remaining 7<3 points. But under the 
hypothesis of the induction this S jl _ 1 is on S n , and hence, by Theorem 
S n l 5, all points of S A are on S n . 

d. Let r + 1 independent points of S n be -TjJ, J, , P r and let 1% be 
not on R M _ X Each of the lines J.Z(7e = l,- -,r) has a point Q K in 
common with R ;i-1 (by S H 1&). The points Q v Q^, '-, Q r are inde- 
pendent; for if not, they would all be on the same S,_ 2 , which, 
together with P^, would determine an S^_ t containing all the pc ; ^ta 
P k (by S r ^ x l &). Hence, by S, , t l a, there is an S r _ 1 on Q v Q z , , Q r 
which, by c, is on both S, and S B . 

e. "We will suppose, first, that one of the given points is R Let 
the other be A. By definition I then meets R n _ 1 m a point A', and, by 
S W _ J 1 J, in only one such point If R is on S B _ P no proof is required 
for this ease. Suppose, then, that R is not on S B _ lr and let be any 
point of S a _ r The line R C7 meets R B _x in a point C' (by definition). 
B^ d, S n _ 1 has in common with R^j an (n 2)-space, S w _ 2 , and, by 



32 THEOREMS OF ALIGNMENT AND DUALITY [CHAP. I 

Theorem S^le, this has in common with the line A'C" at least 
one point D'. All points of the line D'O are then on $- by S^jl &. 
Now the line I meets the two lines C'D' and C0 r ; hence it, meets the 
line CD' (Assumption A3), and has at least one point on S n _ r 

We will now suppose, secondly, that both of the given points are 
distinct from R . Let them be denoted by A and B, and suppose that 
R is not on S M _ 1 . By the case just considered, the lines R Q A and 
R Q B meet S n _ i in two points A' and B' respectively. The line /, which 
meets R -4' and R B' must then meet A'JB' in a point winch, by 
Theorem S n _ 1 l'b, is on S n _^ 

Suppose,. finally, that R is on S n _ 1} still under the hypothesis that I 
is not on R . By d, S n _ l meets R n _ x in an (n 2)-space Q /( _ 2 , and 
the plane R Q l meets R n-1 in a line I'. By Theorem S fl _ 1 l e, I 1 and 
Q n _ 2 have ui common at least one point P. Now the lines I and R P 
are on the plane R Z, and hence have in common a point Q (by Theorem 
S 2 1 e Theorem 5). By S^l Z the point Q is common to S n _ 1 and I. 

f. Let the w-space determined by T and T n _ x be denoted by T n . 
Any pouit of T B is on a hne joining T with some point of T B _ r 
Hence, by &, every point of T M is on S n Let P be any point of S n 
distinct from T . The luie T JP meets T,^ in a point, by e. Hence 
every point of S n is a point of T n . 

COROLLARY. Onn + 1 independent points there is one and but one S M . 

This is a consequence of Theorem S B 1 a and S B 1/. The formal 
proof is left as an exercise 

THEOREM S n 2 An S r and an S^ having in common an S v , lut 
not an S /J+1 , are on a common S r+L _ p and are not both on ilte same 



Proof. Itk*=p, S k is on S r . If k >p, let J? be a point on S* not 
on S p Then J* and S r determine an S rH lf and J$ and S p an S p hlj 
such that S p+1 is contained in S,. +1 and S^ If & >p + 1, let J^ be a 
point of S* not on S p+r Then P z and S r+1 determine an S r + s , while 
P z and S p+1 determine an S J)+2 , which is on S rH . 2 and S A . This process 
can be continued until there results an S p+i containing all the points 
ofSj,. By Theorem S tt l, Cor, we have i= "k p. At this stage in the 
process we obtain an S r4 . ft _ p which contains both S r and S k . 

The argument just made shows that 2J, Jj|, . . . , P k _ p) together with 
any set Q v Q a , . ., Q r+1 , of r + 1 independent points of S r , constitute 



12] SPACE OF N DIMENSIONS 33 

a set of r + Jc p + 1 independent points, each of which is either in 
S, or S i If S r and S k were both on an S B , where n < r + 1$ p> these 
could not be independent. 

THEOREM S n 3. An S r and an S h contained in an S n arc ~botli on the 
same S, +i _ n . 

Proof. If there were less than r + 7c n -f- 1 independent points 
common to S r and S^, say r+kn points, they would, by Theorem S B 2 ; 
determine an S 5 , where gr = r + k (r + k n 1) = n + 1. 

Theorems S B 2 and S n 3 can be remembered and applied very easily 
by means of a diagram in winch S n is represented by n + 1 points. 
Thus, if n 3, we have a set of four points That any two S 2 's have 
an S 1 in common corresponds to the fact that any two sets of three 
must have at least two points in common. In the general case a set 
of r + 1 points and a set of Jc + 1 selected from the same set of n + 1 
have in common at least r + k n + 1 points, and this corresponds 
to the last theorem. This diagram is what our assumptions would 
describe directly, if Assumption E were replaced by the assumption : 

Every line contains two and only two points. 

If one wishes to confine one's attention to the geometry in a space 
of a given number of dimensions, Assumptions E 2, E 3, and E3 ; may 
be replaced by the following : 

En. Not all points are on the same S A , if Jc < n. 

En' If S ts an S n , all points are on S. 

For every S n there is a principle of duality analogous to that which 
we have discussed for n = 3. In S n the duality is between Sj;^ and S n _ t _ ^ 
(counting a point as an S ), for all 7c's from to n 1 If n is odd, 
there is a self-dual space in Sj if n is even, S n contains no self-dual 
space. 

EXERCISES 

1. State and prove the theorems of duality in S 6 , in S n . 

2. If m + 1 is the number of points on a line, how many S^'s aie there in 
anS n ? 

* 3. State the assumptions of extension by which to replace Assumption En 
and En' for spaces of an infinite number of dimensions. Make use of the 
transnmte numbers. 

* Exercises marked # are of a more advanced or difficult character. 



CHAPTER II 

PROJECTION, SECTION, PERSPECTIVES. ELEMENTARY 
CONFIGURATIONS 

13. Projection, section, perspectivity. The point, line, and plane 
are the simple elements of space*, we have seen in the preceding 
chapter that the relation expressed by the word on is a reciprocal 
relation that may exist between any two of these simple elements. 
In the sequel we shall have little occasion to return to tlie notion of 
a line as being a class of points, or to the definition of a plane ; but 
shall regard these elements simply as entities for winch the relation 
" on " has been defined. The theorems of the preceding chapter are to 
be regarded as expressing the fundamental properties of this relation. f 
We proceed now to the study of certain sets of these elements, and 
begin with a series of definitions. 

DEFINITION. A figure is any set of points, lines, and planes in space. 
A plane figure is any set of points and lines on the same plane. A 
point figure is any set of planes and lines on the same point. 

It should be observed that the notion of a point figure is the space 
dual of the notion of a plane figure. In the future we shall fre- 
quently place dual definitions and theorems side by side. By virtue 
of the principle of duality it will be necessary to give the proof of 
only one of two dual theorems. 

DEFINITION. Given a figure F DEFINITION. Given a figure F 
and a point P, every point of F and a plane TT; every plane of F 
distinct from P determines with distinct from IT determines with 
P a line, and every line of F not IT a line, and every line of F not 
on P determines with P a plane, on IT determines with TT a point; 
the set of these lines and planes the set of these lines and points 
through P is called the projection on TT is called the section ^ of F 

* The word space is used in place of the three-space in which are all the elements 
considered. 

t We shall not in future, however, confine ourselves to the "on" terminology, 
but shall also use the more common expressions 

$ A. section by a plane is often called a plane section. 

34 




13] PROJECTION, SECTION, PEKSPECTIVITY 35 

of F from P. The individual lines by TT. The individual lines and 

and planes of the projection are points of the section are also 

also called the projectors of the called the traces of the respective 

respective points and lines of F. planes and lines of F 

If F is a plane figure and the point P is in the plane of the figure, the 
definition of the projection of F from P has the following plane dual : 

DEFINITION. Given a plane figure F and a line I in the plane of F; 
the set of points in which the lines of F distinct from I meet I is 
called the section of F by I The line I is called a transversal, and 
the points are called the traces of the respective lines of F. 

As examples of these definitions we mention the following: The 
projection of three mutually intersecting nonconcurrent lines from a 
point P not in the plane of the lines consists of three planes through P; 
the lines of intersection of these planes are part of the projection only 
if the points of intersection of the lines are thought of as part of the 
projected figure The section of a set of planes all on the same line 
by a plane not on this line consists of a set of concurrent lines, the 
traces of the planes The section of this set of concurrent lines in a 
plane by a line in the plane not on their common point consists of 
a set of points on the transversal, the points being the traces of the 
respective lines. 

DEFINITION. Two figures F v F 2 are said to be in (1, 1) correspond- 
ence or to correspond in a one-to-one reciprocal way, if every element 
of F x corresponds (of. footnote, p 5) to a unique element of F 2 in such 
a way that every element of F 2 is the correspondent of a unique ele- 
ment of F r A figure is in (1, 1) correspondence with itself, if every 
element of the figure corresponds to a unique element of the same 
figure in such a way that every element of the figure is the corre- 
, spondent of a unique element. Two elements that are associated in 
this way are said to be corresponding or homologous elements. 

A correspondence of fundamental importance is described in the 
following definitions: 

DEFINITION. If any two homol- DEFINITION. If any two homol- 
ogous elements of two corre- ogous elements of two corre- 
sponding figures have the same spending figures have the same 
projector from a fixed point 0, trace in a fixed plane a>, such 
such that aH the projectors are that all the traces of either 



36 PKOJECTION, SECTION, PERSPECTTVITY [CHAP. II 

distinct, the figures are said to figure are distinct, the figures are 
be perspective from 0. The point said to be perspective from co. 
is called the center of perspec- The plane a> is called the plane 
twity. of perspectivity. 

DEFINITION. If any two homologous hues in two corresponding 
figures in the same plane have the same trace on a line I, such 
that all the traces of either figure are distinct, the figures are said 
to be perspective from L The line I is called the axis of perspectivity. 

Additional definitions of perspective figures will be given in the 
next chapter (p 56). These are sufficient for our present purpose. 

DEFINITION. To project a figure in a plane a from a point onto a 
plane a', distinct from a, is to form the section by a' of the projection 
of the given figure from 0. To project a set of points of a line I from 
a point onto a line I', distinct from I but in the same plane with I 
and 0, is to form the section by I' of the projection of the set of points 
from 

Clearly in either case the two figures are perspective from 0, pro- 
vided is not on either of the planes a, a' or the lines I, V. 

EXERCISE 

What is the dual of the process described in the last definition ? 

The notions of projection and section and perspectivity are fun- 
damental in all that follows.* They will be made use of almost 
immediately in deriving one of the most important theorems of pro- 
jective geometry. We proceed first, however, to define an important 
class of figures 

14. The complete n-point, etc. DEFINITION. A complete n-point in 
space or a complete space n-point is the figure formed by n points, no 
four of which lie in the same plane, together with the n(n -l)/2 
lines joining every pair of the points and the n(n T)(n2)/& planes 
joining every set of three of the points. The points, lines, and planes 
of this figure are called the vertices, edges, and faces respectively of 
the complete w-point. 

* The use of these notions in deriving geometrical theorems goes back to early 
times, Thus, e.g., B. Pascal (1623-1662) made use of them in deriving the theorem 
on a hexagon, inscribed in a conic which bears his name. The systematic treatment 
of these notions is- due to Poncelet ; cf . his Traite" des proprie'te's projectives des 
figures, Paris, 1822. 



14] N-POINT, JV-PLASTE, JV-LIKE 37 

The simplest complete %-point in space is the complete space 
four-point. It consists of four vertices, six edges, and four faces, 
and is called a tetrahedron It is a self-dual figure. 

EXERCISE 

Define the complete n-plane in space by dualizing the last definition. The 
planes, lines, and points of the complete n-plane are also called the fate*, 
edges, and vertices of the n-plane 

DEFINITION. A complete n-point in a plane or a complete plane 
n-point is the figure formed by n points of a plane, no three of 
which are collinear, together with the n(n 1)/2 lines joining every 
pair of the points. The points are called the vertices and the lines 
are called the sides of the w-point. The plane dual of a complete 
plane w-point is called a complete plane n-hne. It has n sides and 
n(n T)/2 vertices. The simplest complete plane w-point consists of 
three vertices and three sides and is called a triangle. 

DEFINITION. A simple space n-point is a set of. n -paints ^P^P^ ,P n 
taken in a certain order, in which no four consecutive points are 
coplanar, together with the n lines %P Z> P z P a , , P n P^ joining suc- 
cessive points and the n planes P^P Z P &) , P,A^ determined by 
successive lines. The points, lines, and planes are called the lertices, 
edges, and faces respectively of the figure The space dual of a simple 
space w-point is a simple space n-plane 

DEFINITION A simple plane n-point is a set of n points P V P Z) P & ,-- P n 
of a plane taken in a certain order in which no three consecutive points 
are collinear, together with the n lines P& P Z P 3 , , P n %. joining suc- 
cessive points. The points and lines are called the vertices and sides 
respectively of the figure The plane dual of a simple plane -point is 
called a simple plane n-line. 

Evidently the simple space w-point and the simple space w-plane are 
identical figures, as likewise the simple plane n-point and the simple 
plane ra-line. Two sides of a simple rc-line which meet in one of its 
vertices are adjacent. Two vertices are adjacent if in the dual relation. 
Two vertices of a simple w-point J?J?> J? (ft even) are opposite if, ID 
the order P& - P n , as many vertices follow one and precede the other 
as precede the one and follow the other. If n is odd, a vertex and a 
side are opposite if, in the order JJP f - - P n , as many vertices follow the 
side and precede the vertex as follow the vertex and precede the side. 



38 PROJECTION, SECTIOK, PEKSPECTIVITY 

The space duals of the complete plane w-point and the complete plane 
w-line are the complete n-plane on a point and the complete n-line on n 
point respectively. They are the projections from a point, of the piano 
w-line and the plane n-point respectively 

15. Configurations. The figures defined in the preceding section 
are examples of a more general class of figures of which we will now 
give a general definition 

DEFINITION. A figure is called a configuration, if it consists of a 
finite number of points, lines, and planes, with the property that each 
point is on the same number 13 of lines and also on the same num- 
ber a 13 of planes ; each line is on the same number a al of points and the 
same number a aa of planes , and each plane is on the same number a al 
of points and the same number S2 of lines. 

A configuration may conveniently be described by a square matrix : 

123 

point line plane 

1 point a n a la a 18 

2 line a 21 a 22 a 2S 

3 plane a 81 a S2 a 88 

In this notation, if we call a point an element of the first kind, a 
line an element of the second kind, and a plane one of the third kind, 
the number a^ (i 3= j) gives the number of elements of the yth kind 
on every element of the itli kind. The numbers a u , a 22 , a 88 give the 
total number of points, lines, and planes respectively. Such a square 
matrix is called the symbol of the configuration. 

A tetrahedron, for example, is a figure consisting of four points, 
six lines, and four planes ; on every line of the figure are two points 
of the figure, on every plane are three points, through every point 
pass three lines and also three planes, every plane contains three lines, 
and through every line pass two planes A tetrahedron is therefore 
a configuration of the symbol 

433 
262 
334 



ic, io] CONFIGURATIONS 3 9 

The symmetry shown in this symbol is due to the fact that the figure 
in question is self-dual. A triangle evidently has the symbol 

3 2 
2 3 

Since all the numbers referring to planes are of no importance m 
case of a plane figure, they are omitted from the symbol for a plane 
configuration. 

In general, a complete plane w-point is of the symbol 

n n 1 

2 in(n-l) 

and a complete space w-point of the symbol 

n n-l (jj-l)(n-2) 

2 n(n-l) n-2 

3 3 $n(-l)(n-2) 

Further examples of configurations are figs 14 and 15, regarded as 
plane figures. 

EXERCISE 
Prove that the nunibeis in a configuration symbol must satisfy the condition 



16. The Desargues configuration. A very important configuration 
is obtained by taking the plane section of a complete space five-point. 
The five-point is clearly a configuration with the symbol 

546 

2 ifo"Y~ 

3 i 3 10 

i 

and it is clear that the section by a plane not on any of the vertices 
is a configuration whose symbol may be obtained from the one just 
given by removing the first column and the first row This is due 
to the fact that every line of the space figure gives rise to a point in 



40 PROJECTION, SECTION, PEESPECTIVITY [CHAP, n 

the plane, and every plane gives rise to a line. The configuration m 
the plane lias then the symbol 



10 3 
3 10 



We proceed to study in detail the properties of the configuration just 
obtained. It is known as the configuration of Desargues. 

We may consider the vertices of the complete space five-point as con- 
sisting of the vertices of a triangle A, B, C and of two points O lt O z 




not coplanar with any two vertices of the triangle (fig 14). The sec- 
tion by a plane a not passing through any of the vertices will then 
consist of the following : 

A triangle A^B^C^ the projection of the triangle ABC from 0^ on a. 

A triangle 4 Z B Z C Z> the projection of the triangle ABC from 2 on a. 

The trace of the line 6> X S . 

The traces A S) B z , <7 8 of the lines BC, CA, AB respectively. 

The trace of the plane ABC, which contains the points A 8 , JB a) C y 

The traces of the three planes AO^, BO^, 00f) v which contain 
respectively the triples of points OA^A^ OB^B^ OC^ V 

The configuration may then be considered (in ten ways) as consist- 
ing of two triangles A^B^C^ and A Z B Z C Z) perspective from a point and 



I ifl] THEOREM OF DESAEGUES 41 

having homologous sides meeting in three collinear points A 9> J3 S , C s . 
These considerations lead to the following fundamental theorem : 

THEOREM 1. THE TIIEOEEM OF DESAEGUES * If two triangles in the 
same plane are perspective from a point, the three pairs of homologous 
sides meet 'in colhnear points, ie the triangles are perspective from 
a line (A, E) 

Proof Let the two triangles he A^^C^ and A Z B Z C Z (fig. 14), the 
lines A^A Z , B^B^, C^ meeting in the point Let B^A V B Z A Z inter- 
sect in the point (7 a ; A^C V A Z C Z in J5 8 ; B^C V B Z C Z m A y It is required 
to prove that A a , B s , C s are collinear Consider any hue through 
which is not in the plane of the triangles, and denote l)y O v O a any 
two distinct points on this line other than Since the lines A Z Z 
and Afli he in the plane (A^A V 0^0^, they intersect in a point A. 
Similarly, B^O^ and B. 2 Z intersect in a point B, and likewise G^O^ and 
C Z Z in a point C. Thus ABCO^, together with the lines and planes 
determined by them, form a complete five-point in space of which the 
perspective triangles form a part of a plane section. The theorem 
is proved by completing the plane section Since AB lies m a plane 
with A 1 B V and also m a plane with A 2 B 2 , the lines A^ v A 2 B a , and 
AB meet in C s So also A^C V A 2 Z , and AC meet in B s , and B^C V 
B Z C Z , and BC meet m A & Since A s , B z , C s lie m the plane ABO and 
also in the plane of the triangles A^B^C^ and A Z B Z C V they are collinear. 

TIIEOEEM 1' If two triangles in the same plane are perspective 
from a line > the lines joining pairs of homologous vertices are con- 
current; ie the triangles are perspective from a point. (A, E) 

This, the converse of Theorem 1, is also its plane dual, and hence 
requires no further proof. 

COROLLARY If two triangles not in the same plane are, perspective 
from a point, the pairs of homologous sides intersect in collinear 
points; and conversely. (A, E) 

A more symmetrical and for many purposes more convenient nota- 
tion for the Desargues configuration may be obtained as follows: 
Let the vertices of the space five-point be denoted by J?, P Z) J%, P, P 6 
(fig. 15) The trace of the line IZ in the plane section is then 
naturally denoted by P lz , in general, the trace of the line $% by Jg 
fa j = 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, i =/). Likewise the trace of the plane J^J may 
* Gorard Desargues, 1593-1662. 



42 PROJECTION, SECTION, PEBSPECTIVITY [CHAP, n 

be denoted by Z yA (i, j, k = I, 2, 3, 4, 5). This notation makes it pos- 
sible to tell at a glance which lines and points are united. Clearly a 
point is on a line of the configuration if and only if the suffixes of 
the point are both among the suffixes of the line Also the third 
point on the line joining J^ and J% k is the point Jf t ; two points are 
on the same line if and only if they have a suffix in common, etc. 



/ * \ x v 

/ X N N 

/ \ 

B/ 



3 / v V X t 

?^V-\.\\B// 




/ 
/ 

/ 

/ 

/ 

/ 
/ 
/ 

1 PU 



& 



ElO. 15 



EXERCISES 

1. Prove Theorem V without making use of the principle of duality. 

2. If two complete n-points in different planes are perspective from a point, 
the pairs of homologous sides intersect in colhnear points. What is the dual 
theorem? What is the corresponding theorem concerning any two plane figures 
in different planes ? 

3. State and prove the converse of the theorems in Ex. 2. 

4. If two complete n-points in the same plane correspond in such a way 
that homologous sides intersect in points of a straight line, the lines joining 
homologous vertices are concurrent; i.e. the two n-points are perspective from 
a point, Dualize. 

5. What is the figure formed by two complete n-points in the same plane 
when they are perspective from a point? Consider particularly the cases n - 4 and 
n = 5. Show that the figure corresponding to the general case is a plane section 
of a complete space (n + 2)-point. Give the configuration symbol and dualize, 

6. If three triangles are perspective from the same point, the three axes of 
perspectivity of the three pairs of triangles are concurrent ; and conversely. 
Dualize, and compare the configuration, of the dual theorem with the case n^A 
of Ex. 5 (cf . fig. 15, regarded as a plane figure). 



IT] 



PERSPECTIVE TETBAHEDKA 



17. Perspective tetrahedra. As an application of the corollary of 
the last theorem we may now derive a theorem in space analogous to 
the theorem of Desargues in the plane. 

THEOREM 2. If two tetrahedra are perspective from a point, the six 
pairs of homologous edges intersect in coplanar points, and the four 
pairs of homologous faces intersect in coplanar lines ; i.e, the tetra- 
hedra are perspective from a plane. (A, E) 





FIG 10 

Proof. Let the two tetrahedra be J?-J?.ZJ and P^P^'P^P^, and let 
the lines jgJJ', P Z PJ, P 6 P t r , PPJ meet in the center of perspectivity 0. 
Two homologous edges P^ and P t 'Pj' then clearly intersect ; call the 
point of intersection P v . The points P n) P 18 , P a!t lie on the same line, 
since the triangles P^P^ and P^P^P^ are perspective from (The- 
orem 1, Cor.). By similar reasonmg applied to the other pairs of 
perspective triangles we find that the following triples of points are 
collinear : 

T> T> p . p p P-P PP'P P P 

fta* *i8> %} -na* J u> *5A) **.*> f u> ^s*? -^asj J u> -*s4 p 

The first two triples have the point P ia in common, and hence 
determine a plane; each of the other two triples has a point in 



44 PROJECTION, SECTION, PBSSPEOTIVITY [CHAP n 

common with each of the first two Hence all the points P lt lie m 
the same plane. The lines of the four triples just given are the lines 
of intersection of the pairs of homologous faces of the tetrahedra 
The theorem is therefore proved. 

THEOKEM 2' If two tetrahedra are perspective from a plane, the 
hues joining pairs of homologous vertices are concurrent, as likewise 
the planes determined ly pairs of homologous edges ; i.c. the tetrahedra 
are perspective from a point. (A, E) 

This is the space dual and the converse of Theorem 2. 

EXERCISE 

Write the symbols for the configurations o the last two Iheoiems. 

18. The quadrangle-quadrilateral configuration. 

DEFINITION. A complete plane DEFINITION. A complete plane 
four-point is called a complete four-line is called a complete 
quadrangle. It consists of four quadrilateral It consists of four 
vertices and six sides Two sides sides and six vertices Two ver- 
not on the same vertex are called tices not on the same side are 
opposite The intersection of two called opposite. The line joining 
opposite sides is called a diag- two opposite vertices is called a 
onal point. If the three diagonal diagonal line. If the three diag- 
points are not collmear, the tri- onal lines are not concurrent, the 
angle formed hy them is called triangle formed by them is called 
the diagonal triangle of the the diagonal triangle of the 
quadrangle * quadrilateral * 

The assumptions A and E on which all our reasoning is based do 
not suffice to prove that there are more than throe points on any line. 
In fact, they are all satisfied by the triple system (1), p. 3 (cf. fig. 17) 
In a case like this the diagonal points of a complete quadrangle are 
collmear and the diagonal lines of a complete quadrilateral concur- 
rent, as may readily be verified Two perspective triangles cannot 
exist in such a plane, and hence the Pesargties theorem becomes 

* In general, the intersection of two sides of a complete plane ra-pomt which do 
not have a vertex in common is called a diagonal point of the ?i-pomt, and the line 
joining two vertices of a complete plane 71-line which do not lie on the same side 
is called a diagonal line of the n-hue. A complete plane n-pomt (n-lmo) then has 
n (n -!)(- 2) (n-3)/8 diagonal points (lines). Diagonal points and lines are 
sometimes called false vertices and/a&e sides respectively. 




w] ASSUMPTION JI 45 

trivial. Later on we shall add an assumption* which excludes all 
such cases as this, and, in fact, provides for the existence of an in- 
finite number of points on a line. A part of what is contained in 
this assumption is the following. 

ASSUMPTION H . The diagonal 
points of a complete quadrangle 
are noncollinear. 

Many of the important theorems 
of geometry, however, require the 
existence of no more than a finite 
number of points We shall there- 
fore proceed without the use of v FlG 
further assumptions than A and E, 

understanding that in order to give our theorems meaning there must 
l)e postulated the existence of the points specified in their hypotheses 
In most cases the existence of a sufficient number of points is 
insured by Assumption H , and the reader who is taking up the 
subject for the first time may well take it as having been added 
to A and E. It is to be used in the solution of problems 

We return now to a further study of the Desargues confirmation. 
A complete space five-point may evidently be regarded (in five ways) 
as a tetrahedron and a complete four-line at a pomt A plane section 
of a four-line is a quadrangle and the plane section of a tetrahedron 
is a quadrilateral. It follows that (in five ways) the Desargues con- 
figuration may be regarded as a quadrangle and a quadrilateral. 
Moreover, it is clear that the six sides of the quadrangle pass through 
the six vertices of the quadrilateral In the notation described on 
page 41 one such quadrangle is JJ a> J% s , J? 4 , -Z? 6 and the corresponding 
quadrilateral is Z 284 , / 286 , l ai& , l m 

The question now naturally arises as to placing the figures thus ob- 
tained in special relations. As an application of the theorem of De- 
sargues we will show how to construct f a quadrilateral which has the 
same diagonal triangle as a given quadrangle. We will assume in our 
discussion that the diagonal points of any quadrangle form a triangle. 

* Merely saying that theie are more than three points on a line does not insure 
that the diagonal points of a quadrangle are noncollinear Cases where the diagonal 
points are collinear occur whenever the number of points on a line is 2 n + 1 

t To construct a figure IB to determine its elements in terms of certain given 
elements. 



46 PROJECTION, SECTION, PEKSPECTIVITY [CHAP, n 

Let P t , P z , PS, P be the vertices of the given complete quadrangle, 
and let Z> 12 , Z> 13 , D u be the vertices of the diagonal triangle, D 12 being 
on the side P^, D 18 on the side JflJ, and Z> lt on the side Ifi* (fig. 18). 
"We observe first that the diagonal triangle is perspective with each of the 
four triangles formed ly a set of three of the vertices of the quadrangle, 
the center of perspectimty "being in each case the fourth vertex. This 
gives rise to four axes of perspectivity (Theorem 1), one corresponding 
to each vertex of the quadrangle.* These four lines clearly form the 
sides of a complete quadrilateral whose diagonal triangle is D 12 , D 13 , D u . 




It may readily be verified, by selecting two perspective triangles, 
that the figure just formed is, indeed, a Desargues configuration. This 
special case of the Desargues configuration is called the quadrangle- 
quadrilateral configuration.^ 

EXERCISES 

1, If p is the polar of P with regard to the triangle ABC, then P is the 
pole of p -with regard to tho same triangle , that is, P is obtained from p by 
a construction dual to that used in deriving p from P. Fiom this theorem it 
follows that the relation between the quadrangle and quadiilateral in this 

* The line thus uniquely associated with a vertex is called the polar of the point 
With respect to the triangle formed by the remaining three vertices The plane dual 
process leads to a point associated with any line. This point is called the pole of the 
line with respect to the triangle. 

t A further discussion of this configuration and its generalizations will be found 
in the thesis of H. F. McNeish, Some of the results in this paper are indicated in 
the exercises 



18,19] QUADRANGULAR SETS 47 

configuration as mutual, thai is, if eithei is given, the other is determined. 
For a leason which will be evident latei, eithei is called a covariant of the 
other. 

2 Show that the configuration consisting of two peispective tetrahedia, 
their center and plane of perspectivity, and the piojectors and tiaces may be 
regarded in six ways as consisting of a complete 5-point P 12 , P 1<p P u , P 16 , P 18 
and a complete 5-plane 7r 8468 , v atM , v aasn , w sa4( ,, Tr^ M6 , the notation being 
analogous to that u&ed on page 41 foi the Desargues configuration. Show 
that the edges of the 5-plane are on the faces of the 5-point. 

3. If Pj, P 2 , P 8 , P 4 , P 6 , are veitices of a complete space 5-point, thu ton 
points Z> y , in which an edge p lf meets a face P L P t P m (/, j, !c, I, m all distinct), 
are called diagonal point*. The tetrahedia P 2 P 8 P 4 P C and Z> 12 Z) 18 D U D 1S are per- 
spective with PJ as center Their plane of perspectivity, ir^ is called the polar 
of Pj with regard to the four veitices. In like nmnnei, the points P 2 , P 8 , P 4 , P B 
deteimme their polar planes 7r 2 , TT S , ir v ir s Piove that the 5-poiut and the polai 
5-plane form the configuration of two perspective tetrahedra ; that the plane 
section of the 5-point by any of the five planes is a quadrangle-quadrilateral 
confirmation ; and that the dual of the above construction applied to the 5-plane 
detei mines the original 5-point. 

4. If P is the pole of TT with regard to the tetrahedron A^l^A^A^, then is TT 
the polai of P with regaid to the same tetrahedion? 

19. The fundamental theorem on quadrangular sets. 

THEOREM 3 If two complete quadrangles P t P z P 9 P and P^P^'P^Pl 
correspond P^ to P^', P z to P^', etc. in sitch a way that five of the 
pairs of homologous sides intersect in points of a line I, then the sixth 
pair of homologous sides will intersect in a point of I. (A, E) 

Tliis theorem holds whether the quadrangles are in the same or 
in different planes. 

Proof, Suppose, first, that none of the vertices or sides of one of 
the quadrangles coincide "with any vertex or side of the other. Let 
P^, P^, P^, PtP a , P& be the five sides which, by hypothesis, 
meet their homologous sides %'PJ, P^P^', P^P^ 1 , P a 'P & f f P^PJ in points 
of I (fig. 19) We must show that P a P^ and P^'PJ meet in a point 
of I, The triangles P^P^ and P^P z 'Pt are, by hypothesis, perspec- 
tive from. l\ as also the triangles P^P^ and P^PJPJ. Each pair is 
therefore (Theorem 1') perspective from a point, and this point is in 
each case the intersection of the lines P^' and P S P Z '. Hence the 
triangles P^P^ and %'%'%* are perspective from and their pairs 
of homologous sides intersect in the points of a line, which is evi- 
dently I, since it contains two points of I But P 8 P and J'J' are 



48 PKOJECTION, SECTION, PKRSPECTIVITY [CHAP. II 

two homologous sides of these last two triangles. Hence they inter- 
sect in a point of the line I 

If a vertex or side of one quadrangle coincides -with a vertex or 
side of the other, the proof is made by considering a third quadrangle* 
whose vertices and sides are distinct from those of both of the others, 
and which has five of its sides passing through tbo five given points 




j. 19 



of intersection of homologous sides of the two given quadrangles. By 
the argument above, its sixth side will meet the sixth side respectively 
of each of the two given quadrangles in the same point of /. This 
completes the proof of the theorem. 

NOTE 1 It should be noted that the theorem is still valid if the line I con- 
tains one or moie of the diagonal points of the quadrangles. The case in which 
I contains two diagonal points is of particular importance arid will be discussed 
in Chap. IV, 31. 

NOTE 2. It is of importance to note in how far the quadrangle P{PPP^ 
is determined when the quadi angle P 1 / > a P 8 P 4 and the line I are given It may 
be readily veiified that in such a case it is possible to choose any point P{ to 
correspond to any one of the vertices P lt P 2 , P 8 , P 4 , say 7^; and that if m is 
any line of the plane ZP X ' (not passing through P{) which meets one of the sides, 
say a, of P^P^ (not passing through P x ) in a point o I, then m may be 
chosen as the side homologous to o. But then the remainder of the figure is 
uniquely determined. 

* This evidently exists whenever the theorem is not trivially obvious. 



19] QUADRANGULAR SETS 49 

THEOREM 3' If two complete quadrilaterals a 1 a 2 a g a 4 and a(a' z a' a a[ 
correspond a 1 to a[, a s to a'%, etc in such a way that Jive of the lines 
joining homologous vertices pass through a point P, the line joining the 
sixth pair of homologous vertices will also pass through P (A, E) 

This is the plane dual of Theorem 3 regarded as a plane theorem. 

DEFINITION A set of points in which the sides of a complete quad- 
rangle meet a line I is called a quadrangular set of points. 

Any three sides of a quadrangle either form a triangle or meet in 
a vertex ; in the former case they are said to form a triangle triple, 
in the latter a point triple of hues In a quadrangular set of points 
on a line I any three points in which the lines of a triangle triple meet I 
is called a triangle triple of points m the set ; three points in which 
the lines of a point triple meet I are called a point triple of points. 
A quadrangular set of points will be denoted by 



where ABC is a point triple and D2SF is a triangle triple, and 
where A and D t B and JS, and G and F are respectively the inter- 
sections with the line of the set of the pairs of opposite sides of 
the quadrangle. 

The notion of a quadrangular set is of great importance in much 
that follows It should be noted again in this connection that one 
or two * of the pairs A, D or B, E or C, F may consist of coincident 
points ; this occurs when the line of the set passes through one or 
two of the diagonal points f 

We have just seen (Theorem 3) that if we have a quadrangular 
set of points obtained from a given quadrangle, there exist other 
quadrangles that give rise to the same quadrangular set In the 
quadrangles mentioned in Theorem 3 there corresponded to every 
triangle triple of one a triangle triple of the other. 

DEFINITION When two quadrangles giving nse to the same 
quadrangular set are so related with reference to the set that to a 
triangle triple of one corresponds a triangle triple of the other, the 

* All three may consist of coincident points m a apace in -which the diagonal points 
of a complete quadrangle are collmear. 

t It should "be kept in mind that similar remarks and a similar definition may he 
made to the effect that the lines joining the vertices of a quadrilateral to a point P 
form a quadrangular set of lines, etc. (of. 30, Chap IV), 



50 



PKOJECTI03ST, SECTION, PERSPECTIVE Y [CHAP. H 



quadrangles are said to be similarly placed (fig 20); if a point triple 
of one corresponds to a triangle triple of the other, they are said to 
be oppositely placed (fig 21) 

It will be shown later (Chap. IV) that quadrangles oppositely 
placed with respect to a quadrangular set are indeed possible. 




21 



With the notation for quadraagular sets defined above, the last 
theorem leads to the following 

COEOLLARY. If all lut one of the points of a quadrangular sot Q (AJBC, 
DJSJ?) are given, the remaining one is uniquely determined. (A, E) 

For two quadrangles giving rise to the same quadrangular set 
with the same notation must be similarly placed, and must hence 
be in correspondence as described in the theorem. 



19,20] DESARGUES CONFIGURATION 51 

The quadrangular set which is the section by a 1-space of a complete 4-point 
in a 2-space, the Desargues configuration winch is the section by a 2-spaco of 
a complete 5-point in a 3-space, the configuration of two perspective tetra- 
hedra which may be considered as the section by a 3-space of a complete G-point 
in a 4 -space aie all special cases of the section by an n-space of a complete 
(n + 3)-pomt in an (n + l)-space The theorems which we have developed foi 
the thiee cases here consideied are not wholly parallel. The leader will find 
it an entertaining and far fioin trivial exeicise to develop the analogy in full 

EXERCISES 

1 A necessary and sufficient condition that three lines containing the ver- 
tices of a tuangle shall be concuirent is that their intei sections P, Q, R with 
a line Z form, with intersections E, F, G of corresponding sides of the tuangle 
with Z, a quadrangular set Q(PQR, EFG) 

2 If on a given transveisal line two quadrangles determine the same quad- 
i angular set and are similarly placed, their diagonal triangles aie perspective 
from the center of peispectivity of the two quadrangles 

3 The polars of a point P on a line I with legard to all tuangles which 
meet I in three fixed points pass through a common point P' on / 

4. In a plane TT let there be given a quadrilateral a 1} a 2 , a s , 4 and a point 
not on any of these lines Let A v A z , A s , A be any tetrahedron whose four 
faces pass through the lines a lt a z , a s) a 4 respectively. The polar planes of 
with respect to all such tetiahedra pass through the same line of it. 

20. Additional remarks concerning the Desargues configuration. 
The ten edges of a complete space five-point may be regarded (in 
six ways) as the edges of two simple space five-points. Two such 
five-points are, for example, P^P^P^ and P^P^P^ Corresponding 
thereto, the Desargues configuration may be regarded in six ways 
as a pair of simple plane pentagons (five-points). In our previous 
notation the two corresponding to the two simple space five-points 
just given are ^AP 8i P ts P &1 and P i8 P 85 P ss P^P 4r Every vertex of each 
of these pentagons is on a side of the other. 

Every point, P^ for instance, has associated with it a unique line 
of the configuration, viz l m in the example given, whose notation 
does not contain the suffixes occurring in the notation of the point 
The line may be called the polar of the point in the configuration, 
and the point the pole of the line. It is then readily seen that the 
polar of any point is the axis of perspectivity of two triangles 
whose center of perspectivity is the point. In case we regard the 
configuration as consisting of a complete quadrangle and complete 



52 PROJECTION, SECTION, PEBSPECTIVITY [CHAP. 11 

quadrilateral, it is found that a pole and polar are homologous vertex 
and side of the quadrilateral and quadrangle. If we consider the 
configuration as consisting of two simple pentagons, a polo, and polar 
are a vertex and its opposite side, eg. 7? 2 and l^I^ 

The Desargues configuration is one o a class of configurations 
having similar properties. These configurations have been studied 
by a numher of writers * Some of the theorems contained in these 
memoirs appear in the exercises below 

EXERCISES 

In discussing these exercises the existence should l>e amnmcfl of a sufficient number 
of point* on each line so that the fitjwes in question do not degenerate. In some ctisea 
it may also ~be assumed that the diagonal points of a complete tjiinifranyle m e not 
colhnear Without these assumptions ow theoiems are true, mth'crf, but Inoittl 

1 What is the peculiarity of the Desargues configuration obtained as the 
section of a complete space five-point by a plane which contains the point of 
intersection of an. edge of the five-point with the face not coutaimng tins edge ? 
also by a plane containing two or thiee such points? 

2 Given a simple pentagon in a plane, construct another pentagon in the 
same plane, whose veitices lie on the sides of the first anil whoso aides con- 
tain the veitices of the fiist (cf p 51) Is the second uniquely determined 
when the fiist and one side of the second are given? 

3 If two sets of thiee points A, B, C and A', D', C" on two coplanar lines 
I and I" lespectively are so related that the hues A A', /?', CC" are concurrent, 
then the points of intersection of the paiis of lines AB' and DA', BC f and CB', 
CA' and A C' are collmeai with the point IV. The line thus dotarmmod is called 
the polar of the point (A A', BB") with respect to I and I'. [Duo-hue 

4 Using the theorem of Ex. 3, give a construction for a hue joining any 
given point in the plane of two lines I, I' to the point of iuterwaotion of I, I' 
without making use of the latter point 

5. Using the definition in Ex 8, show that if the point P f is on the polar p 
of a point P with lespect to two lines /, /', then the point P ia on the polar/ 
of P f with, respect to /, V 

6. If the vertices A v A 2 , A a , A 4 of & simple plane quadrangle are respec- 
tively on the sides a v a a ,a s , a 4 of a simple plane quadrilateral, and if the inter- 
section of the pair of opposite sides A l A a , A S A 4 is on the line joining the pair 
of opposite points a^, a 2 n a , the remaining pair of opposite sides of the quad- 
rangle will meet on the line pining the remaining pair of opposite vertices of 
the quadrilateral. Dualize. 

* A Cayley, Collected Works, Vol. I (1846), p. 817. G. Veronese, Mathema- 
tische Annalen, Vol XIX (1882) Further references will be found in a paper by 
w B Carver, Transactions of the American Mathematical Society, Vol VI U005} 
p. 684 ft\ n 



20] EXEECISES 53 

7. If two complete piano w-poiuts A v A v , A n and A^, A^, , A,' t arn 
so related that the side A^i^ and tho u>uwimng 2 ( 2) sides passing through 
A : and A z meet the coi responding sides of the other ?i-point in points of a lino /, 
the remaining pairs of homologous sides of the two n-pomls meet on I and the 
two n-pomts aie peispective fioiu a point. Dualize. 

8. If five sides of a complete quadrangle A^^A^A^ pass thiough five 
vertices of a complete quadnlatei al a^a^ m such a way that A^ s is on 
a a a 4 , A Z A S on a 4 a lt etc., then, the sixth side of the quadrangle passes through 
the sixth vertex of the quadnlateial. Dualize. 

9. If on each of three ooncuri ent lines a, b, c two points are given, A j , A 3 
on a; B lt B z on &; C v C z on c, there can be formed four pairs of triangles 
A i B j C k (i,j, k = l, 2) and the pairs of corresponding sides meet in six points 
which are the vertices of a complete quadnlateral (Veronese, Atti del Lincei, 
1876-1877, p 649). 

10 With nine points situated in sets of thiee on three concurrent lines 
aie foimed 36 sets of thiee peispective triangles For each set of three dis- 
tinct triangles the axes of perspectivity meet in a point; and the 36 points 
thus obtained from the 36 sets of triangles lie in sets of four on 27 lines, 



giving a confirmation 



36 3 



(Veronese, loc. cit ). 



4 27 

11. A plane section of a 6-pomt in space can be considered as 3 triangles 
perspective in pairs from 3 collmear points with coriesponding sides meeting 
in 3 collmear points 

12. A plane section of a 6-pomt in space can be considered as 2 perspective 
complete quadi angles with corresponding sides meeting in the vertices of a 
complete quadrilateral. 



13 A plane section of an w-point m space gives the configuration * 



n 2 

ti^fi 



which maybe considered (in n C n _ L ways) as a set of (n k) ^-points pei&pective 

C M JL 2 

in pairs from n -iPz points, which form a configuration "-- a ~ " and 



the points of intersection of corresponding sides form a configuration 

14. A plane section of a 7-point in space can be considered (m 120 ways) 
as composed of three simple heptagons (7-points) cyclically circumscribing 
each other. 

15 A plane section of an 11-point in space can be considered (in [0 ways) 
as composed of five 11-pomts cyclically circumscribing each other. 

16 A plane section of an n-point in space for n prime can be considered 

(in [ 2 ways) as ~ simple n-points cyclically circumscribing each other. 

A 

* The symbol n C r is used to denote the number of combinations of n things 
taken r at a time. 



54 PROJECTION, SECTION, PERSPECTIVITY [CHAP II 

17 A plane section of a 6-point in space gives (in six ways) a 5-point "whose 

10 3 
sides pass tluough the points of. a configuiation 

3 10 
18, A plane section of an n-pomt in space gives a complete (?? l)-point 

/-f ., _ O 

whose sides pass thiough the points of a configuiation "~ 1 a 

3 n-1^3 

* 19 The n-space section of an ?-point (m n + 2) 111 an (n + l)-space can be 
considered in th e n-space as (m A*) ^-points (in m C m _ A ways) perspective in pan s 
from the vertices of the n-space section of one (ni A)-pomt, the r-spaces of 
the fc-point figures meet in (r l)-spaces (r = 1, 2, , n 1) which foim the 
n-space section of a fc-point. 

*20. The figure of two peispective (n + 1) -points in an n-space separates 
(in n + 8 ways) into two dual figures, respectively an (n + 2)-point cucum- 
scribing the figure of (n + 2) (n l)-spaces. 

*21. The section by a 3-space of an n-pomt in 4-space is a configuration 

n C 2 n-2 tt _5sC 2 
3 ,A n-8 . 
6 4 B C 4 

The plane section of this configuration is 

C n-8 



22. Let there be three points on each of two concurrent lines Z lf l z . The 
nine lines joining points of one set of three to points of the other determine 
six triangles whose vertices are not on / a or J a , The point of intersection of l 
and l z has the same polar with regard to all six of these triangles. 

23. If two triangles are perspective, then are perspective also the two 
triangles whose vertices are points of intei section of each side of the given 
triangles with a line joining a fixed point of the axis of peispectivity to the 
opposite vertex. 

*24. Show that the configuration of the two perspective tetrahedra of 
Theorem 2 can be obtained as the section by a 3-space of a complete 6-point 
in a 4-space. 

* 25. If two 5-points in a 4-space are perspective from a point, the corre- 
sponding edges meet in the vertices, the coiresponding plane faces meet in the 
lines, and the corresponding 8-space faces in the planes of a complete 5-plane 
in a 3-space, 

* #6. If two (n + l)-points in an n-space are perspective from a point, 
their corresponding r-spaces meet in (r l)-spaces which lie in the same 
(n l)-space (r = l, 2 , 1) and form a complete configuration of 
(n + 1) (n 2)-spaces in (n l)-space. 



CHAPTER III 

PROJECTIVITIES OF THE PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS OF 
ONE, TWO, AND THREE DIMENSIONS 

21. The nine primitive geometric forms. 

DEFINITION A. pencil of points DEFINITION. A. pencil of planes 
or a range is the figure formed by or an axial pencil * is the figure 
the set of all points on the same formed by the set of all planes on 
line. The line is called the axis the same line. The line is called 
of the pencil. the axis of the pencil. 

As indicated, the pencil of points is the space dual of the pencil 
of planes. 

DEFINITION. A pencil of lines or a flat pencil is the figure formed 
by the set of all lines which are at once on the same point and the 
same plane ; the point is called the vertex or center of the pencil 

The pencil of lines is clearly self-dual m space, while it is the 
plane dual of the pencil of points The pencil of points, the pencil 
of lines, and the pencil of planes are called the primitive geometric 
forms of the first grade or of one dimension. 

DEFINITION The following are known as the primitive geometric 
forms of the second grade or of two dimensions : 

The set of all points on a plane The set of all planes on a point 
is called a plane of points. The is called a "bundle of planes. The 
set of all lines on a plane is called set of all lines on a point is called 
a plane of lines The plane is a "bundle of lines. The point is 
called the "base of the two forms, called the center of the bundles. 
The figure composed of a plane The figure composed of a bundle 
of points and a plane of lines of lines and a bundle of planes 
with the same base is called a with the same center is called 
planar field. simply a "bundle. 

DEFINITION. The set of all planes in space and the set of all points 
in space are called the primitive geometric forms of the third grade 
or of three dimensions. 

* The pencil of planes is also called by acme writers a sheaf. 
55 



56 PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS [CHAP, in 

There are then, all told, nine primitive geometric forms in a space 
of three dimensions * 

22. Perspectivity and projectivity. In Chap. II, 13, wo gave a 
definition of perspectivity This definition we will now apply to the 
case of two primitive forms and will complete it where needed. We 
note first that, according to the definition referred to, two pencils of 
points in the same plane are perspective provided every two homol- 
ogous points of the pencils are on a line of a flat pencil, for they 
then have the same projection from a point. Two planes of points 
(lines) are perspective, if every two homologous elements are on a 
line (plane) of a bundle of lines (planes) Two pencils of lines in the 
same plane are perspective, if every two homologous lines intersect 
in a point of the same pencil of points. Two pencils of planes are 
perspective, if every two homologous planes are on a point of a pencil 
of points (they then have the same section by a line). Two bundles of 
lines (planes) are perspective, if every two homologous lines (planes) 
are on a point (line) of a plane of points (lines) (they then have the 
same section by a plane), etc. Our previous definition does not, how- 
ever, cover all possible cases In the first place, it does not allow for 
the possibility of two forms of different kinds being perspective, such 
as a pencil of points and a pencil of lines, a plane of points and a 
bundle of lines, etc. This lack of completeness is removed for the 
case of one-dimensional forms by the following definition It should 
be clearly noted that it is in complete agreement with the previous 
definition of perspectivity ; as far as one-dimensional forms are con- 
cerned it is wider in its application 

DEFINITION. Two one-dimensional primitive forms of different kinds, 
not having a common axis, are perspective, if and only if they corre- 
spond in such a (1, 1) way that each element of one is on its homol- 
ogous element in the other ; two one-dimensional primitive forms of 
the same kind are perspective, if and only if every two homologous 
elements are on an element of a third one-dimensional form not 
having an axis in common with one of the given forms. If the third 
form is a pencil of lines with vertex P, the perspectivity is said to be 

* Some -writers enumerate only six, by defining the set of all points and lines on 
a plane as a single form, and by regarding the set of all planes and lines at a, point 
and the set of all points and planes m space each as a single form. We have fol- 
lowed the usage of Enriques, Vorlesungen iiber Projektive Geometrle. 



22] PEESPECTIVITY 57 

central with center P; if the third form is a pencil of points or ft pencil 
of planes with axis I, the perspectivity is said to bo a^nal with axis /, 

As examples of tins definition we mention the following: Two 
pencils of points on skew lilies are perspective, if every two homol- 
ogous elements are on a plane of a pencil of planes ; two pencils of 
lines in different planes are perspective, if every two homologous 
lines are on a point of a pencil of points or a plane of a pencil of 
planes (either of the latter conditions is a consequence of the other); 
two pencils of planes arc peispective, if every two homologous pianos 
are on a point of a pencil of points or a line of a pencil of lines (in 
the latter case the axes of the pencils of planes are coplanar) A pen- 
cil of points and a pencil of lines are perspective, if every point is on 
its homologous line, etc 

It is of great importance to note that our definitions of perspective 
primitive forms are dual throughout; i.e. that if two forms are per- 
spective, the dual figure will consist of perspective forms Hence any 
theorem proved concerning perspectivities can at once be dualized ; in 
particular, any theorem concerning the perspectivity of two forms of 
the same kind is true of any other two forms of the same kind. 

We use the notation [P] to denote a class of elements of any kind 
and denote individuals of the class by P alone or with an index or 
subscript. Thus two ranges of points may be denoted by [P] and [<?]. 
To indicate a perspective correspondence between them we write 



The same symbol, ^, is also used to indicate a perspectivity between 
any two one-dimensional forms. If the two forms are of the same 
kind, it implies that there exists a third form such that every pair 
of homologous elements of the first two forms is on an element of 
the third form The third form may also be exhibited in the notation 
by placing a symbol representing the third form immediately over 
the sign of perspectivity, ^. 
Thus the symbols 



denote that the range [P] is perspective by means of the center A with 
the range [$], that each Q is on a line r of the flat pencil j>], and 
that the pencil |>] is perspective by the axis a with the flat pencil [s]. 



58 PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS [CHAP in 

A class of elements containing a finite number of elements can 
be indicated by the symbols for the several elements. When this 
notation is used, the symbol of perspectivity indicates that elements 
appearing in corresponding places in the two sequences of symbols 
are homologous. Thus 

123 4: = ABC D 
A 

implies that 1 and A, 2 and 3, 3 and C, 4 and Z> are homologous 

DEFINITION.* Two one-dimensional primitive forms [or] and [a- 1 ] (of 
the same or different kinds) are said to be protective, provided there 
exists a sequence of forms [r], |V], >, [T (B) ] such that 

Co-1 __ r T -i _ r r n _ . _ rynri _ r n 
1 J A L J A L J A A L J A L J * 

The correspondence thus established between [a-] and |V] is called 
a protective correspondence or projectivity, or also a protective trans- 
formation. Any element a- is said to be projected into its homologous 
element or 1 by the sequence of perspectivities. 

Thus a projectivity is the resultant of a sequence of perspectivities 
It is evident that [cr] and |V ] may be the same form, in which case 
the projectivity effects a permutation of the elements of the form. 
For example, it is proved later in this chapter that any four points 
A, B, C, D of a line can be projected into JB, A, D, respectively. 

A projectivity establishes a one-to-one correspondence between the 
elements of two one-dimensional forms, which correspondence we may 
consider abstractly without direct reference to the sequence of perspec- 
tivities by which it is defined. Such a correspondence we denote by 



Projectivities we will, in general, denote by letters of the Greek 
alphabet, such as TT. If a projectivity TT makes an element cr of a 
form homologous with an element a- 1 of another or the same form, 
we will sometimes denote this by the relation 7r(o-) = <r'. In this 
case we may say the projectivity transforms a- into cr'. Here the 
symbol I JT( ) is used as a functional symbol f acting on the variable^ 
tr, which represents any one of the elements of a given form. 

* This is Poncelet'0 definition of a projectivity. 
t Just like F(x), sin (a), log(), etc. 

t The definition of variable is " a symbol x which represents any one of a class 
of elements [*] " It is m this sense that we speak of " a variable point." 



23] 



PEOJECTIVITY 



59 



23. The projectivity of one-dimensional primitive forms. The 

projectivity of one-dimensional primitive forms will be discussed 
with reference to the projectivity of pencils of points. The corre- 
sponding properties for the other one-dimensional primitive forms 
will then follow immediately by the theorems of duality (Theorems 
11-13, Chap. I). 

THEOREM 1. If A, B, C are three points of a line I and A', J5', C' 
three points of another line I', then A can le projected into A f , B into 
B', and C into C' ly means of two centers of perspectimty, (The lines 
may be in the same or in different planes.) (A, E) 

Proof. If the points in any one of the pairs AA', BB', or CO' are 
coincident, one center is sufficient, viz, the intersection of the lines 
determined by the other 
two pairs. If each of these 
pairs consists of distinct 
points, let S be any point 
of the line AA', distinct 
from A and A r (fig 22). 
Prom S project A, B, C 
on any line I" distinct 
from I and I', but con- 
taining A' and a point 
of I If B", C" are the 
points of I" correspond- 
ing to B, C respectively, 

the point of intersection S' of the lines B'B" and C'C" is the second 
center of perspectivity. This argument holds without modification, 
if one of the points A, B, C comcides with one of the points A 1 , B' t C' 
other than its corresponding point. 

COROLLARY 1. IfAfB^ and A', B', G r are on the same line, three 
centers of perspectivity are sufficient to project A, B, into A', B 1 , C f 
respectively, (A, E) 

COROLLARY 2. Any three distinct elements of a one-dimensional 
primitive form are projectile with any three distinct elements of 
another or the same one-dimensional primitive form. (A, E) 

For, -when the two forms are of the same kind, the result is ob- 
tained from the theorem and the first corollary directly from the 




60 PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS [CHA*. m 

theorems of duality (Theorems 1113, Chap. I). If they are of differ- 
ent kinds, a projection or section is sufficient to reduce them to the 
same kind 

THEOREM 2 The projectimty ABCD-^BADC holds for any four 
distinct points A, B, C, D of a line. (A, E) 

Proof. From a point S, not on the line I = AB, project ABCD into 
AB'C'D 1 on a line V through A and distinct from I (fig 23). From D 
project AB'C'D' on the line SB. The last four points will then project 
into BADO by means of the center C'. In fig. 23 we have 

S D C' 

AB CD = AB' C'D' = BB' C"S = BAD C. 

A A A 

It is to be noted that a geometrical ordei of the points ABCD has no bearing 
on the theorem. In fact, the notion of such order has not yet been introduced 

into our geometry and, indeed, cannot 
be introduced on the basis o the 
present assumptions alone The theo- 
rem meiely states that the corievpond- 
ence obtained by interchanging any two 
of four colhnear points and also inter- 
changing the remaining two is projectwe 
The notion of order is, however, im- 
plied in our notation of projectivity 
and perspectivity. Thus, for example, 
we introduce the following definition . 

DEFINITION. Two ordered pairs of elements of any one-dimensional 
form, are called a throw; if the pairs are AB, CD) this is denoted by 
T(AB, CD) Two throws are said to be equal, provided they are 
protective ; in symbols, T (AB, CD] T (A'B', C'D'), provided we have 
ABCDj;A'B'C'D'. 

The last theorem then states the equality of throws ; 

T(AB, CD) = T(BA, JDC)T(CZ>, AB) = J(DC, BA). 

The results of the last two theorems may be stated in the follow- 
ing form : 

THEOREM 1 ; . If 1, %, 3 are elements of any one-dimensional prim- 
itive form, there exist protective transformations which will effect any 
-one of the six permutations of these three elements. 




23] PROJECTIVITY 61 

THEOREM 2'. If 1, @, 8, 4- an any four distinct elements of a one- 
dimensional primitive form, there exist protective transformations 
which will transform 1234 into any one of the following permuta- 
tions of itself: 1234, 2143, 3412, 4321. 

A protective transformation has been defined as the resultant of any 
sequence of perspectivities. We proceed now to the proof of a chain 
of theorems, 'which lead to the fundamental restilt that any project/we 
transformation between two distinct one-dimensional primitive forms 
of the same kind can be obtained as the resultant of two perspectivities. 

THEOREM 3 If [P], [P 1 ], [P"] are pencils of points on three distinct' 

S , 8 r 

concurrent lines I, I', I" respectively, such that [P] == [P'} and [JP '] == 

S" 
[P"], then likewise [P] = [P"], and the three centers of perspectivity 

S, S' S" are collinear. (A, E) 

S" 




Proof. Let be the common point of the lines l } V, I". If P i} P z , P s 
are three points of [P], and P^'Ps' and P^'P^P^" the corresponding 
points of [JP'], [P' r ] (fig. 24), it is clear that the triangles -Z^'-ZJ", 
P^P^PX", P S P 8 'P 8 " are perspective from 0* By Desargues's theorem 
(Theorem 1, Chap II) homologous sides of any pair of these three 
triangles meet in collinear points. The conclusion of the theorem then 
follows readily from the hypotheses 

* If the points in each of these sets of three are collinear, the theorem is obvious 
and the three centers of perspectivity coincide. 



62 PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS [CHAP.III 

COROLLARY. If n concurrent 'lines l lt l z) l s , , l n are connected ly 

perspectivities [JJ] =i? [J>] = [J] =t ^-' ft], and */ ^ and l n 
are distinct lines, then we have [J%] = [j] (A, E) 

JProo/. This follows almost immediately from tlie theorem, except 
when it happens that a set of four successive lines of the set ljl a l t > . l n 
are such that the first and third coincide and likewise the second and 
fourth. That this case forms no exception to the corollary may be 
shown as follows : Consider the perspectivities connecting the pencils 
of points on the lines l v l v l s , l on the hypothesis that ^= l v l 2 l t 
(fig. 25.) Let l v l z meet in 0, and let the line S 12 S 2a meet l t in A 




A l = A, B, B 3 C, a 



and l z in A z \ let A^A^ and A be the corresponding points of l s and 
l t respectively, Further, let S v B z , 3^ B and C v C v C v C be any 
other two sequences of corresponding points in the perspectivities. 
Let SH be determined as the intersection of the lines A^A^ and B^B V 
The two quadrangles S 1Z S^B Z C Z and S^S^S^ have five pairs of 
homologous sides meeting l^l t in the points OA^B z Q y Hence 
the' side S u C t meets ^ in O l (Theorem 3, Chap. II). 

THEOREM 4. If [JJ, [P z ], [P] are pencils of points on distinct 

a 

Imes l v l v I respectively, such that [J] = [P] == [J], and if [P 1 ] is 

the pencil of points on any line V containing the intersection of l v I 
and also a point of l s) "but not containing $,, then there esoists a point 

81 on S&, such that [P,] [P'] [jg. (A, E) 



23] PEOJECTIVITY 63 

Proof. Clearly we have 

K] = F] = [^fK]. 

But by the preceding theorem and the conditions on V we have 

SI 
] [ p/ l> where S[ is a point of 8^ Hence we have 

81 8. 



This theorem leads readily to the next theorem, which is the result 
toward which we have been working We prove first the following 
lemmas : 

LEMMA 1. Any axial perspectivity between the points of two skew 
lines is equivalent to (and may be replaced by] two central perspectivities 
(A,E) 

Tor let [P], [P 1 ] be the pencils of points on the skew lines. Then 
if S and S r are any two points on the axis s of the axial perspectivity, 
the pencils of lines S[P], S'[P'"\ * are so related that pairs of homol- 
ogous lines intersect in points of the line common to the planes of the 
two pencils S[P] and S'[P']> since each pair of homologous lines lie, 
by hypothesis, in a plane of the axial pencil s[P]=s[P 7 ]. 

LEMMA 2. Any projectivity between pencils of points may "be defined 
by a sequence of central perspectivities. 

For any noncentral perspectivities occurring in the sequence defining 
a pro jectivity may, in consequence of Lemma 1, be replaced by sequences 
of central perspectivities. 

THEOREM 5. If two pencils of points [P] and [P'~\ on distinct lines 
are protective, there esdsts a pencil of points [Q] and two points S, S r 

S S 1 
such that we have [P] = [Q] = [P']. (A, E) 

Proof, By hypothesis and the two preceding lemmas we have a 
sequence of perspectivities 

# #, 8. & 



* Given a class of elements [P]; the symbol S[P] is used to denote the class 
of elements SP determined by a given element 8 and any element of [P]. Hence, 
if [P] is a pencil of points and S a point not in [P], 8 [P] is a pencil of lines -with 
center S ; if s is a line not on any P, 8 [P] is a pencil of planes 'with aaas 8. 



64 PEIMITIVE GEOMETEIC FOEMS [CHAP, m 

We assume the number of these perspectivities to be greater than two, 
since otherwise the theorem is proved. By applying the corollary of 
Theorem 3, when necessary, this sequence of perspectivities may be 
so modified that no three successive axes are concurrent. We may 
also assume that no two of the axes l t l v l v l v , V of the pencils 
[PI [PI, [Pa] , K] , [-?'] are coincident ; for Theorem 4 may evidently 
be used to replace any l k (= l t ) by a line l' k (& ty. Now let l[ be the 
line joining the points # t and lj a , and let us suppose that it does not 
contain the center 8 t (fig 26). If then [P^] is the pencil of points 
on l[, we may (by Theorem 4) replace the given sequence of per- 

% , % Sir 8 * 
spectivities by [P] = [P/] = [P^\ == [J?] ^ and this sequence 

may in turn be replaced by 
I, tfj $ 8 t 




(Theorem 3). If S s is on the line 
joining Hi an d lJa> we mav replace 
^ by any line % through the inter- 
section of ljl a which meets I and 
p JG 2 Q does not contain the point # x (The- 

orem 4). The line joining Z 2 8 to 

l$l does not contain the pomt S" which replaces 8 y For, since /S 2 is 
on the line joining 8 Z 2 to ll v the points l a l z and 11^ are homologous 
points of the pencils [P 8 ] and [P] ; and if S'J were on the line join- 
ing l a l z to UC, the point l a l z would also be homologous to tt('. We 
may then proceed as before. By repeated application of this process 
we can reduce the number of perspectivities one by one, until finally 
we obtain the pencil of points [Q] and the perspectivities 

8 S' 



As a consequence we have the important theorem : 

THEOREM 6. Any two protective pencils of points on skew lines are 
axially perspective (A, E) 

Proof, The axis of the perspectivity is the line 88' of the last 
theorem. 

24. General theory of correspondence. Symbolic treatment. In 
preparation for a more detailed study of protective (and other) corre- 
spondences, we will now develop certain general ideas applicable to 



24] CORRESPONDENCE 65 

all one-to-one reciprocal correspondences as defined in Chap. II, 13, 
p. 35, and show in particular how these ideas may be conveniently 
represented in symbolic form * As previously indicated (p. 58), we 
will represent such correspondences in general by the letters of the 
Greek alphabet, as A, B, F, . The totality of elements affected 
by the correspondences under consideration forms a system which we 
may denote by S. If, as a result of replacing every element of a system 
Sj by the element homologous to it in a correspondence A, the sys- 
tem S x is transformed into a system S 2 , we express this by the relation 
A(S 1 ) = S 2 In particular, the element homologous with a given ele- 
ment P is represented by A (P). 

I. If two correspondences A, B are applied successively to a sys- 
tem Sj, so that we have A(Sj)= S 2 and B(S 2 ) = S 3 , the single corre- 
spondence r which transforms S t into S s is called the resultant or 
product of A by B; in symbols S 8 = B (S 2 ) = B (A(S 1 )) ** BA (S^, or, 
more briefly, BA = T Similarly, for a succession of more than two 
correspondences. 

II Two successions of correspondences A m A m-1 Aj and 
"BqBq-i ' Bj_ have the same resultant, or their products are equal, 
provided they transform S into the same S'; in symbols, from the 
relation 



foUows A.A..! A 1 -B.B a _ 1 ...B 



1 . 



III. The correspondence which makes every element of the sys- 
tem correspond to itself is called the identical correspondence or simply 
the identity, and is denoted by the symbol 1. It is then readily seen 
that for any correspondence A we have the relations 



IV. If a correspondence A transforms a system S t into S 2 , the corre- 
spondence which transforms S 3 into Sj is called the inverse of A and is 
represented by A" 1 , i.e. if we have A (SJ = S 2 , then also A" 1 (S 2 ) = S r 
The inverse of the inverse of A is then clearly A, and we evidently 
have also the relations 



* In this section, we have followed to a considerable extent the treatment given 
by H. Wiener, ^enohte der K sachsischen Gesellschaft der Wisspnschaften, Leipzig, 
Vol. XLII (1890), pp. 249-252. ........ 



66 PRIMITIVE GEOMETEIG FORMS [CHAP, ill 

Conversely, if A, A' are two correspondences such that we have 
AA' = 1, then A' is the inverse of A. Evidently the identity is its 
own inverse. 

V. The product of three correspondences A, B, F always satisfies 
the relation (FB) A = F (BA) (the associative law). For from the 
relations A(S X )=S 2 , B(S a )=S 8 , F(S 8 )=S 4 follows at once BA(S 1 )=S S , 
whence F(BA) (SJ =S 4 ; and also FB(S 2 ) = S 4 , and hence (FB) A (SJ 
= S 4 , which proves the relation in question. More generally, in any 
product of correspondences any set of successive correspondences may 
be inclosed in parentheses (provided their order be left unchanged), 
or any pair of parentheses may be removed; in other words, in a 
product of correspondences any set of successive correspondences may 
be replaced by their resultant, or any correspondence may be replaced 
by a succession of which the given correspondence is the resultant. 

VI. In particular, we may conclude from the above that the inverse 
of the product M BA is A~ 1 B~ 1 M"" 1 , since we evidently have 
the relation M BAA^B' 1 . M" 1 **! (of. IV). 

VII. Further, it is easy to show that from two relations A = B and 
F = A follows AF = BA and FA = AB. In particular, the relation 
A = B may also be written AB- X = 1, B^A = 1, BA- 1 = 1, or A^B = 1. 

VIII. Two correspondences A and B are said to be commutative 
if they satisfy the relation BA = AB. 

IX. If a correspondence A is repeated n times, the resultant is writ- 
ten AAA = A". A correspondence A is said to be of period n, if n 
is the smallest positive integer for which the relation A n = 1 is satisfied. 
When no such integer exists, the correspondence has no period ; when 
it does exist, the correspondence is said to be periodic or cyclic. 

X. The case n = 2 is of particular importance. A correspondence 
of period two is called involutoric or reflexive. 

25. The notion of a group. At this point it seems desirable to 
introduce the notion of a group of correspondences, which is funda- 
mental in any system of geometry. We will give the general abstract 
definition of a group as follows : * 

DEFINITION. A class G of elements, which we denote by a, I, 
c, ., is said to form a group with respect to an operation or law of 

* We have used here substantially the definition of a group given by L. E. Dickson, 
Definitions of a Group and a field by Independent Postulates, Transactions of the 
American Mathematical Society, Vol. VI (1005), p. 109. 



25,26] GROUPS 67 

combination o, acting on pairs of elements of G, provided the fol- 
lowing postulates are satisfied : 

G 1. for every pair of (equal or distinct} elements a, b of G, the 
result a o t of acting with the operation o on the pair in the order 
given * is a uniquely determined element of G. 

G 2. The relation (aob)oc = ao(boc) holds for any three (equal or 
distinct} elements a, o, c of G. 

G 3 There occurs in G an element i, such that the relation aoi = a 
holds for every element a of G 

G4. For every element a in G there exists an element a' satisfying 
the relation aoa'= i. 

From the above set of postulates follow, as theorems, the following 

The relations aoa'=i and a o i = a imply respectively the relations 
a'oa = i and ioa = a 

An element i of G is called an identity element, and an element a 1 
satisfying the relation a o a' = i is called an inverse element of a. 

There is only one identity element in G. 

For every element a of G there is only one inverse. 

We omit the proofs of these theorems. 

DEFINITION A group which satisfies further the following postulate 
is said to be commutative (or alelian} : 

G 5. The relation aoo = 'boa is satisfied for every pair of ele- 
ments a, & in G. 

26. Groups of correspondences. Invariant elements and figures. 
The developments of the last two sections lead now immediately 
to the theorem: 

A set of correspondences forms a group provided the set contains 
the inverse of any correspondence in the set and provided the resultant 
of any two correspondences is in the set 

Here the law of combination o of the preceding section is simply 
the formation of the resultant of two successive correspondences 

DEFINITION. If a correspondence A transforms every element of a 
given figure F into an element of the same figure, the figure F is said 
to be invariant under A, or to be left invariant by A In particular, 

* I e a o & and 6 o a are not necessarily identical. The operation o simply defines 
a correspondence, whereby to every pair of elements o, b in G m a given order corre- 
sponds a unique element; this element is denoted by ao&. 



68 PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS [CHAP. Ill 

an element which is transformed into itself by A is said to be an 
invanant element of A, the latter is also sometimes called a double 
element or a, fixed element (point, line, plane, etc). 

We now call attention to the following general principle : 
TJie set of all correspondences in a group G which leave a given 
figure invariant forms a group 

This follows at once from the fact that if each of two corre- 
spondences of G leaves the figure invariant, their product and their 
inverses will likewise leave it invariant , and these are all in G, since, 
by hypothesis, G is a group. It may happen, of course, that a group 
denned in this way consists of the identity only 

These notions are illustrated in the following section : 
27. Group properties of projectivities. From the definition of a pro- 
jectivity between one-dimensional forms follows at once 

THEOEEM 7 The inverse of any projectivity and the resultant of 
any two projectimhes are projectivities. 

On the other hand, we notice that the resultant of two perspec- 
tivities is not, in general, a perspectivity ; if, however, two perspec- 
tivities connect three concurrent lines, as m Theorem 3, their resultant 
is a perspectivity. A perspectivity is its own inverse, and is therefore 
reflexive. As an example of the general principle of 26, we have 
the important result : 

THEOREM 8. The set of all projectivities leaving a given pencil of 
points invariant form a group. 

If the number of points in such a pencil is unlimited, this group con- 
tains an unlimited number of projectivities. It is called the general 
protective group on the line Likewise, the set of all projectivities on a 
line leaving the figure formed by three distinct points invariant forms a 
subgroup of the general group on the line. If we assume that each per- 
mutation (cf. Theorem 1') of the three points gives rise to only a single 
projectivity (the proof of which requires an additional assumption), 
this subgroup consists of six projectivities (including, of course, the 
identity). Again, the set of all projectivities on a line leaving each of two 
given distinct points invariant forms a subgroup of the general group. 

We will close this section with two examples illustrative of the 
principles now under discussion, in which the projectivities in ques- 
tion are given by explicit constructions. 



27] GEOTJP OF PEOJECTIVITIES C9 

EXAMPLE 1. A group of projectivities leaving each of two given 
points invariant Let M, 2f be two distinct points on a line I, and 
let m, n be any two lines through M, N respectively and coplanar 
with I (fig. 27). On m let there be an arbitrary given point S. If S t 
is any other point on m and not on I or n, the points S, ^ together 
with, the line n define a projectivity TT I on I as follows : The point 
7r l (A) = A' homologous to any point A of Hs obtained by the two 

o a 

perspectivities [A] == [A^\ ~= [A 1 ], where [Aj] is the pencil of points 

on n Every point $, then, if not on I or n, defines a unique pro- 
jectivity TTJ we are to show that the set of all these projectivities ?r t 
forms a group. We show first that the product 
of any two TT I} ir z is a uniquely determined pro- 
jectivity 7r s of the set (fig. 27). 
In the figure, A 1 = ir^ (A) 
and A"= ir z (A'} have been 

s ^ 
n '""" 




constiucted. The point S 8 giving A" directly from A by a similar con- 
struction is then uniquely determined as the intersection of the lines 
A" Ay m. Let B be any other point of I distinct from M, N, and let 
B'= ir^JB) and B"~ ir t (jB') be constructed ; we must show that we have 
J?"=7r 8 (JJ). We recognize the quadrangular set Q(MS'A' t NA"") as 
defined by the quadrangle SS^A^ But of this quadrangular set all 
points except B" are also obtained from the quadrangle S^B^A^ 
whence the line 8^ determines the point B" (Theorem 3, Chap II) 
It is necessary further to show that the inverse of any projectivity in 
the set is ia the set Tor this purpose we need simply determine 2 
as the intersection of the line AA S with m and repeat the former argu- 
ment. This is left as an exercise Finally, the identity is in the set, 
since it is TT V when S^S. 



70 



PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FORMS 



[CHAP. Ill 



It is to be noted that in this example the points Jf and N are 
double points of each projectivity in the group; and also that if P, P' 
and Q, Q' are any two pairs of homologous points of a projectivity 
we have Q(MPQ, NQ'P'). Moreover, it is clear that any projectivity 
of the group is uniquely determined by a pair of homologous elements, 
and that there exists a pro]ectivity which 
will transform any point A of I into any 
other point B of I, provided only that 
A and B are distinct from 
Jf and N By virtue of 
the latter property the & 




group is 

to be transitive. 



EXAMPLE 2. Commutative projectivities. Let M be a point of a 
line I, and let m, m' be any two lines through M distinct from I, but 
in the same plane with I (fig. 28.) Let S be a given point of m, and 

let a projectivity ^ be defined by another pomt S l of m which deter- 

o a 

mines the perspectivities [A] = [A^] == [A'], where [Aj] is the pencil 

of points on m'. Any two projectimties defined m, this way by points $ { 
are commutative Let 7r 2 be another such projectivity, and construct 
the points A'ir^A), A 1 ' ir z (A'}, and A[**7r z (A). The quadrangle 
SS^A^ gives Q(MAA' t MA"A[}\ and the quadrangular set determined 
on I by the quadrangle SS^A'^ has the first five points of the former 
m the same positions in the symbols. Hence we have ir^Af) = A", and 
therefore TT^ = Tr,pr v 

EXERCISES 

1. Show that the set of all projectivities v t of Example 2 above forms a 
group, which is then a commutative group. 

2. Show that the projeotivity ^ of Example 1 above is identical with the 
projectivity obtained by choosing any other two points of m as centers of 
perspectivity, provided only that the two projectivities have one homologous 



27,28] TWO-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES 71 

pair (distinct fiom M 01 JV") in common Investigate the general question as 
to how far the consti notion may be modified so as still to preserve the propo- 
sition that the projectivitaes aie determined by the double points M, N and 
one pair of homologous elements 

3 Discuss the same general question for the projectivities of Example 2. 

4. Apply the method of Example 2 to the piojectivities of Example. 1. 
Why does it fail to show that any two of the lattei aie commutative? State 
the space and plane duals of the two examples. 

5 ABCD is a tetrahedron and a, /3, y, 8 the faces not containing A,B,C,D 
respectively, and / is any line not meeting an edge. The planes (I A, IB, 1C, ID) 
are protective with the points (la, I ft, ly, IS). 

6 On each of the ten sides of a complete 5-point in a plane there are three 
diagonal points and two vertices. Write down the piojectivities among these 
ten sets of five points each 

28. Projective transformations of two-dimensional forms. 

DEFINITION. A protective transformation between the elements of 
two two-dimensional or two three-dimensional forms is any one-to- 
one reciprocal correspondence between the elements of the two forms, 
such that to every one-dimensional form of one there corresponds 
a protective one-dimensional form of the other. 

DEFINITION. A collineation is any (1, 1) correspondence between 
two two-dimensional or two three-dimensional forms in which to every 
element of one of the forms corresponds an element of the same kind 
in the other form, and in which to every one-dimensional form of one 
corresponds a one-dimensional form of the other. A. protective colhne- 
ation is one in which this correspondence is projective. Unless other- 
wise specified, the term collineation will, in the future, always denote 
a projective collineation.* 

In the present chapter we shall confine ourselves to the discus- 
sion of some of the fundamental properties of collineations In this 
section we discuss the collineations between two-dimensional forms, 
and shall take the plane (planar field) as typical ; the corresponding 
theorems for the other two-dimensional forms will then follow from 
duality. 

The simplest correspondence between the elements of two distinct 
planes TT, TT' is a perspective correspondence, whereby any two homol- 
ogous elements are on the same element of a bundle whose center 
is on neither of the planes TT, TT'. The simplest collineation in a plane, 

* In how far & collineation must be projective will appear later. 



72 PRIMITIVE GEOMETEIC FOBMS [CHAP m 

i.e. which transforms every element of a plane into an element of the 
same plane, is the following : 

DEFINITION. A perspective collineation, in a plane is a projective 
collineation leaving invariant every point on a given line o and every 
line on a given point 0. The line o and the point are called the 
axis and center respectively of the perspective collineation. If the 
center and axis are not united, the collineation is called a planar 
homology; if they are united, a, planar elation. 

A perspective collineation in a plane TT may be constructed as 
follows : Let any line o and any point of TT be chosen as axis and 
center respectively, and let TT X be any plane through o distinct from -TV. 
Let O v O z be any two points collinear with and in neither of the 
planes TT, 7r r The perspective collineation is then obtained by the 

two perspectivities [P] == [PJ == [P r ], where P is any point of TT and 

P v P' are points of ir^ and TT respectively. Every point of the line o 
and every line through the point clearly remain, fixed by the trans- 
formation, so that the conditions of the definition are satisfied, if 
only the transformation is projective. But it is readily seen that 
every pencil of points is transformed by this process into a perspec- 
tive pencil of points, the center of perspectivity being the point 0; 
and every pencil of lines is transformed into a perspective pencil, the 
axis of perspectivity being o. The above discussion applies whether 

or not the point is on the line Q, 

THEOREM 9. A perspective col~ 
lineation in a plane is uniquely 
defined if the center, axis, and any 
two homologous points (not on the 
anois or center) are given, with the 
single restriction that the homol- 
ogous points must be collinear 
with 0. (A,E) 

Proof. Let 0, o be the center and axis respectively (fig. 29). It is 
clear from the definition that any two homologous points must be 
collinear with 0, since every line through is invariant ; similarly 
(dually) any two homologous lines must be concurrent with o. Let 
A, A' be the given pair of homologous points collinear with 0. The 




28] TWO-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES 73 

point }S r homologous to any point B of the plane is then determined. 
We may assume B to be distinct from 0, A and not to be on o, 
B 1 is on the line OB, and if the line AB meets o in C, then, since G 
is invariant by definition, the line AB = A C is transformed into A' C. 
B' is then determined as the intersection of the lines OB and A'C. 
This applies unless B is on the line AA'; in this case we determine 
as above a pair of homologous points not on AA', and then use the 
two points thus determined to construct B'. This shows that there 
can be no more than one perspective collineation in the plane with 
the given elements 

To show that there is one we may proceed as follows : Let ^ be 
any plane through o distinct from TT, the plane of the perspectivity, 
and let 6> x be any point on neither of the planes TT, TT X If the line AO^ 
meets TT X in A v the line A'A\ meets 00 t in a point O z . The perspec- 
tive colbneation determined by the two centers of perspectivity O v O a 
and the plane TT X then has 0, o as center and axis respectively and A, A' 
as a pair of homologous points. 

COROLLARY 1. A perspective collineation in a plane transforms every 
one-dimensional form into a perspective one-dimensional form. (A, E) 

COROLLARY 2. A perspective collineation with center and aoois o 
transforms any triangle none of whose vertices or sides are on o or 
into a perspective triangle, the center of perspectivity of the triangles 
leing the center of the collineation and the axis of perspectivity being 
the axis of the collineation (A, E) 

COROLLARY 3. The only planar collineations (whether required to 
"be protective or not) which leave invariant the points of a line o and 
the lines through a point are homologies if is not on o, and 
elations if is on o. (A, E) 

Proof. This will be evident on observing that in the first paragraph 
of the proof of the theorem no use is made of the hypothesis that the 
collineation is projective. 

COROLLARY 4 If H is a perspective collineation such that H(0) = C>, 
H(0) = o } H(.4) =tA r , H(5) = B' where A, A', B, B 1 are collinear with 
a point JT of o, then we have Q(OAB, KB' A'}. (A, E) 

Proof. If is any point not on AA' and H() = C", the lines AC 
and A'C' meet in a point L of o, and BC and B'C 1 meet in a point M 
of o ; and the required quadrangle is CC'LM (of fig. 32, p. 77), 



74 



PRIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FOEMS 



[CHAP. Ill 



THEOREM 10. Any complete quadrangle of a plane can be trans- 
formed into any complete quadrangle of the same or a different plane 
by a projective colhneation which, if the quadrangles are in the same 
plane, is the resultant of a finite number of perspective collineatwns. 
(A,E) 

Proof. Let the quadrangles be in the same plane and let their ver- 
tices be A, B, 0, D and A', B', C', D' respectively. We show first that 
there exists a collineation leaving any three vertices, say A' } B', C', of 




Fro. 30 

the quadrangle A'B'C'D 1 invariant and transforming into the fourth, 
D', any other point Z> 8 not on a side of the triangle A'B'C'fig. 30). Let 
jD be the intersection of A'D &) B'D' and consider the homology with 
center A 1 and axis B'C' transforming 2) a into 35. Next consider the 
homology with center B' and axis C'A' transforming U into D', Both 
these homologies exist by Theorem 9. The resultant of these two 
homologies is a oollineation leaving fixed A', B', C' and transforming 
Z> 8 into D 1 . (It should be noticed that one or both of the homologies 
may be the identity.) 

Let O t be any point on the line containing A and A f and let <? t be 
any line not passing through A or A'. By Theorem 9 there exists a 



28,29] THBBE-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECT1VITIES 75 

perspective collmeation ir l transforming A to A' and having and o l 
as center and axis. Let B v C v J) : be points such that 



In like manner, let o z be any line through A' not containing B or 
B' and let 2 be any point on the line B^B*. Let 7r a be the perspec- 
tive collmeation with axis o 3 , center a , and transforming J^ to B'. 
Let ,= TT^) and a = TT,^) Here 



Now let O a be any point on the line C Z C' and let ir a be the per- 
spective collmeation which has A'B'o a for axis, O a for center, and 
transforms C t to C". The existence of 7r a follows from Theorem. 9 as 
soon as we observe that C' is not on the line A'B', by hypothesis, 
and C a is not on A'JB'; because if so, C l would be on A'B^ and there- 
fore C would be on AB. Let 7r 3 (Z> a ) = Z> 8 . It follows that 



The point D a camiot be on a side of the triangle A'B'C' because 
then JD Z would be on a side of A'B'C Z> and hence JD^ on a side of 
A'B^CV and, finally, D on a side of ABC. Hence, by the first para- 
graph of this proof, there exists a projectivity 7r 4 such that 

= A'JB'C'JD'. 



The resultant Tr^TTg-Tr.^ of these four collmeations clearly transforms 
A, B, C, D into A 1 , B', C", D' respectively If the quadrangles are in 
different planes, we need only add a perspective transformation between 
the two planes. 

COROLLAEY There exist protective collinoations in a, plane which 
will effect any one of the possible @4> permutations of the vertices of 
a complete quadrangle in the plane. (A, E) 

29. Protective collmeations of three-dimensional forms. Protective 
collmeations in a three-dimensional form have been defined at the 
beginning of 28. 

DEFINITION. A protective collineation in space which leaves inva- 
riant every point of a plane CD and every plane on a point is called a 
perspective collineation. The plane e is called the plane ofperspectivity; 
the point is called the center. If is on w, the collineation is said 
to be an elation in space ; otherwise, a homology in space. 



Y6 PEIMITIVE G-EOMETEIO FOBMS [CHAP, in 

THEOREM 11. IfOis any point and o> any plane, there, exists one 
and only one perspective collineation in space having O, co jfor center 
and plane of perspe^mty respectively, which transforms cct^y point A 
(distinct from and not on to) into any other point A' (distinct from 
and not on o>) cottinear with AO. (A, E) 

Proof. "We show first that there cannot be more than, one per- 
spective coUineation satisfying the conditions of tlie theorem, by 
showing that the point B 1 homologous to any point JS is iiniquely 




Pro 31 



determined by the given conditions. We may assume IS not on a> 
and distinct from and A. Suppose first that B is not cm the lino 
AO (fig. 31). Since BO is an invariant line, J?' is on J3O; and if 
the line AB meets o> in L, the line A B AL is transfer JUG J into 
the line A f L. Hence B' is determined as the intersection of JiO 
and A'L. There remains the case where B is on A O aixd distinct 
from A and (fig 32). Let C, C' be any pair of homologous points 
not on AO, and let AC and BC meet to in L and M respectively. 
The line MB - MO is transformed into M C 1 , and the point l? r is then 
determined as the intersection of the lines BO and MC f . That this 
point is independent of the choice of the pair O t C 1 now follows 
from the fact that the quadrangle MLCC' gives the quadrangular 
set Q(KAA ( , OB'B), where JT is the point in which AO meets a> 
(Xmay coincide with without affecting the argument). The point 
B' is then uniquely determined by the five points O, JC, A, A' t B. 
The correspondence defined by the construction in the paragraph 
above has been proved to be one-to-one throughout. On tb.e line AO 
it is projective because of the perspectivities (fig. 32) 



29] THEEE-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES 77 



On OJB, any other line through 0, it is proactive because of the per- 
spectivities (fig. 31) . ,, 



That any pencil of points not through is transformed into a 
perspective pencil, the center of perspectivity being 0, is now easily 
seen and is left as an exercise for the reader Erom this it follows 




K 

PIG 32 

that any one-dimensional form is transformed into a protective form, 
so that the correspondence which has been constructed satisfies the 
definition of a projective collineation. 

TIIEOKEM 12. Any complete five-point in space can be transformed 
into any other complete five-point in space by a projective collineation 
which is the resultant of a finite number of perspective collineations. (A,E) 

Proof. Let the five-points be ABODE and A'B'C'D'E' respectively. 
We will show first that there exists a collineation leaving A'JB'C'D' 
invariant and transforming into E 1 any point J$ not coplanar with 
three of the points A'B'C'D'. Consider a homology having A'B'C' as 
plane of perspectivity and D f as center. Any such homology trans- 
forms E into a point on the line JE Q D' Similarly, a homology with 
plane A'B'D' and center C' transforms IS' into a point on the line E'C'. 
If H D' and E'0 ! intersect in a point JS V the resultant of two honiol- 
ogies of the kind described, of which the first transforms E Q into JS? t 
and the second transforms E^ into M' } leaves A'B'C'D 1 invariant and 
transforms J into E'. If the lines JS D' and E'C' are skew, there 
is a line through ' meeting the lines J^-D' and E'C' respectively 



78 PEIMITIVE GEOMETRIC FOEMS [CHAP, in 

in two points JS t and IS 2 . The resultant of tlie three homologies, of 
which the first has the plane A'B'C' and center D' and transforms 
JS to JB V of which the second has the plane A'C'D' and center B' 
and transforms J& t to E v and of which the tliird has the plane A'B'D 1 
and center C' and transforms E z to JS', is a collineation leaving A'B'C'D' 
invariant and transforming JS to E'. The remainder of the proof is 
now entirely analogous to the proof of Theorem 10. The details are 
left as an exercise. 

COROLLARY There exist protective collineations which will effect 
any one of the possible 120 permutations of the vertices of a complete 
Jive-point in space. (A, E) 

EXERCISES 

1 Prove the existence of perspective colhneations in a plane without 
making use of any points outside the plane 

2 Discuss the figure formed by two triangles which aio homologous 
undei an elation. How is this special form of the Desarguos configuration 
obtained as a section of a complete five-point in space? 

3 Given an elation in a plane with center and axis o and two homol- 
ogous pairs A , A' and B, B' on. any line through O, show that wo always 
have Q(OAA', OB'B). 

4 What permutations of the vertices of a complete quadrangle leave a 
given diagonal point invariant? every diagonal point? 

5. Wnte down the permutations of the six sides of a complete quadrangle 
brought about by all possible permutations of the vertices. 

6. The set of all homologies (elations) in a plane with the same center 
and axis form a group. 

7. Prove that two elations in a plane having a common axis and center 
are commutative. Will this method apply to prove that two homologies with 
common axis and center are comrmitalave ? 

8. Prove that two elationa in a piano having a common axis are commu- 
tative. Dualize. Prove the corresponding theorem in space. 

9. Prove that the resultant of two elations having a common axis is an 
elation. Dualize. Prove the corresponding theorem in space. What groups 
of elations are defined by these theorems? 

10. Discuss the effect of a perspective collineation of space on ; (1) a pencil 
of lines j (g) any plane; (8) any bundle of lines; (4) * tetrahedron} (5) a 
complete i-ve^oint in space. 

11. The set of all collineations in space (in a plane) form a group. 

12. The set of all protective collineations in space (in a plane) form a group, 
, 13 Show that under certain conditions the configuration of two p wp&otive 
tetrahedra is left invariant by 120 oollmeations (of, Ex. 8, p. 4(7), > 



CHAPTER IV 



HARMONIC CONSTRUCTIONS AND THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 
OF PROJECTIVE GEOMETRY 

30. The projectivity of quadrangular sets. We return now to a 
more detailed discussion of the notion of quadrangular sets introduced 
at the end of Chap. II. "We there defined a quadrangular set of points 
as the section by a transversal of the sides of a complete quadrangle ; 
the plane dual of this figure we call a quadrangular set of lines;* 
it consists of the projection of the vertices of a complete quadrilateral 
from a point which is in the plane of the quadrilateral, but not 011 
any of its sides ; the space dual of a quadrangular set of points we 
call a quadrangular set of planes ; it is the figure formed by the 
projection from a point of the 
figure of a quadrangular set 
of lines. We may now prove 
the following im- 
portant theorem : 

THEOREM 1. 
The section "by a 
transversal of a 
quadrangular 
set of lines is a 
quadrangular 
set of points. 
(A,E) 

Proof By Theorem 3', Chap. II, p. 49, and the dual of Note 2, on 
p 48, we may take the transversal I to be one of the sides of a com- 
plete quadrilateral the projection of whose vertices from a point P 
forms the set of hues in question (fig. 33). Let the remaining three 
sides of such a quadrilateral be a, 6, c. Let the points 5c, cat, and ab 

* It would be more natural at this stage to call such a set a quadrilateral set of 
lines ; the next theorem, however, justifies the term we have chosen, which has the 
advantage of uniformity. 

79 




80 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP. IV 

be denoted by A, J?, and C respectively. The sides of the quadrangle 
PABCmGQt I in the same points as the lines of the quadrangular set 
of lines. 

COROLLARY. A set of collinear points which is protective with a 
quadrangular sot is a quadrangular set (A, E) 

THEOREM 1'. The projection from a point of a quadrangular set of 
points is a quadrangular set of lines. (A, E) 

This is the plane dual of the preceding ; the space dual is : 

THEOREM 1". The section "by a plane of a quadrangular set of planes 
is a quadrangular set of lines. (A, E) 

COROLLARY. If a set of elements of a primitive one-dimensional form 
is projective with a quadrangular set, it is itself a quadrangular set. 
(A,E) 

31. Harmonic sets. DEFINITION. A quadrangular set Q (12 3, 124) 
is called a harmonic set and is denoted by H(12, 34). The elements 
3, 4 are called harmonic conjugates with respect to the elements 1, 2 ; 
and 3 (or 4) is called the harmomc conjugate of 4 (or 3) with respect 
to 1 and 2. 

From this definition we see that in a harmonic set of points 
\\(AC, JBJD), the points A and are diagonal points of a complete 




FIG. 84 FIG. 85 



quadrangle, while the points B and D are the intersections of the 
remaining two opposite sides of the quadrangle with the line AC 
(fig, 34). Likewise, in a harmonic set of lines H (ac, Id), the lines a 
and c are two diagonal lines of a complete quadrilateral, while the 



31] HARMONIC SETS 81 

lines 5 and d are the lines joining the remaining pair of opposite 
vertices of the quadrilateral to the point of intersection ac of the 
lines a, and G (fig. 35). A harmonic set of planes is the space dual 
of a harmonic set of points, and is therefore the projection from a 
point of a harmonic set of lines. 

In case the diagonal points of a complete quadrangle are collmear, any 
three points of a line foim a harmonic set and any point is its own harmonic 
conjugate with regaid to any two points collmear with it Theorems on hai- 
monic sets aie therefoie tuvial in those spaces for which Assumption Jf is 
not tine. We shall therefoie base oiu leasonmg, in this and the following 
two sections, on Assumption If 0) though most of the theorems are obviously 
true also in case H is false. This is why some of the theoiems aie labeled as 
dependent on Assumptions A and E, whereas the proofs given involve H also. 

The corollary of Theorem 3, Chap. II, when applied to harmonic 
sets yields the following: 

THEOREM 2 The harmonic conjugate of an element with respect to 
two other elements of a one-dimensional primitive form is a unique 
element of the form (A, E) 

Theorem 1 applied to the special case of harmonic sets gives 

THEOREM 3. Any section or projection of a harmonic set is a 
harmonic set. (A, E) 

COROLLARY. If a set of four elements of any one-dimensional prim- 
itive form is projective with a harmonic set, it is itself a harmonic set. 
(A,E) 

THEOREM 4. If 1 and 2 are harmonic conjugates with respect to 
3 and 4, 3 and 4 are harmonic conjugates with respect to 1 and 2. 
(A, E, H ) 

Proof. By Theorem 2, Chap III, there exists a projectivity 

1234^3412. 

But by hypothesis we have H(34, 12). Hence by the corollary of 
Theorem 3 we have H (12, 34). 

By virtue of this theorem the pairs 1, 2 and 3, 4 in the expression 
H (12, 34) play the same role and may be interchanged,* 

* The corresponding theorem for the more general expression Q (128, 456) 
cannot be derived without the use of an additional assumption (cf. Theorem 24, 
Chap. IV). 



82 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAF.IV 

THEOREM 5. Given two harmonic sets H (12, 34) and H (1'2', 3'4'), 
there exists a projectimty such that 1234 -^ 1'2'3'4'. (A, K) 

Bw/. Any projectivity 123^ 1'2'3' (Theorem 1, Chap. Ill) must 
transform 4 into 4' by virtue of Theorem 3, Cor., and the fact that 
the harmonic conjugate of 3 with respect to 1 and 2 is unique (Theo- 
rem 2). Tliis is the converse of Theorem 3, Cor. 

COROLLARY 1. If H (12, 34) and H (12', 3'4') arc two harmonic sets 
of different one-dimensional forms having the element 1 <iu common, 
we toe 1234 =12'3'4'. (A, E) 

For under the hypotheses of the corollary the pro] ectivity 1 2 3 -^ 1'2 '3' 
of the preceding proof may be replaced by the perspectivity 123 12'3'. 

COROLLARY 2 If H (12, 34) is a harmonic set, there exists a projec- 
tivity 1234 ^1243. (A, E) 

This follows directly from the last theorem and the evident fact 
that if H(12, 34) we have also H (12, 43). The converse of this 
corollary is likewise valid ; the proof, however, is given later in this 
chapter (cf. Theorem 27, Cor. 5) 

We see as a result of the last corollary and Theorem 2, Chap. ITI, 
that if we have H (12, 34), there exiRt projectivities which will trans- 
form 1234 into any one of the eight permutations 

1234, 1243, 2134, 2143, 3412, 3421, 4312, 4321.* 

In other words, if we have H (12, 34), wo have likewise H (12, 43), 
H(21, 34), H(21, 43), H(34, 12), H(34, 2]),H(43, 12), H (43, 21). 

THEOREM 6. The two sides of a complete quadrangrle wfiieh meet in 
a diagonal point are harmonic conjugates witJb respect to the two sides 
of the diagonal triangle which meet in this point. (A, E) 

Proof. The four sides of the complete quadrangle which do not 
pass through the diagonal point in question form a quadrilateral 
which defines the set of four lines mentioned as harmonic in tho 
way indicated (fig. 36). 

It is sometimes convenient to speak of a pair of elements of a 
form as harmonic with a pair of elements of a jEorm of different 
kind. For example, we may say that two points are harmonic with 
two lines in a plane with the points, if the points determine two 

* These transformations form the so-called eight-group* 



31] 



HARMONIC SETS 



83 




lines through the intersection of the given lines which are harmonic 
with the latter; or, what is the same thing, if the line joining the 
points meets the lines in two points 
harmonic with the given points 
With this understanding we may 
restate the last theorem as follows: 
The sides of a complete quadrangle 
which meet in a diagonal point are 
harmonic with the other two diago- 
nal points. In like manner, we may 
say that two points are harmonic 
with two planes, if the line joining 
the points meets the planes in a 
pair of points harmonic with the 
given points ; and a pair of hues is 
harmonic with a pair of planes, if p IG 30 

they intersect on the intersection 

of the two planes, and if they determine with this intersection two 
planes harmonic with the given planes 

EXERCISES 

1 Piove Theorem 4 dhectly fiom a figure without using Theorem 2, 
Chap. III. 

2. Prove Theorem 5, Coi. 2, directly fiom a nguie. 

3 Through a given point in a plane constiuct a line which passes through 
the point of intersection of two given lines in the plane, without making use 
of the lattei point. 

4. A line meets the sides of a triangle ABC in the points A v B I} C l} and 
the harmonic conjugates A z , B z , C z of these points with respect to the two 
vertices on the same side are deteimmed, so that we have W(AB, C^C^), 
H(pC,A l A t '),ainiaLH(CA,B 1 B t ). Show that A v B z , C a , B v C v A 9 \C lt A st B 9 
are collinear; that AA Z , BB Z , CC % are concurrent; and that AA S , BB V CC V 
AA l} BB Z , CC^ AA V BB V CC Z aie also concurrent. 

5. If each of two sides AB, BC of a triangle ABC meets a pair of opposite 
edges of a tetrahedron in two points which are harmonic conjugates with 
respect to A, B and B, C respectively, the third side CA will meet the third 
pair of opposite edges in two points which are harmonic conjugates with 
respect to C, A. 

6. A, B, C, D are the vertices of a quadrangle the sides of which meet a 
given transversal I in the six points P v P v P 8 , P 4 , P 5 , P 6 ; the harmonic conju- 
gate of each of these points with respect to the two corresponding vertices of the 



84 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP IV 

quadrangle is constructed and these six points are denoted by P{, Pg, Pg, P^, 
Pj, Pg respectively The thiee lines joining the pairs of the latter points 
which lie on opposite sides of the quadi angle meet m a point, P, which in the 
hanuomc conjugate of each of the points in which these thioe lines meet / 
with icspect to the pans of points P' defining the lines. 

7 Defining the polai line of a point with itjspoet to a pan of hues as the 
haimomc conjugate line of the point with i eg aid to the pan of lines, piove 
that the three polar lines of a point as to the pairs of lines of a tuangle foim 
a triangle (called the cogredient tiiangle) peispective to the given tuanglo 

8. Show that the polar line defined in Ex 7 is the same as the polai line 
denned m Ex. 3, p. 02. 

9. Show that any line through a point and meeting two intersecting 
lines I, I' meets the polai of with respect to I, I' in a point which is the 
liairnonic conjugate of with lespect to the points in which the line through 
meets Z, I' 

10 The axis of perspectivity of a triangle and its cogredient triangle is the 
polar line (cf . p 4G) of the triangle as to the given point. 

11 If two triangles arc peispective, the two polai lines of a point on then 
axis of perspectivity meet on the axis of perspectivity 

112 If the lines joining corresponding vertices of two n-hnes meet in a point, 
the points of intersection of coiiespondmg sides meet on a line. 

13 (Generalization of Exs 7, 10 ) The n polar lines of a point P as to the n 
(n l)-lmes of an n-hne in a plane form an n-hne (the cogredient n-line) 
whose sides meet the coriesponding sides of the given n-lme in the points of 
a line p. The line p is called the polar of P as to the n-line * 

14. (Geneialization of Ex. 11.) If two n-lines are perspective, the two 
polar linos of a point on their axis of perspectivity meet on this axis. 

15. Obtain the plane duals of the last two problems. Generalize them to 
three- and n-dimensional space. These theorems are fundamental for the con- 
struction of polars of algebuue curves and suifaces of the n-tlx degree. 

32. Nets of rationality on a line. DEFINITION A point P of a line 
is said to be harmonically related to three given distinct points A, ft, C 
of the line, provided P is one of a sequence of points A, S, 0, B v // 2 , JG",, 
of the line, finite in number, such that H^ is the harmonic conju- 
gate of one of the points A, J3, C with respect to the other two, and 
such that every other point H t is harmonic with three of the set A, B, 0, 
JF V JST 2 , . -, J^_ v The class of all points harmonically related to three 
distinct points A, J3, C on a line is called the one-dimensional net oj 
rationality defined by A> #, G\ it is denoted by R(JLBC) t A net oj 
rationality on a line is also called a linear net. 

* This is a definition by induction of the polar line of a point with respect to ax 
n-line. 



32] 3STETS OF RATIONALITY 85 

THEOREM 7. If A, B, 0, D and A', B', C', >' are respectively points 
of two lines such that ABCD-rA'B'C'D', and ifD is harmonically 
related to A, B, C, then D' is harmonically related to A' } B' } C'. (A, E) 

This follows directly from the fact that the projectivity of the theo- 
rem makes the set of points Hj which defines D as harmonically related 
to A, B, projective with a set of points J/J such that every harmonic set 
of points of the sequence A, B, C, H v H 2 , , D is homologous with a 
harmonic set of the sequence .4', B', C', H[, H' Z) -,!>' (Theorem 3, Cor ). 

COROLLARY. If a class of points on a line is protective with a net 
of rationality on a line, it is itself a net of rationality. 

THEOREM 8. If K, L, M are three distinct points of R (AB C), A, B, C 
are points of R (KLM ) (A, E) 

Proof. From the projectivity ABGK-^ BAKC follows, by Theorem?, 
that C is a point of R (ABK). Hence all points harmonically related 
to A, B, C are, by definition, harmonically related to A, B, K Since K 
is, by hypothesis, in the net R(ABC), the definition also requires that 
all points of R(ABK) shall be points of R(ABC). Hence the nets 
R(ABC) and R(ABK) are identical; and so R(ABC) = R(ABK) 
= R (AMK) = R (KLM). 

COROLLARY. A net of rationality on a line is determined by any 
distinct three of its points. 

THEOREM 9. If all lut one of the six (or five, or four) points of a 
quadrangular set are points of the same net of rationality R, this 
one point is also a point of R. (A, E) 

Proof. Let the sides of the quadrangle PQRS (fig 37) meet the 
line I as indicated in the points A, A^\ J5,jB 1? ' C, C v so that B 3= B^\ 
and suppose that the first five of these are points of a net of rationality 



We must prove that C^ is a point of R. Let the pair of lines US and 
PQ meet in B'. We then have 

8 



Since A is in R(BGB l ) > it follows from this projectivity, in view of 
Theorem 7, that C^ is in R (BA&) *= R. 

DEFINITION. A point P of a line is said to be guadrangularly 
related to three given distinct points A } B, C of the line, provided 



86 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP. IV 

P is one of a sequence of points A, , C, ff v /Z" a , J/ 8 , . . of the line, 
finite in number, such that 11^ is the harmonic conjugate of one o 
the points A, B, C with respect to the other two, and such that overy 
other point S t is one of a quadrangular set of which the other tivo 
belong to the set A, JB, C, H v // 2 , , #",_! 




PIG- 37 

COROLLARY The class of all points quadrangularly related to three 
distinct collinear points A, B, C is R (AJiC). (A, E) 

From the last corollaiy it is plain that R (ABC) consists of all points that 
can "be constructed from A , J3, C by means of points and linos alone ; that 
to say, all points whose existence can be infeired from Assumptions A, E, II,,, 
The existence or nonexistence of further points on the line ABC is unde- 
termined as yet. The analogous class of points in a plane is the system of nil 
points constructible, by means o points and lines, out of four points A , 72, ( ', /), 
no three of which are collinear. This class of points is studied by an indirect 
method in the next section. 

33. Nets of rationality in the plane, DEFINITION. A point is said 
to be rationally related to two noncollinear nets of rationality R u R B 
having a point in common, provided it is the intersection of two lines 
each of which joins a point of R t to a distinct point of R a . A line is 
said to be rationally related to R! and R 8 , provided ifc joins two points 
that are rationally related to them. The set of ajl points and lines 
rationally related to R v R fl is called the net &f rUonM$ fy a $law 
(or of two dimensions) determined by R v f^j, it is alii oSbUM the 
planar net denned by R w R a . 

Prom this definition it follows directly that all the points of R x 
and R a are points of the pknax net denned by R R, , 



33] NETS OF RATIONALITY 87 

THEOREM 10. Any line of the planar net R 2 defined ly R v R 2 meets 
R,andR z . (A, E) 

Proof We prove first thai il a line of the planar net R a meets R v 
it meets R 2 . Suppose a line I meets R x in Aj it then contains a second 
point P of Rl By definition, through P pass two lines, each of which 
joins a point of R 1 to a distinct point of R 2 . If li& one of these lines, 
the proposition is proved ; if these lines are distinct from /, let them 
meet Rj and R 2 respectively in the points B v B z and %, P z (fig 38). 
If is the common point of R 19 R 2 , we then have 

OA^P^OA^P,, 

where A 2 is the point in which I meets the line of R 2 Hence A 3 is a 
point of R 2 (Theorem 7). 

Now let I be any line of the net R 2 , and let P, Q be two points 
of the net and on I (del). If one of these points is a point of R x or 
R 2> the theorem is proved by the case just considered. If not, two 
lines, each joining a point of R 1 to a distinct point of R 2 , pass through 
P; let them meet R x in A v B v and R 2 in A v B z respectively (fig 38). 
Let the lines QA : and QB l meet R 2 in A[ and J? a ' respectively (first case). 




O At A, B' t B t P t 



Then if I meets the lines of R l and R 2 in J% and P% respectively, the 
quadrangle PQA^B^ gives rise to the quadrangular set Q(^ 2J B a , 
QB'zA'J) of which five points are points of R 2 ; hence P z is a point of R 2 
(Theorem 9). J? is then a point of R x by the first case of this proof. 

THEOREM 11. The intersection of any two lines of a planar net is 
a point of the planar net (A, E) 



gg 



THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 



[CHAP. IV 




B, 



Proof This follows directly from the definition and the last theo- 
rem, except when one of the lines passes through 0,the point common 
to the two linear nets R x , R 3 defining the planar net. In the latter 
case let the two lines of the planar net be l v l a and suppose l a passes 
through 0, while l^ meets R 1? R 2 in A v A z respectively (fig. 39). If the 
point of intersection P of y, were not a point of the planar net, l a 

would, by definition, 
contain a point Q of 
the planar net, dis- 
tinct from O and P. 
The lines QA l and 
QA Z would meet R 3 
and Rj in two points 
J5 2 and 7> x respec- 
tively. The point C s 
m which the line 
PB^ met the line of 

89 R a would then be the 

harmonic conjugate 
of JB 2 with respect to and A z (through the quadrangle JPQA^); 
<7 2 would therefore be a point of R a , and hence P would be a 
point of the planar net, being the intersection of the lines A^A Z 
and B^Cy 

THEOREM 12. The points of a planar net R 3 on a line of t7ie planar 
net form a linear net. (A, E) 

Proof. Let the planar net be defined by the linear nets R y R a and 
let I be any line of the planar net. Let P be any point of the planar 
net not on I or Rj or R 2 . The lines joining P to the points of R 2 on I 
meet R^ and R 2 by Theorems 10 and 11. Hence P is the center of 
a perspectivity which makes the points of R 2 ou I perspective with 
points of R x or R 2 . Hence the points of I belonging to the planar not 
form a linear net. (Theorem 7, Cor.) 

COBOLLAKY. The planar net R* defined "by two linear nets R p R 9 is 
identical with the planar net R 2 a defined "by two linear nets R 8 , R 4 , pro- 
vided R 8 , R 4 are linear nets in R x s . (A, E) 

For every point of R t a is a point of R a 8 by the above theorem, and 
every point of R a * is a point of R t a by Theorem 10. 



33,34] NETS OF BATIONALITY 89 

EXERCISE 

If A, B, C, D are the veitices of a complete quadrangle, there is one and 
only one planar net of rationality containing them ; and a point P boloiigw to 
this net if and only if P is one of a sequence of points ABCD1)^D Z , iinile 
in number, such that D i is the intei section of two sides of the original quad- 
rangle and such that eveiy othei point D f is the intersection of two lines join- 
ing pans of points of the set ABCDD^ 2? t -i- 

34. Nets of rationality in space. DEFINITION. A point is said to 
be rationally related to two planar nets R*, R 2 in different planes but 
having a linear net in common, provided it is the intersection of two 
lines each of which joins a point of R. 2 to a distinct point of R| 
A line is said to be rationally related to R 2 , R 2 2 , if it joins two, a plane 
if it joins three, points which are rationally related to them. The set 
of all points, lines, and planes rationally related to R 2 , R 2 2 is called the 
net of rationality in space (or of three dimensions] determined by 
R 2 , R 2 , it is also called the spatial net defined Tby R; 2 , R 2 2 

Theorems analogous to those derived for planar nets may now be 
derived for nets of rationality in space. We note first that every point 
of R 2 and of R a 2 is a point of the spatial net R 3 defined by R/, R 2 2 (the 
definition applies equally well to the points of the linear net common 
to R 2 , R, 2 ) ; and that no other points of the planes of these planar nets 
are points of R 3 . The proofs of the fundamental theorems of align- 
ment, etc., for spatial nets can, for the most part, be readily reduced 
to theorems concerning planar nets. We note first : 

LEMMA. Any line joining a point A of R 2 to a distinct point P of 
W meets R*. (A,E) 

Proof. By hypothesis, through P pass two lines, each of which 
joins a point of R 2 to a distinct point of R 2 . We may assume these 
lines distinct from the line PA V since otherwise the lemma is proved. 
Let the two lines through P meet Rf, R 2 3 in JB V B z and C v C z respec- 
tively (fig. 40). If A v v C l are not collinear, the planes PA^B^ and 
PA^CI meet R. 2 in the lines A l S l and A^C y respectively, which meet 
the linear net common to R 2 , R a 2 in two points S, T respectively 
(Theorems 11, 12). The same planes meet the plane of R 2 in the lines 
ASB 2 and TO Z respectively, which are lines of R 2 2 , since $ T are points 
of R|. These lines meet in a point A z of R a 2 (Theorem 11), which 
is evidently the point in which the line PA^ meets the plane of R 2 a . 
If A v B v C l are collinear, let A e be the intersection of PA V with the 



90 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 

plane of R 2 2 and 8 the intersection of A,B^ with the linear not 
common to R and R| Since A, is in R (7^), the 



implies thai, J a is in 



in 




THEOREM 13. Any tit. 
RfandR*. (A, E) 



o/ the spatial net R" 
A 



Rf, R.f 




FIG. 41 



Proof. By definition the given lipe I contains two points A and B 
of the net R* (fig, 41)', It A or JS? is on R.? or R a 8 , the theorem raducea 
to the lemma. If not, let J% he a point of R^, and A and J5 a the points 
in whioh, by the lemma, %A und $B meet R a a j 



NETS OF RATIONALITY 



91 



point of R 2 not in the plane P^AB, and let P^A and P^'B meet R 2 2 in A[ 
and J3' 2 . The lines A a B z and A'^Bl meet in a point of R 2 (Theorem 11), 
and this point is the point of intersection of / with the plane of R 2 a . 
The argument is now reduced to the case considered in the lemma. 

THEOREM 14. The points of a spatial net lying on a line of the 
spatial net form a linear net (A, E) 

Proof. Let I be the given line, R* and R 2 2 the planar nets defining 
the spatial net R', and L^ and L 2 the points in which (Theorem 13) 
I meets R x 2 and R| (L^ and L z may coincide). Let A i be any point of 
Rf not on I or on R 2 2 , and S the point in which A^ meets the linear 
net common to R 2 and R a 2 (fig. 42). If L : and L 2 are distinct, the lines 





FIG. 42 



FIG. 43 



SLj_ and SL Z meet R 2 and R 2 2 in linear nets (Theorem 12); and, by 
Theorem 13, a hue joining any point P of R 8 on I to A^ meets each 
of these linear nets. Hence all points of R 8 on I are in the planar 
net determined by these two linear nets. Moreover, by the definition 
of R 8 , all the points of the projection from A i of the linear net on SL a 
upon I are points of R 8 . Hence the points of R 8 on I are a linear net 
If Li L^ S, then, by definition, there is on I a point A of R 8 , and 
the line AA 1 meets R| in a point A z (fig. 43). The lines 8A^ and SA^ 
meet R and R a 2 in linear nets R t and R 2 by Theorem 12. If 3^ is 
any point of R t other than A v the line AB meets R 2 2 in a point J3 8 by 
Theorem 13. By Theorem 12 all points of I in the planar net deter- 
mined by Rj and R 2 form a linear net, and they obviously belong to R 8 . 
Moreover, any point of R 8 on I, when joined to A v meets R 2 2 by Theo- 
rem 13, and hence belongs to the planar net determined by Rj and R a . 
Hence, in this case also, the points of R 8 on I constitute a linear net. 



92 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP. IV 

THEOREM 15. The points and lines of a, spatial net R 3 which lie on 
a plane a of the net form a planar net. (A, E) 

Proof. By definition a contains three noncollmear points .4,1?, C of 
R* and the three lines AB, BC, CA meet the planar nets R and R a 2 , 
which determine R 8 , in points of two linear nets R, and R 2 , consisting 
entirely of points of R 8 . These linear nets, if distinct, determine a 
planar net R 2 in a, which, by Theorem 10, consists entirely of points 
and lines of R 8 . Moreover, any hue joining a point of R" in a to A 
or B or C must, by Theorem 13, meet R x and R a and hence be in R fl . 
Hence all points and lines of R 3 on a are points and lines of R a . Thw 
completes the proof except in case R x = R,, which case is left as an 
exercise. 

COROLLARY 1. A net of rationality in space is a space satisfying 
Assumptions A and E, */ "hne" le interpreted an "linear nd" and 
"plane" as "planar net" (A, E) 

Tor all assumptions A and E, except A3, are evidently satisfied; 
and A 3 is satisfied because there is a planar net of points through 
any three points of a spatial net R 3 , and any two linear nets of this 
planar net have a point in common. 

This corollary establishes at once all the theorems of alignment in 
a net of rationality in space, which are proved in Chap. I, as also the 
principle of duality. We conclude then, for example, that two planes 
of a spatial net meet in a line of the net, and that three planes of a 
spatial net meet in a point of the net (if they do not meet in a lino), 
etc. Moreover, we have at once the following corollary : 

COROLLARY 2. A spatial net is determined ly any two of its planar 

nets. (A, E) 

EXERCISES 

1, If A,S, C,D,E are the vertices of a complete Bpace fivci-point, thoro is 
one and only one net of rationality containing them all, A point P belongs to this 
net if and only if P is one of a sequence of points ARCDKJJi , finite in 
number, such that J x is the point of intersection of three faoun of the original 
five-point and every other pomt I t is the mlcmujction of three distinct pianos 
through triples of points of the set ABCDEI^ / t _j.. 

2 Show that a planar net is determined if three noncollinear points anl a 
line not passing through any of these points are given, 

3 Under what condition is a planar net determined by a linear net and two 
points not in this net? Show that two distinct planar nets in the same plane 
can have at most a linear net and one other pomt in common. 



34,36] THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 93 

4. Show that a set of points and lines which is piojective with a planar 
net is a planar net 

5 A line joining a point P of a planar net to any point not in the nut, but 
on a line of the net not containing P, has no other point than P in common 
with the net 

6. Two points and two lines 111 the same plane do not in geneial belong to 
the same planar net 

7 Discuss the determination of spatial nets by points and planes, similarly 
to Exs. 2, 3, and G. 

8 Any class of points piojective with a spatial net is itself a spatial net. 

9 If a perspective colhneation (homology 01 elation) in a plane with 
centei A and axis I leaves a net of rationality in the plane invariant, the 
net contains A and I 

10 Prove the conespondmg proposition for a net of rationality in space 
invariant under a perspective tiansfonnation. 

11 Show that two linear nets on skew lines always belong to some spatial 
net, in fact, that the uunibei of spatial nets containing two given hnea" 
nets on skew lines is the same as the numbei of linear nets through two given 
points, 

12. Three mutually skew lines and three distinct points on one of them 
determine one and only one .spatial net 111 which they lie. 

13 Give further examples of the determination of spatial nets by lines. 

35. The fundamental theorem of projectivity. It has been shown 
(Chap III) that any three distinct elements of a one-dimensional 
form may be made to correspond to any three distinct points of a 
line by a projective transformation. Likewise any four elements of 
a two-dimensional form, no three of which belong to the same one- 
dimensional form, may be made to correspond to the vertices of a 
complete planar quadrangle by a projective transformation ; and any 
five elements of a three-dimensional form, no four of which belong 
to the same two-dimensional form, may be made to correspond to 
the five vertices of a complete spatial five-point by a projective 
transformation. 

These transformations are of the utmost importance. Indeed, it is 
the principal object of projective geometry to discover those prop- 
erties of figures which remain invariant when the figures are sub- 
jected to projective transformations. The question now naturally 
arises, Is it possible to transform any four elements of a one- 
dimensional form into any four elements of another one-dimensional 
form? This question must be answered in the negative, since a har- 
monic set must always correspond to a harmonic set. The question 



94 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP. IV 

then arises whether or not a projective correspondence between one- 
dimensional forms is completely determined when three pairs of 
homologous elements are given. A partial answer to this funda- 
mental question is given in the next theorem 

LEMMA 1 If a projectivity leaves three distinct points of a, line fixed, 
it leaves fixed every point of the linear net defined ly these points, 

This follows at once from the fact that if three points are left 
invariant hy a projectivity, the harmonic conjugate of any one of 
these points with respect to the other two must also be left inva- 
riant by the projectivity (Theorems 2 and 3, Cor.). The projectivity 
in question must therefore leave invariant every point harmonically 
related to the three given points 

THEOREM 16. THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF FROJISCTIVITY FOR A 
NET OF RATIONALITY ON A LINE. If A, B, C, D are distinct points of 
a linear net of rationality, and A', B', 0' are any three distinct points 
of another or the same linear net, then for any projcstimtias giving 
AB CD - A'B'C'D' and AB CD -^ A'B'C'D[, we have D' = D[ (A, E) 

Proof. If IT, TJ-! are respectively the two pro jectivities of the theorem, 
the projectivity TTyrr" 1 leaves A'B'C' fixed and transforms D' into D[. 
Since D' is harmonically related to A', B', C' (Theorem 7), the theorem 
follows from the lemma. 

This theorem gives the answer to the question proposed m its 
relation to the transformation of the points of a linear net. The 
corresponding proposition for all the points of a line, i.e. the 'prop- 
osition obtained from the last theorem by replacing " linear net " by 
"line," cannot be proved without the use of one or more additional 
assumptions (cf. 50, Chap. VI). We have seen that it is equiva- 
lent to the proposition: If a projectivity leaves three points of a 
line invariant, it leaves every point of the line invariant. Later, by 
means of a discussion of order and continuity (terms as yet unde- 
fined), we shall prove this proposition. This discussion of order 
and continuity is, however, somewhat tedious and more difficult 
than the rest of our subject ; and, besides, the theorem in question 
is true in spaces,* where order and continuity do act txtefe It has 



* Different, of course, frpro ordinary space; "rational sipaoss" (ff/.p. 08 and 
the next footnote) are examples in which continuity does not exist; " finite spaces, 1 * 
of which examples are given in the introduction ( 2), are spaces in which neither 
order nor continuity xist, 



35] THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 95 

therefore seemed desirable to give some of the results of this 
theorem before giving its proof in terms of order and continuity. 
To this end we introduce here the following provisional assumption 
of projectivity, which will later be proved a consequence of the order 
and continuity assumptions which will replace it This provisional 
assumption may take any one of several forms. We choose the fol- 
lowing as leading most directly to the desired theorem : 

AN ASSUMPTION OF PROJECTIVITY : 

P. If a projectivity leaves each of three distinct points of a line 
invariant, it leaves every point of the line invariant * 

We should note first that the plane and space duals of this assump- 
tion are immediate consequences of the assumption. The principle of 
duality, therefore, is still valid after our set of assumptions has been 
enlarged by the addition of Assumption P. 

We now have 

TIIEOEEM 17. THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM OF PROJECTIVE GEOM- 
ETRY, f Ifl, 2, 3,4 are any four elements of a one-dimensional primitive 
form, and 1', 2', 3' are any three elements of another or the same one- 
dimensional primitive form, then for any projectivities giving 1234~j^ 
1>>3'4' and 1234 ^ l'%'3'4[, we h a 4' = 4[ (A, E, P) 

Proof, The proof is the same under the principle of duality as that 
of Theorem 16, Assumption P replacing the previous lemma 

This theorem may also be stated as follows : 

A projectivity "between one-dimensional primitive forms is uniquely 
determined when three pairs of homologous elements are given, (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY. If two pencils of points on different lines are projective 
and have a self-corresponding point, they are perspective. (A, E, P) 

* We have seen in the lemma of the preceding theorem that the projectivity 
described in this assumption leaves invariant every point of the net of rationality 
defined by the three given points. The assumption simply states that if all the points 
of a linear net remain invariant under a projective transformation, then all the points 
of the line containing this net must also remain invariant. It will be shown later 
that in the ordinary geometry the points of a linear net of rationality on a line coi re- 
spond to the points of the line whose coSrdmates, when represented analytically, are 
rational numbers. This consideration should make the last assumption almost, if 
not quite, as intmtionally acceptable as the previous Assumptions A and E. 

t On this theorem and related questions there is an extensive literature to which 
references can be found in the EncyklopaMie articles on Projective Geometry and 
Foundations of Geometry. It is associated with the names of von Staudt, Klein, 
Zeuthen, Luroth, Darbous, P. Schur, Pieri, Wiener, Hilbert. Of. also 50, Chap. VI. 



96 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP iv 

Proof. For if is the self-corresponding point, and AA' and BB' 
are any two pairs of homologous points distinct from 0, the perspec- 
tivity whose center is the intersection of the lines AA', BB' is a 
projectivity between the two lines which has the three pairs of 
homologous points 00, A A', BB', which must be the projectivity of 
the corollary by virtue of the last theorem. 

The corresponding theorems for two- and three-dimensional forms 
are now readily derived. We note first, as a lemma, the propositions 
in a plane and in space corresponding to Assumption P. 

LEMMA 2. A protective transformation which leaves invariant each 

j; * j- f our j. j> a plane three . 7 . 7 , , 7 

of a set of points of no , of which belong to the same 

J J jive * J space four J J 

line 7 . . , . , _, the plane . , ,-, T ,. 

, leaves invariant every point of * (A, E. P) 

plane a * J space. \ > > / 

Proof. If A, B, C, D are four points of a plane no three of which 
are collinear, a proactive transformation leaving each of them inva- 
riant must also leave the intersection of the lines AB, CD invariant. 
By Assumption P it then leaves every point of each of the lines AH, 
CD invariant. Any line of the plane which meets the lines AB and 
CD in two distinct points is therefore invariant, as well as the inter- 
section of any two such lines. But any point of the plane may be 
determined as the intersection of two such lines. The proof for the 
case of a projective transformation leaving invariant five points no 
four of which are in the same plane is entirely similar. The existence 
of perspective collineations shows that the condition that no three 
(four) of the points shall be on the same line (plane) is essential, 

THEOREM 18. A projective collineation* "between two planes (or 
within a single plane) is uniquely determined when four pairs of 
homologous points are given, provided no three of either set of four 
points are collinear. (A, E, P) 

Proof. Suppose there were two collineations TT, 7r t having the given 
pairs of homologous points. The collineation ir^" 1 is then, by the 
lemma, the identical collineation in one of the planes. This gives at 
once TTjSs TT, contrary to the hypothesis. 

* We confine the statement to the case of the oollineation for the s&ke of sim- 
plicity of enunciation. Projeotive transformations which are not ColUmeations will 
he discussed in detail later, at which time attention will he called explicitly to the 
fundamental theorem, 



35] THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 97 

By precisely similar reasoning we liave : 

THEOEEM 19 A projectile colhneation in space is uniquely deter- 
mined when five pairs of homologous points are given, provided no 
four of either set of five points are in the same plane. (A, E, P) 

The fundamental theorem deserves its name not only because so 
large a part of protective geometry is logically connected with it, but 
also because it is used explicitly in so many arguments. It is indeed 
possible to announce a general course of procedure that appears in 
the solution of most "linear" problems, i.e problems which depend on 
constructions involving points, lines, and planes only. If it is desired 
to prove that certain three lines l v 1 2 , l a pass through a point, find two 
other lines m v m z such that the four points m^, m t l 2 , m 1 Z 8 , m 1 m z may 
be shown to be protective with the four points m a l v m z l z) m z l s , m z m v 
respectively. Then, since m this pro^ectivity the point m 1 m 2 is self- 
corresponding, the three lines l v l z) 1 8 joining corresponding points 
are concurrent (Theorem 17, Cor.) The dual of this method appears 
when three points are to be shown colhnear. This method may be 
called the principle of projectivity, and takes its place beside the 
principle of duality as one of the most powerful instruments of pro- 
jective geometry. The theorems of the next section may be regarded 
as illustrations of this principle. They are all propositions from which 
the principle of projectivity could be derived, i.e. they are propositions 
which might be chosen to replace Assumption P. 

We have already said that ordinary real (or complex) space is a 
space in which Assumption P is valid. Any such space we call a 
properly protective space. It will appear in Chap. YI that there 
exist spaces in which this assumption is not valid. Such a space, 
i.e. a space satisfying Assumptions A and E but not P, we will call 
an improperly protective space 

From Theorem 15, Cor. 1 and Lemma 1, we then have 

THEOREM 20. A net of rationality in space is a properly protective 
space (A, E) 

It should here be noted that if we added to our list of Assump- 
tions A and E another assumption of closure, to the effect that all 
points of space belong to the same net of rationality, we should 
obtain a space in which all our previous theorems are valid, in- 
cluding the fundamental theorem (without using Assumption P). 



98 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP. IV 

Such a space may be called a rational space. In general, it is clear 
that any complete five-point in any properly or improperly projective 
space determines a subspace which is rational and therefore properly 
projective. 

36. The configuration of Pappus. Mutually inscribed and circum- 
scribed triangles. 

THEOREM 21. If -A, B, are any three distinct points of a line I, 
and A', B', C' any three distinct points of another line I 1 maetinff I, 
the three points of intersection of the pairs of hnes AB' and A'li, ISC' 
and B'C, CA' and C'A 
are collinear (A, E, P) 




Proof. Let the three points of intersection referred to in the theorem 
be denoted by C", A", B" respectively (fig. 44). Let the line Ji"C" 
meet the line B' C in a point Z> (to be proved identical with A"); 
also let B"C" meet I 1 in A v the line A'B meet A C 1 in JB V the line AB' 
meet A'C in B[. We then have the following perspectivities : 

A'CP'^JB = A'B[B"C = A"B"D. 

By the principle of projectivity then, since in the projectivity thus 
established C" is self-corresponding, we conclude that the three lines 
A^A 1 , "B V JOB meet in the point C', Hence D is identical with A", 
and A", B", C" are collinear 

It should be noted that the figure of the last theorem 'is a con- 
figuration of the symbol 

9 8 
3 9 



36] COJSTFIGUKATION OF PAPPUS , * 99 

It is known as the configuration of Pappus.* It should also be notetlv I Q; 
that this configuration may be considered as a simple plane hexagon 
(six-point) inscribed in two intersecting lines. If the sides of such a 
hexagon be denoted in order by 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6, and if we call the sides 
1 and 4 opposite, likewise the sides 2 and 5, and the sides 3 and 6 (of. 
Chap. II, 14), the last theorem may be stated in the following form . 
COROLLARY. If a simple hexagon be inscribed in two intersecting lines, 
the three pairs of opposite sides will intersect in collinear points.^ 

Finally, we may note that the nine points of the configuration of 
Pappus may be arranged in sets of three, the sets forming three 
triangles, 1, 2, 3, such 
that 2 is inscribed in 
1, 3 in 2, and 1 in 3. 
This observation leads 
to another theorem con- 
nected with the Pappus 
configuration. 

THEOREM 22. // 
A, t B z C z "be a triangle 
inscribed in a triangle 
A^BjCv there exists a 

certain set of triangles each of which is inscribed in the former and 
circumscribed about the latter. (A, E, P) 

Proof. Let [a] be the pencil of lines with center A^ [5] the pencil 
with center 2^; and [c] the pencil with center C f 1 (fig. 45) Consider the 

3.A Z J3 Z C, 

perspectivities [a] === [&] === [c]. In the projectivity thus estab- 
lished between [a] and [c] the line A l C l is self-corresponding; the 
pencils of lines [a], [c] are therefore perspective (Theorem 17, Cor. 
(dual)). Moreover, the axis of this perspectivity is C Z A S ' for the lines 
AjC a and CjO z are clearly homologous, as also the lines A^A Z and C^A Z . 
Any three homologous lines of the perspective pencils [a], [b], [c] then 
form a triangle which is circumscribed about -4 1 J? 1 C' 1 and inscribed 
in A S S Z C Z . 

* Pappus, of Alexandria, hyed about 840 A.I>. A special case of this theorem may 
he proved without the use of the fundamental theorem (cf. Ex 3, p. 62). 

t In this form it is a special case of Pascal' s theorem on conic sections 
(cf. Theorem 8, Chftp, V). 




100 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP IV 

EXERCISES 

1. Given a triangle ABC and two distinct points A', B' t determine a point C" 
such that iheline$AA',BB', C6 v aie concimeiit, and also the lines AB',BC f , CA' 
aie concurrent, i e. such that the two tuanglcs aie perspective from two dif- 
feient points The two triangles aie then said to be doubly perspective 

2 If two triangles ABC and A'&C' aie doubly perspective in such a way 
that the vertices A, B, C are homologous with A', R', C' respectively in one 
peispectivity and with B', C', A' respectively in the other, they will also be per- 
spective fiom a thiid point m such away that./!, B, Care homologous respec- 
tively with C", A', J3'; i e. they will be triply perspective. 

3. Show that if A", B", C" aie the centers of perspectivity for the triangles 
in Ex. 2, the three triangles ABC, A'B'C', A"B"C" aie so related that any two 
are triply perspective, the centers of peispectivity being in each case the veitices 
of the remaining tiiangle. The nine veitices of the three triangles form the 
points of a configuration of Pappus. 

4. Dualize Ex. 3. 

37. Construction of projectivities on one-dimensional forms. 

THEOREM 23. A necessary and sufficient condition for tlie projectimty 
on a line MNAB -^ MNA< B' (M 1= N) is Q (JfAJB, NB'A'). (A, E, P) 




Proof. Let n be any line on N not passing through A (fig. 46). Let 1 
be any point not on n or on MA, and let A^ and JB l be the intersections 
respectively of O^A and O^B with n. Let O z be the intersection of A'A l 
andjB'5 r Then Q Q 

NAB =1 NA.B. = NA'J* 1 . 

A l * A 

By Theorem 17 the pro j activity so determined on the line AM is the 
same as MNAB 



The only possible double points of the projectivity are N" and the 
intersection of AN with O t 2 . Hence 0^ passes through M, and 
Q (MAB, NB'A') is determined by the quadrangle OjO^AjBy 



37] ONE-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES 101 

Conversely, if Q(MAB, NB'A') we have a quadrangle O^A^B V 
and lienoe ~ 



and by this construction Mia self-corresponding, so that 
MNAB-j^MNA'B'. 

If m the above construction we have M=N, we obtain a projeo- 
tivity with the single double point M N 

DEFINITION A projectivity on a one-dimensional primitive form 
with a single double element is called parabolic. If the double ele- 
ment is M, and AA', BB' are any two homologous pairs, the pro- 
jectivity is completely determined and is conveniently represented 
by MMAB-^MMA'B'. 

COROLLARY. A necessary and sufficient condition for a parabolic 
projectivity MMAB-^MMA'B' is Q(MAB, MB' A'). (A, E, P) 

THEOREM 24 If we have 

Q(ABC, A'B'C'}, 
we have also Q (A'B'C', ABC] 

Proof By the theorem above, 

Q(ABC, A'B'C') 

implies AA'BC^AA'C'B', 

which is the inverse of A'AB'G' -^ A' A OB, 

which, by the theorem above, implies 

Q (A'B'C 1 , ABC), 

The notation Q (ABO, A'B'C 1 ) implies that A, B, are the traces of a 
point triple of sides of the quadrangle determining the quadrangular set. 
The theorem just proved states the existence of another quadrangle 
for which A', B', C" are a point triple, and consequently A } B, C are a 
triangle triple. This theorem therefore establishes the existence of 
oppositely placed quadrangles, as stated in 19, p. 50 This result 
can also be propounded as follows 

THEOREM 25 If two quadrangles P^P^ and Q^Q Z Q Z Q^ are so related 
J^ to Q v PZ to Q z , etc that five of the sides P i P J (i,j 1^,3,4', 
i =/) meet the five sides of the second which are opposite to Q i Q J in points 
of a hne I, the remaining sides of the two quadrangles meet on I, (A,E,P) 



102 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP rv 

Proof. The sides of the first quadrangle meet /ma quadrangular 
set Q (P u P ia P w P 8i P 2l P 2 ,) , hence Q (P^PA P 1S PM. But, by hypoth- 
esis, five of the sides of the second quadrangle pass thiough these 
points as follows : Q$ z through P w $ x $ 3 through P M , Q t Q t through P 23 , 
Q s Qi through P^, $ 4 $ 2 through JJ 8 , Q a Q z through P^ As five of these 
conditions are satisfied, by Theorem. 3, Chap. II, they must all be 
satisfied. 

EXERCISES 

1. Given one double point of a projectivity on a line and two pairs of 
homologous points, constiuct the othei double point. 

2. If a, b, c are thiee nonconcuirent lines and A', B', C f are three collmear 
points, give a construction for a triangle "whose vertices A , B, C are lespectively 
on the given lines and whose sides SC } CA, AB pass respectively through the 
given points. What happens when the three lines a, 6, c are concurrent ? Dualize 

38. Involutions. DEFINITION. If a projectivity in a one-dimensional 
form is of period two, it is called an involution. Any pair of homol- 
ogous points of an involution is called a conjugate pair of the involution 
or a pair of conjugates. 

It is clear that if an involution transforms a point A into a point A', 
then it also transforms A' into A; this is expressed by the phrase that 
the points A, A 1 correspond to each other doubly. The effect of an invo- 
lution is then simply a pairing of the elements of a one-dimensional 
form such that each element of a pair corresponds to the other ele- 
ment of the pair. This justifies the expression "a conjugate pair" 
applied to an involution, 

THEOREM 26. If for a single point A of a line which is not a double 
point of a projectivity tr on the line we have the relations ir (A) A 1 
and i rr(A')=iA > the projectivity is an involution. (A, E, P) 

Proof. For suppose P is any other point on the line (not a double 
point of TT), and suppose 7r(P) = P'. There then exists a projectivity 

g ivin S AA'PP'-^A'AP'P 

(Theorem 2, Chap. III). By Theorem 17 this projectivity is TT, since 
it has the three pairs of homologous points A^ A'-, A', A, P, P'* But 
in this projectivity P' is transformed into P. Thus every pair of 
homologous points corresponds doubly. 

CORQLLAJRY. 'An involution is completely determined when two pairs 
of conjugate point* are gwen. (A, E, P) 



38,39] INVOLUTIONS 103 

THEOREM 27. A necessary and sufficient condition that three pair? 
of points A, A' ; B, B' ; C, C' "be conjugate pairs of an involution is 
Q(ABQ,A'B'C'). (A, E, P) 

Proof. By hypothesis we have 

AA'BC-^A'AB'O 1 . 
By Theorem 2, Chap. Ill, we also have 



which, with the first projectivity, gives 

AA'BC^ AA'C'B'. 

A necessary and sufficient condition that the latter projectivity hold 
is Q(ABC, A'B'C'} (Theorem 23). 

COROLLARY 1 If an involution lias double points, they are harmonic 
conjugates with respect to every pair of the involution. (A, E, P) 

For the hypothesis A^A',B = B' gives at once H (AB, CO') as the 
condition of the theorem. 

COROLLARY 2 An involution is completely determined when two 
doulle points are given, or when one doulle point and one pair of 
conjugates are given (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 3. If M,N are distinct double points of a projectivity 
on a line, and A, A'; B, B' are any two pairs of homologous elements, 
the pairs M, N; A, B 1 ; A', B are conjugate pairs of an involution* 
(A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 4. If an involution has one double element, it has another 
distinct from the first. (A, E, H fl , P) 

COROLLARY 5, The projectivity ABCD-^ABDC letween four dis- 
tinct points of a line implies the relation H (AB, CD}. (A, E, P) 

For the projectivity is an involution (Theorem 26) of which A, B 
are double points The result then follows from Cor 1. 
39. Axis and center of homology. 

THEOREM 28. If [A] and [B] THEOREM 28'. If [1] and [m] 
are any two protective pencils are any two protective pencils of 
of points in the same plane on lines in the same plane on distinct 

* This relation is sometimes expressed by saying, "The pairs of points are in 
involution." From what precedes it is clear that any two pairs of elements of a 
one-dimensional form are m involution, but in general three pairs are not. 



104 



THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM 



[CHAP IV 



distinct hnes l v Z 2 , there exists a 
line I such that if A v B^ and A z , J? 2 
are any two pairs of homologous 
points of the two pencils, the lines 
A 1 B n and A Z B^ intersect on L 
(A,E,P) 

DEFINITION The line I is called 
the axis of homology of the two 
pencils of points. 



points S v S z , there exists a point S 
such that if a v l^ and 2 , \ are 
any two pairs of homologous linos 
of the two pencils, the points aji^ 
and aj) 1 are collinear with S 
(A, E, P) 

DEFINITION The point S is 
called the center of homology of 
the pencils of lines. 



Proof. The two theorems being plane duals of each other, we may 
confine ourselves to the proof of the theorem on the left. From the 
projectivity [B] -^ [A] follows A^B^B^A] (fig 47). But in this pro- 
jjectivity the line A^ is self-corresponding, so that (Theorem 17, Cor ) 



A t 




the two pencils are perspective. Hence pairs of corresponding lines 
meet on a line I ; e.g. the lines A^B^ and J^A n meet on I as well as 
A^ and B^. To prove our theorem it remains only to show that 
B Z A^ and A Z B S also meet on I. But the latter follows at once from 
Theorem 21, since the figure before us is the configuration of Pappus. 
COROLLARY. If [A], [B] are not COROLLARY. If [1], [m] are not 
perspective, the axis of homology is perspective, the center of homology 



the line joining the points homol- 
ogous with the point IJ, Z regarded 
first as a point of l : and then as 
a point of l a . 



I 



is the point of intersection of the 
lines homologous with the line 8^ 
regarded first as a line of [I] and 
then as a line of [m]. 



For in the perspectivity AB]~B l [A] the line ^ corresponds to 
Bi(ll^)t and hence the point l^l z corresponds to M t in the projectivity 
[B] ~ [A] Similarly, ll z corresponds to l^ y 



39] CENTEK AND AXIS OF HOMOLOGY 105 

EXERCISES 

1 Tlieie is one and only one piojectivity of a one-dimensional form leaving 
invariant one and only one element 0, and tiansfoinung a given other element 
A to an clement B 

2. Two piojective langes on skew lines are always perspective 

3 Prove Cor 5, Theoiem 27, without using the notion of involution 

4. If MNAB-^MNA'B', then MNAA'-^MNBB' 

5 If P is any point of the axis of homology of two piojective ranges 
[A"]-r [.5], then the piojectivity P[A~\-r- P[B~\ is an involution. Dualize. 

6. Call the faces of one tetrahedron %, a 2 , a 8 , a 4 and the opposite veitices 
A^A^A^Ai respectively, and similarly the faces and vertices of another tetra- 
hedron fa, fa, fa, fa and B v B z , B a , B+ If A lt A z , A a> A 4 lie on fa, fa, fa, fa 
respectively, arid B\ lies on oj, JB 2 on 03, B 3 on a 3 , then B lies on o 4 Thus 
each of the two tetrahedra related in this fashion is both inscribed and cir- 
cumscribed to the other. 

7 Prove the theorem of Desargues (Chap II) by the pimciple of pro- 
jectivity. 

8 Given a tiiangle ABC and a point A', show how to construct two points 
B', C f such that the tuangles ABC and A'B'C' are peispective from four 
different centers. 

9. If two triangles A^B^C^ and A Z B Z C Z aie peispective, the three points 

(AiB v A Z BJ = C 3 , (A&, A 2 C,) = B 8 , (^C 2 , B Z CJ = A v 

if not collineai, form a triangle perspective with the first two, and the three 
centers of perspectivity aie collinear. 

* 10. (a) If TT is a piojectivity m a pencil of points [A] on a line with inva- 
riant points A lt AV and if \L"\, [M] are the pencils of points on two lines Z, m 
through A lt A s respectively, show by the methods of Chap. Ill that there exist 
three points S v S z , S a such that we have 

S-, 



where ir(A)-A'; that S v S^A a are collinear; and that S^S^Aj^ are collinear. 
(&) Using the fundamental theorem, show that there exists on the line S 1 A 3 
a point S such that we have 



(c) Show that (7;) could be used as an. assumption of projectivity instead of 
Assumption P ; i.e. P could be replaced by , If TT is a projectivity with fixed 
points A t > A z , giving TT (A) - A' in a pencil of points [A], and [L] is a pencil 
of points on a line I through A v there exist two points S v S z such that 



10 8 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP.IV 

.11. Show that Assumption P could be replaced by the corollary of 

Th nrShow that Assumption P could be replaced by the following. If we 
have a projectivity in a pencil of points defined by the perspective. 

and [M] is the pencil of points on the line S&, there exist on the base of [] 
two points S, S such that we have also 



40 Types of collineations in the plane. We have seen in the 
proof of Theorem 10, Chap III, that if 0,0,0, is any triangle, there 
exists a coUineation II leaving O v O z> and 0. invariant, and trans- 
forming any point not on a side of the triangle into any other such 





o 





]f 10. 48 

point. By Theorem 18 there is only one such collineation II. By the 
same theorem it is clear that II is fully determined by the projec- 
tivity it determines on two of the sides of the invariant triangle, say 
S B and 0^. Hence, if Hj is a homology with center O l and axis 
S 8 , which determines the same projectivity as II on the line O t O g , 
and if H a is a homology with center O a and axis 0^ which deter- 
mines the same projectivity as II on. the line 2 8 , then it is evident 

* U =? HH 



40] TYPES OF COLLINEATIONS 107 

It is also evident that no point not a vertex of the invariant triangle 
can be fixed unless II reduces to a homology or to the identity. Such 
a transformation II when it is not a homology is said to be of Type I, 
and is denoted by Diagram I (fig. 48) 

EXERCISE 

Piove that two homologies with the same center and axis aie commutative, 
and hence that two projectivities of Type I with the same invariant figuie aie 
commutative. 

Consider the figure of two points O v O a and two lines o v o s , such 
that O t and O z are on o v and o x and o 2 are on O r A collineation II 
which is the product of a homology H, leaving a and 2 invariant, 
and an elation E, leaving O l and o i invariant, evidently leaves this 
figure invariant and also leaves invariant no other point or line. If A 
and B are two points not on the lines of the invariant figure, and we 
require that TL(A)=B t 

this fixes the transformation (with two distinct double lines) among 
the lines at O v and the parabolic transformation among the lines at O s> 
and thus determines II completely. Cleaily if II is not to reduce to a 
homology or an elation, the line AB must not pass through t or O g . 
Such a transformation II, when it does not reduce to a homology or 
an elation or the identity, is said to be of Type II and is denoted by 
Diagram //(fig 48). 

EXERCISE 

Two protective collineations of Type 71, having the same invariant figure, 
are commutative. 

DEFINITION. The figure of a point and a line o on is called a 
lineal element Oo. 

A collineation having a lineal element as invariant figure must effect 
a parabolic transformation both on the points of the line and on the 
lines through the point Suppose Aa and Eb are any two lineal ele- 
ments whose points are not on o or collinear with 0, and whose lines 
are not on. or concurrent with a. Let E t be an elation with center 
and axis OA, which transforms the point (oa) to the point (06). Let E 2 
be an elation of center (AS, o) and axis o, which transforms A to B. 
Then II = E s E t has evidently no other invariant elements than and o 
and transforms Aa to J55. 



108 THE FUNDAMENTAL THEOREM [CHAP IV 

Suppose that another projectivity II' would transfer A a to />'& with 
Oo as only invariant elements The transformation II' would evidently 
have the same effect on the lines of and points of o as II. Hence 
n'H" 1 would be the identity or an elation. But as n'TI" 1 ^) = B it 
would be the identity. Hence II is the only pro]ectivity which trans- 
forms Aa to Bb with Oo as only invariant. 

A transformation having as invariant figure a lineal element and no 
other invariant point or line is said to be of Type III, and is denoted 
by Diagram /// (fig 48). 

A homology is said to be of Type /Fand is denoted by Diagram IV. 

An elation is said to be of Type V and is denoted by Diagram V. 

It will be shown later that any collineation can be regarded as be- 
longing to one of these five types. The results so far obtained may be 
summarized as follows : 

THEOREM 29 A protective collineation with given invariant fly nro F, 
if of Type I or II will transform any point P not on a, line of F into 
any other suoh point not on a, line joining P to a point of F; if of 
Type III will transform any lineal element Pp such that p in not on 
a point, or P on a line, of F into any other such dement Qg ; if of 
Type IV or V, will transform any point P into any other point on the 
line joining P to the center of the collineation. 

The i61e of Assumption P is well illustiated by this theorem. In case of 
each of the fust three types the existence of the required collineation wan proved 
by means of Assumptions A and E, togethei with the existence of a sufficient 
number of points to effect the construction. But its ttwV/www* was eHtabliwluul 
only by means of Assumption. P In case of Types IV and V, both existence 
and uniqueness follow from Assumptions A and E. 

EXERCISES 

1. State the dual of Theorem 20. 

2. If the number of points on a lino is p + 1, the number of collineations 
with a given invariant figure is as follows : 

Type/, 0>-2)Cp-8). 

Type/7, (p- 8) (/-!). 

Type J/J, j,(j-l). 

Type IV, p - 2. 

TypeF, ;>-!. 

In accordance with the results of this exercise, when the number of points 
on a line is infinite it is said that there are oo 2 transformations of Type / or //; 
oo 8 of Type ///; and oo 1 of Types /Fand V. 



CHAPTER V* 

CONIC SECTIONS 



41. Definitions. Pascal's and Brianchon's theorems. 

DEFINITION The set of all points of intersection of homologous 
lines of two protective, nonperspective flat pencils which are on the 
same plane but not on the same point is called a point conic (fig. 49). 
The plane dual of a point conic is called a line conic (fig 50). The 
space dual of a point conic is called a cone of planes, the space dual 





FIG. 40 FIG, 60 

of a line conic is called a cone of lines. The point through which 
pass all the lines (or planes) of a cone of lines (or planes) is called 
the vertex of the cone. The point conic, line conic, cone of planes, 
and cone of lines are called one-dimensional forms of the second degree.-^ 

The following theorem is an immediate consequence of this defi- 
nition. 

TIIEOEEM 1. The section of a cone of lines ~by a plane not on the 
vertex of the cone is a point conic The section of a cone of planes ly 
a plane not on the vertex is a line conic. 

Now let A^ and B^ be the centers of two flat pencils defining a 
point conic. They are themselves, evidently, points of the conic, for the 
line A^ regarded as a line of the pencil on A corresponds to some 
other line through B l (since the pencils are, by hypothesis, projective 

* All the developments of this chapter are on the basis of Assumptions A, E, P, 
and HQ. 

t A fifth one-dimensional form a self-dual form of lines in space called the 
regulus will be defined in Chap. XI This definition of the first four one-dimen- 
sional forms of the second degree is due to Jacob Sterner (1796-1863). Attention 
will be called to other methods of definition in the sequel 

109 



110 



CONIC SECTIONS 



[CHAP. V 



but not perspective), and the intersection of these homologous lines 
is B v The conic is clearly determined by any other three of its 
pomts, say A v JB Z , C z , because the projectiviLy of the pencils is then 
determined by 

^W*M-*BJ4**M 

(Theorem 17, Chap. IV). 

Let us now see how to determine a sixth point of the conic on a 
line through one of the given points, say on a lino I through 7? . Jf the 
Ime I is met by the lines A^ A^C Z> ^A y J3 l C s in the points JS, T, U> A 




c, 



"*..." 



FIG. 51 



respectively (fig. 51), we have, by hypothesis, SB^U^A. The other 
double point of this projectivity, which we will call C v ia given by tho 
quadrangular set Q(B Z ST, C,AU} (Theorem 23, Chap. IV), A quad- 
rangle which determmes it may be obtained as follows : Let tho lines 
A Z B V and A,B Z meet in a point 0, and the lines AC and A C in a 
point*; then therequired quadrangle is^C^.and C, is determined 
as the intersection of A Z B with I w-wwmrnea 



Ci 






" U A ** 
?. 



This means 
* * be the 



z , B 9 , <7 ? , C, are points of a point 



41] PASCAL'S THEOREM 111 

determined "by two protective pencils on A and B v if and only if the 
threepoints C=(A i B & )(A s B 1 ),B = (A 1 C z )(A,C 1 ),A = (B 1 C s )(B 2 C 1 ) are 
collinear. The three points in question are clearly the intersections 
of pairs of opposite sides of the simple hexagon A^B^G^B^Cy 

Since A v B v C l may be interchanged with A z , B z , C z respectively 
in the above statement, it follows that A v B v C v C a are points of a 
conic determined by projective pencils on A z and J3 2 . Thus, if C 1 is 
any point of the first conic, it is also a point of the second conic, 
and vice versa. Hence we have established the following theorem : 

THEOREM 2. STEINER'S THEOREM. If A and B are any two given 
points of a conic, and P is a variable point of this come, we have 



In view of this theorem the six points in the discussion may be 
regarded as any six points of a conic, and hence we have 

THEOREM 3. PASCAL'S THEOREM.* The necessary and sufficient con- 
dition that six points, no three of which are collinear, be points of 
the same conic is that the three pairs of opposite sides of a simple 
hexagon of which they are vertices shall meet in collinear points f 

The plane dual of this theorem is 

THEOREM 3'. BRIANCHON'S THEOREM. FJie necessary and sufficient 
condition that six lines, no three of which are concurrent, be lines of 
a line conic is that the lines joining the three pairs of opposite vertices 
of any simple hexagon of which the given lines are sides, shall be 
concurrent.^ 

As corollaries of these theorems we have 

COROLLARY 1. A line in the plane of a point conic cannot have more 
than two points in common with the conic. 

COROLLARY 1'. A point in the plane of a line conic cannot be on 
more than two lines of the conic 

* Theorem 8 was proved by B Pascal m 1640 when only sixteen years of age 
He proved it first for the circle and then obtained it for any conic by projection 
and section This is one of the earliest applications of this method Theorem 3' 
was first given by C J. Bnanchon m 1806 (Journal de 1'Ecole Polytechmque, 
Vol VI, p 801), 

t The line thus determined by the intersections of the pairs of opposite sides of 
any simple hexagon whose vertices are points of a point conic is called the Pascal 
line of the hexagon The dual construction gives rise to the Brianchon point of a 
hexagon whose sides belong to a line come. 



112 CONIC SECTIONS [UIUP V 

Also as immediate corollaries of these theorems we have 
THEOREM 4 There is one and only one point conic, eantitimity five. 

given points of a plane no three of which are collinmr. 

THEOREM 4'. There is one and only one line conic containing Jive 

given lines of a plane no three of which are concurrent. 

EXERCISES 

1. What are the space duals of the above theorems? 

2. Prove Buanchon's theorem without making uao of tho principle of 

duality. . , .. . , . , 

3 A necessaiy and sufficient condition that six pomls, no lhnu of which 
are collmeai, be points of a point conic, is that thoy lo tho points of mk-i- 

section (a&')> (6c / ), (O ( fifl ')> W> (0 of tho &1(lcs rt > 6 ' c aml "' '''' '"' of iwo 
perspective tnangles, in which a and a', I and //, c ami tf aio homologous. 

42. Tangents. Points of contact. DEFINITION. A lino p in the 
plane of a point conic which meets the point conic iu ono and only 
one point P is called a tangent to the point conic! at P. A point 1> in 
the plane of a line conic through which pasnofl ono and only ono lino 
p of the line conic is called a point of contact of the lino conic on p. 

THEOREM 5 Through any point of a point conic there is one and 
only one tangent to the point conic 

Proof. If P Q is the given point of the point conic, and I{ is any 
other point of the point conic, while P is a variable point ot this 
conic, we have, by Theorem 2, 



Any line through P meets its homologous line of tho poiujil on I{ in 
a point distinct from P , except when its homologous lino in I{1^. 
Since a projectivity is a one-to-one correspondence, thero i,s only ono 
line on P which has P^ as its homologous lino, 

THEOREM 5'. On any line of a line conic there fa one and only OHG 
point of contact of the line conic. 

This is the plane dual of the preceding theorem. 

EXERCISE 

Give the space duals of the preceding doBniticraa anil theorems, 
Eeturning now to the construction in the preceding section for the 
points of a point conic containing five given points, we recall that 



42] TANGENTS 113 

the point of intersection (7 X of a line I through J? 2 was determined by 
the quadrangular set Q^ST, Q^AU}. The points J5 3 and C t can, 
by the preceding theorem, coincide on one and only one of the lines 
through B z * For this particular line I, A becomes the intersection 




o 
U 



FIG 52 

of the tangent at 7? 2 with BQ, and the collmearity of the points A, B, G 
may be stated as follows : 

THEOREM 6. If the vertices of a simple plane five-point are points 
of a point conic, the tangent to the point conic at one of the vertices 
meets the opposite side in a point collinear with the points of inter- 
section of the other two pairs of nonadjacent sides. 

This theorem, by its derivation, is a degenerate case of Pascal's 
theorem. It may also be regarded as a degenerate case in its state- 
ment, if the tangent be thought of as taking the place of one side 
of the simple hexagon. 

It should be clearly undei stood that the theoiem has been obtained by 
specializing the figure of Theorem 3, and not by a continuity argument 
The latter would be clearly impossible, since our assumptions do not require 
the conic to contain more than a finite number of points. 

Theorem 6 may be applied to the construction of a tangent to 
a point conic at any one of five given points JfJ, P^, P^ P^ Jj? of the 
point conic (fig. 53). By this theorem the tangent j a at J% must be 

* As explained in the fine print on page 110, this occurs when I passes through 
the point of intersection of SiCi with the line joining C = (AiB z ) (A z Bi) and 



114 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP.V 

such that the points Pl (P^ = 4 (-M -5) = *> *nd ^) (W) = 
are collmear. But ^ and C are determined by J?, P z> P 8) P it P 6 , and 
hence p 1 is the line joining P to the intersection of the lines *>" 
and 




FIG. 63 

In like manner, if P v P z , P 3 , P i3 and p l are given, to construct the 
point J on any line I through P of a point conic containing P v P Z) P a , P 
and of which p^ is the tangent at P v we need only determine the points 
A =j 1 (^), B = l(P l P a ), and C = (AB) (P a P B )-, then Jja meets I in J 
(fig 53). 




. 64 



In case I is the tangent y t at ^ } ^ coincides with P< and the fol- 
lowing points are collmear (fig. 54) : 



42] TANGENTS 115 

Hence we have the following theorem : 

THEOREM 7 If the vertices P v J\, P s , P 4 of a simple quadrangle are 
points of a point conic, the tangent at I( and the ftido /iJ/J, the, tanynit 
at PI and the side P : P Z , and the pair of sides 7J./J and 7j/j meet in three 
collinear points. 

If P i} P z , P & , P & and the tangent p l at P t are given, the construction 
determined by Theorem 6 for a point P of the point conic on a line I 
through P 8 is as follows (fig. 53): Determine = (P t P 6 ) (PP,), A **$ 
and B = (A C)(P^ ; then P & B meets I in P v 

In case I is the tangent at P s , P^ coincides with P & and we have the 
result that C = (P l P,)(P & P a ), A=p 1 p s> B = (P^(P,P^ are collinear 
points, which gives 




FIG. 65 

THEOREM 8. If the vertices of a complete quadrangle are points of 
a point conic, the tangents at a pair of vertices meet in a point of the 
line joining the diagonal points of the quadrangle which are not on 
the side joining the two vertices (fig 55). 

The last two theorems lead to the construction for a point conic 
of which there are given three points and the tangents at two of 
them. Eeverting to the notation of Theorem 7 (fig 54), let the given 
points be JF, JJ, P 8 and the given tangents be p# p r Let I be any line 
through P v If PH is the other point in which I meets the point conic, 
the points A = p l (P a P t ), =p^ (P l P i ), and C = (P Z P 8 ) (P^) are collinear. 
Hence, if C=l(P l P i ) and S=p i (AC) ) then P z is the intersection of I 
with Pi* 

In case I is the tangent p s at P z , the points P% and P B coincide, and 
the points 



CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP.V 

are collinear Hence the two triangles P.P.P, and p,p,p, are per- 
spective, and we obtain as a last specialization of Pascal's theorem 

( fi g- 56 )' . , f . , . 

THEOREM 9. A triangle whose vertices are points of a, point conic 

is perspective with the triangle formed ly the tangents at these points, 
the tangent at any vertex levng homologous with the side of the first 
triangle which does not contain this vertex. 

COROLLARY. If P v P s , P are three points of a point conic, the lines 
P&PV P a % are harmonic with the tangent at P s and the line Joining P 3 
to the intersection of the tangents at JJ and P 

Proof. This follows from the definition of a harmonic set of lines, 
on considering the Quadrilateral P^A, AB, BP V PJl (fig. 56). 




FIG. 56 



43. The tangents to a point conic form a line conic. If P v 7>, P 6 , I* 

are points of a point conic and p v p z , p s , p t are the tangenta to the 
conic at these points respectively, then (by Theorem 8) the lino join- 
ing the diagonal points (P : P Z ) (P S P^ and (P^ (/>/*) contains the inter- 
section of the tangents Pv p 9 and also the intersection of p a , p^ This 
line is a diagonal line not only of the quadrangle P^I^J^ but also of 
the quadrilateral PlPsPtPt . Theorem 8 may "therefore be stated in 
the form: 

THEOREM 10. The complete quadrangle formed ly four points of 
a point conic and the complete quadrilateral of the tangents at these 
points have the same diagonal triangle. 

Looked at from a slightly different point of view, Theorem 8 gives 
also 

THEOREM 11. The tangents to a point conic form a line conic. 



43] TANGENTS 117 

Proof. Let P if P 2) P 8 be any three fixed points on a conic, and let P 
be a variable point of this conic. Let p v p.,, p a , p bo respectively the 
tangents at these points (fig 57) By the corollary of Theorem 28, 
Chap. IV, P^ is the axis of homology of the projcctivity between the 
pencils of points on p i and p a denned by 

P l(PlP) (PiPt) 7- (PiPjWPiP*)' 

But by Theorem 10, if Q=(P i P 2 ) (P S P), the points pp z> p L p a , and Q are 
collmear. For the same reason the points p z p a , pp v Q are collmear. 
It follows, by Theorem 28, Chap. IV, that the homolog of the variable 




FIG. 67 



point p t p is p a p; ie. p is the line joining pairs of homologous points 
on the two lines p v p v so that the totality of the lines p satisfies the 
definition of a line conic. 

COROLLARY. The center of homology of the projectivity P^ [P] -^ P z [P] 
determined ly the points P of a point conic containing P v P z is the 
intersection of the tangents at P v P a . The axis of homology of the 
projectivity p l [p] -^p z [p] determined "by the lines p of a line conic 
containing the lines p v p z is the line joining the points of contact 

f Pv Pi- 

THEOREM 12. If P : is a fixed and P a variable point of a point 
conic, and p v p are the tangents at these two points respectively f then 



CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP. V 

Proof. Using the notation of the proof of Theorem 11 (fig D7), 

weliave 



where Q is always on P& But we also have 



and, by Theorem 11, 1?M T^ 

Combining these projectivities, we have 



The plane dual of Theorem 11 states that the points of contact, of 
a hne come form a, point come. In view of these two theorems and 
their space duals we now make the following 

DEFINITION. A eonic section or a conic is the figure formed by a 
point conic and its tangents. A cone is the figure formed by a cono 
of lines and its tangent planes. 

The figure formed by a line conic and its points of contact is then 
hkewise a conic as defined above ; i e a conic (and also a cone) is a 
self-dual figure. 

The duals of Pascal's theorem and its special cases now give \w a 
set of theorems of the same consequence for point conies as for line 
conies. We content ourselves with restating Brianchon's theyrem 
(Theorem 3') from this point of view. 

BRIANCHON'S THEOREM. If tlie sides of a simple hexagon are tan- 
gents to a conic, the lines joining opposite vertices are concurrent; 
and conversely 

It follows from the preceding discussion that in forming the plane 
duals of theorems concerning conies, the word conio is left unchanged, 
while the words point (of a conic) and tangent (of a conic) are inter- 
changed. We shall also, in the future, make use of the phrase a conic 
passes through a point P, and P is on the conic, when P is a point 
of a conic, etc. 

DEFINITION. If the points of a plane figure are on a conic, the figure 
is said to be inscribed in the conic; if the lines of a plane figure 
are tangent to a conic, the figure is said to be circumscribed about 
the conic. 



43] TANGENTS 119 

EXERCISES 

1 State the plane and space duals of the special caaoH of Pascal's theorem. 

2 Constiuct a conic, given (1) five tangents, (2) foni Undents ami tho 
point of contact of one of them, (3) three tangents and the points of contuoti 
of two of them. 

3 ABX is a triangle whose veitices ate on a conic, and , li t j; are the tnn- 
gents at A, B, X lespectively If A, B are given points and X is vanablo, 
deteimine the locus of (1) the centei of perspectivifcy of tho triangles ABX 
and d)i , (2) the axis of peispectivity. 

4 A", Y, Z are the vertices of a variable triangle, such that X, Y ai e always 
on two given lines a, I lespectively, -while the sides XY, ZX, ZY always pass 
through thiee given points P, A s B respectively Show that the loons of tho 
poi nt Z is a point conic containing A,B,D = (aJi) , M (A P) 1), and N = (BP) a 
(Maclaurin's theoiem). Dualize. (The plane dual of this theorem is known 
as the theorem of Braikenridge.) 

5. If a simple plane n-pomt varies in such a way that its sides always pass 
thiough n given points, while n 1 of its vertices aie always on n 1 given 
lines, the ?ith veitex describes a conic (Poncelet). 

6 If the vertices of two triangles are on a conic, the six sides of these two 
tiiangles are tangents of a second conic, and conveisely. Corresponding to 
every point of the fiist conic there exists a triangle having this point as a 
vertex, whose other two veitices aie also on the fiist conic and whose sides 
are tangents to the second conic Dualize. 

7. If two tiiangles in the same plane aie perspective, the points m which 
the sides of one triangle meet the nonhomologous sides of the other are on 
the same conic , and the lines joining the vertices of one triangle to the nou- 
homologous vertices of the other are tangents to another conic. 

8. If A, B, C, D be the vertices of a complete quadiangle, whose sides 
AB, AC, AD, BC, BD, CD are cut by a line in the points P, Q, R, S t T, V 
respectively, and if E t F, G, K, Z, M are respectively the harmonic conjugates 
of these points with respect to the pairs of vertices of the quadrangle so that 
we have H (AB, PE), H (A C, QF), etc., then the six points E, F, <7, K,L,M 
are on a come which also passes thiough the diagonal points of the quadrangle 
(Holgate, Annals of Mathematics, Ser. 1, Vol VII (1893), p. 73). 

9. If a plane a cut the six edges of a tetrahedron in six distinct points, 
and the harmonic conjugates of each of these points with respect to the two 
vertices of the tetrahedron that lie on the same edge are determined, then the 
lines joining the latter six points to any point of the plane a are on a cone, 
on which are also the lines through and meeting a pair of opposite edges of the 
tetrahedron (Holgate, Annals of Mathematics, Ser. 1, Vol. VII (1808), p. 73). 

10 Given four points of a conic and the tangent at one of them, construct 
the tangents at the other three points. Dualize. 

11. A, A', B, B' are the vertices of a quadrangle, and m, n are two lines 
in the plane of the quadrangle which meet on A A', M is a variable point 



120 



CONIC SECTIONS 



[CHAP 



on m, the lines BM, B'M meet n in the points JV, 2V' respectively; th e lines 
AN, A'N' meet in a point P. Show that the locus of the lines PM is a line 
come, which contains the lines m, p = P (n, BB"), and also the hues /I , 1 ' /;/,' 
.4'.B', -4.C (Amodeo, Lezioni di Geomelna Projettiva, Naples (1903), p. ;J3l), 

12. Use the lesult of Ex 11 to give a contraction of a line conic dek'i- 
nimed by five given lines, and show that by means of this construction it is 
possible to obtain two lines of the conic at the same time (Amodeo, loc cit } 

13. If a, b, c are the sides of a triangle whose vertices aie on a came and 
m, m' are two lines meeting on the conic which meet a, ft, c in the points A /> C 
and A' t J5', C' respectively, and which meet the conic again in JV, 2V' respec- 
tively, we have ABCN-^A'B'C'N' (cf Ex 6). 

14. If A, J5, C, D are points on a conic and a, ?>, c, d are the tail gents to 
the conic at these points, the four diagonals of the simple quadrangle A BCD 
and the simple quadrilateral abed aie concurrent 

44. The polar system of a conic. 

THEOREM 13. I/P is apoint in 
the plane of a come, Intt not on the 
conic, the points of intersection of 
the tangents to the conic at all the 



THEOREM 13'. Ifp is a line in the 
plane of a conic, Imt not tangent to 
the conic, the lines joining the points 
of contact of pairs of tangents to the 



pairs of points which are collmear conic which meet on p gag* tit. rough 

with Pare on a line, winch also con- a point P, through which pans (duo 

tains the liarmonic conjugates ofP the harmonic conjugates of p with 

with respect to these pairs of points, respect to these pairs of tangents. 




. 58 



7(ng.*>). 



44] POLAR SYSTEM 121 

respectively, the line D^ passes through the intersection Q of p v p z 
(Theorem 8). Moreover, the point P' in which DJ>^ meets 7J/JJ is the, 
harmonic conjugate of P with respect to 1{, K (Theorem 6, Chap. IV). 
This shows that the line 1)^= QP 1 is completely determined by the 
pair of points P v P z Hence the same line QP 1 is obtained liy replacing 
P 8 , PI by any other pair of points on the conic collinear with P, and 
distinct from P v P v This proves Theorem 13. Theorem 13' is the 
plane dual of Theorem 13. 

DEFINITION The line thus asso- DEFINITION. The point thus 

ciated with any point P in the associated with any line p in the 

plane of a conic, hut not on the plane of a conic, but not tangent 

conic, is called the polar of P to the conic, is called the pole of p 

with respect to the conic. If P with respect to the conic If p is 

is a point on the conic, the polar a tangent to the conic, the pole is 

is defined as the tangent at P. defined as the point of contact of JP. 

THEOREM 14. The line joining THEOEEM 14'. The point of 

two diagonal points of any com- intersection of two diagonal hnes 

plete quadrangle whose vertices of any complete quadrilateral 

are points of a conic is the polar whose sides are tangent to a conic 

of the other diagonal point with is the pole of the other diagonal 

respect to the conic line with respect to the conic. 

Proof. Theorem 14 follows immediately from the proof of Theo- 
rem 13. Theorem 14' is the plane dual of Theorem 14 

THEOREM 15. The polar of a THEOREM 15'. The pole of a 

point P with respect to a conic line p with respect to a conic is 

passes through the points of con- on the tangents to the conic at the 

tact of the tangents to the conic points in which p meets the conic, 

through P, if such tangents exist if such points exist. 

Proof. Let P^ be the point of contact of a tangent through P, and 
let P z , Pj be any pair of distinct points of the conic collinear with P. 
The line through P l and the intersection of the tangents at P >2 , Pj 
meets the line P 9 P S in the harmonic conjugate of P with respect to 
P 8 , % (Theorem 9, Cor.). But the line thus determined is the polar of P 
(Theorem 1 3) This proves Theorem 1 5 Theorem 1 5 ' is its plane dual 

THEOREM 16 If p is the polar of a point P with respect to a conic, 
P is the pole ofp with respect to the same conic. 



122 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP, v 

If p is not on the conic, this follows at once by comparing Theo- 
rem 13 with Theorem 13' If P is on the conic, it follows immediately 
from the definition. 

THEOREM 17. If Hi* polar of a point P passes iliromjli, a point Q 9 
the polar of Q passes through P. 

Proof If P or Q is on the conic, the theorem is equivalent to 
Theorem 15. If neither P nor Q is on the conic, let PP l be a line 

~ 




Fie. 59 

meeting the conic in two points, P^, P v If one of the lines J^Q, J\Q 
is a tangent to the come, the other is also a tangent (Theorem 13); 
the line J*j = P^P is then the polar of Q, which proves the theorem 
under this hypothesis. If, on the other hand, the lines P^Q, QQ meet 
the conic again in the points P s , P respectively (fig. 59), the point 
(P^) (P a PJ is on the polar of Q (Theorem 14). By Theorems 13 and 1 4 
the polar of (P^) (P S P) contains the intersection of the tangents at 
P v P} and the point Q. By hypothesis, however, and Theorem 13, the 
polar of P contains these points also. Hence we have (1J J3) (^J<) = P> 
which proves the theorem. 

COROLLARY 1. If two vertices of a triangle are the poles of their 
opposite sides vrith respect to a conic, the third vertex is the pole of 
its opposite side. 

DEFINITION. Any point on the polar of a point P is said to be 
conjugate to P with regard to the conic; and any 15ne pn the pole 



44] POLAR SYSTEM 123 

of a line p is said to be conjugate to p with regard to the conic. 
The figure obtained from a given figure in the plane of a conic by 
constructing the polar of every point and the pole of every line of 
the given figure with regard to the conic is called the polar or polar 
reciprocal of the given figure with regard to the conic.* A triangle, 
of which each vertex is the pole of the opposite side, is said to be 
self-polar or self-conjugate with regard to the come 

COROLLARY 2 The diagonal triangle of a complete quadrangle whose 
vertices are on a conic, or of a complete quadrilateral whose sides are 
tangent to a conic, is self-polar with regard to the conic; and, conversely, 
every self-polar triangle is the diagonal triangle of a complete quad- 
rangle whose points are on the conic, and of a complete quadrilateral 
whose sides are tangent to the conic. Corresponding to a given self -polar 
triangle, one vertex or side of such a quadrangle or quadrilateral may 
be chosen arbitrarily on the conic. 

Theorem 17 may also be stated as follows : If P is a variable point 
on a line q, its polar p is a variable line through the pole Q of g. In the 
special case where q is a tangent to the conic, we have already seen 
(Theorem 12) that we have 

m-zW- 

If Q is not on q, let A (fig. 60) be a fixed point on the come, a the 
tangent at A, X the point (distinct from A, if AP is not tangent) in 
which AP meets the conic, and x the tangent at X. We then have, by 
Theorem 12, 



By Theorem 13, (ax) is on p, and hence p = Q (ass). Hence we have 

[ZlAW 

If P' is the point pq, this gives 



But since the polar of JP' also passes through P, this projectivity is 
an involution. The result of this discussion may then be stated as 
follows : 

* It was by considering the polar reciprocal of Pascal's theorem that Brianchon 
derived the theorem named after him. This method was fully developed by Poncelet 
and Gergonne in the early part ol the last century in connection with the principle 
of duality. 



124 CONIC SECTIONS t0.ir V 

18 On any I * tan^nt to a fl*x < 0" P*ir, 



a " 



, f - , 

It points, these points are tU ao^U point* of ***. 

COBOLIARY As a yot f <"*" a V"^ f ?" ' ' 2 ar 
to My tonie varies over a prj* P** / *" 




FIG. 60 

The pairing of the points and lines of a plane brought 
about by associating with every point its polar and with ovory line its 
pole with respect to a given conic in the plane is called a polar system. 

EXERCISES 

1. If in a polar system two points are conjugate to a third point A , the 
line joining them is the polar of A 

2. State the duals of the last two theorems. 

3. If <z and 6 are two nonconjugate lines in a polar system, every point A 
of a has a conjugate point B on Z>. The pencils of points [/I] and [#] are 
protective; they are perspective if and only if a and & intorseob on the conies 
of the polar system 

4. Let A he a point and 6 a line not the polar ef A with respect to a given 
conic, but in the plane of the conic. If on any line I through A we determine 
that point P which is conjugate with the point Ib, the locus of P is a conic 
passing through A and the pole J3 of &, unless the line AB is tangent to the 



POLAE SYSTEM 

conic, in which case the locus of P is a line. If A B is not tangent, to the conic, 
the locus of P also passes through the points in which ft meets the given conic 
(if such points exist), and also through the points of contact of the tangents to 
the given conic through A (if such tangents exist). Dualize (Keye-IIolgate, 
Geometiy of Position, p 106) 

5. If the vertices of a tuangle are on a given conic, any line conjugate to 
one side meets the other two sides in a pair of conjugate points. Conversely, 
a line meeting two sides of the triangle in conjugate points passes thiough 
the pole of the third side (von Staudt). 

6 If two lines conjugate with respect to a conic meet the conic in two 
pans of points, these pairs are projected from any point on the conic by a 
haimomc set of lines, and the tangents at these pairs of points meet any 
tangent in a haimomc set of points 

7 With a given point not on a given conic as center and the polar of this 
point as axis, the conic is tiansfoimed into itself by a homology of period two. 

8. The Pascal line of any simple hexagon whose veitices are on a conic is 
the polar with respect to the conic of the Bnanchon point of the simple hexagon 
whose sides aie the tangents to the conic at the vertices of the first hexagon. 

9 If the line joining two points A, B, conjugate with respect to a conic, 
meets the conic in two points, these two points ai e harmonic with A , J5. 

10 If in a plane theie are given two conies C* and C 2 2 , and the polars of 
all the points of C 3 with respect to C 2 2 are detei mined, these polars aie the 
tangents of a third conic. 

11 If the tangents to a given conic meet a second conic in pairs of points, 
the tangents at these pairs of points meet on a thud conic 

12 Given five points of a conic (or four points and the tangent thi ough 
one of them, or any one of the other conditions determining a conic), show 
how to construct the polar of a given point with respect to the conic. 

13. If two pans of opposite sides of a complete quadrangle are pairs of 
conjugate lines with respect to a conic, the third pair of opposite sides are 
conjugate with lespect to the conic (von Staudt) 

14 If each of two triangles in a plane is the polar of the other with i espect 
to a conic, they aie peispective, and the axis of perspectivity is the polar of the 
center of perspectivity (Chasles). 

15. Two triangles that are self-polar with respect to the same conic have 
their six vertices on a second conic and their six sides tangent to a thiid 
conic (Steinei). 

16. Kegarding the Desargues configuration as composed of a quadrangle 
and a quadnlateral mutually inscribed (cf. 18, Chap II), show that the 
diagonal triangle of the quadrangle is perspective with the diagonal triangle 
of the quadrilateral. 

17. Let A) B be any two conjugate points with respect to a conic, and let 
the lines AM, BM joining them to an arbitrary poinb of the conic meet the 
latter again in the points C, D respectively. The lines AD, BC will then meet 
on the come, and the lines CD and AB aie conjugate. Dualise. 



126 CONIC SECTIONS [OBAV. V 

45. Degenerate conies. For a variety of reasons it is dcsiniblo to 

* 1 I 

regard two coplanar lines or one line (thought of as two eomcuK'nt 
lines) as degenerate cases of a point conic; and dually to re#aw 
two points or one point (thought of as two coincident points) i 
degenerate cases of a line conic This conception makes it poHwilw* 
to leave out the restriction as to the plane of section in Thooivm 1. 
For the section of a cone of lines by a plane through the vurtcx if 
the cone consists evidently of two (distinct or coincident) liiun, i.e. 
of a degenerate point conic; and the section of a cone of plaiiow by 
a plane through the vertex of the cone is the figure formed by floiw 
or all the lines of a flat pencil, i.e a degenerate line conic. 

EXERCISE 

Dualize in all possible ways the degenerate and nondegonorate cani'B of 
Theorem 1. 

Historically, the first definition of a conic section was given by tho andont 
Greek geometeis (e.g. Mensechmus, about 350 B.C ), who defined them UN tin* 
plane sections of a "light circular cone." Jn a later chapter \vo mil show 
that in the " geometry of reals " any nondegeneiate point conic is pi'ojcetivuly 
equivalent to a circle, and thus that for the ordinary geometry tha modern 
protective definition given in 41 is equivalent to the old definition, We luv 
here using one of the modern definitions because it can be applied before devel- 
oping the Euclidean metric geometiy. 

Degenerate comes would be included in our definition (p. 100), if 
we had not imposed the restriction on the generating protective 
pencils that they be nonperspective ; for the locus of the point of 
intersection of pairs of homologous lines in two perspective flat 
pencils in the same plane consists of the axis of perspeotivity and 
the line joining the centers of the pencils. 

It will be seen, as we progress, that many theorems regarding non- 
degenerate conies apply also when the conies are degenerate, For 
example, Pascal's theorem (Theorem 3) becomes, for the case of a 
degenerate conic consisting of two distinct lines, the theorem of 
Pappus already proved as Theorem 21, Chap. IV (of. in particular the 
corollary). The polar of a point with regard to a degenerate conic 
consisting of two lines is the harmonic conjugate^ tjie point with 
respect to the two lines (cf. the deftniM0;a, ,p. 84, $x. 7).^ Htoo* tha 
polar system of a degenerate co&ic 
points) determines an involution, 




-45,46] THEOREM OF DESARGUES 

EXERCISES 

1 State Brianchon's theorem (Theorem 3') for the caso of a degenerate 
line conic consisting of two points 

2. Examine all the theoiems of the preceding sections with refoienoo to 
their behavior when the conic in question becomes degenerate. 

46. Desargues's theorem on conies. 

TIIEOEEM 19. If the vertices of a complete quadrangle are on a conic 
which meets a line in two points, the latter are a pair in the invo- 
lution determined on the line by the pairs of opposite sides of the 
quadrangle.* 

Proof Reverting to the proof of Theorem 2 (fig. 51), let tho line 
meet the conic in the points I? 2 , <7 X and let the vortices of the quad- 
rangle be A v A a> 23 V O a . This quadrangle determines on the line an 
involution in which 8, A and T, U are conjugate pairs. But in the 
proof of Theorem 2 we saw that the quadrangle A^A^BG determines 
Q(B S ST, C^AU}. Hence the two quadrangles determine the same 
involution on the line, and therefore # 2 , C l are a pair of the involution 
determined "by the quadrangle A^AyB^Cy 

Since the quadrangles A^A^B^C^ and A^A Z BO determine the same 
involution on the line when the latter is a tangent to the conic, we 
have as a special case of the above theorem : 

COKOLLARY. If the vertices of a complete quadrangle are on a conic, 
the pairs of opposite sides meet the tangent at any other point in pairs 
of an involution of which the point of contact of the tangent is a double 
point. 

The Desargues theorem leads to a slightly different form of statement foi 
the construction of a conic through five given points Oil any line through 
one of the points the complete quadrangle of the other four determine an 
involution ; the conjugate in this involution of the given point on the line 
is a sixth point on the conic. 

As the Desargues theorem is related to the theorem of Pascal, so 
are certain degenerate cases of the Desargues theorem related to the 
degenerate cases of the theorem of Pascal (Theorems 6, 7, 8, 9). Thus 
in fig 53 we see (by Theorem 6) that the quadrangle JBCP^ deter- 
mines on the line P^ an involution in which the points P^ P of the 
conic are one pair, while the points determined by p v J^P & and those 



* First given by Desargues in 1639; of. CBuvres, Paris, Vol. I (1864), p. 188', 



12 g CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP, v 

determined by 2>J?, %P 6 are two other pairs. This gives the following 
special case of the theorem of Desargues : 

THEOREM 20. If the vertices of a triangle are on a conic, and a line I 
meets the conic in two points, the latter are a pair of the involution 
determined on I ly the pair of points in which two sides of the triangle 
meet I and the pair in which the third side and the tangent at the 
opposite vertex meet I In case I is a tangent to the conic, the point of 
contact is a double point of this involution. 

In teims of this theoiem we may state the construction of a conic thiough 
four points and tangent to a line thiough one of them as follows . On any lino 
through one of the points which is not on the tangent an involution is deter- 
mined in which the tangent and the line passing through the other two points 
determine one pair, and the lines joining the point of contact to the other two 
points determine another pan. The conjugate of the given point on the line 
in this involution is a point of the conic. 

A further degenerate case is derived either from Theorem 7 or 
Theorem 8. In fig. 54 (Theorem 7) let I be the hue 2j. The quad- 
rangle ABP^ determines on I an involution in. which 1%, P a are one 
pair, in which the tangents at P v P determine another pair, and in 
which the line P i P i determines a double point. Hence we have 

THEOREM 21. If a line I meets a conic in two points and P v P are 
any other two points on the conic, the points in which I meets the conic 
are a pair of an involution through a double point of which passes the 
line P^ and through a pair of conjugate points of which pass the 
tangents at P I} P, If I is tangent to the conic, the point of contact is 
the second double point of this involution. 

The construction of the conic corresponding to this theorem may be stated 
as follows : Given two tangents and their points of contact and one other point 
of the conic. On any line I through the latter point is determined an involution 
of which one double point is the intersection with I of the line joining the two 
points of contact, and of which one pair is the pair of intersections with I of 
the two tangents The conjugate in this involution of the given point of the 
conic on I is a point of the conic 

EXERCISE 
State the duals of the theorems in this section 

47, Pencils and ranges of conies. Order of contact. The theorems 
of the last section and their plane duals determine the properties of 
certain systems of conies which we now proceed to discuss briefly. 



47] 



PENCILS AND RANGES 



129 



DEFINITION. The set of all conies 
through the vertices of a complete 
quadrangle is called a pencil of 
conies of Type I (fig 61) 

Theorem 19 and its plane dual 
THEOREM 22. Any line (not 
through a vertex of the deter- 
mining quadrangle] is met "by the 
conies of a pencil of Type I in the 
pairs of an involution.* 



DEFINITION. The set of all conies 
tangent to the sides of a complete 
quadrilateral is called a range of 
conies of Type I (fig. 62). 
give at once : 

THEOREM 22'. The tangents 
through any point (not on a side 
of the determining quadrilateral) 
to the conies of a range of Type / 
are the pairs of an involution. 





FIG 61 



FIG. 62 




Fia 68 

COROLLABY. Through a gen- 
eral^ point in the plane there is 
one and only one, and tangent to 
a general line there are two or no 
conies of a gwen pencil of Type L 



FIG. 64k 

COROLLARY. Tangent to a gen- 
eral line in the plane there is one 
and only one, and through a gen- 
eral point there are two or no 
conies of a given range of Type L 



* This form of Desargues's theorem is due to Ch. Sturm, Atmales de Math<5ma- 
t The vertices of the quadrangle are regarded as exceptional points. 



130 



CONIC SECTIONS 



[CHAP V 



DEFINITION. The set of all conies 
through the vertices of a triangle 
and tangent to a fixed line through 
one vertex is called a pencil of 
conies of Type II (fig. 63). 



DEFINITION. The set of all comes 
tangent to the sides of a triangle 
and passing through a fixed point 
on one side is called a range of 
conies of Type II (fig. 64). 



Theorem. 20 and its plane dual then give at once: 



THEOREM 23. Any line in the 
plane of a pencil of conies of 
Type II (which does not pass 
through a vertex of the determin- 
ing triangle) is met liy the conies 
of the pencil in the pairs of an 
involution. 

COROLLARY. Through a general 
point in the plane there is one and 
only one conic of the pencil; a,nd 
tangent to a general line in the 
plane there are two or no conies 



THEOREM 23', The tangents 
through any point in the plane 
of a range of conies of Type II 
(which is not on a side of the 
determining triangle} to the conies 
of the range are the pairs of an 
involution. 

COROLLARY. Tangent to a gen- 
eral line in the plane there is one 
and only one conic of the range; 
and through a general point in 
the plane there are two or no 
conies of the range. 



of the pencil. 

DEFINITION. The set of all conies through two given points and 
tangent to two given lines through these points respectively is called 

a pencil or range of conies of Type 
IV* (fig. 65). 

Theorem 21 now gives at once: 

THEOREM 24 Any line in the plane 
of a pencil of conies of Type IV (which 
does not pass through either of the 
points common to all the conies of 
the pencil) is met "by the conies of the 
pencil in the pairs of an involution. 
Through any point in the plane (not 
on either of the lines that are tangent 
to all the conies of the pencil) the 
tangents to the conies of the pencil are the pairs of an involution. The 
line joining the two points common to all the conies of the pencil meets 

* The classification of pencils and ranges of conies into types corresponds to the 
classification of the corresponding plane collineations {of, Bare. 2, 4, 7, below). 




FIG. 65 



47] PENCILS AND RANGES 131 

any line in a double point of the involution determined on that hue. 
And the point of intersection of the common tangents is joined to any 
point by a double line of the involution determined at that point 

GOKOLLAHY. Through any general point or tangent to any general 
line in the plane there is one and only one conic of the pencil. 

EXERCISES 

1. What are the degenerate conies of a pencil or range of Type J? The 
diagonal triangle of the fundamental quadrangle (quadnlateral) of the pencil 
(range) is the only triangle which is self-polar with respect to two conies of 
the pencil (range). 

2. Let A z and J3 2 be any two comes of a pencil of Type I, and let P be any 
point in the plane of the pencil. If p is the polar of P with respect to A s , and 
P' is the pole of p with respect to U 2 , the coirespondence thus established 
between [P] and [P'] is a piojective colhneation of Type 7, whose invariant 
triangle is the diagonal triangle of the fundamental quadrangle. Do all pio- 
jective collineations thus determined by a pencil of comes of Type I form a 
gioup? Dualize. 

3. -What are the degenerate conies of a pencil or range of Type III 

4 Let a pencil of comes of Type 7/be determined by a triangle ABC and 
a tangent a through A. Further, let o" be the harmonic conjugate of a with 
respect to AB and A C, and let A' be the intersection of a and BC. Then 
A , a and A', a' are pole and polar with respect to every conic of the pencil , and 
no pair of conies of the pencil have the same polars with regard to any other 
points than A and A' Dualize, and show that all the collineations determined 
as in Ex. 2 are in this case of Type JL 

5 What are the degenerate comes of a pencil or range of Type IV 1 

6. Show that any point on the line joining the two points common to all 
the conies of a pencil of Type IV has the same polar with respect to all the 
comes of the pencil, and that these all pass through the point of intersection 
of the two common tangents. 

7 Show that the collineations determined by a pencil of Type/ V by the 
method of Ex 2 are all homologies (i e of Type IV). 

* The pencils and ranges of conies thus far considered have in com- 
mon the properties (1) that the pencil (range) is completely denned 
as soon as two conies of the pencil (range) are given ; (2) the comes 
of the pencil (range) determine an involution on any line (point) in 
the plane (with the exception of the lines (points) on the determining 
points (lines) of the pencil (range)). Three other systems of conies may 
be denned which likewise have these properties. These new systems 

* The remainder of this section may be omitted on a first reading. 



CONIC SECTIONS I 

may be regarded as degenerate cases of the pencils and ranges already 
defined. Their existence is established by the theorems given below, 
which, together with their corollaries, may be regarded as degenerate 
cases of the theorem of Desargues. We shall need the following 

LEMMA. Any conic is transformed ly a projective collineation in 
the plane of the conic into a conic such, that the tangents at homologous 
points are homologous. 

Proof. This follows almost directly from the definition of a conic. 
Two projective flat pencils are transformed by a projective coUmeation 
into two projective flat pencils. The intersections of pairs of homologous 
lines of one pencil are therefore transformed into the intersections 
of the corresponding pairs of homologous lines of the transformed 
pencils. If any line meets the first conic m a point P, the transformed 
line will meet the transformed conic in the point homologous with P. 
Therefore a tangent at a point of the first conic must be transformed 
into the tangent at the corresponding point of the second conic. 

THEOREM 25. If a line p Q is a tangent to a conic A* at a point P Q , 
and Q is any point of A z , then through any point on the plane of A z 

out not on A z or p , 
there is one and only 
one conic B* tJirough 
P Q and Q, tangent to 
p , and such that there 
is no point of p Qf ex- 
cept J, having the same 
polar with regard to 
loth A* and B\ 

Proof. If P' is any point of the plane not on p or A*, let JP be 
the second point in which P P' meets A 2 (fig. 66) There is one and 
only one elation with center P and axis P Q changing P into P' 
(Theorem 9, Chap. III). This elation (by the lemma above) changes 
A* into another conic B z through the points P Q and Q and tangent 
to #,. The lines through P are unchanged by the elation, whereas 
their poles (on_p ) are subjected to a parabolic projectivity. Hence 
no point cm A (distinct from J>) has the same polar with regard to A* 
as with regard to B\ Since A* is transformed into & by an elation, 
the two conies can have no other points in common than JR and Q. 




47] 



PENCILS AND RANGES 



133 



That there is only one conic B* through P' satisfying the con- 
ditions of the theorem is to be seen as follows Let QP meet p Q in 
S, and QP' meet p in S' (fig. 66). The point S has the same polar 
with regard to A z as S' with regard to any conic J5 3 , since this polar 
must be the harmonic conjugate of p Q with regard to P Q and P Q P. 
Let p be the tangent to A 2 at P and p' be the tangent to J? 2 at P', 
and let p and p' meet p in T and 2 1 ' respectively. The points 




Em 07 



T and T' have the same polar, namely P P, with regard to A* and 
any conic B z . By the conditions of the theorem the projectivity 



must be parabolic Hence, by Theorem 23, Cor , Chap. IV, 

Q(P ST, P T'S') 

Hence p and p' must meet on P^Q in a point R so as to form the quad- 
rangle RQPP'. This determines the elements P , Q, P',p Q , p 1 ot B*, 
and hence there is only one possible conic B*. 

COROLLARY 1. Tlie conies A s and B z can have no other points in 
common than P and Q. 

COROLLARY 2. Any line I not on P or Q which meets A 2 and JB a 
meets them in pairs of an involution in which the points of intersection 
of I with P^Q and p are conjugate 

Proof, Let I meet A* in N and 2T V B*ia.L and L v P QinM, and 
p in Jfj (fig. 67). Let 7f and JT X be the points of A* which are trans- 
formed by the elation into L and L respectively. By the definition of 
an elation JT and Jf x are collinear with M, while JTis on the hne ZP 
and JTj on L& Let KN^ meet p^ in J8, and ^TJ? meet JT^ in & 



134 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP V 

Then since N, K, N v K, are on the conic to which PQ is tangent at J, we 
have'by Theorem 6, applied to the degenerate hexagon ^KXN^ 
that S L and S are collinear. Hence the complete quadrilateral 
SB KN V KK I has pairs of opposite vertices on P Q M and P,M V J' N 
and P,N V 3/and % He ce ( MNL > ^Wi)-* 

DEFINITION The set of all conies DEFINITION The set of all conies 
through a point Q and tangent to tangent to a line q and tangent to 
a line p at a point P Q> and such 
that no point of p except P Q has 
the same polar with, regard to two 
conies of the set, is called a pencil 



of comes of Type III (fig- 68) 



a line p at a point P , and such 
that no line on P except p has 
the same pole with regard to two 
conies of the set, is called a range 
of conies of Type III (fig 09). 




Fiu 09 



Two conies of such a pencil (range) are said to have contact of the 
second order, or to osculate, at P Q . 

Corollary 2 of Theorem 25 now gives at once: 

THEOREM 26. Any line in the 
plane of a pencil of conies of 
Type III, which is not on either of 
the common points of the pencil, is 
met T)y the conies of the pencil in the 
pairs of an involution. Through 
any point in the plane except the 
common points there is one and 
only one conic of the pencil; and 
tangent to any line not through 
either of the common points there 
are two or no conies of the pencil. 



20'. Through any point 
in the plane of a range of conies of 
Type III, which is not on sitlwr of 
the common tangents of the range, 
the tangents to the cornea of the pen- 
cil are the pairs of an involution. 
Tangent to any line in th c plane, e,<3- 
cept the common tungcuts there is 
one andonli/ona conic of the 'range; 
and through any point not on either 
of the common tangents there are 
two or no conies of the range. 



* This argument has implicitly proved that three pairs of points of a conic, as 
JOTi, NNi, P Q, such, that the lines joining them meet in a point JMT, are projected 
from any point of the conic l>y a quadrangular set of lines (Theorem 10, Chap, VIII), 



47] 



PENCILS AND RANGES 



135 



The pencil Is determined by 
the two common points, the com- 
mon tangent, and one conic of the 
pencil. 



The range is determined by 
the two common tangents, the 
common point, and one conic of 
the range. 



EXERCISES 

1 What are the degenerate comes of this pencil and range ? 

2 Show that the colhneation obtained by making coi respond to any point P 
the point P' which has the same polar p with regard to one given conic of the 
pencil (lange) that P has with regard to anothei given conic of the pencil (range) 
is of Type JIJ. 

THEOREM 27. If a hue p Q is tangent to a conic A* at a point P , 
there is one and only one conic tangent to p 6 at P Q and passing 
through any other point P' of the plane of A z not on p Q or A* 
which determines for every point of p Q the same polar line as does A*. 

Proof. Let P be the second point in which P^P' meets A 2 (fig. 70) 
There is one and only one elation of which P is center and p Q axis, 
changing P to P'. This elation changes A* into a conic J5 2 through 




FIG. 70 

P', and is such that if q is any tangent to A* at a point Q, then c[ is 
transformed to a tangent q f of JB* passing through qp Q , and Q is trans- 
formed into the point of contact Q' of %', collinear with Q and J 
Hence there is one conic of the required type through P'. 

That there is only one is evident, because if I is any line through P', 
any conic j# 8 must pass through the fourth harmonic of P' with regard 
1o Ipt and the polar of Ip as to A z (Theorem 13), By considering two 
lines I we thus determine enough points to fix JB*. 

COROLLARY 1. By duality there is one and only one conic JS a tangent 
to any line not passing through P^ 



136 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP, v 

COROLLARY 2. Any line I not on P Q which meets A z and B z meets 
them in pairs of an involution one double point of which ^s Ip 0) and 
the other the point of I conjugate to Ip with respect to A 2 . A dual 
statement holds for any point L not on p . 

COROLLARY 3. The conies A* and B z can have no other point in 
common than P Q and no other tangent in common than p . 

Proof. If they had one other point P in common, they would have 
in common the conjugate of P in the involution determined on any 
line through P according to Corollary 2 

DEFINITION. The set of all comes tangent to a given line p Q at a 
given point P Q , and such that each point on p has the same polar 
with regard to all conies of the set, is called a pencil or range of 
conies of Type V. Two conies of such a pencil are said to have 
contact of the third order, or to hyperosculate at P , 

Theorem 27 and its first two corollaries now give at once : 

THEOREM: 28. Any line I not on the common point of a pencil of 
Type V is met by the conies of the pencil in pairs of an involution 
one double point of which is the intersection of I with the common 
tangent. Through any point L not on the common tangent the pairs 
of tangents to the conies of the pencil form an involution one double 
line of whicJi is the line joining L to the common point. There is one 
conic of the set through each point of the plane not on the common 
tangent, and one come tangent to each line not on the common point. 

The pencil or range is determined by the common point, the common 
tangent, and one conic of the set. 

EXERCISES 

1. What are the degenerate comes of a pencil of Type VI 

2. Show that the collineation obtained by making correspond to any 
point P the point Q which has the same pole p with regard to one conic of 
a pencil of Type V that P has with regard to another conic of the pencil is 
an elation. 

3. The lines polar to a point A with regard to all tho conies of a pencil 
of any of the five types pass through a point A'. The points A and A' are 
double points of the involution determined by the pencil on the line A A', 
Construct A'. Dualize. Derive a theorem on the complete quadrangle as a 
special case of this one. 

4. Construct the polar line of a point A with regard to a come C a being 
given four points of C z and a conjugate of A with regard to <7 a . 



47] PENCILS AND RANGES 137 

5. Given an involution I on a line I, a pair of points A and A' on I not 
conjugate in I, and any othei point JB on /, construct a point B' such that A 
and A' and J3 and jB' are pans of an involution I' whose double points are a 
pair in I The involution I' may also be desciibed as one which is commu- 
tative -with I, or such that the product of I and I" is an involution. 

6 There is one and only one conic through thiee points and having a 
given point P and line p as pole and polar. 

7. The comes through three points and having a given pair of points as 
conjugate points form a pencil of comes. 

MISCELLANEOUS EXERCISES 

I. If and o are pole and polar with regard to a conic, and A and B are 
two points of the come collinear with 0, then the conic is generated by the 
two pencils A [P] and B [P'] where P and P' are paired in the involution 
on o of conjugates with regard to the conic. 

2 Given a complete plane five-point ABODE. The locus of all points X 

such that 

X(BCDE) A(BCDE) 
is a conic. A 

3 Given two projective nonperspective pencils, [ja] and [<?]. Every line I 
upon which the projectivity Z[j>]-T-Z[0] is mvolutoric passes thiough a fixed 
point 0. The point is the pole of the line joining the centers of the pencils 
with respect to the conic generated by them. 

4. If two complete quadrangles have the same diagonal points, their eight 
vertices he on a conic (Cremona, Projective Geometry (Oxford, 1885), Chap. XX). 

5. If two conies intersect in four points, the eight tangents to them at 
these points are on the same line conic Dualize and extend to the cases 
where the conies are in pencils of Types II-V- 

6. All conies with lespect to which a given triangle is self -con jugate, and 
which pass through a fixed point, also pass through three other fixed points. 
Dualize. 

7. Construct a conic through two given points and with a given self- 
conjugate triangle. Dualize. 

8. If the sides of a triangle are tangent to a conic, the lines joining two 
of its vertices to any point conjugate with regard to the conic to the third 
vertex are conjugate with regard to the conic. Dualize. 

9. If two points P and Q on a conic are joined to two conjugate points P', Qf 
on a line conjugate to PQ, then PP' and QQf meet on the conic 

10. If a simple quadrilateral is circumscribed to a conic, and if I is any 
transversal through the intersection of its diagonals, I will meet the conic and 
the pairs of opposite sides in conjugate pairs of an involution. Dualize. 

II. Given a conic and three fixed collinear points A,B,C. There is a fourth 
point D on the line AB such that if three sides of a simple quadrangle in- 
scribed in the conic pass through A, B, and C respectively, the fourth passes 
through D (Cremona, Chap. XVH). 



138 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP V 

12 If a vauable simple 7i-lme (n even) is inscubed in a conic in suclx a way 
that n 1 of its sides pass thiough n 1 fixed collinear points, then the otliei 
side passes thiough anothei fixed point of the same line Puah/e this theorem 

13. If two comes inteisect in two points A, B (01 aie tangent at a point A) 
and two lines through A and B lespectivoly (01 thiough the point oi contact 
A) meet the conies again in 0, 0' and L, L', then the lines OL and O'L' meet 
on the line joining the lemaming points of intellection (i existent) of the 
two conies. 

14. If a conic C 2 passes through the vertices of a triangle which is self- 
polar with lespect to another conic /C 2 , theie is a tuangle msciibed in C 2 and 
self -polar with regard to K 2 , and having one vertex at any point of C 2 The 
lines -which cut C 2 and K z in two pairs of points which are haimonically con- 
jugate to one another constitute a line conic Cg, which is the polai leciprocal 
of C 2 with regard to 1C 2 (Ciemona, Chap. XXII). 

15. If a vanahle tuangle is such that two of its sides pass lespectively 
thiough two fixed points 0' and lying on a given conic, and the vertices oppo- 
site them lie respectively on two fixed lines u and u f , while the third vertex 
lies always on the given conic, then the third side touches a fixed conic, which 
touches the lines u and u'. Dualize (Cremona, Chap. XXII) 

16. If P is a vauable point on a conic containing A, B, C, and I is a vari- 
able line thiough P such that all throws T (PA, PB, PC, I) are projective, 
then all lines I meet in a point of the conic (Schroter, Jouinal fiir die reine uud 
angewandte Mathematik, Vol. LXII, p. 222). 

17. Given a fixed come and a fixed line, and three fixed points A , B, C 011 
the conic, let P be a variable point on the conic and let PA, PB, PC meet 
the fixed line m A', B', C' If is a fixed point of the plane and (0.1", PB") = K 
and (JTC") = I, then K descubes a conic and I a pencil of lines whose center is 
on the conic described by K (Schiotei, loc. cit.). 

18. Two tiiangles ABC and PQR are perspective in four ways Show that 
if ABC and the point P are fixed and Q, R are variable, the locus of each of 
the latter points is a conic (cf. Ex. 8, p. 105, and Schioter, Mathematische 
Annalen, Vol II (1870), p 553). 

19. Given six points on a conic. By taking these in all possible orders 
60 different simple hexagons inscribed in the conic are obtained. Each of 
these simple hexagons gives rise to a Pascal line The figmo thus associated 
with any six points of a conic is called the hexafframmum myttticum.* Piove the 
following properties of the hexagranimum. mystictun : 

i. The Pascal lines of the thi ee hexagons PiPgPBP^PgP,,, PiP 4 P^P 6 P 6 P z , 
and P 1 P P 8 P 8 P 6 P 4 are concurrent. The point thus associated with such, a set 
of three hexagons is called a Steiner point, 

ii There are in all 20 Steiner points. 

* On the Pascal hexagram cf Stemer-Rchrbter, Vorlesungen liber Synthetische 
Geometne, Vol II, 28 , Salmon, Conic Sections m the Notes ; Christine Ladd, 
American Journal of Mathematics, Vol, II (1879), p 1. 



47] ' EXERCISES 13 Q 

iii. Fiom a given simple hexagon five others are obtained by permuting 
in all possible ways a set of thiee vertices no two of which are adjacent. The 
Pascal lines of these six hexagons pass through two Steinei points, which ai*e 
called conjugate Sterner points. The 20 Steiner points fall into ten pahs of 
conjugates. 

iv The 20 Steiner points lie by fours on 15 lines called Steiner lines. 

v What is the symbol of the configui ation composed of the 20 Steiner 
points and the 15 Steiner lines ? 

20. Discuss the problem corresponding to that of Ex. 19 for all the special 
cases of Pascal's theorem 

21. State the duals of the last two exercises 

22. If in a plane there are given two conies, any point A has a polai with 
respect to each of them If these polars intersect iu A', the points A, A' aie 
conjugate with respect to both comes. The polars of A' likewise meet in A. 
In this way every point in the plane is paired with a unique other point. By 
the dual piocess every line in the plane is paned with a unique line to which 
it is conjugate with respect to both comes Show that in this correspondence 
the points of a line correspond in geneial to the points of a conic. All such 
comes which correspond to lines of the plane have in common a set of at most 
three points. The polais of eveiy such common point coincide, so that to each 
of them is made to correspond all the points of a line. They foim the excep- 
tional elements of the coirespondence. Dualize (Reye-PIolgate, p. 110).* 

23 If in the last exercise the two given comes pass through the vertices of 
the same quadrangle, the diagonal points of this quadrangle are the "common 
points " mentioned in the preceding exercise (Reye-Holgate, p 110). 

24 Given a cone of lines with vertex and a line u thiough 0. Then a 
one-to-one correspondence may be established among the lines thiough O by 
associating with every such line o its conjugate a' with respect to the cone 
lying in the plane au If, then, a descubes a plane tr, of will desciibe a cone of 
lines passing thiough u and through the polar line of IT, and which has in 
common with the given cone any lines common to it and to the given cone 
and the polar plane of u (Reye-Holgate, p. Ill) * 

25. Two conies are determined by the two sets of five points A^B,C,D,E 
and A , B, C, H, K. Construct the fourth point of intersection of the two conies 
(Castelnuovo, Leziom di Geometna, p 391). 

26. Apply the result of the preceding Exercise to construct the point P such 
that the set of lines P(A, J3, C, D, E) joining P to the vertices of any given 
complete plane five-point be projective with any given set of five points on a 
line (Castelnuovo, loc. cit.). 

27. Given any plane quadrilateral, construct a line which meets the sides 
of the quadrilateral in a set of four points projective with any given set of 
four collinear points. 

* The correspondences defined in Exs. 22 and 24 are 
quadratic correspondences. 



140 CONIC SECTIONS [CHAP.V 

28. Two sets of five points A, B, C, D, E and A, B, If, K, L determine 
two comes which intersect again in two points X, Y. Construct the line XY 
and show that the points X, Y are the double points of a certain involution 
(Castelnaovo, loc. cit.). 

29. If three conies pass through two given points A, B and the three pairs 
of comes cut again in three pairs of points, show that the three lines joining 
these pairs of points are concurrent (Castelnuovo, loc. cit ). 

30. Prove the converse of the second theoiem of Desargnes * The conies 
passing through thiee fixed points and meeting a given line in the pairs of 
an involution pass through a fourth fixed point. This theorem may be used 
to construct a conic, given three of its points and a pan of points conjugate 
with respect to the conic. Dualize (Castelnuovo, loc. cit.). 

31. The poles of a line with respect to all the conies of a pencil of conies 
of Type / are on a conic which passes through the diagonal points of the 
quadrangle defining the pencil. This conic cuts the given line in the points 
in which the latter is tangent to conies of the pencil. Dualize. 

32. Let p be the polar of a point P with regard to a triangle ABC. If P 
varies on a conic which passes through A, JB, C, then 7? passes through a fixed 
point Q, (Cayley, Collected Works, Vol I, p. 361). 

33. If two comes are inscribed in a triangle, the six points of contact aie 
on a third conic. 

34. Any two vertices of a triangle circumscribed to a conic are separated 
harmonically by the point of contact of the side containing them and the point 
where this side meets the line joining the points of contact of the other sides. 



CHAPTER YI 

ALGEBRA OF POINTS AND ONE-DIMENSIONAL COORDINATE 

SYSTEMS 

48. Addition of points. That analytic methods may be introduce! 
into geometry on a strictly projective basis was first shown by voi 
Staudt.* The point algebra on a line which is defined in this chapte 
without the use of any further assumptions than A, E, P is essentially 
equivalent to von Staudt's algebra of throws (p. 60), a brief accoum 
of which will be found in 55. The original method of von Staudi 
has, however, been considerably clarified and simplified by moderr 
researches on the foundations of geometry f All the definitions ano 
theorems of this chapter before Theorem 6 are independent of As 
sumption P. Indeed, if desired, this part of the chapter may be read 
before taking up Chap IV. 

Given a line l t and on I three distinct (arbitrary) fixed points which 
for convenience and suggestiveness we denote by P Q , P lt P a) we define 
two one-valued operations $ on pairs of points of I with reference to 
the fundamental points P , P^ P n The fundamental points are said 
to determine a scale on I. 

DEFINITION. In any plane through I let l n and IL be any two lines 
through P n) and let Z be any line through JfJ meeting Z and IL in 
points A and A' respectively (fig 71). Let P x and P y be any two points 
of I, and let the lines P X A and P V A' meet Z and Z* m the points X 
and Y respectively. The point JJ +f , in which the line JET meets I, is 
called the sum of the points P x and P y (in symbols P^+P^P^^ in 

* K G. 0. von Staudt (1798-1867), Beitiage zur Geometne derLage, Heft 2 (1857), 
pp. 166 et seq This book is concerned also with the related question of the inter- 
pretation of imaginary elements in geometry. 

t Of., for example, G. Hessenberg, TJeber emen Geometrischen Calcul, Acta 
Mathematica, Vol. XXIX, p 1. 

| By a one-valued operation o on a pair of points A, B is meant any process 
whereby with every pair 4, B is associated a point (7, which is nmque provided 
the order of A, B is given j in symbols AoB = C Here "order" has no geo- 
metrical significance, but implies merely the formal difference of AoB and Bo A 
TiAQBs=BoA, the operation is commutatwe; if (J.oJB)oC= Ao(BoG), the opera- 
tion is associative, 

HI 



142 



ALGEBRA OF POINTS 



[CllAl?. VI 



the scale P , P v P a The operation of obtaining the sum of two points 
is called addition * 




THEOREM 1. If P x and P y are distinct from P Q and }>, Q(/i/J7>, 
) is a necessary and sufficient condition for the (^nudity 

Z + r ( A > E ) 

This follows immediately from the definition, AA'Y being a 
quadrangle which determines the given quadrangular set. 

COROLLAEY 1. If P x is any point of I, we have P x +P<> Ps + P K ~P x , 
andP^P m ^P m +P m ^^(P m ^P m ), (A,E) 

This is also an immediate consequence of the definition. 

COROLLARY 2. The operation of addition is one-valued for every 
pair of points P^ P y of I, except for the pair P w) P a . (A, K) 

This follows from the theo- 
rem above and the corollary of 

* The historical origin of this con- 
struction will be evident on inspection 
of the attached figure This ia the 
figure which results, if we choose for 
& the "line at infinity" in the plane 
in the sense of ordinary Euclidean 
geometry (cf p. 8), The construction 
is clearly equivalent to a translation. 
of the vector P P y along the line J, 
which brings its initial point into coincidence with the terminal point of the vector 
PP*, which is the ordinary construction for the sum of two vectors oa a Itoe, 




ADDITION 143 

Theorem 3, Chap II, in case P x and P y are distinct from 7 and /;. 
If one of the points P x , P y coincides with P (} or P w) it follows from 
Corollary 1 

COEOLLARY 3. The operation of addition is associative; i.e 



for any three points P x> P u , P g for which the above expressions are 
defined. (A, E) 

Proof (fig. 73). Let P^ + Py he determined as in the definition by 
means of three lines L, V n , 1 Q and the line XY. Let the line P Q Y be 
denoted by ', and by means of l a , IL, IQ construct the point (P x +P y ) -f P z) 




which is determined by the line ZZ t say. If now the point P v -h 7* 
be constructed by means of the lines l a> IJ,, IQ, and then, the point 
P J , + (P y + P z ) be constructed by means of the lines , /, 1 0> it will be 
seen that the latter point is determined by the same line XZ, 

COROLLARY 4 The operation of addition is commutative; i.&. 

<K "T* ^y "~ -*y "T~ J~x 

for every pair of points P y> P v for which the operation is defined. (A, E) 

Proof. By reference to the complete quadrangle AXA'Y (fig. 71) 
there appears the quadrangular set Q(P a!> P v P 0) P n P^+y), which by the 
theorem implies that P v + P x = P a + ^ But, by definition, 
Hence P y + P x 



ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP VI 

THEOREM 2. Any three points P x> P y , P a (P a *&) satisfy the relation 



ie. the correspondence established ly malting each point P r of I corre- 
spond to P x ' = P x + P a > where P a (* P.) is any fixed point of I, is projectile. 

(A,E) * . 

Proof The definition of addition (fig 71) gives tins projectivity as 
the result of two perspectivities : * 



The set of all pi oj activities determined by all possible choices of P a in the 
formula P' x = P x +P<t is the group described in Example 2, p. 70. Thu stun of 
two points P a and P 6 might indeed have been defined as the point into which 
P b is transformed when P is tiansformed into P by a projectivil-y of this 
group. The associative law for addition would thus appear as a special oaao 
of the associative law which holds for the composition of correspondence's in 
general ; and the commutative law for addition would be a consequence of tho 
commutativity of this particular gioup, 




Po 



49. Multiplication of points. DEFINITION In any plane through / 
let J , l v l v be any three lines through P , P v P m respectively, and let J t 
meet Z and 4, in points A and B respectively (fig. 74). Let P x) P u be any 
two points of I, and let the lines P X A and P V B meet C and / in the points 
X and T respectively. The point P XJI in which the line JET meets I is 



-^ *J? 1**^. ** 71 corres P d to the notation of this theorem, P v must T>e 
identified with P a , ' * 



49] MULTIPLICATION 145 

called the product ofP x ly P y (m symbols JP P y = PJ m the scale P Q , P lt P a 
on I. The operation of obtaining the product of two points is called 
multiplication * Each of the points P x , P v is called a factor of the 
product .% P y . 

THEOEEM 3 If P x and P y are any two points of I distinct from 
PO> ^v P> Q(^-^J P<P v P X u) w necessary and sufficient for the equality 
P x P V = P XV . (A,E) 

This follows at once from the definition, AXJBY being the defining 
quadrangle. 

COROLLARY 1 For any point P x (^=P a> ) on I we have the relations 

P ' P = P . P = P ' P P = P P P p p p T> r> f-p, r>\ 
*! ** '-at -*! - l x> J t x - L x J -Q J: o> - c *> J: x J-y *> K> (J^ = 1 Q ). 

This follows at once from the definition 

COROLLARY 2. TJie operation of multiplication is one-valued for 
every pair of points P x , P y of I, except P 9 P a and P m P . (A, E) 

This follows from Corollary 1, if one of the points P x , P u coincides 
with P , P v or j. Otherwise, it follows from the corollary, p. 50, in 
connection with the above theorem. 



B 




* The origin of this construction may also be seen m a simple construction of 
metric Euclidean geometry, which results from the construction of the definition 
by letting the line l u be the "line at infinity" (of. p 8) In the attached figure 
which gives this metric construction we have readily, from similar triangles, the 
proportions: 



which, on taking the segment P Pi=l, gives the desired result PoP^^ 



146 ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP VI 

COROLLAKY 3 The operation of multiplication is associative, i.e we 
have (P v 'P y )'P z = P 3 (P v P s ) for every three points P x , P v , P s for which, 
these products are defined (A, E) 

Proof (fig 76). The proof is entirely analogous to the proof for 
the associative law for addition. Let the point P x P v be constructed 




J?IG 70 

as in the definition by means of three fundamental lines 1 0> l 
the point P xy being determined by the line XY. Denote the line 
by l[, and construct the point P^ P e = (P f J;J) - P g) using the linos Z , J|, ?, 
as fundamental Further, let the point P a J = / be constructed by 
means of the lines 1 0) l(, I*, and then let P x - P^ P X > (P v - 2*) be con- 
structed by means of 1 Q) l v /. It is then seen that the points I* J^ 
and P xa P g are determined by the same line. 

By analogy with Theorem 1, Cor. 4, we should now prove that mul- 
tiplication is also commutative. It will, however, appear presently 
that the commutativity of multiplication cannot be proved without 
the use of Assumption P (or its equivalent). It must indeed be clearly 
noted at this point that the definition of multiplication requires the 
first factor P x in a product to form with J and J a point triple of 
the quadrangular set on I (cf. p. 49) ; the construction of the product 
is therefore not independent of the order of the factors. Moreover, 
the fact that in Theorem 3, Chap. II, the quadrangles giving the points 
of the set are similarly placed, was essential in the proof of that 



49] MULTIPLICATION 147 

theorem We cannot therefore use this theorem to prove the coin 
imitative law for multiplication as in the case of addition. 

An important theorem analogous to Theorem 2 is, however, inde- 
pendent of Assumption P Et is as follows 

THEOREM 4 If the relation P^-P^P^ holds letween any three 
points PI, P v , P IU on I distinct from />, we have P M P^P X -^ P^P^ 
and also P^P^P^Py-j^P^P^P^; ie. the correspondence established by 
making each point P x of I correspond to J^'=^ -P a (or to Pj = P a 'P,), 
where P a is any fixed point of I distinct from P Q) is protective. (A, E) 

Proof. The definition of multiplication gives the first of the above 
projectivities as the result of two perspectivities (fig. 76): 



The second one is obtained similarly In fig 76 we have 



The set of all projectivities deteimined by all choices of P a in the for- 
mula P f x T> x P a 1S t ne group described in Example 1, p 69 The proper- 
ties of multiplication may be legarded as properties of that group in the same 
way that the piopeities of addition aiise fiom the gioup descubed in Example 
2, p. 70 In particular, this furnishes a second proof of the associative law 
for multiplication. 

THEOREM 5. Multiplication is distributive with respect to addition; 
i.e. if P x) P v , P s are any three points on I (for which the operations 
"below are defined), we have 



Proof Place 

+?=+* -S'-S-J 

By Theorem 4 we then have 



But by Theorem 1 we also have Q(P a ,P x P 0> %,%%+) Hence, by 
Theorem 1, Cor., Chap IV, we have Q(^ ^A+a,)) which, 
by Theorem 1, implies % + %=%&+ The relation 



is proved similarly. 



14g ALGEBBA OF POINTS [CHAP VI 

50 The commutative law for multiplication. With the aid of 
Assumption P we will now derive finally the commutative law for 
multiplication : 

THEOREM 6. The operation of multiplication in commutative, ; i.e. 

we have P x P = P y % f or ever y P air f ^ oin ^ J * ^ l ^ T wllich 
these two products are defined. (A, E, P) 

Proof. Let us place as before J - P = P xy , and P v - P, = P vr . Then, by 
the first relation of Theorem 4, and interchanging the points P A , P yf 



and from the second relation of the same theorem we have 



By Theorem 17, Chap. IV, this requires P^P^- 

In view of the fact already noted, that the fundamental theorem 
of protective geometry (Theorem 17, Chap. IV) is equivalent to 
Assumption P, it follows (cf. 3, Vol. II) that : 

THEOREM 7. Assumption Pis necessary and sufficient for the, com- 
mutative law for multiplication.* (A, E) 

51. The inverse operations. DEFINITION. Given two points J' tt Jj 
on /, the operation determining a point P x satisfying the rotation 
j4-JP=Jjis called subtraction; in symbols /jJ--J* = JP. The point 
P x is called the difference of .ZjJ from P a . Subtraction is the iiwne of 
addition. 

The construction for addition may readily be reversed to give a con- 
structionf or subtraction. The preceding theorems on addition then give: 

THEOREM 8 Subtraction is a one-valued operation for every pair 
of points P , P b on I, except the pair P M> P n , (A, K) 

COROLLARY. We have in particular J-~JP==:.7jJ for every point 
nl (A, E) 



* The existence of algebras in which multiplication is not commutative ifl then 
sufficient to establish the fact that Assumption P is independent of the previous 
Assumptions A and E Por in order to construct a system (cf . p. (5) which satisfies 
Assumptions A and E without satisfying Assumption P, we need only construct an 
analytic geometry of three dimensions (as described in a later chapter) and uae as a 
baswa nbncomnratative number system, e g. the system of quaternions. That the 
fundamental theorem of protective geometry is equivalent to the commutative 
fcw for multiplication was first established by Hilbert, who, in MB Foundations of 
Crfometry, showed that the commutative law is equivalent to the theorem of Pappus 

mStheo The ktter M eaSily Seen t0 b6 ec * ulvalent to to 6 funda " 



so, si, 52] ABSTRACT NUMBER SYSTEM 149 

DEFINITION. Given two points P at P b on l\ the point P x determined by 
the relation P a P x = P b is called the quotient of P h by P u (also the ratio 
of P b to P a ) ; in symbols P b /P a = P^ or P b : P a - P, The operation deter- 
mining P b /P a is called division; it is the inverse of multiplication.* 

The construction for multiplication, may also be reversed to give a 
construction for division. The preceding theorems on multiplication 
then give readily : 

THEOREM 9. Division is a one-valued operation for every pair of 
points P a , P b onl except the pairs P^ P Q and J, P n (A, E) 

COROLLARY. We have in particular P a /P a = P i} PjP a =^P^, %/% = %, 
etc., for every point P a onl distinct from P and P n . (A, E) 

Addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division are known as 
the four rational operations 

52. The abstract concept of a number system. Isomorphism. The 
relation of the foregoing discussion of the algebra of points on a line 
to the foundations of analysis must now be briefly considered. With 
the aid of the notion of a group (cl Chap. Ill, p. 66), the general con- 
cept of a number system is descnbed simply as follows : 

DEFINITION. A set N of elements is said to form a number system, 
provided two distinct operations, which we will denote by and o 
respectively, exist and operate on pairs of elements of N under the 
following conditions: 

1. The set N forms a group with respect to . 

2 The set N forms a group with respect to o, except that if i + is 
the identity element of N with respect to , no inverse with respect 
to o exists for *' + .f If a is any element of N, a o i + = i + O a = i + . 

3. Any three elements a, &, c of N satisfy the relations a (b e) 
= (aofy(aoc) and (& c) o a, = (& o a) (c o a) 

The elements of a number system are called numbers, the two oper- 
ations and o are called addition and multiplication respectively. 
If a number system, forms commutative groups with respect to both 
addition and multiplication, the numbers are said to form b 



* What we have defined is more precisely right-handed division The left-handed 
quotient is defined similarly as the point P* determined by the relation Pa, P = P&- 
In a commutative algebra they are of course equivalent. 

t The identity element i+ in a number system is usually denoted by (zero) 
The class of all ordinary rational numbers forms a field; also the class of real 
numbers; and the class of all integers reduced modulo p (jp a prime), etc. 



150 ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP.VI 

On the basis of this definition may be developed all the theory 
relating to the rational operations i.e. addition, multiplication, sub- 
traction, and division in a number system The ordinary algebra 
of the rational operations applying to the set of ordinary rational or 
ordinary real or complex numbers is a special case of such a theory. 
The whole terminology of this algebra, in so far as it is definable in 
terms of the four rational operations, will in the future "be assumed 
as defined. We shall not, therefore, stop to define such terms as 
reciprocal of a number, exponent, equation, satisfy, solution, root, etc. 
The element of a number system represented by a letter as a will be 
spoken of as the value of a. A letter which represents any one of a 
set of numbers is called a variable; variables will usually be denoted 
by the last letters of the alphabet. 

Before applying the general definition above to our algebra of 
points on a line, it is desirable to introduce the notion of the 
abstract equivalence or isomorphism between two number systems. 

DEFINITION. If two number systems are such that a one-to-one 
reciprocal correspondence exists between the numbers of the two 
systems, such that to the sum of any two numbers of one system 
there corresponds the sum of the two corresponding numbers of the 
other system; and that to the product of any two numbers of one 
there corresponds the product of the corresponding numbers of the 
other, the two systems are said to be abstractly equivalent or (simply) 
isomorphic.* 

When two number systems are isomorphic, if any series of oper- 
ations is performed on numbers of one system and the same series 
of operations is performed on the corresponding numbers of the 
other, the resulting numbers will correspond. 

53. Nonhomogeneous coordinates. By comparing the corollaries 
of Theorem 1 with the definition of group (p. 66), it is at once 
seen that the set of points of a line on which a scale has been estab- 
lished, forms a group with respect to addition, provided the point & 
be excluded from the set. In this group J is the identity element, 
and the existence of an inverse for every element follows from 
Theorem 8. In the same way it is seen that the set of points on 
a line on which a scale has been established, and from which the 

* For the general idea of the isomorphism between groups, see Burnside's Theory 
of Groups, p. 22. 



03] COORDINATES 151 

point; !$> has been excluded, forms a group with respect to multipli- 
cation, except that no inverse with respect to multiplication exists 
for J^; J^ is the identity element in this group, and Theorem 9 insures 
the existence of an inverse for every point except J%. These con- 
siderations show that the first two conditions in the definition of a 
number system are satisfied by the points of a line, if the operations 
and o are identified with addition and multiplication as defined in 
48 and 49. The third condition in the definition of a number 
system is also satisfied in view of Theorem 6. Finally, in view of 
Theorem 1, Cor 4, and Theorem 6, this number system of points on 
a line is commutative with respect to both addition and multipli- 
cation This gives then: 

THEOREM 10 The set of all points on a line on which a scale lias 
"been established, and from which the point J is excluded, forms a field 
with respect to the operations of addition and multiplication previously 
defined. (A, E, P) 

This provides a new way of regarding a point, viz., that of regarding 
a point as a number of a number system This conception of a point 
will apply to any point of a line except the one chosen as &. It is 
desirable, however, both on account of the presence of such an excep- 
tional point and also for other reasons, to keep the notion of point 
distinct from the notion of number, at least nominally. This we do 
by introducing a field of numbers a, ft, c, > , 7, &, , as, y, z t - which 
is isomorphie with the field of points on a line. The numbers of the 
number field may, as we have seen, be the points of the line, or they 
may be mere symbols which combine according to the conditions 
specified m the definition of a number system ; or they may be ele- 
ments defined in some way in terms of points, lines, etc.* 

In any number system the identity element with, respect to addi- 
tion is called zero and denoted by 0, and the identity element with 
respect to multiplication is called one or unity, and is denoted by 1. 
We shall, moreover, denote the numbers 1+1, 1 + 1 + 1, , a, 
by the usual symbols 2, 3,. -, a, --.f In the isomorphism of our 
system of numbers with the set of points on a line, the point J must 
correspond to 0, the point J to the number 1; and, in general, to every 

* See, for example, 55, on von Staudt's algebra of throws, where the numbers 
are thought of as sets of four points. 

t Cf. however, in this connection 57 below, 



152 ALGHEBBA OF POINTS [CHAP VI 

point will correspond a number (except to J), and to every number 
of the field will correspond a point In tins way every point of tlie 
line (except j) is labeled by a number. This number is called the 
(nonliornogeneous) coordinate of the point, to which it corresponds. 
This enables us to express relations between points by means of 
equations between their coordinates The coordinates of points, or 
the points themselves when we think of them as numbers of a 
number system, we will denote by the small letters of the alphabet 
(or by numerals), and we shall frequently use the phrase "the point x" 
in place of the longer phrase " the point whose coordinate is x." It 
should be noted that this representation of the points of a line by 
numbers of a number system is not in any way dependent on the 
commutativity of multiplication ; i e. it holds in the general geom- 
etries for which Assumption P is not assumed. 

Before leaving the present discussion it seems desirable to point 
out that the algebra of points on a line is merely representative, 
under the principle of duality, of the algebra of the elements of any 
one-dimensional primitive form. Thus three lines , l v l n of a flat 
pencil determine a scale in the pencil of lines; and three planes 
a , a v a a of an axial pencil determine a scale in this pencil of planes ; 
to each corresponds the same algebra. 

54. The analytic expression for a projectivity in a one-dimensional 
primitive form. Let a scale be established on a line I by choosing 
three arbitrary points for P Q ,P^P a } and let the resulting field of points 
on a line be made isomorphic with a field of numbers 0, 1, a, , so 
that J corresponds to 0, P^ to 1, and, in general, P a to a. For the 
exceptional point P*, let us introduce a special symbol oo with excep- 
tional properties, which will be assigned to it as the need arises. 
It should be noted here, however, that this new symbol oo does not 
represent a number of a field as defined on p 149. 

We may now derive the analytic relation between the coordinates of 
the points on I, which expresses a protective correspondence between 
these points. Let x be the coordinate of any point of L We have seen 
that if the point whose coordinate is as is made to correspond to either 
of the points 

(I) a/ # + , (a^oo) 

or (II) x'-ax, 



54] LINEAR FRACTIONAL TRANSFORMATION 153 

where a is the coordinate of any given point on I, each of the result- 
ing correspondences is projective (Theorem 2 and Theorem 4). It is 
readily seen, moreover, that if x is made to correspond to 

(III) a/-i, 

the resulting correspondence is likewise projective. For we clearly 
have the following construction for the point l/.u (fig. 77} With the 
same notation as before for the construction of the product of two 




numbers, let the line scA meet /, in JT. If Y is determined as the 
intersection of IX with 1 0) the line BY determines on I a point #', 
such that scx'=l, by definition. We now have 

M. JL 



The three projectivities (I), (II), and (III) are of fundamental 
importance, as the next theorem will show. It is therefore desirable 
to consider their properties briefly ; we will thus be led to define the 
behavior of the exceptional symbol oo with respect to the operations 
of addition, subtraction, multiplication, and division. 

The projectivity x'~ go + a, from its definition, leaves the point J&, 
which we associated with oo, invariant. We therefore place oo -f a = oo 
for all values of a (a = oo). This projectivity, moreover, can have no 
other invariant point unless it leaves every point invariant ; for the 
equation x so + a gives at once a = 0, if $ = oo. Further, by prop- 
erly choosing a, any point on can be made to correspond to any point x f ; 



154 ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

but when one such pair of homologous points is assigned in addition 
to the double point oo, the projectivity is completely determined. 
The resultant or product of any two projectivities '=,'+ ami 
x l =x + b is clearly x' = x + (a-\- 6). Two such projectivities are 
therefore commutative. 

The projectrvity os 1 = ax, from its definition, leaves the points and co 
invariant, and by the fundamental theorem (Theorem 17, Chap IV) 
cannot leave any other point invariant without reducing to the iden- 
tical projectivity. As another property of the symbol co we have 
therefore co = a co (a = 0) Here, also, by properly choosing a, any 
point a? can be made to correspond to any point ai', but then the pro- 
jectivity is completely determined. The fundamental theorem in this 
case shows, moreover, that any projectivity with the double points 0, co 
can be represented by this equation The product of two projectivities 
x 1 = ax and x' = lx is clearly x' = (ab) ss, so that any two projectivities of 
this type are also commutative (Theorem 6). 

Finally, the projectivity x' l/x, by its definition, makes the 
point co correspond to and the point to oo. We are therefore led 
to assign to the symbol co the following further properties : ] /oo = 0, 
and 1/0 = co. This projectivity leaves 1 and 1 (denned as 1) 
invariant Moreover, it is an involution because the resultant of two 
applications of this projectivity is clearly the identity; i.e. if the 
projectivity is denoted by TT, it satisfies the relation, TT* =s 1. 

THEOREM 11. Any projectivity on a line is the product of projec- 
tivities of the three types (/), (//), and (III), and may "be expressed 
vn, the form 

(1) *-" + * 
v ' ax + d 

Conversely, every equation of this form represents a projectimty, if 
ad-bo^Q (A, E, P) 

Proof. We will prove the latter part of the theorem first. 1C wo 
suppose first that c ^ 0, we may write the equation of the given 
transformation in the form 

&-*? 

(2) a/ = ^+ V 
v c w + d 

This shows first that the determinant ad lc must be different from 
, otherwise the second term on the right of (3) would vanish, which 



54] LINEAR FRACTIONAL TRANSFORMATION 155 

would make every x correspond to the same point a/c, while a pro- 
jectivity is a one-to-one correspondence. Equation (3), moreover, 
shows at once that the correspondence established by it is the result- 
ant of the five : 



/7 ft< A / 

[O -- ) # 8 , of = x , -f 
\ c / 



Uc Q, and ad = 0, this argument is readily modified to show that 
the transformation of the theorem is the resultant of projectivities of 
the types (/) and (II). Since the resultant of any series of projectiv- 
ities is a projectivity, this proves the last part of the theorem. 

It remains to show that every projectivity can indeed be repre- 

sented by an equation s/ = To do this simply, it is desirable 



to determine first what point is made to correspond to the point oo by 
this projectivity. If we follow the course of this point through the 
five projectivities mto which we have j'ust resolved this transforma- 
tion, it is seen that the first two leave it invariant, the third trans- 
forms it into 0, the fourth leaves invariant, and the fifth transforms 
it into a/c ; the point oo is then transformed by (1) into the point 
a/c This leads us to attribute a further property to the symbol GO, 

viz, , , 

ax + o a 



x = GO. 
cx + d o 

According to the fundamental theorem (Theorem 17, Chap. IV), a pro- 
jectivity is completely determined when any three pairs of homolo- 
gous points are assigned. Suppose that in a given projectivity the 
points 0, 1, co are transformed into the points p, q, r respectively. 
Then the transformation 



clearly transforms into p t 1 into #, and, by virtue of the relation 
just developed for oo, it also transforms co into r. It is, moreover, of the 
form of (1) The determinant ad "be is in this case (# p) (r(i)(r p}, 
which is clearly different from zero, if p, q, r are all distinct. This 
transformation is therefore the given projectivity. 
COROLLARY 1, The projectivity so r *= a/x(a = 0, or oo) transforms 
oo and co into 0. (A, E, P) 



156 ALGEBBA OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

For it is the resultant of the two projectivities, a^-l/a and 
a'= ax of which the first interchanges and oo, while the second 
leaves them both invariant. We are therefore led to define the tymbok 
a/Q and a/cc as equal to oo and respectively, when a is neither 

nor oo 

COROLLARY 2. Any projectivity leaving the point oo invariant may 
le expressed in the form x' = ax + 1. (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 3 Any projectivity may le expressed analyticalli/ tyj 
the -bilinear equation cxx' + dx'-ax-l - 0; and conversely, any 
Ulmear equation defines a projective correspondence letwwn its two 
variables, provided adl>c=f= 0. (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 4 If a projectivity leaves any points invariant, the 
coordinates of these double points satisfy the quadratic equation 
cy ?j r (d-a)x-'b=Q. (A, E, P) 

DEFINITION. A system of mn numbers arranged in a rectangular 
array of m rows and n columns is called a matrix, if m s= n, it is 
called a square matrix of order n * 

The coefficients f a ^ j of the projective transformation (1) form a 

V / 

square matrix of the second order, which may bo conveniently used to 

denote the transformation Two matrices \ } , } and ( a , L } repre- 

yc (if \c a/ 

sent the same transformation, if and only if a : a' I ; I' s c : c' ~ d : d 1 . 
The product of two projectivities 



ax + 5 , 

aud so" ~ TT. 
cas + d 1 



is given by the equation 



This leads at once to the rule for the multiplication of matrices, 
which is similar to that for determinants. 
DEFINITION. The product of two matrices is defined by the equation 



fa' V\/a l\ faa' + cb 1 
\c' d')\c d) \ac r +cd' 



. the P 11110 ^ 1 Properties of 
r Algebra, pp. 20 ff. 



54,55] THBOWS 157 

Tins gives, in connection with the result just derived, 
THEOREM 12. The product of two projcctivities 



7T , , 

.c a 



is represented ly the product of their matrices , in symbols, 



COROLLARY 1. The determinant of the product of two projectivities 
is equal to the product of their determinants (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 2. The inverse of the projectivity TT = ( , ) is given 

\ G w 

"by vr" 1 = ( ~" ) = ( r> T) ) where A, B> C, D are the cof actors 

\ 6 a I \J5 JLs I 

\ / \ / -T 



of a, &, c, d respectively in the determinant 



c d 



(A,E,P) 



This follows at once from Corollary 3 of the last theorem by inter- 
changing a?, x' We may also verify the relation by forming the 

product 7r~V = ( T~ , , ), which transformation is equiva- 

/i \ \ ad ~ lc ' 

lent to ( n .j I The latter is called the identical matrix 

CPROLLARY 3. Any involution is represented ly ( a ), that is 

\6 ~ a I 
ax 4- 1) 
ly a/ = ~ , with the condition that a* + Ic =f= (A, E, P) 

Cw * ' Cfi 

55. Von Statidt's algebra of throws. We will now consider the 
number system of points on a line from a slightly different point of 
view On p. 60 we denned a throw as consisting of two ordered 
pairs of points on a line ; and denned two throws as equal when they 
are projective. The class of all throws which are projective (i.e; equal) 
to a given throw constitutes a class which we shall call a mark. 
Every throw determines one and only one mark, but each mark 
determines a whole class of throws. 

According to the fundamental theorem (Theorem 17, Chap. IV), if 
three elements A f J?, C? of a throw and their places in the symbol 
T(AB, CD) are given, the throw is completely determined by the 
mark to which it belongs. A given mark can be denoted by the 
symbol of any one of the (projective) throws which define it. We 
shall also denote marks by the small letters of the alphabet. And so, 
since the equality sign ( ) indicates that the two symbols between 



ALGEBKA OF POINTS [CHAr. VI 



which it stands denote the same thing, we may write T(AB t 
a = l if a, b, T(AB, CD) are notations for the same mark. Thus 
T(AB, OZ>)'=T(2L4, VC} = 7(CD, AB)=>T(I>C, J3A) are all symbols 
denoting the same mark (Theorem 2, Chap. III). 

According to the original definition of a throw the four elements 
which compose it must be distinct. The term is now to be extended 
to include the foUowing sets of two ordered pairs, where A, Jt, are 
distinct. The set of all throws of the type T (AB, CA) is called a 
mark and denoted by co; the set of all throws of the type T(AJ!, OB) 
is called a mark and is denoted by ; the set of all throws of the type 
T(AB, CO) is a mark and is denoted by 1. It is readily seen that 
if J, J?, J are any three points of a line, there exists for every point 
P of the line a unique throw T (Jg J, J? P) of the line; and con- 
versely, for every mark there is a unique point P. The mark co, by 
what precedes, corresponds to the point J; the mark to /% and 
the mark 1 to P. 

DEFINITION. Let T(AJ3, CXJ be a throw of the mark , and let 
T(AB, <7D 2 ) be a throw of the mark &; then, if Z> 8 is determined by 
Q(AD 1 B, AD Z D S ), the mark c of the throw T(A, CD 9 ) is called the 
sum of the marks a and 5, and is denoted by a + & ; in symbols, 
a + b = c. Also, the point D^ determined by Q(AI> i C } JSD^) deter- 
mines a mark with the symbol T(AjB, CD' 6 ) ** o f (say), which is called 
the product of the marks a and & ; in symbols, ab = c'. As to the 
marks and 1, to which these two definitions do not apply, we define 
further: a+0 = + a = a, a-0 = 0-a = 0, and a 1 a 1 . a a. 

Since any three distinct points A, J3, C may be projected into a fixed 
triple R, %, J, it follows that the operation of adding or multiplying 
marks may be performed on their representative throws of the form 
T(Z,P IIP). By reference to Theorems 1 and 3 it is then clear that 
the class of all marks on a line (except co) forms a number system, with 
respect to the operations of addition and multiplication just defined, 
which is isomorphic with the number system of points previously 
developed, 

This is, in brief, the method used by von Staudt to introduce ana- 
lytic methods into geometry on a purely geometric basis.* We have 



5M,Bfl] CROSS TUT 10 159 

given it here partly on account of its historical importance; partly 
because it gives a concrete example of a number system isomorphio 
with the points of a lino*; and partly because ifc gives a natural 
introduction to the fundamental concept of the cross ratio of four 
points. This we proceed to derive in the noxt section. 

56. The cross ratio. We have seen in the preceding section that 
it is possible to associate a number with every throw of four points 
on a line. By duality all the developments of tins section apply also 
to the other one-dimensional primitive forms, i.e. the pencil of lines 
and the pencil of planes. With every throw of four elements of any 
one-dimensional primitive form there may be associated a definite 
number, which must be the same for every throw projective with the 
first, and is therefore an invariant under any protective transforma- 
tion, i.e. a property oC the throw that is not changed when the throw 
is replaced by any protective throw This number is called the cross 
rutin of the throw. Jt is also called the double rtttw or the anhar- 
mtfiu'ft ratio. The reason for these names will appear presently. 

hi general, four given points yivG rise to si,u rffj/tirunt cross ratios. 
For the 24 possible permutations of the letters in the symbol 
T(AJi, CD} fall into sets of four which, by virtue of Theorem 2, 
Chap. JIT, have the same cross ratios. In the array below, the per- 
mutations in any line are projective with each other, two permuta- 
tions of different lines being in general not projective : 



AH, CD 


HA, 2)0 


DC, JL-L 


CD, AK 


AB, DG 


MA, CD 


CD, HA 


DC, AB 


AC, HD 


CA, DB 


DK, CA 


rw, AC 


AC, DJ* 


CA, IW 


IW, CA 


DB, AC 


AT), HC 


DA, CJi 


cj?, DA 


JiC, AD 


AD, Cli 


DA, BC 


BC, DA 


CH, AD 



If, however, the four points form a harmonic set H (AB, CD), the 
throws T(AB, CD) and T(AH, DC) are projective (Theorem 5, 
Cor. 2, Chap. IV) In this case the permutations in the first two rows 
of the array just given are all projective and hence have the same cross 
ratio, The four elements of a harmonic set, therefore, gim rise to only 
three cross ratios. The values of these cross ratios are readily seen 

* Ct 53. Here, with every point of a line on which a scale has been estab- 
lished, is associated a mark which, is the coordinate of the point. 



ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

to b e __ i l 2 respectively, for the constructions of our number 
system give at once H (Jg, J^PJ, H (J, 7>7?), and H (/;, />/.{). 

We now proceed to develop an analytic expression for the cross 
ratio B (xfa t x s x t ) of any four points on a line (or, in general, of any 
four elements of any one-dimensional primitive form) whoso coordi- 
nates in a given scale are given. It seems desirable to proewlo this 
derivation by an explicit definition of this cross ratio, which is inde- 
pendent of von Staudt's algebra of throws. 

DEFINITION. The cross ratio R (x^, -' a .r 4 ) of elements ;>\, ;>' s , >!.,, .'^ 
of any one-dimensional form is, if x i} sc v u\ arc dLstiiu-t, Llw coordi- 
nate X, of the element of the form into which a; 4 i,s tran Rftiriuod by 
the projectivity which transforms ss v x r a into co, 0, I re,spt3(5tivly ; 
le the number, X, defined by the projectivity ^j.,.'/',,,^ A ooOlX. If 
two of the elements x v x z , x 3 coincide and 4 is distinct from all of 
them, we define R (xjs z , xjsj as that one of $ (^,r 1( ,*y g ), Ijb (,/ 
sc,% ), $ (x.x si x n x,), for whicli the first three elements tiro 

""I 2/' ^^ \ 4 8' S 1' * 

THEOREM 13 IVie cross ratio "& (x^, x^ of the, four 
whose coordinates are respectively x v x z) x z> x is yircn 1>y the, mltttitm 

(A,E,P) ^"^ ^""^ 

Proof. The transformation 

jKj a? a3 g a? 

is evidently a projectivity, since it is reducible to the form of a 
linear fractional transformation, viz.. 



in which the determinant (x^ x^ (x z as,) (a? 8 ^) is not zoro, pro- 
vided the points % v x z) x s are distinct. This projectivity transforms 
ay ss 2 , x z into co, 0, 1 respectively. By definition, therefore, this pro- 
jectivity transforms 4 into the point whose coordinate is the cross 
ratio in question, i.e. into the expression given in the theorem. If 
a^ 2 , x s are not all distinct, replace the symbol B (0^, 8 a? 4 ) by one 
of its equal cross ratios B (x z x v a; A ), etc. ; on of these must have 
the first three elements of the symbol distinct, elnoe in a cross ratio 
of four points at least three must be distinct (d$f,). 



56] CROSS RATIO 161 

COROLLARY 1. We have in particular 
Tfr (x,x v x s x^ = oo, B (x^ z , x s x s ) = 0, and B (x^ t x a x s ) = 1, 

if x v x z , x 9 are any three distinct elements of the form. (A, E) 
COROLLARY 2. The cross ratio of a harmonic set H (x^, x a x t ) is 

B (a:^, x a x t ) = 1, for we have H (GO 0, 1 1) (A, E, P) 

COROLLARY 3 If B (x^, a? 8 oj 4 ) = X, tf/ie other Jive cross ratios of the 

throws composed of the four elements w v x a , x s , x are 

B (x^, a A) = ^ > ^ (0i4 ^a^a) = ~Y- 

$ (aj.-a:.. a;,,a3,) = 1 X. 
V * " 2 *' 



1a , ^ 

(A, E, P) 
The proof is left as an exercise. 

COROLLARY 4 If x v x^, x a , x^ form a harmonic set H (x^ x^x^, 
we have 

2 = ! + ! . 

i 1 i *v* ^y* .--i 'y 'v* . ___ o" 

Wo ^^ W- l4>a ^^ <**.* W/j ^^ bt*.| 

(A, E, P) 
The proof is left as an exercise. 

COROLLARY 5. If a, I, c are any three distinct elements of a one- 
dimensional primitive form, and a', &', c' are any three other distinct 
elements of the same form, tJien the correspondence established "by the 
relation Tfr (ab } ex) = B (a'&', c'x 1 ) is projective. (A, E, P) 

Proof. Analytically this relation gives 
a c "b x 



a x & o a'' b' - G' 

which, when expanded, evidently leads to a bilinear equation in 
the variables x, x', which defines a projective correspondence by 
Theorem 11, Cor. 3. 

That the cross ratio 

ffi i ~" ^a . x a_~~_ x $ 

1 "**** A S *""" *4 

is invariant under any projective transfoimation may also be verified directly 
by observing that each of the three types (I), (II), (III) of projectivities on 
pp. 152, 158 leaves it invariant That every projectivity leaves it invariant 
then follows from Theorem 11. 



162 ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

57. Coordinates in a net of rationality on a line. We now con- 
sider the numbers associated with the points of a net of rationality 
on a line. The connection between the developments of this chapter 
and the notion of a linear net of rationality is contained in tho 
following theorem : 

THEOREM 14 The coordinates of the points of the net of rationality 
R(j=>jj)/om a number system, or field, which consists of all numbers 
each of which can be obtained by a finite number of rational algebraic 
operations on and 1, and only these (A, E) 

Proof. By Theorem 14, Chap. IV, the linear net is a lino of the 
rational space constituted by the points of a three-dimensional not of 
rationality. By Theorem 20, Chap. IV, this three-diimmsional not in 
a properly projective space. Hence, by Theorem 10 of the present 
chapter, the numbers associated with R(Olco) form a field. 

All numbers obtainable from and 1 by the operations of addi- 
tion, subtraction, multiplication, and division are in R(Olco), bueanso 
(Theorem 9, Chap. IV) whenever x and y are in R (Olco) the, quadran- 
gular sets determining x + y, xy, % y, ly have live out of six 
elements in R(Oloo). On the other hand, every number of R(Oloo) 
can be obtained by a finite number of these operations. This follows 
from the fact that the harmonic conjugate of any point a in R(Olco) 
with respect to two others, b, c, can be obtained by a finite number 
of rational operations on a, b, c. This fact is a consequence of Theo- 
rem 13, Cor 2, which shows that sc is connected with a, b, c by the 

relation 

(x b)(a c) + (x c) (&) 0. 

Solving this equation for x, we have 

2 be - ab ao 

x ~- , > 

2a 5 o 

a number * which is clearly the result of a finite number of rational 
operations on a, 5, c. This completes the proof of the theorem. We 
have here the reason for the term net of rationality, 

It is well to recall at this point that our assumptions are not yet sufficient 
to identify the numbers associated with a net of rationality with the system 
of all ordinary rational numbers. We need only recall the example of the 
miniature geometry described in the Introduction, 2, which contained only 

* The expression for st cannot be indeterminate unless 6 s= c, 



57,58] HOMOGENEOUS CQOKDINATES 163 

three points on a line. If in that triple-system geometry wo perform the con- 
struction foi the number 1 + 1 on any line in which we have assigned the 
numbeis 0, 1, oo to the thiee points of the hue in any way, it will be found 
that this consti uction yields the point Thit> is due to the fact previously 
noted that in that geometiy the diagonal points of a complete quadi angle 
are collmeai In every geometry to which Assumptions A, E, P apply we 
may constiuct the points 1 + 1,1 + 1 + 1,, , thus foiimng a sequence of 
points which, with the usual notation foi these sums, we may denote by 0, 1, 
2, 3, 4, . Two possibilities then present themselves, either the points 
thus obtained aie all distinct, in which case the net R (Olw) contains all the 
ordinary lational numbers ; or some point of this sequence coincides with one 
of the pieceding points of the sequence, in which case the numbei of points 
in a net of lationality is finite. We shall consider this situation in detail in 
a later chaptei, and will then add furthei assumptions Here it should be 
emphasized that our lesults hitheito, and all subsequent results depending only 
on Assumptions A, E, P, are valid not only in the ordmaiy real or complex 
geometries, but in a much more general class of spaces, which are chaiacter- 
ized meiely by the fact that the coordinates of the points on a line are the 
numbers of a field, finite or infinite. 

58. Homogeneous coordinates on a line. The exceptional character 
of the point ., as the coordinate of which we introduced a symbol 
ao with exceptional properties, often proves troublesome, and is, more- 
over, contrary to the spirit of projective geometry in which the points 
of a line are all equivalent ; indeed, the choice of the point R was 
entirely arbitrary. It is exceptional only in its relation to the opera- 
tions of addition, multiphcation, etc., which we have denned in terms 
of it. In this section we will describe another method of denoting 
points on a line by numbers, whereby it is not necessary to use any 
exceptional symbol 

As before, let a scale be established on a line by choosing any thret 
points to be the points J, J, J ; and let each point of the line be 
denoted by its (nonhomogeneous) coordinate in a number system 
isomorphic with the points of the line. We will now associate with 
every point a pair of numbers (x v # a ) of this system in a given order, 
such that if x is the (nonhomogeneous) coordinate of any point dis- 
tinct from J&, the pair (x v C 2 ) associated with the point on satisfies the 
relation x Jx y With the point J we associate any pair of the 
form (k, 0), where Tc is any number (Jc 3= 0) of the number system 
isomorphic with the line To every point of the line corresponds a pair 
of numbers, and to every pair of numbers in the field, except the pair 



ALGEBRA OF POINTS [OHAP.VI 

(0, 0), corresponds a unique point of the line. These two numbers are 
called homogeneous coordinates of the point with which they are 
associated, and the pair of numbers is said to represent the point 
This representation of points on a line by pairs of numbers is not 
unique, since only the ratio of the two coordinates is determined; 
le. the pairs (x v x z ) and (mx v mx z ) represent the same point for all 
values of m different from The point J is characterized by the 
fact that X T ; the point J& by the fact that # 2 = ; and the point 
J;* by the fact that a^ = x z . 

THEOREM 15. In homogeneous coordinates a projectimty on a line is 
represented ly a linear homogeneous transformation in two variables, 

m P x>=ax,+ lx z , (ad-lo+Q) 

v ' pa% == cx^ + dx 2 , 

where p is an arbitrary factor of proportionality. (A, E, P) 
Proof. By division, this clearly leads to the transformation 

(2) r - fla + ^' 

w ex + d 

provided a? 2 ' and x z are both different from 0. If a3 a = 0, the trans- 
formation (1) gives the point (#/, x) = (a, c) ; i e. the point ^ = 
(1, 0) is transformed by (1) into the point whose nonhomogeneous 
coordinate is a/c And if C 2 '=0, we have in (1) ( v % a )~(d, c); 
ie (1) transforms the point whose nonhomogeneous coordinate is 
d/c into the point JS. By reference to Theorem 11 the validity 
of the theorem is therefore established. 

( 7i\ 
, J of the coefficients may conveniently 

be used to represent the projectivity The double points of the pro- 
jectivity, if existent, are obtained in homogeneous coordinates as 
follows : The coordinates of a double point (x v se s ) must satisfy the 
equations x 



These equations are compatible only if the determinant of the system 



vanishes. This leads to the equation 



a p 
G 



HOMOGENEOUS COOEDI1TATES 



165 



for the determination of the factor of proportionality p. This equa- 
tion is called the characteristic equation of the matrix representing 
the projectivity. Every value of p satisfying this equation then leads 
to a double point when substituted in one of the equations (3) ; viz , 
if p v be a solution of the characteristic equation, the point 

(x v x z ) = (-&,- Pl ) = (d- Pi> - c) 
is a double point.* 

In homogeneous coordinates the cross ratio 1^(AB, CD) of four 
points A = (a v a a ), B = (& & 3 ), C = (c v c 2 ), D = (d v dj is given by 

(ae) m (be) 



where the expressions (ac), etc, are used as abbreviations for a^a^, 
etc This statement is readily verified by writing down the above 
ratio in terms of the nonhomogeneous coordinates of the four points 
We will close this section by giving to the two homogeneous coor- 
dinates of a point on a line an explicit geometrical significance. In 
view of the fact that the coordinates of such a point are not uniquely 
determined, a factor of proportionality being entirely arbitrary, there 
may be many such interpretations. On account of the existence of 
this arbitrary factor, we may impose a further condition on the coor- 
dinates (x v x s ) of a point, in addition to the defining relation x l /x 2 =x, 
where x is the nonhomogeneous coordinate of the pomt in question. 
We choose the relation a, + = 1 If this relation is satisfied, 



1 -1 

1 

1 -1 




1 
1 


1 


1 -1 

1 

1 -1 


- 


1 
1 


1 



loo, 



Thus homogeneous coordinates subject to the condition x^ + x^ I 
can be defined by choosing three points A, B, arbitrarily, and letting 
jCj, = B (AB, CZ) and 03 2 = B (AC, J?-3T) The ordinary homogeneous 
coordinates would then be defined as any two numbers proportional 
to these two cross ratios. 

* This point is indeterminate only if 6 = c = and. a = d The projeotwty as 
then the identity. 



ALGEBRA OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

59. Projective correspondence between the points of two different 
lines. Hitherto we have confined ourselves, in the development of 
analytic methods, to the points of a single line, or, under duality, to 
the elements of a single one-dimeusioual primitive form. Suppose 
now that we have two lines I and m with a scale on each, and let 
the nonhomogeneous coordinate of any point of I be represented by 
os, and that of any point of m by y The question then arises as to 
how a projective correspondence between the point 02 and the point y 
may be expressed analytically. It is necessary, first of all, to givo a 
meaning to the equation y x. In other words : What is meant by say- 
ing that two points # on I, and y on m have the same coordinate ? 
The coordinate a? is a number of a field and corresponds to the point 
of which it is the coordinate in an isomorphism of this field with the 
field of points on the line I. "We may think of this same field of 
numbers as isomorphic with the field of points on the line m. In 
bringing about this isomorphism nothing has been specified except 
that the fundamental points J%, J%, JS, determining the scale on m 
must correspond to the numbers 0, 1 and the symbol oo respectively. 
If the correspondence between the points of the line and the numbers 
of the field were entirely determined by the respective correspond- 
ences of the pomts J, J, J just mentioned, then we should Icnow 
precisely what points on the two lines I and m have the same coor- 
dinates. It is not true of all fields, however, that this correspondence 
is uniquely determined when the points corresponding to 0, 1, oo are 
assigned.* It is necessary, therefore, to specify more definitely how 
the isomorphism between the points of m and the numbers of the 
field is brought about. One way to bring it about is to make uses of 
the projectivity which carries the fundamental points 0, 1, co of I 
into the fundamental points 0, 1, oo of m, and to assign tlio coordinate 
a; of any point A of I to that point of m into which A is transformed 
by this projectivity. In this projectivity pairs of homologous points 
will then have the same coordinates. That the field of points and the 
field of numbers are indeed made isomorphw by this process follows 
directly from Theorems 1 and 3 in connection with Theorem 1, Cor., 
Chap. IY. We may now readily prove the following theorem : 

* This is shown by the fact that the field of all ordinary complex numbers can 
DO isomorphic with itself not only by mafcmg each number correspond to itself, but 
also by making each number a + ib correspond to its conjugate a - #>. 



69] EXEECISES 167 

THEOEEM 16. Any protective correspondence /between the points [x~\ 
and [y] of two distinct hnes may le represented analytically l>y the 
relation y = x ly properly choosing the coordinates on the two lines 
Jf the coordinates on the two hnes are so related that the relation 
y = x represents a projective correspondence, then any projective cor- 
respondence "between the points of the two lines is given ly a relation 

ax+l , ., , m 

y = ' > (ad oc3= 0). 

y cx + d v ' 

(A, E, P) 

Proof. The first part of the theorem follows at once from the pre- 
ceding discussion, since any projectivity is determined Tby three pairs 
of homologous points, and any three points of either line may be 
chosen for the fundamental points. In fact, we may represent any 
projectivity between the points of the two lines by the relation y = x } 
by choosing the fundamental points on I arbitrarily; the fundamental 
points on m are then uniquely determined. To prove the second part 
of the theorem, let IT be any given projective transformation of the 
points of the line I into those of m, and let TT O be the projectivity 
y = x, regarded as a transformation from m to I. The resultant 
7r 7r = 7r x is a proj'ectivity on /, and may therefore be represented by 
x' = (ax + 1) /(ex + d] Since TT = w ~ 1 '7r 1 , this gives readily the result 
that TT may be represented by the relation given in the theorem 

EXERCISES 

1. Give constructions for subtraction and division in the algebra of points 
on a line. 

2. Give consti uctions for the sum and the pioduct of two lines of a pencil 
of lines in which a scale has been established. 

3 Develop the point algelna on a line by using the properties expressed in 
Theorems 2 and 4 as the definitions of addition and multiplication respec- 
tively. Is it necessary to use Assumption P from the beginning ? 

4. Using Cor 3 of Theorem 9, Chap III, show that addition and multi- 
plication may be defined as follows . As before, choose three points P , P x , 
PW on a line Z as fundamental points, and let any line through P be labeled 
Z,. Then the sum of two numbers P a and P y is the point P x + y into which P v 
is transformed by the elation with axis Z, and center P w which transforms 
P into P,,.; and the product P x P v is the point P w into which P y is trans- 
formed by the homology with axis Z w and center P which transforms P x into 
PX. Develop the point algebra on this basis without using Assumption P, 
except in the proof of the commutativity of multiplication. 



168 ALGEBRA. OF POINTS [CHAP. VI 

5 If the relation ax = ly holds between four points a, &, x, y of a lino, 
show that we have Q(Qba, coyr). Is Assumption P necessary for this losult 1 ? 

6 Piove by duect computation that the expiession l~ x & ?.'g "", >' liS 

*i-J4 x s -J>i 
unchanged in value when the foui points x lt x z , x s , x are subjected to any 

linear fractional transformation x r ? x - - 

ex + a 

7. Prove that the transformations 

\t \ V w -I i \t 1 \/ A, .., X 1 

A A, A i A = 1 A, A = > A = r > A = 

A 1 A A -~ Z X 

form a group. What aie the periods of the vanous transformations of tins 
group? (Cf Theorem 13, Cor, 3.) 

8. If A, B, C, P v P z , , P n are any n + B points of a line, show that 
every cross latio of any four of these points can be expressed rationally in 
terms of the n cross ratios \= ft (AB, CP { ), = 1,2, , n. When n = 1 
this reduces to Theoiem 13, Cor. 3. Discuss m detail the case n = 2, 

9. If T% (XjX z , x s x) = X, show that 

1-X _ 1 X__ 

a; 8 a, 4 a; 3 x z x s x^ 
The relation of Coi. 3 of Theoiem 13 is a special case of this relation. 

10. Show that if B (AB, CD) = ft (AS, DC), the points fonn a harmonic 
set H (AB, CD) 

11. If the cioss ratio R (A B, CD) - X satisfies the equation X 2 - X + 1 = 0, 
then $ (AB, CD) = T&(AC, DD) = TJ (AD, J3C) = X, 

and $ (AB, DC) = $ (A C, BD) = # (.4 D, CU) = - X a . 

12. If A, B, X, Y, Z are any five distinct points oil a line, show that 

B (AB, XY) B (AB, TZ) U (AB, ZX) = 1. 

13. State the eorollaues of Theorem 11 lu homogeneous coordinates. 

14. By direct computation show that the two methods of determining the 
double points of a projectivity described in 54 and 58 arc equivalent 

15 If Q(ABC,XYZ),ibsa. 

B (AX, YC) + T* (BY, ZA) + # (CZ, X7i) , 1. 

16. If M v J/ 2J M t are any thiee points in the plane of a line / but, not on 
/, thecross ratios of the lines I, PM PM Z , PM a aro dlilmMil for ay two 
points P on / ^ 

17. If A, B are any two fixed points on a line Z, and A", F are two variable 

that B (AB, XY) is constant, the set m to prc,jcti ve with tha 



CHAPTER VII 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS IN TWO- AND THREE-DIMENSIONAL* 

FORMS 

60. Nonhomogeneous coordinates in a plane. In order to repre- 
sent the points and lines of a plane analytically we proceed as follows : 
Choose any two distinct lines of the plane, which we will call the 
axes of coordinates, and determine on each a scale ( 48) arbitrarily, 
except that the point of intersection of the lines shall he the 
0-pomt on each scale (fig. 78). This point we call the origin Denote 
the fundamental 
points on one of 
the lines, which 
we call the x-axis, 
kyO,, 1, GO,; and 
on the other line, 
which we will call 
the y-axis t by O y , 
l v , co y . Let the 
line cOjjOOj, be de- 
noted by /. 

Now let P be any point in the plane not on Z. Let the lines Poo 9 
and Poo.,, meet the re-axis and the ^-axis m points whose nonhomoge- 
neous coordinates are a and 5 respectively, in the scales just estab- 
lished The two numbers a, 1 uniquely determine and are uniquely 
determined by the point P. Thus every point in the plane not on l n 
is represented by a pair of numbers ; and, conversely, every pair of 
numbers of which one belongs to the scale on the oj-axis and the 
other to the scale on the y-axis determines a point in the plane (the 
pair of symbols GO,., oo y being excluded). The exceptional character 
of the points on I* will be removed presently ( 63) by considera- 
tions similar to those used to remove the exceptional character of 

*A11 the developments of this chapter are on the basis of Assumptions 
A,E,P. 

169 




78 



170 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP vn 

the point co in the case of the analytic treatment of the points of a 
line ( 58) The two numbers just described, determining the point 
P, are called the nonhomogeneoiis coordinates of P with reference to 




FIG 79 

the two scales on the so- and the 2/-axes. The point P is then repre- 
sented analytically by the symbol (a, 6). The number a is called the 
x-Goordinate or the abscissa of the point, and is always written first 
in the symbol representing the point; the number Z> is called the 
y-coordinate or the ordinate of the point, and is always written last 
in this symbol. 

The plane dual of the process just described leads to the corre- 
sponding analytic representation of a line in the plane. For this pur- 
pose, choose any two distinct points in the plane, which we will call 
the centers of coordinates; and in each of the pencils of lines with 
these centers determine a scale arbitrarily, except that the line o join- 
ing the two points shall be the 0-line in each scale. This line we call 
the origin. Denote the fundamental lines on one of the points, which 
we will call the u-center, by O tt , !, oo tt ; and on the other point, which 
we will call the it-center, by 0,,, !, QO B . Let the point of intersection 
of the lines oo tt , oo be denoted by R> (fig. 79). 

Now let I be any lin in the plane not on J. Let the points Zoo,, 
and l<x> v be on the lines of the ^-center and the 0-center, whose non- 
homogeneous coordinates are m and n respectively in the scales just 
established. The two numbers m, n uniquely determine and are 
uniquely determined by the line I. Thus every line in the plane not 
on . is represented by a pair of numbers ; and, conversely, every pair 
of numbers of which one belongs to the scale on the ^-center and the 
other to the scale on the v-center determines a line in the plane (the 
parr of symbols co w , co tf being excluded). The exceptional character 



CO, 61] 



COUEDINATES IN A PLANE 



171 



of the lines on & will also be removed presently. The two numbers 
just described, determining the line /, are called the norihomogeneous 
coordinates of I with reference to the two scales on the u- and 
^-centers. The line I is then represented analytically by the symbol 
[m, ri]. The number m is called the u-coordinate of the line, and is 
always written first in the symbol just given ; the number n is called 
the v-coordviiate of the line, and is always written second in this 
symbol. A variable point of the plane will frequently be represented 
by the symbol (x, y) ; a variable line by the symbol [u, v~\. The coor- 
dinates of a point referred to two axes are called point coordinates , 
the coordinates of a line referred to two centers are called line coor- 
dinates. The line l n and the point J are called the singular line and 
the singular point respectively. 

61. Simultaneous point and line coordinates. In developing further 
our analytic methods we must agree upon a convenient relation 
between the axes and centers of the point and line coordinates respec- 
tively. Let us consider any triangle in the plane, say with vertices 




JIG. 80 



0, U", V. Let the lines OU and OF be the y- and #-axes respectively, 
and in establishing the scales on these axes let the points U, V be 
the points <, oo,,, respectively (fig. 80). Further, let the points V, V 
be the 'it-center and the ^-center respectively, and in establishing the 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP VH 

scales on these centers let the lines UO, VO be the lines co tt , co u 
respectively. The scales are now established except for the choice of 
the 1 points or lines in each scale. Let us choose arbitrarily a point 
1. on the 0-axis and a point 1, on the y-axis (distinct, of course, from 
the points 0, V, F). The scales on the axes now being determined, 
we determine the scales on the centers as follows : Let the line on 
U and the point - 1, on the a;-axis be the line l w ; and let the lino 
on V and the point l g on the y-axis be the line !. All the scales 
are now fixed. Let nr be the projectivity ( 59, Chap. VI) between 
the points of the cc-axis and the lines of the it-center in "which points 
and lines correspond when their so- and w-codrdinates respectively 
are the same. If IT' is the perspectivity in which every line on the 
w-center corresponds to the point in which it meets the a-axis, the 
product TT'TT transforms the #-axis into itself and interchanges and 
co.,., and 1. and 1^ Hence TT'TT is the involution x' 1/ai Hence 
it follows that the line on U whose coordinate is u is on the point of 
the 3B-aocis whose coordinate is 1/u; and the point on the x-axfa 
whose coordinate is x is on the line of the it-center whose coordinate 
is 1/sB. This is the relation between the scales on the awixis and 
the w-center. 

Similar considerations with reference to the y-axis and the *-center 
lead to the corresponding result in this case : The line on V whose coor- 
dinate is v is on that point of the y-as&is whose coordinate is -~l/v; 
and the point of the y-axis whose coordinate is y is on that line of the 
^-center whose coordinate is l/i/. 

62. Condition that a point be on a line. Suppose that, referred to 
a system of point-and-line coordinates described above, a point P has 
coordinates (a, V) and a line I has coordinates [m, ri\. The condition 
that P be on I is now readily obtainable. Let \is suppose, first, that 
none of the coordinates a, 6, m, n are zero. We may proceed in either 
one of two dual ways. Adopting one of these, we know from the 
results of the preceding section that the line [m, n\ meets the #-axis 
in a point whose ^coordinate is 1/wi, and meets the y-axia in a 
point whose y-coordinate is 1/n (fig 81). Also, by definition, the 
line joining P = (a, 5) to U meets the aj-axis in a point whose #-eob*r~ 
dinate is a ; and the line joining P to V meets the y-axis in a point 
whose y-coordinate is & If P is on l t we clearly have the following 
perspectivity : 



62] 
(1) 

Hence we have 
(2) 



COORDINATES IN A PLANE 



173 



- l -o, 

m 



i 0,oo A 

n y / 



which, when expanded (Theorem 13, Chap. VI), gives for the desired 
condition 

(3) ma, + rib + 1 = 0. 

This condition has been shown to be necessary. It is also sufficient, 
for, if it is satisfied, relation (2) must hold, and hence would follow 
(Theorem 13, Cor. 5, Chap. VI) 

Oaca x -r- Ooo 6. 

m A n 

But since this projectivity has the self-c'orrespondmg element O, it 
is a perspectivity which leads to relation (1). But this implies that 
P is on L 




81 



If now a = (b 3* 0), we have at once 5 = 1/n ; and if 6 = (a =5*= 0), 
we have likewise a = 1/m for the condition that P be on I But 
each of 'these relations is equivalent to (3) when = and 6=0 
respectively. The combination a, = 0, 6 = gives the origin wliich. 
is never on a line [m, n] where m 3= GO ^ n It follows in the same 
way directly from the definition that relation (3) gives the desired 
condition, if we have either m or n = 0. The condition (3) is 
then valid for all cases, and we have 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP.VII 

THEOREM 1 The necessary and sufficient condition that a point 
P = (a, 1) le on a line I = [m, n] is that the relation ma + nb + 1 = 
be satisfied. 

DEFINITION. The equation DEFINITION. The equation 
which is satisfied by the coordi- which is satisfied by the coordi- 
nates of aU the points on a given nates of all the lines on a given 
line and no others is called the point and no others is called the 
point equation of the line. line equation of the point. 

COROLLARY 1. The point equa- OOHOLLAIIY 1'. The line equa- 
tion of the line [m, n] is tion of the point (a, 5) is 



EXERCISE 
Derive the condition of Theoiem 1 by dualizing the proof given. 

63. Homogeneous coordinates in the plane. In the analytic repre- 
sentation of points and lines developed m the preceding sections the 
points on the line TJV o and the lines on the point were left 
unconsidered. To remove the exceptional character of these points 
and lines, we may recall that in the case of a similar problem in the 
analytic representation of the elements of a one-dimensional form we 
found it convenient to replace the iionhomogeneous coordinate x of 
a point on a line by a pair of numbers x v # 2 whose ratio $j/K 2 was 
equal to x(x = eo), and such that a? a = when x = co. 

A similar system of homogeneous coordinates can be established for 
the plane. Denote the vertices 0, U, V of any triangle, which we will 
call the triangle of reference, by the " coordinates " (0, 0, 1), (0, ] , 0), 
(1, 0, 0) respectively, and an arbitrary point T t not on a side of tho 
triangle of reference, by (1, 1, 1). The complete quadrangle QUVT 
is called the/rame of reference* of the system of coordinates to bo 
established The three lines UT, VT, OT meet the other sides of the 
triangle of reference in points which we denote by 3 e (I, 0, 1), 
l tf = (0, 1, 1), !,=(!, 1, 0) respectively (fig. 82). 

We will now show how it is possible to denote every point in the 
plane by a set of coordinates (x v a? a , :). Observe first that wo have 
thus far determined three points on each of the sides of the triangle 

* Frame of reference is a general term that may be applied to the fundamental 
elements of any coordinate system 



63] HOMOGENEOUS COORDINATES 175 

of reference, viz.. (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 1), (0, 1, 0) on OU; (0, 0, 1), (1, 0, 1), 
(1, 0, 0) on 07; and (0, 1, 0), (1, 1, 0), (1, 0, 0) on UV. The coordi- 
nates which we have assigned to these points are all of the form 
(x v # 2 , 8 ). The three points on OU are characterized by the fact that 
#! = 0. Fixing attention on the remaining coordinates, we choose the 
points (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 1), (0, 1, 0) as the fundamental points (0, 1), 
(1, 1), (1, 0) of a system of homogeneous coordinates on the line OU. 
If in this system a point has coordinates (I, m), we denote it in our 
planar system by (0, 1, m). In like manner, to the points of the other 
two sides of the triangle of reference may be assigned coordinates of 
the form (7c, 0, m) and (Is, I, 0) respectively. We have thus assigned 
coordinates of the form (x lf x 2> ss 3 ) to all the points of the sides of the 
triangle of reference. Moreover, the coordinates of every point on 
these sides satisfy one of the three relations x : = 0, x s = 0, x 8 = 0. 

Now let P be any point in the plane not on a side of the triangle 
of reference. P is uniquely determined if the coordinates of its pro- 
jections from any two of the vertices of the triangle of reference on 
the opposite sides are known Let its projections from U and V on 
the sides V and U be (k, 0, n) and (0, I', n') respectively. Since 
under the hypothesis none of the numbers k, n, I', n' is zero, it is 
clearly possible to choose three numbers (ss v x z , x s ) such that aj x : x a 
= k:n, and x z : x z = I' . n' We may then denote P by the coordinates 
(ac v J 2 , x s ). To make this system of coordinates effective, however, 
we must show that the same set of three numbers (x,. x., x.) can be 

J,* & o/ 

obtained by projecting P on any other pair of sides of the triangle 
of reference In other words, we must show that the projection of 
P = (x v a? 2 , x a ) from on the line UV is the point (% v x z , 0). Since 
this is clearly true of the point ^ = (1, 1, 1), we assume P distinct 
from T. Since the numbers x v x a , x 9 are all different from 0, let us 
place xs 1 :x^ = x, and x^:x & = y, so that x and y are the nonhomoge- 
neous coordinates of (x v 0, x s ) and (0, (c a , B 8 ) respectively in the scales 
on 0V and OU defined by = 0, !, F co,, and = O y , l y , U= oo t . 
Finally, let OP meet UV in the point whose nonhomogeneous coor- 
dinate in the scale defined by Z7= O e , 1 B , V=s oq, is g; and let OP 
meet the line 1J7 in A. We now have 

V 

co 1 g = 1 TA = en 1 H. 

* * A * A 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAI>.VII 

where C is the point in which VA meets OU. This projectivity 
between the hnes UV and OU transforms 3 into , oo 8 into 0,,, and 
l z into 1 . It follows that C has the coordinate 1/s in the scale on 
U. We have also ^ 



,, f 

which gives . 

, = B KO,, Itf - ( ,0,, - y\ - *?/- 
\ U/ 

Substituting x = OL : a? 8 , and y = a a : OJ B , this tfivoa tlio dcvsirod rolation 
2 = c a. The results of this discussion may l>e summarised as 

1 * 

follows : 




FIG. 82 



THEOREM 2. DEFHSTITION. If P is any point not on a side of the 
triangle of reference OUT, there exist three numbers x v # a , cc 8 (all dif- 
ferent from 0) such that the projections of P from the wrtiees 0, V, 
V on the opposite sides have coordinates (x^ z) 0), (as v 0, ,'W B ), (0, J a , <r 8 ) 
respectively. These three numbers we catted the homogeneous coordi- 
nates of P, and P is denoted ly (x v 03 2 , B ). Any set of three numbers 
(not all equal to 0) determine uniguely a point whose (homogeneous) 
coordinates they are. 

The truth of the last sentence in the above theorem follows from 
the fact that, if one of the coordinates is 0, they determine uniquely 
a point on one of the sides of the triangle of reference ; whereas, if 
none is equal to 0, the lines joining U to (to v 0, a s ) and V to (0, ai a> a$ 
meet in a point whose coordinates by the reasoning above are (^aj^a?,), 



63] HOMOGENEOUS COORDINATES 177 

COROLLARY. The coordinates (x lt x z , # 8 ) and (Jcx i} kx z , k% 8 ) determine 
the same point, if k is not 

Homogeneous line coordinates arise by dualizing the above discus- 
sion in the plane. Thus we choose any quadrilateral in the plane as 
frame of reference, denoting the sides by [1, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 1], 
[1, 1, 1] respectively. The points of intersection with [1, 1, 1] of the 
lines [1, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 1] are joined to the vertices of the tri- 
angle of reference opposite to [1, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 1] respectively 
by lines that are denoted by [0, 1, 1], [1, 0, 1], [1, 1, 0]. The three 
lines [1, 0, 0], [1, 1, 0], [0, 1, 0] are then taken as the fundamental 
lines [1, 0], [1, 1], [0, 1] of a homogeneous system of coordinates in 
a flat pencil If in this system a line is denoted by \u v u z ], it is 
denoted in the planar system by \u v u z , 0] In like manner, to the 
lines on the other vertices are assigned coordinates of the forms 
[0, u & , u s ] and [u v 0, u s ~\ respectively As the plane dual of the 
theorem and definition above we then have at once 

THEOREM 2'. DEFINITION. If I is any line not on a vertex of tJie 
triangle of reference, there exist three numbers u v u z , u & all different 
from zero, such that the traces of I on the three sides of the triangle of 
reference are projected from the respective opposite vertices ly the lines 
[u v u z) 0], [u v 0, u a ], [0, u s , u a ]. These three numbers are called the 
homogeneous coordinates of I, and I is denoted by \u v u a , u a ]. Any 
set of three numbers (not all zero} determine uniquely a line whose 
coordinates they are. 

Homogeneous point and hue coordinates may be put into such 
a relation that the condition that a point (x v o? 2 , % s ) be on a line 
[u v u z , u s ] is that the relation u^ + w 2 03 3 + u s x s =* be satisfied. We 
have seen that if (x v x z , x s ) is a point not on a side of the triangle of 
reference, and we place x = xjx z , and y = x z /ac z , the numbers (x, y) 
are the nonhomogeneous coordinates of the point (x v x z , x s ) referred 
to OF as the a-axis and to OU as the y-axis of a system of nonho- 
mogeneous coordinates in which the point T=(l, 1, 1) is the point 
(1, 1) (0, V", V being used in the same significance as in the proof of 
Theorem 2). By duality, if [u v u a> u a ] is any line not on any vertex 
of the triangle of reference, and we place u = uju^ and v = u z /u 9 , 
the numbers [u, v} are the nonhomogeneous coordinates of the line 
u u a , % referred to two of the vertices of the triangle of reference 



178 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS 



[('HAP. VII 



as Z7-center and F-center respectively, and in which the line [1, 1, 1] 
is the line [1, 1] It now, we superpose these two systems of nonhom- 
ogeneous coordinates m the way described in the preceding section, 
the condition 'that the point (x, y) be on the line [u, v] is that the 
relation use + vy + 1 == be satisfied (Theorem 1). It is now easy to 
recognize the resulting relation between the systems of homogeneous 
coordinates with which we started. Clearly the point (0, 1, 0) = U w 
the Z7-center, (1, 0, 0) = V is the F-center, and (0, 0, 1) => is the third 




. 88 



vertex of the triangle of reference in the homogeneous system of line 
coordinates Also the line whose points satisfy the relation x^ is 
the line [1, 0, 0], the line for which x a = is the line [0, 1, 0], and 
the line for which x z = is the line [0, 0, 1]. Finally, the line 
[1, 1] = [1, 1, 1], whose equation in nonhomogeneous coordinates is 
+ y + 1 = 0, meets the line o^ = in the point (0, 1, 1), and the 
line 2 *= in the point ( 1, 0, 1). The two coordinate systems are 
then completely determined (fig. 83). 

It now follows at once from the 'result of tlie preceding section 
that the condition that (x v os s) aj s ) be, j>n ,the,Kne [it ^, J t is 
+ 8 a? 8 0, if none pf 



1 7 $. 



cs] HOMOGENEOUS COORDINATES 179 

is zero. To see that the same condition holds also when one (or more) 
of the coordinates is zero, we note lirst that the points (0, 1^ ij 
( 1, 0, 1), and ( 1, 1, 0) are collmear. They are, in fact (fig 83), on 
the axis of perspectivity of the two perspective triangles OUV and 
la-lj,!^ the center of perspectivity being T. It is now clear that 

the line [1, 0, 0] passes through the point (0, 1, 0), 
the line [0, 1, 0] passes through, the point (1, 0, 0), 
the line [1, 1, 0] passes through the point ( 1, 1, 0). 

There is thus an involution between the points (x v x z , 0) of the line 
x a = and the traces (a/, a?/, 0) of the lines with the same coordinates, 
and this involution is given by the equations 



In other words, the line [u v 2 , 0] passes through the point (~u z , u lf 0). 
Any other point of this line (except (0, 0, 1)) has, by definition, the 
coordinates ( w 2 , u v x & ) Hence all points (x v sc z , # 8 ) of the line 
[u v 2 , 0] satisfy the relation u^ + u z ss 2 + u a x s = 0. The same argu- 
ment applied when any one of the other coordinates is zero estab- 
lishes this condition for all cases. A system of point and a system 
of line coordinates, when placed in the relation described above, -will 
be said to form a system of homogeneous point and line coordinates in 
the plane. The result obtained may then be stated as follows . 

THEOREM 3. In a system of homogeneous point and line coordinates 
in a plane the necessary and sufficient condition that a point (x v x z> OJ 3 ) 
le on a line [u v w a , u a ] is that the relation u^ + u^x a + u s x a = O fe 
satisfied 

COROLLARY. The equation of a line through the origin of a system, 
of nonliomogeneous coordinates is of the form mx + ny 0. 

EXERCISES 

1 The line [1, 1, 1] is the polar of the point (1,1, 1) with regard to the 
triangle of reference (cf . p. 46) 

2. The same point is repiesented by (a x , a 2 , a 8 ) and (l v & 2 , 6 g ) if and. only 

if the two-rowed determinants of the matrix /?* 2 J 8 \ are all zero 



3 Describe nonhomogeneous and homogeneous systems of line and plane 
coordinates in a bundle by dualizing in space the preceding discussion. In 
such a bundle what is the condition that a line be on a plane ? 



lgo 



COOBDINATE SYSTEMS 



64. The line on two points. The point on two lines. Given two 
points, A = (a v a,, 8 ) and 3 = (6 V \, \), the question now arises as 
to what are the coordinates of the line joining them; and the dual 
of this problem, namely, given two lines, m = [m v m v m s ] and n - 
\n,n , J to fc"* tne coordinates * the P 0111 *' ^ in tersection of the 
two lines. 

THEOEEM 4. The equation of THEOREM 4'. The equation of 
the line joining the points (a^a^) the point of intersection of the 
and (b v l z , & a ) is IMM& [m v m v m a ] and [n v n v n s ] is 



= 0. 



= 0. 



Proof. When these determinants are expanded, we get 



n a 



0, 



respectively. The one above is the equation of a line, the one below 
the equation of a point. Moreover, the determinants above both 
evidently vanish when the variable coordinates are replaced by the 
coordinates of the given elements. The expanded form, just given 
leads at once to the following : 

COROLLARY 1'. The coordinates 
of the point of intersection of the 
lines [m 13 m z , m s ], [n v n^, n^] are 



COROLLARY 1. The coordinates 
of the line joining the points 
(a v a s) a s ), (& & 2 , & 3 ) are 



Ms 



yt * M ftn 

W^B 



n 



There also follows immediately from this theorem : 

COROLLARY 2. The condition COROLLARY 2'. The condition 

that three points A, B, C "be col- that three lines m, n, p "be con~ 

linear is current is 



\ \ 



~ 0. 



Pi 



EXAMPLE. Let us verify the theorem of Desargues (Theorem 1, Chap. II) 
analytically. Choose one of the two perspective triangles aa triangle of refer- 
ence, say A' = (0, 0, 1), B f = (0, 1, 0), C" = (1, 0, 0), and let the center of per- 
spectivity he P - (1, 1, 1). If the other triangle is ABC, we may place 



64,63] PROJECTIYE PENCILS 

A = (1, 1, ), I? = (1, ft, 1), C = (c, 1, 1) , foi the equation of the lm e p^ f 
is x 1 Zy , and since -4 is, by hypothesis, on this line, its fust two coordi- 
nates must be equal, and may thereinto bo assumed equal to 1, the thud 
cooidinate is aibitiary Similaily foi the other points. Now, from the above 
theoiems and then coiollanes we leadily obtain in succession the following : 

The coordinates of the line A'B' are [1, 0, 0]. 

The coordinates of the line AB are [1 aft, a 1, b 1]. 

Hence the coordinates of their intersection C" are 

C"' = (0, 1-6, a- 1). 

Similaily, we find the coordinates of the intersection A" of the lines B'C', EC 
tobe 4" = (l-c, 6-1, 0); 

and, finally, the coordinates of the intersection B" of the lines C'A', CA to be 

J3" = (c-l,0, 1-a) 
The points A", B", C" are leadily seen to satisfy the condition foi collinearity. 

EXERCISES 

1 Work through the dual of the example just given, choosing the sides of 
one of the triangles and the axis of perspectivity as the fundamental lines of 
the system of cooidinates Show that the work may be made identical, step 
for step, with that above, except foi the interpretation of the symbols. 

2 Show that the system of coordinates may be so chosen that a quadi angle- 
quadiilateral configuration as represented by all the sets of coordinates that 
can be foimed from the numbers and 1. Dualize 

3. Derive the equation of the polar line of any point with regard to the 
triangle of reference. Dualize. 

65. Pencils of points and lines. Projectivity. A convenient ana- 
lytic representation of the points of a pencil of points or the lines of 
a pencil of lines is given by the following dual theorems : 

THEOREM 5. Any point of a THEOREM 5'. Any line of a 
pencil of points may "be, repre- pencil of lines may "be represented 
sented "by "by 

P = (\ 1 + \\, \a z + Xj&j, p = [/y^ 



where A = (a^ a z , a a ) and JB = where m = \m v m 2 , m a ] and n = 
(b v & 2 , & 8 ) are any two distinct [n v n z> n 8 ] are any two distinct 
points of the pencil. lines of the pencil. 

Proof. We may confine ourselves to the proof of the theorem on 
the left. By Theorem 4, Cor. 2, any point (a^, x z) a; 8 ) of the pencil of 
points on the line AB satisfies the relation 



182 COORDINATE SYSTEMS 



(1) 



0. 



We may then determine three numbers p, X 2 , X/, sucn that we have 
(2) p^XX+V^- (*1, 2, 3) 

The number p cannot be under the hypothesis, for then we should 
have from (2) the proportion a^ : a s : a s = 5j : 5 2 : & 8 , which would imply 
that the points A and B coincide. We may therefore divide by p. 
Denoting the ratios X 2 //o and X///D by X 2 and X x , we see that every 
point of the pencil may be represented in the manner specified. 
Conversely, every point whose coordinates are of the form specified 
clearly satisfies relation (1) and is therefore a point of the pencil 

The points A and B in the above representation are called the lasc 
points of this so-called parametric representation of the elements of 
a pencil of points. Evidently any two distinct points may be chosen 
as base points in such a representation. The ratio \/X a is called the 
parameter of the point it determines. It is here written in liomoga- 
neous form, which gives the point A for the value \ = and the 
point B for the value X 2 = 0. In many cases, however, it is more 
convenient to write this parameter in nonhomogeneous form, 

P = (a 1 +X5 1J a 2 +X& 3 , 3 +X5 3 ), 

which is obtained from the preceding by dividing by \ and replacing 
\/\ by X. In this representation the point B corresponds to the 
value X = oo. We may also speak of any point of tlie pencil under 
this representation as the point X X :X 2 or the point X when it corre- 
sponds to the value X a /X 2 = X of the parameter. Similar remarks and 
the corresponding terminology apply, of course, to the parametric 
representation of the lines of a flat pencil It is sometimes convenient, 
moreover, to adopt the notation A + \J3 to denote any point of the 
pencil whose base points are A, B or to denote the pencil itself ; also, 
to use the notation m + ^n to denote the pencil of lines or any line 
of this pencil whose base lines are m, n 

In order to derive an analytic representation of a projectivity 
between two one-dimensional primitive forms in the plane, we seek 
first the condition that the point X of a pencil of points A + \3 be 
on the line /* of a pencil of lines m 4- /w. By Theorem 3 tlxe condition 
that the point X be on the line /i is the relation 



PEOJECTIVE PENCILS 183 

a.4-X& 1 )=0. 



When expanded this relation gives 

1=8 t=8 

= 0. 



This is a bilinear equation whose coefficients depend only on the coor- 
dinates of the base points and base lines of the two pencils and not 
on the individual points for which the condition is sought Placing 



this equation becomes Cp\ + Dp A\ JB = 

which may also be written * 

(1) , 

v ' p 



The result may be stated as follows : Any perspective relation "between 
two one-dimensional primitive forms of different kinds is obtained "by 
establishing a protective correspondence between the parameters of the 
two forms. Since any protective correspondence between two one- 
dimensional primitive forms is obtained as the resultant of a sequence 
of such perspectivities, and since the resultant of any two linear frac- 
tional transformations of type (1) is a transformation of the same 
type, we have the following theorem : 

THEOREM 6. Any protective correspondence between two one-dimen- 
sional primitive forms in the plane is obtained by establishing a 
protective relation x + /3 

/*= >"[x (aS 

f/A, -J- O 

between the parameters p, \ of the two forms. 

In particular we have 

COROLLARY 1. Any projectivity in a one-dimensional primitive 
form in the plane is given by a relation of the form 



where \ is the parameter of the form. 



* The determinant 
X and /j. is (1, 1). 



AS 
CD 



does not vanish because the correspondence between 



184 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP.VH 

COROLLARY 2. If \, X 2 , X 3 , X 4 are the parameters of four claiwnttt 
AV A z , A z , A of a one-dimensional primitive form., the cross ratio 
B (AiA z , AyA]) is given T>y 



A projectivity between two different one-diniensional forms may 
be represented in a particularly simple form by a judicious choice oC 
the base elements of the parametric representation. To fix ideas, k-t 
us take the case of two protective pencils of points. Choose any two 
distinct points A, B of the first pencil to be the base points, and lot 
the homologous points of the second pencil be base pomln of the 
latter. Then to the values X = and X = GO of the first pencil must 
correspond the values p = and p = oo respectively of the, second. 
In this case the relation of Theorem 6, however, assumes the form 
p = 1c\. Hence, since the same argument applies to any diwtmot 
forms, we have 

COROLLARY 3. If two distinct protective one-dimensional primitive 
forms in the plane are represented parametricalli/ so that thfi Itrw 
elements form two homologous pairs, the projectivity is represented li/ 
a relation of the form p = 7cX oetween the parameters p, X of the two 
forms. 

This relation may be still further simplified Taking again the pruso 
discussed above of two projective pencils of points, wo have seen that, 
in general, to the point (^+ o v a a + & 2 , a, s + & 8 ), io. to X *= 1, rorro- 
sponds the point + &/, a a '+fc& a ', aj+Mh io. the point p**k. 
Suice the point ' = (&/, &,/, & a ') is also represented by the sot of wil>wU- 
nates (&/, W Zi Jebj), it follows that if we choose the late values f r tho 
coordmates of the base point ', to the value X 1 will <;oimsp<md 
the value /* = 1, and hence we have always /* X. In other wordn, 
we have 

COROLLARY 4, If two distinct one-dimensional forms im project far, 
the Use elements may le so chosen that the parwnefrra of any two 
homologous elements are equal 

Before closing this section it seems desirable to call atUmlion 
explicitly to the forms of the equation of any line of a ponc.il and of 
the equation of any point of a pencil which is implied by Theorem 5' 
and Theorem 5 respectively. If we place m . m^ + m,x, + m& and 



65,66] EQUATION OF A CONIC 2.85 

n = njS&i + n z x z + n s aj s , it follows from the first theorem mentioned 
that the equation of any hue of the pencil whose center is the inter- 
section of the lines m 0, n = is given by an equation of the form 
m + fm = 0. Similarly, the equation of any point of the line joining 
A a^ + a 2 w a + a & u s = and B = \u^ + \u z + \u 9 = is of the 
form A +\B = 0. 

66. The equation of a come. The results of 65 lead readily to 
the equation of a conic. By this is meant an equation m point (line) 
coordinates which is satisfied by all the points (lines) of a conic, and 
by no others. To derive this equation, let A, B be two distinct points 
on a conic, and let 

m m^ + m 2 aJ 2 -f- m, 3 x 3 = 0, 

(1) n = n^ + ?i 2 # 2 + 7t 3 # s = 0, 



be the equations of the tangent at A, the tangent at B, and the line 
AB respectively. The conic is then generated as a point locus "by 
two protective pencils of lines at A and B, in which m, p at A are 
homologous with p, n at B respectively This projectivity between 
the pencils 

m + \p**Q, 
^ ' p + pn = 

is given (Theorem 6, Cor. 3) by a relation 

(3) p = &X 

between the parameters p, \ of the two pencils. To obtain the equa- 
tion which is satisfied by all the points of intersection of pairs of 
homologous lines of these pencils, and by no others, we need simply 
eliminate /*, \ between the last three relations. The result of this 
elimination is 

(4) p*-7cmn=Q, 

which is the equation required. By multiplying the coordinates of 
one of the lines by a constant we may make k = 1 

Conversely, it is obvious that the points which satisfy any equation 
of type (4) are the points of intersection of homologous lines in the 
pencils (2), provided that /* = 7e\ If m, n, p are fixed, the condition 
that the conic (4) shall pass through a point (a v a 2 , a s ) is a linear 
equation in L Hence we have 



186 



COORDINATE SYSTEMS 



[CHAP VII 



THEOREM 7. If m 0, n 0, 
jp = are the equations of two 
distinct tangents of a conic and 
the line joining their points of con- 
tact respectively, the point equa- 
tion of the conic is of the form 

p z lcm,n 0. 

The coefficient k is determined "by 
any third point on the conic. Con- 
versely, the points whicJi satisfy 
an equation of the above form 
constitute a conic of which m = 
and n = are tangents at points 
on p = 0. 

COROLLARY. By properly cJwos- 
ing the triangle of reference, the 
point equation of any conic may 
be put in the form 

where x l = 0, # 8 = are two tan- 
gents, and # a = is the line join- 
ing their points of contact. 



THEOREM 7 ' If A = 0, B = 0, 
C=Q-are the equations of two 
distinct points of a conic and the 
intersection of the tangents at these 
points respectively, the line equa- 
tion of the conic is of the form 



The coefficient k is determined by 
any third line of the conic Con- 
versely, the lines which satisfy an 
equation of the above form consti- 
tute a conic of which A and 
JB=Q are points of contact of the 
tangents through = 0. 

COROLLARY. By properly choos- 
ing the triangle of reference, the 
line equation of any conic may 
be put in the form 

where u^ 0, u a = are two points, 
and u z = is the intersection of 
the tangents at these points. 



It is clear that if we choose the point (1, 1, 1) on the conic, we have 
k 1. Supposing the choice to have been thus made, we inquire 
regarding the condition that a line [u v u v u e ] be tangent to the conic 



This condition is equivalent to the condition that the line whose 



equation is 







shall have one and only one point in common with the conic. Elimi- 
nating a; 8 between this equation and that of the conic, the points 
common to the line and the conic are determined by the equation 

U^X* + Ufttti + W 8 OJ 2 a 0. 

The roots of this equation are equal, if and only if we have 

ul 4 UU = 0. 



66,67] LINEAR TKANSFOEMATIOlSrS 187 

Since this is the line equation of all tangents to the conic, and since 
it is of the form given m Theorem 1', Cor , above, we have here a new 
proof of the fact that the tangents to a point conic form a line conic 
(cf Theorem 11, Chap V). 

When the linear expressions for m, n, p are substituted in the equa- 
tion p z kmn of any conic, there results, when multiplied out, a 
homogeneous equation of the second degree in x v x z> x s> which may 
be written in the form 

(1) a u x? + a^xl + a 8 X + 2 a^x^ + 2 a ia x t x s + 2 a sa x z x a = 0. 

We have seen that the equation of every conic is of this form. We 
have not shown that every equation of this form represents a conic 
(see 85, Chap. IX). 

EXERCISE 

Show that the conic 

a n x? + a 22 r| + a 33 xj + 2 a^x^ + 2 a^or, + 2 a zs x z x & = 
degenerates into (distinct or coincident) stiaight lines, if and only if we have 



Dualize (A, E, P, H ) 

67. Linear transformations in a plane. We inquire now concern- 
ing the geometric properties of a linear transformation 



Such a transformation transforms any point (x v x z , as s ) of the plane 
into a unique point (as/, a? a ', iC 8 ') of the plane. Reciprocally, to every 
pomt x' will correspond a unique point x, provided the determinant 

of the transformation 

a n a i2 a is 
A = * a 22 a zs 

a 8l a sz a S8 

is not 0. For we may then solve equations (1) for the ratios O3 t : oj a : x t 
in terms of a?/: 2 ': # 8 ' as follows : 



(2) 



188 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [C.UAP.VU 

here the coefficients A rj are the cofactors of the elements a ti mspoc- 
tively m the determinant A. 

Further, equations (1) transform every line in the plane into a 
unique line In fact, the points x satisfying the equation 

W 1 1 +tt 2 # 2 +w 3 a j 8= !0 
are, by reference to equations (2), transformed into points a/ satisfy- 

ing the equation 

3 ) x[ + (A zl u { + A s ^ + A w u,} ^ 

x =* 0, 



which is the equation of a line. If the coordinates of this new lino be 
denoted by [< < fl, we clearly have the following relations between 
the coordinates [u v u v u 3 ] of any line and the coordinates [< < <| 
of the line into which it is transformed by (1) : 



(3) a-u^A^ 

fful = A^ 

We have seen thus far that (1) represents a collineation in the plane 
in point coordinates The equations (3) represent the same collineation 
in line coordinates 

It is readily seen, finally, that this collineation is protective. For 
this purpose it is only necessary to show that it transforms any 
pencil of lines into a protective pencil of lines But it is clear that if 
m = and n are the equations of any two lines, and if (1) trans- 
torms them respectively into the lines whose equations aro m' = 
and H/=0, any line m + \nQ is transformed into m'4-Xw' 0, 
and the correspondence thus established between the lines of the 
pencils has been shown to be projective (Theorem 6). 

Having shown that every transformation (1) represents a projective 
collineation, we wiH now show conversely that every projective 
collmeation in a plane may be represented by equations of the form 
(1) To this end we recall that every such collineation is completely 
rlef.A-nmnp.fi as soon as the homologous elements of any complete 
quadrangle are assigned (Theorem 18, Chap. IV). If we can show 
that likewise there is one and only one transformation of the form 
^(1) changing a given quadrangle into a given quadrangle, it will 
follow that, since the linear transformation is a projective collineation, 
it is the given projective collineation. 



67] LINEAR TRANSFORMATIONS 

Given any protective collineation in a plane, let the fundamental 
points (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 0), (1, 0, 0), and (1, 1, 1) of the plane (which 
form a quadrangle) be transformed respectively into the points 
A = (a v a v a,), B = (b v \, &,), = (o v c 2 , c 8 ), and D = (d v d v dj, form- 
ing a quadrangle. Suppose, now, we seek to determine the coefficients 
of a transformation (1) so as to effect the correspondences just indi- 
cated Clearly, if (0, 0, 1) is to be transformed into (a v a s> a^) 3 W e 

must have ,. _ - 

a w = \a v 28 =Xa 2 , a 83 =Xa s , 

\ being an arbitrary factor of proportionality, the value (= 0) of which 
we may choose at pleasure. Similarly, we obtain 



Since, by hypothesis, the three points A, B, C are not collinear, it 
follows from these equations and the condition of Theorem 4, Cor. 2, 
that the determinant A of a transformation determined in this -way 
is not Substituting the values thus obtained in (1), it is seen that 
if the point (1, 1, 1) is to be transformed into (d v d z , d 3 ), the following 
relations must hold : 



Placing p = 1 and solving this system of equations for v, p, X, we 
obtain the coefficients a y of the transformation. This solution is 
unique, since the determinant of the system is not zero. Moreover, 
none of the values X, /A, v will be ; for the supposition that v = 0, 
for example, would imply the vanishing of the determinant 



which in turn would imply that the three points D, B, A are collinear, 
contrary to the hypothesis that the four points A, B, (7, D form a 
complete quadrangle. 

Collecting the results of this section, we have 

THEOREM 8. Any projective calUneation in the plane may "be repre- 
sented in point coordinates "by equations of form, (1) or in line coordi- 
nates "by equations of form (3), and ^n each case the determinant of 



IQQ COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP. VII 

the transformation is different from , conversely, any transforma- 
tion of one of these forms in which the determinant is different from 
represents a protective collineation in the plane. 

OOKOLLAEY 1. In nonhomogeneous point coordinates the equations of 
a protective collineation are 



. a..x 
X 



- 



a a ^ . 



GOROLLAEY 2. If the singular line of tJie system of nonhomogeneous 
point coordinates is transformed into itself, these equations can be 
written saf=ax 



y' = 

68. Collineations between two different planes. The analytic form 
of a collineation between two different planes is now readily derived. 
Let the two planes be a and j3, and let a system of coordinates be 
established in each, the point coordinates in a being (x v x z , # 8 ) and 
the point coordinates in (3 being (y v y z , y 8 ). Further, let the isomor- 
phism between the number systems in the two planes be established 
in such a way that the correspondence established by the equations 

2/1=^ y>-. 2/8 = ^ 

is projective. It then follows, by an argument (cf. 59, p. 166), 
which need not be repeated here, that any collineation between the 
two planes may be obtained as the resultant of a projectivity in the 
plane a, which transforms a point X t say, into a point X', and the pro- 
jectivity Y X 1 between the two planes. The analytic form of any 
projective collineation "between the two planes is therefore : 



with the determinant A of the coefficients different from 0. And, con- 
versely, every such transformation in which A = represents a projec- 
tive collineatwn between the two planes. 

69. Nonhomogeneous coordinates in space. Point coordinates in 
space are introduced in a way entirely analogous to that used for the 
introduction of point coordinates in the plane. Choose a tetrahedron 
of reference OUVW and label the vertices (),=: ()= 0,, #" oo a> 



COORDINATES IN SPACE 



191 



y=<x> y , W=co g (fig. 84) ; and on the lines 0.^, 0^, O z oo g> called 
respectively the oc-axis, the y-axis, the z-axis, establish three scales by 
choosing the points l a , l y , l a . The planes Ooo^cx> v , Ooo^oOg, Ooo co are 
called the xy-plane, xz-plane, yz-plane respectively. The point is 
called the origin. If P is any point not on the plane co^co^, which 
is called the singular plane of the coordinate system, the plane 
P co^coj. meets the a>axis in a point whose nonhomogeneous coordinate 
in the scale (0.,., l x , GO,,) we call a. Similarly, let the plane 
meet the y-axis in a point 
whose nonhomogeneous 
coordinate in the scale 
(O y , l y , co y ) is I ; and let 
the plane Pco^ meet the 
#-axis in a point whose 
nonhomogeneous coordi- 
nate in the scale (0,., l e , co a ) 
is c. The numbers a, 5, c 
are then the nonhomo- 
geneous x-, y-, and z-coor- 1* 
dinates of the point P 
Conversely, any three 
numbers a, 5, c determine 
three points A, B, on 

the so-, y-, and #-axes respectively, and the three planes ^too, 
Coo a co y meet in a point P whose coordinates are a, &, c. Thus every 
point not on the singular plane of the coordinate system determines 
and is determined by three coordinates. The point P is then repre- 
sented by the symbol (a, &, c). 

The dual process gives rise to the coordinates of a plane. Point 
and plane coordinates may then be put into a convenient relation, as 
was done in the case of point and line coordinates in the plane, thus 
giving rise to a system of simultaneous point and plane coordinates 
in space. We will describe the system of plane coordinates with 
reference to this relation. Given the system of nonhomogeneous point 
coordinates described above, establish in each of the pencils of planes 
on the lines VW, UW, UV a scale by choosing the plane UVW as 
the zero plane M = () = O w in each of the scales, and letting the planes 
VW, OUW,OU7\)ethe planes oo tt , oo v , oo w respectively. In the ^scale 




. 84 



192 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP. VIS 

let that plane through VW be the plane 1 M , which meets the ,^-axis 
in the point I,. Similarly, let the plane ! meet the y-axis in the 
point \ y \ and let the plane l w meet the z-axis in the point 1 g 
The it-scale, v-scale, and w-scale being now completely determined, 
any plane TT not on the point (which is called the singular point 
of this system of plane coordinates) meets the a:-, y-, and #-axes in 
three points L, M, N which determine in the w-, v-, and w-scalea planes 
whose coordinates, let us say, are I, m, n. These three numbers are 
called the nonhomogeneous plane coordinates of TT. They completely 
determine and are completely determined by the plane TT. The plane 
TT is then denoted by the symbol [I, m, n]. 

In this system of coordinates it is now readily seen that the con- 
dition that the point (a, b, c) be on the plane [I, m, n] is that the relation 
la + mb + ne + l=Q be satisfied. It follows readily, as in the planar 
case, that the plane [I, m, n~\ meets the %-, y-, and #-axes in points 
whose coordinates on these axes are l/l, l/m, and 1/n respec- 
tively.* In deriving the above condition we will suppose that the 
plane IT [I, m, n] does not contain two of the points Z7, V t W> leav- 
ing the other case as an exercise for the reader. Suppose, then, that 
U=*GQ X and F= oo ff are not on TT. By projecting the y-plane with 
U as center upon the plane -rr, and then projecting TT with V as center 
on the a-plane, we obtain the following perspectivities : 

[(.y.)]|[toy,^][too,i)], 

where (x, y, s) represents any point on TT, The product of those two 
perspectivities is a projectivity between the ys-plane and the ire-plane, 
by which the singular line of the former is transformed into the sin- 
gular line of the latter. Denoting the ^-coordinate of points in the 
ys-plane by &', this projectivity is represented (according to Theorem 
8, Gor. 2, and 68) by relations of the form 

(1) l^ X+ lZ + Cv 

We proceed to determine the coefficients n v l v Gy The point of 
intersection of * with the y-axis is (0, -1/ TO , 0), and to clearly 



69] COORDINATES IN SPACE 

transformed by the projectivity in question into the point (0, 0, 0) 
Hence (1) gives - 

c = 
m 

The point of intersection of TT with the a-axis is, if %=(), (0, 0, 1/ri) 
and is transformed into itself. Hence (1) gives 

n m 

1 m 
If n = 0, we have at once \ = 0. 

Finally, the point of intersection of TT with the a-axis is ( 1/Z, 0, 0), 
and the transform of the point (0, 0, 0) Hence we have 

__. _i _ n 

7 > 

It ffli 

1 m 

Hence (1) becomes y = x z 

m m m 

a relation which must be satisfied by the coordinates (x, y, 2) of any 
point on TT. This relation is equivalent to 

Ix + my + nz + 1 = 0. 
Hence (a, 5, c) is on [I, m, n], if 

(2) la + mb + nc + 1 = 0. 

Conversely, if (2) is satisfied by a point (a, &, c), the point (0, 6, c)= _P 
is transformed by the projectivity above into (a, 0, c) = $, and hence 
the lines P U and Q V which meet in (a, b, c) meet on TT. 

DEFINITION. An equation which DEFINITION. An equation which 
is satisfied by all the points (x, y, 3) is satisfied by all the planes [u,v,w] 
of a plane and by no other points on a point and by no other planes 
is called the point equation of the is called the plane equation of the 
plane. point. 

The result of the preceding discussion may then be stated as follows : 
THEOREM 9. The point equation THEOREM 9'. The plane equation 
of the plane [I, m, ri\ is of the point (a, b, c) is 

Ix + my H- nz + 1 = 0, au + bv + cw + 1 = Q. 



19 4 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP, vn 

70. Homogeneous coordinates in space. Assign to the vertices 0, Z7, 
F, W of any tetrahedron of reference the symbols (0, 0, 0, 1), (1, 0, 0, 0), 
(0, 1, 0, 0), (0, 0, 1, 0) respectively, and assign to any fifth point T 
not on a face of this tetrahedron the symbol (1, 1, 1, 1). The five 
points 0, V, F, W, T are called the frame of reference of the system 
of homogeneous coordinates now to be described. The four lines join- 
ing T to the points 0, U, F, W meet the opposite faces in four points, 
which we denote respectively by (1, 1, 1, 0), (0, 1, 1, 1), (1, 0, 1, 1), 
(1, 1, 0, 1). The planar four-point (0, 0, 0, 1), (0, 0, 1, 0), (0, 1, 0, 0), 
(0, 1, 1, 1) we regard as the frame of reference (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 0), 
(1, 0, 0), (1, 1, 1) of a system of homogeneous coordinates in the plane. 
To any point in this plane we assign the coordinates (0, x v x a , o? 4 ), if 
its coordinates in the planar system ]ust indicated are (aj a , J 8 , o& 4 ). In 
like manner, to the points of the other three faces of the tetrahedron of 
reference we assign coordinates of the forms (a^, 0, x s , x t ), (x v x z , 0, ) 4 ), 
and (x v x z , x s , 0) The coordinates of the points in the faces opposite 
the vertices (1, 0, 0, 0), (0, 1, 0, 0), (0, 0, 1, 0), (0, 0, 0, 1) satisfy respec- 
tively the equations x l = 0, x z = 0, # 8 = 0, 03 4 = 

To the points of each edge of the tetrahedron of reference a notation 
has been assigned corresponding to each of the two faces which meet 
in the edge. Consider, for example, the line of intersection of the 
planes 0^=0 and x z = 0. Regarding this edge as a line of M^ 0, the 
coordinate system on the edge has as its fundamental points (0, 0, 1, 0), 
(0, 0, 0, 1), (0, 0, 1, 1). The first two of these are vertices of the tetra- 
hedron of reference, and the third is the trace of the line joining 
(0, 1, 0, 0) to (0, 1, 1, 1). On the other hand, regarding this edge as a 
line of a! 3 =0, the coordinate system has the vertices (0, 0, 1, 0) and 
(0, 0, 0, 1) as two fundamental points, and has as (0, 0, 1, 1) the trace 
of the line joining (1, 0, 0, 0) to (1, 0, 1, 1). But by construction the 
plane (0, 1, 0, 0) (1, 0, 0, 0) (1, 1, 1, 1) contains both (0, 1, 1, 1) and 
(1, 0, 1, 1), so that the two determinations of (0, 0, 1, 1) are identical. 
Hence the symbols denoting points in the two planes != and 
a? a = are identical along their line of intersection. A similar result 
holds for the other edges of the tetrahedron of reference. 

THEOREM 10. DEFINITION. If P is any point not on a face of the 
tetrahedron of reference, there exist four numbers x v x at 8 , 4 , oU 
di/erentfrom zero, such that the projections of P from, the four vertices 
(1, 0, 0, 0), (0, 1, 0, 0) t , (0, 0, 1, 0), (0, 0, 0, 1) respectively upon 



70] COORDINATES IN" SPACE 195 

opposite faces are (0, 2 , a> 8 , a? 4 ), fo, 0, a? 8 , osj, (a^, a 2 , 0, a? 4 ), (a^, as,, a;,, 0) 
57wse four numbers are called the Jwmof/eneous coordinates of P and 
P is denoted ly (x v x a , o& a , a; 4 ) Any ordered set of four numbers, not 
all zero, determine uniquely a point in space whose coordinates they are. 

Proof. The line joining P to (1, 0, 0, 0) meets the opposite face in 
a point (0, x z> x s , B 4 ), which is not an edge of the tetrahedron of refer- 
ence, and such therefore that none of the numhers a? 2 , as 8 , zc 4 is zero. 
Likewise the line joining P to (0, 1, 0, 0) meets the opposite face in 
a point (as/, 0, #', aJ 4 ), such that none of the numhers x[, x^ %[ is zero. 
But the plane P(l, 0, 0, 0) (0, 1, 0, 0) meets a; 1 = in the line joining 
(0, 1, 0, 0) to (0, # 2 , SG S , a: 4 ), and meets x z in the line joining 
(1, 0, 0, 0) to (a?./, 0, xl, a?/). By the analytic methods already devel- 
oped for the plane, the first of these lines meets the edge common 
to x : = and x a = in the point (0, 0, x a , # 4 ), and the second meets 
it in the point (0, 0, a?/, 03 4 ). But the points (0, 0, D S , x 4 ) and 
(0, 0, xl , xl) are identical, and hence, by the preceding paragraph, we 
have a? 8 /a2 4 = #//#/ Hence, if we place x l = x[xjx[ y the point 
(x^ 0, a, xl} is identical with (x v 0, x a , x t ). The line joining P to 
(0, 0, 1, 0) meets the face x a = in a point (a?/', # 2 ", 0, #/'). By the 
game reasoning as that above it follows that we have x / x^ *= xj x^ 
and x" /xl' = xjx^ so that the point (x", x r , 0, a? 4 ") is identical with 
(x v 03 a , 0, a? 4 ). Einally, the line joining P to (0, 0, 0, 1) meets the face 
a; 4 =s in a point which a like argument shows to be (x v a; 2 , x 3 , 0). 

Conversely, if the coordinates (x v x v x a , # 4 ) are given, and one of 
them is zero, they determine a point on a face of the tetrahedron 
of reference. If none of them is zero, the lines joining (1, 0, 0, 0) 
to (0, x s) x s , 03 4 ) and (0, 1, 0, 0) to (x lt 0, o) 8 , * 4 ) are in the plane 
(1, 0, 0, 0) (0, 1, 0, 0) (0, 0, x 9 , aJ 4 ), and hence meet in a point which, 
by the reasoning above, has the coordinates (x v x z , x a , x^ 

COEOLLABY. Tlie notations (x v x z ,x 3 ,xj and (kx v 7ex a , Jex s , Tcx^ 
denote the same point for any value of TV not equal to zero 

Homogeneous plane coordinates in space arise by the dual of the 
above process. The four faces of a tetrahedron of reference are denoted 
respectively by [1, 0, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0, 0], [0, 0, 1, 0], and [0, 0, 0, 1]. 
These, together with any' plane [1, 1, 1, 1] not on a vertex of the 
tetrahedron, form the frame of reference. The four lines of inter- 
section of the plane [1, 1, 1, 1] with the other four planes in the order 

i * > I 



} 
I 



196 COOKDEKTATE SYSTEMS [CHAP VII 

above are projected from the opposite vertices by planes which are 
denoted by [0, 1, 1, 1], [1, 0, 1, 1], [1, 1, 0, 1], [1, 1, 1 , 0] respectively 
The four planes [0, 1, 0, 0], [0, 0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 0, 1], and [0, 1, 1, 1] form, 
if the first in each of these symbols is suppressed, the frame of 
reference of a system of homogeneous coordinates in a bundle (the 
space dual of such a system in a plane). The center of this bundle 
is the vertex of the tetrahedron of reference opposite to [1, 0, 0, 0]. 
To any plane on this point is assigned the notation [0, u v 8 , wj, if 
its coordinates in the bundle are \u v u s , wj. In like manner, to the 
planes on the other vertices are assigned coordinates of the forms 
[u v 0, w 8 , wj, [u v u a , 0, wj, [u v u a , u 3> 0], The space dual of the last 
theorem then gives : 

THEOEEM 10'. DEFINITION. Ifwis any plane not on a vertex of the 
tetrahedron of reference, there exist four numbers u v u z , u z> w 4 , all differ- 
ent from zero, such that the traces of IT on the four faces [1, 0, 0, 0], 
[0, 1, 0, 0], [0, 0, 1, 0], [0, 0, 0, 1] respectively are projected from the 
opposite verities ly the planes [0, u z , u 3 , wj, \u v 0, w 3 , 4 ], [u v u z , 0, wj, 
\u v u z ,u s , 0] These four numbers are catted the homogeneous coordinates 
of IT, and IT is denoted ly [u v u z , u s , wj. Any ordered set of four num- 
bers, not all zero, determine uniquely a plane whose coordinates tJiey are. 

By placing these systems of point and plane coordinates in a proper 
relation we may now readily derive the necessary and sufficient con- 
dition that a point (x v os z , x s , x 4 ) be on a plane [u v u^, u s , i*J. This 
condition -will turn out to be 

!! + U 2 3S a + U 3 3S a + U& = 0. 

We note first that in a system of point coordinates as described above 
the six points (- 1, 1, 0, 0), (- 1, 0, 1, 0), (- 1, 0, 0, 1), (0, - 1, 1, 0), 
(0, 0, - 1, 1), (0, - 1, 0, 1) are coplanar, each being the harmonic con- 
jugate, with respect to two vertices of the tetrahedron of reference, of 
the point into which (1, 1, 1, l) 1S projected by the line joming the 
other two vertices The plane containing these is, in fact, the polar 
of (1, 1, 1, 1) -with respect to the tetrahedron of reference (ef Ex 3 
p. 47). Now choose " ' 

as the plane [1, 0, 0, 0] the plane ^ = 0, 
as the plane [0, 1, 0, 0] the plane x z ~ 0, 
as the plane [0, 0, 1, 0] the plane a 8=s = 0, 
as the plane [0, 0, 0, 1] the plane x^ 0, 



TO] COORDINATES IN SPACE 197 

3 the plane [1, 1, 1, 1] the plane containing the points ( 1, 1, 0, 0), 
-1,0,1,0), (-1,0,0,1). 

With this choice of coordinates the planes [1, 0, 0, 0], [0, 1, 0, 0], 
3, 0, 1, 0], and [1, 1, 1, 0] through the vertex F" 4 , say, whose point 
3ordmates are (0, 0, 0, 1), meet the opposite face # 4 = in lines 
hose equations in that plane are 

x^ =0, x z 0, tf s =0, x l + a3 a 4- % s = 0. 

ence the first three coordinates of any plane \u v u z> u s> 0] on F" 4 
'e the line coordinates of its trace on x = 0, in a system so chosen 
tat the point (x v x z) os s ) is on the line [u v u 2 , u s ] if and only if the 
'lation ufii + u z x z + u s x s = is satisfied Hence a point (x v x z , x s , 0) 
3s on a plane [u v u z , u a> 0] if and only if we have u 1 x i +u z x Si + 
t x s = 0. But any point (x v x z , % 8 , 4 ) on the plane [u v u z , u a , 0] has, 
r definition, its first three coordinates identical with the first three 
ordinates of some point on the trace of this plane with the plane 
= 0. Hence any point (x v x z , #, # 4 ) on [u v u z , u s , 0] satisfies the 
ndition u^ + w 2 # a + u s x s + 4 a? 4 = Applying this reasoning to 
ch of the four vertices of the tetrahedron of reference and dualizing, 
3 find that ^f one coordinate of [it, v u z , u z , wj is zero, the necessary 
id sufficient condition that this plane contain a point (x v x z , a? a , 3 4 ) 
that the relation 

U^ + Ufa + U a X 3 + W 4 # 4 = 

satisfied; and if one coordinate of (x v x z , % a , 4 ) is zero, the neces- 
ry and sufficient condition that this point "be on the plane [?^,w 2 ,?t a ,wj 
likewise that the relation just given "be satisfied 
Confining our attention now to points and planes no coordinate of 
lich. is zero, let xjx^x, xjx^y, xjx^z, and let uju^u, 
/Ut=*v, uju^w. Since x, y, * are the ratios of homogeneous 
ordinates on the lines x z = x & = 0, x^ = x s = 0, and ^ = a; 2 = respec- 
r ely, they satisfy the definition of nonhomogeneous coordinates 
,-en in 69. And since the homogeneous coordinates have teen 
chosen that the plane (u v u z , u a , w 4 ) meets the line o2 2 = x s = in 
3 point ( u^ 0, 0, w x ) = ( l/u, 0, 0, 1), it follows that w, v, w are 
nhomogeneous plane coordinates so chosen that a point (x, y, z), 
ne of whose coordinates is zero, is on a plane [u, v, w\ none of 
lose co8rdmates is zero, if and only if we have (Theorem 9) 

was + vy + we + 1 = ; 



198 COOEDINA.TE SYSTEMS [CHAP VII 

that is, if and only if we have 

U& + u z x s + u s x s + u 4 is t = 

This completes for all cases the proof of 

THEOREM 11. The necessary and sufficient condition that a point 
(x v x v # 8 , 4 ) le on a plane [u v u z , u s , uj is that the relation 

upi + tt a afe + u s x g + u^ 
le satisfied. 

By methods analogous to those employed in 64 and 65 we may 
now derive the results of Exs. 1-8 below. 

EXERCISES 

1 The equation of the plane through the three points A = (ct 15 a z , a 3 , a 4 ), 



Dualize 

2 The necessary and sufficient condition that four points A, B, C, D be 
coplanar is the vanishing of the determinant 



3. The necessary and sufficient condition that three points A) B, C be 
collinear is the vanishing of the thiee-rowed determinants of the matrix 



4. Any point of a pencil of points containing A and B may be represented by 
P X + X} 



5 Any plane of a pencil of planes containing m = [m x , m a , w 8 , w 4 ] and 
" = Oti n s> n 8> "4] ma y be represented by 



+ Xjj^, Xgma + A^, X^wij, + X^g, X 2 m 4 + X^J, 

6 Any projectivity between two one-dimensional primitive forma (of points 
or planes) in space Is expressed by a relation between their parameters X, /* 
of the form 

oX + ft 

^"^xTs" 

If the base elements of the pencil are homologous, this relation reduces to 



. 

' V v *-'/*' 

70,71] LINEAR TRANSFORMATION " ^199 1 

<**',- -^ 
7 If \ v A 2 , A s , A 4 aie the parameters of four points or planes of a pencil K " -~.^ 

then ciobs ratio is *" 



l ~ <t 2 "~ 4 

8 Any point (plane) of a plane of points (bundle of planes) containing 
the noncollineai points A, JB, C (planes a, /8, y) may be repiesented by 

P - (A^ + A^ + A 8 c T , kfy + Xgb z + A 8 c a , A^a + A 2 Z> 8 + A 8 c s , A^ + A,i 4 + A 8 c 4 ). 

9. Derive the equation of the polar plane of any point with regard t<? the 
tetrahedron of reference 

10. Derive the equation of a cone. 

*11. Derive nonhomogeneous and homogeneous systems of codrdinates in 
a space of four dimensions. 

71. Linear transformations in space. The properties of a linear 
transformation in space 

+ ax 



"IS^S 

(i) p a*z. f .~ J "~ J " 



are similar to those found in 68 for the linear transformations in a 
plane. If the determinant of the transformation 



is different from zero, the transformation (1) will have a unique in- 
verse, viz. : 



p'x s 
^ ' ' B + AX, 



X + AX + AX> 
where the coefficients ^ are the cofactors of the elements a y respec- 
tively in the determinant A. 

The transformation is evidently a collineation, as it transforms the 

P 

into the plane 



* 
+ A * 



200 COORDINATE SYSTEMS |C"Ai-. VH 

Hence the collineation (1) produces on the planes of space the trans- 
formation 

' ' 



To show that the transformation (1) is productive consider any 
pencil of planes 

+ & a 2 + V 8 + ^ 0, 



In accordance with (2) this pencil is transformed into a pencil of the 
form 

(o/jBi + a/a^ + a 3 'a? 8 + a 4 'as 4 ) + X (&/! + l& 9 + &'!, + &/,*; 4 ) = 0, 

and these two pencils of planes are protective (Ex. 6, p. 108). 

Finally, as in 67, we see that there is one and only 0110 trans- 
formation (1) changing the points (0, 0, 0, 1), (0, 0, 1, 0), (0, 1, 0, 0), 
(1, 0, 0, 0), and (1, 1, 1, 1) into the vertices of an arbitrary eomplutu 
five-point in space. Since this transformation is a protective collinwi- 
tion, and since there is only one projeotivo collinoatioii transforming 
one five-point into another (Theorem 19, Chap. IV), it fullowH that 
every projective collmeation in space may he represented by a liiuwr 
transformation of the form (1). This gives 

THEOREM 12. Any projective collinmtion of ^mea mmj 1w repre- 
sented in point coordinates by equations of the, /upin, (1), or in yfana 
coordinates by equations of the form (3). lib cttftji, anac the drtaruMMitt 
of the transformation is different from sort). $ww/wj/y, // trans- 
formation of this form in which, the det&nwtoumt is- differ ant front, aero 
represents a projective collineation of space. 

COROLLARY 1. In nonhomogeneons point covrdinfttrtt a prtyeetiw 
collineation is represented ly the linear fraot/imml cij>iuttwn8 



y i = V + a^y + orft + a^ 

'' 



vn which the determinant A is di/erentfrom zero. 



71,72] FINITE SPACES 201 

OOEOLLAEY 2. If the singular plane of the nonhomoffeneous system 
is transformed into itself, these equations reduce to 

sd = a^ + a z y + a# + a v ^ a z 8 

y / & 1 aj + & a y+6 4l a + J 4 , \ \ \ ^ 0. 

' = c^x + c z y + c<p -f- <? 4 , e i G z c s 

72. Finite spaces. It will "be of interest at this point to emphasize 
again the generality of the theory which we are developing. Since 
all the developments of this chapter are on the "basis of Assumptions 
A, E, and P only, and since these assumptions imply nothing regard- 
ing the number system of points on a line, except that it be commu- 
tative, it follows that we may assume the points of a line, or, indeed, 
the elements of any one-dimension al form, to be in one-to-one recip- 
rocal correspondence with the elements of any commutative number 
system. We may, moreover, study our geometry entirely by analytic 
methods. From this point of view, any point in a plane is simply a 
set of three numbers (as v C 2 , 03 8 ), it being understood that the sets 
(x v # 2 , x 8 ) and (ksc v Tcx z> kx a ) are equivalent for all values of k in the 
number system, provided k is different from 0. Any line in the plane 
is the set of all these points which satisfy any equation of the form 
16^+ u s x z + u a x a = 0, the set of all lines being obtained by giving 
the coefficients (coordinates) \u v u z , u s ] all possible values in the 
number system (except [0, 0, 0]), with the obvious agreement that 
\u v u z , w 8 ] and \ku v ku z) ku & ] represent the same line (/=()). By 
letting the number system consist of all ordinary rational numbers, 
or all ordinary real numbers, or all ordinary complex numbers, we 
obtain respectively the analytic form of ordinary rational, or real, or 
complex projective geometry in the plane. All of our theory thus 
far applies equally to each of these geometries as well as to the 
geometry obtained by choosing as our number system any field 
whatever (any ordinary algebraic field, for example). 

In particular, we may also choose a finite field, i e. one which con- 
tains only a finite number of elements The simplest of these are 
the modular fields, the modulus being any prime number^?.* If we 

* A modular field with modulus p is obtained as follows : Two integers w, n' 
(positive, negative, or zero) are said to be congruent modulo p, written n=n', mod. p, 
if the difference n n" is divisible by jp. Every integer is then congruent to one 
and only one of the numbers 0, 1, 2, , p 1 These numbers are taken as the 
elements' of our field, and any number obtained from these by addition^ subtraction, 



202 COORDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP.VII 

consider, for example, the case p = 2, our number system contains 
only the elements and 1 There are then seven points, which we 
will label A, B, C, D, E, JF, G, as f ollows : A = (0, 0, 1), B = (0, 1, 0), 
C = (l, 0, 0), D = (0, 1, 1), JP-(1, 1, 0), ^ = (1, 1, 1), = (1, 0, 1). 
The reader will readily verify that these seven points are arranged 
in lines according to the table 

A B D IS F & 
C D E F G A 
D E F G A B C, 

each column constituting a line For example, the line o^ = clearly 
consists of the points (0, 0, 1) = A, (0, 1, 0) = B, and (0, 1, 1) = D, these 
being the only points whose first coordinate is "We have labeled 
the points of this finite plane in such a way as to exhibit clearly its 
abstract identity with the system of triples used for illustrative pur- 
poses in the Introduction, 2.* 

EXERCISES 

1. Verify analytically that two sides of a complete quadrangle containing a 
diagonal point are harmonic with the other two diagonal points. 

2 Show analytically that if two piojective pencils of lines in a plane have 
a self-coriesponding line, they are perspective. (This is equivalent to Assump- 
tion P ) 

3 Show that the lines whose equations aie a^ + A..e 2 = 0, x z + it% z = 0, and 
x a + vxj = are concui rent if X/xv = 1 j and that they meet the opposite 
sides of the triangle of reference respectively in collinear points, if Xp> = 1 

4 Find the equations of the lines joining (c v c a , c 8 ) to the four points 
(1, 1, 1)> and determine the cross ratios of the pencil. 

and muttvphcation, if not equal to one of these elements, is replaced by the element 
to which it is congruent. The modular field with modulus 5, for example, consists of 
the elements 0, 1, 2, 3, 4, and we have as examples of addition, subtraction, and 
multiplication 1 + 8 = 4, 2 + 8 = (since 5 = 0, mod. 6), 1 4 = 2, 2 8 = 1, etc. 
Furthermore, if a, 6 are any two elements of this field (a 5* 0), there is a unique 
element determined by the congruence o=6, mod, jp; this element is defined 
as the quotient b/a (For the proof of this proposition the reader may refer to any 
standard text on the theory of numbers,) In the example discussed we have, for 
example, 4/3 = 8. 

* For references and a further discussion of finite projective geometries see a 
paper by Veblen and W. H, Bussey, Finite Projective Geometries, Transactions 
of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. VII (1906), pp, 241-260 Also a sub-* 
sequent paper by 0. Veblen, Collineations in a Finite Projective Geometry, Trans- 
actions of the American Mathematical Society, Vol. VIII (1907), pp, 266-268, 



72] EXEECISES 203 

5. Show that the throw of lines determined on (c lf c a , c a ) by the four 
points (1, 1, 1) is projective with (equal to) the throw of lines determined 
on (&j, Z> a , & 3 ) by the points (a 19 a 2 , a 8 ), if the following relations hold: 



and that the six cross ratios are a 2 /a 3 , a^/a^, a^/a z , a s /a 2 , (t^/a^ 
2 /a 1 (C. A. Scott, Mod. Anal. Geom , p 50). 

6 Wiite the equations of transformation for the five types of planai col- 
lineations desciibed in 40, Chap. IV, choosing points of the tuangle of 
refeience as fixed points 

7. Generalize Ex. 6 to space 

8 Show that the set of values of the paiameter A. of the pencil of lines 
wi + An = is isomorphic with the scale determined in this pencil by the lines 
for which the fundamental lines are respectively the lines A. = 0, 1, oo 

9 Show directly fiom the discussion of 61 that the points whose non- 
homogeneous cooidinates x, y satisfy the equation y = x aie on the line joining 
the ongin to the point (1, 1). 

10 Theic is then established on this line a scale whose fundamental points 
are respectively the origin, the point (1,1), and the point in which the line m eefcs 
the line .. The lines joining any point P in the plane to the points oo y , oo x 
meet the line y x in two points whose coordinates in the scale just determined 
aie the nonhomogeneous coordinates of P, so that any point in the plane 
(not on L,) is lepresented by a pair of points on the line y = x. Hence, show 
that in general the points (x, y) of any line in the plane deteimine on the 
line y x& projectivity with a double point on Z ; and hence that the equa- 
tion of any such line is of the foini y = ax + b. What lines are exceptions to 
this proposition? 

11. Discuss the modular plane geometiy in which the modulus is p = 3 ; 
and by properly labeling the points show that it is abstractly identical with 
the system of quadruples exhibited as System (2) on p. 6. 

12. Show in geneial that the modular projective plane with modulus p 
contains p* -f p + 1 points and the same number of lines ; and that there are 
p + 1 points (lines) on every line (point). 

13. The diagonal points of a complete quadrangle in. a modular plane pio- 
jective geometry are collinear if and only if p = 2 

14. Show that the points and lines of a modular plane all belong to the 
same net of rationality. Such a plane is then properly projective without the 
use of Assumption P. 

15. Show how to construct a modular three-space. If the modulus is 2, 
show that its points may be labeled 0, 1, . . . , 14 in such a way that the 
planes are the sets of seven obtained by cyclic permutation from the set 
1 4 6 11 12 13 (i.e. 1 2 5 7 12 13 14, etc.), and that the lines are ob- 
tained from the lines 1 4, 2 8, 5 10 by cyclic permutations. (For a 



204 COOEDINATE SYSTEMS [CHAP. VII 

study of this space, see G M. Conwell, Annals of Mathematics, Vol 11 
(1910), p. 60 ) 

16. Show that the ten diagonal points of a complete five-point in space 
(0, 0, 0, 1), (0, 0, 1, 0), (0, 1, 0, 0), (1, 0, 0, 0), (1, 1, 1, 1) aie given by the 
remaining sets of coordinates in which occur only the digits and 1. 

17. Show that the ten diagonal points in Ex 16 determine in all 45 planes, 
of which each of a set of 25 contains foui diagonal points, while each of the 
remaining 20 contains only three diagonal points. Through any diagonal 
point pass 16 of these planes. The diagonal lines, i.e. lines joining two 
diagonal points, are of two kinds through each of the diagonal lines of the 
first kind pass five diagonal planes ; through each line of the second kind pass 
four diagonal planes 

18 Show how the results of Ex 17 are modified in a modular space with 
modulus 2 , with modulus 3. Show that in the modular space with modulus 
5 the lesults of Ex. 17 hold without modification. 

* 19. Derive homogeneous and nonhoniogeneous cooidinate systems for 
a space of n dimensions, and establish the formulas for an n -dimensional 
projective collmeation. 



CHAPTER VIII 

PROJECTIVITIES IN ONE-DIMENSIONAL FORMS* 

73. Characteristic throw and cross ratio. 

THEOREM 1. If M, N are double points of a projectvoity on a, line, 
and AA', JBB' are any two pairs of homologous points (ie. if 
MNAB % MNA'B'}, then MNAA' -% MNBB 1 . 

Proof. Let S, S' be any two distinct points on a line through 
M (fig. 85), and let the lines SA and S'A' meet in A", and SB and 

S 




S'B' meet in B". The points A", B", JVare then collinear (Theorem 23, 
Ohap. IV). If the line A"B" meets SS' in a point Q, we have 

A" B" 

MNAA' == MQ88' === MNBB 1 . 

This proves the theorem, which may also he stated as follows : 

The throws consisting of the pair of double points in a given order 
and any pair of homologous points are all egual. 

DEFINITION. The throw T(MN, A A'), consisting of the double points 
and a pair of homologous points of a projectivity, is called the charac- 
teristic throw of the projeotivity ; and the cross ratio of this throw 
is called the characteristic cross ratio of the projectivity.f 

* All the developments of this chapter are on the basis of Assumptions .A T? P TT 
t Since the double points enter symmetrically, the throws T / '"" r 
T (JVlf, AA') may be used equally well for the characteristic th 
spending cross ratios Jfr (Jf JT, A A') and Bs (N3f t A A') are reoip"" 
(of. Theorem 13, Cor. 3, Chap. VI). 

20F 



206 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP vin 

COEOLLAEY 1. A projectivity on a line with two given distinct 
double points is uniquely determined by its characteristic throw or 
cross ratio. 

COBOLLAEY 2. The characteristic cross ratio of any involution with 
double points is I. 

This follows directly from Theorem 27, Cor 1, Chap. IV, and 
Theorem 13, Cor 2, Chap VI 

If m, n are nonhomogeneous coordinates of the double points, and 
k is the characteristic cross ratio of a projectivity on a line, we have 
x'm f x in _ , 
x'n x n 

for every pair of homologous points x, x' This is the analytic expres- 
sion of the above theorem, and leads at once to the following analytic 
expression for a projectivity on a line with two distinct double points 
m, n: 

COKOLLAEY 3 Any projectivity on a line with two distinct doulle 
points m, n may be represented by the equation 

x r m __ , x m 
x'n x n' 
*', x being any pair of homologous points. 

For when cleared of fractions this is a bilinear equation in x' } x 
which obviously has m, n as roots. Moreover, since any projectivity 
with two given distinct double points is uniquely determined by one 
additional pair of homologous elements, it follows that any projec- 
tivity of the kind described can be so represented, in view of the fact 
that one such pair of homologous points will always determine the 
multiplier h These considerations offer an analytic proof of Theo- 
rem 1, for the case when the double points M, JVare distinct. 

It is to be noted, however, that the proof of Theorem 1 applies 
equally well when the points M, N coincide, and leads to the follow- 
ing theorem : 

THEOEEM 2. If in a parabolic projectivity with double point M the 
points AA! and SB' are two pavrs of homologous points, the parabolic 
projectivity with double point M which puts A into 3 also puts A' 
into B'. * 

COBOLLAEY. The characteristic cross ratio of any parabolic 
timty is unity. 



73] CHARACTERISTIC! THROW 207 

The characteristic cross ratio together with the double point is 
therefore not sufficient to characterize a paiabolic projectivity com- 
pletely Also, the analytic form for a projectivity with double points 
TO, n, obtained above, breaks down when m n. We may, however, 
readily derive a characteristic property of parabolic projectivities, 
from which will follow an analytic form for these projectivities. 

THEOREM 3. If a, parabolic projectivity ivith double, point M trans- 
forms a point A into A' and A' into A 1 ', the pair of points A, A" is 
harmonic with tlie pair A'M; i.e we have H (MA 1 , AA"). 

Proof By Theorem 23, Chap IV, Cor., we have Q(MAA', MA" A'). 

Analytically, if the coordinates of M, A, A', A" are m, x, x 1 , ss" 
respectively, we have, by Theorem 13, Cor. 4, Chap. VI, 



m js iii sd' m 
This gives 

1 __ J^^ 1 __ 1 

a/ 111 x m ,il' m x' m 

which shows that if each member of this equation be placed equal to 
t, the relation 

(1) 



~ 
x'm x m 

is satisfied by every pair of homologous points of the sequence obtained 
by applying the projectivity successively to the points A, A', A", . 
It is, however, readily seen that this relation is satisfied by every pair 
of homologous points on the line. For relation (1), when cleared of 
fractions, clearly gives a bilinear form in t and x, and is therefore a 
projectivity; and this projectivity clearly has only the one double 
point m. It therefore represents a parabolic projectivity with the 
double point m, and must represent the projectivity in question, since 
the relation is satisfied by the coordinates of the pair of homologous 
points A, A' } which are sufficient with the double point to determine 
the projectivity. 

We have then : 

COROLLARY 1. Any parabolic projectivity with a double point, M, 
may "be represented ly the relation (1). 

DEFINITION. The number t is called the characteristic constant of 
the projectivity (1). 



208 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PBOJEOTIVITIES [CHAP VIII 

COROLLARY 2. Conversely, if a projectivity with a double point 
M transforms a point A into A', and A' into A", such that we have 
H (MA', AA"), the projectivity is parabolic. 

Proof The double point M and the two pairs of homologous 
points A A', A' A" are sufficient to determine the projectivity uniquely; 
and there is a parabolic projectivity satisfying the given conditions. 

74. Projective projectivities. Let TT be a projectivity on a lino I, 
and let ir^ be a projectivity transforming the points of I into the 
points of another or the same line I'. The projectivity -n-^TTf 1 is then 
a projectivity on I'. Tor wf 1 transforms any point of I' into a point 
of I, IT transforms this point into another point of I, which m turn is 
transformed into a point of V by w r Thus, to every point of V is made 
to correspond a unique point of I', and this correspondence is projec- 
tive, since it is the product of protective correspondences. Clearly, 
also, the projectivity ^ transforms any pair of homologous points of 
TT into a pair of homologous points of w^TTf 1 . 

DEFINITION. The projectivity WjWTrf 1 is called the transform of IT 
ly 7r x ; two projectivities are said to be protective or conjugate if one 
is a transform of the other by a projectivity. 

The question now arises as to the conditions under which two pro- 
jectivities are projective or conjugate. A necessary condition is evi- 
dent. If one of two conjugate projectivities has two distinct double 
points, the other must likewise have two distinct double points; if 
one has no double points, the other likewise can have no double points; 
and if one is parabolic, the other must be parabolic. The further 
conditions are readily derivable in the case of two projectivities with 
distinct double points and in the case of two parabolic projectivities. 
They are stated in the two following theorems : 

THEOREM 4. Two projectivities each of which has two distinct double 
points are conjugate if and only if their characteristic throws are equal, 

Proof. The condition is necessary. For if TT, TT' are two conjugate 
projectivities, any projectivity ir^ transforming TT into TT' transforms 
the double points M, N of TT into the double points M 1 , N' of ir 1 , and 
also transforms any pair of homologous points A, A v of TT into a pair 
of homologous points A 1 , A^ of TT' ; i e. 



But this states that their characteristic throws are ecjual 



74,75] GROUPS ON A LINE 209 

The condition is also sufficient; for if it is satisfied, tho projec- 
tivity TT, defined by 



clearly transforms TT into TT'. 

COROLLAEY. Any two involutions with double points are conjugate. 
THEOREM 5. Any two parabolic projectivities are conjugate. 

Proof. Let the two parabolic projectivities be defined by 
ir(MMA}=*MMAv and ir'(M'M' A 1 ) - M'M'Af. 
Then the projectivity 71^ defined by 



clearly transforms TT into IT'. 

Since the characteristic cross ratio of any parabolic projectivity is 
unity, the condition of Theorem. 4 may also be regarded as holding 
for parabolic projectivities. 

75. Groups of projectivities on a line. DEFINITION. Two groups G 
and G' of projectivities on a line are said to be conjugate if there 
exists a projectivity ir^ which transforms every projectivity of G into a 
projectivity of G', and conversely. We may then write ir^-ir- 1 = G / ; 
and G' is said to be the transform of G "by ir f 

We have already seen (Theorem 8, Chap III) that the set of all 
projectivities on a line form a group, which is called the general pro- 
jective group on the line. The following are important subgroups : 

1. The set of all projectivities leaving a given point of the line 
invariant. 

Any two groups of this type are conjugate Tor any projectivity 
transforming the invariant point of one group into the invariant point 
of the other clearly transforms every projectivity of the one into 
some projectivity of the other Analytically, if we choose % = oo as 
the invariant point of the group, the group consists of all projectivities 

of the form 

#'= asa + b. 

2. The set of all projectivities leaving two given distinct points 
invariant. 

Any two groups of this type are conjugate. For any projectivity 
transforming the two invariant points of the one into the invariant 
points of the other clearly transforms every projectivity of the one 



210 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP vm 

into a projectivity of the other Analytically, if x lt x a are the two 
invariant points, the group consists of all projectivities of the farm 




The product of two such projectivities with multipliers & and lc' is 
clearly given by 



, 

tAs ^ v(J* 






30 



This shows that any two projectivities of this group are commuta- 
tive. This result gives 

THEOREM 6. Any two projectivities which have two double points 
in common are commutative. 

This theorem is equivalent to the commutative law for multiplication. 
If the double points are the points and oo, the gioup consists of all piojccs- 
tivities of the form yf ax. 

3. The set of all parabolic projectivities with a common double point 
In order to show that this set of projectivities is a group, it is only 
necessary to show that the product of two parabolic projectivities 
with the same double point is parabolic This follows readily from 
the analytic representation. The set of projectivities above described 
consists of all transformations of the form 

1 - l 4-f 

- - -f- (, 

/yi ^ M / M _ M 

tfj |/- |A/ "- tAj 

where x^ is the common double point (Theorem 3, Cor. 1). If 

~~j ^ | and . ~ ___ _j_ j 
x' x l jj x ar ajj ta ^ a 

are two projectivities of this set, the product of the first by the second 
is given by 11 

r'r ~ v v +t i +i *> 

tb *""* iA/- tfa " tXj't 

which is clearly a projectivity of the set. It showa, moreover, that 
any two projectivities of this group are commutative. Whence 

THEOREM 7, Any two parabolic projectivities on a line with the 
same double point are commutative. 

This theorem is independent of Assumption P, although this assumption 
is implied in the pi oof we have given. The theorem has already been proved 
without thia assumption in Example 2, p. 70, 



75] GEOUPS ON A LINE 211 

Any two groups of this type are conjugate. For every projectmty 
transforming the double point of one group into the double point of 
the other transforms the one group into the other, since the projec- 
tive transform of a parabolic projectivity is parabolic 

DEFINITION. Two subgroups of a group G are said to be conjugate 
under G if there exists a transformation of G which transforms one 
of the -subgroups into the other. A subgroup of G is said to be self- 
conjugate or invariant wider G if it is transformed into itself by 
every transformation of G; ie if every transformation in G trans- 
forms any transformation of the subgroup into another (or the same) 
transformation of the subgroup. 

We have seen that any two groups of any one of the three types 
are conjugate subgroups of the general protective group on the line. 
We may now give an example of a self-conjugate subgroup. 

The set of all parabolic projectivities in a group of Type 1 above is 
a self-conjugate subgroup of this group. It is clearly a subgroup, since 
it is a group of Type 3. And it is self-conjugate, since any conjugate 
of a parabolic projectivity is parabolic, and since every projectivity of 
the group leaves the common double point invariant. 

EXERCISES 

1. Wiite the equations of all the protective transformations which permute 
among themselves (a) the points (0,1), (1,0), (1,1), (&) the points (0, 1), 
(1,0), (1,1), (a, ft), (<0 the points (0,1), (1,0), (1,1), (-1,1). What 
are the equations of the self-conjugate subgroup of the group of transforma- 
tions (a)? 

2. If a projectivity of = (ac + Z)/(ca; + d) having two distinct double ele- 
ments be written in the form of Cor. 3, Theorem 1, show that 

^t^ (1 + fr) 2 (a + <*) 2 
that v . = , / 
k ad be 

3. If a parabolic projectivity xf = (ax + V)/(cx + d) be written in the form 
of Theorem 8, Cor. 1, show that m = (a d)/2 c, and t 2 c/(a + a") 

4. Show that a projectivity with distinct double points x v x z and charac- 
teristic cross ratio k can. be written in the form 

a; 1 

* ^ i 
ar a fcc 9 1 

ar= x 1 
a? 1 1 



212 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTTVITIES [CKAP. VIII 

5. Show tli.it the parabolic project! vity oE Theorem 8, Cor. 1, may be 

written in the form 

a; 1 

1 1 

I te. + l 

1M* * 

* ~ x 1 

,'! 1 1 

1 t 

6. If by means of a suitably chosen transfoimation of a group any of the 
elements transformed may be tiansformed into any othei element, the group 
is said to be tramitwe. If by a suitably chosen traiibfoimation of a group any 
set of n distinct elements may be tiansformed into any othei set of n distinct 
elements, and if this is not true for all sets of n + 1 distinct elements, the 
gioup is said to be n-ply transitive. Show that the general projective group on 
a line is tuply transitive, and that of the subgroups listed in 75 the first 
is doubly tiansitive and the other two are simply tiansitive. 

7. If two projectivities on a line, each having two distinct double points, 
have one double point in common, the characteristic cross latio of then prod- 
uct is equal to the product of theii characteristic cross ratios. 

76. Projective transformations between conies. We have consid- 
ered hitherto projectivities between one-dimensional forms of the 
first degree only. We shall now see how projectivities exist also be- 
tween one-dimensional forms of the second degree, and also between 
a one-dimensional form of the first and one of the second degree. 
Many familiar theorems will hereby appear in a now light. 

As typical for the one-dimensional forms of the second degree wo 
choose the conic. The corresponding theorems for the cone then 
follow by the principle of duality. 

Let TT X be a projective collmeation between two planes a, <x v and 
let <7 2 be any conic in cc. Any two projective pencils of lines in a 
are then transformed by ^ into two projective pencils of lines in <x lt 
such that any two homologous lines of the pencils in <x are trans- 
formed into a pair of homologous lines in t\ ; for if IT be the projoc- 
tivily between the pencils in a, ^Tm-f 1 will be a projectivily between 
the pencils in ^ (cf. 74). Two projective pencils of lines generating 
the conic C? 2 thus correspond to two pencils of linos in ^ generating 
a conic Cf. The transformation ^ then transforms every point of (7 a 
into a unique point of 0%, Similarly, it is seen that ^ transforms 
every tangent of <7 a into a unique tangent of C*, 

DEFINITION. Two conies are said to be protective if to every point of 
one corresponds a point of the other, and to every tangent of one 



70] 



TRANSFORMATION OF CONICS 



213 



corresponds a tangent of the other, in such a way that this correspond- 
ence may be brought about by a projective collineation between the 
planes of the conies The projective collineation is then said to 
generate the projectivity between the comes. 

Two conies in dii'feient pianos are piojective, for example, if one is the pro- 
jection of the other from a point on neithei of the two planes If the second 
of these is projected back on the plane of the first from a new center, we 
obtain two conies in the same plane that are projective We will see presently 
that two projective conies may also coincide, in which case we obtain a pro- 
jectivity on a conic. 

THEOREM 8. Two conies that are protective with a third are 
projeetive, 

Proof. This is an immediate consequence of the definition and the 
fact that the resultant of two collmeations is a collineation. 

We proceed now to prove the fundamental theorem for projec- 
tivities between two comes. 

THEOREM 9. A projectivity between two conies is uniquely deter- 
mined if three distinct points (or tangents) of one are made to corre- 
spond to three distinct points (or tangents) of the other 



C' 





PIG 80 



Proof. Let C'\ C f 1 a be the two conies (fig. 86), and let A, 3, be 
three points of C z , and A', B', C' the corresponding points of Cf. Let 
P and P' be the poles of AB and A'B' with respect to C* and C\ 
respectively. If now the collineation IT is defined by the relation 
7r(ABCP)=A r J3'C'P' (Theorem 18, Chap. IV), it is clear that the 
conic <7 a is transformed by ir into a conic through the points A', B 1 , C', 
with tangents A'P' and B'P r > This conic is uniquely determined by 
these specifications, however, and is therefore identical with C7 x a . The 
collineation tr then transforms (7 a into C* in such a way that the 
points A, B, are transformed into A', B', C' respectively. Moreover, 



214 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES [CHAP VIII 

suppose TT' were a second collmeation transforming C z into C? in the 
way specified Then w'-V would be a collineation leaving A, B, C, P 
invariant , i.e TT = TT'. 

The argument applies equally well if A'J3'C' are on the conic C*, 
i e. when the two conies C' 2 , C* coincide. In this case the projectivity 
is on the conic 0. This gives 

COROLLARY 1. A projectivity on a conic is uniquely determined when 
three pairs of homologous elements (points or tangents') are given. 

Also from the proof of the theorem follows 

COROLLARY 2. A collineation in a plane which transforms three 
distinct points of a come into three distinct points of the same conic and 
which transforms the pole of the line joining two of the first three 
points into the pole of the line joining the two corresponding points 
transforms the conic into itself. 

The two following theorems establish the connection between pro- 
jectivities between two conies and projectivities between one-dimen- 
sional forms of the first degree. 

THEOREM 10 If A and B' are THEOREM 10'. If a and I' are 
any two points of two protective any two tangents of two projectile 
conies C z and Cf respectively, the conies C* and Q% respectively, the 
pencils of lines with centers at A pencils of points on a and &' are 
and B'are protective if every pair projective if every pair of homol- 
of homologous lines of these pencils ogous points on these lines is on 
pass through a pair of homologous a pair of homologous tangents of 
points on the two conies respectively, the conies respectively. 

Proof. It will suffice to prove the theorem on the left. Let A 1 be 
the point of (7* homologous with A. The collmeation which generates 
the projectivity between the comes then makes the pencils of lines at 
A and A' projective, in such a way that every pair of homologous 
lines contains a pair of homologous points of the two conies. The pen- 
cil of lines at B' is projective with that at A f if they correspond in 
such a way that pairs of homologous lines intersect on Of (Theorem 
2, Chap. V). This establishes a projective correspondence between 
the pencils at A and B' in which any two homologous lines pass 
through two homologous points of the conies and proves the theorem. 

It should be noted that in this projectivity the tangent to a at A 
corresponds to the line of the pencil at B 1 passing through A 1 . 



76] 



TRANSFORMATION OE CONICS 



215 



COROLLARY. Conversely, if two 
conies correspond in such a way 
that every pair of homologous 
points is on a pair of homologous 
lines of two projectwe pencils of 
lines whose centers are on the 
conies, they are projectile. 



COROLLARY. Conversely, if two 
conies correspond in such a way 
that every pair of homologous tan- 
gents is on a pair of homologous 
points of two protective petals of 
points whose axes are tangents of 
the conies, they are protective. 



Proof. This follows from the fact that the projectivity between the 
pencils of lines is uniquely determined by three pairs of homologous 
lines A projectivity between the conies is also determined by the 
three pairs of points (Theorem 9), in which three pairs of homolo- 
gous lines of the pencils meet the comes. But by what precedes 
and the theorem, above, this projectivity is the same as that described 
in the corollary on the left The corollary on the right may be proved 
similarly If the two comes are in the same plane, it is simply the 
plane dual of the one on the left. 

By means of these two theorems the construction of a projectivity 
between two conies is reduced to the construction of a projectivity 
between two primitive one-dimensional forms. 

It is now in the spirit of our previous definitions to adopt the 
following : 

DEFINITION. A point conic and 
a pencil of lines whose center is a 
point of the conic are said to be 
perspective if they correspond in 
such a way that every point of 
the conic is on the homologous 
line of the pencil. A point conic 
and a pencil ol points are said to 
be perspective if every two homol- 



ogous points are on the same line 
of a pencil of lines whose center 
is a point of the conic. 



DEFINITION. A line conic and 
a pencil of points whose axis is 
a line of the conic are said to be 
perspective if they correspond in 
such a way that every line of the 
conic passes through the homolo- 
gous point of the pencil of points. 
A line conic and a pencil of lines 
are said to be perspective if every 
two homologous lines meet in a 
point of a pencil of points whose 
axis is a line of the conic. 



The reader will now readily verify that with this extended use of 
the term perspective, any sequence of perspectivities leads to a pro- 
jectivity. For example, two pencils of lines perspective with the same 
point conic are projective by Theorem 2, Chap, "V; two point conies 




216 ONE-DIMENSIOSTAX PROJEGTIVITIES [CHA* vm 

perspective with the same pencil of lines or with the same pencil of 
points are proiective by Theorem 10, Cor., etc. ^ 

Another illustration of this extension of the notion of perspectivity 
leads readily to the f oUowing important theorem : 

THEOREM 11 Two conies whicJi are not in tU same plane and have 

a common tangent at a point A are sections of one and the same cone. 

Proof. If the two conies C\ Of (fig 87) are made to correspond 

in such'a way that every tangent * of one is associated with that 

tangent x 1 of the other 
which meets re in a 
point of the common 
tangent a of the conies, 
they are projective, 
Tor the tangents of 
the conies are then, 
perspective with the 
FlG> 87 same pencil of points 

(cf Theorem 10', Cor.). Every pair of homologous tangents of the two 
comes determines a plane. If we consider the point of intersection 
of three of these planes, say, those determined by the pairs of tangents 
W cc' dd', and project the conic Cf on the plane of <7 2 from 0, there 
results a conic in the plane of 0\ This conic has the lines &, c, d for 
tangents and is tangent to a at .4; it therefore coincides with C 
(Theorem 6', Chap. V). The two conies C\ 0} then have the same 
projection from 0, which proves the theorem.* 

EXERCISES 

1. State the theorems concerning cones dual to the theorems of the preced- 
ing sections. , . j. u 

2 By dualizing the definitions of the last article, define what is meant by 
the perspectivity "between cones and the primitive one-dimensional forms. 

3 If two projective comes have three self-corresponding points, they are 
perspective with a common pencil of lines. 

4. If two projective comes have four self-corresponding elements, tney 

coincide. 

5. State the space duals of the last two propositions. 

It will he seen later that this tbaopfe leads to the proposition, that any conic 
may he ohtained as the projection of a oWftj tangent t<|> It In, WteW* P^e, 

' ' 



76, 77] 



PEOJECTIVITIES ON A CONIC 



217 



6 If a pencil of lines and a conic in the plane of the pencil are projective, 
but not perspective, not more than thiee lines of the pencil pass through then 
homologous points on the conic (Hint. Con&idei the points of intersection of 
the given conic with the conic generated by the given pencil and a pencil of 
lines pei&pective with the given conic ) Dualize. 

7. The homologous lines of a hue conic and a projective pencil of lines in 
the same plane intersect in points of a " cuive of the third order" such that 
any line of the plane has at most three points in common with it. (This fol- 
lows readily from the last exercise ) 

8 The homologous elements of a cone of lines and a projective pencil of 
planes meet in a " space curve of the third oider" such that any plane has 
at most thiee points in common with it. 

9. Dualize the last two propositions 

77. Projectivities on a conic. We have seen that two projective 
conies may coincide (Theorems 8-10), in which case we obtain a 
projective correspondence among the points or the tangents of the 




TIG. 88 



conic. The construction of the projectivity in this case is very 
simple, and leads to many important results. It results from the 
following theorems". 

THEOREM 12. If A, A' are any THEOREM 12' If a, a' are any 

two distinct "homologous points of two distinct homologous tangents 

a projectivity on a conic, and]) } B'; of a projectivity on a conic, and 

C, C f ; etc , are any other pairs of I, V ; c, c'; etc., are any other pairs 



218 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJEGTIVITIES [OKAP.VIII 



homologous points, the lines A'B of honioloyouit twiffentH, the 
and AJB', A'G and AC', etc, meet a'b and ah', a'n <md tin', de., nre 
in points of the same hue ; and eolFuiear with the, mine point,; 
this line is independent of the pair and tins point is independent, of 
AA' chosen. Mw pw ' /. 

Proof The pencils of lines A' (ABC- ) and A(A'Ji'C'' - ) are pro- 
jeotive (Theorem 10), and since they have a solf-comjspondinju' line 
AA', they are perspective, and the pairs of homologous lines of these 
two pencils therefore meet m the points of a line (iig. 88). This 
proves the first part of the theorem on the left. That the line thus 
determined is independent of the homologous pair AA 1 chosen then 
follows at once from the fact this line is the Pascal lino of the simple 
hexagon AB'QA'BC', so that the lines JB'C and JiQ' and all other 
analogously formed pairs of lines meet on it. The theorem on the 
right follows by duality. 

DEFINITION. The line and the point determined by the above dual theo- 
rems are called the axis and the center of the projectivity respectively. 

COROLLARY 1. A (nonidentical) COROLLARY 3 ; . A (nonidenti- 

projectiwty on a conic is uniquely cal) projectivity on a conic is 

determined when the axis of pro- uniquely determined when the 

jectimty and one pair of distinct center and one pair of distinct 

homologous points are given. homologous tangents are given. 

These corollaries follow directly from the construction of the pro- 
jectivity arising from the above theorem. This construction is as 
follows: Given the axis o and a pair of distinct homologous points 
AA' } to get the point P' homologous with any point P on the conic j 
join PtoA'; the point P' is then on the line joining A to the point 
of intersection of A'P with o. Or, given the center and a pair of 
distinct homologous tangents aa' t to construct the tangent / homolo- 
gous with any tangent p ; the line joining the point a'p to the center 
meets a in a point of jt/. 

COROLLAKY 2 Every dvulle CoBOLLABT 2'. flv&ry double 

point of a projectimty on a conic line of a pro/eetiwty on a, conic 

is on the axis of the projectfoity ; contains the center of the projec- 

and, conversely, every point com^ tivity; anfc, 

mon to the axis and the conic is ff ent 
a doulle point. 




77] 



PEOJECTIVITIES ON A CONIC 



219 



COROLLARY 3. A projectivity COROLLAEY 3'. A projectivity 

among the points on a come is among the tangents to a conic is 

parabolic if and only if the axis parabolic if and only if the center 

is tangent to the conic. is a point of the conic. 

THEOREM: 13 A projectimty among the points of a conic determines 
a projectimty of the tangents in which the tangents at pairs of homol- 
ogous points are homologous 

Proof. This follows at once from the fact that the collineation in 
the plane of the conic which generates the projectivity transforms 
the tangent at any point of the conic into the tangent at the homol- 
ogous point, and hence also generates a projectivity between the 
tangents. 

THEOREM 14. The center of a projectimty of tangents on a conic 
and the axis of the corresponding projectimty of points are pole and 
polar with respect to the conic. 




Proof Let AA' } BB', CO' (fig. 89) be three pairs of homologous 
points (AA 1 being distinct), and let A'B and AB' } A'C and AG', meet 
in points R and 8 respectively, which determine the axis of the pro- 
jectivity of points. Now the polar of E with, respect to the conic is 
determined by the intersections of the pairs of tangents at A', B and 
A, B' respectively ; and the polar of 8 is determined by the pairs of 
tangents at A', C and A, C' respectively (Theorem 13, Chap. V). The 
pole of the axis RS is then determined as the intersection of these 



220 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP VIII 

two polars (Theorem 17, Chap V). But by definition these two polars 
also determine the center of the projectivity of tangents. 

This theorem is obvious if the projectivity has double elements ; the proof 
given, however, applies to all cases. 

The collmeation generating the projectivity on the conic transforms 
the conic into itself and clearly leaves the center and axis invariant. 
The set of all collineations in the plane leaving the conic invariant 
form a group (of. p 67). In determining a transformation of this 
group, any point or any line of the plane may be chosen arbitrarily 
as a double point or a double line of the collmeation ; and any two 
points or lines of the conic may be chosen as a homologous pair of 
the collineation. The collmeation is then, however, uniquely deter- 
mined. In fact, we have already seen that the projectivity on the 
conic is uniquely determined by its center and axis and one pair of 
homologous elements (Theorem 12, Cor. 1); and the theorem just 
proved shows that if the center of the projectivity is given, the axis 
is uniquely determined, and conversely 

COROLLARY 1 A plane protective collineation which leaves a non- 
degenerate come in its plane invariant is of Type I if it has two 
double points on the conic, unless it is of period two, in which case it 
is of Type IV; and is of Type III if the corresponding projectivity 
on the conic is parabolic 

COROLLARY 2. An elation or a collineation of Type II transforms 
every nondegenerate conic of its plane into a different conic. 

COROLLARY 3. A plane protective collineation which leaves a conic 
in its plane invariant and has no double point on the conic has one 
and only one double point in the plane. 

THEOREM 15 The group of protective collineations in a plane leav- 
ing a nondegenerate conic invariant is simply isomorphic* with the 
general projective group on a line. 

Proof. Let A be any point of the invariant conic. Any projectivity 
on the conic then gives rise to a projectivity in the flat pencil at A in 
which two lines are homologous if they meet the conic in a pair of 
homologous points. And, conversely, any projectivity in the flat 

* Two groups are said to be simply isomorphic it it is possible to establish a (1,1) 
correspondence between the elements of the two^ groups such that to the product of 
any two elements of one of the groups corresponds the product of the two corre- 
sponding elements of the other. - 

~ ' ' 



77,78] INVOLUTIONS 221 

pencil at A gives rise to a projectivity on the conic. The group of all 
projectivities on a conic is therefore simply isomorphic with the group 
of all projectivities in a flat pencil, since it is clear that in the corre- 
spondence described between the projectrvities in the flat pencil and 
on the conic, the products of corresponding pairs of projectivities will 
be corresponding projectivities. Hence the group of plane collineations 
leaving the conic invariant is simply isomorphic with the general pro- 
jective group in a flat pencil and hence with the general protective 
group on a line 

78. Involutions. An involution was defined (p. 102) as any projec- 
tivity in a one-dimensional form which is of period two, i.e. by the 
relation I 2 = 1 (I = 1), where I represents an involution. This relation 
is clearly equivalent to the other, I = I~ 1 (I=f= 1), so that any projec- 
tivity (not the identity) in a one-dimensional form, which is identical 
with its inverse, is an involution It will be recalled that since an in- 
volution makes every pair of homologous elements correspond doubly, 
i.e. A to A 1 and A' to A, an involution may also be considered as a 
pairing of the elements of a one-dimensional form ; any such pair is 
then called a conjugate pair of the involution. We propose now to 
consider this important class of projectivities more in detail. To this 
end it seems desirable to collect the fundamental properties of invo- 
lutions which have been obtained in previous chapters. They are as 
follows : 

1. If the relation TT* (A) = A "holds for a, single element A (not a 
double element of IT) of a one-dimensional form, the projectivity IT is 
an involution, and the relation holds for every element of the form 
(Theorem 26, Chap. IV). 

2. An involution is uniquely determined when two pairs of conju- 
gate elements are given (Theorem 26, Cor., Chap. IV). 

3. The opposite pairs of any quadrangular set are three pairs of 
an involution (Theorem 27, Chap. IV). 

4. If M, N are distinct double elements of any projectivity in a 
one-dimensional form and A, A' and B, B 1 are any two pairs of 
"homologous elements of the projectivity, the pairs of elements MN, AJB' 
A'B are three pairs of an involution (Theorem 27, Cor. 3, Chap. IV), 

5. If M, J?V are double elements of an involution, they are distinct, 
and every conjugate pair of the involution is harmonic with M> N 
(Theorem 27, Cor. 1, Chap. IV). 



222 



ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP.VIII 



6. An involution is uniquely determined, if two double elements are 
given, or if one double element and another conjugate pair are given. 
(This follows directly from the preceding.) 

7. An involution is represented analytically by a "bilinear form 
cxx'a(x + #') 6 = 0, or "by the transformation 



ex a 
(Theorem 12, Cor. 3, Chap. VI). 

8. An involution with double elements m, n may "be represented "by 
the transformation 



(Theorem 1, Cors. 2, 3, Chap. VIII). 

We recall, finally, the Second Theorem of Desargues and its various 
modifications ( 46, Chap. V), which need not be repeated at this 
place. It has been seen in the preceding sections that any projec- 
tivity in a one-dimensional primitive form may be transformed into a 
projeotivity on a conic. We shall find that the construction of an in- 
volution on a conic is especially simple, and may be used to advantage 
in deriving further properties of involutions. Under duality we may 

confine our consideration 

*V to the case of an involu- 

tion of points on a conic. 
THEOREM 16. The lines 
joining the conjugate points 
of an involution on a conic 
all pass through the center 
of the involution. 

Proof. Let ^U' (fig. 90) 
be any conjugate pair (A 
not a double point) of an 
involution of points on a 
conic C*. The line A A' is then an invariant line of the coUioeation. gener- 
ating the involution. Every line joining a pair of <iisti:ao!t conjugate 
points of the involution is therefore invariant, and the generating 
collineation must be a perspective collineatiqni, sinjce a&^joajjlfiaeatian 
leaving four lines invariant is either $ertp<|trvje bl rib* I Id^iiithr 

1 ' F ! * ' * j] i> j j i i i i 




. 90 





78] INVOLUTIONS 223 

(Theorem 9, Cor. 3, Chap III) It remains only to show that the 
center of this perspective colhueation is the center of the involution. 
Let B, B' (B not a double point) be any other conjugate pair of the 
involution, distinct from A, A'. Then the lines AB' and A'B inter- 
sect on the axis of the involution. But since B, B' correspond to each 
other doubly, it follows that the lines AB and A'B' also intersect 
on the axis. This axis then joins two of the diagonal points of the 
quadrangle AA'BB' The center of the perspective collineation is 
determined as the intersection of the lines A A' and BB', le it is 
the third diagonal point of the quadrangle AA'BB'. The center of 
the collineation is therefore the pole of the axis of the involution 
(Theorem 14, Chap. V) and is therefore (Theorem 14, above) the center 
of the involution 

Since this center of the involution is clearly not on the conic, the 
generating collineation of any involution of the conic is a homology, 
whose center and axis are pole and polar with respect to the conic. 
A homology of period two is sometimes called a harmonic homol- 
ogy, since it transforms any point P of the plane into its harmonic 
conjugate with respect to and the point in which OP meets 
the axis. It is also called a projective reflection or a point-line reflec- 
tion. Clearly this is the only kind of homology that can leave a conic 
invariant 

The construction of the pairs of an involution on a conic is now 
very simple. If two conjugate pairs A, A' and B, B' are given, the lines 
AA' and BB' determine the center of the involution The conjugate 
of any other point G on the conic is then determined as the intersec- 
tion with the conic of the line joining C to the center. If the involu- 
tion has double points, the tangents at these points pass through the 
center of the involution; and, conversely, if tangents can be drawn to 
the conic from the center of the involution, the points of contact of 
these tangents are double points of the involution. 

The great importance of involutions is in part due to the following 
theorem : 

THEOREM 17. Any projeotivity in a one-dimensional form may be 
obtained as the product of two involutions. 

Proof, Let II be the projectivity in question, and let A be any 
point of the one-dimensional form which is not a double point. 



224 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIEtf [CUAP vm 

Further, let 11(4) = A' and ft (A 1 ) = A" Then, if I, is the involution 
of which A' is a double point and of which A A" is a conjugate pair 
(Prop. 6, p. 222), we have 



so that in the projectivity I^II the pair AA 1 corresponds to itself 
doubly. Ii II is therefore an involution (Prop. 1, p. 221). If it he 
denoted by I,, we have I 1 -n = I 2 , or II ^ I 2 , which was to be 
proved 

This proof gives at once : 

COROLLARY 1 Any projectivity IT may be represented ff Me prod- 
uct of two involutions, 11 1^-1^ either of which (but not both) has 
an arbitrary po^nt (not a double point of II) for a double point. 

Proof We have seen above that the involution I x may have an 
arbitrary point (A 1 ) for a double point If 111 the above argument we 
let I 2 be the involution of which A' is a double point and AA" is a 
conjugate- pair, we have II l a (A'A") = A" A!] whence II I 2 is an invo- 
lution, say I r We then have II = I x 1 2 , in which I 8 lias the arbitrary 
point A' for a double point. 

The argument given above for the proof of the theorem applies 
without change when A =A", i.e. when the projectivity II is an in- 
volution This leads readily to the following important theorem : 

COROLLARY 2 If A A' is a conjugate pair of an involution I, the 
involution of which A, A' are double points transforms I into itself, 
and the two involutions are commutative. 

Proof The proof of Theorem 17 gives at once I^Ij-Ig, where Ij 
is determined as the involution of which A, A 1 are double points. We 
have then I t I = I 2 , from which follows, by taking the inverse of both 
sides of the equality, M^I-i^I,, or I^I-My or I^M^-I, 

As an immediate corollary of the preceding we have 

COROLLARY 3. The product of two involutions with double points 
A, A' and B t B' respectively transforms into itself the involution in 
which A A' and B B' are two conjugate pairs. 

Involutions related as are the two in Cor. 2 above are worthy of 
special attention. 

DEFINITION, Two involutions are said to be harmonio it their 
product is an involution. 



s 78, 79] INVOLUTIONS 225 

THEOREM 18. Two harmonic involutions are commutative. 

Proof. If Ij, I 2 are harmonic, we have, by definition, I t I 2 = T 8 , where 
I s is an involution. This gives at once the relations ^ I a I 3 = 1 and 

^i 'a = *%' *r 

COEOLLAEY Conversely, if two distinct involutions arc commutative) 
ttiey are Jiarmonic. 

For from the relation I x - I a = I a - I t follows (I x . I 2 ) 2 = 1 ; i.e. I x . I 2 
is an involution, since I x Ij^l. 

DEFINITION. The set of involutions harmonic with a given involu- 
tion is called a pencil of involutions. 

It follows then from Theorem 17, Cor, 2, that the set of all involu- 
tions in which two given elements form a conjugate pair is a pencil. 
Thus the double points of the involutions of such a pencil are the 
pairs of an involution 

79. Involutions associated with, a given projectivity. In deriving 
further theorems on involutions we shall find it desirable to suppose 
the projectivities in question to be on a conic. 

THEOREM 19. If a projectivity on a conic is represented as the product 
of two involutions, the axis of the projectivity is the line joining the 

centers of the two involutions 

0, 
Proof. Let the given projec- ^ 

tivity be II = I 2 \ ; I v I 2 being 

two involutions. Let O v O z be 

the centers of I t , I 2 respectively 

(fig 91), and let A and B be 

any two points on the conic 

which are not double points of 

either of the involutions I x or I a 

and which are not a conjugate 

pair of I x or I 2 . If, then, we 

have II (AB) = A'B', we have, by ^ 91 

hypothesis, ^(AJS) A^ and 

I a ( J 4 1 J5 1 ) = A'B'-, A v 2?j being uniquely determined points of the conic, 

such that the lines AA V BB^ intersect m O l and the lines A^A', B^B' 

intersect in 2 . The Pascal line of the hexagon AA^A'BB^B' then 

passes through O v O s and the intersection of the lines AB' and A'B. 

But the latter point is a point on the axis of U. This proves the theorem. 




226 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECT IV IT IKS [CirAi-. vm 

COEOLLAEY. A projectivity on a conic, is the, product of two involu- 
tions, the center of one of which may be any arbitrary point (not, a 
double point] on the axis of tlie projectivity ; the cantor of the other 
is then uniquely determined. 

Proof Let the projectivity II be determined by its axis I and any 
pair of homologous points A, A 1 (fig. 93). Let O l bo any point on tho 
axis not a double point of II, and let I t be the involution of which 
O t is the center. If, then, I l (A)^A v the center () a of tho involution 
I 2 such that n = I 2 I x is clearly determined as the intersection of the 
line A^A' with the axis. For by the theorem tho product 7 U / x is a 
projectivity having I for an axis, and it has the points A, A 1 as a homol- 
ogous pair. This shows that the center of the first involution may 
be any point on the axis (not a double point). The modification of 
this argument in order to show that the center of the second involu- 
tion may be chosen arbitrarily (instead of the center of tho first) is 
obvious. 

THEOEEM 20. There is one and only one involution commutative 
with a given nonparabolic noninvolutoric pro/ectimti/. If the projec,- 
timty is represented on a conic, the center of this involution is the 
center of the projectivity. 

Proof Let the given nonparabolic projectivity II be on a conic, 
and let I be any involution commutative with IT ; ie, such that we 
have H . I = I. H. This is equivalent to EM IT" 1 I. That is to say, 
I is transformed into itself by IL Hence the center of I is transformed 
into itself by the collineation generating II, But by hypothesis the 
only invariant points of this collineation are its center and the points 
(if existent) in which its axis meets the conic, Since the center of I 
cannot be on the conic, it must coincide with the center of II, More- 
over, if the center of I is the same as the center of H, I is trans- 
formed into itself by the collineation generating II, II. I. II"" 1 " I. 
Hence 11.1 = 1-11. Hence I is the one and only involution commu- 
tative with H. 

COROLLARY 1. There is no involution commutative with a parabolic 
projectivity. 

DEFINITION. The involution commutativf ;with a given nonpars 
bolic noninvolutoric projectivity is called ^^VQlution Mon to 
the given prajectivity. An involution fe&yuft to 

.,11! 



79] INVOLUTIONS 227 

COHOLLAKY 2 If a nonparabolic projectivity has double points, the 
involution belonging to the projectivity has the same do-Me points. 

For if the axis of the projectivity meets the conic in two points, 
the tangents to the conic at these points meet in the pole of the axis 

It is to be noted that the involution I belonging to a given projec- 
tivity II transforms II into itself, and is transformed into itself by II. 
Indeed, from the relation II I = I II follow at once the relations 
I-II 1 = 11 and n-I-n- 1 ^!. Conversely, from the equation 

n.i-n- 1 follows 11.1=1-11. 

THEOREM 21. The necessary and sufficient condition that two invo- 
lutions on a conie be harmonic is that their centers be conjugate with 
respect to the conic. 

Proof. The condi- 3 A 

tion is sufficient For 
let I x , I a be two invo- 
lutions on the conic 
whose centers O v O z 
respectively are con- 
jugate with respect 
to the conic (fig. 92). 

Let A be any point Fio> 92 

of the conic not a 

double point of either involution, and let l l (A)=A 1 and 
If, then, Ij_ (A') A[, the center 0^ is a diagonal point of the quadrangle 
AA^A'A^, and the center O z is on the side A^A!* Since, by hypothesis, 
O s is conjugate to O x with respect to the conic, it must be the diago- 
nal pomt on A^', i.e. it must be collinear with AA[. We have then 
I z <\i(AA') = A' A, i.e. the projectivity I^L^ is an involution I 8 , The 
center 8 of the involution I 8 is then the pole of the line 0^ with 
respect to the conic (Theorem 19). The triangle O a O a 8 is therefore 
self-polar with respect to the conic. It follows readily also that the 
condition is necessary. For the relation L^ -12 = 13 leads at once to 
the relation I^ I^l,,. If O v 2 , O a are the centers respectively of 
the involutions l v I 2 , I 8 , the former of these two relations shows 
(Theorem 19) that 8 is the pole of the line C^; while the latter 
shows that 2 is the pole of the line X 8 . The triangle O^0 z t is 
therefore self-polar. 




228 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP VIII 

OOEOLLAEY 1. Given any two involutions, there exists a third invo- 
lution which is harmonic with each of the given involutions 

For if we take the two involutions on a conic, the involution whose 
center is the pole with respect to the conic of the line joining the 
centers of the given mvolutions clearly satisfies the condition of the 
theorem for each of the latter 

GOEOLLAEY 2 Three involutions each of which is harmonic to the 
other two constitute, together with the identity, a group. 

COEOLLAKY 3. The centers of all involutions in a pencil of involu- 
tions are collinear. 

THEOEEM 22. The set of all projectivities to which belongs the same 
involution I forms a commutative group. 

Proof If II, H! are two projectivities to each of which belongs the 
involution I, we have the relations I-HM = II and I E^ I = n r 
from which follows I -IE" 1 I^II" 1 and, by multiplication, the rela- 
tion I-n M-H! l^l-IL'U^l^U'Uy which shows that the set 

forms a group. To show 
that any two projectivities 
of this group are commu- 
tative, we need only sup- 
pose the projeotivities 
given on a conic. Let A 
be any point on this 
conic, and let II (A) = A 1 
and II 1 (.4 / ) Al t so that 
TL.>Tl(A) = A' Since the 

PIG. 93 x . , .. 1 T . , 

same involution I belongs, 

by hypothesis, both to II and H v these two projectivities have the 
same axis ; let it be the line I (fig. 93). The point TL^A) A t is now 
readily determined (Theorem 12) as the intersection with the conic of 
the line joining A' to the intersection of the line AA[ with the axis I. 
In like manner, II (A^ is determined as the intersection with the 
conic of the line joining A to the intersection of the line A^A' with 
the axis I. Hence II (A = A{, and hence II - TL^A) *= A[. 

It is noteworthy that when the common axis of the projectivities 
of this group meets the conic in two points, which ,ar6 tliein* common 
double points of all the projectivities of the group, tq (rcojip is the 




79] INVOLUTIONS ' 229 

same as the one listed as Type 2, p 209. If, however, our geometry 
admits of a line in the plane of a come but not meeting the conic, the 
argument just given proves the existence of a commutative group 
none of the projectivities of which have a double point 

THEOREM 23. Two involutions have a conjugate pair (or a doulle 
point} in common if and o\dy if the product of the two involutions 
lias two double points (or is paritbolw] 

Proof Tins follows at once if the involutions are taken on a conic 
For a common conjugate pair (or double point) must be on the line 
jonnug the centers of the two involutions. This line must then meet 
the conic in two points (or be tangent to it) in order that the involu- 
tions may have a conjugate pair (or a double point) in common. 

EXERCISES 

1. Dualize all the theorems and coiollanes of the last two sections. 

2. The product of two involutions on a conic is paiabohc if and only if the 
line joining the centeis of the involutions is tangent to the conic. Dualize. 

3. Any involution of a pencil is uniquely determined when one of its con- 
jugate pahs is given 

4. Let II be a noninvolutoiic piojectivity, and let I be the involution be- 
longing to II; further, let II (A A') = A' A", A being any point on which the 
piojectivity operates which is not a double point, and let I(A") = A Show, 
by taking the piojectivity on a come, that the points A'A[ are harmonic 
with the points A A". 

5. Derive the theoiem of Ex. 4 directly as a corollaiy of Prop. 4, p. 221, 
assuming that the projectivity II has two distinct double points. 

6 From the theorem of Ex. 4 show how to construct the involution be- 
longing to a projectivity II on a line without making use of any double points 
the projectivity may have 

7. A projectivity is uniquely determined if the involution belonging to it 
and one pair of homologous points are given. 

8. The product of two involutions I 1} I a is a projectivity to which belongs 
the involution which is harmonic with each of the involutions I x , I 2 

9. Conversely, every projectivity to which a given involution I belongs can 
be obtained as the product of two involutions haimonic with I. 

10. Show that any two piojectivities TI lt II a may be obtained as the 
product of involutions in the form IL^ =1 I t , II 2 = I 3 I; and hence that the 
product of the two projectivities is given by n^f!]. = I 3 > I 1 

11. Show that a projectivity II I Ij may also be written II = I a -I, I 2 
being a uniquely determined involution , and that in this case the two invo- 
lutions I I are distinct xmless IT is involutoric. 



230 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJEGTIVITIES [OHAP.VIII 

12. Show that if I x , I 2 , I 3 are three involutions of the same pencil, the 
relation (I t I 2 I 8 ) a = 1 must hold 

13 If act?, W, cc f aie the cooidmates of three paiis of points m involution, 

_,, , a' 1) V c c' a - 

show that r = ! 

a' c b a c'b 

80. Harmonic transformations. The definition of harmonic involu- 
tions m the section above is a special case of a more general notion 
which can be defined for (1, 1) transformations of any kind whatever. 

DEFINITION Two distinct transformations A and B are said to be 
harmonic if they satisfy the relation (AB~ 1 ) 2 =1 or the equivalent 
relation (BA" 1 ) 2 = 1, provided that AB" 1 * 1. 

A number of theorems which are easy consequences of this defini- 
tion when taken in conjunction with the two preceding sections are 
stated in the following exercises (Of. C. Segre, Note sur les homo- 
graphies binaires et leur faisceaux, Journal fur die reine mid ange- 
wandte Mathematik, Vol. 100 (1887), pp. 317-330, and H. Wiener, 
Ueber die aus zwei Spiegelungen zusammengesetzten Verwandt- 
schaften, Berichte d. K. sachsischen Gesellschaft der Wissensoliaften, 
Leipzig, Vol. 43 (1891), pp. 644-673 ) 

EXERCISES 

1 If A and B are two distinct involutoric transformations, they are har- 
monic to their product AB. 

2. If three involutoric transformations A, B, T satisfy the relations 
(ABr) 2 = 1, ABIV 1, they are all tlneo harmonic to the transformation AB. 

3. If a transformation S is the product of two involutono transformations 
A, B (i.e 5 = AB) and T is an involutoric transfoimation harmonic to S, then 
we have (ABr) 2 = l 

4. If .4, B, C, A", B', <7 are six points of a line, the involutions A, B, T, 
such that T(AA*) = B'B, A(5B') = C"C, B(CC") = A'A t are all harmonic to 
the same projectivity. Show that if the six points are taken on a conic, this 
proposition is equivalent to Pascal's theorem (Theorem 8, Chap. V). 

5. The set of involutions of a one-dimensional form which are harmonic 
to a given nonparabolac projectivity form a pencil Hence, if an involution 
with double points is harmonic to a projectivity with two double points, the 
two pairs of double points form a harmonic set. 

6. Let o be a fixed point of a line I, and let Q be called the fnUpofa* of a 
S^art to^ and's ' pr vided that C is ^ e harmonic oopfnptt of with 

from O, and ASf have the same mid-point as^^A 'JG" ^ib^Hmi 
mjd-pomt as src t them CA' irSl have the sa^e 4^p]Lj ^<f|: \ 



80,81] SCALE ON A CONIC 231 

7. Any two involutions of tho same one-diiuonsional form determine a 
pencil of involutions. Given two involutions A, B and a point J/, show how 
to construct the olhtu double point of that involution of the pencil of which 
one double point is M 

8 The involutions of conjugate points on a line I -\\ith regard to the conies 
of any pencil o conies in a plane with / ioini a pencil of involutions. 

9. If two nonpaiabohc piojcctivities aie commutative, the involutions 
belonging to them coincide, unless both proj activities aie involutions, in which 
case the involutions may be harmonic 

10. If [II] is the set of projectivities to which belongs an involution I and. 
A and B are two given points, then we have [II(^L)J -T- [II (JB)]. 

11. A conic through two of the foui common points of a pencil of conies 
of Type / meets the conies of the pencil in pans of an involution. Extend 
this theorem to the other types of pencils of comes. Dualize 

12. The pairs of second points of intersection of the opposite sides of a 
complete quadrangle with a conic circumscribed to its diagonal triangle are in 
involution (Stuiin, Die Lehie von den Geometiischen Verwandtschaften, 
Vol I, p. 149). 

81. Scale on a conic. The notions of a point algebra and a scale 
which, we have developed hitherto only for the elements of one- 
dimensional primitive forms may also be studied to advantage on a 
conic. The constructions for the sum and the product of two points 
(numbers) on a conic are remarkably simple. As in the case on the 
line, let 0, 1, co be any three arbitrary distinct points on a conic C z . 
Regarding these as the fundamental points of our scale on the conic, 
the sum and the product of any two points x, y on the conic (which 
are distinct from <x>) are defined as follows : 

DEFINITION. The conjugate of in the involution on the conic 
having oo for a double point and x, y for a conjugate pair is called 
the sum of the two points x, y and is denoted by x + y (fig. 94, left). 
The conjugate of 1 in the involution determined on the conic by the 
conjugate pairs 0, oo and x, y is called the product of the points x t 
y and is denoted by x y (fig. 94, right). 

It will be noted that under Assumption P this definition is entirely 
equivalent to the definitions of the sum and product of two points on 
a line, previously given (Chap. VI). To construct the point x + y on 
the conic (fig. 94), we need only determine the center of the involution 
in question as the intersection of the tangent at oo with the line joining 
the points x, y. The point so + y is then determined as the intersection 
with the conic of the line joining the center to the point 0. Similarly, 



232 ONE-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIYITIES [Ciur. Vill 

to obtain the product of the points x, y we determine the center of the 
involution as the intersection of the lines Ooo and asy. The point s, y 
is then the intersection with the conic of the line joining this center to 





FIG 04 



the point 1. The inverse operations (subtraction and division) lead to 
equally simple constructions Since the scale thus defined is obviously 
projective with the scale on a line, it is not necessary to derive again 
the fundamental propeities of addition and subtraction, multiplication 
and division It is clear from this consideration that tJie points of a 
come form a field with reference to the operations junt defined. This 
fact will be found of use in tlie analytic treatment of conies, 

At this point we will make use of it to discuss the existence of the 
square root of a number in the field of points. It is clear from the 




FIG. 96 



preceding discussion that if a numl^er to satisfies the equation 05 8 a> 
the tangent to the conic at the point a must pass through the inter- 
section of the lines Oco and 1 a (fig, 00). 4. number a* wifl therefore 
Twee a square root in the field if'anjL only if a, tangent w% |e foatofi'to 

* ? ' ' 



81] 



SCALE ON A CONIC 



233 



the conic from the intersection of the lines Ooo and la; and, conversely, 
if the number a has a square root in the field, a tangent can le drawn 
to the conic from this point of intersection. It follows at once that if 
a number a has a square root x, it also has another which is obtained 
by drawing the second tangent to the conic from the point of inter- 
section of the lines Ooo and la. Since this tangent meets the conic 
in a point which is the harmonic conjugate of x with respect to Ooo, 
it follows that this second square root is x. It follows also from 
this construction that the point 1 has the two square roots 1 and 1 
in any field in which 1 and 1 are distinct, ie whenever ZT is satisfied. 

We may use these considerations to derive the following theorem, 
which will be used later 

THEOKEM 24. If A A', BE' are any two distinct pairs of an involu- 
tion, there exists one and only one pair CC' distinct from BB' such 
that the cross ratios 
&(AA', BB') and 
B (AA' } CC') are 
equal. 

Proof. Let the ^^ L n _<? 

involution be taken 
on a conic, and let 
the pairs AA f and 
BB' be represented 
by the points Ooo 
and la respectively (fig. 96). Let xx' be any other pair of the invo- 
lution. We then have, clearly from the above, xx l = a. Further, the 
cross ratios in question give 

]J(Oco, la) = i, B(0oo, xx')*=-,. 
a x ' x' 

These are equal, if and only if x' = ax, or if xx 1 = ax*. But this implies 
the relation a ax*, and since we have a =j= 0, this gives a? 2 = 1. The 
only pair of the involution satisfying the conditions of the theorem 
is therefore the pair CC f = 1, a. 

EXERCISES 

1. Show that an involution which has two harmonic conjugate pairs has 
double points if and only if 1 has a square root in the field 

2 Show that any involution may Tbe repiesented by the equation afx = a. 




96 



234 



ONE-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CUAP.VIII 

S The eauation of Ex. 13, p. 230, is the condition that the linen joining 
the three pairs of points aa>, W, f on a conic aie oououironl. 

V Show that if the involution ** = a has a conjugate pa.r W such that 
the cross ratio B(0oo, W) has the value X, the nnmlHi a\ has a Hquaro root 
in the field 

82 Parametric representation of a conic. Let a scale be established 
on a 'come C* by choosing three distinct points of the conic as the 
fundamental points, say, - 0, Jf - oo, A - 1 Then let us establish 
a system of nonhomogeneous point coordinates in the plane of the 
3 conic as follows: Let 

N the line OM be the x- 

axis, with as origin 
and M as oo^. (fig, 07). 
Let the tangents at 
and M to the conic 
meet in a point N, and 
let the tangent ON be 
the y-axis, with N as 
coj,. Finally, let the 
point A be the point 
(1, 1), so that the line 
AN meets the a?-axis 
in the point for which 
te 1, and AM meets 
the y-axis in the point for which y =* 1. Now let P X be any point 
on the conic. The coordinates (x t y} of P are determined by the 
intersections of the lines JPJVand PIT with the o:-axis and the #-axis 
respectively. We have at once the relation 

since the points 0, oo, 1, X on the conic are perspective from M with 
points 0, oo, 1, y on the y-axis. To determine x in terms of X, we note, 
first, that from the constructions given, any line through N meets the 
conic (if at all) in two points whose sum in. the scale is 0, In. par- 
ticular, the points 1, 1 on the conic are colHniSar with N and the 
point 1 on the oj-axis, and the points X, X on the conic are eolliaear 
with JVand the point so on the a?4m S}nc$ the latter point is al^o 
on the line joining and oo on ? t|ie oon,ic, the OQ$str;Ucii<Jtt for multi- 
plication on the conic show^tliati anv, line tntouizh !thi Itiiblat & 




. 97 




82] PARAMETRIC REPRESENTATION 235 

the x-axis meets the conic (if at all) m two points whose product is 
constant, and hence equal to A 2 . The line joining the point x on the 
aj-axis to the point 1 on the conic therefore meets the conic again in 
the point A 2 . But now we have 0, co, 1, X 2 on the conic perspective 
from the point 1 on the conic with the points 0, <x>, 1, x on the 
tf-axis. This gives the relation 

a; = A 2 . 

We may now readily express these relations in. homogeneous form 
If the triangle OHN is taken as triangle of reference, ON heing 
x l = 0, OM being # a 0, and the point A being the point (1,1, 1), 
we pass from the nouhomogeneous to the homogeneous by simply 
placing x = %i/x z , y = M a /% s - The points of the come <7 a may then 
le represented by the relations 

(1) ^rtfgitfgSsX^X: 1 

This agrees with our preceding results, since the elimination of X 
between these equations gives at once 

a; 2 -aV 3 =0, 

which we have previously obtained as the equation of the conic. 

It is to be noted that the point M on the conic, which corresponds 
to the value X = co, is exceptional in this equation. This exceptional 
character is readily removed by writing the parameter X homogene- 
ously X = X 1 -X 2 . Equations (1) then readily give 

THEOREM 25. A conic may le represented analytically "by the equa- 
tions cc l ;x, i :x s = X 2 . \\ z : X, 2 . 

This is called a parametric representation of a conic. 

EXERCISES 

1. Show that the equation of the line joimng two points A t , A 2 on the conic 
(1) above is a: t (A x + A 2 ) jr a + AiA.^ = , and that the equation of the tan- 
gent to the conic at a point A x is x l 2 Ajo: 2 + \iZ s 0. Dualize. 

5J. Show that any collineation leaving the conic (1) invariant is of the form 
atf J ar 2 ' : z,' - a 2 *, + 2 a#r g + /8%? B : ay^ + (08 + y) x z + @8x 3 y*^ + 2 ySo; 2 + S V 
(Hint Use the parametric representation of the conic and let the projectivity 
generated on the conic by the collineation be Af = oA 4 + /3A a , A.J = y\i + SA,.) 



CHAPTER IX 

GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS. INVARIANTS 

83. The degree of a geometric problem. The specification of a line 
by two of its points may be regarded as a geometric operation* 1 The 
plane dual of this operation is the specification of a point by two 
lines In space we have hitherto made use of the following geometric 
operations the specification of a line by two planes (this is the 
space dual of the first operation mentioned above) ; the specification 
of a plane by two intersecting lines (the space dual of the second 
operation above) ; the specification of a plane by three of its points 
or by a point and a line ; the specification of a point by three planes 
or by a plane and a line. These operations are known as linear 
operations or operations of the first degree, and the elements deter- 
mined by them from a set of given elements are said to be obtained 
by linear constructions, or by constructions of the first degree. The 
reason for this terminology is found in the corresponding analytic 
formulations Indeed, it is at once clear that each of the two linear 
operations in a plane corresponds analytically to the solution of a 
pan- of linear equations; and the linear operations m space clearly 
correspond to the solution of systems of three equations, each of the 
first degree. Any problem which can be solved by a finite sequence 
of linear constructions is said to be a linear problem or a proUem 
of the first degree. Any such problem has, if determinate, one and 
only one solution. 

In the usual representation of the ordinary leal project geometry in a 
plane by means of points and hues dia*n, let us say, with a pencil on a sheet 

* u P6r A Constructions are evidently those that can be carried 

out by the use of a straightedge alone There is no familmr mechanical 



to tse o dvenel e ? ^ T* 3 M A& *** as a Despondence whereby 





83] DEGREE OF A GEOMETRIC PROBLEM 237 

device for di awing lines and planes in space. But a pictuie (which is the 
section by a plane of a projection fioin a point) of the lines and points of 
intei section of linearly constructed planes may bo constructed with a stiaight- 
edge (cf. the definition of a plane). 

As examples of linear problems we mention (a) the determination 
of the point homologous with a given point in a projectivity on a 
hue of which three pairs of homologous points are given; (I) the 
determination of the sixth point of a quadrangular set of which five 
points are given ; () the determination of the second double point 
of a projectivity on a line of which one double point and two pairs of 
homologous points are given (this is equivalent to (&) ) ; (d) the deter- 
mination of the second point of intersection of a line with a conic, one 
point of intersection and four other points of the conic being given, etc. 

The analytic relations existing between geometric elements offer 
a convenient means of classifying geometric problems.* Confining 
ourselves, for the sake of brevity, to problems in a plane, a geometric 
problem consists in constructing certain points, lines, etc., which bear 
given relations to a certain set of points, lines, etc, which are sup- 
posed given in advance. In fact, we may suppose that the elements 
sought are points only ; for if a line is to be determined, it is sufficient 
to determine two points of this line ; or if a conic is sought, it is suffi- 
cient to determine five points of this conic, etc. Similar considera- 
tions may also be applied to the given elements of the problem, 
to the effect that we may assume these given elements all to be 
points. This merely involves replacing any given elements that are 
not points by certain sets of points having the property of uniquely 
determining these elements Confining our discussion to problems in 
which this is possible, any geometric problem may be reduced to 
one or more problems of the following form: Given in a plane a 
certain finite number of points, to construct a, point which shall bear 
to the given points certain given relations. 

In the analytic formulation of such a problem the given points 
are supposed to be determined by their coordinates (homogeneous or 
nonhomogeneous), referred to a certain frame of reference. The ver- 
tices of this frame of reference are either points contained among the 
given points, or some or all of them are additional points which we 

* The remainder of this section follows closely the discussion given in Castel 
nuovo, Lezioni di geometria, Rome-Milan, Vol. I (1904), pp. 407 ff. 



238 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [OHAP.IX 

suppose added to the given points The set of all given points then 
gives rise to a certain set of coordinates, which we will denote by 
1, a, 6, c, ' * and which are supposed known These numbers to- 
gether with all numbers obtainable from them by a finite number of 
rational operations constitute a set of numbers, 

K = [1, a, 6, c, ], 

which we will call the domain of rationality defined ly the data f In 
addition to the coordinates of the known points (which, for the sake 
of simplicity, we will suppose given in nonhomogeneous form), the 
coordinates (x, y) of the point sought must be considered The con- 
ditions of the problem then lead to certain analytic relations which 
these coordinates x, y and a, 6, c must satisfy. Eliminating one 
of the variables, say y, we obtain two equations, 

/i(*)-0, /,(a,y) = 0, 

the first containing ss but not y ; the second, in general, containing 
both x and y The problem is thus replaced by two problems : the 
first depending on the solution of f^x) = to determine the abscissa 
of the unknown point ; the second to determine the ordinate, assum- 
ing the abscissa to be known 

In view of tins fact we may confine ourselves to the discussion of 
problems depending on a single equation with one unknown. Such 
problems may be classified according to the equation to which they 
give rise. A problem is said to be algebraic if the equation on which 
its solution depends is algebraic, i.e. if this equation can be put in 
the form 

(1) x n + ttjaf-H a a a3 B - 2 + . . . + a n - 0, 

in which the coefficients a v # 2 , . . ., n are numbers of the domain of 
rationality defined by the data. Any problem which is not algebraic 
is said to be transcendental Algebraic problems (which alone will 
be considered) may in turn be classified according to the degree n of 

* In case homogeneous coordinates are used, a, &, c, denote the, mutual ratios 
of the codrdmates of the given elements. 

t A moment's consideration will show that the points whose coBrdinates are 
numbers of this domain are the points obtainable from the data by linear construc- 
tions Geometrically, any domain of rationality on a line may be defined as any 
class of points on a line which is closed under harmonic co$strjn&t!ois ; j^e, such 
that *A,BiO are any three points of the class, the harmonid tofriotoa ft A With 
respect to J5 and C is a pomt of the class. , , * \ ! 



83] DEGREE OF A GEOMETRIC PROBLEM 239 

the equation on which their solutions depend. We have thus problems 
of the first degree (already referred to), depending merely on the solution 
of an equation of the first degree; problems of the second degree, 
depending on the solution of an equation of the second degree, etc. 

Account must however be taken of the fact that equation (1) 
may be reducible within the domain K ; in other words, that the left 
member of this equation may be the product of two or more poly- 
nomials whose coefficients are numbers of K. In fact, let us suppose, 
for example, that this equation may be written in the form 



where fa, fa are two polynomials of the kind indicated, and of degrees 
Tij and n z respectively (n t + n s = n). Equation (1) is then equivalent 
to the two equations 

0i(HO, fc(3)-0. 

Then either it happens that one of these two equations, e g. the first, 
furnishes all the solutions of the given problem, in which case fa being 
assumed irreducible in K, the problem is not of degree n, but of degree 
Wj < n ; or, both equations furnish solutions of the problem, in which 
case fa also being assumed irreducible in K, the problem reduces to 
two problems, one of degree n l and one of degree n v In speaking of 
a problem of the %th degree we will therefore always assume that 
the associated equation of degree n is irreducible in the domain of 
rationality defined by the data. Moreover, we have tacitly assumed 
throughout this discussion that equation (1) has a root ; we shall see 
presently that this assumption can always be satisfied by the intro- 
duction, if necessary, of so-called improper elements. It is important 
to note, however, since our Assumptions A, E, P do not in any way 
limit the field of numbers to which the coordinates of all elements 
of our space belong, and since equations of degree greater than one 
do not always have a root m a given field when the coefficients of 
the equation belong to this field, there exist spaces in which problems 
of degree higher than the first may have no solutions. Thus in the 
ordinary real projective geometry a problem of the second degree 
will have a (real) solution only if the quadratic equation on which 
it depends has a (real) root. 

The example of a problem of the second degree given in the next 
section will serve to illustrate the general discussion given above. 



240 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP rx 

84. The intersection of a given line with a given conic. Given a 
conic denned, let us say, by three points A, B, C and the tangents at 
A and B , to find the points of intersection of a given line with this 
conic. Using nonhomogeneous coordinates and choosing as C-axis one 
of the given tangents to the conic, as ^-axis the line joining the points 
A and B, and as the point (1, 1) the point C, the equation of the conic 
may be assumed to be of the form 



The equation of the given line may then be assumed to be of the form 



The domain of rationality defined by the data is in this case 

K -[!,*, 2]. 

The elimination of y between the two equations above then leads to 
the equation 

(1) s? px # = 0. 

This equation is not m general reducible in the domain K. The 
problem of determining the points of intersection of an arbitrary line 
in a plane with a given conic in this plane is then a problem of the 
second degree If equation (1) has a root in the field of the geometry, it 
is clear that this root gives rise to a solution of the problem proposed ; 
if this equation has no root in the field, the problem has no solution. 
If, on the other hand, one point of intersection of the line with the 
conic is given, so that one root of equation (1), say x r, is known, 
the domain given by the data is 

*'-[!, !,&*], 

and in this domain (1) is reducible , in fact, it is equivalent to the 
equation 

(x + rp) (x r)=Q. 

The problem of finding the remaining point of intersection then 
Depends merely on the solution of the linear equation 



* There is no loss in generality in assuming this form; for if in the choice of 
coordinates the equation of the given line -were of the form aj *= c, we should' merely 
have to choose the other tangent as x-axis to bring the problem into the form here 
assumed. 



84, 85] 



PROPOSITION 



241 



that is, the problem is of the first degree, as already noted among 
the examples of linear problems. 

It is important to note that equation (1) is the most general form 
of equation of the second degree. It follows that every problem of the 
second degree in a plane can be reduced to the construction of the points 
of intersection of an arbitrary line with a particular conic. We 
shall return to tins later ( 86). 

85. Improper elements. Proposition K a . We have called attention 
frequently to the fact that the nature of the field of points on a line 
is not completely determined by Assumptions A, E, P, under which 
we are working We have seen in particular that this field may be 
finite or infinite. The example of an analytic space discussed in the 
Introduction shows that the theory thus far developed applies equally 
well whether we assume the field of points on a line to consist of all 
the ordinary rational numbers, or of all the ordinary real numbers, 
or of all the ordinary complex numbers. According to which of these 
cases we assume, our space may be said to be the ordinary rational 
space, or the ordinary real space, or the ordinary complex space. 
Now, in the latter we know that every number has a square root. 
Moreover, each of the former spaces (the rational and the real) are 
clearly contained in the complex space as subspaces. Suppose now 
that our space S is one in which not every number has a square 
root. In such a case it is often convenient to be able to think of our 
space S as forming a subspace in a more extensive space S', in which 
some or all of these numbers do have square roots. 

We have seen that the ordinary rational and ordinary real spaces 
are such that they may be regarded as subspaces of a more exten- 
sive space in. the number system associated with which the square 
root of any number always exists. In fact, they may be regarded as 
subspaces of the ordinary complex space which has this property. 
"Pat a general field it is easy to prove that if a v a z , , a n are any 
finite set of elements of a field F, there exists a field F', containing 
all the elements of F, suoh that each of the elements a, v a v , is a 
square in F'. This is, of course, less general than the theorem that 
a field F' exists in which 4very, element frf F is a square, but it is 
sufficiently general fr^marm gattf " - ; ' - J - -'- " - - - < 



242 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP ix 

PROPOSITION K 2 If any finite number of involutions are given in 
a space S satisfying Assumptions A, E, P, there exists a space S' of 
which, S is a subspace,* suck that all the given involutions have 
double points in S' 

A proof of this theorem will be found at the end of the chapter. 
The proposition is, from the analytic point of view, that the domain 
of rationality determined by a quadratic problem may be extended so 
as to include solutions of that problem. The space S' may be called 
an extended space. The elements of S may be called proper elements ) 
and those of S' which are not in S may be called, improper A projec- 
tive transformation which changes every proper element into a proper 
element is likewise a proper transformation; one which transforms 
proper elements into improper elements, on the other hand, is called 
an improper transformation. Taking Proposition K 2 for the present as 
an assumption like A, E, P, and H , and noting that it is consistent 
with these other assumptions because they are all satisfied by the ordi- 
nary complex space, we proceed to derive some of its consequences. 

THEOREM 1. A proper one-dimensional projectivity without proper 
double elements may always be regarded in an extended space as 
having two improper double elements. (A, E, P, H , K a )f 

Proof. Suppose the projectivity given on a conic If the involu- 
tion which belongs to this projectivity had two proper double points, 
they would be the intersections of the axis of the projectivity with 
the conic, and hence the given projectivity would have proper double 
points. Let S' be the extended space in which (K 2 ) the involution 
has double points. There are then two points of S' in which the 
axis of the projectivity meets the conic, and these are, by Theorem 20, 
Chap VIII, the double points of the given projectivity. 

COROLLAHY 1. If a line does not meet a conic in proper points, it 
may be regarded in an extended space as meeting it in two improper 
points. (A, E, P, H , K s ) - 

COROLLARY 2. JUiery quadratic equation with proper coefficients has 
two roots which, if distinct, are both proper or both improper. (A, E, 
P, H , K a ) 

* We use the word sulspace to mean any space, every point of "which is a point 
of the space of which it is a suhspace With this understanding the subspace may 
be identical with the space of which it is a subspace. The ordinary complex space 
then satisfies Proposition K 2 . -f Cf . Ex , p. 261. 



80] PROPOSITION K 2 243 

For the double points of any projectivity satisfy an equation of 
the form cj? + (if <i) ,r b = (Theorem 1 J , Our 4, Chap VI), and 
any quadratic equation may bo put into this form. 

TIIKOIIKM 2 Any two involution* in, tlie mint one-dimensional form 
have a conjugate pair in common, which may le proper or improper. 
(A, E, P, 1I , K 2 ) 

This follows at once from the preceding and Theorem 23, Chap. VIII. 

COROLLARY. In any involution there exists a conjugate pair, proper 
or improper, which is harmonic with any given conjugate pair. (A, 
E, P, H 0) K a ) 

For the involution which lias the given pair for double elements 
has (by the theorem) a pair, proper or improper, in common with the 
given involution. The latter pair satisfies the condition of the theorem 
(Theorem 27, Cor. 1, Chap. IV). 

We have seen earlier (Theorem 4, Cor v Chap VIII) that any two 
involutions with double points are conjugate. Under Proposition K 2 
we may remove the restriction and say that any two involutions are 
conjugate in an extended space dependent on the two involutions. If 
the involutions are on coplanar lines, we have the following 

THEOREM 3. Two involutions on distinct lines in the same plane 
are perspective (the center of perspeetivity being proper or improper), 
provided the point of intersection of the lines is a double point for 
loth or for neither of the involutions. (A, E, P, K g ) 

Proof. If the point of intersection of the two lines be a double 
point of each of the involutions, let Q and M be an arbitrary pair 
of one involution and Q 1 and Jtf an arbitrary pair of the other involu- 
tion The point of intersection of the lines 'QQ' and MR' is then a 
center of a perspectivity which transforms elements which determine 
the first involution into elements which determine the second. If 
the point is a double point of neither of the two involutions, let 
M be a double point of one and M ' of the other (these double points 
are proper or else exist in an extended space S f which exists by 
Proposition K 2 ). Also let .Wand JZV"' be the conjugates of in the two 
involutions. Then by the same argument as before, the point of 
intersection of the lines MM 1 , $W may be taken as the center of 
the perspectivity. 



244 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP.IX 

It was proved in 66, Chap. VII, that the equation of any point 
conic is of the form 

_ 2 1 2 J_ O /V rv m 1 O /v rv /yi -I O /v /y /v U1TTT . A 

/"I \ /V /* _L_ * I C(/nnfX' "*T -" w-tnwJiXsn "7~ ^J "^IR^I^ffl "T" " ^Qfl j! 8 """"" J 

but it was not shown that every equation of this form represents a 
conic The line ^ = contains the point (0, # 2 , o; 8 ) satisfying (1), 
provided the ratio x z : x t satisfies the quadratic equation 

Similarly, the lines x z = and a; 8 = contain points of the locus 
defined by (1) 3 provided two other quadratic equations are satisfied 
By Proposition K 2 there exists an extended space in which these 
three quadratic equations are solvable. Hence (1) is satisfied by the 
coordinates of at least two distinct points P, Q (proper or improper).* 

A linear transformation 



(2) 



evidently transforms the points satisfying (1) into points satisfying 
another equation of the second degree. If, then, (2) is so chosen as 
to transform P and Q into the points (0, 0, 1) and (0, 1, 0) respec- 
tively, (1) will be transformed into an equation which is satisfied by 
the latter pair of points, and winch is therefore of the form 

(3) ax* + c^ajjj H- c z x^ + c & x^x z = 0. 

If c x = 0, the points satisfying (3) lie on the two lines 
! = 0, ax i + c a x a + c s x 2 = ; 

and hence (1) is satisfied by the points on the lines into which these 
lines are transformed by the inverse of (2). If c x = 0, the trans- 
formation 



* Proposition Ka has been used merely to establish the existence of points satis- 
fying (1). In case there are proper points satisfying (1), the whole argument can be 
made without K 2 



85, so] PBOBLEMS OF THE SECOND DEGREE 245 

transforms the points (x v x y x s ) satisfying (3) into points (.-/, xj, ,r a ') 
satisfying 

(5 ) L - A\ ,,[ + (,X + v /) 4 = 0. 

\ by / 

But (5) is in the form which was proved in Theorem 7, Chap. VII, 
to be the equation of a conic. As the points which satisfy (5) are 
transformed by the inverse of the product of the collineations (2) and 
(4) into points which satisfy (1), we see that in all cases (1) repre- 
sents a point conic (proper or improper, degenerate or nondegenerate). 

This gives rise to the two following dual theorems : 

THEOREM 4. Every eguatwn of the form 

a u aif + a,yp* 4- a w x% + 2 a^x^ + 2 a u x^ + 2 a z& x z x s = 

represents a point come (proper or improper) which may, however, 
degenerate ; and, conversely, every point conie may le represented T)y 
an equation of this form. (A, E, P, H , K 2 ) 
THEOREM 4' Every equation of the form 

A u uf + A^ 4- 4 M * + 2 -/!!, + 2 A u UjU t + 2 A^uja^ = 
represents a lim conic (proper or improper} which may, however, de- 
(jenerate ; and, conversely, every line conie may "be represented "by an 
equation of this form, (A, E, P, II , K a ) 

86. Problems of the second degree. We have seen in 83 that 
any problem of the first degree can be solved completely by means 
of linear constructions ; but that a problem of degree higher than the 
first cannot be solved by linear constructions alone. In regard to 
problems of the second degree in a plane, however, it was seen in 
84 that any such problem may bo reduced to the problem of find- 
ing the points of intersection of an arbitrary lino in the plane with 
a particular conic in the plane. This result we may state in the 
following form: 

THEOREM 5. Any problem of the second degree in a plane may le 
solved "by linear constructions if the intersections of every line in the 
plane with a single conic in this plane are assumed Jcnown. (A, E, 
P, H OI K 2 ) 

In the xisual representation of the protective geometry of a real plane by 
means of points, lines, etc., drawn with a pencil, say, on a sheet of paper, the 
linear constructions, as has already been noted, are those that can be per- 
formed with the use of a straightedge alone. It will be shown later that any 



246 



GKEOMETEIC CONSTRUCTIONS 



[CHAP. IX 



conic in. the leal geometry is equivalent protectively to a circle The instru- 
ment usually employed to draw circles is the compass It is then clear that 
in this lepresentation any pioUem of the second degree can be solved 1>y ineani> of 
a stiaightedye and compass alone The theoiem just stated, however, shows that 
if a single circle is drawn once foi all in the plane, the straightedge alone 
suffices for the solution of any problem of the second degree in this plane. 
The discussion immediately following serves to indicate briefly how this may 
be accomplished. 

We proceed to show how tliis theorem may be used in the solution 
of problems of the second degree. Any such problem may be reduced 
more or less readily to the first of the f ollowing : 

PROBLEM 1. To find the double points of a projectimty on a line of 
which three pairs of homologous points are given. We may assume 




A 



that the given pairs of homologous points all consist of distinct points 
(otherwise the problem is linear) In accordance with Theorem 5 
we suppose given a conic (in a plane with the line) and assunu 
known the intersections of any line of the plane with this conic. Le 
be any point of the given conic, and with as center project lh< 
given pairs of homologous points on the conic (fig. 98). These defim 
a projectivity on the conic. Construct the axis of this projectivit; 
and let it meet the conic in the points P, Q The lines OP, OQ thei 
meet the given line in the required double points. 

PROBLEM 2, To find the points of intersection of a given line wih 
a conic of which five points are given. Let A, B, C, JO, E be the give 
points of the conic The conic is then defined by the projectivit 
D(A, 3, G)-^E(A, B, C) between the pencils of lines at D and J5 



86] SEXTUPLY PERSPECTIVE TEIANGLES 247 

This projeclivily gives rise to a projectivity on the given line of 
which three pairs of homologous points are known. The double 
points of the latter projectivity are the points of intersection of the 
line with the conic The problem is thus reduced to Problem 1. 

PKOJILTCM 3. We have seen that it is possible for two triangles in 
a plane to be perspective from four different centers (cf. Ex 8, p 105) 
The maximum number of ways in which it is conceivable that two 
triangles may be perspective is clearly equal to the number of per- 
mutations of three things three at a time, ie. six The question then 
arises, 7s it poimille to construct two triangles that are perspective from 
six different centers? Let the two triangles be ABC and A'JJ'C', and let 

B! =0, $ a = 0, <B, = 

be the sides of the first opposite to A, 7?, respectively. Let the 
sides of the second opposite to A', J3', C' respectively be 



s + # 3 =0, x 1 + //ajg + F.e B = 0, x l ,+ l'x z + 1\ = 0. 

The condition for ABC~A'B'C' is that the points of intersection of 
corresponding sides be collmear, i e. 

1 -1 

(1) -F 1 = F-Z'0. 
-P 1 

In like manner, the condition for JBCA ^- A'B'C' is 

-l V 

(2) -101 =H"-^=0. 

~/y i o 

From these two conditions follows 

-F ti 

~l" 1 -H^-F-O, 

1 -1 

which is the condition for CAB ~ A'B'C'. Hence, if two triangles are 
in the relatwna ABC ~~ A'B'C' and BCA~~A'JB'G', they are also in 

the relation CAB A'B'C 1 * Two triangles in this relation are said to 
A 

be triply perspective (cf. Ex. 2, p, 100)*, The domain of rationality 
defined by the data of our problem; is clearly 



248 GEOMETEIC CON STKUC TICKS [CHAP. IX 

Since numbers in this domain may be found winch satisfy equutionH 
(1) and (2), the problem of constructing two triply perspective tri- 
angles is linear 



The condition for ACB == A'H'C' is 

A 

(3) L J -l= 



If relations (1), (2), and (3) are satisfied, the triangles will be per- 
spective from four centers Let k be the common value of // and I" 
(3), and let I be the common value of I' and V (1) Relation (2) then 
gives the condition Jc 2 I = 0. The relations 



then define two quadruply perspective triangles. The problem of 
constructing two such triangles is therefore still linear. 

If now we add the condition for CBA A'B'C', the two triangles 
will, by what precedes, be perspective from six different centers The 
latter condition is 

(4) F2'-Z"=0. 

With the preceding conditions (1), (2), (3) and the notation adopted 
above, this leads to the condition 



The equation k s 1 = is, however, reducible in K; indeed, it w 
equivalent to 



The first of these equations leads to the condition that A', 7?', C' are 
eollinear, and does not therefore give a solution of the problem The 
problem of constructing two triangles that are sextuply perspective 
is therefore of the second degree. The equation 







has two roots w, w* (proper or improper and, in general,* distinct). 
Hence our problem has two solutions. One of these consists of the 
triangles 



^+^=0, a^ + ias. + wfyasO, i + ^a 4- ww = 



* They can coincide only if the number system IB such that 1 + 1 + 1 = 0: e.g. in 
a finite space involving the modulus 3. 



80] SEXTUPLY PERSPECTIVE TRIANGLES 249 

Two of the sides of the second triangle may be improper.* The 
points of intersection of the sides of one of these triangles with the 
sides of the other are the following 1 nine points : 

(0, -1,1) (0, w*, -10) { 0, w t -w*) 

(5) (-1, 0, 1) (-10*, 0, 1 ) (-w, 0, 1 ) 

(-1, 1, 0) ( 10, -1, ) (w\ -1, ) 

They form a configuration 

4 
3 12 

which contains four configurations 

3 
3 

of the land studied in 36, Chap IV. All triples of points in the 
same row or column or term of the determinant expansion of their 
matrix are collinear.f If one line is omitted from a finite plane (in 
the sense of 72, Chap VII) having four points on each line, the 
remaining nine points and twelve lines are isomorphic with this 
configuration, 

EXERCISES 

The problem in a plane ffiven Mow that are of the second degree are to be solved 
1>H linear construct ions, with the amtmplum that the points of intersection of any line 
in the plane with a given faed conic in the plane are known; i.e. "with a straiglit- 
cilye and a y wn circle in the plane" 

1. Construct the points of intersection of a given lino with a conic deter- 
mined by (i) four points and a tangent through one of them ; (a) three points 
unrl the tangents through two of thorn ; (in) five tangents. 

2. Construct the conjugate pair common to two involutions on a line, 

3. Given a conic determined by five points, construct a triangle inscribed 
in this conic whose sides pass through three given points of the plane. 

* It may be noted that in the ordinary real geometry two sides of the second 
triangle are necessarily improper, so that in this geometry our problem has no 
real solution. 

t They all lie on any cubic curve of the form * + | + aJ 8 s + fiXa^o* = for 
any value of X, and are, in fact, the points of inflexion of the cubic. This configura- 
tion forms the point of departure tor a variety of investigations leading into many 
different branches of mathematicSi v 



250 GEOMETKIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP. IX 

4. Given a triangle A Z B Z C 2 inscnbed in a tnangle A v K l C r In how 
many ways can a tnangle A 9 B s C a be inscubed in A z B^C a and cncumsciibod 
to A^C^i Show that in one case, in which one vertex of A a B a C. t may be 
chosen arbitiarily, the problem is hneai (cf. 3(3, Chap IV) , ami that, in 
another case the problem is quadratic. Show that this pioblem gives all con- 



figurations of the symbol 



9 3 
3 9 



Give the consti actions 01 all cases (c. 



S. Kantor, Sitzungsbenchte der inathematisch-naturwissenschafthcheu Clnaae 
der Kaiserhchen Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Wien, Vol. LXXXIV 
(1881), p 915) 

5. If opposite vertices of a simple plane hexagon P]P s ,P a P lt P B P a arc on 
three concurrent lines, and the lines P^P^ P S P^ P 5 P 6 ai e concurrent, then the 
lines P Z P S , PiP 6 > P 6 Pi are also concurrent, and the figure thus formed is a 
configuration of Pappus 

6. Show how to constiuct a simple n-point iusciibed in a given simple 
n-point and circumscribed to another given simple n-point. 

7 Show how to inscnbe in a given conic a simple n-point whose sides 
pass respectively through n given points 

8 Construct a conic through four points and tangent to a line not meeting 
any of the four points 

9 Construct a conic thiough thiee points and tangent to two lines not 
meeting any of the points. 

10 Constiuct a conic thiough four given points and meeting a given line 
in two points harmonic with two given points on the line. 

11. If A is a given point of a conic and X, Y are two variable points of the 
conic such that AX, AY always pass through a conjugate pan of a given 
involution on a line I, the line JTFwill always pass thiougli a fixed point J3. 
The line AB and the tangent to the conic at A pass through a conjugate pair 
of the given involution 

12. Given a collineation in a plane and a line which does not contain a 
fixed point of the collineation ; show that thei e is one and only one point on 
the line which is transformed by the collineation into another point on the line. 

13. Given four skew lines, show that there are in general two hues which 
meet each of the given four lines ; and that if there are three such lines, theie 
is one through every point on one of the lines, 

14. Given in a plane two systems of five points A^^A^A^A^ and 
B 1 B Z B 9 B^B 6 , given also a point X in the plane, determine a point Y such 
that we have XtA-LAiAiAiA^-j-Y^BiByBzBiBt). In general, there is one 
and only one such point Y. Under what condition is there more than one ? 
(R. Sturm, Mathematische Annalen, Vol. I (1869), p, 583,*) 

* This is a special case of the so-called problem of projectwity, 3Tor references 
and a systematic treatment see Sturm, Die Lehre von den geometrischen Ver- 
wandtschaften, Vol. I, p 848. 



87] 



INVARIANTS 



251 



87. Invariants of linear and quadratic binary forms. An expres- 
sion of the form a^ + <V a is called a linear binary form, in the 
two variables x v x z The word linear refers to the degree in the 
variables, the word Unary to the number (two) of the variables. A 
convenient notation for such a form is <\. The equation 



defines a unique element A of a one-dimensional form in which a 
scale has been established, viz. the element whose homogeneous co- 
ordinates are (x v as a ) = (a z> a x ). If & = \x^ + & a # 2 is another linear 
buiary form determining the element B, say, the question arises 
as to the condition under which the two elements A and B coincide 
This condition is at once obtained as the vanishing of the determinant 
A formed by the coefficients of the two forms ; i.e. the elements A 
and B will coincide if and only if we have 

0. 

Now suppose the two elements A and B are subjected to any pro- 
jective transformation II : 

a @ 

ry 8 

The forms a x and 1 9 will be transformed into two forms and & 
respectively, which, when equated to 0, define the points A 1 , B' into 
which the points A, B are transformed by II. The coefficients of 
the forms < 
follows ; 



^, in terms of those of a s) l x arj readily calculated as 



which gives 
Similarly, we find 



a 1 -f- 5a 2 . 



Now it is clear that if the elements J, J3 coincide, so also will the 
new elements A', B' coincide. If we have A 0, therefore we should 



also have A' 
We have 



a/ 



0. That this is the case is readily verified. 



252 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP.IX 

by a well-known theorem in determinants. This relation may also 

be written 

a ft 



A' = 



8 ' A - 



The determinant A is then a function of the coefficients of the forms 
a x) l x) with the property that, if the two forms are subjected to a lin- 
ear homogeneous transformation of the variables (with nonvaiiishmg 
determinant), the same function of the coefficients of the new forms 
is equal to the function of the coefficients of the old forms multiplied 
by an expression which is a function of the coefficients of the trans- 
formation only. Such a function of the coefficients of two forms is 
called a (simultaneous) invariant of the forms. 

Suppose, now, we form the product a f - &, of the two forms a^ & a . 
If multiplied out, this product is of the form 



Any such form is called a quadratic Unary form. Under Proposi- 
tion K 2 every such form may be factored into two linear factors 
(proper or improper), and hence any such form represents two ele- 
ments (proper or improper) of a one-dimensional form. These two 
elements will coincide, if and only if the discriminant D a = a& 
a n - a zz of the quadratic form vanishes. The condition D a = there- 
fore expresses a property which is invariant under any projectivity. 
If, then, the form a* be subjected to a projective transformation, the 
discriminant D a , of the new form. a must vanish whenever J) n van- 
ishes. There must accordingly be a relation of the form Z> n , = Jc D n . 
If a% be subjected to the transformation II given above, the coefficients 
a n> ia> a aa of fcne new form ^ are readily found to be 



By actual computation the reader may then verify the relation 



a $ 
7 8 



The discriminant D a of a quadratic form 0% is therefore called an 
invariant of the form. 



87] INVARIANTS 253 

Suppose, now, we consider two binary quadratic forms 

Each of these (under jfiQ represents a pair of points (proper or im- 
proper). Let us seek the condition that these two pairs be harmonic. 
This property is invariant under projective transformations ; we may 
therefore expect the condition sought to be an invariant of the two 
forms. We know that if a v & a are the nonliomogeneous coordinates 
of the two points represented by a = 0, we have relations 

2B 2 & 13 

a^ ct, z > ttj + a a - > 

with similar relations for the nonhomogeneous coordinates & p & 2 of 
the points represented by &J = 0. The two pairs of points a v a a ; \, 5 2 
will be harmonic if we have (Theorem 13, Cor. 2, Chap. VI) 

i 
This relation may readily be changed into the following : 

which, on substituting from the relations just given, becomes 



This is the condition sought. If we form the same function of the 
coefficients of the two forms a^ 8 , V* obtained from a t 1% by subjecting 
them to the transformation II, and substitute from equations (1), we 
obtain the relation 




In the three examples of invariants of binary forms thus far 
obtained, the function of the new coefficients was always equal to 
the function of the old coefficients multiplied by a power of the 
determinant of the transformation. This is a general theorem regard- 
ing invariants to which we shall refer again in 90, when a formal 
definition of an invariant will be given, Before closing this section, 
however, let us consider briefly the cross ratio B (a^a,, Zj.6 a ) of the 
two pairs of points represented by a* 0, &* *= 0. This cross ratio 



254 ' GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP. IX 

is entirely unchanged when the two forms are subjected to a pro- 
jective transformation. If, therefore, this cross ratio be calculated in 
terms of the coefficients of the two forms, the resulting function of 
the coefficients must be exactly equal to the same J!imctioii of the 
coefficients of the forms a[, 5j , the power of the determinant referred 
to above is in this case zero. Such an invariant is called an absolute 
invariant, for purposes of distinction the invariants which when 
transformed are multiplied by a power = of the determinant of 
the transformation are then called relative ^nvariants. 



EXERCISES 

1 Show that the cross latio Ijfc (cjOj, Va) referred to at the end of the 
last section is 




and hence show, by reference to preceding results, that it is indeed an absolute 
invariant. 

2. Given three pans of points denned by the three binary quadratic forms 
as = 0, 1% = 0, cj = ; show that the three will be in involution if we have 

= 0. 

Hence show that the above determinant is a simultaneous invariant of the 
three forms (cf. Ex 13, p. 230). 

88. Proposition E^. If we form the product of n linear binary 
forms a x 'a' x -a'J' - > a*" 1 *, we obtain an expression of the form 



An expression of this form is called a Unary homogeneous form or 
guantic of the nth degree. If it is obtained as the product of n linear 
forms, it will represent a set of n points on a line (or a set of n ele- 
ments of some one-dimensional form) 

If it is of the second degree, we have, by Proposition K BJ that there 
exists an extended space in which it represents a pair of points. At 
the end of this chapter there will be proved the following generali- 
sation of K a : 



88,89] PKOPOSITION K a 255 

PROPOSITION K n . If a^ a^ -are a finite number of binary homo- 
geneous forms whose coefficients are proper in a space S which satisfies 
Assumptions A, E, P, there exists a space S', of which S is a sub- 
space, in the number system of which each of these forms is a product 
of linear factors. 

As in 85, S' is called an extended space, and elements in S' but 
not in S are called improper elements Proposition K n thus implies 
that an equation of the form a w " = can always be thought of as 
representing n (distinct or partly coinciding) improper points in an 
extended space in case it does not represent any proper points 

Proposition K n could be introduced as an (not independent) assump- 
tion in addition to A, E, P, and H Its consistency with the other 
assumptions would be shown by the example of the ordinary com- 
plex space in which it is equivalent to the fundamental theorem 
of algebra. 

89. Taylor's theorem. Polar forms. It is desirable at this point 
to borrow an important theorem from elementary algebra 

DEFINITION. Given a term Ax? of any polynomial, the expression 
o?~ l is called the derivative of Ax? with respect to x k in symbols 



The derivative of a polynomial with respect to a?, is, by definition, the 
sum of the derivatives of its respective terms. 

Q 

This definition gives at once f-A = 0, if A is independent of av 

o^i 

Applied to a term of a binary form it gives 
nk3%' l se? t -j- ^xf 



With this definition it is possible to derive Taylor's theorem for the 
expansion of a polynomial. *We state it for a binary form as f ollows : 
Given the binary form 

~\ -f- * ^~~ 1 } A W ~ X 



* For the proof of this theorem on the basis of the definition just given, of. Fine, 
College Algebra, pp.; <I|Q~462. 



256 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [OUAP.IX 

If herein we substitute for x v x a respectively the expressions ,)\ + X?/ ; , 
, + X?/ 2 > we obtain, 

3 



Here the parentheses are differential operators. Thus 



ay a ran ay a ra/i . T . ,, 

where ~ means - M- r-~- means - - - U etc It is readily 

a#i ^iL^J ^a^i ^ /J L^iJ 

proved for any term of a polynomial (and hence for the polynomial 
itself) that the value of such a higher derivative as ^ 2 //a, a a. 1 is 
independent of the order of differentiation; i.e. that we have 

a 2 / = a 3 / 

aCj&Bj Sas^jj, 

DEFINITION The coefficient of X in the above expansion, viz, 
yfif/dx^ + y^f/dx z is called the first polar form of (y v y a ) with 
respect to f (x v x a ) ; the coefficient of X 2 is called the wfitml ; the 
coefficient of X" is called the nth polar form of (y v y^ with rasped 
to the form f If any polar form be equated to 0, it represents a set 
of points which is called il\Q first, second, , nth polar of the point 
(y v y s ) with respect to the set of points represented %/ (^, jr a ) ~ 0. 

Consider now a binary form/ (x v se z ) = and the effect upon it of 
a projective transformation 



If we substitute these values in / (oz x , x s ), we obtain a new form 
F(x[, 0$. A point (x v ss z ) represented by/( 1 , aJ 8 )= will bo trans- 
formed into a point (as/, aj a ') represented by the form y(sp[ t ii)0. 
Moreover, if the point (y v y,) be subjected to the same projectivity, 
it is evident from the nature of the expansion given above that the 
polars of (y lf g/ a ) with respect to f(x v o} 2 ) = are transformed into 
the polars of (y/, yj) with respect to ff(es[ t %) = 0. 



& so, oo] INVARIANTS 257 

"We may summarize the results thus obtained as follows : 

THEOREM 6 If a Unary form f is transformed ly a projective 
transformation into the form F, the set of points represented by f= Q 
is transformed into the set represented ly ^=0. Any polar of a 
point (y v 7/ a ) with respect tof=Q is transformed into the correspond- 
ing polar of the point (y[, v/ a ') with respect to F= 

The following iw a simple illustration of a polar of a point with 
respect to a set of points on a line 

The form ayj a = represents the two points whose nonhomo- 
geneous coordinates are and co respectively. The first polar of any 
point (y v y a ) with respect to this form is clearly y^ + y z x : = Q, and 
represents the point (y v y^)] in other words, the first polar of a 
point P with respect to the pair of points represented by the given 
form is the harmonic conjugate of this point with respect to the pair. 

EXERCISE 

Determine the geomeh ical consti notion of the ( l)tih polar of a point 
with lespoct to a sot of n distinct points on a line (of. Ex 3, p 51). 

90. Invariants and covariants of binary forms. DEFINITION. If a 
binary form a = a v a% + na^~ l x z -\ ----- h aa be changed by the 
transformation / _ , 



l 



into a new form A$ ~ A ^ n + ^X"~X + ---- 1" 4X B an y rational 
function f(n Q) a v , a n ) of the coefficients such that we have 

I(A Q , A v , 4.) = ^(, A % 8) /(a,, a v . - , oj 
is called an invariant of the form ". A function 

C(a 9t a v -.,a n ; as lf x s ) 
of the coefficients and the variables such that we have 

C(A 0) -4,-. -,4,; /, <) = f (, &7, SJ-C'K, ^,...,^5 fl^, aO 
is called a covariant of the form a The same terms apply to func- 
tions I and C of the coefficients and variables of any finite number 
of binary forms with the property that the same function of the 
coefficients and variables of the new forms is equal to the original 
function multiplied by a function of , & 7, $ only; they are" then 
called siwrnUaneous invariants or eovariants, 



258 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [OIIAP. IX 

In 87 we gave several examples of invariants of binary forms, 
linear and quadratic. It is evident from the definition that the con- 
dition obtained "by equating to any invariant of a form (or of a 
system of forms) must determine a property of the st't of points 
represented by the forin (or forms) which in invariant 'tinder a pro- 
jective transformation. Hence the complete study of the projeetive 
geometry of a single line would involve tl*e complete theory of invari- 
ants and covariants of binary forms. It is not our purpose in this 
book to give an account of this theory. But we will mention one 
theorem which we have already seen verified in special cases. 

The functions <f>(a, /3, 7, 8) and ty(a, ft, 7, 8) occnrrvny in (he, 
definition above are always powers of the determinant S--/:ty of 
the projectile transformation in question.* 

Before closing this section we will give a simple example of a oovu- 
riant. Consider two binary quadratic forms a?, b% and form the new 
quantic 

c * = Wi ~ A) x i + K & 3 - 'A) A + (a A ~ <* A) 
By means of equations (1), 87, the reader may then verify without 
difficulty that the relation 



holds, which proves <7 n6 to be a covariant. The two points represented 
by <?6 = are the double points (proper or improper) of the involu- 
tion of which the pairs determined by a* = 0, V* = are conjugate 
pairs. This shows why the form should be a covariaut. 

EXERCISE 
Piove the statement contained in the next to the last sentence. 

91 . Ternary and quaternary foi ms and their invariants. The remarks 
which have been made above regarding binary forms can evidently be 
generalized. A p-aryform of the nth degree is a polynomial of the wth 
degree homogeneous in p variables. When the number of variables is 
three or four, the form is called ternary or quaternary respectively. 
The general ternary form of the second degree when equated to xero 
lias been shown to be the equation of a conic. In general, the set of 
points (proper and improper) in a plane which satisfy an equation 



* For proof, of., for example, Grace and Young, Algebra of Invariants, pp, 21, 



9 i] INVARIANTS 259 

obtained by equating to zero a ternary form of the wth degree is 
called an algebraic curve of the nth degree (order). Similarly, the set 
of points determined in space by a quaternary form of the wth degree 
equated to zero is called an algebraic surface of the nth degree 

The definitions of invariants and covanants of p-ary forms is pre- 
cisely the same as that given above for binary forms, allowance being 
made for the change in the number of variables Just as in the 
binary case, if an invariant of a ternary or quaternary form vanishes, 
the corresponding function of the coefficients of any projectively 
equivalent form also vanishes, and consequently it represents a prop- 
erty of the corresponding algebraic curve or surface which is not 
changed when the curve or surface undergoes a protective transforma- 
tion. Similar remarks apply to covanants of systems of ternary and 
quaternary forms. 

Invariants and covariants as defined above are with respect to the 
group of all protective collineations. The geometric properties which 
they represent are properties unaltered by any projective collmeation. 
Like definitions can of course be made of invariants with respect to 
any subgroup of the total group. Evidently any function of the 
coefficients of a form which is invariant under the group of all col- 
lineations will also be an invariant under any subgroup. But there 
will in general be functions which remain invariant under a subgroup 
but which are not invariant under the total group. These correspond 
to properties of figures which are invariant under the subgroup with- 
out being invariant under the total group. We thus arrive at the 
fundamental notion of a geometry as associated with a given group, 
a subject to which we shall return in detail in a later chapter. 

EXERCISES 

1. Define by analogy with the developments of 89, the n - 1 polars of a 
ternary or quaternary form of the nth degree. 

2. Regarding a triangle as a curve of the third degree, show that the second 
polar of a point with regard to a triangle is the polar line defined on page 46. 

3. Generalize Ex. 2 in the plane and in space, and dualize. 

4. Prove that the discriminant a\l aJJ o| of the ternary quadratic form 
is an ^variant. What is its geometrical interpretation? Cf. Ex,, p J87- 



260 GEOMETRIC CONSTRUCTIONS [CHAP IX 

92. Proof of Proposition K^. Given a rational integral function 

<jE> (x) = a ,e n + ap*- 1 + + n ni a = 0, 

whose coefficients belong to a given field F, and which is irreducible in 
F, there exists a field F', containing F, in which the equation $ (x) = 
has a root 

Let/(#) be any rational integral function of x with coefficients in 
F, and let ,; be an arbitrary symbol not an element of F. Consider 
the class F, = [/(/)] of all symbols /(/), where [/(as)] is the class of 
all rational integral functions with coefficients in F. We proceed to 
define laws of combination for the elements of F^ which render the 
latter a field. The process depends on the theorem * that any poly- 
nomial f(x) can be represented uniquely in the form 



where q(x) and r(x) are polynomials belonging to F, ie. with 
coefficients in F, and where r(x) is of degree lower than the degree 
n of < (x) If two polynomials f lt / a belonging to F are such that 
their difference is exactly divisible by < (x), then they are said to be 
congruent modulo <f)(x), in symbols / t = / 2 , mod. <>(#). 

1 Two elements f^j), / 2 (/) of F, are said to be equal, if and only 
\lfi(x} and/ 2 (#) are congruent mod <(e). By virtue of the theorem 
referred to above, every element f(j) of F f is equal to one and only 
one element /' (/) of degree less than n. We need hence consider only 
those elements /(/) of degree less than n. Further, it follows from 
this definition that $ (/) = 0. 

2. If / t (x) +/, (x) =/ 3 (as), mod. (*), then /, (/) + /, (/) -/, (/)- 

3- VfM /, (^^/.(a!), mod. 0(0?), then /,(;)/.(/)=/ 0> 
Addition and multiphcation of the elements of F^ having thus 

been defined, the associative and distributive laws follow as immedi- 
ate consequences of the corresponding laws for the polynomials/^.'). 
It remains merely to show that the inverse operations exist and are 
unique. That addition has a unique inverse is obvious To prove 
that the same holds for multiplication (with the exception of 0) we 
need only recall f that, since $(x) and any polynomial /(x) have no 
common factors, there exist two polynomials h(x) and k(x) with 
coefficients in F such that 



* Fine, College Algebra, p. 156. f Kne, loc, cit., p. 208, 



92] PROOF OF K n 261 

This gives al once Ji (j) f(j) 1, 

so that every element f(J) distinct from has a reciprocal. The class 
F, is therefore a field with respect to the operations of addition and 
nmtiplieation defined above (of. 52), such that <j>(j)= 0. It follows 
at once* that xj is a factor of <(#) in the field F,, which is there- 
fore the required field F'. The quotient <j>(x)/(x j) is either irre- 
ducible in F J} or, if reducible, has certain irreducible factors If the 
degree of one of the latter is greater than unity, the above process may 
be repeated leading to a field F^,,/' being a zeio of the factor m 
question Continuing in this way, it is possible to construct a field 
F ., j w , where m ^jin 1, in which <f> () is completely reducible, 
i.e. in which <j>(%) may be decomposed into n linear factors This 
gives the following corollary : 

Given a polynomial < (,#) belonging to a given* field F, there exists a 
field F' containing F in which <j> (x) is completely reducible. 

Finally, an obvious extension of this argument gives the corollary 

Given a finite number of polynomials each of which belongs to a 
given field F, there exists a field F', containing F, in which each of the 
given polynomials is completely reducible. 

This corollary is equivalent to Proposition K n . For if S be any 
space, let F be the number system on one of its lines. Then, as in 
the Introduction (p. 11), F' determines an analytic space which is 
the required space S' of Proposition K n . 

The more general question at once presents itself: Given a field 
F, does there exist a field F', containing F, in which every polynomial 
belonging to F is completely reducible ? The argument used above 
does not appear to offer a direct answer to this question. The ques- 
tion has, however, recently been answered in the affirmative by an 
extension of the above argument which assumes the possibility of 
well ordering " any class, f 

EXERCISE 

Many theoiems of this and other chapters are given as dependent on 
A, E, P, H 0> whereas they are provable without the use of H . Determine 
which theorems are true in those spaces for which H is false. 

* Erne, College Algebra, p. 169, 

t Cf. B. Steinitz, Algebraisclie Theorie der Kbrper, Journal fur reme u. ange- 
wandte Matheraatik, Vol. CXXXVII (1909), p. 107 ; especially pp. 271-286. 



CHAPTER X* 

PROJECTIVE TRANSFORMATIONS OF TWO-DIMENSIONAL FORMS 

93. Correlations between two-dimensional forms. DEFINITION. A 
protective correspondence between the elements of a plane of points 
and the elements of a plane of lines (whether they be on the same 
or on different bases) is called a correlation. Likewise, a protective 
correspondence between the elements of a bundle of planes and the 
elements of a bundle of lines is called a correlation f 

"Under the principle of duality we may confine ourselves to a con- 
sideration of correlations between planes In such a correlation, then, 
to every point of the plane of points corresponds a unique line of the 
plane of lines ; and to every pencil of points in the plane of points 
corresponds a unique projective pencil of lines in the plane of lines. 
In particular, if the plane of points and the plane of lines are on the 
same base, we have a correlation in a planar field, whereby to every 
point P of the plane corresponds a unique line p of the same plane, 
and in which, if Jjj*, P z , P 8 , P are collinear points, the corresponding 
lines p v p s> p a , PI are concurrent and such that 



That a correlation T transforms the points [P] of a plane into the 
lines [p] of the plane, we indicate as usual by the functional notation 



The points on a line I are transformed by T into the lines on a 
point L This determines a transformation of the lines [Z] into the 
points [], which we may denote by F', thus: 

F(i)-i 

That F' is also a correlation is evident (the formal proof may be 
supplied by the reader). The transformation F is called the correla- 
tion induced by I\ If a correlation F transforms the lines [I] of a 

* All developments of this chapter are on the basis of Assumptions A, E, P, and 
H Cf . the exercise at the end of the last chapter. 

t The terms reciprocity and duality are sometimes used in place of correlation. 

262 



93] COREELATIONS 263 

plane into the points [L] of the plane, the correlation which trans- 
forms the points [IV] into the lines [LL 1 ] is the correlation induced 
by T. If T' is induced by F, it is clear that T is induced by I". 
For if we have 



we have also 



and hence the induced correlation of I" transforms P z into jp a , etc. 

That correlations in a plane exist follows from the existence of the 
polar system of a conic. The latter is in fact a projective transforma- 
tion in which to every point in the plane of the conic corresponds a 
unique line of the plane, to every line corresponds a unique point, 
and to every pencil of points (lines) corresponds a projective pencil 
of lines (points) (Theorem 18, Cor , Chap. V). This example is, how- 
ever, of a special type having the peculiarity that, if a point P corre- 
sponds to a line p, then in the induced correlation the line p will 
correspond to the point P ; i.e. in a polar system the points and lines 
correspond doubly. This is by no means the case in every correlation. 

DEFINITION. A correlation in a plane m which the points and 
lines correspond doubly is called a polarity. 

It has been found convenient in the case of a polarity defined by 
a conic to study a transformation of points into lines and the induced 
transformation of lines into points simultaneously. Analogously, in 
studying collineations we have regarded a transformation T of points 
P P v P,, J into points JJ' f #, If, J?, and the transformation T' of 
the lines jJJ, 2J2J, PA P& into the lines ##, P 2 'P 8 ', tftf, -W BB 
the same collineation, In like manner, when considering a trans- 
formation of the points and lines of a plane into its lines and points 
respectively, a correlation T operating on the points and its induced 
correlation T 1 operating on the lines constitute one transformation of 
the points and lines of the plane. For this sort of transformation we 
shall also use the term correlation. In the first instance a correlation 
in a plane is a correspondence between a plane of points (lines) and 
a plane of lines (points). In the extended sense it is a transformation 
of a planar field either into itself or into another planar field, in 
which an element of one kind (point or line) Corresponds to an ele- 
ment 



;ii H 



204 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP.X 

The following theorem is an immediate consequence of the defini- 
tion and the fact that the resultant of any two projective correspond- 
ences is a protective correspondence. 

THEOREM 1 Tlie resultant of two correlations is a projective col- 
Iwieatwn, and the resultant of a correlation and a prujeetvve eolhnea- 
tion is a correlation. 

We now proceed to derive Hie fundamental theorem for correlations 
between two-dimensional forms 

THEOREM 2. A correlation between two two-dimensional primitive 
forms is uniquely defined when four pairs of homologous elements are 
(/iven, provided that no three elements of either form are on the same 
one-dimensional primitive form. 

Proof. Let the two forms be a plane of points a and a plane of 
lines a 1 . Let C' a be any conic in a', and let the four pairs of homol- 
ogous elements be A, B, G, D in a and a', I', c', d' in a'. Let A', B', 
C', D' be the poles of a', &', e', d' respectively with respect to C z . If 
the four points A, 73, 0, D are the vertices of a quadrangle and the 
four points A', B', C', D' are likewise the vertices of a quadrangle 
(and this implies that no three of the lines a', V, c', d' are concurrent), 
there exists one and only one collmeation transforming A into A', B 
into B', G into C', and D into D' (Theorem 18, Chap. IV). Let this 
collmeation be denoted by T, and let the polarity denned by the conic 
C 2 be denoted by P. Then the projective transformation T which is 
the resultant of these two transforms A into a', B into &', etc. More- 
over, there cannot be more than one correspondence effecting this 
transformation. For, suppose there were two, T and T r Then the 
projective correspondence I\- 1 T would leavo each of the four points 
A, B, C, D fixed ; i.e. would be the identity (Theorem ] 8, Chap. IV). 
But this would imply I\ = 37. 

THEOREM 3, A correlation which interchanges the vertices of a 
triangle with the opposite sides is a polarity. 

Proof, Let the vertices of the given triangle be A, B, C, and let 
the opposite sides be respectively a, &, c. Let P be any point of the 
plane ABO which is not on a side of the triangle. The line p ink 
which P is transformed by the given correlation T does not, then, pas$ 
through a vertex of the triangle ABO. The correlation T is deter 
mined by the equation F (ABCP) = abcp, and, by hypothesis, is suol 



93] COREELATIONS 265 

that T (ale) = ABC The points [Q] of c are transformed into the 
lines [17] on C, and these meet in a pencil [Q 1 ] projective with [Q] 
(fig 99) Since A corresponds to B and B to A in the projectivity 
[Q] -fr[Q'], this projectivity is an involution T. The point Q in which 




FIG. 90 

CP meets c is transformed by T into a line on the point cp; and 
since Q Q and cp are paired in I, it follows that cp is transformed 
into the line CQ CP. In like manner, lp is transformed into J5P. 
Hence p = (<$>, &2?) is transformed into P = (CP, BP). 

THEOREM 4. Any projective collineation, IT, in a plane, a, is the 
product of two polarities. 

Proof. Let Aa be a lineal element of a, and let 
H (Aa) = A'a', H (A 1 a') = A" a". 

Unless II is perspective, Aa may be so chosen that A, A', A" are not 
collinear, aa'a" are not concurrent, and no line of one of the three 
lineal elements passes through the point of another. In this case there 
exists a polarity P such that P(AA'A") a"a f a, namely the polarity 
denned by the conic with regard to which AA n (aa") is a self-polar tri- 
angle and to which a f is tangent at A'. If II is perspective, the existence 
of P follows directly on choosing Aa, so that neither A nor a is fixed. 
We then have 



and hence the triangle AA'(aa') is self-reciprocal Hence (Theorem 3) 
PII P x is a polarity, and therefore II P^. 



266 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES [CHAP. X 

94. Analytic representation of a correlation between two planes. 
Bilinear forms. Let a system of simultaneous pomt-and-hhe coordi- 
nates be established in a planar field. We then have 

THEOREM 5. Any correlation in a plane is given as a transforma- 
tion of points into lines ly equations of the form 

pu^= a n x t -\- a lz x a + a ls x 3 , 
(1) pul = a^ + a 22 zc a + a^x 3 , 



where the determinant A of the coefficients a lt is different froin zero. 
Conversely, every transformation of this form in which the determinant 
A is different from zero represents a correlation. 

The proof of this theorem is completely analogous to the proof of 
Theorem 8, Chapter VII, and need not be repeated here. 

As a corollary we have 

COROLLARY 1. The transformation pu[ x l} pu^ = x s> pu(=x 3 in 
a plane represents a polarity in which to every side of the triani/le of 
reference corresponds the opposite vertex. 

Also, if (u[, u' 2> u a ) be interpreted as line coordinates in a plane 
different from that containing the points (x lt x z , ; 8 ) (and if the num- 
ber systems are so related that the correspondence X 1 == X between 
the two planes is projective), we have at once 

COROLLARY 2. The equations of Theorem 5 also represent a correla- 
tion between the plane of (x v x z , J 8 ) and the plane of (u[, u^, u) 

Returning now to the consideration of a correlation in a plane 
(planar field), we have seen that the equations (1) give the coordi- 
nates (u[, u.!,, u s ) of the line u'= F (X], which corresponds to the 
point X (x v # 2 , a? 3 ) By solving these equations for x t , 



(2) 



we obtain the coordinates of JT= P" 1 (u'} in terms of the coordinates 
u' of the line to which JTis homologous in the inverse correlation T~\ 
If, however, we seek the coordinates of the point X' = F (u) which 
corresponds to any line u in the correlation. F, we may proceed as 
follows : 



94] CORRELATIONS 267 

Let the equation of the point Z' = (A/, ic a ', x) in line coordinates be 

It/it!/ + 16} X! 2 + WgiCg = 0. 

Substituting in this equation from (1) and arranging the terms as a 
linear expression in x v x a , x a , 

at f\ -I- /v L ji. fi 

we readily find 

fV\ M/ /y ft JL, ft f>t JL ft <y ' 

The coordinates of Jl r ' in terms of the coordinates of u are then 
given by 

1 " " 11 1 *^ 12 2 ' 1JJ S* 

/ j \ t A 

i n \ lit* yi / 

V*/ Vl "a ""-21 ' 



This is the analytic expression of the correlation as a transformation 
of lines into points ; i.e. of the induced correlation of F. These equa- 
tions clearly apply also in the case of a correlation between two 
different planes. 

It is perhaps well to emphasize the fact that Equations (1) express T as a 
transformation of points into lines, -while Equations (4) represent the induced 
correlation of lines into points, Since we consider a con elation as a trans- 
formation of points into lines and lines into points, T is completely represented 
by (1) and (4) taken together. Equations (2) and (8) taken together repre- 
sent the inverse of T. 

Another way of representing T analytically is obtained by observ- 
ing that the point (x v x v # 8 ) is transformed by F into the line whose 
equation in current coordinates (x[, x^ #/) is 



or, 

(5) (a u o!i + a la flj a + o^) / + (a.^4- a 23 3 + <V 8 ) ^ 

+ ax + ** - 0- 



The left-hand member of (5) is a general ternary "bilinear form. We 
have then 

COROLLARY 3. Any ternary "bilinear form in wbicJi the determinant 

"" ^^"entlrgr^ &ro, represents a, correlation m a plane. 

1 * > ii * * , , - , , t 

. i ' * * ' x 5 * i , ' ? ' , 5 ' 5 , ! * l< ; 

1 * I I ' ' r , ! ' ' , ' - \ ? ,1 i t 1 S ? I i ,* I t t ' 



268 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES [CHAP x 

95. General projective group. Representation by matrices. The 

general projective group of transformations in a plane (which, under 
duality, we take as representative of the two-dimensional primitive 
forms) consists of all projective collmeations (including the identity) 
and all correlations in the plane. Since the product of two collmea- 
tions is a collineation, the set of all projective collineations forms a 
subgroup of the general group Since, however, the product of two 
correlations is a collineation, there exists no subgroup consisting 
entirely of correlations.* 

According to the point of view developed in the last chapter, the 
projective geometry of a plane is concerned with theorems which 
state properties invariant under the general projective group in the 
plane. In particular, the principle of duality may le regarded as a 
consequence of the presence of correlations in this group. 

Analytically, collineations and correlations may be regarded as 
aspects of the theory of matrices. The collineation 



x' t = 

.7=1 



may be conveniently represented by the matrix A of the coefficients a tj : 




The product of two collineations A = (a y ) and B = (&^) is then given 
by the product of their matrices : 



Z> 



At 



the element of the *th row and the t /th column of the matrix BA 
being obtained by multiplying each element of the tth row of B by the 
corresponding element of the/th. column of A and adding the products 
thus obtained. It is clear that two collineations are not in general 
commutative. 

* A polarity and the identity form a group ; but this forma no exception to the 
statement just made, since the identity must be regarded as a collineation. 



MATRICES 269 

Of the two matrices 




either of which is obtained from the other by interchanging rows and 
columns, one is called the conjugate or transposed matrix of the 
other. The matrix 



A A A 
r-*i3 -"as M wi 

is called the adjoint matrix of the matrix A. The adjoint matrix is 
clearly obtained by replacing each element of the transposed matrix 
by its cof actor Equations (2) of 67 show that the adjoint of a 
given matrix represents the inverse of the eollineation represented "by 
the given matrix. Indeed, by direct multiplication, 

' a u a is a u '4 U Ai -V '^00' 
a ai a aa a as - 4 ia ^22 As = A 
,8i tf 3a "MI A 4s 4*1 ,00^, 

and the matrix just obtained clearly represents the identical col- 
Imeation. Since, when a matrix is thought of as representing a 
eollineation, we may evidently remove any common factor from all 
the elements of the matrix, the latter matrix is equivalent to the 
so-called identical matrix,* 

1 0' 

010. 

, !; 

Furthermore, Equations (3), 67, show that if a given matrix 
represents a eollineation in point coordinates, the conjugate of the 
adjoint matrix represents the same eollineation in line coordinates. 
Also from the representation of the product of two matrices just 
derived, follows the important result: 

The determinant of the product of two matrices (collineations) is 
equal to the product of the determinants of the two matrices (col- 
lineations). 

* In the general theory of matrices these two matrices are not, however, re- 
garded as the same. It is only the interpretation of them as collineations which 
renders them equivalent. 



270 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIYITIES [CHAP.X 

From what has ]ust been said it is clear that a matrix does not 
completely define a collineation, unless the nature of the coordinates 
is specified If it is desired to exhibit the coordinates in the nota- 
tion, we may write the collineation x[ = 2a^ in the symbolic form 



The matrix (a y ) may then be regarded as an operator transforming 
the coordinates x = (x v x s , x s ) into the coordinates xf = (x[, x[ t x^) If 
we place d tj = a jl} the matrix conjugate to (a if ) is (a,,) Also by plac- 
ing I lj = A Jl > the adjoint matrix of (a tj ) is (A t] ). The inverse of the 
above collineation is then written 



Furthermore, the collineation x 1 (a tj )x is represented in line coordi- 
nates by the equation 

% ' = (A*) W - 

This more complete notation will not be found necessary in gen- 
eral in the analytic treatment of collmeations, when no correlations 
are present, but it is essential in the representation of correlations 
by means of matrices. 

The correlation (1) of 94 may clearly be represented symbolically 
by the equation 

'=K)0, 

where the matrix (a v ) is to be regarded as an operator transforming 
the point x into the line u r . This correlation is then expressed as a 
transformation of lines into points by 



The product of two correlations u' (a^ x and '= (Z^) x is there- 
fore represented by 

' = WK) 
(cf. Equations (4), 94), or by 

' = &,) (4,)* 
Also, the inverse of the correlation u' = (a^os is given by 

orby "&>* 



95,96] 



TYPES OF COLLINEATIONS 



271 



EXERCISE 

Show that if [II] is the set of all colhneations in a plane and I\ is any 
con elation, the set of all correlations in the plane is [Iirj, so that the two 
sets of transformations [II] and [IH\] comprise the general protective gioup 
in the plane By vntue of this fact the subgroup of all protective colhneations 
is said to be of index 2 in the general projective group.* 

96. Double points and double lines of a collineation in a plane. 

Referring to Equations (1) of 67 we see that a point (x v x^ X 9 ) 
which is transformed into itself by the collineation (1) must satisfy 
the equations 



which, by a simple rearrangement, may be written 



(1) 



If a point (io lt x z , x s ) is to satisfy these three equations, the deter- 
minant of this system of equations must vanish ; i.e. p must satisfy 
the equation 



(2) 



0. 



This is an equation of the third degree in p, which cannot have more 
than three roots in the number system of our geometry, 

Suppose that /? x is a root of this equation. The system of equa- 
tions (1) is then consistent (which means geometrically that the 
three lines represented by them pass through the same point), and 
the point determined by any two of them (if they are independent, 
i.e. if they do not represent the same line) is a double point. Solving 
the first two of these equations, for example, we find as the coordi- 
nates (x v x z) # 8 ) of a double point 



(3) 



"a& 



$i <&ii~""i 



*21 



* A subgroup [II] of a group is said to be of index n, if there exist n 1 trans- 
formations Ti (i = 1, 2 r . . . n - 1), such that the n - 1 sets [nr f ] of transformations 
together with the set [II] contain, all the transf prmaMons of the group, while no two 
transformations within the same set or from a$y two sets aie identical. 



272 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP X 

winch represent a unique point, unless it should happen that all the 
determinants on the right of this equation vanish. Leaving aside 
this possibility for the moment, we see that every root of Equation 
(2), which is called the characteristic equation of the collmeation (or 
of the representative matrix), gives rise to a unique double point. 
Moreover, every double point is obtainable in tins way. This is the 
analytic form of the fact already noted, that a collineation which is 
not a homology or an elation cannot have more than three doulle 
points, unless it is the identical collineation 

If, however, all the determinants on the right m Equations (3) 
vanish, it follows readily that the first two of Equations (1) represent 
the same line. If the determinants formed analogously from the last 
two equations do not all vanish, we again get a unique double point ; 
but if the latter also vanish, then all three of the equations above 
represent the same line. Every point of this line is then a double point, 
and the collmeation must be a homology or an elation. Clearly this 
can happen only if p l is at least a double root of Equation (2) ; for 
we know that a perspective collmeation cannot have more than one 
double point which is not on the axis of the collineation. 

A complete enumeration of the possible configurations of double 
points and lines of a collineation can be made by means of a study 
of the characteristic equation, making use of the theory of elementary 
divisors * It seems more natural in the present connection to start 
with the existence of one fixed point (Proposition K 3 ) and discuss 
geometrically the cases that can arise. 

By Theorem 4 a collineation is the product of two polarities. Hence 
any double point has the same polar line in both polarities, and that 
polar line is a double line Hence the invariant figure of double points 
and lines is self-dual. 

Eour points of the plane, no three of which are collinear, cannot 
be invariant unless the collineation reduces to the identity. If three 
noncollmear points are invariant, two cases present themselves. If 
the collineation reduces to the identity on no side of the invariant 
triangle, the collmeation is of Type I (cf. 40, Chap. IV). If the 
collmeation is the identity on one and only one side of the invariant 
triangle, the colhneation is of Type JFif If two distinct points are 

* Cf BOcher, Introduction to Higher Algebra, Chaps XX and XXI. 

t If it is the identity on more than one side, it is the identical collineation. 



00] TYPES OF COLLnSTEATIONS 273 

invariant, but no point not on the line I joining these two is invariant, 
two possibilities again arise If the collmeation does not leave every 
point of this line invariant, there is a unique other line through one 
of these points that is invariant, since the invariant figure is self-dual. 
The collineation is then of Type //. If every point of the line is 
invariant, on the other hand, all the lines through a point of the 
line I must be invariant, since the figure of invariant elements is 
self-dual. The collineation is then of Type V. 

If only one point is fixed, only one line can be fixed. The collinea- 
tion is then parabolic both on the line and on the point, and the 
collineation is of Type III, 

We have thus proved that every collineation different from the 
identity is of one of the five types previously enumerated. Type I 
may be represented by the symbol [1, ], 1], the three 1's denoting 
three distinct double points. In Type IV there are also three distinct 
double points, but all points on the line joining two of them are fixed 
and Equation (3) has one double root. Type IV i& denoted by [(1, 1), 1]. 
In Type II, as there are only two distinct double points, Equation 
(1) must have a double root and one simple root This type is ac- 
cordingly denoted by the symbol [2, 1], the 2 indicating the double 
point corresponding to the double root. Type Fis then naturally repre- 
sented by [(2, 1)], the parentheses again indicating that every point 
of the line joining the two points is fixed. Type III corresponds to a 
triple root of (1), and may therefore be denoted by [3]. We have 
then the following : 

THEOREM 6. Every pro/active collineatwn in a, plane is of one of 
the following Jim types : 

[1,1,1] [(1,1),!] 

[2. 1] [& 1)] 



In this table the first column corresponds to three distinct roots 
of the characteristic equation, the second colximn. to a double root, 
the third column to a triple root. The first row corresponds to the 
cases in which there exist at least three double points which are 



274 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP.X 

not collmear ; the second row to the case where there exist at least 
two distinct double points and all such points are on the same line ; 
the third row to the case in which there exists only a single double 
point. 

With every collineation in a plane are associated certain projec- 
tivities on the invariant lines and in the pencils on the invariant 
points. In case the collineation is of Type /, it is completely deter- 
mined if the projectivities on two sides of the invariant triangle are 
given. There must therefore be a relation between the projectivities 
on the three sides of the invariant triangle (of. Ex. 5, p 276). In a 
collineation of Type // the projectivity is parabolic on one of the 
invariant lines but not on the other. The point in which the two 
invariant lines meet may therefore be called singly parabolic. The 
collineation is completely determined if the projectivities on the 
two invariant lines are given In a collineation of Type III the pro- 
jectivity on the invariant line is parabolic, as likewise the projectivity 
on the invariant point. The fixed point may then be called doubly 
parabolic. The projectivities on the invariant lines of a collineation 
of Type V are parabolic except the one on the axis which is the 
identity. The center is thus a singly parabolic point. In the table 
of Theorem 6 the symbols 3, 2, and 1 may be taken to indicate 
doubly and singly and nonparabolic points respectively.* 

We give below certain simple, so-called canonical forms of the 
equations defining collmeations of these five types. 

Type I. Let the invariant triangle be the triangle of reference. 
The collineation is then given by equations of the form. 



/>.<= a ss x 



in which a n , a zz , a ss are the roots of the characteristic equation and 
must therefore be all distinct 

Type IV, Homology. If the vertices of the triangle of reference 
are taken as invariant points, the equations reduce to the form written 
above ; but since one of the lines x 1 = 0, # 2 = 0, x a = is pointwise 

* For a more detailed discussion of collineataons, reference may be made to 
Newson, A New Theory of Collmeations, etc., American Journal of Mathematics, 
Vol. XXIV, p 109. 



90] TYPES OF GOLLINEATIONS 275 

invariant, we must have either a aa - a ss or ff !13 = a n or a n = a Z2 Thus 
the homology may he written 



A harmonic homology or reflection is obtained by setting a aa = ~l. 
jfyjpe JJ. The characteristic equation has one double root, p l = p 
say, and a simple root p 3 Let the double point corresponding to 
Pi~P* be ^=(0, 0, 3), let the double point corresponding to p s be 
Z7 8 = (l, 0, 0), and let the third vertex of the triangle of reference 
be any point on the double line w 8 corresponding to p a , which line 
will pass through the point Z7 r The collineatiou is then of the form 



z) 



since the lines 0^= and x%= are double lines and (1, 0, 0) is a 
double point. The characteristic equation of the collineation is clearly 

K-P)K~/ ) )K3~^= 

and since this must have a double root, it follows that two of the 
numbers u , a2 , a m must be equal. To determine which, place 
P = a M ) using the minors of the second row, we find, as coordinates 
of the corresponding double point, 

(0, (a u - a 2a ) (a ea - ), a ss (a u - a 22 ) ), 

which is U v and heuce we have a 2a == a as . The collineation then is 
of Type II, if u = a 22 . Its equations are therefore 



where a 3a * and a u ^ a a2 . 

Type III. The characteristic equation has a triple root, p^p^ p & , 
say. Let U^ (0, 0, 1) be the single double point, and the line x^ be 
the single double line. With this choice of cobrdinates the collineation 
has the form , 



276 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP X 

By writing the characteristic equation we find, in view of the fact 
that the equation has a triple root, that a n = 22 = a ay The form of 
the collineation is therefore 



where the numbers a 21 , a S2 must be different from 

Type F, Elatwn Choosing (0, 0, 1) as center and ^=0 as axis, 
the equations of the collineation reduce to the form given for Type ///, 
where, however, a 82 must be zero in order that the line x l be 
pointwise invariant. The equations for Type II also yield an elation 
in case a u = a 22 . Thus an elation may be written 



EXERCISES 

1 Determine the collineation -which transforms the points A = (0, 0, 1), 
B = (0, 1, 0), C = (1, 0, 0), D = (1, 1, 1) into the points B, C, D, A respec- 
tively Show that the chaiacteiistic equation of this collineation is (p 1) 
(p 2 + 1) = 0, which in any field has one loot. Deteimine the double point 
and double line corresponding to this root Assuming the field of numbers to 
be the ordiuaiy complex field, determine the cooidmates of the remaining two 
double points and double lines. Veiify, by actually multiplying the matiices, 
that this collineation is of period 4 (a fact which is evident from the defini- 
tion of the collineation). 

2 With the same cooidmates for A, B, C, D determine the collineation 
which transforms these points respectively into the points ft, A , D, C. The 
le&ultmg collineation must, from, this definition, be a homology. Why? De- 
termine its center and its a,xis By actual multiplication of the matrices 
veufy that its squaie is the identical collineation. 

3. Express each of the collineations in Exs. i and 2 in terms of line 
coordinates 

4. Show that the characteristic cross ratios of the one-dimensional projcc- 
tivities on the sides of the invariant triangle of the collineation a % ' = ar 1 , 
x l ~ ^a> x l = CX 3 are *^ e ia faos of the numbers a, b, c. Hence show that the 
product of these cross ratios is equal to unity, the double points being taken 
around the tuangle in a given oider. 

5 Prove the latter part of Ex. 4 for the cross ratios of the projectivities 
on the sides of the invanant triangle of any collineation of Type /. 



an] TYPES OF COLLINEATIOKS 277 

6 Write the equations of a collineation of period 3 ; 4 , 5 , .; n ; 

7 By properly choosing the system of nonhomogenoous cooidmatcs any 
collmcatHm of Type / iiuy be iopi osented by equations ?' = rw , / = by The 
.sot ol all colhneatums obtained by giving the parameter* n, b all possible 
values J'oiuiH <i gioup. Show that the eollmeatiom *' = <u, y' - a'i/, -where r 
is constant foi all eollinejitions of the set, form a subgroup Show that eveiy 
collineation of this subgroup leaves invanant every ciuve whose equation is 
?/ = cjf, where c is any constant. Such curves aie oalled path cwves of the 
colhneations. 

8. If P is any point of a given path curve, p the tangent at P, and 
A,B, C the vortices of the invariant tiiaugle, then Ijfc (;;, 7M, PB, PC) is a 
constant. 

9. For the values ? =- 1, 2, % the path ciuves of the collineations of the 
subgroup described in Ex 7 are conies tangent to two sides of the invariant 
triangle at two vertices. 

10. If r - 0, the subgroup of Ex 7 consists entirely of homologies 

11. Prove that any collineation of Type / may be expiessed in the form 



with the restriction a -M 2 = 1 

12. Prove that any collineation can be expressed as a product of colhnea- 
( tions of Type 7. 

13. Let the invariant figure of a collineation of Type 77 be A, B, 1, m, 
where l AB, B lm. Tho product of such a collmeation by another of 

j Type 77 with invariant figure A', B, I, m' is in general of Type 77, but may 

1 be of Types 777, TV, 01 V. Under what conditions do tho latter cases anse ? 

14. Using the notation of Ex. 13, the product of a collineation of Type II 
with invariant figure A , B, I, m by one with invariant figure A , B' t I, m' is 
in general of Type 77, but may be of Types 777 or IV, Under what conditions 
do the latter cases arise ? 

15 Prove that any collineation can be expressed as a product of collinea- 
tions of Type 77. 

16. Two collineations of Type 777 with the same invariant figure are not 
in general commutative. 

17. Any protective collineation can be expressed as a pioduct of collinea- 
tions of Type 777. 

18. If II is an elation whose center is C, and P any point not on tho 
axis, then P and C are harmonically conjugate with respect to n- 1 (P) 
and II (7>), 

19. If two coplanar conies are projoetive, tho correspondence between the 
points of one and the tangents at homologous points of the other determines 
a correlation. 

20. If in a collineation between two distinct planes every point of the 
line of intersection, of the planes is self-corresponding, the planes are per- 
spective. 

t 
3 



278 



TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJEOTIVITIES [CHAP X 



21 In nonhomogeneous coordinates a collineation of Type I with fixed 
points (a v a a ), (b v 6 2 ) (c v c 2 ) may be wntten 



x y 1 



a; ?/ 1 



,_ 
X ~ 



x y I ' 
! a 1 1 



a: # 1 
Oj a 2 1 1 
l> \ k 



Type II may be -written 



X'= 



s 



s x s 2 

and Type III may be written 
or y 1 



t 



x y 
a a 



1 

! 






z 



1 



t 





1 
1 1 
i 




x y 
a t a 2 
S s 



97. Double pairs of a correlation. We inquire now regarding the 
existence of double pairs of a correlation in a plane. By a double pair 
is meant a point X and a line u such that the correlation transforms 
X into u and also transforms u into X; in symbols, if T is the cor- 
relation, such that T(X) = u and r(w)==X We have already seen 
(Theorem 3) that if the vertices and opposite sides of a triangle are 
double pairs of a correlation, the correlation is a polarity. 

We may note first that the problem of finding the double pairs of 
a correlation is in one form equivalent to finding the double elements 



97] DOUBLE PAIRS OF A CORRELATION 279 

of a certain collineation. In fact, a double pair X, u is such that 
T(X)=u and F a (JtT) = F (w) = X, so that the pomt of a double pair 
of a correlation F is a double point of the colhneation F a . Similarly, 
it umy be seen that the lines of the double pairs are the double lines 
of the collmeatiou F 3 It follows also from these considerations that 
F is a polarity, if F a is the identical collineation. 

Analytically, the problem of determining the double pairs of a 
correlation leads to the question For what values of (x v % s , x 3 ) are 
the coordinates 



of the line to which it corresponds proportional to the coordinates 



of the line which corresponds to it in the given correlation ? If p is 
the unknown factor of proportionality, this condition is expressed by 
the equations 



(1) K~^^^+K~p 2a )a3 2 +(ff 23 --/)a 82 )a; 3 == 0, 



which must be satisfied by the coordinates (x lt x v Kg) of any point 
of a double pair. The remainder of the treatment of this problem is 
similar to the corresponding part of the problem, of determining the 
double elements of a collineation ( 96). The factor of proportionality 
p is determined by the equation 

a u 

(2) *ai 



which is of the third degree and has (under Proposition K a ) three 
roots, of which one is 3 , and of which the other two may be proper 
or improper Every root of this equation when substituted for p in 
(1) renders these equations consistent The coordinates (x v % a; 8 ) 
are then determined by solving two of these. 

If the reciprocity in question is a polarity, Equations (1) must be 
satisfied identically, i.e. for every set of values (x lt ss z) a? 8 ), This would 
imply that all the relations 

S-/ K ** aa <&/=!, 2, 3) 

are satisfied. 



280 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP.X 

Let us suppose first that at least one of the diagonal elements of the 
matrix of the coefficients (a ) be different from 0. If this be a n , the 
relation a u pa u =Q gives at once p = l; and this value leads at 
once to the further relations 

% = S> (v = l, 2, 3). 

The matrix in question must then be symmetrical If, on the other 
hand, we have a u a zz = a 6a 0, there must be some coefficient v 
different from 0. Suppose, for example, a ia =f= Then the relation 
a 12 &a 21 = shows that neither Ic nor a sl can be The substitution 
of one in the other of the relations a lz = ka zl and 21 = ka lz then gives 
& 2 = 1, or Jc = 1. The value Jo = 1 again leads to the condition that 
the matrix of the coefficients be symmetrical The value Jc = -1 
gives a h =0, and #= a j{ , which would render the matrix skew 
symmetrical. The determinant of the transformation would on this 
supposition vanish (since every skew-symmetrical determinant of odd 
order vanishes), which is contrary to the hypothesis The value 
& = -1 is therefore impossible. We have thus been led to the fol- 
lowing theorem: 

THEOEEM 7. The necessary and sufficient condition that a reci- 
procity in a plane be a polarity is that the matrix of its coefficients 
"be symmetrical. 

If the coordinate system is chosen so that the point which corre- 
sponds to p = 1 in Equation (2) is (1, 0, 0), it is clear that we must 
have a zl = a lz and a 31 = a 18 . If the line corresponding doubly to 
(1, 0, 0) does not pass through it, the coordinates [1, 0, 0] may be 
assigned to this line. The equations of the correlation thus assume 

the form 

pu[= a n x^ 

(3) K= 



and Equation (2) reduces to 



(4) 



0. 



The roots, other than 1, of this equation clearly correspond to points 
on [1, 0, 0]. Choosing one of these points (Proposition K 2 ) as (0, 0, 1), 
we have either a zs = 8a , which would lead to a polarity, or a 88 = 0. 



07] DOUBLE PAIRS OF A CORRELATION 281 

In the latter case it is evident that (4) has a double root if a w = a t) 
Imt that otherwise it has two distinct roots. Therefore a con elation 
in which (1, 0, 0) and [1, 0, 0] correspond doubly, and which is not 
a polarity, may be reduced to one of the three forms : 



(Q = C = 1, rt = 0) 



IV pul~ -x a , (a =0) 

K= 

The squares of these correlations are collmeations of Types /, //, IV 
respectively. 

If the line doubly corresponding to (1, 0, 0) does pass through it, 
the coordinates [0, 1, 0] may be assigned to this line, and the equa- 
tions of the correlation become 

K= n* 

puf - %i + Ogfa + a 38 a; 8 , (a M ^ 0, 28 & a 82 ) 

pMg'sa 8a a +a 88 a! 8 , 

Equation (2) at the same time reduces to 

Ml-?) 8 =0, 

and the square of the correlation is always of Type ///. There are 
thus five types of correlations, the polarity and those whose squares 
are collmeations of Types J, //, J/J, IV. 

EXERCISES * 

1 The points which lie upon the lines to which they correspond in a cor- 
relation form a conic section C 8 , ami the hues which lie upon the points to 
which they correspond arc, the tangents to a conic A' 2 How are C 9 and K z 
related, in each of the five types of correlations, to one another and to the 
doubly corresponding elements ? 

* On the theory of correlations see Seydewitz, Arclnv der Mathematik, 1st series, 
Vol VIII (1846), p. 82 ; and SchrSter, Journal ftir die reme und angewandte Mathe- 
matik, Vol. ZJOCVII (1874), p. 105. 



282 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJEOTIVITIES 

2. If a line a does not lie upon the point A' to which it conesponds in a 
coir elation, there is a projectivity between the points of a and the points in 
which their corresponding lines meet a. In the case of a polarity this pio- 
jectivity is always an involution. In any other correlation the lines upon 
which this projectivity is involutoric all pass through a unique fixed point 
The line o having the dual property coi responds doubly to The double 
points of the involutions on the lines through aie on the conic C 2 , and the 
double lines of the involutions on the points of K* are tangent to K* and o 
are polar with respect to C 2 and /C a . If a correlation determines involutions 
on three nonconcurrent lines, it is a polarity. 

3. The lines of K z through a point P of C 2 are the line which is ti ansf ormcd 
into P and the line into which P is transformed by the given coi relation. 

4. In a polarity C 2 and K z aie the same conic 

5. A necessary and sufficient condition that a colhneation be the pioduct of 
two reflections is the existence of a correlation which is left invariant by the 
colhneation * 

98. Fundamental conic of a polarity in a plane. We have jusl 
seen that a polarity m a plane is given by the equations 



(1) 



DEFINITION. Two homologous elements of a polarity in a plane ar 
called pole and polar, the point being the pole of the line and th 
line being the polar of the point. If two points are so situated the 
one is on the polar of the other, they are said to be conjugate. 

The condition that two points in a plane of a polarity be conji 
gate is readily derived. In fact, if two points P = (x v x s , x s ) an 
P f =z(xl, x'v C 8 ') are conjugate, the condition sought is simply tin 
the point P' shall be on the line p'= [/, w 2 ', M B '], the polar of JP; i 
u[x[ -f- ufaz + w 8 X = 0. Substituting for u[, u, u their values 
terms of x v x z , 8 from (1), we obtain the desired condition, viz. : 



(2) 

4- 



As was to be expected, this condition is symmetrical in the cobr 
nates of the two points P and P'. By placing x[ = ic t we obtain 1 

* This is a special case of a theorem of Dunham Jackson, Transactions of 
American Mathematical Society, Vol. X (1909), p 479. 



POLAB, SYSTEM. 283 

condition that the point P be self-conjugate, i.e that it be on its polar. 
We thus obtain the result . 

THEOREM 8 The sdf -conjugate points of the polarity (1) are on 
the conic whose equation is 

(3) a n x? + a n ^x* + a ss x$ + 2 a^x z + 2 a^te, + 2 28 x^ = ; 
and, conversely, every point of this come is self-conjugate. 

This conic is called the fundamental conic of the polarity. All of 
its points may be improper, but it can never degenerate, for, if so, 
the determinant \a^\ would have to vanish (cf. Ex., p. 187). By 
duality we obtain 

THEOREM 8'. The self-conjugate lines of the polarity (1) are lines 
of the conic 

(4) A u u?+ A n uf+A n u*+ 2 ^ M 1 w a + 2 A n u^ + 2 A n u t u t - , 
and, conversely, every line of this conic is self-conjugate. 

Every point JT of the conic (3) corresponds in the polarity (1) to 
the tangent to (3) at X. For if not, a point A of (3) would be polar 
to a line a through A and meeting (3) also in a point J5. B would 
then be polar to a line 5 through B, and hence the line a = AB 
would, by the definition of a polarity, be polar to ab = B. This woxild 
require that a correspond both to A and to B 

If now we recall that the polar system of a conic constitutes a 
polarity (Theorem 18, Cor., Chap. V) in which all the points and 
lines of the conic, and only these, are self-conjugate, it follows from 
the above that every polarity is given by the polar system of its 
fundamental conic. This and other results following immediately 
from it are contained in the following theorem : 

THEOREM 9. Every polarity is the polar system of a conic, the 
fundamental conic of the polarity. The self-conjugate points are 
the points and the self-conjugate lines are the tangents of this conic. 
Every pole and polar pair are pole and polar with respect to the 
fundamental conic. 

This establishes that Equation (4) represents the same conic as 
Equation (3). The last theorem may be utilized to develop the ana- 
lytic expressions for poles and polars, and tangents to a conic. This 
we take up in the next section. 



284 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP X 

99, Poles and polars with respect to a conic. Tangents. We 

have seen that the most general equation of a conic in point coor- 
dinates may be written 

(1) a n aj 1 2 + ^22^+ Vs 2 + 2 <WB + 2 VA+ 2 Va^ 0. 



The result of the preceding section shows that the equation of the 
same conic in line coordinates is 



(2) 4X+ -4.X + 4X + 2 A u i tt + 2 4Xtt,+ 2 ^ 28 w 2 w s = 0, 
where -4 is the cofactor of a in the determinant 



This result may also be stated as follows 

THEOREM 10. The necessary and sufficient condition that the line 
u^+ u z oe 2 -\- u 3 x a = be tangent to the conic (1) is that Equatwn (2) 
be satisfied. 

COROLLARY. This condition may also be written in the form 

a n a i2 a is u i 

u : u a u s 

Equation (2) of the preceding section expresses the condition that 
the points (x v x z , # 8 ) and (x[, x}, x) be conjugate with respect to the 
conic (1). If in this equation (#/, aj 2 , #') be supposed given, while 
(x v a; 2 , C 3 ) is regarded as variable, this condition is satisfied by all the 
points of the polar of (x[, x, a; 3 ') with respect to the conic and by no 
others It is therefore the equation of this polar. When arranged 
according to the variable coordinates x l} it becomes 

while if we arrange it according to the coordinates #/, it becomes 



(4) 



+ (! + a 28 a; 2 + 83 a5 8 ) = 0. 

Now it is readily verified that the latter of these equations may 
be derived from the equation (1) of the conic by applying to the 
left-hand member of this equation the polar operator 



i uo,ioo] VAEIOUS DEFINITIONS OF CONICS 285 



( 89) and dividing the resulting equation by 2. Furthermore, if 

we define the symbols ~> .> -~ to be the result of substituting 

dx{ tog dx^ 

(ic/, a3 2 , ,Tg) for (IL\, ,r a , .c 3 ) m the expressions ~- >>- (f being any 

9.^ t 3it' 2 oJ3 8 

polynomial in a^, je 2 , .'e a ), it is readily seen that Equation (3) is 
equivalent to 

x <L + X $L + X K^Q 

where now/ is the left-hand member of (1). 
This loads to the following theorem : 

TIIEOHKM ]]. IffQis the equation of a conic in homogeneous 
point coordinates, the equation of the polar of awy point (./, x^ ac) is 
given "by either of the equations 



If the point (a;/, .r a ', a; a ') is a point on the come, either of these equa- 
tions represents the tangent to the conic f = at this point. 

100. Various definitions of conies. The definition of a (point) 
conio as the locus of the intersections of homologous lines of two 
projective flat pencils in the same plane was first given by Steiner in 
1832 and used about the same time by Chasles. The considerations 
of the preceding sections at once suggest two other methods of defi- 
nition, one synthetic, the other analytic. The former begins by the 
synthetic definition of a polarity (of. p. 263), and then defines a point 
conic as the set of all self-conjugate points of a polarity) and a line 
conic as the set of all self-conjugate lines of a polarity. This defini- 
tion was first given by von Staudt in 1847. From it he derived the 
fundamental properties of conies and showed easily that his definition 
is equivalent to Steiner's. The analytic method is to define a (point) 
conic as the set of all points satisfying any equation of the second 
degree, homogeneous in three variables go v # 8 , a? 8 - This definition (at 
least in its nonhomogeneous form) dates back to Descartes and format 
(1637) and the introduction of the notions of analytic geometry. 



286 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP x 

The oldest definition of conies is due to the ancient Greek geometeis, who 
denned a conic as the plane section of a circular cone. This definition involves 
metnc ideas and hence does not concern us at this point. We will leturn to it 
later It is of interest to note in passing, howevei, that fiom this definition 
Apollomus (about 200 B c ) derived a theorem equivalent to the one that the 
equation of a conic in point cooidinates is of the second degiee. 

The reader will find it a valuable exercise to derive for himself 
the fundamental properties of polarities synthetically, and thence to 
develop the theory of conies from von Staudt's definition, at least so 
far as to show that his definition is equivalent to Stemer's. It may 
be noted that von Staudt's definition has the advantage over Stemer's 
of including, without reference to Proposition K 2 , conies consisting 
entirely of improper points (since there exist polarities which have 
no proper self-conjugate points) The reader may in this connection 
refer to the original work of von Staudt, Die Geometrie der Lage, 
Nurnberg (1847) , or to the textbook of Ennques, Vorlesungen iiber 
projective Geometrie, Leipzig (1903), 

EXERCISES 

1 Derive the condition of Theorem 10 dn ectly by imposing the condition 
that the quadratic which determines the intei sections of the given line with 
the conic shall have equal loots What is the dual of this theorem ? 

2. Verify analytically the fundamental pioperties of poles and polais with 
respect to a conic (Theorems 13-18, Chap. V) 

3 State the dual of Theorem 11. 

4. Show how to constiuct the correlation between a plane of points and a 
plane of lines, having given the homologous pairs A , a'; B, I' ; C, c' ; D, d' 

5 Show that a correlation between two pianos is uniquely determined if 
two pencils of points in one plane are made projective respectively with two 
pencils of lines in the other, provided that in this projectivity the point of 
intersection of the axes of the two pencils of points coriesponds to the line 
joining the two centers of the pencils of lines. 

6. Show that in our system of homogeneous point and line cobrdmates the 
pairs of points and lines with the same cobrdmates are poles and polars with 
respect to the conic a:, 2 + a;., 2 + a; 2 = 0. 

* a o 

7 On a general line of a plane in which a polanty has been defined the 
pairs of conjugate points form an involution the doxible points of which are 
the (proper or improper) points of intersection of the line with the funda- 
mental conic of the polarity. 

^ 8 A polarity in a plane is completely defined if a self-polar triangle is 
given together with one pole and polar pair of which the point is not on a 
side nor the hue on a vertex of the triangle, 



loo, 101] PAIRS OF CONICS 287 

9. Prove Thcoicm 3 analytically 

10. Given a simples plane pentagon, theie exists a polaiity in -which to each 
vertex conesponds the opposite side 

11 The three points A', B', C' on the Bides BC, CA, AB of a triangle that 
are conjugate in a polanty to the veitices A, B, C respectively are collineai 
(cf. Ex 13, p. 125). 

12. Show that a polaiity is completely determined when the two involutions 
of conjugate points on two conjugate lines are given. 

13 Constiuct the polarity determined Ity a self-polar tuangle ABC and an 
involution of conjugate points on a line. 

14. Construct the polarity determined by two pole and polai pans A, a and 
B, b and one pair of conjugate points C, C". 

15 If a triangle STU is self-polai with regard to a conic C 2 , and A is any 
point of C 2 , there are three triangles having A as a vertex which ate inscribed 
to C 3 and circumscribed to STU (Sturm, Die Lehre von den geometrischen 
Verwandtschaften, Vol I, p. 147) 

101. Pairs of conies. If two polarities, i.e. two conies (proper or 
improper), are given, their product is a collineation which leaves 
invariant any point or line which has the same polar or pole with 
regard to both conies. Moreover, any point or line which is not left 
invariant by this colhnealion must have different polars or poles 
with regard to the two conies. Hence the points and lines which 
have the same polars and poles with regard to two conies in the 
same plane form one of the five invariant figures of a nonidentical 
collineation. 

Type L If the common self-polar figure of the two conies is of 
Type I, it is a self-polar triangle for both conies. Since any two conies 
are protectively equivalent (Theorem 9, Chap. YIII), the coordinate 
system may be so chosen that the equation of one of the conies, A*, is 

(1) s-*+a, 9s!S 0. 

With regard to this conic the triangle (0, 0, 1), (0, 1, 0), (1, 0, 0) is 
self-polar. The general equation of a conic with respect to which this 
triangle is self-polar is clearly 

(2) &&1 ckfll + a 8 aj a 3 ss 0. 

An equation of the form (2) may therefore be taken as the equation 
of the other conic, J5 a , if (1) and (2) have no other common self-polar 
elements than the fundamental triangle, Consider the set of conies 

(3) 



288 



TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP X 



The coordinates of any point which satisfy (1) and (2) also satisfy (3). 
Hence all conies (3) pass through the points common to A z and B*. 
For the value X = a s , (3) gives the pair of lines 

(4) (a 1 - a s ) xl - (a 2 - a s ) x* = 0, 

which intersect in (0, 0, 1). The points of intersection of these lines 
with (1) are common to all the comes (3) 

The lines (4) are distinct, unless ft 1 = a 3 or a z =a s But if a 1 = a 3 , 
any point (a;/, 0, a; 3 ') on the line x z has the polar x[x v + # 8 'a? 3 = 
both with regard to (1) and with regard to (2). The self-polar figure 
is therefore of Type IV In order that this figure be of Type I, the 
three numbers a v a 2> a s must all be distinct If this condition is 
satisfied, the lines (4) meet the conies (3) m four distinct points. 

#010) 




(100)\ 



FIG 100 

The actual construction of the points is now a problem of the second 
degree. We have thus established (fig. 100) 

THEOREM 12. If two conies have a common self -polar triangle (and 
no other common self-polar pair of point and line], tli&y intersect in 
four distinct points (proper or improper] Any two conies of the 
pencil determined ly these points have the same self-polar triangle. 
Dually, two such conies have four common tangents, and any two 



101] 



PAIRS OF CONICS 



289 




conies of the range determined by these common tangents have the same 
self -polar triangle 

COKOLLAKY Any pencil of comes of Type I can be represented by * 

the four common points being in this ease (1, 1, 1), (1, 1, 1), (1, 1, 1), 
and ( 1, 1, 1). 

Type II. When the 
common self-polar figure 
is of Type //, one of the ^t^/^^ _ (oi- 
points lies on its polar, \ /'"^^ ~^~>^ *s:- a=: [ooi] 
and therefore this polar is 
a tangent to each of the 
comes A 3 , 2> a . Since two 
tangents cannot intersect 
in a point of contact, the 
two lines of the self-polar 
figure are not both tan- 
gents. Hence the point B 
of the self-polar figure 

which IB on only one of the lines is the pole of the line 5 of the figure 
which is on only one of the points (fig 101), and the line a on the two 
points is tangent to both conies at the point A which is on the two lines. 

Choose a system of coordinates with ^. = (1, 0, 0), a [Q, 0, 1], 
B (0, 1, 0), and & = [0, 1, 0]. The equation of any conic being 



A=(100) 



101 



the condition that A be on the conic is a i = ; that a then be tan- 
gent is & 8 ; that I then be the polar of B is \ 0. Hence the 
general equation of a conic with the given self-polar figure is 

2 = 0. 



(6) 



+ 



* Equation (6) is typical for a pencil of conies of Type I, and Theorem 12 is a 
sort of converse to the developments of 47, Chap. V. The reader will note that 
if the problem of finding the points of intersection of two conies is set up directly, 
it is of the fourth degree, but that it is here reduced to a problem of the thud 
degree (the determination of a common self-polar triangle) followed "by two quad- 
ratic constructions. This corresponds to the well-known solution of the general 
biquadratic equation (cf. Fine, College Algebra, p,,486). For a further discussion 
of the analytic geometry of pencils of conies, cf. Clebsch-Lindemann, Vorlesungen 
uber Geometne, 2d ed., Vol. I, Part I (1906), pp, 212 ft 



290 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP x 

Since any two conies are projectively equivalent, A 2 may be chosen 

to be 

(7) af+xi+Zx&^O. 

The equation of B* then has the form (6), with the condition that 
the two conies have no other common self-polar elements Since the 
figure in which a is polar to A and b to B can only reduce to Types 
IV or V, we must determine under what conditions each point on a 
or each point on & has the same polar with regard to (6) and (7). 
The polar of (#/, # a ', a? 8 ') with regard to (6) is given by 

= 0- 



Hence the first case can arise only if a a = & 2 ; and the second only 
if a a = & 2 

Introducing the condition that a a , a a , 5 2 are all distinct, it is then 
clear that the set of comes 

OJB* + a a x* + 2 \x : x s + X (a + xf + 2 o^) = 
contains a line pair for X = a z> viz the lines 

(a, - a,) xl + 2 (&, - a 2 ) a;^ = 

Hence the comes have in common the points of intersection with (7) 

of the line 

(a, o a ) 8 + 2 (& 2 a a ) a?! = 
This gives 

THEOREM 13 If two comes have a common self -polar figure of 
Type II, they have three points in common and a common tangent at 
one of them. Dually, they have three common tangents and a common 
point of contact on one of the tangents The two conies determine a 
pencil and also a range of conies of Type II. 

COROLLARY. Any pencil of conies of Type II may le represented 
ly the equation x* x\ + Xo^ = 0. The conies of this pencil all pass 
through the points (0, 1, 1), (0, 1, 1), (1, 0, 0) and are tangent to 
a- 8 =0. 

Type III. When the common self-polar figure is of Type III, the 
two conies evidently have a common tangent and a common point 
of contact, and only one of each. Let the common tangent be # 8 *** 0, 
its point of contact be (1, 0, 0), and let A 2 be given by 

( 8 ) as? +20^=0. 



ioi] PAIRS OF CONIGS 291 

The general equation of a conic tangent to # 3 = at (1, 0, 0) is 

(9) (ijrl + #r% + 2 j^a^R, + 2 Igfcft = 0, 

with regard to which the polar of any point (./, a 1 ,, 0) on x s = is 
given by 

( 1 0) X a; 2 + I 1 a^x 9 + fc^X = 0. 

This will "be identical with the polar of (x[, aJ 2 ', 0) with regard to A z 
for all values of x[, a?j, if & 2 = 2 and \= 0, Since (1, 0, 0) only is to 
have the same polar with regard to both conies, we impose at least 
one of the conditions Z> 3 = tt a , & a = 0. The line (10) will now be 
identical with the polar of (8) for any point (x[ t #/, 0) satisfying the 
condition 



This quadratic equation must have only one root if the self-polar figure 
is to be of Type IIL This requires & 2 = 2 , and as 5 a , a a cannot both 
be unless (9) degenerates, the equation of J:? 8 can be taken as 

(11) x* + 2 x& + a,r + 2 \x^ = 0, (& t * 0). 

The conies (8) and (11) now evidently have in common the points of 
intersection of (8) with the 
line pair 




and no other points. Since 
# 8 = is a tangent, this gives 
two common points. If the 
second common point is taken A~(l 00) a=[o ll 

to be (0, 0, 1), the set of 
conies which have in com- 
mon the points (0, 0, 1) and (1, 0, 0) = A and the tangent a at A t 
and no other points, may be written (fig. 102) 

THEOBEM 14. If two conies have a common self-polar figure of 
Type III, they have two points in common and a common tangent 
at one of them, and one other common tangent They determine a 
pencil and a f range of conies of type IIL 



292 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PROJECTIVITIES [CHAP. X 

COROLLARY A pencil of conies of Type III can be represented "by 
the equation x\ + 2 x^ + \x 2 x s 0. 

Type IV. When the common self-polar figure is of Type IV, let the 
line of fixed points be x a = and its pole be (0, 0, 1) The coordinates 
being chosen as they were for Type /, the conic A* has the equation 

a - n 



and any other conic having in common with A 2 the self-polar tri 
angle (I, 0, 0), (0, 1, 0), (0, 0, 1) has an equation of the form 






The condition that every point on x s shall have the same polar 
with regard to this conic as with regard to A* is a t = a z . Hence B 
may be written - 



Any conic of this form has the same tangents as A* at the points 
(1, 1, 0) and (1, 1, 0) (fig. 103). Hence, if X is a variable parameter, 

the last equation represents 
a pencil of conies of Type IV 
according to the classification 
previously made. 

/OfljT""--^ V / / J THEOREM 15. If two conies 

^""^^ \ i / / j iave a common self-polar 

figure of Type IV, they have 
two 'points in common and 

Fl - 103 n f * ^ * 

the tangents at these points. 

They determine a pencil (which is also a range) of conies of Type IV, 

COROLLARY. A pencil of conies of Type IV may be represented ~by 

the equation 




, , 
xl 0.7 -f Xa3 8 2 = ; 

and also by the equation 

x? + \x z x s = 0. 

Type V. When the common self-polar figure is of Type F, let the 
point of fixed lines be (1, 0, 0) and the line of fixed points be a? 8 == 0. 
As in Type ///, let -4 2 be given by 

(8) ^+2^=0. 

We have seen, in the discussion of that type, that all points of # 8 = 
have the same polars with respect to (8) and (9), if in (9) we have 



101] PAIRS OF CONICS 293 

\ = a z and l) t = 0. Hence, IE A 3 and li 2 are to have a common self- 
polar figure of Type V, tlio equation of If must have the form 

(1 il) a a (atf + 2 r r a ) + a^* = 

From the form of equations (8) and 

(13) it is evident that the comes have 

m common only the point (1, 0, 0) and 

the tangent a, = 0, and that every point 

on a? a = has the same polar with re- a=[00l] A = (<ioo) 

spect to both conies (fig. 104). Hence, 

they determine a pencil of Typo V. 

THEOREM 16. If two conies have a common self-polar figure of 
Type V, they have a lineal element (and no oilier elements) in com- 
mon and determine a pencil (which is also a range) of conies of 
Type V according to the classification already given. 

COROLLARY. A pencil of conies of Type V can be represented, "by the 

equation 







As an immediate consequence of the corollaries of Theorems 12-16 
we have 

THEOREM 17. Any pencil of conies may be written in the form 



where f= and ff=*Q are the equations of two conies (degenerate or 
not) of the pencil. 

EXERCISES 

1. Prove analytically that tho polars of a point P with respect to the 
conies of a pencil all pass through a point Q. Tho points P and Q a-ie double 
points of the involution determined by the conies of tho pencil on the line PQ 
Give a linear construction for Q (of. Ex. 3, p. 130). The coirespondence 
obtained by letting every point P correspond to the associated point Q is a 
"quadiatic birational transformation." Determine the equations representing 
this transformation. The point <2, which is conjugate to P with regard to all 
the conies of the pencil, is called the conjut/ale of P with respect to the pencil. 
The locus of the conjugates of the points of a line with legard to a pencil of 
conies is a conic (cf. Ex, 81, p. 140). 

2. One and only one conic passes through four given points and has two 
given pomes as conjugate points, provided the two given points are not con- 
jugate with respect to all the conies of the pencil determined by the given 
set of four. Show how to construct this conic. 



294 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PEOJECTIVITIES [CHAP X 

3 One conic in general, or a pencil of conies in a special case, passes 
through three given points and has two given pairs of points as conjugate 
points. Give the construction 

4 One conic in geneial, 01 a pencil of conies in a special case, passes 
thiough two given points and has thiee pans of given points as conjugate 
points ; or passes thiough a given point and has four pairs of given points as 
conjugate points ; or has five given pans of conjugate points. Give the cor- 
responding constructions for each case 

102. Problems of the third and fourth degrees.* The problem of 
constructing tlie points of intersection of two conies in the same 
plane is, in general, of the fourth degree according to the classifi- 
cation of geometric problems described in 83 Indeed, if one of 
the coordinates be eliminated between the equations of two conies, 
the resulting equation is, in general, an irreducible equation of the 
fourth, degree. Moreover, a little consideration will show that any 
equation of the fourth, degree may be obtained in this way. It 
results that every problem of the fourth degree in a plane may 
be reduced to the problem of constructing the common points (or 
by duality the common tangents) of two comes. Further, the prob- 
lem of finding the remaining intersections of two conies in a plane 
of which one point of intersection is given, is readily seen to be of 
the third degree, in general; and any problem of this degree can be 
reduced to that of finding the remaining intersections of two conies 
of which one point of intersection is known. It follows that any 
problem of the third or fourth degree in a plane may be reduced 
to that of finding the common elements of two conies in the 
plane, f 

A problem of the fourth, (or third) degree cannot therefore be 
solved by the methods sufficient for the solution of problems of the 
first and second degrees (straight edge and compass) $ In the case 
of problems of the second degree we have seen that any such prob- 
lem could be solved by linear constructions if the intersections of 

* In this section we have made use of Amodeo, Lezioni di Geometria Projettiva, 
pp, 436, 437. Some of the exercises are taken from the same book, pp. 448-461. 

t Moreover, we have seen (p. 289, footnote) that any problem of the fourth 
degree may be reduced to one of the third degree, followed by two of the second 
degree. 

t With the usual representation of the ordinary real geometry we should require 
an instrument to draw conies 



102] THIRD AND FOURTH DEGREE PROBLEMS 295 

every line in the plane with a fixed conic in that plane were assumed 
known. Similarly, any problem of the fourth (or third) degree can 
be solved by linear and quadratic constructions if the intersections 
of every conic in the- plane with a iixod conic in this plane are 
assumed known. This follows readily from the fact that any conic 
in the plane can be transformed by linear constructions into the 
fixed conic. A problem of the third or fourth degree in a plane 
will then, in the future, be considered solved if it has been reduced 
to the finding of the intersections of two conies, combined with 
any linear or quadratic constructions. As a typical problem of the 
third degree, for example, we give the following: 

To find the double points of a, noniperspcctive collineation in a, plane 
which is determined "by four pairs of homologous points. 

Solution. When four pairs of homologous elements are given, we 
can construct linearly the point or line homologous with any given 
point or line in the plane. Let the collineation be represented by II, 
and let A be any point of the plane which is not on an invariant 
line. Let U(A)**A' and tt(A')**A". The points A t A', A" are then 
not collinear. The pencil of lines at 
A is protective with the pencil at 
A', and these two protective pencils 
generate a conic C a which passes 
through all the double points of II, 
and which is tangent at A' to the 
line A' A" (fig. 105). The conic C* is 
transformed by the collineation II 
into a conic Cf generated by the pro- 
jective pencils of lines at A' and A". Hia ' 

Cl also passes through A' and is tangent at this point to the line 
AA', The double points of n are also points of <7 X 2 . The point A 1 
is not a double point of II by hypothesis. It is evident, however, 
that every other point common to the two conies 2 and 0* is a 
double point. 

If <7 2 and Cl intersect again in three distinct points L, M, N, the 
latter form a triangle and the collineation is of Type /. If a and C? 
intersect in a point N, distinct from A', and are tangent to each other 
at a thfrd point Z^M, the oollineation has M, N for double points 




296 TWO-DIMENSIONAL PKOJECTIVITIES [CHAP, x 

and the line MN and the common tangent at M for double lines 
(fig. 106), it is then of Type //. If, finally, the two conies have 
contact of the second order at a point L = M=N, distinct from A f , 
the collineation has the single double line which is tangent to the 
comes at this point, and is of Type /// (fig. 107). 





FIG 107 

EXERCISES 

1. Give a disciission of the problem above -without making at the outset 
the hypothesis that the collineation is nonpeispective. 

2 Construct the double pans of a correlation in the plane, which is not 
a polanty. 

3. Given two polarities in a plane, construct their common pole and 
polar pahs 

4. On a line tangent to a conic at a point A is given an involution I, and 
fiom any pair of conjugates P, P' of I aie drawn the second tangents p, p' to 
the conic, their points of contact being Q, Q' 1 espectively. Show that the locus 
of the point pp' is a line, Z, passing through the conjugate, A', of A in the invo- 
lution I, and that the line QQ' passes through the pole of I with lespect to 
the conic. 

5. Construct the conic which is tangent at two points to a given conic and 
which passes through three given points Duali/e 

6. The lines joining pairs of homologous points of a nomnvolutoric pro- 
jectivity on a come A a aie tangent to a second conic # 3 which is tangent to 
A 3 at two points, or which hyperosculates A*. 

7. A pencil of conies of Type II is determined by three points A, JFS, C 
and a line c through C. What is the locus of the points of contact of the 
conies of the pencil with the tangents drawn from a given point P of c? 

8. Construct the conies which pass through a given point P and which, are 
tangent at two points to each of two given conic?. 

9. If /= 0, r=Q, 7i = are the equations of thice conies in a plane not 
belonging to the same pencil, the system of conies given by the equation 

X/+ w + vli = 0, 



102] THIRD AND FOURTH DEGEEE PROBLEMS 297 

X, fj-, v being vaiiable parameters, is culled a luiitlle of cornea Thiough every 
point of the plane passes a pencil of conies belonging i,o this bundle ; tlnough 
any two disl.mei. points passes in geneml one and only one conic of the bundle 
If the comes/, y, k have a point in common, this point is common to all the 
conies of the bundle. Give a noualgebiaic definition of a bundle of comes. 

10 The set of all comes in a plane passing through the vertices of a triangle 
form a bundle. If the equations of the sides of tlas tiiaugle are I 0, m = 0, 
n = 0, show that the bundle may be represented by the equation 

A.HM + pid + vim = 0. 

What are the degenerate comes o this bundle?* 

11. The set of all conies in a plane which have a given tuangle as a self- 
polai triangle forms a bundle. If the equations of the sides of this tuangle aie 
I 0, m = 0, n = 0, show that the bundle may be represented by the equation 



What are the degenerate conies of this bundle ? 

12. The comes of the bundle described in Ex. 11 which pass through a 
general point P of the plane pass tlnough the other three veitices of the 
quadrangle, of which one vertex is P and of which the given triangle is the 
diagonal triangle. What happens when P is on a side of the given triangle ? 
Dualize. 

13. The reflections whose centeis and axes aie the vertices and opposite 
sides of a triangle foim a commutative gioup. Any point of the plane not 
on a side of the triangle is transformed by the operations of this group into 
the other three vertices of a complete quadrangle of which the given triangle 
is the diagonal triangle If this tiiangle is taken as the reference triangle, 
what are the equations of transformation ? What conies are transformed into 
themselves by the group, and how is it associated with the quadrangle- 
quadnlatrral configuration ? 

14. The necessary and sufficient condition that two reflections be com- 
mutative is that the centei of each shall be on the axis of the other. 

15. The invariant figure of a colliueatioii may be regarded as composed of 
two lineal elements, the five types corresponding to various special relations 
between, the two lineal elements. 

16. A correlation which transforms a lineal element Aa into a lineal 
element Bb and also transforms Bb into Aa is a polarity 

17 How many collmeatious and correlations are in the group geneiated 
by the reflections whose centers and axes are the vertices and opposite sides 
of a triangle and a polarity with regard to which the triangle is self-polai ? 

* In connection with this and the two following exercises, of. Castelmiovo, 
Lezioni di Geometria Analitica e Projettiva, Vol. I, p. 395. 



CHAPTER XI* 



FAMILIES OF LINES 

103. The regulus. The following theorem, on which depends the 
existence of the figures to be studied in this chapter, is logically 

equivalent (in the presence of Assump- 
tions A and E) to Assumption P. It 
might have been used to replace that 
assumption 

THEOREM 1. If l v l z) l & are three 
mutually skew lines, and if m^ m a , m a , 
9?i 4 are four lines each of which meets 
each of the lines l v l v l at then any line l 
which meets three of the lines in v m z , 
w 8 , wi 4 also meets the fourth. 

Proof The four planes ljn v l^n^ 
ljn z , Z 1 ??i 4 of the pencil with axis l t are 
perspective through the pencil of points 
on l s with the four planes l a m v Z 2 m 2 , 
l z m s , Z 2 m 4 of the pencil with axis l z 
(fig. 108). For, by hypothesis, the lines 




FIG 108 



of intersection m v m a , m a , m^ of the 



pairs of homologous planes all meet l a . 
The set of four points in which the four planes of the pencil on l v 
meet Z 4 is therefore protective with the set of four points in which 
the four planes of the pencil on l z meet l v But 4 meets three of the 
pairs of homologous planes in points of their lines of intersection, 
since, by hypothesis, it meets three of the luxes m v m z , m^, w 4 . Hence 
in the projectivity on Z 4 there are three invariant points, and hence 
(Assumption P) every point is invariant Hence Z 4 meets the remain- 
ing line of the set m v m z , m s , m 4 

* All the developments of this chapter are on the basis of Assumptions A, B, P, HO. 
But see the exercise on page 261 

208 



io.Jj THE KEGULUS \ 29Sb 

DEFINITION. If l v l z> 1 A are throe lines no two of which are- in the 
same plane, the set of all lines which meet each of the three given lines" 
is called a regidus The line-s l v l z , l a are called directrices of this regulus. 

Ic is clear that no two lines of a regulus can intersect, for other- 
wise two of the directrices would lie in a plane. The next theorem 
follows at once from the definition. 

THEOREM 2. If l v a , l a arc three lines of a regulus of which 
m v m a , m a are directrices, m v m 2 , m s are lines of the regulus of which 
l v 1.,, l a are directrices 

It follows that any three lines no two of which lie in a plane are 
directrices of one and only one regulus and are lines of one and only 
one regulus. 

DEFINITION. Two reguli which are such that every line of one 
meets all the lines of the other are said to be conjugate. The lines of 
a regulus are called its generators or rulers ; the lines of a conjugate 
regulus are called the directrices of the given regulus. 

THEOREM 3. Every regulus has one ana 1 only one conjugate regulus. 

This follows immediately from the preceding. Also from the proof 
of Theorem 1 we have 

THEOREM 4 TJie correspondence THEOREM 4'. The correspond^ 
established ly the lines of & regu- ence established "by the lines of a 
lus "between the points of two lines regulus "between the planes on any 
of its conjugate regulus is projec- two lines of its conjugate regulus 
tive. is projective. 

THEOREM 5. The set of all lines THEOREM 5'. The set of all lines of 
joining pairs of homologous points intersection of pairs -of homologous 
of two protective pencils of points planes of two protective pencils of 
on skew lines is a regulus, planes on sJcew lines is a regulus. 

Proof. We may confine ourselves to the proof of the theorem on 
the left. By Theorem 6, Chap. Ill, the two pencils of points are 
perspective through a pencil of planes. Every line joining a pair of 
homologous points of these two pencils, therefore, meets the axis of 
the pencil of planes. Hence all these lines meet three (necessarily 
skew) lines, namely the axes of the two pencils of points and of the 
pencil of planes, and therefore satisfy the definition of a regulus. 
Moreover, every hue which meets these three lines joins a pair of 
homologous points of the two pencils of points. 



300 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP XI 

THEOREM 6. If [p] are the lines of a regulus and q is a directrix 
of the regulus, the pencil of points q [p] is protective with the pencil 
of planes q[p~\- 

Proof Let q' be any other directrix By Theorem 4 the pencil of 
points q[p] is perspective with the pencil of points q'[p]. But each 
of the points of this pencil lies on the corresponding plane gp. 
Hence the pencil of points q'[p] is also perspective with the pencil 
of planes q[p~\. 

EXERCISES 

1. Every point -which is on a line of a regulus is also on a line of its 
conjugate regulus 

2. A plane which, contains one line of a legulus contains also a lino of its 
conjugate regulus. 

3 Show that a regulus is uniquely denned by two of its lines and thiee 
of its points,* piovided no two of the latter aie coplanar with either of the 
given lines 

4 If four lines of a legulus cut any line of the conjugate regulus in points 
of a harmonic set, they aie cut by every such line in points of a harmonic 
set. Hence give a construction for the harmonic conjugate of a line of a 
regulus with respect to two other lines of the legulus 

5. Two distinct reguli can have in common at most two distinct lines. 
6 Show how to construct a regulus having in common with a given 
regulus one and but one luler 

104. The polar system of a regulus. A plane meets every line of 
a regulus in a point, unless it contains a line of the regulus, in which 
case it meets all the other hues in points that are collmear. Since 
the regulus may be thought of as the lines of intersection of pairs of 
homologous planes of two protective axial pencils (Theorem 5'), the 
section by a plane consists of the points of intersection of pairs of 
homologous lines of two projective flat pencils. Hence the section 
of a regulus by a plane is a point conic, and the conjugate regulus 
has the same section. By duality the projection of a regulus and its 
conjugate from any point is a cone of planes. 

The last remark implies that a line conic is the "picture " in a plane oi 
a regulus and its conjugate For such a picture is clearly a plane section of 
the pioj'ection of the object depicted from the eye of an observer. Fig. 108 
illustrates this fact. , 

* By a point of a regulus is meant any point on a line of the regulus. 



104] THE EEGULUS 30 

The section of a regulus by a plane containing a line of the regi 
lus is a degenerate conic of two lines. The plane section can neve 
degenerate into two coincident lines because the hues of a reguli 
and its conjugate are distinct from each other. In like manner, tt 
projection from a point on a line of the regulus is a degenerate cor 
of planes consisting of two pencils of planes whose axes are a rult 
and a directrix of the regulus. 

DEFINITION. The class of all points on the lines of a regulus 
called a surface of the second order or a quadric surface. The plane 
on the lines of the regulus are called the tangent planes of the su 
face or of the regulus. The point of intersection of the two lines ( 
the regulus and its conjugate in a tangent plane is called the poit 
of contact of the plane. The lines through the point of contact in 
tangent plane are called tangent lines, and the point of contact of tt 
plane is also the point of contact of any tangent line. 

The tangent lines at a point of a quadric surface include the line 
of the two conjugate roguli through this point and all other line 
through this point which meet the surface in no other point. An 
other line, of course, meets the surface in two or no points, since 
plane through the line meets the surface in a conic. The tanger 
lines are, by duality, also the lines through each of which passes onl 
one tangent plane to the surface. 

THEOREM 7 The tangent planes at the points of a, plane section o t 
a quadric surface pass through a point and constitute a cone of plane 
Dually, the points of contact of the cone of tangent planes through 
point are coplanar and form a point conic. 

Proof It will suffice to prove the latter of these two dual theorem 
Let the vertex P of the cone of tangent planes be not a point of to 
surface. Consider three tangent planes through P } and their points ( 
contact. The three lines from these points of contact to P are tai 
gent lines of the surface and hence there is only one tangent plar 
through each of them. Hence they are lines of the cone of lines ass< 
ciated with the cone of tangent planes. . Let TT be the plane throug 
their points of contact. The section by IT of the cone of planes throug 
P is therefore the conic determined by the three points of conta< 
and the two tangent lines in wljich two of the tangent planes me< 
IT. The plane TT, however, meets the regulus in a conic of which, tl 
three points of contact are points. The two lines of intersection wit 



302 FAMILIES OF LIKES [CHAP. XI 

TT of two of the tangent planes through P are tangents to this conic, 
because they cannot meet it in more than one point each The section 
of the surface and the section of the cone of planes then have three 
points and the tangents through two of them, in common. Hence these 
sections are identical, which proves the theorem when P is not on 
the surface. 

If P is on the surface, the cone of planes degenerates into two lines 
of the surface (or the pencils of planes on these lines), and the points 
of contact of these planes are all on the same two lines. Hence the 
theorem is true also in this case 

DEFINITION. If a point P and a plane TT are so related to a regulus 
that all the tangent planes to the regulus at points of its section 
by TT pass through P (and hence all the points of contact of tangent 
planes through P are on TT), then P is called the pole of TT and TT the 
polar of P with respect to the regulus. 

COROLLARY. A tangent plane to a regulus is the polar of its point 
of contact. 

THEOREM 8. The polar of a point P not on a regulus contains all 
points P' such that the hne PP' meets the surface in two points which 
are harmonic conjugates with respect to P, P.' 

Proof Consider a plane, a, through PP' and containing two lines 
a, 1} of the cone of tangent lines through P. This plane meets the 
surface in a conic <7 2 , to which the lines a, & are tangent. As the polar 
plane of P contains the points of contact of a and &, its section by a 
is the polar of P with respect to <7 2 . Hence the theorem follows 
as a consequence of Theorem 13, Chap. V. 

THEOREM 9. The polar of a point of a plane TT with respect to a 
regulus meets TT in the polar line of this point with regard to the conic 
which is the section of the regulus ty ir. 

Proof. By Theorem 8 the line in which the polar plane meets TT 
has the characteristic property of the polar line with respect to a conic 
(Theorem 13, Chap. V). This argument applies equally well if the 
conic is degenerate. In this case the theorem reduces to the following 

COROLLARY. The tangent lines of a regulus at a point on it are 
paired in an involution the double lines of which are the ruler and 
directrix through that point. Each line of a pair contains the polar 
joints of all the planes on the other tine. 



104] .THE EEGULUS 303 

THEOREM 10 The polars with regard to a regulus of the points of 
a line I are an axial pencil of planes protective with the pencil of 
points on L 

Proof. In case the given line is a line of the regulus this reduces 
to Theorem 6. In any other case consider two planes through I In 
each plane the polars of the points of I determine a pencil of lines 
projective with the range on I. Hence the polars must all meet the 
line joining the centers of these two pencils of lines, and, being per- 
spective with either of these pencils of lines, are protective with the 
range on L 

DEFINITION A line V is polar to a line I if the polar planes of the 
points of I meet on V. A line is conjugate to I if it meets V. A point 
P' is conjugate to a point P if it is on the polar of P. A line p is 
conjugate to P if it is on the polar of P. A plane TT' is conjugate to 
a plane TT if TT' is on the pole of TT. A line p is conjugate to TT if it 
is on the pole of TT. 

EXERCISES 

Polar points and planes witJi respect to a regulus are denoted by corresponding 
capital Roman and small Greek letters. Conjugate elements of the same kind are 
denoted by the same letters until primes 
1 If IT is on JR, then P is on p. 

2. If Hs polar to I, then lia polar to L 

3. If one element (point, line, or plane) is conjugate to a second element, 
then the second element is conjugate to the first, 

4. If two lines intersect, their two polar lines intersect. 

5. A ruler 01 a duectrix of a regulus is polar to itself. A tangent line is 
polar to its harmonic conjugate with regard to the ruler and directrix through 
its point of contact. Any other line is skew to its polar. 

6. The points of two polar lines are conjugate. 

7. The pairs of conjugate points (or planes) on any line form an involu- 
tion the double points (planes) of which (if existent) are on the regulus. 

8. The conjugate lines in a flat pencil of which neither the center nor the 
plane is on the regulus form an involution, 

9. The line of intersection of two tangent planes is polar to the line 
joining the two points of contact. 

10 A line of the regulus which meets one of two polar lines meets the other. 

11. Two one- or two-dimensional forma whose bases are not conjugate or 
polar are projective if conjugate elements correspond. 

12. A line I is conjugate to V if and only if some plane on I is polar to 
some point on V. < 



304 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP.XI 

13 Show that theie are two (proper or improper) lines r, s meeting two, 
given lines and conjugate to them both Show also that r is the polar of s. 

14 If a, b, c aie thiee generators of a legulus and a', &', c' three of the con- 
3Ugate regulus, then the three diagonal lines joining the points 

(be') and (6'c), 
(c'a) and (ca') 5 
(a&') and (a'&) 

meet in a point S which is the pole of a plane containing the lines of intersec- 
tion of the pairs of tangent planes at the same vertices. 

15 The six lines a, 6, c, a', &', c' of Ex. 14 determine the following tuos 
of simple hexagons 

(bc'db'ca"), (ba'ac'cb''), (bb'aa'cc'), 
(bc'aa'cb"), (bb'ac'ca"), (ba'ab'cc'). 

The points S determined by each trio of hexagons aie colhnear, and the two 
lines on which they lie are polar with legard to the quadnc suiface * 

16 The section of the figuie of Ex 14 by a plane leads to the Pascal 
and Biianchon theorems , and, in like manner, Ex 15 leads to the theoiem 
that the 60 Pascal lines corresponding to the 60 simple hexagons foimed 
fioni 6 points of a conic meet by threes in 20 points which constitute 10 
pairs of points conjugate with regaid to the conic (cf. Ex. 19, p 138). 

105. Protective conies. Consider two sections of a regulus by 
planes which are not tangent to it. These two comes are both per- 
spective with any axial pencil of a pair of axial pencils which generate 
the regulus (cf. 76, Chap. VIII). The correspondence established 
between the comes by letting correspond pairs of points which lie on 
the same ruler is therefore projective On the line of intersection, I, 
of the two planes, if it is not a tangent line, the two comes determine 
the same involution I of conjugate points Hence, if one of them inter- 
sects this line in two points, they have these two points in common. 
If one is tangent, they have one common point and one common 
tangent. ^The projectivity between the two conies fully determines a 
projectivity between their planes in which the line I is transformed 
into itself. The involution I belongs to the projectivity thus deter- 
mined on I The converse of these statements leads to a theorem 
which is exemplified in the familiar string models : 

THEOREM 11. The lines joining corresponding points of two pro- 
jettire comes in different planes form a regulus, provided the two 
comes determine tJie same involution, I, of conjugate points on the 

* Cf Sanaa, Lezioni di Geometria Projettiva (Naples, 1895), pp. 262-263. 



105] 



PROJECTIVE CONICS 



305 



line of intersection, I, of the two planes ; and provided the eollineation 
between the two planes determined by the correspondence of the conies 
transforms I into itself by a projectivtty to which I belongs (in par- 
ticular, if the conies meet in two points which are self-corresponding 
in the projcetimty). 

Proof, Let L be the pole with regard to one conic of the line of 
intersection, /, of the two planes (fig. 109). Let A and B be two 




points of this conic collinear with L and not on I. The conic is gen- 
erated by the two pencils A[P] and B[P'] where P and P' are con- 
jugates m the involution I on I (of. Ex. 1, p. 137). Let A and 
B be the points homologous to A and B on the second conic, and let 
A be the point in which the second conic is met by the plane con- 
taming A, A, and the tangent at A ; and let B be the point in which 
the second conic is met by the plane of J?, B, and the tangent at B. 

The line AB contains the pole of I with regard to the second conic 
because this line is protective with AB. Since the tangents to_the 
first conic at A and B meet on I, the complete quadrangle A ABB has 
we diagonal point, the intersection, of A A and JBJB, on I ; hence the 



306 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP. XI 

opposite side of the diagonal triangle passes through, the pole of L 
Hence it intersects AB in the pole of I But the intersection of AB 
with AB is on this diagonal line. Hence AB meets AB in the pole 
of L Hence the pencils A [P] and B [P 1 ] generate the second conic. 
Hence, denoting by a and & the lines AA and BB, the pencils of planes 
a[P] and &[P'] are protective and generate a regulus of which the 
two conies are sections 

The projectrvity between the planes of the two comes established 
by this regulus transforms the line I into itself by a projectivity to 
which the involution I belongs and makes the point A correspond 
to 2. The projectivity between two conies is fully determined by 
these conditions (cf. Theorem 12, Cor. 1, Chap. VIII). Hence the 
Imes of the regulus constructed above join homologous points in the 
given projectivity. Q E.D. 

It should be observed that if the two conies are tangent to I, the 
projectivity on I fully determines the projectivity between the two 
comes. For if a point P of I corresponds to a point Q of I, the unique 
tangent other than I through P to the first conic must correspond to 
the tangent to t>he second conic from Q. If the projectivity between 
the two comes is to generate a regulus, the pfojectivity on I must be 
parabolic with the double point at the point of contact of the comes 
with L For if another point D is a double point of the projectivity 
on I, the plane of the tangents other than I, through D to the two 
comes meets each conic in one and only one point, and, as these 
points are homologous, contains a straight line of the locus generated. 
As this plane contains only one point on either conic, it meets the 
locus in only one line, whereas a plane meeting a regulus in one 
line meets it also in another distinct line. 

Since the parabolic projectivity on I is fully determined by the 
double point and one pair of homologous points, the projectivity be- 
tween the two comes is fully determined by the correspondent of one 
point, not on Z, of the first conic 

To show that a projeetivity between the two comes which is para- 
bolic on I does generate a regulus, let A be any point of the first 
conic and A' its correspondent on the second (fig. 110). Let the 
plane of A' and the tangent at A meet the second conic in A". 
Denote the common point of the two conies by JB, and consider the 



105] 



PROJECTIVE CONICS 



307 



two comes as generated by the flat pencils at A and B and at A" 
and />'. The correspondence established between the two flat pencilf 
at B by letting correspond lines joining B to homologous points ot 
the two cornea is perspective because the line I corresponds to itself. 
Hence there is a pencil of 
planes whose axis, I, passes 
through B and whose planes 
contain homologous pairs 
of lines of the flat pencils 
at II The correspondence 
established in like manner 
between the flat pencil at A 
and the flat pencil atyl"may 
be regarded as the product 
of the projectivity between 
the two planes, which car- 
ries the pencil at A to the 
pencil at A', followed by 
the projectivity between the 
pencils at A' and A" generated by the second conic. Both of these 
projectivities determine parabolic projectivities on I with B as inva- 
riant point. Hence their product determines on I either a parabolic 
projectivity with B as invariant point or the identity. This product 
transforms the tangent at A into the line A 11 A'. As these lines meet 
I in the same point, the projectivity determined on I is the identity. 
Hence corresponding lines of the projective pencils at A and A" meet 
on I, and hence they determine a pencil of planes whose axis is a, = AA n 
The axial pencils on a and 1) are projective and hence generate a 
regulus the lines of which, by construction, pass through homologous 
points of the two conies. We are therefore able to supplement 
Theorem 11 by the following 




110 



OOROLLAEY 1. The lines joining corresponding points of two 
jective conies in different planes form a regulus, if the two conies 
have a common tangent and point of contact and the projectivity 
determined between the two planes "by the projectivity of the conies 
transforms their common tangent into itself and has the common 
point of the two conies as its only fixed point. 



308 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP XI 

The generation of a regulus by protective ranges of points on skew 
lines may be regarded as a degenerate case of this theorem and cor- 
ollary. A further degenerate case is stated in the first exercise 

The proof of Theoiern 11 given above is moie complicated than it would 
have been if, under Pioposition K 2 , we had made use of the points of mlei- 
section of the line Z with the two conies But since the discussion of linear 
families of lines in the following section employs only pioper elements and 
depends in part on this theoiem, it seems more satisfactory to piove this 
theorem as we have done It is of comse evident that any theoiem i elating 
entirely to proper elements of space which is proved with the aid of Pi oposi- 
tion K n can also be proved by an argument employing only pioper elements. 
The latter form of pi oof is often much moie difficult than the foimer, but it 
often yields more information as to the constructions related to the theoiem. 

These results may be applied to the problem of passing a quadric 
surface through a given set of points in space. Proposition K 2 will be 
used in this discussion so as to allow the possibility that the two con- 
jugate reguli may be improper though intersecting in proper points. 

COEOLLAEY 2. If three planes a, ft, 7 meet in three lines a y&y, 
6 = ya, c = aft and contain three comes A 2 , B z , G*, of which B* and s 
meet in two points P, P' of a, C 2 and A* i/ieet in two points Q, Q' of 1), 
and A z and B 2 meet in two points R, R' of c, then there is one and but 
one quadric surface * containing the points of the three conies. 

Proof. Let M be any point of s . The conic B* is projected from 
M by a cone which meets the plane a in a conic which intersects A 2 
in two points, proper or improper or coincident, other than R and R'. 
Hence there are two lines m, m 1 , proper or improper or coincident, 
through M which meet both A z and B z . The projectivity determined 
between A* and B z by either of these lines generates a regulus, or, 
in a special case, a cone of lines, the lines of which must pass through 
all points of C* because they pass through P, P', Q', Q, and M, all of 
which are points of C*. 

The conjugate of such a regulus also contains a line through M 
which meets both A* and B*, Hence the lines m and m 1 determine 
conjugate reguli if they are distinct. If coincident they evidently de- 
termine a cone. The three conies being proper, the quadric must con- 
tarn proper points even though the lines m, m' are improper. 

* In this corollary and in Theorem 12 the term guadnc surface must be taken, 
to include the points on a cone of lines as a special case. 



100] 



QUADEIC THROUGH NINE POINTS 



309 



If six points 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 are given, no four of which are co- 
plttnar,* there evidently exist two planes, <x and & each containing 
three of the points and having none on their line of intersection. 




PIG. ill 



Assign the notation so that 1, 2, 3 are in a. A quadric surface which 
contains the six points must meet the two planes m two conies A*, 
& which meet the line afi^c in a common point-pair or point of 
contact ; and every point-pair, proper or improper or coincident, of c 
determines such a pair of conies. 

Let us consider the problem of determining the polar plane co of 
an arbitrary point on the line c. The polar lines of with regard 
to a pair of conies A* and B* meet c in the same point and hence 
determine to. If no two of the points 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 are collinaar 
with 0, any line I in the plane a determines a unique conic A z with 
regard to which it is polar to 0, and which passes through 3, 2, 3. 
A* determines a unique conic J2 2 which passes through 4, 5, G and 
meets c in the same points as A*-, and with regard to this conic O 

* The construction oi a quadric surface through mne points by the method used 
in the text is given in Eohn and Papperitz, Darstellende Geometrie, Vol II 
(Leipzig, 1896), 676, 677 ' 



310 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP. XI 

has a polar lino in. Thus there is established a one-to-one corre- 
spondence II between the lines of a and the lines of ft. This corre- 
spondence is a collmeation For consider a pencil of lines [I] in a. 
The conies A* determined by it form a pencil. Hence the point-pairs 
in which they meet c are an involution Hence the conies J5 2 deter- 
mined by the point-pairs form a pencil, and hence the lines [m] form 
a pencil. Since every line I meets its corresponding line m on c, the 
correspondence II is not only a collmeation but is a perspectivity, 
of which let the center be C. Any two corresponding lines I and m 
are coplanar with C. Hence the polar planes of with regard to 
yuadrics through 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 are the planes on C. 

This was on the assumption that no two of the points 1, 2, 3, 4, 5, 6 
are colhnear with If two are colknear with 0, every polar plane 
of must pass through the harmonic conjugate of with regard to 
them. This harmonic conjugate may be taken as the point C. 

Now if nine points are given, no four being in the same plane, the 
notation may be assigned so that the planes a 123, /3 = 456, 7 = 789 
are such that none of their lines of intersection a = /3<y, & = 70;, c = aft 
contains one of the nine points Let be the point afty (or a point 
on the line aft if a, ft, and 7 are in the same pencil) By the argu- 
ment above the polars of with regard to all quadrics through the 
six points in a and 13 must meet in a point C. The polars of with 
regard to all quadrics through the six points in ft and 7 must simi- 
larly pass through a point A, and the polars with regard to all quad- 
rics through the six points in 7 and a must pass through a point B. 

'If A, B, and C are not collinear, the plane (o ABO must be the 
polar of with regard to any quadric through the nine points. The 
plane to meets a, ft, and 7 each in a line which must be polar to 
with regard to the section of any such quadric But this determines 
three conies A* in a, B* in ft, and C* in 7, which meet by pairs in 
three point-pairs on the lines a, &, c. Hence if a, ft, 7 are not in the 
same pencil, it follows, by Corollary 2, that there is a unique quadnc 
through the nine points. If a, ft, 7 have a line in common, the three 
conies A z , B z , C* meet this line in the same point-pair. Consider a 
plane a- through which meets the conies A*, B*, C* in three point- 
pairs. These point-pairs are harmonically conjugate to and the 
trace, s, on cr of the plane to. Hence they He on a conic Z> 2 , which, 
with A* and B 2 , determines a unique quadric. The section of this 



103,106] LINEAR DEPENDENCE 01? LINES 

quadrio by the plane 7 has in common with C a two point-pairs and 
the polar pair 0, s. Hence the quadric has 6' a as its section by y. 
.. In case A, /?, and C are oollinear, there is a pencil of planes o> which 
meet them. There is thus determined a family of quadrics which is 
called a pencil and is analogous to a pencil of comes. In case A, , 
and C coincide, there is a bundle of possible planes a> and a quadric is 
determined for each one. This family of quadrics is called a "bundle. 
Without inquiring at present under what conditions on the points 
1, 2, ' -, 9 these cases can arise, we may state the following theorem : 
THEOREM 1 2. Through nine points no four of which are coplanar 
there passes one quadric surface or a pencil of quadrics or a faindle 
of quadriGS. 

EXERCISES 

1. The lines joining homologous points of a projoctive conic and stiaight 
line foim a regulus, provided the line meets the conic and is not coplanar 
with it, and their point of intersection is self-uorresponding. 

2. State the duals of Theorems 11 and 12. 

3. Show that two (proper or impioper) conjugate leguli pass through two 
conies in different planes having two points (proper or improper or coincident) 
111 common and through a point not in the plane of either conic. Two such 
comes and a point not in either plane thus determine one quadric surface. 

4. Show how to consti uct a regulus passing through six given points 
and a given line 

106. Linear dependence of lines. DEFINITION. If two lines are co- 
planar, the lines of the flat pencil containing them both are said to 
be linearly dependent on them. If two lines are skew, the only lines 
linearly dependent on them are the two lines themselves. On three 
skew lines are hnearly dependent the lines of the regulus, of which 
they are rulers. Jll v l v -.*, l n are any number of lines and m v m a , , m K 
are lines such that m^s linearly dependent on two or three of l v Z a , , , 
and m & is linearly dependent on two or three of l v l s , -, l n , m v and 
so on, m k being linearly dependent on two or three of l v l^> , l n , m v 
m z> - - ,'m k _ 1 , then m k is said to be linearly dependent on l v l z> * , l n . 
A set of n lines no one of which is linearly dependent on the n 1 
others is said to be Imearly independent. 

As examples of these definitions there arise the following cases of 
linear dependence of lines on three linearly independent lines which 
may be regarded as degenerate cases of the regulus. (1) If lines a 



312 FAMILIES OF LUSE8 [CHAP XI 

and b intersect in a point P, and a line c skew to both of them meets 
their plane m a point Q, then in the first place all lines of the pencil 
ab are linearly dependent on a, 6, and c ; since the line QP is in this 
pencil, all lines of the pencil determined by QP and c are m the set 
As these pencils have in common only the line QP and do not con- 
tain three mutually skew lines, the set contains no other lines. 
Hence in this case the lines linearly dependent on a, b, c are the flat 
pencil ab and the flat pencil (c, QP). (2) If one of the hues, as a, meets 
both of the others, which, however, are skew to each other, the set df 
linearly dependent lines consists of the flat pencils ab and ac This 
is the same as case (1) (3) If every two intersect but not all in the 
same point, the three lines are coplanar and all lines of their plane 
are linearly dependent on them. (4) If all three intersect m the same 
point and are not coplanar, the bundle of lines through their common 
point is linearly dependent on them. The case where all three are 
concurrent and coplanar does not arise because three such lines are 
not independent. 

This enumeration of cases may be summarized as follows : 

THEOREM 13. DEFINITION. The set of all lines linearly dependent 
on three linearly independent lines is either a regulus, or a bundle of 
lines, or a plane of lines, or two Jlat pencils having different centers 
and planes but a common tine. The last three sets of lines are called 
degenerate reguli. 

DEFINITION. The set of all lines linearly dependent on four linearly 
independent lines is called a linear congruenee The set of all lines 
linearly dependent on five linearly independent lines is called a linear 
complex * 

107. The linear congruence. Of the four lines a, b, c, d upor 
which the lines of the congruence are linearly dependent, b, c, d 
determine, as we have just seen, either a regulus, or two flat pencils 
with different centers and planes but with one common line, or a 
bundle of lines, or a plane of lines. The lines &, e, d can of course be 
replaced by any three which determine the same regulus or degen- 
erate regulus as 5, c, d 

* The terms congruence and complex are general terms to denote two- and three- 
parameter families of lines respectively For example, all lines meeting a carve or 
all tangents to a surface form a complex, wlnle all lines meeting two curves or all 
common tangents of two surfaces are a corgruence. 



107] THE LINEAK CONGRUENCE 313 

So in case b, c, d determine a noudegenerate regulua of which a is 
not a directrix, the congruence can bo regarded as determined by four 
mutually skew lines. In case a is a directrix, the lines linearly de- 
pendent on a, b, c, d clearly include all tangent lines to the regains 
led, whose points of contact are on a. But as a is m a flat pencil 
with any tangent whose point of contact is 011 a, and one of the 
rulers, the family of lines dependent on a, b, c, d is the family de- 
pendent on b, c, d and a tangent line which does not meet &, c, d. Hence 
in either case the congruence is determined by four skew lines. 

If one of the four skew lines meets the regulus determined by the 
other three in two distinct points, P > Q, the two directrices p> q 
through these points meet all four lines. The line not in the regulus 
determines with the rulers through P and Q, two flat pencils of lines 
which join P to all the points of q, and Q to all the points of y 
From this it is evident that all lines meeting both p and q are linearly 
dependent on the given four. For if P v is any point on p, the line 
P^Q and the ruler through J^ determine a flat pencil joining P x to 
all the points of q; similarly, for any point of q. No other lines 
can be dependent on them, because if three lines of any regulus 
meet p and q, so do all the lines. 

If one of the four skew lines is tangent to the regulus determined 
by the other three in a point P, the family of dependent lines in- 
cludes the regulus and all lines of the flat pencil of tangents at P. 
Hence it includes the directrix p through P and hence all the tangent 
lines whose points of contact are on p By Theorem 6 this family 
of lines can be described as the set of all lines on homologous pairs 
in a certain projectivity II between the points and planes of p. Any 
two lines in this set, if they intersect, determine a flat pencil of lines 
in the set. Any regulus determined by three skew lines I, m, n of 
the set determines a projectivity between the points and planes on p, 
but this projectivity sets up the same correspondence as H for the 
three points and planes determined by I, m, and n. Hence by the 
fundamental theorem (Theorem. 17, Chap. IV) the projectivity deter- 
mined by the regulus Imn is the same as II, and all lines of the 
regulus are in the set. Hence* when one of four &kew lines is tangent 
to the regulus of the other three, the family of dependent lines consists 
of a regulus and all lines tangent to it at points of a directrix. The 
directrix is itself in the family. 



314 



FAMILIES OF LINES 



[CHAP. XI 



If no one of the four skew lines meets the regulus of the other 
three m a proper point, we have a case studied more fully below. 
1 In case I, c, d determine two fiat pencils with a common line, a 
may meet the center A of one of the pencils The linearly dependent 
lines, therefore, include the bundle whose center is A The plane of 
the other flat pencil passes through A and contains three noucon- 
current lines dependent on a, I, c, d. Hence the family of lines also 
includes all lines of this plane. The family of all lines through a 
point and all lines in a plane containing this point has evidently 
no further lines dependent on it This is a degenerate case of a con- 
gruence If a is in the plane of one of the flat pencils, we have, by 
duality, the case just considered. If a, meets the common line of the 
two flat pencils in a point distinct from the centers, the two flat 
pencils may be regarded as determined by their common line d' and 
by lines V and c 1 , one from each pencil, not meeting a. Hence the 
family of lines includes those dependent on the regulus ab'cf and its 
directrix d'. This case has already been seen to yield the family of all 
lines of the regulus aW and all lines tangent to it at points of d'. 




TIG 112 

If a does not meet the common line, it meets the planes of the 
two pencils in points C and D. Call the centers of the pencils A and 
S (fig. 112). The first pencil consists of the lines dependent on AD 
and AS, the second of those dependent on AS and SO. As CD is 
the line a, the family of lines is seen to consist of the lines which 
are linearly dependent on AS, SO, CD, DA Since any point of JBD 
is joined by lines of the family to A and (7, it is joined by lines of 



107] THE LINEAR CONGRUENCE 

the family to every point of A C Hence this case gives the family 
of all lines meeting both AC and HD. 

In case 1), c, d determine a bundle of lines, ct, being independent of 
them, does not pass through tho center of the bundle. Hence the 
family of dependent hues includes all hues of the plane of a and the 
center of the bundle as well as the bundle itself. 

Lastly, if o, c, d are coplauar, we have, by duality, the same case as 
if &, c, d were concurrent. We have thus proved 

THEOREM 14. A linear congruence is either (1) a set of hues 
linearly dependent on four linearly independent S?MW lines, such that 
no one of them meets the regidus containing the other three in a proper 
point, or (2) it is the set of all lines meeting two skew lines; or (3) 
it is the set of all rulers and tangent lines of a given regidus which 
meet a fixed directrix of the reyulus , or (4) it consists of a bundle 
of lines and a plane of lines, the center of the bundle leing on the 
plane. 

DEFINITION. A congruence of the first kind is called elliptic; of the 
second kind, hyperbolic; of the third kind, parabolic , of the fourth 
kind, degenerate. A line which has points in common with all lines 
of a congruence is called a directrix of the congruence. 

COEOLLAEY. A parabolic congruence consists of all lines on corre- 
sponding points and planes in a project ivity between the points and 
planes on a, line. The directrix is a hne of the congruence. 

To study the general nondegenerate case, let us denote four linearly 
independent and mutually skew lines on which the other lines of the 
congruence depend by a, I, c, d, and let 7r t and 7r a be two planes in- 
tersecting in a. Let the points of intersection with TT I and ir z of &, c, 
and d be JB V C v and D l and !?, <7 2 , and D B respectively By letting 
the complete quadrilateral a, J)^0 V 0^, I> 1 7? 1 correspond to the 
complete quadrilateral a, J3 S C Z , C Z 2) Z , J5 2 7? a , there is established a 
projective colhneatioii II between the planea 77^ and 7r a in which 
the lines 5, c, d join homologous points (fig. 113). 

Among the lines dependent on a, 5, c, d are the lines of the reguli 
ale, acd, ado, and all reguli containing a and two lines from any 
of these three reguli. But all such reguli meet t rr l and ir z in lines 
(e.g, -BjZ^, JB Z D Z ) because they have a in common with TJ^ and 
7r z . Furthermore, the lines of the fundamental reguli join points 



316 



FAMILIES OF LINES 



[CHAP XI 



which correspond in II (Theorem 5 of this chapter and Theorem 18, 
Chap. IV) Hence the reguh which contain a and lines shown by 
means of such reguh to be dependent on a, I, c, d are those gen- 
erated by the projectivities determined by II between lines of ^ 
and 7r 2 

d tit, 



\ 




FIG 113 

Now consider reguli containing triples of the lines already shown 
to be in the congruence, but not containing a Three such lines, I, 
m, n, ]om three noncolhnear points L v M v N^ of ir^ to the points 
L v M v N z of 7r 2 which correspond to them in the colhneation II The 
regulus containing Z, m, and n meets ir^ and tr z in two conies which 
are projective in such a way that L v M v N^ correspond to L z , Jf 2 , N v 
The pro]ectivity between the conies determines a projectivity between 
the planes, and as this projectivity has the same effect as II on the 
quadrilateral composed of the sides of the triangle L^H^ and the 
hne a, it is identical with U. Hence the lines of the regulus Imn 
join points of w t and Tr 2 which are homologous under II and are 
therefore among the lines already constructed. 

Among the lines linearly dependent on the family thus far con- 
structed are also such as appear in flat pencils containing two inter- 
secting lines of the family If one of the two lines is a, the other 
must meet a in a double point of the pro]ectivity determined on a by 
H. If neither of the two lines is a, they must meet w-j and 7r 2 , the 
first in points P v P a and the second in points Q v Q z> and these four 



io?J THE LINEAR CONGRUENCE 317 

points are clearly distinct from one another. But as the given lines of 
the congruence, PJ^ and Q^Q^ intersect, so must also the lines P t Q 1 and 
of 77*! and 7r a intersect, and the pro j activity determined between 
and P$ z by II is a perspectivity. Hence the common point of 
and P^Q Z is a point of a and is transformed into itself by H. 
Hence, if lines of the family intersect, II has at least one double point 
on a, which means, by 105,* that the line a meets the regulus led 
and the congruence has one or two directrices. Thus two lines of a 
nondcgenerate congruence intersect only in the parabolic and hyper- 
bolic cases , and from our previous study of these cases we know that 
the lines of a congruence through a point of intersection of two lines 
form a flat pencil 

We have thus shown that all the lines linearly dependent on 
a, &, c, d, with the exception of a flat pencil at each double point of 
the projectivity on a, are obtained by joining the points of TT X and 7r 2 
which are homologous under II. From this it is evident that any four 
linearly independent lines of the congruence could have been taken 
as the fundamental lines instead of a, b, c, d These two results are 
summarized as follows : 

THEOREM 15. All the lines of a linear congricence are linearly 
dependent on any linearly independent four of its lines No lines not 
in the congruence are linearly dependent on four such lines 

THEOREM 16 If two planes meet in a line of a linear congruence 
and neither contains a directrix, the other lines of the congruence meet 
the planes in homologous points of a projectivity. Conversely, if two 
planes are protective in such a way that their line of intersection cor- 
responds to itself, the lines joining homologous points are in the same 
linear congruence. 

* If there are two double points, JE7, F, on a, the conic BiCiDiJSF roust be trans- 
formed by n into the conic BaOaD*EF, and the lines joining corresponding points of 
these conies must form a regulus contained m the congruence. As JS and F are 
on lines of the regulus bed, there are two directrices p, q of this regulus which 
meet JS7 and F respectively, The lines p and q meet all four of the lines a, 6, c, d. 
Hence they meet all lines linearly dependent on a, 6, c, d, 

In the parabolic case the regulus bed must be met by a in the single invariant 
point JET of the parabolic projectivity on a, because the conic tangent to a at U and 
passing through BiCiDi must be transformed by II into the conic tangent to a at H 
and passing through JBgC7 2 Z> 2 ; and the lines joining homologous points of these conies 
must form a regulus contained in the congruence As IT, a point of a, is on a line 
of the regulus bed, there is one and only one directrix jp of this regulus which meets 
all four of a, 6, c, d and hence meets all lines of the congruence. 



318 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP xi 

The dual of Theorem 16 may be stated in the following form . 

THEOREM 17. From two points on the same line of a linear congru- 
ence the latter is projected by two projective bundles of planes. Con- 
versely, two bundles of planes projective in such a way that the hne 
joining their centers is self -corresponding, generate a linear congruence 

DEFINITION A regulus all of whose rulers are in a congruence is 
called a regulus of the congruence and is said to be in or to be con- 
tained in the congruence 

COROLLARY If three lines of a regulus are in a congruence, the 
regulus is in the congruence 

In the hyperbolic (or parabolic) case the regulus bed (in the notation 
already used) is met by a in two pomts (or one point), its points of 
intersection with the directrices (or directrix) In the elliptic case the 
regulus bed cannot be met by a in proper pomts, because if it were, 
the pro]ectivity II, between ir l and 7r 2 , would have these points as 
double points. Hence no line of the congruence meets a regulus of 
the congruence without being itself a generator Hence through each 
point of space, without exception, there is one and only one line of 
the congruence. The involution of conjugate points of the regulus 
bed on the line a is transformed into itself by II, and the same must 
be true of any other regulus of the congruence, if it does not con- 
tarn a. Since there is but one involution transformed into itself by a 
nomnvolutoric projectivity on a line (Theorem 20, Chap VIII), we 
have that the same involution of conjugate pomts is determined on 
any line of the congruence by all reguli of the congruence which do 
not contain the given line This is entirely analogous to the hyper- 
bolic case, and can be used to gam a representation in terms of proper 
elements of the improper directrices of an elliptic congruence. 

The three kinds of congruences may be characterized as follows : 

THEOREM 18. In a parabolic hnear congruence each line is tangent 
at a fixed one of its points to all reguli of the congruence of which it is 
not a ruler On each hne of a hyperbolic or elliptic congruence all reguli 
of the congruence not containing the given line determine the same 
involution of conjugate points Tlirough each point of space there is 
one and only one line of an elliptic congruence For hyperbolic and 
parabolic congruences this statement is true except for points on a 
directrix. 



107, 108] THE LINKAK COMPLEX 

EXERCISES 

"r" 

1. All lines of a congruence can be constuicted from four lines by means 
of reguli all of which have two given lines in common. 

2. Given two involutions (both having or both not having double points) 
on two skew lines Thiough each point of space there are two and only two 
lines which are axes of peispectivity projecting one involution into the othei, 
i e. such that t-vo planes through conjugate pans of the fiist involution pass 
through a conjugate pair of the second involution. These lines constitute 
two congruences. 

3. All lines of a congiucnce meeting a line not in the congiuence form 
a regulus. 

4. A linear congruence is self-polar with regaid to any regulus of the 
congruence. 

5. A degenerate linear congruence consists of all lines meeting two inter- 
secting lines. 

108. The linear complex. THEOREM 19. A linear complex con- 
sists of all lines linearly dependent on the edges of a simple skew 
pentagon.* 

Proof. By definition ( 106) the complex consists of all lines 
linearly dependent on five independent lines Let a be one of these 
which does not meet the other four, &', c', d', e'. The complex consists of 
all lines dependent on a and the congruence I'c'd'e'. If this con- 
gruence is degenerate, it consists of all lines dependent on three sides 
of a triangle cde and a line & not in the plane of the triangle 
(Theorems 14, 15). As & may be any line of a bundle, it may be 
chosen so as to meet a ; e may be chosen so as to meet &, and e may 
be so chosen as to meet a. Thus in this case the complex depends 
on five lines a, I, c, d, e not all coplanar, forming the edges of a simple 
pentagon. 

If tlie congruence is not degenerate, the four lines &", c", d", e" upon 
which it depends may (Theorem 15) be chosen so that no two of 
them intersect, but so that two and only two of them, 6" and e", 
meet a. Thus the complex consists of all lines linearly dependent 
on the two flat pencils ab" and ae n and the two lines G" and d". Let 
5 and e be the lines of these pencils (necessarily distinct from each 
other and from a) which meet e" and d" respectively. The complex 
then consists of all lines dependent on the flat pencils a&, le 1 ', ae, ed". 

* The edges of a simple skew pentagon are five lines m a given order, not all 
coplanar, each line intersecting its predecessor and the last meeting the first. 



320 FAMILIES OF LINES [OHAP.XI 

Finally, let c and d be two intersecting lines distinct from 6 and e, 
which are in the pencils be" and ed". The complex consists of all lines 
linearly dependent on the flat pencils aZ>, 6c, cd, de, ea. Not all the 
vertices of the pentagon abcde can be coplanar, because then all the 
lines would be in the same degenerate congruence. 

THEOREM 20. DEFINITION There are two classes of complexes such 
that all complexes of either class are protectively equivalent. A com- 
plex of one class consists of a line and all lines of space which meet 
it. These are called special complexes. A complex of the other class 
is called general. No four vertices of a pentagon which determines it 
are coplanar. 

Proof. Given any complex, by the last theorem there is at least 
one skew pentagon abcde which determines it If there is a ImeZ 
meeting the five edges of this pentagon, this line must meet all lines 
of the complex, because any line meeting three linearly independent 
lines of a regulus (degenerate or not) meets all lines of it. Moreover, 
if the line I meets a and & as well as c and d, it must either join 
their two points of intersection or be the line of intersection of their 
common planes If I meets e also, it follows in either case that four 
of the vertices of the pentagon are coplanar, two of them being on e. 
(That all five cannot be coplanar was explained at the end of the 
last proof) Conversely, if four of the five vertices of the skew- 
pentagon are coplanar, two and only two of its edges are not in this 
plane, and the line of intersection of the plane of the two edges with 
the plane of the other three meets all five edges. 

Hence, if and only if four of the five vertices are coplanar, there ex- 
ists a line meeting the Jive lines Since any two skew pentagons are pro- 
jectively equivalent, if no four vertices aie coplanar (Theorem 12, 
Chap. Ill), any two complexes determined by such pentagons are 
projectively equivalent. Two simple pentagons are also equivalent 
if four vertices, but not five, of each are coplanar, because any simple 
planar four-point can be transformed by a colhneation of space into 
any other, and then there exists a collmeation holding the plane 
of the second four-point pomtwise invariant and transforming any 
point not on the plane into any other point not on the plane. There- 
fore all complexes determined by pentagons of this kind are projec- 
tively equivalent But these are the only two kinds of skew pentagons 
Hence there are two and only two kinds of complexes 



108] 



THE LINEAR COMPLEX 



321 



In case four vertices of the pentagon are ooplauar, we have seen 
that there is a lino I meeting all its edges Since this line was 
determined as the intersection of the plane of two adjacent edges 
with the plane of the other three, it contains at least two vertices. 
It cannot contain three vertices because then all five would be 
coplanar. As one of the two planes meeting on I contains three 
independent lines, all lines of that plane are lines of the complex. 
The lino I itself is therefore in the complex as well as the two lines 
of the other plane. Hence all lines o both planes are in the complex. 
Hence all lines meeting I are in the complex But as any regulus 
three of whose lines meet I has all its lines meeting I, the complex 
satisfies the requirements stated in the theorem for a special complex. 




FIG. 114 



A more definite idea of the general complex may be formed as 
follows Lot piPiPnPiPs (fig- 114) be a simple pentagon upon whose 
edges all lines of the complex are linearly dependent. Let q be the 
line of the flat pencil p s p^ which meets p v and let Jffi be the point of 
intersection of q and p r Denote the vertices of the pentagon by 7 J ia , 
P 3 , P H , PW, P 6li the subscripts indicating the edges which meet in a 
given vertex. 

The four independent lines p^p^q determine a congruence of lines 
all of which are in the complex and whose directrices are a^RP^ 
and a 1 = P^P^- In like manner, qp^p^p^ determine a congruence whose 
directrices are l = RP^ and 6' = ^ 4 ^i The complex consists of all 
lines linearly dependent on the lines of these two congruences. The 



322 



FAMILIES OF LINES 



[CHAP. XI 



directrices of the two congruences intersect at ft and P^ respectively 
and determine two planes, ab = p and a'b' = ir, which meet on q. 

Through any point P of space not on p or TT there are two lines 
I, tn, the first meeting a and a', and the second meeting b and b' 
(fig. 115) All lines in the flat pencil Im are in the complex by defi- 
nition This flat pencil meets p and TT in two perspective ranges of 




PIG 115 



points and thus determines a projectivity between the flat pencil ab 
and the flat pencil a'b', in which a and a', b and b' correspond and q 
corresponds to itself. The projectivity thus determined between the 
pencils ab and a'b' is the same for all points P, because a, b, q always 
correspond to a', b', q 1 . Hence the complex contains all lines in the 
flat pencils of lines which meet homologous lines in the projectivity 
determined by 



Denote this set of lines ly S. We have seen that it has the property 
that all its lines through a point not on p or TT are coplanar. If a 
point P is on p but not on q, the line PR has a corresponding line p' 
in the pencil a'b' and hence S contains all lines joining P to points 
of p'. Similarly, for points on TT but not on q. By duality every plane 
not on q contains a flat pencil of lines of S. 

Each of the flat pencils not on q has one line meeting q. Hence 
each plane of space not on q contains one and only one line of S 
meeting q. Applying this to the planes through P s not contain- 
ing q } we have that any line through P sl and not on p is not in the 



108] THE LINEAK COMPLEX 333 

set S. Lei I be any such line. All lines of S in each plane through 
I form a fiat pencil P, and the centers of all these pencils lie on a line 
I', because all lines through two points of I form two flat pencils each 
of which contains a line fiom each pencil P Hence the lines of S 
meeting I form a congruence whose other directrix I 1 evidently lies on 
p. The point of intersection of I 1 with q is the center of a flat pencil 
of lines of S all meeting I Hence all lines of the plane Iq form, a flat 
pencil Since I is any line on P 34 and nob on TT, this establishes that 
each plane and, by duality, each point on q, as well as not on q, con- 
tains a flat pencil of hues of S. 

We can now prove that the complex contains no lines not in S 
To do so we have to show that all lines linearly dependent on lines 
of S are in S If two lines of S intersect, the Hat pencil they deter- 
mine is by definition in S. If three lines m v m zi m^ of S are skew to 
one another, not more than two of the directrices of the regulus con- 
taining them are in S. For if three directrices were in S, all the tan- 
gent lines at points of these three lines would be in S, and hence any 
plane would contain three nonconcurreut lines of S. Let I be a 
directrix of the regulus >n\m^n v which is not in S. By the 'argu- 
ment made in the last paragraph all lines of S meeting I form a con- 
gruence. But tins congruence contains all linos of the regulus mjn$n, v 
and hence all lines of this regulus are in S. Hence the set of lines S 
is identical with the complex. 

THEOREM 21 (SYLVESTEK'S THEOREM *). If two pro/active flat pencils 
with different centers and planes have a line q in common wMeJi is 
self -corresponding, all lines meeting homologous pairs of lines in these 
two pencils are in the same linear complex This complex consists of 
these lines together with a parabolic congruence whose directrix is #. 

Proof. This has all been proved in the paragraphs above, with the 
exception of the statement that q and the lines meeting g form a 
linear congruence Take three skew lines of the complex meeting q , 
they determine with j a congruence C all of whose Hues are in the 
complex. There cannot be any other lines oC the complex meeting q, 
because there would be dependent on such lines and on the congru- 
ence C all lines meeting q, and hence all lines meeting q would be in 
the given complex, contrary to what has been proved above. 

# Of. Comptes Bendus, Vol. UI (1861), p, 741. 



324 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP. XI 

Another theorem proved in the discussion above is : 

THEOREM 22. DEFINITION OF NULL SYSTEM. All the lines of a 
linear complex which pass through a point P lie in a plane TT, and all 
the lines which lie in a plane IT pass through a point P. In case of 
a special complex, exception must be made of the points and planes on 
the directrix. The point P is called the null point of the plane TT and 
TT is called the null plane of P with regard to the complex. The cor- 
respondence between the points and planes of space thus established is 
called a null system or null polarity. 

Another direct consequence, remembering that there are only two 
kinds of complexes, is the following . 

THEOREM 23. Any five linearly independent lines are in one and 
only one complex. If the edges of a simple pentagon are in a given 
complex, the pentagon is skew and its edges linearly independent. If 
the complex is general, no four vertices of a simple pentagon of its 
lines are coplanar. 

THEOREM 24. Any set of lines, K, in space such that the lines of the 
set on each point of space constitute a flat pencil is a linear complex. 

Proof (a) If two lines of the set K intersect, the set contams all 
lines linearly dependent on them, by definition 

(&) Consider any hue a not in the given set K Two points A, B on 
a have flat pencils of lines of K on different planes ; for if the planes 
coincided, every line of the plane would, by (a), be a line of K Hence 
the lines of K through A and JB all meet a line a' skew to a. From 
this it follows that all the lines of the congruence whose directrices 
are a, a' are in K. Similarly, if b is any other line not in K but meet- 
ing a, all lines of K which meet b also meet another line b'. More- 
over, since any line meeting a, b, and b' is in K and hence also meets 
a', the four lines a, a', b, b' he on a degenerate regulus consisting of the 
flat pencils ab and a'b' (Theorem 13). Let q (fig. 115) be the common 
line of the pencils ab and a'b'. Through any point of space not on one 
of the planes ab and a'b' there are three coplanar lines of K which 
meet q and the pairs aa' and bb'. Hence K consists of lines meeting 
homologous lines in the pro;jectivity 

gab - qa'b', 
and therefore is a complex by Theorem 21. 



108] THE LINEAR COMPLEX 325 

COROLLARY. Any (1, 1) correspondence between the points and the 
planes of space such that each point lies on its corresponding plane 
is a null system. 

THEOREM 25 Two hnear complexes have in common a linear 

congruence. 

Proof. At any point of space the two flat pencils belonging to the 
two complexes have a line 111 common. Obviously, then, there are 
three linearly independent lines l v l J, common to the complexes. 
All lines in the regulus 1,1,1, are, by definition, in each complex. Bufc 
as there are points or planes of space not 011 the regulus, there is a 
line Z 4 common to the two complexes and not belonging to this regulus. 
All lines linearly dependent on l lt Z 2 , Z 8 , J, are, by definition, common 
to the complexes and form a congruence. No further line could be 
common or, by Theorem 23, the two complexes would be identical. 

COROLLARY 1. The lines of a complex meeting a line I not in the 
complex form a hyperbolic congruence 

Proof. The line is the directrix of a special complex which, by the 
theorem, has a congruence in common with the given complex. The 
common congruence cannot be parabolic because the lines of the first 
complex in a plane on I form a flat pencil whose center is not on l f 
since I Is not in the complex. 

COROLLARY 2. The lines of a complex meeting a line I of the com- 
plex form, a parabolic congruence. 

Proof. The centers of all pencils of lines in this congruence must 
be on I because I is itself a line of each pencil. 

DEFINITION. A line I is a polar to a line V with regard to a 
complex or null system, if and only if I and V are directrices of a 
congruence of lines of the complex. 

COROLLARY 3. If I is polar to V, V is polar to I A line is polar 
to itself, if and only if it is a line of the complex. 

THEOREM 26. A null system is a proactive correspondence between 
the points and planes of space. 

Proof. The points on a line I correspond to the planes on a line V 
by Corollaries 1 and 2 of the last theorem. If I and V are distinct, 
the correspondence between the points of I and planes of V is a per- 
spectivity. If l = V, the correspondence is projective by the corollary 
of Theorem 14, 



32G FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP. XI 

EXERCISES 

1 . If a point P is on a plane p , the null plane TT of P is on the null point Roip 

2 Two pan s of lines polai with i egard to the same null system ai e always in 
the same legulus (degenerate, if a line of one pan meets a line of the other pan) 

3 If a line I meets a line m, the polai of Z meets the ^polar of in 

4. Pairs of lines of the regulus in Ex. 2 which aie polar with i egard to 
the complex aie met hy any dnectrix of the legulus in pans of points of an 
involution. Thus the complex determines an involution among the lines of 
the regulus. 

5. Conversely (Theorem of Chasles), the lines meeting conjugate pans of 
lines in an involution on a legulus aie in the same complex. Show that 
Theoiem 21 is a special case of this. 

6 Find the lines common to a linear complex and a regulus not in the 
complex 

7. Three skew lines I, I, m determine one and only one complex contain- 
ing k and having I and m as polai s of each othei 

8. If the numbei of points on a line is n + 1, how many reguli, how many 
congruences, how many complexes are there in space? How many lines aie 
there in each kind of regulus, congiuence, complex ? 

9 Given any general complex and any tetiahedion whose faces ai'e not 
null planes to its vertices The null planes of the veitices constitute a second 
tetrahedron whose veitices be on the planes of the fiist tetiahedron The 
two tetrahedia are mutually inscribed and ciicumscribed each to the other* 
(cf . Ex. 6, p. 103). 

10. A null system is fully determined by associating with the three vertices 
of a tnangle three planes through these veitices and having their one common 
point in the plane of the tiiangle but not on one of its sides 

11 A tetrahedron is self -polar with regaid to a null system if two opposite 
edges are polar. 

12 Every line of the complex determined by a pair of Mobius tetrahedra 
meets their faces and projects their vertices in protective throws of points and 
planes 

13 If a tetrahedron T is insciibed and ciicumscribed to 7\ and also to !T 2 , 
the lines joining corresponding vertices of T^ and T s and the lines of intersec- 
tion of their corresponding planes are all in the same complex 

14 A null system is determined by the condition that two pairs of lines 
of a regulus shall be polar 

15 A linear complex is self-polar with regard to a regulus all of whose 
lines are in the complex. 

16 The lines from which two projective pencils of points on skew lines 
are projected by involutions of planes are all in the same complex Dualize 

* This configuration was discovered by Mobius, Journal fur Mathematik, Vol. Ill 
(1828), p 273 Two tetrahedra in this relation are known as Mobius tetrahedra. 



109] LINE COOEDINATES 327 

109. The Pliicker line coordinates. Two points whose coordinates are 

(*!> Ej - 7 ' 3 > ^''t) 

(2/1, y*> 2/ 3 > &) 

determine a line L The coordinates of the two points determine six 
numbers 



#34 = 



2/ a 



2/ 3 



2/8 



2/4 2/2 



2/ 



2/a 2/' 



which are known as the Pluclwr coordinates of the line. Since the 
coordinates of the two points are homogeneous, the ratios only of the 
numbers p l} are determined Any other two points of the line deter- 
mine the same set of line coordinates, since the ratios of the ^> f/ 's are 
evidently unchanged if (x v j 2 , x &t aij is replaced by (jCj+X^, 
The six numbers satisfy the equation* 

== 0. 



This is evident on expanding in terms of two-rowed minors the 
identity 



2/ 3 



2/4 = 



2/4 







Conversely, if any six numbers, p ij} are given, which satisfy Equa- 
tion (1), then two points P = (os v x z , x a> 0), Q~(y v 0, y n , y 4 ) can be 
determined such that the numbers p (f are the coordinates of the line 
PQ. To do this it is simply necessary to solve the equations 



which are easily seen to be consistent if and only if 



Hence we have 

THEOREM 27. Jl^ery line of space determines and is determined 
"by the ratios of six numbers p w p 18 , j9 :4 , p Mi jp 48 , p ag sitbjeot to the 



* Notice that in Equation (1) the number of inversions in the four subscripts of 
any term is always even 



328 
cond^t^on 

\2/i> 2/2' y B> 



FAMILIES OF LINES 



[CHAP XI 



are 



= 0, such that if (x lt x z , x a , # 4 ) and 
on ^e hne, 



2/ 2 



2/ 



as. % 



-! ^4 

O* 'T* 

2 S 

2/2 2/3 



COEOLLAEY ^bwr independent coordinates determine a line. 
In precisely similar manner two planes (w ls u z> u s> ^6 4 ) and (Vj^, v z , v s , -yj 
determine six numbers such that 



234 = 



242 = 



u, 



The quantities q v satisfy a theorem dual to the one just proved for 
the p v 's 

THEOREM 28. TJie p and q coordinates of a line are connected 1y 
the equations p 12 : p l3 : p u p a4 : p, z ' p 2a = ^ . q iz ' q za ' q lz : q ls : q^. 

Proof Let the p coordinates be determined by the two points 
(x v x zt x a , x^, (y v y z , y s> y 4 ), and the q coordinates by the two planes 
(u v u 2 , u a> w 4 ), (v v v z> v 3 , v t ). These coordinates satisfy the four equations 

U S X S + U^ = 0, 
V 3 X S + Vft = 0, 



4 = 0. 

Multiplying the first equation by v 1 and the second by u^ and adding 
we obtain . 



In like manner, from the third and fourth equations we obtain. 

Ziaft + 2is/ 8 + Su^= 0. 
Combining the last two equations similarly, we obtain 



or, 13 42. 

ft* ^28 

By similar combinations of the first four equations we find 

JPl ' JPlS : Pl4 : ^84 : P42 : ^28= ^34 = ^42 = ^23 ! 2l2 : ?! : 14- 



i(M) f iio] 



LLIS'E COORDINATES 



329 



EXERCISE 

Given the tetiahedron of reference, the point (1, 1, 1, 1), and a line ', 
determine six sots of oui points each, whose cioss latioh aie the cooidmates 
of/ 

110. Linear families of lines. THEOREM 29. The necessary and 
sufficient condition that two lines p and p' intersect, and hence are 
coplanar, is 

PI K +p u p +PUPL +p*ipL+p a pU +v<>pL = o, 

where p n are the coordinates of p ant ^ P'J f P'- 

Proof. If the first line contains two points x and y, and the second 
two points %' and y', the lines will intersect if and only if these foui 
points are coplanar ; that is to say, if and only if 



0== 



1 l ^ 



y[ 



THEOREM 30. 'Aflat pencil of linen consists of the lines whose coordi- 
nates are \p ti + pplj, if P and 2 J ' arft t' wo ^ nes f ^ >(i pnwil 

Proof. The lines p and p' intersect in a point A and are perspec- 
tive with a range of points \( 1 + pD. Hence their coordinates may be 
written 

ofp 

' ' 



i, etc. 



which may be expanded in the form 



d, d. 



THEOREM 31. The lines whose coordinates satisfy one linear 
equation 

(1) a w jp-h !#+ 14 2 7 n+ ^P 4 + JP4a+ ' 28 ^ 2S = 



form a> linear complex. F/iose whose coordinates satisfy two independ- 
ent linear equations form a linear congruence, and those satisfying 
three independent linear equations form a regulus. Four independent 
linear equations are satisfied T>y two (distinct or coincident] lines, 
which may %e improper, 



330 



FAMILIES OF LIKES 



[CHAP. XI 



Proof If (& v & 2 , & 3 , & 4 ) is any point of space, the points fo, as v # 3 , # 4 ) 
which lie on lines through \, & 2 , 6,, 6 4 satisfying (1) must satisfy 



rt !2 



M 



3 

i ""'a 



-M, 



'\ "4 

Cj # 4 



= 0, 



or 



(2) 



! A) l 



! A 



ft s A) s, + (- a i A 



which is the equation of a plane. Hence the family of lines repre- 
sented by (1) has a flat pencil of lines at every point of space, and so, 
by Theorem 24, is a linear complex. 

Since two complexes have a congruence of common lines, two linear 
equations determine a congruence Since a congruence and a complex 
have a regulus in common, three linear equations determine a regulus. 

If the four equations 

+ <^ 2S = 0, 
42 + <jPss= 0, 

4 2 + <K= 0, 



are independent, one of the four-rowed determinants of their coeffi- 
cients is different from zero, and the equations have solutions of the 



If one of these solutions is to represent the coordinates of a line, it 
must satisfy the condition 

ia** 



which gives a quadratic equation to determine X//*. Hence, by Propo- 
sition K 2 , there are two (proper, improper, or coincident) lines whose 
coordinates satisfy four linear equations. 

COROLLARY 1. The lines of a regulus are of the form 



u-Jtere p f , p", p'" are lines of the regulus. In like manner, the lines of 
a congruence are of the form, 



* Of Bocher, Introduction to Higher Algebra, Chap IV. 



i]0,m] LINE COORDINATES 331 

and of a complex of the form 



All of these formulas must be, taken in connection with 



COROLLARY 2. As a transformation from points to planes the null 
system determined Inj the complex whose equation is 



is 

w x = 



I (\ 

The first of these corollaries simply states the form of the solu- 
tions of systems of homogeneous linear equations in six variables. 
The second corollary is obtained by inspection of Equation (2) the 
coefficients of which are the coordinates of the null plane of the 
point (& 11( 5 2 , 6 3 , & 4 ) 

Coiollary 1 shows that the geometric definition of linear dependence of 
lines given in this chapter corresponds to the conventional analytic concep- 
tion of linear dependence. 

111. Interpretation of line coordinates as point coordinates in S 6 . 

It may be shown without difficulty that the method of introducing 
homogeneous coordinates iii Chap. VII is extensible to space of any 
number of dimensions (cf. Chap. I, 12). Therefore the set of all sets 
of six numbers 



can be regarded as homogeneous point coordinates in a space of five 
dimensions, S 6 . Since the coordinates of a line in S 8 satisfy the 
quadratic condition 

they may be ^garded as forming the points of a quadratic locus or 
spread,* L 4 a , in S 5 . The lines of a linear complex correspond to the 
points of intersection with this spread of an S 4 that is determined by 
one linear equation The lines of a congruence correspond, therefore, 
to the intersection with \- of an S a , the lines of a regulus to the 

* This is a generalization of a conic section. 



$2 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP XI 

intersection with L 4 2 of an S 2 , and any pair of lines to the mtersec- 
Aon with L 2 of an S r 

Any point (p' w p' ls , p' u , p' M , p' 4Z , p' 2S ) of S 5 has as its polar* S 4 , with 
regard to L 2 , 

( 2 ) PLPu + PLPu + PaPu + PuPK + PuPv + PuP*** > 



which is the equation of a linear complex in the original S 3 Hence 
any point in S 5 can l>e thought of as representing the complex of hncs 
represented ty the points of S 5 m which its polar S 4 meets L 4 2 

Since a Ime is represented by a point on L 4 2 , a special complex is 
represented by a point on L 2 , and all the lines of the special complex 
by the points in which a tangent S 4 meets L 4 a . 

The points of a line, a + X5, in S 5 represent a set of complexes 
whose equations are 

(3) (**+** ^P*+(**+*)p + = 0, 



and all these complexes have ni common the congruence common to 
the complexes a and &. Their congruence, of course, consists of the 
lines of the onginal S 3 represented by the points in which L 4 2 is met 
by the polar S 3 of the line a + X& 

A system of complexes, a + X6, is called a pencil of complexes, and 
then 1 common congruence is called its "base or lasal congruence. It 
evidently has the property that the null planes of any point with 
regard to the complexes of the pencil form an axial pencil whose 
axis is a line of the basal congruence Dually, the null points of 
any plane with regard to the complexes of the pencil form a range 
of points on a line of the basal congruence 

The cross ratio of four complexes of a pencil may be defined as 
the cross ratio of their representative points in S 6 From the form of 
Equation (3) this is evidently the cross ratio of the four null planes J 

of any point with regard to the four complexes. 

A pencil of complexes evidently contains the special complexes ' 

whose directrices are the directrices of the basal congruence Hence f M 

* Equation (2) may be taken as the definition of a polar 84 of a point with 

regard to l_ 4 a Two points are conjugate with regard to L 4 2 if the polar S 4 of one I 

contains the other The polar S 4 's of the points of an S, (i = 1, 2, 8, 4) all have an J. 

S 4 _, m common which is called the polar S 4 _t of the S, These and other obvious * 
generalizations of the polar theory of a conic or a regulus we take for granted 

without further proof. ' 



111] LINE COORDINATES 333 

there are two improper, two proper, one, or a flat pencil of lines which. 
are the directrices of special complexes of the pencil. These cases 
arise as the representative hue a + \l meets L 4 a m two improper 
points, two proper points, or one point, or lies wholly on Lf Two 
points in which a representative line meets L 4 2 are the double points 
of an involution the pairs of which are conjugate with regard to L 2 . 

Two complexes y, p' whose representative points are conjugate 
with regard to Lf are said to be conjugate or in involution. They 
evidently satisfy Equation (2) and have the property that the null 
points of any plane with regard to them are harmonically conjugate 
with regard to the directrices of their common congruence. Any 
complex a is in involution with all the special complexes whose 
directrices are lines of a. 

Let a x be an arbitrary complex and 3 any complex conjugate to 
(in involution with) it. Then any representative point in the polar S 8 
with regard to L 4 a of the representative line a^ represents a complex 
conjugate to a : and a . Let ct^ be any such complex. The represent- 
ative points of a v 2 , form a self-conjugate triangle of L 4 3 Any 
point of the representative plane polar to the plane a^a^ with 
regard to L 4 a is conjugate to a^a^. Let such a point be a 4 . In like 
manner, a 6 and a can be determined, forming a self-polar 6-point of 
L 4 2 , the generalization of a self-polar triangle of a conic section The 
six points are the representatives of six complexes, each pair of which 
is in involution. 

It can be proved that by a proper choice of the six points of refer- 
ence in the representative S 6 , the equation of L* may be taken as any 
quadratic relation among six variables, llenoe the lines of a three- 
space may be represented analytically by six homogeneous coordinates 
subject to any quadratic relation. In particular they may be repre- 
sented by (us v a? a) - , sn & ), where 

0.* 



In this case, the six-point of reference being self-polar with regard 
to L 4 2 , its vertices represent complexes which are two by fcvo in 
involution. 

* These are known as Klein's coordinates. Most of the ideas in the present sec- 
tion are to he found in F. filein, Zur Theorie der Linienooraplexe des ersteu und 
sweiten Grades, Mathematisohe Annalen, Vol. H (1870), p. 198. 



-334 FAMILIES OF LINES [CHAP. XI 

EXERCISES 

1 If a pencil of complexes contains two special complexes, the basal con- 
giuence of the pencil is hypcibolic 01 elliptic, according as the special com- 
plexes aie piopei or impropei 

2. If a pencil of linear complexes contains only a single special complex, 
the basal congruence is parabolic. 

3 If all the complexes of a pencil of linear complexes aie special, the 
basal congruence is degenerate. 

4 Define a pencil of complexes as the system of all complexes having a 
common congiuence of lines and derive its piopeities synthetically 

5. The polais of a line with legard to the complexes of a pencil form 
a legulus. 

6. The null points of two planes with regaid to the complexes of a pencil 
generate two piojective pencils of points 

7 If C= 0, C' 0, C"= aie the equations of three linear complexes 
which do not have a congruence in common, the equation C + \C' + p.C" = 
is said to lepresent a bundle of complexes The lines common to the thiee 
fundamental complexes C, C", C" of the bundle form a legulus, the con- 
jugate legulus of which consists of all the dnectuces of the special com- 
plexes of the bundle. 

8 Two lineal complexes ^a t) p t j = and "S,b tj p t j = aie m involution if and 
only if we ha\e 



9 Using Klein's cooidmates, any two complexes are given by 2a,a: t = 
and 25&,z t = These two aie in involution if 2a,6 t = 

10 The six fundamental complexes of a system of Klein's coordinates 
inteisect in pans in fifteen linear congiuences all of whose directrices are dis; 
tmct. The directrices of one of these congruences are lines- of the remaining 
four fundamental complexes, and meet, theiefore, the twelve directrices of 
the six congruences determined by these four complexes. 



52/1 



INDEX 



Tllo nuniboia rofor U> pages 



Abolian group, 07 

Abscissa, 170 

Abstract science, 2 

Addit . J * .' J - H2 291 * 1 
on, U I I! . I l i - ' o: 107, 
EXH 8, 4 

Adjacent sides or vortices of simple 
n-hno, 87 , 

Algebraic curve, 250 

Algebraic problem, 288 

Algebraic surface, 25',) 

Alignment, assumptions of, 1(5 ; consist- 

' ency oi assumptions of, 17 j theorems 
of, for the piano, 17-20 , theorems of, 
for 3-space, 20-24 ; theorems of, for 
4-space, 26, Ex. 4, theorems of, for 
n-space, 20-33 

Ainodoo, P., 120, 294 

Anharmomc ratio, 160 

Apollomus, 280 

Associative law, for correspondences, 
66, f oi'. addition of points, 143; for 
multiplication of points, 140 

Assumption, II , 45; IT , role of, 81, 
261, of 4 n( ,*i.,,*v (>5; of projec- 
tivity, i- ' . i \ ' - of, 105, 1Q6, 
Exs. 10-12 , 208 

Assumptions, are necessary, 2; exam- 
ples of, for a mathematical science, 
2; consistency of, 8; Independence 
of f 6,; categdriealness of, ; of align- 
ment, 16; of alignment, conHistenoy 
1 of, 17; of extension, 18, 24; of clo- 
sure, 24 , for an n-spaeo, 88 

Axial pencil, 55 

Axial pcrspectivity, 67 

Axis, of porspeotivity, 86; of pencil, 
J6 ; of perspective collinoation, 72 ; of 
homology, 104; of coordinated, 160, 
191'; of projectivity on conic, 218 

Base, of plane of points or lines, 55 ; of 
pencil * complexes, 882 , 

Bilinear equation, binary, represents 
project! vity on a line, 150; ternary, 
represents correlation in a plane, 267 

Binary form, 261, 252, 254 

BOcher, M., 166, 272, 289, 880 

Braikenridge, 119 

Brianchon point, 111 

BriancJaon's theorem, 111 



Bundle, of planes or linos, 27, 66; of 
COUJCH, 207, BXH. 0-12, of quadrics, 
811 ; oi complexes, 884, Ex 7 

Bnniwdo, W., 150 
, W. II., 202 



Canonical forms, of collineations in 
plane, 274-27U, of correlations in a 
plane, 281 ; of pencils of comes, 287- 
208 

Castelnuovo, G., 130, 140, 287, 297 

Categorical set of asHumptions, 6 

Coyloy, A., 52, HO 

Center, of pcrspeciivity, 36, of flat pen- 
cil, 65, of bundle 1 , 55, of perspective 
colliiioation in plant', 72 , oi perspec- 
tive collinoation m space, 76; of 
1i - 1 1 H.-. 1 n l rC f-drrtinates, 170; 
(, i , . i . i . ,-c, 218 

( i r -si -i- r -7 

( . , i i , .- i i- -of parabolic 
projeotivity, 207 

Characteristic equation of matrix, 165 

Characteristic throw and crow* ratio, of 
one-dimensional projoctivity, 205, 211, 
Exs, 2, 8, 4; 212, Exs. 6, 7 ; of involu- 
tion, 20(1; of parabolic projectivity, 
206 

Chaslos, 125 

Class, notion of, 2; elements of, 2; re- 
lation of belonging to a, 2 ; subclass of 
a, 2; undefined, 16; notation for, 57 

Clebsoh, A., 280 

Cogretliont n-lino, 84, Ex. 18 

Cotfredieat triangle, 84, Exs. 7, 10 

Gollineation, denned, 71 ; pewsppctivo, in 
plane, 72 ; perspective, in space, 75 ; 
transfonfting a quadrangle into a 
quadrangle, 74 ; transforming a live- 
point into a live-point, 77 ; Irannf orm- 
imr a conic, into a conic, 182 ; In piano, 
analytic form of, 381), 100, 2118; be- 
tween two planes, analytic, form of, 
190; in space, analytic- form of, 200; 
-leaving oonio invariant, 214, 220, 285, 
Ex. 2 ; is the product of two polar- 
ities, 265; which is the product of 
two reflections, 282, Ex. 5 ; double ele- 
ments of, in plane, 271; character- 
istic equation of, 272 j invariant figure 
of, is self-dual, 272 



336 



INDEX 



Collmeations, types of, in piano, 106, 
273 , associated with two comes of 
a pencil, 131, Exs 2, 4, 6, 135, 
Ex. 2 , 136, Ex 2 , group of, 111 plane, 
268, represented by matnces, 268- 
270 , two, not in general commuta- 
tive, 268 , canonical forms of, 274- 
276 

Commutative coirespondence, 66 
Commutative group, 67, 70, Ex 1, 228 
Commutative law of multiplication, 

148 
Commutative projectivities, 70, 210, 228 

Compass, constructions with, 246 

Complete it-line, in plane, 37, on point, 38 

Complete n-plane, in space, 37 , on point, 
38 

Complete n-pomt, in space, 36 , in plane, 
37 

Complete quadrangle and quadrilat- 
eral, 44 

Complex, linear, 312, determined by 
skew pentagon, 319 , general and spe- 
cial, 320 , determined by two piojec- 
tive flat pencils, 323 , determined by 
five independent lines, 324, deter- 
mined by coirespondence between 
points and planes of space, 324 , null 
system of, 324 , generated by involu- 
tion on regulus, 826, Ex. 5 , equation 
of, 329, 331 

Complexes, pencil of, 332 , in involu- 
tion, 333 , bundle of, 834, Ex. 7 

Concrete representation or application 
of an abstract science, 2 

Concurrent, 16 

Cone, 118, of lines, 109, of planes, 109, 
section of, by plane, is conic, 109, 
as degenerate case of quadnc, 308 

Configuration, 38, symbol of, 38, of 
Desargues, 40, 51, quadrangle-quad- 
rilateral, 44 , of Pappus, 98, 249 , of 
Mobius, 326, Ex. 9 

Congruence, linear, 312 ; elliptic, hyper- 
bolic, paiabolic, degenerate, 315 , de- 
termined by four independent lines, 
317 , deteinuned by protective planes, 
317 , determined by two 'complexes, 
325 , equation of, 329, 330 

Conic, 109, 118 , theorems on, 109-140 , 
polar system of, 120-124, equation 
of, 185, 245, projectivity on, 217, 
intersection of line with, 240, 242, 
246 , through four points and tangent 
to line, 250, Ex 8 , through three 
points and tangent to two lines, 250, 
Ex. 9 , through four points and meet- 
ing given line m two points harmonic 
with two given points, 250, Ex 10, 
determined by conjugate points, 293, 
Ex. 2 , 294, Exs 3, 4 

Conic section, 118 



Comes, pencils and ranges of, 128-136, 
287-293 , projective, 212, 304 

Con]ugate groups, 209 

Conjugate pair of involution, 102 

Conjugate points (lines), with legard to 
conic, 122 , on line (point), form invo- 
lution, 124 , with regaid to a pencil of 
comes, 136, Ex. 3 , 140, Ex. 31 , 293, 
Ex 1 

Conjugate projectivities, 208; condi- 
tions for, 208, 209 

Conjugate subgroups, 211 

Consistency, of a set of assumptions, 8 , 
of notion of elements at infinity, 9 , 
of assumptions of alignment, 17 

Construct, 45 

Constructions, linear (first degree), 236 , 
of second degree, 245, 249-250, 
Exs , of third and fourth degiees, 
294-296 

Contact, point of, of line of line conic, 
112 , of second order between two 
comes, 134, of third older between 
two comes, 136 

Conwell, G M , 204 

Coordinates, nonhomogeneous, of points 
on line, 152 , homogeneous, of points 
on line, 163, nonhomogeneous, of 
points in plane, 169, nonhomogene- 
ous, of lines in plane, 170 , homogene- 
ous, of points and lines in plane, 174, 
in a bundle, 179, Ex 3 , of quadran- 
gle-quadrilateral configuration, 181, 
Ex. 2, nonhomogeneous, in space, 
190 , homogeneous, m space, 194 , 
Pluckei's line, 327 , Klein's line, 333 

Coplanar, 24 

Copunctal, 16 

Correlation, between two-dimensional 
forms, 262, 263, induced, 262, be- 
tween two-dimensional foims deter- 
mined by four pairs of homologous 
elements, 264, which interchanges 
vertices and sides of tuangle is polar- 
ity, 264 , between two planes, analytic 
representation of, 266, 267, repie- 
sented by ternaiy bilinear form, 267 
represented by matuces, 270 , doubk 
paiis of a, 278-281 

Conelations and duality, 268 

Correspondence, as a logical term, 5 
perspective, 12 , (1, 1) of two figures 
85, geneial theoiy of, 64-66; iden 
tical, 65, inverse of, 65, period of 
66, periodic or cyclic, 66, involutoric 
or reflexive, 66 , peispective betweei 
two planes, 71 , quadratic, 139, Exs 
22, 24, 293, Ex. 1 

Correspondences, resultant or produc 
of two, 65, associative law for, 66 
commutative, 66 , groups of, 67, leav 
ing a figure invariant form a group, 6i 



INDEX 



337 



Corresponding oloinouta, 85, doubly, 
102 

Covariant, 257 , example of, 258 

Cremona, L., 187, 188 

Gross latio, 15!), ot haimomc set, 150, 
101 , clutuuticm of, 100 , expression foi, 
100 , 111 homogeneous coimhnates, 
105, theorems on, 107, 108, Exs , 
characteristic, ot piojoetivily, 205, 
characteristic, of involution, 200, <is 
an invariant, of two quadratic binary 
forms, 254, Ex, 1 , of four complexes, 
882 

Crohs ratios, tlio BIX, defined by four ole- 
monts, 101 

Curvn, ot third order, 217, Exs. 7, 8, ; 
algebraic, 250 

Cyclic correspondence, 0(5 

Darboux, U., 05 

Degenerate conies, 120 

Degenerate rogulus, 811 

Degree of geometric problem, 280 

Derivative, 255 

Dusargues, configuration of, 40, 61 ; the- 
orem on perspective triangles, 41, 
180 ; theorem on conies, 127, 128 

Dascartos, tt., 285 

Diagonal point, (line), of complete quad- 
rangh ("'.I' 1 lit *,.^ 44; of eom- 
plote i -*! if--. ; piano, 44 

Diagonal triangle ot quadrangle (quad- 
rilateral), 44 

Dickson, L. E., 00 

Difference of two points, 148 

Differential operators, 250 

Dimensions, spaou of threw, 20 ; Bpaco of 
n, 80 ; assumption!) for space of n, 88 ; 
space of live, 881 

Directrices, of a regulus, 200 j of a con- 
gruence, 816 ; of a special complex, 
324 

Distributive law for multiplication with 
respect to addition, 147 

Division of points, 140 

Domain of rationality, 288 

Double element (point, line, plane) of 
correspondence, 08 

Double pairs of a correlation, 07 

Double points, of a productivity on a 
line satisfy a quadratic equation, 150 ; 
of pro j activity on a line, homogeneous 
coordinates of, 104; of projectivity 
always exist in extended space, 242 j 
of projectivity on a line, construction 
of, 246 ; of involution determined by 
covariant, 258 ; and lines of collinea- 
tion in plane, 271, 295 

Double ratio, 159 

Doubly parabolic point, 274 

Duality, in three-space, 28, in plane, 
20; at a point, 20, in four-space, 29, 



Ex. ; a consequence of existence of 
correlations, 208 

Edge of it-point or ri-plano, 30, 37 
Elation, in plane, 72 , in space, 75 
Element, undefined, 1 , of a figure, 1 , 
fundamental, 1, ideal, 7, bimplo, of 
space, 84; Invariant, or double, or 
fixed, 08 , lineal, 107 
Eleven-point, plane section of, 58, Ex. 15 
Enriquos, F., 50, 280 
Equation, of hnu (point), 174, of come, 
185,245; oi plane (point), 103, 198, 
redui'ible, irreducible, 280; quadiatic, 
has roots in extended space, 242 
"Equivalent number systems, 150 
Extonded space, 2 12, 255 
Extension, assumptions of, 18, 24 

Fact! of n-point or it-piano, 80, 37 

Format, P., 285 

Field, 140 , points on a line form a, 151 , 
finite, modular, 201, extended, m 
which any polynomial is reducible, 200 

Figure, 34 

Fine, II. B., 255, 200, 201, 289 

Finite spaces, 201 

Five-point, piano section of, in space, 
3D ; in space may be translormod into 
any other by projootivo collineatiou, 
77 , diagonal points, linos, and planes 
of, in spaee, 204, Exs 16, 17, 18; 
simple, in space determines linear 
congruence, 810 

Five-points, perspective, in four-space, 
54, Ex. 25 

Fixed element, of correspondence, 08 

Flat pencil, 55 

Forms. *"n>' j '"p .;/.<" e j ' IP of one, two, 
and i.i- i i -i- ( - ">. one-dimen- 
sional, of second degree, 109; linear 
binary, 251 ; quadratic binary, 252 , 
of nth degree, 254; polar forms, 250 ; 
ternary lulinoar, loproaents correla- 
tion in piano, 207 

Four-space, 25, Ex. 4 

Frame of roi'cmmce, 174 

Fundamental elements, 1 

Fundamental points of a scale, 141, 281 

Fundamental propositions, 1 

Fundamental theorem of projectivity, 
94-97, 218, 204 

General point, 120 

Geometry, object of, Ij starting point 

of, 1 ; distinction between projjective 

and metric, 12 ; Unite, 201 ; associated 

with a group, 259 
Gergonne, J. D., 29, 128 
Grade, geometric forms of first second. 

third, 55 
Group, 66 ; of correspondences, 67 5 gen* 

eral projective, on line, 68, 209; 



338 



INDEX 



examples of, 69, 70 , commutative, 70 , 
general projective, in plane, 268 

HO, assumption, 45 , r61e of, 81, 261 

Harmonic conjugate, 80 

Harmonic homology, 223 

Harmonic involutions, 224 

Harmonic set, 80-82 , exercises on, 83, 
84 , cross ratio of, 159 

Harmonic transformations, 230 

Harmonically related, 84 

Hesse, 125 

Hessenberg, G , 141 

Hexagon, simple, inscribed in two inter- 
secting lines, 99 , simple, msciibed in 
three concurient lines, 250, Ex 5, 
simple, inscribed m conic, 110, 111 

Hexagram, of Pascal (hexagramma mys- 
ticum), 138, Exs 19-21, 304, Ex 16 

Hilbeit, D , 3, 95, 148 

Holgate, T. F , 119, 125, 139 

Homogeneous coordinates in plane, 
174 

Homogeneous coordinates, m space, 11, 
194 , on line, 163 , geometrical signifi- 
cance of, 165 
Homogeneous forms, 254 
Homologous elements, 35 
Homology, in plane, 72 , in space, 75 , 
axis and center of, 104, harmonic, 
223, 275 , canonical f oim of, in plane, 
274, 275 
Hyperosculate, applied to two comes, 136 

Ideal elements, 7 

Ideal points, 8 

Identical coirespondence, 65 

Identical matrix, 157, 269 

Identity (correspondence), 65, element 
of group, 67 

Improper elements, 239, 241, 242, 255 

Improper transformation, 242 

Impropeily proactive, 97 

Independence, of assumptions, 6 , neces- 
sary for distinction between assump- 
tion and theorem, 7 

Index, of subgroup, 271 ; of group of col- 
hneations in general projective group 
in plane, 271 

Induced correlation in planar field, 262 

Infinity, points, lines, and planes at, 8 

Inscribed and circumscubed triangles, 
98, 250, Ex. 4 

Inscribed figure, in a conic, 118 

Invariant, of two linear binary forms, 
252 , of quadratic binary forms, 252- 
254, Ex. 1; of bmaiy form of nth 
degree, 257 

Invariant element, 68 

Invariant figure, under a correspond- 
ence, 67 , of collineation is self -dual, 
272 



Invanant subgroup, 211 

Invariant triangle of collineation, rela- 
tion between projectivities on, 274, 
276, Ex 5 

Inverse, of a coriespondence, 65, of 
element in gioup, 67 , of piojectivity 
is a piojectivity, 68, of piojectivity, 
analytic expiession for, 157 

Inverse opeiations (subtraction, divi- 
sion), 148, 149 

Involution, 102 , theorems on, 102, 103, 
124, 127-131, 133, 134, 136, 206, 209, 
221-229, 242-243 , analytic expression 
for, 157, 222, 254, Ex. 2, character- 
istic cross latio of, 206 , on conic, 222- 
230 , belonging to a proj activity, 226 , 
double points of, in extended space, 

242 , condition foi, 254, Ex 2 , dou- 
ble points of, 1 * determined by covan- 
ant, 258 , complexes in, 333 

Involutions, any projectivity is product 
of two, 223 , haimonic, 224 , pencil 
of, 225, two, have pair in common, 

243, two, on distinct lines are per- 
spective, 243 

Involutoric coriespondence, 66 
Irieducible equation, 239 
Isomorphism, 6, between number sys- 
tems, 150 , simple, 220 

Jackson, D . 282 
Join, 16 

Kantoi, S , 250 
Klein, F , 95, 333, 334 

Ladd, C , 138 

Lage, Geometne dei, 14 

Lennes, N J , 24 

Lmdemann, F , 289 

Line, at infinity, 8 , as undefined class 

of points, 15 , and plane on the same 

three-space inteisect, 22 , equation of, 

174, and conic, inteisection of, 240, 

246 

Line conic, 109 
Line coordinates, in plane, 171 ; in space, 

327, 833 

Lineal element, 107 
Linear binary forms, 251 , invariant of, 

251 
Linear dependence, of points, 30, of 

lines, 311 

Linear fractional tiansformation, 152 
Linear net, 84 
Linear operations, 236 
Linear transformations, m plane, 187 , 

in space, 199 
Lines, two, in same plane intersect, 

18 
Luroth, J , 95 



INDEX 



339 



Maclaunn, C., 110 

MacNoish, II E., 46 

Mathematical science, 2 

Matrices, product of, 156, 268 , determi- 
nant ot pioduct of two, 269 

Matrix, as symbol for configuration, 88 , 
definition, 15(5, used to denote pro- 
jectivity, 156, identical, 157, 269, 
oharaotoiiBtic equation of, 105, 272; 
conjugate, transposed, adjoint, 209, 
as operator, 270 

Memeolmms, 120 

Metric geometry, 12 

Midpoint oi pair of points, 280, Ex. 6 

Mobius tetrahodra, 105, Ex. 6; 826, 
Ex. 

Multiplication of points, 145, 281 , the- 
oic'ins on, 145-J48; commutative law 
of, is equivalent to* Aasmuption P, 
148, other definitions of, 107, Exs. 
8,4 

n-line, complete or simple, 87, 88, in- 
scribed in conic, 188, Ex. 12 

n-plane, complete m space, 87 ; on point, 
88 , simple in space, 87 

n-point, complete, in space, 86 ; complete, 
m a piano, 87, simple, iu space, 37, 
simple, in a piano, 37; plane section of, 
in space, 58, Exs. 18j 16 , 54, Ex. 18; 
m-ftpace section of, in (n + 1) -apace, 
54, Ex. Ifl , section by three-space of, 
in four-space, 54, Ex. 21 ; inscribed 
m came, 119, Ex 5; 250, Ex. 7 

71-pomts, in different planes and per- 
spective from a point, 42, Ex. 2, in 
same plane and perspective from a 
line, 42, Ex. 4; two complete, in a 
plane, 68, Ex. 7 ; two perspective, in 
(n 1) -space, theorem on, 64, Ex. 
26; mutually inscribed and circum- 
scribed, 250, Ex. 

Net of rationality, on line (linear net), 
84; theorems on, 85; in plane, 86; 
theorems on, 87, 88, Exs. 92, 98; in 
space, 89 ; theorems on, 89-92, Exs. 02, 
98 , in plane (space) left invariant by 
perspective collineation, 08, Exs. 0, 
10; in space is properly projeotive, 
97; coordinates in, 162 

Newson, H. B., 274 

Nonhomogeneous coordinates, on a line, 
152 ; in plane, 160; in space, 100 

Null system, 824 

Number system, 140 

On, 7, 8, IS 

Operation, one-valued, commutative, as- 
sociative, 141; geometric, 2$0; linear, 
280 

Operator, differential, 2$0; represented 
by matrix, 270 > pmar ? 284 



Opposite sides of complete quadrangle, 

44 
Opposite veitex and side of simple 

n-pomt, 37 
Opposite veitices, of complete quadnlat- 

eralj 44 , of simple n-point, 87 
Oppositely placed quadi angles, 50 
Order, 60 
Ordinal e, 170 
Origin of coordinates, 169 
Osculate, applied to two conies, 184 

Padoa, A., 3 

Papperite, E , 800 

Pappus, configuration of, 98, 99, 100, 

126, 148 

Parabolic congruence, 815 

Parabolic point of collineation in plane, 
274 

Parabolic projoctivities, any two, are 
conjugate, 209 

Parabolic projoetlvity, 101 , charac- 
teristic cross ratio of, 206; analytic 
expression for, 207 ; chaiactenstic con- 
stants, 207 ; gives II( MA', AA"), 207 

Parametric representation, of points 
(linos) of pencil, 182 ; of conic, 284; of 
roguluH, congruence, complex, 880, 881 

Pascal, B., 36, 1)0, 111-110, 128, 126, 

127, 188, 189 

Pencil, of points, planes, lines, 55; of 
conies, 120-186, 287-208; of points 
(lines), coordinates of, 181 , paiamet- 
ric representation of, 182 ; base points 
of, 182 ; of involutions, 225 ; of com- 
plexes, 832 

Period of correspondence, 06 

Perspective collinoation, in plane, 71 ; 
in space, 75 ; in plane donned when 
center, axis, and one pair of homol- 
ogous points are given, 72 , leaving JB a 
( 8 ) invariant, 98, Exs. 9, 10 

Perspective conic and pencil of lines 
(points), 215 

Perspective correspondence, 12, 18 ; be- 
tween two planes, 71, 277, Ex. 20 

Perspective iigures, from a point or 
from a plane. 35 ; from a line, 80 ; if 
A,B,C and A', B', C' on two coplanar 
lines are perspective, the points (AB', 
&A')> (AC', OA% and (B<7, CS') are 
collinear, 52, Ex. 8 

Perspective geometric forms, 56 

Perspective n-lines, theorems on, 84, 
Exs, 13, 14 ; five-points in four-space, 
64, Ex. 25 

Perspective (n + l)-points in n-spaoe, 
64, Exs. SO, 26 

3|erspectlve tetrahedra, 48 

perspective triangles, theorems on, 41. 
ft Exs. 0, 10, 11 5 64, Ex. 28; 84, 
, EXS, 7, 10, 11 ; 246 ; sextuply, 246 



340 



IHDEX 



Perspectivity, center of, plane of, axis 

of , 36 , notation for, 57 , central and 

axial, 57 , between conic and pencil 

of lines (points), 215 
Fieri, M , 95 
Planar field, 55 
Planar net, 86 

Plane, at infinity, 8 , defined, 17 , deter- 
mined uniquely by three noncollmear 
points, or a point and line, or two in- 
tersecting lines, 20 , and line on same 
tluee-space are on common point, 
22 , of perspectivity, 36, 75, of points, 
55, of lines, 55, equation o, 193, 
198 

Plane figure, 34 

Plane section, 34 

Planes, two, on two points A, B are on 
all points of line AB, 20, two, on 
same three-space are on a common 
line, and conversely, 22 , three, on a 
thiee-space and not on a common 
line aie on a common point, 23 

Plucker's line coordinates, 327 

Point, at infinity, 8 , as undefined ele- 
ment, 15 , and line determine plane, 
17, 20 , equation of, 174, 193, 198 , of 
contact of a line with a conic, 112 

Point come, 109 

Point figure, 34 

Points, thiee, determine plane, 17, 20 

Polar, with respect to triangle, 46, 
equation of, 181, Ex 3 , with respect 
to two lines. 52, Ess 3, 5 , 84, Exs. 7, 
9 , with respect to tuangle, theorems 
on, 54, Ex. 22 , 84, Exs 10, 11 , with 
respect to n-lme, 84, Exs 13, 14 , with 
respect to conic, 120-125, 284, 285 

Polai forms, 256 , with lespect to set of 
ji-pomts, 256, with lespect to regu- 
lus, 302 , with respect to linear com- 
plex, 324 

Polar reciprocal figmes, 123 

Polaiity, in planai field, 263, 279, 282, 
283 , in space, 302 , null, 324 

Pole, with respect to triangle, 46 , with 
respect to two lines, 52, Ex 3 , with 
respect to conic, 120 , with respect to 
regulus, 302, with respect to null 
system, 824 

Poncelet, J V , 29, 36, 58, 119, 123 

Problem, degree of, 236, 238 , algebraic, 
transcendental, 238, of second de- 
giee, 243 , of projectivity, 250, Ex 14 

Product, of two correspondences, 65, 
of points, 145, 231 

Project, a figure from a point, 86 , an 
element into, 58, ABC can be pro- 
jected into A'B'C', 59 

Projection, of a figure from a point, 34 

Protective collineation, 71 

Piojective conies, 212, 304 



Project! ve correspondence or transfor- 
mation, 13, 58 , general group on line, 
68 , m plane, 268 , of two- or three- 
dimensional forms, 71, 152 

Projective geometry distinguished from 
metric, 12 

Projective pencils of points on skew 
lines are axially perspective, 64 

Projective projectivities, 208 

Projective space, 97 

Projectivity, definition and notation for, 
58, ABC-xA'B'Q', 59; ABCD-^- 
BADG, 60 , in one-dimensional forms 
is the lesultof twopeispectivities, 63 , 
if H (12, 34), then 1234-^1243, 82, 
fundamental theorem of, for linear 
net, 94 , fundamental theorem of, for 
line, 95, assumption of, 95, funda- 
mental theorem of, for plane, 96 , for 
space, 97 , principle ot, 97 , necessaiy 
and sufficient condition for MNAB -^- 
MNA'E' is Q(MAB, NB'A*), 100, 
necessary and sufficient condition 
f 01 MMAB x MMA'B' is Q (MAB, 
MB' A'), 101 , parabolic, 101 , ABCD 
-rABDC implies H(AB, CD), 103, 
nonhomogeneous analytic expiession 
for, 154-157, 206 , homogeneous ana- 
lytic expression for, 164, analytic 
expiession for, between points of dif- 
ferent lines, 167 , analytic expression 
for, between pencils in plane, 183 , 
between two comes, 212-216, on 
conic, 217-221, axis (centei) of, on 
conic, 218, involution belonging to, 
226 , problem of, 250, Ex. 14 

Projectivities, commutative, example of, 
70 , on sides of invariant triangle of 
collineation, 274, 276, Ex 5 

Projector, 35 

Pioperlyprojective, 97, spatial net is, 97 

Quadrangle, complete, 44, quadrangle- 
quadrilateral configuiation, 46, sim- 
ple, theorem on, 52, Ex. 6 , complete, 
and quadnlateial, theoiem on, 53, 
Ex 8, any complete, may be trans- 
formed into any other by piojective 
collineation, 74, opposite sides of, 
meet line in pans of an involution, 
103 , comes thiough vertices of, meet 
line in pairs of an involution, 127 , 
inscribed in conic, 137, Ex. 11 

Quadrangles, if two, correspond so that 
five pairs of homologous sides meet, 
on a line 2, the sixth pair meets on 
I, 47, perspective, theorem on, 53, 
Ex. 12 , if two, have same diagonal 
tuangle, their eight vertices are on 
come, 137, Ex. 4 

Quadrangular set, 49, 79 , of lines, 79 ; of 
planes, 79 



INDEX 



341 



Quadrangular section by transveihal of 
quadrangular set, of linos is a quad- 
rangulai set of points, 70 ; of elements 
projoctive with quadrangular wL is 
a quadrangular sot, 80; Q(MAH, 
NB'A') is tho condition for MNA B-r 
MNA'B' 100 , Q(MA B, Mli'A') is tho 
condition for MMAB-^WMA'B', 101 , 
Q(ABC, A'Jl'C') iniplujK Q(A'irW, 
ABC), 101, Q(ABV, A'W(J') is tlio 
condition that ./I/I', />'/?', CO' are in in- 
volution, 103 , Q(P* P.PQ, 7'/',Ai-) 
is necessary and suthciont fin /', 4- /' 
= /',+ 112; Q(/Vy>i, 2VV'.#) 
is necessary and sufheiont for P x P v 
= /*, M5 

Quadrangularly related, 8(5 

Quadratic binary ionn, 252; invariant 
of, 2, r )2 

Quadratic correspondence, 18!), 1C vs. 
22, 24 

Quartno spread in SB, 331 

Quadno surface, 801 ; degenerate, .308 ; 
determined by ninopomts, 311 

Quadrilateral, complete, 44 , if two quad- 
rilaterals correspond ho that live of tho 
lines joining pairs of homologous vor- 
tices pass through a point, P, tho lino 
joining the .sixth pair of vertices will 
also pass through P, 49 

Quantic, 254 

Quaternary forms, 258 

Quotient of points, 140 

Range, of points, 55; of conies, 128-180 

Katio, of points, 140 

Kational operations, 140 

Rational space, 08 

Rationality, not of, on lino, 84, 85 ; planar 
net, of, 80-88 ; spatial not of, 80-05} 3 
domain of, 288 

Rationally related, 80, 80 

Reducible equation, 280 

Reflection, point-line, projoctivo, 228 

Reflexive c-nvrfUTion-lc""" <KI 

RcguluK, 1. 1 ,i" . i 3 I'-n ' i. - 208; 
directrices of, 200 ; generators or 
rulers of, 200; conjugate, 200; gen- 
erated by projeoUve ranges or axial 
pencils, 200 ; generated by projeetivo 
comes, 804, 807 ; polar system of, 800 ; 
picture of, 800 ; degenerate COHOS, 81 1 , 
of a congruence, 818 

Related ilgnres, 85 

Resultant, of two correspondences, 05; 
equal, 65; of two projectivities is a 
project! vity, 08 

Reye, T,, 125, 180 

Holm, K., 300 

Salmon, G., 188 
Sannia, A., 304 



Scale, defined by Lliroo points, 141, 231 , 
on a conic, 28 % 1 

Schrotoi, IT., 188, 281 

Helmr, E , 05 

ijuionuu, abstiact mathematical, 2, con- 
crete application or representation of, 2 

Scott, C A , 203 

Suction, of iiguro by pUuiu, 34 , of piano 
llgiue by line, 35, conic section, 100 

Sogru, C., 280 

Hiill'-conjugato Hiibgrou]i, 211 

Sulf-eonjugato triauglo vvitli respect to 
conn;, 128 

Self-polar triangle with respect to come, 
128 

Set, synonymous with class, 2 , quadran- 
gular, 40, 70 , ot elemental projoctivo 
with quadrangular sot is quadrangu- 
Icir, 80, harmonic, 80; theorems on 
luuimmiu .sets, 81 

Seven-point, piano section of, 53, Ex. 14 

SuydowitK, If , 281 

Sheaf of planes, 55 

Side, of n-pomt, 87 ; false, of complete 

s . quadrangles, 50 

huupio cieuumr, of spaco, 30 
Simple ?i-pomt, n-lino, n-plano, 37 
Singly parabolic point, 274 
Singular point and lino in nonhomoge- 

neous eooulmates, 171 
Six-point, plane section of, 54, Ex. ] 7 ; 

in four-space suction by three-space, 

54, Ex. 24 
Skew lines, 24, projectivo pencils on, 

are perspective, 105, Kx. Ji ; fom, are 

met by two lines, 250, Ex. 18 
Spat',0, nualytUi projectivo, 11 ; of three 

dimensions, 20; theorem of duality 

for, of three dimensions, 28, n-, 80; 

assumption for, of n dimensions, 83 ; 

as equivalent of three-space, 84; 

properly or improperly projoctivo, 

07; rational, 08; Unite, 201, 202; 

extended, 242 
Spatial not, 80; theorems on, 80-02; 

IH properly protective, 07 
von Htauilt, K. (3. C., 14, 05, 125, 141, 

151, 158, 10, 28(J 
Hteinor, J,, 100, 111, L25, 188, 180, 286, 

280 

SLoinor point and lino, 188, Ex. 10 
SteiniU, K., 201 
Sluriu, Oh., 120 
Sturm, 11., 281, 250, 287 
Subclass, 2 
Subgroup, 08 
Subtraction of points, 148 
Sum of two points, 141, 281 
Surface, algebraic, 260; quadrlo, 801 
Sylvester, J. J., 828 
System affected by a correspondence, 65 



342 



INDEX 



Tangent, to conic, 112 

Tangents to a point conic form a line 
conic, 116 , analytic proof, 187 

Taylor's theorem, 255 

Ternary foims, 258, bilinear, repre- 
sent correlation in a plane, 267 

Tetrahedra, perspective, 43, 44 , config- 
uration of perspective, as section of 
six-point in four-space, 54, Ex. 24, 
Mobius, 105, Ex. 6 , 326, Ex. 9 

Tetiahedron, 37, four planes joining 
line to vertices of, projective with 
four points of inteiaection of line 
with faces, 71, Ex 5 

Three-space, 20, determined uniquely 
by four points, by a plane and a point, 
by two nomnteisectmg lines, 23 , the- 
orem of duality foi, 28 

Throw, definition of, 60 , algebra of, 141, 
157, characteristic, of projectivity, 
205 

Throws, two, sum and product of, 158 

Trace, 35 

Transform, of one piojectivity by an- 
other, 208 , of a group, 209 

Transform, to, 58 

Tiansfonnation, perspective, 13, pio- 
jective, 13 , of one-dimensional foims, 
58, of two- and thiee-dimensional 
forms, 71 

Tiansitive group, 70, 212, Ex 6 

Triangle, 37; diagonal, of quadiangle 
(quadrilateral), 44 , whose sides pass 
through three given collmear points 
and whose vertices are on three given 
lines, 102, Ex 2, of leference of 
system of homogeneous coordinates 



in plane, 174, invariant, of collinea- 
tion, i Ration between projectivities 
on sides of, 274, 276, Ex. 5 

Triangles, perspective, from point aie 
perspective from line, 41 , axes of 
perspectivity of three, in plane per- 
spective from same point, are con- 
current, 42, Ex. 6 , peispective, theo- 
rems on, 53, Exs. 9, 10, 11 , 105, Ex. 
9 ; 116, 247 ; mutually inscribed and 
circumscribed, 99, perspective, fiom 
two centers, 100, Exs. 1, 2, 8, from 
four centers, 105, Ex 8 , 138, Ex 18 , 
fiom six centers, 246-248 , inscribed 
and cucumscribed, 250, Ex. 4 

Triple, point, of lines of a quadrangle, 
49 , of points of a quadrangulai set, 49 

Triple, triangle, of lines of a quadran- 
gle, 49; of points of a quadrangulai 
set, 49 

Triple system, 3 

Undefined elements in geometry, 1 

United position, 15 

Unproved propositions in geometry, 1 

Variable, 58, 150 

Veblen, O , 202 

Veronese, G., 52, 53 

Vertex, of ?i-pomts, 36, 37 , of n-planes, 
37, of flat pencil, 55, of cone, 109, 
false, of complete quadrangle, 44 

Wiener, H , 65, 95, 230 
Zeuthen, H. G,, 95 




NOTES AND CORRECTIONS 



Page 22. In the proof of Theorem 0, under the Loading 2, it is assumed that A 
is not on a. But if -A. were on a, the theorem would, bo verified. 

Page 34. In the definition of projection, after "P," in the last line on the page, 
insert " , together with the lines and planes of F through P,". 

Page 34. In the definition of section, after " TT," in the last line on the page, insert 
" together with the lines and points of F on TT,". 

Page 35. In the definition of section of a plane figure F by a line Z, the section 
should include also all the points of F that are on Z 

Page 44, line 6 from "bottom of page. The triple system referred to does not 
of course, satisfy J 8 . It is not difficult, however, to build up a system of triples 
which does satisfy all the assumptions A and JS. Such a finite S a would contain 
15 "points" and 15 "planes" (of which the given triple system is one) and 35 
"lines" (triples). See Ex. 8, p. 25, and Ex. 15, p. 203. 

Page 47, Theorem 3. Add the restriction that the lino I must not contain a 
vertex of either quadrangle. 

Page 49 In the definition, of quadrangular set, after "a lino Z" insert " not 
containing a vertex of the quadrangle,". 

Page 62, Ex. 1. The latter part should road- "... of an edge [joining two 
vertices of the five-point with the face containing the other three vertices ? " 

Page 53, Exs. 14, 15, 10. The term circumscribed may be explicitly defined as 
follows : A simple n-point is said to bo circumscribed to another simple n-point 
if there is a one-to-one reciprocal correspondence between the lines of the first 
n-pomt and the points of the second, such that each lino passes through its corre- 
sponding point. The second n-point is then said to be inscribed m the first. 

Page 53, Ex. 16. The theorem as stated is inaccurate. If w is the smallest 
exponent for -which 2"*sl, mod. w, the vertices of the plane section may be 

VL i T MM 1 

divided into - simple n-points, which fall into cycles of m n-points 

2 2 771 

each, such that the w^points of each cycle circumscribe each other cyclically. 
Thus, when n = 17, there are two cycles of 4 n-points, the n-points of each cycle 
circumscribing each other cyclically. 

Page 85, Theorem 9. If the quadrangular set contains one or two diagonal 
points of the determining quadrangle, these diagonal points must be among the 
five or four given points. 

Page 88, Theorem 12, To complete the proof of this theorem the perspectivity 
mentioned must be used in both directions i.e. it also makes the points of Bj or 
E a perspective with the points of JB a on I. 

Page 99, Theorem 22. See note to p. 58, Exs. 14, 15, 16. 

Page 108, Theorem 29. tinder Type III, the proviso should be added that the 
line PQ is not on the center of F and the point pg is not on the axis of F. 

Page 119, Ex. 6. The latter part of this exercise requires a quadratic construc- 
tion. Bee Cha$>. IX. 

Page 137, Ex. 7 (Miscellaneous Exercises). The two points must not be collinear 
With- a vetted ; oy, if eolUnear with a vertex, they must be harmonic with respect 
to the vertex and the opposite side. 

848 

* ; 

T * 

> f r 
If 



344 NOTES AND CORRECTIONS 

Page 165, last paragraph. The point ( 1, 1) forms an exception in the definition 
of homogeneous coordinates subject to the condition x t + x a = 1. An exceptional 
point (or points) will always exist if homogeneous coordinates aie subjected to a 
nonhomogeneous condition 

Page 168, Ex 10. The points A, B, G t D must be distinct 
Page 182, bottom of page We assume that the center of the pencil of lines is 
not on the axis of the pencil of points (cf . the footnote on p. 183) 

Page 186 While the second sentence of Theorem 7 is literally correct, it may 
easily be misunderstood If the left-hand member of the equation of one of the 
lines m = 0, n = 0, or p = be multiplied by a constant p, the value of k may 
be changed without changing the conic In fact, by choosing p properly, k may be 
given an arbitrary value (5* 0) for any conic. 

As pointed out in the review of this book by H. Beck, Archiv der Mathematik, 
Vol. XVIII (1911), p. 85, the equation of the conic may be written as follows 
Let (c^, a 2 , a s ) be an arbitrary point in the plane of the conic, and let 
m x = mfa + m 2 a> 2 + m a x 3 , 
n x = 
Px J 
then the equation of the conic may be written 

Jc 2 m a n a p% k^mxUx = 
When the equation is written m this foim, there is one and only one conic for 

Tf 

every value of the ratio -i 
k z 

Page 301. The fiist sentence is not correct under om oiiginal definition of section 
by a plane. We have accordingly changed this definition (cf note to p. 34) 

Page 301. In the sentence before Theorem 7 the tangent hues referred to are 
not lines of the quadnc surface 

Page 303, Ex 5 The tangent line must not be a line of the surface. 

Page 303, Ex. 7. The line must not be a tangent line. 

Page 304. Theorem 11 should read " . . form a legulus or a cone of lines, pro- 
vided . . ". In case the collineation between the planes of the comes leaves every 
point of I invariant, the lines joining corresponding points of the two comes form 
a cone of lines. In this case A = A and B = 2?, and the lines a and b intersect 

Page 306, line 7 After "sections," insert ", unless a and 6 intersect, in which 
case they generate a cone of lines " (cf . note to p 304). 

Page 308, proof of Corollary 2. Let A\ be the projection on a of 5 2 from the 
point Jf A\ might ha\e double contact with A z at E and JR', or might have con- 
tact of the second order at R or H' However, if C a is not degeneiate, it is possible 
to choose M for which neither of these happens For if all conies obtained from 
[M ] had either of the above properties, they would form a pencil of comes of 
which A 2 is one There would then exist a point M for which A\ and A* would 
coincide C 2 would m this case have to contain three collmear points and would 
then be degenerate. 

Page 310, paragraph beginning "Now if nine points . . ". It is obvious that 
no line of intersection of two of the planes a, )3, 7 will contain one of the nine 
points, no matter how the notation is assigned. 

Page 315, line 12 from bottom of page. Neither^ nor ir z must contain a directrix. 

Page 319, Ex 2. If the two involutions have double points, the points on the 
lines joining the double points are to be excepted in the second sentence. 



NOTES AND CORKECTIONS 345 

Pages 320, 321. In the proof of Theorem 20 the possibility that tliioe of the 
vertices of the simple pentagon may be collmear is overlooked. Theiefoic the 
third sentence of the last paragraph of page 320 and the third bontence of 
page 321 are incorrect It is not haul to restate the proof correctly, as all the 
facts needed are grven in the text, but thus restatement requires, several verbal 
changes and rb therefore left as an excrci.se to the reader