Skip to main content

Full text of "Psychological review"

See other formats


03  & 
THE 


Psychological  Review 


EDITED  BY 

J.  MARK  BALDWIN  J.  McKEEN  CATTELL 

AND 

PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY  COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY 


WITH  THE  CO-OPERATION  OF 

ALFRED  BINET,  ficoLE  DES  HAUTES-£TUDES,  PARIS;'  JOHN  DEWEY,  H.  H.  DONALD- 
SON, UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO;  G.  S.  FULLERTON,  UNIVERSITY  OF  PENNSYLVANIA; 
G.  H.  HOWISON,  UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA;  JOSEPH  JASTROW,  UNI- 
VERSITY OF  WISCONSIN;    G.  T.   LADD,  'YALE   UNIVERSITY;    HUGO 
MtfNSTERBERG,  HARVARD  UNIVERSITY;   M.  ALLEN  STARR, 
COLLEGE  OF  PHYSICIANS  AND  SURGEONS,  NEW  YORK;  CARL 
STUMPF,  UNIVERSITY,  BERLIN;   JAMES  SULLY, 
UNIVERSITY  COLLEGE,  LONDON. 


Volume  VI.     1899. 


PUBLISHED    BI-MONTHLY   BY 

THE  MACMILLAN  COMPANY, 

41  N.  QUEEN  ST.,  LANCASTER,  PA. 
66  FIFTH  AVENUE,  NEW  YORK;  AND  LONDON. 


P7 


PRESS  OF 

THE  NEW  ERA  PRINTING_COMPANY, 
LANCASTER,  PA. 


CONTENTS   OF  VOLUME  VI. 


ALPHABETICAL  INDICES  OF  NAMES  AND  SUBJECTS  WILL   BE  FOUND  AT   THE 
END  OF  THE  VOLUME. 

ARTICLES. 

PAGE 

History  and  Psychology  :  HUGO  MONSTERBERG i 

The  Relations  between  certain  Organic  Processes  and  Conscious- 
ness: J.  R.  ANGELL  and  H.  B.  THOMPSON 32 

Professor  Miiller's  Theory  of  the  Light  Sense :  C.  LADD  FRANK- 
LIN      70 

On    Certain    Hindrances    to    the    Progress    of    Psychology    in 

America:  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD 121 

The  Evolution  of  Modesty  :  HAVELOCK  ELLIS... 134 

Proceedings  of  the  Seventh  Annual  Meeting  of  the  American 

Psychological  Association,  New  York,  December,  1898....   146 

The  Study  of  Geometrical  Illusions:  CHARLES  H.  JUDD 241 

The  Nature  of  Animal  Intelligence  and  the  Methods  of  Investigat- 
ing it :  WESLEY  MILLS 262 

The  Development  of  Voluntary  Movement :  E.  A.  KIRKPATRICK  275 
The  Instinctive  Reaction  of  Young  Chicks :  EDWARD  THORN- 
DIKE 282 

Studies  on  the  Telegraphic  Language ;  the  Acquisition  of  a  Hier- 
archy of  Habits :  W.  L.  BRYAN  and  NOBLE  HARTER 346 

Communications  from  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  Harvard 
University : 

Automatic  Reactions:  L.  M.  SOLOMONS 376 

Recognition  under  Objective  Reversal :  GEORGE  V.  N.  DEAR- 
BORN   395 

A  Plea  for  Soul-substance:  W.  P.  MONTAGUE 458 

The  Reaction-time  of  the  Eye:  RAYMOND  DODGE 477 

A  Study  in  the  Dynamics  of  Personal  Religion:   G.  A.  COE 484 

On  the  Validity  of  the  Griesbach  Method  of  determining  Fatigue : 

JAMES  H.  LEUBA 573 


iv  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

On  the  Invalidity  of  the  yEsthesiometric  Method  as  a  Measure  of 

Mental  Fatigue :  DR.  GEO.  B.  GERMANN 599 

A  Plea  for  Soul-Substance  II. :  W.  P.  MONTAGUE...  .  606 


DISCUSSION   AND   REPORTS. 

Professor  Groos  and  Theories  of  Play:  H.  M.  STANLEY 86 

Professor  Eucken  on  the  Spiritual  Content  of  Life :  FRANCIS 

KENNEDY 92 

Experience  under  the  Influence  of  Ether:  J.  B 104 

The  Material  versus  the  Dynamic  Psychology:  C.  L.  HERRICK..  180 

The  Postulates  of  a  Structural  Psychology:  W.  CALDWELL 187 

Psychological  Methods:  W.  CALDWELL 191 

Professor  Mii nsterberg  on  Mysticism  :  J.  H.  HYSLOP 292 

Mr.  Marshall  and  the  Theory  of  Religion:  H.  M.  STANLEY 298 

A  Lecture  Experiment  in  Hallucinations:  E.  E.  SLOSSEN 407 

Professor  Hyslop  on  Mysticism  :  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG 408 

Psychology  and  the  Real  Life :  C.  B.  BLISS 410 

A  Reply  to  '  The  Nature  of  Animal  Intelligence  and  the  Methods 

of  Investigating  it ' :  EDWARD  THORNDIKE 412 

Notes  on  After-images  :  J.  M.  GILLETTE 420 

Attributes  of  Sensation :  M.  W.  CALKINS 506 

Is  the  Memory  of  Absolute  Pitch  Capable  of  Development  by 

Training:  MAX  MEYER 514 

The  Growth  of  Voluntary  Control :  HENRY  DAVIES 639 

Ethological  Psychology  :  THOMAS  P.  BAILEY,  Jr 649 

Sensation  Attributes  and  Sensation:  GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN..  651 
After-images  :  MARGARET  FLOY  WASHBURN 653 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

Mivart's  Groundwork  of  Science:  A.  C.  ARMSTRONG,  JR 107 

Peres  1'Art  et  le  real:  W.  M.  URBAN no 

Royce's  Studies  of  Good  and  Evil,  and  the  Conception  of  God : 

J.   G.    HlBBEN Ill 


CONTENTS.  V 

PAGE 

Hibben's  Problems  of  Philosophy:  J.  H.  HYSLOP , 113 

Individual  Psychology  (Guicciardiand  Ferrari)  :  H.  C.  WARREN   113 

Vision:  C.  LADD  FRANKLIN 117 

Psychophysical  and  Physiological  (Binet's  Annee,  IV.,  1898; 
Yale  Studies,  V.,  1898)  :  J.  R.  ANGELL,  G.  V.  N.  DEAR- 
BORN, B.  B.  BREESE 195 

Fatigue   (Kemsies,  Wagner,  Kraepelin)  :   R.  MAcDouGALL 203 

Time-sense  (Schumann,  Ebhardt)  :   C.  H.  JUDD 208 

Vision   (Greef,  Miiller,  Marbe)  :    C.  LADD  FRANKLIN,   C.  H. 

JUDD 212 

Sutherland's  Moral  Instinct :  A.  ALLIN 4 216 

Peckham's  Habits  of  Wasps:  H.  M.  STANLEY 219 

Westermarck's  Essence  of  Revenge:  H.  M.  STANLEY 221 

Creighton's  Logic:  J.  G.  HIBBEN 222 

Leroy's  Education  de  la  volonte :  W.  R.  NEWBOLD 225 

Blondeau's  1'Absolu  :  H.  N.  GARDINER 228 

Cron  and  Kraepelin's  Auffassungsf ahigkeit :  E.  C.  JONES 229 

Mind  and  Body  (Rehmke,  Heymans,  Weinmann)  :  D.  S.  MILLER  233 

Le  Bon's  Psychology  of  Peoples:  G.  A.  TAWNEY 305 

Mercier's  Psychologic  contemporaine :   R.  S.  WOODWORTH. 307 

Piat's  Personne  humaine :   H.  N.  GARDINER 310 

Lloyd's  Citizenship  and  Salvation:   C.  M.  BAKEWELL 312 

Hogan's  Study  of  a  Child:  K.  C.  MOORE 316 

Child  Psychology  (Gutzmann,  Ziehen)  :   R.  MAcDouGALL 317 

Worm's  Collective  and  Individual  Psychology:   C.  B.  BLISS 322 

Heinrich's  Intensitatsschwankungen,  Fairchild's  Ethical  Instruc- 
tion, Weir's  Dawn  of  Reason :  C.  B.  BLISS,  E.  A.  KIRK- 
PATRICK  326 

Vision:   C.  LADD  FRANKLIN 329 

General :  C.  B.  BLISS,  WILFRED  LAY,  C.  E.  SEASHORE,  W.  M. 

URBAN 332 

Physiology  and  Neurology:  G.  V.  N.  DEARBORN 338 

Powell's  Truth  and  Error:  D.  S.  MILLER 423 

James's  Human  Immortality:  C.  W.  HODGE 424 

Recejac's  Mystic  Knowledge  :  A.  T.  ORMOND 426 

Stern's  Veranderungsauffassung :  E.  F.  BUCHNER 428 


Vi  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

Ziehen's  Psych ophysiologische  Erkenntnistheorie :    E.  F.  BUCH- 
NER      432 

D'Eichthal's  John  Stuart  Mill :  J.  G.  HIBBEN 440 

General:  E.  F.  BUCHNER,  ARTHUR  ALLIN,  H.  C.  WARREN,  C. 

B.  BLISS 440 

Vision:  C.  L.  FRANKLIN,  M.  W.  CALKINS 447 

Pathology  and  Neurology  (Duprat's  ITnstabilite  mentale)  :  D. 

P.  BARNITZ,  G.  V.  N.  DEARBORN 451 

Marshall's  Instinct  and  Reason:  G.  A.  TAWNEY 517 

Villa's  La  Psicologia  Contemporanea  :  G.  TOSTI... 529 

Gidding's  Elements  of  Sociology:  J.  H.  TUFTS 533 

James's  Talks  to  Teachers  on  Psychology:  E.  H.  GRIFFIN 536 

Dexter's  Conduct  and  the  Weather :  THE  AUTHOR 539 

Dearborn's  Emotion  of  Joy  :  THE  AUTHOR 540 

Optical  Illusions  (Lipps,  Witasek,  Einthoven,  Zehender)  :  C. 

H.  JUDD 543 

General  (Iowa  Studies,  Magic,  etc.)  :  S.  I.  FRANZ,  J.  McK.  C., 

F.  KENNEDY,  G.  V.  N.  DEARBORN 548 

Muir's  Adam  Smith:  J.  W.  L.  JONES 556 

Gamble's  Weber's  Law  and  Smell:  G.  M.  STRATTON 557 

Experimental:  S.  I.  FRANZ,  H.  C.  WARREN 561 

Ethology:  C.  B.   BLISS 563 

Genetic,  Educational  and  Social:   R.  MACDOUGALL,  J.  M.  B., 

G.  V.  N.  DEARBORN 564 

Neurology    and   Pathology     (Janet's    Nevroses    et    ide"es  fixes), 

Church  and  Peterson  on  Nervous  and  Mental   Diseases : 

M.  ALLEN  STARR 655 

The  Emotions  (Hartenberg  and  Vaschide)  :  H.  N.  GARDINER  ; 
(Stumpf) :     EDWARD   FRANKLIN    BUCHNER:      (Stanley 

Hall)  :    ARTHUR  ALLIN 660 

Experimental :    C.  E.  SEASHORE,   RAYMOND  DODGE,  CHARLES 

H.  JUDD 668 

Philosophical:  R.  M.  WENLEY,  F.  KENNEDY,  N.  P.  GILMAN...  670 

New  Books: 118,  235,  343,  453,  569,  673 

Notes: "9»  237>  344>  456>  571.  673 


VOL.  VI.     No.  i.  JANUARY,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.1 

BY  PROFESSOR  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 
Harvard   University. 

A  few  years  ago,  at  the  Philadelphia  meeting  of  our  Asso- 
ciation, the  Presidential  Address  sketched  the  wonderful  progress 
of  our  modern  psychology  and  culminated  in  the  statement : 
"  We  are  past  the  time  for  systems  of  psychology;  now  hand- 
books of  psychology  are  prepared."  Psychology,  indeed,  since 
its  declaration  of  independence,  is  eager  to  find  out  and  to  collect 
the  special  facts,  without  allowing  the  traditional  interference  of 
metaphysical  philosophy,  and  that  which  brings  us  together  in 
our  Association  ought  to  remain  our  common  interest  in  the  dis- 
covery of  empirical  psychical  facts.  And  yet  I  cannot  help  think- 
ing that  many  of  us  who  sincerely  agree  with  that  enthusiasm  for 
daily  use  are  ready  to  confess  the  wish  of  thoughtful  hours  that, 
while  handbooks  of  psychology  appear  now  in  masses,  the  time 
may  come  again  for  systems  of  psychology.  We  strive,  I  think, 
from  the  disconnected  facts  towards  a  systematic  unity,  and  know 
that  such  unity  is  never  reached  by  even  the  most  complete  col- 
lection of  facts,  but  only  by  a  philosophical  understanding  of 
the  fundamental  principles  of  our  work.  The  discussion  of  the 
basal  conceptions  and  categories  of  psychology,  of  its  presup- 
positions and  its  limitations,  of  its  relations  to  other  empirical 
sciences  and  to  philosophy,  seems  thus  still  more  important  and 
essential  than  the  results  of  any  observation,  and  the  fact  that 
in  recent  years  inquiries  in  regard  to  the  psychological  standpoint 

1  President's  Address,  American  Psychological  Association,  New  York  Meet- 
ing, December,  1898. 


2  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

have  come  everywhere  to  the  foreground  of  epistemological  re- 
search appears  to  point  more  strongly  towards  the  real  progress 
of  psychology  than  any  discovery  between  the  walls  of  our 
laboratories.  I  welcome,  therefore,  the  more,  the  honorable  op- 
portunity of  this  hour,  as  I  understand  that  the  Presidential  Ad- 
dress should  emphasize  the  general  problems  of  our  science. 

My  address  deals  with  the  limits  of  psychology.  I  know 
quite  well  that  such  a  choice  easily  suggests  the  suspicion  of 
heresy ;  whoever  asks  eagerly  for  the  limits  of  a  science  appears 
to  the  first  glance  in  a  hostile  attitude  towards  it.  To  emphasize 
its  limiting  boundaries  means  to  restrain  its  rights  and  to  lessen  its 
freedom.  It  seems,  indeed,  almost  an  anti-psychological  under- 
taking for  any  one  to  say  to  this  young  science,  which  is  so  full  of 
the  spirit  of  enterprise  :  Keep  within  the  bounds  of  your  domain. 
But  you  remember  the  word  of  Kant :  "  It  is  not  augmentation, 
but  deformation  of  the  sciences,  if  we  efface  their  limits."  Kant 
is  speaking  of  logic,  but  at  present  his  word  seems  to  be  for  no 
field  truer  than  for  psychology.  Psychology,  it  seems  to  me, 
encouraged  by  its  quick  triumphs  over  its  old-fashioned  meta- 
physical rival,  to-day  moves  instinctively  towards  an  expansion- 
istic  policy.  A  psychological  imperialism  which  dictates  laws 
to  the  whole  world  of  inner  experience  seems  often  to  be  the 
goal.  But  sciences  are  not  like  the  domiciles  of  nations ;  their 
limits  cannot  be  changed  by  mere  agreement.  The  presuppo- 
sitions with  which  a  science  starts  decide  for  all  time  as  to  the 
possibilities  of  its  outer  extension.  The  botanists  may  resolve 
to-morrow  that  from  now  on  they  will  study  the  movements  of 
the  stars  also ;  it  is  their  private  matter  to  choose  whether  they 
want  to  be  botanists  only  or  also  astronomers,  but  they  can  never 
decide  that  astronomy  shall  become  in  future  a  part  of-  botany, 
supposing  that  they  do  not  claim  the  Milky  Way  as  a  big  vege- 
table. Every  extension  beyond  the  sharp  limits  which  are  de- 
termined by  the  logical  presuppositions  can  thus  be  only  the 
triumph  of  confusion,  and  the  ultimate  arbitration,  which  is  the 
function  of  epistemology,  must  always  decide  against  it.  It 
is  thus  love  and  devotion  for  psychology  which  demands  that  its 
energies  be  not  wasted  by  the  hopeless  task  of  transgressions 
into  other  fields. 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY. 


Philosophers  and  psychologists  are  mostly  willing  to  ac- 
knowledge such  a  discriminative  attitude  when  the  relations 
between  psychology  and  the  normative  sciences,  ethics,  logic, 
aesthetics,  are  in  question.  They  know  that  a  mere  description 
and  causal  explanation  of  ethical,  assthetical  and  logical  mental 
facts  in  spite  of  its  legitimate  relative  value  cannot  in  itself  be 
substituted  for  the  doctrines  of  obligation.  The  line  of  demarca- 
tion thus  separates  with  entire  logical  sharpness  the  duties  from 
the  facts,  the  duties  which  have  to  be  appreciated  in  their 
validity  as  ideals  for  the  will,  and  the  facts  which  have  to  be 
analyzed  and  explained  in  their  physical  or  psychical  existence 
as  objects  of  perception.  But  can  we  overlook  the  symptoms 
of  growing  opposition  against  the  undiscriminative  treatment  of 
the  world  of  facts  in  the  empirical  sciences?  The  creed  of 
those  who  believe  in  such  uniformity  is  simple  enough  :  the 
universe  is  made  up  of  physical  and  psychical  processes,  and  it 
is  the  purpose  of  science  to  discover  their  elements  and  their 
laws  ;  we  may  differentiate  and  classify  the  sciences  with  regard 
to  the  different  objects  which  we  analyze  or  with  regard  to  the 
different  processes  the  laws  of  which  we  study,  but  there  cannot 
exist  in  the  world  anything  which  does  not  find  a  suitable  place 
in  a  system  in  which  all  special  sciences  are  departments  of 
physics  or  of  psychology.  In  a  period  of  naturalistic  thinking 
like  that  of  the  Darwinistic  age  the  intellectual  conscience  may 
be  fascinated  and  hypnotized  by  the  triumphs  of  such  atomizing 
and  law-seeking  thought  even  to  the  point  of  forgetting  all  doubts 
and  contradictions.  But  the  pendulum  of  civilization  begins  to 
swing  in  the  other  direction.  The  mere  decomposition  of  the 
world  has  not  satisfied  the  deep  demand  for  an  inner  under- 
standing of  the  world ;  the  discovery  of  the  causal  laws  has  not 
stilled  the  thirst  for  emotional  values,  and  there  has  come  a  chill 
with  the  feeling  that  all  the  technical  improvement  which  sur- 
rounds us  is  a  luxury  which  does  not  make  life  either  better  or 
worthier  of  the  struggle.  The  idealistic  impulses  have  come  to 
a  new  life  everywhere  in  art  and  science  and  politics  and  so- 
ciety and  religion ;  the  historical  and  philosophical  thinking  has 
revived  and  rushes  to  the  foreground.  We  begin  to  remember 
again  what  naturalism  too  easily  forgets,  that  the  interests  of 


4  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

life  have  not  to  do  with  causes  and  effects,  but  with  purposes 
and  means,  that  in  life  we  feel  ourselves  as  units  and  as  free 
agents,  bound  by  culture  and  not  only  by  nature,  factors  in  a 
system  of  history  and  not  only  atoms  in  a  mechanism. 

Such  a  general  reaction  demands  its  expression  in  the  world 
of  science  too,  and  there  cannot  be  any  surprise  if  psychology 
has  to  stand  the  first  attack.  The  naturalistic  study  of  the  phys- 
ical facts  may  not  be  less  antagonistic  to  such  idealistic  de- 
mands, and  yet  it  is  the  decomposition  of  the  psychical  facts 
which  oppresses  us  most  immediately  in  our  instinctive  strife 
for  the  rights  of  the  personality.  The  antithesis  becomes  thus 
most  pointed  in  the  conflict  between  psychology  and  history, 
and  it  seems  to  me  that  only  two  possibilities  are  open.  One 
possibility  is  that  these  sciences  stay  yoked  together,  the  one 
forcing  the  other  to  follow  its  path.  Then,  of  course,  two 
cases  may  happen.  Either  psychology  remains  as  hitherto 
the  stronger  one ;  history  must  then  follow  the  paths  of  psycho- 
logical analysis  and  must  be  satisfied  with  sociological  laws ; 
every  effort  of  history  which  goes  beyond  that  is  then  unscientific, 
and  the  works  of  our  great  historians  must  seek  shelter  under 
the  roof  of  art.  Or — and  this  second  case  has  all  odds  in  favor 
of  it — the  belief  in  the  unity  of  personality  becomes  stronger 
than  the  confidence  in  science,  which  merely  decomposes,  and 
psychology  becomes  subordinated  to  the  historical  view  of  man. 
That  is  possible  under  a  hundred  forms,  but  the  final  result  must 
be  always  the  same,  the  ruin  of  real  psychology.  I  think  this 
undermining  of  psychology  with  the  tools  of  history  is  to-day 
in  eager  progress.  Here  belong,  of  course,  all  the  most  modern 
attempts  to  supplement  the  regular  analyzing  psychology  by  a 
pseudo-psychology  which  by  principle  considers  the  mental  life 
as  a  unity  and  asks  not  about  its  constitution  but  about  its  mean- 
ing. Whether  authors,  half  unconsciously,  alternate  with  these 
two  views  from  chapter  to  chapter,  or  whether  they  demand 
systematically  that  both  kinds  of  psychology  be  acknowledged, 
makes  no  essential  difference.  Both  forms  are  characteristic 
for  a  period  of  transition  ;  both  must  lead  in  the  end  to  giving 
up  fully  the  analyzing  view,  to  shifting  the  results  of  such 
analysis  over  to  physiology,  and  thus  to  confining  psychology 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  5 

entirely  to  the  anti-causal  categories,  that  is  to  denying  psy- 
chology altogether.  Such  turnings  of  the  scientific  spirit  are 
slow,  but  if  history  and  psychology  remain  chained  up  together 
the  symptoms  of  the  future  are  too  clear :  there  is  no  hope  for 
psychology. 

But  there  is  a  second  alternative  open.  The  chain  which 
forces  psychology  and  history  to  move  together  may  be  broken, 
the  one  may  be  acknowledged  as  fully  independent  of  the  other. 
What  appears  as  a  conflict  of  contradictory  statements  may 
then  become  the  mutual  supplementation  of  two  partial  truths, 
just  as  a  body  may  appear  very  different  from  the  geometrical, 
from  the  physical  and  from  the  chemical  points  of  view  while 
each  one  gives  us  truth.  To  those  who  have  followed  the  re- 
cent development  of  epistemological  discussion,  especially  in 
Germany,  it  is  a  well-known  fact  that  this  logical  separation  of 
history  and  psychology  is,  indeed,  the  demand  of  some  of  the 
best  students  of  logic.  They  claim  that  the  scientific  interest  in 
the  facts  can  and  must  take  two  absolutely  different  directions : 
we  are  interested  either  in  the  single  fact  as  such  or  in  the  laws 
under  which  it  stands,  and  thus  we  have  two  groups  of  sciences 
which  have  nothing  to  do  with  each  other,  sciences  which  de- 
scribe the  isolated  facts  and  sciences  which  seek  their  laws.  A 
leading  logician  baptizes  the  first,  therefore,  idiographic  sci- 
ences, the  latter  nomothetic  sciences ;  idiographic  is  history ; 
nomothetic  are  physics  and  psychology.  Psychology  gives 
general  facts  which  are  always  true,  but  concerning  which  it  has 
not  to  ask  whether  they  are  realized  anywhere  or  at  any  time ; 
history  refers  to  the  special  single  fact  only,  without  any  relation 
to  general  facts. 

I  consider  this  logical  separation  as  a  liberating  deed,  not 
only  because  it  is  the  only  way  for  psychology  to  escape  its 
ruin  through  the  interference  of  an  historically  thinking  ideal- 
ism, and  also  not  only  because  the  value  and  unity  and  freedom 
of  the  personality  which  history  preaches  can  now  be  followed 
up  without  interference  on  the  part  of  psychology,  but  because, 
independent  of  any  practical  results,  it  seems  to  me  the  neces- 
sary outcome  of  epistemological  reflection.  And  yet  the  argu- 
ments which  have  led  to  this  separation  appear  to  me  mistaken 


6  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

and  untenable  in  every  respect.  I  agree  heartily  with  the  de- 
cision, but  I  absolutely  reject  the  motives.  No  antithesis  is 
possible  between  sciences  which  study  the  isolated  facts  and  sci- 
ences which  generalize ;  such  a  methodological  difference  does 
not  exist.  We  shall  see  that  it  must  be  replaced  by  a  difference 
of  another  kind,  but  the  end  must  be  the  same  :  psychology 
and  history  must  never  come  together  again.  To  criticise  the 
one  way  of  attaining  this  end  and  to  illuminate  the  other  new 
way  which  I  propose  is  the  purpose  of  the  following  considera- 
tions. 

We  must  proceed  at  first  critically ;  what  is  the  truth  of  the 
view  which  contrasts  idiographic  and  nomothetic  sciences?  At 
the  first  glance  the  importance  of  the  discrimination  seems  so 
evident  that  it  appears  hard  to  understand  how  it  could  ever  have 
been  overlooked.  It  seems  a  matter  of  course  that  the  empirical 
sciences  can  ask  either  about  the  general  facts  of  reality,  the 
laws  which  are  true  always  and  everywhere  and  which  do  not 
say  what  happened  on  a  special  place  and  in  a  special  time,  and 
on  the  other  hand  about  the  single  facts  which  are  character- 
ized just  by  their  uniqueness.  We  may  be  interested  in  the 
physical  and  chemical  laws  of  fire,  but  our  interest  in  the  one 
great  fire  which  destroyed  Moscow  has  an  absolutely  different 
logical  source,  and  if  we  extend  our  historical  interest  from  the 
physical  to  the  psychical  side,  and  investigate  the  stream  of 
associations  which  passed  during  the  days  of  that  fire  through 
the  mind  of  Napoleon,  we  have  again  an  absolutely  different 
kind  of  interest  from  that  of  the  psychologist  who  studies  the 
laws  of  association  and  inhibition,  which  are  true  for  every  mor- 
tal. How  small  from  a  logical  standpoint  appears  the  difference 
between  the  search  for  physical  laws  and  the  search  for  psycho- 
logical laws  compared  with  the  unbridgable  chasm  between  the 
search  for  laws  and  the  inquiry  for  special  facts  which  happened 
once !  And  this  difference  grows  if  we  consider  that  all  our 
feelings  and  emotions  refer  to  the  special  single  object,  not  to 
any  laws,  that,  above  all,  the  personalities  with  which  we  come 
in  contact  come  in  question  for  us  just  in  their  singleness,  and 
that  we  ourselves  feel  the  value  of  our  life  and  the  meaning  of 
our  responsibility  in  the  uniqueness  of  the  acts  by  which  we 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  7 

mark  our  individual  role  in  the  history  of  mankind.  These  ar- 
guments of  recent  epistemological  discussions  will  easily  find 
the  ear  of  the  multitude.  Common  sense,  which  demands  for 
itself  the  prerogative  of  being  inconsistent,  will  probably  hesi- 
tate only  at  the  unavoidable  postulate  of  this  standpoint,  that  also 
the  development  of  our  solar  system,  of  our  earth,  of  our  flora 
and  fauna,  belongs  then  to  history  and  not  to  natural  science,  as 
they  describe  a  process  which  happened  once,  and  not  a  law. 

I  may  begin  my  criticism  at  the  periphery  of  the  subject, 
moving  slowly  to  the  center.  I  claim  first  that  all  natural 
sciences,  of  which  psychology  is  one,  do  not  seek  laws  only  but 
set  forth  also  judgments  about  the  existence  of  objects.  Of 
course,  we  can  make  the  arbitrary  decision  that  we  acknowledge 
the  natural  sciences  as  such  only  so  far  as  they  give  eternal  laws 
without  reference  to  their  realization  in  a  special  place  or  in  a 
special  time,  while  any  judgment  about  the  existence  here  or 
there,  now  or  then,  has  to  be  housed  under  the  roof  of  history. 
The  sciences  as  they  practically  are  would  then  be  mixtures  of 
historical  and  naturalistic  statements,  the  historical  factor  dimin- 
ishing the  more,  the  more  abstract  the  science,  reaching  its  min- 
imum in  pure  mechanics.  Such  decision  has  only  recently 
found  able  defense,  but  do  we  not  destroy,  by  its  acceptance,  the 
whole  meaning  of  natural  science?  Are  the  laws  for  themselves 
alone  still  of  any  scientific  interest  at  all?  Why  do  we  care  at 
all  for  such  general  laws,  as  the  law  of  causality,  the  most  gen- 
eral of  them,  which  embraces  all  the  others,  is  included  already 
in  the  presuppositions  of  science,  and  thus  anticipated  before- 
hand? When  formal  logic  or  mathematics  deals  with  A  and  B 
and  C,  they  state  valid  relations  without  asking  whether  A, 
B  or  C  is  given  anywhere  or  at  any  time,  even  without  ex- 
cluding the  possibility  that  their  real  existence  may  be  impos- 
sible. The  scientific  judgments  of  physics  and  psychology,  on 
the  other  hand,  have  lost  all  their  meaning  if  we  deprive  them 
of  the  presupposition  that  objects  which  prove  the  validity  of 
such  laws  have  real  existence  in  the  world  of  experience. 

We  can  construct  well-founded  physiological  laws  also  for 
the  organism  of  the  centaur  and  psychological  laws  for  the 
mind  of  nixes  and  water  fairies,  but  both  attempts  do  not  be- 


8  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

long  within  the  system  of  science.  The  claim  of  existential- 
ity  is  not  explicitly  expressed  in  the  formulation  of  scientific 
knowledge,  not  because  it  is  unessential,  but  because  it  is  a 
matter  of  course.  The  larger  the  circle  for  which  the  law  is 
valid  the  more  we  find  these  included  judgments  of  reality  de- 
prived of  their  reference  to  special  local  and  temporal  data,  but 
even  in  the  most  general  propositions  of  mechanics,  such  judg- 
ments are  tacitly  included.  The  question  is  not  whether  the  ob- 
jects with  which  the  laws  of  mechanics  deal  have  real  existence 
from  a  philosophical  point  of  view ;  certainly  they  have  not. 
The  important  point  is  that  mechanics  by  its  laws  tries  at  the 
same  time  to  make  us  believe  that  even  the  atoms  have  existence. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  existential  judgment  must  become  the 
more  detailed  the  more  special  the  law  is,  that  is,  the  more  com- 
plicated the  conditions  of  its  realization.  If  the  psychologist 
states  the  laws  of  the  feelings,  he  claims  that  it  is  not  true  that 
only  men  without  feelings  exist ;  he  claims  that  men  with  feel- 
ings have  reality  too.  If  he  gives  us  the  more  special  laws  of 
ethical  feelings,  he  claims  that  experience  knows  men  with 
ethical  emotion.  If  he  goes  on  with  his  specialization  of  the 
psychical  laws,  claiming  that  under  special  conditions  the  eth- 
ical emotion  of  obedience  to  the  state  comes  to  inhibit  the  desire 
for  life,  he  tells  us  that  this  really  happened.  His  psycholog- 
ical law  becomes  finally  only  still  more  detailed  if  he  lays  it 
down  that  under  such  and  such  conditions  obedience  to  the  state 
discharges  itself  in  the  drinking  of  a  hemlock  potion  in  spite  of 
antagonistic  suggestions  of  escape  from  philosophical  friends. 
It  is  a  psychological  law  and  yet  it  claims  at  the  same  time  that 
all  this  once  at  least  really  happened,  while  the  complication  of 
conditions  practically  excludes  the  possibility  of  its  happening 
more  than  once  in  the  world  of  our  experience. 

Of  course,  it  remains  a  law  of  general  character  with  regard 
to  the  absolute  space  and  the  absolute  time ;  when  all  conditions 
including  our  solar  system  and  all  the  events  on  the  earth  are 
given  once  more  in  infinity,  then  Socrates  necessarily  must  drink 
once  more  the  poisoned  cup.  But  in  the  limited  space  and 
time  of  our  experience  the  conditions  for  the  realization  of  such 
a  psychological  law  can  have  been  given  only  once,  and  that 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  9 

they  really  once  were  given  is  decidedly  claimed  and  thus 
silently  reported  by  the  law.  If  our  opponents  maintain  that 
the  naturalistic  sciences  need  as  supplement  a  historical  descrip- 
tion of  one  special  stage  of  the  world  to  give  a  foothold  for  the 
working  of  the  eternal  laws,  we  can  thus  reject  this  external 
help  for  the  explanation  of  the  world,  as  the  laws  themselves 
furnish  all  that  we  need.  The  system  of  the  laws  is  at  the  same 
time  a  full  and  graduated  system  of  existential  propositions  with 
regard  to  the  limited  space  and  time  of  our  experience.  If  ever 
and  anywhere  in  the  empirical  universe  a  molecule  had  moved 
otherwise  or  another  thought  had  passed  through  a  conscious- 
ness, then  the  system  of  laws,  thought  in  ideal  perfection,  would 
have  demanded  a  change.  Our  physics  and  psychology  pre- 
suppose and  assert  the  real  existence  of  exactly  our  world. 
They  do  not  seek  the  laws  with  the  intention  of  neglecting  and 
ignoring  the  special  facts. 

The  separation  of  the  single  facts  from  the  general  facts  is  thus 
untenable,  because  the  explanatory  law  includes  the  description  ; 
but  we  can  also  emphasize  the  other  side  of  this  mutual  relation  : 
every  description  includes  explanation,  every  assertion  of  a 
special  fact  demands  reference  to  the  general  facts.  A  descrip- 
tion has  a  logical  value  only  if  it  points  towards  a  law.  We 
describe  a  process  by  the  help  of  conceptions  which  are  worked 
up  from  the  general  facts,  common  to  a  group  of  objects,  and 
these  general  conceptions  are  the  more  valuable  for  the  purposes 
of  description  the  more  their  content  is  a  condensed  representa- 
tion of  real  objective  connections.  The  descriptions  in  popular 
language  make  use  of  conceptions  which  are  deduced  from  super- 
ficial similarity,  but  every  new  insight  into  the  physical  and 
psychological  laws  gives  to  the  general  conceptions  a  more  and 
more  valuable  shape.  The  history  of  science  is  the  steady  de- 
velopment of  the  means  of  description ;  there  is  no  description 
which  by  its  use  of  conceptions  does  not  aim  at  working  out  the 
laws.  Thus,  far  from  the  trivial  belief  that  the  law  is  merely 
a  description  of  facts,  we  ought  not  to  forget  that  the  description 
of  facts  involves  the  laws  and  is  only  another  form  of  their  ex- 
pression. To  describe  a  physical  thing  as  a  group  of  atoms  or 
an  idea  as  a  group  of  sensations  demands  the  whole  knowledge 


10  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

of  the  psychological  and  mechanical  laws  and  condenses  in  its 
conceptions  the  progress  of  science.  To  separate  the  descrip- 
tive report  from  the  explaining  apperception  is  thus  again  im- 
possible. 

It  could  appear  that  this  does  not  hold  for  all  kinds  of 
description ;  we  communicate  with  one  another  in  practical  life 
without  relying  on  general  conceptions.  But  our  communica- 
tion then  is  no  description.  Any  mode  of  personal  expression, 
gestures  or  tears,  may  tell  us  what  is  going  on  in  the  mind  of 
another  without  reference  to  psychological  laws.  But  the  fact 
is  that  they  give  no  description  either;  they  give  a  sugges- 
tion. The  words  of  practical  life,  the  words  of  the  poet  and, 
as  we  may  add  at  once,  the  words  of  the  historian,  work  like 
such  movements  of  expression ;  they  make  every  mental  vibra- 
tion resound  in  us,  because  they  force  us  unintentionally  or  with 
conscious  art  to  follow  the  suggestion  and  to  imitate  the  mental 
experience.  The  rhythm  and  the  shade  of  the  words  may  then 
be  substituted  for  logical  exactitude,  and  interjections  may  have 
deeper  influence  than  complete  judgments,  but  all  that  is  de- 
cidedly no  description,  as  a  description  demands  a  communi- 
cation of  the  elements.  Such  a  suggestion  allows  us  an  un- 
derstanding of  the  meaning,  but  gives  us  no  knowledge  of 
the  constitution.  Where  a  single  object  really  has  to  be 
described,  there  conceptions  and  laws  are  inevitable,  and  the 
historian  cannot  make  an  exception. 

But  just  this  fact,  that  description  and  explanation  cannot  be 
separated  and  that  the  conception  includes  the  law,  has  opened 
in  recent  philosophical  discussions  a  new  way  of  thought  which 
also  seems  to  lead  to  those  claims  which  we  rejected.  Granted, 
it  is  said,  that  every  description  presupposes  generalizing  ab- 
stractions, but  such  abstraction  must  then  lead  us  away  from  the 
endless  manifoldness  of  the  reality.  Every  scientific  description 
deals  with  physical  or  psychological  abstractions  ;  does  that  not 
mean  that  we  need  still  another  kind  of  treatment  which  does 
justice  to  the  existing  richness  and  fullness  of  the  real  single 
fact?  If  we  give  this  mission  to  history  we  acknowledge  that 
its  communications  would  not  be  ordinary  descriptions,  but  we 
should  in  any  case  again  have  the  separated  camps  with  the 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  II 

antithesis  :  Manifoldness  and  abstraction,  single  fact  and  general 
fact.  But  the  presupposition  is  wrong  ;  the  manifoldness  of  the 
reality  is  not  endless  and  the  abstracting  conceptions  are  not  at 
all  unfit  to  do  justice  to  the  richness  of  the  single  fact.  The 
single  conception  abstracts,  but  the  connection  of  conceptions 
in  the  sentence  reconstructs  again.  On  the  other  hand,  what- 
ever is  the  possible  object  of  perception  and  discrimination 
must  be  the  possible  object  of  descriptive  determination. 
Whether  the  task  of  a  complete  conceptional  description  is 
difficult  or  not  is  no  question  of  principle ;  impossible  it  is  not. 
The  ability  to  perceive  differences  is  even  inferior  compared 
with  the  power  to  separate  the  differences  conceptionally,  and 
the  abstracting  description  of  science  must,  therefore,  frequently 
increase  and  not  decrease  the  manifoldness  of  the  object.  We 
know  about  the  objects  more  than  we  perceive ;  above  all,  the 
description  can  never  leave  behind  it  a  perceivable  remainder 
which  from  its  too  great  manifoldness  excludes  description.  The 
full  variety  of  the  single  facts  thus  belongs  just  as  much  as  the 
most  general  law  to  the  physical  and  psychological  sciences ; 
the  antithesis  psychology  and  history  as  coinciding  with  the 
antithesis  abstraction  and  manifoldness  of  reality  is  then  impos- 
sible. That  history  stands,  indeed,  nearer  to  reality  than  any 
psychology  we  shall  later  fully  acknowledge,  but,  as  we  shall 
see,  for  very  different  reasons ;  history  abstracts,  we  shall  see, 
not  less  than  psychology,  and  psychology  is  interested  in  the 
variety  of  the  facts  just  as  much  as  is  history. 

This  brings  us  to  our  central  arguments  :  Every  science  con- 
siders the  single  facts  in  their  relations  to  other  facts,  works 
towards  connection,  towards  generalities.  Science  means  con- 
nection and  nothing  else,  and  history  also  aims  at  general  facts, 
or  it  cannot  hope  for  a  place  in  the  system  of  science.  Does 
that  mean  that  it  is  valueless  to  consider  the  single  fact  as  it 
stands  for  itself,  isolated  and  separated  from  everything  else? 
Certainly  not ;  the  isolation  is  not  less  valuable  than  the  con- 
nection, but  it  never  forms  a  science ;  it  is  the  task  of  art.  The 
single  fact  belongs  to  art  and  not  to  history ;  history  has  to  do 
with  the  general  facts.  That  is  the  thesis  which  I  must  inter- 
pret and  defend.  One  point,  of  course,  is  clear  before  the  dis- 


12  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

cussion.  If  we  maintain  that  history  has  also  to  work  up  its 
material  with  respect  to  the  general  facts  and  not  with  regard  to 
the  single  facts,  then  it  is  evident  that  there  is  in  the  deepest 
principle  of  the  inquiry  no  methodological  difference  between 
physics  and  psychology  on  the  one  side  and  history  on  the 
other.  But  we  insisted  that  an  important  difference  does  exist. 
The  difference  must  then  be  not  in  the  kind  of  treatment,  but  in 
the  material  itself.  To  be  sure,  there  cannot  be  a  physical  or 
psychical  object  in  the  universe  which  would  not  be  possible 
material  for  psychology  or  physics ;  if  history  deals  with  a  ma- 
terial which  is  different  from  the  possible  objects  of  those  em- 
pirical sciences,  then  it  must  deal  with  facts  which  differ  from 
the  physical  and  psychical  objects  in  their  kind  of  existence ; 
in  short,  the  difference  between  psychology  and  history  is  not  a 
methodological  but  an  ontological  one. 

We  must  then  ask  what  kind  of  existence  belongs  to  the 
material  with  which  physics  and  psychology  deal  and  how  it  is 
related  to  reality ;  above  all,  how  far  reality  offers  still  an- 
other kind  of  facts  which  could  be  the  substance  of  other  sci- 
ences. Reality  means  to  us  here  the  immediate  experience 
which  we  live  through.  This  immediate  truth  of  life  may  be 
transformed  and  remoulded  in  theories  and  sciences,  and  these 
remodelings  of  reality  may  be  highly  valuable  for  special  pur- 
poses of  life ;  we  may  even  reach  finally  a  point  of  reconstruc- 
tion from  which  the  subjective  experience  appears  as  an  illusion 
and  the  supplementation  stands  as  the  only  truth.  Yet  the 
importance  of  such  constructions  must  not  make  us  forget 
that  we  have  then  left  reality  behind  us.  Our  doubting  and 
remoulding  itself  belongs  to  the  reality  for  which  its  prod- 
ucts can  never  be  substituted.  And  this  primary  reality  can,  of 
course,  never  be  reached  when  we  start  from  the  finished  theories 
of  the  physical  or  psychological  sciences.  Whether  we  pre- 
tend that  the  world  is  a  content  of  our  consciousness,  a  system 
of  psychological  ideas,  or  whether  we  start  from  the  mechanical 
universe  and  consider  experience  as  effect  of  the  outer  world 
on  the  consciousness,  or  whether  we  confuse  the  two  and  call 
the  world  a  product  of  the  brain,  it  is  all  equally  misleading  if 
we  seek  the  reality,  as  each  view  presupposes  equally  the  psy- 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  13 

chological  or  physical  constructions.  It  is  then,  of  course,  for 
us  also  impossible  to  reach  the  less  remoulded  primary  experi- 
ence by  going  backward  through  the  genetic  development  of 
the  individual  or  of  the  race  to  an  earlier  simpler  stage  of  ex- 
perience. Just  this  genetic  tracing  backward  fully  presup- 
poses the  categories  of  the  psychological  view ;  we  must  have 
already  considered  our  own  inner  life  as  a  complex  combina- 
tion of  elements  before  it  has  a  meaning  to  call  the  mental  life 
of  the  child  or  of  the  animal  less  complex ;  the  starting  point  of 
the  genetic  development  is  thus  itself  an  artificial  construction 
which  lies  further  away  from  the  primary  experience. 

If  we  thus  escape  all  theories  and  stand  firm  against  the  sug- 
gestions which  psychology  and  physics  plentifully  bring  to  us, 
then  we  find  in  the  reality  nothing  of  ideas  or  of  mechanical 
substances,  neither  consciousness  nor  a  connected  universe. 
The  reality  we  experience  does  not  know  the  antithesis  of  psy- 
chical and  physical  objects,  but  in  the  primary  stage  merely  the 
antithesis  subject  and  object.  We  feel  our  personal  reality  in 
our  subjective  attitudes,  in  our  will  acts  which  we  do  not  perceive 
but  which  we  live  through,  and  with  the  same  immediacy  we  ac- 
knowledge other  personalities  as  subjects  of  will.  They  too  are 
not  objects  which  we  merely  perceive,  but  we  acknowledge  them, 
by  our  feeling,  as  subjects  with  whom  we  agree  or  disagree  and 
whose  reality  is  thus  not  less  certain  than  our  own.  Our  acts  as 
subjects  are  directed  towards  objects  which  in  reality  exist  only 
as  such  objects  of  will,  that  is,  as  values.  They  are  our  ends 
and  means,  our  tools  and  purposes,  and  nothing  is  to  us  real  that 
is  not  called  to  be  selected  or  rejected,  to  be  favored  or  dis- 
missed. Subjective  acts  of  will  and  objects  of  will  form  the 
reality,  the  whole  reality,  nothing  lies  outside  and  nothing  is  valid 
beyond  this  world  of  will  relations,  and  even  if  we  form  judg- 
ments about  objects  which  we  think  as  independent  of  the  will, 
this  judgment  and  this  thought  itself  is  an  act  of  will  working 
towards  a  purpose. 

As  soon  as  we  begin  to  bring  order  into  the  manifoldness  of 
this  real  world  the  subjective  acts  as  well  as  the  objects  divide 
themselves  into  two  groups,  those  of  individual  character  and 
those  which  are  common  to  all,  over-individual.  This  division 


H  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

means  not  a  result  of  counting  whether  several  subjects  or  by 
chance  only  one  subject  have  made  the  decision  or  appreciated 
the  object :  it  is  a  question  of  intention  merely.  My  act  is  over- 
individual  if  it  is  willed  with  the  meaning  that  it  belongs  to 
every  subject  which  I  acknowledge,  and  my  object  is  overin- 
dividual  in  so  far  as  I  consider  it  as  a  possible  object  of  attitude 
for  every  subject.  My  overindividual  will-act  is  that  factor  of 
reality  which  we  call  duty ;  every  duty  lies  in  us  as  subjects,  as 
our  own  deepest  will,  and  yet  as  more  than  our  individual  de- 
cision. The  overindividual  objects  are  those  which  we  call 
physical ;  the  individual  objects  are  the  psychical  ones ;  we 
must  only  not  forget  that  these  physical  and  psychical  objects 
are  in  reality  not  in  question  as  independent  objects  of  percep- 
tion, but  are  always  related  to  the  will ;  they  are  not  contents  of 
consciousness  and  mechanical  bodies  in  a  continuous  space,  but 
suggestions  which  have  a  meaning,  things  which  have  a  use. 
We  find  thus  four  factors  of  reality,  beyond  whose  validity  a 
constructive  metaphysics  alone  can  go.  Metaphysics  may  ask 
whether  the  individual  and  overindividual  acts  do  not  blend  in 
an  absolute  subject  and  whether  the  objects  are  not  posited  by 
such  a  subject  of  higher  order ;  epistemology  must  be  satisfied 
with  the  more  modest  task  of  settling  how  we  deal  with  this 
reality  in  our  scientific  or  aesthetic  knowledge.  Reality  itself 
is,  of  course,  neither  art  nor  science,  but  life.  Art  and  science 
must  be  thus  transformations  of  the  material  which  life  offers  to 
us,  while  these  transformations  themselves  are  acts  of  the  sub- 
jects and  thus  belonging  to  those  will-formations  which  claim 
for  themselves  an  overindividual  character,  creating  the  values 
of  beauty  and  truth. 

The  acts  which  lead  from  life  to  art  and  science  are  thus  for 
epistemology  free  acts  of  that  subjectivity  which  we  find  in  our- 
selves by  immediate  feeling,  and  which  we  acknowledge  in 
others  by  an  understanding  of  their  propositions  and  sugges- 
tions ;  they  are  not  functions  of  the  psychophysical  organism,  not 
psychophysical  processes,  as  we  must  have  reached  already  the 
artificial  reconstruction  of  science  before  the  subject  is  replaced 
by  that  object  among  other  objects,  the  psychophysical  person- 
ality. Scientific  and  aesthetic  acts  are  not  the  only  functions  of 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  15 

the  real  subject;  the  ethical  and  others  stand  coordinated,  but 
we  are  concerned  here  only  with  the  two  functions  which  do  not 
aim  to  change  and  to  improve  the  world  but  to  rethink  it  in 
beautiful  or  truthful  creations.  It  seems  to  me  now  that  the 
two  attitudes  are  in  every  respect  antagonistic ;  to  express  their 
direction  in  a  short  formula,  I  should  say  science  connects  the 
factors  of  reality ;  art,  on  the  other  hand,  isolates  them.  The 
material  of  science  and  of  art  is  then  the  same,  though  treated 
by  a  different  method.  Both  can  deal  with  all  the  four  factors 
of  reality,  with  individual  acts  and  overindividual  acts,  with  in- 
dividual objects  and  overindividual  objects.  Life  does  not  iso- 
late fully  and  gives  no  complete  connection ;  whatever  we  turn 
to  with  our  will  has  features  which  lead  us  further  and  further 
to  ever  new  interests  ;  life  does  not  let  us  sink  into  the  one  alone 
— we  rush  beyond  it  to  new  realities.  And  life  does  not  give 
connections  beyond  the  immediate  needs  of  practical  purposes 
in  the  narrow  circle  of  chance  experience.  Wherever  is  full 
isolation  of  single  facts  there  is  beauty,  wherever  truth  there 
must  be  full  connection. 

The  assertion  that  every  isolated  fact  in  its  singleness  means 
beauty  has  for  us  here  only  the  character  of  a  critical  argument 
and  is  not  for  itself  object  of  our  discussion.  It  has  for  us  merely 
the  negative  purpose  of  proving  that  the  singleness  cannot  be 
characteristic  of  history.  We  cannot  thus  defend  here  this  asser- 
tion by  detailed  discussion  ;  we  have  only  to  elucidate  its  meaning. 
Certainly  the  real  life,  too,  brings  us  pulses  of  experience  in 
which  our  will  is  captivated  by  the  given  experience,  satisfied 
with  the  object  in  itself  or  in  the  acknowledgment  of  other  sub- 
jective acts ;  then  we  have  the  beauty  of  nature,  the  beauty  of 
forms  and  of  landscapes,  of  love  and  of  friendship.  Of  course, 
it  is  only  an  exception  when  life  offers  to  us  in  the  untrans- 
formed  reality  such  complete  beauty ;  it  remains  the  duty  of  art  to 
change  the  world  till  everything  is  eliminated  that  leads  the  sub- 
ject beyond  the  single  experience,  and  the  will  can  rest  in  the 
single  fact.  The  world  of  objects  is  thus  transformed  in  paint- 
ing and  sculpture,  the  world  of  subjective  acts  remoulded  in 
poetry.  The  sentiment  or  the  conflict  which  the  poet  suggests 
to  us,  the  bust  or  the  landscape  which  the  artist  brings  before 


1 6  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

our  eye,  is  severed  from  the  practical  world  ;  as  long  as  anything 
connects  it  with  the  background  of  the  daily  world  it  may  be 
useful  or  inspiring  or  instructive,  but  it  is  not  beautiful.  The 
poet  projects  his  work  into  an  ideal  past ;  the  painter  cuts  an 
ideal  space  out  of  the  reality,  and  the  sculptor  fills  an  ideal  space, 
not  the  space  of  our  surrounding,  to  take  care  thus  that  the  acts 
and  objects  may  not  link  into  our  real  world,  may  never  become 
causes  for  outer  effects,  motives  for  actions,  or  centers  for  as- 
sociations which  lie  beyond  the  frame. 

We  ought  not  to  become  skeptical  in  regard  to  this  point  on 
account  of  the  overhasty  generalizations  in  which  empirical 
psychology  mostly  characterizes  the  aesthetic  act  as  rich  in  as- 
sociations. The  epistemological  problem  we  are  discussing  can 
not  be  settled  by  psychology,  but  as  soon  as  the  facts  are  ex- 
pressed in  the  terms  of  psychological  language  they  can  not 
possibly  assert  the  opposite  of  the  epistemological  truth.  But 
there  is  no  reason  for  such  a  conflict,  as  psychology  is  undoubt- 
edly in  the  wrong.  The  psychological  claim  is  based  on  the 
general  theory  that  all  pleasant  mental  states  represent  an  in- 
crease of  activity,  and  with  it  an  increase  of  associations,  while 
all  unpleasant  states  are  marked  by  a  decrease  of  activity  and 
lack  of  associations.  I  think  that  is  wrong  ;  there  are  different 
kinds  of  increase  and  different  kinds  of  decrease  in  both  ideas 
and  actions.  The  antithesis  pleasure  and  displeasure  does  not 
at  all  coincide  with  increase  and  decrease  if  we  do  not  arbi- 
trarily select  such  emotions  as  joy  on  the  one  and  grief  on  the 
other  side.  Increase  of  activity  characterizes  pleasant  and  un- 
pleasant states,  only  in  the  pleasant  states  it  produces  action  of 
the  extensors,  in  the  unpleasant  states  action  of  the  flexors.  In 
the  same  way  decreases  of  activity  can  have  a  double  type ;  it 
can  have  its  ground  in  the  absence  of  stimulations,  and  this  is, 
indeed,  characteristic  of  some  unpleasant  states,  but  the  lack  of 
outer  action  can  have  its  ground  also  in  the  fact  that  every  mo- 
tor impulse  goes  to  the  antagonistic  muscles  equally.  This  in- 
crease of  tonicity  without  possible  action  is  characteristic  for 
one  pleasant  state  above  all,  the  aesthetic  one.  The  increase 
and  decrease  of  associations  is  here,  as  always,  parallel  with  the 
motor  impulses.  Here  also  increase  of  associations  is  essential 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  17 

for  some  pleasant  states,  but  for  some  unpleasant  ones  too,  only 
like  the  muscle  activity,  in  antagonistic  directions,  in  the  one 
case  turning  to  the  future,  in  the  other  case  falling  back  to  the 
past.  And  the  same  doubleness  is  to  be  noted  in  the  decrease  of 
associations  ;  in  some  unpleasant  states  the  decrease  comes  from 
a  mere  lack  of  ideational  impulses,  in  some  pleasant  states 
from  the  fascination  which  leads  every  ideational  impulse  again 
to  the  object  itself,  so  that  no  thought  can  lead  beyond  it.  This 
is  again  true,  above  all,  for  the  aesthetic  state.  The  beautiful 
object  includes  all  that  it  suggests  in  itself,  and  where  we  con- 
nect we  sin  against  the  spirit  of  beauty. 

By  the  contrast  with  art  the  fullest  light  falls  on  the  process 
of  science ;  every  step  towards  science  leads  in  the  opposite  di- 
rection. The  incomplete  connections  of  life  are  severed  by  art, 
but  made  complete  by  science,  while  the  material  is  the  same. 
We  had  four  groups  of  facts  in  reality,  and  we  must  thus  have 
four  groups  of  sciences  which  bring  systematic  connections  into 
the  four  different  fields.  We  have  the  science  of  the  over-in- 
dividual objects,  that  is,  physics  ;  secondly,  the  science  of  the  in- 
dividual objects,  that  is,  psychology  ;  thirdly,  the  sciences  of  the 
over-individual  will-acts,  that  is,  the  normative  sciences;  and, 
last,  not  least,  the  sciences  of  the  individual  will-acts,  that  is,  the 
historical  sciences.  Physics  and  psychology  have  thus  to  do  with 
objects  ;  history  and  the  normative  systems,  ethics,  logic,  aesthet- 
ics, deal  with  will-acts.  Psychology  and  history  have  thus  ab- 
solutely different  material ;  the  one  can  never  deal  with  the 
substance  of  the  other,  and  thus  they  are  separated  by  a  chasm, 
but  their  method  is  the  same.  Both  connect  their  material ;  both 
consider  the  single  experience  under  the  point  of  view  of  the  to- 
tality, working  from  the  special  facts  towards  the  general  facts, 
from  the  experience  towards  the  system.  And  yet  the  differ- 
ence of  material  must,  in  spite  of  the  equality  of  the  methodo- 
logical process,  produce  absolutely  different  kinds  of  systems 
pof  science.  We  must  consider  again  from  the  standpoint  of  real 
life  how  the  connections  of  objects  is  different  from  the  connec- 
tion of  attitudes,  and  how  the  purposes  of  the  systematizing  re- 
construction are  different  in  the  two  cases. 

We  and  the  other  subjects  have  objects  which  are  in  reality, 


1 8  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

as  we  have  seen,  objects  of  our  will.  Why  have  we  an  interest 
in  considering  the  objects  from  a  scientific  standpoint,  that  is  in 
systematized  connection?  If  we  do  so,  it  must  serve,  of  course, 
a  special  purpose  in  our  real  life.  The  purpose  is  clear.  We 
cannot  do  the  duties  of  our  life,  that  is,  we  cannot  act  on  the  ob- 
jects, if  we  do  not  know  what  to  expect  from  them  with  regard 
to  the  reality  which  we  prepare,  and  we  call  the  reality  which 
we  can  still  prepare  the  future.  We  must  ask,  therefore,  what 
we  have  to  expect  for  the  future  from  the  objects  alone,  that  is 
from  the  objects  thought  as  if  they  were  independent  from  the 
subjective  will  reaction.  The  answer  to  this  question  as  to  our 
justified  expectations  is  the  system  of  physical  and  psychological 
sciences.  To  reach  this  end  we  must  think  the  objects,  the 
individual  or  over-individual  ones,  as  if  they  were  no  longer 
objects  of  a  will,  as  if  the  subject  were  deprived  of  its  real  ac- 
tivity and  were  a  merely  passive  perceiving  subject  the  objects 
of  which  are  thus  definitely  cut  away  from  the  will.  Our  inter- 
est was  to  determine  their  influence  on  the  future.  We  thus  con- 
sider every  object  as  the  cause  of  an  expected  effect,  and  call 
those  characteristics  of  the  object  which  determine  our  expecta- 
tion of  the  effect  its  elements.  Physics  and  psychology  thus  look 
on  their  objects  as  complexes  of  elements.  It  is  the  task  of  sci- 
ence to  reconstruct  and  to  transform  the  objects  till  each  is  thought 
as  such  a  combination  of  elements  that  the  effects  to  be  expected 
can  be  fully  determined  from  the  elements.  In  this  service 
grew  up  the  atom  doctrine  in  physics  and  the  sensation  doctrine 
in  psychology.  Each  object  is  thus  linked  into  a  causal  system  ; 
each  is  considered  not  as  that  which  it  really  is,  but  as  a  complex 
of  constructed  factors  which  are  substituted  for  the  purpose  of 
the  causal  connection,  and  each  is  in  question  in  its  relation  to 
all  the  others.  The  world  thus  becomes  a  system  of  causally 
linked  objects  which  can  be  described  by  their  elements,  while 
these  elements  themselves  are  chosen  from  the  point  of  view  of 
explanation  by  causality.  The  determination  of  the  effects  by 
means  of  the  elementary  causes  is  expressed  by  the  laws  which 
give  the  rules  for  our  expectations.  We  can  say  thus  that 
physics  and  psychology  may  very  well  consider  any  special 
facts,  and,  as  we  have  seen,  they  certainly  do  not  ignore  the  spe- 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  19 

cial  facts  at  all,  but  they  consider  them  with  regard  to  the  causal 
law,  and  the  laws  as  types  of  causal  connections  are  thus  the 
only  general  facts  towards  which  the  systematized  study  of  ob- 
jects can  lead  us. 

Quite  different  is  the  systematic  connection  of  the  subjective 
will-attitudes ;  we  may  abstract  here  at  first  from  the  over-indi- 
vidual attitudes  and  concentrate  our  interest  on  the  individual 
will-acts.  In  psychology  the  will-attitude  as  such,  as  act  of  the 
real  subject,  cannot  have  any  place  whatever ;  psychology  deals 
with  objects  ;  the  subjective  attitude  is  never  an  object ;  it  is  never 
perceived ;  it  is  experienced  by  immediate  feeling  and  must  be 
understood  and  interpreted,  but  not  described  and  explained. 
If  psychology  wishes  to  treat  of  the  will,  the  psychophysical 
organism  must  be  substituted  for  the  real  subject  and  thus  the 
will  be  considered  as  a  process  in  the  world  of  objects.  The 
description  of  any  known  will-acts  as  psychophysical  functions, 
that  is,  as  illustrations  of  psychological  laws,  thus  as  a  matter 
of  course  belongs  to  psychology,  and  if  the  psychologist 
should  analyze  into  psychophysical  elements  and  explain  as 
causally  determined  all  will-acts  and  human  functions  of  the 
last  three  thousand  years,  he  would  not  transcend  the  limits  of 
psychology.  It  would  be  a  very  useless  psychological  under- 
taking, but  it  would  be  such  and  not  history.  History  starts 
from  and  deals  with  the  real  subjective  will-acts  which  cannot 
be  found  in  the  world  of  psychophysical  objects. 

Our  personal  life  in  its  political,  economical,  religious,  scien- 
tific, aesthetic,  technical  and  practical  aspects  is  a  manifoldness 
of  will  attitudes  and  acknowledgments.  We  live  in  the  midst 
of  a  variety  of  political  and  social,  technical  and  practical  in- 
stitutions, but  no  institution  means  anything  else  than  expecta- 
tions and  demands  which  reach  our  will,  and  suggestions  towards 
which  we  take  attitudes.  State  and  church,  legal  community  and 
social  set,  what  else  are  they  but  will  attitudes  which  we  acknowl- 
edge and  which  are,  therefore,  never  understood  in  their  real 
meaning  if  they  are  considered  as  describable  objects,  but  which 
must  be  interpreted  and  appreciated  as  subjective  will  relations, 
striving  towards  purposes  and  ends.  And  to  understand  all  the 
technical  and  practical  institutions  which  civilization  brings  to 


20  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

us  means  again  not  to  describe  or  explain  them,  but  to  interpret 
them  as  will  suggestions  to  be  imitated.  The  machine  and  the 
book,  the  law  and  the  poem,  are  not  physical  and  psychical  ob- 
jects for  our  interests  as  living  men,  but  suggestions  and  demands 
for  the  understanding  of  the  intentions  and  attitudes  of  other 
subjects  which  we  can  enter  into  only  by  taking  an  imitating  or 
rejecting  attitude,  thus  reaching  will  by  will.  All  our  knowing 
and  believing,  our  enjoying  and  respecting — as  long  as  we  ab- 
stract from  their  over-individual  values — all  our  education  and 
civilization,  our  politics  and  our  professional  work,  is  such  a 
complex  of  real  affirmations  and  negations,  demands  and  inhi- 
bitions, agreements  and  disagreements,  which  have  to  be  under- 
stood and  felt  and  interpreted,  but  which  are  not  touched  in 
their  reality  if  merely  their  p&ychophysical  substitutions  are 
analyzed  and  causally  explained.  To  be  a  Chinese  or  Moham- 
medan, a  symbolist  or  a  Hegelian  or  an  atomist,  means  to  be  the 
subject  of  special  complexes  of  will  attitudes  and  nothing  else. 
If,  for  instance,  we  substitute  the  race  for  the  state,  then,  of 
course,  we  have  objects  before  us  and  no  longer  subjective  atti- 
tudes, but  then  we  deal  with  biological  conceptions  and  no  longer 
with  history. 

The  manifoldness  of  will-acts  the  totality  of  which  forms  my 
real  personality  thus  refers  in  every  act  to  the  will- acts  and 
attitudes  of  other  subjects  which  I  acknowledge  or  oppose,  imi- 
tate or  overcome.  These  demands  and  suggestions  of  others 
are  not  in  question  in  my  life  as  causes  or  partial  causes  of  my 
will ;  they  have  not  to  be  sought  in  the  interest  of  a  causal  con- 
nection ;  they  are  merely  conditions  which  I  as  subject  of  atti- 
tude and  acts  presuppose  for  my  free  decision  and  which  are 
thus  logically  contained  in  it ;  the  connection  is,  therefore,  not  a 
causal,  but  merely  a  teleological  one.  The  endless  world  of 
will-acts  which  stands  thus  in  teleologically  determining  relation 
to  our  own  will-attitudes  forms  the  only  material  of  history. 

The  material  is,  of  course,  unlimited.  If  every  act  of  ours 
means  an  attitude  towards  acts  of  others  which  we  must  try  to 
understand,  it  is  clear  that  those  others  are  understood  only  if 
their  acts  again  are  interpreted  as  attitudes  towards  the  proposi- 
tions and  demands  and  suggestions  of  others,  and  so  on  and 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  21 

on.  Every  will-act  is  thus  ideally  related  to  an  unlimited  mani- 
foldness  of  other  acts,  just  as  the  movement  of  every  grain  of 
sand  is  causally  related  to  every  molecule  in  the  universe.  It  is 
the  unique  task  of  history  as  a  science  to  work  out  and  make 
complete  this  teleological  system  of  individual  will-relations, 
thus  to  bring  out  the  connections  between  our  acts  and  all  the 
acts  which  we  must  acknowledge  as  somehow  teleologically 
influencing  our  own.  While  physics  and  psychology  thus  pro- 
duce a  connected  system  of  causes  and  effects,  linking  all  ob- 
jects which  stand  in  connection  with  our  objects,  history  follows 
up  all  the  subjective  acts  which  stand  in  will-relation  to  our  sub- 
jective attitudes. 

Physics  and  psychology,  as  we  have  seen,  reach  this  end 
through  striving  towards  laws  and  causality ;  that,  of  course, 
cannot  be  the  way  of  history.  The  objects  interested  us  only 
as  factors  which  influence  the  future,  and  the  laws  by  which  we 
have  connected  them  have  satisfied  this  expectant  interest.  The 
subjects,  on  the  other  hand,  do  not  interest  us  in  first  line  as  causes 
of  effects.  Of  course,  we  are  able  to  consider  them  also  as  ob- 
jects which  produce  effects,  and  that  aspect  may  become  impor- 
tant to  us  in  many  practical  respects  ;  psychophysics  will  fully 
satisfy  this  kind  of  interest.  And  in  the  same  way  we  may  look  on 
the  development  of  peoples  with  an  interest  in  what  we  have  to 
expect  from  them  ;  they  are  then  sociological  organisms,  the 
laws  of  which  we  study ;  but  such  study  is  not  history.  The 
aim  of  the  real  historian  is  not  to  prophesy  the  future.  Peoples 
never  learn  from  history,  and  the  forgotten  doctrine  that  we 
ought  to  study  history  to  find  out  what  we  have  to  expect  from 
the  future  stands  on  the  same  level  with  its  contemporary,  the 
doctrine  that  it  is  the  purpose  of  art  to  instruct  us  and  to  make 
us  better.  No,  the  historian  makes  us  understand  the  system 
of  will  attitudes  to  which  our  individual  will  is  related.  That, 
indeed,  alone,  is  our  primary  interest  in  the  will-acts  of  other 
subjects ;  we  want  to  understand  them,  not  to  analyze  them  into 
elements  ;  we  want  to  interpret  their  meanings  and  not  to  calcu- 
late their  future.  The  objects  awake  our  expectations ;  the 
subjects  interest  our  appreciation,  and  all  that  we  want  to  know 
about  them  is  with  what  other  attitudes  they  agree  or  disagree. 


22  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

We  thus  have  the  logical  aim,  to  consider  them  in  their  rela- 
tions to  all  other  will  attitudes  and  to  work  out  the  system  of 
these  connections ;  that  is,  to  consider  the  institutions  which 
are  the  representatives  of  will  suggestions,  together  with  the 
personalities  themselves,  as  links  of  this  endless  chain  of  will 
relations. 

The  purpose  of  history  is  not  reached  until  every  institution 
and  personality  with  which  we  may  be  in  a  direct  or  indirect 
will  relation  is  understood  as  a  complex  of  agreements  and  dis- 
agreements, that  is,  of  will  attitudes  towards  other  subjects.  This 
regress  must  be,  of  course,  infinite,  just  as  no  physical  process 
can  be  reached  which  has  not  again  causes  and  effects ;  and 
this  task  demands  also,  like  the  naturalistic  sciences,  a  continual 
transformation.  Just  as  the  physical  object  is  not  really  a  com- 
plex of  atoms  and  the  psychological  idea  not  really  a  complex 
of  sensations,  but  must  be  in  thought  transformed  into  such  to 
make  causal  connection  possible,  so  in  exactly  the  same  way 
history  must  reconstruct  the  personalities  and  institutions  as 
complexes  of  will  attitudes,  which  they  really  are  not,  but  as 
which  they  must  be  considered  to  make  the  unbroken  teleological 
connection  possible.  And  again,  like  physics  and  psychology, 
history  too  cannot  communicate  to  us  the  whole  of  the  connected 
system,  but  has  to  work  out  the  general  facts  which  give  to  every 
single  fact  at  once  its  place  in  the  whole  system.  These  gen- 
eral facts  in  the  teleological  will  system  cannot  be  causal  laws, 
but  must  be  will  relations  of  more  and  more  comprehensive 
character.  Just  as  in  the  world  of  objects  the  general  law 
covers  and  determines  the  causal  changes  of  an  unlimited 
number  of  objects,  so  the  important  will-actions  cover  and  deter- 
mine in  the  world  of  subjects  the  impulses  and  suggestions  for  the 
decisions  and  attitudes  of  an  unlimited  number.  The  regularity 
of  the  causal  law  and  the  importance  of  the  imposing  will  lift  in  a 
corresponding  way  the  general  fact  over  the  level  of  the  single 
facts.  It  is  the  work  of  history  to  make  conspicuous  the  in- 
creasingly important  will  influences,  as  it  is  the  work  of  physics 
and  psychology  to  work  out  the  laws.  If  I  say  I  am  a  German, 
I  want  to  assert  by  that  statement  that  I  acknowledge  by  my  will 
a  world  of  laws,  institutions,  hopes  and  ideals  which  are  the  will 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  23 

demands  of  an  undetermined  multitude  of  subjects  ;  this  multitude 
constitutes  the  historical  nation  of  Germany.  But  it  would  be  un- 
scientific if  I  should  start  to  interpret  the  attitude  of  every  one 
who  is  part  of  that  chaotic  mass  of  subjects  ;  it  is  the  work  of  sci- 
ence to  find  those  influences  which  determined  the  multitude, those 
will-acts  which  were  imitated  and  acknowledged  by  the  unim- 
portant subjects.  The  chaos  thus  becomes  order,  and  Goethe  and 
Beethoven,  Kant  and  Hegel,  Luther  and  Bismarck,  stand  as  the 
general  facts  for  the  millions  and  millions  of  less  important  sub- 
jects who  were  determined  by  their  suggestions.  Any  individual's 
historical  place  is  then  characterized  by  his  will  attitudes  towards 
the  leaders.  Just  as  the  naturalist  knows  a  whole  hierarchy  of 
sciences  which  work  out  increasingly  general  laws  up  to  me- 
chanics as  the  most  abstract  system,  so  history  can  consider  in 
different  stages  the  will  relations  of  more  and  more  comprehen- 
sive character.  The  most  abstract  view  is  represented  by  the 
so-called  philosophy  of  history,  which  aims  at  understanding  the 
history  of  the  world  as  determined  by  one  decision  of  the  will. 
In  this  spirit  the  conception  of  original  sin  in  the  theological 
systems  of  the  Middle  Ages  was  in  the  field  of  historical  think- 
ing perhaps  not  less  marvelous  than  the  conception  of  atomistic 
mechanism  in  the  realm  of  natural  science.  The  fact  that 
Adam  did  not  exist  in  reality  is  as  little  an  objection  to  the 
mediaeval  construction  as  the  fact  that  no  atom  can  really  exist 
militates  against  our  atomism ;  both  reconstructions  of  reality 
fill  merely  ideal  places  as  necessary  goals  of  thought. 

On  the  other  hand,  in  the  same  way  that  mechanics  does  not 
lower  the  importance  of  special  natural  sciences,  no  all-embrac- 
ing theory  of  the  history  of  man  can  interfere  with  the  impor- 
tance of  the  special  historic  disciplines  down  to  the  biographies 
of  single  personalities.  But  even  the  biography  has  to  work  in 
the  same  direction  as  the  most  abstract  philosophy  of  history,  in 
the  direction  of  general  connection.  The  real  biography  writ- 
ten in  an  historical  spirit  shows  in  the  individual  the  attitudes 
towards  the  demands  and  suggestions  which  make  the  history 
of  mankind ;  the  single  man  becomes  thus  the  crossing  point 
of  all  the  political,  technical,  religious,  aesthetical,  intellectual 
impulses  of  his  time,  and  he  is  thus  by  the  will-attitudes  which 


24  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

constitute  his  personality  connected  with  the  whole  universe  of 
will-acts.  As  the  astronomer  in  his  calculations  describes  the 
one  curve  of  a  star  as  the  combination  of  a  large  number  of  im- 
pulses by  attraction,  and  thus  brings  the  star  in  relation  to  the 
whole  firmament,  so  the  historical  biographer  reconstructs  the 
one  life  as  a  system  of  single  attitudes  towards  an  endless  mul- 
titude of  demands  and  suggestions.  It  is  a  complete  transfor- 
mation in  the  service  of  connection.  The  man's  life  can  be 
told  also  otherwise  :  the  life  as  he  feels  it  as  a  personal  experi- 
ence ;  so  also  do  we  learn  to  understand  the  man ;  but  we  have 
then  poetry  and  not  history ;  it  is  isolation  and  not  connection. 
And  if  we,  instead,  describe  and  explain  his  life  as  a  set  of  ideas, 
feelings,  emotions  and  volitions  which  arose  in  his  psychophys- 
ical  system  from  birth  to  death,  then  we  have  again  a  transforma- 
tion in  the  service  of  connection,  but  this  time  for  the  causal 
connection  of  objects,  not  for  the  teleological  connection  of  sub- 
jects ;  it  is  again  not  history,  but  psychology. 

The  separation  of  the  material  of  the  two  sciences  is  thus 
simple  and  clear ;  there  can  never  be  a  doubt  about  the  line  of 
demarcation,  as  there  is  no  psychophysical  object  in  the  world — 
from  the  sensations  of  a  frog  up  to  the  ideas  of  Newton,  the 
emotions  of  Byron,  and  the  volitions  of  Cromwell — which  is  not 
a  suitable  object  of  psychology,  and  as  there  is  no  subjective  in- 
dividual act  which  cannot  be  linked  into  the  endless  teleological 
system  of  history.  A  division  of  material,  as  if  a  social  psy- 
chology, for  instance,  were  to  deal  with  the  psychical  processes 
of  the  unknown  masses,  while  history  were  to  deal  with  the  psy- 
chical processes  of  the  well-known  men,  is  an  absurdity.  Not 
less  misleading  would  be  an  antithesis  between  savagery  and 
civilization.  From  a  psychophysical  standpoint  such  a  line  is 
secondary ;  the  organism  which  has  outer  appendages  of  his 
body  to  make  the  psychophysical  functions  more  effective  has 
reached  merely  a  higher  stage  of  biological  development,  but  is 
not  different  in  principle  from  the  lower  type  in  which  nature 
does  not  provide  for  detachable  acquisitions  of  the  organism. 
The  animal  which  runs  with  locomotives,  sees  with  microscopes, 
hears  with  telephones,  makes  gestures  of  expression  through 
newspapers,  attacks  through  cannons,  remembers  through  libra- 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  25 

ries,  stands  above  the  savage  as  a  dog  stands  above  a  jelly-fish, 
but  it  is  by  principle  nothing  new ;  it  is  a  more  complicated 
product  of  nature  which,  therefore,  offers  a  more  difficult  prob- 
lem to  the  descriptions  and  explanations  of  psychology  and 
physiology,  but  does  not  become  as  such  material  for  history. 
And  still  another  line  of  separation  has  to  disappear ;  the  fight 
between  the  *  materialists '  and  the  '  idealists '  of  the  recent  eco- 
nomical schools  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  doubleness  of  psy- 
chological naturalism  and  real  historical  aspect.  If  the  materi- 
alists claim  that  every  occurrence  among  men  is  the  direct  or  in- 
direct effect  of  economical  causes,  while  the  idealists  consider 
other  causes  still  which  seem  to  them  independent  of  material 
conditions,  for  instance,  religious  and  patriotic  emotion  or  ambi- 
tion and  love,  both  sides  stand  fully  on  the  ground  of  psy- 
chology and  outside  of  history.  Those  emotions  of  practical 
idealism  are  in  question  only  as  psychophysical  causes  and  are 
thus  material  merely  for  a  causal  system.  In  the  system  of  his- 
tory exists  no  causality. 

Here  is  the  point  where  even  the  historians  themselves  are 
inclined  to  compromises  which,  at  least  in  principle,  must  be 
rejected.  Whether  or  not  practically  quite  interesting  reports 
of  periods  of  civilization  can  be  written  by  mixing  the  two 
attitudes  is  secondary.  Historians,  we  know,  produced  in 
earlier  times  their  deepest  effects  by  mixing  history  with  ethics, 
but  the  philosopher  at  least  must  be  clear  that  ethics  is  not 
history,  and  he  ought  to  be  still  less  in  doubt  that  a  causally 
explaining  social  psychology  is  not  history  either.  As  soon 
as  it  is  acknowledged  that  we  have,  on  the  one  side,  an  interest 
to  consider  human  life  as  an  object  and  thus  to  describe  and  to 
explain  it,  and  that  we  have,  on  the  other  side,  a  logical  aim  to 
understand  human  life  as  subjective  acts  which  can  be  only 
interpreted  and  linked  together  by  will  attitudes,  then  we  must 
have  the  energy  to  keep  the  two  systems  separated.  Each  is 
logically  valuable,  each  is  therefore  true,  but  if  confused  both 
become  logically  useless. 

We  can  say  that  Socrates  remained  in  the  prison  because  his 
knee  muscles  were  contracted  in  a  sitting  position  and  not  work- 
ing to  effect  his  escape,  and  that  these  muscle-processes  took 


26  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

place  because  certain  psychophysical  ideas,  emotions  and  voli- 
tions, all  composed  of  elementary  sensations,  occurred  in  his 
brain,  and  that  they,  again,  were  the  effects  of  all  the  causes 
which  sense  stimulations  and  dispositions,  associations  and  inhi- 
bitions, physiological  and  climatic  influences,  produced  in  that 
organism.  And  we  can  say,  on  the  other  hand,  that  Socrates  re- 
mained in  the  prison  because  he  decided  to  be  obedient  to  the 
laws  of  Athens  unto  death.  This  obedience  means,  then,  not  a 
psychophysical  process,  but  a  will  attitude  which  we  must  under- 
stand by  feeling  it  and  living  through  it,  an  attitude  which  we 
cannot  analyze,  but  which  we  interpret  and  appreciate.  The 
first  is  a  psychological  description ;  the  second  is  a  histor- 
ical interpretation.  Both  are  true.  They  are,  to  be  sure,  not 
equally  valuable  for  science,  as  that  particular  psychophysical 
process  is  not  more  important  for  the  understanding  of  the  psy- 
chological system  than  millions  of  other  emotions  in  unknown 
men,  while  that  will  attitude  influenced  by  its  demand  the  ac- 
knowledging will  of  twenty  centuries,  and  is  thus  most  impor- 
tant in  the  historical  system.  And  yet  both  are  equally  true, 
while  they  blend  into  an  absurdity  if  we  say  that  those  psycho- 
physical  states  in  the  brain  of  Socrates  were  the  objects  which 
inspired  the  will  of  his  pupils  and  were  suggestive  through  two 
thousand  years. 

A  history  which  interprets  subjectively  and  understands  their 
purposes  out  of  the  deeds  of  men  relinquishes,  indeed,  its  only 
aim  if  it  coordinates  these  teleological  relations  with  the  causal 
explanation  of  human  happenings  from  climatic  and  geograph- 
ical, technical  and  economical,  physiological  and  pathological 
influences.  The  subject  which  is  determined  by  purposes  is 
free  ;  the  action  which  is  the  effect  of  causes  is  unfree.  In  the 
unfree  world  there  cannot  be  any  action  which  must  not  be 
understood  causally,  and  we  have  no  right  to  stop  anywhere  in 
our  explanation  ;  the  unexplained  action  means  only  an  unsolved 
problem  which  is  in  no  way  solved  if  we  seek  for  its  subjective 
meaning  instead  of  its  elements  and  causes.  In  the  world  of 
freedom,  on  the  other  hand,  it  would  be  meaningless  to  ask  for 
cause,  as  the  objects  then  come  in  question  merely  as  objects  for 
the  willing  subjects  and  not  as  realities  for  themselves.  The 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  27 

realm  of  freedom  is  not  made  up  of  oases  in  the  world  of  neces- 
sity ;  the  reality  of  history  is  not  spread  here  and  there  over  the 
field  of  nature,  but  lies  fully  outside  of  its  limits.  The  an- 
tithesis between  psychology  and  history  is  thus  not  law  and  sin- 
gle event,  but  causality  and  freedom,  and  this  difference  is  the 
logical  result  of  the  ontological  difference  of  the  material,  the 
one  dealing  with  objects,  the  other  with  subjects.  Both  go 
methodologically  the  same  way,  considering  the  single  facts 
from  the  point  of  view  of  the  general  fact,  and  both  transform- 
ing the  disconnected  material  until  a  perfectly  connected  system 
is  reached.  But  because  objects  are  understood  by  describing 
and  explaining  them,  while  subjects  are  understood  by  interpret- 
ing and  appreciating  them,  the  connection  of  the  one  system 
must  be  causal,  that  of  the  other  system  teleological,  and  the 
general  fact  in  the  one  field  must  be  a  law  and  in  the  other  field 
the  will  relation  of  importance.  As  every  subjective  act  can  be 
substituted  by  a  psychophysical  function  of  an  organism  in  the 
world  of  objects,  and  as  every  object  can  be  understood  as  a 
value  for  a  will,  the  whole  reality  can  be  brought  without  any 
possible  remainder  under  the  one  aspect  as  well  as  under  the 
other.  History,  in  the  real  historical  spirit,  then  need  no  longer 
fear  that  the  progress  of  psychology  can  inhibit  its  functions, 
and  the  psychologist  need  not  feel  discouraged  that  his  psycho- 
logical laws  of  history  appear  so  utterly  trivial  to  the  historian. 
That  which  is  important  for  psychology,  that  which  is  fit  for 
constructing  connections  between  psychological  objects,  has  the 
privilege  of  being  indifferent  for  the  historian,  that  is,  of  being 
unfit  to  link  subjective  will  attitudes.  Psychology  and  history 
cannot  help  each  other  and  cannot  interfere  with  each  other  as 
long  as  they  consistently  stick  to  their  own  aims.  Each  of 
them  has  thus  unlimited  opportunities  for  development.  The 
processions  of  the  great  psychologists  from  Aristotle  to  Herbart, 
and  that  of  the  great  historians  from  Thucydides  to  Macaulay, 
can  both  have  for  the  future  an  unlimited  number  of  followers 
without  any  quarrel,  in  spite  of  the  naturalistic  claims  of  our 
age,  which  for  a  while  was  under  the  illusion  that  all  is  under- 
stood when  all  is  explained,  and  that  the  historians  should  better 
become  psychologists. 


28  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

As  soon  as  the  difference  of  the  two  standpoints  is  recog- 
nized, light  falls  on  all  the  special  characteristics  of  the  two 
sciences.  Now  we  understand  why  history  stands  so  much 
nearer  to  real  life  than  psychology.  Not,  as  it  was  suggested, 
because  history  deals  with  single  facts  and  psychology  with 
general  facts,  but  because  psychology  deals  with  objects  which 
are  thought  as  independent  of  the  subject,  while  in  reality  and 
so  in  history  the  material  is  acknowledged  only  in  relation  to 
willing  subjects.  In  real  life  we  are  subjects  which  must  be 
understood  but  not  described ;  psychology  starts  thus  at  once 
with  a  material  which  in  its  singleness  is  already  farther  away 
from  reality  than  the  material  with  which  history  deals.  Now 
we  understand  also  why  the  substance  of  history  has  value  for 
us,  while  the  objects  of  psychology  and  of  all  naturalistic  sciences 
are  emotionally  indifferent.  That  is  not,  as  it  was  suggested, 
because  the  single  facts  are  important  for  us  and  the  general 
facts  indifferent;  no,  it  is  because  the  psychological  objects,  the 
contents  of  consciousness,  are  thought  as  cut  loose  from  the  will 
and  thus  no  longer  possible  objects  for  appreciation,  while  the 
historical  objects  are  thought  as  in  their  relation  to  the  attitudes 
of  the  will.  Now  we  understand  also  under  which  principle 
the  historian  selects  his  material.  If  we  accept  the  view  that 
all  single  facts  belong  to  history  as  such,  it  is  arbitrariness  to 
chronicle  Napoleon's  battles  and  state  acts  but  not  his  flirtations 
and  breakfasts,  while  now  we  understand  how  it  is  that  this  se- 
lection means  the  most  essential  part  of  the  historian's  work,  as 
it  is  the  way  to  transform  the  reality  into  a  system  of  teleolog- 
ical  connections,  thus  dropping  more  and  more  the  will-acts 
which  have  no  teleological  importance  for  will-attitudes  of  other 
subjects.  Now  we  understand  also  why  the  language  of  the 
historian  has  so  much  similarity  with  that  of  the  poet.  The  his- 
torian, we  have  seen,  has  aims  which  are  directly  antagonistic  to 
those  of  the  poet,  as  the  poet  isolates,  while  the  historian,  like 
every  scientist,  connects  his  material.  But  the  materials  them- 
selves, the  subjective  acts,  are  common  to  the  poet  and  the  histo- 
rian. Where  the  psychologist  encourages  the  reader  to  take  the  at- 
titude of  the  objectively  perceiving  observer,  the  poet  and  the  his- 
torian speak  of  facts  which  can  be  understood  only  by  interpreta- 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND  HISTORY.  29 

tion  and  inner  imitation ;  they  cannot  be  described  by  enumer- 
ating their  elements  ;  they  must  be  suggested  and  reach  somehow 
the  willing  subject  which  enters  into  the  subjective  attitude  of 
the  other.  Thus  the  means  of  both  may  approximate  to  each 
other.  The  poet  and  the  historian  may  use  the  same  methods 
of  suggestion  to  reenforce  in  the  reader  the  subjectifying  atti- 
tude which  is  the  presupposition  for  the  understanding  of  the 
isolated  will-acts  in  the  work  of  poetry  and  the  connected  will- 
acts  in  the  work  of  history,  while  the  psychologist  has  to  adapt 
even  his  style  and  his  presentation  to  the  service  of  his  objectify- 
ing aim. 

But  we  now  understand  and  see  in  a  new  light  also  the  rela- 
tions of  the  psychological  and  historical  sciences  to  the  norma- 
tive doctrines,  to  ethics,  logic  and  aesthetics.  As  long  as  his- 
tory appears  merely  as  a  part  of  psychology  or  as  long  as 
the  one  is  given  over  to  single  facts,  the  other  to  laws,  all  the 
normative  sciences  stand  without  any  inner  relation  to  any 
empirical  science,  those  speaking  of  duties,  these  of  facts.  For 
us  the  relation  takes  a  very  different  form.  We  have  seen  that  all 
the  historical  sciences  are  systems  of  individual  will  relations  and 
nothing  else.  On  the  other  hand,  we  have  found  that  duty  never 
means  anything  but  our  own  over-individual  will-act.  All  the  nor- 
mative sciences  are  thus  the  systematic  connections  of  our  over- 
individual  will-attitudes,  our  will-attitudes  aiming  toward  morality 
and  truth  and  beauty  and  religion.  As  the  over-individual  will 
is,  of  course,  thought  as  independent  of  the  individual  sub- 
ject, the  connection  which  is  sought  cannot  lead  as  it  did  in  his- 
tory from  subject  to  subject ;  as  all  subjects  are  presupposed  as 
agreeing  in  their  over-individual  acknowledgment,  the  connec- 
tion, the  scientific  aim  can  then  lie  here  merely  in  the  systematic 
connection  of  our  own  over-individual  purposes  and  their  inter- 
pretation. A  transformation  becomes  here,  too,  necessary  in  the 
interest  of  connection ;  each  single  will  attitude  must  be  linked 
into  this  teleological  system  and  must  thus  be  transformed  till  it 
represents  a  crossing  point  of  all  the  ethical,  aesthetical,  re- 
ligious and  logical  impulses  and  demands.  The  normative  sci- 
ences and  history  stand  thus  in  the  nearest  relation  to  each  other  ; 
both  are  transformations  of  will-acts  in  the  service  of  teleolog- 


30  HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

ical  connection,  only  the  one  reconstructs  and  systematizes  the 
individual  will-acts  in  us,  the  other  the  over-individual  will- 
acts. 

The  relation  between  these  two  groups  of  sciences,  the  histor- 
ical and  the  normative  ones,  is  thus  perfectly  parallel  to  the  rela- 
tion between  the  psychological  sciences  and  the  physical  sci- 
ences, of  which  the  one  systematizes  the  individual  objects  and 
the  other  the  over-individual  objects.  The  proportion — history 
— stands  to  the  normative  doctrines,  as  psychology  stands  to 
physics — is,  indeed,  true  in  every  respect  and  in  every  conse- 
quence. We  may  consider  here  as  our  last  word  only  one  of 
them.  The  historical  development  of  the  naturalistic  sciences 
shows  the  continuous  tendency  to  take  more  and  more  of  the 
properties  of  the  physical  object  into  the  psychological  object, 
that  is,  to  show  that  the  apparent  over-individual  qualities  of  the 
thing  are  qualities  which  depend  upon  the  individual ;  color  and 
sound,  smell  and  taste,  go  over  from  the  physical  thing  into  the 
idea,  and  thus  the  whole  manifoldness  of  our  experience  moves 
over  into  the  sphere  of  ideas.  In  exactly  the  same  way  and  led  by 
the  same  methodological  motives,  history  takes  more  and  more 
of  the  normative  duties  over  into  its  own  field,  and  shows  how  the 
special  duties,  the  logical  beliefs,  ethical  convictions,  aesthetical 
demands  and  religious  postulates  are  the  results  of  individual 
attitudes  under  the  suggestion  of  the  individual  groups  of  will- 
influences.  The  absolute  duties  and  beliefs  and  obligations  and 
truths  seem  thus  lost  in  our  life  as  the  colors  and  sounds  and 
smells  are  lost  for  the  physical  objects.  But  the  parallelism  holds 
for  the  end-point  of  this  development  too.  We  must  deprive  the 
physical  object  of  its  colors  and  sounds,  but  we  cannot  give  up 
the  truth  that  there  is  a  physical  object  nevertheless,  as  the  quan- 
titative reality  to  which  we  project,  with  objective  truth,  our  sen- 
sations and  ideas  ;  all  the  naturalistic  sciences  would  be  destroyed 
if  we  were  to  give  up  this  realistic  conviction  of  physics.  In 
the  same  way  we  may  take  into  the  individual  all  the  single 
over-individual  special  duties  of  special  nations  and  ages  and 
social  groups,  but  the  reality  of  the  background  of  projection 
we  cannot  give  up.  Whatever  history  teaches,  the  postulate  of 
the  reality  of  duties,  of  absolute  values,  stands  firm.  The  abso- 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   HISTORY.  31 

lute  duties  may  be  abstract  and  deprived  of  color  and  sound  as 
is  the  world  of  physics,  but  they  stand  and  must  last  like  the 
physical  universe,  and  whoever  in  striving  towards  truth  denies 
the  reality  of  absolute  values  and  gives  up  the  belief  in  morality 
and  the  belief  in  logic,  thus  destroys  and  undermines  his  own 
endeavor  to  find  the  truth  as  logical  thinker  and  to  stand  for  the 
truth  as  ethical  man. 


A  STUDY  OF  THE  RELATIONS    BETWEEN  CER- 
TAIN ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND 
CONSCIOUSNESS. 

BY  PROFESSOR  JAMES  ROWLAND  ANGELL  AND  HELEN 
BRADFORD  THOMPSON. 

I.  INTRODUCTORY. 

Circulation  and  respiration  are  the  organic  processes  with 
which  this  paper  is  mainly  concerned.  An  inspection  of  the 
literature  dealing  with  the  relation  of  these  processes  to  con- 
sciousness reveals  a  condition  of  disagreement  among  investi- 
gators, both  as  regards  fact  and  theory.  On  the  side  of  fact  the 
discrepancies  are  gradually  giving  way  before  more  accurate 
methods  of  observation  and  experiment.  On  the  side  of  theory, 
however,  the  progress  toward  agreement  is,  perhaps,  less  notice- 
able. 

The  thesis  which  we  shall  defend  in  the  following  pages 
is  based  primarily  upon  experiments  undertaken  by  us  some 
two  years  ago  with  the  purpose  of  determining  whether  changes 
in  the  character  of  attention  were  accompanied  by  any  regular 
alterations  in  the  organic  processes  above  mentioned.  The 
formulation  we  have  reached  should,  however,  if  true,  be 
equally  applicable  to  the  observations  of  other  investigators. 
This  we  believe  to  be  the  case,  although  the  description  of  these 
observations  is  often  too  meager  on  the  psychological  side  to 
permit  a  satisfactory  comparison  with  our  own  work.  Within 
the  bounds  of  its  pretensions  our  formula,  if  correct,  will  have 
the  value  of  a  centralizing,  harmonizing  principle  for  a  mass  of 
facts  which,  from  many  points  of  view,  appear  self-contradictory 
and  unintelligible. 

At  the  risk  of  devoting  a  disproportionate  part  of  our  space 
to  the  matter,  we  shall  begin  by  attempting  a  sketch  of  the 
more  important  of  the  relevant  facts  hitherto  observed.  So  far 
32 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  33 

as  we  are  aware,  these  have  never  been  brought  together  in 
the  form  we  adopt,  and  they  furnish  the  best  possible  proof  of 
the  necessity  for  some  general  connective  principle. 

II.  HISTORICAL  OUTLINE. 

It  will  be  convenient  to  state  first  the  factors  in  the  processes 
under  consideration  which  have  been  thus  far  differentiated.1 

The  most  striking  alterations  shown  by  the  respiration  con- 
sist in  changes  of  rate  and  depth,  or  amplitude.  The  general 
type  of  the  breathing  also  displays  certain  differences  under 
varying  conditions.  Thus  breathing  in  which  costal  or  thoracic 
movements  predominate  may  take  on  a  more  abdominal  or  dia- 
phragmatic character.  In  addition  to  these  changes,  however, 
must  be  mentioned  alterations  in  the  general  rhythm  and  in  the 
duration  of  the  various  constituent  factors  in  the  total  respiratory 
act.  Thus  the  slight  pause  which  follows  expiration  may  be 
exaggerated  or  may  practically  disappear.  Similarly  the  pause 
concluding  inspiration  may  be  altered  in  its  relation  to  the  total 
act.2  Again,  as  accompaniments  of  such  changes,  we  may  find 
the  usual  relation  between  the  phase  of  inspiration  and  that  of 
expiration  altered ;  the  normal  relation  being  that  of  a  slight  ex- 
cess of  expiration  over  inspiration.3 

The  more  important  aspects  of  the  circulation,  to  which  ref- 
erence is  made  in  this  connection,  may  be  summarized  as  fol- 
lows :  (i)  The  rate  and  force  of  the  heart-beat.  (2)  The 
tension  in  the  walls  of  the  blood  vessels — constriction  or  dila- 
tion. (3)  The  blood-pressure.  (4)  The  amount  of  blood  sent 

1  Excellent  descriptions  and  illustrations  of  apparatus  employed  in  such  in- 
vestigations will  be  found  in  '  La  Fatigue  Intellectuelle, '  Binet  and  Henri,  Paris, 
1897.     The  technique  of  such  apparatus  has  been  carefully  studied   by  Hiirthle, 
Pfliiger's  Archiv,  53  ;  also  by  Binet  and  Courtier,  LSAnnee  Psychologique,   1895. 
Cf.  also  Langendorf,  Physiologische  Graphik. 

2  Certain  authorities  question  the  genuineness  of   these  pauses  and   regard 
the  second  as  distinctly  abnormal.     Cf.  Landois  and  Stirling,  Physiology,  p.  200. 

3  The  amount  of  air  breathed  under  various  conditions,  the  amount  of  oxy- 
gen used  and  the  amount  of  carbon  dioxide  exhaled  have  all  been  studied  with 
much   care,  but  we  shall   make  no  reference   to  these  features,  as  the  results  at- 
tained do  not  appear  to  bear  in  any  essentials  upon  the  considerations  with  which 
we  are  here  immediately  concerned.     See  Speck,  Physiologic  des  Menschlichen. 
Athmens,  Leipzig,  1892. 


34  /•   R>   ANGELL  AND  H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

to  the  brain.  (5)  The  amount  of  blood  sent  to  the  viscera.1 
(6)  The  amount  sent  to  the  periphery.  (7)  The  interrelations 
between  (4),  (5)  and  (6).  (8)  The  features  of  the  cardiac, 
arterial  or  capillary  pulse :  its  height  or  amplitude,  shape,  etc., 
with  special  reference  to  its  anacrotic  or  catacrotic  character- 
istics. It  will  of  course  be  understood  that  in  this  analysis  of 
salient  features  in  the  circulatory  process,  no  implication  of 
complete  independence  of  the  elements  so  distinguished  is  for 
an  instant  contemplated.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  some  of  the  pro- 
cesses do  at  times  vary  irrespective  of  the  action  of  others,  but 
these  interrelations  will  be  canvassed  more  closely  later  on.2 

We  may  summarize  the  results  of  the  various  investigations 
as  follows :  The  dominant  tendency  of  sensations  of  every 
kind  is,  according  to  the  latest  and  most  careful  observations, 
to  produce  a  vaso-constriction  in  the  periphery  and  an  afflux  of 
blood  to  the  brain.  The  amount  and  regularity  of  these  alter- 
ations probably  depend  on  the  intensity  and  duration  of  the 
stimulus.  Those  investigators  who  find  regular  differences  in 
the  organic  processes  as  accompaniments  of  the  algedonic  tone 
of  the  sensation,  would  necessarily  make  an  exception  in  favor 
of  such  sensations  as  are  distinctly  agreeable  and  productive  in 
their  experiences  of  peripheral  dilations.  The  effects  of  sen- 
sation upon  the  heart-beat,  the  form  of  the  pulse  curve  and  the 
respiration  vary  too  widely  with  varying  conditions  to  permit 
any  generalized  statement.  But  wherever  a  sensation  breaks 
in  upon  a  state  of  relative  quiet  and  repose,  so  that  a  mild 
emotion  or  shock  is  produced,  it  generally  produces  acceleration 
of  heart-beat  and  respiration,  the  latter  being  a  trifle  spasmodic 
and  often  deeper. 

Mental  activity  of  the  type  illustrated  by  application  to 
mathematical  computation,  memorizing  or  recalling  past  experi- 
ences is,  when  contrasted  with  conditions  of  greater  repose,  ac- 
companied by  afflux  of  blood  to  the  brain.  Under  the  conditions 
of  the  ordinary  laboratory  experiment,  such  psychological  pro- 

1  Points  (5)  and  (7)  concern  processes  too  inadequately  investigated  to  per- 
mit very  definite  formulations. 

2  As  in  the  case  of  the  respiration  and  for  similar  reasons,  we  make  no  reference 
to  the  observations  upon  the  chemical  changes  attendant  on  alterations  in  these 
various  phases  of  the  circulation.     Cf.  Hermann's  Handbuch  der  Physiologic. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  35 

cesses  are  sometimes  productive  of  peripheral  constrictions  and 
sometimes  show  peripheral  dilations.  Their  effects  upon  the 
form  of  the  pulse  curve  are  equally  equivocal,  but  they  result 
with  greater  regularity  in  increasing  the  rate  of  both  heart-beat 
and  respiration,  the  latter  as  a  rule  becoming  more  superficial. 
Emotions  of  every  sort  seem  more  effective  than  other  psy- 
chological processes  in  producing  increase  of  blood  in  the  brain. 
Vaso-constriction  seems  to  be  by  far  the  most  frequent  volume 
change  in  the  periphery,  although  a  modification,  similar  to  that 
mentioned  under  the  head  of  sensation,  has  to  be  made  in  favor 
of  those  investigators  who  find  opposite  physiological  expres- 
sions for  agreeable  and  disagreeable  experiences.  The  same 
restriction  has  to  be  placed  on  the  statement  that  acceleration  of 
heart  and  respiration  and  increased  depth  of  the  latter  are  ac- 
companiments of  all  emotions.  It  is  not  possible  at  present  to 
speak  definitely  of  the  changes  in  the  form  of  the  pulse  curve.1 

Without  injustice  to  earlier  investigators,  it  may  be  said  that  our 
serious  knowledge  of  the  connections  between  consciousness  and  the 
organic  processes  with  which  we  are  here  concerned,  begins  with  the 
classic  and  revolutionary  observations,  both  clinical  and  experimental, 
of  the  great  Italian  physiologist,  Angelo  Mosso. 

The  results  of  his  investigations  maybe  briefly  summarized  as  fol- 
lows, bearing  in  mind  that  the  psychological  conditions  involved  are 
those  of  sensation,  emotion  and  application  to  mental  calculations. 
We  may  notice  first  the  facts  concerning  changes  in  volume : 

Psychic  activity  of  every  kind  produces  an  increased  flow  of  blood 
to  the  brain  and  a  decreased  flow  to  the  periphery.2  The  changes 
which  follow  emotional  excitements  are  much  more  marked  than  any 
produced  by  intellective  processes,  and  the  responses  to  emotional 
stimuli  are  more  noticeable  in  the  brain  than  in  the  periphery.3  Sleep 
is  accompanied  by  a  withdrawal  of  blood  from  the  brain.4  Deep  in- 

1  We  shall  occupy  the  remainder  of  this  section  with  a  more  detailed  state- 
ment of  the  investigations  upon  which  this  summary  is  based. 

2 Die  Temperatur  d.  Gehirns,  p.  109.  Cf.  also  Patrizi,  Riv.  musicale  ital., 
1896.  Some  interesting  exceptions  to  this  general  rule  have  been  observed. 
They  consist  of  cases  in  which  the  activity  of  attention  distinctly  antedated  the 
circulatory  change.  Cf.  Die  Ermiidung,  p.  195. 

3Kreislauf  d.  Blutes  im  Mensch.  Gehirn,  p.  72  ft. 

*Kreislauf  d.  Blutes  im  Mensch.  Gehirn,  p.  74  ff.  Stimulations  which  are 
oo  feeble  to  produce  awakening  nevertheless  result  in  circulatory  alterations  of 


36  /.    R.    ANGELL  AND  H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

spirations  produce  a  decrease  of  blood  in  the  brain,  whereas  deep  ex- 
pirations cause  an  increase.  The  same  thing  is  noticed  in  the  upper 
limbs,  but  in  the  lower  limbs  the  relations  are  exactly  reversed,  a  fact 
which  apparently  depends  upon  the  inverse  pressure  relations  of  the 
thoracic  and  abdominal  cavities,  the  walls  of  the  one  moving  out  as  the 
walls  of  the  other  move  in.1  Superficial  breathing  produces  practi- 
cally no  effect  upon  the  cerebral  circulation.  The  plethysmographic 
changes  are  not  distributed  simultaneously  over  the  whole  of  the  body. 
Local  changes  of  both  blood  pressure  and  volume  occur.2  The  changes 
in  the  volume  of  the  brain  generally  precede  the  changes  in  the  pe- 
riphery and  are,  therefore,  not  to  be  regarded  as  on  every  occasion  the 
mere  consequences  of  such  peripheral  alterations.3  The  change  in  the 
brain  is  also  often  observed  to  outlast  the  change  in  the  periphery. 
Moreover,  the  amount  of  such  changes  in  the  volume  of  blood  in  the 
brain  is  much  less  than  the  contemporary  changes  often  occurring  in 
the  arm,  for  example,  and  of  course  much  less,  therefore,  than  those 
of  both  arms  together.*  Added  to  this  is  the  fact  that  a  decrease  in 
the  volume  of  a  limb  is  not  invariably  accompanied  by  an  equivalent 
increase  of  the  brain  volume.5  The  disparity  is  at  times  extreme. 

Upon  the  much-mooted  point  as  to  whether  or  no  the  blood  supply 
of  the  brain  is  controlled  directly  by  mechanisms  of  its  own,  or  indi- 
rectly through  changes  in  pressure  inaugurated  elsewhere  in  the  body, 
Mosso  inclines  to  a  positive  opinion  in  favor  of  some  neural  process 
intrinsic  to  the  brain  itself,  chiefly  on  the  ground  of  the  apparently 
primary  and  independent  variations  in  the  cerebral  circulation.6 

the  brain  and  periphery.  Several  observers  have  confirmed  these  observations 
upon  the  effects  of  unconscious  stimuli.  Cf.  Binet  and  Henri,  ibid.,  p.  80 ;  also 
Howell's  Physiology  of  Sleep,  Jour.  Experimental  Med.,  1897. 

1  Kreislauf  d.  Blutes,  etc.,  p.  133.  For  following  statements  see  pages  126 
and  106.  Cf.  Marey,  Circulation  du  Sang,  for  account  of  changes  due  to  costal 
or  abdominal  forms  of  breathing. 

2Cf.  Bayliss  and  Starling,  Jour,  of  Physiology,  1894,  p.  159. 

3  Die  Temperatur  d.  Gehirns,  p.  152.     Mosso's  observations  on  changes  in 
the  blood  pressure  do  not  lend  themselves  readily  to  a  generalized  statement. 
The  observations  of  other  investigators  to  be  mentioned  later  cover  the  ground 
more  fully,  and  we  therefore  make  no  attempt  to  epitomize  Mosso's  work  on 
this  point. 

4  Mays  questions  the  accuracy  of  these  observations.     He  states,  moreover, 
that  he  has  only  succeeded  in  obtaining  noticeable  alterations  in  cerebral  circula- 
tion in  response  to  emotions,  other   psychic  processes  being  ineffective.     Vir- 
chow's  Archiv,  1882. 

5 Die  Temperatur  d.  Gehirns,  p.  147. 

6  The  researches  of  Roy  and  Sherrington  point  to  the  direct  effects,  me- 
chanical or  chemical,  of  the  metabolisms  of  the  brain  as  sources,  on  some  occa- 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  37 

This  is  a  convenient  place  to  mention  Mosso's  striking  view,  con- 
firmed in  part  by  other  observers,  that  the  cerebral  circulation  is  after 
all  not  the  matter  of  primary  import  in  determining  the  phenomena  of 
psychic  activities.  It  might  naturally  be  expected  that  if  mere  in- 
crease of  blood  to  the  brain  were  the  essential  precondition  of  intense 
psychoses,  any  medium  which  would  produce  such  increase  of  blood 
would  be  followed  by  increased  mental  activity.  This  is  not  always 
the  case ;  witness  the  effects  of  amyl  nitrite.  The  activity  of  the  atten- 
tion and  of  consciousness  in  general  is  rather  to  be  connected  with  the 
functioning  of  certain  nerves,  which  control  those  activities  of  the 
brain  cells  that  are  accompanied  by  psychic  events.  The  appropriate 
analogy  is  that  of  the  glands.  Just  as  we  find  in  these  organs  that 
mere  afflux  of  blood  is  insufficient,  aside  from  the  action  of  certain 
nerves,  to  produce  inception  of  their  secretory  functions,  so  the  brain 
cells  require  blood  for  the  exercise  of  their  peculiar  activities,  but  the 
mere  presence  of  blood  is  not  alone  an  adequate  stimulus  to  such  func- 
tioning.1 

Turning  now  to  Mosso's  observations  on  the  pulse  and  the  heart- 
beat, we  find  the  following  general  principles.  With  the  exception  of 
the  rhythm  and  the  height,  or  amplitude,  the  peculiarities  of  the  pulse 
curve  are  entirely  independent  of  the  heart  and  find  their  explanation 
in  the  changing  conditions  of  the  various  blood  vessels  concerned.2 
The  relations  between  the  energy  and  frequency  of  the  heart-beat  are 
not  as  yet  definitely  formulated.  The  heart-beat  is  ordinarily  slower 
during  sleep  than  at  other  times.  The  pulse  becomes  anacrotic  (Fig. 
i,  A,  after  Mosso)  after  physical  exercise,  after  heating  the  vessels 
and  after  the  inception  of  complete  physical  and  mental  quiet ;  also  as 
the  result  of  hunger.  On  the  other  hand,  intellectual  activity  is  ac- 
companied by  a  catacrotic  pulse  (Fig.  I,  B),  which  is  also  the  form 
observed  after  a  meal.  The  anacrotic  pulse  is  not  peculiar  to  the 

sions  at  least,  of  circulatory  control.  Journal  of  Physiology,  XL,  p.  85.  Cf. 
also  Wertheimer,  Archives  de  Physiologic,  1893,  p.  297.  Gley  has  shown 
that  in  mental  activity  the  flow  of  blood  to  the  brain  is,  as  Mosso  thought,  due 
to  other  causes  than  the  heart.  Etude  experimentale  sur  1'etat  du  pouls,  etc. 
Paris,  1 88 1. 

1  Die  Ermtidung,  p.  195  ff.  Moreover,  it  does  not  appear  that  the  brain  acts 
more  promptly  or  more  accurately  (within  the  limits  of  ordinary  non-patholog- 
ical changes  of  volume)  when  it  is  flushed  with  blood.  Patrizi  has  found  the 
reaction  time  at  the  height  of  undulations  in  volume  very  slightly  better  than 
that  at  the  lowest  point  of  such  oscillations.  Cf.  Patrizi,  Archiv  d.  Psichia- 
tria,  1896. 

2Kreislauf  d.  Blutes,  p.  49. 


3 8  /.   R-   AN G ELL  AND  H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

brain,  but  is  found  under  certain  conditions  in  other  parts  of  the  body.1 
The  changes  in  the  form  of  the  brain  pulse  are  noticeable  only  when 
vigorous  mental  activity  is  contrasted  with  complete  rest.  Intense  in- 
tellective processes  are  accompanied  by  increased  force  of  the  heart- 
beat, probably  because  of  the  contraction  of  peripheral  vessels  neces- 
sitating a  greater  power  to  propel  the  blood  through  them.2  Changes 
in  the  heart-beat  are  not  always  results  of  changes  in  the  respiration, 
for  they  occur  independently  of  such  changes.8 

Apart  from  the  changes  already  mentioned  in  connection  with  the 
circulation,  Mosso's  statements  about  the  respiratory  accompaniments 
of  psychic  processes  are  somewhat  unsatisfactory.  In  his  book  on 
fatigue  he  says,  that  observations  upon  himself  show  that  revery  is 
accompanied  by  faster  breathing  than  voluntarily  directed  trains  of 
thought.4  When  one  does  not  attend  closely,  the  diaphragm  tends  to 
become  quiet  and  the  thorax  makes  larger  but  irregular  movements. 
In  sleep  the  diaphragm  is  probably  passive,  but  periodic  changes  occur 
under  the  effects  of  drowsiness.  In  an  earlier  work,  however,  he  says 
it  is  impossible  to  make  any  satisfactory  classification  of  breathing 
types  as  connected  with  mental  activity,  and  some  of  his  diagrams 
certainly  conform  but  poorly  to  his  formulation  above  quoted.5 

M.  Fere",  in  his  treatise  on  sensation  and  movement,  gives  the  first 
definite  statement  of  antithetical  physiological  processes  as  the  accom- 
paniments of  agreeable  and  disagreeable  experiences  respectively.6  He 
differs  from  Mosso  in  finding  certain  sensory  stimulations  of  emotional 
tone,  which  cause  dilations  of  the  peripheral  vessels,  instead  of  contrac- 
tions. As  is  well  known,  he  connects  agreeable  experiences  of  vari- 

1  These  statements  may  be  verified  by  reference  to  Kreislauf  d.  Blutes,  etc., 
pp.  52-58,  IH- 

2  Die  Ermudung,  p.  184. 

3  Die  Temperatur  d.  Gehirns,  p.  150.    There  are,  however,  certain  well-recog- 
nized changes  in  the  heart-beat,  as  well  as  in  the  blood  pressure  and  volume, 
which  are  due  to  respiration.     The  beats  corresponding  to  inspiration  are  some- 
what quicker  than  the  others,  and  the  amplitude  of  the  pulse  seems  somewhat 
smaller.     Binet  and  Henri  (ibid.,  p.  50)  have  called  attention  to  similar  rhyth- 
mic changes  occurring  at  intervals  of  three  or  four  respiratory  movements. 

4  Die  Ermudung,  p.  182  ff.     The  description  of  the  conditions  under  which 
these  observations  were  made  is  too  inadequate  to  permit  satisfactory  compari- 
son with  the  work  of  other  investigators. 

5Cf.  Kreislauf  d.  Blutes,  etc.,  p.  70  ff.  The  irregularities  in  the  breathing 
which  he  meets  with  in  mental  calculations  are  probably  due  to  the  distinctly 
abnormal  conditions  of  his  subjects. 

6 Sensation  et  Mouvement,  Paris,  1887.  He  uses  the  words  'exciting'  and 
'depressing'  instead  of  agreeable  and  disagreeable,  but  his  meaning  seems  to 
be  essentially  as  indicated. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  39 

ous  kinds  with  such  dilations  of  the  peripheral  blood  vessels  and  with 
heightened  tone  of  the  voluntary  muscles.  Disagreeable  experiences 
he  finds  accompanied  by  the  opposite  conditions  of  peripheral  con- 
striction and  lowered  muscular  tone.1  He  finds  momentary  intellect- 
ual activity  accompanied  by  momentary  increase  of  power  in  the 
voluntary  muscles.2  His  monograph  is  too  inadequate  in  its  state- 
ment of  details  to  warrant  critical  comparison  with  the  more  complete 
investigations  now  at  hand.  It  has  distinct  historical  importance, 
however,  because  its  statements,  like  those  of  the  next  author  we  shall 
mention,  have  been  somewhat  dogmatically  incorporated  in  recent 
psychological  treatises. 

A.  Lehmann,  in  his  scholarly  treatment  of  feeling,  reports  with 
much  fullness  his  observations  on  the  physiological  accompaniments  of 
agreeable  and  disagreeable  experiences.3  These  agree  essentially  with 
those  of  Fere,  but  emphasize  the  following  facts.4  Pleasurable  experi- 
ences are  probably  accompanied  by  increased  amplitude  of  heart  move- 
ments, disagreeable  experiences  by  decreased  amplitude  of  these  move- 
ments and  ordinarily  by  dilation  of  the  deep-lying  blood  vessels.  He 
also  emphasizes  more  explicitly  than  Fere  the  deeper  and  more  super- 
ficial phases  of  the  breathing  which  he  finds  characterizing  the  two 
antitheses  of  feeling.5 

Probably  the  most  careful,  systematic  and  important  experiments, 
after  those  of  Mosso,  are  those  conducted  by  Binet  in  conjunction 
with  Henri,  Courtier  and  Vaschide.  However  much  one  may  take 
issue  with  their  usually  conservative  generalizations — and  this  is  cer- 
tainly the  least  convincing  part  of  their  work — one  cannot  abstain  from 
the  expression  of  admiration  for  the  shrewd  ingenuity  and  foresight 
with  which  they  have  executed  their  tasks.6 

xCf.  ibid.,  p.  noff.  and  p.  7. 

2 The  experiments  of  Patrizi  (quoted  by  Binet  et  Henri,  loc.  cit.,  p.  194) 
showed  that  mental  work  carried  on  for  an  hour  weakened  the  power  of  the 
voluntary  muscles,  unless  there  was  some  emotional  excitement  involved,  in 
which  case  increased  power  was  observed.  In  the  last  case,  however,  after  a 
time  the  muscular  strength  fell  below  the  normal. 

3  Hauptgesetze  d.  Mensch.  Gefiihlslebens,  translated  by  Bendixen,  Leipzig, 
1892. 

<Ibid.,  p.  82  ff. 

5Lehmann's  results,  which  were  obtained  by  experiments  upon  five  persons, 
certainly  require  confirmation.  Like  Fare's,  they  differ  in  the  manner  pointed 
out  above  from  the  results  of  Mosso,  and  they  are  distinctly  at  variance  with 
many  results  obtained  by  recent  investigators,  not  to  mention  our  own. 

6  It  will  be  convenient  to  refer  in  connection  with  these  authors  to  a  certain 
amount  of  the  recent  monograph  literature,  much  of  which  is  canvassed  by 
them. 


40  J.   JR.  AN  CELL  AND  H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

They  find  that  vaso-constriction  of  the  peripheral  blood  vessels  is 
the  usual  result  of  psychic  activity  of  any  sort,  especially  when  this 
follows  relatively  greater  quiet.1  There  does  not  seem  to  be  any  con- 
stant and  demonstrable  relation  between  agreeable  and  disagreeable  ex- 
periences on  the  psychic  side  and  vaso-dilation  and  constriction  on  the 
physiological  side.  Pain  has  been  observed  to  cause  a  dilation  under 
certain  peculiar  conditions,  and  moderate  pleasure  has  on  several  oc- 
casions been  accompanied  by  constrictions.2  The  true  psychic  oppo- 
sites  from  this  point  of  view  seem  to  be  repose  and  activity  with  vary- 
ing degrees  of  physiological  excitation  as  their  counterparts.3  When 
attention  is  vigorously  fixed  on  a  calculation,  for  example,  there  is 
sometimes  a  dilation,  whose  nature  is  not  known,  and  sometimes  a 
constriction  of  greater  or  less  duration.* 

1This  agrees  with  Mosso.     See  above. 

2Binet  et  Courtier,  L?Ann&e  Psychologique,  1897,  p.  87  ff.,  also  p.  126; 
Binet  et  Henri,  ibid.,  p.  92. 

Cf.  also  Patrizi,  ibid.  Rivista  di  Freniatria,  etc.,  1897.  We  know  these 
articles  only  from  reports. 

Shields  finds  vaso-constriction  of  periphery  with  both  agreeable  and  dis- 
agreeable odors — Journal  of  Experimental  Medicine,  1896. 

Dumas,  Revue  Philosophiqtie,  1896,  also  1897.  Dumas'  investigations  with 
morbid  and  insane  cases  confirm  in  general  the  antithetical  relations  formulated 
by  Lehmann  and  others  regarding  joy  and  sadness  and  the  physiological  ex- 
expressions  of  dilation,  constriction,  etc.;  adding  some  interesting  observations 
on  the  changing  number  of  blood  corpuscles  under  these  conditions.  He  meets 
curious  exceptions,  however. 

Sewall  and  Sanford,  studying  changes  of  volume  in  the  forearm  under  vari- 
ous forms  of  electrical,  mechanical  and  thermal  stimulation,  found  that  strong 
stimulations  generally  produced  constriction,  whereas  weak  stimulations  gave 
slight  dilations  after  transitory  constrictions — Journal  of  Physiology,  XL,  p. 
179  ff. 

3  The  very  interesting  experiments  of  Howell  on  sleep,  already  referred 
to,  furnish  beautiful  supplements  to  Mosso's  observations,  and  show  that  in 
normal  sleep  there  is  first  a  rapid  decrease  of  blood  in  the  brain,  owing  to  fall 
in  arterial  pressure  (chiefly  in  the  periphery,  it  appears)  with  flooding  of  the 
peripheral  vessels.  This  is  followed  by  a  period  of  relative  quiet,  and  then  the 
pressure  gradually  rises,  the  peripheral  vessels  undergo  constriction  and  finally 
awakening  occurs.  He  regards  the  fatigue  of  the  vaso-motor  mechanism  as  the 
immediate  cause  of  sleep.  He  is  inclined  to  disagree  with  Mosso  concerning 
an  independent  vaso-motor  mechanism  of  the  brain. 

4MacDougall,  in  his  article  on  the  Physical  Characteristics  of  Attention 
(PSYCHOL.  REVIEW,  3-158),  practically  agrees  with  the  French  observers,  of 
whom  we  are  writing,  as  regards  the  volume  changes  here  referred  to.  Under 
the  head  of  '  pulse  and  volume  changes '  appearing  when  attention  is  focussed 
on  a  continuous  sensory  stimulus,  he  omits  any  definite  reference  to  the  second 
part  of  his  paragraph  title,  so  we  cannot  record  his  results.  With  what  he  calls 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  41 

Short,  intense  mental  application — e.  g.,  the  solution  of  a  mathe- 
matical problem  extending  over  three  or  four  minutes — almost  invari- 
ably increases  the  rate  of  the  heart-beat.1  After  the  cessation  of  the 
work,  this  acceleration  may  continue,  or  there  may  be  a  reaction  toward 
a  rate  slower  than  the  original  one.  The  effects  of  long  mental  effort 
are  less  well  known,  but  there  seems  to  be  an  increased  tendency 
toward  slowing  of  the  heart-beat,  when  compared  with  the  natural 
tendency  to  retardation  during  the  later  hours  of  the  day  and  in  gen- 
eral under  increasing  fatigue.2  Emotions  of  every  kind,  practically 
without  exception,  produce  increase  in  the  rate  of  the  heart-beat.  A 
few  rare  cases  of  pain  and  sadness  have  been  observed  to  produce  a 
gentle  slowing  of  the  rate.  In  general  the  changes  observed,  not  only 
on  the  heart,  but  also  on  the  other  organic  processes  under  considera- 
tion, show  much  more  dependence  upon  the  intensity  of  the  emotion 
or  affective  condition  than  upon  the  quality  as  agreeable  or  disagree- 
able.3 

1  perceptual  attention '  he  obtains  first  constrictions  and  then  periodic  fluctua- 
tions of  dilations  and  constrictions.  These  undulations  appear  under  several 
of  the  conditions  he  has  studied,  e.g.,  attention  to  calculations,  recalling  of 
past  experiences,  and  continued  sense  impressions. 

1  This  has  been  noticed  by  a  number  of  investigators,  Cf.  La  Fatigue  Intel- 
lectuelle,  p.  41  ff.  Mentz  (Phil.  Studien,  XL,  p.  567  ff.)  reports  a  quickening  of 
the  pulse  which  seems  closely  related  in  its  rate  to  the  difficulty  of  the  task  un- 
dertaken. 

Moderate  physical  exercise  generally  increases  the  rate  and  force  of  the 
heart-beat,  but  where  excessive  a  contrary  effect  may  be  produced.  The  changes 
under  physical  exercise  are,  perhaps,  due  more  immediately  to  alterations  of 
blood  pressure,  which  Marey  has  shown  may  by  merely  mechanical  means  affect 
the  rate  of  the  heart.  In  mental  activity  the  pressure  seems  to  rise,  and  as  this 
alone  should,  on  the  grounds  of  merely  mechanical  explanations,  decrease  the 
rate,  it  is  probable  we  have  here  a  direct  nervous  control.  Cf .  La  Fatigue  Intell. , 
p.  37  ff.  and  58.  Mentz  finds  (Cf.  ibid.,  pp.83,  95,  101)  that  auditory  stimuli, 
•whether  noises  or  tones,  produce  at  first  slowing  of  the  pulse  and  then  a  gradual 
quickening.  Changes  in  intensity  show  the  same  result,  the  quickening  begin- 
ning at  the  point  where  the  stimulus  becomes  disagreeable.  With  involuntary 
attention  acoustic  stimuli  were  found  to  produce  slowing,  with  voluntary  atten- 
tion quickening  of  the  pulse.  MacDougall  (ibid.,  pp.  163,  169)  obtained,  with 
voluntary  perceptual  attention,  increase  of  heart  rate,  with  continuous  sensory 
stimuli  (tracing  of  figures  on  the  face)  slowing.  The  cases  of  retardation  in  the 
heart-beat  reported  by  both  these  investigators  seem  to  lend  themselves  with 
difficulty  to  harmonious  incorporation  in  the  observations  and  hypotheses  of 
Binet  and  his  fellow  workers.  They  agree  with  our  own  observations,  however. 

2 The  capillary  pulse  may  almost  disappear  under  these  conditions.  It  has 
been  suggested  that  this  is  due  to  increased  pressure.  If  true,  this  fact  would 
seem  to  present  a  rather  troublesome  anomaly  for  Howell's  interesting  theory  of 
sleep,  elsewhere  referred  to.  Cf.  Binet  et  Henri,  loc.  cit.,  p.  96  ff. 

3  Binet  et  Courtier,  U  Annde  Psychologique,  1897,  pp.  104,  125-126. 


42  /.    R.  ANGELL  AND  H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

Mental  work  when  intense  shows  a  tendency  to  alter  the  form  of 
the  capillary  pulse  curve  by  decreasing  its  amplitude  and  with  some 
persons  rendering  its  angles  blunter,  while  the  dicrotic  may  move  up- 
ward or  shrink.  With  others  there  is  instead  of  this  a  distinct  em- 
phasizing of  the  dicrotic  and  no  noticeable  decrease  in  angularity.1 
Conditions  of  quiet  and  repose  are  ordinarily  accompanied  by  a  pulse 
of  large  amplitude  with  clear  dicrotic.  It  is  possible  that  a  classifica- 
tion of  the  emotions  may  prove  to  be  feasible  on  the  basis  of  the 
changes  of  the  pulse,  but  this  is  hypothetical. 

The  blood  pressure  probably  rises  under  every  mental  excitation, 
whether  the  occasion  be  attention  to  a  sensation,  to  a  calculation  or  to 
an  emotion. 2  Nor  does  the  nature  of  the  emotion  apparently  affect 
the  fact  of  this  rise,  although  it  may  show  a  difference  in  the  degree 
of  the  latter. 

The  rate  of  respiration  is  increased  by  mental  work  of  every  kind, 
both  the  expiration  and  the  expiratory  pause  being  shortened,  emotions 
producing  an  increased  amplitude  in  the  respiratory  curve,  mental  cal- 
culations and  the  like  producing  more  superficial  breathing,  with  de- 
crease of  amplitude  in  the  curve.  Occasionally  sadness  produces  a 
slowing  of  respiration.3  The  effects  of  emotional  states  are,  however, 
relatively  irregular. 

1  Gley  (ibid. )  finds  mental  work  increases  the  amplitude  of  the  carotid  pulse 
and  accentuates  the  dicrotic.  Binet  et  Henri  (ibid.),  p.  98  ff.,  also  113  and  120 
ff.  Binet  et  Courtier  (ibid. ),  pp.  30-65.  Physical  exercise  of  a  violent  type 
seems  to  lessen  the  amplitude  of  the  pulse  and  to  diminish  the  clearness  of  the 
dicrotic. 

2Kiesow's  observation  (Philos.  Studien,  1895)  that  changes  in  blood  pres- 
sure are  noticeable  only  in  connection  with  affective  psychic  conditions  is  criti- 
cised on  the  ground  of  inadequate  technique. 

3  Binet  et  Henri,  ibid.,  p.  156  ff.     Binet  et  Courtier,  ibid.,  p.  65. 

Delabarre  (JRevue  Philosophique ,  Vol.  XXXIII.,  p.  639  ff.)  found  that  per- 
sons who  naturally  breathe  rapidly  show  relatively  little  effect  on  their  respira- 
tion when  their  attention  is  engaged  ;  but  persons  who  ordinarily  breathe 
slowly  display  a  distinct  tendency  to  acceleration  of  respiration  when  exer- 
cising their  attention,  the  acceleration  seeming  to  bear  a  general  relation  to 
the  measure  in  which,  the  attention  is  exercised. 

MacDougall  (ibid.)  found  that  with  perceptual  and  sensory  attention  there 
are  generally  increased  rapidity  and  superficiality  of  respiration.  The  long  in- 
spiration and  short  expiration  of  sleep  and  relaxed  inattention  give  way  to 
lengthening  of  the  time  occupied  by  the  second  factor  and  shortening  of  the 
time  of  the  first.  The  effects  on  the  respiratory  pause  are  ambiguous.  Calcu- 
lation produces  the  same  general  changes  found  by  the  French  investigators. 
Recall  of  past  events,  when  tinged  with  emotional  excitation,  is  productive  of 
great  irregularity  of  amplitude  and  form,  although  the  increase  of  rate  is  still 
observed. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  43 

Like  ourselves,  these  investigators  have  been  relatively  less  inter- 
ested in  the  effects  of  psychological  conditions  upon  the  voluntary 
muscles.  Mental  activity  certainly  affects  the  muscles,  but  the  effects 
differ,  depending  on  the  length  of  time  devoted  to  the  psychic  process 
and  on  the  presence  or  absence  of  an  emotional  tone  in  the  experi- 
ence.1 

III.  THEORETICAL  CONSIDERATIONS.2 

It  will  be  observed  that  the  investigations  which  we  have 
been  reviewing  deal  with  two  separate  problems.  The  first 
problem  concerns  the  differences  in  circulation,  respiration  and 
muscular  tone  which  characterize  the  antithetical  affective  con- 
ditions denominated  respectively  agreeable  and  disagreeable. 
The  second  has  to  do  with  the  differences  manifested  by  these 
physiological  activities  under  the  various  typical  psychological 
conditions,  e.  £*.,  sensation,  intellection,  etc.,  and  more  espe- 
cially with  the  differences  distinguishing  the  affective  from  the 
non-affective  processes.  It  is  unnecessary  to  emphasize  the  lack 
of  any  established  general  principle  of  correlation  for  the  re- 
sults of  these  various  investigations,  much  less  to  dwell  upon  the 
disagreements  in  regard  to  details. 

Mentz  (ibid. ).  In  general  the  breathing  tends  to  follow  the  rate  of  the  pulse 
reported  above.  The  strong  tendency  of  heart  and  respiration  to  change  rate 
together  and  in  the  same  direction  has  been  noticed  repeatedly.  The  intimate 
nature  of  the  connection  is  unknown. 

Lehmann's  interesting  observations  (Philos.  Studien,  Vol.  IX.,  p.  66)  on 
the  fluctuations  of  attention  and  the  different  phases  of  respiration  seem  to  show 
that  the  moment  of  completed  inspiration,  when  the  volume  and  pressure  of 
the  blood  in  the  brain  are  at  a  maximum,  is  most  favorable  for  mental  activity. 
Needless  to  say,  this  does  not  altogether  agree  with  Patrizi's  observations. 
r  -  Whipple  has  found  (Amer.Jour.  of  Psychology,  1898,  p.  560)  that  forced 
respiration  seems  to  assist  muscular  activities,  but  to  interfere  with  psychic  pro- 
cesses and  the  functions  of  the  higher  centers. 

^astrow  (Amer.  Jour,  of  Psycho  I.,  IV.,  398  ;  V.,  223)  and  Tucker  (Arner. 
Journal  of  Psychol.,  VIII.,  394)  have  studied  the  nature  and  direction  of  cer- 
tain unconscious  movements  of  the  voluntary  muscles  connected  with  different 
psychological  processes.  Heiurich  (Zeits.  fur  Psycho 1.  und  Physio I.  d.  Sinnes- 
o-rgane,  IX.,  342  ;  XI.,  410)  and  Mentz  (ibid.)  have  found  that  with  mental 
calculations  the  pupils  dilate,  the  lenses  become  flat  and  the  eyes  assume  nearly 
parallel  axes. 

2  Logically  and  chronologically,  Section  IV.  of  the  paper  dealing  with  our 
own  experiments  should  precede  Section  III  ,  for  the  views  defended  here  are 
based  on  the  observations  therein  reported.  The  present  order  is  adopted  in  the 
interests  of  brevity  and  clearness  in  presentation. 


44  /•   -ff-   ANGEL L  AND  H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

If  we  knew  the  precise  significance  in  terms  of  organic  me- 
tabolisms of  such  processes  as  constriction  and  dilation,  we  might 
hope  to  build  up  a  theory  on  the  basis  of  such  knowledge.  Un- 
fortunately, this  is  not  the  case.  Furthermore,  we  have  seen 
that  various  observers  have  failed  to  note  any  uniform  connec- 
tion of  these  processes  with  pleasure  and  pain,  in  which  condi- 
tions the  *  vitality  '  theories  would  find  the  reflection  of  organic 
weal  and  woe.  We  find  ourselves  thrown  back  then  upon  some 
general  view  of  the  organism  as  a  whole,  if  we  desire  a  prin- 
ciple of  interpretation  for  the  phenomena  concerned. 

Such  a  view  is  offered  us  by  the  ordinary  evolutionary  doc- 
trine, which  finds  the  essential  problem  of  the  organism  in  the 
adapting  of  itself  to  an  environment.  This  adaptation  must 
involve  on  its  physiological  side  metabolisms  of  various  kinds,  in 
which  katabolisms  and  anabolisms  must  sustain  certain  fairly 
definite  relations  of  dynamic  equilibrium,  provided  the  life  pro- 
cess is  to  be  subserved. 

If  we  make  reference  to  any  one  region  or  to  any  one  pro- 
cess, the  exact  relations  of  these  antithetic  metabolisms  must  be 
constantly  changing.  Slight  excesses  of  wastage  at  one  point 
and  one  period  will  be  offset  by  repair  at  a  later  period.  The 
variations  from  equilibrium  must  in  conditions  of  health  be  rela- 
tively insignificant,  in  order  to  permit  of  elastic  response  to  the 
demands  of  the  total  environment.  Moreover,  these  adaptive 
processes  must  be  constantly  in  progress  and  must  accompany 
the  psychological  conditions  called  intellective  quite  as  truly  as 
those  called  affective.  Having  regard,  therefore,  to  the  very 
various  circumstances  in  which  the  organism  is  called  upon  to 
respond  to  changing  stimulations,  it  seems  at  least  possible  that 
the  regularity  with  which  these  metabolic  processes  progress, 
rather  than  the  presence  or  absence  of  any  one  feature  in  the 
process,  should  be  the  most  characteristic  expression  of  the 
total  organic  condition.  Certainly  the  presumption  that  a  psy- 
chological process  like  pleasure  in  its  multiform  phases  should, 
regardless  of  its  concomitant  mental  conditions,  be  accompanied 
invariably  by  a  single  physiological  process  like  dilation,  im- 
plies a  simplicity  of  structure  and  function  in  the  psycho-phys- 
ical organism  and  a  constancy  of  organic  and  environmental 
conditions  which  probably  do  not  exist. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  45 

In  view  of  such  considerations  our  experimental  observa- 
tions lead  us  to  believe  that  the  changes  in  circulation  and  res- 
piration which  accompany  alterations  of  consciousness  can  be 
formulated  in  terms  of  attention  as  follows  : 

When  the  attentive  process  runs  smoothly  and  uninterrupt- 
edly, these  bodily  activities  progress  with  rhythmic  regularity.1 
Relatively  tense,  strained  attention  is  generally  characterized  by 
more  vigorous  bodily  accompaniments  than  is  low-level,  gentle 
and  relatively  relaxed  attention  (of  drowsiness,  for  instance)  ; 
but  both  agree,  so  long  as  their  progress  is  free  and  unimpeded, 
in  relative  regularity  of  bodily  functions.  Breaks,  shocks  and 
mal-coordinations  of  attention  are  accompanied  by  sudden, 
spasmodic  changes  and  irregularities  in  bodily  processes,  the 
amount  and  violence  of  such  changes  being  roughly  propor- 
tional to  the  intensity  of  the  experience.2 

In  order  to  make  clear  the  application  of  this  hypothesis  to 
the  facts  at  issue,  we  must  analyze  briefly  the  mental  conditions 
concerned  with  reference  to  the  attention.  We  shall  need  to 
consider  the  following:  (i)  Emotions  of  various  kinds.  (2) 
Sensations  both  feeble  and  intense,  both  expected  and  un- 
expected, both  transitory  and  continuous,  both  agreeable  and 
disagreeable.  (3)  Intellective  processes  involving  memorizing, 
recalling  and  reasoning  in  the  narrow  sense,  e.  g:,  mathematical 
calculations ;  also  revery. 

Now,  emotions  represent  psychological  conditions  of  great 
instability.  Especially  is  this  true  when  the  emotion  is  profound. 
The  necessity  is  suddenly  thrown  upon  the  organism  of  react- 

1  To  prevent  tedious  repetition  we  shall  hereafter,  except  when  otherwise 
stated,  use  the  phrases  'bodily  activities,'  'bodily  processes,'  'functions,'  etc., 
to  mean  respiration  and  circulation. 

2  It  will  be  remembered  that  the  fundamental  antithesis  found  by  Binet  and 
his  co-workers  is  that  of  mental  activity  in  general  as  against  mental  passivity. 
In  apparently  abandoning  any  one  physiological  change  like  vaso-constriction 
or  increased  rate  of  respiration  as  a  criterion,  of  the  psychological   condition, 
we  do  not  mean  to  imply,  even  tacitly,  that  no  single  change  of  such  character 
is  an  essentially  constant  companion  of  any  one  psychological  process,  like  the 
emotion  of  anger,  for  instance.     We  simply  emphasize  the  apparent  absence  of 
any  such  change  as  an  invariable  index  of  more  than  one  or  two  conditions, 
whereas  the  changes  as  we  formulate  them  appear  to  be  constant  for  all  condi- 
tions.    The  experimental  portion  of  the  paper  will  bring  this  point  out  more 
fully. 


46  /.   /?.   ANGELL   AND   H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

ing  to  a  situation  with  which  it  is  at  the  moment  able  to  cope 
only  imperfectly,  if  at  all.  The  condition  is  one  in  which  nor- 
mal, uninterrupted,  coordinated  movements  are  for  a  time 
checked  and  thrown  out  of  gear.1  Equally  spasmodic  and  in- 
terrupted is  the  activity  of  attention.  It  may  on  the  other  hand 
be  asserted,  in  opposition  to  this  view,  that  never  is  attention  so 
monopolized  and  completely  absorbed  by  a  situation  as  in  the 
case  of  a  deep  emotion.  But  this  is  to  overlook  the  cataclys- 
mic change  at  the  outset  of  the  emotion,  as  well  as  the  violently 
recurrent  rhythms  with  which  the  situation  is  surveyed.2  In  no 
strict  sense  does  the  attention  ever  delay  long  with  absolutely 
one  phase  of  an  idea,3  and  by  so  much  as  the  profound  emo- 
tions are  more  intense  than  the  ordinary  experiences  of  life,  by 
so  much  are  the  shifts  in  attention  more  violent  than  usual. 

Moreover,  affective  conditions  of  every  kind  show  their  af- 
finity with  the  emotions  by  a  similar  instability  of  attention. 
This  instability  is  far  less  with  agreeable  experiences  than  with 
disagreeable  ones.  This  may  be  connected  with  the  fact,  made 
much  of  by  some  psychologists,  that  pleasure  represents  a  ten- 
dency to  persist  and  pain  a  tendency  to  change.4  It  calls  to 
mind  also  the  theories  of  pleasure  as  associated  with  normal  and 
moderate  activities,  and  pain  as  associated  with  excessive  activi- 
ties.5 But  whenever  the  experiences  are  very  intense  we  meet, 

]Cf.  Dewey,  'Theory  of  the  Emotions,'  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  Vols.  I. 
and  II. 

2  It  may  at  first  sight  appear  that,  however  fairly  this  description  applies  to 
the  more  tempestuous  emotions,  like  anger,  it  is  seriously  defective  when  ap- 
plied to  some  of  the  semi-morbid  phases  of  grief  and  depression.     Waiving 
the  justice  of  the  criticism  of  this  characterization  of  the  play  of  attention  in 
the  depressive  emotions  (we  think  the  apparent  difference  of  opinion  rests  on  a 
confusion  of  attention  to  a  topic  of  thought  with  attention  to  a  single  image),  we 
may  simply  reiterate,  that  our  observations  indicate  that  the  bodily  changes 
run  parallel,  as  regards  their  regularity  or  irregularity,  with  the  mode  in  which 
attention  proceeds.     In  general  the  emotions  show  a  much  disturbed  condition 
in  this  particular.     But  for  us  this  is  more  or  less  of  an  accident,  and  our  con- 
tention would  be  in  no  wise  affected  if  emotions  showed  a  precisely  contrary 
condition,  provided  attention  also  changed  its  characteristics. 

3  Cf.  James,  Prin.  of  Psy.,  Vol.  L,  p.  421.     Ribot's  Psychol.  of  Attention 
presents  a  thoroughgoing  account  of  attention  as  '  monoideism.'    The  effects 
of  neural  fatigue  would  forbid  any  long-continued  dwelling  upon  literally  one 
idea.     Cf.  Hylan,  'Attention,'  Monograph,  PSYCHOI,.  REVIEW,  1897. 

*  Stephen,  Science  of  Ethics.     Horwicz,  Psychol.  Analysen. 
6  Spencer,  Prin.  of  Psychology. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  47 

at  the  moment  of  their  initiation  at  least,  with  relative  instability 
of  attention,  though  the  continuance  of  this  instability  is  incom- 
parably more  marked  with  the  unpleasant  states  than  with  the 
pleasant  ones.1  This  is  tantamount,  of  course,  to  saying  that 
the  whole  distinction  is  relative. 

The  different  conditions  of  attention  under  which  sensations 
may  be  experienced  vary  rather  more  widely  than  those  of 
emotions,  so  that  if  we  had  regard  only  to  the  fact  of  the  pres- 
ence of  a  sensation,  we  might  fallaciously  assume  a  uniformity 
of  conditions  which  does  not  exist.  What  we  have  said  of  af- 
fective conditions  in  general,  in  the  previous  paragraph,  holds 
equally  true  when  these  affective  experiences  have  a  sensation 
as  their  basis,  and  need  not  be  repeated  here. 

The  distinction  between  expected  and  unexpected  transitory 
sensations  is  one  of  considerable  import  for  our  interpretation.2 
This  is  the  more  true  the  more  powerful  the  sensory  stimulus 
employed.  It  becomes  relatively  insignificant  as  such  stimuli 
approach  the  limen.  The  effect  of  an  expected  sensation  upon 
attention  will,  if  the  sensation  be  not  so  intense  as  to  produce 
shock,  nor  so  feeble  as  to  require  excessive  effort  to  detect  it, 
be  the  securing  of  a  slight  strain  of  anticipation,  with  at  times  a 
somewhat  definite  relaxation  when  the  sensation  is  felt.  On  the 
whole  the  play  of  attention  is  relatively  free  and  unimpeded. 
When  the  stimulus  is  so  faint  as  to  require  great  concentration 
we  may  get  more  irregularities,  owing  to  the  fluctuations  of  at- 
tention from  fatigue,  distraction,  etc.  But  still  the  conditions 
are  relatively  stable.  With  the  very  intense  stimulus,  whether 
expected  or  not,  there  is  sure  to  be  something  approaching  shock, 
and  with  this  the  introduction  of  a  distinctly  disagreeable  affec- 

1  Ward's  formulation  of  pleasure  and  pain  in  terms  of  the  effectiveness  of 
attention  has  much  that  is  allied  with  the  view  we  are  presenting.     It  does  not, 
however,  seem  to  do  full  justice  to  the  neutral-toned  consciousness  of  moderate 
intellectual  labor,  where  attention  is  apparently  exercised  with  distinct  effec- 
tiveness.    (Cf.  Ency.  Brit.,  article  'Psychology.') 

2  The  conditions  involved  in  expected  and  unexpected  sensations  approxi- 
mate closely  those  of  voluntary  and  involuntary  sensory  attention  (cf.  Mentz, 
ibid.).    The  so-called  cases  of  involuntary  sensory  attention  are  such  as  occur 
when  a  stimulus  succeeds  in  breaking  in  upon  a  condition  of  mental  pre-occu- 
pation,  whether  one  be  engaged  in  intense  thought  processes  or  in  some  of  the 
various  forms  of  revery.      We  cover  both  these  cases,  but  do   not  use  this 
terminology. 


4§  /•    R.  ANGELL  AND  H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

tive  condition,  whose  consequences  we  have  already  canvassed. 
Indeed,  a  sensory  stimulus  of  very  moderate  intensity  may,  if 
unexpected,  produce  this  shock  in  a  rudimentary  way,  and  this 
more  violent  disturbance  to  attention  is  the  principal  difference 
noticed  between  the  expected  and  the  unexpected  sensation. 
With  many  unexpected  sensations  this  shock  may  practically 
disappear.  The  process  going  on  at  the  time  the  stimulus  is 
given  will  determine  in  large  measure  its  effectiveness  or  in- 
effectiveness in  producing  such  shock. 

Sensations  which  are  continuous,  provided  they  be  not  very 
intense,  produce  conditions  of  attention  which  are  relatively  reg- 
ular and  stable.  We  speak  here  of  the  cases  in  which  atten- 
tion is  intentionally  fixed  on  the  sensations.  If  continued  long, 
we  shall  get  rather  definite  fluctuations  of  attention,  but  these 
need  not  be  violent  within  any  ordinary  limit  of  time.  Sooner 
or  later  we  should  meet  total  collapse  of  attention,  preceded  by 
the  phenomena  of  mal-coordination  that  accompany  fatigue. 
Continuous  sensations,  which  are  not  made  definite  objects  of 
attention,  produce  very  various  results,  sometimes  being  rela- 
tively ineffective  and  at  other  times  seeming  to  modify  materi- 
ally the  attentive  process.  The  psychological  conditions  in- 
volved appear  too  ambiguous  to  warrant  laying  much  stress  on 
these  cases.1  A  series  of  very  intense  sensations,  or  a  really 
continuous  sensation  of  this  kind,  will  produce,  as  in  the  case 
of  the  transitory  sensation,  distinct  shock  and  its  disturbing  con- 
sequences for  attention. 

From  the  standpoint  of  attention  the  intellective  processes 
involved  in  memorizing  and  in  simple  mathematical  calculations 
have  much  of  affinity  with  the  continuous  sensation  and  repre- 
sent relative  stability  and  regularity.  If  the  task  becomes  too 
confused,  as  it  may  when  one  is  required  to  multiply  mentally 
one  three-place  number  by  another,  then  we  may  meet  with 
breaks  and  irregularities  in  attention.  Moreover,  we  shall  often 
find  that  such  experiences  are  accompanied  by  a  slight  feeling 
of  anxiety  and  distress,  springing  from  the  interest  in  accom- 

*Cf.  Mentz  (ibid.).  The  chief  difficulty  in  these  instances  arises  from  at- 
tempting to  apportion  the  responsibility  for  the  changes  observed  between  the 
existing  mental  processes,  into  which  the  continuous  sensation  is  supposed  at 
times  to  inject  itself,  and  the  sensation  itself. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  49 

plishing  the  work  promptly  and  correctly.  Where  this  element 
enters  to  any  degree,  we  may  look  for  the  characteristics  of 
emotion.  Indeed,  we  may  properly  remark  in  this  connection 
that  under  ordinary  conditions  these  processes,  which  we  are 
analyzing  separately,  necessarily  overlap  one  another  at  times. 
The  mental  application  in  the  case  of  the  intellective  processes 
is  usually  to  problems  received  from  sensory  sources,  visual,  au- 
ditory, etc.  The  sensations  impinge  upon.already  existing  affec- 
tive and  intellective  conditions,  and  emotions  are,  with  the  best  of 
intentions  on  the  part  of  the  experimenters  and  subjects,  likely 
to  intrude  themselves  in  some  measure  upon  all  the  processes 
studied.  When  the  attention  is  relatively  strained  and  tense, 
we  meet  the  greatest  stability  and  regularity,  if  the  task  in  hand 
is  just  difficult  enough  to  be  successfully  carried  forward  at  the 
rate  at  which  new  aspects  of  it  open  up.  Thus  we  may  obtain 
great  regularity  of  functioning,  if  series  of  problems  in  addi- 
tion or  multiplication  are  presented  at  just  that  rate  which  per- 
mits their  most  rapid  solution,  avoiding  on  the  one  hand  unoc- 
cupied leisure  between  the  problems,  and  on  the  other  hand 
insufficient  time  for  completing  them. 

The  cases  in  which  one  attempts  to  recall  past  events  show 
considerable  variations,  depending  on  the  nature  of  the  subject- 
matter  recalled.  Verbal  material  which  has  been  learned  by 
heart  may  be  recalled  under  conditions  of  great  stability  and 
regularity  of  attention.  Events,  on  the  other  hand,  may  or  may 
not  be  recalled  readily,  and  if  they  do  not  come  to  mind  easily 
we  shall  get  more  or  less  instability  of  attention,  the  results  de- 
pending on  the  amount  of  effort  put  forth.  Such  processes  are 
especially  prone  to  take  on  emotional  coloring  with  its  tendency 
to  instability. 

Revery,  in  the  proper  sense  of  the  word,  represents  fre- 
quently a  high  degree  of  free  and  regular  play  of  attention, 
interrupted  now  and  then  by  the  emotional  suggestiveness  of 
the  subject  of  thought.  When  revery  passes  over  into  drowsi- 
ness, the  attention  becomes  much  relaxed  and  functions  on  a  low 
level  of  intensity,  but  yet  as  a  rule  with  a  considerable  degree 
of  smoothness.  Individuals  vary  vastly,  however,  in  the  nature 
of  the  revery  process. 


50  /.    R.   ANGELL   AND   H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

If  we  turn  now  and  arrange  our  psychological  conditions  in 
a  hierarchy  representing  increasing  stability  of  attention,  we 
shall  obtain  something  of  this  kind  :  (i)  The  profound  emo- 
tions, presenting  sometimes  an  appearance  of  stability,  but  even 
here  distinctly  of  the  abnormal,  paralytic  type.  (2)  The  more 
violent  affective  conditions,  certainly  the  disagreeable  and  pain- 
ful experiences,  less  confidently  the  instances  of  extremely  pleas- 
urable experiences.  (As  has  often  been  mentioned,  it  is  ex- 
ceedingly difficult  to  produce  very  intense  pleasures  under 
laboratory  conditions.)  (3)  Cases  of  transitory  and  relatively 
superficial  emotions  (including  cases  in  which  emotional  ex- 
citement occurs,  although  the  conditions  are  ostensibly  those  of 
intellective  processes,  e.  g.,  recall  of  past  events)  intermingled 
with  responses  to  unexpected  sensory  stimuli  of  moderate  in- 
tensity and  brief  duration.  Expected  sensations,  if  relatively 
intense,  also  belong  in  this  class,  together  with  many  agreeable 
sensory  experiences.  (4)  Cases  of  continuous  sensations,  the 
regularity  being  greater  in  proportion  to  the  effort  made  to 
attend  and  being,  perhaps,  greatest  with  relatively  weak  sen- 
sations. Mental  application,  as  in  the  case  of  mathematical 
calculations,  when  executed  under  the  most  favorable  conditions 
as  above  described.  Many  cases  of  non-emotional  revery. 
The  revery  of  drowsiness  differs  in  its  type  of  regularity  from 
that  manifested  by  application  to  a  problem,  in  that  one  is  ac- 
companied by  the  phenomena  of  relaxation  and  the  other  by 
those  of  greater  organic  excitation.  But  both  are  relatively 
stable.1 

This  brings  us  to  a  consideration  of  our  experimental  ma- 
terial. After  a  brief  description  of  the  conditions  under  which 
we  have  worked,  apparatus,  etc.,  we  shall  proceed  to  show  how 
radically  the  physiological  accompaniments  of  apparently  sim- 
ilar psychological  conditions  may  vary  from  time  to  time,  de- 
pending on  the  manner  in  which  attention  functions.  It  should 

1  It  will  be  understood  that  this  classification  pretends  to  nothing  but  a 
rough  suggestiveness  of  the  relations  these  different  processes  bear  to  one  an- 
other when  attention  is  employed  in  this  way  for  connecting  them.  It  will 
have  served  its  purpose  if  it  brings  out  a  few  salient  relationships,  such,  for  ex- 
ample, as  the  community  of  certain  sensation  processes  with  intellective  con- 
ditions and  that  of  certain  other  sensation  processes  with  emotion. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  51 

not  be  understood  that  we  dogmatically  deny  any  constancy  of 
changes  aside  from  the  form  of  constancy  we  emphasize,  al- 
though such  constant  conditions  are  rare.  We  simply  maintain 
that  from  our  observations  the  only  feature  which  appears  es- 
sentially constant  under  ALL  PSYCHOLOGICAL  conditions  is  the 
relative  stability  and  instability  (of  the  dynamic  type)  which 
these  organic  activities  manifest  in  connection  with  the  different 
processes  of  attention.  We  have  stated  this  previously,  but 
repeat  it  to  avoid  confusion  and  misunderstanding. 

IV.  REPORT  OF  EXPERIMENTS. 

The  experiments  which  give  rise  to  this  paper  consist  of  two 
very  complete  series  of  tests  taken  from  two  different  subjects. 
Less  extended  observations  upon  a  number  of  other  subjects 
have  tended  to  confirm  our  confidence  in  the  general  position 
we  adopt. 

The  curves  showing  circulatory  changes  are  all  capillary 
pulse  tracings,  taken  with  the  air  plethysmograph  invented  by 
Hallion  and  Comte.  The  air  plethysmograph  was  adopted  in 
preference  to  the  water  plethysmograph,  cardiograph,  or  any  of 
the  methods  of  taking  the  arterial  pulse  directly,  because  of  the 
greater  delicacy  and  accuracy  with  which  it  registers  slight  varia- 
tions in  the  form  and  amplitude  of  the  pulse  curve.  The  plethys- 
mograph was  connected  with  a  Marey  tambour,  writing  in  the 
ordinary  manner  upon  a  smoked  drum.  After  a  somewhat  ex- 
tended series  of  experiments  upon  technique,  the  most  advan- 
tageous bodily  position,  adjustment  of  the  plethysmograph, 
quality  of  rubber  and  length  of  pointer  for  the  tambour  and 
relative  position  of  tambour  and  drum  were  adopted  and  pre- 
served throughout  the  experiments.1  Careful  tests  upon  the 
accuracy  of  the  instruments  have  convinced  us  that  the  curves 
may  be  relied  upon  for  recording  the  direction  of  changes  in 
the  volume  of  the  blood  in  the  hand,  in  the  rate  of  the  heart- 
beat, and  in  the  form  and  amplitude  of  the  capillary  pulse.2 

1  The  conditions  adopted  by  us  agree  substantially  with  those  of  Binet  and 
his  co-workers.     The  fact  that  a  few  of  our  curves  are  to  be  read  in  a  different 
direction  from  the  others  arises  from  a  temporary  reversal  of  the  drum,  which 
has  no  effect  whatever  on  the  curves,  although  we  regret  the  lack  of  uniformity 
in  their  appearance. 

2  The  apparatus  does  not  record  pressure  changes. 


52 


/.    R.    ANGELL   AND   H.   B.    THOMPSON. 


•II 

.83 


bo 


|8J 

III1 


C 

1 

8 
6 

1 

C/J 

1 

a, 

CO 

^ 

C/5 

CU 

. 

H 

<U 

t 

cf 

£5 

* 

0 

•i-T 

•a 

CU 

c 

. 

c 

^2 

CO 
CO 

H 

1 

CO 

ci' 

0, 
CU 

tt 

D 

c 

*^ 

•^ 

Emban 

CJ 
O 

o 

CJ 

cu 

curve  a 

cu 

c 

3 

CO 

0 

1 

cu 

c/) 

1" 

CO 

p 
0 

h-( 

LANAT] 

C 

£ 

0 

5. 

1 

.5 

I  immedia 

hH 

PU 

rt 

^ 

^j 

cu 

C 

w 

C 

«S 

3 

CU 

>fl 

*^ 

CM 

£ 

;? 

CO 

cu 

*-> 

CO 

«     rt 
bo          j£ 

"C  Jo*  g 

o  —,  «S 

r  1  ^ 
2  s  s 

ell 

o  .«     ^ 


5     S     3 
cu     O,    g 

<u    . 

S5  § 

ill 

co     p. 

^^     rt     co 
— *    cj    cu 


u,    cu 

«     «   03 

cti  H 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  53 

The  absolute  measurements  of  the  curves  of  one  day  could  not, 
however,  be  compared  with  those  of  another,  since  slight 
changes  in  the  adjustment  of  the  plethysmograph  or  of  the  tam- 
bour produce  slight  alterations  in  the  absolute  dimensions  of  the 
curves.1  A  modified  form  of  Bert's  respirator  was  used  for  re- 
cording the  breathing  curves. 

The  emotional  experiences  of  this  series  of  experiments 
were  spontaneous  emotions  arising  from  the  subject's  own 
thoughts  when  left  to  himself.  The  most  noticeable  effects  of 
emotional  states  upon  the  bodily  processes  are  the  sudden, 
violent  changes  and  irregularities  produced.  The  vaso-motor 
shifts  are  the  most  evident  of  these  changes,  although  marked 
irregularities  in  the  rate  and  amplitude  of  both  breathing  and 
pulse  curves  occur.  In  Plate  I.,  Figs.  I.  and  II.  show  char- 
acteristic cases  of  violent  emotion ;  Fig.  III.  is  an  example  of 
one  of  the  milder  emotions,  embarrassment. 

It  is  in  the  case  of  the  emotions,  where  the  agreeable  and 
disagreeable  experiences  are  most  intense,  that  we  should  ex- 
pect to  find  the  most  marked  and  constant  correspondence  of 
agreeable  states  with  one  set  of  physiological  processes  and  of 
disagreeable  states  with  an  antithetical  set,  if  any  such  relation- 
ship existed.  But  our  curves  show  not  the  slightest  evidence  of 
such  an  interconnection.  None  of  the  various  factors  involved, 
vaso-motor  level,  rate  and  amplitude  of  the  pulse  curve,  posi- 
tion and  emphasis  of  the  dicrotic  notch,  or  rate  and  amplitude  of 
the  breathing,  changes  uniformly  in  one  direction  for  agreeable 
experiences,  and  in  the  opposite  direction  for  disagreeable  ex- 
periences. No  doubt  cases  occasionally  occur  where  some 
regular  connection  of  the  kind  mentioned  is  found.  But  it  is 
occasional  and  not  invariable,  in  fact  probably  rare.  Almost  all 
of  our  emotional  experiences,  whether  agreeable  or  disagreeable, 
produced  vaso-constrictions.  This  agrees  with  the  observa- 
tions at  the  Sorbonne  and  is  what  Mosso's  work  would  lead 
us  to  expect.  Figs.  IV.  and  V.  (Plate  II.)  are  examples  of  an 
unpleasant  and  a  pleasant  anticipation  respectively,  experienced 

1  Binet  expresses  a  greater  confidence  in  the  comparability  of  curves  taken 
at  different  sittings  than  our  experience  has  led  us  to  feel.  But,  as  the  matter 
is  largely  one  of  skill,  he  is  doubtless  justified  in  his  assurance. 


54 


/.   /?.   ANGELL   AND   H.    B.    THOMPSON. 


a, 
c 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  55 

by  the  same  subject  at  one  sitting.  Both  cause  violent  vaso-con- 
strictions.  The  most  important  exception  to  this  rule  is  the  fact 
that  with  one  of  the  subjects,  laughter  causes  a  slight,  sudden 
vaso-dilation  (see  Fig.  VI.,  Plate  II.). 

At  first  sight  the  vaso-dilations  due  to  laughter  would  seem 
to  be  a  confirmation  of  the  theory  that  agreeable  experiences  are 
accompanied  by  dilations  of  the  peripheral  blood  vessels.  But 
there  are  several  facts  which  take  away  the  value  of  this  evi- 
dence. In  the  first  place,  the  vaso-motor  change  seems  to  be  a 
secondary  effect  of  the  sudden  spasmodic  change  in  the  breath- 
ing. Of  course,  the  spasmodic  breathing  of  laughter  is  an  es- 
sential factor  in  it,  and  it  is  impossible  to  separate  the  secondary 
vaso-motor  changes  due  to  breathing  from  those  accompanying 
the  feeling  of  amusement  in  laughter.  But  the  character  of  the 

O  O 

vaso-dilations  seems  to  run  parallel  with  the  breathing  changes 
rather  than  with  the  feeling  of  amusement,  which  does  not,  as 
every  one  knows,  always  correspond  with  the  heartiness  of  the 
laughter.  A  hearty  laugh,  causing  sudden,  violent  changes  in 
the  breathing  curve,  is  accompanied  by  the  sharpest  and  most 
marked  vaso-dilation,  while  a  smile  or  mild  laughter  causes 
much  slighter  and  more  gentle  changes  in  the  vaso-motor  curve. 
In  confirmation  of  this  view,  we  have  one  curve  from  this  same 
subject,  in  which  mere  feeling  of  amusement,  unaccompanied 
by  any  of  the  breathing  changes  of  laughter,  produced  a  slow 
vaso-constriction  (VII.,  Plate  II.).  But  more  important  still,  as 
contrary  evidence,  is  the  fact  that,  in  the  case  of  the  other 
subject,  constriction  and  not  dilation  is  the  most  marked  vaso- 
motor  accompaniment  of  laughter.  VIII.,  Plate  III.,  shows  char- 
acteristic laughter  curves  for  this  subject.  They  display  slight 
initial  dilations  followed  by  marked  constrictions.  In  this  case, 
too,  the  amount  of  the  vaso-motor  change  is  in  general  propor- 
tional to  the  amount  of  the  disturbance  in  the  breathing.  But 
why  in  one  subject  spasmodic  breathing  should  have  vaso-dila- 
tion as  its  concomitant,  and  in  another  subject  vaso-constric- 
tion, is  a  mystery.  However,  the  facts  show  that  the  dilations 
of  laughter  in  this  case  can  not  be  taken  as  confirming  the 
theory  that  vaso-dilation  accompanies  pleasant  experiences. 
The  amplitude  of  the  pulse  curve  shows  a  greater  or  less 


/.   R.   ANGELL  AND  H.   B.    THOMPSON. 


bo 

3 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS. 


57 


58  /.    R.  ANGELL  AND  H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

decrease  for  both  subjects  in  almost  all  of  the  emotional  experi- 
ences,whether  agreeable  or  disagreeable.  There  were,  however, 
a  few  cases  of  increase  of  amplitude.  The  great  irregularity  of 
amplitude  during  emotional  experiences  is  a  more  uniform  factor. 
(See  Figs.  I.,  II.,  III.  and  IX.)  The  rate  of  the  heart-beat  is 
sometimes  increased  on  an  average,  sometimes  decreased,  and 
sometimes  not  changed  at  all.  Increase  of  rate  is  much  the 
most  frequent  occurrence  regardless  of  the  quality  of  the  emotion, 
but  all  of  these  changes  take  place  during  each  of  the  two  great 
emotional  states  (compare  Figs.  I.,  rate  unchanged  ;  II.,  rate  in- 
creased;  III,  rate  both  increased  and  decreased  ;  and  X.,  rate  de- 
creased). But  whatever  the  average  change  of  rate  may  be,  a 
more  uniform  and,  in  our  opinion,  more  significant  feature  is  the 
spasmodic  irregularities  of  the  rate  characteristic  of  curves  cor- 
responding to  emotional  states  (compare  Figs.  I.,  II.,  III.,  IV., 
V.  and  X.),  a  feature  strongly  indicative  of  the  general  physio- 
logical instability  of  emotional  states  for  which  we  are  contend- 
ing. The  changes  in  form  and  position  of  the  dicrotic  notch1  are 
as  erratic  as  the  amplitude  and  rate  changes.  The  notch  is 
sometimes  raised,  sometimes  lowered,  sometimes  emphasized 
and  sometimes  flattened,  with  entire  disregard  to  the  affective 
tone  of  the  emotion. 

The  breathing  during  emotional  experiences  shows  no  greater 
uniformity  in  direction  of  change  than  the  pulse.  All  the  varia- 
tions of  increase  and  decrease  of  both  rate  and  amplitude  of  the 
breathing  are  found  accompanying  both  agreeable  and  dis- 
agreeable experiences.  In  the  more  violent  emotions  (see  Figs. 
I.  and  IL),  and,  of  course,  in  laughter,  the  breathing  becomes 
very  spasmodic  and  irregular  as  to  both  rate  and  amplitude. 
The  lesser  emotions  show  smaller  disturbances  (see  Figs.  IV., 
and  X.),  while  some  of  them  show  no  change  at  all  (see  Fig. 

1  The  emphasis  and  position  of  the  dicrotic  notch  vary  greatly  in  our  dif- 
ferent curves.  This  is  no  doubt  largely  due  to  the  fact  that  the  dicrotic 
notch  varies  so  greatly  at  different  times  of  the  day  and  under  different  condi- 
tions of  nutrition  and  of  activity.  (See  Binet  and  Courtier,  L'Annee  Psy- 
chologique,  1897,  p.  10. )  It  may  also  be  due  in  part  to  slight  differences  in  the 
adjustment  of  the  instruments  at  various  sittings.  But,  since  our  conclusions 
are  based  upon  immediately  successive  changes  in  the  form  of  the  curve  only, 
this  is  a  matter  of  no  moment  in  the  present  case. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS. 


59 


C/3     O 


*<§ 


!-      G, 

s  s 


2  <u 


S.5. 


x 


60  /.    R.  ANGELL  AND  H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

IX).  The  breathing,  then,  at  least  in  the  case  of  the  more  vio- 
lent emotions,  shows  the  same  functional  disturbance  which  has 
already  been  shown  to  be  characteristic  of  the  pulse  curves. 

According  to  the  psychological  analysis  of  the  states  known 
as  emotion,  sensation  and  intellectual  application,  which  was 
offered  in  the  preceding  section,  we  found  that,  when  classified 
with  respect  to  the  stability  of  the  attentive  process  involved, 
sensation  occupies  a  middle  range  between  emotion  and  mental 
application.  It  was  also  pointed  out  that  the  term  sensation 
covers  a  great  variety  of  experiences,  some  of  which  border 
closely  upon  emotional  states,  while  others  approach  the  intel- 
lective conditions.  If  the  hypothesis  is  correct,  that  the  degree 
of  stability  of  the  physiological  processes  runs  parallel  with  the 
degree  of  stability  in  the  attentive  process,  we  ought  to  find  in 
general  the  curves  for  sensation  showing  less  disturbance  than 
those  for  emotional  states,  and  more  than  the  curves  for  intel- 
lectual application.  Moreover,  we  ought  to  find  the  curves  rep- 
resenting sensation  varying  from  curves  approaching  the  emo- 
tional type  to  those  closely  resembling  the  type  of  intellectual 
application,  according  to  the  quality  of  the  sensation  as  regards 
the  functioning  of  attention.  This  is  exactly  the  relationship 
which  a  study  of  our  curves  reveals. 

Figs.  XI.  to  XVI.,  inclusive,  are  typical  curves  of  sensory 
stimulation.  The  first  three  of  the  set  are  taken  from  one  sub- 
ject, and  the  last  three  from  the  other.  A  comparison  of  these 
curves  with  the  preceding  ones  of  emotional  experiences  and 
with  the  succeeding  curves  of  mental  application  (Figs.  XXVI. 
to  XXXI. )  will  show  that  the  vaso-motor  shifts  for  sensory  stimuli 
are  not  so  great  as  those  for  emotional  experiences,  but  are  much 
greater  than  those  in  the  mental  application  curves.  The  am- 
plitude and  rate  are  less  spasmodic  and  irregular  than  those  for 
emotional  states,  but  not  nearly  so  uniform  and  even  as  the  rates 
and  amplitudes  of  the  curves  of  mental  application.  The  am- 
plitude and  rate  changes  which  occur  are  often  equal  in  amount 
to  those  of  emotional  experiences,  but  they  are  less  jerky  and 
irregular.  They  approach  more  nearly  the  even,  progressive 
changes  of  mental  application. 

But  within  the  large  class  of  psychic  states  known  as  sensa- 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS. 


61 


62  j.    R.  AN G ELL   AND   H.    B.    THOMPSON. 

tion,  for  which  the  statements  in  the  preceding  paragraph  are 
true  in  general,  we  find  the  wide  variations  in  the  accompany- 
ing bodily  processes  which  our  psychological  analysis  has  led 
us  to  expect.  Various  sensory  stimuli  produce  experiences  of 
widely  different  intensities.  A  hot  object  touching  the  skin 
produces  a  much  more  intense  experience  than  a  colored  light 
impinging  on  the  retina,  and,  therefore,  makes  a  much  more 
imperative  demand  for  attention.  The  shift  from  the  preceding 
state  to  the  new  experience  is  much  more  sudden  and  violent 
in  the  case  of  the  hot  stimulus,  and  involves  a  rudimentary 
shock,  which  is  entirely  lacking  in  the  color  stimulation.  The 
different  bodily  processes  accompanying  these  two  sensations  are 
shown  in  Figs.  XVII.  and  XVIII.  The  sudden  violent  changes 
in  vaso-motor  level  accompanying  the  heat  stimulus  are  much 
like  those  of  the  emotional  experiences,  while  the  slight  gentle 
fluctuations  of  the  color  experience  approach  the  mental  appli- 
cation curves. 

But  even  the  same  kind  of  sensory  stimulus  occasions  states 
which  differ  greatly  in  intensity  at  various  times,  according 
to  the  actual  physical  intensity  of  the  stimulus,  the  nervous 
irritability  of  the  subject  at  the  moment  when  the  stim- 
ulus occurs,  and  the  element  of  surprise  involved.  A  loud 
noise,  for  instance,  produces  a  much  greater  shock,  and  a 
correspondingly  greater  disturbance  in  the  bodily  processes, 
when  it  is  unexpected  than  it  does  when  the  subject  is  prepared 
for  it.  Fig.  XV.  shows  the  effects  of  an  unexpected  noise.  Fig. 
XIX.  is  a  curve  for  noise  taken  at  the  same  sitting,  with  the  sole 
difference  that  in  Fig.  XIX.  the  noise  was  expected.  The  shock 
involved  in  the  unexpected  noise  made  the  experience  take  on 
an  emotional  tone,  which  is  reflected  in  the  spasmodic  change 
of  vaso-motor  level  and  amplitude,  while  the  expected  noise 
produces  only  a  slight  irregularity  in  the  curve.  When  both 
noises  are  unexpected,  a  loud  noise  produces  a  much  more 
violent  shift  of  attention  than  a  slight  one.  Fig.  XII.  is  a  char- 
acteristic curve  for  a  loud  noise,  while  Fig.  XX.  shows  the  effect 
of  a  slight  noise  upon  the  same  subject.  The  contrast  is  much  the 
same  as  that  between  the  expected  noise  and  the  unexpected  one. 
Furthermore,  a  stimulus  which  occurs  while  the  subject  is 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND   CONSCIOUSNESS. 


W 

h 
< 

PL! 


64 


/.   R.   ANGELL  AND   H.    B.    THOMPSON. 


PLATE  VIII. 


XXXIV.,  Capsicum;  XXXV.,  Knocking;  XXXVI.,  Cross  i,  Camphor;  Cross  2,  Rub- 
ber Cement;  XXXVII.,  Addition. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  65 

nervously  excited  produces  a  muc  hmore  disturbing  effect,  and 
makes  the  readjustment  of  attention  a  much  more  difficult  mat- 
ter, than  the  same  stimulus  would  if  the  subject  were  calm. 
Fig.  XI.  is  the  curve  of  a  cold  stimulus  which  occurred  during 
a  state  of  emotional  excitement.  Fig.  XXI.  is  also  the  curve  of 
a  cold  stimulus,  given  at  the  same  sitting,  but  at  a  time  when  the 
subject  was  calm.  The  difference  in  the  effect  of  the  two 
stimuli  is  entirely  disproportionate  to  the  slight  difference  there 
may  have  been  between  the  absolute  intensities  of  the  two. 

The  breathing  luring  sensory  stimulations  undergoes  irregu- 
lar changes  in  rate  and  amplitude,  more  or  less  analogous  to 
those  of  the  pulse.  An  experience  intense  enough  to  cause  a 
profound  change  in  one  usually  shows  itself  in  the  other  also 
(see  Fig.  XL).  When  the  experience  is  less  intense  it  some- 
times produces  an  effect  on  the  pulse  curve,  but  none  on  the 
breathing,  although  the  reverse  seldom  happens.  On  the 
whole,  the  breathing  in  cases  of  sensory  stimulations  is  charac- 
terized by  slight  spasmodic  irregularities,  usually  of  short  dura- 
tion (Figs.  XL,  XII. ,  XIII. ,  XIV.,  XXV.).  With  the  weaker 
and  less  effective  stimuli  these  are  often  lacking,  and  some- 
times fail  even  with  the  more  intense  experiences  (see  Fig. 
XVII. ).  As  compared  with  emotional  states,  the  disturbances 
of  the  breathing  during  sensory  stimulation  are  of  less  frequent 
occurrence  and  of  briefer  duration. 

The  search  for  uniformity  in  classes  or  kinds  of  sensory 
stimuli  is  as  fruitless  as  it  proved  to  be  in  the  emotional  states. 
An  overwhelming  majority  of  sensory  stimuli  of  all  kinds, 
whether  agreeable  or  disagreeable,  caused  vaso-constrictions. 
The  few  cases  of  pronounced  vaso-dilation  do  not  correspond 
to  the  distinctly  pleasant  stimuli.  The  most  distinctly  pleasur- 
able stimulus  used,  harmony,  caused  constrictions  on  all  of  the 
few  occasions  when  it  was  given.  Unpleasant  odors,  such  as 
camphor  and  capsicum,  caused  dilations  on  a  few  occasions. 
Figs.  XXII.  and  XXIII.  are  the  curves  for  two  disagreeable 
odors,  both  capsicum,  given  within  a  few  minutes  of  each 
other  to  the  same  subject.  As  the  curves  show,  one  caused  a 
slight  dilation  and  the  other  a  somewhat  greater  constriction. 

The  amplitude  changes  of  the  pulse  curve  show  no  greater 


66  /.   R.   AN  CELL  AND   H.   B.    THOMPSON. 

constancy  in  the  direction  of  change  for  different  kinds  of  stim- 
uli than  does  the  vaso-motor  level.  There  is  a  great  preponder- 
ance of  decreases  of  amplitude  over  increases  for  sensory 
stimuli  as  a  whole,  but  here  again  there  seems  to  be  no  particu- 
lar significance  in  the  direction  of  the  change  for  different  ex- 
periences. For  instance,  disagreeable  odors  cause  sometimes 
increase  and  sometimes  decrease  of  amplitude  (see  Figs.  XXII. 
and  XXIII.) .  Cold  is  sometimes  accompanied  by  a  decrease  of 
amplitude  (Figs.  XL  and  XIV.)  and  sometimes  by  increase  (Fig. 
XXI. ) .  The  relatively  few  cases  of  harmony  among  our  tests  all 
produced  an  increase  of  the  amplitude  of  the  pulse  curve,  a  fact 
which  suggests  increase  of  amplitude  as  a  correlate  of  pleasant 
experiences,  until  we  notice  that  discords  have  the  same  effect. 

The  rate  changes  of  the  heart-beat  during  sensory  stimula- 
tions are  about  equally  divided  between  increases  and  decreases. 
Cold,  noise,  odors — in  fact,  all  the  stimuli  of  which  we  have  any 
considerable  number  of  tests — cause  sometimes  one  and  some- 
times the  other  in  a  manner  which,  on  present  data,  is  entirely 
erratic.  The  cold  stimulation  shown  in  Fig.  XIV.  causes  a  slight 
temporary  decrease  of  the  pulse  rate,  while  that  of  Fig.  XI. 
is  accompanied  by  a  progressive  increase.  Figs.  XXIV.  and 
XXV.  show  the  curves  for  two  camphor  stimulations,  the  first  of 
which  causes  an  increase  of  pulse  rate  and  the  second  a  decrease. 

The  dicrotic  notch  changes  its  emphasis  and  its  position 
with  reference  to  the  apex  of  the  pulse  curve  with  as  little  re- 
gard to  the  nature  of  the  stimulus  as  is  shown  by  the  other  fac- 
tors. With  one  subject  the  dicrotic,  when  it  suffers  any  change 
at  all,  undergoes  an  almost  uniform  flattening  during  sensory 
stimuli  of  all  kinds.  With  the  other  subject  it  is  emphasized 
almost  as  often  as  it  is  flattened.  The  position  of  the  dicrotic 
remains  unchanged  during  the  great  majority  of  sensory  stimuli 
for  both  subjects.  When  it  is  raised  or  lowered  it  happens  ap- 
parently without  reference  to  the  nature  of  the  stimulus. 

The  mental  application  tests  used  were  chiefly  simple  arith- 
metical problems  given  as  fast  as  the  subject  could  perform  them. 
In  a  few  cases  the  memorizing  of  a  series  of  nonsense  syllables 
was  employed.  The  curves  of  mental  application  are  character- 
ized by  the  slight  amount  of  the  vaso-motor  changes  involved,  and 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND   CONSCIOUSNESS.  67 

by  the  even  progression  in  which  changes  in  rate  and  amplitude 
take  place,  when  they  occur  at  all.  The  vaso-motor  level 
usually  shows  slight  fluctuations,  although  they  are  always  less 
than  the  fluctuations  of  revery  for  the  same  day.  Frequently  the 
changes  are  so  slight  as  to  be  scarcely  noticeable  (Figs.  XXVI., 
XXVII.  and  XXVIII.).  The  respiratory  rhythms  disappear. 

The  breathing  is  more  regular  in  most  cases,  although  there 
are  some  exceptions.  In  memorizing  nonsense  syllables  the 
breathing  curve  is  broken  up  by  a  tendency  to  pronounce  the 
syllables.  In  some  cases  of  mental  application,  such  as  Fig. 
XXXVII.  there  are  occasional  irregularities.  The  fact  that  the 
breathing  is  under  voluntary  control,  and  that  it  is  immediately 
affected  by  any  tendency  to  use  motor  images  of  words,  would 
lead  us  to  expect  that  the  uniformities  would  be  less  evident  in 
that  case  than  in  the  case  of  the  purely  reflex  vaso-motor 
phenomena.  As  compared  with  emotional  experiences  and 
with  sensory  stimulations,  and  even  with  revery,  the  bodily  pro- 
cesses accompanying  mental  application  are  characterized  by 
greater  stability  and  regularity.  If  our  psychological  analysis  is 
correct,  mental  application  is  a  state  in  which  the  attentive  pro- 
cess is  most  stable,  runs  most  smoothly  and  offers  greatest 
resistance  to  change.  Here,  again,  the  correspondence  be- 
tween the  degree  of  stability  of  the  attentive  process  and  the 
degree  of  stability  of  the  accompanying  bodily  processes  holds. 

But  as  in  the  former  cases,  so  in  mental  application,  the  di- 
rection of  the  various  changes  which  do  occur,  offers  no  basis 
of  classification  which  articulates  with  the  psychological 
classification,  either  into  intellective  as  opposed  to  affective 
states,  or  into  agreeable  as  opposed  to  disagreeable  states. 
The  subjects  found  no  distinctly  affective  tone  in  the  vari- 
ous mental  application  tests  used.  Since  no  psychological 
classification  on  the  basis  of  agreeable  and  disagreeable  is 
possible  in  this  case,  it  would  be  absurd  to  intrepret  the  vaso- 
dilations  and  constrictions  as  having  such  a  significance.  If 
the  direction  of  the  changes  characterized  intellective  states  as 
opposed  to  affective  states  we  ought,  of  course,  to  expect  to  find 
some  uniformity  in  the  direction  of  change  of  mental  application 
tests  as  a  whole.  But  this  is  entirely  lacking.  In  almost  half 


68  /.   R.   ANGELL  AND    H.   B.    THOMPSON, 

of  the  mental  application  tests  the  vaso-motor  level  shows  both 
dilations  and  constrictions  within  a  single  test  (Figs.  XXVI., 
XXVII.  and  XXVIII.) .  Where  the  vaso-motor  level  changes  in 
only  one  direction  it  seems  to  be  an  even  chance  whether  it  shall 
be  a  dilation  or  a  constriction.  Frequently  there  is  no  change  of 
level.  Fig.  XXIX.  illustrates  a  mental  application  test  where 
there  is  only  constriction  and  Fig.  XXXVII.  one  where  there  is 
only  dilation. 

The  amplitude  of  the  pulse  curve  in  mental  application 
shows  a  greater  tendency  to  decrease  than  to  increase.  In  all 
of  the  few  tests  made,  which  exceeded  two  minutes  in  time, 
there  was  a  marked  decrease  of  amplitude  at  the  end,  even  when 
there  was  an  increase  at  the  beginning.  But  among  the  tests 
of  shorter  duration  there  were  several  where  the  amplitude  in- 
creased without  any  subsequent  decrease.  The  pulse  rate  of 
mental  application  shows  a  greater  tendency  to  increase  than 
to  decrease,  but  the  cases  of  decrease  of  rate,  although  less  nu- 
merous than  those  of  increase,  are  frequent.1  But,  whatever 
the  direction  of  the  change,  it  takes  place  slowly  and  gradually. 
(See  Fig.  XXXVII.  for  increase  of  pulse  rate  and  Fig.  XXXI. 
for  decrease  of  rate.) 

The  rate  and  amplitude  of  the  breathing  curves  change  in 
contrary  directions  during  mental  application  in  quite  as  erratic 
a  manner  as  the  pulse  curves.2  One  subject  shows  an  almost 
uniform  increase  of  breathing  rate,  while  the  other  has  a  few 
more  cases  of  decrease  than  of  increase.  With  both  subjects 
the  amplitude  is  more  often  decreased  than  increased,  but  there 
are  frequent  cases  of  increase.  (See  Fig.  XXVII.  for  increase 
of  breathing  amplitude  and  Fig.  XXXVII.  for  decrease.) 

As  a  summary  of  the  results  of  these  experiments,  we  can  offer 
nothing  better  than  a  series  of  tests  illustrating  each  of  the  differ- 
ent types  of  processes  from  curves  obtained  at  a  single  sitting  of 
about  an  hour's  duration.  There  is  first  the  emotional  experi- 
ence of  the  sudden  thought  of  a  friend's  illness  (Fig.  XXXII.), 

1  Most  investigators  report  much  greater  constancy  in  the  cases  of  increase 
of  rate  in  the  heart  under  these  conditions.  Certainly  it  is  the  most  usual  oc- 
currence. 

2MacDougall  and  the  French  writers  report  increase  in  rate  and  decrease 
in  amplitude  as  constant.  Delabarre's  observations  suggest  a  considerable  dif- 
ference in  individuals  in  this  respect. 


ORGANIC  PROCESSES  AND    CONSCIOUSNESS.  69 

with  its  marked  fall  in  vaso-motor  level  and  its  irregularity  in 
all  the  features  of  pulse  and  breathing  curves.  Next  comes  the 
startling  noise  (Fig.  XXXIII.),  which  involves  as  sudden  and 
violent  a  shift  of  attention  as  the  emotion  and  produces  a  very 
similar  curve.  Next  in  order  is  a  disagreeable  and  annoying 
odor — capsicum  (Fig.  XXXIV.).  In  this  case  the  vaso-motor 
fall  is  less,  though  still  very  evident,  and  irregularities  in  ampli- 
tude and  rate  are  decreased.  The  slight  disturbance  caused  by 
an  unexpected  knock  at  the  laboratory  door,  makes  still  less  of 
a  fall  in  vaso-motor  level,  but  yet  shows  other  irregularities  (Fig. 
XXXV.).  The  odors  of  camphor  and  rubber  cement,  which 
were  not  at  all  annoying  unless  strong,  produce  no  marked 
change  in  the  curve  (Fig.  XXXVI.) .  The  slight  shifts  of  vaso- 
motor  level,  and  slight  irregularities  of  rate  and  amplitude, 
resemble  closely  those  of  the  preceding  state  of  revery.  No 
strong  demand  for  attention  is  made  by  them.  Finally,  mental 
application  (Fig.  XXXVII.)  produces  a  steady  strain  of  atten- 
tion, which  is  accompanied  by  a  curve  practically  devoid  of 
fluctuations  in  vaso-motor  level,  with  an  amplitude  which  is 
almost  constant,  and  a  slowly,  progressively  increasing  rate. 

All  the  processes  with  which  we  have  been  dealing  are  cases 
of  readjustment  of  an  organism  to  its  environment.  Attention 
is  always  occupied  with  the  point  in  consciousness  at  which  the 
readjustment  is  taking  place.  If  the  process  of  readjustment 
goes  smoothly  and  evenly,  we  have  a  steady  strain  of  attention 
— an  equilibrated  motion  in  one  direction.  The  performance 
of  mental  calculation  is  a  typical  case  of  this  sort  of  attention. 
But  often  the  readjustment  is  more  difficult.  Factors  are  intro- 
duced which  at  first  refuse  to  be  reconciled  with  the  rest  of  the 
conscious  content.  The  attentive  equilibrium  is  upset,  and  there 
are  violent  shifts  back  and  forth  as  it  seeks  to  recover  itself. 
These  are  the  cases  of  violent  emotion.  Between  these  two  ex- 
tremes comes  every  shade  of  difficulty  in  the  readjustment,  and 
of  consequent  intensity  in  emotional  tone.  We  have  attempted 
to  show  in  the  preceding  paper  that  the  readjustment  of  organ- 
ism to  environment  involves  a  maintenance  of  the  equilibrium 
of  the  bodily  processes,  which  runs  parallel  with  the  mainte- 
nance of  the  attentive  equilibrium,  and  is  an  essential  part  of  the 
readjustment  of  the  psychophysical  organism. 


PROFESSOR  MULLER'S  THEORY  OF  THE 
LIGHT-SENSE.1 

BY  CHRISTINE  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

Professor  Whitman,  in  his  address  as  Vice-President  of  the 
Section  of  Physics,  has  given  an  admirable  account  of  the 
present  state  of  discussion  upon  the  color-sense,  as  far  as  it  re- 
gards the  theories  of  Helmholtz  and  of  Hering,  and  he  has  also 
devoted  much  time — more,  perhaps,  than  they  deserve  ! — to  the 
modifications  of  those  theories  which  have  been  made  by  Eb- 
binghaus  and  v.  Kries.  He  has,  very  politely,  refrained  from 
anticipating  what  I  have  to  say  by  giving  an  account  of  the  sub- 
ject of  this  paper,  the  theory  of  Professor  G.  E.  Miiller,  a 
theory  which,  in  my  opinion,  deserves  to  be  put  quite  in  the  front 
rank  of  the  various  attempts  that  have  been  made  to  account  for 
the  color-process  of  the  retina.  I  regret  very  much  that  this 
paper  of  Professor  Whitman's  was  given  before  the  physicists 
at  an  hour  when  it  could  not  be  listened  to  by  the  members  of 
this  Section,  for  it  contained  a  very  clear  account  of  the  recently 
discovered  facts  of  color-vision,  a  knowledge  of  which,  on  your 
part,  would  perhaps  have  lent  something  more  of  interest  to 
my  discussion  of  the  theory  of  Professor  Muller. 

This  theory  is  set  forth  in  four  papers  which  have  been 
printed  in  1896  and  1897  in  the  Zeitschrift fur  Psychologic  und 
Physiologic  der  Sinnesorgane  j  these  papers  cover  some  two 
hundred  and  fifty  large  pages,  and  form  therefore  practically  a 
book  on  the  subject.  The  appearance  of  this  volume,  as  it  may 
properly  be  called,  marks  a  real  epoch  in  the  long  discussion 
that  has  been  going  on  in  the  effort  to  reduce  to  order  and  sys- 
tem the  phenomena  of  the  sensation  of  light.  Its  author  has 
shown  a  remarkable  mastery  of  the  immense  mass  of  facts  which 
have  a  bearing  upon  the  case,  and  a  no  less  remarkable  keenness 

JRead  before  the  Section  of  Anthropology,  A.  A.  A.  S.,  August,  1898. 
70 


MULLERS   THEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  7 1 

of  logic  in  attributing  to  them  their  proper  weight  in  the  discus- 
sion of  theoretical  considerations.  Professor  Miiller  won  his 
spurs,  as  a  young  man,  by  his  very  acute  treatment  of  the  fun- 
damental problems  of  psycho-physics  ;  his  reasoning  processes 
are  of  a  far  more  rigid  character  than  those  which  are  usually 
consecrated  to  the  subject  of  color-vision.  His  theory  presents 
great  points  of  superiority  over  the  Hering  theory,  and  it  is  by 
far  the  best  attempt  that  has  yet  been  made  to  construct  a  theory- 
based  upon  the  assumption  of  antagonistic  retinal  processes  for 
the  colors  and  for  white  and  black. 

Professor  Miiller  himself  modestly  refers  to  his  theory,  in 
many  places,  as  merely  a  modification  of  the  theory  of  Hering ; 
at  other  times  he  speaks  of  it  plainly  as  die  hier  vertretene 
Theorie,  in  distinction  from  that  of  Hering.  There  is  no  ques- 
tion that  the  latter  designation  is  the  correct  one.  When  a 
theory  has  some  points  in  common  with  another  it  is  difficult  to 
know  just  where  to  draw  the  line  between  regarding  it  as  the 
same  and  regarding  it  as  different — it  is  impossible  to  lay  down 
any  general  rule  that  shall  cover  such  cases.  In  regard  to  the 
extraordinary  fact  of  color  vision — so  totally  unlike  anything 
that  happens  in  sound  or  in  any  other  quality  of  sensation — that 
when  certain  two  colors,  which  are  neither  particularly  alike 
nor  particularly  unlike,  as  far  as  one  can  tell  beforehand,  are 
seen  together,  they  both  absolutely  disappear  from  conscious- 
ness, that  their  place  is  taken  by  a  plain  undifferentiated  gray — 
in  regard  to  this  fact1  there  are,  in  two  different  respects,  two  dif- 
ferent lines  of  explanation.  In  the  first  place,  this  extraordinary 
fact  of  disappearing  color-pairs  may  be  a  matter  of  physiology 
or  it  may  be  a  matter  of  psychology, — that  is,  it  may  be  (in  the 
latter  case)  that  it  is  the  judgment,  or  rather  the  imagination, 
which  causes  us  to  lose  all  sense  of  color  in  the  sensation  of 
white,  or  it  may  be,  on  the  other  hand,  that  the  loss  takes  place 
in  some  lower  stratum  of  the  passage  from  external  light  to  the 

1  It  is  an  act  of  discourtesy  to  the  adherents  of  one  or  the  other  of  the  two 
great  schools  of  color-theorists  to  call  such  color-pairs  as  this  either  antago- 
nistic or  complementary  colors,  for  either  term  commits  us  at  once,  of  course,  to 
an  opinion  as  to  the  intrinsic  nature  of  the  processes  which  call  them  forth.  The 
difficulty  can  be  avoided  if  we  refer  to  such  a  pair  of  colors  as  a  disappearing 
color-pair. 


72  C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

final  sensation — for  instance,  in  the  photo-chemical  process, 
whatever  it  may  be,  of  the  retina.  In  each  of  these  two  cases 
the  loss  of  color  may  be  of  the  nature  of  a  composition  into  a 
resultant  gray,  or  it  may  be  of  the  nature  of  an  antagonism,  and 
a  suppression  of  color,  with  the  re-emergence  of  a  gray  which 
was  present  all  the  time  in  a  state  of  abeyance  or  of  conceal- 
ment.1 The  only  psychical  theory  that  has  been  proposed  hith- 
erto is  the  Young-Helmholtz  theory ;  but  there  might  equally 
well  be  a  psychical  antagonistic  theory,  in  which,  by  the  action 
of  the  mind,  the  colors  of  a  color-pair,  upon  proper  occasion,  de- 
stroyed each  other.  This  theory  would  have  quite  as  much 
reason  in  its  favor  as  the  psychical  complementary  theory  of 
Helmholtz,  and  it  is  merely  by  an  oversight,  no  doubt,  that  it 
has  not  yet  been  seriously  proposed. 

If  the  cause  of  the  disappearance  of  color  is  physiological, 
it  may,  as  I  have  said,  be  either  of  the  nature  of  a  re-composition 
of  the  several  constituents  of  white,  or  of  the  nature  of  an  antago- 
nism, and  a  suppression  of  color.  Now  the  theory  of  Miiller  be- 
longs to  the  same  one  of  the  four  possible  classes  of  theories  as 
that  of  Hering — it  is  physiological  and  antagonistic.  But  that 
is  not  enough  to  make  it  the  same  theory.  If  the  assumption 
of  four  antagonistic  colors  and  a  separate  process  for  black  and 
white  were  sufficient  to  characterize  a  theory,  then  the  theory  of 
Hering  would  not  belong  to  Hering,  for  all  that  was  maintained 
by  Mach  for  ten  years  before  the  appearance  of  Hering's 
first  paper  on  color-theory.  What  is  distinctive  of  the  Hering 
theory  is  the  assumption  of  assimilation  and  dissimilation  as  the 
bases  of  the  antagonistic  sensation-pairs.  For  this  Professor 
Miiller  substitutes  the  conception  of  *  reversible  chemical  ac- 
tion,' and  he  shows  conclusively  the  utter  inadequacy  of  the 
processes  of  assimilation  and  dissimilation  to  play  the  part  re- 
quired of  them.  (Aside  from  all  other  difficulties,  they  are  not 
even  antagonistic  processes ;  dissimilation  does  not  inhibit  as- 
similation, but,  on  the  contrary,  the  more  rapidly  any  tissue  is 
being  used  up,  the  more  quickly  does  nature  hasten  to  restore 

1  Thus  there  are  four  possible  classes  of  color-theory — the  psychical  and  the 
physiological  compository  theories  (or  complementary  theories)  and  the  psy- 
chical and  the  physiological  antagonistic  theories. 


MULLENS    THEORY   OF   THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  73 

it.)  This  difference  in  the  character  of  the  antagonism  con- 
cerned is  very  fundamental — so  much  so  that  in  the  one  case 
(that  of  the  assimilation  and  dissimilation  of  Hering)  it  is  quite 
impossible  to  accept  the  theory  based  upon  it,  while  the  other 
theory  (that  of  Professor  Miiller)  is  not  to  be  so  lightly  brushed 
aside,  but,  on  the  contrary,  gives  room  for  serious  discussion.  I 
have,  therefore,  no  hesitation  in  designating  the  theory  of  Pro- 
fessor Miiller  as  a  new  theory,  although  it  is  a  theory  belonging, 
like  the  theory  of  Hering,  to  the  class  of  physiological  (instead 
of  psychical)  theories,  and  to  that  of  antagonistic  (instead  of 
complementary)  theories. 

Professor  Miiller's  paper  begins  with  an  acute  discussion  of 
the  doctrine  of  psycho-physical  parallelism.  He  sets  forth  th'e 
several  axioms,  five  in  number,  into  which  that  doctrine  may 
be  resolved.  He  shows  that  Hering  has  violated  these  princi- 
ples in  a  fundamental  manner,  in  assuming  that  the  quality  of 
a  sensation  of  gray  depends  only  upon  the  -proportion  of  black 
and  white  which  enter  into  it,  while  their  absolute  amounts  may 
vary  to  any  extent  without  affecting  sensation.  This  palpable 
defect  in  the  theory  of  Hering  is  removed  by  Miiller  by  the  as- 
sumption that  the  effect  of  light  upon  the  black-white  photo- 
chemical substance  is  such  that  whenever  more  white  process 
goes  on,  by  just  so  much  there  is  less  of  the  black  process,  and 
hence  that  a  given  -proportion  does  not,  as  matter  of  fact,  occur 
with  different  absolute  amounts  of  the  two  elements  which  make 
it  up ;  if  it  did,  we  should  see  a  given  quality  of  gray  in  vari- 
ous different  degrees  of  intensity ',  what  is  not  the  case. 

Another  application  of  the  principles  of  psycho-physical 
parallelism  is  made  by  Professor  Miiller  to  determine  what  he 
calls  a  psychic  quality- series.  Sensation  is  subject  to  ceaseless 
change  ;  we  assume  it  as  self-evident  that  we  are  capable  of  dis- 
tinguishing whether  a  sensation  is  varying  in  a  constant  direc- 
tion, or  not;  if,  for  instance,  we  are  making  a  purple  light  out 
of  a  physical  mixture  of  red  and  blue,  we  shall  assume  that  we 
can  distinguish  between  the  several  cases,  whether  the  operator 
is  adding  always  more  and  more  blue  to  the  mixture,  whether 
he  suddenly  begins  to  add  more  red,  or  more  white,  or  more 
black ;  if  the  sensation  is  growing  steadily  more  and  more  like 


74  C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

a  distinct  other  sensation,  the  series  shall  be  called  a  series  which 
varies  in  a  constant  direction ;  in  this  case  we  are  required  to 
assume  that  the  underlying  physiological  process  which  im- 
mediately precedes  consciousness  is  also  in  some  sense  a  series 
which  varies  in  a  constant  direction ;  this  may  be  a  constant 
change  in  quality  (a  change  in  a  vibration  period,  for  instance), 
or  it  may  be  a  constant  change  in  the  relative  intensity  of  the 
two  elements  of  a  mixture.  Professor  Muller  shows,  by  an 
exhaustive  piece  of  reasoning,  that  in  the  case  of  the  color 
series  there  is  every  reason  to  believe  that  the  latter  is  the 
case,  that  the  physiological  process  is  a  varying  mixture  of 
two  processes.  This  is,  in  fact,  the  only  supposition  that  is 
possible  if  the  physiological  process  is  of  the  nature  of  a 
chemical  change  (for  a  chemical  change  is  not  capable  of  a 
very  large  number  of  different  qualities)  ;  and  that  it  is  of  the 
nature  of  a  chemical  change  there  seems  to  be  very  little  rea- 
son to  doubt.  Nothing  else  would  be  at  all  possible  except  an 
electrical  process,  and  that,  if  it  took  place,  would  be  due  to  a 
preceding  chemical  effect;  so  it  is  simpler,  in  the  absence  of 
reasons  to  the  contrary,  to  assume  a  chemical  effect  only. 

The  question  which  next  arises  is  this, — and  it  is  a  very  im- 
portant one.  Does  the  whole  gamut  (a  circular  gamut)  of  satu- 
rated color-tones  correspond  to  one  or  to  more  than  one,  and  if  to 
more  than  one,  then  to  how  many  -psychic  quality  series^  in  the 
above  sense  of  the  term  ?  It  is  plain  that  there  are  four  such 
series  in  the  whole  congeries  of  color-tones.  The  end  mem- 
bers of  the  series  are  the  fundamental  colors,  red,  yellow,  green 
and  blue.  Four  fundamental  color-tones  have  been  assumed 
before,  but  many  psychologists  have  objected  to  the  grounds 
upon  which  both  Mach  and  Hering  urged  the  claims  of  these 
four  colors  to  their  exceptional  position.  They  have  said  that 
in  looking  at  an  orange  color,  for  example,  it  is  impossible  to 
extract  from  it  the  red  and  yellow  of  which  it  is  composed,  in 
the  same  way  in  which  one  can  hear  in  a  chord  its  separate 
notes ;  and  violet  does  not  *  remind  '  us,  they  say,  of  red  and 
blue  any  more  than  red  and  blue  remind  us  of  violet.  Pro- 
fessor Muller  concedes  that  when  we  look  at  the  colors  singly 
they  appear  all  to  be  of  equal  dignity.  By  simply  looking  at  a 


MULLERS    THEORY  OF   THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  75 

given  color,  we  cannot  tell  whether  it  is  a  mixture  or  more  or 
less  nearly  an  elementary  sensation.  The  colors  must  be  ar- 
ranged in  quality-series ;  then  the  difference  between  the  end 
members  and  the  intermediate  members  of  these  series  becomes 
distinct.  Are  a  given  set  of  quality  changes  proceeding  in  a 
constant  direction  or  not?  The  colors  of  the  spectrum  are  not 
well  adapted  for  obtaining  the  answer  to  this  question — they 
differ  too  much  in  brightness.  It  is  better  to  take  a  complete 
series  of  papers,  or,  better  still,  of  gelatine  sheets,  which  can  have 
their  brightness  regulated  by  putting  different  grays  behind  them. 
Then,  if  one  looks  on  dispassionately,  one  cannot  help  saying 
to  oneself :  When  I  pass  from  red  through  orange  to  yellow 
the  change  in  the  quality  of  the  sensation  proceeds  constantly 
in  the  same  direction ;  so  when  I  pass  from  yellow  through 
olive  to  green.  These  are,  in  the  above  sense  of  the  term, 
psychic  quality  series.  But  when  I  pass  from  orange  to  yellow 
and  from  yellow  to  olive,  or  from  olive  to  green  and  from  green 
to  blue-green,  the  second  part  of  the  change  is  not  in  the  same 
direction  as  the  first — these  color-sensations  are  not  members  of 
one  and  the  same  quality  series.  For  a  person  who  cannot  per- 
ceive the  difference  that  is  here  insisted  upon,  there  is  indeed 
nothing  to  be  done ;  but  to  the  unprejudiced  observation  it  may 
be  confidently  predicted  that,  if  we  put  in  say  five,  or  seven, 
color-tones  between  purple  and  orange,  through  the  reds,  and 
also  between  red  and  yellow,  through  the  various  tones  of 
orange,  the  difference  in  character  of  the  two  series  will  *  spring 
into  the  eyes  '  with  perfect  distinctness. 

All  Professor  Miiller's  discussion  of  this  subject,  of  which  I 
can  give  only  a  brief  indication  here,  I  regard  as  excellent,  and 
I  adopt  it  bodily  as  a  firm  substratum  for  my  own  theory.  But, 
unfortunately,  it  does  not  fit  Professor  Miiller's  theory  well 
at  all.  In  order  that  the  four  colors  which  a  careful  inspection 
of  our  sensations  tell  us  are  fundamental  may  also  be  antagonistic 
(or,  in  the  phrase  of  the  other  theory,  complementary} ,  it  is 
necessary  to  manipulate  those  colors  a  little.  The  blue  and  the 
yellow  which  consciousness  tells  us  are  end-members  of  psychic 
series  are,  it  is  true,  also  complementary ;  but  green  (in  any 
ordinary  signification  of  the  word)  is  not  complementary  to  red 


76  C.   LADD  FRANKLIN. 

at  all.  In  order  to  make  things  fit,  Hering  is  obliged  to  assume 
as  green  a  color  which  the  unbiased  eye  would  pronounce  to  be 
a  distinct  blue-green.  (As  confusion  is  constantly  arising  from 
the  fact  that  the  simple  word  green  has  two  totally  different  sig- 
nifications, according  as  one  is  speaking  in  the  language  of 
Hering  or  of  Helmholtz,  I  propose  to  modify  the  spelling  of 
that  green  which  is  in  reality  a  blue-green,  and  to  write  it  grehn , 
meaning  by  this  word  the  green  of  Hering.  It  is  then  grehn 
and  not  green  which  is  the  complementary  color  to  red.)  Now, 
this  beautiful  structure  of  the  psychic  quality  series  goes  all  to 
pieces  as  soon  as  we  attempt  to  fit  the  Muller-Hering  theory  to 
it ;  the  grehn  which  is  the  complementary  or  antagonistic  color 
to  red  is  not  an  end-member  of  a  psychic  quality  series,  but  it 
is  a  member  which  comes  very  distinctly  in  the  middle  of  such 
a  series.  While  then  this  whole  discussion  of  Miiller's  gives 
my  theory  a  firm  standing-ground  against  those  psychologists 
who  profess  not  to  be  able  to  see  that  orange  is  a  mixture,  it 
works  immediate  destruction  to  the  theories  of  Muller  and  of 
Hering. 

The  central  idea  of  the  theory  of  Professor  Muller  is,  as  I 
have  said,  that  of  a  reversible  chemical  action.  (Assimilation 
and  dissimilation  are  offiosite  chemical  actions,  in  a  sense,  but 
they  are  not  reversible — the  products  of  dissimilation  are  not  re- 
formed into  the  original  tissue.)  Professor  Muller  places  at  the 
head  of  his  presentation  of  his  theory  this  passage  from  the 
Theoretical  Chemistry  of  Nernst :  *  *  We  were  formerly  of  the 
opinion  that  the  reversible  reactions  belonged  to  the  exceptions, 
or  that  it  was  necessary  to  distinguish  between  two  different 
classes  of  reactions,  the  reversible  and  the  not-reversible.  But 
we  know  now  that  a  sharp  limit  of  that  kind  is  wholly  non- 
existent ;  there  can  be  no  doubt  that,  upon  proper  arrange- 
ment of  the  experiment,  every  reaction  can  be  caused  to 
proceed  now  in  one  and  now  in  the  other  direction — that  is, 
that  every  reaction  is,  in  principle,  reversible."  This  very 
modern  idea  of  the  chemist  furnishes  the  basis  for  Professor 
Miiller's  conception  of  the  antagonism  between  the  funda- 
mental retinal  processes,  and  he  refers  here  not  only  to  the 
color-pairs,  red-grehn  and  blue-yellow,  but  also  to  the  connected 


MULLEK'S    TPIEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  77 

pair  of  sensations,  black  and  white  :  that  is,  he  conceives  that 
the  *  proper  arrangement  of  the  experiment,'  which  Nernst  says 
is  the  only  condition  necessary  to  make  chemical  reactions  re- 
versible, has  been  secured  for  the  vertebrate  retina.  Confining 
himself  at  first  to  the  black-white  pair  of  sensations,  in  order  to 
facilitate  speaking  about  them,  he  goes  on  to  preciser  his  con- 
ception of  the  retinal  chemical  process  at  the  base  of  them  in 
these  terms.  A  white-reaction,  expressed  in  quite  general  terms, 
consists  in  this  :  that  a  molecules  of  a  substance  A,  ft  molecules 
of  a  substance  B,  f  molecules  of  a  substance  C,  etc.,  come  to- 
gether in  order  to  form  a!  molecules  of  a  substance  A',  ft  mole- 
cules of  a  substance  B' ',  f  molecules  of  a  substance  O,  and  so 
forth.  And  then  a  black-reaction  consists  in  o.'  molecules  of  A1 ', 
ft'  molecules  of  Bj  etc.,  returning  to  their  original  places  so  as 
to  form  again  a  molecules  of  the  substance^,  ft  molecules  of  B ', 
etc.  This  chemical  reaction  may  be  expressed  in  this  form  : 

aA  -f  ftB  -f  .  .  .  g=p  a! A'  +  ft'B'  +  etc.  (i) 

If  this  is  read  from  left  to  right  it  is  a  white-reaction  ;  if  it  is  read 
from  right  to  left  it  is  a  black-reaction. 

Nothing,  of  course,  is  to  be  said  as  to  the  actual  degree  of 
complexity  of  these  reactions,  that  is,  as  to  the  number  of  the 
substances,  on  the  right  hand  and  on  the  left,  which  are  involved 
in  them  ;  they  may  be  numerous,  or  they  may  be  one  only.  In 
any  case  the  total  amount  of  the  substances  A,  B,  C,  etc. 
constitutes  the  white-material  which  is  present,  and  the  amount 
of  the  substances  A,  B',  C',  etc.  constitutes  the  black-material 
which  is  present ;  the  separate  substances,  A,  B,  ...  A,  B1  ^ . .  . 
are  the  components  of  the  black  and  of  the  white  material  re- 
spectively. For  a  chemically  homogeneous  portion  of  that  layer 
of  the  retina  which  is  sensitive  to  light,  the  intensity  of  the  white 
process  will  be  equal  to  the  number  of  white  reactions  which  take 
place  in  unit  volume  of  the  retinal  substance  during  an  element 
of  time.  The  law  of  mass  action,  which  plays  an  important 
role  in  his  theory,  will  then  be  exhibited  in  this  form  : 

K  aa  Wcv  . . .  dt 

~ 


78  C.   LADD  FRANKLIN. 

where  0,  3,  c,  . . .  are  the  masses  of  the  photo-chemical  sub- 
stances (expressed  in  gram-molecules)  a,  /?,  f,  . .  .  are  the 
numbers  of  these  present  in  a  given  portion  of  the  substance, 
v  is  the  volume  of  that  substance,  and  ./Tis  a  coefficient,  depend- 
ing upon  the  temperature  and  other  factors,  which  may  be  called 
the  specific  velocity-coefficient  of  the  white-process.  We  have 
a  similar  expression  for  the  intensity  of  the  black-process.  But 
as  there  is  no  occasion  for  concerning  ourselves  with  the  separate 
components  of  the  black  and  the  white  material,  we  may  write 
these  equations 

Iw  =  KwMwdt, 

/  =  Ks  M8  dt, 

with  similar  expressions  for  the  two  pairs  of  color-processes. 
This  is  simply  the  mathematical  expression  of  the  fact  that  the 
intensity  of  any  photo-chemical  process  in  the  retina  is  propor- 
tional to  the  amount  which  is  present  of  the  material  of  the  re- 
action in  question.  Stated  in  this  way,  it  does  not  seem  to  be  a 
proposition  which  any  one  need  hesitate  to  admit. 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  theory  of  Professor  Miiller,  in  making 
use  of  the  ideas  of  the  reversible  chemical  -process  and  of  the 
effect  of  mass-action ,  is  a  theory  of  the  very  highest  fashion. 
Let  us  see  in  detail  how  he  overcomes  the  discrepancies  which 
exist  in  the  theory  of  Hering.  A  chief  objection  to  the  view  of 
Hering,  for  those  who  have  been  interested  in  its  theoretical  as- 
pect, is  the  inconsistency  which  meets  us  at  the  very  beginning ; 
why  should  black  and  white  be  regarded  as  an  antagonistic 
sensation-pair,  when  they  do  not  destroy  each  other,  but  give 
us,  on  the  contrary,  the  whole  series  of  grays?  Professor 
Miiller,  in  his  general  rectification  of  Hering's  theory,  has  de- 
vised an  ingenious  means  of  meeting  this  difficulty.  He 
assumes  that  the  black  and  white  chemical  processes  do  exactly 
neutralize  each  other  when  they  take  place  in  equal  amounts  in 
the  retina,  but  that  there  is  a  continuous  black-white  excitation 
going  on  in  the  cortex  (unaccompanied  by  any  color-excitation) , 
that  that  is  the  cause  of  the  so-called  self-light  of  the  retina — 
the  faint  gray  sensation  which  we  are  never  free  from  though 
the  eyes  are  closed — and  that  any  gray  excitation  sent  up 


MULLENS    THEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  79 

from  the  retina  is  added  to  or  subtracted  from  this  endog- 
enous cortical  excitation,  corresponding  to  an  antagonistic 
pair  of  colors,  according  as  the  black  or  the  white  predominates 
in  it.  If  the  black  and  white  processes  are  equal  in  amount,  no 
additional  excitation  of  the  brain  is  sent  up  from  the  retina,  and 
the  self-light  is  the  only  sensation  experienced.  But  this  is  to 
introduce  a  fresh  difficulty  as  serious  as  the  one  which  it  is  at- 
tempted to  remove.  Why  should  not  the  yellow-blue  substance 
of  the  cortex  be  subject  to  a  continuous  excitation  as  well  as  the 
black-white  substance?  If  the  two  pairs  of  chemical  processes 
must  be  so  unlike  in  the  end,  why  take  the  trouble  to  make  them 
so  like  in  the  beginning?  The  situation  is  this  :  for  sensation, 
black  and  white  constitute  a  psychic-quality  series  (in  the  above 
defined  sense  of  the  term),  while  yellow  and  blue  do  not ;  as  re- 
gards the  assumed  chemical  -processes^  the  one  for  the  yellow- 
blue  series  is  finally  antagonistic  in  the  retina,  while  the  one  for 
the  black-white  series  must  have  a  distinct  and  additional  pro- 
cess which  can  be  superimposed  upon  it  in  the  cortex.  Is  it  not 
much  simpler  to  admit  once  for  all  that  black  and  white  do  not 
stand  to  each  other  in  the  same  relation  as  yellow  and  blue  (nor 
as  red  and  grehn)  ?  Why  force  them  into  an  unnatural  resem- 
blance which  they  must  immediately  afterwards  be  despoiled  of? 
Why  introduce  a  wholly  unnecessary  difficulty  into  a  theory 
merely  for  the  sake  of  showing  with  what  ingenuity  it  can  after- 
wards be  done  away  with?  This  whole  construction  of  chemi- 
cal processes  is  at  best  purely  an  imaginary  one  ;  absolutely  the 
only  virtue  that  it  can  have  is  the  virtue  of  consistency.  The 
idea  of  black  and  white  occupying  the  same  place,  in  a  proposed 
system  of  explanations,  with  a  disappearing  color-pair  is,  von 
vorn  herein,  most  causeless  and  most,  unfortunate,  and  no 
amount  of  bolstering  up  by  subsidiary  hypotheses  can  make  it 
anything  else.  Professor  Miiller's  real  ground  for  executing 
this  tour  de  force  is  that  he  conceives  it  to  be  demanded  by  the 
phenomena  of  constrast,  successive  and  simultaneous.  The 
fact  that  unless  black  and  white  are  regarded  as  a  perfectly  con- 
gruent sensation-pair  with  yellow  and  blue  (and  red  and  grehn), 
the  explanations  of  contrast  and  of  after-image  do  not  run 
exactly  part  passu  for  colored  and  for  colorless  sensations,  is 


So  C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

regarded  by  Miiller  as  a  fatal  objection  to  every  theory  except 
his  own  and  that  of  Hering.  As  matter  of  fact,  Helmholtz  gave 
too  much  importance  to  the  psychical  elements  involved  in  con- 
trast, and  we  are  all  now  convinced  that  the  correct  explanation 
is  to  be  looked  for  along  physiological  lines — a  conviction  which 
we  owe  to  Professor  Hering  and  one  for  which  our  gratitude  is 
due  him.  But  every  explanation  of  contrast  which  can  be  given 
in  the  language  of  Hering  and  of  Miiller  can  be  given  just  as 
consistently  in  the  language  of  any  of  the  complementary  color 
theories ;  it  is  true  that  it  will  read  a  little  differently  according 
as  the  contrast  to  be  explained  is  one  of  colored  or  of  uncolored 
surfaces,  but  that,  instead  of  being  a  defect,  is  altogether  a  point 
of  merit ;  since  the  grays  do  not  constitute  a  series  of  the  same 
nature  as  the  mixtures  of  yellow  with  blue  (or  of  red  with  grehn) , 
it  is  a  feature  of  extreme  ineptitude  when  their  contrast-effects 
are  explained  in  exactly  the  same  language. 

An  admirable  chapter  in  Professor  Miiller's  work  is  his  dis- 
cussion of  the  visual  purple,  as  it  was  unfortunately  named, 
since  it  is  now  known  pretty  positively  that  it  is  not  a  chemical 
basis  for  vision  any  more  than  it  is  -purple  in  color,  in  the  Eng- 
lish meaning  of  that  term.  Professor  Miiller  adopts  my  as- 
sumption that  the  rod-pigment  ( as  I  prefer  to  name  it)  is  a 
secondary  means  for  securing  adaptation  to  a  faint  light,  and 
not  directly  a  vision-producing  substance  at  all  ;  I  suppose 
that  it  acts  by  absorbing  (for  the  purpose  of  re-enforcing  faint- 
light  vision)  a  large  amount  of  the  light  which  usually  passes 
entirely  through  the  transparent  rods  and  cones  to  be  lost  in 
the  choroid  coat,  and  Professor  Miiller  takes  it  as  acting  as  a 
sensibilisator,  in  the  photographer's  sense  of  the  term.  In  Pro- 
fessor Miiller's  assumption,  its  color  has  no  significance.  In 
mine  it  is  of  great  importance ;  it  is  adapted  to  aiding  vision  in 
the  gloomy  depths  of  forests,  because  green  light  is  the  light 
which  it  absorbs  ;  and  fishes,  which  alone,  of  all  vetebrates,  have 
a  rod-pigment  of  a  distinctly  different  color,  are  exactly  fitted 
for  utilizing  the  last  rays  of  the  light  which  penetrates  deep  into 
the  water  of  the  sea.  v.  Kries  opposes  this  view,  and  he  is  led 
thereby  into  countless  inconsistences  and  contradictions  ( espe- 
cially in  regard  to  the  gray-vision  of  the  periphery  of  the  normal 


MULLERS    THEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  8 1 

eye ).     He  goes   so  far  as  to  regard  the  rods  as  functionless 
whenever  they  lack  their  purple  coloring  substance.1 

The  progress  of  our  knowledge  of  color-blindness  forms  one 
of  the  interesting  chapters  in  the  history  of  science.  The 
Young-Helmholtz  theory  of  three  (instead  of  four)  fundamental 
colors  having  been  taken  as  fact  instead  of  theory,  the  conclu- 
sion was  jumped  at  that  a  defect  in  color-vision  must  consist  in 
the  absence  of  some  one  or  more  of  these  three  colors,  and  the 
common  forms  of  the  defect  were  described  as  red-blindness 
and  as  green-blindness.  By  a  very  brilliant  piece  of  reason- 
ing, it  was  discovered,  about  1850,  by  William  Pole,  F.R.S. 
(professor  of  Engineering  in  University  College,  London,  and 
author  of  the  well-known  work  on  whist),  who  is  himself  color- 
blind, that  as  matter  of  fact  the  sensations  experienced  in  both 
cases  are  blue  and  yellow^  instead  of  blue  and  red  or  blue  and 
green.  This  discovery  did  not  awaken  as  much  interest  as  it 
ought  to  have  done,  and  the  reasoning  by  which  it  is  established, 
cogent  as  it  is,  did  not  prove  convincing  to  all ;  Sir  John  Her- 
schel  said,  "  What  the  sensations  of  the  color-blind  really  are 
we  shall  never  know  with  certainty."  It  happened  not  to  occur 
to  him  that  there  was  a  possibility  of  some  individual  being  color- 
blind in  one  eye  only.  It  was  only  after  the  true  state  of  the 
case  had  been  put  wholly  beyond  question  by  several  cases  of 
monocular  color-blindness  that  it  became  matter  of  common 
knowledge — in  fact,  it  continues  to  be  most  unaccountably  ig- 
nored in  England  to  the  present  day.  This  fact,  that  the  senses 
for  red  and  for  green  are  lost  together  and  that  the  color- 

1  It  has  lately  been  affirmed  by  Sherman  and  others  that  there  is  a  certain 
amount  of  change  in  the  relative  brightness  of  the  different  portions  of  the  spec- 
trum for  the  rodless  regions  of  the  retina  when  the  light  is  diminished — that  is, 
that  the  Purkinje  phenomenon  is  not  wholly  wanting  there — an  amount  so  small 
however,  that  it  has  been  denied  to  exist  by  other  observers.  This  would  be  a  fact 
very  damaging  to  the  assigning  of  the  adaptation -function  to  the  visual  purple,  if 
it  could  not  be  explained.  It  can,  however,  be  explained  very  easily.  Kiihne, 
who  is  still  the  chief  authority  on  changes  in  the  photo-chemical  substancesof  the 
retina,  expressly  states  that  the  yellow  coloring  matter  of  the  macula  is  subject 
to  a  slight  change  in  quantity  with  a  changing  intensity  of  the  illumination;  the 
change  in  relative  value  of  the  blue  sensation  which  is  affirmed  to  exist  by  Sher- 
man is,  therefore,  just  what  is  needed  to  parallel  this  physiological  variation  in 
the  amount  of  a  colored  substance  which  absorbs  blue  light. 


82  C.   LADD  FRANKLIN. 

vision  which  persists  in  these  cases  is  vision  for  blue  and  yellow, 
was  taken,  and  very  properly,  as  working  immensely  to  the  good 
of  the  theory  of  Hering.  But  immediately  it  appeared  that  the 
situation  was  not  so  simple  as  it  had  seemed  to  be  ;  while  the 
warm  end  of  the  spectrum  is  seen  by  all  alike  as  yellow,  never- 
theless there  are  still  two  classes  of  these  defectives  as  regards 
ivhat  -part  of  the  warm  end  of  the  spectrum  is  seen  to  be  of  the 
brightest  yellow ;  and  these  classes  are  totally  distinct — there 
are  no  intermediate  cases.  It  is  as  if  red-vision  had  fallen  out 
and  green-vision  had  been  turned  into  yellow-vision  for  the 
one  sort ;  and  for  the  other  sort  it  is  as  if  green-vision  had  fallen 
out  and  yellow-vision  had  taken  the  place  of  red-vision.  Hering 
denied  for  a  long  time  that  there  is  anything  in  this  difference, 
more  than  can  be  explained  by  individual  differences  in  the 
yellow  coloring  matter  of  the  macula.  But  Miiller  admits  the 
fact,  and  endeavors  to  account  for  it.  The  red  light  of  the 
spectrum,  he  assumes,  besides  its  effect  on  the  red-green  sub- 
stance, may  have  also  an  effect  on  the  yellow-blue  substance, 
and  it  may  even  have  two  such  effects — it  may  act  upon  it  in 
the  first  place  directly,  by  producing  out  of  the  decomposition 
of  the  red-green  substance  some  one  or  more  of  the  constituents 
of  the  yellow  material  (with  which,  in  the  original  form  of  the 
hypothesis,  red  light  had  nothing  to  do).  The  first  type  of  the 
red-green  blind — those  formerly  called  red-blind — are  totally 
lacking  in  the  red-green  substance ;  these  are  the  typical  yel- 
low-blue visioned.  But  the  second  type — those  formerly  called 
green-blind — see  yellow  in  the  place  of  both  red  and  green  for 
some  totally  different  reason — either  because  the  nervous  fibres 
which  conduct  the  retinal  excitation  are  not  of  the  normal  con- 
stitution, or  because  some  still  other  constituent  which  is  usually 
found  already  prepared  in  the  retina  is  now  absent.  In  this 
fashion  it  will  be  seen  that  the  so-called  red-blind  lack  all  the 
indirect  effect  of  the  light  of  the  spectrum  upon  the  yellow-blue 
substance,  while  that  indirect  effect  still  persists  for  the  green- 
blind.  It  is  plain  that  this  is  an  explanation  which  is  compli- 
cated and  far-fetched  in  the  extreme. 

The  value  of  a  theory  which  is  offered   as  explanation  of 
any  series  of  connected  facts  can  be  determined  only  by  the 


MULLERS   THEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  83 

method  of  comparison  with  the  other  theories  which  it  is  pro- 
posed that  it  should  replace.  Any  theory  is  better  than  no 
theory,  and  the  theories  of  Newton,  Young,  Helmholtz  and 
Hering  have  filled  a  useful  function  in  giving  direction  to  the 
immense  amount  of  work  which  has  been  expended  upon  this 
subject  in  laboratories.  But  as  soon  as  theories  are  thought  out 
which  offer  a  more  probable  and  a  more  natural  conception  as 
to  the  nature  of  the  unattainable  link  between  external  light  and 
conscious  light-sensation,  then  the  usefulness  of  the  provisional 
theories  is  at  an  end.  It  has  been  said,  within  a  few  years,  by 
the  Vice-President  of  this  Section,  who  is  also  one  of  the  editors 
of  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  that  the  best  theories  now  in  the 
field  are  the  theory  of  Bonders,  that  of  Wundt  and  my  own ; 
in  this  opinion  I  heartily  concur  !  In  all  of  these  theories  the 
attempt  (which  is  fore- doomed  to  failure)  to  represent  the  black- 
white  series  as  of  the  same  nature  as  a  self-destroying  color- 
pair,  although  it  is  plainly  a  non-self-destroying  pair  of  sensa- 
tions, is  given  up.  Black  is  regarded  as  a  sensation  which  is 
connected  with  white  not  differently  from  the  way  in  which  it 
is  connected  with  blue  or  with  green,  or  that  in  which  blue  and 
green  are  connected  with  each  other.  By  this  means  the  in- 
genuity which  is  required  to  explain  the  fact  that  black  and 
white  do  not  destroy  each  other  is  rendered  unnecessary — there 
is  no  reason  why  they  should  destroy  each  other,  for  they  are 
in  no  sense  antagonistic.  These  three  theories  are  all  of  the 
physiological  type :  the  cause  of  the  mutual  destruction  of  a 
color-pair  is  in  the  retina  and  not  in  the  imagination.  Two  of 
them  are  of  the  component  type ;  the  other  (that  of  Wundt)  is 
of  the  antagonistic  type.  Wundt,  as  matter  of  fact,  assumes 
more  than  four  elementary  colors,  but  there  is  no  reason  what- 
ever why  he  should  do  so.  If  Wundt  were  to  accept  Professor 
Miiller's  demonstration  of  the  fact  that  there  are,  for  conscious- 
ness, just  four — no  more  and  no  less — elementary  colors,  and  if 
he  were  to  translate  into  the  language  of  his  own  theory  all  the 
Hering-Muller  explanations  of  contrast  and  after-image  (which 
are,  in  reality,  not  explanations  at  all,  in  the  correct  sense  of 
the  term),  his  theory  would  be  an  admirable  one. 

My  own  theory  possesses  the  simple  advantage  that  it  is  able 


84  C.   LADD  FRANKLIN. 

to  assume  all  the  good  points  of  all  the  other  theories,  and  to 
avoid  all  their  bad  points  !  It  takes  on,  for  instance,  the  whole 
doctrine  of  the  color-triangle,  which  is  a  bete  noire  for  Hering, 
but  which  nevertheless  is  the  expression  of  a  vast  body  of  fact 
in  the  domain  of  color-mixture ;  and  it  takes  on  the  whole  new 
doctrine  of  the  perceptible  psychic  quality  series  of  Miiller, 
which  renders  absolutely  necessary  the  assumption  of  four  ele- 
mentary colors  instead  of  three,  but  which  is  destructive  to 
Miiller's  own  hypothesis,  because  the  green  which  it  takes  as 
elementary  cannot  possibly  be  both  an  end  member  of  a  psychic- 
quality  series  and  the  antagonistic  color  to  red.1  Moreover,  there 
is  no  explanation  of  any  fact  of  contrast  which  is  given  by  the 
theory  of  Miiller  which  cannot  be  given  just  as  well  by  my 
theory  and  in  quite  parallel  terms.  The  idea  of  a  partial 
chemical  decomposition  is  in  no  sense  more  speculative  than 
that  of  a  reversible  chemical  process.  A  reversible  chemical 
action  has  no  distinct  analogy  in  any  other  known  physiological 

1  While  my  theory  assumes  four  fundamental  colors,  red  and  green  are 
nevertheless  not  complementary.  I  represent  diagrammatically  the  progressive 
development  of  a  color-substance  in  the  retina  in  this  way  : 

I.  II.  III. 

o 

o        o-o         11=0 
o 

I  suppose  that  a  primitive  undifferentiated  substance  is  composed  of  mole- 
cules which  (though  they  maybe  of  any  degree  of  complexity)  are  indifferently 
completely  destroyed  by  light  of  every  wave-length ;  thus  in  a  later  stage  this 
substance  consists,  in  each  of  its  molecules,  of  two  distinct  parts,  one  fitted  to 
be  shaken  to  pieces  by  light  from  the  warm  end  of  the  spectrum  and  the  other 
by  light  from  the  cold  end  of  the  spectrum ;  and  that  in  a  third  stage  of  devel- 
opment the  yellow-producing  constituent  is  in  its  turn  broken  up  into  two  parts 
of  such  different  internal  vibrative  periods  that  they  respond  respectively  to  the 
red  light  and  the  green  light  of  the  spectrum.  (It  cannot  be  said  that  there  is  any- 
thing repugnant  to  the  ideas  of  the  chemists  in  this  representation  of  molecules  ; 
this  very  diagram  III.  has  lately  been  used  in  another  connection  as  a  picture  of 
a  molecule  byDuclaux.)  Partial  color  blindness  is  an  atavistic  condition  in 
which  the  second  stage  of  development  is  permanent,  and  in  total  color-blind- 
ness the  entire  color  substance  remains  in  the  primitive  condition  in  which  gray 
is  the  only  sensation  produced.  Blue  and  yellow  are  complementary  colors,  but 
red  and  green,  when  acting  in  conjunction,  re-compose  the  yellow-producing 
substance  out  of  which  they  have  been  developed,  instead  of  together  mak- 
ing white.  In  other  words,  the  fundamental  green  of  this  theorjr  is  a  real 
green,  and  not  the  evident  blue-green  of  Hering. 


MULLERS   THEORY  OF  THE  LIGHT-SENSE.  85 

process ;  but  we  have  not  far  to  go  for  an  analogy  for  a  partial 
chemical  decomposition — the  retina  itself  presents  in  the  rod- 
pigment  (which  is  first  broken  down  into  a  yellow  substance 
and  then  into  a  colorless  substance)  exactly  the  analogy  which 
is  required.  And  this  is  not  all :  it  seems  to  have  been  made 
out  by  Hamburger  and  by  Kottgen  and  Abelsdorff  that  this  de- 
composition in  two  successive  stages  occurs  in  no  animals  lower 
than  man ;  this  is  an  instance  of  a  progressive  differentiation  of 
function  in  an  adjunct  photo-chemical  substance  which  is  ex- 
actly what  is  needed  to  form  a  parallel  case  with  the  develop- 
ment of  a  color-substance  subject  to  a  partial  decomposition  out 
of  an  undifferentiated  gray-substance,  which  is  what  my  theory 
requires. 


SHORTER  CONTRIBUTIONS   AND   REPORTS. 

PROFESSOR  GROOS  AND  THEORIES  OF  PLAY. 

Professor  Groos's  book  on  Animal  Play — to  which  renewed  atten- 
tion is  given  by  its  appearance  in  English  dress — invites  discussion  and 
criticism  from  several  points  of  view.  In  the  first  place,  we  must  re- 
gret that  human  play  is  deferred  for  separate  treatment,  for  assuredly 
the  child  is  preeminently  animal  in  its  plays.  A  monkey  which  de- 
lights in  snapping  open  a  match-safe  and  a  child  which  does  the  same 
are  at  the  same  stage  and  should  be  treated  together.  To  divide  plays 
into  animal  and  human,  and  animal,  into  plays  of  birds,  mammals, 
etc.,  has  little  significance. 

Professor  Groos  sets  forth  elaborately  the  practice  theory  of  play. 
Play  is  the  expression  of  developing  instinctive  tendencies,  an  antici- 
patory, tentative  practicing,  which  accomplishes  no  immediate  serious 
service.  Thus  the  kitten  pounces  on  the  straying  leaf,  and  so  prac- 
tices for  pouncing  on  its  prey.  We  may  express  it  by  saying  that  Na- 
ture here  shows  her  prentice  hand,  or  that  here  is  Nature's  school,  but 
no  forced  attendance,  no  specified  time,  no  set  lessons,  and  only  free, 
spontaneous,  pleasant  activity.  Under  natural  selection  this  play 
period  of  instinct  has  been  developed,  wherein  the  energies  of  the  pro- 
tected young  act  in  non-serious  forms  in  preparation  for  mature  life. 

To  this  theory  of  play  we  must  object  that  instinct  as  such  needs 
not  practice,  and  again  that  instinct  fully  formed  at  birth  is  the  more 
advantageous.  If  the  kitten  could  at  once  seize  a  mouse  as  a  chick 
does  a  grain  of  wheat,  it  would  be  much  to  its  advantage.  If  the 
prey  of  cats  were  of  definite  size,  color  and  motion,  and  always  ap- 
peared at  the  same  distance,  an  instinct  would  work  at  the  first  occa- 
sion; but  as  it  is,  instinct  cannot  cover  the  varying  complexity, 
but  intelligent  play  practice  is  called  in.  The  kitten  has  the  in- 
stinct to  spring,  but  the  regulating  for  size,  distance,  etc.,  is  acquired 
intelligently.  The  learning  may  be  by  hereditary  impulse,  but  yet  it 
is  better  to  define  play  in  terms  of  intelligence  rather  than  in  terms 
of  instinct. 

But  much  of  the  developing  activity  of  animals  can  scarcely  be 
brought  under  the  term  play  as  psychic.  Thus  the  young  bird,  flut- 
86 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  87 

tering  and  trying  its  wings,  seems  not  playing,  but  serious,  as  also  the 
child  taking  its  first  steps.  But  when  the  bird  becomes  skilled  in  fly- 
ing, it  flits  playfully,  and  when  the  child  is  able  to  run  easily,  it  de- 
lights in  running  plays.  A  large  proportion  of  Professor  Groos's 
examples  of  play  fall  under  work.  The  imperfect,  immature,  prac- 
tice is  not  thereby  play,  as,  for  instance,  the  calf  sucks  your  finger  as 
seriously  as  it  does  the  teat.  Real  sucking  play  we  see  in  children 
sucking  through  straws.  Play  belongs  to  childhood  rather  than  to  in- 
fancy, though  both  are  full  of  developing  activities. 

We  must,  then,  dissent  from  bringing  all  the  inceptive  preliminary 
activities  of  young  animals  under  play.  Further,  it  is  not  proved  that 
play  as  fact  of  biologic  history  originates  in  these  activities.  Has  it 
yet  been  shown  that  play  does  not  appear  first  as  life  method  among 
organisms  adult  from  the  start,  long  before  a  youth  period  emerges  ? 
Some  micro-organisms  seem  to  swim  playfully,  and  a  sham  alarming 
and  attacking  is  seen  among  adults  low  in  the  scale  of  life.  It  is  quite 
conceivable  that  play  started  with  adult  practice,  and  was  conserved 
and  developed  through  natural  selection,  at  length  becoming  most 
prominent  in  earliest  phases  of  life  period,  and  so  making  the  youth 
time.  The  adult  practicing  among  his  mates  must  be  harmless,  and 
so  easily  became  sportive,  that  is,  practice-work  became  play,  a  pleas- 
ing method  of  unreality. 

Another  outlook  for  the  origin  of  play  is  in  the  one-sided  form, 
teasing.  A  very  combative  animal,  having  no  enemy  to  fight,  will 
be  led  to  attack  its  mates,  but  not  violently,  as  that  would  break  up  all 
its  associations,  but  teasingly.  This  tendency  is  so  strong  in  the  horse 
that  we  have  the  term  '  to  nag.'  The  tricks  of  boys  and  the  chaffing 
and  practical  jokes  of  men  are  plainly  a  low  form  of  play,  and  per- 
haps point  toward  the  primitive  form.  The  scare  game  is  also  a  very 
popular  and  crude  play  with  animals  and  children.  To  rouse  real 
though  groundless  fear  gives  an  aboriginal  delight  in  sense  of  power 
both  to  achieve  and  deceive.  After  a  time  the  teased  one  would  learn 
that  its  best  defense  is  not  to  resent,  but  to  play  back,  and  hence  arises 
full,  two-sided,  mutual  play.  The  teasing  hypothesis  of  the  origin  of 
play  is,  like  practice  of  young  or  adult,  a  possible  mode  which  ought 
to  be  kept  in  mind  by  the  investigator. 

One  point  which  deserves  notice  in  this  connection,  but  which 
does  not  appear  to  be  touched  on  by  Professor  Groos,  is  the  relation 
of  the  play  of  domestic  animals  to  the  play  of  their  wild  congeners. 
Though  the  dog  has  been  domesticated  for  millenniums,  its  play  is  wild 
and  wolfish,  and  so  contrary  to  practice  for  its  adult  life.  The  colt 


88  THEORIES    OF  PL  A  Y. 

in  its  play  rears,  kicks  and  bites — wild  habits  which  have  to  be  over- 
come in  its  domestic  life.  The  colt  does  not  play  at  drawing  loads, 
nor  the  collie  at  driving  sheep.  Selection  by  man  is  but  a  kind  of 
natural  selection,  and  we  might  expect  some  preparatory  play,  or  at 
least  some  reduction  in  the  period  of  wild  play.  But  is  this  the  case? 
Though  young  domestic  animals  do  not  have  tame  plays,  yet  they  may 
play  at  work  taught  by  man,  as  the  elephants  at  Bridgeport  sometimes 
playfully  practice  standing  on  their  heads.  It  is  probable  that  many 
wild  animals  are  more  playful  than  their  tame  congeners  largely  because 
intelligence  and  alertness  are  more  required  in  the  wild  state.  Wild 
sheep  are  a  case  in  point.  But  if  man  had  bred  the  sheep  for  intelli- 
gence rather  than  wool,  would  not  the  domestic  sheep  be  more  play- 
ful than  the  wild  ?  Some  breeds  of  dogs,  being  bred  for  their  play- 
fulness, are  doubtless  far  more  playful  than  any  wild  dogs.  But  what 
we  need  here,  as  everywhere  on  play,  are  data. 

Another  point  which  is  not  considered  by  Professor  Groos  is  the 
close  relationship  of  play  and  work,  which  requires  a  study  of  both  to 
understand  either.  The  life  of  animals  and  children  is  a  complex  of 
play  and  work,  a  rapid  passing  from  one  to  the  other.  Man,  adult 
and  civilized,  is  the  only  persistent  player  or  worker.  Birds  in  build- 
ing or  nesting  seem  to  be  continually  interrupting  play  with  work  and 
work  with  play.  A  boy  begins  to  pile  wood  in  the  shed  as  play,  but 
as  soon  as  it  is  felt  to  be  work  he  ceases,  unless  you  offer  a  wage. 
The  start  is  often  play,  but  the  continuance  work.  In  most  plays  the 
pressure  of  companions  makes  some  continue  playing  against  inclina- 
tion, that  is,  makes  them  work.  From  dead  earnest  to  pure  play  is  a 
long  series  of  mergent  psychoses.  Pure  play  and  work  are  rare,  most 
activities  being  merely  dominantly  one  or  other. 

We  have  noted  that  preparatory  activity  of  young  is  not  always 
play,  and  vice  versa.  Thus  the  fledgling,  coaxed  and  compelled  in 
its  learning  to  fly  by  its  parents,  is  plainly  working,  and  the  colt  rear- 
ing, kicking,  and  doing  just  what  he  must  not  do  as  adult,  is  plainly 
playing.  Now,  both  reversion  and  recapitulation  are  practically  ig- 
nored by  Professor  Groos.  But  it  is  certainly  worth  inquiring 
whether  play  tendencies  of  survival  origin  may  not  exist,  say  among 
monkeys.  Is  not  there  a  general  psychic  embryology  which  has  play 
forms  ?  The  place  for  reversion  in  the  play  of  youth  is  evident  in 
such  actions  as  climbing,  swinging,  playing  with  stones,  animal  plays 
and  plays  with  animals,  deceit  plays — civilization  is  founded  on  truth 
— hunting,  fishing,  camping.  That  these  latter  sports  appeal  little  to 
the  gentler  sex  may  be  due  to  the  inherited  reminiscence  of  camp 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  89 

drudgery  of  savage  life,  and  the  fact  that  the  excitement  of  the  chase 
was  not  then  their  part.  Indeed,  anticipatory  play  is  more  common 
with  woman  than  reversionary,  because  reversion  is  mainly  joyless.  If 
the  work  methods  of  past  life  are  the  plays  of  to-day's  life,  the  works 
of  to-day  will  be  the  play  of  '  beyond-man'  millenniums  hence. 

If  we  divide  all  conscious  activities  into  work  and  play,  we  have 
a  difficulty  in  distinguishing  them  in  the  plexus  of  life.  Take  the 
commonest  actions  in  daily  routine,  as  the  morning  toilet.  Here, 
many  are  merely  mechanical,  and  so  neither  work  nor  play.  But  so 
far  as  consciousness  enters  it  is  generally  work  for  men  and  play  for 
women.  In  walking  down  town  one  will  often  go  several  times 
through  the  variations  of  work,  play  and  the  mechanical.  But  play  is 
constantly  emerging  in  life  as  activity  for  its  own  sake.  Thereby  it 
is  amateurish,  is  not  a  means,  and  has  no  wage.  Is  then  pleasurable 
work  play?  Professor  Groos  remarks  (p.  253)  that  bird  courtship, 
while  being  set  a  «  real  end,  yet  may  have  the  psychological  aspect  of 
mere  play,'  because  of  4  satisfaction '  in  the  exercise.  But  we  think 
that  4  satisfaction  '  applies  to  work.  Work-pleasure  is  satisfaction  in 
results  achieved  by  effort,  but  play-pleasure  is  not  satisfaction ;  rather 
it  is  the  immediate,  fleeting,  inherent  pleasure  in  the  act  itself.  Fresh, 
free,  joyous  spontaneity  is  the  mark  of  play,  which  begins,  ceases,  re- 
begins  when,  where  and  how  it  pleases.  And  play-pleasure  has  no 
form  of  its  own,  but  is  that  of  power,  skill,  competition,  possession, 
etc.,  that  is  work-pleasure,  so  pointing  to  work  as  the  origin  of  play. 

Professor  Groos's  definition  of  play,  *  instinctive  activity  exerted 
for  purposes  of  practice  or  exercise,  and  without  a  serious  intent/  begs 
the  question.  '  Not  of  serious  intent*  means  play,  and  that  is  what 
he  is  defining.  Practice,  being  less  serious  than  the  thing  practiced, 
easily  degenerates  into  play,  but,  so  becoming  less  efficient  than  seri- 
ous practice,  it  would  not  be  favored  by  natural  selection.  We  often 
see  play  originating  as  degenerate  practice,  as  when  a  company  as- 
semble to  practice  for  an  exhibition,  but  this  completely  spoils  the 
practice.  The  less  playful  practice  is,  the  better  it  is.  We  surely 
grant  all  that  can  be  said  for  practice,  yet  much  play  is  recapitulation 
or  embryologic,  and  reversionary  or  degenerate  or  recreative,  or  it 
may  be  wanton.  Plays  of  the  degenerate  type  are  gambling,  drunk- 
enness, debauchery  and  similar  amusements,  and,  indeed,  all  degener- 
ation belongs  under  play  rather  than  under  work.  In  degenerate 
activities  play  freedom  is  only  subjective;  there  is  really  bondage. 
And  all  play  freedom  is  false  and  unreal  as  being  mere  hereditary 
impulse,  and  in  so  far  as  the  play  world  is  one  of  unreality  and  illu- 


90  THEORIES   OF  PLAY. 

sion.  Rational  and  real  freedom  lies  in  work ;  the  captain  of  an  At- 
lantic liner  has  a  truer  and  higher  freedom  than  a  boy  sailing  a  mimic 
craft  in  a  pond.  It  is  easy  to  idealize  play  as  spontaneous  practice, 
perfectly  free,  pure  and  joyous,  but  at  best  play  is  only  conservative, 
and  very  often  is  reversionary  and  even  degenerate.  Play  is  a  low  form 
of  life ;  and  it  might  be  said  to  be  on  the  whole  of  more  disservice 
than  service,  and  to  be  supplanted  in  the  highest  evolution  of  man  by 
work-satisfaction,  of  which  we  already  see  some  evidences. 

Play,  as  we  have  noted,  may  be  described  as  fresh,  free,  joyous, 
spontaneous,  impulsive,  self-contained  activity,  whether  practice  or  any 
other  mode.  The  unseriousness  of  a  practice  does  not  of  itself  make 
play,  for  the  unseriousness  may  be  carelessness  and  laziness,  the  re- 
verse of  play. 

To  the  elements  of  play  we  have  mentioned  are  we  to  add  sham- 
ming? It  might  seem  that  activity  which  did  not  contain  shamming 
must  be  earnest,  and  so  not  playful,  but  earnestness  enters  into  play, 
and  makes  it  real  play.  In  shamming,  the  activity  is  so  far  unreal, 
and  if  playful,  doubly  so.  That  is  shamming,  deceit,  guile,  is  a  work 
form  of  activity  evolved  in  the  struggle  of  existence,  and  may,  like 
any  other,  become  play.  Shamming  play  is  then  merely  one  definite 
kind,  rather  than,  as  Professor  Groos  would  make  it,  a  phase  general 
to  later  forms.  Much  of  later  play  is  not  mock  activity,  but  a  real 
activity  used  as  a  pleasure  in  itself.  The  boy  driving  his  ponies  is 
playing  as  well  as  the  boy  who  is  playing  horse  by  driving  his  com- 
panion or  riding  a  stick,  and  the  man  yachting  is  playing  as  well  as 
the  child  sailing  chips  in  a  tub.  So  any  activity  once  fully  integrated 
through  work  by  race  or  individual  may  be  either  played  or  played 
at,  both  modes  growing  side  by  side  through  the  whole  history  of  play. 

Professor  Groos  traces  aesthetics  to  shamming  play.  But  the  only 
fine  art  for  which  such  play  could  account  is  realistic  portraiture. 
However,  mere  resemblance  is  not  art.  An  interest  in  clever  counter- 
feits of  reality  for  the  skillful  way  they  deceive  is  plainly  not  the 
aesthetic  feeling  for  the  intrinsic  beauty  of  the  thing.  Do  not  '  What 
a  good  likeness ! '  and  4  What  a  beautiful  picture ! '  indicate  different 
mental  states  ?  Now  the  method  of  development  shows  the  method 
of  origin,  and  the  method  of  progress  in  fine  art  is  plainly  one  of 
severest  toil.  ^Esthetics  must  then  originate  as  work-form  under 
natural  selection  as  mode  of  socialization,  specially  in  sexual  relation, 
and  becoming  integrated,  reappears,  like  other  integrated  activities,  in 
play  form.  Struggle,  effort,  is  the  initiating  and  developing  factor  in 
evolution,  and  how  is  art  an  exception  by  a  unique  relation  to  play  ? 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  91 

To  the  artist  and  art-lover  lart  is  the  most  serious  and  highest  work. 
If  art  originated  in  shamming  play  we  should  expect  the  earliest  art- 
plays  of  children  to  have  this  form.  But  we  see  children  showing  a 
crude  aesthetic  enjoyment  in  whistling  and  drumming,  which  cannot 
be  accounted  deceptive  play.  Woodpecker  music — unnoticed  by  Pro- 
fessor Groos — is  a  similar  play.  So  also  if  animals  and  children  show 
aesthetic  appreciation  of  bright  colors,  this  cannot  be  based  on  decep- 
tiveness.  (We  have  discussed  the  subject  more  fully  in  4  Evolutionary 
Psychology  of  Feeling,'  Chapter  XVII.) 

As  to  classification  of  plays  Professor  Groos's  scheme  is  certainly 
not  shown  to  be  a  complete  and  connected  natural  whole.  He  omits 
humor,  which  ought  to  be  discussed  as  a  possible  play  with  the  very 
highest  animals ;  and  scare  plays  are  unnoticed.  My  dog  took  the 
same  delight  in  coming  up  quietly  behind  a  small  dog  and  giving  a 
terrifying  bark  as  does  the  child  in  jumping  out  from  a  corner  and 
crying  boo !  Fighting  and  hunting  plays  are  hardly  to  be  separated 
as  two  distinct  kinds.  He  makes  the  rationale  of  fighting  play 
among  non-predacious  animals  to  be  preparation  for  struggle  for  the 
female ;  but  do  not  also  young  females  fight,  and  may  not  such  fight- 
ing be  preparatory  to  struggle  for  food  and  for  defense  of  young  ? 
He  makes  courtship  a  division  of  plays,  but  it  is  plain  that  4  calf  love ' 
and  flirtation  are  in  strict  sense  the  only  love  plays,  that  is,  playing 
love  and  playing  at  love.  Again  does  not  imitative  play  enter  into 
all  kinds  of  play? 

But  what  we  need  as  a  basis  of  classification  is  a  thorough  scien- 
tific record  and  study  of  the  facts.  For  instance,  a  continuous  study 
of  a  dog  from  birth  to  death  for  play  and  work  with  photographs  and 
phonograms  would  be  a  first  step  in  a  science  of  play,  if  made  by  a 
psychologist  familiar  with  dogs.  The  records  which  Professor  Groos 
uses,  as  made  by  travellers  and  naturalists,  are  mostly  incidental  ob- 
servations of  slight  value.  However,  it  is  plain  that,  since  any  volun- 
tary activity  may  be  played,  the  classification  of  such  activities  be- 
comes that  of  plays  also.  Thus  among  children  even  winking  and 
breathing  may  be  used  playfully,  and  we  also  have  finger  plays,  toe 
plays,  etc.  But  such  an  anatomical  or  physiological  classification  is 
little  fruitful  for  psychology.  It  would  see  more  in  such  stages  as 
simple  play,  play  and  plaything,  playing  at,  player  and  person  played 
to.  As  any  psychosis  may  become  a  play  form,  a  genetic  classifica- 
tion of  psychoses  would  apply  to  plays.  Any  psychosis  well  inte- 
grated as  instinct  in  the  race  or  as  habit  in  the  individual — habit  plays 
are  lawyers'  jokes  among  lawyers,  etc. — may  issue  in  play.  Play  is 


92  A   SPIRITUAL    CONTENT  OF  LIFE. 

a  peculiar  emotion  which  may  invest  any  action.  Play  is  probably 
the  earliest  of  the  complex  emotions.  Its  distinctness  in  kind  is  shown 
by  the  fact  that  we  can  define  it  only  in  terms  of  itself;  when  we  say 
an  action  is  playful  we  have  but  used  the  simplest  terms,  and  every 
one  who  can  play  recognizes  the  peculiar  psychosis  implied.  Play  is 
a  generic  general  phase  of  emotionalism,  which  may  express  itself  in 
the  form  of  any  intellectual  or  feeling  mode  or  of  any  outward  ac- 
tivity. 

HIRAM  M.  STANLEY. 
LAKE  FOREST,  ILL. 


THE  STRUGGLE  FOR  A  SPIRITUAL  CON- 
TENT OF  LIFE.1 

Eucken's  latest  and  most  significant  work  has  as  yet  received  no 
adequate  notice  in  the  English  or  American  philosophical  magazines. 
The  following  is  an  attempt  to  give  the  reader  some  understanding  of 
the  methods  and  conclusions  of  this  remarkable  contribution  to  the 
metaphysics  of  our  time. 

While  the  reviewer  is,  of  course,  responsible  for  the  general  run  of 
the  following,  he  has  taken  the  liberty  of  paraphrasing  the  text  in 
numerous  places.  In  this  connection  it  may  be  well  to  say  that  the 
paper  was  submitted  to  Professor  Eucken,  who  advised  its  publication 
in  its  present  form. 

He  who,  to-day,  raises  the  question  of  the  meaning  of  existence 
and  the  goal  of  our  activity  is  caught  up  not  only  by  the  stream  of  the 
time,  but  also  by  a  great  flood  which  springs  out  of  the  world's  history. 
The  answer  to  which  he  is  carried  is  clear  and  simple.  Man  belongs 
to  nature — he  is  a  part  of  her — body  and  soul.  She  surrounds  us  from 
outside;  she  rules  us  from  within.  She  points  out  to  us  the  only  way 
to  truth.  When  man  in  his  pride  and  strength  turns  from  nature,  his 
home,  and  pictures  to  himself  the  existence  of  an  independent  world 
of  spirit,  he  has  only  fallen  into  error — he  has  only  gone  out  in  search 
of  a  fabulous  realm.  And  this  vain  thought  of  a  spiritual  world  is 
only  a  bar  to  truth  and  to  happiness.  As  such  it  is  to  be  fought  and 
conquered. 

With  this  thought  of  our  time  has  come  a  great  turning-point  in 
history.  Through  it  there  arises  the  hope  of  a  return  to  primitive, 

JDer  Kampf  urn  einen  geistigen  Lebensinhalt ;  von  Rudolf  Eucken,  Profes- 
sor in  Jena.  Veit  &  Comp.,  Leipzig.  1896. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND   REPORTS.  93 

elemental  truth.  Once  more  humanity  shall  be  revived  through  closer 
and  more  intimate  contact  with  nature. 

Into  such  a  relation  to  nature  our  time  has  actually  brought  us. 
And  this  it  was  able  to  do  just  by  means  of  its  incomparably  sharp 
distinction  between  spirit  and  nature.  At  first  both  were  one,  indis- 
tinguishably  woven  together.  The  reflection  of  ancient  times  and  the 
Middle  Ages  spun  around  nature  a  web  of  human  thought.  But  this 
network  was  to  be  broken — nature  was  to  be  seen  in  its  independence, 
in  its  self-existence.  Its  true  being,  as  distinct  from  man,  was  yet  to  be 
distinguished,  and  the  soul,  as  an  evil  spirit,  was  to  be  driven  out. 
This  accomplished,  nature  was  seen  to  be  a  complex  of  spiritless 
masses  and  motions — all  unity  was  dissolved  into  small  and  smallest 
elements,  all  worths  and  ends  as  mere  figments  of  mind  were  banished 
in  behalf  of  a  self-sufficient,  self-satisfying  actuality.  For  in  this 
vision  of  nature,  so  simple  and  so  complete,  where  is  there  place  for 
thought?  in  this  vision  of  world-energy  governed  by  an  imminent  logic 
of  its  own,  where  is  there  room  for  spirit? 

As  soon  as  this  reduction  was  accomplished  and  spirit  was  driven 
out  of  nature,  spirit  and  nature  were  seen  to  be  two  opposing  realms. 
The  independence  of  each  was  recognized.  But  nature  revolted 
against  this  opposition.  She  turned  against  man  in  his  isolation  and 
in  his  alienation.  She  went  out  to  draw  him  to  her  again,  to  sub- 
jugate him.  And  she  succeeded.  That  she  was  successful  was  due 
to  the  very  power  which  man  had  acquired  over  her  by  virtue  of  his 
alienation  from  her. 

The  decay  of  the  vision  of  the  Middle  Ages  and  the  rise  of  an  exact 
natural  science  was  a  triumph  of  man  over  nature,  a  subjugation  of 
the  external  world  through  human  thought.  And  so,  also,  the  applica- 
tion of  technical  knowledge  and  skill.  But,  again,  it  was  in  reality 
the  vanquished  which  was  victorious.  For  the  vision  which  resulted 
from  the  outgoing  of  man  to  the  external  world  to  overcome  it,  was  so 
clear  and  well  ordered  that  it  acquired  a  peculiar  power  and  charm, 
by  virture  of  which  it  was  carried  over  to  the  inner  world.  Our  con- 
cepts of  the  natural  became  so  definite  and  exact  that  on  their  lines 
was  built  up  our  view  of  the  spiritual.  The  more  our  knowledge  of 
the  exterior  world  develops,  the  more  are  we  occupied  with  it ;  the 
more  our  technical  skill  increases,  the  more  is  life  bound  up  in  the  ma- 
chine ;  the  more  power  man  wields  over  nature,  the  more  she  rules  his 
thought,  his  life  and  his  senses.  In  this  manner  man,  who  believed 
that  he  had  subjugated  nature,  was  overcome  by  nature.  And  thus 
we  find  that  the  opposition  between  man  and  nature  has  been  over- 


94  A    SPIRITUAL    CONTENT   OF  LIFE. 

come  by  our  time.  It  has  been  dissolved  by  the  rise  of  our  knowledge 
of  nature  and  by  the  development  of  our  technical  mastery  over  her. 
There  exists  no  longer  a  recognition  of  the  two  independent  worlds, 
each  existing  in  and  for  itself. 

But  the  effect  of  this  dissolution  was  not  the  reduction  of  nature 
to  the  inner  power  by  which  we  came  to  rule  over  her,  but  the  oppo- 
site. Man  has  been  reduced  to  nature.  He  has  become  in  his  thought 
of  himself  a  mere  moment  in  the  world  processes,  an  insignificant  fac- 
tor in  the  varied  interplay  of  phenomena.  In  the  laws  which  grind 
out  the  world  he  must  find  his  satisfaction;  in  the  hard  actuality 
which  opposes  him  he  must  see  the  end  of  his  existence.  He  falls 
back  again  into  nature ;  there  is  a  return  to  the  naive  view  of  the 
world  in  which  man  and  nature  are  one. 

And  in  this  philosophy  of  our  time  is  there  not  a  certain  sublimity  ? 
He  who  would  give  up  his  self-existent  spiritual  world,  who  would 
again  turn  himself  out  into  nature,  must  be  prepared  to  leave  behind 
many  a  desire  cherished  through  centuries.  But  the  reward  of  this 
self-denial  is  the  falling  down  of  the  barriers  between  humanity  and 
the  all. 

But  sublime  as  this  philosophy  is;  as  deeply  rooted  in  our  time  as 
it  is ;  as  strongly  as  the  current  of  world  history  forces  it  upon  us — we 
must  still  raise  the  question  as  to  whether  it  can  be  our  philosophy. 
For  if  it  be  true,  our  ethics  and  our  religion  lose  their  significance ;  if 
it  be  true,  a  really  developing  life  is  no  longer  possible;  if  it  be  true, 
there  is,  in  short,  no  spiritual  world  at  all.  It  is  the  primal  thesis  of 
our  work  that  it  is  not  true.  It  is  the  central  belief  of  our  author  that 
man  has  broken  through  nature — that  there  exists  in  and  for  itself  a 
self -centered  spiritual  world. 

Of  the  thesis  let  us  at  the  start  make  sure.  Nature  knows  of  no 
working  from  within,  no  being  for  itself,  no  self-activity,  no  initiative 
of  the  thing.  Rather  every  element  is  bound  to  its  environment,  it 
exists  only  as  a  link  in  an  endless  chain ;  all  work  is  the  result  of 
stimulus  from  without  and  is  directed  to  another.  If  we  men  were 
mere  things  in  nature,  time  and  space  would  completely  dominate ; 
by  them  we  would  be  forever  limited  and  hemmed  in.  But  the  old 
opinion  is  false ;  man  transcends  time — it  is  his  very  nature  to  rise 
above  the  temporal  flow.  True,  we  stand  in  time  and  seem  to  be 
driven  about  in  its  stream.  But  not  quite.  Were  it  so,  human  his- 
tory would  be  impossible,  for  such  a  history  does  not  arise  in  a  mere 
flowing  by  of  events.  In  order  that  there  may  be  a  history  man  may 
not  merely  live  his  span  of  years,  but  he  must  reach  back  into  the 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  95 

past ;  that  which  is  gone  must  become  present ;  he  must  unroll  the 
course  of  time  anew.  And  in  doing  this  we  do  not  merely  contem- 
plate the  past :  we  take  it  up  into  our  life ;  it  becomes  a  part  of  our 
doing;  it  complements  the  present.  Through  history  the  limitation 
and  contingency  of  the  moment  are  overcome ;  through  history  we 
conquer  time.  And  so  with  space. 

And  thus  through  history  there  arises  a  unity  which  transcends 
time  and  space.  This  unity  is  more  than  a  mere  summation — it  is  a 
welding  of  the  life  of  the  past  with  the  life  of  the  present.  But  as 
such  it  transcends  nature.  For  nature  is  dominated  by  time  and  space. 
And  in  nature  there  is  no  unity  which  is  not  a  mere  being  together — a 
mere  summation.  Man  as  a  part  of  nature  is  a  mere  point — like  other 
parts — the  mere  point  of  self-preservation.  An  inner  subordination  of 
the  one  to  the  whole,  the  recognition  of  the  right  and  love  of  another 
as  products  of  nature  were  wonders,  compared  with  which  the  wonders 
of  the  religions  pale.  From  time  immemorial  the  energies  of  man 
have  endeavored  to  reduce  the  source  of  all  action  to  the  mere  interest 
of  the  individual.  But  through  all  time  the  self-sacrifice  of  man 
stands  out  in  protest.  What  has  the  overcoming  of  self  to  do  with  the 
interest  of  self  ?  Are  the  heroes  and  martyrs  only  sharper  Jews  than 
the  rest  of  us  ?  Is  not  all  this  a  protest  against  a  mere  natural  ordering 
of  things  ?  In  our  history  and  art,  in  our  ethics  and  religion,  in  our 
very  penetration  of  the  external  world,  have  we  not  overcome  nature  ? 

These  facts  of  human  life  are  the  proof  of  our  thesis.  Through 
them  we  see  the  necessity  of  the  existence  of  an  independent  world  of 
spirituality  over  against  nature. 

But  this  new  reality  did  not  fall  as  a  ripe  fruit  into  the  lap  of  man ; 
it  does  not  surround  us  as  something  given.  It  was  fought  for  through 
work  and  experience ;  it  was  produced  by  self-activity ;  it  is  the  result 
of  a  long  and  fierce  struggle.  For  the  mere  natural  processes  could 
never  have  produced  this  spirituality — it  must  be  the  result  of  a  free 
act,  a  transcending  of  nature  through  self-activity. 

The  first  step  in  the  struggle  for  a  spiritual  life  was  the  lifting  of 
ourselves  above  the  mere'  natural  environment,  a  freeing  of  ourselves 
from  the  limitation  and  narrowness  of  the  immediate,  a  breaking  away 
from  the  life  which  exhausts  itself  in  its  effort  to  preserve  itself  and  to 
adapt  itself  to  the  immediate  situation.  For  in  order  to  have  a  spirit- 
ual world  at  all  we  must  transcend  the  here  and  the  now,  we  must 
raise  ourselves  above  the  demands  of  a  natural  environment. 

This  step  marked  the  great  turning-point  in  the  history  of  human- 
ity. It  brought  about  something  utterly  new,  something  opposed  to 


96  A    SPIRITUAL    CONTENT   OF  LIFE. 

the  merely  natural  life.  It  freed  us  from  nature  in  that  it  freed  us 
from  the  bonds  of  the  immediate  and  from  the  littleness  of  the  natural 
self.  For  as  long  as  our  activity  was  consumed  in  a  mere  adjustment 
of  ourselves  to  the  situation  of  the  moment  there  could  be  no  freedom, 
no  opportunity  for  the  creative  work  of  spirit.  As  long  as  ourselves 
were  mere  points,  the  mere  centers  of  natural  instincts,  there  could 
arise  no  spiritual  world.  The  immediateness  of  life  and  the  punctu- 
ality of  the  selves  of  that  life  had  to  be  transcended.  For  the  spirit- 
world  is  not  a  world  which  rests  upon  a  point.  It  is  a  world  which 
rises  above  all  points,  which  embraces  all  reality.  Thus  this  spiritu- 
ality which  arose  out  of  nature  as  a  new  creation  was  a  sphere  which 
floated  above  the  individual.  It  was  a  whole,  a  unity.  For  the  indi- 
vidual as  such  could  never  have  conceived  it,  could  never  have  created 
it.  It  was  the  whole  which  spiritualized  the  individual.  And  the 
spiritual  life  wherever  it  exists  is  something  which  is  not  depend- 
ent upon  any  one  self,  but  something  in  which  the  particular  self  finds 
its  existence.  It  is  always  an  independent,  self-existent  whole.  And 
yet  this  whole  was  brought  about  in  the  creative  activity  of  man.  His 
free  act  is  needed  that  it  come  into  being.  It  found  its  origin  in  a 
union  of  free,  creative  activity  transcending  all  particularity. 

And  what  is  this  common  activity  but  work?1  It  is  the  idea  of 
work  which  marks  the  great  turning-point  in  life.  Through  work 
there  arises  a  new  content  of  life.  By  means  of  work  we  raise  our- 
selves above  the  limitation  and  contingency  of  the  natural  here  and 
now.  For  all  work  arises  out  of  some  transcendent  whole ;  in  it  a  unity 
to  be  realized  is  always  presupposed.  Work  means  life-work,  At 
first  this  unity  is  the  particular  unity,  a  whole  to  be  gotten  by  the  in- 
dividual. But  even  so  the  work  of  the  particular  brings  about  the 
work  of  the  whole.  The  particular  works  are  worked  into  the  work 
of  the  whole.  Reality  is  the  work  of  works. 

As  this  common  reality  is  the  result  of  work,  so  is  work  the  result 
of  transcending  the  immediate  here  and  now — the  product  of  our 
struggle  to  rise  above  the  mediocrity  of  life,  of  our  strife  against  the 
average. 

In  work  we  see  a  new  creation,  something  which  cannot  be  de- 
duced from  the  spiritless  masses  and  motions  of  nature.  It  is  a  self- 
centered  spirituality,  a  self-active  life,  a  world  resting  in  the  struggle 
of  the  whole.  As  such  it  hangs  over  against  nature  and  the  punctual 
self. 

And  thus,  in  conclusion,  we  see  that  the  spiritual  life  has  no  exist- 

1  This  word  is  a  translation  of  Werk  as  distinct  from  Arbeit. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  97 

ence  and  no  meaning,  no  strength  and  no  marrow  without  a  rising 
above  the  average ;  that  no  such  transcendence  is  possible  without 
spiritual  self-activity ;  that  there  is  no  self-activity  at  any  one  point 
without  a  self-activity  of  the  whole,  without  a  universal  life,  without 
the  opening  of  a  new  world. 

Man,  as  it  were,  hangs  between  these  two  worlds — between  spirit 
and  nature.  Both  are  real.  Of  this  there  can  be  no  doubt. 

Nature  confronts  us  at  every  turn.  A  large  portion  of  our  life  is 
devoted  to  her.  On  the  other  hand,  the  world  of  spirit  is  with  us  also. 
To  deny  its  reality  is  equally  absurd.  And  what  is  man  to  do  with 
these  confronting  realms  ?  Both  cannot  equally  claim  him.  At  the 
start  let  us  do  away  with  the  idea  of  an  empty  compromise.  Nor  can 
he  reduce  the  spiritual  to  the  natural.  This  attempt,  as  seen  in  the 
philosophy  of  our  time,  amounts  simply  to  a  denial  of  the  reality  of 
the  spiritual.  For  centuries  the  idea  of  the  development  of  all  reality 
from  the  pure  activity  of  spirit  has  exerted  a  fascinating  power  over 
man.  But  if  we  follow  the  links  of  the  chain  from  Plotinus  to  Hegel 
we  see  that  either  life  became  a  mere  sum  of  abstractions,  or  that  ex- 
perience, which  at  the  beginning  had  been  so  sharply  pushed  aside, 
was  unconsciously  called  in  to  complete  the  intuition,  to  give  life  to 
the  otherwise  empty  forms.  Nor  does  the  distinction  between  form 
and  matter  aid  us.  For,  on  the  one  hand,  the  spiritual  is  far  too  self- 
centered  and  real  to  stand  merely  as  part  of  the  whole.  And  on  the 
other,  nature  is  far  too  cold  and  capricious  when  seen  in  contrast  to  the 
spiritual  to  adapt  itself  as  matter  to  form. 

And  yet  the  dualism  is  intolerable.  The  idea  of  the  independent 
existence  of  two  coordinate  but  different  worlds  of  reality  in  life  is 
more  than  can  be  borne.  The  opposition  must  somehow  be  overcome. 
These  two  masters  man  cannot  serve.  And  yet  neither  of  them  can 
be  denied. 

If  we  would  work  our  way  out  beyond  this  dilemma  there  is  but 
one  course  for  us  to  take.  Both  of  our  worlds  are  real  and  yet  differ- 
ent. If  we  are  to  see  them  united  in  life  we  must  see  them  both  as 
the  product  of  a  reality  deeper  than  either. 

Here,  again,  we  stand  at  a  great  turning-point  and  once  more  great 
possibilities  open  before  us.  We  must  grasp  the  world  as  the  develop- 
ment of  a  substantial  spirituality,  of  an  essential  life.  We  must  see 
our  own  free  activity  as  a  part  of  a  deeper  life.  We  must  see  nature 
as  a  product  of  profounder  reality. 

With  the  idea  of  a  substantial  spirituality,  which  brings  forth  a 


98  A    SPIRITUAL    CONTENT  OF  LIFE. 

new  and  peculiar  being  out  of  the  depths  of  activity  itself,  there  opens 
a  new  view  of  our  world  and  our  life,  an  altogether  new  experience  of 
reality.  Both  of  those  worlds,  each  of  which  lived  in  its  own  right 
and  seemed  to  pretend  to  the  whole  of  reality,  are  seen  to  be  expres- 
sions of  an  essential  being.  Our  free  activity  must  have  a  deeper  life 
behind  itself. 

If  these  two  realms  are  one  in  their  origin,  the  problem  is  to  realize 
that  unity.  It  is  ours  to  find  in  nature  this  primordial  force,  this  sub- 
stance ;  to  wrest  it  from  her ;  to  appropriate  it  to  ourselves.  It  is  ours 
to  conquer  nature.  The  act  shall  take  being  up  into  itself ;  thus  it 
shall  itself  become  real. 

This  substantial  spirituality  is  not  a  part  of  us ;  we  are  rather  a 
part  of  it.  Through  it  we  acquire  freedom  ;  as  a  part  of  it  man  makes 
his  history ;  we  feel  it  stirring  in  us,  and  we  go  out  to  create.  But  this 
primordial  activity  will  tolerate  no  limits ;  it  will  not  be  imprisoned ; 
it  will  be  hemmed  in  by  no  barrier.  There  is  nothing  in  the  world 
which  may  oppose  it;  it  will  brook  nothing  foreign  or  alien  to  itself. 
Therefore  we,  as  stirred  by  it,  must  conquer  the  exterior  world ;  we 
must  transform  it  by  our  spirituality ;  we  must  take  it  up  into  our  own 
activity.  As  the  artist  spiritualizes  nature — as  he,  accomplishing  the 
impossible,  transforms  it  with  his  own  inner  life — so  must  we  all  over- 
come the  outer  world. 

It  is  by  this  free  act  that  the  spiritual  acquires  character  and  deter- 
mination. The  inner  world,  hanging  over  things  as  the  spirit  hung 
over  the  waters  at  the  creation,  lacks  substantiality.  As  it  broke  loose 
from  nature  and  rested  in  its  alienation  from  her,  a  certain  indeter- 
minateness  possessed  it.  It  saw  nature  as  something  hostile  and  for- 
eign. But  the  spiritual  life  can  acquire  substance  only  as  it,  through 
activity,  takes  nature  up  into  itself — only  as  it  spiritualizes  the  external 
through  free  activity. 

The  first  great  struggle  of  mankind  was  for  the  existence  of  the 
spiritual.  It  overcame  nature  in  the  battle  for  a  spiritual  life.  But 
the  life  lacked  determination,  and  thus  arose  a  second  struggle.  It 
too  was  a  fight  against  nature ;  but  the  end  of  the  struggle  was  not 
her  destruction,  but  her  spiritualization — it  was  the  strife  for  the  char- 
acter of  the  spiritual. 

And  man,  in  so  far  as  this  world-power  rises  up  in  him,  becomes 
world-power  himself.  Man  as  a  part  of  nature  is  driven  hither  and 
thither  by  forces  exterior  to  him ;  for  he  is  but  a  mere  point,  a  link  in 
an  endless  chain.  But  when  he  rises  up  into  his  primordial  activity 
he  thereby  becomes  world-power.  Through  him,  in  him,  by  him,  is 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS,  99 

world-history  brought  forth.  Hereby  he  transcends  himself,  he  rises 
above  the  punctuality  of  life,  he  becomes  a  part  of  the  whole,  his  life 
moves  on  in  the  world  life.  Thus  the  individual  becomes  micro- 
cosmus,  and  the  all  a  world  of  worlds.  When  doubt  rises  up  in  us, 
doubt  as  to  God,  the  world,  men  and  life,  it  must  at  last  lead  back  to 
doubt  of  ourselves,  the  doubt  as  to  the  ideality  of  our  nature,  the 
presence  of  a  spiritual  substance  in  our  life. 

In  our  descriptions  up  to  this  point  we  seem  to  have  traced  the 
triumphal  march  of  spirit,  but  in  reality  we  have  been  following  only 
the  progress  of  battle.  And  this  struggle  is  one  which  never  ends. 
The  strife  continues  in  each  plane  of  life.  At  first  it  was  the  struggle 
of  spirit  to  raise  itself  above  the  chaotic  manifold  of  nature — the  strug- 
gle for  existence ;  then  it  was  the  struggle  to  lift  experience  up  into 
spirituality,  that  the  latter  might  acquire  determinateness — the  struggle 
for  character ;  and  now  we  have  to  see  this  spirituality  enter  into  a 
new  strife  for  the  world-power  of  spirit.  For  as  soon  as  the  spiritual 
life  takes  on  concreteness  and  character,  there  arises  a  host  of  new  con- 
tradictions which  threaten  its  destruction,  which  seem  ready  to  shatter 
the  new  life.  The  powers  which  seemed  to  have  been  conquered 
spring  up  again  with  new  force ;  the  old  contradictions  which  seemed 
to  have  been  transcended  appear  in  new  forms.  The  very  forces 
which  worked  for  good  now  seem  to  take  on  an  evil  nature.  The 
woe  of  the  world,  its  contradictions,  the  thought  of  death,  which 
seemed  to  be  the  kindly  spirits  of  man  aiding  him  on,  now  turn  against 
him.  The  whole  structure  of  spirit  seems  to  have  been  founded  on 
sand  and  to  be  on  the  point  of  being  shattered  by  the  contradictions 
which  have  grown  up  within  itself.  Doubt  as  to  the  reality  of  the 
spiritual  life  arises ;  we  faint  in  the  struggle  against  the  evil ;  the  con- 
tradictions seem  insurmountable,  and  we  are  threatened  with  the  loss 
of  that  which  we  so  hardly  won  and  a  return  to  naturalism  appears 
to  await  us. 

The  first  attack  on  the  new  life  arises  out  of  our  new  relations  to 
nature.  Here  lies  the  first  battle-ground  in  the  struggle  for  the  world- 
power  of  the  spiritual  realm.  For  the  better  we  have  come  to  know 
the  exterior  world,  the  more  foreign  it  seems  to  be ;  the  more  we  have 
to  do  with  it,  the  colder  and  more  alien  it  grows.  The  forces  of  nature 
work  in  blind  objectivity,  without  respect  to  the  spirituality  they  hem 
in  and  destroy.  Fire,  water,  storm  and  earthquake  annihilate;  the 
little  forces  of  destruction  do  not  sleep.  Nature  works  without  re- 
spect to  high  or  low,  good  or  bad ;  she  operates  without  feeling,  and 


100  A    SPIRITUAL    CONTENT  OF  LIFE. 

handles  the  individual,  the  masterwork  of  spirit,  in  perfect  indiffer- 
ence. 

And  as  the  knowledge  of  nature  grows  with  the  development  of 
spirit,  there  grows  also  the  knowledge  of  the  utter  dependence  of  the 
individual  on  nature.  We  have  long  known  that  the  soul  is,  in  gen- 
eral, conditioned  upon  the  body ;  but  we  now  see  in  oppressive  clear- 
ness how  every  spiritual  activity  is  based  upon  the  corporeal.  And 
then  the  thoughts  of  heredity  and  environment  steal  in  and  shed  their 
weird  light  over  the  world.  And  thus  man,  in  his  thought  of  himself, 
becomes  a  mere  episode  in  the  world-processes.  Is  it  any  wonder  that 
he  loses  faith  in  the  new  world — in  the  spiritual  substance  ? 

And  so  it  is  with  the  moral  world. 

The  ethical  life  has  always  been  the  great  refuge  of  man  from  the 
bondage  of  nature.  When  all  else  topples  and  falls  the  eternal  worth 
of  the  pure  heart  and  noble  mind  has  stood  fast.  Here,  if  nowhere 
else,  man  rises  above  the  limitation  of  nature  to  the  freedom  and  re- 
ality of  the  spiritual ;  in  this  realm,  if  in  no  other,  the  dark  despot  of 
the  punctual  self  of  nature  is  overcome.  But,  even  here,  the  spiritual 
is  threatened  by  the  destroying  might  of  contradiction.  After  this 
world  has  been  brought  into  being,  we  see  for  the  first  time  its  incon- 
sistencies. For,  instead  of  an  all-embracing  love  and  justice,  there 
arises  a  love  and  justice  bounded  and  limited  by  the  instincts  and  pas- 
sions of  the  self  of  nature.  Our  morality  is  well  and  good  only  so 
long  as  it  favors  ourselves,  our  party,  our  narrow  circle  or  our  race. 
And  thus  the  object  of  the  moral  world  is  a  manifold  of  scattered 
units  instead  of  the  totality  of  humanity — a  collection  of  little  centers 
separated  by  a  wide  gulf,  instead  of  the  whole  of  mankind.  Here  we 
see,  in  all  clearness,  the  triumph  of  evil,  the  unconquerable  nature  of 
sin,  bound  up  as  it  is  in  all  our  spiritual  activities.  So  we  doubt  the 
reality  of  our  ethical  life. 

And  we  fare  no  better  when  we  turn  to  history,  for  here  we  find 
the  past  to  be  only  a  great  mass  of  actions  done  and  gone.  We  are 
unable  to  draw  from  it  the  fresh,  active  present  for  which  we  had 
hoped.  History  should  solve  our  problems  for  us — in  the  past  of 
human  life  should  be  seen  a  line  of  steady  development  making  for 
eternal  truth.  But  instead  of  that,  we  find  only  a  nexus  of  contradic- 
tory intuitions  and  faiths.  History  should  have  solved  our  problems, 
but  instead  of  that  it  has  travailed  only  to  bring  problems  forth.  And 
we  lose  our  faith  in  the  past  of  human  experience. 

And  so  is  it  also  when  we  consider  the  nature  of  society,  fate  and 
the  very  spiritual  power  itself. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  IOI 

The  evil  does  not  lie  on  the  surface;  it  reaches  down  into  the 
fundamental  conditions  of  our  very  existence.  The  spirituality  which 
does  appear  seems  too  weak  to  overcome  the  great  attacks  which  are 
made  upon  it  unceasingly.  In  its  own  development  it  constitutes 
rather  an  indifferent  form  to  a  content  than  a  full  world.  History  has 
rather  increased  than  diminished  the  complications.  The  new  world 
has  been  brought  forth,  but  only  cracked  and  broken  by  fundamental 
contradictions.  Once  more  we  find  ourselves  in  a  great  dilemma — 
again  we  have  reached  a  position  where  we  must  either  turn  back  or 
go  on  still  further.  No  compromise  is  possible ;  to  stand  still  is  in- 
tolerable ;  some  solution  to  the  problem  of  our  relation  to  the  evil  in 
the  world  must  be  found. 

The  history  of  world-thought  contains  many  attempts  to  escape 
this  dilemma ;  indeed,  it  has  been  largely  occupied  in  endeavoring  to 
offer  some  solution  to  the  problem.  There  have  been  in  general 
two  great  answers  to  the  question.  According  to  the  first  of  these, 
the  evil  in  the  world  is  mere  appearance,  the  good  alone  is  real ;  ac- 
cording to  the  second,  the  evil  alone  is  real,  the  good  is  mere  appear- 
ance. The  former  is  optimism;  the  latter,  pessimism.  Each  comes 
to  its  conclusion  by  denying  the  reality  of  one  side  of  the  dilemma. 

The  first  great  plea  of  optimism  lies  in  the  thought  that  if  we  could 
but  see  the  world  from  its  center  the  evil  would  disappear.  The  bad 
is  in  the  last  analysis  good,  for  through  the  bad  the  good  rises  up  and 
grows.  The  second  plea  lies  in  the  thought  that  if  we  would  but  do 
the  good  the  evil  would  cease  to  exist  for  us — if  we  would  but  center 
our  lives  in  the  world  of  the  pure  and  high  the  world  of  the  impure 
and  low  would  be  forced  into  non-existence.  But  whether  the  opti- 
mism be  that  of  consideration  or  of  action,  its  falsity  remains.  For,  no 
matter  what  our  point  of  view  may  be,  no  matter  how  our  actions 
may  be  directed,  evil  remains  and  must  ever  remain.  It  were  as  easy 
to  prove  that  the  good  serves  the  evil  as  the  evil  the  good.  If  we 
must  write  our  theodicies  why  not  also  our  satanodicies  ? 

The  essence  of  pessimism  lies  first  in  the  thought  that  the  world 
down  to  its  very  center  is  evil,  and  second  in  the  act  of  giving  up  the 
hope  of  attaining  the  good  or  the  true.  The  theoretical  view  of  the 
world  as  bad  and  truth  as  an  illusion  must  end  practically  in  the  giv- 
ing up  of  the  good  and  the  true — the  philosophy  of  evil  must  inevita- 
bly result  in  the  philosophy  of  self-denial. 

But  if  there  be  neither  happiness,  virtue  nor  truth  in  the  world, 
what  have  we  to  give  up?  If  the  idea  of  the  good  be  an  illusion, 


102  A    SPIRITUAL    CONTENT  OF  LIFE. 

what  is  the  meaning  of  self-denial  ?  The  very  fact  that  the  turning 
away  from  happiness  costs  us  so  much  effort  and  gives  us  so  much  in- 
spiration \sprima  facie  proof  of  the  existence  of  happiness.  And  so 
with  truth  and  goodness.  Truth  and  goodness  remain  in  all  their  sub- 
limity; pessimism  is  but  the  turning  away  from  them. 

Pessimism  and  optimism  may  annihilate  each  other  in  their  struggle 
for  supremacy ;  but  the  good  remains  good,  evil  does  not  cease  to  be 
evil,  and  both  are  real.  And  the  moralist  still  moralizes  on  the 
*  mixed  character  of  human  life.'  Truly  life  is  mixed,  not  merely 
on  its  surface,  but  in  its  very  depths.  And  after  all  the  dilemma  still 
remains  unsolved  and  still  demands  solution.  But  if  there  be  any 
power  and  courage  left  in  life  there  is  one  way  of  escape  open — we 
can  transcend  the  sphere  of  conflict,  we  can  raise  ourselves  above  the 
contradictions  into  a  new  realm.  The  world  of  struggle  is  not  the 
only  world ;  its  barriers  shall  not  block  our  progress.  There  opens 
a  sphere  of  activity  beyond  the  sphere  of  these  contradictions ;  in  it 
must  we  center  our  life. 

This  new  order  would  appear  as  something  transcendental,  some- 
thing which  lies  beyond  the  horizon  of  our  world.  But  in  truth  it 
should  only  expand  the  real ;  it  should  command  for  itself  the  first 
place  in  our  world  and  force  all  else  into  a  subordinate  position ;  but 
still  it  should  be  within  the  real,  our  real.  The  ultimate  and  final  it 
must  always  be ;  it  must  contain  all  absolute  truth ;  in  it  must  be 
builded  the  world-power.  As  such  and  as  such  alone  can  it  transcend 
all  contradiction  and  overcome  all  opposition. 

This  is  a  hard  saying — this  last  step  in  our  spiritual  life  is  the  most 
difficult  of  all  to  grasp  in  thought  and  to  realize  in  action.  But  the 
saying  nevertheless  is  true.  And  that  it  is  such  we  can  see,  if  we  can 
see  at  all,  from  the  workings  of  religion.  For  this  struggle  and  this 
realm  are  essentially  the  struggle  and  the  realm  of  religion. 

In  religion  the  individual  rises  out  of  the  contradictions  of  the 
world.  He  does  this  because  he  lays  hold  of  the  absolute  life.  The 
contradictions  of  the  world  do  not  disappear ;  they  are  rather  intensi- 
fied; but  in  that  something  absolute  is  realized,  they  are  transcended. 
The  barriers  are  not  broken  down ;  we  leap  over  them.  For  in  re- 
ligion we  leave  this  world  of  struggle  behind,  we  rise  up  into  a  realm 
of  absolute  truth  which  knows  no  contradictions — the  spirit  reaches 
the  plane  in  which  it  becomes  the  world-power.  For  the  struggle  to 
reach  an  ultimate  point  and  to  bind  all  life  to  it  is  essentially  the 
struggle  of  religion. 

But  this  new  life  is  not  an  abstraction — it  is  a  personal  activity,  a 


SHORTER   CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  103 

coming  into  relation  to  the  absolute  life.  It  is  not  something  given, 
but  something  to  be  gotten  by  a  free  and  original  act.  It  is  to  be 
gotten  because  all  that  confounded  us  in  the  lower  life  is  overcome  in 
something  higher. 

If  this  new  and  final  realm  is  to  be  seen  from  the  standpoint  of 
religion,  it  is  now  clear  that  the  rest  of  spirituality  is  to  be  seen  from 
the  standpoint  of  culture.  First  of  all  we  have  a  struggle  for  the 
creation  and  preservation  of  the  spiritual  in  general ;  then  the  struggle 
to  penetrate  and  overcome  nature,  and  finally  the  struggle  to  rise  to 
an  ultimate  reality  beyond  the  contradictions  of  the  former  stages. 
The  second  of  these  steps  belongs  essentially  to  the  world  of  culture, 
the  third  to  that  of  religion.  And  these  two  worlds  must  ever  remain 
distinct  and  separate  spiritual  experiences.  They  have  often  striven 
with  each  other ;  each  has  claimed  its  sole  right  to  exist,  but  mankind 
ever  returns  to  them  both.  Neither  can  be  omitted  from  the  great 
system  of  the  spiritual. 

In  conclusion  we  may  sum  up  the  foregoing  as  follows : 

We  saw  the  world  of  the  real  open  itself  in  three  levels. 

The  first  problem  was  that  of  the  independence  of  the  spiritual 
life.  This  life  cannot  exist  as  a  mere  expression  of  a  foreign  activity. 
It  must  be  self -centered.  That  it  arises  in  its  purity  was  due  to  a 
breaking  away  from  turmoil  and  particularity  of  nature  and  the  forma- 
tion of  a  new  and  peculiar  realm  of  ideal  worths.  With  the  develop- 
ment of  the  independence  of  the  spiritual  there  arose  not  a  world  of 
particulars  which  left  alone  the  rest  of  reality,  but  the  soul  of  the  real 
itself.  Through  it  came  about  a  turning  of  being  to  its  own  truth,  a 
finding  of  itself,  a  delving  into  the  depth  of  life.  As  such  it  is  more 
than  a  mere  human  phenomenon.  Mankind  is  thereby  taken  up  into 
world  movements  which  raise  man  above  particular  powers  and  inter- 
ests ;  which  raise  him  above  the  mere  average  of  life. 

But  necessary  as  this  step  was,  by  means  of  it  alone  the  spritual  at- 
tained only  general  outlines.  A  second  step  was  required  to  secure 
it  character.  This  was  taken  in  order  that  the  great  opposition  be- 
tween the  spiritual  and  non-spiritual  external  world  be  overcome. 
Thus,  there  took  place  a  return  of  the  spiritual  to  mere  existence. 
Nature  was  grasped  from  the  standpoint  of  the  new  life  in  order 
to  spiritualize  her.  But  this  struggle  could  not  meet  with  success 
without  transcending  of  the  work  of  the  mere  individual  and  the 
formation  of  a  unity  of  spiritual  life.  Thus  there  arose  a  life- 
system,  a  totality  of  work,  a  spiritual  substance,  a  struggle  for 


104         EXPERIENCE    UNDER  INFLUENCE   OF  ETHER. 

the  character  of  life.  And  thus  the  happy  end  of  life  and  satis- 
faction with  the  real  seemed  near  at  hand.  But  the  struggle  with 
the  content  of  our  human  experience  developed  unforeseen  but  funda- 
mental contradictions.  The  new  life  was  seen  to  be  rent  with 
irreconcilable  oppositions,  the  actuality  with  which  it  had  to  deal,  cold 
and  indifferent.  All  attempts  to  reconcile  or  wipe  out  proved  failures ; 
the  whole  was  lost  but  for  the  opening  of  a  new  world,  the  rising  of 
spirit  to  a  new  level. 

Thus  a  third  step  was  undertaken,  and  there  came  about  a  struggle 
for  the  world-power  of  spirit.  Life  was  raised  above  the  contradic- 
tions ;  it  was  united  to  the  absolute  life. 

But  in  so  doing  the  old  world  was  not  to  be  given  up.  Its  levels 
were  to  be  preserved  in  their  distinction  and  integrity.  In  the  rela- 
tion of  each  to  the  life  process  was  to  be  found  the  consummation  of 
spirituality. 

From  beginning  to  end  this  spirituality  was  to  be  conceived  as  a 
noologic  reality,  something  not  based  on  the  psyche,  but  on  the  nous. 
It  is  a  coming  to  itself  of  reality,  being  turning  to  its  own  truth. 

We  may  not  start  with  the  world  or  with  the  soul,  but  with  a  life 
which  is  over  and  beyond  these ;  which  does  not  belong  to  man,  but  of 
which  man  may  become  a  part. 

FRANCIS  KENNEDY. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  COLORADO. 


EXPERIENCE  UNDER  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  ETHER.1 

I  have  called  this  a  description  of  my  experience  under  the  influence 
of  ether,  although  chloroform  was  used  for  a  few  moments  at  the  start, 
producing  no  noticeable  effect,  however,  except  a  taste  of  sweetness. 
The  ether  had  a  decidedly  disagreeable  taste. 

After  about  two  minutes  the  larger  muscles  of  the  leg  began  to  be 
affected,  those  of  the  calf  first,  closely  followed  by  those  of  the  upper 
leg.  The  feeling  was  that  of  tiredness,  with  a  prickling  sensation 
somewhat  like  that  felt  as  the  blood  begins  to  course  after  one's  limb 
has  been  4  asleep/  somewhat  like  that  felt  in  an  electric  bath,  but  not 
exactly  like  either.  The  ends  of  the  nerves  seemed  to  vibrate,  as  it 
were,  and  I  imagined  the  nerves  contracting  in  length.2 

1  An  experience  of  I.  B.  communicated  by  Professor  K.  A.  Kirkpatrick  ; 
suggested  by  the  communication  from  Professor  W.  James,  in  the  May  number 
of  the  REVIEW. 

2 1  have  always  had  a  nervous  feeling  similar  to  this  when  hearing  of  one's 
passing  through  excessive  pain,  and  can  quite  readily  reproduce  it  since  my  ex- 
perience with  ether. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  REPORTS.  105 

These  sensations  were  soon  followed  by  a  feeling  of  inability  to 
get  breath,  like  that  produced  by  the  pressure  upon  the  chest  of  a 
bather  who  is  not  accustomed  to  the  water.  The  muscles  of  exhala- 
tion, however,  did  not  seem  to  be  much  affected.  Later  there  was  a 
slight  sense  of  suffocation,  but  I  do  not  remember  that  breathing  be- 
came at  any  time  very  laborious. 

The  next  muscles  to  be  affected  were  those  of  the  arms,  the  biceps 
first.  The  sensations  produced  were  much  like  those  in  the  legs,  but 
milder. 

By  this  time  the  prickling  sensations  in  the  leg  muscles  had  been 
gradually  replaced  by  a  weariness  that  was  almost  unendurable. 
Every  muscle  seemed  to  be  utterly  exhausted.  I  would  seek  tem- 
porary relief  by  crossing  and  recrossing  the  legs,  until  they  finally 
became  so  heavy  and  numb  that  I  could  not  move  them.  I  do  not 
remember  any  muscular  relaxation,  nor  any  internal  feelings,  as  of 
the  heart  or  stomach. 

The  last  sensation  I  remember  was  that  of  my  weight  upon  the 
stretcher.  I  have  no  remembrance  of  the  time  when  the  smaller  mus- 
cles became  affected,  nor  of  the  bodily  feelings  just  before  entire  in- 
sensibility came  on;  it  seemed  to  come  upon  all  parts  of  the  body  at 
once. 

Following  bodily  insensibility  began  a  horrible  mental  struggle  even 
more  indescribable  than  the  bodily  sufferings.  It  was  a  life-and-death 
struggle  between  existence  and  non-existence.  I  seemed  to  see  myself 
as  in  a  dream,  a  space  of  light  about  four  or  five  inches  in  diameter. 
Surrounding  this  space  was  non-existence,  a  thick,  heavy,  material 
darkness,  which  steadily  encroached  upon  the  limits  of  the  light.  The 
awful  part  of  it  was  that  I  seemed  bound  to  resist  to  the  last  possible 
moment  and  yet  realized  that  darkness  must  finally  triumph.  I  had 
no  sense  of  having  or  wishing  weapons  to  use  in  the  struggle  with 
darkness,  nor  any  remembrance  of  ever  having  had  bodily  members. 

For  a  short  time  there  remained  the  idea,  somewhat  comforting, 
that  I  should  sometime  awake  from  my  condition  and  be  free  again. 
Nearly  to  the  last  I  retained  an  indistinct  visual  memory,  and  I  saw 
myself  going  through  some  former  activities.  The  last  thought  I  re- 
member was :  4  Thou  alone  art  able ;  so,  Lord,  watch  over  me.' 

This  mental  struggle  seemed  to  last  some  ten  to  thirty  minutes ; 
for  the  most  of  which  period  of  existence,  this  luminous  space  seemed 
to  be  in  the  form  of  a  funnel,  and  gradually  to  decrease  in  size  until 
it  became  a  point  of  light,  which  vanished  in  about  the  direction  of 
the  North  Star.  The  struggle  seemed  to  begin  in  an  enclosure  about 


106        EXPERIENCE    UNDER  INFLUENCE    OF  ETHER. 

the  size  of  my  head.     This  enlarged  in  all  directions  until  its  limits 
became  infinite.1 

On  awakening,2  my  desire  was  to  blow ;  at  first  my  efforts  were 
very  feeble.  I  desired  principally  to  blow  the  doctor  out  of  existence. 
I  was  in  a  general  fighting  state  of  mind,  and  as  I  went  out  upon  the 
street  desired  to  shake  my  fist  at  show-bills  and  people,  but  refrained 
for  fear  I  should  be  thought  crazy.  It  took  a  day  or  more  for  this  ef- 
fect of  the  ether  fully  to  wear  off.  The  ether  made  me  quite  sick  for 
nearly  a  week,  and  for  several  years  afterward  the  smell  or  mention 

of  it  produced  a  feeling  of  dread. 

I.  B. 

1 1  have  several  times  had  this  experience  in  the  partial  delirium  of  fever  ; 
with  this  difference,  however,  that  in  fever  the  sensation  is  a  painful  one,  the 
room  in  which  I  imagine  myself  enlarging  until  the  thought  of  it  gives  pain  ; 
often,  too,  this  enormous  space  will  seem  painfully  empty,  with  perhaps  two 
or  three  voices  in  different  parts  or  enormous  animals  tramping  about. 

2  My  attendant  informed  me  that  while  coming  out  of  the  sleep  I  would 
raise  one  leg,  then  the  other,  striking  my  heels  heavily  on  the  couch. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

The    Groundwork   of    Science.     A   Study  of    Epistemology.     ST. 
GEORGE  MIVART.     The  Science  Series.     New  York,  G.  P.  Put- 
nam's Sons;  London,  Bliss,  Sands  &  Co.     Pp.  xviii+328. 
The  term  science  is  used  in  this  work  with  an  ambiguous  mean- 
ing.    At  times   the  author    employs    it  in  the    general  etymological 
sense  to  cover  all  forms  of    systematic  knowledge  and  inquiry.     For 
the  most  part,  however,  he  means  by  it  the  empirical  sciences,  divided 
into  two  classes,  those  which  relate  to  the  physical  world  and  those 
which  have  to  do  with  the  inner,  psychical  life.     The  aim  of  the  work 
is  to  investigate  the  principles  which  lie  at  the  basis  of  '  science ;'  and 
so  the  inquiry  becomes  an  essay  in  general  epistemology,  with  particu- 
lar reference  throughout  to  the  noetics  of  science  in  its  more  narrow 
and  technical  significance. 

The  psychological  foundation  of  Professor  Mivart's  theory  of 
knowledge  is  a  sharp  distinction  between  the  lower  and  higher 
faculties  of  knowledge.  The  former  belongs  to  animals  as  well  as 
man,  and  the  harmonious  working  of  its  several  subordinate  processes 
('consentience')  enables  the  brute  to  manifest  phenomena  which  re- 
semble the  results  of  man's  higher  psychical  activities  without  in  the 
least  being  the  same  as  these.  The  human  infant,  it  is  true,  in  many 
respects  is  not  unlike  the  animal,  but  the  likeness  is  superficial,  since,, 
in  reality,  there  is  a  great  gulf  fixed  between  the  two  orders  of  con- 
sciousness. Latent  in  the  mind  of  the  child  lie  the  germs  of  his  future 
thought ;  but  the  animal  is  limited  to  his  lower  level,  with  no  hope  of 
future  development.  Moreover,  those  who  maintain  that  the  higher 
faculty  in  man  has  been  reached  by  a  process  of  natural  selection  are 
in  error ;  for  natural  selection  has  no  power  in  itself  to  bridge  a  gap 
*  in  kind,'  and  the  truths  which  are  attained  by  means  of  the  faculty 
in  question  are  in  the  great  majority  of  cases  such  as  *  never  could 
have  given  their  possessors  an  improved  chance  of  survival '  (pp. 
xiii.,  272  ff.). 

This  higher  faculty  of  knowledge  is  described  in  a  variety  of  ways. 
It  is  4  intellectual,'  in  distinction  from  sensuous,  'perception;'  it  is  the 
source  of  'intellectual  conceptions;'  it  is  intellectual  intuition;  it  is 

107 


108  THE    GROUNDWORK  OF  SCIENCE. 

reflex  self-consciousness ;  it  is  the  power  of  cognizing  relations ;  above 
all,  or  rather  in  all,  it  is  the  source  whence  we  derive  the  primary  and  self- 
evident  principles  which  form  the  ultimate  premises  of  all  ratiocination 
and  without  the  support  of  which  science,  like  knowledge  of  every  kind, 
becomes  an  impossible  dream.  As  these  original  intuitions  are  con- 
sidered by  Professor  Mivart  the  foundation  of  all  thinking,  he  is  care- 
ful to  repeat  his  summary  of  them  at  various  points  in  his  work.  The 
briefest  statement  of  the  list  is  as  follows : 

"  The  existence  of  certainty;  the  existence  of  an  external  world; 
our  continuous  substantial  existence ;  the  validity  of  the  process  of 
inference ;  the  self-evidence  of  some  truths ;  the  principle  of  contra- 
diction ;  the  evidence  of  axioms ;  the  principle  of  causation ;  the  uni- 
formity of  nature ;  and  the  existence  of  necessity  and  contingency  " 
(p.  310). 

Chief  among  these,  at  least  in  the  amount  of  energy  expended  in 
its  defense,  is  the  second,  which  is  stated  more  in  detail  on  page  106 : 
"  An  external,  objective  world  exists  and  is  truly  apprehended  by 
some  of  our  intellectual  acts,  an  absolutely  certain  knowledge  of  ob- 
jectivity being  afforded  us  through  memory,  which  reveals  to  us  real 
existence  external  to  all  our  present  experience."  The  entire  third 
chapter  of  the  book  is  devoted,  in  the  spirit  of  this  principle,  to  the 
refutation  of  idealism.  The  argument  is  vehement  and  decided, 
although  it  is  not  till  a  later  stage  in  the  inquiry  that  the  Berkeleyan 
is  classed  with  the  insane,  for  the  author  believes  that  physical 
science  is  possible  for  those  who  accept  idealistic  views  only  because 
a  beneficent  nature  has  endowed  them  with  faculties  that  guide  them 
aright  in  spite  of  their  speculative  vagaries.  Nevertheless,  it  would 
be  difficult  to  maintain  that  Professor  Mivart's  discussion  furnishes 
many  new  weapons  with  which  to  repel  the  idealistic  attack.  In  fact, 
it  is  doubtful  whether  he  clearly  distinguishes  between  empirical 
idealism  and  metaphysical  idealism ;  and  it  is  certain  that,  confident 
in  the  a  priori  arguments,  he  fails  to  avail  himself  of  the  realistic  im- 
plications with  which  modern  physical  science  abounds. 

In  the  last  two  chapters  of  the  work  we  come  in  sight  of  a  theistic 
capstone  for  the  epistemological  edifice ;  while  the  last  of  all,  with  the 
same  title  as  the  whole  book,  brings  a  short  consideration  of  the 
metaphysics  of  science  (force,  energy,  time,  space,  etc.,  p.  297  ff.). 

The  type  of  philosophy  thus  presented  is  so  familiar  that  no  ex- 
tended critique  is  demanded.  The  way  in  which  it  is  presented,  how- 
ever, calls  for  rather  more  attention.  The  following  quotation  may 
serve  as  an  example  of  the  care  with  which  the  argument  is  conducted, 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  1-09 

for  it  is  scarcely  to  be  credited  that  it  is  a  fair  specimen  of  the  author's 
philosophical  erudition : 

"  For  the  whole  of  the  philosophy  of  Germany  and  Holland,  from 
Spinoza  to  Hartmann,  has  been  a  result  of  the  mental  seed  first  sown 
in  men's  minds  by  Berkeley,  who  explicitly  produced  what  was  im- 
plicitly contained  in  Locke"  (pp.  40-41). 

Here  are  two  examples  of  accuracy  in  reasoning  about  the  subtlest 
epistemological  questions : 

"  Though  we  are  for  the  most  part  content  to  act  on  reasonable 
probabilities,  yet  certainty  attends  us  at  every  turn.  *  *  *  If  we 
find,  on  returning  to  our  library,  that  a  window  which  we  had  care- 
fully closed  before  starting,  is  open,  we  are  quite  sure  that  some  one 
must  have  opened  it "  (p.  98). 

"  The  first  and  most  important  of  these  "  [self-evident]  "  principles 
is  the  perception  of  the  reality  of  existence — that  which  we  perceive 
to  exist  evidently  does  in  truth  so  exist.  This  is  often  expressed  by 
the  formula  *  A  is  A  '  *  *  *  "  (p.  242) . 

Finally,  we  may  cite  one  or  two  instances  of  philosophical  humor 
such  as  rarely  lighten  the  labors  of  the  epistemological  student : 

"  To  the  other  idealistic  extreme,  that  by  Hume,  we  will  sacrifice 
no  space,  for,  in  spite  of  its  author's  acuteness  and  great  ability,  it 
does  not  really  admit  of  logical  statement,  so  utterly  incoherent  is  it, 
and  so  confident  are  we  that  its  ingenious  author  had  no  belief  in  it 
himself,  but  was  laughing  in  his  sleeve  at  his  inept  admirers  and  dis- 
ciples "  (p.  83). 

And  this,  in  criticism  of  Mr.  Spencer's  assertion  of  our  anthropo- 
morphic interpretation  of  physical  causation : 

"  Surely  greater  nonsense  has  rarely  been  written.  Let  us  suppose 
the  partly- sawn- through  tree  to  be  not  even  touched  by  us,  but  that  a 
gale  has  sprung  up  which,  after  having  swayed  it  to  and  fro,  breaks  it 
off  and  prostrates  it,  just  as  we  have  supposed  it  prostrated  by  human 
efforts.  Are  we  not  then  to  say  that  the  wind  has  exerted  as  much 
force  as  was  ours  ?  Can  we  not  say  this  confidently,  without  being 
such  idiots  as  to  attribute  '  feelings  '  to  the  wind?"  (p.  261). 

These,  it  is  true,  are  among  the  most  striking  illustrations  of  the 
style  of  the  work.  But  they  are  not  isolated  cases.  And,  in  spite 
of  the  learning  and  insight  which  are  evidenced  in  this  as  well  as 
in  the  other  products  of  this  well-known  author's  pen,  it  is  to  be  re- 
gretted that  the  philosophical  volume  in  a  scientific  series  should  itself 
be  so  unscientific  in  character. 

A.  C.  ARMSTRONG,  JR. 

WESLEYAN  UNIVERSITY. 


HO  AESTHETIC   SENTIMENT. 

IS  Art  et  le  Reel ;  Essai  de  Metaphysik  fondee  sur  VEsthetique. 

Par  JEAN  PERES.     Paris,  Felix  Alcan.     1898. 

An  attempt  at  developing  the  metaphysical  implications  of  the 
aesthetic  sentiment,  this  work,  though  lacking  somewhat  of  the  system- 
atic character  of  the  masters  (of  a  Schelling,  for  instance,  under 
whose  influence,  by  the  way,  much  of  it  seems  to  be  conceived),  is  yet 
true  to  the  French  traditions  of  good  style  and  does  justice  to  the  more 
important  assthetic  and  sociological  intuitions  of  the  time. 

Though  mainly  of  metaphysical  interest,  it  is  full  of  keen  psycho- 
logical analyses,  especially  of  the  sentiments  of  the  beautiful  and  the 
real,  upon  the  identity  of  which  (as  seen  in  the  analysis)  a  striking 
argument  for  a  monistic  doctrine  of  experience  and  existence  is  built. 
The  advantage  of  going  out  from  the  aesthetic  side  of  experience,  in  a 
metaphysical  reconstruction  of  the  real,  lies  in  the  fact  that  art  is 
double-faced,  on  the  one  side  historical  reality,  and  on  the  other,  as 
embodying  the  sentiment  of  beauty,  it  implies  nature.  Transcending 
alike  the  abstract  dualism  of  subject  and  object,  which  abstract  thinking 
entails,  and  the  dualism  which  volition  discovers  between  the  self  and 
the  world,  sentiment  alone  can  attain  the  absolute  unity  of  intuition. 
The  method  of  this  metaphysical  analysis  of  sentiment  is  not,  there- 
fore, the  abstract  analysis  of  psychology — its  beauty  is  not  the  beauty 
of  psychology,  nor  its  real  the  real  of  science.  It  is  the  difference 
between  concept  and  sentiment.  Now  the  sentiment  of  reality,  as 
distinguished  from  the  notion  of  the  real,  is  possible  only  when  the 
habitual  of  intellection  or  volition  is  transcended,  for  the  conceptual 
is  the  sphere  of  the  possible ;  the  individual  volitional,  from  the  stand- 
point of  immediate  experience,  is  the  sphere  of  chance.  The  senti- 
ment of  the  real  is  always  an  intuition  of  universality,  of  destiny, 
brought  about  by  the  4  choc'  of  a  novel  experience.  This  sentiment 
of  the  real  in  contrast  to  the  notion  of  the  real  has  in  it  the  inherent 
power  of  grasping  subject  and  object,  nature  and  soul  in  a  higher 
unity,  and  is  characterized  as  4  une  vivante  analyse  du  reelj  called 
forth  by  states  of  high  action  and  intense  nervous  energy.  An  anal- 
ysis of  the  aesthetic  sentiment  shows  it  to  be  of  the  same  character,  in 
so  much  that  the  author  calls  it  the  culmination  of  the  sentiment  of 
the  real.  The  highest  form  of  the  love  of  existence  is  the  love  of 
beauty. 

The  concept  of  life,  therefore,  as  a  primal  activity  expressing  itself 
in  its  highest  potencies  in  the  sentiment  of  the  beautiful  real,  is  fund- 
amental;  "  il  semble  in  effet  que  1'homne  embrasse  le  reel  par  la 
connaissance  et  la  contemplation  de  toute  1'ardeur  de  toute  l'intensit£ 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  Ill 

du  sentiment  par  lequelle  il  comprend  ce  qui  lui  manque  pour  etre  ce 
qui  est." 

Upon  this  basis  the  book  proceeds  to  show  in  detail  the  manner  in 
which  art  has  been  a  progressive  realization  of  elementary  forces  of 
life  by  means  of  the  emotions  of  reality  which  it  affords.  The  chap- 
ters upon  the  aestheticising  of  the  categories  of  space  and  time,  of 
unity  and  infinity,  upon  the  social  necessity  of  reflection  upon  the  real, 
and  the  essentially  aesthetic  qualities  of  the  past  as  compared  with  the 
present  and  future  are  interesting,  both  as  developments  of  M.  Pores' 
doctrine,  and  also  as  specimens  of  fine  metaphysical  analysis. 

In  conclusion  we  may  call  attention  again  to  the  originality  of  these 
analyses  of  the  sentiments  of  the  Real  and  the  Beautiful. 

WILBUR  MARSHALL  URBAN. 
URSINUS  COLLEGE. 

Studies  of  Good  and  Evil.     JOSIAH  ROYCE.     New  York,  D.  Apple- 
ton  &  Co.     1898.     Pp.  xv+384- 

In  this  collection  of  essays  Professor  Royce  has  presented  the  prin- 
ciples of  his  idealistic  philosophy  in  their  application  to  the  problems 
of  life.  They  show  the  author  at  his  best  in  the  sphere  of  concrete 
thought.  His  idealism  is  here  essentially  a  philosophy  of  reality.  He 
touches  upon  various  themes,  most  of  which  bear  upon  the  ethical  as- 
pects of  life.  His  topics  range  from  the  problem  of  Job  to  modern 
character  studies  in  the  essays  on  Meister  Eckhart  and  Jean  Marie 

Guyau  and  such  social  problems  as  are  suggested  by  The  Squatter 
Riot  of  1850  in  Sacramento.  The  several  essays  on  consciousness  and 
also  the  one  entitled  The  Case  of  John  Bunyan,  must  prove  of  special 
interest  to  the  student  of  psychology ;  those  who  are  interested  espe- 
cially in  the  mental  experiences  of  the  abnormal  type  will  appreciate 
Professor  Royce's  exhaustive  analysis  of  Bunyan's  religious  experience. 

JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN. 

The  Conception  of  God.  A  Philosophical  Discussion  Concerning  the 
Nature  of  the  Divine  Idea  as  a  Demonstrable  Reality.  By  JOSIAH 
ROYCE,  JOSEPH  LE  CONTE,  G.  H.  HOWISON  and  SIDNEY  ED- 
WARD MEZES.  New  York,  The  MacmillanCo.  1897.  Pp.  xxxviii 
+  354.  Price,  $1.75. 

These  papers  were  originally  presented  in  a  discussion  concerning 
the  being  of  God  which  was  held  under  the  auspices  of  the  Philosoph- 
ical Union  of  the  University  of  California.  To  the  main  discussion 
there  is  added  a  supplementary  essay  by  Professor  Royce  outlining 


112  THE    CONCEPTION  OF   GOD. 

his  position  more  in  detail.  The  main  argument  is  by  Professor 
Royce,  and  is  unfolded  with  his  usual  skill  and  dialectic  subtlety.  In 
the  implications  of  our  ignorance  he  finds  the  intimation  of  an  absolute 
knowledge,  and  in  the  attribute  of  omniscience  he  discovers  the  germi- 
nal concept  of  God,  insisting,  however,  that  absolute  knowledge  also 
implies  love,  will,  wisdom  and  the  other  divine  attributes.  His  posi- 
tion of  monistic  idealism  is  combated  by  Professor  Howison,  who 
urges  the  impossibility  of  reconciling  an  immanent  God  with  the  free 
activity  of  individuals.  Professor  Royce,  in  rebuttal,  discusses  at 
length  the  principle  of  individuation  which  according  to  his  view  lies 
in  that  exclusive  interest  which  is  characteristic  of  the  individual  will. 
He,  therefore,  very  stoutly  maintains  that  the  unity  of  the  world  in 
terms  of  self-consciousness  does  not  destroy  individuality  as  Professor 
Howison  would  insist,  but,  on  the  contrary,  while  transcending  the 
category  of  individuality,  the  unity  of  consciousness  need  not,  however, 
sunder  the  individuals  which  are  embraced  in  it. 

Professor  Mezes'  main  criticism  of  Professor  Royce's  argument  is 
that  the  concept  of  God  as  given  by  Professor  Royce  seems  to  lack  the 
elements  of  spirituality.  In  defense,  however,  it  is  urged  that  the 
idea  of  spirituality,  so  far  as  it  is  a  valid  idea,  must  be  one  of  the  ideas 
which  the  Absolute  finds  fulfilled  in  his  experience.  In  other  words, 
Professor  Royce  contends  that  the  idea  of  spirituality  is  implied  in  his 
concept  of  God,  inasmuch  as  an  absolute  knowledge  and  experience 
must  be  an  absolute  knowledge  and  experience  of  the  spiritual  as  well 
as  of  the  purely  intellectual  elements  of  consciousness. 

Professor  Le  Conte  in  this  discussion  urges  that  the  concept  of  God 
is  illumined  by  a  true  interpretation  of  the  phenomena  of  evolution.  He 
finds  in  the  process  of  evolution  a  real  progress  from  what  he  designates 
a  diffused  form  of  Divine  Energy  to  a  personal  form.  Professor  Royce 
does  not  seem,  however,  to  be  in  sympathy  with  Professor  Le  Conte's 
metaphysical  interpretation  of  the  theory  of  natural  evolution,  and  in- 
sists, moreover,  that  along  such  lines  of  thought  very  little  progress  will 
be  made  towards  a  solution  of  the  vexed  problems  of  evil,  of  immor- 
tality, or  of  freedom. 

This  discussion  is  of  special  significance  inasmuch  as  it  has  not 
been  a  mere  clashing  of  conflicting  opinions,  but,  on  the  contrary,  the 
several  participants  seem  to  agree  substantially  "in  recognizing,"  as 
Professor  Howison  himself  remarks,  u  in  some  form  or  other  an  or- 
ganic correlation  among  the  three  main  objects  common  to  philosophy 
and  religion — God,  Freedom,  Immortality." 

JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  113 

The  Problems  of  Philosophy.  By  JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN.  New 
York,  Charles  Scribner's  Sons.  1898.  Pp.  203. 
Professor  Hibben  has  undertaken  an  important  service  for  phi- 
losophy in  this  country.  It  may  be  a  little  querulous  to  ask  why  not 
write  a  philosophy  itself  instead  of  a  mere  description  of  its  problems. 
It  is  a  philosophy  that  we  need  much  more  than  a  propaedeutic  to  its 
problems.  But  there  is  a  good  excuse  for  doing  the  latter,  and  it  is 
that  no  one  will  permit  another  to  make  the  undertaking  with  any 
peace.  There  is  too  little  belief  in  its  possibility  for  any  one  to  have 
the  necessary  courage.  But  it  is  permissible  to  state  what  the  insolu- 
ble problems  are.  Professor  Hibben  thus  labors  under  a  disadvantage 
in  the  restraints  which  a  philosophical  public  imposes  upon  him,  and 
I  judge  from  some  observations  in  his  book  that  he  would  be  glad  to 
be  free  from  them.  But  the  task,  whether  grateful  or  ungrateful,  has 
been  done  in  a  very  clear  and  concise  manner.  In  mapping  out  the 
lines  of  thought  for  the  student  the  book  will  be  found  to  have  per- 
formed an  excellent  service.  I  would  criticise  only  the  introductory 
chapter,  as  too  much  of  an  attempt  to  purloin  an  interest  for  the  sub- 
ject from  the  field  of  literary  ideals.  Philosophy  has  taken  on  the 
severer  aspect  of  science,  and  does  not  well  tolerate  an  appeal  to  senti- 
ment. The  other  portions  of  the  book,  however,  sustain  a  different 
tone,  and  ought  to  accomplish  the  object  for  which  it  was  written. 

J.  H.  HYSLOP. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

INDIVIDUAL   PSYCHOLOGY. 

I t  testi  mentali*  per  Vesame  degli  alienati.  Note  di  psicopatologia 
individuale  dei  dottori  G.  GUICCIARDI  e  G.  C.  FERRARI.  Reggio- 
Emilia,  Calderini.  1896.  (Riv.  Sperim.  di  Freniat.,  1896, 
XXII.)  Pp.  20. 

Di  alcune  associazioni  verbali.  Ricerche  di  psicologia  individuale 
dei  dottori  G.  GUICCIARDI  e  G.  C.  FERRARI.  Reggio-Emilia, 
Calderini.  1897.  (Riv.  Sperim.  di  Freniat.,  1897,  XXIII.) 
Pp.  26. 

//  lettore  del  pensiero   ''John   Dalton.'     Contributo  allo   psicologia 
dellepiccole  percezioni  e  dei  movimenti  minimi.     G.  GUICCIARDI 
e    G.    C.    FERRARI.      Reggio-Emilia,    Calderini.     1898.     (Riv. 
Sperim.  di  Freniat.,  XXIV.)     Pp.  56. 
In  the  first  paper  the  authors  describe  a  series  of  tests  used  in  the 

psychological  laboratory  of  the  Psychiatrical  Institute  at  Reggio  for 


114  INDIVIDUAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

determining  the  higher  mental  powers  of  patients.  The  tests  were  of 
five  classes:  (i)  Motor  phenomena.  As  a  study  of  more  or  less  un- 
conscious movements  the  subjects  were  told  to  write  a  set  of  20  figures, 
dictated  at  a  uniform  rate,  then  a  similar  set  dictated  at  an  irregular 
rate,  and  finally  to  perform  a  simple  operation  in  division.  The 
graphical  errors,  repetitions,  delays,  etc.,  which  varied  greatly  among 
different  patients,  were  taken  as  measures  of  individual  and  type  dif- 
ferences. To  test  the  conscious  control  of  movements  the  Charriere 
apparatus  was  employed.  (2)  Vaso-motor  phenomena  and  emotional 
states.  The  sphygmograph  was  used  while  the  patient  was  asked 
various  questions,  some  of  which  he  could  answer,  others  not.  The 
record  indicated  the  patient's  emotional  excitability.  (3)  Field  of 
apperception  and  attention.  In  a  dark  room  a  number  of  stimuli 
were  simultaneously  illuminated  by  a  spark  from  a  Holtz  machine ; 
the  stimuli  used  in  different  tests  were  figures,  capital  letters  in  chance 
order,  the  same  forming  a  word,  and  letters  of  different  colors  in 
chance  order.  The  object  was  to  determine  the  number  of  stimuli 
recognized  in  each  case.  (4)  Reasoning,  cesthetic  emotion  and  as- 
sociation. Reproductions  (uncolored)  of  celebrated  pictures,  simple 
in  motive,  such  as  the  Angelus,  were  shown ;  also  a  series  of  eighteen 
photographs  representing  a  celebrated  French  actor  in  various  guises. 
The  subjects  were  to  tell  what  each  represented  or  sugggested.  (5) 
Organic  memory ;  sense  of  time  and  space.  A  dial  was  arranged 
with  a  hand  moving  in  one  direction,  slowly  and  uniformly.  This 
hand  was  first  made  to  move  over  a  determined  space  on  the  dial ; 
the  subject  was  then  blindfolded  and  told  to  make  the  hand  cover  the 
same  space,  starting  and  stopping  it  by  an  electric  key. 

The  authors  report  typical  results  obtained  from  the  patients  for 
each  test,  which  they  compare  with  results  obtained  on  normal  indi- 
viduals. They  do  not  attempt,  however,  to  tabulate  the  entire  series. 
The  third  and  fourth  tests  are  mentioned  as  giving  especially  interesting 
results,  which  differ  greatly  from  the  normal.  In  connection  with  the 
fifth  test,  the  authors  note  the  distinction  between  spatial  and  temporal 
types  of  individual,  as  well  as  a  neutral  type,  the  latter  measuring  the 
rate  equally  well  by  either  datum. 

The  second  paper  describes  experiments  performed  on  54  normal 
persons — 30  men  and  24  women.  Each  subject  was  tested  separately. 
A  paper  was  given  him,  on  which  were  written  the  five  combinations, 
He,  eno,  ago,  ondo  and  olle,  and  he  was  asked  to  set  down  as  many 
words  ending  in  each  of  these  as  he  could  think  of  in  ten  minutes. 
The  experimenters  noted  the  order  in  which  the  words  were  set  down, 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  115 

with  special  reference  to  the  skipping  about  from  one  ending  to  an- 
other ;  they  also  noted  the  number  set  down  during  each  successive 
minute.  From  the  tables  given  we  find  that  the  men's  average  was 
much  greater  than  the  women's  (39.2,  as  compared  with  27.5)  ;  that 
of  persons  30  years  of  age  or  over  greater  than  of  those  under  30 
(for  the  men  41.8,  as  compared  with  33.6),  and  the  average  number 
found  during  the  first  five  minutes  from  two  to  three  times  greater  for 
every  class  of  individuals  than  during  the  last  five  minutes.  A  differ- 
ence was  observed  in  the  procedure  of  men  and  women ;  the  former 
generally  endeavored  to  think  of  a  number  of  words  with  one  ending 
before  passing  to  another ;  the  latter  usually  attempted  to  find  one 
word  under  each  head  successively.  The  curve  representing  the  num- 
ber found  each  minute  falls  steadily  for  both  men  and  women,  except 
during  the  seventh  minute,  when  it  makes  a  decided  rise. 

There  are,  unfortunately,  several  serious  numerical  errors  in  the 
tables  published — notably  the  division  (three  times!)  in  Table  I.  by 
39,  instead  of  30,  the  number  of  males.  These  and  other  errors  throw 
doubt  on  the  reckoning  generally  and  tend  to  impair  the  value  of  the 
conclusions. 

In  the  third  paper  the  authors  describe  their  experiments  on  the 
4  thought  reader '  John  Dalton — who  is,  by  the  way,  a  great-nephew 
of  the  discoverer  of  Daltonism.  Dalton  lays  no  claim  to  any  occult 
powers,  but  simply  to  unusual  acuteness  of  perception  for  small  mus- 
cular indications  and  other  minute  forms  of  expression.  He  sub- 
mitted himself  willingly  to  all  the  tests,  and  seemed  eager  to  assist  as 
far  as  possible  in  elucidating  the  phenomena  in  question. 

Cranial  measurement  showed  nothing  noteworthy.  The  visual 
field  was  normal ;  the  visual  acuteness  slightly  below  the  normal.  A 
number  of  mental  tests  made  were  similar  to  those  described  above 
in  the  first  paper.  In  the  test  of  spatio-temporal  memory  Dalton 
proved  to  be  of  the  purely  spatial  type.  The  test  of  the  apperceptive 
field,  with  letters  illuminated  by  a  spark,  showed  him  to  be  rather  above 
the  normal.  With  the  Charriere  apparatus  for  testing  motor  ability  he 
proved  to  be  extraordinarily  expert  in  both  hands.  A  series  of  mem- 
ory tests  with  numbers,  colors,  etc.,  indicated  a  high  degree  of  devel- 
opment of  the  memory.  The  reaction  times  on  sight,  hearing  and 
touch  were  rather  large.  The  association  test  showed  a  decided  pre- 
ponderance of  visual  images,  with  a  large  number  of  ideational  asso- 
ciations; purely  verbal  associations  and  images  from  other  senses  were 
few  in  number.  The  subject  was  asked  to  describe,  blindfolded,  the 
nature  of  objects  placed  in  his  hand ;  the  results  showed  great  acute- 
ness  of  tactual  perception. 


n6  INDIVIDUAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

One  of  Dalton's  professional  '  specialties '  is  the  designation  of  an 
object  chosen  among  a  set  and  thought  of  earnestly  by  the  l  wilier/ 
whose  thoughts  he  'reads.'  He  accomplishes  this  both  with  and 
without  direct  contact  with  the  '  wilier.'  In  the  case  of  direct  contact 
the  minute  muscular  expressions  of  the  '  wilier '  furnish  the  general 
clue,  but  here,  as  in  the  case  without  direct  contact,  he  declares 
that  the  ultimate  indications  are  furnished  by  the  latter's  breathing. 
Tests  of  this  were  made  at  the  laboratory,  with  and  without  contact, 
a  pneumograph  being  used  to  record  the  *  willer's '  breathing.  Dalton 
picked  out  the  required  object  at  once,  but  purposely  passed  it  over 
two  or  three  times  before  finally  indicating  it.  The  breathing  curve 
showed  a  marked  change  whenever  he  approached  the  object.  The 
muscular  indications  proper  were  of  course  not  open  to  direct  experi- 
ment. Dalton  asserts  that  they  enable  him  to  discover  at  once  whether 
the  subject  is  good  or  not.  These  indications  are  not  always  of  the 
same  sort ;  some  subjects  give  l  guiding,'  some  '  opposing '  indications ; 
both  classes  of  hints,  however,  are  favorable.  It  is  only  when  a  sub- 
ject, through  lack  of  attention,  fails  to  give  any  indications  at  all,  or 
through  nervousness  makes  various  movements  besides  those  due  to 
the  object  in  question,  that  he  is  unable  to  succeed.  The  indications 
he  interprets  are  minute  in  character,  and  must  not  be  confused  with 
the  more  apparent  muscular  movements  which  the  unpracticed  ob- 
server might  regard  as  indications. 

In  the  latter  part  of  the  paper  the  authors  discuss  at  some  length 
the  history  and  theory  of  '  thought  reading.'  Three  distinct  theories 
have  been  advanced  to  account  for  the  phenomenon:  (i)  The  direct 
passage  of  something  from  brain  to  brain — the  spiritualistic  interpre- 
tation. (2)  The  transmission  of  nervous  force  from  brain  to  brain  by 
some  dynamic  process  not  yet  understood — by  a  sort  of  induction,  or 
by  some  species  of  transformation  of  energy.  (3)  The  transmission 
is  only  apparent ;  it  is  really  due  to  minute  and  unconscious  expres- 
sions on  the  one  hand  and  an  abnormally  acute  perception  on  the 
other.  The  present  tests,  corroborating  Dalton's  own  statements,  in- 
dicate that  the  third  explanation  will  cover  all  cases  where  the  l  thought 
reader '  and  his  subject  are  in  close  proximity.  In  accordance  with 
this  view  the  authors  ascribe  the  power  to  a  partial  dissociation  of 
subconscious  personality,  which  gives  rise  to  a  species  of  partial  autom- 
atism. They  believe  that  the  study  of  telepathic  phenomena  proper 
must  start  from  this  point  and  work  up,  proceeding  by  means  of  psy- 
chological experimentation,  and  using,  as  far  as  possible,  psychological 
laws  already  established.  HOWARD  C.  WARREN. 

PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  117 

VISION. 

Untersuchungen  zur  Pathologic  der  Pupillenweite  und  der  centrip- 
etalen   Pupittarfasern.      O.   SCHIRMER.     Graefe's  Archiv,   Bd. 

44>  PP-  358-4°4- 

Disturbances  in  the  pupillar  reflex  may  be  due  as  well  to  anomalies 
in  the  centripetal  part  of  the  reflex  circuit  as  in  the  centrifugal,  but 
almost  no  instances  of  such  anomalies  are  to  be  found  in  the  books, 
for  the  very  simple  reason  that  they  are  extremely  difficult  to  diagnos- 
ticate. The  subject  has,  however,  acquired  great  interest  since  it  has 
been  affirmed  by  v.  Gudden,  and  independently  by  Bechterew,  that 
there  are  special  centripetal  fibres  in  the  optic  nerve  for  the  regulation 
of  the  width  of  the  pupil.  These  fibres  are  thicker  than  the  visual 
fibres ;  they  cross,  in  half,  in  the  chiasma,  like  them ;  they  run  by  the 
side  of  the  visual  fibres  from  the  same  point  of  the  retina,  and  they 
leave  the  visual  fibres  only  in  the  region  of  the  external  geniculate 
body.  v.  Gudden  found  in  rabbits  that  the  removal  of  one  of  the 
corpora  quadrigemina  produced  contralateral  blindness  without  affect- 
ing the  movements  of  the  pupil ;  only  after  portions  of  the  thalamus 
were  also  disturbed  did  the  pupil  of  the  blind  eye  also  remain  widened. 
Schirmer  has  been  able,  by  an  admirable  series  of  observations  on  the 
human  eye,  to  make  the  following  additions  to  our  knowledge  of  this 
subject.  The  pupillar  fibres  of  the  optic  nerve  do  not  reach  so  far  as 
the  layer  of  rods  and  cones,  but  they  start  in  an  earlier  layer  of  the 
retina ;  their  terminal  organs  are  in  all  probability  the  amacrine  cells. 
The  macula  and  its  region  is  abundantly  supplied  with  pupillar  fibres, 
but  they  are  not  wanting  in  the  periphery ;  they  are  sufficiently  numer- 
ous there  to  keep  the  pupil  more  contracted  than  in  the  case  of  the 
cutting  of  the  optic  nerve.  The  pupillar  fibres  resist  mechanical  com- 
pression much  better  than  the  visual  fibres  do,  but  they  are  equally 
subject  to  inflammatory  processes,  and  hence  the  width  of  the  pupil 
may  become  an  aid  to  diagnosis. 

C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

BALTIMORE. 


Ii8  NEW  BOOKS. 

NEW  BOOKS. 

Beitrdge  zur  Akustik  und  Musikwissenschaft.  Herausg.  von  C. 
STUMPF.  2  Heft.  Leipzig,  Barth.  1898.  Pp.  170. 

Essai  cTune  Philosophic  nouvelle  suggeree  par  la  Science.  L. 
RIBERT.  Paris,  Alcan.  1897.  Pp.  562.  Fr.  6. 

System  der  Werttheorie.  CHR.  v.  EHRENFELS.  Leipzig,  Reisland. 
1897-8.  Bd.  i,  pp.  277.  Bd.  2,  pp.  270. 

Spirit  Slate- Writing  and  Kindred  Phenomena.  W.  E.  ROBINSON. 
New  York,  Munn  &  Co.  1898.  Pp.  155.  $i. 

Destinee  del'homme.  C.  PIATT.  Paris,  Alcan.  1898.  Pp.  244. 
Fr.  5. 

Les  Origines  de  la  Psychologic  contemporaine.  D.  MERCIER.  Lou- 
vain,  Institut  Super,  de  Philosophic.  1897.  Pp.  686.  Fr.  5. 

The  Psychology  of  Peoples.     G.  LE  BON.     New  York,  The  Mac- 

millan  Co.     1898.     Pp.  xii+236.     $1.50. 
La  Famille  dans  les  differ ents  Societes.     C.  N.  STARKE.     Paris, 

Giard  et  Briere.     1898.     Pp.  278.     Fr.  5  and  7. 
Sammlung  der  Abhandlungen  aus  Pddagogische  Psychologic.     Bd. 

II.,  H.   i.     Arbeitshygiene  der  Schule.     F.  KEMSIES.     Pp.  64. 

Bd.  II.,  H.  2.    Psychologische  Analyse  der  Thatsache  der  Selbst- 

erzeihung.     G.  CORDES.    Pp.  54.    Berlin,    Reuther  u.  Reichard. 

1898. 
Instinct  and  Reason.     H.  R.  MARSHALL.     New  York  and  London. 

1898.     Pp.  xiii  +  574.     $3.50. 
Apercus  de  Taxinomie  generale.     J.  P.  DURAND  (de  Gros).     Paris, 

Alcan.     1899.     Pp.  265.     Fr.  5. 
Psychophysiologische     Erkenntnistheorie.      TH.     ZIEHEN.      Jena, 

Fischer.     1898.     Pp.  105. 
Le  libre  arbitre.     ERNEST   NAVILLE.     2me  e"d.     Paris,  Alcan ;  Bale 

et  Geneve,  Georg.     1898.    Pp.  xiv+3ii.     Fr.  5. 
The  Doctrine  of  Energy.     B.  L.  L.     London,  Kegan  Paul.      1898. 

Pp.  x+io8. 
Anneebiologique.      YVES  DELAGE.    2me  anne"e,   1896.     Paris,  Rein- 

wald.     1898.     Pp.  xxxv-f  808.     Fr.  20. 
Report  of  the    Commissioner  of  Education  for  the    Tear  ending 

1896-7.      W.  T.    HARRIS.      Vol.    I.     Washington,    Government 

Printing  Office.     1898.     Pp.  vii+H36. 


NOTES.  119 

Contains  a  section   devoted  to  the   recent  literature  of  imitation 
made  up  of  articles  by  Miss  A.  Tolman  Smith,  W.  T.  Harris  (Chair- 
man), and  E.  H.  Russell. 
Psychologic   der     Veranderungsauffassung.     L.  WILLIAM  STERN. 

Breslau,  Preuss  &  Jiinger.     1898.     Pp.  xiii  -f  264. 
L?  Education  des  Sentiments.     P.  F.  THOMAS.    Paris,  Alcan.     1899. 

Pp.  287.     Fr.  5. 
Truth  and  Error,  or  the  Science  of  Intellection.     J.  W.  POWELL. 

Chicago,  Open  Court  Co.     1898.     Pp.  428.     $1.75. 


NOTES. 

THE  Macmillan  Co.  announce  the  early  appearance  of  an  English 
translation  of  M.  Tarde's  Les  Lois  Sociales,  by  Professor  H.  C. 
Warren,  of  Princeton.  We  reserve  our  notice  of  this  important  and 
timely  resume  of  M.  Tarde's  larger  works  until  the  translation  ap- 
pears. 

IN  accordance  with  the  request  of  the  Government  of  Venezuela 
and  of  the  Committee  on  Organization,  the  III  Pan-American  Medical 
Congress  is  postponed  to  meet  in  Caracas  in  December,  1900. 

THE  prospectus  has  been  issued  of  *  An  American  Journal  of 
Anthropology'  (name  not  yet  decided),  conducted  by  an  editorial 
board  of  well-known  anthropologists  with  F.  W.  Hodge  as  secretary 
and  managing  editor.  The  journal  is  to  be  the  organ  of  Section  H  of 
the  A.  A.  A.  S.,  and  it  will  replace  the  American  Anthropologist. 
Advance  subscriptions  should  be  sent  to  Dr.  Franz  Boas,  Columbia 
University,  New  York.  Quarterly,  $4. 

WE  have  received  also  the  prospectus  of  the  Zeitschrift  fur 
Pddagogische  Psychologic,  to  be  issued  first  in  January,  1899  (Ed. 
Dr.  F.  Kemsies,  Berlin ;  publisher,  H.  Walther,  Berlin).  Bimonthly. 
8M. 

THE  Archiv  f.  System.  Philos.,  Bd.  IX.,  Heft  4,  contains  its 
annual  Bibliography  of  Philosophical  Literature  for  1897  °^  23°7 
titles.  The  Revue  Neo-Scholastique  also  continues  its  quarterly 
Sommaire  Ideologique,  printed  on  one  side  of  the  paper  onlv,  for 
pasting  on  cards. 


120  NOTES. 

AT  a  recent  meeting  of  the  Academy  of  Moral  and  Political  Sci- 
ences, the  Gegner  prize  (3,800  fr.)  was  awarded  to  M.  F.  Pillon,  the 
Jean  Reynaud  prize  (10,000  fr.)  to  M.  Paul  Janet,  and  half  of  the 
Penanrtm  prize  (2,000  fr.)  to  l'Abb6  Piat  for  his  book  La  Personne 
humaine. 

THE  attention  of  psychologists  may  be  called  to  a  '  Critical  Re- 
view '  on  c  Modern  Neurology '  by  Dr.  Adolf  Meyer,  beginning  in  the 
Journ.  of  Comp.  Neurology,  November,  1898. 


VOL.  VI.     No.  2.  MARCH,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


ON   CERTAIN   HINDRANCES   TO    THE    PROGRESS 
OF   PSYCHOLOGY  IN  AMERICA.1 

BY  PROFESSOR  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

Yale   University. 

The  progress  of  any  of  the  positive  sciences  is  always  de- 
pendent upon  the  personal  characteristics  of  the  men  devoted  to 
the  special  science,  quite  as  much  as  upon  any  other  condition. 
The  history  of  their  development  in  the  past  would  show  this 
statement  to  be  true  even  in  the  case  of  those  sciences  which  are 
most  independent  of  all  subjective  influences.  A  survey  of  all 
the  favorable  and  unfavorable  conditions  under  which  astronomy, 
physics,  chemistry  and  biology  are  developing  at  the  present 
time — in  spite  of  the  enormous  recent  increase  in  the  impor- 
tance of  instrumentation  and  technique — does  not,  I  believe, 
throw  discredit  upon  the  value  of  personal  characteristics.  It 
is,  after  all,  the  quality  of  its  scientific  men  which  largely  or 
chiefly  determines  whether  the  rate  of  scientific  progress  shall 
be  rapid  or  slow  in  any  particular  age. 

If  this  dependence  on  the  character  of  the  mind  which  goes 
into  them  is  obvious  for  the  physico-chemical  sciences,  it  may  be 
taken  for  granted  as  the  chief  condition  determining  the  rate  of 
the  progress  of  psychological  science.  For  psychology  is  the 
science  of  mind — of  the  mental  life  and  mental  development  of 
the  individual  man ;  it  is,  therefore,  in  its  essential  nature,  more 
influenced  than  are  the  physico-chemical  sciences  by  the  kind 
of  a  mind  that  undertakes  to  deal  scientifically  with  the  things 

1  Read  before  the  American  Psychological  Association,  New  York,  Decem- 
ber, 1898. 


122  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

of  the  mind.  Its  method,  moreover,  is  such  as  to  lay  emphasis, 
in  respect  of  content,  upon  a  rich  experience  of  knowledge, 
sentiment  and  practical  activities ;  and,  in  respect  of  way  of  ap- 
proach, upon  training  in  introspective  analytics  and  in  herme- 
neutical  skill.  Sympathy  with  all  that  is  really  human,  and 
experience  which  covers  all  which  is  essentially  human ;  these 
are  indispensable  qualifications  of  the  high-class  psychologist. 
In  psychology,  -personnel  and  materiel  are  most  intimately 
allied. 

I  am  going  to  undertake  an  ungrateful  task,  and  one  which 
cannot  expect  to  appeal  strongly  to  the  sympathies  of  my  au- 
dience ;  perhaps  it  cannot  even  get  its  conclusions  accredited  by 
them  as  having  a  basis  of  accepted  facts.  For  this  reason  the 
undertaking  may  fitly  begin  with  a  few  words  of  more  or  less  ab- 
ject apology.  And,  first,  what  will  be  said  cannot  be  proved 
true  either  by  demonstration  or  by  induction ;  and  to  attempt  its 
proof  by  the  method  of  illustration  would  be,  of  all  ways,  most 
unfortunate.  Its  value  can  be,  at  most,  only  such  as  may  be  ac- 
corded to  the  opinions  of  one  who  has  been  watching  the  course 
of  psychological  science  in  this  country,  from  an  interior  point 
of  view,  during  a  score  of  years.  The  opinion  you  are  respect- 
fully asked  to  consider  may  be  briefly  summarized  as  follows  : 
As  compared  with  the  increase  in  number  of  trained  teachers 
and  investigators,  and  in  the  amount  and  quality  of  laboratory 
and  other  equipment,  the  science  of  psychology  is  not  making 
with  us  the  progress  which  may  rightfully  be  expected  of  it. 
When  inquiry  is  made,  however,  into  the  hindrances  of  progress, 
and  after  due  allowance  for  the  intrinsic  difficulties  of  the  science 
and  for  all  the  remaining  deficiencies  in  equipment,  it  is  found 
that  one  of  these  hindrances  consists  in  the  limited  and  faulty 
qualifications  of  psychologists. 

The  grounds  for  this  state  of  my  own  belief  I  shall  now  pro- 
ceed to  make  clear  in  several  particulars.  And  though  my 
theme  concern  personal  qualifications,  I  distinctly  disclaim  all 
intentional  personalities. 

The  first  hindrance  to  the  progress  of  psychology  in  America 
to  which  I  wish  to  call  attention  is  an  excessive  aloofness  from, 
and  a  consequent  ignorance  of,  the  real  mental  life  and  mental 


HINDRANCES  TO  PS  YCHOLOG  Y  IN  AMERICA.  1 23 

development  of  the  average  human  being.  Now,  we  psycholo- 
gists may  define  the  subject  matter  of  our  science  and  limit  its 
special  problems  as  we  please ;  and  I  have  nothing  to  urge 
against,  but  much  to  say  in  favor  of,  the  high  specialization 
and  careful  experimental  methods  of  modern  psychology.  At 
the  same  time,  where  such  specialization  is  not  based  upon,  and 
constantly  united  with,  an  ever  widening  and  more  sympathetic 
acquaintance  with  many  men  of  many  kinds,  its  results  are  un- 
satisfactory. This  is  likely  to  be  true  both  from  the  scientific 
and  from  the  practical  points  of  view.  If  I  may  be  allowed  an 
old-fashioned  term — which  is,  however,  just  as  valuable  and 
significant  now  as  it  ever  was — psychology  is  nothing  but  the 
descriptive  and  explanatory  study  of  the  *  souls '  of  men.  And 
there  is  no  way  of  knowing  what  souls  are,  and  can  do,  which 
does  not  involve  the  interpretation,  in  terms  of  one's  own  self- 
consciousness,  of  the  physical  signs  given  of  the  conscious 
state  of  other  souls.  The  psychologist,  then,  who  is  a  mere 
experimentalist,  or  a  mere  scholastic  student  and  teacher,  or  a 
mere  reader  of  books,  does  not  know  thoroughly  his  business. 
For  his  business  is  human  nature ;  and  human  nature  shows 
itself,  as  it  really  is,  only  to  the  man  who,  having  it  all  in 
himself  and  having  a  trained  self-knowledge,  is  fitted  to  observe, 
and  to  interpret,  and  to  theorize  upon,  the  natures  of  his  fellow- 
men. 

"  Wills t  du  dick  selber  erkennen,  so  sieh  ivie  die  Anderen  es  treiben; 
Willst  du  die  Anderen  verstehn,  blick  in  dein  eigenes  Herz." 

Whatever  may  be  said  in  depreciation  of  the  so-called  *  old 
psychology,'  it  cannot  be  denied  that  its  more  permanent  and 
rapid  gains  were  largely  due  to  the  fact  that  the  problems  of  the 
human  soul  have  enlisted  the  efforts  of  so  many  men  widely 
acquainted  with,  and  sympathetically  interested  in,  the  whole 
body  of  their  fellow-men.  The  knowledge  of  human  mental 
life  and  development  which  is  obtained  by  experience  only  with 
certain  classes  of  people,  or  with  certain  aspects  of  human 
nature,  is,  indeed,  usually  prejudiced,  narrow,  and  not  entitled 
to  credit  for  its  scientific  character.  But  it  all  furnishes  invalu- 
able material  for  the  scientific  psychologist.  The  man  of  busi- 
ness, the  physician,  the  pastor,  the  police  judge  or  keeper  of 


124  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

the  jail,  and  even  the  gambler,  the  tramp,  the  prostitute,  knows 
something  that  answers  to  fact  and  to  reality  about  the  soul  of 
man.  This  knowledge,  too,  has  a  bearing  upon  the  problems 
of  the  school. 

In  my  judgment — to  cite  one  or  more  examples — it  is  not 
scientific,  not  to  say  ethically  proper,  without  knowing  what 
observers  of  human  nature  in  the  large  know,  to  establish  de- 
terminism on  the  basis  of  a  few  thousand  reactions  in  the  psy- 
chological laboratory ;  or  to  resolve  the  moral  and  religious 
sentiments  of  humanity  into  modifications  of  the  pleasure-pains  ; 
or  to  deny  the  rights  of  that  instinctive  metaphysics  without 
which  the  «  man  of  the  school '  is  justly  deemed  by  the  '  man  of 
affairs '  to  be  lacking  in  '  common  sense/ 

The  soul  of  man  is  no  simple  equation  to  be  stated  in  terms 
of  the  *  differentiation,'  *  aggregation,'  '  redintegration,'  of  sensa- 
tional factors.  Its  manifold  beliefs,  fears,  hopes,  aspirations, 
and  even  cognitions,  that  take  hold  on  what  is  forever  hidden 
from  sense,  and  yet  give  support  and  value  to  sensation  itself, 
are  integral  'moments 'in  its  own  being.  The  scientific  psy- 
chologist, much  more  than  the  Latin  poetizer,  is  committed  to 
the  principle  of  not  esteeming  anything  human  foreign  to  him- 
self. And  while  he  must,  of  course,  restrict  his  more  special 
investigations  to  comparatively  narrow  lines,  if  this  is  done  in 
the  spirit  of  aloofness  from,  or  in  ignorance  of,  the  actual  human 
nature  of  the  multitude  of  men,  he  cannot  claim  to  have  the  best 
fitness  for  the  pursuit  of  his  chosen  science.  Above  all  other 
hindrances  will  the  genuine  student  of  psychology  dread  the 
limitations  of  academic  narrowness  and  bigotry.  For  him  the 
worst  of  slaveries  is  to  be  confined  by  the  bands  of  the  scholastic 
temper  and  habit  of  life.  Better  the  ornithologist  who  knows 
nothing  of  birds  in  the  wild  wood,  or  the  geologist  who  has 
studied  only  the  collections  of  his  college  museum,  or  the  anato- 
mist who  has  dissected  only  the  manikin  of  his  medical  school, 
or  the  artist  who  knows  only  the  artificial  poses  of  his  favorite 
model,  than  the  psychologist  who  has  no  wider  acquaintance 
with  the  souls  of  men  than  the  laboratory,  or  the  class-room,  or 
the  book  of  his  favorite  author,  can  give  him. 

The  teachers  of  psychology  in  the  higher  institutions  of  learn- 


HINDRANCES  TO  PSYCHOLOGY  IN  AMERICA.  125 

ing  in  this  country  are  to-day,  on  the  whole,  much  better  trained 
in  scientific  spirit  and  method,  much  better  acquainted  with  the 
technique  and  the  literature  of  their  science,  than  were  the 
teachers  of  twenty-five  and  fifty  years  ago.  For  this  reason 
they  are  more  largely  the  younger  men.  These  facts  are  on 
the  whole  hopeful  for  the  more  satisfactory  progress  in  the 
future  of  psychology  and  the  allied  sciences.  But  unless  at  the 
same  time  their  interest  in,  and  acquaintance  with,  human  life 
in  a  large  way  is  correspondingly  cultivated,  these  teachers  will 
not  in  some  respects  be  the  equals,  much  less  the  superiors,  of 
the  teachers  of  the  olden  time.  He  cannot  know,  or  understand 
— whether  to  describe  or  to  explain — what  is  '  in  man,'  who  has 
not  somehow  had  it  first  in  his  own  experience  with  himself. 

It  is  perhaps  partly  in  reaction  against  an  excessive  scho- 
lastic spirit  and  method,  that  another  and  quite  opposed  hin- 
drance to  the  progress  of  psychology  has  recently  appeared. 
I  refer  now  to  an  absurd  surplusage  of  attempts  to  render  the 
science  popular,  which  has  emanated  chiefly  from  writers  who 
lack  almost  all  the  qualifications  of  the  trained  expert.  It  would 
seem  as  though  the  secret  meditations  of  not  a  few  of  these 
popularizers  of  psychology  might  be  expressed  in  somewhat  the 
following  fashion.  *  'These  professors  of  psychology,  these  Fach- 
Seelenforscher,  are  not  up  to  their  business ;  for  they  are  not 
telling  the  people  much  that  is  new  about  human  nature ;  and 
what  they  do  tell  is  not  intelligible  to  the  people,  neither  is  it  ex- 
pressed in  an  altogether  taking  way.  Go  to, 'now :  I  will  show 
them  how  to  do  it.  Since  I  am  a  teacher  of  something,  or  at 
least  know  what  plain  people  want,  I  will  be  a  teacher  of  psy- 
chology to  these  same  plain  people.  That  is  to  say,  I  will  write 
a  book  which  shall  have  all  the  science  of  the  professor,  and 
shall  also  be  easily  intelligible  and  practical." 

Perhaps  such  expressions  as  the  foregoing  misinterpret  the 
consciousness  of  this  swarm  of  improvised  teachers  of  psycho- 
logical science  in  America  to-day.  But  there  is  one  fact  which 
seems  to  admit  of  only  one  conclusion  :  the  multiplication  of 
books  popularizing  psychology,  written  by  authors  who  have 
never  had  any  truly  scientific  training,  is,  on  the  whole,  a  dis- 
tinct hindrance  to  the  best  progress  of  this  science.  And,  in- 


126  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

deed,  what  valid  reason  is  there  for  such  an  altogether  dispro- 
portionate affliction  of  this  particular  science  in  this  particular 
way  ?  Books  on  physics,  chemistry,  zoology,  physiology,  do 
not  proceed  in  rival  numbers  from  the  pens  of  men  who  have 
never  made  any  prolonged,  well  concentrated,  and  judiciously 
guided  study  of  the  subjects  treated  by  these  positive  sciences. 
We  are  inclined  to  look  somewhat  too  contemptuously  upon  the 
'  old  psychology'  and  upon  its  teachers,  because  mere  schooling 
as  a  minister,  when  made  up  into  a  college  president,  was  es- 
teemed a  sufficient  test  of  fitness  to  exploit  one's  self  as  an  author- 
ity in  psychological  science.  But  what  better  is  this  modern 
way  of  gathering  from  here  and  from  there,  concealing  in  whole 
or  in  part  the  sources  from  which  the  information  is  gathered, 
emphasizing  the  didactic  calling  as  practiced  from  the  platform 
of  the  school  rather  than  that  of  the  church,  and  then  issuing 
a  patchwork  book  into  the  already  overcrowded  shelves  of  the 
publishers  ? 

Fortunately,  however,  these  two  opposite  tendencies  may  be 
expected  in  time  to  correct  each  other ;  and  if  those  authorities 
who  have  scientific  preeminence  and  scholastic  opportunity 
finally  get  their  scientific  knowledge  popularized,  the  crude  at- 
tempt at  popularization  made  by  the  multitude  of  tyros  may 
have  prepared  the  way  for  them.  In  the  meantime,  the  multi- 
tude of  books  on  psychology  by  those  who  have  really  never 
made  any  serious,  not  to  say  sufficient,  study  of  psychology 
would  seem  to  be  a  hindrance  to  the  progress  of  the  science. 

Another  hindrance  to  the  more  rapid  advance  of  psychology 
is  to  be  found,  I  think,  in  the  manner  in  which  much  of  the 
presentation  and  discussion  of  psychological  problems  is  con- 
ducted. This  manner  is  by  no  means  always  or  even  generally 
ill-meant :  nevertheless,  it  seems  to  me  inconsistent  with  the 
higher  and  more  noble  purposes  of  psychological  science.  For, 
in  the  first  place,  it  excites  suspicion,  if  it  does  not  engender 
distrust  and  scorn,  on  the  part  of  the  community  looking  on 
from  outside  the  inner  circle  of  psychologists  themselves.  A 
dead  uniformity  of  opinion,  or  an  enforced  consensus  of  ex- 
pression, is,  of  course,  not  the  genuine  scientific  attitude  toward 
any  subject  of  investigation ;  nor  does  it  further  the  progress  of 


HINDRANCES  TO  PSYCHOLOGY  IN  AMERICA.  127 

any  science  to  try  to  secure  prematurely  such  opinion,  such 
consensus.  At  the  same  time,  without  some  common  basis  of 
knowledge  and  of  method,  it  is  foolish  to  speak  of  the  *  science ' 
of  psychology  at  all,  and  idle  to  form  an  association  of  men 
who  are  in  the  common  pursuit  of  such  science.  For  one,  I 
believe  that  there  already  exists  a  science  of  psychology.  It  is 
not  all  a  *  natural  science,'  in  the  sense  of  being  a  physiological 
or  cerebral  psychology  :  it  is  not  all  an  experimental  psychology, 
or  a  psycho-physical  psychology,  or  a  speculative  psychology. 
It  is  simply  the  net  result  of  human  experience,  gathered  in 
whatever  way,  as  to  the  faithful  description  and  satisfactory  ex- 
planation of  the  mental  life  of  the  individual  man.  These  net 
results  constitute  a  very  respectable  body  of  established  truths  ; 
they  are  the  science  of  psychology.  Whoever  underestimates 
and  depreciates  these  commonly  accepted  truths,  and  over- 
emphasizes his  own  peculiar  conclusions  or  methods  to  the  dis- 
credit of  these  truths,  is  likely  to  hinder  rather  than  to  advance 
the  real  interests  of  psychology.  Before  the  layman  he  makes 
the  same  impression  which  is  made  by  the  new  recruit  to  the 
missionary  force  when  he  proceeds  at  once  to  proclaim  loudly 
the  differences  of  his  sect  or  school  from  all  others  that  bear  the 
common  name  of  Christian. 

One  cannot  for  a  moment  believe  that  the  psychologists  of 
this  country  are  any  less  under  the  dominion  of  authority,  or 
any  more  exacting  in  the  tests  they  apply  to  their  hypotheses  and 
theories,  than  are  the  physicists,  the  chemists  or  the  biologists. 
Yet  it  is  my  impression  that  the  latter  are,  when  compared  with 
the  former,  more  respectful  toward  matured  opinions,  more  ap- 
preciative of  long-continued  services,  more  accustomed  to  place 
the  emphasis — where  it  belongs — upon  the  growing  body  of  ac- 
credited conclusions,  and  more  courteous  in  the  discussion  of 
minor  differences.  It  will  be  said  that  if  such  a  difference 
really  exists,  it  is  due  to  the  difference  in  the  character  of  the 
subjects  studied.  For  my  part,  I  believe  that  this,  too,  is  an 
affair  of  personnel  rather  than  of  materiel. 

In  close  connection  with  these  differences,  one  is  almost 
forced  to  remark  another  difference  that  concerns  the  literary 
style  of  that  discussion  of  mooted  points  in  which  we  psycholo- 


128  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

gists  are  apt  to  indulge.  Am  I  wrong  in  believing  that  there  is 
a  higher  average  of  dignity  and  reserve  in  the  polemics  of  our 
colleagues  of  the  physico-chemical  and  biological  sciences? 
Certainly  *  discussion  '  is  indispensable  to  progress  in  psychology 
as  in  all  the  other  positive  forms  of  science ;  and  the  place  given 
to  it  in  the  journalism  or  in  the  associations  of  psychologists  is 
not  too  large.  Even  lively  polemics  over  scientific  subjects  is 
not  always  undesirable :  although  it  is  probable  that  a  careful 
examination  of  the  history  of  the  development  of  the  positive 
sciences  would  show  that  polemics  really  counts  for  compara- 
tively little  as  a  contribution  to  such  development.  Most  of  the 
work  which  really  advances  science  is  done  by  those  who  are 
most  diligent  in  research,  patient  in  forming  their  own  conclu- 
sions, and  least  eager  to  play  the  part  of  the  brilliant  and  de- 
structive critic  of  other  men's  conclusions. 

But  one  fails  to  see — at  least  in  the  first  instance — why  the 
jaunty,  snappy,  newspaper  style  should  be  more  appropriate  to 
the  science  of  psychology  than  to  any  of  the  other  natural  sci- 
ences. Is  the  soul  of  man  itself  such  an  inferior  kind  of  reality 
that  the  discussion  of  its  attributes,  activities  and  development, 
should  run  the  risks  of  the  other  worst  improprieties,  in  order  to 
escape  the  charge  of  dullness  ?  Is  not  levity  as  inappropriate  to 
the  scientific  examination  and  exhibition  of  the  facts  of  human 
consciousness,  as  it  is  to  the  description  and  explanation  of  the 
behavior  of  an  amoeba  or  of  the  development  of  the  egg  from  a 
common  barn-fowl?  Or,  again,  why  should  voluminous  and 
prolonged  descriptions  of  a  certain  species  of  micro-organisms 
be  welcomed  as  worth  years  of  scientific  research,  and  then 
similar  studies  of  mental  development  be  subjected  to  jest  or  to 
fault-finding  for  the  same  qualities  of  thoroughness — and  this 
by  psychologists  themselves? 

On  approaching  the  next,  and  fourth,  kind  of  hindrances  to 
the  best  progress  of  psychological  science  in  America,  so  far  as 
these  hindrances  are  under  the  immediate  control  of  psycholo- 
gists themselves,  I  am  well  aware  of  treading  on  yet  more 
doubtful  and  dangerous  ground.  I  must  again,  however,  ask 
a  brief  indulgence  for  the  expression  of  somewhat  vague  beliefs 
and  fears  rather  than  conclusions  based  on  indisputable  facts. 


HINDRANCES  TO  PSYCHOLOGY  IN  AMERICA.  129 

These  beliefs  and  fears  it  is  which  lead  me  to  say  that  the 
growth  of  the  commercial  spirit  within  academical  circles,  and 
as  touching  scholastic  affairs,  is  becoming  a  real  hindrance  to 
psychological  science.  Now  the  spirit  of  genuine  science  is 
sincere  and  unselfish.  The  man  who  adopts  as  his  profession 
any  form  of  science — to  use  a  familiar  expression — chiefly  *  for 
what  he  can  make  out  of  it '  is  really  not  tn,  or  inside  of,  that 
science  at  all.  But  the  mind  that  follows  the  science  of  man's 
mental  life,  through  feelings  of  personal  ambition,  or  under  the 
influence  of  jealousy,  prejudice  or  bigotry — either  theological 
or  anti-theological — makes  itself  thereby  less  capable  of  dis- 
cerning and  appreciating  its  full  content,  functioning  and  de- 
velopment. 

That  the  'commercial  spirit'  is,  the  world  over,  just  now 
increasingly  dominant  in  social  and  political  institutions  and 
relations,  admits  of  no  doubt.  Hitherto  the  higher  educational 
circles  and  institutions  of  this  country  have  had  a  large  and 
fortunate  exemption  from  the  influences  of  this  spirit.  They 
are  still  in  the  enjoyment  of  a  relative  exemption  from  these 
influences.  The  teachers  of  the  sciences  are  still,  I  believe,  less 
dominated  by  merely  personal  considerations  in  the  pursuit  of 
their  ideals — the  ideals  of  knowledge  as  related  to  the  increase 
of  human  well-being — than  are  any  other  class  of  men  in  the 
country,  clergymen  not  excepted.  But  there  are  signs  that  the 
commercial  spirit  is  to  a  certain  extent  displacing  the  truly 
scientific  spirit,  even  in  these  higher  scholastic  circles. 

I  find  these  signs  of  the  intrusion  of  the  commercial  spirit 
upon  the  domains  of  science  in  the  following  results  :  To  this 
spirit  it  is  due,  in  part,  that  there  is  an  increasing  amount  of 
premature  publication  on  the  subject  of  psychology.  I  am  not 
one  of  those  who  believe  that  the  student  should  withhold  his 
conclusions  until  he  has  made  them  absolutely  unassailable  in 
respect  of  proof,  and  perfect  in  form.  If  this  were  the  rule, 
no  wise  man  would  ever  publish  anything.  It  is  quite  legitimate, 
moreover,  to  subject  one's  own  work,  while  immature — and 
even  on  account  of  its  confessed  immaturity — to  the  criticism  of 
one's  colleagues.  For  the  metabolism  of  every  body  of  a  posi- 
tive science  consists  in  the  appropriation  of  only  a  part  of  what 


130  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

is  offered  to  it,  and  in  the  rejection  of  the  remainder.  But  when 
premature  publication  is  largely  encouraged  by  the  ambition  to 
get  one's  self  into  notice,  or  to  better  one's  financial  condition, 
rather  than  to  advance  the  cause  of  science,  its  excess  may 
become  a  positive  hindrance  to  science. 

In  part,  also,  to  the  growth  of  the  commercial  spirit  is  due 
the  practice  of  saying  really  commonplace  things  in  strange 
and  unfamiliar  ways;  as  though,  indeed,  mannerism  in  ex- 
pression, or  license  in  the  invention  of  new  terms,  would  be 
mistaken  for  originality  in  research  and  for  independence  of 
thinking.  Doubtless,  psychology  has  the  same  right  as  any 
other  science  to  develop  a  technical  terminology.  And  if  a  new 
mental  factor,  or  faculty,  or  law  of  mental  life,  is  discovered  by 
any  student  of  psychology,  and  no  appropriate  term  for  the  dis- 
covery seems  to  be  at  hand,  why — I,  for  one,  am  not  going  to 
say  that  the  discoverer  is  not  entitled  to  signalize  the  triumph  of 
his  insight  by  giving  a  new  name  to  his  discovery.  At  the  same 
time,  the  science  of  psychology  may  well  be  very  conservative 
in  such  matters.  A  time-honored  truth  is  no  better,  a  time-worn 
fallacy  is  no  more  acceptable,  because  either  is  presented  in 
language  calculated  to  deceive  the  laity  into  thinking  that  it  is 
the  latest  thing  in  modern  psychology.  Genuine  science  will 
not  increase  its  speed  by  exacerbating  our  characteristic  Ameri- 
can impatience.  After  all,  even  modern  science  goes  pretty 
slow ;  not  a  few  of  its  most  loudly  applauded  recent  results  will 
probably  have  to  be  carefully  reconsidered  and  much  modified 
before  they  are  adopted  into  the  body  of  its  assured  results. 

Hitherto  the  pursuit  of  the  positive  sciences  in  this  country 
has  been  remarkably  free,  as  compared  with  European  countries 
generally,  from  hindrances  growing  out  of  personal  and  insti- 
tutional jealousies.  This  freedom  has  been  partly  due  to  dif- 
ference in  the  mode  of  making  academic  appointments,  and  in 
the  relations  of  supply  and  demand  as  touching  the  candidates 
for  these  appointments.  There  are  some  signs  that  the  growth 
of  the  commercial  as  distinguished  from  the  genuine  scientific 
spirit  is  beginning  to  breed  and  to  foster  personal  and  institu- 
tional jealousies  among  us.  If  these  signs  tell  the  truth,  then 
the  truth  is  to  be  deplored.  But  surely  the  remedy  for  this  hin- 


HINDRANCES  TO  PS YCHOLOGY  IN  AMERICA.  131 

drance  to  the  more  rapid  progress  of  psychology,  if  it  exist,  is 
an  affair  of  personnel  rather  than  of  materiel. 

There  is  one  other  hindrance  to  psychology,  as  a  claimant 
to  some  established  position  among  the  positive  sciences,  which 
I  wish  to  note.  This  is  a  certain  vacillating  and  insecure  attitude 
toward  the  other  most  closely  allied  sciences — an  attitude  some- 
what similar  to  that  of  the  nouveaux  riches  toward  the  recog- 
nized aristocratic  classes  of  society.  I  firmly  believe  that  psy- 
chology, in  respect  both  of  subject-matter  and  of  method,  and 
also  of  available  accumulations,  might  make  itself  entitled  to 
take  a  place  of  equality — equally  independent  and  free-spirited, 
equally  docile  and  temperate — among  the  modern  sciences. 
The  physico-chemical  and  biological  sciences  all  have  much 
wealth  of  knowledge  and  of  technique  to  share  with  psychol- 
ogy ;  I  believe  that  psychology  might  have  something  approach- 
ing an  equal  value  to  share  with  them.  And  the  recent  «  affili- 
ation '  to  which  every  meeting  of  this  Association  bears  witness 
is  one  of  the  best  signs  of  the  *  better-time-coming  '  for  psy- 
chological science. 

The  older  psychology  was  too  much  disposed  to  maintain  an 
attitude  of  exaggerated  independence,  of  stiff  and  proud  aloof- 
ness, toward  physics,  chemistry  and  the  biological  sciences. 
Its  teachers  knew  that  their  souls  were  their  own ;  and  they 
often  appeared  to  suppose  that  the  scientific  study  of  these  souls 
could  be  best  conducted  in  complete  disregard  of  the  physical 
conditions  and  environment  in  which  all  mental  life  and  mental 
development  is  set.  The  new  psychology,  in  its  proper  reaction 
from  this  attitude  of  unscientific  isolation,  is  tempted  to  take 
an  attitude  of  equally  unscientific  servility.  Its  teachers  are  less 
sure  that  their  souls  are  their  own,  or  even  that  there  are  any 
souls,  than  were  the  teachers  of  the  earlier  days.  Some  of  them 
are  less  sure  than  is  the  average  chemist,  physicist  or  biologist, 
who — however  modern  he  may  be  in  his  own  specialty — is 
rather  apt  to  be  conservative  with  regard  to  the  existence  of  his 
own  soul. 

In  the  history  of  scientific  development  always,  but  perhaps 
never  more  than  of  late,  there  has  existed  in  the  minds  of  some 
— enthusiastic  dreamers,  for  the  most  part,  albeit  often  men  of 


132  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

great  eminence  in  the  particular  sciences — the  captivating  notion 
of  a  '  universal*  science.  If  we  could  only  get  at  this  one 
science,  in  all  its  depth  and  height  and  length,  then  we  should 
have  at  least  the  key  to  all  the  mysteries  of  universal  Nature. 
She  would,  to  be  sure,  still  remain  rather  a  complicated  and 
somewhat  freakish  and  irregular  creature  ;  but  man  would  have 
the  science  of  her,  in  the  large,  as  it  were.  Of  late,  the  last- 
century  conception  of  the  universal  mechanism,  under  which  all 
selves  and  all  things  alike  come,  has  been  somewhat  thoroughly 
shaken  up.  But  the  demand,  or  the  hortation,  for  another  step 
toward  the  ideal  of  unity,  is  generally  issued  at  present  by  some 
one  of  the  particular  sciences  to  those  others  which  lie  nearest 
its  own  door.  For  example,  physics  may  be  willing  to  unify 
chemistry — by  absorbing  it  into  itself.  Chemistry  may  wish  to 
effect  a  complete  harmony  with  physiology,  in  somewhat  the 
same  way.  Undoubtedly,  in  the  minds  of  a  multitude  of  bi- 
ologists, psychology,  as  a  science,  is  only  a  subdivision  of  bi- 
ology, a  dependent  branch  on  the  tree  of  universal  life.  All 
this  reminds  one  of  the  current  practical  proposals  to  effect  a 
unity  of  the  Church,  which,  in  the  thought  of  each  particular 
denomination,  take  the  form  of  an  <  embracement '  of  all  the 
other  denominations,  by  that  particular  one  making  itself  the 
universal. 

On  the  other  hand,  I  wish  to  testify  out  of  my  personal  ex- 
perience that  I  have  found  more  of  the  truly  scientific  reserve  and 
caution,  in  the  matter  of  premature  and  unverified  extension  of 
their  own  principles,  on  the  part  of  the  most  thoroughly  culti- 
vated men  in  the  physico-chemical  and  biological  sciences,  than 
on  the  part  of  a  large  number  of  psychologists  when  dealing 
with  these  same  physical  and  biological  principles.  Suppose, 
for  example,  the  question  arises  as  to  the  bearing  of  the  theory 
of  the  conservation  and  correlation  of  energy  upon  the  psycho- 
logical problem  of  the  will ;  or  that  the  accepted  principles  of 
cerebral  physiology — granted  the  very  doubtful  claim  that  such 
principles  can  be  found — be  asked  to  contribute  to  the  discussion 
of  the  hypothesis  of  psycho-physical  parallelism ;  or  what  not 
among  hypotheses  of  this  order.  It  is  my  experience  that  the 
psychologist  who  has  only  a  smattering  of  knowledge  on  these 


HINDRANCES  TO  PS YCHOL OGY  IN  AMERICA.  1 33 

physico-chemical  subjects  is  much  the  likelier  to  take  the  un- 
scientific and  prematurely  i  cocksure '  position,  with  regard  to 
their  application  to  psychological  subjects — in  the  name  of  the 
borrowed,  but  misunderstood  and  misapplied,  authority  of  the 
chemico-physical  and  biological  sciences. 

But  however  this  may  be,  there  is  little  doubt  that  any  other 
than  an  independent  attitude,  which  is  also  respectful  and  docile, 
toward  allied  sciences  is  distinctly  disadvantageous  to  the 
science  of  psychology.  There  is  just  as  little  doubt  that  the 
vacillating  and  uncertain  or  servile  attitude  toward  certain  other 
sciences,  which  not  a  few  students  of  psychology  assume,  is  a 
convincing  witness  to  a  raw  and  immature  and  misinformed  con- 
dition of  mind  respecting  their  own  science.  Psychology,  if  it 
wishes  to  get  more  respect  from  the  other  members  of  the  great 
brotherhood  of  science,  must  respect  itself.  In  order  to  entitle 
itself  to  more  self-respect  and  to  more  of  respect  from  others,  it 
must  be,  of  course,  respectful  and  teachable  toward  all  truth ; 
but  it  must  also  know  its  own  peculiar  rights  of  domain,  must 
maintain  and  defend  them,  and  must  cultivate  this  domain 
by  its  own  somewhat  peculiar  methods,  with  the  free  and  inde- 
pendent spirit  which  belongs  to  every  worker  in  every  field  of 
science.  Psychology  must  remain  <  affiliated ;'  it  must  enter 
more  intimately  into  the  circle  of  affiliated  science ;  but  it  must 
go  there  more  and  more  richly  laden,  to  teach  and  to  learn,  as 
*  one  among  many '  who  are  really  all  working  toward  the  same 
end.  That  end  is  the  scientific  conquest  of  all  reality,  to  the 
improvement  of  human  society. 

Well,  brethren  of  the  Association  of  Psychologists  in  Amer- 
ica, I  have  expressed  somewhat  freely  my  private  opinions. 
They  are  mere  opinions ;  and  you  will,  of  course,  take  them 
only  for  what  they  may  seem  to  you  worth.  There  is,  of  course, 
another  and  brighter  side ;  abundant  helps  and  signs  of  prog- 
ress, as  well  as  certain  hindrances  and  indications  of  an  unsat- 
isfactory rate  of  progress.  It  is  of  the  latter,  so  far  as  they  be- 
long more  to  personnel  than  to  materiel,  that  I  have  ventured  to 
speak.  And  the  practical  lesson,  if  there  be  any,  is  obvious. 


THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MODESTY. 

BY    HAVELOCK    ELLIS. 
Cornwall,  England. 

Modesty — which  may  be  provisionally  defined  as  an  almost 
instinctive  fear,  prompting  to  concealment,  and  usually  centering 
around  the  sexual  nature — while  common  to  both  sexes  is  more 
especially  feminine,  so  that  it  may  almost  be  regarded  as  the 
chief  secondary  sexual  character  of  women  on  the  psychic  side. 
The  woman  who  is  lacking  in  this  kind  of  fear  is  lacking  also 
in  sexual  attractiveness  to  the  normal  and  average  man.  As 
a  psychic  secondary  sexual  character  of  the  first  rank,  is  it 
necessary,  before  any  psychology  of  sex  can  be  arranged  in 
order,  to  obtain  a  clear  view  of  modesty.1 

1  have  not,  however,  been  able  to  find  that  the  subject  of 
modesty  has  been  treated  in  any  comprehensive  way  by  psy- 
chologists.    Though  valuable  facts  and  suggestions  bearing  on 
sexual  emotions,  on  disgust,  on  the  origin  of  tattooing,  on  orna- 
ment and  clothing,  have  been  brought  forward  by  physiologists, 
psychologists  and  ethnographists,  few  or  no  attempts  appear  to 
have  been  made  to  reach  the  general  synthetic  statement  of  these 
facts  and  suggestions.2     The  subject  is  indeed  complicated  by 

1 1  may  remark  that  the  present  paper  is  an  abstract  of  a  study  to  be  pub- 
lished in  the  second  volume  of  my  Studies  in  the  Psychology  of  Sex. 

2  It  is  true  that  many  unreliable,  slight  or  fragmentary  attempts  have  been 
made  to  ascertain  the  constitution  or  basis  of  this  emotion.     Herbert  Spencer, 
followed  by  Sergi  and  others,  regarded  modesty  simply  as  the  result  of  clothing. 
This  view  is  overturned  by  the  well  ascertained  fact  that  many  races  which  go 
absolutely  naked  possess  a  highly  developed  sense  of  modesty.     These  writers 
have  not  realized  that  psychological  modesty  is  earlier  in  appearance,  and  more 
fundamental,  than  anatomical  modesty.     A  partial  contribution  to  the  analysis 
of  modesty  has  been  made  by  Professor  James,  who  with  his  usual  insight  and 
lucidity  has  set  forth  certain  of  its  characteristics,  especially  the  element  due  to 
*  the  application  to  ourselves  of  judgments  primarily  passed  upon  our  mates.' 
Westermarck,  again,  followed  by  Grosse,  has  very  ably  and  convincingly  set 
forth  certain  factors  in  the  origin  of  ornament  and  clothing,  a  subject  which 


THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MODESTY.  135 

the  difficulty  of  excluding  closely  allied  emotions, — shame,  shy- 
ness, bashfulness,  timidity,  etc. — all  of  which,  indeed,  however 
defined,  adjoin  and  overlap  modesty.1  It  is  not,  however,  im- 
possible to  isolate  the  main  body  of  the  emotion  of  modesty,  on 
account  of  its  special  connection,  on  the  whole,  with  the  con- 
sciousness of  sex.  I  here  attempt,  however  imperfectly,  to  reach 
my  own  analysis  of  its  constitution  and  development. 

That  modesty  is  based  on  fear,  one  of  the  most  primitive  of 
the  emotions,  seems  to  be  fairly  evident.  It  is,  indeed,  an  ag- 
glomeration of  fears,  especially,  as  I  hope  to  show,  of  two  im- 
portant and  distinct  fears,  one  of  much  earlier  than  human  origin 
and  supplied  solely  by  the  female,  the  other  of  more  distinctly 
human  character  and  of  social  rather  than  sexual  origin. 

A  child  left  to  itself,  though  very  bashful,  is  wholly  devoid 
of  modesty.  Every  one  is  familiar  with  the  shocking  inconve- 
nances  of  children  in  speech  and  act,  with  the  charming  ways  in 
which  they  innocently  disregard  the  conventions  of  modesty 
their  elders  thrust  upon  them,  or,  even  when  anxious  to  carry 
them  out,  wholly  miss  the  point  at  issue. 

Under  civilized  conditions,  moreover,  the  convention  of 
modesty  long  precedes  its  real  development.  It  may  fairly  be 
said  that  this  takes  place  at  the  advent  of  puberty.  We  should 
not,  however,  be  justified  in  asserting  that  on  this  account 
modesty  is  a  purely  sexual  phenomenon.  The  social  impulses 
also  develop  about  this  time,  and  to  that  coincidence  the  corn- 
many  writers  imagine  to  cover  the  whole  field  of  modesty.  More  recently, 
Ribot,  in  his  work  on  the  emotions,  has  vaguely  outlined  most  of  the  factors  of 
modesty,  but  has  not  developed  a  coherent  view  of  their  origins  and  relation- 
ships. 

1  Timidity,  as  understood  by  Dugas  in  his  interesting  essay  on  that  subject, 
is  probably  most  remote.  Dr.  H.  Campbell's  <  Morbid  Shyness  '  (British  Med- 
ical Journal,  26  September,  1896)  is  in  part  identical  with  timidity,  in  part  with 
modesty.  The  matter  is  further  complicated  by  the  fact  that  '  modesty  '  itself 
has  in  English  (like  virtue)  two  distinct  meanings.  In  its  original  form  it  has 
no  special  connection  with  sex  or  with  woman,  but  may  rather  be  considered  as 
a  masculine  virtue.  Cicero  regards  '  modestia '  as  the  equivalent  of  the  Greek 
cutypoavvrj.  This  is  the  '  modesty  '  which  Mary  Wollstonecraft  eulogized  in  the 
last  century,  the  outcome  of  knowledge  and  reflection,  '  soberness  of  mind,' 
1  the  graceful  calm  virtue  of  maturity.'  In  French  it  is  possible  to  avoid  this  con- 
fusion, and  '  modestie  '  is  entirely  distinct  from  '  pudeur.'  It  is  of  course  with 
*  pudeur'  that  I  am  here  concerned. 


136  HA  VELOCK  ELLIS. 

pound  nature  of  the  emotion  of  modesty  may  well  be  largely 
due. 

The  sexual  factor  is,  however,  the  simplest  and  most  prim- 
itive element  of  modesty,  and  may,  therefore,  be  mentioned  first. 

This  fundamental  animal  factor  of  modesty,1  rooted  in  the 
natural  facts  of  the  sexual  life  of  the  higher  mammals,  and 
especially  man,  obviously  will  not  explain  the  whole  phenomena 
of  modesty ;  it  fails  to  account  for  ornaments  and  garments,  and 
it  scarcely  appears  to  present  an  adequate  basis  for  modesty  in 
the  male.  For  this  we  must,  in  large  part  at  least,  turn  to  the 
other  great  primary  element  of  modesty,  the  social  factor. 

We  cannot  doubt  that  one  of  the  most  primitive  and  universal 
of  the  social  characteristics  of  man  is  an  aptitude  for  disgust, 
founded  as  it  is  on  a  yet  more  primitive  and  animal  aptitude  for 
disgust  which  has  little  or  no  social  significance.  In  nearly  all 
races,  even  the  most  savage,  we  seem  to  find  distinct  traces  of 
this  aptitude  for  disgust  in  the  presence  of  certain  actions  of 
others,  an  emotion  naturally  reflected  in  the  individual's  own 
actions,  and  hence  a  guide  to  conduct.  Notwithstanding  our 
gastric  community  of  disgust  with  lower  animals,  it  is  only  in 
man  that  this  disgust  seems  to  become  highly  developed,  to 
possess  a  distinctly  social  character,  and  to  serve  as  a  guide  to 
social  conduct.  The  objects  of  disgust  vary  infinitely  accord- 
ing to  the  circumstances  and  habits  of  particular  races,  but  the 
reaction  of  disgust  is  fundamental  throughout. 

The  best  study  of  the  phenomena  of  disgust  known  to  me  is 
without  doubt  Professor  Richet's.2  Richet  concludes  that  it  is 
the  dangerous  and  the  useless  which  evoke  disgust.  Certain 
excretions  and  secretions,  being  either  useless  or,  in  accordance 
with  wide-spread  primitive  ideas,  highly  dangerous,  the  sacro- 
pubic  region  became  a  concentrated  focus  of  disgust.  It  is  for 
this  reason,  no  doubt,  that  savage  men  exhibit  modesty,  not  only 
towards  women,  but  towards  their  own  sex,  and  that  so  many  of 

1  For  the  detailed  treatment  of  which  the  forthcoming  work  may  be  con- 
sulted. 

2  C.  Richet,   '  Les   causes  du  de'gout,'  Uhomme  et  V intelligence,  1884.     This 
eminent  physiologist's  elaborate  study  of  disgust  was  not  written  as  a  contribu- 
tion to  the  psychology  of  modesty,  but  it  forms  an  admirable  introduction  to  the 
investigation  of  the  social  factor  of  modesty. 


THE  E  VOL  UTION  OF  MODES  TY.  137 

the  lowest  savages  take  precautions  to  obtain  seclusion  for  the 
fulfilment  of  natural  functions.  The  statement  now  so  often 
made  that  the  primary  object  of  clothing  is  to  accentuate  rather 
than  to  conceal  has  in  it — as  I  shall  point  out  later — a  large  ele- 
ment of  truth,  but  it  is  by  no  means  a  complete  account  of  the 
matter.  It  seems  very  difficult  not  to  admit  that  there  is  a 
genuine  impulse  to  concealment  among  the  most  primitive  peo- 
ples, and  the  invincible  repugnance  often  felt  by  savages  to  re- 
move the  girdle  or  apron  is  scarcely  accounted  for  by  the  theory 
that  it  is  a  sexual  lure. 

In  this  connection  it  seems  to  me  instructive  to  consider  a 
special  form  of  modesty  very  strongly  marked  among  savages 
in  some  parts  of  the  world.  I  refer  to  the  feeling  of  immodesty 
in  eating.  When  this  feeling  exists,  modesty  is  offended  when 
one  eats  in  public ;  the  modest  man  retires  to  eat.  Indecency, 
said  Cook,  was  utterly  unknown  among  the  Tahitians  ;  but  they 
would  not  eat  together ;  even  brothers  and  sisters  had  their 
separate  baskets  of  provisions,  and  generally  sat  some  yards 
apart,  with  their  backs  to  each  other,  when  they  ate.1  Karl  von 
den  Steinen  remarks,  in  his  interesting  book  on  Brazil,  that, 
though  the  Bakairi  of  Central  Brazil  have  no  feeling  of  shame 
about  nakedness,  they  are  ashamed  to  eat  in  public  :  they  retired 
to  eat,  and  hung  their  heads  in  shamefaced  confusion  when  they 
saw  him  innocently  eat  in  public.  Hrolf  Vaughan  Stevens 
found  that,  when  he  gave  an  Orang  Laut  (Malay)  woman  any- 
thing to  eat,  she  not  only  would  not  eat  if  her  husband  were 
present,  but  if  any  man  were  present  she  would  go  aside  before 
eating  or  giving  her  children  to  eat.2 

It  is  quite  easy  to  understand  how  this  arises.  Whenever 
there  is  any  pressure  on  the  means  of  subsistence,  as  among 

1  Crawley  (Jour.  Anthropological  Inst.,  May,  1895)  gives  numerous  similar 
instances,  even  in  Europe,  with,  however,  special  reference  to  sexual  taboo.     I 
may  remark  that  English  people  of  lower  classes,  especially  women,  are  often 
modest  about  eating  in  the  presence  of  people  of  higher  class.     This  feeling  is 
no  doubt  due  in  part  to  the  consciousness  of  defective  etiquette,  but  that  very 
consciousness  is  a  development  of  the  fear  of  causing  disgust  which  is  a  compo- 
nent of  modesty. 

2  Stevens,  4  Mittheilungen  aus  dem  Frauenleben  der  Orang  Belendas,"   Zt. 
fur  Ethnologie,  1896,  Heft  IV.,  p.  167. 


138  HA  VEL  O  CK  ELLIS. 

savages  at  some  time  or  another  there  nearly  always  is,  it  must 
necessarily  arouse  a  profound  emotion  of  anger  and  disgust  to 
see  another  person  putting  into  his  stomach  what  one  might  as 
well  have  put  into  one's  own.  The  special  secrecy  sometimes 
observed  by  women  is  probably  due  to  the  fact  that  women 
would  be  more  sensitive  to  the  emotion  of  disgust  that  the  act 
of  eating  arouses  in  onlookers.  As  social  feeling  develops  a 
man  desires  not  only  to  eat  in  safety,  but  also  to  avoid  being  an 
object  of  disgust,  and  to  spare  his  friends  all  unpleasant  emo- 
tions. Hence  it  becomes  a  requirement  of  ordinary  decency  to 
eat  in  private.  A  man  who  eats  in  public  becomes — like  the 
man  who  in  our  cities  exposes  his  person  in  public — the  object 
of  disgust  and  contempt. 

Long  ago,  when  a  hospital  student  on  midwifery  duty  in 
London  slums,  I  had  occasion  to  observe  that  among  the  wo- 
men of  the  poor,  and  more  especially  in  those  who  had  lost  the 
first  bloom  of  youth,  modesty  consisted  chiefly  in  the  fear  of 
being  disgusting.  There  was  almost  a  pathetic  anxiety,  in  the 
face  of  pain  and  discomfort,  not  to  be  disgusting  in  the  doctor's 
eyes.  This  anxiety  expressed  itself  in  the  ordinary  symptoms  of 
modesty.  But  as  soon  as  the  woman  realized  that  I  found 
nothing  disgusting  in  whatever  was  proper  and  necessary  to  be 
done  under  the  circumstances,  it  almost  invariably  happened  that 
every  sign  of  modesty  at  once  disappeared.  In  the  special  and 
elementary  conditions  of  parturition,  modesty  is  reduced  to  this 
one  fear  of  causing  disgust,  so  that  when  that  is  negatived,  the 
emotion  is  non-existent  and  the  subject  becomes,  without  an 
effort,  as  direct  and  natural  as  a  little  child.  A  fellow-student  on 
similar  duty,  who  also  discovered  for  himself  the  same  character 
of  modesty,  remarked  on  it  to  me  with  some  sadness  ;  it  seemed 
to  him  derogatory  to  womanhood  that  what  he  had  been  accus- 
tomed to  consider  its  supreme  grace  should  be  so  superficial  that 
he  could  at  will  set  limits  to  it.  I  thought  then,  as  I  think  still, 
that  that  was  rather  a  perversion  of  the  matter,  and  that  nothing 
becomes  degrading  because  we  happen  to  have  learnt  something 
about  its  operations.  But  I  am  more  convinced  than  ever  that 
the  fear  of  causing  disgust — a  fear  quite  distinct  from  that  of 
losing  sexual  lure  or  breaking  a  rule  of  social  etiquette — plays 


THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MODESTY.  139 

a  very  large  part  in  the  modesty  of  the  more  modest  sex  and  in 
modesty  generally.  Whatever  magnifies  self-confidence  and 
lulls  the  fear  of  evoking  disgust — whether  it  is  the  presence  of 
a  beloved  person  in  whose  good  opinion  complete  confidence  is 
felt,  or  whether  it  is  merely  the  grosser  narcotizing  influence  of 
a  slight  degree  of  intoxication — always  automatically  lulls  the 
emotion  of  modesty.  Together  with  the  sexual  factor,  the  social 
fear  of  evoking  disgust  seems  to  me  the  most  fundamental  ele- 
ment in  modesty. 

It  is  on  this  animal  basis  that  the  human  and  social  fear  of 
arousing  disgust  has  developed.  Among  civilized  people,  it 
may  be  added,  the  fear  of  arousing  disgust  is  the  ultimate  and 
most  fundamental  element  of  modesty. 

Another  factor  of  modesty,  which  reaches  a  high  develop- 
ment even  in  savagery,  and  among  more  or  less  naked  races, 
is  the  idea  of  ceremonial  uncleanness.  It  may  be  to  some  ex- 
tent rooted  in  the  elements  already  referred  to,  and  it  leads  us 
into  a  much  wider  field  than  that  of  modesty,  so  that  it  is  only 
necessary  to  mention  it  here.  Ritual  tends  to  crystallize  around 
any  act  of  life  on  which  men  expend  deliberate  attention,  and 
the  duties  of  modesty  among  savages  are  a  sufficiently  serious 
part  of  life  to  constitute  a  nucleus  for  ritual.  No  doubt  offences 
against  ritual  may  be  regarded  as  more  serious  than  offences 
against  modesty,  but  they  are  so  obviously  allied  in  early  cul- 
ture that  the  one  reinforces  the  other,  and  they  cannot  be  easily 
disentangled.  All  savage  and  barbarous  people  who  have  at- 
tained any  high  degree  of  ceremonialism  have  included  cer- 
tain animal  functions  more  or  less  stringently  within  the  bonds 
of  that  ceremonialism.  It  is  only  necessary  to  refer  to  the 
Jewish  ritual  books  of  the  Old  Testament,  to  Hesiod,  or  to  the 
customs  prevalent  among  Mohammedan  peoples. 

So  far  it  has  only  been  necessary  to  refer  incidentally  to  the 
connection  of  modesty  with  clothing.  I  have  sought  to  em- 
phasize the  unquestionable  but  often  forgotten  fact  that  modesty 
is  in  its  origin  independent  of  clothing,  that  physiological  modesty 
takes  precedence  of  anatomical  modesty,  and  that  the  primary 
factors  of  modesty  were  developed  long  before  the  discovery  of 
either  ornament  or  garments.  The  rise  of  clothing  probably 


1 40  HA  VttL  O  CK  ELLIS. 

had  its  first  psychic  basis  on  an  emotion  of  modesty  already 
compositely  formed  of  the  elements  we  have  traced.  Both  the 
main  elementary  factors,  it  must  be  noted,  must  naturally  tend 
to  develop  and  unite  in  a  more  complex,  though,  it  may  well 
be,  much  less  intense  emotion.  A  very  notable  advance,  I  may 
remark,  is  made  when  the  primary  attitude  of  defence  against 
the  action  of  the  male  becomes  merely  a  defence  against  his 
eyes.  We  may  thus  explain  the  spread  of  modesty  to  various 
parts  of  the  body.  We  see  the  influence  of  this  defence  against 
strange  eyes  in  the  special  precautions  in  gesture  or  clothing 
taken  by  the  women  in  various  parts  of  the  world  against  the 
more  offensive  eyes  of  civilized  Europeans. 

But  in  thus  becoming  directed  merely  against  sight  and  not 
against  action,  the  gestures  of  modesty  are  at  once  free  to  be- 
come merely  those  of  coquetterie.  When  there  is  no  real  dan- 
ger of  offensive  action,  there  is  no  need  for  more  than  playful 
defence,  and  no  serious  anxiety  should  that  defence  be  taken 
as  a  further  invitation.  Thus  the  road  is  at  once  fully  open  to- 
wards the  most  civilized  manifestation  of  the  comedy  of  court- 
ship. 

In  the  same  way  the  social  fear  of  arousing  disgust  combines 
easily  and  perfectly  with  any  new  development  in  the  invention 
of  ornament  or  clothing  as  sexual  lures.  Even  among  the  most 
civilized  races  it  has  often  been  noted  that  the  fashion  of  feminine 
garments  (as  also  sometimes  the  use  of  scents)  has  the  double 
object  of  concealing  and  attracting.  The  heightening  of  attrac- 
tion is  indeed  a  logical  outcome  of  the  fear  of  evoking  disgust. 

The  contention  of  Westermarck,  that  ornament  and  clothing 
are  in  large  part  due  to  the  desire  to  give  not  concealment 
but  greater  prominence,  may  certainly  be  accepted,  so  long  as 
we  realize  that  it  is  not  the  whole  of  the  truth,  and  that  it  is 
far  from  offering  a  complete  explanation  of  the  phenomena 
of  modesty.  The  great  artistic  elaboration  often  displayed  by 
such  articles  of  ornament  and  clothing,  even  when  very  small, 
and  the  fact — as  shown  by  Karl  van  den  Steinen  regarding  the 
Brazilian  uluri — that  they  may  serve  as  common  elements  in 
general  decoration,  sufficiently  prove  that  such  objects  attract 
rather  than  escape  attention.  And  while  there  is  an  invincible 


THE  E  VOL  UTION  OF  MODE  STY.  141 

repugnance  among  some  peoples  to  remove  these  articles,  such 
repugnance  being  often  strongest  when  the  adornment  is  most 
minute,  others  have  no  such  repugnance,  or  are  quite  indifferent 
whether  or  not  their  aprons  are  accurately  adjusted.  The  mere 
presence  or  possession  of  the  articles  gives  the  required  sense  of 
self-respect,  of  human  dignity,  of  sexual  desirability.  But,  on 
the  whole,  all  the  motives  already  noted  combine  to  concentrate 
modesty  on  the  garment. 

When  clothing  is  once  established,  another  element,  this 
time  a  social-economic  element,  often  comes  in  to  emphasize  its 
importance  and  increase  the  anatomical  modesty  of  women.  I 
mean  the  growth  of  the  conception  of  women  as  property. 
Waitz,  followed  by  Schurtz  and  Letourneau,  has  insisted  that 
the  jealousy  of  husbands  is  the  primary  origin  of  clothing  and, 
indirectly,  of  modesty.  It  is  undoubtedly  true  that  married 
women  are  often  only  or  chiefly  clothed,  while  the  unmar- 
ried women,  though  full-grown,  are  not.  In  many  parts  of 
the  world,  also,  Mantegazza  and  others  have  shown,  where  the 
women  are  covered  and  the  men  are  not,  clothing  is  regarded 
as  a  sort  of  disgrace,  and  men  can  only  with  difficulty  be  per- 
suaded to  adopt  it.  Before  marriage  a  woman  was  often  free 
and  not  bound  to  chastity,  and  at  the  same  time  was  often  un- 
clothed ;  after  marriage  she  was  clothed  and  no  longer  free.  To 
the  husband's  mind,  the  garment  appears — illogically  though 
naturally — a  moral  and  physical  protection  against  any  attack 
on  his  property.  Thus  a  new  motive  was  furnished,  this  time 
somewhat  artificially,  for  making  nakedness,  in  women  at  all 
events,  disgraceful.  As  the  conception  of  property  also  extended 
to  the  father's  right  over  his  daughters,  and  the  appreciation  of 
female  chastity  developed,  this  motive  spread  to  unmarried  and 
married  women  alike.  It  probably  constitutes  the  chief  element 
furnished  to  the  complex  emotion  of  modesty  by  the  barbar- 
ous stages  of  human  civilization. 

The  chief  new  feature — it  is  scarcely  an  original  element — 
added  to  modesty  when  an  advanced  civilization  slowly  emerges 
from  barbarism  is  the  elaboration  of  its  social  ritual.  Civiliza- 
tion expands  the  range  of  modesty  and  renders  it  more  capri- 
cious and  changeable.  The  French  seventeenth  century  and 


142  HA  VELOCK  ELLIS, 

the  English  eighteenth  represent  early  stages  of  modern  Euro- 
pean civilization,  and  they  both  devoted  special  attention  to  the 
elaboration  of  the  minute  details  of  modesty.  The  frequenters 
of  the  Hotel  Rambouillet,  the  precteuses  satirized  by  Moliere, 
were  primarily  engaged  in  refining  the  language,  but  indirectly 
also  in  refining  feelings  and  ideas  and  in  enlarging  the  bound- 
aries of  modesty.  In  England  such  famous  and  popular  authors 
as  Swift  and  Sterne  bear  witness  to  a  new  ardor  of  modesty  in 
the  sudden  reticences,  the  dashes  and  the  asterisks,  which  we 
find  throughout  their  works.  The  altogether  new  quality  of  liter- 
ary prurience  of  which  Sterne  is  still  the  classic  example  could 
only  have  arisen  on  the  basis  of  the  new  modesty  which  was 
then  overspreading  society  and  literature.  Idle  people,  mostly 
the  women  in  salons  and  drawing-rooms,  people  more  familiar 
with  books  than  with  the  realities  of  life,  now  laid  down  the 
rules  of  modesty,  and  were  ever  enlarging  it,  ever  inventing 
new  subtleties  of  gesture  and  speech,  which  it  would  be  im- 
modest to  neglect,  and  which  were  ever  being  rendered  vulgar 
by  use  and  ever  changing. 

It  would,  however,  be  a  mistake  to  suppose  that  this  process 
is  an  intensification  of  modesty.  It  is,  on  the  contrary,  an  at- 
tenuation of  it.  The  observances  of  modesty  become  merely  a 
part  of  a  vast  body  of  rules  of  social  etiquette,  though  a  some- 
what stringent  department  of  these  rules  on  account  of  the 
vague  sense  still  persisting  of  a  deep-lying  natural  basis.  The 
whole  emotion  has  been,  in  a  certain  sense,  undermined,  and 
yields  more  readily  than  in  its  primitive  state  to  any  invasion 
supported  by  a  sufficiently  strong  motive.  The  savage  Indian 
woman  of  America,  the  barbarous  woman  of  some  Mohamme- 
dan countries,  can  scarcely  sacrifice  their  modesty  even  in  the 
pangs  of  childbirth.  Fashion,  again,  in  the  more  civilized 
countries  can  easily  inhibit  anatomical  modesty,  and  rapidly 
exhibit  in  turn  almost  any  portion  of  the  body.  In  savage  and 
barbarous  countries  modesty  often  possesses  the  strength  of  a 
genuine  and  irresistible  instinct.  In  civilized  countries  any  one 
who  places  considerations  of  modesty  before  the  claims  of  some 
real  human  need  excites  ridicule  and  contempt. 

It  is,  however,  impossible  to  contemplate  this  series  of  phe- 


THE  EVOLUTION  OF  MODESTY.  143 

nomena,  so  radically  persistent,  whatever  its  changes  of  form, 
and  so  constant  throughout  every  stage  of  civilization,  without 
feeling  that,  although  modesty  cannot  properly  be  called  an  in- 
stinct, there  must  be  some  physiological  basis  to  support  it. 
Undoubtedly  such  a  basis  is  formed  by  that  vasomotor  mechan- 
ism of  which  the  most  obvious  outward  sign  is  in  human  beings 
the  blush.1  All  the  allied  emotional  forms  of  fear — shame, 
bashfulness,  timidity — are  to  some  extent  upheld  by  this  mechan- 
ism, but  this  is  especially  the  case  with  the  emotion  we  are  now 
concerned  with.  The  blush  is  the  sanction  of  modesty. 

When  the  Brazilian  offered  Karl  van  den  Steinen  some  food 
which  he  ate  immediately  in  public,  the  Brazilian  hung  his 
head.  Whether  or  not  he  blushed,  he  was  certainly  conscious 
of  that  capillary  turmoil  of  the  face,  of  which  the  shock  of 
offended  modesty  is  the  cause  and  blushing  the  most  visible 
sign.  It  is  scarcely  an  accident  that,  as  has  been  often  observed, 
criminals  or  the  anti-social  element  of  the  community — whether 
by  the  habits  of  their  lives  or  by  congenital  abnormality — blush 
less  easily  than  normal  persons.2  The  importance  of  the  blush 
and  the  emotional  confusion  behind  it  as  the  sources  of  modesty 
is  shown  by  the  significant  fact  that  by  skillfully  lulling  emotional 
confusion  it  is  possible  to  inhibit  the  sense  of  modesty  itself.  In 
other  words,  it  may  be  said  that  we  are  here  in  the  presence  of 
a  fear — to  a  large  extent  a  sex-fear — impelling  to  concealment, 
and  the  emotion  naturally  disappears,  even  though  its  ostensible 

*The  blush  is  indeed  only  a  part,  almost  perhaps  an  accidental  part,  of  an 
organic  turmoil  with  which  it  is  associated.  Partridge,  who  has  studied  the 
phenomena  of  blushing  in  120  cases  {Pedagogical  Seminary,  April,  1897),  finds 
that  the  following  are  the  chief  symptoms  :  tremors  near  the  waist  or  passing 
from  the  feet  to  the  head,  weakness  in  the  limbs,  pressure,  trembling,  warmth, 
weight,  a  beating  in  chest,  warm  wave  from  feet  upwards,  quivering  of  heart, 
stoppage  and  rapid  beating  of  heart,  coldness  all  over  followed  by  heat,  dizziness, 
tingling  of  toes  and  fingers,  numbness,  something  rising  in  throat,  smarting  of 
eyes,  ringing  of  ears,  prickling  sensation  of  face,  pressure  inside  head. 

2 Kroner  (Das  korperliche  Gefuhl,  1887,  p.  130)  remarks:  "The  origin  of 
a  specific  connection  between  shame  and  blushing  is  the  work  of  a  social  selection. 
It  is  certainly  an  immediate  advantage  for  a  man  not  to  blush ;  indirectly,  how- 
ever, it  is  a  disadvantage,  because  in  other  ways  he  will  be  known  as  shameless, 
and  on  that  account,  as  a  rule,  he  will  be  discriminated  against  in  marriage.  This 
social  selection  will  be  especially  exercised  on  the  female  sex,  and  on  this  account 
women  blush  to  a  greater  extent  and  more  readily  than  men.'* 


144  HAVELOCK  ELLIS. 

cause  remains,  when  it  is  apparent  that  there  is  no  cause  for 
fear.  Thus  it  is,  to  some  extent  at  least,  true  that  people  are 
modest  because  they  blush,  or  because  they  feel  the  possibility 
of  blushing,  rather  than  that  they  blush  because  they  are  modest. 
In  the  same  way  we  may  explain  the  curious  influence  of  dark- 
ness in  restraining  the  manifestations  of  modesty.1  This 
mechanism  of  blushing  thus  runs  parallel,  on  the  physiological 
side,  with  that  fear  of  evoking  disgust  to  which  I  have  already 
referred.  It  is  to  the  blush  also  that  we  must  attribute  a  curious 
complementary  relationship  between  the  face  and  the  sacro-pubic 
region  as  centers  of  anatomical  modesty.  The  women  of  some 
African  tribes  who  go  naked,  Ploss  remarks,  cover  the  face 
with  the  hand  under  the  influence  of  modesty.  When,  as  among 
many  Mohammedan  peoples,  the  face  is  the  chief  focus  of 
modesty,  the  exposure  of  the  rest  of  the  body,  including  even 
the  sacro-pubic  region,  becomes  a  matter  of  comparative  indif- 
ference. All  such  facts  serve  to  show  that,  though  the  forms  of 
modesty  may  change,  it  is  yet  a  very  radical  constituent  of 
human  nature  in  all  stages  of  civilization,  and  that  it  is  to  a  large 
extent  maintained  by  the  mechanism  of  blushing. 

It  may  still  be  asked,  finally,  whether  on  the  whole  modesty 
really  becomes  a  more  predominant  emotion  as  civilization  ad- 
vances. I  do  not  think  this  position  can  be  maintained.  It  is 
a  great  mistake,  as  we  have  seen,  to  suppose  that  in  becoming 
extended  modesty  also  becomes  intensified.  On  the  contrary, 
this  very  extension  is  a  sign  of  weakness.  Among  savages 
modesty  is  far  more  radical  and  invincible  than  among  the  civ- 
ilized. Of  the  Araucanian  women  of  Chili  Treutler  has  re- 
marked that  they  are  distinctly  more  modest  than  the  Christian 
white  population,  and  such  observations  might  be  indefinitely 
extended.  It  is,  as  we  have  already  noted,  in  a  new  and  crude 
civilization,  anxious  to  mark  its  separation  from  a  barbarism  it 
has  yet  scarcely  escaped,  that  we  find  an  extravagant  and  fan- 
tastic anxiety  to  extend  the  limits  of  modesty  in  life  and  art  and 
literature.  In  older  and  more  mature  civilizations — in  classic 

1The  influence  of  darkness  in  inhibiting  modesty  is  a  very  ancient  observa- 
tion. Burton  in  the  Anatomy  of  Melancholy  quotes  Dandinus  :  'Nox  facit  im- 
pudentes,'  rightly  connecting  the  influence  with  blushing. 


THE  E  VOL  UTION  OF  MODES  TV.  1 45 

antiquity,  in  old  Japan,  in  France — modesty,  while  still  a  very 
real  influence,  becomes  a  much  less  predominant  and  all-per- 
vading influence.  In  life  it  becomes  subservient  to  human 
use,  in  art  to  beauty,  in  literature  to  expression.  Among  our- 
selves we  may  note  that  modesty  is  a  much  more  invincible  motive 
among  the  lower  social  classes  than  among  the  more  cultivated 
classes.  Modesty  is  a  part  of  self-respect,  but  in  the  fully  de- 
veloped human  being  self-respect  itself  holds  in  check  any  ex- 
cessive modesty.  We  must  remember,  moreover,  that  there  are 
more  definite  grounds  for  the  subordination  of  modesty  with  the 
development  of  civilization.  We  have  seen  that  the  factors  of 
modesty  are  many,  and  that  most  of  them  are  based  on  emotions 
which  make  little  urgent  appeal  save  to  races  in  a  savage  or  bar- 
barous condition.  Thus  disgust,  as  Richet  has  truly  pointed 
out,  necessarily  decreases  as  knowledge  increases.1  As  we  an- 
alyze and  understand  our  experiences  better,  so  they  cause  us  less 
disgust.  As  disgust  becomes  analyzed,  and  as  self-respect  tends 
to  increased  physical  purity,  so  the  factor  of  disgust  in  modesty  is 
minimized.  The  factor  of  ceremonial  uncleanness,  again,  which 
plays  so  urgent  a  part  in  modesty  at  certain  stages  of  culture, 
is  to-day  without  influence,  except  in  so  far  as  it  survives  in 
etiquette.  In  the  same  way  the  social-economic  factor  of  mod- 
esty belongs  to  a  stage  of  human  development  which  is  wholly 
alien  to  an  advanced  civilization.  Even  the  most  fundamental 
impulse  of  all,  the  gesture  of  sexual  refusal,  is  normally  only 
imperative  among  animals  and  savages.  Thus  civilization  tends 
to  subordinate  if  not  to  minimize  modesty,  to  render  it  a  grace 
of  life  rather  than  a  fundamental  social  law  of  life.  But  an 
essential  grace  of  life  it  still  remains,  and  whatever  delicate  va- 
riations it  may  assume  we  can  scarcely  conceive  of  its  disappear- 
ance. 

1  Disgust  is  a  sort  of  synthesis  which  attaches  to  the  total  form  of  objects,  and 
which  must  diminish  and  disappear  as  scientific  analysis  separates  into  parts 
what  as  a  whole  is  so  repugnant. 


PROCEEDINGS  OF  THE  SEVENTH  ANNUAL  MEET- 
ING   OF    THE    AMERICAN   PSYCHOLOGICAL 
ASSOCIATION,  COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY, 
NEW  YORK,  DECEMBER,  1898. 

REPORT   OF  THE  SECRETARY  FOR  1898. 

The  seventh  annual  meeting  of  the  American  Psychological 
Association  was  held  at  Columbia  University,  New  York,  De- 
cember 28,  29  and  30,  1898,  the  same  time  and  place  having 
been  chosen  by  the  American  Society  of  Naturalists  and  the 
Affiliated  Societies. 

In  point  of  numbers  the  meeting  was  the  most  successful  in 
the  history  of  the  Association,  there  being  fifty-one  members  in 
attendance  at  the  various  sessions.  On  the  morning  of  Thurs- 
day, a  joint  meeting  with  the  American  Physiological  Society 
was  held,  members  of  both  societies  contributing  papers,  and, 
by  invitation,  Professor  Ogden  N.  Rood,  of  the  Department  of 
Physics  of  Columbia  University,  read  a  paper  on,  and  exhibited 
his  Flicker  Photometer.  On  Thursday  afternoon  the  Associa- 
tion adjourned  for  the  discussion  before  the  Naturalists  on  <  Ad- 
vances in  Methods  of  Teaching,'  Professor  Miinsterberg  repre- 
senting the  Psychologists. 

The  members  of  the  Association,  for  the  most  part,  attended  the 
addresses  by  Mr.  Morris  K.  Jesup  and  Professor  Henry  F.  Osborn, 
at  the  American  Museum  of  Natural  History,  on  Wednesday 
evening,  and  later  the  reception  to  the  visiting  societies,  given  by 
Professor  and  Mrs.  Osborn,  at  their  residence.  About  thirty 
members  were  present  at  the  annual  dinner  of  the  Affiliated  So- 
cieties, held  at  the  Hotel  Savoy,  on  Thursday  evening.  Presi- 
dent Hugo  Miinsterberg  presided  at  the  meetings  of  the  Asso- 
ciation. 

At  the  business  meeting  of  the  Association  on  Friday  morn- 
ing, the  following  was  transacted  :  Election  of  officers  for  1899  : 

146 


AMERICAN  PS  YCHOL  O  GICAL  AS  SO  CIA  TION.  1 47 

President,  Professor  John  Dewey,  University  of  Chicago  ;  Sec- 
retary and  Treasurer,  Dr.  "Livingston  Farrand,  Columbia 
University;  Members  of  the  Council,  Professor  J.  McKeen 
Cattell,  Columbia  University,  and  Professor  H.  N.  Gardiner, 
Smith  College. 

The  following  new  members  were  elected :  Dr.  Raymond 
Dodge,  Wesleyan  University;  Dr.  Eleanor  A.  McC.  Gamble, 
Wellesley  College ;  Dr.  Gervase  Green,  Yale  University ;  Dr. 
A.  L.  Jones,  Columbia  University  ;  Mr.  James  H.  Leuba,  Bryn 
Mawr  College ;  Professor  Ernest  H.  Lindley,  University  of 
Indiana ;  Dr.  Walter  T.  Marvin,  Columbia  University ;  Mr. 
Will  S.  Monroe,  State  Normal  School,  Westfield,  Mass. ;  Miss 
Ethel  D.  Puffer,  Radcliffe  College;  Professor  George  Santa- 
yana,  Harvard  University ;  Professor  Langdon  C.  Stewardson, 
Lehigh  University ;  Dr.  Edward  L.  Thorndike,  Western  Re- 
serve University ;  Dr.  Gustavo  Tosti,  New  York  City. 

The  following  amendment  to  the  constitution  proposed  at  the 
meeting  in  Ithaca,  in  1897,  was  taken  up  and  passed,  viz.  :  That 
the  Secretary  be  elected  for  a  term  of  three  years  and  be  ex- 
ojficio  a  member  of  the  Council. 

On  motion  of  Professor  Baldwin,  a  Standing  Committee  on 
Psychological  and  Philosophical  Terminology  was  appointed, 
consisting  of  the  following  members  :  Professors  Miinsterberg, 
Cattell,  Sanford,  Creighton,  Royce,  Minot  and  Baldwin.  The 
duties  of  this  Committee  shall  be  :  (i)  To  recommend,  from  time 
to  time,  new  terms  in  Psychology  and  Philosophy.  (2)  To 
recommend  choice  of  alternative  terms  in  those  fields.  (3)  To 
recommend  foreign  equivalents  for  translating  work  both  into 
English  and  into  foreign  languages.  (4)  To  keep  the  Associa- 
tion informed  as  to  the  growth  of  terminology  in  other  depart- 
ments, especially  in  Neurology.  The  Committee  shall  have 
power  to  get  help  from  foreigners  who  are  not  members  of  the 
Association,  such  individuals  to  be  known  as  'Associates'  of  the 
Committee. 

On  motion  of  Professor  Sanford,  it  was 

Resolved:  First,  that  the  matter  of  the  organization  of  the 
Association  with  reference  to  a  possible  philosophical  section  be 
referred  to  the  Council,  to  be  reported  upon  at  the  next  meeting  ; 


1 48  S£  VENTH  A NNUAL  MEE  TING. 

Second,  that  the  Secretary  be  instructed  in  arranging  the  pro- 
gramme for  the  next  meeting  to  gather  philosophical  papers  as 
far  as  practicable  into  the  programme  of  one  session ;  Third, 
that  the  Secretary  be  instructed  to  send  out  during  the  course  of 
the  year  a  circular  letter  requesting,  for  the  information  of  the 
Council,  the  opinion  of  the  individual  members  of  the  Associa- 
tion on  the  above  mentioned  question  of  the  organization  of  the 
Association. 

Professor  Cattell,  Chairman  of  the  Committee  on  Physical 
and  Mental  Tests,  presented  the  report  of  that  Committee  upon 
its  work  during  the  past  year. 

REPORT    OF   THE    TREASURER   FOR    1898. 

Livingston  Farrand  in  account  with  The  American  Psychological 
Association. 

DR. 

To  balance  at  last  meeting $669  10 

Dues  of  members 249  oo 

Sale  of  Proceedings 25 

$918  35 
CR. 
By  expenditures  for 

Postage,  telegrams,  etc $n   20 

Stationery 5   70 

Printing,  clerical  work,  etc 22  57 

Expenses  of  meeting  of  Affiliated  Societies 3  oo 

Committee  on  Physical  and  Mental  Tests 75  oo 

117  47 

Balance  on  hand $800  88 

Audited  by  the  Council  and  found  correct. 

LIVINGSTON  FARRAND, 
Secretary  and  Treasurer. 

ABSTRACTS  OF  PAPERS. 
Address  of  the  President :  Psychology  and  History.    By  HUGO 

MUNSTERBERG. 

The  psychological  view  of  human  life  and  the  really  historical 
view  are  necessarily  in  conflict ;  for  the  one  the  personality  is  a 
complex  of  elements  and  causally  determined,  for  the  other  it  is 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  149 

a  unity  and  free.  The  naturalistic  tendencies  of  the  last  half  cen- 
tury have  favored  the  analytic  and  explanatory  treatment,  but 
our  time  shows  a  new  revival  of  historical  thinking.  In  this 
conflict  the  belief  in  the  rights  and  duties  of  the  personality  must 
destroy  psychology  if  it  cannot  be  shown  that  both  are  partial 
truths,  and  thus  no  conflict  between  them  necessary,  since  the  one 
does  not  exclude  the  other.  Recent  writers  have  claimed,  in- 
deed, that  psychology  and  history  are  two  coordinated  ways  of 
dealing  with  the  reality  of  life  in  so  far  as  psychology  seeks 
laws  and  tries  thus  to  explain,  while  history  deals  merely  with 
the  single  facts  as  such.  These  arguments  are  untenable  :  first, 
because  every  law  implies  also  existential  propositions  and  offers 
thus  descriptions  together  with  the  explanations ;  secondly,  be- 
cause every  description  of  single  facts  includes  the  laws,  since 
the  conceptions  by  which  we  describe  are  the  condensed  results 
of  explanations  ;  thirdly,  because  the  single  object  as  such,  really 
isolated,  is  not  object  of  any  science  but  always  object  of  art. 
Every  science  connects  the  facts,  and,  therefore,  the  historical 
sciences  too  must  deal  with  general  facts.  There  is  thus  no 
methodological  difference  between  history  and  psychology. 
And  yet  a  most  important  difference  between  the  two  does  ex- 
ist :  it  is  an  ontological  difference.  Both  connect  their  material 
by  general  facts,  but  the  material  of  psychology  consists  of  ob- 
jects which  as  such  can  be  described  and  explained,  while  the 
material  of  history  consists  of  subjective  will  acts  which  as  such 
can  merely  be  interpreted  and  appreciated.  Our  interest  in  ob- 
jects means  merely  our  expectation  as  to  what  we  have  to  await 
from  them ;  if  we  consider  mental  life  as  object,  we  transform 
it  in  the  interest  of  causal  connection  and  seek  causal  laws.  The 
subjective  will  acts  on  the  other  hand  interest  us  in  the  first  in- 
stance with  regard  to  their  meaning ;  we  want  to  understand 
with  what  other  subjective  acts  they  agree  and  disagree,  and  we 
come  thus  to  a  teleological  system  in  which  every  will  act  is 
linked  with  every  other  will  act  as  every  molecule  in  the  causal 
world  is  dependent  upon  the  whole  universe.  In  such  a  teleo- 
logical system  the  general  fact  is  then  not  a  causal  law  but  a 
will  relation  of  inclusive  character.  As  every  willing  person- 
ality can  be  thought  of  as  replaced  by  the  psychophysical  organ- 


1 50  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE  TING. 

ism,  that  is  by  an  object,  therefore  every  human  experience  can 
be  brought  into  the  causal  and  into  the  teleological  system.  As 
long  as  they  are  not  mixed  each  is  true,  but  each  is  a  transforma- 
tion of  reality  and  not  reality  itself. 

Discussion  on  the  Relations  of  Will  to  Belief.  PROFESSOR 
JAMES  and  DR.  MILLER,  who  were  to  have  taken  part  in  the 
debate,  being  prevented  from  attending,  the  discussion  was 
carried  on  by  PROFESSORS  LADD,  HIBBEN,  CALDWELL  and 
ARMSTRONG,  as  follows : 

By  JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN. 

It  will  doubtless  be  conceded,  by  all  who  take  part  in  this 
discussion,  that  the  will  does  either  directly  or  indirectly  factor 
in  those  complex  mental  processes  which  lead  to  belief.  A 
question  which  naturally  suggests  itself  from  the  standpoint  of 
logic  is  whether  the  presence  of  will  in  belief  is  a  reflection 
upon  man's  reasoning  powers.  Should  all  conclusions  be 
reached  in  the  '  dry  light  of  reason,'  and  when  this  is  impossi- 
ble should  we  withhold  judgment  altogether?  This  is  an  ideal 
which,  in  certain  situations,  it  is  impossible  to  realize,  for  we 
must  distinguish  between  the  area  of  exact  knowledge  and 
that  larger  sphere  of  our  experience  which  lies  beyond  this  area 
of  light.  In  the  former  sphere  our  beliefs  form  a  series  of 
judgments  grounded  upon  knowledge,  elements  which  comprise 
a  system  of  inter-related,  coordinated  parts.  Here  belief  arises 
from  evidence  mediated  by  experiment,  and  admitting  of  exact 
verification.  In  such  a  sphere  to  allow  the  *  passional  nature  ' 
to  influence  our  judgments  is  to  prove  recreant  to  our  sacred 
obligation  to  follow  the  light  of  reason  alone  in  the  realm  of 
exact  knowledge.  Lying  without  this  region,  however,  are 
spheres  in  which  the  will  may  be  consciously  operative  in 
the  formation  of  our  judgments,  without  sacrificing  the  integrity 
of  our  nature  as  rational  animals.  I  would  indicate  three  of 
these  spheres  : 

i.  Where  complete  evidence  is  lacking,  and  yet  some  action, 
which  in  itself  is  a  decision,  is  imperative.  A  judge  may  with- 
hold his  decision  for  fuller  evidence,  but  not  so  the  actor  in  the 
struggle  of  life.  He  must  often  make  up  his  mind  from  an  im- 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  151 

plicit  apprehension  of   the    situation  viewed  as  a  whole,   and 
which  resists  all  attempts  to  analyze  it  further. 

2.  Where  our  belief  as  to  the  result  of  our  activity  is  itself  a 
factor  in  producing  that  result.     This  is  the  sphere  in  which 
"  hope  creates  out  of  its  own  wreck  the  thing  it  contemplates." 

3.  Where  an  initial  interest  in  a  proposition,  or  an  investiga- 
tion, is  of  such  a  nature  as  not  to  prejudge  the  result,  but  to 
stimulate  the  attention  in  such  a  manner  that  all  possible  evi- 
dence is  duly  considered.     A  will  to  attend  is  thus  related  inti- 
mately to  the  resulting  belief. 

By  WILLIAM  CALDWELL. 

I.  The  relation  of  will  to  belief  can  be  discussed  only  under 
the  presuppositions  of   (a)  the  newer  psychology  of  volition, 
(6)  the  philosophy  of  volition  inaugurated  by  Schopenhauer, 
(c)  the  logical  doctrine  of  different  *  universes  of  reality,'  in  re- 
gard to  which  the  expert  or  <  believer '  in  question  is  the  first 
court  of  appeal,  (d)  the  fact  that  into  the  formation  of  belief 
elements  at  first  non-intellectual  undoubtedly  enter,  (e)  the  fact 
that  theologians  as  well  as  psychologists  are  expounding  beliefs 
from  the  point  of  view  of  dynamo  genesis. 

II.  Both  will  and  belief  have  retrospective  and  -prospective 
aspects,    (a)  Retrospectively  considered,  a  man's  will  represents 
the  sum  of  tendencies  to  act,  that  his  experience  has  led  him  to 
regard  as  in  conformity  with  the  tendency  of  things ;  while  a 
man's   belief  is  his  active  sense  of  the  realities  with  which  his 
experience  has  brought  him  into   contact.      (3)  Prospectively 
considered,  a  man's  will  or  tendency-to-act  (like  an  '  appercep- 
tive  system')  is  always  slightly  in  advance  of  the  matter  of  his 
present  or  formulated  knowledge.     And  as  to  belief \  a  man  has 
the  power  of  testing  by  conscious  experience  the  action-value 
or  organization-value  (i.  £.,  the  value  so  far  as  the  systematizing 
and  developing  of  his  own  nature  and  tendencies  are  concerned) 
of  the  highest  religious  or  moral  practices   and  ideals  of  his 
time.     Only,  a  man's  adoption  of  this  *  social '  or  *  organization ' 
standpoint  is  far  more  matter  of  unconscious  and  inevitable  vo- 
lition than  of  conscious  and  arbitrary  volition.     We  are  prac- 
tically necessitated  (and  not  merely  *  free ')  to  believe  in  that 
which  furthers  our  development. 


152  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE TING. 

III.  We  are  still  too  close  to  Cartesianism  and  Hegelianism 
and  '  faculty-psychology '  and  '  presentationism  '  and  to  external 
views  of  the  realities  of  belief,  to  be  able  to  accept  the  doctrine 
that,  in  the  individual  and  in  the  race,  volition  comes  first  and 
knowledge  and  belief  afterwards,  without  feeling  that  some  kind 
of  injustice  is  done  to  knowledge.  We  really  believe  not  in 
things  *  beyond  '  knowledge,  but  only  in  that  which  we  know — 
only  in  those  things  which  we  know  to  constitute  the  reality  and 
the  conditions  of  our  experience. 

By  A.  C.  ARMSTRONG,  JR. 

The  historical  consideration  of  this  question  demands  a 
broad  interpretation  of  it.  It  concerns  belief  (a)  as  affected 
not  merely  by  *  will '  in  the  technical  sense  but  by  the  whole 
*  passional '  or  *  non-intellectual  nature ' ;  (b)  as  meaning  assent 
to  propositions  not  demonstrably  established.  One  root  of  the 
'  faith-philosophy'  is  found  by  Miller  (International  Journal 
of  Ethics,  Jan.,  1899,  p.  169)  in  the  egoistic  and  adventurous 
spirit  of  the  Revolution  and  the  romantic  movement.  A  second, 
more  widely  spread  and  more  important,  source  is  the  tendency 
shown  in  periods  of  Aufklarung  to  appeal  from  the  head  to  the 
heart  in  support  of  the  imperiled  foundations  of  the  ideal  life. 
Hence  the  positions  of  Pascal  and  Bayle  in  the  seventeenth  cen- 
tury ;  of  Rousseau,  Kant,  Schleiermacher  and  others  at  the  end  of 
the  eighteenth  and  the  beginning  of  the  nineteenth  ;  of  Balfour, 
Romanes,  James,  of  the  neo-Kantian  and  Ritschlian  philoso- 
phers of  religion  in  the  present  age.  But  there  is  a  counter-argu- 
ment, also  historical  and  recurrent,  in  behalf  of  pure  reason  :  that 
the  faith-philosophy  is  obscurantism  and  unreason,  even  that  it  is 
dishonest  and  unworthy  (cf.  Miller,  of.  cit.,pp.  172,  173).  If 
the  defenders  of  the  '  will  to  believe '  cite  history,  therefore,  it 
is  competent  to  their  opponents  to  demand  consideration  for  the 
historical  elements  in  their  own  contention.  The  solution  ap- 
pears to  be :  (a)  the  faith-philosophy,  moderately  stated,  oc- 
cupies a  defensible  position ;  (b)  nevertheless,  the  criticism  of 
the  '  rationalists '  shows  the  point  where  it  is  most  open  to  attack 
and  where  further  development  must  begin.  This  is  the  slack- 
ness in  determining  the  grounds  and,  especially,  the  criteria  of 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  153 

belief.  The  task  has  been  attempted,  indeed,  e.  g.,  by  Kant 
(the  faith  of  reason)  ;  by  James  (the  mingled  psychology, 
noetics  and  ethics  of  'genuine  options'  etc.);  by  those  who 
base  belief  on  judgments  of  ideal  worth.  But  the  bearing  of 
the  history  is  not  to  urge  any  one  or  any  combination  of  these 
as  correct,  but  to  evidence  the  necessity  of  some  such  develop- 
ment of  the  doctrine  in  question. 

Development  of  Voluntary  Motion.  By  E.  A.  KIRKPATRICK. 
(To  appear  in  full  in  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.) 
The  case  of  a  child  of  seventeen  months  that  had  never  tried 
to  stand  or  walk  alone,  who,  upon  seeing  some  cuffs  on  a  table, 
crawled  to  it,  pulled  herself  up,  put  on  the  cuffs,  then  walked  and 
ran  all  over  the  house,  was  reported.  The  claim  was  made  that 
movements,  such  as  walking,  that  seem  to  be  learned,  are  in  re- 
ality largely  inherited,  and  that  other  nervous  and  muscular  con- 
nections are  less  a  matter  of  experience  than  is  usually  thought. 
It  was  shown  that  Professor  Baldwin's  principle  of  reproduction 
of  favorable  stimuli  by  an  organism  must  depend  upon  certain 
physiological  connections,  and  that  chance  is  a  less  important 
factor  in  the  selection  of  movements  for  repetition  than  Baldwin 
has  indicated.  It  was  claimed  that  there  is  a  physiological 
space  relation  between  different  tactual  and  visual  stimulations 
and  the  movements  they  call  forth.  In  learning  movements 
the  attention  of  the  child  is  concentrated  upon  the  stimulus  and 
the  end  to  be  gained,  and  there  is  little  or  no  consciousness  of 
the  movements  themselves.  Therefore,  to  analyze  any  manual 
task  to  be  learned  into  its  elementary  movements  and  requiring 
each  to  be  learned  separately,  then  combined  with  others,  and 
finally  all  used  for  an  end,  is  contrary  to  the  natural  order,  and 
a  partial  undoing  of  inherited  connections  that  should  simplv  be 
completed  and  perfected. 

Refort  on  the  Effects  of  Cannabis  Indtca.     By  E.  B.  DELA- 

BARRE. 

The  effects  of  Cannabis  Indica  as  determined  by  eleven  tests 
on  myself,  in  doses  of  0.5  to  1.5  grains  of  the  solid  extract,  may 
all  be  attributed  to  an  induced  hyperexcitability  of  the  nervous 


1 54  SJS  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE  TING. 

system — sensory,  associational  and  motor.  The  particular 
effects  are  very  variable,  depending  on  a  large  number  of  fac- 
tors. Many  further  tests  are  necessary.  In  general,  a  gradual 
increase  in  sensory,  intellectual,  emotional  and  motor  activity 
occurs,  lasting  about  half  the  total  duration  of  the  main  influ- 
ence ;  followed  by  a  gradual  decrease  to  normal  or  below.  The 
increase  is  not  continuous,  but  intermittent  or  rhythmical.  The 
duration  is  from  five  to  nine  hours  or  more,  though  the  influence 
is  measurable  for  several  days.  No  depressive  reaction  has 
occurred. 

In  the  first  half  there  is  a  tendency  to  hyperaesthesia,  to  in- 
crease in  delicacy  of  discrimination,  in  rapidity  of  association 
and  intellectual  work,  in  richness  of  imagery  and  thought,  in  rate 
of  pulse  and  breathing,  with  diminished  depth  of  both ;  to  de- 
crease in  muscular  strength  and  steadiness,  in  secretions,  in  ex- 
pansive but  not  in  contractive  reactions.  In  the  second  half,  in 
case  no  fatigue  occurs,  there  is  a  gradual  intermittent  return  to- 
ward normal ;  if  fatigue,  a  reversal  beyond  normal. 

No  noteworthy  increase  in  illusions  of  suggestibility  has  oc- 
curred. Introspection  has  been  trustworthy  and  valuable,  largely 
increased  in  power.  The  state  appears  to  be  an  exaggeration 
of  normal  states,  tendencies  and  rhythms.  Hence  its  enormous 
value  in  analysis.  Besides  the  careful  attention  to  gaining  exact 
experimental  results,  which  covered  a  much  wider  field  than  can 
be  indicated  here,  interesting  analyses  were  made  of  emotions, 
of  motor  influences  in  emotion,  in  discrimination,  in  geometrical 
illusions,  of  attention,  association  and  expression,  and  of  philo- 
sophical concepts. 

In  larger  doses,  or  on  other  persons,  the  results  might  in 
some  respects  be  different  from  those  thus  far  obtained. 

The  Psychological  Imagination.     By  DICKINSON  S.   MILLER. 
(Read  by  title.) 

Certain  Hindrances  to  the  Progress  of  Psychology  in  America. 
By  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD.  (Printed  in  full  in  THE  PSY- 
CHOLOGICAL REVIEW,  March,  1899.) 
Starting  from  the  assumed  truth  that  the  progress  of  any 

positive  science  depends  largely  upon  the  quality  of  the  men 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  155 

who  chiefly  cultivate  it,  the  opinion  was  ventured  that  psychology 
is  not  at  present  making  in  this  country  the  progress  which  may 
be  reasonably  expected.  It  would  seem,  then,  that  the  hin- 
drances are  partly,  at  least,  matters  of  -personnel  rather  than  of 
materiel. 

If  we  inquire  more  carefully  into  the  particular  hindrances 
of  this  order,  the  following  seem  to  be  among  the  more  prom- 
inent :  First,  a  certain  aloofness  of  psychologists  from,  and  a 
consequent  ignorance  of,  the  mental  life  and  mental  development 
of  the  common  people.  Without  depreciating  the  value  of  any 
of  the  forms  of  specialization  in  laboratory  or  other  allied  work, 
the  nature  of  psychology  is  such  as  to  make  a  wide  acquaint- 
ance with  average  human  nature  desirable,  if  not  indispensa- 
ble. In  contrast  with  this  hindrance,  due  to  an  excess  of  the 
scholastic  spirit  and  method,  is,  second,  the  excessive  amount 
of  popular  publications  written  by  authors  of  insufficient  scien- 
tific training.  Connected  with  this  is,  third,  the  injury  done  to 
the  science  of  psychology,  in  the  estimate  of  the  intelligent 
laity,  by  mannerisms  of  discussion  and  of  the  expression  of 
tenets  and  discoveries,  such  as  appear  unfit  for  any  body  of  men 
that  are  penetrated  with  the  genuine  spirit  of  science.  The 
confession  seems  forced  upon  us  that  there  is  too  little  of  re- 
serve and  dignity  in  controversy  among  psychologists  as  a  class, 
and  too  much  concession  to  popular  demands  that  tend  to  lower 
our  scientific  standard. 

But,  in  the  fourth  place,  a  certain  invasion  of  the  wide- 
spreading  '  commercial  spirit '  seems  likely  to  work  harm  to  the 
science  of  psychology.  The  fear  is  not  wholly  unfounded,  that 
this  will  cause  an  increase  of  personal  and  institutional  rivalries 
and  jealousies,  of  premature  publication,  of  a  somewhat  disin- 
genuous way  of  seeking  for  personal  reputation  rather  than  for 
the  progress  of  science  and  for  the  welfare  of  mankind.  On 
the  other  hand,  fifth,  psychologists  do  not,  on  the  whole,  main- 
tain a  sufficiently  independent,  yet  teachable  and  friendly  atti- 
tude to  the  other  most  closely  allied  positive  sciences.  An 
increase  of  a  courageous  but  modest  self-respect,  and  a  de- 
termination to  merit  the  respect  of  workmen  in  allied  sciences, 
will  undoubtedly  do  much  to  remove  this  hindrance. 


156  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE TING. 

The  intention  of  this  paper  being  only  to  speak  of  hin- 
drances in  so  far  as  they  belong  to  the  personnel  o>i  psychology, 
reference  to  favoring  conditions  and  to  encouragements  is,  of 
course,  omitted. 

Reason  a  Mode  of  Instinct.     By  HENRY  RUTGERS  MARSHALL. 

Instinct  is  commonly  opposed  to  Reason. 

The  objective  mark  of  an  Instinct  is  that  it  determines  in  an 
organism  typical  reactions  of  biological  significance  to  the  or- 
ganism. Subjectively  we  have  « Instinct  feelings  '  when  the  re- 
actions take  place  ;  when  they  are  inhibited  we  have  <  impulses.' 
The  physical  and  psychical  aspects  of  Instinct  are  as  wide  as 
life.  Turning  to  the  opposition  to  Instinct  we  find  its  objective 
mark  in  variation  from  typical  reactions ;  this  is  indicated  by 
hesitancy  and  then  choice.  Subjectively  choice  is  represented 
by  Will,  and  in  our  complex  life  the  antecedent  to  choice  is 
reasoning.  As  variation  is,  so  choice  and  will  are  conceded  to 
be,  as  wide  as  life;  but  so  also,  if  analogy  is  any  guide,  must 
be  the  physical  process  antecedent  to  choice,  and  Reason  the 
psychic  coincident  of  this  antecedent  process. 

Variation  and  reasoning  both  appear  as  reactions  of  a  part 
of  a  complex  physical  and  psychical  system,  as  though  it  were 
an  isolated  entity  out  of  relation  to  the  whole  system  to  which 
it  properly  belongs. 

Variation  is  thus  statable  in  terms  of  Instinct;  and  hence 
Reason  itself  must  be  looked  upon  as  a  mode  of  Instinct,  the  ob- 
served opposition  between  the  two  being  due  to  the  fact  that  Rea- 
son and  Variation  as  we  experience  them  are  phenomena  ap- 
pearing in  connection  with  psychical  and  physical  activities  of 
very  complex  organisms  formed  of  complex  systems  integrated 
with  still  more  complex  systems. 

Reason  is  thus  referred  back  to  Instinct.  But  Instinct,  in 
its  turn,  is  referable  to  the  simplest  of  all  phenomena  of  life — 
the  reaction  of  a  living  cell  to  a  stimulus.  To  this  simplest  of 
all  reactions  we  therefore  finally  trace  back  both  Reason  and  In- 
stinct. The  problems  connected  with  the  difference  between 
Reason  and  Instinct  are  thus  resolved  into  those  connected  with 
the  determination  of  the  relations  between  parts  of  systems — 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  157 

of  the  nature  of  what  we  call  the  integration   of  psychical  and 
physical  systems. 

Animal  Intelligence  and  the  Methods  of  Investigating  it.     By 

WESLEY  MILLS.  (To  appear  in  full  in  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL 

REVIEW.) 

Comparative  Psychology  is  advanced  rather  by  systematic 
observations  and  experiments  than  by  anecdotes,  nevertheless 
the  latter  when  strictly  true  are  not  valueless. 

The  study  of  the  development  of  the  animal  mind  (genetic 
psychology)  is  of  the  highest  importance. 

Insufficient  attention  has  been  paid  to  distinguishing  between 
normal,  subnormal  and  supernormal  comparative  psychology, 
an  objection,  however,  which  applies  with  a  certain  degree  of 
force  to  human  psychology.  In  making  experiments  on  ani- 
mals it  is  especially  important  that  they  be  placed  under  con- 
ditions as  natural  as  possible. 

The  neglect  of  this  is  a  fatal  objection  to  the  work  of  the 
.author  of  *  Animal  Intelligence,' published  as  a  monograph  sup- 
plement to  the  PSYCH.  REVIEW,  Vol.  II.,  No.  8,  June,  1898. 

The  portion  of  this  research  referring  to  chicks  is  the  most 
reliable,  and  the  suggestions  as  to  pedagogics,  etc.,  valuable. 

This  investigator's  experiments  show  that  certain  associa- 
tions may  be  formed  under  highly  unnatural  conditions,  which 
associations,  etc.,  however,  bear  about  the  same  relations  to  the 
normal  psychic  evolution  of  animals  that  the  behavior  of  more 
or  less  panic-stricken  or  otherwise  abnormal  human  beings  does 
to  their  natural  conduct. 

It  is  not  proven,  as  asserted  in  the  publication  in  question, 
that  animals  do  not  imitate,  remember,  have  social  conscious- 
ness, imagination,  association  and  perception  ;  nor  that  their  con- 
sciousness is  only  comparable  to  that  of  a  human  being  during 
swimming  or  when  playing  outdoor  games  as  understood  by 
this  writer.  It  is  highly  probable  that  animals,  even  the  highest 
below  man,  have  only  rarely  and  at  the  best  but  a  feeble  self- 
consciousness,  if  it  exists  at  all. 

But  on  this  point  and  on  the  question  of  inference,  reason- 
ing, etc.,  the  time  is  not  yet  ripe  for  positive  assertions. 


158  SEVENTH  ANNUAL  MEETING. 

It  seems  more  than  probable  that  the  mental  processes  of  the 
highest  animals  are  not  radically  different  from  those  of  man  so 
far  as  they  go,  but  that  the  human  mind  has  capabilities  in  the 
realms  both  of  feeling  and  intellection  to  which  animals  cannot 
attain.  While  it  is  desirable  to  push  analysis  as  far  as  possible, 
it  is  safer  to  remain  in  the  region  of  the  indefinite,  and  to  re- 
frain from  making  very  precise  and  positive  statements  as  to 
whether  the  animal  mind  does  or  does  not  possess  certain  pow- 
ers, till  we  are  in  possession  of  a  larger  storehouse  of  facts, 
especially  of  the  nature  of  exact  and  systematic  observations 
(or  experiments).  Festinate  lente  is  a  good  rule  in  regard  to 
drawing  conclusions  in  Comparative  Psychology. 

Psychological  Classification.      By    MARY    WHITON   CALKINS. 

(To  appear  in  full  in  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.) 

The  traditional  theory  that  sensations  have  the  *  attributes ' 
of  quality,  intensity,  extent  and  duration  is  unjustifiable,  if  the 
conception  of  sensations  as  unanalyzable  and  irreducible  ele- 
ments of  consciousness  is  at  the  same  time  upheld,  since  the 
possession  of  attributes  is  synonymous  with  complexity.  The 
admission  of  attributes  is  only  possible  on  the  theory  that  the 
sensation  is  not  abstractly  unanalyzable,  but  that  it  is  rather  the 
simplest  possible  concrete  experience.  But  this  hypothesis  ig- 
nores the  fact  that  percepts,  images,  emotions  or  volitions — never 
sensations,  even  in  this  looser  conception  of  them — are  the  sim- 
plest elements  of  actual  experience.  Only  as  an  abstract  and 
hypothesized  and  unanalyzable  element  has  the  term  *  sensation ' 
any  valid  meaning  in  psychology ;  and  on  this  definition  there 
is  no  longer  room  for  attributes  of  this  irreducible  datum,  which, 
rather,  is  itself  an  attribute. 

Scrutinized,  each  for  each,  the  so-called  attributes  are  read- 
ily classified  on  other  principles.  Duration  distinguishes  itself 
from  all  the  rest  in  that  it  is  attribute  of  physical  as  well  as  psy- 
chological phenomena,  and,  therefore,  not  attribute  at  all  in  a 
psychological  sense — not  an  elementary  content  of  the  fact  of 
consciousness,  but  a  reflection  about  facts,  physical  and  psychical. 

Quality  is  identified  with  sensation-element  by  most  writers, 
even  by  those  who  teach  the  attribute-theory.  Similarly,  in  the 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  159 

opinion  of  the  writer,  intensities  can  be  shown  to  be  sensation- 
elements,  distinguishable  and  unanalyzable  factors  of  conscious- 
ness ;  and  extent,  if  not  a  sensational  element,  is  a  complex  of 
such  elements. 

Exhibition  of  Instruments  for  the  Study  of  Movement  and  Fa- 
tigue.   By  J.  McKEEN  CATTELL. 

Apparatus  devised  for  special  research  on  movement  and 
fatigue  in  the  Columbia  Laboratory  was  shown  and  described. 
Several  of  the  instruments  have  been  already  published,  but 
these  are  now  being  used  for  experiments  in  new  directions. 
The  instruments  were  as  follows:  (i)  Apparatus  for  measur- 
ing the  time  of  discrimination  and  movement.  In  addition 
to  the  arrangements  for  exact  determination  of  a  single  reac- 
tion, instruments  and  methods  were  shown  by  which  a  series 
of  processes  can  be  measured  by  simple  means.  Experiments 
by  Mr.  Germann  on  the  formation  of  motor  habits  were  men- 
tioned. (2)  An  ordinary  grindstone  was  arranged  so  that 
reaction-times  can  be  measured  without  chronoscope  or  chrono- 
graph. (3)  Instruments  and  methods  for  studying  the  ac- 
curacy of  movement,  its  force,  time,  extent  and  localization 
were  exhibited,  and  experiments  in  progress  by  Mr.  Woodworth 
were  described.  (4)  An  automatograph  giving  a  continuous 
curve  for  extensor  and  flexor  movements.  (5)  A  spring 
ergometer  intended  to  replace  the  Mosso  ergograph.  (6)  A 
dynamometer  in  which  the  pressures  are  continually  added  and 
counted,  making  the  study  of  muscular  fatigue  and  the  effect  of 
mental  conditions  on  fatigue  possible  without  elaborate  appara- 
tus. All  the  instruments  were  shown  in  working  order,  and  at- 
tention was  called  to  the  use  in  many  cases  of  simple  means  in 
place  of  more  complicated  apparatus,  and  to  the  improvement  of 
the  latter  in  several  ways,  such  as  the  avoidance  of  batteries, 
mercury  for  contacts,  and  smoked  paper. 

The  Physiological  Basis  of  Mental  Life.     By    HUGO  MUN- 

STERBERG. 

The  psychologist  must  demand  that  the  physiological  theory 

of  the  brain  processes  shows  a  manifoldness  of  factors  which  cor- 

\ 


1 60  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE TING. 

responds  to  the  manifoldness  of  the  psychical  elements.  The 
theories  of  to-day  are  not  satisfactory  in  that  respect.  Every 
psychophysiological  excitement  is  considered  as  variable  with 
regard  to  locality  and  amount  of  the  centripetal  stimulation.  On 
the  psychical  side  the  quality  of  the  sensation  corresponds  to 
the  local  variation  of  the  sensory  end  station  and  the  intensity 
of  the  sensation  to  its  quantity  of  excitement.  But  this  is  an  ab- 
stract scheme  which  makes  the  central  process  simpler  than  it 
is,  as  it  does  not  take  account  of  the  fact  that  every  central  sen- 
sory process  is  at  the  same  time  the  starting  point  of  a  centrifugal 
process  which  depends  upon  the  disposition  of  the  whole  centrif- 
ugal system.  This  central  discharge  varies,  of  course,  also  in 
quantity  and  locality,  depending  upon  the  openness  of  the  chan- 
nels. If  we  consider  the  sensation  as  the  accompaniment  of  the 
physiological  process  which  transforms  the  centripetal  stimula- 
tion into  a  centrifugal  discharge,  we  have  then  a  fourfold  mul- 
tiplicity of  the  central  process.  This  allows  us  to  account  for 
two  more  factors  of  the  sensation  which  cannot  be  reduced  to 
differences  of  quality  and  intensity :  the  different  degrees  of 
vividness,  down  to  the  unconscious  states,  and  the  different  sub- 
jective values,  as,  for  instance,  the  time  values,  the  feeling  tones, 
the  belief  tone  and  many  others.  The  vividness  must  be  con- 
sidered as  dependent  upon  the  quantitative  amount  of  the  dis- 
charge and  the  values  dependent  upon  the  local  character  of  the 
discharging  paths.  Every  sensation  is  thus  by  principle  an  in- 
nervation  feeling  and  its  physiological  basis  is  equally  depen- 
dent upon  the  processes  in  the  sensory  system  and  in  the  central 
motor  apparatus. 

On  the  Confusion  of  Tastes  and  Odors.  By  G.  T.  W.  PATRICK. 
This  was  a  preliminary  report  upon  some  experiments  upon 
taste  and  smell  made  at  the  Iowa  Laboratory.  The  experi- 
ments were  made  upon  a  subject  having  complete  congenital 
anosmia  and  upon  normal  subjects  acting  as  controls.  The  sub- 
ject was  first  tested  with  about  one  hundred  odorous  substances, 
including  those  from  all  the  nine  classes  of  odors  given  by 
Zwaardemaker.  None  of  these  gave  any  sensation  or  reaction 
whatever.  Two  other  classes  of  substances,  however,  gave 


A  M ERIC  AN  PS  YCHOL  O  GICAL  AS  SO  CIA  TION.  1 6 1 

reactions,  the  first  being  sensations  of  touch  and  the  second 
sensations  of  taste.  As  examples  of  the  former,  are  menthol, 
sulphurous  oxide,  acetic  acid,  ammonia  and  various  ammonia 
compounds.  As  examples  of  the  latter  are  chloroform,  ether 
and  pyridin. 

The  subject's  sense  of  taste  was  then  tested,  and  the  sensi- 
bility to  simple  tastes  found  to  be  about  normal. 

Then  followed  a  series  of  experiments  upon  taste  made  upon 
the  anosmic  subject  and  simultaneously  upon  two  normal  sub- 
jects to  determine  so  far  as  possible  the  part  played  by  sensa- 
tions of  smell,  touch,  temperature  and  sight  in  so-called  taste 
sensations  as  given  in  ordinary  foods  and  drinks.  These  ex- 
periments extended  over  about  ten  weeks  and  included  one  hun- 
dred and  eighty-five  such  substances,  sensations  of  sight  and 
temperature  being  eliminated  as  far  as  possible.  About  half  a 
teaspoonful  of  each  substance  was  given  to  each  subject,  who 
was  allowed  to  smell  it  and  taste  it  as  much  as  she  wished  and 
finally  to  swallow  it.  The  substances  were  divided,  according 
to  the  results,  into  three  classes.  The  first  were  those  recognized 
both  by  the  anosmic  and  the  normal  subjects.  These  would  be 
presumably  the  foods  and  drinks  recognized  by  the  sense  of 
taste  alone,  but  an  examination  of  the  list  which  included  the 
various  spices,  different  kinds  of  syrups  and  molasses,  cherry 
juice,  etc.,  offered  some  grounds  for  the  conclusion  that,  with 
the  exception  of  typical  simple  tastes,  such  as  sugar,  tartaric 
acid,  quinine,  etc.,  the  recognition  depended  in  every  case  upon 
the  senses  of  touch  and  temperature.  The  second  class  in- 
cluded those  substances  recognized  by  the  blindfolded  normal 
subjects  but  not  by  the  anosmic.  Presumably  they  would  de- 
pend upon  their  odor  for  their  recognition.  They  were  as  fol- 
lows :  coffee,  tea,  normal  alcohol,  port  wine,  claret,  vinegar, 
spirits  of  almond,  tincture  of  rhubarb,  vanilla  extract,  absolute 
alcohol,  tincture  of  ginger,  chocolate,  cocoa,  milk,  milk  and 
water,  sour  milk,  nearly  all  the  common  fruits,  boiled  turnip, 
raw  and  boiled  onion,  yoke  of  boiled  egg,  white  of  raw  egg, 
oil  of  rose,  and  kerosene.  A  third  list  of  substances  included 
those  recognized  by  one  of  the  normal  subjects  but  not  by  the 
other  nor  by  the  anosmic.  A  fourth  list  included  the  substances 


1 62  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEE TING. 

recognized  by  none  of  the  blindfolded  subjects.  Among  other 
conclusions,  the  following  was  drawn :  what  commonly  passes 
for  taste  sensations,  so  far  as  their  discriminative  or  intellectual 
value  is  concerned,  is  the  composite  result  of  the  mingling  of 
sensations  of  smell,  touch,  temperature,  sight  and  taste,  the 
latter,  however,  playing  little  or  no  part  in  the  discrimination  of 
our  common  foods  and  drinks.  Taste  sensations  proper  furnish 
rather  the  emotional  element  in  the  total  conscious  effect. 
Sweet  things  we  call  <  good,'  and  bitter  things  we  call  *  bad/ 
while  salt  and  sour,  if,  indeed,  they  are  simple  taste  sensations, 
add  a  certain  piquancy  which  is  pleasing  when  they  are  not  ex- 
cessive. 

Methods  of  Demonstrating  the  Physiology  and  Psychology  of 

Color.     By  E.  W.  SCRIPTURE. 

The  most  complete  and  effective  method  of  teaching  color 
is  by  means  of  the  tricolor  lantern.  This  is  a  special  kind  of 
triple  lantern  which  I  now  show  you.  The  idea  of  color  pro- 
jection in  this  way  originated,  I  believe,  with  Du  Hauron ;  this 
special  lantern  is  the  invention  of  R.  D.  Gray.  It  is  arranged 
for  lime-light,  as  the  color  work  cannot  be  done  with  electric  or 
acetylene  light.  The  three  jets  are  packed  closely  into  one 
lantern-body.  The  three  condensers  are  as  close  together  as 
possible.  Three  lenses  exactly  alike  are  mounted  on  the  front 
board.  The  jets  have  all  adjustments  for  regulating  the  gas, 
manipulating  the  lime,  etc.  Limes  turned  in  the  lathe  are  used 
in  order  not  to  disturb  the  focus  as  they  are  rotated  in  the  lan- 
tern. Regulators  are  placed  on  the  cylinders. 

Three  colored  films,  red,  green  and  blue,  are  placed  in  the 
triple  lantern.  I  now  show  you  a  slide  which  gives  on  the 
screen  the  elementary  colors  singly  with  their  combinations  in 
pairs  and  in  triple.  Shades  are  shown  by  slowly  turning  the 
light  down.  The  various  hues  and  the  laws  of  combination  are 
illustrated  by  varying  the  intensities  of  the  jets.  The  properties 
of  the  color  triangle  and  the  color  pyramid  are  thus  illustrated. 
Hues,  tints,  shades  and  complementaries  are  readily  explained. 
When  the  laws  of  color  have  been  thoroughly  impressed  by 
this  method,  slides  of  concrete  objects  are  used  for  study.  Thus, 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  163 

a  group  of  flowers  affords  an  illustration  of  the  automatic  solu- 
tion of  color  equations. 

The  phenomena  of  color  blindness  can  also  be  represented 
with  the  tricolor  lantern.  The  usual  theory  of  color  blindness, 
according  to  which  the  defect  arose  by  the  failure  of  one  of  the 
three  fundamental  colors,  can  be  illustrated  by  covering  up  one 
of  the  lenses.  For  red  blindness  the  red  lens  is  covered,  and 
the  resulting  picture  appears  in  combinations  of  green  and  blue  ; 
for  green  blindness  the  green  lens  is  covered,  and  for  the  hy- 
pothetical blue  blindness  the  blue  one  is  covered.  To  illustrate 
the  newer  theory,  the  blue  slide  is  left  unchanged,  but  two  slides 
are  made  for  red  and  two  for  green.  For  the  dichromats  of  the 
first  class — the  red-blue  persons — the  two  slides  taken  through 
the  red  ray  filter  are  placed  in  the  red  and  green  lanterns. 

The  method  also  furnishes  a  remarkable  analogy  to  the 
decomposition  of  the  colors  by  the  eye  into  three  fundamentals 
and  their  mental  recomposition  into  sensations  of  color.  The 
tricolor  views  are  taken  by  a  camera  used  three  times  in  succes- 
sion with  a  differently  colored  screen  each  time.  The  red  rays 
impress  one  of  the  plates,  the  green  rays  the  second  and  the 
blue  rays  the  third.  The  three  negatives  differ  in  their  shading. 
Three  positives  are  made  which  differ  likewise.  The  three 
positives  produce  views  appropriately  shaded  when  projected 
on  the  screen  by  the  colored  lights.  The  result  is  a  recomposi- 
tion in  natural  colors.  The  approximation  to  the  original  colors 
is  close  if  the  slides  are  properly  made  and  manipulated. 

Finally  I  will  call  your  attention  to  the  latest  development  of 
lantern  projection  in  color.  Only  one  lantern  is  used.  Several 
methods  have  been  tried ;  this  one — which  is  not  original  with 
me — seems  to  be  the  only  thoroughly  successful  one.  It  is  here 
shown  publicly  for  the  first  time.  Three  views  are  taken  of 
the  original  object  in  the  usual  way  through  color  screens. 
The  three  negatives  are  then  used  to  produce  three  positives  at 
the  same  place  between  two  glass  plates.  These  three  positives 
are  separately  colored  in  red,  yellow  and  blue  dyes.  The  light 
transmitted  through  the  slide  then  shows  the  original  colors  of 
the  object  photographed.  As  these  views  can  be  used  with  an 
electric  lantern,  the  most  brillian  tand  beautiful  effects  can  be 
produced. 


1 64  S£  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEETING. 

Rates  of  Breathing  and  Degree  of  Mental  Activity.     By  J. 

E.  LOUGH. 

The  paper  is  a  report  of  an  experiment  performed  in  the 
Psychological  Laboratory  of  Wellesley  College  upon  thirty 
women,  students  and  teachers  in  the  college.  Visual  stimuli, 
consisting  of  water-colors,  printed  pages  to  be  read  silently,  and 
series  of  indicated  simple  mathematical  operations  to  be  carried 
out  silently,  were  given  to  the  subjects,  always  under  exactly 
similar  conditions,  each  stimulation  lasting  about  forty  seconds. 
Records  of  the  rate  of  breathing  were  taken  during  stimulation 
and  for  the  forty  seconds  preceding  and  for  the  forty  seconds 
following  stimulation.  The  average  rate  for  the  forty  seconds 
preceding  a  given  stimulation  is  taken  as  the  basis  of  comparison 
for  that  experiment,  and  the  average  rate  during  the  stimulation 
and  following  the  stimulation  is  always  reduced  to  a  ratio  of  this 
standard.  By  this  method  only  changes  of  rate  are  shown 
when  such  a  change  takes  place  within  one  of  given  periods, 
thus  eliminating  all  changes  not  produced  by  the  one  variation 
of  the  subject — that  of  the  presence  or  removal  of  the  stimulus. 
And  since  only  the  relative  changes  are  shown,  it  is  possible  to 
make  direct  comparisons  of  the  effect  of  stimulation  without  re- 
gard to  the  absolute  rate  of  breathing. 

The  experiments  show  a  rather  wide  range  in  the  effect  of  a 
given  stimulus.  But  the  average  of  the  effect  the  stimulus  has 
had  upon  all  subjects  eliminates  the  individual  differences  and 
shares  its  general  influence.  There  is  in  every  case  an  increase 
in  the  rate  during  stimulation  and  a  return  to  the  standard  after- 
wards. But  the  amount  of  this  increase,  produced  by  a  given 
stimulus,  corresponds  in  a  general  way  to  the  degree  of  mental 
activity  produced. 

Recent  Investigations  at  the  Harvard  Laboratory.    By  ROBERT 

MACDOUGALL. 

Recent  Investigations    at   the    Tale   Laboratory.     By  E.  W. 

SCRIPTURE. 

(a)  Investigations  in  the  Psychology  of  Speech.  Gramo- 
phone plate  records  of  prose,  poetry  or  music  are  obtained  in 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  165 

such  a  way  that  time,  stress,  quality,  etc.  of  the  elements  of 
speech  can  be  accurately  measured.  Results  were  reported  in 
brief. 

(3)  Cross  Education.  Experiments  showing  that  training 
of  a  digit  on  one  side  of  body  is  followed  by  increase  in  ability  of 
all  the  others,  even  though  not  practiced.  Hypothesis  is,  physi- 
ologically speaking,  that  the  development  of  the  center  govern- 
ing a  particular  member  causes  at  the  same  time  the  develop- 
ment of  higher  centers  connected  with  groups  of  members. 
Psychologically  speaking,  development  of  will  power  in  con- 
nection with  any  activity  is  accompanied  by  a  development  of 
will  power  as  a  whole. 

(c)  Investigations  with  Currents  of  High  Frequency. 
Sinusoidal  alternating  currents  of  varying  frequencies  were 
produced  by  a  Kennelley  generator.  The  generator  was  run  by 
a  motor,  which  was  started  at  slow  speed.  The  speed  was  grad- 
ually increased,  alternation  becoming  more  frequent.  Elec- 
trodes were  applied  to  the  finger.  The  sensations  were  as  fol- 
lows :  at  low  frequency  there  was  no  sensation  ;  as  the  frequency 
was  increased  the  threshold  of  sensation  was  reached.  At  a 
higher  frequency  the  threshold  of  disagreeableness  appeared. 
At  a  still  higher  frequency  pain  appeared.  At  a  still  higher 
frequency  the  pain  ceased  and  an  agreeable  numbness  was  per- 
ceived ;  at  a  still  higher  frequency  there  was  a  faint  sensation 
only.  I  was  not  able  to  run  the  generator  high  enough  to 
cause  sensation  to  disappear  totally,  but  it  would  undoubtedly 
have  done  so,  as  we  can  infer  from  Tesla's  experiments. 

In  the  course  of  these  experiments  observation  was  made 
that  rapidly  alternating  currents  could  be  used  to  produce  an- 
aesthesia and  analgesia  to  touch  and  cold  (though  apparently  not 
to  heat).  We  are  now  developing  an  apparatus  to  apply  this 
discovery  practically.  Our  latest  attempt — not  yet  completed — 
consists  in  running  a  light  arm  with  a  contact  around  a  rim  con- 
taining 1,000  saw  cuts  filled  with  hard  rubber.  The  arm  revolves 
about  100  times  per  second,  giving  100,000  interruptions  per 
second.  The  results  will  be  announced  shortly.  The  impor- 
tance of  such  a  convenient  method  of  producing  anaesthesia 
without  any  of  the  dangers  or  inconveniences  of  ether,  chloro- 


1 66  SEVENTH  ANNUAL  MEETING. 

form,  nitrous   oxide   gas    or  cocaine,  makes  us  hope  that  the 
method  may  soon  be  made  practical. 

Recent  Investigations  at  the  Illinois  Laboratory.     By  J.   P. 
HYLAN. 

I.  The  Division  of  Attention.     The  object  of  the  following 
experiments  was  to  throw  some  light  upon  the  problem  as  to 
whether  the  attention  can,  as  is  generally  believed,  be  divided. 

A  screen  placed  before  a  revolving  kymograph  drum  has  in 
it  a  small  opening  so  placed  that  a  series  of  lines  passes  imme- 
diately behind  it.  Without  knowing  the  number  of  lines,  the 
subject  is  directed  to  fixate  his  gaze  upon  a  fixation  point  half 
a  centimeter  from  the  opening,  and  count  the  lines  as  rapidly  as 
possible,  the  drum  first  rotating  rapidly  and  then  being  grad- 
ually slowed  down  until  the  correct  number  can  be  given  with 
a  fair  degree  of  certainty.  The  time  needed  for  counting  a 
single  line  was  calculated.  Besides  the  series  with  a  single 
screen  opening,  series  with  two,  with  three,  and  with  four  open- 
ings respectively  were  tried,  each  opening  having  its  series 
of  lines,  and  the  fixation  mark  being  used  as  at  first.  The 
method  of  the  experiment  was  also  the  same,  except  that  with 
more  than  one  opening  the  subject  was  directed  to  divide  his  at- 
tention if  possible  and  count  all  the  lines  that  appeared  in  the 
several  openings. 

The  problem  was  also  approached  by  means  of  auditory  sen- 
sations. Single,  double,  triple  and  quadruple  series  of  musical 
clicks  were  used,  and  the  time  for  counting  a  single  click 
in  the  different  series  was  obtained,  as  in  the  last  experiment. 
In  other  than  the  single  series  the  clicks  came  in  succession  and 
each  was  of  a  distinctly  different  pitch. 

Results  were  given  which  argue,  in  the  main,  against  the 
division  of  attention. 

II.  Effect  of  Amount  of  Motor  Impulse  on  Motor  Memory. 
In  this  experiment  Miinsterberg's  muscle  apparatus  was  used, 
with  one  of  the  pans  weighted  with  200  grs.,  500  grs.,  1,000 
grs.  and  1,500  grs.,  in  order  to  make  the  carriage  move  with 
varying  degrees  of  difficulty.     Each  series  with  a  weight  was 
followed  by  a  series  without  a  weight  to  act  as  control.     When 


AMERICAN  PS  YCHOL O GICAL  A SSOCIA  TION.  1 67 

each  subject  had  gone  through  each  series,  the  experiments  were 
repeated  with  the  carriage  pushed  instead  of  pulled  as  at  first, 
to  vary  the  effect  of  the  joint  sensations,  and  also  repeated  with 
an  interval  of  10  and  of  30  seconds  between  the  first  and  the 
repeated  movement. 

The  results  show  that  the  repeated  movements  were  dis- 
tinctly more  accurate  in  pushing  than  in  pulling,  and  that  this 
difference  was  greater  with  the  weights  than  without  them.  The 
weights  seem  to  have  been  a  disturbing  factor,  but  much  less  so 
for  pushing  than  for  pulling.  In  pushing,  the  tendency  was 
constantly  to  underestimate  the  distance,  but  to  do  so  by  a  fairly 
constant  amount. 

Recognition  under  Objective  Reversal.  By  GEORGE  V.  DEAR- 
BORN. (To  appear  in  full  in  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.) 
This  research,  conducted  in  the  Harvard  Psychological  Lab- 
oratory during  the  first  five  months  of  1898,  is  a  study  of  the 
relative  recognizability  of  objects  turned  or  reversed  in  each  of 
the  four  quadrants  and  in  the  mirror-reversal  and  always  in  a 
plane  at  right  angles  to  the  line  of  sight.  The  essential  appa- 
ratus employed  was  a  set  of  368  chance  blots  of  ink  made  on 
white  cards  4  cm.  square,  and  arranged  in  series  of  ten  with 
three  reversals  in  each  series.  These  objects  were  exhibited  to 
each  of  the  nine  subjects,  and  their  judgments  as  to  recognition 
recorded  by  means  of  precise  electrical  mechanism  and  a  kymo- 
graph. It  was  found  that  the  repeated  characters  when  one-quar- 
ter reversed  over  toward  the  left  were  recognized  61.4%  as  often 
as  were  those  unturned ;  inverted,  72.8  %  ;  three-quarter  reversed, 
47.1%  ;  erect  mirror-reversed,  65.7%  ;  and  inverted  mirror- 
reversed,  45.7%.  In  other  words,  it  appears  that  an  object  is 
recognized  more  readily  when  inverted  then  when  in  either  of 
the  two  intermediate  positions,  and  more  readily  also  than  in  the 
erect  mirror-reversal  or  in  that  position  inverted. 

It  is  suggested  that  these  empirical  results  may  be  in  part 
explained  respectively  by  the  law  of  habit ;  the  optical  condi- 
tions of  vision ;  the  fact  that  we  habitually  perceive  the  upper 
left-hand  corner  of  a  flat  object  first ;  and  by  our  familiarity  with 
mirrors,  natural  and  artificial. 


1 68  SEVENTH  ANNUAL  MEETING. 

Further  Measurements  of  Pain.     By  ARTHUR  MACDONALD. 

Tables  of  measurements  made  by  the  writer  were  distributed^ 
and  the  conclusions  reached  were  as  follows  : 

1.  In   general    the  sensibility  to  pain    decreases   as   age  in- 
creases.    The  left  temple  is  more  sensitive  than  the  right.    This 
accords  with  former  experiments  that  the  left  hand  is  more  sen- 
sitive to  pain  than  the  right  hand.     There  is  an  increase  of  ob- 
tuseness  to  pain  from  ages  10  to  n  ;  then  a  decrease  from  n  to 
12;  then  an  increase  from  12  to  13.     From  13  to  17,  while  the 
right  temple  increases  in  obtuseness,  the  left  temple  increases  in 
acuteness.     This  is  in  the  post-pubertal   period.     There  is    a 
general  variation,  which  experiments  on  larger  numbers  might 
modify. 

2.  Girls  in  private  schools,  who  are  generally  of  wealthy  pa- 
rents, are  much  more  sensitive  to  pain  than  girls  in  the  public 
schools.     It  would  appear  that  refinements  and  luxuries  tend  to 
increase  sensitiveness  to  pain.     The  hardihood  which  the  great 
majority  must  experience  seems  advantageous.     This  also  ac- 
cords with   our  previous   measurements   that  the   non-laboring 
classes  are  more  sensitive  to  pain  than  the  laboring  classes. 

3.  University  women  are  more  sensitive  than  washerwomen, 
but  less  sensitive  than  business  women.     There  seems  to  be  no 
necessary   relation  between  intellectual  development  and  pain 
sensitiveness.     Obtuseness  to  pain  seems  to  be  due  more  to  har- 
dihood in  early  life. 

4.  Self-educated  women,  who  are  not  trained  in  universities, 
are    more  sensitive  than  business  women.     Giving,  then,   the 
divisions   in  the  order  of   their  acuteness  to  the  sense  of   pain, 
they  would  stand  as  follows  :     ist,  girls  of  the  wealthy  classes  ; 
2d,  self-educated  women  ;  3d,  business  women  :    4th,  university 
women;  5th,  washerwomen.     The  greater  sensitiveness  of  self- 
educated  women   as   compared  with  university  women  may  be 
due  to  the  overtaxing  of  the  nervous  system  of  the  former  in 
their  unequal  struggle  after  knowledge. 

5.  The  girls  in  the  public  schools  are  more   sensitive  at  all 
ages  than  the  boys.     This  agrees  with  the  results  of  our  previous 
measurements  that  women  are  more  sensitive  to  pain  than  men. 

These  measurements  of  least  disagreeableness,  or  of  thresh- 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  169 

old  of  pain,  are  approximate  measurements  of  the  combination 
of  nerve,  feeling  and  idea.  The  temple  algometer  designed  by 
the  writer  was  also  described  and  exhibited. 

Theory  of  the  Will  in  Aristotle's  Ethics.     By  WM.  A.  HAM- 
MOND. 

The  two  component  elements  in  the  ethical  will  are  the  Prac- 
tical Reason  (vo5c 7T/>oxr«6c,  Dean.  433*14,  16  ;  404*5  ;  Eth.  Nic. 
1142°  23-30;  dtdvoca  TTpaxrcxij,  De  an.  433*18)  and  Desire 
(iTriSufjtla,  De  an.  432*6  seq.  ;  433"  2;  o/>e&c,  433° *5  seqq.). 
Desire,  as  Aristotle  employs  it,  is  not  a  purely  pathic  element 
or  a  mere  feeling  of  pleasure  or  pain.  He  describes  it  as  an  effort 
after  what  is  pleasant ;  i.  £.,  he  includes  in  it  an  activity  element 
(433*24  seqq.).  It  is  feeling  with  an  added  quality  of  impulse  or 
Trieb.  It  involves  further  an  idea  or  presentative  element.  The 
details  of  Aristotle's  analysis  of  desire  are,  therefore,  (i)  Idea. 
There  can  be  no  desire  without  an  image  (opzxrtxbv  ds  oux  dvsu 
ydyraffiac,  433*28).  (2)  Feeling.  In  every  desire  the  element  of 
pleasure  or  pain  constitutes  the  stimulating  force  to  action  (433° 
21 ;  i iii6i 7).  (3)  Effort  or  activity,  the  actual  impulse  to  pur- 
sue or  avoid  (433°9,  13  ;  H39a22).  Between  the  practical  and 
theoretical  reason  Aristotle  draws  a  distinction.  The  theoret- 
ical or  speculative  reason  deals  with  necessary  truths  (432*24 
seqq. ;  1139*10  seqq.),  the  practical  reason  operates  in  the  sphere 
of  choice  and  of  the  variable ;  the  theoretical  reason  does  not 
command,  is  concerned  with  the  true  and  false  ;  practical  reason 
is  imperative,  is  concerned  with  good  and  bad,  judges,  weighs, 
determines ;  its  sphere  of  activity  is  the  sphere  of  conduct. 
The  characteristic  virtue  of  the  practical  reason  is  prudence 
(<pp6v7f<T«z) .  While  prudence  describes  the  moral  quality  of  the 
practical  reason,  the  method  of  its  operation  is  described  by 
the  practical  syllogism  (434*16-20;  1 147*1-7;  1144*31  seqq.). 
The  Practical  Reason  contains  a  jussive  or  epitactic  force ; 
the  desire  contains  an  active  quality  of  impulse.  Aristotle  de- 
fines the  moral  will,  therefore,  as  reason  stimulated  by  desire  or 
desire  penetrated  by  reason  (1139*4).  The  moral  will,  as  this 
complex  of  reason  and  desire,  functions  under  the  modes  of  (a) 
deliberate  choice  and  (b)  freedom,  and  issues  by  means  of  par- 


170  SE  VENTH  A  NNUAL  MEE  TING . 

ticular  acts  in  (c)  fixed  habit  or  the  persistent  character.  As 
Aristotle  regards  the  whole  of  psychical  life  as  impulse  or  ac- 
tivity tending  towards  the  realization  of  a  potentiality,  one  may 
find  in  this  doctrine  of  Iviffzia.  the  correspondent  of  the  non- 
moral  or  metaphysical  will  of  the  moderns.  The  will  of  Ethics, 
however,  the  voluntas  intellectivus  of  Aquinas,  is  conceived  of 
as  feeling  acting  under  the  forms  imposed  by  reason. 

Psychology  and  Ethical  Scepticism.     By  W.  G.  EVERETT. 

Is  a  science  of  ethics  possible?  Ethical  scepticism  has  de- 
nied its  possibility.  Each  individual,  by  virtue  of  a  peculiar 
nature,  is  a  law  unto  himself.  Moral  laws  are  the  rough  com- 
promise which  convention  effects  to  render  some  sort  of  social 
life  possible.  They  have  no  natural  or  rational  sanctions.  To 
escape  these  difficulties  appeal  has  been  made  to  religion  with 
its  supernatural  sanctions.  But  this  is  fatal  to  a  science  of 
ethics  and  is  practically  unsatisfactory,  as  large  numbers  are 
untouched  by  supernatural  sanctions.  Like  difficulties  con- 
front a  metaphysical  ethic.  A  metaphysic  of  ethics  is  valid  and 
necessary,  but  as  a  complement,  not  a  substitute,  for  a  science 
of  ethics.  The  existence  of  natural  and  rational  sanctions  is 
presupposed  by  such  a  science.  Many  profoundly  believe  that 
there  are  adequate  sanctions  in  human  experience.  Can  they 
be  reduced  to  scientific  form?  If  so,  we  must  have  an  ade- 
quate psychology  of  moral  experience.  Ethics  requires  not 
only  a  social  psychology  but  also  a  psychology  of  the  subtler 
phases  of  individual  moral  experience.  What  then  is  the  rela- 
tion of  the  ethical  elements  of  consciousness  to  the  total  con- 
scious life  of  the  individual  ?  What  part  do  these  elements  play 
in  mental  development?  How  do  they  stand  related  to  mental 
deficiencies  and  excellencies  ?  What  are  the  results  upon  the 
affective  states  of  such  vices  as  envy,  jealousy  and  self-seeking? 
In  states  of  ennui,  despair  and  pessimism  are  there  elements 
which  result  from  ethical  deficiencies?  Is  it  true  psycholog- 
ically that  lust  and  greed  are  the  sure  seeds  of  uneasiness  and 
dissatisfaction?  To  answer  these  and  similar  questions  satis- 
factorily would  be  to  ground  moral  law  and  its  sanctions  in 
man's  own  nature,  and  at  the  same  time  securely  to  establish 
the  science  of  ethics. 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  171 

Professor  Baldwin's  "  Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations  in 
Mental  Development."  By  W.  CALDWELL. 
This  paper  was  an  attempt  at  a  positive  and  appreciative 
criticism  of  Professor  Baldwin's  second  volume  on  Mental  De- 
velopment, the  Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations.  Mr.  Bald- 
win's book  achieves  the  object  of  its  endeavor — the  exhibition 
of  social  organization  and  personal  (mental  and  moral)  organ- 
ization under  the  same  psychological  principles.  Its  classical 
recognition  of  epistemological  principles  is  one  of  its  merits, 
and  it  confines  itself,  on  the  whole,  to  the  genetic  point  of  view. 
The  apparently  ever-recurring  circular  process  from  the  *  self ' 
to  *  society '  and  from  society  to  the  self  and  then  back  again, 
instead  of  being,  as  some  critics  maintain,  a  drawback  or  de- 
fect of  the  book,  must  be  studied  as  part  of  its  central  lesson 
and  main  contention.  Mr.  Baldwin  does  not  exactly  assume, 
without  any  explanation,  the  self  and  society ;  he  assumes  the 
fact  of  mental  development,  and  then,  when  studying  its  begin- 
nings and  its  different  phases,  finds  that  it  involves  the  concep- 
tion and  the  reality  of  the  self  as  a  socius — as  one  term  or 
another  in  a  related  thought  or  action  content.  The  concluding 
sections  of  the  volume,  about  the  final  and  irreducible  conflict 
between  the  moral  man  and  society,  are  proof  positive  that  its 
author  believes  in  the  reality  of  the  human  personality  as  some- 
thing more  than  a  mere  phase  of  a  '  social  situation.'  Nor  is  Mr. 
Baldwin's  use  of  the  genetic  point  of  view  a  mere  arbitrary  pro- 
cedure ;  he  justifies  his  use  of  that  method  by  letting  us  see 
that  consciousness  and  conscious  process  cannot  be  understood 
apart  from  it. 

The  positive  value  of  the  work  lies  in  the  fullness  of  detail 
with  which  the  relations  of  the  thought-process  to  the  movement- 
process  are  worked  out.  Its  teaching  about  imitation  as  the 
social  method  par  excellence  must  be  taken  along  with  what  is 
taught  in  Mr.  Baldwin's  first  volume  upon  that  process.  And 
then,  lastly,  the  genetic  point  of  view  fully  justifies  the  conten- 
tion that  society  is  a  psychological  organization.  The  book  has 
a  high  general  value  at  the  present  time,  tracing,  as  it  does, 
many  important  scientific  and  philosophic  tendencies  to  their 
psychological  roots. 


172  SJS  VENTH  A NNUAL  MEE  TING . 

The  Genetic  Determination  of  the  Self.     By  J.  MARK  BALD- 
WIN.     (Read  by  title.) 

Consists  of  sections  added  in  the  second  edition  of  the 
author's  *  Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations,'  in  which  some 
of  the  applications  of  the  theory  of  the  *  Dialectic  of  Personal 
Growth '  are  brought  together  more  explicitly  in  view  of  criti- 
cism. It  is  to  appear  in  full,  under  the  title  '  The  Social  and  the 
Extra-Social,'  in  the  Amer .  Journal  of  Sociology,  March,  1899. 

Art    in   the   Light   of  Modern   Psychology.     By    G.    TOSTI. 
(Read  by  title.) 

A  Study  of  Geometrical  Illusions.     By  CHAS.  H.  JUDD.     (To 

appear  in  full  in  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  May,  1899.) 

The  main  thesis  of   the  paper  is  that  the  underestimation  of 

acute  angles   and  overestimation  of  obtuse   angles,  which  is  a 

common  feature  of  many  illusions,  is  not  a  fundamental  fact, 

but  is  to  be  explained  as  due  to  the  false  estimation  of  the  length 

of  the  sides  of  the  angles. 

Overestimation  and  underestimation  of  linear  distances  are 
always  accompanied  by  false  judgments  in  the  opposite  direc- 
tion in  the  surrounding  field  of  vision.  It  is  possible  to  find 
illusions  in  the  surrounding  field  even  when  the  figure  suffers 
no  internal  illusion.  These  facts  lead  to  the  conclusion  that  such 
illusions  are  in  general  due  to  the  shifting  of  points  in  their  spa- 
tial relations. 

The  simplest  form  of  the  angle  illusions,  the  Poggendorff 
illusion,  is  due  to  underestimation  of  the  distance  between  the 
interrupted  ends  of  the  oblique  lines,  not  to  false  estimation  of 
the  angles.  This  is  supported  negatively  by  comparison  of  the 
angles  under  a  variety  of  conditions,  under  some  of  which  the 
illusion  appears,  and  under  others  of  which  it  does  not.  Posi- 
tive evidence  is  produced  in  quantitative  determinations  of  the 
error  in  the  estimation  of  the  distance  in  question. 

As  in  the  case  of  the  Poggendorff  illusion,  so  in  the  estima- 
tion of  all  angles,  whether  subject  to  illusion  or  not,  the  estimated 
length  of  the  sides  is  a  most  important  factor.  When  the  side 
is  overestimated  the  angle  is  underestimated  and  when  the  side 
is  underestimated  the  angle  is  overestimated. 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  173 

Subjective    Colors    and    the    After-Image.       By    MARGARET 

FLOY  WASHBURN. 

This  paper  describes  experiments  designed  to  show  the  effect 
on  the  series  of  colors  produced  in  the  *  ringing  off '  of  an 
after-image,  by  efforts  to  call  up  subjective  color  sensations  of 
red,  green  and  blue.  It  was  found  that  the  color  changes  of 
the  image  were  very  materially  influenced  by  this  process ; 
traces  of  a  given  color  in  the  image  being  intensified  by  central 
excitation  until  the  entire  image  was  tinged  with  the  visualized 
color.  Since  the  process  thus  investigated  does  not  differ  essen- 
tially from  the  process  of  voluntary  attention  to  a  given  color, 
the  experiments  furnish  evidence  that  attention  has  a  positive, 
intensifying  function,  and  they  suggest  that  the  increase  of  in- 
tensity on  the  part  of  the  conscious  state  attended  to  comes  not 
from  a  single  *  attention  center '  but  from  associated  centers  of 
the  same  order  as  that  which  gives  rise  to  the  conscious  state  in 
question. 

Three  New  Cases  of  Total  Color-Blindness.     By  CHRISTINE 
LADD  FRANKLIN.      (Read  by  title.) 

A  New  Color  Illusion.     By  GEORGE  TRUMBULL  LADD. 

A  diagram  on  p.  50  of  Fick's  Lehrbuch  der  Augenheilkunde, 
used  by  the  author  to  illustrate  <  red-green  blindness,'  became 
the  point  of  starting  for  an  investigation  not  yet  completed. 
The  illusion,  consisting  of  the  complete  disappearance  of  the 
red-colored  letter  E  and  the  substitution  of  the  color  of  the 
green  background,  was  first  noticed  by  Dr.  George  T.  Stevens, 
of  New  York  City. 

Investigation  has  shown  that  strips  of  red,  blue  and  orange, 
on  a  great  variety  of  backgrounds,  give  the  same  illusion,  al- 
though the  orange  seems  to  have  a  different  way  of  disappear- 
ing from  that  followed  by  the  other  two  colors.  A  marked  dif- 
ference was  discovered  between  two  classes  of  backgrounds. 
Green  of  two  different  shades,  dark  violet,  dark  blue,  and  black 
gave  the  illusion  readily.  But  yellow,  orange,  gray,  white,  and 
a  lighter  blue  or  green,  and  a  reddish  violet  gave  the  illusion 
with  greatly  increased  difficulty  or  not  at  all.  These  colors 


1 74  S£  VENTH  A  NNUA  L  MEE  TING. 

for  the  strips  and  backgrounds  seem  to  retain  their  peculiarities 
even  when  combined  on  the  same  general  field  of  vision. 

Explanations  of  this  illusion  are  not  yet  clearly  made  out. 
It  may  be  partly  due  to  the  production  of  a  temporary  blind- 
spot.  It  seems  to  be  connected,  also,  with  the  rhythm  of  atten- 
tion in  fixation.  And  there  is  some  evidence  that  the  substituted 
color  is  of  a  complicated  cerebral  origin.  Further  investiga- 
tion will  follow. 

REPORT    OF   THE    COMMITTEE    ON    PHYSICAL    AND  MENTAL 

TESTS. 

Professor  Cattell,  the  Chairman,  stated  that,  owing  to  the  ab- 
sence abroad  during  a  considerable  portion  of  the  year  of  four 
of  the  five  members  of  the  committee,  no  regular  meeting  had 
been  held.  In  any  case,  the  committee  needed  trials  and  re- 
ports of  the  tests  already  recommended  before  further  joint  ac- 
tion could  be  taken  to  advantage.  Individually  the  members  of 
the  committee  had  continued  its  work.  In  this  regard  each 
must  speak  for  himself ;  at  Columbia  the  tests  had  been  regu- 
larly made  and  extended  to  include  students  of  Barnard  Col- 
lege, several  new  tests  had  been  devised  and  tried,  and  a  gym- 
nasium examination  had  been  arranged  that  added  to  the  value 
of  the  tests  made  in  the  Psychological  Laboratory.  The  sum 
of  $100  appropriated  at  the  Ithaca  meeting  had  been  in  part 
distributed  as  follows :  $25  to  Professor  Jastrow  toward  the 
cost  of  his  card-sorting  apparatus  in  order  that  it  might  be  sold 
at  a  lower  rate ;  $25  to  Professor  Cattell  for  record  blanks,  the 
blanks  to  be  distributed,  at  the  cost  of  press-work,  to  members 
of  the  Association  wishing  to  use  them ;  and  $25  to  Professor 
Warren  for  an  investigation  of  individual  differences  in  memory 
and  imagery. 

Tests  for  Sense-Type.     By  HOWARD  C.  WARREN. 

The  following  set  of  tests  is  proposed  as  a  means  of  study 
ing  the  comparative  value  of  the  several  senses  in  the  life  of  the 
individual.  The  object  of  the  series  as  a  whole  is  to  determine 
the  respective  role  of  each  sense  in  perception,  association, 
memory,  imagination,  etc.  The  different  tests  take  these  func- 
tions up  separately. 


AMERICAN  PS YCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIA TION.  1 75 

I.  PERCEPTION  TEST. — A  simple  passage  of  400  words, 
containing  40  misprints,  some  of  which  appeal  to  the  eye  and 
others  to  the  ear.     The  subject  is  asked  to  read  the  passage  and 
mark  the  misprints.     The  proportion  of  misprints   as  a  whole 
and  of  each  kind  is  noted. 

II.  PERCEPTION- ASSOCIATION   TEST. — A  list  of  50  words, 
chosen  for  their  richness  of  sense-connotation,  and  so  arranged 
that  those  in  immediate   succession   are   not  likely  to  suggest 
images  from  the  same  senses.     They  are  read  to  the  subject, 
who  is  requested  to  state  the  kind  of  sense  imagery  suggested 
first,  later,  and  most  prominently,  in  each  case. 

III.  MEMORY  TEST. — Six  series  of  nine  figures  each ;  to  be 
dictated  or  shown  to  the  subject,  who  is  to  repeat  or  write  each 
series  from  memory  after  it  has  been  completed. 

IV.  MoTOR-Co-ORDiNATiONTEST. — i.  Writing  on  the  fore- 
head ;  the  direction  of  the  writing  showing  the    relative  impor- 
tance of  the  visual  and   muscular  factors  in  this  function.     2. 
Five   separate   tests   in   mirror-writing   (i.  <?.,  looking   into  the 
mirror  and  writing  so  that  the  phrase  shall  read  correctly  in  the 
mirror)  ;    the  hand  and  paper    are    not  seen   directly — merely 
their  reflection  in  the  mirror ;  the  mirror  is  placed  at  the  right 
of  the  paper  in  two  cases,  and   above  it  (i.  e.,  in  front)  in  the 
rest. 

V.  MENTAL  IMAGERY  TEST. — The  subject  is  asked  to  call 
up  a  vivid  image  of  a  definite  sensation  described  to  him ;  there 
are  n  tests;  the  time  consumed  in  the  effort  is  noted,  together 
with  the  degree  of  success  or  failure. 

VI.  REACTION  TEST. — Six   series   of  ten   reactions   each ; 
with  natural,  sensory  and  motor   attention,  and  on   sound  and 
light  stimuli  respectively. 

VII.  QUESTIONNAIRE. — A  set  of  questions  to  bring  out  the 
absolute  and  relative  importance,  for  the  subject,   of  various 
senses  (including  muscular)  in  certain  respects. 

These  tests  are  expected  to  yield  some  useful  data  in  the 
field  of  individual  psychology.  They  should  help  in  the  final 
determination  of  a  certain  number  of  the  general  tests  that  your 
committee  is  seeking  to  formulate ;  and  it  is  on  this  ground  that 
the  application  is  made  for  an  appropriation  from  the  fund 
allotted  to  that  object. 


1 76  SE  VENTH  ANNUAL  MEETING. 

OFFICERS    AND   MEMBERS    OF  THE   AMERICAN    PSY- 
CHOLOGICAL ASSOCIATION,   1899. 

President,  Professor  John  Dewey,  University  of  Chicago.  Secre- 
tary and  Treasurer,  Dr.  Livingston  Farrand,  Columbia  University. 

Council,  term  expiring  1899,  Professor  Joseph  Jastrow,  University 
of  Wisconsin,  Professor  J.  E.  Creighton,  Cornell  University;  term 
expiring  1900,  Dr.  A.  Kirschmann,  University  of  Toronto,  Professor 
E.  B.  Delabarre,  Brown  University;  term  expiring  1901,  Professor  J. 
McK.  Cattell,  Columbia  University,  Professor  H.  N.  Gardiner,  Smith 
College. 

LIST  OF   MEMBERS. 

ABBOTT,  MR.  A.  H.,  University  of  Toronto,  Toronto,  Canada. 

AIKENS,  PROFESSOR  H.  AUSTIN,  Western  Reserve  University,  Cleve- 
land, Ohio. 

ALBEE,  DR.  ERNEST,  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  N.  Y. 

ALEXANDER,  PROFESSOR  ARCHIBALD,  10  W.  54th  Street,  New  York 
City. 

ANGELL,  PROFESSOR  J.  R.,  University  of  Chicago,  Chicago,  111. 

ARMSTRONG,  PROFESSOR  A.  C.,  JR.,  Wesleyan  University,  Middle- 
town,  Conn. 

BAKEWELL,  PROFESSOR  C.  M.,  Bryn  Mawr  College,  Bryn  Mawr, 
Pa. 

BALDWIN,  PROFESSOR  J.  MARK,  Princeton  University,  Princeton,  N.  J. 

BIGHAM,  DR.  JOHN,  DePauw  University,  Greencastle,  Ind. 

BLISS,  DR.  C.  B.,  New  York  University,  New  York  City. 

BOAS,  DR.  FRANZ,  American  Museum  of  Natural  History,  New  York 
City. 

BRANDT,  PROFESSOR  F.  B.,  Philadelphia  High  School,  Philadelphia, 
Pa. 

BRYAN,  PROFESSOR  W.  L.,  Indiana  University,  Bloomington,  Ind. 

BUCHNER,  DR.  E.  F.,  New  York  University,  New  York  City. 

BUCK,  MR.  A.  F.,  Union  College,  Schenectady,  N.  Y. 

BURNHAM,  DR.  W.  H.,  Clark  University,  Worcester,  Mass. 

BUTLER,  PROFESSOR  N.  M.,   Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 

CALDWELL,  PROFESSOR  WILLIAM,  Northwestern  University,  Evans- 
ton,  111. 

CALKINS,  PROFESSOR  MARY  WHITON,  Wellesley  College,  Wellesley, 
Mass. 


AMERICAN  PS  YCHOL O GICAL  A SSOCIA  TION.  1 77 

CATTELL,  PROFESSOR  J.  McKEEN,  Columbia  University,  New  York 

City. 
CHRYSOSTOM,  BROTHER,  Manhattan  College,  Grand  Boulevard  and 

I3ist  Street,  New  York  City. 

COWLES,  DR.  E.,  McLean  Hospital,  Somerville,  Mass. 
CRAWFORD,  MR.  J.  F.,  1060  N.  Halstead  Street,  Chicago,  111. 
CREIGHTON,  PROFESSOR  J.  E.,  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  N.  Y. 
DANA,  PROFESSOR  CHARLES  L.,  Cornell  Medical  School,  New  York 

City. 

DEGARMO,  PROFESSOR  CHARLES,  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  N.  Y. 
DELABARRE,  PROFESSOR  E.  B.,  Brown  University,  Providence,  R.  I. 
DEWEY,  PROFESSOR  JOHN,  University  of  Chicago,  Chicago,  111. 
DODGE,  DR.  RAYMOND,  Wesleyan  University,  Middletown,  Conn. 
DONALDSON,  PROFESSOR  H.  H.,  University  of  Chicago,  Chicago,  111. 
DUNCAN,  PROFESSOR  G.  M.,  Yale  University,  New  Haven,  Conn. 
EVERETT,  PROFESSOR  W.  G.,  Brown  University,  Providence,  R.  I. 
FARRAND,  DR.  LIVINGSTON,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 
FITE,  PROFESSOR  WARNER,  Williams  College,  Williamstown,  Mass. 
FRANKLIN,  MRS.  CHRISTINE  LADD,  1507  Park  Ave.,  Baltimore,  Md. 
FRANZ,   MR.   SHEPHERD   IVORY,   Columbia    University,    New  York 

City. 

FRENCH,  PROFESSOR  F.  C.,  Vassar  College,  Poughkeepsie,  N.  Y. 
FULLERTON,  PROFESSOR  G.  S.,  University  of  Pennsylvania,  Philadel- 
phia, Pa. 
GAMBLE,   DR.  ELEANOR  A.   McC.,  Wellesley  College,   Wellesley, 

Mass. 

GARDINER,  PROFESSOR  H.  N.,  Smith  College,  Northampton,  Mass. 
GILMAN,  DR.  B.  I.,  Museum  of  Fine  Arts,  Boston,  Mass. 
GREEN,  DR.  GERVASE,  Yale  University,  New  Haven,  Conn. 
GRIFFIN,   PROFESSOR  E.  H.,  Johns  Hopkins  University,  Baltimore, 

Md. 

HALL,  PRESIDENT  G.  STANLEY,  Clark  University,  Worcester,  Mass. 
HAMMOND,   PROFESSOR   WILLIAM   A.,   Cornell    University,    Ithaca, 

N.  Y. 

HIBBEN,  PROFESSOR  J.  G.,  Princeton  University,  Princeton,  N.  J. 
HINMAN,  DR.  ALICE  HAMLIN,  University  of  Nebraska,  Lincoln,  Neb. 
HODGE,  DR.  C.  W.,  Princeton,  N.  J. 

HUME,  PROFESSOR  J.  G.,  University  of  Toronto,  Toronto,  Canada. 
HYLAN,  DR.  JOHN  P.,  University  of  Illinois,  Champaign,  111. 
HYSLOP,  PROFESSOR  J.  H.,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 
IRONS,  DR.  DAVID,  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  New  York. 


178  S£  VENTH  ANNUA  L  MEE  TING. 

JAMES,  PROFESSOR  W.,  95  Irving  Street,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

JASTROW,  PROFESSOR  JOSEPH,  University  of  Wisconsin,  Madison, 
Wis. 

JOHNSON,  PROFESSOR  R.  B.,  Miami  University,  Oxford,  O. 

JONES,  DR.  A.  L.,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 

JUDD,  PROFESSOR  C.  H.,  New  York  University,  New  York  City. 

KIRKPATRICK,  MR.  E.  A.,  Fitchburg,  Mass. 

KIRSCHMANN,  DR.  A.,  University  of  Toronto,  Toronto,  Canada. 

KROHN,  PROFESSOR  W.  O.,  Hospital,  111. 

LADD,  PROFESSOR  G.  T.,  Yale  University,  New  Haven,  Conn. 

LEIGHTON,  DR.  J.  A.,  Hobart  College,  Geneva,  N.  Y. 

LEUBA,  MR.  JAMES  H.,  Bryn  Mawr  College,  Bryn  Mawr,  Pa. 

LINDLEY,  PROFESSOR  ERNEST  H.,  University  of  Indiana,  Blooming- 
ton,  Ind. 

LLOYD,  PROFESSOR  A.  H.,  University  of  Michigan,  Ann  Arbor,  Mich. 

LOUGH,  DR.  J.  E.,  State  Normal  School,  Oshkosh,  Wis. 

MACDONALD,  DR.  ARTHUR,  Bureau  of  Education,  Washington,  D.  C. 

MACDOUGALL,  DR.  ROBERT,  Harvard  University,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

MARSHALL,  MR.  HENRY  RUTGERS,  3  West  29th  Street,  New  York 
City. 

MARVIN,  DR.  WALTER  T.,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 

MEAD,  PROFESSOR  GEORGE  H.,  University  of  Chicago,  Chicago,  111. 

MEZES,  PROFESSOR  SIDNEY  E.,  University  of  Texas,  Austin,  Texas. 

MILLER,  DR.  DICKINSON  S.,  312  South  Tenth  Street,  Philadelphia,  Pa. 

MILLS,  PROFESSOR  WESLEY,  McGill  University,  Montreal,   Canada. 

MINOT,  PROFESSOR  C.  S.,  Harvard  Medical  School,  Boston,  Mass. 

MONROE,  MR.  WILL  S.,  State  Normal  School,  Westfield,  Mass. 

MUNSTERBERG,  PROFESSOR  HUGO,  Harvard  University,  Cambridge, 
Mass. 

NEWBOLD,  PROFESSOR  W.  ROMAINE,  University  of  Pennsylvania, 
Philadelphia,  Pa. 

NICHOLS,  DR.  HERBERT,  3  Berkeley  Street,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

NOYES,  DR.  WM.,  Boston  Insane  Hospital,  Pierce  Farm,  Mattapan, 
Mass. 

ORMOND,  PROFESSOR  A.  T.,  Princeton  University,   Princeton,  N.  J. 

PACE,  PROFESSOR  E.,  Catholic  University,  Washington,  D.  C. 

PALMER,  PROFESSOR  G.  H.,  Harvard  University,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

PATRICK,  PROFESSOR  G.  T.  W.,  University  of  Iowa,  Iowa  City,  Iowa. 

PIERCE,  MR.  EDGAR,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

PUFFER,  Miss  ETHEL  D.,  Radcliffe  College,  Cambridge,  Mass. 

ROYCE,   PROFESSOR  JOSIAH,   Harvard  University,  Cambridge,  Mass. 


AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION.  179 

RUSSELL,  PROFESSOR  J.  E.,  Teachers  College,  New  York  City. 

SANFORD,  PROFESSOR  E.  C.,  Clark  University,  Worcester,  Mass. 

SANTAYANA,  PROFESSOR  GEORGE,  Harvard  University,  Cambridge, 
Mass. 

SCHINZ,  DR.  ALBERT,  Clark  University,  Worcester,  Mass. 

SCHURMAN,  PRESIDENT  J.  G.,  Cornell  University,  Ithaca,  N.  Y. 

SCRIPTURE,  DR.  E.  W.,  Yale  University,  New  Haven,  Conn. 

SHAW,  MR.  W.  J.,  30  Maitland  Street,  Toronto,  Canada. 

SHORE  Y,  PROFESSOR  PAUL,  University  of  Chicago,  Chicago,  111. 

SINGER,  DR.  E.  A.,  University  of  Pennsylvania,  Philadelphia,  Pa. 

SMITH,  PROFESSOR  W.  G.,  Smith  College,  Northampton,  Mass. 

SNEATH,  PROFESSOR  E.  HERSHEY,  Yale  University,  New  Haven, 
Conn. 

STANLEY,  PROFESSOR  H.  M.,  Lake  Forest  University,  Lake  Forest, 
111. 

STARR,  PROFESSOR  M.  ALLEN,  22  West  48th  Street,  New  York  City. 

STEWARDSON,  PROFESSOR  LANGDON  C.,  Lehigh  University,  Bethle- 
hem, Pa. 

STRONG,  PROFESSOR  C.  A.,  Columbia  University,  New  York  City. 

TAWNEY,  PROFESSOR  G.  A.,  Beloit  College,  Beloit,  Wis. 

THILLY,  PROFESSOR  FRANK,  University  of  Missouri,  Columbia,  Mo. 

THORNDIKE,  DR.  EDWARD  L.,  Western  Reserve  University,  Cleve- 
land, O. 

TOSTI,  DR.  GUSTAVO,  35  East  5oth  Street,  New  York  City. 

URBAN,  DR.  W.  M.,  Ursinus  College,  Collegeville,  Pa. 

WARREN,  PROFESSOR  H.  C.,  Princeton  University,  Princeton,  N.  J. 

WASHBURN,  PROFESSOR  MARGARET  FLOY,  Wells  College,  Aurora, 
N.  Y. 

WENLEY,  PROFESSOR  R.  M.,  University  of  Michigan,  Ann  Arbor, 
Mich. 

WILDE,  DR.  NORMAN,  University  of  Minnesota,  Minneapolis,  Minn. 

WITMER,  PROFESSOR  LIGHTNER,  University  of  Pennsylvania,  Phila- 
delphia, Pa. 

WOLFE,  PROFESSOR  H.  K.,  University  of  Nebraska,   Lincoln,  Neb. 

Members  will  please  notify  the  Secretary  of  any  errors  in  names  or 
addresses  as  given  in  the  above  list. 


DISCUSSIONS. 

THE  MATERIAL  VERSUS  THE  DYNAMIC  PSYCHOLOGY. 

It  is  not  a  little  remarkable  that  in  this  era  of  dynamism  in  phys- 
ical science  and  of  various  attempts  at  the  application  of  dynamic  con- 
cepts in  psychology  there  have  been  so  few  really  consistent  presenta- 
tions of  the  material  of  modern  psychology  from  the  dynamic  standpoint. 
In  this  respect  -we  recall  hardly  a  recent  book  besides  that  of  Jodl  in 
which  the  old  garment  has  not  suffered  from  the  addition  of  the  new 
cloth.  Titchener's  text-book  and,  to  a  certain  extent,  that  of  Ebbing- 
haus  are  exasperatingly  inconsequent  in  this  regard.  The  net  result 
of  the  experimental  psychology,  industriously  cultivated  during  ten 
years,  is  admittedly  so  small,  so  far  as  facts  are  concerned,  that  it  is  a 
pity  if  it  cannot  at  least  give  us  a  point  of  view. 

The  reason  for  this  condition  is  not  far  to  seek.  It  is  because  our 
psychologists  have  been  narrow  in  their  preparation  and  are  conse- 
quently uninfluenced  by  the  recent  change  of  base  on  the  part  of  molec- 
ular physics  and  higher  mathematical  concepts.  It  may  be  asserted 
that  the  student  of  psychology  as  well  as  of  biology  cannot  hope  to 
take  a  comprehensive  view  of  his  own  domain  without  at  least  follow- 
ing the  results  of  recent  physical  speculation. 

A  psychology  which  is  so  largely  occupied  with  waves  of  air  and 
pulsations  of  ether  may  be  forgiven  for  speaking  of  atoms  and  mole- 
cules, but,  inasmuch  as  a  system  of  psychology  is  profoundly  influ- 
enced by  the  ontological  notions  underlying  it,  one  should  have  a  care 
that  the  use  of  the  convenient  terms  of  conventional  physics  does  not 
interfere  with  a  logical  development  of  the  science.  Still  more  per- 
nicious is  the  effect  of  the  '  matter  idea '  on  current  epistemology. 

While  it  may  seem  incongruous  for  one  who  touches  psychology 
from  the  side  of  neurology  to  present  the  claims  of  an  immaterial 
psychology,  it  is  hoped  that  it  may  not  be  without  interest  to  psycholo- 
gists by  profession  to  receive  the  testimony  of  a  worker  in  the  so-called 
material  substrate.  Proceeding  from  the  statement  that  psychology  is 
the  science  of  experience — of  consciousness,  in  which  all  will  agree, 
for  the  purpose  of  this  discussion  at  least,  it  is  apparent  that  the  ma- 
terial presented  to  consciousness  is  in  the  form  of  activity.  It  does 

1 80 


DISCUSSIONS.  181 

not  matter  much  that  we  admit  with  Professor  Caldwell  that  con- 
sciousness is  activity,  for  all  we  know  of  activity  is  based  on  its  ex- 
perience and  on  the  result  of  inferences  formed  on  such  experience. 
The  condition  of  passive  receptivity  is  one  which  the  neurologist  can- 
not accept  as  in  accord  with  anything  we  know  regarding  the  nervous 
mechanism  of  thought.  The  elements  of  experience  are  all  acts. 
Why  is  not  psychology  content  to  start  with  the  actual  dynamic  units 
of  experience  and  to  use  them  till  they  are  found  wanting  or  until 
proof  is  forthcoming  of  the  existence  of  material  units  in  place  of 
them  ?  But,  it  is  replied,  it  is  one  of  the  necessary  laws  of  thought 
that  forces  must  reside  in  some  substance,  that  forces,  in  fine,  are 
properties.  We  might  be  content  to  rejoin  that  this  is  an  excursion 
into  other  than  psychological  fields,  but  we  were  but  now  complaining 
of  the  restricted  range  which  psychology  allows  itself.  The  experi- 
mental psychologist  of  all  men  should  be  distrustful  of  hard  and  fast 
laws  of  thought.  It  is  not  long  since  he  has  had  beautiful  illustra- 
tion of  the  possibility  of  living  in  a  world  where  everything  is  wrong 
side  up  and  yet  acquiring  the  power  to  adjust  his  habitual  way  of  see- 
ing things  to  the  new  conditions  most  completely.  It  is  impossible  to 
say  why  it  is  any  more  necessary  to  the  mind  to  conceive  of  forces  as 
properties  of  matter  than  it  is  to  think  of  matter  as  a  convenient  in- 
ferential classification  form  for  force.  Psychology  would  be  more 
logical,  more  i  genetic,'  if  it  would  begin  with  the  impersonal  dy- 
namic form  of  statement  4  it  rains,'  '  there  is  a  noise,'  '  it  mews,'  '  it 
hurts,'  etc.,  in  describing  experience.  The  fact  that  the  various 
forces  of  experience  are  combined  into  secondary  units  of  apparently 
simple  experience  does  not  impair  the  propriety  of  such  usage.  Excen- 
tric  projection  does  seem  to  place  our  sensation  in  the  end  of  the 
pointer,  but  we  do  not  oppose  this  fact  of  experience  to  our  knowledge 
that  the  mechanism  of  sensation  is  in  the  several  discrete  points  in  the 
fingers.  We  are  reconciled  to  live  in  a  world  of  illusions  and  realize 
that,  so  far  as  materiality  is  concerned,  the  rainbow  is  as  real  an  ob- 
ject as  the  mountain  over  which  its  brilliant  banner  is  unfurled. 

A  careful  examination  of  the  field  will  convince  any  one  that  the 
greater  number  of  difficulties  at  present  perplexing  psychology  are 
due  directly  or  indirectly  to  the  influence  of  the  c  matter  idea.'  What 
reams  of  good  paper  have  been  spoiled  in  the  attempt  to  explain  or 
explain  away  the  doctrine  of  psychophysical  parallelism.  What 
absurdities  in  the  name  of  anatomy  have  been  perpetrated  in  the  effort 
to  find  a  seat  for  the  soul.  How  incompatible  has  it  not  seemed  that 
there  should  be  such  a  multiplicity  of  activities,  but  a  single  thread  of 
consciousness. 


182  MATERIAL    VERSUS  DYNAMIC  PSYCHOLOGY. 

But  it  may  be  clearly  shown  that  physical  science,  which  formu- 
lated the  matter  idea  as  a  scientific  postulate,  has  found  it  inadequate  for 
its  own  purposes  and  contradictory  of  the  facts  in  the  more  recondite 
applications  in  molecular  physics.  In  support  of  this  statement 
the  reader  is  referred  to  the  literature  of  the  vortex  atom,  especially 
the  mathematical  physical  discussions  of  Lord  Kelvin,  also  to  the 
address  of  the  President  of  the  Mathematical  Section  of  the  Brit- 
ish Association  for  1895.  Dr.  Hicks  suggests  that,  when  all  is 
known,  u  it  will  be  found  that  all  phenomena  are  manifestations  of 
motion  (energy)  in  one  continuous  medium."  The  postulate  of  '  one 
continuous  medium '  is  a  concession  to  the  supposed  necessity  of 
mediating  between  one  form  of  activity  and  the  next  following,  and 
this  necessity  is  felt  to  be  due  in  turn  to  the  idea  that  forces  are  prop- 
erties of  matter.  Having  gotten  rid  of  the  material  units,  it  were 
simpler  to  part  with  this  idea  of  medium  and  accept  the  fact  of  inter- 
action, which  is  quite  as  simple  and  intelligible  as  any  machinery  that 
can  be  devised  wherewithal  to  explain  it. 

Among  those  who  have  attacked  this  question  from  the  side  of 
physicial  science  no  one  has  more  illuminated  it  than  Professor 
Wilhelm  Ostwald,  professor  of  chemistry  at  Leipzig.  In  his  well- 
known  address  before  the  naturalists,  at  Liibeck,  he  called  attention 
to  the  unjustifiable  extension  of  the  physical  law  of  the  conservation 
of  energy  to  form  the  metaphysical  axiom  of  the  conservation  of 
matter.  He  says:  "  It  is  important  to  notice  that  by  this  extension  a 
multitude  of  hypothetical  elements  have  been  introduced  into  the 
notion  which  was  at  first  quite  free  of  hypotheses.  Particularly,  in  the 
light  of  this  theory,  chemical  processes  are  construed  in  opposition  to 
appearance  in  such  a  way  that  in  case  of  chemical  combination,  in- 
stead of  a  new  substance  with  new  properties  resulting  from  the 
process,  the  old  substances  remain  in  the  new.  Thus,  in  the  com- 
bination of  iron  and  oxygen  to  form  ferrous  oxide,  although  the 
familiar  properties  disappear  and  new  ones  take  their  place,  we  are 
yet  to  believe  that  the  iron  and  the  oxygen  are  somehow  concealed 
in  the  compound  and  simply  have  taken  on  new  properties.  We  have 
become  so  accustomed  to  this  view  that  it  is  difficult  for  us  to  realize 
its  peculiarity  or  rather  its  absurdity.  But  when  we  reflect  that  all  that 
we  know  of  any  substance  is  the  sum  of  its  properties  it  appears  that 
the  assumption  that  a  given  substance  is  indeed  present,  but  no  longer 
possesses  any  of  its  properties,  is  not  far  removed  from  nonsense." 

"  As  a  matter  of  fact,  this  purely  formal  assumption  serves  merely 
to  combine  the  commonplace  facts  of  chemical  processes,  particularly 
stoichiometric  laws,  with  the  notion  of  an  invariable  matter." 


DISCUSSIONS.  183 

uThe  assumption  that  all  natural  phenomena  must  be  referable 
ultimately  to  mechanical  forms  is  not  entitled  even  to  be  regarded  as  a 
serviceable  working  hypothesis— it  is  a  simple  error." 

"The  most  promising  scientific  legacy  of  the  departing  century  is 
the  substitution  for  the  old  mechanical  view  of  nature  of  the  energetic 
view."  "  If  all  that  we  know  of  the  external  world  is  in  the  form  of 
relations  of  energy,  what  reason  have  we  to  assume  in  this  external 
world  something  of  which  we  have  no  experience?  Yes,  it  is  replied, 
but  energy  is  simply  a  product  of  thought — an  abstraction,  while 
matter  is  the  real.  I  reply,  just  the  contrary.  Matter  is  the  theoretical 
thing  which  we  have  constructed,  and  that  very  imperfectly,  in  order 
to  represent  the  permanent  in  the  changeable  of  the  phenomena. 
Now  that  we  begin  to  understand  that  the  actual,  i.  e.,  that  which  acts 
upon  us,  is  simply  energy,  we  have  to  determine  what  the  relative 
position  of  the  two  ideas  is,  and  the  outcome  is  not  doubtful ;  it  is  that 
the  predicate  of  reality  can  only  apply  to  energy." 

I  have  quoted  these  passages  with  the  more  pleasure  because  sim- 
ilar ideas  have  been  uttered  in  my  own  class  room  for  many  years 
from  the  standpoint  of  biology  and  psychology.  It  may  be  permitted 
to  repeat  words  used  years  ago  but  printed  again  in  the  Denison  Quar- 
terly in  1896.  "  The  separation  of  force  as  distinct  from  matter  is  a 
secondary  analysis — curious  from  its  psychological  side  and  wholly 
illusory  and  connected  with  limited  conceptions  of  volition — and 
hence  of  causation.  With  all  this  sophistication  we  have  forgotten  or 
neglected  that  primitive  naive  method  of  nature  contemplation  which 
views  phenomena  as  phenomena,  i.  e.,  as  events,  not  as  the  apotheosis 
of  something  else — say  of  matter.  There  is  no  reason  why  we  should 
discriminate  against  this  view  which  involves  the  immediate  accept- 
ance of  the  data  of  consciousness  as  real."  u  The  attempt  to  introduce 
the  element  or  idea  of  cause  at  this  point  is  to  misapprehend  the 
sphere  of  causation,  which  as  limited  and  of  subjective  origin,  has  no 
place  in  ontology.  What  then  is  *  substance  *  which  forms  the  ground 
of  the  phenomenal  ?  We  have  seen  that  it  is  not  necessarily  matter. 
It  might  be  shown,  to  mention  one  difficulty  out  of  many,  that  no  ex- 
planation of  the  molecular  conditions  of  matter  has  been  able  to  dis- 
pense with  the  postulate  of  a  non-material  ether.  Our  own  answer 
to  the  question  propounded  is  briefly :  Substance  is  pure  spontaneous 
energy.  Energy  is  used  to  imply  a  doing  without  the  implication  of 
resistance,  thus  of  effort.  *  *  To  speak  of  energy  as  residing"  in  some- 
thing is  to  introduce  an  utterly  incongruous  concept,  for  it  continues 
our  quest  ad  infinitum" 


184  MATERIAL    VERSUS  DYNAMIC  PSYCHOLOGY. 

Now  we  venture  to  suggest  that  such  a  view  of  substance  is  of  the 
greatest  service  to  the  psychologist,  even  though  it  may  seem  to  the 
metaphysician  to  cut  rather  than  to  untie  the  Gordian  knot.  Accept- 
ing the  data  of  experience  as  the  foundation,  a  dynamic  psychology, 
like  a  dynamic  physics,  seeks  to  construct  its  superstructure,  not  by 
the  introduction  of  metaphysically  postulated  matter,  but  by  com- 
bining the  elements  of  experience.  The  organ  of  consciousness  is 
adapted  to  analyze  the  various  forces  impinging  on  it  by  recognizing 
differences  in  the  form  and  rate,  in  the  kind  and  intensity  of  the 
stimuli,  and  these  differences  are  the  material  of  consciousness.  It  is 
idle  to  object  that  differences  in  mere  form  of  vibration  or  mode  of 
action  are  insufficient  to  account  for  the  diversity  of  the  essences 
making  up  the  universe.  That  is  exactly  the  question.  Light  waves 
of  one  rate  produce  upon  the  mind  an  impression  totally  different  in 
kind  from  those  vibrating  at  a  slightly  different  rate,  and  the  effect  of 
electrical  waves  in  one  phase  is  quite  unlike  that  of  similar  waves  in 
another  phase.  In  fact,  the  whole  world  of  physics  is  a  sphere  in 
which  observed  differences  are  reduced  to  variations  in  rate  and  form 
of  motions.  It  is  this  same  idea  that  must  make  a  permanent  place 
for  itself  in  psychology  before  further  progress  toward  the  simplicity 
of  truth  can  be  made.  Nor  should  we  feel  that  the  dignity  and  worth 
of  the  psychical  are  lost  by  the  recognition  that  it  is  one  in  essence  with 
humbler  activities.  The  sap  that  feeds  the  rough  bark  also  nourishes 
the  blossom.  From  the  above  point  of  view  one  may  approach  the 
vexed  question  of  psychophysical  parallelism  with  more  confidence. 
It  is  not  true  that  the  body  and  soul  are  disparate  and  wholly  incapable 
of  interaction,  for  they  are  different  expressions  of  the  same  force  as- 
sociated as  parts  of  one  system.  It  is  not  true  that  the  two  are  identi- 
cal, for  they  are  different  in  form,  and  this  difference  is  sufficient  to 
distinguish  physical  and  psychical  toto  coelo.  It  is  not  true  that  one 
is  the  outside  and  the  other  the  inside  of  the  same  curve ;  they  are  not 
different  aspects  of  identity,  but  they  are  parts  of  the  same  system  and 
so  intimately  related,  but,  being  different  in  form,  they  are,  in  fact, 
different  in  essence.  It  is  to  be  expected  that  these  ideas  will  seem 
obscure  to  many  by  reason  of  their  unfamiliarity,  but  we  believe  that 
the  method  is  that  of  unsophisticated  experience  and  that  the  results 
conform  to  the  highest  criteria  of  modern  science.  The  application 
of  this  theory  to  the  search  for  an  organ  of  consciousness  has  formed 
the  subject  for  a  paragraph  in  an  article  in  the  Journal  of  Compara- 
tive Anatomy  for  March  of  the  present  year. 

From  this  article  I  may  be  permitted  to  quote : 


DIS  C  US  S  IONS.  1 85 

u  The  search  for  the  organ  of  consciousness  has  remained  unfruitful 
by  reason  of  the  total  disparity  between  the  conscious  and  any  con- 
ceivable form  of  purely  neural  activity.  Nevertheless  it  is  plain  that 
some  sort  of  neurosis  does,  in  every  case,  form  the  immediate  pre- 
liminary to  consciousness,  and  it  is  equally  clear  that  not  every  sort  of 
nervous  excitation  is  an  adequate  occasion  for  the  emergence  of  con- 
sciousness. The  metaphysical  nature  as  well  as  the  peculiar  unity 
and  continuity  of  consciousness  has  militated  against  the  idea  of  local- 
izing this  power,  and  has  disposed  to  a  dynamic  view,  viz.  :  that  the 
condition  of  consciousness  is  not  topographical  but  consists  in  the 
form  of  activity. 

"  It  is  plain  that,  in  the  nature  of  the  case,  it  is  impossible  to  discover 
a  specific  portion  or  a  definite  kind  of  matter  in  which  consciousness 
resides,  for  no  complexity  of  the  material  unit  could  make  intelligible 
the  diversity  in  consciousness,  while  any  complexity  destroys  the  ob- 
jective grounds  of  unity.  It  is  equally  hard  to  discover  any  physi- 
ological basis  for  the  continuity  of  consciousness.  The  idea  of  con- 
sciousness as  a  property  is  accordingly  abandoned,  and  it  remains  to 
conceive  of  it  as  a  form  of  energy.  Pure  energy  with  the  attribute 
of  spontaneity  it  could  only  be  if  it  were  in  the  mode  of  absolute 
equilibrium,  in  which  its  activities  should  be  wholly  reflected  into 
themselves.  This  can  only  be  predicated  of  infinite  essence,  and  it  is 
necessary  to  substitute  the  conditions  of  relative  equilibrium  in  a 
sphere  of  interfering  activities.  The  last  few  years  have  revealed  in 
the  cerebrum  a  mechanism  of  neural  equilibration  of  unsuspected 
complexity,  and  all  that  we  have  recently  learned  of  the  physiology  of 
the  nerve  stimulus  only  emphasizes  the  belief  that  the  whole  of  the 
cortical  complex  is  adapted  to  act  as  a  unit  though  not  as  an  invariable 
unit." 

Nor  does  the  energetic  point  of  view  simplify  alone  the  problems 
of  psychology.  There  has  been  a  notable  tendency  in  America  of 
late  to  return  to  a  vitalistic  hypothesis  in  biology.  It  is  no  answer  to 
those  who  advocate  a  vital  force  to  state  that  such  a  force  has  not  been 
isolated.  It  seems,  when  stated,  a  self-evident  proposition  that  the  re- 
ceptivity of  man,  which  by  the  limitations  necessitated  by  the  condi- 
tions of  its  development  is  adapted  to  admit  certain  segments  of  the 
infinite  sphere  of  energy  and  no  others,  could  not  be  expected  suddenly 
to  develop  an  '  organ '  by  which  vital  forces  could  be  apprehended  in 
other  terms  than  those  applied  to  physical  forces.  This  is  much  the 
same  difficulty  as  that  experienced  by  the  chemist  when  required  by 
the  biologist  to  afford  him  an  analysis  of  living  matter.  The  chemist 


1 86  MATERIAL    VERSUS  DYNAMIC  PSYCHOLOGY. 

must  first  kill  the  protoplasm,  and  it  will  never  be  possible  for  him  to 
affirm  that  the  formula  he  determines  expresses  the  state  of  aggrega- 
tion of  the  living  organism.  Biologists,  accordingly,  have  become 
modest,  and  admit  that  no  forces  have  been  found  in  living  things  not 
also  common  to  inanimate  objects.  It  is  added  that  the  peculiarity  of 
living  matter  that  distinguishes  it  from  all  inorganic  substances  is  its 
power  of  coordinating  the  physical  forces  for  the  perpetuation  of  the 
individual  existence  or  a  chain  of  such  lives.  To  say  that  the  various 
physical  forces  are  coordinated  might  mean  that  there  is  some  outside 
force  restraining  them,  or  it  might  mean  that  by  some  means  the  sev- 
eral forces  concerned  are  brought  into  a  state  of  relative  equilibrium 
by  reason  of  interaction  among  themselves.  Now,  this  state  of  equilib- 
rium is  simply  a  modified  form  of  motion,  and,  as  the  differences 
between  the  several  forces  are,  as  we  have  seen,  simply  matters  of 
form,  we  here  have  just  what  is  necessary  to  constitute  a  new  or  differ- 
ent force  as  a  result  of  the  fusion  of  its  components.  When  this  form 
of  action  is  disturbed,  the  force  breaks  up  into  the  familiar  modes  of 
ordinary  experience,  and  '  vital  force '  as  such  eludes  our  search.  This 
does  not  prove  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  vital  force.  In  fact,  we 
learn  of  vital  force,  as  we  do  of  any  other  of  the  forces  for  which  we 
have  no  special  '  organ,'  by  inferential  processes,  and  this  fact  does 
not  invalidate  the  inference.  In  view  of  the  present  tendency  toward 
vitalism,  it  is  simply  desired  to  show  that  a  form  of  this  idea  is  justi- 
fied from  the  dynamic  point  of  view.  There  is  just  as  much  evidence 
for  the  existence  of  a  vital  force  as  there  is  of  the  existence  of  a  force 
called  electricity.  Electricity  and  vital  force  are  both  forms  of  ac- 
tivity, and  all  activity  has  its  roots  in  a  common  energy,  the  several  so- 
called  forces  being  simply  various  forms  of  its  expression.  Very 
much  of  what  has  been  said  of  vital  force  applies,  mutatis  mutandis, 
to  the  psychical  manifestations. 

To  the  student  of  metaphysics  who  knows  his  Schopenhauer 
these  conceptions  are  familiar.  The  author  of  '  The  World  as  Will 
and  Idea'  said:  "Matter  is  nothing  more  than  causation.  Its  true 
being  is  its  action."  This  is  built  upon  a  psychological  foundation ;  but 
it  must  be  admitted  that  the  effect  of  metaphysics  upon  psychology  has 
apparently  been  wholly  insignificant.  In  conclusion,  it  may  be  noted 
that  by  the  use  of  the  term  '  energy '  for  the  universal,  and  '  force '  for 
the  limited  manifestation  of  action,  we  reverse  the  usage  of  German 
writers,  as  may  be  seen,  e.  g.,  in  the  recent  work  of  Adolf  Wagner, 
Grundprobleme  der  Naturwissenschaft,  a  work,  by  the  way,  that  pre- 
sents the  metaphysical  aspects  of  energetics  in  an  attractive  manner. 


DISCUSSIONS.  187 

The  writer's  apology  for  thus  trespassing  on  this  field  is  his  desire  to 
promote  a  frank  adoption  of  a  dynamic  method  in  psychology. 

C.  L.  HERRICK. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  NEW  MEXICO,  September,  1898. 

THE  POSTULATES  OF  A  STRUCTURAL  PSYCHOLOGY.1 

This  article  is  a  manifesto  of  importance  to  all  students  of  psy- 
chology and  philosophy.  Its  question  has  become  one  of  general  im- 
portance,2 and  Professor  Titchener,  by  virtue  of  his  recognized  achieve- 
ments in  his  chosen  field  of  psychology,  and  by  virtue  of  his  general 
official  prominence,  is  more  than  entitled  to  deal  authoritatively  with 
conceptions  about  the  scope  and  method  and  material  results  of  ex- 
perimental psychology. 

I.  The  chief  gains  that  accrue  from  this  paper  are  due  to  what  may 
naturally  be  called  its  epistemological*  point  of  view.  I  do  not  alto- 
gether like  to  put  the  matter  thus,  for  I  do  not  wish  to  lose  light  of 
the  positive  psychology  that  it  contains,  or  of  its  author's  statement  of 
its  *  main  object.'  And  I  also  wish  to  do  all  I  can  to  remove  the 
erroneous  impression  that,  '  of  course,  philosophers  never  will  make 
any  serious  attempt  to  get  really  inside  the  psychological  point  of 
view.'  Mr.  Titchener's  epistemological  point  of  view  is  defined  in 
the  first  third  of  his  paper  in  regard  to  the  scope  and  the  divisions  of 
psychological  science,  and  in  the  second  two-thirds  in  regard  to  what  he 

*Cf.  the  article  by  E.  B.  Titchener.  Philosophical  Review,  September, 
1898,  pp.  449-465. 

2  Professor  Titchener  informs  us  in  a  note,  occupying  the  half  of  his  first 
page,  that  his  article  'contains  a  part'  of  his  '  reply'  to  a  criticism  (published 
in  this  REVIEW,  July,  1898)  of  his  '  view  of  the  psychological  self,'  made  by  me 
at  the  1897  meeting  of  the  American  Psychological  Association.     His  article  has 
a  value  independently  of  that  criticism  of  mine,  and  I  shall  not  in  the  main 
speak  of  it  as  a  reply  to  my  criticism.     My  criticism  was  not  so  much  of  his 
*  psychological  self,'  as  such,  as  of  the  fact  that  he  did  not  seem  to  me  to  allow, 
in  his  treatment  of  the  '  psychological  self,'  for  some  admissions  that  he  made  in 
certain  general  portions  of  the  book.     His  present  article  opens  up  some  impor- 
tant epistemological  considerations  which  at  once  generalize  and  dignify  our 
'  discussion.'     It  is,  at  the  present  moment,  idle  to  deplore  or  ignore  methodo- 
logical  and   plain    statements   regarding  psychology  and   psychological  facts. 
There  are  not  wanting  signs,  in  a  recent  article  (this  REVIEW  for  November, 
1898)  by  Professor  Mtinsterberg,  that  he  too  has  felt  their  necessity  in  dealing 
with  some  of  his  '  English'  and  '  foreign  '  co-workers  and  critics.     The  '  discus- 
sion,' too,  of  Professors  Baldwin  and  Dewey  in  the  November  number  of  the 
Philosophical  Review  certainly  turns  upon  epistemological  considerations  re- 
garding psychology. 

3  Professor  Miinsterberg  uses  this  word,  loc.  cit. 


1 88  STRUCTURAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

himself  calls  the  nature  and  number  of  the  structural  elements  of  mind. 
As  an  outcome  of  the  first  part  we  recognize  how  true  were  the  words 
of  Mr.  Stout,  in  his  preface  to  his  Analytic  Psychology ',  about  the  com- 
ing of  the  time  when  no  one  man  would  any  more  think  of  writing  a 
book  upon  psychology  in  general  than  he  would  think  of  writing  a 
book  upon  mathematics  in  general.  (A)  Mr.  Titchener  distinguishes 
for  us,  with  the  help  of  biological  considerations,  (i)  the  psychology 
of  structure  or  structural  psychology,  (2)  the  psychology  of  function 
or  functional  (descriptive)  psychology,  (3)  ontogenetic  psychology, 
(4)  taxonomic  psychology,  (5)  social  psychology,  (6)  phylogenetic 
psychology.  A  'very  large  portion  of  experimental  psychology'  is 
really  structural  or  morphological  psychology ;  it  is  a  4  vivisection 
which  shall  yield  structural,  not  functional  results.'  This  is  Mr. 
Titchener's  chosen  domain — the  discovery  of  "what  is  there  [in 
'  mind ']  and  in  what  quantity,  not  what  it  is  there  for."  His  own  Out- 
line, he  would  have  us  infer,  deals  with  the  first  of  the  six  different 
brands  of  psychology. 

(B)  "  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  much  of  the  criticism  passed  upon 
the  new  psychology  depends  upon  the  critic's  failure  to  recognize  its 
morphological  character."  Surely,  then,  no  one  in  the  future  will 
criticise  experimental  psychology  for  not  giving  us  what  it  does  not 
profess  to  give.  Indeed,  we  shall  not  do  so  if  the  said  experimental 
psychology  keep  rigidly  to  its  own  point  of  view.  (C)  Mr.  Titchener 
again  tells  us  that  structural  psychology  has  not  yet  come  to  an  agree- 
ment about  more  than  the  psychology  of  sensation  and  the  constitu- 
tion of  the  sensation  element.  He  himself  regards,  as  we  know,  the 
affection  process  to  be  also  an  elemental  process.  A  majority  of  psy- 
chologists do  this,  he  says,  there  being  a  minority  who  do  not.  "It  is 
natural,  in  view  of  the  intrinsic  difficulty  of  the  subject,  that  the  psy- 
chology of  feeling  should  be  in  a  less  settled  state  than  the  psychology 
of  sensation."  Going  up  higher,  the  '  anatomy  of  functional  com- 
plexes,' i.  e  ,  the  structural  study  of  the  'higher  [mental]  process,' 
the  '  perceptions  and  emotions  and  actions  handed  down  in  popular 
and  psychological  tradition,'  is  as  yet  *  *  *  a  '  mere  plan  of  arrange- 
ment.' (D)  As  to  the  second  way  in  which  the  epistemological  point 
of  view  is  applied:  "The  elements  of  the  experimentalists,  as  they 
themselves  have  been  the  first  to  acknowledge,  are  artifacts,  abstrac- 
tions, usefully  isolated  for  scientific  ends,  but  not  found  in  experience 
save  as  connected  with  their  like."  This  is  emphatic  enough.  Let 
us  not  any  more  go  to  experimentalists  and  say :  4  Your  sensations 
and  affections  and  volitions  and  emotions  are  very  different  things 


DISCUSSIONS.  189 

from  what  we  actually  experience,  are  just  so  many  poor,  thin,  cari- 
catures of  the  organic  experiences  we  feel  in  daily  life.'  He  can 
reply  to  us  that  he  is  dealing  with  the  structural  phases  of  these  pro- 
cesses, and  that  for  more  than  that  we  had  better  betake  ourselves  to 
some  of  his  colleagues.  Now  I  think  that  I  understand  these  four 
points.  Let  me  look  at  some  of  their  consequences,  for  I  must  be 
brief. 

II.  ( i )  As  far  as  in  him  lies,  should  not  a  structural  psychologist 
observe  that  accuracy  of  confinement  within  his  own  proper  sphere 
that  he  request  his  critics  to  think  about  before  attacking  him?  Mr. 
Titchener  says  things  about  functional  psychology  that  may  be  ques- 
tioned, (a)  "It  cannot  be  said  that  this  functional  psychology,  de- 
spite what  we  may  call  its  greater  obviousness  to  investigation,  has 
been  worked  out  with  as  much  patient  enthusiasm  or  with  as  much 
scientific  accuracy  as  has  the  psychology  of  mind  structure."  Far 
be  it  from  me  to  compare  the  zeal  or  the  patience  of  a  body  of  men 
from  the  time  of  Aristotle  to  that  of  the  English  associationists  with 
that  of  the  heroic  pioneers  and  workers  in  the  experimental  psychology 
of  this  century,  but  I  shrug  my  shoulders  and  ask  about  the  standard 
of  'scientific  accuracy'  implied  in  the  preceding  and  the  following 
sentence.  "  But  it  is  also  true  that  the  methods  of  descriptive  psy- 
chology cannot,  in  the  nature  of  the  case,  lead  to  results  of  scientific 
finality."  Finality  on  any  one  plane  of  investigation  is  a  different 
thing  from  finality  along  some  other  plane.  Ai<poiro  ftav  IxavaJs,  el 
xard  rrtv  unozei/j.£v7)v  ukqv  oiaffayrjOsirj.  Mr.  Titchener's  conception  of 
science  in  this  article  is,  I  think,  to  be  inferred  from  his  phrase  about 
the  arrival  of  the  'time'  for  i  the  transformation  [of  psychology] 
from  philosophy  to  science.'  He  means  experimental  science,  as  that 
is  ordinarily  understood,  consequently  he  has  no  right  to  judge  of 
functional  psychology  merely  from  his  standpoint.  And  if  some  of 
his  words  in  this  article  (to  which  I  shall  immediately  refer)  about 
the  last  things  of  mind  were  true,  some  of  his  other  four  psycho- 
logical disciplines  would  also  be  'in  the  air,' — be  absolutely  unscientific. 

(/3)  Ought  not  a  structural  psychologist — and  this  point  is  even  more 
vital — to  be  able  to  adhere  rigidly  to  his  '  structural'  point  of  view,  at 
least  within  the  realm  of  his  own  observation  and  scientific  disputa- 
tion? I  will  adduce  one  or  two  reasons  for  saying  that  I  do  not  find 
Mr.  Titchener  to  do  this.  (/)  He  uses  the  expressions  'elemental 
processes '  (457),  and  '  elements  '  (455,  462),  and  '  last  things  of  mind  * 
— I  will  not  say  interchangeably,  but  at  least  in  a  manner  that  makes 
it  difficult  for  the  reader  to  keep  the  '  structural '  view  persistently  in 


190  STRUCTURAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

sight.  I  am  only  too  painfully  aware  of  the  imperfections  of  lan- 
guage to  press  this  point,  although  I  cannot  overlook  it  nor  fail  to  see 
its  influence  in  wrecking  his  own  argument.  I  will,  therefore,  sup- 
plement it  by  saying  that  perhaps  he  ought  to  be  held  responsible  (/5) 
only  for  the  use  of  the  two  4  elements '  called  with  admirable  precision 
the  sensation-element  and  the  affection- element.  These  two  things 
bear  the  weight  of  his  whole  article.  He  is  endeavoring  to  set  forth 
the  structural '  elements '  (450,  453)  in  the  elementary  mental  processes. 
And  his  result  is  (462):  "  The  affection-element  is  constituted  of 
quality,  intensity  and  duration;  the  sense-element  (sensation  or  idea) 
of  quality,  intensity,  duration,  clearness,  and  (in  some  cases)  extent." 
But  quality,  intensity,  duration,  etc.,  are  not  elements;  they  are 
characteristics  or  categories  [of  sensation  and  affection].  That 
is,  despite  his  words  constituted  (and  constituents  (p.  450)  ),  he 
does  not  analyze  the  sensation-element  or  the  affection-element  into 
simpler  elements.  Nor  are  the  sensation-element  and  the  affection- 
element  themselves  elements;  they  are  processes  or  phases  of  pro- 
cesses. (Mr.  Titchener  uses  the  word  processes  again  and  again  on  pp. 
457—8-9,  and  he  compares  his  elementary  processes  to  other  alleged 
'processes,'  such  as  will-processes,  etc.)  Now  are  processes,  or 
phases  of  processes,  facts  of  structure  or  facts  of  sequence  ?  I  think  that 
they  are  facts  of  sequence.  Indeed,  the  very  fact  of  process  is  not  a  fact 
of  4  structure,'  but  something  more  than  this.  In  short,  Mr.  Titchener 
does  not  succeed  in  maintaining  the  structural  point  of  view  through- 
out the  central  sections  of  his  article,  (p)  Terminology  and  state- 
ment apart,  Mr.  Titchener  does  not,  in  disputation,  keep  to  his  own 
confession  that  the  4  elements  of  the  experimentalists  are  artifacts,  ab- 
stractions.' He  uses  them  as  if  they  were  real  things,  and  does  bat- 
tle with  them  against  all  other  '  candidates '  for  <  elemental  rank,'  such 
as  alleged  will-process.  He  uses  them  not  merely  4  for  scientific  ends ' 
but  for  dogmatic  and  ontological  purposes.  "  What  (459)  is  our  jus- 
tification for  looking  upon  them  ['  these  different  processes,'  preceding 
sentence]  as  last  things  of  mind  ?"  How,  I  ask,  can  an  4  artifact '  be 
a  last  thing  of  mind  ?  A  last  thing  of  mind  might,  e.  g.,  be  the  con- 
nection which  Mr.  Titchener  tells  us  always  exists  between  these  ele- 
ments, but  not  the  element  as  an  *  artifact.' * 

JI  purposely  overlook  Mr.  Titchener's  '  anatomical'  reasons  for  regarding 
sensation  and  affection  as  last  things  of  mind.  The  '  irreducibility'  test  and  the 
physiology  test  yield  different  results  to  different  psychologists,  and  would  yield 
different  results  to  Mr.  Titchener's  six  psychologists.  Mr.  Baldwin,  e.  g.,  rep- 
resenting Mr.  Titchener' s/yM  kind  of  psychology,  claims  that  the  mind  cannot 
think  of  itself  save  as  one  term  of  a  social  relation.  The  inability  of  mind,  if 


DIS  C  US  S  IONS.  1 9 1 

III.  What  I  do  find  in  Mr.  Titchener's  article  is  a  double  point  of 
view  about  structural  psychology,  (i)  The  conception  of  structural 
psychology  as  denoting  the  accredited  results  of  a  certain  point  of 
view  regarding  mental  process  or  processes,  to  wit,  the  point  of  view 
characterized  by  the  categories  of  quality,  intensity,  quantity,  duration, 
etc.  (2)  The  conception  of  structural  psychology  as  depending  upon 
certain  peculiarities  in  its  object-matter,  to  wit,  that  its  object-matter 
is  mental  '  elements,'  irreducibles  of  some  kind  or  other.  I  think  that 
the  first  point  of  view  is  successfully  set  forth  by  Mr.  Titchener  as  the 
point  of  view  adopted  by  experimental  psychology,  and,  in  general, 
it  is  my  opinion  that  experimental  psychology  should  seek  to  differen- 
tiate itself  from  the  other  five  psychologies,  not  by  its  subject-matter 
(for  surely  its  hope  is  to  treat  all  mental  processes  experimentally) , 
but  by  its  point  of  view — its  '  categories.'  And  I  think  that  the  sec- 
ond point  of  view  breaks  down  in  Mr.  Titchener's  own  hands.  This 
is  enough  for  my  purpose.  Of  course,  I  believe  that  it  will  break 
down  in  anybody's  hands. 

W.  CALDWELL. 

NORTHWESTERN  UNIVERSITY. 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  METHOD.1 

These  three  articles  of  Mr.  McDougall  (read  as  papers  before  the 
Aristotelian  Society,  London)  seem  to  have  an  undoubted  relevancy 
and  utility  at  the  present  time,  when  the  subject  of  psychological 
method  is  for  various  reasons  being  actively  discussed.  They  accom- 
plish their  purpose,  if  by  method  we  mean  (with  Mr.  McDougall) 
not  so  much  ways  and  means  of  going  to  work  in  psychology,  but  the 
method  of  conceiving  the  scope  of  psychology  and  of  psychological 
processes.  By  their  contention  that  there  can  be  '  no  complete  science 
of  conscious  processes'  as  such,  they  will  be  welcome  to  the  experi- 
mentalists ;  while,  by  their  view  of  the  dynamic  function  of  conscious- 
ness and  of  the  efficient  or  active  relation  sustained  by  '  conscious '  to 
4  neural '  process,  they  will  gratify  the  opponents  of  what,  in  the  re- 
real,  is  a  last  thing  about  the  mind,  just  as  much  as  the  perception  of  color.  In 
one  regard  it  is  a  '  complex'  fact ;  in  another  it  is  a  simple  and  irreducible  fact. 
The  physiology  test,  again,  yields  the  fact  of  function  as  a  last  thing  about 
mind.  A  physiological  expert,  e.  g.,  Mr.  J.  S.  Haldane,  insists  (Nin.  Cent., 
Sept.,  '98)  on  the  difference  between  physiological  and  mechanical  process,  by 
holding  that  physiology  studies  vital  functions.  All  this  shows  that  no  one 
kind  of  psychology  is  entitled  to  talk  about  the  last  things  of  mind. 

1  A  Contribution  towards  an  Improvement  in  Psychological  Method.  W- 
McDougall.  Mind,  New  Series,  Nos.  25,  26,  27,  January,  April,  July,  1898. 


192  STRUCTURAL   PSYCHOLOGY. 

gion  of  mind,  since  the  days  of  Leibnitz,  has  been  called  automatism. 
They  provide,  in  other  words,  for  the  unification  of  our  conceptions 
regarding  the  relation  of  '  conscious '  to  '  neural '  process.  Let  me 
outline  the  argument. 

Leading  psychologists  of  to-day  (<?.  g.,  Ward,  James,  Stout),  of 
course,  recognize  in  their  writings  functions  of  the  mind  instead  of 
faculties  of  the  soul,  and  they  also  allow  of  the  existence  of  processes 
not  easily  recognizable  by  direct  introspection  and,  in  fact,  usually 
discoverable  only  by  inference.  They  do  not,  however,  set  forth 
clearly  the  relation  of  the  'unconscious  constituent'  (Stout)  to  the 
flow  of  mental  activity  or  to  the  ordinary  presentations  (Ward)  of 
the  mind.  The  doctrine  of  the  simple  concomitance  of  mental  and 
neural  process  as  represented  by  various  writers  is  objectionable  for 
two  reasons:  (i)  it  cannot  be  brought  into  relation  with  our  general 
conception  of  causal  sequence;  (2)  the  teleological  reason  that  any 
phenomenon  (consciousness,  in  the  present  instance)  that  constantly  ap- 
pears in  any  group  of  animals  has  a  part  to  play  in  the  development 
of  the  individual  or  the  species.  There  are  various  forms  of  the  con- 
comitance or  the  parallelism  doctrine,  but  they  are  all  unsatisfactory. 

What,  then,  to  simplify  matters,  are  the  conditions  of  the  occur- 
rence of  consciousness  in  terms  of  neural  process?  The  answer  is 
that  consciousness  seems  to  occur  wherever  new  experience  has  to  be 
acquired.  Experience  means  the  establishment  of  new  relations 
among  nerve  cells  and  their  processes ;  it  is  the  establishment  of  new 
relations  among  neurons.  This  view  is  tested  by  careful  analysis  and 
illustration  in  Mr.  McDougall's  second  article.  The  nervous  system 
of  a  mammal  seems  to  consist  of  superposed  systems  of  reflex  paths, 
together  with  a  great  mass  of  neurons  (i.  <?.,  nerve  cells  and  their  pro- 
cesses) at  the  top  of  the  systems,  not  yet  or  only  imperfectly  organized 
into  reflex  paths.  His  biological  and  physiological  theory  of  conscious 
process  is  in  agreement  with  Stout's  doctrine  of  apperception  as  the 
process  by  which  a  mental  system  appropriates  a  new  element  or 
otherwise  receives  a  fresh  determination.  In  terms  of  neural  process 
apperception  must  be  conceived  as  an  extension  and  further  complica- 
tion of  a  mental  system  by  the  incorporation  into  it  of  other  neurons 
and  systems  of  neurons,  so  that  the  complex  path  leads  to  a  modified 
efferent  outflow. 

The  logical  inference  from  the  foregoing  is  that  "  all  adaptation  of 
nervous  reaction  to  environment  has  been  accompanied  by  conscious- 
ness," and  that  "the  organization  of  the  simple  reflexes  and  instincts 
of  the  lower  animals  was  accompanied  by  a  consciousness  of  a  very 


DISCUSSIONS.  193 

low  kind."  In  man  the  reflexes  of  the  cord  and  lower  part  of  the 
brain  were  organized  long  ago,  before  man  was  man,  and  some  low 
form  of  consciousness  accompanied  their  organization.  The  highest 
organism  is  not  the  one  whose  nervous  system  is  most  completely 
organized  for  reaction  upon  a  limited  environment,  but  the  one  whose 
nervous  system  affords  the  greatest  possibility  of  new  adaptations,  and 
so  of  the  most  complex  and  intense  consciousness.  Consciousness, 
then,  is  the  force  that  makes  mind,  that  makes  of  neural  process  ex- 
periences. 

All  this  is  set  forth  in  Mr.  McDougall's  articles  with  admirable 
clearness  and  competency,  on  the  basis,  too,  of  much  exact  scientific 
and  philosophical  scholarship.  They  are  a  kind  of  touchstone  on 
which  the  psychologist  of  '  structure '  or  the  psychologist  of  4  func- 
tion'or  the  philosophical  psychologist  may  try  the  validity  and  the 
actuality  and  the  relevancy  of  his  ideas  on  mental  processes  or  on  the 
''positive  science  of  mental  process'  (Stout).  And  there  are  a  few 
metaphysical  thoughts,  at  the  close  of  the  third  paper,  on  the  relation 
of  consciousness  to  'other  existents'  (Shadworth  Hodgson).  I  should 
much  enjoy  discussing  these  in  another  place.  The  upshot  of  the 
exposition  is  that  no  psychologist  should  allow  himself  to  think  of  any 
line  of  absolute  separation  between  psychical  and  neural  process. 
This  is  the  simple  outcome  of  the  teaching  of  biology  and  physiology 
— sciences  from  which,  in  my  opinion  (and  it  is  obviously  Mr.  Mc- 
Dougall's), both  the  psychologist  of  function  and  the  psychologist  of 
structure  have  still  much  to  learn.  It  is  manifestly  absurd  to  think  of 
neural  process  as  a  thing  altogether  complete  in  itself  before  the  irrup- 
tion of  consciousness,  for,  as  Mr.  McDougall  points  out,  we  are  war- 
ranted in  crediting  the  simplest  organisms  with  a  kind  of  conscious- 
ness. From  the  genetic  point  of  view  in  psychology  (represented,  for 
example,  in  Professor  Baldwin's  recent  work)  we  may  see  in  our  neu- 
ral and  automatic  and  instinctive  and  l  unconscious  '  processes  the  or- 
ganization of  experience  that  was  slowly  and  consciously  acquired  in 
the  past.  The  whole  difficulty  in  which  psychologists  find  themselves 
concerning  the  relation  of  conscious  to  *  unconscious '  process  is  due, 
I  think,  to  the  old  tendency  of  thinking  of  consciousness  in  the  Car- 
tesian way  as  the  representation  of  l  representations,'  altogether  apart 
from  the  fact  of  the  activity  or  experience  process  of  the  organism, 
or  apart  from  the  fact  that  our  consciousness  of  the  self  is  not  static 
but  dynamic,  and  that  our  consciousness  makes  us  aware  only  of  the 
thought  relations  of  an  experience  process  or  content.1  All  this  has 

1 1  have  tried  to  show  this  in  my  '  Schopenhauer's  System  in  its  Philoso^h- 


194  STRUCTURAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

become  most  apparent  from  recent  psychological  discussion.1  But  to 
Mr.  McDougall  we  must  express  our  obligations  for  formulating  the 
question  of  the  relation  of  conscious  to  neural  process  as  one  lying  at 
the  threshold  of  our  conception  of  the  scope  and  province  of. psy- 
chology. 

W.  CALDWELL. 
NORTHWESTERN  UNIVERSITY. 

teal  Significance*  (Blackwood.  Scribner's,  1896.  Reviewed  in  this  REVIEW 
Nov.  i,  1896). 

*Even  Stout,  e.  g.  {Analytic  Psychology},  argues  for  the  idea  that  psy- 
chology may  be  considered  as  '  the  science  of  the  development  of  mind.'  Else- 
where he  says  that  the  *  individual's  consciousness  is  but  a  fragment  of  the  gen- 
eral system  of  the  world.'  And  Baldwin  {Mental  Development,  p.  3)  expresses 
the  same  surprise  that  I  have  already  referred  to,  that  the  *  new  psychology  ha& 
hitherto  made  so  little  use  of  the  genetic  (or  biological)  point  of  view.'  James, 
in  his  Principles  of  Psychology,  talks  of  the  '  efficiency  of  consciousness '  in 
a  way  that  is  altogether  in  advance  of  Cartesianism  or  presentationism. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

PSYCHOPHYSICAL   AND    PHYSIOLOGICAL. 

The  Reaction  Time  of  the  Heart,  of  the  Vaso-motor  Nerves  and  of 

the  Blood  Pressure. 
Some  Reflections  and  a  Hypothesis  upon  the  Form  of  the  Capillary 

Pulse.      A.   BINET.     L'Annee    Psychologique,     1898,   pp.    316— 

^  336- 

The  Influence  of  Prolonged  Intellectual  Work  upon    the  Rate  of 

the  Pulse.     N.  VASCHIDE.       Ibid.,  pp.  356. 

The  Application  of  the  Graphic  Method  to  the  Study  of  the  Inten- 
sity of  the  Voice.  B.  BOURDON.  Ibid.,  p.  369. 
In  his  first  article  M.  Binet  reports  some  experiments  made  with 
plethysmographic  methods  in  the  attempt  to  determine  the  time  re- 
quired for  reaction  by  the  various  organs  indicated  in  his  title.  Thus, 
for  example,  with  a  plethysmograph  attached  to  one  hand,  his  subject 
was  required  to  press  with  the  other  upon  a  dynamometer.  The  point 
at  which  the  heart-beat  accelerated  was  then  determined,  and  the  time 
between  this  and  the  pressure  of  the  dynamometer  gives  the  duration 
of  the  heart  reaction.  M.  Binet  discusses  a  number  of  sources  of 
error,  which  are  numerous,  and  gives  as  an  approximate  figure  for  the 
average  of  such  reactions  1.5  seconds.  The  vaso-motor  reaction  aver- 
ages 3.5  seconds.  Other  observers  have  shown  that  the  small  vessels 
react  much  more  slowly  than  the  large  ones,  so  this  average  is  some- 
what equivocal.  The  experiments  in  pressure  were  not  successful. 
The  difficulty  encountered  [using  Mosso's  sphygmomanometer]  rests  on 
the  inter-relations  of  changes  in  pressure  with  changes  in  vaso-con- 
striction.  It  is  very  difficult  to  isolate  these  factors  from  one  another. 
The  second  article  is  dedicated  to  showing  the  inadequacy  of  the 
generally  accepted  statement  that  increase  of  pressure  causes  a  de- 
crease in  the  distinctness  of  the  dicrotic.  The  vascular  tonus,  the 
force  of  the  heart-beat,  the  quantity  of  blood  and  the  rate  of  blood- 
flow  all  play  a  part  in  the  determination  of  the  form  of  the  pulse.  A 
series  of  facts  is  cited  to  show  the  contradictions  involved,  if  change 
in  pressure  is  alone  invoked  to  explain  the  changes  in  the  dicrotism. 
Vascular  tonicity  and  high  pressure  apparently  are  antithetic  to  one 


196  PSYCHOPHYSICAL  AND  PHYSIOLOGICAL. 

another,  the  former  resulting  in  increase,  the  latter  in  decrease  of  the 
dicrotic.  M.  Vaschide  reports  his  observations,  extending  over  a  num- 
ber of  days,  showing  that  intense  intellectual  labor,  when  continuous 
throughout  such  a  period  (the  most  striking  results  occur  in  nine 
consecutive  days),  produces  relatively  regular,  progressive  decrease  in 
the  average  rate  of  the  heart-beat.  This  agrees  with  the  observations 
of  previous  investigators,  but  the  periods  concerned  are  longer  than 
those  hitherto  studied. 

M.  Bourdon's  article  is  in  large  measure  given  over  to  a  presenta- 
tion of  the  difficulties  involved  in  his  problem  of  measuring  the  in- 
tensity of  the  voice.  Apparatus  is  described  for  determining  the  force 
of  the  breath,  both  from  the  nose  and  the  mouth,  the  vibrations  of  the 
walls  of  the  throat  and  the  movement  of  the  lips.  A  table  shows 
the  results,  measured  by  tambour  tracings  on  a  smoked  drum,  of  com- 
bining each  of  the  consonants  with  the  eleven  chief  vowel  sounds  in 
French.  Both  methods  and  results  are  apparently  still  in  the  pioneer 
stage,  and  the  latter  do  not  as  yet  lend  themselves  to  any  very  sweeping 
generalizations. 

JAMES  ROWLAND  ANGELA. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO. 


Studies  from  the  Yale  Psychological  Laboratory.  Edited  by  E.  W. 
SCRIPTURE.  Yale  University,  New  Haven,  Conn.  1898.  Vol. 
V.  Pp.  105. 

The  major  portion  of  the  present  number  of  the  Yale  Studies  is 
devoted  to  acoustic  space.  Mr.  Matsumoto  publishes  his  thesis  on 
this  subject  presented  to  the  University  of  Tokyo  for  the  doctorate. 
The  value  of  the  paper  lies  not  so  much  in  the  presentation  of  new 
facts,  as  in  the  systematic  and  thorough  treatment  of  the  various  fac- 
tors involved. 

The  apparatus  employed  in  most  of  the  experiments  consisted  of 
a  spherical  cage  in  which  the  subject  was  seated  and  upon  which  tele- 
phones or  small  metallic  hammers  could  be  adjusted  at  certain  points. 
In  part  of  the  tests  a  cloth  chamber  was  substituted  for  the  cage,  in 
order  to  eliminate  the  effects  of  reflected  sound.  When  desired,  two 
sounds  could  be  given  simultaneously  from  different  directions  and 
with  like  or  different  intensities. 

Like  other  observers,  Mr.  Matsumoto  finds  that  the  localization  of 
sound  depends  on  the  difference  between  the  sensations  arising  from 
the  two  ears.  A  sound  is  localized  on  the  side  of  the  ear  from  which 
the  most  intense  sensation  is  received.  When  both  ears  are  stimu- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  197 

lated  with  equal  intensity  the  sound  is  localized  in  the  median  plane. 
The  great  uncertainty  attaching  to  the  localization  as  front  or  back  in 
this  plane  is  lessened  by  anything  tending  to  afford  differentiation  for 
sounds  from  the  two  directions:  e.  g.,  diminished  intensity  or  modifi- 
cation of  overtones  of  sounds  from  the  rear,  owing  to  the  effects  of  the 
pinnae  and  the  conformation  of  the  external  meatus.  Two  sounds  at 
different  levels  will,  if  of  equal  intensity,  be  localized  at  a  point  mid- 
way between  the  two.  When  two  such  sounds  move  from  a  common 
starting-point  in  different  directions,  the  localizations  will  take  a  direc- 
tion representing  the  resultant  of  the  two  movements.  The  confusion 
of  front  and  back  leads  to  occasional  exceptions  to  this  rule.  Judg- 
ments of  distance  apparently  conform  to  the  relations  involved  in 
Weber's  law,  z.  £.,  geometrical  increase  of  sound  intensity  is  accom- 
panied by  arithmetical  decrease  of  estimated  distance.1  The  judg- 
ment of  distance  thus  depends  upon  absolute  sound  intensity,  whereas 
direction  depends  upon  the  relative  intensity  of  the  component  factors 
from  the  two  ears.  The  discrimination  for  change  in  the  direction  of 
sound  is  most  delicate  when  the  point  of  departure  is  in  the  median 
plane  and  the  movement  is  away  from  this. 

The  concluding  part  of  the  paper  is  devoted  to  a  very  brief  crit- 
ical review  of  typical  theories  of  acoustic  space.  The  author  adopts 
what  he  calls  a  motor  theory,  in  accordance  with  which  acoustic  space 
seems  to  resolve  itself  into  a  series  of  motor  impulses  flowing  from 
auditory  stimulations.  These  impulses  develop  according  to  the  gen- 
eral laws  of  association  and  natural  selection.  Space  is  primarily 
visual,  tactual  and  motor.  The  connection  of  this  theoretical  matter 
with  the  experimental  observations  is  the  least  successful  portion  of 
the  thesis,  which  gives  evidence  of  a  deal  of  painstaking  labor.  It  is 
to  be  hoped  that  Mr.  Matsumoto  will  publish  a  fuller  account  of  the 
introspective  observations  of  his  subjects,  and  also  some  statement  of 
the  method  by  which  the  localizations  were  indicated,  e.  g.,  whether 
by  pointing,  and  the  errors  thus  involved. 

Dr.  Scripture,  in  a  brief  article  on  binaural  space,  proposes -a  form- 
ula for  the  general  expression  of  the  dependence  of  the  localization 
of  a  sound  upon  the  intensities  of  the  respective  components  from  the 
two  ears.  He  supposes  (i)  that  "the  distance  right  or  left  of  the 
median  plane  is  proportional  to  the  difference  between  the  intensi- 
ties of  the  two  components,  i.  e. ,  x  =  cd,  when  c  is  the  factor  of  propor- 
tionality "  and  d  the  difference  in  intensity  between  the  right  and  left 

1A  similar.relation  between  intensity  of  light  and  judgments  of  distance  has 
just  been  observed.  Cf.  Ashley,  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  1898. 


198  PSYCHOPHYSICAL  AND   PHYSIOLOGICAL. 

components;  (2)  *  *  *  "the  relation  between  the  distance  from 
the  median  plane  and  the  distance  from  the  auditory  axis  is  expressed 

x* 

by  v  =  me ,  where  m  is  the  distance  of  the  sound  when  x  =  o 

J  J  am 

(i.  £.,  d  =  o)  and  a  is  a  proportionality  factor."  A  complete  expres- 
sion must  provide  for  reference  to  a  system  of  coordinates  in  which 
the  three  principal  planes  of  the  body  shall  be  represented,  e.  g.,  X, 
Y,  Z,  so  that  a  localization  in  any  direction  may  be  accounted  for. 

x*  x1 

Then  x  —  cd,  y  =  me .  sin  « ,  z  =  me -  .  cos  a.     A  series 

am  am 

of  curves  plotted  in  accordance  with  these  expressions  agree  with  Mr. 
Matsumoto's  observations,  which  do  not,  however,  furnish  a  perfect 
demonstration  because  of  the  lack  of  accurate  measurements  for  the 
intensities  of  sound  employed. 

Dr.  Scripture  also  reprints  from  Science  (1897)  his  note  on  '  cere- 
bral light,'  maintaining  from  several  observations  that  the  so-called 
4  retinal  light '  is  of  cortical  origin.  The  field  for  such  light  is  single, 
not  double ;  the  figures  do  not  move  when  the  position  of  the  eyes  is 
changed,  whether  by  ordinary  rotation  or  by  actual  displacement 
under  pressure.  The  appearance  of  visual  memory  images  with 
these  figures  leads  the  author  to  ascribe  their  origin  to  some  of  the 
higher  brain  centers. 

W.  C.  Cooke  and  C.  M.  Warren  join  with  Dr.  Scripture  in  a 
very  brief  report  of  some  tests  upon  the  memory  for  arm  movements. 
They  find  the  constant  error  as  related  to  the  elapsed  interval  variable 
for  different  individuals,  for  different  absolute  distances  and  for  differ- 
ent modes  of  experimentation. 

Dr.  Scripture  contributes  a  longer  article  upon  the  principles  of 
laboratory  economy,  which  contains  a  number  of  ingenious  and  use- 
ful suggestions  upon  the  arrangement  of  laboratory  and  lecture  rooms 
and  upon  general  equipment.  He  also  expresses  his  views  as  to  the 
organization  of  psychological  work  in  the  university  and  the  ideals 
which  should  be  kept  in  view.  Laboratory  instruction,  as  distinct 
from  research  work,  he  would  employ  simply  for  developing  the 
powers  of  observation  and  technical  facility,  reserving  for  lecture 
courses  the  conveying  of  the  facts  of  psychology.  The  whole  article 
reflects  Dr.  Scripture's  well-known  tendency  to  emphasize  strongly 
the  mechanical,  physical  and  mathematical  sides  of  experimental  psy- 
chology, and  it  is  no  doubt  well  that  we  should  have  among  us  so  able 
a  prophet  of  technique.  The  following  sentence  deserves  to  be 
quoted  in  this  connection  [p.  95]  :  *  *  *  *  "  If  the  other  depart- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  199 

merits,  such  as  physics,  can  show  better,  brighter  and  more  numerous 
pieces  of  apparatus,  the  students  are  apt  to  draw  disparaging  conclu- 
sions. The  students  are  no  longer  a  '  class '  to  be  taught ;  they  are 
an  audience  that  must  be  led."  This  is  not  the  place  to  discuss  the 
merits  of  Dr.  Scripture's  attitude  upon  this  question.  It  may,  how- 
ever, be  safely  asserted  that  many  of  his  colleagues  will  feel  that,  with 
all  which  is  admirable  in  his  own  work  and  the  work  of  his  students, 
there  is  constant  danger,  not  always  successfully  avoided,  of  missing 
the  forest  for  the  trees. 

The  size-weight  illusion  among  the  blind  is  the  subject  of  a  brief 
report  by  J.  A.  Rice.  The  illusion  is  found  to  obtain  among  the 
blind,  and  follows  the  same  general  laws  as  among  the  seeing,  but  for 
touch  and  the  muscle  sense  it  is  less  marked  than  with  normal  per- 
sons. A  few  notes  offering  blue-prints  of  Yale  apparatus,  explaining 
the  Yale  color-tester  and  correcting  misprints  in  the  previous  volume 
of  studies,  conclude  the  number. 

JAMES  ROWLAND  ANGELL. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO. 


Subconscious  Homicide  and  Suicide;  their  Physiological  Psy- 
chology. CHARLES  P.  BANCROFT.  Am.  Jnl.  Insanity,  Vol. 
LV.,  No.  2,  pp.  263-273. 

Dr.  Bancroft,  Superintendent  of  the  New  Hampshire  Asylum  at 
Concord,  in  this  interesting  though  brief  paper  (read  before  the 
American  Medico-Psychologic  Association  in  St.  Louis,  May,  1898), 
has  touched  upon  timely  topics  of  interest  both  to  medical  juris- 
prudence and  to  psychology.  It  offers  theoretical  explanations  illus- 
trated by  two  similar  cases,  one  attempted  suicide  and  the  other  homi- 
cide, both  committed  in  what  the  writer  considers  a  condition  of  split- 
off  consciousness,  induced  most  likely  by  mild  toxic  agencies,  and 
accompanied  or  followed  by  amnesia. 

The  writer  recognizes  the  importance  to  psychiatry  of  admitting 
the  practical  parallelism  postulated  to  exist  between  consciousness  and 
neural  function.  It  is  suggested  that  the  physiological  neural  dis- 
sociation, which  the  work  of  Dr.  Sidis  has  shown  to  be  present  in 
hypnosis,  may  obtain  at  other  times,  as  in  these  two  instances, 
through  the  agency  of  poisons,  and,  disintegrating  the  sum  of  ten- 
dencies of  which  a  personality  is  composed,  cause  just  such  an  aberra- 
tion of  the  real  purpose  of  the  self  as  suicide  and  homicide  often 
present.  He  considers  that  the  action  is  conducted  on  precisely  the 
principle  of  reflex  action,  the  normal  inhibitory  faculties  of  the  indi- 


200  PSYCHOPHYSICAL  AND  PHYSIOLOGICAL. 

vidual  being  then  in  abeyance,  like  his  judgment.  In  short,  Dr.  Ban- 
croft aptly  concludes,  the  organism  has  then  for  the  time  become  an 
automaton,  uncontrolled,  and  actuated  by  suggestions  more  or  less 
subconsciously  received  in  normal  hours. 

GEORGE  V.  DEARBORN. 

On  the  Measurement  of  Mental  Activity  through  Muscular  Activity 
and  the  Determination  of  a  Constant  of  Attention.  JEANNETTE 
C.  WELCH.  Am.  Jnl.  of  Physiology,  Vol.  I.,  No.  3,  May, 
1898,  pp.  263-306. 

This  is  an  article,  timely  and  concise,  describing  work  done  in  the 
Hull  Physiological  Laboratory  of  the  University  of  Chicago.  It  is  a 
'continuation'  of  a  research  reported  by  Professor  Loeb  in  a  prelim- 
inary communication  published  in  1886  ('  Muskelthatigkeiten  als  Maass 
Psychischer  Thatigkeit,'  '  Arch,  f .  d.  ges.  Physiol.,'  XXXIX.,  p.  592) . 
An  important  part  of  the  report  is  that  wherein  the  dynamograph 
of  Loeb,  with  which  the  work  was  done,  is  illustrated  and  described. 
This  piece  of  apparatus  will  doubtless  become  common  in  psycholog- 
ical laboratories,  it  having  some  advantages  over  those  now  generally  in 
use.  It  consists  of  an  axle  to  which  is  attached  below  a  short  flat  bar 
of  spring-steel,  which  when  in  use  impinges  against  an  iron  wedge, 
adjustable  in  position  by  a  screw.  To  the  upper  side  of  the  axle  is 
attached  a  rod  connected  to  the  handle  in  which  the  subject's  fingers 
are  placed,  while  the  palm  of  the  hand  gets  its  purchase  from  a  small 
iron  post.  From  the  upper  portion  of  the  axle's  surface  a  writing 
lever  projects  to  the  surface  of  a  kymograph  record-drum. 

Miss  Welch  found  that,  when  various  sorts  of  mental  activity  were 
practiced  simultaneously  with  the  static  maximum  contraction  of  the 
hand,  the  physical  force  decreased  in  proportion  to  the  attention  re- 
quired upon  the  mental  efforts.  The  mental  work  was  various  in 
kind,  and  comprised  such  exertions  as  counting  the  conflicting  rhythms 
of  pendulums,  strained  visual  perception,  reading,  writing,  adding, 
multiplying,  etc.  By  measuring  the  ordinates  and  abscissas  of  the 
curves  traced  by  the  dynamograph  the  '  constant  of  attention '  was  de- 
termined in  each  case,  and  this  afforded  the  means  for  determining  the 

concentration  of  attention  required  in  the  various  sets  of  experiments. 

p ^ 

This  constant  of  attention  was  found  according  to  the  formula  — D^^* 

In  this  P  represents  the  maximum  pressure  of  the  dynamograph,  i.  e., 
its  records  when  the  attention  was  wholly  upon  the  muscular  work ; 
p  represents  the  maximum  of  the  muscular  effort  with  concomitant 
mental  work. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  2OI 

The  determination  of  this  constant  was  found  to  be  no  easy  task, 
but  in  case  of  some  subjects  quite  satisfactory  results  were  obtained. 
The  attention-constant  in  the  case  of  one  subject  was  found  to  range 
from  0.22  during  the  '  registration  of  the  vibration  of  a  pendulum  by 
pressing  one  tube,  the  perception  being  visual,'  to  0.585  obtained  as  a 
mean  while  '  counting  the  register  of  the  fifth  vibration  of  a  met- 
ronome and  the  second  vibration  of  a  pendulum ' — the  most  difficult 
of  the  mental  tasks  imposed. 

It  was  found  that  the  constant  of  attention  for  any  activity  increases 
with  (i)  the  effort  of  accommodation  of  the  special  sense-organs; 
(2)  the  effort  in  coordination  of  the  muscles;  (3)  the  effort  of  the 
memory,  and  (4)  the  number  of  simultaneous  ;  activities.'  It  seems 
likely  to  the  experimenter  that  all  control  of  the  body  depends  upon 
inhibition-impulses.  "  After  a  certain  amount  of  practice,"  says  Miss 
Welch,  u  and  with  care  to  have  like  conditions  in  every  case,  I  believe 
that  the  mean  constant  of  attention  for  any  mental  activity  can  be  de- 
termined for  every  subject  with  as  slight  variation  as  the  personal 
equation  in  time-reaction." 

GEORGE  V.  DEARBORN. 

The  Reinforcement  of  Voluntary  Muscular  Contractions.      ALLEN 

CLEGHORN,  M.D.     Am.  Jnl.  Physiology,  Vol.   I.,  No.  3,  May, 

1898,  pp.  336-345. 

This  is  a  report  of  a  research  conducted  in  the  Harvard  Physiolog- 
ical Laboratory  to  determine  what  effect  sensory  stimuli  have  upon 
voluntary  muscular  movements.  The  stimuli  employed  were  light 
(from  a  32  c.p.  glow-lamp),  a  sudden  sound  (hammer  falling  on  a 
tin  disk),  and  induction  shocks  on  the  skin  (of  the  arm).  These 
were  applied  by  electrical  mechanism  at  the  instigation  of  the  move- 
ments studied.  A  Mosso's  ergograph  was  employed,  the  resistance 
being  two  kilograms. 

It  was  found  that  a  sensory  stimulus  applied  just  as  the  muscles 
began  to  contract  caused  an  increase  in  the  recorded  contraction,  as 
other  experimenters  have  reported.  On  the  other  hand,  the  relaxation 
phase  of  the  phenomenon  is  shortened  by  a  sensory  stimulus  applied 
at  the  beginning  of  the  contraction. 

The  substance  of  the  experimental  portion  of  this  report  may  be 
given  briefly  thus :  The  average  duration  in  seconds  of  a  voluntary 
muscular  contraction  with  simultaneous  sensory  stimulation  is  with 
light  0.49  ;  with  sound  0.47  ;  and  with  induction  shock  0.44,  in  con- 
trast to  0.51,  0.43  and  0.38,  respectively,  without  sensory  stimulation. 


202  PSYCHOPHYSICAL  AND  PHILOSOPHICAL. 

The  average  duration  of  the  relaxation  is  with  light  0.29;  with  sound 
0.29;  and  with  induction  shock  0.33,  as  compared  with  0.61,  0.49 
and  0.51  in  cases  without  stimulus — a  decided  and  constant  decrease 
in  the  time. 

As  to  the  causes  of  these  phenomena,  Dr.  Cleghorn  suggests  that 
the  ''acceleration  of  the  relaxation  is  not  due  to  augmentation  of  the 
contraction  of  the  antagonistic  muscles,  for  the  relaxation  of  the  ex- 
tensors does  not  visibly  differ  in  rapidity  and  extent  from  the  relaxation 
of  the  flexors."  And,  again,  "the  acceleration  of  the  relaxation  can- 
not be  ascribed  to  the  sensory  stimulus  inhibiting  the  discharge  of 
motor  neurons  and  thus  permitting  the  rapid  passive  extension  of  the 
muscles  by  the  load  of  the  ergograph,  for  the  acceleration  does  not  in- 
crease with  an  increase  of  the  load."  The  experimenter  concludes 
that  in  the  present  state  of  knowledge  the  acceleration  is  best  explained 
as  "an  augmentation  of  an  active  relaxation-process  by  sensory 
stimuli." 

GEORGE  V.  DEARBORN. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

Inhibition.     H.  S.  CURTIS.    Pedagogical  Seminary,  Vol.  VI.,  No.  i, 

October,   1898. 

The  author  does  not  explain  why,  in  his  '  summary  of  the  chief 
theories  and  facts  of  inhibition,'  with  which  he  introduces  the  paper, 
he  confines  himself  to  the  psychologies  of  Herbart,  Beneke,  Taine 
and  Roux.  Are  these  the  only  psychologists  that  have  contributed 
anything  of  value  on  inhibition  ? 

Four  pages  are  given  to  Wundt's  Mechanik  der  Nerven  and  the 
physiology  of  the  vagus  nerve.  Section  II.  is  a  discussion  of  the 
effect  of  one  activity  upon  another:  Excessive  mental  work  may 
diminish  the  strength  of  the  muscles  and  otherwise  interfere  with 
physiological  function.  On  the  other  hand,  hard  and  long-continued 
physical  labor  may  be  the  cause  of  mental  stupidity.  One  activity 
may  inhibit  another,  (i)  by  its  waste  material,  (2)  by  decreasing  the 
blood  supply,  (3)  by  absorbing  nutrition  directly  from  resting  tissue, 
and  (4)  by  draining  energy  from  other  brain  areas. 

The  higher  areas  are  connected  with  the  motor  areas  by  associa- 
tional  fibers,  which  are  at  first  more  or  less  impermeable.  If  mental 
activity  has  lowered  the  energy  in  one  of  the  higher  centers,  the  en- 
ergy of  other  centers  tends  to  press  in  upon  the  area  of  low  pressure, 
and  by  overcoming  the  resistance  make  permeable  inter-connecting 
paths.  Education  has  to  do  with  the  formation  of  these  paths  whereby 
one  area  may  use  the  energy  of  others. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  203 

The  explanation  of  restlessness  in  children  is  found  in  the  theory 
hat  the  lower  brain  areas  of  the  child  have  not  yet  developed  paths  to 
the  <  rational  or  associational '  areas.  The  energy  of  the  motor  cen- 
ters has  no  chance  to  drain  off  into  the  higher  centers,  consequently  it 
discharges  into  the  motor  nerves.  By  means  of  pedometer  records 
taken  from  34  persons  of  various  ages,  the  writer  finds  that  country 
children  are  more  active  than  city  children,  and  that  activity  is  greatest 
below  six  years  of  age.  It  reaches  its  maximum  on  Saturday.  Mon- 
day and  Tuesday  are  days  of  high  activity,  but  on  Wednesday,  Thurs- 
day and  Friday  it  falls  off  abruptly  and  makes  the  minimum  on 
Sunday.  By  the  questionnaire  method  an  attempt  is  made  to  get  some 
data  on  such  topics  as  '  Sitting  Still,'  '  Restlessness  in  Sleep,'  the 
physical  and  mental  characteristics  of  the  i  Restless '  and  the  l  Quiet 
Child,'  '  Sickness  in  its  relation  to  activity '  and  ;  Excitement.'  The 
results  are  of  little  value. 

The  author  closes  with  a  section  which  he  calls  '  Pedagogical  In- 
ferences.' He  thinks  that,  since  the  motor  areas  are  to  furnish  so 
much  energy  for  intellectual  activities,  "  physical  health  and  develop- 
ment must  be  the  first  interest  of  education."  This  section  contains 
much  irrelevant  matter. 

A  serious  defect  in  the  whole  paper  is  that  the  theory,  unprofitable 
in  itself,  is  unsupported  by  facts.  What  few  experiments  are  given 
are  wholly  unrelated  to  the  theoretical  part. 

B.  B.  BREESE. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

FATIGUE. 

1.  Arbeitshygiene  der  Schule  auf  Grund  von  Ermiidungsmessen. 
F.  KEMSIES.     Berlin,  Reuther  und  Reichard.      1898. 

2.  Unterricht  und  Ermudung.      L.  WAGNER.      Berlin,   Reuther 
und  Reichard.      1898. 

3.  Zur    Ueberbilrdungsfrage.     DR.    KRAEPELIN.      Jena,  Fischer. 


Since  Professor  Mosso's  work  appeared,  half  a  dozen  years  ago 
(Die  Ermudung,  Leipzig,  1892),  a  mass  of  German  monographs 
upon  the  phenomena  of  fatigue  have  accumulated.  Most  of  these 
bear  directly  upon  the  practical  question  of  school  work  and  its  ex- 
haustive effect  upon  children,  yet  the  work  has  been  done  chiefly  by 
physiologists,  psychologists  and  alienists.  After  Mosso  the  names  of 
Griesbach  in  Miihlhausen,  Ebbinghaus  in  Breslau,  Burgerstein  in 
Vienna,  Kraepelin  in  Heidelberg,  and  Schulze  in  Leipzig  are  most 


204  •  FATIGUE. 

familiar  to  us  as  investigators  along  these  lines.  Little  has  been  done 
by  practical  school-teachers,  who,  with  directors  and  school  boards, 
are  in  the  end  the  persons  to  be  reached  if  such  experiments  are  to 
have  effect  in  the  abolition  of  unhygienic  conditions  and  reform  in 
methods  of  work. 

Scientific  interest  in  such  matters  has  now  spread  to  the  school- 
room, and  busy  masters  make  time  for  long  series  of  observations 
upon  the  pupils  under  their  charge.  During  the  past  year  two 
numbers  of  Schiller  and  Ziehen's  Abkandlungen  aus  dem  Gebiete 
der  Pddagogischen  Psychologic  have  been  given  up  to  reports  of 
such  studies;  the  one  (supra  No.  i)  consisting  of  observations  on 
pupils  of  the  third  year  in  a  Berlin  grammar  school,  the  other  (supra 
No.  2),  of  observations  on  the  scholars  in  the  gymnasium  at  Darm- 
stadt. Next  spring  it  is  proposed  to  unite  the  scattered  investigators 
of  Germany  into  an  association  for  the  study  of  children,  in  the  work 
of  which  the  problems  of  fatigue  will  assume  an  important  place. 
The  next  years,  therefore,  are  likely  to  see  appreciable  advances  in 
our  application  of  the  principles  of  hygiene  to  school  work.  Of  the 
above-mentioned  brochures  I  have  shortly  to  speak,  together  with  the 
recent  work  of  Dr.  Kraepelin,  professor  of  psychiatry  at  Heidelberg 
(supra  No.  3),  which  is  one  of  the  most  discerning  and  suggestive 
among  contributions  to  the  study  of  fatigue  in  the  school-room. 

A  sharp  distinction  must  be  drawn  between  objective  and  subjective 
exhaustion,  between  fatigue  (Ermiidung)  and  weariness  (Miidigkeit). 
The  one  is  a  constant  factor  and  corresponds  to  the  amount  of  work 
done ;  the  other  is  fluctuating  and  depends  upon  the  degree  of  interest 
in  the  work.  Weariness  is  a  superficial  fact  of  attention,  which  may 
appear,  disappear  and  reappear  many  times  in  a  day ;  fatigue  is  a 
deep-seated  phenomenon  of  nervous  exhaustion,  which  steadily  in- 
creases with  continuance  of  work,  and  its  results  cannot  be  averted, 
though  they  may  be  obscured.  Weariness  can  be  induced  in  a  fresh 
subject  by  dull  work,  monotony,  stale  familiarity,  while  the  capacity 
for  work,  as  expressed  in  the  ergographic  record,  or  by  refinement  of 
skin  sensibility,  continues  unabated.  Change  the  topic  of  study,  sub- 
stitute another  teacher,  adopt  a  picturesque  method,  and  the  pupil's 
weariness  vanishes.  No  such  easy  recovery  from  fatigue  is  possible ; 
it  can  be  removed  only  by  rest,  food,  sleep,  and  light  exercise  in  the 
open  air.  Weariness  may  abate  as  fatigue  increases ;  the  subject 
frequently  appears  fresher  at  the  end  of  a  piece  of  work  than  in  the 
middle,  and  his  zest  of  accomplishment  is  manifested  in  a  reduction 
in  the  fatigue  curve  itself.  But  that  it  is  not  a  permanent  refreshment 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  205 

is  shown  by  the  rapid  and  extensive  increase  in  fatigue  subsequent  to 
the  completion  of  the  work.  Fatigue  means  a  reduction  in  the  total 
effective  force  of  the  individual,  which  can  be  discriminated  and 
measured  ;  weariness  is  a  fluctuating  personal  attitude  which  is  scarcely 
susceptible  of  record  in  any  form.  In  the  study  of  fatigue,  therefore, 
we  have  to  seek  for  the  phenomena  of  actual  reduction  in  capacity  for 
productive  work ;  and  from  its  effects  we  must  discriminate  the  fac- 
tors of  interest  and  weariness. 

This  makes  the  question  of  method  an  important  one.  The  phe- 
nomenon to  be  measured  is  the  reduction  in  central  nervous  tonicity 
which  marks  successive  periods  of  school  work.  There  is  no  practi- 
cal way  of  observing  this  directly ;  indirect  forms  of  measurement 
must,  therefore,  be  resorted  to.  These  fall  into  two  general  groups, 
depending  upon  the  different  ways  in  which  central  nervous  activity  is 
expressed :  first,  mental,  in  fixation  of  the  attention,  with  its  complica- 
tions in  memory,  judgment  and  the  like ;  and  second,  physical,  in 
muscular  innervation.  The  physical  method  of  measuring  fatigue 
was  adopted  by  the  pioneer  in  the  study,  Professor  Mosso,  whose 
records  were  taken  in  the  form  of  dynamometric  tracings  of  the  ergo- 
graph.  This  test,  while  it  is  open  to  the  objection  that  it  involves  too 
cumbrous  apparatus  for  wide  use,  yet  continues  to  be  one  of  the  most 
reliable  methods  which  have  yet  been  devised. 

The  mental  test,  on  the  other  hand,  has  been  extensively  applied. 
It  is  Kraepelin's  method  and  the  method  of  Burgerstein,  Haser,  Kem- 
sies  and  many  others.  The  form  may  vary  widely  :  firstly,  in  the  char- 
acter of  the  work  required,  which  may  be  either  a  long  series  of  simple 
examples  (v.  Laser,  Holmes,  Richter) ,  or  a  few  pieces  of  more  diffi- 
cult work  (v.  Sikorsky,  Friedrich,  Kemsies  )  ;  and  secondly,  in  the 
method  of  measuring  fatigue,  which  may  be  either  by  the  decrease  in 
the  rapidity  with  which  the  work  is  done  or  by  the  increase  in  the 
number  of  errors  which  occur.  A  test  which  has  been  called  the 
combination  method  was  devised  by  Ebbinghaus,  who  used  para- 
graphs of  text  from  which  here  and  there  words  had  been  erased. 
The  subjects  were  required  to  fill  in  all  the  blanks,  within  a  given 
time,  with  words  which  made  sense  with  the  context.  Measurement 
was  by  the  number  of  errors  occurring.  The  apparatus  for  all  such 
mental  tests  is  simple ;  it  requires  only  the  preparation  of  a  set  of 
arithmetical  problems  or  the  mutilating  of  a  printed  page.  Its  method 
of  reading  results  is  likewise  easy,  since  it  consists  in  a  mere  counting 
and  averaging  of  errors.  The  truth  of  its  interpretations  is,  however, 
by  no  means  so  certain.  The  test  does  not  get  at  the  phenomenon  to  be 


206  FATIGUE. 

studied  at  all  directly  or  unequivocably,  unless  the  distinction  between 
fatigue  and  weariness  is  to  be  overlooked  altogether.  The  material 
from  which  the  results  are  read  is  the  product  of  the  total  set  of  mental 
conditions  obtaining  at  the  time  of  the  investigation,  and  the  number 
of  errors  in  any  given  case  will  as  readily  be  affected  by  a  feeling  of 
rivalry  between  the  pupils  or  by  a  momentary  distraction  as  by  the 
influence  of  fatigue  itself.  These  influences  cannot  unconditionally  be 
set  down  as  constant  factors,  which  are,  therefore,  eliminable.  The 
anticipation  of  recess  or  the  conclusion  of  work  may  very  well  be 
potent  in  establishing  a  law  of  rhythmical  increase  and  decrease  in  the 
number  of  errors,  which  will  well  combine  with  the  actual  exhaustion 
effects  to  produce  a  curve  which  does  not  at  all  truly  represent  the 
rise  in  fatigue.  The  results  of  practice,  likewise,  interfere  with  the 
purity  of  the  fatigue  curve  when  it  is  determined  by  the  number  of 
errors  occurring. 

In  view  of  such  sources  of  error  in  the  purely  mental  test  Gries- 
bach  has  employed  an  assthesiometer  to  determine  the  amount  of 
fatigue,  a  method  which  has  been  adopted  by  Wagner  throughout  his 
experiments  in  the  Darmstadt  schools.  An  area  was  selected  upon 
the  cheek  and  jaw  of  which  the  normal  discrimination  distance  for 
two  touch  impressions  was  taken  before  school  work  began.  The 
amount  of  fatigue  was  measured  by  the  decline  in  discriminative  acute- 
ness  which  appeared  after  each  successive  hour  of  school  work.  This 
form  of  test  has  apparently  proved  decidedly  satisfactory ;  it  unites 
the  simplicity  of  a  physical  method  with  a  direct  psychological  fatigue 
factor. 

I  shall  speak  of  the  results  of  the  various  investigations  in  common. 
The  best  work  of  the  school  day  is  done  in  the  first  two  hours ;  the  last  two 
are  the  most  unfavorable.  Within  the  first  two  hours  the  majority  of 
pupils  reach  their  maximum  ;  only  on  Monday  do  the  third  and  fourth 
hours  show  better  work.  If  work  of  equal  quality  is  to  be*  obtained 
during  these  last  two  hours  it  must  be  done  more  slowly.  For  children 
under  twelve  years  the  school  day  should  not  exceed  four  hours ;  from 
twelve  to  sixteen  a  maximum  of  five  may  be  imposed. 

The  best  work  of  the  school  week  is  done  on  Monday  and  Tues- 
day ;  the  worst  is  met  with  on  Saturday ;  the  intervening  days  show  a 
fairly  steady  decline  from  maximum  to  minimum.  After  every  holi- 
day a  return  to  the  initial  freshness  of  Monday  occurs.  There  is  no 
significant  increase  of  fatigue  during  the  course  of  the  school  term, 
apart  from  the  increase  of  pressure  toward  its  close.  There  appears 
thus  an  incomplete  recovery  as  the  week  progresses,  from  the  strain  of 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  207 

the  preceding  day,  a  grave  item  to  be  considered  in  the  arrangement 
of  school  curricula. 

The  employment  of  any  given  hour  in  work  which  taxes  the  pupil 
heavily  is  marked  by  a  falling  off  in  quality  of  work  during  the  hour 
succeeding  it.  This  holds  true  in  spite  of  change  of  work,  which  is 
designed  to  relieve  the  pupil  by  calling  new  powers  into  play.  Change 
of  work  is  held  to  be  rest ;  but  the  fatigue  persists,  no  matter  what  the 
new  subject  of  study  may  be.  Change  of  work  is  recreation  only 
when  the  new  occupation  calls  into  activity  a  fresh  set  of  powers,  that 
is,  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  rest.  Such  a  method  may  easily  be  applied 
to  obtain  relief  from  physical  labor;  it  is  to  be  doubted  if  it  can  be 
successfully  employed  as  a  means  of  release  from  mental  strain.  The 
facts  cited  point  to  the  conclusion  that  mental  work  of  every  kind  is 
accompanied  by  general  and  not  localized  central  fatigue,  and  it  is 
questionable  if  new  faculties  can  be  appealed  to.  The  fact  of  clearly 
defined  fatigue,  upon  which  Wagner  lays  especial  stress,  bears  directly 
against  such  a  conclusion.  All  mental  work  involves  fatigue  of  all 
and  every  part  of  the  pupil's  faculties,  and  there  appears  no  absolute 
escape  from  it  by  variation  of  studies.  Only  rest  will  reach  it,  and  to 
this  end  both  Wagner  and  Kemsies  recommend  the  introduction  of  ten- 
minute  pauses  at  the  conclusion  of  each  hour's  work. 

Four  types  of  subject  are  to  be  discriminated :  (I.)  What  may  be 
called  the  normal,  marked  by  a  relatively  brief  rise  in  efficiency  at- 
tributable to  elimination  of  initial  distraction,  which  is  followed  by  a 
continuing  depression,  the  curve  falling  away  steadily  through  increas- 
ing fatigue.  In  this  type  a  second  maximum  sometimes  occurs  to- 
wards the  close  of  the  forenoon's  work. 

(II.)  In  this  type  there  is  an  initial  maximum  from  which  the 
curve  falls  away  rapidly  and  continuously  throughout  the  day.  Such 
children  are  of  weak  resistance  and  must  be  carefully  considered  with 
reference*  to  the  problem  of  fatigue.  They  have  little  elasticity,  and 
rest  is  absolutely  necessary  to  effective  work. 

(III.)  The  third  type  is  characterized  by  a  depression,  often  ex- 
cessive, in  the  middle  of  the  school  period,  the  curve  declining  sharply 
from  the  beginning  till  mid-forenoon,  and  there  rising  toward  a  sec- 
ondary maximum  during  the  following  period.  This  type  resembles 
the  preceding  in  its  low  resistance,  but  differs  from  it  in  its  elasticity. 
The  recess  almost  restores  its  initial  tonicity.  Easily  fatigued,  it 
readily  recovers  from  depression,  and  the  problem  of  fatigue  is  here 
less  grave  than  with  those  in  whom  the  depression,  more  slowly  mani- 
fested, is  much  more  permanent.  In  this  type  the  second  maximum 


208  TIME-SENSE. 

is  usually  reached  before  the  close  of  a  four-hour  school  session,  and 
the  last  working  period  is  marked  by  a  rapid  increase  of  fatigue. 

(IV.)  This  type,  which  Dr.  Wagner  calls  the  neuropathic  group, 
is  marked  by  a  uniform  initial  depression,  from  which  the  curve  of  effi- 
ciency rises  irregularly  and  rather  slowly  towards  a  maximum,  which 
in  most  cases  is  reached  before  the  close  of  the  forenoon's  work.  In 
all  four  types  the  maximum  is  followed  by  a  rapid  increase  in  fatigue, 
which  reaches  its  extreme  form  in  the  neuropathic  group.  Here  the 
breaking  strain  comes  swiftly,  and  if  work  be  continued  for  any  length 
of  time  after  the  reaction  sets  in  it  is  liable  to  issue  in  sudden  extreme 
exhaustion.  This  type  is  deceptive  and  needs  the  closest  care. 

The  relation  of  individual  studies  to  the  problem  of  fatigue  is  of 
minor  importance.  Every  discipline  in  turn  may  be  made  refreshing  or 
fatiguing.  The  personality  of  the  teacher  counts  for  immensely  more 
than  the  nature  of  the  material.  Nevertheless,  considered  in  themselves 
a  scale  of  values  may  be  made  out.  Mathematics  and  Classics  stand 
high  in  all  the  lists ;  singing,  drawing  and  religion  come  far  down,  as 
does  also  the  study  of  German.  That  is,  studies  which  demand  close 
application  tax  the  pupil  heavily,  while  those  in  which  practice  and 
mechanical  routine  can  play  a  part  are  marked  by  slight  fatigue. 
Gymnastic  exercise,  instead  of  being  recuperative,  ranks  among  the 
most  fatiguing  forms  of  school  work.  Only  light  exercise  is  recreation. 
Even  the  recess  period  is  marked  by  deep  fatigue  in  those  who  in- 
dulge in  violent  exercise.  Instead  of  the  customary  intervention,  the 
various  investigators  agree  in  recommending  a  shorter  pause  after 
each  hour's  work,  during  which  noisy  games  shall  be  discouraged 
and  the  children  taught  to  seek  rest,  fresh  air  and  gentle  movement. 
In  these  lies  the  solution  of  the  problem  of  fatigue  in  school. 

R.  MACDOUGALL. 
HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 


TIME-SENSE. 

Zur  Psychologic  der  Zcitanschauung.     F.   SCHUMANN.     Zeitsch. 
f.  Psych,  und  Phys.  d.  Sinnesorgane,  Vol.  XVII.,  pp.  106-148. 

Zur  Schdtzung  leerer,   von  einfachen  Sc/ialleindruckeiz  begreuzter 
Zeiten.     F.   SCHUMANN.     Zeitsch.  f.   Psych,  und  Phys.   d.   Sin- 
nesorgane, Vol.  XVIII.,  pp.  1-48. 
The  first  article  opens  with  six  pages  of  quotation  from  Professor 

G.  E.  Miiller's  dictata    on   time-perception.     A  brief    review  of   the 

general  theory  there  announced  is  as  follows :    All  sensation  qualities 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  209 

are  capable  of  certain  modifications.  For  example,  a  given  tonal 
quality  may  undergo  modifications  in  intensity  and  in  clang-color.  Some 
of  these  modifications  are  of  such  a  character  that  they  cannot  appear 
at  the  same  time  in  the  same  quality:  for  example,  a  high  and  a  low 
intensity.  The  result  is  that  we  form  a  complex  idea  of  the  quality, 
which  contains  a  series  of  possible  modifications  in  intensity.  In  the 
case  of  a  second  quality  we  form  a  similar  complex  idea,  which  also 
contains  a  series  of  modifications  in  intensity  which  are  the  same  as  those 
in  the  first  case.  We  come  in  this  way  to  isolate  the  notion  of  intensity. 
It  is  in  reality  only  a  kind  of  modification  of  sensation  quality ;  it  is  not 
independent  in  the  mind.  Time  is  analogous  to  intensity.  The  differ- 
ence is  that  in  the  case  of  time  we  must  deal  not  with  a  single  sensa- 
tion, but  with  a  complex  idea  including  two  or  more  sensations,  and 
we  have  in  this  case  not  a  uniform  mode  of  modification,  but  a  uniform 
relation  between  qualities.  The  relation  may  be  recognized  because 
more  than  one  set  of  qualities  appear  in  the  same  relation.  But 
the  knowledge  of  temporal  changes  is  not  the  result  of  a  special  relating 
activity  which  is  outside  of  the  ideas  themselves.  The  whole  group 
of  sensations  is  held  together  by  the  mind  in  a  certain  relation,  and 
this  relation  is  essential  to  the  formation  of  the  idea.  Its  recognition 
is  due  to  its  recurrence  with  different  groups  of  qualities. 

This  general  theory  of  Miiller's,  Schumann  attempts  to  elaborate 
and  defend.  First,  time  is  not  a  special  content  distinct  from  the  sen- 
sation factors.  In  general,  the  discovery  of  differences  between  simple 
ideas,  as,  for  example,  the  difference  between  two  shades  of  gray,  is  not 
due  to  a  separate  content  corresponding  to  the  difference.  The  whole 
process  is  made  up  of  two  sensations  and  the  immediately  resulting 
judgment  of  difference.  Introspection  reveals  nothing  further.  Even 
the  assumption  of  a  comparing  activity  finds  no  justification  through 
introspection.  The  comparing  activity  is  not  something  different  from 
the  joint  apprehension.  In  cases  where  the  difference  is  difficult  to 
perceive  and  conscious  effort  is  present,  the  apparent  comparison  is 
merely  a  higher  degree  of  attention,  unless,  indeed,  the  mind  makes 
use  of  secondary  aids  in  the  formation  of  the  judgment. 

Secondly,  there  is  no  need  of  assuming  that  for  the  formation  of  a 
temporal  judgment  both  sensational  elements  must  be  simultaneously 
present  in  consciousness.  Of  course,  the  first  impression  must  leave 
its  trace,  but  this  is  not  a  conscious  idea ;  it  is  much  rather  to  be  thought 
of  as  a  physiological  trace.  There  is  no  other  possibility  of  immediate 
perception  of  duration,  for  if  we  require  a  conscious  comparison  then 
the  judgment  becomes  mediate.  Thirdly,  the  psychical  present  is  never 


2 1 0  TIME-SENSE. 

a  point ;  it  is  a  line,  and  as  a  psychical  process  must  be  regarded  as  a 
complex  of  greater  or  less  duration. 

The  assumption  of  a  form-quality  or  of  a  form-feeling  is  opposed, 
on  the  ground  that  introspection  shows  no  such  factors  and  it  is  not 
required.  The  remainder  of  this  article  and  the  whole  of  the  second 
are  devoted  to  a  defense  of  the  author's  earlier  results  and  explanations 
against  the  attacks  of  other  investigators,  particularly  Meumann. 

Estimation  of  intervals  depends  on  the  secondary  data  of  expecta- 
tion and  surprise  which  arise  when  the  given  interval  does  not  corre- 
spond to  that  for  which  attention  is  i  set.'  This  position  is  supported 
by  introspection,  by  the  phenomena  of  contact,  the  underestimation  of 
intervals  observed  with  lax  attention,  the  overestimation  of  intervals 
following  a  pause,  and  the  parallelism  between  the  rise  and  fall  of  ex- 
pectation and  bodily  movements. 

It  has  been  reported  that  when  the  last  of  three  stimuli  marking  off 
two  equal  intervals  of  time  is  intensified  the  second  interval  is  over- 
estimated. Now,  the  intensification  of  a  stimulus  results  in  surprise, 
and  this  should,  according  to  Schumann's  principle,  have  just  the 
opposite  effect  to  that  reported.  In  answer,  the  author  reports  ex- 
periments in  which  he  shows  that  the  common,  simple  result  is  under- 
estimation rather  than  overestimation.  In  the  cases  where  the  intensi- 
fication led  to  a  conscious  introduction  of  rhythm  the  result  was  over- 
estimation.  The  normal  results  are  in  agreement  with  the  theory ; 
the  rhythmical  complications  explain  the  others. 

The  constant  errors  of  judgment  at  intervals  of  different  lengths 
are  not  fundamental  facts,  but  are  all  to  be  explained  by  one  or  more 
of  a  variety  of  influences,  such  as  contrast  with  previously  given  in- 
tervals, accompanying  sensations  of  strain,  rhythmical  apprehension, 
and  possibly  others. 

Meumann  finds  that,  in  a  long  series,  sounds  heard  at  a  given  rate 
seem  more  rapid  than  only  two  or  three  sounds  at  the  same  rate. 
Schumann  finds  that  in  all  cases  where  this  error  in  judgment  ap- 
pears it  is  based  on  a  relaxing  of  the  attention  during  the  longer 
series.  Finally,  in  regard  to  Meumann's  results  that  a  series  of  strong 
sounds  which  succeed  each  other  at  short  intervals  seems  more  rapid 
than  a  series  of  weaker  sounds  given  at  the  same  rate,  Schumann 
finds  that  his  subjects  either  perceive  no  difference  at  all  or  else  ob- 
serve the  exact  opposite  of  that  reported  by  Meumann.  The  contradic- 
tion may  be  due  to  subjective  conditions  or  to  the  objective  conditions 
under  which  the  experiments  were  tried. 

The  investigations  of  time-perception  are  among  the  most  difficult 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  21 1 

undertaken  in  experimental  psychology.  If  one  overlooks  the  earlier, 
rather  crude  experiments,  the  number  of  valuable  treatments  of  this 
subject  reduces  to  five  or  six.  Unfortunately,  the  results  thus  far 
obtained  are  frequently  of  such  a  conflicting  character  that  one  feels 
that  the  whole  ground  must  be  gone  over  anew  before  any  interpreta- 
tion can  be  commenced.  The  articles  have  come  to  take  on  a  polem- 
ical and  too  often  personal  character  that  does  not  tend  to  stimulate 
unqualified  acceptance  of  the  statements  of  either  party.  The  per- 
sonal equation  doubtless  plays  a  very  large  part  in  estimation  of  time 
intervals,  and  perhaps  it  would  be  well  for  investigators  to  recognize 
this  fact  once  for  all,  and  not  to  be  too  hasty  in  generalizing  from  their 
own  individual  observations  or  from  those  of  their  own  '  school.' 

The  theories,  too,  are  hypothetical  in  the  last  degree,  and  must  be 
so  regarded.  It  seems  clear  to  the  present  reviewer  that  both  space 
and  time  must  ultimately  be  explained  as  recognitions  of  relations  and 
not  as  contents.  It  is  difficult,  however,  to  give  such  a  theory  an  in- 
telligible statement,  and  the  difficulty  of  finding  a  psychical  process  in 
which  a  relation  is  apprehended  is  always  difficult.  This  latter  diffi- 
culty can  certainly  not  be  disposed  of  by  calling  it  an  c  immediate ' 
process  or  by  referring  it  to  some  undefined  physiological  traces. 
The  close  relation  between  the  unanalyzed  processes  of  immediate  per- 
ception and  the  more  complex  processes  of  mediate  judgment  furnishes 
perhaps  a  clue  that  will  aid  in  the  solution.  The  simpler  process 
must  be  like  the  more  complex  in  kind,  if  not  in  degree. 

CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY, 

SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 

Zwei  JBeitrage  zur  Psychologic   des   Rhythmus  und   des    Tempo. 

KURT  EBHARDT.     Zeitsch.  fiir  Psych,  und  Phys.  der  Sinnesorgane, 

Bd.   XVIII.,  Hf.  2. 

The  general  result  of  this  investigation  may  be  briefly  summarized 
in  the  following  principle :  Whenever  a  subject  who  is  producing  a 
series  of  sounds  by  means  of  movements  of  the  hand  is  required  to 
increase  in  any  way  the  effort  necessary  to  produce  the  proper  move- 
ment, his  attention  will  be  in  part  absorbed  by  the  increase  in  effort 
and  he  will  not  perceive  fully  the  lapse  of  time.  The  result  will  be 
that  he  will  judge  to  be  equal  intervals  which  are  in  reality  different — 
longer  intervals  with  greater  effort  being  judged  as  equal  to  shorter 
intervals  with  less  effort. 

In  the  first  group  of  experiments  the  subject  produced  series  of 


212  VISION. 

movements  at  regular  intervals.  The  interval  was  left  to  the  subject's 
choice  and  varied  between  0.3  and  0.6  of  a  second.  In  a  first  series 
all  the  movements  were  of  equal  intensity.  In  a  second  series  every 
second  movement,  in  a  third,  every  third  movement,  was  emphasized. 
The  result  was  that  all  intervals  following  accented  movements  were 
longer  than  those  following  unaccented  movements. 

In  the  second  group  of  experiments  it  was  found  that  a  musical 
composition  played  without  its  full  accompaniment  required  more  time 
than  one  played  with  the  accompaniment.  Or  a  piece  of  music  exe- 
cuted on  a  set  of  keys  not  connected  with  strings,  and  thus  producing 
no  sounds,  required  more  time  than  one  executed  on  the  ordinary  in- 
strument. In  both  of  these  cases  the  subject  is  forced  to  supply  the 
part  omitted  by  an  increased  effort  of  imagination.  This  increased 
effort  absorbs  the  attention  and  causes  him  to  underestimate  the  duration. 
Ebhardt  holds  that  in  all  these  cases  we  have  to  do  with  phenomena 
of  activity  and  \vith  the  sensations  most  directly  associated  with  ac- 
tivity rather  than  with  the  more  passively  received  sensations.  But 
even  from  this  point  of  view  it  is  not  easy  to  see  how  greater  concen- 
tration of  attention  on  the  sensations  is  to  obscure  the  duration.  The 
duration  can  not  be  regarded  as  a  separate  content  which  can  be  pushed 
out  of  consciousness  by  strong  sensations  of  movement.  Duration  is 
an  attribute  of  sensations  or  complexes  of  sensations.  That  concen- 
tration on  these  sensations  is  to  obscure  their  temporal  attributes  cer- 
tainly requires  some  explanation  rather  than  mere  dogmatic  assertion. 

CIIAS.  H.  JUDD. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY,  SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 


VISION. 

S.  Ramon  y  Cajal's  Neuere  Beitrdge  zur  Histologie  der  Retina. 

R.  GREEF.     Ztsch.  f.  Psych,  u.  Physiol.  der  Sinnesorgane,  Vol. 

XVI.,  1898,  pp.  161-187. 

Dr.  Greef  gives  an  interesting  summary  of  the  most  recent  additions 
made  by  Ramon  y  Cajal  to  our  knowledge  of  the  structure  of  the  retina ; 
the  subject,  up  to  the  stage  of  its  development  here  described,  has  been 
made  most  accessible  to  the  non-specialist  reader  in  Die  Retina  der 
Wirbelthiere  (Wiesbaden,  1894)  by  Dr.  Greef ,  who  has  also  made 
contributions  of  his  own  to  the  work  of  the  Spanish  author.  The 
most  interesting  points  now  made  out  (which  may  be  added,  for  the 
English  reader,  to  the  excellent  account  in  the  System  of  Diseases  of 
the  Eye,  by  Norris  and  Oliver)  are  the  following : 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  213 

Most  important  of  all,  it  can  now  be  affirmed,  without  doubt,  that 
the  cones  are,  quite  simply,  rods  in  a  higher  stage  of  development. 
This  fact  is  very  much  to  the  favor  of  those  theories  of  the  light  sense 
which  regard  the  color  function  of  the  cones  as  a  developed  form  of 
the  rod  function,  the  latter  affording  no  means  of  discriminating  be- 
tween lights  of  different  periodicity.  That  the  cones  are  intrusted  with 
the  conveyance  of  some  more  complicated  form  of  excitation  (what- 
ever the  nature  of  the  excitation  may  be)  is  indicated  by  the  fact  that 
the  knob-like  basilar  ending  of  the  rods  is  replaced  in  them  by  numer- 
ous thread-like  expansions.  If  our  subjectively  acquired  belief  regard- 
ing the  different  functions  of  the  rods  and  cones  had  happened  to  be 
the  reverse  of  what  it  is  (if  we  had  been  induced  to  attribute  the 
color  sense  to  the  rods  and  the  undiscriminated  light  sense  to  the 
cones) ,  knowledge  on  this  subject  would  now  be  at  a  standing-still  point 
of  contradiction ;  as  it  is,  it  can  go  on  its  way  rejoicing  in  one  more 
of  those  mutual  confirmations  of  reasoning  processes  proceeding  by 
different  routes  which  are,  in  general,  the  source  of  the  confidence  we 
feel  in  our  interpretation  of  the  phenomena  of  the  natural  world. 
Even  the  latest  writers  on  the  histogenesis  of  the  retina  have  had  little 
to  say  on  the  early  stages  of  the  infra-limitant  portion  of  the  rods  and 
cones.  It:  has  only  now  been  made  out,  by  the  Golgi  method,  and 
especially  by  means  of  the  double  impregnation  and  the  rolling-up  of 
the  retina,  that  the  rods  and  cones  pass  through  a  period  (in  the  new- 
born cat,  for  instance)  when  they  exhibit  no  difference  in  structure 
(so  far  as  structure  is  preserved  in  these  methods),  and  can  only  be 
distinguished  from  each  other  by  the  circumstance  that  the  nucleus  of 
one  is  surrounded  by  a  somewhat  thicker  layer  of  protoplasm  than  that 
of  the  others,  and  so  stains  darker.  (This  is  a  stage  in  which  the  end 
members  are  wholly  undeveloped,  and  so  can  give  no  means  of  orien- 
tation.) The  question  of  their  embryonal  identity — a  question  which 
Cajal  himself  was  formerly  obliged  to  give  up — he  has  now,  there- 
fore, been  able  to  solve  in  the  affirmative  sense. 

Other  points  which  may  be  noticed  in  this  summary  of  results  are 
these :  There  have  been  many  reasons  for  regarding  the  rods  and 
cones  as  differentiated  epithelial  cells  and  not  as  nerve  cells  or  as 
neuroglia  cells — the  epithelioid  appearance  of  their  outer  members, 
their  position  as  limiting  cells  in  the  interior  of  the  primitive  optic 
cup,  etc.  That  they  are,  in  fact,  such  is  now  established  by  the  cir- 
cumstance that  in  their  development  they  pass  through,  like  nerve 
cells,  a  monopolar  phase,  but  that,  unlike  the  neuroblasts  of  His,  the 
cellulipetal  process  is  first  developed,  and  not  the  cellulifugal.  If 


214  vision. 

R.  y  Cajal  is  right,  we  have  now  a  criterion  by  which  to  distinguish 
between  the  three  classes  of  cells  which  are  capable  of  conducting 
nervous  currents :  (i)  cells  in  which  the  cellulipetal  process  is  formed 
first  (rods  and  cones,  taste-cells,  etc.)  ;  (2)  those  which  begin  their 
development  with  the  sending-out  of  a  cellulifugal  process  (the  great 
majority  of  the  multipolar  cells  of  the  nervous  centers)  ;  (3)  cells 
which  seem  to  form  both  processes  at  the  same  time  (bipolar  cells  of 
the  retina,  of  Corti's  organ,  etc.).  The  difference  between  the  bi- 
polar cells  intended  for  the  rods  and  those  intended  for  the  cones  is 
much  greater  in  mammals  the  fourth  day  after  birth  than  it  is  later, 
which  confirms  Cajal's  discovery  that  these  cells  are  distinctly  differ- 
ent.— Recent  studies  of  the  retina  of  the  sparrow  (in  which  this  organ 
has  reached  an  extremely  high  development)  disclose  a  new  form  of 
cell  (later  detected  also  in  the  retinae  of  reptiles  and  of  some  mam- 
mals) which  resembles  both  in  shape  and  in  position  the  amacrine 
cells,  but  which  differs  from  them  in  having  an  immensely  long  (some- 
times a  millimeter  long)  axis-cylinder  process.  Their  function  seems 
to  be  to  act  as  association-fibres  between  distant  amacrine  cells.  They 
are  extremely  numerous,  and  it  is  very  probable  that  the  ramifications 
of  the  centrifugal  nervous  fibres  are  spread  out  around  these  cells. 
They  may  be  called  the  amacrine-association  cells. — The  retinae  of 
birds  offer  the  best  field  for  the  study  of  the  centrifugal  fibres ;  for 
the  finch,  sparrow,  etc.,  the  Golgi  method  is  best;  for  the  thicker 
retina  of  the  dove,  that  of  Ehrlich.  Cajal  is  now  thoroughly  con- 
vinced that  these  fibres  all  terminate  in  close  contiguity  with  amacrine 
cells,  and  that  the  function  of  the  latter  is  to  form  an  important  mem- 
ber in  a  conducting  chain  between  the  brain  and  the  junction  of  the 
bipolar  with  the  ganglion  cells. — Among  the  regular  cells  of  the 
ganglion  layer  are  certain  others  which  are  now  made  out  to  be  true 
amacrine  cells,  but  not  in  their  proper  place — dislocated  amacrine 
cells.  R.  y  Cajal  has  before  laid  down  the  rule  that  for  the  recogni- 
tion of  the  nature  of  a  nervous  cell  one  should  not  attend  so  much  to 
the  position  of  the  cell-body,  for  that  may  vary  greatly,  but  rather  to 
the  position  and  the  relations  of  the  protoplasmic  processes  and  the 
axis-cylinder.  By  means  of  this  principle  Lenhossek  has  been  able  to 
discover  the  bipolar  cells  of  Cephalopods,  although  they  are  on  top  of, 
instead  of  beneath  the  feet  of,  the  rods  and  cones,  and  also  their 
amacrine  cells,  although  the  bodies  of  these  cells  are  quite  out  of  their 
natural  position. — It  is  more  than  ever  certain  that  there  are  nowhere 
in  the  retina  either  nervous  reticulations  or  protoplasmic  anastomoses. 

C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  215 

Ueber    Raumwahrnehmung    beim    monDCularen    Sehen.     ROBERT 

MULLER.     Philosophische    Studien,  Vol.  XIV.,  No.  3,  pp.  402- 

470. 

This  is  another  investigation  of  monocular  depth-perception  by 
Hering's  method  of  dropping  marbles  through  the  field  of  vision. 
Only  indirect  vision  was  investigated,  the  aim  being  to  find  whether 
empirical  evidence  could  be  educed  in  support  of  Kirschmann's  theory 
of  the  importance  of  parallax  in  indirect  vision.  The  results  are  held  to 
indicate  the  presence  of  a  means  of  judging  vaguely  monocular  depth, 
«ven  when  movements  are  excluded.  The  absolute  localization  is  at- 
tributed to  binocular  factors  that  can  never  be  eliminated. 

Like  all  investigations  by  this  method,  the  results  require  a  good 
deal  of  interpreting  before  the  conclusion  can  be  put  in  its  accepted 
form.  Interpretation  and  historical  review  make  up  the  main  part  of 
the  article. 

CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY,  SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 


Die  stroboskopischen  Erscheinungen.  KARL  MARBE.  Philoso- 
phische Studien,  Vol.  XIV.,  No.  3,  pp.  376-401. 
The  article  opens  with  a  summary  of  all  the  references  to  strobo- 
scopic  phenomena  and  a  criticism  of  the  results  thus  reviewed.  Then 
follows  a  restatement  of  Talbot's  law  on  which  it  is  held  that  these 
phenomena  depend.  The  only  part  of  this  section  that  is  particularly 
new  is  the  description  of  an  experiment  suggested  by  the  work  of 
Griinbaum  in  the  Journal  of  Physiology,  to  show  that  the  slower  the 
contours  of  surfaces  which  are  to  fuse,  vary,  the  less  will  be  the 
fusion  at  a  given  slow  rate  of  movement.  A  mirror  is  covered  with 
black  paper  in  which  there  are  two  small  openings.  These  openings 
are  so  arranged  that  in  one  there  will  be  seen  the  reflection  of  the 
periphery  of  a  rotating  disk  made  of  white  and  black  sectors.  The 
other  opening  reflects  a  part  of  the  same  disk  nearer  the  center.  If 
the  rotation  is  just  fast  enough  to  produce  fusion  at  the  periphery, 
there  will  not  be  fusion  at  the  center. 

The  apparent  movement  of  stroboscopic  figures  is  due  to  a  failure 
of  the  subject  to  detect  the  omitted  phases  of  the  movement.  These 
omitted  phases  may  be  brought  out  by  especially  arranged  conditions. 
Such  apparent  movement  is  accordingly  due  to  a  central  process. 

CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY,  SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 


2l6  INSTINCT. 

GENERAL. 

The   Origin   and   Growth    of  the    Moral   Instinct.      ALEXANDER 

SUTHERLAND,  M.  A.     London  and  New  York,  Longmans.     1898. 

2  vols.     Pp.  xiii  -f-  797* 

These  two  handsome  volumes  are  well  worth  reading.  The 
language  of  the  author  is  lucid  and  non-technical.  His  thought  is 
simply  presented,  although  it  has  involved  many  years  of  thought  and 
labor.  The  author  claims  full  half  of  the  book  to  be  a  detailed  ex- 
pansion of  the  fourth  and  fifth  chapters  of  Darwin's  Descent  of  Man. 
The  whole  work,  however,  is  independent  in  its  thought  and  execution. 

Adam  Smith  and  Darwin  are  the  godfathers  of  the  present  child. 
Adam  Smith,  it  is  claimed,  needed  only  a  suspicion  of  what  Darwin 
established  to  have  revealed  the  true  origin  of  our  *  moral  instincts/  He 
founded  morality  on  sympathy,  but  knewnotwhence  the  sympathy  arose. 

Mr.  Sutherland's  position  may  be  summed  up  somewhat  as  fol- 
lows:  The  4  moral  instinct' is  of  an  emotional  nature.  Intelligence 
is  a  concomitant.  A  moral  action  is  one  which  is  founded  on  sym- 
pathy. While  philosophers,  as  Schiller  says,  are  disputing  about  the 
government  of  the  world,  Hunger  and  Love  are  performing  the  task. 
These  two  great  masses  of  reactions  and  tendencies,  in  the  form  of 
self-preservation,  selfishness,  ambition,  will-power,  etc.,  on  the  one 
hand,  and  sympathy,  generosity,  altruism,  love,  etc.,  on  the  other,  are 
present  as  potentialities  in  each  human  being.  The  latter  sum  of  ten- 
dencies Mr.  Sutherland  calls  moral.  In  a  far  more  inductive  and 
thorough  spirit  than  that  of  Herbert  Spencer  or  Drummond,  he  traces 
the  growth  of  the  sympathetic  or  altruistic  feelings,  showing  how 
absolutely  necessary  they  are  biologically  considered.  Parental  care 
must  have  made  its  beneficent  appearance  as  an  agency  essential  to 
the  survival  of  the  better  fitted,  of  the  higher  gifted.  Sympathy  and  al- 
truism arose  thus  as  advantageous  variations,  securing  by  their  presence 
longer  play  and  developing  periods  (Karl  Groos)  so  necessary  in  phy- 
logenetic  development.  In  the  second  volume  the  suggestive  and  in- 
teresting experiments  on  the  temperature  of  different  animals  during 
hatching  and  incubation  are  given  more  fully  than  in  the  author's  first 
communications. 

Many  facts  are  adduced  of  the  rise  and  growth  of  parental  care, 
first  in  the  cold-blooded  animals,  then  in  the  warm-blooded  types,  then 
among  mankind.  This  growth  is  also  well  described  among  the  savages, 
civilized  and  cultured  races  and  classes.  Conjugal  tenderness  and 
fidelity  begin  only  on  the  level  of  the  warm-blooded  animals.  As  the 
sympathetic  tendencies  increase  in  the  human  races  there  dawn  the 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  217 

feelings  of  chastity,  modesty,  etc.  He  combats  with  right  Wester- 
marck's  doctrine  that  fear  and  hatred  of  incest  are  instinctive.  Parental 
care,  sympathy  and  solicitude  extend  gradually  to  the  members  of  the 
family  and  finally  to  the  members  of  the  community,  guild  and  race. 
Thus  the  stoic  cosmopolite  is,  in  some  respects  at  least,  the  acme  of  civ- 
ilization. This  feeling  of  sympathy,  so  helpful  and  advantageous,  bio- 
logically speaking,  is  strongly  evidenced  in  the  multitudinous  hospitals, 
asylums  and  similar  institutions  of  this  century.  (Parenthetically  it 
may  be  mentioned  that  Ohio  in  1894  contributed  $1,146,721  to  feed 
the  paupers  of  the  State  and  $4,175,915  for  all  charitable  purposes; 
the  sum-total  of  the  incomes  of  all  the  colleges  and  universities  in  the 
State  amounted  to  less  than  $1,000,000.) 

The  suggestive  point  is  made  that  morality  grows  out  of  the  family 
(perihestic) ,  while  public  law  springs  out  of  the  uniform  usages  out- 
side the  family  (aphestic).  Public  law  has  its  origin  rather  in  the 
hunger  tendencies  of  the  race,  in  feuds,  retaliation,  arbitration,  police 
necessities,  etc.  Thus  public  law  never  gave  rise  to  any  moral  feeling, 
but  moral  feeling  gave  rise  to  corresponding  public  laws. 

Since  sympathy  is  emotional,  an  examination  is  made  of  the  nature 
of  the  emotions  and  of  their  physical  basis  or  concomitance.  The 
James-Lange  theory  is  presented,  though  worked  out  independently  of 
them  both.  Mind  is  the  continuous  consciousness  of  sensations  and 
emotions,  the  former  arising  from  variations  in  sense  organs,  the  latter 
from  variations  in  the  general  vascular  tone  of  the  body.  The  biolog- 
ical necessity  of  fear,  joy,  etc.,  and  their  connections  with  the  action 
of  the  vascular  system  are  pointed  out. 

In  criticism  several  points  may  with  advantage  be  raised.  In  the 
love  and  hunger  series  of  tendencies  the  implication  is  that  if  one 
(sympathy)  is  moral  the  other  is  either  immoral  or  non-moral.  The 
judgment  of  the  race  affirms  that  both  are  necessary,  useful,  good  and 
moral  when  they  are  conducive  to  the  race  in  general.  That  is  the 
biological  test  of  the  ages.  The  speculative  theories  of  the  past  were 
brilliant  guesses.  As  a  general  rule  they  mixed  up  gloriously  the 
ought  with  the  actual.  The  motive,  for  example,  does  not  justify  and 
make  an  action  moral  unless  it  is  conducive  to  the  greatest  good  of 
that  particular  species  or  of  the  race.  Neither  is  the  hedonistic  doc- 
trine any  better.  The  test  of  the  age  is  not  is  he  happy  or  is  he  not. 
That  is  not  what  history  and  science  call  the  fittest  in  survival.  The 
fittest  has  been  of  various  kinds  and  forms.  At  one  time  it  is  lying, 
stealing,  might,  courage,  at  another  their  opposites.  At  one  time  it  is 
intellectual  in  its  nature  (  Kidd's  Social  Evolution  ) ,  at  another  emo- 


2l8  INSTINCT. 

tional  and  at  another  volitional.  Moral  (human)  conduct  is  that  sum 
of  habitual  human  actions  which  are  conducive  to  the  general  good. 
This  is  no  speculation,  but  the  general  test  of  the  ages.  Ethics  as  a 
science  deals  with  the  '  oughts '  of  history,  their  rise  and  fall,  the  causes 
of  their  success  and  failure.  It  deals  with  uniformities  in  the  actions 
of  men,  their  causes  and  probable  continuance.  As  such  it  is  a  part 
of  psychology  and  rests  ultimately  upon  biological  principles. 

The  measure  of  morality  is  the  measure  of  fitness  and  accuracy  of 
adaptation  or  attention.  It  is  not  a  question  as  to  whether  a  certain 
action  produces  pain  or  pleasure — upon  that  subject  the  success  and 
progress  of  the  world  have  not  hinged — nor  is  it  a  question  as  to  com- 
plexity, coordination  or  apparent  goodness  in  itself  of  an  action — for 
a  jewelled  watch  is  of  no  value  or  '  no  good '  in  sunless  obscurity ;  but 
it  is  an  important  issue  as  to  whether  an  action  has  been  of  some  value 
or  of  some  advantage  to  the  needs  of  the  environment,  present  or  future. 
Appropriation  of  property  may  be  painful  or  pleasurable ;  it  is  in  itself, 
however,  neither  right  nor  wrong.  When  appropriated  by  the  State, 
whether  from  a  willing  or  an  unwilling  subject,  it  is  considered  a  good 
act  on  this  condition,  that  it  is  for  the  greatest  good  of  the  greatest 
number.  Appropriation  of  property  for  an  evil  purpose  is  theft. 
Suum  cuique  is  a  false  definition  of  justice. 

4 '  Thou  shalt  not  kill "  either  thy  neighbor  or  thyself.  But  we 
praise  the  action  of  a  Winkelried  or  a  Christ,  who  marched  to  volun- 
tary deaths.  The  man  whose  voluntary  death  is  of  disadvantage  to 
his  family  and  to  the  community  at  large  we  call  a  suicide.  More- 
over, that  which  was  useful  once  may  not  be  useful  now.  The  tiger's 
fierce  passions  may  be  hurtful  possessions  to-day.  In  short,  morality  is 
measured  and  always  has  been  measured  in  the  great  world's  perspective 
by  the  degree  of  advantageous  adaptation.  Ethics  as  a  science  leaves 
the  narrow  anthropocentric  attitude  of  Kant  and  the  Hedonists  and 
assumes  the  wider  view  of  an  objective,  biological  standpoint. 

The  author  has,  I  believe,  failed  to  analyze  this  important  point, 
which  has  such  a  vital  connection  with  his  subject-matter.  He  says, 
4 '  Right  conduct  arises  from  the  moral  instinct,  after  due  allowance 
has  been  made  for  the  reasonable  exercise  of  the  self -preserving  in- 
stinct," p.  19.  Again,  "  As  a  rule,  moral  conduct  is  right  conduct; 
in  other  words,  our  moral  or  sympathetic  instincts  in  general  impel  us 
to  what  is  for  the  good  of  our  race  as  a  whole,  but  not  always,"  p.  18. 
That  is  to  say,  Mr.  Sutherland  does  not  fully  identify  moral  conduct 
with  right  conduct.  Sympathy  (his  morality)  does  not  constitute  in 
his  opinion  the  highest  and  truest  test  of  right  conduct.  This  point 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  219 

certainly  needs  more  careful  analysis.  Furthermore,  the  hunger  side 
of  our  tendencies,  or  as  Benjamin  Kidd  in  his  much  and  rightly  abused 
book  would  say,  the  rational  or  intellectual  side  of  our  nature,  should 
not  be  burdened  with  the  evilly  significant  term  '  selfish.'  The  modern 
world  of  inventions  and  culture  can  ill  afford  to  endure  a  speculative 
philosopher's  assertion  that  such  are  selfish,  or  are  not  conducive  to  the 
good  of  the  race. 

Mr.  Sutherland  fails  again  to  make  a  clear  and  firm  analysis  of  the 
terms  mentioned  in  the  following  extracts  :  "  that  moral  instinct  which, 
with  its  concomitant  intelligence,  forms  the  noblest  feature  as  yet- visi- 
ble on  this  ancient  earth  of  ours"  (p.  i);  "  the  moral  instinct  with 
all  its  accompanying  accessories,  the  sense  of  duty,  the  feeling  of  self- 
respect,  the  enthusiasm  of  both  the  tender  and  the  manly  ideal  of  ethic 
beauty"  (p.  2).  One  of  the  clearest  expositions  the  writer  has  seen 
of  these  phenomena  is  that  of  Dr.  J.  H.  Leuba's,  4  The  Psycho- 
Physiology  of  the  Moral  Imperative  '  in  the  American  Journal  of 
Psychology,  Vol.  VIII.,  No.  4. 

In  a  word,  the  author  has  given  us  an  excellent  treatise  on  the  rise 
and  growth  of  sympathetic  reflex  actions.  The  closing  words  of  his 
introductory  remarks  are  significant :  "  Hence  the  moral  instinct  is  not 
an  instinct  of  right  conduct,  a  thing  which  has  no  existence,  but  an  in- 
stinct, mainly  sympathetic,  which  we  find  it  conducive  to  man's  highest 
good  to  encourage,  by  giving  to  the  actions  which  it  prompts  the  ap- 
proving name  of  right  conduct"  (p.  19). 

ARTHUR  ALLIN. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  COLORADO. 

The    Instincts   and   Habits  of  the  Solitary    Wasps.     GEORGE  W. 
PECKHAM  and  ELIZABETH  G.   PECKHAM.     Madison,  Wis.,  Pub- 
lished by  the  State.      1898.     Pp.  245.      With  Plates. 
This  work,  as  the  record  of  careful  and  patient  observation  of 
forty-five  species  of  solitary  wasps,  is  of  considerable  interest  to  the 
comparative  psychologist.     The  authors  find  these  wasps  to  have  large 
variability,  individuality  and  intelligence.      "The  social  hymenoptera 
are  born  into  a  community,  and  their  mental  processes  may  be  modi- 
fied and  assisted  by  education  and  imitation,  but  the  solitary  wasp  (with 
rare  exceptions)  comes   into  the  world  absolutely  alone.     It  has   no 
knowledge  of  its  progenitors,  which  have  perished  long  before,  and  no 
relations  with  others  of  its  kind.     It  must  then  depend  entirely  upon  its 
inherited  instincts  to  determine  the  form  of  its  activities,  and  although 
these  instincts  are  much  more  flexible  than  has  been  generally  sup- 


220  INSTINCT. 

posed,  and  are  often  modified  by  individual  judgment  and  experience, 
they  are  still  so  complex  and  remarkable  as  to  offer  a  wide  field  for 
study  and  speculation."  The  remark  about  absence  of  imitation  rather 
conflicts  with  page  228,  where  the  imitative  acts  are  made  a  distinct 
variety.  The  most  striking  observation  on  intelligence  is  that  of  one 
Ammophila  (p.  23)  which  picked  up  a  pebble  in  her  mandibles  and 
used  it  to  hammer  the  earth  smooth  over  her  nest.  This  seemed  a  case 
of  improvising  a  tool  and  making  an  intelligent  use  of  it.  The  account 
is  corroborated  by  a  report  from  an  independent  observer.  Another 
remarkable  instance  of  intelligence  was  the  hanging  of  spiders  in  plants 
to  keep  them  out  of  the  way  of  ants,  which  was  noted  in  several 
individuals.  The  comparative  activity  (pp.  150,  158)  is  also  notable. 
The  luring  (p.  115)  may  have  been  either  self-deception  or  confusion. 
The  authors'  studies  do  not  uphold  the  idea  as  to  the  wonderful 
stinging  instinct  by  which  the  wasp  is  supposed  always  to  hit  the  nerve 
center  of  spiders,  etc.,  in  such  a  way  as  to  produce  permanent  paraly- 
sis, and  so  give  fresh  food  to  its  future  offspring.  They  show  that  the 
results  of  stinging  are  extremely  variable,  and  that  larva?  subsist 
healthily  upon  dead  material.  The  authors  do  not  make  it  clear  how 
far  the  wasp  consciously  uses  its  sting  as  subjugating  weapon,  aiming 
at  large  and  vital  parts,  or  whether  it  be  mere  imperfect  instinct  (cf. 
pp.  203,  227,  232).  The  writers  find  no  sense  of  direction  in  wasps, 
but  their  numerous  observations  show  that  wasps  carefully  study 
localities  and  note  landmarks,  and  yet  frequently  lose  their  nests. 
(Yet  here  again  there  is  not  complete  consistency,  cf.  pp.  60  and  8.) 
The  psychological  analysis  is  not  as  clear  and  thorough  as  we  could 
wish.  There  is  too  much  careless  writing  of  this  sort:  "Just  here 
must  be  told  the  story  of  one  little  wasp  whose  individuality  stands  out 
in  our  minds  more  distinctly  than  that  of  any  of  the  others.  We 
remember  her  as  the  most  fastidious  and  perfect  little  worker  of  the 
whole  season,  so  nice  was  she  in  her  adaptation  of  means  to  ends,  so 
busy  and  contented  in  her  labor  of  love,  and  so  pretty  in  her  pride 
over  her  contemplated  work  "  (p.  22).  Our  general  impression  from 
this  work  is  that  the  solitary  wasps,  while  obeying  general  instinctive 
impulses,  as  stinging,  nesting,  etc.,  are  far  more  largely  than  is  gener- 
ally supposed  guided  by  intelligence  in  the  specific  applications.  It 
is  to  be  hoped  that  the  authors  pursue  their  studies,  especially  in  the 
way  of  experiment,  and  extend  their  work  to  the  social  wasps  on  the 
lines  intimated  on  page  68.  They  might  also  tell  us  whether  wasps 
numerate,  play,  and  what  emotions  they  have. 

HIRAM  M.  STANLEY. 
LAKE  FOREST,  ILLINOIS. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  221 

The  Essence  of  Revenge.     DR.   E.  WESTERMARCK.     Mind,   July, 

1898. 

Dr.  E.  Westermarck  opens  this  article  by  a  sharp  criticism  of  Dr. 
Steinmetz's  theory  that  revenge  is  essentially  a  mode  of  enhancing  the 
self-feeling,  and  in  its  earliest  form  is  undirected,  falling  upon  any 
convenient  victim  rather  than  the  real  aggressor.  He  points  out  that 
the  instances  of  undirected  revenge  adduced  by  Steinmetz  are  irrele- 
vant or  tend  the  other  way,  and  he  thinks  that  the  so-called  instance  of 
undirected  revenge  is  merely  either  *'  sudden  anger  or  it  is  the  outburst 
of  a  wounded  '  self -feeling/  which,  when  not  directed  against  its  proper 
object,  can  afford  only  an  inadequate  consolation  to  a  revengeful 
man."  We  may  observe  on  this  matter  that  an  oriental  despot  in  mas- 
sacring a  host  of  non-aggressors  merely  to  enhance  his  power  and  dig- 
nity is  plainly  not  moved  by  revenge.  However,  the  running  amuck 
by  a  Malay,  or  the  assassination  of  an  innocent  Empress  by  an  anarch- 
ist, may  be  generally  directed  revenge  and  misdirected,  but  not  undi- 
rected revenge.  Certainly  Dr.  Westermarck's  contention  seems  sound, 
namely,  that  revenge  is  not  at  first  undiscriminating,  not  a  purely  sub- 
jective exaltation  of  selfhood  which  bears  no  definite  action  and  feel- 
ing toward  aggressor  as  such.  To  our  modern  individualism  much 
savage  revenge  must  appear  undiscriminating  when  it  really  is  di- 
rected to  what  it  judges  collective  responsibility. 

After  remarking  on  cases  of  revenge  among  animals  which  indi- 
cate discrimination,  and  then  touching  on  the  close  connection  of  anger 
and  revenge,  Dr.  Westermarck  briefly  indicates  the  function  of  re- 
venge in  self-conservation  and  self -furtherance.  It  would,  of  course, 
require  a  volume  to  treat  properly  the  natural  history  of  revenge,  its 
culmination  as  life  factor,  and  its  decadence  in  its  primitive  forms  in 
the  highest  civilization.  The  duel  is  survival  form,  and  I  think  the 
admiration  shown  for  a  murderer  by  many  women  in  civilization 
probably  is  survival  of  the  ancient  savage  feminine  admiration  of 
the  most  successful  head-hunter.  On  the  other  hand,  Britain's  venge- 
fulness  protects  her  citizens  in  all  parts  of  the  world,  and  fc  Revenge 
the  Maine ! '  was  lately  the  war-cry  of  a  great  nation.  Dr.  Wester- 
marck agrees  with  Dr.  Steinmetz  that  strict  equivalence  is  not  a  gen- 
eral law  of  revenge.  He  instances  Hannibal  slaying  3,000  captives 
in  revenge  for  the  death  of  his  grandfather,  but  I  doubt  that  Hannibal 
would  acknowledge  injustice.  Revenge  gets  even  from  its  own  point 
of  view.  Dr.  Westermarck  distinguishes  equivalence  as  qualitative 
and  quantitative,  and  ascribes  qualitative — c  the  paying  back  in  his 
own  coin ' — mainly  to  l  wounded  pride,'  but  maintains  that  quantita- 


222  LOGIC. 

tive  is  determined  by  public  opinion.  "If  the  offender  is  one  with 
whose  feelings  men  naturally  sympathize  this  sympathy  will  keep  the 
desire  to  see  him  punished  within  certain  limits,  and  if  they  sympa- 
thize equally  with  the  suffering  of  the  offender  and  with  that  of  his 
victim  they  will  demand  a  punishment  only  equal  to  the  offense. 
This  demand,  in  combination  with  the  rough  ideas  natural  to  an  un- 
cultured mind  that  offense  and  punishment  are  to  be  measured  by 
their  external  aspects,  lies  at  the  foundation  of  the  strict  rule  of 
equivalence,  which  is  thus  an  expression,  not  of  an  unrestrained  bar- 
barism, but  of  advancement  in  humanity  and  civilization.  If  this 
explanation  be  the  correct  one  the  rule  in  question  must  have  been 
originally  restricted  to  offenses  committed  by  fellow-tribesmen,  as 
public  opinion  could  not  otherwise  have  been  an  impartial  judge." 
However,  is  it  not  the  natural  tendency  of  revenge  to  hurt  the  other  as 
bad  in  the  same  kind?  And  does  not  the  regulation  of  revenge  pro- 
ceed mainly  from  caution,  both  of  the  revenger,  who  fears  counter  re- 
prisal, and  of  his  kin  and  friends,  who  have  to  undertake  any  revenge 
for  him?  No  one  but  an  absolute  despot  can  afford  to  retaliate  every 
aggression  with  death.  In  savage  life  an  individual  who  always  sets 
out  on  death-dealing  revenge  would  get  short  shrift  himself ;  and  thus 
natural  selection  weeds  out  both  the  over-revengeful  and  the  under- 
revengeful,  and  establishes  a  tit-for-tat,  which  comes  to  be  natural  jus- 
tice, as  the  simplest  law  of  socialization.  Dr.  Westermarck  inti 
mates  and  asserts  that  sympathy  of  companions  as  regulating  re- 
venge moulds  moral  consciousness,  but  he  does  not  develop  with  any 
clearness  or  fullness  a  most  interesting  point  which  lies  out  of  the 
direct  scope  of  his  paper.  Certainly,  a  simpler  solution  of  the  duty- 
consciousness  lies  in  the  revenge  become  not  merely  impulsive,  but 
compulsive,  at  urging  of  wife,  children  and  relatives,  a  duty  to  be 
done. 

With  some  remarks  on  intention  in  revenge  and  on  the  compara- 
tive method  of  study,  Dr.  Westermarck  closes  a  paper  which  certainly 
advances  our  knowledge  of  the  subject,  but  which  on  some  points  is 
more  suggestive  than  conclusive. 

HIRAM  M.  STANLEY. 

LAKE  FOREST,  ILLINOIS. 

An  Introductory  Logic.     JAMES  EDWIN  CREIGHTON.     New  York, 
The  Macmillan  Company.     1898.     Pp.  vii+387- 
In  this  volume  Professor  Creighton  has  presented  very  clearly  the 
essentials  of  the  traditional  logic,  which  at  the  same  time  he  has  sup- 
plemented with  an  admirable  statement  of  the  salient  features  of  the 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  223 

modern  logic.  An  introductory  outline  of  his  treatment  of  the  subject 
is  followed  by  a  brief  historical  sketch  which  serves  to  indicate  the 
several  phases  through  which  logic  in  its  development  has  passed. 
This  gives  to  the  student  at  the  very  beginning  a  point  of  view  and  a 
general  conception  of  the  scope  of  the  subject.  It  also  tends  to  stimu- 
late his  interest  in  the  following  portions  of  the  book.  The  author 
divides  the  subject-matter  into  three  parts  :  the  first  treats  of  the  deduc- 
tive logic  ;  the  second,  of  the  inductive  ;  and  the  third,  of  the  general 
theory  of  logic. 

The  first  part  begins  with  a  general  account  of  the  syllogism,  reserv- 
ing, however,  for  a  subsequent  chapter  the  detailed  discussion  concern- 
ing the  specific  rules  of  the  syllogism  and  their  application.  This  pro- 
cedure seems  to  me  to  be  a  very  happy  one,  as  it  opens  up  the  subject 
at  that  point  which  is  most  familiar  to  those  who  have  never  studied 
logic,  and  yet  who,  in  a  vague  way  at  least,  have  some  notion  of  the 
inferential  processes  which,  to  their  minds,  it  may  be,  are  almost,  if  not 
altogether,  synonymous  with  logic  itself.  Thus  starting  on  somewhat 
familiar  ground,  this  much  is  gained,  that  the  student  is  not  at  the 
outset  deterred  by  the  array  of  definitions  which  in  most  text-books 
on  formal  logic  seem  to  block  the  way  to  the  heart  of  the  subject. 
Though  it  may  not  be  as  strictly  logical  a  procedure,  yet  for  pedagogi- 
cal reasons  it  is  better  to  begin  at  the  center  with  some  idea  of  the 
meaning  of  inference,  and  thence  work  towards  the  elementary 
material  which  environs  it.  Throughout  the  treatment  of  the  deduc- 
tive logic  there  is  a  clearness  of  statement,  and  also  a  due  sense  of 
proportion  in  passing  over,  with  but  a  brief  mention,  such  portions 
as  have  historical  rather  than  present  interest  either  of  a  specula- 
tive or  of  a  practical  nature,  as,  for  instance,  the  subject  of  reduction. 
Professor  Creighton's  illustrations  and  examples  are  not  of  the  con- 
ventional order,  and,  therefore,  they  do  not  leave  the  impression 
which  traditional  examples  in  logic  so  often  do  leave,  namely,  that 
syllogistic  reasoning  has  no  counterpart  in  the  actual  inferences  of 
everyday  life. 

In  the  author's  exposition  of  the  inductive  logic  we  find  that  the 
practical  procedure  in  inductive  investigation  is  kept  prominently  in 
view,  and  the  various  methods  of  research  are  clearly  explained  in  the 
concrete  by  giving  a  number  of  appropriate  examples  of  actual  ex- 
periments whose  results  have  materially  augmented  the  wealth  of 
scientific  knowledge. 

Professor  Creighton's  classification  of  the  inductive  methods 
seems  to  me  to  be  somewhat  at  fault.  He  divides  the  methods  into 


224  LOGIC. 

those  of  observation  and  those  of  explanation ;  the  former  embrace  the 
methods  of  enumeration,  of  statistics  and  of  causal  determination ;  and 
the  latter,  the  methods  of  explanation,  are  chiefly  the  methods  of 
analogy  and  hypothesis.  My  criticism  of  this  division  is  that  causal 
determination  is  in  itself  an  explanation.  It  is  true  that  the  causal 
relation  is  generally  further  analyzed  or  simplified  by  analogy  or  by 
some  hypothesis,  but  for  the  most  part  the  hypothesis  or  analogy  ex- 
plains by  referring  to  some  underlying  causal  connection.  It  is  due 
to  Professor  Creighton  to  state  that  he  himself  acknowledges  that  in 
this  classification  the  difference  between  the  two  kinds  of  methods  is 
one  of  degree  rather  than  of  essential  nature l  and  yet  it  perhaps  would 
have  been  better  not  to  make  a  distinction  which  is  not  one  of  essen- 
tial nature  the  basis  for  differentiating  so  prominently  these  methods 
of  research. 

In  the  third  section,  which  treats  of  the  nature  of  thought,  or  the 
general  theory  of  logic,  the  author's  point  of  view  is  in  its  essential 
features  quite  in  accord  with  that  of  Bosanquet.  Professor  Creighton 
insists  upon  the  conception  of  thought  as  a  living,  growing  phenomenon, 
and  not  a  mere  mechanical  grouping  of  ready-made  ideas,  and  also  that 
the  growth  of  thought  is  to  be  regarded  as  a  process  of  development 
which  proceeds  ever  from  simpler  to  more  complex  states,  according  to 
the  manner  of  all  evolutionary  processes.  He  regards  the  judgment 
as  the  unit  of  thought,  and  defines  the  concept  as  '  the  series  of  judg- 
ments which  have  already  been  made.' 2  By  way  of  comment  upon 
this  definition  of  concept,  he  adds  that  "  to  make  the  thought  our  own, 
to  gain  the  real  concept,  it  is  necessary  to  draw  out  or  realize  to  our- 
selves the  actual  set  of  judgments  for  which  the  word  is  but  the  short- 
hand expression."3  The  concept,  however,  is  not  merely  a  summa- 
tion of  a  number  of  judgments.  It  is  rather  a  blending  of  the  various 
elements  which  the  several  judgments  have  furnished  in  such  a  way 
that  these  judgments  which  have  been  operative  in  the  formation  of 
the  concept  are  implicitly  rather  than  explicitly  apprehended.  For 
there  is  such  a  thing  as  an  implicit  apprehension  of  the  significance  of 
a  whole  without  a  conscious  analysis  of  its  component  parts,  as  Mr. 
Stout  has  so  admirably  set  forth  in  his  Analytic  Psychology.  The 
function  of  the  concept  is  essentially  «  adjectival '  until  it  is  subjected 
to  an  analysis  which  discloses  explicitly  the  parts  which  form  the 
4  actual  set  of  judgments '  but  which  before  such  analysis  were  dis- 
cerned implicity. 

Professor  Creighton  has  stoutly  defended  the  necessity  of  a  uni- 
1P.  220.  2  p.  270-  3  p.  27I. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  225 

versal  element  in  some  form  or  other  as  the  ground  of  inference.  In 
this  view  he  takes  exception  to  Mill's  contention  that  reasoning  is  from 
particular  to  particular.  The  author  very  happily  sums  up  the  argu- 
ment in  support  of  his  position  in  the  following  sentences,  which 
clearly  indicate  his  general  point  of  view  as  regards  the  theory  of  in- 
ference :  u  Knowledge  sees  the  universal  in  the  particular,  or  reads  the 
particular  as  a  case  of  the  universal.  And  when  thus  interpreted  the 
particular  ceases  to  be  a  bare  particular  and  becomes  an  individual 
with  a  permanent  nature  of  its  own.  When  one  reasons  from  an  indi- 
vidual case,  then  it  is  the  universal  or  typical  nature,  not  the  particular 
or  momentary  existence,  upon  which  the  inference  proceeds.  If  there 
were  any  merely  particular  facts  in  knowledge  we  could  never  reason 
from  them.  But  the  so-called  particular  facts,  as  elements  of  knowl- 
edge, possess  a  universal  or  typical  aspect  in  virtue  of  which  alone  in- 
ference is  possible." l 

JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 

L?  Education  Rationelle  de  la   Volonte:    Son  emploi  therapeutique. 

PAUL  EMILE  LEVY.     Preface  de  M.  le  DR.  BERNHEIM.     Paris, 

Alcan.     1898.     Pp.  v  +  234. 

Dr.  Levy  divides  his  monograph  into  two  sections,  a  4  Theoretical 
Study '  and  ;  Practical  Applications.' 

From  the  theoretical  point  of  view,  psychotherapy  is  based  upon 
one  fundamental  principle  :  "  Thought  is  in  act  in  the  nascent  state; 
it  is  a  beginning  of  activity.  *  *  *  The  transformation  of  the  idea 
into  an  act  may  take  place  in  two  distinct  ways.  Either  the  idea 
becomes  a  positive  act,  i.  £.,  feeling,  volition,  sensation,  movement, 
or  it  becomes  a  negative  act — in  other  words,  it  neutralizes  the  act, 
prevents  the  feeling,  the  volition,  the  sensation,  the  movement  from 
being  realized  (se  produire).  Dynamogeny,  inhibition — these  are, 
briefly,  two  aspects  of  the  same  process."  (Pp.  13,  14.) 

Granting  this  principle,  all  that  is  needed  to  bring  about  any  given 
change  is  to  awaken  in  the  mind  an  idea  of  the  change  in  question, 
i.  e.,  to  give  a  suggestion.  The  suggestion  may  be  administered  by 
another  (81-97)  (hetero-suggestion),  or  by  the  patient  himself  (auto- 
suggestion) .  It  is  with  the  latter  only  that  Dr.  Levy  concerns  him- 
self. To  make  the  auto-suggestion  most  effective  it  should  be  admin- 
Jstered  in  a  state  of  mental  repose  (49)  (recueillement},  and  should  be 
reinforced,  when  possible,  by  directing  upon  it  any  available  emotion 

'P- 344- 


226  GENERAL. 

(55),  and  by  the  deliberate  adoption  of  such  conduct  as  the  suggestion 
would  itself,  if  realized,  inspire  (63-79)  (entrainement  actif).  The 
suggestion  should  not  be  in  the  form  of  an  effort  to  will  its  realization ; 
it  should  rather  be  put  as  a  categorical  statement  (52),  but  voluntary 
attention  should  be  concentrated  upon  it  to  ensure  its  taking  root  (32) 
(52,  note)  (128).  : 

The  same  principle  may  be  applied  to  the  realization  of  a  highly 
abstract  ideal  (Mental  Hygiene,  99-120).  By  fixing  the  concept  of 
the  ideal  in  mind  as  an  auto-suggestion  its  influence  will  be  felt  at 
unexpected  moments,  modifying  the  details  of  conduct. 

By  wz'//we  mean  nothing  more  than  the  resultant  (125),  as  ex- 
pressed in  conduct,  of  all  the  active  tendencies  of  simultaneously  co- 
existing ideas,  but  it  must  be  remembered  that  a  small  part  only  of 
these  (126)  are  conscious,  the  larger  part  being  subconscious.  The 
weakness  of  will  which  prevails  in  modern  society  (French  society?) 
is  due  to  the  fact  that  the  intellectual,  social  and  political  upheavals  of 
the  last  century  have  undermined  the  definite  convictions  which  ruled 
the  conduct  of  our  ancestors  and  have  given  us  nothing  in  their  place 
(121-125).  It  is  obvious  (127  ff.)  that  the  theory  of  auto-suggestion ,, 
supplemented  by  hetero-suggestion,  is  the  only  scientific  method  of 
training  the  will  and  developing  character. 

Such  is  Dr.  Levy's  theory.  It  embraces  much  that  is  true — although 
nothing  new — but  it  suffers  from  a  lack  of  what  may  be  termed  the 
quantitative  sense,  and  an  indifference  to  the  niceties  of  conceptional 
discrimination.  To  take  the  last  first,  surely  it  is  only  by  doing  vio- 
lence to  the  plain  meaning  of  words  that  the  tendency  spontaneously 
to  adopt  the  beliefs  of  others,  the  tendency  on  the  part  of  certain  ideas 
to  give  rise  to  the  corresponding  sensation,  and  on  the  part  of  other 
ideas  to  give  rise  to  a  movement,  are  all  subsumed  under  the  concept 
of  *  nascent  act/  which  is  strictly  applicable  to  the  last  only  of  the 
three.  There  is  an  analogy  between  these  three  tendencies,  but  they 
are  far  from  identical. 

The  quantitative  sense  is  the  ability  to  discriminate  tendencies 
from  necessary  causal  relations,  possibilities  from  probabilities,  and 
this  Dr.  LeVy  seems  to  lack.  The  facts  now  in  hand  go  far  towards 
rendering  plausible  the  hypothesis  that  every  mental  state  possesses — 
perhaps  vicariously,  as  the  representative  of  cortical  process — certain 
intrinsic  tendencies,  which,  when  the  inhibition  of  other  states  is 
removed,  would  result  in  such  determinate  events  as  the  development 
of  an  illusion,  the  suggestion  of  an  associated  idea,  the  production  of  a 
movement,  the  modification  of  metabolism.  But  to  base  upon  such  a 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  22 7 

doctrine  the  elaborate  system  of  practice  proposed  by  Dr.  Levy  and 
to  hold  forth  such  confident  hopes  to  those  who  stand  in  need  of  aid 
is  a  very  different  matter.  Such  a  leap  should  be  taken  only  after  the 
practicability  of  the  proposed  method  has  been  demonstrated.  What 
has  Dr.  L£vy  done  towards  demonstrating  it? 

He  has  conducted  experiments  for  four  (218)  months  upon  him- 
self and  six  other  persons.  We  are  told  nothing  of  the  physical  or 
mental  traits  of  these  other  persons,  although  it  would  appear  (p.  185) 
that  one  at  least,  '  C,'  was  an  advanced  hysteric.  Such  details  are 
quite  irrelevant  to  the  question,  Dr.  Levy  thinks  (217).  Nor  are  we 
told  anything  of  their  reliability  as  witnesses;  merely  that  (145,  note) 
each  one  must  have  known  whether  the  results  he  reports  were  due  to 
suggestion  or  to  coincidence.  We  are,  however,  told  that  no  one  of 
them  received  more  than  ten  or  fifteen  minutes'  instruction  from  Dr. 
Levy  (218)  as  to  the  method  of  experimenting  and  of  recording  ex- 
periments. No  record  whatever  is  made  of  the  negative  results, 
though  we  are  told  that  two  subjects,  whether  two  of  the  above  men- 
tioned six  or  not  is  not  stated,  could  get  no  positive  results  (219).  Of 
the  positive  results  some  are  given.  A  few  illustrations  taken  at  ran- 
dom will  give  an  idea  of  their  character. 

"  One  of  my  subjects,  a  merchant,  frequently,  before  going  to  see 
his  customers,  gave  himself  the  suggestion  to  succeed  in  the  business 
which  he  had  to  do  with  them.  Often,  he  said,  the  suggestion  was 
followed  by  the  desired  result"  (162).  This  is  due,  Dr.  Levy  thinks, 
to  the  greater  self-confidence  and  persuasiveness  imparted  by  the  sug- 
gestion. 

Or  an  observation  of  Coste  de  Lagrave's — UI  sing  badly;  I  re- 
sort to  the  auto-suggestion  that  I  should  sing  with  taste,  should  give 
pleasure  to  the  audience ;  I  receive  compliments  for  the  first  time  in 
my  life"  (162). 

u  I  try  to  concentrate  my  mind  upon  my  work  alone,  to  the  exclu- 
sion of  all  else  in  life.  I  note  at  the  end  of  the  afternoon  that  my 
time  has  been  much  better  spent  than  usual"  (160). 

44  After  having  grippe,  though  a  light  attack,  I  used  to  lie  thence- 
forward quite  a  while  before  I  could  go  to  sleep,  and  woke  two  or 
three  times  every  night.  These  disturbances  lasted  about  a  week ;  in 
about  the  same  time  I  succeeded  in  making  them  disappear  by  auto- 
suggestion "  (172). 

u  Trembling  of  the  right  hand  had  lasted  about  two  months  when 
the  patient  thought  of  treating  it  by  auto-suggestion.  Was  improved 
after  several  attempts,  then  definitely  cured  in  a  period  of  time  the 
duration  of  which  is  not  clearly  marked"  (189). 


228  GENERAL. 

"  Very  violent  headache,  only  in  temple  and  forehead,  with  throbs. 
Cure  very  rapid  by  auto-suggestion  "  (190). 

Severe  itching  in  three  middle  fingers  of  right  hand,  lasting  a 
week,  cured  in  four  or  five  days  by  auto-suggestion  (201). 

"Being  dyspeptic  and  having  no  appetite  I  give  myself  the  sug- 
gestion to  be  hungry.  At  the  next  meal  I  really  eat  with  very  good 
appetite"  (206). 

A  few  of  Dr.  LeVy's  cases  are  better  than  these,  but  the  great  ma- 
jority are  marked  by  the  same  disregard  of  essential  details,  and  the 
same  reckless  ascription  of  the  result  to  the  suggestion,  when  it  might 
obviously  have  been  due  to  some  totally  different  cause,  which  makes 
these  cases  worthless. 

WM.  ROMAINE  NEWBOLD. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  PENNSYLVANIA. 


ISAbsolu  et  sa  lot  constitutive.    CYRILLE  BLONDEAU.     Paris,  Alcan. 

1897.     Pp.  xxv  -f  350. 

The  '  Absolute '  is  the  immutable  universe  in  which  things  and 
thoughts  are  alike  confounded.  *  The  higher  law  from  which  results 
nature  or  life '  is  formulated  as  follows  :  "  The  mutual  relation  of  the 
elements  which  constitute  a  body  is  in  inverse  ratio  to  the  relation  of 
these  elements  to  the  environment  which  contains  the  body"  (p.  344). 
This  is  put  forth,  in  all  seriousness,  as  a  revelation  of  the  world's  '  most 
secret  resources/ 

The  only  thing  in  the  book  of  any  special  interest  to  the  psy- 
chologist is  the  author's  conception  of  the  relation  of  physiological 
process  to  the  facts  of  consciousness.  He  speaks  of  this  as  a  discov- 
ery of  'the  passage  from  physiology  to  psychology'  and  regards  it 
as  an  achievement  of  cardinal  importance  in  his  discussion  (p.  xxi), 
enabling  the  intelligence  '  to  radiate  freely  in  the  world  without  finding 
any  further  obstacle  to  its  infinite  expansion'  (p.  114).  What  then  is 
the  fulfilment  of  this  profession?  First,  a  reassertion  of  a  solution  of 
continuity  between  physiology  and  psychology;  secondly,  the  assertion 
of  a  similar  abyss  between  consciousness  made  up  of  sensations  and 
images  and  the  pure  reflecting  activity  of  the  mind ;  thirdly,  as  ex- 
planatory theory,  the  assertion  of  relatively  free  forces  at  different 
levels  in  the  nervous  system  by  virtue  of  which  sensations  are,  on  the 
one  hand,  perceived  and,  on  the  other,  reflected  on.  "  The  sensations 
and  images  are  perceived  by  the  free  force  most  directly  related  to  the 
force  subject  to  the  external  and  internal  action;  the  parts  more  in- 
directly related  to  the  sense  organs  are  now,  in  virtue  of  their  saturation 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  229 

and  the  law  of  equilibrium,  able  to  exercise  themselves  on  those  which 
furnish  the  sensations  and  images"  (p.  129).  "  Thus  the  inner  world 
is  broken  up  into  two  parts :  one  belongs  provisionally  to  the  thing 
whence  the  action  emanates,  the  other  remains  outside,  and  it  is  solely 
by  this  part  of  the  inner  force  not  absorbed,  free,  therefore,  relatively 
to  that  particular  connection,  that  it  is  permitted  to  perceive  the  sensa- 
tion, which  is  thus,  in  principle,  nothing  but  a  relation  of  inner  to 
outer"  (p.  132).  As  a  purely  physiological  hypothesis  much  can  be 
said  in  favor  of  the  conception  of  lower-  and  higher-level  centers  with 
which  related  but  relatively  independent  stores  of  disposable  energy 
are  incorporated,  corresponding  respectively  to  lower  and  higher  pro- 
cesses of  consciousness;  but  to  see  in  such  an  hypothesis — which, 
morever,  is  not  new — *  the  passage  from  physiology  to  psychology ' 
requires  surely  more  than  ordinary  clairvoyance. 

The  book  abounds  in  apothegm  and  paradox  ('  consciousness  con- 
tradicts reason,'  4  the  love  of  truth  is  not  reasonable/  etc.),  and  is  not 
wholly  free  from  contradiction  ('one  must  be  convinced  of  human 
liberty  relatively  to  the  absolute/  p.  208 ;  '  from  the  absolute  point  of 
view  there  is  no  liberty,'  p.  69;  cf.  p.  211,  4  conciousness  is  only  free 
relatively  to  things').  Its  pretensions  are  preposterous  (e.  ^".,  p. 
xix),  its  style  insipid,  its  construction  loose,  like  the  jottings  of  a 
note-book.  There  is  much  by  the  way  to  stimulate  reflection,  but  in 
the  end  epigram  on  the  absolute  and  its  constitutive  law  through 
nearly  four  hundred  closely  printed  pages  becomes  not  a  little  tedious. 

H.  N.  GARDINER. 
SMITH  COLLEGE. 


Ueber  die  Messung  der  Auffassungsfahigkeit.     LUDWIG  CRON  und 
EMIL  KRAEPELIN.     Separat  Abdruck  aus  :  Kraepelin,  Psycholog. 
Arbeiten.     II.  Bd.     2  Heft.     Pp.  203-325.     Leipzig,  1897. 
This  is  an  account  of  experiments  conducted  primarily  to  deter- 
mine the  influence  which  the  peculiarities  of  the  individual  exert  upon 
the  form  of  the  apperceptive  faculty  and  to  discover  the  common  fac- 
tors involved  in  the  act  of  apprehending.     Subjects  were  kept  at  the 
continuous  apprehension  of  printed  words  and  an  attempt  made  to 
estimate  the  precision  and  reliability  of  the  performance.     For  this 
purpose  the  region  of  the  threshold  was  used,  i.  e.,  stimuli  were  pre- 
sented to  the  eye  only  for  so  long  a  time  that  they  could  be  perceived 
in  a  number  of  cases  but  not  always  distinctly.     The  number  of  cor- 
rectly read  stimuli  furnished  a  measure  for  the  ability  of  apprehending, 
while  from  the  incorrect  readings  deductions  could  be  made  as  to  the 


230        MEASURE  OF  THE  ABILITY  OF  APPREHENDING. 

action  of  error  processes.  The  experiment  consisted  essentially  of 
three  drums  on  which  were  pasted,  in  spiral  form,  (i)  nonsense  sylla- 
bles, (2)  one-syllable  words,  (3)  two-syllable  words.  The  drums  re- 
volved at  a  constant  speed  of  24  mm.  per  second,  and  were  observed 
through  an  opening  or  slit  in  a  screen  from  a  fixed  distance.  The 
observation  slit,  5  mm.  in  height,  was  regulated  in  width  by  means  of  a 
micrometer  screw,  so  that  the  time  during  which  the  stimulus  was  vis- 
ible could  be  varied.  Three  different  widths  were  used,  5,  4  and  3 
mm.  By  means  of  a  contact  arrangement,  which  noted  the  entrance 
of  each  letter  into  the  field  of  vision  and  its  disappearance,  the  dura- 
tion of  visibility  could  be  exactly  measured.  Such  measurements 
gave  for  the  three  different  slit  widths,  290,  230  and  170  thousandths 
of  a  second,  respectively.  Each  subject  endeavored  to  read  aloud  the 
words  as  they  passed  the  opening  of  the  screen  and  the  correct  read- 
ings, errors  and  omissions  were  noted  down  in  shorthand  by  the  ex- 
perimenter. The  same  experiment  was  performed  on  three  different 
days.  There  were  six  subjects,  three  normal  and  three  pathological 
cases  from  a  clinic. 

The  results  show  surprising  differences  in  capacity  to  apprehend 
the  matter  presented.  Certain  facts  and  principles,  however,  were 
common  to  all. 

Results  of  experiments  with  nonsense  syllables  show  that  the 
greater  part  of  the  syllables  were  correctly  read,  the  number  decreas- 
ing with  the  narrowing  of  the  observation  slit,  yet  more  slowly  than 
the  visibility.  On  shortening  the  time  of  exposure  one-fifth,  correct 
readings  showed  only  an  insignificant  decrease.  In  the  normal  sub- 
jects at  4  mm.  the  limit  was  very  nearly  reached  beyond  which  a  wider 
opening  could  effect  little  improvement.  As  the  time  of  exposure 
was  shortened,  omissions  became  -decidedly  more  numerous,  while 
errors  showed  only  a  moderate  increase,  omissions  being  evidently  the 
measure  of  the  difficulty  of  apprehension.  Errors  in  which  only  one 
letter  was  misread  predominated.  The  first  letter  was  by  far  the  most 
frequently  misread,  the  last  next;  the  middle  letter,  least  of  all,  indi- 
cating that  the  attention  was  directed  especially  to  the  middle  so  that 
the  syllable  was  taken  as  a  unity.  The  difference  in  apprehending 
the  first  and  the  last  letter  is  ascribed  by  the  authors  to  incomplete 
cessation  of  attention.  The  single  syllables  here  follow  one  another 
every  i  %  sec.,  but  2  sec.  is  the  most  favorable  space  of  time  between 
signal  and  stimulus  for  the  complete  cessation  of  attention.  This 
would  hinder  the  apprehension  of  the  first  letter  to  a  greater  degree 
than  the  last. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  231 

One-syllable  words.  Results  show  a  greater  facility  in  apprehend- 
ing than  for  nonsense  syllables,  notwithstanding  the  greater  number 
of  letters  to  a  word.  The  word-idea  present  in  the  process  of  appre- 
hension is  assigned  as  the  cause.  The  number  of  correct  readings 
•sank  10%  with  the  narrowing  of  the  observation  opening  from  5  mm. 
to  3  mm.,  a  smaller  diminution  than  resulted  in  the  case  of  nonsense 
syllable  under  like  conditions.  Single-letter  errors  are  most  numerous, 
two-letter  errors  only  slightly  less.  The  initial  letter  is  almost  always 
relatively  well  recognized  here  because  a  capital  and  so  attracting  the 
attention.  The  second  letter  is  generally  indistinctly  apprehended, 
the  third  favored,  the  -fourth  neglected,  indicating  a  two-fold  rhythm  of 
apprehension.  The  number  of  nonsense  misreadings  out  of  the  total 
misreadings  varies  in  the  different  subjects  from  6%  to  31%.  From 
the  number  of  nonsense  misreadings  deductions  are  made  as  to  the 
influence  of  word-ideas.  Such  influence  is  maintained  to  be  greater 
the  smaller  the  number  of  nonsense  misreadings.  Two  classes  of 
misreadings  are  made,  namely,  those  which  occur  in  the  same  word 
again,  and  those  which  are  repeated  in  different  words.  In  the  former 
an  error  once  committed  becomes  fixed,  while  in  the  latter  an  idea  has 
acquired  such  power  that  it  moves  the  thoughts  in  a  certain  direction. 
This  is  indicated  by  such  errors  as  Heft  for  Kost,  Heil  and  Geist ; 
Stadt  for  Sold,  Stoltz,  Druck,  Stift,  Saar,  Staub,  Wohl  and  Stern, 
where  little  connection  is  apparent  between  stimulus  and  error,  but 
evidently  an  impulse  present  to  express  an  idea  whose  content  is  from 
another  source. 

Two-syllable  words.  In  apprehending  two-syllable  words  two 
subjects  showed  a  better  record  than  in  the  two  previous  experiments ; 
in  others,  however,  there  was  a  falling-off  showing  itself  in  the  num- 
ber of  omissions,  the  number  of  errors  remaining  about  the  same. 
According  to  the  view  previously  noted  this  would  indicate  greater  diffi- 
culty in  recognizing  words  with  less  liability  to  error.  The  appre- 
hension here,  unlike  that  of  shorter  words,  takes  place  by  spelling, 
giving  little  opportunity  for  conjecture  and  influence  of  ideas,  hence 
greater  accuracy.  The  initial  letter  is  again  distinctly  favored.  The 
rhythm  of  apprehension  which  was  earlier  expressed  only  in  two  sub- 
jects appeared  very  distinctly  in  others.  One  subject  appeared  to 
recognize  best  the  first  and  fifth  letters,  indicating  a  grouping  of  greater 
extensity.  The  same  misreadings  were  not  so  frequently  repeated  in 
different  words  as  in  the  case  of  one-syllable  words. 

As  a  rule  the  number  of  correct  readings  increased  from  day  to 
day.  The  improvement  from  the  first  to  the  second  day  is  much  more 


232  MIND  AND  BODY. 

pronounced  than  for  the  second  to  the  third  day.  This  the  authors 
attribute  to  the  influence  of  habit  rather  than  to  facility  gained  by 
practice,  for  the  former  exerted  in  the  control  of  disturbing  processes 
reaches  its  height  under  such  conditions  quicker  than  the  latter.  Prac- 
tice quite  generally  in  the  experiments  shortens  the  time  of  perception 
and,  according  as  the  inclination  is  to  misreadings  or  omission,  causes 
a  decrease  of  the  former  or  latter.  Fatigue,  which  appears  to  stand  in 
close  relation  to  practice,  develops  the  opposite  effects,  yet,  on  account 
of  the  changing  conditions  of  work  and  the  short  time  of  the  experi- 
ment, its  effect  was  limited. 

From  the  results  obtained  conclusions  are  drawn  as  to  the  differ- 
ent influences  which  determine  the  formation  of  the  process  of  appre- 
hension. Such  influences  are:  (i)  quickness  of  perception,  which 
determines  the  distinctness  of  the  impressions;  (2)  articulation  of  ap- 
prehension, which  determines  the  clearness  of  the  constituent  parts  of 
the  impression ;  (3)  sensuous  precision  of  perception  and  influence  of 
ideas, which  affect  the  reliableness  of  apprehension ;  (4)  the  more  or  less 
striving  or  effort  to  make  the  best  possible  record,  which  leads  to  the 
suppression  of  readings  felt  to  be  erroneous ;  (5 )  practice  and  fatigue ; 
(6)  memory,  noticeable  in  the  frequent  return  of  the  same  misreading 
in  the  same  word. 

The  combined  effect  of  these  conditions  occurring  with  different 
strength  in  the  individual  observers  determines  the  aptness  of  appre- 
hension. In  closing,  a  characterization  of  the  different  subjects  is 
made  on  the  basis  of  the  proportion  and  combination  of  those  influ- 
ences appearing  in  the  investigation.  ~ 

_L<.   \-s •   JONKS. 

YALE  UNIVERSITY. 

Aussenwelt  und  Innenwelt,  Leib  und  Seele.     JOHANNES  REHMKE. 
Rektorats   rede  Univ.,  Greifswald.     Greifswald,  1898.     Pp.  48. 
Zur  Par allelismusf rage.     G.  HEYMANS.     Zeitschrift   fur  Psychol- 
ogic, Bd.  XVII.,  Heft,  I.-IL,  S.  62. 

Die  erkenntnisstheoretische  Stellung  des  Psychologen.  RUD. 
WEINMANN.  Zeitschrift  fiir  Psychologic,  Bd.  XVII. ,  Heft  3, 
4,  S.  215. 

Professor  Rehmke  has  given  us,  in  his  inaugural  address  of  last 
spring,  what  is  designed  as  an  exhaustive  statement  of  the  possibilities 
of  general  theory  touching  the  relation  of  mind  and  body,  and  a  de- 
cision on  logical  grounds  in  favor  of  interaction.  In  a  preliminary 
historical  sketch  his  aim  is  to  show  in  their  simplicity  the  logical  mo- 
tives that  have  forced  the  development  of  theory.  In  his  direct  treat- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  233 

ment  of  the  problem  the  distinction  between  the  thing  or  (more  gen- 
erally) the  existence,  and  its  properties,  furnishes  the  basis.  Ancient 
materialism  regarded  the  mind  as  a  thing,  modern  materialism  as  the 
property  or  peculiarity  of  a  thing — the  body  or  brain.  The  Platonic 
teaching  and  the  author  regard  it  not  as  a  thing  but  as  a  separate 
immaterial  existence.  Solipsism  regards  the  body  as  a  property  or 
peculiarity  of  the  mind.  Spinozism  (a  name  that  Dr.  Rehmke  gives 
to  modern  parallelism  in  general)  accounts  mind  and  body  as  equally 
properties  or  peculiarities  of  a  substance  which  manifests  itself  in 
them.  Experience  tells  us  that  mind  and  body  are  connected.  Ex- 
perience tells  us  also  that  the  connection  of  '  things'  is  causal.  If 
mind  and  body  are  both  *  things,'  they  interact.  But  the  mind  is  not  a 
thing ;  the  grounds  need  not  be  here  repeated.  In  that  case,  it  is  held, 
it  cannot  be  a  party  to  interaction,  for  only  natures  alike  in  kind  can 
interact.  How  then  shall  we  understand  the  evident  connection? 
Shall  we  say  with  modern  materialism  that  the  body  (or  brain)  is  the 
thing  and  the  mind  the  property  ?  But  in  no  case,  as  here,  can  a  thing 
be  to  all  appearance  fully  conceived  without  its  property,  and  its  prop- 
erty without  the  thing,  and  against  this  as  against  the  view  that  the 
body  is  a  mere  property  of  the  mind  the  testimony  of  experience  to 
the  distinctness  of  mind  and  body  in  our  world  of  reality  is  final.  Are 
the  two  connected  then  as  properties  of  a  third  somewhat  ?  The  Spin- 
ozistic  doctrine  merely  repeats  the  fallacy  of  Occasionalism  ;  it  resorts 
to  an  alien  substance  to  do  what  it  has  pronounced  impossible.  Ex- 
perience does  not  show  us  a  quality  changing  punctually  of  itself 
whenever  another  quality  of  the  same  existence  changes.  The  con- 
nection of  quality  with  quality  must  then  on  this  view  be  causal.  But 
two  qualities  of  the  same  existence  do  not  stand  in  causal  relation  to 
each  other,  nor  an  existence  in  causal  relation  to  its  qualities.  We 
must  recognize  the  following  pair  of  first  principles :  (i)  Only  a  sep- 
arate existence  suffers  change  ;  qualities  cannot  suffer  it.  (2)  An  ex- 
istence suffers  change  only  when  there  is  another  existence  involved 
as  the  active  condition  of  the  change.  (Reference  to  author's  Lehr- 
buch  d.  Psych.,  S.  41-45,  andZeits.f.  imm.Phil.,  Bd.  II.,  S.  349 ff.). 
Mind  and  body  are  accordingly  separate  existences  interacting.  The 
rule  that  all  interacting  existences  must  be  alike  in  kind  is  a  hasty  gen- 
eralization from  the  fact  that  interacting  things  are  alike  in  kind.  But 
is  not  the  quantity  of  motion  (Dr.  Rehmke  rejects  the  term  4  energy' 
as  vague)  unalterable  ?  How  then  can  non-physical  things  produce 
it?  The  answer  is  that  the  law,  which  is  universal,  applies  only 
where  thing  moves  thing,  not  where  a  non-physical  existence  causes  a 


234  MIND  AND  BODY. 

thing  to  gain  or  lose  motion.  How  far,  if  at  all,  the  brain  loses  mo- 
tion when  the  mind  is  affected,  and  the  mind  parts  with  power  (in 
any  sense)  when  the  brain  is  affected,  we  are  not  yet  in  a  position  to 
determine. 

Dr.  Rehmke's  subtle  and  dexterous  treatment  of  this  much  agi- 
tated question  may  be  described  as  scholastic,  if  relentless  logical  an- 
alysis entirely  without  psychological  analysis  of  the  terms  is  the 
typical  scholastic  tendency.  The  argument  seems  to  depend  wholly 
on  the  finality  and  exhaustiveness  of  the  distinction,  as  applied  for 
instance  to  the  mind,  between  a  4  separate  existence'  and  its  t  properties.' 
It  is  curious  to  see  so  assured  an  idealist  as  Dr.  Rehmke  so  confident 
of  this.  His  remarks  on  parallelism,  in  part  fruitfully  suggestive,  are 
vitiated  by  his  confounding  the  modern  theory  in  all  its  forms  with 
Spinozism.  Were  Clifford  and  Fechner  (themselves  far  enough 
apart)  believers  in  a  *  substance '  of  which  mind  and  body  were  the 
4  properties '  ?  Moreover,  when  the  author  speaks  of  the  hypothesis 
that  when  a  pin  produces  a  wound,  and  through  it  a  cerebral  discharge, 
the  pin's  psychic  counterpart  produces  the  psychic  counterpart  of  the 
bodily  disturbances  and  then  the  pain  accompanying  the  cerebral  dis- 
charge, as  a  fancy  too  mystical  to  be  entertained  by  the  modern  paral- 
lelist,  he  is  tossing  aside  what  many  regard  as  of  the  essence  of  their 
principle.  To  substitute  <  the  conservation  of  motion  '  for  that  of  en- 
ergy, as  though  the  former  would  be  acknowledged  tantamount  to  the 
latter,  or  more  generally  regarded  as  true,  is  a  serious  error.  It  should 
be  remarked,  too,  that  an  author  who  uses  the  term  ;  the  solipsists '  to 
designate  one  of  the  schools  of  philosophical  opinion  should  inform 
us  who  these  thinkers  may  be  and  where  they  are  to  be  found. 

The  best  comment  on  the  artificial  method  of  Dr.  Rehmke's  essay 
is  furnished  by  the  second  on  our  list ;  the  article  of  a  fellow-idealist 
defending  4  monastic '  parallelism  from  the  attacks  of  Professor  Stumpf 
and  more  recent  writers.  Dr.  Heymans  calls  attention  to  many  mis- 
understandings of  the  theory,  rejects  Spinoza's  substance,  and  in  a 
lengthened  exposition  explains  that  it  is  only  from  the  convenient 
point  of  view  of  the  human  mind,  which  makes  an  independent  endur- 
ing world  of  its  own  perceptions,  instead  of  conceiving  the  world  in 
the  true  terms  of  outer  mind-stuff,  and  so  doubles  the  facts,  that  there 
is  any  parallelism  at  all.  The  remainder  of  his  article  consists  of 
acute  replies  to  the  recent  assailants  of  the  theory.  The  objections 
to  it  on  the  score  of  evidence  he  does  not  fully  face.  This  essay  is  the 
most  closely  and  carefully  reasoned  of  the  three  before  us. 

The  article  on  the  epistemological  position  of  the  psychologist  is 


NEW  BOOKS.  235 

a  vigorous  defence  of  realism  by  psychological  arguments.  The  author 
advances  to  battle  with  a  light  heart,  and  lays  about  him  with  boyish 
confidence  against  the  whole  host  of  contemporary  German  phenom- 
enists,  Schuppe,  Schubert- Soldern,  Kaufmann,  Mach,  Rehmke,  Le- 
clair,  Laas,  Cornelius,  Avenarius ;  that  is  to  say,  the  school  of  i  im- 
manente  Philosophic,'  the  strict  sect  of  Avenarius,  and  certain  detached 
kinsfolk  of  these.  "  The  psychological  compulsion  which  drives  us  to 
apprehend  that  which  we  are  conscious  of,  which  we  experience,  as 
objective,  is  no  mere  jest  which  our  Psyche  perpetrates,  but  an  in- 
stinctive indication  of  the  view  to  which  the  purely  philosophical  and 
logical  consideration  of  the  matter  of  experience  by  rightful  conse- 
quence leads."  Various  departments  of  psychology  are  drawn  upon 
to  show  the  underlying  realistic  assumption  of  the  science.  Much  is 
made  of  the  argument  that  idealism  does  away  with  the  distinction  be 
tween  psychology  and  other  sciences.  It  can  hardly  be  said  that  the 
article  exhibits  a  delicate  sense  of  the  besetting  difficulties  of  the 
long-vexed  problem  or  a  complete  grasp  of  the  opinions  it  condemns. 
It  is  a  philosophical  instance  of  the  illusion  of  simplicity. 

D.  A.  MILLER. 
PHILADELPHIA. 


NEW  BOOKS. 

Social  Elements.    C.R.HENDERSON.    New  York,  Scribners.     1898. 
Pp.  ix  -f  405. 

Le   Role  Social  de  la  Femme.      Mme.  A.   LAMPERIERE.      Paris, 

Alcan.      1898.     Pp.  175.     Fr.   2.75. 
La  Psicologia  contemporanea.      GUIDO  VILLA.      Bibliot.  di  Scienze 

Moderne.     Turin,  Bocca.     1899.     Pp.  660.     Lire  14. 
Report   of    U.    S.   Commissioner   of  Education,    1896-7.     W.    F. 

HARRIS,  Vol.   2.     Washington,  Govt.  Press.     1898.     Pp.  vii  and 

"37-239°- 
L*  Instabitite  mentale.     G.  L.  DUPRAT.     Paris,  Alcan.     1898.     Pp. 

310. 
Wild  Animals  I  have  Known.     E.    S.    THOMPSON.     New  York, 

Scribners.      1898.     Pp.  358.     $2.50. 

A  delightful  series  of  chapters  on  animal  genius-heroes.  Mr. 
Thompson  ought  to  tell  us  more  explicitly,  however,  just  what  inci- 
dents the  psychologist  may  quote  on  his  authority  as  a  naturalist  ! 

J.  M.  B. 


236  NEW  BOOKS. 

Democracy.     A    Study   of    Government.      J.    H.    HYSLOP.     New 

York,  Scribners.     1899.     ^P'  x*v  +  3°°* 
The  First  Philosophers  of  Greece.     A.   FAIRBANKS.      New  York, 

Scribners.      1898.     Pp.  vii  -f-  300.     $2.00. 

Footnotes  to  Evolution.  D.  S.  JORDAN  and  others.  New  York, 
Appletons.  1898.  Pp.  viii  +  392. 

Leibnitz,  The  Monadology  and  other  Philosophical  Writings.  R. 
LATTA.  Oxford,  Clarendon  Press.  1898.  Pp.  437. 

Principles  of  Biology.  HERBERT  SPENCER.  Revised  and  enlarged 
edition.  Vol.1.  New  York,  Appletons.  1898.  Pp.  xii -f- 706. 

Die  Spiele  der  Menschen.  KARL  GROOS.  Jena,  Fischer.  1899. 
Pp.  viii  -f  538. 

Christian  Science.  A  Sociological  Study.  C.  A.  L.  REID.  Cin- 
cinnati, McClelland.  1898.  Pp.  32. 

A  spirited  negative  examination  of    Christian  Science  by  a  physi- 
cian.    His   paper  is  printed  by  request  of    the   Northwestern   Ohio 

Medical  Association,  before  which  it  was  read. 

Double  Personality.  J^enten  Hysteria.  W.  L.  HOWARD.  Two 
papers  reprinted  from  the  Maryland  Medical  Journal.  Pp.  4  and 

4- 
Intensitatsschwankungen  eben  mekliche  optischer  und  akustischer 

Eindriicke.     W.  H.  HEINRICH.  Se;.  Abd.  aus  Anz.  d.  Akac.  d. 

Wiss.  in  Krakau.     Nov.,  1898.     Pp.  365-381. 
The  Scottish  Contribution  to  Moral  Philosophy.    J.  SETH.     Inaug. 

Lect.  Univ.  of  Edinburgh.     Edinburgh  and  London,  Blackwood. 

1898.     Pp.  43.     6d. 

Ueber  unsere  gegeniuartige  Kenntnissvom  Ur sprung  des  Menschen. 
By  E.  HAECKEL.  Bonn,  Strauss.  1898. 

Ueber  die  Grundvoraussetzungen  der  individualist  is  chen  Weltan- 
schauung. By  W.  LUTOSLAWSKI.  Helsingfors,  J.  Simelii  Erben. 
1898.  Pp.  88. 

The  Message  of  the  World's  Religions.     Reprinted  from  The  Out- 
look.    New  York,  Longmans.      1898.     Pp.  125. 
A  series  of  chapters  giving  the  point  of  view  of  each  of  the  great 
religions,  i.  e.,  Judaism  (Rabbi  Gottheil),  Buddhism  (Ruys  Davids), 
Confucianism    (A.   H.    Smith),    Mohammedanism    (G.  Washburn), 
Brahmanism  (Professor  Lanman),  Christianity  (Lyman  Abbott).     A 
remarkably  interesting  little  book.  J.  M.  B. 


CORRESPONDENCE  AND  NOTES.  237 

The    Beginnings   of  Art.     E.   GROSSE.      New  York,  Appletons. 

1897.     Pp.  xiv+327. 

The  German  edition  of  this  already  well-known  book  was  noticed 
at  length  in  this  REVIEW  (III.,  1896,  p.  560).  We  need,  therefore, 
only  repeat  our  commendation  of  it,  and  strongly  recommend  the  Eng- 
lish version  to  psychologists.  J.  M.  B. 


CORRESPONDENCE  AND  NOTES. 

PROPOSED  CHANGES  IN  THE  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION. 

At  the  recent  meeting  of  the  Association  in  New  York,  certain 
members  proposed  the  formation  of  a  separate  section  to  be  devoted 
to  the  reading  and  discussion  of  philosophical  papers.  On  account  of 
the  small  number  present  when  the  matter  was  brought  up,  decision 
was  postponed  until  the  next  meeting,  and  the  Secretary  was  requested 
to  send  out  cards  to  all  members  asking  for  a  general  expression  of 
opinion  on  the  point. 

Certainly,  every  member  should  have  an  opportunity  to  be  heard 
with  reference  to  a  proposition  which  logically  involves  changes  in  the 
name  and  constitution  of  the  Association,  but  a  vote  taken  without 
discussion  will  fail  to  express  the  thoughtful  wishes  of  the  members. 
I  venture  to  suggest  that  questions  of  sufficient  importance  to  be  re- 
ferred to  a  vote  of  the  whole  Association  ought  to  receive  some  atten- 
tion in  the  pages  of  the  REVIEW,  and  beg  leave  to  restate  some  of  the 
reasons  why,  in  the  interests  of  philosophy,  as  well  as  psychology,  the 
proposed  action  seems  unwise  at  the  present  time.  Most  of  these 
reasons  were  mentioned  in  the  discussion  at  the  meeting. 

First,  judging  from  the  experience  of  the  programme  committee, 
it  would  be  difficult  to  arrange  a  programme  for  such  a  section  without 
interfering  with  the  regular  meetings. 

Second,  our  best  psychologists  are  among  our  best  philosophers, 
and  their  withdrawal  from  even  a  part  of  the  meetings  of  the  Asso- 
ciation would  be  a  serious  loss.  At  the  same  time  the  greatest  need 
of  psychology  at  present  is  more  of  sound  philosophy,  and  the  great- 
est need  of  philosophy  more  of  sound  psychology.  Closer  union  is 
more  to  be  desired  than  further  separation. 

Third,  philosophical  papers  are  already  welcome  whenever  they 
offer  contributions  to  psychology  or  show  the  bearing  of  psychology 


238  CORRESPONDENCE   AND   NOTES. 

on  problems  of  philosophy.  This  offers  a  wide  range  of  subjects 
for  those  who  are  interested  in  any  branch  of  philosophy,  and  such 
papers  always  form  a  part  of  our  programme.  So  far  as  possible, 
they  are  grouped  together  in  the  same  sessions. 

Fourth,  when  it  comes  to  the  making  of  interesting  programmes, 
philosophical  subjects  are  by  no  means  equal  to  scientific  subjects. 
As  a  rule  the  papers  are  too  long.  Scientific  theories  and  results  can 
be  stated  briefly,  but  it  takes  time  to  set  forth  philosophical  opinions. 
Such  are  not  suitable  subjects  for  general  discussion,  and  discussion 
ought  to  be  the  most  important  feature  of  these  meetings.  There  is 
no  object  in  coming  together  to  listen  to  papers  which  can  be  read  at 
home.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  at  our  own  meetings  philosophical  papers 
never  called  forth  as  much  interest  as  the  scientific,  while  attempts 
in  other  places  to  hold  meetings  for  the  exclusive  discussion  of  prob- 
lems in  philosophy  have  repeatedly  ended  in  failure. 

Finally,  the  Association  is  now  making  splendid  progress  and  is 
becoming  a  source  of  inspiration  to  workers  in  the  field  of  psychology. 
At  the  same  time  it  is  doing  a  real  and  lasting  service  for  philosophy 
in  furthering  the  development  of  scientific  spirit  and  methods  in  the 
realm  of  mental  phenomena.  Nevertheless  much  remains  to  be  done 
before  psychology  comes  into  right  relations  with  the  rest  of  the  sci- 
ences. There  is  need  of  all  the  wisdom  and  energy  available  to  im- 
prove the  character  of  our  scientific  work,  and  it  is  extremely  impor- 
tant that  no  step  be  taken  which  will  weaken  the  Association. 

CHARLES  B.  BLISS. 

(THE  REVIEW  is  ready  to  print  other  concise  opinions  on  this  or 
other  matters  pertaining  to  the  Association.  J.  M.  B.) 

MRS.  LAURENCE  HUTTON,  whose  interest  in  Miss  Helen  Keller  is 
well  known,  allows  us  to  print  the  following  passage  from  a  personal 
letter  from  Miss  Keller  to  her,  written  under  date  of  January  17,  1899. 
Psychologists  will  be  interested  in  the  passage,  both  because  it  is  Miss 
Keller's  and  also  because  of  the  sentiment  which  her  project  embodies  : 
"  Have  you  seen  Kipling's  *  Dreaming  True,'  or  4  Kitchener's 
School'?  It  is  a  very  strong  poem,  and  has  set  me  to  dreaming  too. 
Of  course  you  have  read  about  the  '  Gordon  Memorial  College,'  which 
the  English  people  are  to  erect  at  Khartoum.  While  I  was  thinking 
over  the  blessings  that  would  come  to  the  people  of  Egypt  through 
this  college,  and  eventually  to  England  herself,  there  came  into  my 
heart  the  strong  desire  that  my  own  dear  country  should  in  a  similar 
way  convert  the  terrible  loss  of  her  brave  sons  on  the  4  Maine'  into  a 


CORRESPONDENCE  AND  NOTES.  239 

like  blessing  to  the  people  of  Cuba.  Would  a  college  at  Havana  not 
be  the  noblest  and  most  enduring  monument  that  could  be  raised  to 
the  brave  men  of  the  '  Maine,'  as  well  as  a  source  of  infinite  good  to 
all  concerned  ?  Imagine  entering  the  Havana  harbor,  and  having  the 
pier,  where  the  'Maine'  was  anchored  on  that  dreadful  night  when  she 
was  so  mysteriously  destroyed,  pointed  out  to  you,  and  being  told  that 
the  great,  beautiful  building  overlooking  the  spot  was  the  '  Maine 
Memorial  College,'  erected  by  the  American  people,  and  having  for 
its  object  the  education  both  of  Cubans  and  Spaniards !  What  a 
glorious  triumph  such  a  monument  would  be  of  the  best  and  highest 
instincts  of  a  Christian  nation !  In  it  there  would  be  no  suggestion  of 
hatred  or  revenge,  nor  a  trace  of  the  old-time  belief  that  might  makes 
right.  On  the  other  hand,  it  would  be  a  pledge  to  the  world  that  we 
intend  to  stand  by  our  declaration  of  war,  and  give  Cuba  to  the 
Cubans,  as  soon  as  we  have  fitted  them  to  assume  the  duties  and  re- 
sponsibilities of  a  self-governing  people." 

J.  M.  B. 

G.  A.  TAWNEY,  Ph.D.,  has  been  promoted  from  Assistant  to  full 
Professor  of  Philosophy  in  Beloit  College,  Wis. 

G.  F.  STOUT,  editor  of  Mind,  has  been  called  from  Aberdeen  to 
the  new  Wilde  Lectureship  in  Mental  Philosophy,  at  Oxford. 

PROFESSOR  JAMES  WARD'S  Gifford  Lectures  on  c  Naturalism  and 
Agnosticism '  are  to  be  issued  at  once  by  the  Macmillans.  The  same 
publishers  are  also  to  print  Professor  Royce's  Gifford  Lectures. 

WE  have  received  the  first  number  of  the  new  series  of  V Inter- 
mediere  des  Biologists,  to  the  title  of  which  the  words  et  des  Medi- 
cins  are  added  by  the  new  editor,  M.  L.  Hallion.  It  has  several  new 
and  interesting  features.  With  it  comes  to  hand  also  the  first  issue  of 
V  Intermediere  des  Neurologistes  et  des  Alienistes,  edited  by  Dr. 
Paul  Sollier. 

WE  notice  that  Mr.  Brooks  Adams'  Law  of  Civilization  and  De- 
cay is  to  be  issued  in  French  translation  by  Alcan,  Paris. 

PROFESSOR  MARTIUS,  of  Bonn,  succeeds  Professor  Riehl  at  Kiel, 
the  latter  going  to  Halle. 

WE  regret  to  record  the  death  of    Robert  Zimmermann,  the  distin- 
guished Herbartian  writer  on  ^Esthetics  and  Philosophy. 

PROFESSOR  HAECKEL'S  interesting  address  (listed  above)  on  Der 
Ursprung  des  Menschen  has  been  brought  out  in  book  form  by  the 
Macmillans  under  the  title  4  The  Last  Link.' 


240  CORRESPONDENCE  AND  NOTES. 

M.  SEAILLES  has  been  appointed  Professor  of  Philosophy  in  the 
University  of  Paris. 

THE  Proceedings  of  the  National  Educational  Association  (Wash- 
ington meeting,  1898)  are  of  more  than  usual  interest.  Papers  by 
Royce,  Krohn,  Draper,  Shaw,  will  interest  psychologists,  as  will  also 
the  transactions  of  the  child-study  section.  Taken  with  Commissioner 
Harris'  admirable  two-volume  Report  just  published  the  educational 
world  has  an  abundance  of  good  reading. 

J.  M.  B. 

DR.  E.  B.  McGiLVARY,  Assistant  Professor  of  Logic  and  the  Theory 
of  Knowledge  in  the  University  of  California,  has  been  appointed  to 
the  Sage  Professorship  of  Moral  Philosophy  in  Cornell  University,  to 
succeed  Professor  James  Seth,  now  Professor  of  Moral  Philosophy  in 
the  University  of  Edinburgh.  Professor  McGilvary  made  his  chief 
philosophical  studies  at  the  University  of  California,  and  received 
there  his  degree  of  Ph.D.,  having  previously  won  his  M.A.  at  Prince- 
ton, and  his  A.B.  at  Davidson  College,  N.  C.  He  will  begin  his 
duties  at  Cornell  with  the  opening  of  the  autumn  term  of  1899. 

THE  Rivista  Italiana  of  di  filosofia  so  long  and  so  successfully 
edited  by  the  lamented  Professor  Ferri,  is  to  be  continued  under  the 
title  Rivista  filosofica.  It  will  be  directed  by  Professor  C.  Cantoni 
of  the  University  of  Pavia. 


VOL.  VI.     No.  3.  MAY,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


A   STUDY   OF   GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS. 

BY   PROFESSOR   CHARLES    H.   JUDD. 
New  York  University. 

With  the  single  exception  of  Brentano's *  unsuccessful  attempt 
to  explain  the  Miiller-Lyer  illusion  by  the  general  fact  that  acute 
angles  are  overestimated  and  obtuse  angles  are  underestimated, 
no  one  has  essayed  to  establish  any  direct  relation  between  the 
illusions  of  linear  distances  and  those  in  which  there  is  false 
judgment  of  the  angles.  The  so-called  angle  illusions  have 
always  been  referred  to  the  Poggendorff  figure  as  the  simplest 
case  of  the  illusion.  Since  1861,  when  Hering2  first  explained 
the  Poggendorff  illusion  as  due  to  the  false  estimation  of  the 
angles,  there  has  been,  in  spite  of  disagreements  as  to  the  ulti- 
mate explanation  of  the  false  estimation,  a  universal  acceptance 
of  the  statement  that  the  angles  are  misjudged.  It  is  the  aim 
of  this  paper  to  present  certain  facts  that  seem  to  show  that  the 
false  estimation  of  the  angles  in  the  Poggendorff  figure  is  merely 
a  secondary  effect,  not  always  present,  and  in  no  case  the  source 
of  the  illusion.  The  illusion  is  rather  to  be  explained  as  due  to 
the  wrong  estimation  of  certain  linear  distances,  and  may  be 
reduced  in  the  last  analysis  to  the  type  of  illusion  found  in  the 
Miiller-Lyer  figure. 

Before  taking  up  the  discussion  of  the  Poggendorff  illusion  it 
will  be  necessary  to  point  out  certain  facts  in  regard  to  the  Miiller- 
Lyer  figure.  The  overestimation  and  underestimation  character- 
istic of  this  figure  are  very  much  more  comprehensive  processes 

'Zeitsch.  fiir  Psych,  und  Phys.,  III.,  349. 
2Beitrage  zurPhys.,  p.  384. 


242  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

than  they  are  ordinarily  recognized  to  be.  The  attention  of  the 
observer  has  always  been  concentrated  on  the  lines  included  be- 
tween the  obliques.  In  developing  his  theory  of  boundaries  Lipps1 
evidently  sees  that  the  concentration  of  the  whole  attention  on  a 
line  within  certain  boundaries  is  a  limitation  which  calls  for  some 
justification.  He  raises  the  question  :  How  does  it  come  that  a 
line  which  bounds  the  figure  within  does  not  at  the  same  time 
act  as  the  boundary  of  the  space  without?  The  very  important 
suggestion  contained  in  this  question  is,  however,  entirely  lost 
in  the  easy  assumption  with  which  Lipps  dismisses  the  difficulty 
that  he  has  raised.  He  assumes  that  when  a  line  is  in  a  posi- 
tion such  that  it  may  be  regarded  as  the  seat  of  the  two  non-con- 
tradictory functions  which  are  relatively  independent,  one  of 
these  functions  will  appear,  while  the  other  will  be  swallowed 
up  in  the  general  perceptual  process.  Such  a  disposition  of  the 
matter  does  not  find  any  justification  in  the  empirical  facts. 
Fig.  i  is  made  up  of  the  two  figures  of  the  Miiller-Lyer  illusion 
so  placed  that  the  ends  of  the  horizontal  lines  are  equally  distant 
from  the  short  vertical  line  placed  between  them.  It  is  evident 
that  overestimation  within  the  figure  is  accompanied  by  under- 
estimation of  the  space  outside  of  the  figure,  and,  conversely, 
underestimation  within  the  figure  is  accompanied  by  overesti- 
mation of  the  neighboring  space.  It  may  be  objected  that  the 
presence  of  the  short  vertical  line  between  the  extremities  of  the 
horizontals  gives  us,  in  effect,  two  new  Miiller-Lyer  figures  of 
empty  space  in  which  the  oblique  lines  will,  of  course,  be  directed 
in  exactly  the  opposite  direction  to  that  in  which  they  extend 
when  regarded  as  parts  of  the  original  figures.  The  answer  to 
this  objection  is  that  if  no  vertical  line  is  used,  but  the  subject  is 
required  to  locate  the  point  which  is  apparently  half-way  between 
the  extremities  of  the  horizontal  lines,  he  will  make  an  error  in- 
dicating the  presence  of  the  illusion  in  its  full  intensity.  This 
will  be  made  somewhat  clearer  by  Fig.  2.  In  this  figure  the 
obliques  are  drawn  in  such  a  way  that  with  respect  to  the  line 
as  a  whole  they  produce  no  illusion.  The  partial  effects  of  the 
oblique  lines  are,  however,  by  no  means  lost.  If  some  neutral 
point  of  reference  is  marked  so  that  direct  comparison  is  possible, 
'Raumaesth.  und  geom.  Taiischungen,  III. 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS. 


243 


244  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

it  can  be  seen  that  the  partial  effects  are  present  in  undiminished 
intensity.  Thus  in  the  figure  the  horizontal  line  as  a  whole 
suffers  no  illusion  whatever.  The  middle  point  is  marked,  and 
it  appears  at  once  that  in  one-half  of  the  line  there  is  under- 
estimation and  in  the  other  half  there  is  an  equal  degree  of  over- 
estimation.  Furthermore,  the  position  of  the  figure  as  a  whole 
with  respect  to  the  short  vertical  lines,  which  are  placed  at  equal 
distances  from  the  extremities  of  the  horizontal  line,  indicates 
that  the  influence  of  the  oblique  lines  on  the  surrounding  space 
is  undiminished. 

Other  similar  facts  are  illustrated  by  Figs.  3  and  4.  In 
these  figures  the  influences  at  the  extremities  of  each  of  the 
horizontals  are  alike  in  kind,  but  unequal  in  degree.  The  re- 
sult is,  again,  a  shifting  of  the  middle  point.  The  illusion  an- 
nounced by  Professor  Baldwin  in  1895 l  also  belongs  here. 
The  illusion  is  in  brief  as  follows  :  If  two  figures  of  unequal 
size,  as  two  squares  or  two  circles,  are  brought  near  to  each 
other  in  the  field  of  vision,  the  point  half-way  between  them 
will  be  attracted  towards  the  larger  figure.  The  similarity  be- 
tween Fig.  3  and  Professor  Baldwin's  circle  figure  is  apparent 
at  once.  But  the  illusion  appears  when  squares  are  used  in- 
stead of  circles.  That  even  in  this  case  the  illusion  belongs 
under  the  principle  here  developed,  rather  than  under  any  prin- 
ciple of  size-contrast,  will  be  apparent  from  Fig.  5.  Here  the 
large  square  contains  the  small  one,  and  yet  the  illusion  is  in 
kind  and  degree  exactly  like  that  described  by  Professor 
Baldwin. 

All  of  these  facts  go  to  show  that  the  processes  of  underesti- 
mation and  overestimation  within  the  figure  are  accompanied  by 
far-reaching  effects  outside  of  the  figures.  In  fact,  overestima- 
tion and  underestimation  are  wholly  inadequate  terms  with 
which  to  describe  the  processes  taking  place.  To  say  that 
points  are  shifted  in  their  spatial  relations  with  reference  to  all 
the  points  in  the  field  of  vision  would  be  much  nearer  to  the 
whole  truth.  Such  shifting  becomes  apparent  only  when  neu- 
tral points  of  reference  are  present  in  the  field  of  vision,  or  when 
direct  comparison  with  points  which  are  shifted  in  the  opposite 

1  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  II.,  244. 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS.  245 

direction  becomes  possible.  When  referred  to  this  general 
principle  it  becomes  evident  that  the  phenomena  of  overestima- 
tion  and  underestimation  are  only  occasional  manifestations, 
under  favorable  conditions,  of  processes  that  are  operative  but 
undetected  in  every  field  of  vision.  In  most  cases  the  ten- 
dencies to  false  estimation  of  one  sort  or  the  other  are  lost  in 
the  complexity  of  the  conditions  or  through  the  absence  of 
points  of  comparison.  One  case  in  which  such  tendencies  are 
present  but  unobserved  is  of  such  importance  for  our  later  dis- 
cussion that  we  may  call  attention  to  it  at  this  time.  If  an 
oblique  line  ends  in  a  horizontal  line  which  extends  for  an  in- 
definite distance  on  each  side  of  the  point  of  meeting  there  will 
be  no  apparent  illusion.  If,  however,  the  attempt  is  made  to 
mark  off  in  the  horizontal  line  equal  distances  on  each  side  of 
the  point  of  intersection  with  the  oblique  line,  it  will  be  found 
that  distances  on  the  acute-angle  side  are  underestimated  and 
distances  on  the  obtuse-angle  side  are  overestimated.  Or  if  the 
point  of  intersection  is  taken  as  the  point  of  greatest  importance, 
the  illusion  will  take  the  form  of  the  shifting  of  that  point  to- 
wards the  extremity  of  the  horizontal  line  which  is  on  the  acute- 
angle  side. 

Having  thus  generalized  the  concepts  overestimation  and  un- 
derestimation, we  turn  to  a  consideration  of  the  Poggendorff 
figure,  and  a  criticism  of  the  theory  which  regards  it  as  the 
simplest  case  of  the  angle  illusions.  First  of  all,  we  have  to  con- 
sider certain  negative  evidences  which  show  that  the  illusion  is 
not  due  to  a  false  estimation  of  the  angles.  Such  negative  evi- 
dence is  at  hand  in  the  now  generally  known  facts.  The  illu- 
sion disappears  when  the  figure  is  so  placed  that  the  intercepted 
line  is  horizontal  or  vertical.  If  the  illusion  were  due  to  wrong 
estimation  of  the  angles  it  is  not  easy  to  see  how  these  particular 
positions  of  the  figure  could  operate  to  destroy  the  illusion.  No 
general  statement  to  the  effect  that  an  acute  angle,  one  of 
the  sides  of  which  is  vertical  or  horizontal,  is  not  subject  to 
false  estimation  will  explain  away  this  difficulty  for  the  angle 
theory,  for  if  the  intercepting  parallels,  instead  of  the  inter- 
cepted line,  are  brought  into  the  vertical  or  horizontal  position, 
the  illusion  appears  in  its  full  intensity.  The  negative  evidence 


246  CHAS.  H.  JUDD, 

presented  in  these  four  positions  of  the  figure  is  strengthened  by 
that  given  in  Figs.  6,  7  and  8.  In  Fig.  6  the  acute  angles  are 
present,  but  the  illusion  does  not  appear  in  any  position  of  the 
figure.  In  Fig.  7  the  parts  of  the  intercepting  parallels  which 
lie  between  the  points  of  interception  are  present,  and  with  these 
the  obtuse  angles.  The  illusion  is  strengthened  so  much  that  it 
cannot  be  made  to  disappear  in  any  position  of  the  figure.  The 
same  is  true  of  the  case  illustrated  by  Fig.  8,  in  which  only  a 
small  part  of  each  of  the  intercepting  parallels  is  present.  With 
regard  to  the  angles,  then,  we  must  conclude  that  the  acute 
angles,  instead  of  being  essential  to  the  illusion,  seem  rather  to 
weaken  it,  for  the  strongest  form  of  the  illusion  appears  when 
these  angles  are  omitted. 

Further  negative  evidence  appears  in  Figs.  9  and  10.  In 
Fig.  9  the  upper  and  lower  halves  show  the  Poggendorff  illusion 
in  opposite  directions.  If  the  angles  were  misjudged,  the  inter- 
rupted lines  should  seem  to  diverge  on  the  left  and  to  converge  on 
,the  right.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  it  will  be  seen  that  all  the  oblique 
lines  .appear  to  be  parallel  with  each  other ;  this  statement  apply- 
ing, of  course,  to  the  two  interrupted  lines  when  compared 
with  each  other.  Furthermore,  since  the  uninterrupted  oblique 
lines  form  the  same  acute  and  obtuse  angles  with  the  intercept- 
ing parallels  as  do  the  intercepted  lines,  it  is  possible  to  make 
a  direct  comparison  between  the  angles  under  discussion  in  cases 
in  which  the  illusion  is  present  and  incases  in  which  it  is  absent. 
No  inequality  will  be  observable.  On  the  other  hand,  it  will 
be  noted  that  the  apparent  width  of  the  spaces  between  the  ob- 
lique lines  is  not  the  same  when  the  right  and  left  sides  of  the 
figure  are  compared.  Thus,  the  interval  between  the  upper 
oblique  and  the  interrupted  line  seems  wider  on  the  left  than  it 
does  on  the  right.  The  space  below  the  intercepted  line  seems 
broader  on  the  right  than  on  the  left.  The  converse  is  true  of 
the  spaces  above  and  below  the  lower  intercepted  line. 

Figure  10  will  be  recognized  as  a  complex  made  up  of  6 
and  7.  The  line  CD  shows  no  illusion  of  the  Poggendorff  type. 
The  lines  AB  and  EF  show  the  typical  illusion.  At  O  and  N  the 
intercepting  parallels  are  somewhat  extended,  and  it  will  be  ob- 
served that  the  acute  angles  thus  formed,  instead  of  seeming 


GE  OME  TRICAL   IL  L  US  IONS. 


247 


248  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

larger  than  the  acute  angles  at  2  and  3,  where  no  illusion  ap- 
pears, seem  rather  to  be  noticeably  smaller. 

In  view  of  this  negative  evidence  it  seems  clear  that  the  false 
estimation  of  the  angles  cannot  be  regarded  as  the  explanation 
of  the  Poggendorff  illusion.  The  real  causes  of  the  illusion  are 
to  be  looked  for  in  some  other  direction.  We  turn  for  our  in- 
vestigation of  the  figure  to  one  of  the  positions  in  which  the 
illusion  disappears.  Such  a  position  is  that  in  which  the  inter- 
ceptedjjline  is  horizontal.  If  the  apparent  length  of  the  interval 
between  the  points  of  interception  is  compared  with  an  equal 
interval  marked  off  by  intercepting  parallels  which  are  perpen- 
dicular to  the  intercepted  line,  it  will  be  observed,  as  seen  in  Fig. 
n,  that  the  interval  in  the  Poggendorff  figure  is  underesti- 
mated. This  underestimation  was  subjected  to  quantitative 
determination.  The  method  employed  in  these  investigations 
was  the  same  as  that  used  by  Heymans.1  Cards  were  arranged 
so  as  to  present  a  pair  of  parallels  perpendicular  to  the  horizon- 
tal line  which  they  intercepted.  The  distance  between  these  par- 
allels, or  the  standard  distance,  was  50  mm.  At  the  right  of  the 
parallels  just  described  was  a  second  pair  of  parallels  also  inter- 
cepting the  horizontal  line,  but  sloping  obliquely  from  the  upper 
right  to  the  lower  left,  forming  an  angle  of  45°  with  the  hori- 
zontal line.  The  extreme  right  part  of  the  figure,  including  the 
right  oblique  line  and  the  part  of  the  horizontal  lying  to  the  right 
of  it,  was  made  movable,  so  that  the  subject  could  easily  adjust 
the  distance  between  the  points  at  which  the  oblique  lines  inter- 
cepted the  horizontal.  The  errors  for  three  subjects  are  given 
in  Table  I. 

TABLE  I. 


SUBJ. 

No.  OF  DETER. 

AVG.  ERROR. 

M.  V. 

i 

10 

6 

6.7  mm. 
14-5 

i.i 
i-3 

c. 

3 

6-3 

i.i 

The  next  step  in  the  investigation  was  to  break  the  figure 
up  into  its  elements,  with  a  view  to  discovering  the  importance 
of  the  different  parts  of  the  oblique  parallels  for  the  illusion. 

1  Zeitsch.fur  Psych,  und  P/iys.,  IX.,  221. 


GE  OME  TRIG  A  L   1L  L  US  I  ON  S. 


249 


B 


25° 


CHAS.  H  JUDD. 


These  oblique  parallels  were  divided  into  four  parts.  The  part 
of  the  left  line  above  the  horizontal  was  designated  a ;  the 
part  of  the  right  oblique  line  above  the  horizontal  was  called  b ; 
in  like  manner  the  lower  left  line  is  c,  the  lower  right  line  d. 
Cards  were  prepared  which  made  possible  all  the  different 
combinations  of  these  lines,  and  measurements  similar  to  those 
reported  in  Table  I.  were  made  with  each  combination.  The 
standard  distance  was  again  50  mm.  ;  the  angle  of  obliquity  was 
as  before  45°.  The  average  errors  are  given  in  mm. 

TABLE  II. 


SUB.  J. 

SUB.  E. 

SUB.  C. 

ORDER  OF  GREAT- 
EST ILLUSION. 

No.  OF  DETERM. 
IN  EACH  CASE. 

10 

6 

3 

SUB.  J 

SUB.E 

SUB.C 

LINES  PRESENT. 

Avg. 

M.V. 

Avg. 

M.V. 

Avg. 

M.V. 

a 

M 

0.9 

ii.  8 

0.6 

7-7 

0.9 

ac 

ad 

cd 

ab 

8.8 

I.O 

13.0 

o-5 

5-3 

i.i 

d 

abd 

abd 

ac 

9-9 

0.9 

ii.  8 

1.2 

S-3 

3-1 

ad 

abed 

abc 

ad 

8.9 

I.O 

17-5 

1.2 

8.7 

i.i 

ab 

acd 

ad 

abc 

2.4 

0.4 

13-3 

I>3 

9.0 

0.6 

abd 

abc 

d 

abd 

8.2 

I.O 

16.1 

0.9 

n.6 

i.i 

a 

ab 

a 

acd 

7.2 

0.7 

13.3 

I.O 

7.6 

0.5 

acd 

a 

acd 

abed 

6.7 

I.I 

14-5 

1.3 

6-3 

i.  E 

abed 

ac 

abed 

b 

3-6 

0.8 

5-7 

0.4 

2.O 

0.6 

bd 

bed 

bed 

be 

I.O 

0.6 

4-7 

0.8 

I.O 

0.6 

none 

d 

ab 

bd 

6.0 

1.4 

7-4 

0.7 

2.0 

o.o 

bed 

cd 

ac 

bed 

4.1 

0.7 

ii.  i 

0-5 

6-3 

I.I 

b 

bd 

b 

c 

2.9 

0.7 

5-3 

0.7 

I.O 

0.6 

abc 

none 

bd 

cd 

2.9 

0-5 

8-5 

0.7 

12.  0 

0.0 

c 

b 

c 

d 

9-7 

8.7 

o.S 

8.0 

0.6 

cd 

c 

be 

none 

5-7 

0.6 

6.8 

0.8 

0.3 

0.9 

be 

be 

none 

There  are  very  noticeable  personal  differences  in  these  re- 
sults, but  the  general  tendencies  are  common.  The  lines  a 
and  d  are  favorable  to  the  illusion  ;  the  lines  b  and  c  are  un- 
favorable. The  figure  resulting  from  the  combination  of  the 
favorable  lines  is  identical  with  the  Miiller-Lyer  figure  for 
underestimation  ;  that  resulting  from  the  combination  of  the  lines 
unfavorable  to  the  illusion  is  identical  with  the  Miiller-Lyer 
figure  for  overestimation.  Even  under  the  last-named  condi- 
tions, however,  there  is  a  slight  underestimation  as  compared 
with  the  standard  made  use  of  in  this  case.  This  renders  it 
necessary  for  us  to  examine  at  the  outset  of  our  discussion  the 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS. 


251 


process  by  which  the  distance  adopted  as  a  standard  in  this 
case  is  estimated. 

Fig.  12  makes  it  possible  to  compare  the  standard  dis- 
tance between  the  parallels  with  three  other  equal  distances.  The 
distance  between  the  free  ends  of  the  interrupted  horizontal 
(case  A)  is  usually  judged  as  shorter  than  the  distance  between 
the  parallels.  That  this  statement  cannot  be  put  in  a  universal 
form  will  appear  when  the  results  of  the  subject  C,  in  Table  II. , 
are  examined.  The  illusion  in  its  general  form  has  been  ob- 
served by  a  large  number  of  individuals  who  were  not  subjected 
to  any  quantitative  tests.  We  are  accordingly  justified  in  re- 
garding C  as  exceptional  in  this  particular.  This  conclusion 
is  confirmed  by  the  fact  that  his  judgment  in  case  B  is  also  ex- 
ceptional. Most  observers  see  a  short  unbroken  horizontal 
line  as  equal  to  the  standard  distance.  The  subject  C,  on  the 
other  hand,  sees  the  horizontal  line  as  longer  than  the  standard. 
Finally,  when  the  interval  between  the  parallels  is  compared  to 
the  interval  between  two  dots  (case  C),  the  latter  is  usually  seen 
as  longer.  The  judgments  in  this  case  are,  however,  so  ir- 
regular that  quantitative  determinations  are  of  little  value.  Cer- 
tain quantitative  results  which  throw  light  on  some  of  these 
cases  are  to  be  found  in  Tables  III.  and  IV.  In  Table  III.  the  re- 
sults are  given  from  comparison  of  the  interval  between  the  free 
ends  of  the  interrupted  horizontal  and  the  interval  between  the 
parallels.  The  method  is  the  same  as  before.  The  standard, 
that  is,  the  distance  between  the  parallels,  was  varied  from  2.5 
to  150  mm.  Ten  determinations  were  made  in  each  case  for  J, 
five  in  each  case  for  E. 

TABLE  III. 


DISTANCE. 

2-5 

5-o 

IO.O 

20. 

50. 

80. 

TOO 

'50 

Subj.  J. 

Subj.  E. 

"     " 

Avg. 
M.  V. 
Avg. 
M.  V. 

1.4 

0.2 

1-3 

O-2 

1.9 

0.2 
2-5 
0.0 

3-3 
0.4 

3-3 

0.2 

3-8 
0.4 
3-2 
0.6 

57 
0.6 
fi.8 
0.8 

8.2 

1-4 

9-9 
i-5 

3-6 

1.2 

S.8 

2-5 

—1.4 

i-7 

~°84 

Table  IV.  presents  the  results  of  a  comparison  by  C  of  the 
distances  marked  off  by  a  number  of  unbroken  horizontal  lines 
and  the  interval  between  the  free  ends  of  an  interrupted  hori- 


252 


CHAS.  //.  JUDD. 


zontal.     The  standard  line  in  each  case  was  the  unbroken  hori- 
zontal, the  number  of  determinations  five. 

TABLE  IV— SUBJECT  C. 


DISTANCE. 

5-o 

IO. 

25- 

50 

70 

IOO 

Avg. 
M.   V. 

2.0 
0.0 

5-8 
o-3 

6.0 

1.2 

10.2 

0.6 

II.  2 
1.4 

14.0 

1.6 

It  will  be  noted  that  Tables  III.  and  IV.  are  directly  com- 
parable. For  J  and  E  the  interval  between  parallels  is  judged 
as  equal  to  the  horizontal  line  which  is  used  as  the  standard  in 
Table  IV.  The  same  general  result  is  to  be  found  in  both 
tables.  The  illusion  is  greatest  for  short  distances. 

In  connection  with  these  facts  attention  is  to  be  called  to 
those  cases  in  Table  II.  in  which  the  free  end  of  the  horizontal 
is  left  after  the  withdrawal  of  both  parts  of  the  oblique.  Take, 
for  example,  the  case  in  which  d  alone  is  present.  It  will  be 
seen  that  for  J  and  C  the  illusion  is  about  as  strong  as  it  is  when 
d  is  combined  with  the  most  favorable  line,  namely,  the  line  a. 
Again,  in  such  cases  as  a,  ac,  and  even  bd,  there  are  indications 
that  the  free  end  of  the  horizontal  is  favorable  to  the  illusion. 

If  we  attempt  to  find  an  explanation  of  the  illusion  which 
appears  when  the  break  in  a  horizontal  line  is  compared  with 
the  interval  between  two  parallels,  or  with  the  unbroken  hori- 
zontal line,  it  is  evident  that  we  cannot  appeal  to  the  principle 
that  filled  space  is%  overestimated  when  compared  with  empty 
space.  The  two  intervals  stand  on  a  par  with  respect  to  their 
content.  Then,  again,  when  these  intervals  are  compared  with 
an  interval  bounded  by  dots,  it  will  be  seen  that  this  last  example 
of  empty  space  is  subject  to  overestimation  rather  than  under- 
estimation. The  theory  of  Lipps,  which  attributes  such  illusions 
to  the  bounding  activity  of  the  various  lines  and  points,  on  the 
general  principle  that  the  greater  the  bounding  activity  of  the 
terminal  lines  or  points  the  more  the  bounded  interval  is  under- 
estimated, does  not  seem  adequate  to  explain  these  facts. 
Thus,  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  the  parallel  lines  can  be  regarded 
as  less  intense  boundaries  than  the  free  ends  of  the  interrupted 
horizontals.  Again,  in  his  explanation  of  the  Miiller-Lyer 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS.  253 

figure,  Lipps  assumes  that  the  oblique  lines  which  slope  out- 
ward have  a  bounding  activity  which  is  negative.  This  can- 
not hold  when  applied  to  case  be  in  Table  II.  To  be  sure,  some 
of  these  difficulties  could  be  avoided  if  the  bounding  activities 
were  regarded  as  applying  to  the  intercepted  lines  rather  than 
to  the  intervals.  But  .this  brings  us  back  to  the  position  taken 
early  in  this  paper,  namely,  the  position  that  the  points  at  the 
end  of  a  line  have  spatial  relations  in  all  directions,  and  any 
modification  of  the  relations  in  one  direction  involved  at  the 
same  time  the  opposite  modification  in  the  opposite  direction. 
Such  shifting  of  points  cannot  be  explained  by  the  bounding 
activity  of  lines  or  points,  for  it  is  the  boundaries  themselves 
that  are  shifted  in  their  spatial  relations. 

The  movement  hypothesis,  on  the  othei  hand,  seems  to  meet 
the  demands  of  all  the  different  cases.  The  more  intense  the 
sensation  of  movement,  the  greater  will  be  the  estimation  of  the 
distance ;  conversely,  the  less  the  intensity  of  the  sensations  of 
movement,  the  shorter  the  estimated  distance.  If  from  a  given 
point  the  tendencies  of  movement  are  outward,  then  the  move- 
ment outward  will  be,  if  it  is  executed,  somewhat  easier.  In 
any  case  the  tendency  will  result  in  an  active  tension  of  the  mus- 
cles which  favor  outward  movement  of  the  eyes.  The  space 
lying  in  that  direction  will  be  underestimated,  while  space  in  the 
opposite  direction  will  be  overestimated.  The  point  from  which 
these  tendencies  emanate  will,  accordingly,  be  shifted  outward. 
If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  tendencies  from  a  given  point  are  in- 
ward, the  point  will  be  shifted  inward.  Influences  of  one  kind 
and  another  may  be  combined  in  great  variety  of  quality  and 
intensity.  The  final  apparent  position  of  a  point  will  be  de- 
termined by  all  of  these  influences  operating  together.  The 
question  now  arises  :  What  are  some  of  the  influences  which 
give  rise  to  tendencies  of  movement?  The  most  important  fact 
in  this  connection  is  that  the  eye  tends  to  follow  lines  rather 
than  to  direct  its  own  course  through  space.  When  lines  are 
present  in  the  field  of  vision  they  tend  to  attract  and  direct  the 
eye  in  its  movements  or  in  its  tendencies  of  movement.  But 
every  line  has  two  directions,  and,  therefore,  it  cannot  in  itself 
determine  the  particular  direction  in  which  the  eye  is  to  move  or 


254  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

to  tend  to  move  in  any  particular  case.  There  enters  at  this 
point  of  our  discussion  a  very  important  and  very  ambiguous 
factor.  We  may  designate  it  by  the  convenient  term,  the  direc- 
tion of  attention.  By  this  we  mean  to  indicate  that  the  particular 
direction  of  movement  in  any  given  case  depends  on  the  relation 
of  that  part  of  the  field  of  space  which  is  subjectively  the  most 
important  to  all  other  parts.  Thus,  in  the  cases  reported  in 
Table  II.  the  important  distances  were  the  breaks  in  the  hori- 
zontal lines.  The  tendencies  of  movement  originating  in  all  of 
the  lines  will  have  their  direction  determined  by  their  relations 
to  these  two  intervals.  If  we  attempt  now  to  discover  which 
lines  are  favorable  to  movement  across  these  intervals  and  which 
are  unfavorable  we  shall  find  full  agreement  between  our  re- 
sults as  recorded  in  the  tables  and  principles  just  developed. 

In  Table  II.  it  will  be  seen  that  all  those  combinations  of 
lines  which  render  movement  across  the  open  interval  easy,  as, 
for  example,  a,  ad,  acd,  deb,  and  others,  are  favorable  to  the 
illusion.  The  fact  that  cb  is  not  a  case  of  overestimation  rather 
than  underestimation  can  be  explained  by  a  consideration  of  all 
the  facts  reported  in  Tables  III.  and  IV.,  together  with  some  of 
the  subjective  observations  made  during  those  tests.  A  char- 
acteristic observation  was  made  by  C  while  comparing  the  hori- 
zontal lines  with  the  interval  between  the  free  ends  of  an  inter- 
rupted horizontal  (Table  IV.).  The  ends  of  the  lines  and  of 
the  interval  seemed  more  or  less  uncertain.  The  ends  of  the  line 
seemed  to  run  out  into  the  surrounding  space,  thus  making  the 
line  seem  longer;  the  ends  of  the  lines  bounding  the  interval, 
on  the  other  hand,  seemed  to  close  in  on  the  interval,  making  it 
seem  smaller.  In  both  these  cases  there  is  evidently  a  strong 
tendency  for  the  movement  which  has  originated  in  the  line  to 
extend  itself  beyond  the  end  of  the  line.  This  holds  for  those 
cases  reported  in  Table  II.,  in  which  the  free  end  of  the  hori- 
zontal is  favorable  to  the  illusion.  To  return  now  to  the  case 
be.  While  these  lines  alone  would  result  in  overestimation  of 
the  interval  as  in  the  normal  Miiller-Lyer  figure,  their  influence 
is  counteracted  by  the  tendencies  produced  in  the  horizontal  lines. 

The  principles  may  also  be  applied  to  the  estimation  of  the 
interval  between  the  dots  as  compared  with  the  interval  between 


GE  OME  TRICAL   ILL  US  IONS. 


255 


jr 


2^6 


CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 


M    A 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS.  257 

the  parallels.  The  dots  give  rise  to  no  tendencies  of  movement 
across  the  interval.  For  most  observers  the  perpendiculars 
counteract  the  tendencies  toward  underestimation  which  origi- 
nate in  the  horizontal  lines.  The  influence  of  these  horizontals 
is  not  entirely  overcome.  In  the  case  of  the  subject  C  it  seems 
to  persist  in  its  full  intensity.  In  fact,  his  description  of  his 
method  of  estimation  would  seem  to  justify  the  special  explana- 
tion that  he  neglects  the  parallels  almost  entirely. 

The  measurements  and  explanations  thus  far  presented  apply 
only  to  the  exceptional  positions  of  the  Poggendorff  figure ;  to 
those,  namely,  in  which  the  typical  illusion  disappears.  That 
the  underestimation  of  the  interval  between  the  points  of  inter- 
ception is  present,  though  in  a  smaller  degree,  in  other  positions 
of  the  figure,  can  be  seen  by  comparing  those  cases  in  which 
the  illusion  appears  with  those  in  which  it  does  not  appear,  as 
given  in  Figs.  6,  7,  8  and  10.  But  this  fact  does  not  suffice  to 
explain  the  appearance  of  the  illusion  in  certain  positions  and 
its  disappearance  in  others.  There  is  another  fact  of  false 
judgment  to  which  attention  was  called  in  the  discussion  of 
Fig.  9.  The  distances  along  the  parallels  (in  the  case  of  Fig.  9 
the  vertical  distances)  are  also  misjudged.  For  the  explanation 
of  this  misjudgment  we  have  only  to  refer  back  to  our  earlier 
discussions.  When  horizontal  or  vertical  distances  along  the 
parallel  lines  are  the  subjects  of  attention,  as  they  are  in  the 
usual  positions  of  the  Poggendorff  figure,  those  portions  of  the 
parallels  lying  on  the  obtuse-angle  side  of  the  intercepted  line 
will  be  overestimated.  The  overestimation  of  this  distance  along 
the  parallels  with  the  underestimation  of  the  oblique  distance 
across  the  interval  gives  us  a  full  explanation  of  the  illusion. 
At  the  same  time  we  have  in  the  appearance  and  disappearance 
of  the  typical  Poggendorff  illusion  in  different  positions  of  the 
figure  an  illustration  of  the  fact  that  lines  produce  illusions  only 
when  they  have  some  direct  influence  on  the  particular  direc- 
tion to  which  the  attention  is  turned.  When  the  Poggendorff 
figure  is  in  such  a  position  that  the  intercepted  line  is  horizontal, 
the  false  estimation  of  distances  along  the  parallels  has  no  direct 
bearing  on  the  distance  to  which  the  attention  is  directed.  The 
whole  influence  of  the  parallels  is  there  absorbed  in  aiding  the 


258  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

intercepted  horizontal  line  in  carrying  the  eye  across  the  in- 
terval. When,  on  the  other  hand,  the  length  of  the  parallel 
becomes  itself  a  matter  of  judgment,  as  it  does  when  the  paral- 
lels, instead  of  the  interrupted  line,  are  vertical  or  horizontal, 
then  the  whole  combination  of  conditions  changes.  The  influ- 
ence of  the  intercepted  line  is  such  that  distances  along  the 
parallels  are  overestimated  on  the  obtuse-angle  side  of  the  point 
of  interception.  The  parallels  no  longer  bridge  over  the  inter- 
val so  fully,  and  the  underestimation  is,  therefore,  much  less 
marked. 

In  view  of  all  these  considerations,  both  negative  and  posi- 
tive, we  conclude  that  the  Poggendorff  illusion  is  not  due  to  the 
false  estimation  of  angles.  The  question  now  presents  itself: 
Can  the  Poggendorff  illusion  under  any  conditions  give  rise  to 
a  false  estimation  of  angles?  Fig.  13  furnishes  empirical  evi- 
dence which  goes  to  show  that  it  can.  The  intercepted  line  in 
this  figure  does  not  seem  parallel  to  the  other  oblique  lines,  but 
slopes  in  such  a  way  that  it  seems  to  meet  the  lower  line  at  the 
left  and  the  upper  on  the  right.  This  leads  to  a  discussion  of 
the  general  question :  How  do  we  in  any  case  judge  the  size  of 
angles  ? 

The  discussions  of  the  estimations  of  angles  have  always 
confined  their  attention  to  the  simplest  case  of  such  judgments, 
namely,  those  in  which  the  vertex  is  expressed  in  the  figure. 
Such  a  limitation  of  the  discussion  is  obviously  unwarranted  and 
has  led  to  theories  of  angles  that  are  correspondingly  short- 
sighted. Angles  may  appear,  and  often  do  appear,  in  concrete 
experiences  between  lines  and  surfaces  not  in  direct  contact. 
How  is  it  possible  for  us  to  estimate  these  angles?  Fig.  14  pre- 
sents a  number  of  cases  in  which  lines  were  so  drawn  that  each 
pair  subtends  exactly  the  same  angle.  All  the  lines  marked  A 
are  parallel  and  all  the  lines  marked  B  are  parallel.  The  dif- 
ference in  apparent  size  of  the  angles  is  noticeable  at  once. 

By  means  of  these  figures  let  us  test  Wundfs  hypothesis, 
which  is  that  small  angles  require  relatively  greater  energy  for 
the  eye  to  move  through  them  on  the  general  principle  of 
physical  and  physiological  inertia.  This  greater  energy  of 
movement  is  interpreted  as  due  to  greater  surface  between  the 


GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS.  259 

sides.  Compare  now  the  two  Angles  IV.  and  VI.  at  the  bottom 
of  the  figure.  The  left-hand  figure  shows  ah  angle  to  which 
Wundt's  theory  should  apply  most  admirably  and  we  should 
have  overestimation.  On  the  other  hand,  the  lower  right 
figure  should  be  beyond  the  range  of  application  of  Wundt's 
theory  and  we  should  have  underestimation.  The  appearance 
is,  of  course,  directly  opposed  to  the  theory  in  both  c^ses. 

Or  take  the  Helmholtz  theory  of  contrast  in  direction  of 
movement,  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  the'  greater  and  weaker 
effects  of  contrast  could  explain  the  differences  in  the  estima- 
tions of  the  angles  in  Fig.  14  for  which  the  vertices  are  not 
expressed.  Yet  there  is  a  very  notable  difference  in  the  judged 
sizes  of  these  angles.  The  general  criticism  of  perspective 
theories  seems  to  the  present  writer  to  have  been  so  fully 
carried  out  by  Wundt  that  there  is  no  call  at  this  time  for  a 
repetition.  The  angles  in  Fig.  14,  it  may  be  noted,  are  so 
drawn  that  perspective  influences  play  little,  if  any,  part.  All 
the  lines  are  in  the  same  direction  and  the  lines  are  drawn  from 
the  vertices  obliquely  towards  the  observer. 

The  most  obvious  induction  from  Fig.  14  is  that  the 
judgment  of  the  length  of  the  sides  of  an  angle  is  a  very  im- 
portant factor  in  the  judgment  of  the  size  of  the  angle.  The 
a  priori  probability  which  attaches  to  this  statement  is  so  great 
that  it  seems  hardly  possible  that  it  should  have  been  persistently 
overlooked.  In  addition  to  this  judgment  of  the  length  of  the 
sides,  there  must  also  be  the  judgment  of  the  distance  between 
the  sides  at  a  certain  distance  from  the  vertex.  In  short,  the 
whole  process  is  a  kind  of  triangulation  in  which  the  mind  takes 
into  account  three  factors,  namely,  the  distances  from  the  ver- 
tex at  which  the  measuring  arc  is  to  be  drawn,  and  the  length 
of  that  arc  with  respect  to  the  whole  circumference  of  the 
circle.  Thus  it  is  possible  for  us  to  recognize  an  angle  whether 
we  measure  the  arc  near  its  vertex  or  at  some  distance  from  the 
vertex.  Such  complex  judgment  is,  however,  subject  to  many 
influences  that  produce  illusion.  If,  for  any  reason,  the  arc  is 
judged  too  long,  the  angle  is  overestimated,  or,  vice  versa,  a 
judgment  which  makes  the  arc  too  short  results  in  underesti- 
mation of  the  angle. 


260  CHAS.  H.  JUDD. 

Misjudgment  of  the  length  of  the  sides  may  lead  indirectly 
to  such  false  estimation  of  angles.  Thus,  if  the  subject  is 
asked  to  point  out  the  vertex  for  Angle  IV.  in  Fig.  14,  he  will 
usually  place  it  t$o  far  from  the  lines,  that  is,  he  will  under- 
estimate the  length  of  the  sides.  Conversely,  in  Angle  I.,  he  will 
place  the  vertjgx  on  A  too  near  the  left-hand  extremity  of  B. 

These  facts  apply  with  less  clearness  to  Angles  V.  and  VI. 
VI.  is  underestimated,  but  the  reason  in  this  case  may  be  that 
the  arc  is  underestimated  rather  than  the  length  of  the  sides 
misjudged.  Explanation  of  Angle  VI.  is  difficult.  The 
principle  discovered  in  the  other  cases,  however,  is  of  very  gen- 
eral importance.  It  can  be  brought  into  direct  relation  with 
the  fact  that  all  acute  angles  are  overestimated  and  obtuse 
angles  underestimated.  This  will  appear  from  Fig.  15.  AC 
is  a  line  at  the  middle  point  of  which  (.Z?),  an  oblique  line  equal 
in  length  to  AB  is  drawn.  Since  movement  from  B  to  A  is 
favored  by  BD,  it  follows,  on  the  principle  developed,  that  the 
point  B  will  be  shifted  towards  A.  As  compared  with  BD 
the  line  BA  will  be  underestimated,  and  the  line  BC  will  be 
overestimated.  In  comparing  the  two  angles  DBA  and  DBC 
the  arcs  will,  therefore,  be  estimated  as  cutting  A  C,  not  at  A  and 
C,  but  at  some  points  as  M  and  N.  The  true  arcs  (or  chords) 
of  measurement  are  DA  and  DC,  but  the  chords  used  are  DM 
and  DN.  And  since  DM  is  longer  than  DA,  while  DN  is 
shorter  than  DC,  the  angle  DBA  will  be  overestimated,  while 
the  angle  DBC  is  underestimated. 

In  this  way  it  is  possible  to  explain  all  the  angle  illusions. 
The  movements  upward  and  downward  of  the  lines  in  the 
Zollner  pattern,  as  observed  and  described  by  Helmholtz,  are 
direct  confirmations  of  this  position.  The  successive  fixation  of 
certain  points  in  the  figure  brings  out  the  illusion  of  length,  first 
on  the  side  of  an  acute  angle,  then  on  that  of  an  obtuse  angle. 
The  angles  do  not  suffer  any  further  change  by  such  successive 
fixation,  but  the  presence  of  a  neutral  point  of  reference  gives 
clearness  to  the  illusions  of  length,  that  is,  the  original  source 
of  the  angle  illusion  appears  in  its  simplest  form.  Furthermore, 
it  will  be  found  that  if  Wundt's  and  Hering's  modifications  of 
the  Zollner  figure  are  so  drawn  that  the  extremities  of  the 


\ 

GEOMETRICAL   ILLUSIONS.  261 

» 
different  oblique  lines  are  not  distinctly  marked  (particularly 

the  point  to  which  all  converge),  the  illusion  of  bending  in  the 
horizontals  will  be  very  much  reduced,  i.f  not  entirely  lost. 

Finally,  Figs.  16,  17  and  18  present  angle  and  distance 
illusions  in  such  relation  that  the  principles  discussed  may  be 
directly  applied  and  at  the  same  time  confirmed.  In  Fig.  16 
the  line  AB  seems  to  be  bent  inward  so  that  its  two  parts  if 
continued  would  form  a  very  obtuse  angle  within  the  circle. 
This  is  due  in  part  to  the  underestimation  of  the  sides  of  the 
acute  angle  and  the  overestimation  of  the  arc  between  the 
points  of  interruption.  Furthermore,  the  rapid  increase  in 
the  distance  between  the  line  and  the  circle  beyond  the  points 
of  contact  may  result  in  overestimation  of  the  arc  by  which  the 
angle  would  be  estimated.  In  Figs.  17  and  18  a  part  of 
the  diagonal  is  drawn  in  such  a  way  that  it  extends  for  equal 
distances  on  each  side  of  the  middle  of  the  rectangle.  In 
Fig.  17  it  will  be  noted  that  the  part  of  the  diagonal  seems  to 
meet  the  left  side  of  the  rectangle  below  the  corner,  and  the 
right  side  above  the  corner.  The  illusion  will  be  clearest  if 
the  ends  of  the  line  are  fixated.  It  will  also  be  observed  that 
there  is  a  marked  tendency  for  the  eye  to  pass  in  its  movement, 
not  through  the  longer  distance  from  the  ends  of  the  line  to  the 
corners,  but  from  the  ends  of  the  line  to  the  nearer  right  and 
left  sides  of  the  rectangle.  This  tendency  is  a  full  explanation. 
It  leads  to  the  angle  illusion  through  the  underestimation  of  the 
side.  Fig.  18  combines  a  number  of  the  facts  already  pointed 
out.  The  detailed  analysis  may  be  left  to  the  reader. 


THE   NATURE    OF   ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE  AND 
THE  MFfHODS  OF  INVESTIGATING  IT. 

BY  PROFESSOR  WESLEY  MILLS. 
Me  Gill  University,  Montreal. 

Those  interested  in  this  subject  may  be  classified  in  the  main 
somewhat  as  follows  perhaps  : 

1.  Those  who  see  in  the  animal  mind  only  a  sort  of  weaker 
human  intellect ;  who  look  chiefly  for  evidences  of  intelligence 
and  take  no  account  of  the  failures  and  stupidity  of  animals. 

2.  Those  who  recognize  that  the    animal   mind  is  not  the 
equivalent  of  the  human  mind  in  all  its  qualities  as  it  exists   in 
men  of  superior  development  in  the   highest  civilization,  but 
who  nevertheless  recognize   the  resemblance  up  to   a  certain 
point  to  man. 

3.  Those  who  approach  more  or  less  closely  to  the  view  that 
animals  are  automata,  or  at  all  events  consider  animal  con- 
sciousness as  utterly  different  from  human  consciousness,  except 
in  a  few  of  its  lowest  states.     With  regard  to  investigation  or 
material  of  knowledge  we  recognize  a  class  who,  while  sus- 
picious with  reference  to  the  conclusions  of  the  anecdotal  school, 
do  not  consider  anecdotes  worthless,  much  less  meriting  the 
supreme  contempt   some  writers    manifest  for  such  evidence. 
They  believe  that  there  is  no  more  reason  to  set  aside  reliable 
anecdotes  of  animals  than  of  men.     Anecdotes  may  illustrate  a 
normal,  sub-normal  or  super-normal  mental  condition  or  devel- 
opment ;  but  if  they  set  forth  facts  it  is  for  the  psychologist  to 
explain,  not  to  ignore  them.     Another  class   of  investigators 
see  little  or  no  good  in  anything  in  comparative  psychology  or 
psychology  in  general,  except  experiment,  which  is  for  them 
the  sole  key  to  a  reliable  knowledge  of  the  mind. 

Among  psychologists  as  among  biologists  there  are  those  who 
are  willing  to  shut  themselves  up  in  the  narrow  lane  of  experi- 
262 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE.  263 

ment — a  lane  with  high  walls  on  each  side  cutting  off  all  view 
of  the  surrounding  domain  open  to  general  observation  and  ex- 
perience. As  these  people  see  so  little  themselves  yet  ever  be- 
hold that  little  before  them,  they  come  to  interpret  everything  in 
the  light  of  their  own  limited  observations.  They  insist  on 
others  believing  as  they  do ;  they  would  have  others  wear  the 
fetters  they  have  put  on  themselves ;  all  thinking  must  conform 
to  the  rigid  conditions  in  which  they  are  content  to  live  and 
move  and  have  their  intellectual  being. 

The  only  hope  of  safety  for  the  man  who  engages  in  experiment 
is  ever  to  check  his  observations,  and,  above  all,  his  conclusions, 
by  other  wider  observations  and  those  broad  general  principles 
which  are  like  the  points  of  the  compass  to  the  mariner ;  and  I 
venture  to  suggest  that  it  is  the  failure  to  do  this  which  accounts 
for  the  greater  part  of  the  wrecks  scattered  along  the  shores 
and  over  the  bottom  of  those  seas  traversed  by  the  experimenter 
in  biology  and  psychology. 

As  we  have  had  what  I  cannot  but  think  a  recent  conspicu- 
ous example  of  the  sort  of  neglect  referred  to,  I  propose  to  criti- 
cise the  methods  pursued  and  the  conclusions  drawn,  the  more 
especially  as  this  investigator  claims  to  have  swept  away,  at  one 
fell  swoop,  almost  the  entire  fabric  of  comparative  psychology.1 
He  appears  to  believe  that  he  has  razed  the  old  structure  to  its 
very  foundations  and  settled  once  and  forever  the  weightiest 
problems  with  which  others  have  been  long  struggling  in  vain. 

Dr.  Thorndike  has  not  been  hampered  in  his  researches  by 
any  of  that  respect  for  workers  of  the  past  of  any  complexion 
which  usually  causes  men  to  pause  before  differing  radically 
from  them,  not  to  say  gleefully  consigning  them  to  the  psycholog- 
ical flames.  For  Dr.  Thorndike  the  comparative  psychologists 
are  readily  and  simply  classified — they  are  all  insane — the  only 
difference  being  the  degree,  for  he  speaks  of  one  of  them  as 
being  *  the  sanest '  of  the  lot. 

Having  thus  cleared  the  way,  this  investigator  proceeds  to 
set  forth,  in  no  uncertain  terms,  what  we  should  believe,  and  his 
creed  is  very  brief  and  easily  remembered.  Animals  neither 

1  ANIMAL  INTELLIGENCE,  by  Ed.  L.  Thorndike.  (Monograph  Supplement 
to  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  Vol.  II.,  No.  4,  whole  No.  8.) 


264  WESLEY  MILLS. 

imitate,  feel  sympathetically,  reason  nor  remember,  though  about 
the  latter  point  he  is  not  quite  so  dogmatic.1  He  comes  very 
near  to  the  belief  that  they  are  automata  pure  and  simple, 
though  this  he  does  not  assert  in  so  many  words.  The  above 
mentioned  views  he  thinks  he  has  deduced  from  experiments. 
If  so,  the  present  writer  thinks  so  much  the  worse  for  the  ex- 
periments. At  all  events,  with  the  exception  of  reasoning  about 
which  I  wish  to  reserve  judgment,  I  have  come  to  widely  dif- 
ferent conclusions  and  from  experiments  also  as  well  as  from 
other  sources  of  information. 

Dr.  Thorndike  in  criticising  my  book2  has  given  the  impres- 
sion that  I  have  not  made  experiments,  or  '  crucial  experiments/ 
Now,  I  think  it  can  be  shown  from  my  publications  that  I  have 
recorded  more  experiments  (not  to  mention  scores  which  have 
not  been  described)  than  all  other  investigators  together,  if  we 
except  those  working  on  insects.  Moreover,  these  experiments 
have  been  invariably  conducted  under  natural  conditions,  the 
absence  of  which  seems  to  be  almost  a  recommendation  with 
some,  but  which  I  consider  a  fatal  objection  to  Dr.  Thorn- 
dike's  work.  Incidentally,  I  may  remark  that  a  laboratory  as 
ordinarily  understood  is  not  well  suited  for  making  psycholog- 
ical experiments  on  animals. 

When  Dr.  Thorndike  charges  that  most  of  the  books  do  not 
give  us  a  psychology,  but  rather  a  eulogy  of  animals  ;  that  they 
have  all  been  about  animal  intelligence,  never  about  animal 
stupidity,  I  recognize  a  certain  amount  of  truth  in  the  imputa- 
tion. But  I  beg  to  suggest  that  to  a  certain  extent  the  same 
applies  to  works  on  human  psychology.  To  what  extent  has  the 
mind  of  the  savage  or  semi-barbarous  man  been  investigated  ? 
Yet  to  make  comparisons  between  man  and  the  lower  animals 
parellel  such  a  study  is  essential.  I  do  not  find  Dr.  Thorn- 
dike's  publication  any  freer  than  others  from  the  fallacies  aris- 

1  In  an  account  of  his  own  work  given  by  Dr.  Thorndike  in  Science  (Vol. 
VII.,  p.  823)  he  goes  still  further  in  his  negations.  "Conception,  inference, 
judgment,  memory,  self-consciousness,  social  consciousness,  imagination,  asso- 
ciation and  perception,  in  the  common  acceptation  of  the  terms,  are  all  absent 
from  the  animal  mind." 

2 The  Nature  and  Development  of  Animal  Intelligence.  London,  T.  Fisher 
Unwin  ;  New  York,  The  Macmillan  Company.  1898. 


ANIMAL  INTELLIGENCE.  265 

ing  from  considering  the  superior  class  of  human  minds  or  the 
civilized  and  educated  man,  and  comparing  him  with  the  lower 
animals.  Dr.  Thorndike  considers  his  experiments  crucial ;  that 
individual  peculiarities  have  been  eliminated ;  that  hunger  is  an 
adequate  stimulus  or  condition ;  that  no  personal  factor  need  be 
considered;  that  "  the  question  of  whether  an  animal  does  or 
does  not  form  a  certain  association  requires  for  an  answer  no 
higher  qualification  than  a  pair  of  eyes  " — all  of  which  I  con- 
sider fallacious  and  to  a  large  degree  explanatory  of  the  mis- 
leading psychology  which  he  has  constructed.  With  dogs  I 
found  several  stimuli  stronger  than  hunger,  as  any  one  really 
acquainted  with  the  nature  of  animals  must  know,  and  such 
stimuli  may,  and  frequently  do,  lead  animals  so  to  deport  them- 
selves that  they  become  a  perfect  revelation  to  those  who  have 
long  been  associated  with  them. 

I  had  that  well  illustrated  in  the  case  of  a  tame  fox  (vixen) 
that  I  reared.  When  a  certain  critical  period  (oestrum)  was 
reached  her  whole  nature  took  on  a  new  character,  and  it  be- 
came practically  impossible  to  control  her  as  formerly ;  and, 
unless  I  had  ocular  demonstration  of  the  facts,  I  would  not  have 
believed  it  possible  for  any  animal  to  have  accomplished  what  this 
fox  did.  Nevertheless,  in  order  to  learn  her  methods  of  proced- 
ure it  was  necessary  to  observe  unawares  to  her,  and  that  I  may 
say  applies  to  very  many  studies  of  animals.  That  a  pair  of 
eyes  is  not  all  that  is  requisite  for  a  complete  outfit  as  an  ob- 
server, Dr.  Thorndike's  work  but  too  pointedly  exemplifies.  I 
venture  to  think  that  in  all  cases  it  is  a  question  of  whose  eyes, 
or,  in  other  words,  the  training  those  eyes  have  had,  and  still 
more  of  the  intellect  that  passes  judgment  on  what  is  seen. 

I  have  all  along  endeavored  to  emphasize  the  importance  of 
individual  differences.  They  do  somewhat  disturb  statistics,  and 
they  rather  spoil  curves,  it  is  true,  and  experimenters  have  al- 
ways been  prone  to  ignore  them ;  but  they  exist  in  nature,  and 
when  adequately  recognized  our  explanations  for  many  things 
will  be  found  altogether  too  simple,  and,  therefore,  delusive, 
rather  than  real  and  adequate. 

Dr.  Thorndike  admits  that  «  an  act  of  the  sort  likely  to  be 
attended  to  will  be  learned  more  quickly.'  Undoubtedly,  yet 


266  WESLEY  MILLS. 

this  investigator  has  practically  ignored  this  in  his  tests,  for  he 
placed  cats  in  boxes  only  20x15x12  inches,  and  then  ex- 
pected them  to  act  naturally.  As  well  enclose  a  living  man  in 
a  coffin,  lower  him,  against  his  will,  into  the  earth,  and  attempt 
to  deduce  normal  psychology  from  his  conduct. 

The  present  writer  has  pointed  out  distinctly  that  when  ani- 
mals are  removed  from  even  their  usual,  not  to  say  natural,  sur- 
roundings they  may  be  so  confused  or  otherwise  diordered  that 
they  fail  to  act  normally,  and  this  I  have  illustrated  by  experi- 
ments. Dr.  Thorndike  found  that  dogs  when  placed  under  simi- 
larly improper  and  disturbing  conditions,  as  I  deem  them,  be- 
haved in  a  like  panicky  way,  except  that  they  gave  up  sooner, 
which  he  attributes  in  part  to  their  being  insufficiently  hungry. 
But  dogs  have  not  as  much  perseverance  as  cats,  as  my  experi- 
ments abundantly  prove.  However,  had  Dr.  Thorndike  wit- 
nessed the  resources  of  my  dogs  when  let  loose  in  the  yard  after 
some  of  their  companions,  which  had  already  been  set  free  in  the 
adjoining  fields  and  woods,  I  can  believe  that  even  one  so  fast 
bound  in  the  grip  of  his  experiments  as  he  would  have  altered 
his  opinions  on  this  and  many  other  subjects.  In  dogs  under  such 
circumstances  we  have  illustrated  not  alone  an  adequate  motive 
or  stimulus,  but  it  is  shown  that  they  have  memory — can  conjure 
up  exciting  pictures  of  the  pleasure-giving  scenes  of  the  past, 
re-experience  in  some  fashion  the  delights  associated  with 
that  past,  make  a  sort  of  generalized  abstract  of  the  whole — in 
a  word,  have  very  much  the  same  experiences  as  the  human 
being  who  accompanies  them  and  delights  in  such  things. 

When  the  contrary  is  proved  by  adequate  observations  or 
experiments,  I  am  ready  to  alter  my  opinions,  but  not  on  such 
evidence  as  seems  to  go  directly  counter  to  all  that  one  has 
borne  in  upon  him  by  daily  observation.  To  do  otherwise  is, 
indeed,  to  bid  adieu  to  common  sense  as  well  as  to  science,  and 
to  accept  as  proof  what  seems  to  me  of  no  more  value  than 
counterfeit  coins,  but  which,  nevertheless,  like  bogus  money,  de- 
ceives the  unwary,  even  among  psychologists. 

The  experiments  on  chicks  I  consider  the  least  misleading 
and  most  valuable  part  of  Dr.  Thorndike's  work.  Not  only  are 
birds  much  lower  in  the  psychological  scale ;  not  only  does  free 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE.  267 

association  explain  more  in  their  case,  but  the  conditions  of  the 
experiments  were  rather  more  natural.  A  pen  16x14x10 
makes  for  a  chick  a  very  different  thing  from  one  20  x  15  X  12 
for  a  cat.  Even  those  curves  which  in  the  case  of  the  cats  and 
dogs  only  serve  to  stereotype  error  are  possibly  of  some  value 
when  applied  to  the  chicks.  Says  Dr.  Thorndike  :  "  I  hate 
to  burden  the  reader  with  the  disgusting  rhetoric  which  would 
result  if  I  had  to  insist  on  particularizations  and  reservations  at 
every  step."  If  anything,  just  such  particulars  might  have  some- 
what redeemed  these  experiments.  They  might  at  least  have 
proved  helpful  in  some  way.  At  the  present  stage  of  compara- 
tive psychology  we  are  in  need  of  observations  down  to  the 
minutest  details.  We  can  better  spare  the  rhetoric. 

When  we  consider  how  widespread — indeed,  almost  univer- 
sal— is  imitation  among  animals  of  the  middle  and  higher  grades, 
that  it  is  difficult  so  to  separate  it  from  the  general  psychic  life  of 
the  animal  as  to  be  able  fairly  to  analyze  their  mental  processes 
and  determine  how  much  is  due  to  independent  development  $er 
se  and  how  much  to  imitation,  one  cannot  but  marvel  at  the  de- 
gree to  which  that  magic  word  of  modern  science  '  experiment ' 
can  blind  the  mind  to  facts  thick  as  the  leaves  of  the  forest,  and 
all  pointing  to  the  importance  of  imitation  in  animal  life.  So 
obvious  an  example  of  imitation  as  the  talking  of  parrots  is  set 
aside  or  twisted  out  of  all  recognition.  It  is,  moreover,  a  case  of 
heads  I  win,  tails  you  lose.  Much  that  Dr.  Thorndike  has  said 
when  discussing  this  subject  is  valuable  as  suggesting  a  basis 
for  observation  and  on  the  genesis  of  imitation,  though  this  ap- 
plies also  to  human  psychology.  There  is  one  fallacy  that  un- 
derlies the  whole  of  Dr.  Thorndike's  experimenting  and  vitiates 
his  conclusions,  namely,  this :  that  he  overlooks  the  many  pos- 
sible and  actual  inhibitions  to  response  to  a  stimulus.  One 
would  have  thought  that  the  case  of  the  cat  mentioned  by  him 
(p.  59)  would  have  given  him  pause.  The  conduct  of  that  cat, 
like  all  the  rest,  only  proves  to  him  that  animals  do  not  imitate. 

I  find  myself  ever  disposed  to  imitate  in  certain  cases,  yet  do 
not.  To  illustrate — when  I  read  a  chapter  on  psychology  writ- 
ten in  the  fascinating  style  of  James,  one  exemplifying  the  pro- 
fundity of  a  Ladd  or  a  Hall,  the  bold  constructive  character  of  a 


268  WESLEY  MILLS. 

Baldwin,  or  a  vigorous  plea  on  behalf  of  modern  psychology  by 
Cattell — the  list  might  be  much  enlarged — I  am  filled  with  ad- 
miration, and  there  is  an  impulse  to  imitate,  but  I  have  not  as  yet 
taken  the  first  step.  Having  thus  been  the  subject  of  experi- 
ment in  this  way  over  and  over  again,  I  should,  according  to 
the  logic  of  Dr.  Thorndike,  be  characterized  as  a  non-imitating 
creature — not  only  as  regards  the  subject  in  question,  but  gen- 
erally. The  truth  is  far  from  this.  There  is  a  strong  tendency 
on  my  part  to  imitate,  but  there  are  stronger  forces  acting  to  in- 
hibit the  process,  and,  moreover,  these  forces  are  not  always  the 
same  nor  is  each  always  equally  potent.  In  truth,  the  whole 
matter  is  very  complex  even  in  animals.  I  find  no  difficulty 
whatever  in  explaining  why  the  animals  did  not  respond  to  the 
stimuli  Dr.  Thorndike  used. 

When  one  meets  the  questionaires  he  seems  at  last  to  strike 
the  rock  bottom  of  common  sense.  The  author  of  the  experi- 
ments referred  to  has  no  high  opinion  of  the  trainers.  "  I 
would  first  adjust  all  things  in  connection  with  the  surroundings 
of  the  cat  so  that  they  would  be  applicable  to  the  laws  of  nature, 
and  then  proceed  to  teach  the  trick."  I  see  much  saving  sense 
in  this  remark,  and  believe  that  had  Dr.  Thorndike  grasped  its 
significance  he  would  have  given  us  a  very  different  psy- 
chology. The  writer  seems  to  have  totally  neglected  the 
methods  and  experience  of  the  trainers  of  dogs  for  field  work, 
and  has  also  I  believe  failed  to  make  use  of  the  lessons  the 
trainers  of  trick  animals  can  teach  us.  Even  to  witness  a  per- 
formance of  trick  animals  is  enough  to  enable  one  to  see  how 
at  one  time  the  tendency  to  imitate  assists  and  at  another  mars 
the  performance.  To  be  sure,  there  is  a  sort  of  deliberate, 
studied,  high-class  imitation  possible  to  man,  but  beyond  the 
reach  of  animals,  but  this  is,  after  all,  comparatively  rarely  em- 
ployed in  the  lives  of  the  great  mass  of  men. 

A  student  of  McGill  University  has  communicated  to  me 
the  fact  that  a  kitten  which  could  not  be  induced  to  jump  over 
an  object  placed  before  it  did  so  only  after  seeing  the  mother 
do  it,  and  after  that  there  was  no  more  trouble  in  getting  it  to  per- 
form the  trick.  The  young  hounds  of  the  Montreal  Hunt  Club 
are  taught  by  being  actually  put  through  the  performance,  t.  e., 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE.  269 

they  are  attached  to  an  old  and  strong  dog  while  hunting,  so 
that  Dr.  Thorndike's  contention  as  to  the  uselessness  of  an  ani- 
mal's being  put  through  a  performance  breaks  down.  Indeed, 
that  was  to  be  expected  even  from  his  own  teaching  as  to  the 
genesis  of  associations,  to  go  no  further.  As  to  the  inability  of 
animals  to  have  memory  images  for  which  Dr.  Thorndike  con- 
tends I  find  myself,  in  the  light  of  my  experience  with  animals, 
quite  unable  to  agree.  I  believe  that  their  memory  is  like  our 
memory  of  the  same  things  so  far  as  image,  etc.,  are  concerned, 
but  that  there  may  be  with  man,  owing  to  the  complexity  of  his 
mental  condition,  a  more  varied  fringe  around  that  memory  core 
which  latter  will  be  much  alike  in  both  the  man  and  the  animal. 

To  refer  to  but  a  single  experiment  to  illustrate  this :  I  had 
a  greyhound  that  was  very  prone  to  chase  cats,  a  habit  which  be- 
came with  him  more  and  more  pronounced,  I  presume,  from  his 
success  in  consequence  of  his  speed.  On  the  occasion  I  wish 
to  emphasize  I  had  taken  the  dog  in  a  certain  direction,  and,  as 
a  result,  a  cat  crossing  the  street  was  so  hotly  pursued  by  him 
that  she  took  to  a  tree.  Many  months  after  I  brought  the  dog 
along  this  same  way,  but  approached  the  scene  of  the  exciting 
chase  from  the  opposite  direction.  Long  before  the  exact  spot 
was  reached  the  dog  was  all  attention.  It  was  perfectly  plain 
that  he  remembered  the  long-past  incident,  and  that  certain  feel- 
ings (which  accompanying  feelings  Dr.  Thorndike  denies  to 
animals')  were  also  aroused ;  but  great  was  my  astonishment 
when  the  dog  stopped  at  a  certain  tree,  looked  up  and  behaved 
otherwise  in  such  a  manner  as  left  no  doubt  in  my  mind  that  he 
remembered  the  identical  tree  and  every  detail  of  the  whole  inci- 
dent. This  cannot  be  explained  by  the  sort  of  consecutive  as- 
sociation that  Dr.  Thorndike  would  substitute  for  *  memory '  as 
ordinarily  understood,  for  the  locality  was  approached  from  the 
opposite  direction. 

The  central  phenomena  of  memory  were  in  this  case  the 
same  with  the  dog  and  his  master,  but  the  feelings  and  the  men- 
tal fringe  or  associated  ideas  were  not  identical.  In  the  one  case 
they  were  appropriate  to  the  dog,  in  the  other  to  the  man,  his 
master,  who  was  in  this  instance  trying  to  draw  some  psycho- 
logical conclusions,  so  the  difference  was  considerable ;  but  had 


270  WESLEY  MILLb. 

it  been  a  hunting  expedition  in  which  both  dog  and  man  took 
an  active  part,  the  resemblance  even  in  revival  would  have  been 
altogether  greater. 

One  finds  in  the  end,  however,  that  Dr.  Thorndike  does  allow 
representation  to  animals  within  very  narrow  limits.  Along  with 
this  writer's  "  I  never  succeeded  in  getting  the  animal  to  change 
its  way  for  mine,"  a  quotation  from  a  recent  interesting  and 
instructive  publication  seems  timely:  "  One  must  be  familiar 
with  the  normal  conditions  of  the  insects  in  question  before  he 
is  able  to  note  those  slight  changes  in  the  environment  that  offer 
some  opportunity  for  an  adaptation  of  means  to  ends,  or  before  he 
is  competent  to  devise  experiments  which  test  their  powers  in 
this  direction."1  The  above  seems  to  the  present  writer  to  be 
applicable  in  the  widest  sense  to  investigations  in  comparative 
psychology. 

The  experiments  to  which  Dr.  Thorndike  refers  under  the 
heading  '  Association  by  Similarity  and  the  Formation  of  Con- 
cepts' only  really  show  that  animals  may  react  to  a  vague 
stimulus,  and  this  is  quite  sufficient  to  meet  the  ends  of  their  ex- 
istence in  many  cases ;  but  neither  these  experiments  nor  any 
others  show  conclusively  that  this  alone  is  the  best  of  which  ani- 
mals are  capable.  The  comparison  of  animal  consciousness  to 
human  consciousness  during  swimming  is  open  to  the  same  ob- 
jection. Such  a  mental  state  is  possible  to  both  man  and  ani- 
mals, but  neither  is  confined  within  such  narrow  limits  of  almost 
pure  sensation. 

I  must  object  to  Dr.  Thorndike's  analysis  of  human  conscious- 
ness in  playing  open-air  games  as  being  inadequate.  It  does 
not  correspond  with  my  own  experience  nor  with  the  accounts  I 
have  heard  persons  of  different  degrees  of  skill  give  as  to  what 
was  going  on  in  their  minds  during  the  playing  of  games.  No 
doubt  Dr.  Thorndike's  account  does  fit  a  certain  portion  of  the 
mental  phenomena,  but  the  whole  matter  is  much  more  complex 
than  he  seems  to  think,  and  is  worthy  of  an  analysis  more  ac- 
curate and  comprehensive  than  has  ever  been  given  to  it.  Such 
views  of  animal  consciousness  as  Dr.  Thorndike  presents  seem 

instincts  and  Habits  of  the  Solitary  Wasps,  by  Geo.  W.  Peckham  and 
Elizabeth  G.  Peckham,  p.  234. 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE.  271 

to  me  altogether  too  narrow  to  meet  the  actual  mental  condition 
of,  say,  a  dog  when  engaged  in  a  fowling  expedition. 

From  certain  experiments  which  I  made  with  my  dogs  in 
play,  taken  along  with  scores  of  others,  I  find  myself  utterly 
unable  to  agree  with  many  of  the  views  of  the  destructive  or  nar- 
rowly restrictive  school  of  comparative  psychologists.  We 
should  surely  be  very  cautious  in  denying  wholly  to  animals 
what  Dr.  Thorndike  terms  *  free  floating  ideas.'  The  believer  in 
evolution  will  demand  that,  in  this  and  other  cases  in  which 
qualities  man  possesses  are  denied  to  animals,  there  be  the  clearest 
proofs  given.  The  burden  of  proof  lies  with  those  who  deny 
them,  and  this  remark  applies  to  feelings  as  well  as  intellectual 
processes,  though  to  a  less  degree.  Nor  can  I  agree  with  those 
who  maintain  that  we  must  always  adopt  the  simplest  explana- 
tion of  an  animal's  action.  Such  does  not  apply  to  man,  and 
why  should  it  meet  every  case  among  animals  ?  Though  in  this 
regard  Professor  C.  LI.  Morgan  with  others  seems  to  me  to  be 
in  error,  I  fully  agree  with  the  views  of  this  writer  as  quoted 
in  the  publication  under  consideration  (p.  86)  :  "  Lastly,  before 
taking  leave  of  the  subject  of  the  chapter,  I  am  most  anxious 
that  it  should  not  be  thought  that  in  contending  that  intelligence 
is  not  reason  I  wish  in  any  way  to  disparage  intelligence,"  etc. 
But  Professor  Morgan  is  more  and  more  in  sympathy  with 
the  destructive  school,  so  that  he  now  seems  willing  to  surrender 
anything  to  all  and  sundry  who  may  ask  him  to  stand  and  de- 
liver. I  have  been  myself  classed  by  one  of  my  reviewers1  with 
Romanes.  While  I  agree  with  much  in  Romanes'  attitude  in 
regard  to  animal  intelligence,  nevertheless,  since  this  writer  pre- 
ferred to  work  upon  second-hand  material  rather  than  make 
observations  and  experiments  for  himself,  and  had,  moreover, 
a  tendency  to  speculation  rather  than  the  accumulation  and 
weighing  of  facts,  I  prefer  to  be  myself  considered  an  humble 
follower  of  Darwin,  who,  so  far  as  he  went  in  animal  psychol- 
ogy, best  illustrates  the  method  and  especially  the  spirit  that 
will,  I  think,  prove  most  fruitful. 

The  one  point  about  which  I  feel  like  withholding  an  opinion 
till  many  more  observations  have  been  made  is  that  of  reasoning. 

1  Science,  Vol.  VIII.,  p.  520. 


272  WESLEY  MILLS. 

That  animals  can  reach  C  by  some  mental  process  when  A  and 
B  are  given,  and  that  this  is  to  be  explained  either  by  some  pro- 
cess of  inference  or  by  one  as  yet  unexplained,  I  have  little 
doubt.  Unquestionably,  association  explains  much  in  the  mental 
structure  of  man  and  still  more  in  animals,  but  that  this  is 
the  whole  story  when  we  get  beyond  elementary  chapters  in 
instinct  I  cannot  for  a  moment  believe,  unless  the  meaning  of 
the  word  is  greatly  and  unwisely  extended.  The  subconscious 
must  enter  largely  into  the  psychic  life  of  animals,  as  of  men, 
and  one  who  observes  animals  long  and  closely  must  believe 
that  no  such  naked  skeleton  as  Dr.  Thorndike  presents  to  us 
can  represent  the  animal  mind. 

The  mental  processes  of  an  animal  are  generally  not  com- 
parable to  pure  tones,  but  rather  like  those  tones  that  abound  in 
overtones,  though  this  applies  still  more  to  man.  Our  age  will 
probably  be  looked  back  upon  as  one  characterized  intellectually 
by  great  destructive  and  constructive  activity,  but  also  as  one 
readily  satisfied  with  unduly  simple  explanations  put  forward 
with  a  confidence  and  rashness  that  will  be  astounding  to  a  later 
age.  As  showing,  however,  a  different  spirit  and  tendency  I 
quote  the  following 1  with  much  gratification,  coming,  as  it  does, 
from  two  most  patient,  sympathetic  and  successful  observers : 
"  Our  study  of  the  activities  of  wasps  has  satisfied  us  that  it  is 
impossible  to  classify  them  in  any  simple  way.  The  old 
notion  that  the  acts  of  bees,  wasps  and  ants  were  all  varying 
forms  of  instinct  is  no  longer  tenable  and  must  give  way  to  a 
more  philosophical  view.  It  would  appear  to  be  quite  certain 
that  these  are  not  only  instinctive  acts,  but  acts  of  intelligence 
as  well,  and  a  third  variety  also — acts  that  are  probably  due  to 
imitation,  although  whether  much  or  little  intelligence  accom- 
panies this  imitation  is  admittedly  difficult  to  determine. 
Again,  acts  that  are  instinctive  in  one  species  may  be  intelligent 
in  another,  and  we  may  even  assert  that  there  is  considerable 
variation  in  the  amount  of  intelligence  displayed  by  different 
individuals  of  the  same  species.'* 

The  same  may,  I  believe,  be  affirmed  for  animals  generally ; 
and  it  is  work  of  the  character  described  in  the  monograph 

JOp.  cit.,  p.  228. 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE.  273 

from  which  I  quote  which  really  advances  comparative 
psychology. 

Were  it  possible  to  observe  an  animal,  say  a  dog,  from  the 
moment  of  its  birth  onward  continuously  for  one  year,  noting 
the  precise  conditions  and  all  that  happens  under  these  condi- 
tions, the  observer  being  unnoticed  by  the  creature  studied,  we 
should,  I  believe,  be  in  possession  of  one  of  the  most  valuable  con- 
tributions it  is  possible  to  make  to  comparative  psychology.  This 
would  imply  not  one,  but  several  persons  giving  up  their  whole 
time,  day  and  night,  by  turns,  to  such  a  task.  As  yet,  but  very 
imperfect  approaches  have  been  made  to  anything  of  the  kind ; 
nevertheless,  such  as  they  have  been,  they  are  the  most  valuable 
contributions  thus  made,  in  the  opinion  of  the  present  writer,  and 
the  more  of  such  we  have  the  better. 

If  to  such  a  study  another  were  added,  in  which  the  effect  of 
altering  conditions  from  time  to  time  with  the  special  object  of 
testing  the  results  on  an  animal  or  animals  similarly  closely 
observed  from  birth  onward,  we  should  have  another  most  val- 
uable contribution  to  comparative  psychology ;  but  experiment 
on  animals  whose  history  is  unknown  must,  in  the  nature  of  the 
case,  be  very  much  less  valuable  than  in  such  an  instance  as 
that  just  supposed. 

As  Professor  Groos  has  suggested  in  a  private  communica- 
tion to  me,  it  is  important  to  make  observations  on  wild  animals, 
and  there  seems  to  be  room  for  the  worker  in  comparative  psy- 
chology in  zoological  gardens  as  well  as  in  the  field  or  forest. 
But  I  must  again  maintain  that  it  is  fact  rather  than  theory — ob- 
servation, as  ordinarily  understood,  and  experiment — that  are 
more  needed  than  anything  else  as  yet. 

RESUME. 

Comparative  psychology  is  advanced  rather  by  systematic 
observations  and  experiments  than  by  anecdotes ;  nevertheless, 
the  latter,  when  strictly  true,  are  not  valueless. 

The  study  of  the  development  of  the  animal  mind  (genetic 
psychology)  is  of  the  highest  importance. 

Insufficient  attention  has  been  paid  to  distinguishing  between 
normal,  subnormal  and  super-normal  comparative  psychology ; 


274  WESLEY  MILLS. 

an  objection,  however,  which  applies  with  a  certain  degree  of 
force  to  human  psychology. 

In  making  experiments  on  animals  it  is  especially  important 
that  they  should  be  placed  under  conditions  as  natural  as  pos- 
sible. The  neglect  of  this  is  a  fatal  objection  to  the  work  of 
the  author  of  '  Animal  Intelligence,'  published  as  a  monograph 
supplement  to  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  Vol  II.,  No.  8, 
1898. 

The  portion  of  this  research  referring  to  chicks  is  the  most 
reliable,  and  the  suggestions  as  to  pedagogics,  etc.,  valuable. 

This  investigator's  experiments  show  that  certain  associations 
may  be  formed  under  conditions  highly  unnatural,  which  as- 
sociations bear  about  the  same  relation  to  the  normal  psychic 
evolution  of  animals  as  the  behavior  of  more  or  less  panic- 
stricken  or  otherwise  abnormal  human  beings  does  to  their 
natural  conduct. 

It  is  not  proved,  as  asserted  in  the  publication  referred  to, 
that  animals  do  not  imitate,  remember,  have  social  conscious- 
ness, imagination,  association,  and  perception  ;  nor  that  their  con- 
sciousness is  only  comparable  to  that  of  a  human  being  during 
swimming  or  when  playing  out-door  games,  as  understood  by 
this  writer. 

It  is  highly  probable  that  animals,  even  the  highest  below 
man,  have  only  rarely  and  at  the  best  but  a  feeble  self-conscious- 
ness, if  it  exist  at  all. 

But  on  this  point  and  on  the  question  of  inference,  reason- 
ing, etc.,  the  time  is  not  yet  ripe  for  positive  assertions. 

It  seems  more  than  probable  that  the  mental  processes  of  the 
highest  animals  are  not  radically  different  from  those  of  men  so 
far  as  they  go,  but  that  the  human  mind  has  capacities  in  the 
realms  both  of  feeling  and  intellection  to  which  animals  cannot 
attain.  While  it  is  desirable  to  push  analysis  as  far  as  possible 
it  is  safer  to  remain  in  the  region  of  the  indefinite,  to  refrain  from 
making  very  precise  and  positive  statements  as  to  whether  the 
animal  mind  does  or  does  not  possess  certain  powers,  till  we  are 
in  possession  of  a  larger  storehouse  of  facts,  especially  of  the 
nature  of  exact  and  systematic  observations  (or  experiments). 
Festinate  lente  is  a  good  rule  to  observe  in  regard  to  conclusions 
in  comparative  psychology. 


THE  DEVELOPMENT  OF  VOLUNTARY  MOVEMENT. 

BY  PROFESSOR  E.  A.  KIRKPATRICK. 

Fitchburgi  Mass. 

The  work  of  a  train  dispatcher  who  has  to  direct  the  move- 
ments and  stoppages  of  a  few  score  of  trains  so  that  there  will 
be  no  delays  or  collisions  is  justly  regarded  as  very  difficult,  and 
the  brightest  minds  must  go  through  years  of  training  before 
they  are  equal  to  the  task.  The  child,  however,  who  gets  up 
from  his  play  and  brings  us  a  book,  and  then  resumes  his  seat, 
performs  an  act  of  much  greater  complexity  and  nicety  of  ad- 
justment, for  as  large  a  number  of  muscles  as  trains  are  moved, 
and  an  impulse  passes  to  and  from  each  muscle ;  all  these  move- 
ments and  adjustments  take  place  in  a  few  seconds,  and  a  varia- 
tion of  a  fraction  of  a  second  in  the  order  of  contraction  inter- 
feres with  the  grace  and  accuracy  of  the  movements  as  much  as 
the  variation  of  a  fraction  of  an  hour  in  the  time  of  trains 
interferes  with  their  successful  movement. 

Without  previous  practice,  pigs,  chickens  and  many  other 
animals  can  coordinate  visual  sensations  and  movements  so  as 
to  walk  or  run,  avoiding  obstacles  and  adapting  themselves  to  the 
nature  of  the  ground.  Young  chickens  can  move  towards  and 
pick  up  food  with  only  a  little  less  accuracy  than  adult  chickens. 
The  human  infant  has  not  such  power  of  motor  control  at  birth, 
and  our  problem  is  to  determine  how  he  comes  into  possession 
of  it  within  a  year  or  two.  First,  it  is  popularly  thought  that  he 
learns  how  to  make  the  movements  ;  second,  it  may  be  claimed 
that  the  power  to  make  such  movements  is  inherited,  just  as  it  is 
in  the  case  of  the  chicken,  except  that  the  mechanism  is  not 
complete  for  some  time  after  birth,  as  is  known  to  be  the  case 
with  birds  as  regards  flying ;  third,  it  may  be  claimed  that  the 
movements  are  partially  provided  for  by  the  inherited  mechanism 
and  partly  acquired  and  learned. 

275 


276  E.   A.   KIRKPATRICK. 

As  to  the  first  supposition,  the  evidence  is  overwhelmingly 
against  the  possibility  of  such  a  stupendous  task  being  per- 
formed by  a  child  in  the  short  space  of  a  few  years.  He  has 
over  four  hundred  muscles,  and  these  may  be  combined  in  prac- 
tically an  infinite  number  of  different  ways.  If  it  depended  en- 
tirely upon  chance  or  the  child's  ingenuity  whether  he  should 
find  the  right  combination  for  any  movement,  as  reaching  for  a 
ball  and  passing  it  from  one  hand  to  the  other,  he  might  work 
during  his  whole  lifetime  at  that  one  puzzle  before  he  would  be 
likely  to  solve  it  by  getting  exactly  the  right  muscles  and  in  the 
right  combinations. 

The  second  theory,  though  contrary  to  ordinary  observation 
and  opinion,  has  many  facts  to  support  it.  For  example,  it  is 
well  known  that  children  and  even  adults  who  have  never 
learned  to  swim  sometimes  succeed  in  swimming  ashore  when 
left  in  the  water  with  nothing  to  do  but  sink.  Fathers  some- 
times use  this  method  of  teaching  their  sons  to  swim.  Many 
parents  have  noticed  that  their  children  learned  to  walk  and 
run  with  surprising  rapidity  after  they  began.  The  most  strik- 
ing instance  of  this  kind  coming  under  my  notice  is  thus  de- 
scribed for  me  by  the  father,  Supt.  Hall,  of  North  Adams, 
Mass. 

"  In  reply  to  yours  of  March  25th,  I  give  you  the  following 
account  of  how  my  little  daughter  Katherine  learned  to  walk. 
She  was  the  youngest  of  a  family  of  five.  The  other  children 
had  learned  to  walk  soon  after  they  were  a  year  old,  and  in  the 
normal  fashion  by  being  encouraged  to  put  forth  a  series  of 
efforts  until  they  were  able  to  go  alone.  Katherine  was  a 
normal  child  in  other  respects,  bright,  active  and  healthy,  yet 
unable  to  walk  a  step  when  she  was  seventeen  months  old.  Of 
course,  we  were  anxious,  fearing  that  the  cause  of  this  ineffi- 
ciency might  be  physical,  especially  as  she  persisted  in  crawl- 
ing and  absolutely  refused  to  try  to  help  herself  under  the 
encouragement  of  any  assistance. 

"At  last  we  referred  the  matter  to  a  physician,  who  said: 
*  It  is  a  peculiar  case,  and  I  can  hardly  tell  whether  the  diffi- 
culty is  physical  or  mental.  If  there  is  no  improvement  in  a 
short  time,  call  me  again.'  Shortly  afterwards  I  came  home 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   VOLUNTARY  MOVEMENT.          277 

one  day  at  noon,  and,  placing  my  cuffs  on  a  table  in  the  sitting- 
room,  threw  myself  on  a  lounge  to  rest.  Katherine  happened 
to  notice  the  cuffs  from  where  she  sat  on  the  floor,  and,  crawl- 
ing across  the  room,  pulled  herself  up  by  the  leg  of  the  table, 
and,  reaching  out  with  one  hand  while  she  held  on  to  the  table 
with  the  other,  took  a  cuff  off  from  the  table  and  slipped  it  on 
over  her  wrist.  Of  course,  to  do  this  she  had  to  stand  alone. 
I  noticed  it  at  once,  and  was  surprised  when  she  reached  out 
her  other  hand  for  the  other  cuff  and  slipped  that  on,  and  then 
stood  looking  in  a  very  interested  way  at  the  cuffs  on  both 
wrists.  Then,  to  our  great  surprise,  she  turned  towards  me 
with  a  very  pleased  expression  on  her  face  and  walked  as  con- 
fidently and  easily  as  any  child  could.  Not  only  this,  but  she 
immediately  ran  across  the  room,  through  another  room  and 
around  through  the  hall-way,  not  simply  walking,  but  running 
as  rapidly  as  a  child  four  or  five  years  of  age  would.  What 
surprised  us  most  was  that  she  did  not  seem  to  be  wearied  by 
her  effort  at  all. 

"  We  allowed  her  to  keep  the  cuffs  on  for  ten  minutes  or  more, 
and  she  was  on  her  feet  all  the  time.  At  last  she  sat  down  a 
moment,  rested,  and  then,  strange  to  say,  got  up  on  both  feet 
without  assistance  and  commenced  to  run  around  the  room  again. 
As  an  experiment,  I  took  the  cuffs  off,  and  she  was  as  unwil- 
ling to  try  to  walk  as  before.  We  could  not  possibly  induce 
her  to  take  a  single  step  without  the  cuffs.  When,  however, 
we  allowed  her  to  put  them  on,  she  seemed  to  be  greatly  de- 
lighted and  walked  and  ran  as  before.  The  result  was  that  I 
gave  her  an  old  pair  of  cuffs  to  put  on  and  allowed  her  to  wear 
them  for  two  days.  This  was  the  only  way  we  could  keep  her 
from  crawling.  After  that  time  she  seemed  to  be  able  to  get 
along  without  the  cuffs,  and  has  not  crawled  any  since." 

Instances  similar  to  this  of  sudden  acquisition  of  control  of  the 
vocal  organs  are  not  unusual.  Numerous  cases  of  remarkable 
movements  by  somnambulists  and  by  persons  frightened  or  ex- 
cited are  so  common  that  it  is  sometimes  said  that  instinctive 
action  is  more  perfect  than  deliberate  action.  The  fact  that 
such  instances  are  rare,  while  most  children  seem  to  spend 
considerable  time  in  learning  movements,  is  not  positive  proof 


278  E.   A.   KIRKPATRICK. 

that  such  movements  as  walking  and  swimming  are  not  inher- 
ited movements.  It  may  be  claimed  that  as  fast  as  the  nervous 
and  muscular  systems  develop  the  child  begins  making  the 
movements  which  when  combined  with  others  constitute  the 
movements  of  walking ;  but  that  those  movements  ordinarily 
looked  upon  as  practice  and  regarded  as  the  cause  of  nervous 
and  muscular  development  are  in  reality  merely  the  effect  and 
sign  of  the  hereditary  perfectment  of  the  nervous  and  muscular 
systems  which  is  going  on.  Such  movements  as  those  of  walk- 
ing and  swimming  may,  therefore,  be  wholly  hereditary,  but 
it  seems  reasonable  to  suppose  that  the  development  of  those 
movements  is  hastened  and  in  part  produced  by  practice,  and 
certainly  it  cannot  be  claimed  that  all  the  various  movements  of 
work  and  play  which  human  beings  perform  are  inherited  rather 
than  acquired,  especially  when  it  comes  to  the  manipulation  of 
tools. 

The  third  theory  is  the  one  more  commonly  held  by  psychol- 
ogists and  physiologists,  and  in  a  general  way  is  probably  the 
most  nearly  correct,  but  in  my  judgment  it  needs  to  be  modified  in 
the  direction  of  the  last  and  made  much  more  definite.  Observa- 
tion of  young  children  has  shown  clearly  that  the  infant  inherits 
the  power  to  make  many  reflex,  instinctive,  expressive  and  im- 
pulsive movements,  and  that  these  simpler  movements  are  com- 
bined in  performing  the  various  voluntary  movements  which  he 
afterwards  performs.  It  seems  to  be  the  common  opinion  that 
chance  and  imitation  are  important  factors  in  effecting  such  com- 
binations, while  some  seem  to  think  that  the  child  learns  the 
simpler  movements  and  then  by  an  act  of  constructive  imagina- 
tion combines  them  in  the  proper  way  to  effect  his  purposes. 
Professor  Baldwin,  who  has  perhaps  contributed  more  than  any 
one  else  to  the  subject,  has  in  part  eliminated  chance  by  show- 
ing that  there  is  a  tendency  in  every  organism  so  to  act  as  to  con- 
tinue, increase  or  repeat  favorable  stimuli.  The  performance, 
repetition  and  perfectment  of  a  movement  do  not,  therefore, 
depend  entirely  upon  the  chance  production  or  repetition  of  the 
stimulus  by  the  environment,  but  the  tendency  in  the  animal  to 
the  circular  form  of  reaction  causes  the  stimulus  to  be  repeated 
again  and  again.  He  does  not,  however,  make  sufficiently  clear 


DEVELOPMENT  OF   VOLUNTARY  MOVEMENT.          279 

the  physiological  basis  of  this  tendency,  and  he  seems  to  allow 
too  large  an  element  of  chance  in  the  determination  of  the  course 
of  nervous  impulses  within  the  organism.  When  a  child  repeats 
again  and  again  a  sound,  as  children  so  often  do  in  the  third  quar- 
ter of  the  first  year,  it  must  be  because  the  auditory  sensory  center 
is  in  closer  connection  with  the  motor  center  for  the  vocal  organs 
than  with  any  other  motor  center ;  otherwise  the  limbs  would  be 
just  as  likely  to  move  as  the  vocal  organs.  More  than  this,  the 
sensory  center  for  that  sound  must  be  more  closely  connected 
with  the  center  for  producing  it,  or  else  any  other  sound  would 
be  just  as  likely  to  be  made.  There  are  probably  more  than  a 
score  of  muscles  concerned  in  articulation,  and  only  when  just 
the  right  ones  contract  in  just  the  right  degree  will  a  given  sound 
be  produced  ;  hence  the  number  of  different  combinations  mathe- 
matically possible  is  hundreds  of  millions.  It  cannot,  therefore, 
be  a  matter  of  chance  when  a  child  repeats,  after  a  few  trials,  a 
sound  that  he  has  heard ;  but  it  must  depend  upon  physiological 
structure  that  makes  the  path  more  open  between  certain  audi- 
tory centers  and  corresponding  motor  speech  centers.  Again, 
when  a  child  imitates  a  movement  he  sees,  it  must  be  because 
there  is  a  connection  between  the  visual  sense  center  and  the 
motor  center  for  moving  the  part  in  a  corresponding  way.  Of 
course,  it  is  a  familiar  fact  that  there  is  an  excess  of  motor  en- 
ergy set  free  in  all  attempts  to  make  new  movements,  especially 
in  the  case  of  children,  which  causes  many  other  than  the  neces- 
sary muscles  to  contract ;  but  physiological  openness  of  certain 
paths  rather  than  chance  determines  which  movements  shall  be 
selected  for  repetition. 

The  next  point  which  I  wish  to  emphasize  is  that  there  is  an 
inherited  physiological  space  relation  between  the  visual  stimu- 
lus of  an  object  in  a  certain  position  and  the  muscles  for  moving 
to  that  object.  A  young  chicken  succeeds  in  picking  up  a  grain 
of  meal,  not  because  he  mentally  judges  the  direction  and  dis- 
tance, but  because  the  visual  sensation  calls  the  right  muscle 
into  play.  In  a  similar  way,  a  child  grasps  an  attractive  object, 
not  because  he  knows  its  direction  and  distance,  but  because  the 
visual  sensation  calls  the  proper  muscles  into  play.  So  accurate 
is  this  physiological  relation  between  visual  sensations  and  move- 


280  E.   A.    KIRKPATRICK. 

ments  that,  though  I  experimented  frequently  from  the  time  she 
began  to  grasp  at  about  three  months,  I  never  succeeded  in  get- 
ting my  little  girl  to  try  to  grasp  an  object  more  than  four  or  five 
inches  beyond  her  reach,  and  rarely  so  far  as  that.  She  would 
stretch  her  hands  towards  more  distant  objects  that  she  wanted, 
but  not  with  the  grasping  movement.  The  direction  of  her 
movement  was  also  from  the  first  nearly  as  accurate  as  the 
fixation  with  her  eyes.  This  physiological  space  relation  of 
certain  motor  reactions  to  certain  stimulations  is,  in  my  judg- 
ment, of  an  importance  hitherto  unappreciated  in  explaining 
not  only  the  development  of  voluntary  movements,  but  also  in 
explaining  ideas  of  space. 

Close  observation  of  the  earliest  attempts  at  grasping  con- 
vinced me  that  the  only  element  prominent  in  consciousness 
at  first  is  the  visual  sensation  of  the  object.  After  it  has  been 
reached,  reflexively  grasped  when  touched  and  instinctively 
brought  to  the  mouth  several  times,  disappointment  is  shown  if 
the  hand,  instead  of  the  object,  comes  in  contact  with  the  lips, 
showing  that  there  was  then  expectation  of  a  certain  kind  of 
sensation  that  was  not  realized.  The  young  child  in  grasp- 
ing objects  has  a  sensation  or  image  of  the  object  in  a  certain 
position  and  an  image  of  a  sensation  to  be  gotten ;  but  according 
to  my  observations  there  is  no  evidence  that  his  consciousness  is 
concerned  at  all  with  the  movements  he  is  making  in  order  to 
get  hold  of  the  object  and  bring  it  to  him.  The  same  is  true  of 
all  the  earlier  voluntary  movements  of  the  child,  and  attention 
to  the  movement  itself  hinders  rather  than  helps  in  learning  the 
movement.  In  the  case  of  Superintendent  Hall's  little  girl  there 
was  inability  to  walk  so  long  as  she  thought  about  her  move- 
ments ;  but  as  soon  as  her  attention  was  concentrated  upon  get- 
ting the  cuffs  on  and  carrying  them  around  she  succeeded  per- 
fectly, though  she  had  never  tried  it  before. 

Every  adult  knows  that  if  he  thinks  about  how  he  is  doing  a 
thing  he  can  do  it  much  less  perfectly  than  when  he  thinks 
merely  about  what  he  wants  to  do ;  yet  it  is  a  common  belief 
that  one  in  learning  any  act  must  go  through  a  stage  of  quite 
acute  consciousness  of  the  movements  involved.  I  maintain,  on 
the  contrary,  that  children  do  not  ordinarily  go  through  any 


DEVELOPMENT  OF    VOLUNTARY  MOVEMENT.          281 

such  stage  in  learning  their  earlier  movements,  and  that  it  is  not 
usually  necessary  for  either  children  or  adults  to  go  through 
such  a  stage  of  consciousness  of  all,  or  even  of  a  large  propor- 
tion, of  the  elementary  movements  involved  in  the  new  act. 

I  have  not  time  to  give  facts  in  support  of  this  conclusion,  nor 
to  point  out  its  importance  in  the  solution  of  various  educational 
problems  ;  but  I  will  close  with  one  or  two  general  considerations. 
In  the  history  of  the  race  arts  have  always  preceded  sciences ; 
men  have  learned  to  do  things,  then  reflected  upon  how  they  do 
them,  analyzed  to  discover  elements,  then  determined  the  gen- 
eral laws  according  to  which  the  actions  may  be  successfully 
performed,  and  this  order  of  procedure  is  the  natural  one  to  the 
child.  It  is  possible  that  in  some  cases  short  cuts  may  be  taken, 
as  Baldwin  has  suggested,  and  possibly  the  order  may  sometimes 
be  reversed  and  time  saved.  A  person  who  knows  one 
language,  for  example,  may  possibly  learn  another  language 
more  quickly  by  studying  its  grammar  first ;  but  I  am  sure  that 
a  child  who  knows  no  language  could  not  learn  one  by  begin- 
ning with  the  grammar.  Adults  who  are  able  to  make  many 
movements  may  learn  more  quickly  a  new  movement  by  having 
attention  called  to  some  of  the  elements,  though  probably  never 
by  having  it  called  to  all ;  but  a  young  child  would  be  hindered 
rather  than  helped  by  such  a  process.  This  is  true,  not  simply 
because  of  the  general  tendency  of  the  mind  to  develop  in  this 
order,  but  because  the  past  experience  of  the  race  has  developed 
a  very  definite  system  of  relations  between  various  stimuli  and 
various  simple  movements,  and  has  probably  developed  less  de- 
finitely various  combinations  of  simple  movements  and  a  ten- 
dency to  other  combinations  in  the  attainment  of  ends  fre- 
quently striven  for  by  the  race.  The  teaching  of  a  movement 
by  having  each  of  its  elements  learned,  and  then  having  these 
elements  combined  and  used,  is  not  only  a  reversal  of  the  natural 
order  in  attaining  an  end  and  a  misdirection  of  attention,  but  is 
an  undoing  of  what  has  been  partially  done  by  the  experience 
of  our  ancestors,  instead  of  completing  the  process. 


THE   INSTINCTIVE  REACTION   OF 
YOUNG  CHICKS. 

DR.  EDWARD  THORNDIKE. 
Western   Reserve    University. 

The  data  to  be  presented  in  this  article  were  obtained  in  the 
course  of  a  series  of  experiments  conducted  in  connection  with 
the  psychological  laboratory  of  Harvard  University  during  the 
year  '96-97.  About  sixty  chicks  were  used  as  subjects.  In 
general  their  experiences  were  entirely  under  my  control  from 
birth.  Where  this  was  not  true  the  conditions  of  their  life  pre- 
vious to  the  experiments  were  known,  and  were  such  as  would 
have  had  no  influence  in  determining  the  quality  of  their  reac- 
tions in  the  particular  experiments  to  which  they  were  subjected. 
It  is  not  worth  while  to  recount  the  means  taken  so  to  regulate 
the  chick's  environment  that  his  experience  along  certain  lines 
should  be  in  its  entirety  known  to  the  observer  and  that  conse- 
quently his  inherited  abilities  could  be  surely  differentiated. 
The  nature  of  the  experiments  will,  in  most  cases,  be  such  that 
little  suspicion  of  the  influence  of  education  by  experience  will 
be  possible.  In  the  other  cases  I  will  mention  the  particular 
means  then  taken  to  prevent  such  influence. 

Some  of  my  first  experiments  were  on  color  vision  in  chicks 
from  18  to  30  hours  old,  just  old  enough  to  move  about  readily 
and  to  be  hungry.  On  backgrounds  of  white  and  black  card- 
board were  pasted  pieces  of  colored  paper  about  2  mm.  square. 
On  each  background  there  were  six  of  these  pieces, — one  each 
of  yellow,  red,  orange,  green,  blue  and  black  (on  the  white 
ground)  or  white  (on  the  black).  They  were  in  a  row  about 
half  an  inch  apart.  The  chicks  had  been  in  darkness  for  all 
but  three  or  four  hours  of  their  life  so  far.  During  those  few 
hours  the  incubator  had  been  illuminated  and  the  chicks  had 
that  much  chance  to  learn  color. 
282 


INSTINCTIVE  REACTION  OF   YOUNG   CHICKS.          283 

The  eight  chicks  were  put,  one  at  a  time,  on  the  sheet  of 
cardboard  facing  the  colored  spots.  Count  was  kept  of  the 
number  of  times  that  they  pecked  at  each  spot  and,  of  course, 
they  were  watched  to  see  whether  they  would  peck  at  all  at 
random.  In  the  experiments  with  the  white  background  all  the 
colors  were  reacted  to  (t.  e.9  pecked  at)  except  black  (but  the 
letters  on  a  newspaper  were  pecked  at  by  the  same  chicks  the 
same  day).  One  of  the  chicks  pecked  at  all  five,  one  at  four, 
three  at  three,  one  at  two  and  one  at  yellow  only.  These  differ- 
ences are  due  probably  to  accidental  position  or  movements. 
Taking  the  sums  of  the  reactions  to  each  color-spot  we  get  the 
following  table : 

I.  Times  reacted  to.  Total  number  of  pecks.1 
Red,                                                12  31 
Yellow,                                            9                                                21 
Orange,                                             6  34 

Green,  5  u 

Blue,  i  3 

I  should  attach  no  importance  whatever  to  the  quantitative 
estimate  given  in  the  table.  The  only  fact  of  value  so  far  is  the 
evidence  that  from  the  first  the  chick  reacts  to  all  colors.  In 
no  case  was  there  any  random  pecking  at  the  white  surface  of 
the  cardboard. 

On  a  black  background  the  same  chicks  reacted  to  all  the 
colors. 

II.  is  a  table  of  the  results. 

II.  Times  reacted  to.  Total  number  of  pecks. 

White,  6  19 

Blue,  4  ii 

Red,  4  8 

Green,  4  4 

Orange,  2  7 

Yellow,  2  4 

In  other  experiments  chicks  were  tried  with  green  spots  on 
a  red  ground,  red  spots  on  a  green  ground,  yellow  spots  on  an 
orange  ground,  green  spots  on  a  blue  ground,  and  black  spots 

1This  double  rating  is  necessary  because  of  the  fact  that  the  chick  often 
gives  several  distinct  pecks  in  a  single  reaction.  The  *  times  reacted  to'  m«an 
the  number  of  different  times  that  the  chicks  noticed  the  color. 


284  EDWARD    THORNDIKE. 

on  a  white  ground.  All  were  reacted  to.  Thus,  what  is  ap- 
parently a  long  and  arduous  task  to  the  child  is  heredity's  gift 
to  the  chick.  It  is  conceivable,  though  to  me  incredible,  that 
what  the  chick  reacts  to  is  not  the  color,  but  the  very  minute 
elevation  of  the  spot.  My  spots  were  made  so  that  they  were 
only  the  thickness  of  thin  paper  above  pasteboard.  Any  one 
who  cares  to  resort  to  the  theory  that  this  elevation  caused  the 
reaction  can  settle  the  case  by  using  color-spots  absolutely 
level  with  the  surface. 

INSTINCTIVE  REACTIONS  TO  DISTANCE,  DIRECTION,  SIZE,  ETC. 

I  have  purposely  chosen  this  awkward  heading  rather  than 
the  simple  one  Space-Perception,  because  I  do  not  wish  to  imply 
that  there  is  in  the  young  chick  such  consciousness  of  space- 
facts  as  there  is  in  human  beings.  All  that  will  be  shown  here 
is  that  he  reacts  appropriately  in  the  presence  of  space-facts, 
reacts  in  a  fashion  which  would  in  the  case  of  a  man  go  with 
genuine  perception  of  space. 

If  one  puts  a  chick  on  top  of  a  box  in  sight  of  his  fellows 
below,  the  chick  will  regulate  his  conduct  by  the  height  of  the 
box.  To  be  definite,  we  may  take  the  average  chick  of  about 
95  hours.  If  the  height  is  less  than  10  inches  he  will  jump 
down  as  soon  as  you  put  him  up.  At  16  inches  he  will  jump 
in  from  5  seconds  to  3  or  4  minutes.  At  22  inches  he  will  still 
jump  down,  but  after  more  hesitation.  At  27  j£  inches  6  chicks 
out  of  eight  at  this  age  jumped  within  5  minutes.  At  39 
inches  the  chick  -will  NOT  jump  down.  The  numerical  values 
given  here  would,  of  course,  vary  with  the  health,  development, 
hunger  and  degree  of  lonesomeness  of  the  chick.  All  that 
they  are  supposed  to  show  is  that  at  any  given  age  the  chick 
without  experience  of  heights  regulates  his  conduct  rather 
accurately  in  accord  with  the  space-fact  of  distance  which 
confronts  him.  The  chick  does  not  peck  at  objects  remote  from 
him,  does  not,  for  instance,  confuse  a  bird  a  score  of  feet  away 
with  a  fly  near  by,  or  try  to  get  the  moon  inside  his  bill.  More- 
over, he  reacts  in  pecking  with  considerable  accuracy  at  the 
very  start.  Lloyd  Morgan  has  noted  that  in  his  very  first 
efforts  the  chick  often  fails  to  see  the  object,  though  he  hits  it, 


INSTINCTIVE  REACTION  OF   YOUNG   CHICKS.         285 

and  on  this  ground  has  denied  the  perfection  of  the  instinct.  But, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  the  pecking  reaction  may  be  as  perfect  at 
birth  as  it  is  after  10  or  12  days'  experience.  It  certainly  is  not 
perfect  then.  I  took  nine  chicks  from  10  to  14  days  old  and 
placed  them  one  at  a  time  on  a  clear  surface  over  which  were 
scattered  grains  of  cracked  wheat  (the  food  they  had  been  eat- 
ing in  this  same  way  for  a  week)  and  watched  the  accuracy  of 
their  pecking.  Out  of  214  objects  pecked  at  159  were  seized, 
55  were  not.  Out  of  the  159  that  were  seized,  only  116  were 
seized  on  the  first  peck,  25  on  the  second,  16  on  the  third,  and 
the  remaining  two  on  the  fourth.  Of  the  55  that  were  not  suc- 
cessfully seized,  31  were  pecked  at  only  once,  10  twice,  10 
three  times,  3  four  times  and  i  five  times.  I  fancy  one  would 
find  that  adult  fowls  would  show  by  no  means  a  perfect  record. 
So  long  as  chicks  with  ten  days'  experience  fail  to  seize  on  the 
first  trial  45 J&  of  the  time,  it  is  hardly  fair  to  argue  against  the 
perfection  of  the  instinct  on  the  ground  of  failures  to  seize  dur- 
ing the  first  day. 

The  chick's  practical  appreciation  of  space  facts  is  seen  fur- 
ther in  his  attempts  to  escape  when  confined.  Put  chicks  only 
twenty  or  thirty  hours  old  in  a  box  with  walls  three  or  four 
inches  high  and  they  will  react  to  the  perpendicularity  of  the 
confining  walls  by  trying  to  jump  over  them.  In  fact,  in  the 
ways  he  moves,  the  directions  he  takes  and  the  objects  he  reacts 
to,  the  chicken  has  prior  to  experience  the  power  of  appropriate 
reaction  to  colors  and  facts  of  all  three  dimensions. 

INSTINCTIVE  MUSCULAR  COORDINATIONS. 

In  the  acts  already  described  we  see  fitting  coordinations  at 
work  in  the  chick's  reactions  to  space  facts.  A  few  more  sam- 
ples may  be  given.  In  jumping  down  from  heights  the  chick 
does  not  walk  off  or  fall  off  (save  rarely),  but  jumps  off.  He 
meets  the  situation  "  loneliness  on  a  small  eminence"  by  walk- 
ing around  the  edge  and  peering  down ;  he  meets  the  situation 
"  sight  of  fellow  chicks  below  "  by  (after  an  amount  of  hesitation 
varying  roughly  with  the  height)  jumping  off,  holding  his  stubby 
wings  out  and  keeping  right  side  up.  He  lands  on  his  feet  al- 
most every  time  and  generally  very  cleverly.  A  four  days'  chick 


286  EDWARD    THORNDIKE. 

will  jump  down  a  distance  eight  times  his  own  height  without  hurt- 
ing himself  a  bit.  If  one  takes  a  chick  two  or  three  weeks  old  who 
has  never  had  a  chance  to  jump  up  or  down,  and  puts  him  in  a 
box  with  walls  three  times  the  height  of  the  chick's  back,  he  will 
find  that  the  chick  will  jump,  or  rather  fly,  nearly,  if  not  quite, 
over  the  wall,  flapping  his  wings  lustily  and  holding  on  to  the 
edge  with  his  neck  while  he  clambers  over.  Chicks  one  day 
old  will,  in  about  57  per  cent,  of  the  cases,  balance  themselves 
for  five  or  six  seconds  when  placed  on  a  stiff  perch.  If  eight 
or  nine  days  old,  they  will,  though  never  before  on  any  perch  or 
anything  like  one,  balance  perfectly  for  a  minute  or  more.  The 
muscular  coordination  required  is  invoked  immediately  when  the 
chick  feels  the  situation  "  feet  on  a  perch."  The  strength  is 
lacking  in  the  first  few  days.  From  the  fifth  or  sixth  day  on 
chicks  are  also  able  (their  ability  increases  with  age)  to  balance 
themselves  on  a  slowly  swinging  perch. 

Another  complex  coordination  is  seen  in  the  somewhat  re- 
markable instinct  of  swimming.  Chicks  only  a  day  or  two 
old  will,  if  tossed  into  a  pond,  head  straight  for  the  shore  and 
swim  rapidly  to  it.  It  is  impossible  to  compare  their  movements 
in  so  doing  with  those  of  ducklings,  for  the  chick  is  agitated, 
paddles  his  feet  very  fast  and  swims  to  get  out,  not  for  swim- 
ming's, sake.  Dr.  Bashford  Dean,  of  Columbia  University,  has 
suggested  to  me  that  the  movements  may  not  be  those  of  swim- 
ming, but  only  of  running.  At  all  events,  they  are  utterly  dif- 
ferent from  those  of  an  adult  fowl.  In  the  case  of  the  adult 
there  is  no  vigorous  instinct  to  strike  out  toward  the  shore. 
The  hen  may  try  to  fly  back  into  the  boat  if  it  is  dropped  over- 
board, and  whether  dropped  in  or  slung  in  from  the  shore  will 
float  about  aimlessly  for  a  while  and  only  very  slowly  reach  the 
shore.  The  movements  the  chick  makes  do  look  to  be  such  as 
trying  to  run  in  water  might  lead  to,  but  it  is  hard  to  see  why  a 
hen  shouldn't  run  to  get  out  of  cold  water  as  well  as  a  chick. 
If,  on  the  other  hand,  the  actions  of  the  chick  are  due  to  a  real 
swimming  instinct,  it  is  easy  to  see  that,  being  unused,  the  in- 
stinct might  wane  as  the  animal  grew  up. 

Such  instinctive  coordinations  as  these,  together  with  the 
walking,  running,  prooning  of  feathers,  stretching  out  of  leg 


INSTINCTIVE  REACTION  OF   YOUNG  CHICKS.          287 

backwards,  scratching  the  head,  etc.,  noted  by  other  observers, 
make  the  infant  chick  a  very  interesting  contrast  to  the  infant 
man.  That  the  helplessness  of  the  child  is  a  sacrifice  to  plas- 
ticity, instability  and  consequent  power  to  develop  we  all  know ; 
but  one  begins  to  realize  how  much  of  a  sacrifice  when  one 
sees  what  twenty-one  days  of  embryonic  life  do  for  the  chick 
brain.  And  one  cannot  help  wondering  whether  some  of  the 
space-perception  we  trace  to  experience,  some  of  the  coordina- 
tions which  we  attribute  to  a  gradual  development  from  random, 
accidentally  caused  movements  may  not  be  more  or  less  defi- 
nitely provided  for  by  the  child's  inherited  brain  structure. 
Walking  has  been  found  to  be  instinctive  ;  why  not  other  things  ? 

INSTINCTIVE  EMOTIONAL  REACTIONS. 

The  only  experiments  to  which  I  wish  to  refer  at  length 
under  this  heading  are  some  concerning  the  chick's  instinctive 
fears.  Before  describing  them  it  may  be  well  to  mention  their 
general  bearing  on  the  results  obtained  by  Spalding  and  Mor- 
gan. They  corroborate  Morgan's  decision  that  no  well-defined 
specific  fears  are  present ;  that  the  fears  of  young  chicks  are  of 
strange  moving  objects  in  general,  shock  in  general,  strange 
sounds  in  general.  On  the  other  hand,  no  such  general  dis- 
turbances of  the  chick's  environment  led  to  such  well-marked 
reactions  as  Spalding  described.  And  so  when  Morgan  thinks 
that  such  behavior  as  Spalding  witnessed  on  the  part  of  the 
chick  that  heard  the  hawk's  cry  demands  for  its  explanation 
nothing  more  than  a  general  fear  of  strange  sounds,  my  experi- 
ments do  not  allow  me  to  agree  with  him.  If  Spalding  really 
saw  the  conduct  which  he  says  the  chick  exhibited  on  the  third 
day  of  its  life  in  the  presence  of  man,  and  later  at  the  stimulus 
of  the  sight  or  sound  of  the  hawk,  there  are  specific  reactions, 
for  the  running,  crouching,  silence,  quivering,  etc.,  that  one 
gets  by  yelling,  banging  doors,  tormenting  a  violin,  throwing 
hats,  bottles,  or  brushes  at  the  chick  is  never  anything  like  so 
pronounced  and  never  lasts  one-tenth  as  long  as  it  did  with 
Spalding's  chicks.  But  as  to  the  fear  of  man,  Spalding  must 
have  been  deluded.  In  the  second,  third  and  fourth  days  there 
is  no  such  reaction  to  the  sight  of  man  as  he  thought  he  saw. 


255  EDWARD    THORNDIKE. 

Miss  Hattie  E.  Hunt,  in  the  American  Journal  of  Psychology  > 
Vol.  IX.,  No.  i,  asserts  that  there  is  no  instinctive  fear  of  a 
cat.  Morgan  did  not  find  such.  I  myself  put  chicks  of  2,  5, 
9  and  17  days  (different  individuals  each  time,  n  in  all)  in  the 
presence  of  a  cat.  They  showed  no  fear ;  went  on  eating  as  if 
nothing  about.  The  cat  was  still,  or  only  slowly  moving.  I 
further  put  a  young  kitten  (eight  inches  long)  in  the  pen  with 
chicks.  He  felt  of  them  with  his  paw,  and  walked  around 
among  them  for  five  or  ten  minutes,  yet  they  showed  no  fear 
(nor  did  he  instinctively  attack  them).  If,  however,  you  let  a  cat 
jump  at  chicks  in  real  earnest,  they  will  not  stay  to  be  eaten, 
but  will  manifest  fear — at  least  chicks  three  to  four  weeks  old 
will.  I  did  not  try  this  experiment  with  a  lot  of  chicks  at  dif- 
ferent ages,  because  it  seemed  rather  cruel  and  degrading  to 
the  experimenter.  When  in  the  case  of  the  older  chicks  nature 
happened  to  make  the  experiment,  it  was  hard  to  decide 
whether  there  was  more  violent  fear  of  the  jumping  cat  than 
there  was  when  one  threw  a  basket  or  foot-ball  into  the  pen. 
There  was  not  very  much  more. 

We  may  now  proceed  to  a  brief  recital  of  the  facts  shown  by 
the  experiments  in  so  far  as  they  are  novel.  It  should  be 
remembered  throughout  that  in  every  case  chicks  of  different 
ages  were  tested  so  as  to  demonstrate  transitory  instincts  if  such 
existed — e.  g.,  the  presence  of  a  fear  of  flame  was  tested  with 
chicks  59  and  60,  one  day  old,  30  and  32,  two  days  old,  21  and 
22,  three  days  old,  23  and  24,  seven  days  old,  27  and  29,  nine 
days  old,  16  and  19,  eleven  days  old,  and  so  on  up  to  twenty 
days  old  chicks.  By  thus  using  different  subjects  at  each  trial 
one,  of  course,  eliminates  any  influence  of  experience. 

The  first  notable  fact  is  that  there  develops  in  the  first  month 
a  general  fear  of  novel  objects  in  motion.  For  four  or  five  days 
there  seems  to  be  no  such.  You  may  throw  a  hat  or  slipper  or 
shaving-mug  at  a  chick  of  that  age,  and  he  will  do  no  more  than 
get  out  of  the  way  of  it.  But  a  twenty-five  days  old  chick  will 
generally  chirr,  run  and  crouch  for  five  or  ten  seconds.  My 
records  show  this  sort  of  thing  beginning  about  the  tenth  day, 
but  it  is  about  ten  days  more  before  it  is  very  marked.  In  gen- 
eral, also,  the  reaction  is  more  pronounced  if  a  lot  of  chicks  are 


INSTINCTIVE  REACTION  OF    YOUNG   CHICKS.          289 

together,  and  is  then  displayed  earlier  (only  two  at  a  time 
were  taken  in  the  experiments  the  results  of  which  have  just 
been  quoted).  Thus  the  reaction  is  to  some  degree  a  social 
performance,  the  presence  of  other  chicks  combining  with  the 
strange  object  to  increase  the  vigor  of  the  reaction.  Chicks 
ordinarily  scatter  apart  when  they  thus  run  from  an  object. 

One  witnesses  a  similar  gradual  growth  of  the  fear  of  man 
(not  as  such  probably,  but  merely  as  a  large  moving  object). 
For  four  or  five  days  you  can  jump  at  the  chick,  grab  at  it  with 
your  hands,  etc.,  without  disturbing  it  in  the  least.  A  chick 
twenty  days  old,  however,  although  he  has  never  been  touched 
or  approached  by  a  man,  and  in  some  cases  never  seen  one  ex- 
cept as  the  daily  bringer  of  food,  and  has  never  been  in  any 
way  injured  by  any  large  moving  object  of  any  sort,  will  run 
from  you  if  you  try  to  catch  him  or  even  get  very  near  him. 
There  is,  however,  even  then,  nothing  like  the  utter  fear  de- 
scribed by  Spalding. 

Up  to  thirty  days  there  was  no  fear  of  a  mocking  bird  into 
whose  cage  the  chicks  were  put,  no  fear  of  a  stuffed  hawk  or  a 
stuffed  owl  (kept  stationary).  Chicks  try  to  escape  from  water 
(even  though  warmed  to  the  temperature  of  their  bodies)  from 
the  very  first.  Up  to  forty  days  there  appears  no  marked  wan- 
ing of  the  instinct.  They  did  not  show  any  emotional  reaction 
to  the  flame  produced  by  six  candles  stuck  closely  together. 
From  the  start  they  react  instinctively  to  confinement,  to  loneli- 
ness, to  bodily  restraint,  but  their  feeling  in  these  cases  would 
better  be  called  discomfort  than  fear.  From  the  loth  or  I2th  to 
the  2Oth  day,  and  probably  later  and  very  possibly  earlier,  one 
notices  in  chicks  a  general  avoidance  of  open  places.  Turn 
them  out  in  your  study  and  they  will  not  go  out  into  the  middle 
of  the  room,  but  will  cling  to  the  edges,  go  under  chairs,  around 
table-legs  and  along  the  walls.  One  sees  nothing  of  the  sort  up 
through  the  fourth  day.  Some  experiments  with  feeding  hive 
bees  to  the  chicks  are  interesting  in  connection  with  the  follow- 
ing statement  by  Lloyd  Morgan:  "  One  of  my  chicks,  three 
or  four  days  old,  snapped  up  a  hive  bee  and  ran  off  with  it. 
Then  he  dropped  it,  shook  his  head  much  and  often,  and  wiped 
his  bill  repeatedly.  I  do  not  think  he  had  been  stung  ;  probably 


290  EDWARD    THORNDIKE. 

he  tasted  the  poison"  (Int.  to  Comp.  Psy.,  p.  86.)  I  fed  seven 
bees  apiece  to  three  chicks  from  ten  to  twenty  days  old.  They 
ate  them  all  greedily ',  first  mashing  them  down  on  the  ground 
violently  in  a  rather  dextrous  manner.  Apparently  this  method 
of  treatment  is  peculiar  to  the  object.  Chicks  three  days  old 
did  not  eat  the  bees.  Some  pecked  at  them  but  none  would 
snap  them  up,  and  when  the  bee  approached  they  sometimes 
sounded  the  danger-note.  Finally  an  account  may  be  given  of 
the  reaction  of  chicks  at  different  ages,  up  to  twenty-six  days, 
to  loud  sounds.  These  were  the  sounds  made  by  clapping  the 
hands,  slamming  a  door,  whistling  sharply,  banging  a  tin  pan 
on  the  floor,  mewing  like  a  cat,  playing  a  violin,  thumping  a 
coal-scuttle  with  a  shovel,  etc.,  etc.  Two  chicks  were  together 
in  each  experiment.  Three-fourths  of  the  times  no  effect  was 
produced.  On  the  other  occasions  there  was  some  running  or 
crouching  or,  at  least,  starting  to  run  or  crouch ;  but,  as  was 
said,  nothing  like  what  Spalding  reports  as  the  reaction  to  the 
'cheep'  of  the  hawk.  It  is  interesting  to  notice  that  the  two 
most  emphatic  reactions  were  to  the  imitation  mew.  One  time 
a  chick  ran  wildly,  chirring,  and  then  crouched  and  stayed  still 
until  I  had  counted  105.  The  other  time  a  chick  crouched  and 
stayed  still  until  I  counted  40.  But  the  other  chick  with  them 
did  not  and  in  a  dozen  other  cases  the  '  meaw '  had  no  effect. 

I  think  that  the  main  interest  of  most  of  these  experiments 
is  the  proof  they  afford  that  instinctive  reactions  are  not  neces- 
sarily definite,  perfectly  appropriate  and  unvarying  responses  to 
accurately  sensed  and,  so  to  speak,  estimated  stimuli.  The  old 
notion  that  instinct  was  a  God-given  substitute  for  reason  left  us 
an  unhappy  legacy  in  the  shape  of  the  tendency  to  think  of  all 
inherited  powers  of  reaction  as  definite  particular  acts  invariably 
done  in  the  presence  of  certain  equally  definite  situations.  Such 
an  act  as  the  spider's  web-spinning  might  be  a  stock  example. 
Of  course,  there  are  many  such  instinctive  reactions  in  which  a 
well-defined  act  follows  a  well-defined  stimulus  with  the  regu- 
larity and  precision  with  which  the  needle  approaches  the  mag- 
net. But  our  experiments  show  that  there  are  acts  just  as  truly 
instinctive,  depending  in  just  the  same  way  on  inherited  brain- 
structure,  but  characterized  by  being  vague,  irregular,  and,  to 
some  extent,  dissimilar  reactions  to  vague,  complex  situations. 


INSTINCTIVE  REACTION  OF   YOUNG   CHICKS.          291 

The  same  stimulus  doesn't  always  produce  just  the  same 
effect,  doesn't  produce  precisely  the  same  effect  in  all  individ- 
uals. The  chick's  brain  is  evidently  prepared  in  a  general  way 
to  react  more  or  less  appropriately  to  certain  stimuli,  and  these 
reactions  are  among  the  most  important  of  its  instincts  or  inher- 
ited functions.  But  yet  one  cannot  take  these  and  find  them 
always  and  everywhere.  This  helps  us  further  to  realize  the 
danger  of  supposing  that  in  observation  of  animals  you  can  de- 
pend on  a  rigid  uniformity.  One  would  never  suppose  because 
one  boy  twirled  his  thumb  when  asked  a  question  that  all  boys 
of  that  age  did.  But  naturalists  have  been  ready  to  believe  that 
because  one  young  animal  made  a  certain  response  to  a  certain 
stimulus,  the  thing  was  an  instinct  common  to  all  in  precisely 
that  same  form.  But  a  loud  sound  may  make  one  chick  run, 
another  crouch,  another  give  the  danger  call,  and  another  do 
nothing  whatever. 

In  closing  this  article  I  may  speak  of  one  instinct  which 
shows  itself  clearly  from  at  least  as  early  as  the  sixth  day, 
which  is  preparatory  to  the  duties  of  adult  life  and  of  no  other 
use  whatsoever.  It  is  interesting  in  connection  with  the  general 
matter  of  animal  play.  The  phenomenon  is  as  follows :  The 
chicks  are  feeding  quietly  when  suddenly  two  chicks  rush 
at  each  other,  face  each  other  a  moment  and  then  go  about  their 
business.  This  thing  keeps  up  and  grows  into  the  ordinary 
combat  of  roosters.  It  is  rather  a  puzzle  on  any  theory  that  an 
instinct  needed  so  late  should  begin  to  develop  so  early. 


DISCUSSIONS. 

PROFESSOR  MtJNSTERBERG   ON  MYSTICISM. 

The  criticism  of  l  The  New  Psychology/  it  seems,  has  a  sequel. 
We  have  an  equal  and  presumably  impartial  attack  upon  Mysticism, 
of  which  one  form  is  psychical  research.  In  taking  up  the  cudgels, 
however,  I  am  not  going  to  defend  this  curious  department  of  inquiry. 
Even  among  those  who  are  interested  in  it  there  is  room  enough  for 
scepticism  of  the  most  scrutinizing  sort.  I  accord  any  man  whatever 
opinion  he  pleases  to  have  about  it.  But  I  should  ask  that  the 
scientific  method  that  Professor  Miinsterberg  demands  in  this  and  all 
psychological  work  be  represented  in  his  criticism,  or  a  frank  admission 
made  that  dogmatism  is  the  fundamental  instrument  of  knowledge. 
To  me  his  recent  article  in  the  Atlantic  Monthly  is  one  of  the  most 
amusing  documents  that  I  have  ever  had  the  pleasure  of  reading.  I 
am  not  going  to  attack  the  discussion  as  a  whole,  but  only  to  deal  with 
that  part  of  it  which  criticises  psychical  research.  Let  us  see  how 
much  science  there  is  in  his  method. 

Professor  Miinsterberg  in  one  passage  confesses  that  until  the  last 
summer  vacation  he  felt  rather  guilty  for  forming  and  stating  opinions 
on  this  subject  before  reading  its  literature.  He  then  proceeds  to  en- 
joy his  vacation  '  in  working  through  more  than  a  hundred  volumes 
of  the  so-called  evidence.' ! ! !  Just  think  of  that!  A  scientist  spend- 
ing the  summer  rest  of  a  few  weeks  reading  more  than  one  hundred 
volumes  of  matters  involving  a  question  of  evidence,  and  actually 
forming  what  he  thinks  a  scientific  conclusion  on  them ! !  I  do  not 
believe  there  are  twenty-five  volumes  in  existence  on  this  subject  that 
any  sane  man  ought  to  read  at  all,  let  alone  doing  it  at  such  a  time. 
I  have  watched  this  subject  for  ten  years,  and  have  in  all  that  time  read 
no  more  than  ten  volumes,  some  of  them  exceedingly  carefully,  and  I 
did  not  dream  of  forming  an  opinion  or  irreversable  conclusion  upon 
them.  On  this  subject  of  psychical  research,  unless  you  have  made 
sufficiently  decisive  experiments  personally  (not  merely  curing  one 
hallucination  by  suggestion),  it  may  take  a  hundred  years  to  arrive  at 
any  scientific  conclusion  at  all.  But  would  Professor  Miinsterberg  ad- 
vise his  students  to  study  psychology  generally  at  the  rate  of  '  more 
292 


DISCUSS/QMS.  293 

than  a  hundred  volumes  '  a  vacation  when  the  temperature  is  between 
eighty  and  a  hundred  ?  Moreover,  what  right  has  a  professed  scientist 
to  depend  upon  books,  no  matter  how  many  of  them,  for  a  conclusion 
that  involves  matters  of  very  delicate  experiment,  and  not  analytical 
and  introspective  methods  ?  Professor  Miinsterberg  says  that  he  is  not 
a  detective.  He  should  then  not  pronounce  upon  problems  that  re- 
quire that  sort  of  ability.  Here  is  a  place  for  a  confession  of  ignorance 
and  to  eschew  the  pretensions  of  knowledge. 

Apropos  of  this  last  remark  it  is  well  to  recall  another  singular 
confession  of  our  author.  His  reason  for  not  making  a  personal  in- 
vestigation into  this  question  is  that  it  is  not  *  dignified  to  visit  such 
performances  '  as  seances  ! !  If  physiology  and  biology  had  acted  on 
this  maxim  we  should  have  known  very  little  about  life  on  the  one 
hand,  and  about  brain  processes  on  the  other,  on  which  Professor 
Munsterberg  relies  so  much  for  his  assurance  against  mysticism. 
Dignity  is  not  anything  that  should  stand  in  the  way  of  experiment  or 
exact  method.  I  confess  I  admire  Darwin  for  playing  a  bassoon  to  his 
garden  plants  to  test  some  supposition,  though  his  neighbors,  had  they 
seen  him  at  it,  would  have  thought  him  suitable  for  a  lunatic  asylum. 
Science  at  one  time  was  too  dignified  to  examine  the  stories  about 
falling  meteors,  but  it  came  to  terms  at  last.  It  did  the  same  with 
hypnotism.  It  first  packed  a  jury  to  condemn  it,  and  thought  it  had 
laid  the  monster,  but  after  forty  years  contempt  decided  to  embrace  it 
as  a  fact  nevertheless !  !  Its  dignity  would  not  save  its  scepticism. 

It  seems,  again,  that  Professor  Munsterberg  cannot  protect  himself 
against  fraud.  He  thinks  the  scientist  is  trained  to  '  an  instinctive 
confidence  in  his  cooperators.'  Granted.  All  scientific  truth  involving 
the  cooperation  of  others,  then,  must  be  taken  on  authority.  Every- 
thing depends  upon  the  assurance  of  men  that  there  is  no  fraud  who 
have  either  not  looked  for  it  or  are  not  able  to  detect  it ! !  When 
science  comes  to  that  pass  I  shall  have  done  with  it.  A  man  who 
cannot  protect  himself  against  fraud  must  not  expect  his  opinion  to  be 
worth  very  much.  He  may  read  '  more  than  a  hundred  volumes'  in 
his  vacation  and  form  theories  in  that  way,  but  he  must  not  expect  us 
to  take  his  experimental  work  seriously. 

Let  us  have  some  science.  "If  I  talk  with  others  whom  I  wish 
to  convince  there  is  no  physical  process  in  question,  mind  reaches 
mind,  thought  reaches  thought,  but  in  this  aspect  thoughts  are  not 
psychophysical  phenomena  in  space  and  time,  but  attitudes  and  propo- 
sitions in  the  sphere  of  the  will."  Well,  this  is  either  telepathy  with 
a  vengeance  or  it  is  blank  nonsense.  Just  think  of  the  statement  that 


294  MYSTICISM. 

there  is  no  physical  process  in  the  communication  of  thoughts ! ! 
Where  is  the  evidence  for  all  this  ?  Can  science  escape  the  demand 
for  fact  to  prove  an  assertion  ?  What  facts  has  Professor  Miinsterberg 
to  show  that  this  view  is  either  true  or  intelligible?  Then,  what  does 
he  mean  by  a  4  proposition  in  the  sphere  of  the  will '  ?  While  we  are 
playing  *  ducks  and  drakes '  with  the  language  of  science,  why  not  go 
further  and  say  that  fear  is  a  feeling  in  the  sphere  of  logic  ?  As  to 
what  Professor  Miinsterberg  may  intend  by  this  description  of  the 
communication  of  ideas,  I  can  well  imagine.  But  I  can  do  it  only  by 
having  some  knowledge  of  the  process  myself,  and  not  from  any  state- 
ment that  he  makes.  When  I  wish  to  transmit  my  thought  to  others 
by  talking  I  make  a  disturbance  in  the  air,  and  the  receiver  interprets 
the  sound.  Now,  if  4  communication  '  be  convertible  with  l  interpre- 
tation '  we  may  agree  that  there  l  is  no  physical  process  in  question/ 
but  in  all  intelligible  parlance,  outside  the  suppositions  of  telepathy, 
4  communication '  means  that  the  physical  process  is  a  part  of  the 
totality.  Otherwise  there  is  no  interpretation  even,  and  the  only  re- 
source for  common  thoughts  would  be  universal  telepathy,  which  Pro- 
fessor Miinsterberg  will  not  admit  as  possible.  And  neither  for  nor 
against  one  or  the  other  of  the  claims  does  he  produce  any  facts ! !  It 
is  simply  bald  blank  assertion,  and  this  is  supposed  to  be  science  after 
laughing  at  the  dogmatism  of  the  Middle  Ages ! 

We  have  another  illustration  of  the  same  sort  of  thing.  ll  The 
ethical  belief  in  immortality  means  that  as  subjects  of  will  we  are  im- 
mortal; that  is,  that  we  are  not  reached  by  death.  For  the  philo- 
sophical mind,  which  sees  the  difference  between  reality  and  psycho- 
logical transformation,  immortality  is  certain;  for  him  the  denial  of 
immortality  would  be  even  quite  meaningless.  Death  is  a  biological 
phenomenon  in  the  world  of  objects  in  time ;  how,  then,  can  death 
reach  a  reality  which  is  not  an  object,  but  an  attitude,  and,  therefore, 
neither  in  time  nor  space  ?  Our  real  inner  subjective  life  has  its  felt 
validity,  not  in  time,  but  beyond  time :  it  is  eternal."  This  is  sci- 
ence, I  suppose ! !  Not  a  fact  to  prove  it.  It  is  said  that  l  philosophy ' 
shows  this.  Whose  philosophy  ?  On  what  facts  is  it  founded  ?  Then, 
again,  what  is  immortal  ?  We  are  not  told  what  it  is.  From  a  pre- 
vious reference  to  the  '  ethical  belief  '  Professor  Miinsterberg  says  that 
it  ends  in  mysticism,  and  I  imagine  that  what  he  says  of  it  here  is  in- 
tended to  be  condemned  as  compared  with  the  philosophic  verdict. 
If  so  it  cannot  be  the  subject  of  will,  and  if  it  is  not  this  we  have  im- 
mortality affirmed  without  telling  us  what  is  immortal.  But  assuming 
it  is  '  we  as  subjects  of  will '  that  are  immortal,  what  is  this  '  we,* 


295 

especially  when  an  earlier  passage  asserts  that  the  4  inner  reality,' 
which  is  here  said  to  be  eternal,  ;  never  consists  of  psychological 
phenomena.'  But  this  sort  of  criticism  aside  as  savoring  of  quibbles, 
I  must  press  the  scientific  demand  for  fact  to  show  that  the  tremendous 
assertion  here  made  has  another  basis  than  the  mere  speculative 
opinion  of  the  author.  As  for  myself  I  must  contend  that  there  is  not 
one  iota  of  rational  evidence  for  immortality,  of  any  intelligible  or  de- 
sirable kind,  outside  the  sphere  and  method  of  psychical  research.  I 
do  not  maintain  that  even  this  is  rational,  but  it  is  all  that  can  lay  the 
slightest  claim  to  being  rational  from  the  standpoint  of  science,  and 
the  philosophic  standpoint  I  absolutely  reject  as  merely  a  process  of 
looking  into  one's  navel  to  solve  the  riddle  of  the  Sphinx.  Heaven 
knows  that  the  spiritualist's  4  scientific '  evidence  for  his  belief  has 
been  meager  and  poor  enough,  but  the  philosopher's  has  been  worse. 
It  has  rested  mainly  on  '  dignity '  and  k  dignified  '  methods,  tempered 
with  equivocation  and  hypocrisy  to  escape  persecution.  I  follow  the 
method  and  accept  the  verdict  of  science  on  this  matter.  If  it  gives 
me  trustworthy  facts  making  immortality  a  rational  belief,  I  can  affirm 
it;  if  it  cannot  produce  these  facts  I  either  suspend  judgment  or 
accept  the  probability,  from  the  connection  of  conciousness  with  a 
perishable  organism,  that  this  function  dissolves  with  it.  And  when 
I  speak  of  immortality  I  mean  personal  survival ;  that  is,  the  con- 
tinuance of  consciousness  beyond  the  life  of  the  body.  Any  other 
immortality  I  do  not  care  a  picayune  for,  and  would  not  be  caught 
juggling  with  any  affirmative  proposition  containing  the  term.  What 
amazes  me  is  that  any  man  making  the  slightest  pretense  to  scientific 
method  would,  after  the  terrible  lesson  of  scholasticism,  attempt  for  a 
moment  to  make  such  a  tremendous  assertion  as  that  of  immortality 
without  at  least  a  small  array  of  empirical  facts  to  support  it.  There 
is  another  very  singular  passage.  After  telling  us  in  fine  language 
that  science  must  not  prejudge  a  question,  must  not  4  reject  a  fact  be- 
cause it  does  not  fit  into  the  scientific  system  of  to-day,'  etc.,  Professor 
Miinsterberg  goes  on  to  say:  "  This  is  the  old  text,"  etc.,  "  Yet  it  is 
wrong  and  dangerous  from  beginning  to  end,  and  has  endlessly  more 
harm  in  it  than  a  superficial  view  reveals,  as  it  is  in  last  conse- 
quences not  only  the  death  of  real  science,  but  worse,  the  death  of  real 
idealism."  Well,  we  have  to  choose  between  psychical  research  and 
idealism.  But  what  is  idealism?  Is  that  so  clear  in  these  times  that 
men  have  no  freedom  to  question  it?  When  I  read  a  book  or  essay 
on  idealism  I  am  reminded  of  the  sermon  which  the  old  woman  could 
not  understand,  but  which,  nevertheless,  edified  and  consoled  her  by 


296  MYSTICISM. 

the  presence  in  it  of  '  the  blessed  word  Mesopotamia.'  Idealism  is 
unintelligible,  but  then  it  is  the  basis  of  ethics  and  art !  I  say  frankly 
that  if  I  had  to  choose  between  psychical  research  and  idealism  I 
should  unhesitatingly  take  the  side  of  psychical  research  for  clearness 
and  knowing  *  where  you  are  at.'  For  I  do  not  know  any  field  of 
thought  which  is  more  full  of  intellectual  hobgoblins  than  that  of 
Kanto-Hegelian  idealism.  I  am  not  opposing  idealism,  because  if  I 
am  allowed  to  define  it  for  myself  I  should  say  that  it  is  a  mere  truism. 
It  is  to  me  like  the  proposition  that  water  is  wet  or  blue  is  a  color. 
But  I  do  not  expect  to  solve  any  problems  with  it.  Least  of  all,  do  I 
consider  it  a  sanctuary  in  which  I  am  not  allowed  to  say  anything 
about  either  materialism  or  spiritualism.  The  only  way  that  idealism 
can  get  into  antagonism  with  any  theory  is  to  limit  itself  to  solipsism. 
In  any  other  form  it  is  only  a  field  for  that  kind  of  intellectual  gym- 
nastics which,  as  Kant  remarks,  characterizes  the  heroes  of  Valhalla. 
They  are  forever  hewing  down  shadows  which  only  spring  up  again 
to  renew  their  ceaseless  and  bloodless  conflict. 

But  the  most  remarkable  thing  about  this  passage  is  its  distinct 
renunciation  of  scientific  method  for  a  dogmatism  that  knows  all  about 
the  universe  without  any  further  inquiry.  I  do  not  see  why  a  man  talks 
any  more  about  4  science '  and  '  scientific '  method  as  an  enemy  of 
superstition  when  he  shows  that  he  has  no  other  conception  of  it  than 
that  which  denies  the  right  to  revise  existing  opinion.  Evidently,  sci- 
ence and  dogmatism  are  the  same  here,  while  idealism  is  '  that  blessed 
word '  which  is  to  exorcise  all  spirits  except  its  own,  and  they  are  as 
shadowy  as  the  ghosts  that  inhabit  Homer's  Cimmerian  shades. 

Taking  the  article  as  a  whole,  I  do  not  see  why  Professor  Miin- 
sterberg  did  not  distinguish  between  the  relevancy  of  the  various  al- 
leged phenomena  that  he  was  criticising.  Table  turning,  telepathy, 
clairvoyance,  hypnotism  and  what  not  were  lumped  together  with  no 
more  conception  of  their  differences  than  is  usually  displayed  by  the 
spiritualist  himself.  The  fact  is  that  not  one  of  them,  unless  we 
except  telepathy,  even  if  they  were  genuine,  has  any  bearing  on  the 
question  of  spiritualism,  and  telepathy,  if  true,  might  be  used  as  a 
very  effective  bar  to  spiritualism.  But  as  in  the  phenomena  of  in- 
sanity and  hallucinations,  which,  by  the  way,  Professor  Miinsterberg  is 
not  too  dignified  to  study,  we  can  classify  alleged  facts  and  discuss  their 
relevancy  to  the  hypotheses  which  they  are  said  to  support.  Professor 
Miinsterberg  should  have  read  that  hundred  volumes  with  sufficient 
care  to  discover  the  distinction  that  a  scientist  ought  to  master  at  first. 
There  is  no  use  to  assume  that  the  spiritualist  has  the  right  conception 


DISCUSSIONS.  297 

either  of  his  problems  or  of  his  facts.  I  consider  that  he  has  neither,  as  a 
rule,  and  it  would  save  some  reputation  if  these  alleged  phenomena 
could  be  treated  as  patiently  as  are  those  of  insanity.  I  am  here  de- 
fending only  the  method  of  psychical  research.  I  do  not  care  what 
becomes  of  its  facts  or  alleged  phenomena.  I  merely  ask  that  its 
critics  deal  with  it  from  the  inside,  and  not  in  a  confessedly  a  priori 
manner.  My  attention  to  it  for  ten  years  has  convinced  me  that  there 
is  enough  in  the  subject  to  engage  serious  consideration,  no  matter 
what  the  conclusions  may  be.  In  fact,  the  plausibility  of  some  tre- 
mendous claims  is  so  great,  and  so  thoroughly  in  accord  with  what 
the  common  mind  in  this  sceptical  age  would  like  to  see  established, 
that  it  will  require  all  the  severity  and  sceptical  scrutiny  of  scientific 
method  at  our  command  to  get  any  proper  attention  to  normal  psy- 
chology. I  happen  to  know  some  genuine  supernormal  phenomena, 
not  explainable  by  either  fraud,  illusion,  or  suggestion,  and  whose 
significance,  or  at  least  plausible  significance,  will  have  to  be  reckoned 
with  by  men  who,  like  the  mediaeval  theologians  refusing  to  look 
through  Galileo's  telescope,  cannot  sacrifice  their  dignity  for  the  sake 
of  controlling  a  movement  instead  of  following  in  its  wake.  Some 
of  those  who  are  making  haste  to  laugh  at  it  without  studying  it  and 
its  alleged  facts  at  first  hand  will  find  themselves  where  they  will 
have  either  to  lose  their  influence  for  all  psychology  or,  in  order  to 
save  it,  will  have  to  4  eat  crow,'  and  4  white  crow'  at  that.  It  is  not 
the  remarkable  nature  of  the  alleged  phenomena  of  psychical  research 
that  gives  them  so  much  interest  and  influence ;  for  the  scientific 
scepticism  of  the  last  century  has  very  well  fortified  the  average  in- 
telligence against  some  of  the  vagaries  of  spiritualism.  But  it  is  the 
wonderful  triumphs  of  invention  and  discovery  in  the  fields  of  both 
science  and  art  that  have  destroyed  the  ordinary  criteria  of  the  limits  of 
human  knowledge  and  capacity,  so  that  the  average  mind  is  rapidly  com- 
ing to  expect  that  almost  anything  is  possible.  Electricity,  the  tele- 
phone, Roentgen  rays,  the  phonograph,  surgery,  hypnotism,  etc.,  have 
opened  up  such  a  fairy  land  of  wonders  and  possibilities  to  the  com- 
mon mind  that  it  is  not  surprising  to  see  many  otherwise  balanced  in- 
tellects yielding  to  the  claims  of  spiritualism.  Science  must  reckon 
with  this  condition  of  mind  and,  instead  of  employing  dogmatism 
against  it,  treat  its  alleged  phenomena  in  the  same  serious  and  sympa- 
thetic manner  that  insanity  receives.  Science  has  taught  us  not  to 
burn  witches,  as  they  did  once,  but  to  put  them  in  asylums.  Perhaps 
the  same  generous  treatment  of  psychical  research  may  still  further 
extend  the  operations  of  humanity.  To  do  this  also  it  will  not  re- 


THEORY  OF  RELIGION. 

quire  us  to  spend  our  summer  vacations  in  reading  any  very  large 
amount  of  occult  lore. 

JAMES  H.  HYSLOP. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


MR.  MARSHALL  AND  THE  THEORY  OF  RELIGION. 

Perhaps  the  most  interesting  problem  with  which  evolutionary  sci- 
ence has  to  deal  is  as  to  the  social  function  of  religion.  Religion  as  a 
very  general  and  large  phenomenon  could  have  survived  and  grown 
only  as  a  useful  element  in  the  struggle  of  existence  of  the  individual 
and  his  society.  This  evolutionary  assumption  that  what  is,  subsists 
and  increases  only  by  virtue  of  function ;  that  natural  evolution  is  an 
evolution  of  utilities,  and  that  useless  factors  are  always  speedily  elim- 
inated in  the  struggle  of  existence,  is  really  a  close  approach  to  the 
old  doctrine  of  evidences  by  which  the  theologian  makes  the  warrant 
of  religion  to  be  the  function  which  it  plays  in  man's  life.  For  in- 
stance, the  apologist  for  prayer  has  always  assured  us  that  such  a  prac- 
tice could  not  have  arisen  and  developed  except  that  it  met  a  real  need 
of  human  life  and  was  in  some  way  truly  answered,  and  the  evolution- 
ist as  biologist  and  sociologist  likewise  finds  that  prayer  by  its  very 
existence  shows  its  validation  as  an  important  factor  in  human  life,  if 
not  in  the  way  the  religionist  assumes,  at  least  in  some  way.  It  is  an 
interesting  fact  that,  though  science,  by  widening  the  domain  of  natural- 
ism indefinitely,  has  shown  that  the  religions  are  ineffectual  in  their 
methods,  yet  science,  by  its  own  assumption,  sees  in  religion  a  func- 
tion which  has  arisen  in  the  struggle  of  existence. 

Of  recent  interpretations  of  religion  from  the  point  of  view  of  evo- 
lutionary science  Mr.  H.  R.  Marshall's  l  Instinct  and  Reason*  is  the 
most  notable  and  thoroughgoing.  Mr.  Marshall  finds  that  evolution 
is  toward  organism,  which  is  action  of  the  part  for  the  whole,  and  in- 
stinct is  the  psychic  side  of  this  organic  tendency,  while  reason  is  the 
correspondent  of  individualistic  action.  The  main  stress  of  evolution 
is  to  subordinate  the  individual  organ  to  the  organic  whole,  the  eye  to 
minister  to  the  body  rather  than  to  itself,  the  individual  body  to  minister 
to  the  perpetuation  of  the  species  and  of  social  wholes.  But  indi- 
vidualism is  also  a  primitive  and  strong  interfering  tendency,  and  so, 
to  give  weight  to  the  organic,  Nature  gives  birth  to  religion  as  an  in- 
stinct restraining  us  from  undue  individualism.  Thus,  when  inclined  to 
selfish  actions  religion  appears  as  restraint,  and  so  impulsive  to  social 
activity.  The  earliest  sociality  has  to  do  with  the  perpetuation  of  the 


DISCUSSIONS.  299 

species  and  the  family  relations ;  hence  the  earliest  form  of  religion  is 
phallicism.  Religion  is  in  this  and  all  its  later  forms  fundamentally  a 
1  governing  instinct '  as  suppressing  individualism  and  helping  to  so- 
ciality. This  is  its  utility  amidst  all  its  seemingly  strange  and  per- 
verse forms,  an  eminent  utility  which  is  subserved  by  all  expressions 
of  the  religious  instinct,  fasting,  prayer,  sacrifice,  etc. 

That  social  utility  is  the  function  whereby  religion  has  persisted 
and  increased  in  human  affairs  is  a  familiar  thought,  but  the  merit  of 
Mr.  Marshall  is  that  he  has  given  this  a  large  biological  setting,  and 
has  brought  it  into  line  with  the  evolutionism  of  to-day.  In  his  theory 
religion  loses  its  absolutism  as  worship  of  the  Deity.  Religion  is 
*'  the  restraint  of  individualistic  impulses  to  racial  ones,"  implying  that 
the  belief  in  the  Deity  as  usually  found  being  from  the  psychological 
point  of  view  an  attachment  to,  rather  than  of  the  essence  of,  the  re- 
ligious feeling.  The  conservatism  of  religion  means  merely  that  it 
is  instinct,  which  is  by  its  nature  conservative,  and  thus  religion  opposes 
individualism  as  an  action  variant  from  the  general  racial  forms.  Re- 
ligion appears  as  restraining  influence,  an  instinctive  *  do  notj  even  in 
its  most  egotistic  forms,  as  it  marks  a  dependence  and  a  certain  out- 
ward reference  of  conduct.  Thus  religion  has  its  value,  not  in  its  sup- 
posed intrinsic  advantage  of  obtaining  good  things  from  a  deity,  which 
is  mostly  fiction  and  illusion,  but  as  repressive  to  the  lower  selfish  in- 
stincts which  tend  to  make  man  an  independent  unsocial  being. 

Now,  in  touching  upon  this  theory,  we  must  first  remark  that  it  re- 
poses in  a  large  part  upon  a  one-sided  view  of  organism.  Mere  natural 
organism  is  in  its  origin  and  early  stage  not  an  altruism  of  part  to 
whole ;  it  is  in  the  struggle  of  existence  a  method  of  advantage  by  a 
reciprocity  of  individuals ;  a  mode  of  exchange  of  values  whereby  the 
exchanger  always  seeks  to  give  the  least  for  the  most ;  to  get  off  with 
as  small  a  quid  pro  quo  as  possible,  or  none  at  all,  if  the  individual  is 
strong  enough.  The  struggle  for  advantage  in  organic  reciprocity  is 
common  to  the  origin  and  early  progress  of  organism  and  of  altruism  as 
mere  justice.  In  the  crude  struggle  of  existence  organic  social  forms 
arise  and  develop  to  a  certain  degree  of  community  of  interest  and 
reciprocity,  but  with  an  intrinsic  struggle  within  the  organism  itself 
for  dominance  by  each  organ.  Societies  are  very  largely  of  this  type 
even  in  civilized  life,  as  in  the  keen  rivalry  of  industrialism  and  com- 
mercialism, which  takes  every  advantage  for  a  bargain.  And  in  every 
organism  under  purely  natural  conditions  there  is  internal  disharmony 
and  rivalry  as  keen  in  its  way  and  as  selfish  as  the  struggle  of  the 
individual  society  with  other  societies.  Hence  religion  in  the  sense  of 


300  THEORY  OF  RELIGION. 

restraint  does  not  appear  in  pure  naturalism,  and  is  not  essential  to 
organic  activity.  The  only  restraint  in  elementary  societies  is  weak- 
ness ;  the  individual  does  not  take  more  because  he  dares  not.  The 
social  organism  as  range  of  reciprocity  is  at  first  wholly  governed  in 
the  measure  of  reciprocity  by  force  and  cunning,  and  thus  religion  as 
restraint  cannot  be  accounted  coextensive  with  organism. 

Now,  in  the  primitive  social  status,  where  a  mere  competitive 
reciprocity  is  the  mainspring,  religion  does  in  a  very  real  sense  exist 
as  direct  function  as  contrasted  with  the  indirect  function  of  restraint. 
Religion  is  primarily  a  method  of  reciprocity  with  superiors,  a  method 
involved  in  the  struggle  of  existence,  a  method  of  worship,  homage, 
devotion,  etc.,  to  find  favor  and  obtain  advantage  with  superiors, 
human  and  extra-human.  Religion  is  a  mode  of  socialization,  a  tie 
which  binds  child  to  parent,  wife  to  husband,  vassal  to  lord,  as  well 
as  a  tie  to  other  superiors  (supposedly  existing  in  our  view)  as  ances- 
tors and  nature  deities.  In  militarism  the  direct  function  of  religion 
is  very  great,  and  most  very  successful  military  leaders  have  been 
largely  successful  by  being  able  to  make  themselves  worshipped  and 
adored  by  their  men,  and  so  securing  perfect  obedience,  and  unity, 
and  dependence.  And  the  leader  surrounds  himself  with  godhood  by 
his  special  relationship  to  the  ancestral  and  nature  deities.  It  is  in 
this  way  that  what  appear  to  us  fictitious  deities  exercise  a  real  and 
valuable  utility  in  socialization ;  that  is,  by  association  with  the  living 
leader  and  chief.  At  the  same  time  it  must  be  recognized  that  mere 
religiousness  as  dependence  upon  the  extra-human  superior  has  been 
disadvantageous  as  destroying  intelligent  self-reliance.  The  superior 
and  intense  religiousness  of  the  Hebrews  never  made  them  a  great  con- 
quering nation.  In  the  military  competitive  struggle  of  tribes  for  ex- 
istence in  West  Africa,  Miss  Kings  ley  notes  that  the  Fans,  a  compar- 
atively unreligious  tribe,  are  in  the  ascendant.  In  modern  times  the 
most  successful  militarism  is  not  the  most  religious,  but  the  most 
scientifically  self-reliant.  And  the  tendency  is  to  rely  less  and  less  on 
religious  observance,  as  noting  of  omens,  invoking  deities,  etc.,  and 
to  give  the  time  to  drill  and  tactics,  and  to  make  the  soldier  self-reliant 
in  every  emergency. 

But  undoubtedly  religion  as  direct  function  plays  yet  a  most  im- 
portant function  in  militarism  and  in  political  and  social  aggregation. 
A  worship  and  homage  bind  the  masses  to  the  Czar  Alexander  and  to 
Queen  Victoria.  Human  beings  transcendently  exalted  by  their 
power,  intellect,  wealth,  still  enlist  a  vast  amount  of  religious  feeling 
and  activity  toward  themselves,  which  unifies  society  under  their  abso- 
lute leadership. 


DISCUSSIONS.  301 

But  the  tendency  of  modern  socialization  is  not  a  unification  of 
inferiors  to  supreme  superiors,  but  of  equals  to  equals  in  democracy. 
Hence,  as  the  supremely  superior  is  lost,  religion  as  direct  social  func- 
tion is  lost  also.  But  this  form  of  religion  has  a  survival  form  in  the 
phrases  of  courtesy,  such  as,  "  I  pray  you  and  beg  you  to  accept,"  by 
which  by  politeness  we  put  ourselves  as  suppliants,  but  this  is  a  mere 
ghost  of  the  historic  reality.  Democracy  emphasizes  vox  populi  as  vox 
dei ;  hence  a  positivist  religion,  religion  as  worship  of  humanity,  is  its 
natural  outcome  and  its  natural  binding  tie.  And  this  religion  directly 
emphasizes  the  true  organic  dependence  of  the  individual  and  the 
supremacy  of  the  race  as  such.  But  this  evolution  has  scarcely  begun, 
and  it  throws  no  light  on  the  historic  function  of  religion,  and  it  can 
hardly  be  claimed  that  the  direct  function  of  religion  sufficiently  ac- 
counts for  the  large  and  important  place  of  religion  in  the  history  of 
society,  but  it  is  still  a  valuable  clue,  and  one  much  neglected  by  Mr. 
Marshall.  Wherever  immense  superiority  has  appeared  man  has  sought 
to  ingratiate  himself  by  acts  of  worship  and  homage,  and  this  has 
been,  and  still  is,  a  successful  method  and  a  social  tie  within  the  range 
of  living  human  superiors ;  but  it  has  been  utterly  insufficient  when 
applied  to  what  science  deems  fictitious  superiors  in  environment,  as 
ghosts  and  nature  deities ;  nor  can  the  religion  of  these  have  its  full 
function  as  merely  a  background  and  basis  for  the  living  human 
superior  fully  to  exalt  himself  and  secure  worship.  Superior  though 
nature  be,  we  now  know  that  the  only  real  adaptation  to  it  is  not  by 
the  personal  method  of  religion,  but  by  intelligent  self-reliant  method 
of  applied  science.  A  vast  deal  of  historic  religion  has  thus  failed  of 
direct  utility,  and  we  can  only  suppose  that  the  justification  of  its  ex- 
istence lies  in  some  indirect  function. 

But,  if  as  mere  sanction  and  basis  of  authority  of  living  human 
superiority  this  religion  is  scarcely  sufficient  function,  we  may  add 
other  indirect  functions ;  for  instance,  dependence  for  example  and  also 
as  restraint. 

First,  then,  it  may  be  said  that  religion  as  dependence  and  obedi- 
ence thereby  emphasizes  and  encourages  a  habit  which  is  most  neces- 
sary to  socialization.  We  must  consider  this  function  of  religion  as  of 
value  in  the  history  of  society,  and  yet  we  must  regard  it  as  of  no  high 
significance.  And  we  must  note  that  religion  begins  rather  as  inter- 
dependence and  reciprocity,  the  god  being  as  dependent  on  the  wor- 
shipper as  the  worshipper  on  him.  In  this  matter  early  religion  but 
reflects  early  society.  But  religion  gradually  loses  reciprocity  and  be- 
comes absolute  dependence  of  man  on  deity,  and  at  the  same  time 


302  THEORY  OF  RELIGION. 

society  assumes  forms  of  absolute  dependence  on  supreme  power  of 
monarch  and  despot  and  hierarch.  It  must,  then,  be  considered  likely 
not  merely  that  religion  sets  a  model  for  social  relations,  but  vice 
versa  also.  Indeed,  so  far  as  religion  concerns  itself  with  the  extra- 
human  it  is  probably  derived  in  its  forms  and  spirit  from  religion  as 
direct  function  in  sociality.  And,  at  any  rate,  religion  as  setting  an  ex- 
ample of  absolute  dependence  is  harmful  to  high  socialization.  Re- 
ligion as  fostering  mendicancy,  poverty,  and  all  forms  of  unreciprocal 
dependence  has  been  a  distinct  drag  on  social  progress,  which  demands 
a  high  interdependence.  The  dependent  classes  are  the  problem  of 
modern  society.  A  vigorous  independence  and  individuality  is  most 
valuable  in  societies  where  freedom  reigns,  where  initiative  has  the 
freest  scope,  and  progress  is  least  hindered  by  conservative  religion. 
The  evolution  of  society  is  from  a  bare  competitive  reciprocity  up 
through  absolutism  to  the  higher  reciprocity  of  rational  free  indi- 
vidualism. Modern  society  is  dominated  by  the  scientific  spirit,  which 
demands  that  man  work  out  his  own  salvation  by  practical  apprecia- 
tion of  scientific  knowledge  and  method.  Science  encourages  an 
intelligent  dependence  on  the  specialist,  but  recognizes  infallibility 
nowhere,  and  it  must  regard  religion  as  anti-social  so  far  as  it  em- 
phasizes dependence  on  extra-human  beings,  and  thus  defeats  real 
social  cooperation  to  secure  the  end.  Thus  the  highest  sociality  is  a 
very  complex  interdependent,  self-reliant  specialism,  which  seeks  to 
control  nature  through  knowledge  by  natural  means.  Thus  the  British 
government  repressing  the  plague  in  India  is  a  higher,  more  success- 
ful type  of  society  than  the  Hindu  attitude  and  method  toward  the 
plague.  And  so  everywhere  religious  socialization  tends  to  be  sup- 
planted by  scientific,  and  so  far  as  religion  hinders,  by  example  or 
precept,  it  must  be  accounted  as  loss,  as  pathological  rather  than  really 
functional. 

We  have  mentioned  the  direct  function  of  religion  and  one  indirect 
function,  namely  as  setting  example  and  giving  emphasis  to  depend- 
ence, and  thus  helping  the  bond  between  inferior  and  superior  in 
society.  These  forms  of  function  have  little  if  any  notice  from  Mr. 
Marshall,  but  the  sociologist  must,  I  think,  regard  them  as  very  im- 
portant, although  hardly  solving  the  whole  problem  of  the  function  of 
religion.  However,  the  negative  side  of  the  indirect  function  we  have 
mentioned  is  restraint.  That  is,  it  is  plain  that  religion,  by  encourag- 
ing dependence,  thereby  restrains  and  inhibits  independence.  In  the 
moment  of  individualistic  action  we  receive  an  instinctive  check  and  an 
impulse  towards  social  and  racial  activity.  Religion  thus  holds  us 
to  the  narrow  path  of  typical  racial  action. 


DISCUSSIONS.  303 

In  regarding  religion  as  merely  negative  and  indirect  function  in 
repressing  the  lower,  unorganic,  individualistic  instincts,  Mr.  Marshall 
must  highly  offend  religionists  in  general,  who  make  religion  the  abso- 
lute and  supreme  end  of  life,  and  not  a  social  means.  Religion  has  al- 
ways had  to  do  battle  with  the  State,  which  has  ever  sought  to  enslave 
her  and  make  her  a  tool,  and  the  restraint  function  theory  lies  along  the 
same  line.  But  we  note  that  so  soon  as  the  feeling  permeates  religion 
itself  that  God  and  the  God-consciousness  are  mere  social  instruments 
religion  is  decadent,  becoming  formal  and  losing  real  vitality.  That 
is,  when  indirect  function  becomes  direct,  and  religion  is  observed  for 
its  social  values,  it  loses  its  real  power.  It  is  certain  that  religion  be- 
coming conscious  that  it  is  not  attaining  its  supposed  and  natural  end, 
but  seeking  to  continue  itself  as  a  mere  social  function,  soon  loses  this 
value.  However,  in  my  paper  on  the  psychology  of  religion  (PSY- 
CHOLOGICAL REVIEW,  May,  1898)  I  have  discussed  this  point  of  the 
socialistic  theory,  and  it  is  only  necessary  here  to  remark  the  paradox 
that  religion  must  be  kept  in  ignorance  of  itself  if  it  is  to  be  itself  and 
exercise  its  due  function. 

That  restraint,  the  negative  indirect  function,  as  impulse  which 
keeps  us  from  offending  the  social  order,  counts  largely  in  explaining 
the  persistence  of  religion  will  at  once  be  granted ;  but  it  cannot  be 
regarded  as  the  sole  social  utility  of  religion,  as  we  have  just  sought  to 
show.  But  early  religion  is  mainly  positive  in  function,  and  it  seems 
highly  improbable  that  it  originated  as  negative  inhibitive  instinct. 
Religion  primarily  is  a  direct  mode  of  obtaining  advantage  from  high 
superiors,  and  has  thus  been  carried  on  by  successive  generations  until 
it  has  become  instinctive,  as,  for  instance,  in  prayer.  It  is  not  unlikely 
that  prayer  originated  in  the  field  of  battle,  when  a  fallen  wounded  foe 
prayed  for  his  life  to  his  conqueror.  Religion  arises,  like  all  other 
utilities,  as  activity  hit  upon  in  a  critical  moment,  in  this  case  by  some 
inferior  in  relation  to  superior,  and  then  continued  and  improved  and  ulti- 
mately embodied  in  the  race  as  instinct.  This  is  the  assumption  which 
brings  religion  into  the  line  of  evolution.  A  Gold  Coast  negro  prays, 
"  God  give  me  to-day  rice  and  yams,  gold  and  agries;  give  me  slaves, 
riches  and  health,  and  that  I  may  be  brisk  and  swift !"  (Taylor, 
Primitive  Culture,  Vol.  II.,  p.  367.)  Where  is  restraint  implied  in 
such  religion  ?  And  yet  it  is  an  extremely  common  form  in  all  degrees 
of  culture,  especially  the  lower.  We  cannot  see  trace  of  restraint-func- 
tion in  a  vast  mass  of  religion  which  must  be  accounted  for.  It  is 
mainly  as  conducing  toward  a  human  intermediary  as  religious  spe- 
cialist, the  sorcerer,  and  so  towards  a  religious  organization  of  society, 


304  THEORY  OF  RELIGION. 

that  such  prayer  and  such  religion  in  general  have  social  bearing  and 
utility,  and  partly  as  fostering  the  habit  of  dependence ;  but  the  re- 
straint function  cannot  be  said  to  appear  at  this  stage.  The  simple, 
self-seeking  one  seeks  without  restraint  a  gratification  by  religious 
means.  In  a  vast  deal  of  similar  religion  there  is  evidently  no  conflict 
of  racial  and  individual,  and  hence  no  higher  governing  instinct,  as 
religion,  to  enter  in  and  restrain  the  powerful  instinctive,  selfish 
activity.  When  religion  becomes  not  merely  personal  means,  but 
personal  indulgence,  religion  becomes  unrestraint,  as  we  see,  for  in- 
stance, in  many  phenomena  of  revivalism.  (See,  for  instance,  Sidis, 
Psychology  of  Suggestion,  passim. )  Religion  has  done  much  to  retard 
society  by  its  formal  conservatism,  and  to  break  up  society  in  the  heat 
of  powerful  emotions ;  and  all  this  must  be  taken  into  account  in  a 
full  view  of  the  subject.  The  reformer  and  radical  believe  they  have 
the  God-given  message  and  methods,  and  thus  society  has  often  been 
disturbed  and  sometimes  even  the  family  set  at  nought,  as  in  hermit- 
age and  celibacy.  In  Christianity  itself  the  family  is  secondary,  and 
the  disciple  must  be  ready  to  hate  even  father  and  mother.  Religion 
of  the  highest  type,  as  interfering  with  the  natural  evolution  of  worldly 
success  and  advantage  by  individuals  and  societies,  and  setting  up  an 
unworldly,  mystic,  spiritual  kingdom,  destroys  natural  evolution,  and 
hence  naturalistic  science  must  consider  it  pathological  or  seek  some 
indirect  function,  as  does  Mr.  Marshall. 

Mr.  Marshall's  definition  of  religion  as  an  instinctive  check  to  indi- 
vidualistic action,  a  *  stopj  '  do  notj  coming  as  from  a  high  divine 
source,  is  far  too  narrow  for  either  psychology  or  sociology,  which  must 
study  religion  as  a  general  relation  of  inferior  to  superior  in  manifold 
forms  and  functions,  as  direct,  and  sanction,  as  example,  as  restraint. 
Every  hypothesis,  such  as  Marshall's,  however  skillfully  deduced  from 
biological  assumptions,  must  be  tested  without  bias  by  definite  and 
extended  study  of  historic  facts,  an  immense  and  very  complex  field. 
And  as  Mr.  Marshall  fails  to  do  this  the  scientific  mind  is  disap- 
pointed. If  even  the  religious  experience  of  some  single  individual 
were  thoroughly  analyzed,  something  would  have  been  gained  for 
scientific  exactness,  but,  as  it  is,  his  work  remains  as  at  best  an  ingenious 
suggestive  speculation. 

HIRAM  M.  STANLEY. 

LAKE  FOREST, ILL. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

The  Psychology  of  Peoples.     GUSTAVE  LE  BON.     New  York,  The 

Macmillan  Company.     1898.     Pp.  xx  -f-  236. 

As  the  title  implies,  the  author  believes  that  it  is  the  psychology, 
chiefly  the  character,  of  peoples  which  determine  their  arts,  institu- 
tions and  history.  The  problems  involved  have  been  treated  more 
fully  in  works  on  the  civilizations  of  the  East,  and  "  this  short  volume 
may  be  regarded  as  a  brief  synthesis."  **  Each  of  the  chapters  com- 
posing it  should  be  regarded  as  the  conclusion  arrived  at  by  anterior 
investigations."  The  work  is  divided  into  five  books  dealing  with  the 
psychological  characteristics  of  races,  how  these  are  displayed  in  the 
various  elements  of  the  culture  of  races,  race-history  determined  by 
race-character,  how  psychological  characteristics  are  modified,  and  the 
dissociation  of  race-character  and  decadence. 

The  central  idea  of  the  work  is  that  races  possess  souls  the  acquisi- 
tion of  which  marks  the  apogee  of  their  greatness  and  the  loss  of 
which  marks  their  decay.  In  this  soul,  sentiment,  beliefs  and  inter- 
ests are  the  moving  and  directing  principles,  and  these  constitute  the 
basis  of  what  the  author  calls  character.  Very  meagre  importance  is 
assigned  to  the  role  of  intelligence  in  the  civilization  of  peoples,  even 
beliefs  being  determined  by  suggestion  and  imitation  so  far  as  they 
affect  the  masses.  Culture  is  merely  a  matter  of  memory:  it  can  be 
acquired  by  inferior  races,  but  does  not  affect  character.  Inferior  races 
are  distinguished  from  superior  ones  by  differences  of  character  solely ; 
superior  races  are  distinguished  from  each  other  by  variations  of  both 
character  and  intelligence.  Wide  variations  between  individuals  are 
the  mark  of  developed  races,  but  they  do  not  count  in  determining  the 
rank  of  a  race.  In  estimating  character,  the  masses  alone  are  to  be 
taken  into  account. 

Ideas  "  do  not  exert  an  influence  until,  after  a  very  slow  evolution, 
they  have  been  transformed  into  sentiments  and  have  come,  in  conse- 
quence, to  form  part  of  character.  They  are  then  unaffected  by  argu- 
ment and  take  a  long  time  to  disappear."  u  Religious  ideas  are 
among  the  most  important  of  the  guiding  ideas  of  a  civilization.  The 
majority  of  historical  events  have  been  due  indirectly  to  the  variation  of 

305 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  PEOPLES. 

religious  beliefs.  The  history  of  humanity  has  always  run  parallel  to 
that  of  its  gods  "  (p.  235).  "  In  religion,  as  in  politics,  success  always 
goes  to  those  who  believe,  never  to  those  who  are  sceptical,  and  if  at 
the  present  day  it  would  seem  as  if  the  future  belonged  to  the  so- 
cialists, in  spite  of  the  dangerous  absurdity  of  their  dogmas,  the  rea- 
son is  that  they  are  now  the  only  party  possessing  real  convictions  " 
(p.  178).  "  Faith  is  the  only  serious  enemy  which  faith  has  to  fear." 
"  A  people  is  only  led  by  those  who  embody  its  dreams."  The  author 
gives  an  interesting  account  of  the  genesis  of  such  faiths,  a  process  in 
which  reason  plays  but  an  insignificant,  and  suggestion  an  all-important, 
role.  Propagation  of  faith  is  never  by  argument,  and  always  by  asser- 
tion, affirmation,  impression.  In  time  "  the  mere  effect  of  imitation, 
acting  as  a  contagion,  a  faculty  with  which  men  are  generally  en- 
dowed in  as  high  a  degree  as  are  the  big  anthropoid  apes,"  insures  the 
spread  of  the  idea ;  and  then  it  is  that  it  becomes  a  matter  of  senti- 
ment and  an  element  in  character  in  the  race.  Then  it  is  irresistible 
to  argument.  It  is  such  factors  of  the  common  life  of  individuals 
which  make  the  race  l  a  permanent  being  that  is  independent  of  time/ 

The  author  holds  that  religious  faith  is  the  all-important  moment 
in  the  life  of  humanity,  but  he  considers  the  objects  of  religious  faith 
to  be  « illusions,'  '  chimeras,'  <  hallucinations'  and  '  the  children  of  our 
dreams,'  leaving  the  reader  to  infer  that  humanity  is  self-deluded. 
And  this  inference  accords  in  general  with  the  almost  cynical  and  pes- 
simistic tone  which  the  author's  thought  at  times  assumes.  He  pre- 
dicts that  Europe  will  be  swallowed  up  of  socialism,  and  that  America 
will  be  torn  to  pieces  by  an  inter-race  war  between  the  incompatible 
elements  that  constitute  her  population.  As  to  human  nature  in  gen- 
eral, "  of  all  the  factors  in  the  development  of  civilizations,  illusions 
are,  perhaps,  the  most  powerful  "  (p.  207).  The  triumph  of  ideas  "  is 
insured  when  they  are  defended  by  the  hallucinated  and  by  enthusiasts. 
It  is  of  slight  importance  whether  they  be  true  or  not"  (p.  206). 
"  Doubtless  it  is  man  who  created  the  gods,  but  after  having  created 
them  he  promptly  became  their  slave"  (p.  192).  Is  it  cynicism,  or  is 
it  simply  a  love  for  antithesis  and  epigram  ? 

The  work  gives  an  interesting  account  of  many  of  the  facts  of  the 
race-consciousness  and  laws  of  its  modifications.  The  style  is  inter- 
esting and  strong.  Many  valuable  suggestions  are  contained  in  the 
work.  The  author's  personal  philosophy  of  religion  is,  however, 
irrelevant  to  the  theme,  and  rather  weakens  than  strengthens  the  clos- 
ing chapters  of  the  work. 

BELOIT  COLLEGE.  GUY  TAWNEY. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  307 

Les    origines   de   la    psychologic    contemporaine.       D.    MERCIER. 

Louvain,  Institut  Superieure  de  Philosophic,  1897.    Pp.  xii  -f  486. 

Fr.  5. 

This  book  is  mainly  a  critical  review  of  modern  idealism  from  the 
standpoint  of  the  neo-scholastic.  To  him  the  development  and  out- 
come of  post-Cartesian  idealism  amounts  to  a  reductio  ad  absurdum  of 
its  fundamental  assumption.  This  assumption  is  none  other  than  the 
sharp  distinction  introduced  by  Descartes  between  the  two  substances 
soul  and  body,  soul  essentially  thought,  body  essentially  extension,  the 
two  being  utterly  irreducible  and  incomparable,  and  their  anion  a 
sphinx's  riddle.  Occasionalism,  ontologism,  and  parallelism  were  but 
so  many  artificial  efforts  to  guess  the  riddle.  More  consequent  is  the  neg- 
ative attitude  of  idealism,  beginning  with  Locke's  denial  of  clear  ideas 
of  the  substances  matter  and  mind,  and  passing  through  Berkeley's  utter 
rejection  of  matter,  and  Hume's  utter  rejection  of  mind,  to  Kant's  de- 
monstration that  knowledge  of  substance  was  not  only  unattained,  but 
from  the  nature  of  thought  unattainable.  Kant  still  believed  in  em- 
pirical certainty,  but  here  the  author  finds  him  inconsequent.  If  the 
objects  of  thought  are  determined  by  thought,  no  certainty  is  possible. 
The  system  of  Hegel  did  not  escape  the  subjectivistic  difficulty,  and 
was,  indeed,  a  construction  of  the  imagination  rather  than  of  reason 
(239).  The  truly  logical  consequences  of  the  Kantian  principles  are 
seen  in  the  doctrines  of  some  recent  French  writers — such  as  Remacle, 
who  contends  that  agnostic  idealism  must  be  extended  to  cover  ideas 
themselves ;  that  is,  that  even  inner  experiences,  as  known,  are  not  the 
experiences  as  they  are  in  themselves — or  such  as  Louis  Weber,  who 
concludes  that  the  only  truth  is  the  truth  of  a  judgment,  that  outside 
of  the  judgment  there  is  no  existence. 

This  position  of  utter  negation,  though  the  only  logical  outcome 
of  idealism,  is  self -destructive  (340).  For  a  judgment  is  meaningless 
unless  it  refers  to  some  existence  independent  of  the  judgment.  And 
unless  an  object  is  known  as  it  is  in  itself,  it  evidently  cannot  be  known 
to  be  different  from  our  idea  of  it.  The  Kantian  difficulty  is  the  Car- 
tesian folly,  that  of  first  conceiving  a  mind  apart  from  its  objects 
('  pure'  reason),  and  objects  apart  from  any  mind  (things  '  in  them- 
selves'), and  then  wondering  how  the  two  are  to  be  brought  together 

(344)- 

As  idealism  proceeds  from  Descartes'  definition  of  the  soul,  so  from 
his  definition  of  the  physical  has  grown  the  conception  of  a  universal 
reign  of  mechanical  law.  If  all  other  bodies  are  machines,  why  not 
the  human  body ;  and  if  the  single  human  body,  why  not  those  largei 


308  PSYCHOLOGIE   CONTEMPORAINE. 

organisms,  the  species  in  its  development  (Darwin),  and  human  so- 
ciety in  its  history  (Comte)  ?  The  system  of  Comte  is  thus  on  its 
positive  side  a  carrying-out  of  the  Cartesian  doctrine  of  body,  while 
on  its  negative,  anti-metaphysical  side  it  is  an  attempt  to  escape  the 
more  brutal  materialistic  consequences  of  the  same  doctrine  (77). 

Thus  our  author  traces  back  to  Descartes  the  two  negative 
characteristics  of  contemporary  psychology ;  its  idealistic  dependence, 
in  all  matters  of  theory,  on  the  data  of  consciousness  alone,  and  its 
positivistic  neglect  of  ontology  and  rational  psychology.  Its  third 
great  characteristic,  derived  from  natural  science,  is  its  increasing  use 
of  experiment.  The  author  brings  together  evidence  of  the  neglect  of 
metaphysics  in  the  universities  and  of  the  vigor  of  experimental  study. 

Among  contemporary  psychologists,  Mercier  picks  out  three  as 
attempting  either  to  harmonize  or  to  supplement  the  current  Cartesian 
tendencies.  Spencer  attempts  a  synthesis  of  the  various  conflicting 
elements.  But  he  supplies  no  true  organic  unity.  Nor  does  his 
4  transfigured  realism '  amount  to  more  than  a  hazy  belief.  As  for 
his  doctrine  of  universal  evolution,  it  is  a  mere  expansion  by  analog/ 
of  a  biological  hypothesis,  and  owes  its  prestige  less  to  agreement 
with  facts  than  to  its  hold  on  the  imagination  (144,  145)-  Fouillee, 
though  idealist  and  positivist,  tries  to  avoid  some  of  the  negative  con- 
sequences of  these  doctrines  by  introducing  the  conception  of  *  idees- 
forces,'  i.  e.,  of  the  idea  as  dynamic,  and  of  conscious  or  sub-conscious 
life  as  the  dynamic  principle  of  all  physical  existence.  But  when  he 
would  furnish  a  ground  for  knowledge  of  substantial  reality,  he  can 
do  no  better  than  to  allow  the  dynamic  idea  to  create  or  postulate  the 
reality  it  wants  ('fiat  Deus').  Wundt  would  enrich  idealism  by 
substituting  the  conception  of  *  actuality  '  for  the  conception  of  sub- 
stance, and  voluntarism  for  intellectualism.  The  latter  attempt  he 
carries  too  far.  His  genesis  of  ideas  from  the  action  of  '  pure  will ' 
is  as  much  a  creation  '  ex  nihilo '  as  the  intellectualist's  derivation  of 
the  will  from  mere  ideas  (214).  Yet  Wundt  is  not  far  from  the 
kingdom.  If  he  "  could  disencumber  himself  of  his  idealistic  and 
positivistic  prejudices,  and  of  the  false  notion  of  substance  that  he 
borrowed  from  Kant,  and  follow  freely  the  direction  which  his  own 
researches  force  upon  him,  he  would  logically  be  led  to  accept  the 
fundamental  theories  of  Aristotle's  psychology.  He  would  no  longer 
consider  the  characteristic  mark  of  the  psychical  as  residing  in  con- 
sciousness. He  would  accept  *  *  *  the  conception  which  regards  the 
soul  as  '  the  first  entelechy  of  the  living  body.'  And  the  soul,  so  consid- 
ered, would  appear  in  all  truth  as  4  that  empirical  concept  of  which 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  309 

everyone  makes  use  who  really  and  successfully  cultivates  empirical 
psychology  and  not  barren  speculation'"  (216). 

This  is  the  doctrine  of  the  soul  which  the  neo-scholastic  pro- 
pounds in  place  of  the  Cartesian  separation  between  body  and  soul. 
Man  as  we  know  him  is  not  a  pure  consciousness,  but  a  compound  of 
mind  and  body.  Results  deduced  from  the  conception  of  conscious- 
ness as  isolated  from  the  body  are  not  applicable  to  the  actual  man. 
Psychology,  so  understood,  is  an  arbitrary  abstraction.  What  is  wanted 
is  an  anthropology,  based  upon  the  fundamental  thesis  of  the  substantial 
unity  of  man  (295).  The  soul  of  man  is  the  soul  of  the  entire  man, 
and  is  not  to  be  found  wholly  in  consciousness.  Its  primordial  func- 
tion is  not  thought  or  feeling,  but  the  « informing  and  animating  of 
the  matter  of  the  body.' 

Between  the  soul  and  its  acts  we  must,  on  metaphysical  grounds, 
assume  the  existence  of  faculties,  substantially  distinct  from  the  soul 
(304) .  Since  a  faculty  is  simply  a  means  of  arriving  at  an  act,  there 
are  as  many  separate  faculties  as  there  are  types  of  the  soul's  action. 
There  are  five  groups  of  faculties,  those  of  organic  life,  those  of  sen- 
sory knowledge,  those  of  intellectual  knowledge,  those  of  will,  and 
those  of  locomotion.  Feeling  and  will,  on  the  other  hand,  are  not 
separate  acts,  but  parts  of  the  same  act.  Feeling  is  but  the  passive 
side  which  appears  in  every  state  of  consciousness,  but  which  has  been 
overlooked  because  the  mind,  in  its  Cartesian  isolation,  was,  almost 
of  necessity,  conceived  as  the  source  of  its  own  ideas  and  as  altogether 
active. 

In  conclusion,  the  author  sketches  the  history  of  the  neo-Thomistic 
movement,  recognizes  that  the  dogmatic  method  of  the  old  scholastic 
philosophers  must  now-a-days  be  replaced  by  a  critical  method,  and 
urges  his  colleagues  to  foster  experimental  psychology,  for  which  their 
own  fundamental  conceptions  provide  the  only  logical  basis. 

The  above  summary  of  the  author's  principal  line  of  argument 
passes  by  several  interesting  chapters,  such  as  those  which  defend  the 
conceptions  of  supra-sensible  knowledge  and  of  finality  immanent  in 
nature.  To  criticise  the  author's  views  would  lead  us  too  far  afield. 
His  style  is  clear  and  attractive.  His  argument  is  skillfully  conducted, 
and  is  well  worth  some  attention  from  those  who  have  been  brought 
up  on  an  idealistic  diet.  The  main  defects  of  the  book  lie  in  the  direc- 
tion of  inadequacy.  His  statements  of  opposing  views  are  admirably 
fair  and  objective,  so  far  as  they  go.  But  he  does  not  do  justice  to 
the  positive  side  of  the  work  of  Kant  and  his  successors.  Still  less  is 
his  summary  statement  of  certain  scholastic  doctrines  adequate  to  carry 


310  LA   PERSONNE  HUMAINE. 

conviction.     For  a  fuller  statement  of  them  the  reader  is  presumably 
referred  to  other  books  by  the  same  author. 

ROBERT  S.  WOODWORTH. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

La  Personne  Humaine.     L'ABBE  C.  PIAT.     Paris,  Alcan.     1897. 

Pp.  401. 

The  theme  of  this  work  is  suggested  by  the  contradiction  between 
the  representations  of  human  personality  formulated  by  the  traditional 
spiritualistic  philosophy  and  those  current  in  modern  scientific  psy- 
chology. According  to  the  former  the  human  person  is  a  unique,  in- 
divisible, self -identical  and  permanent  entity,  actively  producing  and 
supporting  its  states  and  possessed  of  intrinsic  capacities  of  reflection, 
in  virtue  of  which  it  is  rational,  responsible  and  free.  According  to 
the  latter  the  conscious  self  is  a  resultant  of  the  play  of  a  manifold  of 
elements,  the  coordination  of  which  constitutes  its  unity,  and  this  co- 
ordination is  never  absolutely  complete,  but  is  capable,  under  patho- 
logical conditions,  of  such  profound  disturbances  that  two  or  even 
more  personal  consciousnesses  may  successively  or  simultaneously  arise 
in  connection  with  the  same  bodily  organism  ;  the  organism  itself,  and 
not  an  independent  conscious  entity,  is  then  commonly  regarded  as  the 
substantial  bearer  of  the  mental  life,  which  latter  is  represented  as 
everywhere  conforming  to  general  principles  of  evolution  and  subject 
to  the  inexorable  necessity  of  nature.  We  have  here  a  clear,  forcible 
and  eloquent  apology  for  the  spiritualistic  tradition  face  to  face  with 
the  newly-discovered  or  newly-emphasized  facts  of  science  and  in  con- 
flict with  dominant  scientific  hypotheses. 

The  argument  falls  into  three  main  divisions,  entitled  respectively 
Perception,  Reflection  and  Responsibility.  The  first  maintains  by  the 
usual  appeal  to  the  unity  of  consciousness,  recognitive  memory,  etc., 
the  original  unity  and  persistent  identity  of  the  self,  and  criticises  the 
evidence  to  the  contrary  in  the  facts  of  double  consciousness.  The 
second  maintains  the  unique  originality  of  the  power  of  the  human 
mind  to  think  of  and  through  universals,  and  criticises  the  evidence  for 
the  derivation  of  this  faculty  on  evolutional  principles  from  an  organic 
process,  from  instinct  or  from  the  language  of  the  lower  animals. 
The  third  maintains  the  reality  of  freedom  relatively  to  the  moral 
ideal  as  a  living  and  concrete  perception,  and,  explaining  the  con- 
sciousness of  responsibility  as  dependent  on  a  number  of  elements  in- 
dependently variable,  sets  forth  the  causes  and  consequences  of  its 
enfeeblement  with  impressive  reference  to  certain  features  in  the  dark 
obverse  of  modern  civilization. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  311 

From  a  scientific  point  of  view  the  most  valuable  parts  of  the 
book  are  probably  the  critical.  The  criticism  of  the  phenomena  of 
double  consciousness  follows  the  lines  made  familiar  to  us  by  Professor 
Ladd  in  demanding  more  accurate  observation  and  description  of  the 
facts  and  in  explaining  the  accredited  phenomena  partly  as  pure  auto- 
matisms and  partly  as  changes  due  to  distraction  of  attention  in  the 
field,  rather  than  in  the  subject  of  consciousness.  The  criticism  of  the 
evolution  theory  in  the  second  part  is  also  unquestionably  acute, 
though  in  insisting  so  strongly  on  the  <  fait  decisif  '  it  seems  to  overlook 
the  vast  heuristic  importance  of  a  conception  which  may  fall  far  short 
of  the  verification  desired.  Still,  as  over  against  a  certain  tendency 
to  elevate  a  scientific  theory  into  a  scientific  dogma,  it  is  not  bad  to  be 
reminded  once  in  a  while,  even  at  the  risk  of  some  exaggeration,  of 
its  actual  shortcomings. 

As  to  the  positive  constructions  of  the  book,  the  questions  involved 
are  so  many  and  so  complex  that  it  is  difficult  to  say  anything  without 
saying  much,  and  any  extended  discussion  would  be  here  out  of  place. 
A  few  words  on  one  point  only  must  suffice.  The  contradiction  which 
the  author  notices  at  the  outset  is  certainly  one  which  occasions  no  lit- 
tle perplexity  to  the  student  and  the  clearing  up  of  which  is  a  task 
worthy  of  a  philosopher.  But  when,  fresh  from  the  reading  of  Ribot 
and  Binet  or,  say,  from  the  penetrating  chapters  of  Mr.  Bradley,  one 
goes  for  more  light  on  the  unity  and  identity  of  the  human  person  to 
the  pages  of  this  book,  one  can  hardly  help  feeling,  with  all  admira- 
tion for  the  lucidity  of  the  style  and  the  intellectual  and  moral  tone  of 
the  discussion,  that  the  real  difficulties  have  not  been  met  after  all. 
One  admits,  of  course,  the  unity  of  the  consciousness,  in  each  particu- 
lar act  of  attention,  what  James  calls  i  the  unity  of  the  passing  state,' 
whether  the  state  be  one  of  perception,  of  recognitive  memory  or  what 
not;  but  to  find  in  this  the  evidence  of  the  unity  and  persistent  identity 
of  the  concrete  self,  seems  trivial.  For  this  unity  of  consciousness, 
even  if  we  include  in  it  the  invisible  unity  of  the  subject  4 1,'  surely 
is  not  the  self,  the  person,  of  which  we  and  the  writers  whom  M.  Piat 
opposes  are  thinking.  And  when,  taking  up  the  concrete  self  in  all 
the  complexity  of  its  changing  content  and  the  variety  of  its  aspects, 
we  ask  after  its  nature  and  significance,  then  it  is  that  our  question  be- 
comes burdened  with  all  the  weight  of  the  problems  of  biological  and 
psychological  science  and  of  social  and  metaphysical  interpretation. 
It  is  noteworthy  that,  while  claiming  for  the  ego  an  existence  as  a  per- 
manent unity,  on  the  direct  testimony  of  consciousness,  M.  Piat  refers 
the  question  of  its  substantiality  to  theology  and  faith.  So  far  as  this 


312  CITIZENSHIP  AND   SALVATION. 

points  to  a  higher  criterion  of  judgment  than  that  furnished  by  empir- 
ical psychology,  it  embodies  a  true  instinct.  For  the  ultimate  mean- 
ing of  personality  is  found,  not  in  the  facts  of  consciousness,  but  in 
ideals  of  the  will.  As  Hegel  said,  the  great  thing  is  not  to  be  a  person, 
but  to  become  one.  But,  if  this  is  so,  then  the  first  thing  to  do  is  to 
discriminate  as  far  as  may  be  with  the  utmost  clearness  the  different 
questions  at  issue  and  the  different  points  of  view  from  which  they 
may  be  legitimately  regarded.  It  is  more  than  likely  that  when  the 
presuppositions  and  relativity  of  the  different  standpoints  are  fully 
understood,  the  disputes  between  spiritualists  and  phenomenalists, 
metaphysicians  and  scientific  psychologists,  will  largely  disappear. 
Philosophical  dogmatism  now  as  of  old  renders  discussion  interminable. 

H.  N.  GARDINER. 
SMITH  COLLEGE. 

Citizenship  and  Salvation,  or  Greek  and  Jew.  A  Study  in  the 
Philosophy  of  History.  ALFRED  H.  LLOYD.  Boston,  Little, 
Brown  &  Co.  1897.  Pp.  142. 

Stevenson,  in  one  of  his  essays,  remarks  that  the  purpose  of  a 
preface  is  to  give  the  author  of  a  book  the  opportunity,  after  his  labors 
are  over,  to  appear  before  the  public  with  his  plans,  and  proudly  pro- 
claim the  nature  of  his  achievement.  The  reviewer  of  Citizenship  and 
Salvation  would  be  much  surer  of  his  ground  if  Dr.  Lloyd  had  availed 
himself  of  this  privilege  of  the  author  and  not  sent  this  interesting,  but 
very  obscure,  little  book  out  into  the  world  without  a  prefatory  word. 
The  work  is  divided  into  three  parts,  entitled,  respectively,  '  The  Death 
of  Socrates,'  '  The  Death  of  Christ/  and  <  Resurrection/  It  is,  as  its 
secondary  title  indicates,  a  '  Study  in  the  Philosophy  of  History/  and 
it  is  conceived  in  a  thoroughly  Hegelian  spirit,  although  entirely  in- 
dependent and  original  in  plan  and  execution.  It  is  also  called  by  the 
author  a  'biological  study  of  self-denial,'  and  might  equally  well  be 
styled  a  metaphysical  study  of  self-realization.  It  is  not  a  '  super- 
natural '  or  '  unnatural  self-hood,'  however,  that  is  realized  in  self-denial, 
not  '  a  self  that  originally  was  not.'  Self-denial  is  *  the  way  to  the  ex- 
pression of  an  already  active  life,  of  an  already  living  ideal.'  In  other 
words,  the  self  that  gets  'fulfilled'  in  the  historical  process  through 
self-denial  was  from  the  first «  secure  '  and  «  active.'  History,  progress, 
means  the  record  of  successive  self-denials,  rendered  necessary  by  the 
incompleteness  of  ideals  and  the  consequent  clashing  of  opposing  ten- 
dencies, which  ever  result  in  self-fulfilment.  Socrates,  for  example, 
the  real  Socrates,  was  '  vitally  present  in  the  life  of  Greece  from  the 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  313 

very  beginning;'  he  was  'the  inner  motive  of  Greece  that  had  in  spite 
of  all  determined  her  destiny  from  the  very  beginning.'  He  was 
alive  in  Greece  long  before  Phaenarete  gave  him  birth  on  the  slopes  of 
Lycabettus,  and  he  continued  to  live  after  he  had  drunk  the  poison, 
getting  fulfilled  even  in  his  own  death  and  in  the  death  of  his  race  in 
the  triumph  of  Rome.  The  contradiction  which  led  to  the  tragedy  of 
Socrates'  death  was  the  contradiction  between  the  worldly  life,  the 
4  miserly '  life,  which  takes  means  for  end,  and  '  the  life  apart  from 
the  world,  which  assumes  that  the  end  will  realize  itself.'  Either 
attitude  alone  would  check  fulfilment.  Divorce  of  means  and  end 
meant  their  reunion  in  an  historical  movement,  which  Philip  of  Mace- 
don  and  Alexander  in  fact  inaugurated,  and  which  Rome  completed. 
Of  this  movement  the  philosopher  was  Aristotle,  who  taught  that  the 
soul  is  not  an  end  by  itself,  but  the  end  or  purpose  of  the  body,  and 
that,  similarly,  the  world  is  to  be  regarded  as  the  incarnation  of  reason. 
When  reason  is  regarded,  however,  as  the  world's,  it  comes  to  be  re- 
garded as  no  longer  man's,  and  thus  forgetf ulness  becomes  '  the  suc- 
cessor of  reason  in  man,'  and  man  himself  is  then  considered  as  '  but 
a  means  to  the  world's  end.'  The  universal  empire  of  Rome,  with  its 
militarism  and  mechanism,  is  the  inevitable  outcome.  Thus  Rome 
completes  the  work  of  Alexander  and  Aristotle. 

The  way  is  now  prepared  for  Christ,  who  as  the  *  World- Reason ' 
(the  '  Word  Incarnate,'  the  *  revealed  ideal ')  is  'the  liberator  of  the 
world.'  This  Christ,  however,  is  not  merely  the  historical  Jesus,  but, 
again,  as  in  the  case  of  Socrates,  a  motive  always  present,  although  in 
him  become  at  last,  in  a  special  sense,  active.  This  idea  of  a  World- 
Reason  revealed  unto  men,  is  the  self  of  Christ  that  triumphs  in  Roman 
Christianity.  When  we  turn  to  Judea,  moreover,  we  observe  a  conflict 
similar  to  that  which  existed  at  Athens ;  there  we  find  the  same  'co- 
operation of  symmetrical  opposites.'  Jewish  idolatry  of  the  past  had 
come  to  be  pure  formalism,  lacking  all  vital  content;  and  Christ,  as 
the  Messiah,  expressed  in  life  '  an  as  yet  unrealized  ideal.'  The  re- 
spective attitudes  of  Christ  and  his  people  were,  however,  but  contra- 
dictory and  one-sided  aspects  of  the  single  activity  which  constituted 
the  national  motive  of  the  Jewish  people.  Hence  the  collision  was 
inevitable,  and  in  that  collision — the  crucifixion — the  Jewish  ideal  is 
set  free.  And  here  we  come  upon  a  very  ingenious  theory  of  our 
author's.  The  motive  of  the  Jewish  people  found  also  its  expression 
in  money  lending.  Money,  as  a  commodity,  is  the  treasured  past 
which  the  Jews  idolized ;  lending,  on  the  other  hand,  affirms  the 
future  as  motive.  '  In  money-lending  the  confusion  of  future  with 


3H  CITIZENSHIP  AND   SALVATION. 

past  found  expression,  and  a  national  life,  so  long  isolated,  so  long- 
deprived  of  participation  in  distinctly  worldly  affairs,  was  set  free,  the 
people  turning  their  necessity  into  opportunity'  (p.  81).  And  so 
the  Jews  became  Christians  in  their  own — 4  a  very  worldly  way.' 
They  with  their  talent  for  money-lending,  and  the  Christians,  with 
their  spiritual  other  -world,  severally  conquer  Rome. 

Let  us  apply  these  ideas.  Rome  had  become,  before  the  appear- 
ance of  Christianity,  a  military  government,  a  mechanism.  Each  part, 
each  citizen,  of  such  a  government  says  in  effect :  *  I  am  not,  because 
we  are  all  one  and  equal.'  Yet  each  feels,  when  the  mechanism 
moves,  as  the  soldier  feels  after  the  battle  :  1 1  did  it'  (p.  90,  91).  'A 
sentient  mechanism  is  a  whole  which  upon  action  breaks  into  a 
group  of  microcosmic  reproductions  of  itself,'  that  is,  it  becomes  an 
organism  (p.  91).  Christianity,  therefore,  was  able  to  interpret  Rome 
unto  herself,  for  Christianity  is  summed  up  in  the  word  organism, 
which  Dr.  Lloyd  '  likes  to  call  the  Christ-motive.'  Now  there  are 
two  4  chief  incidents  of  all  activity,'  sanction  and  interpretation. 
(This  is  introduced  with  an  '  of  course.')  Socrates  '  sanctioned ' 
the  Roman  empire,  Christ  '  interpreted '  it.  But  the  interpretation 
is,  as  always,  fatal.  Organism  and  mechanism  cannot  co-exist.  The 
remaining  history  of  Rome  is  simply  the  record  of  a  process,  in  which 
the  leaven  of  the  idea  of  organism  is  spreading  more  and  more.  Phi- 
losophy, with  her  dispute  over  universals,  over  substances  and  monads 
and  a  priori  forms,  tells  the  same  story.  And  Kant  is  the  last  great 
Roman  philosopher. 

In  the  third  part  of  the  book,  conclusions  are  drawn — not  without 
an  apology.  Democracy  is  seen  to  be  the  goal,  and  at  the  same  time 
the  fulfilment  of  monarchy.  It  is  also  the  consummation  of  the 
4  Christ-motive' organism.  In  a  democracy,  each  citizen  is,  in  fact, 
a  parvus  in  suo  genere  rex,  each  has  4  imperial  rights  over  his  own 
complete  self-expression.'  At  the  same  time,  each  becomes  a  media- 
tor for,  represents,  all  the  rest,  in  his  own  individual  way.  In  order 
that  he  may  properly  do  this,  however,  he  should  have  '  credit '  pre- 
cisely in  proportion  to  his  power  to  apply  the  world's  forces,  and  the 
bank  should  be  merely  an  institution  for  gauging  this  credit  by  accu- 
rately measuring  each  man's  individual  *  capacity  for  action.'  When 
banking  reaches  this  perfect  stage,  every  capitalist  will  be  a  laborer, 
and  every  laborer  a  capitalist.  The  church  will  undergo  a  similar  res- 
urrection. It  will  cease  hoarding  the  future,  as  the  bank  will  cease 
hoarding  the  past,  and  turn  its  attention  to  the  '  more  vital  expression' 
of  the  soul,  here  and  now.  Prayer  is  then  simply  4  the  earnest,  hon- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  315 

est,  trusting  definition  of  the  sphere  of  one's  activity ; '  it  is  4  science 
becoming  motive,  or  mind  liberating  soul.'  And,  on  the  other  hand, 
4  ritual '  is  simply  '  body  expressing  soul,'  the  action  which  prayer  sets 
free. 

To  criticise  Dr.  Lloyd's  work  in  any  complete  way  would  require 
a  book  larger  than  the  volume  before  us.  I  shall  confine  myself  there- 
fore to  a  few  of  the  more  obvious  reflections  that  suggest  themselves. 
It  is  probably  safe  to  surmise  that  no  one  will  be  convinced  by  the 
book.  It  is  far  too  brief  to  prove  its  position,  and  far  too  long  for  a 
mere  statement  of  it.  There  are  numerous  repetitions — a  defect  which 
the  author  himself  recognizes.  Now,  very  frequently  these  repetitions 
concern  just  those  matters  about  which  we  should  like  to  have  more 
light,  but  the  repetition  does  not  give  the  added  light.  Startling  as- 
sertions are  frequently  made  as  matters  of  course,  a  fact  which  inti- 
mates that  Dr.  Lloyd  has  as  yet  let  the  world  only  into  a  little  corner 
of  his  thinking-shop.  One  cannot  but  feel  that  there  is  much  that 
is  fanciful  in  our  author's  reasoning,  as,  for  instance,  in  his  discussion 
of  money-lending  as  4  left-handed '  Christianity,  and  in  the  whole 
treatment  of  banking.  So  in  the  characterization  of  historical  events 
and  personages,  one  is  sure  that  the  facts  are  distorted,  or,  at  least,  but 
very  partially  presented,  in  order  to  fit  the  formula.  The  description 
of  Socrates,  for  example,  as  a  '  spendthrift,'  taking  end  for  means, 
and  standing  for  '  abstract  spirituality,'  is  Socrates  twisted  so  as  to 
form  the  proper  antithesis  to  his  contemporaries,  regarded,  also  by  a 
tour  deforce,  as  ;  misers  taking  means  for  end.'  Again,  when  we  are 
told :  c  in  the  nature  of  organisms,  as  he  who  runs  may  read,  are  the 
primal  teachings  of  Christ'  (p.  92),  we  are  hardly  satisfied  to  forego 
the  evidence.  To  try  to  show  that  history  had  to  be  as  it  has  been,  is 
a  dangerous  and  difficult,  if  not  impossible,  undertaking.  Dr.  Lloyd 
would  seem  not  to  have  a  proper  appreciation  of  the  magnitude  of  his 
task.  He  slips  over  and  around  obstacles  smoothly  enough,  but  for 
this  very  reason  leaves  the  impression  that  much  of  his  writing  is 
mere  word-play.  It  is  often  hard  to  see  what  he  is  thinking  behind 
his  phrases.  Words  are  not  used  with  that  consistency  which  logical 
procedure  demands.  We  find  ourselves  reading  of  Christ,  the  motive 
of  his  people,  and  anon,  without  warning,  we  are  dealing  with  the 
historic  Jesus  of  Nazareth.  There  is  a  similar  shuffling  in  the  case  of 
Socrates.  The  term  organism  is  used  with  great  vagueness.  The 
general  objection  to  this  whole  way  of  thinking  the  universe  under  the 
form  of  an  organism — the  objection,  namely,  that  the  individual  is  lost 
in  the  process,  that  his  significance,  his  freedom,  is  destroyed — is 


A   STUDY  OF  A    CHILD. 

lightly  passed  over  with  the  remark,  repeated  several  times,  with 
slight  variations,  that  when  we  say  that  history  '  required '  the  appear- 
ance of  a  given  man,  at  a  given  time,  we  mean  also  that  his  own  true 
selfhood  required  the  same  thing :  (p.  61)  that  '  internal  sanction,'  cor- 
responding to  l  external  stimulus,'  frees  us  from  determinism.  But 
this  '  true  selfhood'  appears,  after  all,  to  be  a  sort  of  spirit  of  hu- 
manity behind  the  scenes,  the  l  inner  motive '  of  the  life  of  the  people, 
and,  thus  considered,  the  doctrine  becomes  '  as  vague  as  all  unsweet.' 
One  finds,  however,  many  passages  in  the  book  which  dimly  suggest 
that  Dr.  Lloyd  has  a  message  of  which  he  has  not  yet  succeeded  in 
delivering  himself.  Citizenship  and  Salvation  is  a  program,  and  it  is 
to  be  hoped  that  Dr.  Lloyd  will  live  to  carry  it  out.  Only  we  cannot 
refrain  from  adding  the  further  wish  that  in  the  meantime  he  read 
more  French  and  less  German,  so  that  the  message  may  be  more  in- 
telligible when  it  comes.  What,  for  instance,  could  be  more  hope- 
lessly obscure  than  pages  72,  73  ? 

CHARLES  M.  BAKEWELL. 
BRYN  MAWR. 

A  Study  of  a  Child.     LOUISE  E.  HOG  AN.     New  York,  Harper  & 

Bros.     1898.     Pp.  x  -f-  220. 

This  is  so  distinctively  a  popular  book  that  one  hesitates  to  offer  a 
review  of  it  for  publication  in  a  psychological  journal.  But  a  justifi- 
cation for  so  doing  is  to  be  found  in  Chapter  L,  wherein  the  author  tells 
us  that  "  the  few  facts  that  were  noted  (during  the  first  year)  may  be 
of  greater  interest  possibly  to  psychologists  than  to  the  general  reader." 
So  she  presents  her  observations  to  psychology.  To  quote  from  these 
records  will  serve  to  illustrate  the  nature  of  them,  and  the  psychologist 
will  perceive  that  he  is  not  to  expect  to  find  trustworthy  observations, 
critically  considered.  "When  the  child  received  his  first  bath  he 
lifted  his  head  unaided  from  the  lap  in  which  he  was  lying,  thus  show- 
ing to  the  popular  mind  an  early  inclination  to  know  what  was  going 
on  about  him  *  *  *  and  to  the  psychologist  great  promise  of  brain 
powers"  (p.  15).  On  page  16  is  noted  his  objection  to  a  Raff  concerto 
for  the  violin  and  piano,  and  his  toleration  upon  the  same  occasion  of 
Handel's  Largo.  This  observation,  at  least  in  its  present  form,  is  not 
available  to  psychology  except  as  having  the  value  of  an  impression ; 
for  it  lacks  the  verification  which  it  should  have  received  from  subse- 
quent observations,  or  from  an  alternation  of  the  concerto  and  the 
largo  in  order  to  determine  whether  the  child's  feelings  changed  with 
the  change  in  the  music.  The  main  feature  of  the  book  is  a  series  of 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  317 

500  drawings  by  the  child,  executed  by  him  during  a  period  of  some 
six  years.  These  show  an  advance  in  the  acquirement  of  manual 
dexterity,  and  an  increasing  appreciation  of  detail  in  the  objects  repre- 
sented. The  subjects  chosen  by  the  child  for  the  exercise  of  his  skill 
are  also  noteworthy,  as  indicating  the  direction  of  his  interests.  But 
we  are  not  told  (except  in  the  case  of  the  locomotive)  whether  draw- 
ings were  often  made  for  him.  so  that  he  followed  or  was  helped  by 
a  copy ;  whether  he  drew  from  an  object,  from  the  memory  of  an  ob- 
ject, or  by  all  of  these  methods.  Many  of  the  drawings  are  obviously 
imaginative.  These  should  have  constituted  a  separate  series.  The 
want  of  system  in  the  arrangement  of  the  cuttings  and  drawings  is  to 
be  regretted,  and  is  a  hindrance  to  their  usefulness. 

The  language  record  also  is  fairly  full ;  yet  here  only  a  time  record 
is  given,  from  which  one  learns  that  the  child  was  able  to  say  certain 
things  by  a  certain  date.  It  is  a  pity  not  to  have  formulated  the  records 
for  correlation  with  other  observations  on  child  language. 

The  book  is  full  of  suggestions  as  to  methods  of  inculcating  de- 
sirable habits  and  various  virtues,  which  will  attract  both  kindergart- 
ners  and  parents,  and  it  leaves  on  one's  mind  the  pleasant  impression 
of  a  happy,  lovable  child. 

KATHLEEN  CARTER  MOORE. 

PHILADELPHIA. 


Die    praktische    Anivendung  der    Sprachphysiologie    beim    ersten 

Leseunterricht.     H.  GUTZMANN.     Berlin,  Reuther  u.  Reichard. 

1898. 

Every  medical  man  is  more  or  less  interested  in  the  physiology  of 
speech  in  proportion  as  he  is  called  upon  to  study  the  many  defects 
which  are  met  with  among  school-children,  and  the  conviction  is 
forced  upon  him  that  by  good  or  bad  methods  of  instruction  latent 
tendencies  to  such  defects  may  be  either  developed  or  eradicated. 
From  such  a  practical  acquaintance  with  the  results  of  imperfect  train- 
ing arose  Dr.  Gutzmann's  interest  in  the  theoretical  problems  discussed 
in  this  work. 

The  monograph  is  divided  into  four  parts :  first,  an  historical  re- 
view of  the  opinions  of  educational  writers  concerning  the  place  of  the 
physiology  of  speech  in  school  instruction ;  second,  the  psychological 
justification  for  the  study  of  speech  physiology,  and  its  practicability  as  a 
school  method;  third,  the  hygienic  value  of  a  physiological  method  in 
teaching  to  read ;  and  fourth,  the  practical  application  of  physiological 
principles  in  school  instruction. 


318  ANWENDUNG  DER   SPRACHPHYSIOLOGIE. 

The  earlier  treatment  of  the  problem  was  based  on  fanciful  anal- 
ogies between  the  form  of  the  printed  letter  and  the  adjustment  of  the 
organs  necessary  in  pronouncing  it,  as  when  Bonet  the  Spaniard  re- 
marks that  the  shape  of  the  letter  B,  with  its  two  semicircles  meeting 
the  perpendicular  line,  signifies  the  closing  of  the  lips  involved  in  ut- 
tering it,  and  that  the  letter  A  is  formed  like  a  trumpet  <|  to  indicate 
that  the  letter  must  be  pronounced  with  open  mouth  and  constricted 
throat,  which  latter,  however,  as  the  cross-bar  indicates,  must  not  be 
wholly  closed.  Passing  by  these,  we  find  that  a  long  series  of  those 
who  grasped  the  real  significance  of  the  speech-learning  process  have 
urged,  or  adopted,  the  physiological  method  of  instruction.  Graser, 
Fechner,  Bohme,  Krug,  Grassmann — all  these  made  earnest  efforts  to 
apply  the  principles  of  speech  physiology  in  their  instruction.  Krug, 
the  most  explicit  and  insistent,  demands  that  every  child  shall  be 
made  to  construct  each  vocal  element  with  a  clear  consciousness  of  the 
various  adjustments  of  the  organs  involved :  this  exercise  shall  precede 
the  actual  instruction  in  reading.  Krug's  principles  are  intricate,  his 
process,  at  least  at  first  sight,  artificial,  and  his  method  tiresome  and 
wasteful.  It  is  necessary  to  seek  more  simplified  and  practicable  ways 
of  applying  these  principles  in  school  instruction. 

The  psychological  justification  of  this  method  lies  in  the  nature  of 
the  processes  involved  in  learning  to  speak  or  to  read.  The  com- 
bined process  involves  the  activity  of  five  brain-centers  with  their 
respective  tracts:  (i)  The  perceptive  centre  and  auditory  nerve - 
tract;  (2)  the  motor  centre  and  nervous  tract  connecting  it  with  the 
mechanism  of  speech;  (3)  the  visual  perception-centre  of  the  move- 
ments of  speech  and  writing ;  (4)  the  kinaesthetic  perception-centre 
which  makes  aware  of  the  adjustments  of  the  organs  involved  in 
speaking  and  writing,  and  (5)  the  motor  centre  by  which  the  move- 
ments of  the  hand  in  writing  are  produced  and  directed. 

The  child  learns  by  imitation ;  in  speech  this  is  chiefly  through  the 
ear,  but  not  solely;  the  eye  also  participates.  The  child  imitates 
movements  of  the  lips  when  soundless ;  blind  children  come  to  speech 
later  than  the  normal ;  of  those  who  have  lost  their  hearing  some 
rapidly  recover  power  to  communicate  by  reading  the  lips.  In 
German  deaf-mute  schools  the  sole  method  of  teaching  vocal  language 
has  been  by  the  use  of  kinsesthetic  and  visual  sensations  in  acquiring 
direct  conscious  control  of  the  mechanism  of  speech.  In  blind  deaf- 
mutes  the  sense  of  touch  replaces  vision  in  connection  with  kinaes- 
thesia. 

The  objection  may  be  urged  that  such  a  method  is  not  practicable ; 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  319 

it  is  too  confusing  and  burdensome,  and  can  be  applied  only  in- 
dividually, not  to  classes.  In  reply,  the  success  of  deaf-mute  instruc- 
tion, and  the  relatively  rapid  progress  of  the  pupils,  demonstrate  its 
possibility.  By  this  method  idiots  have  been  taught  to  speak  when 
all  other  means  had  failed,  (v.  Piper,  Gutzmann,  etc.)  In  normal 
fully-endowed  children  the  progress  should  be  correspondingly  more 
rapid.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  it  has  been  successfully  used  with  young 
children  and  with  stutterers  to  the  number  of  nearly  400  by  the  elder 
Gutzmann.  The  objection  is  valid  only  against  particular  forms  of 
the  method  which  have  been  employed  in  the  past,  a  disability  which 
a  perfectly  possible  simplification  will  remove. 

The  hygienic  value  of  the  physiological  method  of  instruction  in 
reading  will  be  found  in  the  correction  of  a  long  list  of  defects  in 
speech  and  the  prevention  of  a  still  greater  number.  There  are  80,000 
stammering  school  children  in  Germany.  The  proportion  increases 
greatly  with  the  age  of  the  pupils,  the  number  in  the  highest  grades 
in  some  schools  reaching  three  times  that  in  the  lowest.  The  statistics 
from  half  a  dozen  cities  show  that  the  most  rapid  increase  takes  place 
between  the  ages  of  seven  and  eight  years,  that  is,  immediately  after 
the  first  instruction  in  reading.  Of  these  a  large  part  on  their  en- 
trance upon  school  life  were  not  developed  stutterers,  but  showed  only 
a  tendency  to  such  defect.  It  lies  in  the  power  of  the  teacher  to  cor- 
rect this  predisposition  by  training ;  else  the  habit, which  is  highly  infec- 
tious, will  be  fixed  through  imitation.  The  still  imperfect  control  of 
speech  when  the  child  begins  school  life,  combined  with  frequent  ten- 
dency to  stuttering  and  lack  of  self-confidence,  affords  at  once  the  con- 
dition for  the  establishment  of  all  sorts  of  defects.  The  root  of  all 
such  troubles  lies  in  the  imperfect  control  of  the  mechanism  of  speech, 
which  has  all  along  been  practically  met  by  directing  attention  to  the 
processes  involved  and  endeavoring  consciously  to  perform  the  correct 
movements.  Diesterweg  and  Gutzmann  especially  have  urged  the  use 
of  this  means  as  a  corrective,  advising  systematic  practice  in  breathing, 
vocalization  and  articulation. 

The  practical  application  of  these  principles  should  not  precede 
the  teaching  of  reading,  but  should  accompany  and  illustrate  it  from 
the  first  moment.  The  question  of  method  presents  three  problems : 
(i)  the  means  which  the  psychology  of  speech  reveals  for  awakening 
the  right  physical  images ;  (2)  the  way  in  which  the  individual  organs 
can  best  be  exercised;  (3)  the  arrangement  of  the  course  of  instruc- 
tion in  response  to  this  demand. 

The  means  are  hearing,  feeling,  seeing.     Clear  apprehension  of  the 


320  DIE  IDEENASSOZIATION  DES  KINDES. 

sound  to  be  produced  is  necessary,  since  by  it  the  correctness  or  incor- 
rectness of  the  adjustment  is  chiefly  to  be  judged.  The  child  should  be 
trained  to  observe,  by  direct  feeling,  how  the  mouth  and  throat  are 
adjusted  in  speaking,  for  by  means  of  these  kinaesthetic  images  the 
movement  is  afterward  produced.  He  should  also  know  the  form 
taken  by  the  vocal  organs  in  pronouncing  the  elements  of  speech, 
for  by  this  means  he  is  directly  assisted  in  the  production  of  the  spe- 
cific sounds  desired. 

The  author  does  not  propose  the  substitution  of  a  radically  new 
method  in  teaching,  but  only  the  introduction  of  a  rational  system  of 
training  in  vocalization  and  articulation,  in  connection  with  the  use  of 
illustrated  primers  and  photographs  of  the  positions  of  the  vocal 
organs  in  articulation.  A  plate  of  twelve  such  pictures  accompanies 
the  monograph. 

ROBERT  MACDOUGALL. 

HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 

Die  Ideenassoziation    des  Kindes.     PROFESSOR  ZIEHEN.     Berlin, 

Reuther  u.  Reichard.     1898. 

In  his  introduction  Professor  Ziehen  reviews  the  experimental 
work  done  concerning  the  association  of  ideas  in  children,  and  gives 
full  bibliographical  references  to  researches  upon  the  nature  of  as- 
sociation in  general.  The  work  reported  on  was  confined  to  children 
from  eight  to  fourteen  years  of  age,  and  considered  four  things :  the 
determination  of  the  child's  store  of  ideas ;  of  the  nature  of  associations 
resulting  from  a  given  initial  idea ;  of  the  rapidity  of  the  association 
process,  and  of  the  influence  of  special  conditions,  such  as  fatigue, 
upon  the  rapidity  of  association.  The  first  inquiry  was  a  preliminary 
one.  Of  the  three  principal  questions  of  the  investigation  only  that 
concerning  the  association  process  is  taken  up  in  the  present  mono- 
graph. The  initial  idea  was  suggested  by  an  object  seen,  heard,  or 
felt,  or  by  a  word.  The  words  were  arbitrarily  chosen  monosyl- 
lables, usually  concrete  ideas,  with  occasional  terms  of  relation 
(e.  g.  '  similarity')  of  processes  (4  storm')  and  proper  names. 

Concerning  the  form  of  association  the  question  of  chief  interest  is 
whether  the  process  of  association  in  the  child  shows  a  greater  or  less 
tendency  than  in  the  adult  to  special  fixed  association  groups. 

Our  earliest  associations  are,  without  exception,  spatially  and  tem- 
porally determined  individual  ideas.  From  these  are  derived  spatially 
and  temporally  indeterminate  object  ideas.  In  adults  the  word  (ex- 
cept in  the  case  of  proper  names)  awakens  throughout  universal 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  321 

ideas ;  to  give  individual  worth  it  is  necessary  to  add  a  definite  article 
or  pronoun.  The  author's  distinction  here  is  a  logical  one,  but  it  is 
doubtful  if  such  a  discrimination  between  adult  and  child  can  be 
drawn  psychologically.  The  image,  or  psychological  representative, 
must  be  without  exception  a  concrete  image,  definite  or  indefinite, 
derived  from  individual  past  experiences.  Accompanying  this 
psychological  element,  however,  is  the  awareness  that  the  image 
means  a  type  and  not  an  individual.  But  such  knowledge  of  his 
meaning  the  child  of  eight  already  possesses.  The  truer  distinction — 
and  perhaps  that  intended — is  that  in  the  adult  the  concrete  image  has 
less  localization ;  it  hangs  before  the  mind  as  an  isolated  thing,  but 
not,  therefore,  as  a  universal. 

Verbal  associations  were  rare  ;  only  in  one  case  were  they  frequent, 
where  they  formed  twenty-four  per  cent,  of  the  total.  Among  adults 
such  forms  are  much  richer  and  more  frequent.  Of  verbal  associa- 
tions the  most  usual  form  was  word-completing,  e.  g.,  £> ett-federn  : 
Post-Karte,  etc.  Rhyme  associations  were  rare,  Schlange  ;  Zange  ; 
Fisch ;  Tisch,  etc.,  but  individual  cases  were  found  with  almost  every 
child.  One  noticeable  type  smacks  strongly  of  the  school  and  its 
training,  e.  g.,  Bett  is  written  with  '/*/'  Macht  is  written  with  a 
capital. 

In  the  case  of  adults  not  only  is  the  representative  image  of  a  con- 
crete term  a  general  one,  but  almost  always  the  image  which  it  calls  up 
is  likewise  general.  It  is  astonishingly  different  with  the  child.  The 
author  says :  "I  was  prepared  for  a  relative  predominance  of  the  in- 
dividual association  form.  Of  the  degree  of  this  prevalence  I  had  not 
the  slightest  suspicion  *  *  *  *  Most  of  the  children  connected  with  al- 
most every  stimulus  word  an  individual  idea,  and  with  this  again  an 
individual  idea,  and  in  many  cases  both  were  spatially  determined." 
The  percentage  of  individual  associations  decreases  with  the  age  of  the 
child ;  in  the  third  class  it  is  seventy-two  per  cent. ;  in  the  first,  sixty- 
two  per  cent. ;  among  adults  the  author  found  it  to  be  on  the  average 
ten  per  cent.,  in  regard  to  analytic  and  synthetic  associations  the  ele- 
mentary idea  never  aroused  another  elementary  hetero-sensorial  idea 
(£.  g.,  sweet  white}.  This  is  natural ;  it  awakens  always  the  totalized 
object  association  (e.  g.,  sweet-sugar}  ;  this  point  suggests  such  phe 
nomena  as  colored  hearing,  of  which  the  author  makes  no  mention, 
and  the  question  whether  they  are  of  later  development  and  not  present 
in  the  imagery  of  children  of  eight  to  fourteen  years  of  age.  The  ele- 
mentary idea  arouses  a  composite  image  four  times  as  often  as  a  simple ; 
the  type  is  red-blood,  not  red-green.  This  also  is  natural ;  the  child 


322  PSYCHOLOGIE  INDIVIDUELLE. 

finds  red  combined  in  the  concrete  with  elements  of  the  other  senses 
constantly,  but  seldom  with  green.  The  composite  idea  arouses  most 
frequently  (59  %  of  all  cases)  as  its  associate  another  composite  which 
bears  no  relation  of  partiality  to  the  first  (e.  g.,  window-door}  ;  next 
to  this,  but  far  behind,  comes  its  association  with  a  greater  composite 
of  which  it  is  a  part  (e.  g.,  window-wall);  very  seldom  is  this  latter 
relation  reversed  (e.  g.,  window-window-sash) . 

The  visual  type  predominates  much  more  than  among  adults.  Af- 
fective partitive^ideasjare  very  rare  (e.g.,  gut — nicht  gut ;  thut  Weh  • 
etc.).  In  spite  of  the  variety  of  content  the  form  of  association  is  al- 
ways contiguity  in  the  wider  sense.  No  case  of  pure  (indisputable) 
association  through  resemblance  was  observed.  Associates  farfetched 
in  space  and  time  are  found  much  oftener  than  with  adults.  With 
adults  familiarity  is  predominant;  with  the  child  congruity  plays  a 
much  greater  r61e;  on  the  other  hand,  distinctness  and  constellation 
bear  a  much  less  important  part.  In  closing  the  author  recalls  again 
the  difficulty  in  tracing  all  the  linkages  of  association  upon  which  the 
very  form  depends,  since  the  child  himself  forgets,  and  the  conse- 
quent need  for  extended  and  patient  investigation  for  the  determina- 
tion of  these  problems. 

ROBERT  MACDOUGALL. 

HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 

Psychologie  collective  et  Psychologie  indimduelle.     RENE  WORMS. 

Lecture  delivered  before  the  Paris  Academy  of  Moral  and  Political 

Sciences,  November  12  and  19,   1898.    Pp.  35. 

These  are  by  no  means  the  first  helpful  words  which  psychologists 
have  received  from  this  eminent  French  sociologist,  but  they  contain 
the  most  pointed  bit  of  advice  which  he  has  addressed  to  them  directly. 

Starting  with  a  reference  to  the  rapid  growth  of  sociology  in  re- 
cent years,  he  passes  with  a  word  the  evident  dependence  of  sociology 
upon  psychology,  and  proposes  to  trace  the  influence  of  sociology  upon 
psychology,  in  the  formation  of  a  collective  psychology  and  in  modi- 
fying the  psychology  of  the  individual,  and  then  to  sketch  the  outline 
of  a  new  psychology  which  would  recognize  these  changes.  He  is 
not  here  concerned  with  the  metaphysical  reality  of  the  collective  mind, 
but  with  the  scientific  inquiry  into  the  causes  of  such  common  phe- 
nomena as  the  mind  of  a  nation,  a  family  or  a  crowd.  He  finds  two 
sets  of  influences  always  present,  a  common  environment  and  the  re- 
ciprocal influence  of  the  members  of  a  group  upon  one  another.  The 
soil,  climate,  and  productions  of  a  country,  for  instance,  arouse  numer- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  323 

ous  common  sentiments  in  the  minds  of  a  people,  while  the  social  rela- 
tions of  family,  friendship,  religion,  politics  and  education  have  an 
equally  large  share  in  the  formation  of  the  national  mind.  In  the  fam- 
ily the  same  influences  are  at  work,  together  with  a  new  element  still 
stronger,  that  of  heredity.  Men  engaged  in  the  same  industry  come 
to  have  mental  characteristics  which  are  distinguished  from  those  of 
the  national  type  in  the  same  twofold  way,  by  the  more  limited  and 
therefore  more  intense  effect  of  the  common  environment — city,  vil- 
lage, shop  and  fellow  workmen,  and  by  the  particular  stamp  of  that 
industry.  The  various  groups  thus  mentally  differentiated  within  the 
nation  may  be  divided  into  four  classes :  those  founded  on  blood-rela- 
tionship— families  and  races ;  second,  those  of  locality — cities,  villages 
and  provinces;  third,  those,  of  industry — farmers,  mechanics,  mer-> 
chants,  etc. ;  fourth,  those  based  on  intellectual  interests — all  sorts  of 
political,  religious,  literary  and  social  organizations.  A  reference  to 
various  French  writers  on  the  state,  family,  city,  provincial  life  and 
the  life  of  workingmen  shows  that  a  collective  psychology  is  already 
an  established  fact.  Few  of  these  writers  are  professional  psycholo- 
gists, and  much  remains  to  be  done,  but  the  way  has  been  mapped 
out.  Development  will  follow  naturally. 

In  showing  how  sociology  has  influenced  the  study  of  individual 
psychology  attention  is  confined  to  the  higher  mental  faculties  of  reason 
and  free  will.  Reason,  as  the  faculty  of  general  ideas,  is  of  practical 
value  in  the  social  life,  since  every  individual  is  making  constant  ap- 
peal to  laws  and  general  ideas,  but  it  is  also  social  in  its  origin. 
Man  gets  his  first  general  ideas  from  the  constant  recurrence  of  phe- 
nomena which  pass  before  his  eyes,  but  he  is  much  more  influenced 
by  the  character  and  action  of  the  men  around  him  than  by  the  cosmi- 
cal  or  biological  elements  of  his  environment.  Therefore,  the  first 
general  ideas  are  social.  The  preservation  and  development  of  these 
ideas  is  in  turn  possible  only  through  the  medium  of  language,  another 
social  function.  In  short,  human  reason  is  penetrated  with  social  ele- 
ments. 

Free  will  is  impossible  apart  from  reason.  Therefore,  free  will, 
in  its  nature,  shares  the  social  elements  of  reason,  while  the  field  of  its 
activity  is  the  social  world.  Its  highest  aim  is  the  moral  elevation  of 
humanity ;  its  standards  of  right  action  are  social  standards ;  its  rules  of 
life  those  which  can  be  adopted  by  all  right  wills.  Thus  the  factors 
in  the  creation  and  development  of  human  personality  are  almost 
wholly  social.  Heredity  may  furnish  the  first  elements  of  our  being, 
but  education  is  equally  important  in  the  formation  of  our  character 


324  PSYCHOLOGY  INDIVIDUELLE. 

and  minds,  and  in  adult  life  it  is  in  social  relations  with  our  fellows 
that  our  personality  is  developed — by  imitation,  opposition  and  adapta- 
tion. The  larger  part  of  individual  mentality  is  a  product  of  our  col- 
lective existence. 

But  although  the  social  mind  has  become  an  object  of  scientific 
study,  and  the  individual  mind  is  shown  to  be  largely  a  product  of  the 
social  life,  there  are  objections  to  setting  up  a  collective  psychology  as 
opposed  to  individual  psychology.  Collective  psychology  is,  in  the 
last  analysis,  psychology  of  individuals,  while  the  mental  life  of  any 
individual  can  be  understood  only  in  the  light  of  the  social  life.  All 
psychology  is  at  the  same  time  collective  and  individual.  Secondly, 
our  ordinary  psychology,  which  is  generally  called  individual,  is  any- 
thing but  individual.  It  deals  with  general  principles  which  are  true 
for  all  men,  and  is  even  more  comprehensive  than  collective  psychology. 

A  better  division  of  psychology  would  study  separately  the  three 
sets  of  elements  which  we  have  found  entering  into  each  personality : 
those  common  to  the  whole  race ;  those  common  to  the  group  of  which 
he  is  a  member,  and  those  which  make  up  his  individual  personality. 
First,  we  would  have  a  general  psychology  of  the  mental  faculties 
common  to  all  human  beings ;  second,  a  special  psychology,  or  what  has 
been  called  collective  psychology.  The  word  ;  special '  brings  out 
more  clearly  the  essential  nature  of  these  researches,  that  of  distin- 
guishing between  different  groups  of  men  which  from  the  social  point 
of  view  constitute  different  species ;  third,  an  individual  psychology 
which  would  study  the  particular  mental  life  of  concrete  individuals, 
the  normal  development  and  crises  of  intellect  and  heart,  their  natural 
tendencies,  their  influence  on  associates,  and  the  net  result  of  their 
mental  existence. 

Should  this  division  be  adopted,  the  younger  science  of  sociology 
would  render  a  distinct  service  to  psychology,  but  at  the  same  time  would 
be  doing  itself  a  good  turn.  The  results  of  psychology  thus  special- 
ized would  be  far  more  valuable  than  the  universal  and  abstract  princi- 
ples of  the  present  psychology.  The  second  of  the  proposed  groups 
would  be  of  especial  value  to  the  sociologist.  In  the  mind  of  the  na- 
tion he  would  find  the  general  causes  of  its  economical,  moral,  and 
political  organization.  In  the  mental  characteristics  of  its  families, 
cities,  industries,  and  social  groups  he  would  often  find  the  explana- 
tion of  the  details  of  this  organization,  and  also  of  the  strifes  and  in- 
ternal difficulties  which  the  national  life  has  to  surmount.  At  the  same 
time  the  first  group  would  give  him  the  general  mental  characteristics 
of  mankind,  and  thus  help  explain  the  striking  similarities  in  the  de- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  325 

velopment  of  different  nations,  while  the  third  group  would  throw  light 
on  the  question  how  the  intellect  or  will  of  a  single  man  sometimes 
transforms  an  industry,  a  whole  region,  or  perhaps  a  nation. 

Our  first  impression  is  that,  so  far  as  the  making  of  books  is 
concerned,  the  second  of  these  fields  belongs  to  the  sociologist,  while 
the  third  is  the  peculiar  province  of  the  man  of  letters.  Our  second 
thought  is  that  the  radical  reforms  suggested  in  psychology  have  al- 
ready taken  place.  Present  psychology  is  not  confined  to  abstract  or 
general  principles.  It  has  had  no  difficulty  in  absorbing  sociological 
doctrines,  if  it  has  not  succeeded  in  absorbing  the  sociologists  them- 
selves, and  it  has  also  picked  up  a  few  facts  from  physiology,  biology, 
anthropology,  history,  and  other  sciences.  Nine-tenths  of  all  the 
large  and  increasing  literature  of  psychology  belongs  to  the  second  or 
third  of  these  groups — practically  all  of  the  so-called  new  psychology 
with  its  experimental  work,  child  study,  educational  investigations, 
animal  psychology,  and  abnormal  psychology,  with  its  suggestive  re- 
searches in  hypnotism,  insanity,  and  the  subconscious  realm.  A  good 
beginning  has  also  been  made,  especially  by  French  psychologists,  in 
the  study  of  individuals ;  for  instance,  noted  writers  and  men  of  skill. 
In  fact,  it  is  impossible  to  carry  on  psychological  investigation  and  add 
to  the  sum  of  the  truths  contained  in  the  first  group  except  through  the 
study  of  the  concrete  individual.  In  this  particular  psychology  is  not 
different  from  geology,  physics,  chemistry,  or  any  of  the  other  sciences. 

But  it  is  feared  that  there  are  many  teachers  of  psychology  in 
America,  as  well  as  in  France,  who  imagine  that  when  it  comes  to 
the  classroom  psychology  is  radically  different  from  the  other  sciences, 
and  that  here  general  truths  may  be  made  interesting  and  profitable 
quite  apart  from  the  concrete  facts.  If  a  fuller  recognition  of  this 
threefold  division  shall  avail  to  inspire  teachers  with  the  newer  spirit 
of  their  science,  and  bring  the  student  into  closer  contact  with  con- 
crete mental  facts,  making  them  all  sociologists  and  giving  them  all 
the  literary  insight  into  human  nature,  and  awakening  them  to  the  prac- 
tical possibilities  of  psychology  in  the  professions  and  in  the  daily 
life  of  every  individual,  psychologists  will,  indeed,  be  grateful  to  the 
sociologist. 

But  it  is  by  no  means  clear  that  anything  would  be  gained  by  at- 
tempting to  introduce  this  threefold  division  into  the  text-books  used 
in  the  ordinary  courses  of  psychology.  Where  only  one  course  is 
given,  at  any  rate,  it  is  better  to  do  justice  to  the  three  elements  simul- 
taneously. There  is  more  crying  need  for  improvement  in  methods 
of  teaching  than  for  wholesale  changes  in  text-books. 

CHARLES  B.  BLISS. 


326  EFFECTIVE  ETHICAL  INSTRUCTION. 

O  ivahaniach  w  natezeniu  minimalnych  optycznych  i  akustycznych 
ivrazen  (zur  Erkldrung  der  Intensitatsschivankungen  eben 
merklicher  optischer  und  akustischer  Eindriicke).  W.  HEIN- 
RICH.  Reprint  from  the  Bulletin  of  the  Academy  of  Sciences  in 
Krakau.  November,  1898.  Pp.  18. 

This  is  an  abstract  of  a  paper  which  reviewed  the  whole  discussion 
of  the  fluctuation  of  minimal  visual  and  auditory  sensations  and  pre- 
sented the  results  of  the  author's  investigations,  some  of  which  at 
least  were  previously  described  in  the  Zeitschrift  fur  Psych,  und  Phys. 
der  Sinnesorgane,  Vol.  IX.  and  XI.  According  to  Heinrich  the  fluc- 
tuations with  visual  stimuli  are  definitely  proved  to  be  due  to  the 
constant  fluctuations  taking  place  in  the  curvature  of  the  lens,  while 
there  is  every  reason  to  believe  that  the  fluctuations  of  auditory  sensa- 
tions are  caused  by  the  effect  of  breathing  upon  the  tension  of  the  ear 
drum.  Experiments  with  a  carefully  trained  observer  who  had  lost 
both  ear  drums  failed  to  reveal  any  fluctuation.  Microscopical  exam- 
ination showed  that  the  ear  drum  does  move  outward  with  every 
inspiration  and  inward  with  every  expiration.  A  graphic  record  of 
the  breathing  and  the  auditory  fluctuations  showed  that  with  deep 
breathing  the  number  of  fluctuations  corresponds  with  the  rate  of 
breathing.  With  normal  breathing,  out  of  fifteen  respiration  periods 
ten  corresponded  to  fluctuations  in  sensation.  The  author  thinks  that 
a  more  exact  knowledge  of  the  movements  of  the  ear  drum  will 
furnish  a  complete  explanation  of  the  phenemenon. 

One  of  the  most  striking  announcements  is  that  no  fluctuation 
could  be  detected  when  the  faint  sound  was  a  steady  tone  instead  of  a 
watch  tick.  These  experiments  were  made  upon  only  one  person, 
and  it  is  hard  to  believe  that  this  will  be  found  true  for  all  persons 
under  all  conditions. 

CHARLES  B.  BLISS. 
LEONARD'S  BRIDGE,  CONN. 

Society's  Need  of  Effective  Ethical  Instruction   in    Church  and 

School,   and  the   Suggestion  of  an  Available  Method.     E.  M. 

FAIRCHILD.      The   American  Journal    of    Sociology,    January, 

1899.     PP-  433-447- 

The  writer  describes  his  method  for  the  visual  instruction  of  ethics 
in  the  public  schools.  By  means  of  the  camera  and  lantern  slides, 
scenes  illustrating  the  various  practical  ethical  problems  of  child  life, 
quarrels  and  fights,  work  and  play,  the  sneak,  the  thief,  the  bully,  the 
cry-baby,  the  general  good-for-nothing,  are  shown  to  the  children, 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  327 

while  the  teacher,  in  a  carefully  prepared  lecture,  describes  the  proper 
adult  feeling  called  forth  by  the  successive  pictures. 

CHARLES  B.  BLISS. 

The  Daivn  of  Reason  or  Mental  Traits  in  the  Lower  Animals. 
JAMES  WEIR,  JR.     New  York,  The  Macmillan  Company.     Pp. 

234- 

The  author  begins  with  the  following  definition,  "Mind  is  a  re- 
sultant of  nerve,  in  the  beginning  of  life,  neuro-plasmic  action, 
through  which  and  by  which  animal  life  in  all  its  phases  is  consciously 
and  unconsciously,  directly  and  indirectly,  maintained,  sustained, 
governed  and  directed."  He  holds  that  conscious  mind  originated  in 
sensual  perception  thousands  of  years  after  unconscious  mind.  The 
book  treats  of  the  following  topics :  Sense  in  the  Lower  Animals, 
Conscious  Determination,  Memory,  Emotions,  ./Estheticism,  Parental 
Affection,  Reason,  Auxiliary  Senses,  and  Letisimulation,  and  the 
whole  is  followed  by  general  conclusions,  a  bibliography  and  an  in- 
dex. No  writings  recognizing  the  Weismann  theories  seem  to  have 
been  consulted,  for  few,  if  any,  appear  in  his  bibliography,  and  he 
writes  as  if  the  inheritance  of  acquired  characteristics  had  never  been 
questioned. 

The  author  has  spent  many  years  in  observing  and  experimenting 
with  animals,  and  reports  some  very  interesting  and  valuable  facts,  but 
his  long  association  with  animals  and  habits  of  reading  his  own  ideas 
and  feelings  into  their  actions  make  him  partisan  and  uncritical.  He 
has  discovered  that  when  dogs  appear  to  be  baying  the  moon  they 
are  listening  to  the  echo  of  their  own  barking,  and  says  that  the 
4  dog's  voice  is  exceedingly  pleasing  to  himself,'  and  that  this  indicates 
a  4  high  degree  of  esthetic  feeling  in  the  dog,'  when  the  more  natural 
explanation  would  be  that  he  supposes  that  he  is  answering  another 
dog.  He  thinks  that  animals  can  count,  and  even  holds  that  a  blind 
dog  who  recognized  the  loss  when  one  of  her  six  puppies  was  taken 
away  soon  after  birth  must  have  had  an  abstract  idea  of  the  number 
six.  The  most  surprising  example  of  uncritical  judgment,  especially 
for  a  medical  man,  occurs  when  he  says  of  the  mason  wasps  that 
u  they  possess  a  mental  faculty  which  far  transcends  any  like  act  of 
human  intelligence ;  they  are  able  to  tell  which  of  the  eggs  will  pro- 
duce males  and  which  females.  Not  only  are  they  able  to  do  this ; 
but  seemingly  fully  aware  of  the  fact  that  it  takes  a  longer  time  for 
the  female  larvae  to  perfect  than  it  does  the  male  larvae,  they  provide 
for  this  emergency  by  depositing  in  the  cells  containing  female  eggs  a 


328  THE  DAWN  OF  REASON. 

larger  amount  of  food."  It  seems  never  to  have  occurred  to  him  that 
nutriment  may  determine  sex.  He  cites  the  recognition  of  one  ant  by 
others  of  its  nest  as  an  example  of  memory,  although  Lubbock  has 
proved  that  this  takes  place  when  the  ant  has  not  been  hatched  in  the 
same  nest,  but  has  been  hatched  elsewhere.  In  general,  he  thinks  of 
but  one  explanation  of  a  fact,  or  else  accepts  the  one  most  favorable 
to  the  intelligence  of  his  animal  friends ;  hence  his  conclusions  in  re- 
gard to  the  higher  mental  activities  of  animals  will  have  little  weight 
in  the  present  critical  study  of  animal  intelligence,  though  some  of  his 
facts  are  valuable. 

His  most  important  contribution  would  seem  to  be  the  work  he 
has  done  in  studying  the  sense  organs  and  discriminative  power  of  the 
lower  animals.  If  he  can  prove  to  the  satisfaction  of  other  psycholo- 
gists what  he  claims  to  have  demonstrated  he  will  be  entitled  to  a  high 
place  as  an  investigator  in  this  field.  In  most  cases  he  gives  few  de- 
tails in  regard  to  his  experiments,  so  that  it  is  impossible  to  judge  as 
to  the  care  with  which  they  were  performed. 

He  holds  that  all  animals  can  tell  the  difference  between  light  and 
dark,  even  without  an  eye  or  optic  nerve,  as  is  shown  by  such  instances 
as  the  blind  fish  from  Mammoth  Cave  always  seeking  the  darkest  place 
in  the  aquaria.  He  holds  that  such  low  animals  as  jellyfish  will 
follow  a  light,  and  that  their  so-called  '  marginal  bodies '  are  eyes,  in- 
stead of  ears,  as  others  have  claimed.  He  claims  to  have  discovered 
rudimentary  eyes  in  the  star  fish,  oysters  and  worms,  and  holds  that  a 
snail  has  a  cornea,  a  lens  and  retina,  and  can  detect  a  white  moving 
object  like  a  ball  of  cotton,  with  which  he  experimented,  at  a  distance 
of  two  feet  and  a  black  one  at  from  twelve  to  fourteen  inches,  and 
that  a  crayfish  can  descry  a  man  at  the  distance  of  twenty  or  twenty- 
five  feet. 

As  to  hearing  he  says  :  "  It  is  highly  probable  that  the  majority  of 
lower  animals,  especially  those  which  are  sound  producers,  can  hear 
just  as  we  hear,"  and  that  others  can  hear  ^ '''by  feeling  the  sound 
waves."  He  claims  to  have  demonstrated  the  organs  of  hearing  in  a 
number  of  insects,  and  that  only  in  the  Lepidoptera  and  certain  Hem- 
iptera  are  they  in  the  antennae,  as  has  been  claimed  by  many  ento- 
mologists. 

He  claims  that  animals  have  at  least  two  auxiliary  senses,  u  tinctu- 
mutation,  the  color-changing  sense,  and  the  sense  of  direction,  or,  as 
it  is  erroneously  termed,  the  '  homing  instinct.'  Neither  of  these  facul- 
ties is  instinctive,  but  they  are,  on  the  contrary,  true  senses,  just  as 
hearing  or  taste  or  smell,"  and  he  thinks  he  has  demonstrated  the  gan- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  329 

glion  centers  concerned  in  these  senses.  If  Dr.  Weir  desires  his  claims 
in  regard  to  the  senses  to  be  accepted  by  scientists  he  should  publish 
further  details,  for  naturally  no  careful  scientist  will  accept  such  im- 
portant conclusions  till  details  have  been  given  and  the  results  verified 
by  the  experiments  and  observations  of  others.  The  present  book  is 
popular  rather  than  scientific,  as,  indeed,  the  author  intended  it 
should  be. 

E.  A.  KlRKPATRICK. 
FlTCHBURG,  MASS. 


Vergleichende  Untersuchungen  der  Sehsckarfe  des  hell-  und  des 
dunkeladaptirten  Augis.  S.  BLOOM,  und  S.  GARTEN.  Pfliiger's 
Archiv,  LXXIL,  372-408.  1898. 

This  paper  contains  errors  of  carelessness  in  the  parts  that  are  open 
to  the  eye  of  the  reader,  and  hence  it  fails  to  inspire  confidence  that 
the  thousand  and  one  little  details  that  require  constant  attention  in  the 
carrying  out  of  any  investigation  have  not  been  neglected.  The  re- 
viewer does  not,  of  course,  usually  take  the  time  to  look  for  such  errors, 
but  in  this  case  he  is  much  struck  to  find,  from  the  diagram  on  p.  404, 
that  the  visual  acuity  of  an  observer  is,  under  certain  circumstances, 
yl^  at  a  distance  of  9°  from  the  fovea,  and  has  risen  to  yg-^  at  a  dis- 
tance of  8°  from  the  fovea,  and  also  that  upon  another  occasion,  the 
change  from  yj^  to  yf ^  of  visual  acuity  takes  place  between  the  dis- 
tances 12°  and  10°  from  the  fovea.  Upon  referring  to  the  table  which 
the  diagram  illustrates,  it  appears  that  this  is  purely  an  error  in  the  draw- 
ing, evidently  caused  by  substituting  at  one  point  millimeters  instead 
of  the  degrees  into  which  they  are  being  converted.  Any  one  is  liable 
to  make  a  momentary  mistake  now  and  then,  but  it  is  difficult  to  un- 
derstand how  so  palpable  an  absurdity  in  a  drawing  can  have  with- 
stood the  inspection  of  the  two  authors  of  the  paper  (and  also,  no  doubt, 
of  the  head  of  the  Physiological  Institute  of  the  University  of  Leipzig) . 
One  is  not  surprised  after  this  to  find  that  there  are  errors  in  the  mak- 
ing up  of  simple  averages.  And  in  glancing  at  the  other  pages  of 
diagrams,  one  notices  that,  on  p.  389,  when  the  visual  acuity  should 
be  twice  as  good  for  the  bright  adapted  eye  as  for  the  other,  it  is  repre- 
sented as  being  three  times  as  good ;  this  causes  such  a  discrepancy  in 
the  course  of  the  two  curves  as  occurs  nowhere  else,  and  hence  it  is 
here  also  very  singular  that  the  authors  did  not  look  back  at  their  tables 
to  see  if  it  was  justified.  On  p.  398  we  are  asked  to  believe  that  an 
observer  is  able  to  distinguish  two  dots  brought  gradually  in  from  the 
periphery  at  exactly  the  same  distance  whether  the  dots  are  five  or 


33°  VERGLEICHENDE   UNTERSUCHUNGEN. 

eight  millimeters  apart — that  is,  that  his  visual  acuity  at  21°  20'  from 
the  fovea  is,  in  a  certain  measure,  both  100  and  63,  and  that  neverthe- 
less a  superiority  of  a  degree  or  two  in  the  distance  at  which  definition 
takes  place  on  the  part  of  the  darkness-adapted  eye  (that  is,  transfer- 
ring to  the  above  measure  a  superiority  of  12)  is  sufficient  to  found 
theories  upon !  Again,  we  find  from  the  table  on  page  388  that  at  6° 
from  the  fovea  and  again  at  13°  30'  the  visual  acuity  of  the  darkness- 
eye  remains  exactly  the  same  up  to  the  one-thousandth  of  the  unit — » 
here  the  ordinary  unit — while  the  objective  illumination  is  increased 
to  eleven  times,  to  fifty-seven  times  and  to  seventy-nine  times  that 
which  was  employed  at  first.  (At  3°  and  at  12°,  on  the  other  hand, 
there  is  shown  a  gradual  improvement.)  This,  indeed,  would  be  an 
addition  to  our  knowledge  of  very  remarkable  interest  if  it  were  a 
result  to  be  depended  upon. 

A  paper  so  riddled  with  evidences  of  utter  ignorance  on  the  part 
of  its  authors  of  the  precautions  to  be  taken  in  observations  on  the 
powers  of  the  human  eye  in  the  periphery  (and  of  the  control  to  be 
exercised  by  common  sense)  has  probably  never  before  found  its  way 
into  print.  But  in  spite  of  these  grounds  for  suspicion  one  finds  one- 
self capable  of  a  fresh  feeling  of  surprise  on  seeing  that  the  summing 
up  of  the  results  of  the  investigation  is  quite  in  disaccord  with  the 
body  of  the  paper.  We  are  told  in  the  summary  that  "  as  appears 
from  all  our  experiments  on  central  and  peripheral  visual  acuity,  *  *  * 
in  spite  of  the  objective  illumination  being  extremely  faint,  and  alike 
for  both  eyes  (the  bright  and  the  dark-adapted),  the  dark  eye,  though 
it  sees  things  much  brighter,  sees  them  much  less  sharply."  But  as 
regards  central  vision,  this  was  not  the  case  at  all  for  a  very  faint  il- 
lumination, as  the  tables  show,  and  as  the  authors  themselves  plainly 
state  a  page  farther  on.  Thus  it  appears  from  the  table  on  p.  388 
that  it  was  only  when  the  lowest  illumination  tried  had  been  increased 
1,170  times  that  the  bright-adapted  eye  saw  better  than  the  dark- 
adapted  eye  in  the  center ;  and  the  authors  say  on  another  page  of 
this  same  summing  up:  u  only  a  much  more  considerable  increase  of 
the  illumination  brought  about  for  the  center  of  the  retina  as  well  a 
superiority  in  the  capacity  of  the  bright-adapted  eye." 

If  we  overlook  these  numerous  marks  of  inadvertence  on  the  part 
of  the  authors  and  treat  their  results,  for  the  moment,  as  deserving 
of  acceptance,  they  would  appear  to  have  made  out  that,  starting 
with  an  illumination  just  invisible  to  the  dark-adapted  eye  at  the  center  : 
(i)  the  dark-adapted  eye  remains  the  superior  up  to  eighty  times  that 
illumination  as  far  as  three  degrees  from  the  fovea,  but  either  farther 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  331 

out,  or  for  brighter  lights,  the  bright-adapted  eye  renders  the  better 
service;  (2)  this  superiority  of  the  bright-adapted  eye  becomes  so 
small  at  a  distance  of  40°  as  to  fall  within  the  probable  error  of  the 
observations,  that  is  to  say,  to  disappear  entirely  (a  fact  which  is  not 
drawn  attention  to  by  the  authors)  ;  (3)  nothing  is  gained  for  the 
dark-adapted  eye  by  reducing  the  illumination  for  it  until  objects  look 
no  brighter  than  for  the  other  eye.  (It  does  not  appear  why  a  long 
investigation  of  this  point  was  thought  necessary,  in  view  of  the  fact 
that  it  had  already  been  shown  that  a  diminution  of  intensity  had  no 
favorable  effect  upon  vision  for  an  eye  in  this  state.  A  condition  X 
having  been  shown  to  be  superior  to  a  condition  Y,  it  would  not  seem, 
as  a  matter  of  logic,  to  be  necessary  to  go  through  an  investigation  to 
show  that  it  is  also  better  than  Yx,  when  it  is  known  that  Yx  is  never 
better  and  is  nearly  always  worse  than  Y.) 

The  authors  give  no  discussion  of  the  theoretical  bearing  of  their 
results,  except  to  point  out  that,  since  there  is  no  illumination  at  which 
the  dark-adapted  eye  sees  as  well  as  the  bright-adapted  eye  sees  at  its 
optimum  illumination,  the  state  of  dark  adaptation  cannot  be  simply  a 
state  of  non-fatigue.     If  our  knowledge  of  the  retina  were  still   in 
the  condition  which  it  was  in  before  we  had  gained  any  information 
about  the  growth  of  the  visual  purple  or  the  descent  of  the  pigment 
granules,  this  would  be  an  interesting   contribution.      As   it  is,  the 
result  is  simply  what  we  had   every  reason  to  expect.       The  with- 
drawal of  the  pigment  granules  has  for  its  evident  effect  the  reinforce- 
ment of  the  faint  light  which  enters  the  retina  by  reflection  and  re- 
fraction from  one  visual  element  to  another ;  it  would  be  very  strange 
if  the  space-giving  elements  of  the  retina,  whichever  they  may  be, 
should  not  perform  much  better  service  when  they  are  isolated  in  their 
beds  of  black  than  when  they  are  subject  to  an  influx  of  light  on  every 
side.     Many  of  the  recent  writers  on  these  subjects  speak  as  if  the 
night-adaptation  of  the  retina  were  an  affair  of  the  visual  purple  only, 
and  apparently  forget  the  important  change  which  takes  place  (and 
which  cannot  be  without  effect)  in  the  position  of  the  black  pigment 
of  the  epithelium,  a  change  which  is  entirely  adapted  to  explaining 
the  diminished  visual  acuity  for  a  given  subjective  brightness  of  the 
night-adapted   eye.      This  phenomenon   does   not  apparently  throw 
any  light  on  the  burning  question  whether  the  rods  are  or  are  not 
chiefly  instrumental  in  the  renewed  vision  that  comes  to  us  by  night. 
It  is  only  when  the  cones  are  known  to  be  hors  de  combat  by  means 
of  the  night-blindness  of  the  fovea,  that  we  can  be  sure  that  we  are 
dealing  with  rods  only;  the  experiment  made  at  this  illumination  goes 


332  DENDRO-PS  YCHOSES. 

to  show  that  what  the  rods  gain  in  sense  of  brightness  by  the  increase 
of  the  visual  purple  they  more  than  lose  in  definition  (/.  <?.,  in  space 
sense)  by  the  loss  of  their  separating  pigment  granules,  but  that  (even 
when  the  increased  sense  for  brightness  is  wholly  counteracted  by  caus- 
ing the  night-adapted  eye  to  look  through  gray  glass)  this  superiority 
practically  ceases  at  a  distance  of  40°  from  the  fovea.  It  would  be  in- 
teresting to  know  if  there  is  here  also  a  diminution  in  the  extent  of  re- 
treat of  the  pigment  granules. 

There  is  every  reason  to  expect  that  the  cones  as  well  as  the  rods 
should  show  subjectively  some  effect  of  night  adaptation,  for  their 
change  of  size  is  a  very  marked  phenomenon.  This  may  easily  ac- 
count for  the  fact  that  there  is  some  slight  adaptation,  if  not  at  the 
center,  still  within  the  rodless  region.  We  know  now  that  the  feeling 
of  pressure  is  dependent  upon  a  deformation  of  the  skin  and  probably 
a  change  of  concentration  of  fluids  in  which  nerve-ends  are  immersed. 
Such  a  change  of  conditions  might  also  easily  follow  upon  the  shrink- 
ing of  the  visual  elements  of  the  retina. 

C.  LADD  FRANKLIN. 

BALTIMORE. 

A  Study  of  the  Sense  Epithets  of  Shelley  and  Keats.  MARY  GRACE 
CALDWELL.  Wellesley  College  Psychological  Studies.  Poet-Lore, 
Vol.  X.,  No.  4,  1898.  Pp.  573-579- 

This  study  gives  a  careful  tabulation  of  all  the  sense  epithets  used 
by  the  two  writers.  The  first  table  compares  the  frequency  of  adjec- 
tives of  the  different  senses — sight,  sound,  touch,  taste  and  smell.  The 
second  shows  the  number  of  adjectives  used  figuratively  compared 
with  the  number  used  literally.  The  third  gives  the  number  of  adjec- 
tives of  color,  lustre  and  form,  while  a  fourth  compares  the  frequency 
of  the  nine  colors  most  used.  Sight  stands  first  in  frequency,  sound 
second,  while  touch,  taste  and  smell  are  less  adapted  to  poetic  use. 
Shelley  writes  less  of  the  external  and  uses  fewer  sense  epithets  than 
Keats.  A  larger  proportion  of  those  that  he  does  use  are  figurative. 

CHARLES  B.  BLISS. 

Dendro- Psychoses.  J.  O.  QUANTZ  .  American  Journal  of  Psy- 
chology, Vol.  IX.,  No.  4,  pp.  443-306. 

Even  a  psychologist  has  to  think,  for  a  moment,  what  Tree-States- 
of-Mind  may  be.  Dr.  Quantz  has  in  this  article  given  in  a  valuable 
collation  of  facts  an  interesting  view  of  the  vegetable  kingdom  as  it 
has  affected  the  body  and  mind  of  man  in  all  their  manifestations — 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  333 

emotions,  customs,  religion,  medicine  and  poetry.  In  the  first  section 
he  sums  up  the  biological  and  anatomical  evidence  for  the  descent  of 
man  from  some  race  of  tree-climbers,  and  in  the  next — 4  Psychic 
Reverberations ' — he  outlines  certain  psychoses  which,  existing  to-day, 
can  be,  he  thinks,  accounted  for  only  by  the  supposition  that  .we  spent 
our  lives  in  trees  in  some  previous  pre-simian  existence.  Such  states 
of  mind  are,  among  others,  fears  of  serpents,  winds,  thunder-storms,  and 
the  fear  of  falling.  '  Tree  Worship,'  '  The  Life  Tree,'  l  The  World 
Tree,'  '  The  Paradise  Tree,'  are  followed  by  the  tree  *  in  Medicine,' 
*  in  Child  Life'  and  'in  Poetry,' the  last  being  the  least  successful, 
as  for  adequate  treatment  it  would  require  a  volume  by  itself.  The 
prominence  of  the  tree  in  all  these  relations  seems,  however,  hardly 
to  be  proved,  even  by  the  very  wide  range  of  folk-lore  covered  by 
the  author ;  and  the  article  at  times  falls  very  near  being  a  mere  cata- 
logue of  the  uses  of  the  word  4  tree '  and  its  synonyms,  wherever  they 
occur.  It  seems  credible  that  vegetable  life,  being  next  in  impor- 
tance to  animal  life,  should  receive  a  secondary  amount  of  human  at- 
tention ;  but  it  seems,  likewise,  somewhat  in  the  air  to  use  these  facts 
as  an  argument  for  the  spiritual  descent  of  the  human  soul  from  the 
sensations  and  reactions  of  tree-climbers.  'T  were  to  consider  too 
curiously  to  consider  so.  It  is  hard  to  tell  upon  what  subject  such  an 
article  might  not  be  written,  where  analogy  runs  rampant  and  the 
result  is  an  intoxicating  series  of  similitudes,  which,  if  regarded  with 
any  degree  of  credulousness,  dazzle  one  with  their  bizarre  aspect. 
From  the  fact  that  when  two  branches  of  a  tree  grow  together  again, 
or  the  twig  of  a  bramble  enters  the  ground  again  making  a  hole,  they 
have  a  remedial  power,  why  should  we  not  better  infer  a  belief 
in  holes  or  circles  than  in  wood  ?  These  examples  seem  just  as  likely 
to  be  instances  of  the  importance  of  the  circle  in  magic  or  of  sugges- 
tion as  a  therapeutic  agent.  As  raw  material  for  poetry  Dr.  Quantz's 
article  is  most  interesting.  WILFRID  LAY. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

Hydro- Psychoses.    FREDERICK  E.  BOLTON.    Am.  Jour.  Psy.,  Janu- 
ary, 1899.    Vol.  X.,  No.  2,  pp.  169-227. 

Minor  Studies  from  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  Clark  Univer- 
sity, XII.,  XIII.  and  XIV.     Ibid.,  pp.  280-295. 
In  the  first-named  paper  the  author  investigates  the  influence  that 

water  has  exerted  in   shaping  and  moulding  man's  psychic  organism. 

Evidences  of   man's  pelagic  ancestry  are  found  in  the  fact  that  his 

embryo  goes  through  all  the  stages  of  evolution.     Thus  he  is,  at  one 


334  HYDRO-PS  YCHOSES. 

time  before  his  birth,  practically  indistinguishable  from  a  fish.  The 
brain  and  nervous  system,  the  organs  of  circulation  and  respiration 
show  structural  rudimentary  organs;  and  vestigial  structures  in  man 
are  cited  to  show  the  subaqueous  existence  of  our  infinitely  distant  an- 
cestors. Of  course,  a  great  argument  is  the  fact  that  there  are  amphib- 
ious animals,  and  that,  when  young,  they  are  all  aquatic ;  and  another 
is  in  the  'animal  retrogressions  to  aquatic  life,'  seen  in  the  whale,  seal, 
beaver,  walrus  and  sea  lion.  '  Psychic  reverberations  '  are  felt  by  us 
even  to-day  in  the  hypnagogic  phenomena  of  swimming,  floating  and 
jumping,  and  in  the  preference  for  suicide  by  drowning.  In  '  the 
primitive  conceptions  of  life  '  water  is  seen  to  be  important,  and  the 
theories  of  the  Ionic  philosophers  are  dragged  in,  in  the  section  '  Wa- 
ter in  Philosophical  Speculation,'  '  Sacred  Waters,'  with  their  oracular 
powers  and  superstitions ;  and  'Water  Deities '  are  cited  in  great  num- 
bers, as  are  '  Rivers  of  Death  '  and  '  Paradise  '  as  a  land  beyond  the  sea. 
Water  itself  is  animate  in  the  superstitions  of  childhood  and  primitive 
culture.  '  Lustrations  and  Ceremonial  Purifications '  by  water,  in- 
cluding « Infant  Baptism,'  show  the  natural  reverence  one  has  for  one's 
forebears.  Even  '  Water  in  Literature,'  poetical  and  religious,  is 
touched  upon  and  found  to  be  a  great  source  of  all  kinds  of  emotion. 
'The  Feelings  of  People  at  Present  toward  Water'  have  been  inves- 
tigated by  Mr.  Bolton  with  a  Clark  University  questionnaire  which 
contained  rubrics  on  '  Running  Water,'  '  Large  Expanses,'  '  Waves, 
Billows,  etc.,'  'Children's  Animistic  Conceptions  of  Water'  and  the 
4  Earliest  Feelings  toward  Water;'  and  the  answers  to  these  numerous 
questions  are  given  to  the  extent  of  almost  nine  pages  of  fine  print. 
The  'Pedagogic  Significance'  of  all  this  is  that  children  like  to  play 
in  the  water,  and  they  ought  to  be  allowed  to  do  it ;  and  that  the  hu- 
man soul  is  benefited  by  communion  with  water.  Here  is  the  final 
sentence  (p.  227)  :  "  The  childhood  of  the  race  was  spent  in  delight- 
ful contact  with  nature ;  the  child,  ontogenetically  recapitulating  the 
phylogenetic  development  of  the  race,  craves  instinctively  for  com- 
munion with  nature." 

The  serious  objection  to  papers  of  this  kind  is  that  the  writer  has 
not  given  proof  of  the  applicability  of  his  facts  to  his  theory  and  to  his 
theory  alone.  This  would  have  been  most  desirable  in  an  article  con- 
sisting largely,  if  not  solely,  of  a  conglomeration  of  facts  and  legends, 
a  mixture  of  science  and  folk-lore. 

This  remarkable  paper  and  its  fellow  Dendro- Psychoses  no- 
ticed immediately  above,  are  beautiful  examples  of  the  way  to  make 
a  syllabus  seem  interesting ;  but  the  possibilities  of  the  continuance,  ad 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  335 

znjin.,  of  such  lines  of  thought  should  be  appalling  to  the  mathemat- 
ically scientific  mind.  For  why  should  we  not  have  articles  on  Aer- 
Psychoses,  Geo-Psychoses  and  Omichlo-Psychoses,  as  air,  earth  and 
fog  (particularly  the  last)  must  have  exercised  a  great,  in  proportion 
as  it  is  distant  in  time  of  evolution,  and,  therefore,  fundamental,  influ- 
ence upon  our  thought.  Supporting  the  thesis  in  Geo-Psychoses 
which  we  expect  to  see  emanating  from  Clark  (I  give  a  few  hints  for 
the  forthcoming  article)  would  be  'Dust  thou  art,'  etc.,  and  the  fact 
that  so  many  people  prefer  to  be  buried  in  the  earth  rather  than  burned 
up ;  and  the  fact  that  a  great  many  persons  will  have  themselves  cre- 
mated and  turned  into  their  constituent  gases  is  a  good  point  for  the 
article  Aer-Psychoses.  The  present  writer  confesses  to  an  extraor- 
dinary fondness  for  similitudes  and  analogies,  and  that  he  much  en- 
joyed reading  Mr.  Bolton's  article,  for  it  awakened  in  him  many  de- 
sires to  drop  books  and  seek  some  well-known  swimming  hole ;  but  it 
is  a  pertinent  fact  that,  while  reading  Hydro- Psychoses,  something 
(was  it  his  subconscious  self?)  kept  humming  in  his  ears  the  tune  out 
of  the  hymn-book :  4  Pull  for  the  Shore.' 

Numbers  XII.,  XIII.  and  XIV.  of  the  Minor  Studies  are  (a) 
1  On  Nearly  Simultaneous  Clicks  and  Flashes,'  (o)  i  The  Time 
Required  for  Recognition '  and  (c)  'Notes  on  Mental  Standards  of 
Length.'  (a)  The  first  research,  conducted  by  Mr.  G.  M.  Whip- 
pie,  seems  to  show  that  the  flashes,  either  by  reason  of  their  faint- 
ness  and  the  focussing  of  the  attention  necessary  to  take  them  in, 
or  for  some  other  reason,  tend  to  be  perceived  before  the  clicks. 
Might  not,  however,  the  variability  of  the  results  of  Whipple  and 
those  of  Exner,  Gonnesiat  and  others  be  due  to  the  visual  or  audi- 
tory type  of  the  subject?  Summed  up,  the  results  of  these  experi- 
ments (6  subjects)  are  to  show  '  a  greater  attention-claiming  quality ' 
of  the  flash,  which  makes  the  interval  for  recognition  shorter 
for  the  flash-click  than  for  the  click-flash  order,  and  that  this  holds 
true  for  series  of  pairs.  (3)  In  the  second  research,  by  F.  W. 
Colegrove,  illustrations  from  magazines  were  shown  to  the  subject, 
some  of  which  he  had  not  seen  before,  and  he  reacted,  indicating 
whether  he  had  or  had  not.  The  results  (from  5  subjects)  seem  to  show 
that  the  judgments  vary  in  quickness  with  the  expectation  of  known 
(quicker)  or  unknown  (slower)  pictures,  (c)  In  the  third,  by  Mr. 
Colegrove,  the  mental  standards  of  length  were  studied  by  giving  10 
subjects  a  series  of  fifty  circles  graduated  from  1%  to  4T\  inches  in 
diameter  and  a  series  of  lines  the  same  lengths,  and  asking  them  to  say 
how  long  they  were.  Three  inches  was  the  favorite  estimation. 
NEW  YORK.  WILFRID  LAY. 


^INVENTION. 

The  Dynamogenic  Factors  in  Pacemaking  and  Competition.  NOR- 
MAN TRIPLETT.  Am.  Jour.  Psych.,  Vol.  IX.,  1898,  pp.  507. 
In  bicycle  races  the  value  of  a  pace  may  be  from  twenty  to  thirty 
seconds  per  mile.  Mr.  Triplett  states  the  theories  that  have  been  pro- 
posed to  account  for  this  wholly  or  in  part.  The  nature  of  each  of  these 
theories  is  indicated  by  their  respective  titles,  namely,  suction,  shelter, 
encouragement,  brain  worry,  hypnotic  suggestion  and  automatism. 
He  then  advances  another  theory,  stated  as  follows  :  **  Bodily  presence 
of  another  rider  is  a  stimulus  to  the  racer  in  arousing  the  competitive 
instinct ;  another  can  thus  be  the  means  of  releasing  or  freeing  nervous 
energy  that  he  cannot  himself  release;  and,  further,  the  sight  of  move- 
ment, by  suggesting  a  higher  rate  of  speed,  is  also  an  inspiration  to 
greater  effort."  This  theory  does  not  exclude  the  above-mentioned 
factors  in  bicycle  pacing,  but  it  is  supported  by  laboratory  experiments 
in  which  most  of  them  were  eliminated.  The  experiments  consisted 
in  a  flag  race.  The  flags  were  attached  to  cord  belts  that  were  run  by 
turning  a  crank  like  that  of  an  ordinary  fishing  reel.  The  races 
were  made  alternately  with  and  without  a  pacemaker  or  rival,  /'.  £., 
alternately  against  time  and  time  pius  a  rival.  Of  forty  children  ex- 
perimented upon,  twenty  were  stimulated  positively;  they  made 
greater  speed  in  the  presence  of  the  pacemaker.  Ten  were  over- 
stimulated  ;  they  lost  by  the  presence  of  the  pacemaker.  Ten  were 
stimulated  but  little.  As  with  wheelmen,  the  value  of  a  pace  was 
different  for  different  children,  but  somewhat  constant  for  the  same 
individual  in  successive  trials.  Variations  for  age  and  sex  were  small 
and  fluctuating. 

In  support  of  the  second  clause  of  the  theory,  he  cites  an  experi- 
ment from  Fere,  illustrating  this  author's  theory  that  the  energy  of  a 
movement  is  proportional  to  the  idea  of  that  movement.  The  third 
clause  of  the  theory  is  based  upon  an  experiment  in  which  the  speed 
of  counting  from  one  to  twenty  was  increased  by  *  pacing.' 

C.  E.  SEASHORE. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  IOWA. 

L? Invention.     Par  FR.    PAULHAN.     Revue   Philosophique.     March 

1898. 

This  contribution  to  the  psychology  of  invention  is  characterized  by 
a  detailed  description  of  the  phenomenology  of  inventive  processes,  on 
the  basis  of  intellectual  and  emotional  experiences  of  the  inventors  them- 
selves. The  two  most  obvious  generalizations  drawn  from  this  wealth 
of  material,  including  inventions  in  art,  science  and  technique,  are, 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  337 

first,  that  all  inventive  processes  are  essentially  alike  in  presenting 
certain  well-defined  phases,  and  secondly  that  these  processes  are  essen- 
tially volitional  in  their  type ;  the  main  -problem  which  emerges  is  the 
question  of  the  relation  of  the  chance  associations  or  suggestions  to  the 
dominating  idea  of  the  invention. 

In  all  invention  there  is  first  of  all  a  tendency  of  desire,  unsatisfied, 
which  imposes  upon  the  mind  certain  more  or  less  fixed  ideas  upon 
which  it  counts  for  satisfaction.  This  is  followed  by  a  crisis,  akin  to 
volition,  in  which  the  dominating  idea  remains  confused  and  unlogical 
often  until  the  last  moment,  and  may  follow  as  well  as  precede  the  de- 
tails. 

The  conditions  of  this  semi-volitional  phenomenon  are  to  be  found 
naturally  in  the  sensational  and  affective  sides  of  consciousness ;  the 
former  being  either  general  nervous  stimulation,  as  when  thought  is 
stimulated  by  music  or  walking,  or  secondly  by  stimulation  through 
some  special  artistic  sense,  either  by  the  same  sense  in  which  the  in- 
vention is  conceived  or  by  a  law  of  transposition  of  the  senses,  as 
Paulhan  calls  it ;  an  invention  in  one  artistic  sense  may  be  stimulated 
by  the  experiences  of  another,  as  when  Massanet  is  stimulated  to  the 
composition  of  oriental  airs  by  the  sight  of  a  turban  or  by  the  taste  of 
Greek  wine,  or  when  Flaubert  desires  to  write  a  story  in  purple ! 
Color  schemes  have  suggested  music,  and  vice  versa. 

The  lack  of  logical  connection  between  the  conditions  and  results 
of  invention  indicates  that  the  connections  between  the  ideas  are  often 
largely  emotional ;  and  to  this  color  is  lent  by  the  foregoing  facts, 
which  lead  the  writer  to  compare  a  specialized  artistic  faculty,  which 
may  be  thus  variously  stimulated  to  the  eye  nerves  whose  functioning 
may  be  brought  about  by  other  than  the  normal  stimulus.  As  further 
proof  of  the  volitional  nature  of  invention,  it  is  shown  that  unsatisfied 
passions  and  instincts  are  often  effective  causes,  Chauteaubriand  and 
Rousseau  furnishing  neat  examples. 

This  tendency  to  affiliate  invention  with  the  volitional  rather  than 
the  logical  side  of  consciousness — going  so  far  indeed  as  to  consider 
the  difference  only  one  of  content — leads  naturally  in  the  direction  of 
reducing  invention  to  a  continuation  of  instinctive  life,  and  to  the  false 
view  which  Ribot  holds  out,  that  it  is  capable  of  a  purely  nervous 
explanation.  But  the  author  saves  himself  from  a  too  mechanical 
point  of  view — which  when  pressed  must  resolve  itself  into  James' 
chance  tipping  of  the  nerve  cells — by  refusing  to  call  in  the  element 
of  chance,  and  by  substituting  for  the  fascinating  definition  of  M.  Paul 
Sauriau,  that  the  element  of  c  hazard '  in  invention  is  *  the  conflict  of 


338  NEUROLOGY. 

external  casualty  with  internal  finality,'  a  more  comprehensive  notion 
of  invention  as  the  resultant  of  a  conflict  of  different  systems  of  inter- 
nal finality.  This  conception  M.  Paulhan  has,  unfortunately,  not 
developed  further,  and  the  reader  will  miss  likewise  a  detailed  treat- 
ment of  the  social  criteria  of  the  reception  of  an  invention.  A  study 
of  these  criteria  from  M.  Paulhan's  volitional  standpoint,  such  as 
Baldwin  has  developed  from  a  different  point  of  view,  is  necessary  to 
the  completion  of  his  study.  In  conclusion  we  can  only  call  atten- 
tion to  the  interesting  discussions  of  the  relation  of  invention  to  imita- 
tion, and  to  the  sources  of  the  subjective  sufficiency  of  an  invention. 

WILBUR  MARSHALL  URBAN. 

On  the  Alleged  Sensory  Functions  of  the   Motor  Cortex  Cerebri. 

E.  A.  SCHAEFER.     Journ.  of  Physiol.,  Vol.  XXIII.,  No.  4,  Nov., 

1898.     Pp.  310-314. 

This  important  though  brief  article  or  report  was  read  before  the 
Congress  of  Physiologists  at  Cambridge,  England,  in  August,  1898.  It 
has  especial  interest  at  this  time  because  of  the  prominence  which 
discussions  of  the  will  as  bodily  action  hold  in  current  psychological 
discussions. 

H.  Munk  had  made  the  assertion,  followed  by  many,  that  "  after 
total  extirpation  of  the  arm-  and  leg-area  [of  the  cortex  of  monkeys] 
tactile  sensibility  of  the  opposite  extremities  is  permanently  lost ;  a 
touch  or  light  pressure  is  without  any  effect;  neither  tactile  reflexes 
nor  eye-  nor  head-movements  are  produced.  The  same  is  the  case  if 
the  whole  arm-  or  leg-region  is  removed  in  monkeys ;  tactile  sensibil- 
ity is  permanently  lost  in  the  opposite  arm  or  leg."  It  was  to  test  the 
truth  of  this  assertion  that  this  set  of  thirty  experiments  was  performed 
on  the  cortex  of  monkeys.  They  were  made  (i)  upon  the  area  con- 
nected with  the  movements  of  the  face  (already  published)  ;  (2)  upon 
the  area  connected  with  the  movements  of  the  leg;  (3)  upon  the  com- 
bined area  connected  with  the  movements  of  both  arm  and  leg ;  and 
(4)  upon  the  gyrus  fornicatus. 

These  experiments  lead  Dr.  Schaefer  to  assert  boldly  that  the 
above  cited  statement  of  Munk  is  c '  entirely  erroneous ;  that,  in  fact, 
complete  voluntary  motor  paralysis  of  a  part  may  be  produced  by  a 
cortical  lesion  without  perceptible  loss  of  tactile  sensibility "  (a  fact 
certainly  in  accord  with  frequent  clinical  experience).  "It  cannot, 
therefore,  be  the  case,"  says  the  writer,  "that  the  motor  paralysis 
which  is  produced  by  a  lesion  of  the  Rolandic  area  is  due  to  a  sensory 
disturbance.  And  it  also  follows  that  tactile  sensibility  is  not  localized 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  339 

in  the  same  part  of  the  cortex  from  which  voluntary  motor  impulses 
directly  emanate."  This  does  not  preclude  the  possibility  that  branch- 
lets  of  the  sensory  sort  of  nerves  enter  the  motor  areas  of  the  brain ; 
indeed,  the  tingling  often  felt  upon  stimulation  of  the  region  suggests 
that  they  do  so.  It  seems  to  the  experimenter  conclusive  that  repeat- 
edly excision  of  the  motor  area  produced  no  anaesthesia  in  the  part 
which  was  thereby  paralyzed.  We  shall  await  with  much  interest 
the  outcome  of  this  important  and  seemingly  difficult  discussion. 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


Recent  Views  as  to  the  Topical  Basis  of  Mental  Disorders.  DR. 
KIRCHHOFF.  Trans,  by  A.  W.  McCoRN.  Am.  Jour.  Insanity, 
Vol.  LV.,  No.  3,  January,  1899.  Pp.  481-495. 

This  is  a  brief  review  of  the  present  status  of  the  localization  of 
cerebral  functions,  with  especial  psychiatrical  reference. 

The  region  about  the  fissure  of  Rolando,  formerly  called  motor,  is 
now  shown  to  be  half-composed  of  sensory  fibres  from  all  parts  of  the 
body ;  hence  it  is  called  by  Flechsig  the  somaesthetic  area.  Quite  an- 
alogous to  this  is  the  visual  center  ( 4  those  cortical  regions  into  which 
the  fibres  of  the  occipito-thalmic  radiations  of  Gratiolet  extend ' — parts 
of  the  cortex  adjacent  to  the  calcarine  fissure),  while  it  further  appears 
that  the  retina  is  directly  represented,  homologously,  in  the  cortex,  as 
to  a  less  perfect  extent  is  the  neural  portion  of  the  ear.  The  auditory 
area  is  in  the  posterior  part  of  the  superior  temporal  gyri  and  in  deeper 
transverse  convolutions.  The  olfactory  area  is  probably  in  the  gyrus 
hippocampi,  and  taste  is  most  likely  represented  in  the  uncus  near  the 
nucleus  amygdalae.  Pain  may  very  probably  be  represented  in  the 
external  limb  of  the  lenticular  nucleus  (the  putamen)  and  in  the  nucleus 
caudatus.  These  centers  seem  to  have  trophic  functions  also,  and  this 
relation  empirical  lessening  of  pain  by  improved  nutrition  corroborates. 
The  unity  of  the  whole  nervous  system  is  to  be  recognized  continually. 
Flechsig's  notion  of  thought-centers  in  the  form  of  association-centers 
scattered  through  the  cortex  between  the  sensory  regions,  but  mainly 
three  in  number,  of  which  two,  the  middle  and  posterior,  are  probably 
united  into  one,  the  seat  of  the  intellect,  Dr.  Kirchhoff  considers  ten- 
tatively admissible. 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 


34°  NE  UROLOG  Y. 

Neural  Dynamics.     W.  J.   HERDMAN.     Journ.  of  the  Am.  Med. 

Assn.,   Vol.  XXXI.,  No.  21,  December  19,   1898.     Pp.    1211- 

1214. 

This  is  another  theory   of  neural   dynamics  and    quite  in   line 
with  the   most  natural  suppositions  concerning  this  doubtful  matter ; 
the   article  was  read  at  the  meeting  of  the  American  Medical  As- 
sociation held  in  Denver  in  June,  1898. 

Dr.  Herdman  likens  neurons  to  charged  electrical  condensers. 
The  nutritive  processes  and  states  of  a  neuron  are  indices  of  its 
readiness  for  action,  it  having  a  surface-tension  and  a  corresponding 
electrical  potential.  The  end-organs  of  sensory  nerves  serve  as  ave- 
nues of  ingress  for  forms  of  motion,  which  latter  causes  rearrangement 
of  the  cell's  molecules  and  a  change  in  the  static  electrical  condition. 
On  the  one  hand,  every  change  in  a  neuron  acts  as  a  stimulus  on 
every  neighboring  neuron,  but  at  the  same  time,  by  the  principle  on 
which  electro-magnetic  induction  acts,  each  neuron  restrains  the 
action  of  the  others,  the  balance  thus  being  easily  disturbable.  "  Thus 
conduction  and  transference  of  nerve  force  are,  according  to  this 
theory,  to  be  regarded  as  of  the  nature  of  electrostatic  phenomena." 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 


Ueber  die  Primitivfibrillen  in  den    Ganglienzellen  vom  Menschen 
und    anderen    Wirbelthieren.      ALBRECHT    BETHE.      Morpho- 
logische  Arbeiten,  VIII.  Band,  i  Heft,  1898.     Pp.  95-115. 
This  article  by  Dr.  Bethe,  of  the  University  of  Strasburg,  is  one 
more  of  the  reports  of   very  important  histological  research  into  the 
nature  of  the  ultimate  neural  unit  which  are  making  this  basal  dis- 
cussion  so  animated  and  seemingly  contradictory.     He  is  one  with 
Remak,    Max     Schultze,    Nissl,    and    Apathy,    besides   very   many 
others,  in  considering  the  fibrilla,  and   by  no   means  the  cells  or  the 
neuron,   as  the  anatomical  and  physiological  unit  of  the  nervous  sys- 
tem.    By  an  improvement  on  Apathy's  method  he  has  been  able  to 
demonstrate  the  fibrillaa  in  the  vertebrates,  namely,  in  the  frog,  dog, 
rabbit,  and  in  man. 

After  a  brief  historical  review  of  the  work  in  this  direction  to  date, 
and  considerations  in  regard  to  methods  employed,  he  describes  the 
ultimate  fibril lae  in,  first,  the  axis-cylinder,  and,  second,  as  it  appears 
in  the  ganglion-cell.  Two  plates  of  drawings,  thirteen  in  number, 
finely  represent  what  he  has  seen  even,  without  the  elaborate  and 
detailed  description  of  the  text.  He  seems  to  have  examined  with 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  341 

his  new  methods  nearly  every  sort  of  nerve-cell  found  in  the  species 
studied,  as  well  as  the  various  sorts  of  conductive  structures. 

Dr.  Bethe  considers  it  probable  that  the  fibrillae  may  conduct  im- 
pressions both  toward  and  away  from  the  cell ;  that  the  protoplasmic 
cell-projections  are  not  neural,  but  nutritive ;  that  the  connection  be- 
tween the  cell,  especially  its  nucleus,  and  the  fibrillae  is  very  4  loose/ 

"  The  result  of  this  research,"  says  its  conductor,  "  I  may  give  in  the 
very  words  of  Max  Schultze,  expressed  more  than  twenty-six  years  ago, 
but  not  recognized  until  to-day :  '  Hence  such  a  ganglion-cell,  out  of 
which  a  centrifugal  nerve-fiber  arises,  has  meaning  as  the  originating 
organ  of  this  fiber  only  in  the  sense  that  the  fibrillae  out  of  which  the 
axis-cylinder  is  composed  lead  to  it  by  way  of  the  lateral  branches  of 
the  ganglion-cell,  while  the  fibrillae,  which  may  be  seen  extending 
through  the  substance  of  the  ganglion-cell,  do  not  arise  from  the  cell, 
but  in  themselves  only  surround  it  after  the  manner  of  the  branches  of 
the  axis-cylinder  and  continue  on  into  other  lateral  branches.'  " 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 


Neuron  Energy  and  its  Psychomotor  Manifestations.  IRA  VAN 
GIESON  and  BORIS  SIDIS.  Archives  of  Neurology  and  Psycho- 
Pathology.  Vol.  I.,  No.  i,  1898.  Pp.  5-24. 

This  is  the  first  article  in  the  State  Hospitals  Bulletin  under  its 
new  title  and  in  its  greatly  improved  dress.  The  object  of  the  article, 
announced  as  only  preliminary,  is  thus  stated  by  its  authors:  "We 
intend  here  to  set  forth,  in  a  concrete,  diagrammatic  form  a  theory 
that  attempts  to  correlate  the  various  general  manifestations  of  psycho- 
motor  life  with  more  or  less  definite  physiological  processes  depending 
on  the  expenditure  or  restitution  of  nerve  energy." 

Many  useful  and  precise  definitions  occur,  and  the  article  is  espe- 
cially rich  (about  three  pages)  in  seemingly  elaborate  algebraic  formu- 
lae expressing  the  various  sorts  of  metabolism  of  the  neuron-groups. 
Psychopathies  indicates  psychic  disaggregation  correlative  to  dissocia- 
tion within  constellations  ofr  neurons,  the  neuron  itself  remaining  un- 
injured; while  Neuropathies  is  defined  as  u  a  group  of  psychophysical 
manifestations  running  parallel  to  fluctuations  of  static  energy  and  ac- 
companied by  organic  changes  in  the  neuron."  In  mental  disease 
psychopathies  may  become  neuropathies,  and  the  latter  may  go  on  to 
cytoclasis  through  processes  of  catalysis  and  cytolysis. 

"  The  cycles  in  dynamic  energy  correspond  to  the  physiological 
manifestations  of  the  nervous  system  in  the  activity  and  rest  of  the 


342  NEUROLOGY. 

individual  in  normal  daily  life.  Concomitant  with  the  expenditure  of 
dynamic  energy  of  the  neurons,  the  individual  passes  through  the 
active  normal  waking  state,  and  hand  in  hand  with  the  restitution  of 
this  expended  dynamic  energy,  he  passes  through  the  sleeping  state  of 
normal  daily  life.  When,  however,  in  the  expenditure  of  energy,  the 
border  line  is  crossed,  dynamic  energy  is  used  up  and  static  energy  is 
drawn  upon.  The  border  line  that  separates  the  normal  physiological 
from  the  abnormal  or  pathological  psychomotor  manifestations  is 
stepped  over.  *  *  *  *  Catalysis  corresponds  to  liberation  of  the 
upper  levels  of  static  energy,  and  is  accompanied  by  retraction  of  ag- 
gregates of  neurons,  bringing  about  the  phenomena  of  psychophysio- 
logical  dissociation.  Restitution  of  the  energy  expended  in  the  cata- 
lytic process  is  accompanied  by  expansion  or  synthesis  of  the  neurons, 
which  are  again  able  to  transmit  or  receive  impulses  in  the  particular 
aggregate  to  which  they  belong.  An  arrest  or  halt  after  the  expendi- 
ture of  energy  in  these  upper  static  levels,  corresponds  again  to  a  state 
of  retraction  of  the  neuron  or  catalysis.  *  *  *  *  Broadly  speaking, 
psychopathies  run  parallel  to  the  phenomena  of  retraction  and  expan- 
sion of  aggregates  of  neurons,  while  neuropathies  are  concomitant 
with  actual  degeneration  of  the  neuron,  especially  of  its  cytolymph. 
*  *  *  *  This  one  continuous  process  of  liberation  of  neuron  energy 
may  cover  the  life  of  a  single  individual  or  may  extend  over  the  life- 
history  of  many  generations. 

44  The  continuous  descending  pathological  process  may  spread  out  in 
time  and  space,  may  extend  over  a  long  duration  of  time  and  embrace 
a  great  number  of  individuals.  The  tide  of  neuron  energy  may  ebb 
away  gradually,  leaving  each  succeeding  generation  on  a  lower  stage 
and  deeper  level  in  the  continuous  process  of  neuron  disaggregation 
and  degeneration,  thus  giving  rise  to  the  different  stages  and  manifes- 
tations of  congenital  degeneracy.  Many  of  the  so-called  degeneracies 
and  the  congenital  diseases  of  the  nervous  system  arise,  we  believe,  in 
this  way." 

44  We  may  conclude  this  brief  preliminary  communication,"  say 
these  two  scientists  of  the  Pathological  Institute,  44  with  a  few  laws 
relating  to  the  metabolic  processes  of  neuron  activity :  I.  Catalysis 
stands  in  direct  and  synthesis  in  inverse  ratio  to  the  number  of  disag- 
gregated neuron  associations.  II.  All  other  conditions  remaining  the 
same,  the  instability  of  a  cell  aggregate  is  proportionate  to  the  number 
and  complexity  of  its  associative  functioning  groups.  III.  The  sta- 
bility of  a  neuron  aggregate  is  proportionate  to  the  frequency  and 
duration  of  its  associative  activity.  IV.  The  instability  of  ;a  neuron 


NEW  BOOKS.  343 

aggregate  is  proportionate  to  the  frequency  and  duration  of  the  inter- 
ruptions in  its  functioning  activity.  V.  The  mass  of  formed  meta- 
plasm  granules  stands  in  direct  ratio  to  the  intensity  of  cyto lysis  and 
in  inverse  ratio  to  the  progress  of  cytothesis." 

GEORGE  V.  DEARBORN. 


NEW  BOOKS. 

De   la  Methode  dans  la   Psychologic  des  Sentiments.     F.   RAUH. 

Paris,  Alcan.     1899.     Pp.  305.     Fr.  5. 
La  Nouvelle  Monadologie.     CH.  RENOUVIER  and  L.  PRAT.     Paris, 

Colin  etCifl.     1899.     Pp.546.     12  fr. 
Wb'rterbuch    der    philosophischen    Begriffe   und  Ausdrucke.     R. 

EISLER.     In  8  parts.     Parts  L,  II.     Berlin,  E.  S.  Mittler  u.  Sohn. 

1899.     Pp  vi  4-  1-96  and  97-192.     M.  2  each  part. 
The   Foundations   of  Zoology.     W.  K.  BROOKS.     New  York  and 

London,  Macmillan.      1899.     Pp.  viii  4-  339*     $2.50. 
The  Development  of  English  Thought.     SIMON  N.  PATTEN.     New 

York  and  London,  Macmillan.      1899.     Pp.  xxvii  4-  409.     $3.00. 
Philosophy  of  Theism.     A.  C.  FRASER.     2d  ed.  amended.     Edin- 
burgh and  London.     1899.     Pp.  xviii  4-  338. 
Manual  of  Psychology.     G.  F.  STOUT.     Vol.  I.     London,  W.  B. 

Clive.      1898.     Pp.  xii  -f  240. 
Essay   on    the    Bases   of    the    Mystic    Knowledge.     E.    RECEJAC. 

Trans,  by  SARA  C.  UPTON.     New  York,  Scribners.      1899.     Pp. 

xi  4-  287.     $2.50. 
The  Public  School  Mental  Arithmetic.     J.  A.  McLENNAN.     New 

York,  Macmillan.      1899.     Pp.  x  4-  138.     25  cents. 
Anthropological  Investigations  on  one  Thousand  White  and  Colored 

Children  of  Both  Sexes.     ALES  HRDLICKA.     Illustrated.     New 

York  and  Albany,  Crawford  Co.     1899  (?).     Pp.  86. 
Spinoza,  his  Life  and  Philosophy.     F.  POLLOCK.     2d  Ed.  London, 

Duckworth;    New  York,  Macmillans.      1899.     Pp.   xxiv  4- 427. 

$3- 

All  students  of  philosophy  will  welcome  the  new  edition  of  Sir 

Frederick  Pollock's  standard  work — so  long  out  of  print.  This  edi- 
tion is  somewhat  reduced  in  size  from  the  omission  of  the  <  critical 
and  bibliographical  matter  collected  '  in  the  former  edition.  The  ap- 
pendices to  the  earlier  edition  are  also  omitted  c  except  the  English  ver- 


344  NOTES. 

sion   of  Colerus.'     Certain  later   bibliographical  indications,   on  the 
other  hand,  are  now  included.  J.  M.  B. 

Lectures  on  the  Republic  of  Plato.     R.  L.  NETTLESHIP.     Ed.  by 

G.R.BENSON.    London  and  New  York,  Macmillans.     1898.    Pp. 

vi  +  364.     $2.75. 


NOTES. 

THE  «  Teacher's  Professional  Library '  is  the  title  of  a  series  of 
books  announced  by  The  Macmillan  Company  under  the  general  edi- 
torship of  Professor  Nicholas  Murray  Butler,  of  Columbia  University. 
The  contributors  to  this  series  will  be  leading  teachers  and  students  of 
education  in  Europe  as  well  as  in  the  United  States.  A  number  of 
volumes  have  already  been  arranged  for. 

PROFESSOR  EDWARD  BRADFORD  TITCHENER  is  preparing  for  pub- 
lication early  in  the  fall  4  A  Laboratory  Manual  of  Experimental  Psy- 
chology,' which  will  be  published  by  The  Macmillan  Company.  The 
work  will  be  in  two  volumes  and  will  detail  an  elementary  course  of 
laboratory  work.  The  first  volume  will  deal  with  qualitative  analysis, 
the  second  with  the  exact  measurement  of  mental  processes.  Each 
volume  will  be  published  in  a  student's  and  a  teacher's  edition,  the 
former  giving  instructions  as  regards  the  conduct  of  experiments,  con- 
trol of  introspection,  etc.,  and  the  latter  furnishing  references,  cognate 
questions  and  exercises,  and  standard  results.  (Publisher's  note.) 

WE  notice  in  the  Journal  of  Mental  Science,  which  is  much  im- 
proved in  form  and  appearance,  the  beginning  of  an  *  Index  Medico- 
Psychologicus,'  prepared  by  Dr.  J.  Turner.  The  first  part  goes  from 
A  to  I,  for  the  year  1893—4.  The  arrangement  is  alphabetical  simply. 

DR.  DODGE  has  been  advanced  to  an  associate  professorship  of 
philosophy  at  Wesleyan  University. 

MESSRS.  MAYER  AND  MILLER,  of  Berlin,  are  publishing  in  three 
volumes  the  mathematical  correspondence  of  Gottfried  Wilhelm  Leib- 
nitz, under  the  editorship  of  C.  J.  Gerhardt. 

DR.  BENJAMIN  RAND,  of  the  department  of  philosophy,  will  pub- 
lish in  April  a  work  entitled  4  The  Life,  Letters  and  Philosophical 
Regimen  of  the  Third  Earl  of  Shaftesbury.' 

EDWARD  THORNDIKE,  Ph.D.  (Columbia),  instructor  in  education 
in  Western  Reserve  University,  has  been  appointed  instructor  in 
genetic  psychology  in  Teachers  College,  Columbia  University. 


VOL.  VI.     No.  4.  JULY,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


STUDIES    ON  THE  TELEGRAPHIC   LANGUAGE. 

THE  ACQUISITION   OF  A   HIERARCHY 

OF   HABITS. 

BY  PROFESSOR  WILLIAM  LOWE  BRYAN, 

University  of  Indiana  / 
AND  SUPERINTENDENT  NOBLE  HARTER, 

Warsaw,  Indiana. 

I. 

THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  AN  OCCUPATION. 

A  field  for  research  is  offered  in  the  psychology  of  occu- 
pations. The  chief  engagement  of  every  one  is  the  acquisition 
or  exercise  of  one  or  another  association  of  habits,  such  as  con- 
stitutes skill  in  a  game,  trade,  profession,  language,  science  or 
the  like.  With  a  little  license  one  may  call  all  of  these  occu- 
pations. In  mastering  an  occupation,  doubtless  the  whole  man 
is  involved,  body  and  mind,  sensation  and  movement,  thought, 
interest,  imagination,  will, — innumerable  known  and  unknown 
aspects  of  our  psycho-physical  life. 

It  might  be  argued  that  such  an  affair  is  too  complex  for 
scientific  treatment  until  we  have  done  with  more  elementary 
things,  the  fusion  of  ideas,  the  psycho-physic  law,  the  chem- 
istry of  the  cell,  or  whatever  may  be  still  more  elementary.  In 
reply,  it  may  be  said  that  the  history  of  science  justifies  the 
study  of  concrete  facts,  however  simple  or  complex,  whether  or 
not  the  results  can  at  once  be  correlated  with  other  facts  and 
theories.  One  studies  microscopically,  another  macroscopically. 
One  studies  the  chemistry  of  the  cell,  another  tone  sensations, 


346  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

another  comparative  religion.  A  fact  fixed  at  any  point  stands 
in  its  own  right,  throws  light  at  once  upon  the  less  and  upon 
the  more  complicated  aspects  of  reality,  and  so  does  its  share 
toward  a  future  correlation  of  the  sciences  into  science.  The 
fashion  of  a  time  may  run  now  to  narrower,  now  to  broader 
studies ;  but  time  justifies  all  work  which  meets  its  test,  verifi- 
ability  ad  libitum. 

Most  psychological  studies,  doubtless  with  good  reason, 
have  dealt  with  abstractions.  This  is  obviously  true  of  the 
studies,  earlier  and  later,  on  will,  association,  attention,  etc. ;  for 
these  '  faculties '  are  plainly  not  concrete  phenomena  of  con- 
scious life,  but  artificially  isolated  aspects  of  conscious  life.  It 
is  no  less  true  that  in  the  later  laboratory  studies  on  the  fatigue 
of  a  muscle,  the  reaction  time  in  a  silence  cabinet,  or  the  like, 
we  are  dealing  with  abstractions.  The  reacting  man,  muscle, 
or  ganglion  is,  indeed,  concrete ;  but  when  a  given  process  in 
one  of  these  is  studied  experimentally,  the  first  and  hardest  task 
is  just  the  isolation  of  that  process  from  *  disturbing  conditions  ' — 
that  is,  from  the  complex  stream  of  life  in  which  alone  it  nor- 
mally occurs. 

The  best  of  these  analytic  studies,  earlier  and  later,  are  in- 
valuable to  science  and,  in  due  course,  to  the  conduct  of  affairs. 
Invaluable,  but  still  far  from  sufficient,  by  themselves,  either 
for  science  or  for  practical  guidance.  The  scholar  singles  out 
of  the  complex  processes  before  him,  some  general  aspect  (law) 
or  some  group  of  facts.  He  exploits  one  or  the  other  precisely 
and  systematically.  Excellent !  But  too  often  the  price  of  this 
precision  and  system  is  an  absorption  which  makes  him  blinder 
than  his  neighbors  to  facts  or  laws  that  are  in  the  processes  con- 
cerned, but  outside  the  range  of  his  methods,  and  to  the  actual 
course  of  events  in  which  all  the  facts  and  laws  known  and  un- 
known are  interfused. 

This  blindness  to  things  before  his  nose,  but  out  of  the  focus 
of  his  attention,  is  the  disease-of-the-scholar.  He  assumes  that 
the  particular  principle  or  fact  which  he  has  defined  sub- 
stantially determines  the  whole  stream  of  life  in  which  it  be- 
longs. He  writes  an  essay  on  will,  or  studies  the  latent  period 
of  an  excised  muscle,  and  thereupon  issues  commands  to  the 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  347 

public  schools.  Science  is  his  debtor  if  he  has  developed  any 
truth.  Science  has  time  to  wait  for  the  rest.  But  if  he  tries  to 
put  his  learning  to  work,  the  realities  which  he  has  ignored  will 
have  their  revenge. 

However,  it  is  easier  to  see  the  need  of  trustworthy  concrete 
psychology  than  to  supply  the  need.  The  actual  concrete  pro- 
cesses of  life  are,  indeed,  all  about  and  within  us,  but  in  a  be- 
wildering tangle.  Out  of  this  tangle  we  are  all  forced  to  get 
some  '  knowledge  of  human  nature'  so  that  we  may  live  to- 
gether. To  our  own  insights  in  this  direction  we  may  add  those 
of  others,  those  of  artists  and  other  sagacious  men,  those  sanc- 
tioned by  the  folk.  In  this  way  we  build  up  a  concrete  psy- 
chology, each  for  himself,  and  by  this  we  guide  ourselves  in 
dealing  with  one  another.  It  is  the  dream  of  the  scholar  to  sup- 
plant this  lore  of  the  folk  by  an  array  of  knowledge  equally 
concrete  and  practical,  but  immeasurably  wider,  more  accurate, 
more  systematic,  and  freer  from  personal  bias.  The  dream  is 
long  in  fulfilling.  There  are  quick  ways,  but  they  lead  to 
pseudo-science.  Witness  phrenology,  physiognomy,  graphology 
and  the  more  precocious  chapters  in  criminology.  Such  out- 
comes warn  us  that  there  is  no  profit  in  fleeing  from  studies 
which  pay  for  their  precision  by  being  abstract,  to  studies  which 
pay  for  their  concreteness  by  being  untrustworthy.  Better  any 
fragment  of  cerebral  physiology  which  is  true,  though  by  itself 
unable  to  tell  any  one  what  to  do,  than  a  Science  of  Human 
Character  which  tells  every  one  what  to  do,  but  is  not  true.  It 
must  be  recognized  that  macroscopic  studies  are  subject  to  the 
same  tests  as  the  microscopic.  The  essential  test  in  both  cases 
is  verifiability  ad  libitum. 

The  best  examples  of  psychological  studies  at  once  concrete 
and  reliable  are  to  be  found  in  the  literatures  of  comparative 
psychology,  psychiatry,  criminal  and  individual  psychology. 
Here  in  the  best  cases  we  have  pictures  of  the  typical  conduct 
of  animals,  children,  melancholiacs,  paranoiacs  et  cetera,  which 
instruct  us  better  than  unscientific  popular  psychology  can, 
what  to  expect  and  what  to  do  in  dealing  with  individuals  of 
these  sorts.  To  this  group  of  studies  the  psychology  of  an  oc- 
cupation would  belong. 


348  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE   HARTER. 

It  would  be  well  worth  while  if  we  could  discern  in  any  one 
man  the  chief  subjective  effects  of  mastering  an  occupation. 
Learning  the  business  has  been  his  chief  concern,  his  most 
thoroughly  evolutionizing  experience.  It  has  been  an  affair  not 
of  weeks  or  months  of  forced  laboratory  practice,  but  of  years, 
wherein  the  natural  interests  of  life  have  constantly  driven  him 
toward  levels  of  skill  only  to  be  reached  under  such  stimula- 
tion. In  the  measure  that  he  has  mastered  the  occupation,  it 
has  mastered  him.  Body  and  soul,  from  head  to  foot,  he  has — 
or  one  may  say  he  is — the  array  of  habits  which  constitutes  pro- 
ficiency in  that  sort. 

Can  such  a  case  be  studied  with  profit  to  science?  The 
probability  that  it  can  be  is  increased  by  the  fact  that  an  occu- 
pation leads  many  men  toward  the  acquisition  of  the  same  set  of 
habits.  These  men  are  scattered  all  along  the  way  from  ap- 
prenticeship to  mastery.  Many  of  them  begin  and  quit  after 
touching  lightly  and  being  lightly  touched  by  the  business. 
These  dabblers  and  failures  are  highly  instructive  objects  of 
study.  Many  others  press  on  into  some  usable  degree  of  pro- 
ficiency. These  men  are  colleagues  not  in  name  only,  but  psy- 
chologically and  physiologically.  They  have  similar  knacks, 
or  similar  traditions  of  the  trade,  or  similar  habitudes  of  some 
kind  necessary  in  their  business.  They  know,  as  well  as  they 
know  anything  about  themselves,  what  the  main  habitudes  de- 
veloped by  their  occupation  are ;  and  if  the  psychologist  can 
find  his  way  to  the  right  questions,  they  can  give  a  valuable  in- 
trospective account  of  those  habitudes.  It  may  be  possible  in 
the  case  of  some  occupations  to  supplement  such  testimony  by 
objective  experimental  tests.  A  few  in  each  occupation  become 
experts,  and  of  these  an  occasional  one  becomes  able  to  do 
easily  and  quickly  what  his  lesser  colleagues  can  scarcely  believe 
possible.  Such  cases  are,  of  course,  hardest  to  understand,  and 
may  escape  all  definition.  But  it  would  surely  be  worth  while 
to  begin  the  study  of  the  genius  by  following  him  along  that 
part  of  his  path  which  he  shared  with  many  others.  We  might 
in  this  way,  at  least,  find  the  point  where  he  disappeared.  That 
would  be  something. 

In  a  word,  society  has  already  made  for  us  in  each  occupa- 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  349 

tion  a  vast  experiment  in  the  development  of  habits.  If  we 
can  make  use  of  some  of  these  ready-made  experiments,  if  we 
can  delineate  the  path  or  paths  by  which  one  travels  toward 
mastery  of  an  occupation,  if  we  can  discover  and  describe  the 
characteristic  stages  of  the  progress,  if  we  can  do  these  things 
so  that  every  detail  of  our  work  can  be  objectively  verified  by 
any  competent  scientist,  and  so  that  the  outcome  will  be  ac- 
cepted as  true  by  those  who  have  mastered  the  occupation,  this 
should  prove  not  unprofitable  work.  It  should  supplement  what 
analytic  psychology  can  do  for  pedagogy  and  psychiatry ;  for 
it  would  portray  the  actual  typical  procedures  of  men  in  learn- 
ing or  in  failing  to  learn.  And  it  should  supplement  what 
analytic  psychology  can  do  toward  developing  the  science  of 
mind;  for %it  would  exhibit  not  theoretical  syntheses  of  alleged 
psychic  elements,  but  the  actual  syntheses  which  the  science  of 
mind  must  accept  and  explain. 

During  the  past  five  years  the  authors  have  made  studies  in 
the  psychology  of  one  occupation — telegraphy,  utilizing 
throughout  the  work  the  experience  of  telegraphers  as  well  as 
the  methods  of  psychological  research.  The  foregoing  pages 
are  not  intended  to  overemphasize  the  importance  of  the  results 
obtained,  but  to  express  a  conviction  which  the  study  has  de- 
veloped, that  in  this  direction  lies  a  programme  worthy  the 
labor  of  many  good  men. 

II. 

DATA  OLD  AND  NEW. 

In  a  former  series  of  studies  on  the  physiology  and  psy- 
chology of  the  telegraphic  language  [PSYCH.  REV.,  IV.,  p.  27] 
the  authors  gave  the  curves  of  improvement  in  sending  and  re- 
ceiving. These  curves  were  determined  by  the  records  of  in- 
dividuals tested  each  week,  from  the  beginning  of  practice  until 
fair  proficiency  was  reached,  and  were  confirmed  by  a  con- 
sensus of  opinion  from  about  two  hundred  operators.  As  the 
conclusions  of  this  paper  are  based  in  part  upon  those  curves, 
one  of  the  figures  (X.)  from  the  former  paper  is  reproduced 
for  convenience  of  reference. 


35° 


WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE   HARTER. 


Reproduced  from  PSYCH.  REV.,  IV.,  44. 


Tfeceiv/vct 


a 


Te.tr < 


RATE.. 


Connected  discourse  curve  at  the  top ;  word  curve  in  the  middle ;  letter  curve 
at  the  bottom. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  351 

The  salient  feature  of  the  pictures  shown  in  Figures  II.  to  X,, 
is  the  difference  between  the  two  curves.  The  sending  curve 
has  a  form  made  familiar  by  many  published  practice  curves. 
The  receiving  curve  has  for  several  months  a  similar  torm,  but 
suddenly  rises  into  what  looks  like  a  second  practice  curve. 
Moreover  the  history  of  expert  telegraphers  shows  that  after 
some  years  the  receiving  curve  may  ascend  rapidly  a  third  time. 

Interest  in  the  novel  form  of  this  curve  deepens  as  evidence 
appears  to  show  that  it  represents,  in  general,  the  course  of  im- 
provement in  various  other  acquisitions,  e.  g*. ,  the  learning  of  a 
foreign  language,  of  chemistry,  of  English  composition,  etc. 
Interest  is  further  challenged  by  the  difficulty  of  explaining  the 
form  of  the  curve.  In  the  former  paper  the  authors  proposed 
no  explanation.  None  of  our  reviewers,  nor  of  the  psychologists 
with  whom  we  have  conversed,  has  given  us  a  hint  as  to  its 
meaning. 

To  investigate  the  problem  further  the  following  experiment 
was  devised.  A  student  should  be  tested  each  week  on 

(<z)  rate  of  receiving  letters  not  making  words, 

(3)  rate  of  receiving  letters  making  words,  the  words  not 
making  sentences, 

(c)  rate  of  receiving  letters  making  words,  the  words  mak- 
ing sentences. 

These  tests  were  made  in  the  winter  of  1896-1897.  The 
subject  was  John  Shaw,  of  Brookville,  Indiana,  who  had  be- 
gun the  study  of  telegraphy  about  six  weeks  before  the  making 
of  first  test,  Oct.  24,  1896.  The  method  of  making  the  test  is 
described  in  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  IV.,  p.  48.  The  test  was 
made  each  week  until  May  9.  One  test  day,  Dec.  26,  was 
missed.  The  results  are  given  in  Figure  XL 

Before  discussing  these  results  we  subjoin  evidence  relating 
thereto  derived  from  the  introspections  and  observations  of 
telegraphers.  As  hitherto  noted  (loc.  cit.,  p.  27),  one  of  the 
authors  (H.)  was  for  years  a  telegrapher.  To  supplement  his 
experience  we  have  held  long  and  satisfactory  conversations 
with  operators1  of  every  grade  up  to  the  most  expert  men  in  the 

1  We  cannot  express  too  warmly  our  thanks  to  the  members  of  the  tele- 
graphic profession  for  their  cordial  assistance  without  which  the  present  study 


35 2  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

country.  We  have  asked  telegraphers  three  principal  ques- 
tions : 

A.  To  what  is  attention  mainly  directed  at  different  stages 
of  progress? 

The  answers  agreed  entirely,  and  were  as  follows  :  (a)  At 
the  outset  one  '  hustles  for  the  letters.'  (b)  Later  one  is  *  after 
words.'  (V)  The  fair  operator  is  not  held  so  closely  to  words. 
He  can  take  in  several  words  at  a  mouthful,  a  phrase  or  even 
a  short  sentence,  (d)  The  real  expert  has  all  the  details  of  the 
language  with  such  automatic  perfection  that  he  gives  them 
practically  no  attention  at  all.  He  can  give  his  attention  freely 
to  the  sense  of  the  message,  or,  if  the  message  is  sent  accu- 
rately and  distinctly,  he  can  transcribe  it  upon  the  typewriter 
while  his  mind  is  running  upon  things  wholly  apart. 

The  feat  of  the  expert  receiver — for  example  of  the  receiver 
of  press  despatches — is  more  remarkable  than  is  generally  sup- 
posed. The  receiver  has  two  advantages  over  the  sender.  He 
can  receive  mentally  far  faster  than  any  one  can  send ;  and 
with  the  typewriter  he  can  transcribe  much  faster  than  any  one 
can  send.  To  bring  the  sender's  rate  up  to  that  of  the  receiver 
abbreviated  codes  have  been  prepared.  The  receiver  must 
translate  the  code  into  English  words,  and  transcribe  these  cor- 
rectly capitalized  and  punctuated,  upon  the  typewriter.  He 
takes,  in  this  way,  eighty  or  eighty-five  words  a  minute.  If 
mistakes  are  made  by  the  sender,  the  receiver  is  expected  to 
correct  them  as  they  come,  and  send  a  clean  copy  to  press. 
The  work  continues  for  hours  without  leisure  for  re-reading, 
the  pages  being  taken  away  to  press  as  fast  as  they  are  fin- 
ished. Yet,  even  during  the  performance  of  this  astonishing 
feat,  the  operator  is  able  at  will  to  think  about  the  significance 
of  the  despatches  or  to  think  of  anything  else  he  chooses.  An 
Associated  Press  man,  who  has  worked  for  years  in  one  of  our 
large  cities,  said  to  us :  "I  am  in  danger  of  allowing  errors 

could  not  have  been  successful^  carried  on.  Especial  thanks  are  due  to  Messrs. 
H.  E.  Jones,  Assoc.  Press,  Cincinnati;  Lot  Lee,  Assoc.  Press,  Indianapolis; 
Supt.  Miller,  Western  Union,  Cincinnati;  E.  B.  Cassel,  Chief  Despatcher, 
Monon  R.  R.,  Bloomington,  Indiana  ;  and  J.  E.  Sullivan,  Chief  Despatcher, 
Wabash  Railroad,  Peru,  Indiana. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  353 

made  by  the  sender  to  get  into  my  copy,  if  I  let  my  mind 
wander ;  but  the  truth  is  that  in  the  last  weeks,  while  taking 
press,  my  mind  has  been  most  of  the  time  at  home  with  a  sick 
child." 

B.  How  far  can  one  '  copy  behind '  in  different  stages  of 
his  progress? 

It  should  be  explained  that  receiving  is  practically  always 
*  copying  behind.'  That  is,  one  does  not,  or  should  not,  antici- 
pate from  part  of  a  group  of  clicks  what  the  rest  will  be ;  for  if 
one  guesses  wrong,  confusion  of  mind  and  error  are  likely  to  fol- 
low. Beginners  are  prone  to  guess  ahead,  and  must  acquire  the 
habit  of  not  doing  so.  Experts  learn  to  wait.  One  expert 
said,  "  It  is  more  natural  to  read  back."  He  was  asked  if  'read- 
ing back '  was  like  counting  the  strokes  of  a  clock  just  after  it 
is  done  striking.  He  replied,  '  precisely.' 1 

The  answers  to  the  second  question  were  also  concurrent. 
(<z)  The  beginner  must  take  each  letter  as  it  comes,  i.  e.,  he 
can  copy  behind  one  letter.  ($)  Later  he  can  wait  for  words. 
(c)  A  fair  operator  can  copy  behind  several  words  in  connected 
discourse.  (<f)  The  expert  prefers  to  keep  six  to  ten  or  twelve 
words  behind  the  instrument. 

A  count  of  the  number  of  clicks  (dots  and  dashes)  in  ten 
groups  of  ten  words  each,  taken  from  a  press  despatch,  gave 
the  following  result:  220,  275,  172,  214,  189,  267,  303,  260, 
196,  281 ;  average,  237.7.  The  achievement  of  the  telegrapher 
in  keeping  correct  hold  of  so  long  a  series  of  sounds,  and  in 
doing  this  with  a  constantly  changing  series  is,  without  doubt, 
one  of  the  most  remarkable  feats  of  its  kind.  This  is  an  ex- 
ample of  a  skill  not  to  be  reached  by  forced  laboratory  practice, 
but  only  by  years  of  intense  work. 

C.  What  happens  when  you   have  to    receive  the   discon- 
nected words  of  a  strange  code  or  list  of  figures,  such  as  bank 
clearings  or  the  like  ? 

The  universal  experience  of  operators  upon  this  point  was 
expressed  by  one  expert  thus  :  "  When  I  get  a  word  indicating 

1  If,  however,  the  first  words  of  a  very  familiar  phrase  occur,  they  may  be- 
tray even  the  expert  into  anticipating  the  rest  of  the  phrase.  This  fact  is  a 
significant  illustration  of  the  subjective  solidarity  of  phrases.  See  below,  p.  364. 


354  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND   NOBLE  HARTER. 

that  a  list  of  figures  is  to  follow,  I  sweat  blood  until  I  can  catch 
up."  He  said  he  could  wait  for  six  figures  if  they  were  in 
groups  of  three  separated  by  a  comma,  but  if  the  figures  were 
isolated,  he  would  want  to  be  not  more  than  three  or  four  be- 
hind. In  a  word,  he  could  hold  in  mind  forty  to  sixty  or  more 
of  the  elementary  groups  of  the  Morse  code,  if  these  '  made 
sense/  but  only  three  or  four,  if  wholly  disconnected. 

Note  on  the  Reading  of  the  Blind.  To  get  cross  light 
upon  some  of  the  foregoing  points,  information  was  sought 
concerning  the  reading  of  the  blind,  from  Miss  Nellie  Love,  an 
expert  teacher  in  the  Indiana  Institute  for  the  Blind  at  Indian- 
apolis. She  reports  as  follows  : 

"  (i)  Upon  what  is  the  attention  of  the  pupil  fixed  as  he 
reads? 

Upon  first  reading  a  new  selection  : 

(a)  In  a  First  Reader  class  of  twelve  every  one  kept  his 
finger  on  the  letters,  spelling  each  word  either  out  loud  or  to 
himself. 

(b)  In  a  Second  Reader  class  of  eighteen  the   attention  of 
all  but  three  was  upon  the  words.     These  three  read  to  see  what 
the  story  was  about. 

(c)  In  the  Fourth  Reader  class  of  seventeen  the  larger  num- 
ber gave  attention  to  the  words ;  the  others  to  the  thought. 

(d)  In  the  next  grade,  a  class  of  about  the  same  size,  more 
regarded  the  thought,  only  three  or  four  the  words. 

(e)  In  the  highest  grades  the  attention  was  upon  the  thought, 
except  when  the  words  were  unfamiliar. 

"  (2)  How  far  does  the  pupil  read  with  his  finger  ahead  of 
his  voice? 

(a)  In  First  and  Second  Reader  classes,  not  at  all. 

(3)  In  Third  and  Fourth  Reader  classes,  most  pupils  keep 
finger  and  voice  together.  Two  report  the  fingers  one  word 
ahead. 

(c)  In  the  highest  reading  classes  the  majority  keep  finger 
and  voice  together.  Several  read  three  or  four  words  ahead. 
One  pupil,  a  very  bright  boy,  keeps  a  line  ahead,  eight  or  ten 
words.  He  reads  the  end  of  one  line  with  the  finger  of  his 
right  hand  and  at  the  same  time  reads  the  beginning  of  the 
next  line  with  his  left  hand. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  355 

(d)  In  the  advanced  classes,  where  reading  is  not  a  special 
subject,  the  best  pupils  keep  finger  and  voice  together.  In  each 
class  that  studies  reading  as  one  subject,  pupils  who  study  each 
day,  read  and  study  the  lesson,  and  then  are  able  to  read 
smoothly,  rapidly,  and  several  words  ahead  of  the  voice." 

In  all  grades,  sentences  are  read  faster  than  disconnected 
words,  and  disconnected  words  faster  than  disconnected  letters. 
The  rates  are  not  reported.  All  these  results  are  closely  anal- 
ogous to  those  found  among  the  telegraphers.  Of  course  there 
are  no  blind  children  who  have  attained  a  proficiency  cor- 
responding to  that  of  the  expert  telegrapher. 

III. 

CONCLUSIONS. 

The  immediate  conclusions  from  the  foregoing  data  will  be 
given  first;  later  (under  IV.),  an  interpretation  and  discussion 
of  these  conclusions  in  connection  with  related  literature. 

i.     A  Hierarchy  of  Habits. 

One  might  perhaps  suppose  that  receiving  telegraphic  mes- 
sages is  simply  transliteration  or,  at  most,  transverbalization  from 
the  code  into  the  mother  tongue.  The  operators  reject  this 
view.  The  evidence  before  us  proves  that  they  are  right  in 
doing  so.  Neither  the  letter  curve  nor  the  word  curve  nor  both 
together,  account  for  the  receiving  curve1  except  for  a  short 
period  (see  Figure  XL).  Most  plainly,  the  letter  and  word 
curves  fail  to  account  for  the  receiving  curve  where  it  rises 
rapidly  from  the  plateau,  while  they  continue  their  slight  ascent. 
From  an  early  stage  some  curve  or  curves  associated  with  the 
combination  of  words  in  connected  discourse  must  coalesce 
wdth  the  letter  and  word  curves  to  give  as  a  resultant  the  receiv- 
ing curve.  At  the  period  when  the  resultant  curve  is  rising 
rapidly,  while  the  letter  and  word  curves  are  rising  slowly,  the 
higher  constituent  curve  (or  curves)  must  be  rising  rapidly. 

What  does  this  higher  constituent  curve  represent  in  the 

1  The  connected  discourse  curve  in  Figure  XI.  will  be  spoken  of  as  the  re- 
ceiving curve  ;  its  constituent  curves,  as  letter  and  word  curves  respectively. 


356  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

learner?  Certainly  not  merely  nor  mainly  increased  familiarity 
with  the  meaning,  structure  or  logical  connection  of  sentences 
in  the  mother  tongue.  When,  for  example,  the  learner  has 
rapidly  shot  up  from  a  rate  of  eighteen  to  a  rate  of  twenty-five 
words  per  minute,  no  one  can  believe  that  he  has  made  this  gain 
because  of  a  sudden  and  enormous  gain  in  knowledge  of  the 
language  he  has  used  all  his  life.  All  the  facts  point  to  the 
conclusion  that  the  telegrapher  must  acquire,  besides  letter, 
syllable,  and  word  habits,  an  array  of  higher  language  habits, 
associated  with  the  combination  of  words  in  connected  dis- 
course. Mastery  of  the  telegraphic  language  involves  mastery 
of  the  habits  of  all  orders.  In  a  word,  learning  to  receive  the 
telegraphic  language  consists  in  acquiring  a  hierarchy  of 
psycho-physical  habits.  For  a  discussion  of  this  conclusion  in 
connection  with  related  literature  see  below,  under  IV.,  p.  360. 

2.      The  Order  of  Learning  the  Habits  of  the  Telegraphic 

Language. 

The  synchronous  curves  of  Table  XI.  and  the  experience  of 
operators  agree  in  showing  that  from  an  early  period  letter, 
word  and  higher  habits  make  gains  (a)  simultaneously,  but  (b) 
not  equally. 

(a)  The  simultaneity  in  these  gains  is  shown  in  Fig.  XI.  by 
the  fact  that  from  the  point  where  the  curves  diverge,  each  con- 
tinues to  rise.  This  is  perhaps  to  be  explained  by  the  fact  that 
from  an  early  stage  the  learner  practises  with  sentences,  taking 
them  as  slowly  as  necessary.  In  this  way  there  is  incidental 
practice  of  every  language  unit  and  of  every  language  unit  in 
its  proper  setting. 

(#)  The  curves  of  Figure  XI.  show  also,  however,  that  for 
many  months  the  chief  gain  is  in  the  letter  and  word  habits, 
that  the  rate  of  receiving  sentences  is,  in  this  period,  mainly  de- 
termined by  the  rate  of  receiving  letters  and  words,  and  that 
rapid  gain  in  the  higher  language  habits  does  not  begin  until 
letter  and  word  habits  are  well  fixed.  This  objective  result  is 
supported  by  the  introspective  evidence  of  operators.  In  the 
first  days  one  is  forced  to  attend  to  letters.  In  the  first 
months  one  is  forced  to  attend  to  words.  If  the  learner  es- 


THE   TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  357 

says  a  freedom  for  which  he  is  unfit,  suddenly  a  letter  or  word 
which  is  unfamiliar  explodes  in  his  ears  and  leaves  him  wrecked. 
He  has  no  useful  freedom  for  higher  language  units  which  he 
has  not  earned  by  making  the  lower  ones  automatic.  The  rank 
and  file  of  operators  are  slaves  to  the  machinery  of  the  tele- 
graphic language.  They  must  copy  close.  They  cannot  at- 
tend much  to  the  sense  of  the  message  as  it  comes,  but  must  get 
its  form,  and  re-read  for  the  sense.  Only  when  all  the  neces- 
sary habits,  high  and  low,  have  become  automatic,  does  one 
rise  into  the  freedom  and  speed  of  the  expert. 

3.    The  Plateaus. 

We  are  now  prepared  to  offer  an  explanation  for  the  salient 
peculiarity  of  the  receiving  curve, — its  plateaus. 

A  plateau  in  the  curve  means  that  the  lower-order  habits 
are  approaching  their  maximum  development :,  but  are  not  yet 
sufficiently  automatic  to  leave  the  attention  free  to  attack  the 
higher-order  habits.  The  length  of  the  plateau  is  a  measure  oj 
the  difficulty  of  making  the  lower-order  habits  sufficiently  auto- 
matic. 

(a)  The  first  ascent.     No  plateau  appears  between  the  learn- 
ing of  letters  and  of  words,  because  very  soon  these  are  learned 
simultaneously.     However,  as  the  letters  are  few,  one  is  each 
week  able  to  give  more  complete  attention  to  the  mastery  of  syl- 
ables  and  words  as  wholes.     This  perhaps  accounts,  in  part,  for 
the  rapid  progress  of  the  first  weeks. 

(b]  The  first  plateau.     For  several  months  the  learner  is 
compelled  to  attend  almost  exclusively  to  words.     The  number 
of  words  which  he  has  to  learn  in  order  to  receive  whatever 
messages    come,   is   great.     The    average  amount  of   practice 
which  each  word  receives  is  therefore  small,  and  the  increase 
in  the  average  rate  of  receiving  correspondingly  slow.     This 
very  slow  increase  of  rate  we  have  called  a  plateau.     It  contin- 
ues until   the   learner  has  the  necessary   vocabulary   so    well 
learned  that  he  can  have  his  attention  free  for  something  else. 

Another  retarding  influence  during  this  period  is  doubtless 
the  learner's  slight  hold  upon  the  higher  language  habits.  The 
importance  of  this  retarding  influence  in  comparison  with  that 


358  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

of  an  imperfect  vocabulary,  can  not  be  determined  without  ad- 
ditional investigation. 

(c)  The  second  ascent  represents  the  acquisition  of  a  new  set 
of  language  habits.     This  is  a  priori  probable  from  the  con- 
sideration that  in  practice  curves  generally  rapid  progress  ap- 
pears when  the  developing  function  is  in  an  early  stage.     We 
are  not,  however,  left  with  a  probability.     While  the  receiving 
curve  is  rising  rapidly  the  synchronous  word  and  letter  curves 
are  continuing  their  ascent  slowly.     We,  therefore,  know  that 
the  learner  is  gaining  speed  by  taking  in  some  way  increasing 
advantage  of  word  combinations.     Part  of  the  reason  why  he 
improves  so  fast  is,  doubtless,  that  he  has  already  been  uncon- 
sciously  habituated   for   certain  phrases    and   forms    of   word 
combination  in  the   period  when  he  was  attending  mainly  to 
words.     It  may  be  that  the  rapid  ascent  of  any  -practice  curve 
represents    mainly  a  quick  realization   of  powers  potentially 
present  by  reason  of  preceding  gradual  and  unconscious  habitu- 
ation.      With  the  increased  ability  in   taking  sentences  there 
comes,  without  doubt,  increased  ability  to  take  isolated  words 
and  letters ;  but,  as  one  improves,  the  three  curves  diverge  more 
and  more.      This  means  that  skill  depends  more  and  more  upon 
the  acquisition  of  higher  language  habits. 

(d)  Only  the  first  few  months  of  the  period  during  which 
one  is  a  practical  operator,  but  not  an  expert,  have  been  inves- 
tigated experimentally.     Our   knowledge  of  this  period  rests 
mainly  upon  the  testimony  of  operators.     Men  of  this  rank,  of 
course,  vary  widely  in  skill  and  in  rate  of  improvement.     There 
is,  however,  one  essential  point  in  which  operators  who  are  not 
experts  are  more  or  less  alike.     They  are  all,  in  some  degree, 
tied  to  the  mechanism  of  the  language.     They  cannot  copy  far 
behind.     The  mind  must  not  wander  far  from  the  incoming 
stream  of  words,  even  to  dwell  upon  the  sense  of  the  words. 
Few  operators  ever  obtain  complete  freedom  in  the  telegraphic 
language.     These  few  must  earn  their  freedom  by  many  years 
of  hard  apprenticeship.     Our  evidence  is  that  it  requires  ten 
years  to  make  a  thoroughly  seasoned  press  despatcher.1 

1  We  have  shown  above  that  receiving  is  not  translating  either  letter  by 
letter  or  word  by  word  into  the  mother  tongue,  but  involves  the  use  of  a  great 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE,  359 

(e)  The  final  ascent.  The  testimony  of  experts  is  that  the 
ascent  from  drudgery  into  freedom  is  as  sudden  as  was  the  as- 
scent  from  the  first  plateau. 

Note  on  the  Sending  Curve. 

Why  does  the  sending  curve  have  no  such  succession  of 
plateau  and  ascent  as  appears  in  the  receiving  curve  ? 

There  is  no  plateau  in  the  sending  curve  in  the  earlier  part  of 
its  course,  because,  as  in  the  early  part  of  the  receiving  curve, 
the  various  habits  involved  are  acquired  simultaneously  (com- 
pare page  357),  and  there  is  no  sharp  ascent  later,  even  when 
one  becomes  an  expert,  because  such  an  ascent  is  mechanically 
impossible.  At  all  stages  one  has  in  mind  plenty  of  words 
ready  to  be  sent  as  fast  as  the  motor  habits  will  permit.  At  first 
one  is  learning  motor  letter  habits.  Soon,  however,  also  motor 
word  habits.  The  sending  curve  rises  accordingly  in  a  fashion 
analogous  to  that  of  the  receiving  curve  in  its  early  stage.  By 
and  by,  however,  a  mechanical  limit  is  reached.  Sending  is, 
at  the  best,  a  slow  business.  A  letter  or  digit  requires  from 
one  to  six  strokes.  Spaces  of  various  length  must  be  allowed 
for.  One  cannot  utilize  both  hands  and  several  fingers,  as  with 
a  typewriter.  So,  at  less  than  fifty  words  a  minute,  a  maximum 
has  been  reached  that  cannot  be  surpassed. 

4.  Effective  Speed  and  Accuracy. 

(a)  Effective  Speed. 

It  has  long  been  known  that  connected  words  can  be  read 
faster  than  disconnected,  and  letters  combined  in  words  faster 
than  disconnected  letters.1  The  facts  upon  this  point,  old  and 
new,  justify,  we  believe,  the  following  conclusion :  Effective 

array  of  higher  language  habits— that  telegraphy  is  psychologically  a  distinct 
language,  almost  or  quite  as  elaborate  as  the  mother  tongue.  This  view  is  sup- 
ported by  the  fact  that  so  long  a  time  and  such  intense  labor  are  required  for  the 
mastery  of  telegraphy — an  amount  of  time  and  labor  which  would,  without 
doubt,  make  the  same  men  equally  expert  in  any  foreign  language. 

1  We  dissent,  however,  from  the  view  that  it  is  only  or  mainly  the  logical  con- 
nection in  sentences  which  accounts  for  the  rapid  rate  in  reading  them.  We 
believe  (p.  366)  that  there^are  mechanical  habits  corresponding  to  often  recurring 
peculiarities  of  sentences.  This  is  shown  by  the  fact  that  a  series  of  words 
making  no  sense,  if  skillfully  arranged  in  familiar  sentence  forms,  can  be  read 
far  faster  than  a  series  of  .words  taken  at  random,  and  almost  as  fast  as  words 
making  sense.  Almost,  but  not  quite.  A  consciousness  of  the  sense  appears  to 
be  still  one  factor  in  the  affair. 


360  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND   NOBLE   HARTER. 

speed  depends,  in  a  relatively  small  degree,  upon  the  rate  at 
'which  the  processes  dominant  in  consciousness  occur;  in  a  rela- 
tively great  degree,  upon  how  muck  t's  included  in  each  of  those 
processes.  For  further  discussion  see  below,  under  IV. ,  4.  p.  374. 

(#)  Effective  Speed  and  Accuracy. 

The  gain  in  speed  made  possible  by  adding  mastery  of  the 
higher  language  habits  to  mastery  of  the  lower,  does  not  lead  to 
less,  but  to  greater  accuracy  in  detail.  We  have  found  invaria- 
bly that  many  more  mistakes  are  made  in  receiving  discon- 
nected letters  than  in  receiving,  at  a  much  more  rapid  rate, 
letters  that  form  words ;  and  that,  in  turn,  many  more  mistakes 
are  made  in  receiving  disconnected  words  than  in  receiving,  at 
a  still  rapider  rate,  connected  discourse.  The  practical  experi- 
ence of  the  telegraph  companies  proves  the  same.  Although 
mastery  of  the  higher  order  habits  thus  helps  the  receiver  to  ac- 
curacy in  details,  it  cannot  supply  his  ignorance  of  details.  If 
a  word  not  in  his  vocabulary  comes  as  part  of  a  dispatch,  he  is 
very  likely  to  get  it  wrong.  If  he  is  often  found  making  errors 
of  this  sort,  it  is  proof  that  he  needs  a  more  extensive  and  accu- 
rate telegraphic  vocabulary.  Such  a  man  is  trying  to  receive 
faster  than  he  can.  He  is  trying  to  gain  speed  at  the  expense 
of  accuracy.  This  is  not  effective  speed,  as  his  superiors  will 
quickly  let  him  discover.  For  further  discussion  see  below, 
IV.,  4.  p.  374. 

IV. 

DISCUSSION. 

In  the  foregoing,  we  have  given  little  more  than  a  bare  state- 
ment of  results.  In  the  discussion  of  these  results,  we  desire,  first 
of  all,  to  give  the  plain  meaning  of  the  facts  known  to  us.  We 
shall,  however,  use  entire  freedom  in  suggesting  a  wider  circle 
of  interpretations  for  which  the  evidence  is  not  made  out.  We 
have,  however,  no  interest  in  any  theory  suggested,  except  to  see 
it  tried  by  facts  and  assigned  its  proper  measure  of  probability. 

i.  A.  Hierarchy  of  Habits. 

A  man  is  organized  in  spots — or  rather  in  some  spots  far 
more  than  in  others.  This  is  true  structurally  and  functionally. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  361 

It  is  strikingly  true  of  the  various  sense  organs  and  their  func- 
tions. No  less  of  the  various  parts  of  the  central  nervous  system 
and  their  functions.  A  man  has  some  habits  which  are  spo- 
radic and  isolated,  some  which  are  bunched  together  in  loose 
groups  (such  as  the  outlay  of  skills  which  make  one  a  carpenter), 
and  then,  some  habits  which  are  knit  together  into  a  hierarchy. 

A  hierarchy  of  habits  may  be  described  in  this  way:  (i) 
There  are  a  certain  number  of  habits  which  are  elementary  con- 
stitutents  of  all  the  other  habits  within  the  hierarchy.  (2) 
There  are  habits  of  a  higher  order  which,  embracing  the  lower 
as  elements,  are  themselves  in  turn  elements  of  higher  habits,  and 
so  on.  (3)  A  habit  of  any  order,  when  thoroughly  acquired,  has 
physiological  and,  if  conscious,  psychological  unity.  The 
habits  of  lower  order  which  are  its  elements  tend  to  lose  them- 
selves in  it,  and  it  tends  to  lose  itself  in  habits  of  higher  order 
when  it  appears  as  an  element  therein. 

There  is  reason  to  believe  that  proficiency  in  chess,  geometry, 
chemistry  and  the  like,  involves  in  each  case  the  mastery  of 
habits  which  are  associated  in  some  such  hierarchical  fashion. 
Leaving  these  slightly  investigated  fields,  however,  we  turn 
to  that  of  language.  The  proposition  that  a  language  exists 
subjectively  as  a  hierarchy  of  habits,  is  supported  by  a  consid- 
erable amount  of  evidence  scattered  through  recent  psycho- 
logical literature.  This  proposition  is  by  no  means  identical 
with  the  obvious  truth  that  a  language  is,  objectively  consid- 
ered, a  system  composed  of  various  units — letters,  words,  sen- 
tences, etc.  The  existence  of  the  objective  system  is  evident  to 
all  who  know  the  language ;  the  existence  of  a  corresponding 
system  of  subjective  habits  demands  proof.  Is  there,  for  ex- 
ample, a  psycho-physically  unitary  habit  corresponding  to  a 
familiar  word,  or  does  the  recognition  of  a  word  involve  the 
separate  recognition  of  each  letter?  The  latter  view  has  been 
held.  It  requires  convincing  evidence  from  experimental  psy- 
chology and  psychiatry  to  prove  that  the  recognition  of  a  word 
is  '  eine  gesonderte  Funktion.'  In  like  manner  it  will  require 
evidence  not  yet  fully  forthcoming,  to  show  what  higher  lan- 
guage units  and  what  characteristics  of  spoken  and  written 
language  (e.  g.,  cadence,  sentence-length,  etc.)  are  rep- 
resented subjectively  by  distinct  habits. 


362  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

(a)  Letters. — A  letter  (printed  or  telegraphic)  presents  to 
sense  a  manifold.  Recognition  of  the  letter  and  recognition  of  its 
elements  are  distinct  functions.  One  may  recognize  the  dash  and 
the  dot  of  the  telegraphic  code  after  a  little  practice,  and  may 
know  that  J  =  — .  — .  ,  without  being  able  to  recognize  that 
group  of  clicks  when  heard.  To  recognize  the  group  as  a 
whole  with  maximum  rapidity  requires  weeks  of  practice.  On 
the  other  hand,  one  may  recognize  a  letter  as  a  whole — for  ex- 
ample, in  Old  English  type — but  be  wholly  unable  to  reproduce 
in  memory  the  essential  parts  of  which  it  is  composed.1 

(£)  Syllables. — Hopfner,  in  his  study  *  Ueber  die  geistige 
Ermiidung  von  Schulkindern,' 2  finding  that  word  errors  are 
more  frequent  than  syllable  errors,  and  that  letter  errors  are 
more  frequent  than  errors  as  to  parts  of  letters,  remarks  :  "  Silben 
sind  im  Wort  und  Buchstabenteile  im  Buchstaben  fester  gefiigt 
als  Worter  im  Satz  und  als  Buchstaben  im  Wort.  Worter  und 
Buchstaben  sind  also  '  sebstandigere '  Elemente." 

This  observation  is  doubtless  correct.  Syllables  are,  how- 
ever, sufficiently  *  independent '  to  make  it  worth  while  for 
primary  teachers  to  use  the  child's  stock  of  known  syllables  in 
teaching  new  words.  Mr.  Harter  is  of  the  opinion  that  a 
learner  of  telegraphy  pays  little  direct  attention  to  the  syllables 
as  such,  but  is  really  helped  in  the  hearing  of  new  words  by 
the  presence  of  familiar  syllables. 

(c)  Words. — A  child  or  one  suffering  partial  aphasia,  may 
recognize  the  letters  of  a  word,  but  not  the  word  as  a  whole.  See, 
for  example,  the  case  reported  by  R.  Sommer,3  who  concludes  : 
"Die  Verbindung  von  Lautreihen  zu  Worter  ist  eine  gesonderte 
Funktion.  Ein  <  Wort'  ist  schon  deshalb  nicht  als  *  Lautreihe ' 
zu  betrachten."  On  the  other  hand,  children  are  frequently 
taught  to  recognize  words  as  wholes  before  they  know  the  let- 
ters of  the  alphabet.  Decisive  proof  that  the  recognition  of  a 
word  does  not  consist  in  the  successive  recognition  of  its  letters, 
is  afforded  by  CattelPs  result 4  that  a  familiar  word  can  be  re- 

1See  Goldscheider  and  Miiller,  Zur  Physiologic  und  Pathologic  des  Lesens. 
Zeitschtift  f.  klin.  Med.,  Bd.,  XXIII.,  s.  131-167  (1893).  Reviewed  by  Wai- 
laschek  in  Zeitschtift  f.  Phys.  und  Psych,  d.  Sinnesorgane,  VII.,  228. 

2  Zeitschriftf.  P.  und  P.  d.  Sinnesorgane,  VI.,  217. 

3  Zeitschrift f.  P.  und  P.  d.  Sinnesorgane,  V.,  318. 
»'  «/%//.  Stud.,  II.,  647;  III.,  470. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  363 

cognized  in  almost  the  same  time  that  it  takes  to  recognize  one 
of  its  letters.  This  abundantly  verified  result  one  of  the  writers 
has  found  true  of  many  children  who  are  in  their  second  school 
year. 

Analogous  facts  appear  on  the  motor  side.  One  may  be 
able  to  produce  the  separate  sounds  of  a  foreign  language  with 
considerable  accuracy,  as  Karsten  points  out,1  and  still  may  not 
be  able,  without  additional  practice,  to  pronounce  words.  On 
the  other  hand,  we  pronounce  the  words  of  our  own  language 
with  ease,  but  require  special  practice  to  produce  the  elementary 
sounds  composing  them.  Karsten  puts  the  matter  thus  : 

(3)  Nach  dem  oben  gesagten  wird  man  nicht  einwenden  wollen, 
dass,  wer  das  bewegungsgefiihl  fur  das  ganze  hat,  auch  das  fur  die 
einzelnen  theile  besitze  und  umgekehrt.  Durch  das  erinnerungsbild 
ist  eine  bewegung  von  anfang  bis  ende  abgegrenzt,  dauer  und  art  der 
mitwirkung  aller  in  betracht  kommenden  organe  fest  bestimmt.  Zwar 
konnen  wir  eine  bewegung  absichtlich  an  irgend  einem  puncte  ab- 
brechen,  aber  diese  abgebrochene  bewegung  ist  dann  eben  nicht  mehr 
dieselbe,  sondern  eine  andere,  welche  bei  geniigender  wiederholung 
ihr  eigenes  erinnerungsbild  entwickelt.  Die  bewegungen  des  arztes 
beim  operieren,  des  rnalers,  des  musikers  sind  mechanisch  und  raum- 
lich  alle  enthalten  in  den  einem  jeden  von  uns  gelaufigen  bewegungen  ; 
doch  gehort  iibung,  das  heisst  ausbildung  der  bewegungsgefiihle  dazu, 
um  gerade  eine  bestimmte  bewegung  genau  auszufiihren.  Auch 
kann  man  eine  bewegung,  die  man  z.  b.  mit  fiinf  fingern  leicht  macht, 
nicht  sof ort  mit  einem  oder  zwei  fingern  nachahmen ;  das  ware  zwar 
ein  theil  der  friiheren,  aber  doch  auch  eine  bewegung  fiir  sich,  fur  die 
das  bewegungsgefiihl  erst  eigens  entwickelt  werden  muss. — Kurz  das 
bewegungsgefiihl  kann  etwas  einheitliches  sein,  auch  wenn  die  wirk- 
liche  bewegung  compliciert  ist,  und  einheitliche  bewegungsgefiihle  fiir 
grossere  lautgruppen  konnen  in  der  seele  sich  bilden  getrennt  von 
denen  fiir  die  einzelnen  theile,  aus  welchen  jene  gruppen  bestehen. 

(d)  Word  groups.  As  certain  letters  often  appearing  in  the 
same  order  give  rise  to  a  unitary  word  habit,  so  several  words 
often  appearing  in  the  same  order  give  rise  to  a  phrase  habit. 
Such  word  groups  sometimes  come  to  have  a  unity  almost  equal 

1  Sprecheinheiten  ii  d.  Rolle  in  Lautwandel  ii  Lautgesetz;  Proceedings 
Mod.  Lang.  Assoc.,  Vol.  III.,  1887,  p.  3. 


364  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

to  that  of  single  words.  As  a  rule,  doubtless,  the  fusion  is  not  so 
close ;  that  is,  we  pass  more  easily  than  in  the  case  of  words 
from  the  consciousness  of  the  whole  to  the  consciousness  of  the 
parts.  Nevertheless,  the  tendency  of  the  first  part  of  a  familiar 
phrase  to  suggest  the  rest,1  and  the  fact  that  everyone  has  not  only 
a  characteristic  vocabulary,  but  a  characteristic  outlay  of  word 
groups,  show  that  phrases  exist  .subjectively  as  unitary  habits. 
Furthermore,  it  has  been  shown  that  one  who  reads  a  language 
with  a  certain  skill  is  liable  to  make  phrase  errors  as  distinct 
from  letter  or  word  errors.2 

Paul3  points  out  that  we  have  many  word  groups  (e.  g.,  auf 
der  Hand  liegen)  in  which  a  word  has  ceased  to  be  associated 
with  its  ordinary  meaning,  in  some  cases  (e.  g.,  das  Bad  austra- 
gen)  so  completely  that  it  requires  a  knowledge  of  the  history 
of  language  to  explain  the  connection  between  the  meaning  of 
the  phrase  and  that  of  the  individual  word.  In  such  cases,  the 
language  unit  dominant  in  consciousness  is  evidently  the  phrase 
and  not  the  word.4 

(e)  Habits  Corresponding  to  Characteristics  of  Words, 
Phrases,  etc.  The  language  habits  so  far  noted  are  specific 
i.  e.,  in  each  case  a  specific  stimulus  (letters,  syllable,  word 
or  group  of  words)  leads  to  a  specific  reaction.  It  is,  how- 
ever, a  fact  of  the  highest  importance  that  one's  stock  of  specific 
habits  contains  the  material  for  innumerable  other  specific  habits 
(and  also,  some  hold,  for  *  generic'  or  '  plastic'  habits).  When 
one  has  learned  bat,  cat,  many,  model,  one  has  four  specific 
habits ;  but  one  is  within  two  steps  (which  may  be  taken  in  a 
breath  or  only  after  deliberate  pains)  of  a  new  habit  corre- 
sponding to  mat.  The  first  step  is  dissociation  (in  the  manner 
described  by  Martineau  and  James5)  of  the  at  from  the  first 
two  words,  and  of  the  m  from  the  second  two  ;  the  second  step 
is  the  fusion  of  these  dissociated  habits,  when  they  appear  in 
the  order  m-  at,  into  one  new  specific  unitary  habit  correspond- 

1  See  case  mentioned  above,  p.  353. 

2  Cf .  Berger  :  Ueber  den  Einfluss  der  Uebung  auf  geistige  Vorgange,  Phil* 
Stud.,  V.,  175. 

3Principien  der  Sprachgeschichte,  2  Aufl.,  83. 
4Cf.  Cattell,  Mind,  XL,  64. 
5 James,  Psychol.,  L,  484. 


THE   TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  365 

ing  to  mat.  (There  is  something  arbitrary  in  the  designation 
of  two  steps  in  the  making  of  a  new  habit  out  of  old  ones. 
To  ordinary  introspection  the  process  seems  to  have  many  steps 
when  it  occurs  slowly  and  painfully,  and  only  one  step  when  it 
occurs  in  a  flash,  as  when  we  recognize  and  adopt  in  an  instant 
a  new  slang  word — mugwump,  popocrat.  The  words  dissocia- 
tion and  fusion  only  designate  and  emphasize  two  essential 
phases  of  the  whole  process  which  ends  in  a  new  habit.) 

In  like  manner,  one's  acquisition  of  these  four  words  is  par- 
tial preparation  for  met,  bet,  cad,  and  also  for  bonnet,  calico, 
and  for  every  word  containing  any  syllable  or  letter  learned. 
Further,  the  trochaic  rhythm  of  many  and  model  may  become 
dissociated  from  these  words,  and  may  reappear  as  an  aid  in 
learning  other  trochaic  words.1 

In  the  same  manner,  any  element  or  characteristic  of  a 
word  group  habit  may  become  serviceable  in  the  learning  of 
new  groups.  Doubtless,  the  primary  effect  of  using  a  given 
word  group  is  to  establish  a  quite  specific  habit.  One  can  re- 
read a  sentence  more  quickly  than  one  can  read  a  new  sentence 
containing  the  same  words  in  a  different  order.  One  can  even 
re-read  a  sentence  more  quickly  if  one  follows  the  rhythm  first 
used.  The  dissociation  of  language  elements  from  the  specific 
wholes  in  which  they  have  occurred,  and  their  use  in  the  con- 
struction or  understanding  of  new  sentences,  are  a  task — perhaps 
the  most  remarkable  task  of  which  men  are  capable.  The 
stupider  or  lazier  one  is,  the  less  one  has  inclination  or  power 
for  this  task.  i3ut  even  the  stupidest  and  laziest  man  meets, 
with  some  measure  of  success,  the  conversational  emergencies 
that  confront  him.  From  his  small  language  capital,  there  rise 
substantially  the  right  nouns,  verbs,  phrases,  but's,  ifs,  not's,  and 
even  the  right  inflections  to  denote  the  attitude  and  temper  of 
his  mind ;  and  these  elements  fall  together  with  amazing  swift- 
ness into  sentences  never  before  used  by  him.  One  who  has 
genius  for  expression  differs  from  the  dullard  in  having  a 
larger  language  capital,  greater  facility  in  dissociating  the  ele- 
ments and  characteristics,  and  greater  facility  in  making  new 
combinations.  Until  we  have  had  a  great  deal  more  research 

1  Miiller  und  Schumann,  Zeitsch.f.  Psych,  u.  Phys.  d.  Sinnesorgane?J\. ,  28of. 


366  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

in  regard  to  the  higher  language  habits,  conclusions  in  respect 
to  them  must  be  proposed  with  reserve.  At  present  the  follow- 
ing points  seem  probable : 

(a)  It  is  well  known  that  the  average  length  of  sentence  is 
characteristic  for  a  given  author.  In  most  cases,  perhaps,  the 
author  is  unconscious  of  his  sentence-length  habit. 

(3)  A  rhythm  often  used  probably  becomes  habitual,  apart 
from  any  particular  words,  and  is  then  an  aid  in  reading  and  a 
factor  in  making  new  phrases,  sentences,  and  paragraphs,  hav- 
ing that  rhythm. 

(c)  A  certain  order  of  the  parts  of  speech  (e.  g.>  *  he  walked 
out  of  the  way,'  or  *  out  of  the  way  walked  he  ')  often  recurring 
becomes  habitual,   determines  the  making  of  new  sentences, 
gives  us  a  sense  of  ease  in  reading  straightforward  prose,  and 
a  sense  of  shock  at  sentences  like  Browning's  *  Irks  care  the 
crop-full  bird?     Frets  doubt  the  maw-crammed  beast?' — even 
when,  as  in  this  case,  the  words  are  all  familiar. 

(d)  A  grammatical  construction  often  used  to  express  a  cer- 
tain feeling  (of  plurality,  futurity,  doubt  or  the  like)  comes  to 
be  automatically  associated  with 'that  feeling,  apart  from  any  par- 
ticular sentence,  so  that  either  instantly  and  effortlessly  sug- 
gests the  other,  to  serve  as  one  of  many  elements  in  the  reading 
or  making  of  a  new  sentence.1 

In  like  manner  we  may  suppose  that  every  peculiarity  of 
style  up  to  the  structure  and  tone  of  a  volume,  corresponds  to  a 
more  or  less  perfectly  fixed  habit.  An  E.  P.  Roeish  novel  be- 
trays in  its  author  a  habit  on  its  way  to  becoming  as  specific  as 
sneezing. 

Note  on  the  development  of  new  habits  out  of  old  ones. 
The  old  theory  that  doing  particular  things  gives  'general  train- 
ing' of  body  and  mind  is  nowadays  confronted  with  the  view 
that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  'general  training'.  The  two  views 
are  perhaps  not  so  irreconcilable  as  they  appear  to  be  in  current 
psychological  and  educational  discussions.  The  chief  subjec- 
tive effect  of  an  act  is  doubtless  its  tendency  to  establish  the 
habit  of  repeating  that  act ;  and,  conversely,  the  best  way  to 

1  For  the  discussion  of  the  point  whether  grammatical  habits  are  specific  or 
plastic,  see  below. 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  367 

acquire  skill  in  a  particular  act  is  to  practise  that,  and  not  some- 
thing else.  But  every  bodily  or  mental  process  involved  in  an 
act  is  practised,  and  through  dissociation  and  reassociation  may 
appear  in  innumerable  other  actions.  In  the  case  mentioned 
above  (p.  364),  the  *  fringes'  of  emotion  and  intention  when  the 
four  words  were  learned  tend  to  [reappear  upon  repetition  of 
these  words  ;  but  may  also,  because  of  their  exercise  then,  come 
up  to  reinforce  the  set  of  mind  in  a  subsequent  attack  upon  the 
multiplication  table  or  the  woodpile.  When  a  boy  drives  the 
last  nail  in  a  fence  as  carefully  as  the  first  he  is  not  thereby 
made  ready  to  build  a  house,  nor  to  codify  the  law  of  the  com- 
monwealth, nor  to  do  anything  else  in  the  world  so  well  as  to 
drive  nails  into  that  fence ;  but  his  skill  in  nail  driving  will  re- 
appear when  he  undertakes  carpentry  ;  and  the  set  of  mind  with 
which  he  drove  them  will  reappear  when  he  is  a  lawyer.  We 
may  deny  that  Grant's  study  of  algebra  gave  him  a  general 
training  of  the  mind  that  prepared  him  for  the  Wilderness,  or 
for  anything  else  so  well  as  for  that  algebra,  and  nevertheless 
see  that  the  mood  of  his  hours  with  the  algebra  came  up  in  his 
4  We'll  fight  it  out  on  this  line  if  it  takes  all  summer.' 

Professor  Royce  suggests1  that  besides  specific  habits  one 
acquires  generic  or  plastic  habits,  which  lead  not  to  a  specific 
reaction  upon  a  specific  stimulus,  but  to  a  certain  sort  of  reac- 
tion upon  a  certain  sort  of  stimulus.  He  mentions  especially 
the  habits  corresponding  to  the  rules  of  syntax  as  in  this  sense 
generic.  This  view  is  attractive,  and  may  be  true.  It  may  be, 
however,  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  plastic  or  generic 
habit,  except  in  the  sense  that  a  habit  may  enter  as  an  element 
into  many  different  processes.  Whether  or  not  there  are  generic 
habits  involved  in  the  origination  of  higher  mental  processes,  we 
believe  that  all  habits  tend  to  become  in  the  same  sense  specific. 

2.  The  Order  of  Acquiring  Habits  which  Constitute  a 

Hierarchy. 

Every  one  knows  that,  in  general,  habituation  in  certain  ac- 
tions leaves  us  free  for  others.  This  principle  is,  however 
empty  and  useless  in  a  given  field  until  we  know  what  habits 

1  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  V.,  118;  Educational  Review,  VI.,  212. 


368  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND   NOBLE   HARTER. 

are  to  be  learned  there,  and  which  of  these  must  be  learned 
first,  which  second,  etc.  It  is  highly  probable  that  in  geometry, 
chemistry  or  whist  one  must  acquire  a  hierarchy  of  habits  ;  that 
some  of  these  habits  should  be  learned  before  others ;  and  that 
some  of  them  may  with  advantage  be  acquired  simultaneously. 
Perhaps  the  most  expert  men  have  already  felt  their  way  to  the 
right  methods  ;  but  psychology  and  pedagogy  would  be  greatly 
enriched  by  explicit  and  verifiable  knowledge  upon  these  points. 
Such  knowledge  the  general  principle  stated  above  is  impo- 
tent to  give.  It  can  only  tell  the  student  to  do  first  things  first. 
To  discover  what  things  are  first  in  any  particular  field  requires 
painstaking  investigation,  or  a  consensus  of  the  practical  experi- 
ences and  intuitions  of  those  who  work  in  that  field,  or  both. 
Though  no  one  can  foresee  the  results  of  such  investigations  in 
any  particular  case,  there  will  be  idlers  in  the  psychological 
market  place,  when  the  results  appear,  ready  to  say  :  "  Nothing 
new.  We  have  known  all  along  that  some  things  must  be 
done  before  others." 

In  point  of  fact,  teachers  of  reading  are  not  agreed  as  to 
the  best  order  of  studying  the  various  language  units.  The 
older  custom  was  to  learn  first  the  letters,  then  many  syllables, 
then  many  words,  and  then  at  last  to  read  sentences.  In  details 
this  method  varied  widely ;  but  its  essential  principle  was  to 
master  lower  units  first  and  use  these  in  picking  out  the  higher. 
The  newer  custom  is  based  upon  an  opposite  principle.  In  the 
*  word-method  '  the  pupil  is  taught  a  word  as  a  whole  before  he 
knows  any  letter.  In  the  '  sentence-method  '  the  pupil  is  con- 
fronted with  a  short  sentence  before  he  knows  any  word  or  let- 
ter. In  the  later  methods  the  subsidiary  language  units  are  to 
be  learned  incidentally,  while  the  main  attention  is  given  to  the 
higher  language  units  and  to  the  sense. 

It  is  proved  possible  to  learn  to  read  by  the  older  or  the 
newer  methods,  and,  indeed,  by  any  method  which  brings  the 
pupil  for  a  long  enough  time  into  contact  with  print.  The  mind 
will  find  a  method  of  its  own.  We  believe,  however,  (i)  that  by 
no  device  is  it  possible  to  gain  freedom  in  using  the  higher  lan- 
guage tinits  until  the  lower  have  been  so  mastered  that  the 
attention  is  not  diverted  by  them;  and  (2)  that  it  is,  never  the- 


THE   TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  369 

)  wise  at  all  stages  to  -practise  with  the  highest  language  units 
possible,  and  thus  learn  all  the  units  in  their  -proper  setting. 

The  alphabet-spelling-book  method  makes  sure  of  the  first 
requirement,  but  is  grossly  wasteful  of  time  in  postponing  read- 
ing exercises  which  involve  simultaneous  practice  of  all  the 
language  units  in  their  proper  setting,  and  which  are  constantly 
more  profitable  because  more  interesting.  The  new  synthetic 
methods  gain  these  advantages,  but  lose  a  more  necessary  one, 
unless  the  teacher  realizes  that  the  pupils  must  all  the  while  be 
getting  the  alphabet  and  vocabulary  and  making  them  automatic. 
If  this  end  can  be  achieved  incidentally,  well  and  good.  If  not, 
it  must  be  achieved  by  periods  of  practice  devoted  thereto.  In 
no  case  can  making  the  language  elements  automatic  be  skipped. 

Similar  principles  hold  in  arithmetic.  It  is  a  mistake  to  de- 
mand of  children  a  thorough  memorizing  of  the  number  series 
and  of  the  fundamental  tables  before  giving  them  any  exercise 
with  concrete  numbers  and  problems.  It  is  a  greater  mistake  to 
spend  the  years  when  the  plastic  memory  is  at  its  best  in  number 
exercises  which  are  interesting,  but  which  leave  the  children  with 
the  alphabets  of  arithmetic  imperfectly  mastered.  The  high- 
school  boy  who  must  halt  in  his  mathematical  work  to  remem- 
ber the  multiplication  table,  is  enjoying  the  fruits  of  a  pseudo- 
freedom  in  the  grades.  There  is  no  freedom  except  through 
automatism.  It  is  possible  to  avoid  both  the  extremes  men- 
tioned. The  work  should  be  filled  with  concrete  interest  in 
ways  fully  displayed  in  our  modern  elementary  text-books  on 
arithmetic.  But  at  all  times  the  teacher  should  see  to  it  that 
there  is  thorough  incidental  practice  of  those  number-relations 
which  should  become  automatic,  and  at  some  times  there 
should  be  direct  hard  work  at  memorizing  those  relations. 

In  addition  to  the  evidence  already  presented  in  favor  of  the 
foregoing  view,  two  general  considerations  are  submitted. 

(i)  It  is  quite  useless  to  raise  the  question  whether  or  not 
children  should  acquire  specific  automatic  habits.  There  is  no 
escape  from  such  habits  except  by  death.  The  Indian  does  not 
escape.  The  wolf  does  not  escape.  Neither  Shakespeare  nor 
Caliban  escape.  There  is  no  question  of  escaping  automatic 
habits.  The  only  real  question  is  :  Which  ones  shall  we  acquire  ? 


37°  WILLIAM  L.    BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

The  school  and  civilization  answer :  While  it  is  possible,  ac- 
quire those  habits  which  are  the  alphabets  of  learning  and  of 
cultivated  life.  This  is  the  first  necessary  step  toward  the  free- 
dom, adaptability,  ingenuity,  and  efficiency  which  give  superi- 
ority to  man. 

(2)  A  school  method  must  be  judged  by  the  moods  and 
tempers  which  it  cultivates,  not  simply  by  what  is  learned,  still 
less  by  the  momentary  interest  it  arouses.  If  one  forces  mas- 
tery of  the  multiplication  table  by  methods  which  keep  one-half 
the  school  cowed  and  the  other  half  rebellious,  one  has  ob- 
tained a  useful  result  at  disastrous  cost.  Better  not  know  the 
multiplication  table  than  be  thus  morally  maimed. 

If,  on  the  other  hand,  one  anxiously  converts  all  school 
work  into  a  round  of  entertainments,  if  one  shields  the  pupils 
from  having  at  any  time  a  sense  of  resolute  effort  with  hard 
tasks,  if  one  keeps  the  pupils  vibrating  between  excitement  and 
ennui  as  at  a  circus  or  picnic,  what  of  the  moods  and  tempers 
thus  cultivated  ?  To  what  set  of  character  do  they  lead  ?  For 
what  occupation  do  they  prepare?  Every  one  knows.  These 
are  the  moods  and  tempers  of  the  loafer,  the  tramp,  the  sport — 
the  idlers,  rich  and  poor,  who  afflict  society  with  their  ineffi- 
ciency and  their  consequent  misery. 

There  is  happily  no  need  to  choose  between  the  galleys  and 
the  circus  as  models  for  the  school  and  home.  There  are  many 
schools  and  homes  where  hard  tasks  are  performed  in  a  good 
temper ;  where  thorough  drill  does  not  arrest,  but  prepares  the 
way  for  higher  development ;  where  children  begin  to  do  what 
they  must  later  do  to  succeed  in  any  business — pass  cheerfully 
from  interest  in  desired  ends  to  a  resolute  drudgery  necessary 
for  the  attainment  of  those  ends. 

If  this  view  of  education  is  correct,  the  course  of  study  has 
no  more  important  function  than  to  make  clear  the  essential 
habits  involved  in  the  mastery  of  each  school  subject,  and  the 
order  in  which  these  are  to  be  acquired ;  and  the  teacher  has 
no  more  important  duty  than  to  arouse  in  children  such  an  in- 
terest in  some  higher  aspect  of  the  subject,  that  they  will  wil- 
lingly lend  themselves  to  mastery  of  its  details. 


THE   TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  371 

3.  Plateaus. 

Wide  variation  and  sudden  changes  in  rate  of  progress  are 
not  peculiar  to  the  learning  of  telegraphy.  In  general,  it  is  in- 
deed a  -priori  highly  improbable  that  the  rate  of  change  in  any 
process  will  be  constant.  For  such  constancy  requires  an  ex- 
tremely improbable  constancy  in  the  many  factors  which  unite 
in  determining  the  rate.  As  these  factors  increase  in  number 
and  complexity,  the  less  likely  they  are  to  effect  a  constant  rate. 
Modern  evolutionary  science  has  emphasized  the  facts  which  in- 
dicate that  changes  in  nature  are  regular  and  gradual.  Natura 
saltum  nonfacit.  It  is,  however,  now  well-known  that  nature 
does  make  leaps.  It  may  even  be  that  saltatory  change  is  the 
rule.  The  recapitulation  theory  invites  us  to  picture  the  history 
of  each  individual  as  a  series  of  steps  corresponding  to  the 
stages  in  animal  and  racial  evolution.  No  one  has  made  out  an 
accurate  time  table  for  all  these  steps  (or  even  ascertained  ex- 
actly what  the  steps  are).  But  no  one  would  claim  that  the 
rate  of  progress  through  them  is  uniform.  The  development  of 
the  body  and  the  mind  both  show  '  resting  periods '  alternating 
with  periods  of  rapid  change.  We  *  perch  and  fly.'  We  live 
for  months  or  years  upon  a  certain  level  of  interests,  efforts  and 
achievements,  and  then  suddenly  undergo  a  more  or  less  radical 
conversion.  All  things  are  become  new.  The  old  life  sinks 
into  the  vast  subsoil  upon  whose  surface,  for  a  season,  bloom  new 
forms  of  the  life  of  attention. 

The  well-known  examples  of  rapid  change  are,  of  course, 
not  cited  as  specifically  analogous  to  the  plateaus  and  ascents  of 
the  telegraphic  curve,  but  only  to  show  that  such  alternations  of 
camping  out  and  moving  ahead  are  not  exceptional  or  abnormal. 
For  specific  analogies  we  must  look  to  the  history  of  analogous 
acquisitions.  In  this  promising  field  for  research  nearly  every- 
thing remains  to  be  done.  Preliminary  inquiry  has  developed 
the  following  provisional  results. 

(<z)  Languages.  As  hitherto  noted,1  in  learning  to  read 
(first  year  primary),  and  in  learning  a  foreign  language,  one's 
progress  is  analogous  to  that  of  the  student  of  telegraphy.  In 

aLoc.  cit.,  52. 


372  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE   HARTER. 

the  latter  case,  especially,  there  is  the  same  rapid  improvement 
at  first,  the  same  dispiriting  level  just  below  the  ability  to  under- 
stand ordinary  conversation,  the  same  rapid  ascent  into  usable 
knowledge  of  the  language,  and  the  same  year  long  struggle, 
seldom  completed,  before  one  has  freedom  in  the  language. 

(b)  English   Composition.     In  the  Indiana  University,  we 
have  each  year  several  hundred  students  in  conditioned  English 
Composition.      All    entering    students    are   tested    as   to   their 
ability  to  write  printable  English.     Those  who  cannot  do  so, 
are  required  to  take  the  conditioned  English  until  they  can  meet 
the  test.     A  student  may  pass  out  of  this  work  at  any  time. 
The  heaviness  of  the  work,  the  discredit  of  having  to  take  it, 
and   the  special  fee  required,  make   the    motives   for   getting 
through  very  strong.     The  instructors  in  this  work  tell  us  that 
the  progress  of  most  students  is  pictured  in  a  general  way  by 
the  receiving    curve.     A  few   students  pass  out  of   the    work 
very  soon.     This  generally   indicates    that  they  failed    to    do 
themselves  justice  in  the  first  test.     In  most  cases,  there  is  rapid 
progress  nearly  up  to  the  passing  level,  and  then  a  long  plateau 
above  which  the  student  seems  incapable  of  rising.     In  some 
cases,  where  students  were  expected  by  the  instructor  to  pass  in 
a  few  weeks,  they  have  kept  drudging  away  for  the  rest  of  the 
year  with  slight  improvement.     Doubtless,  in  these  cases,  the 
interference  of  established  language  habits  is  an  important  factor 
in  retarding  progress. 

(c)  Chemistry.     Several  teachers   of   chemistry   have    re- 
ported that  the  progress  of  students  during  the  first  year's  work 
in  that  subject  is  similar   to   that   of  the  telegraphic   student. 
There  is  the   same  period  of   rapid    improvement  in   the  first 
months,  followed  by  a  long  period  of  slow  progress.     In  the 
Indiana  University  chemical    laboratory    the  latter  period  has 
long  been  recognized  and   named  '  the  period  of  depression.' 
At  one  time  it  was  supposed  by  the  instructors  that  this  period 
of  depression  might  be  due  to  an  inferiority  in  the  latter  part  of 
the  laboratory  manual,  but  further  experience  has  shown  that 
this  is  not  the  case.     An  explanation  of  the  chemist's  plateau 
analogous  to  that  given  for  the  telegrapher's  plateau  would  be : 
that  on  the  plateau  the  learner  is  constantly  hampered  because 


THE   TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  373 

he  cannot,  on  demand,  remember  any  one  of  a  large  number  of 
elementary  facts  which  he  has  once  learned ;  that  the  large 
number  of  elementary  facts  which  he  needs  to  know,  makes  his 
progress  toward  sufficient  mastery  of  them  very  slow ;  that  a 
rapid  progress  comes  at  last  when  he  can  turn  his  attention  from 
mastering  the  elements  to  a  freer  use  of  these  facts  in  attacking 
more  complex  chemical  problems.  The  chemists  whom  we 
have  consulted  incline  to  regard  this  explanation  as  correct. 

(d)  Miscellaneous.  A  large  number  of  individuals  have  re- 
ported analogous  experiences  in  learning  mathematics,  music, 
whist,  chess,  checkers,  et  cetera.  In  all  these  fields  we  find 
one  or  more  long  discouraging  levels,  where  practice  seems  to 
bring  no  improvement,  ending,  at  last,  in  the  case  of  those  who 
persevere,  in  a  sudden  ascent.  It  is  probable  that  in  each  case 
one  must  acquire  habits  of  lower  and  higher  order,  and  that  the 
explanation  for  the  telegraphic  plateaus  is  the  explanation  for 
the  plateaus  in  these  fields.  Of  course,  the  curves  in  these 
widely  differing  fields  must  have  different  specific  characters. 
Each  must  be  investigated  for  itself.  In  a  time  when  some  fear 
a  dearth  of  significant  problems  for  psychological  research  the 
prospect  of  such  a  field  is  inspiriting. 

In  general,  we  have  here  a  point  of  view  from  which  we 
may  discern  a  difference  between  the  master  and  the  man  of 
*  all-round '  development,  who  is  master  of  nothing.  Both  have, 
from  the  informal  experiences  of  life,  some  knowledges  and 
skills  which  fit  them  to  undertake  the  mastery  of  a  given  field. 
Both  have  developed  these  potential  instruments  of  mastery, 
have  '  gone  over  '  the  principal  items  of  knowledge  and  *  gone 
through'  with  the  principal  forms  of  skill  required.  The  mas- 
ter has  not  stopped  here.  He  has  initiated  himself  body  and 
soul  in  the  elements,  so  that  after  a  time  such  things  are  to  him 
like  letters  and  words  to  an  educated  man.  They  shoot  to- 
gether easily  into  new  combinations.  They  are  units  of  medi- 
tation, of  invention.  Meanwhile,  to  the  man  who  has  only  «  a 
good  general  knowledge  of  the  field/  the  feats  of  the  master 
are  impossible  and  almost  incredible.  The  master's  units  of 
thought  are  each  to  him  a  problem.  He  must  give  time  and 
pains  to  each  one  separately.  He  cannot  think  with  them.  He 


374  WILLIAM  L.   BRYAN  AND  NOBLE  HARTER. 

is  necessarily  a  follower,  or,  if  he  essays  the  freedom  without 
the  power  of  the  master,  he  is  worse  than  a  follower — a  crank. 

4.  Effective  Speed  and  Accuracy. 

There  is  scarcely  any  difference  between  one  man  and  an- 
other of  greater  practical  importance  than  that  of  effective 
speed.  In  war,  business,  scientific  work,  manual  labor  and  what 
not,  we  have  at  the  one  extreme  the  man  who  defeats  all  ordi- 
nary calculations  by  the  vast  quantity  of  work  he  gets  done,  and 
at  the  other  extreme  the  man  who  no  less  defeats  ordinary  cal- 
culation by  the  little  all  his  busyness  achieves.  The  former  is 
always  arriving  with  an  unexpected  victory ;  the  latter,  with  an 
unanswerable  excuse  for  failure. 

It  has  seemed  to  many  psychologists  strongly  probable  that 
the  swift  man  should  be  distinguishable  from  the  slow  by  reac- 
tion time  tests.  For  (#),  granting  that  the  performances  de- 
manded in  practical  affairs  are  far  more  complicated  than  those 
required  in  the  laboratory  tests,  it  seems  likely  that  one  who  is 
tuned  for  a  rapid  rate  in  the  latter  will  be  tuned  for  a  rapid 
rate  in  the  former,  when  he  has  mastered  them.  Moreover  (£), 
a  rapid  rate  in  elementary  processes  is  favorable  to  their  fu- 
sion into  higher  unitary  processes,  each  including  several  of  the 
lower.  Finally  (c),  a  rapid  rate  in  elementary  processes  is  fa- 
vorable to  prompt  voluntary  combinations  in  presence  of  new 
emergencies. 

In  face  of  these  a  -priori  probabilities,  eleven  years'  experi- 
ence in  this  laboratory  (the  first  three  being  spent  mainly  on  re- 
action times)  has  brought  the  conviction  that  no  reaction  time 
test  will  surely  show  whether  a  given  individual  has  or  has  not 
effective  speed  in  his  work.  Very  slow  rates,  especially  in 
complicated  reactions,  are  strongly  indicative  of  a  mind  slow 
and  ineffective  at  all  things.  But  experience  proves  that  rapid 
rates  by  no  means  show  that  the  subject  has  effective  speed  in 
the  ordinary,  let  alone  extraordinary,  tasks  of  life.  How  is 
this  to  be  explained  ? 

The  following  answer  is  proposed :  The  rate  at  which  one 
makes  practical  headway  depends  partly  upon  the  rate  of  the 
mental  and  nervous  processes  involved ;  but  far  more  upon  how 


THE    TELEGRAPHIC  LANGUAGE.  375 

much  is  included  in  each  process.  If  A,  B  and  C  add  the  same 
columns  of  figures,  one  using  readily  the  method  of  the  light- 
ning adder,  another  the  ordinary  addition  table,  while  the  third 
makes  each  addition  by  counting  on  his  fingers,  the  three  are 
presently  out  of  sight  of  one  another,  whatever  the  rates  at  which 
the  processes  involved  are  performed.  The  lightning  adder 
may  proceed  more  leisurely  than  either  of  the  others.  He  steps 
a  league  while  they  are  bustling  over  furlongs  or  inches. 

Now,  the  ability  to  take  league  steps  in  receiving  telegraphic 
messages,  in  reading,  in  addition,  in  mathematical  reasoning 
and  in  many  other  fields,  plainly  depends  upon  the  acquisition 
of  league-stepping  habits.  No  possible  proficiency  and  rapidity 
in  elementary  processes  will  serve.  The  learner  must  come  to 
do  with  one  stroke  of  attention  what  now  requires  half  a  dozen, 
and  presently,  in  one  still  more  inclusive  stroke,  what  now  re- 
quires thirty-six.  He  must  systematize  the  work  to  be  done  and 
must  acquire  a  system  of  automatic  habits  corresponding  to  the 
system  of  tasks.  When  he  has  done  this  he  is  master  of  the 
situation  in  his  field.  He  can,  if  he  chooses,  deal  accurately 
with  minute  details.  He  can  swiftly  overlook  great  areas  with 
an  accurate  sense  of  what  the  details  involved  amount  to — in- 
deed, with  far  greater  justice  to  details  than  is  possible  for  one 
who  knows  nothing  else.  Finally,  his  whole  array  of  habits  is 
swiftly  obedient  to  serve  in  the  solution  of  new  problems. 
Automatism  is  not  genius,  but  it  is  the  hands  and  feet  of  genius. 


COMMUNICATIONS    FROM   THE    PSYCHOLOGICAL 
LABORATORY  OF   HARVARD   UNIVERSITY. 

AUTOMATIC  REACTIONS. 

BY  DR.   LEON  M.    SOLOMONS, 

University  of  Wisconsin. 

The  experiments  upon  the  time  of  automatic  reactions,  of 
which  I  wish  to  give  a  brief  account  here,  are  an  outgrowth  in 
part  of  the  work  on  Motor  Automatism  published  by  Miss  Stein 
and  myself  in  the  REVIEW  for  September,  1896.  I  had  three 
main  objects — to  see  whether  the  various  stages  of  automatism 
which  we  there  distinguished  had  characteristic  reaction  times ; 
to  get  evidence,  if  possible,  for  the  theory  advanced  in  that 
article,  that  the  feeling  of  personal  agency  accompanying  a 
movement  is  due  primarily  to  the  motor  neurons  of  the  cortex — 
that  is,  that  it  is  the  absence  of  their  activity  which  gives  a 
movement  its  feeling  of  impersonality;  and  third,  to  attack  the 
problem  of  the  relation  of  attention  to  the  different  types  of 
reaction  by  studying  reactions  in  which  attention  was  totally 
absent. 

The  experiments  are  not  complete,  and  their  evidence  is  not 
as  clear  and  convincing  as  it  might,  I  believe,  be  made.  But 
since  it  is  doubtful  whether  I  shall  be  able  to  continue  them  in 
the  near  future,  and  especially  since  some  of  the  indications 
may  prove  valuable  suggestions  to  other  workers  in  the  field,  I 
think  it  advisable  to  give  at  least  a  preliminary  account  now. 

GENERAL  METHOD.  The  mode  of  distraction  adopted  was 
the  same  as  in  the  experiments  on  motor  automatism — the  read- 
ing of  light,  entertaining  literature.  The  stimulus  was  the 
sound  of  an  electric  hammer.  During  part  of  the  experiments 
the  Scripture  reaction  key  was  used.  During  the  last  part  this 
was  changed,  since  some  of  the  subjects  found  difficulty  in 

376 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL    LABORATORY.  ^77 

maintaining  the  contact  between  reactions  without  interfering 
with  the  complete  automatism  of  the  movement.  I  accordingly 
changed  to  an  Ewald  key,  but  used  a  contact  through  mer- 
cury instead  of  the  simple  metallic  contact.  With  this  key 
a  considerable  unconscious  pressure  might  be  exerted  by  the 
subject  upon  the  key  without  breaking  the  connection,  and  yet 
the  reaction  require  no  special  effort.  The  mercury  contact 
had  only  a  very  slight  immersion — never  more  than  ^3_  of  an 
inch — and  did  not,  I  believe,  appreciably  affect  the  reaction 
time,  while  it  was  of  considerable  assistance  in  maintaining  con- 
nections during  the  intervals  between  the  reactions. 

The  chronoscope — placed  in  a  separate  room  to  prevent  the 
subject  knowing  when  an  observation  was  to  be  made — was 
connected  in  the  usual  way,  the  stimulus  closing  the  circuit,  and 
the  breaking  of  the  contact  by  the  reaction  opening  it.  Find- 
ing it  difficult  to  maintain  an  adjustment  of  the  fall  hammer 
constant  over  long  periods  of  time,  recourse  was  had  to  a  pendu- 
lum control.  This  had  the  disadvantage  that  the  time  of  the 
control  was  greater  than  that  of  the  reactions  studied.  But  as 
relative  values  only  were  desired,  this  was  no  real  difficulty, 
while  the  greater  certainty  of  constancy  of  conditions  from 
month  to  month  was  a  distinct  gain. 

The  subject  was  instructed  to  keep  his  attention  as  closely 
as  possible  upon  what  he  was  reading,  and  not  to  think  of  the 
experiment.  He  was  asked  to  introspect  as  carefully  as  cir- 
cumstances permitted,  but  not  so  as  to  interfere  with  the  autom- 
atism. The  subjects  differed  considerably  in  the  ease  with 
which  they  acquired  the  ability  to  react  automatically,  but  the 
stages  seemed  to  be  the  same  in  all. 

At  first  the  attention  is  all  on  the  experiment,  the  subject 
reading  without  understanding.  Gradually  the  incidence  of  at- 
tention shifts,  and  he  is  able  to  keep  his  mind  on  his  reading 
between  reactions,  but  has  to  stop  reading  to  react.  The  inter- 
ference produced  by  this  reaction  becomes  less  and  less,  until 
the  various  stages  of  automatism  are  reached  and  passed 
through.  Some  subjects  become  automatic  after  very  little 
practice ;  others  require  a  good  deal,  and  their  results  are  more 
valuable  for  the  light  they  throw  on  the  passage  from  voluntary 


LEON  AL    SOLOMONS. 

to  automatic  reactions,  than  for  the  passage  from  simple  auto- 
matic to  subconsciousness. 

At  first  the  reaction  times  were  studied  by  the  usual  method 
of  taking  the  average,  corrected  if  necessary  by  throwing  out 
those  with  very  large  residuals.  But  during  this  process  it  was 
observed  that  the  small  residuals  were  not,  as  they  should  be, 
in  the  majority ;  but  that  often,  on  the  contrary,  there  were  a 
large  number  of  large  residuals  of  about  the  same  value,  with 
few,  if  any,  small  ones.  This  showed  that  the  average  was 
simply  a  mean  between  two  reaction  times  of  different  value, 
and,  therefore,  thoroughly  misleading.  Accordingly  I  adopted 
the  method  of  plotting  the  reactions,  as  one  plots  an  error  curve. 
The  resulting  curve  is,  of  course,  of  the  same  form  as  would  be 
obtained  by  plotting  the  residuals,  the  position  of  the  Y  axis 
alone  being  changed. 

The  curves  so  obtained  did  not  in  general  assume  the  form 
of  the  theoretical  error  curve,  but  showed  a  grouping  of  the  re- 
actions about  several  points.  It  had  been  my  intention  to  study 
the  effect  of  frequency,  intensity  of  stimulus,  etc.,  on  the  reac- 
tion times,  and  I  had  arranged  my  apparatus  with  that  end. 
But  finding  the  problem  complicated  by  the  reactions  being  of 
mixed  types,  I  thought  it  best  to  confine  myself  to  my  main 
problem. 

Owing  to  the  uncertainty  of  the  last  figure  of  a  reaction  time 
obtained  in  thousandths  of  a  second,  I  plotted  the  curves,  during 
the  course  of  the  experiments,  for  hundredths  of  a  second  only. 
Becoming  satisfied,  however,  that  this  method  failed  to  bring  out 
some  important  features  of  the  reactions,  I  commenced  a  more 
minute  study,  with  various. methods  of  plotting.  A  comparison 
of  these  results  convinced  me  that  the  best  method  for  these  re- 
sults was  to  let  the  ordinate  corresponding  to  any  time  repre- 
sent the  number  of  reactions  having  a  value  within  2  a  of  that 
time.  This  gives  a  curve  the  main  features  of  which  may  be 
seen  at  a  glance,  but  which  is,  nevertheless,  not  misleadingly 
simple. 

It  will  be  seen  in  the  following  discussion  that  I  do  not  place 
much  reliance  upon  the  lesser  variations  in  the  curves.  They 
;ire  probably  important,  but  the  chronoscope  is  too  inaccurate  an 
instrument  to  warrant  reliance  upon  them. 


HARVARD   PSYCHOLOGICAL  LABORATORY.  379 

THE  TYPES  OF  REACTION. — My  subjects,  eight  in  number, 
may  be  divided  into  three  groups.  Group  one,  consisting  of 
subjects  G,  B  and  D,  required  long  practice  before  becoming 
thoroughly  automatic.  They  tended  toward  the  auditory  type. 
That  is,  their  thought  is  largely  in  sound  terms,  and  their  atten- 
tion is  readily  attracted  and  held  by  sounds.  The  subject  G 
sometimes  distracted  himself  by  thinking  of  music  he  had  heard. 
Group  two,  consisting  of  subjects  M,  S,  and  De,  were  of  the 
visual  motor  type.  They  could  not  recall  sounds  at  all.  Their 
imagery  was  all  visual  and  motor.  These  subjects  readily  be- 
came automatic  and  passed  through  all  the  stages  of  automatism. 
Group  three,  consisting  of  subjects  Ho  and  Ha,  were  inter- 
mediate. They  were  poor  visualizers,  but  their  motor  and  audi- 
tory memories  were  good.  They  occupied  an  intermediate  posi- 
tion as  regards  automatism.  They  found  it  difficult  to  keep  the 
attention  from  wandering  to  the  experiment.  Their  automatism, 
while  in  general  apparently  very  good,  was  easily  disturbed. 
These  two  subjects  experienced  the  most  difficulty  in  maintain- 
ing the  contact  during  the  intervals  between  the  reactions. 
Whether  the  correlation  here  appearing  between  the  types  of 
imagery  and  the  tendency  to  automatism  is  accidental  or  signifi- 
cant, remains  to  be  seen. 

Fig.  i  presents  a  series  of  curves  obtained  from  the  subject 
G.  Each  curve,  except  the  first,  represents  the  results  of  re- 
actions taken  at  one  sitting.  The  abscissa  gives  the  time 
of  the  reaction ;  the  ordinate,  the  number  of  reactions  having 
that  time,  or  coming  within  2<r  of  it.  The  curves  are  arranged 
in  time  order,  beginning  at  the  bottom,  and  illustrate  the  progress 
of  automatism.  The  subject  G  did  not  in  general  react  auto- 
matically. He  found  it  difficult  to  keep  his  attention  away  from 
the  experiment,  and  when  he  did  the  reactions  were  often  vol- 
untary. That  is,  he  had  to  turn  his  attention  to  the  experiment 
when  the  stimulus  came  in  order  to  react.  He  eventually  be- 
came fairly  automatic,  however.  His  imagery  is  auditory  and 
visual. 

A  glance  at  the  curves  shows  immediately  this  characteristic. 
There  are  a  large  number  of  comparatively  quick  reactions  in 
the  earlier  ones,  then  long  reactions  predominate,  and  then  short 


3So 


LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  381 


LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 


FIG.  5. — This  curve  shows  the  distribution  of  518  reactions  taken  from  5 
different  subjects. 

ones  again.  All  the  subjects  showed  this  peculiarity.  The 
reason  is  that  at  first  the  attention  is  on  the  experiment,  and  the 
subject  in  a  condition  of  expectation,  and  we  therefore  have 
something  near  the  conditions  of  the  ordinary  simple  reaction. 
Later  he  learns  to  keep  his  attention  off  the  experiment,  and  the 
reactions  are  slow.  Then  the  path  gets  worn  smooth  by  habit, 
and  the  various  stages  of  automatism  commence,  ending  in  a 
very  quick  reaction. 

The  subject's  notes  amply  confirm  this  explanation,  if  con- 
firmation is  necessary.  G  notes  for  the  first  curve,  which  rep- 
resents the  results  of  three  days'  observations  during  November, 
that  his  attention  was  more  or  less  on  the  experiment  all  the 
time. 

For  Jan.  19  we  have  the  note,  "  Attention  somewhat  on  ex- 
periment, but  not  enough  to  give  any  really  voluntary  reactions. 
No  very  fast  ones,  as  when  attention  is  on  reaction ;  nor  any 
very  slow  ones,  as  when  I  do  not  react  and  then  recollect  my- 
self." The  results  of  self-observation  are  amply  confirmed  by 
the  curve. 

Feb.  25  the  reactions  were  judged  to  be  about  *  in  between 
voluntary  and  automatic.'  On  Mar.  25  the  automatism  is  con- 
sidered fair,  and  on  Apr.  15  '  more  automatic  than  usual.' 
On  May  20  the  automatism  was  judged  to  be  very  good,  and  he 
expressed  a  doubt  as  to  whether  he  heard  the  stimulus  distinctly 
before  he  felt  the  reaction. 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  383 

It  will  be  noticed  that  during  the  period  between  the  reac- 
tions in  which  the  attention  was  on  the  experiment,  and  the  ap- 
pearance of  good  automatism,  the  bulk  of  the  reactions  are 
above  290*7.  After  automatism  sets  in  the  bulk  of  the  reactions 
are  below  2900-,  and  on  May  20,  when  for  the  first  time  a  doubt 
appears  as  to  there  being  a  distinct  interval  between  stimulus 
and  reaction,  there  are  a  large  number  below  230*7.  The  re- 
sults from  other  subjects  show  that  these  peculiarities  are 
significant. 

Fig.  2  shows  a  similar  series  of  curves  from  the  subject  D. 
Like  G,  the  usual  imagery  of  D  is  auditory  and  visual.  She 
became  automatic  much  more  quickly,  however,  though  remain- 
ing for  a  long  time  in  the  first  stage.  The  first  move  represents 
the  result  of  the  first  day's  experimenting.  She  had  very  little 
difficulty  in  keeping  her  attention  off  the  experiment,  and  after 
a  very  little  practice  the  reactions  ceased  to  disturb  her  reading. 
Nevertheless,  it  will  be  noticed  that  even  in  her  case  we  have  a 
greater  preponderance  of  short  reactions  in  the  first  curve.  The 
next  curve  shown  is  for  Mar.  2.  Her  report  was  'Attention 
first  attracted  by  sound,  reaction  automatic.'  The  next  curve 
shown  is  for  March  10.  The  number  of  reactions  below  230*7 
is  now  at  a  minimum.  She  reported  the  reactions  as  seeming 
*  perfectly  regular  and  automatic.'  '  She  always  heard  the  stim- 
ulus first,  and  then  the  reaction  followed,  without  an  interval 
between,  or  any  movement  of  attention,  or  effort.  March  17 
she  was  asked  to  compare  the  interval  between  the  sound  and 
the  reaction,  with  that  between  the  reaction  and  the  click  made 
by  the  key  on  striking.  She  found  it  difficult,  but  thought  the 
second  interval  rather  longer. 

On  March  25  I  began  giving  the  stimuli  more  frequently — 
every  7^  seconds  on  an  average,  instead  of  every  15.  The 
subject's  judgment  was  that  the  greater  frequency  increased  the 
automatism.  In  one  sense  this  is  apparently  true.  It  should  be 
noticed  though  that  in  her  case,  as  in  that  of  G,  the  introduction 
of  the  more  frequent  stimuli  is  marked  by  an  increase  in  the 
number  of  short  reactions  greater  than  that  of  subsequent  dates. 
I  am  inclined  to  believe,  therefore,  though  they  did  not  notice  it 
themselves,  that  the  greater  frequency  at  first  had  the  effect  of 


3 §4  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

drawing  their  attention  to  the  experiment  a  little,  and  that  this 
effect  passed  away  later. 

On  April  14  she  notes  that  in  one  place  the  reaction  and  the 
stimulus  seemed  simultaneous,  and  that  some  of  the  reactions 
seemed  'impersonal.'  It  will  be  noticed  that  corresponding  to 
this  note  we  have  a  large  number  of  reactions  below  230,  and 
several  in  fact  below  180.  Impersonality  was  never  noted  by 
her  again,  though  on  May  25  she  again  observed  some  reac- 
tions in  which  stimulus  and  reaction  seemed  «  almost  simul- 
taneous.' 

It  is  to  be  noticed  that  D's  reactions  were  nearly  always  be- 
low 290.  The  long  period  in  which  the  reactions  were  above 
this,  shown  by  G,  is  absent  in  her  case^  owing  apparently,  to 
the  almost  immediate  occurrence  of  automatism.  The  subject 
B,  the  third  of  this  type,  gave  results  similar  to  G.  She  was 
a  long  time  in  becoming  automatic  according  to  her  report,  and 
her  reactions  showed  a  majority  above  2900-  for  a  long  time. 
With  D  as  with  G,  further,  *  simultaneous '  reactions  were 
noted  with  the  reappearance  in  number  of  reactions  below  230. 

The  indications  from  these  three  subjects  are,  then,  that  the 
reaction  time  for  automatic  response  to  sounds  begins  somewhere 
in  the  neighborhood  of  290.  A  reaction  time  longer  than  this 
indicates  that  some  effort  of  attention  or  will  is  necessary.  There 
is  no  change  in  this  subjective  condition  until  we  reach  a 
region  below  230*7,  when  apparently  a  new  type  of  automatic  re- 
action begins.  To  study  this  other  type  we  must  turn  to  the 
records  from  other  subjects.  The  exact  limits  of  the  first  type, 
as  well  as  the  significance  of  the  different  groups  of  reactions 
indicated  by  the  curve  within  this  general  type,  had  best  be  con- 
sidered later. 

As  to  the  character  of  this  group  of  subjects,  supposing  that 
it  does  represent  a  type  of  person,  there  is  not,  I  think,  any  good 
reason  for  thinking  the  difference  between  them  and  others 
other  than  one  of  degree.  With  time  and  proper  methods  they 
will,  I  believe,  pass  through  all  the  phases  of  automatism.  I 
made  no  special  effort  to  hurry  them,  for  I  was  more  than  will- 
ing that  some  of  my  subjects  should  remain  in  this  phase,  for 
its  better  study.  Instead  of  trying  to  adapt  the  conditions  of 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  385 

the  experiment  to  the  habits  of  attention  of  the  subject,  I  made 
them  the  same  for  all  subjects.  Naturally  the  differing  habits 
of  attention  resulted  in  differing  responses  upon  the  part  of  the 
subjects.  As  the  practice  was  infrequent — I  had  none  of  my 
subjects  oftener  than  twice  a  week — these  individual  differences 
had  free  scope. 

Group  2,  Fig.  3  shows  a  series  of  curves  obtained  from 
M.  M  is  of  the  visual  motor  type.  The  first  curve,  March  2d, 
shows  results  of  the  first  day.  He  reported  no  trouble  in  read- 
ing during  the  reaction,  but  an  undercurrent  of  attention  on  ex- 
periment. His  attention  was  attracted  first  by  the  stimulus. 
The  stimulus  and  the  reaction  sometimes  seemed  simultaneous. 
The  time  between  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction  usually  seemed 
shorter  than  that  between  the  reaction  and  the  second  click. 

On  March  9  he  reports  his  reactions  rather  regular.  The 
stimulus  comes  distinctly  first,  then  his  feeling  of  reacting,  then 
the  sound  marking  the  completion  of  the  reacting.  On  March 
i6th,  for  the  first  time,  some  of  the  reactions  seem  impersonal. 
In  these  impersonal  reactions  the  second  interval,  that  between 
the  feeling  of  reacting — a  muscular  feeling  in  arm  or  finger — 
and  the  sound  made  by  the  key,  seemed  shorter  than  the  first 
interval.  In  a  few  reactions  he  can  recognize  the  stimulus  be- 
fore the  reaction,  but  in  many  he  doubts  whether  he  would 
know  the  order  of  events  but  for  former  experiences.  OK 
March  3Oth  nearly  all  the  reactions  feel  impersonal.  The  whole 
interval  between  the  two  sounds  seems  shorter,  but  the  interval 
between  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction  feeling  is  about  the  same 
as  that  between  the  reaction  and  the  second  click.  On  April  6  the 
reactions  are  still  impersonal.  He  gets  the  stimulus  by  a  memory 
after-image.  The  reaction  first  attracts  his  attention,  and  then 
he  is  aware  of  the  whole  thing  at  once,  though  in  the  totality 
thus  present  the  stimulus  seems  to  be  first.  It  seems  to  be  a 
*  succession  of  things  all  at  once.'  In  the  latter  part  of  the  ex- 
periment the  reaction  was  sometimes  all  over  before  he  knew  it, 
and  the  whole  thing  came  as  a  sort  of  memory  after-image. 
May  n,  *  sometimes  the  attention  is  first  attracted  by  a  funny 
feeling  marking  the  completion  of  the  reaction,  a  restless  nerv- 
ous feeling.  On  May  18  he  reported  a  curious  feeling  which 


386  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

was  also  noticed  frequently  by  S.  He  knows  the  stimulus  has 
come  before  he  really  hears  it.  It  is  a  perfect  imitation  of  an 
hysterical  anaesthesia  with  '  clairvoyant'  tendencies.  The  ex- 
planation is,  presumably,  that  the  sensory  nerve  current  passes 
over  into  a  reaction  before  rousing  its  usual  response  in  the 
auditory  centers  of  the  cortex.  The  reactions  on  this  occasion 
were  only>partly  impersonal.  They  were  frequently  entirely 
over  before  he  knew  anything  about  it.  On  May  25th  this 
characteristic  was  still  more  marked,  being  almost  unconscious 
toward  the  end.  The  reactions  were  only  in  part  impersonal. 
In  some  cases  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction  seemed  all  one  ;  in 
other  cases  the  reaction  was  almost  simultaneous  with  the  second 
click. 

It  will  be  noticed  in  this  case  that  impersonal  reactions  do 
not  appear  until  we  have  reactions  below  180*7;  that  they  are 
not  judged  to  be  nearly  all  impersonal  until  the  great  majority 
are  below  this  point ;  and  that  when  this  ceases  to  be  the  case 
the  reactions  are  again  only  in  part  impersonal. 

Further,  it  will  be  noticed  that  the  first  type  of  simple  auto- 
matic reaction  that  predominated  in  the  reactions  of  D  and  G — 
that  is,  a  personal  reaction  with  the  stimulus  coming  distinctly 
and  clearly  first — is  not  noted  after  March  Qth,  when  reactions 
above  230(7  cease  to  be  prominent.  The  indications  then  agree 
with  those  obtained  from  D  and  G.  The  first  type  of  automatic 
reaction  stops  at  about  2310-.  The  impersonal  reactions  begin 
below  180*7.  How  about  the  interval?  The  reactions  between 
180  and  230  are  sometimes  characterized  by  '  simultaneous  re- 
actions,' but  not  always.  When  they  first  occur  they  have  this 
peculiarity.  Afterward,  though  they  are  very  distinct  from 
both  the  impersonal  and  the  simple  automatic,  the}7  are  difficult  to 
describe.  The  subject  M,  it  will  be  noted,  only  observed  really 
simultaneous  reactions  once,  though  throughout  the  experi- 
ments he  noted  reactions  not  belonging  to  the  other  types.  D, 
another  subject  of  this  group,  only  experimented  once.  Like 
M,  he  became  automatic  very  quickly.  He  reported  many 
*  simultaneous  reactions.'  The  other  subject  belonging  to  this 
group,  the  writer,  S,  had  a  similar  experience.  I  noticed 
simultaneous  reactions  very  frequently  at  first — over  a  longer 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL  LABORATORY.  387 

period  than  M  and  De,  but  relatively  short — but  very  seldom 
afterward.  On  two  occasions  this  simultaneity  was  so  marked 
and  striking  that  I  stopped  the  experiment  to  find  out  the  record. 
Both  showed  reactions  of  209^7.  In  general  it  is  not  possible  to 
get  a  judgment  of  the  character  of  an  isolated  reaction — one 
can  only  get  a  general  impression  of  a  number.  Nevertheless, 
though  absolute  simultaneity  is  not  frequent,  reactions  which 
feel  very  similar  to  these  are  frequent  and  perfectly  distinct. 
They  are  the  quickest  feeling  reactions — unless  we  judge  the 
time  by  the  interval  between  the  two  clicks.  They  are  char- 
acterized by  uncertainty  about  the  order  of  events,  and  a  general 
predominance  in  the  mass  of  feelings  composing  the  total  reac- 
tion— stimulus,  movement,  etc. — of  the  muscular  and  innervation 
feelings.  Before  passing  to  the  general  discussion  of  the  re- 
sults, however,  it  will  be  worth  while  to  consider  briefly  the  third 
group. 

Fig.  4  gives  a  few  curves  from  the  subject  Ho.  Ho  is  a 
poor  visualizer,  but  has  a  good  auditory  and  motor  memory. 
He  was  rather  erratic  in  his  reactions,  sometimes  being  very 
automatic,  and  at  other  times  not  so.  The  first  curve  shown  is 
far  February  24th.  By  that  time  he  had  settled  down  to  greater 
regularity.  He  notes  that  his  attention  is  first  attracted  by  the 
reaction.  Also,  that  throughout  the  experiment  there  is  a 
slight  feeling  of  tension  in  the  arm.  For  March  4th  he  notes 
some  impersonality.  March  nth,  sometimes  simultaneous, 
sometimes  impersonal.  On  March  23d,  "Not  as  automatic  as 
usual  condition  of  expectation.  Some  simultaneous,  very  few 
impersonal.  Second  interval  most  marked."  On  March  23d  the 
more  rapid  stimuli — every  7^  seconds — were  first  introduced. 
With  Ho,  as  with  the  others,  their  first  introduction  is  marked 
by  a  preponderance  of  shorter  reactions.  But  Ho  notes  a  dis- 
turbance of  the  automatism,  which  the  others  did  not.  I  be- 
lieve the  explanation  is  the  same  in  all  cases,  but  that  only  in 
Ho  was  the  disturbance  great  enough  to  be  noticed.  In  this 
case,  whenever  the  shortness  of  the  reaction  is  due  to  atten- 
tion being  on  the  experiment,  the  short  reactions  do  not  feel 
impersonal.  Simultaneous  reactions  are,  however,  noted, 
though  there  are  but  two  or  three  reactions  within  the  interval 
where  they  usually  occur.  Both  facts  are,  I  believe,  significant. 


388  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

The  last  reactions  are  noted  as  very  impersonal.  The  first 
interval  seems  the  longer. 

Perhaps  the  most  important  thing  in  these  reactions  is  the 
indication  of  a  fourth  type  of  reaction  below  130.  The  subjec- 
tive conditions  corresponding  to  these  low  reactions  do  not  seem 
to  differ  much  from  those  of  the  third  type.  They  are,  per- 
haps, a  little  more  strikingly  impersonal,  and  the  second  inter- 
val is  still  shorter.  But  these  differences  might  appear  in  the 
third  type  after  practice  had  worn  its  path  smooth  and  the  sub- 
ject had  grown  more  accustomed  to  its  observation.  I  am  in- 
clined to  think,  therefore,  that  the  difference  between  the  paths 
indicated  by  these  two  groups  of  reactions  does  not  involve  any 
difference  in  consciousness ;  that  the  change  is  entirely  in  the 
lower  centers. 

GENERAL  DISCUSSION. — Until  the  facts  are  more  clearly  es- 
tablished I  do  not  feel  justified  in  taking  up  the  time  of  the 
readers  of  the  REVIEW  with  a  full  discussion  of  their  signifi- 
cance, for  this  would  involve  the  presentation  and  examination 
of  a  much  larger  number  of  curves,  a  very  tedious  discussion, 
and,  in  the  end,  still  much  doubt  and  uncertainty.  This  would 
be  worth  while  only  if  no  more  conclusive  evidence  could  be 
obtained.  But  as  I  believe  that  more  extensive  experiments 
will  save  this,  the  proper  course  seems  to  be  to  give  only  a  brief 
statement  of  the  most  general  conclusions  to  which  the  experi- 
ments have  led  me. 

Above  290*7  we  have  reactions  in  which  some  element  of 
will  appears.  In  the  slowest  there  is  an  idea  of  the  movement 
about  to  be  made.  In  those  nearer  to  300*7  there  seems  to  be  no 
idea  between  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction — nothing  but  a  feel- 
ing of  voluntariness,  of  somehow  willing  what  takes  place. 
This  is  not  the  feeling  of  effort  mentioned  as  one  of  the  elements 
of  a  sensory  motor  reaction  in  my  paper  on  *  Normal  Motor 
Automatism.'1  The  feeling  of  effort  does  not  appear  in  these 
simple  movements,  unless  the  subject  gets  tired.  It  is  rather  a 
portion  of  what  we  called  the  '  motor  impulse,'  and  described 
as  "  a  melange  of  visual  and  kinsesthetic  material,  as  well  as 
other  elements  not  easily  described,  and,  perhaps,  really  a  direct 

1  PSYCH.  REVIEW,  Vol.  III.,  No.  5,  p.  498. 


HARVARD   PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  389 

consciousness  of  a  motor  current."  The  results  of  these  reaction 
experiments  permit,  I  think,  a  somewhat  closer  analysis  of  this 
motor  impulse  and  the  stages  of  its  disappearance.  The  «  visual 
and  kinassthetic  material '  seems  to  disappear  first,  and  then  this 
peculiar  will  feeling.  My  chief  evidence  for  this  view  is  the 
statement  of  the  subject  G,  on  days  when  his  reactions  were 
largely  between  280  and  340,  that  between  the  stimulus  and  the 
reaction  there  were  *  feelings,'  but  no  ideas  or  readily  describ- 
able  reactions. 

Below  290*7  we  have  nothing  left  of  the  motor  impulse  ex- 
cept the  feeling  of  personal  activity.  In  the  typical  reaction  of 
this  class  the  subject  is  resting  quietly,  when  his  attention  is  sud- 
denly attracted  by  a  sound — or,  rather,  he  suddenly  hears  a 
sound,  for  there  is  no  conscious  movement  of  attention.  Immedi- 
ately after  he  feels  himself  react.  Then  he  hears  a  click  tell- 
ing him  that  the  key  has  been  pressed  down.  During  all  this 
time  he  has  gone  on  with  his  reading  undisturbed.  He  is  con- 
scious of  what  has  happened,  but  that  is  all.  These  reactions 
seem  to  correspond  to  the  usual  '  sensory  reaction.'. 

The  next  type,  from  about  175  to  about  225,  is  characterized 
by  the  prominence  of  the  reaction  feeling.  When  reactions  of 
this  type  first  appear  their  distinguishing  feature  is  the  simul- 
taneity of  the  stimulus  and  the  reaction.  The  subject's  attention 
being  fully  on  his  reading,  he  is  aware  at  once  of  a  sound  and  a 
movement.  He  finds  himself  pressing  a  key  at  the  same  time 
that  he  hears  a  sound.  Later  he  does  not  really  hear  the  sound 
at  the  same  time  as  he  reacts.  He  is  suddenly  conscious  of 
reacting,  and  later  of  two  sounds.  Of  these  sounds,  the  one 
seems  to  be  a  memory  after-image  of  a  sound  made  before  the 
reaction,  the  other  to  be  the  sensation  of  a  sound  coming  after 
the  reaction.  The  explanation  of  this  change  seems  to  me  to 
be  this  :  In  the  first  type  the  sensory  current  goes  first  to  the 
auditory  centers,  where  it  awakens  a  response,  and  then  to  the 
centers,  whatever  they  are,  whose  activity  gives  the  reaction 
feeling,  or  the  beginning  of  the  reaction  feeling,  and  then  out 
to  the  muscles.  In  this  second  type  the  sensory  current  divides, 
part  going  direct  to  the  reaction  center,  part  to  the  auditory 
center,  and  rousing  both  to  activity  at  about  the  same  time.  As 


390  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

the  new  path  gets  worn  less  stimulus  goes  to  the  auditory  centers, 
and  they  respond  only  after  some  time.  To  put  it  another  way, 
with  the  establishment  of  the  shorter  path  the  attention  gets 
more  completely  away  from  sounds.  Now,  whenever  we  fail  to 
hear  a  sound  immediately,  and  later  turn  our  attention  to  it,  we 
get  it  by  a  sort  of  memory  after-image.  This  memory  after- 
image has  peculiarities  of  its  own  which  enable  us,  or  cause  us, 
to  apperceive  it  as  such,  and  project  it  into  its  proper  time  rela- 
tions, or  what  knowledge  and  habit  would  indicate  to  be  its 
proper  time  relations.  Thus,  though  the  reaction  is  the  first 
thing  to  come  into  consciousness,  we  apperceive  the  whole  group 
of  stimulus  (perceived  by  memory  after-image),  reaction  feeling 
and  final  click,  according  to  previous  experience  and  our 
knowledge  of  the  particular  circumstances.  This  view  of  the 
relation  between  the  two  types  is  in  entire  accord  with  the  fact 
that  subjects  with  active  and  sensitive  auditory  centers  remain 
so  much  longer  in  the  first  stage  than  those  whose  motor  centers 
are  the  more  active. 

In  the  third  stage,  the  impersonal  reaction,  the  last  element 
of  the  motor  impulse,  has  disappeared.  In  this  type  the  reaction 
feeling  is  followed  very  quickly,  if  not  accompanied,  by  the  final 
click.  Sometimes  the  subject  heard  the  stimulus  very  distinctly 
before  the  reaction.  Sometimes  he  is  first  conscious  of  the  re- 
action, and  gets  the  stimulus  by  a  memory  after-image ; — but 
there  is  no  doubt  in  his  mind  that  the  stimulus  came  before  the 
reaction.  What  is  the  meaning  of  these  observations?  What 
has  happened  when  the  reaction  becomes  impersonal?  The 
shorter  interval  between  the  reaction  feeling  and  the  final  click, 
as  well  as  the  longer  interval  between  the  stimulus  and  the  re- 
action feeling,  seem  to  demand  one,  and  only  one,  explanation. 
In  the  previous  types  the  beginning  of  the  reaction  feeling  was 
an  activity  in  the  cortex.  In  this  the  reaction  feeling  is  purely 
a  sensation  from  the  muscles  of  the  hand  and  arm.  The  sen- 
sory current  must  now  go  over  into  a  motor  reaction  through  the 
lower  centers  entirely,  or,  at  any  rate,  without  awakening  any 
response  upon  the  part  of  the  cortex.  To  this  extent  then  I  be- 
lieve that  the  theory  advanced  by  Miss  Stein  and  myself  as  to 
the  origin  of  the  feeling  of  personality  is  fully  confirmed  by 


HARVARD   PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  391 

these  experiments.  The  reaction  becomes  impersonal  when  the 
last  center  that  contributes  anything  to  consciousness  drops  out 
of  the  sensory  motor  path,  and  this  center  contributes  nothing 
but  this  feeling  of  personality. 

When  we  come  to  inquire  more  carefully  into  the  identity  of 
this  center  difficulties  arise.  The  reaction  feeling  is  the  same 
in  the  impersonal  and  the  personal  reactions.  It  has  changed 
nothing  but  its  orientation,  so  to  speak.  It  is  felt  in  a  different 
relation  to  the  personality  and  the  stimulus.  The  sensations  are 
the  same.  How  is  it  then  that  in  the  personal  reactions  the 
whole  reaction  feeling  is  timed  by  the  part  of  it  which  simply 
gives  its  personal  coloring?  This  fact  suggests  the  view  that 
this  last  center,  which  gives  the  personal  relation,  is  a  kinagsthetic 
center,  and  includes  a  feeling  of  the  reaction  identical  with  that 
furnished  by  return  sensations  alone.  But  this  view  in  turn  has, 
it  seems  to  me,  grave  difficulties.  All  the  kinaesthetic  part  of 
the  sensory  motor  path  seemed  to  have  dropped  out  before  the 
first  stage  of  automatism.  Moreover,  in  the  personal  reaction 
one  is  not  conscious  of  both  the  reaction  feeling  and  the  return 
sensations.  It  is  necessary,  therefore,  to  suppose  that  the  two 
fuse,  though  occurring  successively.  But  if  we  admit  that  nerv- 
ous disturbances  separated  by  such  an  interval  of  time  may  fuse 
into  one  presentation,  the  necessity  for  supposing  the  center  giv- 
ing the  personal  feeling  to  be  kinsesthetic  ceases.  The  most 
natural  supposition,  then,  seems  to  be  that  it  is  a  motor  center ; 
and  that  its  activity  gives  the  personal  feeling  to  the  sensations 
that  follow.  I  do  not  mean  that  the  activity  of  the  motor  cen- 
ters gives  a  consciousness  of  personality  alone.  The  feeling 
that  one  has  reacted  is-  not  a  feeling  of  personal  activity  plus  a 
muscular  feeling.  It  should  rather  be  said  that  when  the  sensa- 
tions from  an  arm  movement  are  -preceded  by  a  discharge  of 
the  corresponding  motor  cells  of  the  cortex  they  are  felt  to  be 
•personal.  The  activity  of  the  motor  cells  is  thus  responsible 
for  the  resulting  state  of  consciousness  taking  this  form.  The 
impersonality  of  the  reaction,  or  its  personality,  as  the  case  may 
be,  is  not  part  of  the  reaction  feeling,  but  a  peculiarity  of  the 
whole  state  of  consciousness  in  which  the  reaction  feeling  is  rep- 
resented in  all  its  relations  to  the  stimulus  and  the  second  click, 


39 2  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

and  to  the  reaction.  It  is  this  characteristic  of  the  whole  state 
of  consciousness  that  is  determined  by  the  presence  or  absence 
of  the  activity  of  the  motor  cells. 

As  to  the  fourth  group  of  reactions,  if  it  exists,  it  must  corre- 
spond to  a  still  shorter  path.  The  neuron  whose  dropping  out 
marks  the  difference  between  this  group  and  the  preceding 
apparently  furnishes  nothing  to  consciousness,  and  is  pre- 
sumably outside  the  cortex.  On  the  other  hand,  though, 
should  it  be  thought  that  the  feeling  of  personality  comes  from 
a  kinassthetic  center,  and  that  this  is  anatomically  distinct 
from  the  motor  zones  of  the  cortex,  the  way  is  open  to  regard 
the  fourth  type  as  the  first  purely  '  extra-cortical.'  In  the 
present  state  of  our  knowledge  of  the  finer  anatomy  of  this  sen- 
sory motor  path  and  the  meagerness  of  these  experiments  it 
would  be  unprofitable  to  discuss  further  the  correlation  of  the 
different  types  of  reaction  with  known  sensori-motor  paths. 

As  to  the  third  question,  the  relation  of  attention  to  reaction 
time,  these  experiments  show  that  all  types  of  reaction  are  pos- 
sible without  the  attention  being  on  any  part  of  the  reaction — 
in  so  far,  that  is,  as  we  take  the  length  of  a  reaction  as  an  index 
of  its  type.  They  further  indicate  that  the  will  has  nothing 
to  do  with  the  ordinary  reaction,  its  function  being  confined, 
after  a  little  practice,  to  placing  the  sensori-motor  path  in  a 
condition  favorable  to  rapid  reaction.  The  muscular  reaction 
is  practically  a  reflex — as  the  Leipsic  school  contend — and  the 
sensory  reaction  is  at  least  automatic. 

Professor  Angell's1  view  that  the  ultimate  effect  of  practice 
is  to  reduce  both  types  of  reaction  to  the  same  time,  seems  to  me 
to  be  confirmed  by  these  experiments.  Professor  Baldwin's 
view,  that  the  subject's  habits  of  attention,  as  reflected  in  his  usual 
imagery,  is  an  important  factor  in  determining  his  behavior  in 
reaction  experiments,  seems  also  to  be  in  accord,  though  my  ex- 
periments do  not  throw  any  light  on  the  more  specific  sugges- 
tions made  by  him  as  to  the  exact  way  in  which  these  habits 
influence  the  simple  reaction.2 

My  observations  on  the  earlier  reactions,  when  the  subject's 

1  PSYCHOLOGIC AI<  REVIEW,  May,  1896. 

2  PSYCHOLOGICAL,  REVIEW,    1895,  p.  259. 


HARVARD  PSYCHOLOGICAL   LABORATORY.  393 

attention  was  still  in  part  on  the  experiment,  would  lead  me  to 
believe  that  the  principal  effect  of  attention  in  this  case  is  to 
bring  the  entire  motor  mechanism  into  a  condition  of  heightened 
sensitivity.  As  a  result,  when  the  stimulus  comes,  all  the  paths, 
or  many  of  them,  are  used.  The  reaction  time  is,  of  course,  the 
time  of  the  fastest ;  but  the  current  also  traverses  the  others. 
On  this  account  the  reactions  never  feel  impersonal,  but  do  very 
often  feel  '  simultaneous.'  The  motor  cells  always  respond 
before  the  return  sensations  from  the  reflex  reaction  have  arrived, 
and  give  the  reaction  a  personal  feeling,  even  though,  in  fact,  it 
is  reflex.  But  the  division  of  the  current  between  the  paths  of 
the  first  and  the  second  type  is  the  most  favorable  condition 
for  *  simultaneity.' 

Before  closing,  a  few  words  may  be  said  concerning  the 
smaller  groupings  shown  by  the  curves.  Though  in  the  curve 
representing  a  single  day's  reactions  it  is  to  be  expected  that 
some  of  these  groups  are  mere  matters  of  chance,  this  explana- 
tion will  not  hold  for  large  numbers  of  reactions.  In  fact,  a 
glance  at  the  curves  will  show  a  great  deal  of  uniformity  in 
this  respect,  showing  that  even  as  few  as  thirty  or  forty  reac- 
tions will  give  reliable  groupings.  Especially  is  the  location  of 
certain  of  the  minima  very  constant  from  day  to  day.  Appar- 
ently the  changes  in  reaction  time  due  to  practice,  and  even  the 
differences  between  one  individual  and  another,  are  due  pri- 
marily, if  not  wholly,  to  the  relative  preponderance  of  different 
groups,  rather  than  to  change  in  the  time  corresponding  to  the 
same  group. 

Fig.  5  shows  a  curve  obtained  from  the  reactions  of  five 
different  subjects,  during  two  weeks  in  May.  I  select  this  period 
because  both  subjects  and  apparatus  were  fairly  constant  in  their 
behavior  throughout  it.  It  will  be  seen  that  the  groupings  are 
by  no  means  destroyed  by  this  combination  of  the  results  from 
several  subjects  and  on  several  different  occasions.  More  hetero- 
geneous selections  of  results  also  continue  to  show  the  grouping 
in  a  very  marked  manner,  but  not  so  satisfactorily  as  this. 

It  will  be  noticed  that  much  of  the  grouping  shows  a  large 
?roup  separated  from  its  neighbors  by  deep  minima,  which  is  di- 
vided in  turn  into  two  groups,  separated  by  a  much  slighter 


394  LEON  M.    SOLOMONS. 

minimum.  This  smaller  grouping  I  do  not  consider  reliable,  as 
it  may  be  largely  due  to  the  chronoscope.  The  larger  group- 
ings can  hardly  be  so  explained,  and  since  they  are  not  marked 
by  differences  in  consciousness  they  presumably  represent  dif- 
ferences in  the  sensori-motor  path  outside  of  the  cortex.  The 
detailed  discussion  of  this  subject,  however,  I  reserve  until  I 
can  present  fuller  and  more  exact  results. 

In  concluding,  I  wish  to  express  my  thanks  to  Professor 
Miinsterberg  and  to  my  fellow-students  in  the  Harvard  Labora- 
tory, for  cordial  cooperation  and  assistance. 


RECOGNITION  UNDER  OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL. 

BY  GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN, 
Columbia  University. 

This  research  was  carried  on  in  the  Harvard  Psychological 
Laboratory  during  the  first  five  months  of  1898.  It  was  under- 
taken for  the  purpose  of  determining  the  facts  as  to  the  relative 
ease  of  recognizing  objects  when  seen  a  second  time,  but  under 
various  degrees  and  modes  of  turning  or  reversal  in  a  plane  at 
right-angles  to  the  line  of  sight.  Knowledge  of  these  condi- 
tions has  value  and  interest  to  psychologists  on  more  than  one 
account,  for  the  problem  of  recognition  is  inter-related  with  the 
whole  theory  of  space  perception  and  with  that  of  vision  in  gen- 
eral, while  the  curious  relations  in  which  right  and  left  are  ap- 
perceived  by  the  subject  are  herein  also  implicated.  The  com- 
parative ease  and  accuracy  of  the  recognition  of  objects  appear 
to  be  the  sole  criterion  by  which  the  relative  naturalness  of  see- 
ing, so  to  say,  may  be  reduced  to  figures  and  so  to  scientific 
exactness,  for  we  are  all  so  fully  accustomed  to  seeing  things 
in  any  possible  mode  or  degree  of  reversal,  both  objective  and 
subjective,  that  comparison  with  a  normal  position  in  each  case, 
with  judgments  by  various  subjects  and  in  very  numerous  cases, 
is  the  only  practicable  means  to  reliable  information  on  the  sub- 
ject. But  in  order  that  such  recognitions  may  approach  the 
threshold  difficulty  many  objects  quite  unfamiliar  to  the  sub- 
jects must  be  employed,  yet  objects  sufficiently  like  each  other 
to  allow  of  reasonable  comparison.  These  conditions,  of  a  very 
large  number  of  unique  and  unfamiliar  objects  easily  made  and 
handled,  and  comparable  in  all  respects,  are  well  satisfied  in  the 
choice  made  of  the  essential  apparatus  of  this  research,  namely, 
the  blots  of  ink,  whose  usefulness  in  Psychology  was  suggested 
by  the  writer  in  the  REVIEW  for  May,  1897,  p.  390,  and  illus- 
trated and  employed  in  a  research  into  imaginations  in  the 

395 


396 


G.    V.   DEARBORN. 


American  Journal  of  Psychology  for  January,  1898  (Vol.  IX., 
No.  2,  p.  183).  In  the  present  case  these  blots  were  made, 
each  unique,  to  the  number  of  about  four  hundred,  on  bits  of 
white  paper  4  cm.  square  and  each  attached  to  a  card  of  thick 
pasteboard  of  equal  size  and  shape ;  these  were  kept,  arranged 
in  order,  in  long,  closely-fitting  metallic  cases.  The  blot-cards 
were  numbered  consecutively  by  figures  on  the  backs,  while  the 
four  edges  of  the  card  were  lettered  respectively  A,  B,  C,  and 
D,  the  arbitrarily  chosen  normal  position  of  the  blot  or  charac- 
ter being  that  in  which  A  was  at  the  bottom  or,  when  lying  flat, 
nearest  the  subject;  similarly  for  the  other  letters,  each  repre- 
sented a  quadrant  of  reversal  from  the  norm.  The  front  and 
back  of  blot  126  are  here  reproduced,  actual  size,  as  an  example. 


C. 


front.  J^cfC- 

Besides  this  regular  series  of  blot-objects,  each  quite  unique, 
there  were  employed  twenty-one  pairs  of  blots  in  which  the 
components  differed  only  in  that  each  was  to  its  mate  as  the 
right  hand  to  the  left,  the  so-called  mirror-reversal.  These 
were  numbered  and  lettered  similarly  to  the  rest,  with  an  R  pre- 
ceding the  number.  These  ink-blots,  thus  prepared  and 
marked  for  exact  determination  at  all  times  and  in  whatever 
position,  constituted  really  the  simple  apparatus  of  the  experi- 
ments. 

The  schedules  by  which  the  characters  were  arranged  in- 
variably in  series  and  sets  of  series,  and  in  that  order  succes- 
sively exhibited  and  judged  upon,  were  made  out  by  their 
numbers  alone — that  is,  without  any  regard  whatever  to  the 


RECOGNITION  UNDER    OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL.         397 

form  or  other  quality  of  the  blots  themselves.  They  thus  being 
taken  quite  at  random  in  preparing  their  order,  there  was  no 
possibility  (because  of  their  large  number)  that  any  differences 
that  might  exist  in  their  suggestibility,  ease  of  being  remembered, 
similarity  of  successive  characters,  etc.,  should  obtain,  and  so 
vitiate  their  proper  recognizability ;  for  « chance '  is  in  such  a 
case,  in  the  long  run,  a  better  safeguard  than  any  deliberate 
selection  by  an  individual  could  be. 

To  secure  the  requisite  precision  and  a  record  of  the  times 
of  observation  required  for  each  judgment,  a  simple  and  ordin- 
ary electrical  apparatus  was  arranged,  which  may  be  described 
as  follows :  On  the  subject's  table  convenient  to  his  left  hand 
were  fixed  two  keys,  each  actuating  a  pen  tracing  on  a  slowly 
revolving  smoked  drum,  the  left  line  indicating  always  the  '  yes ' 
judgments  and  the  right  the  «  no  '  judgments.  Between  these  re- 
cord-lines, an  inch  or  less  apart,  a  time-line  marking  seconds  was 
traced  by  a  similar  pen  worked  by  a  Lough  electric  pendulum. 
Thus  in  small  space  there  was  kept  a  complete  record  of  every 
judgment,  both  as  to  its  quality  and  as  to  the  exact  time  its  judg- 
ing required.  Subjective  notes  were  also  regularly  written  with 
the  other  records  on  the  drum.  Convenient  to  the  right-hand 
of  the  subject,  and  piled  face-up  in  a  frame  made  to  fit,  the  vari- 
ous blot-cards  were  successively  exposed  by  the  subject  and 
judged  upon. 

TABLE   I. 


SET    V. 


Series 
41 

Series  1 
42 

Series 
43 

Series 
44 

Series 
45 

Series 
46 

Series 
47 

Series 
48 

Series 
49 

Series 
50 

281 

Rl66 

Rl66l 

299 

306 

316 

320 

327 

334 

341 

282 

282C 

292 

300 

307 

317 

321 

32iB 

335 

342 

283 

288 

293t 

293D 

308 

3o8C 

322 

328 

328C 

343 

275B 

Ri67 

301 

3°9 

318 

323t 

323B 

336 

336D 

276B 

289 

294 

294D 

310 

Ri69 

329 

337 

344 

284 

2840 

295 

302 

3'i 

319 

324 

330 

330C 

345 

285 

Ri68 

RI681 

303 

312 

Ri7o 

Ri70l 

338 

338D 

286 

290 

296 

3°4 

313 

3I3C 

325 

325^ 

339 

346 

2796 

291 

297 

305 

314 

3I4C 

R32ii 

332 

332C 

347 

287 

2870 

298 

2980 

315 

R35i 

333 

340 

34oD 

The  368  blots  employed  were  arranged  in  successive  series 
of  ten,  with  ten  such  series  in  a  set,  one  set  being  the  number 


398  G.    V.   DEARBORN. 

judged  upon  at  each  day's  sitting.  The  plan  being  to  expose 
to  the  subject  certain  of  the  blots  twice,  or  sometimes  thrice,  in 
various  quadrants  of  reversal,  the  five  sets  were  arranged  in  a 
manner  best  conveyed  by  the  representation  of  an  actual  set- 
scheme  here.  Cf.  Set  V.,  reproduced  in  Table  I.  This  repre- 
sents the  invariable  order  in  which  the  series  of  blots  were  pre- 
sented to  the  subject,  always  with  an  accurate  interval  of  three 
minutes  between  the  beginnings  of  the  successive  series.  Thus 
the  time  which  elapsed  between  perception  of  the  character  in 
its  normal  position  and  the  judgment  as  to  recognition  was  in 
each  case  nearly  constant.  It  will  be  observed  that,  with  the 
exception  of  Series  45,  in  which  all  the  blots  are  new  to  the 
subject  as  a  test,  30  per  cent,  of  the  object-figures  are  repeti- 
tions, a  fact,  of  course,  quite  unknown  to  the  subject,  as  were 
all  other  details  of  the  schedule.  In  this  set  Series  41  will  be 
seen  to  have  its  quota  of  repetitions  like  the  rest,  but  judgments 
upon  the  three  have  only  secondary  interest,  and  are  not  counted, 
because  seen  perhaps  days,  instead  of  the  regular  three  minutes, 
before.  In  Series  42,  then,  it  is  evident  that  the  second,  sixth, 
and  tenth  characters  were  repeated  and  quite  inverted,  as  the  C 
in  each  case  indicates.  In  Series  43  the  first,  fourth,  and 
seventh  blots  were  repetitions  ;  but  here  the  normal  (A)  positions 
of  the  mirror-reversal  were  compared,  as  also  is  the  case  in 
Series  47.  In  Series  44  and  50  the  degree  of  reversal  was  270°, 
or  three-fourths  (D)  ;  and  in  Series  48,  90°,  or  the  B  reversal. 
By  such  a  degree  of  irregularity  in  placing  the  repetitions  in  the 
series  all  chance  of  suggesting  any  regularity  to  the  subject  was 
avoided. 

The  instructions  given  to  the  subject  were  as  follows  :  '  '  Make 
your  judgments  yes  or  no  in  answer  simply  to  the  explicit  ques- 
tion, Have  you  ever  seen  this  blot  before?  Make  your  judg- 
ments only  when  a  feeling  of  certainty  is  in  consciousness  equal 
to  that  attained  from  the  comparison  of  two  blot-characters,  one 
seen  just  before  and  the  other  never  seen  before.  When  ready, 
make  your  judgment  reactions  with  equal  energy  and  prompt- 
ness in  all  cases,  so  that  the  mere  time-reactions,  as  a  constant 
function,  may  be  disregarded.  Let  a  quick  double  reaction  on 
a  key  indicate  extreme  certainty,  and  a  prolonged  pressure  a 


RECOGNITION  UNDER    OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL.         399 


proportional  degree  of  doubt.  Read  or  converse  between  series, 
so  as  not  to  review  in  imagination  the  blots  just  seen.  Report 
all  possible  subjective  notes  of  interest."  Thus  the  subject  knew 
nothing  of  any  reversals,  of  the  number  of  repetitions  in  each 
series,  nor  of  the  purpose  of  the  research  even  ;  he  or  she  merely 
answered  yes  or  no  to  the  question  as  to  recognition,  when 
'  certain  '  of  his  or  her  judgment  in  that  regard.  Within  the 
period  of  three  minutes  no  incentive  to  hurry  was  suggested. 

TABLE  II. 


REPEATED    BLOTS. 


SUBJECT. 

REVERSAL  POSITION. 

A. 

B. 

c. 

r>. 

R1A. 

R'C. 

Recognitions.  Per  cent. 

61 

30 

51 

16 

54 

57 

I. 

Whole  No.  cases. 

33 

33 

97 

19 

37 

14 

Recognitions.   Per  cent. 

33 

24 

39 

15 

45 

25 

Whole  No.  cases. 

12 

21 

61 

14 

22 

4 

Recognitions.  Per  cent. 

9i 

73 

76 

60 

73 

40 

3- 

Whole  No.  cases. 

12 

15 

4i 

10 

15 

5 

Recognitions.   Per  cent 

62 

25 

29 

40 

28 

• 

Whole  No.  cases. 

21 

12 

35 

i 

10 

ii 

Recognitions.  Per  cent. 

91 

17 

53 

75 

55 

40 

• 

Whole  No.  cases. 

12 

12 

32 

4 

9 

5 

< 

Recognitions.   Percent. 

55 

33 

43 

50 

o 

Whole  No.  cases. 

9 

6 

23 

i 

4 

5 

Recognitions.   Per  cent. 

70 

67 

52 

50 

33 

• 

Whole  No.  cases. 

10 

6 

22 

i 

4 

6 

3 

Recognitions.   Per  cent. 

o 

17 

33 

o 

o 

Whole  No.  cases 

3 

6 

9 

3 

6 

0 

Recognitions.   Per  cent. 

•67 

100 

83 

9- 

Whole  No.  cases. 

3 

3 

17 

i 

i 

2 

Average  per  cent. 

70 

43 

5i 

33 

46 

32 

The  seventy  blot-cards  required  for  one  sitting  being,  then, 
arranged  in  order  on  a  table  behind  the  subject  seated  at  the 
apparatus,  the  method  of  procedure  was,  in  brief,  constantly  as 
follows :  The  time-pendulum  being  in  action,  the  first  series  of 


400 


G.    V.   DEARBORN. 


ten  blots  was  arranged  according  to  the  scheme  for  that  set  (as 
exampled  above)  and  placed  in  the  holder  face  up,  but  covered, 
before  the  subject,  whose  left  hand  covered  the  judgment-keys. 
At  a  given  signal,  whose  exact  temporal  position  was  carefully 
marked  on  the  time-line,  the  subject  lifted  the  blank  covering 
card  and  exposed  the  first  blot,  reacted  yes  or  no  in  the  proper 
manner  when  his  judgment  was  made,  turned  the  used  blot- 
card  face-downward  near  by  (so  that  marginal  retinal  images 
would  not  interfere),  then  immediately  proceeded  to  the  next, 
and  so  on  through  the  series  of  ten.  After  an  interval  of  three 
minutes  from  the  time  of  beginning  on  the  first  series  the  sec- 
ond was  begun,  and  so  on  through  the  set  for  the  day.  This 
number  of  judgments,  although  occupying  only  thirty  minutes, 
was  found  quite  sufficient  for  the  best  work  of  the  subjects,  they 
generally  reporting  the  judgments  very  tiring,  especially  those 
who  are  *  motiles '  or  *  audiles '  in  imaginational  type. 

Nine  subjects  were  employed  in  these  experiments ;  two  of 
these  were  professors  of  philosophy,  and  the  rest  students  and 
instructors  in  the  Laboratory,  one  being  a  student  of  Radcliffe 
College. 

The  figures  which  represent  the  more  interesting  part  of  the 
results  of  the  research  are  given  in  the  accompanying  Table  II., 
useful  as  a  matter  of  record  chiefly.  Altogether  they  represent 
over  2800  judgments  (and  none  too  large  a  number) ;  of  these, 
30  per  cent,  are  on  repetitions.  In  the  tables,  A  indicates 

TABLE  III. 

UNREPEATED    BLOTS. 


"  RECOGNITIONS.'1 

NON-RECOGNITIONS. 

(FALSE.  ) 

(TRUE.) 

SUBJECT. 

PER  CENT. 

CASES. 

PER  CENT. 

CASES. 

I. 

21 

126 

79 

466 

2. 

19-5 

62 

80.5 

256 

3- 

51 

133 

49 

126 

4- 

22 

61 

78 

215 

5- 

27 

52 

73 

144 

5- 

27 

35 

96 

7- 

24 

32 

76 

lor 

8. 

16 

10 

84 

54 

9- 

65.5 

40 

34-5 

21 

AV. 

30- 

70. 

RECOGNITION  UNDER    OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL.         401 

normal  position  of  blot;  B,  90°  reversal  over  toward  the  left; 
C,  inversion  ;  D,  270°  reversal  over  toward  the  left ;  RXA,  erect 
mirror-reversal ;  and  R^C,  inverted  mirror-reversal.  The  last 
tabulation  of  figures  (Table  III.)  gives  the  numerical  details  of 
the  judgments  on  the  blots  exhibited  to  the  subject  but  once, 
but  judged  as  to  recognition  in  the  same  manner  as  the  rest. 
Of  this  class  there  were  somewhat  over  2000  judgments,  or  70^ 
of  the  whole  number  of  exposures.  It  will  be  noticed  from  this 
second  table  of  result  figures  that  seven  of  the  nine  subjects 
judged  that  they  recognized  approximately  one  out  of  every  five 
of  the  blots  which  in  reality  they  had  not  seen  before,  about 
22<£  of  their  so-called  <  recognitions' of  these  unrepeated  blots 
being  mistaken.  Of  the  two  remaining  subjects,  one  (number 
3),  with  259  of  this  class  of  judgments,  *  recognized'  over  51/0, 
and  the  other  (number  9),  who,  by  the  way,  reported  especially 
*  certainty  in  most  cases,'  thought  that  he  recognized  65.5^  of 
characters  which  he  had  never  before  seen.  On  the  average 
the  percentage  of  false  t  yes  '  judgments  was  30^.  The  cause  of 
a  part  of  this  error  rate  is  evidently  to  be  found  in  the  actual 
formal  similarity  which  some  of  these  chance  blots  bear  to  each 
other,  a  circumstance  not,  however,  to  be  eliminated  from  any 
set  of  objects  of  necessity  so  numerous  ;  indeed,  in  these  charac- 
ters this  similarity  is  reduced  to  a  degree  which  lends  continual 
interest  to  their  use.  Cases  of  great  doubt  were  most  often,  and 
not  unnaturally  perhaps,  put  on  the  '  no'  line  of  judgments,  a 
4  doubtful '  key  and  record-line  having  been  for  a  time  employed, 
but  of  necessity  soon  abandoned,  because  through  its  over-use 
the  research  threatened  to  be  vitiated. 

Having  now  before  us  more  or  less  complete  the  data  of  the 
experiments,  let  us  try  to  make  more  plain  the  circumstances  to 
which  they  relate. 

The  objective  conditions  of  the  research  are  obviously  the 
simplest  which  are  logically  possible  for  a  comprehensive  study 
of  the  natures  of  reversal  and  of  recognition,  the  mental  con- 
fusion of  memory  blot-images,  arising  from  the  large  number 
seen,  serving  only  to  reduce  the  stimulus  to  the  threshold- 
intensity — a  requisite  of  the  method  here  employed.  Owing, 
however,  to  this  confusion,  in  the  main  the  *  feeling  of  recogni- 


402  G.    V.   DEARBORN. 

tion'  was  by  no  means  regularly  present  in  any  degree,  and 
often  not  at  all,  recognition  usually  taking  place  by  the  sug- 
gested association  in  the  reviewing  consciousness  of  some  cog- 
nitional  fact  that  had  formed  part  of  the  perception  or  feeling 
present  when  the  blot  was  first  seen  as  the  norm.  Most  often, 
indeed,  it  was  some  precise  fact,  remembered  in  terms  of  num- 
ber, or  some  extrinsic  suggested  resemblance,  or  even  by  some 
wholly  external  complication  whose  relation  could  not  perhaps 
be  traced.  Very  often  the  recognition  depended  on  the  recall 
of  some  very  small  portion  of  the  blot,  such  as  a  peculiar  point 
or  knob,  or  some  more  than  usually  grotesque  end  or  corner. 
Though  small,  the  characters  were  so  rich  in  detail  that  often 
the  whole  as  such  was  not  in  any  proper  sense  perceived. 
Recognition,  however,  most  often  depended  on  apperception, 
and  not  on  any  feeling  of  recognition,  and  could  be  classed  as 
of  the  mediate,  rather  than  the  immediate  or  general  variety. 

Some  of  the  subjective  notes  as  to  the  various  methods  of 
remembering  and  recalling  may  in  this  connection  have  some 
interest,  although  it  was  not  easy  to  throw  light  on  a  process 
which  required  only  the  brief  times  which  the  subjects  usually 
deemed  sufficient  for  a  *  certain '  judgment  of  a  blot.  Four, 
then,  of  the  subjects  reported  that  the  characters  instantly  called 
up  actual  objects  by  association,  and  that  their  recognition 
occurred  by  this  means.  Two  subjects,  on  the  other  hand, 
reported  that  such  products  of  imagination  did  not  appear  in 
their  cases.  One  subject  (and  he  who  made  more  judgments 
than  any  of  the  others)  reported  a  constant  tendency  for  the 
blots  immediately  to  place  themselves  in  certain  classes  as  re- 
gards general  form  of  outline,  proportional  size  of  their  various 
parts,  mode  of  shading,  etc.  Most  of  the  subjects  remarked 
the  immediacy  of  the  judgment  oftentimes  (obviously  often 
being  wrong  cases  of  auto-suggestion),  and  in  cases  of  great 
doubt,  that  the  ensuing  confusion  made  matters  worse  and 
judgment  sometimes  vain.  Two  subjects  reported  their  method 
to  be  to  *  count  the  tails '  or  projections  of  the  object.  The  two 
subjects  who  made  the  greatest  number  of  wrong  *  yes  '  judg- 
ments made  likewise  the  greatest  number  of  right  *  yes  '  judg- 
ments, one  of  these  two  being  he  who  reported  '  great  certainty,' 


RECOGNITION  UNDER    OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL.         403 

and  the  other  a  man  known  in  his  college  for  his  self-asserted 
unmistakability.  The  subject  who  made  the  smallest  average 
of  recognitions  was  a  man  noted  as  an  unusually  partial  '  mo- 
tile,' who  often  reported  it  most  difficult  for  him  to  recognize  the 
blots  at  all,  although  he  made  more  judgments  than  any  of  the 
other  subjects  save  one.  This  subject,  with  two  others,  also 
reported  that  he  never  apperceived  reversal  as  such,  while  to 
others  it  was  regularly  in  consciousness  when  it  occurred. 
Although  the  same  set  of  blots  was  judged  upon  by  the  same 
subject  in  some  cases  several  times  on  different  days  often  a 
week  or  two  apart,  no  improvement  was  visible  in  the  record  of 
such  a  set,  and  no  suspicion  ever  entered  the  subject's  mind 
that  this  repetition  was  occurring.  This  was  true  in  one  case 
where  the  subject  saw  the  same  set  six  times  with  no  statable 
improvement.  Owing  to  this  circumstance  hundreds  of  blot- 
cards  sufficed  where  else  thousands  would  have  been  required. 
The  time  required  for  each  of  the  more  than  twenty-eight 
hundred  judgments  was  exactly  recorded ;  but  it  has  appeared 
that  so  great  is  the  complexity  of  the  conditions  subjectively 
and  objectively,  especially  as  regards  individual  differences  and 
as  to  temporary  mood,  that  nothing  of  interest  in  this  direction 
can  be  given  in  precise  numerical  terms.  The  reaction  time  for 
the  mechanical  process  of  uncovering  a  blot,  pressing  the  proper 
key  and  overturning  the  blot-card  when  used,  was,  approximately 
on  the  average,  one  second.  The  total  times  vary  then  from 
almost  this  period  to  often  eight  or  ten  seconds ;  the  average 
time  required  was  not  far  from  three  seconds  (and  this  when 
nearly  as  many  minutes  was  the  outer  limit).  Length  of 
judgment  time  seems  to  have  no  constant  relation  to  accu- 
racy, owing  evidently  to  the  quickly-arising  confusion  on  in- 
trospection ;  yet  the  most  accurate  judgments  on  the  average 
were  kmade  by  the  subjects  whose  time  records  are  the  most 
irregular,  as  occasional  retrospection  on  the  occurrence  of  a 
doubt  would  necessitate.  The  inevitable  effort  which  most  sub- 
jects make  to  produce  a  rapid  record,  despite  remonstrances, 
did  much  here,  as  elsewhere  in  psychological  'experiments,  to 
reduce  the  accuracy  of  the  judgments ;  but  as  long  as  human 
nature  remains  as  it  is  it  will  be  so. 


404  G.    V.   DEARBORN. 

The  purpose  of  the  research  was  to  determine  the  relative 
recognizability  of  objects  erect  and  in  various  modes  and  de- 
grees of  reversal.  Let  us  examine  the  results  in  this  regard,  and 
try  to  suggest  their  meaning,  psychological  and  physiological, 
as  far  as  may  be.  Of  the  blots  repeated  or  reviewed  in  the  nor- 
mal or  A-position,  recognitions  were  on  the  average  7°^>>  and 
this  almost  exactly  corroborates  the  average  percentage  of  right 
judgments  as  to  unrepeated  objects,  70/0  being  there  also  the 
nearest  whole  number — in  other  words,  the  average  of  recog- 
nitions of  erect  repetitions  and  the  average  of  non-recognitions 
of  unrepeated  blots  exactly  prove  each  other.  This  70^)  is,  then, 
properly  the  standard  of  the  research,  with  which  the  averages 
under  the  various  reversals  are  to  be  compared.  This  is  the 
proven  general  personal  equation,  so  to  say,  of  recognition  of 
these  objects  when  repeated  exactly,  without  any  objective 
complications.  Using  this,  then,  as  the  standard  of  loofi  (A- 
position,  or  normal) ,  B-reversal,  or  a  quarter-turn  (in  a  direction 
opposite  to  the  hands  of  a  watch),  gives  61.4^0  of  recognitions ; 
the  C-reversal,  or  complete  inversion,  72.8^  recognitions;  the 
D-reversal,  or  a  turning  of  270°,  47.1/0;  the  R*A  reversal,  or 
erect  mirror-position,  65.7^  ;  and  the  RTC  reversal,  or  inverted 
mirror-position,  45.7^  of  recognitions.  In  other  words,  it  ap- 
pears from  the  research  (and  this  is  the  kernel  of  its  interest) 
that  an  object  is  recognized  more  readily  when  inverted  than 
in  either  of  the  two  intermediate  -portions  of  quarter-re- 
versal^ and  more  readily  than  in  the  erect  mirror-position  or 
that  -position  inverted — an  object  upside  down  appears  more 
natural  than  when  turned  on  its  side  or  seen  in  a  mirror.  Fur- 
thermore, one-quarter  reversal  toward  the  left  is  more  favorable 
to  recognition  than  three-quarter  reversal  (important  only  for 
certain  forms)  ;  while  least  favorable  of  the  six  positions  com- 
pared in  these  experiments  is  the  inverted  mirror-reversal,  most 
rarely  encountered  of  them  all  in  general  experience. 

These  facts  are  simple,  while  their  explanation  in  psycho- 
logical terms  is  neither  so  easy  nor  so  sure.  Yet  something  in 
that  direction  may  be  suggested  here. 

The  great  Law  of  Habit,  individual  and  inherited,  seems  in 
general  to  furnish  sufficient  reason  why  uncomplicated  repeti- 


RECOGNITION  UNDER    OBJECTIVE  REVERSAL.         405 

tion — that  is,  when  the  blot-object  is  repeated  in  the  normal  posi- 
tion— should  be  more  easily  recognized  than  in  any  case  of 
several,  this  being  the  condition  ordinarily  in  experience.  Ex- 
periments in  which  the  experimenter  wore  for  some  weeks  be- 
fore his  eye  a  lens  which  inverted  his  field  of  vision  have  proven 
that  it  is  comparatively  easy  to  get  accustomed  to  objective  in- 
version even  of  objects  seldom  or  never  ordinarily  seen  so  re- 
versed. Indeed,  to  the  lowest  orders  of  animal  life  inversion 
must  be  the  rule  of  their  experience,  to  them  making  no  differ- 
ence. It  is  easy  to  conjecture  that  a  sufficient  degree  of  atavism 
in  vision  is  easily  brought  about  even  in  cases  like  those  of  the 
present  research,  making  inversion  relatively  natural ;  further- 
more, it  must  be  remembered,  that  the  retinal  image  is  an  in- 
version of  the  object,  a  fact  adding  little  here,  save  of  possi- 
bility. It  would  be  interesting  to  know  from  experiments  if  a 
person  unfamiliar  writh  either  condition  could  not  learn  to  read 
print  upside  down  more  easily  than  print  made  from  type  turned 
on  their  sides.  At  any  rate,  the  perfect  facility  with  which 
printers  read  directly  from  the  type  in  any  position  as  ordinarily 
set  shows  how  easily  reading  under  inversion  becomes  natural. 

Again,  on  the  other  hand,  vision  of  objects  turned  on  their 
sides  (or  one-quarter  reversed)  is  very  seldom  experienced,  in- 
deed, and  especially  in  the  case  of  unfamiliar  objects.  Noth- 
ing in  organic  structure  or  in  physiologic  habit  affords  practice 
in  this  sort  of  recognition.  The  longer  axis  of  many  of  these 
blots  runs  vertically  or  else  horizontally,  and  from  the  fact  that 
the  right  halves  of  both  retinae  are  *  supplied'  by  only  one  visual 
center,  the  left,  and  vice  versa,  it  is  obvious  that  a  quarter  re- 
versal of  these  objects  would  involve  more  new  brain  elements 
than  would  their  inversion,  and  so  make  them  seem  less  familiar,, 
often  very  likely,  in  the  former  case,  stimulating  both  cortical 
sight  centers  as  not  in  the  latter  case ;  at  any  rate,  implicating 
else  unused  *  apperceptive  cells*  or  regions. 

As  regards  the  apparent  difficulty  of  recognition  under  three- 
quarter  reversal  over  that  in  the  case  of  one-quarter  left  reversal, 
it  is  pertinent,  perhaps,  that  our  almost  universal  habit  in  read- 
ing is  to  begin  at  the  upper  left-hand  corner  of  the  page  or  card, 
thence  looking  along  the  top  ;  and  similarly  more  or  less  in  per- 


406  G.    V.   DEARBORN. 

ceiving  all  plane  representations.  This  firmly-fixed  habit 
doubtless  holds  in  the  perception  of  these  blot-characters,  the 
spot  receiving  the  focus  of  attention  at  first  being  undoubtedly 
in  general  the  upper  left-hand  quadrant  of  the  object,  or  at  least 
so  in  some  degree.  A  quarter-turn  then  would  present  for 
recognition  a  more  or  less  familiar  percept,  while  three-quarters 
reversal  by  the  same  principle  would  offer  to  the  attention  a 
wholly  new  portion  of  the  blot,  a  portion,  in  fact,  at  the  first  in- 
stant of  viewing,  quite  out  of  range  of  the  habitual  perceptive 
field,  and  so,  from  this  circumstance,  less  fully  apperceived. 

With  the  mirror-reversal,  finally,  all  are  fully  familiar  from 
early  and  constant  perception  of  the  hands,  feet  and  limbs  in 
general,  and  from  considerable  experience  with  the  use  of 
mirrors,  both  natural  and  artificial.  Here  again  habit  affords 
relations  which  our  research  only  exemplifies.  Here,  too  (and 
more  exactly"),  the  easily  acquired  habit  of  reading  directly  from 
type  is  an  instance  and  an  illustration.  Add  inversion  to  the 
condition  of  common  mirror-reversal,  and  the  most  complicated 
position  of  the  six  here  studied  is  produced,  a  relation  to  the 
subject  practically  never  experienced  under  ordinary  conditions. 
Habit  here  has  had  no  chance  to  produce  an  effect,  and  we 
have  found  that  the  percentage  of  recognitions  is  in  this  case  the 
lowest  of  them  all. 

Further  experiments  should  amplify  these  results,  employ- 
ing yet  more  involved  relations  between  subject  and  object, 
varying  them  indefinitely.  Especially  would  it  be  of  interest  to 
know  if  subjective  reversal  of  various  sorts  would  bring  out  the 
same  results  as  to  the  habits  of  our  seeing.  Indeed,  subjective 
reversal  would  seem  to  be  a  field  fertile  in  many  respects,  both 
physiological  and  psychological. 


SHORTER  CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

A  LECTURE  EXPERIMENT  IN  HALLUCINATIONS. 

An  experiment  to  illustrate  a  popular  lecture  must  be  striking, 
quick  and  sure  to  work.  As  it  is  not  always  easy  to  tell  beforehand 
whether  an  experiment  will  answer  these  requirements,  the  following 
scheme  for  the  production  of  a  hallucination  of  smell  may  be  worth 
recording.  I  had  prepared  a  bottle  filled  with  distilled  water  carefully 
wrapped  in  cotton  and  packed  in  a  box.  After  some  other  experi- 
ments I  stated  that  I  wished  to  see  how  rapidly  an  odor  would  be  dif- 
fused through  the  air,  and  requested  that  as  soon  as  anyone  perceived 
the  odor  he  should  raise  his  hand.  I  then  unpacked  the  bottle  in  the 
front  of  the  hall,  poured  the  water  over  the  cotton,  holding  my  head 
away  during  the  operation  and  started  a  stop-watch.  While  awaiting 
results  I  explained  that  I  was  quite  sure  that  no  one  in  the  audience 
had  ever  smelled  the  chemical  compound  which  I  had  poured  out,  and 
expressed  the  hope  that,  while  they  might  find  the  odor  strong  and 
peculiar,  it  would  not  be  too  disagreeable  to  anyone.  In  fifteen  sec- 
onds most  of  those  in  the  front  row  had  raised  their  hands,  and  in  forty 
seconds  the  '  odor'  had  spread  to  the  back  of  the  hall,  keeping  a  pretty 
regular  '  wave  front '  as  it  passed  on.  About  three-fourths  of  the  audi- 
ence claimed  to  perceive  the  smell,  the  obstinate  minority  including 
more  men  than  the  average  of  the  whole.  More  would  probably  have 
succumbed  to  the  suggestion,  but  at  the  end  of  a  minute  I  was  obliged 
to  stop  the  experiment,  for  some  on  the  front  seats  were  being  unpleas- 
antly affected  and  were  about  to  leave  the  room.  No  one  in  the  audi- 
ence seemed  offended  when  it  was  explained  that  the  real  object  of  the 
experiment  was  the  production  of  a  hallucination. 

Hallucinations  of  temperature  or  pain  are  easily  induced  by  sug- 
gestion in  susceptible  individuals  by  the  use  of  magnets,  though  the  ex- 
periment is  not  suitable  for  lecture  purposes.  It  is.  of  course,  necessary 
that  the  subject  should  have  hazy  ideas  about  magnetism,  but  it  is  un- 
fortunately only  too  easy  to  find  such  persons.  The  'magnet'  need 
not  be  magnetized,  but  should  have  plainly  marked  poles  and  the  sug- 
gestion be  conveyed  by  suitable  '  patter ',  to  use  a  conjurer's  phrase. 
-Sensations  of  heat  may  be  produced  by  the  north  pole  of  the  magnet, 

407 


408  MYSTICISM. 

and  cold  by  the  south,  or  one  pole  may  be  made  to  give  a  tingling  or 
smarting  pain  in  the  right  hand  and  side  of  the  body,  and  the  south 
pole  on  the  left,  or  any  other  such  scheme  not  too  complicated.  The 
illustrated  magazine  articles  of  the  effects  produced  on  hypnotized  sub- 
jects by  Luys,  with  magnets  and  sealed  tubes  of  chemicals,  are  useful 
to  reinforce  the  suggestions.  Of  course,  the  deception  should  be 
thoroughly  explained  after  the  experiment,  not  only  because  otherwise 
the  subject  sometimes  complains  of  pain  in  the  hand  worked  upon,  but 
also  in  order  that  the  experiment  may  serve  as  a  lesson  to  the  sub- 
ject no  less  than  to  the  spectators. 

Slight  hallucinations  of  sound  are  easily  induced;  but  I  have  never 
succeeded  in  getting  unhypnotized  subjects  to  see  red  and  blue  flames 
on  the  poles  of  a  magnet,  or  in  obtaining  any  similar  hallucinations  of 
sight.  Simple  experiments  in  suggestion  on  persons  in  a  normal  state 
are  generally  better  for  demonstration  than  the  more  striking  results 
obtained  in  hypnosis. 

E.  E.  SLOSSON. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  WYOMING. 


PROFESSOR  HYSLOP   ON  MYSTICISM. 

In  the  last  number  of  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW  Professor 
Hyslop  criticises  a  paper  on  Psychology  and  Mysticism  which  I  pub- 
lished in  the  Atlantic  Monthly,  and  have  since  reprinted  as  the  last 
essay  of  my  recently  published  book  '  Psychology  and  Life/  My 
paper  was  for  him  '  one  of  the  most  amusing  documents  that  he  has 
ever  had  the  pleasure  of  reading.'  I  have  not  the  slightest  desire  to 
disturb  this  happy  mood  of  amusement  by  a  serious  defence  against  his 
attacks.  A  scientific  defence  or  discussion  must  have  as  its  aim  that 
the  opponent  shall  understand  and  agree  with  me ;  but  I  feel  myself 
so  absolutely  free  from  this  ambitious  aim  that  a  discussion  is  really 
superfluous.  In  regard  to  only  one  passage  of  my  paper  does  he  claim 
that  he  does  understand  what  I  wish  to  say  and  would  agree  with  me  j 
it  is  my  reference  to  communication.  "As  to  what  Professor  Muen- 
sterberg  may  intend  by  this  description  of  the  communication  of 
ideas  I  can  well  imagine.  But  I  can  do  it  only  by  having  some 
knowledge  of  the  process  myself,  and  not  from  any  statement  that  he 
makes."  And  then  he  goes  on  to  interpret  my  meaning  in  a  way 
which  is,  in  every  respect,  the  exact  opposite  of  my  thought,  and  which 
would  deprive  my  arguments  of  all  meaning.  If  he  had  not  found 
anything  in  the  paper  which  he  believed  himself  to  understand,  I 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.        409 

should,  perhaps,  have  taken  the  trouble  to  enter  into  a  discussion  that 
he  might  feel  that  he  understood  me.  But  after  this  test  case  I 
know  that  we  think  with  a  different  logic,  and  I  prefer  that  my  state- 
ments continue  to  be  for  him  '  blank  nonsense.'  I,  therefore,  do  not 
argue,  but  wish  merely  to  put  straight  a  few  facts  which  Professor 
Hyslop  mentions  as  if  he  objectively  reproduced  my  own  words  and 
statements,  and  where  the  reader  of  his  criticism  might  believe  that  I 
am  truly  represented. 

Professor  Hyslop  says:  u  His  reason  for  not  making  a  personal 
investigation  into  this  question  is  that  it  is  not  '  dignified  to  visit  such 
performances  '  as  Seances  !  !  "  That  is  all,  and  what  follows  are  merely 
exclamations  of  contempt  for  such  an  utterance.  My  text  sasy  this : 
"  I  consider  it  undignified  to  visit  such  performances  as  one  attends  a 
variety  show  for  amusement  only,  without  attempting  to  explain  them." 
Is  it  really  possible  not  to  see  the  difference  between  my  statement, 
with  which  every  decent  scientist  will  agree,  and  his  false  denuncia- 
tion, which  must  make  me  contemptible  to  every  scientific  man  ? 

Another  illustration  :  "  Professor  Miinsterberg  did  not  distinguish 
between  the  relevancy  of  the  various  alleged  phenomena  that  he  was 
criticizing ;  table  turning,  telepathy,  clairvoyance,  hypnotism  and  what 
not  were  lumped  together  with  no  more  conception  of  their  differences 
than  is  usually  displayed  by  the  spiritualist  himself."  This  is,  indeed, 
very  bad  on  my  part ;  but  the  reader  will  become  a  little  milder  if  he 
chances  to  take  the  trouble  to  open  my  article,  and  convince  himself 
that  more  than  half  of  the  paper  is  expressly  devoted  to  the  clean 
discrimination  of  these  and  similar  conceptions,  and  to  the  disentangle- 
ment of  hypnotism  from  the  rest. 

A  third  illustration:  I  had  said  that  up  to  the  last  summer  vacation, 
in  which  I  read  systematically  telepathic  and  spiritualistic  litera- 
ture :  "  I  had  not  really  studied  all  the  recorded  Phantasms  of  the  Liv- 
ing and  all  the  Proceedings  of  the  Societies  for  Psychical  Research, 
and  I  am  afraid  I  had  forgotten  to  cut  the  leaves  of  some  of  the  occult 
magazines  on  my  own  shelves."  Out  of  this  material  Professor 
Hyslop  makes  a  confession,  on  my  side,  that  until  the  last  summer 
vacation  I  felt  guilty  of  forming  and  stating  opinions  on  this  subject 
4  before  reading  its  literature.'  Because  I  have  not  read  4  all  the  re- 
ports'  and  '  all  the  proceedings'  I  have  not  read  the  literature.  If  I 
really  did  not  care  to  read  the  literature,  why  did  I  then  subscribe  for 
the  occult  magazines  on  my  shelves?  And  immediately  after  it,  Pro- 
fessor Hyslop  says  that  he  himself  thinks  that  there  are  not  twenty-five 
volumes  in  existence  on  this  subject  that  any  sane  man  ought  to  read 


410  PSYCHOLOGY  AND  LIFE. 

at  all.  As  all  the  reports  fill  hundreds  of  volumes,  he  thus  says  clearly 
that  a  sane  man  ought  not  to  read  them  all ;  and  yet  because  I  say  that 
I  had  not  read  them  '  all '  he  denounces  me  for  confessing  that  I 
formed  opinions  4  before  reading  the  literature.' 

I  do  not  care  to  go  on ;  the  other  remarks  are  in  the  same  spirit. 
Professor  Hyslop  says  about  me  :  u  He  thinks  the  scientist  is  trained  to 
an  instinctive  confidence  in  his  cooperators ;"  and  he  answers  :  "  A  man 
who  cannot  protect  himself  against  fraud  must  not  expect  his  opinion 
to  be  worth  very  much."  I  think  both  sides  are  correct  here.  I 
think,  indeed,  that  a  scientist  is  trained  to  an  instinctive  confidence  in 
his  cooperators,  and  I  for  one  am  inclined  to  consider  in  this  sense 
even  my  critics  as  my  cooperators,  expecting  that  in  spite  of  disagree- 
ment they  will  quote  me  correctly.  But  if  the  distortion  transcends 
certain  limits,  I  think  Professor  Hyslop  is  right  in  demanding  that  the 
scientist  ought  to  discover  it,  and  thus  to  protect  himself  in  spite  of 
his  instinctive  supposition  that  such  things  are  impossible. 

HUGO  MUNSTERBERG. 

HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 


PSYCHOLOGY  AND   LIFE. 

The  appearance  of  Professor  Miinsterberg's  book  with  the  above 
title  calls  attention  afresh  to  the  various  points  which  have  been  criti- 
cised as  the  chapters  have  appeared  in  the  Atlantic  Monthly  and  else- 
where. 

Professor  Miinsterberg  refers  to  my  former  reply  to  one  of  his 
articles  (not  reprinted)  as  an  unjust  criticism,  and  one  which  leaves  his 
opponent  still  unreconciled.  I  hasten  to  assure  Professor  Miinster- 
berg that  his  subsequent  article  on  Education,  reprinted  in  this  col- 
lection, fully  grants  all  I  ever  thought  of  asking  in  that  criticism,  and 
much  more. 

I  do  not  think  it  wise,  at  present,  to  try  to  teach  experimental 
psychology  in  the  high  school.  At  the  same  time  I  wish  to  protest 
against  the  fundamental  position  of  this  whole  book,  in  the  hope  that 
certain  other  points  of  difference  may  be  as  happily  adjusted. 

I  am  certainly  in  hearty  sympathy  with  the  great  questions  at 
stake.  Professor  Miinsterberg  is  to  be  congratulated  upon  the  whole- 
hearted way  in  which  he  emphasizes  the  realities  of  life,  of  the  will, 
of  feelings  and  their  values,  over  against  the  mechanical,  lifeless  forms 
of  which  we  see  so  much  in  current  psychology.  But  what  higher 
law  makes  it  necessary  to  set  these  realities  outside  of  psychology  ? 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.       411 

Who  determines  the  limits  of  our  science,  and  says  we  shall  not  include 
in  it  anything  not  fully  explained  by  the  law  of  causation  ?  Who  says 
the  biologist  may  not  stand  face  to  face  with  the  facts  of  life  even 
while  he  is  a  scientist  ? 

Undoubtedly  the  feelings  of  effort  and  strain  connected  with  will 
acts  are  sensations ;  but,  after  taking  them  away,  very  much  is  left. 
Why,  then,  is  it  necessary  to  step  outside  of  our  text-book  of  psychol- 
ogy to  say  so,  and  to  call  upon  the  student  to  go  to  real  life  to  see  for 
himself  what  mind  is  ? 

The  same  is  true  of  the  emotions.  The  pleasures  of  expanding 
chest  and  relaxing  muscles  as  one  watches  a  sunset  are  sensations ;  but 
something  remains  after  these  are  subtracted,  and  psychology  has  a 
right  to  call  attention  to  the  fact. 

If  necessary,  in  order  to  admit  these  subjects  to  psychology,  I 
should  be  willing  to  question  the  fundamental  propositions  in  Pro- 
fessor Miinsterberg's  epistemology  which  makes  it  necessary  for  him 
so  to  limit  psychology.  The  world  of  things  and  the  world  of  ideas 
are  not  two  sides  of  the  same  thing  in  any  sense  in  which  the  world  of 
will  and  feeling  is  not  also  a  side  of  the  same  reality. 

All  the  history  and  traditions  of  American  psychology  call  for  a 
study  of  real  life.  That  is  what  has  given  psychology  the  place  it  has 
always  held  in  our  colleges  and  universties;  what  gives  it  its  firm 
position  among  the  sciences  to-day.  Psychology  is  dealing  with  real 
life,  and  is  able  to  make  that  life  richer  and  fuller.  Experimental 
psychology's  recent  development  rests  upon  that  very  fact. 

No  sensationalism  or  mechanical  theory  of  association  will  ever 
take  the  place  of  a  Hopkins,  a  Porter,  or  a  McCosh. 

Professor  Mtinsterberg's  insistence  upon  the  realities  of  the  inner 
life  is  but  one  sign  of  a  returning  of  psychologists  to  real  life.  Let 
us  make  our  psychology  broader  and  deeper,  not  give  it  up  altogether, 
if  this,  his  new  view,  prevails. 

We  might  go  back  to  the  old  name,  mental  philosophy;  or  we 
might  adopt  some  new  name,  like  ethology,  which  has  been  recently 
suggested.  But  the  word  psychology  has  proved  its  right  to  remain. 
In  the  minds  of  men  at  large  it  does  stand  for  reality,  and  that  is  why 
the  world  is  turning  to  psychologists  for  solution  of  the  problems  of 
life.  We  ought  not  to  refuse  to  answer  while  we  settle  questions  of 
terms  or  the  imaginary  limits  of  our  science. 

CHAS.  B.  BLISS. 
LEONARD'S  BRIDGE,  CT. 


412  ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE. 

A    REPLY    TO    "THE   NATURE    OF   ANIMAL    INTELLI- 
GENCE AND  THE  METHODS  OF  INVESTI- 
GATING IT."1 

My  first  duty  is  to  beg  the  reader's  pardon  for  a  certain  personal 
tone  in  this  discussion.  As  Professor  Mills  has  mentioned  Dr.  Thorn- 
dike  twenty-nine  times  in  his  article,  this  reply  will  of  necessity  con- 
tain the  word  4 1 '  oftener  than  one  would  wish. 

There  are  two  sorts  of  assertions  in  Professor  Mills'  article  :  first,  a 
number  of  important  objections  to  a  certain  method  of  studying 
animal  psychology ;  second,  a  number  of  attacks  on  my  '  Experimental 
Study  of  the  Associative  Processes  in  Animals.'2  The  former  I  am 
glad  to  have  the  opportunity  to  discuss,  because  they  should  be  of  real 
interest  to  all  comparative  psychologists.  The  latter  can  be  safely  left 
to  the  judgment  of  anyone  who  has  read  the  monograph  itself,  and 
will  be  taken  up  here  only  because  that  monograph  has  probably  been 
seen  by  only  a  few  of  the  many  who  have  read  the  attack  upon  it. 

Let  us  turn  first  to  the  important  objections  to  my  method  of 
studying  the  formation  of  associations  in  animals.  I  say  my  method, 
because  it  seems  likely  to  be  thought  of  chiefly  in  connection  with  my 
experiments,  though  Lubbock  used  practically  the  same  method  with 
insects.  It  is,  in  fact,  odd  that  Lubbock's  recommendation  as  to  in- 
sects was  not  sooner  followed  with  mammals.  He  says,  "  In  order  to 
test  their  intelligence,  it  has  always  seemed  to  me  that  there  was  no 
better  way  than  to  ascertain  some  object  which  they  would  clearly  de- 
sire, and  then  to  interpose  some  obstacle  which  a  little  ingenuity  would 
enable  them  to  overcome"  (Ants,  Bees  and  Wasps,  N.  Y.,  1896,  p. 
247).  He  used  food  as  the  ;  object,'  as  I  did,  and  interposed  mechan- 
ical obstacles  as  I  did. 

Professor  Mills'  weightiest  objection  is  that,  when  confined  while 
hungry  in  such  boxes  and  pens  as  I  used,  the  dogs  and  cats  were  in  a 
4  panic-stricken '  condition  and,  therefore,  temporarily  lost  their  normal 
wits.  Now,  it  is  true  that  in  many  of  the  trials  with  cats  and  chicks, 
notably  the  first  ten  or  twenty  trials  with  each  animal,  there  is  often, 
as  I  fully  noted,  great  violence  and  fury  of  activity.  And  this  might 
be  the  result  of  mental  panic,  and  so  might  be  a  sign  of  a  loss  of 
normal  mentality.  But  the  animals  (the  dogs  and  some  of  the  cats) 
which  did  not  display  this  excitement  and  fury  did  not  display  any 
variation  in  the  results  toward  more  intelligence.  Nor  did  the  animals 

1  By  Professor  Wesley  Mills,  pp.  262-274  of  the  May  number  of  THE  PSY- 
CHOLOGICAL REVIEW. 

2  Animal  Intelligence,  Monograph  Supplement,  No.  VIII.,  to  THE  PSYCHO- 
LOGICAL REVIEW. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.       413 

which  showed  certain  results  in  the  experiments  of  which  confinement 
in  small  boxes  was  an  essential  feature  show  any  variation  from  those 
results  in  the  experiments  (see  pp.  87-91  and  96  of  the  monograph 
already  cited)  in  which  there  was  no  excitement,  no  different  activity 
from  that  shown  all  the  time.  In  these  experiments  the  cats  were  in 
the  big  cage  which  had  been  their  home  for  weeks. 

Furthermore,  it  seems  unlikely  that  in  the  case  of  the  animals  which 
had  already  been  the  subjects  of  two  or  three  experiments,  and  which 
had  been  in  such  boxes  a  hundred  or  more  times,  the  violence  and 
fury  of  activity  could  have  been  the  result  of  fear  or  in  any  way  a  sign 
of  its  presence.  For,  as  was  stated  in  the  monograph,  such  animals 
which  have  been  made  during  a  number  of  trials  to  crawl  into  these 
boxes  which  Professor  Mills  supposes  were  so  disturbing  to  them, 
habitually  of  their  own  accord  'went  into  them  again  and  again. 
Nor  did  they  try  to  escape  when  I  picked  them  up  to  drop  them  in. 
In  the  experiments  in  which  I  moved  the  animal's  limbs,  putting  him 
through  the  movements,  there  was  after  from  o  to  12  trials  no  fear  of 
my  handling.  (See  p.  68  of  the  monograph.) 

In  short,  all  evidences  of  panic  may  be  absent  without  any 
change  in  mental  functioning,  and  the  only  cause  of  mental  panic 
which  would  seem  probable,  namely,  fear,  was  certainly  not  present 
in  the  greater  number  of  the  experiments.  So  I  feel  bound  still  to 
maintain  the  account  given  in  the  monograph,  and  attribute  the  animal's 
fury  of  activity  not  to  mental  panic,  but  to  a  useful  instinctive  reaction 
to  confinement.  It  should  be  remembered  that  even  in  the  midst  of 
the  utmost  activity  the  cats  would  take  instant  advantage  of  any  chance 
to  escape  which  appealed  to  their  instinctive  equipment  (e.  g.,  the 
widening  of  an  orifice).  It  should  further  be  remembered  that  the 
most  violent  animals  did  the  most  pseudo-intelligent  acts.  If  any  one 
of  the  eight  or  ten  psychologists  and  biologists  who  saw  the  experi- 
ments in  progress  had  seen  signs  of  mental  panic  in  the  animals  I 
should  have  inserted  this  discussion  in  the  monograph.  But  I  venture 
to  think  that  if  Professor  Mills  had  repeated  five  or  six  of  my  experi- 
ments he  would  have  discarded  this  mental  panic  objection. 

The  next  important  objection  is  that  the  surroundings  were  unnat- 
ural. I  myself  long  since  criticised  my  method  on  these  grounds,1 
and  I  am  and  always  have  been  ready  to  admit  that  an  animal  may  be 
able  to  reason  with  certain  data,  to  imitate  certain  acts,  and  yet  be  un- 
able to  reason  with  the  data  with  which  you  confront  him  or  imitate 
the  act  you  present  as  a  model.  For  that  reason  I  chose  varied  acts, 
Science,  Vol.  VIII.,  No.  198,  p.  520. 


4H  ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE. 

very  simple  acts,  trying  each  with  different  animals  and  making  many 
of  them  approach  very  closely  to  acts  common  in  animal  life,  and 
making  others  practically  identical  with  acts  which  have  been  recorded 
as  proofs  of  high  mental  ability  in  animals  (vide  the  experiments  with 
boxes  C,  D  and  G) .  We  have  seen  that  so  far  as  the  mere  being  in 
boxes  is  concerned  the  animals  soon  got  used  to  it,  did  not  fear  it,  and 
presumably  could  and  did  use  their  mental  powers  while  in  that  situa- 
tion. If  Prof essor  Mills  had  specified  some  particular  situation  as  un- 
natural, and  argued  in  concrete  terms  that  its  remoteness  from  the  or- 
dinary conditions  of  animal  life  made  it  unfit  to  call  forth  what  mental 
functions  the  animal  had,  I  should  here  either  try  to  show  that  it  was 
fit  to  call  them  forth  or  confess  that  from  the  animal's  conduct  in  it  no 
conclusion  could  be  drawn  save  the  one  that  the  animal's  mentality 
was  such  as  was  not  aroused  thereby.  Even  this  one  conclusion  would 
be  valuable.  Even  if  we  had  to  say,  '  all  that  these  experiments  prove  is 
that  these  circumstances  will  not  cause  the  animal  to  manifest  memory, 
imitation,  etc.,'  we  should  be  saying  a  good  deal,  for  the  advocates  of 
the  reason  theory  have  pretty  uniformly  given  as  evidence  the  reac- 
tions of  animals  to  novel  mechanical  continuances. 

Professor  Mills  does  not  argue  in  concrete  terms,  does  not  criticise 
concrete  unfitness  in  the  situations  I  devised  for  the  animals.  He 
simply  names  them  unnatural.  Moreover,  it  would  seem  that  he 
makes  this  word  face  two  ways.  When  talking  of  my  experiments,  he 
uses  the  word  in  the  sense  of  novel,  unfamiliar  to  the  animal.  When 
arguing  that  my  conclusions  are  wrong,  he  uses  the  word  in  the  sense 
of  beyond  the  limits  of  their  mental  functions,  abhorrent  to  their  nor- 
mal intellection.  Of  course,  the  former  may  be  true  and  the  latter 
false.  The  fact  that  cats  are  not  ordinarily  treated  as  mine  were  does 
not  imply  that  my  cats  could  not  and  did  not  come  to  be  at  home  in 
the  life  I  imposed  on  them  to  such  an  extent  that  they  could  use 
therein  all  the  general  intellectual  functions  they  possessed.  Professor 
Mills  himself  has  based  statements  about  the  presence  of  certain  men- 
tal functions  on  the  conduct  of  a  kitten  in  gaining  a  certain  resting- 
place  (in  a  bookcase,  if  I  remember  rightly),  in  spite  of  mechanical 
obstacles  interposed.  The  situation  here  coped  with  is  as  'un- 
natural' as  that  in  a  majority  of  my  experiments. 

The  general  argument  of  the  monograph  is  used  in  all  sorts  of 
scientific  work  and  is  simple  enough.  It  says:  "If  dogs  and  cats 
have  such  and  such  mental  functions,  they  will  do  so  and  so  in  certain 
situations  and  will  not  do  so  and  so ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  ab- 
sence of  the  function  in  question  will  lead  to  the  presence  of  certain 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.       415 

things  and  the  absence  of  certain  other  things."  To  provide  the  *  cer- 
tain situations'  was  the  task  my  experiments  undertook.  It  is  mere 
rhetoric  to  damn  the  whole  argument  with  a  word,  *  unnatural.'  The 
thing  to  do  is  to  show  the  error  in  the  logic  or  the  disturbing  factor  in 
each  experiment,  to  repeat  the  experiment  minus  that  factor,  get  oppo- 
site results,  and  so  refute  my  claims.  Dr.  Kline  has  in  one  slight 
case  gained  results  by  the  use  of  more  4  natural '  surroundings  and  his 
results  agree  with  mine.  (See  Am.  J.  of  Psy.,  Vol.  X,  pp.  277—8.) 
I  may  say  here  that  Dr.  Kline  has  in  this  article  treated  of  fear  and 
novel  surroundings  as  disturbing  features  in  my  experiments  more  dis- 
criminatingly, perhaps,  than  Professor  Mills,  and  that  this  paper  is  in- 
tended to  be  an  explanation  which  will  satisfy  his  criticisms  as  well  as 
those  of  the  latter. 

Observational  records  are,  as  I  said  in  the  review  in  Science  which 
has  already  been  quoted,  of  very  great  value ;  but  the  fact  remains  that 
the  host  of  observations  so  far  collected,  including  the  large  number 
of  Professor  Mills'  own  to  which  he  refers  on  page  264,  had  not  pro- 
vided us  with  agreement  about  the  presence  of  a  single  general  func- 
tion in  animal  consciousness  that  was  in  dispute.  I  tried,  therefore,  to 
devise  situations  in  which  the  conduct  of  the  animals  might  be  really 
illuminating.  It  would  seem  that  Professor  Mills  allows  that  if  the 
experiments  were  only  free  from  the  disturbing  factors  we  have  been 
talking  about,  the  conclusions  reached  would  be  probably  true,  for  he 
does  not  criticise  the  logic  of  the  deductions.  Now  these  conclusions 
are  so  far  reaching  that  I  am  reviled  for  even  pretending  to  have  made 
such  important  ones.  But  this  goes  to  show  just  that  the  method  will, 
if  we  can  show  that  these  factors  are  not  present,  or  can  modify  the 
method  so  as  to  exclude  them,  get  us  somewhere  psychologically.  So 
my  general  plea  for  experiments  in  animal  psychology  is  that  they  at 
least  pretend  to  give  us  an  explanatory  psychology,  and  not  fragments 
of  natural  history. 

Finally,  just  as  in  experiments  like  mine  you  may  miss  the  truth 
by  some  mistake  you  make  in  picking  the  circumstances,  the  situation 
to  test  the  presence  of  a  function,  so  in  the  mere  observation  of  the 
habitual  life  of  animals  or  the  experimental  regulation  of  their  ordi- 
nary activities,  you  may  miss  the  truth  by  mistaking  instinctive  for 
imitative  acts,  associative  for  rational  acts,  permanent  associations  for 
memories.  For  instance,  Professor  Mills  offers  in  his  article,  as  a  proof 
of  the  presence  of  an  imitative  faculty,  an  act  (p.  268)  which  might 
very  possibly  have  been  the  result  of  the  instinct  to  follow  common  to 
so  many  young  animals,  so  far  as  one  can  judge  from  his  account — 


ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE. 

"a  student  of  McGill  University  has  communicated  to  me  the  fact 
that  a  kitten  which  could  not  be  induced  to  jump  over  an  object  placed 
before  it,  did  so  only  after  seeing  the  mother  do  it,  and  after  that  there 
was  no  more  trouble  in  getting  it  to  perform  the  trick."  We  shall  see 
that  another  observation,  that  of  the  dog  and  the  tree,  which  Professor 
Mills  quotes  to  refute  me,  may  have  suffered  in  the  interpretation. 

Of  course,  it  is  clear  that  the  psychological  story  told  by  correct 
experimentation  will  not  conflict  with  the  story  told  by  correct  obser- 
vations reported  correctly  at  first,  second  or  tenth  hand.  But  I  am 
not  yet  sure  that  any  trustworthy  observation  about  the  interpretation 
of  which  there  is  general  agreement,  conflicts  with  the  results  of 
my  observations  under  test  conditions  in  such  a  way  as  to  render  nec- 
essary the  presupposition  that  in  them  there  was  some  vital  flaw. 
Such  refutation  of  them  may  come,  but  Professor  Mills  does  not  seem 
to  have  brought  it. 

So  much  in  general  defence  of  the  methods  I  used.  It  may  now 
be  permitted  to  mention  some  matters  of  detail:  Professor  Mills 
finds  in  the  printed  report  of  my  experiments  signs  of  conceit  and  of 
lack  of  4  respect  for  workers  of  the  past  of  any  complexion/  For 
psychological  interpretations  of  the  sort  given  by  Romanes  and  Lindsay 
I  certainly  had  and  have  no  respect,  though,  of  course,  I  esteem  them 
for  their  zeal.  But  I  cannot  see  that  the  presence  or  absence  of  me- 
galomania in  me  is  of  any  interest  to  comparative  psychology.  The 
monograph  in  question  was  not  a  presentation  of  personal  opinion,  but 
of  certain  facts,  the  accuracy  of  which,  and  of  certain  impersonal  induc- 
tions and  deductions,  the  logic  of  which,  should  be  attacked  imperson- 
ally. The  question  is  whether  certain  facts  exist  and  what  they  mean  , 
and  does  not  concern  the  individual  psychology  of  any  person. 

Professor  Mills'  humor  in  making  believe  that  because  I  character- 
ize Lloyd  Morgan  as  the  ;  sanest '  of  comparative  psychologists,  I 
think  of  them  all  as  insane  (p.  263),  seems  a  bit  disingenuous  in  view 
of  the  fact  that  his  article  will  probably  be  the  sole  source  of  informa- 
tion about  my  book  to  a  large  number  of  people.  Of  course,  when 
I  wrote  '  sanest,'  I  meant  sanest.  Had  I  meant  '  least  insane '  I  should 
assuredly  have  so  written.  On  page  264  our  author  says,  <  He '  (Dr. 
Thorndike)  '  comes  very  near  to  the  belief  that  they  are  automata  pure 
and  simple,  though  this  he  does  not  assert  in  so  many  words.'  This, 
I  may  be  permitted  to  say,  is  an  absolute  misrepresentation.  In  every 
associative  process  discussed  in  the  book  I  find  present  as  an  impor- 
tant element,  impulses,  and  impulse  I  expressly  define  as  '  the  con- 
sciousness accompanying,'  etc.  (p.  14).  Again,  I  speak  everywhere 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND    DISCUSSIONS.       417 

of  the  pleasure  resulting  from  the  attainment  of  freedom,  food,  etc., 
as  stamping  in  the  connection  between  sense-impression  and  impulse. 
So,  also,  I  speak  everywhere  of  the  sense-impression  as  the  starting- 
point  of  the  mental  association.  As  a  fact,  mental  processes  are  men- 
tioned throughout  the  whole  discussion.  The  one  place  where  I 
frankly  offered  opinion  in  addition  to  fact  was  where  I  also  attributed 
representations  to  animals :  '  my  opinion  would  be  that  animals  do 
have  representations,  and  that  such  are  the  beginning  of  the  rich  life  of 
ideas  in  man'  (p.  77).  Again,  after  an  attempt  to  '  describe  graphic- 
ally *  *  *  the  mental  fact  we  have  been  studying,'  I  say  (p.  89)  :  u  Yet 
there  is  consciousness  enough  at  the  time,  keen  consciousness  of  the 
sense-impressions,  impulses,  feelings  of  one's  bodily  acts.  So  with 
the  animals.  There  is  consciousness  enough,  but  of  this  kind." 

On  page  264  Professor  Mills  talks  as  if  I  were  trying  to  answer  the 
question  as  to  whether  the  animal  mind  was  comparable  to  the  human 
mind,  and  to  answer  it  in  the  negative  for  the  sake  of  exalting  the 
human  mind  above  the  realm  of  natural  evolution.  The  reader  of  the 
monograph  will  remember  that  one  of  the  results  of  the  study  was  the 
attainment  of  a  possible  mental  evolution  of  an  entirely  natural  sort. 
I  never  tried  to  answer  the  question,  '  How  far  does  the  mentality  of 
a  dog  or  cat  equal  that  of  man  in  general,  genus  homo,'  for  such  a 
question  seems  to  me  fruitless.  It  is  like  asking  how  far  is  2  like  x. 
The  mentality  of  man  in  general  is  an  unknown  quantity,  has  a  lot  of 
possible  values  and  so  cannot  be  well  used  as  a  measure  of  anything. 
Any  answer  to  it  will  be  partially  false  and  partially  meaningless. 
Whether  cats  infer  and  compare,  whether  they  imitate  as  present  day 
adult  human  beings  known  to  psychologists  do,  whether  they  form 
associations  minus  impulses  of  their  own,  are  clear,  answerable  ques- 
tions. Such  I  tried  to  answer.  To  say  or  to  prove  that  the  human 
mind  of  Europeans  of  to-day  comes  by  continuous  evolution  from  the 
animal  mind  does  not  make  the  latter  any  higher,  endow  it  with  a 
single  new  function  nor  alter  it  one  whit.  The  protozoa  are  not  at  all 
different  from  what  they  were  before  after  we  call  them  the  ancestors 
of  the  vertebrates.  And  one  is  free,  it  seems  to  me,  to  find  out  about 
questions  of  descriptive  psychology,  as  well  as  of  morphology,  with- 
out meddling  with  questions  of  classification. 

On  page  265  Professor  Mills  rebukes  me  for  considering  hunger 
the  strongest  stimulus  to  animals.  Of  course,  I  did  not  so  consider  it, 
and  I  am  not  aware  of  anything  in  the  monograph  which  even  looks 
as  if  I  did. 

Again,  on  this  same  page  he  misrepresents  me  by  quoting  a  sentence 


41 8  ANIMAL   INTELLIGENCE. 

without  its  context  and,  indeed,  with  comments  which  positively  give  a 
wrong  notion  of  the  context.  The  sentence  is :  *  the  question  of 
whether  an  animal  does  or  does  not  form  a  certain  association  requires 
for  an  answer  no  higher  qualification  than  a  pair  of  eyes.'  This  sen- 
tence, as  anyone  may  see  by  reading  pages  5,  6  and  7  of  the  mono- 
graph, refers  to  the  particular  associations  involved  in  learning  to 
escape  from  boxes.  And  whether  an  animal  does  or  does  not  learn  to 
escape  from  a  box  certainly  can  be  observed  by  anyone  with  a  pair  of 
eyes.  And  as  the  text  clearly  states,  it  was  just  because  I  did  not  wish 
to  impose  on  any  one  my  own  opinions  or  even  observations,  because 
I  wanted  to  use  a  method  which  any  one  else  could  employ  and  gain 
results  which  any  one  else  could  verify  or  refute,  that  I  planned  experi- 
ments which  depended,  so  to  speak,  on  impersonal  eyes,  eyes  in  gen- 
eral, for  many  of  their  results.  I  unhesitatingly  affirm  that  so  far  as 
the  facts  of  escape  or  non-escape  and  the  time  records  (and  the  sen- 
tence concerns  nothing  else),  Professor  Mills  or  any  one  else  would 
have  kept  just  the  same  records  as  I  myself  did — that  his  eyes  would 
have  seen  no  more  nor  less  than  mine. 

On  page  267  I  am  accused  of  sacrificing  particulars  about  facts  for 
the  sake  of  rhetoric,  again  on  the  basis  of  an  entirely  misrepresented 
quotation.  On  pages  38  and  39  of  the  monograph  I  say  that  henceforth 
I  shall  frequently  use  the  word  '  animal '  or  i  animals '  when  I  mean  to 
make  statements  only  about  the  particular  score  of  animals  which  were 
the  subjects  of  my  experiments,  as  "  really  I  claim  for  my  animal  psy- 
chology only  that  it  is  the  psychology  of  just  these  particular  animals." 
After  giving  one  reason  for  this  verbal  usage  I  add,  "  my  second  rea- 
son is  that  I  hate  to  burden  the  reader  with  the  disgusting  rhetoric 
which  would  result  if  I  had  to  insert  particularizations  and  reserva- 
tions at  every  step."  Professor  Mills  quotes,  omitting  the  first  five 
words,  and  giving  the  impression  that  I  generally  omitted  details  so  as  to 
have  good  paragraphs  or  something  of  that  sort,  whereas  the  only  '  par- 
ticularizations' to  which  I  objected  were  such  as  saying,  Cats  i  (8— 10 
months),  2  (5-7  months),  3  (5-11  months)  etc.,  up  to  cat  13;  Dogs 
etc.,  etc.,  did  not  do  so  and  so  every  page  or  two,  when  by  means  of 
this  little  note  upon  verbal  usage  the  reader  could  on  each  occasion 
interpret  the  word  «  animals'  to  mean  "  the  particular  animals  which 
he  observed,  not  necessarily  all  animals."  The  rhetorical  excellence 
thus  gained  requires  absolutely  no  sacrifice  of  fact  of  any  sort. 

If  I  were  sure  that  Professor  Mills  would  enjoy  a  bit  of  jocularity, 
I  should  reply  to  his  explanation  of  the  failure  of  my  animals  to  imi- 
tate, by  his  own  failure  to  imitate  Professors  James,  Ladd,  Hall  and 


SHORTER   CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS.       419 

Cattell,  by  saying  that  it  was  a  good  explanation,  that  they,  like  him, 
did  not  imitate  because  they  could  not.  His  whole  discussion  of  my 
views  on  imitation  should,  in  fairness,  be  accepted  only  after  a  careful 
reading  of  what  the  monograph  said  on  that  subject.  There  is  room 
in  this  reply  for  only  one  more  comment,  on  another  matter. 

To  prove  that  dogs  have  memory  in  the  sense  of  the  ability  to 
"  refer  the  present  situation  to  a  situation  of  the  past  and  realize  that 
it  is  the  same"  (the  meaning  taken  in  the  monograph),  Professor 
Mills  tells  us  of  a  dog  which  stopped  at  a  certain  tree,  up  which  he  had, 
months  ago,  chased  a  cat,  "  looked  up  and  behaved  otherwise  in  such 
a  manner  as  left  no  doubt  in  my  mind  that  he  remembered  the  iden- 
tical tree  and  detail  of  the  whole  performance."  I  suppose  this 
description  of  the  effect  on  Professor  Mills,  beginning  with  the  words 
*  behaved  otherwise,'  means  that  the  dog  barked  at  or  jumped  at  the 
tree,  or  behaved  as  he  would  if  the  cat  were  there.  It  must  be  con- 
fessed that  to  a  hardened  disbeliever  the  argument,  "  the  dog  remem- 
bered because  he  behaved  so  that  I  know  he  remembered,"  seems 
hardly  scientific ;  but  supposing  that  the  description  means  what  we 
have  suggested,  it  still  does  not  prove  that  the  dog  felt  a  memory  of 
previous  incident.  At  the  table  this  morning  I  took  hold  of  a  cup, 
raised  it  to  my  lips  and  drank,  acted  toward  the  cup  just  as  I  did  a 
month  ago,  but  I  had  absolutely  no  memory  in  connection  with  the 
act.  Indeed,  if  the  dog  really  remembered  the  previous  chase,  he 
would  have  good  reasons  not  to  stop  at  the  tree  and  act  as  if  a  cat 
were  there.  Let  us  suppose  that  Professor  Mills  and  his  dog  were 
both  out  for  cats  ;  that  they  chased  a  cat  to  a  tree ;  that  the  dog  barked, 
etc.,  at  the  foot ;  and  that  Professor  Mills,  running  up,  shot  his  gun  at 
the  cat.  Next  month  they  come  along  toward  the  tree.  Now,  suppose 
that  Professor  Mills  should  run  up  and  shoot  his  gun  as  he  did  the 
other  time.  Would  we  think  he  remembered  his  chase  of  a  month 
before?  No!  we  would  think  that  he  had  gone  daft,  or  had  for- 
gotten that  the  cat  was  there  a  month  ago.  Such  an  act  would  be  the 
natural  result  of  a  permanent  association  between  the  sight  of  that 
tree  and  certain  impulses,  or  of  an  ill-defined  representation ;  but  it 
would  be  one  of  the  last  things  to  expect  as  a  result  of  a  memory  of 
the  previous  occasion. 

This  reply  should  close  with  an  apology.  Discussions  of  method 
and  argument  over  results  are  likely  to  be  less  profitable  and  much  less 
interesting  than  new  constructive  work.  This  reply  was,  however, 
necessary  because  of  Professor  Mills'  eminence  as  an  observer  of  ani- 
mals, and  because  of  the  importance  of  getting  at  the  truth  about  the 


420  NOTES    ON  AFTER-IMAGES. 

possible  disturbing  influence  of  fear  and  novel  surroundings  in  certain 
convenient  and,  if  legitimate,  illuminating  experiments. 

[NOTE. — On  page  268  Professor  Mills  has  put  '  to  the  laws  of 
nature '  instead  of  '  to  the  laws  of  its  nature,'  which  means  something 
rather  different.] 

EDWARD   THORNDIKE. 
WESTERN  RESERVE  UNIVERSITY, 
CLEVELAND,   OHIO. 


NOTES  ON  AFTER-IMAGES. 
LOCATION  OF  AFTER-IMAGE. 

The  following  Experiment  I  was  made  while  I  studied  at  Prince- 
ton, January  26,  1895.  With  an  ordinary  students'  stand-lamp,  I  closed 
the  left  eye,  shaded  it  with  the  hand,  and  gazed  steadily  at  the  flame 
until  an  exceedingly  strong  image  was  secured.  Then,  closing  this 
eye  and  likewise  covering  it  with  the  hand,  I  secured  a  strong  image 
with  the  left  eye. 

Then,  with  a  large  piece  of  cardboard  the  eyes  were  shaded  from 
the  lamp-light  and  the  after-image  of  the  right  eye  was  projected  upon 
the  wall,  which  was  of  a  light  shade.  While  this  image  was  comple- 
menting from  green  to  red,  and  at  just  the  time  the  red  was  well  pro- 
duced, that  eye  was  closed  and  the  image  of  the  left  eye  was  thrown 
upon  the  wall,  which  image  was  found  to  be  green  at  the  instant  that 
of  the  right  was  red.  In  like  manner,  when  the  image  of  the  left 
eye  was  complemented  into  red,  and  the  image  of  the  right  eye  was 
at  that  time  found  to  be  green.  Opening  and  closing  the  eyes 
alternately,  it  was  found  that  each  eye  had  its  own  independent  after- 
image. 

Experiment  2. — Proceeding  as  before  in  securing  the  after-images 
opposite  in  color  for  the  eyes,  the  left  eye  was  closed  and  the  image  of 
the  right  eye  was  projected  on  the  wall.  When  this  after-image  had 
changed  to  red  I  projected  the  after-image  of  the  left  eye  upon  that  of 
the  right,  that  of  the  left  at  that  instant  being  green.  The  combined 
image  appeared  green.  Upon  closing  the  left  eye,  or  upon  shifting  its 
image  to  the  left  so  as  to  make  two  separate  images,  it  was  found  that 
the  image  of  the  right  continued  to  be  red  while  that  of  the  left  was 
green.  The  reverse  was  likewise  accomplished.  With  sufficiently 
strong  images  this  shifting  of  images  into  and  away  from  each  other 
proved  an  exceedingly  interesting  and  beautiful  process. 


SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS,       421 

The  above  experiments,  if  taken  alone,  seem  to  indicate  quite  de- 
cisively that  the  after-image  pertains  to  the  retina  of  the  eye.  Mr. 
McCurdy,  who  frequently  studied  in  my  room,  upon  being  informed 
of  this  experiment,  tried  it  and  obtained  the  same  result,  and  likewise 
felt  satisfied  with  the  evidence  of  retinal  location. 

AFTER-IMAGE  AND  TEMPERATURE. 

The  following  describes  what  was  rather  an  experience  than  an 
experiment,  since  it  conducted  itself,  and  that  so  impressively  that  I 
was  enabled  to  chronicle  it  in  detail  after  going  to  my  room. 

It  is  necessary  to  explain  that,  while  studying  in  Chicago,  I  was 
accustomed  to  public  speaking  each  Sunday  evening,  and  finding  that 
a  double  bath — that  is,  a  hot  bath  succeeded  by  a  cold  one — proved 
beneficial  toward  reducing  nervous  excitement  following  on  the  effort 
of  speaking,  and  conducive  to  sleep,  it  was  habitually  practised. 

On  an  evening  in  March,  1898,  while  lying  in  a  bath  as  hot  as  I 
could  well  endure,  my  eyes  being  closed,  I  noticed  a  very  lively  after- 
image. I  presume  it  had  been  caused  by  looking  at  the  gas  light  in 
the  bath  room,  although  unconsciously.  Its  peculiar  shape  and  bril- 
liancy attracted  my  notice  so  much  that  I  became  interested  in  its  life 
history.  Its  shape  was  that  of  a  heart  and  its  color  that  of  the  gas 
flame  recently  lighted.  Besides  its  peculiar  form,  another  novelty  was 
the  trimming  of  green  globules  which  embroidered  the  image.  While 
attending  this  feature  I  became  aware  that  the  image,  instead  of 
diminishing  in  intensity,  as  becomes  the  normal  after-image,  was  grow- 
ing more  intense  and  brilliant.  At  the  time  I  had  become  so  warm 
that  perspiration  stood  out  on  my  face  and  forehead.  As  I  watched, 
the  globular  fringe  began  to  shift  around  to  one  side — the  left  side — 
and  to  thicken  there  into  a  kind  of  knob.  At  about  the  same  time  an- 
other small  after-image  of  exactly  the  same  color  and  shape  as  the 
former  image  began  to  form  in  the  right  center  of  the  latter.  It  must 
be  noticed  here  that  the  old  image  persisted  in  remaining  the  same 
color  and  refused  to  complement  itself.  The  second  image  grew 
rapidly;  and  now  a  strange  thing  took  place,  namely,  the  small 
image  moved  closer  outside  to  the  right  of  the  older  and  larger,  and  in- 
creased to  about  the  same  size.  Then  both  images  changed  position, 
rolled  over,  as  it  were,  upon  their  sides,  with  their  niches  toward  each 
other.  The  green  fringe  of  globules  now  concentrated  in  each  image 
at  the  niche  and  the  two  images  began  to  coalesce.  First,  the  mar- 
ginal perimeters  remained  distinct  between  them,  then  merged  into 
one  separatrix,  but  eventually  disappeared,  leaving  but  one  after- 


422 


NOTES    ON  AFTER-IMAGES. 


image,  with  a  core,  as  it  were,  in  the  center.  At  this  point  the  image 
was  much  larger  than  the  first  image  had  been,  and  more  intense  than 
any  I  had  ever  previously  observed.  And,  strange  to  say,  the  color 
persisted  without  complementing.  That  is,  in  general,  for  the 
color  had  gradually  shaded  into  a  beautiful  pink,  while  the  center 
was  a  sort  of  apple  green.  In  fact,  the  appearance  of  the  image 
at  its  zenith  resembled  a  large  pink  candy  apple  with  its  green 
center  toward  the  eye.  At  this  time  I  was  suffering  from  the  heat. 
Turning  on  the  cold  water,  the  bath  began  gradually  to  cool.  With 
the  decrease  of  temperature  the  size  and  intensity  of  the  after-image 
reduced.  By  the  time  the  bath  was  reduced  in  temperature  so  as  to 
feel  decidedly  chilly,  it  had  entirely  disappeared.  The  last  glimpse  I 
got  as  it  was  fast  paling — there  was  an  orange  colored  daub  across  the 
left  center.  When  the  water  was  really  cold  I  not  only  could  not  get 
a  return  of  the  image,  but  could  get  but  a  very  poor  after-image  by 
repeatedly  gazing  at  the  gas  flame. 

I  judge  from  this  experience  that  the  high  temperature  of  the 
bath  caused  a  rush  of  blood  to  the  periphery  of  the  body  and  so  to  the 
end  organs  of  the  optic  nerves,  stimulating  the  retina,  so  that  feeble 
impressions  were  wrought  up  to  remarkable  intensity. 

J.  M.  GILLETTE. 

BIBLE  NORMAL  COLLEGE,  SPRINGFIELD,  MASS. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

Truth  and  Error,  or  The  Science  of  Intellection.     J.  W.  POWELL. 

Chicago,    The    Open    Court     Publishing  Co. ;    London,  Kegan 

Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  &  Co.     1898.     Pp.  423. 

It  is  a  precious  discipline  for  the  schooled  laborers  in  psychology 
and  philosophy  that  they  must  submit  to  learn  from  minds  that  obsti- 
nately refuse  to  learn  from  them  or  their  masters.  Mr.  Powell's  book 
has  the  freshness,  suggestion,  courage  and  masterful  quality  that  we 
associate  with  the  thinkers  who  inaugurate  '  periods '  and  who  are  un- 
oppressed  and  unchastened  by  a  long  dismal  vista  of  strenuous  and 
largely  ineffectual  thought  behind  them.  He  has  striking  conceptions, 
and  often  admirable  expression,  but  he  will  not  learn  his  a,  b,  c's. 
He  has  the  familiar  refrain  of  condemnation  for  '  metaphysics'  and 
those  who  are  deceived  by  words,  but  his  own  unguarded  reliance  on 
words,  joined  with  an  arbitrary  definition  of  them,  is  not  encouraging. 
For  instance,  '  metaphysics '  itself.  "  In  modern  times  those  who  hold 
that  noumena  are  inexplicable,  that  is,  unknown  and  unknowable 
properties,  call  themselves  '  metaphysicians.' "  Mill,  Spencer,  Aris- 
totle, Plato,  Newton,  Berkeley,  Kant  and  Hegel,  are  freely  refuted; 
but  the  author's  insight  into  other  men's  thoughts  and  methods  falls 
considerably  below  his  confidence.  The  strictness  and  prudence  of  his 
own  reasoning — his  philosopher's  conscience  about  assumption  and 
assertion — mighfbe  pointedly  illustrated. 

4  The  war  of  philoso  phy,'  we  are  told,  has  been  *  between  Idealists 
and  Materialists,'  according,  of  course,  to  Mr.  Powell's  definitions. 
"  The  philosophy  here  presented  is  neither  Idealism  nor  Materialism ; 
I  would  fain  call  it  the  philosophy  of  science."  It  is  realistic  in  the 
modern,  and,  one  is  tempted  to  add,  in  the  scholastic  sense.  He  takes 
his  first  principles  avowedly  from  empirical  science  and  seems  to  be 
untroubled  by  the  scruples  of  epistemology.  "  I  shall  propound  the 
hypothesis  that  consciousness  inheres  in  the  ultimate  particle,  and  at- 
tempt to  show  that  it  \_i.  e.,  the  hypothesis]  harmonizes  the  principles 
of  psychology."  "An  ultimate  particle,  and  hence  every  body,  has  five 
essentials  or  concomitants,  these  terms  being  practically  synonymous. 
*  *  *  The  essentials  of  the  particle  are  unity,  extension,  speed,  per- 

423 


424  LITERATURE. 

sistence  and  consciousness,  which  are  absolute.  The  relations  that 
arise  from  them,  in  order,  are  multeity,  position,  path,  change  and 
choice,  which  give  rise  to  number,  extension,  motion,  time  and  judg- 
ment, as  properties  that  can  be  measured.  It  has  been  pointed  out 
that  particles  are  incorporated  in  bodies  through  affinity  as  choice,  and 
by  this  incorporation  the  quantitative  properties  become  classific 
properties  which,  in  order,  are  class,  form,  force,  causation  and  con- 
ception." Unfortunately  one  must  content  oneself  with  these  quota- 
tions. This  philosophy  of  science  is  interesting ;  and  if  somewhat  re- 
mote from  both  modern  philosophy  and  science,  it  remains  true  that 
the  book  abounds  in  suggestive  statement  and  clever  expression,  and 
furnishes  striking  illustrative  passages  to  the  student  of  that  attractive 
but  undeveloped  subject,  the  psychology  of  philosophic  speculation. 

D.  S.  MILLER. 
PHILADELPHIA. 


Human  Immortality.     WILLIAM  JAMES.     Boston  and  New  York, 

Houghton,  Mifflin  &  Co.     1898.     Pp.  i  -f-  170. 

This  little  book  of  Professor  James'  is  the  Ingersoll  Lecture  for 
1898.  The  author  seeks  to  answer  two  objections  of  modern  culture 
to  immortality.  The  first  of  these  is  the  proposition  of  Physiological 
Psychology  that  thought  is  a  function  of  the  brain.  This  general 
idea  has  been  carried  into  detail  by  the  hospitals  and  laboratories 
which  have  located  special  forms  of  thought  in  special  brain  areas. 
Professor  James  asks  us  to  accept  this  result  for  the  sake  of  argument, 
and  asks  whether  it  compels  us  to  surrender  belief  in  immortality. 
Most  persons  imbued  with  the  '  Puritanism  of  science,'  he  tells  us, 
would  answer  in  the  affirmative.  But  this  conclusion  is  not  logically 
coercive,  because  the  physiologist  assumes  that  the  only  kind  of  '  func- 
tional dependence '  is  production,  and  supposes  that  the  brain  produces 
consciousness.  But  this  overlooks  4  permissive  function '  and  '  trans- 
missive  function,'  with  which  we  are  familiar  even  in  the  physical 
world.  Professor  James'  thesis  is  that  when  we  say  that  thought  is  a 
function  of  the  brain,  we  are  entitled  to  think  of  '  permissive '  and 
'  transmissive '  function.  He  considers  the  latter,  which  he  illustrates 
physically  by  the  keys  of  an  organ,  which  transmit  the  air  from  the 
air  chest  through  the  pipes  into  the  world,  in  certain  special  forms. 
Suppose  that  the  whole  universe  of  material  things  is  only  a  4  surface 
veil  of  phenomena'  hiding  the  reality  behind,  or  a  dome  refracting  the 
4  white  light  of  eternity.'  And  suppose  this  dome,  usually  opaque  to 
the  eternal  light,  could  at  certain  places  grow  less  so,  admitting  to  this 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  425 

world  so  many  restricted  rays.  Just  so  our  brains  can  be  conceived 
as  thin  places  in  the  dome  through  which  the  genuine  reality,  the  life 
of  souls,  breaks  through  into  this  world  in  restricted  forms  of  finite 
consciousness,  which  would  only  cease  in  these  special  forms  when 
the  various  brains  ceased  to  exist.  Thus  our  conscious  life  would  de- 
pend on  our  brains,  and  yet  an  immortal  life  beyond  the  veil  be  possi- 
ble. Professor  James  says  in  one  of  the  notes  that  he  takes  the  dual- 
istic  standpoint  of  natural  science,  because  this  objection  arises  on  this 
plane.  From  this  standpoint,  he  says,  if  we  reject  the  notion  that  the 
brain  produces  consciousness,  we  have  no  other  alternative  but  to 
believe  that  consciousness  preexists  and  is  transmitted  into  this  world 
of  phenomena  by  the  brains  which  give  it  its  finite  forms.  He  then 
shows  that  the  idea  of  production  is  quite  as  metaphysical  as  the 
idea  of  transmission,  and  finally  gives  certain  positive  advantages  of 
the  transmission  theory. 

Several  questions  suggest  themselves.  There  is  space  here  only 
for  two.  The  first  has  reference  to  the  idea  of  ;  transmission/  If  it 
be  admitted  that  thought  is  a  function  of  the  brain,  and  also  that  '  trans- 
mission '  can  be  called  a  function,  then  Professor  James  might  exclude 
all  other  theories  than  production  and  transmission  without  any  refuta- 
tion, on  the  ground  that  they  do  not  make  thought  a  function  of  the 
brain.  But  if  the  physiologist  can  reply  that  this  idea  of  transmission 
of  preexisting  consciousness  by  the  brain  does  not  make  the  former  a 
function  of  the  latter,  it  would  seem  that  we  have  given  up  the  prop- 
osition we  were  to  have  accepted,  and  the  transmission  theory  would 
have  to  hold  its  own  against  other  theories  which  hold  an  absolute  be- 
ginning of  the  finite  consciousness,  such,  for  example,  as  those  which 
say  that  it  is  created  either  absolutely  or  through  the  generation  of 
parents.  And  if  the  brain  passively  transmits  a  preexisting  conscious- 
ness as  a  'thin  place  in  the  dome '  lets  in  light,  it  would  seem  as 
though  it  could  not  be  said  that  thought  is  a  function  of  the  brain,  if 
function  is  to  have  any  intelligible  sense.  If  this  theory  does  not  have 
the  right  any  more  than  others  to  the  support  of  the  physiologist's 
proposition,  it  must  take  its  place  in  the  arena  with  the  others. 

A  second  question  is  suggested  by  the  author  himself :  How  does 
this  theory  help  us  to  realize  our  finite  and  individual  immortality? 
Our  finiteness  seems  to  be  a  part  of  the  warp  and  woof  of  our  per- 
sonality ;  and  if  when  the  brain,  the  organ  of  this  finiteness,  vanishes, 
our  spirits  revert  to  their  original  source,  what  is  to  become  of  our 
personal  immortality?  Professor  James  admits  that  these  are  vital 
questions,  but  declines  to  enter  into  the  discussion  of  what  he  calls 


426  LITER  A  TURE. 

i  these  higher  or  more  transcendental  matters.'  He  merely  says  by 
the  way,  that  if,  as  the  philosophers  say,  l  all  determination  is  nega- 
tion,' it  might  prove  that  the  loss  of  these  particular  determinations  is 
not  a  matter  for  regret,  and  that  they  are  not  worth  keeping.  But 
what  if  all  determination  is  not  negation  ?  What  if  those  elements  of 
our  finite  personalities  are  positive  and  worth  keeping,  and  their  loss 
a  i  matter  for  regret  ?'  It  would  then  seem  that  this  theory  would  not 
help  us  greatly  in  the  question  of  immortality.  If  it  is  to  be  a  valid 
argument  for  immortality  it  would  first  have  to  prove  that  '  all  deter- 
mination is  negation.'  Nor  does  it  relieve  the  matter  that  Professor 
James  says  in  a  note  at  the  end  of  the  book  that  it  is  not  necessary  to 
identify  the  preexisting  consciousness,  which  this  theory  presupposes, 
with  the  Absolute  of  transcendental  idealism.  Even  though  the 
theory  only  requires  that  consciousness  preexists  *  in  vaster  entities ' 
than  our  finite  spirits,  we  lose  ourselves  just  as  much  in  the  bosom  of 
these  '  vaster  entities '  as  we  would  in  that  of  the  Absolute. 

The  second  objection  to  immortality,  for  which  there  is  little 
space  here  left,  has  reference  to  the  incredible  number  of  beings  which 
must  be  immortal  if  we  hold  fast  to  our  belief  in  immortality.  Pro- 
fessor James  shows  that  this  is  a  fallacy  resulting  from  our  failure  to 
realize  the  inner  significance  of  these  alien  lives,  which  is  as  great  for 
them  as  that  of  our  own  for  us.  Moreover,  we  cannot  say  that  God 
has  no  need  for  these  lives  because  we  ourselves  have  not.  If  God 
suffers  us,  surely  we  can  suffer  one  another. 

C.  W.  HODGE. 
PRINCETON. 

Essays  on   the  Bases  of  the   Mystic    Knowledge.      E.    RECEJAC. 

Translated  by  SARA  CARR  UPTON.     New  York,  Charles   Scrib- 

ner's  Sons.     1899. 

This  exceedingly  interesting  and  suggestive  book,  which  has  been 
well  rendered  into  English,  may  be  characterized  as  a  search  for  the  Ab- 
solute through  the  mystic  intuition.  '  Reason  is  in  possession  of  too 
much  light,'  the  author  says  in  his  introduction,  c  to  be  able  to  remain 
quite  at  ease  in  the  region  of  clear  ideas,  but  not  enough  to  know  first 
principles  of  actual  knowledge.  In  this  penumbra  who  can  trace  the  ex- 
act limit  of  perceptions  and  say  where  the  true  disappears  in  the  prob- 
able, where  the  probable  vanishes  in  illusion?'  The  author  holds  the 
common  ground  of  mysticism  with  reference  to  the  inability  of  pure  rea- 
son. It  is  impossible  to  grasp  the  highest  truth  by  a  rational  act,  or  to 
reduce  it  to  the  form  of  definite  conceptions.  The  Absolute  can  only  be 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  427 

grasped  by  a  species  of  inspiration,  and  the  highest  truth  transcends 
ideas  and  is  only  expressible  in  symbols.  The  author  is  at  the  same 
time  a  positivist  and  an  agnostic,  and  yet  denies  that  science  is  the  only 
organ  of  knowledge.  The  '  Heart,'  by  which  is  meant  a  synthesis  of 
freedom  or  moral  spontaneity  and  imagination  acting  under  the  regu- 
lative categories  of  duty,  constitutes  an  ultra- rational  and  ultra-scien- 
tific organ  of  truth.  The  relation  of  mysticism  to  science,  the  author 
argues,  is  purely  negative.  Mysticism,  when  it  understands  itself, 
does  not  encroach  on  the  territory  of  scientific  knowledge.  It  admits 
and  leaves  it  to  itself,  and  claims  the  power  of  discovering,  through  its 
own  organ,  truths  that  are  inaccessible  to  science.  The  mystical  ob- 
ject is  not  ontologically  transcendent.  The  Absolute  is  nowhere  but  in 
consciousness.  But  it  is  to  be  reached  only  by  a  consciousness  raised 
to  a  high  degree  of  intensity,  which,  by  an  act  of  4  excess'  or  k  disin- 
terestedness,' or  '  self-alienation,'  transcends  its  ordinary  plane  of  in- 
tellection and  moral  egotism,  and  in  this  act  of  '  transcendence'  be- 
comes, for  the  time,  identical  with  the  Absolute  and  attains  to 
supersensuous,  absolute  truth.  This  apprehension  is  not  intellectual, 
however,  and  cannot  be  represented  in  terms  of  ordinary  knowledge. 
It  can  only  be  expressed  in  symbols,  and  these  must  also  be  the  crea- 
tion of  the  excited  consciousness  in  which  the  intuition  takes  place. 
The  mystical  symbol  cannot,  therefore,  possess  universal  value,  like 
the  principles  of  rational  knowledge.  How,  then,  is  mysticism  to  be 
guarded  against  enthusiasm  and  subjective  caprice  ?  A  negative  cri- 
terion arises  out  of  the  relation  of  mysticism  to  science.  Mysticism 
must  not  enter  the  preserves  of  science.  When  it  essays  to  occupy 
fields  open  to  science  it  becomes  false  mysticism  and  is  to  be  con- 
demned. But  the  most  important  criterion  is  positive.  The  i  Heart' 
must  be  impelled  by  the  motives  of  pure  morality,  and  the  result  of  its 
mystical  act  must  submit  to  be  judged  by  the  laws  of  duty.  It  must 
be  tributary  to  the  moral  good.  The  author  is  here  a  disciple  of  Kant, 
as  he  is  Kant's  disciple  in  accepting  as  final  his  condemnation  of 
metaphysics.  This  symbolic  knowledge,  though  not  amenable  to  the 
tests  of  that  which  makes  the  claim  of  universality,  is  not  without  its 
own  appropriate  canons  of  self-criticism. 

The  discussion  of  the  book  is  divided  into  three  parts.  In  Part  I., 
entitled  "  The  Absolute,"  the  problem  is  how  the  Absolute  is  to  be 
apprehended ;  the  first  chapter  being  devoted  to  various  defective 
mental  attitudes  toward  the  Absolute,  while  the  second  treats  of  the 
mystic  consciousness  as  the  only  organ  for  the  real  apprehension  of  ab- 
solute truth.  Part  II.,  entitled  "  Symbols,"  treats  of  the  mode  of  ap- 


428  LITERATURE. 

prehending  and  expressing  the  mystical  intuition,  while  Part  III., 
under  the  title  of  "  The  Heart,"  deals  with  the  moral  and  religious 
aspects  of  mysticism.  It  would  be  impossible,  in  the  limits  which 
must  be  observed  in  this  notice,  to  follow  the  author  into  any  of  the 
details  of  his  discussion.  One  is  impressed  with  the  general  sanity  of 
the  discussion  and  the  fine  irenic  temper  which  pervades  it,  as  well  as 
with  the  author's  intelligent  appreciation  of  the  results  of  modern  in- 
vestigation. The  book  embodies  an  attempt  to  bring  a  very  recalci- 
trant theme  within  the  sphere  of  critical  treatment.  The  phenomena 
of  mysticism  are  treated  mainly  from  the  psychologist's  point  of  view, 
and  it  is  from  this  standpoint  chiefly,  therefore,  that  the  attempt  is  to 
be  judged.  The  psychological  interest  and  value  of  the  author's  work 
seem  to  me  to  be  unquestionable,  though  the  extent  to  which  mystical 
phenomena  are  open  to  psychological  treatment  is  a  question  on 
\vhich  difference  of  opinion  is  likely  to  prevail.  The  proposal  to  sub- 
stitute '  Mystic  Positivism '  for  rational  theology  or  metaphysical 
idealism  touches  some  of  the  great  issues  of  the  ages.  Whilst  free  to 
admit  my  own  scepticism  as  to  the  adequacy  of  the  substitute  and  my 
persistent  adherence  to  a  larger  faith  in  reason,  I  am  yet  of  the  opin- 
ion that  the  author  has  performed  an  important  service  to  philosophy. 
To  one  who  is  foolish  enough  in  these  degenerate  days  to  be  troubled 
about  the  ultimate  problems  of  life  and  destiny  the  book  is  refreshing 
as  well  as  illuminating.  It  proves  that  the  search  for  the  Absolute 
has  not  yet  become  antiquated,  and  it  leads  one  to  think  that  philosophy 
may  possibly  have  something  important  to  learn  from  the  mystics. 

ALEXANDER  T.  ORMOND. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 

Psychologic    der    Veranderungsaujfassung.     L.  WILLIAM    STERN. 

Mit  15  Figuren  im  Text.     Breslau,  Preuss  und  Jiinger.      1898. 

Pp.  viii  +  264. 

Ever  since  the  acceptance  of  the  dictum  Semper  idem  sentire  ac 
non  sentire  ad  idem  reverimt  (Hobbes),  psychologists  have  been 
searching  the  multiple  variations  which  crowd  in  upon  consciousness ; 
and,  of  late,  these  empirical  facts  have  had  a  semblance  of  scientific 
treatment  in  the  so-called  *  law  of  variety '  (Hamilton)  or  '  law  of 
relativity'  (Wundt).  Change  as  objective  sequence,  and  change  as 
having  meaning,  have  given  no  end  of  trouble  to  clear  thinking, 
whether  in  metaphysics  or  in  science.  The  work  under  review  pre- 
sents itself  with  the  avowed  purpose  of  bringing  together  the  facts 
and  meaning  of  change  from  the  psychological  point  of  view. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  429 

Noting  the  historical  and  metaphysical  importance  of  the  concept 
of  change  and  its  congeners,  the  author  passes  to  the  problem  which 
change  offers  to  psychology,  formulating  it  thus  :  "  To  exhibit  all  the 
forms  which  the  apprehension  [Aufassung]  of  change  can  assume  in 
universal  thinking  (including  the  interrelations  of  them  one  to  an- 
other) and  to  describe  the  ideational  contents  of  these  various  forms 
of  apprehension"  (p.  5).  Change  has  many  different  aspects:  as, 
quantitatively,  the  increase  or  decrease  of  substance,  the  heightening 
or  lessening  the  intensity  of  an  experience,  the  enlargement  or  dim- 
inution of  its  extensity,  the  improvement  or  deterioration  in  value, 
and  variation  in  rapidity  of  change;  secondly,  the  type  or  quality  of 
change,  as  transition,  transformation,  interchange,  beginning,  progres- 
sion; thirdly,  the  local  direction  of  change,  as  movement,  transition, 
process,  etc.  In  its  highest  orders  change  appears  in  the  form  of 
development,  history  and  mathematical  functions.  To  this  descrip- 
tive problem  there  is  attached  another  quite  as  important,  which  rep- 
resents the  last  stage  of  differentiation  that  psychology  reaches,  viz.  : 
the  causal  investigation  of  the  nature,  origin,  amount  and  law  of  the 
apprehension  of  change  (p.  n). 

This  double  statement  of  the  problem  is  inadequate  without  a 
definition  of  Aujfassung,  the  second  member  of  the  title.  The  author 
finds  difficulty  in  defining  precisely  what  is  to  be  included  in  this  term. 
His  is  distinctly  not  the  problem  of  the  *  perception '  of  changes,  nor 
of  the  effects  of  objectively  changing  stimuli  upon  the  senses;  but 
rather  of  the  manner  how  a  certain  form  of  our  ideation  and  thinking 
is  constituted  (p.  12  f.).  Aujfassung  implies  the  complex,  discrimi- 
native, psychical  activity  wrhich  meets  all  varieties  of  stimulation  and 
issues  in  all  forms  of  judgment  (pp.  120  f.,  138).  The  monograph  is 
thus  an  extended  study  of  sensation,  perception  and  mental  activity  as 
complexly  involving  change,  its  fundamental  thought  being  that  the 
active  functioning  of  consciousness  is  the  only  hypothesis  which  offers 
any  aid  for  the  solution  of  the  technical  difficulties  involved  in  at- 
tempts at  harmonizing  our  varying  experiences  of  changes  (p.  255). 
Changing,  rather  than  constant,  impressions  alone  are  the  conditions 
for  awakening  this  functioning  (p.  140).  In  every  paragraph,  almost, 
there  is  a  steady  mindfulness  of  this  two-fold  problem. 

The  monograph  is  divided  into  two  parts.  Part  I.  (pp.  19-73) 
treats  of  '  the  origin,'  and  Part  II.  (pp.  78-256)  of  '  the  fineness  of  the 
apprehension  of  change.'  The  former  is  purely  qualitative ;  the  latter, 
more  quantitative  in  its  treatment.  In  Chapter  I.  there  is  given  a  dis- 
cussion of  the  sources  of  changes  as  found  in  Perception,  involving  the 


43°  LITERATURE. 

psychological,  rather  than  the  punctual  or  mathematical,  present  in 
consciousness.  Fixed  and  gradually  changing  stimulations,  and  the 
changes  which  the  subject  may  induce  in  its  own  conscious  stream  and 
in  the  members  of  its  body,  serve  as  the  varied  starting-points  whence 
change  is  apprehended.  In  every  act  of  perception  which  is  essen- 
tially extended  in  time  there  is  an  intuitive  apprehension  of  change. 
Otherwise  Reproduction  and  Comparison  (Chapter  II.)  could  not  take 
part  in  bringing  about  those  ideas  which  have  change  as  their  char- 
acteristic category.  Feelings  of  recognition  accompany  these  purely 
intellectual  processes  (p.  54).  The  comparison  of  varying  changes, 
whether  minute  or  extensive,  is  given  a  very  high  function,  its  greatest 
importance  being  to  promote  awareness  of  specific  stadia  in  any  series 
of  changes  which  involves  more  than  two  members ;  as,  for  example, 
in  the  growth  of  a  plant  we  are  able  to  detect  '  phases '  now  and  then. 
This  process  is  essentially  involved  in  consciousness's  recognition  of 
itself  and  its  past.  (In  this  process,  also,  S.  finds  '  the  most  important 
psychological  root'  of  the  idea  of  Ding  an  sich.,  p.  67.)  These 
'phases'  are  resting-points,  boundary  lines,  which  are  necessary  as 
soon  as  we  attempt  to  fix  the  changes  by  thought,  word  or  number 
(p.  72). 

The  analytical  distinctions  not  only  aid  the  later  examination  of 
the  measurement  of  change,  but  the  quantitative  analysis  tends  to 
complete  and  reenforce  them.  Part  II.  gathers,  in  critical  fashion, 
the  results  in  this  '  relatively  young  field  of  experimental  psychology.' 
Chapter  III.  describes  the  Technique  concerning  the  few  special  pieces 
of  apparatus  which  have  been  used  in  measuring  stimulus  changes  in 
brightness  and  color,  in  pitch,  intensity  and  direction  of  tones,  in 
pressure,  thermic  and  other  changes  due  to  chemical  and  mechanical 
stimulation.  The  mechanical  devices  used  in  the  studies  by  Preyer, 
Hall  and  Motora,  von  Frey,  Seashore,  Stratton,  and  by  S.  in  his 
earlier  studies  on  brightness,  movement  and  tones,  are  noted  in  this 
connection.  The  latter  part  of  this  chapter  discusses  the  two  groups 
of  methods  of  getting  at  the  fineness  of  discrimination  of  changes,  viz. : 
judgment  and  reaction.  In  this  matter  of  method  S.  finds  a  field  of 
questions  that  is  new  and  unexplored  (pp.  102  f.),  and  offers  sugges- 
tions for  reducing  varying  affirmative  and  negative  judgments  to  quan- 
titative values,  which  he  regards  as  the  more  desirable  results  in  ex- 
perimental tests  (pp.  97f-5  91)' 

Chapter  IV.,  entitled  Psychical  Excitability  for  changes  and  its 
Laws,  is  by  far  the  most  important  part  of  the  monograph,  both  as  to 
bulk  (pp.  119-256)  and  contents.  Its  first  section  is  occupied  with  a 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  431 

search  for  a  technical  term  which  shall  be  generic  to  sensibility  and 
discriminability.  This  term  is  Erregbarkeit  (pp.  119,  124),  which 
means  the  collective  reaction  of  the  soul  upon  external  stimulation. 
The  development  of  this  position  brings  S.  to  a  critical  rejection  of 
Preyer's  view  that  sensation  is  merely  a  function  of  stimulus  changes 
(pp.  144,  157  f.).  The  remainder  of  the  chapter  endeavors,  by  a 
careful  examination  of  the  conditions  of  psychical  response  to  external 
objects  (§§  9—11),  and  later  by  a  review  of  the  modifications  of  these 
conditions  in  the  special  senses  as  revealed  by  the  somewhat  conflict- 
ing results  of  the  experimental  studies  mentioned  above  (§§  12—14), 
to  reach  a  special  law  generalizing  psychical  excitability  to  changes. 
(It  is  noteworthy  that  S.  does  not  find  Weber's  Law  to  have  any  great 
bearing  upon  his  problem,  p.  131,  note.)  All  senses,  except  that  of 
temperature,  readily  yield  to  the  propositions  to  be  mentioned  later. 
The  perception  of  heat  and  cold  and  their  changes  seem  to  defy  the 
alleged  uniformity  of  conditions  for  the  apprehension  of  changes, 
leading  to  a  suggested  hypothesis  of  heat  and  cold  being  relations 
only.  Experimental  data  in  vision,  hearing,  pressure  and  the  modi- 
fications of  constant  and  transition-sensations  due  to  fatigue,  surprise, 
expectation,  etc.,  are  given  a  careful  examination  in  the  interests  of 
the  special  formula  sought  to  generalize  the  facts  of  the  variations  in 
the  rapidity  and  other  features  with  which  stimulus  changes  affect  the 
perceptibility  of  those  changes.  By  his  earlier  investigations  S.  has 
entitled  himself  to  this  critical  comparison  of  the  data  in  this  special 
field  (PSYCH.  REV.,  II. :  313  f.,  V. :  98  f.).  This  composite  review 
is  suggestive  and  appreciative,  even  when  critical  of  the  work  of 
others — which  is  by  no  means  uncommon. 

The  ^ Hauptgesetz,  mentioned  above  as  the  objective  point  of  the 
treatment  of  the  quantitative  values,  is  slowly  reached  and  presented 
in  sections,  pertinent  to  the  specific  conditions  and  the  type  of  sensa- 
tion and  reaction.  In  the  serial  order  its  parts  read  thus  :  i.  "  It  is  not 
the  absolute  value  of  the  excitations  always  present  in  sensory  nerves, 
and  radiating  from  there  to  the  motor  fields,  to  which  motor  nerves 
respond  with  a  reaction ;  but  it  is  rather  the  change  in  this  value  from 
moment  to  moment "  (p.  145).  2.  "  It  is  not  the  absolute  value  of  the 
stimulus  affecting  motor  nerves  which  produces  a  movement,  but  it  is 
rather  the  change  in  this  value  from  moment  to  moment"  (p.  145). 
3.  (Physiologically)  "A  nerve  stimulation  may  become  a  specific 
cause  for  the  performance  of  physical  and  psychical  activity  only  when 
the  stimulation  is  a  changing  one."  4.  (Or,  psychologically)  "A 


43 2  LITERATURE. 

sensation  may  become  a  specific  cause  for  the  performance  of  physical 
or  psychical  activity  only  when  it  is  apprehended  in  the  process  of 
changing"  (p.  158).  5.  ' l  The  incitation  to  the  physical  or  psychical 
reaction  varies  directly  with  the  rapidity  of  the  change  in  the  sensa- 
tion" (p.  211).  In  a  series  of  tone  discriminations,  varying  from  % 
to  2  vibrations,  lasting  2,  4,  6  and  8  seconds,  S.  found  that  the  most 
favorable  time  for  detecting  the  amount  of  increase  and  direction  of 
stimulation  was  6  seconds'  duration  (pp.  189-195).  On  this  basis  he 
offers  the  law  of  the  most  favorable  time  for  apprehending  changes. 
6.  u  If  a  changing  stimulus  is  persistently  observed,  certain  favorable 
stadia  will  be  found  within  the  observation  time  in  which  the  capa- 
bility of  perception  (the  tendency  to  complete  a  judgment — or  motor — 
reaction)  is  especially  strong.  Since,  within  such  a  favorable  time 
changes  of  varying  rapidity  can  be  perceived,  the  slower  changes 
which,  up  to  that  point  of  time  have  acquired  only  a  lesser  extent,  are 
relatively  more  favorably  placed"  (p.  211).  7.  (In  addition  to  2) 
u  The  greater  the  rapidity  of  change  in  the  stimulus  the  greater  is  the 
incitation  to  motor  activity"  (p.  213).  3  and  4  express  the  law  of 
change  in  its  best  forms.  The  actual  experimental  deviations  from  the 
law,  noticed  at  length  by  S.  (p.  224f),  must  be  omitted. 

The  law  is  less  suggestive  in  its  formula  than  in  the  discussions 
which  point  the  way  to  it.  Its  formulation  is  rather  defective  in  being 
so  scattered.  It  remains  isolated,  finally,  and  is  not  exactly  brought 
into  harmony  with  his  problem  as  defined  in  terms  of  apprehension. 
And,  furthermore,  the  attempts  at  emulation  are  rather  too  pronounced. 
On  the  other  hand,  in  its  review  of  the  few  experimental  studies,  the 
monograph  can  well  serve  as  a  hand-book.  The  detailed  analysis  of 
many  facts  and  relations  brings  them  up  to  the  point  where  only  special 
investigation  can  carry  them  forward.  This  is  one  of  the  most  valu- 
able features  of  this  very  circumspect  treatment  of  the  problems  con- 
nected with  the  apprehension  of  change. 

EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 

NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY,  SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 

Psychophysiologische  Erkenntnistheorie.    THEODOR  ZIEHEN.    Jena, 

Gustav  Fischer.      1898.     Pp.  105. 

In  the  rush  to  epistemology  the  serious  student  may  well  question 
whether  we  are  keeping  ourselves  aloof  from  a  neo-scholasticism  which 
threatens  scientific  method,  on  the  one  hand,  and  disables  the  efforts  of 
thought  by  an  apparent  show  of  consistency  on  the  other.  Noetical 
theories,  once  unknown  and  unsought,  are  now  so  common  that  they 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  433 

even  serve  the  purpose  of  setting  up  standards  for  giving  advice. 
Whether  this  highest  court  of  Appeal  in  the  kingdom  of  mind  is  not 
deserving  of  far  more  respect  than  is,  by  popular  consent,  manifest, 
can  scarce  be  a  matter  of  question.  Consistency,  however,  is  the  chief 
emblem  of  this  bar,  and  the  essay  under  review  presents  itself  with 
titular  claims  to  a  frank  hearing.  It  reposes  upon  the  earlier  efforts  of 
its  writer  in  the  field  of  physiological  psychology,  and  thus  comes  with 
the  promise  and  potency  of  unsuspected  extensions  in  the  domain  of 
theory  of  knowledge. 

In  all  exploration,  results  are  in  primary  demand ;  and  the  author 
has  spared  the  reviewer  much  by  bringing  in  one  section  (§  22,  pp. 
100-103)  a  'dogmatic  resume' of  his  inquiries.  Though  opposed  to 
the  very  spirit  of  epistemology  (which  the  author  recognizes),  he  ven- 
tures to  give  a  succinct  exhibition  of  the  conclusions  to  which  he  has 
been  led  in  his  analyses.  Freely  rendered,  this  ^Lexikon^  so  zu  sagen, 
of  his  theory  of  knowledge  runs  about  thus : 

"  Sensations  [Empfindungeri\  and  ideas  [  Vorstellungen\  are 
given  to  us."  Both  are  summed  up  in  the  terms  psychical  processes, 
or  the  psychical.  Non-psychical  is  a  meaningless  term.  Things,  my 
ego,  alter  egoes  are  ideas  only. 

On  the  basis  of  epistemological  analysis  each  sensation  is  made 
up  of  two  components,  the  residual  factor,  or  the  reduced  sensation, 
and  the  v-component.  [The  '  v '  factor  is  the  primary  experience 
derived  from  the  activity  of  the  sense-organs,  as  tactile,  visual,  etc., 
p.  22] .  The  former  factors  have  reciprocal  relations,  which  can  be  ex- 
pressed by  universal  laws.  The  totality  of  these  laws  is  designated  as 
the  '  causal  formula.'  [This  is  the  summary  of  the  coordination  of 
tactile  and  optical  series  mutually  dependent — e.  g.,  in  seeing  my  hand 
movements  and  pen  movements  spatially  and  temporally  connected. 
This  is  the  sequence  of  value  to  the  natural  sciences,  p.  25.] 

A  certain  group  of  sensations  is  designated  as  the  group  of  v-sen- 
sations.  The  residual  factors  of  these  sensations  work  first  recipro- 
cally with  the  residual  factors  of  the  other  sensations  which  can  be 
expressed  by  the  causal  formula ;  but,  secondly,  they  react  indepen- 
dently upon  these  residual  factors  when  they  have  undergone  a  change 
through  the  residual  factors  of  another  sensation. 

These  reactions  are  not  arranged  according  to  space  and  time. 
They  cannot  be  expressed  by  the  laws  of  the  causal  formula,  but 
rather,  in  their  entirety,  by  other  laws  (uniform  fusions) .  The  total- 
ity of  these  lawful  fusions  is  designated  by  the  term  parallel-formula 
[z.  e.,  changes  in  sensation-complexes  that  are  simultaneous  and  not 
successive,  pp.  25-6]. 


434  LITERATURE. 

The  residual  factor  of  a  sensation,  which  causally  effects  in  a  cer- 
tain degree  and  certain  quality  the  constituent  part  of  the  v-sensation 
is  altered  by  the  parallel-reaction  of  the  latter.  The  process  of  trans- 
ition is  designated  by  the  term  v-change,  or  individualization,  the 
change  itself  as  the  v-component. 

Epistemology  is  trying,  with  the  help  of  natural  science,  including 
psychology,  to  eliminate  these  v- components,  and  to  present  the  resid- 
ual factor  itself  [t.  e.,  the  ' object'].  The  idea  of  this  residual  factor 
is  the  resultant  idea,  or  the  reduced  sensation.  (Hence)  the  method 
of  theory  of  knowledge  is  called  ;  reduction '  [Y.  e. ,  thought  must  not 
turn  to  'things'  as  external,  but  continue  a  consistent  analysis  of  sen- 
sations, until  it  reaches  that  sensational  quale  which  cannot  be  elimi- 
nated, p.  31  f.  This  residue  is  the  nervous  system,  at  times  fibers, 
and  again  cortical  centers,  pp.  35,  59,  65].  The  residual  factors  are 
only  to  be  ideated. 

The  v-sensations  are  arranged  in  complexes,  which  are  commonly 
called  sensory  nervous  system. 

All  sensations  are  made  up  of  v-components  of  a  single  complex  of 
v-sensations ;  so  far  forth  they  are  individually  psychical ;  the  residual 
factors  can  also  be  ideated  only  as  psychical,  but  as  universally- 
psychical. 

Since  the  idea  of  the  individual  ego  is  itself  an  idea  resulting  from 
the  process  of  reduction,  the  idea  of  a  universal-psychical  is  neither 
contradictory  nor  meaningless. 

Sensations,  in  so  far  as  they  all  possess  v-components,  are  also 
called  object- sensations  or  stimulus-sensations. 

With  the  omission  of  the  v-components  the  object-sensation  disap- 
pears. Its  residual  factor  must  be  ideated  as  abiding. 

Every  reduction  factor  transforms  itself  into  so  many  object-sensa- 
tions— t.  £.,  is  individualized  just  so  often  as  it  affects  the  v-sensation- 
complexes  and  experiences  their  reactions. 

All  sensations  are  positively  only  in  space,  at  the  place  of  the 
residual  factor.  Spatial  and  temporal  series  belong  primarily  to  the 
reduced  sensations  (i.  e.,  the  residual  factor).  It  is  influenced  only 
secondarily  by  individualization. 

In  like  manner,  the  quality  and  intensity  of  object- sensations  are 
determined  by  the  reduced  sensations,  and  only  secondarily  by  the 
v-components.  Theory  of  knowledge,  in  so  far  as  it  demands  univer- 
sal ideas  of  reduction,  is  trying,  with  the  help  of  natural  science  and 
psychology,  to  subsume  the  qualities  and  intensities  under  a  single  re- 
duction-idea. As  such  a  universal  the  idea  of  energy  is  to-day  com- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  435 

ing  under  consideration.  The  idea  of  mass,  inasmuch  as  it  is  to  in- 
dicate more  than  a  numerical  factor,  is  contradictory  or  meaningless 
[z.  £.,  'mass'  does  not  carry  one  over  into  realism]. 

An  affective  tone,  as  a  feature  independent  of  the  other  charac- 
teristics, does  not  belong  to  the  reduced  sensation. 

The  difference  between  ideas  and  sensations  consists  in  sensuous 

vivacity. 

*         *          *          *         * 

Object-sensations  always  require,  for  their  individualization,  con- 
junction with  ideas. 

Ideas  [like  sensations]  are  simple  or  complex,  individual  or  uni- 
versal. [Ideas  are  only  memory-pictures  of  sensations,  p.  37.] 

Ideas  of  Relation  form  a  special  group.  They  are  just  as  depen- 
dent upon  the  v-sensations  as  are  the  other  ideas.  Like  all  other  ideas, 
they  are  developed  only  from  sensations. 

Among  these  ideas  of  relation,  those  which  have  special  epistem- 
ological  importance  are  the  six  categorical  ideas  [not  in  the  Kantian 
or  Hegelian  sense  of  the  term  '  category ']  of  likeness,  similarity  and 
difference,  persistency,  change  and  interchange.  [  /.  £.,  upon  the  sole 
condition  of  like  sensations,  simultaneous  and  in  sequence,  etc.,  the 
child  builds  up  these  rational  ideas,  by  extracting  those  elements 
present  in  the  varying  sensation-complexes,  pp.  7—15.]  The  relational 
idea  of  causality  is  based  upon  the  relational  idea  of  change.  The  re- 
duction ideas  of  epistemology  are  the  most  universal  ideas  of  sensations 
and  sensation-relations. 

In  the  formation  of  epistemological  reduction-ideas  the  regulative 
principle  is  so  to  plan  the  reductions  that  a  general  similarity  appears 
in  the  place  of  single  similarities  of  the  object-sensations  and  their 
changes.  Our  reduction-ideas  are  subject  to  a  progressive  develop- 
ment and  selection,  since  object-sensations  are  never  given  us  in  their 
totality. 

Ideas  of  ideas,  hence  ideas  of  reduction-ideas,  do  not  exist. 

Those  reductions  which  unite  with  the  epistemological  basis  are, 
in  so  far  as  the  latter  does  not  change,  not  further  in  need  of  reduction. 

The  causal  changes  within  the  v-complexes  are  often  continued 
through  the  reduction-factors  of  sensations  which  are  closely  connected, 
spatially,  with  these  v-complexes.  They  are  designated  as  /x-sensa- 
tions,  and  correspond  to  the  motor  system  of  our  bodies.  These 
/^-complexes  affect,  in  their  turn,  according  to  the  causal  formula,  the 
reduction-factors  of  ordinary  object-sensations.  These  influences  are 
called  'actions  ;'  and  they  complete  the  circle  of  causal  changes." 


436  LITERATURE. 

11  Can  there  any  good  thing  come  out  of  Nazareth?"  is  a  ques- 
tion pointing  to  an  active  field  in  philosophical  inquiries.  Ziehen  re- 
plies, as  the  newly  adopted  apostle  of  old,  «  come  and  see/  while  he 
attempts  to  draw  noetical  values  out  of  Nazarene  sensations,  sensa- 
tion-complexes and  sequent  images.  If  there  is  any  virtue  in  the  doc- 
trine of  sensation,  as  it  has  of  late  decades  crept  into  science  and  phi- 
losophy, then  this  essay  is  the  most  virtuous  of  all  recent  productions 
which  aspire  to  truth  and  consistency.  The  specific  problem  of  epis- 
temology  is  presented  as  the  merely  analytical  *  reduction'  of  the  con- 
tent of  experience  to  certain  forms,  validated  for  the  means  and  ends 
of  empirical  sciences,  especially  of  empirical  psychology.  *  Reduc- 
tion' may  mean  transformation,  fusion,  synthesis.  In  this  writing  it 
is  presented  as  the  chief  and,  in  truth,  only  means  of  noetical  achieve- 
ment (§8  pp.  31-35)-  It  purports  to  be  such  an  analysis  of  sensa- 
tions and  the  elimination  of  those  accidental  factors  which  leads  the 
naive  thinker  to  affirm  c  things,'  and  the  scientist  to  end  with  extra- 
psychical  forces.  This  gives  rise  to  antinomies,  which  it  is  the  special 
problem  of  noetics  to  remove,  and,  in  this  instance,  succeeds  to  the 
satisfaction  of  one  person  in  rendering  all  factors  and  processes  psych- 
ical. To  this  extent  the  author  is  almost  mortgaged  to  a  prejudice, 
while  the  reviewer  frankly  confesses  to  the  privileges  in  the  very  op- 
posite direction — namely,  that  an  objective,  impersonal  analysis  of 
psychical  contents  of  the  lowest,  or,  perhaps  better,  initial,  order  is 
not  paramount  to  the  demands  which  can  and  must  be  made  upon  any 
serious  attempt  to  explicate  the  nature  of  what  we  men  call  4  knowl- 
edge.' 

That  the  analysis  here  spread  forth  in  an  exceedingly  abstract, 
schematic,  algebraic  fashion  is  astutely  regarded  as  adequate,  may  be 
seen  from  the  following  passages,  which  well  illustrate  the  flavor  of 
the  essay,  if  not  its  detailed  method  of  analysis : 

"A  special  'function  of  judging'  does  not  exist."  For  cen- 
turies, psychology,  logic,  and  theory  of  knowledge  have  fruitlessly  at- 
tempted to  find  in  the  features  of  judgment  what  is  here  for  the  first 
time  clearly  provided  for  in  those  preliminary  fusional  abstractions 
which  engage  simple  ideas.  "  There  is  still  less  occasion  for  accept- 
ing other  '  faculties,' beyond  judgment  *  *  *  such  as  reason,  the  source 
of  syllogisms  or  intuitions,  etc.  Exactly  at  the  place  where  philos- 
ophy has  so  often  ventured  the  leap  from  epistemology  into  meta- 
physics, is  the  Calvary  of  the  many  '  higher  functions  of  soul' ;  here 
lie  the  Ao^o?  arid  vou?  and  <pp6yqats  and  pavta  and  xiim?  of  Greek  phi- 
losophy *  *  *  and  the  reasons  and  pure  ego's  and  apperceptions  of 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  437 

modern  philosophy.  Tt  is  generally  supposed  that  a  connection  with  the 
extra-psychical  must  be  sought  for  in  the  highest  psychical  faculties. 
This  extra-psychical  is  a  senseless  term,  and  the  highest  psychical  is  al- 
ready included  in  the  formation  of  ideas  [as  detailed  by  the  elaborated 
schemata].  Right  here  is  the  principal  divergence  of  this  theory  of 
knowledge  from  the  pathway  of  the  earlier  theories."  The  scope  and 
duty  of  epistemology  are  thus  greatly  modified  and  simplified.  We 
are  no  longer  concerned  "  with  finding  the  criteria  of  true  judgment, 
of  certainty,  or  whatever  one  may  term  it ;  but  only  with  feeling  our 
sensations  and  ideating  our  ideas  with  others,  and  with  forming  new 
combined  general  and  relation-ideas,  and  among  these  specially  reduc- 
tion-ideas which  correspond  to  the  sensations.  The  only  criterion  is 
the  agreement  with  sensations,  the  fulfillment  of  the  expectations 
which  become  joined  to  the  reduction-ideas"  (pp.  85— 87) • 

The  somewhat  more  readily  assimilated  results  of  this  'new' 
theory  of  knowledge,  based  upon  and  strictly  held  down  to  the 
nervous  system  and  its  initial  processes  in  consciousness,  are  neatly 
presented  in  the  closing  section  (pp.  103-105)  which  anticipates 
(rightly)  and  attempts  to  set  at  rest  k  the  almost  instinctive  objec- 
tions* which  are  put  to  his  analyses,  i.  If  it  is  supposed  that  the 
'  residual  factor'  of  this  theory  is  identical  with  '  matter,'  in  the  ordi- 
nary sense  of  the  term,  it  is  replied  that  '  matter '  is  a  meaningless, 
metaphysical  dogma,  and,  strictly  speaking,  the  '  residual  factor '  is  an 
idea  which  we  employ  in  order  to  reach  universal  laws  relating  our 
sensations  and  ideas.  The  only  aspect  common  to  '  matter'  and  the 
'residual  factor'  is  'change  according  to  universal  laws.'  2.  If  it  is 
presumed  that  one  result  of  this  reduction  of  things  and  ego's  to  a 
world  of  purely  psychical  process  is  to  undermine  all  laws  from  that 
of  gravitation  to  that  of  electro-magnetic  light,  the  objector  is  told 
that  their  validity  remains  unchanged.  Their  labels  only  are  changed, 
and  our  manner  of  speech  is  altered  so  as  to  avoid  all  contradictory  and 
meaningless  terms.  3.  If  the  critic  fancies  that  inroads  are  thus  made 
upon  the  principle  of  psycho-physical  parallelism,  he  is  reminded  that 
'  the  psychical  series  alone  is  given,'  and  is  the  only  view  which  avoids 
the  specious  wit  involved  in  the  affirmation  of  two  unlike  but  equally 
persistent  series  (Cf.  his  Introd.  to  Phys.  Psych.,  p.  3Oif.  (Eng.  tr.)). 
4.  Almost  overcome,  the  critic  finally  gasps  for  the  reinstatement  of 
'Metaphysics,  the  a  priori,  the  forms  of  Intuition,  the  Categories!' 
He  is  left  to  get  his  assurance  in  the  reply  that  "  no  room  remains  for 
them.  We  must  limit  ourselves  to  this  procedure,  to  gather,  com- 
pare and  then  reduce  ^sensations  scientifically  in  order  to  attain  the 


438  LITERATURE. 

universal  ideas  of  their  relations.  This  labor  is  divided  between  the 
descriptive  and  mathematical  natural  sciences,  psychology  and  theory 
of  knowledge.  Metaphysics,  just  as  religion,  has  been  only  the  his- 
torical precursor  of  these  sciences.  It  would  be  better  to  relegate 
metaphysics  and  its  younger  sister,  metapsychic,  among  the  fine  arts." 
5.  '  And  these  circumlocutory  designations ' — must  we  introduce  them 
into  daily  speech,  instead  of  the  simple  terms  of  our  mother-tongue? 
— e.  g.,  using  i  the  residual  factor  of  tree-sensation'  instead  of  4  tree '? 
No.  The  exposition  of  epistemology  is  sesquipedalian  for  the  very 
prosaic  purpose  ;  of  keeping  removed  those  so  often  falsely  added 
ideas '  of  realities !  Thus  the  objector  is  bade  to  rest  agnostically  and 
nihilistically  on  the  quiet  bed  of  positivism,  which  simplifies  ends  and 
means  without  measure. 

The  spirit  of  this  essay  is  extremely  serious  in  its  efforts  to  reduce 
objects  by  a  bare-handed  treatment  of  sensations,  which  are  now 
identified  with  events  in  nerve  fibers  and  ganglionic  cells,  and  now 
with  events  in  consciousness.  There  is  an  avowed  attempt  to  make 
epistemology  grow  out  of  the  soil  of  empirical  psychology,  as  under- 
stood by  the  author  in  his  Leitfaden  of  some  nine  years  ago,  bien  en- 
tendu.  What  are  the  exact  relations  between  the  two  branches  of 
thought  is  not  readily  ascertained.  Throughout  the  entire  exposition 
in  detail  there  is  no  advance  beyond  what  ought  to  be  treated  under 
psychology  as  it  actually  is  understood  by  most  contributors  to  this 
field.  Definite  statements  (pp.  4,  n,  58,  61,  65,  74,  85)  are  not 
steadfastly  explicit  upon  this  point.  Psychology  enumerates,  analyzes 
and  exhibits  the  development  of  our  complex  ideas,  while  theory  of 
knowledge  selects  this  or  that  idea,  and  presents  the  development  of 
that  which  is  significant  for  its  purpose,  only  in  so  far  as  empirical 
psychology  has  not  solved  the  problem.  The  basis  of  that  selection, 
as  personal,  or  logical,  or  objective,  is  not  made  plain.  Again 
(p.  75),  in  tracing  the  formation  of  ideas  of  relation  (which  are  not  to 
be  identified  with  the  concepts  employed  in  logical  theory)  the 
descent  is  made  to  the  idea  of  '  sameness'  as  the  given  datum.  The 
'  comparison'  necessary,  upon  the  repetition  of  similar  sensations,  is  a 
gratuitous  assumption ;  for  it  is  frankly  admitted  that  mere  description 
is  all  that  can  be  undertaken  in  this  region  of  the  inexplicable.  On 
the  whole,  then,  epistemology  for  the  author  means  going  back,  here 
and  there,  of  his  specific  psychological  conclusions  and  endeavoring  to 
make  them  intelligible  by  a  further  process  of  <  reduction '  instituted 
in  securing  them.  In  this  sense  the  essay  is  radically  defective  in  not 
establishing,  in  a  more  clear-cut  fashion,  those  differences  in  the  two 
disciplines  of  which  he  gives  promise  in  the  beginning. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  439 

The  tone  of  the  work  is  not  the  most  generous.  It  reveals  an  utter 
complacency  in  its  Berkeleian  idealism  upon  a  sensory  foundation 
(pp.  5,  59).  The  ingenuous,  at  times,  and  severely  schematic  treat- 
ment sweeps  aside,  in  almost  ruthless  fashion,  i  the  insights'  of  other 
thinkers  and  ;  the  demands'  of  the  problem  of  thought  and  reality  as 
perceived  by  them.  In  the  light  of  its  initial  claims  perhaps  this  pro- 
cedure is  commendable.  One  feature  of  this  analysis  of  knowledge  is 
to  simplify  to  the  grade  of  algebraic  imagination  the  erstwile  serious 
tasks  of  philosophical  reflection.  Thus  it  becomes  an  exceedingly  per- 
tinent question  to  ask  how  this  literalistic  chart  would  fare  when  con- 
fronting actual  knowledge.  Would  one  recognize  and  identify  his 
cognitions  on  the  basis  of  the  analytic  and  explanatory  clues  offered  in 
this  essay?  Indeed,  there  is  lacking  that  admiration  for  the  fact  of 
knowledge,  even  on  a  neuro-sensory  basis,  which  every  analyst  ought 
to  feel.  Another  interesting  feature  in  this  essay  is  the  attempt  to 
square  its  results  with  those  of  Kant's  theory  of  knowledge,  implying 
the  general  validity  of  the  Kantian  position  as  an  abstract  expression  01 
truth,  which  finds  proper  treatment  only  in  the  concrete  (?)  elabora- 
tion of  this  theory  of  knowledge.  (Cf.  pp.  50 +,53— 57,  72—86.) 
In  this  fashion  there  are  repeated  claims  as  to  the  exceeding  advantage 
of  this  exposition  over  that  of  others. 

The  central  question,  perhaps,  incited  by  this  attempt  at  a  theory 
of  knowledge,  which  does  not  advance  much  beyond  a  detailed  anal- 
ysis of  sensation-complexes  (tactile,  optical,  and  motor  coming  in  for 
almost  exclusive  attention)  is  this :  Can  an  historical  analysis  of  cer- 
tain of  our  residual  experiences  satisfy  even  a  scientific  study  of  what 
we  find  men  calling  '  knowledge'  ?  The  Zielstrebigkeit  characteristic 
of  every  cognitive  construction  of  an  '  object'  is  a  psychological  ex- 
hibit which  the  epistemologist  is  compelled  to  recognize.  (Cf .  Bald- 
win, Ment.  Develop.,  Soc.  and  Eth.  Int.,  pp.  249  f.,  377.)  It  often 
is  not  the  point  from  which,  but  the  point  to  which,  cognition  tends 
that  is  the  essential  feature.  This  is  more  than  primary  motor-reac- 
tions (Ziehen.,  p.  875^)*  and  must  be  adequately  recognized.  Other 
constructive  tendencies  might  be  pointed  out  which  all  cognition  ex- 
hibits, but  of  these  the  essay  takes  no  notice.  The  benefits  of  the  task 
of  this  essay,  then,  is  twofold :  one,  in  indicating  the  fact  that  on 
some  assumptions  a  theory  of  knowledge  leads  itself  into  a  blind-alley, 
cutting  off  further  philosophical  progress;  the  other,  a  benefit  in 
awakening  our  thankfulness  for  being  shown  the  limitations  imposed 
by  its  methods  and  content. 

EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 

NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY, 

SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 


44°  GENERAL. 

John  Stuart  Mill.      Correspondence  inedite  avec  Gustave  D'Eich- 

thal.  Avant-propos  et  traduction  par  EUGENE  D'EiCHTAL.  Paris, 

Felix  Alcan.      1898. 

The  correspondence  between  Mill  and  D'Eichthal  is  in  these  pages 
given  to  the  public  for  the  first  time  in  a  complete  form.  Many  of 
the  letters  had  been  published  previously  in  the  Cosmopolis  ;  additional 
ones,  however,  have  found  a  place  in  the  volume,  together  with  two 
letters  of  Eyton  Tooke  to  D'Eichthal.  The  friendship  of  Mill  and 
D'Eichthal,  which  continued  through  a  period  of  some  forty  years  or 
more,  presents  many  features  of  a  most  interesting  nature,  as  disclosed 
in  this  correspondence.  To  the  student  of  psychology  an  opportunity 
is  afforded  of  noting  the  effect  of  an  emotional  temperament,  as  that  of 
D'Eichthal,  upon  a  coldly  intellectual  nature,  as  that  of  Mill,  and, 
also,  of  observing  the  marked  contrast  between  the  French  and  Eng- 
lish traits  of  mind.  In  these  letters  Mill  exposes  to  a  searching  criti- 
cism the  doctrines  of  Saint  Simon  as  expounded  by  D'Eichthal  and 
his  friends ;  there  is,  however,  a  growiug  appreciation  of  the  motives 
and  purposes  of  the  Saint  Simonian  school,  evidently  induced  by  the 
disinterested  labors  and  self-sacrificing  zeal  of  its  members.  While 
criticising  their  methods,  Mill  had  only  words  of  praise  for  the  high 
humanitarian  ideals  of  this  school. 

The  strain  of  deep  sentiment,  which  was  a  characteristic  feature 
of  Mill's  nature,  and  yet  hidden  from  the  view  of  the  world,  is  revealed 
in  the  letters  which  he  wrote  at  the  time  of  Tooke's  tragic  death,  as 
also  upon  the  occasion  of  the  death  of  D'Eichthal's  father.  The  cor- 
respondence, indeed,  serves  as  a  valuable  appendix  to  the  Autobiog- 
raphy, inasmuch  as  it  throws  additional  light  upon  the  inner  life  of 
the  great  logician,  disclosing  in  that  many-sided  nature  the  elements 
which  prove  his  love  of  humanity  as  well  as  his  love  of  truth. 

JOHN  GRIER  HIBBEN. 

PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


GENERAL. 

Social  Automatism   and  the  Imitation    Theory.     B.    BOSANQUET. 

Mind,  No.  30,  N.  S.,  April,  1899,  p.  167. 

The  writer  aims  to  point  out,  in  this  way-side  preface  to  a  forth- 
coming book,  a  fundamental  error  in  the  imitation  theory  of  socio- 
logical psychology  as  an  attempt  to  reduce  to  principle  the  behavior  of 
individuals  in  a  group.  Secondary  automatism  suggests  an  analogy 
which  throws  light  on  political  philosophy.  Social  life  is  necessarily 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  441 

and  increasingly  constituted  by  adjustments  which  have  become  auto- 
matic, and  are  thus  put  beyond  the  range  of  discussion.  In  the  re- 
sulting economy  of  attention  the  social  mind  is  set  free  for  new  ideas. 
The  routine  of  civic  life,  the  use  by  the  state  of  coercion  upon  the  in- 
dividual, and  the  function  of  punishment  to  awaken  attention  are  ex- 
plained in  terms  of  this  automatism.  The  biological  principle  of 
4  short  cuts '  is  given  application  in  tracing  the  transformations  of 
stimuli  and  reacting  apparatus  in  the  world  of  volition.  In  society 
phenomena  of  identity  and  phenomena  of  difference  are  at  once  of 
prime  importance,  as  is  evidenced  by  the  principles  of  imitation  and 
invention,  active  under  the  forms  of  habit  and  accommodation.  B. 
finds  that  repetition  and  similarity  are  only  superficial  characteristics 
of  the  true  operative  nature  of  social  unity.  No  differentiation  can 
be  got  out  of  the  tendency  to  reproduce  a  copy  per  se.  To  introduce 
i  invention,'  as  explanatory  leaves  an  awkward  dualism.  Baldwin's 
analysis  of  mental  development  is  regarded  rather  as  failing  in  its 
resolute  repudiation  of  this  dualism.  The  root  of  this,  and  other 
similar  failures,  is  traced  to  a  fallacy  introduced  by  the  influences  of 
the  atomic  doctrine  of  association,  or  the  repetition  of  similar  units. 
Baldwin,  in  attempting  to  remould  the  theory,  strains  the  idea  of  imi- 
tation by  extending  it  to  cover  volition — the  passing  of  an  idea  into 
fact,  instead  of  limiting  the  process  to  mere  reproduction  of  a  copy. 
Nothing  of  serious  importance  happens  by  genuine  imitation.  All 
the  business  of  society  goes  on  by  differentiated  reactions.  Every 
man  in  society  is  what  he  is  through  a  law  or  scheme  which  assigns 
him  an  individual  position,  differing  from  all  others,  and  identified 
with  them  precisely  through  these  differences,  by  which  alone  he  can 
cooperate  with  them.  The  error  in  question  springs  from  working 
with  similarity  instead  of  identity  (of  factors  and  processes).  Di- 
rectly we  introduce  identity,  difference  falls  into  its  place  as  an  in- 
herent aspect  of  the  principle.  Every  action,  without  any  exception, 
is,  in  principle,  a  difference  within  an  identity.  Relative  Suggestion 
is  a  more  adequate  view  of  identity  than  Associationism,  and  B.  finds 
in  Baldwin's  later  writings  a  tendency  toward  the  former. 

EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 

The  Nature  of  Judgment.     G.  E.  MOORE.    Mind,  No.  30,  N.  S., 

April,  1899,  p.  176. 

This  article  suggests  a  theory  of  perception  and  knowledge  which 
has  avowedly  much  in  common  with  Kant,  differing  chiefly  in  substi- 
tuting for  sensations,  as  the  date  of  knowledge,  concepts ;  and  in  re- 


442  GENERAL. 

fusing  to  regard  the  relations  in  which  they  stand  as,  in  some  obscure 
sense,  the  work  of  the  mind.  The  view  which  inclines  to  take  the 
categorical  judgment  as  the  typical  form,  and  attempts  in  consequence 
to  reduce  the  hypothetical  judgment  to  it,  is  attacked.  A  judgment  is 
universally  a  necessary  combination  of  concepts,  equally  necessary 
whether  it  be  true  or  false.  It  must  be  either  true  or  false ;  but  its 
truth  or  falsehood  cannot  depend  on  its  relation  to  anything  else  what- 
ever— reality,  for  instance,  or  the  world  in  space  or  time.  Both  of 
these  must  be  supposed  to  exist,  in  some  sense,  if  the  truth  of  our 
judgment  is  to  depend  upon  them ;  and  then  it  turns  out  that  the  truth 
of  our  judgment  depends  not  on  them,  but  on  the  judgment  that  they, 
being  such  and  such,  exist.  The  truth  or  falsehood  of  this  judgment 
must  be  immediate  properties  of  its  own,  not  dependent  upon  any  re- 
lation it  may  have  to  something  else.  The  existential  judgment, 
which  is  presupposed  in  Kant's  reference  to  experience,  or  in  Bradley's 
reference  to  reality,  remains  merely  a  necessary  combination  of  con- 
cepts, for  the  necessity  of  which  we  can  seek  no  ground,  and  which 
cannot  be  explained  as  an  attribute  to  4  the  given/  A  concept  is  not 
in  any  intelligible  sense  an  '  adjective,'  as  if  there  were  something  sub- 
stantive, more  ultimate  than  it.  It  is  not  a  mental  fact,  nor  any  part 
of  a  mental  fact.  Concepts  are  possible  objects  of  thoughts ;  they  may 
come  into  relation  with  a  thinker ;  and  in  order  that  they  may  do  any- 
thing, they  must  already  be  something.  It  is  indifferent  to  their  nature 
whether  anybody  thinks  them  or  not.  They  are  incapable  of  change ; 
and  the  relation  into  which  they  enter  with  the  knowing  subject  im- 
plies no  action  or  reaction.  It  is  a  unique  relation  which  can  begin 
or  cease  with  a  change  in  the  subject ;  but  the  concept  is  neither  cause 
nor  effect  of  such  a  change.  It  is  of  such  entities  as  these  that  a 
proposition  is  composed.  The  difference  between  a  concept  and  a 
proposition,  in  virtue  of  which  the  latter  alone  can  be  called  true  or 
false,  would  seem  to  lie  merely  in  the  simplicity  of  the  former.  What 
kind  of  relation  makes  a  proposition  true,  what  false,  cannot  be  further 
defined,  but  must  be  immediately  recognized.  Existential  proposi- 
tions do  not  escape  this  description.  We  must  regard  the  whole 
world  as  formed  of  concepts,  these  being  our  only  objects  of  knowl- 
edge. Perception  is  to  be  regarded  philosophically  as  the  cognition  of 
an  existential  proposition,  and  thus  it  furnishes  a  basis  for  inference. 
From  this  description  of  a  judgment  there  must,  then,  disappear  all 
reference  either  to  our  mind  or  to  the  world.  Neither  of  these  can 
furnish  4  ground '  for  anything,  save  in  so  far  as  they  are  complex 
judgments.  EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  443 

Time  as  related  to  Causality  and  to  Space.  MARY  WHITON  CAL- 
KINS. Mind,  No.  30,  N.  S.,  April,  1899,  p.  216. 
The  phenomenal  unity  of  different  kinds  of  multiplicity  is  traced 
to  the  relations  of  time  as  controlling  the  categorical  relations  of  caus- 
ality and  space.  Heretofore,  time  and  space  have  been  treated  in  the 
same  breath,  much  to  the  misfortune  of  each.  Analogy  is  not  taken 
as  a  guide  in  the  treatment  of  the  categorical  complexities  involved. 
The  thesis  of  the  paper  is  the  assertion  that  time  and  causality  are  sub- 
ordinate forms  of  the  principle  of  the  necessary  connection  of  phe- 
nomena, and  that  the  third  and  coordinate  form  of  the  category  is 
reciprocal  determination,  not,  as  is  often  stated,  space.  Succession,  and 
not  duration,  must  be  admitted  as  constituting  the  nature  of  the  tem- 
poral manifold.  The  synthesis  of  manifoldness  follows  fundamental 
distinctions,  involving  two  sorts  of  necessity :  first,  the  dependence  of 
synthesis  in  general  upon  ultimate  unity ;  and  second,  of  the  moment 
upon  the  preceding  moment.  In  this  way  it  may  be  seen  that  time 
really  belongs  among  the  categories,  as  the  irreversible  connection  of 
the  irrevocable,  relatively  abstract  manifold.  The  psychology  of  time- 
consciousness  verifies  the  metaphysical  doctrine.  The  awareness  of 
more-than-one,  possessing  an  inner  connection,  presents  unanalyzable 
elements  given  immediately  in  consciousness.  The  causality  con- 
nection is  more  easily  applied  to  outer  than  to  inner  life,  and  thus 
remains  subject  to  the  temporal  sequence.  The  spatial  sequence  is  no 
fundamental  category,  or  uniting  principle,  but  itself  one  variety  of  the 
manifold  to-be-categorized.  Space,  as  a  sense-quality  or  a  notion,  is 
clearly  a  construct  of  experience. 

EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 
SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY, 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY. 


U  Education  des  Sentiments.     P.  FELIX  THOMAS.     Paris,     Alcan. 

1899,  p.  287. 

The  author,  who  has  appeared  before  the  public  in  other  writings 
on  philosophical  and  pedagogical  subjects,  presents  us  here  with  an 
analysis  of  the  sentiments  and  emotions  with  pedagogical  hints  and 
suggestions  as  to  the  best  methods  of  utilizing  them.  He  combats  the 
tendency  in  education  toward  excessive  emphasis  of  the  intellectual, 
and  pleads  the  cause  of  the  algedonic  and  volitional  elements  in  our 
nature.  Intellectualism  tends  to  destroy  the  will  and  the  pleasure- 
pain  values  of  life.  It  is  conduct  and  emotional  value  which  makes 
life  worth  living,  not  creeds  religious,  philosophical  or  scientific.  Pain 


444  GENERAL. 

and  pleasure  depend  upon  the  laws  of  vital  rhythm.  The  appetites, 
desires,  anger,  fear,  play,  instinct  of  proprietorship,  love  of  domina- 
tion, curiosity,  sympathy,  pity,  social  inclinations,  self-love,  etc.,  are 
treated  in  turn. 

The  style  is  literary  rather  than  scientific.  Some  very  good  sug- 
gestions are  made,  and  the  author  generally  strikes  the  right  keynote 
in  a  happy  manner.  There  is  little  justification  for  the  neglect  of 
recent  American  contributions  on  the  same  subjects.  There  is  a  good 
table  of  contents,  but  no  index. 

ARTHUR  ALLIN. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  COLORADO. 

II  metodo  deduttivo  come  strumento  di  ricerca.     GIOVANNI  VAIL  ATI. 

Turin,  Roux,  Frasati  &  Co.      1898.     Pp.  44. 
Alcune  osservazioni  sulle  questioni  di  parole  nella  storia  della  sci- 

enza  e  della  cultura.     GIOVANNI  VAILATI.     Turin,  Frat.  Bocca. 

1899.     Pp.  39. 

These  two  papers  are  introductory  lectures  in  a  course  on  the  His- 
tory of  Mechanics,  delivered  by  the  author  in  the  University  of  Turin. 
In  the  first  Dr.  Vailati  discusses  the  value  of  the  deductive  method ; 
he  examines  the  history  of  discovery  in  mechanics,  from  Galileo 
down,  and  insists  that  many  of  its  more  important  laws  '  would  still 
be  unknown  to  man,  at  least  in  their  generalized  form,  if  he  had  not 
at  his  disposal  another  method  besides  that  of  observation  and  direct 
measurement.'  Admitting  the  supremacy  of  induction,  as  a  means  of 
scientific  discovery,  the  author,  nevertheless,  points  out  the  important 
role  that  deductive  reasoning  has  played  from  an  historical  stand- 
point. He  believes  that  Bacon's  diatribes  anent  the  sterility  of  Aris- 
totle's dialectic  and  the  syllogism,  were  called  forth  by  the  excessive 
use  of  deductive  methods  in  scholastic  times,  and  would  have  been 
modified  had  induction  received  proper  recognition  in  those  days. 
The  latter  part  of  the  paper  is  a  discussion  of  the  practical  applica- 
tion of  the  various  forms  of  induction  and  deduction  to  the  discovery 
of  scientific  laws. 

The  second  paper  takes  up  the  question  of  terminology  in  its  re- 
lation to  objective  truth  and  the  history  of  scientific  thought.  Dr. 
Vailati  refers  to  the  undue  stress  sometimes  laid  on  the  etymological 
significance  of  a  word.  He  denies  the  objective  importance  of  the 
distinction  between  definable  and  indefinable  terms.  The  impossibility 
of  defining  a  term  may  be  due  to  the  simplicity  of  the  notion,  as  well 
as  to  its  obscurity ;  in  either  case  it  is  a  subjective  factor  that  distin- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  445 

guishes  it  from  a  definable  term.  The  author  works  out  for  the  bene- 
fit of  his  pupils  a  number  of  well-known  principles  underlying  scien- 
tific discovery  and  the  definition  of  concepts. 

HOWARD  C.  WARREN. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


Pensare   senza    coscienza.      G.    SERGI.      (Reprinted.)     La   Rivista 

Moderna,  Vol.  II,  Fasc.  I.      1899.     Pp.  18. 

This  is  an  amplification  and  in  some  respects  an  advance  on  the 
author's  doctrine  of  the  unconscious,  as  developed  in  his  Psychologic 
physiologique.  Professor  Sergi  starts  out  with  the  view  that  conscious 
thought  is  merely  the  last  term  in  a  series  of  unconscious  brain  states. 
In  support  of  this  theory  he  cites,  from  his  own  experience  and  others', 
numerous  examples  in  which  a  problem  has  been  solved  or  a  train  of 
reasoning  worked  out  to  a  conclusion  while  the  mind  was  occupied 
with  something  entirely  different.  In  some  instances  the  process  ex- 
tended over  an  hour,  in  others  over  a  day,  week,  month  or  more.  In 
his  own  case  he  finds  many  instances  of  this  unconscious  brain  work 
proceeding  during  sleep ;  at  one  time  it  was  so  pronounced  that  he  grew 
accustomed  to  read  up  the  theme  of  any  paper  he  was  to  write,  and 
then  immediately  dismiss  the  whole  question  from  his  mind,  without 
working  out  the  plan  of  the  paper ;  in  the  morning  he  would  begin  the 
writing  at  once  with  no  hesitation  or  difficulty,  the  subject  having 
apparently  been  analyzed  and  arranged  for  treatment  during  the  night. 

Professor  Sergi  reviews  the  theories  of  Kant,  Leibnitz,  Hamilton, 
J.  S.  Mill  and  Carpenter,  on  obscure  ideas,  subconsciousness  and  un- 
conscious cerebration.  He  gives  preference  to  Hamilton's  view,  that 
4  latent  agencies — modifications  of  which  we  are  unconscious — must 
be  admitted  as  a  groundwork  of  Phenomenology  of  Mind.'  The 
author,  however,  goes  further,  holding  that  this  "unconscious  cerebral 
and  physiological  work  constitutes  the  whole  phenomenon,  not  merely 
one  side  of  it,  and  that  the  consciousness  of  the  phenomenon  is  merely 
its  superficial  revelation,  which  adds  nothing  to  the  essence  and  com- 
pleteness of  the  phenomenon  in  question."  He  claims  to  solve  the 
problem  of  psychological  dualism,  by  making  the  physiological  pro- 
cess the  sole  '  essence '  and  the  state  of  consciousness  a  mere  '  mani- 
festation'. In  spite  of  the  brevity  of  the  paper  and  the  lack  of  novelty 
in  its  standpoint,  it  calls  for  attention  on  account  or  the  new  ob- 
servational data  which  the  author  has  brought  forward. 

HOWARD  C.  WARREN. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


446  GENERAL. 

Individual  Memories.    F.W.  COLGROVE.    American  Journal  of  Psy- 
chology, X.,  1899;  pp.  1-29. 

This  dissertation  is  based  upon  the  returns  of  the  Clark  University 
questionaires,  and  the  results  are  presented  in  the  usual  form.  1,658 
replies  were  tabulated  upon  a  roll  of  paper  one  foot  eight  inches  wide 
and  fifty-two  feet  long,  after  almost  incessant  labor  for  five  months. 
A  second  tabulation  followed,  grouping  replies  under  more  than  sixty 
different  headings.  We  admire  the  patience  of  the  writer's  wife,  who 
did  all  this  work,  but  we  fail  to  discover  any  great  value  in  the  results. 
Absolutely  no  attention  is  given  to  the  degree  of  certainty  of  the 
various  conclusions;  we  are  told  that  the  males  have  the  greatest 
number  of  memories  for  protracted  or  repeated  occurrences,  people, 
and  clothing,  and  that  they  excel  in  topographical  and  logical  memor- 
ies, while  females  have  better  memories  for  novel  occurrences  and 
single  impressions,  for  Christmas  gifts  and  dolls,  without  a  single 
figure  to  back  up  the  important  statement. 

In  the  same  way  we  are  told  that  Indians  find  shorthand  helpful 
to  memory,  and  so  on  throughout  the  various  subdivisions  under  the 
thirteen  questions. 

Nothing  is  said  as  to  the  class  of  people  from  whom  the  replies 
were  collected,  the  ages  of  those  questioned,  or  about  the  seriousness 
with  which  the  answers  were  written. 

C.  B.  BLISS. 


Schmeckversuche  an  einzelnen  Paplllen.    F.  KIESOW.  Philos.  Stud., 

XIV,  4,  591-615. 

This  article  gives  an  account  of  experiments,  a  continuation  of 
work  by  Oehrwall,  to  discover  whether  or  not  the  single  taste  papillas 
reacted  only  to  certain  taste  substances.  Thirty-nine  points  on  the 
tongues  of  two  subjects  were  tested.  Of  these,  four  gave  no  reaction 
to  salt,  sugar,  acid  or  quinine  solutions ;  seven  others  gave  character- 
istic tastes  of  each  of  the  stimuli ;  one  reacted  only  to  sugar  and 
another  only  to  quinine.  Of  the  remainder  19  +  5  (  ?  =  doubtful)  re- 
acted to  sugar,  ii  -f  13  (?)  to  salt,  1 1  -f-  1 1  (  ?)  to  acid,  and  6  +  8  (?) 
to  quinine.  Mechanical  and  electrical  stimuli  were  used  by  the  author, 
but  the  results  are  left  for  a  later  article. 

SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  447 

GENERAL. 

Ueber  die  Auffassung   einfachster  Raumformen.      RICHARD  SEY- 

FERT.     Philos.  Stud.,  XIV.,  4,  550-566. 

This  research  was  an  attempt  to  discover  some  of  the  factors  in- 
fluencing the  accuracy  of  reproduction  (judgment)  of  simple  geo- 
metrical figures.  Various  triangles  were  shown  for  a  time  under 
different  conditions,  and,  after  a  few  seconds,  the  subject  attempted  to 
reproduce  the  same. 

The  six  following  conditions  were  used :  ( i )  Eyes  fixed  upon  a 
point  within  the  triangle;  (2)  eyes  followed  a  point  which  described 
the  sides  of  the  (imaginary)  figure;  (3)  the  eyes  were  shut  and  the 
finger  was  moved  over  the  sides  of  the  triangle ;  (4)  the  triangle  was 
looked  at  and  the  eyes  were  moved  over  its  contour  as  in  (2)  ;  (5)  the 
eyes  and  finger  were  made  to  describe  the  sides  of  an  imagined  tri- 
angle ;  (6)  the  eyes  followed  and  the  finger  described  the  form  of  a 
seen  triangle. 

Owing  to  the  varied  ability  and  training  in  drawing,  this  simple 
method  (by  drawing)  of  reproduction  was  not  used.  After  the  figure 
was  shown  or  felt,  the  subject  was  given  a  card  on  which  was  drawn 
a  base ;  on  this  he  was  instructed  to  mark  with  a  p'in  the  apex,  and 
from  this  point  sides  were  drawn  to  the  extremities  of  the  base  and  the 
angular  errors  were  noted. 

From  the  results  of  nine  subjects  the  author  concludes:  (i)  The 
decisive  factor  for  accuracy  of  reproduction  of  simple  forms  is  not  the 
retinal  image,  but  the  sensation  of  eye-movements.  The  most  exact 
reproduction  of  such  forms  occurs  when  the  eye  sees  the  figure  as  a 
whole  and  follows  its  outline.  (2)  Pure  eye-movements  without  the 
image  of  the  form,  are  next  for  exactness  of  the  reproduction.  With 
practiced  subjects  this  kind  of  reproduction  equals  the  first  in  exact- 
ness. (3)  The  perception  with  fixed  eyes  is  very  puzzling,  and  suc- 
cessful only  for  practiced  .individuals.  With  unpracticed  subjects  it 
is  almost  impossible  to  prevent  the  eyes  following  the  outline  of  the 
object.  (4)  Simultaneous  movements  of  the  hand  and  eye  ('und  des 
Auges*  not  '  und  des  Armes\  see  pp.  558  and  560)  as  a  rule  lessen  the 
accuracy  of  reproduction.  Great  practice  of  the  muscles  can  increase 
the  accuracy.  (5)  The  least  exact  method  is  reproduction  from  pure 
hand  and  arm  movements. 

Horizontal  and  vertical  errors  in  placing  the  apex  of  the  figure 
would  give  similar  results.  These  errors  the  author  has  not  attempted 
to  separate. 

SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


448  VISION. 

Bemerkungen     uber     Kinderzeichnungen.      KARL     PAPPENHEIM. 

Zeitschrift  fiir  padagogish  Psychologic,  L,  pp.  57-73. 

This  is  a  review  of  the  different  studies  made  of  children's  draw- 
ings chiefly  in  America.  It  covers  methods  of  study  of  children  who 
show  special  aptitude,  the  origin  of  types,  the  different  stages  of  de- 
velopment, the  relation  of  drawings  to  memory,  observation  and  lan- 
guage. The  use  of  drawing  in  the  teaching  of  botany,  geography 
and  zoology  is  supported. 

Heredity  and  Environment.     A   Study  in    Adolescence.     EDGAR 

JAMES  SWIFT.  American  Physical  Education  Review,  1898,  pp.  8. 
Reflex  Neuroses  in  Children.  EDGAR  JAMES  SWIFT.  American 

Physical  Education  Review,  1899,  pp.  8. 

The  first  address  describes  a  series  of  questions  asked  of  Reform 
School  boys,  about  the  causes  which  had  brought  them  into  trouble. 
The  results,  though  not  decisive,  in  many  cases  offer  good  suggestions 
for  further  work. 

The  second  address  calls  attention  to  the  fact  that  defects  of  the 
eye,  ear,  or  nose,  are  often  causes  of  dullness  in  school  children. 

C.  B.  BLISS. 

VISION. 

Wahrnehmungen  mit  einem  einzelnen  Zapfen  der  Netzhaut.     G. 

F.   SCHOUTE.     Ztsch.   f.   Psych,   u.    Physiol.    der   Sinnesorgane, 

XIX.,  251-263. 

The  author  of  this  interesting  paper  shows,  in  opposition  to  Asher 
(Ztsch.  f.  Biol.,  XXXV.,  400),  that  it  is  perfectly  possible  to  throw 
upon  the  retina  an  image  whose  diameter  is  less  than  that  of  a  single 
cone.  This  is  important,  because  it  removes  any  doubt  that  may  have 
been  felt  as  to  the  validity  of  the  demonstration,  by  Hering  and  by 
Konig,  that  a  minute  point  of  white  light  is  not  seen  to  be  now  red, 
now  green  and  now  blue,  as  it  falls  now  upon  one  and  now  upon 
another  of  the  retinal  cones.  This  demonstration  gives  an  experi- 
mental death-blow  to  any  three-fiber  theory,  and  in  consequence  no 
such  theory  has  of  late  years  been  upheld  by  any  one.  Holmgren's 
experiments  of  an  opposite  bearing  have  failed  to  win  acceptance. 

Schoute  finds  that  he  can  distinguish  no  less  than  eight  different 
sizes  in  small  bright  objects  when  their  images  are,  even  the  largest  of 
them,  so  small  as  to  fall  upon  the  top  of  a  single  cone.  Such  facts  as 
this  have  hitherto  been  explained  by  supposing  that,  though  no  differ- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  449 

ence  can  be  perceived  in  the  images  themselves,  there  is  nevertheless 
sufficient  light  in  their  diffusion  circles  to  enable  the  judgment  to  dis- 
tinguish between  their  different  sizes. 

Schoute  shows  by  ingenious  experiments  that  this  is  not  the  source 
of  the  distinction,  but  that  it  rests  simply  upon  the  difference  in  the 
amount  of  luminosity.  Within  the  range  of  these  small  dimensions,  a 
given  object  cannot  be  distinguished  from  another  which  is  both  smaller 
and  brighter.  If  a  larger  amount  of  light  falls  upon  a  given  cone,  we 
have  no  means  of  knowing  whether  it  comes  from  a  larger  or  from  a 
brighter  object,  but  because  we  are  far  more  interested,  in  general,  in 
the  size  of  objects  than  in  slight  differences  in  their  brightness,  and 
hence  make  a  far  greater  number  of  judgments  of  this  nature  than  of 
the  other,  we  here  interpret  an  ambiguous  difference  in  sensation  as  a 
difference  of  that  character  which  stands  for  more  to  us.  (In  these 
small  images  we  have  also  no  means  of  distinguishing  shape,  and 
hence  all  such  objects  appear  to  us  to  be  of  the  simplest  shape  or 
round.)  The  proposition  is  thus  established  that  for  images  which  fall 
upon  a  single  cone,  the  judgment  as  to  size  is  determined  by  the 
product  of  surface  and  intensity  of  light,  as  has  been  shown  before,  in 
fact,  by  Ricio  (Ann.  d'Ottalmol.,  1877)-  Asher's  error  was  an  error 
of  method ;  he  looked  at  a  minute  object  with  a  microscopic  arrange- 
ment of  lenses,  and  found  that  for  different  degrees  of  diminution  of 
its  image,  it  always  appeared  to  be  of  the  same  size ;  but  this  is  merely 
what  was  to  be  expected,  in  the  light  of  present  results,  for  the  quantity 
of  light  thrown  upon  the  single  cone  was  in  each  case  the  same. 
Schoute  makes  the  curious  observation  that  when  the  image  of  an 
object  covers  more  than  two  cones,  he  has  the  distinct  feeling  of  basing 
his  judgment  as  to  size  upon  the  pure  sensation  of  extension,  that  with 
equal  certainty  he  feels  that  he  is  guided  by  difference  in  brightness 
alone  when  the  image  falls  upon  one  cone  only,  and  that  when  it  is  of 
just  the  size  of  two  cones  he  finds  his  judgment  wavering,  so  that  he 
cannot  say  with  certainty  whether  he  is  judging  of  size  from  bright- 
ness or  from  the  extent  of  the  image. 

C.  L.  FRANKLIN. 

BALTIMORE. 

Subjective  Colors  and  the  After-images :  their  Significance  for  the 
Theory  of  Attention.     MARGARET  F.  WASHBURN.     Mind,  N. 
S.,  29,  January,  1899. 
Professor  Washburn  reports  with  admirable  clearness  the  results  of 

a  series  of  experiments  upon  the  possibility  of  influencing  the  succes- 


450  VISION. 

sion  of  colors  in  after-images  by  the  vivid  image  of  a  color.  The 
most  important  outcome  of  the  paper  is  summarized  in  the  statement 
which  follows : 

The  conditions  under  which  the  after-images  were  obtained  were 
those  suggested  by  Helmholtz  in  the  Physiologische  Optik.  The 
subjects,  of  whom  there  were  four,  fixated,  for  twenty  seconds,  one 
point  of  an  upper  window  frame ;  their  eyes  were  then  closed  and 
covered,  and  they  noted  the  sequence  of  colors  of  the  after-images. 
The  subjects  were  practiced  until  this  order  became  invariable ;  they 
were  then  directed  4  by  an  effort  of  will '  to  '  turn  the  image  red  all 
through  its  course.'  Similar  suggestions  were  made  in  regard  to  blue 
and  to  green.  These  suggestions  were  almost  invariably  effective, 
either  by  intensifying  c  the  traces  of  color  already  present  in  the  field,' 
or  by  lengthening  or  anticipating  the  time  of  a  suggested  color,  which 
normally  occurred  in  the  after-image  series.  Thus,  a  subject  whose 
ordinary  sequence  of  colors  in  the  series  of  after-images  was  c  blue- 
positive,  green-positive,  red-negative,  dark-blue-negative,'  when  asked 
to  visualize  red  had  the  following  series  of  color  changes :  4  first,  a 
red  image  with  dark  lines,  interrupted  once  by  a  momentary  green 
image;  the  dark  lines  then  became  bright  and  the  red  negative  image 
remained  until  the  end  of  the  series,  traces  of  the  blue  appearing  from 
time  to  time.' 

The  most  evident  inference  from  these  results  is  the  identity,  for 
psychology,  of  percept  and  image — of  sensations  peripherally  and 
centrally  aroused.  These  experiments,  therefore,  though  so  distinct 
in  subject-matter,  strengthen  the  conclusions  from  Dr.  Washburn's 
earlier  study  of  the  effect  of  visual  images  upon  cutaneous  local- 
ization. 

The  results  are  also  considered  in  their  relation  to  the  doctrine  of 
attention.  4  The  effort  to  call  up  subjectively  a  certain  color  meant,' 
at  least  for  the  three  subjects  of  moderate  visualizing  power,  c  simply 
an  unusually  intense  effort  to  attend  to  that  color.'  But  the  result  of 
this  attention  was  an  actual  increase  of  the  intensity  and  duration  of  a 
peripherally  excited  sense-experience,  and  it  follows  that  the  "function 
of  attention  is  positive  as  well  as  negative,  intensifying  as  well  as 
inhibiting." 

A  criticism  is  added  of  Wundt's  theory  that  the  frontal  lobes  are 
an  attention-center.  Against  this  assumption  it  is  urged  that  it  ac- 
counts for  nothing  which  can  not  be  as  well  explained  4  on  the 
hypothesis  that  the  organ  of  attention  is  the  cortex  as  a  whole ' ;  but 
though  the  argument  is  well  sustained  it  does  not  connect  itself  closely 
with  the  experimental  results. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  451 

As  a  whole,  the  paper  is  an  instructive  illustration  of  the  value  of 
the  experimental  results  which  may  be  obtained  without  the  aid  of 
laboratory  or  of  apparatus,  by  an  investigator  who  is  quick  to  appre- 
hend a  problem,  accurate  in  defining  it  and  ingenious  in  methods  of 
working  it  out. 

Zur  Kenntniss  der  nachlaufenden  Bilder.     A.  SAMOJLOFF.     Zeit- 

schrift  f.  Psychol.,  XX.,  2  and  3. 

Samojloff  experimented,  at  von  Kries's  suggestion,  on  the  after- 
images, from  morning  light-stimuli,  with  especial  reference  to  the 
points  at  issue  between  von  Kries  and  Hess :  the  color  of  the  after- 
image and  its  relation  to  stimulation  of  the  center  of  clearest  vision. 
The  method  and  apparatus  of  the  older  experiments  were  completely 
set  aside,  in  order  to  avoid  the  sources  of  possible  error  suggested  by 
Hess.  The  color  stimuli  were  given  through  openings  of  a  revolving 
desk,  which  formed  the  front  of  a  '  dark  box'  whose  degree  of  illumi- 
nation could  be  regulated.  The  results  confirmed  von  Kries's  conclu- 
sions ;  the  after-images  of  the  yellow  stimulus  were  blue,  and  those  of 
the  blue  were  yellowish,  that  is,  the  after-images  were  negative,  and 
not  in  accordance  with  Hess's  results.  Positive  experiments  on  the 
stimulation  of  the  center  of  vision  also  show  results  similar  to  those  of 
the  earlier  Freiburg  experiment:  in  the  vivid,  even  though  inexact, 
words  of  Samojloff  uthe  after-image  overleaps  the  central  region 
around  the  fixation-point."  It  is  shown  that  this  is  not  a  mere  case  of 
obliteration  of  an  after-image  through  the  brightness  of  the  fixated 
point,  for  an  equally  intense  light,  illuminating  the  periphery  of  the 
retina  does  not  annihilate  the  after-image. 

The  writer  calls  attention  to  the  close  correspondence  of  his  results 
with  von  Kries's  theory  that  the  after-image  depends  upon  the  activity 
of  the  ''Dunkelapparat*  which  is  wanting  in  the  center  of  vision;  yet 
he  does  not  claim  that  these  experiments  furnish  4  rigid  proof '  of  the 
entire  lack  of  the  '•Dunkelapparat*  in  this  part  of  the  retina. 

M.  W.  CALKINS. 

WELLESLEY  COLLEGE. 

PATHOLOGY  AND  NEUROLOGY. 

L?  Instabilite  Mentale.     Essai  sur  les  donnes  de  la  psycho-patholo- 

gie.     G.  L.  DUPRAT.     Paris,  Alcan,  1898.     8vo.     Pp.  310. 

The  motive  of  M.  Duprat's  book  is  not  so  much  psychological  as 

philosophical  :  his  intention,  in  his  own  words,  is  less  to  write  a  book 

of  science  than  to  consider  scientific  conclusions  and  to  examine  the 


452  PATHOLOGY  AND  NEUROLOGY. 

first  principles  of  the  science  with  which  he  deals  in  order  to  give  it,  if 
possible,  a  philosophic  foundation.  In  pursuance  of  this  plan  M.  Du- 
prat  attempts  to  show  the  primacy  which  psychology  has  over  physi- 
ology in  the  study  of  mental  pathology.  The  more  particular  pur- 
pose of  the  book  is  to  emphasize  the  importance  of  the  concept  '  men- 
tal instability '  in  psychical  disease,  and  to  relate  all  concrete  mental 
maladies  to  this  as  species  to  genus.  No  mental  process  can  normally 
occur  unless  there  exist  a  principle  directing  the  mental  evolution, 
which  by  its  permanence  resists  the  natural  instability  of  the  mind. 
The  more  feeble  the  principle,  the  greater  the  distraction.  Duprat's 
book,  then,  occupies  itself  with  collecting  the  various  medico-psycho- 
logical observations  upon  the  diverse  forms  of  psychopathy,  and  with 
discovering  in  each  of  these  forms  a  foundation  of  psychological  in- 
stability. In  pursuance  of  this  purely  philosophical  plan  the  book  is 
divided  into  three  parts. 

The  first  part,  a  general  introduction  to  the  rest,  is  concerned  with 
the  mental  processes  as  a  whole,  normal  and  abnormal,  and  attempts 
to  show  that  biology  can  go  only  part  of  the  way  in  psychiatry,  and 
that  psychology  must  do  theg  reater  part  of  the  work.  It  is  impossible 
to  deny  the  existence  of  biological  disturbances  underlying  psychic 
ones,  but  there  may  at  the  same  time  be  purely  psychological  causes 
of  psychopathies.  The  biologic  centers  are  also  psychic  centers. 

The  second  part  occupies  itself  with  the  consideration  of  the  vari- 
ous psychopathic  symptoms  in  detail,  and  attempts  to  find  in  each  the 
fundamental  fact  of  mental  instability.  This  root-malady  is  classed 
according  to  its  four  aspects :  instability  of  the  intellect — incoherent 
thought ;  instability  of  the  tendencies — the  illogical  rise  of  one  from 
another ;  instability  of  the  feelings — the  rapid  alternation  from  love  to 
hate,  etc. ;  and  instability  as  action — aboulia,  ataxia,  etc.  In  the  same 
part  of  his  work,  after  considering  the  particular  mental  diseases  spe- 
cifically, M.  Duprat  considers  them  as  a  whole,  under  the  title  '  path- 
ology of  personality,'  and  the  alternations  of  this  general  psychopathy 
according  to  sex,  habit  of  life,  and  age.  Here  is  included  marked 
mental  stability — the  stubbornness  of  melancholia,  for  instance — 
which  is  shown  itself  to  be  rooted  in  the  more  fundamental  disturb- 
ance of  mental  instability. 

The  third  and  last  part  of  the  book  is  occupied  with  the  practical 
conclusions  resulting  from  these  conclusions. 

The  value  of  M.  Duprat's  book,  as  he  himself  admits,  is  purely 
philosophic,  and  can  have  interest  only  for  those  interested  in  attempts 
at  logical  classifications,  and  the  inclusion  of  specific  concepts  under 


NEW  BOOKS.  453 

one  concept  embracing  them.  This  being  the  case,  it  is  to  be  regret- 
ted that  M.  Duprat  has  been  unable  to  define  his  class  concept  of  men- 
tal instability  in  any  definite  way ;  so  that  after  following  all  the  con- 
crete mental  pathologies  through  M.  Duprat's  close-written  pages, 
and  learning  that  they  are  explained  by  one  inclusive  concept — men- 
tal instability — we  are  compelled  to  ask,  what  is  mental  instability  ? 

D.  P.  BARNITZ. 
HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 

1  Zur  Theorie  der  Nerventhatigkeit*  Professor  EWALD  HERING 
('  Akademische  Vortrag').  Leipzig,  1899.  Pp.  31. 
This  little  pamphlet  of  Professor  Hering,  while  not  the  product  of 
actual  experimental  research,  has  interest  and  value  because  it  repre- 
sents the  opinion  of  a  man  who  is,  from  his  broad  outlook,  most  com- 
petent to  judge  in  a  case  so  long  and  actively  controverted  as  is  this 
one.  The  writer  in  substance  upholds  the  doctrine  of  the  specific 
energies  of  the  various  parts  of  the  neural  organism,  following  therein 
especially  J.  Miiller,  but  he  goes  further  (as  the  rise  of  the  neuron- 
theory  necessitates),  and  strongly  believes  that  not  the  cells  of  the 
neurons  only,  but  also  the  prolongations  from  these  have  forms  of 
nervous  activity  peculiar  to  themselves  and  to  their  respective  uses  in 
the  organism.  "  The  activity  of  the  neuron  and  of  its  fibers,"  he 
says  "  may  depend  not  alone,  as  some  think,  on  the  intensity  but  also 
on  the  quality  of  its  sort  of  stimulus,  whether  this  come  from  its  own 
peripheral  sense-organ  or  from  a  neighboring  neuron."  The  physical 
basis  of  the  difference  in  function  is  deemed  to  consist  in  the  various 
forms  of  neural  vibration  which,  with  indefinite  differences  in  the 
neural  substance  chemically,  is  emphasized  as  the  4  inheritance'  of  the 
neuron  and  its  projections. 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


NEW  BOOKS. 

Psychology  and  Life.     HUGO  MUNSTERBERG.     Boston,  Houghton, 

Mifflin  &  Co.,  1899.     Pp.  xiv  +  282. 
Criteriologie  Generale,  ou  Theorie   generale  de  la  certitude.     D. 

MERCIER.    Louvain,  Inst.  Super,  de   Philosophic.     Pp.  v  4-371. 

6Fr. 
Discorsi  su  la  Natura  e  sul    Governo  dei  Popoli.     F.  P.  C.  SIRA- 

GUSA.     Palermo,  Virzi,  1899.     Pp.  410.     L.  5. 


454  NEW  BOOKS. 

The  Messages  of  the  Earlier  Prophets.     F.  K.  SANDERS  and  C.  F. 

KENT.     Second  ed.,  New  York,  Scribners,  1899.     $1.25,  net. 
The  Psychology  of  Reasoning.     A.  BINET.    Trans,  from  zd  French 

edition  by  A.   G.  WHYTE.    Chicago,  Open  Court  Co.,  1899.    Pp. 

191. 

It  is  well  to  have  in  English  this  new  edition  of  Professor  Binet's 
well-known  book — one  of  the  first  publications  of  this  prominent 
French  psychologist.  Its  positions  are  too  well  known  to  require 
statement.  The  translation  is  very  well  done.  J.  M.  B. 

Die  Philosophie  der  Geschichte  als  Sociologie.     P.  BARTH.     Erster 

Teil,  Leipzig,  Reisland,  1897.     Pp.  xii  -f  396. 

Mainly  a  historico-critical  review  of  sociological  theories.  Ex- 
tended notice  of  this  important  work  is  reserved  until  the  appearance 
of  the  later  parts.  J.  M.  B. 

La  Psicogenesi  della  Istinto  e  della  morale  secondo  C.  Darwin.    P. 

SCIASCIA.     Palermo,  Reber,  1899.     Pp-  xv  +  J7^'     L.  4. 
Talks  to  Teachers  on  Psychology  and  to  Students  on  some  of  Life's 

Ideals.  WM.  JAMES.  New  York,  Holt,  1899.  Pp.  xi  -f-  301. 
Marriages  of  the  Deaf  in  America.  E.  A.  FOY.  Washington, 

GIBSON  for  Nolta  Bureau,  1898.     Pp.  vii  -f  527. 

A  valuable  statistical  study,  with  conclusions  on  the  inheritance 
of  deafness,  etc.,  having  important  general  bearings. 

J.  M.  B. 

Personal  Competition.     C.  H.   COOLEY.     Vol.  IV.,  No.  2  of  Eco- 
nomic   Studies,  American    Economic  Association.     New  York, 

Macmillans,  1899.     Pp.  173. 
Les  Transformations  du  pouvoir.     G.  TARDE.     Paris,  Alcan.  1899. 

Pp.  x  +  266. 
Worterbuch  der  philosophischen  Begriffe  und  Ausdriicke.     R.  Eis- 

LER.     Dritte  Lieferung,  Empfindung  to   Geschichtsphilosophie. 

Berlin,  1899,     M.  2. 

As  this  important  Worterbuch  proceeds,  both  its  excellences  and 
its  defects  appear.  It  is  made  up  mainly  of  citations  under  each 
head  of  definitions  by  various  authors.  It  attempts  no  critical  or  defi- 
nitive settling  of  meanings.  It  gives  no  equivalents  in  other  languages. 
Its  greatest  defect  is  its  extraordinary  limitation  in  the  matter  of  literary 
citation — limitation  to  German  sources.  Of  English  and  American 
writers  since  Hamilton  and  Spencer,  we  have  noticed  in  the  psycho- 
logical articles  of  the  three  first  Lieferungen  :  one  reference  to  James, 
one  to  Stout,  one  to  Baldwin,  and  none  to  any  other  English  or  Amer- 
ican writer  except  Bain ;  and  this,  after  looking  up  several  of  the  most 


NEW  BOOKS.  455 

important  psychological  topics.  The  compiler  seems  limited,  in  his 
citations  of  both  French  and  English  authors,  to  works  which  have 
been  translated  into  German.  Wundt  is  the  authority  quoted  under 
all  the  headings.  When  completed,  the  work,  which  is  a  perfect  mine 
of  citation  from  German  writers,  will  be  given  full  notice  in  the  RE- 
VIEW. J.  M.  B. 
Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases.  H.  CHURCH  and  F.  PETERSON. 

Philadelphia,  W.  B.  Saunders,  1899. 

A  remarkably  able  and  valuable  compendium.  The  Neurology  is 
written  by  Dr.  Church  and  the  Psychology  by  Dr.  Peterson.  It  is 
fully  illustrated  and  the  cuts  of  apparatus  have  great  interest  to  the 
psychologist,  to  whom  indeed  the  entire  book  should  prove  of  very 
great  value.  We  hope  to  print  a  detailed  expert  review. 

J.  M.  B. 

The  Metaphor :  A  Study  in  the  Psychology  of  Rhetoric.  G.  BUCK. 
Inland  Press,  Ann  Arbor,  Michigan,  no  date. 

Geschichte  des  Lebensmagnetismus  und  des  Hypnotismus  von  den 
dltesten  Zeiten  bis  auf  die  Gegenwart.  H.  R.  P.  SCHROEDER. 
In  12  Lieferunden.  Parts  I.— V.  Leipzig,  Strauch,  1899.  Parts 
M.  i  each. 

Das  Hypnotische  Hells  eh- Experiment  in  Dienste  der  naturwissen- 
shaftlichen  Seelenforschung.  R.  MULLER.  I.  Band,  das  Veran- 
derungsgesetz ;  Band  II.,  das  normale  Bewusstein.  Leipzig, 
Strauch,  1899.  Pp.  viii  -f  168,  and  169-322.  M.  5  and  4. 

Beivusstsein  und  Hirnlokalization.  W.  v.  BECHTEREW.  Deutsch 
von  R.  WEINBERG.  Leipzig,  Georgi,  1898.  Pp.  50.  M.  1.50. 

Suggestion  und  ihre  sociale  Bedeutung.  W.  v.  BECHTEREW. 
Deutsch  von  R.  WEINBERG.  Vorwort  von  P.  FLECHSIG.  Leipzig, 
Georgi,  1899.  Pp.  iv  -f-  84. 

Mathematical  Contributions  to  the  Theory  of  Evolution,  VI.  Gen- 
etic (Reproductive)  Selection.  Inheritance  of  Fertility  in  Man 
and  of  Fecundity  in  Thoroughbred  Race  Horses.  K.  PEARSON, 
A.  LEE,  and  L.  BRAMLEY-MOORE.  Philos.  Trans.  Roy.  Society 
of  London;  London,  Dolan  &  Co.,  1899.  35.  6d. 

Des  Religions  Comparees,  au  point  de  vue  Sociologique.  R.  DE  LA 
GRASSERIE.  Paris,  Giard  et  Briere,  1899.  Bib.  sociologique 
intern.,  No.  xvii.  Pp.  396.  9  fr.  or  7  fr. 

Interpretation  Sociale  et  Morale  des  Principes  du  Developpement 
Mental.  J.  MARK  BALDWIN.  Paris,  Giard  et  Briere,  1899.  Bib. 
sociologique  intern.,  No.  xviii.  Pp.  vi  +  580.  12  fr.  or  10  fr. 


456  NOTES. 

Naturalism  and  Agnosticism.  JAMES  WARD.  Gifford  Lectures, 
Aberdeen,  1896-1898.  London  and  New  York,  1899.  Pp.  xviii 
-f-  302  and  xiii  -f-  294.  $4. 


NOTES. 

DR.  A.  E.  LOVEJOY  has  been  appointed  assistant  professor  of 
philosophy  in  Stanford  University. 

From  Comte  to  Benjamin  Kidd ;  the  Appeal  to  Biology  or  Evo- 
lution for  Human  Guidance  is  the  title  of  a  book  by  Robert  Mackin- 
tosh, to  be  published  immediately  by  The  Macmillan  Company. 

PROFESSOR  A.  H.  KEENE,  F.R.G.S.,  late  Vice-President  of  the 
Anthropological  Institute  of  London,  has  written  a  work  on  Man, 
Past  and  Present,  which  will  be  published  in  the  United  States  by 
The  Macmillan  Company. 

DR.  D.  S.  MILLER,  formerly  of  Bryn  Mawr  College,  is  to  give 
courses  (see  the  Harvard  4  Announcement '  in  this  issue  of  the  REVIEW) 
in  the  Harvard  Philosophical  Department  during  the  coming  year, 
Professor  James  being  away  on  his  *  Sabbatical '  vacation. 

WE  regret  to  record  the  death  of  Professor  Ludwig  Striimpel,  of 
Leipzig.  He  had  reached  the  age  of  87  years. 

AMONG  psychologists  and  philosophers  summering  abroad  we  note 
President  Patton  and  Professors  Gardiner,  Howison,  Bliss. 

PROFESSOR  JASTROW  is  to  return  to  his  work  in  the  University  of 
Wisconsin  in  September. 

ASSISTANT  PROFESSOR  F.  KENNEDY  has  been  made  full  Professor 
of  Philosophy  in  the  University  of  Colorado. 

P.  H.  HORNE,  a  graduate  of  and  instructor  in  the  University  of 
North  Carolina,  has  been  appointed  instructor  in  the  department  of 
philosophy  in  Dartmouth  College. 


ON  page  288  of  the  May  number  of  the  REVIEW,  line  2  should  be 
4  asserts  that  there  is  an  instinctive  fear  of  a  cat.'  The  title  of  the 
article  should  be  '  The  Instinctive  Reactions  of  Young  Chicks.'  On 
page  286,  in  the  last  line,  '  prooning  '  should  be  '  preening.' 

EDWARD  THORNDIKE. 


VOL.  VI.     No.  5.  SEPTEMBER,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


A  PLEA  FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.     (I.) 

BY  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

Instructor  in  Logic,    University  of  California. 

I. 

De  Anima,  an  Anima  Sit. 

Modern  philosophy,  both  empirical  and  transcendental,  has 
manifested  a  growing  hostility  toward  all  doctrines  may 
be  labelled  '  scholastic.'  Substance  in  general  and  soul-sub- 
stance in  particular  are  concepts  that  are  peculiarly  and  essen- 
tially scholastic,  and  as  such  they  have  fallen  into  pretty  general 
discredit  with  the  thinkers  of  this  century.  Herbart  and  a  few 
others  have,  indeed,  favored  the  hypothesis  of  the  '  something 
I  know  not  what '  as  the  basis  and  support  of  our  mental  life, 
but  these  defenders  are  few  and  their  theories  of  the  soul 
have  not  greatly  influenced  the  psychology  of  to-day.  In- 
deed, it  is  just  the  very  question  of  '  how  to  get  along  without 
substance '  about  which  all  the  tendencies  of  modern  specula- 
tive philosophy  may  be  said  to  center.  Pre-Kantian  and  ancient 
thought  accepts  the  conception  of  substance ;  modern  thought 
rejects  it ;  and  philosophy,  since  Hume  and  Kant,  can  be  under- 
stood as  a  series  of  efforts  to  explain  phenomena  without  referring 
them  to  substance  or  substances.  In  the  place  of  the  indefinite 
something  called  substance  Kant  put  the  definite  nothing,  or  ding 
an  sich,  leaving,  as  the  only  tangible  subject  matter  of  metaphys- 
ics, phenomena  and  the  laws  of  phenomena,  Content  and  Form. 
Given  these  two  categories  as  the  data  of  speculation,  the  ques- 
tion naturally  arises  as  to  which  of  the  two  is  to  be  regarded  as 
primary.  Is  it  form  or  relation-stuff,  or,  on  the  other  hand, 
is  it  content  or  sensation-stuff  in  terms  of  which  experience  is 


45^  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

to  be  described?  The  answers  to  this  question  are  to  be  found 
in  the  two  schools  or  tendencies  of  apriorism  and  empiricism. 
Both  apriorist  and  empiricist  are  united  in  repudiating  the  no- 
tion of  substance,  and  both  join  in  attacking  materialism  and 
agnosticism,  or,  indeed,  any  doctrine  which  does  not  bow  down 
to  the  all-sufficiency  of  the  two  categories  of  form  and  content. 

This  attitude  of  philosophy  is  thoroughly  in  keeping  with  the 
spirit  of  the  age,  recognizing,  as  it  does,  the  importance  of  util- 
ity and  economy  alike  in' the  conceptional  as  in  all  other  spheres 
of  action.  For  note :  Spinoza  found  that  he  can  get  along 
with  one  substance  instead  of  two ;  Kant  reduces  substance  to 
shadow,  while  his  successors,  with  a  still  greater  ardor  for  con- 
ceptual economy,  attempt  to  do  without  even  the  shadowy  ding 
an  sich.  "  Give  us  form  and  content,  or  even  pure  form  alone, 
and  we  can  deduce  or  explain  everything,"  cry  the  post-Kan- 
tian idealists. 

"  Give  us  content  and  form,  or  content  and  the  fictions  due 
to  habit  (which  latter  are  themselves  mere  facts  or  phenomena), 
and  we  can  unify  or  describe  everything,"  cry  Hume  and  his 
disciples — each  school  endeavoring  to  economize  by  doing  with- 
out some  conception  deemed  necessary  by  a  preceding  school, 
and  each  justifying  its  omissions  on  the  ground  of  the  inutility 
of  the  discarded  category.  As  a  consequence  of  this  wise  fru- 
gality we  find  that  the  modern  as  distinguished  from  the  ancient 
criterion  for  accepting  or  rejecting  a  new  hypothesis  consists 
wholly  in  the  utility  or  non-utility  of  the  proposed  conception, 
and  not  in  its  inherent  rationality  or  irrationality. 

Since  this  is  so,  it  is  fitting  that  in  attempting  to  reinstate  the 
conception  of  a  substantial  soul  we  should  begin  by  assur- 
ing ourselves  that  there  exists  a  genuine  need  for  some  such 
conception.  Are  we  able  to  explain  mental  phenomena 
without  the  hypothesis  of  soul  ?  is  this  hypothesis  of  any 
use  to  philosophy  or  psychology  ?  Now  the  various  depart- 
ments of  philosophy  have  all  shown  their  eagerness  to  an- 
swer in  the  negative.  "  The  soul  monad  is  not  what  morality 
and  religion  demand.  It  is  not  required  by  metaphysics  or 
epistemology."  But  psychology,  in  particular,  has  outstripped 
the  other  philosophical  sciences  in  the  vigor  and  frankness  with 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  459 

which  it  denies  and  repudiates  the  existence  of  soul-substance. 
We  have  in  fine  the  gladly  acknowledged  paradox  of  a  *  psy- 
chology without  a  soul.'  There  are,  it  is  true,  no  end  of  sub- 
stitutes for  the  old  substantial  soul,  '  formal  unities,'  '  concrete 
totals  of  experience,'  *  unique  centers  of  perception  and  activity,' 
besides  all  sorts  of  '  Egos  '  transcendental  and  otherwise  ;  but 
no  one  of  these  has  either  the  virtues  or  the  vices  of  the  medi- 
aeval soul-substance. 

Since  it  is  in  psychology  that  the  complete  uselessness  of 
the  soul  is  supposed  to  have  been  most  clearly  demonstrated,  it 
will  be  well  for  us  to  undertake  our  task  from  the  psychological 
standpoint  rather  than  from  any  other.  We  begin  then  by  in- 
dicating the  facts  which  would  seem  to  us  to  necessitate  the  ac- 
ceptance of  the  theory  of  soul-substance  as  a  sine  qua  non  of 
modern  scientific  psychology. 

Psychology  has  for  its  subject  matter  states  of  conscious- 
ness as  such,  i.  e.,  thoughts,  sensations,  feelings,  etc.,  consid- 
ered as  4  facts  '  and  not  as  «  values  '  —  mental  content  viewed 
apart  from  its  normative  worth.  The  same  phenomena  of  con- 
sciousness which,  when  treated  from  the  point  of  view  of  worth 
or  conformity  to  ideals,  make  the  subject  matter  of  the  norma- 
tive sciences  of  Logic,  Ethics  and  ^Esthetics,  when  treated 
merely  as  facts  form  the  subject  matter  of  the  descriptive  sci- 
ence of  Psychology.  It  is  for  this  reason  that  psychology 
occupies  a  unique  position  among  the  sciences.  It  is,  or  at 
least  it  ought  to  be,  a  strictly  descriptive  science  ;  at  the  same 
time  all  its  data  have  a  normative  aspect.  As  a  descriptive 
science  it  is  bound  to  repudiate  final  causes  and  to  recognize 
only  efficient  causes  ;  and  yet  there  are  scarcely  any  mental 
sequences  which  can  be  understood  apart  from  teleological  — 
i.  £.,  normative  or  unpsychological  considerations.  Take,  for 
example,  the  following  mental  sequence 

a          /3  f 


Considered  ideologically  the  causal  law  of  this   sequence  is 
obvious  ;  but  the  same  sequence  considered  psychologically  is 


460  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

by  no  means  so  easy  to  deal  with.  The  Law  of  Identity  or  the 
dictum  de  omni  can  have  no  direct  meaning  for  psychology,  and 
so  when  we  seek  the  cause  of  the  inevitable  succession  of  the 
mental  state  f  upon  the  preceding  states  a  and  /5  we  are  in  a 
quandary,  and  are  apt  to  explain  the  sequence  on  some  such 
grounds  as  the  possession  by  the  individual  thinker  of  certain 
organic  dispositions,  certain  brain  conditions  which  respond  with 
mechanical  necessity  to  particular  stimuli.  In  short,  we  are  in 
duty  bound  to  suggest  any  explanation  whatever,  no  matter  how 
complicated,  so  long  as  it  be  not  the  natural  explanation  of  the 
teleological  Law  of  Identity  operating  on  a  rational  mind.  It 
must  once  for  all  be  understood  that  every  fact,  mental  as  well 
as  physical,  has  an  efficient  cause ;  and  it  is  the  business  of  all 
descriptive  sciences  to  seek  out  these  efficient  causes  by  the 
method  of  Induction.  The  flowers  are  what  they  are,  not  be- 
cause of  the  delight  which  they  give,  but  simply  because  of  cer- 
tain material  conditions,  to  ascertain  the  nature  of  which  is  the 
business  of  the  descriptive  science  called  botany.  The  final 
cause  is  quite  outside  the  world  of  facts,  and  never,  except  in- 
directly, is  it  of  the  least  use  in  scientific  explanation. 

The  mental  world  offers  the  spectacle  of  a  seeming  con- 
formity to  teleological  norms  ;  indeed  so  strongly  is  this  evidenced 
that  when,  after  a  long  train  of  reasoning,  we,  as  psychologists, 
are  forced  to  say  that  the  various  rational  ideals  by  which  our 
reasoning  has  been  governed  are  absolutely  and  utterly  in- 
effective, and  that  not  one  single  act  can  be  said  to  have  its  true 
cause  in  any  rational  consideration ;  when  I  say  we  are  forced 
to  acknowledge  this,  we  seem  to  ourselves  to  commit  an  ab- 
surdity, the  absurdity  namely  of  endeavoring  to  make  mental 
phenomena  amenable  to  the  canons  of  descriptive  science. 
What  indeed  remains  to  psychology  if  final  causes  are  banished? 
How  few  and  of  what  a  low  order  are  those  mental  sequences 
in  which  we  can  get  even  the  smallest  glimpse  of  the  mechan- 
ical or  efficient  causes  which  are  to  explain  them?  While  on 
the  other  hand,  it  is  equally  true  that  if  we  do  not  give  up  final 
causes,  we  admit  the  impossibility  of  a  science  of  psychology. 
To  say  that  a  final  cause  can  in  itself  be  a  vera  causa  in  pro- 
ducing any  effect  in  the  world  of  phenomena  is,  from  the  point 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  461 

of  view  of  the  modern  scientist,  exactly  the  same  as  talking 
about  noisy  triangles  or  yellow  lies.  The  two  spheres  of 
mechanism  and  finality  of  '  fact'  and  '  value,'  of  '  description' 
and  *  appreciation,'  of  '  Madam  How '  and  '  Lady  Why,'  are 
and  ought  to  be  separated  with  genuine  Cartesian  rigor. 

Now  grant  all  this,  and  we  can  see  at  once  that  the  psycholo- 
gist has  upon  his  hands  a  first-rate  mystery  of  the  highest  order 
— the  great  and  ever-present  mystery  of 

THE  SEEMING    EFFICACY  OF   FINAL  CAUSES  IN  THE  WORLD 
OF  MENTAL  FACTS.* 

The  existence  of  this  mystery  cannot  be  doubted,  and  the 
need  of  its  solution  is  so  pressing  that  until  this  need  is  satisfied 
the  psychologist  has  no  right  to  dignify  his  study  by  the  name 
'  science.' 

The  methods  of  solving  this  mystery  are  five.  In  the  first 
place,  we  may  hold  that  it  is  the  efficient  causes  which  are  fic- 
titious, and  that  final  causes  rule  the  world  and  the  details  of  the 
world  that  everything  happens  because  of  its  fulfilling  some 
rational  end  and  for  no  other  reason  whatever.  Teleology  of 
this  extreme  type  is,  indeed,  logically  conceivable  as  a  means 
of  explaining  the  seeming  communication  of  the  two  worlds ; 
but  inasmuch  as  this  theory  precludes  not  only  descriptive  psy- 
chology, but  any  descriptive  science  whatsoever — /.  e.9  any 
science  which  seeks  for  the  how  of  a  process  rather  than  for  its 
possible  why — it  may  here  be  passed  over. 

The  remaining  four  methods  of  grappling  with  our  problem 
are  the  several  doctrines  of  '  materialism,'  *  occasionalism/ 
'  parallelism  '  and  *  spiritualism.' 

Just  as  the  theory  of  absolute  teleology  mentioned  above  is 
possible  only  if  science  is  abandoned  altogether,  so  its  counter- 
part materialism  is  incompatible  with  a  belief  in  the  meaning 
or  significance  of  any  phase  of  experience.  Take,  for  example, 
the  case  of  a  sequence  of  psychical  states  culminating  in  a  ra- 
tional '  conclusion  ' :  just  so  soon  as  we  deny  that  the  conclusion 

JThis  puzzling  phenomenon  of  the  apparent  interaction  of  two  totally  in- 
commensurate orders  of  experience  is,  of  course,  not  confined  to  psychology, 
but  it  is  nowhere  else  evidenced  with  such  unambiguous  clearness. 


42  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

was  reached  because  of  any  logical  significance  or  teleological 
reference  contained  in  the  premises — and  this  denial  we  as  ma- 
terialists are  bound  to  make — then  indeed  the  meaning  of  the 
conclusion — /.  £.,  the  conclusion  itself — has  simply  vanished. 

In  a  =  3,  b  —  c  :  therefore  a  =  c,  to  a  really  consistent  ma- 
teralist  the  *  therefore  '  which  precedes  the  conclusion  is  out  of 
place.  It  is  not  because  a  and  c  are  both  equal  to  b  that  they 
are  equal  to  each  other,  but  because  the  psychophysical  nature 
of  the  individual  who  thinks  the  sequence  happened  to  be  so 
constructed  that  the  mental  states  a  =  b,  b  =;  £,  a  =  c,  suc- 
ceeded one  another  with  mechanical  necessity.  But  if  the  con- 
clusion a  =  c  is  due  to  mechanical  causes,  and  in  no  sense  to  the 
law  of  identity,  then  all  meaning  is  gone  from  the  syllogism. 
In  short,  materialism  contains  its  own  disproof  in  that  a  rational 
demonstration  of  the  materialistic  thesis  would  be  inconsistent 
with  a  view  which  denies  significance  to  final  causes ;  for  any 
rational  demonstration  depends  for  its  validity  on  final  causes — 
that  is,  on  teleological  rather  than  mechanical  consideration. 

Leaving  these  two  extreme  methods  of  accounting  for  the 
seeming  efficacy  of  final  causes,  we  come  to  the  remaining 
three  doctrines,  which  in  their  several  ways  endeavor  to  com- 
promise the  matter.  Let  us  begin  by  considering  the  theory  of 
Occasionalism. 

The  advocate  of  occasionalism  grants  the  existence  of  both 
efficient  and  final  causes,  grants  also  the  fundamental  difference 
between  them,  and  boldly  asserts  that  notwithstanding  the  fact 
of  incommensurability  the  two  realms  of  mechanism  and  teleol- 
ogy, of  matter  and  mind,  do  actually  interpenetrate — by  the  aid 
of  a  miracle.  Every  time  that  the  rational  sequence  of  ideas  is 
influenced  by  the  material  world,  and  every  time  that  material 
events  are  made  to  conform  to  rational  law,  then  is  a  miracle 
performed  by  God.  Occasionalism  has  the  merit  of  recognizing 
the  three  great  truths  which  are  the  data  of  our  problem : 

1.  The  full  significance  of  the  separation  of  Finality  from 
Mechanism. 

2.  The  equally  evident  truth  of  the  reality  of  both  worlds. 

3.  The  apparent  influence  which  they  occasionally  exert 
upon  each  other. 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  463 

Notwithstanding  the  credit  due  to  occasionalism  for  its  frank 
recognition  of  the  difficulties  of  the  problem,  the  theory  itself  is 
impossible  as  a  serious  doctrine,  at  least  for  contemporary 
thought.  Not  only  have  miracles  gone  out  of  fashion,  but  also 
the  very  notion  of  a  miracle  is  entirely  negative  as  a  scientific 
explanation.  The  scientist  rejects  occasionalism  and  all  kin- 
dred doctrines,  not  so  much  on  account  of  their  probable  falsity, 
but  rather  on  account  of  the  certainty  of  their  uselessness  to 
science  even  if  proved  true.  Occasionalism  and  a  science  of 
psychology  are  mutually  exclusive,  and  to  presuppose  the  mir- 
aculous— z.  £.,  inexplicable  character  of  what  is  to  be  explained 
— is  at  best  an  unfruitful  method  of  procedure.  In  view  of  all 
this  we  are  justified  in  clearing  the  field  of  all  hypotheses  ex- 
cept those  of  Parallelism  and  Spiritualism. 

The  parallelist  holds  that  mind  and  matter  are  two  separate 
worlds  parallel  to  one  another,  and  that  they  never  come  in 
contact  any  more  than  do  two  plane  parallel  lines.  As  for  the 
4  psychologist's  mystery,' — viz.,  the  apparent  contact  of  mind 
and  matter — it  is  accounted  for  by  an  established  harmony  due 
either  to  a  divine  person  or  to  natural  evolution.  This  is  the 
doctrine  which  in  one  form  or  another  is  the  basis  of  whatever 
is  best  in  modern  psychology.  Clearly  formulated  by  Spinoza 
and  Leibniz,  it  remained  for  Kant  to  establish  it  upon  a  sound 
epistemological  basis. 

The  great  scientific  advantages  of  this  theory  of  psycho- 
physical  parallelism  are  easily  brought  to  light  by  comparing  it 
with  the  three  rival  methods  just  treated.  It  resembles  the  ab- 
solute teleology  of  the  first  method  in  so  far  as  it  leaves  to  the 
world  all  its  significance  and  meaning,  but  it  differs  from  that 
method  in  not  rejecting  true  scientific  or  mechanical  explana- 
tion. And,  again,  it  is  quite  as  scientific  as  materialism  without 
at  the  same  time  sacrificing  all  norms  and  ideals  to  a  blind  me- 
chanical fate.  While,  thirdly,  as  compared  with  occasionalism, 
it  is  equally  frank  in  recognizing  the  distinction  between  finality 
and  mechanism,  yet  it  substitutes  for  a  series  of  miraculous  acts 
on  the  part  of  the  Deity  a  single  miraculous  construction  of  the 
universe,  which  is  obviously  a  great  gain  in  conceptual  economy. 
Take,  for  example,  the  case  already  given  :  a  syllogism  contain- 


464  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

ing  universal  truths  is  uttered  by  an  individual  man.  The  pure 
teleologist  denies  in  toto  the  psychological  or  descriptive  side  of 
the  process ;  while  the  materialist,  if  consistent,  must  deny  that 
the  conclusion  was  due  to  any  rational  or  logical  causation 
whatever.  The  occasionalist  refers  the  mystery  to  a  miracu- 
lous interference  ;  but  the  Parallelist  at  once  undertakes  a  dual 
investigation  which  has  for  its  ends  (i)  a  logical  or  normative 
explanation  of  the  syllogism,  and  (2)  a  mechanical  or  descrip- 
tive account  of  the  how  of  the  process,  /*.  e.,  a  statement  of  the 
psychophysical  conditions  existing  in  the  organism  of  that  par- 
ticular individual  which  enabled  the  psychophysical  event  called 
the  *  conclusion'  to  follow  with  mechanical  necessity  the  psycho- 
physical  events  called  the  '  premises.' 

It  needs,  however,  only  the  most  casual  glance  to  see  the  im- 
measurable superiority  of  parallelism  as  compared  with  the 
other  methods.  If  parallelism  is  to  yield  to  any  rival  hypoth- 
esis, certainly  that  hypothesis  can  only  be  the  hypothesis  of  a 
soul-substance. 

Let  us  now  turn  from  the  strong  points  of  the  parallelistic 
doctrine  to  some  of  the  difficulties  connected  with  the  theory. 
In  the  first  place,  we  are  struck  with  the  fact  that  parallelism, 
when  taken  seriously  as  the  ultimate  explanation  of  our  prob- 
lem, presents  us  with  a  universe  which  is  extremely  and  dis- 
agreeably artificial.  Parallelism  in  the  theistic  or  Leibnizian 
form  would  have  us  believe  that  the  Deity  went  to  an  infinite 
amount  of  apparently  needless  labor  to  get  the  atoms  so  arranged 
that  they  should  be  in  exactly  the  right  position  in  the  brain  of 
every  future  thinker  or  speaker  to  accompany  mechanically  his 
particular  utterances  and  the  complicated,  because  teleological, 
sequences  of  those  utterances.  It  may,  indeed,  be  urged  against 
this  objection  that  its  cogency  is  purely  emotional  and  not  log- 
ical ;  and,  furthermore,  that  it  is  no  more  than  the  objection  to 
which  any  theory  of  preordination  is  exposed.  Now  it  is  true 
that  the  objection  of  artificiality  is  not  a  logical  objection.  It  is, 
after  all,  a  healthy  common-sense  bias  in  favor  of  simplicity, 
rather  than  a  reasoned  conviction  of  its  truth,  which  leads  us  to 
look  askance  upon  the  possibility  of  the  ultimate  validity  of  any 
needlessly  artificial  hypothesis.  And  Leibniz's  monadology,  in 


A   PLEA    FOR    SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  465 

spite  of,  or  perhaps  because  of,  its  wonderful  ingenuity,  is  a 
doctrine  which  it  is  morally  impossible  to  accept.  We  feel,  in- 
deed, that  Leibniz  himself,  had  he  been  the  creator,  might  very 
well  have  overcome  the  difficulty  of  connecting  mind  and  matter 
by  copying  from  the  clock-maker ;  but  although  we  may  believe 
that  Leibniz,  or,  for  that  matter,  any  one  of  us,  might  have 
adopted  this  plan  of  creation,  we  know  all  the  while  that  God 
did  not  and  could  not.  And  really  to  suppose  that  he  did,  is 
to  take  our  own  abstractions  too  seriously.  Nor  can  it  be  urged 
that  the  preestablished  harmony  is  no  more  artificial  than  the 
common  and  reasonable  notion  of  predestination,  for  the  latter 
simply  implies  the  divine  authorship  of  a  concrete  world  of  souls, 
while  the  Leibnizian  doctrine  implies  a  divine  fitting  together  of 
two  human  abstractions.  But  if  we  turn  away  from  such  peculi- 
arly artificial  anthropomorphism,  we  come  at  once  to  the  other 
horn  of  the  parallelists'  dilemma,  we  have,  namely,  the  task  of 
giving  a  naturalistic  in  place  of  a  supernaturalistic  account  of  the 
origin  of  this  wonderful  harmony.  Perhaps,  as  one  psychol- 
ogist has  expressed  it,  we  are  justified  for  methodological  pur- 
poses in  regarding  the  atoms  as  *  having  conspired  together '  to 
form  combinations  and  sequences ,  which)  although  conducted  en- 
tirely on  the  mechanical  -plan,  shall  yet  Jit  in  so  nicely  with  the 
teleological  world  of  mind  as  to  appear  to  influence  and  be 
influenced  by  it.  There  is  perhaps  no  logical  ground  for  re- 
jecting this  conceit.  We  cannot  say  that  such  a  blind  atomic 
conspiracy  is  infinitely  improbable  for  the  reason  that  the  dis- 
tinction between  the  probable  and  the  improbable  becomes 
meaningless  when,  all  data  being  transcended,  it  is  applied  to 
the  universe  as  a  whole,  Von  Hartmann  to  the  contrary  not- 
withstanding. Nevertheless,  despite  the  advantage  of  this 
theory  as  a  working  hypothesis,  I  must  again  fall  back  upon 
the  ignoble  refuge  of  common  sense,  and  appeal  to  our  emotional 
prejudice  against  such  artificiality  as  is  manifested  in  this  ac- 
count, as  sufficient  reason  for  rejecting  it  as  an  ultimate  solution 
of  the  '  psychologist's  mystery.' 

Let  us  see,  however,  whether  the  modern  doctrine  of  evolu- 
tion can  offer  a  less  unsatisfactory  method  of  explaining  the 
genesis  of  a  parallelistic  world.  Can  it  be  shown  that  the 


466  w.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

joining  of  mind  and  matter  in  the  living  organism  is  an  aid  in  the 
struggle  for  existence?  If  so,  we  have  a  fairly  reasonable 
theory,  and  a  theory  that  is  in  harmony  with  the  Darwinian 
spirit  of  the  times.  The  seeming  artificiality  of  the  two 
previous  types  of  parallelistic  cosmogony  is  no  longer  a  draw- 
back to  the  theory  itself,  for  we  have  the  simple  knowledge  that 
parallelism  is  a  *  survival  of  the  fittest,'  and  that  a  psychophys- 
ical  organism, — /.  £.,  a  brain  or  nervous  system — has  outstripped 
both  the  purely  physical  and  the  purely  psychical  forms  of  ex- 
istence. Now  if  this  claim  can  be  justified,  parallelism  has  a 
very  strong  case.  But  can  it  be  justified?  Let  us  remember 
that  mind  and  matter  can  never  have  influenced  one  another,  for 
the  very  reason  that  they  are  parallel  and  incommensurate. 
There  is  a  certain  formation  of  matter,  to  wit,  the  brain,  which 
happens  to  harmonize  with  thought — i.  £.,  to  act  as  if  it  were 
affected  by  final  causes ;  and,  again,  there  is  a  certain  kind  of 
mind-stuff  that  acts  as  if  it  were  influenced  by  physical  causes. 
But  if  mind  and  matter  are  really  parallel,  if  they  never  affect 
each  other,  how  can  the  principle  of  natural  selection  aid  us  in 
accounting  for  the  origin  of  their  harmonizing  in  the  living 
being?  From  the  point  of  view  of  matter,  consciousness  must 
be  regarded  by  the  parallelist — as  by  Huxley — as  an  epifhenome- 
non,  a  phenomenon  which  is  absolutely  without  effect  in  the 
material  world.  We  are  automata  endowed  with  consciousness — 
*'.  £.,  endowed  with  the  power  of  looking  on  at  the  actions  per- 
formed by  our  bodies.  But  if  consciousness  and  matter  in 
general  are  helpless  to  affect  one  another,  it  follows  that  -par- 
ticular types  of  consciousness  and  of  matter  (e.  g. ,  a  mind  ap- 
parently conforming  to  mechanical  laws  or  a  brain  apparently 
conforming  to  teleological  laws)  will  be  equally  helpless  to  aid 
or  to  hinder  the  actions  of  their  counterparts.  If  consciousness 
is  a  mere  spectator,  we  may  for  a  moment  suppose  it  to  be  ab- 
sent. What  change  would  then  result?  No  change  at  all. 
The  world  would  proceed  exactly  as  before ;  human  bodies 
would  walk  and  talk  and  go  through  all  the  multitude  of  appa- 
rently rational  actions,  and  indeed,  according  to  Huxley  and  the 
consistent  parallelist,  there  would  not  be  the  slightest  difference, 
from  a  factual  standpoint,  between  our  living  world  and  a  world 


A   PLEA    FOR    SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  467 

which  was  absolutely  without  life — a  world  which  lacked  the 
epiphenomenon  of  consciousness.  To  return  then  to  the  point 
at  issue  :  we  see  that  although  a  brain  might  very  well  be  a  sur- 
vival of  the  fittest,  the  joining  of  brain  to  consciousness  could 
never  be  such  a  survival  without  allowing — contrary  to  hypo- 
thesis— that  consciousness  is  a  true  cause  and  not  an  epiphe- 
nomenon in  the  material  world. 

But  supposing  that  we  waive  all  the  difficulties  attending  the 
naturalistic  as  well  as  the  supernatural  theories  of  the  origin  of 
parallelistic  harmony  ;  suppose,  I  say,  that  we  waive  all  objections 
to  the  genetic  side  of  the  matter,  and  pass  to  a  consideration  of  the 
logical  consistency  or  possibility  of  this  alleged  harmony.  We 
are  told  that  mind  and  matter  do  not  really  influence  one  another, 
that  they  are  parallel  and  that  the  causal  law  does  not  bind  them 
together.  Inductive  science  has  furnished  us  with  a  grandly 
simple  test,  which  is  expressly  meant  to  be  applied  to  all  such 
cases  as  this ;  we  have  only  to  use  the  three  following  rules  in 
order  to  determine  whether  or  not  two  things  are  causally  united. 

Let  the  two  phenomena  be  A  and  B ;  then  the  rules  may  be 
expressed  thus  : 

1.  When  A  is  absent  B  must  be  absent. 

2.  When  A  is  present  B  must  be  present. 

3.  When  A  varies  B  must  vary  proportionately. 

Now,  if  mind  and  matter  should  ever  be  found  to  fulfill 
these  three  conditions,  would  it  not  be  a  scientific  duty  to  regard 
them  not  as  parallel  and  sundered.,  but  as  reciprocally  influenced 
by  one  another?  As  a  matter  of  fact,  we  do  find  a  class  of 
cases  which  fulfill  these  three  conditions,  namely,  all  cases  of 
individual  life.  And  inasmuch  as  life,  so  far  as  we  know,  is 
never  unindividualized,  we  are  justified  in  saving  that  all  life  is 
an  example,  and  the  only  example,  of  a  causal  relation  between 
mind  and  matter — between  the  realms  of  teleology  and  mechan- 
ism. Whenever  there  is  life  then  it  holds  true  that 

i.  Absence  or  cessation  of  consciousness  involves  (or  is  in- 
variably accompanied  by)  the  absence  of  certain  material  con- 
ditions or  brain  processes ;  and  conversely,  when  these  brain 
processes  are-interrupted  consciousness  ceases.1 

1  About  the  precise  nature  and  location  of  these  processes  little  is  known, 
but  of  their  existence  there  is  no  question. 


468  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

2.  Presence  of  consciousness  implies  the  presence  in  the 
brain  of  the  mentioned  processes,  and  conversely. 

3.  Qualitative  and  intensive  changes  in  consciousness  imply 
and  are  implied  by  corresponding  changes  in  the  brain,  which 
are  respectively  qualitative  (t.  e.9  structural)  or  quantitative  (t.  e., 
functional). 

Must  we  not  then  admit  that  all  life  is  an  example  of  caus- 
ality between  mind  and  matter,  and  that  when  the  parallelist 
denies  this  causality  he  repudiates  the  canons  of  inductive 
science  ?  If  it  is  really  true  that  in  life  these  two  great  orders 
of  events — the  mechanical  and  the  teleological — fulfill  all  the 
conditions  of  reciprocal  causality,  it  becomes  a  scientific  impos- 
sibility to  regard  them  as  parallel  solely  because  they  appear  to 
us  incommensurate. 

But  suppose  it  be  objected  that  this  criticism  is  based  upon  a 
naive  misapprehension  of  the  parallelistic  thesis,  the  whole 
force  of  which  depends  upon  the  truth  of  the  (purely  apparent) 
causality  between  mind  and  matter  which  we  as  critics  of  par- 
allelism have  been  at  such  pains  to  establish.  I  answer  that  the 
distinction  between  actual  causality  and  the  illusion  of  causality 
exists  only  when  the  conditions  for  inferring  the  causality  are 
imperfectly  fulfilled.  When  two  things  act  to  some  extent  as 
though  they  were  causally  related,  then  we  may  with  propriety 
hold  that  the  causality  can  be  either  seeming  or  real ;  but  when 
all  the  conditions  for  a  valid  inference  of  cause  are  fulfilled 
then  we  can  no  longer  entertain  the  possibility  of  a  causality 
merely  seeming  the  result,  let  us  say,  of  a  parallelism  between 
the  two  events.  In  short,  although  parallelism  might  very  well 
counterfeit  a  causality  only  -partly  verified,  it  would  be  impossi- 
ble, or  at  least  infinitely  improbable,  that  a  perfectly  verified 
causality  was  the  result  of  a  parallelism,  however  elaborate,  at 
least  in  a  world  in  which  there  was  any  approach  to  what  we 
call  the  <  uniformity  of  nature.'  The  truth  of  this  can  be  seen 
by  a  brief  examination  into  what  it  is  that  gives  cogency  to  the 
third  canon  of  inference  stated  above.  When  two  events  are 
observed  to  be  present  and  absent  together  at  once,  there  is  a 
certain  probability  that  they  are  causally  connected  ;  when  they 
are  observed  as  mutually  present  and  absent  on  ten  occasions, 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  469 

we  have  a  probability  of  their  being  causally  connected  which 
is  ten  times  as  great  as  the  first ;  and  so  when  they  are  present 
and  absent  together  on  an  infinite  number  of  occasions  there  is 
an  infinite  probability — 2.  £.,  a  certainty — of  a  real  causal  con- 
nection between  them.  Now  any  continuous  quantity  can  be 
regarded  as  containing  an  infinite  number  of  discrete  quantities  ; 
and  so  a  continuous  variable — say,  a  curve — contains  an  infinite 
number  of  separate  variations  :  hence  when  two  continuously 
varying  processes  of  events  agree  with  each  other  throughout 
the  probability  that  they  stand  in  a  causal  relation  is  infinite 
and  equivalent  to  certainty ;  and  the  third  rule  of  inference  is 
simply  the  continuous  or  infinitely  repeated  verification  of  the 
conditions  of  the  first  and  second  rules. 

If,  then,  the  canons  of  inference  hold  good,  parallelism 
must  be  rejected.1  Mind  and  matter  do  really  influence  one 
another  wherever  there  is  life ;  indeed  life  may  be  roughly  de- 
fined as  the  single  known  condition  for  the  existence  of  an  order 
of  events  which  is  neither  purely  teleological  nor  purely  me- 
chanical, nor  yet  a  harmonious  parallelism  of  both,  but  rather  a 
perfect  interpenetration  of  mechanism  and  finality,  of  solid  fact 
and  airy  meaning. 

The  fact  of  correspondence  could,  on  account  of  the  (  equa- 
tionlessness '  or  complete  lawlessness  of  the  curves,  never  be 
referred  to  a  parallelism — /.  e.,  to  a  prearrangement  on  the  part  of 
Nature  or  God — but  only  to  a  continuously  operative  causality. 
It  is  this  latter  type  of  connection  that  unites  the  mechanical 
and  teleological  orders  of  experience. 

Notwithstanding  the  various  objections  which  have  so  often 
been  urged  against  psychophysical  parallelism,  the  theory  has 
taken  such  firm  root  and  in  such  high  places  that  I  venture  one 
more  attempt  to  show  the  difficulty  inherent  in  the  conception. 

1Two  phenomena  or  two  sequences  of  phenomena  which  fulfilled  only  the 
first  and  second  criteria  of  cause — which  implied  merely  the  presence  and  absence 
respectively  of  each  other — might  very  well  be  parallel,  and  only  appear  to  be 


A- 


causally  related.     They  could  be  symbolized  thus  :^ .     On  the  other  hand, 

two  sequences  which  in  addition  to  the  characters  of  the  above  pair  exhibited 
the  phenomenon  of  concomitant  variation,  could  only  be  regarded  as  reallv 
causally  connected ;  and  they  could  be  symbolized  by  two  concomitant  but  infi- 
nitely variable  or  '  equationless  '  curves. 


47°  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

A  mechanical  world  in  so  far  as  it  is  mechanical  is  a  world 
of  quantities ;  and  a  teleological  world  in  so  far  as  it  is  teleo- 
logical  is  a  world  of  qualities.  The  one  is  continuous^  the  other 
is  discrete.  Given  any  two  pure  quantities,  and  there  is  also 
given  an  infinite  number  of  intermediate  quantities  ;  while,  on  the 
contrary,  between  any  two  pure  qualities  there  is  given  no  inter- 
mediate excepting  the  quite  formal  unity  of  the  perceiving  con- 
sciousness. Of  course,  we  never  get  pure  quantities  in  the  phys- 
ical world,  nor  pure  qualities  in  the  world  of  mind.  The  science 
of  Mechanics  cannot  be  reduced  to  geometry,  because  the  discrete 
positions  and  masses  of  the  moving  bodies  are  just  as  important 
factors  as  the  continuous  distances  through  which  they  move. 
And  analogously  we  can  never  reduce  epistemology  or  logic  to 
a  completed  system  of  mutually  exclusive  or  absolutely  discrete 
concepts  or  categories.  It  was  this  latter  ideal  which  Hegel 
thought  he  had  attained  in  his  Logic  ;  and  the  attempt  to  express 
all  mental  life  as  a  dialectical  product  of  the  'Idea  and  its  Other,' 
of  identity  and  difference  is  as  grand  and  as  impossible  as  the 
complementary  attempt  to  express  all  material  bodies  as  the 
product  of  a  continuous  space  or  continuous  ether.  Neverthe- 
less, in  spite  of  the  failure  to  separate  things  into  pure  qualities 
and  pure  quantities,  it  remains  true  that  qualities  as  such  are 
related  in  only  two  ways,  while  quantities  as  such  are  related 
in  an  infinite  number  of  ways.  Any  quality  A  has  its  formal 
opposite  not-^4,  while  of  the  quantities  two  only  stand  to  each 
other  as  opposites,  viz.,  zero  and  infinity;  and  the  only  way  in 
which  a  quantity  can  be  '  turned  into  its  opposite  '  (without  in- 
troducing any  qualitative  determinant,  such  as  difference  in  sign) 
is  by  combining  it  with  zero  or  infinity.  To  make  a  change 
in  a  quantitative  system  which  should  be  adequate  or  parallel  to  a 
change  in  a  qualitative  system  would  involve  an  infinite  increase 
or  decrease  of  the  energy  or  quantitative  value  of  the  system. 

Take  now  the  typical  case  of  a  qualitative  change.  I  make 
the  successive  judgments :  '  Man  is  mortal,'  *  Man  is  not  mor- 
tal.' The  conceptional  universes  of  consequences  which  follow 
respectively  from  each  of  these  assertions  are  mutually  exclusive 
— are  qualitatively  different.  Now,  according  to  the  parallelist, 
there  were  two  material  systems  accompanying  these  two  men- 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  471 

tal  systems,  and  when  I  changed  from  judgment  number  one  to 
judgment  number  two,  material  system  number  one  made  a  cor- 
responding change  and  became  material  system  number  two. 
And  as  the  two  changes  were  parallel  to  one  another,  the 
measure  of  the  change — /'.  £.,  the  ratio  of  the  second  state  to  the 
first — must  be  the  same  in  both  cases.  Consequently  the  change 
in  the  material  or  quantitative  universe  must  have  been  infinite, 
as  otherwise  the  differences  could  not  correspond  with  nor  par- 
allel one  another.  But  surely  it  is  preposterous  to  suppose 
that  the  physical  world  makes  these  tremendous  jumps  in  quan- 
tity whenever  any  one  divides  a  universe  of  discourse  into  A 
and  not  A.  And  yet  if  we  leave  it  to  itself,  cut  off  from  any 
causal  connection  with  and  yet  exactly  corresponding  to  the 
world  of  concepts,  that  is  just  \vhat  must  happen.  But,  as  a 
matter  of  fact,  what  does  happen  in  the  physical  world  when 
there  is  a  change  in  the  conceptional  world?  I  say  *  Man  is 
mortal,'  and  a  certain  brain-state  and  consequently  a  certain 
modification  of  the  entire  material  universe  are  present  at  the 
moment  of  my  utterance.  I  now  change  the  judgment  to  *  Man 
is  not  mortal,'  and  simultaneously  the  material  universe  changes 
also,  but  changes  almost  infinitesimally  instead  of  infinitely. 
The  addition  of  the  word  '  not '  is  accompanied  by  the  tiniest 
and  most  insignificant  of  changes  in  the  world  of  matter,  al- 
though it  completely  reverses  my  conceptional  universe.  If, 
instead  of  the  word  *  not?  I  had  put  a  nonsense  syllable  of  three 
letters,  the  physical  change  would  have  been  equally  great, 
while  the  conceptional  change  would  have  been  absolutely  nil. 
Indeed,  if  we  are  to  continue  to  hold  to  the  parallelistic  theory, 
we  must  once  for  all  give  up  the  idea  that  the  energy  of  the 
effect  varies  quantitatively  with  the  cause.  The  change  from  a 
brain  state  accompanying  the  rational  affirmation  of  a  judgment 
to  the  brain  state  accompanying  its  negation  is  primarily  a  quali- 
tative change,  and  as  such  can  only  find  its  sufficient  reason,  its 
vera  causa  in  the  qualitative — t.  £.,  conceptional — change  that 
occurs  in  the  mind.  In  short  brain-states,  like  all  the  other 
quantitative  or  continuously  changing  elements  of  the  mechan- 
ical world,  no  matter  how  cunningly  arranged  by  a  Leibnizian 
god,  would  be  of  themselves  infinitely  lacking  in  the  power  to 


47 2  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

keep  up  with  the  absolute  or  qualitative  changes  involved  in 
reasoning. 

Every  one  will  grant  that  psychology  has  for  its  object  matter 
a  process  that  has  a  double  aspect.  Each  psychical  event  is  both 
&fact  and  a  meaning.  Must  we  not,  however,  go  even  further, 
and  admit,  on  the  strength  of  our  criticism  of  parallelism,  that 
psychical  events  do  not  have  even  these  two  aspects  purely  dis- 
tinct? Neither  thefact — i.  £.,  the  actual  presence  of  the  feel- 
ing— on  the  one  side,  nor  its  meaning  and  significance  on  the 
other,  are  able  to  be  understood  apart  from  one  another.  There 
is  no  fact  of  consciousness  which  does  not,  even  in  its  mere 
brute  presence,  imply  some  meaning ;  while,  again,  there  is  no 
meaning  or  judgment  so  universal  and  so  thoroughly  ideal  that 
its  utterance  by  an  individual  does  not  to  some  extent  particu- 
larize or  individualize  it.  In  short,  it  is  not  only  true  that  norms 
and  facts  influence  one  another,  but  each  norm  is  itself  to  some 
degree  tainted  with  fact;  and  conversely,  each  fact  is  qua  fact  to 
some  degree  dignified  with  an  ideal  significance.  Mediateness 
and  immediateness  are,  in  spite  of  their  opposed  and  incom- 
mensurate natures,  matters  of  more  and  less. 

But,  one  may  well  ask,  What  has  all  this  to  do  with  the  con- 
ception of  a  substantial  soul  ?  Suppose  all  consciousness  is  a 
continuous  sequence  of  events  of  such  a  nature  that  mechanical 
and  teleological  orders  of  existence  persist  both  collectively 
and  individually  in  exchanging  salutations  and  in  deferring  to 
each  other's  laws ;  grant  that  this  insufferable  state  of  things 
exists,  and  that  on  account  of  it  psychology  is  impossible  for 
the  simple  reason  that  a  psychological  law  could  be  nothing  but 
a  preposterous  blending  of  physics  and  epistemology :  does 
it  therefore  follow  that  we  should  add  to  the  confusion  occa- 
sioned from  a  mixture  of  two  incommensurates  by  proceeding  to 
introduce  an  unknowable  tertium  quid?  Because  matter  and 
mind  interfere  with  each  other  in  consciousness,  are  we  to  in- 
voke a  substantial  soul  as  an  aid  to  comprehension?  I  answer, 
yes ;  it  is  logically  necessary  to  call  in  a  third  thing,  a  thing, 
moreover,  about  which  we  know  very  little,  precisely  in  order 
to  explain  this  interpenetration  of  the  material  and  the  teleolog- 
ical which  is  the  everyday  mystery  of  consciousness.  Our  jus- 
tification for  this  step  is  the  following  axiom : 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  473 

When  two  things,  A  and  B,  are  related  to  each  other,  there 
is  implied  by  that  relation  the  existence  of  a  third  thing  or 
medium,  X,  whose  nature  is  *  individual''  or  '  simple"*  and  dif- 
ferent from  either,  though  homogeneous  and  commensurate  with 
both. 

When  A  and  B  are  *  attributes'  then  ^Twill  be  *  substance/ 
The  paradox  implied  in  the  notion  of  substance  is  simply  this — 
a  substance  (X)  cannot  be  a  phenomenon  or  attribute  (A,  B, 
C,  •  -  •)  ;  it  cannot  add  to  the  qualitative  content,  to  the  '  what- 
ness'  of  the  object,  and  is,  therefore,  in  one  sense  nothing ;  while 
on  the  other  hand,  inasmuch  as  the  attributes  or  phenomena 
cannot  exist  or  be  understood  in  themselves,  either  singly  or 
collectively,  it  follows  that  they  must  have  their  real  being  in  a 
substance  which  underlies  and  connects  them.  To  put  the 
thing  in  the  modern  and  expressive  terminology  of  Mr.  Brad- 
ley, every  object  is  composed  of  a  *  that '  and  an  indefinite 
number  of  *  whats.'  What  the  '  that '  is  we  cannot  easily  say 
for  the  very  reason  that  it  is  not,  properly  speaking,  a  '  what,' 
but  a  'that';  it  is  the  subject  of  which  qualities  can  be  pred- 
icated and  which  de  facto  is  not  itself  an  ordinary  predicate. 
But  it  by  no  means  follows ;  that  the  inherent  difficulty  of  de- 
scribing the  'that'  justifies  a  denial  of  its  existence.  Each 
'  what '  carries  on  its  face  its  own  inadequacy  to  stand  alone  or 
to  explain  its  relations  to  its  fellows  ;  and  the  reality  of  the  '  that ' 
— the  reality  of  substance — is  not  only  given  immediately  in  ex- 
perience, but  can  be  indirectly  or  mediately  inferred  by  reflec- 
tion upon  the  imperfection  and  unsubstantiality  of  the  attributes. 

Now  mind  by  itself  cannot  explain  matter  nor  matter  explain 
mind  ;  therefore  the  proved  fact  of  their  relation  can  only  be  un- 
derstood by  regarding  them  as  attributes  of  a  substance,  a  soul, 
whose  nature  if  understood  would  explain  their  mysterious  con- 
nection. As  said  above,  the  soul  could  be  provisionally  defined 
as  "  that  which  made  final  causes  efficient  in  the  material  world  ; 
and  conversely,  as  that  which  enabled  efficient  causes  to  pro- 
duce teleological  effects  or  meanings." 

We  have  now,  I  think,  set  forth  all  the  conditions  of  our 
problem  and  the  negative  or  indirect  reasons  for  solving  that 
problem  by  the  theory  of  soul-substances.  From  the  outset  we 


474  W-  P-  MONTAGUE. 

have  tacitly  assumed  that  *  mind  '  and  '  matter  '  were  synonymous 
respectively  with  '  teleology  '  or  *  finality  '  and  '  mechanism ' 
or  *  efficiency' ;  the  reasons  for  this  assumption  being  the  advis- 
ability of  keeping  clear  of  the  issue  between  cosmological  real- 
ism and  idealism.  All  esse  may  be  -percifi  or  it  may  not ;  for 
our  purposes  the  important  thing  was  to  distinguish  between 
-percifo  which  was  mechanical  and  percifi  which  was  teleo- 
logical.  Consequently  the  most  ardent  Berkeleyan  would  have 
no  right  to  rebel  against  speaking  of  matter  as  real  if  the  term 
matter  were  simply  used  as  a  generic  term  for  all  those  events 
and  sequences  of  events  which  conform  to  mechanical  or  factual 
-as  distinguished  from  teleological  or  normative  laws. 

After  having  pointed  out  the  equal  reality  and  mutual  incom- 
mensurability of  these  two  orders  of  experience,  together  with 
the  indubitable  fact  of  their  apparent  influence  upon  one  another 
throughout  the  domain  of  life  or  consciousness,  we  next  consid- 
ered the  five  methods  of  solving  this  problem  of  a  seeming  rela- 
tion between  two  incommensurates.  These  methods  were : 

1.  Absolute  teleology,  which  denies  the  existence  of  material 
or  mechanical  sequences. 

2.  Materialism*,  which  denies  the  existence  of  mental  or  tele- 
ological sequences. 

3.  Occasionalism,  which  admits  the  reality  of  both  mind  and 
matter,  but  explains  their  interaction  by  a  series  of  miracles. 

4.  Parallelism,  a  doctrine  which,  like  occasionalism,  admits 
matter  and  mind  as  realities,  but  explains  their  apparent  inter- 
action as  an  illusion  produced  by  a  naturally  or  supernaturally 
established  harmony. 

5.  The  theory  of  the  soul — a  theory  which  holds  that  mind 
and  matter  are  the  two  real  aspects  or  attributes  of  a  single  sub- 
stance in  virtue  of  which  they  can  and  actually  do  interpenetrate. 

Thus  far  we  have  accomplished  half  of  our  appointed  task  : 
we  have  shown  the  inadequacy  of  the  two  attributes  of  mechan- 
ism and  teleology  to  explain  their  own  blending  in  the  concrete 
sequences  of  consciousness  ;  and  we  have,  therefore,  been  driven 
to  infer  the  existence  of  a  tertium  quid — a  soul-substance — 
which  so  far  has  only  been— -functionally  defined — z.  e.,  defined 
in  terms  of  what  it  can  do.  It  now  remains  to  determine,  so  far 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  475 

as  possible,  what  the  soul-substance  is,  and  until  this  is  done 
we  have  no  right  to  distinguish  the  soul  conceived  as  substance 
from  the  soul  conceived  as  ding  an  sich.  Indeed,  the  valid  and 
positive  notion  of  substance  differs  from  the  negative  and  useless 
notion  of  the  thing-in-itself  solely  in  virtue  of  its  complete  fulfill- 
ment of  a  set  of  requirements  which  are  only  partially  fulfilled 
in  the  concept  of  a  thing-in-itself.  These  requirements  are  three 
in  number,  and  may  be  stated  as  follows  : 

1.  A  substance  must,  in  order  to  be  defined,  possess  an  in- 
telligible essence    or    character — a  mode  of  its  own — distinct 
from  the  attributes. 

2.  This   '  substantial  form,'  or  essence,  must  be  related  to 
all  the  attributes  as  genus  to  species. 

3.  And  also  to  each  attribute  as  species  to  genus. 

The  significance  of  these  requirements  may  be  best  illustrated 
by  observing  what  results  if  we  omit  any  one  of  them.  Suppose 
we  omit  the  first  requirement ;  we  are  left  with  the  undefined 
that,  the  ding  an  sich.  It  is  the  genus  of  the  attributes,  because 
all  qualities  have  the  character  of  being  presented  or  of  existing ; 
while,  again,  existence  is  itself  a  *  somewhat*  different  from  any 
or  all  qualitative  determinations.  That  which  constitutes  the 
difference  between  the  hundred  real  and  the  hundred  possible 
dollars  is  not  to  be  denied,  although  it  cannot  be  described. 
'  Existence '  is  then  both  genus  and  species ;  and  to  find  the  form 
of  existence  the  '  whatness '  of  the  < thatness '  would  be  all  that 
was  necessary  to  change  the  conception  of  the  ding  an  sich  into 
the  conception  of  substance. 

Suppose,  however,  that  instead  of  omitting  the  first  require- 
ment we  omit  the  second.  We  should  then  have  in  place  of  a 
generic  substance  simply  an  additional  and  merely  specific  at- 
tribute. If,  for  example,  it  is  said  that  the  soul  is  neither  material 
nor  ideal,  we  may  know  in  advance  that  it  can  never  explain  as  its 
logical  derivatives  the  attributes  of  materiality  and  ideality.  In 
excluding  the  attributes  from  its  own  ungeneric  nature  it  excludes 
also  the  possibility  of  explaining  the  relation  between  them.  It 
is  the  omission  of  this  second  requirement  that  marks  the  imper- 
fection of  such  systems  as  that  of  Thales.  Water  is  not  the  sum- 
mum  genus,  consequently  it  cannot  be  the  absolute  substance. 


476  W.  P.  MONTAGUE. 

Finally,  if  we  attempt  to  get  along  without  the  third  require- 
ment ;  if  we  say  that  the  soul  is  nothing  but  mind  and  matter ; 
that  it  has  no  new  quality,  no  differentia  of  its  own — we  have 
pure  phenomenism  or  positivism,  a  doctrine  which  holds  that 
the  substance  of  a  thing  is  merely  the  sum  of  its  attributes.  In 
short,  to  omit  this  third  requirement  is  to  give  up  the  conception 
of  substance  altogether. 

These  three  requirements  for  a  valid  or  adequate  concep- 
tion of  substance  are  implicitly  recognized  in  all  metaphysics ; 
but  in  St.  Thomas's  conception  of  God  and  in  Hegel's  concep- 
tion of  the  Begriff,1  the  recognition  is  clear  and  explicit,  so 
much  so  that  one  might  almost  say  that  the  problem  of  the  Ab- 
solute appears  for  these  thinkers  as  neither  more  nor  less  than 
the  problem  of  substance  as  above  defined. 

We  are  now  in  a  position  to  understand  the  nature  of  the 
last  half  of  our  task.  Once  having  justified  our  right  to  be- 
lieve in  a  soul-substance  as  existing,  we  must  further  proceed 
to  define  our  ding  an  sich,  to  fill  in  the  blank  which  is  as  yet 
only  determined  functionally — as  an  unknown  locus  of  known 
relations.  In  a  later  paper  I  hope  to  show  that  the  moral 
consciousness  affords  a  valid  and  unique  instance  of  what  is 
required  for  the  adequate  definition  of  substance ;  and  that  in 
moral  sequences  we  find  a  type  of  causality  that  is  at  once 
mechanical  and  teleological,  while  yet  differing  from  both 
exactly  as  the  common  limit  of  two  separate  series  differs  from 
those  series. 

In  this  paper  I  have  attempted  only  a  demonstration  of  the 
existence  of  a  genuine  need  for  a  soul-substance  from  the 
point  of  view  of  descriptive  psychology,  and  a  vindication  of 
the  right  to  hypostasize  such  a  conception  as  soon  as  it  shall  be 
properly  defined. 

1  See  particularly  Hegel's  chapter  on  Kraft  und  Verstand,  in  his  PJtanom- 
enologie  des  Geistes. 


THE  REACTION  TIME   OF  THE   EYE. 

5 

BY  ASSOCIATE   PROFESSOR  RAYMOND   DODGE. 

Wesleyan   University. 

The  reaction  time  of  the  eye  has  an  unique  significance  for 
the  physiologist  and  the  psychologist,  partly  on  account  of  the 
peculiar  half  unconscious  character  of  the  eye  movements  and 
the  consequent  general  bearing  upon  the  problems  of  reaction, 
but  more  particularly  because  every  change  of  direction  of  the 
line  of  regard  is  fundamentally  an  eye  reaction. 

For  the  proof  of  this  proposition  I  am  compelled  to  refer 
the  reader  to  the  original  discussion,1  where  will  be  found  as 
well  the  proof  of  the  fact  which  makes  it  important,  viz.  :  In 
jevery  change  in  the  point  of  regard  in  a  complex  field  of 
vision  the  eye  distinguishes  nothing  during  the  actual  move- 
ment. That  this  statement  seems  to  be  contradicted  many  times 
daily  suffices  to  explain  how  the  erroneous  conceptions  of  the 
eye  movements  could  have  remained  unchallenged  so  long  and 
how  so  many  false  interpretations  could  have  clustered  around 
them. 

Important   as   these   facts    are  for   the   general   theory  of 
physiological    optics,   they  have    as  well    a   very   interesting 
bearing  on  the  physiology  of  the  eye  in  reading,  whose  prob- 
lems gave  the  first  cue  to  their  discovery.     On  the  one  hand, 
they  explain  the  regular  alternation  of  pause  and  movement  in 
the  reading  eye,  to  which   attention  has  recently  been  called 
almost  simultaneously  on  both  sides  of  the  Atlantic.2     On  thej 
other  hand,  the  experimental  demands  in  the  apparatus  for  the  \ 
study-  of  reading  can  only  be  satisfied  when  the  eye  reaction  is 
understood  and  measured. 

1  Erdmann   und  Dodge,  Psychologische   Untersuchungen  Uber  das  Lesen. 
Halle,  Max  Niemeyer,  1898.     S.  68-76. 

2  Op.  cit.,  Kapitel  I.    E.  B.  Huey,  Preliminary  Experiments  in  P.  and  P.  of 
Reading,  Am.  Jour,  of  Psy.,  July,  1898.     P.  583. 

477 


478  RAYMOND  DODGE. 

The  most  favorable  conditions  for  the  exposure  of  letters, 
words,  etc.,  will  naturally  approximate  the  conditions  of  the 
normal  pauses  of  the  eye  in  reading.  Simplicity  in  the  experi- 
mental conditions,  however,  demands  that  indiscriminate  change 
in  the  point  of  regard  should  be  eliminated. 

In  all  previous  experimental  work  where  exclusion  of  the 
eye  movements  was  essential,  recourse  was  had  to  illumination 
of  very  short  duration. 

Helmholtz,  Aubert  and  others  used  for  illumination  an  elec- 
tric spark,  whose  duration  Helmholtz  estimated  at  a  fraction  of 
a  thousandth  of  a  second.  Under  less  exacting  conditions  it 
has  been  customary  to  use  intervals  varying  from  i  to  10  thous- 
andth of  a  second,  assuming  that  the  movement  of  the  eye  dur- 
ing such  small  intervals  of  time  could  be  disregarded. 

The  fact  above  referred  to,  that  the  eye  can  perceive  nothing 
in  a  complex  field  over  which  it  sweeps  during  the  movement 
itself,  evidently  prevents  any  compromising  effects  arising  from 
a  movement  begun  before  or  simultaneously  with  the  exposure ; 
and  makes  it  possible  to  use  an  exposure  whose  duration  is 
limited  only  by  the  time  which  would  permit  the  eye  to  begin 
and  carry  out  a  new  movement  after  the  exposure  had  begun. 
Such  a  lengthening  of  the  exposure  as  this  would  permit,  not 
only  reduces  the  mechanical  difficulties  of  exposure  appara- 
tus, but  has  the  more  important  advantage  of  adequate  stimula- 
tion. Equally  desirable  in  view  of  the  interest  that  has  sud- 
denly sprung  up  in  the  psychology  of  reading  is  the  adoption  of 
a  generally  accepted  interval  of  exposure,  by  whose  use  the  re- 
sults of  different  investigators  may  be  made  comparable. 

It  is  in  the  interests  of  such  a  standard  exposure  that  I  have 
thought  it  best  to  present  results  of  measurements  in  a  short 
paper  independent  of  their  general  theoretical  bearing. 

The  strained  conditions  and  consequent  inevitable  func- 
tional disturbances  which  all  attachments  to  the  eye  must  pro- 
duce, render  all  results  with  such  appliances  open  to  serious 
criticism ;  while  the  general  discomfort  of  such  methods  neces- 
sarily limits  their  applicability.  These  mechanical  difficulties 
led  to  the  discovery  of  a  purely  optical  method  which,  in  spite 
of  the  rather  clumsy  apparatus  at  our  command  in  Halle,  was 


THE  REACTION   TIME    OF   THE  EYE.  479 

so  satisfactory  that  I  have  used  it,  with  some  modifications  of 
detail,  in  the  following  measurements. 

In  general  the  method  is  as  follows  :  A  stimulus  f,  ca- 
pable of  variation  and  accurate  measurement  in  duration,  is 
thrown  on  the  blind  spot  of  an  eye  at  rest.  Since  any  slight 
movement  of  the  eyes  will  bring  it  into  view,  the  natural  move- 
ment, which  follows  some  peripheral  stimulation  e?,  will  bring  it 
into  view,  provided  its  duration  is  sufficient.  The  necessary 
duration  of  the  stimulusy,  which  will  just  permit  the  observer  to 
see  it  after  the  cue  for  movement  is  given,  is  evidently  the  reac- 
tion time  of  the  eye. 

As  the  aim  of  the  Halle  measurements  was  solely  a  negative 
one,  viz.,  to  determine  a  maximum  safe  exposition  time,  we  did 
not  feel  warranted  at  that  time  in  constructing  the  special  ap- 
paratus required  for  a  more  accurate  measurement. 

In  designing  a  pendulum  tachistoscope  for  some  general 
work  at  the  Wesleyan  University  Laboratory  I  incorporated 
the  special  features  necessary  for  satisfactory  measurements  of 
the  eye  reaction.  The  essentials  of  the  apparatus  are  as  follows  : 
A  heavy  second  pendulum  resting  on  broad  knife  edges  and 
swinging  through  90°,  carrTes  two  large  disks  on  its  axis,  one 
of  which  is  temporarily  fixed,  while  the  other  may  be  rotated 
and  clamped  at  any  point.  The  smaller  disk  has  a  radius  cf 
12  inches;  the  larger,  of  16.5  inches. 

One  inch  from ,  the  periphery  of  the  smaller  circle  is  drawn 
a  fine  black  arc,  concentric  with  the  disk,  which,  when  viewed 
through  a  blackened  tube  and  a  horizontal  slit  in  a  black  screen, 
placed  immediately  in  front  of  the  disks,  appears  as  a  short 
vertical  line  as  long  as  the  horizontal  slit  is  wide.  This  serves 
as  the  primary  point  of  regard,  and  would  not  change  its  appear- 
ance, even  during  the  oscillations  of  the  pendulum,  if  the  arc 
were  long  enough.  The  arc  is,  however,  so  short  that  before 
the  pendulum  has  completed  ^  of  its  excursion,  after  release, 
the  primary  point  of  regard  disappears ;  and  at  the  same 
moment  there  appears  a  similar  short  line,  which  serves  as  the 
peripheral  stimulation,  made  by  a  concentric  arc  y&  inch  from 
the  periphery  of  the  smaller  disk.  The  excursion  of  the  eye  as 
it  looks  from  the  disappearing  primary  point  of  regard  to  the 


480  RAYMOND   DODGE. 

appearing  peripheral  stimulus,  is  a  double  sine  of  ^  inch  in 
length,  corresponding  to  an  arc  of  about  3°,  when  the  axis  of 
rotation  of  the  eye  is  16  inches  distant  from  the  disks.  Four 
inches  from  the  primary  point  of  regard  in  the  larger  and  mov- 
able disk  is  cut  a  circular  slit,  l/&  inch  wide,  concentric  with 
the  disk.  Through  this  slit  a  strong  light  corresponding  to 
f  falls  on  the  blind  spot  when  the  eye  is  at  its  primary  position, 
and  becomes  visible  only  after  the  eye  moves. 

The  reaction  time  of  the  eye  is  evidently  measured  by  the 
necessary  length  of  the  arc  corresponding  to  the  stimulus^/". 

In  the  Wesleyan  apparatus  this  is  measured  in  .01"  by  direct 
reference  to  the  vibrations  of  a  tuning  fork,  registered  on  the 
periphery  of  the  inner  or  fixed  disk. 

The  whole  apparatus  has  a  delicate  levelling  adjustment,  and 
the  oscillations  of  the  pendulum  are  consequently  constant. 

Since  the  release  of  the  pendulum,  although  practically 
noiseless,  is  nevertheless  usually  perceptible  as  a  slight  jar, 
the  result  of  the  eye  movement  is  not  registered  on  the  first 
oscillation  of  the  pendulum,  but 'always  on  the  second.  The 
observer  only  answers  the  question  whether  the  bright  stimulus 
was  seen  or  not  seen.  The  record  is  ignored  in  the  calculation 
if  the  observer  was  conscious  of  false  movements  or  imperfect 
fixation. 

The  results  of  the  experiments  are  given  in  the  following 
tables.  Observer  J^  is  Mr.  E.  M.  Quittmeyer,  class  of  1899, 
Wesleyan  University,  an  honor  student  in  philosophy.1 

Observer  D  is  the  writer.  A  long  series  of  preliminary  ex- 
periments gave  for  each  experimenter  the  probable  upper  and 
lower  limits  of  variation  from  the  true  reaction  mean. 

The  succeeding  experiments  were  made  in  blocks  of  ten,  in 
which  'f  was  given  an  arbitrary  duration.  A  sufficient  num- 
ber of  such  blocks  of  experiments  was  made  to  give  D  100  ex- 
periments each,  when  '_/"'  had  the  values  160,  170,  180  and 
190  0,  after  the  cue  for  movement  had  been  given.  J§L  niade  50 

1  Mr.  Quittmeyer's  services  in  the  experiments  reported  are  more  than  the 
faithful  work  of  a  careful  observer.  Many  of  the  details  of  illumination  are 
due  to  his  suggestion,  and  if  a  number  of  circumstances  had  not  conspired 
to  prevent  it,  it  was  intended  that  he  should  make  the  report. 


THE  REACTION  TIME    OF   THE  EVE.  481 

experiments  each  when  *y '  had  the  values  150,  160,  170,  180 
and  1 90*7. 

The  lower  limits  were  determined  by  a  larger  number  of 
trials,  as  they  were  of  peculiar  importance.  No  attempt  was 
made  to  determine  accurately  the  upper  limits  beyond  which  no 
negative  answers  were  given.  As  is  general  in  reaction  studies, 
the  maximum  records  have  very  little  meaning,  owing  to  the 
complex  conditions  which  determine  them. 

In  a  very  large  number  of  experiments  J<J/s  lower  limit  for 
(f  was  140*7.  Z?'s  lower  limit  for  '  f '  was  150*7. 

4, 

f=  150       160       170       180       190 

seen  =2  6         31         41         44 

not  seen  =     48         44         19  9  6 

The  mean  reaction  time  evidently  cannot  be  reckoned  as  an 
arithmetical  average  of  all  the  reactions,  but  must  be  given  as 
that  value  which  l  f '  must  have  in  order  that  just  as  many  re- 
actions should  lie  above  as  below  it.  This  will  be  the  case  when 

% 
seen  =  — .     From  the  above  data  it  is  evident  that  the  mean  re- 

2 

action  of  J^Mies  between  160  and  170,  and  must  have  a  value  of 
167.6*7. 

D. 

f  =  160  170  180  190 

seen  =    15  41  58  73 

not  seen  =    85  59  42  27 

The  mean  reaction  time  of  D  lies  consequently  between  170 
and  180,  and  has  a  value  of  175.8*7. 

It  is  evident  that  the  time  interval  thus  measured  does  not 
correspond  exactly  with  the  reaction  time  as  ordinarily  under- 
stood. In  addition  to  the  peripheral  and  central  processes, 
which  theoretically  make  up  the  true  reaction  time,  the  eye  re- 
action includes  two  other  processes  :  first,  the  slight  movement 
necessary  to  bring  the  light  on  to  a  sensitive  part  of  the  retina ; 
and  secondly,  the  duration  of  that  stimulation  necessary  to  pro- 
duce a  sensation. 


RAYMOND  DODGE. 

Of  these  the  second  is  well  known  to  be  only  a  fraction  of  a 
thousandth  of  a  second,  and  may  be  disregarded. 

The  first  is  apparently  more  important ;  but,  according  to 
the  known  rapidity  of  the  movement  of  the  eye,  must  be  much 
smaller  than  the  mean  variation,  since  the  eye  moves  through 
5°  in  10-15  0;1  while  the  stimulus  '/"'  touches  a  sensitive  part 
of  the  retina  and  appears  as  a  bright  band  before  the  eye 
has  moved  i°  in  30'.  Moreover,  this  small  lost  movement  is 
scarcely  to  be  obviated  by  any  mechanical  means,  since  it 
represents  an  excursion  of  a  point  on  the  cornea  of  about  .on 
inch,  an  excursion  which  even  the  most  delicate  mechanical 
attachment  could  scarcely  reduce. 

If  we  attempted  any  correction  for  these  constant  errors,  it 
would  reduce  the  mean  reaction  time  about  6<r. 

4J.  to  162*7. 
D  to  170*7. 

The  minimal  reactions,  however,  signify  more  for  the  de- 
termination of  experimental  conditions  than  the  mean  reaction 
time.  In  view  of  the  foregoing  measurements,  I  feel  justified 
in  making  the  general  recommendation  that  whenever  practic- 
able the  exposures  in  the  psychology  of  reading,  as  well  as 
elsewhere,  where  a  maximum  constant  exposure  is  desired, 
which  is  still  too  short  for  a  change  in  the  primary  point  of 
regard,  be  given  a  uniform  duration  of  .1". 

Undoubtedly  a  slightly  longer  exposure  might  be  used  in 
most  cases ;  but,  in  general,  I  believe  it  to  be  advisable  to  use  a 
duration  so  small  that  it  may  remain  constant,  while  the  ease 
with  which  .1"  can  be  measured  and  controlled  is  perhaps  an 
added  argument  in  its  favor. 

There  is  a  difficulty  in  the  above  method  that  makes  it  use- 
less for  unpractised  observers ;  this  is  the  general  inability  to 
keep  the  eye  fixed  when  expecting  a  peripheral  stimulation. 
It,  however,  is  the  most  accurate  optical  method  when  one  has 
become  master  of  the  eye  movement,  since  a  very  slight  move- 
ment is  enough  to  bring  the  bright  light  into  view. 

1  Lamanski,  Bestimmung  der  Winkelgeschwindigkeit  der  Blickbewegung. 
Pfliiger's  Archiv  f.  d.  g.  P.,  II.,  p.  418-422.  Dodge,  Anhang  zu  psycholo- 
gische  Untersuchungen  iiber  das  Lesen. 


THE  REACTION  TIME    OF  THE  EYE.  483 

A  much  simpler  method  is  recommended  when  the  aim  is 
merely  to  control  the  time  of  exposure,  or  to  demonstrate  to  a 
class  that  within  the  given  exposure  no  movement  of  the  eye 
takes  place.  Under  these  conditions  it  is  only  necessary  to 
expose  two  letters  for  the  interval  in  question,  far  enough  apart, 
so  that  when  either  one  is  fixated  the  other  is  not  recognizable. 
If  one  is  exposed  at  the  primary  point  of  regard,  only  a  move- 
ment can  make  the  other  visible ;  and  unless  it  is  possible, 
after  repeated  trials,  to  see  both,  the  interval  of  exposure  must 
be  too  short  for  the  movement  in  question.  If  the  attempt  were 
made  to  determine  the  mean  reaction  time  by  this  method,  the 
corrections  for  the  time  of  movement  of  the  eye  would  assume 
considerable  importance,  and  would  demand  special  measure- 
ments. 


A  STUDY  IN  THE  DYNAMICS  OF  PERSONAL 
RELIGION. 

BY  PROFESSOR  GEORGE   ALBERT  COE. 
North-western   University. 

Up  to  1891  the  history  of  psychology  contained  no  example 
of  the  systematic  application  of  empirical  methods  of  research 
to  the  religious  phenomena  in  the  midst  of  which  we  are  living. 
Since  that  time,  however,  President  Hall  and  several  of  his 
pupils,  notably  Professor  Starbuck,  have  published  significant 
contributions  upon  certain  branches  of  this  subject.1  The  chief 
result  is  the  establishment  of  definite  correlations  between  relig- 
ious experience  and  adolescence.  The  conclusion  most  thor- 
oughly worked  out  is  that  the  period  of  greatest  religious  trans- 
formation for  both  males  and  females  is,  in  general,  the  period 
of  physical  transformation  from  childhood  to  adult  life.  Another 
important  generalization  is  that  what  is  called  conversion  is 
only  one  of  many  forms  in  which  a  normal  adolescent  religious 
change  clothes  itself.  From  the  case  in  which  childhood  re- 
ligion grows  mature  without  special  agitation,  to  the  cases  in 
which  conversion  takes  place  amid  volcanic  outbursts  of  emo- 
tion, there  is  every  grade  and  variety  of  disturbance,  though 
with  the  same  general  outcome  when  adolescence  is  over. 

These  differences  have  never  been  satisfactorily  accounted 
for,  and  indeed  the  question  has  hardly  been  raised  except  for 
the  sake  of  hazarding  a  guess.  "The  explanation  of  sudden 
conversions,"  says  Bain,  "is  no  doubt  to  be  sought  in  some  over- 
powering impression  upon  the  mind  that  supplies  a  new  and 
energetic  motive  to  the  will,  thereby  initiating  a  new  line  of 

!G.  Stanley  Hall:  The  Moral  and  Religious  Training  of  Children,  Ped. 
Sem.,  I.,  196!? . ;  E.  D.  Starbuck:  A  Study  of  Conversion,  Am.  J.  Psy.,  VIII., 
268ff.,  and  Some  Aspects  of  Religious  Growth,  Am.  J.  Psy.,  IX.,  yoff. ;  A.  H. 
Daniels  :  The  New  Life,  Am.  J.  Psy.,  VI.,  6iff. ;  J.  H.  Leuba  :  A  Study  in  the 
Psychology  of  Religious  Phenomena,  Am.J.  Psy.,  VII.,  sogff.  See  also  Luther 
Gulick:  Age,  Sex  and  Conversion,  Association  Outlook,  Dec.,  1897. 

484 


DYNAMICS   OF  PERSONAL  RELIGION.  485 

conduct.  *  *  *  Such  changes  occasionally  happen,  but  not 
without  terrific  struggles,  which  prove  how  hard  it  is  to  set  up 
the  volition  of  a  day  against  the  bent  of  years."1  Here  all  sud- 
den conversions  are  lumped  together  as  though  they  were  all 
of  one  type ;  all  are  declared  to  be  accompanied  by'  terrific 
struggles,  and  all  are  explained  by  a  single  circumstance. 

Equally  incomplete  is  the  explanation  of  Nietsche  when  he 
snarls  at  Christianity  because,  as  he  thinks,  it  is  not  in  contact 
with  reality.  He  declares  that  Christianity  cultivates  "  an 
imaginary  psychology  (nothing  but  self-misunderstandings,  in- 
terpretations of  pleasant  or  unpleasant  general  feelings, — for  ex- 
ample, the  conditions  of  the  nervus  sympathicus^ — with  the 
help  of  the  sign-language  of  religio-moral  idiosyncrasy, — repen- 
tance, remorse  of  conscience,  temptations  by  the  devil,  presence 
of  God").2  Doubtless  this  statement  contains  some  truth;  yet 
it  is  as  inadequate  to  explain  the  broad  variety  of  experiences  oc- 
curring under  Christian  influences  as  it  is  to  explain  the  whole 
sphere  of  perception,  normal  and  abnormal  together. 

Here  and  there  a  more  probable  hint  has  appeared.  Thus, 
Havelock  Ellis  makes  the  remark  that  a  sudden  explosion  of 
suppressed  hypnotic  centers  is  '  the  most  important  key  to  the 
psychology  of  conversion.'3  Leuba,  speaking  of  the  conver- 
sion of  John  Wesley,  throws  out  this  hint :  "  An  interesting  re- 
mark can  be  made  here  concerning  the  influence  of  suggestion  : 
it  is  as  the  change  that  God  works  in  the  heart  is  being  described 
that  the  very  same  transformation  takes  place  in  Wesley."4  The 
same  writer  also  remarks  that  "  the  particular  forms  in  which 
affective  states  dress  themselves  are  functions  of  the  intellectual 
atmosphere  of  the  time." 5  This  is  undoubtedly  a  hopeful  clue  ; 
but  when  the  same  writer  goes  on  to  affirm  that  joy  "  is  never 
altogether  wanting,  and  is  always  violent  during  the  first  hours 
or  days  that  follow,"6  he  misses  an  essential  fact.  Starbuck 
was,  I  believe,  the  first  writer  to  give  adequate  recognition,  with 

Emotions   and  Will,  3d  ed.,  N.  Y.,  1876,  453^ 
2Antichrist,  Works,  N.  Y.,  1896,  XL,  253. 
3 Man  and  Woman,  2d.  ed.,  Lond.,  1898,  292. 
4Psy.  of  Relig.  Phenomena,  Am.  J.  Psy.,  VII.,  340. 
5  Id- ,357- 
•Id.,  351. 


486  GEORGE  ALBERT  COE. 

empirical  data,  to  the  marvellous  varieties  that  cluster  about 
such  terms  as  conversion.  He  advanced  a  step  toward  their 
explanation,  also,  when  he  showed  that  something  more  than  a 
conscious  exercise  of  either  intellect  or  will  was  central  in 
adolescent  conversions.1  He  came  still  closer  to  the  problem 
when  he  found  imitation,  example,  etc.,  presenjt  as  motives  in  15 
per  cent,  of  his  cases.2  Nevertheless,  a  moment's  reflection 
upon  the  capacity  of  the  average  person  to  tell  the  truth  re- 
garding his  own  motives  will  reveal  some  insecurity  in  these 
results  and  bring  up  the  whole  question  of  the  best  method  &f 
getting  at  the  facts.  Another  clue  emerged  in  Starbuck's  ad- 
mission that  <  much  depends  upon  temperament.'3  Yet  this 
clue  has  never  been  followed  up.  In  fact,  this  same  writer, 
commenting  on  some  of  his  cases,  confesses  that  some  religious 
experiences  <  seem  to  come  in  the  most  unaccountable  ways.'4 
Now,  I  venture  to  believe  that,  if  we  could  secure  sufficiently 
full  information  as  to  the  conditions,  every  one  of  these  cases 
could  be  accounted  for. 

The  present  study,  accordingly,  is  an  attempt  at  a  more 
complete  analysis  of  individual  cases  than  has  heretofore  been 
attempted.  If  we  can  lay  bare  the  factors  in  a  few  cases  that 
are  fully  accessible,  the  information  thus  acquired  may  after- 
ward be  of  service  in  interpreting  the  broader  differences  of 
sects  and  religions.  To  forestall  misunderstandings,  it  may  be 
well  to  state  at  this  point  that  the  phrase  '  the  dynamics  of  per- 
sonal religion '  is  not  intended  to  convey,  and  cannot  properly 
convey,  any  metaphysical  meaning.  The  problem  concerns  the 
concomitance  of  certain  groups  of  phenomena  and  nothing  more. 
The  question  of  divine  influences  in  the  mind  of  man  and  in  his- 
tory must  stand  in  exactly  the  same  position  at  the  end  of  such 
a  study  as  it  does  at  the  outset.  Any  one  who  prefers  to  do  so 
is  at  liberty  to  interpret  every  result  as  a  description  of  the  mode 
of  God's  working  in  the  world.  Nothing  in  the  study  itself  has 
any  logical  tendency  to  undermine  this  belief. 

Our  task  consists  in  looking  for  coordinations  between  spe- 
cific inner  states  and  tendencies  and  specific  external  circum- 

1  Am.  J.  Psy.,  VIII. ,  292.  *Am.  J.  Psy.,  IX.,   no. 

2 Id.,  281.  *Id.,8i. 


DYNAMICS   OF  PERSONAL  RELIGION.  487 

stances.  We  are  confronted  at  the  outset  with  the  problem  of 
how  to  secure  adequate  data.  In  previous  studies  in  the  psy- 
chology of  religion  reliance  has  been  placed  upon  the  question- 
naire method,  which  consists  in  securing  from  many  persons 
written  answers  to  printed  questions  regarding  their  experiences. 
This  is  doubtless  a  satisfactory  method  of  securing  certain  facts  ; 
but  our  inquiry  calls  also  for  information  which  the  writers  of 
such  papers  ordinarily  do  not  and  cannot  possess.  Accordingly, 
my  question  list  was  so  constructed  and  the  answers  so  used  as 
to  make  the  latter  not  merely  a  record  of  certain  facts,  but  also 
a  reflection  of  the  personality  of  the  writer.  These  answers 
were  also  supplemented  in  various  ways :  First,  personal  inter- 
views were  had  with  a  large  proportion  of  the  persons  examined. 
The  cross-questioning  which  these  interviews  made  possible  not 
only  cleared  up  doubtful  points  in  the  papers,  but  also  elicited 
many  new  and  important  facts.  Second,  a  large  proportion  of 
the  subjects  were  placed  under  careful  scrutiny  by  myself  and 
others,  with  a  view  to  securing  objective  evidence  as  to  tempera- 
ment. These  observations  were  guided  by  a  carefully  prepared 
scheme  of  temperamental  manifestations.  Third,  interviews, 
based  upon  the  same  scheme,  were  had  with  friends  and  ac- 
quaintances of  certain  of  the  persons  under  examination. 
Finally,  in  order  to  get  at  the  facts  of  suggestibility,  hypnotic 
experiments  were  made  upon  all  the  important  cases  that  were 
accessible.  Fuller  description  of  some  of  these  methods  of 
gathering  data  will  appear  later. 

The  number  of  persons  examined  was  74.  Of  these,  50  were 
males,  and  24  females.  Nearly  all  are  college  students  who 
are  healthy  in  both  mind  and  body  and  have  had  the  advantage 
of  positive  moral  and  religious  training.  Nearly  all  are  just 
past,  or  are  just  passing  out  of,  the  adolescent  period.  The 
average  age  of  the  men  was  24.7,  and  of  the  women  (one  case, 
65  years  of  age  being  excluded),  22.  Though  this  narrows 
the  range  of  observation  of  temperament  chiefly  to  the  forma- 
tive years,  it  brings  these  compensating  advantages  :  the  near- 
ness of  the  chief  religious  experiences,  the  habit  of  introspec- 
tive analysis  specially  characteristic  of  adolescence;  and  the 
na'ive  and  spontaneous  expression  of  personal  facts.  Again,  a 


GEORGE  ALBERT  COE. 

large  majority  of  the  subjects  were  brought  up  under  the  influ- 
ence of  the  Methodist  Church,  which  lays  great  stress  upon 
personal  religious  experiences.  The  opportunity  to  study  the 
effects  of  suggestion  was  therefore  excellent.  In  general,  in 
spite  of  some  limitations  of  the  field  of  observation,  the  differ- 
ences in  both  type  of  religious  experience  and  type  of  mental 
organization  were  many  and  great.  The  accessibility  of  the 
material,  moreover,  and  the  opportunity  to  observe,  ask  ques- 
tions and  experiment  repeatedly — these  easily  outweigh  all  the 
limitations.  It  is,  indeed,  not  easy  to  see  how  a  more  satisfac- 
tory set  of  cases  could  be  secured. 

Let  us  now  turn  to  the  variations  in  religious  experience 
from  individual  to  individual.  The  chief  one,  and  the  one 
with  which  this  study  is  occupied,  is  in  the  degree  of  abrupt- 
ness of  religious  changes.  One  person  reaches  a  higher  plane 
of  the  religious  life  by  a  process  of  development  scarcely  ruffled 
by  excitement ;  another  attains  the  same  state  by  passing  through 
a  mental  cataclysm.  Some  elements  of  the  explanation  lie  on 
the  surface.  For  instance,  the  striking  changes  occur  chiefly 
among  denominations  that  definitely  aim  to  secure  them.  Fur- 
thermore, these  denominations  have  discovered  many  of  the 
conditions  favorable  for  producing  such  changes,  such  as  a  par- 
ticular type  or  particular  types  of  preaching  and  appeal ;  the 
use  of  music,  particularly  of  certain  kinds ;  intense  social  feel- 
ing fostered  by  meetings  ;  the  provision  of  external  acts,  signs 
or  instruments — such  as  rising  for  prayers  or  to  indicate  de- 
cision, going  forward,  the  altar,  the  mourners'  bench — all  of 
which  evoke  expression  of  the  inner  state  and  thereby  intensify 
it ;  and,  finally,  the  fitting  of  all  the  conditions  together  so  as  to 
produce  a  climax  or  a  series  of  climaxes.  What  we  need  to 
determine  next  is  the  mental  mechanism  to  which  all  this  ap- 
peals, and  also  the  reason  why  it  fails  of  its  result  in  many 
cases  in  which  the  conditions  give  hope  of  success.  For  it  is  a 
matter  of  everyday  knowledge  in  revival  churches  that  of  two 
persons  brought  up  in  the  same  manner,  and  apparently  meet- 
ing the  same  conditions,  one  may  experience  a  brilliant  conver- 
sion, while  the  other  may  experience  no  such  states  at  all. 

In  order  to  secure  definite  ground  for  an  hypothesis  on  this 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  489 

point,  the  persons  under  examination  were  divided  into  two 
groups  :  those  who  had  experienced  a  marked  transformation, 
and  those  who  had  not.  The  fact  that  religious  changes  show 
all  degrees  of  rapidity  and  of  emotional  intensity  made  it  neces- 
sary to  draw  this  line  with  great  care.  In  every  case,  there- 
fore, which  the  papers  left  in  doubt,  a  personal  interview  was 
had.  Striking  transformation  was  defined  to  the  subject  as  a 
profound  change,  which,  though  not  necessarily  instantaneous, 
seems  to  the  subject  of  it  to  be  distinctly  different  from  a  pro- 
cess of  growth,  however  rapid.  As  soon  as  the  subject  grasped 
this  definition,  he  was  requested  to  classify  himself,  and  his  de- 
cision was  accepted  as  final. 

In  the  second  place,  a  cross  division  was  made  on  the  basis 
of  predisposition  of  the  mind  toward  such  experiences.  Let  us 
call  this  basis  '  expectation  of  transformation.'  A  careful  study 
was  made  of  the  home  influences,  the  general  church  environ- 
ment and  the  specific  circumstances  surrounding  the  religious 
awakening.  Here,  again,  much  had  to  be  drawn  out  by  personal 
interviews.  A  considerable  number  of  the  subjects  had  been 
taught  that  one  who  has  been  religious  from  childhood  does  not 
need  a  marked  conversion.  Others  indicated  that  their  thoughts 
were  never  turned  strongly  in  the  direction  of  conversion.  All 
such  were  classed  as  not  expecting  a  transformation. 

Combining  these  two  modes  of  division  we  secure  two  posi- 
tive classes  for  minute  study — those  who  expected  a  transforma- 
tion and  experienced  one,  and  those  who  expected,  but  failed 
to  experience.  In  the  working  out  of  this  scheme  a  third  division 
was  found  necessary  in  order  to  tabulate  cases  in  which  these  two 
classes  overlap ;  for  a  number  of  persons  who  experienced  a 
marked  transformation  were  unsatisfied  and  sought  for  some- 
thing more  without  securing  it,  while  others  were  satisfied,  but 
sought  for  a  still  higher  experience  in  vain. 

To  do  justice  to  the  case,  it  is  necessary  to  note  the  caution 
that  was  exercised  in  making  the  classes.  For  example,  in  the 
class  of  those  who  expected  but  failed  to  experience  there  are 
included  none  who  did  not  distinctly  declare  that  they  sought 
an  experience  without  finding.  Most,  if  not  all,  of  them  had 
subsequently  learned  how  to  be  religious  in  spite  of  this  disap- 


49°  GEORGE  ALBERT   COE. 

pointment,  yet  the  struggle  in  a  large  proportion  of  the  cases 
had  been  acute. 

From  theology  the  suggestion  may  come  that  possibly  these 
persons  did  not  really  surrender  themselves  to  God.  But  an 
a  -priori  assertion,  or  rather  guess,  like  this  ought  to  have  little 
weight  as  against  the  following  :  All  the  evidence  of  the  facts 
goes  to  show  that  those  who  were  disappointed  had  put  them- 
selves in  the  same  attitude  of  will  as  the  others  :  furthermore,  a 
large  majority  of  the  disappointed  ones  are  now  living  positively 
religious  lives  in  the  evangelical  sense  of  religious. 

These  two  classes  were  next  examined  with  respect  to  tem- 
perament. This  was  a  laborious  and  perplexing  undertaking, 
both  on  account  of  the  unsatisfactory  treatment  of  temperament 
by  writers  on  psychology,  and  because  of  the  complexity  of  the 
facts  to  be  observed.  It  is  easy  for  any  psychologist  to  give 
a  classification  of  temperaments  that  can  be  brilliantly  illus- 
trated from  history,  but  it  is  quite  another  thing  to  devise  a 
method  for  [grouping  the  persons  one  comes  in  contact  with. 
At  the  present  day  two  classifications  are  employed.  The  first, 
represented  by  Wundt1  and  many  followers,  is  based  upon  the 
fact  that  one's  mental  processes  may  vary  in  both  rapidity 
and  strength.  This  basis  yields  four  temperaments  which 
correspond  fairly  well  with  the  traditional  fourfold  division. 
The  rapid-strong  temperament  corresponds  to  the  choleric,  the 
rapid-weak  to  the  sanguine,  the  slow-strong  to  the  melancholic, 
and  the  slow-weak  to  the  phlegmatic.  On  the  other  hand, 
French  writers  for  the  most  part  adopt  a  qualitative  basis  —  that  is, 
classify  according  to  the  faculty  or  function  that  predominates. 
This  is  true  of  Ribot,2  Queyrat,3  Levy4  and  Fouillee.5  Perez, 
however,  retains  liveliness  and  intensity  as  the  basis.6  This  is 
not  the  place  to  discuss  the  general  topic  of  temperament,  nor  to 
go  into  the  merits  and  defects  of  these  two  plans  of  classifica- 


1  Grundzuge  der  Phys.  Psy.,  Leipzig,  1893,    II.,  Sigff.     See   also    Lotze  : 
Microcosmus,  Vol.   II.,  Bk  VI.,  Ch.   II.;   and  Ladd  :  Els.    Phys.  Psy.,  N.  Y., 
1897,  572ff. 

2  Psy.  of  the  Emotions,  London,  1897,  388ff. 
*  Les  Caracteres,  Paris,  1896,  36ff. 

*Psy.  du  Caractere,  Paris,  1896,  i82ff. 

6  Temperament  et  Caractere,  Paris,  1895,  2off. 

6  Le  Caractere,  Paris,  1892. 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  491 

tion.  It  is  sufficient  to  remark  that  a  practical  scheme  must 
provide  at  least  a  fairly  definite  mode  of  describing  any  and 
every  person  whose  individuality  is  sufficiently  marked  to  be 
noticeable  at  all. 

Wundt's  scheme  was  first  employed,  but  it  quickly  proved 
itself  inadequate  to  give  a  genuine  characterization  of  many 
distinctly  marked  individualities.  This  was  especially  true 
when  Wundt's  classes  were  interpreted  as  if  they  were  identical 
with  the  traditional  four  temperaments.  The  qualitative  plan 
was  next  tried ;  but,  while  it  supplemented  the  other,  it  proved 
inadequate  taken  by  itself.  In  the  interest  of  a  workable 
scheme,  therefore,  it  was  found  necessary  to  combine  the  two 
modes  of  division.  The  result  was  not  a  new  classification  of 
temperaments,  but  what  we  may  call  a  scheme  of  the  constitu- 
ents of  temperament.  The  mode  of  procedure  now  consisted, 
first,  of  judging  whether  sensibility,  intellect  or  will  was  the 
most  prominent  faculty ;  next,  of  finding  the  second  in  promi- 
nence ;  then  of  estimating  the  place  of  each  of  the  three 
faculties  in  respect  to  promptness  and  intensity.  For  each  sub- 
ject, in  the  end,  there  were  three  descriptive  designations,  as, 
for  example,  prompt-intense  intellect,  prompt-weak  sensibility, 
prompt-weak  will ;  and  these  three  were  arranged  in  the  order 
of  prominence. 

The  sources  of  evidence  for  temperament  were  the  same  as 
those  employed  by  the  writers  just  named,  namely,  permanent 
modes  of  action,  of  speech  and  of  point  of  view ;  permanent 
interests;  likes  and  dislikes;  habitual  social  interactions,  etc., 
whether  observed  and  recorded  by  the  subject  himself  or  by 
other  persons.  The  data  were  secured  by  the  following  meth- 
ods :  First,  by  inserting  in  the  question  list  a  number  of  ques- 
tions concerning  likes  and  dislikes,  laughter  and  weeping, 
anger  and  its  effects,  habits  of  introspection,  moods,  prompt- 
ness or  its  opposite  in  decisions,  ideals,  the  effects  of  excite- 
ment, habits  with  respect  to  physical  activity,  etc.  A  particu- 
larly fruitful  interrogation  was  the  following:  "If  you  were 
obliged  to  spend  a  whole  day  alone,  felt  at  perfect  liberty  to 
follow  your  inclinations  and  had  the  means  to  do  so,  what 
would  you  do?  "  At  no  point  in  the  questions  was  temperament 
or  disposition  mentioned. 


49 2  GEORGE  ALBERT   COE. 

The  second  method  was  by  observation  of  the  general  tone 
of  the  papers.  The  question  list,  it  may  be  remarked,  was 
very  lengthy.  It  included  approximately  200  specifications,  all 
planned  with  reference  to  the  evoking  of  memories  rather  than 
the  securing  of  categorical  replies.  Its  length  precludes  its 
presentation  here.  The  responses  were  correspondingly  ex- 
tended, and  not  the  least  remarkable  thing  about  them  was  the 
amount  of  information  they  imparted  between  the  lines.  It  was 
obvious  that  they  were  not  merely  a  record  of  phenomena,  but 
also  a  body  of  original  phenomena.  Sometimes  what  they 
purported  to  be  as  a  record  had  to  be  offset  by  what  they  were 
as  new  facts.  Thus,  in  response  to  the  question,  '  Do  your 
friendships  last?'  nearly  every  writer  gave  an  affirmative  an- 
swer. Here  it  is  probable  that  the  ideal  of  the  writers  rather 
than  their  actual  experience  comes  to  expression.  These  an- 
swers have  value,  therefore,  as  evidence  of  the  nature  of  the 
social  instinct,  but  hardly  as  evidence  of  actually  existing  social 
relations.  Occasionally  the  manner  of  responding  to  a  ques- 
tion revealed  more  than  did  the  content  of  the  response.  In- 
tellectual interest  stood  out  in  one,  strenuous  seriousness  or 
passionate  earnestness  in  another,  while  the  chattiness  of  a  third 
revealed  a  type  of  impressionability  strongly  contrasted  with 
both. 

A  third  method  was  by  objective  observation  and  interviews, 
as  already  described.  The  scheme  of  questions  underlying  this 
part  of  the  investigation  was  also  extended.  It  included,  among 
other  topics,  the  following :  The  habitual  state  of  the  muscles, 
particularly  the  face,  whether  tense  or  relaxed ;  one's  carriage 
and  motions,  whether  quick,  jerky,  irregular,  or  more  slow, 
free  and  pendulum-like ;  one's  mode  of  speech  and  the  quality 
of  the  voice ;  the  expression  of  the  eyes,  and  any  other  signs 
that  show  whether  the  subject  is  wide-awake  to  his  surround- 
ings;  whether  one  is  more  given  to  the  reception  of  impressions 
or  to  active  effort  to  control  surroundings  ;  readiness  to  laugh 
and  cry  ;  specific  manifestations  of  anger  ;  characteristic  moods  ; 
persistency ;  social  self-assertiveness  of  various  types ;  intel- 
lectual habits ;  religious  habits. 

The  data  obtained  by  all  these  methods  were  compared,  and 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  493 

thus  the  final  judgment  was  based  upon  a  really  wide  range  of 
facts.  Furthermore,  in  most  cases,  independent  judgments 
were  formed  by  different  observers,  and  these  judgments  were 
finally  checked  off  against  one  another.  As  soon  as  a  definite 
and  comprehensive  mode  of  procedure  was  discovered,  the  facts 
began  to  fall  into  place  with  the  sort  of  inevitableness  that  in- 
spires confidence  in  one's  method.  The  amount  of  agreement 
reached  by  observers  independently  of  one  another  was  another 
evidence  of  the  trustworthiness  of  the  method.  If  the  lack  of 
precision  and  of  quantitative  determinations  should  seem  to  im- 
pair the  value  of  the  results,  two  considerations  might  be  offered 
in  defence.  The  first,  is  that  all  the  knowledge  of  temperament 
possessed  by  biographers  and  historians  and  by  literary  work- 
ers, and  nearly  all  that  possessed  by  psychologists  themselves, 
has  been  gathered  by  methods  analogous  to  this,  though  rarely, 
if  ever,  by  methods  so  systematic  and  comprehensive.  The 
other  consideration  is  that  this  manner  of  learning  men  is  one 
of  the  bases  of  the  world's  successful  business.  Indeed,  a  large 
part  of  the  practical  interests  of  life  hang  upon  our  ability  so  to 
observe  temperamental  manifestations  as  to  be  able  to  predict 
the  general  quality  of  one's  reactions  in  different  sets  of  cir- 
cumstances. Of  course,  this  is  not  a  sphere  in  which  claims  to 
scientific  infallibility  become  even  plausible ;  nevertheless,  the 
thorough  and  systematic  analysis  employed  may  fairly  entitle 
the  results  to  some  degree  of  confidence. 

The  temperamental  classification  of  the  members  of  the  three 
groups  concerning  whom  adequate  information  was  obtainable 
yields  the  results  shown  in  the  table  on  the  next  page. 

The  most  marked  contrast  in  this  table  concerns  the  relation 
of  the  two  main  groups  to  intellect  and  sensibility.  Where  expec- 
tation is  satisfied,  there  sensibility  is  distinctly  predominant ;  but 
where  expectation  is  disappointed,  there  intellect  is  just  as  dis- 
tinctly predominant.  To  appreciate  the  strength  of  this  conclu- 
sion, it  will  be  well  to  remind  ourselves  once  more  of  the  range 
of  facts  upon  which  it  is  based.  In  only  three  cases  in  Group 
I.  and  one  case  in  Group  II.  was  it  necessary  to  rely  solely 
upon  the  subject's  paper.  A  second  interesting  result  is  that 
those  whose  expectation  is  satisfied  belong  almost  exclusively 


494 


GEORGE  ALBERT   COE. 


to  the  slow-intense  and  prompt-weak  varieties,  the  tempera- 
ments approaching  most  nearly  those  traditionally  known  as  the 
melancholic  and  the  sanguine.  On  the  other  hand,  those  whose 
expectation  is  disappointed  belong  more  largely  to  the  prompt- 
intense  variety,  or  the  choleric  temperament ;  though  the  distri- 
bution between  the  choleric,  melancholic  and  sanguine  is  not 

RELATION  OF  STRIKING  TRANSFORMATION  TO  TEMPERAMENT. 


Sensi- 
bility 
Predom- 
inant. 

Intellect 
Predom- 
inant. 

Will 
Predom- 
inant. 

Prompt- 
Intense. 

Slow- 
Intense. 

Prompt- 
Weak. 

Slow- 
Weak. 

GROUP  I.  —  17  per- 

s  o  n  s   who   e  x- 

pected   a    trans- 

formation   and 

experienced  it... 

12 

2 

3 

i 

6 

8 

2 

GROUP  II.  —  1  2  who 

expected  but  did 

not  experience... 

2 

9 

i 

7 

3 

2 

GROUP    III.  —  5 

others   who    be- 

long to  both  the 

above  classes  

2 

2 

I 

markedly  uneven.  Again,  comparing  the  two  main  groups 
with  respect  to  promptness  and  intensity,  each  by  itself,  we  find 
that,  on  the  whole,  Group  II.  exceeds  Group  I.  in  both  prompt- 
ness and  intensity.  Finally,  some  slight  confirmation  of  the 
representative  character  of  these  results  is  found  in  the  hetero- 
geneity of  the  cases  in  Group  III.  The  full  significance  of 
these  results  concerning  temperament,  however,  will  not  appear 
until  we  have  examined  the  same  subjects  with  respect  to  au- 
tomatisms and  suggestibility. 

Careful  inquiry  was  made,  both  in  the  question  list  and  by 
personal  cross-questioning,  for  evidence  of  mental  and  motor 
automatisms.  The  inquiry  divided  itself  into  these  heads : 
striking  dreams  in  connection  with  religious  awakenings ;  hal- 
lucinations in  connection  with  religious  transformations ;  hal- 
lucinations occurring  at  other  times ;  motor  automatisms  oc- 
curring at  the  time  of  religious  transformation,  and  similar 
automatisms  occurring  at  other  times.  The  purpose  of  the 
inquiry  did  not  make  it  necessary  to  render  these  various  classes 


DYNAMICS   OF  PERSONAL  RELIGION.  495 

rigorously  precise.  Accordingly,  when  it  was  difficult  to  de- 
cide whether  a  given  phenomenon  was  to  be  classed  as  a  dream 
or  as  a  hallucination,  I  followed  the  impression  of  the  subject. 
If  he  insisted  that  he  was  awake  at  the  time,  the  experience  was 
classed  as  a  hallucination.  Similarly,  the  group  of  motor 
automatisms  contains  some  cases  that  fall  near  the  boundary 
line.  But,  in  general,  it  is  believed  that  the  list  which  follows 
is  a  full  and  substantially  accurate  census.  It  contains  all  the 
facts  of  these  classes  discovered  in  the  entire  investigation. 
Striking  dreams  in  connection  with  religious  awakening: 

Dreamed  of  being  cast  into  hell.     Suffered  all  the  torments 
of  the  damned  that  he  had  ever  heard  about. 

Dreamed  of  being  cast  out  of  heaven. 

Dreamed  of  a  heavenly  procession  which  he  could  not  join. 

Dreamed  of  taking  an  examination  of  fitness  to  go  to  heaven. 
Hallucinations  in  connection  with  religious  transformation: 

Streaks  of  light  shone  down. 

A  somewhat  bright,  diffused  light  just  above  the  eyes ;  oc- 
curred twice. 

Seemed  to  observe  the  joy  in  heaven. 

Saw  a  vision  of  the  broad  way  and  of  the  narrow  way,  with 
many  persons  in  the  former  and  few  in  the  latter. 
Motor  automatisms  at  time  of  religious  transformation : 

Uncontrollable  laughter  for  fully  five  minutes. 

A  powerful  thrill  through  the  whole  body. 

Sudden  clapping    of  hands  before  any  change  of   feeling 
came. 

Tobacco  habit  broken  without  effort  or  even  seeking. 
Other  hallucinations : 

Saw  a  light  spring  up  from  a  tomb  in  a  cemetery. 

Used  to  hear  his  name  spoken  when  he  was  about  to  com- 
mit some  sin. 

Had  just  retired  after  private  devotion.     Saw  a  dim,  diffused 
light  above  the  eyes. 

Was  touched  by  an  absent  friend. 

Saw  a  dog  that  was  not  there. 

Heard  deceased  grandfather's  voice. 

Heard  mother's  voice  when  she  was  far  away. 


496  GEORGE  ALBERT  COE. 

Heard  the  voice  of  a  friend. 

Felt  the  presence  of  an  absent  friend.  It  seemed  to  be  an 
objective  fact  and  not  a  mere  impression. 

Heard  music  different  from  any  he  had  ever  listened  to. 

Heard  angels  sing. 

In  the  midst  of  a  public  speech  twice  saw  a  scene  he  was 
describing. 

Childhood  fear  of  the  dark  has  persisted.  The  feeling 
that  a  fiend  is  just  behind  and  ready  to  spring  upon  him  some- 
times becomes  so  intense  that  self-control  becomes  impossible. 

An  inner  voice  which  expresses  approval  at  times  of  per- 
plexity by  saying,  "  Fear  not,  I  am  with  you." 

God  tells  her  where  things  are  that  she  is  looking  for.  Also 
tells  her  things  before  they  come  to  pass. 

Voices  and  visions  just  before  sleeping  at  night.  Has  often 
gone  to  the  window  or  out  of  doors  to  see  where  the  music 
came  from. 

Up  to  age  of  thirteen  used  every  night  to  see  figures  in  the 
room. 

When  praying  had  a  vision  of  an  absent  friend  who  gave 
just  the  information  that  was  desired. 

Waked  one  night  and  saw  a  great  luminous  eye  in  the  ceil- 
ing :  thought  it  was  God's  eye. 
Other  motor  automatisms : 

Automatic  laughter. 

At  times  something  very  holy  seems  to  be  dictating  his 
thoughts. 

Has  always  felt  himself  under  two  influences  :  one  good  and 
one  bad,  and  neither  of  them  any  part  of  himself. 

Surprising  and  incomprehensible  outburst  of  defiance  to  God 
at  age  of  about  ten  or  twelve  years ;  shook  fist  at  the  sky  and 
told  God  he  hated  him. 

"The  Holy  Spirit  often  fills  me  so  that  I  feel  light,  and  it's 
no  trouble  to  walk  and  not  feel  tired."  (A  lady  well  advanced 
in  years.) 

Talking,  singing,  whistling  to  one's  self.  This  seems,  at 
times,  to  become  an  automatic,  sub-conscious  performance.  A 
parent  affected  in  the  same  way  sometimes  lets  out  secrets  by 
this  means. 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL  RELIGION.  497 

Let  us  now  ask  how  these  phenomena,  exclusive  of  the  dreams, 
are  distributed  among  the  different  sets  of  cases.  Of  eighteen 
persons  in  Group  I.,  eight  have  had  either  hallucinations  or 
motor  automatisms  ;  of  the  five  persons  in  Group  III.,  four  have 
had  similar  experiences.  Hence  of  twenty-three  persons  who 
have  had  a  striking  religious  transformation,  twelve  have  also 
exhibited  these  automatic  phenomena.  But  of  the  twelve  per- 
sons in  Group  II.,  who  sought  a  striking  religious  transformation 
in  vain,  only  one  has  had  either  a  hallucination  or  a  motor 
automatism. 

The  total  number  of  persons  examined  with  respect  to  autom- 
atisms was  seventy-four.  Of  these,  nineteen  had  exhibited 
such  phenomena;  but  twelve  of  these  nineteen  persons  are 
found  in  Groups  I.  and  III. — that  is,  one-sixth  of  the  entire 
number  of  persons  examined  embrace  two-thirds  of  the  cases  of 
automatisms.  Putting  these  results  in  the  form  of  percentages, 
we  get  the  following  : 

General  average  of  automatisms  for  74  persons,  25^  per  cent. 

Average  for  those  who  have    experienced    a 

striking  religious  transformation,        .  52  " 

Average  for  those  who  sought  such  a    transfor- 
mation in  vain,          .          .          .          .          .         8^        " 
In  other  words,  the  average  for  those  who  had  a  striking  relig- 
ious transformation  is  twice  as  high  as  the  general  average,  and 
six  times  as  high  as  the  average  for  those  who  sought  such  a 
transformation  in  vain. 

If  the  general  average  of  automatisms  seems  rather  exces- 
sive, the  following  explanatory  circumstances  should  be  borne 
in  mind  :  First,  motor  automatisms  are  included  along  with  hal- 
lucinations. Secondly,  nearly  all  the  persons  examined  were  too 
young  to  have  forgotten  such  experiences.  Thirdly,  the  cross- 
questioning  already  described  brought  out  a  number  of  facts 
not  elicted  by  the  questionnaire,  and  not  likely  to  be  elicited  by 
a  census  of  hallucinations  conducted  by  correspondence  alone. 
Finally,  it  now  becomes  obvious  that  the  high  general  average 
depends  upon  the  -presence  of  a  relatively  large  number  of  per- 
sons who  have  experienced  striking  religious  transformations. 
The  results  are  so  unequivocal  that  interpretation  is  unnec- 


498  GEORGE  ALBERT  COE. 

essary.  It  may  be  worth  while  to  add,  however,  that  in  two 
cases  of  motor  automatism  occurring  at  the  time  of  religious 
transformation  there  was  clear  evidence  of  a  congenital  tendency 
to  such  performances.  In  both  cases  a  parent  had  exhibited  a 
similar  automatism  under  similar  religious  conditions.  In  a 
third  case  it  was  possible  to  identify  a  phenomenon  as  probably 
automatic  through  a  similar  but  more  pronounced  phenomenon 
in  a  parent.  One  case  of  hallucination  was  likewise  clearly 
referable  to  congenital  tendencies.  Three  of  these  four  cases  of 
congenital  proclivity  belong  in  Group  I.  Furthermore,  to  Groups 
I.  and  III.  belong  nearly,  if  not  quite,  all  the  persons  who  have 
experienced  the  healing  of  disease  by  faith,  those  who  have 
received  remarkable  assurance  of  answered  prayer  in  advance 
of  the  event,  and  those  who  reported  other  veridical  premoni- 
tions. The  conclusion  is  that  the  mechanism  of  striking  relig- 
ious transformations  is  the  same  as  the  mechanism  of  our 
automatic  mental  processes. 

There  remains  for  study  the  relative  suggestibility  of  the 
three  groups.  At  first  thought,  this  seems  to  be  a  simple  prob- 
lem of  more  and  less.  But  it  is  neither  simple  nor  merely 
quantitative.  Indeed,  the  qualitative  varieties  of  suggestibility 
are  quite  as  marked  and  quite  as  important  as  the  '  suggestibil- 
ity and  non-suggestibility'  which  chiefly  figure  in  the  literature  of 
suggestion.  It  must  have  struck  many  experimenters  as  a  strange 
incident  that,  whereas  persons  of  sound  body  and  trained  mind 
make  excellent  subjects,  most  of  the  literature  represents  suggesti- 
bility as  identical  with  relative  prominence  of  the  lower  centers. 
The  fact  seems  to  be  that  some  persons  are  easily  hypnotized,  not 
because  the  higher  rational  centers  are  undeveloped,  but  pre- 
cisely because  the  high  development  of  these  centers, — the 
habit  of  prompt  concentration  of  voluntary  attention, — makes  it 
possible  to  follow  the  suggestions  of  the  operator  with  precision. 
Moll  remarks  that  the  ability  to  direct  one's  thoughts  in  any 
particular  direction  is  favorable  to  hypnosis,  but  that  this  ability 
is  usually  considered  to  be  a  sign  of  strength  of  will.1  As  the 
persons  under  examination  in  the  present  part  of  our  study  are, 
perhaps  without  exception,  healthy,  and  as  all  have  had  con- 

1  Hypnotism,  London,  1895,  40. 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  499 

siderable  mental  training,  it  will  be  seen  that  ready  response  to 
suggestion  cannot  be  regarded  as  an  unambiguous  sign.  The 
experimentation  was  begun  under  the  tentative  hypothesis  that 
auto-suggestion  might  possibly  account  in  part  for  the  failure 
of  persons  in  Group  II.  to  secure  the  desired  experiences.  The 
problem  then  became  whether  external  suggestion  was  more 
prominent  in  Group  I.  and  auto-suggestion  in  Group  II. 

The  problem  may  be  more  precisely  put  by  distinguishing 
between  passive  suggestibility  and  spontaneous  auto-suggestion. 
The  necessity  of  thus  stating  the  distinction  grows  out  of  the 
ease  of  misunderstanding  certain  phenomena,  particularly  those 
commonly  described  as  <  resisting  the  operator's  suggestion.' 
Thus,  if  a  subject  struggles  to  open  his  eyes  when  I  tell  him 
that  he  cannot  do  so,  this  is  no  evidence  of  spontaneity.  For 
the  very  assertion,  in  the  early  stages  of  hypnosis,  that  the  eyes 
cannot  open  is  a  challenge  to  try ;  it  is  a  double  suggestion. 
This  was  exquisitely  demonstrated  upon  one  of  my  subjects. 
For  some  time  I  had  tried  in  vain  to  close  the  eyes  by  making 
the  usual  passes  and  giving  the  usual  suggestions  of  drowsiness, 
etc.  At  last  the  subject,  who  was  apparently  wide  awake,  de- 
clared that  she  could  not  close  them  and  keep  them  closed. 
Catching  at  this  hint,  I  suddenly  remarked,  "  You  cannot  close 
them  !  "  They  immediately  clapped  shut  with  every  appearance 
of  doing  it  automatically.  In  another  case  in  which  the  usual 
suggestions  seemed  to  have  little  or  no  effect,  the  subject  was 
instructed  to  keep  his  eyes  closed  voluntarily  for  a  while ;  but 
his  eyes  opened  very  soon,  and  did  so  repeatedly.  He  finally 
declared  that  it  seemed  as  if  he  could  not  keep  them  closed.  In 
two  other  cases  it  was  found  that  a  previously  formed  conviction 
on  the  part  of  the  subjects  that  they  were  suggestible  had  tended 
to  make  them  appear  more  passive  than  they  really  were. 

What  was  looked  for,  then,  was  evidence  of  spontaneity  or 
originality,  rather  than  mere  readiness  of  response  or  its  opposite. 
An  illustration  or  two  will  make  this  clear.  To  one  subject  I 
declared  that  his  outstretched  arm  was  rigid  and  could  not  move. 
The  arm  immediately  stiffened  out,  but  began  a  series  of  incipi- 
ent up-and-down  motions.  This  was  clearly  a  product  of  my 
own  suggestion,  as  were  also,  perhaps,  the  sympathetic  writh- 


500  GEORGE  ALBERT   COE. 

ings  of  the  body  and  contortions  of  the  face.  The  cataleptic 
arm  was  the  right  one.  Presently  the  left  arm  was  raised  and 
began  to  push  down  on  the  right  one,  evidently  in  an  effort  to 
lower  it.  Failing  in  the  effort,  the  left  arm  itself  now  became 
cataleptic,  and  could  not  lower  itself.  Here  the  evidence  of 
spontaneous  auto-suggestion  is  unmistakable.  Contrast  this, 
now,  with  another  case  in  which  a  suggestion  was  given  that 
an  arm  was  cataleptic.  Certain  incipient  responses  to  the  chal- 
lenge were  made  as  before ;  but  they  ceased  in  a  few  seconds, 
while  the  face  and  the  rest  of  the  body  expressed  little  or  no 
interest  in  what  was  going  on. 

Let  us  compare  two  other  cases  that  are  less  striking,  and 
yet  unambiguous.  In  both,  passes  in  front  of  the  eyes  and 
suggestions  of  heavy  eyelids,  etc.,  meet  with  very  slow  response, 
so  slow  that  I  finally  close  the  lids  with  my  fingers.  If,  now,  I 
say  "  Your  eyes  are  closed  tight;  you  cannot  open  them,"  both 
subjects  open  their  eyes.  Similarly,  they  can  unclasp  their 
hands,  and  the  like,  whenever  they  are  challenged  to  try.  Thus 
far  the  two  cases  correspond  point  for  point.  But  if,  after 
closing  the  eyes,  I  leave  the  subjects  alone,  avoiding,  as  far  as 
possible,  the  giving  of  further  suggestions,  a  decided  difference 
presently  appears.  One  of  the  subjects  sits  with  closed  eyes  for 
an  indefinite  length  of  time — that  is,  shows  no  initiative  ;  but  the 
other,  as  often  as  the  experiment  is  repeated,  spontaneously 
opens  his  eyes  after  a  short  interval. 

Such  experimentation  resulted  in  separating  the  cases  ac- 
cording to  two  fairly  well-marked  types.  In  respect  to  readi- 
ness of  response  to  hypnotic  suggestion  the  two  types  do  not 
seriously  differ.  Under  both  types  fall  cases  in  which  the  re- 
sponse was  almost  immediate,  and  also  cases  in  which  it  was 
very  slow.  But  the  behavior  under  suggestion  was  decidedly 
different.  Let  us  call  the  two  types  the  passive  and  the  spon- 
taneous. Under  the  former  belong  those  who  take  no  decided 
or  original  part  in  the  experiment.  Their  response  to  external 
suggestion  may  not  be  very  pronounced,  but  they  initiate  noth- 
ing after  once  they  have  begun  to  yield.  Under  the  spontane- 
ous type  belong,  on  the  other  hand,  the  few  who  appear  to  be 
non-suggestible  and  those  who,  while  responding  to  suggestion, 


DYNAMICS   OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  501 

take  a  more  or  less  original  part  by  adding  to  the  experiment  or 
by  waking  themselves  up. 

Comparing  Groups  I.,  II.  and  III.  with  respect  to  this  point, 
we  find  certain  plain  differentiations.  To  begin  with,  as  might 
be  expected,  nearly  all  the  persons  who  have  experienced  any 
of  the  mental  or  motor  automatisms  already  described  are  '  pas- 
sives.' Thirteen  such  persons  were  experimented  upon,  arid,  of 
these,  ten  clearly  belonged  to  the  passive  type.  This  fact  makes 
it  appear  that  the  two  types  here  described  are  substantially 
parallel  with  those  sifted  out  by  certain  experiments  at  Harvard 
University.1 

A  few  cases  were  not  accessible  for  purposes  of  experiment. 
The  numbers  experimented  upon  in  the  two  groups  were  respec- 
tively 14  and  12.  All  the  persons  in  Group  III.  were  experi- 
mented upon.  The  results  are  as  follows  :  In  general,  the  line 
between  Groups  I.  and  II.  coincides  with  that  between  the  pas- 
sive and  the  spontaneous  types,  though  apparent  exceptions 
exist,  and  though  the  interpretation  of  the  facts  is  not  equally 
clear  in  all  cases.  Of  the  14  cases  in  Group  I.  (persons  who 
expected  a  striking  transformation  and  experienced  it),  13  are 
of  the  passive  type.  Of  the  12  persons  in  Group  II.  (expecta- 
tion disappointed)  9  clearly  belong  to  the  spontaneous  type,  i 
is  entirely  passive  and  2  are  open  to  some  doubt.  Of  the  5 
persons  in  Group  III.  (striking  experience,  yet  disappointed),  2 
are  passive  and  3  spontaneous. 

The  nature  of  the  evidence  may  be  further  illustrated  and 
the  conclusion  still  further  strengthened  by  reference  to  the 
negative  and  doubtful  cases.  The  one  case  in  Group  I.  that  is 
not  clearly  passive  is  the  one  first  mentioned  on  a  preceding 
page  in  illustration  of  the  double  character  of  many  verbal  sug- 
gestions. This  case  is  probably  a  passive  one,  therefore ; 
though  not  so  counted  in  the  above  figures.  Another  member 
of  this  group  seemed  for  some  time  to  be  an  exception  to  the 
general  rule.  She  had  had  three  striking  experiences,  and  yet 
was  apparently  not  suggestible.  One  day,  however,  mention 
having  been  made  in  the  class  in  psychology  of  pain  induced 
in  a  tooth  by  imagining  a  dental  operation,  she  soon  felt  a  tooth- 

1  Cultivated  Motor  Automatism,  by  Gertrude  Stein,  PSY.  REV.,  V.,  2951*. 


502  GEORGE  ALBERT   COE. 

ache.  It  became  intense  and  lasted  for  three  or  four  hours,  the 
face  meantime  becoming  sore  and  apparently  swollen.  This 
settled  the  question  of  passive  suggestibility.  Turning,  now,  to 
the  negative  and  doubtful  cases  in  Group  II.,  we  find  that  the 
one  clearly  negative  case  is  one  that  stands  on  the  border  be- 
tween Groups  I.  and  II.  This  subject  had  more  difficulty  in 
classifying  himself  than  any  other  one  in  either  group.  Again, 
of  the  two  cases  scheduled  as  doubtful,  one  is  the  only  case  in 
this  entire  group  in  which  any  form  of  mental  or  motor  automa- 
tism was  discovered.  Nevertheless,  the  case  remains  ambigu- 
ous ;  for,  though  external  suggestions  are  accepted  with  every 
sign  of  passivity,  the  subject  has  heretofore  practised  auto-sug- 
gestion, even  to  the  extent  of  curing  toothache  and  other  minor 
pains  thereby.  His  present  passivity,  therefore,  may  be  partly 
or  wholly  due  to  training.  By  way  of  parenthesis  it  may  be 
remarked  that  each  subject  was  questioned  as  to  whether  he  had 
ever  been  hypnotized  or  had  ever  witnessed  hypnotic  experi- 
ments, and  his  reactions  were  judged  according  to  his  replies. 

The  correlation  between  one's  religious  experience  and  one's 
type  of  suggestibility  was  sometimes  found  to  be  curiously  com- 
plete. Here,  for  example,  is  a  subject  whose  response  to  passes 
and  suggestions  of  drowsiness  is  not  prompt;  yet  when  the  re- 
sponse comes  it  simply  plumps  itself.  The  subject  is  now  very 
passive.  In  response  to  a  suggestion,  an  arm  quickly  becomes 
cataleptic ;  but,  in  the  midst  of  the  experiment,  something  hav- 
ing incidentally  appealed  to  the  subject's  interest,  he  sponta- 
neously opens  his  eyes  and  appears  to  be  completely  out  of  the 
hypnosis.  This  man  was  converted  at  the  age  of  sixteen,  with 
marked  manifestations.  His  whole  being  was  thrilled  with  joy, 
and  he  had  what  he  regarded  as  the  witness  of  the  Spirit.  But 
from  seventeen  to  nineteen  he  endured  terrible  storm  and  stress, 
in  which  he  sought  in  vain  to  recover  his  original  status.  He 
finally  settled  down  to  the  conviction  that  we  are  children  of 
God  in  our  deeds  and  thoughts  rather  than  in  our  particular 
moods  and  feelings. 

A  still  more  remarkable  parallel  is  as  follows :  Response 
very  prompt;  lids  clapped  shut  and  trembled.  At  the  sugges- 
tion that  they  could  not  open,  they  quickly  opened.  The  re- 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL   RELIGION.  503 

mark  was  then  made  that  perhaps  the  lids  would  not  close  so 
promptly  next  time.  The  suggestion  worked,  for  now  it  required 
many  passes  to  shut  the  eyes.  The  arm  refused  to  become  cata- 
leptic ;  but  when  I  began  to  breathe  deeply  and  slowly,  as  if 
asleep,  the  subject's  head  promptly  began  to  fall  forward ;  and 
it  continued  downward  until  it  rested  on  the  breast.  The  sub- 
ject was  now  apparently  in  a  deep  sleep ;  but  after  awhile  a 
spontaneous  awakening  occurred.  He  was  re-hypnotized  and 
told  that  he  could  not  pronounce  his  name ;  a  gentle  struggle 
ensued  and  lasted  for  a  considerable  time,  but  the  effort  was  not 
given  up  until  the  name  was  successfully  pronounced.  The 
characteristics  here  are  initial  passivity  followed  after  a  while 
by  decided  spontaneity.  This  exactly  describes  the  subject's 
religious  experiences  also.  On  two  different  occasions,  after 
earnestly  seeking  for  a  marked  experience,  he  happened  to  notice 
some  incidental  thing  in  his  environment  that  he  took  to  be  a 
divine  token.  Immediately  he  experienced  great  exaltation ; 
his  heart's  desire  seemed  to  be  realized ;  but  after  a  few  days 
the  emotion  waned,  and  reaction  setting  in  pronounced  a  severe 
verdict  upon  the  whole  performance. 

In  order  to  appreciate  the  weight  of  these  results  concern- 
ing the  relation  of  suggestibility  to  religious  transformations,  it 
will  be  necessary  to  notice  once  more  the  principle  upon  which 
cases  were  classed  in  Group  II.  This  group  contains  no  case 
in  which  there  was  not  a  distinct  effort  to  obtain  an  experience 
that  never  came.  Now,  of  the  74  persons  examined,  there  are 
many  whose  training  and  environment  were  equally  adapted  to 
induce  expectation  and  seeking,  but  did  not  do  so.  It  is  there- 
fore probable  that  spontaneous  auto-suggestion  prevented  expec- 
tation in  some  as  it  prevented  the  fulfillment  of  expectation  in 
others.  Hence,  the  sphere  in  which  it  plays  a  decisive  role  is 
undoubtedly  much  larger  than  the  numerical  proportions  seem 
to  indicate. 

Moreover,  no  statistical  display  can  do  justice  to  facts  of  this 
sort.  For  not  only  must  the  numbers  express  in  some  degree 
one's  interpretation  of  facts,  and  not  merely  the  bare  facts  them- 
selves, but  the  qualities  with  which  we  are  dealing  are  too  pro- 
found and  pervasive  to  be  expressed  in  any  simple  formula. 


504  GEORGE   ALBERT   COE. 

The  whole  style  of  one's  mental  organization  is  involved.  It  is 
safe  to  say  that  any  observer  of  human  nature  would  perceive 
the  propriety  of  setting  off  Groups  I.  and  II.  from  each  other. 
The  personalities  in  each  group  taken  by  itself  are  relatively 
alike,  while  the  two  groups  are  clearly  different  from  each 
other.  Psychology  merely  renders  this  obvious  difference  more 
precise  by  saying  that  the  difference  is  one  of  temperament  and 
of  a  more  or  less  spontaneous  attitude  toward  environment. 

It  has  been  shown  that  three  sets  of  factors  favor  the  attain- 
ment of  a  striking  religious  transformation — the  temperament 
factor,  the  factor  of  expectation,  and  the  tendency  to  automa- 
tisms and  passive  suggestibility*.  Let  us,  in  conclusion,  note  the 
effect  of  combining  these  three  factors.  Of  10  cases  in  which 
there  is  expectation  of  a  marked  transformation,  together  with 
predominance  of  sensibility  and  passive  suggestibility,  the  num- 
ber whose  expectation  was  satisfied  was  9;  but  of  n  cases  of 
such  expectation,  together  with  predominance  of  intellect  or  of 
will,  and  with  spontaneous  auto-suggestion,  not  one  was  satis- 
fied. These  numbers  include  cases  from  Group  III.  as  well  as 
from  Groups  I.  and  II. 

If  our  groups  seem  to  contain  rather  few  cases,  it  should  be 
remembered  that  a  problem  of  this  kind  requires  relatively  com- 
plete knowledge  of  a  few  cases  rather  than  an  item  or  two  of 
knowledge  regarding  many  cases.  Our  procedure  must  neces- 
sarily consist  in  a  gradual  narrowing  down  of  the  range  of 
cases,  together  with  increasing  minuteness  of  scrutiny  in  each 
case.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  we  have  approached  about  as  closely 
to  the  strict  method  of  experiment  as  the  subject  permits.  The 
factors  are  so  definitely  identified  that  prediction  becomes  safe 
wherever  either  of  the  two  combinations  just  mentioned  is  found 
present.  Given  three  factors,  the  fourth — the  general  character 
of  one's  religious  experiences — can  be  predicted  with  a  high 
degree  of  probability. 

It  is  supposed  by  many  that  striking  transformations  in  the 
affective  life  are  reserved  for  those  who  have  been  great  sin- 
ners. The  idea  seems  to  be  that  an  abrupt  transition  from  moral 
badness  to  moral  goodness  naturally  carries  great  emotional 
disturbances  with  it.  And  doubtless  such  circumstances  do  tend 


DYNAMICS    OF  PERSONAL  RELIGION.  505 

to  intensify  whatever  happens.  But  it  does  not  at  all  appear 
that  these  circumstances  are  the  chief  factors  that  determine  the 
degree  of  affective  transformation  at  conversion  ;  for  among  the 
cases  belonging  to  Groups  I.  and  III.  there  is  only  a  meagre 
sprinkling  of  persons  who  had  ever  been  bad  in  anv  very  positive 
sense.  In  fact,  of  the  entire  23  persons,  only  5^report  having 
experienced  any  sorrow  for  specific  sins,  and  even  Mien  the  sin 
repented  of  was  generally  a  bad  temper  or  some  similar  in- 
firmity. On  the  other  hand,  of  13  persons  in  Group  II.,  all  of 
whom  sought  a  striking  transformation  in  vain,  3  also  report 
sorrow  for  specific  sins. 

In  short,  everything  goes  to  show  that  the  chief  ^circumstances 
favorable  to  these  striking  experiences  are  expectation,  abun- 
dance of  feeling  and  passive  suggestibility  with  its  tendency  to 
automatisms.  Shall  we  therefore  conclude  that  conversion  is 
practically  an  automatic  performance?  By  no  means.  What 
has  been  proved  is  simply  that  when  conversion  or  an  equiva- 
lent change  takes  place  in  one's  moral  attitude  toward  life  and 
destiny  and  God,  it  may  clothe  itself  in  certain  emotional  habili- 
ments provided  certain  factors  are  present,  but  otherwise  not. 

"  Would  you  cast  the  horoscope  of  a  human  life?"  says  Fouil- 
lee.  "  It  is  not  to  be  read  in  the  constellations  of  the  sky,  but 
in  the  actions  and  reactions  of  the  interior  astronomical  system — 
do  not  study  the  conjunction  of  the  stars,  but  those  of  the 
organs."1  Similarly,  we  may  now  add  :  Would  you  understand 
the  emotional  aspects  of  religious  experiences?  Do  not  as- 
cribe them  to  the  inscrutable  ways  of  God,  but  to  ascertainable 
differences  in  men's  mental  constitutions ;  do  not  theorize  about 
divine  grace,  but  study  the  hidden  workings  of  the  human 
mind ! 

1  Temperament  et  Caractere,  Paris,  1895,  88. 


SHORTER  CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 
ATTRIBUTES  OF   SENSATION.1 

I  have  the  temerity  to  propose  an  attack  upon  the  anomalous  and, 
as  I  think,  indefensible  position  of  the  so-called  attributes  of  sensation  : 
quality,  intensity,  extent  and  duration.  Entrenched  as  it  is  behind 
traditional  opinion,  I  hold  that  the  entire  conception  of  attributes  of 
sensation  is  untenable,  and  this  for  two  main  reasons :  first,  because 
sensation  is  an  elemental  fact  of  consciousness  and  as  such,  by  defini- 
tion, irreducible:  second,  because  each  so-called  attribute  may  be 
shown  to  be  either  itself  an  element  of  consciousness  or  a  complex  of 
such  elements. 

I. 

Of  these  two,  the  more  general  argument  should  first  be  con- 
sidered. By  common  consent  of  the  psychologists  who  treat  of  con- 
sciousness from  the  analytic  standpoint,  sensations  are  unanalyzable 
elements.  Thus  Wundt2  defines  Empjindungen  as  "  Zustande  unseres 
Bewusstseins  welche  sich  nicht  in  einfachere  Bestandtheile  zerlegen 
lassen" ;  Ladd3  says  definitely  that  '  simple  sensations  '  are  "  processes 
of  our  sense-experience  which  we  are  unable  in  any  way  to  regard  as 
composite  or  as  analyzable  into  still  more  nearly  ultimate  factors"; 
Kiilpe*  coordinates  sensations  with  affections  as  "letzen  Elemente 
*  *  einer  genauen  Analyse"  ;  James5  observes  that l '  sensation,  so  long 
as  we  take  the  analytic  point  of  view,  differs  from  perception  only  in 
the  extreme  simplicity  of  its  object  or  content,"  and  Titchener  calls 
sensations  '  elemental  conscious  processes  '6  and  defines  conscious  ele- 
ments as  "  mental  processes  which  cannot  be  further  analyzed,  which 
are  absolutely  simple  in  nature  and  which  consequently  cannot  be  re- 
duced even  in  part  to  other  processes."7 

1  Read  at  the  New  York  meeting  of  the  American  Psychological  Association, 
December,  1898. 

2 Physiologische  Psychologie,  4te  Aufl.,  I.,  281. 

3  Psychology  Descriptive  and  Explanatory,  p.  92. 

4  Grundriss  der  Psychologic,  §3,  Hi. 

6  Principles  of  Psychology,  V.  II.,  p.  i. 
•  Outline  of  Psychology,  §7. 
7O/.  ciV.,  §4,  p.  13. 

506 


ATTRIBUTES   OF  SENSATION.  507 

Our  next  question  concerns  the  nature  of  this  analysis  and  its  re- 
sults. 'Element  of  consciousness'  may  mean  the  simplest  concrete 
experience,  the  least  complex  content  of  actual  consciousness ;  or  it 
may  mean  the  simplest  distinguishable,  though  inseparable,  ingredient 
of  a  given  experience — a  result  of  abstraction,  an  unanalyzable  datum 
of  consciousness.  It  can  be  shown  that  this  second  more  rigid  sense 
is  that  in  which  the  word  is  used  by  those  who  treat  psychology  ana- 
lytically. Thus  Ladd  is  at  pains  to  say  that  a  "  simple  sensation  is  a 
convenient  abstraction  of  psychological  science1  and  definitely  states 
that  "  such  elements  are  never  to  be  regarded  as  actually  separable  by 
analysis  either  from  each  other  or  from  the  state  in  which  they  are2 
said  to  exist.  *  *  *  No  psychologist  *  *  *  thinks  of  maintaining  the 
separate  reality  of  the  factors  of  mental  life."  Wundt's  assertion  is  as 
unequivocal:3  u  Isolirt  ist  uns  die  einfache  Empfmdung  niemals  ge- 
geben,  sondern  sie  ist  die  Resultat  einer  Abstraction."  Similarly,  Kiilpe 
says  distinctly:4  "Die  seelischen  Elementarphanomene  [sind]  stets 
in  irgend  welcher  Verschmelzung  oder  Verkniipfung  mit  anderen 
wahrnehmbar.  *  *  *  Ein  wirkliches  Erleben  nur  einer  einzigen  Emp- 
findung  kommt  nicht  vor."  And  with  equal  decision,  Titchener5 
asserts  that  "the  particular  sensation,  regarded  apart  from  other  sen- 
sations is  the  product  of  scientific  analysis,  an  abstraction  of  actual 
mental  experience." 

By  common  admission,  therefore,  the  sensation,  so  far  as  it  is  ana- 
lytically treated  as  an  element  of  consciousness,  is  not  a  concrete  ex- 
perience at  all,  but  a  result  of  abstraction,  useful  for  purposes  of  close 
observation  and  of  scientific  classification.  It  is  certainly,  then,  an 
apparent  contradiction  to  speak  of  the  element  as  having  attributes,  in 
the  ordinary  meaning  of  attribute,  which  is  just  '  quality '  or  4  char- 
acteristic/ The  element  is  precisely  that  which  cannot  be  further 
reduced,  characterized  or  qualified.  Therefore,  only  the  complex 
phenomenon  has  attributes,  and  these  turn  out  to  be  precisely  the  ele- 
ments of  which  it  is  composed. 

This  objection  to  the  ordinary  doctrine  of  attributes  has  been 
generally  overlooked.  Kiilpe,  to  be  sure,  says  briefly:6  "Spite  of 
the  qualitative  simplicity*  of  the  sensation,  different  attributes  dis- 
close themselves,"  and  Schumann 7  in  a  recent  contribution,  '  Zur 
Psychologie  der  Zeitanschauung,'  observes  that  it  is  not  securely  set- 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  92.  «  Op.  cit.,  §3, 115. 

2/Z>.,  p.  89.  6  Op.  cit.,  §43. 

3  Op.  cit.,  L,  281.  6  Op  cit.,  §4,  Hi. 

7  Zeitsch.f.  Phys.  und  Psychol,  der  Sinnesorgane,  XVII.,  I,  p.  112. 


5o8       SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND   DISCUSSIONS. 

tied  (sicker festgestellt)  "how  we  come  to  distinguish  the  attributes 
of  intensity,  quality  and  temporal  duration  in  the  inseparable  unity 
(untrennbarer  Einheit)  of  an  auditory  sensation ;  "  but  these  are  cases 
in  which  the  contradiction  is  calmly  faced  and  accepted.  Titchener 
proposes  the  following  solution  of  the  problem  :  "Although  the  sen- 
sation," he  says,1  "is  an  element  of  mind — /.  £.,  a  process  which  can- 
not be  split  up  into  simpler  processes — yet  it  has  various  aspects  or  at- 
tributes— presents  different  sides,  so  to  speak — each  of  which  may  be 
separately  examined  by  the  psychologist."  But  the  attribute,  thus  de- 
fined, cannot  be  distinguished  from  the  element  by  the  fact  that  it 
is  presented  to  a  psychologist  and  examined  by  him,  for  the  same  holds 
as  true  of  the  sensation  itself  as  of  any  attribute.  And  the  question 
at  issue  is  precisely  this :  If  the  process  really  cannot  be  split  up  into 
simpler  processes,  how  does  it  happen  to  have  more  than  one  «  side  ' 
or  '  aspect '  ? 

In  the  essay  from  whose  earlier  pages  we  have  already  quoted, 
Schumann  seems  to  suggest2  another  explanation  of  the  difficulty. 
He  observes  that  the  sensation,  spite  of  its  oneness  (trotz  ihrer 
durchaus  einheitlichen  Natur'},  can  call  up  distinct  judgments  of 
intensity,  quality,  extent  and  duration.  But  in  insisting  upon  the  irre- 
ducibleness  of  the  sensation  and  in  finding  the  diversity  of  the  attri- 
butes in  the  judgments  about  sensation,  he  is  as  untrue  to  introspection 
as  to  traditional  theory,  for  a  sensation  deprived  of  all  its  attributes 
will  itself  vanish.  As  Kiilpe  has  it,  "  Die  Empfindung  ist  nichts  aus- 
ser  ihren  Eigenschaften.  Es  bleibt  kein  Rest  *  *  *."  One  may,  of 
course,  make  judgments  about  quality,  intensity  and  extent ;  but  all 
judgments  are  based,  in  their  last  analysis,  on  immediate  conscious- 
ness, and  the  attributes,  in  order  to  be  judged  about  at  all,  must  first 
be  immediately  experienced.3 

The  only  detailed  justification,  which  I  know,  of  the  theory 
of  attributes,  is  contained  in  a  discriminating  paper,  from  which  I 
quote  at  length,  by  Dr.  Ellen  Talbot,  on  '  The  Doctrine  of  Conscious 
Elements.'4  "  We  have  said,"  Miss  Talbot  remarks,  "  that  when  we 
have  resolved  our  mental  facts  into  facts  which  are  themselves  irre- 
solvable, our  process  of  analysis  is  finished.  This  is  true ;  yet  it  would 
not  be  correct  to  say  that  there  is  no  further  occasion  for  analysis. 
There  is  need  of  a  second  process  for  the  purpose  of  determining  the 

^Op.cit.,  §8,  p.  29. 

2  Op.  tit.,  p.  131. 

3  Op.  cit.,  §4,  Hi. 

4  Philosophical  Review,  IV.,  p.  162. 


ATTRIBUTES   OF  SENSATION.  509 

properties  of  our  elements  *  *  *  its  various  attributes,  such  as  in- 
tensity and  quality.  But  this  does  not  shake  our  faith  in  the  validity 
of  our  general  criterion  of  ultimates,  for  this  second  analysis  is  in  no 
sense  a  continuation  of  the  first  process.  *  *  *  In  the  first  analysis,  we 
passed  successfully  from  one  process  to  another,  finding  in  each  new 
stage  the  explanation  of  the  more  complex  one  which  preceded  it. 
When  we  have  at  length  reached  a  process  which  we  cannot  explain 
by  any  other  process,  our  regress  is  finished,  our  element  is  discovered. 
Whatever  analysis  may  now  be  possible  will  be  entirely  distinct  from 
the  first  and  will  in  no  way  affect  its  claim  to  be  distinct." 

The  argument  is  ingenious,  but  misleading.  Even  if  one  grant 
Miss  Talbot's  contention  that  sensations,  on  the  one  hand,  and  qualities 
or  intensities,  on  the  other,  are  reached  by  different  processes  of  an- 
alysis, it  still  remains  true  that  the  results  of  that  second  analysis  may 
justly  claim  the  title  of  i  element'  rather  than  that  of  4  attribute.'  But 
the  entire  hypothesis  of  a  second  analysis  shows  itself,  on  closer  scru- 
tiny, to  be  baseless.  It  is  probably  derived  from  the  false  analogy 
with  an  atom  or  with  a  chemical  element,  which,  while  physically  and 
chemically  unanalyzable,  is  obviously  characterized  by  psychic  attri- 
butes, such  as  weight  and  form,  and  color  or  odor.  But  just  as  a 
chemical  element  is  not  further  decomposable  and  reducible  to  chem- 
ical attributes,  so  it  is  logically  impossible  that  a  psychic  element 
should  lend  itself  to  further  psychological  analysis. 

Introspection  bears  out  this  a  priori  conclusion.  The  analysis 
whose  results  are  admitted  to  be  elements  of  consciousness — that  is,  the 
discrimination  within  a  complex  percept  of  distinct  sensations  and  affec- 
tions— does  not  differ  noticeably  from  the  analytic  study  of  its  hues,  in- 
tensities and  forms,  which,  according  to  Miss  Talbot,  is  a  second  sort 
of  analysis.  But  if  this  4  second  analysis'  into  attributes  is  indeed  a 
mere  continuation  of  the  first,  into  sensations,  then  these  sensations 
can  no  longer  claim  to  be  unanalyzable  elements  of  consciousness. 
The  only  escape  from  this  position  would  be  by  a  return  to  the  re- 
jected theory  that  c  element'  means,  not  an  undistinguishable  abstrac- 
tion, but  the  simplest  fact  of  real  experience.  In  this  case,  however, 
as  has  been  suggested,  analysis  has  already  gone  too  far,  for  even  the 
combination  of  quality,  intensity  and  extent  which  makes  up  a  sensa- 
tion, on  the  ordinary  view,  is  an  artificial  abstract  and  not  the  simplest 
of  concrete  mental  experiences.  If  elements  are  to  be  defined,  on  this 
principle,  as  the  simplest  factors  of  actual  experience,  then  they  can 
include  nothing  more  remote  from  reality  than  ideas  or  images  and 
emotions. 


510       SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

In  truth,  one  cannot  have  it  both  ways :  either  the  sensation  has 
attributes,  but  then  it  is  a  complex,  no  element  and  has  lost  its  excuse 
for  psychological  being ;  or  the  sensation  is  an  irreducible  and  unan- 
alyzable  element,  but  then  its  simplicity  is  absolute,  not  to  be  trifled 
with,  and  not  to  be  explained  away  by  reference  to  any  second  process 
of  analysis  into  elements,  which  yet  are  not  elements,  but  only  l  at- 
tributes,' 4  aspects  '  or  something  equally  vague  and  meaningless. 

II. 

The  conclusion  that  an  element  of  consciousness  cannot  possess 
attributes  leaves  untouched  the  question  of  the  nature  of  the  so-called 
attributes.  For,  however  misleading  the  colors  under  which  they 
sail,  quality,  intensity,  extent  and  duration  are  nevertheless  genuine 
factors  of  our  experience.  If  the  traditional  classification  is  rejected, 
some  other  must  be  suggested  in  its  place. 

At  the  outset,  duration  must  be  sharply  distinguished  from  its  fel- 
low-'attributes.'  When  it  is  said  that  sensations  have  quality,  inten- 
sity and — in  some  cases — extent,  the  meaning  is,  that  to  have  the  sen- 
sation at  all  one  must  be  immediately  conscious  of  quality,  intensity 
and  sometimes  of  extent.  But  we  are  not  by  any  means  always  con- 
scious of  the  duration  of  a  given  sensation ;  on  the  other  hand,  we  are 
notoriously  oblivious  of  the  passage  of  time  in  much  of  our  sense  ex- 
perience. And  yet  always,  whether  we  are  conscious  of  it  or  not,  the 
sensation  has  duration — that  is,  "it  lasts  a  certain  time."1  Duration 
is  not,  therefore,  an  attribute,  like  the  rest,  by  virtue  of  being  a  con- 
stituent of  sensation,  but  is,  as  it  were  a  reflective  attribute,  what 
Schumann  calls  a  ''Beurtheilung  der  Dauer' 2  Moreover,  duration, 
even  in  this  sense,  is  not  a  purely  psychic  attribute,  but  belongs  to 
physical  as  well  as  to  conscious  facts,  and  is  in  truth  the  characteristic 
of  all  serial  phenomena.  Of  course,  duration,  besides  being  later 
predicated  of  an  event  of  consciousness,  may  itself  also  be  immediately 
experienced ;  and  indeed  such  direct  acquaintance  is  the  basis  of  the 
later  prediction.  But  duration  is,  in  this  case,  distinctly  a  complex 
experience.  Hoffding3  has  analyzed  it  very  acutely  into  the  factors 
of  *  change'  and  of  fc  connection.'  Certainly  it  lacks  the  simplicity  of 
the  attribute. 

irntchener,  op.  cit.,  §  8,  p.  30. 

*Op.  cit.,  p.  131.  Schumann,  curiously  enough,  treats  all  the  attributes  as 
judgments  called  forth  by  the  '  einheitliche  Empfindungen,'  ignoring  the  imme- 
diateness  of  our  experience  of  them. 

3Eng.  Tr.  Outlines  of  Psychology,  pp.  184-186. 


ATTRIBUTES   OF  SENSATION.  511 

Even  the  most  ardent  advocate  of  the  traditional  theory  should, 
therefore,  reject  *  duration '  as  an  attribute  of  conscious  elements,  for 
either  it  is  an  unpsychological  attribute  of  phenomena  in  general,  re- 
flectively *  added '  to  the  sensation,  or  else  it  is  a  complex  psychic  con- 
tent. i  Quality,'  ' intensity '  and  'extent'  must  be  differently  treated. 
They  are  '  attributes  '  by  virtue  of  being  psychic  contents,  and  if  we 
refuse  them  the  name  we  must  fit  them  into  some  other  appropriate 
corner  of  our  psychological  scheme. 

The  case  of  quality  may  be  most  readily  considered,  for  already 
the  universal  habit  of  classifying  sensations  according  to  quality1  and 
the  admission  by  most  psychologists  that  quality  is  the  most  impor- 
tant element  have  correctly  suggested  that  quality  is  itself  sensation. 
Titchener  goes  further.  Besides  reproducing  Kiilpe's  description 2  of 
quality  as  the  l  core  or  kernel  of  sensation ' 3  to  which  the  other  attri- 
butes are  referred  as  the  duration,  intensity  and  extent  of  a  quality; 
and,  not  content  with  calling  quality  the  '  most  important  and  funda- 
mental ' 3  and  the  '  absolute ' 4  attribute,  Titchener  says  definitely  :8  "It 
is  quality  which  makes  sensation  an  elemental  conscious  process." 
More  than  this,  in  his  paragraph  on  the  *  total  number  of  elementary 
sensations,'5  he  states  distinctly  that  each  of  these  40,000  qualities  is  a 
conscious  element,  distinct  from  all  the  rest  and  altogether  simple  and 
unanalyzable.  This  reduction  of  quality  to  sensation-element  accords 
with  the  plain  results  of  introspection.  Such  'qualities'  as  'this 
blue,'  '  this  pitch,'  '  this  warmness,'  are  surely  distinguishable  factors 
of  consciousness,  though  they  are,  of  course,  inseparable  from  certain 
intensities  and — in  the  case,  at  least,  of  the  color  and  the  warmness — 
from  certain  extents.  But  if  distinguishable,  since  they  are  also  irre- 
ducible, they  are  by  definition  elements  of  consciousness. 

Nothing  forbids  a  similar  treatment  of  intensities  as  sensation  ele- 
ments ;  but  such  a  theory  lacks  even  the  virtual  sanction  of  the  author- 
ities, and  must,  therefore,  be  more  carefully  considered.  It  appeals, 
in  the  first  instance,  to  ordinary  self-observation.  Does  not  introspec- 
tion clearly  reveal  that  complex,  sensational  experiences  differ  in  in- 
tensity as  truly  as  they  differ  in  quality  ?  A  very  soft  sound  of  a  given 
pitch  is  as  distinctly  '  different,'  though  differently  different,  from  a 
loud  tone  of  the  same  pitch,  as  two  tones  of  the  same  intensity  but  of 
discordant  pitch.  In  the  same  way  highly  salted  food  differs  unequiv- 
ocally from  that  which  is  only  slightly  salted ;  '  brightness '  as  well  as 

*Ladd,  Elements  of  Psychol.,  356;  Baldwin,  Senses  and  Intellect,  85. 
*0p.  «V.,§4,  2.  */*.,  p.  77. 

3  Oj>.  «VM  p.  31.  6O/  «V.,  §  22,  p.  67. 


512        SHORTER   CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

•'  blueness '  is  a  direct,  distinguishable  element  in  a  visual  sense  experi- 
ence ;  and  the  loudness  as  well  as  the  high  C  quality  is  a  noticeable 
constituent  of  the  auditory  content.  Of  course,  the  blueness  is  more 
definitely  named,  more  practically  important  and  perhaps  more  affect- 
ively toned,  yet  it  is  not  more  undeniably  present,  as  a  distinguishable 
part  of  the  experience. 

To  those  who  already  virtually  admit  that  '  quality '  is  itself  sensa- 
tion, an  additional  introspective  argument  will  be  found  in  the  relation 
of  intensity  to  quality  in  the  visual  series  of  greys.  For  here,  as  is 
generally  admitted,  intensity  and  quality  coincide ;  a  grey  of  lessened 
intensity  is  a  grey  of  a  different  shade.  This  seems  to  show  so  close 
a  relation  between  the  two  that  the  one  may  surely  be  treated  as  sen- 
sational element,  if  the  other  is. 

Three  objections  to  this  doctrine  must  be  seriously  considered. 
The  first  lays  stress  upon  the  relative  nature  of  intensity.  "  We  esti- 
mate intensity,"  Titchener  says,1  u  always  by  comparison  with  other 
intensities.  Our  use  of  terms  indicates  this.  c  Blue '  means  something 
fixed  and  absolute,  but  <  large '  is  altogether  relative  and  comparative." 
This  distinction,  which  must  certainly  be  admitted,  does  not,  however, 
invalidate  the  claim  of  intensity  to  be  regarded  as  an  element  of  con- 
sciousness. It  is  a  fact  that  we  have  few  names  for  intensities,  partly 
because  there  are  so  many  of  them  shading  almost  imperceptibly  into 
each  other,  and  partly  because  only  the  greater  differences  of  intensity 
are  of  practical  concern  to  us  through  their  connection  with  our  emo- 
tional experience  or  through  their  harmful  effect  on  our  bodies.  But  if 
the  possession  of  a  name  were  the  essential  distinction  of  the  '  quality  ' 
from  the  4  intensity/  then  odors  for  the  most  part  could  no  longer  be 
classed  as  qualities,  since  they  notably  belong  to  the  group  of  the 
unnamed.  The  relativity  of  intensities,  though  admitted  in  this  sense, 
does  not,  therefore,  debar  them  from  coordination  with  the  qualities, 
among  the  conscious  elements. 

It  may  be  urged,  in  the  second  place,  that  intensity  is  too  general  a 
characteristic  to  be  classed  as  sense  element ;  that  variations  in  degree 
are  common  to  colors,  sounds,  odors — indeed,  to  all  sensations;  and 
that  so  common  an  attribute  cannot  itself  be  a  sensational  element  of 
consciousness.  Now,  granting  the  assertion  that  intensity  is  a  pecu- 
liarly '  general '  sort  of  conscious  content,  this  means  only  that  one 
and  the  same  sort  of  intensity  accompanies  all  sorts  of  conscious  ele- 

1  Of.  cit.,  §  26,  pp.  77-78.  This  argument  and  those  which  follow  are  offered 
by  their  author  as  proofs  of  the  relative  importance  of  quality,  compared  with 
the  other  «  attributes.' 


ATTRIBUTES   OF  SENSATION.  513 

ments,  and  this  hypothesis  is  not  inconsistent  with  the  teaching  that 
intensity  is  a  psychic  element.  This  possibility  need  not,  however,  be 
discussed,  for  introspection  does  not  bear  out  the  observation  on  which 
it  rests.  Color  intensities  are  not  the  same  sorts  of  intensity  as  sound- 
intensities.  Parallel  with  the  difference  between  color  and  pitch,  there 
is  a  difference  between  brightness *  and  loudness.  So  there  is  a  differ- 
ence between  hardness — a  pressure  intensity — and  the  marked  degree 
of  a  given  sweetness.  Intensities  are  really,  therefore,  as  individual  as 
qualities. 

The  last  and  most  weighty  argument  remains.  To  quote  again  from 
Titchener,  no  distinct  "bodily  process  in  a  definite  bodily  end-organ 
is  connected  with  a  sensation-intensity,  since  one  and  the  same  kind 
of  bodily  process  may  *  *  *  be  more  or  less  well-marked  (in- 
tensity of  sensation)  in  different  instances."  Now  to  those  who  believe, 
with  the  writer,  that  observed  distinctness  is  the  ultimate  criterion  of 
psychological  analysis,  and  that  the  discovery  of  assignable  physio- 
logical differences  may  strengthen  and  supplement,  but  never  contra- 
dict, the  result  of  psychological  analysis,  this  argument  cannot  be  final, 
even  if  one  admit  what  it  implies,  that  there  are  no  characteristic 
physiologic  accompaniments  of  intensity.  Such  admission,  however, 
is  unnecessary ;  nor  need  we  take  refuge,  to  save  our  theory,  in 
the  unverified  hypothesis,  that  contents  which  differ  in  intensity  are 
conditioned  by  the  excitation  of  different  cortical  layers.  In  truth,  the 
physiological  correlate  of  intensity  is  as  readily  assigned  as  the  physical 
stimulus :  amplitude  of  atmosphere  or  of  ether-wave.  Just  as  differ- 
ences in  the  locality  of  nervous  excitation  correspond  with  differences 
in  sense-quality,  so  differences  in  the  degree  of  physiological  excita- 
tion may  correspond  with  differences  in  psychical  intensity.  Such  dis- 
tinctions of  physiological  intensity  cannot,  it  is  true,  be  connected  with 
definite  conscious  states  after  the  manner  in  which  '  sense  centers ' — 
that  is,  quality  centers — have  been  localized,  but  undeniably  they  exist 
and  may  be  regarded  as  the  physiological  correlates  of  psychical  in- 
tensities. 

Thus  the  objections  to  the  sensation-character  of  intensity  lose  their 
force,  either  because  they  involve  unessential  criteria  of  sensation  or 
through  contradiction  of  the  results  of  introspection.  Intensities, 
therefore,  like  qualities — loudnesses  and  brightnesses,  like  hues  and 
pitches — take  their  places  among  the  distinguishable  elements  of 
consciousness. 

By  almost  precisely  parallel  arguments  it  might  be  shown  that  ex- 

*In  the  sense  'color-intensity  ' ;  not  in  Titchener's  sense  '  grey.' 


5H        SHORTER   CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

tensity,  if  regarded  from  a  nativistic  point  of  view,  is  itself  an  element  of 
consciousness,  whereas,  to  the  empiricist,  it  is  a  complex  of  sensational 
elements,  chiefly  motor.  In  either  case  there  is  nothing  gained  by 
naming  it  4  attribute '  of  sensation.  For  if  abstract  irreducibleness  and 
distinctness  be  seriously  maintained  as  the  sole  criteria  of  the  psychic 
element,  analytic  psychology  has  no  place  and  no  use  for  the  '  attri- 
bute '  of  sensation. 

MARY  WHITON  CALKINS. 
WELLESLEY  COLLEGE. 

IS  THE   MEMORY  OF  ABSOLUTE   PITCH  CAPABLE  OF 
DEVELOPMENT    BY   TRAINING  ? 

The  experiments  the  results  of  which  I  am  going  to  report  here 
were  made  in  Berlin  during  the  time  from  March  to  October,  1895, 
jointly  by  Dr.  Victor  Heyf elder  and  myself.  I  did  not  publish  them 
earlier,  because  I  expected  to  make  a  complete  investigation  into 
the  memory  of  absolute  pitch.  After  having  given  up  this  intention  I 
shall  describe  those  experiments  separately. 

The  theoretically  important  question  is :  whether  human  beings 
are  to  be  divided  into  two  classes,  one  of  them  enjoying  a  memory  of 
absolute  pitch,  the  other  wanting  it,  or  whether  there  is  but  a  gradual 
difference  in  memory  of  absolute  pitch,  some  people  needing  more, 
some  less  practice  to  obtain  an  equal  facility. 

Should  the  former  be  true,  we  would  have  to  assume  that  the  first 
class  possesses  a  physiological  property,  the  lack  of  which  prevents 
the  others  from  acquiring  that  mental  faculty.  But  it  would  be  very 
difficult  to  say  what  kind  of  physiological  property  it  might  be. 

In  favor  of  the  latter  is  the  fact  that  everyone  has  a  certain  amount, 
however  small,  of  memory  of  absolute  pitch,  being  able  to  recognize 
and  discriminate,  e.  g.,  the  sounds  of  a  violin  and  a  bassviol  merely 
through  the  pitch. 

Kries1  indeed  will  not  grant  that  this  already  may  be  called  a 
memory  of  absolute  pitch.  But  I  do  not  see  any  reason  for  refusing 
this  name  in  any  case  where  the  individual  is  unable  to  determine  the 
pitch  with  an  average  error  less  than  a  certain  interval,  viz.,  a  third. 
That  there  is  no  such  reason  is  proved  by  our  experiments,  which 
show  that  individuals  with  not  more  memory  of  absolute  pitch  than 
above  described  by  systematical  and  sufficiently  lasting  practice  may 
be  trained  to  meet  the  conditions  of  Kries.  It  may  be  mentioned 

1  Zeitschrift  fur  Psychologic  und  Physiologic  der  Sinnesorgane,  Vol.  3, 
p.  257-279. 


DEVELOPMENT  BY  TRAINING. 


5 '-5 


that  the  possibility  of  such  training  by  Kries  and  many  others  has 
been  denied. 

We  used  for  our  experiments  tuning  forks  as  well  as  a  piano.  In 
both  cases  we  named  the  pitches  not  by  their  musical  names,  but  by  their 
vibration  rates,  a  table  of  which  we  had  lying  before  us.  We  began 
with  few  pitches  and  from  time  to  time  added  some  new  ones,  as  is  to 
be  seen  in  the  tables.  Each  tone  was  repeated  as  often  as  wished. 

On  the  piano  we  began  with  10  pitches  at  intervals  of  a  sixth. 
When  the  number  of  different  pitches  reached  20,  the  intervals  were 
major  thirds ;  when  39,  whole  tones. 

TONE  PRODUCED  BY  TUNING  FORKS;  MARCH  TO  MAY,   1895. 


HEYFELDER. 

MEYER. 

Correct  Judgments  %. 

83 

78 

70 

56 

75 

71 

67 

59 

Number  of  Judgments. 

136 

365 

457 

91 

137 

364 

460 

92 

f                       100 

* 

V 

21 

| 

¥ 

V 

1 

122 

V 

V 

M 

y 

¥ 

V 

I 

ISO 

0 

o 

fir 

0 

0 

\3 

7 

188 

V 

V 

ff 

¥ 

V 

V 

1 

V, 

220 

0 

o 

-3JL 

0 

0 

V 

^ 

5 

300 

¥ 

V 

1^4 

4 

1 

¥ 

H 

pd 

400 

0 

ft 

ff 

1 

' 

0 

H 

C  " 

480 

V 

V 

V 

i 

f 

V 

O 

680 

0 

V 

I 

| 

0 

f  T 

V8 

CS 

800 

0 

o 

0 

i 

0 

0 

o 

,0 

960 

¥ 

V 

TT 

< 

I 

1! 

if 

f& 

j 

^ 

I2OO 

0 

0 

5-4- 

^ 

r 

0 

0 

f  ^ 

I6OO 
2400 

f 

1! 

if 

- 

. 
i 

$ 

t! 

fj 

1 

3200 

0 

0 

0 

1 

f 

0 

0 

0 

', 

4000 

V 

¥ 

V8 

V 

¥ 

V 

\ 

The  fractions  give  the  relation  of  right  to  wrong  cases. 


TONE  PRODUCED  ON  THE  PIANO;  JUNE  TO  OCTOBER,   1895. 


Number  of 

HEYFELDER. 

MEYER. 

different 
pitches. 

Number  of 

Correct 

Number  of 

Correct 

judgments. 

judgments  %. 

judgments. 

judgments  #. 

10 

69 

8l 

69 

86 

12 

46 

72 

46 

85 

^ 

t 

70 

75 

f 
69 

65 
61 

18 

92 

74 

92 

66 

20 

368 

73 

368 

59 

39 

736 

64 

736 

60 

SHORTER    CONTRIBUTIONS  AND  DISCUSSIONS. 

Even  when  we  had  the  choice  of  39  pitches,  more  than  one-half  of 
our  judgments  were  correct,  and  errors  surpassing  the  neighboring 
pitch  on  either  side  were  quite  rare. 

We  did  not  continue  those  experiments  further,  because  the  value 
of  the  acquired  facility  did  not  seem  to  us  to  correspond  to  the  expense 
of  time.  Now,  after  several  years  have  passed  we  have  lost  the  greater 
part  of  what  we  had  acquired,  by  the  want  of  continued  practice. 

MAX  MEYER. 
CLARK  UNIVERSITY. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

Instinct  and  Reason,  an  Essay  concerning  the  Relation  of  Instinct 
to  Reason,  with  some  special  Study  of  the  Nature  of  Religion. 
HENRY  RUTGERS  MARSHALL.  New  York  and  London,  Macmil- 
lans.  Pp.  vii  +  574.  $3.50. 

This  work  presents  a  most  ingenious  and  interesting  hypothesis, 
the  fruit  of  fifteen  years  of  special  study  and  reflection,  as  to  the  rela- 
tions and  relative  biological  values  of  these  two  groups  of  mental  proc- 
esses. The  work  possesses  a  thorough-going  quality,  born  of  patience 
and  sincerity,  found  only  in  works  produced  in  a  similar  manner.  Its 
first  object  was  to  present  the  conception  of  religion  which  it  contains ; 
but  to  this  end  it  was  necessary  to  treat  of  both  instinct  and  reason,  and 
the  discussion  of  religion  assumes  a  subsidiary  place. 

The  method  of  the  work  is  '  objective.'  Like  the  investigations 
which  resulted  in  the  law  of  evolution,  the  method  here  subordinates 
the  inner  to  the  outer,  the  psychic  to  the  organic,  and  construes  all 
mental  processes,  even  religion,  in  biological  terms.  The  work  accord- 
ingly does  not  concern  itself  with  questions  of  origin.  The  law  of 
evolution  does  not  touch  the  question  of  origins,  and  is  not  a  law  of 
progress  except  for  those  whose  desires  and  impulses  lead  them  so  to 
construe  it.  The  empirical  relations  of  instinct  and  reason,  together 
with  their  biological  significance  and  value,  are  here  in  question ;  and 
these  problems  are  to  be  studied  by  construing  wide  objective  groups 
of  human  and  animal  activities  in  the  light  of  the  biological  doctrine 
of  evolution.  We  are  studying  throughout  the  work  what  may  or 
must  be  conceived,  rather  than  what  is — a  task  which,  in  all  scientific 
procedure,  goes  before  the  work  of  verifying  and  establishing,  and 
shades  imperceptibly  into  it.  The  work  presents  something  more  than 
an  unusually  suggestive  working  hypothesis. 

The  book  is  divided  into  five  parts  treating  of  introductory  concep- 
tions, instinct,  impulse,  reason  and  certain  relations  between  instinct 
and  reason,  respectively.  First,  as  to  method.  While  our  point  of 
view  is  similar  to  that  which  an  utter  stranger  to  our  planet  might  be 
conceived  to  assume  in  order  to  arrive  at  some  intelligible  account  of 
human  and  animal  conduct — a  purely  objective  point  of  view ;  never- 
theless we  are  not  far  from  the  mental  series  at  any  time.  The  doc- 

517 


5*8  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

trines  that  mind  acts  on  body,  that  body  -acts  on  mind,  that  both  are 
aspects  of  one  fact  (epiphenomenon  theory),  and  that  the  two  series  of 
events  are  simply  parallel,  are  passed  in  review  and  criticized.  Psychic 
states  constitute  part  of  the  conditions  of  processes  in  the  motor  centers 
of  the  cortex,  and  we  are  forced  to  one  or  other  of  two  conclusions — 
either  the  psychic  effect  alters  the  sum-total  of  physical  energy  in  the 
brain  (which  cannot  be  accepted),  or  there  is  something  psychic  in  all 
causation.  Our  brain  processes,  moreover,  constitute  a  group  of 
mental  states  within  that  larger  group  called  objects  of  the  outside 
world,  and  it  is  between  this  small  group  within  a  group  of  mental 
phenomena  and  the  remainder  of  the  content  of  consciousness  that  the 
causal-interaction-theory  asserts  a  causal  relation.  But  this  strange 
hypothesis  is  not  necessary :  another — that  of  parallelism — is  equally 
tenable  and  serves  our  purpose  well.  This  theory  assumes  a  psychic 
somewhat,  which  the  author  calls  '  mentality,'  coincident  with  each 
neural  activity  within  us.  Where  neural  structures  organize  into  a 
system,  and  neural  activities  become  continuous,  mentality  likewise 
organizes  into  a  system  and  becomes  self-conscious.  The  psychic 
phenomena  of  double  consciousness,  hypnotism,  amnesia,  and  hysteria 
are  coincident  with  disintegrated  neural  systems.  The  Ego  of  psy- 
chology is  ' an  unanalyzable  whole,  and  part  of  consciousness':  "the 
ego  and  the  field  of  inattention,  therefore,  would  seem  to  be  one  and 
the  same  thing,  the  differences  in  the  application  of  the  terms  being 
determined  by  differences  in  the  point  of  view."  Neural  systems 
organized  under  one  preeminent  system  constitute  the  brain,  and  under 
certain  conditions  may  be  functionally  separated  from  their  connection 
with  the  preeminent  system.  The  destruction  of  '  association  fibers;  ' 
the  bearing  of  neuro-psychological  rhythm,  as  developed  differently  in 
different  systems  and  at  different  times,  upon  the  phenomena  of  normal 
and  disunited  consciousness ;  and  the  differences  between  this  view  and 
the  old  '  mind-stuff  theory,'  are  discussed  in  some  detail.  The  discussion 
of  parallelism  closes  with  a  few  brief  but  interesting  metaphysical 
suggestions  in  the  form  of  questions.  The  entire  chapter,  although  of 
course  not  absolutely  new,  is  vigorous  and  courageous. 

The  last  discussion  of  Part  I.  takes  up  general  definitions  of  in- 
stinct, habit  and  reason.  "  Instincts  are  forces  *  *  *  which  appear 
in  us  because  we  are  organisms ;  *  *  *  which  are  more  or  less  thor- 
oughly coordinated  "  (p.  68) .  They  have  been  acquired  by  the  race 
"  because  in  the  long  run  they  have  been,  as  they  in  general  still  are, 
valuable  to  life  under  the  conditions  which  normally  arouse  them." 
(p.  7°)-  Habits  may  be  called  pseudo-instincts  which  have  been 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  519 

learned,  not  inherited,  by  the  individual.  Reason,  on  the  other  hand, 
is  "  that  which  leads  us  to  adapt  ourselves  to  new  conditions,  to  guide 
and  change  the  actions  which  are  determined  by  instinct,  and  is  what 
we  may  call  the  verdant  factor  in  psychic  life"  (p.  70).  Reason 
covers  intelligence — "we  act  intelligently  when  we  would  override 
and  vary  the  actions  to  which  we  are  led  by  our  organic  instinct "  (p. 
80). 

Part.  II.,  Concerning  Instinct.  Instinctive  actions  are  not  dependent 
in  any  degree  upon  our  appreciation  of  the  advantages  they  bring  us ; 
and  we  are  here  not  concerned  with  the  question  as  to  how  they  orig- 
inated. In  any  cell- aggregate  two  influences  will  always  be  opera- 
tive in  the  determination  of  conduct :  first,  "  the  elemental  variant  in- 
fluence which  would  lead  any  cell  to  act  for  itself  alone,"  and  second, 
"  the  modifying  influence  from  the  aggregate  of  which  the  stimulated 
cell  is  an  element."  In  the  higher  forms  of  organic  life,  those  activi- 
ties which  are  determined  by  the  influence  of  the  aggregate  are  in- 
stinctive, while  those  which  are  determined  by  the  elemental  variant 
influence  are  reason  (p.  109  ff.).  All  congenital  series  of  actions  deter- 
mined by  the  constitution  of  the  organism,  and  subserving  definite 
biological  ends,  must  be  classed  together  as  instincts  (p.  87)  ;  and  the 
presence  of  some  biological  end  subserved  by  the  instinctive  activity 
is  the  all-important  thing.  Determination  by  organization,  definite- 
ness  of  reaction,  should  not  for  a  moment  be  made  a  differentia  of  in- 
stinct (as  by  Professor  Morgan)  (p.  90).  Fixity  of  reaction  is  only 
an  ideal  seldom  reached,  but  the  biological  end  is  fixed,  and  this  is  the 
objective  mark  of  instinct.  The  subjective  mark  of  instinct  is  the  ab- 
sence of  any  influence  from  the  conception  of  the  biological  end.  Not 
the  particular  act,  but  the  trend  of  many  is  the  truly  instinctive  thing; 
the  former  varies,  the  latter  is  constant.  Impulse  is  a  plain  state  due 
to  the  inhibition  of  instinct-actions,  to  the  failure  to  carry  out  distinct 
images  of  motor  activities.  Impulse  should  always  have  a  subjective 
significance  in  psychology. 

The  term  instinct  applies,  also,  to  the  activities  of  parts  of  organ- 
isms, where  these  are  in  unison  with  the  activities  of  the  entire  organ- 
ism and  occur  in  response  to  regularly  recurring  stimuli,  as,  e.  g".,  the 
activities  of  the  heart,  lungs,  etc.  All  the  instinctive  activities  are  au- 
tomatic, and  their  psychic  concomitants  merely  form  part  of  the  unan- 
alyzable  psychic  mass  called  the  Ego.  Fundamental  in  organisms  are 
the  instinct-actions  toward  advantageous  stimuli,  and  away  from  dis- 
advantageous stimuli.  Instincts  are  classified  into  three  groups :  those 
tending  to  the  preservation  of  the  individual,  those  tending  to  the  pres- 


520  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

ervation  of  the  race  (sexual  instincts),  and  those  tending  to  the  preser- 
vation of  social  groups  to  be  found  among  many  species  of  animals. 

First,  those  tending  to  preserve  the  individual.  Owing  to  the  uni- 
form dependence  of  organisms  on  their  environment,  certain  instinct 
actions  are  universal,  and  receive  definite  names.  The  corresponding 
instinct-feelings  are  emotions  such  as  joy,  sorrow,  dread  and  relief 
(p.  113).  Corresponding  to  instinct-movements  toward  objects  and 
other  organisms,  love  appears  subjectively  ;  corresponding  to  move- 
ments away,  anger  and  fear  ;  to  the  instinctive  functional  adjustments  of 
the  sense  organs  to  objects,  surprise.  Another  group  of  instinct-actions 
is  Professor  Baldwin's  '  self-exhibiting  reactions  '  ;  but  this  group  is  so 
rare,  irregular  and  weak  that  the  corresponding  instinct-feelings  fail  to 
be  realized.  Marshall  does  not  favor  the  '  back-stroke  '  theory  of  the 
emotions  ;  he  assimilates  emotional  expression  and  emotion  to  the  cate- 
gories of  '  instinct-action'  and  '  instinct-feeling.'  Differences  of  mus- 
cular reactions  in  expression  do  not  make  the  differences  in  emotional 
states  which  the  back-stroke  theory  would  lead  us  to  expect.  The 
emotion  is  the  psychic  coincident  of  the  total  reaction  of  the  neural 
system  concerned  at  the  moment  of  emotional  expression.  In  general, 
all  individualistic  instincts  must  be  subordinated  to  those  which  relate 
to  the  persistence  of  the  species  to  which  the  organism  belongs,  just 
as  the  reactions  of  the  elementary  cells  for  their  own  benefit  get  sub- 
ordinated to  reactions  for  the  good  of  the  organism  as  a  whole. 

Instincts  relating  to  the  preservation  of  the  species  are  the  second 
group  considered  :  these  are  the  instincts  pertaining  to  reproduction. 
Here  come  up  for  consideration  such  topics  as  sexual  pursuit,  self-ex- 
hibiting reactions  that  attract,  mating,  the  protection  of  mother  and 
young,  and  instincts  of  the  '  deferred  type.'  The  forms  in  which  these 
groups  appear  in  the  higher  organic  life  of  man  are  discussed  at  some 
length.  Individual  variant  instincts  may  become  rational  ends,  as 
when  a  student  or  professional  man  suppresses  the  reproductive  in- 
stincts in  the  effort  to  secure  personal  ease,  or  freedom  from  the  cares 
of  ordinary  family  life.  "  Evidently,  we  see  here  very  clearly  the  re- 
lation of  intelligence,  of  the  reasoning  process,  to  elemental  variance  " 


The  third  group  consists  of  instincts  relating  to  the  persistence  of 
social  groups.  Here  the  different  forms  of  cooperative  conduct,  such 
as  attacks  made  in  combination  by  ants,  wolves  and  men,  herding 
for  facility  in  finding  food,  herding  for  defence  and  offence.  In  man 
we  see  forgetfulness  of  self,  family,  etc.,  in  times  of  war;  monogamy; 
personal  loss  suffered  rather  than  commit  murder  ;  hunger  rather  than 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  521 

theft ;  benevolence  and  art  instincts  tending  to  the  advantage  of  the 
race  rather  than  to  that  of  the  individual.  In  all  this  the  individual's 
advantage  is  either  indirect  or  entirely  absent.  Here,  intelligence  and 
reason  interfere  only  in  the  interests  of  unpatriotic  tendencies,  viola- 
tion of  the  marriage  relations,  etc.  Ethical  impulses  are  instinct  feel- 
ings which  have  no  individualistic  significance.  The  inhibition  of 
impulses  to  kill  enemies  and  to  commit  adultery  is  due  to  instinct — 
violators  are  simply  atavistic.  Sympathy  and  pity,  philanthropy  and 
art  are  here  discussed.  But  in  this  higher  sphere,  Nature's  problem 
becomes  complex ;  the  same  sets  of  circumstances  can  seldom  recur ; 
consequently  only  certain  trends  of  action  persist ;  but  thought  of  the 
trend  of  instinctive  action  destroys  the  force  of  the  impulse.  Indi- 
vidualistic instincts  reassert  themselves  in  killing,  licentiousness  and 
theft,  and  in  all  of  this  the  effects  of  reasoning  are  most  marked.  But 
there  is  a  possible  serious  hesitancy,  a  sincere  doubt,  solved  by  ra- 
tional argument. 

Apart  from  these  groups  of  instincts,  those  which  have  to  do  with 
the  relations  of  other  instincts,  such  as  imitation  and  play,  are  men- 
tioned. Imitation  belongs  to  a  complex  instinctive  type,  and  is  not 
identifiable  with  the  '  circular  process '  which  Professor  Baldwin 
would  have  us  call  imitation. 

Throughout  this  discussion,  the  assumption  has  been  determinant 
that  the  race  instincts  develop  out  of  and  upon  the  individualistic  in- 
stincts, and  that  the  social  instincts  develop  out  of  and  upon  the  other 
two  groups.  The  subordination  of  the  first  group  to  the  second  and  of 
both  to  the  third  is  a  necessity  of  the  race  and  a  universal  fact.  Hence 
the  conception  of  a  hierarchy  of  instinct-efficiencies  established  and 
preserved  by  Nature  by  the  method  of  natural  selection. 

But  how  is  this  hierarchy  to  be  established  and  preserved  in  the 
individual  ?  Granting  that  those  in  whom  it  does  not  appear  tend  to 
disappear  from  society,  it  is  more  conceivable  that  all  should  disappear 
than  that  such  a  hierarchy  should  spring  up  by  chance.  Can  the 
social  organism  be  t»aid  to  exert  the  necessary  control  over  the  indi- 
vidual ?  Chapter  VII.  is  devoted  to  the  task  of  showing  that  society, 
although  organic,  is  analogous  merely  to  those  low  forms  of  organic 
life  which  grow  by  accretion  of  like  elements  and  which  exert  but 
little  influence,  as  organisms,  upon  the  individual  elements.  It  is  a 
matter  of  indifference  whether  we  compare  society  to  psychological 
or  to  physiological  organisms :  the  two  correspond,  or  rather  the  one 
is  dependent  upon  the  other  (p.  183)— e.  statement  which  does  not  seem 
perfectly  consistent  with  the  picture  given  on  page  34  of  the  relation 


522  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

of  one  series  to  the  other.  Why  are  societies  analogous  to  low  rather 
than  to  high  forms  of  organic  life  ?  The  reasons  given  in  the  work 
do  not  seem  at  all  adequate.  For  example,  among  others,  the  point 
is  made  that  in  the  higher  organisms  the  life  of  the  parts  (the  heart, 
e.  ^*.)  depends  upon  the  life  of  the  whole,  while  in  society  individuals 
live  on  whether  the  social  organization  lives  or  not.  Now  it  seems 
as  though  the  judicial  or  legislative  functionaries  of  society  would  be 
more  analogous  to  the  heart  than  is  the  individual  citizen.  It  is  a 
question  whether  the  absolute  separation  from  each  other  of  the  in- 
dividuals composing  society  would  not  involve  their  death  as  social 
units  just  as  truly  as  the  separation  of  the  cells  composing  an  organism 
involves  their  death  as  cells.  It  seems  like  bad  logic  when  the  author 
reasons  from  this  fancied  analogy  to  the  conclusion  that  there  is  little 
likelihood  that  the  race  will  ever  attain  to  high  social  organization ; 
and  again,  when  he  reasons  that  if  there  were  such  a  thing  as  a  social 
consciousness,  the  individual  could  no  more  know  it  than  a  sensation 
can  appreciate  our  higher  life  of  reflection.  This  chapter's  significance 
for  the  argument  is  its  rejection  of  the  thought  that  social  suggestion 
and  control  preserve  the  hierarchy  of  instinctive  efficiencies  which 
the  theory  demands. 

In  the  next  chapter,  the  eighth,  the  tendency  to  variation  in  social 
aggregates  is  represented  as  excessive.  Under  the  special  stress  of  un- 
usually strong  stimulation,  and  wherever  the  restraints  due  to  social 
instincts  are  removed  or  weakened,  the  individual  tends  to  act  as  an 
individual.  Reasoned  processes  are  the  latest  and  highest  develop- 
ments of  this  variant  principle;  but  ratiocination  is  not  an  important 
determinant  in  the  struggle  for  existence  (p.  204).  Racial  and  social 
instincts  can  be  accounted  for  on  the  hypothesis  that  the  result  on  the 
whole  is  better  individual  adaptation  for  existence  in  an  environment. 
But  we  cannot  help  recalling  attention  to  this  point,  for  natural  selec- 
tion does  not  seem  self -consistent  here.  What  was,  to  start  with,  a 
struggle  of  the  individual  with  his  individual  environment  seems  to 
be  unconsciously  understood,  when  the  argument  demands  it,  as  a 
struggle  of  the  individual  with  the  environment  of  the  social  group. 
The  discussion,  not  being  concerned  with  origins,  does  not  tell  us  why 
the  individual  stops  struggling  with  that  part  of  his  environment  con- 
stituted by  the  remainder  of  his  social  group,  or,  in  other  words,  how 
he  comes  to  identify  himself  with  the  social  group  to  such  an  extent 
as  to  fail  to  discriminate  between  the  two  environments.  Professor 
Huxley  maintained  that  an  egoistic  struggle  for  existence  could  never 
become  so  intense  or  far-sighted  as  to  develop  into  an  altruistic  sacrifice 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  523 

of  self :  the  survival  of  the  fittest  is  a  law  of  individual  survival,  and 
we  do  not  know  that  any  one  has  shown  how  it  can  become  a  law  of 
the  survival  of  social  groups.  In  the  sphere  of  psychological,  ethical 
and  social  evolution,  the  law  of  natural  selection  explains  very  little. 
The  discussion,  however,  establishes  the  need  of  some  controlling  in- 
stinct to  preserve  the  hierarchy  of  instinct-efficiencies,  and  the  point 
which  I  have  above  disputed  is  not  absolutely  essential  to  the  argu- 
ment. 

This  controlling  or  governing  instinct  is  to  be  religion ;  and  chapter 
nine  discusses  the  question,  Is  religion  instinctive  ?  Actions  expres- 
sive of  religion  are  organic,  and  subserve  biological  ends,  and  these 
are  the  marks  of  instinct.  It  is  not  necessary  that  they  should  be  defi- 
nite and  regular:  the  higher  instincts  are  rarely  so;  and  we  should 
consider  the  fact  that  religious  activities  are  practically  universal  in  the 
race,  although  it  is  not  necessary  to  the  argument  that  they  should  be 
entirely  so.  The  function  of  religious  expressions  is,  to  restrain  the 
tendency  to  over-variation  from  typical  forms  of  reaction  and  to  em- 
phasize the  order  of  impulse  efficiency  developed  above.  To  under- 
stand this,  we  should  consider  instinct-actions,  and  neglect  both  origins 
and  beliefs.  Seclusion,  fasting  and  self-torture  are  three  typical 
forms  of  religious  expression.  They  are  not  in  themselves  advantag- 
eous to  the  individual  nor  to  the  race,  rather  the  opposite,  and  yet  they 
have  persisted.  They  have  persisted  because  they  tend  to  produce  a 
quiet  of  soul  and  a  reduction  of  physical  vigor  which  favor  the  hearing 
of  the  4  voice'  within  which  is  the  voice  of  our  racial  and  social  instincts. 
The  fact  that  religious  illuminations  seem  to  come  from  without  is 
due  to  their  hallucinatory  character.  Exhaustion  from  hunger,  fatigue 
and  self-torture  make  the  zealot  peculiarly  susceptible  to  hallucinations. 
By  these  activities  the  individual  instincts  are  suspended  and  the  so- 
cial and  racial  instincts  are  permitted  to  make  themselves  felt.  There 
may  have  been,  must  have  been  a  time  when  the  racial  (sexual)  instincts 
needed  this  religious  support  in  order  to  the  perpetuity  of  the  race 
and  its  proper  development,  and  hence  the  various  forms  of  phallic 
worship  which  have  appeared  in  the  past.  Submission  to  the  Power 
that  guides  the  universe  is  involved  in  all  three  forms  of  religious 
activity. 

Prayer  persists  because,  in  the  silent  seclusion  of  the  closet,  with 
the  attention  fixed  upon  some  concrete  or  ideal  object  of  wide  import, 
the  tendency  to  individualistic  reaction  is  repressed  and  the  sugges- 
tions from  man's  deeper  nature  are  emphasized.  Sacrifice  has  a  like 
value.  Celfoacy  and  pilgrimages  either  produce  the  same  effects 


524  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

upon  the  soul  or  favor  those  forms  of  religious  expression  which  do 
produce  them.  The  efforts  of  those  who  hear  the  «  voice  '  to  enforce 
their  admonitions  on  others  take  the  forms  of  teaching,  temples  and 
mysterious  ceremonials.  Purifications  and  lustrations,  initiations  into 
religious  brotherhoods,  stimulations  to  the  aBsthetic  sense,  such  as  pro- 
cessions, pageants,  songs  and  temples,  are  all  discussed  in  this  con- 
nection. The  analysis  of  these  religious  phenomena  is  very  sugges- 
tive ;  but  it  is  undertaken  in  order  to  show  that  religious  exercises  sub- 
serve biological  ends,  and  many  will  feel,  doubtless,  that  the  analyses 
appear  plausible  only  after  we  have  assumed  that  religious  exercises 
do  subserve  biological  ends.  Our  problem  is  that  of  conceiving, 
rather  than  that  of  demonstrating,  relations,  and  it  is  a  fact  that 
conversion  and  other  religious  phenomena  seem  to  be  empirically 
connected  with  puberty  and  the  development  of  the  social  and  racial 
instincts ;  but  if  the  discussion  of  the  function  of  religion  were  in- 
tended as  an  argument  to  show  that  religious  exercises  subserve  bio- 
logical ends,  it  could  scarcely  stand  before  the  charge  of  reasoning  in  a 
circle.  And  yet,  unless  we  take  this  discussion  as  an  argument  (as  we 
cannot  do),  the  author  has  not  shown  that  religion  is  an  instinct.  Per- 
haps* many,  again,  will  feel  that  the  organic  character  of  religious  ac- 
tivities was  not  clearly  enough  established  to  warrant  the  conclusion 
based  upon  the  point. 

Part  III.,  Concerning  Impulse.  Impulse  is  the  subjective  aspect  of 
the  objective  inhibition  of  an  instinct-action.  The  analysis  of  craving 
and  desire  in  the  light  of  this  definition  follows  (p.  348).  Every  man 
represents  a  hierarchy  of  impulses  corresponding  to  the  order  of  sub- 
ordination of  the  instincts,  and  this  gives  his  ethical  standard  for 
the  moment  (pp.  358-362).  Wherever  the  efficiencies  of  opposing 
impulses  are  equal,  my  '  egohood'  decides,  and  I  will  which  I  shall 
follow.  (The  ego  is  identical  with  the  field  of  inattention.)  We 
never  act  contrary  to  the  ethical  standard  of  the  moment,  but  this  varies 
from  moment  to  moment  and  from  man  to  man.  For  each  man  at 
each  moment  there  is  an  individual  standard  of  the  moment ;  but  a 
relatively  stable  individual  standard  arises  in  moments  of  reflection  and 
restraint  from  immediate  action.  This  forms  the  basis  of  mature  eth- 
ical judgment,  a  third  standard ;  but  this  one  also  changes  with  the  en- 
vironment and  with  habit  (p.  372).  Social  influences,  however,  give 
rise  to  the  conception  of  the  ethical  standard  of  the  most  highly  moral 
man  of  whom  we  can  conceive,  and  this  standard,  though  variable,  is 
relatively  stable. 

This  standard  is  not,  however,  the  basis  of  conscience.     "  Consci- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  525 

ence  is  the  protest  of  a  persistent  instinct  against  its  inhibition  by  a  less 
persistent,  but,  for  the  moment,  more  powerful  force"  (p.  388).  Con- 
science is  itself  not  an  instinct,  but  a  relation  between  instincts  (p. 
408) .  Besides  the  ethical  conscience  we  have  also  patriotic,  aesthetic 
and  various  pseudo-consciences.  True  conscience  tells  us  of  instinct, 
while  a  pseudo-conscience  tells  merely  of  organized  habit  (p.  395). 
Conscience,  the  sense  of  duty,  remains  always  the  same,  but  we  find  a 
new  development  of  conscience  in  connection  with  the  development  of 
the  religious  instinct  (p.  397).  "The  existence  within  us  of  a  sense 
of  duty  as  it  is  experienced  in  its  fullest  form,  is  conclusive  evidence 
at  the  same  time  of  the  existence  within  us  of  the  religious  instinct " 

(P-  398). 

Part  IV.,  Concerning  Reason.  By  this  process  we  are  to  under- 
stand "  the  capacity  found  in  animals,  and  in  ourselves  as  animals,  to 
act  apparently  in  opposition  to,  or,  at  least,  without  reference  to,  in- 
stinct" (p.  414).  The  distinction  is  made  between  '  reasoned '  or 
1  intelligent  actions  '  and  '  reasoned  '  or  '  intelligent  feelings.'  The 
pursuance  of  future  ends  and  the  choice  of  means  for  their  attainment 
are  the  marks  of  reason.  Reason  is  marked  by  choice  (an  objective  re- 
suit},  and  choice  is  the  evidence  of  will  on  the  psychic  side  both  in 
ourselves  and  in  the  lower  animals.  Reason  in  germ  or  in  complex 
form  must  be  a  process  as  wide  as  psychic  life.  Reason  and  will  are 
indissolubly  connected,  all  rational  processes  ending  in  will,  and  all 
volition  being  at  the  moment  of  volition  rational  (p.  424). 

All  reasoned  action,  again,  must  be  '  referred  back'  to  instinct-ac- 
tion— it  is  action  according  to  an  older,  simpler  and  more  highly  or- 
ganized instinct,  relating  only  to  the  stimulated  element  of  the  organ- 
ism when  some  more  recent,  more  complex  and  less  highly  organized 
instinct  relating  to  the  organism  as  a  whole  or  to  the  social  organism 
would  have  asserted  itself,  had  not  immediate  and  decisive  action  been 
made  necessary  by  the  nature  of  the  stimulus.  '*  All  reasoned  actions 
must  also  be  referred  back  to  and  appear  as  modes  of  that  simplest  of  all 
phenomena  of  activity,  the  reaction  of  a  single  cell  to  the  stimuli  from 
its  environment"  (p.  438).  The  distinction  between  instinct  and  rea- 
son is  really  not  fundamental ;  it  is  the  distinction  between  a  typical 
reaction  and  a  variant  reaction.  Reason  represents  the  influence  in 
organic  life  which  breaks  down  our  complex  inherited  tendencies. 

Consequently,  our  inherited  impulses  are  a  safer  guide  to  right 
conduct  than  reason,  as  a  general  rule.  That  instinct  is  of  higher  im- 
port than  reason,  is  the  burden  of  nearly  one  hundred  pages  at  the 
close  of  the  work.  But  the  ethical  impulses  are  not  instincts  accord- 


526  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

ing  to  the  author's  definition — they  deal  with  relations  between  in- 
stinct actions — and  religious  expressions  are  instincts  which  have  to  do 
with  the  preservation  of  a  proper  order  of  instinct-efficiencies.  Hence 
arise  the  last  problems  of  the  discussion,  viz.,  the  relations  of  morality 
to  religion  on  the  one  hand,  and  of  both  to  reason  on  the  other.  As 
to  the  first  problem,  morality  is  practically  ineffectual  except  it  be  re- 
ligious, although,  in  our  theorizing,  ethical  conceptions  are  the  logical 
basis  of  religious  opinions,  so  that  the  latter  grow  in  adequacy  with 
the  growth  of  moral  experience  and  thought.  Hence  the  importance 
of  the  utmost  conscientiousness  in  life,  if  we  would  not  fail  of  the  best 
attainment  possible  for  us.  It  is  possible  for  an  intensely  religious 
person  to  be  immoral,  and  hence  such  anomalies  as  the  prayer  of  the 
thief  for  success  in  his  present  attempts  to  filch  his  neighbor,  etc. 

As  to  the  relation  of  religion  to  reason,  the  accumulated  wisdom 
of  the  ages  is,  on  the  face  of  it,  probably  of  greater  worth  than  the 
thought  of  any  single  individual  in  any  particular  community  at  any 
particular  time.  We  ought,  in  the  interest  of  progress,  to  listen  to 
reason,  to  reason  freely  and  fearlessly,  indeed,  and  to  take  risks ;  but 
we  should  never  forget  that  in  doing  so  we  do  take  risks.  In  search- 
ing for  a  rule  of  conduct  we  have  the  following  as  a  final  word : 
"Act  to  restrain  the  impulses  that  demand  immediate  reaction,  in 
order  that  the  impulse  order  determined  by  the  existence  of  impulses 
of  less  strength,  but  of  wider  significance,  may  have  full  weight  in  the 
guidance  of  your  life.  In  other  words — Be  Religious" 

The  theory  thus  presented  with  as  little  comment  as  possible  speaks 
for  itself,  but  we  desire  to  ask  a  few  questions.  First,  as  to  the  objec- 
tive method  adopted.  Does  it  not  make  it  impossible  to  use  some 
facts  and  distinctions  which  are  essential  to  the  discussion  ?  At  some 
places  the  author  himself  has  departed  a  little  from  the  rule  of  perfect 
objectivity  to  consider  subjective  marks  of  instinct,  etc.  One  asks 
himself,  for  example,  for  the  subjective  difference  between  instinct 
and  reason.  If  we  regard  the  two  marks  of  organization  and  sub- 
servience to  biological  ends  purely  in  the  objective,  why  may  we  not 
show  that  reason  itself  is  instinctive?  Construing  these  marks  objec- 
tively simply,  one  feels  that  it  would  be  easier  to  show  that  reason  is 
instinctive  than  that  religion  is.  Indeed,  the  rational  process  does 
creep  into  the  tents  of  instinct  very  frequently,  and  it  seems  to  be 
merely  the  necessity  of  a  '  variant  factor '  in  the  theory  that  prevents 
reason  from  stalking  boldly  into  the  main  street  of  the  opposite  camp. 

Again,  this  hierarchy  of  instincts  and  impulses,  which  seems  so 
definite  in  its  subordinations  and  coordinations  when  considered  as  an 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  527 

objective  phenomenon  what  is  it  from  a  subjective  point  of  view  ? 
Some  will  feel  that  the  author's  picture  is  as  much  removed  from  mental 
experience  as  are,  e.g.,  the  rules  of  the  syllogism  in  formal  logic — I 
mean,  of  course,  the  mental  experience  of  the  race  as  well  as  that  of 
the  individual.  To  illustrate  my  meaning,  take  the  order  of  appear- 
ance of  the  different  ranks  of  instincts  and  impulses,  as  depicted  by 
the  discussion.  Is  it  true  that  the  racial  instincts  appear  after  the  in- 
dividual and  before  the  social,  or  that  the  social  appear  as  far  behind 
the  individual  as  the  theory  demands  ?  It  seems  more  than  question- 
able to  some.  Moreover,  the  discussion  assumes  that  there  is  always  in 
the  individual  a  strong  tendency  to  revert  to  the  individualistic  type 
of  reaction :  the  biological  end  of  religion  is  to  counteract  this  ten- 
dency. But  it  is  an  open  question  whether  the  individual  is  thus  in- 
dividualistic at  bottom,  as  a  matter  of  psychological  fact.  The 
genetic  distinction  seems  to  some  to  be  between  the  more  and  the  less 
rational.  Professor  Baldwin  and  others  have  watched  children  with 
these  various  theories  in  mind,  and  have  been  surprised  to  find  what 
may  be  called  social  reactions  (using  the  terms  in  Mr.  Marshall's 
sense)  as  early  as  individualistic  reactions,  after  excepting  those  which 
are  purely  organic  and  which  occur  before  the  child  can  be  said  to  be 
any  more  psychic  than  a  plant.  There  seem  to  be  many  reasons  for 
believing  that  this  is  true  of  the  race  as  well. 

Again,  how  many  of  the  author's  social  reactions  are  instinctive, 
and  how  many  are  due  to  suggestion  and  imitation  ?  Shall  we  include 
the  latter  social  reactions  in  the  class  of  instincts  ?  Mr.  Marshall  seems 
to  say  so.  But  do  they  not  belong  to  the  category  of  variations,  leading 
to  the  modification  of  old  ways  of  reacting  to  stimuli  ?  Are  we  to 
broaden  our  notion  of  instinct  so  as  to  include  the  organized  reactions 
of  the  social  group  to  its  environment,  as  well  as  those  of  the  individual 
to  his?  If  so,  then  Prof essor  Baldwin  may  grant  that  imitation  in  this 
sense  is  a  complex  instinct  (as  Marshall  maintains)  without  abandon- 
ing his  own  position  that  it  is  not  an  instinct.  It  comes  to  be  a  ques- 
tion as  to  the  meaning  of  instinct,  and  perhaps  some  will  feel  that  Mr. 
Marshall  makes  the  word  far  too  wide. 

Lastly,  as  to  Reason,  the  '  variant  factor  in  psychic  life.'  Does  not 
every  instance  of  reacting  to  old  stimuli  in  new  ways,  of  adaptation  or 
accommodation,  belong  to  the  category  of  reason  as  here  understood  ? 
Reason  covers  intelligence,  and  the  marks  of  both  are  selection  and 
biological  aim  (as  objectively  discoverable  in  the  results  of  the  act). 
Mr.  Marshall  says  that  reason  must  be  coextensive  with  psychic  life. 
But  what  of  those  primitive  acts  evidencing  selection  and  aim,  which 


528  INSTINCT  AND  REASON. 

give  rise  to  so  many  other  instincts — e.g.,  the  expanding  and  contract- 
ing movements  which  many  assume  to  be  the  organic  correlatives  of 
pleasure  and  pain?  These  are  classed  by  our  discussion  as  instincts 
(p.  icxjff.).  They  must  belong  to  both  categories,  as  the  author  uses 
them.  This  same  difficulty  appears  in  the  analysis  of  reason  later  in 
the  work.  Reason  is  the  variant  factor  in  psychic  life ;  but  in  discuss- 
ing the  subject  on  page  448  we  read  that  variation  is  sometimes  '  pro- 
duced immediately  as  the  result  of  a  very  forcible  stimulus,'  and  then 
it  does  not  '  involve  any  previous  effects  upon  consciousness  at  all ' — 
t.  £.,  it  is  not  instinctive.  Lower  down,  on  the  same  page,  we  read 
that  "  all  variation  is  determined  finally  by  instinctive  reaction,  diverg- 
ences being  due  to  differences  of  width  and  complexity  of  the  organic 
systems  involved."  On  pages  79  and  80  we  read  that  activities  de- 
termined by  the  influence  of  the  aggregate  are  instinctive,  while  those 
due  to  elemental  variation  are  '  reasoned '  in  the  higher  forms  of  life 
at  least;  but  page  439,  "the  distinction  between  instinct  and  reason  is 
indeed  not  fundamental."  On  page  449  the  basis  of  the  emphasis  of 
the  partial  impulses  connected  with  variation  is  the  stimuli  which  de- 
termine the  impulses,  "  and  here  we  find  ourselves  dealing  with  the 
essential  processes  of  reasoning."  The  difficulty  here  is  not  merely  a 
verbal  one.  Reason  tends  always  in  the  author's  discussion  to  disap- 
pear in  instinct;  but  if  reason  is  instinct,  and  if  variation  is  reason, 
then  how  is  evolution  possible  ?  I  do  not  see  how  we  can  determine 
the  relation  of  instinct  to  reason  without  considering  the  question  of 
origins,  which  the  author  everywhere  rules  out  of  the  discussion. 

We  wish  Mr.  Marshall  had  discussed  the  '  circular  reaction  theory ' 
of  the  biologists  and  of  Professor  Baldwin  and  others.  In  this  circular 
process  which  they  understand  to  be  the  law  or  essential  method  of 
organic  and  of  psychic  life,  there  are  both  aim  and  selection,  both  or- 
ganization and  biological  end ;  but  it  seems  to  fall  into  both  of  Mr. 
Marshall's  categories.  If  this  process  is  defined  as  one  which  repeats 
its  own  stimulus,  and  if  this  is  the  typical  form  of  all  psycho-physical 
reaction,  then  socially  cooperative  conduct  ought  to  develop  in  or- 
ganic life  side  by  side  with  individualistic  conduct.  In  other  words, 
if  the  circular  process  is  a  true  conception,  I  do  not  see  how  Mr. 
Marshall's  view  of  the  relations  between  the  various  instincts  can  be 
maintained. 

The  author  regards  reason,  will  and  choice  as  coextensive  with 
psychic  life ;  but  is  not  this  a  needless  broadening  of  the  meanings  of 
terms? 

I  may  have  failed  to  grasp  this  complex  and  interesting  theory  in 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  529 

its  details;  but,  if  not,  it  would  seem  clear  that  the  method  of 
the  work  is  too  4  objective'  (it  is  deductive),  and  that  the  terms  of  the 
discussion  are  used  too  loosely. 

G.  A.  TAWNEY. 
BELOIT  COLLEGE,  WISCONSIN. 


La    Psicologia    Contemporanea.      GUIDO   VILLA.      Turin,    Fratelli 

Bocca,  1899.     In  Svo.     Pp.  xvi-f-66o. 

The  object  of  this  volume,  as  explained  by  the  author  himself,  is  to 
give  a  clear  account  of  the  present  condition  of  psychological  studies 
in  those  countries  where  the  scientific  study  of  the  mind  is  most  in 
favor,  as  in  Germany,  in  England,  in  the  United  States  and  in  France 
(preface) .  The  author  apologizes  for  not  having  said  much  of  his 
own  country.  He  seems  to  believe  that,  thus  far,  the  contributions  of 
his  countrymen  to  the  advancement  of  scientific  psychology  have  been 
scanty  and  insignificant.  Signer  Villa  remarks  that  most  of  the  Italian 
psychologists  are,  properly  speaking,  philosophers ;  that  the  dominant 
tendency  in  psychology  is  still  that  of  the  'inner  sense*  which  goes, 
with  certain  authors,  as  far  as  a  purely  spiritualistic  conception  of  the 
mind.  It  is  only  a  short  time  since  works  were  being  published  on 
physiological  psychology,  like  those  of  Sergi,  De  Sarlo,  Buccola, 
Faggi.  But,  he  concludes,  the  new  psychologists,  by  going  to  the 
opposite  extreme  of  the  spiritualistic  philosophers,  seem  to  be  oc- 
erced  into  such  an  intensity  of  materialistic  beliefs  as  to  lose  the 
equilibrium  of  feeling  required  for  dealing  scientifically  with  the  facts 
of  mental  life  (pp.  78-79).  This,  with  the  exception  of  a  few  scat- 
tered references  to  books  published  in  Italy  on  various  psychological 
topics,  is  about  all  he  says  concerning  the  Italian  psychologists,  in  a 
volume  of  more  than  660  pages. 

For  such  a  shameful  lack  of  enthusiasm  over  the  work  of  the  Ital- 
ians in  the  field  of  psychology,  Signor  Villa  has  been  very  severely 
reprimanded  by  Professor  Sergi.  (II  Pensiero  Nuovo,  Vol.  IV., 
1899.)  Sergi  claims  that  Italy  can  stand  comparison  with  any  other 
country  in  regard  to  psychological  work.  As  a  proof,  he  recalls  the 
fact  that  a  laboratory  of  experimental  psychology  was  founded  at 
Reggio  Emilia  by  Tamburini  as  far  back  as  1880,  that  psychological 
laboratories  were  soon  after  organized  in  the  Universities  of  Naples, 
Rome  and  Turin,  in  connection,  respectively,  with  the  chairs  of  psy- 
chiatry, anthropology  and  physiology;  that  since  1879  *ne  ^rs^  work 
on  physiological  psychology  was  published  in  Italy  by  Sergi  himself, 
the  same  work  being  later  on  translated  into  French  by  Ribot  and  Es- 


53°  LA   PSICOLOGIA    CONTEMPORANEA. 

pinas  and  published  in  Alcan  series.  Sergi  further  recalls  the  names 
of  the  most  prominent  contributors  to  the  advancement  of  experi- 
mental and  comparative  psychology  in  Italy:  Vignoli,  Lombroso, 
Morselli,  Buccola,  Mantegazza,  Mosso,  Luciani,  Tanzi,  De  Sanctis, 
Patrizi,  De  Sarlp,  Ferri,  Ferrero,  Sighele. 

We  are  willing  to  concede  that  Signor  Villa  has  somewhat  exag- 
gerated the  insignificance  of  the  Italian  contributions  to  scientific 
psychology,  probably  for  the  purpose  of  pleasing  certain  old  caryatides 
who  control  the  distribution  of  university  chairs.  We  will  also  admit 
that  it  cannot  be  asserted,  as  Villa  does,  that  the  tendency  still  prevail- 
ing in  Italy  in  the  study  of  the  mind  is  that  of  the  '  inner  sense.'  This 
is  only  true  in  reference  to  a  few  men  who  teach  psychology  as  a  part 
of  philosophy  in  some  of  the  universities.  These  fossils,  however, 
cannot  be  made  to  represent  the  whole  movement  of  studies  and  re- 
search in  psychology  which  is  growing,  outside  of  the  philosophical 
faculties,  chiefly  in  connection  with  the  chairs  of  nervous  diseases 
and  physiology.  But  we  cannot  share  Sergi's  indignation  at  Villa's 
alleged  lack  of  patriotism.  There  should  be  no  l  chauvinisme '  in  a 
discussion  of  this  kind.  Nobody  can  deny  that  scientific  psychology 
has  found,  even  in  Italy,  a  number  of  competent  students.  But  we 
cannot  seriously  claim,  as  does  Sergi,  that  Italy  stands  second  to  no 
other  country  in  the  line  of  psychological  work.  Psychology  has  not 
even  gained  in  Italy  a  recognition  as  an  independent  '  natural  science  * 
in  the  university  curriculum.  It  is  still  a  branch  of  philosophy. 
Consequently,  there  cannot  be  specialists  devoting  their  life  to  psy- 
chology alone.  Occasional  psychologists,  however  intelligent  they 
may  be,  are  recruited  among  physiologists,  neurologists,  anthropolo- 
gists. Thus,  psychological  research  appears  to  be  a  sort  of  by-work. 
There  is  absolutely  no  sign  in  Italy  of  a  movement  of  psychological 
studies  and  researches  comparable  to  that  flourishing  in  Germany  or  in 
the  United  States.  Partial  attempts,  scattered  and  isolated  efforts,  in  a 
word,  something  which  is  undoubtedly  growing,  but  is  still  very  imma- 
ture ;  this  is  the  real  condition  of  psychological  studies  in  Italy  to-day. 
The  fact  recalled  by  Sergi,  that  a  psychological  laboratory  was 
founded  in  Italy  in  1880,  is  not  a  conclusive  argument.  The  im- 
portant thing  is  not  to  have  so-called  laboratories,  as  a  novelty  imported 
from  abroad  through  a  sort  of  scientific  snobbishness,  but  to  have  stu- 
dents who  do  nothing  but  psychological  work  and  who  make  discov- 
eries of  new  facts.  What  are,  then,  the  original  contributions  made 
by  Italian  psychologists  which  can  be  said  to  mark  a  step  onward 
in  the  building  up  of  scientific  psychology  ?  Is  there  any  Italian  work 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  531 

to  be  compared  to  those  of  Wundt,  of  James  or  of  Ribot  ?  Of  course, 
I  am  speaking  of  purely  psychological  works.  Golgi,  Luciani, 
Mosso,  Morsel li — men  of  whom  Italy  is  justly  proud — cannot  be  con- 
sidered as  psychologists  as  long  as  physiology  and  psychiatry  are  to 
be  looked  upon  as  sciences  totally  distinct  from  psychology. 

Signor  Villa's  book  is  a  work  of  popularization.  If  advanced 
students  and  trained  specialists  have  nothing  to  learn  from  Villa's 
resume's,  beginners  will  find  it  a  useful  guide  to  the  study  of  psy- 
chology. In  the  conditions  now  prevailing  in  Italy  a  book  like 
this  may  undoubtedly  help  to  arouse  interest  in  pyschological  research, 
to  extend  the  circle  of  psychological  students,  to  bring  the  last  results 
of  experimental  work  abroad  within  the  knowledge  of  a  wider  range 
of  persons.  Such  a  work  had  never  been  attempted  in  Italy.  We  are 
far  from  saying  that  Villa  has  succeeded  in  his  difficult  task.  He  is 
undoubtedly  a  conscientious  worker,  but  sadly  lacks  the  talent  of  dis- 
tributing his  subject-matter  in  the  most  convenient  and  suggestive 
form.  The  book  is,  therefore,  full  of  unnecessary  repetitions,  it  is 
heavy  and  cumbersome,  its  reading  is  tiring  through  prolixity  and  over- 
abundance of  4  historical  stuff.'  But,  in  spite  of  that,  Villa's  patient 
and  truly  meritorious  effort  deserves  the  warmest  encouragement, 
and  we  cannot  help  declaring  that  Sergi  has  been  utterly  unjust  in 
accusing  Villa  of  ignoring  the  laboratory  and  of  being  a  '  dilettante.' 
That  Villa  is  fairly  well  informed  of  the  results  of  experimental  work 
and  of  the  physiological  facts  bearing  on  psychological  research  is 
abundantly  proved  by  his  chapter  on  '  Psychological  Methods,'  and  by 
the  clear  account  which  he  gives  of  the  recent  discoveries  in  nervous 
histology  by  Golgi,  Ramon  y  Cajal  and  others,  in  the  chapter  on  '  Mind 
and  Body,'  one  of  the  best  in  the  whole  book. 

The  following  are  the  general  headings  of  the  chapters :  Introduc- 
tion; I.,  Historical  Development  of  Psychology;  II.,  Conception  of 
Psychology;  III.,  Mind  and  Body;  IV.,  The  Methods  of  Psychology; 
V.,  The  Psychical  Functions;  VI.,  Consciousness;  VII.,  Psycho- 
logical Laws ;  Conclusion. 

Signor  Villa  is  thoroughly  acquainted  with  German  psychological 
literature,  especially  with  Wundt's  works.  He  gives,  on  the  whole, 
one  of  the  best  resumes  of  Wundt's  doctrines  as  unfolded  in  the  three 
standard  psychological  works  of  the  great  German  master  and 
in  all  his  monographs  published  in  the  '  Philosophische  Studien.' 
Especially  worthy  of  notice  is  the  re"sum6  of  Wundt's  theory  of  Will 
(pp.  432-438)  ;  all  the  more  so,  as  Wundt's  theory  of  will  is  one  of  the 
most  important  elements  of  his  interpretation  of  the  facts  of  mental 


53  2  LA  PSICOLOGIA    CONTEMPORANEA. 

life  and  cannot  be  found  in  a  coherent  and  unique  statement;  but  it  is 
to  be  reconstructed  from  nearly  all  his  works,  and  chiefly  from  the 
*  System  der  Philosophic, '  the  '  Grundziige  der  Physiolog.  Psychol.,' 
and  the  '  Grundriss  der  Psych.'  Villa  is  also  well  acquainted  with 
French  and  English  literature.  But  he  is  a  determined  follower  of 
Wundt's  doctrines.  Perhaps  his  admiration  for  that  powerful  intellect 
carries  him  too  far  beyond  the  limits  of  '  rationabile  obsequium.' 
Wundt's  doctrines  are  for  him  the  alpha  and  the  omega  of  psychol- 
ogy. He  tenaciously  clings  to  the  presupposition  of  4  psychophysical 
parallelism/  but  fails  to  understand  that  a  provisional  empirical  as- 
sumption, justified  only  by  the  adoption  of  the  '  natural  science '  stand- 
point in  psychology,  cannot  be  transformed  into  an  imperative  dogma 
without  overstepping  the  boundaries  of  science  and  running  into 
metaphysics.  He  says  (p.  413)  that  there  is  an  absolute  difference  be- 
tween the  physiological  phenomenon  and  the  psychical  process.  But, 
by  emphasizing  the  hiatus  between  the  causal  series,  by  vigorously  as- 
serting the  irreducible  difference  between  the  elementary  facts  of  both 
series,  he  helps  to  accentuate  what  has  always  been  the  weakest  point 
in  Wundt's  system — i.  e.,  the  impossibility  of  conceiving  a  '  parallel- 
ism '  where  experience  shows  4  dependence '  of  one  series  (the  psy- 
chological) upon  the  other  (the  physiological).  Parallelism  presup- 
poses the  independence  of  the  two  orders  of  fact.  But  what  becomes 
of  the  psychical  process  if  the  nervous  system  disappears  ?  The  truth 
is  that  the  assumption  of  a  psychophysical  parallelism,  alleged  to  be 
a  merely  empirical  statement  of  facts  to  be  provisionally  and  un- 
critically accepted  as  the  starting-point  of  scientific  psychology,  has 
resulted,  in  the  end,  in  a  desperate  attempt  to  preserve,  in  a  new  and 
insidious  form,  the  postulates  of  spiritualism.  When  disfigured  through 
dogmatism  and  forced  into  the  turbid  region  of  metaphysics,  the 
principle  of  psychophysical  parallelism  must  necessarily  end  in  a 
puzzling  enigma.  If,  as  Villa  declares,  the  origin  of  the  mental  fact 
coincides  with  the  origin  of  life  on  earth,  so  that  the  two  series  of 
facts — the  mental  and  the  vital — reveal  their  alleged  parallelism 
throughout  the  whole  animal  series  (p.  656)  ;  if  we  can  explain  the 
biological  phenomenon  as  a  result  of  highly  complex  chemical  proc- 
esses, which  in  turn  maybe  traced  back  to  the  general  laws  of  physics 
(p.  658)  ;  if,  on  the  other  hand,  we  cannot  explain  the  elementary 
psychical  fact  as  the  result  of  the  same  physico-chemical  agencies  pro- 
ducing life  (ibid.'}  ;  then  the  origin  of  the  mental  fact  remains  unex- 
plained as  something  which  springs  up  ex  nihilo  while  life,  its  con- 
comitant, has  definite  antecedents.  We  cannot  escape  the  '  impasse  * 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  533 

without  prolonging  the  psychical  series  beyond  the  limen  of  life  into  the 
inorganic  world,  just  as  we  prolong  the  biological  series  down  to  the 
lower  plane  of  chemical  processes.  We  must,  in  other  words,  attri- 
bute to  the  inorganic  world  some  sort  of  unconscious  mentality. 
Thus,  when  pressed  too  far,  the  principle  of  psychophysical  parallel- 
ism leads  directly  to  some  new  form  of  animism,  hence  to  pure 
mysticism. 

But  this  is  not  the  place  for  discussing,  in  an  episodical  way,  such 
momentous  problems.  We  will  simply  add  that  Villa  does  not  seem  to  be 
acquainted  with  recent  American  literature  as  well  as  with  the  Ger- 
man. Of  Professor  Baldwin's  works,  he  seems  to  know  only  the  'Hand- 
book '  thoroughly.  The  brilliant  studies  on  '  Child-Psychology  '  seem 
to  be  known  to  Villa  only  by  the  title  (pp.  84,  89).  He  is  ignorant  of 
Professor  Baldwin's  most  recent  work  4  Social  and  Ethical  Interpreta- 
tions in  Mental  Development,'  thus  missing  one  of  the  most  important 
contributions  of  American  thought  to  the  advancement  of  both  psy- 
chology and  sociology,  a  work  which,  together  with  '  Les  Lois  de 
ITmitation,'  by  Tarde,  marks  a  critical  moment  in  the  growth  of  social 
science.  I  have  also  noticed  lack  of  exactness  in  biographical  infor- 
mation regarding  prominent  American  psychologists.  For  instance, 
he  gives  Professor  Munsterberg  (pp.  86,  125)  as  lecturing  at  Frei- 
burg, and  Professor  Baldwin  (p.  83)  at  Toronto.  The  ignorance  of 
Tarde's  and  Baldwin's  works  accounts  for  the  extreme  vagueness  and 
confusion  we  have  noticed  throughout  the  book  in  regard  to  the 
conception  of  social  psychology  and  to  the  relationship  of  social  psy- 
chology to  sociology. 

In  conclusion,  we  will  say  that  Signor  Villa's  book,  taken  all  in 
all,  is  a  conscientious  work  which,  despite  the  author's  most  decided 
infatuations  for  certain  deceptive  Wundtian  formulas,  might  become  a 
very  useful  guide  to  beginners,  if  the  author,  in  a  new  edition,  would 
use  the  scissors  freely  in  order  to  suppress  all  the  unnecessary  repeti- 
tions which  make  the  book  so  voluminous  in  its  present  arrangement. 
A  carefully  prepared  index  would  very  greatly  increase  the  usefulness 
of  this  work. 

GUSTAVO  TOSTI. 

NEW  YORK  CITY. 

The  Elements  of  Sociology.      FRANKLIN  HENRY  GIDDINGS.      The 

Macmillan  Co.,  New  York  and  London,  1898. 

This  volume  "  is  not  an  abridgment  of  the  author's  4  Principles  of 
Sociology,'  but  is  a  new  book."  To  the  psychologist  the  most  sig- 


534  THE  ELEMENTS   OF  SOCIOLOGY. 

nificant  feature  in  the  work  as  compared  with  the  c  Principles  '  is  the 
increased  prominence  given  to  social  psychology.  The  '  Principles ' 
devoted  a  large  space  to  discussion  of  the  scope  and  method  of  Soci- 
ology. The  present  work  makes  a  great  advance  toward  organizing 
all  the  manifold  phenomena  with  which  Sociology  has  attempted  to 
deal,  and  viewing  them  as  manifestations  of  a  single  principle,  which, 
it  is  needless  to  say,  is  that  of  '  consciousness  of  kind.'  Whether  soci- 
ologists are  likely  to  take  kindly  to  this  tendency  to  make  their  science 
essentially  a  Social  Psychology  is  for  them  to  say,  but  it  cannot  fail  to 
interest  the  psychologist. 

As  in  the  4  Principles '  so  in  the  '  Elements,'  the  author  does  not 
seem  to  recognize  any  more  recent  psychology  than  that  of  Mr. 
Spencer  and  the  associationists.  "The  unit  of  investigation  in  the 
study  of  consciousness  is  sensation,  which  is  the  simplest  of  all  mental 
facts."  But  the  most  serious  objection  to  the  author's  central  principle 
seems  to  me  to  be  that  it  is  a  clear  case  of  the  psychologist's  fallacy. 
It  not  merely  makes  the  whole  motor  force  of  human  societies  pre- 
eminently cognitive  rather  than  impulsive  in  character,  but  it  assumes 
that  the  like-mindedness  by  which  people  become  co-workers  is  the 
product  in  large  measure,  at  least,  of  their  recognition  that  they  are 
alike.  To  put  it  in  a  form  which  is  more  extreme  than  Prof.  Gid- 
dings'  statement,  but  which  after  all  is  quite  in  the  spirit  of  his  general 
thesis :  people  have  common  interests  because  they  discover  they  are 
like-minded,  instead  of  discovering  that  they  are  like-minded  because 
they  have  common  interests.  The  primacy  of  the  intellectual  or  of  the 
impulsive  aspect  of  consciousness  is  the  matter  at  issue,  and  the  biolog- 
ical evidence  seems  to  point  increasingly  to  the  latter  alternative.  Some 
of  the  particular  illustrations  of  the  power  of  '  consciousness  of  kind ' 
strike  one  as  remarkably  devious  paths  for  explaining  simple  facts. 
Thus,  for  example:  when  two  strangers  meet  unexpectedly  "there  is 
either  a  shock  of  unpleasant  feeling  or  a  certain  thrill  of  pleasurable 
feeling."  "Now  the  feeling  of  shock  surprise,  anger  disgust,  which 
may  happen  to  be  the  experience  in  the  case  is  beyond  doubt  due  to  a 
very  complicated  impression  of  unlikeness  which  the  stranger  makes." 
Even  the  psychologist  who  will  have  naught  of  Darwin  or  James  in  his 
theory  of  emotions  would  be  loath  to  trace  all  disagreeable  reactions  to 
a  perception  of  unlikeness.  Indeed  Prof.  Giddings  goes  on  in  the  same 
paragraph  to  suggest  the  simpler  explanation  without  any  apparent 
consciousness  that  this  is  the  case.  "  The  man's  appearance  as  seen 
with  the  eye  may  be  repellent  or  threatening,  his  voice  may  grate  re- 
pel lently  on  the  ear."  A  threatening  appearance,  a  grating  voice  may 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  535 

be  just  our  own  most  prominent  characteristic;  they  will  not  be  any 
the  more  pleasurable  in  a  stranger  on  this  account.  We  dislike  the 
threatening  appearance  because  of  the  anticipated  pain,  or  because  its 
past  associations,  individual  or  hereditary— not  because  of  its  unlike- 
ness.  And  as  regards  children,  it  is  the  familiarity  of  objects  or 
persons,  or  their  likeness  to  those  objects  or  persons  with  which  he  is 
familiar,  not  their  likeness  to  himself,  which  occasions  pleasure.  The 
child  who  has  never  seen  a  negro  may  be  at  first  afraid ;  but  the  child 
nursed  by  the  negro  4  mammy '  has  no  such  experience.  It  is  because 
the  negro  is  unlike  the  other  persons  of  its  acquaintance,  is  unfamiliar, 
that  the  child  in  the  former  case  feels  fear.  It  is  the  common  interests 
of  the  primitive  family  which  make  the  kinsman  dear  and  the  stranger 
an  object  of  suspicion. 

Another  case  in  which  a  devious  instead  of  a  simple  method  of 
explanation  is  followed,  appears  in  the  account  of  belief.  This  is  de- 
fined as  "the  confident  expectation  that  what  we  desire  will  come 
true ;  that  what  we  find  extremely  interesting  in  accounts  of  the  past 
were  true."  "This  confidence  we  feel  because  in  a  majority  of  in- 
stances the  things  we  have  desired  and  striven  for  have  been  realized." 
This  seems  to  me  an  attempt  to  explain  a  fact  of  social  psychology  by 
an  individualistic  hypothesis.  Belief  as  signifying  the  acceptance  for 
practical  purposes  of  any  idea  or  theory  or  presumed  fact  must  in  the 
large  proportion  of  cases  be  based,  not  on  immediate  personal  experi- 
ence, but  on  information  or  authority  of  others.  The  whole  possi- 
bility of  the  child's  profiting  at  all  by  the  past  experience  of  the  race 
or  by  the  larger  knowledge  of  parent  and  teacher  depends  on  belief  in 
what  he  is  taught.  Natural  selection  as  well  as  social  selection  would 
soon  eliminate  those  members  of  a  race  who  believed  nothing  except 
what  they  had  themselves  experienced.  The  antecedents  of  belief,  if 
not  the  belief  itself,  are  to  be  found  in  any  social  group  of  animals, 
the  members  of  which  depend  upon  each  other  for  news  of  food  or 
warning  of  danger. 

The  ultimate  psychological  law,  according  to  the  author,  which 
explains  the  fact  of  consciousness  of  kind  and  so  of  all  other  social 
facts,  is  that  "consciousness  endeavors  to  attain  painless  clearness,  or 
positive  pleasure,  with  a  minimum  of  difficulty."  As  one  reflects  on 
the  work  and  manifold  activities  of  the  world,  on  the  development  of 
civilization  by  the  long  and  unresting  struggle,  on  the  ever-widening 
range  of  interests  that  emerge,  one  is  tempted  to  say  that  the  formula 
is  both  too  abstract  and  too  simple  to  be  of  use  for  actual  explanation. 
Consciousness  cannot  be  adequately  defined  in  terms  either  intellectual 


536  TALKS    TO  TEACHERS   ON  PSYCHOLOGY. 

('clearness')  or  affective  (pleasure),  and  the  poet  was  a  good  psy- 
chologist when  he  wrote  '  More  life  and  fuller,'  as  the  basal  law  of 
human  striving. 

J.  H.  TUFTS. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO. 

Talks  to  Teachers  on  Psychology,  and  to  Students  on  Some  of 
Life's  Ideals.  WILLIAM  JAMES.  New  York,  Henry  Holt  &  Co. 
1899.  Pp.  vi  +  301. 

This  book  consists  of  lectures  on  psychology  given,  in  1892,  at  the 
request  of  the  Harvard  Corporation,  to  the  Cambridge  teachers,  and 
of  three  addresses  at  women's  colleges.  The  latter  are  not  peda- 
gogical, but  they  are  so  congruous  in  subject  and  mode  of  treatment 
that  they  are  properly  included  in  the  volume. 

The  '  Talks  to  Teachers '  start  from  the  biological  conception  of 
man  as  an  organism  adapted  to  react  on  its  environment.  This  con- 
ception is  not  offered  as  a  complete  statement  of  the  facts.  The  author 
is  explicit  on  this  point  at  the  outset :  "  No  one  believes  more  strongly 
than  I  do  that  what  our  senses  know  as  '  this  world '  is  only  one  por- 
tion of  our  mind's  total  environment  and  object  "  (p.  25).  In  the  last 
lecture  Professor  James's  well-known  position  in  regard  to  free  will 
is  stated:  "  a  belief  in  free  will  and  purely  spiritual  causation  is  still 
open  to  us.  *  *  I  myself  hold  with  the  f ree-willist "  (p.  191).  The 
4  ultra-simple  point  of  view'  is  adopted  for  the  sake  of  the  unity  and 
simplicity  which  it  imparts  to  the  exposition.  It  has  the  advantage  of 
preserving  the  continuity  between  human  and  animal  psychology,  and 
of  coordinating  the  brain  life  and  the  mental  life  as  having  one  funda- 
mental kind  of  purpose.  Whatever  higher  functions  and  products  the 
mind  may  be  capable  of  are  necessarily  conditioned  upon  useful  adapta- 
tions, so  that  these  may  be  considered  the  more  essential,  or  at  least 
the  more  primordial. 

But  however  proper  it  may  be  to  abstract,  as  all  sciences  do,  from 
the  totality  of  phenomena  for  the  purpose  of  clearer  understanding, 
this  procedure  is  attended  with  peculiar  danger  in  psychology.  To 
take  the  senses,  a  few  instinctive  impulses,  association  and  the  ideo- 
motor  function  of  will,  and  treat  these  as  the  whole  of  mind,  is  mis- 
leading. 4  c  I  cannot  but  think  that  to  apperceive  your  pupil  as  a  little 
sensitive,  impulsive,  associative  and  reactive  organism,  partly  fated 
and"  (the  qualification  should  be  observed)  "  partly  free,  will  lead  to 
a  better  understanding  of  all  his  ways.  Understand  him,  then,  as 
such  a  subtle  little  piece  of  machinery"  (p.  196).  "  Such  is  the  little 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  537 

interested  and  impulsive  psychophysical  organism  whose  springs  of 
action  the  teacher  must  divine"  (p.  62).  The  frequent  characteriza- 
tion of  the  subject  of  psychology  as  an  i  organism '  and  a  «  machine/ 
the  emphasis  put  upon  reaction  on  the  environment  as  the  essential 
thing  about  it,  the  use  of  physiological  instead  of  psychical  terms  of 
description — this  tends  to  concentrate  attention  upon  mechanical  ele- 
ments and  aspects.  The  definition  of  education  leaves  out  of  account 
ideal  ends — truth  as  intrinsically  excellent,  one's  perfection  as  a 
rational  being,  etc. — and  insists  only  on  serviceable  behavior.  "  Edu- 
cation cannot  be  better  described  than  by  calling  it  the  organization 
of  acquired  habits  of  conduct  and  tendencies  to  behavior"  (p.  29). 
In  the  enumeration  of  native  instincts  and  tendencies  the  biological 
standpoint  is  kept  in  view;  fear,  curiosity,  imitation,  emulation,  am- 
bition, ownership,  constructiveness,  are  adduced — the  existence  of  dis- 
interested impulses  is  recognized  only  in  the  bare  mention  of  love. 
The  expository  advantages  of  the  point  of  view  adopted  are  counter- 
balanced by  an  inevitable  obscuring  of  the  free  activity  of  mind,  and 
by  the  ruling  out  of  consideration,  for  the  greater  part,  of  its  higher 
manifestations — intellectual,  aesthetic  and  ethical.  This  may  not  be  a 
fair  criticism  in  view  of  the  care  taken  by  the  author  to  prevent  mis- 
understanding ;  but  it  is  pertinent  to  ask  whether  partial  points  of  view, 
gotten  by  abstracting  from  the  complete  facts,  are  desirable  in  psy- 
chology ;  whether,  for  example,  it  is  expedient  to  exclude,  as  Professor 
James  would  do,  all  metaphysical  prepossessions  and  implications. 
If  the  facts  do  not  involve  these,  there  can  be,  of  course,  no  dispute ; 
but  those  who  believe  that  conscious  experience  is  ontological  in 
essence  may  well  consider  whether  it  is  best  to  ignore  this  in  the  dis- 
cussion of  psychological  problems. 

These  lectures  illustrate  the  advantages  of  entrusting  the  *  popular- 
ization' of  science  to  the  hands  of  a  master.  The  extravagant  claims, 
the  incautious  generalizations,  the  profuse  use  of  technical  language, 
with  which  we  are  so  familiar  in  works  of  a  certain  class,  are  here 
refreshingly  absent.  It  is  something  to  be  thankful  for  that  instruc- 
tion and  counsel  so  wholesome  and  timely  as  that  contained  in  the 
opening  remarks  should  gain  so  wide  a  hearing.  "  In  my  humble 
opinion  there  is  no  '  new  psychology'  worthy  of  the  name.  There  is 
nothing  but  the  old  psychology  which  began  in  Locke's  time,  plus  a 
little  physiology  of  the  brain  and  sense  and  theory  of  evolution,  and  a 
few  refinements  of  introspective  detail.  *  *  *  I  say  moreover  that  you 
make  a  great,  a  very  great  mistake  if  you  think  that  psychology,  being 
the  science  of  the  mind's  laws,  is  something  from  which  you  can 


TALKS    TO    TEACHERS   ON  PSYCHOLOGY. 

deduce  definite  programmes  and  schemes  and  methods  of  instruction  for 
immediate  schoolroom  use.  Psychology  is  a  science,  and  teaching 
is  an  art ;  and  sciences  never  generate  arts  directly  out  of  themselves' 
(p.  7).  "  Least  of  all  need  you,  merely  as  teachers,  deem  it  part  of 
your  duty  to  become  contributors  to  psychological  science,  or  to  make 
psychological  observations  in  a  methodical  or  responsible  manner.  I 
fear  that  some  of  the  enthusiasts  for  child-study  have  thrown  a  certain 
burden  upon  you  in  this  way.  *  *  *  For  Heaven's  sake,  let  the  rank 
and  file  of  teachers  be  passive  readers,  if  they  so  prefer,  arid  feel  free 
not  to  contribute  to  the  accumulation"  (pp.  12,  13).  If  the  last 
quoted  remark  should  deter  any  too  zealous  investigator  from  entering 
one  field,  in  particular,  in  which  some  truly  fearful  results  have  been 
achieved — that  of  pathological  psychology— the  service  will  be  by  no 
means  small. 

It  is  needless  to  say  that  the  same  qualities  of  thought  and  style 
which  appear  in  the  author's  other  works — not  the  least  of  them  being 
a  happy  incapacity  for  dulness — are  abundantly  manifest  in  these 
*  talks.'  One  is  inclined  to  envy  Professor  James  the  friends  who 
tell  him  so  many  delightful  anecdotes,  exactly  fitted  to  illustrate  his 
points.  A  number  of  stories  are  given  such  as  would  make  one's  for- 
tune at  a  dinner-party.  If  Falstaff  were  a  sufficiently  dignified  person- 
age, he  might  be  quoted  in  explanation:  "I  am  not  only  witty  in 
myself,  but  the  cause  that  wit  is  in  other  men."  There  is  doubtless  a 
delicate  concession  to  the  lady  auditors  in  this  change  of  gender  : 
4 'Anecdotes  and  reminiscences  will  abound  in  all  her  talks,  and  the 
shuttle  of  interest  will  shoot  backward  and  forward ;  another  teacher 
has  no  such  inventive  fertility,  and  his  lesson  will  always  be  a  dead 
and  heavy  thing"  (p.  96). 

The  lectures  on  habit,  attention,  memory,  will,  contain  all  that  is 
most  concrete  and  practical  in  the  corresponding  chapters  of  the  Prin- 
ciples of  Psychology.  The  use  of  needlessly  mysterious  and  preten- 
tious words  for  expressing  simple  meanings  is  effectively  commented 
on  in  the  lecture  on  apperception.  The  following  helpful  pedagogic 
suggestions^r-a  few  out  of  many — may  be  noted :  the  transitoriness  of 
instincts  (p.  61),  elementary  defects  not  fatal  (p.  135),  too  few  heads 
of  classification  (p.  163),  the  bulky  will  (p.  181),  two  types  of  inhi- 
bition (p.  193). 

The  4  talks  to  students,'  which  constitute  the  second  part  of  the 
volume,  have  these  titles :  *  The  Gospel  of  Relaxation,'  '  On  a  Cer- 
tain Blindness  in  Human  Beings,'  l  What  Makes  a  Life  Significant?' 
The  first  is  an  interesting  and  persuasive  protest  against  mental  and 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  539 

moral  over-tension ;  the  other  two  insist  on  the  importance  of  a  sym- 
pathetic appreciation  of  the  points  of  view  and  the  ideals  of  others, 
showing  that  only  thus  is  the  common  life  of  humanity  redeemed  from 
apparent  insignificance  and  discerned  in  its  potentialities  of  dignity 
and  heroism.  An  application  of  the  line  of  thought  in  the  second  and 
third  addresses  is  suggested  in  the  Preface,  which  may  not  b*e  entirely 
agreeable  to  readers  of  '  imperialistic '  proclivities. 

This  volume  deserves  the  attention,  not  only  of  teachers,  but  of 
parents,  and  of  all  persons  interested  in  psychology  and  in  education. 

EDWARD  H.  GRIFFIN. 
JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY. 

Conduct  and  the    Weather — An  Inductive   Study  of  the  Mental 

Effects   of  Definite    Meteorological     Conditions.     Monograph 

Supplement  to  THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  No.  x.     EDWIN 

GRANT  DEXTER.     Pp.  viii-fio5. 

This  study  is  an  attempt  to  throw  some  light  upon  the  question  of 
the  weather  in  its  relation  to  human  activities.  The  method  is  for  the 
most  part  inductive  and  consists  of  a  comparison  of  the  occurrence  of 
certain  data  of  conduct,  under  definite  meteorological  conditions,  with 
the  normal  prevalence  of  those  conditions. 

The  study  was  made  for  the  cities  of  New  York,  and  Denver,  Colo. 

The  data  considered  were  taken  from  the  various  public  records  of 
those  cities  and  consist  of  misdemeanors  in  the  public  schools  and 
penitentiaries,  arrests  for  assault  and  battery  (males  and  females  con- 
sidered separately) ,  arrests  for  insanity,  the  death-rate,  suicide,  clerical 
errors  in  banks  and  strength-tests  in  the  gymnasium  of  Columbia 
University.  A  period  of  more  than  ten  years  is  covered  and  some- 
thing over  400,000  data  considered. 

As  a  basis  for  the  study,  the  mean  temperature,  barometer  and 
humidity,  the  total  movement  of  the  wind,  the  character  of  the  day 
and  the  precipitation,  as  recorded  by  the  officers  of  the  United  States 
Weather  Bureau,  for  each  day  of  the  period  covered,  are  used.  The 
occurrence  of  bad  deportment  in  the  schools  and  penitentiary,  of  as- 
sault and  of  the  other  classes  of  data  are  then  referred  to  these 
meteorological  conditions,  and  the  exact  weather  upon  which  they  are 
most  prevalent  determined.  These  relations  are  shown  by  means  of 
tables  and  more  than  150  curves. 

Some  interesting  things  are  shown.  Among  them,  that  upon  cloudy 
and  rainy  days  there  are  less  bad  marks  given  in  the  schools — with  the 
smaller  attendance  allowed  for — less  arrests  for  assault,  and  even  less 


54°  THE  EMOTION  OF  JOY. 

suicides  than  upon  clear,  dry  days.  The  death-rate,  however,  in- 
creases a  little  for  wet  weather.  Upon  perfectly  calm  days  the  latter 
is  high,  while  all  the  other  occurrences  mentioned  are  below  the 
average.  Extremely  high  winds,  too,  seem  to  have  a  soothing  effect, 
for  excesses  in  conduct  are  comparatively  few  at  such  times.  Moder- 
ately brisk  winds  have  the  worst  effect.  For  high  humidities,  all  the 
data,  except  the  death-rate,  were  low.  This  seems  rather  strange,  for 
muggy,  sticky  days  are  of  such  a  character.  A  very  marked  effect  is 
shown  by  the  barometer.  With  the  exception  of  death,  all  the  occur- 
rences were  low  for  high  readings,  and  high  for  the  reverse  condition 
of  the  mercury  column.  Some  conclusions  are  drawn  with  respect  to 
the  relations  of  the  barometer  to  periods  just  preceding  storms.  The 
effects  of  different  degrees  of  heat  are  shown  to  be  the  greatest  of  all, 
temperature  of  from  75°  to  85°  being  accompanied  by  nearly  50% 
more  assaults  and  other  evidences  of  bad  conduct  than  the  normal. 
Temperatures  above  85°  show  a  marked  falling  off,  as  if,  under  such 
excessive  heat,  little  energy  was  left  for  bad  behavior.  A  large  part  of 
the  paper  is  devoted  to  the  study  of  school  children.  In  it  are  dis- 
cussed the  answers  to  a  questionnaire  sent  out  to  nearly  200  teachers 
in  various  parts  of  the  country,  asking  their  opinions  as  to  the  effects 
of  the  weather  upon  their  pupils.  These  answers  are  compared  with 
the  exact  effects  shown  by  the  study  of  the  records  of  deportment  in 
the  school  registers.  The  teachers  were  almost  unanimous  in  their 
opinion  that  the  weather  has  its  influence  not  only  upon  the  deport- 
ment, but  upon  the  character  of  the  class  work  of  their  charges. 

A  study  of  school  attendance  is  included  in  their  work,  and  some 
conclusions  drawn  as  to  the  influence  of  the  weather  upon  the  health 
of  the  pupils. 

The  general  conclusions  arrived  at  in  the  paper  are  that  those 
weather  states  which  are  physically  energizing  and  exhilarating  are 
accompanied  by  an  unusual  number  of  excesses  in  deportment  and 
the  minimum  of  deaths  and  mental  inexactnesses,  while  the  opposite 
meteorological  conditions  show  the  reverse  effects. 

THE  AUTHOR. 

The   Emotion  of  Joy.     GEORGE  V.   N.    DEARBORN.     Monograph 
supplement   to   THE   PSYCHOLOGICAL    REVIEW,  No.  IX.,    New 
York,  Macmillans.     April,  1899.     Pp.  ii  +  yo. 
Starting  with  evolution,  psychophysical  parallelism,  and  the  kin- 
aesthetic  theory  of  emotion  as  necessary  and  basal  presuppositions, 
this  monograph  discusses  the  emotion  of  joy  with  somewhat  of  that 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  541 

detail  which  every  emotion  in  turn  demands.  On  the  one  hand,  joy 
is  considered  in  its  bodily  aspects  as  dependent  on  universal  biologic 
inheritance  from  simpler  organic  forms,  while  on  the  other  hand  its 
psychical  characteristics  are  pointed  out,  and  especially  those  funda- 
mental social  relations  which  constitute  so  important  a  part  of  all 
human  emotional  phenomena.  The  adequate  study  of  an  emotion  is 
shown  to  implicate  well-nigh  every  aspect  of  biology,  in  the  narrow 
sense  of  the  term.  The  research  was  introspective  as  well  as 
experimental. 

Three  years  of  practical  work  in  the  psychological  laboratories  of 
Harvard  and  of  Columbia  is  described  in  the  reports  of  five  distinct 
though  related  series  of  experiments.  Three  of  these  investigate  and 
fully  confirm  the  ancient  but,  for  science,  hitherto  rather  vague  sup- 
position that  pleasant  mental  states  are  correlated  in  the  body  with  con- 
traction of  muscles  classed  as  extensor  and  unpleasant  states  with  flexor 
activity,  the  three  series  of  experiments  relating  respectively  to  the 
reactions  of  the  hand  and  the  head,  the  forearm,  and  the  leg.  The 
hand,  because  the  most  mobile  portion  of  the  body  at  our  disposal, 
showed  most  emphatically  the  psychophysical  tendency  in  question. 
The  forearm  was  studied  only  as  to  its  reaction  to  pleasantness  and  un- 
pleasantness in  voluntary  extensions  and  flexions  through  an  arc  of 
about  forty  degrees,  while  in  case  of  the  hand,  head  and  leg  only  the 
involuntary  and  unconscious  movements  were  observed.  The  stimuli 
employed  were  odors,  colored  light  and  sound,  and  these  were  judged 
as  pleasant,  indifferent  or  unpleasant  in  seven  degrees,  <  one '  being 
the  most  relatively  pleasant  and  l  seven '  the  most  unpleasant.  These 
experiments  together  number  about  three  thousand,  and,  considering 
the  practical  difficulties  of  any  laboratory  research  into  affective  con- 
ditions, strongly  verify  the  chief  presupposition  which  from  general 
considerations  seemed  a  priori  to  be  so  probable. 

The  much  discussed  nature  of  the  smile  and  laugh  is  hereby  ex- 
plained, early  embryonic  conditions  showing  that  the  muscles  active  in 
these  phenomena  are  properly  extensor  muscles,  thus  at  once  explain- 
ing the  hitherto  mysterious  fact  of  laughter  and  confirming  the  under- 
lying theory. 

The  fourth  set  of  experiments  deals  with  the  bodily  correlation  in 
general  of  joyous  emotion  in  a  novel  and  more  or  less  productive  way, 
while  the  fifth  series  is  a  research,  quantitative  as  well  as  qualitative, 
into  the  vascular  and  respiratory  somatic  concomitants  of  joy. 

Emotion,  the  most  complex  of  human  psychological  phenomena, 
is  defined  as  u  a  temporal  portion  of  excited  sentient  experience 


542  THE  EMOTION  OF  JOY. 

wherein  the  subjectivity  and  the  psychophysical  attention  to  the  ob- 
ject, real  or  ideal,  are  heightened  with  or  without  a  tone  of  pleasantness 
or  of  unpleasantness,  and  wherein  the  feeling  and  the  bodily  position 
or  movement  are,  or  tend  to  be,  characteristic  and  correlative."  Emo- 
tion properly  so  called  may  be  found  pure,  then,  only  in  the  'lower* 
or  simpler  orders  of  life,  for  in  man  the  vast  complexities  of  his, 
always  social,  personality  render  any  such  affective  period  beyond  the 
physiologist's  power  of  description.  In  the  simpler  orders  of  animal 
life,  down  to  its  vanishing-point  in  the  amoaba,  the  pleasantness-ex- 
tension and  unpleasantness-flexion  principle  is  more  complete;  in 
man,  however,  with  all  the  complicating  and  often  conflicting  tenden- 
cies there  obtaining,  its  manifestations  may  still  be  regularly  observed, 
with  constant  exceptions  here  explained,  as  the  persistence  of  basal 
biologic  law  necessitates. 

The  regular  occurrence  of  habitual  inhibitions,  due  to  complex 
conditions  of  civilized  social  development,  supplies  the  apparent  de- 
ficiency in  the  kinaesthetic  theory  of  the  emotions  of  man.  Any  emo- 
tion, being  biologically  in  animals,  savages  and  naive  infants  a  more 
or  less  constant  series  of  phenomena,  is  theoretically  at  least  susceptible 
of  future  scientific  determination  more  or  less  exact ;  while  the  emo- 
tional processes  of  civilized  human  selves  are  so  complicated  by  social 
interaction  as  to  be  no  longer  properly  emotions  in  the  biologic  sense, 
but  rather  concrete  expressions  of  the  affective  social  consciousness  at 
present  indefinite  and  involved. 

Analysis  discriminates  five  components  of  a  period  of  emotion — 
namely,  psychophysical  excitement;  various  feelings  and  their  con- 
comitant bodily  movements  and  strains ;  heightened  consciousness  of 
the  emotion's  object  as  in  relation  with  the  subject-agent;  often  a 
pleasant  or  an  unpleasant  tone  of  consciousness ;  and  at  times  increased 
self -reference. 

An  emotion  is  an  affair  invariably  of  both  a  mind  and  a  body,  prac- 
tically the  whole  of  the  latter  of  which  it  regularly  implicates :  it  is 
universally  dynamogenic. 

Contraction  of  the  extensor  muscles  is  more  pleasant  in  itself  than 
contraction  of  the  flexors,  and  this  fact,  together  with  the  general 
tendency  to  flexion  which  a  (naturally  unpleasant)  sudden  shock  pro- 
duces, perhaps  determined,  phylogenetically,  the  empirical  opposed 
mode  of  affective  bodily  function. 

A  bibliography  of  about  one  hundred  and  twenty-five  volumes 
bearing  on  the  subject  and  its  relations  may  be  found  at  the  conclusion 
of  the  monograph. 

THE  AUTHOR. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  543 

OPTICAL  ILLUSIONS. 

Raumdsthetik  und  geometrisch-optische  Tauschungen.  THEODOR 
LIPPS.  Zeitsch.  f.  Psych,  u.  Phys.,  XVIII.,  p.  405. 

Ueber  die  Natur  der  geometrisch-optischen  Tauschungen.  ST. 
WITASEK.  Zeitsch.  f.  Psych,  u.  Phys.,  XIX.,  p.  Si. 

Eine  einfache  physiologische  Erkldrung  fur  verschiedene  geome- 
trisch-optische Tauschungen.  E.EINTHOVEN.  Pfliiger's  Archiv, 
LXXL,  p.  i. 

Ueber  geometrisch-optische  Tduschung.  W.  VON  ZEHENDER. 
Zeitsch.  f.  Psych,  und  Phys.,  XX.,  p.  65. 

The  article  by  Lipps  is  written  in  reply  to  the  criticisms  made  by 
Heymans  in  his  review  of  Lipps'  book  on  optical  illusions.  The 
special  discussions  of  the  particular  figures  may  be  omitted  in  this 
brief  review.  They  are  in  part  new,  in  part  repetitions  of  the  earlier 
applications  of  the  principles  of  weight,  bounding  activity  and  the 
other  assthetical  factors  of  which  Lipps  has  made  use  in  all  his  writ- 
ings. 

On  the  more  general  question  of  the  nature  of  illusions,  Lipps 
again  defends  at  length  the  position  that  illusions  are  false  judgments, 
not  false  percepts.  They  arise  through  comparison,  and  it  is  dur- 
ing the  act  of  comparison  that  the  idea  based  on  the  percept — not  the 
percept  itself — is  so  modified  by  the  addition  of  the  assthetical  ideas 
that  it  is  changed  from  its  original  form  to  the  illusory  form. 

The  article  of  Witasek  takes  up  the  problem  with  which  Lipps 
deals,  and  attempts  to  show  on  theoretical  and  on  empirical  grounds, 
that  the  illusion  in  the  Zollner  figure,  and  presumably  those  in  the  other 
figures,  cannot  be  due  to  false  judgments,  but  must  be,  in  some  way, 
due  to  modifications  in  sensation  processes. 

The  paper  opens  with  a  comprehensive  review  of  the  recent  work 
on  geometrical  illusions  and  an  attempt  to  arrange  all  the  various 
theories  in  an  appropriate  scheme  of  classification.  All  processes 
containing  illusions  are  complete  only  when  they  close  with  a  judg- 
ment. The  judgment  is  based,  however,  on  percepts,  and  any  illusion 
may  be  due  either  to  the  percepts  on  which  the  judgment  is  based,  or  to 
the  method  of  dealing  subjectively  with  the  percept  during  the  act  of 
judging.  According  as  the  one  phase  or  the  other  of  the  complete 
process  is  selected  as  responsible  for  the  illusion  the  theories  may  be 
classed  as  judgment-theories  or  perception-theories.  But  perception 
is  the  result  of  combining  sensations.  It  is  possible,  therefore,  to  sub- 
divide perception-theories  into  these  which  attribute  the  illusion  to  the 


544  OPTICAL  ILLUSIONS. 

sensation  factors  and  those  which  attribute  the  illusion  to  the  synthetic 
process.  The  nature  of  the  synthetic  process  is,  however,  always 
predetermined  by  the  sensation  factors  entering  into  the  percept,  and 
so  the  sub-class  which  attributes  the  illusion  to  the  synthetic  processes 
is  of  small  importance. 

As  between  judgment-theories  and  perception-theories,  the  writer 
decides  on  the  following  theoretical  grounds  in  favor  of  the  latter. 
Judgments  may  be  acts  of  comparison  or  acts  of  classification.  But 
a  judgment  which  discovers  a  difference  between  two  percepts  must 
have  found  the  difference  in  some  actual  disagreement  present  in  the 
percepts  themselves,  otherwise  no  ground  for  judging  a  difference 
would  be  present.  An  illusion  always  involves  such  a  judgment  of 
difference ;  we  must  then,  according  to  the  above,  look  for  the  ground 
of  this  judged  difference  in  the  percept  rather  than  in  the  process  of 
judgment.  In  the  second  place,  a  false  classification  cannot  be  re- 
garded as  the  explanation  of  illusions,  for  it  is  not  a  question  here  of 
right  naming  or  right  grouping  under  remembered  categories :  but 
rather  it  is  a  question  of  the  continuity  of  a  perceived  category  (as,  for 
example,  whether  a  line  is  continuously  straight  or  not),  or  it  is  a  ques- 
tion of  the  correspondence  between  two  cases  of  the  same  general 
category. 

The  empirical  evidence  with  which  the  writer  confirms  his  theo- 
retical discussions  is  derived  from  two  groups  of  experiments  on  the 
Zollner  figure.  In  the  first  group  the  parallels  and  the  transverse 
obliques  were  drawn  on  two  separate  cards  and  united  binocularly 
into  a  single  figure.  At  the  beginning  of  experimentation  the  ob- 
server was  disturbed  by  binocular  rivalry,  but  after  practice  the  writer 
tells  us  that  he  was  able  to  overcome  this  enough  to  observe  the 
figures  for  considerable  intervals  without  rivalry.  The  illusion  was 
at  first  lost  entirely,  but  as  rivalry  was  gradually  overcome  it  reappeared 
and  steadily  increased  in  intensity.  At  last,  when  rivalry  disappeared 
entirely,  the  illusion  was  clearly  noticeable  but  somewhat  less  intense 
than  when  the  two  parts  of  the  figure  are  observed  in  the  ordinary  way. 
This  decrease  in  intensity  was  subjected  to  quantitative  determinations, 
and  proved  to  be  on  a  general  average  about  75  per  cent.  The  writer 
argues :  the  Zollner  figure  percept  formed  by  binocular  fusion  in  the 
manner  described  is  just  the  same  for  judgment  as  one  formed  in'  the 
ordinary  way.  The  decrease  in  intensity  of  the  illusion  which  was 
discovered  was,  therefore,  not  explicable  on  any  judgment-theory.  The 
decrease  must  be  attributed  to  the  change  in  the  conditions  of  percep- 
tion. Similar  results  leading  to  the  same  conclusion  were  secured  on 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  545 

other  figures,  though  there  is  no  detailed  report  of  the  other  experi- 
ments. 

The  second  group  of  experiments  deals  with  the  presence  of  un- 
noticed illusory  influences.  When  a  single  line  is  crossed  by  trans- 
verse obliques  the  illusory  effect  may  be  present,  though  it  is  too  small 
to  be  easily  judged.  The  method  of  the  experiment  was  as  follows : 
a  mercury  mirror  was  so  arranged  that  cards  could  be  placed  on 
edge  on  the  horizontal  surface  of  the  mirror.  The  cards  were  thus 
held  perpendicular  to  the  mirror.  Along  the  horizontal  edge  of  the 
cards,  just  at  the  surface  of  the  mirror,  were  drawn  horizontal  lines. 
From  these  horizontals  were  drawn  perpendicular  verticals.  The 
verticals  were  so  reflected  in  the  mirror  that  they  and  their  reflections 
seemed  to  form  continuous  straight  lines.  When  the  perpendiculars 
were  inclined  toward  the  horizontals,  or  when  they  seemed  so  in- 
clined, the  line  and  its  reflection  no  longer  seemed  continuous,  but 
seemed  to  form  an  obtuse  angle  at  the  surface  of  the  mirror.  There 
are  two  ways,  then,  of  judging  whether  the  angles  between  the  hori- 
zontal and  verticals  are  right  angles :  one  is  by  inspection  of  the  angle 
itself,  the  other  is  by  judgment  of  the  straightness  of  the  line  formed 
by  the  real  line  and  its  reflection.  If  transverse  obliques,  such  as 
those  used  in  the  Zollner  figures,  are  drawn  across  the  vertical,  it  will 
be  found  that  at  certain  angles  of  obliquity  a  really  vertical  line  will  be 
so  slightly  affected  by  the  transverse  lines  that  inspection  of  the  angle 
does  not  reveal  any  noticeable  diminution  of  the  right  angle,  while  ob- 
servation of  the  mirror  line  will  show  that  the  apparent  continuity  of 
vertical  and  reflection  is  destroyed.  The  writer  argues  that  the  illu- 
sory effect  must  have  been  present  in  the  inspected  right  angle,  but  it 
was  too  slight  to  be  noticed  under  those  relatively  unfavorable  condi- 
tions of  judgment.  There  may,  therefore,  be  a  perceptual  illusion 
even  when  there  is  no  illusion  of  judgment. 

The  binocular  experiments  are  quite  as  difficult  to  criticise  as  they 
were  to  perform.  The  fact  that  rivalry  was  overcome  by  practice  is 
a  result  of  importance  in  itself,  and  certainly  calls  for  some  further  in- 
vestigation. Other  investigators  have  been  unable  to  overcome  rivalry 
by  practice.  The  character  of  the  result  obtained  under  such  condi- 
tions will  always  be  questionable.  And  it  certainly  does  not  follow, 
as  against  Lipps,  for  example,  that  such  binocular  images  are  equal  in 
value  to  the  ordinary  Zollner  figures.  The  attention  must  be  seriously 
distracted  by  the  strain  of  overcoming  rivalry,  and  the  assthetical  effect 
will  naturally  be  reduced  proportionately.  Or,  in  terms  of  Filehne's 
hypothesis,  one  might  say  that  the  conditions  here  presented  are  fur- 


546  OPTICAL  ILLUSIONS. 

ther  removed  than  ever  from  ordinary  perspective  drawings,  and  the 
effect  of  tridimensional  associations  is  accordingly  much  weakened. 

The  mirror  experiments  are  ingenious  in  method  and  tend  to  es- 
tablish a  fact  of  importance.  That  the  reflected  image  does  not  enter 
as  a  disturbing  factor  is  not  clearly  made  out  by  the  writer. 

The  main  thesis  of  the  paper,  as  opposed  to  Lipps'  contention  that 
illusions  are  due  to  judgment,  opens  up  an  issue  on  which  it  seems  im- 
possible to  reach  any  generally  acceptable  opinion.  Conscious  and 
unconscious  judgments,  associations  of  all  degrees,  synthetic  percep- 
tual processes,  all  pass  so  easily  into  each  other  that  it  is  impossible  to 
draw  a  hard  and  fast  line  and  say  the  illusion  is  here  or  there.  If  a 
group  of  sensation  factors  is  such  as  to  invite  the  addition  of  this  or 
that  association  factor,  and  if  after  the  association  factor  has  been 
added,  the  subject  finds  his  judgment  biased,  then  there  is  undoubtedly 
a  sense  in  which  the  illusion  belongs  in  every  stage  of  the  process. 
Until  agreement  can  be  reached  on  the  more  fundamental  psycholog- 
ical questions  of  the  relations  of  sensations  to  percepts  and  of  percepts 
to  judgments,  there  will  always  be  disagreements  in  this  special  field. 
The  more  concrete  question  of  what  the  association  factor  is — putting 
aside  now  the  question  of  where  it  is  added — is  an  exceedingly  com- 
plex one.  Recent  discussions  have  all  tended  to  the  general  impres- 
sion that  such  factors  may  be  of  great  variety  even  in  a  single  illusion. 
The  writers  who  depend  on  movement,  those  depending  on  aBsthetical 
motives,  those  who  call  in  perspective,  and  finally  those  who  give  less 
generally  applicable  explanations  of  particular  illusions,  are  not  neces- 
sarily in  opposition  to  each  other,  though  the  criticisms  with  which 
these  writers  usually  introduce  their  work  indicate  a  general  lack  of 
agreement. 

Finally,  as  to  the  source  or  motive  of  the  association  or  other  cause 
of  the  illusion,  every  new  writer  points  out  some  new  possibility.  It 
is  at  this  point  that  we  may  introduce  the  last  two  articles  of  our  list. 
The  paper  by  Einthoven  offers  in  explanation  of  illusions  of  the  Miil- 
ler-Lyer  and  Poggendorff  types,  a  theory  which  is  allied  to  the  irradia- 
tion explanation  of  the  latter  figure  given  by  Helmholtz  (p.  708,  4th 
edit.).  Einthoven's  hypothesis  is  as  follows:  Most  of  the  points  of 
a  figure  cast  their  images  on  the  periphery  rather  than  on  the  center 
of  the  retina.  These  peripheral  images  are  made  up  of  diffusion  cir- 
cles, and  in  judging  of  lengths  and  directions  the  observer  is  guided  by 
the  greatest  amount  of  overlapping  of  the  diffusion  circles.  Thus  in 
the  Poggendorff  figure  the  diffusion  circles  lead  the  observer  to  locate 
the  point  of  contact  of  the  intercepting  parallels  and  the  intercepted 
oblique  within  the  acute  angle. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  547 

The  explanation  does  not  aim  to  apply  to  all  illusions,  but  only  to 
the  types  mentioned.  The  freedom  with  which  it  deals  with  indirect 
vision,  which  is  at  best  an  obscure  factor,  and  the  apparently  direct 
vision  involved  in  all  illusions,  furnish  the  criticisms  of  this  theory. 
Figures  seen  in  indirect  vision,  when  attended  to  at  all,  are  usually 
interpreted  in  terms  of  what  is  seen  when  the  image  falls  on  the 
fovea,  not  vice  versa. 

The  fourth  paper  is  a  deplorable  example  of  misdirected  effort. 
It  illustrates  in  a  very  striking  way  the  danger  of  making  hypotheses 
on  the  basis  of  some  one's  else  results.  How  it  could  ever  have 
escaped  the  attention  of  author  and  editors  that  the  facts  are  exactly 
reversed  is  hard  to  understand.  Such,  however,  is  the  case,  as  will  be 
seen  from  the  following :  The  main  thesis  of  the  paper  is,  that  the 
Poggendorff  illusion  can  be  explained  by  certain  facts  long  ago  discov- 
ered by  Volkmann.  Volkmann  took  two  lines :  one  fixed,  the  other 
capable  of  rotation  around  its  center.  He  allowed  the  observer  to  set 
them  so  that  they  seemed  parallel.  The  result  was  (and  it  is  quoted  in 
italics  by  von  Zehender)  that  '''•Die  Diameter  [that  is,  the  lines  referred 
to] tuelche  parallel  erscheinen  divergiren  ohne  Ausnahme  nach  oben."1 
That  is,  lines  which  seem  parallel  do  in  reality  diverge  at  the  top. 
Lines  which  are  in  reality  parallel  will  therefore  seem  to  converge. 
In  spite  of  this  well-known  fact,  von  Zehender  lays  at  the  foundation 
of  his  hypothesis  the  following  statement,  in  accordance  with  which 
all  his  figures  are  drawn,  and  on  the  validity  of  which  the  value  of  his 
theory  of  course  depends:  "  Die  beiden  Linien  A  und  B  in  vor- 
stehender  Figur  2  seien  die  ivirklichen  Parallellinien,  durch  deren 
Zwischenraum  die  Continuitat  des  Schrdgstriches  (a°/?°)  unterbro- 
chen  tvird.  Nach  den  Ergebnissen  der  Volkmann' schen  Versuche 
erscheinen  diese  beiden  Parallellinien  nach  oben  schwach  diver- 
gent" 2  The  explanation  which  follows  is  based  on  this  statement  and 
requires  no  comments. 

In  the  second  part  of  the  paper  the  writer  attacks  a  somewhat  dif- 
ferent problem  on  the  basis  of  certain  facts  first  reported  by  Oppel. 
The  problem  is  the  estimation  of  the  sizes  of  acute  angles.  If  a  ver- 
tical and  a  horizontal  line  are  so  drawn  that  they  intersect  at  right  angles 
in  the  middle  of  a  visual  field,  thus  dividing  the  field  into  rectangular 
quadrants,'  and  if  then  the  subject  is  asked  to  bisect  the  four  right 
angles  thus  formed,  it  will  be  found  that  the  lines  of  bisection  will 
always  be  placed  too  near  the  horizontal  lines.  That  is,  an  angle 
which  has  one  horizontal  edge  and  is  in  reality  small,  will  seem  equal 

ip.  70.  «P.  71. 


548       PSYCHOLOGY  AND    THE  INDIVIDUAL    TEACHER. 

to  an  angle  with  one  edge  vertical  which  is  in  reality  larger.  The 
small  angle  is  evidently  taken  for  larger  than  it  really  is,  while  the 
larger  angle  is  correspondingly  underestimated.  Here  is  von  Zehen- 
der's  statement :  "*  *  *  dass  {Spitze}  Winkel,  die  sick  mit  einem 
ihrer  Schenkel  der  verticalen  Richtung  anschliessen,  irrthumlich 
leicht  fur  grosser  gehalten  tverden  als  sie  sind,  wdkrend  ebensolche 

Wink e^  die  sick  mit  einem  ihrer  Schenkel  der  horizontalen  Richtung 
anschliesen,  ebenso  leicht  fur  kleiner  gehalten   iverden    als   sie  in 

Wirklichkeit  sind."  l 

If  the  conclusion  were  to  be  seriously  considered  in  spite  of  its 
wrong  statement,  it  might  be  objected  that  two  acute  angles  which  are 
parts  of  a  right  angle  are  hardly  suitable  examples  on  which  to  test  the 
attributes  of  acute  angles  in  general.  But  the  further  consideration  of 
the  paper  may  be  omitted. 

CHARLES  H.  JUDD. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY. 


Psychology  and    the    Individual    Teacher.     CHARLES    H.    JUDD. 

Journal  of  Pedagogy,  XII.,  136-148.     1899. 

The  present  article  is  a  defence  of  the  value  of  the  study  of  experi- 
mental psychology  to  the  teacher.  The  general  standpoint  is  found 
in  the  relation  of  the  teacher  to  the  child. 

Education  is  analyzed  to  be  in  its  broadest  sense  the  '  acquiring, 
arranging  and  applying  experiences/  For  such  activities  the  teacher 
is  not  necessary.  The  child  by  itself  will  learn  something,  however 
little,  and  instruction  becomes  necessary  only  that  the  individual  may 
economize  time  and  energy  in  the  acquirement  of  experience.  The 
teacher  has,  accordingly,  a  twofold  function  in  dealing  'with  the 
content  of  human  experience '  and  *  with  the  child  who  is  to  be  put 
into  possession  of  this  content.'  Material  and  method  are  alike  indis- 
pensable to  the  teacher.  With  the  first  psychology  claims  to  have 
nothing  to  do,  and  it  is  only  from  the  point  of  view  of  method  that 
the  science  can  pretend  to  be  of  advantage  to  the  teacher.  The 
author  assigns  to  the  teacher  the  function  of  training  the  child  to  look 
at  various  experiences  in  the  same  manner  as  does  the  adult,  and  he 
shows  that  it  is  the  plan  and  the  duty  of  psychology  to  indicate  how 
the  higher  level  may  be  best  and  most  easily  reached.  Experimental 
psychology  shows  the  teacher  how  to  analyze  material  for  the  better 
presentation  to  the  growing  mind,  and  it  makes  him  familiar  *  by 
analogy  with  the  relation  of  children's  mental  lives  and  their  external 

»P.  99- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  549 

conditions.'  Rules  for  the  teacher  to  obey  should  not  be  given  by 
psychology,  but  principles  should  be  established,  which  may  be  ap- 
plied under  varying  conditions.  This  last  factor,  variation,  brings 
out  most  clearly  the  value  to  the  individual  teacher  of  the  study  of 
psychology.  If  principles  are  understood,  and  some  facts  underlying 
the  principles  are  known,  new  facts  will  be  assimilated  and  arranged 
with  the  old,  and  methods  will  be  changed  accordingly.  With  fixed 
rules,  however,  new  conditions  find  the  teacher  unprepared  by  train- 
ing, and  method  becomes  forced  and  stilted. 

Finally,  what  the  teachers  need  "is  a  broad,  general  course  in 
psychology  to  bring  them  back  into  a  vital  sympathetic  relation  with 
the  practical  investigation  of  the  child's  mental  condition.  Such  train- 
ing places  the  individual  teacher  above  the  theory." 

SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ. 


University  of  Iowa  Studies  in  Psychology.     Edited  by  G.  T.  W. 
PATRICK.     Vol.  II. ,  pp.  163.     1899.     Iowa  City,  la.     $1.00. 

The  present  volume  includes  (i)  short  studies  by  Professor  Seashore 
on  the  Mtiller-Lyer  illusion,  a  material-weight  illusion,  localization  of 
sound,  acuteness  of  hearing,  pitch  discrimination  and  motor  ability; 
(2)  an  account  of  experiments  upon  the  analysis  of  the  perceptions  of 
taste;  (3)  a  discussion  of  some  phenomena  of  the  secondary  person- 
ality, and  (4)  the  description  of  two  new  pieces  of  apparatus. 

i .  The  first  series  '  have  been  selected/  we  are  told,  4  with  refer- 
ence to  the  need  of  data,  their  interrelations,  and  the  adaptation  of 
methods  and  apparatus/  Some  of  the  experiments  are  standard  ones, 
4  some  have  been  developed  by  other  investigators  and  are  here  devel- 
oped a  step  farther,  and  some  are  new.' 

(«)  Various  forms  of  the  Miiller-Lyer  illusion  were  used  to  note 
the  effect  of  the  illusion  under  varying  circumstances.  The  limiting 
lines  were  circles,  coins,  squares  and  angles.  It  was  found  that  the 
force  of  the  illusion  decreased  with  the  size  of  the  coin,  and  when,  in- 
stead of  coins,  circles  were  used  the  illusion  was  lessened.  Complex- 
ity of  outline  increases  the  force  of  the  illusion,  and  "  it  also  appears 
that  the  fainter  the  outline  is  the  more  the  eye  strives  to  follow  it." 
The  introduction  of  a  base  line  lessened  the  illusion,  and  the  limiting 
lines  greatly  affect  the  amount  of  the  illusion — circles,  13  %  ;  squares, 
i  %.  "A  vertical  distance  is  overestimated  when  compared  with  a 
horizontal  distance."  Practice  has  no  effect  in  increasing  or  diminish- 
ing the  illusion  if  the  subject  remains  in  ignorance  of  its  presence, 


55°  STUDIES  IN  PSYCHOLOGY. 

but  there  is  a  decrease  in  variability.  Women  are  more  suscep- 
tible to  the  illusion  and  are  more  variable  than  men.  Two  hundred 
children  that  were  tested  showed  double  the  effect  noted  on  adults,  but 
no  difference  was  noted  for  the  two  sexes.  There  seemed  to  be  no 
regular  decrease  with  growth  and  no  general  relation  with  mental 
ability  was  found. 

(3)  The  material-weight  illusion.  Each  of  three  cylindrical  blocks 
of  wood,  iron  and  cork,  of  the  same  size  and  of  uniform  weight,  was 
compared  with  standard  sets  of  blocks  and  the  estimation  of  weight 
was  noted.  Eight  determinations  were  made  by  each  subject  with 
each  block.  In  general  the  cork  and  the  wood  blocks  were  overesti- 
mated and  the  iron  block  underestimated.  The  illusion  is  about  18  % 
of  the  actual  weight,  and  is  about  the  same  for  women  as  for  men. 
The  essential  condition  of  the  illusion  is  that  the  preliminary  estima- 
tion of  the  weight  of  the  different  blocks  shall  be  wrong — 2*.  £.,  the 
subject  has  the  autosuggestion  that  the  cork  and  the  wood  blocks  are 
light  and  the  iron  one  heavy ;  but  when  lifted  the  cork  and  the  wood 
blocks  are  felt  heavier  than  was  supposed,  while  the  iron  block  is  much 
lighter  than  was  judged.  The  illusion  persisted  even  when  its  nature 
was  known,  but  not  so  strongly.  There  seems  to  be  no  variation  with 
age  or  sex. 

An  interesting  suggestion  is  made  that  it  may  be  possible  to  in- 
crease the  muscular  ability  by  means  of  the  illusion.  If  the  subject 
thinks  he  is  lifting  less  than  what  he  is  actually  lifting,  would  he  be 
as  greatly  fatigued  after  lifting  this  weight  one  hundred  times  as  he 
would  be  if  it  felt  heavier  ?  And,  in  like  manner,  may  not  the  maximum 
effort  be  increased  by  means  of  this  illusion?  A  few  experiments 
show  that  the  maximum  effort  was  affected  by  the  size-weight  illusion. 
1  '  Nearly  all  who  have  tried  it  can  lift  more  in  the  barrel  (a  flour- 
barrel)  than  in  the  half-peck  measure." 

(c)  Localization  of  sound  in  the  median  plane.  A  100  v.d. 
tuning-fork  connected  with  an  induction  coil  gave  sounds  in  three 
different  places  relative  to  the  observer — above,  right  and  left.  Strong 
and  weak  sounds  were  given,  and  sometimes  two  sounds  together. 
Estimations  were  made  of  the  distance  in  feet,  and  the  direction 
in  degrees  in  the  vertical  and  horizontal  planes.  There  was  a  tendency 
to  locate  the  sound  produced  overhead  as  '  upward  and  forward.'  Of 
the  fused  sounds  (right  and  left  together),  25%  were  thought  to  be  in 
front  of  the  vertical  plane,  73%  back  of  it  and  3%  in  it.  72%  of  the 
sounds  were  located  above  the  horizontal  plane,  12%  below  and  16% 
in  it.  The  grouping  of  the  subjects  into  three  classes  according  to  the 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  551 

•differences  in  acuteness  of  hearing  between  the  two  ears  showed  a 
marked  tendency  to  locate  a  median  sound  toward  the  side  of  the 
stronger  ear.  When  the  sounds  were  in  the  median  plane  and  their 
probable  location  unknown,  there  was  found  little  ability  to  locate 
them  properly.  The  ability  was  not  improved  when  the  probable 
location  was  known. 

(<£)  Hearing-ability  and  discriminative  sensibility  for  pitch.  In 
these  tests  great  individual  differences  were  noted.  The  average  hear- 
ing ability  of  the  men  and  women  was  found  to  be  about  equal.  The 
women,  however,  had  much  better  discriminative  ability  for  pitch.  No 
marked  relation  between  keenness  of  hearing  and  accuracy  of  pitch 
discrimination  was  noted.  The  keenness  of  hearing  of  children  seems 
to  increase  with  age,  and  likewise  the  pitch  discrimination.  Some  of 
the  differences,  however,  may  be  due  to  lack  of  understanding  on  the 
part  of  the  younger  scholars,  not  to  mention  the  error  of  drawing  con- 
clusions from  such  a  small  number  of  children  that  were  tested.  No 
relation  was  found  to  exist  between  pitch  discrimination  and  mental 
ability,  the  distribution  of  cases  seeming  to  be  a  chance  arrangement. 
It  is  concluded  that  "this  is  the  strongest  evidence  in  favor  of  the 
theory  that  the  discriminative  sensibility  for  pitch  depends  principally 
upon  the  natural  structure  of  the  end-organ  and  is  subject  only  to  small 
variation  with  education."  It  seems  to  the  reviewer  that  a  more 
extended  series  of  observations  must  be  made,  and  the  results  con- 
firmed ere  this  conclusion  can  be  safely  accepted. 

(e)  Motor  ability,  reaction  time,  rhythm  and  time  sense.  Fifty-six 
subjects  were  tested,  and  no  differences  were  found  between  men  and 
women  either  in  rapidity  of  movement  or  in  the  variation.  Reaction 
to  sound  gave  the  shortest  and  least  variable  times,  reactions  to  touch 
were  next  in  length  and  reactions  to  light  took  the  longest  time.  Dis- 
crimination time — i.  e.,  the  whole  time  less  the  simple  reaction  time — 
was  found  to  be  about  750-  and  the  choice  time  about  900-.  The  varia- 
tion in  each  of  these  series  was  about  equal.  A  free  rhythm  was  kept 
quite  constant  for  90  seconds  by  all  observers.  The  pressure  with 
which  the  rhythm  was  made  constantly  increased.  The  rhythm  estab- 
lished seemed  to  be  somewhat  determined  by  the  respiratory  and  cir- 
culatory processes.  In  a  regulated  rhythm,  the  subject  making  taps  in 
conjunction  with  a  mechanical  stimulus,  there  was  found  a  marked 
tendency  to  accelerate  the  movement,  and  the  men  seemed  to  be 
slightly  more  accurate  than  the  women.  Estimations  of  empty  time 
intervals  of  %,  ^,  i,  2,  5,  10,  20  and  40  seconds  by  the  method  of 
average  error  showed  an  overestimation  for  the  shorter  intervals  and 


55 2  STUDIES  IN  PSYCHOLOGY. 

(with  two  exceptions)  an  average  underestimation  for  the  longer  times. 
School  children  made  almost  correct  estimations  of  5  seconds,  but 
underestimations  of  the  10-  and  2O-second  intervals.  No  sexual  differ- 
ences were  noted  in  this  test. 

2.  In  this  article  Professor  Patrick  gives  an  interesting  and  valuable 
account  of  taste  experiments  with  an  anosmic  subject.  Popularly  the 
taste  of  any  substance  is  thought  to  be  conditioned  largely  by  taste 
sensations.  It  is  known,  however,  that  smell,  touch  and  sight  play 
large  parts  in  our  taste  perceptions.  The  analyses  of  the  influence  of 
each  of  these  factors  have  been  few  and  incomplete,  and  the  present 
study  will  be  gladly  welcomed.  The  several  theories  regarding  the 
qualities  of  tastes  are  noted.  The  theory  that  there  are  four  primary 
tastes,  which  by  combinations  and  fusions  produce  an  indefinite  num- 
ber of  other  tastes,  was  tested  with  the  anosmic  and  three  normal 
women  as  observers.  Mixtures  of  salt,  sweet,  bitter  (quinine)  and 
sour  (tartaric  acid)  solutions  were  used  to  discover  whether  such  mix- 
tures gave  new  qualitative  tastes  or  permitted  the  simple  constituent 
tastes  to  be  perceived.  The  latter  condition  was  found  to  be  true.  All 
the  observers  were  able  to  analyze  the  mixtures  with  a  considerable 
degree  of  accuracy.  After  considering  other  investigations  the  author 
concludes  "  that  the  hypothesis  which  seems  at  present  most  in  accord 
with  known  facts  is  that  there  are  only  four  taste  sensations  (possibly 
only  two)  ;  that  these  remain  distinct  in  consciousness,  not  subject  to 
fusion  or  mixture  with  each  other,  and  that  the  manifold  taste  percep- 
tions of  daily  experience  are  made  up  of  these  four  taste  sensations, 
with  their  grades  of  intensity,  and  sensations  of  smell,  touch,  tempe- 
rature, sight,  and  muscle  sensations."  Of  touch  and  smell,  the  more 
important  is  probably  touch,  while  sight  plays  a  more  important  part 
than  has  commonly  been  supposed.  In  any  analysis  of  tastes  various 
difficulties  confront  the  investigator  and  the  only  factor  easily  elimi- 
nated is  sight.  With  normal  subjects  smell  cannot  be  entirely  elimi- 
nated even  by  closing  the  nostrils,  while  it  is  almost  impossible  to  ex- 
clude touch  sensations.  In  complete  anosmia  results  may  be  obtained 
which  are  uninfluenced  by  smell  sensations,  since  these  are  wholly 
wanting.  The  observer  used  was  a  woman  peculiarly  suited  by  educa- 
tion for  such  experiments.  Blindfolded  she  was  unable  to  get  any  reac- 
tion or  sensation  from  over  twenty-five  substances  which  ranged  through 
the  nine  classes  of  smells  enumerated  by  Zwaardemaker.  Those  sub- 
stances which  could  be  determined  were  found  to  give  taste  sensations 
in  the  back  of  the  throat  or  to  produce  touch  sensations  in  the  mucous 
membranes.  The  observer's  taste  sensations  were  then  tested  with 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  553 

numerous  familiar  chemical  and  household  substances,  and  the  results 
were  compared  with  those  from  several  normal  persons.  The  anosmic 
was  found  to  be  less  active  in  judgment  of  salt,  quinine  and  acid  so- 
lutions. She  had  finer  discrimination  for  passive  touch.  It  was 
found  that  the  substances  that  could  not  be  recognized  by  any  of  the 
subjects  depended  entirely  upon  visual  sensations  for  their  supposed 
qualities,  those  recognized  by  the  normal  observers  evidently  de- 
pended upon  the  smell  qualities,  those  recognized  by  all  depended  upon 
taste,  touch  and  muscular  sensations,  while  those  recognized  only  by 
the  anosmic  depended  upon  differences  in  texture  (i.  £.,  in  touch  sen- 
sations). "  On  the  whole  the  experiments  confirm  the  hypothesis 
made  in  this  article,  and  while  not  diminishing  the  importance  which 
has  been  given  to  sensations  of  smell  in  the  '  tastes '  of  common  ex- 
perience, they  indicate  that  touch  and  muscle  sensations  play  an  unex- 
pectedly important  part."  The  article  brings  out  clearly  some  of  the 
unsolved  problems  of  the  relations  of  the  less  intellectual  senses  and  it 
will  undoubtedly  draw  the  attention  of  many  to  this  almost  virgin  field. 

3.  Professor  Patrick's  second  article  is  already  known  to  readers 
of  the  REVIEW,  from  which  it  is  reprinted  (Vol.  V.,  No.  6).     It  needs 
no  further  mention. 

4.  Two  new  pieces  of  apparatus  are  described  by  Dr.  Seashore. 
The  spark  chronoscope  is  a  pendulum  chronoscope  with  arrangements 
for  taking  records  by  the  graphic   method  while  the  pendulum  is  in 
motion.     The  following  excellences  are  claimed  for  the  new  instru- 
ment:  u  Accuracy,  adaptation  for  a  variety  of  connections,  soundless 
action,  direct  reading,  ease  and  permanence  of  adjustment,  and  quick- 
ness and  convenience  of  manipulation." 

The  audiometer  is  an  instrument  to  produce  variations  in  sounds 
and  to  measure  the  keenness  of  hearing.  The  new  feature  of  the  in- 
strument is  the  use  of  varying  sized  secondary  coils  of  an  induction 
apparatus  for  sending  currents  to  telephone  receivers.  The  larger  the 
secondary  coil — i.  e.,  the  greater  the  number  of  wire  turns — the  more 
intense  will  be  the  sound  produced.  The  intensities  vary  from  i  to 
1079.  Simplicity,  convenience,  accuracy,  constancy  and  size  are 
noted  as  some  of  the  merits  of  the  apparatus. 

The  whole  volume  is  interesting  and  instructive.  The  sole  criti- 
cism the  reviewer  would  make  is  that  the  first  series  of  articles  are 
1  minor  studies.'  None  of  the  problems  are  treated  exhaustively  and, 
as  Dr.  Seashore  rightly  suggests,  "  all  the  time  and  energy  might  well 
have  been  devoted  to  one  of  the  problems  or  a  part  of  one."  It  is 
hoped  that  the  researches  here  begun  will  be  completed  in  future 
issues  of  the  Studies.  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ. 


554  POPULAR  WISSENSCHAFTLICHE   STUD  IE. 

Magic,  Stage  Illusions  and  Scientific  Diversions,  including  Trick 
Photography.  Compiled  and  edited  by  ALBERT  F.  HOPKINS, 
with  an  Introduction  by  HENRY  RIDGELY  EVANS.  New  York, 
Munn  &  Co.,  1897.  Pp.  xii  -f  556,  400  illustrations. 
Spirit  Slate  Writing  and  kindred  Phenomena.  WILLIAM  E. 
ROBINSON.  New  York,  Munn  &  Co.,  1898.  Pp.  v  -f  146,  66 
illustrations. 

The  contents  of  the  work  on  *  Magic '  are  indicated  by  the  five 
books  into  which  it  is  divided,  which  are  as  follows:  (i)  Con- 
jurers' tricks  and  stage  illusions;  (2)  Ancient  magic;  (3)  Science 
and  the  theater;  (4)  Automatic  and  curious  toys,  and  (5)  Photo- 
graphic diversions.  There  is  also  a  useful  bibliography.  '  Slate 
Writing '  describes  most  of  the  phenomena  of  the  ordinary  spiritual- 
istic seance. 

The  books  are  primarily  intended  for  the  general  public  and  are 
well  suited  for  instruction  and  amusement.  The  boy  who  learns  these 
tricks  at  fourteen  has  a  pleasant  and  useful  employment,  and  is  less 
likely  to  be  a  spiritualist  or  Christian  scientist,  and  more  likely  to  be 
a  serious  student  of  physics  and  psychology  ten  years  later. 

But  the  books  also  deserve  notice  in  a  psychological  journal  and  a 
place  in  the  psychological  library.  Conjurers'  tricks  and  illusions 
offer  a  rich  and  almost  unworked  mine  for  the  study  of  the  psychol- 
ogy of  perception.  Suggestibility  and  the  psychology  of  the  crowd 
are  important  factors  in  the  success  of  such  exhibitions,  and  from 
this  point  of  view  they  offer  opportunity  for  research.  The  books 
should  certainly  be  read  by  those  interested  in  '  psychical  research.' 
The  numerous  and  varied  methods  by  which  ghosts  can  be  made 
to  appear  and  slate  writing  can  be  produced  should  lead  every  one  to 
doubt  his  senses  and  his  ingenuity  on  the  occasion  of  their  production. 
Lastly,  many  of  the  devices  used  for  the  production  of  illusions, 
etc.,  are  extremely  ingenious,  and  could  to  advantage  be  copied  in 
the  laboratory.  The  methods  of  chrono-photography,  though  scarcely 
deserving  to  be  classed  under  '  magic,'  are  of  special  interest,  as  these 
should  be  used  by  the  psychologist  for  the  study  of  both  perception 
and  movement.  J.  McK.  C. 


Kant  und  Helmholtz:    Popularivissenschaftliche  Studie.    LUDWIG 
GOLDSCHMIDT.     Leipzig,  Leopold  Voss.      1898.     Pp.  135. 
It  is  only  in  Germany  that  such  a  work  as  this  could  possibly  be 

considered  popular.    Indeed,  even  in  that  country  its  popular  character 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  555 

must  consist  chiefly  in  the  usual  quotations  from  the  '  Dichterphilo- 
soph '  Goethe,  for  not  only  is  the  thought  difficult,  but  the  style,  at 
least  in  parts,  is  excessively  stilted  and  artificial. 

The  author  is  evidently,  above  all,  a  mathematician,  and  the  work 
throughout  is  written  from  a  mathematical  standpoint.  It  is  divided 
into  three  parts.  The  first  describes  some  of  the  more  general  relations 
between  the  two  thinkers ;  the  second  is  devoted  to  an  exposition  of 
Kant,  particularly  of  doctrines  relating  to  mathematics;  the  third, 
which  is  the  largest  and  by  all  means  the  most  significant,  deals  with 
the  conflict  between  the  doctrines  of  space  represented  by  each  investi- 
gator. This  chapter  contains  an  interesting  discussion  of  the  modern 
non-Euclidian  geometry.  Toward  the  end  the  author  becomes  critic 
as  well  as  expositor  and  endeavors  to  defend  the  Kantian  doctrine  of 
the  a  priori  character  of  space  against  the  attacks  of  Helmholtz. 

The  chief  value  of  the  works  consists  in  the  exposition.  Its  diffi- 
culty lies  in  its  manner,  for  the  style  is  not  clear  and  the  author  has 
made  the  mistake,  unusual  in  a  German  work,  of  failing  to  subdivide 
his  material.  The  latter  fault  is  particularly  trying,  especially  in  a 
book  in  which  constant  re-orientation  is  an  absolute  necessity.  The 
author  is  very  evidently  a  master  in  his  field. 

F.  KENNEDY. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  COLORADO. 

A  Basis  for  Theory  of  Color- Vision.     WILLIAM  PATTEN,  PH.D. 

American  Naturalist,  Vol.  XXXII.,  No.   383,   Nov.,   1898.     Pp. 

832-857. 

Professor  Patten,  of  Dartmouth,  in  this  paper,  prepared  for  the 
Morphological  Society  meeting  of  December,  1896,  takes  a  step  in  the 
direction  which  is  apt  to  lead  to  a  theory  of  color-vision  more  satis- 
factory than  those,  based  chiefly  on  the  phenomena  of  the  process, 
which  we  now  have.  From  histological  research  made  more  than  a 
dozen  years  ago  (see  *  Mitt,  aus  Neapel.,'  1896)  and  since,  he  has 
reason  to  believe  that  the  eye  in  its  essential  structure  and  action  is 
somewhat  similar  to  the  ear.  He  investigated  the  visual  organs  of  the 
lower  orders,  chiefly  the  mollusca  and  arthropods,  and  as  a  result 
maintains  that  "the  rods  and  cones,  or  the  parts  corresponding  to 
them  in  the  lower  animals,  are  not  homogeneous,  but  fibrillated,  and 
that  in  a  number  of  invertebrates  the  fibrils  are  arranged  according  to 
their  length  in  accurately  graded  series,  and  in  such  a  position  that 
they  always  stand  at  right  angles  to  the  rays  of  light  that  fall  on  them. 
The  ether  waves  thus  vibrate  across  a  series  of  fibrils  of  different 


556  THE  ETHICAL    SYSTEM  OF  ADAM  SMITH. 

lengths."  The  structural  unit  of  the  eye,  then,  appears  to  be  a  fibril 
from  one  to  four  micro-millimeters  in  length,  many  hundreds  of  which 
may  be  present  in  each  rod  or  ganglion-cell.  It  seems  highly  proba- 
ble to  Dr.  Patten  that  this  structure  is  that  also  of  all  eyes,  however 
difficult  it  may  be  to  prove  the  fact  in  the  higher  animals  and  man. 

This  structural  hypothesis  is  applied  interestingly  to  the  various 
conditions  of  vision,  chromatic  and  achromatic,  and  it  appears  to  suit 
very  well.  Ten  illustrations  are  scattered  about  the  text. 

Is  is  interesting  to  note  that  the  main  thesis  of  this  paper  have  been 
recently  corroborated  in  general  terms  by  the  elaborate  researches  of 
Professor  Apathy  into  the  fibrillation  of  the  neurons  as  well  as  by  the 
work  of  several  histologists  upon  the  finer  structure  of  the  sensory  end- 
organs  and  of  the  neural  fabric  in  general.  The  probability  that  the 
retinal  elements  are  fibrillated  in  a  manner  proportional  to  the  em- 
pirical complexity  of  their  function  is  rendered  highly  presumable  by 
this  extended  work  here  rathei  too  briefly  reported. 

GEORGE  V.  DEARBORN. 
COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 

The  Ethical  System  of  Adam  Smith.     ETHEL  MUIR.     Cornell  Uni- 
versity.     1898.     Pp.  67. 

After  a  brief  statement  of  the  antecedent  4  moral  sense'  philoso- 
phers, the  writer  considers  the  ethical  system  of  Adam  Smith  in  two 
chapters ;  Sympathy ;  The  Nature  of  Conscience.  In  the  Conclusion 
this  division  is  adhered  to  and  reinforced  by  a  discussion  of  '  the 
function  of  reason  and  sense  in  The  Theory  of  Moral  Sentiments' 

With  Adam  Smith,  approval  and  sympathy  are  coextensive.  He 
endeavors  to  meet  Hutcheson's  objection  that  we  sometimes  do  ap- 
prove without  sympathizing,  by  positing  a  <  conditional  sympathy.' 
That  is,  in  all  cases  where  we  approve  without  sympathizing,  we  know 
we  should  sympathize  if  we  attended  sufficiently  to  the  impression. 
The  approval  is  grounded  in  this  ;  conditional  sympathy.'  Dr.  Muir 
accepts  this  view  and  goes  so  far  as  to  say  that  it  is  not  the  excep- 
tion (as  Adam  Smith  considered  it)  but  the  rule :  we  approve  not 
upon  sympathy,  but  upon  '  conditional  sympathy.'  If  the  character- 
istic quality  of  sympathy  be  considered,  the  recognition  of  myself  in 
another,  then  in  the  ensuing  sense  of  ownership  in  that  other,  I  can- 
not avoid  a  certain  emotional  warmth.  Why  this  emotional  quality 
accompanying  the  sense  of  ownership,  should  be  called  sympathy 
only  when  it  has  risen  to  a  certain  degree  it  is  difficult  to  see.  It 
appears  that  this  distinction  between  sympathy  and  '  conditional  sym- 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  557 

pathy '  is  a  remnant  of  the  ancient  logical  method  in  psychological 
procedure,  and  is  in  the  nature  of  things  uncalled  for.  On  the 
other  hand,  if  we  invariably  sympathize  when  we  approve,  it  cannot 
be  said  that  we  necessarily  approve  when  we  sympathize.  Often 
the  sympathetic  expression  is  so  shot  through  with  feelings  of  at- 
tachment, tenderness,  etc.,  that  the  individual  never  attains  to  the 
ethical  moment,  when  he  either  approves  or  disapproves.  His  sym- 
pathy is  the  spontaneous  expression  of  a  primitive  form  of  himself. 
Sympathy  that  is  also  approval,  has  freed  itself  from  these  trammels 
and  stands  as  a  moral  attitude.  It  is  the  expression  of  the  ethical  self. 

Dr.  Muir  considers  the  relation  of  Reason  to  Sympathy,  the  great 
problem  of  The  Theory;  and  believes  the  great  underlying  principle 
of  the  system  is  reason.  Unfortunately  we  are  not  told  whether  4  the 
judging  faculty '  or  « the  higher  reason '  is  intended.  Here  is  indeed 
a  great  obstacle  to  a  purely  expositional  and  critical  study  of  any  but 
the  most  modern  moralists.  Even  up  to  Adam  Smith's  time,  psychol- 
ogy had  not  yet  ripened  into  a  propaedeutic  to  ethics ;  and  terms  were 
largely  used  either  in  the  loose  popular  sense  or  left  altogether  unde- 
fined. In  the  relation  of  Reason  to  Sense,  the  writer  sharpens  the 
position  of  Adam  Smith  by  opposing  it  to  that  of  Kant.  "  Smith 
regards  reason  as  supreme,  and  sympathy  as  occupying  a  subordinate 
position  (p.  64)  *  *  *.  But  reason  is  dependent  upon  sympathy  for 
assistance  in  the  formation  of  its  judgments  and  its  rules.  For,  with- 
out sympathy  man  would  be  unable  to  enter  into  any  relations  where 
morality  would  be  possible  or  where  there  could  be  any  necessity  for 
the  moral  judgments  of  reason"  (p.  67) .  Adam  Smith  is  said  by  Dr. 
Muir  to  identify  conscience  with  reason;  again,  "  The  supreme  judge 
of  conduct  is  the  self  "  (p.  56) .  It  would  probably  be  a  correct  read- 
ing of  Adam  Smith's  theory  to  say  that  to  him  the  highest  good  is 
self -approbation.  This  the  writer  implies,  but  nowhere  very  clearly 
expresses. 

J.  W.  L.  JONES. 

PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


The  Applicability  of  Weber's  Law  to  Smell.  ELEANOR  ACHESON 
McCuLLOCH  GAMBLE.  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  X., 
1-62. 

Miss  Gamble's  main  problem  is  indicated  by  the  title  of  her  dis- 
sertation, and  the  evidence  she  offers  is  the  result  of  her  own  pains- 
taking experiments  in  this  difficult  and  somewhat  unattractive  field. 
Zwaardemaker's  olfactometer  was  employed  (in  which,  as  is  well- 


558  WEBER'S  LA  W  AND   SMELL. 

known,  the  intensity  of  the  odor  is  regulated  by  slipping  out  beyond 
the  end  of  a  glass  inhaling-tube  more  or  less  of  a  surrounding  cylinder 
containing  the  redolent  material) ,  and  there  were  used  some  twenty- 
six  odorous  substances  both  liquid  and  solid,  gathered  from  the  four 
quarters  of  the  globe.  In  the  main,  the  procedure  was  to  give  an  in- 
halation of  the  standard  intensity,  then  a  stimulation  clearly  stronger 
or  weaker,  whereupon  the  subject  moved  the  sliding  cylinder  until 
the  sensation  was  just  noticeably  different  from  the  standard.  If  the 
experiments  were  from  the  first  designed  to  test  Weber's  law,  it 
is  surprising  that,  of  so  many  performed,  so  few  were  carried  out 
without  changing  either  the  subject  or  the  substance  or  the  nostril  or 
the  method.  The  net  number  of  experiments  in  which  all  these  con- 
ditions remained  constant,  with  a  change  of  the  standard  intensity  alone, 
is  very  small ;  and  even  among  these  no  system  is  apparent  in  the 
variations  of  the  standard. 

Out  of  it  all,  however,  there  is  the  indication  that  for  two 
standard  intensities,  the  difference-threshold  often  makes  some  ap- 
proach to  what  Weber's  law  would  require,  although  striking  departures 
are  likewise  apparent.  For  the  two  standards  the  threshold  was,  on  an 
average,  something  over  one-third  for  the  lower,  and  over  one-fourth  for 
the  higher.  In  other  words,  the  value  came  closer  to  a  relative  constancy 
of  the  threshold  than  to  an  absolute  constancy,  and  consequently  (the 
author  argues)  it  may  be  said  to  be  evidence  in  favor  of  the  law.  This 
would  of  course  be  better  reasoning  if  we  were  sure  that  the  threshold 
must  show  either  one  or  the  other  form  of  constancy,  and  that  by  ex- 
cluding the  one  alternative  we  could  force  on  the  other :  but  whether 
these  alternatives  exhaust  the  field  is  one  of  the  matters  to  be  proved. 

As  regards  the  value  of  the  difference-threshold  for  the  different 
odors,  regardless  of  intensity,  it  was  found  to  lie  in  the  neighborhood 
of  one-third  in  a  large  proportion  of  cases,  and  to  be  fairly  constant 
for  the  different  odors  (as  against  Zwaardemaker) ,  except  for  some 
few  substances  when  the  apparatus  is  supposed  to  have  been  at  fault. 

The  author  is  aware  that  the  adjusting  of  the  tube  by  the  subject 
was  a  possible  source  of  error,  in  that  the  judgment  may  have  been 
influenced  by  the  feeling  of  the  distance  the  hand  was  moving,  as  well 
as  by  the  mere  variation  of  the  odor.  In  fact  the  error  from  this 
source  she  believes  to  have  been  one  of  the  main  causes  for  the  falling 
off  of  the  threshold  for  the  higher  intensities.  It  seems  to  me  that  this 
might  also  account  for  some  of  the  constancy  found  for  the  different 
substances.  Certainly  in  view  of  so  grave  a  source  of  error  the  rea- 
sons offered  for  not  having  the  experimenter  make  the  changes — that 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  559 

it  would  have  excluded  some  of  the  substances  used,  or  would  have 
made  the  procedure  more  laborious — seem  quite  inadequate.  Fewer 
experiments  concentrated  on  definitely  arranged  standard  intensities, 
with  fewer  subjects  and  fewer  substances,  could  well  have  given  clearer 
results  as  far  as  the  main  problem  was  concerned. 

The  good  historical  introduction  and  the,  at  times  perhaps,  too 
minute  account  of  the  preparation  of  materials,  with  all  the  difficulties 
involved,  should  be  read  by  any  one  who  proposes  work  in  this  line. 

G.  M.  STRATTON. 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA. 

Psychology  for    Teachers.     By  C.  LLOYD  MORGAN.     New  York, 

Charles  Scribner's  Sons.     Pp.  xi  -f  240. 

In  writing  this  book  the  author  evidently  intended,  not  so  much  to 
present  a  system  of  psychology,  as  to  point  out  the  more  important 
traits  the  teacher  must  take  account  of  to  produce  a  rounded  mental  re- 
sult. It  is,  of  course,  a  nice  matter  in  such  a  case  to  determine  just 
how  much  psychology,  and  of  what  sort,  can  best  be  employed ;  and 
some  will  undoubtedly  feel  that  Mr.  Morgan  might  well  have  appor- 
tioned his  space  in  a  different  may.  In  fact,  with  the  exception  of  the 
last  two  chapters,  of  which  more  will  be  said  later,  the  best  things  in 
the  book  are  not  given  the  systematic  chapter  discussions,  but  are  tucked 
away  in  scattered  paragraphs. 

The  author's  psychology  has  the  strong  points  of  the  great  English 
tradition — an  emphasis  on  association  and  language  and  personal  ex- 
perience and  the  constant  testing  of  conceptions  thereby ;  and  yet  with 
no  slighting  of  the  motor  and  emotional  and  volitional  functions  of 
mind.  But  teachers  will  look  in  vain  for  their  old  friend  '  appercep- 
tion,' nor  will  they  find  a  single  reference  to  a  nerve-cell  or  a  4  higher- 
center.'  The  book  may  thus  seem  a  trifle  tame  to  those  who  take 
their  summer  recreation  at  the  psychological  laboratory  and  are  at 
home  in  child  study  and  the  central  nervous  system.  And  yet,  even 
though  the  author  treats  all  these  things  as  if  they  were  not,  he  has 
written  in  a  most  helpful  way  because  of  his  grasp  of  the  real  purpose 
of  education  and  of  the  deeper  structure  of  the  mind. 

Like  many  a  good  story,  however,  the  book  does  not  carry  one 
along  at  first.  The  somewhat  labored  distinctions  between  sensation 
and  *  sencept ' — an  unpardonable  word — percept  and  concept,  percep- 
tion and  conception,  fail  to  arouse  much  interest,  and  may  discourage 
many  a  conscientious  reader  who  feels  that  he  can  not  go  on  unless  he 
masters  these.  Less  abstractions  here,  and  more  reliance  on  illustra- 


5^0  PSYCHOLOGY  FOR    TEACHERS. 

tions  drawn  from  the  field  of  illusion,  which  the  author  neglects  ei> 
tirely,  would  perhaps  have  served  the  purpose  better.  Association, 
although  given  an  entire  chapter,  is  kept  well  within  bounds,  and  not 
made  an  all-explaining  principle ;  so  that  he  can  perhaps  the  more  read- 
ily believe  not  only  in  the  uses  of  interest  but  also  in  those  of  drudgery 
and  of  sheer  resolve.  Expression  is  only  touched  on  here  and  there,  and 
then  with  more  regard  for  its  social  value  than  for  its  reactive  and  clari- 
fying effect  upon  the  mind.  It  is  a  great  means  of  self-mastery  and  in 
teachers'  psychology  should  have  a  prominent  place.  The  intellectual  as 
well  as  the  moral  use  of  skill  in  hand- work  and  games,  which,  of 
course,  is  one  phase  of  expression,  is,  however,  briefly  but  forcibly 
stated  by  the  author.  If  mention  were  to  be  made  of  scant  justice 
done  to  other  subjects  pedagogically  important,  there  is  certainly  not 
given  to  imitation  and  suggestion  generally  the  treatment  that  the  pres- 
ent interest  might  be  expected  to  invite. 

The  different  threads  of  the  mental  life  are  kept  well  together. 
One  does  not  have  that  constant  view  of  various  strands  at  once, 
which  a  writer  like  Hoffding  gives;  but  for  the  teachers'  purpose 
the  same  end  is  approached  by  some  good  images — the  spirited  horses 
and  coach  and  driver  (the  provisional  figure  for  the  different  sides  of 
mind)  having  finally  to  be  consolidated  into  a  centaur  to  express  the 
true  relation,  and  again  where  he  says  that  "  the  cognitive  aspect  of 
experience  *  *  *  gives  the  form  and  grouping  of  the  picture  of  con- 
sciousness ;  the  emotional  aspect  *  *  *  gives  the  color  and  tone  of  the 
picture."  But  best  of  all  is  his  happy  insistence  on  the  l  margin '  and 
1  background '  of  consciousness,  with  their  vital  relation  to  all  that 
comes  within  the  focus  of  attention.  The  art  of  teaching  is  not 
merely  to  provide  for  a  suitable  play  and  clearness  of  this  intellectual 
fixation-point,  but  to  get  the  right  things  '  inextricably  woven  into  the 
mental  background,'  and  to  lay  up  there  stores  of  '  strength  and  wisdom 
and  emotional  prejudices  of  a  goodly  human  kind.'  What  a  bene- 
fit if  this  mere  phrase  from  the  book — '  emotional  prejudices  of  a 
goodly  human  kind  '  (quoted  by  the  author  from  Miss  Simcox) — could 
itself  become  inextricably  interwoven  into  every  teacher's  mental  back- 
ground !  But  the  book  is  temperate  throughout,  and  there  is  no  over- 
rating of  feeling  or  of  will  at  the  expense  of.  the  more  purely  intellec- 
tual processes,  as  if  the  child  could  be  stanch  and  steady  irrespective 
of  his  intellectual  insights. 

Education,  on  the  contrary,  is  seen  by  the  author  to  be  a  many- 
sided  affair,  and  no  cheap  and  ready  formula  is  offered  for  its  attain- 
ment. It  is  not  to  be  reached  without  doing  justice  to  the  intellectual 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  561 

and  emotional  and  volitional  sides  of  life,  and  so  directing  these  that 
the  child  is  put  in  rapport  with  the  great  spiritual  possessions  and 
ideals  of  mankind.  He  must  be  brought  face-to-face  with  facts 
and  thus  make  his  conceptions  tally  with  them,  but  he  must  de- 
velop his  powers  of  appreciation  and  of  sociability.  The  closing 
chapters  on  '  literature '  and  on  ;  character  and  conduct  '  ought  to 
be  read,  even  if  all  the  rest  be  skipped.  The  teacher  is  shown  that 
in  some  way  the  inner  warmth  of  art  and  especially  of  literature  must 
be  imparted;  and,  in  so  doing,  knowledge  of  the  work — its  intel- 
lectual aspect — must  not  be  confused  with  the  peculiar  aesthetic  enjoy- 
ment. Education  also  means  the  growth  of  character — the  adoption 
of  the  social  aim,  not  in  a  spirit  that  is  sentimental  and  visionary, 
but  with  an  active  interest  in  small  and  unimposing  social  gains 
wherever  possible.  It  means  finally  the  cultivation  of  the  religious 
attitude,  as  distinguished  from  special  forms  of  belief.  The  author 
is  fully  aware  that  these  are  the  most  delicate  and  searching  parts  of 
the  teacher's  work,  and  are  to  be  accomplished  less  by  direct  instruc- 
tion than  by  a  fine  spiritual  contagion.  The  teacher's  own  sympathies 
and  appreciations,  here,  rather  than  his  precepts,  are  what  count. 

G.  M.  STRATTON. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA. 

Ein    einfacher   Apparat   zur   J3  estimmung   der   Empfindlichkeit 
von    Temperaturpunkten.     F.  KIESOW.      Philos.   Stud.,  XIV., 

4>  589-590- 

Dr.  Kiesow  here  describes  an  apparatus  for  finding  heat  and  cold 
spots.  Heretofore  a  difficulty  has  been  experienced  in  having  to  use 
instruments  that  would  not  keep  an  even  temperature  or  whose  tem- 
perature could  not  readily  be  altered.  The  present  instrument  seems 
to  have  overcome  the  latter  difficulty  but  not  the  former. 

The  apparatus  consists  of  a  hollow  cone  in  which  are  two  pipes 
with  leads  from  bottles  containing  hot  and  cold  water  respectively. 
The  temperature  is  regulated  by  raising  or  lowering  one  of  the  bottles, 
so  that  the  hot  or  cold  (as  the  case  may  be)  water  flows  towards  the 
other.  This  permits  a  ready  change  in  the  temperature  of  the  instru- 
ment, but  the  arrangement  for  constancy  is  awkward.  The  constant 
cooling  of  the  instrument  necessitates  a  continual  shifting  of  the 
bottles  to  keep  the  liquid  always  of  the  same  temperature. 

An  electric  apparatus,  though  more  expensive,  might  be  devised 
to  overcome  all  the  difficulties. 

SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ. 

COLUMBIA  UNIVERSITY. 


562  EXPERIMENTAL. 

L'Asymetrie  sensorielle.     J.  J.  VAN  BIERVLIET.    Brussels,   Hayez. 

1897.     Pp.  43.     (Repr.  fr.  Bull,  de  1'Acad.  roy.  de  Belg.,  Vol. 

XXXIV,  1897.) 

This  paper  is  an  attempt  to  correlate  right-  and  left-handedness 
with  a  functional  preponderance  of  the  same  side  in  other  senses.  The 
evidence  is  purely  experimental.  One  hundred  subjects,  mostly  uni- 
versity students,  were  tested  in  the  muscular  sense,  hearing,  vision  and 
touch.  The  muscular  test  consisted  in  pulling  with  each  hand  a  load 
attached  by  a  string.  The  load  raised  by  the  stronger  hand  remained 
unchanged  and  served  as  standard.  In  the  first  test,  the  two  loads 
were  started  equal,  and  the  one  judged  heavier  was  gradually  decreased 
till  it  seemed  equal  to  the  standard.  Another  test  was  then  made,  with 
an  ascending  series  of  the  variable  weight.  In  all,  three  descending 
and  three  ascending  tests  were  made  on  each  subject,  each  with  four 
different  standards  (500,  1000,  1500  and  2000  gm.).  Of  the  100  sub- 
jects, 78  were  right-handed  and  22  left-handed  according  to  this  test 
— none  were  *  ambidextrous.'  With  but  two  or  three  exceptions,  the 
results  when  averaged  were  remarkably  uniform,  the  ratio  being  about 
450  gm.  with  the  weaker,  to  500  gm.  with  the  stronger  hand,  which- 
ever it  might  be ;  the  same  ratio  held  for  the  other  weights. 

For  the  sense  of  hearing,  two  shot-fall  apparatus,  almost  exactly 
similar,  were  made,  and  each  enclosed  in  a  sound-proof  box,  with  a 
tube  running  out  to  one  ear  of  the  subject.  The  two  balls  were 
dropped  in  rapid  succession,  and  the  subject  compared  the  intensity  of 
the  sounds.  For  right-handed  subjects  the  right  ear  was  taken  as 
standard,  and  the  height  of  the  left  shot  varied  till  the  two  sounds 
seemed  equal ;  the  procedure  was  reversed  with  left-handed  subjects. 
Five  series  each  were  taken  with  increasing  and  decreasing  intensity 
and  averaged  together.  After  a  number  of  cases  of  partial  deafness 
were  thrown  out,  the  variations  of  the  rest  were  all  in  the  same 
direction  as  the  muscular  tests,  and  the  ratio  almost  exactly  the  same. 

The  visual  tests  consisted  in  measuring  the  distance  at  which  type 
of  a  certain  size  could  be  read.  Considerable  difficulty  was  experi- 
enced from  the  various  minor  defects  of  vision,  and  many  cases  were 
out  of  all  relation  to  the  normal.  Rejecting  these,  the  difference 
between  the  two  eyes,  in  almost  all  the  rest,  was  again  in  the  same 
direction  and  nearly  the  same  ratio. 

Finally,  the  tactile  sense  was  tested  by  means  of  Weber's  sensory 
circles.  The  author  does  not  describe  any  means  used  to  secure  ex- 
actly corresponding  regions  of  the  two  hands.  Ten  tests  each  were 
made  in  ascending  and  descending  series.  The  right  hand  was  found 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  563 

to  have  a  lower  threshold  than  the  left  in  right-handed  persons,  and 
vice  versa,  and  the  ratio  was  about  the  same  as  before. 

In  the  muscular  tests  the  ratio  in  question  was  9.00  to  10  (right- 
handed)  and  9.02  to  10  (left-handed)  ;  in  the  auditory  tests  9.10  to  10 
for  each;  in  the  visual,  9.08  to  10  and  9.04  to  10  respectively;  and  in 
the  tactile,  9.06  to  10  and  8.93  to  10  respectively.  The  persistency  of 
this  fraction  (y9^)  seems  remarkable,  and  should  be  submitted  to  further 
test ;  if  verified,  it  will  rank  with  the  fractions  determined  for  Weber's 
Law,  or  outrank  them  in  importance.  The  uniform  preponderance 
of  the  same  side  through  the  four  senses  tested  is  also  notable.  The 
author  declares  his  belief  that  it  points  to  an  anatomical  rather  than  a 
physiological  basis  for  right-  and  left-handedness. 

HOWARD  C.  WARREN. 
PRINCETON  UNIVERSITY. 


ETHOLOGY. 

Ethology:    Standpoint,    Method,     Tentative  Results.      THOS.     P. 

BAILEY,  Jr.,  University  of   California.     University  Press,   1899. 

Pp.  30. 
Bibliographical  References  in  Ethology.     THOS.  P.  BAILEY,  Jr., 

University  of    California  Library  Bulletin,  Vol.   13.     University 

Press,  Berkeley,  1899.     Pp.  25. 

This  account  of  a  new  undertaking  in  the  University  of  California 
is  deserving  of  more  than  a  passing  notice.  Here  is  a  psychologist,  a 
philosopher,  and  a  student  of  education,  devoting  all  his  energies  to 
the  study  of  character.  His  title  is  inspiring :  *  Associate  Professor 
of  Education  as  Related  to  Character.' 

At  the  same  time  it  is  a  commentary  on  the  present  condition  in 
higher  educational  circles.  Such  a  title  would  not  be  possible  if  our 
educational  leaders  recognized  that  the  whole  problem  of  education  is 
one  of  character. 

At  the  same  time  we  feel  obliged  to  protest  against  that  view  of 
psychology  which  finds  it  necessary  to  create  a  new  science  in  order  to 
make  the  study  of  character  legitimate.  True,  the  idea  that  psychol- 
ogy is  unsympathetic,  mechanical,  lifeless,  is  abroad  in  the  land,  but 
that  is  not  the  view  of  our  best  psychologists,  with  whom  the  cry  of 
*  Back  to  real  life,'  is  strong  and  clear.  We  can  assure  our  author 
that  there  are  many  psychologists  who  will  welcome  ethology  as  it  is 
here  outlined,  as  a  new  chapter  in  their  own  science,  and  that  there 
are  yet  more  who  believe  the  sole  aim  of  all  branches  of  psychology  to 
be  the  better  understanding  of  mind  with  a  view  to  its  development. 


564  GENETIC  AND  EDUCATIONAL. 

This  certainly  is  the  belief  which  has  given  psychology  its  place  in 
our  colleges,  and  the  one  permitting  the  life  of  all  psychology  to-day 
in  our  own  country.  Experimental  psychology,  particularly,  has 
grown  upon  it. 

At  the  same  time  there  may  be  no  harm  in  giving  this  group  of 
problems,  the  most  important  in  all  psychology,  a  special  name,  and 
assigning  them  to  a  special  department  in  our  University  at  least. 
There  are  people  who  will  grant  the  reality  of  character  and  the  im- 
portance of  its  study  when  they  see  it  rechristened  with  a  new  Greek 
name.  We  expect  help  from  Ethology  in  the  University  of  California, 
but  should  not  like. to  see  a  chair  of  Ethology  in  every  college.  We 
do  hope  that  the  work  itself  will  be  felt  in  every  course  in  psychology 
in  the  country. 

If  the  author  finds  it  difficult  to  describe  his  new  methods,  the  ten- 
tative results  and  the  many  lines  of  effort  it  certainly  is  impossible  to 
reproduce  them  here,  to  say  nothing  of  giving  the  criticism  for  which 
he  asks. 

The  perspective  drawing  of  a  cave,  with  surface  lines  indicating 
lines  of  character  growth,  and  cross  sections  showing  successive  stages 
of  character  development  in  the  race  and  in  the  individual,  and  also 
corresponding  stages  in  education  from  the  Kindergarten  to  the  Uni- 
versity, is  a  helpful  way  to  bring  before  the  eye  many  of  the  elements 
which  enter  into  character.  It  is,  however,  impossible  to  represent  in 
this  way  the  relative  importance  of  the  different  elements. 

Perhaps  a  place  might  be  made  for  the  influence  of  personality 
and  for  authority.  This  latter  is  suggested  by  the  remark  of  a  psy- 
chologist in  a  mission  field — an  excellent  place  for  character  study,  by 
the  way — that  in  their  schools  the  discipline  counted  for  more  in  char- 
acter building  than  did  all  the  secular  and  religious  instruction.  At 
the  corresponding  point  in  this  diagram  we  see  only  the  spontaneous 
development  of  boy  nature  under  the  influence  of  the  various  studies. 

C.  B.  BLISS. 

GENETIC,  EDUCATIONAL  AND  SOCIAL. 

Psychologische  Analyse  der    Thatsache  der   Selbsterziehung.      G. 

CORDES.    Berlin,  Reuther  u.  Reichard.    1898.    Pp.54.    M.  1.20. 

For  the  material  of  his  enquiry  Dr.  Cordes  turns  to  the  experiences 
of  his  own  life,  stripping  these  as  far  as  possible  of  all  that  makes 
them  personal  and  unique,  and  dealing  only  with  those  aspects  which 
are  typical  of  the  process  in  all  men.  The  author's  interest  being  a 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  565 

psychological  one,  it  lies  as  far  from  his  purpose  to  enquire  into  the 
metaphysical  possibility  of  self-education,  on  the  one  hand,  as  to  make 
an  ethico-pedagogical  application  of  his  results  on  the  other. 

By  '  education '  is  to  be  understood  the  activity  of  one  person — 
the  teacher — which  exerts  upon  another — the  pupil — such  enduring  in- 
fluence that  his  mental  processes  and  outward  behavior  realize  an 
ideal  of  thought  and  conduct  existing  in  the  mind  of  the  teacher. 
Under  this  conception  one  can  speak  of  self -education  only  by  analogy, 
which  is  yet  a  real  analogy,  since  here,  too,  an  activity  is  found  which 
exerts  an  enduring  influence  upon  our  psychical  processes  in  conse- 
quence of  ideals  which  exist  in  consciousness.  To  indicate  the  con- 
ditions and  elements  of  this  process  is  the  object  of  the  monograph, 
which  can  here  be  only  briefly  summarized. 

At  the  outset  two  aspects  of  the  matter  present  themselves :  first, 
as  to  the  presuppositions — the  psychical  material  and  means — of  self- 
education;  and  secondly,  the  processes  themselves  which  it  involves. 
The  presuppositions,  putting  aside  disputes  as  to  freedom  or  its  con- 
trary, and  the  possibility  of  self-observation,  involve  three  things 
which  correspond  respectively  to  the  personality  of  the  pupil,  the  ideals 
of  the  teacher,  and  the  educating  influence  which  mediates  between 
them.  The  whole  complex  fact  of  past  experience  and  present  char- 
acter gives  the  first,  in  which,  without  following  the  detailed  analysis 
of  the  writer,  are  to  be  separated  the  individual  psychical  acts  and  the 
personal  disposition,  whether  resulting  from  these  acts  or  due  to  in- 
heritance. In  the  second  place  there  must  be  set  over  against  this, 
another  order  of  psychical  experiences,  non-existent  as  yet  for  the  prac- 
tical subject,  which  consists  of  the  ideals  into  which  the  present  psychi- 
cal processes  are  to  be  transformed.  These  ideals,  derived  from  the 
lives  of  other  persons  either  through  indirect  suggestion  or  generalized 
observation,  become  effective  through  the  strong  emotion  with  which 
they  are  conceived,  an  emotion  depending  upon  a  comparison  of  the 
two  orders  of  experience  with  respect  to  their  worth,  and  a  resultant 
higher  valuation  of  the  ideal.  The  third  of  these  presuppositions  is 
the  will  for  which  this  ideal  order  of  experiences  becomes  a  motive. 
The  preceding  judgment  of  worth  is  an  effectless  reflection  which  is 
energized  by  the  will  as  a  process  of  choice. 

The  second  consideration  is  as  to  the  actual  processes  of  self-edu- 
cation. If  one  defines  self-education  as  the  shaping  of  the  personal 
disposition  so  that  each  individual  life-experience  shall  correspond  to 
our  highest  moral  valuation,  then  the  general  desire  for  betterment 
must  be  supplemented  by  a  definite  transformation  of  concrete  indi- 


566  GENETIC  AND  EDUCATIONAL. 

vidual  impulses  if  it  is  to  be  realized.  This  education  takes  place  in 
three  directions :  First,  with  respect  to  intellectual  processes,  the 
whole  order  of  ideas,  concepts  and  judgments  is  to  be  shaken  up  and 
transformed ;  and  these  ideas  and  concepts,  which  possess  each  its  par- 
ticular emotional  overtone,  must  be  stripped  of  this  overtone  and  united 
to  a  new  quality  of  feeling.  Secondly,  with  respect  to  emotional  pro- 
cesses there  are  to  be  revalued  under  the  criterion  of  the  ideal  order  of 
experience  the  sensuous  feelings,  or  emotional  overtone  of  sensations, 
common  feeling,  by  which  is  understood  that  fusion  of  inner  and  outer 
sensations  in  which  our  general  well-being  or  ill-being  is  expressed, 
and  the  passions,  through  which  not  only  are  the  ideas  intensified,  but 
they  together  with  the  will-processes  are  modified  and  transformed. 
Thirdly,  with  respect  to  the  will-process  itself  self-education  exerts  a 
three-fold  influence.  First,  in  regard  to  the  will's  reaction  upon  mo- 
tives, education  is  expressed  in  a  more  swift  and  decisive  process ; 
secondly,  in  regard  to  activity  in  general,  it  is  expressed  in  an  increase 
in  the  total  will-power  or  energy  of  the  subject;  and  thirdly,  in  regard 
to  the  voluntary  direction  of  the  attention,  it  is  characterized  by  a 
greater  control  over  the  objects  which  shall  occupy  consciousness.  The 
short  bibliography  which  Dr.  Cordes  appends  to  his  clear  and  detailed 
analysis  would  be  of  value  if  it  were  more  precise.  A  general  refer- 
ence toWundt's  Grundriss  der  Psychologic  orNahlowsky's  Gefiihls- 
leben  is  too  much  like  a  wave  of  the  hand  to  help  in  one's  literary 
orientation. 

ROBERT  MACDOUGALL. 
HARVARD   UNIVERSITY. 

Uber  Willens-  und  Characterbildung  auf  physiologisch-psycholog- 
ischer  Grundlage.  JULIUS  BAUMANN.  Berlin,  Reuther  u. 
Reichard.  1897.  Pp.  86.  M.  1.80. 

In  suggestive  contrast  with  the  introspective,  theoretical  work  of 
Dr.  Cordes  (summarized  in  the  foregoing  note)  stands  this  mono- 
graph of  Professor  Baumann,  of  Gottingen.  The  former  is  a  subjec- 
tive analysis  of  individual  personal  experience,  the  latter  an  objective 
study  of  the  education  of  the  will,  the  result  of  a  life  of  personal  ob- 
servation as  a  teacher  in  the  schools  of  Germany.  The  laws  which 
Dr.  Baumann  sets  down  grew  up  as  working  principles  in  his  teaching, 
and  are  intended  to  have  a  direct  practical  bearing.  They  are,  the 
author  tells  us,  a  concise  re-statement  of  ideas  already  set  forth  both 
in  his  Handbook  of  Ethics  (1879),  and  in  his  Introduction  to  Peda- 
gogy (1890),  supported  by  the  most  recent  results  of  physiological 
and  pathological  psychology. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  567 

We  must  distinguish  between  the  will  as  theoretic  choice  and  the 
will  as  psychological  activity ;  in  the  latter  sense  it  is  expressed  in  a 
series  of  reactions  and  depends  upon  a  psychophysical  mechanism. 
With  the  development,  educability  and  derangements  of  this  will  Pro- 
fessor Baumann  here  deals.  The  author  refers  briefly  to  the  physical 
basis  of  mental  life  in  general  as  indicated  by  the  localization  of  brain 
functions,  influence  of  drugs,  effects  of  fatigue,  and  the  like  facts, 
then  proceeds  to  a  detailed  statement  of  the  physical  relations  which 
condition  the  will-functions,  for  the  evidence  of  which  he  turns  to  the 
various  phenomena  of  pathological  will-conditions,  abulias,  amnesias 
and  automatisms.  It  is  through  these  interferences  with  the  psycho- 
physical  mechanism  by  which  the  attitudes  of  the  practical  individual 
are  expressed,  interferences  which  pervert  or  inhibit  his  desires,  that 
the  conditioning  of  the  will  upon  these  processes  is  brought  most 
forcibly  to  our  notice.  The  undeveloped  will  is,  then,  that  psycho- 
physical  organism  in  which  the  orderly  connection  of  these  parallel 
activities  has  not  been  established  upon  the  basis  of  practical  experi- 
ence, and  the  pathological  will  is  that  in  which  the  customary  syn- 
thesis of  perception  or  desire  with  motor  reactions  has  been  interrupted. 
The  educability  of  the  will  depends  upon  the  possibility  of  organizing 
and  extending  this  system  of  coordinated  physical  and  psychical  activ- 
ities, and  the  development  of  it  consists  in  the  actual  process  of  trans- 
forming the  elementary  impulses  and  powers  into  such  an  orderly 
series  of  desire-  and  choice-fulfilling  acts.  In  the  child  only  the 
negative  conditions  of  a  willing  subject  are  given.  The  vague  dis- 
comfort is  there,  the  vague  desire,  but  the  stimulation,  whether  per- 
ipheral or  central,  does  not  call  forth,  as  in  the  adult,  definite  and 
adapted  reactions.  The  capacity  for  reaction  and  the  impulse  toward 
original  activity  exist  in  the  child  but  are  not  yet  coordinated.  In 
this  coordination  consists  the  education  of  the  child- will.  Professor 
Baumann  next  proceeds  to  an  analysis  of  the  chief  psychological  laws 
involved  in  the  process  of  volitional  education  and  the  training  of  char- 
acter, with  especial  reference  to  the  development  of  moral  qualities. 

But  first,  since  the  healthy  will  involves  a  good  mental  tone  and 
sound  physical  state,  a  fundamental  condition  of  its  training  lies  in 
constant  care  for  the  health  and  attention  to  exercise,  rest  and  refresh- 
ment, both  bodily  and  mental.  The  development  of  the  will  is  two- 
fold, corresponding  to  the  active  and  receptive  aspects  of  the  person- 
ality: first,  increase  in  the  precision  and  energy  of  the  will  in  those 
activities  which  we  already  possess;  and  secondly,  extension  of  the 
will-activity  to  new  objects  and  interests.  The  primary  law  of  the 


568  EVOLUTION  OF  MORALITY. 

first  form  is  practice ;  the  activity  in  process  of  acquisition  is  estab- 
lished only  through  repitition,  and  the  activity  once  under  control  of 
the  will  must  never  be  allowed  to  lapse  wholly  from  use.  Spontaneous 
imitation  the  author  is  inclined  to  reject  as  an  element  in  the  educa- 
tion of  the  will,  on  the  ground  that  it  is  only  the  realization  of  a 
tendency  already  existing,  and  is  strictly  limited  in  its  functions. 
Voluntary  attention  is  emphasized  as  a  moment  in  the  process  parallel 
to  the  factor  of  repetition.  To  these  must  be  added  the  influence  of 
success  and  failure  in  effort,  indirect  training,  example,  emulation  and 
the  like,  as  factors  in  the  development  of  the  will.  All  these  laws 
which  condition  the  form  of  the  individual  will-act  enter  also,  with 
their  combinations,  into  the  formation  of  character,  that  permanent 
disposition  towards  organized  systems  of  activities  which  the  indi- 
vidual act  tends  to  beget,  and  from  which  reciprocally  it  springs. 

Professor  Baumann's  monograph  closes  with  a  consideration  of  the 
pathology  of  mental  and  moral  impulses,  and  a  discussion  of  the 
theories  of  Beneke  and  Herbart  concerning  the  education  of  the  will. 

ROBERT  MACDOUGALL. 
HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 

L?  Annee  Sociologiqtie.    E.  DURKHEIM.    Deuxieme  Annee  (1897-98). 

Paris,  Alcan,  1899.     Pp.  vi  +  596,  10  fr. 

The  two  volumes  now  issued  of  this  annual  make  a  capital  start. 
They  are  similar  in  scope  to  the  Annee  Psychologique,  having  a  Part 
I.  devoted  to  Memoires  originaux,  and  Part  II.  given  up  to  Analysis 
of  books  and  articles  published  between  July  ist  of  one  year  and  June 
3Oth  of  the  next.  Sociology  is  understood  in  the  widest  sense.  The 
original  memoirs  are,  for  the  most  part,  outside  of  our  scope,  but  we 
may  call  attention  to  Professor  Simmel's  remarkable  paper,  in  the  first 
Annee,  on  4  The  Persistence  of  Social  Groups,'  now  translated  in  the 
Amer.Jour.  of  Sociology,  March,  May,  1898.  It  contains  much  psy- 
chological matter  on  the  different  phases  of  so-called  <  honor.' 

J.  M.  B. 

L?  Evolution  mentale  cJiez  les  Animaux.  CH.  LETOURNEAU.  Re- 
vue de  1'  Ecole  d'  Anthropologie  de  Paris,  Vol.  9,  V.,  15  May, 
1899.  Pp.  137-152. 

This  is  a  lecture  delivered  as  an  introduction  to  a  course  on  the 
Evolution  of  Morality,  at  the  School  of  Anthropology  of  Paris.  In 
method  and  content  the  article  is  on  purely  evolutionary  lines,  and  is 
divided  into  seven  topics,  as  follows  :  The  Problem  of  Consciousness, 


NEW  BOOKS.  569 

Motivity,  The  Genesis  of  Desire,  Sensation,  Feelings  and  Emotions, 
Intelligence  and  Reason,  and  Domestication  and  Civilization.  As  a 
sort  of  summary  of  the  development  briefly  traced  under  these  heads, 
we  may  quote  his  words  thus : 

"At  first,  in  the  protozoa,  we  see  only  confused  movements  of  the 
protoplasmic  substance  (Amoeba).  Then,  in  the  lowest  radiates,  the 
nervous  tissue  begins  to  differentiate,  to  control  the  movements  of  the 
contractile  substance,  and  even  to  be  aware  of  sensations  and  to  pre- 
serve a  trace  of  them  (Medusa).  Among  the  higher  radiates  this 
nervous  memory  is  perfected  and  from  this  there  result  complicated 
reflex  acts,  which  seem  combined,  coordinated,  for  the  attainment  of 
an  end,  while  being  almost  certainly  unconscious.  Organic  and 
psychic  progress  is  accentuated  among  the  molluscs,  where  one  sees 
plainly  appear  the  organs  of  special  sense,  already  well  developed  in 
the  cephalopods.  In  the  higher  molluscs  the  relative  perfection  of 
the  sense  organs  and  of  the  nervous  system,  which,  however,  as  yet 
ganglionic,  authorizes  admission  of  the  existence  of  a  well-developed 
nervous  consciousness,  of  distinct  sensations,  of  simple  feelings,  and 
even  of  an  intelligence  still  rudimentary.  Finally,  in  the  divisions  of 
the  vertebrates,  and  particularly  among  the  first  of  the  mammals,  the 
existence  of  mentality  very  analogous  to  that  of  man  can  scarcely  be 
doubted." 

Dr.  Letourneau  considers  thought  4  a  complex  product  of  nervous 
consciousness,'  while  reason  he  judges  to  be  nothing  else  than  "  coor- 
dinated application  of  the  elements  of  nervous  consciousness  to  partic- 
ular and  desired  ends." 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 


NEW  BOOKS. 

Psychologic    mit   Anwendung  auf  Erziehung  und    Schulpraxis. 

KARL    HEILMANN.      Leipzig,    Diirrschen    Buchhandlung,    1899. 

Pp.  86. 
DAnnee  Psychologique.     A.  BINET.     5me  Ann£e.     Paris,  Schleicher 

Freres,  1899.     Pp.  902.      15  Fr. 
Worterbuch    der    Philosophischen    Begriffe    und  Ausdrucke.     R. 

EISLER.     Vierte    Lieferung.     Berlin,  -Mittler,    1899.     Pp.    289- 

384- 

Sensationi    vibratorie.      N.     R.    D'ALFONSO.      Seconda    edizioae 
Roma,  Soc.  Dante  Alighieri,  1899.     Pp.  39. 


57°  NEW  BOOKS. 

Through  Nature  to  God.     JOHN   FISKE.     Boston  and  New  York, 

Houghton,  Mifflin  &  Co.,  1899.     Pp.  xv  -f-  194. 
Spinoza  and  Schopenhauer.     SAMUEL  RAPPAPORT.     Berlin,   Hey- 

felder,  1899.     Pp.  148. 
Nouvelles  Esquisses  de  la   Philosophie  Critique.     A.   SPIR.     Paris, 

Alcan,  1899.     Pp.  30 -f  147. 
I  Sogni,  Studi  Psicologici  e  Clinici.     SANTE  DE  SANCTIS.     No.  17 

in  Pic.  Bibl.   di   Sci.  Moderne.     Turin,  Frat.  Bocca,  1899.     Pp. 

390.     5L. 

An  extremely  well  written  and  interesting  account  of  dreams  by  a 
competent  psychologist.  The  successive  chapters  sum  up  adequately 
the  literature  of  the  subject  and  give  bibliographies  under  the  several 
heads  :  /.  £.,  '  Dreams  and  Mysticism,'  '  Methods  of  Studying  Dreams,' 
'  The  Dreams  of  Animals,'  '  Of  Children,'  '  Of  the  Aged,' '  Of  Adults,' 
'Of  the  Neuropathic '  (of  several  different  classes),  'Of  Criminals,' 
'  Dreams  and  Emotions,'  'Dream  Psychoses  in  Health  and  Disease,' 
'  Psychophysics  of  Dreaming,'  '  The  Marvellous  in  Dreams.'  An 
English  translation  would  probably  serve  a  good  purpose.  J.  M.  B. 
The  Philosophical  Theory  of  the  State.  B.  BOSANQUET.  London 

and  New  York,  Macmillans,  1899.     Pp.  xviii  +  342.      $3.25. 
The  Races  of  Europe ;    a  Sociological  Study.  W.  Z.  RIPLEY.  With 

A  Selected  Bibliography  of  the  Anthropology  and  Ethnology  of 

Europe  (a  supplementary  volume  published  by  the  Trustees  of  the 

Boston  Public  Library).     New  York,  Appletons,  1899.     Pp.  xxix 

+  624. 

This  work  comprises  Professor  Ripley's  Lowell  Lectures  which 
have  already  attracted  much  attention  in  their  serial  publication  in 
the  Popular  Science  Monthly. 
La  Dissolution  opposee  a  V Evolution  dans  les  Sciences  physiques  et 

morales.     A.  LALANDE.     Paris,  Alcan,   1899.     Pp.  viii  -f-  492. 

7  fr-  50- 
Aberglaube  und  Zauberei  von  der  dltersten  Zeiten  an  bis  in  die 

Gegenwart.     A.  LEHMANN.     Deutsche  Ausgabe  von  Dr.  PETER- 
SEN.     Stuttgart,  Enke,  1898.     Pp.  xii  +  556. 
The  Value  of  Religious  Facts.     J.   H.  WOODS.     New  York,  Dut- 

ton,  1899.     Pp.  165.     $i. 
The  Physical  Nature  of  the    Child  and  how  to    Study  it.     S.   H. 

ROWE.     New  York  and  London,  Macmillans,  1899.     Pp.  xiv  -f 

207.     $i. 
Friedrich  Nietzsche,  Aphorismes  et  fragments  choisis.     H.   LICH- 

TENBERGER.     Paris,  Alcan,  1899.     Pp.  xxxii-f  181. 


NOTES.  571 


NOTES. 

THE  circular  announcing  the  Fourth  International  Congress  of 
Psychology  has  appeared.  It  may  be  had  by  addressing  M.  Pierre 
Janet,  Secretaire  general,  21  rue  Barbet-de-Jouy,  Paris.  The  con- 
gress— of  which  we  hope  to  make  fuller  announcement  shortly — is  to 
be  held  in  Paris,  Aug.  20-25,  1900. 

OTHER  congresses — to  be  held  in  connection  with  the  Exposition — 
which  may  interest  psychologists  are :  that  for  Philosophy,  Aug.  2-7 
(see  circular  of  organization  issued  in  the  Revue  de  Met.  et  de  Morale, 
July,  1899:  another  circular  is  in  preparation  giving  an  international 
4  Committee  of  Patronage'  for  this  Congress),  Secretaire  M.  Xavier 
Leon,  39  rue  des  Mathurin,  Paris;  that  for  *  Instruction  in  the  Social 
Sciences,'  second  half  of  July  (having  French  organization  and  an 
international  4  Committee  of  Honor'),  Secretaire  M.  Dick  May,  22 
rue  Victor  Masse;  that  on  the  4  History  of  Religions,'  September 
3-9,  Secretaires  MM.  J.  Reville  and  Leon  Marillier,  Sorbonne,  Paris. 

WE  regret  to  record  the  death,  on  June  i4th,  of  Professor  N. 
Grote,  of  the  University  of  Moscow,  the  distinguished  Russian  psy- 
chologist and  philosopher.  Professor  Grote  was  editor  of  the  Vo- 
prosii  philosophii  and  President  of  the  Psychological  Society  of 
Moscow.  The  death  is  also  announced  (on  June  i3th)  of  Professor 
Nourrisson,  the  well-known  academician  and  historian  of  philosophy. 

PROFESSOR  A.  C.  ARMSTRONG,  JR.,  of  Wesleyan  University,  is 
to  be  abroad  the  coming  year  on  4  Sabbatical '  leave,  wintering  prob- 
ably at  Oxford.  The  department  will  be  in  charge  of  Associate-Pro- 
fessor Dodge. 

WE  have  received  the  first  numbers  of  two  new  journals,  the 
Revue  de  Morale  Sociale,  edited  by  L.  Bridel,  of  Geneva  (Paris, 
Giard  et  Briere,  quarterly,  10  fr.)  and  the  Zeitschrift  fur  Padagog- 
ische  Psychologie^  edited  by  F.  Kemsies,  of  Berlin  (Berlin,  Walther, 
bimonthly,  M.  8). 

MESSRS.  WILEY  &  SONS,  New  York,  announce  a  work  entitled 
Statistical  Methods  with  special  reference  to  Biological  Variation, 
by  Dr.  C.  B.  Davenport,  of  Harvard  University. 

THE  prospectus  of  the  Jaresbericht  iiber  Neurologie  und  Psy- 
chiatrie  has  reached  us.  It  is  to  be  edited  by  Professor  Mendel,  of 
Berlin,  with  a  corps  of  distinguished  collaborators.  The  first  volume 
will  be  devoted  to  the  literature  of  1897.  Authors  are  requested  to 


572  NOTES. 

send  books  and  reprints  for  analysis  to  the  publisher  (S.  Karger,  Ber- 
lin, N.W.  6,  Karl  str.,  15).  A  section  devoted  to  Psychology  will  be 
in  charge  of  Professor  Ziehen,  of  Jena. 

WE  note  the  appearance  of  the  German  translation  of  Professor 
James'  Will  to  Believe. 

WE  learn  also  that  Professor  Sanford's  Course  in  Experimental 
Psychology  is  being  translated  into  French  by  Dr.  Schinz,  and  Pro- 
fessor Baldwin's  Story  of  the  Mind  into  French  and  Italian. 

DR.  W.  O.  MONTAGUE,  of  Harvard,  has  been  appointed  Instructor 
in  Logic  in  the  University  of  California. 

PROFESSOR  BALDWIN  has  been  given  a  half  year's  absence  from 
Princeton  to  see  the  Dictionary  of  Philosophy  and  Psychology 
through  the  press  in  England.  He  intends  to  sail  on  September  i9th 
and  wishes  all  the  American  contributions,  proofs,  etc.,  to  be  in  his 
hands  in  the  first  week  of  September  (address  until  September  loth, 
Buzzards  Bay,  Mass.).  His  London  address  is  care  Macmillan  & 
Co.,  Limited,  St.  Martin's  St.  His  courses  at  Princeton  will  be  in 
the  hands  of  Professor  Warren. 


AFTER  the  appearance  of  this  issue  all  communications  for  the 
'editor,  books  for  review,  etc.,  should  be  sent  to  Professor  J.  McK. 
Cattell,  Garrison-on-Hudson,  N.  Y. 


VOL.  VI.     No.  6.  NOVEMBER,  1899. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW. 


ON  THE  VALIDITY  OF  THE  GRIESBACH  METHOD 
OF  DETERMINING  FATIGUE.1 

BY  DR.  JAMES  H.  LEUBA, 
Bryn  Maivr  College. 

In  the  opinion  of  many  psychologists  the  results  published 
by  Griesbach  and  his  imitators,  Dr.  Ludwig  Wagner  and  Dr. 
Vannod,  were  highly  surprising.  Experience  with  the  aesthesi- 
ometer  leads  easily  to  the  opinion  that,  although  the  ability  to 
discriminate  simultaneous  touch  sensations  might  very  well  be 
altered  by  fatigue,  it  would  be  impossible  to  measure  its  influ- 
ence without  taking  into  account  many  other  factors.  That, 
without  regarding  these  other  factors,  the  dependency  of  the 
discrimination  sensibility  on  fatigue  could  be  ascertained  safely 
and  easily  enough  to  make  of  '  the  method  of  Griesbach  a  prac- 
tical means  of  determining  and  of  comparing  the  degree  of 
fatigue  ' 2 — a  method  applicable  to  the  school  problem,  for  in- 
stance— went  against  what  many  thought  to  be  a  legitimate  in- 
terpretation of  their  experience. 

Griesbach's  paper,  coming  at  the  timely  moment  when  the 
fatigue  question  was  the  topic  of  the  day  in  many  a  teacher's 
circle,  attracted  a  great  deal  of  attention,  and  speedily  found 
imitators  among  teachers  apparently  delighted  to  have  at  last  in 

1  The  larger  part  of  the  experiments  here  recorded  were  performed  at  Heidel- 
berg, Germany,  in  part  in  the  Laboratory  of  Professor  Kraepelin,  and  with  the 
improved  Griesbach  cesthesiometer  belonging  to  the  said  laboratory.  Our 
thanks  are  due  to  Professor  Kraepelin  for  his  assistance,  and  to  Dr.  and  Mrs. 
Lindley,  who  acted  as  subjects  during  the  experiments  carried  out  in  Germany, 
and  generally  cooperated  with  the  writer. 

2  Wagner's  '  Unterricht  u.  Ermiidung,'  p.  112. 


574  JAMES   H.    LEUBA. 

hand  an  easy  means  of  settling  the  bitter  discussion  of  school 
fatigue.  The  results  of  Drs.  Wagner  and  Vanned  confirmed 
the  claim  of  the  initiator,  and  to-day  the  method  is  widely  ac- 
cepted as  filling  the  need  of  the  teacher  and  of  the  physician  for 
a  comparative  determination  of  fatigue-states. 

The  writer  undertook  last  winter  a  series  of  experiments 
which  were  to  be  the  beginning  of  an  exhaustive  investiga- 
tion into  the  various  factors  influencing  the  discrimination 
of  simultaneous  touch  sensations  :  the  temperature  of  the  sur- 
rounding atmosphere  and  of  the  parts  affected ;  the  blood  circu- 
lation ;  the  emotional  state,  etc.  As  the  preliminary  measure- 
ments clearly  contradicted  the  claims  of  the  authors  cited,  it  was, 
for  several  reasons,  thought  wise  to  publish  them  without  wait- 
ing longer  for  the  completion  of  a  work  already  several  times 
postponed. 

The  point  at  issue  in  what  follows  is  not  so  much  the  correla- 
tion of  fatigue  with  discrimination  sensibility,  as  the  validity  of 
the  aesthesiometric  method  for  the  determination  of  fatigue. 

The  measurements  on  which  we  base  our  conclusions  ex- 
tended over  14  days  and  include  some  6,000  separate  judgments. 
They  were  taken  at  Heidelberg  on  three  persons  whom  we  shall 
designate  by  the  numerals  I,  II,  III.  The  writer  was  one  of 
the  subjects ;  his  measurements  were  taken  by  Dr.  Lindley. 
To  these  data,  about  180  threshold-determinations  were  added 
at  Bryn  Mawr,  involving  about  2,000  separate  judgments,  ob- 
tained from  six  young  women  students  at  Bryn  Mawr  College, 
by  three  post-graduate  students  who  had  been  prepared  by  a 
good  deal  of  practice.1  Dr.  Lindley  and  myself  had  both 
worked  before  with  the  aesthesiometer ;  nevertheless,  to  insure 
from  the  start  dexterous  use  of  the  instrument,  tests  were  taken 
during  two  days  before  record  was  made  of  them. 

At  Heidelberg  we  used  the  instrument  carefully,  guarding  as 
far  as  possible  against  the  known  sources  of  errors,  such  as  cold 
spots,  momentary  hyperaesthesia  easily  induced,  in  some  persons 
at  least,  by  focusing  the  attention  on  one  bit  of  the  skin ;  the 
interference  of  after-images  and  the  partial  anaesthesia  caused 

1  Miss  M.  Hussey,  Miss  G.  Locke  and  Miss  N.  Wood,  to  whom  I  desire  to 
express  my  thanks. 


DETERMINING   FATIGUE.  575 

by  too  frequent  and  too  rapid  touches.  We  found  it  necessary 
to  allow  about  6  minutes  for  the  determination  of  the  thresholds 
of  one  person  taken  at  two  places  ;  this  included  frequent  in- 
tervals for  the  skin  to  return  to  its  normal  state.  We  proceeded 
as  Griesbach  had  done  :  the  threshold  for  one  and  that  for  two 
points  were  successively  found  for  the  forehead  —  along  a  line 
running  horizontally  across  the  middle  of  the  forehead  —  and 
for  the  ball  of  the  thumb.  The  place  was  marked,  but  we 
took  care  to  avoid  putting  the  points  always  on  the  same  spots. 
The  threshold  for  one  point  was  sought  by  a  gradual  de- 
crease ;  that  for  two  by  a  gradual  increase  of  the  distance  be- 
tween the  points  of  the  instrument.  Each  threshold  determina- 
tion involved  usually  about  eight  judgments,  sometimes  more,  es- 
pecially when  after  having  said  <  one,'  the  subject  fell  back  to 
two,  although  the  distance  had  been  further  reduced.  In  a  case 
of  this  kind  the  figure  put  on  record  was  the  one  indicating  the 
longest  distance  at  which  the  two  points  were  definitely  felt  as 
one. 

In  order  to  draw  a  parallel  between  the  discrimination  sen- 
sibility and  fatigue,  it  is  evidently  not  sufficient  to  have  a 
measure  of  the  former  ;  we  should  also  have  a  measure  of  the 
latter.  To  establish  the  discrimination  curve  and  then  to  in- 
terpret its  ups  and  downs  in  fatigue  terms  with  one's  own  feel- 
ing, or  the  probable  fatigue  effect  of  a  lesson  in  geometry  or  in 
singing  as  the  only  guide,  is  evidently  a  '  pis  aller.'  If,  in  this 
respect,  we  did  not  do  much  better  than  the  investigators  in  ques- 
tion, we  had  at  any  rate  the  production  of  fatigue  under  better 
control  than  was  the  case  with  the  school  boys  and  apprentices 
tested  by  them  ;  we  could  so  choose  the  objects  of  our  attention 
and  so  direct  it  that  a  relatively  constant  increase  of  fatigue 
took  place.  Moreover,  we  were  enabled  to  measure  the  amount 
of  work  done  for  two  half  hours  daily  during  six  days.  This 
was  afforded  us  by  the  experiments  carried  on  at  the  time  by 
Dr.  Lindley,  experiments  in  which  all  three  of  us  participated.1 
They  were  so  conditioned  and  controlled  that  the  number  of 


account  of  these  experiments  tending  to  determine  the  influence  of 
periods  of  rest  of  various  lengths  on  the  amount  of  work  performed  in  a  given 
time,  is  to  be  published  in  Kraepelin's  Psychologische  Arbeiten. 


576  JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 

additions  performed  in  the  half  hour,  or  in  the  hour,  could  be 
taken  as  the  measure  of  the  mental  work  done.  Unfortunately 
for  us,  the  limitation  of  the  adding  to  two  daily  half  hours  re- 
duces seriously  the  value  of  this  control.  To  submit  oneself  to 
the  conditions  required  by  such  experiments,  if  they  were  to 
last  for  several  hours  during  three  or  four  days,  would  be  an 
ordeal  beyond  the  endurance  of  most  men. 

In  the  measurements  taken  at  Bryn  Mawr  the  method  pur- 
sued was  the  one  used  by  Wagner :  the  threshold  was  gradually 
approached  from  two  extreme  distances,  one  evidently  too  great 
and  the  other  clearly  too  small ;  the  former  distances  alternating 
with  the  latter.  This  procedure  has  the  advantage  of  keeping 
clearly  before  the  subject's  mind  the  qualitative  differences  be- 
tween what  he  is  to  call  'two'  and  what  he  is  to  call  'one,' 
while  the  other  practice  delays  the  recognition  of  '  twoness '  and 
of  '  oneness.' 

We  begin  with  the  experiments  performed  at  Heidelberg. 
The  three  subjects  noticed  early  in  the  investigation,  as  other  ob- 
servers had  done  before  them,  that  the  passage  from  '  oneness ' 
to  'twoness'  is  through  a  sensation  of  length :  the  touch  looses 
its  pointed  quality  and  acquires  that  of  a  line  gradually  stretch- 
ing until  it  breaks  in  the  middle,  thus  producing  two  spatially 
disconnected  sensations.  A  similar  transformation  takes  place, 
but  in  the  reverse  order,  when  the  threshold  for  one  is  sought. 
It  was  therefore  agreed  to  keep  answering  '  one '  however  ex- 
tended the  sensation,  as  long  as  the  break  had  not  occurred. 

In  the  following  accounts  of  our  experiments  we  shall,  for 
the  sake  of  directness  and  concision,  refrain  from  entering  into 
details  which,  interesting  though  they  might  be  to  the  psychol- 
ogist, do  not  bear  directly  upon  our  immediate  object.  For  the 
same  reason  we  shall  give  only  as  many  of  the  curves  we  have 
obtained  as  appears  to  us  necessary  to  establish  our  opinion. 

Fig.  I  will  enable  the  reader  to  compare  the  oscillations  of 
the  discrimination  sensibility  during  the  three  days  of  severe 
mental  work  with  those  having  taken  place  during  three  days 
of  rest.  Each  curve  is  the  resultant  of  three  daily  curves.  The 
full  lines  are  the  rest  curves,  the  dotted  ones  the  fatigue  curves. 
The  time  at  which  the  measurements  were  taken  is  indicated  by 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE. 


577 


the  figures  along  the  axis  of   ordinates.     The  thresholds   are 
given  in  millimeters. 

We  kept  at  work  from  9  or  9  115  A.  M.  until  i  P.  M.  with- 
out other  interruption  than  the  one  occasioned  by  the  taking  of 
the  tests  at  10  145  or  n  o'clock.  During  the  afternoon  we  had 


. 

(7 


y  is. 

4  17. 

vS  /6' 

XX.  *s- 

*$  n. 

^  13. 

^  /i- 

V^  /'/. 


/s. 
n. 

16. 
15. 
/f. 
13. 
12. 
11. 


9.  m~n  te.  1.  2rs:f.  f.  6.  7.  s.  &. 


0.  10. 11.  u.  1.  2. 3.k.  £6.7. 8.  9. 


.  10. 11. 12. 1. 2.  3.  4-.  S.  6,  2  8.9. 


* 


v§     47. 
1     <* 

^•^s. 
H. 


.  10.11.12.1.  2  3.  ±  5.  6.  7.  S. 


JJ 


17. 
16: 

15. 


12.1.  2.3.  k  £  6.7  89. 


11. 
10. 


.  6.  7.  8.9. 


17. 


. 

12. 
11 
W. 


$.  10.  It  '2.  /  2. 3..  k  5.6.7.  S.  9. 


578 


/O. 

8. 
7 
6. 
S. 


JAMBS  H.   LBUBA. 
III. 


to. 
9 

S. 


S. 


.  /.  2.3.  #  S.  <?.  7  #.  $• 


giO.  II.  Ill,  2.  J.~ 


7.  8.  9. 


so. 

4 

S. 

7 

6. 

5. 


/O 

& 

3. 
7. 
6 
S. 


to.  //./2./3.2  3.  £  5\  6.7.  S. 


g  /o.l/./z,  /.  2.  3.  ¥•.  56.  7.  8  9 


from  two  to  three  hours  of  work  before  5  P.  M.,  and  we  set  to 
work  again  immediately  after  an  early  supper — i.  e.,  from  about 
7  :  15  or  7  :  30  until  9:15?.  M.  The  subjects  kept  on  working 
until  their  time  came  to  be  tested.  I.  spent  most  of  her  time 
reading  German  literature  (Goethe)  ;  III.  perused  books  on 
psychology  and  philosophy  (chiefly  Wundt's  Grundriss  der 
Psychologie),  while  II.  computed  the  returns  from  the  experi- 
ments before  referred  to,  a  task  by  no  means  easy.  The  Ger- 
man language  introduced  in  our  reading  an  additional  element 
of  fatigue ;  Goethe  required  on  the  part  of  I.  close  attention  and 
induced  very  soon  real  fatigue.  We  did  our  best  all  through 
the  day  not  to  allow  our  mind  to  wander,  even  though  it  cost 
us  frequent  painful  efforts. 

We  worked  all  three  in  the  same  room  to  eliminate  the 
fluctuations  of  temperature  and  of  blood  circulation  which  would 
have  been  produced  by  the  passage  from  the  open  winter  air 
into  the  warm  atmosphere  of  a  room.  Our  life  was  well  regu- 
lated ;  we  retired  early  and  nearly  at  the  same  hour  each  day 
and  our  coffee  and  tea  drinking  was  kept  as  much  as  possible 
the  same  during  the  six  days  of  experimentation. 

The  fatigue  produced  was  well  marked.  The  words  used 
to  describe  it  were,  for  the  first  day :  «  Quite  tired ;  a  little 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE.  579 

nervous'  (HI);  'very  tired,  understand  no  more'  (I); 
*  worked  with  energy  all  day,  but  could  not  go  on  much  longer  ' 
(II).  For  the  second  day:  'Tired'  (III)  ;  I.,  who  felt  very 
tired  before  supper,  was  somewhat  excited  and  disposed  to  go 
on  when  9  :  15  P.  M.  came ;  *  very,  very  tired,  tired  out'  (II). 
At  the  end  of  the  third  day  we  were  all  three  quite  tired  and  ex- 
tremely glad  at  the  prospect  of  the  coming  days  of  rest.  The  last 
hour  of  the  morning  was  usually  quite  burdensome,  not  that  our 
work  was  lacking  in  interest,  but  that  we  were  no  more  able  to 
attend  spontaneously;  it  was  already  fatigue  and  not  simply 
nervousness.  The  reader  might  wish  that  we  should  give  the 
curves  for  each  one  of  the  six  days,  together  with  a  designation 
of  our  fatigue  feelings  at  the  moment  of  the  measurements  and 
not  only  the  resultants.  If  anything  more  than  what  can  be 
inferred  from  the  resultant  curves  could  be  derived  from  the 
separate  curves,  they  would  be  reproduced  here  ;  but  it  is  not  the 
case :  the  daily  curves  do  not  follow  the  fatigue  feelings  any 
better  than  the  resultants. 

As  each  one  of  us  engaged  for  the  whole  morning  in  mental 
work  engrossing  his  attention  and  requiring  a  considerable  de- 
gree of  mental  tension  and  drove  himself  continuously  at  full 
speed,  the  reader  acquainted  with  Griesbach,  Wagner's  or  Van- 
nod's  papers  will  expect  our  fatigue-curves  to  ascend  more  or 
less  regularly  from  9  A.  M.  to  i  P.  M.  The  ups  and  downs 
of  the  curves  of  these  investigators  due,  according,  to  them,  to 
the  different  degree  of  difficulty  presented  by  the  lessons,  some 
of  them  being  hours  of  relaxation,  could  not  be  expected  in  our 
case.  At  5  P.  M.  the  curves  should  not  be  found  much,  if  any 
lower  than  at  i,  the  after-dinner  rest  being  offset  by  from  two 
to  three  hours  of  work  ;  and  we  should  expect  them  to  reach  the 
highest  point  at  9  :  15. 

Concerning  Fig.  I  the  following  points  are  to  be  noted : 
i.  The  vertical  extremes  between  which  the  fatigue-curves 
wander  remain  very  near  together.  For  II.  the  distance  be- 
tween these  limits  goes  once  beyond  3mm  and  reaches  that  figure 
three  times  only  ;  for  I.  it  never  reaches  3mm  and  four  times  only 
does  it  go  beyond  2mm,  while  for  III.  it  exceeds  2mm  only  once 
and  then  just  by  a  fraction  of  a  millimeter. 


58°  JAMBS  H.   LEUBA. 

2.  A  striking  and  not  to  be  expected  lack  of  agreement  be- 
tween the  curves  for  the  two-threshold  and  those  for  the  one- 
threshold.     Concerning  the  four  pairs  of  curves  of  I.,  only  the 
thumb  fatigue-curves  agree  tolerably  well  with   each  other,  as 
the  reader  will  see.     With  III.  the  fatigue  and  also  the  rest- 
curves  for  the  thumb  agree  fairly  well,  but  those  for  the  head 
show  more  frequently  opposite  directions.     The  tracings  of  II. 
may  be  called  satisfactory  in  this  respect. 

3.  The  corresponding   forehead-  and  thumb-curves    agree 
still  less ;  neither  in  the  tracings  of  I.  nor  in  those  of  II.  is  there 
any  general  agreement  to  be  found ;  on  the  contrary,  the  curves 
are  on  the  whole  the  opposite  of  each  other.     III.  distinguishes 
himself  in  that  he  shows  two  pairs  of  curves  in  agreement :   the 
fatigue-curves  of  the  one-threshold  and  the  rest-curves  of  the 
two-threshold. 

4.  A  comparison  of  the  fatigue-  with  the  rest-curves  does 
not  bring  to  light  any  general,  decided  tendency.     The  oscilla- 
tions of  the  rest-curves  are  about  as  great  as  those  of  the  fatigue- 
curves,  although  Griesbach  states  that  "the  sensibility  under 
normal  conditions  [he  means  no  fatigue]  changes  not  at  all  or 
only  very  little."    Sometimes  the  rest-curve  ends  higher  above  its 
beginning  than  in  the  case  for  the  corresponding  fatigue-curves  ; 
sometimes   they  follow  each   other  almost   parallelly.      If  we 
draw  total  average  curves  summarizing  for  each  subject  the  four 
rest-  and  the  four  fatigue-curves,  we  get  the  tracings  of  Fig.  II, 
in  which  the  oscillations  are  so  much  reduced  that  we  had  to 
increase  four  times  the  scale  of   the  drawing.     The  distances 
between  the  vertical  extremes  of  each  curve,  expressed  in  mil- 
limeters, are  as  follows:    for  rest,  i  (I),  i  (II),  -if  (III)  ;    for 
fatigue  :    ij  (I),  i|  (II),  1}  (III).     If  we  compare  in  each  line 
the  starting  with  the  ending  point,  we  find  two  of  the  rest-curves 
(I  and  III)  ending  exactly  where  they  began  and  one  (I)  ending 
i  mm.  below ;    while  of  the  fatigue-curves  two  end  higher  and 
one  lower:    +  i  mm.  (I),  +  i|  (II),  —  |  (III).     If  we  consider 
only  the  morning  part  of  the  tracings,  we  find  that  concerning  I. 
two  of  the  rest-curves  end  higher  than  they  start,  one  ends  at  the 
same  level  and  the  other  lower ;    while  of  the  fatigue-curves 
two  end  lower,  one  at  the  same  level  and  one  higher.    Concern- 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE. 


58l 


Z. 


.~2r3  4-..$  6.  7.8,9. 


t  10.  //.  12.  1.2.  3  £  5.  0.  7  &  9. 


izr. 


#  «//v«YarTnr*~  7  <?  p; 

The  scale  in  Fig.  II.  is  four  times  larger  than  in  Fig.  I. — *".  e.,  four  squares, 
instead  of  one,  stand  for  one  millimeter. 

The  starting  points  of  the  curves  of  Fig.  II.  have  been  arbitrarily  determined. 

ing  II.,  two  of  the  rest-curves  end  higher  than^they  began  and 
the  two  others  lower,  while  the  four  fatigue-curves  end  higher. 
Concerning  III.,  the  rest-curves  end  lower  in  three  cases  and  at 
the  same  level  in  the  fourth  one,  while  the  four  fatigue-curves 
end  lower  than  their  starting  point. 

It  is  clear  that  from  Figs.  I.  and  II.  no  general  deduction  re- 
garding the  effect  of  fatigue  could  be  drawn  with  any  confi- 
dence, and  yet  the  curves  put  in  regard  the  discrimination  sensi- 
bility during  three  days  of  severe  mental  work  and  three  days 
of  rest.  If  the  agsthesiometric  method  does  not  yield  here  un- 
ambiguous results,  how  could  it  be  used  in  the  class-room? 

Let  us  pass  to  the  curves  of  Fig.  III.  Each  curve,  with 
the  exception  of  those  in  the  middle,  represents  the  changes  in 
the  discrimination  sensibility  as  they  occurred  during  one  hour 


5S2 


JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 


of  adding  performed  on  five  successive  days.  The  distances 
from  one  point  to  the  next,  measured  vertically,  indicate  the 
modification  of  the  sensibility  during  one  hour  of  adding. 
The  hour  was  divided  in  two  halves  separated  as  follows  :  ist 
day,  no  rest;  2d  day,  5  minutes  rest;  3d  day,.  15  minutes;  4th 
day,  30  minutes ;  5th  day,  60  minutes.  The  continuous  lines 
represent  the  one-threshold ;  the  broken  line,  the  two- threshold. 
The  curves  in  the  middle  are  each  the  resultant  of  the  four 
others  belonging  to  the  same  subject.  No  value  is  to  be  given 


I. 


/o 

8. 
7. 

S. 

2 
/ 


in. 


DETERMINING   FATIGUE.  583 

to  the  position  of  the  starting-point  of  the  segments  as,  in  order 
to  get  a  curve,  the  end-point  of  one  day  was  used  as  the  begin- 
ning of  the  next. 

Concerning  Fig.  Ill,  we  notice  that:  i.  As  in  Fig.  I,  the 
one-threshold  curves  agree  only  occasionally  with  the  two- 
threshold  curves.  Compare,  for  instance,  the  thumb-curves  of 
III.  Those  agreeing  best  are  the  forehead  curves  of  II.,  and 
even  then  one  of  them  indicates  a  decrease  of  sensibility  during 
the  adding  of  the  third  day,  while  the  other  shows  an  increase. 

2.  The  agreement  of  the  head-  with  the  thumb-curves  is  no 
better  than  previously.     In  the  case  of  II.  and  of  III.  the  diver- 
gences   generally  reach    opposition.     In   I.  the    one-threshold 
curves  exhibit  a  noteworthy  concordance. 

3.  Regarding  the  relation  between  fatigue  and  the  sensibil- 
ity, we  have  in  the   addition  returns    a   means  of  measuring 
fatigue,  and  consequently  of  controlling  the  results  yielded  by 
the  assthesiometric  method,  which,  if  not  absolutely  reliable,  is 
at  any  rate  of  some  value.     We  should  not  take  it  for  granted, 
even  though  we  could  assume  that  the  initial  psycho-physiolog- 
ical state  of  the  subject  was  each  day  the  same,  that  the  degree 
of  fatigue  varies  in  inverse  proportion  to  the  length  of  the  rest- 
period  separating  the  two  half-hours  of  work.     The  amount  of 
work  actually  performed  will  be  a   much  safer  index   of  the 
fatigue  increase.     But  can  we   accept  the   statement  that   the 
greater  the  amount  of  work,  the  greater  the  fatigue ;  and  that, 
as  far  as  the  adding  periods  are  concerned,  all  the  work  done 
is  represented  by  the  number  of  additions ;  and  can  we  conse- 
quently assume  that  the  fatigue  increase  bears,   in  the   same 
person,  a  constant   relation   to   the  number  of    additions  per- 
formed?    Man  is  a  too  complex  and  not  well  enough  unified 
machine  for  such  an  assumption  to  be  true.     Coexistently  with 
the  physiological  activity  involved  in  adding,  many  other  proc- 
esses take   place  equally  efficient  as  modifying  factors  of  the 
body  metabolism,  but  not  constant  enough  to  constitute  a  fixed 
quantity.     The  muscular  tensions  which  vary  so  much  from  one 
time  to  the  other  will,  for  one,  contribute  their  share  towards 
the  fatigue  increase  and  at  the  same  time  tend  to  bring  about  a 
reduction  in  the  amount  of  the  mental  work  performed.     The 


JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 

number  of  additions  will  not  even  represent  the  whole  product 
of  the  physiological  activity  having  a  conscious  correlate ;  the 
adding  process  is  at  times  accompanied,  at  other  times  inter- 
rupted, by  trains  of  thoughts  and  feelings  varying  greatly,  from 
day  to  day,  in  duration  and  vividness.  This  supplementary 
mental  work,  the  adding  does  not  record ;  or  if  its  effect  is 
perceivable  in  the  number  of  additions,  it  is  as  a  decrease  that 
it  reveals  itself.  Stated  in  general  terms,  the  objection  here 
formulated  is  that  the  number  of  additions  performed  during  a 
given  time  is  not  the  whole  of  the  psycho-physiological  activity, 
and  consequently  cannot  be  an  exact  correspondent  of  the 
fatigue  increase.  Nevertheless  it  may  serve  as  an  approximate 
means,  and  therefore  we  give  in  the  following  Table  the  re- 
turns of  the  adding  for  comparison  with  the  curves  of  Fig. 
III.  It  is  evident  that  it  would  be  sheer  waste  of  time  to  com- 
pare these  figures  with  the  separate  curves  of  Fig.  III.,  as,  if 
they  agreed  with  one  of  them,  they  must  necessarily  disagree 
with  another,  since  between  head  and  thumb,  as  also  between 
the  one-  and  the  two-threshold  there  reigns  an  apparently  hope- 
less discrepancy.  The  only  possible  thing  would  be  to  make 
use  of  the  resultants  of  the  four  curves  of  each  subject,  however 
slight  the  confidence  deserved  by  a  curve  having  such  progeni- 
tors. 

A.     FOR  THE  WHOLE  HOUR. 


I. 

II. 

III. 

2d  day  —  84 
3d   «    +78 
4th"     +89 
5th"    +64 

—  10.8 

+  17 

Il48-.i 

-  72.8 

+  I45-2 
—424.8 
+285.2 

B.     FOR  THE  SECOND  HALF  HOUR. 

2d  day  -|-   12 
3d    "     +  94 
4th  "     +  59 
5th"     +110 

—  21.4 

+  10.6 

+234- 
+  49-6 

—  101.9 

+  83.1 
—231 
+176.1 

C. 


DIFFERENCES  BETWEEN  THE  FIRST  AND  SECOND  HALF 
HOUR  OF  THE  SAME  DAY. 


1st  day  —  103 

—148 

+  122 

No  Rest 

2d       »      +5 

—  180 

—    9 

5m    " 

3d     "     +95 

-163 

+    12 

i5m    " 

4th  "     +124 

—  72 

—   26 

3om    " 

5th   "     +180 

+  66 

+    41 

6om    " 

DETERMINING  FATIGUE.  585 

A  gives  the  differences  in  the  number  of  additions  performed 
between  the  day  named  opposite  the  figure  and  the  preceding 
one.  For  instance,  2d  day  —  84.,  means  that  during  the  second 
day  there  was  a  decrease  of  84  in  the  number  of  additions  of  the 
first  day. 

B  takes  into  account  only  the  second  half  of  the  hour  and 
C,  instead  of  comparing  two  successive  days,  gives  the  differ- 
ences between  the  first  and  the  second  half  hour  of  the  same 
day.  The  influence  of  practice  has  been  eliminated  by  the  de- 
duction of  the  practice  gain.  How  the  practice  gain  was  deter- 
mined may  be  ascertained  from  Professor  Lindley's  paper, 
already  referred  to.  The  figures  of  C  represent,  in  our  opinion, 
the  nearest  approach  to  a  successful  expression  of  the  changes 
in  the  fatigue  state,  provided  they  are  interpreted  as  follows :  a 
falling  off  in  the  additions  in  the  second  half  hour  as  compared 
with  the  first  is  a  sign  of  fatigue ;  consequently  we  shall  expect 
the  curve  to  move  upward  whenever  the  second  half  hour 
yielded  less  work  than  the  first,  and  vice  versa.  How  far  this 
interpretation  is  to  be  relied  upon  is  not  at  all  clear ;  but  it  seems 
to  us  the  best  use  we  can  make  of  these  figures.  When  con- 
strued in  this  way  the  resultant  curve  of  subject  II.  follows  re- 
markably well  the  figures ;  and,  barring  the  segment  of  the  first 
day,  that  of  I.  is  also  satisfactory.  But  inasmuch  as  the  curve 
of  III.  does  not  at  all  reflect  the  oscillations  shown  by  the  figures, 
no  general  inference  can  be  drawn. 

Against  A  and  B^  looked  upon  as  fatigue  indicators,  it  may 
be  urged  that  the  initial  work-power  of  the  subject  is  not  taken 
into  account,  as  it  should  in  order  that  the  figures  be  really  indic- 
ative of  proportional  fatigue  changes.  For  instance,  the  num- 
ber —  84  is  to  be  interpreted  as  indicating  a  smaller  loss  of  work- 
power  (less  fatigue  increase)  during  the  second  than  during  the 
first  day.  But  if  the  initial  fatigue  was  greater  the  second  than 
the  first  day,  a  loss  of  84  in  the  number  of  additions  during  the 
second  day  may  very  well  mean  greater  losjs  of  working  power 
during  the  hour  than  was  experienced  the  preceding  day,  al- 
though more  work  was  done ;  we  should  then,  if  that  supposi- 
tion was  true,  expect  the  curve  of  the  second  day  to  show  a 
greater  rise  than  the  one  of  the  first,  despite  the  fact  that  less 
work  was  accomplished. 


586  JAMES  H.    LEUBA. 

The  measurements  taken  upon  the  Bryn  Mawr  students  need 
not  delay  us  long ;  they  confirm  the  negative  results  of  the 
others.  Out  of  the  thirty-six  separate  curves  obtained,  we  pick 
out  twelve  (Fig.  VI)  possessing  as  fairly  as  possible  the  charac- 
teristics of  the  whole  batch.  The  aesthesiometer  was  used  at 
Bryn  Mawr  as  Wagner  used  it — t.  e.9  instead  of  determining  the 
one-  and  the  two-threshold,  the  instrument  was  applied  alterna- 
tively with  the  points  too  far  apart  to  be  felt  as  one  and  too  near 
together  to  give  the  impression  of  twoness ;  from  these  two  ex- 
treme distances  the  threshold  was  gradually  approached.  To 
keep  the  attention  of  the  subject  and  prevent  the  influence 
which  regularly  in  the  succession  of  the  sensations  expressed 
as  '  two,'  <  one ' ;  '  two,'  *  one '  might  have,  the  subjects  were 
frequently  touched  with  one  point  only.  The  measurements 
were  taken  without  haste  and  with  due  regard  for  the  cir- 
cumstances on  which  exactness  of  result  depends :  absence  of 
disturbing  external  stimuli ;  ignorance  on  the  part  of  the  subject 
of  the  method  pursued ;  interruption  of  about  one  minute  and  a 
half  after  every  four  or  five  touches,  etc.  Moreover,  to  prevent 
the  bewildering  effect  which  too  many  touch  sensations  produce 
when  crowded  in  a  short  space  of  time,  we  endeavored  to  reach 
safe  results  with  as  few  touches  as  possible.  Eight  applications 
of  the  instrument  were  found  the  lowest  practical  number  for 
each  threshold.  Under  these  conditions  about  five  minutes  were 
required  for  the  determination  of  the  two  thresholds — forehead 
and  cheekbone — taken  at  each  sitting.  No  attempt  was  made 
in  this  series  to  find  out  and  avoid  the  temperature  spots,  our 
intention  being  primarily  to  imitate  Dr.  Wagner's  method,  and 
to  use  it  on  persons  younger  than  the  Heidelberg  subjects. 
Nevertheless  we  proceeded,  even  in  these  experiments,  with  more 
care  than  the  German  investigators.  The  students  who  served 
as  subjects  were  requested  to  keep  faithfully  at  work  from  8:15 
A.  M.  to  i  :  15  P.  M. ;  they  understood  that  we  wanted  them  to 
get  as  tired  as  possible,  and  they  willingly  entered  into  our  pur- 
pose. During  the  morning  they  attended  either  three  or  four 
lectures  or  recitations  ;  the  rest  of  the  time  they  filled  with  private 
work.  The  two  post-graduate  students  who  took  the  measure- 
ments here  recorded  knew  that  the  discrimination  sensibility  is 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE. 


587 


22 
2/. 
20. 
/9 
/*. 
//• 

tf. 

/3. 


8- 


22. 

20. 
/$. 


IS 


//.#      <e.  // 


/O. 


6. 
S. 
t. 


/o. 
*- 

9 
o 


9. 
8. 
7. 
6. 
S. 
k 
3. 


g.JS 


yo./s 


11.  IS 


588  JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 

thought  to  decrease  with  fatigue,  and  expected  their  returns  to 
agree  with  this  belief ;  instead  of  this,  they  show  an  almost  con- 
stant increase  in  the  sensibility.  The  figures  increase  only  15 
times  out  of  108  possibilities  as  we  pass  from  one  measurement 
to  the  next,  and  only  5  of  the  36  curves  end  higher  than  they 
begin  ;  yet  the  last  measurement  was  taken  at  i  :  15  P.  M.,  after 
five  hours  of  mental  work,  interrupted  only  by  the  time  neces- 
sary for  the  tests,  the  first  of  which  was  taken  15  minutes  after 
breakfast.  As  to  the  correspondence  of  the  forehead  with  -the 
cheekbone  curve,  the  reader  will  see  that  on  the  whole  it  is  closer 
than  in  the  previous  curves,  but  how  far  yet  from  the  admirable 
harmony  reigning  between  Griesbach's  tracings  ! l 

The  preceding  facts  warrant,  it  seems,  the  following  gen- 
eral conclusion :  If  the  ability  to  discriminate  simultaneous 
tactile  sensations  is  in  some  way  under  the  influence  of  fatigue, 
it  depends  also  and  to  such  an  extent  upon  other  factors  that  it 
cannot  serve  as  an  index  of  the  fatigue-state.  These  other  fac- 
tors are  the  temperature  spots,  the  irregularities  in  the  sensitive- 
ness of  adjacent  bits  of  the  skin  surface,  the  temperature  of  the 
surface  tested,  the  state  of  the  blood  circulation,  the  highly  com- 
plex inner  determinants  of  the  intensity,  duration,  and  kind  of 
attention  paid  to  the  sensation,  in  so  far  as  they  are  independent 
of  fatigue,  etc. 

It  is  not  our  present  purpose  to  enter  into  a  discussion  of  the 
relative  importance  of  these  several  factors  ;  to  do  this  profitably 
would  require  long  series  of  skillfully  planned  and  carefully 
carried  out  experiments.  But  we  may,  before  closing,  support 
our  general  conclusion  by  the  results  obtained  and  the  opinion 
expressed  by  Tawney  in  a  recent  and  painstaking  work,2  and 
also  by  a  criticism  of  the  method  used  and  of  the  results  obtained 
by  Griesbach  and  Wagner. 

According  to  Tawney — and  this  we  have  ourselves  often 
noticed — it  is  of  the  greatest  importance  that  the  points  of  the 
aesthesiometer  produce  a  sensation  of  equal  subjective  intensity. 
This  cannot  be  secured  by  equal  pressure  of  the  points,  since 

JThe  full-line  is  the  forehead  curve ;  the  broken  line,  the  cheekbone  curve. 
2  Guy  A.  Tawney,  Ueber  die  Wahrnehmung  zweier  Punkte  mittelst  des 
Tastsinnes,  Philosophische  Studien,  1898,  Vol.  13,  p.  163. 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE. 


Fig. 


Fig.  XT 


Fig.  XT 


Figs.  VII.,  VIII. ,  IX.,  X.  and  XI.  are  taken  from  Guy  A.  Tawne/s  paper 
before  mentioned. 


59°  JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 

neighboring  bits  of  the  skin  differ  considerably  in  the  thick- 
ness of  the  insensitive  superficial  layer,  and  probably  also  in  the 
sensitiveness  of  the  deeper  layer.  He  found,  for  instance,  in 
one  part  of  the  shoulder  blade  that  the  point  touching  the  skin 
lightly  was  felt  more  distinctly  than  the  other,  although  heavily 
applied.  Concerning  the  relative  importance  of  fatigue  and  of  the 
mood  (Gemuthslage),  he  .writes  "  Es  Wiirde  namlich  bemerkt 
dass  die  Gemuthslage  der  Versuchperson  eine  sehr  bedeutende 
Rolle  spielt,  wahrend  z.  b.  der  Umstand  dass  sie  bis  12  Uhr  in 
der  vorigen  Nacht  gearbeitet  hatte,  fast  gar  keine  Rolle  spielte." 
He  found  also  that  widely  different  results  were  obtained  when 
the  attention  was  transferred  from  the  object  touching  the  skin 
to  the  subjective  sensation,  or  when  its  intensity  was  altered  by 
means  of  suggestions  in  the  form  of  information  imparted  to  the 
subject  on  the  purpose  of  the  experiments.  But  the  point  of 
greatest  interest  to  us  in  Tawney's  paper  is  the  great  variations 
shown  by  the  threshold  of  the  same  person,  measured  at  the 
same  spot  and  at  the  same  time  on  different  days.  Fig.  VII 
and  Fig.  VIII,  pp.  16-19,  g^ve  tne  thresholds  of  two  subjects 
measured  at  7:30  A.  M.,  on  the  same  part  of  the  body  (the 
dorsal  side  of  the  forearm  in  the  case  of  Fig.  VII ;  the  dorsal 
side  of  the  upper  arm  in  the  case  of  Fig.  VIII)  on  successive 
days. 

The  thresholds  recorded  for  these  curves  are,  for  each  day, 
averages  of  four  threshold-determinations.  This,  according  to 
Tawney,  accounts  for  the  regularity  of  the  decrease  of  curve  VII, 
a  decrease  due  to  practice ;  but  it  does  not  prevent  Fig.  VIII 
from  showing  daily  oscillations  reaching  almost  20  mm.  We 
are  not  told  how  the  preceding  nights  were  spent,  but  the  re- 
mark quoted  above  indicates  clearly  enough  that,  in  the  opinion 
of  the  author,  irregularities  of  the  curve  cannot  be  explained 
by  fatigue  due  to  late  work  and  insufficient  sleep.  Fig.  IX 
shows  similar  oscillations ;  but  as  the  time  of  the  measurements 
was  not  always  the  same,  we  cannot  make  use  of  them.  The 
time  at  which  the  tests  recorded  in  Figs.  X  and  XI  were  taken 
is  not  mentioned ;  we  may  suppose  that  the  rule  was  followed, 
namely,  to  measure  always  at  the  same  time  of  day.  The  fol- 
lowing figures,  representing  the  thresholds  for  the  volar  side  of 


DETERMINING   FATIGUE.  591 

the  forearm,  measured  daily  during  19  days,  indicate  again  very 
great  variations :  60,  52,  60,  64,  54,  52,  55,  50,  42,  40,  45,  40, 
45,  40,  38,  41,  42.  The  table  numbered  XV  in  Tawney's  paper 
exhibits  a  similar  irregularity ;  the  thresholds  for  ten  days 
separated  by  intervals  of  one  to  six  days'  duration  are  :  15,  25, 
30,  40,  45,  45,  25,  16,  35,  45.  The  preceding  curves  and  fig- 
ures are  not  picked  out  of  a  larger  number ;  they  represent  the 
whole  of  the  results  obtained  by  Tawney  bearing  upon  our  in- 
vestigation. He  had  himself  no  intention  of  studying  the  re- 
lation of  fatigue  to  the  discrimination  sensibility. 

When  these  results  and  those  obtained  by  ourselves  are  put 
together,  it  becomes  difficult  to  look  upon  the  work  of  Griesbach, 
Wagner  and  Vanned  with  any  other  feeling  than  one  of  wonder. 
When  the  resultant  curves  of  three  persons  for  three  comparable 
days  of  hard,  persistent  work  and  for  three  days  of  rest — to 
speak  only  of  the  part  of  our  work  which  we  offer  here — move 
up  and  down  apparently  without  any  reference  to  a  fatigue 
clearly  felt  and  legitimately  inferred  from  the  work  performed ; 
when  an  hour  of  adding  by  three  persons,  during  six  days, 
yields  no  better  result ;  when  five  morning  hours  of  intellectual 
activity  on  the  part  of  six  college  students  interrupted  by  only 
short  pauses,  bring  with  them  remarkably  uniform  increase  in 
the  discrimination  sensibility  ;  when,  moreover,  it  is  known  that 
the  same  spot  may  yield  on  successive  days  and  under  appar- 
ently the  same  conditions,  results  varying  up  to  20  mm.,  the 
admirable  consistency  and  uniformity  of  the  results  published 
by  the  said  investigators  become  a  problem  whose  solution  is  not 
easily  found.  To  this  should  be  added  that  these  remarkable 
results  have  been  obtained  under  circumstances  far  from  favor- 
able to  exactness  of  return.  Wagner,  for  instance,  measured  in 
10  minutes — the  length  of  the  interval  between  the  class  sittings 
— from  six  to  ten  persons  at  one  point,  and  Griesbach,  in  ap- 
parently the  same  time,  two  or  three  subjects  in  six  different 
places.  This  appears  to  us  verging  on  the  impossible. 

If  we  now  turn  to  the  consideration  of  the  method  used 
by  the  German  investigators,  we  find  that  Griesbach  is  not 
very  explicit  in  his  description  of  the  manner  in  which  he  pro- 
ceeded. His  method  was  the  one  we  followed  at  Heidelberg ; 


592  JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 

only,  judging  from  the  rather  vague  utterances  of  his  mono- 
graph and  from  a  private  communication,  he  allowed  himself  a 
good  deal  of  freedom.  How  far  one  could,  with  the  help  of  a 
little  looseness  in  the  use  of  the  sesthesiometer — a  looseness  un- 
avoidable, it  seems,  when  the  measurements  are  to  be  taken  as 
rapidly  as  they  were  in  this  case — unconsciously  influence  one's 
returns  when  possessed  by  an  idea  which,  if  confirmed  by  ex- 
periments, would  prove  of  great  scientific  and  of  much  practical 
value,  is  an  open  question.  We  may  be  excused  for  formu- 
lating it  on  this  occasion. 

Wagner's  method  was  similar  to  the  one  used  in  Bryn  Mawr 
by  our  students  and  ourselves  :  too  great  and  too  small  distances 
alternating  until  the  threshold  is  reached.  This  procedure  is 
decidedly  to  be  preferred  to  the  former  under  the  circumstances 
in  point,  the  alternation  of  distances  giving  clearly  two,  with 
distances  yielding  but  one  sensation,  gives  to  the  subject,  from 
the  very  beginning,  a  clear  knowledge  of  the  difference  with 
which  his  judgment  is  to  deal.  Otherwise,  if,  for  instance,  the 
experimenter  begins  with  a  very  small  distance  and  increases  it 
until  the  threshold  is  reached,  the  subject  who  has  not  had  the 
opportunity  of  comparing  twoness  with  oneness  will  often  show 
by  his  answers  that  he  does  not  know  what  he  is  to  call  '  one ' 
and  what  '  two.'  We  tested  many  persons  with  regard  to  this, 
and  found  in  almost  every  case  that  the  usual  verbal  instruc- 
tions are  not  sufficient :  before  the  subject  is  made  acquainted 
with  the  sensations  he  is  to  call  '  two '  and  «  one,'  he  may  call 
'  two,'  two  points  clearly  below  the  threshold  and  give  the 
same  answer  when  touched  by  one  point ;  this  source  of  error 
will  be  greatly  increased  if  the  subject  gets  into  his  head  that  it 
is  to  his  credit  to  feel  two  points  as  often  as  possible.  This  ob- 
jection applies  with  all  its  force  to  the  method  used  by  Gries- 
bach,  since  his  subjects  changed  generally  each  day  and  were 
expected  from  the  very  first  trial  to  give  recordable  judgments. 

Wagner  declares  his  results  to  be  in  perfect  agreement  with 
those  of  Griesbach,  and  concludes  that  "the  assthesiometric 
method  of  Griesbach  is  a  practical  means  of  determining  the 
degree  of  fatigue  and  of  comparing  it  quantitatively"  (p.  12). 
There  is  shown,  he  holds,  '  a  clear  relation,'  between  the  dis- 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE.  593 

crimination  sensibility  and  six  specified  circumstances,  among 
which  we  find  not  only  the  sort  of  instruction  received,  but  also 
the  teaching  ability  of  the  instructor.  For  the.  interpretation  of 
separate  turns  of  his  curves  he  shows  a  boldness  of  which 
Griesbach  was  not  guilty.  No  doubt  his  results  are  in  close 
agreement  with  those  of  Griesbach,  yet  there  is  one  particular 
in  which  the  concordance  appears  defective ;  in  looking  over 
his  tracings  it  occurred  to  us  that  their  upward  gain  was  made 
chiefly,  if  not  entirely,  between  the  first  and  the  second  meas- 
urement, and  that  they  frequently  ended  below  the  point  reached 
at  the  second  test — /'.  £.,  after  the  first  hour  of  study.  In  order 
to  reach  a  definite  opinion  on  this  interesting  point  the  sum  was 
made  (i)  of  the  measurements  taken  before  the  beginning  of  the 
lessons;  (2)  of  those  taken  after  the  first  hour;  (3)  of  those 
taken  after  the  last  morning  hour,  with  the  results  given  below. 
Each  table  in  Wagner's  paper  includes  the  measurements  taken 
on  from  five  to  ten  students  of  the  same  class,  before  the  begin- 
ning of  the  morning's  work  and  after  each  recitation  of  one 
day.  There  were  usually  five  recitations,  separated  from  each 
other  by  an  interval  of  ten  minutes.  Each  one  of  the  figures 
composing  the  first  vertical  row  of  our  tables  is  the  sum  of  the 
figures  representing  the  measurements  taken  before  work  in  one 
of  the  tables  of  Wagner ;  the  figures  of  the  second  row  give 
each  the  sum  of  the  measurements  after  the  first  class  hour,  and 
those  of  the  third  row  the  sums  of  the  last  measurements  of  the 
same  table.  We  have  added  before  the  figures  the  names  of 
the  studies  after  which  the  tests  were  taken.  We  omitted  the 
measurements  taken  after  *  Religion '  when  given  during  the 
last  hour,  because  the  lesson  was  attended  by  only  about  half  the 
students  used  as  subjects.  We  acted  similarly  with  gymnastics 
that  intellectual  work  only  be  taken  into  .account.  Furthermore, 
when  the  last  figure  was  missing  we  left  out,  for  that  day,  the 
measurements  of  the  person  concerned. 


594 


JAMES  H.   LEUBA. 


TABLE  A. 

MEASUREMENTS   IN    QUARTA. 


55 

French  exercise,          79 

Phaedrus,  80 

Thresholds  of  6  subjects. 

42 

Arith.  (Rechnen),      67 

Latin,         91 

8 

86 

French,                        108 

German,  120 

8 

78 

German,                      no 

Geom.,     135 

8 

70 

Geometry,                   118 

Latin,       106 

6 

45 

Arithmetic,                   73 

Latin,         97 

6 

73 

Arithmetic,                106 

Latin,       136 

7 

83 

104 

French  exercise,    \ 
German  compos.,  /     * 

Latin,       173 
German,  175 

9 

10 

127 

Latin  exercise,           178 

Latin,        180 

10 

114 

Geometry,                   188 

History,    167 

10 

Arithmetic,                 160 

Totals:  877 

1358 

1460 

88 

The  average  increase  of  the  threshold  between  the  initial  and  the  final  test 

is,  accordingly,  in  millimeters, 6.6 

Between  the  first  and  the  second  measurement, 5.5 

Between  the  second  and  the  final  measurement, 1.2 

TABLE  B. 

MEASUREMENTS  IN  UNTERTERTIA. 


27 

Latin,                  35 

Geogr.  ,                     44 

Thresholds  of  4  subjects. 

47 

History,               51 

Latin,                       43 

4 

55 

Greek  Ex.,          77 

Geom.,                    65 

6 

93 

German,            114 

History,                   99 

8 

57 

Greek,                  65 

Geom.,                    73 

5 

83 

Greek  Ex.,        114 

Natural  Sci.,         107 

8 

81 

Latin  Ex.,          107 

Geogr.,                     98 

8 

97 

Greek,                107 

Geom.,                   106 

8 

87 

Greek  Ex.,        108 

Natural  Sci.,         118 

8 

90 

Latin  Ex.,         119 

Geogr.,                   114 

8 

Totals     717 

897 

867 

67 

The  average  increase  of  the  threshold  between  the  initial  and  the  final  test 

is,  accordingly,  in  millimeters, » 2.2 

Between  the  first  and  the  second  measurement, 2.7 

Between  the  second  and  the  last  measurement, — 0.4 

Remarks  on  Table  B. — Wagner  explains  as  follows  the  sur- 
prising fall  of  the  figures  at  the  end  of  the  morning  in  the 
second  series  (47,  51,  43) :  "  *  *  *  alles  Erstaunen  verschwindet 
und  die  Theorie  erhalt  gerade  hier  eine  interessante  Bestatigung, 
sobald  man  erfahrt,  dass  alle  4  Stunden  dieses  Tages  von  ange- 
henden  Accessisten  gehalten  wurden,"  p.  63 .  Unfortunately,  the 
fourth  series  exhibits  a  similar  drop  (93,  114,  99)  without  *  Acces- 
sisten.' 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE. 


595 


Notice,  also,  that  the  6th  (83,  114,  107)  and  the  pth  series 
(87,  108,  118)  exhibit  inverse  changes  of  the  sensibility,  although 
the  subjects  of  study  were  for  both  days  the  same :  Ovid,  Latin, 
Religion,  Natural  Science. 

TABLE  C. 

MEASUREMENTS   IN   OBERTERTIA  AND  UNTERSECUNDA. 


35 

Caesar, 

7i 

History, 

68 

Thresholds  for  6  subjects. 

75 

German  compos., 

126 

Latin  Gram 

,117 

•     8 

32 

Latin  Grammar, 

39 

History, 

49 

1     4 

37 

Greek, 

36 

Latin, 

54 

1     5 

72 

Greek, 

99 

Latin, 

96 

'     7 

44 

Algebra, 

58 

Xenophon, 

67 

'     5        " 

Totals:  295 

429 

45i 

35 

The  average  increase  of  the  threshold  between  the  initial  and  the  final  test 

is,  accordingly,  in  millimeters, 4.5 

Between  the  first  and  the  second  measurement, 3.8 

Between  the  second  and  the  last  measurement, 0.6 

What  do  these  figures  mean  ?  Can  they  be  reconciled  with 
the  claims  made  in  favor  of  the  aesthesiometric  method?  Are 
they  to  be  interpreted  as  meaning  that  fatigue  takes  place  al- 
most entirely  during  the  first  hour,  and  remains  nearly  the  same 
through  four  additional  hours  of  work,  one  or  two  of  which  re- 
quire as  much  exertion  as  the  first  ?  Before  proceeding  with  this 
problem  let  us  notice  that,  in  this  respect,  Wagner's  results  agree 
neither  with  those  of  Griesbach  nor  with  ours.  During  the  first 
hour  of  work  the  sensibility  of  the  three  Heidelberg  subjects 
increased  (see  Resultants,  Fig.  II).  The  same  is  true  of  the 
Bryn  Mawr  students,  while  the  Griesbach  curves  continue  to 
ascend  more  or  less  regularly  after  the  first  hour  and  generally 
end  at  the  close  of  the  morning  (12  o'clock),  higher  than  after 
the  first  hour — we  refer  chiefly  to  the  cheek  bone  and  forehead 
curves.  It  might  be  that  this  lack  of  agreement  between  the 
German  investigators  is  due  to  the  unequal  difficulty  of  the  sub- 
jects with  which  the  morning's  work  opened  in  the  respective 
classes  to  which  their  subjects  belonged.  As  a  matter  of  fact, 
in  the  classes  with  which  Griesbach  dealt,  natural  history  and 
modern  languages  are  frequently  at  the  beginning  of  the 
schedule.  But  whether  this  be  the  ground  of  their  disagree- 


596  JAMES   H.   LEUBA. 

ment  or  not,  the  problem  before  us  remains.  It  will  not  do  to 
have  recourse  at  this  juncture  to  the  different  degree  of  atten- 
tion required  by  the  several  branches  of  study,  for,  if  we  con- 
sider only  the  subjects  of  the  last  hour,  leaving  out  of  count  the 
three  middle  ones,  we  see  that  they  cannot  be  said  to  be  clearly 
inferior  to  the  first  in  respect  of  their  fatigue-producing  power ; 
and  even  though  they  were  of  a  somewhat  less  exhaustive  kind, 
the  curves  would  not  thereby  be  explained  unless  it  could  be 
shown  that  between  the  first  and  the  last  hour  the  sensibility,  in 
consequence  of  the  recuperative  quality  of  the  three  interme- 
diary subjects,  had  nearly  returned  to  the  norm.1  But  to  ac- 
cept this  would  be  equivalent,  it  seems  to  us,  to  giving  up 
the  claims  of  the  believers  in  the  method.  It  cannot  be  said 
either,  by  way  of  explanation,  that  the  10  minutes  rest  between 
each  hour  was  enough  to  produce  return  to  the  normal ;  and  that, 
consequently,  the  figures  show  the  fatigue  increase  to  have  been, 
on  the  whole,  about  the  same  for  each  hour.  It  is  evidently  not 
true  that  two,  three,  four  or  five  hours  filled  with  the  Gymnasium 
studies  just  mentioned  leave  the  student  just  as  fresh  10  minutes 
after.2  We  should  rather  be  disposed  to  affirm  that  10  minutes 
after  the  first  hour  of  work  a  student  might  be  quite  fresh,  while 
10  minutes  after  thefifth  hour  hewould  be  quite  tired  and  often  ex- 
hausted. Another  explanation,  plausible  this  time,  but  destruc- 
tive of  the  claims  under  consideration  presents  itself  to  us  :  al- 
though nothing  is  said  as  to  the  place  where  the  first  tests  were 
taken,  we  may  assume  that  it  was  in  the  school  building,  the  first 
measurement  being  taken  as  the  students  arrived  from  their  homes. 
Now  the  usual  condition  of  a  young  man  after  an  early  morning 

xThe  intermediary  subjects  for  the j  days  on  which  the  measurements  were 
taken,  were  :  History,  Geometry  and  Phsedrus ;  Phsedrus,  Grammar,  and  Geog- 
raphy; French,  Gymnastic  and  History;  Geometry  and  History;  Drawing,  Re- 
ligion and  Geography  (this  group  is  found  only  once) ;  Drawing,  Algebra,  Ovid ; 
Geometry,  French,  Greek  and  other  similar  groups.  Considering  Gymnastic, 
Wagner  says  (p.  126)  summarizing:  "The  hour  of  Gymnastic  has  *  *  *  in  y$ 
of  all  the  students  (according  to  the  most  favorable  construction  of  the  figures) 
produced  a  relative  recuperation ;  in  the  two  other  thirds  it  induced  a  clearly 
marked  [ganz  ausgesprochene]  fatigue." 

2  Or  shall  we  assume  that  it  is  only  during  the  first  hours  that  the  Gymnasium 
student  really  works  and  that  during  the  rest  of  the  morning,  either  because  of 
exhaustion  or  of  laziness,  he  foregoes  all  tiresome  mental  effort  ?  Probably  no 
gymnasium  director  would  countenance  such  a  supposition. 


DETERMINING  FATIGUE.  597 

walk  and  the  exhilarating  encounter  with  classmates  is  one  of 
comparative  bodily  and  mental  alertness.  An  hour  later,  after  a 
recitation  in  Latin,  Greek  or  Geometry,  the  blood  circulation, 
the  respiration  and  the  general  feeling  may  be  assumed  to  have 
changed  considerably.  Under  such  dissimilar  circumstances  we 
should  hardly  expect  to  get  comparable  aesthesiometric  results. 
We  have  taken  some  measurements  with  the  hope  of  determining 
the  influence  of  these  physiological  changes,  but  we  have  been 
unable  to  have  our  subjects  fulfill  sufficiently  well  the  conditions 
necessary  for  exact  experimentations  to  warrant  any  positive 
conclusion.  The  temperature  of  the  part  of  the  body  tested  and 
of  the  room  in  which  the  measurements  are  taken  should  also 
be  taken  into  consideration  in  an  attempt  to  interpret  the  curve- 
peculiarity  under  discussion.  Wagner  experimented  during 
February  and  the  first  part  of  March ;  consequently  both  the 
temperature  of  the  skin  of  the  face  and  that  of  the  room  would 
change  materially  during  the  first  hour.  Loewenton  found  that 
the  threshold  was  elevated  by  an  increase  of  temperature  of  the 
room.  We  need  not  insist  on  the  possible  influence  of  these 
two  factors  ;  the  reader  will  see  how  they  might  have  combined 
to  bring  about  the  relatively  low  figures  of  the  first  measure- 
ments. If  accepted,  this  explanation  would  invalidate  the  con- 
clusions drawn  by  the  German  investigators  :  the  chief  rise  of 
the  curves  would  not  be  due  to  fatigue,  but  to  other  causes. 
Unfortunately,  we  do  not  know  whether  Griesbach's  different 
figures  must  be  interpreted  as  discrediting  this  solution,  for  we 
are  not  informed  as  to  the  circumstances  on  which  the  compar- 
ableness  of  the  figures  of  the  two  investigators  depends.  As  to 
our  own  curves,  all  that  can  be  said  on  this  point  is  that  they 
do  not  show  a  corresponding  rise  during  the  first  hour ;  and  that 
the  cause  we  have  suggested  for  this  rise  as  it  occurs  in  Wagner's 
curves  existed  neither  in  the  case  of  subjects  I.,  II.  and  III., 
nor  in  that  of  the  Bryn  Mawr  students,  since  the  latter  and  I. 
and  II.  were  tested  in  their  own  rooms,  while  the  measurements 
of  III.  were  taken  15™  after  his  entrance  into  the  rooms  occu~ 
pied  by  I.  and  II. 

Returning  to  the  general  problem  of  the  discrepancy  exist- 
ing between  our  results  and  those  of  the  German  investigators, 


598  JAMES  H.    LEUBA. 

we  may,  in  closing,  advert  to  such  thought  as  the  following : 
the  Heidelberg  and  the  Bryn  Mawr  subjects  might  be,  one  and 
all,  abnormal  persons ;  or,  we  may  have  failed  to  get  correct 
thresholds  because  of  lack  of  skill  in  handling  the  instrument ; 
or,  our  subjects  were  older  than  those  of  Griesbach  and  Wag- 
ner ;l  or,  the  discrimination  sensibility  of  German  youth  is  not 
comparable  in  its  behavior  to  that  of  American  men  and  women 
— thoughts  which  appear  to  us  either  inadmissible,  or  insufficient 
to  silence  the  suspicion  that  the  conclusions  of  the  papers  here 
considered  are  not  well  founded. 

In  this  state  of  indecision  we  must  let  the  matter  rest  for  the 
present  and  until  a  thorough  and  systematic  investigation  of  all 
the  factors  affecting  the  discrimination  of  simultaneous  touches 
enables  us  to  assign  to  fatigue  its  particular  role.  Two  groups 
of  factors  will  have  to  be  taken  into  consideration  :  (i)  those 
affecting  the  peripheral  organs — temperature,  thickness  of  epi- 
dermis, the  peripheral  blood  supply,  etc. ;  (2)  those  affecting 
the  general  psycho-physiological  condition  of  the  subject,  and 
more  especially  his  ability  to  attend.  An  a  -priori  considera- 
tion of  the  influence  possessed  by  these  factors  leaves  but  little 
ground  for  the  hope  that  the  discrimination  sensibility  to  simul- 
taneous touches  may  serve  as  a  practical  test  of  fatigue,  for 
many  of  them  (temperature,  blood  circulation)  vary  under  un- 
changed fatigue  conditions.  As  to  attention — considered  inde- 
pendently of  its  relation  to  fatigue — it  lacks  the  constancy  and 
steadiness  which  are  absolutely  required  if  the  experimenter  is 
to  draw  his  inferences  from  a  very  small  number  of  measure- 
ments. It  is  a  rhythmic  function,  and,  moreover,  is  readily  and 
rapidly  modified  by  the  will  to  attend — a  quantity  that  cannot 
be  maintained  constant. 

1  No  age  limit  is  set  by  them  to  the  applicability  of  the  pretended  relation 
existing  between  the  discrimination  sensibility  and  fatigue.  When  testing  per- 
sons of  the  age  of  our  Bryn  Mawr  subjects,  Griesbach  found  the  same  results  as 
when  dealing  with  younger  persons. 


ON  THE  INVALIDITY  OF  THE  ^ESTHESIOMETRIC 
METHOD  AS  A  MEASURE  OF  MEN- 
TAL FATIGUE. 

BY  DR.  GEO.  B.  GERMANN, 
Columbia   University. 

While  engaged  in  reading  the  literature  on  fatigue  some  two 
years  ago,  I  became  interested  in  Dr.  Griesbach's  investigation 
on  the  relation  between  mental  fatigue  and  the  discriminative 
sensibility  of  the  skin.1  Dr.  Griesbach,  it  will  be  recalled, 
claimed  to  have  ascertained  a  close  and  definite  correspondence 
to  exist  between  the  extent  of  sensation  areas  and  the  fatigue 
incident  to  school  and  other  mental  work,  the  main  hypothesis 
being  that  fatigue  increases  the  size  of  such  areas,  while  rest 
diminishes  their  extent  on  any  defined  portion  of  the  skin. 
His  interesting  results  apparently  confirmed  this  hypothesis, 
but  I  doubted  the  validity  of  his  method  and  therefore  his  re- 
sults. That  method  consisted  in  rapidly  increasing  minimal 
distances  and  decreasing  maximal  distances  between  the  aes- 
thesiometer  points  until  the  extent  of  the  sensation  area  was  de- 
termined. Furthermore,  apparently  only  one  determination 
was  ascertained  in  each  case.  Griesbach  fails  in  his  paper  to 
indicate  how  he  satisfied  himself  that  he  had  obtained  this  end 
within  any  reasonable  degree  of  accuracy.  It  is  a  matter  of 
common  experience  that  as  the  sensation-area  limit  is  ap- 
proached, tactile  illusions  become  numerous,  and  any  sin- 
gle determination  near  the  limit  may  be  more  of  a  guess,  or 
perhaps  a  purely  illusory  statement,  than  a  safe  judgment. 
The  employment  of  the  method  of  right  and  wrong  cases  is  un- 
doubtedly the  safest  method  whereby  to  determine  the  accuracy 
of  a  series  of  judgments  relative  to  tactile  discriminations. 

Wishing  to  get  at  the  facts  of  the  case,  I  undertook  the  fol- 
lowing investigation  during  the  period  from  February  24  to 

1  Archivfur  Hygiene,  1895,  Vol.  XXIV.,  124-212. 

599 


600  GEO.    B,    GERM  ANN. 

March  25,  1898.  As  subject  I  made  use  of  my  sister  S,  age 
twenty-three,  a  student  at  Barnard  College,  an  earnest  and 
diligent  worker,  health  good,  nervous  condition  normal. 

The  method  employed  was  that  of  right  and  wrong  cases. 
Jastrow's  aesthesiometer  was  used  during  the  entire  investiga- 
tion. This  aesthesiometer  is  so  constructed  that  when  the  points 
are  placed  upon  a  horizontal  surface  the  pressure  upon  that 
surface  is  equal  to  the  weight  of  a  constant  portion  of  the  in- 
strument. In  order  to  obviate  the  inequality  of  pressure  inci- 
dent to  tipping  the  aesthesiometer  sidewise  in  securing  a  one 
point  contact,  the  instrument  was  slightly  modified  so  as  to 
secure  the  desirable  equality  of  pressure  without  the  usual 
inclination. 

All  of  the  usual  and  necessary  conditions  attaching  to  aesthe- 
siometric  experiments,  such  as  equality  in  the  temperature  of 
the  room,  absence  of  undue  surface  tension  of  the  skin,  blind- 
folding the  subject,  securing  focalized  attention, etc.,  were  care- 
fully observed  and  rigidly  adhered  to.  All  determinations  were 
made  upon  a  circumscribed  area  of  the  skin  of -the  back  of 
the  right  hand  between  the  second  and  third  metacarpals  and 
about  two-thirds  distant  from  the  corresponding  carpals.  A 
previous  series  of  morning  determinations,  checked  by  means  of 
the  method  of  right  and  wrong  cases,  had  indicated  the  length 
of  the  sensation  area  of  the  circumscribed  region  tested  to  be, 
on  the  average,  a  slight  fraction  of  a  millimeter  over  two  centi- 
meters. This  (2  -f  cm.)  was  the  constant  distance  between  the 
aesthesiometer  points  employed  during  the  investigation. 

Fifty  contacts  were  made  during  each  of  the  first  thirty-five 
tests,  while  during  each  of  the  other  seven  tests  I  had  an  oppor- 
tunity to  make  one  hundred  contacts,  thus  affording  a  total  of 
2450  separate  discriminations  to  be  made  by  S  during  the  prog- 
ress of  the  investigation.  Each  contact  lasted  about  one-half 
a  second.  An  interval  of  ten  seconds  was  allowed  to  elapse 
between  successive  contacts.  On  27  out  of  the  30  days  covered 
by  the  investigation  a  total  of  42  tests  was  made.  Of  these  42 
tests,  20  occurred  in  the  morning  between  8  and  10  o'clock, 
previous  to  any  definite  study,  while  the  remaining  22  tests  were 
made  in  the  evening,  slightly  distributed,  but  for  the  most  part 


MENTAL   FATIGUE. 


601 


between  9  and  10  :  15  o'clock.  At  least  eight  hours  of  the  in- 
terim between  the  morning  and  the  evening  experiments  were 
always  fully  occupied  by  S  with  her  collegiate  studies,  of  which 
two  hours'  work  usually  preceded  the  evening  test. 

In  collating  my  data  I  have,  in  order  to  reduce  the  results  of 
the  experiments  to  a  very  simple  form,  determined  (a)  the  total 
percentage  of  errors  in  discrimination  occurring  during  each 
test,  (&)  the  percentage  of  errors  occurring  during  each  test  in 
the  discrimination  of  two  points  only,  and  (c)  the  percentage  of 
errors  occurring  during  each  test  in  the  discrimination  of  one  point 
only.  The  references  to  (a),  (&)  and  (c)  are  in  the  following  state- 
ments designated  by  total,  two  and  one,  respectively.  The  re- 
sults of  the  investigation  may  be  most  readily  collated  as  follows  : 


(i)  MORNING. 

(2)  EVENING. 

AVERAGE. 

VARIATION. 

AVERAGE. 

VARIATION. 

Total. 
Two. 
One. 

iS.i  % 

17-3% 
12.8  % 

6.8  % 
10.1% 

9-5  % 

12.6 
20+% 

5  + 

9-1  % 
16.4% 
5     % 

Explanation. — Glancing  at  statement  (i)  we  perceive  that 
during  the  morning  tests  the  total  percentage  of  errors  arising 
in  the  discrimination  of  both  two  points  and  one  point  amounts 
to  15.1^,  with  a  variation  of  6.SJ&  ;  that  the  percentage  of  er- 
rors arising  in  the  discrimination  of  two  points  alone  amounts 
to  17.3^0,  with  a  variation  of  10.1^;  and  that  the  percentage 
of  errors  arising  in  the  discrimination  of  one  point  alone  amounts 
to  1 2.0^,  with  a  variation  of  9.5^.  The  interpretation  of  state- 
ment (2),  which  refers  to  the  evening  tests,  is  to  be  made  in  the 
same  way. 

Of  the  total  number  of  tests,  14  pairs  were  conducted  on 
the  morning  and  evening  of  the  same  days.  It  is  both  interest- 
ing and  significant  to  consider  these  pairs  apart  from  the  entire 
series,  and  I  believe  that  the  following  statements  will  serve  to 
throw  the  results  into  bold  relief. 


(3) 

(4) 

(5) 

A.  M.  =  P.  M. 

A.  M.  >  P.  M. 

A.  M.  <  P.  M. 

Total. 

4 

8 

2 

Two. 

I 

9 

4 

One. 

2 

9 

3 

602  GEO.    B.    GERM  ANN. 

Explanation. — Statement  (3)  indicates  the  number  of  times 
that  the  morning  (A.  M.)  and  evening  (P.  M.)  tests  of  the  same 
day  contained  the  same  total  percentage  of  errors  in  the  discrimi- 
nation of  both  two  points  and  one  point  (total),  of  two  points 
only  (two),  and  of  one  point  only  (one).  Statement  (4)  indi- 
cates similar  results  with  respect  to  the  number  of  times  that 
the  percentage  of  errors  was  greater  in  the  morning  than  in  the 
evening  ;  while  statement  (5)  refers  to  the  number  of  times  that 
such  percentage  of  errors  was  less  in  the  morning  than  in  the 
evening. 

A  comparison  of  statements  (i)  and  (2)  brings  to  light  several 
important  facts.  The  percentage  of  all  errors  occurring  during 
the  morning  series  is  15.1^  =b6.8J&,  while  the  percentage  of  all 
errors  occurring  during  the  evening  experiments  is  12.6^)^9.1/0. 
That  is,  less  errors  occurred  in  the  evening  than  in  the  morning, 
if  the  variation  be  discarded.  Including  the  variation,  we  have 
practically  equal  results  at  the  upper  limit,  while  at  the  lower 
limit  the  errors  are  less  and  in  favor  of  the  evening  tests.  It  is 
also  readily  seen  that  the  percentage  of  errors  in  the  discrimina- 
tion of  two  points  is  slightly  less  in  the  morning  than  in  the 
evening  (this  taken  by  itself  would  favor  Dr.  Griesbach's  hy- 
pothesis) ;  and  that  the  percentage  of  errors  in  the  discrimina- 
tion of  one  point  is  more  than  twice  as  great  in  the  morning 
than  in  the  evening. 

If  we  now  examine  statements  (3),  (4)  and  (5),  the  general 
trend  of  my  results  will  become  much  more  clearly  defined. 
We  see  at  a  glance  that  out  of  the  14  days  there  considered,  on 
8  days  the  total  number  of  errors  was  greater  in  the  morning 
than  in  the  evening,  on  4  days  the  total  number  of  errors  of 
both  morning  and  evening  was  equal,  and  on  only  2  days  did 
the  total  number  of  errors  in  the  evening  exceed  the  number 
occurring  in  the  morning.  Furthermore,  on  9  days  was  the 
number  of  errors  occurring  in  the  discrimination  of  two  points 
greater  in  the  murning  than  in  the  evening,  on  4  days  less  in 
the  morning  than  in  the  evening,  and  on  i  day  equal.  The  in- 
terpretation of  the  results  of  the  one-point  discrimination  can 
be  readily  made  in  a  similar  manner. 

Now  according  to  Dr.  Griesbach's  hypothesis,  mental  fatigue 


MENTAL  FATIGUE.  603 

diminishes  cutaneous  sensibility,  and  this  diminution  in  sensi- 
bility is  normally  accompanied  by  and  correlated  with  an  in- 
crease in  the  extent  of  any  single  sensation  area.  Were  this 
normally  and  universally  true,  then  in  a  series  of  experiments 
where  the  distance  between  the  aesthesiometer  points  remained 
constant  we  should  be  led  to  expect  an  appreciable  increase  in 
the  number  of  errors  in  discrimination,  at  least  in  the  discrimi- 
nation of  two  points,  toward  evening  and  after  a  day  of  severe 
mental  work.  But  my  results  plainly  indicate  that  in  a  suf- 
ficiently prolonged  study  of  these  phenomena  in  the  case  of  a 
normal,  healthy  and  active  student  no  such  appreciable  increase 
in  errors  occurs.  In  fact,  an  examination  of  the  above  state- 
ments (i)  to  (5)  in  toto  may  have  the  tendency  to  force  the  con- 
viction that  just  a  diametrically  opposite  condition  of  affairs 
prevails ;  so  that  were  I  inclined  to  be  rash  I  might  be  tempted 
to  advance  the  hypothesis  that,  in  the  case  of  at  least  one  stu- 
dent, mental  work  and  its  concomitant  nervous  strain  have  a 
tendency  to  refine  cutaneous  discriminative  sensibility,  probably 
owing,  I  should  then  be  tempted  to  add,  to  a  general  hyper- 
aesthesia  induced  by  a  general  diffusion  of  neural  energy.  But 
I  do  not  advance  any  such  hypothesis. 

The  results  of  this  investigation  are  summarized  in  the  ac- 
panying  curve. 

Explanation  of  the  Curve. — The  line  of  abscissae  represents 
the  successive  tests,  while  the  line  of  ordinates  represents  the 
percentage  of  errors  occurring  during  each  test.  The  three 
main  lines  of  inquiry  are  here  indicated.  The  dash  curve  indi- 
cates the  percentage  of  errors  occurring  during  the  tests  in  the 
discrimination  of  two  points  ;  the  dotted  curve  indicates  similar 
errors  in  the  discrimination  of  one  point,  and  the  continuous 
heavy  line  indicates  the  total  percentage  of  error  in  each  test. 
The  following  numbered  tests  represent  morning  experiments  : 
2,  5,  6,  8, 10,  12,  13,  15, 17,  19,  21,  23,  25,  29,  31,  33,  37,  38, 
40,  42.  The  others  represent  the  evening  experiments.  The  fol- 
lowing tests  occurred  in  pairs — i.  e.,  on  the  morning  and  evening 
of  the  same  days  :  6  and  7,  8  and  9,  10  and  n,  13  and  14,  15  and 
16,  17  and  18,  19  and  20,  21  and  22,  23  and  24,  25and  26,  29  and 
30,  31  and  32,  33  and  34,  40  and  41.  It  will  be  observed  that  the 


604 


GE  O.   B.    GERM  ANN. 


MENTAL   FATIGUE.  605 

above  continuous  heavy  curve  contains  several  of  the  character- 
istic properties  of  a  practice  or  habit  curve.  This  is  what  we 
should  be  led  to  expect  from  the  work  of  others,  who  have  ascer- 
tained that  a  refinement  in  tactile  discrimination  ensues  as  the 
result  of  the  continued  exercise  of  this  sense.  It  may,  further- 
more, be  of  interest  to  note  that  during  the  progress  of  the  ex- 
periments S  several  times  remarked  of  her  own  accord  that  she 
believed  she  could  feel  the  two  points  better  than  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  series.  Beginning  with  the  twenty-fourth  test,  the 
variations  are  not  so  great  as  previously,  nor  are  the  percentages  of 
errors  very  large.  Yet  the  record  of  the  subjective  condition  of 
S  indicates  a  state  neither  more  nor  less  favorable  or  unfavorable 
toward  the  end  than  at  the  beginning.  In  order  to  anticipate 
any  objections  that  might  be  raised  on  the  ground  of  the  experi- 
menter's clumsiness  at  the  beginning  of  the  series,  I  wish  merely 
to  remark  that  I  thoroughly  tested  my  method  and  gained  fa- 
cility before  applying  it.  Of  course,  added  practice  begets  added 
facility. 

From  the  above  results,  I  believe,  we  may  reasonably  con- 
clude that  the  aesthesiometric  method  in  a  special  normal  case, 
at  least,  does  not  furnish  a  constant  nor  even  relative  index  as  to 
the  amount  of  mental  fatigue  experienced  by  the  individual. 
I  have  found  in  several  investigations  on  sensation  areas,  by 
Judd  and  Tawney,  an  enumeration  of  normal  fluctuations  that 
correspond  quite  closely  with  the  amplitude  of  variation  which 
Griesbach,  and  more  recently  Wagner,  ascribe  to  the  influence 
of  fatigue.  Furthermore,  the  subjective  state  of  S  was  care- 
fully ascertained  during  the  progress  of  the  investigation.  A 
general  comparison  of  that  subjective  condition  with  the  per- 
centage of  errors  during  each  test  gives  further  evidence  in 
support  of  my  conclusion  that  in  at  least  one  normal  case  the 
-percentage  of  errors  in  cutaneous  tactile  discrimination  bears 
no  constant  nor  even  relative  correspondence  to  the  menial 
fatigue  experienced  by  the  subject. 

I  am  convinced  that,  in  special  cases,  the  agsthesiometric 
method  is  absolutely  inadequate  for  the  determination  of  mental 
fatigue.  Moreover,  I  strongly  doubt  its  validity  in  any  case. 


A  PLEA  FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.     II. 

BY  W.  P.  MONTAGUE, 
Instructor  in  Logic^    University  of  California. 

6  De  Nattira  AmmceS 

This  inquiry  into  the  nature  of  the  soul,  or,  more  exactly, 
into  the  nature  of  soul-substance,  is  the  sequel  to  a  former  paper 
on  the  existence  of  soul-substance.  The  contents  of  that  paper 
were  as  follows : 

1.  An  introductory  statement  of  the  causes  for  the  unpopu- 
larity of  conceptions  of  substance  in  modern  philosophy  and 
particularly  in  modern  psychology. 

2.  A  description  of  the  central  problem  of  explaining  the 
apparent  interaction  of  the  world  of  Mind  or  teleological  law, 
and  the  world  of  Matter  or  mechanical  law. 

3.  An  outline  of  the  five  hypotheses  actually  used  in  the 
solution  of  this  problem  of  the  seeming  causality  between  in- 
commensurates,  to  wit : 

a.  Absolute  Teleology — the  denial  of  efficient  causes. 

b.  Materialism — the  denial  of  final  causes. 

c.  Occasionalism — the  co-reality  of  mechanism  and  teleology 
admitted — their  mutual   interaction  being   explicable   only   by 
miracles. 

d.  Parallelism — the  admission  of  both  realms  as  real,  but 
their  apparent  interaction  explained  as  an  illusion  due  to  a  com- 
plete parallelism. 

e.  Spiritualism — the   theory   of   a    soul-substance   different 
from  mind  and  matter,  yet  partaking  of  the  nature  of  both — 
therein  explaining  the  possibility  of  real  causality  between  the 
two  spheres. 

4.  An  exposition  and  attempted  refutation  of  the  first  four 
theories — especially  of  Parallelism.1 

1In  this  refutation  of  Parallelism  I  made  use  of  the  fact  that  concomitant 
variation  excluded  Parallelism.     There  seem  to  me  to  be  a  certain  obscurity  and 
606 


A    PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  607 

5.  An  indirect  proof  of  the  existence  of  soul-substance  based 
on  the  failure  of  all  other  possible  solutions  of  the  problem.     Di- 
rect proof  based  upon  the  axiom  of  "  No  action  at  a  distance." 

6.  Conclusion — exposition  and  proof  of  the  three  require- 
ments to  be  fulfilled  by  a  valid  conception  of  Substance  in  order 
to  distinguish  it  from  (a)  the  *  Ding  an  Sich,'  (b)  the  «  addi- 
tional attribute,'  (c)  the  '  totality  of  attributes.' 

It  is  the  explicit  purpose  of  the  present  paper  to  show  the 
nature  of  the  soul-substance  the  existence  of  which  is  to  be  re- 
garded as  proved  in  the  first  paper.  To  accomplish  this  task  it 
is  necessary  to  show  that  experience  affords  us  an  example  of  a 
mode  of  sequence  which,  while  it  is  neither  merely  mechanical 
nor  merely  teleological,  is  nevertheless  (i)  simple  and  intelligi- 
ble in  itself;  (2)  related  to  efficient  and  final  causality  as  genus 
to  species,  and  (3)  as  species  to  genus. 

Such  a  mode  of  experience  would  be  the  direct  expression 
or  definition  of  the  nature  of  soul-substance.  Its  substantiality 

imperfection  in  the  argument  as  there  given,  and  I  therefore  take  this  oppor- 
tunity of  supplementing  it  bj  the  following  statement : 

Notwithstanding  the  fact  that  Mill  (Logic  Bk.  III.  Ch.  8)  regarded  the 
Method  of  Difference  as  superior  to  the  Method  of  Concomitant  Variations,  yet 
it  seems  to  me  that  the  latter  method  is  by  far  the  more  cogent,  supplementing, 
as  it  does,  the  Method  of  Difference  very  much  as  that  method  supplements  the 
Method  of  Agreement.  The  Method  of  Agreement  gives  a  probability  that  A 
is  at  least  part  of  the  cause  of  B.  The  Method  of  Difference  gives  a  certainty 
that  A  is  at  least  part  of  the  cause  of  B.  The  Method  of  Concomitant  Varia- 
tion gives  a  certainty  that  A  is  part  of  the  cause  of  B,  and  also  a  probability 
that  A  is  the  whole  cause  of  B,  which  probability  approaches  certainty  as  the 
concomitance  approaches  perfection.  The  ground  of  our  belief  that  A  is  not 
merely  a  part  or  '  collocation  '  of  the  cause  of  B,  but  the  whole  cause  itself,  is  the 
fact  that  for  every  part  of  B  there  is  a  corresponding  part  in  A,  and  that  there 
is  nothing  in  A  without  its  correlatein  B.  The  concomitant  variation  of  the 
ratiocinative  and  physiological  sequences,  which  is  admitted  by  the  parallelist  to 
be  perfect  or  complete,  carries  us  beyond  parallelism ;  for  if  it  is  complete,  it 
implies  a  correspondence  of  every  infinitesimal  part  of  the  one  process  to  every 
infinitesimal  part  of  the  other.  Such  a  type  of  relation  is  perfect  as  to  its 
homogeneity  and  is  all  that  we  can  mean  by  causality.  Just  as  two  parallel 
lines  when  prolonged  to  infinity  cease  to  be  parallel,  and  just  as  two  similar  ob- 
jects if  their  similarity  were  infinite  would  cease  to  be  similar  and  become  iden- 
tical—-just  so  a  psycho-physical  parallelism  when  it  is  made  as  perfect  as  it  claims 
to  be — and  must  be — ceases  to  be  parallelism  and  becomes  causality.  In  short,  the 
parallelistic  theory  when  closely  examined  is  seen  to  be  necessarily  and  pecu- 
liarly self-transcendent. 


608  W.  P.   MONTAGUE. 

with  respect  to  the  mental  and  material  attributes  would  be  pro- 
visionally manifested  in  its  appearance  as  the  common  Limit 
approached  on  the  one  hand  by  a  series  of  teleological  sequences, 
becoming  more  and  more  perfect,  /'.  e.,  more  free  from  the  taint 
of  contingency — and  on  the  other  hand,  by  a  series  of  mechanical 
sequences  approaching  mechanical  perfection  or  absolute  inde- 
pendence of  all  teleological  references. 

The  resemblance  between  the  concept  of  Limit  and  the  con- 
cept of  substance  is  sufficiently  striking  to  demand  careful 
consideration.  What  is  a  mathematical  limit?  It  is  the  goal 
or  end  approached  by  a  series,  e.  g.,  the  sum  of  i  +  ^  +  J^ 
_j_  y§  _j_  ...  approaches  2  as  its  limit.  Now  2  is  a  perfectly 
definite  thing  with  a  perfectly  real  and  definable  nature ;  at  the 
same  time  it  differs  absolutely  from  the  sum  of  n  terms  of  the 
series,  when  n  is  any  number  we  please.  If  we  represent  the 
sum  of  the  first  r  terms  of  Jthis  series  by  2"r,  we  may  express  our 
series  thus  :  2\  22  23  2r  ••>  2,  where  2  is  the  limit  or  last  term 
of  the  series.  It  is  to  be  noted  that  the  members  of  this  series 
(so  far  as  they  are  viewed  serially,  i.  e.,  as  interrelated)  have 
one  common  quality  which  makes  us  classify  them  as  members 
of  one  series.  The  influence  of  the  limit  of  a  series  is  present 
throughout  the  series  determining  the  relations  of  the  members  to 
one  another  precisely  as  the  Universal  of  a  class  is  present  in 
each  of  the  particular  members. 

The  limit  differs,  however,  from  the  mere  Universal  in  two 
highly  important  points  : 

1.  While  it  is  admitted  by  all  except  Platonists  that  the  Uni- 
versal can  never  exist  apart  from  or  independently  of  its  partic- 
ulars, yet  it  is  perfectly  evident  that  the  Limit  can  and  invariably 
does  exist  as  prior  to  and  aside  from  the  members  of  the  series 
which  approach  it. 

2.  The  Universal  can  never  be  made  a  member  of  its  own 
genus   (although  Aristotle   accused  Plato    of    doing    that  very 
thing)  ;  while,  on  the  other  hand,  the  Limit  is  always  a  member 
of  the  series  which  it  determines,  e.  g.,  2  is  the  last  member  of 
the  series  given  above,  and  it  is  also  a  member  differing  from 
all  previous   members  in  that  it  alone  is  an   integral    number. 
Thus  it  appears  that  the  Limit  has  not  only  the  generic  char- 


A   PLEA   FOR    SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  609 

acter  common  to  all  universals,  but  that  it  also  has  the  individual 
character  of  existing  and  of  being  known  independently  of  any- 
thing outside.  And  last  and  most  remarkable,  it  has  the  char- 
acteristic of  being  a  member,  and  a  wholly  unique  member,  of 
its  own  class  (series). 

When  we  affirmed  that  the  substance  concept  must  possess 
the  three  qualities  of  being  : 

1.  Self-intelligible. 

2.  Related  to  its  attributes  as  genus  to  species. 

3.  Related  to  its  attributes  as  species  to  genera.     We  might 
well  have  felt  that  modern  philosophy  was  fully  justified  in  re- 
pudiating such  a  thoroughly  inconsistent  and  paradoxical  notion 
as  that  of  Substance.     And  yet  in  the  familiar  and  useful  con- 
ception of  a  Mathematical   Limit  we   are   able  to  see  with  the 
greatest  clearness  and  certainty  all  of  these  three  essential  prop- 
erties of  Substantiality.     By  virtue  of  its  knowability  and   defi- 
niteness,  the  concept  of  substance,  like  its  mathematical  brother 
the  Limit,  differs  from  Pure  Being  or  from  the  Ding  an  Sich ; 
by  virtue  of  its  generic  character  it  differs  from  all  particular 
qualities  or  atoms,  and  by  virtue  of  its  specific  character  it  differs 
from  universals  or  ideas. 

In  view  of  these  considerations  we  shall  be  guided  in  our 
search  for  the  nature  of  soul-substance  by  the  well-known 
method  of  Limits.  We  have  for  our  problem  given  the  nature 
of  the  attributes  (viz.,  mind  and  matter),  and  the  fact  of  their 
interaction — to  discover  the  nature  of  the  Medium  (viz.,  soul- 
substance),  in  virtue  of  which  the  relation  of  these  attributes  is 
possible. 

Our  undertaking  will  be  divided  in  two  general  parts. 

i .  The  search  for  the  limiting  forms  or  perfect  types  of  me- 
chanical or  material  relation.  2.  The  search  for  the  limiting 
forms  of  teleological  or  mental  relation. 

First,  then,  we  have  to  seek  for  the  limiting  or  perfect  form 
of  mechanical  causality  or  of  the  relation  between  facts  as  such. 
Take  the  following  case  :  I  hear  the  word  'Jacques/  and  im- 
mediately there  presents  itself  to  my  mind  a  picture  of  a  melan- 
choly fellow  in  a  green  doublet ;  following  upon  this  picture 
there  comes  another  picture  of  another  melancholy  man  in  a 


6iO  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

red  cloak.  I  am  a  school  boy  commanded  to  write  a  composi- 
tion on  *  As  you  Like  It,'  and  I  write  the  sentence,  "Jacques 
resembles  Hamlet."  This  is  a  typical  psychical  sequences,  and 
without  attempting  the  impossible  task  of  a  complete  analysis 
of  what  occurs,  it  will  at  least  be  useful  for  our  purpose  to  note 
some  of  the  more  obvious  factors  at  work  in  the  process.  In 
the  first  place,  Hamlet  and  Jacques  both  possess  the  quality  of 
*  melancholy,'  hence  I  have  a  rational  ground  for  asserting  their 
resemblance.  Hamlet  is  associated  with  Jacques  as  co-member 
of  the  same  species.  This  then  is  the  teleological  ground  of 
my  judgment  regarded  as  a  psychological  sequence,  and  when 
so  regarded  it  is  usually  called  Association  by  Similarity.  In 
the  second  place,'!  write  down  the  sentence,  "Jacques  resembles 
Hamlet."  I  write  this  because  I  want  to  finish  my  exercise  in 
composition  as  soon  as  possible  in  order  to  be  free  to  go  skating. 
I  do  it  to  fulfill  a  want  or  need  of  my  immediate  organism. 
This  desire  for  satisfaction,  or  aversion  to  dissatisfaction,  may 
be  called  the  organic  or  biological  cause  of  the  action.  In  the 
third  place,  the  image  of  Jacques  in  a  green  doublet  calls  up 
the  image  of  Hamlet  in  a  red  cloak — why  this  change  of  color? 
Upon  reflection  I  cannot  remember  ever  having  seen  Hamlet 
dressed  in  red,  and  yet  it  is  this  color  and  no  other  that  is  pre- 
sented with  vividness  to  my  mind's  eye.  We  know,  however, 
that  green  and  red  are  complementary  colors,  and  that  one  is 
apt  to  call  up  the  other  owing  to  what  is  probably  a  chemical 
change  in  the  substance  of  the  retina.  Let  us  then  call  this  the 
chemical  cause  of  the  process.  And  now  there  is  one  more 
type  of  causality  at  work  in  the  production  of  this  judgment. 
It  so  happened  that  I  read  <  Hamlet '  and  *  As  You  Like  It '  to- 
gether. As  a  consequence  of  this  fact,  the  sense  impressions 
of  the  one  play  are  very  closely  bound  up  with  those  of 
the  other.  The  two  sets  of  personages  are  associated  by 
Contiguity.  No  one  doubts  the  validity  of  this  psychical 
law  of  Association  by  Contiguity.  Some  psychologists,  in  their 
praiseworthy  ambition  to  banish  final  causes  from  their  science, 
even  go  so  far  as  to  reduce  Association  by  Similarity  to  a  mere 
complex  kind  of  Association  by  Contiguity.  Inasmuch  as 
Contiguity  is  a  mechanical  and  temporal  affair,  while  Similarity 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  6ll 

is  Ideological  and  non-temporal,  we  may  assume,  on  the  strength 
of  the  criticism  of  Psychophysical  Parallelism  given  in  the 
former  paper,  that  this  attempt  at  simplification  is  doomed  to  fail- 
ure. It  may  perhaps  be  asked  on  what  grounds  we  select  the 
law  of  Association  by  Contiguity  as  the  distinctively  mechanical 
type  of  mental  causality.  By  way  of  answer  let  us  consider 
what  probably  happens  when  two  ideas  are  associated  by  Con- 
tiguity. A  sense  impression  a  is  suggested  to  the  mind  at  a 
given  time  tr  Another  sense  impression  ft  is  suggested  to  the 
mind  at  a  later  period  of  time  /2.  Physiological  psychology 
warrants  the  supposition  that  at  the  moments  when  a  and  ft  are 
perceived  there  are  two  physical  modifications  a  and  b  induced 
on  the  matter  of  the  brain,  and  the  same  science  also  warrants 
us  in  supposing  that,  corresponding  to  the  mental  process  of  a 
arousing  ft,  there  is  a  physical  process  consisting  in  the  com- 
munication by  spatial  transition  of  something  in  a  to  something 
in  b.  Experimental  psychology  proceeds  further,  and  assures 
us  that,  other  things  equal,  the  rapidity  and  the  certainty  or  con- 
stancy of  the  association  between  a  and  ft  varies  inversely  as 
the  length  of  the  time  interval  separating  tl  and  ty  Granting 
these  facts,  we  have  the  case  of  a  mental  sequence  conforming 
exactly  to  the  laws  which  govern  a  purely  physical  change,  i.  e., 
a  change  from  one  position  in  space  to  another.  The  rapidity 
and  certainty  of  this  change  moreover  are  measured  by  the  '  dis- 
tance '  between  the  two  positions.  From  this  it  follows  that  we 
are  justified  in  the  assertion  that  in  Association  by  Contiguity 
we  have  a  case  of  psychical  sequence  conforming  to  the  quanti- 
tative laws  of  mechanics. 

So  much  for  the  four  kinds  of  causes  which  we  may  call  the 
Teleological,  the  Biological,  the  Chemical  and  the  Mechanical. 
Let  us  now  leave  the  domain  of  mental  life  in  which  these  four 
kinds  of  cause  are  usually  found  operating  together,  in  order 
that  we  may  study  in  comparative  isolation,  and  so  far  as  may 
be  in  serial  order  these  several  types  of  relation.  At  one  end 
of  the  series  we  have  purely  '  final  causality,'  at  the  other  end 
we  have  *  efficient  causality.'  Between  the  two  we  have  the 
biological  causality,  which  is  predominantly  teleological,  and  the 
chemical  causality,  which  is  predominantly  mechanical.  When 


6l2  W.  P.    MONTAGUE. 

we  leave  the  neutral  or  mixed  ground  of  psychology  for  the  field 
of  biology,  what  difference  do  we  notice  in  the  laws  of  the  two 
sciences,  as  to  their  respective  types  of  relations  between  facts? 
In  biology,  all  changes  or  sequences  are  explained  on  the 
basis  of  the  desires  or  needs  of  the  organism.  Two  phenomena 
a  and  ft  are  seen  to  follow  one  another  in  time.  If  the  sequence 
fulfills  the  three  conditions  requisite  for  the  valid  inference  of 
causality,  viz.,  mutual  presence  and  absence  and  concomitant 
variation — then  the  biologist  is  justified  in  assuming  that  a  and 
ft  are  connected  with  some  specific  need  of  the  organism  and 
therein  connected  with  one  another.  This  medium  of  relation 
has  two  aspects — a  qualitative  aspect  which  depends  upon  the 
kind  of  organism  in  question  and  the  particular  circumstances 
in  which  it  is  placed,  and  a  quantitative  aspect  which  is  simply 
the  strength  of  the  desire.  Given  the  knowledge  of  these 
two  conditions  the  actions  or  sequences  of  an  animal  may  be 
predicted.  In  the  higher  organisms  the  qualitative  aspect  is 
much  more  pronounced  than  in  the  lower  organisms.  In  the 
case  given  above  in  which  I  associated  Hamlet  with  Jacques,  the 
quantitative  aspect  of  the  sequence,  regarded  biologically,  would 
be  the  degree  to  which  my  judgment  of  resemblance  contributed 
to  the  preservation  of  my  organism.  Obviously  this  was  very 
small  indeed.  If  I  had  made  any  other  assertion  or  had  failed 
to  make  any,  the  vitality  of  my  organism  would  have  suffered  to 
an  extent  almost  inappreciable.  Supposing,  however,  that,  in- 
stead of  desiring  to  write  a  composition  on  a  play  of  Shakes- 
peare's, I  had  desired  to  satisfy  a  particular  craving  for  a  certain 
kind  of  food — in  this  case  the  quantitative  aspect  of  the  causal 
relation  would  play  a  much  greater  part.  In  a  healthy  organism 
all  cravings  are  normal,  and  the  satisfaction  of  any  one  is  a  direct 
contribution  to  the  vitality  of  the  animal.  In  so  far  as  these 
cravings  are  numerous  and  varied  the  same  needs  of  the  organism 
can  be  satisfied  by  different  objects.  An  animal  desires  one  kind 
of  food,  but  if  this  is  unattainable,  his  desire  can  be  almost  as 
well  satisfied  by  another.  In  short,  just  what  the  particular  acts 
of  an  animal  will  be  depends  upon  qualitative  conditions  much 
more  than  on  conditions  of  quantity.  Nevertheless  as  we  de- 
scend in  the  scale  of  organic  complexity  the  qualitative  factor 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  613 

in  the  actions  decreases  in  importance,  until  in  the  lowest  types 
of  animals  or  the  highest  types  of  vegetables  we  find  a  few  well- 
defined  desires,  usually  arranged  in  a  pretty  definite  hierarchy, 
and  it  becomes  more  and  more  difficult  to  satisfy  one  desire  with 
the  objects  of  another,  or  to  leave  a  desire  unsatisfied  without 
destroying  the  whole  organism.  We  express  this  decrease  of 
qualitative  and  increase  of  quantitative  causality  by  saying  that 
the  lower  the  organism  the  less'  selective  are  its  acts,  the  more 
is  it  dependent  upon  or  determined  by  its  environment,  and 
the  more  certainly  predictable  are  its  changes.  Its  nature  is 
less  intrinsic  and  more  extrinsic.  Finally  when  in  the  descend- 
ing scale  we  leave  the  lowest  type  of  vegetable  and  enter  upon 
the  study  of  the  actions  of  the  crystal,  we  find  the  qualities  of 
this  semi-organism  arranged  not  merely  in  a  general  hierarchy, 
in  which  each  desire  is  indefinitely  stronger  or  more  important 
than  its  neighbor  next  below,  but  rather  do  we  find  a  state  of 
things  in  which  each  quality  bears  a  definite  and  mathematically 
determinable  relation  to  every  other  quality.  The  changes  in 
the  crystal  become  subject  to  the  a  priori  laws  of  quantity  when 
once  we  have  learned  empirically  the  specific  or  qualitative 
nature  of  the  crystal.  We  may  put  the  matter  thus — why  and 
how  the  crystal  should  be  what  it  is  is  not  explicable,  i.  e.,  not 
dependent  upon  any  objects  external  to  it,  but  being  what  it  is, 
all  its  changes  may  be  explained  or  predicted. 

Let  us  now  pass  from  the  sphere  of  Biological  Causality  to 
that  of  Chemical  Causality.  At  first  sight  the  new  class  of  phe- 
nomena does  not  appear  to  differ  very  much  from  the  phenomena 
of  crystallization.  We  have  a  substance  known  to  possess  cer- 
tain properties  or  qualities,  known  also  to  be  decomposable  into 
a  definite  number  of  certain  other  and  simpler  substances  called 
elements,  and  finally  known  to  possess  definite  and  unchange- 
able relations  both  qualitative  and  quantitative  to  all  other  sub- 
stances. We  notice,  however,  that  we  can  decompose  a  chem- 
ical substance  into  its  elements  and  then  put  these  elements 
together  and  get  back  the  original  substance.  Now  with  no 
type  of  organism  or  of  crystal  is  this  reverse  process  possible. 
And  this  is  the  most  noteworthy  difference  between  the  sub- 
stances of  biology  and  the  substances  of  chemistry.  The  chem- 


614  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

ical  substance  has  apparently  no  intrinsic  life  of  its  own,  not 
even  a  crystalline  power  of  initiative.  It  has,  to  be  sure,  a  very 
rich  qualitative  nature,  but  we  can  force  it  to  run  through  the 
whole  gamut  of  its  changes  simply  by  altering  its  relations  to 
other  substances.  An  organism,  however,  refuses  to  be  put 
through  its  tricks  against  its  will.  Break  a  crystal  or  an 
organism  and  you  cannot  mend  it.  Break  the  chemical  com- 
pound and  usually  nothing  is  easier  than  to  mend  it.  Hence  in 
Chemical  Causality  we  first  come  to  what  appears  to  be  a  rever- 
sible series — the  possibility  of  a  change  which  is  not  also  a 
growth.  A  chemical  substance  can  be  changed  in  two  direc- 
tions— can  grow  old  and  can  grow  young,  i.  e.,  not  grow  at  all, 
but  only  alter.  We  have,  to  be  sure,  the  interesting  fact  that 
all  chemical  processes  have  strong  preferences  of  direction  in 
these  reversible  changes.  It  is  very  easy  to  produce  water  by 
combining  hydrogen  and  oxygen,  while  it  is  somewhat  more  dif- 
ficult to  decompose  the  water  into  its  elements.  And  this  fact 
is  interesting,  I  say,  as  showing  that  the  break  between  the  or- 
ganic and  the  inorganic  world  may  not  be  an  absolute  matter, 
but  only  one  of  degree.  A  chemical  substance  which  persisted 
in  altering  in  one  direction  only  in  spite  of  all  external  agencies 
could  very  properly  be  classed  as  an  organism. 

As  we  turn  from  the  more  complex  substances  to  the  less 
complex,  we  naturally  find  the  qualities  of  the  substance  grow- 
ing more  and  more  simple  and  the  quantitative  factor  coming 
more  and  more  into  prominence.  Until  the  discovery  of  Men- 
deleef's  Law  it  seemed  that  the  process  of  simplification  had 
come  to  a  final  stop  with  the  classification  of  all  chemical  sub- 
stances into  various  quantitative  compounds  of  the  original  ele- 
ments. Mendeleef  s  Law,  however,  shows  that  these  elements 
are  not  only  related  to  one  another  quantitatively,  but  that  the 
several  qualities  which  distinguish  the  elements  from  one  another 
form  a  somewhat  irregular,  though  undeniable  series,  analo- 
gous in  type  to  the  series  of  spectrum  colors.  The  nature  of 
this  series  is  such  as  to  enable  us  to  predict  the  qualitative  na- 
ture of  an  undiscovered  element  simply  from  a  knowledge  of 
its  quantitative  relation  to  Hydrogen.  Thus  in  this  last  dis- 
covery we  see  the  element  of  quantity  all  but  supreme,  and  it  is 


A   PLEA   FOR    SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  615 

an  easy  step  from  these  quantitatively  related  elements  of  Phys- 
ical Chemistry  to  the  quantitatively  related  states  of  matter  which 
form  the  subject-matter  of  physics  proper.  Ice  changes  to 
water  and  water  to  gas,  and  these  three  qualities  are  all  pro- 
duced in  turn  by  simply  changing  the  motion  of  the  molecules. 
Motion,  however,  is  but  a  function  of  Space  and  Time,  and 
to  reduce  all  change  to  a  change  of  molecular  motion  is  equiva- 
lent to  reducing  all  causality  to  the  change  of  spatial  position 
by  a  material  body.  The  laws  that  govern  molecular  motion 
are  not  yet  known,  hence  physics  is  still  to  some  extent  depend- 
ent upon  the  empirical  observation  of  qualities.  But  now  the 
qualitative  element  is  merely  the  ratio  cognoscendi  of  the  causal 
laws  and  not  as  in  biology,  the  ratio  essendi.  In  mechanics  and 
kinematics  we  at  last  arrive  within  sight  of  pure  quantitative 
causality  untainted  with  any  spark  of  teleology,  /.  £.,  of  qual- 
ity, unless  indeed  the  quanta  of  mass  and  distance  be  themselves 
called  qualitative. 

Mechanical  change  is  change  of  position.  Mechanical 
causality  is  the  law  which  governs  this  change  of  position,  and 
it  is  a  simple  function  of  the  initial  velocity,  the  mass  and  the 
distance.  The  velocity  or  measure  of  motion  is,  as  we  have 
seen,  simply  the  limiting  ratio  of  a  particular  filled  space  to  a 
particular  filled  time,  while  the  mass  of  a  body,  as  Karl  Pear- 
son so  well  shows,  can  be  expressed  or  measured  in  terms  of 
the  acceleration  produced  upon  other  bodies.  The  velocity  of 
the  falling  apple  has  a  definite  acceleration,  which  is  the  effect 
and  measure  of  the  mass  of  the  earth.  Since  mechanical  change 
can  be  adequately  expressed  wholly  in  terms  of  space  and  time, 
and  since  time  relations  permit  of  spatial  representation,  we 
have  it  in  our  power  to  symbolize  adequately  every  mechanical 
change  by  a  geometrical  graph,  called  by  its  discoverer  a 
6  Hodograph.'  When  a  body  moves  according  to  mechanical 
law  we  can  regard  any  antecedent  state  of  that  movement  as  the 
cause  of  every  consequent  state  or  effect.  In  short,  it  is  only 
in  the  case  of  the  freely  moving  particles  that  we  can  accept 
with  a  clear  conscience  the  Humean  identification  of  causality 
with  universal  sequence.  If  we  feel  it  necessary  to  ask  for  the 
third  substance,  or  thing  in  virtue  of  which  the  two  terms  of  ante- 


616  w.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

cedence  and  consequence  are  causally  united,  we  simply  point 
to  the  empty  time  and  space  intervals  separating  the  two  terms. 
The  very  fact  that  the  pure  movement  between  two  *  space- 
time  '  or  «  Hodographic '  points  is  not  only  a  continuous  change 
in  the  popular  sense  of  the  word  continuous,  but  a  homo- 
geneous or  truly  continuous  change,  is  enough  to  satisfy  the 
demand  of  reason  for  the  third  thing  or  medium  as  ground  of 
relation  between  two  terms.  Two  commensurate  quantities  are 
just  as  truly  related  through  the  fact  of  continuity  as  are  two 
qualities  through  the  fact  of  participating  in  a  third  or  generic 
quality. 

Now  not  only  has  Professor  Pearson  (after  Clifford)  reduced 
Mechanics  to  a  species  of  geometry,  but  geometry  itself  is  re- 
ducible to  a  species  of  algebra,  called  analytic  geometry.  In 
virtue  of  this  latter  science  we  are,  with  respect  to  a  fixed  point 
chosen  arbitrarily  and  called  an  origin,  able  to  express  all  posi- 
tion in  space  as  a  complex  algebraic  quantity,  the  degree  of 
complexity  depending  upon  the  number  of  axes  necessary  to 
distinguish  every  point  from  every  other. 

If  all  positions  were  confined  to  a  straight  line,  we  could  de- 
termine each  of  them  by  a  single  algebraic  quantity  (V).  If, 
again,  all  our  points  were  in  a  plane  we  should  require  a  dual 
quantity  for  the  definition  of  a  point  (x9y)  •  In  our  actual  three- 
dimensional  space  we  require  three  axes  from  which  to  meas- 
ure, and  consequently  a  point  can  only  be  algebraically  defined 
by  a  three-fold  quantity  (x9y9  z).  When  we  introduce  in  addi- 
tion to  the  merely  spatial  relations  the  kinematical  factor  of  the 
temporal  velocity  with  which  the  particles  are  altering  their  po- 
sitions, we  are  obliged  to  bring  a  fourth  element  (z;)  into  our 
quantity  in  order  to  define  it  as  distinct  from  its  '  spatio-tem- 
poral '  or  hodographic  neighbors  ;  and  finally  when  we  take  into 
consideration  the  mechanical  factor  of  Mass  or  accelerated 
velocity  (w),  we  may  be  said  to  be  dealing  with  changes  in  a 
five-dimensional  world,  and  consequently  to  require  a  quantity 
of  five-fold  complexity  in  order  to  express  the  whole  state  of  a 
body  with  a  given  mass  and  velocity,  at  a  given  point  in  space 
and  time,  in  such  a  way  that  its  future  states,  i.  e.9  its  future 
relations  to  another  similarly  determined  body  (viz.,  the  center 


A   PLEA   FOR    SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  617 

of  mass  of  the  system  in  which  it  is),  may  be  predicted  with  cer- 
tainty. Thus  any  body  which  being  a  member  of  a  mechanical 
system  is  at  any  moment  of  time  ^  represented  by  the  five  co- 
ordinate quantities  (  \xv  yv  ^J,^,  z^),  signifying  respectively 
its  position  in  three-dimensional  space,  its  velocity  or  position  in 
time,  and  its  acceleration  or  mass,  all  relative  to  a  fixed  point 
O  which  is  both  origin  and  center  of  mass — will  at  any  subse- 
quent moment  /2  have  changed  to  a  state  which  can  be  repre- 
sented by  Q#2,jx2,  z2]  v2,  w^,  where  ({#2,  j/2,  z2}va,  w^)  is  a  deter- 
minable  function  of  ( \xl9yl9  z^\vv  ^1)9  and  as  before  said,  we 
can  regard  the  body  in  the  first  state  as  the  cause  of  the  body  in 
the  second  state.  For  brevity  let  us  call  these  two  complex 
quantities  Al  and  A2.  Now  we  know  for  various  reasons  (among 
others  the  fact  of  the  loss  of  energy  necessary  in  every  system) 
that  no  change  is  wholly  cyclic,  t.  £.,  the  state  of  a  material  sys- 
tem never  repeats  itself  in  time.  With  respect  to  O9  Al  and 
A2  or  An  and  An  -f  m  must  differ,  and  what  is  more  important, 
they  must  differ  positively  or  in  one  direction  only — for  if  they 
did  not  the  history  of  a  system  would  repeat  itself  and  we  should 
have  a  cyclic  change,  which  is  impossible.  An  +  m  can  never 
be  equal  to  An,  and  consequently  An,  An  +  i,  An  -f  2  ... 
An  +  m  must  be  quantities  which  stand  in  an  irreversible  series 
— a  series  such  that  any  member  Ar  must  be  *  further '  from 
Ar  —  2  than  from  Ar  —  i.  This  character  is,  however,  pre- 
cisely the  character  of  our  own  numerical  series,  and  we  may, 
therefore,  say  that  the  series  in  question  is  not  only  an  irrever- 
sible but  an  increasing  series.  But  it  must  be  remembered  that 
all  this  is  only  true  with  respect  to  our  own  chosen  origin  O. 
We  can  always  select  another  point  in  space  O'  as  origin  and 
center  of  mass,  with  respect  to  which  the  series  A19  A2,  A^  could 
be  read  in  the  reverse  direction,  where,  for  example,  A2  with 
respect  to  O  could  be  shown  to  be  less  than  Al  with  respect  to 
O'.  Hence  it  is  only  on  the  supposition  that  O  is  a  fixed  point 
that  we  can  show  that  mechanical  change  is  irreversible  or  ab- 
solute, and  not  reversible  or  relative.  What  does  this  possibility 
of  selecting  another  origin  mean  ?  It  means  simply  that  no  given 
system  is  absolute,  but  only  relative,  and  that  consequently  the 
changes  in  a  system  can  only  be  predicted  in  so  far  as  that  system 


618  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

is  taken  as  absolute,  /.  <?.,  as  either  isolated  from  or  inclusive  of  the 
rest  of  the  universe.  This  is  precisely  the  assumption  upon  which 
Science  proceeds.  In  a  small  system  of  bodies  the  error  due  to 
the  interference  of  other  systems  is  great.  As  the  system  is  en- 
larged the  changes  become  more  regular,  and  the  error  decreases, 
owing  to  the  diminishing  interference  of  other  systems  until  it 
finally  can  be  neglected.  Could  we  grasp  the  universe  as  a 
whole,  we  should  then  have  a  system  in  which  every  element 
necessarily  changed  in  one  direction,  and  could  consequently  be 
expressed  as  an  increasing  quantity  or  series  of  quantities  with 
respect  to  an  absolute  center  of  Mass  or  Origin. 

We  have  now  reviewed  the  various  types  of  causality  in  the 
order  of  descent.  Starting  from  the  mixed  stage  of  psychical 
causation,  we  traversed  the  fields  of  biology,  chemistry  and 
physics,  gradually  eliminating  the  qualitative  or  teleological 
element  until  we  finally  reached  the  perfect  or  limiting  form  of 
mechanical  causality  in  which  the  cause  became  the  antecedent 
and  the  effect  the  consequent ;  the  sole  relation  between  the  two 
being  the  relation  of  a  less  quantity  Al  to  a  greater  quantity  A2. 
Pure  quantitative  increase  is  then  the  limit  or  substantial  form 
of  relation  in  the  mechanical  world  or  world  of  Facts.  Let  us 
now  endeavor  to  find  the  limiting  form  of  teleological  causality, 
the  relation  between  Meanings. 

Returning  to  our  point  of  departure,  the  case  of  mixed 
causality  or  psychical  association,  we  may  remember  that  the 
process  in  which  the  psychical  state  « Jacques  '  called  up  the 
psychical  state  '  Hamlet '  (which  we  expressed  in  the  judgment, 
'Jacques  resembles  Hamlet ')  was  grounded  or  explicable  on  a 
dual  relation  between  the  antecedent  subject  and  the  consequent 
predicate.  These  two  types  of  causal  relation  are  named  by 
psychology  Association  by  Similarity  and  Association  by  Con- 
tiguity, the  former  being  a  case  of  teleological  or  final  causality  ; 
the  latter,  a  case  of  mechanical  or  efficient  causality.  In  order 
to  find  out  just  what  mechanical  causality  meant,  we  were 
obliged  to  work  downward  through  the  various  conditions  which 
governed  this  particular  sequence,  regarded  on  its  factual  or 
particular  side,  until  in  the  course  of  our  process  all  those  teleo- 
logical elements  which  permeate  the  factual  order  were  one 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  619 

after  another  eliminated.  We  have  then  now  to  follow  the 
exactly  opposite  course ;  instead  of  gradually  eliminating  the 
biological  and  chemical  qualities  which  taint  the  space-time 
world  of  the  factual  order  with  a  teleological  meaning — a  nor- 
mative significance — which  is  logically  foreign  to  it,  we  must 
now  proceed  to  eliminate  the  hypothetical  and  assertorial  par- 
ticularity which  taints  the  non-temporal  world  of  teleological 
norms  with  an  irrational  and  mechanical  character  which  de- 
tracts from  its  purity.  Indeed  this  is  one  of  the  most  noteworthy 
and  remarkable  characteristics  of  the  universe — that  although 
the  '  world  of  norms  '  is  diametrically  opposed  to  the  '  world  of 
facts,'  yet  each  of  these  diametrically  opposed  worlds  is  tainted 
and  permeated  with  the  characteristics  of  the  other.  Biology 
and  chemistry  are  certainly  factual,  as  distinguished  from 
normative,  sciences,  and  yet  we  have  seen  to  what  extent  they 
imply  the  qualitative  or  teleological  element.  Just  so  logic  and 
ethics  are  distinctively  normative  sciences,  nevertheless  they 
imply  as  we  shall  see  all  sorts  of  factual  considerations.  And 
it  is  this  fact  of  separation  without  purity  which  makes  the 
method  of  limits  the  only  proper  instrument  for  attaining  a  com- 
prehension on  the  one  hand  of  what  an  Idea  or  norm  really  is, 
and  the  nature  of  its  relation  to  other  Ideas  or  norms ;  and, 
on  the  other  hand,  of  what  a  mechanical  or  material  fact  is 
and  its  relation  to  other  facts.  The  Judgment  «  Hamlet  re- 
sembles Jacques '  is  not  a  purely  normative  judgment,  that  is  to 
say,  it  does  not  adequately  represent  that  absolute  relation  be- 
tween two  meanings  which  we  call  Truth.  For  in  the  first  place 
there  is  no  such  person  as  Jacques  and  no  such  person  as  Ham- 
let. They  live  in  a  world  which  does  not  truly  exist,  and  it  is 
only  by  my  assumption  of  this  make-believe  world  as  a  real 
world  that  my  judgment  is  true.  In  short  my  meaning  would 
be  more  truly  expressed  if  I  said,  "  If  Jacques  were  real  he  would 
resemble  Hamlet."  This  judgment  is  then  a  judgment  of  possi- 
bility, and  as  such  its  truth  is  imperfect.  We  call  this  kind  of 
imperfect  judgment  by  the  name  <  Hypothetical,'  which  means 
that  the  relation  is  not  grounded  in  reality  but  on  a  hypothesis. 
But  you  will  at  once  reply — Hamlet  and  Jacques  are  not  merely 
hypothetical  personages,  mere  empty  possibles,  a  mere  possible 


620  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

is  nothing,  and  obviously  Jacques  is  not  nothing  but  a  very  im- 
portant being  whom  the  world  could  ill  dispense  with.  In  fine, 
Jacques  has  some  sort  of  actuality  as  a  state  of  my  conscious- 
ness and  of  many  consciousnesses,  of  which  Shakespeare's  is  one. 
As  such  then  it  is  more  than  a  hypothetical  relation  in  which  he 
stands  to  Hamlet.  Taking  Hamlet  and  Jacques  as  states  of 
consciousness  it  is  really  and  not  hypothetically  true  that  they 
resemble  one  another.  But  what  is  the  ground  of  this  relation? 
Is  it  a  ideologically  necessary  connection,  or  does  it  just  hap- 
pen to  be  what  it  is?  We  can  conceive  Shakespeare  to  have 
made  a  Jacques  who  would  be  merry  instead  of  melancholy, 
and  who  consequently  would  not  have  resembled  Hamlet.  From 
this  consideration  we  derive  the  important  conclusion  that  the 
teleological  similarity  of  Jacques  to  Hamlet  is  itself  dependent  on 
certain  unteleological  brute  facts  in  the  temporal  world  in  which 
Shakespeare  lived.  Our  grounds  then  for  making  the  judg- 
ment are  to  some  extent  at  least  purely  factual,  and  we  express 
this  imperfection  by  saying  that  the  judgment  is  *  assertorial.' 
But  just  as  we  saw  above,  that  it  was  unfair  to  regard  the  judg- 
ment as  merely  hypothetical  for  the  reason  that  Hamlet  and 
Jacques  were  something  more  than  purely  possible  beings, 
so  here  also  we  must  admit  that  it  would  be  unfair  to  call  the 
judgment  merely  assertorial.  Hamlet  and  Jacques  are  related 
not  merely  as  facts,  but  also  to  some  extent  as  necessary 
facts.  Given  the  fact  that  both  conceptions  involve  the  charac- 
ter of  melancholy,  it  is  rationally  or  ideologically  necessary  to 
admit  that  they  resemble  one  another.  In  short  I  must  acknowl- 
edge that  these  semi-hypothetical  facts,  being  what  they  are, 
bear  a  certain  relation  to  each  other  which  I,  as  a  rational  being, 
cannot  disregard  nor  look  upon  with  the  indifference  with  which  I 
have  a  perfect  right  to  look  upon  pure  matter  of  fact.  A  pure 
fact  might  be  other  than  it  is,  but  the  relation  between  these 
particular  facts  when  once  they  are  accepted  could  not  be  con- 
ceived to  be  other  than  rational  and  necessary.  This  character 
of  necessity  makes  the  judgment  in  which  it  is  present  an 
*  apodictic '  judgment.  These  three  degrees  of  modality  are 
always  to  be  found  in  teleological  sequences,  i.  e.,  sequences 
whose  terms  are  related  in  virtue  of  their  common  participation  in 


A    PLEA    FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  621 

some  third  quality.  And  now  that  we  have  shown  in  a  somewhat 
labored  fashion  that  our  chosen  example  of  the  mental  sequence 
in  which  Jacques  calls  up  Hamlet  not  only  contains  biological, 
chemical  and  physical  causality  on  the  mechanical  side,  but  also 
hypothetical,  assertorial  and  apodictic  causality  on  the  teleolog- 
ical  side,  it  will  be  necessary  to  study  these  types  of  teleological 
causality  in  isolation  in  order  to  discover  the  limit  approached  by 
the  teleological  relation  as  it  is  gradually  freed  from  the  un- 
teleological  factors  which  usually  accompany  it  with  the  result 
of  obscuring  its  true  nature. 

Absolutely  hypothetical  judgments  or  judgments  about  purely 
possible  entities  would  possess  no  psychical  cogency,  would  ex- 
ercise no  constraint  over  the  mind  of  the  thinker.  An  example 
of  such  a  judgment  would  be  the  assertion — "  If  there  is  a 
jaberwock,  he  would  eat  a  griffin."  This  judgment  exercises 
absolutely  no  control  over  the  mind,  for  two  reasons :  first,  be- 
cause neither  jaberwocks  nor  griffins  exist;  and,  secondly,  be- 
cause there  is  no  reason  for  connecting  even  the  bare  idea  of 
jaberwock  with  the  idea  of  griffin-eating.  Now  take  an  exam- 
ple of  a  judgment  of  the  next  higher  degreee  of  modality. 
"  If  there's  a  mermaid,  she  lives  in  the  sea."  This  resembles 
the  preceding  judgment  in  so  far  as  its  subject  is  unreal,  and 
again  in  so  far  as  there  is  no  rational  connection  between  subject 
and  predicate — no  intrinsic  reason  for  a  mermaid's  not  living  in 
a  pond  ;  it  differs  from  the  previous  judgment,  however,  in  so  far 
as  in  the  quasi-real  world  of  fairyland  it  has  actually  been 
learned  from  experience  that  mermaids  live  in  the  sea  and  no- 
where else.  What  is  actual  for  a  hypothetical  world  is  hypo- 
thetical in  a  real  world.  We  are  actually  limited  by  this  judg- 
ment, i.  e.9  forced  to  recognize  its  cogency  whenever  we  choose 
to  talk  about  fairyland. 

These  two  types  of  judgment  exhaust  the  realm  of  the  hypo- 
thetical, and  we  have  now  to  enter  on  that  of  the  actual  or  as- 
sertorial judgments.  And  just  as  we  found  two  degrees  of 
hypothetical  judgment  dealing  respectively  with  unreal  connec- 
tions, and  with  real  connections  in  an  unreal  world,  so  now  we 
shall  find  two  kinds  of  assertorial  judgments — (i)  non-rational 
or  contingent  relations  between  real  facts,  and  (2)  necessary 


622  W.   P.    MONTAGUE. 

relations  between  unreal  facts.  The  non-rational  between  real 
facts  is  exemplified  in  such  judgments  as  "  The  grass  is  green," 
"  The  rain  is  falling,"  "  The  match  is  twojnches  long,"  "  To-day 
is  Tuesday,  not  Wednesday."  These  judgments  are  true,  and 
there  is  no  discoverable  teleological  ground  for  their  truth. 
They  differ  from  the  hypothetical  judgments  in  that  they  have 
absolute  cogency  over  the  mind  for  the  moment  in  which  their 
terms  are  perceived.  They  are  necessary  not  for  the  under- 
standing, but  for  the  sensibility.  (The  hypothetical  judgments 
only  had  cogency  over  the  mind  on  the  condition  of  the  mind's 
voluntarily  accepting  the  hypothetical  world.) 

The  other  type  of  assertorial  judgment  is  not  a  judgment  of 
fact,  but  a  judgment  about  determined  relations  between  unreal 
entities.  For  example :  If  a  mermaid  is  defined  as  a  being 
which  if  it  lived  would  live  in  the  sea,rthen  the  judgment  that 
a  mermaid  would  be  able  to  endure  salt-water  would  have  as- 
sertorial validity,  /.  £.,  cogency  over  the  mind  of  the  thinker  as 
a  brute  fact  in  the  real  world.  Or,  again,  whether  any  three 
things  A,  B  and  C  are  real  or  not,  it  is  nevertheless  a  fact  that 
if  A  =  B  and  if  C  =  B  then  A  =  C,  and  the  validity  of  this 
conclusion  is  absolutely  independent  of  the  existence  or  non- 
existence  of  A,  B  and  C.  It  has,  however,  assertorial  validity 
and  nothing  more.  The  thinker  would  only  have  to  recall  the 
fact  that  A  and  B  were  creatures  of  his  fancy  and  all  sense  of 
necessity  would  cease — his  judgment  would  resolve  itself  into 
the  mere  recognition  of  his  consciousness  as  having  a  certain 
form.  He  finds  this  character  of  unity  in  his  consciousness  and 
recognizes  its  existence  in  this  particular  case,  just  as  he  recog- 
nizes that  the  grass  is  green  or  that  to-day  is  not  yesterday.  In 
short,  the  final  test  of  the  degree  of  modality  possessed  by  any 
judgment  is  the  amount  of  the  force  which  it  exerts  over  our 
actions.  The  fact  that  an  unreal  thing  is  identical  with  itself  is 
equal  to  no  more  than  a  simple  recognition  of  an  actual  relation, 
whose  terms  being  unreal  is  itself  nothing  more  than  a  fact,  and 
as  such  only  determines  our  actions  in  so  far  as  they  concern 
themselves  with  it. 

If  we  now  pass  to  the  third  and  final  type  of  teleological  se- 
quence we  shall  be  able  to  see  better  the  justness  of  this  serial 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  623 

arrangement  of  the  first  and  second  degrees  of  modality.  We 
come  to  the  world  of  necessity  in  which  judgments  are  neither 
hopothetical  nor  assertorial  but  apodictic.  If  it  be  true  that  pos- 
sibility, actuality  and  necessity  really  stand  in  a  serial  order,  we 
ought  to  be  able  to  predict  the  nature  of  apodictic  validity  from 
a  consideration  of  hypothetical  and  assertorial  validity.  We 
found  that  hypothetical  judgments  could  be  of  two  kinds.  We 
could  assert  a  possible  relation  between  possible  facts — "  a  jaber- 
wock  would  eat  a  griffin  "or  "  people  in  Mars  have  three  arms  " 
(and  these  judgments,  exerting  absolutely  no  cogency,  could 
fitly  be  called  '  problematic '  rather  than  hypothetical)  ;  or 
again,  instead  of  asserting  a  possible  relation  between  possible 
facts,  we  could  assert  an  actual  relation  between  possible 
facts,  t.e.,  "Mermaids  live  in  the  sea."  The  mermaids  are 
to  be  sure  unreal,  but  the  relation  between  the  concept  'mermaid ' 
and  the  concept  '  sea-dwelling '  is  real  though  contingent  when 
taken  merely  as  a  relation.  The  hypothetical  judgment  or  the 
judgment  about  possibilities  concerns  itself  with  relations  and 
not  facts.  The  assertorial  judgment  or  the  judgment  about 
actualities  concerns  itself  with  facts  apart  from  relations.  The 
fact  was  either  simple,  as  in  the  judgment  of  the  grass  being 
green,  or  complex,  as  when  formed  by  the  actual  coexistence 
or  intersection  in  one  consciousness  of  two  purely  hypothet- 
ical judgments  or  assertions  of  mere  relation.  If  the  com- 
bination of  two  possibles  makes  an  actual  we  should  expect 
that  the  combination  of  a  possible  and  an  actual,  a  relation  and 
a  fact,  would  yield  a  necessary.  Let  us  see  if  this  really  hap- 
pens. A  triangle  is  an  actual  fact  and  the  relation  between 
the  sum  of  the  angles  of  a  triangle  and  two  right  angles  is  a 
genuine  relation,  i.  e.,  a  relation  which  is,  if  not  genuinely  in- 
telligible, yet  more  than  a  mere  fact  of  perception.  Hence  the 
judgment,  "  the  sum  of  the  angles  of  a  triangle  is  equal  to  two 
right  angles,"  is  a  judgment  which  combines  a  relation  or  rule 
of  reason  with  an  actual  thing  or  fact  of  sense  experience,  and 
as  such  possesses  apodictic  validity.  Now  the  question  arises 
as  to  whether  there  are  degrees  of  necessity.  Would  there  be 
any  meaning  in  saying  that  one  apodictic  judgment  was  more 
necessary  than  another?  We  have  said  that  the  degree  of 


624  W.   P.    MONTAGUE. 

validity  of  any  judgment  was  measured  by  the  degree  of 
cogency  which  it  exerted  over  the  mind  of  the  thinker.  Hence 
if  we  find  that  several  apodictic  judgments  differ  in  their 
cogency,  we  can  admit  that  there  are  degrees  of  necessity.  Let 
us  examine  the  following  three  judgments  :  (i)  A  straight  line 
is  the  shortest  distance  between  two  points;  (2)  7  +5  =  12; 
(3)  Every  event  is  identical  with  itself.  All  these  judgments 
are  apodictic,  but  they  possess  different  degrees  of  importance. 
We  cannot,  indeed,  deny  the  axioms  of  geometry,  but  can  we 
not  to  a  large  extent  neglect  them  ?  In  so  far  as  our  experience 
is  spatial  it  is  dependent  upon  the  laws  of  space;  but  a  large 
part  of  our  experience  is  not  spatial  and  is  to  that  extent  inde- 
pendent of  the  axiom  of  the  straight  line.  It  only  possesses 
cogency  over  part  of  the  mind.  Now  the  second  judgment,  like 
all  judgments  about  particular  numbers,  involves  in  itself  the 
whole  number  series ;  and  as  number  applies  to  inner  experi- 
ence as  well  as  to  outer,  we  have  in  the  numerical  judgment  a 
greater  because  a  more  extensive  cogency  than  in  the  judgment 
about  the  straight  line.  Finally  in  the  third  judgment,  the 
axiom  of  identity,  A  =  A,  we  have  a  cogency  and  consequently 
a  validity  more  nearly  universal  than  that  of  either  spatial  or 
numerical  judgments.  For  if  there  is  a  large  part  of  experience 
that  is  independent  of  the  laws  of  space  and  a  smaller  surplus 
of  experience  which  is  independent  of  number,  there  would  at 
first  glance  seem  to  be  no  experience  at  all  that  is  not  dependent 
upon  the  law  of  identity.  We  must  then  admit  that  there  are 
degrees  of  necessity,  that  apodictic  validity  may  vary  in  its  ex- 
tent. Hence  it  will  not  be  enough  to  say  that  any  apodictic 
judgment  can  be  regarded  as  the  limit  of  the  series  of  teleolog- 
ical  sequences.  To  find  the  limit  we  must  find  the  judgment 
which  is  cogent  throughout  all  experience  and  not  merely 
throughout  particular  departments.  Perhaps  the  axiom  of 
identity  fulfills  this  demand  for  an  absolute  or  universal  neces- 
sity. To  prove  this  we  have  only  to  show  that  there  is  no  case 
in  which  a  thing  changes  its  identity.  But  does  not  the  very 
statement  of  the  task  bring  out  the  impossibility  of  its  attainment? 
Wherever  there  is  change  the  law  of  identity  is  neglected.  A 
does  not  remain  identical  in  so  far  as  it  gives  rise  to  B.  One 


A  PLEA    FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  625 

thing  becomes  another  thing.  We  need  not  take  the  fact  of 
change  as  a  violation  of  the  law  of  identity  for  there  must 
always  remain  a  constant  or  identical  element  throughout  every 
change.  We  have,  however,  the  right  to  regard  change  as  an 
example  of  the  limitation,  if  not  the  contradiction,  of  the  axiom 
that  A  =  A.  Change  may  imply  identity;  but  identity  is  not 
the  whole  essence  of  change,  and  whenever  we  attend  to  the 
changing  forms  and  states  of  a  thing  rather  than  to  the  thing 
itself,  we  are  in  just  so  far  attending  to  a  phase  of  experience 
over  which  the  judgment  of  identity  is  not  cogent. 

Professor  Royce  in  his  Religious  Aspect  of  Philosophy  gives 
an  example  of  a  judgment  which  would  seem  to  possess  the 
sort  of  universal  validity  for  which  we  have  just  sought  in  vain 
in  the  judgment  of  identity.  The  judgment  that  '  every  doubt 
implies  a  reference  to  an  objective  truth '  is  absolutely  universal 
throughout  the  realm  of  reason.  To  deny  or  to  doubt  the  truth 
of  this  judgment  is  to  affirm  it,  because  any  rational  doubt  of 
the  truth  of  a  proposition  is  based  upon  the  belief  that  it  does 
not  conform  to  the  established  nature  of  things  nor  to  objective 
Truth,  and  the  existence  of  this  objective  Truth  is  all  that  the 
judgment  asserted.  Before  submitting  this  proposition  of  Pro- 
fessor Royce's  to  a  final  test  of  the  universality  of  its  cogency, 
we  should  recall  the  manner  in  which  the  limitations  of  the  pre- 
vious judgments  were  manifested.  When  confronted  with  the 
axioms  of  geometry  we  could  say :  There  is  a  portion  of  our 
experience  over  which  these  laws  have  no  sway.  Again  in  the 
case  of  the  axioms  of  arithmetic  we  could  point  to  the  concrete 
differences  in  the  qualities  of  experience  as  being  outside  the 
laws  of  number.  Finally  in  the  third  judgment  we  could  in- 
stance the  phenomena  of  time  and  change  as  examples  of  ex- 
periences, the  whole  nature  of  which  could  not  be  expressed  by 
the  principle  of  identity.  We  have  then,  if  we  would  show 
Professor  Royce's  refutation  of  scepticism  to  be  limited  in  its 
degree  of  validity,  simply  to  follow  the  same  path  as  before, 
z.  £.,  to  find  some  experience  over  which  the  law  in  question 
does  not  hold.  The  topic  of  the  judgment  is  itself  an  indica- 
tion of  its  limitation.  What  are  truth  and  error?  They  are 
objects  of  Reason — the  law  which  binds  them  together  is  a  law 


626  w.    P.    MONTAGUE. 

of  Reason.  Is  there  any  portion  of  experience  that  is  not 
purely  rational?  Feeling  and  acting  may  be  reasonable  but 
are  they  not  something  more?  Every  sensation  and  every  act 
of  will  contains  an  element  or  an  aspect  which  is  not  reducible 
to  the  laws  which  govern  our  thought.  And  in  so  far  as  we 
have  experience  which  is  not  merely  rational,  just  in  so  far  is 
our  experience  independent  of  Professor  Royce's  proposition 
about  the  necessary  implication  of  a  rational  doubt.  For  a  non- 
rational  being  and  for  any  being  in  so  far  as  he  is  non-rational, 
the  judgment  in  question  possesses  no  cogency  nor  validity.1 

The  question  naturally  arises  here  as  to  whether  there  is  any 
single  judgment  the  consequences  of  which  we  cannot  escape 
by  changing  or  extending  our  point  of  view.  We  may  remem- 
ber that  when  we  arrived  in  the  series  of  mechanical  sequences  at 
what  seemed  to  be  a  purely  quantitative  and  irreversible  change, 
we  found  that  it  was  possible  by  changing  our  origin  or  center 
of  mass  to  view  the  sequence  in  reverse  order.  The  only  ways 
in  which  it  was  possible  to  transcend  this  reversibility  or  rela- 
tivity of  mechanical  processes  was  by  extending  the  material 
system  until  it  embraced  the  entire  universe  for  which  there  is 
only  one  center  of  mass,  or  by  selecting  a  system  (e.  £•.,  an 
organism)  which  possessed  a  unique  center  of  mass  which  could 
not  be  exchanged  for  any  other.  The  case  is  precisely  the  same 
in  the  present  series  of  teleological  sequences.  All  rational 
sequences,  z*.  £.,  all  apodictic  judgments,  seem  to  be  permeated 
with  relativity — there  is  always  some  other  point  of  view,  as  it 
were,  some  other  center  of  mass,  with  respect  to  which  our 
sequence  loses  its  validity.  I  can  think  of  only  one  type  of 
judgment  from  the  consequences  of  which  it  is  impossible  to 
escape.  In  the  moral  judgment  or  judgment  of  duty  there  seems 
to  me  no  relativity  whatever.  The  judgment  that  A  =  A  does 
not  forbid  us  to  neglect  it  in  so  far  as  experience  is  temporal  or 

*If  this  reasoning  be  valid,  there  follows  what  seems  to  me  to  be  a  rather 
important  result,  viz.,  this  :  In  so  far  as  the  arguments  used  by  Professor  Royce 
and  Mr.  Bradley  for  the  demonstration  of  the  Absolute  as  a  being  in  whom  evil 
and  pain  are  transcended — depend  upon  the  conclusion  that  error  is  transcended 
— they  are  baseless.  That  is  to  say,  there  is  no  inconsistency  in  regarding  God 
as  necessarily  rational  but  by  no  means  either  good  or  happy.  The  divine  tran- 
scendence of  evil  and  pain  does  not  follow  from  the  mere  transcendence  of  error. 


A   PLEA    FOR  SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  627 

subject  to  change.  The  judgment  that  every  rational  doubt 
implies  an  absolute  truth  does  not  prevent  us  from  neglecting 
altogether  the  world  of  the  rational  in  favor  of  the  world  of 
sense.  But  the  moral  judgment  that  something  ought  to  be  not 
only  forbids  us  to  deny  it,  but  it  also  forbids  us  to  neglect  it  for 
anything  else.  When  we  stand  in  the  presence  of  a  duty,  the 
moral  law  does  not  simply  assert  its  validity  or  cogency  for  a  single 
department  of  experience,  it  asserts  its  own  apodictic  truth  and  as 
it  were  in  the  same  breath  it  claims  our  attention  and  our  absolute 
and  peremptory  obedience  to  it.  This  is  the  peculiarity  of  the 
'  Categorical  Imperative,'  that  in  addition  to  the  apodictic  valid- 
ity which  it  possesses  in  common  with  all  necessary  judgments, 
it  puts  in  an  extra  claim  to  be  recognized  as  more  important 
than  anything  else.  It  forbids  us  to  deny  its  truth,  and  it  also 
forbids  us  to  neglect  it.  Its  cogency  is  not  merely  negative  but 
positive,  it  commands  us  to  vindicate  our  recognition  of  its  abso- 
luteness by  determining  our  actions  in  accordance  with  its 
maxims.  It  appeals  to  us  not  in  so  far  as  we  are  subject  to  the 
laws  of  space  and  number,  not  in  so  far  as  we  are  subject  to  the 
Laws  of  Identity  and  contradiction,  not  even  in  so  far  as  we  are 
rational  or  sensuous,  or  social  or  virtuous.  It  condescends  not 
at  all  to  justify  itself  by  pointing  to  any  one  mode  or  aspect  of 
our  nature.  It  bids  us  unconditionally  to  recognize  it  and  to 
follow  it  with  all  the  strength  that  we  have.  These  attributes 
of  the  moral  law  may  be  very  edifying  or  they  may  be  the  re- 
verse ;  our  interest  in  the  Categorical  Imperative  is  not  in  the 
least  emotional,  we  simply  cite  it  as  a  very  peculiar  phenomenon 
and  a  very  significant  one  for  students  of  epistemology  and 
logic.  Its  significance  is  due  to  the  fact  that  it  fulfills  the  ideal 
of  absolute  validity  or  truth.  It  is  the  limit  of  the  series  of 
judgments  in  which  each  possessed  a  greater  degree  of  truth 
than  the  one  before. 

From  the  problematic  judgment  which  exerted  no  cogency 
whatever,  and  the  hypothetical  judgment  which  was  valid  only 
if  we  voluntarily  admitted  the  condition  upon  which  it  was 
based,  on  through  the  assertorial  judgments  whose  validity  was 
limited  to  the  moment  of  perception,  up  to  the  apodictic  judg- 
ment which  was  absolute  through  some  one  department  of  ex- 


628  W.   P.    MONTAGUE. 

perience  and  finally  to  the  judgment  of  Practical  Reason,  which 
possessed  an  absolute  and  unconditional  cogency  over  the  entire 
self — through  all  this  process  we  have  noted  the  genuinely 
serial  order.  Each  term  of  the  series,  each  type  of  judgment 
possesses  all  that  the  previous  terms  possessed.  And  at  the  end 
of  the  process  we  reach  the  limiting  term,  the  type  of  judgment 
which  declares  itself  as  absolute.  The  moral  judgment  alone, 
as  the  limit  of  the  series,  contains  in  itself  the  perfect  validity  to 
which  the  speculative  judgments  could  only  approximate. 

We  hear  a  great  deal  at  present  about  the  judgment  of  worth 
as  superior  to  the  judgment  of  truth.  Practical  Reason  is  dog- 
matically asserted  to  be  more  real  than  speculative  Reason,  and 
the  return  to  the  epistemological  dualism  of  Kant  is  advocated 
as  '  the  only  refuge  for  Theology  in  its  flight  from  the  persecu- 
tions of  science.'  The  object  of  this  study  in  the  method  of 
limits  is  simply  an  attempt  at  some  sort  of  justification  of  Kant's 
hypothesis  of  the  supremacy  of  Practical  Reason.  If  one  is 
content  with  simply  asserting  that  moral  truths  are  superior  to 
the  truth  of  reason,  he  is  helpless  against  anybody  who  makes 
the  opposite  assertion.  If  Speculative  and  Practical  Reason  are 
wholly  incommensurate  the  one  with  the  other,  there  is  no  cri- 
terion for  deciding  as  to  the  supremacy  of  either.  To  assert 
one  as  prior  to  the  other  is  a  senseless  and  arbitrary  act.  But 
if  we  can  show  that  the  judgments  of  the  one  faculty  form  a 
continuous  series  with  the  judgments  of  the  other,  we  vindicate 
our  right  to  a  division  into  higher  and  lower.  In  the  light  of 
our  analysis  it  is  no  longer  a  paradox  to  assert  the  existence  of 
duty  as  truer  than  truth.  For  as  we  have  seen  the  degree  of 
truth  possessed  by  a  judgment  is  measured  by  the  degree  of 
cogency  which  it  exerts  over  the  mind.  The  judgment  of  duty 
is  absolute  or  unconditional  and  as  such  has  more  cogency  than 
any  other  possible  judgment,  hence  it  possesses  a  maximum  of 
validity  or  truth. 

Now  that  we  have  found  the  limit  of  the  series  of  teleolog- 
ical  sequences  it  is  necessary  to  analyze  it  in  order  that  by  ob- 
serving its  inner  nature  we  may  be  able  to  see  if  it  is  at  all  com- 
mensurate with  the  limiting  type  of  mechanical  sequence.  To 
simplify  this  analysis  I  must  ask  you  to  assume,  without  proof, 


A  PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  629 

that  the  moral  law  only,  or  at  all  events  primarily,  appears  in 
its  own  form  under  certain  definite  conditions.  We  use  the 
word  '  ought'  in  a  variety  of  cases  in  which  moral  obligation  is 
not  felt  at  all,  or  if  felt,  it  is  only  indirectly  and  by  analogy. 
The  three  conditions  under  which  the  moral  law  makes  its  ap- 
peal are  : 

1.  The  recognition  of  a  good. 

2.  The  immediate  possibility  of  realizing  the  good. 

3.  The  fact  that  I  and  not  someone  else  am  the  agent  for  its 
realization. 

We  make  use  of  the  word  ought  when  any  one  of  these  con- 
ditions is  present ;  but  we  only  use  it  in  its  true  and^proper,  z*.  £., 
in  its  moral  sense  when  all  three  conditions  are  fulfilled. 

Omit  the  first  condition,  and  we  have  the  class  of  what  Kant 
called  Hypothetical  Imperatives.  "I  ought  to  come  in  out  of 
the  rain  " — there  is  no  moral  obligation  contained  in  this  judg- 
ment unless  I  make  the  further  judgment  that  it  is  morally  good 
to  keep  dry. 

Again,  omit  the  second  condition,  *'.  £.,  the  possibility  of 
action,  and  we  get  that  class  of  judgments  which  express  regret 
or  remorse  or  distress  without  obligation  to  act.  "  My  past  ac- 
tions ought  to  be  different."  "  I  ought  not  to  be  in  this  condi- 
tion." In  these  judgments  I  see  the  impossibility  of  realizing 
the  good  by  any  action,  and  with  this  recognition  the  obligatory 
cogency  of  the  judgment  of  duty  is  destroyed.  And,  thirdly, 
when  I  say  you  ought  or  he  ought  to  do  so  and  so,  I  fail  to  per- 
ceive the  peculiar  strain  or  compelling  force  of  the  Moral  Im- 
perative. It  is  only  when  I  realize  that  there  is,  first  a  good, 
wL.~  i  s,  second,  immediately  -possible,  third,  for  me  to  realize 
— it  is  only  then,  I  say,  that  the  judgment  of  Practical  Reason 
sets  up  its  claim  for  absolute  and  peremptory  obedience.  And 
I  think  that  if  one  takes  the  trouble  to  analyze  his  feelings  when 
he  fancies  that  moral  obligation  is  present  independently  of 
the  presence  of  all  these  three  conditions,  he  will  find  that 
either  on  the  one  hand  the  apparent  obligation  will  pass  away, 
or  on  the  other  hand,  he  will  insist  on  projecting  himself  into  a 
world  in  which  the  duty  in  question  is  possible  and  possible  for 


630  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

him  alone.1  Granting  this  we  may  state  the  judgment  of  duty 
as  a  judgment  in  which  a  possible  good  is  connected  with  its 
realization  in  the  world  of  fact — by  means  of  the  ego.  The 
cause  or  antecedent  term  of  the  judgment-sequence  is  an  idea ; 
the  effect  or  consequent  term  is  the  idea  realized  or  actualized. 
We  must  here  note  a  further  peculiarity  of  the  moral  judg- 
ment. It  is  self-transcendent  in  the  sense  that  it  refers  to  some- 
thing beyond  itself,  z*.  e.,  to  its  realization  in  the  world  of  fact. 
The  judgment,  "  I  ought  to  do  this,"  is  only  fulfilled  or  com- 
pleted in  the  process  of  realizing  the  judgment  in  action.  To 
recognize  or  think  a  duty  as  binding  is  only  the  most  rational 
of  judgments  when  it  is  accompanied  by  the  specific  realiza- 
tion of  the  good.  The  moral  judgment  is  truer  than  the  specu- 
lative judgment,  but  the  acting  out  of  the  moral  judgment  is 
the  only  way  to  complete  or  exemplify  this  truth.  Hence  this 
final  type  of  teleological  sequence  is  the  change  from  an 
idea  of  a  good  deed  to  a  good  deed.  It  is  the  change  from  the 
possible  to  the  actual.  A  is  the  subject  of  the  judgment,  A'  is  the 
predicate.  A  is  the  idea  of  the  good,  A'  is  the  realized  fact. 
A  is  the  antecedent  or  causal  term  of  the  sequence,  A'  is  the 
consequent  term  or  the  effect.  A  as  a  possible  is  the  cause  of  A 
as  an  actual.  To  find  the  essence  of  the  sequence  we  have  sim- 
ply to  find  the  difference  between  the  possible  and  the  actual,  the 
idea  of  the  fact  and  the  fact  itself.  The  effect  only  differs  from 
the  cause  in  possessing  existence.  What  then  is  the  predicate 
of  existence?  As  Kant  expressed  it,  How  does  the  actual  dollar 
which  will  pay  a  debt  differ  from  the  idea  of  the  dollar — which 
will  not  pay  a  debt?  That  there  is  a  difference  between  a  fact 
and  the  idea  of  a  fact  we  cannot  doubt.  A  man  is  thoroughly 
good  when  he  turns  his  ideas  of  good  into  facts ;  a  man  is  thor- 
oughly bad  when  he  possesses  the  idea  of  the  good,  the  knowl- 
edge of  his  duties,  but  refuses  to  realize  that  knowledge.  The 
antithesis  between  the  idea  and  the  fact  is  of  the  same  kind  and 
of  the  same  degree  as  the  antithesis  between  conscious  sin  and 

1This  is  what  happens  in  the  case  of  remorse :  we  either  recognize  the  use- 
lessness  of  regretting  what  is  necessarily  the  case  and  the  remorse  vanishes,  or 
we  persist  in  projecting  ourself  into  the  past  circumstance  in  which  the  regretted 
action  was  not  a  necessary  but  a  freely  chosen  possibility. 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  631 

conscious  virtue.  The  existential  predicate  is  something  real, 
but  it  is  not  a  quality.  We  cannot  point  out  any  quality  which 
the  actual  dollar  possesses  that  is  not  also  possessed  by  the  pos- 
sible dollar.  How  do  we  detect  the  presence  of  this  predicate 
of  existence  if  it  is  not  visible  as  a  quality  ?  We  detect  it  by  its 
effects,  it  manifests  its  reality  and  its  nature  in  its  functions  in 
its  relations  to  other  things.  The  real  dollar  is  known  to  be 
different  from  the  ideal  dollar  because  the  two  stand  in  different 
relations  to  a  debt.  The  one  produces  certain  effects  which  the 
other  does  not,  and  by  the  principle  of  sufficient  reason  we  are 
bound  to  explain  the  visible  difference  in  the  effects  by  positing 
a  genuinely  real  though  invisible  and  non-qualitative  difference 
in  the  respective  causes.  There  have  been  suggested  various 
criteria  for  distinguishing  the  external  world  from  the  sensa- 
tions about  it. 

There  is  Humes'  criterion,  based  upon  the  difference  of 
vividness  between  the  real  and  ideal.  This  criterion  is  imper- 
fect in  so  far  as  it  affords  no  basis  for  condemning  as  unreal  or 
merely  subjective  the  remarkably  vivid  hallucinations  of  an  in- 
sane man.  We  are  driven  to  adopt  a  second  criterion,  the 
opinions  of  our  fellow-men.  What  our  fellows  pronounce  actual, 
that  is  really  actual ;  and  what  they  say  is  mere  idea  or  possi- 
bility is  really  so,  no  matter  how  vivid  it  may  seem  to  us.  There 
is  to-day  an  increasing  body  of  thinkers  who  stop  here  and  accept 
the  verdict  of  the  '  social  consciousness  '  as  the  final  and  all-suffi- 
cient criterion  for  distinguishing  the  real  from  the  ideal.  What 
constitutes  lunacy? — simply  having  an  experience  which  your 
neighbors  do  not  have.  If  there  were  ninety-nine  men  who 
possessed  in  common  a  certain  hallucination,  and  one  man  who 
did  not  possess  it,  then  we  are  told  that  that  one  man  would  be 
insane  so  far  as  that  community  was  concerned.  It  is  doubtful 
if  any  one  could  ever  seriously  believe  in  this  theory,  if  its 
necessary  implications  were  clearly  seen,  and  yet  like  all  forms 
of  Berkeley's  doctrine  of  the  identity  of  esse  and  percipi,  it  is  a 
pleasant  paradox  and  one  that  is  easy  to  defend. 

For  in  the  first  place,  this  appeal  to  the  verdict  of  the  Social 
Consciousness  as  the  ultimate  test  of  what  is  real,  involves  an 
endless  and  vicious  regress.  "  A  thing  is  real  because  my 


632  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

neighbors  say  it  is  real."  Why  do  my  neighbors  say  it  is  real ; 
what  is  the  rational  ground  for  their  assertion?  According  to 
this  theory  their  only  ground  must  lie  in  the  fact  that  their 
neighbors  assert  the  experience  as  real,  the  opinions  of  the  latter 
being  in  turn  justified  only  by  the  beliefs  of  their  neighbors, 
and  so  on  until  finally  we  should  exhaust  the  number  of  men 
and  arrive  at  the  individual  who  acted  as  bell-wether  to  the 
human  flock.  Whatever  he  said  was  real,  that  also  everyone 
else  would  pronounce  real.  But  what  would  be  his  ground 
for  distinguishing  between  the  real  and  the  ideal?  Not  the 
rational  (  ?)  ground  of  '  imitation '  because  in  this  first  case  there 
would  be  no  one  to  imitate.  We  must  either  admit  that  in  the 
last  analysis  the  distinction  of  subjective  and  objective  rests 
upon  pure  caprice,  or  else  we  must  seek  a  criterion  beyond  the 
'  Social  Consciousness.'  Other  men  happen  not  to  dream  your 
dreams,  but  that  is  not  the  reason  that  your  dreams  lack  an 
existential  predicate  I1 

There  is,  however,  a  third  criterion  for  distinguishing  the 
ideal  from  the  real,  viz.,  the  criterion  of  permanency.  When 
the  patient  suffering  from  an  illusion  refuses  to  believe  his 
neighbors,  he  is  when  possible  taken  to  the  apparent  cause  of 
his  illusion  and  allowed  to  test  it  with  other  senses  than  the  one 
affected,  upon  which  the  illusion  usually  vanishes.  The  part  of 
it  which  is  unaltered  by  changes  in  time  and  in  sense  remains 
for  him  as  real.  Hence,  in  general,  we  may  take  the  common 
sense  view  that  the  unalter ability  of  a  thing  is  the  final  test  of 
its  reality. 

Now  what  is  the  meaning  of  this  word  *  Unalterability  '  ?  It 
means  what  cannot  be  altered.  A  man  tries  to  alter  an  ex- 
perience and  can't  succeed.  Why?  Because  the  thing  resists 
him ;  he  tries  to  change  it  and  fails — then  he  feels  safe  in  pro- 
nouncing it  real  or  objective.  A  baby  feels  an  uneasy  sensation 

1There  is  nothing  mysterious  in  the  seeming  plausibility  of  the  Social  Con- 
sciousness theory,  for  this  plausibility  is  due  to  a  very  simple  hysteron  proteron. 
A  real  thing  usually  shows  its  reality  by  being  an  object  for  a  plurality  of  sub- 
jects, in  much  the  same  way  and  for  much  the  same  reason  that  to  a  real  body  in 
space  a  number  of  lines  can  be  drawn.  Stand  this  truth  on  its  head  and  we  get 
the  idealistic  doctrine  that  because  a  body  has  relations  it  is  real.  Relations  are 
at  most  the  ratio  cognoscendi,  but  never  the  ratio  essendi  of  existence. 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  633 

in  its  finger — finds  he  can  stop  it.  He  also  sees  the  moon  and 
wants  it  and  can't  get  it.  What  is  the  obvious  and  legitimate 
induction  for  the  baby  to  make?  Finger  sensations,  thoughts 
and  gurglings  are  one  kind  of  thing  ;  moons  and  cribs  and  other 
people's  voices  are  a  different  sort  of  thing.  The  first  class  be- 
long to  me,  they  are  subjective  the  other  class  do  not  belong  to 
to  me,  they  are  objective.  Why  even  such  a  very  subjective 
thing  as  a  pain  will  if  it  resist  long  enough  be  objectified.  The 
first  day  of  a  hard  toothache  the  sufferer  speaks  of  *  my  tooth- 
ache ' ;  the  third  day  he  speaks  of  '  that  infernal  pain,'  as 
though  it  did  not  belong  to  him  at  all. 

A  thing  which  resists  our  will  is  actual,  a  thing  which  does 
not  is  possible.  We  identify  that  which  resists  our  will  with  the 
realm  of  external  experience,  because  a  purely  internal  thing, 
like  a  train  of  thought,  is  wholly  identified  with  and  amenable  to 
our  wishes.  The  feeling  of  resistance  or  of  continuity  with 
something  not  our  self  is  at  once  the  ground  of  our  belief  in  ob- 
jective experience  as  being  caused  and  in  subjective  experience 
as  being  free.  There  is  no  sensation  so  purely  possible  as  not 
to  contain  a  slight  degree  of  stubbornness  or  resistance,  nor  is 
there,  on  the  other  hand,  any  sensation  so  intensely  actual  as  not 
to  be  in  some  degree  changeable  by  our  will.  The  property  of 
resistance  is  then  a  relative  or  quantitative  affair.  It  is  recog- 
nized as  akin  to  our  own  effort-feeling  because  it  varies  con- 
tinuously and  directly  with  our  effort.  As  in  our  feeling  of 
effort  we  get  the  intuition  of  pure  quantity  freed  even  from  the 
semi-qualitative  attribute  of  extension,  so  in  our  intuition  of  the 
objective  correlate  of  effort  we  are  likewise  compelled  to  think 
of  a  purely  quantitative  entity.  The  moral  change  from  the 
purely  possible  or  practically  unresisting  idea  of  the  good  to 
the  actual  or  practically  unalterable  good  deed  is  not  only  the 
most  thoroughly  rational  and  teleological  of  sequences,  but  it  is 
also  a  change  from  one  quantity  to  a  quantity  infinitely  greater. 
Existence  is  manifested  in  resistance  and  resistance  is  a  matter 
of  quantity,  hence  existence  is  also  a  matter  of  quantity.  The 
change  from  a  possible  dollar  or  a  possible  good  deed  to  an 
actual  dollar  or  an  actual  good  deed,  is  a  change  which  involves 
the  addition  of  an  existential  predicate,  i.  £.,  the  addition  of  an 


634  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

infinite  quantity.  We  cannot  change  the  possible  dollar  into 
the  actual  dollar,  but  we  can  change  the  possible  good  into  the 
actual  good.  But  you  may  answer,  Surely  the  difference  be- 
tween the  idea  of  the  good  and  the  fact  of  good  is  too  funda- 
mental to  be  explained  by  a  mere  increase  of  quantity.  To  this 
I  answer  by  offering  an  analogy.  If  we  decrease  a  surface  in- 
finitely we  reach  a  line.  Now  the  difference  between  the  line 
and  the  plane  is  of  the  same  fundamental  nature  as  the  difference 
between  fact  and  idea,  and  yet  the  conception  of  an  infinite 
quantitative  increase  is  all  that  is  required  to  explain  the  one 
case.  May  it  not  then  explain  the  other  also? 

The  limit  approached  by  the  first  or  mechanical  series  was 
the  change  from  a  less  to  a  greater  quantity,  the^  amount  of 
change  being  finite.  The  limit  approached  by  the  second  series, 
/.  £.,  the  series  of  teleological  judgments  is  also  a  change 
from  a  less  quantity  to  a  greater,  though  in  a  perfect  moral  act 
the  change  would  be  infinite.  The  two  attributes  of  the  soul 
are  in  their  essential  or  limiting  forms  homogeneous  -with  each 
other  and  imply  a  common  substance. 

But  the  most  cursory  examination  of  the  act  of  duty  reveals 
another  and  equally  important  characteristic,  viz., r its  perfectly 
material  physical  causality.  Our  actions  are  quantitative  or 
mechanical  in  so  far  as  they  follow  from  the  intensity  of  desire, 
rather  than  from  the  quality  of  the  desire.  The  moral  law  is 
essentially  and  peculiarly  material  or  physical,  in  that  it  bids  us 
seek  the  greatest  possible  quantum  of  Good,  the  maximum  of 
desirability  quite  regardless  of  the  quality  of  the  object.  This 
is  why  the  good  manifests  itself  in  such  a  variety  of  objects, 
though  never  completely  or  adequately  in  any  one.  Pleasure 
qua  pleasant  or  Beauty  qua  beautiful  can  never  be  moral  ends. 
Only  what  is  most  desirable  and  because  it  is  most  desirable  can 
be  recognized  as  an  object  of  duty. 

The  moral  action  then  has  as  much  to  do  with  the  sensuous 
and  physical  as  with  the  rational  and  teleological,  and  the 
realization  of  an  act  of  virtue  manifests  its  quantitative  and 
spatio-temporal  nature  in  the  feeling  of  effort,  to  the  same  ex- 
tent and  at  the  same  time  that  it  exhibits  its  non-temporal  and 
universal  or  ideal  validity.  This  double  aspect  of  moral  phe- 


A   PLEA   FOR   SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  635 

nomena  is  evidenced  in  the  use  of  the  two  terms  '  right '  and 
1  good.'  Every  moral  act  is  right  or  rational  and  at  the  same 
time  *  good*  or  '  desirable.'  The  ethical  rationalists  or  rigorists 
attempt  to  restrict  ethics  to  a  study  of  the  law  of  right,  the 
Categorical  Imperative.  The  opposite  school  of  ethical  writers 
— who  are  in  general  Hedonists — regard  ethics  simply  as  a  study 
of  the  summum  bonum.  The  former  claim  that  the  Good  or  end 
of  conduct  is  deducible  from  and  secondary  to  the  Right,  or  law 
of  conduct.  The  latter  claim  that  the  Right  or  categorical  imper- 
ative is  deducible  from  and  secondary  to  the  summum  bonum. 
The  end  must  justify  means  is  their  watchword,  while  the  watch- 
word of  the  Rationalists  is  "  Let  Justice  prevail  though  the  Heav- 
ens fall."  The  means  must  justify  the  end.  The  Hedonists 
forget  that  the  limiting  or  perfect  type  of  the  Desirable  must 
somehow  imply  the  existence  of  a  perfectly  right  or  rational 
means  by  which  it  is  to  be  attained,  the  Highest  Good  must  be 
compatible  with  Right  action.  The  Rigorists  on  their  side  forget 
that  the  limiting  or  perfect  form  of  Right  must  be  something 
more  than  a  merely  rational  or  formal  law,  and  must  lead  towards 
the  maximum  Desirable.  To  find  a  single  principle  of  moral  ac- 
tion which  should  in  its  own  simple  nature  express  and  harmo- 
nize these  two  opposite  motifs  of  our  moral  nature,  upon  which 
the  two  methods  of  ethics  are  based,  would  constitute  the  solu- 
tion of  the  moral  antinomy,  the  '  masterknot.' 

For  our  purposes  it  is  sufficient  to  recognize  the  significance 
of  the  moral  act  as  the  unique  embodiment  of  a  perfectly  pure 
or  limiting  type  of  efficient  causality,  and  a  perfectly  pure  or 
limiting  type  of  teleological  causality.  When  Kant  pointed  out 
the  Practical  Reason  as  the  only  clue  to  the  nature  of  Reality, 
he  discovered  a  veritable  mine  of  metaphysical  wealth,1  none  the 
less  rich  from  the  fact  of  its  all  but  universal  neglect  at  the  hands 
of  his  disciples. 

From  the  nature  of  the  moral  act  as  containing  in  its  own 

1Not  least  among  the  many  curious  and  beautiful  phenomena  of  the  moral 
consciousness  is  the  fact  which  we  have  foreborne  to  mention  that  although  the 
moral  act  is  the  only  example  of  perfect  efficient  causality  and  of  perfect  final 
causality,  it  is  also  the  only  act  whose  causality  is  genuinely  indeterminate  or 
free.  The  extent  to  which  a  man  realizes  any  given  ideal  of  good  is  a  wholly 
independent  variable  governed  by  nothing  in  the  past  or  present  except  itself. 


636  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

simple  and  irreducible  nature,  both  efficient  and  final  causality, 
we  can  and  must  infer  the  nature  of  the  moral  agent  as  a  being 
or  substance,  which  is  at  once  as  particular  and  as  material  as 
the  atom  of  the  physicist,  and  as  universal  and  intelligible  as  the 
concept  of  the  logician. 

Such  then  is  the  nature  of  the  soul.  We  may  call  it  a 
*  substance '  because  it  fulfills  the  three  conditions  mentioned 
above  as  the  requisites  for  a  valid  concept  of  substance.  It 
differs  from  a  mere  Ding  an  Sich  in  that  it  is  known  to  exist 
under  a  form  of  its  own,  viz.,  the  moral  form ;  and  it  stands  to 
its  attributes  in  that  peculiar  double  relation  (due  to  its  nature  as 
limiting  type  or  essence)  whereby  it  is  at  once  the  common 
genus  of  both  and  a  distinct  species  of  each.  That  the  soul 
exists  as  a  substance  distinct  from  matter  and  mind,  yet  com- 
mensurate with  each  therein,  furnishing  the  only  possible  ex- 
planation of  their  interaction,  we  have  seen.  We  have  seen,  too, 
that  it  is  a  simple  and  not  a  composite  substance,  for  the  act  of 
duty  in  which  the  soul  manifests  itself  under  its  own  form  is  a 
simple  act,  and  not  a  mere  complex  of  elements.  May  we  ask, 
in  conclusion,  as  to  the  destiny  of  the  soul  ?  Does  the  soul  enjoy 
a  genuine  immortality,  i.  £.,  an  individual  continuance  of  con- 
sciousness under  conditions  to  some  extent  analogous  to  those 
of  time  and  space?  The  outlook  is  extremely  sobering  and 
dark.  The  evidence,  when  candidly  scrutinized,  seems  to  re- 
duce itself  to  a  few  ghost  stories  and  a  mighty  yearning.  What 
indeed  does  the  universe  want  of  an  individual's  consciousness 
after  death  ?  The  world  of  the  physicist  certainly  does  not  need 
it.  The  dead  body  in  its  mere  decomposition  fulfills  satisfactor- 
ily all  the  laws  of  conservation  of  matter,  motion  and  energy. 
Not  only  is  there  no  need  for  a  '  loose  consciousness,'  but  if 
there  were  anything  left  beside  the  dead  body  the  symmetry 
and  unity  of  the  physicist's  world  would  seem  to  be  threatened. 
Nor  is  the  case  different  with  the  world  as  viewed  by  the 
transcendental  philosopher.  An  individual  consciousness  is  as 
far  from  harmonizing  with  the  Platonic  Ideas  or  pure  forms  of 
the  panlogist  as  with  the  atoms  and  energy  of  the  materialist. 
For  the  individual  consciousness,  just  so  long  and  just  in  so  far  as 
it  is  individual  is  permeated  with  a  particularity  and  contingency 


A   PLEA    FOR  SOUL-SUBSTANCE.  637 

which  absolutely  defies  and  sets  at  naught  the  attempt  to  define 
it  in  terms  of  universals.  In  short,  consciousness  is  in  very  much 
the  same  position  as  the  classical  bat,  there  is  no  place  for  it  in 
the  empire  of  the  earth,  neither  in  the  empire  of  the  air,  and 
condemned  to  flit  helplessly  between  the  two  realms,  it  will  ever 
be  as  a  thorn  in  the  side  of  the  consistent  empiricist  and  mate- 
rialist and  the  consistent  rationalist  and  idealist.  For  what 
indeed  is  the  individual  consciousness  but  the  hybrid  product  of 
the  union  of  *  matter '  and  '  meaning,'  of  '  facts '  and  '  values/ 
of  brain  cells  and  '  pure  forms  ' — a  thing  incommensurate  with 
and  wholly  different  in  its  nature  and  processes  from  the  two 
orders  of  being  with  which  it  deals  ?  Truly  an  'epiphenomenon ' 
with  respect  to  either  of  the  two  factors  from  whose  union  it 
arises,  what  right  can  it  possibly  have  to  continue  to  exist  when 
that  union  is  annulled?  And,  indeed,  modern  philosophy  when 
true  to  itself  must  answer  the  question  as  to  a  genuine  immortality 
in  the  negative.  We  have,  it  is  true,  several  substitutes  for 
genuine  immortality.  The  transcendentalist  doctrine  that  the 
ego  is  a  timeless  fact,  and  hence  not  mortal,  but  possessing  non- 
mortality  of  the  same  type  as  that  possessed  by  the  Pythagorean 
theorem  or  any  other  eternal  verity.  Again,  we  have  the  other 
type  of  panlogistic  '  immortality ' — that  advocated  by  Dr.  Paul 
Carus,  according  to  whom,  as  I  understand  it,  we  may  hold 
man  immortal  in  so  far  as  the  form  or  meaning  of  his  life  is 
preserved  in  the  memory  of  his  successors  and  is  influential  in 
moulding  history.  And,  finally,  we  have  the  materialist's  *  im- 
mortality,' which  assures  us  that  our  real  self  is  the  matter  of 
our  body  and  will  continue  forever. 

It  seems  to  me  that  if  we  regard  the  real  man  as  consisting 
in  the  matter  of  his  body  or  the  sensational  modifications  of  that 
matter,  or  in  the  timelessly  valid  ideas  with  which  his  intellect 
deals,  or  finally  and  most  of  all  in  the  mere  Hegelistic  unity 
of  these  two  sides  of  his  nature,  that  we  have  no  right  to 
hope  for  genuine  immortality.  But  in  truth  the  real  man, 
the  man  himself,  is  neither  matter  nor  idea,  nor  both  together ; 
the  real  man  is  the  '  something  I  know  not  (thoroughly) 
what,'  which  makes  possible  the  extraordinary  phenomenon 
of  consciousness,  i.  £.,  of  the  union  of  the  two  apparently 


638  W.   P.   MONTAGUE. 

incommensurate  orders  of  existence.  Nature  makes  no  leaps 
— there  is  no  action  at  a  distance ;  and  it  is  simply  unbe- 
lievable and  unthinkable  that  a  bundle  of  Platonic  Ideas  and  a 
bundle  of  brain  cells  could  on  their  own  initiative  and  without 
any  third  thing  or  medium  commune  together  in  the  violation 
of  all  laws  of  logic  and  of  physics.  And  yet  they  do  so  com- 
municate. All  consciousness  bears  witness  to  the  fact,  and  the 
moral  consciousness  testifies  to  the  additional  fact,  that  these  two 
phases  of  being  have  their  true  reality,  their  essential  nature  in 
something  which  is  more  real  than  either,  viz.,  the  substantial 
soul.  And  when  consciousness  goes  out  and  the  universal 
truths  and  ideals  which  swayed  the  life  of  the  living  man  re- 
turn again  to  their  own  place,  leaving  the  brain  cells  again  free 
to  follow  the  laws  of  inorganic  matter — when  that  event  takes 
place,  something  will  remain,  something  more  real  and  more 
precious  than  what  has  gone,  something  that  being  the  condi- 
tion of  consciousness,  and  having  under  certain  circumstances 
manifested  itself  in  consciousness,  may,  under  new  circumstan- 
ces, once  more  feel  and  think  and  act. 


DISCUSSION   AND   REPORTS. 

THE  GROWTH  OF  VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

Some  time  ago  a  series  of  experiments  was  conducted  by  Professor 
Ladd  connected  with  the  voluntary  control  of  the  '  Eigenlicht.'  Little 
attention  was  paid  to  the  results,  which  were  briefly  embodied  in  an 
article  published  at  the  time  in  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW.  This 
was  somewhat  surprising  considering  the  importance  of  the  general 
principles  involved.  There  can  be  no  doubt  that  the  dominance  of 
the  physical  explanation  of  phenomena  has  reacted  to  the  detriment  of 
our  naive  faith  in  the  all-powerfulness  of  the  will.  Mechanism  has 
the  floor  just  now.  We  should  be  entirely  unwarranted,  however,  in 
drawing  the  conclusion  that  the  will  and  its  old-time  spontaneity  are 
4  for  sale  cheap.'  The  experiments  conducted  by  Professor  Ladd 
showed  that  the  common  conclusion  is,  to  say  the  least,  hasty.  For 
the  averages  obtained,  based  on  an  extended  series  of  experiments  and 
conducted,  under  his  direction,  by  some  twenty  special  students  of 
psychology,  revealed  the  fact  that  voluntary  control,  though  varying 
in  degree  in  the  particular  function  in  question,  as  was  to  be  expected, 
was  nevertheless  in  every  case  more  or  less  superior  to  the  physical 
conditions  which  surrounded  the  experimenters.  We  are  not,  then 
(for  I  was  one  of  the  experimenters),  wholly  submerged  in  the  meshes 
of  mechanism. 

I  propose  to  trace,  briefly,  the  growth  of  this  fact  of  voluntary 
control,  especially  in  connection  with  the  function,  illustrated  in  Pro- 
fessor Ladd's  experiments,  which  the  will  serves  as  a  mediating  term 
between  mechanism  and  so-called  freedom.  For  I  take  it  that  the  two 
statements,  «  the  will  is  limited'  and  'the  will  is  free/  cannot  be 
reconciled  except  through  the  study  of  the  evolution  of  the  mind's  pro- 
gressive self-mastery.  The  real  significance  of  the  will,  as  an  element 
of  psychic  life,  is  to  be  found,  I  think,  in  the  way  it  is  occupied  in  ad- 
justing means  and  ends,  mechanism  to  freedom.  This  aspect  of  voli- 
tion has  not,  it  seems  to  me,  received  the  attention  it  deserves.  To 
present  some  of  the  facts  connected  with  this  phase  of  mental  life, 
taken  from  the  psychology  of  volition,  may  serve  the  double  purpose 
of  calling  attention  again  to  the  facts  contended  for  by  Professor  Ladd 

639 


640  GROWTH   OF    VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

in  the  experiments  above  referred  to ;  and  also  to  suggest  a  new  way 
of  approaching  the  problem  of  freedom  as  a  psychological  factor  of 
noetics  and  ethics.  We  may  present  the  subject  under  the  following 
heads:  spontaneous  control,  or  tact;  immediate  control,  or  conscious 
adjustment;  teleological  control,  or  self-control. 

i .  The  subject  of  tact  is  one  of  the  most  mysterious  in  the  whole 
range  of  psychology.  Here  we  can  only  follow  out  the  suggestions 
given  by  nature ;  for  the  key  to  the  mystery  lies  in  the  organic  and 
instinctive  activities,  the  preexistent  factors  of  which  may  be  taken  as 
affording  the  clues  to  the  various  concrete  types  of  spontaneous  con- 
trol. These  are  mainly  three  :  (i)  One  kind  of  spontaneous  control 
results  from  a  peculiar  facility  of  the  will  to  isolate  itself  in  the  de- 
veloping organism  in  certain  directions  to  the  neglect  or  indifference 
of  others.  We  may  call  this  the  tact  that  isolates.  Ultimately,  this 
form  of  spontaneous  control  rests  upon  the  relationship  of  the  chemical 
and  physiological  elements  of  the  vegetative  life  and  the  resultant  dif- 
ferentiation of  organ  and  function.  The  will,  in  some  cases,  and  at 
some  periods  always,  follows  the  index  finger  of  nature,  and  the  tact 
manifested,  for  example,  in  the  control  of  the  bodily  functions,  in  the 
progress  from  infancy  to  youth,  is  a  concrete  illustration  of  this  general 
fact.  Where  this  species  of  tact  is  pronounced,  the  tendency  to  con- 
trol by  isolation  is  continued.  The  phenomena  of  genius,  in  all  its 
forms,  depend  upon  this  fact  of  organic  tactf ulness  for  isolation ;  on 
this  side  of  it,  genius  is  merely  the  spontaneous  ability  to  ignore  certain 
directions  of  possible  control  for  the  sake  of  those  which  are  more 
spontaneous.  Isolation  is  the  physiological  condition  of  self-limitation 
and  it  is  largely  a  matter  of  spontaneity,  the  will  tactfully  taking  the 
line  of  least  resistance  as  the  '  rational '  line  of  self-realization.  In 
support  of  this,  it  is  a  fact,  well  vouched  for  by  physiological  students, 
that  certain  organs  and  functions  develop  more  quickly  than  others  and 
this  fact  has  its  corresponding  feature  in  control.  In  abnormal  cases, 
e.  ^.,  abnormal  and  neurotic  children,  and  children  born  of  parents 
married  late  in  life,  it  is  frequently  observed  that  the  rudimentary  or- 
gans of  the  mind,  the  head  and  brain  in  particular,  attain  to  a  quicker 
relative  development  and  are  thus  isolated  for  spontaneous  voluntary 
control  for  the  rest  of  life.  This  fact,  however,  if  associated  with  rela- 
tive stability  among  the  elements,  leads  to  marked  character  and  greatly 
increased  facility  of  control.  (2)  The  will  spontaneously  and  instinc- 
tively controls  the  changes  introduced  by  growth  and  experience. 
This  is  another  species  of  tact,  viz.,  the  tact  for  variation.  The  body, 
at  first  in  absolute  isolation  from  the  world,  always  shows  this  tendency 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  641 

when  introduced  into  its  larger  environment.  But  it  may  also  become 
a  specialized  form  of  activity,  just  as  the  tendency  to  isolation  does ; 
both  isolation  and  variation  are  organic ;  but  either  may,  under  appro- 
priate and  opportune  influences,  become  voluntary  and  automatic. 
In  early  life,  we  have  doubtless  noticed  the  tendency  of  the  will  to 
make  departures  in  the  matter  of  control.  Abnormal  and  criminal 
children  are  cases  when  this  tendency  has  run  to  excess.  It  rests  upon 
the  relative  instability  of  the  elements  of  organic  life,  as  well  as  upon 
the  failure  of  training.  Tact  for  change,  for  variation,  is  a  positive 
gift  of  the  normal  individual,  however,  as  these  abnormal  cases  show. 
The  control  is  spontaneous  in  this  case.  No  teaching  or  training 
seems  to  be  necessary.  The  child  suckles  the  breast  without  any 
previous  education  and  this  is  a  type  of  the  tactful  control  of  variation 
in  all  its  phases.  Further  illustrations  occur  in  the  voluntary  control 
of  the  means  of  conscious  and  teleological  control.  (3)  Isolation  and 
variation  are  conditions  of  natural  selection ;  natural  selection  itself, 
however,  is  conditioned  on  the  law  of  heredity.  It  is  matter  of  general 
observation  that  many  of  the  spontaneous  acts  of  the  will  are  heredi- 
tary, i.  £.,  reproduce  the  features  of  tact  based  on  preexistent  determi- 
nation: e.  g.,  the  kind  of  spontaneous  control  shown  by  the  children 
of  musicians,  artists,  etc.,  resembles  in  kind,  though  not  in  degree, 
the  peculiarities  of  their  originals.  For  all  species  of  tact,  and  there- 
fore all  kinds  of  spontaneous  control,  depend  on  conscious  and  teleo- 
logical control,  subject  to  the  laws  whereby  acts  are  mechanized  in 
habits  and  temperaments.  The  notion  that  the  voluntary  control  itself 
is  a  matter  of  heredity  is  still  unproved.  Reflex  movements  are  par- 
tially determined  by  heredity ;  but  tact  is  more  than  reflex  movement 
plus  heredity ;  there  is  a  residuum  not  contained  in  the  chain  of  organic 
conditions  which  is  the  self-activity  of  the  will  itself.  Thus,  in  cer- 
tain of  the  arts  and  crafts,  aptitude  for  the  control  of  tools  has  become 
considerably  facilitated  by  the  operation  of  heredity  laws.  In  the 
Middle  Ages,  the  guilds  of  workmen  exhibited  this  fact  in  a  very  con- 
crete way :  generations  of  the  same  families  continued  in  the  line  of 
service  marked  out  by  their  ancestry.  So  to-day  in  older  countries, 
where  the  tendency  to  variation  has  not  entirely  overcome  the  other 
tendencies,  a  great  part  of  domestic  and  industrial  life  rests  upon  the 
spontaneous  control  of  hereditary  instincts. 

These  three  kinds  of  spontaneous  control  condition  all  other  kinds 
of  voluntary  control.  Tact  constantly  broadens  as  life  unfolds ;  but 
the  development  of  individuality  and  character  is  unfailingly  faithful 
to  the  type  discovered  in  the  earliest  spontaneous  reactions  of  the  will. 


642  GROWTH  OF   VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

In  other  words,  voluntary  control,  in  its  spontaneous  form  has  a  mo- 
dicum of  "freedom,"  and  a  maximum  of  u  mechanism."  The  point 
we  make  is  that  freedom  and  mechanism  could  not  be  mediated  in  any 
case,  not  even  in  the  form  of  tact,  without  the  control  of  the  will,  at 
least  in  the  assenting  and  instinctive  manner  peculiar  to  it.  Tact  it- 
self is  the  result  of  contact,  i.  e.,  of  the  intercourse  and  inter-play  of 
spontaneity  and  mechanism.  It  is,  in  short,  the  will  that  gives  to  our 
earliest  exertions  at  control  the  aspect  of  experience. 

2.  There  is  no  marked  line  between  spontaneous  and  conscious 
control ;  the  one  develops  out  of  the  other ;  the  latter  bears  all  the  char- 
acters of  the  former.  The  new  factor  introduced  is  the  influence  of 
training ;  for  as  soon  as  we  leave  the  phenomena  of  instinctive  and 
tactful  control,  we  see  the  necessity  of  the  will  '  to  take  a  hand '  in 
all  its  experience.  Now  this  conscious  exertion  of  will  is  the  main 
characteristic  of  the  mind  of  the  child.  Dim  and  inchoate  are  its  ideas 
and  but  for  a  rough-and-ready  equipment  of  bodily  organs  and  func- 
tions, together  with  tact  in  the  progressive  control  of  them,  everything 
has  to  be  learned.  But  a  great  deal  of  this  conscious  control  rests 
upon  tact:  e.  g.,  the  formation  of  the  various  areas  of  reaction  in  the 
brain  rests  upon  an  organic  adaptation  in  the  organs  concerned  for 
their  particular  functions.  Take  the  visual  area.  This  is,  mechan- 
ically, easily  explained ;  but  from  the  standpoint  of  voluntary  control 
it  is  a  very  complex  process,  involving  adjustment  of  eye  balls,  con- 
trol of  muscles  and  the  unique  fact  of  development  in  the  visual  area. 
The  same  is  true  of  the  other  so-called  '  ideal '  sense,  hearing.  Me- 
chanically organ  and  function  are  beautifully  adapted ;  but  the  will, 
only  after  long  processes,  learns  to  control  this  source  of  perceptions 
and  sensations.  To  a  large  extent,  tact  again  explains  the  difference, 
e.  g.,  between  the  organic  response  of  a  child  to  sound  stimulation 
and  that  of  a  trained  musician.  The  large  interpretative  factor  in  the 
4  ear '  of  a  Beethoven  points  to  the  relatively  larger  control  of  the 
sound  impressions.  The  ear  of  both,  other  things  being  equal  and 
presupposing  a  normal  organ  and  auditory  area,  records  equally  well 
the  stimuli ;  but  only  conscious  and  immediate  voluntary  control  can 
explain  the  fact  that  Beethoven  wrote  his  grandest  music  after  losing 
control  of  the  mechanism  of  hearing  altogether.  But  the  conscious 
and  progressive  control  of  our  organs  of  sensation  is,  nevertheless, 
largely  a  matter  of  spontaneity,  of  tact,  dependent  upon  the  large 
amount  of  mechanical  process  involved.  And  facts  go  to  show  that 
our  conscious  efforts  follow  the  features  of  tact  already  mentioned. 

The  control  of  the  senses  in  combination  is  a  matter  of  conscious 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  643 

voluntary  effort,  i.  e.,  it  is  the  result  of  immediate  forth-putting  of 
conation.  Indeed,  when  sufficient  strength  has  been  obtained,  the 
voluntary  control  becomes  competent  to  inhibit  and  even  suspend  the 
activities  of  the  bodily  mechanism.  It  is  now  generally  understood 
that  the  feelings  and  the  will  are  intimately  related,  and  that  the  feel- 
ings are  closely  allied  to  certain  visceral  and  sympathetic  nervous  cen- 
ters. These  are  under  the  control  of  the  will,  so  that,  in  states  of 
fear,  anger,  or  remorse,  or  similar  more  or  less  complex  affective 
states,  the  constitutional  arrangements  of  the  body  may  be  interfered 
with.  Functional  activity,  indeed,  we  regard  as  subject  not  only  to 
immediate  control,  but  to  teleological  also.  We  train  children  upon 
this  assumption  at  any  rate :  that  the  spontaneous  will  to  indulge  these 
functions  must  give  place  to  a  higher  and  immediate  control.  Dirti- 
ness is  not  only  a  matter  of  functional  defect ;  it  is  a  moral  affair. 

The  control  of  intellection  shows,  in  like  manner,  a  growth  of  vol- 
untary activity.  Language  is  the  greatest  achievement  of  man  and  to 
a  large  extent  language  is  a  matter  of  tact  in  the  form  of  the  so-called 
imitative  will.  The  conquest  of  vocabulary,  beginning  as  it  does  in 
single  words,  and  extending  as  intelligence  extends,  to  verbs  and  rela- 
tive parts  of  speech,  is  based  upon  experience  of  the  self  in  its  action  on 
the  environment.  No  emergence  of  intelligence  is  easy,  still  less  nec- 
essary, when  the  motor  centers  are  undeveloped.  Activity  again  ex- 
presses the  normal  feature  of  the  formation  of  speech.  '  Willie  do 
this,'  '  Willie  do  that,'  shows  the  mode  of  self-activity.  Always  '  do  ' 
something.  The  will  must  be  appealed  to  and  aroused.  No  word  is 
truer  of  children  and  grown  men  than  that  they  learn  by  doing.  The 
order  of  volitional  control  in  speech  is  first  the  noun.  'Willie' 
stands  for  certain  associated  images  of  actions ;  and  this  is  based  on 
previous  experience  with  other  concrete  objects.  Next  verbs :  '  do  ' 
implies  the  impulsive  and  imitative  will ;  and  this  is  securely  founded 
upon  experience  with  self  in  the  past  and  instinctive  tactfulness. 
'This'  and  'that'  show  the  related  yet  the  discriminated  thought  of 
purposive  action.  The  complicated  phenomena  of  speech  are  often 
amusingly  illustrated  in  the  voluntary  control  of  the  aspirate.  The 
h '  is  a  very  active  part  of  speech,  and  failure  to  control  it  is  an  evi- 
dence of  failure  in  motor  control,  as  connected  with  the  imitative  use 
of  the  will.  This  is  a  serious  matter  in  self-consciousness;  for  it 
points  to  volitional  instability  in  muscular  and  functional  reaction. 
No  one  can  doubt  the  volitional  effort  required  to  control  this  refrac- 
tory member,  involving  breathing,  muscular  contraction,  intellection 
and  conscious  and  immediate  will-power.  Some  children  never  con- 
trol the  aspirate.  Some  nations  make  havoc  of  it  even. 


644  GROWTH  OF   VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

The  control  of  thought  is  another  and  higher  step  in  voluntary  ac- 
tivity. Through  speech  thought  is  coordinated  and  knowledge  ex- 
tended. Whether  thought  exists  apart  from  speech  cannot  be  de- 
termined from  the  introspective  standpoint.  What  we  know  is  that 
thought  develops  and  comes  under  the  control  of  the  will  as  speech  is 
mastered ;  thinking  and  speaking  are  the  same  things  on  different  sides, 
speech  being  the  volitional  expression  of  thought.  Now  no  thought 
bears  the  aspect  of  reality  which  lacks  will.  Even  the  comparatively 
passive  process  of  sense-perception  would  be  blind  without  the  active 
presence  of  the  laws  of  thought ;  for  an  object,  thoroughly  perceived, 
observed  in  all  its  elements,  is  a  thought-object ;  even  the  infant's  per- 
ceptions are,  potentially,  of  this  nature.  Strictly  speaking,  of  course, 
thought  cannot  be  controlled,  but  only  followed ;  but  thought  is  not  a 
matter  of  experience  and  knowledge  without  will,  and  in  so  far  as  the 
nature  of  thought  becomes  a  matter  for  speech,  it  is  entirely  under 
voluntary  control,  i.  £.,  it  is  an  adaptation  of  mechanism  and  spon-4 
taneity. 

In  both  these  processes,  speech  and  thought,  the  tact  of  sponta- 
neous control  betrays  itself.  Generically,  this  fact  may  be  expressed 
by  the  manifestation  of  peculiar  combinations  of  instincts,  feelings  and 
motions  in  the  back  ground  of  thought  so  to  speak.  These  subjective 
aspects  of  consciousness  are,  however,  forms  of  willing  and  involve 
intellection.  For  we  are  never  merely  receptive.  A  feeling,  even  an 
organic  impulse,  is  an  active  state,  whether  viewed  from  the  aspect  of 
pleasure  or  pain.  The  volitional  control  of  feeling  is  therefore  ob- 
viously possible,  either  through  the  spontaneous  activities,  or  through 
intellection.  There  is  no  affective  state  which  cannot  be,  to  some  ex- 
tent, controlled  through  these  channels.  We  may  thus  summon  the 
intellect  and  emotions  to  support  the  will  against  any  attack  upon 
4  freedom.'  It  is  true  the  intensity  of  the  stimulus,  say  an  intense 
feeling  of  pain,  cannot  be  controlled  by  the  will,  i.  e.,  cannot  be  got 
rid  of,  or  displaced  by  indifferent  mental  contents,  since  the  relation 
of  stimulus  and  reaction  is  permanent;  but  all  our  higher  life,  all 
teleological  control,  rests  upon  the  assumption  that  the  will  is  not 
bound  by  this  mechanical  relation.  For  the  will's  significance  in 
mental  life  is  just  this :  it  is  endowed  with  the  function  of  standing 
between  the  mechanical  relation  of  stimulus  and  reaction  and  the  ends 
involved  in  consciousness  as  a  progressive  and  self-conscious  reality. 

This  voluntary  control  of  intellection  can  be  illustrated  in  the  ac- 
tivity of  attention.  Attention  is  a  complex  operation  involving  both 
voluntary  and  involuntary  elements.  In  a  loose  sense,  primary  intel- 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  645 

lection  is  a  species  of  spontaneous  voluntary  control  based  on  reflex- 
activity  ;  in  the  simplest  act  of  attention,  however,  there  is  involved, 
something  more  than  reflex-activity,  though  it  is  difficult  to  draw  the 
line  between  what  is  mechanical  and  what  is  '  free/  The  bridge  over 
the  chasm  between  mechanism  and  freedom  is  again  to  be  found  in 
the  phenomena  of  progressive  control.  This  control  proceeds  along 
two  lines.  Along  one  of  these  we  observe  a  growing  power  of  the 
will  to  subordinate  the  character,  intensity,  and  duration  of  the  sensu- 
ous content,  upon  which  so  much  of  what  requires  attention  depends, 
to  ends.  This  power,  primarily,  rests,  as  all  else  in  voluntary  control, 
upon  the  organic  and  affective  life.  We  adjust  ourselves  easily  to  what 
greatly  excites  us.  The  clearness  and  degree  of  absorption  in  our  at- 
tentive states,  in  other  words,  depend  on  motor  control  of  the  sub- 
conscious sort.  What  is  called  mind  wandering  is  simply  the  inability 
of  the  will  to  control  the  motor  side  of  our  mental  associations  in  an 
immediate  and  conscious  manner :  the  will  flows  spontaneously  along 
the  stream  of  suggestion.  But  training,  i.  e.,  the  practice  to  which  our 
organic  powers  are  submitted  in  contact  with  suitable  environments, 
soon  gives  the  cure  for  this  state.  That  cure  consists,  essentially,  in 
introducing  into  the  stream  of  sensuous  and  mental  stimulation,  the 
deeper  principles  of  suggestibility  involved  in  control  of  the  ideolog- 
ical sort.  Along  another  line,  control  is  secured  in  attention  through 
interest.  A  certain  school  of  thinking  to-day,  following  the  isolated 
suggestions  of  thinkers  as  far  back  as  Comenius,  says  that  interest  is 
the  alpha  and  omega  of  attention.  We  think  not.  It  is  undoubtedly 
a  strong  influence  :  we  easily  attend  to  what  interests  us ;  but  the  '  prick ' 
of  sensuous*  organic,  excitement  is  just  as  strong.  The  strength  of 
interest  lies  in  the  large  amount  of  the  self-referring  activity  involved. 
We  are  concerned  when  '  our  interests '  appeal  to  our  wills.  The 
ego,  in  the  form  of  feeling,  is  what  we  mean  by  interest ;  but,  for  the 
reason  that  the  ego  is  involved,  interest  expresses  the  complex  unity  of 
thoughts  and  volitions  which  go  to  make  up  the  total  man  considered 
as  a  person.  Interest  is  thus  the  total  man  '  bulging '  in  the  curve  of 
feeling ;  it  is  self  in  the  intensest  form,  self-interest.  As  such  it  is  al- 
most entirely  under  the  voluntary  control  of  the  will.  Attention,  at 
any  rate,  either  as  sensuously  determined  or  as  determined  by  self-in- 
terest, is  a  growth  in  which  we  discover  a  progressive  adjustment  of 
reflex-action  to  higher  and  higher  modes  of  self-activity.  The  phe- 
nomena of  religious  experience,  in  conviction  of  sin,  repentance  and 
new  life,  show,  as  Hoffding  says,  a  relative  failure  of  control ;  but 
he  is  entirely  wrong  in  his  analysis  of  humility.1  The  interests  which 
1  Outlines  of  Psychology,  p.  244. 


646  GROWTH   OF   VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

we  may  deem  at  any  time  desirable  as  favoring  our  private  ends  are 
not  so  high  and  noble  as  those  which  may  be  contrary  to  our  personal 
prospects.  Egoistic  influences,  exclusively  followed,  do  not  make  the 
demand  on  voluntary  control  that  those  of  the  more  sympathetic  type 
make.  So  far  as  attention  is  concerned,  the  voluntary  control  grows, 
in  very  few  cases,  normally,  and  the  types  of  tact  maintain  themselves 
in  their  concreteness,  just  as  the  forms  of  feeling  and  temperament  re- 
main relatively  permanent.  The  point  we  make  is  this  :  the  attempt 
to  resolve  interest  into  exclusive  states  of  feeling,  purely  self -regard- 
ing, and  to  maintain  that  it  is  interest,  in  this  sense,  that  determines 
attention,  is  not  a  complete  analysis  of  the  phenomena  of  attention. 
Interest  involves  a  certain  instinctive  and  conscious  exertion  of  the 
will  and  so  far  is  not  merely  a  state  of  feeling.  That  it  also  involves 
representation,  in  intellection  and  thought,  is  obvious  when  the  object 
of  attention  is  considered.  It  is  nothing  against  the  will  that  in  any 
particular  act  of  attention  it  adjusts  itself  to  the  prevailing  forms  of 
feeling  at  hand ;  this  is  no  disgrace,  no  compromise  of  freedom ;  it  is 
the  type  of  all  forms  of  voluntary  control.  At  any  rate,  the  whole  of 
the  religious  and  ethical  life  proceeds  upon  the  assumption  that  the  will 
is  responsible  and  free,  and  what  this  can  mean,  if  attention  is  abso- 
lutely conditioned  on  the  affective  experiences  involved  in  interest,  is 
more  than  can  be  understood,  at  any  rate,  by  the  writer. 

Immediate  and  conscious  control,  then,  is  a  belief  which  is  sup- 
ported by  a  considerable  array  of  facts.  It  will  be  observed  that  it 
starts  and  abides  in  instinctive  control,  or  tact ;  but  presents  this 
marked  character :  the  gradual  subordination  of  the  mechanism  of 
mental  life  to  its  ends.  Step  by  step,  the  will  assumes  the  power  as 
it  is  disclosed,  and  maintains  its  self-activity  by  practice  until  the 
authority  of  reason  has  become  possible.  In  short,  we  meet  with  the 
same  phenomenon  here  as  we  meet  in  spontaneous  volition,  viz.,  the 
constant  mediating  of  reflex  action  and  '  freedom.' 

3.  The  same  fact  is  presented  in  what  I  have  described  as  teleo- 
logical  control,  or  self-control  in  the  ultimate  sense.  The  life  of  man, 
says  Hartley,  is  a  journey  from  self-interest  to  self-annihilation.  This 
thought,  which  is  sadly  neglected  in  both  psychology  and  pedagogy, 
owing  to  the  dominion  of  physical  theories  of  conduct,  plainly  im- 
plies a  progress  from  a  certain  aspect  of  the  self  to  another,  with  the 
full  consciousness  of  ends.  Not  to  wrangle  on  the  meaning  of  the 
terms,  *  self-interest,'  and  «  self-annihilation,'  all  will  finally  admit  that 
the  most  distinctive  characteristic  of  mind  is  activity  directed  towards 
ends.  The  will,  in  other  words,  is  teleological.  In  the  first  place,  it 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  647 

is  so,  spontaneously.  Tact  is  a  species  of  semi-conscious  adaptation 
of  means  to  ends.  Mechanism  is  not  opposed  to  purposive  selection ; 
it  is  itself  an  example  of  selection,  and  therefore  rests  finally  on  vol- 
untary control.  In  the  case  of  spontaneous  control,  the  end  sought  is 
so  largely  involved  in  the  operation  of  the  reflex-activities,  that  the 
apparent  automatic  response  given  bears  the  outward  marks  of  being 
purely  involuntary.  But  in  so  far  as  ends  are  proposed  will  is  involved. 
If  the  phenomena  of  tact  be  resolved  entirely  into  mechanism,  it  ceases 
to  be  a  state  of  the  finite  consciousness  except  as  re-presented. 

The  presence  of  ends  in  immediate  voluntary  activity  is  more 
readily  verified.  Synthetic  activity  is  now  denied  by  none  but  mate- 
rialists, and  so  far,  therefore,  the  will  in  seeking  the  control  of  the 
operations  of  consciousness  is  teleological.  In  specific  cases,  multi- 
tudes of  which  can  be  gathered  in  the  class  room  of  any  school  in  the 
land,  the  conscious  adjustment  involved  in  this  fact  can  be  seen.  The 
presence  of  ends  is  the  light  of  all  mind. 

But  it  is  more  particularly  when  the  ideals  of  reason  are  consid- 
ered that  the  full  swing  of  voluntary  activity  is  made  known.  The 
will  is  never  'freer'  than  when  it  brings  itself  under  the  laws  imma- 
nent in  reason.  A  lawless  will  is  an  abnormality  :  spiritual  principles 
lie  back  of  all  mechanism,  and  it  is  one  of  the  glories  of  man  that  he 
can  be  appealed  to  on  grounds  higher  than  those  of  self-interest.  Now 
the  stable  condition  of  voluntary  control  which  is  reached  as  a  result 
of  '  self-denial '  for  the  sake  of  higher  objects  and  ideals,  is  the  result 
of  conscious  adjustment:  c  The  self  as  an  immediate  object  of  direct 
cultivation  is  brought  under  higher  rational  ideals,  through  the  unify- 
ing activity  involved  in  all  our  teleological  self-activity.  What  we 
call  self-control,  which  expresses  both  spontaneity  and  final  purpose, 
is  thus  the  most  concrete  case  of  voluntary  control.  It  includes  the 
so-called  bodily  self,  with  its  mechanical  arrangement  of  organs 
and  functions;  it  includes  the  empirical  self,  and  developing  intellec- 
tion ;  it  includes  the  ideal  self,  that  is,  the  spiritual  self  which  furthers 
or  hinders  all  the  other  processes.  In  the  construction  of  this  self, 
it  is  will  that  plays  the  controlling  part.  The  feeling  about  the  neck 
and  head,  into  which  some1  would  resolve  the  consciousness  of  self, 
is  purely  an  organic  matter,  not  directly  connected  with  self-con- 
sciousness. But  '  nature '  could  appear  a  unity  only  for  the  reason 
that  the  will  teleological  ly  synthesizes  the  complex  activities  of  the  self ; 
nature  has  no  meaning  apart  from  unifying  intelligence,  and  therefore 
knowledge  would  be  impossible,  even  knowledge  of  the  neck-  and 

1  Cf.  Professor  James'  Principles  of  Psychology,  Vol.  I.,  300  p.  ff. 


648  GROWTH   OF   VOLUNTARY  CONTROL. 

head-feelings,  apart  from  voluntary  control.     The  essence  of  selfhood 
is  this  voluntary  activity  directed  by  ideals. 

In  ethics  and  religion  these  phenomena  are  matters  of  obvious  ex- 
perience.1 The  point  we  make  is  that  the  phenomena  of  voluntary 
control  are  obedient  to  a  general  relation,  which  obtains  between  re- 
flex-activity and  all  the  forms  of  '  freedom ' ;  that  the  real  question  in- 
volved is  this  mystery  of  control,  and  not  freedom  or  mechanism,  as 
the  alternative  is  usually  put. 

The  relation  of  these  facts  to  the  problem  of  noetics  and  ethics  is 
obvious,  but  too  large  to  be  explained  in  this  connection.  It  is  plain, 
however,  that  the  claim  for  free  intelligence  as  a  constitutive  element 
of  knowledge  and  conduct ;  the  claim  that  knowledge  is  impossible 
without  synthetic  activity,  turns  on  the  implicit  acknowledgment  or 
denial  of  the  phenomena  briefly  presented  above.  In  the  experiments 
conducted  by  Professor  Ladd,  briefly  referred  to,  the  claim  made  was 
that  the  will  not  only  can,  but  does,  control  the  physical  conditions  of 
intellection.  It  is  true  the  isolation  involved  in  all  experimentation 
required  special  conditions,  and  the  purposive  choice  of  means  and 
ends,  in  the  class  of  facts  brought  out  by  him ;  but  the  general  result 
was  to  establish  a  far  greater  degree  of  control  than  was  commonly, 
or  academically,  supposed  possible.  Even  making  all  due  allowance 
for  the  influence  a  distinguished  teacher  is  almost  always  able  to  exert 
on  the  pupils  he  teaches ;  making  all  allowance  for  the  fact  that  we 
are  liable  to  see  what  we  'want  to  see ;  the  simple  fact  is  (and  it  is 
borne  out  by  the  psychology  of  suggestion),2  that  the  will  has  more 
control  and  is  a  more  prominent  factor  in  our  life-history  than  current 
psychology  is  in  the  habit  of  admitting.  Whether  we  look  at  the 
spontaneous,  the  conscious,  or  the  teleological  form,  we  make  our  own 
character  and  destiny ;  I  would  go  further  and  say,  in  the  light  of  the 
few  facts  we  know,  that  unknown  possibilities  of  voluntary  control  are 
the  necessary  corollary  of  the  known,  and  that  the  future  life  and  hu- 
man immortality  are  (in  any  worthy  sense),  dependent  upon  the 
'free'  adjustment  of  our  souls,  in  the  society  of  being  (the  ultimate 
nature  of  which  cannot  exclude  intelligent  purpose)  to  God,  freedom 
and  immortality. 

HENRY  DAVIES. 

YALE  UNIVERSITY. 

1  Cf .  Bosanquet,  Psychology  of  the  Moral  Self. 
2Cf.  Sidis,  Psychology  of  Suggestion. 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  649 

ETHOLOGICAL  PSYCHOLOGY. 

In  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW  for  September,  1899,  Mr.  C.  B. 
Bliss  reviews  my  pamphlets  on  Ethology  in  sympathetic  and  apprecia- 
tive fashion.  These  pamphlets  were  prepared  primarily  at  the  sugges- 
tion of  one  of  my  colleagues  at  the  University  of  California  and  for 
the  purpose  of  giving  the  University  people  some  idea  of  the  work  I 
was  trying  to  do.  New  work  is  always  in  great  need  of  both  criti- 
cism and  sympathy.  I  hungered  and  do  hunger  for  both.  Knowing 
that  my  colleagues  could  find  out  more  about  the  work  if  they  wanted 
to,  I  ventured  to  pack  into  a  very  few  pages  an  amount  of  material 
far  too  great  to  be  clearly  set  forth  in  anything  less  than  a  good-sized 
book.  As  some  of  the  readers  of  this  REVIEW  may  agree  with  Mr. 
Bliss  that  the  work  is  important,  perhaps  I  may  be  pardoned  if  I  com- 
ment on  the  impression  my  work  has  produced  on — may  I  say — my 
fellow-psychologists.  The  history  of  the  terms  '  Education  as  Rela- 
ted to  Character  '  and  '  Ethology '  cannot  well  be  discussed  here ; 
suffice  it  to  say,  they  have  a  history  and  are  largely  due  to  local  condi- 
tions. I  certainly  have  no  desire  to  give  new  names  when  they  can  be 
avoided. 

In  a  sense,  all  the  sciences  that  have  to  do  with  consciousness  may 
be  called  psychology.  I  do  not  plead  guilty  to  the  charge  of  holding 
unworthy  views  of  psychology.  Unless,  however,  the  social  sciences, 
philosophy,  and  the  study  of  education  must  all  be  called  psychology, 
I  cannot  agree  that  the  science  of  the  development  of  concrete  charac- 
ter ought  to  be  called  a  chapter  in  psychology.  If  we  agree  that  all 
the  sciences  concerning  themselves  with  consciousness  should  be  called 
psychology,  I  see  no  reason  why  the  term  '  ethology '  should  not  be 
changed  to  *  ethological  psychology.'  In  one  sense,  geology  may 
be  called  4  geological  physics.' 

I  am  exceedingly  sorry  if  I  have  given  the  impression  that  I  regard 
psychology  as  'unsympathetic,  mechanical  and  lifeless.'  Such  an 
assertion  certainly  does  not  occur  in  my  writings.  For  instance,  I  re- 
gard the  teaching  of  psychology  by  my  colleague,  Professor  Stratton, 
as  sympathetic,  organic  and  full  of  life.  Perhaps  Mr.  Bliss  will  agree 
with  me  that  what  is  ordinarily  spoken  of  as  *  empirical  psychology  ' 
does  not  deal  with  concrete  character,  however  much  it  may  concern 
itself  with  interesting  and  concrete  psychical  experience.  The  other 
psychological  sciences  deal  with  various  aspects  of  our  complex  char- 
acter-life ;  ethological  psychology  deals  with  these  aspects  in  their  in- 
terrelation as  functions  of  actual  characters.  Hence,  for  instance, 


650  ETHOLOGICAL   PSYCHOLOGY. 

ethology  is  particularly  interested  in  the  study  of  scientific  biography. 
Most  of  my  advanced  students  are  working  on  biography.  '  Child- 
study  '  is  regarded  by  us  as  a  phase  of  biography.  We  try  to  keep 
the  characters  we  study  l  all  of  a  piece '  as  far  as  we  can.  Hence 
the  necessity  of  using  diagrams.  "  A  science  of  character  must  make 
the  whole  man  significant,  must  show  his  development  in  all  its  aspects, 
must  integrate  the  ethological  aspects  of  biological,  psychological, 
social  and  historical  sciences,  as  well  as  relate  itself  to  the  various 
philosophical  disciplines."  In  the  sentence  just  quoted  I  am  willing 
to  strike  out  all  of  the  adjectives  qualifying  the  word  '  sciences '  ex- 
cept the  term  '  the  psychological.'  Ethology  would  still  remain  as  a 
chapter  of  psychology  very  different  in  its  method  and  standpoint  from 
all  the  other  chapters.  * 

The  '  cone '  diagram  in  my  pamphlet  is  not  intended  to  show  all 
aspects  of  the  subject.  Diagrams  are  like  parables ;  they  must  not  be 
taken  too  literally  or  pushed  too  far.  Not  only  are  we  careful  in  our 
work  not  to  put  too  much  dependence  on  mechanical  devices ;  we  are 
also  careful  to  provide  ourselves  with  diagrams  that  show  to  some  ex- 
tent the  varying  value  of  the  different  aspects  of  character.  To  illus- 
trate :  we  use  a  diagram  showing  the  spiral  movement  in  the  develop- 
ment of  character  from  the  predominance  of  self-assertion,  through 
the  predominance  of  religious  instincts,  to  the  primacy  of  logical  in- 
sight. In  another  diagram  we  indicate  the  connection  of  self-asser- 
tion with  the  instincts  or  tendencies  for  play,  art  and  ideality. 

As  my  work  at  present  is  in  connection  with  a  department  of 
pedagogy,  it  is  natural  that  I  should  seem  to  put  too  much  stress  on 
the  school-studies  and  too  little  on  the  influence  of  authority  and  per- 
sonality. Mr.  Bliss  would  not  find  that  fault  with  the  actual  etholog- 
ical work.  I  meant  what  I  said  when  the  following  words  were  written 
in  the  pamphlet  on  ethology  :  "  Each  one  of  us  reflects  the  universe 
from  his  own  peculiar  standpoint.  Each  is  himself  and  not  another. 
Each  character  is  unique;  particular  and  universal;  social,  individ- 
ualistic and  personal.  The  universe's  interests  are  ours  and  ours  are 
the  universe's.  We  seek  to  bring  about  the  society  of  which  each  one 
of  us  is  a  member.  We  seek  not  the  society  apart  from  ourselves,  or 
ourselves  apart  from  the  society.  So  far  as  we  interact  with  others 
we  are  simply  natural  agents,  products  and  not  creators;  so  far  as 
we  really  cooperate  with  others,  we  are  creators,  and  are  members  of 
the  Kingdom  of  which  God  is  the  Integrator."  Indeed,  the  4  studies ' 
are  partial  results  of  character-life,  and  cannot  take  the  place  or  even 
share  the  place  of  real  living.  My  '  ethology '  would  have  a  poor  out- 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  651 

come  if  it  made  me  exalt  the  machinery  of  education.  In  an  essay 
recently  published  (JLove  and  Law,  San  Francisco,  1899)  I  take 
strong  ground  against  the  dispensation  of  the  '  Hoe  with  the  Man.' 

It  is  only  fair  to  say  that  our  study  of  ethology  is  being  applied  to 
the  school-work.  With  the  aid  of  Mrs.  Frances  Bracken  Gould,  a 
graduate  of  the  University  of  California,  and  a  very  clear-headed 
kindergartner,  we  have  been  able  to  see  many  of  our  ideas  put  to  the 
test  of  practice.  Work  is  also  being  done  on  history  in  the  schools, 
and  in  other  directions. 

THOMAS  P.  BAILEY,  JR.  • 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA. 


SENSATIONAL  ATTRIBUTES  AND  SENSATION. 

Professor  Calkins,  of  Wellesley,  in  the  last  number  of  the  REVIEW, 
brings  up  a  topic  still  much  in  need  of  similar  discussion  by  psychol- 
ogists ;  it,  however,  seems  to  me  that  she  makes  her  conclusions,  demon- 
strated by  excellent  arguments,  tend  in  rather  the  wrong  scientific 
direction,  her  logic  assisting,  moreover,  the  contention  of  the  present 
writer,  namely,  that  these  conclusions  do  not  go  far  enough. 

The  very  fact  that  introspection  at  once  belies  the  common  as- 
sertion of  the  best  text-books  that  sensations  do  have  attributes,  and 
this  despite  the  circumstance  that  by  definition  they  should  not  have 
them,  would  seem  to  argue  that  the  definition  itself  is  useless,  or  worse. 
That  the  term  is,  indeed,  worse  than  useless  is,  in  short,  the  conten- 
tion of  the  present  writer.  No  one  term  in  current  psychology  seems 
to  be  more  misleading  or,  as  Miss  Calkins  shows,  more  illogically 
used  than  that  of  this  very  concept. 

The  expression  sensation  *seems  to  be  one  that  indicates  little,  if 
anything,  more  than  a  somewhat  which  if  it  did  exist  might  serve  as 
a  basis  for  the  better  understanding  of  something  else,  namely,  the 
term  feeling.  It  is  as  if  one  precise  about  technical  terms,  in  teaching 
psychology  should  say :  You  all  know  what  a  feeling  is — well,  im- 
agine all  the  attributes  taken  away  from  feeling  and  you  have  a  notion 
of  a  sensation.  Indeed,  to  current  usage,  a  sensation  is  nothing  more 
than  the  unnecessary  Ding-an-sich  of  a  feeling,  or  its  logical  substance 
in  the  Spinozistic  sense. 

It  is  not  here  the  place  to  sketch  a  history  of  affective  terms  as 
used  in  mental  science,  nor  is  it  needful  to  do  so  clearly  to  suggest 


652         SENSATIONAL  ATTRIBUTES  AND   SENSATION. 

that  at  present  this  term  is  ordinarily  devoid  of  meaning.  It  is  hoped 
that  in  the  forthcoming  philosophical  dictionary  all  these  terms  will 
be  fixed  as  is  best  for  future  scientific  usage.  It  surely  is  not  neces- 
sary to  keep  the  term  in  use  in  its  common  sense  as  defined  by  Wundt, 
James,  Ladd,  Titchener  and  the  rest,  for  the  sake  of  denoting  the  insep- 
arable periods  of  special  consciousness  which  an  infant  is  supposed  to 
have  during  the  first  days  of  his  life,  nor  yet  to  signify  certain  rare  and 
almost  abnormal  experiences  had  by  adults  in  the  so-called  ;  anaesthesia,' 
or  on  awakening  from  coma.  Yet  these  are  almost  the  only  occasions 
on  which  a  '  sensation '  has  any  objective  existence.  If  we  examine  into 
the  connotative  properties  of  these  periods  of  consciousness,  we  find 
but  one,  and  that  deficiency — deficiency  of  '  quality,  intensity,  extent 
and  duration/  the  so-called  attributes  of  sensation.  This  Professor 
Calkins  aptly  shows.  Science  has  no  proper  use  for  terms  thus 
purely  negative. 

It  is,  in  part,  the  presence  in  psychology  and  in  allied  branches  of 
knowledge  of  such  concepts  as  this  of  sensation  that  makes  the  sub- 
ject so  often  difficult  and  confusing  to  the  beginner  and  frequently  so 
uncertain  of  expression  to  the  more  advanced  psychologist.  The 
term  sensation  is  not,  like  the  purely  abstract  notions  common  enough 
in  other  sciences,  denotative  of  something  fundamentally  important, 
but  its  proper  use,  as  noted  above,  is  very  infrequent  and  relatively  in- 
significant. The  terms  atom  and  ether,  for  example,  have  for  chem- 
istry and  physics  fundamental  importance,  for  on  them,  at  present,  is 
reared  in  part  the  noble  structures  of  these  sciences.  '  Sensation,'  on 
the  contrary,  is  a  relic  of  a  now  quite  outworn  psychology  of  mind- 
stuff,  and  positively  misleads  therefore  in  this  important  regard, 
while  indicating  nothing  of  value  as  amends.  Sensation,  as  defined 
and  in  use  to-day,  is  not  the  substance  out  of  which  is  characteristic- 
ally carved,  so  to  say,  a  feeling ;  nor  is  the  sensation  buried  beneath 
the  feeling,  forming  its  base;  but  in  general  the  sensation  simply  is 
not  concerned  in  the  feeling  at  all :  the  feeling  is  feeling  all  the  way 
through  and  it  is  nothing  else. 

Modern  advance  toward  demonstration  of  the  doctrine  of  paral- 
lelism has  done  away  with  any  usefulness  the  term  sensation  might 
have  (as  defined  by  J.  S.  Mill,  for  example),  as  the  immediate  con- 
comitant of  a  bodily  change,  for  feelings  as  certainly  as  sensa- 
tions are  now  considered  to  be  direct  correlates  of  somatic  conditions. 
For  popular  use  the  term  still  has,  of  course,  reason  to  exist ;  our 
present  strictures  apply  only  to  the  technical  usage,  when  it  is  im- 
portant to  be  exact. 


DISCUSSION  AND  REPORTS.  653 

My  attack  then,  is  not,  like  that  of  Professor  Calkins,  on  the  attri- 
butes of  sensation,  but  upon  the  term  sensation  itself  as  its  most  fre- 
quent application  defines  it. 

GEORGE  V.  N.  DEARBORN. 

HARVARD  UNIVERSITY. 


AFTER-IMAGES. 

In  his  recently  published  monograph  on  'After-Images,'  Mr.  S.  I. 
Franz  makes  with  reference  to  some  work  of  mine  a  slightly  mislead- 
ing statement.  The  article  referred  to  appeared  in  Mind  for  last 
January,  and  Mr.  Franz  implies  that  its  writer  while  noting  the  ex- 
istence of  individual  variations  in  the  color  changes  of  the  image,  ar- 
bitrarily eliminated  them,  and  that  '  her  subjects  had  to  be  drilled  to  see 
a  normal  image  (i.  e.,  like  her  own)/  This  way  of  putting  the 
matter  would  lead  one  to  suppose  that  the  uniformity  of  results  at- 
tained was  an  artificial  one,  produced  by  suggestion  :  that  is,  that  the 
subjects  were  told  what  I  saw,  and  drilled  until  they  could  see  the 
same  thing.  On  the  contrary,  as  the  object  of  the  study  was  to  ob- 
serve the  effect  of  suggestion  on  the  image,  I  was  careful  to  give  no 
hint  to  my  subjects  of  my  own  experiences,  during  the  experiments  to 
determine  the  normal  course  of  the  image.  I  simply  found  that  while 
great  individual  differences  existed  at  first,  they  tended  to  disappear  in 
large  measure  with  practice.  I  quite  agree  with  Mr.  Franz  that  the 
causes  of  these  variations  deserve  thorough  investigation,  but  I  am  in- 
clined to  think  that  one  important  cause  is  simply  lack  of  practice  in 
discriminating  the  image  from  subjective  or  other  retinal  phenomena, 

MARGARET  FLOY  WASHBURN. 
WELLS  COLLEGE. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE. 

NEUROLOGY  AND   PATHOLOGY. 

Nevroses  et  idees  fixes.     Etudes  experimentales  sur  les  troubles  de  la 

volonte",  de  1'attention,  de  la  memoire ;  sur  les  emotions,  les  idees 

obs6dantes  et  leur  traitement.     DR.  PIERRE  JANET.     Felix  Alcan. 

1898.     Pp.  492. 

In  this  work  Dr.  Janet  has  brought  together  a  number  of  papers 
of  psychological  interest  read  before  various  societies,  and  has  added 
to  them  a  series  of  chapters  based  upon  studies  made  upon  invalids 
suffering  from  various  forms  of  mental  disease. 

In  the  introduction  he  calls  attention  to  the  fact  that  much  valu- 
able information  for  psychologists  is  to  be  obtained  from  the  study  of 
abnormal  minds,  and  that  no  psychological  system  can  be  considered 
adequate  which  does  not  take  into  consideration  the  disturbances  of 
will,  of  attention,  of  memory  and  of  emotion  so  commonly  manifested 
by  the  insane. 

At  the  Salpetriere  Dr.  Janet  had  the  opportunity  of  studying 
many  such  cases  of  mental  disease  especially  among  the  hysterical  pa- 
tients of  Professor  Raymond,  to  whom  the  volume  is  dedicated.  The 
first  fifty  pages  are  devoted  to  a  careful  analysis  of  the  mental  pro- 
cesses in  a  young  hysterical  girl,  who  manifested  a  number  of  fixed 
ideas.  These  led  in  her  case  to  apparent  defects  of  will  power,  to  im- 
perfect power  of  attention  and  memory  and  to  abnormal  acts  of  many 
kinds.  The  attempt  is  made  to  trace  these  acts  and  defects  to  the  ex- 
istence of  ideas,  present  to  the  subconscious  self  rather  than  existing  in 
consciousness.  And  the  proof  of  this  is  given  in  the  fact  that  hyp- 
notic suggestions  succeeded  in  combatting  the  ideas  and  thus  changing 
the  character,  acts  and  conduct.  These  fixed  ideas  seemed  to  vary  in 
duration  and  intensity,  a  fact  which  Janet  implies  by  the  expression 
idees  fixes  stratifiees,  and  the  most  permanent  were  found  more  diffi- 
cult to  reach  by  suggestion  than  others.  A  true  hysterical  explosion 
seemed  to  be  followed  by  a  clearing  away  of  the  ideas  and  a  normal 
train  of  thought,  and  eventually  the  patient  returned  to  a  state  of  com- 
plete sanity  after  a  number  of  such  attacks. 

This  chapter  with  its  painstaking  analysis  of  this  girl's  character 
illustrates  well  the  position  of  Janet  that  "experimental  psychology 
654 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  655 

consists  above  all  in  mastering  the  particular  subject  studied,  his  life, 
his  temperament,  his  character,  his  ideas ;  and  in  being  convinced  that 
one  can  never  learn  enough.  It  is  necessary  to  place  this  subject  in 
various  given  circumstances  and  notice  exactly  what  he  says  and  does. 
This  method  enables  us  to  discover  many  things  which  are  not  with- 
out interest  for  pathological  psychology"  (67). 

In  chapter  second  Janet  describes  certain  results  obtained  in  an 
attempt  to  measure  the  degree  of  attention  and  the  reaction  time  of 
certain  individuals,  normal  and  abnormal ;  his  results  being  about  the 
same  as  those  of  other  observers. 

Chapter  third  contains  a  careful  study  of  a  patient  whose  memory 
of  events  was  suddenly  arrested  by  a  shock  at  a  given  date  and  who 
for  nearly  nine  months  appeared  to  have  no  memory  of  things  occur- 
ring subsequently  to  that  shock,  i.  <?.,  she  lost  her  power  of  acquiring 
new  memories.  Janet  distinguishes  this  condition  from  the  more 
common  one  in  which  certain  memories,  as  of  language,  are  obliter- 
ated by  disease ;  and  he  shows  what  a  different  influence  it  has  on  the 
character.  This  form  of  defective  memory  he  names  continued  am- 
nesia. The  subject  Mme.  D.  seemed  to  see  persons  and  objects,  but  a 
moment  after  failed  to  recognize  them  or  to  have  any  memory  of  hav- 
ing seen  them.  All  impressions  rolled  away  and  left  no  trace,  even 
events  of  importance  to  her  were  entirely  forgotten  at  once.  An  indi- 
vidual may  after  an  accident  forget  a  few  weeks  of  his  life  but  up  to 
the  time  of  the  accident  his  memory  was  good.  An  individual  of  two 
personalitities  under  suggestion  may  forget  in  state  II  the  events  of 
state  I,  but  when  again  in  state  I  the  memory  becomes  continuous. 
But  in  Mme.  D.  there  was  a  disappearance  of  the  power  of  acquiring 
new  memories  for  this  entire  period.  When,  however,  she  was  hyp- 
notized and  questioned,  she  related  accurately  all  the  events  which  had 
occurred  during  this  period  showing  the  existence  of  an  unconscious 
memory  which  was  not  available  on  the  conscious  state.  Hence 
though  apparently  without  memory  Mme.  D.  really  was  not  deprived 
of  memory  and  her  talk  during  sleep  revealed  the  existence  of  memo- 
ries of  things  about  her.  She  also  had  a  clear  memory  of  things  sug- 
gested in  a  hypnotic  state,  would  execute  post-hypnotic  suggestions. 
Automatic  writing  also  showed  the  existence  of  memory  of  current 
events.  Janet  attempts  to  explain  this  condition  by  separating  the 
power  of  acquiring  memories  from  the  power  of  reproducing  memories 
acquired.  In  the  case  of  Mme.  D.  the  latter  was  defective.  It  is  not 
enough  that  a  simple  isolated  sensation  should  be  produced  in  the 
mind  that  it  thereby  should  be  perceived.  There  is  needed  for  com- 


656  NEUROLOGY  AND  PATHOLOGY. 

plete  consciousness  of  a  sensation  which  is  expressed  by  the  words  I 
perceive,  a  second  mental  operation  in  addition  to  the  first — not  only 
a  personal  perception  of  memories  but  a  psychological  assimilation  of 
images  (p.  135).  And  any  distraction  of  the  mind  is  capable  of  in- 
terfering with  this  process.  Hence  Janet  explains  this  defect  of 
memory  as  he  does  the  anaesthesia  of  hysterical  subjects  as  a  limitation 
of  the  field  of  consciousness,  a  feebleness  of  the  personality  incapable 
of  synthetizing  all  the  sensations.  The  origin  of  this  defect  of  mem- 
ory in  Mme.  D.  was  a  sudden  shock,  and  Janet,  believing  that  this 
shock  was  really  a  fixed  idea  before  the  mind  causing  a  distraction, 
succeeded  in  curing  Mme.  D.  by  modifying  her  emotional  state  during 
hypnosis  by  suggestions  directed  to  the  emotion.  Thus  all  suggestions 
of  return  of  memory  having  failed,  he  suggested  certain  modifications 
of  the  original  emotion  and  thus  changed  the  distraction  of  the  mind 
by  the  emotion  into  a  more  normal  state.  As  a  result  the  distraction 
ceased  and  then  memory  returned. 

Another  case  was  that  of  a  young  woman  who  became  possessed 
of  the  fixed  idea  that  she  was  a  victim  of  cholera.  All  the  symptoms 
followed  in  a  series  of  attacks,  but  from  each  she  recovered,  remain- 
ing, however,  completely  unequal  to  any  mental  or  physical  effort  on 
account  of  this  prevailing  fear.  Various  attempts  in  a  hypnotic  state 
succeeded  in  modifying  the  fixed  idea  but  not  in  abolishing  it.  Finally 
Janet  tried  to  decompose  the  idea  and  thus  destroy  it.  "  The  fixed 
idea  consists  of  a  synthesis  of  many  images,  and  instead  of  attacking 
it  as  a  whole  we  attempted  to  transform  its  elements,  substituting  one 
for  another  and  thus  to  destroy  the  idea  as  a  whole"  (p.  164).  The 
patient  had  a  mental  picture  of  cadavers  ready  for  burial.  Janet  sug- 
gested a  certain  Chinese  general  with  his  robes  in  place  of  the  cadaver, 
and  then  suggested  that  this  figure  was  alive  and  walking  about,  thus 
removing  the  fear  of  the  cadaver  and  of  the  cholera  causing  death. 
But  this  was  not  sufficient,  and  then  the  attempt  was  made  to  substi- 
tute for  the  word  cholera  other  words  by  analyzing  its  syllables  and 
suggesting  others  in  their  place,  until  finally  the  word  cholera  appeared 
to  lose  its  significance  for  the  patient.  She  could  not  recollect  it,  and 
it  no  longer  caused  alarm.  In  this  way  the  fixed  idea  being  removed 
the  fear  ceased  and  recovery  ensued.  There  were  in  this  case  other 
secondary  fixed  ideas  which  are  most  interestingly  discussed  in  this 
chapter,  and  which  in  turn  finally  disappeared. 

On  the  basis  of  these  cases  Janet  gives,  in  Chapter  V. ,  a  resume 
of  the  great  influence  such  fixed  ideas  may  play  on  the  mental  char- 
acter of  hysterical  patients ;  the  idea  being  sometimes  subconscious, 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  657 

not  recognized  or  known  by  the  patient,  yet  nevertheless  determining 
the  acts  and  feelings  and  conduct.  The  essential  feature  of  hysteria 
is  the  existence  of  these  subconscious  ideas  or  representations  (  Vorstel- 
lungen).  They  are  perfectly  comparable  to  post-hypnotic  suggestion, 
controlling  action  without  being  conscious.  In  some  cases  such  ideas 
may  be,  however,  conscious,  develop  in  spite  of  the  will,  and  are  not 
under  voluntary  control.  In  the  majority  of  cases  it  is  some  emotional 
shock  which  gives  rise  to  the  idea  either  conscious  or  unconscious,  and 
hence  emotional  shocks  are  the  frequent  cause  of  hysterical  symptoms. 

In  the  succeeding  chapters  Janet  studies  various  forms  of  hysterical 
manifestations,  hemianopsia,  allocheiria ;  contractures  and  spasms  of 
the  trunk  with  disturbances  of  respiration,  in  all  of  which  he  shows  that 
the  subconscious  idea  determined  the  effect,  and  its  removal  by  hypnotic 
suggestion  resulted  in  a  cure  of  the  symptom.  Such  cases  as  he  pre- 
sents in  detail  with  much  interesting  psychological  analysis  are  familiar 
to  many  physicians,  and  are  not  at  all  peculiar  to  the  French.  It  is, 
however,  unfortunate  that  in  this  country  patients  are  far  less  easily 
hypnotized  in  the  ordinary  manner,  although  the  success  of  the  admo- 
nitions of  mental  healers  and  Christian  scientists,  so-called,  demon- 
strate that  auto-suggestion  has  over  many  minds  a  controlling  influ- 
ence. It  is  quite  certain  that  the  mental  state  of  calm  induced  by 
certain  methods  advocated  by  these  misguided  and  ignorant  individuals 
may  act  as  hypnosis  acts  to  counteract  states  of  emotional  excitement 
of  a  subconscious  kind  and  thus  benefit  the  individual. 

Chapter  IX.  contains  a  study  of  a  case  of  insomnia,  the  remark- 
able case  of  a  young  woman  who  for  two  and  a  half  years  did  not 
sleep  at  all,  being  wakened  within  a  minute  of  falling  asleep  by  a 
terrifying  idea,  the  memory  of  the  death  of  her  child.  The  actual 
character  of  this  idea  she  had  no  recollection  of  during  her  waking 
state ;  and  it  was  only  in  a  state  of  somnambulism  induced  by  hypnotic 
suggestion  that  Janet  succeeded  in  eliciting  from  her  the  memory 
which  caused  the  terror.  By  suggestion  during  hypnotism  this  mem- 
ory was  disintegrated  and  she  was  cured.  Janet  emphasizes  the  great 
influence  which  subconscious  or  semi-conscious  ideas  have  upon  sleep 
and  its  disturbances,  a  fact  only  too  well  known  to  almost  every  one 
practically  who  has  suffered  from  insomnia.  The  existence  of  a  fixed 
idea  on  the  subconscious  level  is  enough  to  prevent  or  disturb  the  con- 
dition of  the  mind  necessary  to  the  obliteration  of  consciousness  oc- 
curring in  normal  sleep.  Many  persons  in  sleep  are  really  in  a  state 
in  which  the  subconscious  self  is  quite  awake.  Thus  a  mother  may 
watch  her  child  while  asleep,  waking  at  the  least  movement  or  cry  of 


658  NEUROLOGY  AND  PATHOLOGY. 

the  child  yet  remaining  undisturbed  by  other  far  louder  noises.  Many 
persons  can  waken  at  a  given  hour.  Thus  it  is  evident  that  subcon- 
scious processes  may  go  on  during  sleep  and  may  modify  or  prevent 
it.  Such  disturbances  of  sleep  as  are  thus  produced  must  be  treated 
as  Janet  shows  rather  by  suggestion  than  by  drugs,  by  removing  the 
fixed  idea  which  dominates  the  subconscious  self  and  reacts  upon  con- 
sciousness. 

Chapter  X.  contains  a  study  of  demoniacal  possession  in  a  lunatic 
and  of  Janet's  success  in  exorcising  the  demon  by  hypnotic  suggestion. 
The  analysis  of  the  condition  of  the  patient  is  most  interesting  and 
will  well  repay  the  study  of  every  alienist  as  there  are  doubtless  in 
every  asylum  similar  cases  easily  curable  if  one  had  the  patience  to  ex- 
amine the  mental  characteristics,  the  method  of  the  development  of 
the  delusion,  and  to  obtain  control  of  the  individual.  The  clue  to 
these  cases  according  to  Janet  lies  in  discovering  the  fixed  idea,  almost 
always  subconscious,  which  gives  rise  to  their  insane  acts,  and  by  re- 
moving it  by  hypnotic  suggestion.  There  is  incidentally  introduced 
into  the  chapter  an  interesting  hint  regarding  the  explanation  of  the 
acts  and  revelations  of  spirit  mediums. 

Janet  ascribes  their  automatic  writing  and  unconscious  statements 
to  the  subconscious  self  open  to  the  suggestion  of  the  individual  con- 
sulting them  and  hence  responding  to  him  as  he  may  desire. 

In  Chapter  XI.  crystal  vision  is  described,  and  the  position  taken 
is  that  the  visions  are  unexpected  involuntary  visual  memories  of  the 
unconscious  self  which  becoming  conscious  cause  surprise,  and  seem 
like  revelations. 

Chapter  XII.  is  of  particular  interest,  as  it  is  devoted  to  a  study  of 
the  effect  of  hypnotism  upon  the  person  hypnotized.  Janet  affirms 
that  after  each  seance  there  is  a  period  of  exhaustion  during  which 
suggestions  made  become  fixed,  and  then  a  latent  period  in  which  sug- 
gestions are  active  but  are  gradually  fading  in  intensity,  and  at  the 
end  of  this  there  comes  a  period  of  desire  to  be  re-hypnotized  with  a 
state  of  mind  in  which  the  patient  is  very  dependent  upon  the  hyp- 
notizer.  If  not  re-hypnotized  the  original  ideas,  paralysis,  etc.,  recur. 
Hence,  Janet  emphasizes  the  need  of  a  course  of  hypnotization  in  any 
case  of  disease  rather  than  the  expectation  of  cure  from  a  single  or  a 
few  seances.  He  then  proceeds  to  study  the  state  of  mind  of  depend- 
ence which  those  who  have  been  hypnotized  feel,  and  shows  that  this 
state  of  mind  is  characteristic  of  many  individuals  in  the  community 
who  need  direction  by  others,  and  who  are  thus  influenced  without  be- 
ing hypnotized.  It  is  the  subconscious  self  which  is  really  reached 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  659 

and  directed  by  a  strong  will   in  the  case  of  these  weak  persons,   and 
unless  it  is  directed  they  are  unhappy  and  incapable. 

As  a  study  in  psychology  few  recent  works  can  approach  this  book 
of  Janet's  for  interest  and  profit.  The  one  fact  which  it  emphasizes 
is  that  character  and  conduct  are  the  result  as  much  of  unconscious  as 
of  conscious  mental  activities,  and  that  no  study  of  individual  action, 
either  sane  or  insane,  can  be  considered  complete  which  neglects  both 
these  factors.  M.  ALLEN  STARR. 

Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases.     H.  CHURCH  and  FREDERICK  PE- 
TERSON.    Philadelphia,  Saunders.     1899. 

It  is  not  an  easy  task  to  write  a  text-book  upon  mental  disease. 
The  writer  should  possess  considerable  knowledge  of  psychology  both 
of  its  subjective  side  and  also  of  the  many  recent  advances  in  the 
physiology  of  the  brain.  He  should,  furthermore,  have  such  a  prac- 
tical knowledge  of  insanity  as  can  only  be  acquired  by  its  clinical 
study  in  an  asylum.  And  lastly  it  is  of  no  little  moment  that  his  lit- 
erary style  should  combine  clearness  and  accuracy  of  thought  with 
a  felicitous  use  of  language.  Among  recent  text-books  upon  Mental 
Diseases,  that  of  Dr.  Peterson  seems  more  nearly  to  fulfill  these  con- 
ditions than  any  with  which  we  are  acquainted.  He  has  a  facility  in 
stating  his  facts  which  renders  his  views  easily  understood  by  the 
the  student  or  by  the  ordinary  reader.  He  has  a  thorough  knowledge 
of  insanity  from  long  residence  in  a  large  institution  where  his  time 
was  not  devoted  to  the  petty  detail  of  management  but  to  the  study  of 
his  patients — and  his  familiarity  with  psychology  is  easily  detected  on 
every  page. 

The  book  falls  naturally  into  two  portions — the  study  of  the  symp- 
toms of  insanity  and  the  study  of  its  various  forms  as  they  are  clin- 
ically manifest.  In  the  first  part  the  physiology  of  the  brain  plays  a 
prominent  part,  and  the  unqualified  materialistic  position  is,  of  course, 
assumed.  This  seems  inevitable  from  the  medical  standpoint,  and  we 
cannot  but  feel  that  too  little  importance  is  given  to  the  subjective  side. 
There  are  many  mental  processes  which  wholly  defy  physiological 
explanation  such  as  the  formation  of  delusions,  or  the  permanence  of 
fixed  ideas  which  either  subconsciously  or  consciously  control  thought 
and  action,  and  it  is  the  tendency  of  the  materialist  to  devote  his  at- 
tention to  these  rather  than  to  the  hallucinations  or  defects  of  memory 
which  are  so  much  more  easily  explained.  It  seems  to  the  writer  that 
too  little  attention  has  been  given  by  the  author  to  the  writings  of  the 
French  school,  especially  to  such  works  as  those  of  Fere"  and  Janet ; 


660  THE  EMOTIONS. 

and  that  their  theories  in  regard  to  the  existence  of  fixed  ideas  below 
the  level  of  consciousness  which  certainly  play  a  large  part  in  the  de- 
velopment of  certain  symptoms  of  insanity  might  have  been  utilized 
in  this  section. 

Dr.  Peterson  has  avoided  very  nicely  the  abyss  into  which  many 
writers  on  mental  diseases  have  fallen  by  refraining  from  any  discus- 
sion of  the  classification  of  the  insanities.  The  time  has  not  yet  come 
for  a  classification,  as  no  basis — pathological,  clinical,  or  theoretical — 
has  yet  been  found.  He  merely  takes  pains  to  give  certain  classifica- 
tions of  other  writers,  and  then  takes  up  the  well-recognized  forms  of 
insanity,  melancholia,  mania,  demenoia,  paranoia  and  paresis.  These 
are  carefully  discussed  and  well  described,  and  will  give  a  good  clin- 
ical picture  to  the  reader. 

The  work  can  be  recommended  to  the  student  of  psychology  and 
of  medicine  as  a  concise  and  satisfactory  text-book  upon  a  difficult 
subject.  M.  A.  S. 

THE   EMOTIONS. 

La  peur  et   le   mechanisme   des   emotions.     DR.    PAUL    HARTEN- 

BERG.  Rev.  Phil.,  XLVIII.  Pp.  113-134.  Aug.,  1899. 
Observations  sur  le  pouls  radial  pendant  les  emotions.  N.  VAS- 
CHIDE.  Rev.  Phil.,  XLVIII.  Pp.  276-316.  Sept.,  1899. 
Hartenberg's  article  is  written  from  the  point  of  view  which  re- 
gards an  emotion  as  an  interior  synthesis  of  motions.  Hence  the  or- 
ganic changes  which,  on  the  James-Lange  theory,  are  the  cause  of 
the  emotion,  are  here  considered  to  be  the  emotion  itself  and  only  the 
cause  of  the  consciousness  of  the  emotion.  This  is  clearly  a  pure 
difference  of  definition.  The  distinguishing  feature  of  the  author's 
analysis  of  the  emotional  process  is  the  insertion  at  both  its  initial  and 
its  final  stage  of  a  central  process  of  association.  The  efferent  dis- 
charge is  held  to  be  controlled  by  a  motor  image  having  its  center  in 
the  prefrontal  convolutions,  an  image  whose  associative  function  is  to 
coordinate  the  various  discharges  and  to  mediate  between  the  '  psychic 
representations' and  the  'emotion.'  And  on  the  completion  of  the 
circuit  there  is  held  to  be  a  similar  sensory  image,  situated  in  the  same 
area,  whose  function  is  to  combine  the  impressions  received  and  to 
connect  them  with  other  images.  There  is  here  a  recognition  at  least 
of  the  coordination  of  elements  in  the  emotional  process,  though  no 
distinct  recognition  of  the  important  problem  of  their  coordination 
relatively  to  the  so-called  '  object.'  Unfortunately,  so  many  of  the 


PSYCHOLOGICAL    LITERATURE.  66 1 

bodily  '  expressions '  appear  to  fall  outside  of  this  last  coordination 
altogether  and  to  be  mere  accidental  accompaniments.  Moreover,  we 
may  at  present  perhaps  still  hesitate  to  accept  the  views  of  association 
centers,  on  which  the  author  builds  his  theory,  as  final.  As  to  the 
emotion  of  fear,  the  only  thing  noticeable  in  the  incidental  treatment 
here  given  of  it  is  the  testimony  against  Lange's  view  of  the  im- 
portance of  the  vaso-motor  phenomena,  the  fact  being  pointed  out 
that,  while  the  most  constant  phenomena  in  fear  are  arrested  respira- 
tion, constriction  of  the  thorax  and  the  feeling  of  stifling,  there  is  a 
great  deal  of  individual  variation. 

Vaschide's  investigations  have  also  reference  to  Lange's  theory,  in 
that  they  deal  with  one  aspect  of  the  relation  of  emotion  to  circula- 
tion. The  particular  question  studied  is  the  relative  frequency  during 
the  course  of  an  emotion  of  the  radial  pulse.  This  subject  had  been 
already  experimented  on  by  Binet  and  Courtier  in  the  laboratory ;  the 
present  study  deals  with  it  in  the  case  of  emotions  spontaneously 
aroused  by  the  experiences  of  common  life.  The  investigation  under 
these  circumstances  was  naturally  one  of  great  difficulty  and  delicacy, 
and  opinion  will  probably  differ,  not  only  as  to  the  value  of  the  results 
obtained  in  any  given  case,  but  also  as  to  the  conditions  under  which 
investigations  of  this  sort  are  even  admirable.  The  proverbial  savant 
who  botanizes  on  his  mother's  grave  is  certainly  not  more  shocking 
in  his  devotion  to  the  sacred  cause  of  science  than  our  psychologist  who 
takes  his  mother's  pulse  on  their  first  meeting  after  the  death  of  his 
father  (p.  300),  and  again  at  his  father's  grave  (p.  301),  and  who  ex- 
amines and  records  his  own  pulse  when  alone  at  the  grave,  after  the 
emotion  had  seized  him  '  avec  une  fureur  et  puissance  enorme  '  (p.  307) . 
However,  the  results  are  not  a  little  interesting.  They  go  to  confirm 
the  experiences  of  Binet  and  Courtier,  viz.,  that  in  all  emotions,  what- 
ever their  quality  and  tone,  there  is  usually  first  an  acceleration  and 
then  a  slowing-down  of  the  movement  of  the  heart.  Vaschide  found 
this  result  uniform  in  all  his  observations  and  under  all  circumstances. 
The  only  important  difference  was  that  in  the  strongest  emotions  of 
grief,  the  movement  both  rose  higher  and  fell  less  evenly  and  to  a 
lower  point  than  in  the  intensest  emotions  of  joy.  In  emotions  of 
moderate  strength  there  was  almost  no  difference.  The  conclusion, 
therefore,  is  that  the  pulse  alone  is  no  criterion  of  the  quality  of  an 
emotion. 

H.  N.  GARDINER. 
SMITH  COLLEGE. 


662  THE  EMOTIONS. 

Ueber  den  Begriff  der  Gemilthsbewegung.  C.  STUMPF.  Zeitschrift 
f.  Psych,  u.  Phys,  d.  Sinnersorgane.  Bd.  XI.  Pp.  47-99. 
The  interest  of  the  author  in  this  article  is  to  get  the  adequate  and 
defensible  definition  of  emotion,  rather  than  to  point  out  the  conditions 
of  its  origin  and  development.  Though  implying  the  entire  affective 
process,  the  considerations  are  limited  to  those  phenomena  which  are 
especially  regarded  as  emotions  {Ajfect},  viz.,  joy,  sorrow,  hope,  fear, 
wonder,  etc.  The  positive  outcome  is  rather  speedily  reached  in  the 
preliminary  analysis  which  concludes  thus.  The  peculiar  quality  of  a 
definite  emotion,  which  constitutes  its  inner  nature  for  our  conscious- 
ness, cannot  be  defined  in  any  manner.  The  most  exact  and  complete 
definition  can  mention  only  certain  rather  uniformly  recurring  marks ; 
but  to  one,  who  has  never  lived  through  the  state,  the  definition  cannot 
make  plain  what  would  transpire  in  his  breast.  This  need  of  imme- 
diate experience  does  not  forestall  an  analytical  account  of  the  emo- 
tional content  of  consciousness,  which  admittedly  presents  nothing 
new,  but  confirms  the  older  intellectual  accounts  given  of  the  emotions. 
The  popular  equivalency  of  emotion  and  affective  process  does  not  aid 
scientific  psychology.  There  is  a  recognizable  difference  between 
emotion  and  other  feelings,  as  to  intensity,  time-rate,  ideas,  and  judg- 
ment involved.  Emotions  do  not  arise  from  sensations  directly.  The 
sphere  of  emotion  is  greatly  widened  when  judgment  is  integrated  in 
the  emotive  state.  This  factor  adds  no  difficulty  to  the  definition. 
Emotion  is  also  distinguishable  from  desire.  The  latter  is  related  to 
the  actual,  the  former  to  that  which  ought  to  be.  In  this  respect,  emo- 
tion may  be  defined  as  a  passive  condition  of  feeling,  which  relates 
itself  to  a  judged  content.  S.  insists  that  a  real  emotion  presupposes  a 
certain  amount  of  mental  development,  rather  than  being  innate,  or 
given  with  the  biological  structure. 

The  scientific  need  of  pointing  out  the  inner  nature  of  emotion 
more  conceptually,  so  to  speak,  has  given  occasion  for  the  formation 
of  the  more  modern  sensualistic  theories.  It  is  supposed  that  referring 
to  blood  and  muscle  makes  the  phenomena  '  clearer,'  because  we  are 
more  familiar  with  these  in  life,  than  with  the  intellectual  principles 
of  the  older  theory.  It  is  also  supposed  that  the  problems  of  classifi- 
cation are  hereby  simplified.  The  critical  portion  of  the  article  takes 
up  the  theories  advocated  by  Ribot,  and  by  James  and  Lange.  The 
former  regards  emotion  as  only  complicated  states  of  the  sensuous 
feelings  of  pleasure  and  pain.  This  theory  might  have  a  show  of  ac- 
ceptability if  judgment,  as  affecting  feeling,  could  be  reduced  to  mere 
idea  or  sensation.  Most  psychologists  to-day  reply  to  this  demand  in 
the  negative. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  663 

The  James-Lange  theory  is  not  to  be  identified  with  that  of  Ribot, 
though  there  is  much  in  common.  This  view  finds  the  essence  of  emo- 
tion in  the  peripheral  corporeal  processes,  L.  selecting  vaso-motor 
changes,  J.  the  vegetative  processes,  or  visceral  sensations.  The  ob- 
scurity of  the  theory  lies,  in  part,  in  its  general  inability  to  locate  the 
emotion  in  its  exact  relation  to  the  sensory  stimulation  and  the  attend- 
ant organic  reflexes.  It  is  shown  how  the  real  conception  of  the  theory 
depends  finally  upon  the  psycho-physical  principle  adopted,  since  it  be- 
comes a  question  of  the  casual  direction.  The  state  of  the  discussion 
of  the  theory,  after  fifteen  years  of  defense,  is  not  encouraging.  Op- 
ponents are  more  numerous  than  adherents.  The  advocates  forget 
that,  in  spite  of  all  objective  and  physiological  psychology,  an  oppor- 
tunity of  self-observation  must  be  essential  to  any  attempted  definition. 
The  question  of  the  theory  cannot  be  referred  to  facts,  since  new  facts 
of  emotive  reactions  are  not  forthcoming.  It  remains  a  question  of 
the  power  of  the  arguments.  The  proof  rests  on  two  considerations  : 
Nothing  of  the  emotion  remains  when  we  think  away  all  the  so-called 
accompanying  phenomena  and  the  corresponding  organic  sensations ; 
secondly,  emotions  are  produced  by  purely  physical  means,  even  when 
the  representation  of  objects  is  entirely  wanting,  the  latter  being  the 
chief  feature  of  the  older  theory.  In  the  first  instance,  the  pathologi- 
cal proofs  fail,  since  the  argument  supports  either  the  old  or  the  new 
theory.  The  proof  is  robbed  of  all  power  by  the  fact  that  in  anaes- 
thesia, e.  g.,  there  is  necessarily  a  reduction  and  impairment  of  the 
intellectual  functions.  The  hypnotic  cases  tried  by  Sollier  fail  in  a 
similar  manner. 

Besides  the  particular  grounds  of  proof  offered,  the  two  projectors 
of  this  theory  appeal  to  certain  general  principles  to  support  their 
views.  We  are  presented  with  the  strange  spectacle  of  a  physiologist, 
L.,  invoking  the  aid  of  philosophical  monism,  and  J.,  a  philosopher, 
putting  forth  the  physiological  law  of  ideo-motor  effects,  to  support 
the  theory.  Monistic  hypotheses  are  rejected,  however,  where  psy- 
chological observation  alone  must  be  admitted  in  determining  a  defini- 
tion. Emotions  are  something  psychical,  whether  the  monism  be- 
comes physical  or  spiritual  in  its  logical  formulation.  The  law  of 
dynamogenesis,  as  interpreted  by  J.,  is  not  fully  proven.  The  factor 
of  the  stimulus  threshold  is  omitted.  Ideo-motor  effects  are  apparent 
only  when  the  stimulus  has  reached  a  certain  intensity.  Fere's  re- 
sults on  sensation  and  movement  are  not  conclusive,  since  they  con- 
tain too  many  defects  of  method.  The  brain  is  not  a  mere  tube, 
through  which  every  drop  of  the  stimulus  flows  immediately  to  the 


664  THE  EMOTIONS. 

periphery ;  it  is  more  like  a  catch-basin.  Every  sensation  does  not, 
fortunately,  as  shown  by  Sommer  and  Herschlaff,  necessitate  re- 
action. J's  contention  must  be  regarded  as  a  gross  exaggeration. 
Thus  the  critic  proceeds  in  pointing  out  the  gaps  in  the  progress  of 
the  arguments,  until  it  is  maintained  that  there  is  not  a  shadow  of 
proof  from  the  standpoint  of  the  theoretical  principles  dragged  into 
the  debate. 

Finally,  it  is  shown  with  some  detail,  that  there  are  positive 
grounds  of  proof  against  the  sensualistic  definition.  It  stands  in  di- 
rect contradiction  with  the  facts  of  consciousness.  According  to  the 
theory,  all  organic  sensations  should  be  emotions,  which  is  manifestly 
untrue.  Again,  in  case  the  theory  were  a  real  interpretation,  emotions 
must  be  identical  in  intensity,  quality,  and  time-rate  with  the  sensa- 
tions through  which  they  become  defined.  Nothing  of  these  relations 
are  found.  J.'s  classification  into  '  coarser'  and  '  subtler'  implies,  by 
comparison,  a  common,  but  unnamed,  factor  which  should  have  been 
taken  as  the  defining  mark  of  emotive  states.  The  article  closes  with 
a  recognition  of  certain  justifiable  points  in  the  physiological  doctrine, 
and  a  brief  discussion  of  the  nature  of  apathy  as  an  emotive  state. 

EDWARD  FRANKLIN  BUCHNER. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY. 

A    Study   of  Anger.      By    G.    STANLEY    HALL.      The    American 

Journal  of  Psychology,  July,  1899. 

President  Hall  contributes  a  very  suggestive  inductive  study  of  a 
much  neglected  subject.  A  good  list  of  words  in  the  English  lan- 
guage bearing  on  states  of  anger  is  given  in  the  beginning.  Medical 
literature  and  anthropological  lore  are  ransacked  for  hints  and  sugges- 
tions bearing  on  the  anger  psychosis.  An  empirical,  inductive  study 
is  then  pursued  based  on  the  questionnaire  method.  Cases  of  spon- 
taneous anger  are  cited.  They  may  be  due  to  the  necessities  of 
growth  or  over  lability  of  nerve  cells  or  centers.  The  satisfaction 
and  real  physical  pleasure  that  sometimes  follow  anger  suggest  that 
it  has  its  place  in  normal  development.  A  long  summation  of  petty 
vexations  culminating  in  a  form  of  erethic  inflammation  may  reach  its 
fulminating  stage  without  any  cause  assignable  by  the  subject  or  ob- 
servable by  others.  Opposition  to  the  dogmatic  habits  of  a  rutty 
specialization  is  one  of  the  most  frequent  of  chologenetic  agencies. 
Education  is  defined,  in  part,  as  learning  to  be  most  angry  with  those 
things  that  most  deserve  it  and  maintaining  a  true  perspective  down 
the  scale.  Chologenetic  agencies  are,  of  course,  numerous,  such  as 


PSYCHOLOGICAL  LITERATURE.  66$ 

personal  antipathies  based  on  physical  forms  and  features,  aversion  to 
particular  acts  or  automatisms,  dress,  ornaments,  habits,  thwarting  of 
expectation  or  purpose,  contradiction,  limitations  of  freedom,  pride, 
justice,  etc.  Play  and  mock  fights  often  contain  a  little  repressed 
anger  and  are  good  vents. 

The  physical  manifestations  of  anger  include  the  vaso- motor  distur- 
bances, glandular  secretions,  salivation,  swallowing,  nausea,  spitting, 
disturbances  of  the  respiration,  various  involuntary  movements,  atti- 
tudes and  postures,  biting,  scratching,  kicking,  etc.,  etc.  The  vaso-motor 
disturbances  present  a  very  alluring  field  for  investigation.  The  very 
painful  cardiac  sensations  are  quite  prominent.  Letting  of  blood 
seems  to  modify  considerably  the  strength  of  the  anger  attack.  Men- 
struation is  sometimes  arrested.  Erethism  of  the  breasts  or  sexual 
parts  occurs  at  times.  A  glandular  psychology  is  mooted.  The 
effect  of  anger  upon  the  mammary  secretions  of  women  is  noted. 
Constipation  and  diarrhoea  are  at  times  the  result  of  irascibility.  In 
two  cases  a  rash,  once  said  to  be  all  over  the  body,  follows  every  fit 
of  anger  in  the  child.  Swallowing,  gagging,  etc.,  preliminaries  of  a 
fit  of  anger,  are  referred  to  as  possible  residua  of  the  actions  of  car- 
nivora  as  they  are  about  to  attack  and  slaughter  their  prey.  As  swal- 
lowing is  the  act  of  appropriating  life-giving  food,  so  the  nausea  and 
the  antiperistaltic  movements  of  anger  mean  the  repulsion  or  even 
the  regurgitation  of  food.  By  a  process  of  short  circuiting  and  trans- 
ference of  associated  kindred  meaning  the  same  physical  movements 
accompany  a  similar  mental  action  or  state.  Some  good  hard  common 
sense  remarks  are  made  in  matters  prophylactic  and  jtherapeutical 
which  might  be  taken  to  heart  by  those,  who  by  reason  of  their  senti- 
mentality have  outgrown  their  age. 

The  present  reviewer  cannot  but  suggest  a  few  theoretical  points 
of  view  in  reference  to  the  study  of  anger.  The  emotions  appear  to 
represent  the  inchoate,  uncivilized  elements  of  our  lives.  They  are 
the  Saturnalia  of  the  animal  and  slave  parts  of  our  inherited  constitu- 
tion. As  reversions  they  are  subject  to  some  possible  explanation. 
An  extension  of  Hughlings- Jackson's  nervous  level  theory  may  be  of 
assistance  here.  With  progressive  automatization  of  the  various  levels 
in  ascending  order,  consciousness  normally  accompanies  the  latest 
evolved  levels.  There  is  apparently  maximum  of  consciousness  with 
maximum  of  nervous  hindrance  and  nervous  expenditure  and  a  mini- 
mum of  consciousness  with  a  maximum  of  automatism.  In  the  nor- 
mal intellectual  life  the  lower  levels  with  their  vascular,  glandular  and 
muscular  subordinated  attachments  act  more  or  less  automatically.  At 


666  THE  EMOTIONS. 

one  time  we  can  easily  imagine  the  whole  mental  life  of  our  early 
ancestors  was  almost  wholly  absorbed  in  the  reports  from  these 
4  serving  organs  of  our  nether  world/  To-day  in  unusual  circum- 
stances and  unwonted  contingencies  some  peculiar  stimulus  or  combi- 
nation of  stimuli,  as  for  instance  a  physical  injury,  may  set  that  same 
nether  world  of  the  lower  levels  in  unwonted  excitement  and  the  vas- 
cular, glandular  and  muscular  combinations  of  another  age  may  be  set 
in  motion  and  reports  thereof,  confused  and  tumultuous,  be  sent  to  the 
present  seat  of  consciousness,  the  cortex.  I  can  discover  in  the  rougher 
emotions  at  least  nothing  else  but  disordered  masses  of  sensations  from 
the  central  and  peripheral  organs  of  the  muscular,  glandular  and  vas- 
cular apparatus  accompanied  generally  by  joy  or  depression.  In  the 
emotion  of  fright,  for  instance,  at  an  umbrella  being  opened  at  my 
side,  I  can  discover  nothing  but  a  mass  of  disordered  sensations  arising 
from  the  convulsive  movements  of  the  muscular  mechanism  accom- 
panied by  vaso-motor  sensations  arising  from  cardiac  congestion. 

Sutherland  has  well  shown  the  growth  of  vaso-motor  adaptations 
in  the  presence  of  sudden  emergencies  and  unwonted  stimuli.  Now 
some  of  these  older  adaptations,  some  of  these  older  coordinations  and 
combinations  existing  between  the  nervous  system  and  the  motor 
mechanism  of  the  body  may  lie  relatively  dormant  or  may  act  auto- 
matically and  unconsciously.  In  the  civilized  life  of  to-day  there  may 
be  no  need  for  them  to  report  to  consciousness  excepting  in  cases  of 
emergencies.  Moreover  when  they  do  function  they  may  result  in 
disordered  masses  of  muscular,  glandular  and  vascular  sensations  ow- 
ing to  the  disorder  produced  by  the  superimposition  of  newer  and 
more  modern  coordinations  due  to  the  newer  adaptations  and  to 
changes  made  necessary  by  correlation  of  growth.  Remove  the  later 
coordinations,  that  is,  remove  the  inhibition  and  control  of  the  later 
formed  associations  of  ideas  and  movements  and  the  result  is  the  emo- 
tional phenomena  of  actual  warfare,  the  struggle  in  all  its  forms, 
strikes,  holidays,  disease,  etc. 

With  the  report  of  every  new  investigation  on  the  nature  of  the 
emotions  it  is  becoming  increasingly  clear  that  visceral  functioning 
furnishes  the  organic  algedonic  basis  of  the  personality.  Some  one 
has  said  that  consumptives  generally  die  happy,  but  no  matter  how 
certain  a  man's  convictions  are  of  a  happy  immortality,  he  will  never 
die  a  triumphant  death  with  disease  below  the  diaphragm. 

ARTHUR    ALLIN. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  COLORADO. 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  667 

EXPERIMENTAL. 

Ueber  die  l  Verschmelzung*  von  Empfindungen, besonders  bei Klang- 
eindrucken.  EJNAR  BUCH.  Philos.  Stud.,  XV.,  1-66  ;  183-278. 
These  articles  were  first  published  in  Danish  as  the  habilitation 
address  of  the  author  in  the  University  of  Denmark.  The  first  is 
theoretical,  containing  a  criticism  of  current  theories  of  fusion,  es- 
pecially those  of  Stumpf,  Cornelius,  Helmholtz,  Wundt,  Kiilpe,  and 
James.  He  takes  up  in  order  the  subjects  of  attention,  apprehension 
or  perception  (Auffassung),  analysis,  and  fusion  proper.  The  r61e  of 
interest  in  voluntary  attention  is  illustrated  by  examples  from  genetic 
psychology.  The  perception  of  a  complex  sense  presentation  is  shown 
to  depend  upon  interest  and  knowledge  of  the  fusing  elements.  Then 
interest  and  previous  experience,  as  determining  the  observer's  attitude 
toward  the  presentation,  are  found  to  be  important  factors  in  determin- 
ing the  limits  of  analysis  or  fusion.  His  definition  of  fusion  is  essen- 
tially expressed  in  the  following:  We  speak  of  fusion  when  we  en- 
counter a  number  of  stimuli  which,  in  place  of  each  arousing  its  own 
sensation  as  clearly  and  distinctly  as  if  it  appeared  alone,  produce  a 
combination-presentation  or  presentation-mass  in  which  a  change 
would  take  place  upon  the  elimination  of  one  of  the  stimuli.  The 
avowed  object  of  the  research  is  to  determine  by  experiment  whether 
this  fusion  is  a  mental  process  by  itself  or  is  simply  the  general  desig- 
nation for  known  influences  upon  perception. 

The  second  article  contains  the  report  of  the  experiments.  The 
principal  apparatus  consisted  of  a  series  of  twenty-three  organ  pipes 
with  a  manometric  contrivance  by  means  of  which  the  pipes  could 
be  energized  with  equal  force.  A  variety  of  combinations  of  tones 
were  produced  by  sounding  the  pipes  simultaneously  in  pairs.  The 
principal  tests  were  made  upon  nine  observers  who  were  simply  re- 
quired to  state  whether  they  heard  one  or  two  tones.  The  ob- 
servers fall  into  two  classes  according  to  the  attitude  they  take  toward 
the  presentation.  One  class  of  observers  attempt  to  analyze  the  tone 
and  consider  failure  to  perform  the  analysis  a  criterion  of  fusion. 
The  other  observers  seem  to  judge  merely  by  the  general  effect.  This 
difference  in  method  brings  about  radical  differences  in  the  results, 
each  class  however,  presenting  some  common  characteristics.  Tones 
at  some  intervals  apart  have  a  greater  tendency  to  fuse  than  at  other 
intervals.  The  intervals  may  be  arranged  in  a  series  according  to  the 
number  of  times  the  respective  tones  fused  in  these  experiments.  The 
author  shows  by  an  elaborate  analysis  of  the  results  that  these  differ- 


668  EXPERIMENTAL. 

ences  may  be  accounted  for  by  the  variation  of  such  known  factors  as 
consonance,  beats  between  partials,  familiarity  with  certain  intervals, 
etc.,  and  therefore  concludes  that  there  is  no  ground  for  assuming  the 
existence  of  degrees  of  fusion  aside  from  the  variation  in  such  factors. 
In  order  to  check  the  results,  he  performed  the  same  experiments  us- 
ing an  Appunn  'Tonmesser,'  and  obtained  results  that  virtually  agreed 
with  those  obtained  with  the  pipes.  Notwithstanding  the  keen  criti- 
cism and  the  careful  and  elaborate  experiments.,  the  author  does  not  ar- 
rive at  anything  essentially  new,  and  the  contribution  has  its  chief  value 
in  the  exposition  of  his  own  theory  of  fusion. 

C.  E.  SEASHORE. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  IOWA. 


Neue  Untersuchungen  iiber  die  Zeitverhaltniss  der  Apperception 
einfacher  Sinneseindriicke  am  Complicationspendel.  CHR.  D. 
PFLAUM.  Philos.  Stud.,  XV.,  139-148. 

This  is  a  repetition  of  Wundt's  experiments  to  determine  the  di- 
rection and  extent  of  disparity  in  time  in  the  perception  of  two  simul- 
taneous impressions  through  different  senses.  The  '  Complications- 
pendel' described  in  Wundt's  Physiological  Psychology  is  employed. 
A  pendulum  moves  a  pointer  over  a  circular  scale  and  rings  a  gong  as 
the  pointer  passes  any  desired  number.  The  observer  is  required  to 
state  at  what  number  on  the  scale  the  pointer  was  when  the  sound  oc- 
curred. The  author  finds  that  the  amount  and  direction  of  the  dis- 
placement vary  with  different  individuals  and  depend  upon  the  speed 
of  the  pointer.  He  thus  reconciles  the  contradictory  results  previously 
obtained  by  Wundt  and  von  Tchisch  by  showing  that  there  are  indi- 
vidual differences  just  as  in  the  personal  equation  in  the  eye  and  ear 
method  of  astronomers.  The  maximum  difference  between  individ- 
uals in  this  test  is  about  o.oi  sec.  which  is  much  less  than  the  differ- 
ences found  in  the  corresponding  personal  equations  of  different  as- 
tronomers. 

C.   E.  SEASHORE. 


Die  Prdcision  der  Blickbewegung  und  der  Localisation  an  der 
Netzhautperipherie.  CHAS.  B.  MORREY.  Ztsch.  f.  Psych,  u. 
Physiol.  der  Sinnesorgane.  XX.,  317-325. 

The  author  measures  the  error  in  the  eye -movement,  by  which  we 
seek  to  fixate  a  momentary  peripheral  stimulus,  by  the  discrepancy 
between  the  actual  position  of  an  electric  spark  and  the  position  of  a 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  669 

pointer,  placed  by  the  observer  at  that  point  of  a  dimly  lighted  back- 
ground, where  the  spark  appeared  to  be. 

After  correcting  for  inaccuracy  in  placing  the  pointer,  the  error 
of  movement  is  found  to  increase  directly  with  the  distance  of -the  pe- 
ripheral stimulus  from  the  primary  point  of  regard,  and  to  consist  of  a 
constant  tendency  to  underestimate  the  distance. 

The  error  in  peripheral  localization  is  assumed  to  be  identical  with 
the  error  in  the  eye-movement. 

The  results  published  are  based  upon  single  experiments,  each  for 
more  than  700  different  positions  of  the  peripheral  stimulus.  No 
measurements  are  made  for  movements  of  less  than  8°.  The  ap- 
parent error  in  the  method  of  designating  the  terminus  of  the  eye- 
movement  averages  half  the  total  error,  while  for  8°  the  two  are  equal. 
These  facts  undoubtedly  account  for  the  extreme  irregularity  of  the 
author's  curves. 

The  problem  is  interesting  and  important,  but  the  method  used  is 
full  of  complications  and  probably  incapable  of  giving  accurate  re- 
sults. It  is  doubtful  if  anything  will  be  entirely  successful,  except 
some  means  of  photographic  registration. 

RAYMOND  DODGE. 

WESLEYAN  UNIVERSITY. 


Die  Form  des  Himmelsgewolbes  und  das  Grosser-Erscheinen  der 

Gestirne  am  Horizont.    W.  VON  ZEHENDER.     Zeitsch.  f .  Psych. 

und  Phys.     XX.,  pp.  353-357. 

This  paper  is  supplementary  to  the  earlier  article  which  has  already 
been  criticized  by  the  present  reviewer  in  the  September  number  of  the 
PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  page  547.  The  same  errors  are  committed 
here  as  in  the  first  aricle.  The  author  speaks  of  '  die  Volkmanrische 
scheinbare  Divergenz  zweier  -vertical  stehender  Parallellinien ' 
(p.  356),  and  states  on  the  next  page: — '  nur  solcJie  Verticallinien 
paralell  erscheinen,  die  in  Wirklichkeit  nicht  ganz  genau  parallel 
sind,  sondern  *  *  *  nach  oben  ein  wenig  convergiren.'  As  has 
been  pointed  out  these  statements  are  the  exact  reverse  of  the  truth. 

The  other  part  of  the  paper  is  devoted  to  an  effort  to  show  that  the 
apparent  flatness  of  the  heavens  is  a  result  of  '  Tradition '  rather  than 
of  connate  ideas  or  of  experience.  Finally,  the  apparent  variation  of 
the  size  of  the  sun  and  moon  is  explained  by  contrast  with  the  ap- 
parent angular  extension  of  the  sky  which  is  overestimated  at  the 
zenith  and  underestimated  at  the  horizon  (again  an  incorrect  state- 
ment) ,  although  no  reason  is  given  why  the  sun  and  moon  should  not 


670  PHIL  OS  OPHICAL. 

suffer  exactly  the  same  sort  of  false  estimation   as  the  sky  in  these 
two  positions. 

CHARLES  H.   JUDD. 
NEW  YORK  UNIVERSITY, 

SCHOOL  OF  PEDAGOGY. 


PHILOSOPHICAL. 

Through  Nature  to    God.     JOHN  FISKE.     Boston  and  New  York, 

Houghton,  Mifflin  &    Co.,   1899.      i6mo,  pp.  xv  -f  195.     Price, 

$1.00. 

Mr.  Fiske's  latest  book  constitutes  the  third  part  of  the  trilogy 
initiated  in  'Man's  Destiny  in  the  Light  of  his  Origin*  (1884),  and 
continued  in  '  The  Idea  of  God  as  affected  by  Modern  Knowledge ' 
(1885).  The  earliest  work,  as  it  may  be  apposite  to  recall,  offers  a 
summary  account  of  evolution  designed  specially  to  lead  up  to  an 
avowal  of  belief  in  the  soul's  immortality,  not  as  a  provable  fact,  but 
as  an  essential  implication  of  '  the'  reasonableness  of  the  universe/ 
The  theistic  continuation,  still  basing  upon  evolution,  contains  a  pro- 
fession of  faith  to  the  effect  that  "  the  Infinite  Power  of  which  the  uni- 
verse is  the  multiform  manifestation  is  psychical,  although  it  is  impos- 
sible to  ascribe  to  Him  any  of  the  limited  psychical  attributes  which 
we  know,  or  to  argue  from  the  ways  of  man  to  the  ways  of  God." 
The  last  little  monograph  proceeds  with  the  discussion  of  problems  in 
Philosophy  of  Religion,  and  contains  illuminating  chapters  on  (i) 
The  Mystery  of  Evil;  (2)  The  Cosmic  Roots  of  Love  and  Self-Sacri- 
fice; (3)  The  Everlasting  Reality  of  Religion. 

The  first  is  mainly  remarkable  for  the  outspoken  way  in  which  it 
accepts  the  conclusion  so  paradoxically  put  by  a  younger  American 
thinker — that  God  is  the  Devil.  In  other  words,  God  must  be  viewed 
as  the  author  of  evil,  as  well  as  of  what  we  call  good ;  and  the  problem 
is  to  throw  such  light  upon  this  unavoidable  inference  as  modern  in- 
vestigation may  bestow.  The  second  repeats,  with  great  force  and 
freshness,  Mr.  Fiske's  well-known  doctrine  as  to  the  part  played  in 
the  evolving  series  by  the  lengthened  infancy  of  the  human  species  of 
ape,  and  concludes  with  an  earnest,  though  dogmatic  statement,  that 
the  universe  exists  for  moral  ends,  if  any  at  all.  The  third  defends 
the  reasonableness  of  the  three  chief  conceptions  incident  to  all  re- 
ligion— the  quasi-Human  God;  the  Undying  Human  Soul,  and  the 
value,  as  a  scientific  fact  (that  is,  as  a  cause  in  the  process  of  evolu- 
tion), of  the  postulate  of  the  Ethical  Significance  of  the  Unseen  World. 
Needless  to  say,  the  argument  is  presented  with  all  the  charm  that 


PSYCHOLOGICAL   LITERATURE.  671 

this  author  has  accustomed  us  to  look  for ;  and,  although  exceedingly 
brief,  and  therefore  wearing  a  certain  air  of  dogmatism,  anyone  who 
reads  between  the  lines  can  note  the  wonderful  range  of  knowledge  it 
presupposes.  It  seems  to  me  that,  without  doubt,  similar,  if  not 
identical,  ideas  will  be  enunciated  by  some  expert  in  this  subject, 
when  the  new  systematic  philosophy  of  religion,  that  so  many  await, 
makes  its  appearance. 

I  have  but  two  criticisms  to  pass.  In  the  hands  of  those  who 
know,  books  of  this  type  can  be  productive  of  nothing  but  good.  But, 
most  unfortunately,  in  the  hands  of  theological  reactionaries,  whose 
unconscious  hypocrisy  is  their  besetting  sin,  a  sin  that  takes  form  in  a 
persistent  defence  of  that  for  which  there  is  no  evidence,  I  feel  sure 
that  Mr.  Fiske's  outspoken  opinions  will  work  widespread  harm.  It 
is,  possibly,  a  pity,  too,  that  he  has  almost  repeated  the  title  of  Dr. 
Edwin  A.  Abbott's  striking  work  (Macmillari,  1877). 

R.  M.  WENLEY. 
UNIVERSITY  OF  MICHIGAN. 

The  seventeenth  volume  of  the  Bibliotheque  Sociologique  Interna- 
tionale is  Des  Religious  Comparees  au  Point  de  Vue  Sociologique, 
by  M.  Raoul  de  la  Grasserie,  who  is  a  judge  at  Rennes.  The  subject 
is  one  of  the  first  order  of  importance,  but  M.  de  la  Grasserie  is  evi- 
dently too  much  of  an  amateur  in  the  field  of  comparative  religion 
for  his  conclusions  to  have  much  weight.  His  chief  authority  is  a 
certain  M.  de  Millone  who  is  not  known  to  fame  on  this  side  of  the 
Atlantic  at  least.  '  Cosmosociology '  is  the  name  that  the  author  would 
give  to  the  '  society  of  God  and  man '  which  is  religion ;  he  discusses 
also  the  '  inter-divine  society '-  of  the  gods  themselves  on  the  lines  of  the 
Iliad;  mortuary  religion  is  not  neglected;  and  the  'organic  nature* 
of  religion  is  brought  to  the  front.  The  chief  value  of  M.  de  la  Gras- 
serie's  work  is  in  occasional  classifications  like  that  of  *  religious  di- 
seases '  (pp.  194  +)  and  such  occasional  touches  as  calling  the  monks 
4  the  specialists  of  Christianity.'  As  a  treatment  of  religion  as  a  social 
force,  the  book  is  quite  inadequate. — Paris,  V.  Giard  and  E.  Briere. 

N.  P.  GILMAN. 

MEADVILLE,  PA. 

Spinoza  und  Schopenhauer.     Von  Dr.  SAMUEL  RAPPAPORT.     Ber- 
lin, R.  Gaertners  Verlagsbuchhandlung.      1899. 
This  work  is  not,  as  its  title  might  suggest,  merely  a  comparative 
study  of  the  two  systems,  but  an  attempt  to  determine  the  character 
and  extent  of  the  influence  of  Spinoza  upon  Schopenhauer. 


672  NEW  BOOKS. 

It  is  a  recognized  fact  that  Schopenhauer,  like  Schelling,  Hegel, 
Schleiermacher  and  all  of  the  important  thinkers  of  the  time,  was  af- 
fected by  the  pantheist.  But  the  influence  might  be  direct  or  indirect 
— either  the  result  of  an  immediate  acquaintance  with  the  works  of 
the  pantheist  or  merely  a  product  of  the  Spinozistical  ideas  which 
were  '  in  the  air '  during  that  period.  Our  author  attempts  the  task, 
which  is  not  as  simple  as  it  might  seem  to  be,  of  showing  that 
Schopenhauer  was  not  only  early  subject  to  a  distinct  mediate  influence 
from  Spinoza  but  actually  acquired  a  first-hand  knowledge  of  his 
works  before  and  during  the  formation  of  his  (Schopenhauer's)  sys- 
tem. This  proof  is  made  valuable,  and  for  that  matter  possible,  by 
reference  to  the  still  unpublished  MSS.  of  the  pessimist. 

The  writer  also  endeavors,  in  an  exhaustive  manner,  to  determine 
Schopenhauer's  opinion  of  the  doctrines  and  personality  of  Spinoza. 

The  work  seems  to  be  conscientious  and  thorough,  and  as  a  detail 
out  of  the  history  of  philosophy  it  is  valuable.  However,  it  is  of  in- 
terest only  to  the  technical  student. 

F.  KENNEDY. 


NEW    BOOKS. 

A  Manual  of  Psychology.  G.  F.  STOUT.  University  Correspond- 
ence College  Press.  London,  W.  B.  Clive ;  New  York,  Hinds  & 
Noble.  1899.  Pp.  xvi  -f  643. 

History  of  Ancient  Philosophy.  W.  WINDELBAND.  Authorized 
Translator,*  H.  E.  Cushman.  New  York,  Charles  Scribner's 
Sons.  1899.  Pp.  xv  +  393«  $2.00. 

The  Evolution  of  General  Ideas.  TH.  RIBOT.  Authorized  trans- 
lation by  Frances  A.  Welby.  Chicago,  The  Open  Court  Pub- 
lishing Co. ;  London,  Kegan  Paul,  Trench,  Triibner  &  Co.,  Ltd. 
1899.  Pp.  xi  +  23i.  $2.25. 

Social  Laws,  an  Outline  of  Sociology.  G.  TARDE.  Translated  by 
Howard  C.  Warren.  New  York  and  London,  The  Macmillan 
Company.  1899.  Pp.  xi  +  213.  $1.25. 

Discourse  on  Method.  Rene  Descartes ;  Veitch's  Translation.  Chi- 
cago, Open  Court  Publishing  Co.  1899.  Pp.  vi  -f  87. 


NOTES.  673 

NOTES. 

WE  regret  to  record  the  death  of  the  well-known  French  philoso- 
pher, M.  Paul  Janet,  member  of  the  Paris  Academy  of  Political 
Science  and  formerly  professor  at  the  Sorbonne. 

A.  KIRSCHMANN,  Ph.D.,  lecturer  in  philosophy  at  the  University 
of  Toronto  since  1894,  has  been  appointed  prof  essor  of  philosophy  and 
director  of  the  psychological  laboratory. 

DR.  CHARLES  G.  SHAW  has  been  appointed  to  the  position  in  the 
department  of  philosophy  in  New  York  University  rnade  vacant  by 
the  resignation  of  Dr.  J.  H.  McCracken,  to  accept  the  Presidency  of 
Westminster  College,  at  Fulton,  Mo. 

The  Regents  of  the  University  of  Texas  have  provided  a  psycho- 
logical laboratory  which  has  been  placed  under  the  charge  of  Professor 
Caswell  Ellis,  of  the  department  of  pedagogy. 

MR.  CLARK  WISSLER,  of  the  Ohio  State  University,  has  been  ap- 
pointed Assistant  in  Psychology  in  Columbia  University. 

S.  I.  FRANZ,  Ph.D.  (Columbia),  and  G.  V.  N.  Dearborn,  M.D., 
Ph.D.  (Columbia),  have  been  appointed  Assistants  in  Physiology  in 
the  Harvard  Medical  School. 

R.  S.  WOODWORTH,  Ph.D.  (Columbia),  has  been  appointed  As- 
sistant in  Physiology  in  University  and  Bellevue  Hospital  and  Medical 
College. 

PROFESSOR  W.  H.  SQUIRES,  who  holds  the  chair  of  psychology 
and  pedagogics  in  Hamilton  College  has  been  given  a  two  years'  leave 
of  absence,  which  he  will  spend  in  study  in  Germany.  W.  B.  Elkin, 
Ph.D.  (Cornell),  Teachers  College,  Columbia  University,  has  been 
appointed  acting  professor. 

DAVID  R.  MAJOR,  Ph.D.  (Cornell),  Teachers  College,  Columbia 
University,  has  been  appointed  Acting  Professor  of  Pedagogy  in  the 
University  of  Nebraska,  Professor  G.  W.  A.  Luckey,  who  holds  the 
Chair  of  Pedagogy,  having  been  given  leave  of  absence  to  carry  on  ad- 
vanced work  at  Columbia  University. 

PROFESSOR  G.  S.  FULLERTON  has  returned  to  the  University  of 
Pennsylvania  after  a  year's  absence  abroad. 

PROFESSOR  J.  MARK  BALDWIN  is  at  present  at  Oxford  (3  Museum 
Road),  where  he  is  revising  for  the  press  the  MS.  of  his  Dictionary 
of  Philosophy  and  Psychology.  Professor  A.  C.  Armstrong,  Jr.,  is 
also  at  Oxford,  and  Professor  G.  H.  Howison  is  expected  there. 
Professor  William  James  may  also  spend  part  of  the  winter  at  Oxford. 


674  NOTES. 

DR.  JAMES  H.  LEUBA,  of  Bryn  Mawr  College,  has  compiled  a 
card  catalogue  of  psychology,  containing  about  10,000  titles.  The 
catalogue  consists  of  the  contents  of  periodicals  from  1860-1899.  The 
periodicals  selected  are  not  confined  to  those  devoted  to  psychology, 
but  include  many  -journals  such  as  Nature,  The  American  Journal 
of  Science,  etc.,  in  which  psychological  articles  might  be  readily 
overlooked.  There  are  indeed  many  journals  omitted,  such  as  the 
German  physiological  archives,  but  it  is  hoped  that  these  may  be  in- 
dexed at  some  future  time.  Dr.  Leuba  offers  to  supply  mimeo- 
graphed copies  of  the  catalogue  on  standard  cards  at  a  price  not  to 
exceed  $50.00. 


INDEX   OF   SUBJECTS. 


Absolute,  The,  228 
After-images,  173,  420,  449,  451,  653 
Animal  Intelligence,  157,  262,  412 
Animals,  Mental  Evolution  in,  568 
l'Anne"e  sociologique,  568 
Apprehension,  Psychology  of,  229,  428 
1'Art  et  le  re"el,  no 
Association  of  Ideas,  320 
I'Asymetrie  sensorielle,  562 
Attention,  166 
Automatic  Reactions,  376 
Automatism,    Social    and    Imitation 
Theory,  440 

Belief  and  Will,  150 
Breathing,  Rates  of,   and  Mental  Ac- 
tivity, 164 

Cannabis  Indica,  153 

Child  Study,  316,  440 

Citizenship  and  Salvation,  312 

Color,  Physiology  and  Psychology  of, 

162  ;  Illusion,  173 
Conduct  and  the  Weather,  539 
Consciousness  and  Organic  Processes, 

32 
Currents  of  High  Frequency,  165 

Dynamics  of  Personal  Religion,  484 

Education ,  Cross,  165 :  Self,  564  ;  of 
Will,  566 

Emotions,  The,  540,  660 

Ether,  Experience  under,  104 

Ethical,  Scepticism  and  Psychology, 
171 ;  System  of  Adam  Smith,  556 

Ethics,  Visual  Instruction  in,  327 

Ethology,  563,  649 

Eye,  Reaction-time  of,  477 ;  Move- 
ment, 667 

Fatigue,  203 ;  and  Movement,  159 ; 
Griesbach  Method  of  determining, 

573>  599 
Fluctuation  of  Sensations,  326 

Genetic  Determination  of  the  Self,  172 
God,  Conception  of,  in 
Good  and  Evil,  Studies  of,  in. 

Hallucinations,  407 
Hearing,  667 

Heat  and  Cold  Spots,  561 
History  and  Psychology,  I,  148 


Illusions,  172,  173,  241,  543,  554 
Immortality,  Human,  424 
Inhibition,  202 
Instinct,  and  Reason,  156,  517  ;  Moral, 

216 

Instincts  of  Solitary  Wasps,  219 
Instinctive  Reactions  of  Young  Chicks, 

282 
Invention,  336 

Joy,  Emotion  of,  540 
Judgment,  440 

Kant  and  Helmholtz,  554 
Knowledge,  Theory  of,  432 

Laboratory  Studies,  Chicago,  32  ;  Yale, 
196  ;  Clark,  333  ;  Harvard,  376  ;  Iowa, 

549 

Light-Sense,  Professor  Muller's  The- 
ory of  the,  70 

Logic,  Creighton's,  222 

Magic,  564 

Memory,  Motor,  166 ;  for  Absolute 
Pitch,  514 

Memories,  Individual,  446 

Mental,  Life,  Physiological  Basis  of, 
159  ;  Disorders,  Topical  Basis  of, 
339;  Instability,  451  ;  Evolution  in 
Animals,  568 

Method,  Psychological,  191 ;  Deduc- 
tive, 444  " 

Mind  and  Body,  Relation  of,  232 

Mill,  J.  S.,  Correspondence  of,  440 

Modesty,  Evolution  of/  134 

Moral  Instinct,  216 

Motion,  Voluntary,  153 

Motor  Impulse  or  Motor  Memory,  166 

Movement,  and  Fatigue,  159  ;  Volun- 
tary, 275 

Muscular,  and  Mental  Activity,  200  ; 
Contractions,  Reinforcement  of,  201 

Mystic  Knowledge,  426 

Mysticism,  292,  408 

Nature,  Through  to  God,  Fiske,  670 
Nervous  and  Mental  Diseases,  Church 

and  Peterson,  659 
Neural,  Dynamics,  340 ;  Unit,  340 
Neurology  and  Pathology,  654 
Neuron,  Energy,  341  ;  Activity  of  the, 

453 


676 


INDEX  OF  SUBJECTS. 


Neuroses  et  Idees  Fixes,  (Janet's)  655 

Odors  and  Tastes,  160 
Organic  Processes  and  Consciousness, 
32 

Pacemaking,  336 

Pain,  Measurements  of,  168 

Pathology  and  Neurology,  654 

Perception,  Time  of,  668 

Personality,  Human,  310 

Philosophy,  Problems  of,  113 

Philosophical,  670 

Physiological  Basis  of    Mental  Life, 

159 

Pitch,  Memory  for,  514 

Play,  Theories  of,  86 

Plethysmographic  Methods,  195 

Psychological,  Association,  American, 
146 ;  Proposed  Changes  in,  237 ; 
Classification,  158 ;  Method,  191 

Psychology  of,  and  History,  I,  148  ; 
Hindrances  to  the  Progress,  in  Amer- 
ica, 121,  154;  Comparative,  157, 
262,  282  ;  of  Color,  162  ;  of  Speech, 
164,  319;  and  Ethical  Scepticism, 
170  ;  Material  versus  Dynamic,  180  ; 
Postulates  of  a  Structural,  187  ;  of 
Rhythm,  211 ;  of  Peoples,  305  ;  Con- 
temporary, 507,  529  ;  of  Invention, 
336 ;  Individual,  113,  and  Collective, 
323,  and  Life,  410;  of  Apprehen- 
sion, 229,  428 ;  and  the  Teacher, 
536,  548,  559 ;  Ethological,  563,  649 

Psychoses,  Dendro-,  332  ;  Hydro-,  333 

Reaction-time  of  the  Bye,  477 

Reactions,  Automatic,  3-76 

Reason,  and  Instinct,  156,  517  ;  Weir's 
Dawn  of,  327 

Recognition,  167  ;  under,  Objective  Re- 
versal, 395 

Religion,  Theory  of,  298  ;  Dynamics  of 
Personal,  484 ;  Comparative,  671 

Reproduction,  Accuracy  of,  447 


Revenge,  221 
Rhythm,  211 

Salvation  and  Citizenship,  312 
Schopenhauer  and  Spinoza,  671 
Science,  Groundwork  of,  107 
Sensation,  506 

Sensations,  Fluctuations  of,  326 
Sensational  Attributes  and  Sensation, 

651 
Sense,  Epithets,  332  ;  Type,  Tests  for, 

174 
Sensory  Functions  of  the  Motor  Cortex 

Cerebri,  338 

Sentiments,  I'dducation  des,  443 
Smell,  557 

Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations,  171 
Sociology,  533 
Soul-substance,  458,  606 
Speech,  Psychology  of,  164,  319 
Spinoza  and  Schopenhauer,  671 
Spiritual  Content  of  Life,  92 
Spirituality,  554 
Subconscious  Homicide  and  Suicide, 

199 

Taste,  446  ;  and  Odors,  160 

Teacher  and  Psychology,  536,  543, 519 

Telegraphic  Language,  346 

Terminology,  444 

Tests,  Physical  and  Mental,  174 

Time,  Sense,  208  ;  Causality  and  Space, 

443  ;  of  Perception,  68 
Truth  and  Error,  Powell's,  423 

Unconscious,  Doctrine  of  the,  445 

Vision,  117,  212,  329,  555 
Voluntary    Movement,  275  ;  Control, 
Growth  of,  639 

Weather  and  Conduct,  539 
Will,  and  Belief,  150 ;  Theory  of,  169, 
Education  of  the,  225,  566. 


INDEX   OF    NAMES. 


Names  of  contributors  are  printed  in  SMALL  CAPITALS,  and  the  page  numbers  of  the  con 
tributions  in  Full  Face  Type.  In  the  case  of  authors  reviewed  the  page  numbers  are  in  Italics 
and  in  case  of  mention  in  the  notes  they  are  in  Roman  type. 


Adams,  B.,  239 
ALLIN,  A.,  216,  443,  664 
ANGELL,  J-  R.,  32,  195 
ARMSTRONG,  JR.,  A.  C.,  107,  75^,  571, 

673 

BAILEY,  Jr.,  T.  P.,  563,  649 
BAKEWELL,  C.  M.,  312 
BALDWIN,  J.  M.,  172,  568,  572, 673 
Bancroft,  C.  P.,  199 
BARNITZ,  D.  P.,  451 
Baumann,  J.,5<5<5 
Bethe,  A,,  340 
Binet,  A.,  195 

BLISS,  C.  B.,  236,  322,  410, 446,  563, 649 
Blondeau,  C.,  228 
Bloom,  S.,  329 
Boas,  F.,  119 
Bolton,  F.  B.,JJJ 
Bosanquet,  B.,  440 
Bourdon,  B.,  795 

BREESE,  B.  B.,  202 

Bridel,  L.,  571 

BRYAN,  W.  L.,  346 

Buch,  B.,  667 

BUCHNER,   B.   F.,   428,  432,  440,  662 

CALDWELL,  W.,  757,  777,  187, 191, 332 
CALKINS,  M.  W.,  158,   443,   449,   45*, 

506,  651 

Cantoni,  C.,  240 

CATTELL,  J.  McK.,  159, 174,  554 
Church,  H.,  659 
Cleghorn,  A.,  201 
Colgrove,  F.  W.,  446 
COE,  G.  A.,  484 
Cordes,  G.,  5^ 
Creighton,  J.  B.,  222 
Cron,  I/.,  229 
Curtis,  H.  S.,  202 

Davenport,  C.  B.,  571 

DEARBORN,  G.  V.  N.,  153,  167,  199, 

338,  395,  453,  540,  555,  568,  651 
DA  VIES,  H.,  648 
DEXTER,  B.  G.,  539 
DODGE,  R.,  344,  477,  669 
Duprat,  G.  L.,  451 
Durkheim,  B-,  568 

Bbhardt,  K.,  ^77 
Binthoven,  B.,5£? 


Blkin,  W.  B.,  673] 
BLLIS,  H.,  134 
Bucken,  R.,  92 
Bverett,  W.  G.,  170 

Fairchild,  B.  M. ,  326 

Ferrari,  G.  C.,  77j 

Fiske,  J.  H.,  670 

FRANKLIN,  C.  I/.,  70,  117,  173,   212, 

329,  448 

FRANZ,  S.  I.,  446,  561,  653,  673 
Fullerton,  G.  S.,  673 

Gamble,  B.  A.  M.,  557 
GARDINER,  H.  N.,  228,  310,  660 
Garten,  S.,  329 
Gerhardt,  C.  J.,  344 
GERMANN,  G.  B.,  599 
Giddings,  F.  H.,5jj 
GILLETTE,  J.  M.,  420 
GILMAN,  N.  P.,  67 1 
Goldschmidt,  I/.,  554 
Grasserie,  R  de  la,  671 
Greef,  R.,  212 
Griesbach,  J7j,  599 
GRIFFIN,  B.  H.,  536 
Groos,  K.,  86 
Grote,  N.,  571 
Guicciardi,  G.,  77j 
Gutzmann,  H.,  J77 

Haeckel,  239 
Hall,  G.  S.,  664 
Hallion,  M.  L.,  239 
Hammond,  Wm.  A.,  169 
Hartenberg,  P.,  660 
HARTER,  N.,  346 
HERRICK,  C.  L,.,  180 

HlBBIN,  J.  G.,  750,  III,  77J,  222,  440 

Herdman,  W.  J.,  340 
Bering,  B.,  453 
Heymans,  G.,  232 
HYSLOP,  J.  H.,  113,  292,  409 
HODGE,  C.  W.,  424 
Hodge,  F.  W.,  119 
Hogan,  L.  B-,J/6 
Howison,  G.  H.,  777,  673 
Hopkins,  A.  F.,  554 
Home,  P.  H.,  456 
Hylan,  J.  P.,  166 

James,  W.,  424,  536,  572,  673 


6y8 


INDEX  OF  NAMES. 


Janet,  P.,  120,  571,  654 
Janet,  Paul,  673 
JONES,  B.  C.,  229 
JONES,  J.  W.  L.,  556 
JUDD,    C.    H.,   172,     208,     241,   348, 
669 

Keene,  A.  H.,  456 

Kemsies,  F.,  203,  571 

KENNEDY,  F.,  92,  456,  554,  671 

Kiesow,  F.,446,  567 

Kirchoff,  339 

KIRKPATRICK,   B.  A.,    104,  153,  275, 

327 

Kirschmann,  A.,  673 
Kraepelin,  229,  203 

LADD,  G.T.,  121, 134, 173,  639 

LEUBA,  J.  H.,  573,  674 

L£vy,  P.  B.,  225 

LAY,  W.,  332 

Lloyd,  A.  H.,  312 

Le  Bon,  G.,  303 

lye  Conte,  J.,  777 

Letourneau,  C.,  568 

Lipps,  T.,  543 

Lough,  J.  B.,  164 

Lovejoy,  A.  B.,  456 

MACDOUGAU,,   R,,  164,  168,  191,  203, 

3J7,  320,  564 
McGilvary,  B.  B.,  240 
Mackintosh,  R.,  456 
Major,  D.  R.,  673 
Marbe,  K.,  215 
Marshall,  H.  R.,  756,  298,  517 
Martius,  239 
Mendel,  571 
Mercier,  D.,  307 
Meyer,  A.,  120 
Mezes,  S.  B.,  in 
Mill,  J.  S.,  440 
MiijyS,  W.,  757,  262,  412 
Mivart,  St.  G.,  707 
MILLER,  D.  S.,  154,  232,  423,  456 
MONTAGUE,  W.  P.,  458,  572,  606 
Moore,  G.  B-,  441 
MOORE,  K.  C.,  316 
Morgan,  C.  L.,  559 
Morrey,  C.  B.,  668 
Muir,  B.,  55^ 
Miiller,  G.  B-,  70 
Miiller,  R.,  ^75 

MUNSTERBERG,  H.,  I,    148,    159,  292, 
408,  410 

NEWBOLD,  W.  R.,  225 
ORMOND,  A.  T.,  426 

Pappenheim,  K.,  448 
Patrick,  G.  T.  W.,  549,  160 
Patten,  W.,  555 


Paulhan,  F.,  336 
i,  B.  W., 
Peres,  J. ,  770 


Peckham, 


and  G.  W.,  219 


Peterson,  P.,  659 
Piat,  C.,  120,  310 
Pflaum,  C.  D.,  668 
Pillon,  F.,  120 
Powell,  J.  W.,^j 

Quantz,J.  O.,JJ2 

Ramon  y  Cajal,  212 
Rand,  B.,  344 
Rappaport,  S.,  671 
Recejac,  E.,  426 
Rehmke,  J.,  232 
Riehl,  239 
Royce,  J.,  ///,  239 
Robinson,  W.  B.  55^ 

Samojloff,  A.,  451 
Sanford,  B.  C.,  572 
Schaefer,  E.  A.,  338 
Schirmer,  O.,  117 
Schoute,  F.,  448 
Schumann,  F.,  208 
Scripture,  E.  W.,  162,  164, 196 
Seailles,  239 

SEASHORE,  C.  E.,  336,  667, 
Sergi,  G.,  445 
Seyfert,  R.,  44-7 
Shaw,  C.  G.,  673 
Sidis,  B.,  341 
SLOSSEN,  B.  B.,  407 
SOLOMONS,  L-  M.,  376 
Squires,  W.  H.,  673 
STANLEY,  H.  M.,  86,  219,  298 
STARR,  M.  A.,  654 
Stern,  L-  W.,  428 
Stout,  G.  F.,  239 
STRATTON,  G.  M.,  557,  559 
Striimpel,  L-,  456 
Stumpf,  C.,  662 
Sutherland,  A.,  216 
Swift,  J.,  44^ 
Tarde,  119 

TAWNEY,  G.  A.,  239,  305,  5*7 
Thomas,  P.  F.,  443 
Turner,  J.,  344 
THOMPSON,  H.  B.,  32 
THORNDIKE,  B.,  282,  344,  412 
Titchener,  B-  B.,  187,  344 
TOSTI,  G.,  529 
Triplett,  N.,  336 
TuFTS,  J.  H.,  533 
URBAN,  W.  M.,   "o,  336 

Vailati,  G.,  444 
Van  Biervliet,  J.  J.,  562 
Van  Gieson,  I.,  341 
Vaschide,  N.,  795,  660 
Villa,  G.,  5^9 


INDEX  OF  NAMES.  679 

Wagner,  L.,  203  Westermarck,  B.,  221 

Ward,  J.,  239    "  Wissler,  C.,  673 

WARREN,  H.   C.,  113,  119,    ^74,  444,      Witasek,  543 

562  WOODWORTH,  R.  S.,  307,  673 

WASHBURN,  M.  F.,  173,  449,  653  Worms,  R.,  322 
Weinmann,  R.,  232 

Weir,  J.,  327  Zehender,  W.  v.,  343 ',  669 

Welch,  J.  C.,  200  Ziehen,  T.,  320,  432 

,  R.  M.,  670  Zimmermann,  R.,  239 


BINDING  SECT 


BF  Psychological  Review 

1 

17 
v.6 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 

UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY