Skip to main content

Full text of "Psychological review"

See other formats


This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on library shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 
to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 
to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 
are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other marginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 
publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we have taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 

We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain from automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attribution The Google "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liability can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 



at |http : //books . google . com/ 



Boston 

Medical Library 

8 The Fenway 




)• : 



"i 



1 ^' 



r 



•i 



J 



/iA/y. /f 



THE 

Psychological Review 

EDITED BY 
J. MARK BALDWIN HOWARD C. WARREN 

Johns Hopkins University ^^^ Princeton Uniyersity 

CHARLES H. JUDD, Yale University {EdUor of the Monograph Series). 

WITH THE CO-OPERATION FOR THIS SECTION OF 

A. C A|(.MSTRONG, Wesleyan University ; ALFRED BINET, £cole des Hautis- 
firuDES, Paris; W. L. BRYAN, Indiana University; WILLIAM CALDWELL, Mc- 
Giu. Umxvbrsity; MARY W. CALKINS, Wellesuey College; JOHN DEWEY, 
Columbia University ; J. R. ANGELL, University op Chicago ; C. LADD FRANKLIN, 
Baltimore; H. N. GARDINER, Sbcth College; G. H. HOWISON, University of 
Caufornia ; P. JANET, College de Francs ; JOSEPH JASTROW, University of Wis- 
consin; ADOLF MEYER, N. Y. Pathol. Institute; C. LLOYD MORGAN, University 
College, Bristol; HUGO MCNSTERBERG, Harvard University; E. A. PACE, 
Catholic University, Washington ; G. T. W. PATRICK, University of Iowa ; 
R. W. WENLEY, University of Michigan. 



Volume XIV., 1907. 



THE REVIEW PUBLISHING CO., 

41 NORTH QUEEN ST., LANCASTER, PA. 

BALTIMORE, MD. 

AABfTS : G. E. STECHERT ft CO., LomdoK (a Scar Yard, Carey St., W. C); 

Lbipzig (Hospital St., lo); Paris (76 rue de Rennet); 

Madrid, D. Jorro (Calle de la Pas, 93). 




010 6 1913 



TM Mw Eua Printim OOHPiMV 
UnoMTW, PH. 




CONTENTS OP VOLUME XIV. 

January 

Definition and Analyeis of the ContciOD«neM of Value (x): W. M. Urban, i. 

Some Important Sitnatione and their Attitndea. A. H. Li<oyd, 37. 

Diacneaion : Genetic Modea and the Meaning of the Psychic. The late C. L. Hbrrick 

54. Corrigenda, 60. 
March 

The Province of Functional Psychology. Jambs Rowi^and Angsli., 61. 
Definition and Analysis of the Conscionsness of Valne (11). W. M. Urban, 92. 
A Study of After-images on the Peripheral Retina. Hbi^bn B. Thompson and Katb 

Gordon, 122. 
Xditon' Announcement, 168. 

May 

Studies from the Laboratory of the University of Chicago : Communicated by J. R. 

Angbi<i^ The Pendular Whiplash Illusion of Motion: H. Carr, 169. 
Thought and Language. J. Mark Baij)win, 181. 
The Nature of the Soul and the Possibility of a Psycho-Hecbanic : The late C. L. 

Hbrrick, 205. 

July 

Studies from the Laboratory of the University of Chicago: Communicated by J. R. 

Angbix. The Role of the Tympanic Mechanism in Audition. W, V. D. 

Bingham, 229. 
On the Method of Just-perceptible Differences. P. M. Urban, 244. 
The Ultimate Valne of Experience. S. S. Coi^vin, 254. 
On Truth. J. Mark Bai^dwin, 264. 
Discussion : A Further Application of a Result Obtained in Experimental JBsthetics. 

B. H. Rowland, 288. Experience, Habit and Attention. A. W. Moore, 292. 

Comment on Prof. Moore's Paper: J. Mark Bai«dwin, 297. 

September 

The Nature of Feeling and Will and their Relations. W. M. Urban, 299. 

A Fourth Progression in the Relation of Body and Mind. R. W. Sbli^ars, 315. 

Sensory Aifection and Emotion: Hbi^bn T. Wooi^i^by, 329. 

Discussion. An Experimental Course in JBsthetics. Max Mbybr, 345. 

November 

Apparent Control of the Position of the Visual Field. H. Carr, 357. 

Concerning Animal Perception. G. H. Mbad, 383. 

A Study in Vertical Symmetry. B. H. Rowi^and, 391. 

Logical Community and the Difference of Discemibles. J. Mark Bai<dwin, 395. 



N. S. Vol. XIV/,^^^ ^^^5X January, 1907. 
■ -^ DEC 6 1913 ' 



iJB 




The Psychological Review. 



DEFINITION AND ANALYSIS OF THE CONSCIOUS- 
NESS OF VALUE.^ I. 

BY PROFESSOR WILBUR M. URBAN, 
Trinity College, 

A cursory examination of the more general terms of worth 
description, good and bad, useful and useless, beautiful and 
ugly, noble and ignoble, etc., or indeed the terms worth and 
worthless, valuable and valueless themselves, and the manner 
in which they are applied, makes us immediately aware of the 
fact that for the unreflective worth consciousness they are at first 
tertiary qualities as much a part of the object as the so-called pri- 
mary and secondary qualities are parts of the physical object 
of cognition. This is especially noticeable in the case of the 
ethical and aesthetic predicates but it is no less true of the 
unreflective use of the terms utility and value, as for instance 
when we say that iron has utility or value even when the con- 
ditions of its applicability are lacking. The intrinsic worth 
judgment is psychologically the more fundamental whatever 
may be inferred upon closer inspection and reflection. 

But while they appear at first sight to be tertiary qualities of 
the object, on closer examination these predicates are seen to be 
acquired meanings of the object for the subject. Without inquir- 
ing too closely for the present into the question whether or not 
such qualities may be in some sense objective, it may be asserted 

^ This paper, part of a larger study now completed, was ready for publication 
six months ago. The appearance in July of Baldwin's Thought and Things 
showed such substantial agreement in general point of view and method, that it 
has seemed desirable to take advantage of the opportunity to make certain 
minor changes in terminology, most of which are specifically noted. 



2 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

unhesitatingly that they are meanings pre-determined by ante- 
cedent psychical processes. As thus pre-determined, they may 
be described as selective and funded meanings. They are 
* selective meanings * ^ in that they represent differentiation of 
aspects of objects acquired in processes of feeling and will. 
They are funded meanings in that they represent the accumu- 
lation of meaning of these processes. We may therefore define 
the worth predicates briefly as the selective funded affective- 
volitional meanings of objects. 

For the purposes of our study the funded meaning of worth 
predicates should be distinguished from the * founded ' mean- 
ings or objects of cognitive experience. By a * founded '* object 
in general we understand one built up by processes of presenta- 
tion or judgment upon primary sensations and perceptions. Such 
a founded object is strictly speaking not the object of perception 
but of presentation or judgment and may be said to be pre-deter- 
mined by these processes. Thus certain ideal objects of presenta- 
tion and judgment, while themselves not sensed or perceived, may 
be said to be founded on sensation and perception. They are 
ideal constructions, and as such selective cognitive meanings. 
The objects of the funded meanings of worth predication may 
be either primary or founded objects, objects of perception or of 
ideal construction. Thus to take a single illustration, the proc- 
esses of sympathetic realization of the feelings of another, are 
in the first place perceptual in character, but upon the basis of 
these processes certain ideal objects, the self and its dispositions 
are built up which become the objects of imputed values. To 
them is imputed the funded meaning of the processes of feeling 
and conation involved in their construction. 

The worth predicates are then the funded meanings of pri- 
mary and founded objects. When, now, we attempt a further 
analysis of the predicates, we are confronted with peculiar dif- 
ficulties, which arise from equivocations in their meaning, 
equivocations so confusing upon first appearance that more 

^ This use of * selective meaning ' as in contrast to ' recognitive meaning ' is 
suggested and developed by Baldwin in his Thought and Things or Genetic 
Logic, I., Chap. VII. 

' The term ' founded ' is a translation of Meinong's expression fundterte 
(Oegenstand, Inhalt) wrongly translated by womt funded. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 3 

than one thinker has counseled entire scepticism in the matter, 
not without a show of reason, it must be admitted. But that 
this initial scepticism is merely a salutary warning will become 
apparent as we follow these equivocations to their sources for it 
is precisely in this process, this study of the grammar of the 
worth consciousness, that we shall find both the nature of the 
processes through which these funded meanings are acquired 
and the basis of their classification. 

These worth equivocations make themselves felt, precisely 
as certain contradictions in cognitive predication, through ab- 
straction of the predicates, as qualities of the objects, from the 
processes of acquirement of meaning through which the funded 
meanings and founded worth objects arise. The character of 
the confusion may be seen at a glance by observing the distinc- 
tions which worth analysis has developed (in all the concrete 
worth sciences, economics, ethics, aesthetics) for the removal of 
the equivocations. Worths are said to be subjective or objec- 
tive, real or ideal, actual or imputed, intrinsic or instrumental. 

The first distinction, between subjective and objective worths 
or values, gives the key to the situation. The same objects, let 
us say diamonds, may have little worth or indeed be distasteful 
to me personally, although in another attitude I may ascribe 
great value to them and, indeed, think of them as intrinsically 
valuable. My friend's action may be sanctioned by me in im- 
mediate appreciation, although from an objective, moral point of 
view I must needs condemn it. Such contradictions can only be 
resolved by a distinction between subjective and objective values. 
Closely connected with this equivocation is that which arises 
when the distinction between intrinsic and instrumental values 
is ignored. An object which is worthless, or indeed the object 
of negative worth judgments of harmful or bad, may acquire the 
predicate worth when it becomes instrumental to some object of 
immediate or intrinsic worth. And within the sphere of instru- 
mental values or utilities, /. tf., the economic, we find an equiv- 
ocation which can be removed only by the use of the distinction 
between subjective and objective. On the one hand, if any 
thing is of worth because it is utilizable, it is always so for a 
subject and with reference to concrete conditions. But on the 



4 WILBUR Af. URBAN. 

Other hand, we are led to ascribe value to an object (for instance 
when we say that iron has value) irrespective of its relation to 
an individual subject and to concrete conditions ; by a process of 
abstraction we give the object value in itself. For these dif- 
ferences in meaning the economists have used the terms subjec- 
tive and objective value, or the latter is sometimes called objec- 
tive exchange value. From these illustrations we see that the 
attitude expressed by a worth judgment, whether the worth be 
described as subjective or objective, is an attitude of a subject, 
but the difference in attitude is determined by the inclusion or 
exclusion of certain presuppositions, the nature of which is to be 
determined. 

The other distinctions, between real and ideal, actual and 
imputed, values show the same desire to remove the equivoca- 
tions inherent in worth predicates. Sometimes we attribute 
worth to an object when we mean that it deserves to be valued 
irrespective of its actual valuation by any person or groups 
of persons. Such value is said to be ideal. Again there 
are objects of valuation, the existence or non-existence, or the 
possibility or probability of realization of which, are not 
inquired into, but which are abstractly valued and said to 
be ideal values in contrast to the real value of objects where 
the judgments of existence or possibility are true or grounded 
judgments. In both cases the real and the ideal values are 
equally functions of the relation of the object to the subject. 
The difference lies in the attitude of the subject, in the different 
presuppositions of the feeling, in the two cases. Confusion of 
meaning arises only when these presuppositions are not made 
explicit. 

The distinction between actual and imputed values, like the 
other distinctions considered, is one which is found not in the 
immediate worth experience itself but which develops when 
the presuppositions of the worth judgment are made explicit 
through reflective analysis. The total worth predicated of an 
object is often seen to have more than one determinant and, 
under certain circumstances, the element in the total value 
corresponding to one subjective determinant will be described as 
actual, while the other element will be described as imputed. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 5 

Thus the elements of a total complex (food for instance) will each 
be said to have its actual value arising from its capacity to 
satisfy separate desires, or to satisfy desire when consumed 
separately. Such worth as an element may get from its com- 
bination with the other elements is said to be, on the other 
hand, an imputed value. In a similar way, when an act of a 
person has value as manifesting a disposition instrumental to the 
fulfillment of social ends, this is described as its actual value, 
while an additional value attributed to it as a part, or manifes- 
tation of the total personality, is described as an imputed value 
over and above the actual value of the act. It is obvious from 
these illustrations that the different moments in the total worth of 
the object have different subjective determinants and that these 
go back to the different objects or aspects of the object upon 
which judgment is directed, to the cognitive presuppositions. 

The selective meanings thus differentiated may be described 
as the existence-meanings oi the worth predicates and, as distin- 
guished from the purely appreciative meanings previously con- 
sidered, represent modifications in worth predication determined 
by differences in cognitive attitude toward the object. The 
necessity of such distinctions arises from the fact that the appre- 
ciative meanings are not wholly independent of the reference to 
reality involved. As simple acts of appreciation, the presuppo- 
sition of existence may not be explicit, and indeed the most primi- 
tive judgments of worth are assertorial — without any condi- 
tional element whatever. But as soon as the question of 
evaluation of the worth predicates themselves is considered, as 
soon as the axiological * problem of the differentiation of subjec- 
tively conditioned values from objectively conditioned, is raised, 
then the presuppositions of reality must be made explicit. 

11. 
From this study of the various selective meanings of the 
worth predicates, it becomes clear that the worth judgments 

' The tenn axiological (constructed on the analogy of the term epistetno- 
logical), is here used to distinguish the problem of validity or evaluation of 
worth predicates from the psychological problem of their description and gene- 
sis. Its value and use become more apparent as the general theory of value 
is developed. 



O WILBUR M. URBAN. 

express not attributes of objects apart from the subject (even 
when the value is described as actual and objective) but rather 
functions of the relation of subject to object. When we speak 
of an object as having absolute or objective value it is only by 
a process of temporary abstraction from the subject in some 
specific attitude, not from the subject itself. The other differ- 
ences of meaning in the worth predicates reflect the same fact. 
Thus when I attribute value to an object, meaning that it is 
actually valued, my attitude is determined by certain presupposi- 
tions of judgments, which are the product of participation in the 
worth judgments of others. When, however, my judgment 
means that the object is ideally of worth, deserves to be valued, 
that judgment expresses a modification of attitude brought about 
either by the exclusion of certain partial determinants of my 
attitude, as when I pass my judgment in opposition to actual 
worth judgments about me, or by inclusion of other presupposi- 
tions, as when, for instance, I appeal from a narrower actual 
worth judgment to a possible more universal judgment. The 
situation is the same in the case of the distinction between actual 
and imputed values. The actual value is always the meaning 
of the object for a subject in some attitude — never an attribute of 
the object itself. The imputed value added to the actual value 
arises from attitudes of the subject, negligible or irrelevant from 
the standpoint from which the actual value is determined. 

Two important consequences follow from this conception that 
worth or value is the meaning of the object for the subject in dif- 
ferent attitudes, or as predetermined by different dispositions and 
interests. In the first place, while the distinctions we have been 
discussing are developed from the axiological standpoint of the 
determination of the relative validity of worth judgments, we 
have in the analysis underlying these distinctions at the same 
time a clue to the psychological analysis and classification of 
the different attitudes. In all these differences of meaning the 
sources of the difference were found in the nature of the cogni- 
tive presuppositions. All valuation, as attitude of the subject, is 
primarily an act of immediate appreciation ; but this primitive 
attitude may be modified to give various meanings by the inclu- 
sion of various types of judgments, existential, instrumental, 



COI^SCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 7 

judgments referring the object of the self or to others, judgments 
of possibility or probability of acquisition and possession , etc. 
While for the axiological point of view the truth of these pre- 
suppositions is significant, for psychological analysis their sig- 
nificance lies in the changes in worth experience, which follow 
upon changes in these presuppositions. 

In the second place, as a result of this conception of worth 
as the affective volitional meaning of the object for the subject 
in different attitudes, the way is now open for an analysis of the 
worth subject and for a classification of the fundamental worth 
attitudes. The equivocations in the meaning of the worth predi- 
cates already considered, indicate certain fundamental differ- 
ences in the subject of the experience. The distinctions between 
subjective and objective worth, between actual and ideal, are 
reducible to differences in the judging subject. These differ- 
ences have led to the conception of different subjects for differ- 
ent types of worth judgments. Thus Kreibig^ distinguishes 
between a primary and secondary worth subject, the primary 
being the individual as such, the secondary being the group or 
race consciousness. So also Meinong,* in treating of the dif- 
ference between ethical and moral judgments distinguishes 
the more personal ethical from the impersonal, moral sub- 
ject. The former is the concrete ego in his relation to the 
alter ; the latter is neither the- ego nor the alter but an abstrac- 
tion, a third person, the impartial spectator which sits in judg- 
ment upon both. These distinctions, appearing as they have 
in the effort to do justice to fundamental differences in worth 
predication, point in the right direction. But they are never- 
theless open to the criticism which attaches to all conceptual 
constructions employed as instruments of analysis, that they are 
in danger of being hypostatized into separate realities and con- 
ceived as real even when abstracted from the individual subject. 
For certain purposes of social and ethical philosophy, we may, 
perhaps, speak of a group consciousness, of an over-individual 

1 Kreibig, Psychologische Grundlegung eines SysUfns der WerUiheot ie^ Wicn, 
1902, p. 5. 

'Meinong, Psycholot[ische-Eihische Untersuchungen zur IVert^hioriet pp. 
72, 163, 216. 



8 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

will, without a serious distortion of the facts, but for the empirical 
analysis of worth judgments it is nearer the truth to say that the 
subject in the r61e of the individual, of the group or race, or of 
the impartial spectator, is the individual in different attitudes. 
The problem is then to account for the origin, differentiation, and 
fixation of these relatively permanent attitudes, and, in the light 
of the preceding discussion, such attitudes of the subject repre- 
sent changes in affective-volitional meaning, as determined by 
changes in cognitive presuppositions (the subject-matter). 

The worth judgment of an individual may then express the 
affective-volitional meaning of an object for the subject, as 
qualified by the subjects (a) participation in, and {b) explicit 
cognition of, the worth attitudes of others, of single persons, of 
social groups, or perhaps of an over-individual worth conscious- 
ness which transcends even group distinctions, giving the im- 
personal attitude of the * impartial spectator.' The difference 
in attitude is determined by the inclusion or exclusion of judg- 
ments as part presuppositions of the meaning. The psycho- 
logical problem is the tracing of the processes by which this 
participation in, and cognition of, the attitudes of others is real- 
ized, the more specific problem of worth analysis itself being to 
determine how this modification of the attitude of the subject 
modifies the worth predicated of the object. 

In a preliminary way we may distinguish three fundamental 
attitudes of the self or subject of worth judgment : (i) Simple 
appreciation of the affective-volitional meaning of an object for 
the self ; (2) the personal attitude in which the worth of the 
object is determined by explicit reference of the object, whether 
a physical possession or a psychical disposition, to the self or 
the alter, and in which characterization of the self or the alter 
is presupposed, and (3) the impersonal attitude, in which the 
subject of the judgment is identified with an impersonal over- 
individual subject and the value of the object is determined by 
explicit reference to the over-individual demand.* 

^This classification corresponds in principle with Baldwin's classification 
of cognitive meanings in the first volume of his Genetic Logic, Chap. VII., p. 
148, where he distinguishes : (i) Simple and private ; (2) aggregate and con- 
aggregate ; (3) social and public, meanings. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 9 

As the subject of value experience, one of the moments in 
. the value function, is constantly changing, expanding and con- 
tracting through inclusion and exclusion of presuppositions of 
judgment, so also the object of valuation undergoes modifica- 
tion. Broadly speaking, the object of worth belongs to the pres- 
entational side of consciousness, is the object of immediate ap- 
prehension with its implicit presupposition or explicit judgment 
of existence. It is, therefore, in the first place, the not-self the 
external object of feeling and will, those aspects of experience 
which are from the beginning presentational. But there is 
scarcely any aspect of consciousness which cannot become pres- 
entational, cannot be presented to consciousness as object, and 
become the object of judgment. Even the attitude of valuation 
itself which we may describe as the * psychical ' preeminently, 
is susceptible of representation, translation into ideal terms and 
of thus taking its place on the objective side of the value 
function.* The psychology of this representation of the psy- 
chical will engage our attention at those points where we shall 
make use of the principle. Here it is merely important to in- 
sist that the general class, worth objects, includes physical and 
psychical and, among the latter, the attitude of valuation itself. 
A more significant distinction among objects of valuation is 
that between primary and secondary or between simple and 
founded objects already considered. These founded objects 
may be of two kinds, according as they are founded in proc- 
esses of perceptual or ideational activity. Illustrations of the 
former are : (a) Beauty or grace of form in objects of percep- 
tion ; {ft) founded qualities acquired in the sensational and per- 
ceptual activities of consumption of food (or more broadly of 
various instinctive activities), such as cleanliness, manners. Any 
harmonious grouping or arrangement of the activities of living 
creates secondary objects of worth, founded upon the primary. 
As illustrations of the secondary worth objects founded in proc- 
esses of ideation and judgment, we may take the ^person and 

1 At was pointed out in another article, Appreciation and Description and 
the Psychology of Values^ Philosophical Review, November, 1905, the capacity 
of feeling attitude of becoming the object of presentation and jadgment is the 
condition of there being appreciative d^cription and communication of attitudes. 



lO WILBUR M. URBAN. 

his affective or conative dispositions built up conceptually on the 
basis of immediate appreciations, as in sympathetic Einfuhlung^ 
or by a process of inference, which, then in turn, become the 
objects of secondary judgments of merit and demerit, etc. To 
these may be added a third group of founded worth objects 
which may be described as over-individual. These are the 
products of the ideal reconstruction of objects of primary worth 
as determined by participation in the worth processes of larger 
social groups or of society at large. To this class belong the 
ideal moral and culture goods of society, economic goods as 
objects of exchange, including the medium of exchange which 
has over-individual worth exclusively. In distinguishing thus 
between founded objects as products of perceptual and ideational 
activities, we cannot of course make the distinction absolute, for 
in the case of many such objects both activities have been at 
work in their construction. 

A preliminary classification of worth objects would then 
include the following groups : (i) Objects of simple apprecia- 
tion or of condition worth. These objects may be either phys- 
ical or psychical and include the founded psychical objects built 
up in perceptual activity. (2) Objects of personal worth such 
as qualities and dispositions of the person (the self or the alter) 
objects founded in the processes of characterization of the person. 
(3) Objects of over-individual or common worth founded in 
processes of social participation, ideal constructions developed 
in the interest of social participation, utilization and exchange 
of objects. In general these objects of worth correspond to the 
fundamental attitudes of the subject of the value experience. 

III. 
The analysis of the meanings of worth predicates, and the 
consequent differentiation and classification .of the fundamental 
types of the subject and object of the judgment of value, bring 
us to a third problem of analysis, namely a more definite char- 
acterization of the term affective-volitional meaning and an 
analysis and classification of the modes of consciousness corre- 
sponding to these meanings. As long as we were concerned 
merely with a preliminary differentiation of cognitive meaning 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. H 

from that aspect of meaning described as worth or value, it was 
sufficient to describe the latter as a meaning predetermined by 
processes of feeling and conation and the judgment of value as 
an appreciation or acknowledgment of that funded meaning. 
But when this criterion is examined more closely and the attempt 
is made to determine more precisely just what aspect of meaning 
is represented by the different types of worth judgment (appre- 
ciation, characterization, participation and utilization) just what' 
the determining processes of feeling and conation are in each 
case, more detailed psychological analysis becomes necessary. 

When we seek to make more specific this very general 
description of the worth relation we are confronted with two 
possible views of the worth moment which may be described 
as a broader and a narrower view. The narrower view recog- 
nizes only two types of value judgment, the ethical and economic, 
thereby limiting the term value to such feeling attitudes as 
follow upon the judgmental affirmation of the existence or non- 
existence as an object for the self or its purposes. This limitation 
denies, therefore, the character of worth attitude to all immediate 
feeling of the meaning of the object for the subject prior to the 
distinctions which we describe as economic and ethical, and 
likewise to all forms of higher immediacy of feeling attitude as 
we have them primarily in the aesthetic consciousness. This 
view, which has been presented most definitely by Witasek ^ and 
Stuart,' logically excludes the aesthetic from the sphere of values, 
in the view of the former because the aesthetic is pre-judgmental, 
I. ^., is feeling which has merely presentations as its content, 
for the latter because he conceives it to be post-judgmental, an 
appreciative state where all judgment subject-matter has lapsed. 
Either mode of cutting the aesthetic attitude off from its closely 
related ethical and economic attitudes is, we shall find, open to 
serious criticism and must necessarily discredit this limitation of 
the term value. 

The reasoning which underlies this the formulation of this 
criterion is well expressed by Stuart in the following paragraph : 

^ Witasek, AUgetneine ^stheiik, Leipzig, 1904. 

* Stuart, ValuaHon as a Logical Process, in Dewey 'a Studies in Logical 
Theory, Chicago, 1903. 



la WILBUR Af. URBAN. 



} 



•' Our general criterion for the propriety of terming any mode 
of consciousness the value of an object must be that it shall per- 
form a logical function and not simply be referred to in its 
aspect of psychical fact. The feeling or emotion, or whatever 
the mode of consciousness in question may be, must play the 
recognized part, in the agent's survey of the situation, of 
prompting and supporting a definite practical attitude with ref- 
erence to the object. If, in short, the experience enters in any 
way into a conscious purpose of the agent, it may properly be 
termed a value." Now, in examining this criterion one recog- 
nizes immediately that it provides a good definition of a certain 
type of reflective value judgments which we may call sec- 
ondary. A ver\^ large group of our worth judgments are de- 
termined by the conscious (recognized) inclusion of the worth 
feeling or emotion as presented content, as partial determinant 
of the judgment. The typical economic judgment takes place 
only upon the occasion of adding to or taking from our store of 
objects and is motived by a reflective inclusion of the worth 
feeling in our tola! practical attitude. The ethical judgment, in 
its typical reflective form, may be shown to be of the same char- 
acter in that the subject's own mode of experience, way of 
feelings presented in terms of disposition or quality of the self, 
enters as a determinant in the total situation. But the sec- 
ondar>' and derived character of these reflective judgments 
soon becomes evident. How can the feeling or emotion as 
presented content. * play a recognized part' as a value • in the 
agents survey of ihe situation * unless, as a moUve to previous 
unrefleciive judgments, before it was presented as a conscious 
determinant, it was also a value or at least value-suggestive. 
We may say, then, that, while much of valuation is a logical 
process in this sense, nevertheless valuation has its roots in 
expenences of simple appreciation where the emotion, while 
determinative, is not so consciously, as object of presenUtion or 
}iidgment and must, therefore, be referred to simply in its aspect 
of psychical fact. 

We muist, accordingly, interpret our definition of value as 
iffecine-vohtional meaning in the broader way already suff- 
gcled, so as to include modes of consciousness, of feeling (or 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 13 

desire) which are merely appreciative of the object, which 
merely apprehend the object with its funded meaning. We 
cannot confine it to attitudes in which this meaning, abstracted 
from the object, becomes a motive in the subject's survey of the 
situation. We shall then be enabled to include both the attitudes 
of lower immediacy, which are pre-judgmental, and those of 
higher immediacy, which are post-judgmental, recognizing the 
intermediate r61e of the reflective judgments (existential, instru- 
mental, possessive, etc.), and recognizing also that the reflective 
and the unreflective, the intrinsic and the instrumental, are con- 
stantly passing over into each other, a phenomenon which we 
shall later describe as value-movement. 

In close relation to this first problem which arises in the 
attempt to make more specific the general definition of worth as 
affective volitional meaning, a second problem arises, namely, 
the question of the specific manner in which we shall set the 
worth moment in relation to its psychological equivalents, feeling 
and conation. Already, in the use of the double term affective" 
"volitional in our preliminary demarcation of worth experience, 
a certain vagueness inheres, which, while excusable when 
viewed in the light of the purpose of the term, must give place 
to explicit psychological analysis if we are to find equivalents 
for the worth moment which shall form the basis for a scientific 
reconstruction of the processes of valuation. The significance 
of this double term lay in the fact that it marked off a species 
under the generic term, meaning. Not that there could be cog- 
nitive meaning without worth references or affective-volitional 
meaning without cognitive presuppositions. Indeed, we shall 
see that these terms are not very clear at the limits. Merely to 
indicate a relative distinction, by means of emphasis of different 
aspects of meaning, was the purpose of this differentiation. 

In the second place, the double term was necessary for the 
reason that only in such a definition could all the attitudes 
toward objects, recognized as worth attitudes, be included. 
For our ordinary usage, at least, makes a clear distinction be- 
tween feeling and will and recognizes, as objects of worth, objects 
upon which both types of attitude are directed, and, prior to more 
scientific analysis, this double relation must be taken as descrip- 



14 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

tive of the worth attitude. But here again, when this general 
definition gives place to psychological analysis, we find that the 
distinction between feeling and conation in some of its forms is 
not very clear at the limits, and it is consequently difiiicult to say 
under which of these terms the immediate experience which is 
the bearer of these meanings, is to be subsumed. On the one 
hand, we find experiences of preference and obligation where 
feeling, if it is described as passive pleasantness and unpleas- 
antness is at a minimum, is scarcely present, or, if present at 
all, is irrelevant, so irrelevant in fact that some theories of worth 
experience (the voluntaristic theories of Brentano and Schwartz) 
find the psychological fundamental in what they describe as 
* intensitiless acts of preference,' denying the worth moment to 
feeling and its intensities. On the other hand, we find worth 
experiences, such as the aesthetic, apparently purely affective, 
where desire, conation in all its forms is at a minimum, and ap- 
pears to be significant, if significant at all, merely as a disposi- 
tion or presupposition. While,. then, in view of these facts the 
general term affective-volitional meaning was necessary to define 
the various meanings of objects included under the term values, 
it is nevertheless evident that the definition can become service- 
able for further psychological analysis and explanation only 
when it is determined which of these moments, the affective or 
conative, is primary and which secondary — that is, which is 
always present actually as conscious experience and which as a 
merely dispositional determinant. But if our general definition 
is to hold, in every attitude which we describe as a mode of 
worth experience both aspects of experience must be present 
either actually or germinally. 

In the light then of these considerations, it would appear 
that the course of our further analysis is clearly and necessarily 
determined. We are compelled, on the one hand, to include 
both concepts, of feeling and conation, in our psychological 
equivalents for the worth moment ; otherwise we should not have 
a true equivalent for the funded meaning of the object described 
as worth. On the other hand, when from the standpoint of the 
analysis of content we look for an experience which shall be a 
common equivalent for all phases of worth determination, one 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 15 

of these moments must assume the role of actual experience and 
the other of dispositional presupposition. One must constitute 
the worth fundamental. Is then the worth fundamental feeling 
or desire? 

In the second place whichever of these two aspects be taken 
as fundamental, a second question necessarily arises — is worth 
coextensive with feeling or desire, or is there a further demar- 
cation within the sphere of feeling or desire, respectively? .In 
other words, have all feelings or desires, whatever their condi- 
tions, however fleeting and however caused, the transgredient 
and immanental references which characterize the worth attitude 
of the subject toward the object ? 

IV. 

Both of these problems have been in the forefront of recent 
psychological analysis of worth experience. They are questions 
which are forced upon the attention as soon as we attempt to 
coordinate and reduce to common t^rms the varying attitudes 
which have been included under worth experience, within the 
worth definition. It is true that there is a point of view from 
which these finer distinctions are irrelevant. One can see that 
for the limited purposes of economic analysis, which requires 
but a short excursion into psychology, we might speak of the 
worth moment now as feeling, and now as desire. Ehrenfels 
is also probably right in saying that the general laws of valua- 
tion and the forms of mutation of values, value movement, hold 
true whether we define worth experience as feeling or desire, 
and changes in judgments of value as due to modifications of 
feeling or desire. It remains true, nevertheless, that a complete 
analysis of the worth consciousness, in all its phases, requires the 
solution of both these problems. 

It is in connection with the first problem that the first diver- 
gence in definition appears, as typified in the different formula- 
tions of Meinong and £hrenfels. Ehrenfels defines the worth 
of an object as its desirability and makes actual desire the worth 
fundamental, assigning to feeling the conceptual, dispositional 
r61e, while Meinong, on the other hand, identifies actual worth 
experience with feeling, desire appearing in his definition only 



l6 WILBUR M. URBAN, 

as presupposed disposition. In some sensi^, we have seen, both 
terms, feeling and conation, must enter into our psychological 
definition ; the question is which shall be given the r61e of fun- 
damental, actual experience and which the dispositional r61e. 

Ehrenfels ^ takes desire as the actual psychological worth 
fundamental. Value, we are told, is proportional to the desira- 
bility of the object — and he continues, as though it were self- 
evident, — * i. e.y to the strength of the actual desire which cor- 
responds to it.' The first part of the definition is certainly true. 
The funded meaning of an object is its desirability, its capacity 
under certain circumstances of calling out desire. The second 
part does not, however, necessarily follow. It does not follow 
either that judgments of worth are determined by actual desire, 
or that the worth of the object is proportional to the strength of 
the actual desire. As to the identification of value or desira- 
bility with actual desire, a consideration of certain simple but 
typical worth experiences, indicates that it is not exclusively an 
actual, but, ultimately, merely a possible desire or desire disposi- 
tion with which worth is to be equated, a modification of his 
earlier definition which Ehrenfels himself accepts. When I 
think of an absent friend I may feel his worth to me without the 
slightest trace of actual desire for his immediate presence, al- 
though the presupposition of that feeling is a desire disposition. 
Or again my consciousness of the objective value of objects of 
economic use may be independent of any actual desire, although 
not of my cognition of their desirableness under certain circum- 
stances. It is equally true that the degree of worth or desirability 
of an object cannot be straightway identified with the degree of 
actual desire. It is undoubtedly proportional to the strength of 
desire disposition presupposed, but the strength of a conative ten- 
dency or disposition is not measured by the intensity of actual 
desire but is inferred indirectly from its effects in volition, or 
through the intensity of the emotional disturbance following upon 
arrest. The assumption that the strength of a desire disposition is 
given directly in immediate modifications of consciousness is one 
which introspection makes highly improbable and Ehrenfels, 

> Ehrenfels, System der Wert-theorie^ Leipzig, 1897, Vol. I., Chap. I., 
especially p. 35. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, ij 

with whose definitioir we are here concerned, at least does not 
admit it. 

It is clear, then, that while desire, and conative tendency in 
general, must find a place in our worth definition, it cannot be 
taken as the psychological fundamental in the sense that it is 
the conscious correlate of the funded meaning of the object. 
This conscious correlate is feeling. Ehrenfels thus brings feel- 
into his definition Desire is not determined by mystical quali- 
ties of objects but by aspects of our consciousness which can be 
reduced to psychological terms. "All acts of desire are deter- 
mined, in regard to their direction as well as their strength, by 
the relative increase of pleasure which they, according to the 
affective dispositions of the individual in question, bring with 
them upon their entrance into, or continuance in, consciousness." 
Feeling is, therefore, after all, primary. The worth of an ob- 
ject is directly proportional to the strength of desire, but this 
strength of desire is determined by the difference between the 
places of the object in the hedonic scale. 

In this conception of Ehrenfels the whole psychological 
problem of the nature of feeling and desire and of their rela- 
tions, is involved. Into that larger question we cannot here 
enter. It will be sufficient to notice certain fundamental diffi- 
culties which have been generally recognized by the critics of 
the position. The criticism turns upon the concept of the deter- 
mination of desire by feeling, upon the idea of the causal rela- 
tion involved. It is maintained with justification that for a feel- 
ing to be a cause of desire it must be actual, that is a present 
state of consciousness. But according to Ehrenfels' conception 
it is not merely a present state, but a state which does not yet 
exist, which is the cause. It is the existence of an object not 
yet realized or the non-existence of a present object, which is 
desired. The hedonic accompaniment of a not-yet existent 
object, itself therefore not existent, cannot in any causal sense 
be the determinant of desire. But it may be said that it is the 
difference of these two states that is the cause. In that case it 
* must be either the unfelt, uncognized difference, an abstraction, 
which is the cause, or else a new feeling following upon the 
judgment of the difference between the actual present feeling 



l8 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

and an imagined feeling arising from the assumption of the 
existence or non-existence of the object. In the first case we 
have a conceptual abstraction made the cause — which is impos- 
sible. In the second case a feeling difference has become the 
object of judgment and a value moment is already present prior 
to desire. It is clear that in some sense feeling or feeling dis- 
position is always presupposed by desire but the relation cannot 
be described as causal. 

Ehrenfels recognizes that upon this causal view of the rela- 
tion of feeling to desire, the proposition must be modified to read : 
desire is determined by feeling or feeling dispositions. But we 
have already seen that worth cannot, in every case be identified 
with actual desire, but only with the capacity of being desired, 
desirability. Thus Ehrenfels is finally left without any conscious 
correlate for the worth moment. Both the feeling and conative 
aspects tend to become dispositional. 

For reasons of the nature of those developed in our criticism 
of Ehrenfels' worth definition, Meinong^ makes feeling the worth 
fundamental. The sense of worth is given in feeling signs, 
Werth-gefiihle, which are determined in character and degree by 
the nature of their presuppositions (Voraussetzungen).* These 
presuppositions he further conceives, in the case of worth feel- 
ings, to be always judgments (or according to his later formula- 
tion, judgments and assumptions — Annahmen) and are there- 
fore distinguishable from feelings which have merely sensations 
or presentations as their presuppositions. With this limitation 
of worth feelings we are not now concerned ; for the present 
our problem is the more general one of the suitability of feeling 
as the worth fundamental — as the psychological equivalent for 
the worth moment. The preferability of feeling as our descrip- 
tion of the worth fundamental seems to me to be beyond doubt 
and for the following reasons. In general our argument would 

^Meinoog, Psychologische-Ethische Unterstuhungen^ Part I., Chap. I. 

' In presentini; Meinong's position I have translated Voraussetznng * pre- 
supposition' rather than precondition, as better adapted to convey his meaning, 
and have retained this broader nsage of presupposition throughout, although in 
the usage of Baldwin it is confined to the higher reflective level, if I understand 
his position correctly, that is, his presupposition is always a ' presupposition of 
belief.* 



CONSCIOC/SNSSS OF VALUE, 19 

be : There can be no sense of worth without a meaning which 
may properly be described as felt meaning, while there can 
very well be a sense of worth without that qualification which 
we describe as desire and volition. 

More specifically, even in those experiences which we 
describe as explicit desire or volition, the essence of the desire 
can be equally well described in terms of feeling without doing 
violence to our speech. The essence of desire is the feeling of 
lack or want. We ^feel the need ' of something. What further 
qualifies desire is the kinaesthetic sensations which are irrelevant 
accompaniments from the standpoint of the essential worth 
moment. But it is by no means in the same sense true that 
every worth experience involves explicit desire. We may 
actually feel the worth of an absent friend without the slightest 
trace of that qualification of our feeling which we describe as 
actual desire, although of course a conative disposition is pre- 
supposed and may become explicit under suitable conditions. 
The same is true of aesthetic and mystical states of repose where 
actual desire is in abeyance. 

What this means for our worth definition is clear. In actual 
worth experience actual desire is not necessarily present although 
feeling is. The desire is present often merely as a dispositional 
moment which, however, may become actual under certain 
definite circumstances. In so far, therefore, as our definition is 
concerned with the desire moment, we must enlarge it to read — 
an object has worth in so far as it is either desired or has the 
capacity of calling out desire, has, in other words desirability. 
This definition includes the mystical and aesthetic states of 
repose already referred to, for no object can become the object 
of such feelings which has not been desired and may not under 
some circumstances be again desired. Conation is present dis- 
positionally (how we shall see later) even in these states of 
repose. But the case is different with feeling. In defining 
worth as feeling with certain characteristic presuppositions we 
mean that every actual worth judgment implies actual feeling 
— even in those cases where the worth attitude is scarcely dis- 
tinguishable from the cognitive. 

Feeling having been taken as the actual conscious corre- 



20 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

Igte of worth predicate^, the second problem arises — whether 
worth feelings are coextensive with feelings in general or 
whether some further differentiation appears within the general 
class feeling. It is at this point that the definition of Meinong, 
the view that feelings of worth are exclusively * judgment-feel- 
ings,' becomes important. This view, which may be described 
as the intellectualistic theory of worth experience, has given rise 
to so many important developments in ethics and aesthetics that 
it demands the most careful consideration. Negatively viewed, 
it denies the character of worth experience to all feelings which 
have as their presuppositions mere presentations, to all feelings 
which may be adequately described as the mere feeling tone of 
the presentation or as the effect of the entrance of the presenta- 
tion into conscioususness. It differentiates * worth feeling ' from 
mere * pleasure-causation,' e. g,^ pleasure viewed as mere reac- 
tion to stimulus. 

Before considering in detail the psychological grounds for 
this view, it will be well to observe the more general fact that 
whether worth experience be defined in terms of desire or feel- 
ing, it cannot be made coextensive with either. Desire, in itself, 
does not constitute the experience of valuation : there are fleet- 
ing desires which do not attain to the level of valuation, a fact 
which leads Kruger in his definition, which is in terms of desire, 
to make the differentia of worth a certain constancy of desire. 
Again, as Meinong points out, illustrations are plentiful of valu- 
ation without actual consciousness of pleasure, while a fleeting 
pleasure does not necessarily involve valuation. Reflection 
upon these facts of experience leads to more strictly logical 
considerations such as those which appeared in our criticism of 
Ehrenfels' definition. The sense of value cannot be identified 
the mere feeling of pleasure (although of course a feeling of 
with pleasure when it is made the object of judgment may become 
a value) for the feeling of value is conditioned not only by the 
presence of objects but also by their absence. The mere absence 
of the object is not the condition of the feeling, but the cogni- 
zance (in Meinong's terms the judgment) of non-existence. 
The hedonic state which would be the effect of the presence of 
the absent object is not actual, and can therefore not be, in any 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 21 

causal sense, the condition of the desire and of valuation. 
Moreover, the cause of the pleasure is often quite distinct from 
the object of the feeling of value, often physiological and uncon- 
scious. The feeling of value can therefore not be viewed as 
the effect or accompaniment of sensation or presentation of an 
object but is conditioned by the presupposition of the existence of 
the object. For the feeling to have that meaning called worth 
it must have an existence meaning. 

The negative aspect of Meinong's position, the denial of the 
character of worth experience to mere presentation feelings, 
appears justified from this analysis of the facts. A funda- 
mental distinction seems to exist between feeling which is a 
mere feeling tone, accompaniment or effect, of a sensation or 
revived image, and feeling attitude which is characterized by 
the direction of the feeling toward the object. Feeling attitudes 
alone seem to contain the worth moment. It is undoubtedly true 
that feeling tone of presentation, when it reaches a certain degree 
of intensity, gives rise to a feeling attitude, to the presentation 
of the cause as object and the direction of judgment upon it, 
and thus to feeling of worth. But this feeling (or desire, as the 
case may be) is distinguished from the feeling tone by the pres- 
ence of additional presuppositions, whether exclusively judg- 
mental or not, is a question to be determined. 

A critical consideration of this positive aspect of Meinong's 
definition requires a closer examination of his use of the term 
presupposition (Voraussetzung). Under this concept he includes 
all those conditions of feeling which are psychical in character, 
as distinguished from other causes of feeling which may be dis- 
positional and physiological. In this sense a presupposition 
may be any psychical process, presentation, judgment (of the 
various types, categorical, hypothetical, etc.) and other types of 
function, perhaps, such as assumption. In every case where 
the presupposition of a feeling is spoken of, the feeling is di- 
rected upon an object and is conditioned by some psychical act, 
of presentation, of imagination, with its assumption of reality, 
or of judgment, judgment being for Meinong a fundamental 
form of psychical process. The significance of this distinction 
is to be found in the fact that the characteristic meanings of 



22 WILBUR Af. URBAN, 

feelings which distinguish them as feelings of value, are not to 
be differentiated in terms merely of the objects toward which 
the feeling is directed, nor yet in terms of the causes of the 
feeling, but in terms of the cognitive acts or attitudes which 
relate the object to the subject. 

V. 

Is then the presupposition of worth feeling exclusively judg- 
mental, as Meinong maintains? To this question our answer 
must be negative. But we may admit, to begin with, that 
nearly all types of worth attitude do have existential judgments 
as presuppositions, and all secondary modifications of worth 
attitude are determined by the inclusion or exclusion of judg- 
ments, existential and relational, as part presuppositions of 
the feeling. But that there is no primary immediate con- 
sciousness of value without explicit judgment of existence or 
non-existence of the object, cannot be maintained. As was 
pointed out in our discussion of the equivocations in the worth 
predicates, ideal and imputed values may be attributed to ob- 
jects when the question whether they exist or may be acquired 
is not raised, and where, accordingly, the attitude can never 
reach the point of explicit judgment. The activities of imag- 
ination and idealization abundantly prove that the feelings di- 
rected upon their objects are really feelings of worth and are 
determinative of worth judgments, although they presuppose 
mere passing assumptions of the reality of the objects. 

Meinong has indeed found himself compelled upon further 
reflection to modify his definition of worth feelings as judgment 
feelings to the extent that he includes with the judgment feelings 
assumption feelings (Annahme-gefiihle). He recognizes that 
* often one values an object at a time when there is entirely 
wanting all chance for judgments of existence and non-exist- 
ence, because it is not determined yet whether the object 
thought of as in the future will exist or not.' Moreover, * it is 
possible, and it frequently happens that we value an abstractly 
presented object without inquiring after its existence.^ And in 

» Meinong, " C/der Werthalten und Wert,'' Arckiv fur Systetnatisdie mios- 
ophicy 1895, pp. 327-346. Also his later work, Uber Annahmen. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 23 

a later paper ^ he further qualifies his position by recognizing 
that it is only some universe of reality which is necessarily pre- 
supposed, in that the presuppositions are not necessarily cate- 
gorical existential judgments, but may be hypothetical or dis- 
junctive. Now in all these cases where the object is • abstractly 
presented,' assumed to exist, or asserted to exist conditionally, 
reality is presupposed in some sense, there is some reference to 
reality. It is also clear that in all these cases the feeling, char- 
acterized as feeling of value, is in some way differently qual- 
ified from the feeling of pleasantness or unpleasantness — by 
this very reference to reality presupposed. The question at 
issue is really merely as to the proper characterization of the 
reality meaning, whether it rests exclusively upon existential 
judgment or not. 

And this question is still more ultimately conditioned by a 
theory of the existential judgment. To this theoretical problem 
we shall presently turn, but it will be in the interests of clear- 
ness to seek a preliminary characterization of this presupposi- 
tion of reality. There can be no question, in the first place, 
that wherever there is the feeling of value, there is reality feel- 
ing. Feeling is qualified by a reality meaning of some type. 
Thus, when once an object (the existence of which was what I 
desired or was what conditioned my feeling of value) is explic- 
itly judged non-existent, the object undoubtedly loses its value 
for me. The essential condition of its being valued is elimi- 
nated. But my appreciation of the worth of an object does not 
necessarily, and in every case, rest upon such explicit judgment 
of existence, but at most upon a primary undisturbed fresum^p^ 
Hon of reality. By this primary presumption of reality (of a 
reality, moreover, in which the more specific existence mean- 
ing has not yet been differentiated) is to be understood the 
mere act of acceptance, taking for granted^ prior to the ex- 

1 " Urtheihgefuhle^ was Sie sind und was Sie nichi sind,'' Archiv fur die 
gesammte Psychologie, Vol. VI., 1905. 

' The nse of the term presumption to characterize this relation to reality is, 
I think, fnlly justified both linguistically and psychologically. Our ordinary 
speech, it is true, frequently fails to distinguish between presumption and as- 
sumption and has, moreover, read into the word presumption a certain ethical 
connotation which partially unfits it for the present use. On the other hand, 



34 WILBUR M. URBAN, 

pHcit taking uf of the object into a pre-determined sphere of 
reality through the existence predicate, and prior to the assump- 
tion of existence of an object in the interest of continuity of any 
trend of activity, whether of the type of cognition or valuation. 

As illustrative of this attitude of primitive presumption we 
may consider first the reality feeling which attaches to percep- 
tion and presentation simply because of the * recognitive mean- 
ing ' ' which they have, among which later, however, distinc- 
tions between existent and non-existent arise — more especially 
the presentations in the fancy or imagination mode where they 
are presumed to be real until the entrance of illusion-disturbing 
moments which require the presumption to pass over into ex- 
plicit judgment and conviction either of existence or non-exist- 
ence. The fairy world of the child is a world neither of pure 
presentation nor of existential judgment but of presumption. 
The same may be said of many ideals of the more developed 
mind, as for instance, religious, about which questions of ex- 
istence and non-existence are not seriously asked. In all these 
cases some psychically pre-determined demand^ whether arising 
from a more objective cognitive factor of recognition or a more 
subjective factor of conative disposition or interest, creates a 
presumption of reality. 

Such presumption must be carefully distinguished from both 
judgment and assumption. The existential judgment arises, 
we shall see, only after disturbance in a sphere of reality 
already presupposed, it is an act which takes place only after 
some disposition, some tendency to recognition, or to renewal 
of attitude of feeling or will meets with opposition or arrest. It 

the original meaning of the latin praesumptio is much nearer to the use that we 
have in mind — it had more the meaning of taking for granted prior to ex- 
plicit judgment and was qaite different from the conscious assumption of re- 
ality as we have it in hypothesis. The modem Bnglish dictionaries give as one 
of the renderings, taking for granted^ the meaning here emphasized. The use 
of the term in formal logic (as in fallacies of presumption), while at first appa- 
rently against our usage, on closer inspection seems to favor it. A presumption 
is a material fallacy, an unconsciously pre-logical taking for granted. Finally, 
the great value of the introduction of this term for our immediate purpose is 
the possibility of using the prefixes prcBy svb and ab^ with the same root, to 
designate modifications of cognitive attitude. 
1 Baldwin's distinction referred to above. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 2$ 

must be equally clearly distinguished from the later, more de- 
rived, attitude of assumption of existence which presupposes dis- 
positions already created by actual judgment. The assumption, 
except when it is what we describe as an unconscious assump- 
tion, (and then it is really an approximation to presumption) 
recognizes the possibility of the non-existence of the object, and 
in some modes of playful assumption (the ' semblant modes ' 
of Professor Baldwin) is so to speak on the verge of explicit 
judgment of non-existence ; but in the making of the assumption 
the act is determined by a subjective factor, a demand arising 
from already existing dispositions and interests. The assump- 
tion is an acknowledgment of this demand. 

It is obvious, after this analysis, that the definition of feel- 
ing of value under consideration, that it is feeling with existen- 
tial judgment as its presupposition, is possible only on the 
theory that the primitive form of judgment is the mere act of 
acceptance (acknowledgment) or rejection^ and involves no 
relational aspect, no separation of two elements subject and 
predicate. The existential judgment is identical with accept- 
ance and the non-existential with rejection. If this view of 
judgment (Brentano's)^ can be maintained it follows necessarily 
that there can be no feeling of value without judgment presup- 
position for all attitude is primarily acceptance or rejection and 
the feeling of value is an attiiudey not mere presentation plus 
feeling. But can mere acceptance or rejection be identified 
with judgment of existence and non-existence and at the same 
time any useful conception of judgment be retained ? I think 
not, and for the following reasons. 

The essentials of the view here under consideration are : (a) 

1 The use of the terma acknowUdgfneni and rejection as correlative ia most 
unfortunate, for it prejudices the whole question. Rejection, as any one who 
will consult the dictionaries will discover, is not the opposite of acknowledg- 
ment/ Acknowledgment has as its opposite disavowal, while the opposite 
of rejection is acceptance. This linguistic relation corresponds precisely to the 
psychological. Acknowledgment and disavowal both represent the explicit 
judgmental acts by which a reality already presupposed is affirmed or denied. 
Mere acceptance or rejection of an object presupposes nothing more than a 
presumption of reality or disturbance of that presumption. 

* For a presentation and discussion of Brentano's theory of judgment see 
Stout, Analytical Psychology^ Vol. I., Chap. 5. 



26 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

That presentation and judgment (acceptance or rejection of 
the existence of the presentation) are two different and irre- 
ducible elementary aspects of consciousness ; {V) that while the 
affirmation or negation of A (as function) adds something to its 
mere presentation (as function), the affirmation or negation of 
A^ existence (as content) adds nothing to the affirmation or 
negation of A (as content). The first thesis is the key to the 
position. Is there such a thing as simple apprehension, pre- 
sentation without acceptance, or does apprehension involve 
apprehension of existence? At first sight the former of the 
two possible alternatives seems to be true. From the stand- 
point of analysis alone, we seem to find cases where the element 
of affirmation is at a minimum, or even seems to be entirely 
lacking, and a merely presentational consciousness remains. 
Leaving out of account the case of doubt or suspended judg- 
ment where, although at a minimum, tendencies to judgment 
still remain, we may turn immediately to the typical case of 
aesthetic contemplation. Here it is said, we have, when the 
contemplation is pure, when the aesthetic is unmixed with other 
factors, a strictly presentational consciousness. This view we 
shall find it necessary to reject and for the following reasons : 
In the first place, aesthetic contemplation is an attitude — not 
mere presentation ; in it there is at least a resting in, * ein Haften 
an der Wirklichkeit,* either outer or inner reality. As such it 
is more than mere presentation. No total concrete state of 
consciousness is mere presentation for, while for the purposes 
of the psychologist the idea of a purely presentational con- 
sciousness is sometimes a useful abstraction, every actual ex- 
perience presupposes a minimum of acceptance or rejection. 
The procedure therefore which takes this abstraction, made for 
purposes of analysis, as a picture of reality and from it infers, 
for instance, the unreality of the aesthetic object and experience 
and its exclusion from the sphere of worth experience, is 
vitiated by serious fallacy. 

But if the merely presentational consciousness be but an ab- 
straction, there still remains the question — to what extent, in 
actual concrete cases of aesthetic attitude, all acceptance and re- 
jection may be seen to be excluded and the purely presentational 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 27 

approached. Perhaps the difference is negligible. Most aesthetic 
attitudes, it is recognized by all, do not give us this contempla- 
tion pure. In the sublime and tragic, for instance, pseudo-sesthetic 
factors, so called, enter in, in the form of acknowledgments and 
rejections, judgments of various kinds, — and even beauty, in its 
narrower sense, contains, as partial moments, normative judg- 
ments. If we are to find any concrete aesthetic experience 
of ^pure contemplation,' presentation, it must be in the simplest 
perceptual forms and form qualities. These are indeed usually 
taken as the typical aesthetic objects when the aesthetic is thus 
defined, but even here it is doubtful whether the element of 
acceptance and rejection, of conation, can be excluded. It is 
true that these forms and form qualities, when abstracted from 
the elements in which they inhere, may be viewed as the objects 
of purely presentational activity ; nevertheless their construction 
was the product of conative activity which involved spontaneous 
acceptance and rejection, presumption of reality. Viewed genet- 
ically, every aesthetic feeling of form presupposes a disposition 
created by preceding conative activity. 

The distinction between simple apprehension and accep- 
tance is then, even in aesthetic contemplation, a relative one. 
What shall be said of the second part of the thesis that accep- 
tance or rejection of an object, A^ is identical with the aSirma- 
tion or negation of the existence of Ay or, in other words, with 
judgment? Acknowledgment or rejection does undoubtedly 
presuppose the reality, in some sense of the presentational con- 
tent. This is the same as saying that all conation is directed 
upon objects presumed to be real. It does not follow however, 
that explicit existential* judgment is involved. We must, I 
think, look upon the existential judgment as derived from a 
simpler and more ultimate attitude toward a coefiScient of reality 
presupposed in all conation, even on the perceptual level. 
Acknowledgment and rejection involves presumption of exist- 
ence but not necessarily judgment. 

Such a distinction between presumption and judgment in- 
volves of course a theory of the nature of judgment. Into the 
logical questions here raised we cannot go in detail, but this 
much at least may be said. The position maintained by Sig- 



28 WILBUR Af. URBAN. 

wart ^ (among other logicians) that judgment, if our conception 
of it is to retain any useful significance, ^ must be regarded as 
establishing a relation, even in its existential form/ seems unas- 
sailable. When the relational aspect is allowed to lapse judg- 
ment becomes practically indistinguishable from conation. It 
is true that the existential judgment occupies a unique position. 
It does not establish a relation between its subject and the 
predicate being * but between an object as idea and an object as 
intuited.' Affirmation of existence or non-existence presupposes, 
as mere acceptance or rejection does not, the beginning at least 
of the differentiation of subject and predicate.* 

On the theory of judgment here developed, the existential 
judgment and the pure presentation (in so far as << contempla- 
tion" is pure presentation) are secondary, derived attitudes, 
derived from the primitive presumftion of reality presupposed 
in all acceptance or rejection of an object. The difference 
between the presumption and judgment is that while in the 
former we have merely acceptance and rejection in the latter we 
have acknowledgment and disavowal, acceptance and rejection 
plus conviction and belief. Returning then to the question of the 
necessary presuppositions of the feeling of value, it is clear that 
there must be the presumption of reality for without it there can 
be no attitude toward the object, attitude involving either accep- 
tance or rejection or disposition to accept or reject. But it is 
equally clear that the existential judgment cannot be the sole and 
necessary presupposition of the feeling, for there can be no such ex- 
plicit judgment (acknowledgment and disavowal) except as there 
is already some reality meaning, some presupposition of reality. 
Again the hypothetical ^wr^ presentation, in so far as there is any 
such mode of consciousness, is equally secondary and derived. 

^Sigwart, Logic (translation), Vol. I., p. 72. 

,'The following quotation taken, by permission, from the proofs of the sec- 
ond volume of Professor Baldwin's Genetic Logic (chapter on "Acknowledg- 
ment and Belief** ) . puts the situation admirably : *' The existence meaning which 
the judgment alwa>8 presupposes in the sense given, may, token expliciiy as- 
serted^ be called a predicate bnt not ana ttributive predicate, not a separate ele- 
ment of presented context or of recognitive meaning, attributed to the subject 
matter. It is only the explicit assertion of the presupposition of belief in the 
sphere in which the subject matter is constitnted an object of thought." 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 29 

It is the result of abstraction from the primitive presumption of 
reality, the result of arrest of this presumption implicit in all 
conation. Meinong's use of the expression (abstractly presented) 
is significant in this connection ; to abstractly present means to 
strip off the reality feeling involved in the first experience. 
This relation to reality feeling may however be partially restored 
by a further movement of conation in which the presented object 
is assumed to exist, an attitude we find characteristic of certain 
secondary contemplative aesthetic experiences. 

This leads us finally to a consideration of the relation of the 
attitude of assumption to the primitive presumption of reality 
and the existential judgment. This is importaxit for the 
reason that the special modification of the feeling which has 
assumption as its * presupposition,' the feelings of the imagina- 
tion (Phantasie-gefiihle) of Meinong's school have been made 
much of in recent discussion. For one thing it has been asserted 
that these feelings are not real and therefore not feelings of value, 
although under certain circumstances they may stand for, or 
represent, real feelings. Our own view, which will be developed 
more fully later, is that they are real feelings in any sense which 
has significance for psychology that they have a presupposition 
of reality, although from the point of view of reflective evalua- 
tion of the objects of such feelings (the axiological point of view) 
the judgments which spring from these feelings may be invalid. 
But a more adequate characterization of this attitude is our first 
problem. 

Assumption, as a cognitive attitude, has two meanings. 
According to its first meanmg it is an acceptance, a taking as 
existent, of an object when there is an underlying sense of the 
possibility of its being non-existent. In this sense also it is a 
half way stage between the primitive presumption of reality and 
the existential judgment with its conviction. In this sense it is a 
secondary movement or act of cognition within a developing 
sphere of reality, bounded by the primitive presumption of reality 
and the existential judgment, aflSrmative or negative. From the 
point of view of conation, it is an act determined by the momen- 
tum of a subjective disposition or interest. In its second mean- 
ing it is not pre- judgmental but post-judgmental, that is a 



30 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

permanent assumption is created by habitual judgment; it pre- 
supposes dispositions created by acts of judgment and is derived 
from the judgment attitude. In this case the assumption 
approaches closely to the presumption and for this attitude the 
two terms are often used interchangeably. It is important 
to emphasize these two meanings* for the feeling attitudes 
involved are in ihany respects quite different, and the confusion 
of the two has led to misinterpretation of worth experience. 
Thus the feelings which attach to assumptions of the first type 
may be described as feelings of the imagination ; they belong 
to the mode of semblance or ' make-believe.' But those which 
attach to assumptions of the second type are more accurately 
described as feeling abstracts or feeling signs and represent the 
acquired funded meaning of past judgment feelings. To this 
class, we shall see later, belong all those feelings, funded mean- 
ings which inhere intrinsically in general concepts. Such terms 
as truth, virtue, duty, etc., have functioned in particular existen- 
tial judgments and it was upon the basis of these judgments that 
the feelings of value for which these terms stand arose, but when 
they are thus formed they are abstractly valued without explicit 
judgments of existence or non-existence. They represent an 
assumption which has arisen through formation of habit. 
Explicit judgment is always the terminal of a process of adapta- 
tion. From the primitive presumption arises, through arrest, 
assumption, which in turn, passes into judgment and the later 
assumption. 

We are now in a position to summarize our position as to 
the nature of simple appreciation, primary feelings of value, in 
so far as it is related to Meinong's criterion. We agree to the 
extent that we include among the feelings of value only such 
feelings as have reality meanings, that is, have some pre- 
supposition of reality. As to the nature of that presupposition 
of reality, we deny its limitation to existential judgment and 
include the two attitudes of presumption and assumption. This 
may be said to be the result of our critical analysis of the 

J Baldwin's recently pnbUshed theory of • schematic,' function recognises 
both these modes of ' assumption,' the existential judgment lying, genetically, 
between them. Genetic Logic, Vol. I. J' K' « 7* 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 3' 

meanings of experiences of worth. There remains still the 
question of the functional and genetic account of these different 
presuppositions. Before undertaking this we must glance briefly 
at another criterion of feelings of value recently developed, more 
especially by Lipps. 

VI. 

It is maintained that all feelings of value are feelings of 
personality — that the analysis which finds the criterion of 
feeling of value in the nature of the attitude toward the trans- 
cendent object, really overlooks the significant moment, which 
is the reference of the feeling to the subject, the personality. 
Feelings of value are feelings of activity of the subject, the acts 
of judgment, etc., being of only secondary importance. Such 
a criterion is presented in the formula of Lipps '} *• Der Wert 
jederLustist bedingtdurch einen Personlichkeits wert." Now, 
while it is undoubtedly true that there are types of feelings of 
value which have as their presupposition explicit reference to 
the personality, — those feelings which we have described as 
values of characterization, including feelings of obligation, desert, 
etc., — it must nevertheless be recognized that these values 
are secondary and acquired, that they presuppose judgments 
referring the attitude to the presented self, the self being a 
founded object, the product of an ideal construction based upon 
preceding experiences of value. The only sense in which this 
statement may be said to be true is that in primary feelings of 
value (as distinguished from simple pleasure), there are certain 
modifications, certain implicit meanings which, when reflected 
upon, lead to their reference to the self. Such a modification 
of Lipps' view we may accept. 

These meanings which appear on the level of simple appre- 
ciation prior to reference to the self, Kruger * has described as 
depth and breadth of the feeling in the personality and he con- 
ceives them to constitute a third dimension of feeling, beside its 
intensity and duration, a dimension which is determined by a 
relative constancy of desire disposition. His development of 

1 Lipps, Die ethischen Grundfrageny Chapter I. 

■Krnger, Der Begriff des absolut Werivollen als Grundbegriff der Moral- 
philosophie, I^ip^ig, 1898, Chapter 3 ( *Zur Psychologie des Wertcs*). 



3 2 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

the criterion is both analytical and genetic. Valuation is dis- 
tinguished from mere desire and simple-pleasure ' causation ' by 
a moment of relative constancy of desire. Desire of itself does 
not constitute valuation and valuation is never mere desire or a 
series of desires. He further conceives the relation of this 
« desire-constant ' to the individual desire on the analogy of the 
relation of concepts. to individual sensations and percepts. A 
valuation always presupposes a relatively constant disposition. 
As a totality this disposition appears as an actual moment in 
consciousness only in a corresponding judgment. Yet the judg- 
ment of value is not the valuation itself. This is given rather 
in the characteristic modification of the experienced desire and 
feeling which he conceives to grow in depth with the develop- 
ment of the * desire-constant.' ^ He suggests that it is probable 
that in the first stages of conscious life only that was consciously 
striven after which brought with it relative increase of pleasure 
and value formation has probably taken its rise in such strivings 
but every desire has a tendency to develop a relative constancy 
and thus to pass into a valuation. It leaves behind in the per- 
sonality constant dispositions, and with them traces of value. 
The mechanism of pleasure-causation is thus broken through 
by the formation of values; and, as soon as the function of 
valuation is formed at a single point, the will is no longer exclu- 
sively determined by the intensity and duration of expected 
pleasure. Through the fact of valuation the affective-volitional 
life gets, so to speak, a third dimension, the value of a constant 
desire is determined by its breadth and depth in the personality. 
The interest of this definition of Kruger's is to be found in 
the fact that it is an attempt to connect the appreciative distinc- 

^ One point, however, he has left undetermined. Is the worth experience 
given in feeling or desire ? In some passages he speaks as though the sense of 
worth were given in feeling as determined by or as determining desire, in others 
as though it were given in the experiences of desire themselves. As a matter 
of fact he does not seem to have faced this question of psychological analysis, 
as the following passage indicates : <* Where the capacity or function of valua- 
tion is to some degree realized, there the individual experiences of feeling and 
desire are in a peculiar manner heightened and deepened, they have a personal 
character. They find, so to speak, in the personality a fuller and more individ- 
ual resonance. We can in such a case speak of a more highly developed 
•Gemiitslcben * " (p. 50) 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. 33 

tions which differentiate feelings of value from other feelings 
(and which lead ultimately to the characterization of the self 
and to the explicit reference of the object to the self) with the 
functional, dispositional conditions of the feeling, and it has 
been presented here at some length because this concept of con- 
ative constants or dispositions as the necessary conditions of 
feelings of value, feelings with depth and breadth, is precisely 
the concept which we need to connect these appreciative mean- 
ings with the reality meanings which the preceding analyses 
have distinguished. At an earlier stage in the development of 
this paper it was seen that both the concepts of feeling and 
conation must find a place in the definition of worth experi- 
ence. It is now seen that feelings of value are not completely 
characterized by reference to their presuppositions of reality 
(presumption, judgment and assumption) but that we must go 
more deeply into the conative dispositions which determined 
these acts of presumption, judgment and assumption. 

How then shall we conceive this relation of the two determi- 
nants of feelings of value ? If we describe the acts of cogni- 
tion as the actual psychical j>resuppositwns and the conative 
tendencies as the dispositional conditions^ our problem would 
read : What is the relation of the actual presuppositions to the 
dispositional conditions as determinants of feelings of value? 
The answer to this question must be in genetic terms. We have 
already seen that there is a certain genetic relation between the 
attitudes of presumption, assumption and judgment. Each, in 
its way, represents a functional attitude toward a psychically 
predetermined object, the acceptance of a demand, acquiescence 
in a control factor, and therefore each is a type of reality 
meaning. But the demands, the controls, vary at different 
stages of the genetic series. An analysis of the manner in 
which the dispositional factor functions at the different stages 
of development should give us a point of view from which to 
unify the results of our study. 

The condition, determinant, of the primitive presumption of 
reality seems to be that the object shall have recognitive mean- 
ing for a conative tendency. At this point the cognitive and 
conative moments can be scarcely distinguished. As far back 



34 WILBUR M. URBAN, 

as we may go in our analysis, interest, conation, seems to deter- 
mine recognition, and recognition is the condition of the first 
reality meaning which characterizes feelings of value. In the 
primitive presumption of reality the dualism between subjective 
and objective control factors has not yet emerged. It is with 
the first arrest of a conative tendency, through the development 
of an independent cognitive interest, and differentiation of the 
recognitive factor from the conative, that the innocency of 
primitive presumption is disturbed and a differentiation of sub- 
jective and objective demands or controls appears. Here the 
attitude of assumption emerges, determined largely by the sub- 
jective control factor of the conative disposition, often in oppo- 
sition to objective controls already established — but not neces- 
sarily so. Assumption of the existence of an object is the 
acceptance of a subjective demand, after arrest of primitive 
presumption, and constitutes a transition stage between pre- 
sumption and explicit acknowledgment of a control as objec- 
tive. I am inclined to agree with Professor Baldwin that a 
pure fancy mode, play of fancy, described by him as the first 
semblant mode, constitutes a genetic transition between pre- 
sumption and assumption, but for our purposes it is negligible. 
From the assumption attitude emerges the existential judgment, 
either positive or negative. It represents not merely the accep- 
tance or rejection of an object but the explicit acknowledgment 
or disavowal of a certain control factor. It is important to ob- 
serve that the control factor may be either the original objective 
moment or the subjective moment determinant in assumption, 
that the existential judgment may be acknowledgment of 
either factor, but in that case the subjective has, by that very 
process, been transferred to the objective side of the equation. 

VII. 
The material is now before us for a summary restatemen 
of our original definition of value, as funded affective-volitional 
meaning, in terms of psychological equivalents. The psycho- 
logical equivalent of the worth predicate is always a feeling, 
with certain meanings determined by actual cognitive presuppo- 
sitions, types of cognitive reaction which actualize pre-existent 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE, 35 

conative dispositions. The value or funded meaning of the 
object is its capacity of becoming the object of feeling and 
desire through actualization of dispositional tendencies by acts 
of judgment, assumption, etc. 

The conative disposition is the fundamental determinant of 
the feeling of value or appreciative meaning of the object but 
the disposition may be actualized^ represented in function by 
different cognitive attitudes, or acts, of the types described, and 
according as it is one or the other of these types are the feel- 
ings qualified in the manner described.* Underlying the feeling 
of value attached to the idea of my friend is the conative dispo- 
sition, the interest created by former desires for his presence 
and satisfaction of those desires, but that feeling may now arise 
upon mere momentary assumptions of his existence without a 
trace of desire for has immediate presence. All * disposition- 
feelings * however actualized, are feelings of value because 
they represent the funded meaning of affective-volitional proc- 
ess, although they have different reality meanings. From the 
standpoint of the extension of the term, the class, feelings of 
value, includes aesthetic feelings, feelings of the imagination, 
so called, as well as practical and ethical attitudes. 

In general, then, we may conclude that feeling of value is 
the feeling aspect of conative process, as distinguished from 
the feeling tone of simple presentations. And by conative 
process we understand the total process of development by 

^ In the consideration of the relation of the actual presuppositions to the dis- 
positional conditions there are still certain questions which have considerable 
bearing upon later discussions. Thus Witasek maintains that while it is probably 
true that feelings of worth arise upon the mere presentation of an object related 
to desire dispositions, nevertheless, since desire presupposes judgment, and these 
dispositions have been formed by preceding judgments, the worth feeling is 
ultimately still a 'judgment-feeling.' Now it may be admitted that judgments 
enter into the formation of these desire dispositions but as dispositional they 
are merely conative tendency, for it is the essence of judgment to be explicit 
and actual. Again it is argued (by Sazinger) that the dispositions correspond- 
ing to judgment feelings are different from the dispositions correlated with 
assumption feelings and he bases his argument upon differences in the laws 
governing the two kinds of feeling. Into the consideration of this question we 
cannot enter here — that will be reserved for a later study. We may simply 
emphasize our own position that worth feeling is a function of conative dispo- 
sition, whetlier conation expresses itself explicitly in judgment or assumption. 



36 WILBUR M. URBAN, 

which affective-volitional meaning is acquired, the total process 
including actual and dispositional moments. How these dispo- 
sitions, and with them the feelings which they condition, are 
modified, both qualitatively and quantitatively, at different 
stages of this development, by changes in presuppositions, and 
more especially by the inclusion of secondary judgments of 
relation, etc., is the problem of the second part of this study. 



SOME IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR 
ATTITUDES. 

BY PROFESSOR ALFRED H. LLOYD, 
University of Michigan. 

The * situation,' already described by some as the absolute 
of a certain conspicuous group of thinkers, is in general taking 
such an important part in current philosophical discussion that to 
an outsider philosophy must seem very like to an employment 
bureau, if it does not appear at last to have become an intelli- 
gence office. Undoubtedly, too, the very commonplaceness or 
the plebeian character of the term is one of the most serviceable 
and hopeful tendencies of current thinking. In the present 
paper, then, only falling into line with so many others who 
have written and spoken, I would discuss, let me not be so bold 
or broad as to say advertise, four peculiarly interesting situa- 
tions and their induced attitudes ; namely, the moral situation, 
the artistic, the practical and the natural, and their four atti- 
tudes, respectively the ethical, the esthetic, the intellectual or 
cognitional, and the spiritual. 

The situation, to begin with, whatever specific variations it 
may have, in general has its rise, which is to say also gets its 
widest meaning, in the fact that structure necessarily implies 
function. Back of this fact, then, I do not propose to go at the 
present writing. But, this admitted, another is immediately 
manifest. Function necessarily implies conjlict. The conflict, 
moreover, which is the general situation, is between (i) an exist- 
ing structure, describable either as the body of the individual 
agent's habits or as the established social environment, the body 
of the social institutions, to which just through his habits the 
individual is, as if conventionally or traditionally or unreflec- 
tively, always a part, and (2) the natural environment as dis- 
tinct from the social or definitely and humanly organized 
environment. In other words the conflict is between man with 

37 



38 ALFRED H. LLOYD. 

his life set to certain norms and nature ; between * second 
nature ' and first nature ; between the formal reason and sensa- 
tion, or the legislative will and impulse. Also it is between 
one organization and another organization, the latter usually if 
not invariably being more inclusive than the former and neces- 
sarily rising into conflict with the former whenever, to use an 
annoying but concise and pertinent term, it * functions ' in any 
way. And, just once more, in order to avoid the serious mis- 
take of even a suspicion that the * natural environment,' here 
mentioned, is external to what is human, let me say of the 
conflict that it is describable also as being between the formal 
or structural in personal experience and the vital, even the most 
distinctively personal, in personal experience. Thus, there is 
a sense, important to a true understanding of what is here 
meant, in which the characteristically personal and the natural 
are identical or synonymous. Both the personal and the natural 
are always coming into conflict with the definite and formal, 
that is, the structural, in life or experience. The structural is not 
distinctively personal or natural ; on the contrary it is * factional' 
or socially corporate.* Accordingly, on the assumption of this 
identity of the personal and the natural, the situation, or its 
conflict, must be due not less to personal initiative than to any 
of the processes of mere ^ natural selection ' and of course too the 
conflict can never be with an external nature. Indeed, if the 
conflict could be with an external nature, then structure simply 
could not imply function. 

So we see that the characteristic condition of the situation in 
general is conflict and we see too, although the foregoing state- 
ment has been very brief, the origin and the nature of this con- 
flict. With this preliminary view, therefore, I turn now to my 
special task. I would show how, to the end of solving its 
conflict, which always is as specific and concrete in its terms 
and issue as the inducing structure is itself definite in char- 
acter, the situation develops through the following principal 
moments. 

1 See an article : * The Personal and the Factional (or formal or stmctural) 
in the Life of Society,' in The Journal of Philosophy^ Psychology and Scientific 
Methods, June 22, 1905. 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 39 

I. The Moral Situation. 

The first moment is naturally that of a presumed sufficiency 
of the subject's or agent's existing structure or, as the terms are 
here used, of the formally human. The definite habits or the 
social institutions are taken and are asserted, not only as quite 
equal to the presented and confronted emergency, but also as 
possessing intrinsic worth and normative or structural finality, 
and the natural, in the sense of that which is formally external 
to these habits or institutions, is an object only of an unreason- 
ing fear. The natural is feared, blindly feared, just because it 
is at once quite real and yet external at least to the formal 
reason, to the reason of the structure-bound human. 

So I view the first moment in the development of the situ- 
ation and it seems to me to present specifically the moral situ- 
ation. Not, of course, that morality is confined to conditions 
such as these, but these are the characteristic conditions of the 
situation as moral. These distinguish the moral situation from 
other defined situations. In a sense, certainly important, all 
situations are moral, as also they are all artistic or practical, 
or natural, but this is only to say, in so many words, that the 
specific conditions which make distinct situations are themselves 
in their way functional as well as structural, and so are general 
to development while being at the same time particular and 
definable. Functionally any moment or situation, any struc- 
ture must comprise all others. 

Possibly the peculiarly moral character of this first distinct 
moment is best seen in what my account has certainly, although 
not openly stated, namely, in the conceit of the freedom of the 
will. The * free will ' is simply a name for the power of the 
agent to fulfil and exemplify the structural adequacy. Accord- 
ingly, to use now this name, the conceit and practice of a ^ free 
will' and the accompanying unreasoning fear of what is external 
to this freedom, a fear which may often take the form of bravado, 
of what can be only an asserted indifference to danger, are the 
determining factors of the moral situation. 

But this, somebody will at once object, makes the moral and 
the legal identical, and such an identity every reflective man 
must promptly and emphatically resent. At once I grant that 



40 ALFRED H, LLOYD, 

the moral and the legal are here made identical. I grant also 
that reflection must separate them. ' But it is to be said, also 
promptly and emphatically, that no situation as such is itself 
reflective. Situations are not attitudes, although they are 
always springing from attitudes and are also constantly in- 
duced by them. Situations, as said before, are structural in so 
far as definable at all, and the moral situation is in consequence 
determined by the formal law. But situations, being also func- 
tional, induce attitudes, and in the particular case at hand the 
moral situation induces the ethical attitude. The very differ- 
ence between these terms, even as they are widely used, tells 
the story. The ethical is the moral, just by dint of the given 
legal structure becoming active or functioning, made reflective 
in an attitude. Again, any induced attitude involves a gener- 
alization and idealization of those formal conditions which make 
the inducing situation, and, although, as we shall see, the attitude 
itself must make a situation, it should never be confused with 
the particular situation whose functioning has given it rise. 
Thus the functional nature of a structure, which here and now 
means specifically those positive conditions that formally deter- 
mine the moral situation, makes certain a movement out of 
formal bondage to those conditions into a state of only mediate 
dependence on them. They become only means to some rela- 
tively undetermined end. They are made mediately rather 
than immediately, ideally rather than materially, spiritually 
rather than literally significant. And thereupon the moral sit- 
uation gives way to the ethical attitude, and by the same token 
morality is saved at least from a positive, uncompromising 
legalism. 

But not from legalism altogether. The ethical attitude is 
still characteristically legalistic ; in terms, however, not of the 
positive law, but of * duty,' * conscience,' or the * moral ideal,' 
which is only an abstraction of its spirit or general functional 
value, from the positive, formal law. The ethical attitude, in- 
duced, as was said, by the functional character of the moral sit- 
uation, asserts the existing structural formalism, the manifest 
legalism, to be worth cultivating, and a cultivated legalism must 
always value law as a general principle above law as a visible 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 41 

program, the program becoming henceforth only instrumental 
to the unseen principle. Lawfulness, in short, rather than the 
specific law or structure, is the concern of the ethical attitude. 
How often ethics is called normative, and surely its normative 
character is nothing more nor less than its abstract legalism. 

Further, the ethical attitude, just because, at least in spirit, 
still legalistic, is also in another respect like its inducing situa- 
tion. Although not dogmatically indifferent to nature nor quite 
blindly fearful of her, it is nevertheless humanly conceited or 
anthropocentric. The principle of law is always more hospitable 
than a legal program ; a structure in use is more widely sym- 
pathetic than a structure just in statu quo ; but the ethical atti- 
tude still sees no positive worth in nature except as she is 
humanly, or humanely, disposed. So to speak the spirit of the 
fear of her still remains, as if to keep its congenial company 
with the surviving, albeit only spiritual or functional legalism. 

Fear become a spirit loses much of its dread. Law become a 
principle loses much of its vigor. In a word, the normative, 
ethical attitude must mean an important modification in the 
actual situation. Ethical, as distinct from social or political 
legalism, by its very idealism, which is to say by its devotion to 
the spirit of law and its feeling only of the spirit of fear, makes 
man actively hospitable towards the organization of nature, with 
which morally he was in such dire conflict, and in doing this it 
induces, or initiates, the artistic situation. The ethical attitude 
put in practice is the peculiar life of art. 

IL The Artistic Situation. 
So I pass to the second moment in the development of the 
general situation, and this I would call, not the moment of as- 
sumed and asserted human sufficiency, in which nature is an 
object of blind fear, but the moment of human condescension, 
assumed and asserted, towards the natural, towards nature's 
law, structure or organization. This, too, as already said, is 
the artistic situation. Art, let it be kept in mind, is character- 
istically a situation, not an attitude. It is just a living up to a 
humanly sympathetic nature and in just so far it actually is the 
practice of what the ethical attitude may be said to preach. 



42 ALFRED H. LLOYD. 

Once more, though I may repeat myself too much, it is, not the 
moral, which is politically legalistic, but the ethical, which is 
functionally, spiritually or personally legalistic, rendered incar- 
nate, and as having such character it shows man actually in a 
truce with nature. In art the human is seen actively to have 
assumed a relation of equilibrium, necessarily more or less un- 
stable, or of something very like an armed neutrality, between 
itself, its structure, the norms of its life, and nature's structure. 
Actively man moulds nature to his conceits. He makes her 
glorify his image. In her life, in her powers and processes, he 
realizes, or presumes to realize, only a deeper and fujler expres- 
sion of himself. Art is thus, like morality, anthropocentric, 
but it is man big with nature. It is the little human swelling 
with the big natural, and as so conditioned it is what we call 
poetic or creative, all its activities being informed with analogies 
of the natural to the human and embodying, although never 
without a violence that only the poetic imagination can have 
made possible, nature's metaphors of the human. The neces- 
sary violence, too, imparts to art as strong a sense of comedy as 
of tragedy, as is shown in the readiness with which we laugh or 
weep whenever we see the little human swollen with the big 
natural. Simply in art, always as comic as tragic, man ap- 
pears, not as teaching or seeking ideally, but as actually prac- 
ticing a legalism that has lost the rigor of the formal law and a 
fear of nature that is tempered by a very real sense of humor. 

But here comes an objector. I am accused of narrowing 
beauty, which is the recognized goal of art, to conditions that 
require accord, if not literal and prosaic, at least metaphorical, 
with the positive structure of the human agent, just as before I 
seemed to identify morality with legality. In a word, I seem to 
have left no room for objective or natural beauty. To the 
present objector, however, I have to make just the answer 
made before. A situation is not an attitude, although it always 
induces one. The artistic situation, as its structure becomes 
function, induces the esthetic attitude, by which the very con- 
ditions making the life of art are idealized. Thus, for the 
esthetic attitude, man is not, as in art, the determining center. 
He is the observer indeed, but only the passive observer. His 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES- 43 

Structure, losing its character of a sole measure for all other 
structures or for the structure of nature as a whole, becomes but 
one among the others, any one of which may be the center from 
which a judgment is passed. True, for the esthetic attitude, all 
structures, or all measures, by which nature, so to speak, is thus 
made to measure or judge herself, are as i/" sensitively human, 
but this only shows how humanly passive the esthetic attitude 
is, how for it nature, not man, is the artist. The characteristic 
object, therefore, of the esthetic attitude truly is beauty, sen- 
sibly manifested and sensitively measured, but, instead of the 
beauty of man to himself, as this is reflected in nature's meta- 
phors just of his life, it is objectively natural beauty. The 
metaphors are no longer exclusively human, but nature objec- 
tively is just a sphere of metaphors, metaphor poised sensitively 
against metaphor and calling deeply and passionately each to 
each and through their poise and their passionate call she is 
beautiful. She is beautiful to man ; not, as in SLTt^ybr him and 
his structural conceits. For the esthetic attitude even the works 
of human art must meet the demands of natural beauty in that 
they must accord, or sensitively sympathize, with what sur- 
rounds them. The setting, or frame, of a work of art is thus 
an important factor in its beauty. 

But where now are the law and the fear? The law, and 
with it, man's so-called freedom have been lost or merged, nay, 
they have been fulfilled in the law and the freedom of nature 
which an objective beauty reveals ; and the fear is become awe. 
Nature is no longer fearful, but awful or sublime. Awe is not 
man fearing for his own safety ; it is man sensitive to the fears 
of the whole world and in that sensitiveness feeling the lawless 
law of nature. Yet such terms as these and the seeming gran- 
diloquence to which they lead may very easily obscure the 
meaning here in my mind. The meaning would take a view 
of life in its lowest as,well as in its highest terms, in its simplest 
as well as in its grandest expressions. A psychologist could 
not be more minute or prosaic in his viewpoint than my mean- 
ing is intended to be. Simply any structure, whatever its size 
or its complexity, its significance or its dignity, being always 
functional, must come to this sensitiveness, which we know. 



44 ALFRED H. LLOYD, 

however grandiloquently, as awe towards the lawless law of 
nature. What is sensation but structure meeting the violence 
of nature. What is structure that nature is mindful of it. 

But the esthetic attitude, induced, as has been shown by the 
artistic situation and ideally sensitive, not merely to the unity of 
man but also, as if actually feeling for them, to the unity of all 
things with nature, leads man out of the artistic into the prac- 
tical situation. 

III. The Practical Situation. 

The practical situation, as the third moment to be consid- 
ered, is the moment of the human structure, the whole body of 
habits and institutions become — but the right phrase is hard to 
find — merely a natural utility. Only, I would call it also, bor- 
rowing a word from the political vocabulary of the day, a * float- 
ing' utility. So does man again put into practice the preaching 
of one of his attitudes. He comes actively to treat his formal 
life just as his esthetic consciousness has already revealed it to 
him, namely, as only mediate to an indeterminate nature, and, 
as he does this, the last traces of his esthetic sensitiveness dis- 
appear and the metaphors, human or objective, in which this 
had found expression, become only dead metaphors. Man no 
longer is even an interested observer of nature ; he is just a 
mechanical incident within her unpurposed movement. 

In social evolution, where the practical situation in all its 
phases is written large, the time is one of traditions and human 
conceits and devotions of all sorts become purely conventional, 
which is to say useful but not yet put in use, or treasured, as 
money is treasured, but not yet actually invested, and accom- 
panying these conditions there is also, as if the last defense of 
the passing regim^, a blind fatalism. So long as this fatalism 
remains blind the old structure of life can at least seem to sur- 
vive, although the immediate vitality once belonging to it has 
already gone. 

Of course, further, when habits and institutions come, as 
said above, to be a mere formal utility, a floating utility, the 
personal in human life has virtually already separated itself 
from the structural and this separation as a positive condition or 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 45 

Status belongs to the situation now under review. But, although 
virtually separate, the personal has not yet so found itself. 
Thus, in social evolution, this condition shows itself in a blind 
individualism, always so assertive of independence of the exist- 
ing structure, yet also so helpless without it : but, psycholog- 
ically or biologically, how best to describe this virtual yet undis- 
covered or unappreciated separation I am at a loss to know. 
Certainly it shows the functional self, the vital nature in an 
agent, become at least blindly superior to the structural or 
morphological self, and it shows, too, whether psychologically 
or sociologically, that although nature seems to be on the point 
of taking to herself the formal life of man, allowing it to 
crumble or rather to assimilate to herself, man nevertheless 
really survives, rising in his vitality only to cooperate with her 
in the use of his establishments. Technically how the psy- 
chologist would wish this moment or situation in developnient, 
perhaps in the development of volition, described, I am quite 
unable to guess, and possibly he has ho suitable term or phrase 
for it, but the situation, I am sure, is a real one. Here, how- 
ever, a possible misunderstanding must be avoided. Thus, in 
the first place, as indeed already indicated, I am now describ- 
ing only a situation and the situation comprises rather a division 
of the self in fact or condition, the structural self having become 
insensitive or mechanical, than a division of the self in conscious- 
ness. To just such a purely factual division the blind fatalism, 
or the blind individualism, mentioned before, was clearly an 
index. Moreover, in the second place, a division of the self, 
whether in bare fact or in consciousness, is rather logical than 
psychological or rather social than personal, and this one needs 
constantly to remember. Logically there may be two selves, 
the vital and the structural, and sociologically also, in so far as 
society is viewed abstractly in terms only of so much formal 
organization, there may be two selves, the individual and the 
citizen, but mere counting is never real seeing. Function and 
structure are truly two, but they are not truly two selves.* 

^ A qnestion certainly worth asking, at least in a note, is here unavoidable 
to him that reads between the lines. Is logic, at least formal logic, even such a 
logic as Kant's * transcendental ' logic, true rather to experience as expressed. 



4^ ALFRED H, LLOYD, 

So, to gather together what has been said so far, this third 
moment, the moment of the practical situation, is the moment of 
the human in a sense profaned and turned merely useful ; it is 
the moment of life wholly without poetry, the once stirring 
metaphors being all dead, and subject to the qualification just 
made — it is the moment of a factual division of the self, the 
structural self still keeping up appearances through a blind 
fatalism or a blind individualism and the vital, functional self 
being as real and also as unseen or unseeing as the blindness. 

And now, for the third time, an objector confronts me with 
a question. In reducing the formal structure of human life to 
a mere natural floating utility am I not confusing the practical 
with the economic? Well, let me concede that so far I have 
defined the practical situation in terms which directly suggest 
the sort of mechanicalism or hollow conservatism and naturalism 
in life that economics demands. Economics characteristically 
demands no interference with the * credit of the country,' which 
is to say the status in quo^ the existing structure or organization, 
but its loyalty to the organization is formal, not substantial. It 
requires mankind to be both morally and esthetically without 
emotion. Its typical man must be just a money making 
machine, and what is money but the incarnation of a floating 
natural utility. Thus, with its peculiar abstraction, economics 
knows only utility, and in the practical situation utility certainly 
seems supreme. It is so supreme that any purpose for it is quite 
forgotten ! Accordingly, as already conceded, the objector is 
right ; he is right, so far as he goes ; and he has, in fact, as 
before, only assisted my exposition. But, to repeat the refrain, 
a situation is never an attitude, although it always induces one. 
For the case in hand, the practical situation induces the reflective 
attitude and this saves the situation from its bondage to a mere 
formal utility. 

socially, which ig to say, of coarse, structaraUy or formally, than to experience 
as personal, vital or functional ? This question, as put, almost begs its own 
answer, an affirmative one. Only real logic, in the sense of a logic that, 
although recognizing form in experience, treats experience as also imbued with 
a vital superiority to its form or structure, as if with a » legal supremacy,' can 
possibly satisfy the demands of what is characteristically personal. Moreover, 
m this fact it would seem as if the pragmatist must find the method in the re- 
puted madaess of his philosophy. 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES^ 47 

The reflective, which, as here understood, is also the cogni- 
tional attitude, only appreciates or idealizes the actual conditions 
of the practical situation. Thus, it takes as something real the 
end which the formal utilitarianism, the idle conventionalism of 
the practical situation has certainly implied but as certainly 
concealed in its blind individual or in its blind fate and just in 
recognizing or facing this end it shows the vital, functional self, 
on the one hand, become conscious — or seeing — and assertive 
independently of mere structure and the structural self, on the 
other hand, made positively mediative, that is, mediative of 
something quite real although formally external to it or * objec- 
tive.' The conscious reality of the vital self and the objective 
character of the mediation of the structural self are thus here 
considered to be just that which makes the attitude now in ques- 
tion reflective or cognitional. For so-called reflection structure 
is become only means, instrument or method and it is method to 
what is regarded distinctly real but is, in the words used before, 
* formally external.* This phrase, let me say further, signifies 
(i) formally or structurally indeterminate,^ a character clearly 
belonging to whatever is said to be objective, and yet also (2) 
real. The reality is not necessarily apart from the structure ; it 
is so only in form, that is, only relatively ; it may be, nay, I 
think it must be actually in the structure, in its very character 
as only means or method, just as any true end must be immanent 
in, or vital to, the means to it. But as an attitude^ reflection 
naturally holds the conscious, vital self and the real end to their 
formal unlikeness or aloofness and so treats the now insensitive 
structure as the medium of what very commonly is known as an 
abstract idea, a universal, a principle, or — not to prolong the 
list further — a conception, that belongs, not to the world of 
sensation or body, but to the world of thought or mind. 

So, to recall a mode of statement already employed, a con- 
ception, which is the typical * object ' of reflection, while in just 
the sense indicated negative only relatively to form or subjective 
structure, nevertheless, in so far as negative or outside, can be 
merely a logical rather than a psychological datum ; although, 

^That is, of conree, so indeterminate relatively to the positive structure of 
the subject or agent. 



48 ALFRED H, LLOTD. 

as a matter of course, a psychologist may still be directly inter- 
ested in the peculiar conditions that determine the data of the re- 
flective attitude as thus amenable to logical treatment. In other 
words, psychologically, there can be no independent conception, 
and the supposed independence of the conception can spring 
only from the standpoint, essentially logical, that would view 
the reflective attitude wholly in terms of the dichotomy of what 
is formally structural and what is not.^ Moreover, the reflec- 
tive attitude itself is the psychological moment for logic, al- 
though the very dichotomy, on which it rests, makes the 
moment only a passing one, as we shall see. 

But, the issues between logic and psychology aside, it is 
now apparent, I think, in what important way the dying of the 
metaphors in human art or in nature, or the accompanying birth 
of an insensitive human structure, or — once more — the devel- 
opment of that purely formal or floating natural utility was des- 
tined to serve the progress of the general situation and the 
solution of the conflict which we found characteristic of it. 
The insensitive structure, as if a medium, or more narrowly a 
language, without emotion or metaphor, made possible what 
somewhat technically is known as strictly scientific research. 
It made possible a free, thoroughly candid or open-minded, struc- 
turally or humanly unprejudiced study of nature instead of the 
more passive and more restrained observation that belonged to 
the esthetic attitude. Thus the esthetic attitude showed man 
not yet free from himself, although his fear had changed to 
awe ; it showed him perhaps free in spirit, but not yet free in 
letter, not yet really free ; whereas the reflective or cognitional 
attitude shows him at least very much nearer to a complete 
freedom. Has not his structure become a real instrument? 
Has he not distinctly found his vital self? Has he not ac- 
knowledged an * objective' nature? The reflective attitude, 
then, shows him free, free from — or in? — himself, in just so 
far as his no longer sensitive structure has become a mere tool 
or method in real use ; that is, in the use of his new-found self 
as this confronts nature. 

» Witness the principles of identity and contradiction. Witness, also, the 
character of the independent concept as an abstract nniversal. 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 49 

And yet, although there is this advance, it is necessary now 
to issue a caution. The reflective attitude must not be under- 
stood to involve any mere betrayal of the quondam metaphors ; 
on the contrary, it is only a fulfilment of them. It cannot 
properly or honestly thank the absolute, I mean the general 
situation, that it is not as the esthetic attitude was ; but, instead, 
it must realize that as the tool or structure is put to real use, as 
the utility is really invested, the experience which has gone 
before, sensitiveness, metaphors and all, is exactly what deter- 
mines the momentum and efficiency of the activity. True, the 

* objective' nature in the case is deepened beyond any mere 
conformity with man, beyond even the licentious conformity of 
the esthetic consciousness, but it is still nature, and the same 
nature too, and the metaphors, although all dead, are dead only 
as sensitive metaphors, and so to speak as insensitive meta- 
phors are still active in the tool or structure. Indeed, however 
grandiloquently, I wonder if the method or the medium or the 
structurally mediated conception of the reflective attitude may 
not be said to be the very metaphors that died with the rise of 
the practical situation spiritually resurrected. Conception 
would then be definable as a sort of greatly deepened and 
spiritualized esthetic experience; an esthetic experience still 
dependent on metaphor, but so deepened or possibly so purely 
objective as to be, not human, but just natural. Is not the nat- 
ural truth, which reflection seeks, I cannot say, which reflection 
observes, and which is always the peculiar content of the con- 
ception, even more awful or more deeply sublime than natural 
beauty? Indeed man, structural man, almost must be declared 
to be, not numb, but dead, in the presence of its sublimity. 

I have just said * almost,' and before, in speaking of the free- 
dom that comes with reflection I used and emphasized the phrase 

* in so far as,' declaring in so many words that the freedom was 
not necessarily complete but was proportional to the measure in 
which the structure of human life had come into real use. Now 
complete use, with that necessary death of the human before 
the sublimity of nature, is not possible in reflection. It is true 
that reflection is active and that reflection uses the medium or 
structure supplied to it, but its use is related to the ideal very 



50 ALFRBD H, LLOYD, 

much as the psychologist tells us attention is related to volition. 
It is true, too, that reflection in its own nature somehow demands 
the complete use referred to, but reflection, characteristically, 
must keep means and end, language and idea, structure and 
meaning, at least somewhat apart. Accordingly the reflective 
attitude can fulfil itself, can realize its own demands, only by 
yielding to a new situation, namely, to the wholly natural 
situation, and to this I now turn. 

IV. The Natural Situation. 

Of this fourth and at least for the present study last special 
situation I shall write somewhat more briefly, concluding my 
paper rather abruptly, as many stories are brought to an end, 
and, also as with the stories, at a point where possibly the situa- 
tion is getting most deeply interesting and might seem to demand 
the longest chapter. 

As the foregoing has ^iQl^ Mi^@fi^jL the physical situa- 
tion belongs to the inbuaent, not of anySqpi^iving conceit of 
human suflSciency, not of ai^£^gl^es|gnHpm,nt of human con- 
descension towards ii^tvre, and not of fo^ merely formal 
naturalism or blind fataK6jja,^lm||^ajt|g ^l^^ ff the death or loss 
of the human structure in then^WfW^'T'ne structural man dies 
just in order that the vital and natural man may live or rather 
the death of the one is in and with the rising life of the other. 
Again, the natural situation is the moment, not of any merely 
miserly utilitarianism, but of the human structure become, instead 
of an aimless, formal, floating, hoarded utility, a real, positively 
natural utility. So, through reflection, has the practical been 
changed to the natural situation. 

Manifestly the reflective attitude calls for this change. By 
its very * self-consciousness,' that makes the human structure 
only mediative, by its conviction of the inner or vital self as 
well as of the outer nature being at once real and formally ex- 
ternal to the structure, and by its own active use of the struc- 
tural medium, it calls for just that fatal invasion or overwhelm- 
ing assertion of nature which makes the natural situation. In 
history as in psychology the reflective attitude is always an in- 
vitation to nature to realize herself. It summons, or already it 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 5^ 

has admitted and recognized, what seems barbarian into what 
has stood for civilization or what seems impulsive, sensuous and 
irrational into the well-controlled and rational, and being such 
an invitation or such a cordial recognition it is mainly occupied 
with a constant — what shall I say? — a constant offering of its 
humanly insensitive, now only mediative structure which pos- 
sibly a Teufelsdrockh would call man's cast off clothing, to 
nature, the world of its • objective ' curiosity. So Alexander, 
pupil of Aristotle, sought to clothe the peoples of the eastern 
Mediterranean, and so the reflective life psychologically, as 
well as historically, would clothe the not less invaded than in- 
vading world of sense. The general process is often known as 
assimilation, more or less benevolent, often as experimentation, 
but under either name it shows nature trying on the human and 
it is conducted under the guidance of the dead, in the sense of 
the dehumanized metaphors of the esthetic consciousness. Per- 
haps these metaphors become wholly insensitive, should rather 
be called analogies, even objective analogies, as is suggested 
by the fact that the experimentation, or the assimilation, strives 
to use them the nature-end forward, not as with the esthetic 
attitude, the man-end forward. But certainly they guide the 
process and testify accordingly to the honesty of the invitation 
to nature or to the cordiality of the recognition of her, and in 
the natural situation one sees, again, that nature has only taken 
reflection at its word. 

Nature takes reflection at its word with a new structure, a 
new organization. The content of this new organization and 
its form are determined, moreover, by the bounds of the inducing 
activity, or of what might also be called the functional capacity 
or versatility of the passing structure, and by the analogies that 
have constantly guided it. Simply, if there be definite structure 
at the start, and just this, as will be remembered, was the start- 
ing point for the present study, then also that stucture is, frofov" 
iionally to its structural definiteness^ limited to a certain sphere 
of activity, or functional character, and the bounds of this sphere 
measure the extent of the new organization, while the inevitable 
analogies developed with its exploitation determine the new 
form. Structure, the definite, can of course be only * relative,' 



53 ALFRED H. LLOYD, 

but being relative it must be complex and being complex it must 
be functional as well as structural, and being functional it must 
induce, through such moments as have been recounted here, new 
structure ; new, because the original structure was relative and 
functional, and structure, because the definite can induce only 
the definite. Must not what is new be always true to its origin? 

But, without further description or explanation of the natural 
situation, an objector must now be met ; perhaps the same, who 
appeared before, although he gave no name. Thus, this time I 
am charged with having confused the natural with the physical. 
The spiritual attitude, however, for so I have to call it, although 
also it may be called volitional or even religious, is what I would 
now depend on to save the natural from being just physical. 
This fourth attitude arises in the following way. It is but an 
appreciation of the fact, suggested early in my narrative, that 
the natural must be also the characteristically personal. Natural 
and personal were said to be both external to, or in conflict with, 
the formal or structural. Moreover in the reflective process of 
experimentation must not that trying-on be as truly on the part 
of the inner vital self, as if the waiting will, as on the part of 
the outer and * objective ' — or physical ? — nature ? How often 
it has been pointed out that the natural was objective and could 
be objective only in the way of being, not essentially, but 
merely formally or structurally external to the human. Nature, 
then, truly is physical only in so far as she is * objective.* Ex- 
ternal to the functional or vital in what is human she cannot 
be, and this being true, in just so far, she is spiritual ; in just 
so far her reconstruction is man's volition ; in just so far man 
says, religiously, of her activity : • What she does, I will.* She 
may never appear literally in man's image, but her life is one 
with his life and the spiritual or volitional or characteristically 
religious attitude puts just this valuation upon her. 

So this paper having accomplished its specific task must 
come to an end. Of course, as from any narrative, a score or 
more of * morals ' might be drawn. The distinction, moral or 
ethical, between good and evil, for example, evidently should 
be judged relatively to the specific situation or to the induced 
attitude, within which it manifestly belongs, and the distinction. 



IMPORTANT SITUATIONS AND THEIR ATTITUDES. 53 

practical or reflective, between truth and error, relatively to 
what is a qualitatively different situation or attitude. Again the 
need, whenever discussion or explanation would become at all 
searching or vital, of always carefully distinguishing between 
the personal and the social, the functional and the structural, 
perhaps too the pragmatic and the dogmatic, and at the same 
time also of always making these distinct things work together 
is also evident. But such < morals,' however urgent or numer- 
ous, may be left safely to the imagination.^ 

^The MS. of thlB article was received December i6, 1906.— Ed. 



DISCUSSION. 

GENETIC MODES AND THE MEANING OF THE 
PSYCHIC.^ 

When we can explain chemical affinity we may attempt to explain 
instinct; when we have explained instinct we may attempt intelli- 
gence. The explanation offered by dynamic realism * of the ' mean- 
ing' of the simplest of natural phenomena will presumptively be the 
explanation of the principle underlying all reactions. 

We may ask why a comet pursues a given course rather than an- 
other. The answer is two-fold. First, because of the nature of the 
forces constituting the comet ; second, by reason of the combinations 
of energy existing in the universe through which it passes. In other 
words, the trajectory of the comet is determined by correspondences 
existing between the comet and its environment. We might say that 
the trajectory of the comet is its path of least resistance, but this is 
only part of the truth. The nature of the energic structure of the 
comet is also a factor — the most important one. It has, we say, a 
certain mass of gravity. It has that which makes it a positive energic 
element in a universe of energy. It might be considered fanciful to 
suppose that as the extrinsic pull which draws the mother to her child 
has also its intrinsic side called affection, so there is an intrinsic affec- 
tion corresponding to the extrinsic pull of the planet. Nevertheless, 
all analogy would indicate that, if not an affection or instinct, there is 
nevertheless an intrinsic element in all these cases. 

So with the chemical element, all that we know about it consists 
in reactions, u «., interferences of some type of energy with the 
energic complex of the environment. One of the most important of 
these reactions is what we call chemical affinity. If we indicate the 
locus formula of sodium by Na and that of chlorine by CI, then the 
expression NaCl (common salt) means that these two loci have certain 

'A fragment found among the author's papers and submitted by C J. 
Herrick. — Ed. 

'Some of the implications of this term as used by the autlhor will be found 
in his later writings, particularly, * Fundamental Conce)>ts and Methodology 
of Dynamic Realism, V^^* PhiL^ Psych,, Set. Methods, Vol. i, No. ii, 1904; 
and ' The Law of Congmousness and iu Logical Application to Dynamic Real- 
ism.' Ibid., Vol. I, No. 32, 1904.— C. J. H. 

54 



DISCUSSION. 55 

compatibilities or correspondences which result, the energic complex 
being what it happens now to be in this particular environment, in a 
closer articulation or assimilation in these particular loci than between 
the activities expressed by Na and H,0, for example. Under other 
conditions of environment, say at a high temperature or in the presence 
of larger amounts of water, the chemical affinity, as this harmony is 
called, would not be apparent. Now the cube of salt deposited from 
saturated solution is an expression to eye and touch of a moie or less 
permanent association of the types of energy labelled Na and CI 
respectively. It is not true that Na and CI are present in salt ; they 
are potentially present in the sense that under certain conditions these 
two loci emerge from the complex with the same value they possessed 
when they entered it. NaCl is a new energy complex capable of 
reacting in its own appropriate way (dependent upon its own genetic 
mode) and is different from either Na or CI. It is not an algebraic 
sum of the energies Na and CI, but a trajectory resulting from their 
blending. Salt occupies a definite position in nature and is capable 
of impressing its energy upon other energic units in a way peculiarly 
its own. Thus, no other substance tastes as salt does. Now if there 
be an intrinsic side of the activity, NaCl, that too may be totally un- 
like that of any other chemical substance. We say salt has an affinity 
for water. Does it thirst? When the human organism is dehydrated 
by evaporation due to exercise or the injestion of water imbibing sub- 
stances, the state of receptivity to water or disturbed equilibrium 
existing in the tissues of the body is converted into a special nervous 
Ejection which may even become an element in consciousness and 
build up the most elaborate system of associations. But at some 
early point in this process we may discover simply living tissue need- 
ing water and back of this certain chemical substances with an affinity 
for water — in other words, exactly the same thing that NaCl has. 

This disposition to change its form by uniting with another ele- 
ment is illustrated by the formation of all solutions and it is a mistake 
to suppose that a substance in solution is the same as a substance in 
solid form. It has claims to be called the same substance only because 
it can be evaporated out. But in the course of this process there is 
always a complete change of properties. Solid salt is not salty to the 
taste, salt in solution is not cubical. In short, we must school our- 
selves to see in the so-called elements or substances energic complexes 
whose form (nature) is at once determined by their primary locus 
formula and the impact or effect of the environment. So true is this 
that any substance can be fully understood only by knowing its pri- 



56 GENETIC MODES AND THE PSYCHIC. 

mary form and also the totality of its reaction with the environment. 
This is perhaps quite unlike our naive apprehension of objects which 
seem to have complete objective independence. The simplest experi- 
ment illustrates the error, however. We suddenly remove the support 
beneath the vase and instead of a thing-of -beauty in repose, we have a 
thing-in-motion and then a thing-in-a-hundred-pieces. The vase is 
just as really dependent, so far as being what it seems is concerned, 
on connections with the environment as the flower is which withers 
when removed from the parent stem. 

Now the existence of any typical form of energy, say a crystal, in 
any energic complex is a fact of interaction. If a broken crystal is 
plunged into a suitable medium, it will be restored (this process goes 
on in rocks in case of metamorphism) . The presence of the crystal 
acts as a determinant for the aggregation of other masses. The 
extraneous energy associates itself with the preexisting types in accord- 
ance with the types of energy already called into being. The most 
noted instance of this power is in the case of animate matter. The 
most astounding fact in nature is perhaps the power of a worm or a 
man to ingest the same materials and create in one case worm sub- 
stance and in the other human tissue. In the case of the crystal there 
may be millions of microliths contained in one crystal and all are alike 
or similar. In the case of the man there are millions of cells and we 
are able to distinguish groups of coordinated types. 

The harmony between a particular energic type and its environ- 
ment may be relatively stable or it may be dependent upon a high 
degree of constancy or invariability in that environment. Again, the 
energic unit may be progressively alternating or cyclical. Such a 
condition is found in the individual life which, like the trajectory of a 
planet, passes through a variety of progressively adjusted relations to 
the environment or comes into relation progressively to different 
environments. That type of energic unit which passes consecutively 
into relations with different energic complexes will alter its locus 
formula. When water passes into a gaseous state it is no longer 
water. 

Here is a moving point. I, as a geometer, make * cross -sections' 
of that point in relation to its environment and construct a locus (say 
y — 2px) . But in doing all this I have not produced the concept of 
a parabola such as I get when I see one. I go on varying the locus 
formula and produce successively a circle, an ellipse, etc. You may 
say that these things can be predicted in advance. The series of locus 
formulae might be, but no power would enable us to experience a 



DISCUSSION, 57 

circle till I saw it. Each new form has a meaning (differentia) in 
experience peculiar to it. 

Now, as a biologist, I have no doubt that the various sense organs 
arose by successive variations from some primitive type. As dynamic 
monist (or functional psychologist, if you prefer), I consider the 
psychical and physical to be two ways of expressing a real activity. 
But, as ' psychic' (Baldwin's limitation^), my subjective experience is 
very different when visual and tactual sensations respectively are 
evoked. As has so often been said, there is no reason why certain 
vibrations awaken sensations of green and others of sweet. 

When eyes came in vogue, a new thing, a new ' genetic mode ' 
arose. You could never have predicted it. You might have pre- 
dicted the size and form of the rods and cones and the index of re- 
fraction of the lens but the subjective interpretation in intimate ex- 
perience is not a priori predictable. It is conceivable that a child 
might, by unconscious movements, happen upon a sensation entirely 
new to it. The series of ' psychic ' events is not subject to scientific 
analysis. The subsequent psychological construction is wholly syn- 
thetic and consists in relational redistribution and combination. These 
may be construed among themselves and with other facts which we do 
not call psychological. 

It may be said that the modes of immediate consciousness are the 
only ones that could be genetic in this sense, that all others could be 
predicted from the earlier. These are doubtless the only ones we can 
know anything about. The power of prediction rests upon the pre- 
sumption of the cyclical nature of action — ' uniformities * we call 
these cycles, whether heart-beats or eclipses. If we project these 
cycles on a ' cross-section ' of experience, our predictions are valid in 
that plane. We may have as complete a system as possible plotted by 
our science, like a plot of hundreds of observations upon some mov- 
able star and may, on this basis, lay out the orbit fully upon the plane 
of experience, but this is not the same thing as the star moving in 
space. The 'meaning 'of this we could perhaps only discover by 
being the star. All this may be another name for the limitation of 
knowledge, but it is a necessary limitation of knowledge and has to be 
reckoned with. But if a thing be truly genetic, every new stage is 
really new and not a repetition, nor can we know from the past what 
new value may attach to the progressive modifications. We must let 
go of the cause-and-effect traditions — never backward turn the wheels 
of time. 

1 Baldwin's Diet, ofPhilos,, art. * Psychic or Mental.' 



58 GENETIC MODES AND THE PSYCHIC. 

A corollary is that another stegc of being is * 'genetically ' possible 
in which the energy of the present shall be elaborated in such forms 
as may present to experience something totally inconceivable to ' the 
heart of man.' 

The further question arises, however, (and this is not so easy to 
answer) if genetic (psychic)* modes arise that have no predicaments 
in the past and no necessary determinants in the present, how do they 
cohere in a universe — how belong in an organic whole ? The answer 
is, ''They do not:' 

The * psychic,' as psychic, is neither parallel to anything nor set 
in any kind of serial, or other, nexus with anything else. Anything 
possessing such relations would necessarily be predictable, /. «., to a 
being having complete knowledge. But no being can know what I 
feel. All tht generalizations I make regarding the data furnished in 
immediate consciousness (everything psychologica:!, in other words) I 
may relate or communicate, the peculiar tone or flavor of conscious- 
ness (its meaning) can neither be imparted nor anticipated. When we 
develop an organ for the ultra-violet rays we shall experience a new 
* genetic mode,' but if the anticipations of science go far enough, we 
may not thereby get a single new psychological element ; we shall 
simply find a value for this particular x and all is in. 

This sphere of epiphenomena can only be interpreted by reference 
to the metaphysical predicate of individuality. The three necessary 
forms or categories of our thinking, time, space and mode, each con- 
tributes to the definiteness of experience by conditioning it. Mode is 
that condition which is indispensable to individuality. Time is the 
necessary y<7r»« of inner experience, space of outer experience, mode 
is prerequisite to a// experience — it is the form of all experience. 

We do not expect to encounter space or time ' spatzierend ' by 
themselves. We do not try to line them up with the contents of special 
experiences and to make them cohere in a system with these. No 
more can we take the predicament of individuality in experience and 
set it in relations. I can say a great deal about green things. I can 
predict that they will arrive in April in special forms, but that which 
miakes greenness different from sweetness or b flat belongs to the 
formal category of mode. We have a sense of spatial extension, of 
temporal limitation, and, in like manner of special peculiarity. This 
is the tag which gives rise to the sense of other-ness or difference. 

■ It does not appear that Professor Baldwin limits genetic modes to the 
psychic, but I am of the opinion that it is safe to nae that term only within these 
limits, if non-predicableness is insisted on in their definition. 



DISCUSSION, 59 

So far as we are concerned, then, the genetic modes find their 
illustrations in the psychic — in our own peculiar content of experience, 
but it may be that every form of self-centered experience — all forms 
of vector activity, at least — have their inner meaning and that this, 
again, is reflected upon the great centre of reference of the whole sys- 
tem as a total meaning. This form of self- interpretation of energy 
that we call consciousness may be one of an innumerable multitude of 
similar incommunicable experiences which taken together form the 
real ' meaning' of the world. 

C. L. Herrick.* 

FORMBRLY OF DKNISON IjNrVKRSITY. 

1 Deceased. 



CORRIGENDA. 

In Dr. Hughes' article, * Categories of the Self,' The 
Review, Vol. VIII., 6, p. 405, line i, read * instinctive ' for 
* instructive ' ; p. 411, line 13, read • the self is not homogenous/ 

In Miss Vichelkowska's article, in the November issue also, 
p- 385* line 7 from the bottom, omit words * and diagonal'; 
line 5 from bottom, add words * See key to Fig. 4a.* 



60 



N. S. Vol. XIV. No. 2. March, 1907. 



The Psychological Review. 



THE PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY.^ 

BY PROFESSOR JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL, 
University of Chicago. 

Functional psychology is at the present moment little more 
than a point of view, a program, an ambition. It gains its vi- 
tality primarily perhaps as a protest against the exclusive excel- 
lence of another starting point for the study of the mind, and it 
enjoys for the time being at least the peculiar vigor which com- 
monly attaches to Protestantism of any sort in its early stages 
before it has become respectable and orthodox. The time 
seems ripe to attempt a somewhat more precise characterization 
of the field of functional psychology than has as yet been of- 
fered. What we seek is not the arid and merely verbal defini- 
tion which to many of us is so justly anathema, but rather an 
informing appreciation of the motives and ideals which animate 
the psychologist who pursues this path. His status in the eye 
of the psychological public is unnecessarily precarious. The 
conceptions of his purposes prevalent in non-functionalist circles 
range from positive and dogmatic misapprehension, through 
frank mystification and suspicion up to moderate compre- 
hension. Nor is this fact an expression of anything peculiarly 
abstruse and recondite in his intentions. It is due in part to his 
own ill-defined plans, in part to his failure to explain lucidly 
exactiy what he is about. Moreover, he is fairly numerous and 
it is not certain that in all important particulars he and his con- 
freres are at one in their beliefs. The considerations which are 

1 Delivered in substantially the present form as the President's Annnal Ad- 
dress before the American Psychological Association at its fifteenth annnal 
meeting held at Columbia University, New York City, December 27, 28 and 
29, 1906. 

61 



62 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

herewith offered suffer inevitably from this personal limitation. 
No psychological council of Trent has as yet pronounced upon 
the true faith. But in spite of probable failure it seems worth 
while to hazard an attempt at delineating the scope of function- 
alist principles. I formally renounce any intention to strike out 
new plans ; I am engaged in what is meant as a dispassionate 
summary of actual conditions. 

Whatever else it may be, functional psychology is nothing 
wholly new. In certain of its phases it is plainly discernible in 
the psychology of Aristotle and in its more modern garb it has 
been increasingly in evidence since Spencer wrote his Psy- 
chology and Darwin his Origin of Species, Indeed, as we 
shall soon see, its crucial problems are inevitably incidental to 
any serious attempt at understanding mental life. All that is 
peculiar to its present circumstances is a higher degree of self- 
consciousness than it possessed before, a more articulate and 
persistent purpose to organize its vague intentions into tangible 
methods and principles. 

A survey of contemporary psychological writing indicates, 
as was intimated in the preceding paragraph, that the task of 
functional psychology is interpreted in several different ways. 
Moreover, it seems to be possible to advocate one or more of 
these conceptions while cherishing abhorrence for the others. I 
distinguish three principal forms of the functional problem with 
sundry subordinate variants. It will contribute to the clarifica- 
tion of the general situation to dwell upon these for fi moment, 
after which I propose to maintain that they are substantially but 
modifications of a single problem. 

I. 
There is to be mentioned first the notion which derives most 
immediately from contrast with the ideals and purposes of struc- 
tural psychology so-called.^ This involves the identification of 
functional psychology with the effort to discern and portray the 

^The most Indd exposition of the •trnctnralist poeition still remains, so far 
as I know, Titchener's paper, * The Postulates of a Stmctnral Psychology,' 
miosophical Review, 1898 [VII.], p. 499. Cf. also the critical-oontroversial 
papers of Caldwell, Psychoixx^icai, Rbvibw, 1899, p. 187, and Titchener, 
I^ilosophical Review, 1899 [VIII.], p. 390. 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 63 

typical operations of consciousness under actual life conditions, 
as over against the attempt to analyze and describe its elemen- 
tary and complex contents. The structural psychology of sen- 
sation, e. g.^ undertakes to determine the number and character 
of the various unanalyzable sensory materials, such as the vari- 
eties of color, tone, taste, etc. The functional psychology of 
sensation would on the other hand find its appropriate sphere 
of interest in the determination of the character of the various 
sense activities as differing in their modus operandi from one 
another and from other mental processes such as judging, con- 
ceiving, willing and the like. 

In this its older and more pervasive form functional psychol- 
ogy has until very recent times had no independent existence. 
No more has structural psychology for that matter. It is only 
lately that any motive for the differentiation of the two has ex- 
isted and structural psychology — granting its claims and preten- 
sions of which more anon — is the first, be it said, to isolate 
itself. But in so far as functional psychology is synonymous 
with descriptions and theories of mental action as distinct from 
the materials of mental constitution, so far it is everywhere 
conspicuous in psychological literature from the earliest times 
down. 

Its fundamental intellectual prepossessions are often revealed 
by the classifications of mental process adopted from time to 
time. Witness the Aristotelian bipartite division of intellect and 
will and the modern tripartite division of mental activities. 
What are cognition, feeling and will but three basally distinct 
modes of mental action ? To be sure this classification has often 
carried with it the assertion, or at least the implication, that 
these fundamental attributes of mental life were based upon the 
presence in the mind of corresponding and ultimately distinct 
mental elements. But so far as concerns our momentary inter- 
est this fact is irrelevant. The impressive consideration is that 
the notion of definite and distinct forms of mental action is 
clearly in evidence and even the much-abused faculty psychol- 
ogy is on this point perfectly sane and perfectly lucid. The 
mention of this classic target for psychological vituperation 
recalls the fact that when the critics of functionalism wish to be 



64 JAMBS ROWLAND ANGBLL 

particularly unpleasant, they refer to it as a bastard offspring 
of the faculty psychology masquerading in biological plumage. 

It must be obvious to any one familiar with psychological 
usage in the present year of grace that in the intent of the dis- 
tinction herewith described certain of our familiar psychological 
categories are primarily structural — such for instance as affec- 
tion and image — whereas others immediately suggest more 
explicit functional relationships — for example, attention and 
reasoning. As a matter of fact it seems clear that so long as 
we adhere to these meanings of the terms structural and func- 
tional every mental event can be treated from either point of 
view, from the standpoint of describing its detectable contents 
and from the standpoint of characteristic mental activity differ- 
entiate from other forms of mental process. In the practice 
of our familiar psychological writers both undertakings are 
somewhat indiscriminately combined. 

The more extreme and ingenuous conceptions of structural 
psychology seem to have grown out of an unchastened indul- 
gence in what we may call the ^ states of consciousness ' doc- 
trine. I take it that this is in reality the contemporary version 
of Locke's * idea.' If you adopt as your material for psycho- 
ogical analysis the isolated ^ moment of consciousness,' it is very 
easy to become so absorbed in determining its constitution as to 
be rendered somewhat oblivious to its artificial character. The 
most essential quarrel which the functionalist has with structur- 
alism in its thoroughgoing and consistent form arises from this 
fact and touches the feasibility and worth of the effort to get at 
mental process as it is under the conditions of actual experience 
rather than as it appears to a merely postmortem analysis. It 
is of course true that for introspective purposes we must in a 
sense always work with vicarious representatives of the particu- 
lar mental processes which we set out to observe. But it makes 
a great difference even on such terms whether one is directing 
attention primarily to the discovery of the way in which such a 
mental process operates, and what the conditions are under 
which it appears, or whether one is engaged simply in teasing 
apart the fibers of its tissues. The latter occupation is useful 
and for certain purposes essential, but it often stops short of 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 65 

that which is as a life phenomenon the most essential, 1. e.y the 
modus operandi of the phenomenon. 

As a matter of fact many modern investigations of an ex- 
perimental kind largely dispense with the usual direct form of 
introspection and concern themselves in a distinctly functionalist 
tic spirit with a determination of what work is accomplished and 
what the conditions are under which it is achieved. Many ex- 
periments in memory and association, for instance, are avow- 
edly of this character. 

The functionalist is committed vom Grunde auf to the avoid- 
ance of that special form of the psychologist's fallacy which 
consists in attributing to mental states without due warrant, as 
part of their overt constitution in the moment of experience, 
characteristics which subsequent reflective analysis leads us to 
suppose they must have possessed. When this precaution is no- 
scrupulously observed we obtain a sort of fdte defoie gras psy- 
chology in which the mental conditions portrayed contain more 
than they ever naturally would or could hold. 

It should be added that when the distinction is made be- 
tween psychic structure and psychic function, the anomalous 
position of structure as a category of mind is often quite forgot- 
ten. In mental life the sole appropriateness of the term struc- 
ture hinges on the fact that any moment of consciousness can 
be regarded as a complex capable of analysis, and the terms 
into which our analyses resolve such complexes are the ana- 
logues — and obviously very meager and defective ones at that 
— of the structures of anatomy and morphology. 

The fact that mental contents are evanescent and fleeting 
marks them off in an important way from the relatively per- 
manent elements of anatomy. No matter how much we may 
talk of the preservation of psychical dispositions, nor how many 
metaphors we may summon to characterize the storage of ideas 
in some hypothetical deposit chamber of memory, the obstinate 
fact remains that when we are not experiencing a sensation or 
an idea it is, strictly speaking, non-existent. Moreover, when 
we manage by one or another device to secure that which we 
designate the same sensation or the same idea, we not only 
have no guarantee that our second edition is really a replica of 



66 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

the first, we have a good bit of presumptive evidence that from 
the content point of view the original never is and never can be 
literally duplicated. 

Functions, on the other hand, persist as well in mental as in 
physical life. We may never have twice exactly the same idea 
viewed from the side of sensuous structure and composition. 
But there seems nothing whatever to prevent our having as 
often as we will contents of consciousness which mean the same 
thing. They function in one and the same practical way, how- 
ever discrepant their momentary texture. The situation is rudely 
analogous to the biological case where very different structures 
may under different conditions be called on to perform identical 
functions ; and the matter naturally harks back for its earliest 
analogy to the instance of protoplasm where functions seem 
very tentatively and imperfectly differentiated. Not only then 
are general functions like memory persistent, but special func- 
tions such as the memory of particular events are persistent and 
largely independent of the specific conscious contents called 
upon from time to time to subserve the functions. 

When the structural psychologists define their field as that 
of mental -process^ they really preempt under a fictitious name 
the field of function, so that I should be disposed to allege fear- 
lessly and with a clear conscience that a large part of the 
doctrine of psychologists of nominally structural proclivities is 
in point of fact precisely what I mean by one essential part of 
functional psychology, /. tf., an account of psychical operations. 
Certain of the official exponents of structuralism explicitly lay 
claim to this as their field and do so with a flourish of scientific 
rectitude. There is therefore after all a small but nutritious 
core of agreement in the structure-function apple of discord. 
For this reason, as well as because I consider extremely useful 
the analysis of mental life into its elementary forms, I regard 
much of the actual work of my structuralist friends with highest 
respect and confidence. I feel, however, that when they use 
the term structural as opposed to the term functional to desig- 
nate their scientific creed they often come perilously near to 
using the enemy's colors. 

Substantially identical with this first conception of functional 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 67 

psychology, but phrasing itself somewhat differently, is the view 
which regards the functional problem as concerned with dis- 
covering how and why conscious processes are what they are, 
instead of dwelling as the structuralist is supposed to do upon 
the problem of determining the irreducible elements of con- 
sciousness and their characteristic modes of combination. I 
have elsewhere defended the view that however it may be in 
other sciences dealing with life phenomena, in psychology at 
least the answer to the question *■ what' implicates the answer 
to the questions * how ' and * why.' * 

Stated briefly the ground on which this position rests is as 
follows : In so far as you attempt to analyze any particular state 
of consciousness you find that the mental elements presented to 
your notice are dependent upon the particular exigencies and 
conditions which call them forth. Not only does the affective 
coloring of such a psychical moment depend upon one's tem- 
porary condition, mood and aims, but the very sensations them- 
selves are determined in their qualitative texture by the totality 
of circumstances subjective and objective within which they 
arise. You cannot get a fixed and definite color sensation for 
example, without keeping perfectly constant the external and 
internal conditions in which it appears. The particular sense 
quality is in short functionally determined by the necessities of 
the existing situation which it emerges to meet. If you inquire 
then deeply enough what particular sensation you have in a 
given case, you always find it necessary to take account of the 
manner in which, and the reasons why, it was experienced at 
all. You may of course, if you will, abstract from these con- 
siderations, but in so far as you do so, your analysis and descrip- 
tion is manifestly partial and incomplete. Moreover, even when 
you do so abstract and attempt to describe certain isolable sense 
qualities, your descriptions are of necessity couched in terms 
not of the experienced quality itself, but in terms of the condi- 
tions which produced it, in terms of some other quality with 
which it is compared, or in terms of some more overt act to 
which the sense stimulation led. That is to say, the very 

1 ' The Relations of Structural and Functional Psychology to Philosophy,' 
Philosophical Review^ 1903 [XII.], p. 203 ff. 



68 JAMES ROWLAND ANGRLL 

description itself is functionalistic and must be so. The truth 
of this assertion can be illustrated and tested by appeal to any 
situation in which one is trying to reduce sensory complexes, 
€. g.y colors or sounds, to their rudimentary components. 

II. 

A broader outlook and one more frequently characteristic of 
contemporary writers meets us in the next conception of the task 
of functional psychology. This conception is in part a reflex 
of the prevailing interest in the larger formulae of biology and 
particularly the evolutionary hypotheses within whose majestic 
sweep is nowadays included the history of the whole stellar 
universe ; in part it echoes the same philosophical call to new 
life which has been heard as pragmatism, as humanism, even 
as functionalism itself. I should not wish to commit either 
party by asserting that functional psychology and pragmatism 
are ultimately one. Indeed, as a psychologist I should hesitate 
to bring down on myself the avalanche of metaphysical invec- 
tive which has been loosened by pragmatic writers. To be 
sure pragmatism has slain its thousands, but I should cherish 
scepticism as to whether functional psychology would the more 
speedily slay its tens of thousands by announcing an offensive 
and defensive alliance with pragmatism. In any case I only hold 
that the two movements spring from similar logical motivation 
and rely for their vitality and propagation upon forces closely 
germane to one another. 

The functional psychologist then in his modern attire is in- 
terested not alone in the operations of mental process considered 
merely of and by and for itself, but also and more vigorously in 
mental activity as part of a larger stream of biological forces 
which are daily and hourly at work before our eyes and which 
are constitutive of the most important and most absorbing part 
of our world. The psychologist of this stripe is wont to take 
his cue from the basal conception of the evolutionary movement, 
I. ^., that for the most part organic structures and functions 
possess their present cl^aracteristics by virtue of the efficiency 
with which they fit into the extant conditions of life broadly 
designated the environment. With this conception in mind he 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 69 

proceeds to attempt some understanding of the manner in which 
the psychical contributes to the furtherance of the sum total of 
organic activities, not alone the psychical in its entirety, but 
especially the psychical in its particularities — mind as judging, 
mind as feeling, etc. 

This is the point of view which instantly brings the psychol- 
ogist cheek by jowl with the general biologist. It is the pre- 
supposition of every philosophy save that of outright ontological 
materialism that mind plays the stellar r61e in all the environ- 
mental adaptations of animals which possess it. But this per- 
suasion has generally occupied the position of an innocuous 
truism or at best a jejune postulate, rather than that of a 
problem requiring, or permitting, serious scientific treatment. 
At all events, this was formerly true. 

This older and more complacent attitude toward the matter 
is, however, being rapidly displaced by a conviction of the need 
for light on the exact character of the accommodatory service 
represented by the various great modes of conscious expression. 
Such an effort if successful would not only broaden the founda- 
tions for biological appreciation of the intimate nature of accom- 
modatory process, it would also immensely enhance the psychol- 
ogist's interest in the exact portrayal of conscious life. It is of 
course the latter consideration which lends importance to the 
matter from our point of view. Moreover, not a few practical 
consequences of value may be expected to flow from this at- 
tempt, if it achieves even a measurable degree of success. 
Pedagogy and mental hygiene both await the quickening and 
guiding counsel which can only come from a psychology of this 
stripe. For their purposes a strictly structural psychology is as 
sterile in theory as teachers and psychiatrists have found it, in 
practice. 

As a concrete example of the transfer of attention from the 
more general phases of consciousness as accommodatory ac- 
tivity to the particularistic features of the case may be men- 
tioned the rejuvenation of interest in the quasi-biological field 
which we designate animal psychology. This movement is 
surely among the most pregnant with which we meet in our 
own generation. Its problems are in no sense of the merely 



70 JAMBS ROWLAND ANGELL 

theoretical and speculative kind, although, like all scientific 
endeavor, it possesses an intellectual and methodological back- 
ground on which such problems loom large. But the frontier 
upon which it is pushing forward its explorations is a region of 
definite, concrete fact, tangled and confused and often most dif- 
ficult of access, but nevertheless a region of fact, accessible like 
all other facts to persistent and intelligent interrogation. 

That many of the most fruitful researches in this field have 
been achievements of men nominally biologists rather than 
psychologists in no wise affects the merits of the case. A 
similar situation exists in the experimental psychology of sen- 
sation where not a little of the best work has been accomplished 
by scientists not primarily known as psychologists. 

It seems hardly too much to say that the empirical concep- 
tions of the consciousness of the lower animals have undergone 
a radical alteration in the past few years by virtue of the studies 
in comparative psychology. The splendid investigations of the 
mechanism of instinct, of the facts and methods of animal 
orientation, of the scope and character of the several sense 
processes, of the capabilities of education and the range of 
selective accommodatory capacities in the animal kingdom, 
these and dozens of other similar problems have received for 
the first time drastic scientific examination, experimental in 
character wherever possible, observational elsewhere, but ob- 
servational in the spirit of conservative non-anthropomorphism 
as earlier observations almost never were. In most cases they 
have to be sure but shown the way to further and more precise 
knowledge, yet there can be but little question that the trail 
which they have blazed has success at its farther end. 

One may speak almost as hopefully of human genetic psy- 
chology which has been carried on so profitably in our own 
country. As so often in psychology, the great desideratum 
here, is the completion of adequate methods which will insure 
really stable scientific results. But already our general psy- 
chological theory has been vitalized and broadened by the 
results of the genetic methods thus far elaborated. These 
studies constantly emphasize for us the necessity of getting the 
longitudinal rather than the transverse view of life phenomena 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 7^ 

and they keep immediately in our field of vision the basic sig- 
nificance of growth in mental process. Nowhere is the differ- 
ence more flagrant between a functional psychology and the 
more literal minded type of structural psychology. One has 
only to compare with the better contemporary studies some of 
the pioneer work in this field, conceived in the more static and 
structuralistic manner, as Preyer's for example was, to feel at 
once the difference and the immensely greater significance 
both for theory and for practice which issues from the func- 
tional and longitudinal descriptions. 

The assertions which we have permitted ourselves about 
genetic psychology are equally applicable to pathological psy- 
chology. The technique of scientific investigation is in the 
nature of the case often different in this field of work from that 
characteristic of the other ranges of psychological research. 
But the attitude of the investigator is distinctly functionalistic. 
His aim is one of a thoroughly vital and generally practical 
kind leading him to emphasize precisely those considerations 
which our analysis of the main aspects of functional psychology 
disclose as the goal of its peculiar ambitions. 

It is no purpose of mine to submerge by sheer tour deforce 
the individuality of these various scientific interests just men- 
tioned in the regnant personality of a functional psychology. 
But I am firmly convinced that the spirit which gives them 
birth is the spirit which in the realms of general psychological 
theory bears the name functionalism. I believe, therefore, 
that their ultimate fate is certain, still I have no wish to accel- 
erate their translation against their will, nor to inflict upon them 
a label which they may find odious. 

It should be said, however, in passing, that even on the side 
of general theory and methodological conceptions, recent de- 
velopments have been fruitful and significant. One at least 
of these deserves mention. 

We find nowadays both psychologists and biologists who 
treat consciousness as substantially synonymous with adaptive 
reactions to novel situations. In the writings of earlier authori- 
ties it is often implied that accommodatory activities may be 
purely physiological and non-psychical in character. From 



72 JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL 

this view-point the mental type of accommodatory act super- 
venes on certain occasions and at certain stages in organic 
development, but it is no indispensable feature of the accom- 
modatory process.* 

It seems a trifle strange when one considers how long the 
fundamental conception involved in this theory has been familiar 
and accepted psychological doctrine that its full implication 
should have been so reluctantly recognized.* If one takes the 
position now held by all psychologists of repute, so far as I am 
aware, that consciousness is constantly at work building up 
habits out of coordinations imperfectly under control ; and that 
as speedily as control is gained the mental direction tends to 
subside and give way to a condition approximating physiological 
automatism, it is only a step to carry the inference forward that 
consciousness immanently considered is fer se accommodation 
to the novel. Whether conscious processes have been the pre- 
cursors of our present instinctive equipment depends on facts of 
heredity upon which a layman may hardly speak. But many 
of our leaders answer strongly in the affirmative, and such an 
answer evidently harmonizes with the general view now under 
discussion. 

To be sure the further assertion that no real organic accom- 
modation to the novel ever occurs, save in the form that involves 
consciousness, requires for its foundation a wide range of obser- 
vation and a penetrating analysis of the various criteria of men- 
tality. But this is certainly a common belief among biologists 
to-day. Selective variation of response to stimulation is the 
ordinary external sign indicative of conscious action. Stated 
otherwise, consciousness discloses the form taken on by primary 
accommodatory process. 

1 At this point there is obviously a possible ambiguity in the use of the term 
accommodatory. Any physiologically adequate process may be described as 
accommodatory. Respiration, for example, might be so designated. Clearly 
one needs a special term to designate accommodation to the novel, for this is 
the field of conscious activity. Of course if the contention be granted for 
which the view now under consideration stands, this could be called conscious 
accommodation and it would be understood forthwith that such accommodation 
was to the novel. 

«Cf. MscDougal's striking papers in Mind, 1898, entitled 'Contribution 
toward an Improvement in Psychological Method.' 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 73 

It is not unnatural perhaps that the frequent disposition of 
the functional psychologist to sigh after the flesh-pots of biology 
should kindle the fire of those consecrated to the c&use of a 
pure psychology and philosophy freed from the contaminating 
influence of natural science. As a matter of fact, alarms have 
been repeatedly sounded and the faithful called to subdue 
mutiny. But the purpose of the functional psychologist has 
never been, so far as I am aware, to scuttle the psychological 
craft for the benefit of biology. Quite the contrary. Psychol- 
ogy is still for a time at least to steer her own untroubled course. 
She is at most borrowing a well-tested compass which biology 
is willing to lend and she hopes by its aid' to make her ports 
more speedily and more surely. If in use it prove treacherous 
and unreliable, it will of course go overboard. 

This broad biological ideal of functional psychology of 
which we have been speaking may be phrased with a slight 
shift of emphasis by connecting it with the problem of discover- 
ing the fundamental utilities of consciousness. If mental proc- 
ess is of real value to its possessor in the life and world which 
we know, it must perforce be by virtue of something which it 
does that otherwise is not accomplished. Now life and world 
are complex and it seems altogether improbable that conscious- 
ness should express its utility in one and only one way. As a 
matter of fact, every surface indication points in the other direc- 
tion. It may be possible merely as a matter of expression to 
speak of mind as in general contributing to organic adjustment 
to environment. But the actual contributions will take place in 
many ways and by multitudinous varieties of conscious process. 
The functionalist's problem then is to determine if possible the 
great types of these processes in so far as the utilities which they 
present lend themselves to classification. 

The search after the various utilitarian aspects of mental 
process is at once suggestive and disappointing. It is on the 
one hand illuminating by virtue of the strong relief into which 
it throws the fundamental resemblances of processes often unduly 
severed in psychological analysis. Memory and imagination, 
for example, are often treated in a way designed to emphasize 
their divergences almost to the exclusion of their functional 



74 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

similarities. They are of course functionally but variants on a 
single and basal type of control. An austere structuralism in 
particular is inevitably disposed to magnify differences and in 
consequence under its hands mental life tends to fall apart ; and 
when put together again it generally seems to have lost some- 
thing of its verve and vivacity. It appears stiff and rigid and 
corpse-like. It lacks the vital spark. Functionalism tends just 
as inevitably to bring mental phenomena together, to show them 
focalized in actual vital service. The professional psychol- 
ogisty calloused by long apprenticeship » may not feel this dis- 
tinction to be scientifically important. But to the young student 
the functionalistic stress upon community of service is of im- 
mense value in clarifying the intricacies of mental organization. 
On the other hand the search of which we were speaking is dis- 
appointing perhaps in the paucity of the basic modes in which 
these conscious utilities are realized. 

Ultimately all the utilities are possibly reducible to selective 
accommodation. In the execution of the accommodatory activ- 
ity the instincts represent the racially hereditary utilities, many 
of which are under the extant conditions of life extremely anom- 
alous in their value. The sensory- algedonic-motor phenomena 
represent the immediate short circuit unreflective forms of select- 
ive response. Whereas the ideational-algedonic-motor series at 
its several levels represents the long circuit response under the 
influence of the mediating effects of previous experience. This 
experience serves either to inhibit the propulsive power intrinsic 
to the stimulus, or to reinforce this power by adding to it its 
own dynamic tendencies. This last variety of action is the 
peculiarly human form of mediated control. On its lowest 
stages, genetically speaking, it merges with the purely imme- 
diate algedonic type of response. All the other familiar psy- 
chological processes are subordinate to one or more of these 
groups. Conception, judgment, reasoning, emotion, desire, 
aversion, volition, etc., simply designate special varieties in 
which these generic forms appear. 

In facing the problem of classifying functions we may well 
turn for a moment to the experience of biologists for suggestions. 
It is to be remarked at once that the significance of function as 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 75 

a basis for biological classification varies greatly in different 
parts of the biological field. Among the more complex animal 
organisms, for example, function, as compared with structure, 
affords a relatively precarious basis of classification, since very 
divergent structures may subserve identical functions. More- 
over, the functions merely as such often fail to indicate with the 
definiteness characteristic of the anatomical structure the genetic 
relations involved in the maturing of a form. But in the study 
of the lower orders of life such as the bacteria, where structural 
variations are so largely to seek, the functional chemico-physio- 
logical reactions are of the utmost significance for classificatory 
purposes. In the botanical field generally there has of late 
been an increasing disposition to employ functional similarity 
and difference for the illumination of plant relationships. 
Indeed, this transition from a purely taxonomic and morpho- 
logical point of view to a physiological and functional point of 
view is the striking feature of recent progress in botanical theory. 

The ultimate value of a psychological classification based on 
functions, if interpreted in the light of these considerations, 
would apparently hinge on one's conception of the analogy 
between consciousness and undifferentiated protoplasm. In the 
measure in which consciousness is immanently unstable and 
variable, one might anticipate that a functional classification 
would be more significant and penetrating than one based upon 
any supposedly structural foundation. But the analogy on 
which this inference rests is perhaps too insecure to permit a 
serious conclusion to be drawn from it. In any event it is to 
be said that functions as such seem to be the most stable char- 
acters in the biological field. They extend in a practically 
unbroken front from the lowest to the highest levels of life — 
allowing for a possible protest in certain quarters against includ- 
ing consciousness in this list. That they are not everywhere 
80 useful as structures for classificatory purposes reflects on the 
aims of classification, not on the fundamental and relatively fixed 
character of functions. 

A survey of current usage discloses two general types of 
functional categories. Of these, the one is in spirit and purpose 
dominantly physiological. It groups all the forms of life func- 



76 JAMBS ROWLAND ANGBLL 

tions, whether animal or vegetable in manifestation, under the 
four headings of assimilation, reproduction, motion and sensi- 
bility. In such a schema assimilation is made to include diges- 
tion, circulation, respiration, secretion, and excretion, while 
motion in the sense here intended applies primarily to those 
forms of movement which enable the organism to migrate from 
place to place and thus accommodate itself to the exigencies of 
local conditions. 

Another group of categories which concerns a deeper and 
more general level of biological interpretations is given by 
such terms as selection, adaptation, variation, accommodation, 
heredity, etc. These are categories of a primarily functional 
sort for they apply in a large sense to modes of behavior. 
Indeed, behavior may be said to be itself the most inclusive of 
these categories. But as compared with the members of the 
first group they have to do with the general trend of organic 
development and not with the specific physiological processes 
which may be concerned in any special case. This does not 
mean that a specific physiological setting cannot sometime be 
given these problems ; but it does mean that at present the gaps 
in our knowledge of these matters are generally too large to be 
spanned with certainty. 

Now it would appear that such general categories as selec- 
tion and accommodation have a perfectly appropriate application 
to mental process. Indeed, as we have already remarked, not 
a few of our modern scientists regard the psychical as precisely 
synonymous with the selective — accommodatory activity as 
this appears in the life history of the individual ; and we have, 
moreover, already pointed out certain limitations and certain 
merits of these categories when applied to the classification of 
mental phenomena. We have found them serving to magnify 
a certain community of organic service in the most various forms 
of psychical activity, but we have also found them rather too 
vague and general to afford a desirable scientific detail. 

If on the other hand, we examine the familiar fhysiological 
functions with reference to their possible relations to mental 
functions, we are at once struck by certain similarities and 
certain disparities between the two. There are some mental 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 77 

operations which have repeatedly been designated as assimi- 
lative. So familiar is this characterization and so commonly 
accepted that we may without undue hesitation assume its appro- 
priateness and relevancy. Under the physiological aspects of 
assimilation are commonly ranged such processes as respiration, 
circulation, secretion, excretion etc. How far these processes 
find analogies in mental action is not altogether clear. Many 
of our psychologists are fond of describing * the stream of con- 
sciousness' and in so far as the metaphor is justifiable one may 
naturally think of the physiological circulation as its counter- 
part. But there are perhaps as many differences as there are 
resemblances between the two. Certainly the cyclical char- 
acter of the circulation of the blood finds no precise analogue 
in the flow of psychical phenomena. Similarly the periodicity 
of respiration may suggest the fluctuation of attention, the storing 
of mental dispositions may be connected with secretion, the 
casting off of mental irrelevancies may be likened to excretion, 
etc. But these relations are so largely metaphorical in char- 
acter that one can hardly assign them a larger consequence 
than springs from such amusement as they may afford. 

It would perhaps be difificult to disprove the theory that re- 
production can be regarded as a mental category quite as truly 
as a physiological category, not only in the sense in which one 
mind can be conceived as the parent of other minds, but also in 
the familiar sense in which the mind is thought of as recreating 
its own ideas from time to time. 

Yet granting all this, it may safely be said that however 
numerous the analogies connecting the mental functions with the 
physiological functions may be, we are not at present in a posi- 
tion to take advantage of them in any very serious way. Motion 
is by common consent applicable to the physiological alone and 
sensibility is in the intent of the classification appropriate to the 
psychical alone. The basal categories utilized by physiologists 
seem therefore to render us but little assistance. This view is 
vigorously maintained by many modern writers, but generally 
on a priori grounds. 

If we examine the historically conspicuous classifications of 
mental process made by psychologists, we discover, as was 



1^ JAMBS ROWLAND ANGBLL 

pointed out in an earlier paragraph, that they are frequently 
suggestive of definitely functional conceptions. The Aristotel- 
ian divisions, the so-called Kantian divisions, the divisions into 
higher and lower powers characteristic of the faculty psycholo- 
gists (and many others not commonly ranked as such), and Bren- 
tano's and Stouf s classifications, to mention no more, are all de- 
cidedly based on dynamic and f unctionalistic considerations. On 
the other hand, not a few of our contemporary authorities, notably 
Wundt, classify their material under the more statical and me- 
chanical categories — ^ elements and compounds.' 

Professor Warren has recently suggested an interesting clas- 
sification in which he proposes as the fundamental functional 
categories the following five : Sensibility, which gives us the 
sensory continuum ; modification, which connotes our ability to 
become aware of intensive modifications in the continuum ; dif* 
ferentiation, which covers our capacity to experience qualitative 
differences ; association, which does not require interpretation, 
and discrimination, which refers to our ability to perform defi- 
nite acts of rational apprehension and to articulate purposes.^ 
These functions taken together will, he alleges, account for all 
forms of consciousness and they are not derivatives from phe- 
nomena of the material world which he regards as outside the 
pale. I do not propose at this time to offer any detailed criti- 
cism of Professor Warren's valuable paper. Indeed, until his 
views are more fully elaborated, extended criticism would be 
premature. 

One distinction, however, to which he calls incidental atten- 
tion as a biological distinction, is formulated in an admirable 
statement with which I fully agree. It presents a sort of func- 
tional analysis which seems to me at once pregnant and sound. 
He speaks of the three-fold division of cognition, affection and 
conative process as intrinsically biological in character and 
corresponding broadly to the differences among the external, 
the systemic and the kinaesthetic senses ; the first reporting to 
us the outer world, the second our own general organic tone 
and the third supplying experiences of our motor activity by 
means of which voluntary control is developed. 

1 « The Fandamental Functions of Consciousness/ Psychological Bulletin, 
X)6, p. 217. 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 79 

Particularly significant is his remark that the * fundamental 
functions of consciousness and the kinds of experience' are 
something quite distinct from one another. It is because he 
believes that the * rise of any particular experience and its make- 
up as a datum of consciousness can be fully described in terms 
of certain mental functions ' that he feels it possible to elaborate 
an independent natural science of psychology free from neuro- 
logical, physiological and biological considerations. It is not 
clear that this conclusion flows from Professor Warren's premises 
any more exclusively than from the premises of the so-called 
structuralist's point of view. Nor is there any strictly logical 
impracticality in carrying out the program of such a pure psy- 
chology. But it is fair to emphasize the extremely pale, atten- 
uated and abstract character of such a science as compared with 
one which should report upon conscious processes as they are 
really found amid the heat and battle of the actual mind-body 
life. It may be a pure science, but it is surely purity bought 
at a great price — i. tf., truth to life. 

All pure science must abstract in a measure from the actual 
circumstances of life, but in the so-called exact sciences the 
abstraction is always away from the irrelevant and disturbing. 
The type of abstraction which Professor Warren champions, in 
common with many other distinguished scholars, is one which 
appeals to me as an abstracting away from the more significant, 
with the consequent fixation of attention upon the relatively less 
important. 

It is a commonplace of logic that classification is intrinsically 
teleological and that the merits of any special classification, 
assuming that it does not distort or misrepresent the facts, is to 
be tested by the success with which it meets the necessities for 
which it was devised. If one desires to emphasize the taxo- 
nomic and morphological features of mentality, no doubt some 
such division as Wundt employs, using the rubrics elements 
and compounds, is preferable. If one wishes primarily to 
emphasize qualitative similarities and dissimilarities, the Kan- 
tian principle of irreducibility is judicious ; and if one wishes to 
bring out the dynamic character of consciousness, such a 
principle as Brentano's, based on the mode in which conscious- 



8o JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL 

ness refers to its object, is effective. If functional psychology 
really possesses several distinct zones of interest, it is quite con- 
ceivable that different classifications may be necessary to fulfil 
most satisfactorily the demands in these several fields. In any 
case we must forego further discussion of the matter at this point 
and return to offer our description of the third of the main sub- 
divisions of the functional problem. 

III. 

The third conception which I distinguish is often in practice 
merged with the second, but it involves stress upon a problem 
logically prior perhaps to the problem raised there and so war- 
rants separate mention. Functional psychology, it is often 
alleged, is in reality a form of psychophysics. To be sure, its 
aims and ideals are not explicitly quantitative in the manner 
characteristic of that science as commonly understood. But it 
finds its major interest in determining the relations to one another 
of the physical and mental portions of the organism. 

It is undoubtedly true that many of those who write under 
functional prepossessions are wont to introduce frequent refer- 
ences to the physiological processes which accompany or con- 
dition mental life. Moreover, certain followers of this faith are 
prone to declare forthwith that psychology is simply a branch of 
biology and that we are in consequence entitled, if not indeed 
obliged, to make use where possible of biological materials. 
But without committing ourselves to so extreme a position as 
this, a mere glance at one familiar region of psychological pro- 
cedure will disclose the leanings of psychology in this direction. 

The psychology of volition affords an excellent illustration 
of the necessity with which descriptions of mental process 
eventuate in physiological or biological considerations. If one 
take the conventional analysis of a voluntary act drawn from 
some one or other of the experiences of adult life, the descrip- 
tions offered generally portray ideational activities of an antici- 
patory and deliberative character which serve to initiate imme- 
diately or remotely certain relevant expressive movements. 
Without the execution of the movements the ideational per- 
formances would be as futile as the tinkling cymbals of Scrip- 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 8l 

ture. To be sure, many of our psychologists protest themselves 
wholly unable to suggest why or how such muscular movements 
are brought to pass. But the fact of their occurrence or of their 
fundamental import for any theory of mental life in which con- 
sciousness is other than an epiphenomenon, is not questioned. 

Moreover, if one considers the usual accounts of the onto- 
genesis of human volitional acts one is again confronted with 
intrinsically physiological data in which reflexes, automatic and 
instinctive acts are much in evidence. Whatever the possibil- 
ities, then, of an expurgated edition of the psychology of voli- 
tion from which should be blotted out all reference to contam- 
inating physiological factors, the actual practice of our repre- 
sentative psychologists is quite otherwise, and upon their 
showing volition cannot be understood either as regards its 
origin or its outcome without constant and overt reference to 
these factors. It would be a labor of supererrogation to go on 
and make clear the same doctrine as it applies to the psychology 
of the more recondite of the cognitive processes ; so intimate is 
the relation between cognition and volition in modern psycho- 
logical theory that we may well stand excused from carrying 
out in detail the obvious inferences from the situation we have 
just described. 

Now if someone could but devise a method for handling the 
mind-body relationships which would not when published im- 
mediately create cyclonic disturbances in the philosophical at- 
mosphere, it seems improbable that this disposition of the func- 
tional psychologist to inject physiology into his cosmos would 
cause comment and much less criticism. But even parallelism, 
that most insipid, pale and passionless of all the inventions be- 
gotten by the mind of man to accomplish this end, has largely 
failed of its pacific purpose. It is no wonder, therefore, that 
the more rugged creeds with positive programs to offer and a 
stock of red corpuscles to invest in their propagation should also 
have failed of universal favor. 

This disposition to go over into the physiological for certain 
portions of psychological doctrine is represented in an interest- 
ing way by the frequent tendency of structural psychologists to 
find explanation in psychology substantially equivalent to 



82 JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL 

.physiological explanation.* Professor Titchener's recent work 
on Sluantitaiive Psychology represents this position very frankly. 
It is cited here with no intent to comment disparagingly upon 
the consistency of the structuralist position, but simply to indi- 
cate the wide-spread feeling of necessity at certain stages of 
psychological development for resort to physiological considera- 
tions. 

Such a functional psychology as I have been presenting 
would be entirely reconcilable with Miss Calkins' * psychology 
of selves ' (so ably set forth by her in her presidential address 
last year) were it not for her extreme scientific conservatism in 
refusing to allow the self to have a body, save as a kind of 
conventional biological ornament. The real psychological self, 
as I understand her, is pure disembodied spirit — an admirable 
thing of good religious and philosophic ancestry, but surely not 
the thing with which we actually get through this vale of tears 
and not a thing before which psychology is under any obliga- 
tion to kotow.* 

It is not clear that the functional psychologist because of his 

>Cf. Munsterberg's striking pronunciamento to this effect in his paper 
entitled ' Psychological Atomism, ' Psychoi^ogical Rbvibw, 1900, p. i. The same 
doctrine is incorporated in his * Grnndziige der Psychologic * and we await with 
interest the completion of that task in order to discover the characteristic features 
of a psychology consistently built on these foundations. 

' Miss Calkins' views on this matter, which are shared by many of our lead- 
ing psychologists, have been lucidly expounded on several papers [particularly 
' Der doppelte Standpunkt in der Psychologic,' and a * Reconciliation between 
Structural and Functional Psychology,' Psychoz.ogicai«R9vibw, 1906, p. 61], to 
say nothing of their embodiment in her widely quoted Introduction to Psy- 
chology. She has done yeoman service in emphasizing the fundamental sig- 
nificance of the ' self ' consciousness for all psychological doctrine and I am in 
entire sympathy with her insistence on this fact. But she seems to me unduly 
to circumscribe the legitimate scope of this 'self.' Possibly I misinterpret her 
meaning, but the following sentences together with the procedure in her Intro- 
duction to Psychology seem to justify me. " By self as fundamental fact of 
psychology is not meant . . . the psychophysical organism, . . . the objection 
is, very briefly, that the doctrine belongs not to psychology at all, but to 
biology," PSYCHOi^OGiCAi, Review, 1906, p. 66. After which reference is made 
to Professor Baldwin's Development and Evolution as a non -psychological 
treatise. Such a settlement of the issue is easy and logically consistent. But 
does it not leave us with a gulf set between the self as mind and the self as 
body, for the crossing of which we are forthwith obliged to expend much 
needless energy, as the gulf is of our own inventing ? 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 83 

disposition to magnify the significance in practice of the mind- 
body relationships is thereby committed to any special theory 
of the character of these relationships, save as was said a 
moment since, that negatively he must seemingly of necessity 
set his face against any epiphenomenalist view. He might con- 
ceivably be an interactionist, or a parallelist or even an advocate 
of some wholly outworn creed. As a matter of fact certain of 
our most ardent functionalists not only cherish highly definite 
articles of faith as regards this issue, they would even go so far 
as to test functional orthodoxy by the acceptance of these tenets. 
This is to them the most momentous part of their functionalism, 
their holy of holies. It would display needless temerity to at- 
tempt within the limitations of this occasion a formulation of 
doctrine wholly acceptable to all concerned. But I shall venture 
a brief reference to such doctrine in the effort to bring out 
certain of its essentials. 

The position to which I refer regards the mind-body relation 
as capable of treatment in psychology as a methodological dis- 
tinction rather than a metaphysically existential one. Certain 
of its expounders arrive at their view by means of an analysis 
of the genetic conditions under which the mind-body differen- 
tiation first makes itself felt in the experience of the individual.^ 
This procedure clearly involves a direct frontal attack on the 
problem. 

Others attain the position by flank movement, emphasizing 
to begin with the insoluble contradictions with which one is met 
when the distinction is treated as resting on existential differ- 
ences in the primordial elements of the cosmos.^ Both methods 
of approach lead to the same goal, however, 1. e.^ the convic- 
tion that the distinction has no existence on the genetically 
lower and more naif stages of experience. It only comes to 
light on a relatively reflective level and it must then be treated 

1 The most striking attempt of this kind with which I am acquainted is 
Professor Baldwin's paper entitled * Mind and Body from the Genetic Point of 
View,' PSYCHOLOGiCAi, Rbvibw, 1903, p. 225. 

< Cf. on this general issue Bawden, ' Functional View of the Relation 
Between the Psychical and the Physical,' Philosophical Review^ 1902, [XL], p. 
474, and 'Methodological Implications of the Mind-body Controversy,' Psycho- 
logical Bulleiin^ 1906, p. 321. 



84 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

as instrumental if one would avoid paralogisms, antinomies and 
a host of other metaphysical nightmares. Moreover, in deahng 
with psychological problems this view entitles one to reject as 
at least temporarily irrelevant the question whether mind causes 
changes in neural action and conversely. The previous ques- 
tion is raised by defenders of this type of doctrine if one insists 
on having such a query answered. They invite you to trace 
the lineage of your idea of causality, insisting that such a 
searching of one's intellectual reins will always disclose the 
inappropriateness of the inquiry as formulated above. They 
urge further that the profitable and significant thing is to seek 
for a more exact appreciation of the precise conditions under 
which consciousness is in evidence and the conditions under 
which it retires in favor of the more exclusively physiological. 
Such knowledge so far as it can be obtained is on a level with 
all scientific and practical information. It states the circum- 
stances under which certain sorts of results will appear. 

One's view of this f unctionalistic metaphysics is almost inev- 
itably colored by current philosophical discussion as to the essen- 
tial nature of consciousness. David Hume has been accused 
of destroying the reality of mind chiefly because he exorcised 
from it relationships of various kinds. If it be urged, as has 
so often been done, that Hume was guilty of pouring out the 
baby with the bath, the modern philosopher makes good the 
disaster not only by pouring in again both baby and bath, but 
by maintaining that baby and bath, mind and relations, are sub- 
stantially one.* Nor is this unity secured after the manner 

«To the simple-minded psychologist this saying, in which many authors 
indulge, that conscionsness is merely a relation seems a trifle dark. The psy- 
chologist has no natural prejudice against relation, but in this special case he 
is as a rule given too little information concerning the terms between which 
this relation subsists. Possibly his vision has been darkened by a perverse logic, 
but relations imply termini in his usual modes of thought and before assenting 
too unreservedly to the * relation • philosophy of consciousness, he urge* a 
fuller illumination as to the character and status of these supporting end terms. 

The following well-known papers will introduce the uninitiated, if any such 
there be, into the thick of the battle. A complete bibliography would probably 
monopolize this issue of the Rbview. James, « DoeP^nsciousness Exist?* 
/oufnal of Philosophy, Psychology and Scientific AfeUtbds, I., p. 477- Wood- 
bridge, • Nature of Consciousness,' in the same Journal, II., p. 119. Also Gar- 
man, * Memorial Volume,* p. 137. Perry, * Conceptions and Misconceptiona of 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 85 

prescribed by the good Bishop Berkeley. At all events the 
metaphysicians to whom I refer are not fond of being called 
idealists. But the psychological functionalist who emphasizes 
the instrumental nature of the mind-body distinction and the 
metaphysician who regards mind as a relation are following 
roads which are at least parallel to one another if not actually 
convergent. 

Whether or not one sympathizes with the views of that wing 
of the functionalist party to which our attention has just been 
directed it certainly seems a trifle unfair to cast up the mind-body 
difficulty in the teeth of the functionalist as such when on log- 
ical grounds he is no more guilty than any of his psychological 
neighbors. No courageous psychology of volition is possible 
which does not squarely face the mind -body problem^ and in 
point of fact every important description of mental life contains 
doctrine of one kind or another upon this matter. A literally 
pure psychology of volition would be a sort of hanging-garden 
of Babylon, marvelous but inaccessible to psychologists of ter- 
restrial habit. The functionalist is a greater sinner than others 
only in so far as he finds necessary and profitable a more con- 
stant insistence upon the translation of mental process into phy- 
siological process and conversely. 

IV. 

If we now bring together the several conceptions of which 
mention has been made it will be easy to show them converging 
upon a common point. We have to consider (i) functionalism 
conceived as the psychology of mental operations in contrast to 
the psychology of mental elements ; or, expressed otherwise, 
the psychology of the how and why of consciousness as dis- 
tinguished from the psychology of the what of consciousness. 
We have (2) the functionalism which deals with the problem of 
mind conceived as primarily engaged in mediating between the 
environment and the needs of the organism. This is the psy- 
chology of the fundamental utilities of consciousness ; (3) and 

Cooficionsness/ Psycho^,' "TCAL Rkvibw, 1904, XI., p. 282. Bush, * An Bxnpi- 
rical Definition of CoDsciot; utas^* Journal of Philosophy^ Psychology and Scien^ 
Hfic Methods, II., p. 561. Stratton, * Difference Between Mental and Phyaical,* 
Psychological Bulletin^ 1906, p. i. * Character of ConscionsnesB,' Ibid,^ p. 117. 



86 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

lastly we have functionalism described as psychophysical psy- 
chology, that is the psychology which constantly recognizes and 
insists upon the essential significance of the mind-body relation- 
ship for any just and comprehensive appreciation of mental life 
itself. 

The second and third delineations of functional psychology 
are rather obviously correlated with each other. No descrip- 
tion of the actual circumstances attending the participation of 
mind in the accommodatory activities of the organism could be 
other than a mere empty schematism without making reference 
to the manner in which mental processes eventuate in motor 
phenomena of the physiological organism. The overt accom- 
modatory act is, I take it, always sooner or later a muscular 
movement. But this fact being admitted, there is nothing for 
it, if one will describe accommodatory processes, but to recog- 
nize the mind-body relations and in some way give expression 
to their practical significance. It is only in this regard, as was 
indicated a few lines above, that the functionalist departs a trifle 
in his practice and a trifle more in his theory from the rank and 
file of his colleagues. 

The effort to follow the lead of the natural sciences and 
delimit somewhat rigorously — albeit artificially — a field of in- 
quiry, in this case consciousness conceived as an independent 
realm, has led in psychology to a deal of excellent work and to 
the uncovering of much hidden truth. So far as this proced- 
ure has resulted in a focusing of scientific attention and endeavor 
on a relatively narrow range of problems the result has more 
than justified the means. And the functionalist by no means 
holds that the limit of profitable research has been reached along 
these lines. But he is disposed to urge in season and out that 
we must not forget the arbitrary and self-imposed nature of the 
boundaries within which we toil when we try to eschew all ex- 
plicit reference to the physical and physiological. To overlook 
this fact is to substitute a psychology under injunction for a psy- 
chology under free jurisdiction. He also urges with vigor and 
enthusiasm that a new illumination of this preempted field can 
be gained by envisaging it more broadly, looking at it as it ap- 
pears when taken in perspective with its neighboring territory. 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 87 

And if it be objected that such an inquiry however interesting 
and advantageous is at least not psychology, he can only reply ; 
psychology is what we make it, and if the correct understand- 
ing of mental phenomena involves our delving in regions which 
are not at first glance properly mental, what recks it, provided 
only that we are nowhere guilty of untrustworthy and unveri- 
fiable procedure, and that we return loaded with the booty for 
which we set out, and by means of which we can the better 
solve our problem ? 

In its more basal philosophy this last conception is of course 
intimately allied to those appraisals of mind which emphasize 
its dominantly social characteristics, its rise out of social circum- 
stances and the pervasively social nature of its constitutive prin- 
ciples. In our previous intimations of this standpoint we have 
not distinguished sharply between the physical and the social 
aspect of environment. The adaptive activities of mind are 
very largely of the distinctly social type. But this does not in 
any way jeopardize the genuineness of the connection upon 
which we have been insisting between the psychophysical 
aspects of a functional psychology and its environmental adap- 
tive aspects. 

It remains then to point out in what manner the conception 
of functionalism as concerned with the basal operations of mind 
is to be correlated with the other two conceptions just under dis- 
cussion. The simplest view to take of the relations involved 
would apparently be such as would regard the first as an essen- 
tial propaedeutic to the other two. Certainly if we are intent 
upon discerning the exact manner in which mental process 
contributes to accommodatory efliciency, it is natural to begin 
our undertaking by determining what are the primordial forms 
of expression peculiar to mind. However plausible in theory 
this conception of the intrinsic logical relations of these several 
forms of functional psychology, in practice it is extremely diflS- 
cult wholly to sever them from one another. 

Again like the biological accommodatory view the psycho- 
physical view of functional psychology involves as a rational 
presupposition some acquaintance with mental processes as 
these appear to reflective consciousness. The intelligent corre- 



88 JAMBS ROWLAND ANGELL 

lation in a practical way of physiological and mental operations 
evidently involves a preliminary knowledge of the conspicuous 
differentiations both on the side of conscious function and on 
the side of physiological function. 

In view of the considerations of the last few paragraphs it 
does not seem fanciful nor forced to urge that these various 
theories of the problem of f untional psychology really converge 
upon one another, however divergent may be the introductory 
investigations peculiar to each of the several ideals. Possibly 
the conception that the fundamental problem of the functionalist 
is one of determining just how mind participates in accommo- 
datory reactions, is more nearly inclusive than either of the 
others, and so may be chosen to stand for the group. But if 
this vicarious duty is assigned to it, it must be on clear terms 
of remembrance that the other phases of the problem are 
equally real and equally necessary. Indeed the three things 
hang together as integral parts of a common program. 

The functionalist's most intimate persuasion leads him to re- 
gard consciousness as primarily and intrinsically a control phe- 
nomenon. Just as behavior may be regarded as the most dis- 
tinctly basic category of general biology in its functional phase so 
control would perhaps serve as the most fundamental category in 
functional psychology, the special forms and differentiations of 
consciousness simply constituting particular phases of the gen- 
eral process of control. At this point the omnipresent captious 
critic will perhaps arise to urge that the knowledge process is 
no more truly to be explained in terms of control than is control 
to be explained in terms of knowledge. Unquestionably there 
is from the point of view of the critic a measure of truth m this 
contention. The mechanism of control undoubtedly depends 
on the cognitive processes, to say nothing of other factors. But 
if one assumes the vitalistic point of view for one's more final 
interpretations, if one regards the furtherance of life in breadth 
and depth and permanence as an end in itself, a d if one 
derives his scale of values from a contemplation of the several 
contributions toward this end represented by the great types of 
vital phenomena, with their apex in the moral, scientific and 
aesthetic realms, one must certainly find control a category more 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 89 

fundamental than the others offered by psychology. Moreover, 
it may be urged against the critic's attitude that even knowledge 
itself is built up under the control mechanism represented by 
selective attention and apperception. The basic character of 
control seems therefore hardly open to challenge. 

One incidental merit of the functionalist program deserves a 
passing mention. This is the one method of approach to the 
problem with which I am acquainted that offers a reasonable 
and cogent account of the rise of reflective consciousness and 
its significance as manifested in the various philosophical disci- 
plines. From the vantage point of the functionalist position 
logic and ethics, for instance, are no longer mere disconnected 
items in the world of mind. They take their place with all the 
inevitableness of organic organization in the general system of 
control, which requires for the expression of its immanent mean- 
ing as ^psychic a theoretical vindication of its own inner princi- 
ples, its modes of procedure and their results.* From any other 
point of view, so far as I am aware, the several divisions of 
philosophical inquiry sustain to one another relations which are 
almost purely external and accidental. To the functionalist on 
the other hand they are and must be in the nature of the case 
consanguineous and vitally connected. It is at the point, for 
example, where the good, the beautiful and the true have bear- 
ing on the efficacy of accommodatory activity that the issues of 
the normative philosophical sciences become relevant. If good 
action has no significance for the enriching and enlarging of 
life, the contention I urge is futile, and similarly as regards 
beauty and truth. But it is not at present usually maintained 
that such is the fact. 

These and other similar tendencies of functionalism may 
serve to reassure those who fear that in lending itself to bio- 
logical influences psychology may lose contact with philosophy 

^ An interesting example of the possible developments in this direction is 
afforded by Professor G. H. Mead's paper entitled 'Suggestions toward a 
Theory of the Philosophical Disciplines,' Philosophical Review^ 1900, IX., p. i. 
My own paper referred to elsewhere on * Psychology and Philosophy,' PhUo- 
sophical Review^ 1903, XII., p. 243, contains further illustrative material. 

Professor Baldwin's recent volume on genetic logic ['Thought and Things,' 
etc., N. Y.» 1906] is a striking case of functional psychology evolving into logic. 



90 JAMES ROWLAND ANGBLL 

and so sacrifice the poise and balance and sanity of outlook 
which philosophy undertakes to furnish. The particular brand 
of philosophy which is predestined to functionalist favor cannot 
of course be confidently predicted in advance. But anything 
approaching a complete and permanent divorce of psychology 
from philosophy is surely improbable so long as one cultivates 
the functionalist faith. Philosophy cannot dictate scientific 
method here any more than elsewhere, nor foreordain the special 
facts to be discovered. But as an interpreter of the psycholo- 
gist's achievements she will always stand higher in the function- 
alist's favor than in that of his colleagues of other persuasions, 
for she is a more integral and significant part of his scheme of 
the cosmos. She may even outgrow under his tutelage that 
* valiant inconclusiveness ' of which the last of her long line of 
lay critics has just accused her. 

A sketch of the kind we have offered is unhappily likely to 
leave on the mind an impression of functional psychology as a 
name for a group of genial but vaguer ambitions and good in- 
tentions. This, however, is a fault which must be charged to 
the artist and to the limitations of time and space under which 
he is here working. There is nothing vaguer in the program of 
the functionalist when he goes to his work than there is in the 
purposes of the psychologist wearing any other livery. He 
goes to his laboratory, for example, with just the same resolute 
interest to discover new facts and new relationships, with just 
the same determination to verify and confirm his previous ob- 
servations, as does his colleague who calls himself perhaps a 
structuralist. ' But he looks out upon the surroundings of his 
science with a possibly greater sensitiveness to its continuity 
with other ranges of human interest and with certainly a more 
articulate purpose to see the mind which he analyzes as it actu- 
ally is when engaged in the discharge of its vital functions. If 
his method tempts him now and then to sacrifice something of 
petty exactitude, he is under no obligation to yield, and in any 
case he has for his compensation the power which comes from 
breadth and sweep of outlook. 

So far as he may be expected to develop methods peculiar 
to himself — so far, indeed, as in genetic and comparative psy- 



PROVINCE OF FUNCTIONAL PSYCHOLOGY 91 

chology, for example, he has already developed such — they 
will not necessarily be iconoclastic and revolutionary, nor such 
as flout the methods already devised and established on a slightly 
different foundation. They will be distinctly complementary to 
all that is solid in these. Nor is it in any way essential that 
the term functionalism should cling to this new-old movement. 
It seems at present a convenient term, but there is nothing sacro- 
sanct about it, and the moment it takes unto itself the pretense 
of scientific finality its doom will be sealed. It means to-day a 
broad and flexible and organic point of view in psychology. 
The moment it becomes dogmatic and narrow its spirit will 
have passed and undoubtedly some worthier successor will fill 
its place. 



DEFINITION AND ANALYSIS OF THE CON- 
SCIOUSNESS OF VALUE. (11.) 

BY PROFESSOR WILBUR M. URBAN. 
Trinity Colleze. 

I. 

The analyses of the preceding paper have led to a demarca- 
tion of that type or class of meanings which are described as 
worths or values. Beginning with the preliminary definition of 
worth as the affective-volitional meaning of the object for the 
subject, we advanced by successive stages of analysis to the 
more specific statement that the worth experience is always a 
feeling attitude which presupposes the actualization of some 
conative disposition by acts of presumption, judgment or assump- 
tion (implicit and explicit). This definition obviously involves 
a certain theory of the nature of feeling and of its relation to 
conation (desire and volition). For one thing, the broader use 
of the term feeling involves a relative distinction between feel- 
ing attitude and affective tone of sensation, a distinction which 
has in fact been insisted upon, and it also leads to the view that 
feeling, as worth feeling, has appreciative distinctions not 
found in passive affection. To this theory, of the nature of 
feeling, and the more abstract psychological analyses which it 
involves, we must turn our attention later ; ^or the present (and 
indeed as a necessary preliminary of this later study) our prob- 
lem is the further development of the appreciative distinctions 
of feeling. 

Earlier in our study a distinction was made between the * ap- 
preciative ' and * reality ' (including existence -) meanings of 
worth predicates. Starting with the analysis of the latter, 
we developed the definition of value in terms of its functional 
presuppositions. But in the course of that very analysis we 
came upon certain appreciative distinctions in feeling (as for 
instance in the study of the criteria of Lipps and Kruger) such 
as feeling of the personality, breadth and depth of feeling in the 

92 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 93 

personality, which were taken as descriptive of feelings of value. 
Logically this analysis of appreciative descriptions of feeling 
should, perhaps, have come first in our own study/ but the order 
of presentation chosen has this advantage, that the critical studies 
of the preceding paper have, by their results both positive and 
negative, defined the sphere of worth experience, and have 
given us the clue to the interpretation of the different qualifica- 
tions of feeling which are worth suggestive, that is give rise to 
those meanings of objects which we call worth predicates. 

These qualifications of feeling are certain aspects of feeling 
attitude which are not only appreciable but which may be de- 
scribed in terms which convey their meaning. It has already 
been pointed out in another connection,^ that the meanings of 
feeling attitudes, grouped under the general terms transgredtent 
and immanental references, are susceptible of communication 
and description in their own special terms, no less than the con- 
tent which acquires these meanings. In fact, feeling may itself 
become the object of both presentation and judgment, and when 
it does there arise, or rather become explicit, certain selective 
meanings which find their own type of description and their own 
media of communication. This description we have called ap- 
preciative description. Into the nature of this description — its 
relation to the normative sciences on the one hand and to psy- 
chological analysis on the other — we cannot here enter. It 
will be suflScient to recall that such description always conveys 
the meaning of attitudes and fixes the place of a feeling attitude 
in a system of possible attitudes toward reality presupposed. 
At the center of that system of meanings is the self to which all 
these meanings refer, either explicitly or implicitly. 

1 In my article : 'Appreciation and Description and the Psychology of 
Valnes,' Philosophical Review, November, 1905, two methodological principles 
were developed as guides in the analysis of the consciousness of value. Psy- 
chological analysis must take its start from appreciative description and, since 
appreciative description conveys functional meaning as well as the content, 
psychological description involves tiie development of the functional presup- 
positiona of the feeling. 

* In the article referred to above. 



94 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

11. 

A. The worth predicates themselves, as tertiary qualities of 
objects, are, in their manifold modifications, appreciative dis- 
tinctions arising from differences in the meaning of feelings. 
They are projections into the object of distinctions within feel- 
ing. The supposition presents itself immediately that these pred- 
icates, since they are funded meanings of feeling processes, 
correspond directly to fundamental differences in feeling itself, 
and that there are as many differences in feeling as there are 
worth predicates. Reflection, however, makes clear that appre- 
ciative description of objects, while the expression of worth feel- 
ings, is not necessarily the appreciative description of those 
feelings themselves. These predicates are what we feel about 
the object, not how we feel. We feel beauty, goodness, nobility, 
sublimity, obligation, but when we describe how we feel in such 
cases a transition has been made to the appreciative description 
of the feeling itself. The feeling has been made the object 
of presentation and description and it is quite possible that in 
this appreciative description of the feeling one of these general 
worth predicates may stand for different modifications of feeling 
or for several at the same time. Thus the predicate good may, 
when applied to an act, have as its equivalent a feeling described 
as the tension of obligation, at another the feeling of satisfied 
repose. In order to adequately describe the feeling I have when 
I call an object sublime it may be necessary to use the terms 
elevation, repose, and, if I wish to add to my description quanti- 
tative terms, to speak of the depth of the feeling. It will be 
apparent then that what is meant by the appreciative distinctions 
in primary worth feeling are those descriptions of his feelings 
which the subject seeks as equivalents for his worth predicates 
applied to objects. The ultimate terms in which such feelings 
of simple appreciation are described should give us the funda- 
mental modifications of worth feeling. 

B. It has been said that there are innumerable nuances of 
feeling and in the same breath it has been asserted that all these 
differences are reducible to differences in intensity and duration 
of a one-dimensional continuum, pleasantness-unpleasantness. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 95 

these differences being due to differences in the sensational » 
perceptual, ideal content with which the feeling is connected. 
With the first part of this statement we may agree but the second 
requires critical examination. The consciousness of the inade- 
quacy of this conception of the dimensions of feeling has been 
growing recently and the demand for new analysis has arisen 
from two distinct quarters, — from the study of the psychology 
of worth experience, on the one hand, and from non-appre- 
ciative psycho-physical analysis, on the other hand, as illus- 
trated in Wundt's three-dimensional theory. 

In the case of the * worth psychologists,' with whom we are 
in this connection primarily concerned, the logic of this an- 
alysis is clear enough. When they turn from the worth pred- 
icates of objects to a description of the experiences which de- 
termine these predicates, they find the old terminology, intensity 
and duration of pleasantness-unpleasantness inadequate for the 
reconstruction of this experience. In the analysis of Kruger 
which we have already considered, worth feeling (which is dis- 
tinguished functionally from pleasure-causation by the fact that 
it presupposes conative constants) is distinguished appreciatively 
by a new dimension depth and breadth in the personality. 
Simmel,^ who likewise makes feeling the worth fundamental, 
also finds it necessary to distinguish the aspects of depth and 
breadth of feeling from intensity. Another class of analysts, 
who hold a voluntaristic theory, find modifications of worth ex- 
perience, which cannot be correlated with feeling if feeling be 
conceived merely as intensity of pleasantness-unpleasantness. 
Brentano' is compelled to assume quasi-logical dimensions of 
acts of preference, to which pleasantness and unpleasantness 
are related merely as redundant passive phenomena and more 
recently and definitely, Schwartz' has found it necessary to dis- 
tinguish fundamentally between degrees of worth experience, 
satisfaction (Sattigung des Gefallen) and intensity of feeling, 
and, on the assumption that feeling is passive pleasantness- 
unpleasantness, to seek a voluntaristic basis for worth experi- 

1 Simmel, Einleitunglin die MorcUwissenschaft. 

* Brentano, PsychologU, Also Ursprung der sittlichen Erkentniss. 

* Schwartz, Rsychologie des Willens^ Chapter II., also Appendix I. 



9^ WILBUR M, URBAN, 

ence. Despite the differences in theory of the nature of the 
worth fundamental, it is clear that these analyses all have in 
view the object of doing justice to appreciative distinctions in 
worth experience, whatever that may be found to be, in terms of 
psychological equivalents. 

C. If then we hold to our view already developed, that worth 
experience is feeling with certain characteristic presuppositions, 
our task is naturally to seek some conception of feeling which 
lies between the two views propounded — both of them unwork- 
able for worth analysis — the proposition that feeling has in- 
numerable modifications, and the view that it is merely intensity 
of pleasantness and unpleasantness. Now the key to our pro- 
cedure is to be found in the fact that ' pleasantness-unpleasant- 
ness ' are but one class of terms which may be applied to the 
description of the concrete feeling attitude, that there are other 
class terms which are equally fundamental for the communi- 
cation of the qualitative differences in feeling. In order to 
communicate the subjective experience corresponding to the 
worth predicate the qualitative differences, pleasantness-unpleas- 
antness, are insufficient. And secondly, when this has become 
clear, it will also appear that in order to express quantitative 
differences in worth feeling it will be necessary to make use of 
other conceptions than that of intensity (in its narrower sense) 
which has been transferred from sensation to the pleasantness 
and unpleasantness which accompanies sensation. 

The problem then is — what are the fundamental class terms 
for the nuances of feeling corresponding to the tertiary quali- 
ties, worth predicates attributed to objects? The answer to this 
question would naturally take the direction of a classification 
of the appreciative descriptions of feeling attitudes and, indeed, 
a desideratum of the greatest importance in the present situa- 
tion of the psychology of feeling is precisely such a pre-scien- 
tific classification of the appreciative terms used in the first 
stages of introspection. As was pointed out in the article re- 
ferred to, the psychology of religious, ethical and aesthetic 
feeling must build its generalizations almost entirely upon these 
appreciative introspections (as for instance in the questionnaire 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 97 

method) and its possibility rests ultimately upon the existence 
of uniformities in such descriptions. Partial contributions to 
such a classification already exist — notably in the sphere of 
religious experience — but in default of any adequate view of 
the whole range of such descriptions, and in view of the im- 
possibility of attempting such a classification here, we may 
resort to the more usual and more direct method of analysing 
our experience directly for the primary fundamental meanings 
of feeling, and then seeking to develop the secondary derived 
meanings by genetic progressions from the fundamental. This 
special application of the genetic method of analysis will have 
the advantage of presenting our results in such a form as to con- 
nect them immediately with the results of the preceding analy- 
sis of functional presuppositions, and the two will act as mutually 
supplementary and corrective. 

III. 

A. What, then, are the primary, irreducible aspects of feeling 
without use of which as predicates the meaning of a feeling 
attitude, i. e.y its place in a system of meanings, cannot be fixed? 
As has been suggested, these aspects must be expressed in terms 
both of quality and degree. Our first concern is therefore with 
the quality meanings. Every concrete feeling attitude has two 
primary aspects or meanings, its directions and its references. 
Its direction is either positive or negative. Its reference is 
either transgredient or immanental. Of the first aspect little 
need be said. It is that fundamental duality of quality which, 
when feeling is viewed retrospectively as passive, as abstracted 
from conation, is described as pleasantness-unpleasantness. As 
direction or meaning of feeling attitude, however, it presupposes 
relation of the attitude to conation. 

What have been described as the references of feeling specify 
more completely, on the other hand, this relation to conation : 
they are aspects of the feeling which refer to something pre- 
supposed, to a disposition already acquired and for which the 
object has a meaning. In the case of the transgredient refer- 
ence it is the sense of a subjective control leading on to other 
states. In the case of the immanental, it is a sense of a control 



98 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

more objective leading to continuance or repose in the same 
state. When it comes to describing these directions and ref- 
erencesy their different nuances and suggestions, use is made of 
metaphorical and analogical terms the significance of which we 
must consider. 

The most fundamental analogical differentiation of feeling 
in appreciative description is in connection with its directions 
and is brought about by application of contrast pairs from the 
different sense regions. Feelings are described as sweet or 
bitter, bright or dull, soft or hard, etc. They specify for 
finer discrimination and description the two fundamental direc- 
tions of feeling, the positive and negative, pleasant and unpleas- 
ant, and the basis of this transference is the fact that the conative 
tendency connected with these feelings, as well as the actual 
organic attitude, even when the feelings are connected with 
perceptual and ideational activity, are the same as those 
associated with sensations in terms of which the feeling is 
described. 

The second group of terms employed in differentiating the 
worth suggestions of feeling attitudes are those which may be 
described as dynamic. They describe the dynamic suggestions 
of the feeling, specify the transgredient reference. This trans- 
gredient reference is ordinarily described metaphorically in terms 
of movement forms from the external world. Of the large 
number of movement forms made use of in such descriptions a 
slight study of appreciative literature, or of those appreciative 
prescientific introspections, to which reference has already made 
been, makes us immediately aware. They are full of terms for 
different nuances of movements of the crescendo or diminuendo 
type — of soaring, of uplift, of sudden breaking in upon con- 
sciousness and of dying away, of height and depth, etc. They 
can probably all be included under the general terms tension, 
restlessness (and perhaps contraction), the nature of which 
dimensions, and the theory connected with this classifica- 
tion, we shall consider presently. From the point of view 
of content such movement forms are also probably complexes 
founded in intensity and duration relations of more ultimate 
elements. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 99 

However that may be, the characteristic of these symbolic 
dynamic descriptions is that they describe transitional aspects of 
experience, transitions from one aspect of content to another by 
which meaning is acquired. By this I mean that in the present 
feeling there is always a transgredient reference to a past or 
future attitude. The present experience is always the fore- 
ground of a background, past or future, which is still, or already, 
dimly felt. Of course in such a feeling there is always refer- 
ence to conation, and it might be objected that we are here deal- 
ing with impulse and desire rather than with feeling if it were 
not, as we shall seek to show, that feeling cannot be completely 
abstracted from conation. 

A third, and qualitatively opposite, class of terms is used 
to characterize appreciatively the nuances of immanental refer- 
ence of feeling. They may all be grouped, I think, under the 
general terms, repose, relaxation, expansion. Feelings of ex- 
pansion have an unusual wealth of descriptive terms at their 
service. Favorite descriptions are in terms of pervasion, pos- 
session. The subject of the emotion describes himself as per- 
vaded — as by an ether, a fluid — as swallowed up by the 
emotion, and in the mystical amorous and religious literature of 
which such descriptions are typical, it is with love with the glory 
or the will of God that the subject is filled. These suggestions, 
meanings, of feelings are likewise probably aspects or qualities 
founded in more elementary content. The significance of the 
terms of their description is to be found in the fact that they 
specify, in their symbolic way, nuances of that fundamental 
meaning of feeling which we have called its immanental 
reference. 

That immanental reference of repose, with its expansion of 
feeling, is a meaning which the feeling gets when the conative 
tendency or disposition, presupposed, has reached the stage of 
habit after accommodation. The object of the feeling occupies 
the whole consciousness but into the meaning of the object is 
taken up all the accumulated meaning of the processes of 
accommodation for which the disposition now stands. The ref- 
erence of the feeling is not beyond the present state but to some- 
thing more deeply involved in it. 



lOO WILBUR M. URBAN. 

In the case of the term expansion (and contraction its corre- 
lative transgredient term) it is obvious that such descriptions are 
metaphorical transferences from the spatial world of perception, 
but I think it can scarcely be denied that, as appreciative 
descriptions, they are as fundamental as the other descriptions 
transferred from the experiences of intensity and duration. It 
has been objected to the three-dimensional theory of feeling 
that if the analogical terms, tension-relaxation, restlessness- 
quiescence are introduced, there is no reason why the terms 
contraction-expansion should not be applied. There is none in 
fact — the only question is whether they are equally irreducible 
terms of appreciative introspection. With an introspection 
which is not appreciative we have in this connection no concern. 

That contraction-expansion are in this sense fundamental 
aspects of feeling I think there can be no question. And in this 
connection it is interesting to note the fact that in a recent study 
of feeling by experimental methods without these appreciative 
distinctions it was found impossible to distinguish the feeling 
tone of simple sensation from a mood or disposition feeling. 
«*The former attaches, so to speak, to the stimulus- complex 
(taste) while the latter spreads over the whole consciousness." 
It was further found that they have different pneumographic 
expressions. The former is attended by quickening, the latter 
by slowing of tespiration.^ 

B. The relation of this analysis to the so-called three-dimen- 
sional theory of feeling developed by Wundt may be stated as fol* 
lows. For us the terms of this theory are descriptive equivalents 
appreciative meanings of total feeling attitudes, for Wundt they 
are qualities of elementary content. The difference arises 
necessarily from the different points of view from which the 
description of the same experience is approached. The appre- 
ciative descriptions try to fixate the meaning of the conative 
references (transgredient and immanental) implicit in the feel- 
ing attitude, references to preceding and succeeding conation. 
The analysis of Wundt, on the other hand, seeks to fixate the 
same experience by terms from which the worth connotation is 

• G, St6mng, » ExperimeoteUeBeitrage znr ]>hre yon Gciiibl,* Archivjur 
dits^ts^mmU P^yckolofiit, Bd. I.. Heft 5, 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE lOl 

more completely abstracted, ^here the implicit reference to the 
self is ignored. Royce, it should however be noted in passing, 
finds the interest in the hypothesis in the * statement it makes 
possible of the relation of feeling and conduct, not adequately 
conceived on the one-dimensional theory/ a clear recognition 
of the fact that he is concerned with appreciative description. 

This theory, of which Royce's recent formulation is in prin- 
ciple the same, distinguishes three fundamental qualities, of 
feeling, pleasantness-unpleasantness, tension-relaxation, rest- 
lessness-quiescence (or excitement-tranquilization). Concrete 
feelings represent combinations of pleasantness-unpleasantness 
with some member of the other groups. There may be a 
pleasant or unpleasant feeling of tension, as hope or fear, a 
pleasant or unpleasant feeling of relaxation, as contentment or 
resignation. These illustrations, it will be observed, are all on 
the cognitive level of emotion or sentiment. The question is 
whether they are likewise aspects of simple hypothetical feeling 
elements, sensation feelings. 

That the three dimensional theory constitutes a true descrip- 
tion of total feeling attitudes is then scarcely open to dispute. 
The slightest appreciative introspection enables us to distinguish 
between the exciting pleasure of hope and the tranquil pleasure 
of peace, between the painful tension of dread and the equally 
painful relaxation of despair. The question at issue is not then 
whether these differences are appreciable among total feeling 
attitudes and constitute worth suggestions but rather whether 
they are equally characteristic of sensation feelings. On this 
question there is no conclusive answer to be made at the present 
time. Wundt has brought forward experimental evidence in 
favor of the view that these additional qualities belong also to 
simple sensation feelings (the feeling tone of colors and sounds, 
for instance). As to the value of the evidence there is of course 
still doubt. Some experimenters do not find the modifications 
of the curves corresponding to the three-dimensional analysis. 
But even if there were no question in regard to the facts them- 
selves, the meaning of these facts would not be unequivocal. 
We cannot, for one thing, be sure that while the stimuli are so- 
called simple sensations the feeling reactions are simple feel- 



I02 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

ings. They may be — and indeed probably are — on the 
emotional level, the organic and muscular sensations due to the 
surplus excitation. It is certainly true that the results are most 
apparent, both in the graphic registration and in introspection, 
as reference to Wundt's studies will show, in those cases where 
the reactions are on the emotional level. Besides, as has 
already been pointed out, although the feeling tone of sensa- 
tion is itself not worth suggestive, on the level of worth feeling, 
nevertheless, when the stimulus has reached a certain intensity 
(or duration) it gives rise to a feeling attitude which is worth 
suggestive. Until the experimental evidence is more un- 
equivocal both introspection and logic would rather lead to the 
view that these dimensions of feeling which seem to belong to 
simple feeling tone of sensation are really qualities of a second- 
ary feeling attitude following upon pleasure-causation. Stor- 
ring's analyses already referred to, would indicate the truth of 

this vicw.^ 

IV. 

A. Be this as it may, I think it may nevertheless at least be 
said that these aspects of experience, whether that experience be a 
hypothetical feeling element or sensation content, become worth 
suggestive^ acquire the transgredient and immanental references 
only on the emotional level, only when the feeling is a feeling 
attitude toward an object. And I think it may further be said 
that the criterion of such a feeling attitude, of emotion (the term 
emotion being used in its broadest sense to include passion, 
emotion, sentiment and mood), is the presence of the cognitive 
presuppositions already analyzed, presumption, judgment and 

* Recent criticisms of the three dimensional theory have been entirely 
justified in saying, on the one hand (Calkins), that these qualifications of feel- 
ing are taken from the side of conative meaning, and on the other (Washbom), 
that when we look for content equivalents for them we find them only in sensa- 
tions, kinaesthetic and organic. Both statements are true and at the same time 
thoroughly consistent with each other, as will appear in our studies of feeling. 
It is only in the appreciatively described total meaning of the attitude that 
these appear as primary qualities of experience. When we take the abstract 
point of view of function they break up into relations of affirmation and arrest of 
tendency. When we take the abstract point of view content or structure, they 
break up into complexes or series of sensations, the reconciliation of structural 
and functional points of view in psychology is to correlate them both with the 
appreciative description from which both take their origin. 



COI^SC/0[/SI\rBSS OF VALUE 103 

assumption. What is meant by this, to state the point more 
fully, is that the differences in feeling attitude appreciatively 
distinguishable appear only in total feeling attitudes and are not 
qualities of the mere feeling tone of sensations. It may be that 
the content which acquires these meanings are certain simple 
affective or sensational elements but they acquire these mean- 
ings only on the cognitive level of emotion. 

The view here developed involves the further conception 
that the criterion of an emotion, a feeling attitude, is to be found 
in the presence of a cognitive act (presumption, judgment, as- 
sumption) as the presupposition of the feeling. Can this view 
be maintained ? I think it may not only be reasonably main- 
tained, but is in fact inevitable if we approach the study of feel- 
ing psychoses (on the level of emotion) from the standpoint of 
their meaning. There is, to be sure, another point of view (the 
more abstract study of content and of emotional expression) 
from which this scarcely seems to be the necessary criterion, 
as for instance in the case of the inherited instinctive emotions, 
of which the instinctive fears of animals is a good illustration. 
But while this is true — and with this view of the facts our pres- 
ent analysis must, in its proper place, be brought into harmony, 
it is nevertheless also true that, as a meaning, an emotional atti- 
tude always presupposes such cognitive acts. Joy and sorrow, 
the two typical and fundamental emotional attitudes which have 
these worth suggestions or meanings, become meaningless, lose 
all internal meaning, when conceived apart from these presup- 
positions. They are usually judgment feelings, although not 
always such (as Meinong maintains), for they may follow upon 
simple presumption or assumption of reality. The joy in the pre- 
sumed, assumed or judged reality of an object is toto genere dif- 
ferent from the pleasantness of a sensation. And the same is true 
of those modes of emotional attitude, such as fear, dread, despair, 
hope, elation, in which the cognitive act is further modified in 
the direction of mere possibility or necessity. It is further to be 
observed that, from the point of view of appreciative analysis, 
these emotional attitudes are variously specified according as 
the fundamental positive or negative direction has transgredient 
reference with its tension or restlessness, or immanental refer- 



I04 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

ence with its relaxation and repose. Joy or sorrow, as we have 
seen, may be of either type. The inevitable conclusion seems 
to be that these meanings arise only when there is that toializa- 
Hon of attitude the condition of which is the actualization of 
conative dispositions through acts of the type described.^ 

There are, however, certain phenomena which constitute an 
apparent exception to this law, namely objectless feelings (emo- 
tions, sentiments and moods) which are clearly worth-suggestive 
in our sense and find expression in worth judgments. Practi- 
cally all the concrete emotional attitudes, joy, sadness, anger, 
fear, may appear as worth feelings without concrete perceptual 
or ideal objects. A nameless sadness or fear, an objectless 
anger, may arise in consciousness with all the worth suggestions 
of enhanced or thwarted conation, but without any object upon 
which it is definitely directed. This does not mean that there 
are not adequate conditions (physiological) but merely that there 
are not suflScient presuppositions, judgmental reference to the 
existence or non-existence of objects. They would appear at 
first sight to be without such presuppositions. In reality, how- 
ever, they are to be viewed as in the main analogous to the im- 
personal judgment in the sphere of cognition. As in the im- 
personal judgment there is no directly asserted subject of the 
predicate discoverable, so in objectless emotions and moods 
there is no directly asserted object of judgment to which the 
worth predicates implied in the feelings of joy, sorrow, etc., 

1 Wnndt (and, it may be added, Hoffding before him) makes much of the 
principle of totalization, of total resultant, in his analysis and theory of feel- 
ing. Whatever be the nature of the simple feelings (the manifold elements 
of content) they all tend to merge in a total resultant a unitary feeling. 
This principle of 'Binheit der Gef tihls-Lage ' is referred to the principle 
of unity of apperception for its explanation, all feeling being viewed as the 
subjective aspect of apperception. The truth of this general proposition is 
beyond question but there are different grades of apperception and diPerent 
degrees of totalization. Undoubtedly when attention is held by a sensation of 
sound or color, or by an organic sensation, its feeling tone tends to dominate 
consciousness and to fuse with it all other feeling tones. But it is not until 
there is explicit reference of the sensation, as object, to a conative disposition 
through judgment or assumption, that totalization of attitude takes place 
which gives rise to the worth suggestions of feeling. In such a totalization 
the feeling tone of sensations, as such, becomes irrelevant and subordinate to 
the worth feelings of the attitude as a whole. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 105 

are applied. Reality is implied — the feelings are real and 
earnest but there is no existential judgment about any definite 
object in reality. There is merely an undifferentiated pre- 
sumption or assumption of reality as presupposition. But this 
is sufficient to make them worth feelings. 

The psychology of the impersonal judgment scarcely leaves 
us room to doubt of its nature. There is for such judgment 
neither subject nor predicate, nor reference of the one to the 
other. It is, so to speak, the amorphous, protoplasmic germ of 
later reflective judgments which do involve a separation of subject 
and predicate. Whatever, in the interests of systematic logic, we 
may seek to supply as the subject of such judgment (in order 
to bring it within the classifications of logical judgment) — 
whether we may describe the subject as universal, undeter- 
mined, the whole of reality, or as a determined and particular 
sensation of the moment — the fact remains that psycholog- 
ically, the * it ' of the impersonal judgment is contentless. Pre- 
cisely similarly, in the objectless worth feeling the object is no 
presentation, with the added judgment of existence or non- 
existence, no presentation either universal or particular, no sen- 
sation either peripheral or organic. Subject and predicate, 
presentation and feeling are not discriminated. We have to do 
here with a protoplasmic worth attitude without judgmental 
presuppositions but which may become definite through inclusion 
among its presuppositions, which are now merely conative and 
dispositional, of some explicit act of judgment. 

B. Can we then correlate these meanings of worth feelings, 
thus appreciatively described, with specific types of cognitive 
presuppositions? The necessary presupposition of worth feeling, 
as we have seen, is the actualization of a conative disposition 
through acts of presumption, assumption and judgment. Can 
we connect the specific type of reference of the feeling with a 
definite type of actual presupposition ? 

The two directions of worth feeling (positive and negative), as 
distinguished from mere pleasantness-unpleasantness, contain 
some presupposition of reality — ^witness our study of joy and 
sorrow, love and anger, hope and despair. And, as we shall see 



I06 WILBUR M, URBAN, 

later, positive and negative worth may vary independently of 
pleasantness-unpleasantness. But it is with the other qualifica- 
tions of feeling, references to conation, that we are chiefly con- 
cerned. When we turn to the transgredient reference, with its 
tension, restlessness, contraction, and immanental reference with 
its relaxation repose and expansion, we find that they are closely 
connected with changes in the presupposition of reality, with 
modification of the cognitive presuppositions. 

In general the transgredient reference appears in all those 
emotional attitudes where an habitual presupposition of reality 
meets with opposition or arrest, where for instance primitive 
presumption passes into assumption and judgment. In such a 
case it may be either the subjective control factor, the conative 
disposition which is felt in the background and gives rise to the 
assumption, or the more objective factor of control, the recog- 
nitive, determining and giving rise to judgment. In either 
case, however, the transgredient reference is to a disposition in 
the background, in the process of determining a new accom- 
modation. 

The immanental reference to realit}s on the other hand, 
represents the emotional attitude which goes with accommoda- 
tion realized. It is the feeling which attaches to judgment 
habit or to the assumption of the second type arising out of that 
habit. The fact that habit has its own feeling, its own worth 
suggestions, is a point which must be emphasized throughout. 

V. 
A. With the analysis of these primary aspects or meanings 
which feelings disclose, we are led to the problem of derived or 
acquired feeling attitudes. There are two possible conceptions 
of the nature of these attitudes and of the process of their 
derivation. The first of these is the concept of fusion or mix- 
ture of feelings, purely analytical in character. On this view 
the aspects of feeling, the selective meanings of appreciative 
description, arc hypostatized as elements and all acquired mean- 
ings are conceived as fusions or mixtures of these elements. 
The second concept, genetic and functional in character, looks 
upon the derived attitude, the acquired meaning, as a new 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 107 

aspect, the product of a new ' totalization ' of consciousness in 
which the old aspects are taken up into the new, but in which 
the new meaning is not exhausted by its analysis into the old 
elements. The new feeling attitude is a new accommodation, 
a * progression ' in meaning or, in terms of worth theory, a value 
movement. 

The former of these views, of very limited applicability at 
the best in any region of psychological explanation, is wholly 
inapplicable to the explanation of the meanings of feeling 
attitudes. Wundt, unfortunately, despite his three-dimensional 
theory, is still too much under the influence of this conception, 
although in applying his fundamental law of psychical causality, 
the law of resultants, he explicitly asserts that there is an ac- 
quired meaning in the resultant complexes or fusions not found 
in the elements. It is better to abandon the concept of elements 
entirely in this connection and to make use wholly of the genetic 
concept of progression or acquirement of meaning through 
change in presuppositions. 

The acquired qualifications, selective meanings of feelings 
may be divided into two groups : (i) the acquired meanings of 
simple appreciation and (2) those of characterization and par- 
ticipation. If we recall these distinctions, previously made, it 
will be remembered that simple appreciation of an object is an 
appreciation of its affective-volitional meaning or worth prior to 
explicit reference of the object to the Ego or the Alter or to 
other objects, prior, in other words, to secondary possessive or 
instrumental judgments. On the level of simple appreciation 
appear, then, certain qualifications of the general transgredient 
and immanental references of feeling. 

B. The first of these acquired meanings to be considered is 
the feeling of ougkiness or obligation. The feeling of oughtness 
that a thing should be^ that an act should take place, is a specific 
form of the feeling of worth. As such, upon our view, it 
should be defined in terms of its presuppositions. Apprecia- 
tively described, it is an acquired modification of the general 
feeling of transgredient reference, of tension. Apart from 
appreciative description it is an experience of mere strain, per^ 



Io8 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

haps, from the point of view of content, a mere strain sensation. 
Its differentia is to be found in the precise character of the 
transgredient reference and therefore in the character of its 
cognitive presuppositions. Now the feeling of oughtness, in 
its simplest form, attaches to objects, to things. It is felt that if 
a thing does not exist it ought to. As thus applied (for instance 
by a child who as yet has practically no sense of personal, 
ethical obligation) it means little more than that the thing is de* 
sired. But just that little additional meaning is the important 
modification. Is it possible to define that additional meaning? 

The point of difference is to be found, I think, in the fact 
that the presuppositions of the feeling of oughtness are not sim- 
ple as in the case of a simple mode of feeling or desire. The 
feeling of oughtness is in fact a transition mode between two 
existential judgments, in which an existential feeling is quali- 
fied by an assumption feeling. The object does not exist, and 
we have the corresponding feeling or desire, but so strong is 
the conative disposition presupposed, that it gives rise to an 
assumption of existence. This assumption is felt to be not 
merely possible but necessary and thus, as Simmel has said, 
obligation is in one aspect a mode of thought lying midway be- 
tween possibility and necessity.^ The source of this assumption 
is the subject's conative disposition and the feeling of oughtness 
is the feeling of that subjective control, but, since the subjective 
control is not explicitly acknowledged in judgment, the ought- 
ness is felt as a tertiary quality of the object. 

The transgredient reference of the assumption is therefore 
to the disposition. To refer again to the figure of the fore- 
ground and background of consciousness, the judgment of ex- 
istence or non-existence of the object is in the foreground, the 
modification of the feeling which we describe as oughtness has 
reference to an object in the background which at first is 
revealed merely in this modification of feeling, but which later, 
through the activities of ideal construction and judgment, becomes 
an explicit ideal object, the self or the social will, when de- 

« SimmePs masterly study of the mode of onghtncaa, dms SolUn ( ' EinleitQiig 
in die Morslwiaseii«A«fi») cSta be merely referred to in pusing. fnller tient- 
ment being reeerred for another connection. The important point is that it is 
a fundamental mode, at the same time cognitive and affective-voUtional. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 109 

veloped ethical obligation is felt. In a sense the simple feeling 
of oughtness is objectless until this stage of ideal construction is 
reached. 

C. Corresponding to the feeling mode of oughtness, the pri- 
mary mode out of which ethical obligation develops, we find a 
second mode of simple appreciation which represents a special 
qualification of the immanental reference of feeling, the < sem- 
blant ' or aesthetic mode.^ This mode, the aesthetic psychosis, is 
always appreciatively described in terms of repose and expansion 
and its worth, in so far as the experience is purely aesthetic, is im- 
manental. Here again, we have, not a simple aspect of feeling 
with simple presuppositions, but an attitude implying transition 
and accommodation, characterized by typical changes in cogni- 
tive presuppositions. 

The characteristics of this mode of feeling, its repose, 
relaxation and expansion, have their origin in the fact that the 
judgments of existence and non-existence, and with them ex- 
plicit conation, desire, are inhibited, reduced to a minimum, 
remain in fact merely as a dispositional presupposition, while 
consciousness is largely absorbed in presentational content. With 
the laws governing the ordering of that content, which condi- 
tion the arrest of desire and the inducing of repose, we are not 
at this point concerned ; it is sufficient to note the general fact 
that formal principles of the aesthetic owe their significance psy- 
chologically to the fact that they are instrumental in producing 
this effect. But, as has already been pointed out, it is not an 
adequate view of the aesthetic to regard it as a purely presenta- 
tional consciousness. While explicit judgment is reduced to a 
minimum, its place is taken by assumptions which relate the 
object to the desire which is now merely dispositional. These 
assumptions, we have seen, may be of two types, the assumption 
which takes the place of primitive presumption after arrest, and 
that which becomes the substitute for the disposition or habit 
created by judgment and desire. In the first case we have the 

*For the lue of the tenn 'setnblani mode,' see Baldwin's Thought and 
Things, Vol. I., especially Chapter VI. As to the complete identification of 
sembling with Ein/uhlung^ I think there is some doubt, since the latter, in at 
least some of its aspects, is earnest, and the feeling has presumption and judg- 
ment — not merely assumption — as its presupposition. 



IIO WILBUR M, URBAN. 

primitive semblant mode, in the latter the more developed mode 
of conteniplation. 

In general, then, the aesthetic mode of sembling or con- 
templation is a complex, derived, mode of feeling of value in 
which the presuppostitions are presentational content and assump- 
tions. To use again the figure of the foreground and back- 
ground of consciousness, the foreground is taken up with pres- 
entational content, the psychical energies involved in judgment 
are occupied with the activities of mere apperception of content 
in its relations, with contemplation, while in the background 
remains the assumption of existence, with its reference to cona- 
tive dispositions. While the object is detached from immediate 
desire, its relation to desire is not severed. The object has its 
own reality coefficient and the feeling is a feeling of value. 
The source of these assumptions and of the objectivity, reality, 
which the object has, differs in important respects from that of 
the assumption in the feeling of oughtness. While the control 
is still partly subjective, is determined by conative disposition, 
the objective factor, the presentational content has a much larger 
share in the determination of the assumption. 

An illustration will show the situation with greater clearness. 
The aesthetic appreciation of feminine beauty is a psychosis 
grafted immediately upon desire and desire dispositions. The 
process by which the aesthetic psychosis supervenes upon that 
of crude desire is one of arrest, social and individual, and a 
rearrangement of the elements of the object presented either 
unconsciously, or consciously as in art, in such a manner as to 
fill the foreground of consciousness with presentational activity 
and to detach the object from immediacy of desire. An implicit 
assumption of the existence of the object for desire is, however, 
a necessary presupposition of the aesthetic appreciation. Should 
the conative disposition become explicit in actual desire, the 
aesthetic repose would cease and a new adaptation take place. 

In both these appreciative modes, it should finally be ob- 
served, worth or affective volitional meaning has been acquired. 
The deepening of the transgredient or immanental reference, as 
the case may be, becomes part of the funded meaning of the 
object, or is imputed to the object. The recognition of this fact 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE m 

is of far reaching importance for all the meanings acquired in 
these modes of appreciation' enter in as determinants in later 
judgments of value. 

D. Simple appreciation, with its two primary modifications de- 
scribed, is further differentiated into secondary acquired mean- 
ings, through certain value movements, progressions, the nature 
of which is to be considered more fully later, but which we may 
here ignore for the reason that our problem is merely apprecia- 
tive description of feeling attitudes. These meanings are those 
which we describe as personal worths (of possession and merit), 
instrumental or utility meanings (values of utilization) and the 
common meanings, or feelings, of participation value. The 
characteristic of all these modifications of primary feeling of 
value is to be found in the fact that they arise through the 
establishment of relational judgments between the object and 
the disposition presupposed. Otherwise expressed, that which 
in simple appreciation was a merely jTelt transgredient or im- 
manental reference, now acquires its explicit object which is 
acknowledged in judgment. 

An analysis of the personal feelings makes this point clear. 
The feeling of possession is more than the feeling of the worth 
of the object, as presumed, judged or assumed to exist. The 
object acquires an imputed value through the explicit acknowl- 
edgment of the subject for which it exists. So also in the case 
of the feeling of personal obligation or merit which arises on 
the basis of a reference of the valued disposition to the person- 
ality. In general we may say that the personal feelings have 
an additional presupposition of reality which the primary feel- 
ings have not. But the more developed modes of these primary 
feelings, the obligation and the semblant are germinal to these 
personal values. They are transition stages in which a new 
feeling mode is introduced, through the transgredient or im- 
manental reference arising upon assumptions. In the csise of the 
personal value the assumption becomes an existential judgment 
of acknowledgment of the self. Of course such a transition re- 
quires ideal construction of the self, and this involves the * feel- 
ing-in ' of primary experiences into others — an extension of 



113 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

simple appreciation through sympathetic Einfuhlung^ a process 
to be studied in another connection. 

The impersonal feelings of the participation values or utility 
values of dispositions and objects involve a further extension of 
this acquirement of common meaning. In addition to the pre- 
supposition of the reality of the desired object there is an 
additional presupposition of similar desires and feelings in the 
minds of others which gives rise ultimately to judgments and 
assumptions of over-individual demands. How such presup- 
positions arise is again, of course, a genetic problem of psychol- 
ogy, more especially of the study of the laws of sympathetic 
imitation and Einfuhlung\ the main point here is that the 
appreciative differences in the meaning of the feelings arises 
through acknowledgment of references which were previously 
merely implicit. 

And it should be noted finally that just as the transgredient 
and immanental references acquire depth of meaning through 
the obligation and aesthetic modes, so in these further processes 
primary feeling is deepened and broadened. 

IV. 

A. Worth predicates have been defined as funded meanings 
of the objects. These predicates or meanings correspond, we 
have seen, to certain qualitative aspects of feeling, primary and 
derived. But these meanings or values have also a quantita- 
tive aspect, of degree. To what aspects of feeling do these 
differences of degree correspond ? 

It has been already pointed out that many psychologists 
have found it necessary to distinguish between degree of feel- 
ing of value and degree of intensity of sensation-feeling and 
some have used such terms as depth and breadth of the feeling 
in the personality to characterize quantitatively the worth sug- 
gestion of the feeling. And when we follow more closely the 
appreciative distinctions made in the sphere of worth experience 
it becomes clear that some such distinction is necessary. For 
In the first place it is to be obser\'ed that, if we make use of those 
appreciative descriptions of feeling subsumed under the general 
terms transgredient and immanental references, we cannot 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE II3 

properly apply the quantitative term intensity. While, for 
instance, we may speak of the degree we cannot properly speak 
of intensity, of repose or expansion. Here we must use the 
terms depth and breadth. Thus we find Munsterberg ^ accept- 
ing the ordinary formula that intensity of feeling decreases 
with repetition and at the same time, in his desire to do justice 
to the concrete facts of worth experience, insisting that repeti- 
tion may increase the depth of feeling tone. Clearly depth and 
intensity are definitely distinguished and admitted to be inde- 
pendently variable. It would appear, then that we must make 
a distinction between degree (or intensity in the broader Kantian 
sense) and intensity in the narrower sense of sensational in- 
tensity, between degree of feeling of value and intensity of 
pleasantness-unpleasantness as feeling tone of sensations. In- 
tensity in this latter sense applies to all sensation feelings, 
* pleasure-causation ' as we have described it, and probably to 
all sensation feelings which enter into a total feeling complex, 
but properly speaking not to feeling attitudes, not to the worth 
aspect of feeling. 

What then is the relation between the degree of acquired 
meaning, value, of a feeling attitude and intensity of pleasant- 
ness-unpleasantness? How are they related for appreciative 
introspection and analysis, and how shall this empirical relation, 
when determined, be connected with our analysis of the condi- 
tions, actual and dispositional, of these two aspects of feeling? 
This question is of the utmost importance not only because of 
the fact that it is a problem implied in our preceding distinctions 
between feeling of value and pleasantness-unpleasantness, be- 
tween pleasantness-unpleasantness and the appreciative aspects 
of feeling attitude, its selective meanings, but also because in 
the solution of this problem is involved the whole question of 
the measurement of feelings of value to which we must pres- 
ently turn. 

B. We find, then, that not only is worth experience distin- 
guishable, in the aspects both of quality and degree, from pleas- 
ure-causation, but also that the worth modificatiobs or sugges- 
tions of feeling are to an extent variable independently of hedonic 

> Miinsterberg, GrundzUge der Psychologies p. 39. 



"4 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

intensity. Two phenomena of our worth experience indicate 
this relation, (i) Positive worth feeling may exist side by side 
with unpleasant experiences and negative worth feeling with 
pleasant. (2) Degree of worth feeling may increase with de- 
crease of hedonic intensity and there are numerous instances 
where worth feelings are practically intensitiless. These facts 
have led to the general conception of the irrelevance of the 
hedonic aspects of a total attitude for worth judgment and the 
formulation of Brentano's term * hedonic redundancies ' to de- 
scribe them. 

We shall examine the facts briefly and then turn to a con- 
sideration of the theories of the relation of the two distinguish- 
able aspects. The first phenomenon is well illustrated in the 
classical description of Lessing. In a letter to Mendelssohn he 
writes : ** Darinn sind wir wohl doch einig, lieber Freund, dass 
alle Leidenschaften entweder heftige Begierden oder heftige 
Verabscheuungen sind? Auch darinn : dass wir uns bei jeder 
heftigen Begierde oder Verabscheuung eines grosser Grads 
unserer Realitat bewusst sind und dass dieses Bewusstsein nicht 
anders als angenehm sein kann? Folglich, sind alle Leiden- 
schafteuy auch die allerunangenehmsten, als Leidenschaften, 
angenehm.** The paradox of calling that which is unpleasant 
pleasant, and the lack of adequate analysis in this description, 
should not blind us to its essential appreciative truth. While 
the same feeling cannot at the same time be both pleasant and 
unpleasant, it is quite possible that we are concerned here with 
two feelings in certain relations to each other. 

Plausible explanations have been given from the point of 
view of the identification of worth feeling with pleasure-causa- 
tion. It might be said that we have to do here with an illusion 
of judgment, that what was formerly unpleasant has really be- 
come pleasant through change in physiological disposition, and 
that the unpleasantness instead of being real is merely a memory 
of former unpleasantness. It seems hardly necessary, however, 
to deny, in the interests of theory, what is a fairly constant 
deliverance of appreciation, namely that positive worth feeling 
may be coexistent with actual unpleasantness. Or it has been 

1 Quoted from Hirn, Origins of Art ^ London, 1900, p. 60. 






CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE "5 

said that we have a simple case of mixed feeling. A pleasant 
and unpleasant sensation feeling may exist side by side in the 
same state of consciousness (as for instance the pleasant taste 
of sugar and the unpleasant sensations of satiety as they are 
just beginning to appear) — why should not two worth feelings 
or worth feeling and simple pleasantness or unpleasantness? 
To this we may answer that the two cases are not parallel. The 
inapplicability of the concept of mixture or fusion to feelings of 
value we have already pointed out and in this case the figure is 
especially misleading. 

If we look at Lessing's description more closely we find that 
his paradox really arises from a failure to analyze — to distin- 
guish between two aspects of the total psychosis, the feeling of 
value and the irrelevant hedonic accompaniments. The situa- 
tion he describes admits of two interpretations. On the one 
hand the passion, of anger let us say, is really a feeling of 
negative worth, with certain cognitive presuppositions, unpleas- 
ant, as Lessing says. It is quite possible, however, that the 
organic disturbance may be pleasantly toned, especially after 
long continued arrest, with its accompanying strain sensations 
negatively toned. We have here then pleasant accompaniments 
of a feeling of negative worth. On the other hand, it is equally 
possible that what Lessing calls the pleasantness of the un- 
pleasant passion may really cover a gradual transition from one 
feeling of value to another, and what he calls the pleasantness 
of the psychosis may be a feeling of value of the personal type. 
The object itself may have negative worth while the entire ex- 
perience of having such a passion, or in fact the knowledge of 
the capacity for such reaction, may give rise to a feeling of 
satisfaction, of personal worth. This might even extend to 
such passions which have unpleasant hedonic accompaniments. 
Feelings of value might be accompanied by unpleasant sensa- 
tion-feelings. 

The second group of facts which lead to this appreciative 
differentiation of degree of intensity of pleasantness-unpleasant- 
ness from degree of worth or meaning of the feeling, are the 
so-called intensitiless attitudes or acts of valuation or preference. 
Here, it is maintained, quasi-logical modifications take the place 



"6 WILBUR Af. URBAN. 

of intensity. If we begin with those two primary modifications 
of simple appreciation, the ethical and aesthetic, we find intensity 
giving place to other modifications. A quiet sense of obligation 
may reveal a degree of worth of an ideal object which the in- 
tensest passion or emotion does not suggest. Similarly in the 
aesthetic, semblant mode a degree of immanental worth may be 
suggested in the depth and breadth of the feeling when the ele- 
ment of intensity is reduced to a minimum. But still more evi- 
dent do these facts become when we pass to the secondary, 
derived feelings, the personal and the impersonal over-individual 
references. In a case of preference between objects to which 
these feelings correspond, a relatively intensitiless feeling of 
personal worth may have an affective- volitional meaning which 
the intensest passion connected with a condition worth has not, 
and so with the over-individual feelings. If then by intensity we 
mean not the broader Kantian conception of any modification 
of degree of inner experience, but that particular degree which 
applies to sensation and feeling tone of sensation, there can be 
no question but that worth feelings, as determined by judg- 
ment and assumption, may be practically intensitiless. These 
acts are of course causally connected with sensation tendencies, 
both peripheral and organic, and every such act has as accom- 
paniment secondary hedonic resonances of more or less inten- 
sity, but the point is that appreciatively we can distinguish the 
two factors and are aware that the latter do not determine the 
worth judgment. 

The facts upon which this hypothesis of independent varia- 
bility of the two factors in a total worth attitude is based are 
now before us, as well as some insight into the subordinate role 
which the hedonic resonance plays in worth judgments. We 
are, however, as yet wholly without any conception which will 
enable us to understand this relation functionally. 

C. There are two general theories of this relation, which 
may be described as the dualistic and monistic, or genetic. The 
dualistic theory is represented by Brentano and Schwartz. In 
Breniano's view,* as we have seen, any concrete attitude of valu- 

» Brentano. PsychologU, especUUy page 197. Also Ursprung der sitUichen 
Ji.rkentntss, especially page 86. 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE ll^ 

ation can be analyzed into two aspects, intensitiless acts of 
preference, acts of love and hate, and the hedonic redundancies 
which accompany them. To the latter, as sensation feelings, 
belong alone, properly speaking, degrees of intensity. To the 
primary reaction belong quasi-logical directions, worth sugges- 
tions, which give rise to worth predicates and judgments. In 
Schwartz's view^ feeling intensity belongs to the passive side 
of consciousness while degrees of worth to the active, voluntar- 
istic side. They appear in the form of acts of analytic and 
synthetic preference. The essential of both conceptions is the 
dualism between feeling and will, and the reference of worth 
distinctions to modifications of will. 

The facts which have given rise to this theory are, as we 
have seen, true enough. So also is the conception of hedonic 
redundancies, in so far as it merely describes for appreciation 
the functional relation of these two aspects. But it is far from 
certain that it is necessary to draw their dualistic conclusion. 
That would follow only on condition that feeling and will are 
totally different elements and the distinction between them as 
active and passive is ultimate, and secondly, that the only 
modification of feeling which could be made the equivalent of 
degrees of worth is hedonic intensity. 

Whether these assumptions are necessary must be deter- 
mined ultimately by a consideration of the whole question of 
the psyschology of feeling and will and their relations, which 
must be reserved for another connection. It will be sufiicient 
here to deny the necessity of such assumptions, and in the 
meantime to suggest a second possible conception, monistic and 
genetic in character. Feeling, according to our analysis, has 
other modifications, other meanings than passive pleasantness 
unpleasantness, transgredient and immanental references to 
conative dispositions. These references which arise only when 
the disposition is actualized by cognitive acts of presumption, 
judgment, assumption, are signs of the affective-volitional 
meaning of the object, its relation to conation. Feeling as 
passive is therefore not to be separated from will as active. 
But more than this — these references, these aspects may, con- 

> Schwartz, Psychologie des WilUns, Chapter II., also Appendix I. 



I 



1 18 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

ceivably, — with repeated actualization of the dispositions — 
become differentiated, as selective meanings, from the aspect 
of hedonic intensity, and increase in depth and breadth. If 
this view should prove tenable, we should have a relation anal- 
ogous to that between the general concept and the particular 
presentation. As the meaning of the concept develops with 
actualization of the judgment disposition in successive cog- 
nitive acts, the particular presentation becomes less and less 
significant, until what is practically imageless apprehension 
may appear. So also with the development of the selective 
meanings of feeling attitude, the hedonic resonance may become 
less and less significant until relatively intensitiless appreciation 
of the worth of the object appears. The substantiation of such 
a conception of affective generalization involves a more ex- 
tended excursion into the psychology of feeling. Here we may 
merely note the fact that such feeling attitudes exist, in the case 
where the presuppositions are assumptions, either of the explicit 
or implicit type. 

V. 

A. In concluding this study we may with advantage return to 
a consideration of that preliminary definition of worth and worth 
predicates from which this entire analysis took its start. This 
analysis, it will be seen, has given content to that definition. It 
has also given us the ground work for further researches into 
the principles governing the concrete phenomena of valuation 
of different types, economic, ethical, aesthetic, etc. A more 
general view, both retrospective and prospective, will serve to 
give unity to the results attained. 

In general, we found worth or value to be the funded affec- 
tive-volitional meaning of the object for the subject. That 
funded meaning, expressed in terms of the worth predicates, 
goodness, utility, beauty, obligation, desert, etc., represents the 
desirability of the object (although not necessarily the fact of 
actual desire). The funded meaning is acquired through actu- 
alization of conative dispositions by acts of presumption, judg- 
ment and assumption, and this actualization results in feeling 
which undergoes certain modifications, with change in presup- 
positions, and with repetition. This feeling, with its modifica- 



CONSCIOUSNESS OF VALUE 1 19 

tions, reflects the funded meaning of the object. Worth predi- 
cation, in the aspects both of quality and degree, is determined 
by appreciative modifications of feeling which in turn are deter- 
mined by changes in presuppositions of the feeling. 

To these funded meanings, roughly classified as simple ap- 
preciation of objects (with its obligation and semblant modes) 
personal worths of characterization, and common over-individ- 
ual values of participation and utilization, correspond certain 
classes of objects, primary and founded, perceptual and ideal. 
All these derived objects, with their corresponding attitudes, are 
perceptual and ideal constructions which emerge, through cer- 
tain value movements or progressions, from simple appreciation. 
The genesis of these objects, with their corresponding predi- 
cates, is one of the chief problems which present themselves. 
This differentiation and fixation of objects and predicates of 
valuation must be traced to fundamental laws of psychical 
process, of processes by which affective-volitional meaning is 
acquired. These laws we may describe as the Laws of 
Valuation. 

B. But worth predication has a quantitative as well as qualita- 
tive side. Worth judgments express the degree of preferability 
of one object over another (as well as degrees of preferability of 
amounts of the same object). We are thus led to the problem 
of the measurement of the worth or funded meaning of objects. 
At this point several questions arise. Is worth or value, as we 
have conceived it, an object, a function, to which the concepts 
of quantity and measurement can be applied ? 

In answering this question we must first note the fact that 
such quantitative judgments do exist. Within the various 
regions of worth predication numerous empirical uniformities 
are discoverable connecting quantity of object with degree of 
worth predicated. Thus in the region of economic * condition ' 
worths, there are certain empirical laws connecting changes 
in the intrinsic desirability or in the utility (instrumental 
desirability) of an object with changes in its quantity. In the 
region of personal worth judgments the obligation or desert 
predicated varies in certain definite ways with changes in the 



I20 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

amount of the object (in this case in dispositions displayed). 
The same is true of those judgments upon dispositions according 
to their over-individual, participation value. It is clear then that 
merely empirical relations of a quantitative character may be 
established between objects and their worth predicates or funded 
meanings. But such empirical laws would constitute no ex- 
planation, nor would they enable us to establish relations of 
degree between objects of these different types. While we 
might formulate empirical statements of dependence of degree 
of value of the object upon changes in the object without for- 
mulating any theory of the psychological grounds for this depen- 
dence, this measurement must, if it is to lead to any insight into 
the nature of worth judgments, involve the reduction of these 
empirical uniformities to more ultimate psychological laws.^ 

The question whether worth, or funded meaning of an ob- 
ject as we have defined it, is susceptible of measurement is 
reduced, then, to the still more fundamental question whether 
the psychological determinants of that meaning are objects of 
measurement. Into the acquired, funded meaning of an object 
enter various elements presupposing various processes and atti- 
tudes. If these can be analyzed out and their contributions to 
the total worth of the object determined, such measurement is 
possible. On the view which we have rejected — that degree 
of worth is to be equated with degree of intensity of pleasant- 
ness-unpleasantness (or as sometimes formulated, with a func- 
tion of intensity and duration) — the problem is, at least theoreti- 
cally, simple. The laws of habit, satiety, contrast, etc., for 
sensation feelings might be applied directly to feelings of value. 
But such a procedure is impossible after our analysis. The 

1 Thus to take an illustration from another region of psydiology, the 8i£r. 
nificance of the empirical formulation of Weber's law for perception holds 
good irrespective of any theory of its psychological explanation. Or, to take 
another illustration from a more closely related region of inyestigation, from a 
special region of economic worth analysis, the law of marginal utility is an 
empirical law which holds, within limits, irrespective of its interpretation and 
is capable of explanation in terms which do not necessitate the hypothesis of 
continuous change in hedonic intensity. We must therefore distinguish be- 
tween the merely empirical formulation of more and less and our theory of the 
psychological determinants of the change in worth or affective volitional mean- 
ing of the object. 



COI^SCIOl/SArJSSS of value 121 

psychological determinants are for us more complex. Having 
defined feelings of value as feelings presupposing dispositions 
actualized by presumption, judgment and assumption, our prob- 
lem is the determination of the capacity of the object, as pre- 
sumed, judged or assumed to exist, to call out feelings of value. 
Since the worth of the object is a function of the capacity of the 
subject for feeling, as determined by these preceding processes 
of accommodation in judgment and assumption, we must inquire 
into the effect of these processes upon the dispositions presup- 
posed. The analysis and formulation of these factors constitute 
the laws of valuation. Such laws are capable of determination, 
and when determined they enable us to explain the empirical 
laws of * more and less ' already described. 



A STUDY OF AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPH- 
ERAL RETINA. 

BY HELEN BRADFORD THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON, 
From the Psychological Laboratory of Mount Holyoke College. 

In a recent paper in this Review ' Miss Grace Fernald dis- 
cussed the effect which the brightness of different backgrounds 
has upon the color tone of stimuli seen in indirect vision. Her 
work, performed in this laboratory, suggested to the writers a 
research in which peripheral after-images should be observed 
with special reference to the brightness of the backgrounds upon 
which they were cast. So far as the writers know this is the 
first systematic study of this particular point. For a general 
statement about peripheral after-images the reader is referred to 
^r. Baird's work «The Color Sensitivity of the Peripheral 
Retina,' pp. 63-65. 

The following experiments were made in the laboratory of 
Mt. Holyoke College and extended through the academic years 
of 1904-1906. The subjects were Miss Lucia Bradley B, Miss 

K !f ^™*^*^ ^' *'"*^^°*^ ^•'^ h«<* *»«d laboratory training but 
Who did not know the purpose of this research, and the writers 
and Lr. T and G did not anticipate the results and avoided 
as lar as possible any speculation during the progress of the 
.nvestigation All these subjects had normal color vision, ex- 
cept for the fact that B had color processes of unusual duration, 
in dav ifh?Mr'"?"' ^"' '""*^" "P°° '^^ light-adapted eye and 
coltTess^^^^^^^^^ '^'^^ "*"^ ^"^ «<»- of *^« -0°^ were 

-unni da'j'"! ?'*""' "' *'' "'"''°"« ^^'^ '^^^^^^ <>" bright 
was don!?„l '""" '''^' '' °'»^" »-«»' nearly all wfrk 

we used n ne clrt L r tfP^"™«."^ ^"« ">-de. As stimuli 
red. orange ve ,ow u7« *'''"" P^P^"" ««"" ' "™'n*' 

violet. Th;srcl • «"•««"♦ bl"«-g'-een. green-blue, blue and 

• Vol x,; """■" '•'°'*° "P°" back-grounds of differ- 

vol. XII., p. 386 ff. 



• ! 



122 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 1 23 

ing brightness made of papers taken from the Hering gray 
series. The five following backgrounds were used : paper no. 
I called white, no. 3 which matched the yellow tissue paper in 
brightness and was called the yellow background, ;io. 7 which 
matched the green in brightness, no. 38 which matched the blue 
and no. 50 which was called black. The greater number of 
readings was taken on the yellow, green and blue grounds (want 
of time prevented work on a background matching red). In 
matching the above colors in brightness two methods were fol- 
lowed ; first, in indirect vision the point was found where yellow 
(resp. green or blue) looked gray, and the color was then ex- 
posed on a variety of the Hering grays until the best match was 
determined on ; in the second place a small patch of gray was 
pasted on a disc of color and the disc rotated, and the gray 
selected which appeared to make least change in the brightness 
of the color. These tests were made on several subjects and 
at various times. 

The apparatus and method of color-exposure were the same 
as thos.e described by Miss Fernald.^ The papers which served 
as backgrounds were mounted upon a campimeter, and along 
this campimeter fixation points were marked. The colors, how- 
ever, were always shown from the same point, /. ^., directly 
below the eye. At the beginning of each test the subject stood 
with the head bent over the campimeter, the eye being steadied 
by a rest moulded to suit the brow and cheek-bone, and looked 
down through a small circular opening in the campimeter into 
a mirror below. The precise adjustment of the eye was ac- 
complished by means of this image in the mirror; with one 
subject, for example, there was only one position in which the 
eye could see itself in the glass, and at the same time get the 
two corners of the eye in line with the row of fixation points on 
the campimeter. The subject's field of view is pictured in Fig. 
I. She stands at X looking down with the right eye at y. 
Starting then from this constant position the eye could be turned 
to any desired fixation point. As soon as a fixation had been 
taken, the color to be exposed, covered by a gray screen like 
the background, was laid over the mirror ; the gray screen was 
then taken off and the color shone up through the opening at T' 

» Op, cit. 



124 HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 

and stimulated an eccentric part of the retina. When the 
stimulation had lasted the desired time the screen was again 
put over the color, thus making with the campimeter a uniform 



Fig. 1. 

gray surface upon which the after-image could be observed.^ 
The size of the retinal image is thus kept constant throughout 
the experiments, i. e.^ its distance and relative position to the eye 
being constant, its absolute area in this case was that of a circle 
about 1.08 mm. in diameter." Twenty fixation points were used, 
the retinal area explored extending from o^ — macular vision — 
to 93° of eccentricity. These points were all on the nasal merid- 
ian of the right eye. The location of the blind-spot was deter- 
mined for all subjects and no stimulus allowed to come near 
enough to have its effect diminished. 

Two plans were followed in regulating the time of exposure 
for the stimulus. In the first set of experiments the stimulus 
was allowed to remain until the color had completely faded, and 
at the spoken signal * gone ' from the subject the gray screen 
was replaced and the subject left to observe the after-image 
until it too had completely faded. On the periphery these times 
were not long enough to be fatiguing to the subject, but in the 
paracentral region the process of waiting for a complete fading 
was found somewhat exhausting. The time was, therefore, in 
this region limited to 45 seconds (in a few cases to 30 sec), but 
the after-image as before was observed until its complete disap- 

* For further description of apparatas cf. Miaa Femald, loc. cU, 

* Distance from cornea to middle of circular opening in campimeter = 17a 
mm. ; from anterior surface of cornea to nodal point of eye (after Poster) =6.7336 
mm.; from nodal point to retina = 16.0954 mm. Diameter of color shown = 



12 mm. 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 125 

pearance. In the second series the time of all exposures was 
limited to 3 seconds ^ and the after-image watched until com- 
pletely faded. Between the complete fading of an after-image 
and giving a new stimulation an interval of 2 minutes was 
given. All times were kept by a stop-watch.* Colors were 
presented in constantly changing order, so that the subject 
could not anticipate them. 

Judgments of color tone were made with reference to a men- 
tal standard, and color names were clearly understood before 
the tests began. A little practice showed that it would be con- 
venient to distinguish about nine intermediate tones between 
neighboring colors, i. e., nine tones between the colors under 

each bracket, carmine, red, orange, yellow, green, blue-green, 

green-blue, blue, violet, including only nine gradations between 
green and blue. The following abbrevations are used in tabu- 
lating results : for carmine, car, orange, or^ yellow, jy/, green, 
gr^ blue, bl and for violet, vi\ for the intermediate hues, e. g.^ 
between car and red there is (i) a very slightly reddish car- 
mine recorded as — red-car ^ (2) a slightly reddish carmine = 
red-car y (3) a reddish carmine ™ red-car^ (4) a decidedly red- 
dish carmine a red-car ^ (5) a color half way between red and 
carmine car + red^ (6) a decidedly carmine red ■ car-red and 
so on to pure red^ the complete series being 

car/— red-car/s= red-car/— red-car/e red-car/car + red/* car- 
red/* car-red/= car-red/— car-red/red. 

1 Sntject B felt somewhat harried and dissatisfied with so short a time, and 
the exposures were in her case lengthened to 4 seconds. 

' Since the completion of our work Dr. Baird's monograph ' The Color 
Sensitivity of the Peripheral Retina ' has appeared, and in this it is reported, 
p. 47, that an interval of 6 minutes was allowed between stimulations. We be- 
lieve, however, that for daylight vision our interval of 2 minutes is satisfactory, 
and for the following reasons : ( i ) Our interval was not from the beginning of 
one stimulus to the beginning of another, but from the end of a completely faded 
after-image to the beginning of the next stimulus, (2) Since we worked in day- 
light iUnmination and with only reflected light from pigment colors it is prob- 
able that our stimuli were relatively less intensive, and (3) An additional series 
of tests was made in which an interval of 5 minutes was maintained and the re- 
sults of these tests are in harmony with our previous results. These last tests 
are recorded in Tables XXIV.-XXXII. Subjects were G (Gordon) and P 
(Femald). 



126 HELEN B. THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON 

If 9 DOWy a stimulus is given several times at the same fixation 
point, and a series of different judgments made, the mean judg- 
ment is found in this way ; in the series — car-^ed^ car + red^ 
■ car-red, the middle color is » car-red. The middle varia- 
tion must depend upon the position of the three colors in the 
series between car and red. According to this the « car-red 
is two steps from car + red and two steps from — carded and 
the middle variation is then 2. 

In the tables on page 135 ff, the stimulus is given at the top 
of each table, the first column at the left gives the number of 
degrees of eccentricity of the retinal point stimulated, the columns 
headed nos. I9 3* 7* 38 and 50 contain the results for the back- 
grounds whose brightnesses were those of white, yellow, green, 
blue and black respectively. In each of these columns is re- 
corded (i) the number of experiments made, (2) the middle 
judgment as to what the stimulus color was, 1. ^., * color seen,' 
(3) the middle variation for such judgments, (4) the middle 
judgment on the color-tone of the after-image, and (5) the 
middle variation for these judgments. In the last ten tables only 
one test was made at each point, hence columns (i)»(3) and (5) 
do not appear. 

Results. 

I. Extent of the Color Field. 
On the darker backgrounds the colors are seen farthest out 
in the periphery ; for example, green. Table V., is visible as gr 
out to 73.5° on the yl ground, visible as gr + yl to 76.5*^ on gr 
ground, as ^gr-yl to 79® on bl ground, and is seen as yl to 
87.5® on the gr and bl grounds. No conclusion can be drawn 
about the relative extension of blue and yellow, red and green 
since we worked with pigment colors varying in their bright- 
ness, saturation and purity of color tone. 

II. Color Tone 0/ Stimuli as Perceived. 
I. Affected by Retinal Location. — At the extreme periphery 
all colors looked gray; next within this zone was a region 
where, at least on the dark backgrounds, all colors tended 
towards bl and yl^ and within this zone was the region of full 
color vision. No indication appeared of the << gegenfarbige 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 127 

Zone " of which Hellpach ^ writes, except in the case of one sub- 
ject and here for one color only, i. ^., Table XXVI., F saw^r 
five times as an unquestioned red. However, this one instance 
does not occur in a region outside of the black-white zone as 
Hellpach's theory demands. 

2. Effect of Background upon Color Tone of Stimulus. — 
A given background appears to enhance that color component 
in the stimulus which differs the more from itself (the back- 
ground) in brightness. Or^ for instance, looks h red-or on the 
light grounds but a — or-yl on the dark. This tendency of the 
background to alter the color tone of the stimulus frequently 
works against the tendency above referred to, namely, for all 
colors to approach at the periphery either bl or yl; for, as in 
Table II. on the light grounds red stays red as long as it is seen 
at all, and, Table V. on the light grounds gr stays gr. Up to 
this point our work merely repeats and confirms facts which 
Miss Fernald has already established. 

III. Color Tone of After-images.^ 

There are at least five factors which must be considered as 
cooperating to determine the color tone of the after-image. 

1. First and most obvious is the color of the stimulus. If 
this alone were operative and if it were seen in its proper hue 
the after-image would probably be a perfect complementary. 

2. A second factor in the color tone of the after-image is its 
retinal location. As an after-image approaches the periphery 
it tends to become either bl ox yl. Thus in Table II. on the j^/ 
ground although the stimulus red is seen as pure r^rfout to 73®, 
yet the after-image which from 0° to 49° is ^gr-bl is from 49° 
to 73® a pure bl. In Table V. ground for yl the stimulus gr is 
seen as pure gr out to 73® but the after-image is from 0° to 55° 
-^red-car or car zn^ from 55° it takes on a distinctly more 
bluish color. Once more, Table VIII. ground for yU gr and 

> ' Die Parbenwahrnehmnng im indirecten Sehen,' PhiL Stud., XV. 

' It was stated abo^e that in one series of tests the stimulns was allowed to 
remain exposed nntil it had completely faded from sight, except that stimuli 
lasting as long as 45 seconds were stopped at that time, and that a second series 
had the stimuli limited to 3 and 4 seconds duration. This difference in the 
stimuli seemed not to affect the color tone of the after-images and the results 
of the two series are therefore not entered separately in our tables. 



128 HELEN B, THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 

blf the Stimulus 61 is seen almost without exception as pure £/» 
but the after-images, which vary considerably farther in, all 
approach pure y I in the peripherj'. This result agrees with the 
experiment recorded by Baird.^ 

3. Effect of Background on the After-image. — This is a 
somewhat complex effect and may be regarded as acting in 
three ways. 

{a) As we saw above, the background is first operative upon 
the stimulus color which it surrounds. To trace, for example, 
the career of an after-image of red we must start with the com- 
plementary of red which is ^ + hi. Now on a dark ground 
this stimulus looks not red but an or-red^ so that we should ex- 
pect to find for its after-image not gr + bl but a color shading 
more into the A/, a gr-bl then. 

{b) But our gr-bl after-image must itself appear upon a dark 
ground. The same dark surface surrounds this image which 
surrounded the stimulus, and we must assume that its power of 
producing a simultaneous contrast effect is still present. This 
effect would tend however to bring out the lighter or gr com- 
ponent in our after-image thus shifting it back towards gr + bl 
or even bl-gr. Thus factor {a) and factor {b) tend to neutralize 
each other. Finally, 

{c) The after-image is not merely surrounded by the dark 
surface but is being cast upon it and so mixed with the light 
which comes from it. Now since the effect of simultaneous 
contrast is probably cancelled, as shown above, we may assume 
that the two most important determinants of the after-image are 
its stimulus color and the amount of light with which the image 
is mixed when it is cast upon its background. 

The effect of the background then seems to be this ; that in 
a colored after-image, that color element is emphasized which 
in brightness approaches the brightness of the background, 
that is, on the lighter grounds the brighter element comes out 
and on the darker grounds the darker color element. The 
transition is nicely illustrated in Table V. at 11. 5**. On the 
white ground the after-image for gr was ■ red-^car^ on the yl 
ground h red-car^ on the gr ground b vi-car^ on the bl ground 
■ car-vi\ and on the black ground m car-vi. At 59.7° the change 

» Op, ciL, pp. 64-65. 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 1 29 

runs cavj^ vi-car^ h vi-car =: vi-bl^ vi. Not every point exhibits 
80 regular a transition, but the general distinction between light 
and dark grounds remains apparent. It is, perhaps, most strik- 
ing in the after-images for blj since here the stimulus is most 
often seen in its true color tone and the change made by the 
background is best isolated. The after-image for bl ranges 
from ai^-^/ and purej^/ on the light to mm yl-or and even«£?r- 
red on the dark grounds. In Table XXVII. the after-image of 
gr^bl is pure ylon the yl ground and pure red on the bl ground, 
although the stimulus is seen as pure bl in both cases. 

The following simple demonstration of this result was suc- 
cessful with the few persons upon whom it was tried and is 
feasible for a class exercise. The color to be observed was 
placed on a gray background which matched it in brightness, 
standing beside this were several other backgrounds of different 
degrees of brightness. The subject after fixating the color for 
about 15 seconds could then throw the after-image upon any 
ground desired. In this way the stimulus and the ground 
against which it was seen remained constant. A set of judg- 
ments taken in this way was as follows : (i) The after-image 
oigr was thrown upon white, 1. ^., Hering gray no. i, and the 
tone was mm red-car^ (2) Another after-image of gr was thrown 
upon no. 7, judgment =s red-car^ (3) Upon 38, mbUcar and (4) 
Upon 50, B bUcar. 

IV. Intensity and Distinctness of After-images. 

I. Relative vividness of after-image and stimulus. In 
general it may be said that the after-images on the light grounds 
were about equal in vividness to their stimuli, whereas on the 
dark grounds they were less vivid than the stimuli. Moreover 
almost all after-images were more difficult to see on the dark 
grounds. At the extreme periphery it sometimes happened : 

(a) That a stimulus which was clearly seen produced no 
after-image. This was most frequently the case on the dark 
grounds : there were altogether 136 instances and of these 78 
per cent, occurred on the bl and black grounds. 

{h) On the other hand there were 1 18 cases in which a sub- 
liminal stimulus produced an after-image which was perfectly 



130 HELEN B. THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 

distinct in color, and 83 per cent, of these instances occurred on 
the grounds for white^ yl and gr. That this somewhat unusual 
result was not the outcome of imagination or suggestion seems 
proved by the fact that these invisible colors gave rise to their 
appropriate after-images : thus, Table X., ground^/ and ^, the 
after-image of an unseen car is myl-gr^ in Table XV. grounds 
whitCy yl and gr the after-image of unseen bUgr is car and red^ 
in Table XVI. the after-image of unseen ^-3/ is or SindyL 

It appears from these considerations as if the dark back- 
grounds which as we saw above tend to enhance the effect of 
the stimulus, and extend the color field, tend to do just the 
opposite with the after-image, to reduce and suppress it. On 
the other hand the light grounds which decrease the effect of 
the stimulus tend to enhance the effect of the after-image. 

2. Intensity as dependent on retinal location. The after- 
images of the paracentral region were more intense than those 
in the periphery but not in a very striking degree. All of the 
subjects experienced surprise in the after-images of the yellow 
spot ; the stimulus seen at 0° was at its maximal intensity, but 
the after-image was strikingly inferior not only to the intensity 
of the stimulus but to the after-images of the paracentral and 
even of the peripheral region. They were often faded and 
elusive in color tone, and on the dl and black grounds were 
sometimes wanting altogether. 

V. Color Discrimination in After-images. 

1. Color discrimination is sometimes finer in the stimulus 
than in the after-image. Redy or and yl^ although clearly dis- 
tinguished as stimuli may give rise to after-images of the same 
color tone, e. g.y in Tables II., III. and IV. ground for ^/ from 
63° outward red is seen as red^ or is seen as ■ red-or and yl 
is seen as = or-yl or pure yly 1. ^., the three though not seen 
in their pure tones are nevertheless different from one another, 
but all of them give for their after-images pure bl. Similarly 
on the bl ground red seen as ™ or-red or » red-or^ or seen as or 
or a or-yly and yl seen as yl all give rise to bl after-images. 

2. Again, color discrimination is sometimes finer in the after- 
images than in the stimulus. Thus, Tables XIV. and XV. yl 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 131 

ground, from 59° outwards gr and bl-gr are both seen as 
pure gr, but the after-images are car or wm vi-car for the gr 
but SB red-car for the bUgr. Again, the stimuli gr-bl, bl and vi 
are all seen in the periphery as pure bl, but their after-images 
are distinguished in Tables VII., VIII. and IX. on the bl 
ground where the peripheral after-image for ^r-i/ lies between 
Ted and or, for bl between or and yl, and for vi it is mostly 
^gr-yL 

It seems from these facts that finer discriminations are made 
in the colors of the red-^yl end of the spectrum whether those 
colors appear as stimuli or as after-images, whereas the colors 
of the^-W end tend towards uniformity whether in stimulus or 
after-image. 

VI. Duration of After-images, 

The duration of after-images proved to be so variable that 
the number of our tests is not sufficient to make a quantitative 
statement very reliable. The following points, however, are to 
be noted : 

1. At the peripheral limits of color the stimulus and after- 
image both appear as momentary flashes. 

2. The duration both of stimulus and after-image gradually 
increases as the center is approached. This is also true of the 
after-image independently of the duration of the stimulus ; for 
in the tests where the length of exposure of (the stimulus was 
limited the after-images increased in duration as they came 
nearer the center. 

3. At the fovea the after-images were frequently briefer 
than in the paracentral region and occasionally were altogether 
wanting, as reported above. 

4. There appears to be some correspondence between the 
duration of the stimulus and of the after-image, but this is not a 
simple ratio for though the longer stimulus often gives the 
longer after-image yet : {a) a brief stimulus, except at the ex- 
treme periphery, gives rise to an after-image longer than the 
stimulus, but (d) a long stimulus frequently occasions an after- 
image shorter than the stimulus. Thus a stimulus of 3 seconds 
produces an after-image of from about 4 to 10 seconds whereas 



13* HELEN B. THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 

a Stimulus lasting upwards of 20 seconds gives usually after- 
images ranging between about to and 25 seconds.^ 

5. Where the duration of the stimulus is constant the dura- 
tion of the after-image is likely to be slightly longer on the light 
grounds than on the dark. 

VII. Alterations in the After-image During the Process 

of Fading. 

1. After-images decrease in saturation, while in brightness 
they seem gradually to approach the brightness of the back- 
ground on which they are seen. 

2. Changes in color tone occur sometimes though by no 
means always.' The commonest of these changes were red 
passing through or and yl to gray, and or and gr passing 
through yl to gray. 

3. Fluctuations between same and other colored phases 
occurred with 24 of B*s after-images. Table XXXIII. shows the 
distribution of this phenomenon. The colors which oscillated 
were usually gr and car. These fluctuations did not occur 
where there had been a long exposure of the stimulus, but were 
the result in every case of stimuli which had been limited to 3 
or 4 seconds* duration. 

VIII. Minor Observations. 

1. An accidental interruption one day gave this result with 
subject B. An after-image had just faded out and B was saying 
' gone ' when a metronome was started in the adjoining room. 
Immediately the color flashed into the after-image again, and 
returned rhythmically with every stroke of the metronome for 
several seconds. 

2. Subject B sometimes found that the after-image was not 
limited in area by the size of the stimulus, but in the case of car 
after-images the color would spread out and occasionally flood 
the whole field of vision. 

3. Subjects T and G sometimes experienced a splitting up 
of the component colors in an after-image, «. e.^ yl at about 70*^ 

» Thew iiiunben hold for T, G and P, not for B whoae color proccflses were 
uncommonly long. 

•In our tables we hnire entered nlways the firat stage of snch after-images. 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 133 

frequently looked to be or and gr at the same time. The sub- 
jects did not at these times see pure yl at all but what appeared 
as or and gr occupying the same space at the same time. 

IX. TheoreticaL 

We have only the following two points to make : 
I. It is possible with the light-adapted eye to arouse periph- 
eral after-images. Our records show upwards of 4,500 tests 
ranging from 0° to 93° on the retina. Investigators who have 
worked in the dark room find that after-images are very diffi- 
cult to observe and that they do not occur much beyond 
40° eccentricity. In agreement with these two groups of 
facts are the relative results which we obtained on the light 
and dark backgrounds, where we found that the lighter 
were more favorable to the appearance of the after-images. 
Now these facts all indicate that the presence of white light is 
necessary to the production of the after-image on the peripheral 
part of the retina. The best explanation for this seems to us to 
be possible upon the Ladd-Franklin ^ theory of color vision. It 
is assumed by this theory that after-images are due to the suc- 
cessive phases of break-down in a color molecule. A ray of 
light, say blue, tears out the blue component of the molecule 

O^ 

OG 

leaving the remaining elements green and red in a state of 
such instability that they subsequently fall to pieces and thus 
give rise to the after-image sensation of yellow. May we not 
suppose that in the central a^id paracentral region, which all 
agree are more sensitive, the color molecules are more unstable 
than in the peripheral region, so that in the central zone the 
shattered molecules will sometimes fall to pieces without any 
further external stimulus, thus giving rise to the colored after- 
images which are sometimes seen in dark- adapted vision. The 
peripheral molecule, on the contrary, we may assume to be less 
easily decomposed, and after a stimulus has been given, to need 

1 Mind, N. S., Vol. 2 ; PsY. Rsv., Vol. 6, etc. 



134 HELEN B. THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 

the added excitation of white light to break down the residual 
portion and so give the after-image. 

It is difficult to see what the explanation would be upon the 
Bering theory, for we should have to suppose that after-images 
caused by an assimilation process are enhanced by the addition 
of white light which stimulates a dissimilation process. More- 
over one might fairly expect on the basis of either the Hering 
or Miiller theory that the antagonistic color process, if it is initi- 
ated by the retina, could take place as well in the dark as in 
the light. 

2. It was stated above, under II., that that component of a 
stimulus is emphasized which varies more from the brightness 
of the background; under III. it was stated that the component 
of an after-image was emphasized which approached the back- 
ground in brightness. These two observations are simply two 
illustrations of the same phenomenon, i. tf., the tendency to 
interpret certain degrees of brightness in terms of certain color 
tones. A stimulus shown on a dark ground is being mixed 
with white by simultaneous contrast, whereas an after-image in 
order to be mixed with white light must be shown on a light 
background. The tables show that stimuli exposed on dark 
grounds and after-images cast on light grounds tend to have 
their lighter color components brought out, but that stimuli 
shown on light, and after-images on dark grounds tend to have 
the dark color element come out. These facts are of interest 
in connection with the case of pseudo-chromsesthesia reported 
by Professor Martin.* A black and white picture was shown to 
her subject but it appeared colored, the masses of shadow being 
purplish and the masses of light being yellowish.' 

' PsYCH. Rbv., XIII., No. 3, Pechner number. 

« The MS. of this article was received July 14. 1906. — Bd. 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 135 



CO 

h 



h 
o 

n 






a 


-non«li«A 


1 


•dS«in|-J9VY 


« « « 1 « « II II 11 II INI 


•nonBHBA 





11M8 JOioD 


3 -^-p S'S'S'ST'S'S'E'S'S 8 
1 1 II 1 II 1 1 1 II 1 


••»»X JO-OKI M mmmmmmmm^m«mm| 


s 


•W)nBH»A 


OOMOOOOOOOO 


■aSviiif-J9)jv 


41 «l « « V 41 b& &&& 

§§§§&§§ &?.?.&&,&&SS2 & 

«««« ««ll nllll 


•OOf^BlJBA 


Ot^O^MOHOOOOOO 


•na^S -ioioo 


3 §3333 g 8-2 SB'S 8 8-2 "2 "2 "S 

** 1 II 1 1 II II II 


•8)89X JO 'ON 1 MfOMC1McOrOfOfOTffOfO'^«0«0«0«OeO 





•UORBUBA 


oIJo«wOO»-«»9mmOmO 


'aSsmi-jdw 


^-^^ ^1 niiiiii 1 1 1 1 1 II 


•noi;BU»A 


00MIO»O»Oi-IM00M0>HM 


TwaS JOioD 


•2-a-ai- 333-P§iSfa8faSS 

S||+33T:++3-rP>S-PS'2-5 
''"'H ■•P-Plllill 1 II 


■s;wx io OK 


MrO«i-ifO'^rO«Cl««0«CIWCI««CI 


1 

I 


•nonBHWA 


^0 M mmOmOmmOMO 


•aaBnn-»w 


1 1 •== 1 ^ II II 1 II 


•nopvpBA 


0"? t^iocoo "?0 « 

M M 


'Odds -loioo 


dark 

dark 

dark 

bl? 

car-f vi 

dark 
ablvi 
bl + vi 
Bcar vi 
Bvicar 
a vicar 

— vicar 

— vicar 
car 

— rdcar 
car 


-S^SSX JO OK 1 MCICIC«Tf^fO<0'^(0'^^rO(0«0(0| 


5 

1 

M 

1 


•uonBHBA 


»9 


'aA«iaf-j9)jY 


1 ° II "" 1 HI i II II n II 


•noi;BpBA 1 1 


•QMS -lOlOO 


bl? 

dark 

dark 

vi 

bl 

vi-f car 

= vicar 

= carvi 

Bcarvi 

s vi car 

= vicar 

= vicar 


•»»8dX JO -OK 1 M M: « M M M »^ M M M M M 1 


•uohbdoi 
IBupan 


''^w^^ni-^ni^^v-ii^ 



136 



HBLRtf B. THOMPSON AlfD KA TB GORDON. 



H 
i 

P 

D 

H 
CO 



h 
H 

CO 






• 


non»pwA 


1 


•aSvuiHatiy 


2 22S|22S22&&b&S 


•uoj;»vi«A 


M 


'Ja9^10\K30 


•?. T^l SS-SS SSI'S 

II I 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 II 1 


••^wXiO ON 


1 M M«»MM»M«»MM«»M 


1 


•BOWWIJBA 


OOOOOOO0O0O'9mOOh0 


aSvnf-MVY 


g g 32222 
S §222222223232 bfe&++ 
« " ■■■&& 


•aof|V)j«A 


mmvOOO'9^mOmcOO«hCImO»^0 


•u»9S -lOlOD 


1 fesl.SS'P.'SlS'gSSglilgl 

" 1 1 ■ II II 1 II T 1 I II 1 1 


»l»X|o-o^ 


1 « « ^« «OCI d rOrO^^*Or0^rorOrOeO^ 


1 


noii«fj«A 


lO M "?M »9m «9 


•aJ«a|-j9vy 


-SD|g+22&22222222&&& & 

'^i^«2 1 im ■ 


•uon»p»A 


*9m •9*9ei »-•«-• 

M fO 


•U9»8JOIOD 


lli's^'sll^sliillm 1 

^^ 1 1 II II II 


nMXiooK 


MMro^MciciM^CieiciroMfiroctei « 


1 

i 

i 


•no()«|j«A 


00000000 tO« M M HI 


*aS*iii|-j9^V 


'»^-3)'?.3-S)-u22222222 &&&&&& 
- -- III nil 


iion»H»A 


mOOOhiOi-ioOOOOOii 


-naas "loioo 


llslllliiilimi-s^ 


•»»«3XJo-ON 


M d « « M d -^lOiO-^cO-^rO^eOfOrOeOCl tfi 


1 

I 
1 


•non»iJWA 




-aS«iix|M)jY 


««. IV. /v. 222 Mb 
2§32S23fcfe&3'^ 

« 1 1! il II 1 


•UOnBlJBA 




•«;»X jo OM 


—red or 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 
aorred 

red 

red 




•nopvoo'i 


'^m^^ii^im^n^-ir 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 



137 



O 
< 
O 



CO 






s 

H 

PQ 
D 
CO 








•noDvuBA 




*9S«an-j9)|y 


S 3 3 33333333&&3 + 

1 1 b 


•noi;inj»A 




■QMS -loioo 


1 1 1 INI 1 1 


•1»X JO OK 




s 


•nonwHBA 


OOOOOOOOOOOOmmOOO 


•9SBm}-J9)JV 


^ «i 33333 


is §333333333333 &&&&& 
•« « 1 II ■ tt 1 


•nonvpBA 


^OOj^«00^"?MOOOMOOOO 


•1I99S -loiOD 


1 mi II 1 II ■ 1 


•B1»X JO -ON 


•-• M « « Ci « « cOPO W eO«OcO«OeOenrOcO»0 


a 
t 


•nonB|4BA 


CO o"?ooo»9oooo»9oomJJ? 


•a«Brai-j3j|v 


«^ 33333 


023333333333333 &&&&& 
« II 1 1 1 1 


•aonvfJBA J^co J^mO»9mOmoowOOO»90 


•i»»S JOIOD 


^t. 08 b fe 

1 1 1 1 II 1 1 1 1 1 


-S)S9X |0 "ON MMCirOMMCVCOdCiCICIfOMCINCI'^CICt 


1 


•nonvuBA 


OOOOOOOOmOOmmOO 


'92b1II|-J9)|Y 


«_ « *; 3 33333 
§'^-^§-a33333333-^3 &&&&& 

« ^--^^ 1 II null n 


•noiiBUBA 


SocooooJJmomociomoo 


•M»S-»oiOD 


''^"^ in nil 1 II in 11 11 


nwX JO OK 1 ei M M cO^cO-^ttOeOcOTfTffOroeoeOeoiOW cO 


1 
1 


•nopBUBA 




•aSBnxv'dlJY 


^ 333 & 

§ 3 333333 &&&33 

» iliH n n 


•nonBfJBA 1 


hmS -ioioo 


dark 
dark 

none 
or + red 

or 
5 or red 
— or red 

yi 

= red or 

red 
= redor 

or 
—red or 


•«I»X JO OK 


u u MMUMMMMMMMM 




•uonBDOl 
IBnpa^ 


sm«^^Hf^l«.^^«*4^^d» 



138 



HELEN B, THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 



O 

I? 



D 
H 
I 

CO 



3 



^ 

\ 


nopvfnA 1 




•aa»ia)-ji9)jY 


§3 S 3 33-PT-PT3T3TTO 

« 1 1 II 1 ■ II 1 « 


•nonvfjVA 




•UMS^OIOD 


" II 


•ni»X JO-OKI •-■•-■ M M M-MMMMMMMM^MJ 


1 


•uonvfjtiA 


oooooo*9oooooo«-'«oJ2« 


•noiivfiWA 


4,M 333 S3 
§ 6333333333333^ >-5Si:T 
^"^ 1 1 II 1 II 


00000*^00 "^M oooooooooo 


•O9»8J0f03 


1 1 


•S1MX JO OK 


fOrOcOM « «*)« « fOcOr0fO*O«OcOcO«O« *0 


O 


•nopB|j»A 


ooooooooo)9"?o"?o"?oo"? 


•aJrvm|-J9VY 


a'S333333333T33TT3333 

^^o 1 1 II 


•DOf^VfJVA 


OOO"?"?'^"?O"?m"?m«9»0oOOO 

M M M 1^ M 


•nMS-ioioD 


-^ lllll II II II II 


■IMx JO OK 


■^00 t^«*i«C*«rOMCI««««C1« ciNeiei 


i 


ixop«H«A 


oooooooo"?o«-iooocoo*? 


•9S«m}-49W 


^^ 3333 3 


§ g3333S33333*P'P P'PSSS P 
« « 1 II II II 1 


•|10p«f4«A 


O ON«OMeO»0'*"*»OOHir-MM»HOOO 


•TOae ioioo 


•"' III II II . 11 1 1 nil 


«wx p OK 


oo o>0» «•*€<>« io^v«<i'0*<o«)rt«<>««>»0 


5 

1 

M 


•aon«H«A 


o 


•a>wiB|-jaVY 


il 333333333333 


•ao|;«lJ»A 


o 


•u»»9ioioo 


^ ^ISII 1 1 


••ls»X JO -OK 






•nopnoHL 


°«EI^5^^B^«l^^*4^-n« 



AFTER-IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 139 






r' 

7 



H 
H 

ST 

CO 



3 



s> 


•lIOR»lJ»A 


•9 


•aawmj-w^jv 


" « 1 II II 1 II II 1 


■w>n¥jj»A 


lO lO 


•naas-ioioo 


III Hill 


•«^»X JO ON 


M MMCIMMMMMMMMMM 


9 

s 


•nopBH»A 


00 000 MVO « M M M 




1^23 s ass gss-pT s-5-^ g-^ S 8 

'''^ '^'^ " Hill lilli 


*iiO{)«|j«A 


.ooo«oJJ woooowooeiooo 


•i»aSJOioD 


1 II "?» i*?^ 1 


H«X JO ON 


M ^fi row cO« M M '^I0c0e0c0c0ro«0(0«0c0 




•no9»pBA 


UmO»OmOOmOOOO»9mm 


■aJhiui|-x9;jY 


§33 §TT:3T-F:3';:-i: g 3 8 gTTT 
**« «ll II mill 


•nonwpwA 


•^*9o»oci»9oMjJo»ooooooM 


•n*»8JOi<o 


** fell II III! II 


•B1»X JO ON 


MdM^WCfMrOWN COCICOM WMfOWfOM 


1 


•aoRBiJBA 


«,?'^5'^:?'^"?o««o"? 


•a9vm|-iai|y 


§ §-?.§§33 833-p-p g S'E'E'E'E S 
" •= =« II III 1 1 1 1 


•nopH}j»A 


OOmOOOOOOOOOO 


•iwsaoioD 


1 lllllb&t&&&&&&»&&& 


•si»x JO ON 


M COM (1 M M ro n C« so lO^ cO"^ to tOfOfOM 


5 


•noRBirtA 


1 


*ai9«iBf-j9^Y 


none 

—vibl 

none 

car 

car 

= rdcr 
— rdcr 

car 
■ rdcr 

car 


•BOpFp»A 1 1 


•iwaSiOioo 


1^ 


•■»»X JO ON 






•Bonwoi 
Ivnpa-H 


^S^^|-^^^l«.^^K^2s>^^o 



140 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



s 





1 

ft 


-no|)«p«A 






•aSwni-wi/V 


•8 "■■"^■IIS " 




•iiO|)«p«A 






■i»a8 Jotoo 


« --■ 1 Hill 

M HIMMMMMMMMM 






•aon»p»A 


o o «oo O M O w « « 




•aS«in|-j9)|V 






•iion»ji»A 


O "? O O O O "? J O 


r?5 


•uMSJoioo 


•?,3§§§fe&fefe+fcS3SS32 
1 & 1 1 II III 


9 


'S^MX JO 'ON MM«MMeo«rOCITf««e*5«*>rO«0«0 


H 


1 

o 


•uopwiJBA t^ •^o|? I?I?0 0^«^ 


1 


*9S*iU(-j»^y 


§§3g Sg+'S-pg'S'S'S-ggg 
""I a l^-SI 1 1 III 


;3 

D 

h 


•non»ia»A 


O O w 2*0 "?® o 


asas 10I03 


<l 4) « «* «,« fefefe&&& 

§§§g Sg&&&&S2SS2Z 
«««« «« illllil 


•BIMXJOON 


HMMM Mnn«<«M«n<«M <on 


H 


1 


•non»|aBA 


^;5«00«M-c. 


1 


'»a«m}-49ijy 


gg§g8-E:S + gS+++8 
""""■ll-E l-g-S-gl 




•aOHVfjvA 


m ooooooooo 




•n»»8JOioD 


gg+a&&&&&322S3 
""S"* III ill 




•«1»»X JO OK 


M CI fO«OM M (<«)fOC<OTO<0«OTO(0 




1 

1 


•nonwoBA 






'aSvmf-MiiV 


■k gSg-ggSB-pb 

« II II 1 II II 1 




•UORBIJBA 1 ■ 1 




•n»»s JOioo 


1 S-&&3S333- 
* 11 ■ ■ III 




■»l»X JO ON 1 M M M M « M l-l « MM 1 




•UOllBOOl 


"s'^l-s^^t^^^g^^s;^!?^ 






AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 



141 



1-1 

n 





^ 


•nopwpwA 







aSvni-jaijY 


S***^ 18 III 11 




•nbnvpvA 


w 




•n99S -10103 


3 S 32222 
23232 5^2 jj;3 fefefefofo 

1 II 1 1 1 1 1 




•»»MX|OOjJ 






i 


-nop«fi«A 


A<^'2o%o^o'0^^%o^ 




•»aTOiiii3»jfv 


*'l''i 1 III mil 




•noi^VfJBA 


0"?OOOOOOOOOmO«00 


• 


'1M98JOI03 


« 23222 


f=9 


§22222222222 &&&&& 
" IMI 1 II II 


^ 


•«;wXJO OK 


n « «« n « n rt« fOrtrt*<*5rtci rtrt 


! 


s 


•uoHVfjvA 


Uo « MOO^J^ti JJo 0««0 


*9>B1IZI-Ja)JY 


«&•?.•?.•?.•?.'?. •P.SS S8SSSS 

*" I 1 MM 1 1 II 1 1 1 II 1 II 1 


3 


•ao|;wfi«A 


00 100 '?i-' « w "?0 


H 
CO 


•OMS JOioo 


S 3 "P 22S2222 
§2-P22-p22+22-p-5: &&&&& 

" 1 :s 1 II nil 




■81»XJooK 


MM>-ic(c«Mcic«Mc«c4cicic«nr«^ci 


h 


en 


•aon»pBA 


00 mo '*0 « lOM eoJJ»90 


S? 


*aS«aii-j9)fy 


••=^ «lll; II II II II 1 II 


C/3 


•UORBpBA 


IJo 




•iz»98 -lOiOD 


M M 2322 
S2 S22222222222 &&&& 
'^ '^ II II 1 1 




•«»MXJooN 


M « N M iO<0«0«OcO»OeOt>«'*eO«0'*Cl cO 




1 


•UORBHBA 






•9J8Bia|-jdW 


a '•«|»*« Ml 81 




•nopBiJBA 1 1 




•i»»S«>ioo 


--,34<^^„2222 
r !■■■ 




s;»x JO ON 


brf hrfkrfkrfkrfkri^l^^kJI^ftK 








•aopBool 
IBnp^H 


°S^m5^^^^l«l^«^2«.^^o 



14* HBLBN B, THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 






D 
D 

h 



D 
CO 



'tion«ix«A 



•aa«aiH99|Y 



« ■ i""! II life! rii II 



•nOD«H«A 



IIMS-iOIOD 



3 i 

33 {^ +3S333u5ua-o.o^^^'0 

II 8 



•nwX JO OK 



•iK>n*jj»A 



-aSvn|-i9Y/V 



JJoiOfOM^O ©"^CfO-^^OOOOWi-" 



- - - I I II ■ ■ ■ ' 



a I T- 



-iiop«|x«A 



'1I998-I0I03 



OOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOOO 



g §333333333333333333 



O O -i « ^ !? •• ® « * ^ 



•oop«|j«A 






•.SU3 I 



■ I I 



•S.I I II I 



o o "? »- o o 



M O O 



-DMe lOfO^ 



'3'SS33333^33333-pT^3 3 



t 



'aO|9«fj|«A I oOOO*9"?OoUt-«Ot-«'?OMO«««-« 



*a)NiB|-i9VY 



^-a^^^^'^T^^^l ^l^-g,! Ill L 



'aon«|x«A 



'n»9s J0I03 



oooooooooo'9o'9»^ooo 



g^ S33333333333333-^3wQ^ 



H 

^ 

I 



•g|«JX jO ON I M "^00 g Oi 0> M CI r>^cO'»rOPOCi '»'»yO<OcO«*> 



I - 



•nonB}j«A I 



-^alIn{^l9W 



t;i ';mi iiiim 



-aonspvA 



'UMS ioioo 



^^^^3^^3^^33 
3333-p33-p3'>-^-p 



•aoniDo^ I 









AFTER IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 143 



O 



CO 

P 

H 
CO 

I 



H 

O 
H 

CT) 






s 
ft 


nopBviBA 




o « "? 1 


•aSvnxf-oa^iY 


S'S^'?. fog's ->.•?.•?. ►.-(;& 
II 1 D n "" 1 1 in B II 1 1 


•aopvuvA 


o o o 


-D»»gj0|a3 


23 

1 u 


•s;:»9X JO 'ON 




ClMMM MwwWWWMWM 


t 

s 


•UOnBpBA 




•aSvmf-Aijy 


V 


II'' II 1 1-?. IIII-?.! Ill 


•oonvpvA 


OOOOOOOO-^iOOOOMCiOO 


•UMS ^oico 


0) 

1 


3333SS33 g+333'?'?:'P'i; 
|3 1 II 


•«»»X JO ON 


M 


fO CI W to O C* fO *0 O to *0 tO tO tO CO fO tO 




tlOilBUBA 


•1 <o 


-aflimi-jai^ 




oon^PVA 


oo"?o o o o "?o "?ioio"?eo»9o 


'□aaS -10105 


3 


gSSgS 333333 ++3 '^3^ 
II 33 1 II 


iqWl JQ OiJ 


^ 


MtOMCIM «CIC«WW«W««-^«W 


1 


■BOllTfJFA 


"?00'^«-»tN«MO"?00'-«M 


'^atetni'Jayv 


1 




-qonBH^A 


ooooooooo|?o«-»oo 


-tnasioiOD 




«4< . T -p 


is S333333333333'5:3*PT 

^^ 1 n 


*nMxjo OM 






1 
1 

1 


•nop»|j»A 


'^ 


•9J9Biin-Jd)|y 


1 i IT. I^ll 1 H t%. 


•noiiBfiBA 




o 


•|»98 40iOD 




8 3333333 gss'S^T 

^ 1 II 1 


■ffl«*X JO 'OK 




M ••CtMPIP^I^i-lMMMMM 


•nopBoo*! 


''^u^^^ii-ini-^i'-^iv 



144 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON 



H 

< 

h 
CO 



M 

ST 

D 
CO 



•J 



R 


•aon«p«A 




'ai9vinf>i9yv 




•iio|i«H«A 




'OMS 10I03 


1 1 II 


•gJWi JO-OMI M»H« «M«M«»HM«M«| 


a 

s 
9. 


•noiYVfJBA 


00I-40000000000 


•dSvinf-jaVV 


1 III! 1 1 &&?.&&&&&&&&&& 


•ao))VH«A 


oJ^rtOoUoooooooooCno 


•UMSJOIOD 


-" 1 1 1 


•t|»X |o OK 


« « «vO iO«OeO« rOrOCOcOcOrOeOcOrO-^CI « 


a" 

o 


•ao^BfiiA 


c*>« o O O O O o o I4 *^ I? ** 


•IIO^^i^^iA 


- ■ ■ 1 1 1 'Ml 


M ror^l^M »* •-• JJ 


'1XMS-U>103 


^^ II 1 1 II 1 1 1 ■ 


••^MX JO OK 


M rtvO eO»OCl«««ci««««»-i«0 


1 


•TXon«MBA 1 «noO 0000«0«000 


■aJ9*ini.49)jy 


|?.&-^&&&,b&&&&&z &&& 


•aoRBpiA 


o«*> c*>0000000»-iO 


•na»SJOioo 


lllisy|H3§§§§B|§ 


•BJMX JO'OK| M.w^^ci^O'^^cOcocOrocOrO^ciciM 


1 

M 

1 


•aouBUBA 


•atBrai-w^jv 




noHBpBA 1 


OMSJOIOO 


^ II II II 1! 


81MX |0 OK 


H»«HM»nHIHI-lH 


•UOnBOOl 


°»m«S^g^«l§«^i«gd« 



AFTBR-IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 145 








s 


•nopvpBA 






•a8vmf-Ai|Y 


2Z 22&2&3« 

III ttinnsi*^ 




•uopB^BA 






•ii»9SioioD 


1 lllllll^m 

1 II ■ 




•«;»X JO on 


, 




1 M MMMMMMMMMMM 




1 


*nop«fl«A mO*^OOOOOmmmmOOO*'? O 




•99B1II|.I9)JV 


«3 2 2232Z3&&&2 
"^ 1 1 1 1 II 1 nH222l 




•nopvpvA 


\0 M fOO M M 


Q 


'a»96 jofco 


1 1 1 1 1 II 1 II 


1 


*6)89X JO 'OK w W « COM eO« «O«O«O»OcOeOt0r0r0eO^M *0 


a" 

I 



to 


•nopBUBA 000*9ooo"?»oir>o »^ci »o 




■a2«ni)-j9)jy 


o-M 2 Z 2ZSZZ3 1«&3 
g-&22Z22 &)2 bS &&&&&&++& 
"=° 1 II III II II 1 122 1 




•aopvuvA 


M mO"?"?mOOhi"?mm ^0 




•n»3SJ0|03 


''III 1 1 III II 1 1 1 II I 


j;^ 


'«)89X JO 'ON 1 MMcOMMcOMM^lOcOCIMClMMeiCtMn 


H 




•nonBij^A 


OOOm ■OwiHOO'^OnM 


CO 


*»8«lDl-J9)JV 


v«>t:^2sS2 222222222 
""=11 II II II II II llll&ll 




•oopvfiVA 


2 "^O OmO mOmOm *?m m 




•i»9S JOI03 


"^ 1 1 II II II II II II II 1 1 




•«1»XJOoii| M^coeiMC4CiMMMeiro(OcocO'^<oc4M | 




1 


•BOPBIJBA 






'a8vm|-j3)jv 


22 M&2 

222222+&32fe 

&llil 




•nopBvwA 1 1 




'iia»8JO|<o 

• 


= or red 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 

red 
— or red 

red 

red 

red 




•g?»XJooN 










•nopKWl 


sES|5^^H^^«.^^«?^gd« 



146 HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



H 
O 



CO 

3 

T 



h 
H 

CO 






I i 



•aSvaq-j9)|y 



2 t)^«o^^ 
22 22S&g&&&&>2 
■»■■■■ 



•DOnVliVA 



•SMS^I<0 



■ ■ I II I ■ I 



•»>»»iiO -ON I 



■oonavnA 



■aSamH»tiV 



■noRatnA 



■OMS '0103 



o o o mo o o o o o « o o o 100 O <9 



— 2 S33S3 

3 g32S3S233S &233 &1&&M&1 



I 



lllll 



O 1- O O « «>« O O w « ■-■ o o o « o o o 



gSSS 8SS 



•?.S-p.'?.+ 8SS'i|||s|||8S88 



••IMXJO'OM I « W f< COW ro<otor0r0t0c0f0r0t*>'^«0«*>'"'^ 



1lop«|J«A 



©•^©©©•^OH^MMM^OOOOM^IJ 



*aSvinf-j9)|V 



-oon«H«A 



■n»96 loioo 



2 2 2 3 2 2 ^ ua .fi ^"O 



•S-q I I I II II I I I ■ II I 



,„q^iOo><?i<?«?"?'<?'9mi-"?0000 

CO tO W <0 



^-fe fefeS'8 'g'S SS'8 o 
*.s;S'^ II ■ ■ ■ H ■ II I ■ II 



III 11 



■«1»X JOOMI M«oc«MMcivieic«M wcietg<€<wwg*g<^_ 



'QOnVflVA 



*9a*iin-j»)nr 



•nopvuvA 



•aMs -KOfoo 



000 »C>^*9m o K?o o o «-• o *9m 



2222 22222^.o^-5 

§222 &&&& 2 &&&&&&&&& 
3 -^ I I I I II II ■ ■ II ■ ■ 1 I 



oio2 n'0'0'0 o'O'Orto' 

M CI w I 



•Co o' 



*'Si III! ■ 1 II g " " ■ ' 



•g^saxjo OK I M CI w M « « f< w COM e» w fO-^c* et w w 



•ao|;«favA 



*98«in|-ja)jy 



22322 + &+&+3 



-nojKijaA I 



•naas jo|oo 



•»»»XjooN 



•g 'ZSS'SS 

§s|'S1s'§ss8S 
I 1 1 1 11 1 






AFIER'IMAGBS ON THB PERIPHERAL RETINA. 147 








A 


•vopviiVA 


M 




*aJ«m|^i9Vy 


3 33 *t^ 
33 3T-5: T'FtS '^JS'P 
nil 1 




•oonwiJWA 


o 




•aaae^oioD 


•?»►• fcT**?* Kfe*?. •?.►»•?> 
II 1 




••l»X |o OK 


MM MMf. MMM MMM 




S 


•ooi;»u»A 


©©•OoOOOOmOOOOOmOm m 




•aSvnn-jaijY 


v^ 3 3 2 2 
§222222222222-^2-p2t:3t 

« II 1 1 II 




•nofivfiBA 


"?o O O O o « o o o o o o o o o 


• 

1^ 


•iu»8-«>i(o 


rss.'^'ts.r.%>ssss^^^ 


••»»x JO OK 


M « « « CI fO«OeO«0«OcOcO«OrO«0«OrO« m ro 


;2 


I 


•iiopwvwA 


ooooo'9o*9ooooooo'9o*9»C> 


i 

3 


•aSvmi-jSYjY 


^ 3 


•3222222223222222222-p 
•3 II 




•nopvfJBA 


o *9*9o o '9io'*«c»o*9io"?'9m o o o o 

MM M M « « 


H 
CO 

1 


•ii»8JoioD 


1,'P.S S'?.'5=>8+-?.++ 8 + 8 8 8'?.'?>'i!«'?. 
^11 1 8188 1 811 1 


O 


-Vf^JL JO OK 


cot^n w««ei«ciciwci«WM««eiwci 


1 


1 


•nonvuBA 


ooo*0o mOOOOOOOOmOO 


*aJBBiiii-J9UY 


« 2 2223 2 2 2 
§222 ti2 fofe&fe;32 ji2222-;:2-p 


•uop»HBA 


JJ-^JOo -^M O M o O O M o o o o 




■OMS lOfOO 


g g ►.8-?.'?.S„ 8 8 ^-^^ J^t 

i i S'?.8 S-S.^-^.'S.S s 8 8 s-?.<s«^>.>. 
"" 1 1 1 1 II 11 1 II 




••;«X JO OK 


« ■♦\0 «nnMMe««««»5'*««>«rt«o«c«« 




1 

M 
1 


•non»v»A 








S S S3 3323 
1 1 II II II II II 1 




•ao))«iJ«A 1 1 




•OMSJOioo 


8 8k 
8 8 •?. 8 -S. 8 8 '?.■?.'?.'?> 

II II II 




-wv^X JO OK 






MMHMMMMMMHM 




•nop«x>l 
IBUIIdTS 


^^m^m^^m^n^-ir 



148 HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GDRDON 



! 

D 
A 
D 

T 

d 

s? 

s 

Vi 



s 



I 


•uopvixwA 


•9 

M 


•aftnBf-J9VV 


«« 1 1 1 1 II II 1 III" 


•«>f»*l»A 





■11996 i0|<0 


II II II II 1 1 1 11 ii 


1 


•iionvM«A ;2 ® "^v? 00«000«OrnHi J? 


-9Braif-J9vy 


•S« 1 «2i III III mil 


•aopvpvA 


OOOxO'-'xrtOOOOwOM 


•odasJOIOD 


II III-?. II 1 _ 


•»MJ, |0*0M 1 c«MC««c*5rtOf*>rO«OrOeO«OPOPO'*««-'*_| 


1 




HOn«fl«A 


ooooo«eoK>oo'^'0"?ooo'^« 


•aSBIUf-AliV 




•aoD«H«A 


oo«o;?;?'-'-'o"?;o«oU«««o 


•093$ 10103 


"^ 1 II 1 1 1 II II II 1 1 1 1 


•t»»X JOON| «0«««*>'^«W«0«MW««««««««0| 


f 


•nof)«1i«A 


"JWi wmOmOOOJOOO 


•aSvmi-jaVY 


§s§s3++-p-pSgS8gg-pS8 

« « 33 11 1 _ 


•nouvfJVA 


g 00 00000 OwJJU" 


•i»»8 JoioD 


"1 II 1 1 1 L 


■t^MX JOONI M«0«C*>i-i««wc*>fO«0'^f*itO*0««« 


i 
I 


•nonvpvA 1 


•aSviBT-jaiiV 


„ „ b s S , S S ^ b 8 


•no|)«p«A 




•11998 10I03 


&&b&&&&&bb& 


••1WX JO-OKI MMMMMMI-.MMMH, 


•UORWOl 


"^^t^^ii-^m^^i^-ii' 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 149 






1 


^ 


•nO})V|JBA 


o 




'aSvmf-jsyy 


"1 ii-s 




*aon«p«A 


•o 




•QMS ^Io5 


1 1Mb 1 will II 1 




t 

S 


•nonvfXBA 


« njM O w O JJo 




•aSBin|-J9)jV 


1 |S1li|ll|38??|8 

•0 -o " i 1 1 1 1 




•nopviJVA 


rt too o o o o JJo 


• 


H996X0103 


„ „„ „ -IIIIIIIBI 


CD 


*«;S»X JO 'ON 1 M WMMMrOeOtOfOfOfOfOrOcOCi-^l 


H 




•UOH»|JBA 


oo«m«^*:?om:?:?^ 




•a>«m|-j3VV 


BsgsS+s'S'S'S'ggT&'Sb 

« -S ■ II 1, 1 1 MM 


S 


•nopvfiBA 0000000"?|J"?0m'^ 


P 

h 


"^ II n II n 1 n 


't|t9X JO OK i MMMm(OeiC«C4Clf«C4C1dCIM« 


o 




•nopvpvA 


»,o««.;^:jMogo;?«. 




*auS«ini-J9VV 


** •S^II'SIIII *^ i-s 




iio{)«p«A 


OOOOoIjmmJJmUo 




'1W9S10I03 


° " 1 III 1 II 1 1 




•«»»X JO OK 


MM « « « ^« « tOCOCI tow « 




1 

g 

1 


•uopviJVA 






'aSviii|-29Yjy 


i«ii mill's 




•non^pwA 1 1 




•UW8JOIOD 


^ 1 II 1 II 1 II 1! 




•«?»X lO-ONi MMMMMMMMMMM 






^'sm^mi^m^^m.i^ 



ISO 



HBLBN B, THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



3 

PQ 

H 
H 

1 

P 
H 

d 

H 
H 

D 
C/5 






1 

ft 


•aon«H«A 




*aSviiiI-i9)|T 




•iio9»|i»A 




•i»»SJOi<o 


2 2 IS 3 
3 S333 SbSS Ji^SfipSji 

1 III 


•«»»X JO -OK 




M MMMMMMMMMMMM 


1 

1 
1 


•iion»p»A 


0"?MOO«OCi«00»nMClrOOM«9« 


■aSvmi-idVV 


^ «"• 1 1 1 II 11 1 1 II 1 1 II 1 


-nofivfjBA 


OOO-OOOOOOOOOMMWOO 


'U99Q JOIOD 


- 3 33333 
.Mi3S33 ^33332333 ti;,S^&&& 

1 II in; 1 1 


1 


•«;t»X JO OK 


•1 « « « « «OrOrOe*>rO«OrOtO^«OiOrO«OCI m 


IV 


•iion»p»A 


o^o;9^io-?o"?o2^;9oo 


•a)Nini-M)jv 


" II ll-RII 1 1 1 1 1 1 


•non»ia»A 


ooooooooooooo 


•n»»8 JOIOD 


g S S 3323 
§ §§333333333333 4-5, titi 

*'*''' bill 


•»i»»X JO ON 


»-ii-iciciMciMcicic«eic<ic<ieici rtM m « 


1 

en 


•non»vi»A 


»9ovo o »2 o «oo o o *9o o »?2^ 


*aJ9*iDI-J9\|Y 


1 ■ 1 1 1 1 1 II 


•nonvpvA 


o oo oooooooooo 


luaS-xoioD 


^ % M 33333 
§ §3|33333333 &&&&& 
'''' ^ II 1 1 1 1 


•«1MX JO OK 


«ciWM«cii-if*»r^«o«oco^to«o«ci 


1 

1 

M 

a 


•ao|i»iJ»A 




•darai-i9)jy 


III II 


•noi;TiiJ»A 1 1 


•i»»8 JOiOD 


2 33 333 
^ 1 II II 1 II 


•«l»XJO OK 




MI-IMMI-IMMMMMM 


•non»Dol 





AFTBR-IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA. 151 



1 

til 

3 



« 

P 









A 


•nopvinA 




•a9raif-ja)jY 


1 ISI-^I I ** 


•vopvpBA 




•i»as JOioo 


3 S^SSSSSSSSSS 

1 


1 


•uonvHBA 


'9'9«« c*0 wO w »« ]2« "^"^ « 


•aJTsnn-J^inr 


" 1 II 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 1 II 1 1 


•nopBHVA 


oo*'?"?ooooooooooooo 


•iwas-ioioD 


•» 2 ^^^ 


gSS t^232S3222Sj5ua^^^^ 

^ 1 


tlwxjooK 


M ei CI « « cOfOt0^tO«OcOrOeOrOtOtOeO«-« tO 


1 


•non»u»A 


OOO^^O^^H.^^H.wol^MCi^^'^^l? 


•»»»uil.»ljV 


« 1 1 II 1 1 II 1 li;ii 1 II 


•vof^vpvA 


0000000000000002*000 


*n998 J0I03 


'8222222222222222-^222 


•■»»X JO OK 


WIO-^WdWPIWWMWWNWWWCICIMCI 


1 


•nopBiJVA 


0»0»^"?0*^"?»?0"?mO«mM?mOOO*2 


•aSvmi-jaijy 


■^•s. 1 1 1 II ■ 1 1 1 1 1 1 II 1 


•Qopv^VA 


0000000000000000 


•i»aSioioD 


MM 3 


2 S S222222222222222^T 


■0|8»XJO -ON 


ei«««««ci«to«w«o^ lovo ^ to eo « « 


M 


•no|;«|j«A 


»9 

M 


•a8«iiXf-J9VY 


■ III -^11 III-?. 


•no|i»p»A 





*ixa9S JOioD 


•° II 


••»»X JO OK 




•|IO|)B30l 


°8^E^i««^^-i«:4«^4^^d<' 



«5* 



HELEN B. THOMPSON AND KA TE GORDON. 



s 

n 





1 

ft 


■w>n»p»A 1 






•aSvnr-j»ljy 


% 1 1; 1 1 1 1 II 1 II 




•iion»{a»A 






-Ii9a6^<0 


3TS3S3S3TSTTT-P 




•«»»X |o ON 






MMlHMMMI-ll-IMMMI-iMM 




i 


•nopwp^A, 


22*'»o ;9« v>o .o-?M o ;2« ^2"*" *" 




•»»»ai|-j»ijv 






•uon»H»A 


00000000000000*2*^00 




•OW9JOIOD 


■^3 ^ 


s 

o 


1 1 


'ff)S9X JO OK 1 i-i«^e«rf)«'*«0«M^«fO«0'*«0^^eoio| 


^4 

> 


1 


nonvRBA 


iooo«^"?o'C>*9o"?»9"?o'^'Otoo 


1 

CO 

3 


-a»nin-j9)jy 


§ lll|->;l II III 1 1 111-;.^ 


P 
S 


•aofivMBA 


ooooooooooooom^ooo 


H 

CO 

1 


*a99S J0|03 




o 


-«1MX JO OK 1 Mf^rOf^COnClvOCIMcOCICIftVIVIMMfOl 


H 




•oon«{a«A 


2* ^"I?'"' o«2'!?"*'*'*'"'I? 


CO 


•aava|-J9)|y 


T T 1 Tiiii-?.ii'^iiT..i 1 


oonvMVA 


o ooooo o^oooooooo 




*ii»96 JOfOO 


^ 1 




'9\99X JO-OKl ciciMiMMeicifO^^roei T>0 i/> wi eo « « « | 




1 

M 
1 


•non»iJ»A 






'aJrai'jayy 


III7.II'?.! II nil 




•nop»H»A 1 1 




•u»»8 JoioD 


1* II 




•Bisax lo-OKI mh.».mmmmmmmm| 




non«3<n 


'^u^^ii-im^^mr 



AFTER-IMAGES ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 153 

Table XIX. 

Subject B. — Stimulus — Carmine. 



Background. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Blue). 


|| 


1 


i 


1 


1 


a 


1 


i 


1 


1 


g 


1 


a 


8 


1 


1 


c 

1 


1 


> 


? 


•0 


1 


1 




> 


"S 

1 


1 


1 


1 


93" 
































90.5 
























none 




none 




87^ 
























none 




none 




84^ 












I 


bl 




yi 






bl 




none 




82 












I 


bl 




yi 






bl 




none 




79 


I 


none 




none 




2 


bl 





sgryl 


4 




car 




bl? 




76.5 


I 


none 




none 




3 


bl 





yi 















73.5 


I 


car 




= gryl 




2 


car + vi 


15 


yi+gr 


5 




svicar 




-gryl 




71 












I 


B car VI 




gr 






car 




yi 




68.5 


2 


car 





P" 


10 


I 


bl 




— gryl 






car 





& 





66 


2 


— rdcr 


i.5=blgr 





I 


vi 




Bgryl 






— rdcar 


1.5 


«r 





63.2 


2 


carH- vi 




-gryl 





I 


B car VI 




= gryl 






car 





gr 


I 


59.7 


3 


avicar 


3 


Sgryl 





I 


a VI car 




S^ 






car 




gr 




55 


3 


«vi car 


I 


= ylgr 





I 


scar VI 




gr 




2 


— rdcar 


I 


gr 





49 


2 


—vicar 


1.5 


& 





I 


K car VI 




gr 




2 


car 





gr 





41.2 


2 


—vicar 


1.5 


=ylgr 


■5 


3 


Si VI car 





= ylgr 





2 


=rdcar 


1 


gr 





31 


2 


= VI car 


.5 


gr 





3 


B VI car 





anylgr 





2 


= rdcar 


I 


gr 





20.5 


2 


car 


3 


gr 


2.5 


I 


— rdcar 




— yigr 




2 


—rdcar 


1.5 


gr 





11.5 


2 


svi car 


I 


gr 





I 


car 




aylgr 




I 


car 




gr 







2 


car 





gr 





I 


car 




gr 




I 


= rdcar 




gr 





Stimulus — Red. 



93° 




















































I 


light 




dark 




84.5 


I 


none 




none 






— ylor 




bl 




I 


y} 




bl 




82 


I 


none 




none 






none 




none 




I 


aiyl or 




bl 




79 


I 


dark 




bl 






B or red 


4 


bl 















76.5 


2 


= or red 





bl 







red 




bl 














73-5 


I 


= or red 




bl 






= or red 




bl 




I 


s red or 




bl 




71 


I 


= or red 




bl 






—or red 


1.5 


bl 





I 


a or red 




bl 




68.5 


^ 


= or red 


I 


bl 







= or red 




"ff" 




I 


= carrd 




bl 




66 


2 


= or red 




—grbl 
Bl 


1.5 




= or red 


.5 





2 


red 


3 


-grbl 


I 


61^.2 


2 


B or red 


2 







— orred 




bl 




2 


s or red 


2 


—grbl I 


59.7 


3 


= or red 





bl 







= or red 




bl 




2 


= or red 





—grblj I 


55 


3 


= or red 





gr+bl 


2 




= or red 




bl 




2 


3 orred 





a grbl 


49.2 


4 


= or red 


.5 


sgrbl 
sBlgr 


1.5 




red 




gr-hbl 




3 


= or red 





gr-hbl 2 


41.2 


2 


—or red 


1.5 


I 




=^orred 




-blgr 




2 


= or red 


.5 


gr+bl 


2 


31 


2 


= or red 





-=blgr 


.5 




a or red 




sblgr 




2 


= or red 


.5 


ablgr 


.5 


20.5 


2 


-or red 


I 


= blgr 
gr + bl 







= or red 




Bblgr 




2 


— orred 


I 


ablgr 





11.5 


I 


as or red 








a red or 




=blgr 




3 


= or red 





= blgr 
sgrbl 


I 





2 


red 





ablgr 


I 




red 




«blgr 




I 


red 







>54 



HELEN B, THOMPSON AND KATE GORDON. 



Table XX, 









Subject B. — Stimulus — ^Orange. 








BAckground. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Blue). 


II 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


i 


i 


t 


8 


1 


1 


1 


1 


g 


|b 


"3 




■S 


u 


% 


'Z 




i 


•S 


•8 




i 




1 




S 


3 


> 


< 


> 


i 


3 


> 


% 


^ 


1 


S 


> 


% 


> 


93" 






















I 


yl? 




none 




f^i 




none 




none 














I 


yl 




bl 






dark 




light 














I 


yl 




none 




84.5 




dark 




«f!" 






none 




bl 




I 


-ylor 




bl 




82 




■ red or 


4 







= or red 




bl 




I 


=oryl 




bl 




79 




= or red 




bl 






=oryl 




bl 














76.5 




=orred 




bl 






=orred 




bl 














73.5 




= or red 




bl 






Bred or 




bl 




I 


=redor 




bl 




71 




H or red 




bl 






—red or 


1.5 


bl 





I 




bl 




68.5 




or 4- red 


^ 


-s" 


I 




H red or 




bl 




I 


Bred or 




bl 




66 




=orred 










= or red 




-blp 




I 


H or red 




"grbl 




63.2 




M or red 





bl 







■i or red 






3 


H or red 





=grbl 


I 


59.7 




—or red 


^5 


—grbl 


I 




■i red or 






2 


M or red 





-grbl 


I 


55 




■ or red 


2.5 


=grbl 


.5 




= red or 




bl 




2 


Bred or 


1-5 


=grbl 


I 


49 




■1 red or 


I gr-fbl 


I 




■lyl or 




bl 




2 


■ red or 


2^S 


■ grbl 


I 


41.2 




or -f red 


2 -igrbl 


3.5 




= or red 




gr + bl 




2 


■ red or 


2^5 


"grbl 





31 




Bred or 


a^gr + M 


2 




or 




gr + bl 




2 


Bred or 


4.5 


-grbl 





ao.5 




— red or 


l-grbl 






■ yl or 




=grbl 




3 


=ylor 





a grbl 





".5 




Morred 


igrbl 


3 




= red or 




"ilgr 




I 


=orrod 




"blgr 
"grbl 









= red or 


— K^bl 


1.5 




or 






2 


or 





.5 



Stimulus — ^Yellow. 



93' 






















z 


yl 




bl 




^i 


I 


none 




none 
























I 


yl? 




none 














I 


yl 




bl 




84.5 


3 


none 




bl 















I 


=oryl 




bl 




82 


I 


■ior yl 




bl 














I 


—gryl 




bl 




79 


I 


■1 or red 




bl 






■ ylor 


6 


bl 















76.5 


I 


a red or 




bl 






■ yl or 




bl 














73.5 


I 


= red or 




bl 






"yl or 




=grbl 




z 


yl 




bl 




71 














■■or yl 




=grbl 




I 


yl 




bl 




68.5 


2 


or 


3 


bl 







■ oryl 




vi 




I 


yl 




bl? 




66 


2 


or -1- red 


2 


bl 







Bylor 




=s" 




2 


=Kryl 


I 


bl 





63.2 


3 


or 


2 


bl 







=or yl 






2 


—gryl 


1.5 


bl 





59.7 


3 


or 


I 


bl 







"ylor 




-E" 




2 


yl 


.5 


bl 





55 


3 


yl + or 


2 


bl 







or 






2 


yl 





—grbl 


I 


49 


3 


Hylor 





= grbl 







"ylor 




-K" 




2 


yl 





—grbl 


I 


41.2 


2 


»yl or 





-^rbl 


1.5 




«or yl 






2 


yl 





-vibl 


IvS 


31 


2 


■■or yl 










yl + or 




bl 




2 


yl 





-vibl 


2 


ao.5 


3 


-gryl 





=vibl 


I 




Bor yl 




bl 




3 


yl 





bl 





"5 


2 


y* . 


2.5 


bl 







=oryl 




bl 




2 


yl 





— vibl 


1.5 





2 


—gryl 


1.5 


-vibl 


I 




yl 




bl 




I 


yl 




=vibl 





AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 155 

Table XXI. 

Subject B. — Stimulus — Green. 



Buskgronnd. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Blue). 




1 


1 


1 




1 


1 


1 


1 


^ 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


n 


"8 

i 




1 


? 


•8 

i 


1 


ff' 


1 


? 


•s 

1 


i 


> 


1 


1 


93' 
























light 




none 




%% 
























yl? 




dark 






none 




none 
















yi 




none 




«4.5 




■oryl 




none 






yi 




bl 






yl 




none 




83 




none 




none 






yi 




bl 






yl 




none 




79 




=oryl 




bl 






— pyi 


1.5 


bl 















76^ 




dark 




bl 






-ylgr 




bl 






-gryl 




none 




73.5 




^> 




vi 






■ ylgr 




▼i 






=gryl 




bl 




i\ 




— blgr 




scrvi 






yi 




bl 






yl 




bl 




3 


2 


car 







■ylgr 




aicr VI 




2 


=gryl 





vi 





66 


2 


-blgr 


1.5 


-vicr 







■ ylgr 




■■crvi 




2 


— gryl 


1.5 


-vicr 





63.2 


2 


— ylgr 


2 


car 









vi 




2 


=gryl 





—vicr 


1.5 


59.7 


3 


-ylgr 


2 


car 







yi+gr 




Hvicr 




2 


=Kryl 


.5 


acrvi 


I 


55 


3 


S 


3 


car 







yi 




= vibl 




2 


=yigr 





avicr 


I 


49 


4 


—blgr 


2.5 


car 


I 




=7\V 




Hvicr 




2 


Bgryl 


I 


cr-fvi 


5 


41.2 


3 


^ 


I 


car 


I 






scrrd 




3 


-ylgr 





cr+vi 


5 


31 


2 


=yigr 


2 


— rdcr 


1.5 




=ylgr 


.5 


—vicr 


.5 


2 


eylgr 


I 


-vicr 


3-5 


20.5 


2 


-V gr 
-blgr 





— rdcr 


L5 




-ylgr 




-vicr 




2 


— ylgr 


1.5 


car 





11.5 


2 


I 


—rdcr 


1.5 




=ylgr 




— vicr 




2 


—ylgr 


I 


car 








2 


=blgr 


I 


car 





2 


V 





car 


.5 


I 


-ylgr 




cr + vi 





Stimulus — Blue-Green. 



93* 
































87^5 
































% 














bl 




none 






bl? 




none 
















none 




none 






bl 




none 




79 


I 


none 




none 






none 




none 














76.5 


I 


dark 




bl? 






none 




none 






bl 




none 




73-5 


I 


dark 




bl? 






— blgr 
gr 




car 






bl? 




none 




71 
















— ylor 






bl 




car 




•^ 


I 
2 


-grbl 
gr 





vi 
—vicr 


L5 






car 
— rdcr 






—ylgr 


8.5 


car 





63.2 


2 


-l^gr 


3 


—vicr 


1.5 


1 


gr 




car 






-ylgr 


6.5 


=rdcr 


2.5 


59-7 


3 


2 


car 







none 




— crrd 






-ylgr 
— bl gr 




red 




55 


2 


=blgr 


1.5 


=rdcr 


.5 




gr 




— crvi 






5 


car 





49 


3 


= blgr 


2 


— crrd 


3 




gr 




— vicr 






=blgr 


4.5 


=crrd 


4.5 


41.2 


3 


-blgr 


I 


—rdcr 


I 




gr 




car 






—ylgr 


I 


car 





31 


2 


-blgr 


.5 


— rdcr 


1.5 




'h 




— rdcr 






-bTgr 





a crrd 


5.5 


20.5 


2 


=blgr 


.5 


=rdcr 


.5 




.5 


—vicr 


I 




1.5 


=:rdcr 


5 


11.5 


2 


=blgr 


.5 


=rdcr 


.5 






— rdcr 






-blgr 




=crrd 







2 


gr+bl 





=crrd 


4.5 




gr 




— crrd 






-blgr 


L5 


=rdcr 


5.5 



156 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



Table XXII. 

Subject B. — Stimulus — Green-Blub. 



Background. 


3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Bine). 


"ag 


1 


1 


1 


§ 


1 


1 


i 


1 


i 


1 


1 


1 


1 


f 


i 


^1 


"3 




\ 


"2 


•S 


"0 




i 


{* 


i 


"8 


1 


1 


i; 


■S 


i 


5 


> 


< 


> 


i 


3 


f 


s 


$ 


1 


a 


> 


5 


> 


93° 
































^l 






















I 


bl 




none 




8M 












I 


=grbl 




Boryl 




I 


bl 




none 




82 


I 


bl 




— oryl 














I 


bl 




none 




79 


I 


bl 




yi 




2 


bl 





yi 















76.5 


I 


none 




■ioryl 






bl 




Mylor 




I 


bl 




=orrd 




73.5 


2 


bl 





—oryl 


I 




bl 




=rdor 




I 


bl 




=orni 




71 


2 


bl? 





— rdor 


1.5 




bl 




or 




I 


bl 




=orrd 


68.5 


3 


bl 





■iylor 


4 




bl 




Moryl 




I 


bl 




or 




66 


2 


-r 


I 


Hylor 







bl 




yl 




2 


bl 


olor-frd 


2 


63.2 


2 





yl + or 


2 




bl 




«oryl 




2 


bl 


ol or 





59.7 


2 


bl 





= rdor 


.5 




bl 




=oryl 




2 


bl 


ojaylor 


4 


55 


2 


-grbi 


I 


=rdor 


.5 




bl 




■ oryl 




2 


bl 





«ylor 


4 


49 


4 


=grbl 


I 


=rdor 







bl 




or 




2 


bl 





or 


3 


41.2 


4 


=grbl 


.5 


= rdor 


.5 




bl 




■■oryl 




2 


-^1" 


I 


nrdor 





31 


2 


-grbl 





aorrd 


4 




>grbl 




Hylor 




3 





=rdor 





20.5 


2 


-grbl 





—rdor 


I 




gt+bl 




■irdor 




I 


gr + bl 




srdor 




"5 


2 


=grbl 


.5 


= rdor 


.5 




gr+bl 




Hrdor 




I 


■ grbl 




^orrd 







2 


=grbl 


.5 


■ rdor 


I 




■ grbl 




Hrdor 




3 


>grbl 





red 






Stimulus — Blub. 



93" 






















2 


none 




none 




fyi 


I 


none 




none 














1 


bl 




none 




I 


dark 




light 






dark 




=oryl 




I 


bl 




none 




84.5 


2 


bl 





■ yl 







bl 




yl 




I 


bl 




■ oryl 




82 














bl 




=oryl 




I 


bl 




=ylor 




79 


2 


bl 





—oryl 


I 




bl 




—gryl 














76.5 


I 


bl 




=oryl 






bl 




yl 














73-5 


I 


bl 




yl 






vi 




yl 




I 


bl 




■ rdor 




71 


I 


bl 




yl 






bl 





yl 















68.5 


2 


bl 





yl 







bl 





-gryl 


1^5 


2 


bl 





— ylor 


I 


66 


2 


bl 





— gryl 







bl 




= oryl 




2 


bl 





■ rdor 





63.2 


2 


bl 





yl 


1.5 




bl 




=:oryl 




2 


bl 





yl + or 


5 


59.7 


3 


bl 





=gryl 







bl 




=oryl 




2 


bl 





—oryl 


I 


55 


3 


bl 





=gryl 


I 




bl 




yl 




2 


-grbl 


1 


■ oryl 


3-5 


49 


5 


bl 





=gryl 


I 




bl 




=oryl 




2 


-r 


L5 


=oryl 





41.2 


3 


bl 





r::rgryl 


I 




■■blvi 




=gryi 




I 




—oryl 




31 


2 


-vibl 


3-5 


■ gryl 


^5 




bl 




yl 




2 


-grbl 


1.5 


■ oryl 


3-5 


20.5 


2 


vi 





= ylgr 







■ blvi 




=gryl 




2 


-grbl 


L5 


—oryl 


2 


"5 


2 


bl 





-gryl 


.5 




bl 




yl 




2 


■ grbl 





■ ylor 


I 





2 


bl 





yl 


.5 


2 


bl 





yl 





2 





-oryl 


I 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THB PBRIPHBRAL RBTINA. 157 



Tablb XXIII. 

Subject B. — Stimulus — Violet. 





3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Bliie). 


\i 


1 


\ 


1 


} 


1 


1 


\ 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


i 


1 


^1 


i 




1 


1 


•8 

i 




> 


1 


1 


•8 

1 




> 


\ 


1 


93» 










dark 




ooae 




I 
I 


bl 

bl 




-ory? 
none 




8« 




dark 




yl? 






bl 




yl 




I 


bl 




-oryl 




83 




bl 




yi 






bl 




=oryl 




I 


bl 




■ oryl 




79 




bl 




yi 






bl 




yl 














76^ 




bl 




yi 






bl 




yl 




I 


bl 




— rdw 




7M 




bl 




yi 






bl 




yl 














ii 




bl 




yi 






bl 




yl 




I 


bl 




=ylor 






bl 





yi 







bl 




yl 




2 


bl 





=oryl 


2 


66 




bl 





yl 







bl 





yl 





2 


= Tibl 


2.5 


yl 


.5 


63.a 




bl 





yl 







bl 




-gryl 




I 


bl 




=gryi 




59.7 




bl 





-gryi 


^ 




bl 




yl 




3 


bl 





-gryl 





55 




bl 





=gryi 







bl 




yl 




2 


bl 





=gryi 


.5 


49 




bl 





-gryl 







bl 





yl 





2 


=vibl 


I 


-gryl 


1.5 


41^ 




Ti 





■gryi 







— carvi 


I 


-gryl 





2 


-blvi 


6.5 


yl 


.5 


31 




— carvi 


i^ 


yi+gr 


2 




▼i 




=gryi 




2 


— blvi 


8.5 


=gryi 


I 


»^ 




Ti 


3 


-ylgr 







Ti 




=yi«r 




I 


vi 




-gryl 




"^ 




— carvi 


I 


-yigr 


3-5 




▼i 




=gryl 




2 


▼i 





-ylgr 


X 







▼i 





-gryl 


.5 




HcarTi 




-gryl 




2 


vi 





-ylgr 


.5 



•58 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



Table XXIV. 

Subject F. — Stimulus — Carmine. 



BMkcnmsd. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


3t(Blae). 


|| 


1 


1 


1 


\ 


i 


1 


n 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


93* 














1^ 














84-S 














83 


dark 


light 










79 






red? 


yl 






76.5 


dark 


yl 










73.5 


dark 


yi 






car 


dark 


^J 


dark 


none 






■icarvi 


dark 


red 


lifbt 


■1 car red 


Ught 


■icarvi 


U? 


red? 


light 


car 


light 


car + n 


dark 


63.a 


red 


light 


car 


=ylgr 


car 


=gryi 


59.7 


red 


light 


dark 


light 


car 


«F 


55 


Ti 


yl 


— red car 


light 


car 


=yigr 


49 


car 


=gfyi 


— ▼icar 


=y;g» 


== red car 


-ylgr 


4i.a 


car 


=yigt 


=vicar 


=yig' 


car 


gr 


31 


car 


-yfgr 


car 


=ylgr 


car 


P 


aa5 


car 


car 


V 


car 


gr 


11.5 


— red car 


=rTg, 


=redcar 


-ylgr 


car 


P* 





car 


car 


V 


car 


P 



Stimulus — Rbd. 



«• 














tii 














84.5 














83 


dark 


"fi* 










79 


or + red 










76.5 


red 


bi 






red 


M 


73.5 


red 


bi 






=redQr 


bl 


71 


red 


bi 


red 


bl 


red 


bl 


68.5 


=orred 


bl 


red 


bl 


red 


bl 


66 


=orred 


bl 


red 


bl 


Hredor 


bl 


63.2 


red 


bl 


—or red 


bl 


=orred 


bl 


59-7 


red 


bl 


red 


bl? 


=orred 


bl 


55 


=orred 


bl 


=orred 


bl? 


■i or red 


U 


49 


red 


"e* 


=orred 


bl 


=orred 


U 


4i.a 


=orred 


red 


bl 


or 


-grbl 


31 


red 


■grbl 


red 


bl 


Mredor 


-grbl 


30.5 


=orred 


His 


=orred 


■ blgr 


i^ or red 


.grbl 


IX.5 


red 


red 


= blgr 


or 


«grU 





red 


scM-red 


none 


==orred 


gr + W 



AFTBR-IMAGBS ON THB PBRIPHBRAL RBTINA. 



»59 



XXV. 





Subject F.- 


- Stimulus — Orange. 






.jroiittd. 3 (Tallow). 


7 (Oieen). 


38 (Bine). 


A 


1 


i 


1 


1 


1 


} 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


93^ 














87.5 














84.5 














&i 














79 


=redor 


bi 










76.5 














73*5 


Bred or 


bi 






=ylor 


bl 


^.'5 


■ red or 


bi 


■ red or 


bl 


=redor 


bl 


=redor 


bi 


■ red or 


bl 


=redor 


bl 


{ 66 


or 


bi 


or 


bl 


yi 


bl 


63.3 


oiorred 


bi 


or 


bl 


Hred or 


bl 


59-7 


or 


bi 


■ or red 


bl 


or 


bl 


55 


=rcdor 


bi 


or 


bl 


=ylor 


bl 


49 


or 


bl 


vredor 


bl 


or 


bl 


41.2 


Mredor 


bl 


=redor 


bl 


=ylor 


bl 


31 


or 


-grbl 


=redor 


—grbl 


or 


=grbl 


ao.s 


or 


-grbl 


=redor 


■ grbl 


or 


=grbl 


11.5 


■1 red or 


gr + bl 


or 


gr-fbl 


or 


-grbl 





or 


bl 


■■red or 


none 


or 


=grbl 



Stimulus — Yellow, 



«• 














§7^5 














t' 


dark? 
or 


"fi» 










79 






=oryl 


bl 






76.S 


yl+or 


bl 






yi 


bl 


73.5 


=ylor 


bl 










# 


-ylor 


bl 


or 


M 


yl 


M 


-^yl 


bl 


or 


bl 


yi 


bl 


-oryl 


bl 


=oryl 


bl 


-<iyl 


bl 


63.3 


-yl^ 


bl 


or 


bl 


yl 


bl 


59-7 


■■red or 


bl 


or 


bl 


yl 


bl 


55 


or 


bl 


=oryl 


bl 


yl 


bl 


49 


or 


bl 


-ylor 


bl 


yl 


bl 


41.3 


or 


bl 


or 


bl 


yl 


bl 


31 


-oryl 


bl 


or 


bl 


—oryl 


bl 


Ja5 


=oryl 


bl 


-oryl 


bl 


—oryl 


bl 


11.5 


-v 


bl 


or 


bl 


yl 


bl 





bl? 


-ylor 


bl 


yl 


none 



i6o 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



Tablb XXVI. 

SuBjBCT F. — Stimulus — Grebn. 



BM^groaad. 3 (Yellow). 


7(Ore«i). 


3lR(Bl»e). 


|| 


i 


1 


i 


t 


i 


I 


-s 


1 


1 


1 




1 


1 

< 


9S» 














%% 














"ti 


or? 


bl? 










79 


dark 


bl 










76.5 


red 


bl 






yl 


u 


73.5 


red red 


blbl 






yl 


none 


d\ 


red red 


blbl 


=oryl 


bl 


yl 


none 


■ or red? 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yl 


U 


66 


.A 


bl 


yl 


bl 


yl 


none 


63.a 


bl 


or 


bl 


yl 


bl 


59.7 


P 


none 


yl 


bl 


yl 


bl 


55 


gr 


vi? 


-pyi 


bl 


yj 


avicar 


49 


V 


car 


-yip 


=vicar 


yl 


car 


4i.a 


tP 


car 


-yigr 


car 


yl 


■ ▼ibl 


31 


«r 


car 


=yi«' 


car 


-yigr 


=vtcar 


20.5 


gr 


car 


-yigr 


car 


g» 


=Ticar 


II.5 


««• 


car 


gf 


car 


gf 


=yictr 





gr 


car 


gr 


car 


F 


red 



Stimulus — Blub-Grbbn. 



93** 














m 














84.5 














fi2 














79 






yH 


bl? 






76.5 














73-5 


dark 


light 










71 


dark 


light 






light 


none 


68.5 


dark 


light 


"darf' 


=orred 


light 


dark 


66 


dark 


light 


car 


light 


dark 


63.2 


dark 


light 


dark 


none 


light 


red 


59.7 


dark 


light 


dark 


none 






55 


-blgr 


car 


-,% 


car 


gr? 


dark 


49 


..«' 


car 


car 


gr+bl 


red 


41.2 


-b gr 


car 


gr 


car 


=b gr 


red 


31 


■iblgr 


car 


-ffgr 


car 


■blgr 


car 


2as 


■ blgr 


=redcar 


car 


=blgr 


=:redcar 


11.5 


. ^ 


car 


gr 


car 


.blgr 


scarred 





■ blgr? 


car 


gr 


car 


-blgr 


car 



<FTBR'JMAGBS ON THB PBRIPHBRAL RBTINA. 



l6l 



NXVII. 

Subject F. 



- Stimulus — Grbbn-Blub. 



Backgrovnd. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Blue). 


% 


1 


j 


1 


1 


i 


1 


«• 














Si 














t' 














79 


dark 


71 










76.5 


bl 


yi 










73.5 


bl 


yi 






bl 


red 


71 


bl 


yi 










68.5 


bl 


yi 


=5" 


yi 


bl 


red 


66 


bl 


yi 


yi 






63.2 
59-7 


bl 


;i 


-S" 


=-/ 


bl 
bl 


red 
red 


55 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=oryl 


bl 


red 


49 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=oryl 


bl 


Horred 


41.2 


bl 


Boryl 
area car 


— grbl 


-oryl 


bl 


red 


31 


-grbl 


-grbl 


■lylor 


-grbl 


=orred 


20.5 


«grbl 


aired car 


-grbl 


=orred 


-grbl 


or + red 


11.5 


-grbl 


■1 or red 


-grbl 


■i or red 


-grbl 


=orred 





-grbl 


car 


-grbl 


car 







Stimulus — Blub. 



93^ 














%i 














84.5 


dark 


light 










82 


bl 


yi 










79 






bl 


=oryl 






76.5 


bl 


yi 






bl 


yi 


73.5 


bl 


yi 






bl 




71 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 






68.5 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


Bred or 


66 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


—or red 


63.2 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=ylor 


59.7 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


55 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


Bred or 


49 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=gryl 


bl 


red? 


41.2 


bl 


yi 


bl 


-gryl 


bl 


=oryl 


31 


bl 


y\ 


bl 


=gryl 


bl 


=gryi 


2a5 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=gryl 


11.5 


bl 


yi 


bl 


yi 


bl 


— ylor 





Ti 


yiH-gr 


=vibl 


yi 







i6s 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND JCATB GORDON. 



Tablb XXVIII. 

Subject F. — Stimulus — Violet. 



BMskgnmiuL 3 (Yeltow). 


r(Ort«i). 


3S(Btae). 


Ij 


i 

1 


1 


1 

1 


1 

1 


1 


! 


»• 














es 














t» 














79 






bl 


yl 






76.5 


bl 


yi 










73.5 


u 


yi 










71 
68.5 


bl 


yi 


bl 


=orTl 


bl 


— ocnd 


bl 


yl 


bl 


yl 


bl 


yl 


66 


bl 


yl 


bl 


yl 






65.a 






bl 


-6ryl 


bl 


yl 


59-7 


bl 


=«tyl 


bl 


yl 


bl 


-gryl 


55 


bl 


yl 


bl 


yl 


bl 


-/r 


49 


bl 


yl 


bl 


=gryi 


bl 


4i.a 


bl 


yl 


bl 


■ gryl 


bl 


=yip 


31 


▼i 


yi+gr 


■ ▼ibl 


yi+g» 


bl 


yl--gr 


las 


▼i 


-gryl 


bl 


■gryl 


bl 


=yigr 


11.5 


▼i 


-yigr 


▼I 


-ylgr 


bl 


yi+p 





▼i 


-gryi 


■ ▼ibl 


V 







Subject G. — Stimulus — C arminb. 



93' 














ei 


dark 


light 






light 


dark 


dark 


light 






light 


dark 


84.5 


dark 


light 






light 


dark 


82 


dark 


light 






car 


dark 


79 


dark 


light 






=redcar 


daik 


76.5 


dark 


-gryl 






Mredcar 


dark 


73.5 


dark 


-gryl 






car 


gr 


71 


dark 


yl 






car 


gr 


68.5 


dark 


=ylgr 






car 


gr 


66 


car 


=yigr 






car 


gr 


63.2 


car 


-y gr 






car 


S 


59.7 


car 


=yigr 






car 


55 


car 


-ylgr 






car 


gr 


49 


c^ 


8? 






car 


gr 


41.2 


=vlcar 


-ylgr 






car 


gr 


31 










car 


gr 


20.5 


car 


gr 






car 


gr 


11.5 



car 


gr 






car 


gr 



AFTBR'IMAGMS ON THB PBRIPHBRAL RBTINA. 



163 



Tablb XXIX. 



Subject G. — Stimulus — Red. 



Bukgtonnd. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Oreen). 


38 (Blue). 


|| 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


1 


4 


1 


1 


1 


< 


1 


1 


«• 














87)5 


dark 


light 






light 


bl 


dark 


light 






or 


-grbl 


t» 


£rk 


light 






=oryl 


V 


79 


red 






yl+or 


g' 


76.5 


red 


bl 






or 


=grbl 


73-5 


red 


bl 






HOT red 


-grbl 


71 


—or red 


-grbl 






■1 or red 


bl 


68.5 


red 


bi 






H or red 


-grbl 


66 


red 


bl 






Horred 


-grbl 


63.2 


red 


bl 






=orred 


—grbl 


59.7 


red 


bl 






—or red 


=grbl 


55 


=orred 


bl 






=orred 


=grbl 


49 


red 


=grbl 






Bcarred 


■ grbl 


41.2 


red 


■ grbl 






Borred 


gr + bl 


31 


red 


-grbl 






=orred 


■ grbl 


30.5 


red 


gr-fbl 






red 


■ grbl 


11.5 


=orred 


■blgr 






=-or red 


gr + bl 


















Stimulus — Orange . 



»• 














iJI 


none 


none 






s 


bl 

bl 


\' 


or 
or 


bl 
bl 






s 


bl 
bl 


79 


— red or 


bl 






or 


bl 


76:5 


= redor 


bl 






or 


bl 


73.5 


or 


bl 






or 


bl 


71 


H or red 


bl 






= or vl 
= red or 


bl 


68.5 


= redor 


— vibl 






bl 


66 


or 


bl 






= orred 


-grb- 


63.2 


or 


bl 






or 


bl 


59.7 


or 


-grbl 






— ylor 


= vibl 


55 


or 


-grbl 






= red or 


-grbl 


49 


or 


=grbl 






= or red 


-grbl 


41.2 


or 


-grbl 






— red or 


-grbl 


31 


or 


bl 






or 


-grbl 


20.5 


or 


-grbl 
■ blgr 






or 


gr + bl 


"•5 


or 






or 


-grbl 


















164 



HBLEN B. THOMPSON AND KATB GORDON. 



Tablb XXX. 

Subject G. — Stimulus — Yellow. 



BackgrcraiuL 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


3« (Blue). 




1 
1 


1 


1 

1 


\ 


1 


1 

< 


93' 














til 


or 


bl 






light 

yl 


bl 
bl 


84.5 


.ylor 


bl 






yl 


bl 


82 


or 


bl 






yl 


bl 


79 


yl 


bl 






yl 


bl 


76.5 


-ylor 


bl 






yl 


bl 


73.5 


yl 


bl 






yl 


bl 


71 


yl+or 


bl 






yl 


bl 


68.5 


=oryl 


bl 






yl 


bl 


66 


or 


bl 






yl 


bl 


63.2 


yl 


bl 






yl 


=vibl 


59-7 


=oryl 


bl 






yl 


bl 


55 


yl 


bl 






yl 


bl 


49 


—ylor 


bl 






yl 


bl + yi 


41.2 


yl+or 


=vibl 






yl 


none 


31 


-oryl 


bl 






yl 


Kblvi 


20.5 


yl 


=vibl 






yl 


bl 


11.5 


yl 


=vlbl 






yl 


■ivibl 


















Stimulus — Green. 



«• 














^1 


none 


none 






light 


none 


dark 


light 






Ught 


dark 


84.5 


dark 


Uffht 
=Ticar 






yl 


none 


82 


«T 






yl 


bl 


79 


dark 


bl 






yl 


none 


76.5 


yl? 


bl 






yl 


none 


73.5 


gr 


vi 






=gryl 


none 


^\ 


-gryi 

—ylor 


bl 
car 






-/y. 


bl 
Hcarvi 


66 


gr 


▼i 






-gryl 


=blvi 


63.2 


gr 


■i red car 






■ ylgr 


=vicar 


59.7 


-ylgr 


=vicar 






yi+gr 


■ carvt 


55 


gr 


car 






=y gr 


=blvi 


49 


gr 


—red car 






=y gr 

yi+gr 


=vicar 


41.2 


gt 


—vicar 






car+n 


31 


gr 


=vicar 






V 


=c«r7i 


20.5 


gr 


car 






p^ 


▼i 


11.5 



V 


= vicar 






gr 


Mcarvi 



AFTBR'IMAGBS ON THE PERIPHERAL RETINA, 

Table XXXI. 

Subject G. — Stimulus — Blue-Green, 



165 



BMksnmnd. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (Green). 


38 (Blue). 


1^ 


1 


1 


1 


1 


I 


1 


« 


1 


\ 


1 




1 




93" 














t{\ 










light 


dark 


dark 


none 






light 


dark 


84.5 










light 


dark 


82 


dark 


Ught 






light 


? 


79 


dark 


Ught 






light 


car 


76.5 


fS^ 


led 






light 


=-=carred 


73.5 


dark 


car? 






light 


dark 


71 


gr 


none 






light 


Bred car? 


68.5 


none 


red? 






gr? 


red 


66 


— bfgr 


red 










63.2 


or 






bl 


red 


59-7 
55 


=bfgr 


=carred 
=carred 






light 
-blgr 


Bred car 
car 


49 
41.3 


—blgr 
-bf^ 


Hredcar 
■1 red car 






:2s 

-Elgr 


car 
car 


31 


red H- car 






HTicar 


30.5 


'^blgr 


car 






-blgr 


■it! car 


11.5 



=blgr 


Hredcar 






-Mgr 


Hvicar 



Stimulus — Green-Blue. 



93* 














t;\ 


dark 


light 






light 
light 


none 
dark 


84.5 


dark 


none 






light 


Bred or 


8a 


bl 


=oryl 






-grbl 


■1 or red 


79 


bl 


.71 or 






bl 


led? 


76.5 


dark 


yi 






"«' 


red 


73.5 


bl 


= oryl 






Bred or 


71 


dark 


= orTl 






bl 


red 


68.5 


bl 


yi+gr 






bl 


=rorred 


66 


■ grbl 


-ylor 






bl 


■ or red 


63.2 


bl 


or 






bl 


=orred 


59-7 


bl 


or 






bl 


= orred 


55 


—grbl 


or 






bl 


red 


49 


—grbl 


-oryl 






-grS 


Borred 


41.2 


=grbl 


or 






= or red 


31 


■ grbl 


or 






Borred 


2a5 


-grbl 


or 






■ grbl 


Borred 


11.5 



■ grbl 


or 






■ grbl 


=orred 



i66 



HBLBN B. THOMPSON AND XATB GORDON. 



Table XXXII. 





Subject G. 


— STimiLus — Blub. 




BMkcTOvad. 3 (Yellow). 


7 (GICCB). 


3«(W«e). 


, 


1 


1 


! 


1 


1 


} 


-s 


1 


1 


1 


^ 


1 


1 


93^ 














tx 


gr? 


light 






none 


n<me 


dark 


yi 






bl 


vred or 


84.5 


dark 


yi 






bl 


8a 


dark 


= oryl 






bl 


or 


79 


dark 


.oryl 






bl 


Morred 


76.5 


bl 


— gryl 






bl 


r-id 


735 


-▼ibl 


-gryi 






bl 


M or red 


71 
68.5 


dark 
bl 


yi 






bl 


■1 red or 

a"' 


66 


bl 






bl 


Morred 


63.a 


bl 


= 8rTl 






bl 


■i or red 


59-7 


bl 


■"/ 






bl 


yi 


55 


bl 






bl 


Bred or 


49 

41.2 


bl 
bl 


rsS 






bl 
bl 


■ red or 


31 


■ blTl 


=yiF 






bl 


yl + oc 


Ja5 










bl 


yl + or 


XI.5 


bl 


yi 






=grbl 


-oryl 


o 















Stimulus — Violbt. 



93* 














9as 










bl 


yi , 


»7.5 










none 


Horjl 


%> 


dark 
bl 


light 






bl 
bl 


= redor 


79 


dark 






bl 


or 


76.5 


dark 


yi 






bl 


yi 


73-5 


dark 


^oryl 






bl 


yi 


^. 


dark 
bl 


-fi" 






bl 
bl 


■i red or 

yi 


66 


bl? 


yi 






bl 


-ylgr 


6s.a 


bl 


-gryl 






bl 


59*7 


bl 


= gryl 






bl 


55 


bl 


■ Sryl 






bl 


-ylor 


49 


bl 


-gryl 






= vibl 


-gryl 


41.2 


— ▼ibl 


-gryl 






=vlbl 


-«tyj 


31 


▼i 


-yigr 






▼i 


■ gryl 


».5 


▼1 


=yigr 






=blvi 


-yi«' 


ir.5 



vl 


=yigr 






vi 


yi+«r 



I 



AFTBJt-IMAGBS ON THB PBRIPHBRAL RBTINA. 1 67 

Table XXXIII. 



Subject B. 


Biudegioaiid. 7(YeUoir). 


Backgroimd. 38 (Blue). 


Flr.pt j Color Seen. After-image. 


Piz.pt| Color Seen. After-image. 



Stimulus — Carmine. 



55- 

41.2 
31 


■it! car 

car 
■i vicar 


■ 7lgr|bl car 

\~-r«dcar 1 gr 
gr 1 - bl gr fear 


31 


■■red car 
aredcar 


gr 1 Miedcar 

gr|car|=ylgr 



Stimulus — Orange. 



41.2 



I red or 



bl|«igrbl|ied 



Stimulus — Green. 



59.7 


zikV 


car|=blgr 


41.5 


-gryl 


vi + car 1 ■ yl gr 


49 


-blgr 


f = vicar| 
\ = blgr 1 car 
HrecTcar | gr 


31 


«r + yi 


car|»ylgr 


31 


gr 


ao.5 


■ ylgr 


carlgr 



Stimulus — Blue-Green. 



= red car I ■ bl gr 
car I Mblgr 
car|— grbl 

==redcar I Hvi 
car I H bl gr 



55 


■ blgr 


41.2 


—blgr 


31 


-blgr 


ao.5 


-blgr 



31 



carlgr 



Stimulus — Green-Blub. 



41.2 



= grbl 



=orredJ 

=car rea | iBgrbl 



55 
31 



bl 
■ blgr 



-red or | Mblgr? 
: or red | v bl gr 



Stimulus — Blue. 



31 



bl 



-yip* I — oryl I 
Hylor I mi red or 
I car 



66 

31 



bl 
I grbl 



I red or | —blgr 
:ylor I =blgr 



Stimulus — Violet. 



55 



bl 



■ ylgr |=ylgr| 

<»r I = yi gr 



EDITORS' ANNOUNCEMENT. 

The editors of the Review announce the completion of ar- 
rangements to issue a new series of Monographs, planned on 
the lines of the Psychological Monograph Series already estab- 
lished. This new series will be devoted to philosophical topics, 
and will bear the title Philosophical Monographs. The two 
series will proceed side by side, being devoted respectively to 
more extended papers on psychological and ph^osophical 
subjects. We are glad to offer to authors and University de- 
partments this wider channel of publication on the terms here- 
tofore extended in connection with the old series. Correspon- 
dence with reference to the printing of Monographs and 
manuscripts should be addressed as follows : 
For the series of Psychological Monographs^ 
to Prof. C. H. JuDD, Yale University, 

New Haven, Conn. 
For the series of Philosophical Monographs^ 
to Prof. J. Mark Baldwin, Johns Hopkins University, 

Baltimore, Md. 



N. S. Vol. XIV. No. 3. May, 1907. 



The Psychological Review. 



STUDIES FROM THE LABORATORY OF THE UNI- 
VERSITY OF CHICAGO. 

COMMUNICATED BY PROFESSOR JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL. 

The Pendular Whiplash Illusion of Motion. 

BY HARVEY CARR, Ph.D. 

I. In an article entitled *The Participation of the Eye 
Movements in the Visual Perception of Motion,'^ Mr. Dodge 
reviews the historical trend of opinion in assigning a less and 
less importance to the factor of eye movement in mediating the 
visual consciousness of motion ; he further takes the extreme 
radical position in this trend of thought by denying to eye 
movements any function at all ; he maintains the thesis that eye 
movements alone can not mediate any consciousness of visual 
motion. ** Not only, however, is there no independent con- 
sciousness of the eye movements, adequate to the refinement of 
the visual perception of motion, but the character of the eye 
movements which occur when we view a moving object furnishes 
evidence that, if our consciousness of them were complete and 
exact, it would be either useless or misleading as a datum in 
the visual perception of motion" (p. 3). In speaking of the 
results of One of his tests, he maintains that it *< serves at once 
to show the utter inability of the pursuit movement either to sub- 
serve the perception of motion of the fixated point or to correct 
the exaggerated data from the displacement of the retinal image 
of the nonfixated point " (p. 14). 

A crucial test of the theory would involve the elimination of 
all other possible functioning factors, the perception of an 

^ PtYCH. Ricv., 1904, pp. 1-14. 

169 



170 HARVEY CARjR. 

isolated moving object whose stimulation remains stationary 
upon the retina. Professor Dodge contends that these ideal 
conditions are obtained in his pendulum test. Two lights of 
weak intensity are placed on the two arms of a counterbalanced 
pendulum. One of these swinging lights is followed by the 
eyes, while the other is perceived peripherally. Former 
photographic tests have demonstrated that the image of the 
fixated light is not displaced on the retina during the last 
quarter of its swing. According to the theory, the fixated 
light should appear motionless during these ideal conditions, 
while of course the second light would still be seen in motion 
during this period. As a matter of fact, the experiment gave 
the expected results ; the peripherally perceived light was seen 
to move an appreciable time after the fixated light came to a 
full stop ; this second light appeared to make < a gratuitous 
whiplash excursion 'of its own. **We have already called 
attention to the fact that the end of ev^y pursuit sweep is freer 
from corrective movements than its beginning. This is con- 
spicuously true of the pursuit sweeps by which the line of 
regard follows a swinging pendulum. Photographs of such 
sweeps give no indication of corrective movements either 
negative or positive within the last quarter of the swings 
studied." He further says that the conditions of the experiment 
are such that it ' constitutes a faultless experimental test of our 
conclusions ' (p. 13). 

There is no doubt as to the genuineness of the whiplash 
phenomenon. Mr. Dodge has well described it. Also, is it 
obvious that the theory will satisfactorily explain the illusion, nor, 
so far as I know, is there any reason for questioning the state- 
ment that ideal conditions obtain during this part of the swing. 

Mr. Dodge further maintains that the illusion is * capable of 
only one explanation,' *. ^., in terms of his theory. If this be 
true, it would logically follow that the phenomenon is proof 
positive of the truth of his theoretical position. The only escape 
from the inevitable logic of the situation is to question his 
proposition that no other explanatory theory is possible. In 
fact, one such possible explanation occurred to the writer upon 
reading the article in question. 



PENDULAR WHIPLASH ILLUSION. 171 

Let US assume the truth of the doctrine generally accepted 
before Dodge advanced his extreme proposition, viz., that eye 
movements can mediate visual motion, but only for the greater 
magnitudes and velocities ; that their limen of perceptibility is 
much greater than that of the factor of retinal displacement. 
The assumption is entirely probable, for surfaces differ in their 
sensitivity to movement. A stimulus of a definite magnitude 
and rapidity may be below the limen of perceptibility on one 
part of the skin, and still be distinctly perceived as movement on 
another area. The same is true for different parts of the retina. 
In fact this is the generally accepted view, which Dodge is try- 
ing to overthrow. As the pendulum approaches the end of its 
swing, the rate of movement gradually decreases to zero. Con- 
sequently, for some definite portion of the end of its swing, its 
rate would be below the eye movement limen, but still above 
the retinal limen of perceptibility. In other words, the retinally 
perceived light would be seen moving for an appreciable time 
after the fixated light had apparently stopped. Hence the 
gratuitous whiplash excursion is evident. Since the function 
of eye movement in the perception of motion is the point at 
ssue, one has as much right to make a ositive assumption as 
Dodge has to assume a lack of function. The theory further 
has the weight of historical opinion behind it. 

A third possible theory developed during a repetition of the 
experiment. The fixated light when successfully followed has 
(during the last portion of its swing) no positive after-image. The 
peripherally perceived light, on the contrary, does leave a pro- 
nounced positive after-image streak. The eye moves in a direc- 
tion opposite to this latter light and consequently the rapidity of 
its retinal displacement equals that of a light, perceived by a 
stationary eye, moving at a rate equal to the combined velocities 
of the two lights used in the pendulum test. Other things being 
equal, the length of the after-image streak varies directly with 
the rapidity of the retinal displacement. Thus a very pro- 
nounced length of the positive streak results in the test. This 
light, with its positive after-image, is viewed peripherally and 
hence is seen indistinctly and en masse; without conscious effort 
on the part of the observer, it appears as an elongated light with 



173 HARVBY CARR, 

no very decided contour, nor sharply discriminated parts; it 
appears as a conscious whole or unity. As the pendulum 
reaches the end of its swing, this elongated mass of light rapidly 
contracts in length at its rear end. This occurs for two reasons : 
(i) the velocity of the pendulum rapidly decreases toward zero, 
and the length of the positive after-image is a function of the 
rate of movement ; (2) the light on its return swing back-tracks, 
as it were, and meets the receding end of the fading after-image, 
but now leaves another positive streak in its rear. If the posi- 
tive streak is six inches long when the pendulum is one inch 
from the end of its swing, and this streak has time to disappear 
while the pendulum is moving and returning over this final inch 
of its arc, it is evident that the total mass of light will have con- 
tracted at its rear end from six inches to one inch in length. 
These values are of course merely illustrative. Movement, 
psychologically, is the consciousness of spatial changes, and 
these changes occur at the two ends of the elongated light, the 
shifting boundaries between the two discriminable visual con- 
tents. One of these cues of movement becomes abnormally ex- 
aggerated as the pendulum comes to a full stop, and still con- 
continues to be operative, without any contrary cue, while the 
pendulum is gathering headway on its return swing. Conse- 
quently, the whole mass of light will appear to be moving on, 
after the pendulum has really stopped. The observed extra 
movement is thus a purely illusory one. Such a conception in- 
volves no new doctrine, for the influence of the receding posi- 
tive after-image streak in mediating the perception of motion is 
well known. At the very least, the theory possesses an a priori 
possibility. 

We shall term these theories A^ j9, and C in the order of 
their exposition. It is to be noted that only A and B are mutually 
exclusive. The phenomenon may be due to the causes desig- 
nated in A^ ov Bf or C, or it may be the combined result of 
those mentioned in A and C, or B and C. We propose to re- 
count some additional observations and tests throwing light 
upon the relative efficiency of these conceptions as explanatory 
principles. 

Hereafter the fixated and the peripherally perceived lights 



PBNDULAR WHIPLASH ILLUSION, 173 

will be termed the upper and the lower lights respectively. 
Unless otherwise stated, the following conditions will obtain : 
The length of the upper arm of the pendulum is slightly shorter 
than that of the lower arm. The lower arm is 78 cm. in length, 
and swings through an arc of 100 cm. The pendulum moves 
at a velocity of two seconds for a complete swing, 1. e.^ for a for- 
ward and a return movement. The observer is stationed at a 
distance of 230 cm., and the eye moves through an angle of 23 
degrees in following the upper light. The angular distance of 
the lower light from the fovea is approximately 30 degrees. 
Two miniature incandescent lights were used of such intensity 
that no other objects were visible. The tests were conducted 
at night in a dark room. 

II. Mr. Dodge alleges that the apparent length of the upper 
light's movement is judged to be much shorter than that of the 
lower one. In order to secure an equality of apparent length 
of movement, he found it necessary to make the upper arc of 
movement three times the length of the lower. He calls atten- 
tion to the similarity between this ratio and that obtained by 
Exner, Von Fleischl, et aL^ between the apparent rates of 
movement when judged with stationary eyes on the one hand, 
and with the eyes following the movement on the other. If the 
experienced velocity and duration of movement of the lower 
light are greater than that of the upper light, apparently it 
should seem to move for the greater distance. 

My observers did not confirm these results as to the apparent 
lengths of movetnent. In fact, they gave judgments of equality 
of movement only when the two arcs were practically equal in 
length.^ Moreover, the argument is not valid that the apparent 
movement of the lower light must be greater than that of the 
upper light because it has the greater apparent velocity and 
duration. In certain illusions, as the PUrkinje dizziness phe- 

' Probably this discrepancy is dae to a difference in the method of judging, 
for there are present several cues upon which the observer may base his judg- 
ments of length. It is practically impossible to make a judgment as to pure 
lengthy nninflnenced by other motives. The apparent rate of movement may 
have a determining influence, or the observer may mentally superimpose the 
two lengths to be compared. My observers invariably found themselves using 
the latter method. 



1 74 HAR VB Y CARR, 

nomenon and especially under some conditions of * autokinetic 
sensations/ I have often observed that the customary mathe- 
matical relation between rate and magnitude of motion does 
not obtain. The light may appear to be moving at the rate of 
two feet a second, and yet after some time one would not judge 
the distance traversed to be over a few feet in length. The 
illusion is so striking to the writer under some circumstances, 
that the felt discrepancy between rate of movement and dis- 
tance traversed forces itself upon the attention. The light ap- 
pears to be moving r af idly ^ but yet does not appear to be getting 
anywhere, to be traversing space. One receives to some extent 
the anomalous feeling that the light is both moving and not 
moving at the same time. On the other hand, in a test to be 
described later, I received the impression occasionally that the 
amount of movement was too great for the velocity, that the 
object got to -positions without moving there. As another illus- 
tration of the truth that axioms of ideal space do not necessarily 
hold true for experienced space, I may cite the fact that in cuta- 
neous space two lengths equal to a third length do not always 
equal each other. In fact, many spatial illusions exist simply 
because the spatial relations of our experiences do not tally with 
the relationships of ideal space. 

According to the theory A^ the upper light appears motion- 
less, when the pendulum has completed three fourths of its 
swing. The lower light is still perceived to be moving during 
the Jast quarter. Consequently, this extra movement of the 
lower light after the upper one has ceased moving ought to be 
equal in length to one fourth of the arc ; with our conditions 
this would be 25 cm. Judgments as to its apparent length gave 
values of but 7~io cm. Such judgments are of course un- 
reliable so far as any nice accuracy is concerned, but the dis- 
crepancy between these values and 25 cm. appears too great to 
be explained in this manner. 

If the upper light appears motionless when the pendulum 
completes but three fourths of its swing, and a screen is in- 
terposed so as to intercept the subject's vision of the lower 
light at this point, 1. ^., cut off from view ^he last quarter 
(25 cm.) of its movement, it follows that the lower light should 



PBNDULAR WHIPLASH ILLUSION, 1 75 

disappear at the same time that the upper light ceases mov- 
ing. This test was made as follows: The position of the 
screen was adjustable so that the subject's vision of the lower 
light was intercepted for any desired portion of the end of the 
swing. The amount of arc intercepted was varied in an 
irregular manner, nor was it known to the observer. The sub- 
ject was asked to judge whether the lower light disappeared 
before, after, or coincidently with the cessation of movement on 
the part of the upper light. As many trials were allowed as 
• the subject desired before giving each judgment. For judg- 
ments of simultaneity, two observers gave an average result of 
5 cm., with an average variation of 2 cm. Within these limits 
(3-7 cm.), hesitancy of judgment was the rule. For the greater 
values of 10-25 cm., the observers were never in doubt; the 
upper light was distinctly perceived in motion after the disap- 
pearance of the lower light, i. tf., during at least nine tenths of 
its swing. 

This experiment was varied by so placing the screen as to 
wholly intercept the sight of the lower light. This screen con- 
tained a small opening, 2 cm. square. This opening could be 
placed at any position along the arc of movement. Conse- 
quently, the lower light would be momentarily visible only at a 
certain desired time during its swing. The observer was now 
asked to judge whether this light was seen before, after or 
coincidently with the cessation of movement on the part of the 
upper light. An average value of 2 cm. was obtained for judg- 
ments of simultaneity. For larger values there was no hesi- 
tancy of judgment. For all points above 5 cm. from the end 
of the swing, the upper light was perceived in distinct motion 
after the lower one became visible. The theory demands that 
the upper light be seen moving only during 75 hundredths of its 
sv^ing. These results show that it is distinctly -perceived in 
motion throughout 90 to 95 hundredths of its arc. 

This extra duration of movement, or the whiplash excursion, 
can be seen under conditions of observation other than those 
taken into account by theory A, It can be seen with stationary 
eyes where both movements are perceived entirely by retinal 
criteria. The subject fixates the point in space where the 



1 76 HAR VB Y CARR. 

upper light comes to a full stop and observes the two move- 
ments under these conditions. When the the two arms of the 
pendulum are equal in length, the whiplash effect is absent. 
However, if the lower arm of the pendulum is much the longer, 
the whiplash phenomenon is again in evidence. Obviously, 
this result can not be explained on the basis of theory A* 

III. The results of the above test can be explained by theory 
C. This conception of the whiplash effect assumes that the 
lower light appears to move for a greater duration of time but 
not necessarily through a greater amount of space. This 
apparent greater duration of movement is due to the stimulation 
of the receding end of the positive after-image streak. The 
duration of this extra movement would thus depend upon the 
length of this streak, and this length would depend, other con- 
ditions being similar, upon the actual velocity of the light. 
When the two lights are viewed with stationary eyes, positive 
streaks follow both lights. When the two arms of the pendu- 
lum are equal in length, the linear velocities of the lights and 
the lengths of their streaks are equal. Both lights would thus 
appear to move after the pendulum actually stopped, but for an 
equal duration of time. When the lower arm is much the 
longer, the lower streak is also the longer. Both lights would 
appear to move a/ler the pendulum stopped, but for unequal 
durations of time. The lower light would appear moving after 
the upper one came to a full stop. In other words, the whip- 
lash effect would be absent in the first case, but present in the 
second, in accordance with my observations. 

In the above judgments of simultaneity where the lower 
light disappeared behind the screen on the one hand, and ap- 
peared through the opening on the other, a larger value was 
obtained in the first case. Granted that this difference of value 
is a valid result under the two conditions, the fact can be 
explained by theory C In the first case the positive streak is 
present, but is absent in the second case because the light is hid 
behind the screen. Simultaneity was secured at 5 and 2 cm. 
from the end of the swing respectively for the two conditions. 
When the positive streak is present, the lower light will be visible, 
in indirect vision, after its actual disappearance behind the 



PBNDULAR WHIPLASH ILLUSION. 1 77 

screen. In order to make its apparent disappearance coinci- 
dent with the cessation of the upper light's movement, it would 
need to be intercepted earlier in its swing by an amount of time 
equal to the functional persistence of the positive streak. As a 
matter of fact when the positive streak was present, the light 
was intercepted 3 cm. earlier in its swing. According to the 
conception, the time taken for the pendulum to move these 3 
cm. should equal the functional duration of the positive streak. 
Since the pendulum moves 100 cm. per second, this time would 
be .03 second, provided that the rate of movement were uniform. 
Since the pendular movement decreases in velocity at the end 
of the swing, the actual time must be greater than this value, 
probably at least .05 second. 

The whiplash illusion is conditioned by the direction of the 
attention. If the positive streak be consciously neglected by 
focussing the peripheral attention upon the forward part of the 
moving light, the whiplash effect is practically eliminated. By 
voluntarily attending to the streak, 1. e., to the receding end of 
the elongated light, the illusion of extra movement at once be- 
comes evident. It was this observation which led to the formu- 
lation of the after-image theory. A second observer who knew 
nothing at all of the theories involved, voluntarily offered the 
same explanation after some observation of the phenomenon. 

A contrary illusion may sometimes be obtained by sharply 
discriminating the light from its positive streak. Instead of 
perceiving the lower light moving forward, it may be seen 
moving backwards a couple of centimeters on its return swing 
while the upper light still appears motionless. 

Since the length of the positive streak varies directly with 
the pendular velocity, it would follow, according to theory C, 
that the illusory effect will vary in direct proportion to the pen- 
dular rate of movement. By a system of weights, the velocity 
was varied without any other alteration of conditions. The 
rates secured were 5,3, and 2 seconds for a complete swing. 
Judgments of the illusory movement were then given in linear 
terms. Values of i, 3, and 6 cm. respectively were obtained 
for the three rates in the order given above. 

A sufficient portion of the end of the swing for each of these 



178 HARVEY CARR, 

rates of movement was intercepted so as to obtain a judgment 
of equality in the duration of movement for the two lights. 
According to the theory the amount of arc intercepted should 
vary in proportion to the three rates. The values of 15, 30 and 
45 mm. respectively were secured. These results correspond 
rather closely to the above values for the apparent lengths for 
this extra movement. The actual numerical values are in them- 
selves unimportant ; they bring out the fact, however, that the 
apparent extra movement does varj' directly with the velocity 
of the pendulum. 

A weak diffused light, 10 x 15 cm. in dimensions, was so 
placed that the lower light would swing past and just emerge 
from it at the end of the movement. This background of dif- 
fused light was so varied in intensity that the positive streak 
could not be differentiated from it by direct observation. The 
experiment was then repeated as usual. At the end of the 
swing, the lower light would flash out sharply against its black 
background, while the positive streak could not be seen. The 
functional efficiency of the receding after-image was thus elimi- 
nated. Under these conditions the illusory movement was not 
apparent, while the lower light would flash out into distinct 
view practically at the same time that the upper light came to a 
full stop. 

IV. But little positive evidence can be given in favor of the- 
ory B. The contrary illusion can be interpreted on this basis. 
The velocity of the pendulum is so small for the end and be- 
ginning of each swing that eye movements can not mediate 
a sense of motion. The upper light is thus not perceived in 
motion for a couple of centimeters at the end and beginning of 
its movement. Since the retina is more sensitive to movement 
than the eyes, the lower light is seen moving during this time ; 
it not only moves forward a centimeter after the upper light 
stops, but also may be seen moving backward on its return 
swing before the upper light gathers a sufficient velocity to 
arouse a movement consciousness. The phenomenon might be 
explained legitimately in other terms, however. 

In so far as the after-image theory does not entirely account 
for the illusory effect, it is legitimate to assume the influence of 



PENDULAR WHIPLASH ILLUSION, 1 79 

factor B. In several of the tests, a slight illusory effect ap- 
peared to be present, although the after-image was eliminated. 
When the light appeared through the opening in the screen, the 
after-image was not present, yet the upper light was judged to 
be motionless when the pendulum lacked two centimeters of 
completing its swing. When the after-image was suppressed 
by the background of diffused light, a slight suggestion of the 
illusory movement was occasionally noticed. These cases are 
explicable in terms of theory -ff, though, of course, they may 
be explained by other means. No conclusive proof of this 
theory can be offered. 

V. On the whole the evidence seems sufficient, to the writer, 
to warrant the conclusions that the phenomenon is not to be ex- 
plained in any measure by theory A ; that the upper light is 
perceived in motion during the major part of the last quarter of 
its swing ; that the phenomenon is due mainly to the receding 
positive after-image ; and that possibly factor B may have a 
small determining influence. 

If Dodge's contention be true that ideal conditions obtain dur- 
ing the last quarter of the arc of movement, and if our tests 
prove that the upper light is seen in motion during the major 
portion of this time, it would logically follow that the experi- 
ment is proof positive against Dodge's theory as to the lack of 
function on the part of eye movements ; that tliey, on the con- 
trary, do function in the perception of movement. However, 
the writer does not presume to advance such a dogmatic con- 
clusion on the basis of a single experiment, in view of the fact 
that the results of several other experiments advanced by Dodge 
and others remain to be controverted. 

VI. A rather interesting phenomenon developed during a 
modification of the pendular experiment. Both lights were 
attached to the lower arm, but at different distances from the 
axis of rotation. If the upper light be followed by the eyes, 
the same results are obtained as formerly, though the whiplash 
effect is not so pronounced. The motion of the lower light is 
retinally perceived, because the eyes do not move to the same 
extent as does this light. When the lower light is followed, the 
eyes move faster than does the upper light, and consequently 



1 80 HAR VB Y CARR, 

retinal cues of movement are present. Moreover, the upper 
light is now freceded by a positive streak. Since the pendular 
velocity decreases at the end of the swing, the elongated light 
must now contract in length on \\& forward end. The forward 
end of the positive streak travels backward in relation to the 
light. Two opposing retinal criteria of movement are now 
present. The receding streak tends to oppose^ or neutralize^ 
instead of emphasizing^ the upper light's motion. As a matter 
of fact, one's consciousness of this motion is strikingly peculiar 
and difficult of description. The movement seems weak and 
attenuated in character ; it lacks body, force and vitality. It 
sometimes appears to be markedly shorter than its actual length, 
while at other times it appears to approximate its normal length, 
but in this case its length seems to be too great for its velocity ; 
it strikes one at times as being in certain positions without hav- 
ing moved there. This illusory appearance becomes striking, 
if the observer suddenly stops the eyes and holds them station- 
ary ; the movement at once flashes out in vigor and vitality. 
Whatever the proper explanation may be, the illusion is cer- 
tainly unique and seems worthy of further study.^ 

> The MS. of thia article was received December 25, '06. — Bd. 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE.* 

BY PROF. J. MARK BALDWIN. 
Johns Hopkins University, 

§ I. The Determination of Thought in a System. 
The description of logical meaning from the point of view 
of the belief embodied in the various forms of judgment, leads 
naturally on to the inquiry as to its development. We have 
seen, in our broad survey of the genesis of the logical mode, 
certain motive principles at work for the establishing of logical 
content or subject matter. It is, of course the continued action 
of these motives that carries on the movement, in the logical 
mode itself, by which its meanings are added to and extended. 
We may therefore, in taking up the problem of the develop- 
ment that logical meanings normally undergo, recall to mind 
the essential movements already recognized. 

1. In the first place, it may be pointed out that logical 
meanings constitute a context of thoughts. The prelogical 
meanings of all sorts, the individuated contents established by 
processes earlier than explicit judgment, are taken up in the 
organized system of experience which is the objective thought- 
world of the thinker. It is first of all the thinker's experience, 
controlled in the inner processes of judgment and acknowledg- 
ment, whatever further reference or confirmation it may have 
as being true to- or cognizant of * reality.' 

2. In the second place, we may recall the outcome of the 
discussion of ^ common ' meanings in the logical mode, to the 
effect that all judgments and hence all thought-contexts are com- 
mon in the sense of being * synnomic ' or * appropriate ' for the 
acceptance of all competent judgment everywhere. The belief 
of the individual as determined in an act of judgment, is for 
him the expression of the belief of the larger world of personal 
selves. Apart from the question as to whether other individual 

'Prom the material of chapter VI. of the writer's work, Thought and 
Things or Genetic Logic, Vol. II., ' Experimental Logic' 

i8i 



1 82 jr. MARK BALD WIN, 

thinkers do or do not at the time agree with him, still, in giving 
his belief, he is constituting a subject matter to which, by the 
essential movement involved, others are expected to give their 
assent. 

3. Furthermore and third, this common character and mean- 
ing of the subject matter of thought was found to rest geneti- 
cally or prelogically upon a process that is both social and 
experimental : the process described in our earlier discussions 
under the term * secondary conversion.' We found that the 
context of knowledge, considered as a confirmed and established 
body of data, was in very essential ways due to the recognition 
and use of the contents of the minds of one's social fellows. 
Before it is judged, knowledge, as so far common, is ^ syn- 
doxic' All but the original substantive parts of experience — 
the parts found directly convertible into the hard coin of per- 
sisting and recurring fact — was actually set off from the fugi- 
tive and private images of fancy, through such secondary and 
essentially social conversion process. It was in the further 
development of this motive, it will be remembered also, that the 
marks of knowledge as general, universal, and even singular 
were derived. The conclusion that knowledge — in any mode 
that is not subpersonal and so subsocial ^ — is a ' social out- 
come rather than a private possession,' summed up our results 
in the matter. 

We should expect, as has been said above, that the develop- 
ment of the context of thinking would be by a process contin- 
uous with that of its origin; that is, that accretions to the 
body of experience would be effected in the same way that 
earlier acquisitions were made. And this appears necessar}' 
when we remember that no material is available at all except 
that which has passed through these simpler modes. The new 
thoughts are always also sensations, memories, images or other 
such meanings that are found available in the development of 
the selective motives by which they are constituted as thoughts. 
There is, therefore, no extension of the context of thought ex- 

* Even the low-grade knowledge of the perceptual mode is shot through 
with the quasi-social meaning that we have called ' commonness of common 
function. ' 



THOUGHT AND LANGUA GE. 183 

cept SO far as the judgment is determined upon meanings by its 
one characteristic process. This process is, as has been said, 
both social and experimental. 

4. Finally we may point out, in addition to the foregoing, 
a character of thought which has not as yet been adverted to ; 
one that fixes genetically both the social motive and the experi- 
mental motive as now put in evidence. It is the linguistic 
character of thought. Thought is a system of predications 
or assertions that may be embodied in a more or less ex- 
plicit system of symbols for purposes of inter-personal com- 
munication. The genetic relation of speech and language to 
judgment will be found to give striking confirmation of the 
point of view developed in the consideration of logical meaning, 
to the effect that judgment is in all cases common or synnomic. 

§ 2. The Linguistic Determination of Thought. 

The old problem put in the question, * Is thought possible 
without speech,' has no real significance except so far as it is 
set genetically or from the point of view of the comparative 
origin and development of these two great functions. But from 
such a point of view it takes on great significance inasmuch as 
even a superficial examination suggests a profound correlation. 
The current theories which deal with the topic from the side of 
language make out, each from its own class of data, certain 
plausible positions ; these may be suggested as introductory to 
our own treatment of the problem. 

I. The Personal or Dynamic Theory. This theory is based 
on the interpretation of * expression.' It finds some sort of 
symbolic representation necessary as soon as the meaning to be 
expressed becomes general or abstract. The symbolism of ges- 
ture language, pictographic writing, etc., precedes that of vocal 
utterance and conventional phonetic written signs. It would 
seem, indeed, that if expression is to develop from a purely 
ejaculatory, demonstrative, or other mainly concrete stage to 
one of general or abstract meaning or import — that is, if it is to 
express something imported^ something additional to the bare 
concrete common content of present experience — there would 
have to be a vehicle of a sort intentionally symbolizing this as- 



1 84 /. MARK BALD WIN. 

pect of meani|ig. For example, a savage could not respond to 
express the meaning * man/ as suggested by but not limited 
to * this man/ except as a sign of this further intent attached 
to his response. Theoretically, of course, any sort of conven- 
tionalized indication — act, posture, sound — might have been 
selected for this function in the processes of development ; but 
we find the function in which it has been embodied to be speech. 
Speech issues in a system of articulate vocal symbols, together 
with that special development of the same symbolism embodied 
in writing. So much may be said on the personal side ; the 
side of personal expression as such. 

For the purposes of linguistic theory, this may be called 
the * personal ' or < dynamic ' point of view. It recognizes the 
fact that the person is the source of new accretions of social 
meaning, and the dynamic movement of such meaning is made 
possible only as the results of personal thought find adequate 
and appropriate expression. It considers language as a live 
things flexible in its growth with the development of thought, 
divergent and varying in its comparative systems of symbolism. 
It gives a comparative philology, and aims at the genetic solu- 
tion of linguistic problems in terms of psychological meanings. 
Evidently, therefore, this point of view is in its own province 
n^ost important. 

But the further question as to the conservation, the conven- 
tionalizing — in the large sense, the socializing — of meanings, 
whereby they show themselves more than personal, and in an 
important sense also less than personal, is equally urgent. This 
question may be put sharply thus : how can a system of sym- 
bols serving as expression of a dynamic movement of personal 
thought, also serve as the embodiment of established and con- 
ventionalized social meaning? 

This inquiry has direct enforcement from the side of the 
psychology of what is called * intercourse.' There is no purely 
* personal ' intercourse ; all intercourse is in its constitution in- 
ter-personal. Its intent is to be understood as well as to be ex- 
pressed. It becomes necessary to enlarge the theory of expres- 
sion to make its unit one of common meaning. The lowest 
functional term of expression is in some crude sense * inter- 



THOUGHT AND LANG UA GE, 1 85 

course' — the development of common meaning. Turning, 
therefore, to the theories of language reached from the social 
side, we find a second type. 

2. The Social or Static Theory. The theory of common 
symbolic meaning would seem not to find its problem in the 
first instance in personal expression. Its problem is not how 
personal meaning could become common in its expression, but 
how a conventionally common meaning could be the vehicle of • 
genuine personal experience. Would not any system of sym- 
bolic meanings become, just by the rigidity and static character 
that its social fixity would impart, unavailable for personal 
purposes ? 

Indeed, the function of language, we are told by the static 
theorists, does not extend to the expression of what is personal 
as such. It comes to reflect personal interest only by being 
first of all conventional and common. The demand of inter- 
course is for a symbolism to express meanings already under- 
stood and accepted. It is only by social generalization that a 
meaning can become eligible for linguistic embodiment at all. 
Witness the fact that feeling and impulse, so far as they are 
not thrown into descriptive form as knowledge, cannot be given 
common linguistic rendering. Music may be cited : what does 
music really express ? It is only so far as a meaning has taken 
on a form that gives it currency in society that it is made a 
matter of intelligible speech. 

Upon this type of theory a view is based which makes lan- 
guage a static, stereotyped system of forms. The classics, 
being no longer living and growing but dead, offer the models 
of literary form. Any current modes of speech and language 
that do not fit into these models, so far fall short of the instru- 
mental adequacy that facile social intercourse demands. 

While stating these two types of theory in this extreme con- 
trasted way, I do not mean that advocates of them in just this 
form are to be found ; but the antithesis presents a fair contrast 
of attitude and spirit. Especially does it appear in the method 
of research that the schools respectively adopt. The men who 
look upon language statically are critical rather than genetic in 
their method ; they study types rather than comparative forms. 



1 86 /. MARK BALD WIN, 

Given the perfect models in which the human thought move- 
ments have once embodied themselves — say in Greek — and 
philology becomes the criticism and application of these models. 
Essential variations in model, reflecting racial and temperamental 
character and essential differences in intent and spirit in the 
actual development of cultural meaning — resulting in a variety 
of comparative modes maturing in common — all this they find 
it difiicult to take interest in. The other school, on the con- 
trary, having in view just the final point of origin and departure 
of all social meaning, the thoughts of the individual, make the 
comparative variations all important. 

The line of solution would seem to lie in the distinction 
already made in the remarks on expression: the distinction 
between meaning on the one hand that is singular and in some 
sense private, and meaning on the other hand that is general 
and universal. Just as there is a sphere of personal experience 
that is ineligible to common and symbolic expression, so there 
is a sphere of common and public experience that is ineligible 
to strictly personal and private uses. In their range, in short, 
personal meanings and social meanings overlap but do not 
coincide. Consequently, there is the requirement all the way 
along that the symbols of conventional expression be so far as 
possible flexible in order to embody the accretions to personal 
experience ; and on the other hand, that they be fixed enough 
to embody the habitual and conventionalized meanings of his- 
torical and common experience. This requirement is embodied 
in the view, now fast gaining ground, that language is a grow- 
ing organic thing, relatively satisfactory for the epoch and the 
group; but by no means containing or requiring a system of 
fixed and stereotyped meanings. 

Moreover the development of the appreciative or aesthetic 
consciousness is, all the while, working out new systems of sym- 
bolism for the more recondite meanings of personal intent and 
ideal fulfilment. The arts are such semi-socialized and in turn 
socializing systems of symbolic meaning. Their r61e is seen, in 
connection with the more conventional symbolism of language, 
in the various forms of conscious literary art. These, just by 
being acceptable as artj become more adequate as embodiments 
of individual meaning. 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE, 187 

These two points of view may serve to guide our further 
thought. On the one hand, we must find the process whereby 
personal experience may be rendered in the symbolism of com- 
mon intercourse ; and on the other hand the process whereby 
the same symbolism, although of necessity fed by the progress 
of personal experience, may nevertheless preserve and embody 
the fruits of social and historical tradition. 

If we assume, as a matter of fact, that the requirements of 
such a system of symbolic meanings are normally met in their 
linguistic embodiment we have then to analyze further the situa- 
tion in which such meanings are in vital and effective use ; and 
the modes of intercourse that embody such developing mean- 
ings will also interest us from the point of view of the genetic 
progress of thought. 

§ 3. Thought as Linguistic Mode. 

We should expect to find, if our earlier positions are well 
taken, that thought, logical meaning of whatever grade, would 
take on a linguistic or other social form. Both of the great 
characters of logical meaning actually require it. 

One of them has already been seen to be effective in the 
sketch just given of the two great points of view current in the 
theory of language — 1, ^., that while speech expresses perso- 
nal meaning, it must still be socially organized. This hits upon 
just the relation of the personal or private to the common strain 
in all logical meaning.. The character of logical meaning as 
being at once personally judged true, and also acknowledged 
as appropriate for common acceptance — this is just the charac- 
ter we have found. It is denominated * synnomic' The tran- 
sition from pre-judgmental to judgmental meaning is just that 
from knowledge that has social confirmation to that which gets 
along without it. The meanings utilized for judgment are those 
already in their presuppositions and implications developed 
through the confirmations of social intercourse. Thus the per- 
sonal judgment, trained in the methods of social rendering, and 
disciplined by the interaction of its social world, projects its 
content into the world again. In other words, the platform 
for all individual movement of judgment to its assertion — the 



1 88 /. MARK BALD WIN. 

level from which it utilizes new experience — is already and 
always socialized; and it is just this moment that we find re- 
flected in the actual result as the sense of the ' appropriateness' 
or the • synnomic ' character of the meaning. 

This requirement, signalized as the common or synnomic 
character of the linguistic embodiment of thought, may be called 
the * habit' aspect — the funded, conserving, retrospective, 
general side of meaning in the logical mode. Evidently it is 
this that the static theorists of language have in mind. Lan- 
guage must embody meanings that are established and common. 
They are personally available only so far as the individual can 
use this kind of meaning, that is so far as his meaning is already 
synnomic. If our theory, however, discovers that all personal 
judgment already embodies suck meanings^ then we may simply 
say that this function, language, is the normal and appropriate 
embodiment of individual judgment no less than of social 
meaning. 

The other aspect, however, is equally real. It may in con- 
trast be called the * accommodation ' side — the side of growth, 
accretion, development of personal meaning through the re- 
sort to language as instrument and means. Of course, it is 
evident that both the general and the schematic, the retrospec- 
tive and the prospective, the belief and the doubt, the assertion 
and the assumption, must be capable of characteristic linguistic 
embodiment. 

It is upon this requirement that we find the dynamic theories 
of language dwelling in turn. They recognize the fact that 
thought would be killed, both personally and also as represent- 
ing any social values, if its vehicle were stereotyped and un- 
changing. The symbolism of language must reflect the mode 
of development and growth peculiar to the progress of thought. 

Now the development of thought, as we are to see in great 
detail,* is by a method of trial and error, of essential experimen- 
tation, through the use of meanings as worth more than they 
are as yet recognized to be worth. The individual must use his 
old thoughts, his established knowledges, his grounded judg- 
ments, for the embodiment of his new inventive constructions; 

* In later chapters of the volume * Experimental I^gic* 



THOUGHT AND LANG UA GE. 1 89 

he erects his thought as we say * schematically ' — in logical 
terms, problematically, conditionally, disjunctively — projecting 
into society an opinion still personal to himself, as if it were true. 
TTius all discovery proceeds. But this is, from the linguistic 
point of view, still to use the current language ; still to work by 
meanings already embodied in social and conventional usage. 
And the result, what of that ? 

The result is now the essential thing. By this experimenta- 
tion both thought and language are together advanced. The 
new meaning is, let us say, not confirmed in the way suggested ; 
the old terms do not fully define and limit the connotation that 
actual trial justifies. Language then grows to fulfil the demand 
of the developing thought. It is accomplished, it is plain, by 
no situation that compels language to be private or public and 
not both. As tentatively suggested the meaning is rendered as 
if common J in common speech ; the new form it takes on, while 
now become common as meaning, is still the individual's per- 
sonal thought as well. Language grows, therefore, just as 
thought does, by never losing its synnomtc or dual reference; 
its meaning is both personal and social from start to finish. 

As soon as we recognize these two essential motives in the 
development of thought, a profound interest attaches to the 
question of the relation of language to thought. There are 
certain statements whose truth now appears, and which bring 
direct confirmation from the side of language of our view of the 
origin and nature of synnomic or judgmental meanings. 

I. It would appear that language is the instrument of social 
habit, in the sense that it conserves and stores up as a social 
heritage the gains of common meaning. And this appears not 
simply as a fact, but by reason of the principle that only in 
language are the available elements of personal experience and 
meaning socially stored and rendered continuously available. 
It is the register of tradition, the record of racial conquest, the 
deposit of all the gains made by the genius of individuals. The 
social * copy-system,' thus established, reflects the judgmental 
processes of the race ; and in turn becomes the training school 
of the judgment of new generations. Not indeed would I say 
that linguistic models and linguistic study as such have any 



190 J. MARK BALDWIN. 

such pedagogical importance ; that is just the fallacy of our 
present-day instruction, that makes a fetish of language as 
such. But every day linguistic intercourse, language -perform- 
ing its vital rdUj is thus important. Linguistic study is instru- 
mental, a means to an end ; the end being admission to the 
storehouse of meanings and models of racial judgment, which 
literature in all its forms serves to mediate. When language is 
made an end — except of course in that department of research 
in which language is itself the content — it becomes a form that 
is eviscerated of its filling and meaning ; much as we eviscerate 
thought of its content and so lose its meaning also, when we 
leave out of account the essential movements of belief. 

2. In speech, the function by which the content of language 
is actively rendered and interpreted, the accommodation side of 
thinking is given its chance. Most of the training of the selfi 
whereby the vagaries of personal reaction to fact and image are 
reduced to the funded basis of sound judgment, comes through 
the use of speech. When the child speaks he lays before the 
world his suggestion of a general and common meaning; the 
reception it gets confirms or refutes him. In either case he is 
instructed. His next venture is now from a platform of knowl- 
edge on which the newer item is more nearly that which is con- 
vertible into the common coin of effective intercourse. The 
point to notice here is not so much the mechanism of the ex- 
change — the sort of conversion — by which this gain is made, 
as the training in judgment that the constant use of it affords. 
In each case, effective judgment is the common judgment ; and 
there grows up the ability to make such judgment effective 
without the actual appeal. This is secured by the development 
of a function whose rise is directly ad hoc — directly for the 
social experimentation by which growth in personal competence 
is advanced — the function of speech.^ 

^The first and more superficial criticism of the reader is here, as elsewhere 
in these genetic discussions, that which raises the question as to whether speech 
is the only function by which this is secured. We are asked whether a child 
who is deaf and dumb does not become a competent thinker. Certainly he does, 
in this measure or that, according to the case, which is only to say that therdle 
normally played by speech may on occasion be taken up in a less efiiective way 
by some other function having a content capable of the symbolic reading thit 
usually attaches to language. 



THOUGHT AND LANGUA GB. 191 

In language, therefore, to sum up the foregoing, we have 
the tangible — the actual and historical — instrument of the de- 
velopment and conservation of psychic meaning. It is the 
material evidence and proof of the concurrence of social and 
personal judgment. In it synnomic meaning, judged as ^ ap- 
propriate,' becomes * social ' meaning, held as socially general- 
ized and acknowledged. The dictionary is the register of 
private judgment become social. Written language, literature, 
is its institutional and traditional side ; speech is the schematic 
and personal rendering of its intent, its accommodative side.^ 

§ 4. The Development of Thought through 
Intercourse. 

The view of thought now briefly indicated justifies certain 
positions regarding the form in which the import of an item of 
knowledge may be expressed when embodied in such a vehicle 
as language. On the surface it appears that the entire import 
of such an item varies with the setting in which it is developing. 

^ There is here a confirmation of the position taken in my work Social and 
Ethical InterpretatianSt in which the method of social organization is found to 
be imitation ; for not only is language the embodiment of generalized cognitive 
content, it is also, as fnnctional in speech, through and through ixnitative in its 
method of learning and propagation. 

We now see how it is that language is instrumental to the development of 
both personal and social meanings. What linguistic theory needs, in fact, is 
better psychology : a psychology that shows the artificiality of the dualism of 
private and social meaning, that the opposed theories assume. If it were true 
that there were no concurrence —no identity — between the movement of indi- 
vidual thought and that of conventional language, then not only would a theory 
of language be impossible — language itself would be impossible as welL This 
is one of the topics, therefore, in which a view of judgment that justifies the 
essentially common character of its meaning renders service in a field of more 
remote interest. If the demonstration of the social genesis of the individual's 
judgment be sound, philology will have for the first time a solution of one of 
its great problems. 

Another fact known to psychologists and philologists alike has an interest- 
ing value in the light of our discussion : the fact of ' internal speech. ' Recent 
investigation shows that it is not a mere by-phenomenon — our having words 
* in our minds ' and ' on our lips ' when engaged in silent thought, reading, etc. 
(see my Mental Development^ chap. XIV.). It is rather the incipient stirring 
up of those social and symbolic equivalents of thought, that vocal rendering em- 
ploys. Since the normal development of thought and speech goes on together, 
the functional processes are not separable. The intended psychic meaning can 
come up only when its symbolic vehicle is incipiently stirred up with it. 



1 92 /. MARK BALD WIN. 

The interest at work may be of this or that sort according as 
this or that group of meanings ordinarily called a * topic ' is be- 
ing pursued. This in turn varies with all the dispositional or 
other tendencies or motives coming to consciousness in the indi- 
vidual. The content itself, so considered as a subject-matter 
of thought, has relations, discovered or not discovered, in a 
larger whole of meaning. For example, the item « horse * may 
have very different lines of import developed according as I am 
conversing with a horseman, a naturalist, a dealer, or a veter- 
inary surgeon. In each case only those ramifications of mean- 
ing that are relevant to the common interest of the parties to the 
situation are elucidated and further advanced. If we consider 
that phase of the situation that concerns the party for whom a 
set of relationships is already established as a whole of subject 
matter, then the form of linguistic expression he employs is 
motived by the interest of what we may call * elucidation.' 
You * elucidate ' to me the fuller import of what you understand. 
The motive to intercourse on his part is in this case not dis- 
covery, not the extension of his system of meanings, but the im- 
parting of it to another — literally its elucidation to one who 
has not yet, it may be, fully thought it out under the same set 
of relevant interests. 

On the other hand, supposing the interests to remain the 
same, the attitude embodied in the use of the term, sentence, 
or other linguistic unit, may be not elucidation but ^ discovery,' 
not teaching but learning. And, of course, on the surface this 
may seem to require no active resort to speech at all. But such 
a statement, as being in any sense a final account of the matter, 
would be very superficial. The process of development of a 
system of logical meanings is never one of passive reception or 
even of relative inactivity. The growth of logical meaning in 
the hearer is by a series of judgments. The process is one of 
individuation of more or less familiar meanings in a new con- 
struction or context, in which the self receives a new impulse 
to its assertion of inner control. The understanding of a state- 
ment, or a series of statements, in detailed discourse, may be 
seemingly complete for each step ; but the elucidation of the 
speaker may vary in effectiveness for the hearer all the way 



THOUGHT AND LANGUA GE. 1 93 

from a mere glamour of familiarity or formal correctness, 
through varied stages of piece-meal, fragmentary, and semi- 
detached judgmental wholes, to that complete response of the 
hearer's logical interest that unifies the entire set of relevant 
items. How the more superficial sorts of comprehension of a 
subject are possible might be made subject of further remark ; 
here it may suffice to say that when they are thus of the super- 
ficial sort, it is pseudo-thinking ; it gives meanings that remain 
in large part either in a mode not yet judgmental, or so habitual 
as to be under mere reality-feeling, or again they are mere 
material for schematic use in this way or that when judgment 
upon their further relevancies is actually achieved. 

If genuinely receptive, indeed, the attitude of the hearer is 
one of continuous thinking. His selective interests are not 
severely taxed, since the relevant information is directly supplied 
to him. But the meanings suggested to him are, in the first 
instance, merely proposed, assumptive, experimental. Each 
item added to the whole requires assimilation by some process 
complementary to that whereby, in the contrasted case, he tests 
in the social environment the meanings of his own suggestion. 
There must be a means, personal to the hearer, of testing the 
content of a thought proposed to him as valid, just as there 
must be a means, social in its nature, of testing the personal 
hypotheses put forth by the individual. Both of these processes 
are made effective through the medium of the common function, 
speech. The one sort of testing is the appeal to the socially 
established context of common meanings, as represented by 
authority ; the other is that whereby the socially ^ problematical 
or assumptive meaning is confirmed by appeal to individual 
judgment. The unit in which such items of meaning are cast 
for either of these modes of confirmation or for both is now to 
be inquired into ; it may be called the unit of linguistic expres^ 
sion. It is what is ordinarily called a Predication^ or a Predi- 
cative Meaning. 

^ ' Social ' in the sense of madg to a hearer by whom it is to be ratified. 
Of coune all social acceptance is constituted by an aggregate of snch individual 
ratifications. 



1 94 /. MARK BALD WIN, 

§ 5. Modes of Predication: Elucidation and Proposal. 

As soon as we take into account the entire situation in a case 
of intercourse of any kind, we find certain points of view from 
which the same meaning may be considered. There are always 
at least two persons to the situation, and if we distinguish these 
persons as • speaker * and * hearer,' we have the two personal 
elements marked off. Each of the persons is either already in 
possession of the judgmental meaning or he is not. If he is, 
then he is in r61e, if not in fact, ' speaker ' ; that is to say, the 
meaning is that which he might utter in place of the actual 
speaker ; and whatever term we apply to the function of ex- 
pressing this meaning, it may be put down as applying to his act 
of participation in the situation. On the other hand, there is 
the point of view of the one to whom the intelligence imparted 
by the meaning is in some sense not already his meaning, but 
an addition to it, or a modification of it. He is the ^ hearer' — 
no matter how many of him there may be I The shadings of 
meaning involved may be distributed under this two fold divi- 
sion — the speaker^ s meaning and the hearer^ s meaning. 

The next thing that occurs to us to note is that each of these 
persons, speaker and hearer, may have in his mind either a 
meaning which he believes or a meaning which he questions : 
either a * logical or a * schematic' meaning ; a < presupposition* 
or an < assumption' may underlie the relational subject-matter 
that constitutes the predication. And there must also be sup- 
posed a form of correlation between these two types of mean- 
ing, considered as being in a situation in which the speaker and 
hearer get the same subject-matter at the same time — as indeed 
they must lest intercourse lose its commonness and so be futile. 

This analysis when pursued exhaustively gives the following 
cases : 

1 . Belief in the subject-matter on the part of the speaker, 
and predication that serves to elucidate the subject-matter : this 
we may call predication as elucidation. If this is accompanied 
by belief before the predication, in the mind of any actual hearer, 
the meaning to him is also one of elucidation, for he might have 
been the speaker. 

2. Question in the mind of the speaker and predication that 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE. 1 95 

in some form proposes something ; this we may call -predication 
asfrofosal. If it be met by belief in the mind of the hearer — 
belief already formed — it is to the hearer not proposal but eluci- 
dation ; and he in turn may proceed to elucidate the proposal of 
the questioner. If, on the contrary, the hearer joins the speaker 
in erecting the subject-matter into a schema of problematical 
meaning, his meaning is then also one of proposal. 

There are therefore four possible cases: (i) Proposal — 
(with) Proposal^ (2) Proposal — Elucidation^ (3) Elucidation — 
Elucidation^ and (4) Elucidation — Proposal^ in each case the 
meaning in the mind of the speaker standing first. Suppose, 
for example, a teacher teaching his class. The pupil says * A 
continent is really an island, isn't it?' (proposal), and the 
teacher replies either 'yes' (elucidation) — case (2) — or *let 
us look in the dictionary and see ' (proposal) — case (i). After 
looking up the dictionary, both pupil and teacher may say, ^ it 
is an island, as we thought' (elucidation with elucidation) — 
case (3) — or the teacher may say, * I still question what you 
read ' (elucidation with proposal) — case (4). It must not be sup- 
posed that * elucidation — proposal ' and * proposal — elucida- 
tion ' give the same situation ; they do not. The former is the 
situation in which there is exposition with reference to which the 
hearer has not arrived at an assenting judgment ; the latter, on 
the other hand, is the case of a question met by an elucidating 
response. The latter is the more fruitful situation, genetically, 
since it results in actual development of meaning in the mind 
of the questioner, giving a third term of elucidation ; and if this 
be also stated, the progression becomes proposal — elucidation — 
elucidation. The other case, that of elucidation — proposal, is 
not of this fruitful issue, unless it be followed by a further eluci- 
dation by the first speaker, and then an elucidation also in the 
mind of the hearer ; but this latter pair of terms brings in one of 
the other situations mentioned above, that of elucidation — 
elucidation. 

Putting it in general terms, we may say first that a statement 
may be met by acceptance or by question, and second, that a 
statement of question may be met by a belief or by a joint ques- 
tion. The instrumental utility, and with it the genetic justifica- 



196 /. MARK BALDWIN. 

tion, of these four cases of predicative meaning should be 
examined. In each of them we find that all predication, and 
with it all use of logical meaning, is in same important sense 
experimental^ when once the social point of view essential to its 
full interpretation is taken up. 

§ 6. Predication as Experimental Meaning. 
It would appear on the surface that if logical meaning is to 
be common, and thus socially available for intercourse, its forms 
must be those by which on occasion the enlargement of the range 
of acceptance could be secured. The forms of predication 
would then be ipso facto instrumental to the production of fur- 
ther judgment and belief. But certain considerations force 
themselves upon us which forbid so easy an instrumental inter- 
pretation. We have seen that the growth of knowledge cannot 
be entirely personal and private ; the necessities of social life, 
which are also personal, forbid. But it is equally true that the 
securing of common acceptance, and the enlargement of the body 
of inter-personal acknowledgments, cannot go on alone, as being 
the entire fulfilment of the rdle of knowledge ; for the individ- 
ual's judgment is all the while the norm of what is established 
as knowledge, and without individual consent there is no social 
acceptance? The propagation of a thought in a social set can 
only be by the intrinsic adoption of the thought by the indi- 
viduals of the set one by one. Any other process would make 
not common knowledge but common hypothesis or proposal, 
with no relatively final solution or elucidation in knowledge. 
In such a case the final criterion to the individual thinker would 
not arise in his own processes of selective thought, but would 
be a calculus as to how many of the community already accepted 
it. Catholicity would take the place of what we call logical 
reasonableness or validity.^ 

> A sort of social pragmatism might be constmcted along this line by rein- 
terpreting — as we have — the individual's judgment of reasonableness back 
into the field of social acceptance — the 'hole from whence it was digged.' 
But this is just what current pragmatism is unable to do, since its entire develop- 
ment is on the basis of the reconstruction of experience in the individual^ for 
* control ' by personal action. The question I put to this latter theory is how, if 
the dualism of inner and outer be one whose value is its instrumental utility 
for the control of action — how can self and other individuals — how can 
society — have any common meaning? A resort to a social discipline of in- 
dividual judgment would seem to be shut out from the start. 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE. 197 

There is in short the attitude toward society expressed in the 
sentence, ^ I believe^ therefore have I spoken' — the attitude 
of conviction, ccelum ruat — as well as the attitude, * I would 
believe, help thou mine unbelief — the attitude of social 
acquiescence. And we should expect that besides the evidently 
instrumental character of the appeal to society, there would be 
a corresponding instrumental appeal of society to the rules of 
individual thought. Put in terms of predication this would read 
— social proposals require individual elucidation, and individual 
proposals require social elucidation. The very development of 
knowledge, if it is to issue in a system of what we may call 
* truths,' requires that both these forms of confirmation be present 
all the while. 

Apart, however, from further theoretical discussion, we may 
point out the fact that as expressive of attitudes toward mental 
objects, meanings reach the poise and equilibrium of knowledge 
only through a two-fold elucidation. That of the speaker is 
still to invoke thai vf the hearer; that of the hearer is again 
submitted to the judgment of a second hearer when the former 
becomes speaker. The judgment of the individual is forever 
fed by the return wave from the circulation through the social 
tissue. On the other hand, the social set are never all convinced, 
and the outriders of society must be subdued to the informing 
and reasonable elucidation of the dominating individuals. 

The process of formation of what we call * truth ' is, there- 
fore, a continuous and dialectic one. Apart from the definition 
of the term truth, and the justification of its use for a body of 
subject-matter constituted as logical content, we may say that 
there are several sorts of truth. A predication which a thinker 
elucidates is true so far as it is -not ineligible to the hearer's 
elucidation and belief ; but it may still actually be mere hypo- 
thesis or proposal to the hearer to whom the elucidation is 
addressed. Again, a matter of social convention, of confident 
social elucidation and advertisement by acclamation, is true in 
so far as it is not ineligible, not mere proposal, to any indi- 
vidual thinker, for the same item is perpetually subject to the 
sharp-shooting of the more expert intellectual marksmen to 
whom the social judgment looks for its reconstruction and 



19S J. MARK BALDWIN, 

direction. There are two sides to the dialectic, two poles around 
which the web of truth must be stretched ; and until both sides 
be compassed and both poles surrounded, truth is unfinished. 

From the instrumental point of view we discover, therefore, 
two sorts of schematism or proposal ; and it is a result to which 
our discussions now directly converge that both are never finally 
banished — that thought — ^and with it truth — remains in one 
sense or the other experimental to the last. 

Proceeding now to isolate the typical cases of proposal in- 
volved in situations of intercourse we find them to be two. 
First, there is the attitude or intent of question in the speaker ^ 
of proposal or assumption of something he hifnselfdoes not yet 
believe or presuppose : this is the attitude in which the individual 
explicitly appeals to social conversion in order that his sche- 
matic context may be confirmed for his own acceptance and judg- 
ment. Second, there is the attitude of question in the hearer, 
the audience, the public, in presence of the elucidations of the 
speaker : this is the attitude in which the social set, the general 
intelligence, waits upon the judgment and predication of the 
individual that the final availability of its meanings may be 
assured. In the former case, there is the question, will it work 
in the whole of society ? — will it bear the social test ? In the lat- 
ter case, there is the question, will it work in the individual's 
system of established beliefs ? — will it bear the test of competent 
private judgment? — is it reasonable? 

These are the two tests always present in the determination 
of new matter in the system of meanings in the logical mode — 
the two tests of truth. They are the test of commonness and the 
test of reasonableness^ both being aspects of the intrinsic intent 
of all logical predication. They are the poles of reference of 
logical meaning in its growth, as first * syndoxic ' or * held^ in 
common,' then synnomic or * judged as common,' and finally 
'catholic' or * judged in common.' The 'reasonableness' of 
the synnomic is just the * appropriateness ' attaching to a nnean- 
ing whose social intent faces both backward and forwards 

A further word on the relation of these two tests to each 
other. 

»That is, ''assumed" or "presumed" in common in a mode sb^^rt of 
judgment. 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE. 1 99 

First, it should be borne in mind that we are here not con- 
cerned, except in certain secondary ways, with the commonness 
of mere catholicity as numerical measure of acceptance; but 
with that more profound ingredient in knowledge whereby, in 
its very formation, the individual judgment intends a common 
meaning. The judgment of the individual once formed is nec- 
essarily a common judgment to him.: it is synnomic in the 
sense of our earlier discussion. But the experimental process 
— the growth of this faculty of judgment in just this synnomic 
direction, both racially and in each individual — requires a 
series of situations in which the proposed or schematic mean- 
ings of the individual have first the syndoxic character <<in 
common,'' and so pass into judgments. The simplest case, of 
course, is one of fact in which the individual is not already 
possessed of the requisite information, and awaits the elucida- 
tion — the narrative — of another. He then, with this increase 
of syndoxic information, forms a judgment of his own that is 
synnomic. Thus arises a judgment of fact, the report of the 
other taking the place, by the operation of social conversion, of 
his own appeal to fact. Before such an appeal, or the recep- 
tion of the equivalent information, his opinion would have been 
schematic and assumptive. It is this case, in which the accre- 
tion to knowledge is a matter of fact, whether reached by direct 
or by social confirmation, that has given rise to the description 
of this test as the ' test of fact.' 

In the more recondite operations of thought, the essential 
appeal is the same. It is for that informing element of content 
or meaning, derived through the common context of socially 
established fact, that brings out the synthesis of judgment. 
The individual resorts to some source apart from his own ready- 
formed context of meanings used by him hypothetically, some 
word of fact in the larger sense, through which his assumption 
may be grounded and his belief justified. The essential redis- 
tribution of meanings that constitutes the process of assimi- 
lation of the proposed data to the body of experience, now takes 
place. In the result the item gets its assimilation, and the con- 
text of believed and grounded items is so far enlarged. 

The other test is different in its nature ; but being a real test. 



200 J. MARK BALDWIN, 

it is equally instrumental to the development of thought. It is 
that of items proposed for social acceptance but awaiting the 
judgment of the individual. It is the appeal to the < reasonable- 
ness' in which the competent thinker renders his synnomic 
meanings. 

We have said above that this resort to the formed judgment 
of the individual is necessary to social acceptance — the accept- 
ance of grounded social judgment. * Commonness ' in the 
simpler senses of that term — the meanings of * common ' short 
of the syndoxic ' — such commonness may exist without logical 
bearing of any kind. There may be mere social aggregate- 
ness. But the passage from what we may call social proposal — 
rumor, contagion, plastic imitation, etc. — however aggregate it 
may be, and however socially diffused, into the status of logically 
common meaning, is always through the mediation of the judg- 
ment of individuals. All * social meaning as such,' and all 
< public ' meaning resting upon it, are subject to the test of 
* reasonableness ' to the individual thinker. Social commonness, 
in short, rests upon individual acceptance or ^ reasonableness ' ; 
while individual acceptance as * reasonable,' has its roots in 
social commonness. The test whereby the social proposal, the 
aggregate or relatively catholic meaning, becomes one of genu- 
ine logical character, we therefore call the * test of reasonable- 
ness ' ' as contrasted with * the test of fact.' ' 

* See the descriptions of snch meanings in my Genetic Logic, Vol. I., chap. 
VII., \\ 5 flF. 

' I take the term ' reasonableness ' as covering the general mark of knowl- 
edge wherein it satisfies and fulfils theoretical or logical interest from C S. 
Peirce. As popularly used it has just the ambiguity of confusing the two phases 
of attitude we are trying so strenuously to separate, acceptance and assumption. 
We ordinarily say we believe a thing because it is ' reasonable ' and also that we 
assume a thing because it seems ' reasonable.' This means that it is by a transi- 
tion of attitude, rather than by a change of content, that knowledge and 
hypothesis are distinguished. A definite set of implications are reasonable, 
grounded, believed ; a set of assumptions not believed but only proposed, sre 
also reasonable so/ar as they go in leading up to belief. It is to the former 
intent, that of actual acceptance, that I shall apply the term. 

<It may be recalled that in the treatment of 'Selective Thinking* in 
another place (DeveL and Evolution^ chap. XVII.), I worked out certain tests 
from the individual point of view, calling them respectively ' test of fact' and 
'test of habit* The test of habit is what is here, fix>m the psychic point of 
view, recognized as schematic assumption. In order not to repeat what is said 



THOUGHT AND LANGUAGE, 20I 

The factors involved in this two-fold dialectical move- 
ment may be shown by the following diagram. It should be 
remembered that it is the progress, or determination, of mean- 
ing from proposal (assumption) to elucidation (belief), that is 
in question, and not the development of pure implication or 
elucidation as a body of related contents already fully deter- 
mined. 

Personal Proposal -^..,^^. ^^^^^^^ Social Proposal 

{Habit) ^^Xl"^ {Convention) 



Personal Judgment . ^"^^ -^^ Social Judgment 

{^Reasonableness) ' Fadl 



Truth 

The point of interest just here does not reside in the further 
explication of either of these tests ; it resides rather in the state- 
ment that no predicated or judged knowledge is ever free from 
that instrumental and problematic reference which one or other 
of these tests would further fulfil. Either that which is reason- 
able is still to be elucidated for some mode of acceptance, or that 
which is generally accepted is still to be proposed for individual 
confirmation as reasonable. 

The process of intercourse, therefore, to be all that it is for 
thought, requires that elucidation should perpetually fulfil the 
demand set by the correlative function of proposal. The social 
reference of thought is all the way along prospective as well as 
retrospective : prospective, in that it presupposes a proposing 
society for which further elucidation is necessary ; retrospective, 
in that it incorporates in its own competent judgment, just that 
strain of commonness which only an earlier prospective refer- 

Ailly there, I may simply call attention to the treatment in that place of (i) 
the ' platform ' or level of determination or systematic meaning from which all 
new items are selected as assumptions, and (2) the resulting theory of truth as 
that which having passed the ' gauntlet of habit ' or assumption then has to 
submit to the test of fact. Truth in the realm of empirical discovery, then, is 
what is in this twofold way selected. What is now added is the point that 
the hearer, society, does the same : brings back its ' assumption ' as mere social 
habit to the test of individual endorsement as ' reasonable.' 

^The socially established meaning may always be classed as ' fact ' since 
it has no further r61e save as established control or test of the individual's 
meanings. 



202 y. MARK BALD WIN, 

ence in its own case could have produced. Put differently, we 
may say that if, at any point, truth can be considered finished 
and absolute, not subject to further growth, but only capable of 
repeated elucidation, then at an earlier stage it might, for tke 
same reason^ have been so considered, and its present stage 
would not have been attained. And so on all the way down 
the line of racial progress. But, on the contrary, the elucida- 
tions of one generation only bring out the proposals of the next; 
the elucidations of society, the proposals of the man of genius. 
And in both cases the extraordinary thing is that in the pro- 
posal that requires a new platform of elucidation, the table is 
turned upon the thinker who makes his knowledge final. The 
judgmental content must be * set' as final, seeing that it is com- 
mon, synnomic, retrospective and in so far also legislative for 
all intelligences. But the newer gage of reasonableness, on 
the one hand, or of fact on the other hand, once thrown down 
with its claim to a new finality, the process of vital reorganiza- 
tion again goes forward. The older truth loses its presupposi- 
tions or finds them restated in a new set of postulations. 

It is not in order at this point to indicate the bearing of this 
result in a theory of knowledge considered as epistemology. 
We are later on to consider the question as to which if either of 
these points of view, these tests, these references to facts and to 
theoretic satisfactions, is the more fundamental. The whole 
matter is here one of genetic adjustment of motive factors in a 
whole function. If one care to select one aspect of the whole 
and say, * thought being experimental and instrumental and 
prospective, is pragmatic through and through ; ' very well, so 
it is, from this aspect of it — the aspect of accommodation, dis- 
covery, development. But if another select the other aspect and 
say • all thought is retrospective, a platform, an organization, a 
social and common meaning, having its relational forms and 
rules of predication, a matter of habit and theoretical worth' — 
what is to prevent his doing so? But both are partial, both 
abstractions. Knowledge is a specific organization within 
whose subject-matter characters appear, on the one hand, that 
fulfil the theoretical interest without which no elucidation, predi- 
cation, implication, language^ would be possible ; and again, 



THOUGHT AND LANGUA GE. 203 

knowledge is an adjustment, motived by a * pragmatelic/ end- 
embracing interest, without which no theoretical organization 
or meaning could ever have been developed. No good social 
psychology, and no epistemology based upon such a psychology, 
^11 be long content with either of these partial and fragmentary 
interpretations.^ 

The conclusions we have now reached are these : (i) that 
all elucidation, all predication that is really judgmental, all 
inner organization of thought in a system of implications, has 
been developed with constant reference to proposals to which it 
is the reply and elucidation, and (2) that all instrumental refer- 
ence of knowledge, all discovery, all postulation, all practical 
insight through truth, are possible only on a basis of established 
judgmental content whose adequate theoretical elucidation it 
presupposes. And the reason of both these statements may be 
put in a sentence — ^the reason is that knowledge is common pro- 
'perty not an individual fossession^ that individual judgment 
presupposes universal acceptance, and that truth is fitted always 
not only to satisfy somebody^ s theoretical interest^ but also to 
stir up somebody* s curiosity and practical impulse. * 

1 It may be said here, and haa been said to me by a thinker who calls him- 
self a ' pragmatist,' that we are still in the entire process dealing with a develop- 
ment for which the movement of cognition is instrumental: the development of 
psychic activity or function as such. To this I do not object, if we include 
objective meaning with function ; although when I come to think it through I 
find the result very far removed from what is usually called ' pragmatism. ' The 
whole development is, on the basis of our results, a social development, a larger 
social order, and with its postulation goes the contrast meaning, postulated 
equally in the logical mode, of a non-social and non-mental order, an environ- 
ment A dualism thus persists and will not down — a dualism whose implica- 
tions forbid a return to any sort of subjective interpretation of reality, as reached 
by thought, which confines it to what is relatively organized in the individual's 
habit The solution is to be found only in some sort of experience that is 
not indeed a-logicaly but super-logical and immediate in its mode. 

'This genetic process of building up a competent individual judgment, as- 
serting its individuality as over against the social body which is its very fons 
et origo, is seen to be a phase of the ' dialectic of personal and social growth ' 
developed in detail in my work Social and Ethical Interpretations, It is there 
shown that the consciousness of the personal self is formed and becomes rela- 
tively self -asserting, as over against society, by a process of imitative assimila- 
tion and ejective re-reading of social material, so that the individual is ' a social 
outcome, rather then a social unit.' ' 



304 /. MARK BALD WIN. 

Language embodies, if our general position be true, that 
stretch of cognitive meaning that is both individually accepted 
and socially rendered. It shows the concurrence of the two 
points of view from which the development of thought may 
be observed. Moreover so far as the individual's psychic life is 
looked upon as one of relative isolation from his fellows, as a 
center, that is, of personal and subjective meanings, the stream 
of his personal development merges concurrently into that of 
the social whole in those meanings which he can render by 
speech. His other meanings, the purely selective ones, the 
appreciations and the quasi-conative ones, the sorts of intent 
that fulfil his personal interests and purposes, together with the 
purely private ones of the fugitive sort that never acquire social 
validity — all these lie outside the sphere of intercourse and fail 
of linguistic embodiment.^ We can, indeed, imagine modes of 
social expression — we have them possibly in the crude quasi- 
linguistic symbolism, of some of the higher animals — in which 
this concurrent rendering of meanings personally in private 
judgment and also socially in common acceptance, has gone 
very little way. A society with only gesture language would 
be one with little such concurrent development ; and one with 
only pictographic signs would be relatively rude in respect to 
that aspect of development represented by written language. 

The principal and striking thing about language, how- 
ever, as thus being both personal and social vehicle of thought, 
is its testimony to the falsity of any individualistic theory oj 
thought. Thought must be social in order to be adequately 
personal, as we have seen : language summarizes and demon- 
strates this necessity. The gradual development of language 
shows the impulse and necessity for intercourse both as ped- 
agogical instrument in the hands of society and also as vehicle 
of the individuals informing and reforming work in society. 

1 It has been interestingly shown, however, by Prof. Urban that there is a 
sort of ' appreciative description ' whereby such meanings may be indirectly 
suggested by verbal description {Philosophical Review^ Nov,, 1905). It would 
appear quite possible to arouse in another an appreciative state like one's own by 
the use of indirect symbolism. We have tie general resort of taking advantage 
of what is called above (in my Vol. I.) the ' commonness of common function ' — 
of exciting a common function by ' analogous feeling stimuli/ to use Darwin's 
classic phrase. 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL AND THE POSSI- 
BILITY OF A PSYCHO-MECHANIC. 

BY THE LATE C. L. HERRICK.» 



One may accept, with all the assurance that ideas in this 
field are capable of exciting, the doctrine that energy is the 
real and that its ^ standing in relation/ or limitation, is the basis 
of substance, while one perceives no less clearly than the dual- 
istic philosopher the fundamental contrast between self and the 
outside world. 

It is no part of our purpose to minimize this contrast or to 
detract from the respect which we feel for the spiritual as con- 
trasted to the phenomenal world. Here our analysis must be 
patient and close and each step must be carefully scrutinized 
but with the constant recollection that everything cannot be said 
at once. 

Even at the risk of using terms that have been much abused 
at times we are now prepared to realize the difference between 
phenomena and epiphenomena. A certain form of energy, ex- 
pressed in alternating modes (a resultant of limitation or inter- 
ference) impinges on equilibrated energy in an animal organ- 
ism in such forms as to modify the latter. (We are well aware 
that torrents of energy are continually passing through our 
bodies and even our brains without awakening any response, 
and we also know something of the nature of the correspond- 
ences by which interaction is rendered possible and do not 
doubt that even these unperceived currents might, by appropri- 
ate transformations become suited for * food for thought') . The 
equilibrated organism is affected (in extreme cases the equilib- 
rium is destroyed) and the equation of the subsequent life of the 
equilibrium is permanently modified. 

But the first result is a state (act) of consciousness. From 
the nature of the equilibrium it follows that only one interfer- 

^ Unrerised MS. submitted, as the author left it, by C. J. Herrick. — Ed. 

205 



306 C, L HBRRICK. 

ence can occur at any given moment of time. An equilibrated 
system may be constantly varying but it is always one system. 

Note^ however^ that the unitary nature of an equilibrium 
does not prevent all sorts of fusions in the external stimuli be- 
fore they affect consciousness. Thus an instantaneous view of 
an object may produce a synthesis which can be remembered 
in terms of multiplicity. But the analysis by judgment of a 
composite of various impressions does not prove that the act of 
perception was multiple in any given moment of time. The 
perception of a chord in music is a single act, though we may 
subsequently analyze it into elementary sense stimuli. 

Experience is, therefore, composed of a series of impres- 
sions, a, £, c, etc., and these are projected as a phenomenal 
series, ^, ^, r, etc. But this is not all. Together with the 
subjective series there is something else which is not variable — 
which serves to make a series of the isolated facts of experi- 
ence — which binds the experience series into a whole. This 
might be a constant from the organism, thus : ajr, bx^ cx^ etc., 
80 that each time a, ^ or ^ is experienced it is accompanied by 
a feeling tone from the organism and from this we derive x (a, 
bj Cy etc.), X being a constant furnished by the organism in the 
act of experiencing. 

In the same way the phenomenal series is affected by a 
somewhat, thus : fy^ qy^ ry^ etc., giving rise to y (^, q^ r, etc.), 
where y is that constant which produces the sense of an external 
continuum or external world. 

More specifically, what is ;v? It may be suggested that the 
somatic sensations which, from their diffuseness, never enter 
consciousness in analyzed or differentiated form, constitute a 
background of consciousness which is at least relatively con- 
stant and serves as an x to be affixed to every a, ^, and c of 
experience. If this were true then it would follow, if one were 
cut off from all such organic sensations by being paralyzed, let 
us say, in all afferent paths of somatic nervous discharge, no x 
would be supplied and one would have no ' self ' concept or 
factor with which to affect the series of experiences, and it 
would remain a simple series of discrete sensations a-4h-c- 
There are facts of pathological experience which go to prove 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL. 207 

that some such truncation of self does follow from the shunting 
out of the somatic part of experience and we have every reason 
to know that the background of somatic or organic experience 
is a very useful means of synthesis for the remainder of ex- 
perience and also a very prominent element in the • self tone 
which goes to make up temperament and disposition. 

But our analysis would need to be more minute than this. 
It is supposable, nay probable, that the very existence of a neural 
equilibrium implies such activities as would keep up a tension of 
experience which, during a state of relative repose, might be 
undefined and unperceived, would be constantly varied by each 
break in the reposeful state, as when, for example, an external 
stimulus is received. Thus we may suppose, the material for 
self-consciousness would be preserved to some extent so long as 
the ability to receive stimuli at all remained. 

X then, is that constant of effort recognized (implicitly) at 
each presentation of an element of experience a, 3, r, and the 
recognition of this constant factor in the variable series is what 
gives rise to the notion (which is of the nature of a dim feeling 
at first as x itself is a feeling of tone) of a continuous self, cotem- 
poraneous with and existing between the series of experience. 
It seems to be a limitation of our consciousness that we do not 
experience unfilled intervals. In the experience of unlikes, a, 
by Cy etc., there is presented with these elements or between 
them, the recognition of change, thus : a (change), b (change), 
Cy etc., which cuts the series into units of experience. On the 
other hand the series of subjective increments Xy Xy Xy etc., has 
no such cleavage phenomena and fuses into one continuing x 
• . . etc. An absolutely unvaried experience, being incapable 
of analysis, has no succession and does not fall into the category 
of time. So we have the curious duplicity of experience of a 
broken series and a continuum or identity side by side with the 
former. This we express thus : x (a, by c) and the constant is 
the elementary self of consciousness, a something invariable in 
the midst of variety and permanent in the midst of fluctuating 
experience. To this constant the variables are referred. 

But we are not guilty in every day life of the refinements 
that have been discussed above. We do not ordinarily stop to 



2o8 c. Z. HERRICK, 

consider the objectivity of the body to the conscious mechanism 
at all. Not merely the organic (and as such unreferred) sen- 
sations, but the relatively constant sensations of bodily presence 
and effort are readily and constantly recognized as having a 
greater constancy than sensations for which we have analytic 
sense organs, such as the visual and tactual sensations. These 
bodily sense stimuli are reported continually, and, just in so far 
as they are constant, they are not specially perceived. They 
pass over as factors of the mental equilibrium and are only per- 
ceived at such times as some change occurs or attention is 
directed to them for some reason. These sensations form a 
vast penumbra about the x of self -consciousness so that we have 
(jr, x\ x'\ etc.) (a, A, c^ etc.) and are able to recognize some 
of the factors of the subjective {x) series objectively and x " 
may, for example, equal c on occasion, i. ^., the same sensory 
element may at one time form a part of the subjective con- 
stant and at another become an objective variable. At any rate 
the entire body furnishes us * self-material ' which can only be 
separated from the self-consciousness by a process of mental 
analysis, while in actual experience it is a real element in itself. 

It has been suggested by M. Rabier* that ** it were to little 
purpose if, the brain having been indefinitely enlarged, we could 
move about in it as in a mill ; or having become transparent like 
glass, our sight might traverse it from part to part. We 
would see there no more psychological phenomena than we see 
in a mill or in a sphere of crystal," and this is true for the simple 
reason that it is the ^ sight traversing it from part to part ' and 
the * moving about ' and the * seeing ' that would be, by defini- 
tion, psychological. If we could imagine the mill as a whole 
having a center of gravity in which all of its complex strains 
were referred and which persisted, ever changing but never de- 
stroyed, or could think of the crystal as having an optical 
center in which its various optical axes and bisectrices focused, 
and could imagine these centers of equilibrated forces being 
self-conscious, then the illustration might have some relevancy. 

When the spiritualist insists that the psychological is some- 
thing sut generis and distinct from the physical, we agree, if ' 

* Legons tU Philosophies T. I., p. 29. 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 209 

only he will go far enough and recognize why this diversity 
exists and how complete and hopeless a separation it really is. 
But this he fails to do. He proceeds at once to set these two 
ways of looking at activity as two commensurable and coexist- 
ing realities in the world and gives to the psychical (which 
differs from the physical because it is subjective and, so far as 
our powers of discrimination go, only for this reason) a separate 
objective existence. This is one of the most singular, most 
persistent, and most hopeless of logical absurdities in current 
metaphysics. 

When I, as a psychologist, examine my neighbor, I actually 
do attempt to enter his brain very much as Rabier describes. 
I find focussing there various activities. I find there a pro- 
digious mechanism for bringing diverse stimuli together in one 
continuum in the cortex. So far from a device for projecting 
stimuli upon one point, as imagined by Descartes and most 
speculative philosophers, the stimuli suffer a sort of dispersion 
in their path toward the field of consciousness. I discover that 
this mechanism is in a terrific state of activity. Currents of 
blood and lymph supplying highly complicated currents of 
energy are passing through the mechanism continually and 
doubtless the energy actually operating in the brain, if convert- 
able into gross forms of work, would lift many tons literally 
miles high daily, for we deal here with what the physicist would 
call intra-molecular types of forces as well as molecular and 
molar forces. Now all this vast activity reveals itself to us in 
scarcely any commensurate return. Just as the spectator look- 
ing at the solar system would see little evidence of the energy 
expressed in the equilibrated system of planets, every molecule of 
which is brim-full of activity in balanced condition, so looking 
at the brain as a mechanism for mental work, we find it set on 
a hair trigger, and a breath on an eye-lash is adequate stimulus 
to liberate vast stores of readjusting energy. 

All the various discoveries which I may make, as a neu- 
rologist viewing my neighbor's brain, and all the observations I 
make as a psychologist upon the reactions to stimuli connected 
with that organism, supplemented by the study of the defici- 
encies and aberrations resulting from extirpation or accidental 



2IO C. L. HER RICK. 

removal of more or less of the mechanism, go simply to show 
that, beyond question, his physiological activities closely re- 
semble my own and I am driven to conclude that he has feelings 
like mine. This inference is substantiated as fully as any mere 
inference can be and is the foundation on which the adjustment 
of all social activities is made. 

A music director expends enormous sums to import from 
Europe a man who is able to cause thirty or forty other men to 
move horse-hair bows and metallic reeds and columns of air in 
certain prearranged fashions, and invites thousands of other 
people to pay large sums to attend the resulting commotion of 
air, because he feels sure that by such antics as these the spirit- 
ual ideas of the profoundest masters of human emotions may be 
reproduced in the souls of the thousands of listening individuals. 
And, making certain necessary allowances, and within narrow 
limits, he is correct. If there is anything that can be said to be 
known, it is this : when a cortical complex in the brain of one 
man is caused to react in a certain way, the consciousness of 
that individual will be affected in a way closely similar ^ to that 
in which a similiar cortical disturbance in another man will re- 
act. To say that the brain does not affect the mind is to talk 
nonsense, and no one really believes such a statement, or else it 
is to talk the most recondite metaphysics and the statement stands 
badly in need of interpretation. 

Yet we still admit, nay assert, that the psychical, as psychical 
is sui generis^ entirely other from and non-commensurable with 
any physical process. Let us take some crude illustrations : 

Here is a thing • . . yonder is the picture of it. 

Here is a man at work . . . yonder is the time book. 

Here is a rifle ball moving . • . yonder is its locus formula. 

Here is an act of perception . . . yonder is a representation 

formed by it. 
Let us attempt to apply the idea. A sensation is produced, then 
another and another. These leave behind them altered condi- 
tions of equilibrium. It is not so much that in two cells or com- 
plexes a vestige, in terms of structural alteration, has been left, 
but it is better expressed that among the streams of interblend- 
ing forces in this equilibrium, one stream or line of communi- 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL. 211 

cation has been reinforced. After a frequent repetition of this 
upsetting of the equilibrium there results a permanent distortion 
in the form, so that, in the long run, as a result of experience, 
education, etc., no single stimulus can gain admission to the 
sensorium without reawakening and bringing with it a perfect 
rain of associated activities, or perhaps better, the curve repre- 
senting the trajectory of the new intruder to consciousness is 
one made up of the contribution from without and the vastly 
greater contribution from within. 

Thus our field of knowledge of the external world gains in 
complexity and there is presented to consciousness with every 
color, sound, or feeling, a panorama already interpreted and 
elaborated in which the new presentation is placed with relations 
of all kinds to the complex. 

This fabric of the imagination is the external world. The 
new presentation may be a line in the spectrum with a certain 
position and color. The observer proceeds to imagine a new 
element in the sun with certain physical properties and, later on, 
it may be, he identifies the same element on the earth. The 
educated imagination has thus vindicated itself. 

Now which is the reality in my subjective furnishing? But 
stay, we are not yet ready for this question. It is conceivable 
that one might by suflSciently delicate processes of investigation 
detect the vestigial * structural ' or dynamic changes in the 
brain or in the force complex which it represents, resulting from 
experience, and thus make these objective to me in the case of 
my neighbor and by transferring the results to self, as one 
would be abundantly justified in doing, conceive of identical 
residual furnishing in his own mental home. But even so, this 
is something different from the experiencing of these changes 
or of thinking things in terms of the phenomenal world. 

Then the doing or the thinking is the thing, and the phan- 
tasmagoria called the external world is relative or unreal ? No^ 
not at all. To attempt to discriminate the thinking from the 
thought, the doing from what is done is folly. This hair ab- 
solutely refuses to be split. The reality consists in thinking a 
thing — of affirmation of attribute — of union of subject and 
object. 



212 C Z. HBRRICK, 

We as souls are indissolubly connected with the rest of the 
universe and there is no use attempting to sever what God 
has united. Finally, therefore, we perhaps see that the psychi- 
cal differs from the physical as the result of a logical analysis 
which is possible by reason of our limitation. So long as indi- 
viduality shuts us up to one point in consciousness, and so long 
as consciousness seems to require equilibrated energy as a con- 
dition of its unity, so long this distinction of subjective (psychi- 
cal) from objective (physical) will remain in force and will be 
to us the most vital of all distinctions. 

This is, you may say, a point of view simply. To this we 
answer, in one sense, yes ; but, from the standpoint of pure 
philosophy, it is the discrimination of attribute from essence. 
So far as I am concerned, this distinction is vital, but in my 
consideration of other men it has no significance at all. But 
surely other men have consciousness. Yes, and they doubtless 
discriminate subjective from objective (their essence from attri- 
bute), but men cannot be at the same time subjective and objec- 
tive, and that they are other men makes them objective to me. 

What then of the souls of other men? We escape from 
psychology when we ask this question for, by the prevailing 
definition, other men can have no souls. It is a curious ab- 
surdity growing out of the restrictive attitude of modern sciences 
whose hedges have grown so high that the workers can see only 
their own little plot of ground, forgetting that the same free air 
of heaven blows over all — it is a curious absurdity we say, 
growing out of the restriction of psyche to consciousness that 
there can be a psychology only of my individual experience and 
such a thing as a general science of psychology is impossible. 
The result is that what is now called psychology is a composite 
of neural physiology and non-related tags and scraps from indi- 
vidual consciousness. 

Relying on the belief in the underlying unity of energy, we 
may attempt to explore a region where, apparently, angels have 
feared to tread and offer suggestions toward a fsycho-mechanic. 

II. 

Our work so far has accomplished one result (let us hope) 
which should lighten the task of construing the conscious life 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL. ^13 

in connection with what is termed ordinary physical manifesta- 
tions ; it has, namely, shown that the physical and the psychi- 
cal inhere in one reality, an activity. If the energist be correct 
in viewing the phenomena of the physical universe as manifes- 
tations of various phases of one universal, indestructible but 
convertible energy, and if psychology be correct in asserting 
that all mental states are acts, and, furthermore, if we are not 
so blinded by prejudice as to shut our eyes to the overwhelming 
evidence of the interaction of these two sorts of activities (a fact 
more certain than any other whatever) then we are driven to con- 
clude that body and mind are phases of one reality — that con- 
sciousness is not unrelated to gravitation, but is a part of the 
same universe of activity. 

This as an abstract statement would give rise to few diffi- 
culties, but when it comes to the fact of our personal conscious- 
ness, this event seems unlike any other which we picture to our- 
selves as taking place in the world at large. It comes home to 
me as something intimate and self-acting — as myself, an ac- 
tivity sui generis. This contrasted condition of out-there-ness, 
which we feel in connection with an objectivized experience, as 
against the I-here-ness of subjectivity, is a necessary result of 
individuality. 

But we believe that every other individual has this same 
kind of consciousness and yet his * I-here-ness ' becomes * out- 
there-ness ' to me. This distinction is, therefore, in this sense, 
a point of view, not a difference in form of activity. 

Here arises a difficulty. A view-point presupposes a view- 
ing subject. How are we to form any concept of such a sub- 
ject? Is it not simplest to follow illustrious example and say 
frankly that this subject is a soul, of which we know nothing 
except that we are it f But, inasmuch as it is possible or neces- 
sary for us to abstract from // any quality of which we can form 
an objective concept, the soul represents simply the residuum 
after such objectivization, an empty capacity for being — some- 
thing back of all that we ever did or experienced, our own suf- 
ficient reason. 

To this result we are not, as dynamic monists, exactly 
driven, though we agree with the conventional conclusion that 



214 C. L. HBRRICK. 

I am a soul. We differ in being unwilling to discard all the 
realities of existence in defining the soul. If we were obliged 
to use the postulate of matter our quest would end here for it 
has appeared evident to all philosophic minds from the earliest 
times that the soul cannot be material. 

For our present point of view this difficulty is removed and 
only one prepossession or preliminary concept is necessary, viz., 
that the mechanism of consciousness is dynamic. Only on this 
presumption can psychical phenomena be linked to the world 
of experience. Another attribute of the soul is at once recog- 
nized — it is an indivisible continuum and is simple. We need 
not take into account subconscious * psychical ' activities. Non- 
psychical psychical activities may have a meaning to a certain 
kind of mind, but it is difficult to see what inducement could be 
offered such a mind to study psychology. 

Consciousness is unitary yet it is wonderfully complex. It 
is conceivable that the whole magnificent panorama of nature 
might be reflected upon it if our sensory apparatus were com- 
plete enough and yet the resultant at any given time would be 
a unit of consciousness. This is not a fact of introspection 
merely. Its philosophical necessity is bound up in the concept 
of individuality. 

One may picture to himself a mechanism of cortical cells at 
the end of a series of * projection systems ' as complex as pos- 
sible, and imagine every cortical cell in ceaseless activity. 
These subconscious phenomena might be as complex as 
possible but consciousness is always one. On the material 
hypothesis the one-ness of consciousness led anatomists and 
physiologists to postulate some center — some pineal gland — 
where all the various activities should impinge on some one ele- 
ment. As a matter of fact, this concept serves but to increase 
the difficulties. What is the use of all the complicated mechan- 
ism if all the changes have to be transmitted to one cell or cell- 
group? Either that cell group is marvelously complex and 
mirrors the complexities of the brain at large, or else there is 
some unity, not material, which can receive all these various 
influences and convert them into a unitary state of conscious- 
ness. Why one organ should be necessary in order to bring 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 21 S 

the complexity to bear on the simple nature of the immaterial 
soul, no one can say. 

On the dynamic view, however, we readily see that one 
condition alone corresponds to the requirements of the given 
phenomena and that is a condition of equilibrium. Diverse proc- 
esses experience a unification only if brought into equilibrium.* 
Such a condition we have postulated. 

Before attempting to apply this idea let us examine other 
dynamic elements in the hope of securing illustrations in a less 
complex sphere. In a uniform medium, as has abundantly 
been shown, the only condition of individuality is that of vector 
activity. Vortex rings serve as illustrations. The discussion 
of vortex atoms has brought out this peculiarity. Two forms of 
activity appeal to our senses, first, progressive or translational 
or molar, second, self-centered or vector activities. In the first 
case the point is conceived as moving in a right line or some 
other progressive manner so that the motion is indeterminate, in 
the second case the motion is cyclical and the center of refer- 
ence is stable. In ordinary parlance, when a body falls, the 
motion is of the first sort but when brought to rest the motion is 
transformed into the second state. The body is in a state of 
rest and with reference to adjacent bodies is in equilibrium. 

Vector motions have a remarkable stabilizing power, as 
witness, for example, the gyroscope. The two classes of 
motion have been called molar and molecular respectively but 
this perhaps involves too large a hypothetical step. The crude 
illustrations used may serve to show at least that the same force 
may have a conservative power in one phase and a dispersive 
power in another. But let one take the still simpler illustration 
of a solenoid. A current of electricity passing through a 
straight wire produces, it is true, an induction effect on the 
neighboring metals but when the same current is forced to pass 
through a spiral path the complex acquires an individuality — 
it is polarized as a whole and acts as a magnet. Similar 
solenoids react against it and a system could be formed from 
innumerable solenoids in equilibrium which would vary with 
the currents sent through the several elements, while the entire 

* Baldwin's Dictionary of Philosophy ^ art. 'Brain,' Functions, I., p. 135. 



2l6 C. L. HBRRICK. 

system would be in equilibrium at all times. While it is not 
suggested that the brain cells are solenoids or anything of so 
crude a nature as that, yet it is believed that the afferent cur- 
rents passing into the cortex produce in more or fewer of the 
brain cells a system of intrinsic activities which react, each 
with each, in the total cortical equilibrium which for each in- 
stant is the dynamic aspect of a state of consciousness — an act 
of mind. The whole involved activity, now more, now less, at 
any given moment, is equilibrated and forms a self-centered 
process of unitary nature. The structural mechanism of the 
brain is an uninterrupted flux of activity of a vital character. 
Vital activities are all analogous, rotational or vector, we might 
say (for illustration solely), as contrasted to translational or 
indeterminate or progressive activities. To be more general, 
what we call structure is evidence of statically condensed energy 
(energy in vector states) and this is competent to enter into re- 
action with afferent impulses and convert them into vector 
activities. The sum of the equilibrated activities in the body 
forms its vital continuum. One phase of the equilibrated con- 
tinuum is the activity of consciousness. So far as we know, 
the conscious continuum is associated with the total vital com- 
plex. It is not proven that any other form of equilibrated vector 
forces is capable of assimilating the afferent stimuli and con- 
verting them into similar terms and so converting them into a 
conscious activity, though it may be said that we know of 
nothing to the contrary. 

To return to our problem, what then is the highest realit}' 
in my being ? To me it is doubtless the * stream of conscious- 
ness * which constitutes myself as known to myself. But even 
here common experience, as well as our most searching analysis, 
shows that only a small part of this stream is resolvable into 
elements of consciousness which are capable of being recog- 
nized as such in present experience. 

The great mass of dream experience, for example, fails to 
affect a nexus with the memory complex at all, and what we 
forget of each day's experience is vastly more than what we 
remember. But all is not lost that has disappeared. The 
wood has disappeared in the grate, but the genial warmth per- 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 217 

vades the room, invades our blood, quickens our pulse, awakens 
vital action, and finally is wrought into the history of our lives. 
So each element of experience is wrought into the sum of our 
life. 

The precise nature of my conscious reaction upon today's 
experience depends not on what I can formally recollect of past 
experience, but on the form of equilibrated unity which is the 
result of past experience in its progressive reaction upon my 
nature. 

If we follow the prevailing custom and accept current defi- 
nitions, the soul is identical with the stream of consciousness, 
I. ^., is the sum of conscious activities. We shall not quarrel 
with this definition. Psychology is the science of conscious- 
ness. The psyche is the object of this science — it is thought 
or consciousness. Very- well ; gastrology is, let us say, the sci- 
ence of stomachs and the object of this science is the organ or 
act of digestion. The suggestion is obvious. Because we, in 
our thinking, can analyze human activities into various depart- 
ments- and think of them separately it does not follow that the 
realities back of these departments are separate or independent. 

Because thinking is a very important part of human activity 
and can be made the subject of special inquiry it does not fol- 
low that there is a thinking agent which does nothing but think. 
Do we come perilously near the idea of a brain that secretes 
thought as a liver secretes bile? I think not, but our peril is 
lest we should allow perjudice to steer us away from the nar- 
row course marked out on the chart of truth. 

The sanest thinkers have always included in the idea of a 
soul a great deal more than thought or even a thinking thing. 
Our strict modern scientific analysis sees the necessity for draw- 
ing the boundaries between the adjacent territories of thought 
very closely, but very frequently forgets that in nature there are 
no such boundaries. 

The soul is a metaphysical concept the moment it becomes 
more than the totality of the stream of consciousness. Lotze 
said : * Sensations, feelings, and acts of will constitute the group 
of familiar facts which we are accustomed to designate, though 
with a reservation in view of future discoveries, as the life of 



2l8 C. L. HERRICK. 

the soul* Here was a careful and very conservative statement 
from one who was as fully aware as any recent psychologist of the 
intricacy of the interrelations between psychology and meta- 
physics. But the definition is a metaphysical one. * A pecu- 
liar being, the soul^ the life of which consisted in the manifes- 
tations which are the facts of psychology — such was the con- 
ception. But does this peculiar being do nothing else? True, 
whatever else it may do may not be subject matter for psychol- 
ogy, but we are walking with seven-leagued boots and care noth- 
ing for fences. 

If our work so far has been valid, we cannot fail to feel that 
forcible isolation of parts which belong together is not logical 
bad faith alone but subversive to reality. * Standing in relation ' 
is an essental thing in reality. But we cannot hope to form a 
science out of materials which are isolated from all others by 
their nature. If the direct and disconnected testimony of our 
subjectivity is to be the basis of our psychology we must at once 
give up the undertaking. In other words the content of sense 
must be objectivized before a science is possible. This content, 
after being construed in apperceptive relations, is our material. 
The acts of thought, as such^ are not available material for sci- 
ence, but only what we think of them, the predicaments of our 
thinking, or the affirmation of attribute applied to these elements. 

This seems a curious and contradictory result. After labo- 
riously reaching the apparent conclusion that the act of thinking 
is the psychological verity, to deny that these acts can be used, 
as such, in our science. But it is, when we rightly consider the 
matter, only what we might have expected, for all science is 
objective and is organized knowledge. We must be content to 
view all psychological processes from the outside. The moment 
we attempt to compare two processes or acts of consciousness, 
they become objective. In this sense the subjective is always 
epiphenomenal to science, which must rest content with her 
equilibriums and her algebraic expressions therefor. If any 
dynamic view be accepted and admitting the best known fact of 
all, I. ^., the effect of mind on body and body on mind, we 
recognize that the unity of soul and body is an organic one. 
This is LIFE. Lotze spoke of the life of the soul. Plain, every 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 219 

day common sense recognizes life as including every phase of 
activity from core to periphery in human activity and we should 
beware of laches of common sense. 

* Life ' shares with * soul ' the role of mystery in science. 
We saw that in the construction of equilibrium rendered neces- 
sary by the unity of consciousness it was necessary to make the 
psychical equilibrium part and parcel of a more general vital 
equilibrium. A center of vector energy in a world of energy 
cannot fail to wrap itself up in parts of the extraneous energy, 
for this is of the very nature of resistance, just as a revolving 
wheel attaches to itself more or less of the mud through which 
it passes, causing currents therein and counter revolutions 
whereby balls of revolving mud fly in all directions as parts of 
a system of which the hub is the center. One moves a lever 
upon a friction clutch and tooth engages wheel and band moves 
upon pulley, till the whir of a thousand wheels follows. Could 
we think of the friction pulley as gradually creating the ma- 
chinery of the mill out of existing energy in resisting phases, as 
the wheel created the mud cycles, we would have a rough im- 
age of the vital organism. 

But do you mean that my foot is part of m3' soul? Yes, I 
mean that the vital activities in my foot form part of my vital 
equilibrium and, in so far as these contain conscious partici- 
pants in the stream of consciousness, they form part of the soul. 
But if I amputate a foot do I mutilate a soul ? Certainly, though 
it may be better to enter into life maimed than to retain a foot 
and go elsewhere. By cutting off a finger a child's soul may 
be maimed of musical faculty. There are organs, the amputa- 
tion of which affects the entire character for life, and one does 
not willingly dispense with the frontal lobes even if he does not 
know precisely what purpose they serve. 

On the other hand, it is possible to add to the sphere of the 
vital activities, as when I place spectacles upon my nose or 
apply my hand to the throttle of a locomotive. Where then is 
the limit of self? It is not for me to draw it. I will not cut the 
narrow isthmus of flesh whicl\ connects me with my twin — the 
universe. The ancients believed that the eye shot out rays to 
grasp the objects of the visual world. What tentacula has not 



320 C. L, HBRRICK, 

modern science produced extending from all our organs to the 
phenomenal world? 

But if we may not define the outer limits of the individual 
life, do we not destroy individuality? Only seemingly, for we 
need not despair of locating its center because the periphery of 
its sphere of activity is indeterminate. The leaven of life may 
be small, but, given time and appropriate conditions, it will 
leaven the whole lump. 

Our analogy of the vector motions carried out would lead to 
the conclusion that wherever such a center originated it would 
tend to assimilate to itself all such activities as are capable of 
offering resistance to it and would, by virtue of the form or 
mode of its activity, cause allied activities to accumulate in har- 
monious adjustment about it, enlarging, and, at the same time, 
intensifying the energy in the original equilibrium. 

Disturbances of this equilibrium there will be, but it will be 
one of the hardest things to exterminate we can imagine, for it 
is intrenched in one of the most recondite energic conditions of 
the universe. Seed may be dried for years in the tombs but it 
will still germinate. No persecution ever succeeded in stamp- 
ing out a vital truth. It is not to be wondered that humanity 
has enduring faith in a life eternal, but this is not the life of the 
soul, if by the soul we mean the * stream of consciousness.' In 
so far as our life, as a whole, fits into the complicated sphere 
of the universal life it will be imperishable. Maimed and 
crippled, it may be, we crawl over the threshold of one worid 
into the fresh glory of another, but if the life be really there, it 
will have no diflSculty in assimilating to itself a body fit for its 
use, as the acorn finds its own body in the crevices of the rock 
and builds it forth in strict accordance with the pattern set in 
the peculiarities of its own vital equilibrium. 

We need not look for pangens, biophores, gemmules, micel- 
lae and the like in our study of heredity, or if we find them, we 
shall regard them as visible manifestations in some temporary 
form of types of equilibrated energy, vortices of specialized 
activity, specific in its form. The newt will grow a new leg. 
It is possible that the leg might grow a new newt if we were 
able to keep the conditions favorable, just as a branch may 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL. 221 

grow a new tree. There is nothing so violently incongruous 
as might appear in the childish planting of nail parings in the 
hope of raising a crop of men. 

Our point is that the type of equilibrium is impressed on the 
part as the energy of the part is reflected upon the whole. Ger- 
minative elements, or seeds, are special adaptations to this end 
but every vital part may share to some extent in this property.^ 

III. 

Historical Notes. — It is not worth while to attempt a resume 
of the history of opinion as to the nature of the soul and it wijl 
serve our purpose to review very briefly the more recent utter- 
ances in this matter. Among these recent utterances are those 
which from anthropological data undertake to voice the earliest 
ideas of dualism between soul and body, ascribing this concep- 
tion first to the phenomena of dreams and memory (Spencer) 
and, second, to the sense of voluntary originative or initiative 
power within ourselves (Schurman, etc.). 

The polyanimism of primitive peoples was not so very dif- 

* On the day following the writing of this paragraph the following memo- 
randum, published by Professor W. E. Ritter in the American Naturalist under 
date of November, 1903, reached the writer : "At the May meeting, this year, 
of the Philadelphia Academy of Science Miss Sarah P. Monks read a note on 
' The Regeneration of the Body of a Starfish ' . . . I quote from this report ; ' In 
studying regeneration on Fhatria {Linckia) fasctalis she had cut arms at differ- 
ent distances from the disc, and a number of the single riLys produced new 
bodies. The free ray produced a new body and the rest of the starfish produced 
a new ray ..." Miss Monks is to be congratulated on having at last produced 
the experimental evidence demanded by the skepticism of recent writers on the 
soundness of Haeckel's conclusion reached long ago that ' jeder abgeloster Arm 
reproducirt die ganzen Scheibe nebst den iibrige Armen,' Zeitschr. tuiss. Zool,, 
Bd. 30. 

In a paper on * Physiological Corollaries of the Equilibrium Theory of Ner- 
vous Action and Control ' published in the Journal of Comparative Neurology^ 
Vol. Vin., No. I, 1898, many of the ideas expressed in this paper were hinted 
At, e, g.t pp* 26-27 ' " From the above it may be gathered that the ground of 
mutual reaction (between protoplasmic and nervous forces) may be sought in 
the fundamental similarity of the two processes, or rather in the close relation 
between the processes of waste and repair lying at the foundation of both. It 
is necessary to suppose, accordingly, that the central nervous system is contin- 
uously affected by the vital phenomena at large as truly as that the vascular 
system is under the control of the nervous system.*' Other passages of like 
tenor will indicate the bearing of the present theory for the neurologist. 



222 C. Z. HBRRICK. 

ferent, in result, from the highly philosophical concept of a soul 
in all things ; in the inanimate world as a principle or ground of 
phenomena, in form or attribute ; while, in the animate objects 
it became the principle of life, of sensibility, and of motion. 

It is perhaps correct to say that we have never risen higher 
than some early expressions of this idea and have often sunk 
immeasurably below it. With the early church fathers, Turtul- 
lian, St. Iraeneus, and St. Justin, the soul was a thinner kind of 
body. Plato and St. Augustine, to be sure, recognized the soul 
as immaterial, but were led to a dualism which set up a conflict 
between body and soul as unfortunate as it was immoral. 

To Descartes we owe the limitation of the soul to immaterial, 
invisible thought, reducing its content to thought alone and 
assigning its activity solely to the intellectual world of ideas. 
This distinction, once made, has taken firm hold on psychology 
to this day, although the phenomena of sensibility have been 
restored to the soul. 

There has been a tendency of late to renew the concept that 
the soul includes the functions of animal life and even the phy- 
siological functions of the human body. This is animism as 
opposed to vitalism and the view presented here must not be 
confused with an animism which does not recognize the dis- 
tinction between consciousness and all other phenomena, nor 
yet with a vitalism which manufactures a vital principle distinct 
from but somehow coordinated with the soul. Dynamic monism 
recognizes both manifestations in a synthesis of equilibrated 
energy which is capable of expressing itself in vital attractions 
and repulsions as well as in apperceptive coordinations. 

A conservative position taken by perhaps a majority of 
recent writers of psychologies is well expressed by Compayrc, 
as follows: **The great number of contradictory conceptions 
of the soul, considered by some as the principle of thought 
alone, by others as a principle that feels, thinks and wills, and 
by still others as the sole cause of life and thought, suffice to 
show how very necessary it is to postpone, if not entirely to 
waive, the obscure and controverted question of the nature of 
the soul." 

That the statement of the limitation of the sphere of psy- 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 223 

chology by recent writers to the stream of consciousness is not 
misleading may be gathered from such a passage as the follow- 
ing from Titchener's Outline of Psychology : '*The psycholo- 
gist can accept this definition (of psychology as the science of 
mind) ... if * mind ' is understood to mean simply the sum 
total of mental processes experienced by the individual in his 
lifetime." ** The question : Is there anything behind the men- 
tal process, any permanent mind? and, if there is, what is its 
nature? — is a question which is well worth while to answer 
but it is not a question that can be raised by psychology. Psy- 
chology sees in mind nothing more than the whole sum of 
mental processes experienced in a single lifetime." 

How artificial this distinction is cannot fail to be apparent. 
It is like erecting a science of shadows in which it is forbidden 
to refer any shadow to the object that cast it. Yet there is a 
science of shadows and this science, if correctly builded, will 
be found to correspond, part for part, variation for variation, 
with the objects casting the shadows. But there is a real fallacy 
here. It seems to be assumed, by Titchener, and probably by 
the rest of us when trying to talk this language, that since con- 
sciousness is something sui generis by reason of its subjectivity, 
we must not disturb that attribute nor admit into our psychology 
any other element. But this shadow refuses to be caught. 
As subjective, we can't create the facts of experience into a 
science. The data of science are necessarily objective. A 
science of pure consciousness is forever impossible. Somebody 
else's consciousness is not subjective and we cannot use our 
own data of consciousness in science till they are objectivized. 
More specifically, neither in the case of another or of myself, 
when I begin to follow the natural course of mental synthesis, 
do I revive the actual states of consciousness, nor do the ele- 
ments of the synthesis I conceive of actually exist in conscious- 
ness. My best efforts produce only an algebra of conscious- 
ness purely objective. 

The monist contends, says C. Lloyd Morgan, ** that, alike 
on its biological and in its physiological aspect, the organism is a 
product of evolution ; that mind is not extranatural nor supra- 
natural, but one of the aspects of natural existence." "What 



224 C. L, HER RICK. 

is practically given is the man ; and the man is one and incU- 
visible, though he may be polarized in analysis into a bodily 
aspect and a conscious aspect." *^ Body and mind are distin- 
guishable but not separable." 

Opposed to this view of monism are two extremes — mate- 
rialism on the one hand, according to which the body is the 
real substance and the mind one of its properties, and spiritual- 
ism, on the other, which states with Charles Kingsley that 
*your soul makes your body as a snail makes its shell.' 
Dynamic monism reconciles these extremes by showing that 
body and mind are expressions of one life. 

Compare the above with such statements as the following : 
*< What mind is in itself is a question that lies outside of psy- 
chology and belongs to philosophy. ... It may, however, be 
said that some idea of mind as a unity, which holds together 
and combines the several states of what we call psychical 
phenomena, is a necessary assumption or presumption in psy- 
chology." ** We must always think of mind as attended by, 
and in some inexplicable way, related to, the living organism, 
and more particularly, the nervous system and its actions." . . . 
"The perception of difference at all is something distinctly 
mental, not to be explained, therefore, by any reference to 
nervous changes. No sound psychology is possible which does 
not keep in view this fundamental disparity of the physical and 
psychical. . . ." {Sully.) 

Consciousness is ''the common and necessary form of all 
mental states ... it is the point of division between mind and 
not-mind." {Baldwin.) 

** For all psychological purposes this (the relation between 
mind and body) must be regarded as a relation of interaction. 
. . . Now when we come to the direct connection between a 
nervous process and a correlated conscious process, we find a 
complete solution of continuity. The two processes have no 
common factor. Their connection lies entirely outside our 
total knowledge of physical nature on one hand and of con- 
scious processes on the other. . . . No reason in the world can 
be assigned why the change produced in the gray pulpy sub- 
stance of the cortex by light of a certain wave-length should be 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL, 225 

accompanied by the sensation red. ... It is equally unintelli- 
gible that a state (sic) of volition should be followed by a 
change in the substance of the cortex and so immediately by 
the contraction of a muscle." {Stout.) 

Such confusion of ideas as the above ramifies the whole of 
modern psychological literature and produces a feeling of hope- 
lessness. When conscious processes are set over against phys- 
ical processes and the two are stated to be incommensurable 
and incapable of reaction in the next breath after a statement 
that * for all psychological purposes the relation of mind and 
body must be regarded as one of interaction ' it seems hopeless 
to expect clear analysis in any department of psychology. 

This is much as though one would say ** The concept of 
greenness, which I at present have, is not capable of being re- 
fracted by a prism and therefore is an entirely different process 
from a wave of red light." Or ** The degree of curvature of an 
ellipse is not a commensurable process with the velocity of the 
planet describing that orbit." 

If dynamic monism is correct, the acting in a certain way is 
a condition of thought, just as acting in another way is a con- 
dition of muscular contraction. The series of acts is continuous 
and what we can deduce by abstract thinking as to the peculi- 
arities or properties of these several forms of activities is not to 
be placed in the same genetic chain as the things we think about 
them. We are (that is our life is made up of) the sum of what 
we do. It is possible to think the experiences of doing apart 
from the doing of them because the doing of each act, a simple 
perception for example, leaves the equilibrium complex perman- 
ently altered — produces back eddies beside the * wave of con- 
sciousness.' These changes express themselves in < psycho- 
logical or interpretative ' rather than * psychic ' or realizable 
terms and we should not attempt to interpolate from the formal 
into the real series nor vice versa. See Baldwin's discussion 
of genetic modes in his Development and Evolution^ Chap. XIX. 
The two things are not things in the same sense and it should 
not surprise us that they do not fit in a causal nexus nor should 
we seek such nexus. It is absurd as it would be if in a machine 
we should attempt in one place to fit a shadow instead of the cog 
required. Yet a shadow is a real thing. 



226 C. L, HERRICK. 

Profesior Stout's regret that « no reason in the world can be 
given • for redness in consciousness may be tempered by the 
fact that no reason in the world can be given for any physical 
ultimate or simple fact. It is curious metaphysics that expects 
it. An occurrence is its own reason and there can be no other. 
Science finds uniformities which it classifies but it finds no 
« reason ' for its * laws.' 

Nevertheles Stout very nearly reaches the point of view re- 
quired, for in criticising materialism, he says : ** Whatever 
plausability it (materialism) possesses arises from the use, or 
rather misuse of the ^wor A /unction. Digestion is the function 
of the alimentary canal. . . . The objection is that we do not 
make the two things the same by applying the same word to 
them, when in their own nature they are radically and essentially 
different. When we say that digestion is a function of the 
stomach we mean that digestion is the stomach engaged in diges- 
tion ... but if we describe the brain at work there is no need 
to mention consciousness at all, and in naming and describing 
the conscious processes there is no need to mention the brain. 
The function of the brain as a physiological organ is to move 
the body ; the contraction of muscles is the result of neural im- 
pulses and in describing it we have to mention the nervous sys- 
tem, including the cortex as engaged in it. But the processes 
of consciousness cannot be analyzed or resolved into such proc- 
esses as chemical and physical changes in nerve cells. If 
consciousness be supposed to be produced by the nervous proc- 
esses, the production is simply a creation out of nothing." 

It were easy to reply that all this is pure assumption. We 
do not know (as it is agreed by a certain class of unscientific 
psychologists to claim) that all the energy entering the brain as 
afferent currents leaves it in efferent nervous energy ; in fact, 
we know that this is certainly not true. We do not find phy- 
siological functions for all parts of the organs and have no right 
to assert that nervous energy is not used in performing all sorts 
of recondite processes which somehow serve as a basis for psy- 
chical phenomena. But we need not disturb ourselves about 
this matter, it is beside the point. 

The fallacy begins in talking of conscious processes as con- 



THE NATURE OF THE SOUL. 227 

trasted to other processes and then using consciousness as an 
abstraction aside from the activity and discovering that it is then 
not of one class with the other activities. Our author says that 
it is the function of the brain to move the body. Very well ; we 
move our arms in a complicated set of * wig-wag ' signals which 
the mind of the observer construes into a message of certain im- 
port. Is this result of the movements of the body for this reason 
physiological ? In the brain certain other movements (of energy) 
are construed in apperceptive terms and resulting relations con- 
stitute the objective content of psychology (we have already seen 
that the pure experiences, as such, can form no part of science) 
and we call this resulting system, psychological. If the body 
caused the wig-wagging and its informing symbolism then, in 
exactly like manner, if not so openly and rudely, the body 
caused the thought. Both are manifestations of energy from 
which it is possible to abstract certain modes, etc. 

We claim that mind or consciousness cannot react on the 
body because the two are incommensurable. (Here again the 
difference between experience which is psychic, and the activi- 
ties concerned are objectively considered.) The living energy 
back of both is continuous through both, but the appearance 
in present experience called consciousness and the data of bodily 
action also converted into terms of experience in the mind form 
a series of commensurables because like in kind. 

The doctrine of psychophysical parallelism, so commonly 
held to-day, might doubtless be expressed to conform to the 
dynamic hypothesis, but, in fact, it is not usually so understood. 
Stout says truly : ** The reason of the connection between con- 
scious processes and the correlated nervous processes is not to be 
found in the nervous and conscious processes themselves. Both 
must be regarded as belonging to a more comprehensive system 
of conditions and it is within the system as a whole that the 
reason of their connection is to be sought. . . . We must further 
assume that the material system in its totality is related to the 
material world in its totality as the individual consciousness is 
related to nervous processes taking place in the cortex of the 
brain. . . . The explanation of psychophysical parallelism is 
ultimately based on an idealistic view of material phenomena. 



328 C. L, HBRRICK. 

... In general all that makes matter material presupposes 
some consciousness which takes cognizance of it." '* The world 
of material phenomena presupposes a system of immaterial 
agency. In this immaterial system the individual conscious- 
ness originates." {Manual of Psychology^ 

Hoeffding's criticism of Lotze is quite to the point here and 
we may quote the former author in support of the djmamic view : 
<< We have no right to take mind and body for two things or 
substances in reciprocal interaction. We are, on the contrary, 
impelled to conceive the material interaction between the ele- 
ments composing the brain and nervous system as an outer 
form of the inner ideal unity of consciousness. What we, in 
our inner experience become conscious of as thought, feeling, 
and resolution, is thus represented in the material world by cer- 
tain material processes in the brain, which as such are subjected 
to the law of the persistence of energy, although this law can- 
not be applied to the relation between cerebral and conscious 
processes. It is as though the same thing were said in two 
languages.'' {Outlines of Psychology ^ p. 65,) 

Supplementary Note. 

Of the strong swing of the pendulum in the direction indi- 
cated in these papers during the last few years evidence is fur- 
nished by the genetic series recently issued by Professor J. 
Mark Baldwin and the writings of the so-called Chicago school. 
See also the recent writings of Royce and James. 

Moore says : ** • Life '-experience is one inclusive activity of 
which consciousness and habit — the psychical and the physi- 
cal — are to the analysis, constituent functions." This is inter- 
estingly akin the statement we made above. 

Professor Bawden, has, however, made this view more ex- 
plicit than any recent writer. See his article, •The Functional 
Theory of Parallelism,' Philos. Review, Vol. XII., 3. " Mind 
is not an entity behind the process of consciousness in an organ- 
ism, it is that process itself. Mind is just as truly a growth as 
any other living thing." {Loc. cit., p. 308.) This view finds 
its physiological expression in the equilibrium theory of con- 
sciousness. (See Baldwin's Diet. Philos. and Psych., Vol. I., 
P- I3S-) 



N. S. Vol. XIV. No. 5. July, 1907 



The Psychological Review. 



STUDIES FROM THE PSYCHOLOGICAL LABORA- 
TORY OF THE UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO. 

COMMUNICATED BY PROFESSOR JAMES ROWLAND ANGELL. 

The Rolb of the Tympanic Mechanism in Audition.* 

BY W. V. D. BINGHAM. 

This paper reports a case of a person who enjoys good 
hearing in spite of the destruction of the * sound-conducting ' 
mechanism of both ears. When she first came under our 
observation, in the summer of 1906, her auditory acuity was 
such that a group of acquaintances who had been her constant 
associates for several weeks had not suspected any auditory 
impairment ; and at the present time, although the condition of 
her hearing is not as good as it was then, it is still acute enough 
to enable her to carry efficiently forward her work as a teacher. 

The statement that efficient hearing is still possible after 
both drum membranes have been destroyed and the larger 
ossicles removed comes as a surprise to those whose attention 
has not been previously directed to the pathology of the ear. 
It means that the account which Helmholtz gave of the mechan- 
ism of sound-conduction is untenable, at least as regards his 
theory of the sound-intensifying function of the tympanic mem- 
brane. Dissatisfaction with this theory has been rife in oto- 
logical circles for some years, owing to its inadequacy when 
confronted by the facts of aural pathology. Beckmann' in 

1 The MS. of this article was received April S, 1907. 

**Zur Theorie des H^rens,' Verhandl. der deutsche otol. Ges., 1898. See 
Trdtel, 'Recent Theories of Soand-condttction,' Archives of Otology^ 1903, p. 
385. Treitel gi^es an admirable sommary of the literature ap to 1902, and con- 
cludes that the problem of the middle ear has not yet been solved. 

229 



330 W^. y- D. BINGHAM. 

1898 went the length of maintaining that the tympanic appa- 
ratus is not a sound-conducting device, but is merely a damping 
mechanism. Zimmermann^ also substitutes a damping for a 
transmitting function, but holds, contrary to Beckmann, that 
the damping operates only with sounds of unusual intensity. 
He assumes that the sound waves are transmitted by air con- 
duction across the tympanic cavity to the promontory wall, and 
thence through bone to the basilar membrane fibers. It is the 
function of the round window to make possible the most subtle 
reaction of these fibers. The ossicles and the stapedius muscle 
serve to regulate the intra-labyrinthine pressure. Secchi ' finds 
in the round window the sole pathway for sound through the 
tympanum to the labyrinth. The tympanic membrane and 
ossicles together with the intrinsic muscles protect the inner 
organs against detonations and also serve to regulate the intra- 
tympanic pressure during attentive hearing. *Of the defenders 
of modified forms of the Helmholtz theory, Bezold and Lucae 
are the most able and active. They are agreed that for high 
tones conduction through the larger ossicles is of little impor- 
tance. Lucae* insists that the round window as well as the 
plate of the stapes is capable of receiving sound-waves. Both 
movements could exist together, a compensatory opening for 
minimal pressures produced by the inward movement of the 
stapes being found in the aquaeductus vestibular, and for the 
fenestral membrane in the aquaeductus cochleae. Bezold ^ does 
not hold to the Helmholtz account of the sound-intensifying 
action of the drum membrane, but he contends vigorously for 
the theory of conduction through the ossicular chain. When 
the skull is set in vibration by direct contact with a sounding 
fork, the labyrinth as well as the chain is actuated, yet only 
those waves are effective which, on their way to the labyrinth 
have actuated the chain to transverse vibration. The function 

> In addition to the articles ftummarized by Treitel, cf . ' Der physiologische 
Werth der Labyrinthfenster/ 1904, Arch,/. PhysioL^ Snppl. Bd., S. 193. AJao 
S. 409 and S. 488. 

« Arch./, Ohrenheilk., LV., Heft. 3-4. Cf. Treitel, /. c. 

^Arch.f, Physiol., 1904. Snppl. Bd., S. 49a 

* " Weitere Untersnchungen Uber ' Knochenleitnng ' nnd Schallleitnngs- 
apparat im Ohr.,»» Zeits.f. Ohrenheilk., XLVIIL, 107. 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION. 231 

of the tympanic mechanism is the conversion of longitudinal 
sound-waves into transverse vibrations, which alone are capable 
of setting into sympathetic vibration the receiving apparatus of 
the cochlea. Bezold is reported as saying *< that there is no 
hearing for the lower half of the tone scale without a tympanic 
membrane and an ossicular chain, and that in the case of the 
upper part of the scale the sound-waves are transmitted to the 
labyrinth by vibrations of the stapedial foot-plate."* The 
earlier part of this conclusion is controverted by the existence 
of such cases of audition as the one here described. 

Thirty-six years ago, when Miss Evans, as she may be 
named, was five years of age, a siege of scarlet fever left her 
with a middle-ear discharge (suppurative otitis media) which 
ruptured both ear drums. In the right ear this chronic dis- 
charge has never healed : and in the left, except for two brief 
periods of temporary cessation, it continued until the fall of 
1906. During girlhood the only method of treatment which 
was tried, that of syringing, proved very painful and was little 
used. The earliest aurist's record available was furnished by 
Dr. Clarence J. Blake, otologist of the Harvard Medical School, 
who treated the case in 1888-90. His records show partial de- 
struction of both drum membranes at that time. ** Hearing was 
effected by direct transmission of the sound waves to the base 
plate of the stapes. There was no evidence of cochlear involve- 
ment." An accumulation of cicatricial adhesion hindered the 
free vibration of the stapes, so that hearing was considerably 
below normal. (Note that the decreased acuity is not explained 
by reference to the condition of the tympanic membrane or the 
< sound-conducting ' mechanism. Dr. Blake says: ** In the 
great majority of suppurative cases the decreased mobility of the 
stapes either from altered position of the ossicular chain or from 
tissue changes within the fenestral niche is the essential thing.") 

In 1898, Dr. M. D. Jones, of St. Lrouis, operated upon the 
right ear, removing the remnant of the tympanic membrane, 
the accumulations of cicatricial adhesions and the two larger 
ossicles which had become much necrosed. No operation has 
been performed upon the left ear, but the incus has been lost 

'Hartmann, in report of German otological society in Wiesbaden, May 29 
and 30, 1903. Archives of Otology, XXXII., 286. 



23* »^. y- D, BINGHAM, 

and the drum membrane is almost totally destroyed. In each 
ear the stapes is imbedded in an accumulation of scar tissue, 
and in the right, poorer, ear is completely hidden from view. 
The Eustachian tubes are completely closed at times, prevent- 
ing the draining of the mucous of the middle ear into the throat, 
and causing an accumulation which interferes with hearing. 
Miss Evans states that her hearing varies with her general nerv- 
ous condition. 

In August, 1906, at the time of making the first of the audi- 
tory tests here reported, the ears were discharging very slightly 
and were therefore probably at their best as to function. Dr. 
J. B. Shapleigh, of St. Louis, who has had the case under ob- 
servation for the past two years, informs me that usually '* im- 
provement in the local inflammatory conditions in these cases 
brings better hearing, but it is not uncommon to find that when 
all secretion ceases and the ear becomes dry, the hearing be- 
comes less. This is undoubtedly due to the dry tissues being 
more rigid and stiff than when moist since with a recurrence of 
slight discharge an increase in hearing is noticed." These vari- 
ations in hearing doubtless have their cause in ** the varying 
mobility of the stapes and the membrane of the round window, 
but especially of the former. In many cases of exhausted 
middle ear suppuration with large loss of the drum membrane 
and with absence of the incus — the conducting chain being thus 
broken — very fair hearing may exist, provided the stapes is 
freely movable and not hampered by adhesions or thickened 
tissue in the niche of the oval window." A considerable dimi- 
nution in Miss Evans' hearing ability has taken place since she 
was tested in the summer of 1906. This is due, however, to a 
recurrence of the old inflammation of the membranes brought on 
by a severe cold, and is not traceable to a complete cessation of 
the discharge with consequent lack of the moisture which seems 
to be essential for maximum flexibility of the annular ring of 
the stapes and the membrane of the round window. No use is 
made of < artificial drums ' or other mechanical aids to hearing.^ 

^ The best ' artificUl drams * so called are mere pledgets of cotton, deftly 
adjusted to increase the pressaie npon the stapes to precisely the right amount 
Sometimes, when the dram membrane is lacking, a bit of vaseline placed upon 
the head of the stapes senres to weight it properly and considerably augment 
hearing. 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION. 233 

In the laboratory Miss Evans was first tested in auditory 
acuity, tonal limits, pitch discrimination, localization of sound 
and analysis of clangs. It is regretted that, owing to the brief 
period which elapsed between the discovery of the case and the 
necessary departure of Miss Evans from the city, some of the 
tests had to be rather fragmentary. Six months later it was 
possible to make a few supplementary tests which were directed 
in part to determining whether the subject's general sensitivity 
is supernormal. Some additional data were also gathered on 
the hearing of difference-tones. 

In this connection it ought to be remarked that cases of audi- 
tion somewhat resembling this one are not of extremely rare 
occurrence in the records of otological clinics. The additional 
features which give to this case an especial value for purposes 
of experimental observation are to be found in the high intel- 
ligence, the more than ordinary powers of concentration, and 
the facility in introspection which the observer brought to her 
tasks. 

The Rinn^ test was negative : that is, a sounding fork which 
had become so faint as to be no longer audible by air conduc- 
tion could be heard again if placed against the mastoid process 
of the temporal bone. The Weber phenomenon was prominent ; 
when a vibrating fork was pressed against the top of the head, 
the sound was localized in the right, poorer, ear, even when the 
fork was placed much nearer to the better ear. Such results 
indicate that the hearing defect is due to trouble in the mechan- 
ism of the middle ear and not in the sound-receiving apparatus 
of the cochlea. 

In testing auditory acuity , the Seashore audiometer was used, 
and also the whispered-word test. The audiometer gives a 
simple noise of fairly constant quality and of an intensity varying 
from o to 40 units of an arbitrary scale. The normal threshold 
lies somewhat below the middle of this scale. Eight students 
wth apparently normal hearing were tested at the same time 
with Miss Evans, and their thresholds of acuity were found to 
range between 15 and 25.^ At the first day's trial Miss Evans' 

^ On the standard instmment of the C. H. Stoelting Co., an acute ear can hear 
intensity 13. A comparison of our instrument with this standard, after the tests 



334 fV. V. D. BINGHAM. 

threshold was determined as 26 for the left ear and 28 for the 
right. Later this was reduced to 25 and 27. 

Since it sometimes occurs that good hearing for conversational 
speech is accompanied by poor hearing for certain simple noises, 
and vice versa, the audiometer test was supplemented by the 
whispered-word test. For determining comparative auditory 
efficiency in this way, Andrews ^ has prepared ten lists of ten 
numerals each, which contain the difierent varieties of conso- 
nant and vowel speech elements in much the same proportion in 
which they are found in spoken language. The use of numer- 
als presents the advantage of uniform apperceptive value for all 
observers and for all the words. This is so well recognized 
among aurists that whispered or spoken numerals are almost 
universally employed in diagnosis. The traditional method of 
using this test is to determine the maximum distance at which the 
observer can hear the numerals. Auditory acuity is expressed 
by a fraction of which this distance is the numerator and the 
normal distance is the denominator. For purposes of accurate 
determination, Andrews criticises this method on the ground 
that its validity rests on two assumptions which his experiments 
have led him to question ; first, that intensity of the sounds of 
speech decreases with approximate regularity as the distance 
from the speaker increases ; second, that the sounds used as 
test words undergo with change of distance merely a quantita- 
tive and not a qualitative alteration. As an improvement upon 
this * method of extreme ranges,' Andrews recommends the 
* method of degree of accuracy,' in which auditory acuity is 
determined by comparing an observer's percentage of accuracy 
at a given distance with the normal percentage at the same dis- 
tance under identical acoustical conditions. 

Andrews' lists of numerals were pronounced to Miss Evans 
and six control observers at the same time. They were seated 
with the left ear toward the speaker, Miss Evans being given 



had been made, showed that the magnet of the telephone receiver had lost 1 
of its strength, and that in consequence the click waa not quite as loud as it 
ahould be. This point shonld be borne in mind if comparisons are made be- 
tween the figures given above and readings taken with other audiometers. 
^ Am. Jour, Psy,, 1904, XV., 36. 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION 235 

the central position. Each was provided with paper on which 
the numbers were recorded as heard. If the observers had been 
tested separately it would have been possible to have them hear 
the words from identically the same place in the room ; but that 
plan would have sacrificed something of uniformity in enunci- 
ation. Even when the usual precautions, of using the residual 
breath after exhalation, etc., are taken, some differences in 
intensity must still remain. In the method here used, these 
inequalities were minimized. Accidental distractions, such as 
outside noises, were also the same for all the observers. 

At a distance of three feet Miss Evans' degree of accuracy 
was 97.5 per cent. That of the others varied from 98.5 per 
cent, to 100 per cent., only one observer hearing every syllable 
correctly. At fifteen feet Miss Evans heard 70 per cent, cor- 
rectly, while the record of the others varied from 88 per cent, 
to 99.5 per cent., the average being slightly less than 95 per 
cent. These figures show clearly by how much Miss Evans' 
hearing is less than normal. It would be entirely incorrect to 
characterize her as • hard-of-hearing.* 

The question may arise whether in Miss Evans' case the 
auditory nerve may not be more sensitive than that of the aver- 
age person. Tests made in several different sense realms 
failed to disclose any general hypersensitivity. Both eyes are 
very slightly astigmatic and far sighted. Bright illumination 
is often painful. Tests with an oculist's chart showed that the 
visual acuity of the left eye was normal and that of the right 
eye a very little less than normal. Sensitivity to differences of 
brightness was tested by means of a Masson disc rotated in an 
illumination of diffused daylight. Miss Evans pointed out a 
gray ring which differed from the background in brightness by 
1/150 and was uncertain as to the next ring which differed from 
the background by 1/2 14. The four other observers tested at 
the same time pointed out both of these rings correctly, and one 
saw a ring which was even fainter. Miss Evans' sensitivity to 
differences of brightness is then certainly not supernormal. 
Tests in matching Holmgren worsteds disclosed an unusually 
well cultivated color discrimination, ^sthesiometer tests on 
the forearms revealed nothing unusual in her tactile discrimina- 



336 HT, V. D. BINGHAM. 

tion of two points ; and tests with small lifted weights indicated 
no peculiar muscular sensitivity. The only tests which point 
to a sensitivity above the average were with the Cattell algom- 
eter. The transition from the sensation of ' pressure ' to that 
of * pressure-plus-pain ' was unambiguous. The threshold on 
the nail of each index finger was i kg. (average of six tests at 
different times ; average deviationt .1 kg.). On the right thumb 
nail the threshold was 1.5 kg. ; on the left, 1.2 kg. ; on the right 
and left temples, each i kg. While these results do not fall 
within the range of hyperaesthesia, they are belowthe average 
for women. 

Although Miss Evans manifests no general hypersensitivity, 
it is natural to suppose that her auditory sensitivity has been 
developed to a high degree during the many years of middle- 
ear difficulty when it was necessary to exercise more than ordi- 
nary efforts of auditory attention. 

In testing for the upper tonal limit, an Edelmann-Galton 
whistle was used. If Edelmann's calibrations on this particular 
pipe hold good for the light bulb-pressure used, and for the pre- 
vailing barometric pressures and temperatures of Chicago, a 
majority of observers can hear tones of from 44,000 to 49,000 
vibrations per second (the pipe-length being from 0.32 mm. to 
0.16 mm. and the width of lip 0.62 mm.). These are, roughly, 
the pitches/^ and g^. Miss Evans heard on the first day tested 
22,000 vibrations (2.17 mm. with same width of lip) with the 
right ear, and 24,000 vibrations (1.87 mm.) with the left. These 
tones are not far irom/^ and g^. A few days later Miss Evans 
could hear 32,000 vibrations (i.oi mm.) with the left ear. 
While this is half an octave below normal, it is well within the 
range where perfectly healthy ears of middle-aged persons often 
reach their higher limit. 

The lower limit for the left ear was below 32 vibrations or 
within an octave of normal. With the right ear no tone could 
be heard from any of the Appunn forks, the smallest of which 
gives 64 vibrations. At the organ, it was possible to hear a 
pipe of 64 vibrations with this ear, if the swell box was open but 
not otherwise. When three pipes were sounding pedal C of the 
contra-octave, 32 vibrations, the observer could detect a sound 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION. 237 

with the better ear closed, but it is probable that what she heard 
was a clang of upper partials. One of these same low pipes 
sounding singly could barely be heard with the better ear at a 
distance of 25 feet, while two other observers could hear it at 
70 feet. In these tests it required an appreciable length of time 
for Miss Evans to decide whether a pipe were sounding or not. 
With pitches and intensities near her lower limit of hearing, her 
discrimination time was often as long as a second and a half. 

A test for the integrity of the scale between 32 and 32,000 
vibrations revealed no discontinuities or tonal islands. A series 
of tests to discover the fundamental tones of the tympanic cavi- 
ties which the absence of an accommodatory apparatus would 
make prominent was not completed. 

Miss Evans has not a * musical ear,' and had had no prac- 
tice in pitch discrimination. When first tested she made errors 
in gross musical intervals ; but with a little practice she devel- 
oped considerable accuracy in telling which of two tones was 
the higher. On the third day she was able to discriminate cor- 
rectly differences of one vibration per second (1/32 tone) from 
^ of 256 vibrations. In these tests heavy Koenig forks mounted 
on resonators were used. It is much easier to approximate uni- 
formity of intensity with these than with the unmounted forks 
sometimes employed.^ 

In the tests on clang analysis, the chief interest centered 
about the hearing of difierence-tones. It will be recalled that 
a tone arising from the simultaneous sounding of two tones from 
independent sources does not actuate a resonator tuned to its 
vibration rate ; consequently it must have its origin within the 
ear. • To account for these so-called subjective difference-tones, 
Helmholtz advanced the theory that the asymmetrical form of 
the tympanic membrane necessitates that when it is set in vibra- 
tion by two different sounds it must vibrate also at a rate equal 
to the difference between the rates of the two primaries, and 

^ Sndi mstances as this one, where excellent discrimination of small pitch 
differences accompanies a total lack of natnral mnsical ability and interest, call 
attention to a fallacy involved in Seashore's suggestion of nsing rough tests of 
pitch discrimination in determining whether a pnblic-school pupil has a suffi- 
dently ' mnsical ear ' to make it worth while for him to be given any musical 
education. {Univ. of Iowa Studies, II., 55, and Educ. Rev,, XXII., 75.} 



238 iV. V, D, BINGHAM. 

thus generate the difference-tone. A secondary hypothesb 
based upon the looseness of articulation between malleus and 
incus was held to be applicable when the primaries are very 
loud. Later workers in this field, notably Stumpf » Ebbinghaus, 
ter Kuile, Max Meyer, Hurst and Ewald, have developed 
theories of audition which seek to explain the facts of difier- 
ence-tones by a mode of functioning of the structures within the 
inner ear, but no one of these theories has succeeded up to the 
present time in commanding general assent by meeting all of 
the facts. 

Recently K. S. Schaefer^ has shown that a telephone dia- 
phragm will generate difference-tones which set in vibration 
properly attuned resonators ; and the suggestion has been made 
that Schaefer's experiments point toward a rehabilitation of 
the Helmholz theory that subjective difference-tones take their 
origin in the tympanic membrane. 

An instance of good audition in which the tympanic mem- 
branes and larger ossicles are lacking presented the opportunity 
for a crucial experiment. The results were unequivocal : Miss 
Evans hears the so-called subjective difference-tones.' 

For preliminar}' practice use was made of small Qjiincke 
tubes and high-pitched organ pipes. The observer was soon 
able to distinguish the first and second difference-tones. Then 
she was set the task of tuning a Stern tone-variator to unison 
with the lower difference-tone arising from two organ pipes 
actuated from independent sources of wind supply. On the 
first trial she succeeded. The second trial was a failure, the 
.variator being tuned not to the pitch of the difference-tone, but 
to a pitch closely consonant with it. The observer was much 
fatigued by the taxing strain of these experiments, and her error 1 

is not surprising, especially when one considers the dissimilarity | 

^'Ueber die Brzeugnng phjtikalischer KombinatiamtOne mittelst des i 

Stentortelephont,' AnntUenderPhysik, 1905, XVII., 572. ' 

* Dennert, in reporting his experiments with interruption-tones ( ' Aknsdach- j 

physiologiache Untersuchungen,' Arch,/, OhrenheUk,^ 1887, XXIV., 173), ssys : 
" Ich babe nan Patienten ohne TrommelfeU, anch solche ohne Trommelfblli 
Hammer und Amboss, mit nnr erholtenem Steigsbagel, anf dieses Verhalten 
hin geprtift und gefnnden, dass sie ebenfalls CombinationstOne horen.' ' Unfor- 
tunately he giTes no further information regarding the hearing of his patients 
or the manner in which the tests were made. 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION, 239 

of timbre between the difference-tone and the objective tone of 
the variator. 

On the following day the procedure was varied in two par- 
ticulars. Heavy Koenig forks mounted on resonance-boxes 
were used to produce the primary tones, and the observer, 
who never sings, was asked to choose on a harmonium the 
tones corresponding to the first and second difference-tones. 
She would begin with the lowest note on the harmonium and 
try each one in turn until she found the desired pitch. While 
the observer was searching for the correct pitch the experi- 
menter was careful to stand out of her field of view, to exclude 
the possibility of an unconscious choice on the basis of some 
involuntary movement on his part. At another time the ob- 
server was told that among the thirty odd forks before her were 
two which had the same pitch as the difference-tones, and she 
was asked to find them. In all of these tests she was uniformly 
successful. 

The pitch-numbers of most of the forks used were in simple 
ratios, so that the difference-tones were in close harmonic rela- 
tion to the primaries. Lest it should be objected that the 
observer, knowing in a vague way what was expected, had 
sought among the available tones until she found the ones that 
fused most perfectly with the primaries, two forks were selected 
whose vibration rates were as S to 7. The lower difference-tone 
would then be 2, and the higher 3. If the observer were 
selecting her tones on the basis of fusion she would have chosen 
the lower octaves of the primaries : but as a matter of fact she 
tried these when she came to them and rejected them as 
promptly as any of the others. 

The successful issue of these experiments shows] that sub- 
jective difference-tones may be generated without the aid of the 
tympanic membrane or any mechanism of the middle ear. This 
in no way reflects upon Helmholtz's mathematical proof that 
asymmetrical membranes must vibrate under the influence of 
two sound-waves of sufficient amplitude in such a manner that 
one, two or more additional pendular vibrations are generated. 
But it does prove that such an explanation is not an adequate 
account of the phenomenon of subjective difference-tones. 



240 m K. D. BINGHAM. 

The question at once arises whether the tympanic mechanism, 
while not essential to the hearing of difference-tones, may not 
augment them. It is conceivable that combination-tones may 
have a physical origin within the labyrinth, as Schaefer urges,^ 
and also in the tympanic mechanism, as Helmholtz held. It is 
possible that wherever two sonorous vibrations of sufficient 
amplitude simultaneously actuate the same body, they may 
generate a pendular vibration of a rate equal to the difference 
between their rates. Lord Rayleigh is authority for the state- 
ment that practically all bodies manifest the required asymmetry 
even in the case of aerial vibrations. He says, *« Whether we 
are considering progressive waves advancing from a source, or 
the stationary vibrations of a resonator, there is an essential 
want of symmetry between the condensation and rarefaction, 
and the formation in some degree of octaves and combination- 
tones is a mathematical necessity." ' 

It was thus desirable to establish whether, in comparison with 
observers who possess tympanic membranes. Miss Evans is able 
to hear difference-tones relatively as well as she hears the 
primaries. 

An attempt to determine this point was made when, in 
February 1907, an opportunity occurred to perform some addi- 
tional tests. As has been already indicated, Miss Evans' hearing 
had considerably diminished since the first experiments were 
made. The audiometer showed an acuity of 31 and 40(?) 
instead of 25 and 27. Whispered words were heard with diffi- 
culty at three feet which had been heard at fifteen feet. The 
upper tonal limit was reduced to 3.45 mm. and 4.46 mm. 
(17,000 and 14,000 vibrations). The lower limit for the better 
ear had risen to 48 vibrations. Bone conduction for tones of 
64 and 128 vibrations was as good as before, if not better; but 
the negative Rinn^ was greater in each case. 

The procedure adopted was as follows : two mounted forks 
were selected whose vibration numbers were 768 and 896, a 
ratio of 6 to 7. Miss Evans correctly located the pitch of the 

' ' Bine nene Brklarung der snbjectiTen Combination8t6ne/ Arch./, d, ges. 
Physiol,, LXXVIII., 505. 

* The Theory 0/ Sound, second edition, 1896, Vol. II., 459. 



THB TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION, 241 

lower, louder difference-tone. By means of two auscultation 
tubes leading from a common stem. Miss Evans and a control 
observer well trained in auditory discrimination listened to the 
sound of the same fork. The experimenter, by moving the 
mouthpiece of the tube to and from the resonating box of the 
fork could make the sound appear and disappear irregularly. 
The observers, who were seated back to back, indicated by a 
movement of the finger when they heard the sound and when 
they did not. This made it possible for the experimenter to 
determine, with the aid of a stop-watch, the difference in the 
ringing -off time for the two observers. Lest there might be an 
inequality in the carrying-power of the two auscultation tubes, 
their use was alternated between the observers. 

In eight trials with the lower fork, the control observer could 
hear it for an average of 13.5 seconds longer than Miss Evans ; 
average deviation i second. The higher fork died away more 
rapidly, and here the difference in ringing-off times for the two ob- 
servers averaged 7 seconds, average deviation less than i second. 
Lastly the two forks were sounded together, and the length of 
time that the difference-tone could be distinguished was re- 
corded, together with the time between the disappearance of the 
difference-tone and the disappearance of the primaries for each 
observer. The experimenter had no check on the introspec- 
tions of the observer as to the length of time the difference-tone 
was audible, as it was impossible for him to vary its intensity 
virithout modifying the primaries. Under such circumstances 
the imagination is certain to be a dangerous factor, and the 
difference-tone will sometimes continue to be reported as heard 
after it has passed below the limit of audibility. The higher of 
the two forks always died away before the lower, and if it were 
actuated lightly again, immediately after the difference-tone was 
reported as lost, the difference-tone did not always reappear, 
although if this primary were made as loud as the other, the 
difference-tone was once more reported as audible. Now for 
Miss Evans, the difference between the ringing-off times of the 
separate forks, 6.5 seconds, was only one second shorter than 
the average time between the disappearance of the difference- 
tone and the vanishing of the louder, lower primary. Appar- 



24a W, V, D. BINGHAM. 

ently the difference-tone could be heard nearly as long as both 
primaries continued to be audible. This was not the case with 
the control observer, who lost the difference-tone six seconds 
before he ceased to hear the weaker primary. One is forced 
to suspect that Miss Evans continued to hear the difference-tone 
in imagination after it had passed below her limit of audibility. 
She herself remarked upon her uncertainty in distinguishing 
between vanishing sensation and vivid image. How difficult 
this discrimination is, those who have practiced clang analysis 
well know. Because this undetermined factor was present, the 
quantitative results are unreliable,. and one cannot assert with 
confidence the conclusion which the experiments strongly sug- 
gested, that Miss Evans' hearing for difference-tones is rela- 
tively better than that of a normal observer with intact tympanic 
membranes.^ 

A few tests in auditory localization in the horizontal plane 
were made in August, 1906. Use was made of the relatively 
pure tone of a tuning fork, the clangs of a stopped pipe and a 
reed pipe and the noise of a metallic click. The ease and accu- 
racy of localization was in proportion to the complexity of the 
sound rather than to its intensity. Of the errors made with 
sounds not in the median plane, somewhat more than half were 
on the right side. At the present time. Bard* is championing 
the theory that the middle ear contains a mechanism which 
accommodates to distance and direction. The nature of the 
rhythmic movements of the chain of ossicles is in part deter- 
mined by the angle of incidence of the sound-wave upon the 
membrane, and the perpendicular and tangential components of 
this motion supply elements to the inner ear which are significant 
for orientation of the origin of the sound. The tensor tympani 
adapts the tension of the drum-membrane to weak or loud sounds. 

* Since the above was placed in type the writer has learned that K. S. 
Schaefer has found in Berlin several cases of patients who hear without drum 
membranes, and some who lack the larger ossicles; and all are able to hear dif- 
ference-tones. A full description of these interesting cases with a discussion of 
their bearing upon theories of difference-tones may be expected soon from Dr. 
Schaefer 's pen. 

' ' Des diverses modalit^s des mouvements de la chaine des o&ButX^Xs^^ Jour. 
Physiol. PathoL, 1905. VII., 665. 



THE TYMPANIC MECHANISM IN AUDITION. 243 

The Stapedius however, according to Bard, is autonomous and 
not antagonistic. It draws backward the head of the stapes, 
and with it the whole chain and the handle of the malleus, 
making tense the anterior portion of the drum-membrane, relax- 
ing the posterior portion, and adapting for the distance of the 
sound. The significance for such a theory of data obtained 
from an observer who lacks this accommodatory mechanism is 
obvious, and it is regretted that it was not possible to carry 
through an extended series of localization tests. 

Summary. — A person who through disease and operation 
lost the tympanic membrane and most of the ossicular chain of 
both ears is not * hard-of-hearing ' but possesses very efficient 
auditory acuity. The foot-plate of the stapes in each ear is 
covered by scar tissue, and it is possible that if the vibrations of 
the stapes were not thus hindered, auditory acuity would be fully 
normal. Sensitivity in other sense realms is not supernormal. 
Absence of the tympanic membranes does not prevent genera- 
tion of ' subjective ' difference-tones. 

As to the significance of the tympanic mechanism in audi- 
tion, such a case as this one suggests that the physical sound- 
conducting functions have been quite generally over-emphasized ; 
while the physiological, protective functions have been treated 
with neglect. What the eye-lid does for the eye, the drum 
membrane does for the ear. It protects delicate structures 
against irritation and injury, and permits the inner membranes 
to be kept moist and in a condition of maximum efficiency.^ 

' The writer desires to express his gratitude to Professor B. B. Breese for his 
kindness in granting, for the second set of tests, the privileges of the psycho- 
logical laboratory of the University of Cincinnati. 



ON THE METHOD OF JUST PERCEPTIBLE 
DIFFERENCES.* 

BY P. M. URBAN. 

If a subject is required to compare two stimuli «S\ and S^ 
many times the judgments vary without any apparent order, so 
that one is unable to tell what the judgment will be in a given 
experiment, but in a great number of experiments each judg- 
ment tends to occur in a certain percentage of all the cases. 
This is the formal character of random events and we introduce 
the notion of a probability of a judgment of a certain type, as- 
suming that there exists a definite probability in every experi- 
ment that the experiment will result in a judgment of a certain 
type. Let us denote by the letter / the probability that S^ will 
be judged greater than S^f and by g the probability that a judg- 
ment will be given which is not a * greater ' judgment. The 
latter group contains all those cases in which S^ is judged 
smaller than S^ and those cases in which the stimuli seem to 
be equal. 

In applying the method of just perceptible differences one 
starts from two stimuli which seem to be equal, increasing one 
stimulus until a difference is perceived ; this difference is re- 
corded as a determination of the just perceptible positive dif- 
ference. Then starting from inequality of the stimuli one 
diminishes the stimulus of greater intensity until the two stimuli 
seem to be equal ; this difference is put down as a determina- 
tion of the just imperceptible positive difference. Both these 
results are combined into a mean, which is called the limen or 
threshold of difference in the direction of increase. By a sim- 
ilar series of experiments one determines the just perceptible 
negative difference and the just imperceptible negative differ- 

* Delivered at the meeting of experimental psychologists at Philadelphii, 
April 17 and i8, 1907. This paper is an abstract of a chapter of a monograph 
on psychophysical methods, which is to appear in the monograph series of the 
Psychological Laboratory of the Uniyersity of Pennsylvania. 

244 



METHOD OF JUST PBRCBPTIBLB DIFFBRBNCBS, 345 

ence, the average of which is the threshold in the direction of 
decrease. A considerable number of such determinations for 
each standard stimulus is required, because a single determi- 
nation is not very reliable. The discrepancies between the re- 
sults are eliminated by means of an algorithm which is nothing 
else but an application of the method of least squares. 

The method of just perceptible differences requires that the 
subject compares pairs of stimuli which have one stimulus, the 
standard stimulus, in common and that these pairs are ordered 
according to the magnitude of the comparison stimuli so that 

There exists for every pair a certain probability that the judg- 
ment * greater ' will be given and we call these probabilities 

where -p^^ is the probability that in the comparison of the stim- 
ulus r^ with the standard the judgment * greater' will be given. 
The probabilities that a judgment will be given which is not a 
* greater ' judgment are correspondingly 



Presenting this series of stimuli to the subject the first pair on 
which the judgment * greater' is given, all the previous pairs 
being judged * smaller' or * equal,' is a result for the method of 
just perceptible differences. The probability that a stimulus 
will be noted as a result of the method of just perceptible dif- 
ferences is, therefore, identical with the compound probability 
that this stimulus is judged greater, and that on all the smaller 
stimuli judgments are given which are not * greater ' judgments 
Denoting these probabilities by /\, P,, • • -i^ we find 

^i=A 

^8 = 9x9^^ 



Pn = 9x9% ' • • fi'n-l A- 



34* F, M. URBAN. 

In a considerable number of determinations each pair will be 
obtained as an observation of the just perceptible difference in 
a number of times which is proportional to this probability, and 
the results of JV series of experiments, after being brought in 
proper order, will have the following form : 

The stimulus r, occurred NPy^ times, which gives for the final 
determination rJ^^N. 

The stimulus r, occurred NP^ times, which gives for the final 
determination rJP^. 

The stimulus r^ occurred NP^ times, which gives for the final 
determination rJ^^N. 

The method of just perceptible differences requires that the 
average of all the valuesr JP^ht, taken as a final determina- 
tion of the threshold, which is 

Jlf-^(r,P,ir+r/VV^+. . .+ rJPjr)^r,P,^ rJP^+ • . . + r,/>.. 

The technical name of this expression is the mathematical ex- 
pectation for the result of this series. 

A number of interesting conclusions may be drawn from this 
analysis of the method of just perceptible differences, but its 
immediate psychological importance becomes clearer by the fol- 
lowing considerations. Taking the average of a series of observa- 
tions has the signification of determining the most probable value 
of the quantity observed. This interpretation, however, can be 
given to the arithmetical mean only if the distribution is sym- 
metrical. It is obvious that such a supposition is not justifiable 
for any particular series of comparison stimuli. The distribu- 
tion of the P's depends entirely on the values of the ^*s, which 
in turn depend on our choice of the comparison stimuli. It may 
be that the distribution is symmetrical in a particular case, but 
generally it will not be. The average of our observations, 
therefore, will not have the character of the most probable 
value, if we use only one series of pairs of comparison stimuli. 
For the further interpretation of the method one circumstance 
which is of the greatest importance, has been observed in almost 
all serious investigations without its importance being recog- 



METHOD OF JUST PERCEPTIBLE DIFFERENCES. 247 

nized. As a rule one does not work with one series only, but 
different comparison stimuli are used and the results of all these 
determinations are combined. For such a combination of inde- 
pendent distributions the theorem holds which Bruns calls the 
conservation of the <^(r)-tyP^> ^^^ which may be formulated in 
this way: The mixture of independent distributions tends 
towards the <^(7')^ype. If we are careful to use several dif- 
ferent series of comparison stimuli the average of all the results 
will have the signification of the most probable value. The 
most probable value is. the one for which /\ is a maximum* 
One can show without difficulty that /\ is a maximum inde- 
pendent of our choice of the following stimuli if / = ^. We 
come to the conclusion that the average of all the observations 
is that amount of difference for which there exists the probability 
one half that the judgment * greater' will be given. By a series 
of similar considerations one finds that the quantity which we 
determine by the algorithm of the method of just perceptible 
differences as the just imperceptible positive difference is that 
amount of difference for which there exists the probability one 
half that the judgment * greater' will not be given. The com- 
bination of the just perceptible and the just imperceptible differ- 
ence, i. e.j the arithmetical mean, gives a more refined determina- 
tion of the same quantity. 

These considerations have some bearing on the practical 
application of the method of just perceptible differences. The 
first is that one must record all the judgments given in order to 
get the most out of one's results. In this way one obtains a set 
of results in the working out of which one may step over from 
the method of just perceptible differences to the method of right 
and wrong cases at any moment. If one records only the first 
pair of the series on which the judgment greater was given, one 
will obtain good results, but the little saving of clerical work i» 
more than compensated by the loss in the lucidity of the results. 
The second important point is to vary the steps * by which one 
approaches the threshold,' because otherwise one can not make 
the supposition of a symmetrical distribution. The third point 
is that the value of the jP's is not changed by the order in which 
the pairs are presented. It is, therefore, not essential to let the 



248 F. M, URBAN. 

pairs follow in the order of the magnitude of the comparison 
stimuli. One may give the stimuli r^, r,, . . . r^ in any order 
whatsoever. All the judgments are recorded and from the 
records one finds the smallest stimulus on which the judgment 
* greater ' was given, and combining the results of several such 
experiments one obtains a result which is identical with that of 
the method of just perceptible differences. The method of giving 
the pairs in irregular order has the advantage of eliminating the 
influence of expectation on the part of the observer and there 
is no difficulty in working out the results since our discussion 
has shown that the order in which the stimuli are presented is 
not essential for the method of just perceptible diiSerences. 

This method was frequently the object of severe criticism 
and it is perhaps not void of interest to make some remarks on 
how its accuracy compares with that of the method of right and 
wrong cases. The empirical data of both methods are the same, 
namely empirical determinations of probabilities. The accuracy 
of such determinations depends on the so-called coefficient of 
precision in Bernouilli's theorem. This quantity depends on the 
probability which is to be determined in this sense, that it is 
smallest for the value one half and it increases when the prob- 
ability which is to be determined approaches zero or the unit. 
In the formulae given above the -P's are products of the ^*s, and 
P^ is always smaller . than f^ except for i = i where /\ = /p 
The precision in the determination of the -P's is, therefore, 
greater than in that of the ^*s. The method of just perceptible 
differences makes use of the P's and, with the same number of 
experiments, its accuracy will be greater than that of the method 
of right and wrong cases which starts from the /*s. 

We will illustrate these theoretical considerations by some 
results of a series of experiments on lifted weights. The 
standard stimulus of 100 gr. was compared with weights of 84, 
88, 92, 96, 100, 104, and 108 gr. The standard was always 
the first to be lifted and the judgments were given on the second 
stimulus. In the experiments a terminology was used similar 
to that suggested by Martin and Mtiller, but for the present 
purpose the results are classed as ^ heavier ' judgments and 
judgments which were not * heavier ' judgments. Table I. 



METHOD OF JUST PERCEPTIBLE DIFFERENCES. 249 

Table I. 

PROBABILITIBS of a ' HBAVIBR ' JUDGMBNT. 



ru 


A 


not-h 


rjt 


A 


not-h 


84 
88 


0.0222 

0.0244 
O.IIII 
0.2933 


0.9778 
0.7067 


100 
104 
108 


o.'8i56 
0.9044 


0.471 I 
0.1844 
0.0956 



Table II. 

VaI^UBS op Pk FOR THB DBTBRMINATION OF THB JUST PBRCBPTIBI^B 
POSITIVB DiFFBRBNCB. 



84 


0.0222 


88 


0.0238 


92 


0.1060 


96 


0.2487 


100 


0.3169 


104 


0.2302 


108 


0.0471 


2; 


0.9949 


Ri 


0.0050 



shows the observed relative frequencies of ^ heavier ' judgments 
in the column marked ^ h ' and in the column < not-^ ' the differ- 
ences of these numbers from the unit for one of seven subjects. 
These numbers of relative frequency are empirical determina- 
tions of the underlying probabilities of a ^ heavier ' judgment and 
one may compute on this basis the value of P for every com- 
parison weight. The results of this computation are given in 
Table II. This table shows that the P's increase at first and 
then approach zero very rapidly after having attained a certain 
maximum. Multiplying these numbers with the intensity of the 
corresponding comparison stimuli and adding these products 
gives what we have to call the just perceptible difference, if the 
distribution is symmetrical. This result is given in Table III. 
We must get the same result within the limits of accuracy of an 
empirical determination, if we count how many times it occurred 
that each weight was the lightest weight of the entire series to 
be judged * heavier.' This means that the judgment * smaller ' 
or • equal ' is given on all the preceding weights and that this 



250 F, M. (/RBAy. 

Tablb III. 

VaI^USS op TkPk FOR THB DbTBRKINATIOK OP THB JUST PB&CBFTlBUt 
POSITIVB DiPPB&BNCB. 



84 


1.8648 


88 


2.0944 


92 


9.7520 


96 


23.8752 


100 


31.6910 


104 


23.9408 


108 


5.0868 


£ 


98.3050 



weight is judged < heavier/ The results of this observation are 
given in Table IV., where under the heading r^ the intensities 
of the comparison stimuli are given and under the heading Nj^ 
the number of times each stimulus was the smallest on which 
the judgment ' heavier * was given. These results arc given for 
four different series each one comprising 100 experiments with 
each pair of comparison stimuli. It will be noticed that in some 
of the columns the sum of all these numbers is somewhat 
smaller than 100. This is due to the fact that those series in 
which no < heavier ' judgment is given do not yield a result by 
the method of just perceptible differences, which is also expressed 
by the fact that the P^ do not add up exactly to one as shown 
in Table II. The combined result of all the four series together 
is given in Table V. The difference between the computed 
value and the observed values is very small. 

Table IV. 

RBSUI^TS op ObSBRVATIONS on THB JUST PBRCBPTIBLB POSfTIVB DiFPBR. 

BNCB IN Four Sbribs (IVa., I., III. and IV.) op 100 Bxpbrimbnts Bach. 





iva. 


I. 


III. 


IV. 


»» 


^k 


r^. 


2 


r^^ 


^k 


rt^k 


^k 


r^. 


84 


4 


336 


168 


I 


84 


I 


84 


88 






>i 


264 


4 


352 


3 


264 


92 


8 


736 


1,656 


7 


644 


12 


I,IOJ 


96 


25 


2,400 


26 


2.496 


*2 


2.592 
2,800 


23 


2.208 


100 


30 


3tOOO 


23 


, 2,300 


28 


37 


3,7W> 


104 


24 


2,496 


19 


i»976 


31 


3.224 


21 


2.184 


108 


8 


864 


6 


648 


2 


216 


2 


216 


£ 


99 


9.832 


97 


9.508 


100 


9,912 


99 


9.760 


Average 




99-47 




98.02 




99.12 




98.59 



METHOD OF JUST PBRCBPTIBLB DIFFBRBNCBS. 251 

Table V. 

RjtSUI^T OF THS COMBINBD SBRIBS. 



ru 


Nt 


"■ r^k 


100 
104 
108 


8 
10 
45 

lOI 

118 

?i 


672 

880 

4,140 

9.696 

11.800 

9.880 

1.944 


2 


395 


39.012 


Obeenred result 
CompQted result 
Difference 


98.714 

98.305 

0409 



In a similar way one may find the just perceptible negative 
difference from the same series of experiments. For this pur- 
pose one first has to find the numbers of relative frequency for the 
< lighter ' judgments and the relative frequencies of judgments 
which are not * lighter ' judgments. From these numbers which 
are given in Table VI. one may find the probabilities Pthat a 

Table VI. 

PROBABII^ITIRS op ' LlOHTltK ' JUDGBCSNTS. 



r 


/ 


not-l 


^h 


/ 


nol-l 


84 

88 


P P P P 


fill 


100 
104 
108 


0.231 I 
0.0956 
0.0156 


0.7689 
0.9044 
0.9844 



certain comparison weight will be obtained as a determination 
of the just perceptible negative difference (see Table VII.). By 

Table VII. 

VaI,U9S op Ph POR THB DBTKRMINATION OP THS JUST PSaCBPTlBI^lt 

Nbgativb Dippbrbncs. 



108 


0.0156 


104 


0.0941 


100 


0.2058 


96 


0.3073 


IS 


0.2641 


0.0976 


84 


0.0145 


z 


0.9990 


R 


0.0010 



352 



F. M. URBAN, 



multiplying these probabilities with the intensity of the corre- 
sponding comparison stimuli one finds the number with which 
each stimulus is most likely to come down for the determination 
of the just perceptible negative difference, and by adding these 
numbers one finds this difference itself. Table VIII. gives 
the course of this computation and Table IX. shows how the 

Table VIII. 

VAlASnS OP rj\ ¥OtL THB DSTBRMIN ATION OP THB JUST PBRCBPTIBLB 
NBGATrvB DiPPBRBNCB. 





84 


1.3104 




88 


8.5888 




92 


24.2972 




96 


29.5008 




100 


20.5764 




104 


9.7864 




108 


1. 2180 




2 


95.2780 



computed result agrees with the -observations on the same sub- 
jects. This table shows how many times it happened that each 
stimulus was the greatest to be judged * lighter/ 1. e.^ how many 
times this stimulus was judged < lighter ' when all the stimuli of 
greater intensity were judged * heavier' or * equal.' The coin- 
cidence of the observed results with the computed results is very 
close as it is seen especially in Table X. The same experi- 
ments were made on six other subjects and the general outcome 
was invariably the same : the coincidence of the observed results 

Table IX. 

RBSXTI^TS op ObSBRVATIONS on THB JUST PBRCBPTIBLB NBGATIVB DiPPBR- 
BNCB IN Four Sbribs (IV a., I., III. and IV.) op 100 Exfbrimbnts Each. 







IVA. 


I. 


lU. 


IV. 


^k 


^. 


rt^k 


^k 


r^. 


^k 


r^» 


^* 


rjAT^ 


84 


2 


168 


I 


84 


2 


168 


4 


336 


88 


6 


528 


12 


1,056 


11 


1,144 


17 


1,496 


92 


30 


2,760 


23 


2,116 


2,576 


33 


1:^ 


96 


29 


2,784 


29 


2,784 


24 


2,304 


30 


100 


21 


2,100 


19 


1.900 


28 


2,800 


14 


1,400 


104 


10 


1,040 


13 


1,352 


I 


104 


2 


208 


108 


2 


216 


3 


324 


4 


432 






2 


100 


9.596 


100 


9,616 


100 


9,528 


100 


9.356 


Average 




95.96 




96.16 




95.28 




93.56 



METHOD OF JUST PERCEPTIBLE DIFFERENCES, 253 

with the theoretical results is very close in all the cases ; in some 
cases it is less, but in other cases it is considerably greater than 
in our example. 

Table X. 
Rbsui«t of thb Combikbd Sbribs. 



n 


N^ 


ruNu 


84 

88 

? 

100 
104 
108 


114 

112 

82 

26 

9 


756 

10,488 

10,752 

8,200 

2,704 

972 




400 


38,096 


Obserred result 
Computed resnlt 
Difference 


95.240 
95.278 

0.038 



We come to the conclusion that the experimental procedure 
which was described by Fechner and Wundt as the method of 
just perceptible differences, by Miiller and Titchener as the 
method of limits, is peculiarly well adapted for its purpose. It 
may be handled in such a way as to yield experimental data 
which can be worked out as well by the algorithm of the method 
of right and wrong cases as by that of the method of just per- 
ceptible difference despite the fact that the pairs of comparison 
stimuli are not presented in the order of their intensity which 
seemed to be an indispensable feature of this method. The 
theoretical basis of the method of just perceptible differences is 
the same as that of the error method, namely empirical deter- 
minations of the probabilities of judgments of different types on 
given differences of intensity. The result of the so-called 
method of just perceptible differences is that amount of differ- 
ence for which there exists the probability one half that it will 
be recognized.^ 

* The MS. of this article was received May 27, 1907. — En. 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE.* 

BY PROPBSSOR STBPHBN S. COLVIN, 
University of Illinois, 

In a brief article appearing in this Review last November, 
I pointed out what seemed to me to be certain essential charac- 
teristics of experience, emphasizing particularly the thought 
that experience is the ultimate essence of the universe, and as 
such is subject, and never object. Hence it follows that this 
most fundamental of all activities cannot be known, since we 
can know only objects. The experience of the moment is pure 
being, immediate and underived, while objects experienced are 
always conditioned being, mediate and derived ; yet only through 
these, can experience as such be described or comprehended. 

This experience, however, as subject,while thus distinguish- 
able from the objects of experience is not something separable 
from them. Without them it could not exist as experience. It 
is not something left over and above them, but becomes an ac- 
tuality only through its objects. Just as light is invisible where 
there are no objects for it to illuminate, so experience vanishes 
when the objects of experience are no more. Yet, although 
experience becomes actual only in its objects, it is not merely a 
logical shadow of these objects themselves. It actually is^ 
although itself it is incapable of being experienced. To give it 
a mere formal existence to satisfy the demands of thought 
would be absurd. It is more actual than any or all of its ob- 
jects. It belongs to another order of being, unknowable be- 
cause unmediated, final, undefined. 

Nothing, then, can be said of this experience except to deny 
to it certain qualities which its objects possess. Its objects flow 
and develop ; they are limited by temporal and causal categories. 
With them nothing is final; all is relative and incomplete. 

^Thia paper was read before the Western Philoeophical AMociation, 
Chicago, March 30, 1907. 

^54 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE. 255 

They have no values in themselves, but possess worth only in 
terms of their origin and goal. Their significance is acquired 
in the process of their development into and integration with 
other objects of experience. Experience as ultimate being, 
however, cannot be limited, or dependent on anything else for 
its value. If it possesses worth and significance, this cannot be 
because it leads anywhere, nor because it serves any ulterior 
purpose. If it has value that value must be ultimate and com- 
plete. 

Little satisfaction, however, can come from such negative 
determinations as these, and we might well let the whole matter 
drop here, were it not for the fact that among the objects of 
experience there exists a group which, although clearly derived 
and secondary in their nature, still in a way function for this 
unknowable, absolute experience, and come to take its place. 
This group of experienced objects which I refer to, forms the core 
of our objective existence. They reside largely in those sen- 
sations that are at the basis of instinctive expressions, that lend 
color and warmth to more external objects — they combine into 
emotions, and give the notion of the self as a feeling and active 
being; they are subconscious; they suggest a beyond; they 
point, as they vanish from a world of conscious objectivity to a 
realm of completed being which contains all and conditions 
reality. 

These subconscious experiences, then, functioning for an 
absolute into which they seem to recede and from which they 
appear to be derived, may be studied by the psychologist, an- 
alyzed and defined, and this analysis may be taken in a certain 
way as representing the pure, subjective experience of which 
they are symbols. These concrete experiences, however, should 
never be identified with the subject of experience, as is often 
the case. They are subjective only in a relative sense. Even 
the self-experience itself is an object among other objects and 
cannot be considered as an3rthing more than a phase or aspect 
of experience, certainly not the experience as such. 

This relatively immediate aspect of this group of objects of 
experience is, I take it, the psychological entity to which Pro- 
fessor James has given the name of * pure experience ' ; it is the 



256 STEPHEN 5. COLVIN. 

part which may be called simple sensation , mere feeling, unde- 
fined longing, objectless impulse. It is as such an abstraction, 
because it never exists in its purity, or if it does so exist it is 
essentially unknowable. This pure experience is that part of 
the total experience which is least objectified, that tends the 
least to develop ; that, however, as far as it does develop, gives 
up its original character, and passes into something quite dif- 
ferent. In so far as it remains undeveloped, however, it resists 
analysis and hence comes to be regarded as quite apart from the 
clear-cut objects of experience in the center of consciousness. 
Thus, vaguely defined and relatively unknowable, it has been 
the fruitful source of mysticism and absolutism in philosophy. 
Here is found, for example, Fitche's Absolute Ego, which re- 
fuses to reveal itself completely in the personal me, and of 
which no assertion can be made. 

Such, then, is this phase of objective experience which may 
be studied by the philosopher and psychologist as representative 
and symbolic of the unconditioned subject of experience, or ex- 
perience as such. One of its most striking and interesting 
characteristics is that it in a certain sense possesses an ultimate 
value. This core of our objective world does not readily pass 
over into the more fleeting objects to which it gives value and 
degrees of worth ; it tends to remain in itself and to be satisfied 
with itself. Its worth, like that of the absolute experience, is 
in the moment, non-temporal and in a sense eternal. Its value 
is simply because it is^ not because it grows into something else. 
It is not good or bad because it is pleasurable or painful. As 
experience, it is good ; it can be bad only in the sense that it is 
not as rich an experience as might be possible. The good of 
the universe from this standpoint is not summed up in the 
thought more pleasurable experience, but rather more experi- 
ence. Common sense recognizes this fact in often cherishing 
those experiences that have been full of pain and trouble because 
they have given glimpses of realities unknown to more mild and 
pleasurable states of mind. " To have loved and lost is better 
than never to have loved at all," for the experience itself with 
all its bitterness has an ultimate value because it is an ex- 
perience. 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE. 257 

In these days, however, we seem to be in danger of losing 
sight of this fact, not in our practice probably, but very possibly 
in our theorizing. We see this tendency to forget that imme- 
diate experience has a value in and for itself exemplified in the 
modern theory of utilitarian and prudential ethics, and in its 
companion theory, in intellectual philosophy, t^ventieth century 
pragmatism* 

This is perhaps somewhat striking when we remember that 
utilitarianism is the legitimate offspring of hedonism, which in 
making pleasure the norm of action, affirmed the ultimate value 
of experience. For pleasure is pleasure of the moment. It is 
the eat-drink-and-be-merry-for-tomorrow-we-die variety. Only 
when it began to rationalize pleasures, put some above others 
as more worthy or satisfying, did hedonism and modern utili- 
tarianism depart from its original position and seek values not 
given in the experience as such. 

The same seems to be true of pragmatism to an ex- 
tent. It also starts with immediate reality in the pure experi- 
ence of James, and seems clearly to reaffirm this principle 
of immanence in the doctrine that truth is satisfaction. My pur- 
pose here is not, however, to dwell on this phase of the incon- 
sistency, but rather to point out that in the rational development 
of these two philosophies they seem at times to have very thor- 
oughly forgotten the immanent basis from which they alike 
originated. To emphasize this latter point we may consider 
more definitely modern utilitarianism in some of its teachings. 

The essence of this doctrine may be summed up, I believe, 
in the statement of * voluntary general altruism ' (so called), that 
the end of virtuous striving is to secure the greatest good for 
the greatest possible number on the whole and in the long run. 
This demands that any act, if it be truly ethical, shall consider 
all the consequences that may flow from it, and thus justify or 
condemn itself. On the surface there seems to be no possible 
objection to such an ethical philosophy, except perhaps the 
difficulty of securing any satisfactory criterion on which to base 
an evaluation of conduct. This, however, is no real objection 
to the theoretical bearings of the system. If we look more 
closely, however, I believe we can detect an inherent weakness 



2S8 STEPHEN S. COLVIN, 

in the doctrine, which relates itself to the general topic under 
discussion in this paper, and which shows this school of ethical 
theorizers to have been better logicians than they were psycholo- 
gists. I can perhaps make my point clearer by a concrete 
example. 

Let us suppose that a person has fallen into the water and 
is in danger of drowning. Someone standing on the bank may 
have an impulse to jump in and attempt at the risk of his own 
life to rescue the other. Now if the man on the bank chances 
to be an utilitarian philosopher he must consider the conse- 
quences of his deed in terms of the general good. Perhaps the 
man that is drowning is of little value to the world, while the 
person who feels moved to risk his own life in order to save the 
unfortunate in the water may occupy an important place in the 
affairs of men. Then he should refrain from the attempt, since 
the greatest good demands his own safety be considered as of 
primary importance. This seems a simple case of logic, but I 
am persuaded that it is too simple. In the analysis something has 
escaped that is more valuable than that which has remained, an 
act of heroism and a heroic impulse have perished. Clearly this 
has worth — a worth arising not merely from the consequences 
that flow from heroic deeds, but a worth in itself. It is good to 
be heroic. As an ultimate experience heroism has value ; con- 
sidered in a mere timeless relationship it is good. 

So the utilitarian philosopher must revise his reasoning in 
this particular emergency. He must include in his calculations 
of ultimate benefits this impulse of heroism and find its place 
in his scale of values. He must see to it that it finds its due 
place. Now this readjustment may seem to satisfy the demands 
of the situation. Logically the system may be thus justified ; 
but psychologically such an attempt would prove an absurdity. 

For let us assume that the utilitarian philosopher attempts in 
the evaluation of his act to consider the worth of the impulse 
that prompts it ; let us suppose that he brings into his focal con- 
sciousness his instinctive heroism. In that moment the impulse 
vanishes, the instinct dies. No one can be heroic if he analyzes 
his heroism. As has already been pointed out it is impossible 
to bring these subconscious tendencies and feelings into atten- 
tion and have Ihem remain in their true value. 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE, 259 

Thus it happens that utilitarianism can never evaluate this 
element. It falls into an obvious dilemma. If the impulse is 
to exist, it cannot form a part of the ethical scheme, which thus 
becomes inadequate ; if rational analysis attempts to place it in 
the scale of values it disappears from experience. Its value as 
an ultimate reality precludes the possibility of its entering into 
the mediate world of rationalized and clearly objectified expe- 
rience. 

Of course it would be quite possible in retrospect to evaluate 
this impulse. This, however, would not give it a place in the 
realm of ethical values in the moment of their existence, and 
would not help, therefore, in the actual situations of life. 
Further this evaluation, in retrospect or in prospect, of impulses, 
tends to destroy these impulses as such. If we lay bare our 
affective life it becomes deadened and mechanical. The real 
enthusiasm, the spontaneity of expression, fail us; sympathy 
becomes mere prudence; courage, rational foresight; just 
indignation, calculating expediency, and so on. This is one 
of the greatest faults of the practical ethics of our present age \ 
over-analysis has often eliminated the ^ Schone Seele ' and even 
the * Categorical Imperative.' 

If we turn from a consideration of utilitarian ethics to utili- 
tarian epistemology we find a parallel difficulty. It is here in 
the noetic realm exactly on a level with hedonism in the conative 
realm; for hedonism says pleasure is the norm of goodness, 
pragmatism says that satisfaction is the measure of truth. So 
any pleasure that is genuine is good ; any satisfaction that is 
real is truth. Here is pure immanence, a genuine absolute, 
self-contained and unconditioned. Yet soon we find these two 
philosophies seeking to go outside this immanence to distinguish 
between pleasures and satisfaction in order to rationalize their 
view-points and organize their thinking. Naturally such a pro- 
cedure is necessary if a system is to be built up. My sole criti- 
cism here would be that their immanent starting point would 
never in itself have developed into such a system without the 
injection of something quite foreign to it in its original form. 
Hedonism and pragmatism can be attitudes of feeling and 
action, but never in their original forms ethics or epistemology. 



26o STEPHEN S. COLVIN, 

Although in the discussions on pragmatism which have 
appeared during the last few years truth has been often spoken 
of as a feeling of satisfaction, the pragmatist has not actually 
held to this description of the experience without soon going 
beyond it. Ethical utilitarianism was long ago forced to depart 
from its immanent starting point to evaluate goodness ; so, too, 
pragmatism has continually sought justification by measuring 
satisfaction in something outside of the immediate satisfaction. 
It has recognized that it could not consider satisfaction as such 
the badge of truth, but only that satisfaction which is based on 
wide experience and clear intelligence. Otherwise the satis- 
faction of the unthinking dogmatist would stand for a greater 
truth, generally speaking, than the more mild and less perma- 
nent contentment of the critical seeker after reality. Clearly 
this further evaluation is quite desirable and necessary. It is 
not, however, in accord with that aspect of pragmatic philosophy 
that has its basis in pure experience. 

In its growth pragmatism like utilitarianism has gone very 
far from a subjective basis ; it has become indeed the complete 
opposite of absolutism, whether subjective or objective. It is a 
philosophy of development, it has no finality, no abiding, no 
permanence. Its only universal truth is that there is no uni- 
versality to truth. What is good in the scheme of utilitarian 
ethics to-day may be bad tomorrow ; what is true in the fabric 
of utilitarian epistemology to-day may be false tomorrow. 

The parallelism between the two doctrines may be carried 
still farther. It has already been pointed out how the ethical 
utilitarian in attempting to evaluate conduct and to arrive at the 
greatest good, leaves out of necessity the very impulses from 
which good actions spring, which impulses are of themselves of 
final worth, not because they lead anywhere but because as 
immanent experience they have an ultimate value. So, too, 
intellectual utilitarianism in carrying out its principle that truth 
depends on relationships is compelled to ignore that factor 
which gives truth its final value, namely that sense of convic- 
tion that comes with every conclusion. This impulse to assert 
that the truth we arrive at is not a merely relative ai^air, and to 
believe that in some way it has a transcendent value is charac- 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE, 261 

teristic of all thinking that ends in a proposition. There is a 
feeling that in some way an abiding fact has been reached. 

Of course in the next moment, the thinker may find his 
assertions unsatisfactory and incomplete, and thought may 
develop toward a new resting place. However, in the moment 
that we have an experience of truth, we possess a feeling of con- 
viction. This conviction is quite at variance with the attitude 
that holds to relativity and incompleteness. This intellectual 
emotion does not thrive well under pragmatic logic. Enthu- 
siasm for truth does not tend to abound and spread over the 
earth, when it is made known that truth as such is not to be 
gained. The utilitarian who confidently asserts that a situation 
is true because it works (or because you can work it), is not apt 
to realize that the very reason why the situation works is because 
there goes with it a feeling of conviction. Action does not 
develop in uncertainty. To hesitate is here as elsewhere to be 
lost. The feeling of certainty is necessary but is not easily in- 
cluded in the pragmatic scheme ; here it tends to lose its instruc- 
tive force and immanent value ; for like the tendency toward 
right action, this impulse toward true action vanishes as soon as 
it is forced into the world of partial and conditioned values. 
The instinct of certainty will not work if it is valued only as a 
thing to be worked ; but, since it is at the basis of all workable 
propositions, nothing will work without it being present; yet no 
pragmatist may say, — **Go to, I need this certainty, in order 
to have my situation work out truly, therefore I will possess 
myself of this feeling in order that I may work it to my practical 
advantage." And even if the pragmatist could accomplish this 
impossibility ; even if by such a means he could make his situa- 
tions work as best satisfy his demands, he would have failed to 
have gained that ultimate experience of truth, which knows no 
relativity in the moment of the experience and which in the scale 
of human values has a final and abiding worth. 

Such a humanizing experience can never come to the phi- 
losopher nor scientist who believes that the truth he now pos- 
sesses, at this moment, is merely a relative affair, and true only 
in the sense that it fits temporarily into a scheme of workable 
relations. As in ethics speculation on a moral impulse helps to 



36a STEPHEN S. COLVIN, 

destroy it, so in logic reflection on the instinct of certainty tends 
to remove all certainty, and thus to hinder intellectual progress. 
The result is the same in either case, a moral or an intellectual 
sophistry. 

To sum up the foregoing: 

Ultimate experience as such cannot be known, since only 
objects can be known; yet such ultimate experience is an 
actuality. Of it as such nothing can be said, except to deny to 
it the characteristics of the objects of experience. There* is, 
however, in every experience a group of objects that function in 
a sense for the ultimate experience (the subject of the objects 
experienced), and which may be taken as symbolic of the pure 
experience that does not reveal itself. One of the most im- 
portant characteristics of this relatively subjective and immediate 
aspect of experience is that it seems to have an ultimate value 
and finality in itself. In modern times two philosophic creeds 
have arisen out of this immanent experience, the one utili- 
tarianism and the other pragmatism. Both have in a sense 
assumed the validity of this immanent experience, the one in 
the doctrine of pleasure as the ultimate end of striving, the other 
in the assertion that satisfaction is the badge of truth ; yet in the 
development of their philosophic beliefs both have departed at 
once from the immanent point of view, thus ignoring their origin. 
Further, these two systems in their evaluation of goodness and 
truth have not taken account of the goodness that is good in and 
for itself, and the truth that is self-contained and unconditioned. 
They have in other words, disregarded the ultimate worth of that 
part of our experience that is relatively subjective and which ordi- 
narily does not enter into the flux of a constantly changing 
world. 

The true point of view seems to be that there are elements 
in our experience that have what may be termed a final value 
in the moment of that experience, that point back to no condi- 
tioning reality, nor forward to a growing system of facts. 
Here are found impulses and feelings that lie at the basis of 
our moral and intellectual judgments and give all experience its 
significance, not only because of that which is to follow, but 
also because of that which actually is. These impulses and 



THE ULTIMATE VALUE OF EXPERIENCE, 263 

feelings are necessary for our right living and true thinking. 
They give a final worth to action and an abiding value to truth. 
An utilitarian philosophy should evaluate them, and find a place 
for them in its world of contrasts and relations. This, how- 
ever, it is singularly incapable of doing, since when it attempts 
such an evaluation the very being of these impulses vanishes. 
Thus there must always be an inadequacy in this philosophy. 
It can never give more than a partial view of the world because 
it ignores one of its most essential constituents. On the other 
hand, an intuitive ethics and an absolute logic, while not free 
from errors, both consider the immanent aspect of experience in 
which these impulses are found. Here a moral impulse and an 
intellectual thrill are given their worth. Rightly or wrongly, 
too, they are held to function for a pure experience, outside of 
the objective flow of consciousness, that contains absolute worth 
and abiding truth. Here is the psychological basis for a 
philosophy of permanent values and transcendent significance. 



ON TRUTH.' 

BY PROFESSOR J. MARK BALDWIN, 
Johns Hopkins University, 

I. The Meaning of Correctness. 

Our discussion of truth may be considerably abbreviated in 
view of the preceding genetic discussions ;' for the lines of pro- 
gression converge very plainly to a consistent point of view. It 
has become evident that the progress of mind is marked by the 
differentiation of control spheres into which the classified and I 

dependable and typical modes of experience fall. All this has | 

been traced in terms of the development of * dualisms.' We 
find certain great psychic dualisms developing and undergoing | 

constant transformation and restatement with the development ' 

of the mental life as a whole. | 

Further, it is simply a necessity of this development of 
dualism, as between the inner and outer control factors, that ! 

there should arise modes of what we have called • conversion.'* 
This is necessary since the progress of consciousness is toward 
setting up its constructions as under mediate control, that is as 
relatively remote from the original experiences with their direct 
coefficients. The entire development of inner control is, as we 
have seen, toward the more and more independent construction 
of a content of presentation and thought, which has its reference 
however back through some process of mediation to the sphere 
in which it is to find its direct confirmation again. Images are 
read as memories, and not fancies, according as they are converti- 
ble into experiences of the perceptual type. Private experiences 
make good only as they are convertible in turn into the corre- 
sponding experiences of other persons besides. Thoughts arc 

» Being part of Chap. XIII. of Thought and Things or Genetic Logic, vol. 
I., 'Experimental Logic*, somewhat modified to make reference to criticisms 
of vol. I., by Dewey and Moore (see the * Comment * below in this issue, p. 297)- 
*See Chap. XI. of vol. I. of Thought and Things, 
^Ibid., Vol. I., Chap. IV., JJ3, 4. 

264. 



ON TRUTH, 265 

true and valid when they find confirmation in some more direct 
mode of experience that they are true to. 

We have, therefore, thfe rise of two modes of meaning — 
one that of mediation, and the other that of lack or failure of 
mediation. The fact of mediation is just that of relative refer- 
ence to the further and more direct control which the given con- 
struction mediates. The lack or failure of mediation, while 
not a negative thing in itself, yet arises from the same motive as 
that whose positive requirement is mediation. 

Now we have found it necessary to recognize at least two 
great cases of outright mediation — cases in which the evident 
value and r61e of a construction is to present an original con- 
trol and conserve its force, at the same time that it is made rel- 
atively remote and mediate. These typical cases are those to 
which we have already given the character of * mediate control' ; 
namely, memory, taken in the broad sense of reproductive im- 
agery, and thought. Memory is a context that mediates per- 
ceptual control by possible conversion into it; this we have 
shown in the three great cases of the physical, the social or 
personal, and the merely temporal (the memory of events).* 
Thought, too, is a context set up in a way that mediates the 
control of the spheres from which its materials come, whatever 
that may be. 

Here we may add, that to deny this character to these two 
modes of construction — whatever else we may deny of them — 
is to destroy them, as the modes of psychic meaning that they 
are. To make a memory inconvertible into direct experience is 
to make it no longer a memory, but a fugitive or fanciful image, 
an illusion, a dream ; for such states are differentiated from 
memories just in that they lack this mediation of the coefficients 
of perceptual or other simpler control. The character of mem- 
ory, then, that makes it what it is in the actual progression of 
cognition, is its correctness^ its accuracy, its way of * matching 
up ' with the experiences whose control the memory mediates. 

So it is with thoughts. Their first and essential character, 
as a system of meanings set up in a mind, is this : they have a 
content that is not capricious, fugitive, disconnected, but one 

'Ibid., Vol. I., Chap. IV. 



266 J. MARK BALDWIN, 

that mediates the sphere of control from which the contents were 
drawn. Thoughts are correct or incorrect, according as they 
are referable or not to something or other in a world in which 
there is a matching with the simpler contents whose control is 
thus mediated. The correctness or incorrectness of memories 
we call their * accuracy ' or inaccuracy ; that of thoughts we 
call their • truth ' or falsity. 

I use the word * match ' deliberately, only to discard it later 
on for the case of truth, since it is actually applicable to mem- 
ory, and has suggestions that are valuable throughout In 
memory there is an actual image, a sort of visual or other pic- 
ture, constructed on the lines of the original perceptual content, 
and we can often bring it up in mind so definitely that the real 
thing can be compared with it, and the details actually matched 
one upon the other. I know when my memory leaves out a 
note, when my visual image leaves out a feature, so soon as I 
have the actual tune or shape reproduced for me, so that I can 
directly match the two. 

In memory, the need of correctness is evident enough. 
Action in the larger sense, on the part of the knower, depends 
upon the accuracy of the image that stands for the actual thing. 
The individual acts upon the thing ; then he acts similarly on 
the memory of the thing ; this he can do because the memory 
has this prime character of mediating the thing. 

Admitting the analogy between the cases of memory and 
thought, we may then suggest for memory a pair of questions 
that are much discussed with reference to thought. Are the 
memories, we may ask, correct because we can act on them in- 
stead of on the things, or is the proper account the reverse — that 
we can act on memories instead of the things because they are 
correct f In reply, I should say that the latter is the proper way 
to put the case; since, while we cannot act successfully on 
what is not correct, we can establish correctness without impli- 
cating the motive to the specific sort of action. That is to say, 
granted that action is implicated, and that it is necessarily carried 
out in actually securing the matching that confirms the correct- 
ness, still it is not genetically the motive to the acceptance of 
the memory item as correct. The same is true of truth, in my 



ON TRUTH ^ 267 

opinion, and so it may be well to examine the case of memory 
more fully here. 

Suppose we take a case recently used by others * in advo- 
cating the opposite view. One is lost in the woods, and has a 
* thought ' — in this case it would be largely a memory — of the 
way to get out. Of all the possible plans of direction, turnings, 
etc., he acts on the one that seems ^ right.' He comes out at 
his home. Now what has constituted the correctness, or truth, 
of his plan ? — why is the thought of the situation on which he 
has acted to be labelled * correct ' ? 

The * action theory ' — so to call it briefly — says the plan is 
true or correct because it has led to successful action : but for 
his success in getting out, his plan would have been false. 
The essence of the correctness or truth of the thought or mem- 
ory is to be found, then, in its being a plan of successful action. 

But certain difficulties with this are so evident that they * fly 
up and strike one in the face.' Suppose we ask, how the case 
would have differed if the man had not got home ; would he 
not still have used the thought as a plan of action? Yes, it is 
said, but not successfully. Then the critical point is not merely 
the action, but the success of the action. Now what is the 
mark of success of the action? — how does the man know his 
action is successful? The only answer is, by what he sees 
or otherwise finds before him when he recognizes the familiar 
surroundings ; that is, by the perceptual experiences found to be 
what the thought or memory presented in image. Without this 
recognition or identification, action is vain. The test then is a 
perceptual experience fulfilling^ the details of the plan that 
guided his action. Instead then of the action establishing or 
guaranteeing the correctness, it is the correctness alone that 
justifies the specific form of action. In other words, we are 
correct in our first proposition made just above, namely, that 
action cannot get to its appropriate goal without the preliminary 
presumption that the thought that guides it is correct. Accu- 
racy of imagery and truthfulness of thought are the conditions 

iRusscU and Dewey, /(?«r«. of I%iios., III., 599, and IV., 201. 
'That is, establishing, confirming, realizing, in the sense of giving the same 
•contents vdth the perceptual coefficients. 



a68 J. MARK BALDWIN. 

of the substitution of these constructions for the original things, 
which as guides to action they mediate. If the man fails to 
recognize his home when he sees it, the plan may still be true 
though to him his action has not been successful. 

The < success' necessary, therefore, does not attach to 
acting thus or so, but to the mediating of the original physical 
control for the individual's experience, or for a larger social ex- 
perience with which the individual's normally agrees. 

Now let us take up the second statement, to wit, that correct- 
ness may be established without the motive to specific action. 
Suppose a school boy is put to drawing a map, and draws one 
that the teacher pronounces correct or truthful, using only the 
data of his history and geography books, together with verbal 
hints and instructions from others. Wherein consists the < cor- 
rectness ' of the map? We are told by the action theory that it 
is correct or true because one might well act upon such a map, 
in going say from Baltimore to Washington . Very good, but is this 
the reason the boy made this map just what it is in its details ; 
is this his motive for accepting the details as correct? Suppose 
instead of doing what his teacher told him to, he had placed 
Washington north of Baltimore instead of south. Apart from 
any experience he has had, any promptings to action on his 
part, that would do just as well. What then has determined 
him, what has motived his actual construction in respect to cor- 
rectness, what has guided and controlled the making of the map? 
Evidently the fact that he did what he was told to doy what aU 
his copies required^ getting what, in other words, could be can- 
verted into experience of a different cognitive order — in this 
case into the reported experience of other persons. AU this is 
what we have called * secondary conversion.* It accepts the per- 
sonal control of another person's thought as mediated by one's 
own present thought. This makes the thing accurate for one- 
self. 

Here the successful mediation of a socially common control 
has established the correctness of the personal thought, apart 
from any further mediation of the actual physical control in the 
country represented in the map. 

Suppose again, instead of making a map, the boy is to give 



ON TRUTH, 369 

an account of a historical scene, or to narrate a series of past 
events. Here, as we have seen, the events, the transitive parts 
of the thought context, are fer se subject to no further con- 
firmation than that given by concurrent testimony.' It is the 
larger social control that mediates the by-gone events as true. 
The truth is tested by its social acceptability — its corroboration 
by testimony, written records, etc. — the process of verification 
being that of secondary conversion into a recondite context of 
original testimony. In some vague sense, we might say that 
this could be tested by action ; it does have, as all knowledge 
has, its following, its dynamogeny of active impulses, always 
proper to the thought ; but the motive to the acceptance of the 
result as correct is not that of doing something or going some- 
where, but that of matching the details of one person's thought 
with those of another's. 

We may put this a little differently in order to sharpen the 
essential issue. To act on a plan is to set up the plan as an 
end for realization. The action is merely a means to this end. 
Successful action is action that gets the end thus set up — no 
longer as mere presentation but as fact. Now how is one to 
know when he gets it? — certainly this confidence is not given 
in the mere action, in the means. It comes only in the realization 
of the thing, the something of fact that the construction repre- 
sented, the fulfilment that the end prophesied. The correctness, 
the truth, then, is the end-realizing character of the presenta- 
tion set up. 

These points seem to me very plain in the case of the control 
mediated by memory. I say to you that your memory of this 
or that is correct or incorrect. Or course, you can use it for 
practical purposes, to get the original things, if it is correct ; 
and you can take the risk if it is not correct. Your justification 
in either case resides in your acceptance of its right to mediate 
a sort of experience called fact, reality, or existence.* 

^ Apart from the remote possibility of tracing out physical effects — sub- 
stantive changes —following upon the event. 

'It may be said in objection that by action is not meant alone the gross 
activity of going to or handling things, but also those functional processes of 
attention, etc., by which the presentation is constituted what it is. < What is 
true ' is only another name, it may be said, for * what is/ under these determin- 



270 / MARK BALDWIN. 

We may observe too, before going further with the discussion 
of truth, that correctness is independent of the mode of origin, 
and the degree of validity for theory, of the original control 
meanings thus mediated by conversion processes. However con- 
sciousness got the meaning * physical control,' and however 
there arose the secondary or mediate controls by which this and 
others are mediated, still the relative modes remain what they 
are in their respective progressions. Given a process that has 
memories, then the entire place and rdle of that mode would be 
destroyed if there were no conversion of it — no mediation into it 
of the coefficients already made up in the earlier processes. 
There are in the progress of consciousness ways of returning 
to a relative immediacy; this appears in the play and sem- 
blant modes ; but the character of such modes is shown just 
in this to be different from that of memory- : their differentia does 
not consist in relative correctness and incorrectness. They are 
not held to the original dualisms as memory is. Memory has 
its justification just in the relative correctness with which it 
mediates the coefficients belonging to the worlds of fact or 
existence. 

In an important sense this is true also for thought ; it mediates 
but does not banish dualisms. Yet the processes whereby the 
mediating control of thought or reflection arises are so complex 
and their subsequent meanings so legislative and seemingly 
independent, that the discussion becomes very much more 
complicated. 

Before going on, however, I may point out a distinction that 
sums up the opposing interpretations suggested above, and shows 
itself sharply in the two current uses of the term < control.' As 

ing processes. This recurs below where we find the ' truth ' to be just the 
' what is ' when the ' is ' is the control in which 'the what ' is acknowledged. 
Bat there our analysis is the same as here (as is anticipated in Vol. I., Chap. III.)» 
i. ^., we find that the control sphere is determined by coefficients of various 
sorts of existence and is not resolvable into the motor processes that operate 
with and upon them. As soon as there is a control meaning at all it is a dualis- 
tic or pluralistic control meaning. There is no valid sense in which these co- 
efficients can be caUed ' habits ' or ' motor complexes '; for habit belongs at the 
pole of ' inner ' as over against external control ; and conflict of habits or of 
habitual selves is within the entire inner sphere that encompasses them (as in 
the larger synergetic process of attention). 



ON TRUTH. 271 

used in my work it means any coefficient or character of a 
content that classifies and delimits it, giving it a sphere in which 
it is or might be -present as itself. We may say of any presenta- 
tion that it is or might be present in its proper class or sphere 
of presence or existence. Now on this view the development of 
knowledge is by the formation and development of these spheres 
of control ; and however far away from the original control 
coefficients a representative or ideal content may be, it still has 
the meaning that gives it its assignment to that and no other 
control. From this point of view knowledge develops within 
the distinctions of control ; there is development of knowledge 
in idea or thought only through the original controls mediated 
by these modes — as we have iust seen to hold of memory. 

Calling this the theory of knowledge through control there 
is a variant upon it that may be called the theory of control 
through knowledge — the * control ' of action, and through it 
of experience, by means of the mediating context of thought. 
This is, as I understand it, the * control' of the Studies in Log- 
ical Theory and other works of the so-called Chicago school.^ 
It is control of a personal sort, management — considered actively^ 
— or effective handling of the details of experience through 
knowledge, reflection, etc. This distinction is, in the sequel, 
important.^ Both phenomena are real, * knowledge through 
control ' and * control through knowledge ' ; but here it may be 
easily seen that to the latter theory control is what is to the former 
* inner' or personal control, one of the sorts of control in general 
found actual by the former. The * control through knowledge ' 
is a concept of this active functional relation between self and its 
world of experience ; that of * knowledge through control ' is 
one of logical or content relation between different modes of 
experience. 

It is of the utmost importance, in my opinion, that this dis- 
tinction should be clearly understood. We may, therefore, 

' I hope here and below I am not again misrepresenting Professor Dewey. On 
the whole, though unfortunate, such experiences are frequent, generally mutual. 
The writers mentioned accept so much that I also hold to, that it is desirable 
that we keep on ' discussing.' My use of ' control * goes back to my address on 
' Selective Thinking ' given in December, 1897. 

*It is developed in detail in a later chapter of Vol. II. of Thought and 
nin^s. 



27^ y. MARK BALDWIN, 

seek to sharpen the line of cleavage between the two concep- 
tions — * control of knowledge by facts/ and * control of facts or 
experience through knowledge' — by showing the fundamental 
way in which the present day distinctions are really based upon 
their implicit recognition.* 

Let us take a detached point of view for the consideration 
of the context of thought or ideas. Here is a set of presenta- 
tions hanging before us for interpretation. We may consider it 
in the greatest detachment simply for itself, as having its own 
organization and relationships ; so considered it is the content of 
formal logic. Formal logic strips thought of its references, its 
implications, both of material truthfulness and also of worth for 
appreciation. For it, inference is purely a matter of relation, 
whether or not it be about something true or something good. 
There is then a neutrality as to further intent in both aspects ; 
the ideal of such a discipline is pure validity. For it thoughts 
are subjects and predicates and nothing more. 

Now it is evident that there are two ways of leaving formal 
logic behind. So soon as we ask what further meaning may 
attach to such a system of thoughts, we come upon the two 
conceptions just distinguished : either the thoughts represent and 
so mediate a control in which they are true, or they represent 
and mediate a mode of appreciation which they ful61. In the 
one case, there is a recognition of a world of facts to be 
acknowledged or extended ; in the other, there is the intent to 
find worth or value in experience in and through the thoughts. 
By the mediation of control we have the development of the 
world of facts, for which the thought is instrumental. Here we 

' I give this of conne as my way of describing the difference of view be- 
tween the two conceptions, not ' saddling * it on anyone else. I cannot accept 
Dewey's account of our difference without modification — an account that makes 
my point of view ' epistemological ' and his own ' logical ' (Joum, ofPkilas.^ May 
9i 'o7> P* 255). For while my own is epistemological, recognizing a dualism of 
self and not-self meanings, his view, while, as having only the dualism of idea 
and fact in view, it can be called logical, yet as theory of control and reconcilia- 
tion of the terms of the dualism, it is in its implications more epistemological ; 
for it implicates control entirely of the inner or active sort. It postulates in other 
words a closed inner process, thus making the entire movement of experience 
'inner.* To do this is I think to mutilate thought by banishing the * outer' 
control while clinging to the ' inner ' ; but the position is still epistemological. 



ON TRUTH, 273 

have experimental or instrumental logic — the science of the 
control of thought through facts ^ or the extension of knowledge 
as truth. 

This science may be looked at in two ways according as 
facts or thoughts are made primary. We may consider the 
motive to be the establishment of thought by appeal to fact, 
giving * experimental logic,' as a method of the proving of 
thoughts ; or we may consider the motive to be the establish- 
ment of facts in thought, when we have the science of the 
development of knowledge as controlled by facts : this is epis- 
temology. We may with confidence write down both instru- 
mental logic and epistemology as sciences of * truth' — the 
sciences of the control of thought through facts. Facts of any 
world, is meant, of course; and facts are experiences of an 
original order of control coefficient. 

But now in contrast to this set of motives and the sciences 
that issue from them, there is the other great way in which the 
context of thought has meaning. The neutrality of purely 
formal logic may be departed from not alone in the way of 
establishing truth by the control of thought by facts ; there is 
the other departure from neutrality found in the intent to fulfil 
personal purpose and interest. The system of thoughts is now 
set up not merely for discovery or confirmation; it is made 
means of the fulfilment of ends. All the selective and pur- 
posive motives to individuation come up in the further reading 
of the context preferentially and so to speak * axiologically.'* 
The mediation of thought is now not the control by fact and the 
embodiment of truth, but the acknowledgment of worth. Truth 
is now means to satisfaction. All the interests besides the 
theoretical come into their own ; and the theoretical interest 
itself appears as a personal and selective motive. 

This is what, I take it, such phrases of current discussion as 
* control of experience,' * control of a situation,' * dealing with 
things profitably,' * readjusting conflicting habits' — phrases 
used by the new school of theorists of the instrumental order — 
really come to. Their emphasis is on the management of situa- 

'The temi 'aziology ' was suggested, I think, by W. M. Urban for the sci- 
ence of worth-predicates as contrasted with predicates of fact. 



274 /. AfARK BALDWIN. 

tions, the manifulation of experience, through the use of a 
context of knowledge. Knowledge enables us to cope with the 
worlds of things, facts, experiences, situations, to get good;^ and 
we use knowledge as means to an end. The inner control 
factors — habit, attention, disposition, interest, constituting the 
self — by which the whole movement is motived, are left 
strangely unexplained. These are not logical terms ; they arc 
affective-conative contents. 

This it is evident is the sort of mediation supplied to the 
factor of inner control by the context set up. The ideas are 
said to guide conduct, the knowledge to become practical in- 
sight, the concrete situation to yield to the interpretation and 
use that thought suggests. All these expressions deal with the 
relation of the reflective to the concrete, of the idea to the fact; 
but as soon as we use the word control with reference to it, we 
see that the *self ' of judgment — the selective, purposive, set of 
factors — is the control that is mediated. By the knowledge, 
the insight, the facts are interpreted, the judgment guided, the 
self factor, whatever its constitution, determined and advanced. 
There is then the control of facts through knowledge, by the 
inner synergetic process that counts as * self.'^ The motive is 
the personal one of reaching an end ; a meaning is set up as a 
desire, a remote worth, and the ideas are accepted as means. 

Even the phrase * solving a problem * used most often by 
these writers invites this criticism ; for the * solution ' of the 
problem is in terms of ' readjusted habit,' ' successful action,' 
etc., all factors of just what I recognize as advancement of 
• inner control ' or * self.' Such a * solution ' actually gives an 
expansion of self-feeling, and a sharpened objective plan of 
the truthful facts ; it is dualistic to the core, 

2. What Truth is. 
We may introduce the discussion of the mode of truth as such 
by asking what would be necessary to constitute an active con- 

^Thifl is the suppressed premise of the whole theory. It substitates 
'good ' for 'true,' and fails to recognize the nature of the inner control, for 
which the good is ' good.* As soon as this is allowed, the correlative dualistic 
term, the ' external ' control, returns also, and the problem is the epistemo- 
logical one of truth — of * knowledge through control.* 

*The organized self oyer against impulse, partial habit, etc 



ON TRUTH. 2ys 

trol process — a mode of action — as the sole criterion or 
mark of truth, and then ask whether thought or reflection 
realizes such a requirement. In this way, we throw into relief 
the differences between the two points of view already spoken 
of and secure the added interest that comes from having current 
theories in mind. 

If then we ask what would be necessary to banish the re- 
quirement of correctness, considered as agreement or corre- 
spondence with some control read as external or foreign to the 
process, our answer would be — simply the banishing of the 
coefficients of externality. The question then would come back 
to one which we asked and answered in the flrst volume of our 
work — the question as to whether the active dispositional 
processes could be conceived as entirely making up, and hence 
as fully fulfilled in, the psychic object, apart from data 
having coefficients requiring reading as * external.' This we 
found to be unrealizable for consciousness such as it is; for 
the existence both of things of the physical order, and of per- 
sons apart from oneself, requires the operation of the motives 
that mature in the mind-body dualism. In other words, the 
dualism of existences, as meanings of separate control, forbids 
a purely active determination of things; and replica of the 
things — the image-objects — together with the variations in 
the correctness of these latter, are meanings that testify to the 
truth of this. Now, how is it with the higher mediation, that 
of truth, in which the terms of the dualism are those of reflection 
or thought? 

It must be admitted that we find here remarkable progress in 
the sort of mediation which would banish the external . control 
factor, and so tend to reduce all controls finally to one, and that 
the control of active inner process. This aspect of the devel- 
opment may be spoken of first, before other motives are 
taken up. 

Two great movements are to be noted : one that whereby 
the control of reflection as mode of inner experience is consti- 
tuted, and the other that whereby the individual judgment be- 
comes * synnomic,' that is, competent without further control 
from that of other persons. Let us look at these two move- 
ments in turn. 



276 /. MARK BALDWIN. 

The process whereby thought, functioning in acts of judg- 
ment, becomes a mode of mediate control, has already been 
described. It establishes a heightened and unified conscious- 
ness of self, as inner control function, which is in a dualism 
with all the objects of thought. These objects mediate the 
inner control which the self in judging exercises over the mate- 
rial it deals with. On the other hand, this inner control process 
arises by a unification of those more partial factors which rep- 
resent the inner* aspects of prelogical meanings. There is, 
therefore, a redistribution of the objective meanings also, their 
resetting as outer pole of the dualism of subject-object. The 
question now urgent is as to whether the original controls by 
which the objects of thought were set up and recognized as 
outer, etc., are now in any sense still operative, when the whole 
context is made one of thought. 

There is, in fact, from the point of view of the personal life- 
process, no motive that arrests the original control factors, so 
that we can say that they are banished. The objects of 
thought, like those of memory, seem to require the sort of ful- 
filment, in fact of some kind, that the objects of memor}** do. 
Yet we find certain complications now for the first time present. 
For whereas the objects of memory were in a sense Miftable' 
from the original things they reported, and also on occasion 
actually lifted from them ; yet this was merely an incident to 
the essential fact that whether thus separated or not, the two 
series dovetail together, submitting, on occasion, to all sorts of 
vicariousnesses and substitutions without confusion. 

In the redistribution found in reflection there is no such 
continuity with fact. The mode of inner control through 
thoughts establishes itself in a much more radical way. The 
contents are not only < lifted ' from things and constituted as 
a different mode of meanings, having a way of mediating the 
original control, but this is done by a mode in which the whole 
dualism is established in the inner world. The dualism is one of 
conscious reflection. In its mediation of the original existence 
spheres it sets its own form of dualism — a new and character- 
istic one. The question at issue now is whether, by becoming 
a svstem both of whose terms are within the one inner control, 



ON TRUTH. 277 

thought loses the intent to refer to spheres of control other than 
itself. Put in terms of action this would read : granting that 
the control processes of the inner world are active — motived by 
purposes, ends, satisfactions, efforts, etc. — can this set of con- 
trol processes find fulfilment in the mere contents it sets up, or 
must there be still a recognition of the external ? If the former, 
then any * truth ' attaching to these contents would be derived 
from their relative worth as fulfilling personal purposes and in- 
terests. That is, there would be no necessity of going to a 
sphere of fact, to any sphere of simpler perceptual or memory 
process, to secure further fulfilment. 

Only on such a supposition, I conceive, can an action theory 
of truth be put through — or any theory distinctively pragmatic. 
It would require the elimination of transcendence as meanings 
the loss of the external meaning of objects, that is, of any con- 
trol-reference beyond the set of ideas themselves. Only if 
ends were fully fulfilled in thoughts and thoughts had no further 
meaning than to serve as ends — only in such complete coinci- 
dence of thoughts and ends would further reference be unnec- 
essary as corrective or control of either. 

Now thought does not accomplish this — no more than does 
memory. Thoughts do not satisfy purpose ; purpose runs up 
against hard facts foreign to it. <^ If wishes were horses the 
beggars would ride." Interest does not stay with thoughts ; it 
seeks fulfilments in various external-seeming modes. The 
thought system mediates these remote controls; it does not 
banish them. 

The struggle of mind, however, to do what the pragmatists 
attribute to it, is interesting and pathetic. It develops a system 
of meanings that approximate and personate the completely 
* lifted ' and self-contained. 

Yet it cannot finally absorb all contents as only ends of action, 
completely dominated by processes of inner control, and rest 
with that. Not so. It marks its failure indeed by falling into 
the diametrically opposite extreme. It aims to banish dualism 
of controls and so suggests the effacement of * self.' For it 
develops the neutrality of a purely theoretical interest ^ and sets 
up a theoretically valid system of thoughts — a system that is 



378 / MARK BALDWIN, 

valid not because it can be acted upon, nor because it is true to 
anything else, but because, simply and only because, it is 
reasonable and self-consistent. 

We have seen this motive in operation, and have described 
it as the prime and only progression proper to thought.^ It b 
all the while recognizing the necessity of control from fact. It is 
inductive, tentative, experimental, schematic, quantitative, ex- 
istential. But in the very bosom of this recognition of foreign 
controls, it hits upon the contradictions and limitations in the 
body of its data that motive the validity of thought proper. 
The whole, set up as identical and self-consistent, then floats 
off in the ocean of logical form as such. Its validities take 
the place of former inductive confirmations; its relevancies 
establish themselves within its own body ; its beliefs propagate 
themselves in the form of syllogistic conclusions ; and a body 
of implications is born that dispenses with any further control 
than just its own constitution as a system of related meanings. 

Now what has happened? It is clear that something impor- 
tant enough has happened. It would seem that thought, the 
system of implications, has won a victory. The flow of valid 
relation would seem to take the place both of the concrete ap- 
peal to action, and of its dualistic mess-mate, the matching of 
thought by fact in a world of foreign control. Personal interest 
has become theoretical, and a body of logical validities has 
arisen to fulfil this personal interest. 

This movement is analogous to the similar swing of the pen- 
dulum — just where we should expect it — in the mode of 
imagery, where the same two factors work out their respec- 
tive places on a lower plane. Mere memory is everything, fancy 
is worthless ; memory is the thing to be interested in, it guaran- 
tees correctness and action ; it reports what actually is and must 
be. Therefore let us rule out preference, personal interest, 
the vagaries of desire ; let us recognize the ' is,' and banish the 
vain < might be.' So here also ; thought sets up a system of 
relations that become for it the valid simply by being linked uf 
together as they are. 

But this of course is not jinaL Personal desire, purpose, 

»In chmpten before this {Thought and Things, Vol. H., Part in., ChAps. 
X.ff.). 



ON TRUTH. 279 

action, * find themselves' in the very process by which theoretical 
interest asserts its exclusiveness. A new dualism arises, one of 
a self that thinks over against the system it thinks about. The 
selections for action are not annulled even when the dictations 
of fact seem to be. Thought even when most abstract is after 
all a system of acceptances, beliefs, personal satisfactions ; and 
the demands of such intent are charged into the abstract forms 
of the syllogism. A whole world of valuation comes to find its 
embodiment in the system of thoughts. Thoughts are thus 
made ends in turn, just as before, and the external controls, the 
things of fact, are reestablished for the * realization ' of those ends* 

We have to recognize, therefore, two general movements in 
this progression of truth. First, there is the development of 
validity pure and simple taking the place of the inductive match- 
ing and conversion processes of external control. And second, 
there is the persistent return of the control of fact through the 
demands of action and appreciation in all the matters of concrete 
life. Both of these are in so far irreducible. The satisfaction 
of active tendencies reasserts fact, while the demands of abstract 
validity tend to mediate truth in a system of static relations. 

In short, if things were different, if the life of purpose and 
action did find complete fulfilment in thought, so that thought 
had no further reference than just this fulfilment, then such a 
meaning as * truth * would be impossible. The * valid ' too 
would have no meaning. The * good ' would take their place. ^ 
Thought fulfils desire and desire arouses and propagates 
thought. There would be no further question as to the exis* 
tence of the desired in any realm other than or beyond thought. 
For to suppose such a realm would open just the question of a 
sphere other than that of purpose or action, giving something 
beyondyZ?r the true to be true to. 

I think we may safely conclude, therefore, in this matter of 
the birth of personal judgment as a control mode, that while it 
seems to show the possibility of bringing all the objects of 
thought under a unifying principle of control by self, and so to 
subject the whole content of reflection to the rule of personal 
action and purpose ; yet it works out differently when we con- 

^Opening James' Pragmatism^ which has just come to my table, I find this 
heading in the Table of Contents "Truth is a good, like health^ wealth, etc.'^ 



a8o /. MARK BALDWIN. 

aider the actual result. Over against the self of control there is 
developed a system of implication which is universal, self-con- 
sistenty and relatively independent of the processes of individual 
control and judgment. With the growing personalizing of the 
knowing process comes the depersonalizing of the content of 
thought. And thereupon there arises the new mode of inner as- 
sertion through purpose and appreciation. 

From another point of view, also, we reach results of some 
interest — the point of view of the * community,' the common 
meaning, of thoughts. This introduces a somewhat neglected 
but withal important set of considerations. 

We found it necessary, it will be remembered,^ to recognize 
as attaching to all judgment two modes of intent both of which 
come under the general character of * community ' ; there is 
community in the two senses covered by the statement that the 
judgment is a content having both a < by whom ' and a ' for 
whom ' force. Whatever is asserted is • synnomic ' in that ii 
intends to be true j or everybody ; and it is also • syndozic ' in 
that it is actually held only by somebody. And these two aspects 
of community are not coincident. One gives the force of the 
judgment 2A jit for acceptance; the other assigns the degree of 
actual prevalence. One indicates the universality and validity 
of the implication contained in the whole meaning ; the other 
indicates the aggregate or catholic process that acknowledges 
this validity. 

Now the question of truth is necessarily a question of tnith- 
to-whom as well as of truth-for-whom ; of acceptance in a social 
group, as well as of worth for acceptance by any single mind. 
And the interpretation of the nature of the truthfulness or falsity 
of a body of implications must not be one that mutilates the full 
two-fold intent of community. 

First, then, looking at the synnomic force — the intent for- 
whom — of a logical content, we find the state of things just de- 
scribed allowing of certain further extensions. The solidifica- 
tion of the inner control, by which a self is determined over 
against the objects of thought, goes far to bring about the domi- 
nance of the selective and active control processes ; especially 
' Again allading to a chapter not yet pabliahed. 



ON TRUTH, 281 

in the pursuit of hypothetical and inductive research. For 
here the schematic meaning rendered as hypothesis is largely 
a matter of personal interest and active pursuit. Allowing this 
— despite the fact that in the result this tendency yields to 
that of setting up an independently valid relational content, 
as remarked just above — allowing, that is, that the processes 
of active control are thus greatly emphasized in the individual, 
still a further question arises as to the determination of the self 
in these active terms. Is the self that now judges, one of 
merely individual and private action and purpose ; is the con- 
trol of the self-of-reflection in any sense a private control ? 

No, it is not. All our work of analysis — and that of recent 
social psychology — goes to show that the self of judgment is 
the self of common function, of syndoxic control, of processes 
so interknit as among individuals that it is reached only by the 
elimination of personal and private factors. The self of judg- 
ment is not the private self of appreciation and valuation ; that 
is expressly excluded in the terms whereby judgment is adhieved. 
The factors of inner control are generalized inner data, read back 
and forth in the dialectic whereby the * socius ' arises. All the 
way along, the child's self is not one that asserts his crude first 
preference or impression, but the disciplined and chastened self 
that has grown, by continuing processes of secondary conver- 
sion, into agreement with others. The opposite process also 
shows the same result : the self that judges legislates its own re- 
sult, so far as now and here accepted, back into the minds of 
others, being obliged to intend it to hold/or everybody. 

The result for our theory of truth is clear. Truth is not a 
matter of individual interpretation at all, whether in terms of 
action or of cognition. Suppose we remove the factor of ex- 
ternal control altogether and say that truth consists in availability 
of knowledge to minister to action ; still the question comes up, 
whose action? Certainly not any individual's action ; this would 
reduce the * for-whom ' to the realm of private preference and 
impulse, making the true that which ministers to personal grati- 
fication in a narrow and private sense. This directly contradicts 
the requirement of synnomic community. The interpretation 
in terms of action would require the sort of common function or 



282 y. MARK BALDWIN. 

action that would support and guarantee the intent of universal 
acceptance. 

But this it is evident would again, in the larger social whole 
of meaning, destroy the distinction between true and good. If 
the truth is to be the socially available, in a pragmatic or utili- 
tarian sense, it is then identified with the social end or good. 
What is good in the larger social sphere of welfare is the social 
end ; and this would then coincide with the thought, determined 
as fulfilment of that end. The same result is reached then on 
this construction, as on that stated above in individualistic terms, 
— the determination of truth in terms of good — except that 
now both terms are socially controlled. 

This result does seem to be fairly reasonable and just. The 
derivation of ethical good from social usage and habit, the 
reflection of social utility in individual conscience, does seem to 
result in a correspondence, in the processes of natural history, 
between the accretions to truth and the accretions to good. But 
the further difficulty would seem to be precisely that which we 
found in the similar correspondence between individual good and 
truth ; the difficulty of eliminating the factor of external con- 
trol which appears in this case also in the realization of the 
ends. Social or common thought could not of itself fulfil the 
social end : that could only come from * things ' that realized 
the thought. Social welfare is not — just as individual purpose 
is not — if so facto fulfilled in the setting up of ends, in this 
case of common ends. There is still here also the need of con- 
verting the social ends set up into actual conditions of social life ; 
just as there is the corresponding need in the case of the indi- 
vidual's purpose. In other words, while the socially true is 
always that upon which social action may go out; still there is 
the recognition of actual social fact ^ whether or not it is what 
is desirable for action. 

The conclusion, then, is that the recognition of the synnomic 
character of the judgment function, while broadening out the 
reference * for-whom ' to judgment process generally, does not 
remove the essential dualism between end and fact.^ The 

^Thifl is my line of answer to Professor Moore's attempt to restate the case 
in 'social ' terms (see below in this issue, p. 294). 



. ON TRUTH. 283 

demands of action are not fulfilled, but only mediated, by the 
thought context. So too with the coefficients of fact ; they are 
mediated, but not banished, in a socially available system of 
thoughts. The system, the entire accepted mass of social 
judgments, thus mediates both controls^ the socially inner or syn- 
nomic and the external, physical and other,^ in a new dualism, 
that of fact and end. Truth is still a relative conversion of the 
contents of social acceptance into the facts of a system of ex- 
ternal controls. Socially considered, truth has an existential 
reference that is not removed by the statement of social desid- 
erata. As of the individualistic formulation so of the * social ' 

— the criticism is the same — the determination of the true is 
not entirely through the postulates of conduct. 

This result is further enforced from the point of view of the 
other aspect in which all judgment has an intent of * community ' 

— the aspect * by whom,' the aspect of relative catholicity. 

Catholicity means relative actual prevalence of acceptance^ 
or quantity of aggregate belief. It is that aspect in which 
meaning is always for a hearer no less than for a speaker, for 
further propagation no less than for repeated statement. We 
have seen that in this aspect, as embodied in the linguistic forms 
of thought,' logical meaning never loses its hypothetical or 
schematic force; there are always in the social whole indi- 
viduals still to instruct or convince, always a future of genera- 
tions yet unborn to whom the linguistic is to be the mode of 
essential training into competent judgment. What shall we say, 
as to the interpretation of judgmental matter as true, from this 
point of view ? 

We have to recognize at once that in this intent of renewed 
• proposal ' to others the meaning is reduced from the logical — 
the fully accepted or * synnomic ' — to the prelogical, the sche- 
matic and personal. That which is not yet accepted is, to the 
intelligence not yet convinced, problematical and personal. The 
question then becomes, how can such meanings, set as sugges- 
tion or * proposal,' become for that person truth. Evidently only 

*The other inclnding the other persons who are read as the centers of 
active and appreciative process just as the one individual is. 
'See the Psvchologicai« Rbvisw, May, 1907. 



284 y. MARK BALDWIN. 

by the processes of confirmation essential in all such cases of the 
passing of hypothetical proposal into judgments of acceptance. 
The processes are those of material confirmation, of experiment 
and induction. But this means a direct resort to those coeflicients 
of control by which fact is established. It is a resort to the 
sphere in which the hypothesis set up finds its relevant control. 
The whole affair, then, the possibility of advance in the matter 
of diffusion, propagation, gain in prevalence and catholicity — 
the process by which more individuals concur in a statement as 
true — is one that reasserts the external controls by which the 
judgment secures its classifications and limitations. I see no 
escape from this conclusion.^ 

It means that the essential process by which relatively 
catholic acceptance, by whoniy passes into * synnomic ' accept- 
ance,y&r whom^ a matter absolutely requisite to the availability 
of judgments for social use — that this process is one of direct 
resort to the controls of fact. It is, once for all, not a resort to 
the sphere of end or action. For the assertion at this stage of 
the individual's purpose or desire would only emphasize that 
divergence that would keep the meaning forever in the selec- 
tive and a-synnomic stage of personal preference. Suppose I 
decided every matter placed before me in the line of my per- 
sonal interest and preference ; then the agreements by which 
common truth and value alike are reached would be impossible. 
There could be no truth, because there could be no judgment at 
all in the mode of * synnomic community' — no judgment of 
that universal import which implicates general agreement. 

The consideration of the community intent of judgment, 
therefore, reinforces, on both counts, our theory of truth. As 
synnomic meaning thought is available for action in so far as it 
is true — it is not true because available for action^ either social 
or individual or both. Of judgment in the forming, of meaning 

> It hu been bronght against me that in my addreaa on < Selective Thinking ' 
( chap. XVII. of Development and Evolution)^ I made tmth ' not what ia selected 
because it is true, bat what ia true because it haa been selected.' But thia does 
not at all contradict what I now say ; for in that address I explicitly made the 
'test o//act^ — \h^ gauntlet of external coefficienta — part of the process of 
selection, just as [I do here. Tmth is what is selected by the whole experi- 
mental judgmental process. 



ON TRUTH, 285 

having a progressive intent * by whom,' this is all the more true ; 
for the content not yet accepted could never be accepted, were 
the rule of determination anything else than confirmation in the 
sphere of control or fact in which the * truth ' is finally to be 
acknowledged as open to common inspection. 

There is, moreover, a further point to observe in this matter 
of community. It is a point that comes up in connection with 
catholicity considered as being a motive that recognizes the in- 
dividuality of the single person. We say that it is impossible 
to construe thought entirely from the point of view of the com- 
munity of synnomic intent, that is, as a body of completely 
established and once for all given truths. The reason is that 
there is always also the intent of further propagation and ac- 
ceptance in a growing social whole. The other aspect or intent 
of community must come into its own as well, and this recog- 
nizes further judgment process not included in the generaliza- 
tion of the personal attitudes, * for whom,' whereby the synnomic 
meaning was constituted. This brings up the singularity and 
separateness of individual judgment centers in a curious and in- 
teresting way. The reference of the meaning to the singular 
persons who do not believe is as real as that to the community 
of persons who do believe. 

Of course, we are not concerned here with the implications 
of the acknowledgment of single individuals by others ; here we 
have to enquire only into the effect of such acknowledgment 
upon the theory of truth. This is shown in two ways that we 
ma} now point out. 

In the first place, the process of conversion, whereby the 
proposed meaning passes over into judgment, is one of recog- 
nition of personalities. It consists in one's taking their thought 
as source of supply for one's own. The act of getting social 
confirmation proceeds always by such recognition of others as 
resourceful selves, whose knowledge is to be drawn upon. 
Thus the very process by which thought is accepted as true im- 
plicates the recognition of a set of judging selves reaching a 
common result. The inference is that no theory of truth can 
stand that does not involve a mode of consciousness having not 
only the subject-object dualism — myself and what I think 



286 /. MARK BALDWIN, 

about — but also a plurality of subject individuals having a 
common body of acknowledged objects, or a common body of 
truths. There is then a common presupposition in the implica- 
tion of truths but an individual presupposition in the implica- 
tion of belie/. Truth is one ; knowers of the truth are many. 
The commonness of any item of truth is achieved by the act of 
judgment ; but the progress of judgment, and with it the exten- 
sion of truth, implicates a set 0/ persons individuated as singular 
selves. 

The second point is that the individuals so implicated are, 
each for himself, a center of inner control process ; and so are 
they all in their meaning to each — a set of objects having this 
character. The social selves are, therefore, truths in the same 
sense that any body of contents are. For me, it is true that 
you are Mr. Brown, just as it is true that my hat is white. The 
essential singularity of you, as Mr. Brown, resides in the mean- 
ing I must give you, of being a self which besides being a true 
meaning to me, also has the common Jund 0/ true meanings with 
me. The true context of thought as a whole for each then, in- 
cludes in it all the others who are also reaching the same true 
context of thought. 

Here is a snag upon which the current instrumentalist 
theories often strike {e. g.^ Moore, in this issue of the Rbvibw). 
The readjustment of < conflicting habits ' is depicted as a proc- 
ess of attention, a process of restoring equilibrium of action 
which, if more than a figure, must be in the individual. But 
when it is pointed out that this is individualistic, resort is made to 
the social force of the content and of the social character of the 
self (often quoting my * social dialectic ''). But this is not a reply ; 
for there is no social attention^ no process of reconciliation of 
socially conflicting wills^ except by a return to the individual as 
a center of action and thought. This problem, whether set in 
terms of action (especially) or of thought (no less finally) must 
be solved in terms of the individual's experience, however fully 

' My earlier work shows the common character of the self-content, bat doet 
not for a moment deny the later logical individuation of singular selves. In 
my present work I trace out this latter movement. Moreover I am disposed to 
agree (and in fact I ax^gued for it in the paper on ' Selective Thinking ') thst 
the mechanism of subjective control is, as Mr. Moore claims, that of attention. 



ON TRUTH. 287 

it may also implicate common meaning. Either all controls 
(other persons, as well as external things) must be entirely and 
finally reflected in the common character of individual judgment, 
or thought in the individual will reassert itself in a mode of 
self-notself dualism, which is also one of personal -pluralism. 
This latter is the outcome in the mode of thought as such, the 
mode of truth. Any essential reconciliation by an act of judg- 
ment is impossible, since judgment sets up its own dualism of 
reflection. The position that objectivity arises only when con- 
flict is not mediated by judgment, and that judgment brings a 
new immediacy, seems to me flagrantly untrue (see the exposition 
of Miss Adams, The ^Esthetic Experienc^^ For when I judge, 
I set up and acknowledge a content as object over against myself. 
The dualism of fact and idea is mediated, in the establishing 
of truth ; but just this it is that also erects the further dualism 
of self acknowledging and things acknowledged, together with 
that other most pregnant dualism between fact and end. 

The true, then, is simply the body of knowledge, acknowU 
edged as belonging where it docs in a consistently controlled 
context. The characters of truth are those attaching to the con- 
tent of judgment as being under mediate control. The mean- 
ing of truth is its intent to mediate the original sphere of exist- 
ence meaning in which it arose. It is possible and necessary, 
just as any other sort of relative correctness is, wherever there 
is an original experience having coeflicients which the mediating 
later experience intends and invokes. It is strictly an experi- 
ential mode, since the controls which it mediates are those of 
developing psychic meaning.' 

^I snppooe Miss Adams' is as accredited exposition — and I should say a 
very clear and able one — of the position of the ' Qhicago School.' 

' Further paragraphs follow on ' How Truth is Made/ * What Truth is True 
to,* 'Falsity and Error/ 'What Truth is Good For,' 'Relative and Absolute 
Truth,' etc. — topics for which space cannot be taken here. The solutions all 
depend, however, on these fundamental positions (i) that truth is a system of 
objective contents set up and acknowledged as under a variety of coefficients of 
control ; (2) that this system is socially derived and socially valid, though ren- 
dered by acts of individual judgment ; (3) that the whole movement issues in 
a dualism of self-acknowledging and objects-acknowledged, a dualism from 
which thought as such cannot free itself. 



DISCUSSION. 

A FURTHER APPLICATION OF A RESULT OBTAINED 
IN EXPERIMENTAL ESTHETICS. 

In a recent experiment on the aesthetic value of a series of repeated 
units in architecture and design/ a certain marked iiifference in the 
introspection of my observers suggested opposing ideals in their aes- 
thetic appreciation, which, it has seemed to me, may have a wider 
application than was claimed for them in that paper. 

The difference was this: In looking at designs consisting of a 
dozen or fifteen repeated figures, which together made a band of 
simple decoration, the observers described their reactions in two dis- 
tinct ways. 

The first, whom I have called the rhythmic type, enjoyed the units 
solely in terms of their rhythmic sequence. The activity of monng 
the attention uniformly from one unit to the next like it was the only 
charm, and they could not describe their pleasure in the repeated 
design in other terms than those of simple temporal sequence, anal- 
ogous to their pleasure in auditory rhythm. 

The observers of the other type, from the first described their ex- 
perience in different terms. They said the passage from one unit to 
the next had no part in their enjoyment, but was often in fact a hin- 
drance. Their pleasure depended on the satisfaction they got from 
any unit as a fixation point, with a marginal amount of attention 
bestowed on the other units extending both sides of the central fig- 
ure. The experience was a stable one, on any figure for itself. The 
fact that any one could enjoy rhythm of succession for its own sake, 
apart from the value of the individual unit, they could not understand. 
This divergence in method of apperception was at first puzzling, but 
it ran systematically throughout the experiment. The rhythmic type 
had little choice as to the unit of the series, provided it was repeated; 
the static type could not enjoy the repetition if the figure was nat in- 
trinsically agreeable — otherwise repetition only made matters worse. 

The rhythmic type could not enjoy the series unless enough time 
was allowed them to look along the design and get accustomed to its 
rhythm ; the static type enjoyed it more if they were not forced to look 

' ' -Esthetics of Repeated Space Forms/ Harvard Psych. Studies, Vol. IL 

288 



DISCUSSION. 289 

along its length, but could keep one figure, whether for a long or short 
time, as the center of balance. 

As might be expected, the rhythmic type was more sensitive to 
uniform spacing between the units. If these interspacings were 
altered so that there were, irregularly, longer breaks between some 
than others, the entire rhythm was broken ; the static type, however, 
could not detect that they felt the interspacing to be equal, although 
they knew it to be. They spent so much attention on each unit for 
itself that they lost any impression of a rhythm in going from one to 
the next. 

These and other differences between the two classes of observers 
have suggested that their two ways of enjoying decorative design are 
typical of a deeper difference which characterizes two opposing demands 
of art as well as of life. Many other conflicts in taste may perhaps 
grow from this fundamental difference of attitude, but I have taken as 
a possible illustration the characteristic art-appreciation of two great 
classes of people, the American and the Japanese. 

That there are both types of observers in every race and in every 
community is of course indicated by this laboratory experiment. But 
it is easier to point out wide divergencies in a national than in an in- 
dividual taste, and I would suggest that in an average of many cases, 
the Japanese would fall preeminently into the static division, while the 
American would fall with more probability into the rhythmic. This 
anticipation seems justifiable since every one of the apperceptive 
differences among the laboratory subjects, points to a more extended 
but similar difference in the ideals of the two nations. 

There is a most interesting account of the aims of the Japanese 
artist in two books ^ by Mr. Okakura, sometime director of the Imperial 
Art School at Tokio, and now of the Hall of Fine Arts in the same 
city, and they illustrate in a striking way the apperceptive method of 
the extreme static type, as opposed to the more rhythmic ideals of 
America. 

These examples are the more interesting since we look to Japan 
especially as the leader in decorative art. It might seem thus, that 
uniformity in repeated designs would be its prime characteristic, but 
on the contrary, it is just the reverse. 

It is western Europe and America that have adopted uniform 
repetition in design, but it is Japan and the East which demand varia- 
tions to a degree that is confusing at first to one educated on the other 
basis. 

» The Ideal$ of the East and The Book of Tea, 



290 RESULT OBTAINED IN EXPERIMENTAL ESTHETICS. 

The Japanese artist may embody the same idea over and over 
again to suggest infinity, but in his decorative series, the figures and 
often the interspacings, are not uniform. His method of apperception 
is to immerse himself completely in each unit — which is, of course, 
utterly opposed to the active hurrying from point to point which the 
rhythmic observer feels essential to his pleasure. 

It is indeed possible to go through the list of characteristics as they 
appeared in the laboratoiy observers, and apply them with equal cor- 
rectness to the art of the two nations. Much of America's improved 
taste has come directly from Japan, so the styles which our public has 
adopted, and which it has, so far, refused to adopt, show distinctly 
where falls the division line, between the two typical tastes. 

1 . The rhythmic types were but little affected by the beauty or 
ugliness of the unit, so long as it was repeated. 

We are certainly familiar with this taste in every-day architecture. 
Rows on rows of undifferentiated pillars, windows, and machine-made 
decorations valueless in themselves are tolerated; but the tiresome 
character of the units does not shock us, as would one or two placed 
above the level, or at unequal distances. Contrast with this the horror 
of monotonous repetition in the mind of the Japanese (p. 96, Book of 
Tea). ^^ Uniformity of Design was considered fatal to freshness of 
imagination." ^* In the tea* room the fear of repetition is a constant 
presence." This dislike of repetition has gone so far as to center the 
skill of Japanese artists on birds and flowers, rather than on the human 
figure ; for a human spectator being always implied by an art- work, 
there would be a repetition of a similar form, if one were also repre- 
sented in the picture 1 The Japanese cannot understand our habit of 
decorating dining-rooms with pictures of game or fruit. Since we of 
necessity eat in the room, it is the place of all others where food should 
not be duplicated in the pictures. One finds continually in cloisonne 
vases different designs within the same pattern, as if the designer were 
impatient of that very recurrence to which we are accustomed. In 
any art, observers of both types would agree that in proportion as a 
unit has individual value, serial repetition becomes less allowable, so 
it would naturally follow that to the observer whose every art-object 
is an end in itself, repeated series would be intolerable. 

2. The rhythmic observer in demanding a given amount of time 
to feel his rhythm, demands necessarily that the succession be not 
hampered by unequal attentive periods on the different units. On 
the other hand the ideal of the Japanese is to ^ catch a glimpse of 
infinity ' in each beautiful figure, and the notion that he is bound to a 



DISCUSSION, 291 

time limit to move from one unit to another similar one, is abhorrent 
to him. Each figure speaks for itself, and involves submersion in ii^ 
not activity in mowmg from it. 

Even the single art object must avoid symmtery (p. 17, Book of 
Tea) since that implies a repetition of equal distances two sides of a 
middle point. This in itself is in striking contrast to the American 
habit of decoration. 

3. Another interesting tendency of the rhythmic observer in the 
laboratory was to greatly overestimate his interspacings. Both types 
were asked to arrange a set of figures at distances from each other 
equal to the width of the figures. Since these units had groups of 
lines within themselves, they had the character of an optical illusion, 
and both classes overestimated the spacing, but in an average of three 
trials, the rhythmic type overestimated twice as much. Apparently 
the very motor activity which constituted bis pleasure, carried the 
rhythmic observer beyond his limits and made him ^ see large,' where- 
as the static type, more absorbed in each unit for its own sake, had 
not the same motor impetus to overcome, and saw smaller. 

Could there be a more obvious distinction between the tastes of 
the two nations? The heavy fa9ades, long colonnades, many steps 
and wide doors which characterize American architecture contrast 
strikingly with the delicately small proportions of the Japanese build- 
ings. We do not mean to imply the superiority of the ' static ' de- 
mand ; certainly the simple repetitions of the Greek temple make that 
impossible ; but the common American * commercial decorating ' 
illustrates the rhythmic ideal without the balance of the opposing ten- 
dency ; and it may be that degenerate Japanese decoration might show 
the opposite fault of confusion, though as yet they seem to have pre- 
served better their artistic conscience. 

If one might generalize even more on this laboratory suggestion, it 
would seem as if the Westerner's love of activity for its own sake was 
an expression of his rhythmic life, his enjoyment of every experience 
in terms of regular accented successions ; while the isolated absorption 
in the unique experience of the Oriental was an equally characteristic 
indication of the static method of apperceiving life as well as art. 

There are both kinds of observers in every race, but in a general 
sense the rhythmic activity of one leads to music, rhymed verse forms, 
and regularly repeated designs, even to athletics and science, since 
these are relative activities, never the perfect moments of repose. 

On the other hand the static type tends more to the visuul arts, 
especially to exquisite materials, color and workmanship, to small 



^9^ BXPERIRNCB, HABIT AND ATTENTION. 

detail and endless variety in design. Moreover it is in the East that 
mystic philosophy and religions flourish, since they express not rela- 
tivity but absolute values, where temporal successions have no meaning. 

Now that Japan is open to the west and gaining our scientific 
activity, she is having to fight hard for her national act, while we are 
learning from her the value of unique beauty as distinct from the 
relative. 

Perhaps the perfect art-lover as well as race, will represent a union 
of both apperceiving types.* 

Eleanor Harris Rowland. 

Mount Holyokk Coi:«i,bgb. 



EXPERIENCE, HABIT AND ATTENTION. 

In my review of Professor Baldwin's 7ii^»^^/ and Things^ Vol.1., 
in the Psych. Bulletin for March of this year, I referred to Professor 
Baldwin's criticisms of the attempt to state cognitive experiences as 
part of the whole process of the readjustment of conflicting habitual 
and instinctive activities through attention. Professor Baldwin's objec- 
tion was that such an account cannot take care of the case of ' a new 
and unwelcome object which simply forces itself upon us, • ♦ * 
which rides full armed through our walls and compels its recognition.' 
My reply was to the effect that this very * new,' * unwelcome,' involun- 
tary, ^ forced ' character of the object, when analyzed instead of being 
accepted as ultimate and quasi-miraculous, turns out to be just as much 
a function of habit and attention as the ^ voluntary ' cases.' 

Without any further attempt at analysis. Professor Baldwin in the 
May number of the Bulletin reaflSrms his objection and adds another 
edition of it from the standpoint of volitional instead of cognitive expe- 
rience to the effect that in such a conception of experience there is no 
* motivation.' He says * I can't rest content with a dynamic that has 
nothing outside to move it and no reason inside for moving.' This 
sounds wonderfully like an appeal to the outside ^ unmoved mover' the 
insoluble difliculties with which our Greek forebears, to say nothing of 
Locke, Hume, Kant, et al., discovered. To rehearse these would, I 
take it, be an unpardonable anachronism. As for * no reason inside for 

^ The MS. of this article was received April 4, 1907. 

■Most of this discnssion was in MS. when Professor Dewey's article, which 
more than anticipates the main point of this paper, appeared in the Jour, of 
Philos. I PsychoL , etc,, for May 9. But as Professor Dewey in that article points 
out the necessity * for constant dripping to wear down the stony hearted ' I send 
this to print as a contribution to the ' drip.' 



DISCUSSION. 293 

moving,' what better reason could there be than the conflict of the 
habitual and instinctive activities with its accompanying dissatisfac- 
tion. 

Again, Professor Baldwin asks : ^^ If experience proceeds by 
readjusting to situations, whence comes the situation that ^ puts it up ' 
to it to adjust " (italics mine) . Now the use of the preposition * to ' 
both locates and at the same time begs the whole issue. In the view 
which Professor Baldwin criticizes experience proceeds by situations 
of readjustment, not by adjustments to situations. The situation to be 
readjusted is one in and of experience, not one which is ' put up * to 
it from without. That Professor Baldwin must be aware in some 
measure of this view seems implied in his next question : ^ Why does 
it (experience) grow discontent with its own habit world' (italics 
mine) ? This certainly assumes that somebody regards the readju^ing 
situation as made by the discontent of experience with its awn habit 
world. 

As for the answer to the question : ' How this discontent can arise,' 
that is not far to seek. As has been pointed out again and again, it is 
due to the fact that habits are constantly coming' into conflict. In 
more general form experience has constantly to face the results of its 
own work and utilize them as the material of its own further develop- 
ment. And if it be further asked how this conflict reveals itself, the 
apswer is ; through dissatisfaction and pain. 

The same point is involved in the following questions on my answer 
to which Professor Baldwin says he * will stake the whole business ' : 

*' First. How can experience of the dynamic-relative type secure or 
utilize knowledge that is socially valid without at the same time rein- 
stating other things as valid, as the social fellows, including the thinker 
himself? 

" Second. How can an experience that has no environment except 
its own habit and no reality, save its present function, set up any 
dynamic at all P 

*' Or to put these two questions in one : In what sense is the will 
of the mother spanking the child part of the habit of the child, and 
why does the child's experience take on this particular phase of rela- 
tive dynamic — this occasional and very disconcerting phase of habit?" 

In this last inclusive and very concrete form of his question I 
assume that Professor Baldwin does not intend to put me at any empi- 
rical disadvantage by having the * mother ' instead of the father do the 
spanking — an arrangement which, personally, both as a child and as 
a parent I have always favored. As for 'staking the whole business 



294 BXPBRIBNCB, HABIT AND ATTBNTION. 

on my answer/ that happily is not necessary, as that is a responsibility 
already shared by many others. 

In general, Professor Baldwin's questions all reveal the chronic 
and apparently incurable determination of most critics of pragmatic 
doctrines to take, at any rate in their criticisms, the terms ^ experience,' 
* consciousness,' ^ habit,' ^ attention,' etc., in the sense of the ^experi- 
ence,' * consciousness,' * habit ' and ^ attention ' of some one individual. 
Whereas all these terms, when they are used without explicit reference 
to a particular individual, refer to the entire world of activity in which 
all experiencing individuals have their being — * experience ' being the 
general term for that world of activity, the other terms meaning partic- 
ular modes or functions of that activity. 

This does not mean that these particular modes or functions, such 
as habit and attention, may be regarded as some sort of disembodied 
^ things in themselves,' capable of an existence apart from individuals. 
They are the functions, the modes of the activity of individuals ^ 
habit being the conserving, the mechanical, the structural mode, atten- 
tion the reconstructive, reforming, readjusting activity. While this 
conception does not then in any sense attempt to substitute experience, 
habit, or thinking in general or at large for the experiences, habits and 
thinking of individuals, it does protest just as insistently against re- 
garding these activities as shut up within the epidermic confines of 
some one individual. However much John Smith's habits and ideas 
belong to him, they belong also to the whole community in which 
he lives and which is aHected in any way by them, be that as large or 
small as it may. Conversely, just this community center of habits and 
ideas is John Smith. That this is to be taken literally and not figura- 
tively, Professor Baldwin himself shows in his volumes on Mental 
Development. 

Now if this conception of the habits and ideas of the individual as 
also functions of the whole community life, be kept steadily in view, 
it would seem that the impossibility of framing such questions as the 
above is as obvious as their answer. 

Turning to the first question. Why should anyone speak of ^ rein- 
stating social fellows ' and ' other things ' ? Who has turned them out ? 
Surely not those who teach that problems arise, run their course and 
find their solution not in the solipsistic realm of John Smith's habits 
and ideas as a complete world in itself, but in the habits and ideas of 
John Smith as a conserving and reconstructive agent of the whole 
community life. 

As for the second question, in view of what has already been said 



DISCUSSION, 295 

of the place of habit in experience, it seems redundant to add : (i) 
that habit cannot be regarded as an external enviroment to experience, 
or (2) that experience does not have to ' get up' any dynamic. The 
* dynamic ' is already there : (a) in the obviously active character of 
the habits; {b) in their coming into conflict; and {c) in the recon- 
structive work of attention. 

Professor Baldwin's putting of the ^ spanking ' question lends itself 
somewhat temptingly to facetious treatment, but as the case is really a 
serious one for all parties concerned, I prefer to treat it so and to ob- 
serve ; first, that in urging the distinction between the experience of the 
mother and that of the child, the question seems irrelevant to the orig- 
inal issue, which is the possibility of stating the whole situation 
whether it involves one person or a thousand, few or many things, in 
terms of a conflict of activities resolved through attention. It insists 
that the whole situation, including the mother, the child and the spank- 
ing, whether regarded from the standpoint of the mother, the child or 
both, is a system of conflicting activities undergoing reconstruction. 
And from this standpoint there is no more need for identifying the 
ideas or will of the mother and the habits of the child in the sense of 
making them the same thing or making one a ^ part ' of the other, than 
of identifying habit and will in the mother, or in running together 
distinguishable functions or aspects of any other process. 

Admitting, yr^///c^ then, the distinction between the activities of 
the mother and those of the child, we must yet keep hold of the fact 
that if they are not * parts' of each other, yet they are ^ parts ^ in the 
sense of constituent interacting activities^ of one situation. This is 
reflected, in general, in the very terms in which we state the case. 
The performance as a whole may be stated either as ^ the mother spank- 
ing the child,' or ' the child being spanked by the mother.' It depends 
on the point of view. Again, the term * mother ' implies that one of 
the individuals is the kind of an individual that has the habit, the atti- 
tude of caring for ' her child.' And the term ' her child' implies that 
the other is the kind of a individual that is to be protected by the 
mother even to the extent of being spanked, if need be. 

Following the analysis still further, and still speaking from the 
standpoint of the whole situation, how can ^ the will to spank ' be re- 
garded as the exclusive production of the mother ? It surely is the 
outcome of the conflict between the mother-attitude of perceiving and 
keeping the child in safety and the child's present activity of, say play- 
ing with the Are. It is a joint product of these two sets of activities, 
and one is as essential as the other. The attempt to regard the will- 



296 BXPBRIBNCB, HABIT AND ATTENTION , 

ing as the exclusive production of the mother alone transforms the con- 
crete will to-spank-this-child-now-playing-with-the-fire into an ab- 
stract ^ will to spank ' iiherhaupt^ with nothing particular to spank,— 
the essence of a profoundly tragic situation. 

But Professor Baldwin may say, after all * the spanking ' is ' forced * 
on the child as the perception of the-child-playing-with-the-fire is 
forced on the mother, to which I would rejoin : ( i ) Even so, this but 
sustains the original contention that however * new ' or ^ forced ' or 
* unwelcome ' the experience may be, it still is statable in terms of the 
readjustment of conflicting habitual activities through attention, and 
even if for any reason one wished to state the case from the standpoint 
of the mother or the child alone there are no other terms so far as I 
can see for the statement. (2) The spanking is no more ^ forced' on 
the child than on the mother. In fact, psychically it may be much 
less so. However skeptical, we may have been about it as children, 
we have since learned that our mothers spake truly when they said : 
*'I am sorry that I am * forced 'to punish you." (3) For both, 
neither ^ the spanking ' nor the playing-with-the-fire \dewed as an oc- 
currence is any more * forced ' than anything else that may have pre- 
ceded, as running, talking, sewing, etc. Even the image of the child 
playing with the fire is no more forced upon the mother than her own 
breathing, her impulse to rescue the child, or her will to spank it. In 
this sense, all those activities which constitute the * self ' of the mother 
upon which other things are said to be * forced ' is as much ^ forced' 
as the things. In this sense everything is ' forced.' ^ Forced ' here 
means simply ' happens.' And in this sense things are no more and 
no less ' forced ' upon us than we are ^ forced ' upon things, or ' forced ' 
upon ourselves. What goes on within our ' walls ' is as much ^ forced ' 
as the thing ' which rides full armed through them.' As a matter of 
fact, this mere happening of things, however ' new ' or * sudden,' e,g*y 
Professor James' classic thunder-clap, is not experienced as ^ forced ' 
unless it conflicts with activities or attitudes already going on. And 
even then the ^ force ' obviously is not all on the side of the ^ new ' 
factor. It is met by the force of the activities already there. Pur- 
suing the figure, the forces behind the ^ walls ' are not asleep waiting 
to be aroused from without. They are already active. And if the 
new factor be recognized as an improvement, it may be made the 
basis, the ideal, of the reorganization, in which case the old habits 
instead of the * new ' content, will appear as the * opposition.' It is, 
then, only when there is a conflict of happenings and some content is 
selected as an end^ that the other activities, the readjustment of which 



DISCUSSION. 297 

this end demands, seem ' opposed ' and ^ external ' to the end^ hut not 
opposed or external to the whole situation or to ^ experience/ 

As these remarks are already heyond their alloted space I cannot 
take up the other and relatively minor points to which Professor 
Baldwin refers. However, regarding my complaint of confusion in 
the use of terms I should like to ask what is meant hy ^ trans-sub- 
jective ' and * extra-psychic ' realities in view of the following : ** The 
envelope of the developing psychic process is nowhere ruptured. The 
controls, * foreign' as well as 'inner' are all psychic meanings." 
(Bulletin for May, p. 126). A foot-note,' p. 12, Thoughts and 
Things^ says extra-psychic ' means independence merely from the 
individuaVs psychic process.' But a foot-note on the psychic ' enve- 
lope ' in the above passage says : '' It is, however, an envelope of 
inter-psychic or common, in no sense private, meaning." So far as I 
can see these passages use ^ psychic ' in three senses : ( i ) As mean- 
ing 'the individual's psychic process'; (2) as including other indi- 
viduals ; (3) as including all ' foreign controls ' whether other persons 
or things (italics mine). 

A. W. Moore. 

Thb Univbrsity of Chicago. 

COMMENT ON PROFESSOR MOORE'S PAPER.* 

Professor Moore's position assumes ' habit ' and ' instinct ' and 
also ' conflict,' and withal ' attention ' to ' readjust ' them. But genesis 
must account for all these things ; the same question of accommodation 
vs. habit arises in the simplest organism and the ' motivation ' of a proc- 
ess is not explained by the assumption of its whole machinery* It is 
this that leads us — the critics — to say that the scheme is thoroughly 
individualistic. It would seem necessary to restate it in social terms. 
To this Professor Moore agrees ; but then, as I think, he fails to give 
us a coherent restatement in social terms. The point at which he fails 
is one indicated in the article above and in detail in my book ; in brief, 
the social process has no ' attention,' the conflict of wills gets no sort of 
readjustment in such terms as habit and instinct — save by a superficial 
analogy — and the whole mediation must go back to the individual proc- 

^ As it happens a proposed contribator to this issue deferred sending in his 
paper ; and I take the space to print part of a chapter of volume two of the 
work that called ont Professor Moore's remarks. In that article (above, p. 264) 
I answer both his and Professor Dewey's criticisms {Joum. ofPhilos., May 9, 
1907) more effectively, by expanding my own view, than I could in such more 
fragmentary discussions as this. 



2^8 COMMBNT ON PROFESSOR MOORE'S PAPER. 

ess again, dealing now with socially derived and socially valid mean- 
ings* That is, social truth must be rendered in individual judgment 
— must be what I have called synnomic. But just here the individual 
factors of the whole mode of personal judgment reassert themselves, and 
the new dualism of self and things^ knower and known, is consti- 
tuted. In other words, the factor of foreign control again arises, in 
the constitution both of things and of the persons of the objective world 
of reflection.^ 

I am, as Professor Moore is, seeking for a reconciling mode of 
experience; I do not, however, find it where he does. I cannot avoid 
seeing that for the knower there is a very compelling and intruding 
sort of experience — that is what the much criticised sentence about 
the ^ unwelcome presence that rides full-armed through our walls' 
means, and about all it means. This is for and by him^ the knower^ 
read as a ' foreign control ' over against the tendencies — habits, instincts, 
volitions, etc. — that come to mean, all the way through, inner control. 
Judgment bridges this chasm, but opens another one — that of the 
dualism of reflection. The real mediation is found in the ' semblant' 
consciousness as I intimated in my closing remarks on Professor 
Moore's review {Psychological Bulletin^ K^xiX 15, pp. 124-6). 

J. Mark Baldwin. 

Johns Hopkins Univbrsity. 

* In this connection I may answer Professor Moore's question as to the 
meaning of 'pijchic' It is as he says " (i) the individnars psychic process, 
(2) as including other individuals [among the meanings it gets and entertains] 
and (3) as including all 'foreign controls' whether other persons or things 
[also among the meanings it gets and entertains]. My explanations are inserted 
In brackets. It is all ' psychic ' in the one sense ; and that hits upon tfae re- 
qnirement noted above, that even when the common or 'social ' point of view 
is taken, the function of readjustment, of advance, of mediation must be in- 
terpreted as going on within the ' psychic-envelope ' of the individual's mind. 



N. S. Vol. XIV. No. 5. September, 1907. 



The Psychological Review. 



THE NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL AND 
THEIR RELATIONS.^ 

BY PROFESSOR WILBUR M. URBAN. 
Trinity College,^ 

I. The Problem. 

The problem of feeling and will and the nature of their 
relations is perhaps the most difficult within the entire field of 
psychological analysis. The reason for this is not far to seek, 
for nowhere is it more important that the distinction between 
appreciative and non-appreciative description should be realized 
and a true theory of their relations formed, and nowhere is there 
such confusion on these points as precisely in this sphere.^ 

To illustrate my point in detail, the distinction between feel- 

' In two recent articles entitled Definition and Analysis of the Consciousness 
of Value, PSYCHOi^OGiCAi, RsviKw, Vol. XIV., Nos. x and 2, a definition of 
feelings of value and an analysis of the different modes of worth experience 
were developed which, as was explicitly stated, presupposed a theory of Peeling 
and Will not fully given in those papers. The present article, while in a sense 
an independent discussion, nevertheless serves to answer certain questions left 
unsolved in those studies. 

'The consequence has been the widely divergent analyses with which psy- 
chologists have been scandalized. The original distinctions within this sphere 
were made from the appreciative point of view because analysis of feeling and will 
first began with the worth problem (Plato and Aristotle and later the English 
Utilitarians). As the original interest became secondary to that of non-appre- 
ciative description, the distinctions developed in appreciative description, when 
the meaning of the feeling, i. e,, its presuppositions, was taken into account, 
were applied without reflection to hypothetical feeling abstracted from its 
presuppositions. Tradition was all powerful here (for we are naturally conser- 
vative in all that affects the feeling and worth side of experience), and when at 
last independence of analysis appeared, the question of the retention or elimi- 
nation of these distinctions seems to have been determined largely by personal 
inclination rather than by considerations of scientific method, and hence again 
the divergence in analyses. 

299 



300 WILBUR M, URBAN. 

ing as passive and will as active is an appreciative distinction. 
One concrete attitude is relatively more passive with reference 
to its meaning in a series of attitudes, with reference to what 
succeeds or precedes ; but when we abstract from the meaning 
of the attitude and apply the distinction to hypothetical content, 
it involves us, we shall find, if it is made absolute, in contradic- 
tions, and is far from representing the facts. The distinctions 
between affect, impulse, desire, wish and will are primarily 
appreciative, made with reference to the meanings of the atti- 
tude and, as we shall see later, go back to certain cognitive 
differences in presuppositions. And finally, the distinction 
pleasantness-unpleasantness, and its selection as the dominant 
in the feeling complex or attitude to the exclusion of other 
aspects, is one which has been determined largely by apprecia- 
tive purposes, i. ^., it is the abstract aspect which appears empha- 
sized when the attitude (subjective) is transformed into a state, 
as object of another attitude. Now when these appreciative 
distinctions, which are largely concerned with the intent of an 
attitude rather than with the content of a state, are taken to 
apply to content from which meaning has been abstracted, in- 
teresting difficulties and contradictions arise. When the distinc- 
tions between passive and active, and feeling and conation (will), 
are taken as non-appreciative ultimate distinctions, we have a 
dualism in affective-volitional meaning which the several dif- 
ferent dualistic theories seek to bridge by establishing relations 
of causal deierminism between the two aspects. One finds 
feeling, as a distinct element (passive pleasantness or unpleas- 
antness), the necessary antecedent of all conation; another, 
giving the primacy to conation, finds in the passive feeling the 
sign of the satisfaction or arrest of some antecedent active im- 
pulse or desire ; or, finally, the dualism may be pressed so far 
(as in the recent work of Schwartz) as to admit the existence of 
volition without feeling. 

The extent to which these fundamental conceptions color all 
worth analysis and theory is obvious. Psychological hedonism, 
with its incapacity to explain a good part of worth experience, 
is the result of the first. A theory which is unable to include 
the aesthetic in the sphere of worths is the result of the second. 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL, 301 

From the third we get the strained formalism of Kant and 
Schwartz, In view of these difficulties, no theory of feeling 
and will and of their relations (and some theory is necessary) is 
of any value unless it is formed with a clear consciousness of 
the problem involved in the relation of the appreciative to the 
scientific description of the psychical. 

There are two views which have been formed with this clear 
consciousness of the methodological presuppositions involved. 
On the one hand, Meinong tells us, to take him as typical, 
the relation of feeling and will can only be determined from the 
worth standpoint, while Wundt, to take him again as typical, 
looks upon the distinctions introduced from the point of view 
of worth analysis, such as the distinctions between feeling, 
desire and will, as ^ pure logical artifacts, not in the least, how- 
ever, psychical ultimates distinct from each other.' As a con- 
sequence, the distinction between feeling and will is for the 
former ultimate, while for Wundt's monistic theory, there is a 
fundamental identity (of feeling elements) underlying all these 
retrospective artificial distinctions. 

Between two such divergent views, with such different 
methodological presuppositions, there would appear to be no 
middle ground and yet to my mind both have a relative validity 
and are susceptible of reconciliation. More than this, I am 
inclined to think that the Identity theory, developed from the 
standpoint of analysis of content, is the only one which will har- 
monize with the distinctions in affective volitional meaning, 
developed from the worth standpoint or the standpoint of func- 
tional intent. 

2. DuALisTic Theories of Feeling and Will. Criticism. 
We may begin our study, then, with a brief critical exami- 
nation of those views which, upon the assumption of absolute dis- 
stinction between feeling as passive pleasantness or unpleasant- 
ness and conation as active, seek to establish a relation of causal 
psychical determination between them. If the distinction is one 
of content viewed apart from its intent or meaning, then it is 
necessary that experience shall show us either passive feeling 
as the necessary antecedent of all active states which are called 



302 WILBUR M, URBAN, 

conative or, on the other hand, that all passive states of feeling 
have as their necessary antecedents arrest or accommodation 
of conscious impulse or desire, in its very nature, as content, 
different from feeling. 

{a) The first of these dualistic views, in its original form of 
psychological hedonism, was beautiful in its simplicity. Feeling, 
as a passive state, is always an effect of content, sensation and 
idea, and their relations. The aspects, quality and intensity, 
vary with the changes of sensational and ideal content, and the 
intensity and quality determine impulse, desire, etc., the active 
side of consciousness. 

A very superficial examination of the facts suffices to show 
us that, if by feeling we mean simple passive pleasantness or 
unpleasantness with certain intensities, it is by no means the 
necessary antecedent of any given impulse or desire. On the one 
hand we have simple impulses for which there is no such con- 
scious hedonic antecedent. When the impulse to take exercise 
comes over me at a given time, introspection will show me that 
it is necessarily preceded neither by a conscious feeling of 
unpleasantness nor by an anticipation of pleasantness, although 
either may be the antecedent. On the other hand there are 
phenomena of a more developed conation which we have seen 
described as * intensitiless ' acts of preference where affective 
disturbance is at a minimum, and which, if feeling be described 
as passive hedonic intensity, certainly show no such feeling ante- 
cedent. Impulses with the note of obligation in them are fre- 
quently of this character. 

That there are changes in affective volitional meaning (Ge- 
mtkthsbewegungen, in the broadest sense), described as im- 
pulse and desire, which do not presuppose an antecedent passive 
hedonic consciousness or consciousness of hedonic difference, is 
clear. If we include in feeling other qualities such as tension- 
relaxation, restlessness-quiescence, it is merely a verbal quibble 
to raise any question of antecedent and consequent. We have 
already attributed to the concrete feeling state the essential 
character of the conative side, a virtual acceptance of the Iden* 
tity theory. 

This fact, that there are numerous impulses and desires which 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL, 303 

follow immediately upon presentation and judgment without 
appreciable hedonic consciousness intervening, is, moreover, 
admitted by the upholders of this theory of dependence, without 
however sacrificing the theory. Thus Kreibig speaks of dispo- 
sitional feelings below the threshold as determining impulse and 
desire, while Ehrenfels speaks of desire as determined by feel- 
ing or feeling'disfositions. And even when it is actual feeling 
which is conceived as causally determinative, it is not, as we 
have seen in our previous analysis of Ehrenfels' worth defini- 
tion,^ feeling as a separate antecedent state, but the feeling dif- 
ference as determined by the object as existing or not existing 
and the feeling disposition of the subject. In the case of the 
impulse to exercise it would be — not necessarily the unpleasant- 
ness of the present state nor the anticipated pleasure — but the 
difference between the two which constitutes the necessary pre- 
supposition of the impulse or desire. 

But it is precisely in these admissions, and consequent modi- 
fications of the original theory, that we see the failure of this 
entire theory of dependence growing out of the separation of 
feeling from conation. For a feeling which does not rise above 
the threshold is a pure conceptual construction. So also is the 
feeling difference when made the presupposition of desire. 
For a feeling difference can be an actual psychical determinant 
in only two ways : either it is a presentation constructed upon 
two presented feelings and then we have presentations as the 
presupposition of the desire, or else this difference is felt as 
tension or restlessness, as an expectancy generated by the hypo- 
thetical disposition, the active conative moment supposed to be 
determined by the feeling, in which case there is no need for 
such duplication of phenomena. In the latter case then, where 
feeling difference is conceived to be the presupposition of cona- 
tion, it is either not distinct from conation or else it is a purely 
conceptual construction. 

{h) The second theory of dependence, which has been 
developed upon the assumption that feeling and conation are 
ultimates from the point of view of content, is that all feelings 
have as their necessary antecedent some phase of conscious co- 

> Cf. articles already referred to. 



304 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

nation, and that feeling is the sign of arrest or satisfaction of 
desire. Here, again, if conation is conceived to be an aspect of 
consciousness which, as content for non-appreciative descriptioD, 
is distinct from feeling, it is difficult to establish a thorough-going 
relation of dependence. It is true that affective attitudes on the 
plane of worth suggestion presuppose the activities of acknowl- 
edgment or rejection, but even here it cannot be said that the 
relation is one of antecedent and consequent, nor can it be said 
that the worth feelings are passive pleasantness and unpleasant- 
ness. But it is by no means easy to include in such a general- 
ization all the phenomena of feeling. There are in the first 
place the feelings which accompany simple sensations, the 
agreeable or disagreeable affective tone of an odor or color. 
There are also the sudden emotions of surprise and fear and 
finally the instinctive emotions, inherited and appearing at first 
without any conative experience as their antecedent. 

As to the first group of phenomena, those who hold the view 
that feeling has its rise in arrested conation insist that even these 
phenomena fall under the general law. So also does the func- 
tional theory in general when it is consistent and sharply distin- 
guishes feeling and conation. Thus, in a recent article written 
from this point of view, unpleasantness is conceived to follow 
upon arrested conation while pleasantness appears only when 
conation is accommodating itself after arrest. States which do 
not contain conative moments are neutral. 

Nevertheless, the difficulties in the way of such an answer 
are not to be minimized. If we examine the reasons given for 
this inclusion we find that they are of two kinds — the first being 
analytical and introspective, the second functional. The first is 
to the effect that it is impossible to get the feeling tone of a 
simple sensation uncomplicated with the aspects of tension-relax- 
ation, restlessness-quiescence, with their suggestion of conative 
presuppositions; the second, the functional argument to the 
effect that the law of decrease of affective tone through habit 
and repetition of stimulus, is primarily a law of adaptation 
of tendency to stimulus, and that, when an odor or tone loses 
its affective tone through repetition, it does so because the tend- 
ency, or need of excitation of the organism, produced by arrest, 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL. 305 

has been satisfied. When we look more closely at these argu- 
ments, the difficulties referred to appear. Here again, as in 
the preceding theory, the relation can be made universal only 
by going beyond immediate experience and supplementing it with 
hypothetical conceptual constructions. The aspects of tension- 
relaxation, of restlessness-quiescence, if they appear in the simple 
feeling tone of sensation, are analytically separable from the 
feeling as antecedent content, intrinsically different from feel- 
ing. Impulse and desire are not conscious presuppositions of 
the feelings. When the intensity of feeling tone diminishes 
with repetition, it does not necessarily mean that actual 
impulse or desire gradually disappears but merely that some 
disposition or tendency diminishes in strength with repetition of 
the stimulus. The proposition that all feeling presupposes cona- 
tion holds only when modified to read, or conative disposition 
and tendency. 

The same reflections hold good for the other phenomena 
of feeling, the sudden emotions of surprise and fear and for the 
inherited instinctive emotions. When, upon walking through 
the woods, I am surprised with the odor of flowers, this surprise 
has as its presupposition no specific experience of impulse or 
desire. Such surprise is possible with relative passivity of con- 
sciousness although, were there complete passivity, even sur- 
prise would be impossible. The situation seems to be that at 
least some general conative tendency toward objects other than 
the flower, objects of presentational activity, must be arrested in 
order that surprise shall arise. The surprise is not occasioned 
by the odor directly but by the arrest of some other conative 
interest or tendency. It does not, however, presuppose actual 
desire. The same may be said of the instinctive emotions. 
Such affects presuppose dispositional or instinctive conative 
tendency, not actual conation : they are themselves experiences 
which may with equal right, be described as feeling or arrested 
impulse. Finally there is the aesthetic feeling in which, while 
conation is presupposed dispositionally, certainly no conscious 
impulse or desire necessarily preceeds. Analysis shows the 
aspects with conative connotation, relaxation and repose, as 
well as the merely hedonic, but these are aspects of the total 
attitude, not different states except for retrospective analysis. 



3o6 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

(r) The conclusion of these reflections is then that a thorough- 
going dependence of feeling, as distinguished from conation, 
upon conation can be established only when we modify our 
proposition to read conation or conative disposition or tendency. 
This is practically the conclusion reached in the examination of 
the theory which makes conation determined by feeling. But 
when we have introduced the dispositional concept, that is when 
we have gone beyond the distinctions of immediate experience 
and supplemented them with conceptual constructions, it does not 
matter greatly whether these dispositions are described as feel- 
ing or desire dispositions. As Ehrenfels wisely recognizes, for 
worth theory — which is concerned with the changes in valua- 
tion and their laws, as determined by changes in dispositional 
presuppositions — it does not matter whether these dispositions 
are described as affective or conative : the laws of valuation 
will hold on either assumption. The conclusion which is of 
importance is, however, that the distinction between feeling and 
will is not one implicit in psychical content, but rather an appre- 
ciative distinction due to the intent of that content. 

3. Monistic and Genetic Theory of Feeling and Will. 
The chief outcome of our consideration of two theories of 
the relation of feeling to will which start with an absolute dis- 
tinction between them, as between the active and the passive, 
is that no thorough-going relation of dependence can be estab- 
lished either way except by leaving the sphere of psychological 
fact and supplementing it with the conceptual constructs of ph}'si 
ological dispositions. If, however, in order that we may fill 
out this relation of dependence, we include among the attributes 
of feeling restlessness-quiescence (which have the conative con- 
notation in them) it is doubtful whether anything is gained by 
this complete separation of the two aspects of experience. The 
* Identity ' theory denies that this distinction is fundamental, but 
asserts rather that it arises only from the difference in point 
of view from which we look at one primary content of conscious- 
ness. My own view is that this theory, rightly understood, 
affords the most satisfactory basis for a true theory of values as 
well as does justice most completely to the facts of analysis. 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL. 307 

We shall now turn our attention to the development of this 
theory, 

{a) In its most general form, it has been well stated by 
Wundt in the psychological part of his Principles of Morality} 
There we are told that these distinctions are purely conceptual, 
determined by the point of view from which we observe a series 
of inner events, the flow of consciousness itself being not con- 
cerned with them. ** Every act of will presupposes a feeling 
with a definite and peculiar tone : it is so closely bound up with 
this feeling that, apart from it, the act of will has no reality at 
all. On the other hand, all feeling presupposes an act of will ; 
the quality of the feeling indicates the direction in which 
the will is stimulated by the object with which the feeling is 
connected." 

This view is developed in more detail from the standpoint of 
psychological analysis of content in the last edition of his Psy- 
chology. Here the affect (or Gefiihlsverlauf) is taken as the 
ultimate of concrete affective-volitional meaning or intent and 
the affect (which as content, is a complex of feeling elements) 
may be called emotion, impulse, desire and will according to the 
nature of this movement or complex. ^^The question is no 
longer what specific conscious content the will is, but what as- 
pect an affect must assume to become volition." This specific 
difference he finds (i) in the character of the end feelings of the 
affect and (2) in a certain meaning or intent of the total affect 
which can be formulated only in retrospective logical terms. As 
to the first point, conation or will process is an affect which 
through its movement produces a final feeling which in turn 
destroys the affect. It is the fnal feeling of relaxation which 
distinguishes the conative process from emotion. Again, in 
the entire affect, when experienced as conation, there dwells a 
Zweck-richtung which is realized in the relaxation of the end 
feeling. Primary conative processes, such as impulse, are 
affects with this meaning ; secondary derived conation, such as 
desire and will, are affects in which certain single feelings and 
presentations, elements in the total affect, are singled out as the 

^ Wundt, Ethics^ Vol. I., 'The Principles of Morality,' pp. 6 and 7. Also 
Physiologiiche Psychologie (5th edition). Vol. III., chapters 16 and 17. 



3o8 WILBUR M. URBAN. 

motive for the final feeling of relaxation. This Zweck-richtung, 
which we retrospectively find the distinguishing character of 
affects with conative meaning, arises from arrest. So that * de- 
sire is not so much the preparatory stage of an actual, as the 
feeling basis of an arrested conation.* The actual affect which 
constitutes desire may be viewed as feeling or conation accord- 
ing to the point of view from which it is observed. All these 
concepts are finally logical artifacts and not fundamental dis- 
tinctions of content. 

A similar view was, in all its essentials, developed by Bren- 
tano * before Wundt's present formulation, and developed, more- 
over, from the point of view of worth analysis. His well known 
claim that in a given series of affective-volitional meanings, a 
vital series of adaptation passing from feeling to will (as for in- 
stance the following, sadness, longing for an absent good, de- 
sire to secure it, courage to undertake to secure it, decision to 
act), it is possible at no point to make an absolute distinction 
between feeling and will. It is rather a continuous series of 
meanings in which these two aspects can be distinguished only 
relatively and conceptually. 

The cnticisms passed upon this conception by the upholders 
of the dualistic views are instructive as showing the contradic- 
tions involved in the theories which make these distinctions 
ultimate differences of content. The upholder of such a dual- 
ism must put his finger on the point in the series where feeling 
ends and conation begins. Ehrenfels finds it immediately after 
the first stage of the series. Sadness alone is pure passive un- 
pleasantness. All the others have the active principle of desire 
in them. But both the superficiality and the contradictions in 
such an analysis become immediately evident. For what is in- 
volved? Clearly, to make the distinction at this point necessi- 

*The considerationt which were influential in this analysis of Brentano 
were precisely those which we have already taken cognizance of. If feeling be 
taken as identical with passive pleasantness and unpleasantness, valuation can- 
not be reduced to determination of conation by feeling, to pleasure causation. 
Feeling, it is true, viewed merely as pleasantness and unpleasantness, is pres- 
ent throughout the entire accommodative or vital series, such as that described 
above^ but it becomes less and less significant in the latter stages where the dy- 
namic tension aspect becomes dominant. Hedonic intensities become irrele- 
vant redundancies and we have practically intensitiless conation. 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL. 309 

tates the throwing of the emotions of hope and courage from the 
feeling to the desire side of the distinction, as indeed Ehrenfels 
does, and the logic of such procedure would be to confine feel- 
ing to pleasantness and unpleasantness as passive and unspeci- 
fied states. But even if this violence were done to appreciation 
and its descriptions, the superficiality of the analysis would 
come to the foreground. Can we say that sadness is pure pas- 
sive unpleasantness? Certainly not. Already in the relatively 
passive state of sadness we have the preliminary stage of the 
accommodative reaction, the vital series. This is to be found 
in the expansion-tendency of the feeling. The concentration 
of images in this phase of brooding sadness, the expansion 
tendency of the feeling, contains already an immanent activity, 
differing only in degree from succeeding phases of more ex- 
plicit conation. The fact of the matter appears to be that feel- 
ing seems to be rnere feeling, and passive, only when we sepa- 
rate it, retrospectively, from the functional whole, the vital 
series of which it is the first phase. Prospectively, in the first 
phase of expanding feeling, is already contained a sense of the 
strength and extent of the conative system arrested, which 
passes without a break over into the relatively more active emo- 
tions, desire and will, acts which follow as the arrest increases 
in strength and duration. From the standpoint of these, the 
initial feeling, viewed as a cause^ seems relatively passive. 

If, on the other hand, we seek, as some do, to find the point 
of distinction between the more active affects and decision, at 
the end of the series, the only point of difference that we can 
find is again an end-feeling of relaxation. The origin of this 
end-feeling, and of the characteristic sensations which go with it, 
is to be found in the simple fact that the general disturbance, 
displayed in the series of affects preceding the moment of de- 
cision, has found a definite motor channel in some specific bodily 
movement or word- formation. But to separate this final phase, 
this end-feeling, from the affects which precede it, is again to 
give us a mere torso, an unreal abstraction. The entire vital 
or worth series is one, with a continuity of affective-volitional 
meaning. Each phase may be interpreted as conation or feel- 
ing according to the point of view from which it is observed. 



3IO WILBUR M. URBAN, 

{c) The consideration of these two attempts to mark off the 
active and passive aspects of experience — to differentiate, in 
terms of elementary content, the affective and conative phases 
of a total vital worth series — shows that such an effort must 
prove unsuccessful. If we abstract from the meaning which 
the attitude has by virtue of its place in such a series, the dis- 
tinction between active and passive, and with it that between 
affection and conation, lapses. We have in these conclusions 
therefore, without further analysis, the grounds for our negative 
position with regard to the dualistic theories of feeling and will 
which find the worth moment in feeling conceived as passive 
pleasantness-unpleasantness or in desire, and for our criticism 
of any conception of causal determination between them. They 
afford positive grounds moreover, for our definition of worth as 
* affective-volitional meaning * and for the view that the worth 
experience is a concrete feeling attitude, in which references to 
conation are always present and conative dispositions always 
presupposed.^ 

4. Interpretation of the Monistic Theory ; Its Rela- 
tion TO THE Definition and Analysis of the 
Consciousness of Value. 
(a) Nevertheless, while this duality, this distinction between 
feeling and will, is not one of elementary content, it is still a 
duality of meaning which becomes fundamental from the appre- 
ciative point of view. They are two meanings of the same 
general content, but what determines the difference in meaning? 
How is this di&erentiation to be understood? Our answer to 
this question must be in the general terms of the Identity theory, 

' It is interesting to note that in a recent article, ' The Nature of Conation 
and MenUl Activity ' ( The British Journal of Psychology, Vol. II., part i ) Pro- 
fessor Stont, while defining conation ' as a complex experience ' which, how- 
ever, contains as one of its elements 'a simple and unanalyzable element 
nniqnely characteristic of it — an element from which the whole derives its dis- 
tinctively conative character ' (which* he describes as felt tendency and which is 
not identical either with motor sensations or affection), nevertheless admits that 
this felt tendency and a£fection, though distingnishable, do not occur separately, 
and he proposes to use the term ' interest ' to express the unity of conative and 
affective characters in the same process. I cannot see that this view differs 
essentiaUy from the one developed here. As analyzed by Professor Stout, these 
two aspects are retrospective abstractions. 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL. 311 

that is, that the difference can be described only in conceptual, 
logical, retrospective terms. By this it is meant — to make the 
general statement more specific — that this duality, this distinc- 
tion, is one of recognitive and selective meaning. The passive 
or active meaning is one which the attitude gets by reason of its 
place in the vital series and one which becomes explicit only 
when the attitude is viewed in relation to preceding or succeeding 
phases of the series. They are differences of genetic mode. 

If we seek to characterize retrospectively these two modes 
— if, in other words, we seek to convey their internal meaning, 
after the fact — we find that we can do so only in terms of cog- 
nition, by description of the cognitive presuppositions of the 
attitudes. According to Wundt, the special aspect which an 
affect must assume to become volition, is an immanental Zweck- 
richtung, and this aspect can be understood only as change in 
cognitive attitude, not in content. In this connection the at- 
tempt of Miinsterberg to characterize the distinction is instruc- 
tive. ** In feeling," he says, *• an object, independent of us, is 
interpreted through conation (Trieb). This Trieb remains, how- 
ever, as overtone atid as a help in apperception of the object, 
thought of as independent, which we judge in feeling. If we 
make the object dependent upon us, so that we perceive it as re- 
tained or excluded, then we experience conation and impulse 
but not, properly speaking, a feeling." * Now, to make the ob- 
ject dependent upon us is to assume its existence or non-exist- 
ence, as the case may be, that assumption being motived by 
the subjective control of the disposition presupposed. To think 
it as independent of us (which according to Miinsterberg's anal- 
ysis, we do when we feel rather than desire) is to judge or as- 
sume its existence or non-existence, the motivation of the cog- 
nitive act being, in this case, a control of a more objective origin 
and character. The significance of this analysis is to be found 
in the fact that the distinction between feeling and will (conation) 
is one which, in the last analysis, is reducible to a difference in 
the immediate functional meaning of a germ content and that, 
when this meaning is retrospectively described, such description 
involves recourse to cognitive presuppositions. 



j * Grundzuge der Psychologies p. 360. 



y2 WILBUR M, URBAN, 

There can be no doubt, however, that this difference in im- 
mediate functional meaning, though retrospectively describable 
only in terms of cognitive attitude, is really implicitly present 
prior to explicit cognitive acts of judgment and assumption, 
below the level of worth experience — that this duality has its 
germs in the simplest types of organic accommodation and habit. 
The * dependence upon ' or * independence of * subjective 
control, which on the higher level is explicitly cognized in acts 
of judgment and assumption, is implicitly felt in the funda- 
mental attitudes of habit, and accommodation after disturbance 
of habit. If we view in this more external way such a vital ac- 
commodative series as that described by Brentano, we find that 
what distinguishes the phases which are predominantly affective 
from those predominantly conative is the degree of inhibition 
of a presupposed disposition or tendency. Whether we call the 
phase in question feeling or will depends upon the point in the 
process of accommodation in which we, so to speak, catch the 
experience. In the Brentano series the first stages are char- 
acterized by the apprehension of the object as relatively inde- 
pendent of the subject (in this case the app^ehension is judg- 
mental) — and in introspection they are interpreted as feeling. 
In the later stages, the object is apprehended as more and more 
dependent, until in the last phases, the belief or judgment 
that it will be accomplished enters, and voluntary decision has 
been reached. Likewise, when Wundt describes the relation 
in the statement that * feeling may just as well be looked upon 
as the beginning of a conative process, as on the other hand, 
will may be conceived as a complex feeling process, and that 
the affect is a transition between both,' he is distinguishing dif- 
ferent phases of one accommodative process. 

{b) With this conception of the nature of the fundamental 
duality in meaning of feeling (as passive), and desire, volition 
(as active), we are in a position to justify our definition and 
analysis of worth experience. Feeling and desire are differ- 
ences of genetic mode, relative differences of functional mean- 
ing, not of content. The worth of an object is therefore its 
affective volitional meaning, and is given in feeling attitudes in 
which there is always reference, transgredient or immanental, 



NATURE OF FEELING AND WILL, 31 J 

to conation. We describe the worth fundamental as feeling, or 
concrete affect, because pure passive a&ect and purely active 
conation are limiting terms in the series and really exist merely 
as abstractions. But the affective-volitional meaning, or worth, 
of an object, namely — its relation to desire and conative dis-- 
position as interpreted through feeling — becomes explicit only 
on the cognitive level where accommodation is in the form of 
cognitive acts of presumption, assumption and judgment. It is 
the actualization of the dispositional tendency, either in feeling 
or desire, through these cognitive acts, which gives to the 
feeling or desire that meaning which we described as worth. ^ 

This leads us finally to the question of the relation between 
feeling and will, of affective-volitional determination in worth 
experience. We have seen from our critical analysis that no 
thorough-going relation of antecedent and consequent can be 
established between feeling and conation when conceived as 
two ultimate content qualities. The only sense in which feeling 
may be said to condition desire, or desire feeling, is that feeling 
always presupposes conative tendency and desire feeling dispo- 
sition. The disposition is the significant concept in our defini- 
tion. The feeling and desire dispositions are one and the same 
conative tendency and whether, when actualized, the disposition 
will give rise to feeling or desire depends upon the cognitive acts 
through which the object is brought into relation with the dis- 
position, these cognitive acts representing accommodations after 
inhibition of habit. 

The manner in which feeling is presupposed in all phases of 
experience described as desire, and conation is presupposed in 
all phases described as feeling, is well expressed in the second 
portion of Miinsterberg's analysis already given.* In feeling 
the conation (Trieb) is present with the perception as * overtone ' 

^ Cf. definition of feeling of Value in papers already referred to. 

s Miinsterberg develops this point more fully in another passage in the same 
chapter : *'Im Trieb ist die Wahrnemung des Gegenwartigen nur ein mitklin- 
gendes secundares Element des Gesamten Inhalts, der sich anf die Zukunft 
bezieht, im Gefiihl, dagegen, ist der triebmassige, anf die Zukunft bezogene 
Empfindungecomplex nur ein farbunggebender Nebenfaktor der Wahmeh- 
mung. Das Gefiihl ist ein Trieb im Dienste der Wahrnehmung, wahrend im 
reinen Trieb die Wahmehmung sich dem Streben unterordnet/' {GrundzSge^ 
p. 361.) 



3H WILBUR M, URBAN, 

as part of the meaning, as means of interpreting the situation. 
With equal right it may be said that in the predominantly pas- 
sive experience which we call feeling, conation is present (in the 
transgredient and immanental references) as overtone, as part 
of the meaning of the feeling. The various modes of this 
meaning we have already analyzed in the earlier articles. 
The importance of this entire conception lies in the fact that it 
disposes of that complete distinction between feeling as passive 
and conation as active which, when made absolute, leads to the 
dualistic conceptions already criticised and to inadequate con- 
ceptions of worth determination. It enables us to look upon the 
relatively pure feeling and will as limiting concepts and to in- 
clude all worth experience, even the aesthetic, under our general 
definition of affective-volitional meaning. 

In conclusion it may be pointed out that in this conception 
of the nature of feeling and will and of their relations we have 
a psychological basis for the study of the laws of valuation. 
The concrete laws of valuation are not reducible to general laws 
of feeling, abstracted from conation, nor of desire abstracted 
from feeling, but rather of affective-volitional process conceived 
as a whole. If we apply the term interest^ employed by Stout 
in the connection already referred to, to designate conative 
process in its two-fold aspect, we may quite properly speak 
of these laws as laws of interest, laws of acquirement of affec- 
tive-volitional meaning.^ 

* The MS. of thii article was received in September, 1906.— En. 



A FOURTH PROGRESSION IN THE RELATION OF 
MIND AND BODY. 

BY R. W. SELLARS, 
University of Michigan, 

If all signs fail not, the valiant inconclusiveness of philos- 
ophy is giving way. No doubt the lists are still crowded and 
battle cries resound but there seems to be, withal , a new eager- 
ness as of hope long deferred coming to pass. It is, then, nat- 
ural, to enquire to what this is due. If a squire who has his 
spurs yet to win, may venture an answer, it is, * To science, 
especially to psychology.' Now this is not spoken to encourage 
that lusty youngster, for he needs none, his boisterousness and 
self-assurance being, the rather, a cause of anxiety to the poor 
metaphysician who, at times, harbors the suspicion that he is 
pitied by this one of his household as a grey dotard. Be that 
as it may, the rejuvenation of logic which promises so much, 
in the way of a clarifying of our categories, appears to be the 
result of the stimulus of social intercourse with psychology and 
scientific methodology. (Cf. Baldwin's Thought and Things 
which Angell describes as *a striking example of functional 
psychology evolving into logic' The Studies in Logical Theory 
might be spoken of in similar terms.) 

With this as a sort of philosophical palinode, giving due 
notice of my peaceful intentions, may I advance a criticism of 
some recent tendencies by way of orientation ? I shall put it 
in the form of a question. May not function win out at the 
expense of structure through the erection of a false antithesis 
between them? Reconstruction, change, experimentation, all 
these are of great importance and deserve the recognition they 
are receiving, at last, but organization is just as real. ** Our ex- 
perience is constantly undergoing modification; there are no 
final truths." Yes, certainly ; but our experience is not a flux. 
We build up vast constructs whose complexity only the scientist 
(taking science in the sense of Wissenschaft) can realize. Of 

315 



3l6 . H, W. SBLLARS. 

course* I would protest against the imputation to myself of a 
radical misunderstanding of pragmatism » such as witnessed to 
in Joachim's essay on the Nature of Truth. Yet, must not the 
functionalist and, with him, the pragmatist widen the scope of 
their outlook to history and sociology and behold the slowness 
of this reconstruction in many important phases of human life? 
I am inclined to maintain that each individuars experience is a 
microcosm in the making (at least, this is its transcendental 
idea, as Kant would phrase it) and that advance is not linear 
but a complex process of development, working through organ- 
ization. (Cf . Stout, Analytic Psychology^ Vol. II.) That this 
is not contrary to functional views is evident from the following. 
<< Functions, on the other hand, persist as well in mental as in 
physical life. We may never have twice exactly the same idea 
viewed from the side of sensuous structure and composition. 
But there seems nothing whatever to prevent our having, as 
often as we will, contents of consciousness which mean the 
same thing.'* (Angell, this Review, March, 1907.) 

Howbeit it is not my intention to engage in general criticisms 
or commendations, which would be as valueless as uncalled for, 
but to re-analyze a problem which lies on the border between psy- 
chology and metaphysics and which, therefore, is of peculiar 
interest to both. To attack this Gordian knot may argue to 
some undue temerity or the breezy rashness of the novice but, 
perchance, it may keep the World-Mephistophiles engaged 
while a wiser spirit outflanks him. My earnest conviction is 
that here is the point where reality is exposed, as it were. Were 
I to need further defense, a recent utterance of a leading psy- 
chologist would suffice. *' No courageous psychology of voli- 
tion is possible which does not squarely face the mind-body 
problem and in point of fact every important description of 
mental life contains doctrine of one kind or another upon this 
matter." (Professor Angell, ibid.) 

In his brief reference to the problem. Professor Angell makes 
such a good analysis of the manner of approach adopted by 
recent writers that I cannot do better than quote. *< The position 
to which I refer regards the mind-body relation as capable of 
treatment in psychology as a methodological distinction rather 



RBLA TION OF MIND A ND BOD Y, 317 

than a metaphysically existential one. Certain of its expounders 
arrive at their view by means of an analysis of the genetic con- 
ditions under which the mind-body differentiation first makes 
itself felt in the experience of the individual (Baldwin). This 
procedure clearly involves a direct frontal attack on the problem. 
Others attain the position by flank movement emphasizing, to 
begin with, the insoluble contradictions with which one is met 
when the distinction is treated as resting on existential differences 
in the primordial elements in the Cosmos." Thus, considerable 
unanimity has been developing of late years in regard to the 
methodological character of the theories of physiology and psy- 
chology in respect to this relation. ** Our task in discussing 
their relation is not to transcend a given dualism, but to get rid of 
one which we have manufactured for ourselves by the manipula- 
tion of experience in the interest of certain special scientific prob- 
lems. Hence, as Mttnsterberg well puts it, we have not to find 
the connection which subsists as an actual fact, between body and 
soul , but to invent a connection in keeping with the general scheme 
of our artificial physical and psychological hypotheses." (Tay- 
lor, Elements 0/ Metaphysics^ p. 315.) Wundt gives an admir- 
able statement of his own position in his Ethics and, since it is to 
defend himself against misunderstanding, may be regarded as 
authoritative. *' Mechanical causality is thus a subordinate form 
of psychical causality. But in the case of all empirical relations, 
where psychical processes may be regarded from an external 
point of view, these processes may either be assigned to the 
complex of psychical events by virtue of their immediate char- 
acteristics or may be ranked within the causal nexus of mechan- 
ical processes by virtue of their external sensible aspect." 
(Wundt, Ethics y Vol. III., pp. 44, note, and 51.) " The psychi- 
cal and the physical are incompatible only because we have made 
them so in the development of our scientific description of the uni- 
verse. The distinction is a functional one, instrumental to the 
practical ends represented in their methodological demands." 
(H. Heath Bawden, Philosophical Review^ 1903, pp. 315-16.) 
With such agreement, one is, at first, inclined to wonder why the 
problem still remains. Why do some thinkers hold still to inter- 
action, while others vow allegiance to parallelism? Angell de- 



3l8 If. W. SELLA RS. 

cidedly hankers after some kind of interaction as he must, per- 
force* since he holds that the mind mediates between the environ- 
ment and the needs of the organism. As he expresses it : <<This 
is the psychology of the fundamental utilities of consciousness." 
(Cf . also, his Psychology ^ Ch. III.) On the other hand, Professor 
Baldwin advocates parallelism, yet insists on a psycho-physical 
evolution since he, too, holds consciousness to be no negligible 
factor. (Cf. Development and Evolution J Ch. I.) There must be 
some ghost here which will not down and, since metaphysicians 
are supposed to prowl about in weird and unseemly realms and 
delight in unsolvable problems, this must furnish a situation 
peculiarly inviting. My endeavor will be, then, to consider Bald- 
win's presentation in the light of recent definitions of the physical 
and psychical. I hope to give reasons for a fourth progression 
and to deduce some interesting conclusions therefrom. 

According to Baldwin (this journal, 1903), there are three 
•progressions': (i) the • projective progression ' which reads 
projects become personal-pr. and thing-pr. ; (2) the * subjective 
progression ' which reads personal-pr. become subject-self and 
object-self; and (3) the •ejective progression' which reads 
object-self become mind and body — the last alone representing 
complete dualism of body and mind. "We find that to think 
of body as presentation is in accordance with progression (3) 
to think other minds with it as presentation and this involves by 
progression (2) thinking of one's own mind as presentation. In 
other words, it is impossible on this hypothesis to take any 
other than a purely fhenomenalistic or presentational view of 
both sorts of objects, body and mind. The procedure which 
involves treating other minds as objective phenomena and, 
at the same time, maintaining the psychic point of view with 
reference to one's own mind is illegitimate." (/5/V/., p. 230.) 
"It is only in the one case of the relation of one mind to one 
body and that its own that such a point of view is still held. In 
the theory of interaction the attempt is made to justify this 
remaining case." (P. 239. Read context.) Here is where 
Baldwin is untrue to the genetic position he otherwise so well 
sustains. He does not go far enough. On the other hand, the 
psychologist when holding to some form of interaction is seeking 



RELATION OF MIND AND BODY, 3 19 

to adopt a fourth progression which he sees only vaguely. He 
is really trying to escape from the physical world considered as 
a closed universe^ a construction which as Wundt among others 
has pointed out is untenable. '^ In consequence, our experi- 
ence of the constancy of objects has crystallized into the notion 
of matter as an absolutely permanent substrate of phenomena. 
It is a concept purely hypothetical in character, but, it has proved 
very useful in the establishment of further principles ; and it is, 
in particular, the foundation of all those laws of constancy 
referred to above as giving to natural causality its peculiar 
feature." {Ethics^ p. 45.) The very nature of the postulates 
involves, a closed system. But, if the physical and the psychical 
are merely instrumental distinctions in experience, as modern 
logic seems to show, this cosmic character of the physical can- 
not be accepted. To resume : in the third progression, the 
object-self is looked upon as M'jB. This is read back into 
ourselves "because the theory requires that the view reached 
should cover the case of the relation of another person's mind to 
his body and that would mean his mind presented as object to 
an onlooker in the same sense that his body is Resented as ob- 
jeci.^^ {Ibid.j p. 232.) Baldwin's analysis here is excellent. 
Now, what occurs when we move from the psychological 
point of view, as this undoubtedly is, to the psychic? (Cf. 
Baldwin's Diet. 0/ Philos.j sub verbo.) Do we advance to a 
higher point of view, genetically speaking, or retrogress? I 
am strongly inclined to maintain that a new progression is the 
consequence of such a changed standpoint, and I would desig- 
nate it the progression of * duplication.' Each individual is now 
put on the same basis and regarded as having a unique psychic 
life. ** The only states of consciousness that we naturally deal 
with are found in personal consciousnesses, minds, selves, con- 
crete particular I's and You's. Each of these minds keeps its 
own thoughts to itself. There is no giving or bartering between 
them. No thought even comes into direct sight of a thought in 
another personal consciousness than its own. Absolute insula- 
tion, irreducible pluralism, is the law. It seems as if the ele- 
mentary psychic fact were not thought or this thought or that 
thought but my thought^ every thought being owned. ♦ ♦ * The 



320 ^. fV, SBLLARS. 

breaches between such thoughts are the most absolute breaches 
in nature." (James, Principles of Psychology^ Vol. I., p. 226.) 
I advise careful study of these pages. We hear too much of 
experience-in-general without mention of the owner. If this be 
the change that overtakes M' of progression (3) how must B be 
affected by it since the terms must be on the same level. In the 
third * progression ' B is my presentation, a part of my psychic 
experience, just as M' is. With the advance to this new pro- 
gression, B must be reinterpreted. If M' becomes unique, 
must not the other also? To many ears, to advocate the as- 
sumption of what corresponds to a psychic point of view with 
regard to the body, may sound strange, but, before a too hasty 
decision is reached, let us ask what it implies. Philosophers 
have so long resided in a world of unincamated sensations and 
thoughts, acknowledging, only in their uninspired moments, the 
facts of death and birth, that the mere suggestion of such an 
attitude may be looked upon as sub-dignitate. The conventional 
horror raised by the term * thing-in-itself ' has prevented a thor- 
ough reinterpretation of it in the light of recent biological and 
neurological facts. It is, however, noteworthy, that here, as 
elsewhere, the heretic is to be found preventing stagnation. 
Professor Strong has argued at considerable length that other 
consciousnesses are * things-in-themselves ' and James, in the 
passage quoted, seems to support similar views ; at least, his 
pluralism has, here, its raison d'etre. ** Another man's mind, 
then, is in the strict sense of the term, a non-empirical existence; 
something real yet inaccessible to my immediate knowledge ; as 
much so as material or mental substance and differing from them 
only in the nature of that which is inferred." (Strong, Why Mind 
Has a Bodyy p. 216.) The criticism one is inclined to pass upon 
Strong is that he did not approach his subject genetically and 
logically. Genetic social psychology would have prevented his 
famous theory of instinctive belief in other minds, and logic, his 
panpsychism. There has been, as a consequence, an unfor- 
tunate neglect of this valuable emphasis on the isolation of 
m^nds. To return. Must not B (organism) drop out of my 
experience in the same way that M' (mind) does? At present, 
there seems to me no possibility of avoiding this conclusion if 



RELATION OF MIND AND BODY. 321 

our genetic postulate is not to be violated, that the two terms 
mtist be on the same level. Let us cast about, nevertheless, for 
corroboration. 

It is not difficult to discover. That every individual's ex- 
periencing is dependent on what we call his organism is a com- 
mon-place of neurology and of pathology to-day. I could refer 
to the researches of Kraepelin, Ellis, Flechsig and others, but 
it would be a work of supererogation. Neurology not only has 
proved cerebral localization, but has discovered that conscious- 
ness arises only in a circuit of at least five neurones involvmg 
the Golgi cell type II. (Cf . an article, Journal of Philosophy^ 
Psychology and Scientific Methods^ where the present argument 
was given in outline. Vol. IV., No. i.) Now, it would be ab- 
surd to assert that another individual's consciousness is depend- 
ent on Bi my presentation ; at least, we do not usually credit 
ourselves with creative power of this kind. From this side, 
also, we are, accordingly, forced to admit that B passes out of 
my experience, just as M' did. Moreover, B does not, then, 
become part of the second individual's experience, else would 
his experiencing depend on a presentation in his experience. 
Strongest of all is, I think, an appeal to death. Upon the in- 
dividual's demise, the body remains. These are trite facts but 
their full significance has not, it seems to me, been recognized. 

If these arguments are correct, a 'peculiar form of Agnos^ 
ticism results which no one, to my knowledge, has developed. 
It will be the further task of the remainder of the article to 
accomplish this, and, in so doing, I hope to indicate the possible 
solution to two very important problems : What is the individual ? 
How can two minds know the same thing? 

I stated that this position leads to a form of agnosticism ; I 
might better have said it results in a reinterpretation of the 
word, * know,' and I wish to develop this to avoid misunder- 
standing. As is easily discernible, the thesis is purely natural- 
istic in its implications and outlook and has no place for an un- 
knowable of the Mansel-Spencer variety. We are limited to 
our experience? Certainly; but who would wish to transcend 
it? To those who have understood Hegel the very question is 
meaningless. The real and vital question is what sort of ex- 



3^2 Jf. W. SBLLARS. 

perience have we? In the first place, if my argument holds, 
* reality ' becomes a more inclusive term than * experience,' exis- 
tentially speaking. Once prove that the organism is more than 
the individual's experience and you can't stop short of the other 
objects in relation to the body. All metaphysicians seem to 
admit this. The organism is in the same complex evolving 
world the rocks and trees and air and waters are. The indi- 
vidual's experience agrees with reality in the sense that it 
mediates the individual's activity in relation to reality. It is as 
a lamp unto his feet. It is adaptive. Of course, the accommo- 
dation must not be limited to the so-called physical world ; the 
environment is also social, but the social is sustained by the 
physical, without it, the social could not be made perfect. And 
here I may include pragmatism, giving it its due place in a meta- 
physics. Thus Professor Dewey's view of agreement as equal- 
ling success must be interpreted by subsumption under the cate- 
gory of * accommodation.' Our universe is a process including 
organizations of various grades seeking adaptation. **You 
cannot get a fixed and definite color sensation, for example, 
without keeping perfectly constant the external and internal 
conditions in which it appears. The particular sense quality is, 
in short, functionally determined by the necessities of the exist- 
ing situation which it emerges to meet." (Angell. this Review, 
March, 1907, p. 17.) 

This doctrine, if granted, does, of course, give the death- 
blow to naive realism. I do not know how Professor Angell 
will relish the deduction of agnosticism from his thesis of the 
utility of consciousness, but that it points in this direction seems 
undeniable, though the word ' know ' must be reinterpreted in 
the light of the teleological nature of consciousness. We must 
not demand a sort of knowledge that is impossible, even un- 
thinkable, and then cry out about an < unknowable.' There is, 
first, the selective character of our sense-organs to be reckoned 
with. "To begin at the bottom, what are our very senses 
themselves but organs of selection ? But of the infinite chaos 
of movements, of which physics teaches us that the outer world 
consists, each sense-organ picks out those which fall within cer- 
tain limits of velocity. To these it responds, but ignores the 



RELATION OF MIND AND BODY, 323 

rest as completely as if they did not exist. * * * Attention, on 
the other hand, out of all the sensations yielded, picks out cer- 
tain ones as worthy of notice and suppresses all the rest. * * * 
The mind selects again. It chooses certain of the sensations 
to represent the thing most truly ^ and considers the rest as its 
appearances, modified by the conditions of the moment." 
(James, Psychology ^ Vol. I., pp. 284-5.) Thus, to know how 
things act and function is all that is necessary. You don't want 
to intuit some mysterious essence. Naturally enough, as soon 
as the absurdity of the old idea of * knowing ' is realized, one 
will not need to use the term * agnostic' To know about an 
ionized solution is not to intuit some mysterious reality or have 
a true idea of it, but to know how the ions behave. In short, 
we can handle things-in-themselves ; we can tear them apart, 
synthesize them, manipulate them in all sorts of ways, but can't 
be them. Stout has well brought out the importance of this for 
our knowledge of the world. ** He may ideally analyze and 
combine in a mechanical way what he cannot actually take to 
pieces and put together again. He may even assume constit- 
uent elements which are beyond the reach of actual perception. 
* * * Modern theories of atoms and molecules and of the 
motions of the particles of ether are examples of the highest 
development attained in this direction." (Stout, Manual of 
Psychology^ pp. 505 ff.) Electricity, which is becoming so 
omnipresent, playing an important r61e in electro-chemistry, 
physical chemistry and biology, is not something to be copied. 
We desire only to know how it acts under certain definite con- 
ditions. It is only in the case of other individuals of like nature 
with ourselves that we can speak of knowing, in the sense of 
content^ for we are in the same stage of evolutionary organiza- 
tion. Our agnosticism in comparative psychology in regard to 
the experience of the ant or fish should be instructive. As I 
said in a former article, ^ epistemology must reckon with evolu- 
tion, for, only thus, can it explain common knowledge by simi- 
larity of organization and relationships.' 

We have answered, then, tentatively at least, and, by impli- 
cation, the first question, What is an individual? Our con- 
clusion is naturalistic^ but not materialistic, since matter has 



3^4 /?. IV. SBLLARS. 

disappeared and left process. Everything points to the belief 
that conscious-experience is a functional part and expression of 
this individual in its selective relations to other individuals of 
various degrees of organization. Of course, when the grade of 
organization is verj' low we do not use the term * individual.' 
We confine it to molar masses usually, though science has a 
perfect right to extend its application. This position agrees 
with the results of evolutionary science, satisfying its prime 
postulate, continuity, and is monistic. This monism grants yhoith 
ever^ James* pluralism. As I said in the former article, ' dif- 
ferent individuals cannot have experiences, in any sense, nu- 
merically identical.' Moreover, I do not perceive the need of 
any world soul or absolute to bind them together. The con- 
nection which makes this a universe comes through the organism 
and its responsibility to its surroundings, and, here again, it is 
a relation of functioning, a dynamic unity, with free interplay 
of parts. The higher the grade of organization the greater the 
independence ; it is, thus, a freedom which is natural to the 
universe, and which is lawful. This will give a hint of the 
bearing of this hypothesis on ethics. 

There is reason, moreover, to believe that the mind-body 
difficulty in methodology will gradually solve itself as biology 
and psychology determine more the categories of our thinking. 
Body and mind will grow into one another. Habit seems to 
offer, at present, some prospect of a mediating factor, for has 
it not been called, rightly enough, the pragmatist's thing-in- 
itself ? Consciousness was looked upon as mysterious under the 
tyrannic reign of the exact sciences, with their impersonal and 
dualistic outlook, but it will secure its rights under a broader 
and truer naturalism. Organization is the scientisfs substitute 
for secondary qualities and is coming to its own. This offers 
a way of escape from the merely quantitative. This may be 
seen, in chemistry, in the study of color compounds, in the so- 
called stereochemistry, in recent physics, in the examination of 
radium, uranium and actinium. Physics is, thus, becoming 
evolutionary and cannot escape quality in some form or other. 

The answer to the second question follows logically. The 
identity involved in the common object must be interpreted 



RELATION OF MIND AND BODY. 325 

functionally, /. ^., < similar organizations in similar relations 
will have like experiences ' and will gradually come to recog- 
nize this likeness. This likeness can only be relative since indi- 
viduals differ and cannot get into exactly the same relations. 
Genetic psychology will trace out the process. This is a very 
simple solution, I may be told, but that is a merit. 

But, I shall be asked with some indignation, do you assume 
space to be actual apart from the individual's experience? Not 
space as an entity or as a form, I reply; still, I believe things 
to be mutually exclusive and in dynamic relation to one another. 
If, perchance, Kant's old dilemma be brought forward, as vet- 
erans usually are, viz., — if space is real how can mathematics 
hold? Hence, space must be transcendentally ideal though 
empirically real — I shall reply, it may be both transcen- 
dentally real and empirically real. Let me explain what I 
mean indirectly. In a recent article, Stout advances the thesis 
that primary qualities are actually more real than secondary. 
He is rather vague and does not succeed in proving his 
point. Incidentally, however, he makes a statement that fits 
in with the position I have advanced, that we can handle 
things-in-themselves and tear them apart. ** Finally, how can 
the internal content of a solid be resolved into any possible 
series of sensory presentations. Slice it as you will, you only 
disclose surfaces, not solid content but only the boundaries of 
solid content." (Aristotelian Society's Proceedings^ 1903-4, p. 
156.) Now, if the organism is, in the sense defined, a thing-in- 
itself and consciousness adapts it in its relations, we would ex- 
pect some mechanism to enable consciousness to shadow forth 
these relations. I suggest that Flechsig's theory of the two great 
silent areas, frontal and parietal, which are whirlpools of asso- 
ciation, the theory of local signs and cerebral localization for 
the parts of the body will solve this problem. There appears 
to be a sort of correspondence between the nervous system and 
the organism and its environment by means of the distance- 
receptors which tallies with the correspondence between con- 
sciousness and reality. The dominance of the distance-receptors 
of the. head is very important in this connection. (Cf . Sherring- 
ton, Integrative Action of the Nervous System^ Ch. IX.) The 



326 R, W. SELLARS. 

experience of the individual is, accordingly, a * microcosm in 
idea ' focalizing itself in special situations to meet the exigencies 
of the organism in relation to the macrocosm of reality. Real- 
ity bends back upon itself by means of the brain whose terrific 
complexity few realize. 

If this mirroring in consciousness by space of the dynamic 
relations of reality is a valid conclusion, we must not forget that 
our space is usually of two dimensions. We are seldom concerned 
with space above our heads or below our feet. The universe as 
a process must not, however, be interpreted in this fashion as a 
going forward as we go forward. That would be too anthro- 
pomorphic. It is a stereometrical process in which various 
organizations and systems of organizations beyond our con- 
ception are equilibrated, or are mutually conflicting and 
adapting. As a consequence, the dynamic relations of reality 
which stereometry shadows forth in a too passive way, 
because conceptual, appear to me more universal than time re- 
lations. Time strikes one as more personal than space. We 
always tend to look upon time as a linear process, a stream 
with a direction, the past-present-future flow. Accordingly, 
the statement that the universe is a process involves, for 
many minds, the flux-view or else some • far off divine event. 
Hold to this dynamic, stereometrical view of process as primary 
and all that is avoided. But, if space has an infinite number 
of dimensions, may it not have an infinite number of directions 
also? At least two possibilities, therefore, seem to be opeo. 
Time must be interpreted stereometrically, or it cannot be ap- 
plied to the universe as a process. Without developing this 
into its intricacies, this much can be said, that each irreversible 
* process-system ' has a time. Our solar system is an example 
of this. Each conscious individual, also, has his time series 
which he fits into the larger series. We have, then, perceptual, 
conceptual and common time. 

It would be impossible in an exposition of this nature to 
justify my thesis in detail, nor shall I attempt it. Contrast and 
comparison with some current teachings may serve, however, 
to give its general trend. ** What, then, is needed, I think, is 
a complete renovation of our ontological conceptions of mind 



RELATION OF MIND AND BODY, 327 

and matter in terms of a functional psychology of experience." 
(H. Heath Bawden, Philosophical Review^ 1903, p. 311.) This 
seems clear enough and most of us, I presume, would second 
the statement but when we find the term * experience ' used con- 
tinually in a vaguely impersonal way, we are disposed to ask — 
Whose experience ? Must not * experience ' be conscious ex- 
perience and, if we throw some hypothetical world-soul out of 
the reckoning, somebody's experience? If this were accepted, 
I would modify Dewey's doctrine of * Immediate Empiricism,* 
in accordance with it. *< Immediate empiricism postulates that 
things — anything, everything, in the ordinary or non-technical 
use of the term * thing ' — are what they are experienced as." 
{Journal 0/ Philosophy^ etc.^ Vol. II., p. 393.) I would restate 
this after the following fashion — In an individual's experience 
things are what they are experienced as. This would save the 
position from the strange reductio ad absurdum of * Reality as 
Experience.' For me, truth, experience, and reality are terms 
with different meanings, although, of course, experience is real. 

A recent movement, seeking to reinstate realism, seems to 
confuse logic and metaphysics. Personally, I do not under- 
stand how a functional psychologist, or one acquainted with 
Berkeley and Kant, could be a naive realist. The view pre- 
sented here, is of the critical sort. ** I shall, accordingly, use 
the word consciousness, to mean experience that is essentially 
the private and unsharable experience of one person and I shall 
conceive such experience which for each one of us is a certain 
streaming of objects of the private type as contrasted with objects 
that are public and directly observable by anyone so far as their 
own nature is concerned. * • • " (Bush, Journal of Philoso- 
phy^ etc.y Vol. II., p. 567.) Now this is, to me, a logical dis- 
tinction more clearly worked out by Baldwin in his Genetic 
Logic. (See pp. 146-8.) We are here engaged with distinctions 
in the social-individual's experience and, thus, the soi-disant 
realists are working out the side of organization neglected by 
the pragmatists. 

I have confined myself as closely as possible to psychology 
and logic. If the progression of duplication holds good, certain 
hypotheses might be propounded which would lead us farther 



Z2S /?. JV, SBLLARS, 

into metaphysics and science. We are in a world greater than 
ourselves and each must say, ^ De Profundis.' 

" Ont of the deep, my child, out of the deep, 
When all that was to be, in aU that was, 
Whirled for a million aeons, thro' the vaat 
Waste dawn of mnltitndinont eddying light — ** 

Yet, the reverse is, also, to be pondered — " Does Charidas in 

truth sleep beneath thee? If thou meanest the son of Aremmas 

of Cyrene, beneath me. O, Charidas, what of the underworld? 

Great darkness. And what of the resurrection? A lie. And 

Pluto? A fable, we perish utterly." (By Callemachus, Antho 

logia Palatina^ 7, 524-)* 

'The MS. of this article was received May 26, 1907. — Bd. 



SENSORY AFFECTION AND EMOTION. 

BY HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY, 
Phrapaioom^ Siam. 

So influential a voice as that of Stumpf raised in favor of 
what has been long considered a lost cause in the psychological 
world, encourages me to make the admission that for a number 
of years I too have regarded the cause as far from lost, and to 
add my mite to the discussion. I feel different about doing so 
because I am writing in a remote corner of the earth where I 
have no library facilities, and only a few of the leading current 
periodicals, which reach me irregularly and whose files extend 
back but a year or two. If, therefore, even my mite of a con- 
tribution proves to be no contribution at all, but a mere repeti- 
tion, I must beg for leniency. In any case I am well aware 
that I have nothing startlingly new to add. My only expec- 
tation was to bring together some of the recent discussions of the 
problem of affective processes in a somewhat new way. 

The paper which prompted this one is entitled * Ueber 
Gemtithsempfindungen,' and appeared in the Zeitschrift fur 
Psychologies I. Abt., Bd. 44, s. I. For the benefit of those who 
may not have Stumpf s discussion freshly in mind, I will give a 
brief summary of it. I wish to make it a starting point for 
what I have to say. 

Stumpf s thesis is in general that the sensory affections are 
themselves another class of sensations, coordinate with those al- 
ready recognized. There are two other views which have been 
held, one that sensory affections are mere attributes of sensa- 
tion, and the other that they are elements of consciousness of a 
different order from sensations. The first view he considers 
sufficiently refuted by Kiilpe's well-known arguments on the 
subject. The second rests chiefly on three distinctions between 
sensation and affection, (a) that sensory affections seem to be- 
long in the same class with emotions in that both are pleasurable 
or painful, and since emotions are not sensations therefore no 

329 



33® HBLBN THOMPSON WOOLLBY. 

member of the same class can be ; (3) that affections are sub- 
jective whereas sensations are objective ; and (f) that a^ections 
lack the spatial extension and localization which many sensa- 
tions possess. As Stumpf points out» (a) has no force for a fol- 
lower of the James-Lange theory of the emotions, but he is not 
an adherent of the theory. For him, too, however, the argu- 
ment is invalid because he believes that the classification of 
sensory affections and emotions in the same category is not 
justified. The emotions proper are, in his opinion, distinguished 
by a peculiar << kernel " which is distinct from the muscular and 
organic accompaniments, and which is entirely lacking in pure 
sensory affection. The distinction on the basis of subjectivity, 
{h) Stumpf considers unsatisfactory because not verified by or- 
dinary introspection. The * plain man ' does not regard pain as 
subjective in any other sense than some other sensations. He 
is entirely ready to admit that the sweetness of an object con- 
sists merely in the way it tastes to him, just as the painfulness 
of another object consists in the way it affects him. Further- 
more, it is not always true that sensations give information 
about the external world. There is a whole class of well rec- 
ognized sensations, muscular sensations from the internal 
organs, which tell us only of the condition of the body itself. 
Finally, the distinction between the ego and the external world 
rests upon a complex mass of experience and cannot logically 
be made the basis for a distinction between classes of elements 
of conscious experience. The third argument, (c) is easily dis- 
posed of since it contradicts verifiable facts. Pain and certain 
kinds of pleasantness and unpleasantness undoubtedly have 
both volume and localization as definite as that of many well 
recognized sensations. Since, then, none of the arguments in 
favor of making affective experiences a separate class of ele- 
ments holds, Stumpf regards it as logical to consider them 
sensations. 

The remainder of the paper is divided into three portions, 
a discussion of (i) pain sensations and the pleasure sensations 
arising in the skin and vegetative organs ; (2) the affective tone 
of the higher senses, and (3) applications. 

I . Stumpf of course discards the view that the sense quality 



SBA^SOR Y AFFECT/ON AND EMOTION, 33 1 

of pain is a pricking sensation to which is united an affective 
element of intense disagreeableness. It seems to him that only 
a theoretical prejudice in favor of separate affective elements 
has led to this view. The painfulness of a pain sensation is 
itself its sense quality. '^Pain is simply painful. The most 
discriminative psychology cannot change that." If one talks 
of agreeable pain sensations, he can only mean a state in which 
pain and pleasure sensations coexist. Although Stumpf does 
not stop to call attention to the fact, this statement reveals his 
opinion of another of the distinctions frequently drawn between 
sensation and affection — that there can be but one affection 
at a time in consciousness whereas there may be many sensa- 
tions. Stumpf, like Royce and Calkins, evidently does not think 
the statement introspectively correct. Of course if pleasure and 
pain are sensations, there is no more reason why they should 
not coexist than there is why one's face should not be warm 
and his hands cold at the same time. Very conclusive evidence 
for the fact that pain is a separate sensation has recently been 
furnished by the experiments of Von Frey, who succeeded in 
isolating pain sensations by peripheral stimulation. The exist- 
ence of delayed pain, both under pathological conditions, and 
normally after certain stimuli such as a needle prick, has long 
been known and is additional evidence of its sensory nature. 

Though we have made no approach to a similar isolation of 
pleasure sensations, Stumpf believes that we have examples of 
them in the tickling and itching sensations of the skin, and in 
the sense of bodily well-being. Whether these sensations are 
due to the stimulation of pleasure nerves, corresponding to the 
pain nerves, he leaves an open question. Their assumption he 
does not regard as necessary to the theory. Certain pleasant and 
unpleasant experiences must be conditioned by purely central 
activities, and it is possible that all pleasure is so conditioned. 

The algedonic sensations leave behind them memory images 
which bear the same relation to the original sensation as in the 
other senses. Kiilpe believes that the important difference 
between sensation and affection is that sensations can be repre- 
sented in consciousness whereas affections can only be reinstated. 
As we have seen, Stumpf questions the fact. He thinks it pos- 



332 HBLBN THOMPSON WOOLLEY, 

sible to have a memory of a pain in the same sense that one has 
of an odor, though the power to call up memory images is not 
universal in either case, and images of algedonic sensations 
easily pass over into hallucinations. 

2. The feeling tone of the so-called higher senses he con- 
siders under two headings, the case of excessive stimulation, and 
that of moderate stimulation. The former is easily dealt with. 
Excessive stimulation affects both the specific nerves and the 
pain nerves. The fact is most evident in pressure and temper- 
ature stimulations. It is in accounting for the feeling tone of 
moderate stimulations, especially in the case of tones and colors, 
that the difficulty comes in, a difficulty increased by the very 
slight intensity of the affective experience. The theoretical 
reasons for regarding the faint agreeable and disagreeable 
experiences as accessory sensations are the same as in the case 
of the more intense experiences . The greater difficulty in accept- 
ing the theory is that it is hard for us to so much as imagine the 
agreeableness of a tone or color in isolation from the given sensa- 
tion. If it is merely an accessory sensation, it should be possible 
with effort to form a separate image of it. Although Stumpf does 
not feel sure that such an isolated image has ever been formed, 
he thinks it not impossible that it should be. In the case of the 
more intense algedonic tone which comes with color and tone 
combinations, and with tastes and odors, some observers assert 
that it is possible to form an image of the affective tone, quite 
independently of the sensation to which it belongs. 

3. Stumpf believes that this view of affection has the advan- 
tage of offering a natural explanation of many facts which caused 
difficulty to the old theory. The complete and partial analgesias 
and hyperalgesias become cases of anesthesia or hyperesthesia. 
The delayed pain sensations cease to be an anomaly. The 
indifferent states cause no difficulty, and the independence of 
affective tone from sense quality is easily accounted for. Futher- 
more the facts known about sensation and the methods elabor- 
ated for its investigation may now become applicable to sensory 
affection. This formulation he also considers more helpful in 
the attempt to give an account of the genesis, both individual 
and racial, of sensory affection. 



S£2\rSOBY AFFECTION AND EMOTION, 333 

While I have long felt that regarding pleasure and pain in 
their simplest terms as themselves sensations, leads to the most 
satisfactory view of consciousness as a whole, I still think with 
Stumpf that there are introspective difficulties in the way. To 
my mind the greatest of them is in finding any experience of 
pleasure which at all corresponds in definiteness and simplicity 
with its supposed opposite pain. Stumpf suggests tickling and 
itching sensations as the typical pleasurable experiences from 
the skin, but itching is to most people a distinctly painful 
experience, and tickling easily becomes so. The traditional 
view of the two is that both are complexes of sensations. The 
nearest approach to simple pleasurable experience from the skin 
which I can find in my own case is the sensation arising from a 
gentle rubbing with some soft surface. There is something 
akin to a faint itching in this sensation, and it is perhaps what 
Stumpf has in mind as the typical pleasurable skin sensation. 

While granting the introspective difficulties, I still consider 
the reasons for Stumpf s view as of far greater weight than 
those against. The point at which I find myself at variance 
with Stumpf, which is of course the one I wish to discuss 
further, is that of the relation between the simple sensory affec- 
tions and the emotions. The question is one which Stumpf dis- 
tinctly shuts out from the present discussion, but he states his 
belief that the emotions are quite a different type of experience 
from the simple sensory affections, and that a sharp line should 
be drawn between them. The grounds for this belief he has. 
published more in detail in a previous paper to which he refers, 
and to which unfortunately I have no access here. However, 
he does in this paper state the point at which my view of the 
emotions, and consequently of their relation to simple sensory 
affections differs from his own. Stumpf does not believe that 
the James-Lange theory of the emotions furnishes a correct 
analysis of them. He holds that stripped of the various ac- 
companying muscular and organic sensations, an emotion still 
remains an emotion. There is in the emotion of fear a * kernel * 
of fearsomeness which is not destroyed when all the muscular 
and organic sensations have been dissected away from it. To 
me, and to all the adherents of the theory it seems equally 



334 HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY, 

plain that the emotional aspect of the experience does indeed 
consist in the mass of muscular and organic sensations. They 
seem to be an integral part of the emotion without which it 
would cease to be an emotion at all. In such a deadlock of in- 
trospective analysis, argument seems to be of little avail. What 
I wish to do is iirst to state a little more fully the view of the 
relation between emotion and simple sensory affection which 
seems rational to one who holds that Stumpf has established his 
thesis with regard to simple sensory affection, but who also 
holds to the James-Lange account of the emotions ; and second 
to point out the general conclusion with regard to the nature of 
consciousness as a whole which seems to follow. 

To one who combines these two points of view the relation 
between sensory affection and emotion is merely that between 
a simple and a complex state of the same type. As I under- 
stand Stumpfs analysis, the composition of a simple sensory 
affection, such as a pleasant sweetness, is the two sensations 
sweet and pleasant. The total state of consciousness may be, 
and probably is, much more complex than this, but none of the 
other simultaneous constituents are to be considered as integral 
parts of the simple sensory affection. Just how he conceives 
the emotional * kernel * I do not know, but evidently the stuff of 
which it is made up is something other than sensation. He 
would, I suppose, analyze an emotion into a central cognitive 
content, the emotional kernel, and as an adjunct, a mass of 
muscular and organic sensations. To which of these constitu- 
ents he would assign the pleasantness or unpleasantness of an 
emotion, I do not know. If it belongs to the emotional kernel, 
and is accordingly non-sensational, it is hard to account for the 
common factor between this class of algedonic experiences and 
the simple sensory affections. If it is one of the accompanying 
sensations, it is non-essential to the emotion itself — a view quite 
opposed to all accepted doctrines. 

But pointing out the difficulties in a theory which I do not 
myself thoroughly understand is probably only displaying my 
ignorance. Let me turn to the aspect of the question in which 
I feel more confident, the advantages of the alternative view. 
According to that view there is no sharp dividing line between 



SENSOJ^ Y AFFECTION AND EMOTION, 335 

simple sensory affections and emotions. The simplest con- 
ceivable case of a sensory affection, in the usual acceptation of 
the term, is a pain sensation without organic or muscular ac- 
companiments. It possesses but one quality and that is pain- 
fulness. The next simplest case is a state consisting of some 
other sensation, for instance, temperature, accompanied by an 
algedonic sensation as secondary. Beyond this there seems to 
be an unbroken series of increasing complexity occasioned by 
the addition of various organic and muscular sensations as sec- 
ondary, and by increasing complexity in the central perceptual 
or ideational content, which ends only with the most complex 
emotion. If then we analyze any simple sensory affect or emo- 
tion, leaving aside those simplest limiting cases which exist 
rather as logical limits than as actual states, we find the same 
constituents — a presentational or representational central con- 
tent with an accompanying mass of sensations in which pleas- 
antness or unpleasantness and muscular and organic sensations 
are prominent. When the central content is largely represen- 
tational, and the accompanying mass of sensations is complex 
and intense, we call the experience an emotion ; when the cen- 
tral content is presentational, and the mass of accompanying 
sensations not very complex, we call the experience a sensory 
affection. The decreased complexity is usually due to the lesser 
number of muscular and organic sensations. 

Within this series of experiences there are many on the 
border line between sensory affection and emotion which might 
equally well be classed with either one. Consider, for instance, 
the state occasioned by a sudden, unexpected, loud sound. As 
a very unpleasant sensory experience one would feel inclined 
to call it a sensory affection, but in this case there are present 
a sufficient number of muscular and organic sensations to give 
it an emotional tone. A friend who is peculiarly susceptible to 
colors can never describe the experiences they give her without 
telling of the cold shivers that run up and down her back. In 
such cases shall we call the state an intense sensory affection 
or a slight emotion? To me it seems immaterial. In fact, in 
most cases of sensory affection, careful observation reveals the 
presence of muscular and organic sensations which seem to me 



33^ HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY. 

to play their part in determining what we call the affective tone 
of the experience. 

The question is closely bound up with that of the number of 
distinguishable affective qualities — a question which is of course 
not decided by regarding pleasure and pain as sensations. The 
algedonic sense may be» like the temperature sense, one which 
possesses but two opposed qualities, or it may possess two op- 
posed classes of qualities, though the latter conception offers 
logical difficulties which I shall not stop to discuss further. 

Stumpf recognizes the possibility that the apparent differ- 
ences between the various kinds of sensory pains may be con- 
stituted by differences in the groups of organic and muscular 
sensations accompanying them, together with variations in the 
intensity and extensity of the pain sensations themselves, but he 
finds this explanation unsatisfactory in the case of the higher 
senses. It seems to him impossible to regard the unpleasant- 
ness of a bad odor or of a discord as having the same quality 
as a pure pain sensation. Most psychologists admit that even in 
the states usually classified as simple sensory affection there are 
present a certain number of muscular and organic sensations 
as well as the characteristic quality, and the algedonic factor. 
Many go even further and admit that this group of sensations 
plays an important part in determining the general tone of the 
state of consciousness. Angell in his new psychology (p. 331) 
says, * All consciousness, to be sure, seems to be toned more or 
less by the sensory reactions which arise from the constant over- 
flow of neural excitement into the muscles, and in so far every 
psychosis has an element of emotion in it.' But they are all 
unwilling to admit that this mass of sensations plays a part in 
determining the affective lone of consciousness. That they re- 
gard as a pleasantness or unpleasantness which must be a single 
simple factor. To make the case concrete — an intense sour 
sensation is usually unpleasant and is usually accompanied by 
distinct sensations of muscular contraction from the muscles and 
glands behind the jaws. The question is, would what we 
ordinarily call the unpleasantness of a sour taste be the same 
unpleasantness without these muscular sensations? To me it 
seems not. In other words the affective tone in this case seems 



SENSORY AFFECTION AND EMOTION. 337 

to me not simple but complex. The feat of isolating the mere 
unpleasant sensation from the invariable muscular portion of 
the experience is a very diflScult piece of introspection and one 
which we are not often called upon to perform. The unpleas- 
antness and the muscular sensations form a unified group, and 
it seems to me clear that it is this group which we mean in or- 
dinary language when we talk about the unpleasantness of a 
sour taste and insist that it is different from other kinds of un- 
pleasantness. This is merely to apply the James-Lange theory 
of the emotions to sensory affections as well. The affective tone, 
then, of a sensory affection is usually not a totally unanalyzable 
portion of consciousness, just as the emotional tone of an emotion 
is not. In the cases where there is least complexity there seems 
to be no difficulty in identifying the unpleasantness with the 
quality of a pain sensation. For instance, an intense but local- 
ized temperature sensation is accompanied by an unpleasantness 
which is readily recognized as of the same quality as isolated 
pain. In such an experience as a discord or an unpleasant color 
combination the unpleasantness is much less intense and the 
muscular sensations much more prominent. The unpleasant 
odor nauseates us and the discord sets our teeth on edge and 
makes our flesh creep. Here the identification is very difficult 
and to many seems impossible. The final appeal is to intro- 
spection and an introspection which is most difficult. One is in 
danger of being unduly influenced by the alluring simplicity of 
the view which recognizes but a single quality of pain or pleas- 
ure. Now I do not pretend to be able to analyze completely 
that which we call the affective tone of an experience. More- 
over, as I shall explain later, I believe this disability to be in- 
herent in the nature of the case. Nor am I able to isolate in- 
trospectively the mere unpleasant factor of a bad odor and of a 
discord and assert that they are of the same quality as pain. 
But it does seem to me quite evident that what we ordinarily 
call the unpleasantness of these two experiences is in both cases 
a complex, and that it is at least very possible that if we could 
isolate the mere sensation of unpleasantness from the more or 
less vague group in which it always occurs, we should find it 
the same in both cases. The logical difficulty of accounting 



33^ HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY, 

for the fact that such varied experiences are all classed as pleas- 
ant or unpleasant would then disappear. The case would be 
one of similarity on the ground of partial identity. 

In discussing the number of qualities to be recognized in the 
algedonic aspect of experience, it seems worth while to add a 
word of comment on the experimental method which has been 
employed to gain evidence on the subject — that of recording 
the modifications of circulation and respiration coincident with 
affective states. The work has been done under the assumption 
that pleasure and pain were an independent order of elements, 
but it would have the same application on the theory that they 
are sensations. The assumption underlying the experiments 
seems to be that if it could be shown that a given supposed ele- 
ment of consciousness were accompanied by a constant set of 
physiological changes in breathing and circulation, it would 
establish the claim of that content to be an element. In con- 
testing this view I may perhaps be fighting a man of straw. It 
is difficult to find an explicit statement of it in the literature, and 
some of the more recent work, such as that of Shepard, is clearly 
exonerated from any suspicion of it. Nevertheless, much of 
the earlier experimentation seems implicitly based upon it. A 
few years ago I took the trouble to make a comparative study 
of the series of investigations in question, summarizing the 
results in tables. The manuscript has never seen the light of 
publication, but is still in my possession, and by reference to it 
I can make some detailed statements of results. One series of 
experimenters, F^r^, Lehman, Mentz, Meuman and Zoneff, 
Brahn, Gent, and Boggs, find antithetical physiological proc- 
esses in the breathing, vasomotor, or pulse activities, one or 
all, which are correlated with pleasantness and unpleasantness. 
Another set, Angell and his co-workers. Shields, Binet and 
Courtier, Bonser, and recently Shepard and Kelchner, failed 
to find such a correlation.^ Recently Wundt and his students 
have attempted to furnish evidence for his tridimensional theory 
by the same method. Brahn and Gent both carried out elab- 

* A bibliography for the earlier part of this series of papers maj be found in 
an article by Angell and Thompson, PSY. Rbv., VI., 32, 1899 ; and for the later 
part in one by John F. Shepard, Am, J, of Psych,, XVIL, 522, 1906. 



SENSOR Y AFFECTION A ND EMOTION. 339 

orate and careful experiments. Each one found a set of results 
consistent with itself, and in accord with the theory — three 
pairs of antithetical physiological processes corresponding to 
the three pairs of affective qualities — but they failed to agree 
with regard to the exact nature of the physiological change 
characterizing each of the three affective pairs. Before dis- 
cussing the theoretical interpretation of these results, I would 
like to point out one more fact which is significant, the fact that 
those workers who failed to find the correspondence in question 
were those who used the greatest variety of stimuli, and that 
Wundt's students who failed to agree about the physiological 
changes characterizing the pairs strain-relaxation and excite- 
ment-depression, used very different stimuli to incite these 
states. For instance, for stimulating excitement Brahn used 
certain odors, high tones, and noises, while Gent used the sug- 
gestion that the subject should try to increase voluntarily the 
volume of one arm. Boggs, who repeated Brahn's work, using 
the same stimuli, obtained the same results. 

Now in the discussion of these results carried on between 
Titchener and his pupils, and the Leipzig school, there has been 
no question of the fundamental validity of the method. The 
mutual criticisms have been directed merely against methods of 
experimentation and of dealing with the curves obtained. But 
what can be the basis of the assumption that a constant set of 
physiological processes means an elementary conscious state ? 
To be sure, we have a general doctrine that two closely similar 
conscious states will have similar physiological accompaniments. 
It is further true that relatively simple states are more easily 
reproduced at will than complex ones. But the question of an 
element of consciousness is a question of absolute, not of rela- 
tive simplicity. It is more than possible that there are in con- 
sciousness certain relatively constant groups of sensations which 
are readily reproduced, and if so they would have relatively 
stable .physiological accompaniments. For instance, suppose 
that Wundt establishes his thesis that strain is always accom- 
panied by a given set of changes in pulse and breathing — does 
that prove that strain is an elementary conscious state? Cer- 
tainly not. It would merely prove that it is a relatively stable 



340 HBLBN THOMPSON WOOLLBY, 

and easily reproduced state of consciousness. In the experi- 
ments in which the writer participated some years ago, the most 
constant set of results obtained was that for mental application 
to simple arithmetical problems, but that was not considered 
evidence that mental application is an element of consciousness. 
Just how similar two states need to be in order to have the same 
sort of physiological accompaniments, we do not know, but it is 
fairly certain that they do not need to be elementary. I must 
repeat, therefore, that it seems to me impossible that the method 
in question should furnish any positive evidence on the question 
of the content elements of consciousness* 

If one adopts the view which has been presented here, a 
certain remodeling of the general formulations of psychology 
becomes necessary. Stated from the point of view of content — 
the aspect of consciousness in terms of which the discussion has 
been carried out — it means that the ultimate product of any and 
every analysis of the content of consciousness must be sensa- 
tions. To put the matter a little more accurately — when the 
final discriminations possible to analysis have been made, the 
discriminated contents are all sensations. The affective ele- 
ments seem to have met the fate which long ago overtook the 
conative elements. 

Whether or not the term element is one which can properly 
be applied to these simplest discriminable contents of conscious- 
ness is a further question which I should answer in the negative. 
The point has been ably argued by Miss Gordon.* The logic 
of her contention seems to me irrefutable. An element is, as 
she says, a content which is completely homogeneous and not 
further analyzable. •* There can logically, of course, be only 
one final element, since opposites always have a common 
ground." Now each sensation can be distinguished from some 
thousands of others, and must therefore have many grounds of 
distinction within it. I also agree with Miss Gordon in her view 
that the discriminated portions of consciousness do not exhaust 
its content. There is always present an undiscriminated back- 
ground of which we can, of course, say but little. The usage 
Miss Gordon seems to favor is to apply the term affection to this 

^Jour, of Phil,, Psych, and Set, Meth,, 1905, II., 617-622. 



SEJVSOI^ Y AFFECTION AND EMOTION 34 1 

undiscriminated background of consciousness. With certain 
concessions which, I take it, Miss Gordon really makes herself, 
the usage strikes me as most happy. I should wish to extend 
the term affection, or affective tone, to cover not only the undis- 
criminated background of consciousness, but the relatively 
undiscriminated portion which is with difficulty distinguished 
from it, as well. In so far as we have succeeded in making dis- 
criminations within this affective realm, the sensations revealed 
are those of pleasure and pain, muscular, and organic sensations. 
Miss Gordon seems to have such an interpretation in mind when 
she tells us that ' feeling is the relatively simple,' that * there 
are many different feeling qualities,' and that ^ an emotion is 
largely made up of muscular stimulations.' 

If this usage be adopted, a distinction must be made between 
the affective tone of an experience and its algedonic tone. The 
latter depends upon the intensity of the algedonic sensations, 
the former upon the total organic reaction of the organism to 
the stimulus. This reaction frequently involves sensations of 
pleasure or pain, but need not necessarily do so. The distinc- 
tion does away with one of the difficulties in the older formula- 
tion which always seemed to me very great. If the affective 
tone of an experience consists merely in its pleasurable or 
painful quality, then it must follow that every experience which 
is strongly affective — such as a strong emotion — must be 
■either intensely pleasurable or intensely painful, whatever else 
it may be. To my introspection, nothing could be a more 
evident distortion of fact to fit theory. The question as to 
whether a given emotion is pleasant or unpleasant is often very 
•difficult to answer. It was experimental work on the affective 
processes which first called my attention to this fact. When 
left for some time in a state of revery while the plethysmographic 
and respiratory records were being taken, emotional memories 
or ideas which caused marked modifications of the curve some- 
times occurred. The experimenter always demanded to know 
whether the emotions were pleasant or unpleasant. Somewhat 
to my own surprise I often found the question most baffling. 
Anger is, in my own case, the emotion par excellence in which 
the algedonic tone is slight, if present at all. Nor is the diffi- 



34 2 HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY, 

culty disposed of by the admission that pleasure and pain may 
coexist in consciousness. Many emotions, as Royce points out, 
are characterized by their simultaneous presence. In fact in 
my own experience, pleasant emotions, if at all violent, have 
an unpleasant element in the very fact of their intensity. Feel- 
ing myself given over to any violent emotion, even though I 
recognize that it is a desired experience, is in so far unpleasant. 
But there are other cases, notably anger, which are intense 
without being either pleasant or unpleasant, or both, to any 
marked extent. In other words, the emotionality of an expe- 
rience does not at all run parallel with its algedonic tone, as the 
accepted theory requires. 

The classical division of psychological phenomena into the 
cognitive, conative and affective realms cannot, on the view 
advocated, be regarded as based on the kind of content into 
which they can be analyzed. They are distinguished on the side 
of content merely by the grouping of their constituent sensa- 
tions, presentative or representative. Roughly we may say that in 
states which we call affective, algedonic sensations, and vaguely 
recognized sensations of an involuntary muscular or organic 
type are prominent. In those called conative, sensations either 
presenting or standing for voluntary movements are most im- 
portant, while the cognitive states are distinguished by the pre- 
dominance of the various sensations which mediate a knowledge 
of the external world. But though these differences hold 
roughly and for many states, the fact remains that no thorough- 
going distinction between these kinds of consciousness can be 
made on the basis of content alone. The function of the state 
in question must always be taken into consideration. 

Though the discussion has been carried out on the basis of 
content analysis, the whole matter may gain in clearness by 
being restated from a functional and genetic point of view such 
as that taken in Angell's Psychology. The condition for the 
appearance of primitive consciousness in the individual is a lack 
of ready-made adjustment to environment, requiring a readjust- 
ment on the part of the organism. At first this readjustment 
involves a general discharge of nervous energy throughout 
the body, bringing about a more or less aimless response of the 
whole organism. On the conscious side, since this is a first ex- 



S£NSOR y AFFECTION AND EMOTION, 343 

perience it is of course an unanaly zed experience. It is James' 
^ big blooming buzzing confusion,' which is nevertheless not 
recognized as a confusion ; it is an * original continuum,' homo- 
geneous to the experiencer. If we are to name it in terms of 
subsequent analysis, it must of course be called an a^ective 
state. It is in fact the only conceivable state which is pure 
affection. As experience progresses, responses to frequently 
repeated stimuli become organized in definite channels of dis- 
charge, while discrimination of content gradually breaks up the 
homogeneity. To the extent to which responses become or- 
ganized and adapted to the stimuli which occasion them, they 
cease to involve the whole organism, gradually lose the organic 
and muscular factors, and consequently their affective tone dis- 
appears. They may finally become reduced to mere percep- 
tions with little or no affective tone. But there always remain 
other situations for which there is no ready-made response and 
which do therefore cause a vague stirring up of the entire 
organism, i. ^., a strongly affective state. 

Thus it comes about that within any developed conscious- 
- ness we can trace a series of states from slight affective tone to 
intense emotion, corresponding to the extent to which responses 
to stimuli have become reduced to habitual reactions. In so far 
as responses are unorganized by habit, they belong on the con- 
scious side to the unanalyzed background of consciousness out 
of which definite experience is constantly emerging. Discrimi- 
nation within consciousness means the presence of organized 
response on the side of habit. The process of the development 
of intelligence is a gradual differentiation of the cognitive from 
the matrix of the affective, coincident with a progressive de- 
velopment of habitual activities. The primitive man is a man 
of feeling in that he is a man of few discriminations and simple 
habits. 

From the functional standpoint, one or two more of the dis- 
tinctions often quoted to prove the disparateness of sensation 
and affection lose their force. It is often stated that whereas 
sensations become more distinct and fixed in consciousness with 
repetition, affections fade and eventually disappear. The fact 
that affections fade and eventually disappear with repetition is 
exactly what we must expect if our account of conscious proc- 



344 HELEN THOMPSON WOOLLEY. 

esses has been at all correct. As we have shown, responses 
which were at first vague and general, and consequently strongly 
affective, become organized in definite habitual channels of 
discharge, and therefore lose their affective tone. To deal 
with the matter completely, I should have to add that I do not 
believe the truth of the statement with regard to the cognitive 
contents of consciousness. But that would take me too far 
afield. 

A point closely related to the one just discussed, though not 
identical with it, is that the cognitive and affective contents of 
experience are asserted to behave differently when attention is 
turned toward them. If attention is fixed upon a cognitive con- 
tent, it develops and grows richer, whereas an affective content 
attended to, fades and disappears. The classic example is that 
as soon as one begins to analyze an emotion, the emotion is de- 
stroyed. This again is what must be expected if an affective 
content is due to the reflex response of the whole organism to a 
given stimulus. As long as attention remains fixed on the 
characteristic stimulus, for instance, the thing that is making 
us angry, the reflex response continues and we remain angry* 
But suppose attention to be turned to the emotion itself. We 
begin to try to analyze the various sensations involved. Now 
organic or muscular sensations are not the normal stimulus for 
anger and therefore when * attention is turned toward them, 
anger ceases. The anomaly which met the old theory in the 
case of physical pain, becomes additional evidence for the cor- 
rectness of this view. Pain is not due to a reflex response of 
the organism, but to the direct stimulation of a sensory nerve. 
So long as attention remains fixed on it, it behaves like other 
cognitive contents — remains distinct and often increases in in- 
tensity. The way to get rid of physical pain is to turn attention 
away from it, and get it absorbed in something else. 

Since writing the above, I have come upon a review of a 
monograph by Rolf Lagerborg, Leipzig, 1905, which leads me 
to think that he has taken the same ground that I have here, 
and has gone much further in physiological explanations. I 
have, of course, not seen the original.' 

*The MS. of this paper was received May 31, '07. — Bd. 



DISCUSSION. 

AN EXPERIMENTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS.^ 

I wish to give a brief sketch of a course in esthetics for which — 
it seems to me — there is a real demand. I have given this course 
repeatedly and am under the impression that the students who took it 
derived more benefit from it than they would have derived from a 
course following the old-fashioned lines, defining the ^ beautiful ' and 
the ^sublime' and informing the student on the historic development 
of esthetic theory from Plato and Aristotle up to the year 1907. I 
present this sketch of a course in order to call forth criticism and 
discussion. 

By an experimental course I do not mean a technical course in 
which the student is taught how to perform experiments and take 
measurements, but a course in which theoretical knowledge is con- 
veyed by the help of experimental demonstrations in class. 

A student who specializes in philosophical studies wants, of course^ 
information on the history of esthetic theory. Such information, how- 
ever, can be obtained as well from reading books as from listening to 
a lecturer. The number of students who want such a course is small 
compared with the numberwho find themselves again and again puzzled 
by questions like the following : 

Why does Mr. X enjoy this piece of sculpture which is to me little 
more than a piece of stone ? Why does Mr. T say that he does not 
care for that picture with which I decorated my study ? Why are 
some people able to spend delightful hours in the galleries of a museum, 
while to me the most delightful moment during a visit to a gallery \% 
the one when I discover that I am approaching the exit? 

Answers to such questions cannot easily be found in books. The 
student who seeks these answers needs the guidance of an instructor. 
And the course which I wish to describe attempts to help the student 
to find them experimentally, to derive them from his own observations 
made in class. 

It is plain that in a course of this kind one cannot require the 
student to have any knowledge of the history of art, or any familiarity 

1 Read before the joint meeting of the Western Philosophical Association 
and the North-Central section of the American Paychological Association^ 
Chicago, March, 1907. 

345 



34^ EXPERIMENTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS. 

with the technic of drawing, painting, modeling, or carving. The 
very students who do not possess such knowledge and have but little 
time to acquire it, are most likely to ask questions like the above and 
seek for answers. I do require, however, that the student shall pre- 
viously have taken a year's course in general psychology covering the 
whole field, from sense perceptions to emotions, from the ordinary 
activities of daily life to the unusual actions of a temporarily or chron- 
ically abnormal human being. Otherwise the course might assume 
the features of a kindergarten course instead of those of a college 
course; and only thus can time enough be found to obtain experi- 
mentally, within a single semester, answers to the questions of prac- 
tical esthetics, answers which are to be of permanent benefit to the 
student in his conduct of life. 

Such words as ^ beautiful, sublime, ugly ' are scarcely ever used 
during the course; and their use is discouraged. The use of such 
words would unavoidably narrow down, from the start, the field of 
esthetic inquiry to the limited area covered by the meaning accidentally 
associated with them in the student's mind. To illustrate this, let me 
mention the case of a student yrho — at the end of the course in 
question — says that he has never applied and will never apply the 
word * beautiful ' to a statue in the nude, but that the course has made 
him comprehend why perfectly decent people will place such statues 
in a museum or use them to decorate their homes. Another student 
says that he can never call a Verestchagin war scene anything but 
disgusting, but that he has come to understand why such a painting 
may properly find its place in a public or private museum or library. 

The most serious mistake which can be made in an experimental 
course of instruction in any science consists in overemphasizing those 
experimental methods and results which are predominant in the recent 
research literature of that science or which have been particularly 
investigated by the individual instructor giving the course. Much 
harm has been done to psychology in general by this mistake having 
been made by some men in charge of psychological courses. The 
result has been the still wide-spread belief of the public that an experi- 
mental course in psychology consists in discussing and performing all 
manner of experiments in order to test the validity of the Weber- 
Fechner law — a law which is of but little more concern to the psy- 
chologist than to the representative of many another science. I have 
tried to avoid this mistake, to have in mind the interest of the 
student rather than that of a few investigators who happen to be his 
contemporaries. 



DISCUSSION. 347 

Instead of beginning the course with a definition of ^ the beautiful/ 
or of * the esthetic ' or * art^' I begin with a practical problem by show- 
ing the student two lantern slides^ representing actual scenery, and 
asking him to answer the following question : If you found yourself 
momentarily free of all mental occupation and had nothing else to do 
in order to while away your time but to inspect either the one or the 
other of these pictures, which one would you select for this purpose ? 
This is a question which erery student immediately comprehends and 
feels entirely competent to answer. The pictures used for this 
purpose are not reproductions of works of art. I do not wish to give 
the student from the start the impression that the esthetic experience 
is restricted to the perception of artistic creations. The pictures are 
lantern slides from a collection intended to serve the purpose of 
instruction in geography, representing scenery from all parts of the 
globe, some by chance ranking rather high esthetically, some ranking 
exceedingly low. But this variety of degree is an advantage rather 
than a disadvantage. I have divided these slides into two groups, 
according as they contain water in the shape of ocean, lake, river, 
brook, or no water. The reason for this division will become clear 
later. Each g^oup contains about twelve or fifteen slides. 

I then show the class the pictures of one of the above groups in 
pairs, presenting each pair long enough for each member of the class 
to answer the question as to which he would select for looking at if 
that was his only possibility of whiling away his time. The number 
of votes of the class are then recorded in a list containing as many 
columns as there are pictures. Picture No. i is first presented together 
with No. 2, and the votes are recorded in the proper columns. No. i 
is then presented with No. 3, and so on until No. i has been shown 
together with all the other pictures of the group. Now No. a is shown 
together with No. 3, with No. 4, etc. This takes of course several 
hours* The votes recorded in each column are then added together. 
The sums thus obtained, of which the largest are many times mul- 
tiples of the smallest, can be regarded as representing a measure of the 
relative esthetic value of the pictures for the group of human beings 
making up the class. 

In order to enable the class to discuss the pictures, they must be 
g^ven names. I do not tell the class the actual names, because these 
would inevitably influence the judgment, a fact which agrees with a 
statement recently made by Professor Lillien Martin who found that 
even knowledge of the artist's name influences the esthetic judgment 
concerning a painting. Being told that of two river views one rep- 



34* BXPBRIMBNTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS. 

resents the Rhine valley, the other an unknown region in Canada, the 
subject feels constrained to prefer the Rhine. I therefore ask the class 
to propose themselves suitable names by which to refer to the pictures. 

While it is very important to obtain esthetic measurements valid 
for the class as a whole, the individual differences must not be obliter- 
ated. I therefore have each student — in particular those who cast 
iheir votes with the minority — write down in his note book a state- 
ment of the fact that he belongs to the majority or minority and also 
of the reasons — if he is conscious of any — why he would select this 
picture rather than the other. 

Having thus collected material for discussion, it is our task to 
explain the relative values recorded by analyzing out of the pictures 
the esthetic factors influencing the judgment. For this analysis we 
need, of course, some guidance. What could guide us better than a 
brief description of the mental processes going on in an artist when he 
creates a work of art which is to exert esthetic influence over others? 
I therefore study with the class a description of these mental proc- 
esses, and I use the description given by the distinguished German 
sculptor Hildebrand in his book The Problem of P^rm in PcUnting 
and Sculpture. Unfortunately, there is, as yet, no English version of 
the book, and the German edition is written in a style so difficult to read 
that the book cannot be given into the students' hands. I therefore 
present its contents in lectures. When I give the course again, an 
English edition of the book will be out. 

I shall give here a brief outline of Hildebrand's book in order to 
make clear its contents and to show how these contents can help the 
student to analyze the esthetic experiences above referred to. There 
has been a good deal of discussion among writers on esthetics as to 
the question what Hildebrand's esthetic theory is and how it is related 
to other theories. As a matter of fact the book contains no esthetic 
theory at all. Hildebrand is the last person in the world who would 
claim to be a scientist, the promoter of a scientific theory, even in a 
science so closely related to art as esthetics. To comprehend his 
book, to use it to the best advantage, we must regard it, not as a the- 
ory of esthetics, but as the confessions of an artist with respect to 
his mode of thought when he is engaged in productive work. And 
this very fact that it is not a theory, but a confession of thought, 
makes the booklet extremely valuable in an experimental course on 
esthetics. 

Hildebrand is chiefly a sculptor; but he asks us to regard him not 
merely as a sculptor; but as a painter and architect as well, when 



DISCUSSION, 349 

reading his confessions. He tells us that when he creates a work of 
art he is conscious of one predominant aim, and this is : to make the 
work of art clear and impressive as a visual percept. All his vary- 
ing thoughts during the process of artistic production are governed by 
this universal aim. The aim has three main aspects: (i) The per- 
ception must be a visual perception; (2) the perception must be 
clear; (3) the perception must be impressive. 

That the purpose of painting, of sculpture, or of architecture is 
visual perception, would be a superfluous statement were it not that 
writers who are not — as Hildebrand is — productive in art, had actu- 
ally tried to convince us otherwise. E, ^., A. Schmarsow tells us 
that * the aim of the painter's art is the representation of the interre- 
lations existing between the things of the world, i. e.^ of the unity of 
nature,' which obviously is the aim of the scientist, but not at all of 
the artist. 

Hildebrand tells us that he cannot create the clearest and most im- 
pressive percepts in works of art unless the creative imagination is 
visual too ; and the psychologist will readily understand this, for it is 
no less true in psychology than elsewhere that like begets like. Not 
that other kinds of imagery are to be excluded : they are as important 
here as elsewhere in human activities. But they have to be translated 
into visual imagery before they influence the artist's productive hands. 
And when the artist tests his own work for its esthetic value, he tests 
it by the eye, as a visual percept, without any aid on the part of other 
sense organs. No matter whether his work is a painting or a statue 
or a building, its esthetic value is based exclusively on the character- 
istics which it presents as a visual percept. 

What, then, are the requirements to be fulfilled in order to have a 
visual percept which is both clear and impressive? The artist tells us 
that, to have the highest possible degree of clearness, the external 
nervous stimulation must be as homogeneous as possible. The psy- 
chologist will he ready to understand this. It is but natural that, the 
more heterogeneous the external stimulations, the greater the possibil- 
ities for distraction of the attention, the less, therefore, the probability 
of that unity of mental activity which we refer to by the word clear- 
ness. Now, everybody knows that even in applying no other sense 
organs to a given situation than our eyes, the external stimulations are 
not exclusively those of retinal sensory elements, but also — as a rule — 
certain stimulations belonging to the sensory region usually referred to 
by the term kinesthetic. This is the case because, in ordinary vision, 
our eyes move, and some of these movements, those of convergence 



350 BXPBRIMBNTAL COURSE IN BSTHBTICS, 

and those of accommodation , resulting from the muscle fibers without 
and within the eyeball, furnish sensory stimulations of much impor- 
tance for the interpretation of the retinal image. But these same 
kinesthetic stimulations, being heterogeneous with the purely visual 
impressions, are a possible and probable source of distraction to the 
artist* s mind. He does not test, therefore, the esthetic value of his 
work by looking at it from close by, but by inspecting it from a suffi- 
cient distance, where convergence or accommodation no longer play 
their r61es in the process of perception. And, likewise, the imagina- 
tion, which controls his hand, always consists in visual imagery repre- 
senting things as seen from a distance. For the artist, then, all the 
esthetic values of visual perception are to be analyzed out of the 
percept of a distance picture, of a pure visual projection^ as we may 
term it. 

Another source of distraction to the artisf s mind, interfering with 
the requirement of the highest possible degree of mental clearness, is 
the fact that in ordinary vision our consciousness does not directly cor- 
respond to our retinal image, but is manufactured out of two different 
images having their details more or less displaced relative to each 
other. Again the psychologist will readily understand the artisf s 
feeling of a lack of unity, of a deficiency in the mental clearness to be 
desired, when his consciousness corresponds, not to the direct sensory 
stimulation, but to an indirectly stimulated nervous process, made up 
for the occasion according to nervous habits well suited to the prac- 
tical demands in the struggle for life, but not adapted to the purpose 
of a playful activity of the mind. This lack of clearness is eliminated 
by the artist in the same manner as the one just mentioned, simply by 
making the visual projection, the distance picture, which is identical 
for both eyes, the exclusive material of both his productive and 
receptive mental activities. 

Further conditions, however, have to be fulfilled in order to give 
the visual percept the highest possible degree of mental clearness. 
The artist requires that the act of forming a percept, a unitary group, 
out of the innumerable sensation elements presented be made as easy 
as possible so that no effort may be experienced, but the playful atti- 
tude of the mind be preserved. For this purpose the horizontal and 
vertical directions in the visual field must be clearly indicated by 
familiar objects such as a tree standing on level ground and throwing 
a shadow upon it. Other means may be used, of which the artist 
makes no direct mention, but which ps3xhologists have begun to study 
in recent years, actual symmetry of form, or, more frequently, a quasi- 



DISCUSSION. 351 

symmetry of attention values. Hildebrand, since he does not pretend 
to offer a scientific theory, makes no effort to obtain a complete list of 
the various factors which can be pressed into service. He is satisfied 
with emphasizing the mere necessity of clearness in the two dimensions 
of the visual field, by whatever means this clearness may be brought 
about. 

More important yet than the manner in which the objects are 
arranged in two dimensions is their arrangement with respect to their 
ability to arouse in us — in spite of our being limited to the visual 
projection — an absolutely clear and effortless perception of depth re- 
lations. Here we have a large field of esthetic investigation in which 
practically nothing has been done thus far by psychologists. Hilde- 
brand tells us that he obtains his end chiefly by two means, by arrang- 
ing the various objects in a comparatively small number of successive 
planes, and by choosing the objects for representation in the various 
planes in such a manner that the observer cannot help reading off 
their depth values from the front of the picture into its depth. 

It is but natural that the clearness, the so-called repose or unity, 
of the perception must be greatly enhanced by the objects not being 
scattered all over the three-dimensional space but being found in a 
small number of planes, meaning by ^ planes,' of course, layers of a 
certain thickness. If they are arranged within these planes in such 
ways that each plane offers a perfectly clear two-dimensional percept, 
there is but one problem left, that of uniting these planes in one act of 
perception, in order to obtain a perfectly clear percept of the total 
space with all its contents. 

For the purpose of uniting the planes Hildebrand's chief require- 
ment is that the observer be made to read off the distance values of 
the planes in a serial order, beginning from the front. Again there is 
no difficulty in understanding this requirement on psychological 
grounds. Whenever our eyes in actual life sweep along a line in the 
direction of the third dimension, as when we look over our writing 
desk, or over the lawn in front of our house, we practically without 
exception fixate a near object first and farther and farther points of 
interest in succession until we have reached the most distant point 
visible. Having acquired a strong habit of this kind, it is plain that 
the ease of perception would suffer if, in inspecting a picture, the 
imaginary eye movement would proceed otherwise, i. «., if any plane 
other than the front plane of the picture (in painting ; and no less in 
sculpture or architecture) would attract our attention first, and the 
less distant plane or planes later. Here again Hildebrand does not 



35 2 BXPBRIMBNTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS, 

attempt to lolve the psychological problem, what the conditions of 
visual sensation or perception are which favor and which are opposed 
to this direction of our reading off movement. He is satisfied with 
emphasizing the fact as being of the greatest importance in his own 
creative thought and with illustrating it by a few examples. 

The third requirement is that of impressiveness. C learness obtained 
by emptiness of the situation would have little, if any, esthetic value. 
The spatial contents presented to the eye must have a meaning, must 
represent life. The artist tells us that life does not invariably mean to 
him actual movement ; it may mean merely possible movement. The 
spatial contents presented arouse in the artist feelings of activity or of 
character by which activity is governed. And these feelings can be 
strong, the impressiveness of the visual percept can be great only when 
the spatial contents consist of objects which possess typical spatial 
forms, which are types of activity or character, for example a sinewy 
hand, or a strong jaw, and when the spatial arrangement itself fulfills 
the requirements of clearness so that there is mental energy enough 
available to perceive the life of the spatial contents, subtracting the 
energy necessary to perceive the total space. Life must be represented 
in the picture, but the question what kind of activity, what kind of 
character this life consists in, is regarded by Hildebrand as a question 
which does not concern the artist as artist, which concerns only the 
individual as individual. 

Having made the students acquainted with the artist's mode of 
thought as confessed by himself and just given in outline, and, indeed, 
while making them acquainted with these thoughts, I ask the students 
to analyze out some of the esthetic factors effective in our experiments 
by trying to apply the artist's mode of thought to the pictures which 
we arranged in a series according to their esthetic effectiveness. The 
students now easily separate the individual factor from factors which are 
of universal application. One of them is much interested in a picture 
because a group of human beings apparently resting after a day of 
labor are visible in the foreground and arouse a strong emotional 
response. Another one prefers a picture because it contains a hilly 
pasture reminding him of childhood days. Aside from such indi- 
vidually effective factors there are now discovered features which sre 
of more universal application, which exert a determining influence on 
the esthetic judgment of all the members of the class. And it is at 
once admitted that the latter factors are those which should be studied 
here, by this class, for that we have our individual preferences can 
scarcely be regarded as a fact to be studied in a course on esthetics, 



DISCC/SSION. 353 

but, perhaps, in a course on individual psychology. It is also admitted 
that thoughts of human toilers, of a playground of our childhood days, 
of a Madonna and Child, so far as they are subjects of esthetic inquiry, 
are not exclusively based on visual perception, but may be conveyed 
by poetry or prose, and must therefore be studied in a further branch 
of esthetics, separate from the problems which have come thus far to 
constitute our center of interest. 

Why, then, is a certain picture clearer and more impressive than 
another picture and receives thus a majority of the votes? Some of 
the instances illustrating the rules of two- and three-dimensional 
arrangement are noticed by the students directly, others by the help 
of an indirect method to be mentioned farther on. Such facts as real 
symmetry, or quasi-symmetry may be observed directly. The effect of 
the presence of water, referred to above, may also largely be grasped 
by direct inspection. Not that water in itself is particularly pleasing 
to look at. Not everyone has pleasant associations derived from 
awimming or boating or other water sports or from the pleasant expe- 
rience of washing down his food. But water nearly always conveys 
a clear idea of the horizontal plane and thus aids in the perception of 
the spatial relations of other things. 

The indirect method referred to is particularly useful in the study 
of the spatial structure in the direction of the third dimension, although 
it is entirely applicable and useful also for the study of two-dimen- 
sional arrangement. The method consists in cutting off from above 
or below, from the right or the left, larger or smaller pieces of the 
picture and studying the new picture with respect to the same question 
with which we started the experiments. This cutting off is easily done 
with lantern slides by means of strips of card board. We observe that 
frequently the resulting picture seems preferable to the original. And 
we have little difficulty in observing that this is the case because of the 
removal of an object which does not obey the rules of arrangement in 
planes and of reading of£ the successive planes from the front to the 
back. We observe that a picture which was g^ven a rather low rank 
in our experiments can thus often be raised to an equal rank with pic- 
tures which previously appeared superior. Nevertheless, the life and 
character of the piece of nature represented may have remained prac- 
tically the same as before. We can use these observations as illustrating 
the fact that in esthetics — if not in general, at least m esthetics as 
applied to art — the formal principles are of more fundamental im- 
portance than those concerning content, that the mere 'fact that a piece 
of nature, because of some accidentally acquired associations, pleases 



354 EXPERIMENTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS. 

someone is no excuse for representing it in art, unless its form makes 
it worthy to be represented. I do not mean, of course, that without 
this method of cutting off pieces of the picture we could not get along. 
Indeed, to some pictures it cannot be successfully applied. We use then 
the direct method for the study of the esthetic effectiveness of the arch- 
itectonic of the picture. And here we observe another, indeed the 
chief effect of the presence of water in a landscape. A water surface 
easily breaks up the infinite number of details into readily perceptible 
groups. And if these groups happen to arrange themselves into larger 
groups, into a few successive planes, and if nothing counteracts, if 
everything aids our tendency to read off these planes from the front to 
the back, the esthetic effect is great. 

It is impossible to enumerate here all the detail questions which 
can be asked and discussed by students and instructor. I wish to men- 
tion only one kind of such questions, those with respect to the means 
by which our tendency to read off the spatial values from the front to 
the back can be aided, and with respect to the opposite effect which 
must be avoided. Hildebrand in his book gives a few instances an- 
swering this question. But many more may be found if we study 
pictures as my students do this in class. E. ^., if one of the ob- 
jects of the first plane is conspicuous by mere size, or color, or light 
contrast, but otherwise uninteresting, it will serve to attract our atten- 
tion at once to the first plane without unduly keeping it there. Facts 
like the one just stated appear cut and dried when stated in abstract 
form, but readily become a valuable addition to the student's store of 
knowledge if he derives them himself from immediate observation, 
applying the scientific laws which he has previously acquired in a 
course in general psychology. 

Studying what I called the impressiveness of a visual percept by 
analyzing landscapes, the student easily discovers that the impressive- 
ness of a visual percept is something different from what the ordinary 
man happens to call ' beauty.' The life and character of a landscape 
consist in the amount of spatial elements arranged for ease of percep- 
tion. We may apply here the traditional esthetic term of unity in 
variety. T^he larger the number of spatial elements, in other words : 
the greater the spatial richness of the picture, the more intense is its 
life, the more pronounced its character. Whether the landscape 
stretches out for many miles or only a few yards, however, is irrele- 
vant, for the absolute size of the spatial elements is a matter of arbi- 
trary choice. 

Turning now to sculpture, first to relief, then to sculpture in the 



DISCUSSION. 355 

round, the student readily comprehends that the esthetic laws of vis- 
ual perception are essentially the same here as in drawing and paint- 
ing. He observes that all his previous observations can be repeated 
here, and he convinces himself of the absurdity of attributing to 
sculpture objective beauty, since sculpture is a thing to be seen^ and 
not to be seen while we are wandering around it, but to be seen from 
a single point of view, that point of view from which the artist con- 
ceived his visual image of the picture. I need not describe in detail 
how I proceed in class with regard to these questions since I follow 
rather closely the lines of discussion chosen by Hildebrand in his book. 

Thus far, no particular mention has been made in this course of the 
law of association upon which so much stress has been laid by Fech- 
ner. I now give my students some lectures on Fechner's principles 
of esthetics and let the students discuss them. It is found then that 
these principles are of much less esthetic importance than the formal 
laws of visual perception previously studied. Much esthetic effective- 
ness that seems to be due to association is really du6 to its influence on 
form perception. For example, what Fechner says about the associa- 
tions based on color, is doubtless true, but practically rather insignifi« 
cant. Saying this, I do not wish to give the impression of believing 
in color-harmony or in any other speculative principle of color esthet- 
ics. I do not believe that colors can be said to harmonize at all, and 
I give my students here the results of the psychological investigations 
of recent years, which clearly show that color-harmony is a meaning- 
less term. But it does not follow that all the esthetic effectiveness of 
color roust then be based on Fechner's principle of association. On 
the contrary, the great importance of color is to be found in its unify- 
ing and separating effects by means of which it aids us immensely in 
perceiving the spatial contents of a spatial whole. 

There is no need of belittling the great accomplishment of Fechner 
in esthetics. His work is invaluable as a welcome reaction from 
purely speculative esthetics which was derived from metaphysical 
principles instead of being based on a study of the laws of the mind 
in esthetic perception. But it would be a regrettable illusion if psy- 
chologists thought that beyond the problems stated by Fechner none 
were left which offered themselves for an experimental investigation. 
I am inclined to believe that the problems of form (in all three 
dimensions) , which are barely hinted at by Fechner, are those which 
promise the most satisfactory results to the experimental investigator. 

The student is now well prepared to discuss critically the esthetic 
value of the discoveries made by artists of recent times, particularly 



35^ BXPBRIMBNTAL COURSE IN ESTHETICS. 

those of the impressionittic school. I give the class a brief outline of 
the theories in which the artistic tendencies of this school are usually 
described ; and by the help of a few typical examples, I let them con- 
elude themselves to what extent these new tendencies can really be 
regarded as new discoveries, to what extent merely as further elabora- 
tions of principles well known and employed by much earlier artists. 
Especially the color theories as applied to their technic by the im- 
pressionists are discussed here by the class. And this takes but little 
time if the members of the class are familiar with the physiological 
theories of color vision. 

I finally give my students a survey of the general esthetic theories 
as proposed by recent writers. It is easy to show that — in spite of 
all divergence — they agree in regarding the esthetic experience essen- 
tially as a playful attitude towards a situation. The more adapted the 
situation is to be responded to in play, the higher its esthetic value. 
Such general theories can be discussed with a class more advantage- 
ously after the esthetic experience itself, in many variations, has 
become a perfectly familiar phenomenon to the student, than they can 
be taught while the student still has to guess what experience the in- 
structor means when talking of the beautiful or the esthetic. If we 
apply the modem esthetic theories to the arts of painting, sculpture, 
and architecture, we can summarise in a few words by saying : An 
esthetic experience is a mental process of playing with a visual percept. 
And to make this clear to the student I have regarded as the aim of 

this course.^ 

Max Meyer. 
Univbhsity op Missouiu. 

' The MS. of this article was received April 6, 1907. 



N. S. Vol. XIV. No. 6. November, 1907. 



The Psychological Review. 



APPARENT CONTROL OF THE POSITION OF 
THE VISUAL FIELD. 

BY DR. HARVEY CARR, 
PraU InstituU. 

One of my students reported that she possessed the ability of 
moving upwards the entire visual field. This translocation first 
occurred involuntarily and after noticing the phenomenon the 
subject found by trial that it could be repeated at will. 

During several conferences and tests the following account 
was obtained, giving the essential facts as to the nature of the 
phenomenon and the circumstances of its occurrence so far as 
the subject had been able to notice them : The subject is afilicted 
with hysteria. A rather severe attack occurred seven years ago 
from which she is slowly recovering. The involuntary trans- 
locations were first noted shortly after this time and they have 
occurred rather infrequently ever since. Fatigue and a pro- 
longed fixation seem to be the conditions under which they 
occur involuntarily. The phenomenon can be produced vol- 
untarily at any time and under any circumstances. The sub- 
ject has refrained from much experimentation for fear of 
aggravating her mental condition. An object is momentarily 
fixated and then slowly raised upwards. The duration of 
fixation necessary before movement can be effected varies from 
one to ten seconds. The rapidity of the movement varies. 
The translocation is sometimes slow and gradual and is effected 
only by continuous effort ; at other times the movement is more 
rapid and comes easily. Fatigue and brightness of the visual 
field decrease the time of necessary fixation and increase the 
rapidity and ease of the translocation. The extent and duration 

357 



358 HARVBY CARR. 

of the displacement is under complete control. The extent of 
the movement may be anywhere from one to forty degrees. 
The field may be held stationary at any desired position^ and 
then be moved on upwards or be brought back to its original 
position. The displacement has been maintained in one posi- 
tion for five minutes, though the continuous strain necessary is 
very fatiguing. The exhaustion due to continuous effort seems 
to be the only limitation of the possible duration of the phenome- 
non. Objects do not become double during the translocation ; 
they are perceived only in their elevated position, although the 
subject is conscious of their original location, for she can at any 
time point accurately in that direction. The entire visual field 
participates in the movement, and all visual objects keep their 
relative positions to each other. The only noticeable change in 
the character of the visual objects is a slight decrease in their 
intensity, though they remain distinct and substantial in appear- 
ance. When the field is lowered to its original position, the 
visual objects receive an added snap of reality the moment they 
reach their real position. It is by this means that the subject 
knows when the objects reach their true positions. Both the 
upward and the return movements are consciously real ; objects 
do not merely appear now in one place and now in another, but 
they appear to move as well. The objects do not move rela- 
tively to the line of sight. The object originally fixated remains 
at the point of fixation throughout the displacement ; in other 
words the point of fixation participates in the translocatory move- 
ment. The visual field remains perpendicular to the line of 
sight, as if it were undergoing a vertical rotation about the head 
as a center. If a person is in the visual field his voice partici- 
pates in the illusion. In the preliminary tests, the subject was 
requested to attempt other directions of movement but she was 
unsuccessful. Moreover, she was successful only with binocular 
vision, and when the eyes were in relatively unconstrained posi- 
tions in the socket during the original fixation. YTith monocular 
vision or when the eyes were rotated far to the periphery, only 
a very slight and momentary displacement could be effected. 

At first it was supposed that the phenomenon could be 
explained on the basis of one of three theories : (i) The trans- 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 359 

location is effected by some ocular innervation which does not 
involve eye movement, but which shifts the space reference of 
the retinae. The phenomenon would thus be similar to the well- 
known illusion due to the paralysis of the external rectus. This 
theory was put out of consideration immediately by the very 
obvious fact that the eyes do not remain stationary, but rotate 
in the direction of, and in proportion to, the visual illusion. If 
the illusion were slight in extent one could not be certain of this 
fact, but a movement of thirty degrees that may be maintained 
for five minutes is too obvious for the most sceptical observer. 
The subject was asked to point out the apparent location of the 
fixated object, and it always coincided with the directional posi- 
tion of her eyes. (2) The second theory supposes that the eyes 
rotate with the illusion, the space reference of the retinae remains 
normal, but that a refractive change, a lateral or rotary move- 
ment of the lens, occurs whereby the rays from the real posi- 
tions of the objects are kept focused upon the same points of 
the retinae in spite of the bulbular or retinal rotation. Such a 
conception is conceivable though its truth is not probable accord- 
ing to current views of ocular physiology. There is some factual 
support for such a theory, because the point of fixation, that por- 
tion of the field corresponding to foveal activity, is displaced and 
the image of the object originally fixated is still located at the point 
of fixation. Foveal positive and negative after-images were 
induced and developed before the translocation. These after- 
images representing foveal activity participated in the move- 
ment and were still located at the point of fixation. Although 
the eye has rotated upwards forty degrees away from the object 
primarily fixated, yet the image of that object must be due to 
the foveal activity of the retinae, for it is located at the fixation 
point and also at the same position in space as a foveal after- 
image. This theory was tested by making a phakoscopic 
examination of the behavior of the refractive surfaces. No 
unusual movements were detected. The lenticular images 
behaved in reference to the corneal image exactly as they did 
during a similar normal rotation. No refractive changes were 
in evidence. Ophthalmoscopic tests were planned but a more 
satisfactory theory was evolved before they were carried out. 



360 HARVBY CARR. 

(3) It may be supposed that the illusion is due to some disturb- 
ance in the sense of bodily position, which illusory disturbance 
is projected upon, or interpreted as belonging to, the objective 
field, the inverse of the haunted swing illusion, etc. There is 
no evidence in favor of this theory. The subject does not feel 
dizzy in the least. Her conceptual, or ideational, space is not 
affected ; she can point out the vertical and cardinal positions, 
and the real location of the displaced objects although she may 
not see anything in that direction. Furthermore, if the theory 
were true, it would be necessary to assume some secondary 
principle, as a refractive change, in order to compensate for 
the effects of the eye rotation. 

The next conception evolved to be experimentally tested 
may be roughly stated as follows : During the entire period of 
the displacement, the retinae are insensitive to all objective stim- 
ulations, and that which the subject sees is a hallucinatory 
positive after-image of the objects primarily perceived. This 
theory was suggested by two facts : (i) The subject is an hys- 
teric, a temporary visual anaesthesia being one of the symptoms ; 
(2) In the preliminary tests I noted that she was extraordinarily 
susceptible to positive after-images. A momentary glance at 
an electric light in daylight is suflScient to induce a positive 
after-image with a duration of seven to eight minutes. This 
conception proved to be true in the main. The tests were made 
at various times of the day with different conditions of illumina- 
tion. Two series were made at night in a room illumined by a 
shaded Welsbach lamp. The remaining tests were made on 
bright clear days in a well-lighted room where the brightness 
of the background could be varied. The various experiments 
will be grouped around a series of propositions. 

A. The translocations may be in any direction and may be 
initiated and sustained by a movement of either the eyes^ head^ 
or body. 

At first the movements had occurred in but the one direction ; 
at my suggestion the subject attempted other directions of move- 
ment but was unsuccessful. If the translocated visual field is 
a positive after-image, it would seem that any direction of move- 
ment should be possible. With this idea in mind, the subject 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 2fii 

was directed to rotate her head slowly sidewise during an up- 
ward displacement. She did so and the displaced field moved 
likewise. The field could now be moved in any direction by 
either a head or eye movement. After this experience, the sub- 
ject was able to start the displacement in any direction, the pre- 
liminary upward movement not being necessary. By turning 
the head and body, the field may be rotated to such an extent 
that the objects originally perceived no longer stimulate the 
retina. This result did not occur with the first displacements of 
forty degrees. The field may be rotated the full 360 degrees 
if desired. 

During the preliminary tests, displacements could not be ef- 
fected with monocular vision, nor when the eyes were in con- 
strained positions. After several months of experimentation, the 
attempt to secure displacements under these conditions was 
repeated with successful results. The translocation was ef- 
fected, but not readily, and the period of necessary fixation was 
longer than in the case of binocular vision with a normal posi- 
tion of the eyes. 

B. AH new objects introduced into the field of vision during 
the displacement are not perceived. 

This statement does not mean that the stimulations do not 
affect vision at all ; it means that these objects are not perceived 
as objects with their proper form, color and position so as to be 
recognized and located in space. At first the subject was kept 
in ignorance of the nature of the tests, and while she occasion- 
ally knew that something had happened to the visual field, she 
did not have the least idea as to what had caused the perceived 
changes. After being iifformed as to the nature of the experi- 
ments, she generally knew that some object had been intro- 
duced into the visual field but she had no idea as to its nature 
or location. 

At night, she fixated a lighted candle near the wall some 
eight feet distant. After a displacement of fifteen degrees, a 
large bright yellow paper was thrust in front of the candle ; it 
was not perceived. The paper was now put eight inches in 
front of each eye in succession, and then held at the same dis- 
tance in front of both eyes for a couple of minutes. The paper 



3*21 HARVBY CARR. 

was large enough (i6 in. square) to intercept the entire visual 
fieldi and a Welsbach light was so situated as to shine directly 
upon it. In neither case was the paper seen. A long series 
of similar tests was performed in bright daylight, the objects 
being introduced at different distances from the eye and in vari- 
ous positions in the visual field. A few typical cases will be 
described : After a twenty degree displacement, a book and a 
lighted candle were placed at the original fixation position. 
The lighted candle was moved back and forth a foot in front of 
her eyes. A bright paper screen was placed a foot in front of 
both eyes so as to intercept the entire visual field. The screen 
was kept in this position for two minutes. Again, the field was 
displaced so that the subject's eyes were directed at an electric 
light some eight feet distant. This light consisted of three six- 
teen-candle incandescents. While the eyes were held in this 
position, the light was turned on for fifteen seconds. This test 
was repeated a dozen times. In one of the tests the light was 
kept on for a full three minutes. In none of these cases were 
the objects perceived. When the visual field is moved more 
than ninety degrees, it is projected against an entirely new 
background of objects and these always remain invisible. 

C. Objects introduced into the visual field during the dis- 
placement J although not ferceived^ may affect the brightness^ 
color tone and distance location of the displaced images. 

The effect varies with the brightness of the field originally 
fixated, and the intensity, extent, and duration of the stimula- 
tion introduced. If the objects displaced be very bright, while 
the stimulation introduced be of small extent or of weak inten- 
sity, no effect is noticeable. If the fifeld be weak in intensity, 
and the stimulation introduced be intense, large and prolonged, 
a maximum effect results. 

When the window was displaced in bright daylight and a 
book or lighted candle was placed at the original fixation posi- 
tion at a distance of ten feet from the subject, no effect was 
noticed. When the screen of bright yellow paper was passed 
close in front of her eyes so as to intercept the vision of one or 
of both eyes, a very dim shadow appeared to pass over the dis- 
tant displaced field. When the lighted candle was thrust close 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 3^3 

in front of her eyes, a marked pupillary reflex was evident, 
and a very dim pale yellow light was suffused over the distant 
field. The bright window and a dull yellow wall were succes- 
sively displaced in the direction of the electric lights ; this stim- 
ulation produced a pale yellow glare over the field, but the 
effect was much more pronounced in the latter case, i. ^., with 
the less intense field. When the image of the window was dis- 
placed against the electric light, no effect was noticeable at 
first; after a few moments the yellow light tinged the field 
and gradually became more intense as the stimulation was pro- 
longed. After a few minutes the yellow glare contracted from 
the periphery and became concentrated in the center of the 
field. Probably in time the lights would have been perceived 
in this case, but the subject was not able to prolong the test 
over three minutes. A dull wall was displaced against a black- 
board as a background at the distance of three feet from the 
observer. A lighted candle was held near the blackboard and 
directly in front of her eyes. At first there appeared a dim 
flare of yellow light which gradually contracted in size and 
increased in intensity. After four minutes the image of this 
candle broke through the displaced field and was perceived as 
a candle. This was the only case in all of the tests where a 
distinct perception of the object occurred, and even here the 
percept of the candle was described as being strange, hazy, and 
unreal in appearance, and much less intense than in ordinary 
vision. Furthermore, in this test the field had been rotated 
more than ninety degrees, so that the objects primarily fixated 
no longer stimulated the retinse, and, as shall be noted later, 
the stimulation from the real objects is effective in maintaining 
their displaced images in consciousness. 

When the screen was placed close before both eyes so as to 
intercept the entire visual field, some of the displaced visual 
objects, after some time, appeared located at the distance of 
the screen as though projected upon it. The screen remained 
invisible and the subject was ignorant as to the nature of the 
experiment. In the first test the subject suddenly reached out 
her hand in order to point out the location of the image, and 
was greatly surprised when her hand came in contact with a 



3^4 HARVEY CARR. 

real object in that position. Only those images foveally per- 
ceived were affected in this manner, and their size was always 
increased in proportion to the nearness of their location. This 
fact is directly contrary to the usual results as to the size of 
after-images when projected on backgrounds of different dis^ 
tances from the observer. However, in the above case it must 
be borne in mind that the eyes remained adapted for the dis^ 
tant position, instead of becoming converged upon the invis- 
ible screen. 

The retinal effectiveness of these new stimulations is genuine. 
The pupillary reflex is indubitable proof. The screen though 
not perceived influences the distance of the displaced images. 
The diffused yellow glare is undoubtedly due to the stimulation 
of the lights. The subject was ignorant of the tests in the 
majority of the cases so that the results probably cannot be due 
to conscious suggestion. The absence of retinal effectiveness 
might be shammed by the subject, but there could be no decep- 
tion when retinal effects are present, unless she had knowledge 
of the nature of the experiments to be performed. 

D. The objects primarily fixated^ though not perceived at 
their real positions^ effectively influence in various ways their 
displaced images so long as their stimulations can reach 
the retina. 

This influence may be tested by displacing the field more 
than ninety degrees, by covering one of the objects with a 
screen, by moving an object in the field, or by removing an 
object entirely from the range of possible vision. 

I. A removal of an object from the range of vision was 
finally effective in all of the experiments. A few cases will 
illustrate the general nature of the results. The electric lights 
were fixated and displaced about twenty degrees. Shortly 
afterwards they were turned off. The displaced image of the 
light immediately exhibited a marked decrease in brightness 
but remained visible during the continuance of the test. The 
writer stood in front of the window and was fixated by the sub- 
ject. After the displacement, he suddenly dropped down out 
of the range of vision. After a half minute his displaced image 
disappeared entirely from sight, though the images of the other 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 365 

objects in the field remained in distinct view. The place of 
image was not filled in by the surrounding visual content, i. e.^ 
the bright light of the window. Neither was the window back 
of his body now perceived. The space was filled in by a 
homogeneous light gray content, a light shadow silhouette 
effect. Upon rising up again to the original position, a rather 
hazy image appeared to view but still in its displaced position. 
The subject was ignorant of the nature of the test. A book 
was held before the window and fixated. After the displace- 
ment it was removed, and in a short time its image disappeared. 
The book was now brought back into the field of vision, but it 
was placed a foot below its original position. Its displaced 
image reappeared, but at a position a foot below that from 
which it had disappeared. The test was repeated a number of 
times, the object being introduced into the field at various posi- 
tions relative to its original location. The same results obtained ; 
the reappearing image was always displaced from the true posi- 
tion of the object and bore the same spatial relation to its posi- 
tion of disappearance as the new location of the real object did 
to its primary position. The object was never perceived simul- 
taneously in the two positions. The first image always disap- 
peared before the second image was seen in the new position. 
The reappearing images were much dimmer than their originals 
and were always perceived with some diflSculty. The objects 
were easier to perceive when brought back to their original 
position than in the case where they were introduced in a new 
position. 

Since the existence of the image of the removed object 
depends upon the presence or absence of that object in the field, 
although the other images in the displaced field remain visible, 
it follows that the objective stimulations must be effective in 
maintaining the vision of their translocated images. Ignorance 
of the tests disposes of the possibility of any sham or suggestion. 

The removal of an intensive stimulation from the original 
field thus produces a decrease of brightness in its displaced 
image. If the stimulation is weak, its displaced image finally 
disappears. If the object is returned to the field, perception 
occurs with difficulty and the new image is much dimmer than 



366 HARVBY CARR. 

the original one. The new image occupies the same relative 
position in the displaced field as the new location of the object 
does in the primary field. 

2. Movement of an object in tl\e primary field may produce 
a change of location on the part of its image. If the movement 
is slow, a perception of motion may result. 

At night the writer stood in the field of view. During the 
displacement, the arm was lifted up slowly to a horizontal posi- 
tion. No movement was perceived at first. After the arm had 
moved about half the distance, the subject noted its new position 
and then perceived it in motion for the remainder of the distance. 
The perception was very vague and difficult. The arm seemed 
to be a mere transparent shadow, for the subject could look 
through it and see the visual objects past which it moved. The 
experiment was repeated while standing before a bright window. 
No movement was perceived ; the arm was finally seen in its 
extended position, presenting a very shadowy and unsubstantial 
appearance, markedly different from the remaining part of the 
body. The electric lights were fixated and displaced ten de- 
grees against a dull yellow wall. The light was then set swing- 
ings pendular fashion, quite rapidly. The arc of movement 
was two feet in extent. The displaced image of the light was 
described as quivering in a vibratory fashion as though it were 
rigid and had been violently jarred. In a similar test, the light 
* was slowly moved backwards and forwards through an arc of 
three feet A similar motion on the part of its displaced image 
was perceived, but its extent was judged to be only six inches 
in length. This decrease in length was not due to the subject's 
ignorance of linear values, for the extent of movement was rep- 
resented graphically after the test. Whether the perceived 
motion was synchronous with the motion of the light, or lagged 
behind it an appreciable time, I do not know, though the latter 
condition probably obtained. The image of the moving object 
was never seen in two positions simultaneously ; the image in 
the first position disappeared before the moving object was per- 
ceived in its second position. 

These results are genuine, for I attempted to induce such 
movements by suggestion, often asserting that my arm was 



CONTROL pF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 367 

being elevated and requesting the subject to perceive the move- 
ment if possible. Siiph attempts were invariably unsuccessful. 
When the field was displaced more than ninety degrees, the 
movement of an object produced no effect upon its image. In 
this case, the object no longer stimulated the retinae. Objects 
were also moved after being hidden behind a screen; this 
movement effected no results upon the displaced image. Con- 
sequently suggestion cannot explain the results. 

3. The various results obtained by the interception of the orig- 
inal stimulus by the introduction of a screen are partly due to 
the new stimulation introduced as well as to the removal of the 
old one. The results due to the new object have been enu- 
merated and described in a previous section (C, pp. 362 ff .). Cer- 
tain other phenomena occur, however, which are due to the 
removal of the original stimulus from the retinas. In the tests 
at night a screen was interposed just in front of the candle 
originally fixated. The image of the candle did not disappear 
but flared out to a large size with an indeterminate contour and 
a marked decrease in luminosity. The image resumed its nor- 
mal appearance when the screen was removed. The test was 
repeated several times in immediate succession with the same 
results. The screen was placed immediately in front of both 
eyes. All visual objects in the displaced field disappeared 
almost at once, but the subject continued to see the space be- 
tween the screen and the distant wall as though nothing had 
happened ; this space appeared light and transparent as in nor- 
mal vision. The background, 1. ^., the image of the wall, 
merely faded away into nothingness ; the further limit of the 
perceived empty space was thus not blackness but a mere void. 
After a short time the image of the candle reappeared at the 
distance of the screen, though all other objects in the field re- 
mained invisible. When this image of the candle reappeared 
to view, vision of the empty space beyond the screen was lost. 
With strong illumination (fixating the window on a bright day), 
a screen interposed just in front of the object of fixation pro- 
duced no noticeable results on the character or continuance of 
its image. When the screen was placed immediately before 
both eyes so as to intercept the entire field, certain objects in 



/ 



3^8 HARVEY CARR. 

the far distance which were perceived through the window dis- 
appeared from vision at once, but the images of the window and 
surrounding walls as well as of the intervening space remained 
visible for nearly a minute. After this period the small part of 
the window foveally perceived became located at the distance 
of the screen. The subject's attention was now attracted to 
this, and she did not notice whether the remaining part of the 
field continued to be visible at its distant position. However, 
the empty space beyond the screen was still perceived until the 
end of the experiment. 

The apparent results of these tests may be stated as follows : 
When the original stimulation is intense and a small portion of 
the field is intercepted, no effect upon the duration of the dis- 
placed image is noticeable. When the stimulation is weak and 
the whole field is intercepted, the displaced images disappear 
almost immediately. Intermediary results can be obtained with 
mean conditions. 

4. The influence of the original stimulations may be inferred 
from certain results obtained by a displacement of more than 
ninety degrees. The introduction of the electric lights before 
the eyes produced more marked results in case the field was dis- 
placed to such an extent that the original objects perceived no 
longer stimulated the retinae. Moreover, the results occurred 
more quickly with such extreme rotations than they did with a 
small displacement. The object introduced into the field was 
perceived as an object only in the case of such an extreme 
rotation. 

The displaced images thus possess a greater resistance to 
the influence of new stimuli so long as the primary field con- 
tinues to stimulate the retinae. 

E. The effect of an old stimulation is much greater than^ 
and Jar different from^ that of any new stimulus introduced 
during the displacement, 

I. An old object introduced into any part of the field after its 
removal is perceived as an object under conditions where the 
introduction of a new object would produce no visual effect 
whatsoever. 

This general statement is derived from a comparison of the 



CONTROL Oi^ POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 3^9 

results of the tests described in sections B, C, and D. The fol- 
lowing test was performed to illustrate the proposition. Under 
conditions of weak illumination, I stood in the field of view hold- 
ing an unlighted candle in my hand. The hand was fixated 
and a ten degree displacement of the field was secured. I now 
moved out of the range of possible vision and lighted the candle. 
After my displaced image had disappeared from view, I came 
back to the original position. The image of myself and candle 
now reappeared, but the light was not perceived save for the 
dim and vague luminosity suffusing the field. It would be pos- 
sible to choose conditions under which even this dim luminosity 
would not occur. 

2. The effect of a new object tends to be diffused over the 
visual field, while the effect of an old object tends to be definite 
and localized. 

The first case is illustrated by the diffused luminosity of the 
candle and electric lights. The second statement is illustrated 
by a number of facts. The displaced image of the electric 
lights decreased in intensity the moment th^ light was turned 
off, although no effect was noted on the remaining part of the 
field. The removal or movement of an object in the primary 
field produced visual effects which were confined entirely to the 
displaced image of that object. When an old object was brought 
back into any part of the field, it was perceived as an object, 
i. e.f its visual effects were definitely localized in space. 

3. The visual effects of a new object are projected in accord- 
ance with the normal laws of retinal space reference. The im- 
age of an old object re-introduced into any part of the field is 
perceived in a displaced position. 

As illustrations of the first statement we may cite the follow- 
ing tests : In the case where the candle introduced into the field 
after a displacement was perceived as a candle, it was correctly 
localized. It was placed directly in front of the subject's eyes 
and it was perceived in that position. In the case where the 
eyes were directed at the electric lights for three minutes during 
a displacement, the diffused luminosity became concentrated in 
a large circle in the center of the field of vision. If this ring 
of light represents the stimulation of the lights, as has been 



370 HARVBY CARR. * 

assumed, it was correctly localized. The second of the above 
statements represents the results given in section D, (i) and (2). 
F. This peculiar and abnormal /uuctional condition of the 
eyes obtaining during the displaccfnents may be maintained^ de^ 
stroyed and reinstated at will. The condition is maintained or 
reinstated by a mental fiat accompanied by an orbital strain^ 
while the condition is discontinued at any time by a mental fiat 
and a relaxation of the orbital strain. 

1. Maintenance of the displacement. During the various 
testSy a careful observation was made of the subject's motor atti- 
tudes and expression in initiating and maintaining the displace- 
ments. The body generally remained quiet but exhibited a 
suppressed tenseness as though the whole energy of the body 
was being concentrated upon the task in hand. The breathing 
was slow, quiet and regular, but much deeper than usual. The 
subject appeared slightly enrapt or entranced as one does with 
extreme absorption in some observation involving steady fixation. 
The extreme concentration was due to the facts that the tests 
were generally of some duration, the subject's attention was 
directed to the observation of all changes occurring in the visual 
field, while many of the phenomena were novel in character. 
It was found on trial that the field could be displaced and main- 
tained in a given position with a relaxed condition of the body 
and with normal breathing. No expression was noted other 
than that occurring in a case of ordinary fixation. Introspec- 
tively, the only necessary conditions for the maintenance of the 
displacement were a marked strain located in the head directly 
back of the eyeballs, and the focusing of the attention upon 
the images. 

2. The discontinuance of the state. We found that it was 
not necessary to move the field back to its original position in 
order to discontinue the state. The subject generally shook 
her head, moved her eyes, blinked several times and relaxed 
her bodily tension. The subject was asked to give an account 
of her method of discontinuing the state at will, but was unable 
to do so with the exception that she had noted that it was not 
necessary to move the field back to its primary position. This 
method was made an object of study in a number of experi- 



I 
CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD, 37' 

ments. It was found that a sudden head or eye movement 
generally caused the field to disappear momentarily during the 
movement. The movements, blinkings and the bodily relaxa- 
tion were not necessary to discontinue the phenomenon though 
they were of some service. The only necessary concomitants 
of the mental decision were the release of the attention from the 
images, and a relaxation of the orbital strain mentioned above. 
The displaced field does not disappear immediately, but fades 
away gradually. The time necessary for the disappearance of 
the images seemed to vary slightly in the different tests. Prob- 
ably, the time is proportional to the intensity of the original 
stimulations. The average duration necessary was from three 
to five seconds. The recovery of normal vision does not occur 
immediately after the disappearance of the displaced images. 
There is an intermediary period in which the visual field pre- 
sents a uniform gray hazy appearance. The images of the real 
objects now before the eyes break through this hazy mist and 
gradually become distinct. The whole process involving the 
disappearance of the displaced field and the recovery of normal 
vision lasts from four to seven seconds. 

3. The reinstatement of the displaced field after its disap- 
pearance. After normal vision has been recovered, the dis- 
placed field may be brought back to consciousness at will with- 
out the necessity of again subjecting the eyes to the original 
stimulations. A mental decision involving a thought of the 
objects and the reinstatement of the orbicular strain is the only 
condition necessary to effect this result. Merely thinking of 
the objects is not sufficient to produce the reinstatement. The 
displaced field does not come back gradually but instantane- 
ously. The subject had not been aware of her ability to recall 
these positive after-images at will and first attempted it at my 
suggestion. The results were so immediate and pronounced as 
to startle her. The phenomenon is best described in the sub- 
ject's own words : ** No sooner had I willed than the displaced 
images burst upon me in full bloom as though they had been 
hidden behind a screen and this screen had been suddenly jerked 
away.'' With the return of the displaced images, the eyes were 
subjected to the various tests described above in order to deter- 



37* HARVBY CARR. 

mine their sensitivity. The eyes are now in exactly the same 
condition of sensitivity as they were during the original dis- 
placement. This voluntary alternation of the abnormal condi- 
tion of the eyes and of normal vision may be successively pro- 
duced in the same experiment apparently as many times as 
desired. In one experiment the field was displaced more than 
ninety degrees and projected against a background of new 
objects. The subject was directed to hold the eyes as motion- 
less as possible, to allow the displaced field to disappear until 
distinct vision of the new background was secured, to call back 
the displaced field so as to hide all vision of the new background 
of objects and to alternate the two states as long as possible. 
The two conditions were alternated six times in succession, 
when the subject was compelled to stop through fatigue. 
Apparently, fatigue is the only limitation on the possible dura- 
tion of the phenomenon. In every case normal vision was 
effected gradually while the abnormal condition was reinstated 
immediately. 

G. The visual ^eld may be moved at will in a third dimen^ 
sional direction. The backward movement is effected by an 
* effortful feeling of expansion * within the eyeball ^ while a ^feeU 
ing of contraction and relaxation ' in the same locality accom- 
panies a forward direction of movement. During these move- 
ments the same abnormal condition of sensitivity obtains as in 
the case of the lateral displacements^ already described. 

At the time when the lateral displacements were first noted 
(seven years ago), third dimensional movements of the field 
sometimes occurred involuntarily, especially under conditions 
of fatigue or of prolonged fixation. By trial, it was found that 
these movements were also subject to voluntary control. They 
can be produced voluntarily much more easily and after a 
shorter period of fixation than can the lateral displacements. 

The field cannot be moved forward to a distance nearer than 
five feet from the subject, but it can be removed to the apparent 
distance of the horizon. Within these limits, the field can be 

^The translocatory moTementa alreftdy described in the previooa sections 
will be tenned hereafter ' lateral displacements,' in order to distinguish them 
from these third dimensional movements. 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 373 

moved and located at will. The images do not become double, 
but are blurred to some extent and are rather confused in out- 
line. With the backward direction of movement, the images 
become slightly smaller, but the decrease in size does not seem 
to be proportionate to the increase of distance according to the 
laws of perspective. The decrease in size seems to be due to a 
^ melting away of the edges ' of the various images. In the re- 
turn movement, the field is judged to have reached its real posi- 
tion when the images attain to their maximum distinctness of 
outline. 

The movement can be effected with monocular vision, but 
it occurs much more readily with the left eye than with the 
right. On the return movement with the right eye, the field 
does not move forward gradually but jumps back quickly in an 
involuntary manner. The images grow less distinct and a trifle 
smaller with the backward movements. The decrease in size 
seems to be due to a < fading away of the edges.' 

When the field is moved backward toward the horizon, the 
subject experiences a ' feeling of expansion ' which is located 
inside of the eyeballs directly back of the cornea. The forward 
movements are accompanied by a * feeling of contraction ' in the 
same locality. The feeling of expansion is described as effort- 
ful, while the contractile feeling is accompanied by a sense of 
relaxation. 

At first it was supposed that these depth movements were 
entirely distinct in nature from the displacement phenomenon, 
and that they were another instance of that voluntary control of 
the depth location of the visual field possessed by Miss Allen. ^ 
This inference was not wholly correct. During a depth dis- 
placement, the visual field may be displaced laterally, or it may 
be moved in a third dimensional direction during a lateral trans- 
location. During the prolonged tests on the lateral displace- 
ments, the subject often lost control of the distance location of 
the displaced field and it would suddenly recede from five to 
ten feet. A series of experiments was performed in order to 
test the sensitivity of the eye during the depth movements. If 
anything, the eye is more insensitive during this phenomenon 

" PSYCHOi^OGiCAi; REVIEW, Vol. XIII., No. 4, pp. 258-275. 



374 HARVSY CAXJi. 

than it is with the lateral displacements. Various objects were 
introduced into the range of possible vision, but they were not 
perceived, nor did they affect the visual field in any way. A 
lighted candle held at a distance of three feet directly in front 
of the eyes did not even suffuse the distant field with a luminous 
glow. When objects were removed from the field, the period 
necessary for the disappearance of their images was longer than 
in the case of the previous phenomenon. The movement of an 
object in the field was not perceived, though the object was 
finally seen in its new position. Objects re-introduced into the 
field were perceived with extreme difficulty unless they were 
brought back to their original positions. In the latter case the 
image of the object is more intense and realistic, and it appears 
to view in less time after the introduction of the stimulus. 

The fact, however, that the moving visual field is of the 
nature of a hallucinatory positive after-image, does not explain 
the mechanism of its distance location. The lateral displace- 
ments are due to head or eye movements, and the depth 
changes must likewise be attributed to some factors just as in 
the case of the distance location of any after-image, either pos- 
itive or negative. Moreover, the changes must be due to fac- 
tors over which the subject has direct voluntary control. 
While this phenomenon is essentially different from that exhib- 
ited by Miss Allen so far as the retinal sensitivity is concerned, 
yet it is possible that the two cases are similar in respect to the 
mechanism involved in this voluntary control over the depth 
location of the visual imagery. In the case of Miss Allen, the 
.depth movements were conditioned by lenticular adjustments 
which involved no convergent changes of the eyes. With the 
present subject, no convergent movements occurred. This fact 
supports the proposition previously enunciated as to the retinal 
effectiveness of the stimulations from a primary field, for if the 
eyes were totally free from the influence of the objects primarily 
fixated, it is inconceivable that the convergence should remain 
unaltered while the visual images are subject to such marked 
changes in respect to depth location. As to the presence of 
lenticular adjustments, no confident assertions can be made. I 
was under the impression that lens changes occurred, but the 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 375 

movements were so slight in extent that I could feel no absolute 
confidence in the validity of the observations. The movements 
were so small that it was impossible to detect whether a partic- 
ular kind of adjustment was invariably correlated with each 
direction of image movement. The small extent of the move- 
ments present, in case the observed results are valid, is expli«- 
cable from the fact that the possible extent of the third dimen- 
sional movements of the visual field was greatly diminished in 
the dim illumination necessary to a phakoscopic examination. 
The lack of clear-cut definite results, as in the case of Miss 
Allen, does not dispirove the lenticular theory ; neither do the 
observations furnish indubitable proof that the depth displace- 
ments are conditioned by appropriate adjustments of the lenses, 
though they do support that theory to some extent. During 
the displacements pupillary changes occur, but they are spas- 
modic and irregular in character, no definite change being 
invariably correlated with each direction of image movement. 
The fact that the displaced images become blurred and confused 
in outline in the third dimensional movements, but do not do so 
during the lateral displacements, indicates the presence of lentic- 
ular disturbances in the former case. The presence of musCular 
feelings inside the eyeballs in the region of the lens may like* 
wise be interpreted in favor of the theory. On the whole the 
writer is disposed to believe that lenticular changes do occur 
and condition the movements to some extent, though they may 
not constitute the sole explanation of the phenomenon. The 
possibility of other conditioning factors is a matter of speculation 
and any such discussion is beyond the range of this paper. 

The preceding account has purported to be as much as 
possible a factual statement of the various experimental results 
with little comment or theoretical digression. Some peculiar 
aspects of the case deserve further consideration. 

Such visual anaesthesias, wherein objective stimulations are 
retinally effective and may indirectly influence consciousness, 
occur with hysteria and may be induced by suggestion. So 
far as the writer is aware, however, such anaesthetic retinal 
areas do not subserve any objectified visual consciousness, as 



37^ HARVBY CARR. 

with the present subject, unless hallucinatory images are 
induced by suggestion. The hallucination and the insensi- 
tivity seem to be a single phenomenon rather than two inde- 
pendent events, for they invariably occur together. This is 
seen from the fact that there is no stage of a total lack of visual 
sense content intervening between normal vision and the abnor- 
mal condition. When the displaced field is caused to disappear, 
there is, it is true, an intermediary stage wherein the visual 
field presents a uniform undifferentiated appearance. But this 
is not a total blindness, for an objectified visual sense content is 
present. When objects were removed from the field and their 
displaced images were allowed to fade from view, no gap was 
left devoid of all sense content. This close relation between 
the presence of the hallucinatory field and the insensitivity, 
and their relation to volition are matters for discussion. Three 
theories may be conceived as to the relations involved : 

1. The anaesthesia may be assumed to be directly subject to 
volitional control, while the hallucination is an effect of the 
anaesthesia. The first relation is conceivable for such anaes- 
thesias can be induced by suggestion, but the second causal 
nexus is hard to conceive and some facts contradict the assump- 
tion of any such invariable connection. An involuntary semi- 
trance, involving a visual anaesthesia and a complete aboulia 
has frequently occurred throughout the subject's life. This 
visual anaesthesia generally involved a complete loss of all 
sense content, i. e.^ it did not produce an hallucination. 

2. It may be supposed that the two phenomena are indepen- 
dent events and are controlled by separate volitional processes, 
but, since the two results cannot be separately initiated, it must 
be assumed that each event is due to a particular process within 
the whole volitional act, but that the two processes are so asso- 
ciated that they cannot be even consciously separated. This 
theory may be true for all that is known to the contrary, but it 
is needlessly complex. 

3. We may assume that the hallucination is volitionally con- 
trolled, but that the presence of the hallucinatory images is the 
cause of the anaesthesia. The second relation may be illustrated 
by the following phenomenon: Let the light from a bright 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 377 

window be reflected into the left eye by one's glasses. The 
image of the window is now projected against the wall of the 
room. If the right eye is closed, the wall back of the projected 
image remains invisible in spite of all efforts to perceive it. The 
stimulations from the wall enter the eye and reach the retina, 
but vision is so dominated by the image of the bright window 
that the stimulations from the wall fail to influence it effectively. 
Likewise, it may be conceived that the hallucinatory activities 
so dominate the visual centers that these latter are impervious to 
the objective stimulations. The phenomenon is thus a matter 
of visual rivalry. This conception is supported by the general 
result enunciated in section C that the visual effect of any new 
stimulation introduced varies with its intensity, extent, and dura- 
tion, and also according to the brightness of the primary field, 
I. ^., the intensity of the hallucinatory field. In the volition 
her attention is positively directed toward the visual images in 
the reinstatement and maintenance of the hallucination, and it 
neglects them in order to discontinue the state. This fact sup- 
ports the view that volition deals directly with the hallucination 
and that the insensitivity is a secondary by-product. The sup- 
position may be further supported by the fact that the stimula- 
tion of an old object is more effective when it is brought back 
to its original location than when it is introduced into the field 
in some new position. In the former case the image is more 
vivid and realistic and is perceived in a shorter time after the 
object is returned to the field. This result may be conceived as 
due to the fact that the stimulation in any secondary position 
comes into rivalry with a hallucinatory image of some other 
object. 

There is a real spatial translocation of the effects of retinal 
stimulation in certain cases. This is illustrated in Fig. i. 
Suppose that the eye momentarily fixates the object F^ while C 
is perceived in indirect vision. The points f and c are the 
retinal areas stimulated by these objects. The eye is now 
rotated upward until the optic axis is directed toward F* . The 
stimulations from the objects F and C now meet the retina at 
the points b and a respectively, while the images of those 
objects are perceived in the positions F' and O . These periph- 



37* HARVEY CARR. 

eral stimulations at a and b influence the brightness, duration, 
location and existence of the visual images f and C which 
should normally correspond to the retinal activity of the areas 
yand e respectively. It is as if the effects of the stimulations 
of a and b were transferred to the points c and / respectively. 
What is true of these two stimulated areas is also true for all 
retinal points. Thus every retinal area, c for example, trans- 
fers the effects of its own stimulation to another area d^ and in 



■^--.4 



Fig. I. F and C, objects in the field of Tkion ; F' and C^, displaced 
images of the objects F and C after the eye rotation ; i», nodal point; <?, center 
of rotation ; /^ fovea ; f-o-n-F^^ optic aads after the rotation ; a, b^ c^ <f, retinal 
points. 

return it receives the effects of the stimulation of the area a. 
However this apparent < transference ' of the stimulation of one 
area to a second retinal area occurs only for * primary stimula- 
tions,' I. ^., only for those objects occupying the original field 
of vision. In the case of < secondary stimulations' — those 
resulting from new objects introduced into the field of vision 
after the displacement — there is at first an apparent retinal 
* diffusion ' ; the results of the stimulation are diffused so as to 
tinge appropriately the entire visual field. This diffusion is 
minimized in extent in proportion to the duration and intensity 
of the secondary stimulation. 

As to the nature and mechanism of this * transference ' and 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 379 

< diffusion ' several pbssibilities are open. It may be supposed 
that the retinal space reference has been altered. Ordinarily 
the image corresponding to the stimulation of a point b on the 
retina is localized along a line running through this point and 
the nodal point n^ but this spatial reference of the retina may be 
altered in certain conditions, e. g.^ the partial paralysis of an 
eye muscle. This conception is disproved by the fact that the 
retina localizes normally in the case of a prolonged and inten- 
sive secondary stimulation, although the transference of the 
primary stimulations still obtains. While the conception might 
explain the < transference phenomenon/ yet it is inadequate to 
account for the * diffusion of secondary stimulations.' 

The phenomena may be supposed to be either retinal or 
central affairs. In fact, they have been couched above in 
retinal terms, but this was done merely for descriptive and not 
explanatory purposes. Analogous results have been obtained 
in experimental psychology. The irradiation phenomenon, 
simultaneous contrast, etc., indicate that in normal experiences 
the conscious effects of any retinal stimulation are not confined 
wholly to the corresponding part of the visual field, but it is not 
known whether this diffusion of results is centrally or retinally 
conditioned. The question is further involved with the general 
problem of the seat of hallucinatory activities, as to which there 
is no unanimity of opinion. Consequently, there is no positive 
evidence to be derived from other sources in favor of either con- 
ception. So far as anatomical possibilities are concerned a 
central location is preferable. The fact of voluntary control 
over the existence and duration of the transference is more ex- 
plicable in central terms. A statement of the facts, however, 
in either retinal or central terms would do little but localize the 
phenomenon. The mechanism and raison JPitre of the process 
would still remain unintelligible. 

The conception which seems most satisfactory to the writer 
involves several propositions : (i) For all points a, ^, c on the 
retina there are corresponding cortical areas A^ By C. The 
habitual pathway of a retinal impulse from any point is to its 
corresponding cortical area (Fig. 2). The course of any im- 
pulse may be varied under certain conditions. It is not neces- 



380 HARVBY CARR, 

sary to assume that the spatial arrangement of the cortical areas 
is in any way similar to that of their corresponding retinal points 
although they have been represented in that manner in the figure 
(2). The hallucinatory images of the displaced field are due 








Fig. 2. a, h^ c^ retinal points; A^ B^ C, cortical areas corresponding 
respectiTely to 0, b^ c: K, X^ Z, displaced images dne to activity of A^ B, C» 
respectively ; Z>, subcortical center. 

mainly to cortical activities, and (3) these cortical activities are 
so intensive and dominating that they interfere with the habitual 
behavior of the incoming retinal impulses. These impulses be- 
come blocked at the subcortical center D. 

We will suppose that the eye perceives three objects, JT, T 
and Z, corresponding to the three neural processes represented 
in the figure. The images of these objects are now displaced 
by an eye movement, and a new object, F, is introduced into the 
field so as to stimulate the retina at b. This retinal impulse is 
checked at D^ and hence a diffusion of the impulse occurs. If 
the stimulation is weak, the effects are drafted off to lower 
centers without conscious effect. A greater intensity of stimu- 
lation gives a diffused effect over the entire visual areas. In 
case the stimulation is very intense and prolonged, the retinal 
impulse becomes strong enough to supplant some one of the 
cortical activities. The impulse will traverse the line of least 
resistance, and this will be along the habitual pathway IhD-B, 
The object Fwill thus be localized in a normal manner. The 
displacement of the images 7" and Z and the correct localization 
of the new object V are thus possible. 

As a result of the eye movement, the object 7" now stimu- 
lates the retina at c instead of at a. This retinal impulse 
becomes^ blocked at D because of the cortical activity of C 
involved in the displaced image Z. This impulse will finally 



CONTROL OF POSITION OF VISUAL FIELD. 381 

break through the hallucinatory field at the point of least resist- 
ance. With primary stimulations this point of least resistance 
is not along the habitual pathway Z?-C, but it is at the 
cortical area A involved in the displaced image Y, This area 
A^ being strongly excited centrally, forms an apperceptive 
center highly susceptible to an appropriate stimulation. The 
impulse from c is transferred to A by the subcortical center D. 
This theory assumes that a psycho-cortical activity will block 
an habitual path to impulses which would arouse qualitative dis- 
similar responses in that center, while it will markedly increase 
the susceptibility of that area to appropriate impulses. This 
conception involves no new doctrine, for the same principle is 
used to explain the selective character of apperceptive attention ; 
central activities increase the mind's sensitivity to stimulations 
of an appropriate character but decrease its susceptibility to all 
other stimulations. Thus it is not necessary to posit the exist- 
ence of a subconscious mind in order to explain the subject's 
ability to react differently to the two kinds of stimulations. 

The volitional control over the existence and duration of the 
hallucinatory images is a noteworthy fact, for generally such 
experiences possess all of the involuntary characteristics of per- 
cepts. What causal relation the orbital strain bears to the exist- 
ence of the abnormal state is a subject concerning which it is 
idle to speculate. It is also rather curious that this abnormal 
condition does not seem to be subject to suggestion in any way, 
although it is so susceptible to volitional influences. 

The subject of these experiences was under the writer's 
observation for six months and the experimental work covered 
a period of three months. Owing to the subject's susceptibility 
to fatigue, it was impossible in this time to investigate the phe- 
nomenon as thoroughly as desired. The case deserves further 
study, as many interesting problems came up during the experi- 
ments whose solution would certainly give a more compre- 
hensive insight into the phenomenon. 

The subject comes of a well-to-do and cultured family. 
She is an only child and was reared in comparative isolation 
from those of her own age. She has been much addicted to day 
dreaming and she possesses an artistic, idealistic and sensitive 



3** MARVBY CARR. 

tetnpertment. Her physical health has always been good. She 
is physically well-developed, and her appearance gives every 
indication of healthful bodily functioning. She has been sub- 
ject all her life to short attacks involving visual anaesthesia and 
aboulia. These attacks are congenital on the mother's side of 
the family. She has often experienced other seizures involving 
faintness and extreme physical weakness, with the presence of 
only a dim vague consciousness. These attacks often leave the 
subject in a very weak condition for some hours. Shortly before 
the phenomenon described in this paper was first noticed, she 
experienced a more profound attack resulting in some permanent 
Amnesias. The complete loss of auditory musical memory 
incapacitated her for her vocation as a music teacher. Her 
retentiveness for academic subjects was much impaired. She 
is now extremely susceptible to fatigue* Her case was diag- 
nosed by a competent nervous specialist who found that she was 
unable to converge upon objects at a distance of less than eight 
feet. She has been using a set of prisms to strengthen the in- 
ternal recti muscles and finds that their constant use has had a 
beneficial effect upon her mental ability.^ 

^ The MS. of this article was rec e lTed October I5» 1907. 



CONCERNING ANIMAL PERCEPTION. 

BY PR0PBS80R GHORGB H. MEAD, 
UnivenUy of Chicago. 

I wish to call attention to a phase of animal psychology 
which has received, it seems to me, but inadequate treatment. 
This inadequacy is evident not only in the general psycholo- 
gies, but also in special experimental investigations of animal 
intelligence. The diflSculty gathers about the doctrine of per- 
ception, and is due in part to the incomplete character of the 
theory of perception in human psychology, and in part to a fail- 
ure to analyze sufSciently the conditions of possible perception 
in lower animal forms. 

Can we draw a line between perception and higher cogni- 
tive processes, leaving below the line a cognition which is not 
rational though intelligent, such as characterizes the adaptations 
of a crab or a rat, and placing above the line all the conscious- 
ness of relation which makes human intelligence rational? Do 
our own predominately perceptive processes, such as those of 
rapidly climbing a steep, rocky cliff, or playing a game of 
tennis, where we are seemingly unconscious of anything except 
the physical environment and our reactions thereto, differ qual- 
itatively from the more abstract processes in which we con- 
sciously deal in symbols and isolate the relations of things? 

If these discursive processes are mere developments of con- 
tents which are implicitly present in perceptual consciousness, 
is there any definite line which can be drawn between the 
intelligence of man and that of the lower forms, unless we deny 
them the form of consciousness which we call perceptual in our- 
selves? Hobhouse,^- for example, assumes that the cat, the 
dog and the monkey, which he observed, apprehend perceptual 
relations, which enabled them to learn by experience, without 
the ability to isolate the relations as elements in thought. 

Stout ' would grant to the chick that learns to reject a cin- 

^Mind in Evolution, p. 117. 

* Manual of Psychology, pp. 84 ff. 

383 



384 GEORGE H. MEAD. 

nabar caterpillar, an < apprehension of meaning or significance, 
which would come to the same thing. On the other hand, 
Thorndyke ^ explains such learning by experience on the part 
of lower animals through the association of an * impulse * with a 
stimulus, which seems to imply a qualitatively difiEerent state of 
consciousness from that which would ordinarily be called per- 
ceptual in human experience. He undertakes to illustrate this 
by phases of human consciousness in which even perception 
would be reduced to a minimum. This latter illustration indi- 
cates a possibility of discrimination which seems to me to have 
been but inadequately recognized. In learning to play billiards 
or tennis, we are moving in a perceptual world, but the process 
of improvement takes place largely below even the perceptual 
level. We make certain movements which are more successful 
than others, and these persist. We are largely conscious only 
of the selection which has already begun. We emphasize this 
and control to some extent the conditions under which the selec- 
tion takes place, but the actual assumption of the better attitude, 
the actual selection of the stroke, lies below even this level of 
consciousness. Thorndyke calls this selection a process of 
stamping in by the pleasure coming with success. This ex- 
planation, however, calls for its own explanation and ascribes 
active control to states of pleasure and pain, which is by no 
means proved and opens up another field of dubious animal 
psychology. Thorndyke calls the process of improvement an 
association of an impulse and a- stimulus, which lies quite out- 
side of associations of ideas. The phrase is perhaps a vague 
one, that calls for further specification, but it answers to a large 
number of instances which are commonly conceived of as per- 
ceptions by the animal psychologists, although it is to be pre- 
sumed that Thorndyke himself assumes that these animals move 
in a perceptual world. The instances to which I refer may be 
well illustrated by the action of the chick in rejecting the cin- 
nabar caterpillar or the orange-peel. Is there a revival of the 
past experiences which leads the chick to reject these disagree- 
able objects ; or may we assume that the impulse to reject has 
become associated with this particular stimulus, without any in- 
tervening redintegrated psychoses? 

> ' Animal Intelligence,' Psy. Rbv. Mon. Suppl., Vol. II., No. 4, pp. 656. 



CONCERNING ANIMAL PBRCBPTION 385 

This question is closely allied to that which arises with 
reference to the plasticity of the young form and the manner in 
which it acquires the specific habits which are not found per- 
formed in its nervous system. A chick learns to make use of 
the impulse to hide when a hawk sails overhead. A young fox 
learns to run away from the odor of man. The process of hid- 
ing and running away are indeed performed in these young 
animals. It is the association of the instinctive action with 
determinate stimuli which is acquired. What seems to take 
place is this : The animal tastes a disagreeable morsel when it 
instinctively strikes at a moving object before it. The action 
of the flavor of the morsel upon the organs of taste sets free an 
equally instinctive reaction of rejecting the morsel. At the 
same time, the chick eyes the caterpillar under the excitement 
of the disagreeable experience. Now the caterpillar hereafter 
to be avoided must be different from a mere moving object such 
as would have called forth the reaction of pecking. It is fair 
to assume that the condition for this discrimination made by the 
chick lies in the different reaction which it has called forth. 
The mere redintegration of the experience would not protect 
the chick. Either the chick would peck again, since presum- 
ably the same bad taste and same rejection would follow, 
simply reinforced by the revival of the past experience, and 
this would bring about no improvement in adaptation ; or else 
the past experience would be revived with the appearance of 
the old stimulus. This stimulus was not a caterpillar with cer- 
tain markings, but a moving object within reach. The revival 
of the experience with this generalized stimulus to which, as 
Lloyd Morgan's experiments show, the chick reacts, would 
lead to the rejection, not of cinnabar caterpillars alone, but of 
all moving objects within reach. The ability to distinguish 
between stimuli which had been identical in their value before, 
arises together with the new reaction, that of rejection. The 
meaning of the plasticity of the young form seems to be that 
there exist in the form instinctive reactions which have not as 
yet determined external stimuli. Through the experience of 
the animal the appropriate stimuli are determined. One condi- 
tion, at any rate, is found in the new visual or olfactory expe- 



386 GSORGM H. MEAD. \ 

rience which arises when, for any reason, this new reaction 
takes place. A dog's shrinking from the sight of the whip 
involves not simply the revival of the painful experience of the 
flogging ; it involves his reacting to characteristicts in the sight 
of the whip which led to no reaction at first. It is not then so 
much the association of an old visual or olfactory experience 
with the impulse, as the arising of a new visual or olfactory 
experience which now becomes the stimulus for the particular 
impulse or reaction. If there be association of ideal contents, 
it is between this new visual or olfactory experience and the old 
experience which had not as yet been discriminated; of this 
association, Mr. Thorndyke remarks,^ we have littie or no evi- 
dence. What we must assume, in what is implied above, is 
that the animal gets the new visual or olfactory experience 
because it is carrying out a new reaction ; that the ground for 
discrimination in sensation lies in the difference of reaction to 
that which is sensed, an assumption that is reinforced by the 
recognition that the process of sensing is controlled and directed 
by the reaction to the stimulus. 

Now what is implied in perception is the association of the 
new sensory experience with the old. If the chick perceives a 
caterpillar as a < thing,' he may associate the former experience 
of pecking at a thing with the new experience of rejecting the 
peculiarly marked thing. But evidence for such an association 
in the case of the chick certainly is lacking. What has appeared 
in its conduct is a new stimulus of a visual character for a per- 
formed reaction, which up to this and other like experiences had 
no determined visual stimulus. 

The question then arises, what are the conditions for the 
appearance of this permanent core to which varying sensory 
elements may be associated? It is impossible to appeal directiy 
to the introspective analysis of human perception. We cannot 
get inside the consciousness of the lower forms. It is, however, 
possible to find in our own experience of physical objects what 
constitutes this core which endows it with its Thinghood, and 
investigate the conduct and sensory equipment of these forms, 
with a view to determining whether their experience can also 
contain this identical core to which varying phases of the same 

^LocciL 



CONCERNING ANIMAL PBRCBPTION 3^7 

object can be referred. Stout ^ finds this core in what he terms 
< manipulation/ understanding by this any contact experiences 
which arise as the result of visual stimuli, such as the hearing, 
scratching, pulling, shoving, as well as our actual handling of 
what we see. This he illustrates by the visual experience of a 
hole to which an animal is fleeing and which answers to an 
experience of contact, that enables the animal to determine 
whether the opening is passable. 

If this distinction be carried out somewhat further, we find 
that the sensory experiences of animal life may be divided into 
two categories : those that come through what may be called 
the distance sense organs, the visual, olfactory and auditory 
senses, and those that come through the contact sensations. 
The distinction suggested by Stouf s use of the term * manipula^ 
tion ' is that intelligent conduct, when it reaches the stage of 
perception, implies a reference of what comes through the dis*- 
tance sensations to contact sensation. There is perhaps nothing 
inherent in contact experiences which accounts for their being 
the substantial element in perception — that to which, so far as 
physical, i. ^., perceptual, experience goes, all other experience 
is referred. Visual discriminations are much finer and more 
accurate than those of manipulation. The auditory and olfactory 
experience are richer in emotional valuations. But it remains 
true that our perception of physical objects always refers color, 
sound, odor, to a possibly handled substrate, a fact which was 
of course long ago recognized in the distinction between the so-- 
called primary and secondary senses. 

The ground of this is readily found in the nature of animal 
conduct, which, in so far as it is overt can be resolved into move- 
ments, stimulated by the distance senses, ending up in the attain- 
ment or avoidance of certain contacts. Overt food, protective, 
reproductive, fighting processes, all are made up of such move- 
ments toward or away from possible contacts, and the success 
of the conduct depends upon the accuracy with which the dis- 
tance stimulation leads up to appropriate contacts. Consciously 
intelligent conduct within the perceptual field lies in the estimate 
of the sort of contact to which distance sensory stimulates the 
animal form, that is the conscious reference of experience result- 
' Loc, dt.f pp. 326 ff. 



388 GSORGB H. MEAD. 

ing from the stimulation of the eye, the ear, the olfactory tracts, 
even the skin, by the movement of the air, etc., to the contacts 
which this stimulation tends to bring about. 

The vast importance of the human hand for perception 
becomes evident when we recognize how it answers to the eye, 
especially among the distance senses. The development of 
space perception follow in normal individuals upon the interac- 
tion of the eye and the hand, and this interaction works a con- 
tinual meeting of the discriminations of the eye by those of the 
skin, mediated through the manipulating hand. It is this con- 
tact experience which gives the identical core to which the 
contents coming from the distance senses are referred in the so- 
called process of complication. It is this core which answers 
to varying experiences while it remains the same. It is this 
core which is a conditio sine qua non of our perception of phys- 
ical objects. Of course this content of contact experience is 
supplied by the process of association or complication out of 
past experience in most of our perceptions. The objects about 
us look hard or soft, large or small. But the reference is 
always there. 

There are two respects in which the contact experiences of 
lower animal forms are inferior to those of man for the purposes 
of perception. The organs of manipulation are not as well 
adapted in form and function for manipulation itself, and, in 
the second place, the contact experiences of lower animals are, 
to a large extent, determined, not by the process of manipula- 
tion, but are so immediately a part of eating, fighting, repose, 
etc., that it is hard to believe that a consciousness of a * thing' 
can be segregated from these instinctive activities. 

To develop this second point a little further, we need only 
to recall what has been brought out by Dewey ^ and Stout* that 
perception involves a continued control of such an organ as that 
of vision by such an organ as that of the hand, and vice versa. 
We look because we handle, and we are able to handle because 
we look. Attention consists in this mutual relationship of con- 
trol between the processes of stimulation and response, each 
directing the other. But while this control is essential to per- 
ception, perception itself is neither eating, fighting, nor any 
^ PsYCHOi*. Rbview, III., p. 359. * Loc, cU. 



CONCERNING ANIMAL PBRCBPTION 3% 

Other of the organic activities which commence overtly with 
stimulation and end with the response. On the contrary, per- 
ception lies within these activities, and represents a part of the 
mechanism by which these activities are carried out in highly 
organized forms. Perception is a process of mediation within 
the act ; and that form of mediation by which the possible con- 
tact value of the distance stimulation appears with that stimula- 
tion, in other words, a mediation by which we are conscious of 
physical things. The actual eating, fighting or resting, etc., 
are not mediations within the act, but the culminations of the 
acts themselves. We could not perceive bread as a physical 
thing if that cognitive state grew out of the presentation of the 
mastication and taste which constitute eating. We perceive 
what we masticate, what we taste, etc., except in so far as we 
may perceive, through their movements, our various organs, as 
things. 

The great importance of the human hand for perception lies 
in the fact that it is essentially mediatory within the organic 
acts out of which the physiological process of life is made up. 
The presentation of a physical thing which must be made up 
out of the contacts necessary to the actual processes of eating 
or those of locomotion cannot offer as fruitful a field for the 
growth of perception as those which are based upon the medi- 
ations of the hand within the act. And the contents of contact 
experience which a mouth or the paws can present must be 
very inadequate, for just that function of correspondence be- 
tween the elements of the retinal and the tactual experience out 
of which the physical world of normal perception arises. 

To assume that a chick can find in the contact of its bill 
together with those of its feet the materials that answer to the 
perception of a physical thing is almost inconceivable. Even 
the cat and the dog must find in their paws or mouths, fash- 
ioned seemingly for the purposes, not of < feeling things,' but 
of locomotion or tearing and masticating, but a minimum of 
that material which goes into the structure of our perceptions. 
In the case of the monkey the question arises whether the func- 
tion of locomotion is so dominant in use of the so-called hands 
that that of * feeling ' can be isolated out of the monkey's con- 
tact experiences to build up perception. 



39^ GMORGS H. MEAD. 

Finally, to recur to the difficulties inherent in the doctrine 
of perception referred to at the opening of this paper, the assump- 
tion of a perception of things, that is, of what is mediatory in 
experience, carries with it the essence certainly of reasoning, 
I. e., the conscious use of something — a certain type of experi- 
ence — for something else, another type of experience. Every 
perceived thing is in so far as perceived a recognized means to 
possible ends, and there can be no hard and fast line drawn 
between such perceptual consciousness and the more abstracted 
processes of so-called reasoning. Any form that perceives is 
in so far canying on a process of conscious mediation within its 
act and conscious mediation is ratiocination.^ 

*Tlie MS. of this artick was ttoAytA September z8, 1907. —£d. 



A STUDY IN VERTICAL SYMMETRY. 

BY BLBANOR HARRIS ROWLAND. 

It is obvious to anyone who looks at a series of pictures, 
landscapes especially, giving particular attention to the position 
of the horizon line, that he usually finds that line just above or 
just below the center, seldom at the extreme boundaries of the 
picture and almost never at the center itself. The question 
naturally arises. Is there any reason for this uniformity of 
choice and would the same conditions and demands hold good 
if reduced to the simplicity of an experiment ? The following 
is an account of an inquiry into the choices made by eleven ob- 
servers of divisions of a rectangular space, and an analysis of 
their methods of apperception. 

To test the question the following apparatus was used : A 
black, rectangular picture-frame, with an opening 33 by 25 cm. 
had a black background placed behind, with light gray fore- 
grounds of graded widths placed before it. 

In the second series the background was gray and the fore- 
grounds were black. These foregrounds were numbered from 
I. to XI. No. VI. measured 12^ cm. filling exactly half the 
opening while the others graded both ways at intervals of 2 cm. 

The method of procedure was to start with the widest gray 
foreground and to exhibit all the sizes down to the narrowest^ 
and back again, against the black background. Then the ob- 
server was asked to tell where she liked to have the dividing 
line come, and, if possible, to tell why she liked it that way. 
The same question was asked with the second series. 

Out of eleven observers in Series L, four preferred to see 
the dividing line just below the center, or the No. V. card; 
two wanted the division just above the center, or the No. VII. 
card; two chose IV., while VIIL, IX. and III. were each 
chosen by one person. In Series II. three observers chose No. 
v., two preferred IV., two VII. and two IX., while III. and 
XI. had each one vote. 

39» 



39* BLBANOR HARRIS ROWLAND, 

The largest group, then, preferred a division just below the 
central line; another group preferred varying points slightly 
above the central line, while choices of the extreme divisions of 
II. and III. or X. and XI. were rare and those for equal divi- 
sion entirely absent. 

The attention of the observers was called to this fact, and 
they were asked why they did not choose the central division. 
The almost uniform answer was, that when it was divided 
evenly they did not < see it as a picture,' it was < too flat and 
uninteresting.' 

This testimony brought several things to light: (i) That 
with no comment on the part of the experimenter they had been 
taking the empty cards < as pictures ' ; (2) that the very unequal 
division resisted their efforts to see it as a picture and therefore 
it was not chosen ; (3) that with the equally divided space it 
apparently did not occur to them to ^ see it as a picture ' at all. 
Just as the slightly unequal spaces had naturally become land- 
scapes, snow-scenes or sea-views, so did the equally divided 
space simply look like two equal cards. This change of apper- 
ception for the equal division was uniform, although none could 
give a reason why she had changed except that the equal cards 
' didn't look like anything.' 

The next questions put to them were : 

1. Can you see the equally divided space, and the very un- 
equal divisions as pictures and those formerly seen as pictures, 
as cards — that is, can the apperception be varied at will? 

2. Is there any difference between the two modes of per- 
ceiving, except the presence or absence of associations? 

3. Does your feeling-tone vary with this change of apper- 
ception ? 

4. Do you find it more difiicult to vary your perception one 
way than the other? 

5. Exactly what do you consciously do to change your 
apperception? 

The answers to some of the questions were uniform, but the 
introspection varied in others. All of the obervsers found that 
they could vary their apperception at will, and that such varia- 
tion not only supplied or deprived the cards of associative value. 



A STUDY IN VERTICAL SYMMETRY, 393 

but made them look deep or ^at. When seen as a picture the 
background retreated, more or less according to the division 
(their favorite division usually had the greatest depth of any) 
but when seen simply as cards, the background moved front or 
the foreground back, to make a plane surface. 

Their feeling-tone varied with this change of view, so that 
three liked the equal division, if they forgot it was equal and 
saw it as something else. 

Most of them had more difficulty in changing the appercep- 
tion for the very unequal divisions, but with practice they could 
also modify these at will. 

The most interesting introspection came however on the last 
question, where despite their difference in expression, there was 
some agreement as to their difference in fixation point in the 
two cases. 

When looking at the cards as at a picture^ the attention was 
more centered, either on the dividing horizontal line or exactly 
above or below it, but always on the median axis. They looked 
from this point to other parts of the surface, but always turned 
back to the same central point. When, however, they looked 
at the divided space simply as cardboards, it at once became 
flat and unaccented. One observer said that she saw it much 
more impartially, looking not only at the median axis or the 
division line, but also around the edges and the frame. An- 
other, when seeing it without picture associations, described her 
attention as following several parallel lines across the space, 
the division line or the central axis being no more important 
than the others. Another looked up and down impartially 
along vertical lines, never resting at the center. Several ob- 
servers spoke of seeing the edges of the cards in the flat apper- 
ception, which they had not noticed when seeing the cards as 
pictures. One observer felt that her fixation for the picture ap- 
perception was at a point in the middle of the division line, 
behind the card, as if she were looking at a distant point, but 
the simple card perception meant aimless travelling along the 
division line over the surface and edges. 

It would seem from these introspections from eleven regular 
observers (and essentially similar results were obtained from a 



394 ELEANOR HARRIS ROWLAND. 

class of forty all observing at once) that a rectangular space 
divided into equal halves by a horizontal line, tends to be taken 
as flat, as free from varied associations and without strong cen- 
tral accent, and it has thereby very little the * picture ' charac* 
ter. On the other hand, the slightly unequal division lends 
itself to apperception of depth, and consequently to associations 
and to being taken as a picture. Doubdess the observers were 
influenced in their association by the fact that most pictures have 
the latter type of division, but the question still remains — Why 
do they? 

It is interesting in this connection, that two observers liked 
the equal division very much, but did not want \\ framed. That 
is, their attention not being bound to a central point, wandered 
at large over the surface, and felt cramped by the frame. This 
suggests a possible reason why we do not, as a matter of fact, 
frame geometrical designs, however satisfactory they may be 
in themselves. In geometric designs, which are usually 
strongly symmetrical, both bilaterally and vertically, however 
much a central point may be indicated, we do not take it as a 
center of interest. Our attention is more or less impartial, it 
extends with equal interest to the edges, and is better satisfied 
by a repetition of itself than by a frame. Its out-going activity 
demands continuance of its design, while the in-going tendency 
of the picture requires exactly the reverse.* 

^ The MS. of this article was received Jtme 30, 1907. — Hn. 



LOGICAL COMMUNITY AND THE DIFFERENCE OF 
DISCERNIBLES- 

BY PROPBSSOR J. MARK BALDWIN, 

Johns Hopkins University, 

In certain of our discussions^ we have reached positions 
which involve the recognition of the intent of judgment to 
hold for more than one individual. We have given to this aspect 
of meaning the name of ' community.' We may now gather 
together the positions taken up in various connections, and show 
certain of their larger bearings. 

1. In the first place, it appears that the process ordinarily 
known as generalization in logic is one in which a common 
meaning arises, that is, a meaning in community. The general 
meaning not only applies to each of the particulars under it, 
but it also holds for different individuals. The general-particu<^ 
lar relationship remains the same whether the different cases 
that serve as particulars be observed by one individual or by 
many. This case is the one covered in logic by the theory of 
< extension.' Certain variations upon it arise when we take 
explicitly the point of view of the community of the meaning. 

2. Second, we find certain peculiarities attaching to the 
meaning rendered as * singular.' When only one object is 
meant, such an object can be made subject-matter of judg- 
ment only from the point of view of community, not from the 
point of view of the extension of the objective class — although 
this is the construction given it by formal logic, which con- 
siders it a universal of a class of one I A single object can be 
generalized only from the point of view of the process that in 
some manner distinguishes in it different instances or particu- 
lars. This occurs in two ways, both of which show the abso- 
lute necessity of recognizing the character of community in 
logic. 

^In Thought and Things^ ot Genetic Logic^ Vol. II., " Qzperiaieiital 
Logic," of which this article constitutes a section (in Chap. xiv.). 

395 



39^ /. MARK BALDWIN. 

The first of these is that in which the one single object is 
actually experienced by different persons^ as for instance, the 

* falling' of a star. If we disregard those aspects of meaning 
wherein the single object may also be one of a class — then there 
is left over only that aspect wherein it is a single object to dif- 
ferent persons. We have elsewhere shown how by processes of 

* secondary conversion ' ^ between different minds this meaning 
arises. The point to consider here is this : such a meaning can 
become logical — in the sense of having different cases to serve 
as basis of generalization — only if different experiences of one 
object can play the r&le of experiences of different objects : that 
isy only if community of experience takes the place of extensive 
quantity. The experiences of different minds furnish the differ- 
ences which become particulars under a general. The identity 
of a singular — say, for example, the identity of the shooting star 
seen by different observers — can be rendered in a judgment only 
through the generalization of the appearances to these observers, 
whereby the event is pronounced the same for all of them. This 
is a movement in community^ or in a mode that preserves the 
force of community. 

We may say, therefore, at this point, that, but for the 
aspect of community attaching to judgment, the logical render- 
ing of a singular would be impossible. 

The other case of the rendering of a singular, seeing its 
great importance, may be placed under a separate heading. 

3. A third case is that of the meaning attaching to a single 
object when experienced by a single person only; in what sense 
can such a meaning be rendered in terms of general and par- 
ticular, and so become subject-matter of judgment? 

Here also it is evident that there is no general meaning in 
extensive quantity. The meaning is a singular because of the 
mark or group of marks which prevent its generalization with 
other objects in a class. How then can we judge such an object 
the same, and expect others, if and when they do experience 
it, to agree with us ? — or not experiencing it, still to accept our 
report of it? 

Here again we have an evident resort to community. If we 

■ See nought and Things, Vol. I., Chap, iv,, { 5. 



THE DIFFERENCE OF DISCERNIBLES. 397 

consider the generalization in the instance just discussed above 
— that of one object seen by different observers — to proceed 
upon differences in experiences, the object being found identical 
through the differences of its appearances to the different ob- 
servers, then the recognition of community gives us the same 
result here. Judgment in community renders meaning as hold- 
ing yi?r different personal acts oj judgment; and the require- 
ments of the case are met as well, and in precisely the same 
way, when recurrent experiences of one person are substituted 
for different experiences of more than one. There arises what 
we may well call a * general of recurrence.' In both cases, 
the generalization proceeds upon the commonness of the various 
constructions of the meaning, whether these be experiences in 
one mind or in many. The process whereby the meaning of 
* sameness ' attaches to an object is the same whether the recur- 
rences of the meaning thus identified as the same be in one mind 
or in more ; for there is either actual reference,^ or the presupposi- 
tion of it, from one experience to another in both cases alike. 
We reach, then, the striking result that a judgment of singular 
identity is one that may arise by the generalization of successive 
experiences in one mind, and this generalization is read in com- 
munity as equally valid for other minds. That is, we again 
come to the conclusion that a judgment of singular identity is 
possible on the basis of a single person's recurrent experience ; 
and that it is a judgment in community, having the force of com- 
monness for all thinkers alike. But for the character of com- 
munity, however, such a judgment would be impossible ; for 
there is no guarantee, apart from the intent of community, that 
the individual's identification of the object through recurrent 
experiences is socially available. 

The cases now interpreted show clearly just what the intent 
of community really is. It is the implication, in the rendering 
of an identical meaning by any one person, of other persons' 
judgment whoever they may be. It rests upon the fact, which 
we have studied in detail, that such a judgment of identity is 
one of recurrent* experiences, whether the objects experienced 

^ Reference of the sort caHed 'conversion' in my Vol. I; see the last note above. 
*'Recnrrent,' that is, in the general sense of duplicated or plnral, not 
necessarily successive. 



39^ /. MARK BALDWIN. 

be one or many, and whether the observers is one or many. 
The intent of community therefore is essential to judgment and 
is independent of variations in the other characters, especially 
of variations in extension. 

This result appears in an interesting light when we view the 
three cases mentioned in the reverse order. If we take a judg- 
ment of a single individual's recurrent experience of one object 
as given, we may ask what it involves besides his personal 
belief. The first additional element of the meaning is found to 
be that this person expects his judgment to be confirmed by any 
one else who may experience the object. That is, the community 
intent is one that allows the substitution of another's personal 
experiences for one's own, or the intercalation of that person's 
experience in the series of one's own as in all respects equivalent 
to one's own. This carries over the meaning to the case men- 
tioned second above — that of an object experienced by different 
observers. 

Another implication then appears. Whenever occasions 
arise in which a judgment of identity in recurrence fails to 
establish itself, the experiences are read as different objects; 
that is, a generalization in extension takes place, whether or no 
there actually be more objects than one. The individual re- 
marks, * I did not recognize you — I took you for a different 
man.' This is precisely the same result as if different individ- 
uals had disagreed in their several reports of the one object. 
The judgment such individi^als would reach after conference is 
that there are two objects of the same class, and this is the 
result the one person reaches on the basis of recurrence. The 
step now taken is that whereby the single individual's treatment 
of recurrent experiences of one object is logically equivalent to 
the ordinary generalization by one or more persons of different 
particular objects. But this holds entirely and only within the 
mode of community, since objectively there is but the one 
object. 

We here come upon a principle which may be formulated 
alongside a celebrated historical dictum, the 'identity, or 
sameness, of indiscernibles.' While usually associated with 
the name of Leibnitz, on account of his use of it in his theory of 



THE DIFFERENCE OF DISCERNIBLES. 399 

< monads,' it has been formulated in somewhat different senses 
by various thinkers.* We might describe it in Hegelian terms 
as the principle of the * oneness of the many/ and set over 
against it a principle to be called the * difference of discernibles * 
or the ^ manyness of the one.' In the terms of our present 
analysis, the * identity of indiscernibles ' means in principle 
that in the absence of discernible difference two or more ob- 
jects are judged to be one and the same in recurrent experi- 
ence. It is evident that we have here the process of individu- 
ating as one, objects which do not give experience of difference. 
This is, therefore, just the case we have pointed out as gener- 
alization in community and not in extension. The experiences 
may be anybody's or everybody's ; they are rendered in a judg- 
ment of singular identity. The experiences of different objects 
are really equivalent to those resulting from the recurrence of 
one. 

The same movement is capable, on our principles, of pre- 
cisely the reverse reading — the reading formulated in the 
phrase * difference of discernibles.' A single object is ren- 
dered, by reason of differences discerned in its several appear- 
ances, as more than one. The experience passes from that form 
in which a single object is found to recur to one mind, and also 
from that in which it appears as one to different minds, to that 
in which its several cases have marks of difference which forbid 
the individuation as one object. 

The principle of * identity of indiscernibles,' when psycho- 
logically interpreted, expresses the movement in community 
whereby like experiences of more than one object may yield an 
object identified as one ; while that of the ' difference of discern- 
ibles ' expresses the movement also in community whereby 
unlike experiences of one object may lead to its determination 
as more than one.' 

^LeibnitZi Monadologie^ 9, and Nouveaux essais, 11., chap. 27, {iff. For 
citations from other authors see Eisler, WMeH>uch d. philos. BegriffCy Art 
Identitaiis indiscemibilium, 

'The epistemological bearings of these principles are reserved for treat- 
ment in the later volume. Here it may be suggested, however, that all gen- 
eralization illustrates the < identity of indiscernibles ' and all singulari^tion 
illustrates the ' difference of discernibles.' For generalization summarizes the 



4«> /. MARK BALDWIN. 

In brief, any judgment, by reason of its community of intent, 
may be read in any one of three ways : as meaning (i) more 
than one object, appearing to one person or many ; (2) one object 
only, appearing to one person or many; or (3) one object 
only, appearing to one person only. The process of generali- 
zation as such, considered as a summarizing of likenesses in 
recurrent experience, can in nowise determine which of these 
three the actual meaning is to be. A paranoiac declares that 
everybody is persecuting him, because he generalizes recurrent 
experiences as all fit to excite his fear of others ; he is working 
under the principle of * identity of indiscernibles.' At the other 
extreme we may cite the individual we call * subjective,' who 
sees always in our conduct, however uniformly kind, new and 
varied signs of change. He in turn is magnifying the * differ- 
ence of discernibles.' The actual force in any case of normal 
judgment is determined by the control factor, the coefficients of 
fact which limit the meaning. The paranoiac's constructions do 
not allow the control that the actual differences in his attendants' 
action should secure ; the uniform tide of his fear obliterates 
these differences. Nor are those of the * subjective ' man con- 
trolled in the larger meaning of kindliness that pervades the 
variety of our acts. In his case, the pebbles of variety choke 
the tide of sameness. Both are abnormal in that the actual 
facts do not get in their proper work.^ 

upects of meaning in which objects are indittingnishAble or identical, and singn- 
larization fixet those aspects in which each object is disoerniblj difierent from 
all others. We now see that this latter process, the logical rendering of the 
singular, ezplidtl j requires the intent of community, a result which shows the 
radical rdle played by the common or social factor in all the'processes of thought 
1 It is interesting to note that there are forms of speech in which meanings 
based on the recurrent appearances of objects are recognised, whether such ap- 
pearances are to one person or many. Propositions in which the predicate is 
modified by the words ' sometimes,' 'often,* 'always,' etc., may embody this 
meaning. ' This woman is always vain ' is a universal in appearance ; it is quanti- 
fied in community ; just as ' women are slways Tain,' equivalent to ' all women are 
▼ain,' has universal quantity in extension. Propositions in < sometimes ' are par- 
ticular in community (as * this woman is sometimes vain ') or in extension (as 
* women are sometimes vain ' ), or in both (as ' some women are sometimes vain* ). 
This sort of proposition rendering variety of appearances, which change with time 
and circumstance, has been said by certain logicians to have multiple quantifica- 
tion (see Johnson in Mind^ 1902, on 'The Logical Calculus,' and Keynes, 
Formal Logic, sect 70). The name is a good one, since the two aspects of 



THE DIFFERENCE OF DISCERNIBLES. 4^1 

I have also found reason, in the detailed discussions from 
which this statement is extracted, to distinguish two modes 
within the meaning of community. Community * for whom ' — 
the intent of a judgment to hold for many individuals as for one 
— is correlated with community * by whom ' — the further in- 
tent to suggest that the meaning may not be universally preva- 
lent or catholic as a fact, but may be actually held by a certain 
number only. It is evident that what has been said in the dis- 
cussion above about generalization in community, holds, in the 
first instance, of community * f or whom/ The question may 
be asked whether the other sort of community, that of catho- 
licity, the relative commonness of the content as actually held 
in different minds, has any logical role. 

There are meanings, and of course forms of speech fitted to 
express them, which not only recognize the recurrence of ap- 
pearances, as basis of the predication made, but also the limi- 
tation of these appearances to a restricted number of persons. 
For example, the propositions * there are observations that indi- 
cate that Mars is inhabited,' and ' Mr. Lowell holds that Mars is 
inhabited,* have both these shades of meaning. The reference 
to a plurality of observers may indeed be the more emphatic ele- 
ment as in the proposition, * as to the truth of evolution there is 
wide agreement among biologists.' Of course, every one would 
admit that such meanings can be expressed, it is a very differ- 
ent thing to say that such an intent is always present in the 
judgment. But if we are right in holding that a problematical 
shading of meaning attaches to all judgments when they are 
actually current; that all judgment intends personal belief, 
which is expressed in order to silence doubt or extend convic- 
tion ; in short, that all judgment has an experimental and in- 
strumental force — then here in this mode of community we 
should find its variations. Probably, as a matter of fact, the 

meaning do both render quantity ; but it ia hard to see how the quantification 
due to recurrent appearances of one object can be brought under the ordinary 
logical doctrine of quantity in extension. If we recognize, however, the recur- 
rent appearances of one object to one mind or more as psychologicaUy equiva- 
lent to the recognitian of a plurality of different objects, for the purposes of 
generalization, then in this movement which gives what I csMl 'community ' the 
additional mode of quantity arises. 



40» /. MARK BALDWIN. 

majority of cultivated people, if asked whether evolution is true, 
would say in effect, ' yes, most of the best biologists accept it.' 
The ground of personal acceptance here seems to be relative 
prevalence and the explicit recognition of this in such a judg- 
ment as that last cited, brings out the presupposition of the mode 
of community < by whom ' in the simple judgment of truth. 
Often the conditions of the appearance of the object or event 
to which the proposition refers require a meaning in catholicity. 

* Shooting stars are often red,' ' sea-serpents have no fins,' 'the 
moon is made of green cheese,' are propositions that require 
this presupposition. They mean to report a certain degree of 
prevalence of the opinion, observation, or belief, which the 
proposition renders, as well as to cite a number of illustrative 
cases or appearances* These variations in prevalence or rela- 
tive catholicity constitute a further sort of quantification. 

The implication made in respect to prevalence varies from 
the singularity of the opinion or judgment rendered as private, 
to the universality of an appeal, let us say, to the catholicity of 

* common sense.' Between these lies the particular quantity 
of a proposition which renders the common judgment of a limited 
group. 

The three modes of quantity therefore that may attach 
to judgments are (i) quantity in extension (as in ' men are 
sometimes irritable '), (a) quantity in communis * for whom ' or 

* community of appearance' (as in <John is sometimes irri- 
table ') and (3) quantity in community * by whom ' or in catholicity 
(as in * we all find John irritable ')• 



« I I 

1 



Ifti