Skip to main content

Full text of "Psychological review"

See other formats


> 

Vol.  XXIV,  No.  6  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW  PUBLICATIONS  November,  1917 

Psychological  Review 

EDITED  BY 

HOWARD  C.  WARREN,    PRINCETON   UNIVERSITY 
JOHN  B.  WATSON,  JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY  (J.ofExp.  Psychol.) 
JAMLS  R.  ANGELL,  UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO  (Monographs} 

SHEPHERD  I.  FRANZ,  GOVT.  HOSP.  FOR  INSANE  (Bulletin)  AND 
MADISON  BENTLEY,  UNIVERSITY  OF  ILLINOIS  (Index) 

ADVISORY  EDITORS 

R.  P.  ANGIER,  YALE  UNIVERSITY;  MARY  W.  CALKINS,  WELLESLEY  COLLEGE  ;  H.  N. 
GARDINER,  SMITH  COLLEGE;  JOSEPH  JASTROW,  UNIVERSITY  OF  WISCONSIN;  C.  H. 
JUDD,  UNIVERSITY  OF  CHICAGO  ;  ADOLF  MEYER,  JOHNS  HOPKINS  UNIVERSITY  ;  W.  B. 
PILLSBURY,  UNIVERSITY  OF  MICHIGAN;  C.  E.  SEASHORE,  UNIVERSITY  OF  IOWA  ;  G.  M. 
STRATTON,  UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA;  MARGARET  F.  WASHBURN,  VASSAR  COLLEGE. 


VOLUME  XXIV,    1917 


PUBLISHED   BI-MONTHLY   BY 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW  COMPANY 

41  NORTH   QUEEN  ST.,  LANCASTER,  PA. 
AND  PRINCETON,  N.  J, 

Entered  as  second-class  matter  July  13,  ^897,  at  the  post-office  at  Lancaster,  Pa.,  under 
Act  of  Congress  of  March  3,  1879 


P7 


1         PRESS  or 

THE  NEW  ERA  PRINTING  COMPANY 
LANCASTER.  PA. 


CONTENTS  OF  VOLUME  XXIV 

January. 

The  Relation  of  Intelligence  to  Social  Status.    JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  and  LILLIAN  E. 

COLER,    I. 

Mental  Tests  with  Delinquents  and  Australian  Aboriginal  Children.    S.  D.  POR- 

TEUS,    32. 

The  Psychological  Concept  of  Clearness.     E.  B.  TITCHENER,  43. 
Compound  Substitution  in  Behavior.     S.  B.  RUSSELL,  62. 
The  Delayed  Reaction  in  a  Child.    W.  S.  HUNTER,  74. 

March. 

The  Laws  of  Relative  Fatigue.     RAYMOND  DODGE,  89. 

More  Concerning  the  Temporal  Relations  of  Meaning  and  Imagery,  EDWARD  C. 
TOLMAN,  114. 

Experiments  on  the  Relative  Efficiency  of  Men  and  Women  in  Memory  and  Reason- 
ing.   ARTHUR  I.  GATES,  139. 

Individual  Differences  in  Judgments  of  the  Beauty  of  Simple  Forms.    EDWARD  L. 
THORNDIKE,  147. 

Preliminary  Report  on  the  Relative  Intensity  of  Successive,  Simultaneous,  Ascend- 
ing and  Descending  Tones.    A.  P.  WEISS,  154. 

Discussion : 

A  New  Method  of  Heterochromatic  Photometry— A  Reply  to  Dr.  Johnson. 

C.  E.  FERREE  and  GERTRUDE  RAND,  159. 

The  Stanford  (1915)  and  the  Vineland  (1911)  Revisions  of  the  Binet  Scale. 
SAMUEL  C.  KOHS,  174. 

.  May. 
/   The  Nature  of  Mental  Process.    HARVEY  CARR,  181. 

A  Reformulation  of  the  Law  of  Association.     WALTER  S.  HUNTER,  188. 

The  Scientific  Productivity  of  American  Professional  Psychologists.    SHEPHERD 

IVORY  FRANZ,  197. 

>  The  Psychology  of  Thinking  in  the  Case  of  Reading.     EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE,  220. 
The  Similarity  of  Brothers  and  Sisters  in  Mental  Traits.     DANIEL  STARCH,  235. 
A  Method  of  Recording  Errors  in  Form  Board  Tests.     E.  K.  STRONG,  JR.,  and  ED- 
WARD P.  GlLCHRIST,    239. 

Discussion  : 
./Introspection  versus  the  Subconscious.     LILLIEN  J.  MARTIN,  242. 

The  Mnemonic  Feat  of  the  '  Shass  Pollak.'    GEORGE  M.  STRATTON,  244. 

July. 

TWENTY-FIFTH  ANNIVERSARY  OF  THE  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGICAL  ASSOCIATION: 
Varieties  of  Psychological  Experience.    JOSEPH  JASTROW,  249. 
'  The  Need  for  Social  Psychology.    JOHN  DEWEY,  266. 


The  Case  of  Self  against  Soul.    MARY  WHITON  CALKINS,  278. 
Relation  between  Structural  and  Behavior  Psychology.    A.  P.  WEISS,  301. 

iii 


iv  CONTENTS. 

Discussion : 

Meaning  and  Imagery.     THOMAS  V.  MOORE,  318. 

Some  Experiments  in  Motor  Reproduction  of  Visually  Perceived   Forms. 

GEORGE  R.  WELLS,  322. 

September. 

An  Attempted  Formulation  of  the  Scope  of  Behavior  Psychology.    JOHN  B.  WAT- 
SON, 329. 

Relation  between  Functional  and  Behavior  Psychology.    A.  P.  WEISS,  353. 
The  Relation  between  Emotion  and  Its  Expression.    HARVEY  CARR,  369. 
The  Theory  of  the  Social  Force*.    H.  G.  KENAGY,  376. 
The  Mental  Work  Curve.     DANIEL  STARCH  and  I.  E.  ASH,  391. 
Individual  Differences  in  a  Normal  School  Class.    ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS,  403. 

November. 

Advance  Adaptation  in  Behavior.    S.  BENT  RUSSELL,  413. 

Relevant  and  Irrelevant  Speech  Instincts  and  Habits.     P.  F.  SWINDLE,  426. 

A  Preliminary  Report  on  *  Work  with  Knowledge  versus  Work  without  Knowledge 
of  Results.'     GEORGE  F.  ARPS,  449. 

The  Behavior  of  the  Human  Infant  During  the  First  Thirty  Days  of  Life.    MAR- 
GARET GRAY  BLANTON,  456. 

Discussion  : 

A  Critique  of  the  Yerkes-Bridges -Hard wick  Comparison  of  the  Binet-Simon 
and  Point  Sea1™.     FRANK  N.  FREEMAN,  484. 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  i  January,  1917 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


THE    RELATION    OF    INTELLIGENCE   TO    SOCIAL 

STATUS 

BY  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

Ohio  State  University 

HISTORICAL 

Among  the  many  reports  of  investigations  with  the  Binet- 
Simon  scale  incidental  references  to  the  influence  of  social 
status  on  intelligence  are  occasionally  found;  but  heretofore 
the  study  of  this  extremely  important  and  interesting  topic 
has  been  relatively  neglected,  although  Binet  with  his  usual 
acumen  did  not  overlook  the  problem. 

In  1910  Decroly  and  Degand1  tested  forty-five  children 
of  both  sexes  in  a  private  school  at  Brussels.  They  found 
that  none  of  the  children  tested  were  below  age,  nine  were 
at  age,  and  the  rest  from  one  to  three  years  above  the  level 
of  their  age.  These  results  were  very  significant,  since  the 
Binet-Simon  scale  is  theoretically  supposed  to  rate  equal 
numbers  retarded  and  advanced  with  the  mode  and  the 
average  at  age. 

Decroly's  and  Degand's  results  were  carefully  studied  by 
Binet.2  He  thought  the  best  explanation  of  the  difference 
between  his  results  and  theirs  was  found  in  the  fact  that  the 
Belgian  children  came  from  a  private  school  in  Brussels  and 
represented  children  of  the  well-to-do  and  largely  professional 
class  while  the  Paris  children  were  from  a  rather  poor  section 

1  Decroly,  O.,  et  Degand,  Mile.  J.,  'La  Mesure  de  1'intelligence  chez  des  enfants 
normaux  d'apres  les  tests  de  MM.  Binet  et  Simon,'  Arch,  de  psychol,  1910,  9,  81-108. 

2  Binet,  A.,  et  Simon,  Th.,  'Nouvelles  recherches  sur  la  Mesure  du  Niveau  In- 
tellectual chez  les  enfants  d'ecole,'  UAnnee  Psychol.,  1911,  17,  145-201. 

I 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


of  the  city.  The  instruction  in  the  Belgian  school  was  also 
more  individual  for  the  classes  were  very  small. 

In  analyzing  the  Brussels  results  by  the  individual  tests, 
Binet  found  that  the  children  from  the  better  social  class 
scored  higher  in  tests  involving  thought  in  the  higher  sense — 
apprehension,  criticism,  comparison,  etc.  They  also  scored 
higher  than  the  less  favored  children  in  the  tests  which  put  a 
premium  on  linguistic  readiness — such  as  the  description  of 
pictures,  abstract  definitions,  comparison  of  objects,  absurdi- 
ties, and  giving  words  for  three  minutes.  Binet  concluded 
that  social  status  must  be  closely  correlated  with  mentality 
and  reckoned  from  the  results  in  the  two  schools  an  average 
difference  of  about  one  and  one  half  years  between  children 
of  the  better  and  poorer  social  classes.  He  does  not  take 
into  account,  however,  that  this  difference  may  vary  with 
different  chronological  ages. 

Binet,  moreover,  criticized1  the  work  of  Katharine  John- 
ston, who  had  examined  two  hundred  pupils  of  the  Sheffield 
schools  in  England,  because  she  had  drawn  her  subjects  from 
at  least  three  distinct  social  groups  and  had  not  kept  these 
groups  separate  in  her  averages. 

Another  study  which  seemed  to  confirm  Decroly's  and 
Degand's  results  was  the  testing  done  by  M.  Morle2  in  a 
school  in  a  poor  part  of  Paris  and  compared  with  the  results 
from  a  school  situated  in  a  wealthy  section.  The  study  was 
on  a  rather  small  scale  as  only  thirty  children  were  taken, 
at  random,  from  each  school.  The  results  were  as  follows: 


Retarded 

At  Age 

Advanced 

2Yr. 

i  Yr. 

i  Yr. 

2Yr. 

Unfavored  school  

I 
I 

II 

3 

13 
10 

4 
IO 

I 

6 

Favored  school  

Thus  sixteen  children  out  of  the  thirty  tested  were  ad- 
vanced in  the  favored  school  while  only  five  were  advanced 
in  the  unfavored  school.  The  children  from  the  poorer 

1  UAnnee  psycho!.,  1911,  17,  195  196. 

2  Morle,  M.,  'L'influence  de  1'etat  social  sur  le  degre  de  1'intelligence  des  enfants,' 
Bull.  Soc.  libre  Educ.  Psychol.  de  I'enfant,  1911,  12,  8-15. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS  3 

section  were  on  the  average  about  one  fourth  year  behind 
the  level  of  their  age,  while  those  of  the  favored  school 
averaged  from  one  fourth  to  one  half  year  advanced,  or  a 
difference  of  about  three  fourths  of  a  year  between  the  two 
social  classes. 

In  1910  the  teachers  of  the  Breslau  schools  in  Germany 
made  a  comparative  study  of  children  of  different  social 
classes  there.  The  demand  for  a  common  school  for  all 
classes  to  replace  the  Vorschule  and  Volkschule  had  arisen 
in  Germany.  The  Volkschule  is  the  elementary  public  school 
attended  by  the  children  of  the  laboring  and  lower  business 
classes,  while  the  Vorschule  is  attended  by  the  children  of 
the  higher  social  classes.  In  Prussia  the  children  could  enter 
the  Gymnasium,  which  has  a  nine-year  curriculum  preparing 
for  the  university  after  three  years  of  preparation  in  the 
Vorschule  but  only  after  four  years  in  the  Volkschule.  The 
purpose  of  this  investigation  was  to  find  whether  the  mental 
maturity  of  the  child,  as  well  as  the  curriculum,  justified  this. 
One  hundred  and  fifty-six  boys  were  tested  from  the  two 
schools.  The  Binet-Simon  scale  modified  by  Bobertag  was 
used.  The  boys  tested  were  seven  and  nine  years  of  age. 
from  the  Vorschule  and  seven,  nine,  and  ten  years  from  the 
Volkschule.  It  was  found  that  the  nine-year  Volkschule 
pupils  scored  10  percent  lower  than  the  pupils  of  the  same 
age  in  the  better  school,  while  the  ten-year-old  Volkschule 
boys  attained  only  the  average  of  the  nine-year-old  Vor- 
schule pupils.  The  difference  in  average  was  due  largely  to 
the  fact  that  the  Vorschule  pupils  did  nearly  twice  as  well 
as  the  Volkschule  pupils  of  the  same  age  in  tests  above  their 
age  level.  The  tests  at  the  age  level  were  passed  about 
equally  well  by  both  schools.  This  raises  the  question  of 
whether  children  of  higher  social  classes  mature  earlier  than 
those  of  the  lower  levels.1 

Children   from   three   very   different  environments   were 
tested  in  191 1  by  J.  and  R.  Weintrob.2     There  were  about  sev- 

1  Hoffman,  A.,  "Vergleichende  Intelligenzpriifungen  an  Vorschulern  und  Volk- 
schiilern,"  Zsch.  f.  Angew.  PsychoL,  1914,  8,  102-120. 

2  Weintrob,  J.  and  Weintrob,  R.,  "The  Influence  of  Environment  on  Mental 
Ability  as  Shown  by  the  Binet-Simon  Tests,"  /.  of  £  due.  PsychoL,  1912,  3,  577-583. 


4  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

enty  children  of  both  sexes  in  each  group  tested.  Group  A 
consisted  of  children  from  a  school  attended  by  children  of 
the  wealthy  class,  with  every  opportunity  for  travel,  etc. 
Group  B  was  composed  of  children  whose  fathers  were  wage- 
earners  or  small  business  men.  Group  C  was  composed  of 
children  from  a  Hebrew  Orphan  Asylum  with  no  real  home 
environment.  The  schools  were  compared  as  to  the  number 
of  children,  testing  above,  at,  or  below  the  norm  for  their 
age,  using  the  Binet-Simon  scale.  The  A  group  was  found 
to  rank  highest,  the  C  group  next  and  the  B  group  last.  The 
investigators  state:  "Judging  from  the  results  environment 
does  not  seem  to  affect  greatly  mental  capacity,  if  at  all." 
Instead  of  the  schools  ranking  A  and  B  and  C  as  might  have 
been  expected,  the  C  school  or  Jewish  Orphanage  ranked  a 
close  second  to  the  wealthy  school.  However,  the  question 
of  race  enters  very  largely  in  this  study  as  the  children  of  the 
Asylum  were  all  Jewish,  while  those  of  Group  A  were  pre- 
dominantly American  with  a  few  Germans,  Jews  and  Italians, 
and  Group  B  was  largely  composed  of  Germans,  Italians  and 
some  American  children.  It  is  very  evident,  as  the  investi- 
gators say,  that  in  order  to  judge  fairly  differences  in  environ- 
mental influences  among  groups,  the  conditions  within  each 
group  must  be  uniform,  and  the  same  races  must  be  judged. 
A  study  involving  social  status,  incidentally,  was  made  in 
Columbia,  S.  C.  by  Miss  Strong.1  Her  primary  purpose  was 
to  investigate  the  difference  between  the  white  and  negro 
children  but  in  order  to  make  a  fair  comparison  she  tested 
white  children  in  both  the  city  schools  and  in  the  mill  district. 
The  results  show  that  less  than  six  percent  of  the  city  school 
children  were  retarded  while  eighteen  percent  of  the  mill 
district  children  were  mentally  over  a  year  below  the  level  of 
their  age.  None  of  the  mill  district  children  were  above 
their  age  level,  although  ten  percent  of  the  city  children 
scored  above  their  years.  Approximately  the  same  percent 
of  the  children  in  each  district  were  at  the  level  of  their  age; 
eighty-four  percent  in  the  city  schools  and  eighty-one  per- 

1  Strong,  A.  C.,  '350  White  and  Colored  Children  Measured  by  the  Binet-Simon 
Measuring  Scale  of  Intelligence;  A  Comparative  Study,'  Fed.  Sem.,  1913,  20,  485-513. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


cent  in  the  mill  district  schools.  Practically  the  same  course 
of  study  was  used  in  the  schools  of  both  districts. 

One  of  the  most  recent  investigations  on  the  subject  of 
social  status  was  made  by  Yerkes  and  Anderson1  in  Cam- 
bridge, Mass.  In  this  investigation  the  Yerkes-Bridges  Point 
Scale2  was  used.  Fifty-four  children  in  the  kindergarten  and 
first  grade  of  school  A  were  compared  with  children  of  the 
same  sex  and  approximately  the  same  age  in  school  B. 
School  A  is  located  in  a  good  neighborhood  and  the  socio- 
logical status  of  almost  all  the  pupils  is  very  good.  School  B 
on  the  contrary  is  located  in  a  medium  to  poor  section  of  the 
city  and  the  majority  of  its  pupils  live  in  a  rather  poor  en- 
vironment. The  children  compared  were  all  of  English- 
speaking  parents. 

The  average  number  of  points  scored  in  the  two  schools 
is  indicated  below: 


Age 

4  Yrs. 

5  Yrs. 

6  Yrs. 

7  Yrs. 

8  Yrs. 

School 

A.. 

JC 

27 

4.2 

AQ 

s6 

School 

B  

17 

22 

29 

35 

4i 

The  favored  school  averages  much  higher  except  in  the 
four-year  group.  The  very  young  children  of  the  unfavored 
group  seem  to  have  the  advantage  here,  probably  because 
they  are  less  timid.  The  results  show  that  there  is  a  difference 
of  from  twenty  percent  to  thirty  percent  in  mental  ability 
which  maybe  associated  with  differences  in  sociological  status. 

The  authors  point  out  that  in  view  of  a  difference  so 
marked  between  children  of  different  sociological  levels,  it  is 
very  unfair  to  judge  them  by  the  same  norm  and  that  further 
investigating  should  be  done  with  the  view  of  establishing 
norms  for  different  social  levels.3 

1  Yerkes,  Robt.  and  Anderson,  Helen,  'The  Importance  of  Social  Status  as  Indi- 
cated by  the  Results  of  the  Point  Scale  Method  of  Measuring  Mental  Capacity,' 
/.  of  Educ.  Psychol,  6,  No.  3,  Mar.,  1915. 

2  Yerkes,  Bridges  and  Hardwick,  'A  Point  Scale  for  Measuring  Mental  Ability,' 
Warwick  and  York,  1915.     Hereinafter  referred  to  as  the  "Point  Scale." 

3  In  a  book  published  since  this  paper  was  written,  Prof.  L.  M.  Terman  discusses 
the  influence  of  social  status.     He  reports  a  difference  of  one  to  two  years  between 
the  superior  and  inferior  classes — a  result  in   close  conformity  with  those  mentioned 
above,     '  The  Measurement  of  Intelligence,'  pp.  72  and  115,  Warwick  and  York,  1916. 


6  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

EXPERIMENTAL 

The  Yerkes-Bridges  Point  Scale  was  used  in  this  investi- 
gation and  three  hundred  and  one  children  were  tested  in 
two  schools  situated  in  very  different  localities  of  Columbus, 
Ohio.  The  children  from  school  A  situated  in  the  better 
district  will  be  designated  as  the  favored  group,  while  those 
of  school  B  will  be  designated  as  the  unfavored  group. 

School  A  is  in  a  very  good  residence  section  near  the  uni- 
versity. The  majority  of  the  people  own  their  homes,  which 
are  surrounded  by  well-kept  lawns.  A  portion  of  the  uni- 
versity campus,  as  well  as  many  wooded  lots  afford  ample 
playground  for  the  children.  The  school  building  is  modern 
in  every  respect,  having  been  completed  about  six  years  ago. 
The  children  of  the  first  and  second  grades  spend  alternate 
half  hours  in  a  well-equipped  Portable  where  their  play  is 
supervised  by  a  teacher  who  has  specialized  in  this  work. 
This  school  is  considered  one  of  the  most  desirable  in  which 
to  teach  in  the  city  and  only  well  qualified  teachers  obtain 
the  positions. 

The  chief  occupations  of  the  fathers  of  the  children  in  this 
district  were  managers,  proprietors  and  officers  of  manu- 
facturies  and  stores,  traveling  salesmen,  real  estate  and 
insurance  agents,  and  a  professional  group  composed  of  pro- 
fessors, doctors,  lawyers,  architects,  and  ministers.  A  more 
complete  analysis  and  grouping  of  the  data  by  the  occupa- 
tions of  the  fathers  will  be  given  later  in  this  paper.  All  the 
children  of  the  first  and  second  grades  were  tested,  and  as 
time  did  not  permit  completing  the  third  grade,  the  children 
were  taken  alphabetically.  All  the  children  in  the  grades 
tested  were  American  born  and  of  English-speaking  parents. 
The  testing  was  done  in  a  hall  where  occasionally  some  one 
passed  but  otherwise  there  was  no  disturbance;  and  no  third 
party  was  present  when  the  examination  was  made.  The 
child's  name,  date  of  birth  and  father's  occupation  were 
recorded  in  every  case  and  checked  by  the  teacher's  record. 

School  B  is  situated  near  the  railroad  in  a  poor  factory 
district  of  Columbus.  The  houses  average  about  four  or  five 
rooms  and  are  usually  built  very  near  the  street.  They  are 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS  7 

often  in  very  bad  repair,  having  been  in  that  part  of  Columbus 
which  was  flooded  three  years  ago.  The  usual  rent  is  from 
38  to  ?io  a  month.  Where  there  are  yards  they  are  so  ill- 
kept  and  muddy  that  the  street  is  the  common  playground 
f  r  the  children.  The  school  house  is  old  and  has  no  inside 
toilet  facilities  or  up-to-date  equipment.  There  is  one  saloon 
on  the  corner  opposite  the  school  building  and  two  others 
within  a  block  and  a  half  of  it.  The  fathers,  if  still  in  the 
family,  are  receiving  low  and  irregular  wages  and  almost  one 
half  of  the  fathers  of  the  children  in  this  district  belong  to  the 
unskilled  and  casual  labor  group.  The  remainder  were  in 
the  more  skilled  mechanical  trades  or  were  teamsters  or 
delivery  men.  The  mothers  are  often  away  all  day  working 
in  the  factories  or  doing  laundry  work  to  supplement  the 
husband's  income,  or  in  many  cases  to  support  the  family 
entirely.  The  parents  have  little  idea  of  the  value  of  educa- 
tion and  the  children  often  stop  school  and  go  to  work  as 
soon  as  they  can  secure  their  working  papers.  The  Asso- 
ciated Charities  say  that  probably  50  percent  of  the  families 
in  this  district  are  registered  with  some  kind  of  philanthropic 
organization.  The  children  are  often  very  poorly  clad,  far 
from  clean  and  frequently  undernourished.  Many  of  the 
teachers  in  this  school  are  young  and  have  not  taught  a  great 
while. 

In  the  case  of  several  children  scoring  lowest,  other  mem- 
bers of  the  family  were  tested.  In  five  cases  the  mothers 
scored  only  from  47  to  54  points  or  a  mental  age  of  about 
eight  years,  and  sisters  and  brothers  were  far  below  their  age 
level. 

The  negroes  and  children  of  non-English  speaking  parents 
were  excluded  in  this  school,  but  every  other  child  in  the 
first,  second  and  third  grade  was  tested,  making  a  total  of 
136  children.  The  testing  was  done  in  a  small  room  free 
from  all  disturbing  elements. 

In  both  schools  the  tests  were  given  during  school  hours 
by  one  examiner1  and  in  all  cases  doubtful  credits  were  dis- 
cussed and  decided  upon  by  the  authors  jointly.  The  child's 

1  Miss  Coler. 


8 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  JE.  COLER 


age  to  the  nearest  month  was  determined  by  subtracting  the 
date  of  the  birth  from  the  date  the  tests  were  given.  A  given 
age  group  includes  all  children  from  the  middle  of  the  year 
below  to  the  middle  of  the  one  above.  Thus,  in  the  group 
of  six-year-olds  are  included  all  boys  (or  girls)  from  five 
years  seven  months  to  six  years  six  months,  inclusive. 

RESULTS 

The  results  for  the  total  301  Columbus  school  children 
will  first  be  considered  and  their  scores  compared  with  the 
scores  for  Cambridge,  Mass.,  school  children  of  the  same 
ages.  These  results  are  presented  in  Table  I.  The  first 

TABLE  I 


Age 

Columbus 

Cambridge 

English 

Non-English 

No. 

A. 

M. 

No. 

A. 

No. 

A. 

6 

8 

9 
10 
ii 

12 

37 

97 
81 

59 
H 

7 

5 

34-i 
42.8 

54-7 
57-3 
55-9 
49.6 
54-8 

33 
45 
55 
59 
56 
50 
55 

55 
48 

47 
43 
53 
55 
40 

29 
35 
4i 
56 
62 
65 
77 

16 
25 
14 
3i 
23 
24 
20 

27 
31 
37 
48 

I6 
62 

67 

A. — Average. 
M. — Median. 

column  gives  the  ages,  the  second  the  number  of  Columbus 
children  tested  at  each  age,  the  third  and  fourth  the  average 
and  the  median  scores  for  Columbus  children  at  each  age, 
while  columns  five  and  six  give  for  comparison  the  number 
and  average  scores  for  Cambridge  children  of  English-speaking 
parents  and  columns  seven  and  eight  the  same  for  children 
of  non-English-speaking  parents.1 

The  results  are  shown  graphically  in  Fig.  I.  Graph  A  is 
for  Columbus  children,  both  schools  combined;  Graph  B  for 
Cambridge,  English-speaking  group,  and  Br  for  Cambridge, 
non-English-speaking  group.  After  nine  years  the  number 
of  Columbus  children  at  each  age  is  very  small  and  after  ten 
years  composed  of  children  from  the  unfavored  school  alone. 

1  Point  Scale,  pp.  66-67. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


This  selection  is  clearly  shown  by  the  drop  in  the  curve  after 
nine  years,  and  is  due  to  the  fact  that  in  our  present  school 
system  a  child  is  behind  if  he  is  over  nine  years  of  age  and  in 
the  third  grade. 


Points 
80 
75 
70 
65 
60 
55 
50 
45 
40 

35 
30 


Ages  6 


9          10          ii 
FIG.  i. 


12 


The  most  striking  feature  in  these  results  is  the  evident 
superiority  of  the  Columbus  children  up  to  ten  years;  but  it 
will  be  shown  in  the  sequel  that  their  superiority  is  entirely 
due  to  the  influence  of  the  favored  group  and  that  when  the 


10 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


groups  are  separated  the  correspondence  between  the  children 
of  the  two  cities  is  even  closer  than  might  have  been  expected. 

TABLE  II 


Age 

6  Yr. 

7Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

Cambridge  Heterogeneous  
Total  Columbus  

Number.  .  .  . 
Score  
Number.  .  .  . 

71 
29 
37 

73 
34 
07 

6l 
39 

Si 

74 

52 

CQ 

76 

59 

Combined  Average  

Score  
Number 

34-1 
108 

42.8 

1  7O 

54-7 

142 

57-3 
i>ii. 

55-9 

QO 

Score  .  

30.7 

39-0 

48 

54-4 

?8.S 

The  Columbus  results  from  the  sixth  to  the  tenth  year 
inclusive  may  be  combined  with  the  Cambridge  results  for 
the  same  ages  to  help  in  the  standardization  of  the  scale. 


Points 
60 


Httey 


Ages  6 


9 

FIG.  2. 


ii 


12 


At  first  the  Columbus  results  were  combined  with  the  Cam- 
bridge heterogeneous  group1  in  the  following  way.  The 
number  of  children  at  each  age  in  the  group  was  multiplied 
by  the  average  score  of  that  age  for  Columbus  and  Cambridge 

1  Point  Scale,  pp.  64-65. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


ii 


separately.  Then  these  results  were  added  and  divided  by 
the  total  number  at  that  age.  Table  II.  shows  the  average 
score  and  number  of  pupils  at  each  age  in  each  group  and  the 
combined  averages  or  new  norms  obtained.  The  latter  are 
also  shown  graphically  in  Fig.  2.  The  solid  line  represents 
the  combined  norm  for  the  total  643  children  of  Columbus  and 


Points 


60 


55 


45 


40 


35 


Ages  6 


8 
FIG.  3. 


Cambridge;  and  the  dotted  line  is  the  original  norm  from  six 
to  ten  years  for  the  355  Cambridge  children  alone. 

As  all  the  children  tested  in  the  Columbus  schools  were  of 
English-speaking  parents  it  seemed  fairer  to  use  as  a  standard 
for  judging  the  Columbus  pupils  a  norm  made  from  the  Co- 
lumbus results  combined  in  the  same  way  with  the  Cambridge 
group  of  children  of  English-speaking  parents,1  instead  of  the 
heterogeneous  group. 

These  norms  are  shown  in  Table  III.  and  graphically  in 
Fig.  3.  In  this  case  the  solid  line  represents  the  combined 

1  Point  Scale,  pp.  66-67. 


12 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


norm  for  245  Cambridge  children  of  English-speaking  parents 
and  288  Columbus  children,  or  a  total  of  534  children.  The 
broken  line  shows  the  original  norm  for  the  Cambridge 
English-speaking  group  alone.  Selection  entering  after  nine 
years  in  the  Columbus  results  will  explain  the  slight  drop  in 
the  solid  curve  from  nine  to  ten  years.  This  curve  was  used 
as  a  norm  for  determining  the  mental  age  and  coefficient  of 

TABLE  III 


Ages 

6Yr. 

?Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

Cambridge  English-speaking 

Number 

re 

4-8 

47 

4-1 

C-2 

Score 

20 

•2C 

4.1 

56 

11 

Total  Columbus 

Number 

37 

Q7 

81 

CQ 

14 

Score 

24  I 

4.2.8 

C4..7 

cy.-j 

ce.o 

Combined  Average  

Number.  .  .  . 

Q2 

I4C 

128 

IO2 

67 

Score  

3I-I 

40.2 

49-7 

56.8 

60.7 

mental  ability  of  the  Columbus  children.  For  scores  above 
or  below  the  six,  seven,  eight,  nine  and  ten  year  averages  the 
norm  for  the  English-speaking  group  of  Cambridge  alone 
had  to  be  used. 

COMPARISON  OF  DIFFERENT  SOCIAL  GROUPS 
The  Columbus  results  from  Schools  A  and  B  will  now  be 
compared.  Tables  IV.  and  V.  show  the  individual  scores 
by  sex  and  age  for  the  favored  and  unfavored  schools  re- 
spectively. The  average  score  for  each  age  and  each  sex 
and  also  for  both  sexes  combined  are  likewise  given  in  each 
table. 

These  results  are  shown  graphically  by  Fig.  4,  curves  A 
and  B,  The  favored  school  is  from  21  percent  to  32  percent 
superior  to  the  unfavored  school  varying  with  the  chrono- 
logical age.  The  curve  drops  at  nine  years  in  School  A  and 
at  ten  years  in  School  B>  showing  that  the  selection  previously 
mentioned  enters  earlier  in  the  former.  After  ten  years  the 
numbers  in  the  unfavored  group  are  very  small  and  the 
scores  are  not  representative  of  these  age  groups. 

As  these  results  are  very  similar  to  those  found  in  the 
Cambridge  investigation  it  is  interesting  to  compare  them 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


TABLE  IV 

FAVORED  A 


6 

r 

3 

< 

> 

i 

0 

ff. 

V. 

fc? 

(g) 

(M6) 

(J7) 

(M6> 

(F4? 

it 

w 

29 

31 

22 

32 

49 

— 

44 

54 

66 

39 

30 

36 



51 

4i 

55 

68 

36 

39 

34 
35 

38 

51 

52 

45 

5° 

52 

62 

49 
64 



39 

35 

40 

52 

49 

56 

63 

75 

40 

43 

52 

49 

60 

63 

42 

42 

40 

45 

53 

Si 

61 

65 

47 

43 

41 

45 

53 

Si 

62 

47 

42 

49 

55 

55 

63 

67 

48 

52 

43 

49 

55 

55 

64 

68 

54 

45 

49 

55 

55 

64 

68 

47 

49 

56 

56 

66 

71 

A  *7 

C*7 

60 

4/ 

bf 

°v 

47 

50 

r  T 

58 

58 

rr\ 

69 

72 

48 

51 
51 

60 

59 

59 

73 

73 

48 

51 

62 

77 

49 

52 

63 

60 

79 

52 

64 

60 

So 

52 

65 

62 

50 

53 

66 

63 

52 

53 

66 

63 

54 

55 

67 

65 

54 

59 

69 

66 

54 

72 

67 

54 

V 

67 

55 

75 

69 

55 

76 

56 

73 

56 

58 

58 

59 

60 

'64' 

64 

66 

72 

Ave       39  8 

Q 

.,  Q  7 

co  8 

61  i 

64.8 

67 

56.8 

41  »9 

43  •  -I 

40.  / 

by-0 

5  /  *9 

Uj.l 

u/ 

40.9 

48 

•4 

58 

.8 

6 

4 

6c 

>.2 

=  25  percent  above  or  below  general  norm. 
=  25  percent  above  or  below  group  norm. 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


TABLE  V 

UNFAVORED  B 


6  Yr. 

7  Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

W 

¥! 

s? 

(K> 

&> 

(F4) 

5S? 

(F8) 

fc! 

V. 

ffi 

V 

Si! 

V2.' 

is> 

16 

21 

22 
23 
23 

17 

23 

14 

21 

25 

2* 
26 

26 

27 

27 
28 
29 
29 
29 

19 

22 
22 
24 

'28* 

22 
25 
27 

'36" 

39 
44 
45 
45 
46 
48 
50 
52 

35 

35 
35 

'38' 

24 
42 

36 
48 

46 

46 

53 

57 

55 

53 

43 

45 

38 
42 
44 
45 
48 
49 
49 
5i 
52 
57 
57 
57 

54 
57 
60 

50 
52 
61 

60 

50 

II 

72 

28 
29 
29 

42 

44 

2 

47 
50 
50 
5i 

53 
54 
54 
58 

f? 
61 

V 

75 

43 
47 
49 
52 
53 
58 
58 
59 

25 
25 

11 

29 

33 
34 

39 

55 

34 
37 
37 
43 

44 
45 

45 

54 

58 

32 
32 
35 
37 
40 

4i 
4i 
42 
43 

44 

62 
62 

68 

50 
54 

Ave  28.3 

27.2 

33-2 

36.6 

43.1 

494 

47-9 

52.2 

53-5 

52 

53-2 

46 

52 

57-5 

_53_ 
53 

28.3 

34-4 

46.2 

50.1 

52.8 

52.1 

54-2 

=  25  percent  above  or  below  general  norm. 

=25  percent  above  or  below  group  norm. 

with  the  two  similar  groups  there.1  Table  VI.  shows  these 
results  and  they  are  also  shown  graphically  in  Fig.  4.  Only 
the  kindergarten  and  the  First  Grade  were  tested  in  the 
Cambridge  favored  school  so  the  curve  is  short. 

TABLE  VI 


Favored  School 

Unfavored  School 

Age  

6Yr. 

7Yr. 

8Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

6  Yr. 

7Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

Cambridge  .  . 
Columbus  .  .  . 

Score  .  . 
Score  .  . 

42 
40.9 

49 

48.4 

56 

58.8 

29 

28.2 

35 
34-4 

& 

56 

SO.I 

62 
52 

64 

60.2 

1  Point  Scale,  p.  74,  p.  66. 


INTELLIGENCE   TO  SOCIAL  STATUS 


Points 

80 
75 

70 

65 
60 

55 
5° 
45 
40 

35 
30 


Ages  6 


9  10  ii 

FIG.  4. 

TABLE  VII 


12  13 


School  A 

School  B 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

Cambridge  
Columbus  

No  
Score  

II 

42 

8 
39-8 

13 

40 

9 
41.9 

29 
29 
14 

28.3 

26 

36 

27.2 

No  

Score  

These   differences    between    the   favored   and   unfavored 
groups  and  the  striking  similarity  between  the  Columbus 


i6 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


and  Cambridge  results  are  even  more  clearly  shown  by  the 
data  for  the  six-year-old  groups  given  in  Table  VII. 

COMPARISON  OF  SEXES 

Tables  IV.  and  V.  should  be  consulted  for  the  individual 
scores.  The  averages  for  boys  and  for  girls  in  both  schools 
combined  are  shown  in  Table  VIII. 

TABLE  VIII 


6  Yr. 

7Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

Males 

•72  C 

42  2 

CA 

c6  Q 

t;8 

Females  

36.3 

44.1 

55 

57-7 

544 

Fig.  5  shows  these  results  graphically.  The  superiority 
of  the  girls  over  the  boys  seems  marked  up  to  ten  years.  By 
examining  Table  IX.  and  Fig.  6,  which  give  the  averages  for 


Points 
60 


55 


45 


40 


35 


Ages  6 


10  II 

FIG.  5. 


12 


each  sex  in  each  school  separately  it  will  be  seen  that  this 
superiority  of  the  girls  is  brought  about  almost  entirely  by 
the  girls  of  the  unfavored  school. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 
TABLE  IX 


6  Yr. 

7Yr. 

8Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

Unfavored  
Favored  

28.3 

39-8 

27.2 
41.9 

33-2 

48.1 

36.6 
48.7 

43-1 

59-8 

49.4 
57-9 

47-9 
63.1 

52.2 
64.8 

53-5 
67 

56.8 

The  difference  between  the  sexes  is  particularly  marked 
in  the  eight-year  group  of  the  unfavored  school,  where  there 
is  an  equal  number  of  boys  and  girls.  At  the  same  age  in 
the  favored  school  the  boys  have  the  advantage.  These 


Points 


Ages  6 


results  seem  to  bear  out  the  theory  held  by  Thorndike1  and 
others  that  females  deviate  less  from  the  norm  than  males; 
for  there  is  less  difference  between  the  performances  of  the 
girls  in  the  two  schools  than  there  is  between  the  performances 
of  the  boys. 

1  'Educational  Psychology',  second  edition,  1910,  pp.  33-43. 


1 8  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

TABLE  X 


First  Grade 

Second  Grade 

Third  Grade 

No. 

M. 

A. 

Age 

No. 

M. 

A. 

Age 

No. 

M. 

A, 

Age 

Favored  .... 
Unfavored  .  . 
Difference  .  .  . 

57 
52 

47 
27-5 
19-5 

45-3 
29.1 

15-7 

6-75  mo. 
6-9!  mo. 
2    mo. 

55 
44 

55 
45-5 
9-5 

56.2 
46.2 
IO 

7-8    mo. 
8-5    mo. 
4^  mo. 

53 

40 

64 

54-5 
9-5 

63.5 

55-i 
8.4 

8-8£  mo. 
9-9    mo. 
i    yr. 

M. — Median. 
A. — Average. 
Age — Chronological  age  in  years  and  months. 

TABLE  Xa 


First  Grade 

Second  Grade 

Third  Grade 

Favored 

Unfavored 

Favored 

Unfavored 

Favored 

Unfavored 

M 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F. 

M. 

F 

M. 

F 

5 

7 

5 

2 

5 

5 

4 

4 

5 

3 

4 

o 

22 

31 

17 

44 

36 

29 

24 

50 

49 

43 

44 

29 

32 

16 

19 

49 

39 

35 

35 

52 

49 

45 

45 

30 

36 

21 

22 

50 

41 

36 

37 

52 

48 

46 

34 

36 

21 

22 

Si 

45 

37 

42 

53 

54 

50 

46 

35 

38 

22 

23 

51 

49 

39 

42 

53 

55 

53 

50 

35 

39 

22 

24 

52 

49 

40 

43 

56 

56 

53 

50 

36 

39 

23 

28 

52 

49 

42 

44 

58 

57 

54 

50 

40 

40 

23 

28 

54 

51 

43 

44 

60 

58 

55 

51 

40 

25 

29 

54 

51 

43 

44 

60 

61 

57 

42 

25 

29 

55 

51 

44 

45 

61 

63 

57 

52 

42 

43 

25 

34 

55 

52 

44 

47 

62 

63 

58 

53 

42 
43 

43 
45 

25 
25 

37 
38 

55 
55 

53 
55 

I 

49 
49 

62 
63 

64 

65 

58 
58 

54 
54 

45 
47 

45 
49 

25 
26 

42 
45 

56 

55 
55 

47 

52 
54 

64 
64 

65 
65 

fo 

55 
57 

47 

49 

26 

45 

56 

55 

48 

57 

64 

67 

62 

58 

47 

50 

26 

48 

58 

59 

49 

57 

66 

67 

72 

59 

47 

51 

27 

58 

59 

50 

58 

66 

68 

60 

47 

52 

27 

58 

60 

50 

67 

67 

68 

61 

48 

52 

27 

59 

60 

52 

68 

71 

61 

48 

52 

28 

63 

62 

52 

69 

61 

48 

53 

29 

64 

62 

53 

69 

72 

68 

48 

54 

29 

65 

63 

54 

69 

73 

75 

49 

50 

3 

29 
32 

66 
66 

66 
67 

11 

72 
73 

73 
75 

52 

32 

66 

67 

76 

54 

33 

72 

69 

77 

54 

34 

75 

79 

55 

35 

60 

35 

64 

36 

38 

39 

41 

Ave  45-3 

45-4 

28.1 

31-2 

57-7 

54-8 

45-6 

46.8 

63.8 

63.2 

554 

54-8 

45-3 

29.1 

56.3 

46.2 

63-5 

55 

INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS  19 

COMPARISON  OF  GRADES 

Table  X.  gives  in  convenient  form  the  number  of  pupils, 
the  median  and  average  scores  and  the  average  chronological 
ages  for  each  grade  in  each  school.  The  individual  scores 
for  each  school  and  each  grade  are  given  on  Table  X<z. 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  superiority  of  the  favored  school  is 
much  greater  for  the  first  than  for  the  second  or  third  grades. 

By  examining  the  Figs.  7,  8,  and  9,  showing  the  modes 
for  the  three  grades,  the  same  thing  will  be  found  to  be  true. 
The  favored  school,  first  grade,  has  a  mode  of  from  45  to  50 
points  and  the  unfavored  school  from  25  to  30  points  or  a 
difference  of  20  points.  The  difference  in  the  second  grade  is 
15  points  and  in  the  third  the  difference  lies  between  10  and 
15  points  as  the  mode  is  not  distinct  here. 

These  results  seem  to  show  that  the  difference  between  the 
children  of  the  two  schools  is  greatest  when  they  enter  the 
school  and  that  it  becomes  less  from  grade  to  grade.  This 
would  mean  that  the  school  work  tended  to  equalize  some  of 
the  original  difference. 

It  is  necessary,  however,  to  examine  further  to  see  if  there 
may  be  another  explanation  before  accepting  this  conclusion. 
The  average  chronological  ages  for  the  three  grades  are  also 
given  in  Table  X.  The  ages  are  nearest  the  same  in  the 
first  grade  where  there  is  only  two  months  difference,  but  this 
difference  increases  to  over  a  year  in  the  third  grade.  This 
age  difference  is  brought  about  by  the  fact  that  in  the  un- 
favored school  so  many  children  are  in  a  low  grade  for  their 
years.  In  our  present  school  system  a  child  enters  at  the 
age  of  six  and  would  therefore  be  in  the  third  grade  at  the 
age  of  eight  to  nine  years  if  regularly  promoted.  Out  of  the 
forty  children  in  the  third  grade  of  the  unfavored  school  there 
were  eight  in  the  ten-year  group,  five  in  the  eleven-year  group, 
four  in  the  twelve-year  group  and  one  in  the  fourteen-year 
group.  That  is,  about  45  percent  of  the  children  in  that 
grade  are  older  than  they  should  normally  be  in  the  third 
grade.  On  the  other  hand  there  are  only  five  older  than  the 
nine-year  group  in  the  third  grade  of  the  favored  school  and 
none  of  these  is  above  ten  years  six  months. 


20 

Number 

20 

10 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


10 


FIRST  GHAJ>E  MOPES. 

A =  FAV°REP 

8__ .   av 


-!B  \ — ;A 


&RADE  MODES 


B  ---  *  U/VCAVOR£J> 


j     i     i 


p0;nts      .-. 

5     10    15    20   25    30   35    40  45    50    55    60   65    70   75    80   85    90   95 

FIGS.  7,  8,  AND  9. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


21 


If  we  now  compare  the  average  scores  for  each  age  group 
in  the  two  schools  we  find  that  the  differences  from  year  to 
year  are  fairly  constant.  These  figures  are  shown  in  Table 
XL 

TABLE  XI 


6  Yr. 

7Yr. 

8  Yr. 

9Yr. 

10  Yr. 

Favored  
Unfavored  .  .  

40.9 

28.3 

48.4 

34'4 

58.8 
46.2 

64 

CO.  I 

60.2 
52.8 

Difference  

"^•3 

12.6 

14 

12.6 

13-9 

74 

The  difference  is  practically  the  same  for  the  six-  and 
seven-year  groups  and  the  decrease  at  ten  years  is  probably 
due  to  selection  entering  in  both  schools  at  this  age.  More- 
over there  are  too  few  ten-year-old  children  for  a  fair  com- 
parison. There  is  thus  very  little  diminution  of  the  initial 
difference  with  age;  and  the  fact  that  the  difference  in  mental 
ability  between  the  two  schools  is  less  in  the  second  and 
third  grades  than  in  the  first,  must  therefore  be  largely  due  to 
the  older  children  in  the  second  and  third  grades  of  the  un- 
favored school  who  tend  to  raise  the  average  of  points  scored 
in  that  grade  and  so  make  it  approach  nearer  to  the  favored 
school's  results. 

A  coefficient  of  mental  ability  for  each  child  was  obtained 
by  dividing  the  number  of  points  actually  scored  by  the 
number  of  points  which  should  be  scored  at  his  chronological 
age.  The  standard  used  was  the  one  obtained  by  combining 
the  total  Columbus  results  with  the  results  of  the  Cambridge 
children  of  English-speaking  parents.1  The  mental  age  of 
the  child  can  also  be  obtained  by  referring  his  score  to  the 
age  at  which  this  score  should  be  obtained. 

The  average  coefficient  of  mental  ability,  average  mental 
age  and  average  chronological  age  for  each  grade  in  each 
school  are  shown  in  Table  XII. 

There  is  a  uniform  difference  of  about  a  year  in  the 
average  chronological  age  of  the  children  from  grade  to  grade 
in  the  favored  school.  On  the  other  hand  there  is  a  differ- 
ence of  almost  two  years  between  the  average  chronological 

1  See  Table  III. 


22 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


age  of  the  children  in  the  first  grade  and  those  of  the  second 
grade  in  the  unfavored  school.  This  indicates  that  the 
children  of  the  first  grade  in  the  unfavored  school  remain 
on  the  average  two  years  in  that  grade  before  being  promoted. 
Moreover  the  mental  age  for  the  children  of  the  unfavored 
school  is  about  a  year  lower  than  their  actual  chronological 
age.  It  would  therefore  seem  that  the  children  of  the  un- 
favored group  are  not  mature  enough  mentally  when  they 
enter  school  at  the  age  of  six  to  be  able  to  do  the  prescribed 

TABLE  XII 


Favored 

Unfavored 

Differenc 

e 

Grade 

I 

III 

I 

II 

ill 

I 

11 

III 

C  A  . 

6—  j\  mo 

7—8  mo 

8-8J  mo 

G—  ot  mo 

3—  c  mo 

Q—  a  mo 

2  mo. 

4.4  mo. 

I  yr.  5  mo 

M.A  
CM.  A... 

7-9 
1.24 

9-3 
1.26 

10-4 
1.18 

:S^9 

•77 

7-9 
.98 

8-1  1 
•93 

2  yr. 
•47 

i  yr.  6  mo. 
.28 

i  yr.  5  mo 

•25 

C.  A.,  chronological  age. 

M.  A.,  mental  age. 

C.  M.  A.,  coefficient  of  mental  ability. 

•work.  The  children  of  the  favored  group,  on  the  contrary, 
are  mentally  a  year  ahead  of  their  chronological  age  and  so 
these  children  might  equally  well  enter  school  at  an  earlier 
age  and  be  able  to  do  the  required  work.  It  is  also  inter- 
esting to  note  in  this  table  that  although  the  difference  in  the 
mental  age  between  the  two  schools  decreases  from  grade  to 
grade,  the  difference  in  their  chronological  age  increases,  thus 
keeping  a  fairly  constant  difference  of  two  years  between  the 
schools  in  the  grades  tested.  Binet  estimated  that  there 
was  a  difference  of  about  one  and  one  half  years  between 
children  of  different  social  classes,  and  M.  Morle  found  about 
a  year's  difference  in  the  groups  he  studied  in  Paris. 

COMPARISON  OF  SEPARATE  TESTS 

Table  XIII.  shows  the  average  scores  for  each  of  the 
twenty  tests  making  up  the  Point  Scale.  Scores  for  the 
favored  and  unfavored  boys  and  girls  are  given  separately 
and  the  combined  average  and  the  difference  between  the 
schools  is  also  given.  The  difference,  although  sometimes 
very  small,  is  always  on  the  side  of  the  favored  school. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


TABLE  XIII 


Test 

Fav.  Boys 

Unfav.  Boys 

Fav.  Girls 

Unfav.  Girls 

Total 

Diff. 

Fav. 

Unfav. 

I 

2.90 

2.62 

2.98 

2.91 

2.94 

2.77 

•17 

2 

3-73 

3-18 

3-88 

3-22 

3-8 

3-2 

.60 

3 

2.97 

2.77 

2.98 

2.71 

2.98 

2.74 

•34 

4 

3.18 

2.48 

3-19 

2.67 

3-19 

2-55 

•64 

5 

3-27 

2.02 

3-24 

2.67 

3.26 

2-35 

.91 

6 

2.22 

1.87 

2.20 

1.94 

2.21 

1.91 

•30 

7 

6.76 

5-90 

6.76 

6. 

6.76 

5-95 

.81 

8 

i-73 

1.46 

1-54 

i-S7 

1.64 

1.52 

.12 

9 

4.58 

3.06 

4.28 

3-59 

4-43 

3-33 

I.IO 

10 

5-42 

3-98 

5.18 

4-64 

5-30 

4-31 

•99 

ii 

2.09 

I.48 

2.25 

1.32 

2.17 

1.40 

•77 

12 

2-43 

2.06 

2.27 

2.25 

2-35 

2.16 

.19 

13 

1-51 

.78 

1.64 

1.40 

1.58 

1.09 

•49 

14 

1.66 

•52 

1.16 

.98 

1.41 

•75 

.66 

IS 

3-40 

2.27 

3-So 

2.40 

345 

2-34 

i.  ii 

16 

1.65 

1.09 

1.38 

1-45 

1.52 

1.27 

•25 

17 

2.05 

•79 

2.OI 

.86 

2.03 

•83 

i.  20 

18 

1-38 

•39 

i-37 

.88 

1.38 

.64 

•74 

19 

.89 

.42 

1.19 

1.05 

1.04 

•74 

•3° 

20 

1.30 

•75 

i-3S 

.90 

i-33 

•83 

.50 

The  five  tests  in  which  the  greatest  superiority  of  the 
favored  school  is  shown  are  given  here  in  the  order  of  the 
amount  of  difference. 

Test  number  17,  absurd  statements,  is  described  by  the 
authors1  of  the  Point  Scale  as  primarily  a  test  for  'logical 
judgment  based  on  imagination,  analysis  and  reasoning.' 

Number  15,  comprehension  of  questions,  tests  ' practical 
judgment  involving  memory  and  imagination.' 

Number  19,  comparison  of  familiar  objects  involves 
f  analysis  and  comparison  of  remembered  objects  and  atten- 
tion.' 

Number  10,  concrete  definitions,  tests  ' ideation  (associa- 
tion) and  analysis.' 

Number  5,  which  shows  the  fifth  greatest  difference 
between  the  two  schools,  consists  of  counting  backward 
from  20  to  i.  Here  the  mental  traits  involved  are  'memory, 
imagination  and  attention.'  Probably  the  reason  for  the 
higher  average  score  in  the  favored  school  is  the  fact  that 
games  involving  counting  backwards  were  played  by  the 
children  of  this  school  and  when  they  were  given  this  test 

1  Point  Scale,  p.  8. 


24  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

they  knew  what  was  expected,  with  little  explanation;  while 
counting  backward  seemed  a  new  process  for  most  of  the 
younger  children  of  the  unfavored  school. 

The  results  of  test  number  19,  abstract  definitions,  would 
probably  have  shown  a  greater  difference  between  the  two 
schools  but  for  the  fact  that  the  average  for  the  unfavored 
school  was  raised  because  a  greater  number  of  unfavored 
children  were  able  to  define  *  charity.'  The  familiarity  with 
this  term  is  easily  understood,  as  charity  in  some  form  is 
extremely  common  in  the  unfavored  district. 

With  the  exception*  of  number  5  it  seems,  then,  that  the 
greatest  difference  in  the  performances  of  the  children  of  the 
two  schools  lies  in  the  tests  involving  primarily  analysis  and 
abstraction.  This  agrees  with  Binet's  analysis  of  the  differ- 
ence between  the  scores  of  the  children  in  the  private  school 
at  Brussels  and  those  from  the  poorer  section  of  Paris.  Binet 
found  the  Belgian  children  superior  in  tests  involving  criti- 
cism, comparison,  abstract  definitions,  absurdities,  or  in  those 
involving  thought  in  the  higher  sense.  He  pointed  out 
that  some  of  these  tests  probably  put  a  premium  on  the 
ready  use  of  language  and  that  the  children  from  the  higher 
social  class  had  the  advantage  in  this  respect. 

The  five  tests  which  show  the  least  difference  between 
the  two  schools  will  now  be  considered.  Number  8,  arranging 
weights,  is  described  as  having  to  do  with  '  kinsesthetic  judg- 
ment, ideation  and  attention.' 

In  number  I,  aesthetic  judgment,  the  difference  between 
the  two  schools  is  also  very  slight.  This  is  described  as 
having  to  do  with  'aesthetic  judgment  involving  perception, 
association  and  analysis.'  As  this  is  probably  the  easiest  of 
all  the  tests,  it  was  seldom  missed  by  either  school,  which 
probably  accounts  for  the  small  difference  in  the  average 
scores. 

'Motor  coordination  and  visual  perception'  are  the  traits 
involved  in  Number  12,  copying  a  square  and  a  diamond. 

Number  3,  comparison  of  lines  and  weights,  tests  Mis- 
crimination'  of  the  visual  type  in  the  first  part  and  of  the 
kinaesthetic  type  in  the  second. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


Number  16,  drawing  of  designs  from  memory,  involves 
'visual  memory,  perception,  attention  and  motor  coordina- 
tion.' 

With  the  exception  of  number  I  the  above  tests  all  involve 
sensory-motor  functions  to  a  great  extent  and  have  to  do 
primarily  with  kinsesthetic  judgment  and  motor  coordination. 

To  summarize:  The  results  from  the  single  tests  show  the 
greatest  difference  in  tests  involving  analysis  and  abstraction 
and  the  least  difference  in  those  involving  primarily  motor 
coordination  and  kinaesthetic  judgment.  This  agrees  with 
Thorndike's  view  that  individuals  differ  least  in  sensory  motor 
functions  and  most  in  analysis  and  abstraction.1 

INDIVIDUAL  SCORES 

The  individual  scores  will  now  be  considered  as  to  the 
number  of  children  who  are  twenty-five  percent  above  or 
below  the  norm  of  their  age,  when  judged  by  the  general 
norm  and  when  judged  by  the  average  of  their  own  school. 
Tables  IV.  and  V.  show  the  individual  scores  by  sex  and  age 
groups  for  each  school.  In  each  group  the  number  of  indi- 
viduals whose  scores  depart  by  twenty-five  percent  or  more 

TABLE  XIV 


No. 

Percent 
of  Total 

Using  general  norm  

Favored  group,  25%  below  the  norm.  .  . 
Favored  group,  25%  above  the  norm.  .  . 

3 
73 

1.8 
44.2 

Unfavored  group,  25%  below  the  norm. 

44 

32.4 

Unfavored  group,  25%  above  the  norm. 

ii 

8.1 

Using  separate  norms  for 

each  school  

Favored  group,  25%  below  the  norm.  .  . 

10 

6.2 

Favored  group,  25%  above  the  norm.  .  . 

10 

6.2 

Unfavored  group,  25%  below  the  norm. 

19 

16.5 

Unfavored  group,  25%  above  the  norm. 

16 

13-9 

from  the  norm  for  that  age  is  indicated.  The  solid  lines 
indicate  the  individuals  who  deviate  twenty-five  percent  or 
more  from  the  general  norm  for  that  age  group.  The  dotted 
lines  indicate  the  number  who  deviate  twenty-five  percent  or 
more  from  their  own  group  norm.  The  exact  numbers  are 
shown  in  convenient  form  in  Table  XIV. 

irrhorndike,  E.  L.,  'Educational  Psychology,'  second  edition,  1910,  pp.  218-223. 


26  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

As  will  be  seen,  nearly  one  third  of  the  children  of  the 
unfavored  school  have  a  coefficient  of  mental  ability  of  .75 
when  judged  by  the  general  norm.  This  has  been  suggested 
by  Dr.  T.  H.  Haines1  as  a  criterion  of  feeble-mindedness. 
He  has  shown  that  it  is  a  more  lenient  criterion  than  four 
years'  retardation  above  the  thirteenth  year.  For  the  ages 
here  considered  it  is  roughly  equal  to  about  two  years'  re- 
tardation. The  number  of  the  favored  group  twenty-five 
percent  or  more  below  the  general  norm  for  their  age  is  only  3. 
On  the  other  hand  the  favored  school  shows  over  44  percent, 
twenty-five  percent  or  more  above  the  norm,  while  the  un- 
favored school  has  only  eight  percent.  If  these  results  are 
compared  with  those  of  Cambridge2  where  practically  the 
same  numbers  are  twenty-five  percent  above  and  below  the 
average,  it  appears  that  the  unfavored  school  is  greatly 
weighted  by  subnormals  and  the  favored  school  by  super- 
normals.  The  question  now  arises  whether  it  is  fair  to  judge 
both  schools  by  the  same  standard.  Let  us  see  what  the 
results  would  show  if  the  unfavored  and  the  favored  schools 
were  judged  by  their  own  norm  or  average.  In  this  case  the 
standard  will  of  course  be  lowered  for  the  unfavored  group 
and  raised  for  the  favored  group.  The  dotted  lines  indicate 
this  in  Tables  IV.  and  V.  The  averages  of  the  pupils  were 
only  used  up  to  and  including  nine  years,  however,  for  beyond 
nine  years  the  scores  were  so  low  and  there  were  so  few  cases 
that  a  fair  average  could  not  be  obtained.  Up  to  the  ten- 
year  group,  then,  the  number  twenty-five  percent  above  and 
below  the  norm  for  each  school  is  about  equal,  as  was  the 
case  in  the  Cambridge  schools. 

Considering  the  great  number  which  must  be  classed  as 
very  inferior  intellectually,  if  not  feeble-minded,  in  the  un- 
favored school  if  the  same  standard  is  used  for  judging  both 
schools,  it  seems  unfair  that  groups  of  children  from  such 
different  social  classes  should  be  judged  by  the  same  norm. 
If  the  sociological  factor  is  not  considered  in  clinical  diagnosis, 
it  seems  probable  that  too  high  a  standard  will  be  expected 

1  Haines,  T.  H.,  'Relative  Values  of  Point  Scale  and  Year  Scale  Measurements 
of  1,000  Minor  Delinquents,'  /.  Exp.  PsychoL,  i,  51-82. 

2  Point  Scale,  p.  55. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS  27 

of  the  unfavored  individuals  and  so  the  degree  of  mental 
deficiency  which  might  exist  would  be  overestimated. 

STUDY  OF  OCCUPATIONS 

The  children  will  now  be  grouped  in  the  two  schools  by 
the  occupation  of  the  father.  The  165  children  in  the 
favored  school  were  classified  as  follows: 

(1)  Professional  group 32 

Professors 17 

Doctors 6 

Lawyers 3 

Editors 3 

Architects 2 

Ministers I 

(2)  Proprietors,  officers  and  managers  of  manufacturies  and  stores 32 

Proprietors 16 

Managers  and  officers 1 1 

Building  contractors 5 

(3)  Traveling  salesmen,  insurance  agents  and  real  estate  dealers 39 

Traveling  salesmen 33 

Salesmen 5 

Insurance  agents 6 

Real  estate  dealers 6 

(4)  Clerical  workers 21 

Clerks 13 

Bookkeepers  and  accountants 5 

Cashiers 3 

(5)  The  remaining  forty-one  children  were  classified  in  a  miscellaneous  group. 

The  main  groups  in  which  the  136  children  of  the  un- 
favored school  were  classified  are  as  follows: 

(1)  Laborers,  unskilled 60 

This  group  includes  odd-job  workers  and  all  unskilled  and  casual  laborers. 

(2)  Skilled  mechanical  trades 45 

Railroad  engineers  and  mechanics 13 

Metal  workers 12 

Building  trades 10 

Electricians 3 

Shoe  cutters 3 

Miscellaneous  skilled  workers 4 

(3)  Teamsters  and  delivery  men 19 

The  remaining  twelve  children  in  the  unfavored  school 
were  put  in  a  miscellaneous  class. 

In  comparing  the  groups  in  the  favored  school,  the  children 
from  one  group  were  matched  with  children  as  nearly  as 


28 


JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 


possible  the  same  age  in  the  other  group.  The  results  are 
here  shown  for  the  professional  group  compared  with  the 
traveling  salesmen.  Thirty  children  from  each  group  were 
matched  in  this  comparison. 


Av.  Chron.  Age 

Av.  Mental  Age 

C.  M.  A. 

Professional  group  
Traveling  salesmen  

7  yr.  7  mo. 
7  yr.  7  mo. 

9  yr.  8  mo. 
9  yr.  3  mo. 

1.42 
1.26 

The  average  chronological  age  is  thus  the  same,  but  the 
professional  group  averages  5  months  superior  to  the  traveling 
salesmen  group  mentally. 

The  clerical  workers  were  rather  a  mixed  group.  Many 
of  the  clerks  were  chief  clerks  and  the  group  as  a  whole  is 
small.  Comparing  seventeen  from  this  group  with  seventeen 
from  the  manager  group  of  corresponding  ages,  the  following 
results  were  obtained. 


Av.  Chron.  Age 

Av.  Mental  Age 

C.  M.  A. 

Clerical             .              

7  yr.  10  mo. 

9  yr.  i  mo. 

1.22 

Managing  class  

7  yr.    8  mo. 

9  yr.  5  mo. 

1.24 

The  managing  class  averages  two  months  younger 
chronologically,  but  shows  about  four  months'  superiority 
mentally. 

In  the  unfavored  school  thirty-six  children  were  matched 
from  the  skilled  and  unskilled  laboring  classes. 


Av.  Chron.  Age 

Av.  Mental  Age 

C.  M.A. 

Skilled    . 

7  yr.  1  1  mo. 

7vr.    6  mo 

Q7 

Unskilled 

8  yr.    I  mo. 

6  yr  1  1  mo 

8O 

The  unskilled  group  here  has  the  advantage  of  being  two 
months  older;  nevertheless  its  average  mental  age  is  seven 
months  less  and  its  coefficient  of  mental  ability  .13  less  than 
the  average  for  the  skilled  group. 

When  a  group  was  selected  from  laborers  to  match  the 
ages  of  the  eighteen  children  in  the  teamster  group,  the 
following  results  were  obtained. 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS 


29 


Av.  Chron.  Age 

Av.  Mental  Age 

C.  M.  A. 

Teamsters  

7  yr.  10  mo. 

7  yr< 

.83 

Unskilled  laborers  

7  yr.  10  mo. 

7  yr.  2  mo. 

.88 

The  teamsters  appear  to  have  as  a  class  an  even  lower 
mentality  than  the  unskilled  laborers,  but  this  is  a  very  small 
group  and  results  might  be  different  if  larger  numbers  were 
compared. 

The  following  is  a  summary  of  the  results  for  the  various 
occupation  groups,  irrespective  of  schools  and  ages: 


No. 

Av.  Chron.  Age 

Av.  Mental  Age 

C.  M.  A. 

Professional 

•J2 

7yr.    3  mo. 

9  yr.    8  mo. 

1.4.2 

Traveling  salesmen  
Proprietors,  etc  

39 
34 

7  yr.    6  mo. 
7  yr.  10  mo. 

9  yr.    2  mo. 
9  yr.    I  mo. 

J.26 
1  .21 

Skilled 

6<? 

8  vr 

7  yr   10  mo 

I  12 

Unskilled  

60 

v   yt, 

8  yr. 

7  yr.  i  mo. 

.83 

It  is  noteworthy  in  this  table  that  although  the  chrono- 
logical age  increases  from  group  to  group,  the  mental  age 
decreases. 

CONCLUSIONS 

Our  results  corroborate  the  conclusions  of  Binet  in  France, 
Hoffman  in  Germany  and  Yerkes  et  al.  in  United  States  that 
there  is  a  very  considerable  dependence  of  intelligence  upon 
sociological  condition.  We  have  further  shown  that  when 
children  are  classified  according  to  the  occupations  of  their 
fathers,  a  striking  correlation  is  shown  between  intelligence 
quotient  and  occupation  group.  Hence,  if  mental  age  rather 
than  chronological  age  were  used  to  determine  the  time  for 
beginning  school,  the  children  of  the  professional  group,  for 
example,  would  begin  school  two  years  earlier  than  the  child- 
ren of  the  unskilled  labor  group;  for  the  former  mature 
intellectually  much  earlier  than  the  latter. 

Incidentally  the  results  have  shown  that  the  correlation 
of  intelligence  and  social  status  is  probably  higher  for  boys 
than  for  girls.  The  girls  of  the  poorer  school  are  considerably 
superior  to  the  boys;  but  the  boys  of  the  better  school  are 
only  at  one  age  noticeably  superior  to  the  girls. 


30  JAMES  W.  BRIDGES  AND  LILLIAN  E.  COLER 

The  superiority  of  the  better  classes  is  most  evident  in 
tests  that  involve  higher  mental  processes  like  analysis  and 
abstraction;  but  it  is  also  shown  to  a  lesser  extent  in  sensory 
motor  functions. 

We  have  not  discussed  the  causes  of  this  relation  of 
intelligence  to  social  status  for  the  very  good  reason  that 
our  data  do  not  contribute  anything  towards  a  solution  of 
the  problem.  They  aim  merely  to  establish  the  fact  and 
amount  of  the  difference,  and  could  be  used  by  adherents  of 
the  "Environment  Theory"  as  well  as  by  advocates  of 
"Inheritance."  Thus,  the  former  could  emphasize  the 
quite  evident  differences  in  home  and  school  environments, 
teaching  staff,  etc.;  while  the  latter  would  point  to  the  just 
as  evident  differences  in  the  character  and  intelligence  of  the 
parents.  It  is  worth  noting  that  in  the  few  cases  where  the 
mothers  were  tested,  they  showed  a  mental  age  about  equiva- 
lent to  that  of  their  children.  If  intelligence  quotient  could 
be  obtained  for  a  number  of  successive  generations  with 
different  environments,  such  data  might  contribute  to  a 
solution  of  the  problem. 

We  have  also  omitted  discussion  of  the  percentage  of 
feeble-minded  in  the  different  social  groups,  and  have  con- 
cerned ourselves  only  with  the  variations  in  intelligence;  for 
we  consider  the  diagnosis  of  feeble-mindedness  and  the 
measurement  of  intelligence  two  quite  distinct  though  re- 
lated problems  that  had  better  not  be  confused.  Diagnosis 
depends  upon  a  number  of  other  considerations  as  well  as 
the  psychological.  The  physical  aspect  can  not  be  wholly 
neglected;  and  the  importance  of  the  patient's  life  history  is 
generally  acknowledged,  especially  if  amentia  is  to  be  dis- 
tinguished from  dementia. 

There  are  also  sociological  considerations  which  the  advo- 
cates of  a  purely  psychological  concept  of  feeble-mindedness 
must  acknowledge  as  soon  as  they  consider  the  problem  of 
the  dividing  line  between  normal  and  feeble-minded  intelli- 
gence. The  various  criteria:  two  to  four  years'  retardation, 
an  intelligence  quotient  below  .75,  the  *  lowest  three  percent' 


INTELLIGENCE  AND  SOCIAL  STATUS  31 

of  the  population,1  etc.,  are  all  ultimately  based  upon  socio- 
logical, or  socio-legal  considerations.  They  are  merely 
statements  of  the  limits  below  which  an  individual  fails  to 
attain  certain  social  standards  of  living. 

Now,  since  these  standards  of  living  vary  greatly  from 
group  to  group,  it  seems  only  reasonable  that  the  above 
mentioned  limits  (and  intelligence  norms)  used  in  diagnosis 
should  vary  too.  Otherwise,  we  might  be  obliged  to  classify 
whole  races  as  feeble-minded.  All  Hottentots  would  prob- 
ably be  feeble-minded,  if  judged  by  Anglo-Saxon  intelligence 
norms;  and  similarly  the  majority  of  the  children  of  the 
unskilled  labor  group  might  be  classed  feeble-minded  if 
judged  by  norms  for  the  professional  group.  The  facts 
discussed  in  this  paper  should  therefore  find  a  place  among 
the  various  considerations  upon  which  careful  diagnosis 
depends;  but  we  have  preferred  to  confine  ourselves  to  the 
strictly  psychological  problem:  the  measurement  of  the 
intelligence  of  different  social  groups. 

1  Pintner,  R.  and  Paterson,  D.  G.,  'A  Psychological  Basis  for  the  Diagnosis  of 
Feeble-mindedness,'  /.  of  Crim.  Law  and  Crim.,  7,  May,  1916. 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS  AND 
AUSTRALIAN  ABORIGINAL  CHILDREN 

BY  S.  D.  PORTEUS 

School  for  Mental  Defectives,  Fitzroy,  Australia 

During  1915  two  groups  of  delinquent  boys  were  ex- 
amined by  a  new  series  of  mental  tests.1  The  first  group 
consisted  of  boys  ranging  in  age  from  nine  to  fourteen  years 
who  had  been  committed  to  the  care  of  the  Boys'  Home  at 
Burwood,  Victoria.  Some  few  were  merely  neglected  chil- 
dren but  the  majority  had  been  before  the  children's  courts 
for  various  minor  offences,  chiefly  truancy  and  petty  thieving. 
Under  ordinary  environment  these  may  be  considered  crimi- 
nals in  the  making. 

The  tests  given  are  based  on  the  maze  plan  and  the 
subject  is  required  to  find  a  way  through  the  maze  in  a  given 
number  of  trials  under  certain  conditions.2  Success  requires 
the  exercise  of  prudence  in  action,  forethought,  and  general 
mental  alertness.  The  tests  are  graded  for  the  mental  ages 
from  three  to  thirteen  years.  It  is  not  claimed  that  they 
enable  us  to  arrive  at  the  general  mental  age  of  the  subject, 
though  in  the  majority  of  cases  there  is  a  close  correlation 
between  results  by  these  tests  and  by  the  Binet-Simon. 
In  another  investigation,  out  of  one  thousand  normal  children 
examined  70.6  percent  passed  by  these  tests  within  one  year 
of  their  Binet  ages. 

Mental  age  per  the  Porteus  tests  means  that,  in  the  capaci- 
ties of  foresight,  prudence,  resistance  to  suggestion,  and  sustain- 
ing the  attention,  the  child  has  reached  the  average  develop- 
ment of  the  age  assigned  to  the  tests  passed  under  the  given 
conditions.  Children  below  ten  years  of  age  are  most  often 
placed  about  one  year  higher  in  mental  age  by  the  Porteus 
tests  than  by  the  Binet.  This  difference  is  accounted  for 

1  Tests  published  by  C.  H.  Stoelting  Co.,  Chicago. 

2  See  /.  of  Exp.  Fed.,  June,  1915,  or  Amer.  J.  of  Psycho-Asthenics,  June,  1915. 

32 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS  33 

mainly  by  the  fact  that  the  former  are  motor  tests  and 
therefore  make  a  more  universal  appeal  to  child  interest  and 
secondly  because  they  were  arranged  so  as  to  permit  of  a 
comparison  between  the  mentally  deficient  and  the  dull 
normal  child.  This  explanation  is  necessary  to  meet  the 
possible  objection  that  the  tests  were  too  difficult. 

Since  impulsive  and  ill-considered  action  had  been  char- 
acteristic of  the  delinquent  boys'  social  behavior  it  was 
thought  likely  that  their  performances  in  the  tests  would 
reflect  to  some  degree  the  same  faults  of  disposition.  How 
this  expectation  was  fulfilled  may  be  seen  by  reference  to 
Table  I.  below.  In  some  cases  where  foresight  was  shown  in 
the  subject's  preliminary  study  of  the  problem  before  be- 
ginning its  working,  failure  resulted  through  a  too  imprudent 
trust  in  the  memory.  Not  a  few  looked  at  the  maze  before 
beginning  the  test  and  remarked  "I  see  the  way  out,"  and 
then  went  impulsively  to  work  only  to  find  that  they  had 
lost  the  plan  and  had  taken  a  wrong  turning,  which,  of 
course,  meant  instant  failure,  since  corrections  are  not 
allowed.  It  was  very  rare  indeed  to  find  a  child  with  the 
most  intelligent  method  of  attack,  viz.,  a  preliminary  sizing 
up  of  the  problem  and  then  a  careful  and  deliberative  work- 
ing— prudence  and  forethought  in  combination. 

The  following  is  a  summary  of  the  scores  of  the  boys  in 
the  tests  as  compared  with  their  chronological  ages. 

TABLE  I 

Passed  Test 

Above  age o 

At  age 5 

1  year  below  chron.  age 3 

2  years     "          "        "  5 

3  years  "        "  5 

4  years  "   3 

5  years      "          "        "   j_ 

Total 22 

Average  chronological  age 12  years  8  months 

Average  test  passed 10     "     4       " 

Average  deficiency 2     "     4       " 

It  is  significant  that  no  boy  passed  a  test  above  his 
chronological  age  while  less  than  25  per  cent,  passed  'at  age.' 


34 


S.  D.  PORTEUS 


In  Table  II.  some  interesting  individual  records  are  given 
together  with  a  brief  report  by  the  superintendent  of  the 
Home  as  to  each  boy's  character. 

Those  in  whose  personal  reports  there  is  a  favorable 
entry  are  placed  in  Section  A.  Those  whose  social  disposi- 
tions are  not  satisfactory  are  shown  in  Section  B. 

TABLE  II 

SECTION  A 


Case 

Chron.  Age 

Test  Passed 

Deficiency 

Superintendent's  Report 

CD. 

II  yrs. 

10  yrs. 

I  yr. 

Quick  wilted,  fairly  reliable,  and 

moderately  intelligent. 

G.T. 

12*  yrs. 

12^  yrs. 

— 

Truant,    good    open    disposition 

fairly  intelligent,  conduct  good. 

A.  A. 

II  yrs.  9  mos. 

12  yrs. 

— 

Fairly   intelligent,   good   disposi- 

tion. 

E.  S. 

ii  yrs. 

iify-re. 

— 

Rather  dull,  but  improving  won- 

derfully. 

W.  G. 

13  yrs. 

12^  yrs. 

lyr- 

Splendid  memory,  intelligent  for 

his  age. 

C.  C. 

12  yrs. 

115  yrs. 

£yr. 

Truant.      Conduct    good,    fairly 

intelligent. 

N.  S. 

12  yrs.  10  mos. 

ii  yrs. 

i*  yrs. 

Truant,  easily  led.    Quiet  dispo- 

sition, fairly  intelligent.    Con- 

duct now  good. 

SECTION  B 

J.D. 

14  yrs. 

II  yrs. 

3  yrs. 

Associated  with  bad  companions. 

Habit  of  petty  thieving. 

J.R. 

I2i  yrs. 

8  yrs. 

4i  yrs. 

Illegitimate.         Rather   untrust- 

worthy and  dull. 

P.M. 

13!  yrs. 

9  yrs. 

4!  yrs. 

Truant.       Fairly  intelligent  but 

of  a  sly  disposition. 

R.  F. 

u|  yrs. 

9  yrs. 

2*  yrs. 

Petty  thief.      Rather  sullen  dis- 

position. 

W.  P. 

niyrs. 

9  yrs. 

2\  yrs. 

Neglected  at  home.       Fairly  in- 

telligent but  sly  disposition. 

C.J. 

12  yrs. 

10  yrs. 

2  yrs. 

A  truant  and  of  plausible  dispo- 

sition.       Fairly   advanced   in 

school. 

It  will  be  seen  that  the  tests  have  brought  out  to  a  rather 
remarkable  degree  the  differences  in  character  in  the  boys 
of  the  two  groups.  The  total  deficiency  by  the  tests  is  for 
Section  A — 3^  years;  for  Section  B — 19  years.  This  accounts 
for  13  boys  out  of  22.  In  the  remaining  nine  cases  there  is 
nothing  noteworthy  in  the  superintendent's  reports  other 
than  the  references  to  their  intelligence. 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS 


35 


It  should  be  stated  that  these  personal  reports  must  be 
considered  thoroughly  independent.  None  of  the  results 
of  the  testing  were  known  to  the  superintendent  at  the  time 
the  reports  were  furnished. 

REFORMATORY  BOYS 

The  next  investigation  was  undertaken  at  the  Royal 
Park  Reformatory,  Melbourne.  In  the  light  of  their  records 
the  subjects  must  be  considered  as  youthful  criminals. 
Table  III.  summarizes  their  results  and  speaks  for  itself. 

TABLE  III 


Passed  Test 
At  aee                                                                     o 

2  years  be' 
3  years 
4  years 
5  years 
6  years 
7  years 
8  years 
Total 

ow  chr 

on.  aj 

>e*.  .                                  .2 

•i 

4 

3 
5 

2 

i 

.  .20 

Average  chronological  age 15  years^6  months. 


10 


Average  test  passed 9 

Average  deficiency 5      {<      g       " 

Note. — In  this  table  15  years  was  taken  as  the  upper  limit  of  chronological  age 

so  as  to  provide  a  basis  of  comparison  with  the  mental  age.     As  a  matter  of  fact  the 

average  age  will  be  seen  to  have  been  above  15  years. 

By  comparison  with  Table  I.  it  will  be  seen  that,  though 
the  average  age  of  the  Reformatory  boys  was  higher  than 
that  of  the  boys  at  the  Home,  they  passed  on  the  average  a 
lower  test.  Some  of  the  individual  records  are  so  interesting 
that  I  may  be  pardoned  for  giving  some  details. 

Some  of  the  offences  charged  against  these  lads  were 
house-breaking  (6) ;  serious  assault  (causing  grievous  bodily 
harm)  (3);  larceny  (7);  obscene  language  (i);  street  gambling 
(i);  obtaining  money  under  false  pretences  (i);  murder  (i). 
The  numbers  in  brackets  here  indicate  the  number  of  such 
offences. 

The  housebreakers  showed  on  the  whole  better  success 
in  the  tests  than  the  others,  the  mental  ages  of  the  six  being 


36  S.  D.  PORTEUS 

12,  ii,  ii,  ii,  10  and  8  years  respectively,  whilst  their  total 
deficiency  amounted  to  23!  years.  Those  who  had  been 
convicted  of  serious  assaults  had  the  mental  ages  of  n,  9,  and 

8  years  respectively,  whilst  the  murderer's  mental  age  was 

9  years.     Those  four,  however,  who  had  committed  crimes  of 
violence  had  a  total  deficiency  of  23   years,  an  average  of 
5!  years  as  against  the  average  of  4  years  for  the  house- 
breakers.    It  would   seem   as   if  the   more   talented   in   this 
group  of  youthful  criminals  were  already  qualifying  for  a 
place  in  the  aristocracy  of  crime,  the  skilled  burglars.     The 
clumsy  insensate  crimes  of  violence  were  left  to  boys  of  a 
much   lower   mental   level.     Three   of   the   four   mentioned 
above  were   sentenced  for  kicking  a   companion   nearly  to 
death.     The  murderer  had  decapitated  his  victim  with  an 
axe  when  they  were  returning  from  a  joint  hunting  expedition. 

It  is  most  significant  that  only  four  of  this  group  of  20 
lads  were  suspected  by  the  penal  authorities  to  be  at  all 
deficient  mentally.  Among  these  was  the  murderer.  But 
the  point  that  should  be  emphasized  is  that  there  were  other 
lads  of  a  lower  mental  level  who  were  considered  fully 
responsible.  When  they  have  committed  equally  atrocious 
.crimes,  their  mental  deficiency  too  may  be  realized. 

Provided  that  the  offenders  show  an  amount  of  low 
cunning  in  the  commission  of  their  crimes  the  police  appear 
very  loath  to  admit  the  fact  of  mental  deficiency.  An  inter- 
esting instance  of  this  was  the  case  of  S.  B.,  aged  15^  years, 
examined  by  me  at  the  Melbourne  Gaol.  He  had  been 
committed  for  stealing  letters  during  their  transit  from  the 
post  office  to  the  city  railway  station.  His  plan  was  to 
represent  himself  to  the  driver  of  the  mail  van  as  an  em- 
ployee of  the  post  office,  sit  at  the  back  of  the  van,  cut  open 
the  mail  bags  and  abstract  the  contents.  The  police  appeared 
very  loath  to  agree  to  a  theory  of  mental  deficiency  in  his  case 
and  he  was  examined. 

The  highest  test  that  he  could  pass  in  the  Porteus  series 
was  that  for  8  years  and  he  required  the  two  trials  allowed 
for  tests  for  6  and  7  years.  When  examined  per  the  Binet, 
his  mental  age  was  also  eight  years.  He  failed  to  tell  the 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS  37 

differences  between  a  butterfly  and  fly,  etc.,  he  could  not 
reckon  the  value  of  the  stamps  nor  repeat  five  numerals 
correctly.  In  the  nine  year  tests  he  could  not  give  change 
nor  arrange  the  weights  and  he  failed  in  ten  year  tests  through- 
out. 

The  dynamometer  records  were  17  kilos  right  hand  and 
10  kilos  left  hand — very  low  for  a  youth  of  16  years  of  age. 
In  the  Fernald-Healy  construction  test  he  required  two 
minutes  thirty  seconds. 

The  diagnosis  of  feeble-mindedness  was,  by  the  foregoing 
results,  indisputable.1 

ABORIGINAL  CHILDREN 

For  comparison  with  the  delinquent  groups  I  am  taking 
the  examination  results  of  some  aboriginal  children  examined 
by  myself  at  the  Mission  Station,  Point  MacLeay,  South 
Australia. 

Few  of  them  were  full-blooded,  though  in  many  cases 
they  were  the  offspring  of  marriages  between  full-blooded 
aborigines  and  half  castes.  Results  are  summarized  in 
Table  IV. 

TABLE  IV 

Passed  Test 

3  years  above  chron.  age I 

2  years      "          "        "  I 

i  year       "          "        "  4 

At  age 12 

1  year   below  chron.  age 7 

2  years      "          "        "   I 

3  years      "          "        "  _2 

Total 28 

Average  age 10  years  2  months 

Average  test  passed 9     "     9       " 

Average  deficiency 5       " 

1  Since  writing  this  article,  I  have  learned  that  this  boy  was  examined  by  a  medical 
officer  at  the  gaol.  He  was  found  to  be  syphilitic  but  the  equally  important  fact  of 
his  mental  deficiency  was  unnoticed  by  the  doctor,  or  was,  at  any  rate,  unmentioned! 
This  implies  either  carelessness  in  examination  or  ignorance  of  modern  methods  of 
psychological  examination.  The  question  of  the  lad's  mental  and  moral  responsibility 
was  not  raised  at  the  trial  and  he  was  sentenced  to  two  years'  imprisonment.  The 
diagnosis  of  deficiency  was  not  disputed  but  ignored. 


38  5.  D.  PORTE  US 

On  examining  the  individual  records  it  was  found  that 
the  younger  children  succeeded,  relatively,  far  better  than 
the  older  ones.  Of  12  children  who  were  over  n  years  of 
age,  9  are  retarded  by  the  tests,  the  total  deficiency  being 
16  years.  Of  the  16  children  under  n  years  of  age,  6  passed 
tests  above  their  chronological  age,  9  passed  'at  age'  and 
I  was  retarded  one  year. 

The  increased  difficulty  of  the  tests  for  the  upper  years 
is  not  sufficient  to  explain  this  failure  of  the  older  children. 
This  result  bears  out  the  view  that  the  period  of  mental 
development  is,  in  aboriginal  children,  comparatively  short. 
This  also  accords  with  the  experience  of  the  teacher  of  the 
school,  who  says  that  he  finds  little  difficulty  in  bringing  his 
pupils  through  the  lower  grades  but  finds  it  very  difficult 
indeed  to  educate  them  beyond  about  the  fourth  grade,  or 
midway  through  the  school  course. 

Dr.  Gertrude  Halley,  chief  schools'  medical  officer,  who 
examined  these  children  physically  found  them  well  de- 
veloped for  their  ages,  weight  and  height  being  above  the 
average.  Puberty  appeared  to  be  rather  early  established. 
The  prepubescent  period  seems  to  be  the  most  favorable  for 
mental  development,  but  is  succeeded  during  early  adoles- 
cence by  a  period  in  which  the  common  racial  characteristics 
of  indolence,  shiftlessness,  and  lack  of  foresight  become 
apparent.  This  view  was  strengthened  by  the  results  of 
the  tests.  It  would  be  interesting  to  discover  by  continuing 
the  tests  whether  the  white  race's  superiority  over  the 
aboriginal  is  mainly  due  to  the  shorter  period  of  mental 
development  in  the  latter,  force  of  heredity  in  the  white 
enabling  him  better  to  withstand  the  physical  strain  associ- 
ated with  the  onset  of  adolescence,  and  allowing  mental 
development  to  proceed  equally  with  that  of  the  body. 

By  comparing  Tables  I.,  III.  and  IV.  it  will  be  seen  that 
relatively  speaking,  the  aboriginal  children  passed  far  better 
than  the  Reformatory  boys  and  considerably  better  than  the 
boys  of  Section  B  of  Table  II.  By  the  use  of  these  tests  and 
of  similar  ones  which  no  doubt  will  soon  be  developed,  it  is 
hoped  that  we  may  reach  a  stage  when  we  can  definitely  state 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS  39 

by  means  of  an  examination  that  a  child  is  abnormal  not 
only  in  intelligence  but  in  disposition  and  that  he  thus  lacks 
the  potentialities  of  good  character  forming.  If,  in  addition, 
psychological  tests  will  enable  us  even  approximately  to 
assess  the  importance  of  these  deficiencies  in  their  bearing 
on  conduct,  then  we  will  have  achieved  a  decided  step  forward 
towards  the  ideal  of  making  training  and  education  ensure 
the  conservation  of  the  child. 

APPLICATION   OF  TESTS  TO    DEAF   CHILDREN 

Interesting  results  were  obtained  by  the  application  of  the 
tests  to  the  children  at  the  school  for  deaf  and  dumb,  Mel- 
bourne. 

For  children  above  nine  years  of  age  the  plan  adopted 
was  to  illustrate  the  working  of  the  six  and  seven  year  tests, 
the  subjects  beginning  with  the  test  for  eight  years.  It  was 
rarely  found  necessary  to  make  any  further  explanations  or 
to  give  further  instructions. 

On  the  whole,  the  deaf  children  found  the  tests  somewhat 
difficult.  Temperamental  peculiarities  were  often  apparent. 
In  some  cases  the  subjects  gave  up  the  task,  signing  that  it 
was  beyond  their  powers.  Very  many  showed  extremely 
quick  perceptions,  and  worked  the  tests  at  a  great  pace  with 
a  resultant  tendency  to  error  through  impulsiveness.  Gen- 
erally they  were  very  quick  to  notice  their  errors.  A  fairly 
large  proportion  were  definitely  feeble-minded,  and  a  number, 
judged  by  ordinary  standards,  must  be  considered  dull.  In 
every  case  in  which  the  tests  showed  the  child  to  be  feeble- 
minded the  teacher's  judgment  concurred.  As  regards  the 
boys,  there  was  a  close  agreement  between  the  teachers' 
estimates  of  intelligence  and  the  verdict  of  the  tests.  That 
is  to  say  that  the  tests,  considered  as  intelligence  tests,  were 
satisfactory.  In  the  case  of  the  girls,  however,  the  agree- 
ment was  not  so  close,  many  failing  to  reach  the  standard 
that  the  teachers  expected. 

This  partial  failure  of  the  tests  may  be  explained  in  two 
ways.  The  first  explanation  is  that  girls  on  the  whole  do 
not  test  as  high  as  the  boys.  Five  hundred  and  eight  girls 


40  S.  D.  PORTEUS 

(normals)  were  tested  in  a  recent  investigation  and  their 
Binet  ages  compared  with  their  ages  per  my  tests.  By  the 
latter,  36  percent  tested  above  their  Binet  age  whilst  43 
percent  tested  below,  the  remaining  20  percent  testing  the 
same.  For  492  boys  the  corresponding  figures  were:  Above 
the  Binet  =  44  percent;  Below,  =  40  percent;  Same,  =15 
percent. 

It  will  be  seen  that  girls  test,  on  the  average,  lower  than 
boys.  This  is  probably  due  to  greater  impulsiveness  and  to 
a  lesser  development  of  foresight  in  girls  than  in  boys. 

The  second  factor  influencing  results  is  that  the  training 
of  the  boys  at  the  school  tends  to  accentuate  the  above- 
mentioned  sex  differences.  Organized  games  and  sport 
generally  are  made  a  special  feature  of  the  boys'  training  at 
the  school.  This  is  not  the  case  with  the  girls.  Undoubtedly 
the  effect  of  this  training  on  the  boys  is  to  make  them  more 
self-reliant,  resourceful,  and  more  mentally  alert  than  the 
girls.  It  was  noticed  that  the  boys  who  played  best,  scored, 
as  a  rule,  highest  in  the  tests. 

Notwithstanding  the  foregoing  objections,  I  am  convinced 
that  the  tests  do  enable  us  to  make  a  useful  estimate,  within 
fairly  correct  limits,  of  the  deaf  child's  native  intelligence. 
They  certainly  allow  him  to  display  his  ability  in  a  much 
fairer  light  than  any  other  tests  do.  Even  if  the  Binet  test 
is  adapted  to  the  deaf  child's  examination,  it  remains,  princi- 
pally, a  language  test,  a  test  of  comprehension.  It  must  be 
admitted,  however,  that  the  successful  application  of  the 
Porteus  tests  depends  on  the  subject's  thorough  under- 
standing of  what  is  required  of  him.  Once  this  understanding 
is  gained  the  application  is  easy. 

The  dynamometer  records  were  also  taken.  The  right- 
hand  and  left-hand  grips  were  added  together  and  the  rank- 
ing of  the  children  in  the  tests  and  their  ranking  in  individual 
grip  records  were  correlated  by  the  Spearman  Footrule 
method. 

The  correlation  was: 

R  =  0.65  (Boys), 
R  =  0.66  (Girls). 


MENTAL  TESTS  WITH  DELINQUENTS 


41 


Considering  the  dissimilarity  existing  between  motor  intelli- 
gence tests  of  a  merely  physical  measurement,  such  as  power 
of  grip,  I  think  this  correlation  may  be  considered  fairly 
high.  A  noticeable  feature  was  the  large  number  of  cases  in 
which  the  grip  of  one  hand  approximated  the  grip  of  the 
other. 

INDIVIDUAL  RECORDS:  DEAF  AND  DUMB  CHILDREN 
Section  A 


Case 
No. 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

Case 

No. 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

R. 

L. 

Total 

R. 

L. 

Total 

I 

I72/12 

13 

47 

48 

95 

19 

9Vl2 

9 

21 

21 

42 

2 

I7Vl2 

13 

45 

48 

93 

20 

H7/12 

12 

20 

17 

37 

3 
4 

12 
12 

46 
43 

43 
44 

89 
87 

21 

22 

I010/12 
98/12 

10 
10 

18 
20 

18 
16 

36 
36 

Is1/!! 

13 

40 

37 

77 

23 

83/12 

IO 

17 

16 

33 

6 

l610/12 

13 

38 

36 

74 

24 

II4/12 

II 

17 

16 

33 

7 

i7g 

II 

32 

42 

74 

910/12 

8 

16 

16 

32 

8 

II 

37 

36 

73 

26 

H10/12 

8 

17 

IS 

32 

9 

5710/i2 

12 

33 

38 

71 

27 

I08/12 

ii 

14 

14 

28 

10 

II 

32 

37 

69 

28 

I22/12 

9 

14 

13 

27 

ii 

I58A2 

II6/12 

35 

33 

68 

29 

I09/12 

10 

13 

12 

25 

12 

l610/l2 

II6/12 

34 

31 

65 

30 

88/12 

ii 

13 

12 

25 

13 

I55/12 

13 

26 

28 

54 

31 

9 

9 

13 

IO 

23 

14 

I25/12 

10 

26 

24 

So 

34 

I010/12 

10 

10 

II 

21 

15 

l61/i2 

13 

26 

23 

49 

35 

73/i2 

8 

II 

10 

21 

10 

13/12 

12 

23 

21 

44 

36 

6U/12 

7 

8 

7 

IS 

17 

I36/12 

II 

20 

23 

43 

37 

62/12 

7 

7 

8 

IS 

18 

I29/12 

12 

23 

20 

43 

38 

65/12 

66/12 

5 

7 

12 

Section  B 
Mentally  Deficient 


Case 

No. 

I 

2 

3 
4 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

Case 

No. 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

R. 

L. 

Total 

R. 

L. 

Total 

ltf/12 
I410/12 
19 
I5U/12 

H4/i2 

I33/12 

10 

9 

II 
IO 

8 
9 

35 
31 

23 
25 
19 
19 

28 
26 
27 
24 
20 
20 

63 

57 
So 
49 
39 
39 

8 
9 

IO 

II 

12 

H2/12 
H 
95/12 

II'/ll 

H3/12 
88/12 

8 

\ 

7 
7 
4 

11 

12 
II 

9 
5 

13 
10 

14 
10 

9 

5 

26 
26 
26 
21 

18 

10 

A  close  approach  to  ambidexterity  appeared  in  about 
sixty  percent  of  cases,  a  difference  of  less  than  four  kilos. 
in  strength  in  each  hand  appearing  in  that  proportion.  In 
this  particular  the  deaf  appear  to  resemble  closely  the  men- 
tally deficient,  a  recent  investigation  by  the  author  amongst 
feeble-minded  revealing  a  similar  condition.  It  may  be  said 


42 


S.  D.  PORTEUS 


of  the  latter  that  they  are  generally  equally  weak  in  each 
hand,  while  of  the  normal  deaf  it  may  be  said  that  they  are, 
generally  speaking,  equally  strong  in  each  hand. 

In  the  following  summary  the  normal  boys'  results  have 
been  separated  from  those  of  the  boys  who  were  considered 
feeble-minded.  In  the  table  showing  individual  records  the 
figures  for  the  latter  are  given  in  Section  B. 

TABLE  V. 

NORMAL  BOYS 

Average  age i27/i2  years 

Average  test  passed io7/i2  years 

Average  deficiency 2       years 

FEEBLEMINDED  BOYS 

Average  age i32/i2  years 

Average  test  passed 8       years 

Average  deficiency S2/i2  years 

GIRLS 

Average  age I  !6/i2  years 

Average  test  passed 9B/i2  years 

Average  deficiency 2l/n  years 

INDIVIDUAL  RECORDS:  GIRLS 


Case 
No. 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

Case 

No. 

Actual 
Age 

Age  per 
Test 

Dynamometer 

R. 

L. 

Total 

R. 

L. 

Total 

I 

I45/12 

10 

34 

26 

60 

15 

I2Vi2 

9 

16 

13 

29 

2 

I310/12 

II 

26 

25 

SI 

16 

U8/12 

10 

IS 

13 

28 

3 

I34/12 

12 

25 

23 

48 

17 

98/i2 

10 

IS 

12 

27 

4 

I25/12 

IO 

25 

23 

48 

18 

I28/12 

8 

14 

13 

27 

I76/12 

12 

24 

23 

47 

19 

I210/ll 

ii 

13 

12 

25 

6 

IS10/12 

II 

25 

21 

46 

20 

82/12 

8 

13 

10 

23 

7 

13 

13 

22 

2O 

42 

21 

8«/u 

8 

10 

9 

19 

8 

I35/!2 

9 

21 

19 

40 

22 

6»/ii 

6 

10 

9 

19 

9 

I3u/i2 

ii 

20 

18 

38 

23 

7Vl2 

6 

IO 

9 

19 

10 

I29/12 

12 

18 

19 

37 

24 

9Vl2 

7 

12 

6 

18 

ii 

I3Vl2 

II 

20 

IS 

35 

25 

64/12 

6 

8 

8 

16 

12 

I2Vl2 

10 

18 

14 

32 

26 

SVu 

5 

6 

6 

12 

13 

I59/12 

9 

16 

16 

32 

27 

73/12 

86/12 

ii 

ii 

22 

14 

I310/i2 

ii 

18 

13 

3i 

In  each  of  the  above  investigations  the  number  of  indi- 
viduals examined  is  certainly  small.  The  results  are  reported 
in  order  to  show  the  applicability  of  the  tests  to  abnormal 
children  generally.  Results  with  mentally  deficient  and  with 
normal  children  have  been  elsewhere  reported. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS 

BY  E.  B.  TITCHENER 

In  1913  C.  A.  Britz  published  a  thesis  for  the  Zurich 
doctorate  entitled  Eine  theoretische  und  experimentelle  Unter- 
suchung  uber  den  psychologischen  Begriff  der  Klarheit.  Cir- 
cumstances over  which  I  have  no  control  postponed  my 
first-hand  acquaintance  with  the  work  to  1916.  I  have  re- 
gretted this  the  more  because  Britz  deals  in  detail  with  two 
psychological  systems  in  which  the  notion  of  clearness  holds 
a  prominent  place,  Wundt's  and  my  own.  Wundt  he  chose 
for  obvious  reasons;  myself,  because  my  'Standpunkt  stellt 
quasi  ein  Extrem  dar.'  Both  of  us  receive  a  severe  mauling: 
which  would  be  wholesome  enough — since  the  criticism  is 
objective  and  based  upon  quotation — if  only  Britz  had  fol- 
lowed a  sound  method.  He  has  not.  He  struggles  with  the 
Wundtian  concepts  of  clearness  and  degree  of  consciousness 
on  the  basis  of  the  sixth  edition  of  the  '  Physiologische  Psy- 
chologic' and  the  seventh  of  the  'Grundriss';  and  it  never 
occurs  to  him  that  the  key  to  their  understanding  is  a  genetic 
study  of  his  author.  He  attacks  my  concept  of  sensory 
clearness  on  the  basis  of  my  'Text-book'  and  of  Hillebrand's 
review  of  my  ' Feeling  and  Attention'  in  the  Zeitschrift;  he 
has  not  referred,  incredible  as  the  thing  appears,  to  the 
Feeling  and  Attention  itself. 

External  circumstances  may  be  in  part  responsible.  The 
thesis  was  undertaken  at  Schumann's  suggestion,  and  the 
experimental  portion  was  apparently  completed  under  his 
direction  at  Frankfurt.  The  author,  however,  returned  for 
his  doctorate  to  his  old  university,  and  the  thesis  was  accepted 
by  G.  F.  Lipps  of  Zurich.  It  is  a  fair  assumption  (is  it  not?) 
that  Schumann  was  chiefly  interested  in  the  experiments, 
and  that  Lipps  was  generously  disposed  to  a  bit  of  work 
originated  and  approved  by  a  psychological  colleague  else- 
where. In  that  case  the  critical  chapters,  about  seventy  per- 

43 


44  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

cent  of  the  whole  paper,  would  have  fallen,  so  to  say,  between 
the  two  professorial  chairs.  Even  so  it  is  astonishing  that 
Britz  should  not  have  learned  for  himself  the  essentials  of 
scientific  method. 

I 

I  do  not  imagine  that  Wundt  will  find  time  to  defend  his 
system  against  these  latest  charges,  and  I  do  not  propose  to 
undertake  the  business  for  him.  I  shall,  however,  try  to  set 
forth,  in  the  light  of  a  genetic  study,  the  use  and  meaning  of 
the  technical  terms  here  in  question.  Such  a  study  is  doubly 
instructive.  It  shows  our  modern  psychology  in  the  making; 
the  long  series  of  Wundt's  books  reflects  the  recent  history 
of  the  science.  It  shows  also  the  manner  of  Wundt's  own 
progress  from  logic  to  psychology,  from  activity  to  content. 
His  fundamental  ideas  have  remained,  for  the  most  part, 
unchanged;  advance  is  made,  habitually,  by  modification  in 
detail,  by  expansion  and  contraction,  by  redistribution  of 
topics  and  change  of  emphasis.  Even  when  the  system 
suffers  a  decided  innovation  (we  shall  have  a  case  presently), 
there  are  always  hints  of  the  new  departure,  if  we  look  closely 
enough,  in  the  previous  work.  Here,  of  course,  I  have  space 
only  to  give  results.  I  hope  to  be  able,  nevertheless,  to  clear 
up  the  difficulties  which  Britz  and,  perhaps,  other  readers 
have  found  in  the  sixth  edition  of  the  '  Physiologische  Psy- 
chologic.' 

We  are  to  ask,  accordingly,  what  Wundt  means  by  con- 
sciousness and  degrees  of  consciousness,  by  clearness,  by 
degrees  of  apperception,  and  especially  what  is  the  relation 
between  degree  of  consciousness  and  degree  of  clearness.  We 
begin  with  consciousness. 

The  keynote  of  Wundt's  psychological  treatment  of  con- 
sciousness is  the  notion  of  synthesis.  Consciousness,  the 
condition  of  all  inner  experience  (i-$Y  or,  more  empirically, 
the  total  contents  of  our  immediate  experience  (6),  cannot 
be  defined  in  psychological  terms.  We  must  be  satisfied  to 
determine  its  conditions  (i),  that  is,  the  phenomena  that 

xBy  these  numbers  I  indicate  the  editions  in  which  the  particular  phrase  occurs; 
minor  verbal  changes  must  here  be  disregarded.  References  are  given  in  later  notes. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  45 

invariably  accompany  its  manifestation  in  experience  (2-5); 
more  exactly,  we  must  be  content  to  give  the  conditions  under 
which  we  observe  such  phenomena  as  we  attribute  to  a  con- 
sciousness (6).  There  are,  now,  two  psychological  processes 
which  are  bound  up  with  consciousness  and  may  be  regarded 
as  its  essential  characters.  The  first  of  these  is  the  formation 
of  ideas  (and  real  feelings)  from  sensations  (and  simple 
feelings).  Our  consciousness  of  ideas  consists  in  the  act  of 
synthesis  whereby  sensations  are  brought  into  temporal  and 
spatial  form  (i);  in  every  act  of  ideation  there  is  effected  a 
connection  of  elementary  sensations  (2-4).  Ideas  and  real 
feelings  arise  from  a  psychological  synthesis  of  elements,  and 
this  connection  of  elements  is  therefore  one  of  the  two  charac- 
teristics of  consciousness  (5,  6).  The  other  is  to  be  found  in 
the  processes  of  reproduction  and  association  of  ideas  (and 
feelings).  The  connection  of  ideas  takes  place  in  conscious- 
ness (i);  it  is  only  by  way  of  reproduction  and  association 
that  consciousness  can  become  aware  of  itself  as  persisting 
without  change  through  all  the  change  of  ideas  (1-3);  this 
changing  flow  of  ideas  is  itself  aware  of  consciousness  as  a 
synthetic  activity  connecting  present  ideas  with  those  that 
have  gone  before  (1—3).  Consciousness  is  empirically  demon- 
strable only  on  condition  (unter  der  Foraussetzung)  of  a  con- 
nection of  the  ideas  (and  feelings)  which  follow  one  another 
in  time  (4,  5);  reproduction  and  association  are  therefore  an 
universal  concomitant  of  consciousness  (6).  An  orderly 
connection  of  ideas  (1-4)  or,  in  more  general  phrase,  a  con- 
nection of  immediate  experiences  (5,  6)  is,  indeed,  the  con- 
dition under  which  alone  consciousness  appears. 

If,  however,  the  primary  thing  about  consciousness  is 
synthesis,  then  we  must  recognize  the  possibility  of  degrees 
or  grades  of  consciousness,  since  such  connections  as  that  of 
sensations  in  the  temporal  or  spatial  idea  may  exist  at  various 
levels  (i).  Self-observation  reveals  these  degrees.  "When- 
ever we  incorporate  an  impression  but  loosely  in  the  context 
of  our  ideas,  or  later  remember  it  but  imperfectly  by  reason 
of  this  looseness  of  connection,  we  credit  ourselves  only  with  a 
lower  degree  of  consciousness  at  the  time  in  question"  (2-6). 


46  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

In  these  instances,  capacity  for  the  connection  of  ideas  (or 
psychical  contents)  is  taken  as  measure  of  degree  of  con- 
sciousness (2-5);  or,  as  Wundt  puts  it  in  his  final  phrasing, 
"the  connection  of  psychical  contents  is  a  certain  measure  of 
degree  of  consciousness"  (6).  Every  connection  of  inner 
states  (or  psychical  elements)  manifests  some  degree  of 
consciousness  (2—6). 

That  is  the  Wundtian  doctrine  of  consciousness  and  its 
degrees,  as  set  forth  in  the  various  editions  of  his  great  work.1 
The  intention  of  the  discussion,  from  the  very  first,  is  psycho- 
logical; even  in  1874  Wundt  is  combating  the  logical  tenden- 
cies which  showed  their  full  force  in  the  Vorlesungen  of  1863. 2 
His  effort  is  not  immediately  successful;  but,  by  degrees, 
changing  here  a  little  and  there  a  little,  he  moves  away  from 
logic  toward  psychology,  away  from  synthetic  activity 
toward  observable  connection.  There  is  no  reason  to  think 
that  he  was,  at  every  stage,  fully  aware  of  the  significance  of 
the  changes;  he  probably  chose  the  wording  that  seemed,  at 
the  time,  best  to  express  his  thought — his  original  no  less  than 
his  present  thought.  In  point  of  fact  the  corrections  of  the 
early  text  serve  in  sum  to  change  the  whole  atmosphere  of  the 
discussion. 

We  find  the  same  sort  of  progress  in  the  treatment  of 
attention.  The  discussion  of  1874  begins  as  follows:  "In 
the  synthesis  of  sensations  and  in  the  association  of  ideas 
consciousness  apprehends  itself  as  active.  Thus  arises  that 
expression  of  consciousness  which  we  name  attention.  It 
makes  itself  known  in  direct  self-observation  by  the  fact  that 
the  interconnection  of  ideas,  with  which  consciousness  is 
correlated,  is  by  no  means  present  to  it  at  all  times  in  the 
same  manner;  consciousness  is  directed  upon  certain  ideas  in 
higher  measure  than  upon  others."  Later  we  have:  "Beside 
the  coming  and  going  of  ideas  we  perceive  within  us  not 
infrequently  (in  varying  fashion)  and  more  or  less  plainly 
an  (inner)  activity  which  we  designate  attention"  (2-6). 

lPhys.  Psych.,  1874,  707  f.,  711  ff.,  717;  1880,  II.,  195  f.,  199,  201;  1887,  II., 
225  f.,  229,  231;  1893,  II.,  255  f.,  259,  261;  1903,  III.,  320  f.,  324  f.;  1911,  III.,  296,  f.; 
299  f. 

2  See  op.  cit.,  1874,  708  ff. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  47 

Degree  of  apperception  is  gauged  by  the  subjective  activity 
with  which  consciousness  turns  to  a  particular  sensory  stimu- 
lus (1-5).  The  simile  of  Blickpunkt  and  Blickfeld,  the  state- 
ment that  the  Punkt  is  really  a  small  Feld  of  varying  extent 
and  that  the  main  field  darkens  in  proportion  as  the  central 
field  brightens,  and  the  distinction  of  perception  and  apper- 
ception are  present  in  all  editions.  Passive  and  active  apper- 
ception are  distinguished  in  the  second,  the  limen  of  conscious- 
ness and  the  limen  of  attention  only  in  the  fourth  edition. 
All  these  things  are  familiar,  and  need  not  be  dwelt  upon. 
What  now  of  clearness,  which  ultimately  becomes  the  sole 
objective  criterion  of  apperception? 

The  brightening  of  the  Blickpunkt  means,  as  we  have 
seen,  that  consciousness  is  directed  upon  certain  ideas  in 
higher  measure  than  upon  others  (1-4);  certain  contents 
become  more  conscious  than  others  (5);  we  observe  in  con- 
sciousness different  degrees  of  conscious  status,  variously  and 
varyingly  distributed  over  its  contents  (6).  If  we  consider 
the  apperceived  contents  themselves,  we  find  the  following 
progression.  We  begin  with  a  clearness  of  ideas,  dependent 
partly  on  the  intensity  of  the  ideas  and  partly  on  adaptation 
of  attention  (1-3).  Presently  this  clearness,  dependent  now 
upon  the  intensity  of  the  sensations  composing  the  ideas  and 
upon  adaptation  of  attention,  is  paired  with  distinctness; 
clearness  is  predicable  of  an  idea  in  its  own  right,  distinctness 
of  an  idea  in  its  relation  to  other  ideas.  Feelings  may  be 
distinct,  but  apparently  can  not  be  clear  (4).  Later  still  this 
same  clearness  attaches  to  all  complex  conscious  contents: 
to  ideas  and  feelings  as  wholes,  and  also  to  particular  ele- 
ments within  ideas  and  feelings  (5,  6).  Clearness,  which 
originally  belonged  to  ideas  alone,  thus  remains  to  the  end  a 
character  of  complex  contents.  "Clearness  and  distinctness 
are  exclusively  characters  of  ideas,  and  may  be  transferred 
to  sensations  only  when  these  are  considered  as  constituents 
of  ideas"  (6).1 

All  this  is  fairly  straightforward,  though  I  must  warn  the 

1  Op.  dt.,  1874,  717  f.,  720,  722,  725,  729;  1880,  II.,  205  f.,  208,  209,  212;  1887, 
II.,  235  f.,  238,  239,  244;  1893,  II.,  266,  267,  269,  271,  272,  282;  1903,  III.,  331, 332  f., 
336,  337  f-,  339,  348,  349J  19",  HI.,  306,  307  f.,  312  f.,  314,  322,  323. 


48  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

reader  that  I  have  passed  over  certain  passages  which  will 
occupy  us  later.  The  pairing  of  distinctness  with  clearness 
offers  no  difficulty;  distinctness  is  always  the  subordinate 
concept,  and  does  not  appear  in  the  final  summary  of  the 
part-processes  in  an  apperception.1  The  irruption  of  the 
new  theory  of  feeling,  in  the  fifth  edition,  does  create  a  diffi- 
culty— as  I  pointed  out  in  Feeling  and  Attention — but  it  is 
not  one  that  directly  concerns  us  here. 

We  are  therefore  ready  to  take  up,  in  a  preliminary  way, 
the  relation  of  consciousness  to  attention  and  of  degree  of 
consciousness  to  degree  of  clearness.  The  first  of  these 
questions  is  easily  answered.  Consciousness,  for  Wundt,  is 
always  wider  than  attention.  In  1874  he  wrote:  "The 
theory  that  consciousness  and  attention  are  identical  is  not 
tenable."  In  1911  he  writes:  "An  impression  that  has  sunk 
below  the  limen  of  apperception  does  not  therewith  disappear 
from  consciousness;"  and  his  whole  treatment  of  the  two 
topics,  from  first  to  last,  implies  this  distinction.2  Conscious- 
ness is  the  total  contents  of  our  immediate  experience;  atten- 
tion is  the  range  of  clear  experience. 

The  second  question  may  be  answered,  to  begin  with,  by 
the  statement  that  degree  of  consciousness  and  degree  of 
clearness  have,  logically,  no  connection  with  each  other. 
Degree  of  consciousness  is  degree  of  organization  of  conscious 
contents.  Let  us  imagine  (if  we  can)  a  consciousness  with- 
out attention.  Such  a  consciousness  would  still  show  degrees 
of  consciousness,  because  the  complex  contents  and  the 
groups  of  complex  contents  which  make  it  up  would  differ 
in  closeness  of  connection  or  organization.  There  are  pass- 
ages in  the  first  edition  which  seem  to  come  very  near  to 
such  an  imaginary  consciousness;3  and  the  recurring  phrase 
"It  is  always  association  that  puts  ideas  at  the  disposal  of 
apperception"  at  any  rate  suggests  it.4  In  reality,  however, 

1  See  op.  ciL,  1911,  III.,  316. 

2  Op,  ciL,  1874,  725;  1911,  III.,  314. 
8  Op.  cit.y  1874,795,  835- 

4  Op.  cit.,  1880,  II.,  212;  1887,  II. ,  244;  1893,  II.,  279.  I  do  not  find  the  phrase 
in  the  two  last  editions;  and  indeed  it  goes  too  far.  See  1903,  III.,  524  f.;  1911,  III., 
498  f. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  49 

consciousness  comes  to  us  in  other  guise.  It  makes  its  own 
history  from  the  very  outset,  and  carries  that  history  with  it; 
and  the  history  is  constantly  interfering,  so  to  say,  with  its 
present  course.1  Or,  to  put  the  same  thing  from  another 
point  of  view,  it  is  organized,  at  whatever  level  and  in  what- 
ever degree,  as  an  attentive  consciousness;  associations  are 
formed  in  passive,  apperceptive  connections  in  active  atten- 
tion.2 While,  then,  degree  of  consciousness  (or  of  organiza- 
tion) and  degree  of  clearness  (or  of  conscious  status)  may  be 
distinguished  logically,  empirically  they  are  bound  together 
in  the  most  complicated  fashion.  One  might  suppose,  per- 
haps, that  the  difference  between  range  of  consciousness  and 
range  of  attention  should  be  directly  observable.  Wundt 
does  not  deny  it,  though  he  seems  to  think  otherwise;  it  is  a 
subsequent  apperception  that  ordinarily  makes  us  aware  of 
the  obscure  fringe;  and  he  does  deny  that  the  simultaneous 
method  is  adequate  to  range  of  consciousness.3  One  might 
suppose,  again,  that  degree  of  consciousness  and  degree  of 
clearness  should  run  parallel;  and  in  many  cases,  at  many 
moments  of  the  history  of  consciousness,  they  doubtless  do; 
but  we  must  remember  that  the  one  tends  to  be  stable  and 
the  other  is  essentially  instable.  Consider,  indeed,  any  case 
of  active  attention.  The  complex  contents  that  now  lie  in 
the  obscurity  of  the  Blickfeld,  and  that  therefore  have  no 
conscious  status  whatever,  were  once  (probably,  many  times 
over)  given  in  passive  apperception,  in  so  far  as  they  are 
organized  at  all;  and  if  their  organization  is  high,  as  it  may 
be,  they  were  given  in  active  apperception.  The  complex 
contents  that  occupy  the  Blickpunkt  and  therefore  possess 
various  degrees  of  conscious  status  vary  in  degree  of  conscious- 
ness, from  moment  to  moment,  according  as  apperception  is 
integrative  or  disruptive  and  their  organization  is  corre- 
spondingly strengthened  or  weakened.  Or  consider  observa- 
tion itself.  Observation  is  always  apperception;  and  we 
cannot  become  aware  of  a  low  degree  of  consciousness  unless 

*  Op.  at.,  1893,  II.,  284. 

2  See  W.  B.  Pillsbury,  Amer.  J.  of  PsychoL,  1897,  8,  329  ff. 

3  Op.  cit.,  1911,  III.,  324,  330;  cf.  1903,  III.,  351  if.,  and  the  stronger  statements 
of  1874,  726;  1880,  II.,  219;  1887,  II.,  261;  1893,  II.,  305. 


50  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

we  give  the  poorly  organized  contents  a  high  conscious 
status.1  So  the  empirical  relation  of  the  two  degrees  (and  I 
have,  of  course,  greatly  oversimplified  it  in  this  brief  account) 
is  complex  in  the  extreme.  Neither  can  exist  without  the 
other;  yet,  since  they  do  not  run  on  parallel  lines,  their 
separate  treatment  is  a  matter  of  practical  convenience,  if 
not  of  necessity;  a  full  account,  historical  and  descriptive,  of 
any  given  consciousness  implies  constant  reference  to  both. 
If  Wundt  inclines,  even  in  his  latest  writing,  to  make  connec- 
tion the  fundamental  character  of  consciousness  and  to 
regard  attention  as  an  activity  within  consciousness2 — when 
we  might  expect  him  to  give  the  two  factors  equal  rank — 
the  reasons  are  historical,  and  not  least  among  them  is  his 
reaction  against  unconscious  ideas. 

I  believe  that  these  answers  to  our  two  questions  are 
fair,  and  that  they  represent  the  essentials  of  Wundt's 
doctrine;  I  confess  that  I  have  rounded  off  some  rather 
prickly  passages.3  We  have  now  to  consider  those  divergent 
statements  to  which  I  have  already  referred. 

1  After  a  good  deal  of  vacillation,  Wundt  settles  down  in  the  sixth  edition  to  the 
definite  terminological  distinction  of  Bewusstseinsstufe  or  Grad  des  Bewusstseins  and 
Grad  der  Bewusstheit:  1911,  III.,  299,  307.     I  have  made  this  distinction  throughout, 
and  have  translated  Bewusstheit  by  'conscious  status.' 

2  Op.  cit.,  1911,  III.,  301. 

8  Let  me  give  an  instance !  Wundt  teaches  that  the  contents  at  the  Blickpunkt 
(an  area,  be  it  remembered)  are  variously  clear,  and  the  contents  in  the  outlying 
Blickfeld  obscure.  In  1903,  III.,  353  (1911,  III.,  326)  we  are  introduced  to  Grade  der 
Verdunkelung,  degrees  of  obscurity.  It  looks,  then,  as  if  the  contents  below  the 
limen  of  attention  might  possess  something  more  than  degree  of  consciousness  (which 
is  all  that  I  have  allowed  them  in  the  text),  something  that  is,  after  all,  very  like 
conscious  status.  I  have,  however,  pointed  out  in  'Feeling  and  Attention'  that  there 
is  here  a  confusion  of  apperception  with  cognition,  of  attributive  with  cognitive  clear- 
ness, and  that  a  recent  worker  in  Wundt's  own  laboratory  has  called  attention  to  it 
(see  237  ff.,  369,  and  cf.  230  f.).  I  have  already  remarked  that  Wundt's  progress  is 
from  activity  to  content:  it  is  not  till  the  fifth  edition  that  'consciousness'  ceases  to 
be  'directed  upon  ideas,'  and  that  'contents  become  more  conscious':  cf.  1903,  III., 
333  with  1893,  II. ,  267. 

Again,  in  1902,  I.,  323  (1908,  I.,  382)  we  are  told  that  change  of  clearness,  as 
distinguished  from  change  of  intensity,  alters  the  relation  between  contents;  clearness 
thus  seems  to  be  confused  with  distinctness.  But  the  passage  in  which  this  state- 
ment occurs  is  not  represented  in  1893;  it  harks  back  to  1887,  I.,  237,  an  edition  in 
which  the  distinction  of  clearness  and  distinctness  had  not  yet  been  drawn.  The 
clearness  of  1902  and  1908  (in  these  particular  sentences)  is  therefore  an  undifferentiated 
clearness  and  distinctness. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  51 

The  discussion  of  the  apperception-center  in  the  fifth 
edition  surprises  us  by  a  reference  to  the  clearness  of  sensa- 
tion: surprises  us  all  the  more  because  the  earlier  editions 
spoke  in  the  same  context  only  of  the  clearness  of  ideas  and 
impressions;  because  the  same  volume  teaches  that  sensations 
are  constituted  solely  of  intensity  and  quality;  and  because 
the  same  edition,  in  a  later  volume,  retains  the  orthodox 
view  that  clearness  and  distinctness  are  exclusively  characters 
of  ideas.  This  third  volume  adds,  however,  that  clearness 
may  be  predicated  of  sensations  when  they  are  considered 
as  constituents  of  ideas  (the  fundamental  of  a  compound 
tone,  the  color  of  a  visual  form);  and  so  it  seemed  possible  to 
interpret  the  sensations  which  become  clear  in  apperception 
as  sensations-in-ideas.1  That  was  a  way  out  of  the  difficulty; 
it  was  not  the  way  the  offending  passage  read.  Those  who 
know  the  'Physiologische  Psychologic'  historically  know, 
however,  that  its  exposition  is  continually  changing  in  detail, 
and  that  the  details  are  likely  to  prove  important;  I  have 
made  the  point  earlier  in  this  paper.  So  one  hoped  for  more 
light  in  a  sixth  edition;  and  the  light  came  with  a  vengeance! 
The  reference  to  clearness  of  sensations  in  the  discussion  of 
the  apperception-center  is  now  justified  by  entirely  new 
matter,  which  introduces  the  chapter  on  Intensity  of  Sensa- 
tion. There  are  (we  learn)  intensive  psychical  magnitudes, 
which  accrue  only  to  the  simple  elements  of  the  mental  life, 
and  there  are  extensive  psychical  magnitudes,  which  result 
from  the  composition  of  elements.  The  three  intensive  mag- 
nitudes are  intensity,  quality,  and — clearness.  And  these 
three  characters  are  three  coordinate  dimensions  of  the 
psychical  elements;  they  are,  that  is  to  say,  attributes  of  sensa- 
tion. Compound  contents  show  different  degrees  of  clear- 
ness in  their  different  parts;  degree  of  clearness  is  unequivocal 

1  Op.  cit.,  1902,  L,  322  f.,  353;  1903,  III.,  338,  349;  cf.  1880, 1.,  218;  1887,  L,  233; 
1893,  L,  228.  These  passages  are  to  be  sharply  distinguished  from  the  casual  and 
physiologically  motived  reference  to  the  apperception  of  sensations  (correlates  of  the 
excitation  of  a  sensory  center)  which  occurs  in  1902,  L,  324,  and  which  appears  in  all 
editions  from  the  second  to  the  sixth. 


52  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

only  in  regard  to  the  elements,  to  simple  contents.  Wundt's 
statements  are  as  definite  as  they  could  well  be.1 

Here,  then,  is  a  new  kind  of  clearness,  different  from  the 
original  clearness  of  ideas  and  real  feelings,  different  also 
from  the  clearness  of  the  sensations-in-ideas.  Wundt  has 
not  made  a  clean  sweep  of  things,  however,  even  in  this 
volume;  the  old  statement,  running  through  all  the  editions, 
that  sensations  are  constituted  solely  of  intensity  and  quality,2 
is  allowed  to  remain.  A  pure  oversight,  no  doubt!  The 
few  references  to  clearness  in  the  second  volume,  of  1910,  are 
neutral.  But  then  we  come  to  the  third  volume,  of  1911, 
and  there  we  are  back  again  in  the  familiar  atmosphere, 
with  the  express  assurance  that  clearness  and  distinctness 
are  exclusively  characters  of  ideas!  Could  ever  anything  be 
more  bewildering? 

Well!  our  bewilderment  is  at  any  rate  less  than  Britz's. 
For  our  genetic  study  proves  that  the  two  clearnesses  do  not 
stand  on  a  level.  The  clearness  of  the  third  volume,  of  1911, 
is  the  traditional  clearness  of  the  Wundtian  system,  deeply 
rooted  in  nearly  forty  years  of  thought  and  expression;  the 
clearness  of  the  first  volume,  of  1908,  is  a  new  phenomenon, 
only  casually  foreshadowed  in  the  corresponding  volume  of 
1902.  Something,  it  appears,  was  moving  Wundt's  ideas, 
even  at  the  earlier  date,  towards  sensory  clearness;  and 
something  happened,  between  the  fifth  and  sixth  editions,  to 
precipitate  and  crystallize  his  ideas.3  Thereafter,  in  the 
interval  between  1908  and  1911,  his  interests  turned  away 
from  this  something;  he  had  forgotten  all  about  his  intensive 

1  Op.  cit.,  III.,   1908,  L,  539  ff.     I  myself  urged  as  early  as   1898  that  clear- 
ness should  be  recognized  as  a  sensory  attribute,  but  printed  no  extended  discussion 
of  the  question  before  this  same  year,  1908.     See  Phil.  Rev.,  8,  461  f.;  'Feeling  and 
Attention,'  references  to  'Clearness'  in  index. 

2  Together  (for  a  time)  with  feeling-tone.     See  1874,  273;  1880,  I.,  272;  1887,  I., 
290;  1893,  L,  282;  1902,  L,  353;  1908,  L,  412. 

8 1  am  in  this  paper  expounding  Wundt,  and  neither  criticizing  his  views  nor 
trying  at  all  completely  to  trace  their  motivation;  the  first  thing  to  do  with  an  author 
(and  it  is  what  Britz  has  failed  to  do)  is  to  understand  him.  I  think,  however,  that 
it  is  safe  to  connect  Wundt's  new  paragraphs  with  the  revival  of  psychophysical 
interest  shown  by  the  works  of  Miiller  (1904),  Lipps  (1903,  1904,  1906),  Titchener 
(1905),  Bruns  (1906),  Keller  (1907)  and  others.  In  particular,  G.  F.  Lipps  was  at 
Leipsic  from  1903  on. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  53 

magnitudes  that  accrue  only  to  the  elements;  and  so  he 
contented  himself  with  the  customary  revision  of  the  former 
text.  Natural  enough,  after  all,  in  view  of  Wundt's  age  and 
multifarious  activities:  the  wonder  is  not  so  much  that  he 
should  have  forgotten  as  that  he  should  have  had,  in  1908, 
the  energy  and  the  open-mindedness  to  attack  once  again 
the  whole  problem  of  mental  measurement,  and  in  doing 
this  to  effect  a  radical  change  in  one  of  his  most  elaborate 
systematic  constructions.  There  is  no  possibility  of  recon- 
ciliation of  the  two  volumes;  Britz's  efforts  are  wasted  labor.1 
It  would  plainly  be  useless  to  reopen  our  questions  of  the 
relation  of  consciousness  to  attention,  and  of  degree  of  con- 
sciousness to  conscious  status,  in  the  light  of  Wundt's  new 
definitions.  The  clearness  which  is  an  intensive  attribute  of 
sensation  is  at  the  same  time  degree  of  apperception  (the 
objective  aspect  of  degree  of  attention)  or  of  keenness  of 
apprehension.2  We  may  work  out,  if  we  will,  what  this 
statement  logically  implies  for  the  treatment  of  consciousness 
and  attention  in  the  third  volume;  or  we  may  wait  patiently 
for  a  seventh  edition.  At  present  the  questions  can  be 
answered  intelligibly  only  if  we  ignore  the  intruding  passages. 
They  can  be  answered,  that  is,  only  in  the  preliminary  way 
in  which  they  have  been  answered  above.  This  conclusion 
seems  to  me  to  be  a  positive  result,  which  justifies  our  re- 
course to  the  genetic  or  historical  method.  It  far  outweighs, 
just  because  it  is  the  result  of  a  sound  method,  any  conclusion 
reached  by  Britz. 

II 

I  must  now  say  something  in  reply  to  Britz's  polemic 
against  my  own  doctrine  of  clearness.  If  only  Britz  knew 
accurately  what  he  is  talking  about!  I  give  a  few  examples 
to  show  that  he  does  not. 

(i)  Britz  finds  five  principal  "criteria"  of  the  sensory 
attribute.  I  am  said  to  rely  only  upon  two,  inseparability 

1  But  what  was  Klemm  about,  who  read  the  proofs,  that  he  did  not  call  his  chief's 
attention  to  the  discrepancy?     See  op.  cit.,  1908,  L,  X;  1911,  III.,  V. 

2  Op.  cit.,  1908,  III.,  541  ff.     The  italicized  Apperzeptionsgrade  of  p.  541,  1.  16 
should  be  Aufmerksamkeits grade. 


54  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

and  independent  variability;  and  I  am  further  said  to  rely 
mainly  upon  the  second.  Turn  to  'Feeling  and  Attention'! 
I  there  begin  by  criticizing  the  'common  definition'  of  an 
attribute.  From  this  definition  I  accept  the  criterion  of 
inseparability.  As  a  mark  of  inseparability  I  instance  the 
reduction  of  the  whole  sensation  to  zero  when  a  single  attribute 
reduces  to  zero.  Britz,  who  raises  this  special  case  of  in- 
separability to  the  rank  of  a  separate  criterion,  speculates  as 
to  what  I  should  make  of  the  argument  if  I  used  it!  From  the 
same  definition  I  get  the  criterion  of  independent  variability, 
and  point  out  that  in  fact  "there  are  bound  attributes  as  well 
as  free,"  so  that  "the  test  of  independent  variability,  useful 
enough  for  a  preliminary  survey,  must  be  applied  with  caution 
when  we  demand  accuracy  of  detail."  Yet  this  is  'Titch- 
ener's  Hauptmerkmal'!  Hillebrand,  from  whom  Britz  de- 
rives my  two  criteria,  states  the  case  correctly;  so  that  Britz 
has  even  misread  Hillebrand.1 

(2)  Britz  does  not  hesitate  to  criticize  Bentley's  experiment 
with  intensities  of  sound  on  the  basis  of  the  passing  reference 
in  my  'Text-book.'      What  series   were  carried  out,   what 
intensities  of  stimulus  were  employed,  what  precautions  were 
taken,  of  course  he  does  not  know.2 

(3)  I   never  use   the   phrase    'degree   of   consciousness'; 
from  my  point  of  view  it  is   as   nonsensical   as   'degree  of 
matter'  or  'degree  of  material  existence'  would  be  in  physics. 
Britz  disregards  my  definition  of  consciousness,  and  his  dis- 
cussion of  the  place  of  Bewusstseinsgrad  in  my    system    is 
consequently  all  in  the  air.3 

(4)  Britz  credits  me  with  'the  assumption  that  the  num- 
ber of  degrees  of  clearness  is  not  the  same  for  all  departments 
of  sense.'     What  I  say  is  that  we  have  'to  determine,  intro- 
spectively,  how  many  degrees  of  clearness  can  be  distinguished 
[how  many  just  noticeable  differences  of  clearness  there  are] 

1  Britz,  op.  cit.,  14,  24;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  8  ff.;  F.  Hillebrand,  Z.  /.  Psych., 
1910,  58,  141. 

2  Op.  cit.,  26;  'Text-book,'  1910,  280;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  361  ff.     I  take  this 
opportunity  to  correct  a  misprint.     In  Table  II.,  p.  364,  the  second  rubric  under 
Height  of  Fall  should  be  74.4-89.6  cm. 

8  Op.  cit.,  41  f. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  55 

in  the  various  departments  of  sense';  I  assume  neither  that 
the  number  is  the  same  nor  that  it  is  different.1 

(5)  I  have  just  said  that  Britz  misreads  Hillebrand:  here 
is  another  case.  "  Hillebrand  has  shown  in  detail,"  he  writes, 
"to  what  absurdities  we  are  led  by  the  identification  of 
attention  and  clearness  when  we  make  clearness  an  attribute 
of  sensation."  Hillebrand  has  shown  no  such  thing.  He 
raises  the  question  "whether  every  attribute  has  its  own 
clearness,  as  an  attribute  of  the  second  order";  if  it  has,  he 
says,  "that  would  lead  to  the  absurd  consequence  that  the 
complete  disregard  of  any  one  attribute  brought  with  it,  to 
say  the  least,  the  disregard  of  all  the  others.  .  .  .  Here 
Titchener  seems  to  me  to  have  overlooked  obvious  difficul- 
ties." Perfectly  fair  criticism!  but  there  is  one  absurdity 
hinging  on  an  'if,'  not  an  ausfuhrliche  Darlegung  of  absurdities 
in  general.2 

It  is  naturally  disappointing,  when  one  is  made  the  part-sub- 
ject of  a  doctorate  thesis,  to  find  one's  views  thus  caricatured. 
But  enough  has  been  said  on  that  matter.  Let  us  now  see  if 
Britz  makes  any  positive  contribution  to  the  discussion  of 
sensory  clearness. 

My  thesis  is  that  clearness  or  vividness  (I  am  not  yet  sure 
which  is  the  better  term,  and  there  is  historical  warrant  for 
both)  is  one  of  the  intensive  attributes  of  sensation.  Britz 
complains  that  I  say  very  little  about  its  actual  nature;  and 
in  a  sense  that  is  true.  You  cannot  say  much  about  a  thing 
that  you  regard  as  ultimate  to  your  science;  any  attempt  at 
a  definition  runs  over,  by  force  of  circumstances,  into  what 
Wundt  would  call  a  tautologische  Umschreibung.  I  have  had 
recourse  to  a  number  of  these  periphrases;  but  I  have  tried, 
above  all,  to  exhibit  the  thing  itself,  to  state  conditions  under 
which  it  may  be  experienced  and  identified  in  experience. 
Quality  and  intensity  are  here  in  the  same  box  with  clearness. 
You  can  exhibit  qualities  or  intensities,  as  you  can  exhibit 
clearnesses;  but  when  you  attempt  to  define  them,  you  find 
yourself  talking  round  them.  If  Britz  had  performed  Geiss- 

1  Op.  cit.,  41,  42;  more  correctly  stated  on  p.  12;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  277  f.; 
*  Text-book,'  295  f. 

2  Op.  cit.,  42;  Hillebrand,  146  f. 


56  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

ler's  simple  experiment  with  the  two  metronomes,  equated 
for  quality  and  intensity  of  sound,  he  would  have  discovered 
at  first  hand  what  I  mean  by  sensory  or  attributive  clearness.1 

My  thesis  is,  secondly,  that  sensory  clearness  is  the  ele- 
mentary phenomenon  in  what  is  ordinarily  called  attention. 
Just  as  sensory  extension  is  the  elementary  phenomenon  in 
spatial  perception,  and  sensory  duration  in  temporal  per- 
ception, just  so,  mutatis  mutandis,  is  sensory  clearness  the 
unique  thing,  the  psychologically  ultimate  thing,  in  attention. 
Hence  I  remark  in  the  'Text-book'  that  "in  the  last  resort, 
and  in  its  simplest  terms,  attention  is  identical  with  sensory 
clearness."  Analyze  an  attentive  consciousness,  and  every- 
thing is  familiar  to  you  but  the  one  thing,  which  you  finally 
arrive  at — this  sensory  clearness  or  vividness;  that  is  new 
and  characteristic. 

The  importance  of  such  a  view  for  experimental  psychology 
is,  I  think,  plain  on  the  surface;  a  new  road  is  opened,  and  a 
road  that  by  all  analogy  should  take  us  an  appreciable  distance 
to  our  goal,  for  an  experimental  attack  upon  attention.  In 
'Feeling  and  Attention'  I  speak  accordingly  of  a  'simplified' 
or  'elementary'  psychology  of  attention;  I  suggest  that  we 
start  out,  not  from  the  gross  facts  of  the  attentive  conscious- 
ness, but  from  the  'rise'  of  the  single  sensation,  the  absolute 
temporal  limen,  the  carrying  power  of  clearness  under  simple 
conditions.  "How  far  this  elementary  psychology  of  atten- 
tion could  be  carried  it  is,  evidently,  impossible  to  predict," 
though  there  is  no  lack  of  specific  problems;  in  any  case,  "the 
results  of  experiment  in  these  fields  must  be  'interpreted'  by 
a  psychology  of  attention;  the  factors  that  make  for  clearness 
must  be  separated  from  the  other  conditions  involved,  and 
must  if  possible  be  separately  estimated  or  'weighted.'" 
That  is  my  view;  and  I  am  correspondingly  surprised  to 
find  Britz,  who  quotes  correctly  the  sentence  from  the  'Text- 
book' given  above,  asserting  in  several  places  that  I  identify 
outright  clearness  with  attention.  If  that  were  the  case  my 

10p.  cit.,  40,  41,  44;  'Text-book,'  53,  279;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  26,  183  ff.; 
L.  R.  Geissler,  in  Amer.  J.  of  Psych.,  1909,  20,  510.  Britz  devotes  a  special  section  to 
Geissler,  as  he  does  also  to  Wirth  and  Jaensch;  all  three  will,  I  expect,  find  something 
to  say  for  themselves. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  57 

chapter  on  Attention  would  hardly  have  been  written  as  it  is. 
But  having  made  this  identification,  it  is  easy  for  my  critic  to 
show  that  the  introductory  examples  of  attention — the  shift 
of  interest  due  to  the  visit  of  a  friend  or  to  the  receipt  of  a 
telephone  message — involve'  more  than  sensory  clearness,  and 
that  I  am  therefore  faithless  to  my  theory  before  I  have  got  it 
formulated.1 

I  hold,  thirdly,  that  clearness  is  not  an  attribute  of  the 
simple  feeling;  and  as  clearness  is  an  intensive  attribute, 
ranging  from  liminal  obscurity  to  terminal  clearness  (just  as 
intensity  ranges  from  the  very  weak  to  the  very  strong), 
this  means  that  feeling  is  for  me  neither  clear  nor  obscure, 
but  only  qualitative,  intensive  and  durative.  The  traditional 
*  obscurity'  of  feeling  rests,  I  believe,  upon  the  customary 
mixture  of  logic  and  psychology.  I  realize  that  the  whole 
psychology  of  feeling  is  debatable  ground;  but,  after  all,  the 
discussion  in  *  Feeling  and  Attention'  is  seriously  written  and 
deserves  to  be  taken  seriously.  Britz  gives  a  single  sentence 
to  the  matter.  We  ought,  he  says,  to  enquire  carefully 
whether  the  clearness  of  my  two  examples  (the  friend's  visit 
and  the  telephone  message)  is  not  applicable  to  feeling;  anach 
meinem  Dafiirhalten  kann  er  [der  Begriff]  angewendet 
werden."  But  that  clearness  is  evidently  cognitive  as  well 
as  attributive;  the  distinction  is  clearly  drawn,  again,  in 
'Feeling  and  Attention.'2 

I  hold,  lastly,  that  in  cross-section  the  attentive  con- 
sciousness is  arranged,  for  many  and  perhaps  for  most  of  us, 
at  two  main  levels,  the  upper  of  which  certainly,  and  the 
lower  probably,  are  'wrinkled'  by  minor  differences  of 
sensory  clearness.  "A  two-level  type,"  Britz  remarks, 
"seems  to  me  to  be  altogether  beyond  the  range  of  psycho- 
logical proof;  it  too  obviously  contradicts  all  and  every 
experience."  Oddly  enough,  it  seems  to  me  to  represent  my 
experience.  Britz  may  very  well  belong  to  the  multi-level 
type,  though  he  does  not  appear  to  have  gone  beyond  casual 
self-observation.  He  continues:  "Within  the  apperceived 

1  Op.  cit.t  12,  40  ff.;  'Text-book,'  266  f.;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  209  f.,  251,  372. 

2  Op.  cit.,  42;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  237  ff. 


58  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

(beachteten)  complex  there  are  degrees  of  clearness  which 
may  be  lower  than  the  highest  upon  the  low  level;  therefore 
it  is  not  permissible  to  speak  of  a  'niveau,'  *  level,'  plane  or 
surface."  I  do  not  know  how  he  gets  his  data;  but  it  is 
surely  plain  that,  if  there  are  anywhere  in  a  given  conscious- 
ness processes  less  clear  than  the  clearest  of  the  lower  level, 
these  processes  must  be  for  me  at  the  lower  level.  To  say 
that  they  are  t within  the  apperceived  complex'  means,  if  it 
means  anything,  that  my  critic  is  thinking  of  the  unitary 
object  of  attention;  and  that  means  that  he  has  fallen  into  a 
form  of  the  stimulus-error. 

Hillebrand's  comment  here  is  more  to  the  point.  He 
asks  why,  if  clearness  is  an  intensive  attribute  of  sensation, 
there  should  be  only  two  main  levels  of  clearness  at  any 
moment  instead  of  an  unbroken  section  of  the  attributive 
continuum.  I  do  not  know,  though  I  might  if  I  knew  more 
physiology.  I  do  not  know  either  why  the  constant  of  atten- 
tion is  6;  our  theories  of  attention  are  still  nothing  better 
than  more  or  less  plausible  hypotheses.  I  am  trying  only 
to  ascertain  the  psychological  facts.1 

We  are  not  reaping  an  abundant  harvest.  Nor  shall  we 
fare  much  better  if  we  ask,  as  I  now  proceed  to  do,  why  Britz 
objects  to  clearness  as  an  attribute  of  sensation.  He  first 
examines  the  criterion  of  inseparability,  and  finds  that  the 
attribute  of  sensation  is  not  separable  by  sensory  attention 
but  is,  of  course,  separable  by  abstraction.  Then  'as  regards 
clearness'  he  adds:  "not  every  phenomenon  that  is  in- 
separable by  sensory  attention  is  thereby  given  immediate 
status  as  attribute  of  sensation."  This  statement,  in  the 
absence  of  examples,  is  a  little  cryptic;  Britz  may  be  thinking 
of  some  form  of  '  inseparable  association.'  We  need  not  guess, 
however,  since  the  conclusion  is  simply  a  non  liquet.  He 
asks,  secondly,  whether  the  sensation  disappears  as  a  whole 
when  clearness  becomes  zero,  and  replies  that,  for  Wundt, 
it  does  not;  Wundt  has  two  limens,  the  one  of  consciousness 
and  the  other  of  attention.  How  this  reply  bears  upon  my 
position  I  do  not  understand;  nor,  by  his  own  admission,  does 

1  Op.  cit.,  53;  Hillebrand,  148. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  59 

Britz.  He  examines,  thirdly,  the  criterion  of  independent 
variability,  and  finds  that  clearness  is  not  an  independent 
variable.  He  forgets  (though  Hillebrand  had  told  him)  that 
I  recognize  bound  attributes  as  well  as  free.  He  asks,  fourthly, 
whether  a  reference  to  clearness  is  necessary  to  the  complete 
description  of  a  sensation,  and  decides  that  it  is  not.  "Can 
we  characterize  a  sensation  completely  without  recourse  to  the 
notion  of  clearness  ?  I  must  answer  this  question  in  the  affirm- 
ative." Yes,  but  he  does  not  show  us  in  a  concrete  case  how 
the  thing  may  be  done.  Further:  a  supposed  attribute  may 
prove  to  be  analyzable  into  a  number  of  really  primary  attri- 
butes. Yes,  and  I  have  been  on  my  guard;  witness  my  treat- 
ment of  Aufdringlichkeit  and  of  tonal  quality.  Britz  quotes 
no  cases.  Further :  very  few  psychologists  have  regarded  clear- 
ness as  an  attribute  of  sensation.  Yes,  again:  and  how  has 
attention  fared  in  the  history  of  psychology  ?  Listen  to  Ebbing- 
haus:  "Attention  is  a  real  perplexity  in  psychology.  Both  in 
the  general  run  of  English  associationism  and  in  certain  com- 
prehensive works  down  to  the  present  day  it  is  altogether  ig- 
nored. In  other  books  it  bears  the  strangest  relation  to  the 
systematic  presentation  of  the  whole  subject,  and  sometimes 
an  author  seems  to  be  entirely  helpless."  And  when  psy- 
chology came  to  deal  with  sensations?  I  quote  Ebbinghaus 
once  more.  "All  statements  of  any  exactness  regarding 
sensations,  their  attributes,  their  liminal  values,  etc.,  imply 
from  first  to  last — as  everybody  always  understands  without 
being  specially  told — that  a  high  degree  of  attention  was  given 
to  them."  In  other  words:  so  long  as  psychology  dealt  with 
the  full  attentive  consciousness,  we  made  no  solid  progress; 
and  when  psychology  acquired  methods  of  precision,  attention 
was  taken  for  granted.  Now  that  a  suggestion  for  the  be- 
ginnings of  an  exact  psychology  of  attention  are  forthcoming, 
one  would  think  they  were  worth  a  trial.  Very  few  psycholo- 
gists have  agreed,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  upon  any  general  view 
of  attention.1 

There  remains,  fifthly,  the  empirical  side  of  an  issue  al- 

I0p.  cit.,  23,  24,  30,  31;  'Text-book,'  54  f.,  95;  'Feeling  and  Attention,'  26  f., 
326  f.;  H.  Ebbinghaus,  'Grundziige  der  Psychologic,'  1902,  I.,  585  f.,  588. 


60  E.  B.   TITCHENER 

ready  raised  theoretically.  Is  clearness  analyzable  and  not 
simple,  derivative  and  not  primary?  Britz  replies,  on  the 
ground  of  critical  discussion  and  of  experimental  work,  with 
an  emphatic  Yes.  Clearness  (both  Wundt's  and  mine,  appar- 
ently) is  a  very  mixed  concept,  deriving  partly  from  the  meta- 
physical philosophy  of  Leibniz,  partly  from  popular  psy- 
chology (we  talk  of  *  clear'  colors  as  we  talk  of  'pure'  tones), 
and  partly  from  the  properly  psychological  distinction  of 
degrees  of  consciousness;  it  may  thus  be  very  variously  em- 
ployed, under  various  empirical  conditions,  and  its  employ- 
ment always  implies  a  process  which  is  of  the  nature  of  judg- 
ment. 

I  have,  now,  said  something  of  the  value  of  Britz's  critical 
discussion,  and  I  could  say  a  good  deal  of  the  value  of  his 
experiments.  He  worked  with  the  tachistoscope  (not  know- 
ing, of  course,  what  I  had  said  of  that  in  'Feeling  and  Atten- 
tion,' though  he  had  read  Mittenzwey);  he  required  his 
observers  to  cognize  and  name  (erkennen  und  benennen)  the 
colors  exposed;  and  he  employed  a  wissentliches  Verjahren  to 
the  extent,  at  any  rate,  that  they  knew  the  nature  of  his 
problem.  What  the  tachistoscopic  analysis  of  the  Erken- 
nungsvorgang  has  to  do,  in  any  direct  way,  with  the  study  of 
attributive  clearness,  it  is  difficult  to  see.1  I  shall  not,  how- 
ever, enter  into  detailed  criticism;  experiment  is  best  met  by 
experiment;  and  while  a  repetition  of  Britz's  work  will  hardly 
help  us  to  a  psychology  of  clearness,  it  may  throw  light  upon 
the  psychology  of  Eindringlichkeit  or  insistence. 

No  higher  honor  can  be  paid  a  scientific  theory  than  criti- 
cal discussion  based  upon  experiments  which  are  conceived 
and  carried  out  expressly  to  test  its  validity.  Here,  however, 
is  a  discussion  that  leaves  out  of  account  the  original  state- 
ment of  the  theory,  and  relies  wholly  upon  secondary  sources; 
and  here  are  experiments  that  fall  into  line  with  the  work 
of  Schumann  and  his  school,  but  by  the  same  token  are 
directed  upon  a  complex  process  of  assimilation.  It  is  a 
great  disappointment. 

1  Op.  cit.,  40,  42  f.,  54  ff.,  67  ff.,  75;  K.  Mittenzwey,  Psych.  Stud.,  II.,  1907,  386  ff. 
("Im  Begriff  der  Assimilation  findet  sich  von  einem  Merkmal  der  Klarheit  zunachst 
gar  nichts.") 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONCEPT  OF  CLEARNESS  61 

Postscript. — Since  writing  this  paper  I  have  learned  that 
Dr.  Britz  is  numbered  among  the  victims  of  the  war.  It  goes 
against  the  grain  to  criticise  thus  sharply  an  author  who  can 
no  longer  reply.  Yet  I  am  sure  that  Britz  would  have  wished 
his  work  to  be  seriously  considered;  and  since  the  points  really 
at  issue  are  not  personal,  but  scientific,  it  is  perhaps  not  too 
much  to  hope  that  some  other  pupil  of  Schumann  or  Lipps 
may  carry  further  the  study  of  clearness  which  Britz  began. 


COMPOUND   SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR 

BY  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 
St.  Louis ,  Mo. 

The  average  man  does  not  seem  to  care  much  how  his 
brain  works.  There  are  many  inquiring  minds,  however, 
that  are  striving  to  add  to  the  sum  of  human  knowledge  of 
the  brain  and  its  operations  which  serve  to  adjust  the  man's 
inner  relations  to  his  outer  relations.  The  search  for  facts  in 
this  field  is  certain  to  be  guided  more  or  less  by  theories  that 
are  based  on  the  results  of  preceding  investigations. 

These  theories,  of  course,  must  be  remodeled  from  time 
to  time.  At  the  present  day  we  find  that  there  are  certain 
theories  of  nervous  mechanisms  that  are  given  some  accept- 
ance in  scientific  circles.  In  brief  outline  these  theories  show 
that  each  nervous  impulse  enters  the  nervous  system  at  a 
receptor  that  is  either  external  or  internal.  It  then  passes 
from  neurone  (nerve  fiber)  to  neurone  across  the  connecting 
synapses  or  junctions.  Following  the  course  that  is  most 
open  to  it,  it  tends  to  arrive  at  one  or  more  muscles  or  other 
effectors.  The  theories  give  a  clear  account  of  reflex  action. 
They  also  account  in  some  degree  for  associative  memory  in 
its  elementary  forms.  They  show  for  example  an  explanation 
of  substitution  of  one  stimulus  for  another  and  an  explana- 
tion of  memorizing  a  series  of  words.1 

In  this  article  it  is  proposed  to  extend  these  theories  and 
seek  to  explain  more  complex  responses  or  rather  responses  to 
more  complex  stimuli  such  as  appear  in  first  lessons  in  mental 
arithmetic,  for  example.  We  will  begin  by  noting  some 
effects  of  greater  numbers  of  neurones.  We  will  then  discuss 
briefly  the  formation  of  simple  associations  and  the  substitu- 
tion of  one  stimulus  for  another  through  association  and  also 
the  linking  of  movements  into  a  definite  order  or  series.  The 
relation  of  such  a  movement  series  to  what  is  known  as 

1  Watson,  John  B.,  'Behavior,'  New  York,  Holt,  1914,  pp.  272,  274. 
62 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  63 

delayed  reaction  will  then  be  taken  up.  With  this  prepara- 
tion we  will  attack  the  main  problem  before  us;  i.  e.,  responses 
to  complex  stimuli. 

To  make  a  proper  beginning  we  will  start  with  a  brief 
definition  of  the  more  important  terms  we  shall  use. 

Selective  reaction  is  a  form  of  simple  association.  It  is 
the  type  of  behavior  shown  when  a  child  points  to  an  object 
upon  hearing  its  name  pronounced.  It  is  always  the  result 
of  training  or  experience. 

Substitution  will  be  used  to  express  simple  substitution 
and  is  the  type  of  behavior  where  one  stimulus  takes  the 
place  of  another  in  provoking  a  given  movement.  It  is  the 
result  of  training  as  in  the  case  of  young  chickens  running  up 
at  the  sound,  'Here  chick,  chick,'  without  waiting  to  see  the 
food. 

Delayed  reaction  is  the  term  used  for  a  case  of  selective 
reaction  or  substitution  when  the  response  does  not  come 
immediately  after  the  determining  or  substitute  stimulus. 
Several  seconds  or  several  minutes  may  elapse  between  the 
stimulus  that  determines  the  movement  and  the  corre- 
sponding response. 

A  memorized  series  is  a  series  of  movements  made  in  a 
definite  order  from  previous  training.  When  a  dog  is  made 
to  'fetch'  he  performs  a  memorized  series  that  he  has  been 
taught. 

Compound  substitution  is  the  same  in  apparent  form  as 
simple  substitution  but  requires  the  cooperation  of  several 
stimuli  to  provoke  the  response.  Herbert  Spencer  in  ex- 
plaining instinct1  used  the  term  compound  reflex  action  to 
describe  automatic  behavior  in  which  complex  stimuli  pro- 
duce complex  movements.  In  compound  substitution  we 
have  a  similar  term.  When  you  teach  a  boy  to  give  a  correct 
answer  to  the  question  "Two  and  one  make  how  many?" 
you  are  developing  a  mechanism  for  compound  substitution. 
If  we  attempt  to  analyze  this  case  after  the  habit  is  fixed,  we 
see  that  the  sound  of  the  word  two  cannot  have  a  great 
tendency  to  provoke  the  utterance  of  the  word  three.  We  see 

1  'Principles  of  Psychology,'  New  York,  Appleton,  1894,  Vol.  I,  p.  432. 


64  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

that  the  sound  of  the  word  one  cannot  have  a  great  tendency 
to  provoke  the  word  three.  The  same  is  true  for  the  other 
words  of  the  question  asked,  when  taken  separately  and  yet 
taken  together,  the  words  do  provoke  the  response  *  Three.' 
How  may  we  account  for  this  ? 

We  see  at  once  that  it  is  much  harder  to  account  for 
compound  substitution  than  it  is  for  simple  substitution.  It 
is  not  so  very  difficult  to  think  of  connecting  nervous  path- 
ways that  would  allow  one  stimulus  to  excite  a  movement 
which  before  training  required  a  different  stimulus.  Neither 
is  it  very  difficult  to  think  of  connecting  paths  that  would 
allow  a  stimulus  from  one  receptor  to  open  up  a  passage  for 
a  stimulus  from  another  receptor,  as  in  a  case  of  selective 
reaction.  When  we  come  to  compound  substitution,  how- 
ever, we  find  a  different  matter.  We  must  now  provide  for 
cooperation  of  stimuli,  or,  if  you  prefer  it,  for  the  resolution 
of  nervous  impulses.  It  would  seem  that  a  new  principle  is 
required.  This  is  the  problem  which  we  are  to  discuss. 
If  the  theories  we  now  have  covering  association  and  sub- 
stitution are  worth  demonstration,  the  extension  of  these 
theories  to  cover  compound  substitution  must  be  also  worth 
while. 

Having  this  much  knowledge  of  what  we  are  seeking  and 
why,  let  us  proceed  with  the  search.  Having  noted  what  a 
great  gap  there  is  between  simple  substitution  and  compound 
substitution,  let  us  now  hunt  for  the  missing  links. 

In  the  course  of  this  discussion  it  will  be  shown  that  the 
key  to  the  mechanisms  for  a  memorized  series  will  prove  to 
be  a  missing  link  as  it  were. 

Let  us  here  briefly  consider  the  effect  of  numbers  of  nerve 
fibers  in  the  system.  The  greater  the  number  of  nerve  fibers 
that  are  simultaneously  aroused  and  tributary  to  a  given 
muscle  the  stronger  will  be  the  contraction  if  any  occurs  and 
moreover  the  greater  will  be  the  tendency  to  contract  actually. 
The  superiority  of  the  human  mind  over  the  brute  mind  must 
be  largely  due  to  the  greatly  superior  number  of  the  neurones 
that  control  movement.  A  dog  can  be  trained  to  respond  to  a 
simple  command  but  not  to  a  long  speech.  A  child  can  be 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  65 

trained  to  respond  to  a  simple  command  and  by  further 
training,  he  comes  to  respond  to  very  lengthy  instructions. 

The  act  of  a  thoughtful  man  is  due  to  the  joint  excitation 
of  many  neurones.  To  educate  a  child,  we  first  train  him 
to  respond  to  simple  commands  from  the  effect  of  association. 
For  each  act  thus  learned,  one  or  more  association  nerve 
fibers  must  be  developed.  We  may  say  that  each  step  of 
learning  is  the  development  of  a  particular  association  fiber. 
Step  by  step,  the  child  learns  to  talk.  Step  by  step,  he  learns 
to  write,  to  read,  and  to  count. 

By  way  of  further  preparing  a  foundation  for  our  dis- 
cussion, let  us  agree  that  selective  reaction  and  substitution 
can  be  explained  by  the  dual  common  path  theory,  which  is 
that  for  every  unit  association  of  which  the  nerve  system  is 
capable,  there  is  a  common  nerve  path  which  is,  we  will  say, 
an  association  fiber.  Moreover  each  association  fiber  has 
two  tributary  fibers  or  private  nerve  paths  coming  from  two 
different  receptors  or  sensory  terminals. 

Each  impulse  that  follows  the  common  path  leaves  a 
resistance  temporarily  lessened  for  a  subsequent  impulse. 
Each  impulse  from  a  private  path  goes  by  way  of  the  associa- 
tion fiber  to  a  certain  muscle  or  other  effector.  If  the  re- 
sistance is  low  enough,  a  feeble  impulse  will  reach  the  effector. 
Let  us  call  such  an  impulse  a  scout  impulse  when  it  only 
serves  to  lower  the  resistance  for  the  next  impulse.  Let  us 
also,  on  the  other  hand,  call  an  impulse  that  follows  a  scout 
impulse  and  is  strong  enough  to  aid  in  causing  movement,  a 
worker  impulse  for  convenience  in  discussion.  When  a  volley 
of  worker  impulses  excite  one  of  a  pair  of  antagonistic  muscles, 
movement  will  take  place  unless  there  be  equal  excitation  of 
the  opposed  muscle. 

By  way  of  illustration,  let  us  think  of  a  child  writing  under 
the  direction  of  his  teacher.  A  certain  movement  may  be 
prompted  by  a  group  of  worker  impulses  from  his  eyes  which 
are  guiding  his  hand  together  with  a  similar  group  from  his 
ear  due  to  the  teacher's  words  and  another  group  of  tactile 
impulses  from  the  feel  of  the  penholder,  etc.,  and  still  another 
group  from  his  hand  and  arm;  i.  e.,  kinaesthetic  impulses  from 


66  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

the  muscles  and  joints  due  to  movements  just  made.  All 
these  worker  impulses  reinforce  each  other  and  compel  the 
contraction  of  a  certain  muscle.  This  illustration  shows  how 
some  of  the  so-called  voluntary  movements  are  caused. 
Such  movements  are  determined  by  previous  training  as 
each  worker  impulse  comes  by  way  of  an  association  fiber 
which  has  been  developed  by  previous  impulses.  It  is  plain 
that  the  formation  of  a  single  letter  is  due  to  a  large  number 
of  association  nerve  fibers  working  together  like  the  instru- 
ments of  a  great  orchestra. 

To  apply  the  theory  of  the  dual  common  path  to  a  typi- 
cal case  of  selective  reaction,  we  may  use  the  following  illus- 
tration. The  sound  of  the  word  'ball'  spoken  by  the  nurse 
excites  a  short  series  of  scout  impulses  in  the  boy's  brain, 
each  opening  up  some  common  path.  The  sight  of  the  ball 
produces  worker  impulses  that  follow  along  the  common 
paths  opened  by  the  scout  impulses.  Of  course  these  paths 
were  developed  by  the  repetition  of  impulses  in  some  previous 
experience.  The  worker  impulses  now  provoke  the  move- 
ment of  pointing  at  the  ball.  The  result  is  due  to  recency 
and  frequency  of  stimuli  in  altering  resistance  to  conduction. 

In  the  case  of  substitution,  the  application  is  similar. 
Let  us  take  this  illustration:  Show  a  horse  an  ear  of  corn  and 
then  call  him,  thus  giving  him  a  lesson.  After  several 
lessons,  he  will  come  at  your  call  without  any  corn.  The 
explanation  is  that  the  lessons  opened  up  the  dual  common 
paths  so  that  the  call  after  training  produces  a  sufficient 
volley  of  worker  impulses  to  provoke  a  forward  movement. 
To  express  it  in  a  different  way  the  effect  of  the  lessons  is  to 
set  up  a  *  conditioned  reflex'  as  it  is  called. 

In  his  presidential  address  given  in  the  March,  1916, 
number  of  this  journal  Professor  John  B.  Watson  showed 
how  the  conditioned  reflex  has  been  used  in  behavior  experi- 
ments and  suggested  its  use  for  investigations  of  association 
reaction,  etc.  Let  us  here  note  that  in  the  cases  he  described 
the  conditioned  reflex  is  the  result  of  simple  substitution  and 
appears  when  the  substitute  stimulus  provokes  a  sufficient 
volley  of  worker  impulses  to  produce  reaction.  In  the  case 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  67 

of  compound  substitution,  however,  the  time  element  is  a 
factor.  Hence,  although  we  find  a  resemblance  in  the  opera- 
tions, the  term  reflex  may  be  thought  inappropriate. 

In  order  to  help  the  reader  keep  in  mind  the  way  impulses 
tend  to  follow  recent  impulses  from  other  receptors,  the 
following  illustration  is  offered:  Suppose  that  Mr.  Brown 
leaves  his  home  in  the  suburbs  in  the  morning  after  a  snow- 
storm, on  the  way  to  the  railway  station.  He  breaks  a  path 
through  the  snow.  A  little  later  his  neighbor  Mr.  Jones 
leaves  his  home  and  soon  strikes  Brown's  trail.  His  easiest 
course  is  to  follow  Brown's  track  to  the  station.  We  may 
say  that  Brown  represents  a  scout  impulse  and  Jones  is  like  a 
worker  impulse  that  coming  from  a  different  source  soon  after 
the  scout  impulse,  tends  to  follow  the  same  nerve  path  because 
it  offers  less  resistance. 

Having  now  a  conception  of  how  elementary  nerve 
mechanisms  are  constituted,  let  us  think  how  they  may  be 
coordinated  so  as  to  account  for  a  memorized  series  in  which 
the  movements  follow  the  same  order  in  which  they  were 
made  before,  in  a  similar  situation.  Each  movement  causes 
afferent  or  kinsesthetic  impulses,  some  of  which  may  be 
worker  impulses  that  excite  the  next  movement  while  others 
are  scout  impulses  that  open  up  the  paths  for  other  move- 
ments to  follow.  The  kinsesthetic  impulses  have  become 
substituted  for  other  stimuli  that  were  received  in  early  train- 
ing before  the  habit  was  fixed.  In  this  way  the  movements 
become  linked  together  so  that  it  is  only  necessary  to  provoke 
the  first  movement  of  the  series  and  if  the  external  conditions 
are  right,  the  other  movements  will  follow  automatically  in 
their  proper  order. 

On  consideration  we  see  that  the  important  factors  for  a 
memorized  series  are  the  kinaesthetic  impulses  and  the  asso- 
ciation nerve  fibers  leading  to  the  muscles  that  must  act.  An 
important  thing  for  us  to  remember  in  this  connection  is  that 
the  scout  impulses  sent  through  by  one  movement  of  the  series 
will  facilitate  the  worker  impulses  for  a  movement  that 
follows  after  intervening  movements  and  a  considerable 
interval  of  time. 


68  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

Let  us  now  pass  on  to  the  behavior  known  as  delayed 
reaction. 

Let  us  suppose  a  small  dog  placed  in  a  box  so  constructed 
that  he  can  see  two  openings  in  front  of  him,  one  to  the  right 
and  one  to  the  left  but  cannot  reach  either  until  the  bar  in 
front  of  him  is  removed.  Over  each  opening  is  a  green  light 
that  can  be  switched  on  or  off  by  the  operator.  One  opening 
always  leads  to  food,  the  other  does  not.  Sometimes  one 
opening  and  sometimes  the  other  leads  to  food.  To  train 
the  dog  the  operator  turns  on  the  light  over  the  opening 
with  food.  After  giving  the  dog  time  to  notice  the  light  he 
turns  it  off  and  half  a  minute  later  releases  him.  After  a 
number  of  trials  the  dog  becomes  trained  so  that  when  re- 
leased he  goes  at  once  to  the  opening  where  the  light  was 
seen.  We  may  explain  the  behavior  in  this  way:  The  sight 
of  a  light  over  the  right-hand  opening  excites  certain  nerve 
paths.  That  is,  it  causes  impulses  that  follow  certain  nerve 
paths.  The  performance  of  going  to  the  right-hand  opening 
is  a  series  of  movements  due  to  impulses  following  certain 
nerve  paths.  Let  us  suppose  that  there  are  particular  asso- 
ciation nerve  paths  that  are  common  to  each  group.  That 
is  to  say,  there  are  particular  association  nerve  fibers  that  are 
aroused  in  executing  the  movement  series  that  are  also 
aroused  by  the  sight  of  the  right-hand  light. 

The  common  paths  will  get  two  excitations  whenever  the 
dog  makes  the  proper  turn  at  the  proper  time.  The  double 
excitation  may  be  assumed  to  have  the  useful  effect  of 
opening  these  common  paths;  i.  e.,  of  lowering  their  resistance. 
Each  succeeding  lesson  will  further  facilitate  the  appropriate 
behavior.  When  the  common  paths  are  sufficiently  developed 
we  may  explain  the  dog's  actions  by  saying  that  the  right- 
hand  light  produces  scout  impulses  that  temporarily  open 
up  further  the  common  paths  and  the  operation  of  releasing 
the  animal  produces  worker  impulses  that  follow  these  com- 
mon paths  and  provoke  the  movement  of  turning  to  the  right. 
It  appears  then  that  delayed  reactions  are  explained  by  the 
dual  common  path  theory. 

We  may  say  that  delayed  reaction  is  by  nature  only  a 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  69 

special  case  of  selective  reaction.  As  a  further  aid  to  under- 
standing the  matter,  we  may  note  that  a  case  of  delayed 
reaction  is  like  a  memorized  series  where  some  of  the  move- 
ments are  omitted  so  as  to  leave  a  gap  in  it.  For  in  every 
movement  series  that  is  habitually  made,  the  movements  in 
the  first  part  of  the  series  are  associated  with  each  move- 
ment in  the  last  part  of  the  series.  In  other  words  each 
movement  causes  impulses  that  facilitate  or  insure  any  move- 
ment that  has  a  place  further  along  in  the  series  as  we  have 
already  observed. 

We  may  say  then  that  delayed  reactions  are  special  cases 
of  memorized  series  behavior.  Or  we  may  say  with  equal 
propriety  that  a  memorized  series  is  a  compound  of  delayed 
reactions,  meaning  by  this  reactions  that  are  more  or  less 
delayed.  For  each  movement  of  such  a  series,  to  some  ex- 
tent, is  determined  by  impulses  that  preceded  it  by  a  con- 
siderable interval  of  time. 

Behavior  students  have  measured  the  comparative  in- 
telligence of  animals  by  the  delayed  reaction  and  by  the 
memorized  series  as  shown  in  escaping  from  a  maze  or  opening 
a  puzzle  box.  The  more  intelligent  an  animal  is  the  quicker 
it  will  master  a  given  maze  or  puzzle  box  and  the  longer  it 
will  remember  what  it  has  learned. 

The  principle  of  learning  is  no  doubt  the  same  with  the 
animal  that  learns  in  a  few  lessons  as  with  the  animal  that 
requires  many.  The  difference  must  be  in  the  nerve  struc- 
ture with  which  he  begins  the  task.  The  animal  of  high 
intelligence  must  have  more  association  neurones  to  take 
part  in  the  proceedings. 

From  this  brief  study  it  would  appear  that  the  delayed 
reaction  can  be  explained  in  some  measure  by  the  same 
mechanisms  that  are  used  for  simpler  forms  of  behavior. 

We  have  considered  four  types  of  behavior,  selective  reac- 
tion, substitution,  the  memorized  series,  and  delayed  reaction 
and  we  find  in  all  of  them  it  is  a  matter  of  association  nerve 
fibers  that  register  the  frequency  and  recency  of  impulses 
traversing  them  in  the  range  of  experience  and  then  in  turn 
regulate  the  passage  of  impulses  that  provoke  movement. 


70  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

To  put  it  another  way  association  is  the  characteristic  feature 
of  the  four  types  of  behavior. 

This  brings  us  to  the  main  question,  the  explanation  of 
compound  substitution. 

Let  us  consider  the  case  of  a  boy  learning  mental  arith- 
metic. In  the  beginning  he  is  taught  simple  problems. 
He  is  taught  to  make  a  certain  response  to  a  certain  series  of 
ear  stimulations.  For  example  when  he  hears  the  question: 
"Two  and  one  make  how  many?"  He  must  respond, 
"Three."  The  reader  will  see  that  we  have  here  a  case  of 
compound  substitution.  As  the  boy  advances  in  the  study, 
the  series  of  excitations  is  increased  in  length  so  that  there 
are  more  factors  to  be  kept  in  his  mind  as  it  were.  In  master- 
ing each  series  he  really  develops  certain  association  fibers; 
i.  e.,  his  experience  opens  up  certain  nerve  paths.  The  asso- 
ciations formed  in  the  earlier  lessons  take  part  in  working 
out  the  later  problems. 

But  let  us  look  into  the  matter  more  closely.  Suppose 
that  the  boy  learns  to  add  by  counting  on  his  fingers.  At 
the  sound  of  "two"  he  holds  up  two  fingers.  At  the  sound 
"one"  he  holds  up  one  finger  of  the  other  hand.  In  response 
to  "How  many?"  he  puts  his  hands  together  and  counts 
"one,  two,  three"  and  answers  "Three."  Here  we  have  a 
memorized  series  in  which  eye  movements,  finger  movements 
and  ^  vocal  movements  are  linked  together  by  association. 
Let  us  note  that  quite  a  large  number  of  association  neurones 
are  stimulated  in  the  course  of  the  performance.  After  the 
boy  has  mastered  this  series,  he  can  be  trained  to  modify  it 
by  counting  in  a  whisper  and  uttering  the  final  word  three 
aloud.  Then  he  can  be  taught  to  suppress  the  finger  move- 
ments so  that  they  are  incipient  only.  The  eye  movements 
also  become  incipient.  It  is  fair  to  suppose  that  the  number 
of  neurones  stimulated  though  lessened,  is  now  nearly  as 
great  as  when  all  the  movements  were  actually  made,  so  we 
still  have  a  large  number  of  neurones  taking  part  in  the 
response. 

On  consideration  we  see  that  a  certain  series  of  auditory 
excitations  provokes  a  memorized  series  composed  of  move- 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  71 

ments  or  incipient  movements  that  lead  up  to  the  desired 
vocal  response.  In  the  case  where  the  intermediate  move- 
ments are  only  incipient,  we  may  say  that  the  series  of 
excitations  given  by  the  question  heard,  provokes  a  series  of 
scout  impulses  and  the  effect  upon  the  nerve  muscle  system 
produces  a  group  of  worker  impulses  that  excite  the  series  of 
actual  movements  included  in  the  proper  response.  These 
nervous  operations  by  long  practice  become  greatly  abbrevi- 
ated, but  we  may  believe  that  the  successive  character  of  the 
operations  still  remains. 

This  shows  that  a  case  of  compound  substitution  may  be 
evolved  from  a  memorized  series,  so  we  see  how  an  elementary 
case  of  compound  substitution  may  be  explained  as  a  modi- 
fied memorized  series  so  to  speak.  The  same  reasoning  may 
be  followed  to  build  up  cases  of  more  and  more  complexity. 
The  behavior  of  a  skillful  lawyer  engaged  as  referee  in  a  legal 
contest  is  largely  determined  by  compound  substitutions 
which  are  due  to  his  special  training.  His  ability  to  keep  in 
mind  an  astonishing  array  of  pros  and  cons  has  been  built 
up  step  by  step.  Each  step  in  the  case  means  more  move- 
ments linked  in  habit  series  and  a  greater  number  of  asso- 
ciation neurones  stimulated.  When  the  great  lawyer  finally 
gives  his  decision  for  the  plaintiff  or  for  the  defendant,  the 
deciding  movement  is  prompted  by  the  discharge  of  a  large 
number  of  association  neurones  which  have  been  duly  pre- 
pared in  the  course  of  the  proceedings. 

A  performing  elephant  will  respond  to  his  trainer's  signal 
by  one  trick  or  another  depending  upon  the  stage  setting  at 
the  time.  In  the  same  way,  the  great  lawyer  responds  to  his 
stage  setting;  i.  e.,  the  pros  and  cons  of  the  legal  problem. 
The  lawyer's  response,  however,  is  due  to  a  far  greater  num- 
ber of  association  neurones  and  to  a  far  greater  number  of 
steps  in  the  ladder  of  learning. 

It  may  be  noted  that  the  above  given  explanation  of  com- 
pound substitution  rests  to  some  extent  upon  an  assumption 
that  all  incipient  movements  can  in  some  way  cause  afferent 


72  '   S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

impulses  similar  to  the  kinaesthetic  impulses  from  actual 
movements.1 

If  our  view  is  the  correct  one,  a  case  of  compound  substi- 
tution may  be  regarded  as  a  memorized  series  that  has  become 
modified  by  suppressing  the  movements  so  that  of  the  differ- 
ent stimuli  concerned,  each  takes  part  in  determining  the 
resultant  response  and  thus  the  stimuli  do  cooperate.  It  is 
evident  too  that  in  the  case  of  compound  substitution  of  a 
long  series  of  stimuli,  delayed  reaction  plays  an  important 
part  for  the  reason  that  it  takes  part  in  all  memorized  series 
as  we  have  seen. 

It  is  hardly  necessary  to  point  out  that  language  habits 
are  the  basis  of  most  compound  substitutions  in  human 
behavior.  Writing  movements  also  are  an  important  aid  in 
forming  the  required  associations. 

From  this  demonstration  we  may  conclude  that  a  rational 
theory  can  be  formulated  for  nervous  mechanisms  for  com- 
pound substitutions  in  behavior  if  we  may  start  with  a  very 
large  number  of  association  nerve  fibers  to  many  of  which 
there  are  tributary  afferent  fibers  coming  from  the  muscles. 
These  fibers  are  developed  by  practice  through  the  influence 
of  frequency  and  recency.  As  brooks  come  together  to  form 
a  river  so  do  the  worker  impulses  meet  and  provoke  move- 
ment. These  nerve  mechanisms  are  of  great  service  in 
adapting  behavior  to  environments  containing  changeable 
features.  In  the  instinctive  behavior  of  all  highly  organized 
animals  they  have  an  important  part.  They  are  especially 
important  in  child  education.  In  fact  we  might  almost  say 
that  in  any  animal  that  has  a  cerebral  cortex,  behavior  is 
mainly  determined  by  such  mechanisms  or  at  least  modified 
by  them. 

If  our  theory  is  the  true  one,  we  shall  find  that  to  have  a 
greater  intelligence,  the  number  of  association  fibers  must 
be  increased  in  much  greater  ratio. 

If  we  take  a  broad  view  of  the  subject,  compound  substi- 

1 A  discussion  by  the  writer  of  'The  Function  of  Incipient  Motor  Processes'  will 
be  found  in  the  PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1915,  22,  163-166.  The  other  main  assumption 
made  in  this  article  and  termed  the  dual  common  path  theory  is  discussed  by  the 
writer  in  the  PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1916,  23,  235. 


COMPOUND  SUBSTITUTION  IN  BEHAVIOR  73 

tution  in  behavior  may  be  defined  as  an  increase  of  the 
correspondence  between  the  organized  individual  and  its 
environment  in  speciality  and  in  complexity.  Furthermore 
it  is  the  coordination  and  integration  of  correspondences,  so 
to  speak.  The  subject  is  such  an  extensive  one  that  the 
demonstration  given  herein,  to  some  readers,  may  appear 
quite  inadequate.  On  the  other  hand,  to  some  readers,  it 
will  seem  a  lengthy  exposition  of  a  simple  proposition.  It  is 
not  practical  in  a  short  article  to  do  more  than  offer  a  con- 
tribution to  the  general  study  of  this  extensive  subject  with 
sufficient  elaboration  to  make  the  main  idea  plain  to  those 
who  are  searching  for  mechanisms  to  explain  mental  growth. 


THE   DELAYED   REACTION   IN  A   CHILD 

BY  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

The  University  of  Kansas 

INTRODUCTION 

The  present  paper  derives  its  chief  significance  from  the 
fact  that  the  child  tested  did  not  possess  vocal  language  and 
probably  not  gesture  language  either. 

In  the  work  with  the  delayed  reaction  on  children  previ- 
ously published,1  five  subjects  were  used:  M.,  8  years, 
Hd.,  L.,  and  H.,  each  6  years,  and  F.,  2j  years.  All  of  these 
children  possessed  vocal  language.  M.  received  38  trials  on 
delays;  Hd.,  46  trials;  H.,  15  trials;  L.,  41  trials.  All  of  them 
succeeded  with  delays  as  great  as  25  minutes.  There  was 
some  indication  that  the  children  first  encountered  particular 
difficulty  in  the  intervals  from  4-6  sees.  The  child  F.  re- 
ceived 507  trials  on  delays.  Her  maximal  delay  was  50  sees. 
The  periods  of  greatest  difficulty  were  at  5  sees.,  7  sees.,  10 
sees.,  15  sees.,  30  sees.,  and  40  sees.  Although  F.  was  given 
45  trials  on  the  one-minute  delay  and  failed,  it  is  possible 
that  more  prolonged  training  would  have  enabled  her  to 
master  the  interval. 

When  the  present  tests  were  begun,  the  writer  hoped  to 
secure  subjects  who  would  fill  in  the  great  gap  between  the 
child  F.  and  the  older  children.  Success  has  not  attended 
these  efforts  mainly  because  of  a  lack  of  convenient  material. 
One  three-year-old  child  was  tested,  but  the  data  are  of  so 
little  value  that  they  will  not  be  presented.  The  second  and 
fundamental  purpose  of  this  study  was,  however,  to  study  the 
delayed  reaction  in  a  child  too  young  to  possess  vocal  language. 
This  is  of  particular  importance  because  of  Watson's  insistence 
that  the  delayed  reaction,  if  solved  by  internal  factors  other 
than  orientation,  must  be  solved  by  vocal  language. 

1  Hunter,  Walter  S.,  'The  Delayed  Reaction  in  Animals  and  Children,'  Behav. 
Monog.,  1913,  2,  No.  I,  pp.  52-62. 

74 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  75 

The  Subject  Tested. — The  subject  of  these  tests  was  the 
writer's  daughter,  Thayer,  thirteen  to  sixteen  months  of  age 
from  first  to  last  of  the  experimentation.  She  was  a  normal, 
healthy  child  physically — a  little  slow  perhaps  on  the  behavior 
side,  due  to  the  lack  of  the  constant  attention  that  many 
children  receive.  She  learned  to  walk  alone  rather  suddenly 
at  about  15  months;  and  by  16  months,  she  could  indicate 
with  a  little  certainty  her  eyes,  ears,  nose  and  mouth.  When 
13  months  old,  she  could  l throw  a  kiss'  and  wave  ' bye-bye.' 
Even  before  this,  as  early  as  the  tenth  month,  she  swayed 
and  waved  her  arms  to  music.  These  observations  are  pre- 
sented as  a  sample  of  her  best  accomplishments.  She  had 
no  vocal  language.  She  made  many  sounds,  some  of  which 
were  in  response  to  definite  stimuli;  but  in  no  case  did  she 
use  the  sounds  spontaneously  and  in  no  case  did  she  use  them 
as  symbols.  Her  equipment  was  not  large  in  the  first  place, 
and  what  there  was  was  purely  of  a  stimulus-response  nature. 
During  the  period  covered  by  the  experimentation,  the 
following  vocal  behavior  was  present:  ' Daddy'  she  said 
whenever  a  distant  door  was  heard  and  I  was  away,  or  when 
she  heard  me  coming  up  the  steps.  'Whitte'  came  in  re- 
sponse to  the  striking  of  the  clock  or  the  ringing  of  the  door 
bell.  She  could  say  'boob-boob'  for  the  dog;  'day-day'  for 
the  duck;  'm-m-m'  for  the  cow;  a  funny  noise  for  the  donkey; 
and  'y-gob,  y-gob'  for  the  turkey.  These  were  in  response 
to  the  specific  questions,  "What  does  the  dog  say?"  etc. 
Some  of  these  she  got  mixed  up  and  later  forgot  all  but  the 
duck,  the  turkey,  and  the  cow.  In  addition  to  these  vocal 
responses  there  occurred  only  the  more  conventional  baby 
noises. 

One  gesture  might  possibly  be  termed  language,  viz., 
raising  her  arms  to  be  taken  up.  It  is  impossible  to  say, 
however,  that  this  was  not  in  response  to  present  stimuli. 
It  is  also  impossible  to  say  with  any  certainty  whether  or 
not  the  child  used  a  vocal  cry  specifically  "to  attract  atten- 
tion" to  her  needs.  I  have  no  evidence  to  indicate  that 
such  was  the  case.  Experimentation  was  purposely  stopped 
before  the  first  signs  of  language  (in  the  conventional  sense) 
appeared. 


76  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

Apparatus  and  Method. — The  apparatus  used  is  shown  in 
Fig.  I.  It  consists  of  three  boxes  placed  upon  a  stand  whose 
top  is  6  inches  above  the  floor.  Each  box  is  approximately 
3  inches  deep,  4  inches  wide,  and  5  inches  long.  Each  is 
covered  by  a  hinged  top.  The  apparatus  was  wired  for 
electric  lights,  but  these  were  never  used.  Another  type  of 
apparatus  more  nearly  approximating  that  used  with  children 
in  the  previous  work  was  constructed.  It,  however,  proved 
unsuited  to  Thayer  and  was  used  only  with  the  three-year-old 
child. 

The  only  features  necessary  to  secure  in  devising  an  appar- 
atus for  the  delayed  reaction  are  these:  (i)  It  must  be  adapted 
to  the  size  of  the  subject  and  to  its  mode  of  response — walking, 
reaching,  swimming  or  flying.  (2)  It  must  provide  a  means 
for  presenting  a  stimulus  in  one  of  several  places.  (3)  These 
stimulus  positions  must  be  equally  accessible  to  the  response. 
And  (4),  the  stimulus  and  the  method  employed  should  be 
such  as  to  present  no  differential  cues  to  the  subject  during 
the  intervals  of  delay.  These  requirements,  although  rigid, 
are  simple  and  can  be  met  for  practically  all  organisms.  I  am 
therefore  unable  to  agree  with  Professor  Yerkes  when  he 
says1  that  the  multiple  choice  method  of  studying  ideational 
behavior  is  superior  to  all  others  in:  (i)  applicability  to  a 
wide  range  of  conditions;  (2)  susceptibility  to  standardiza- 
tion; (3)  quantitative  nature  of  results;  and  (4)  intelligibility 
of  data  acquired.  Nor  can  I  acquiesce  in  the  claim  that 
"It  is  already  obvious  that  the  method  enables  us  to  com- 
pare, as  has  never  before  been  possible,  the  responses  to 
certain  standard  situations,  of  human  and  infra-human,  nor- 
mal and  abnormal,  mature  and  immature  subjects."  Both 
the  multiple  choice  and  the  delayed  reaction  methods  are 
valuable  for  the  study  of  human  and  animal  behavior;  but 
they  are  applicable,  I  think,  to  very  different  problems. 

In  the  experiments  reported  in  this  paper,  the  following 
method  was  used.  Thayer  sat  in  front  of  the  apparatus,  as 
shown  in  Fig.  I,  and  the  stimulus  object  was  placed  in  her 

1  Yerkes,  Robt.  M.,  'Methods  of  Studying  Ideational  Behavior  in  Man  and  Other 
Animals,'  PSYCHOL.  BULL.,  1915,  12,  330-331. 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  77 

hand.  A  great  variety  of  things  were  used  for  stimuli:  dolls, 
keys,  rattles,  shoe-buttoners,  small  books,  etc.  Every  effort 
was  made  to  keep  up  the  child's  interest.  Occasionally  two 
different  stimulus  objects  were  used  in  the  course  of  the 
day's  work.  Such  methods  are  necessary  if  a  child  of  this 
age  is  even  to  approximate  to  the  vigor  with  which  a  hungry 


FIG.  i.     Thayer  opening  box  c. 

animal  attacks  its  problem.  The  stimulus  object  was  taken 
away  from  the  child  almost  as  soon  as  she  received  it  and 
was  placed  in  one  of  the  boxes.  The  lid  of  the  box  was  left 
open  and  Thayer  was  pushed  over  (or  permitted  to  lean  over) 
and  made  to  look  into  the  box.  Often  she  tried  to  reach  in 
and  get  the  stimulus;  but  in  every  case,  her  hand  was  with- 
drawn and  she  was  raised  back  to  an  upright  position.  The 
lid  of  the  box  was  now  closed.  Save  for  a  few  instances  to 
be  mentioned  in  due  time,  the  subject  was  distracted  during 
the  interval  of  delay.  Distraction  took  either  one  of  several 
forms:  (i)  I  might  place  my  hands  over  her  eyes  and  rock 
her  body  back  and  forth  from  right  to  left.  (2)  She  might 
be  stood  up,  turned  around  with  her  back  to  the  apparatus, 
kept  there  awhile  and  then  put  down.  (3)  I  might  cause 
her  to  turn  her  head  by  speaking  to  her.  She  would  remain 
in  this  position  and  imitate  animals  for  me  (as  described 


7S  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

above  under  vocal  habits)  as  long  as  any  delays  here  used 
required.  About  2  sees,  before  the  end  of  the  delay  period, 
her  body  was  straightened  around  and  she  sat  facing  the 
middle  box,  &,  entirely  free  from  contact  with  me.  (She 
almost  never  looked  back  at  me;  and  when  she  did,  she  paid 
no  further  attention  to  the  problem.  I  never  spoke  to  her 
during  the  delay.  These  facts  together  with  the  child's  in- 
ability to  reach  delays  of  a  minute  or  more,  indicate  that  she 
was  not  deriving  cues  from  the  experimenter.)  Thayer  was 
now  left  to  her  own  devices  until  she  opened  the  box  con- 
taining the  stimulus  object.  In  all  but  a  few  cases,  she  began 
to  hunt  for  the  stimulus  as  soon  as  she  was  straightened 
around.  Time  was  taken  with  an  ordinary  watch  and  was 
counted  from  the  moment  the  box  lid  was  closed  until  the 
subject  made  some  movement  toward  one  of  the  boxes.  In 
the  records  particular  attention  was  given  to  the  orientation 
at  the  time  of  response  and  to  the  behavior  during  the  delay. 
A  reaction  was  counted  wrong  if  the  child  opened  any  box 
save  that  containing  the  stimulus. 

EXPERIMENTAL  RESULTS 

In  this  experiment  there  was  no  period  of  learning  the 
association  between  the  stimulus  object  and  the  three  boxes. 
Seeking  for  objects  that  had  disappeared  was  already  a 
part  of  the  subject's  behavior  equipment.  I  noticed  as  early 
as  her  eleventh  month  that  if  I  showed  her  a  toy  and  then 
hid  it  behind  something,  she  would  immediately  reach  or 
creep  toward  the  spot.  I  have  no  doubt,  however,  that  this 
type  of  reaction  occurred  earlier.  The  present  test  was 
more  complex  than  this  in  that  the  toy  might  be  in  either  one 
of  three  different  places. 

I  quote  the  following  from  my  diary  records  indicating 
the  results  at  the  very  beginning  of  the  work.  "Date,  10- 
23-15.  Trial  I.  Toys  put  in  middle  box  and  door  shut. 
(All  this  done  by  Thayer  on  her  own  initiative.)  I  now  put 
my  hands  over  her  eyes  and  shook  her  head  and  whole  body 
playfully  but  thoroughly.  No  orientation  of  upper  part  of 
body  retained.  13  sees,  delay  from  time  she  straightened  up 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD 


79 


after  closing  box  until  she  reached  toward  b.  She  reacted 
correctly,  straight  to  middle  box." 

"Trial  2.  Toys  put  in  right  box,  a.  12  sees,  delay  with 
distraction  as  above.  Reacted  correctly." 

"Trial  3.     Same  as  No.  2,  13  sees,  delay.     O.  K." 

"Trial  4.  Thayer  preferred  right  or  middle  box.  I  had 
her  put  toys  in  left  one,  c.  Distraction  by  standing  her  up 
and  turning  her  to  me.  17  sees.  O.  K." 

"Trial  5.  Middle  box  used.  Baby  tired  of  test.  14  sees. 
Distracted  as  in  first  trial.  Reaction  wrong." 

In  these  tests  made  on  the  first  day,  Thayer  missed  one 
of  five  or  20  percent.  The  delays  ranged  from  12-17  sees. 
Distraction  was  always  used.  The  same  orientation  at  the 
moment  of  release  was  held  for  all,  viz.,  orientation  to  b. 
These  long  delays  were  very  startling  and  held  out  a  promise 
of  very  rapid  development  through  training.  This  was  the 
last  of  October.  A  longer  stage  of  delay  was  not  success- 
fully reached  and  consistently  maintained  until  after  Christ- 
mas. This  fact  is  shown  in  Table  L 

TABLE  I 


Delay  in  Sees. 

Correct  Trs. 

Wrong  Trs. 

Percent.  Correct 

3 

3 

O 

IOO 

4 

I 

O 

100 

6 

0 

IOO 

6 

3 

0 

IOO 

7 

2 

2 

50 

8 

4 

2 

66 

9 

4 

I 

80 

10 

ii 

4 

73 

ii 

6 

2 

75 

12 

6 

3 

66 

13 

s 

O 

IOO 

H 

6 

8 

42 

is 

13 

ii 

54 

16 

5 

5 

50 

17 

4 

3 

57 

18 

2 

i 

66 

19 

I 

i 

50 

20 

9 

IS 

37 

21 

i 

5 

16 

22 

2 

3 

40 

23 

I 

o 

IOO 

24 

2 

3 

40 

25 

0 

3 

o 

26 

I 

i 

50 

30 

3 

5 

37 

35 

2 

0 

IOO 

So 


WALTER  S.  HUNTER 


This  table  shows  the  size  of  the  delays  and  the  number  of 
correct  and  incorrect  reactions  made.  All  trials  given  the 
subject  through  December  2  are  included.  The  statement 
is  not  chronological.  The  reason  the  intervals  of  delay 
increase  so  gradually  is  that  within  a  few  seconds  variation, 
Thayer  herself  determined  when  she  would  begin  the  reac- 
tion. All  I  could  do  was  to  place  her  facing  the  apparatus 
and  await  results.  Table  II.  groups  the  delays  into  five 


TABLE  II 


Delays 

3-7    sees. 

8-12      " 

13-17      " 
18-22      " 


Percent  Correct 


.72 

•55 
•37 
•44 


classes  which  may  be  called  the  5  sec.,  10  sec.,  15  sec.,  20  sec., 
and  25  sec.  intervals.  The  10  sec.  interval  may  be  regarded 
as  mastered,  bat  no  higher  interval.  (This  is  understated, 
as  will  be  indicated  below.)  Table  III.  gives  data  gathered 

TABLE  III 


Delay  in  Sees. 

Right 

Wronj 

Percent  Right 

6 

4 
o 

O 

77 

8 
9 

3 

2 
I 

I 

O 

o 

82 

10 

12 
T  r 

IO 
2 
2C                     { 

3 
»               8 

7c 

20 

2C 

24 
2 

IO. 
2 

70 
50 

from  January  2  through  January  10.  An  interval  of  one 
month  had  elapsed  during  which  no  tests  were  made.  A  com- 
parison of  Tables  II.  and  III.  indicates  a  marked  gain  in 
ability  to  deal  with  the  15  sec.  and  20  sec.  intervals.  In 
Table  III.  the  15  sec.  interval  can  be  regarded  as  mastered 
and  the  20  sec.  interval  as  practically  perfected. 

The  tables  just  given  are  valuable  in  showing  just  what 
the  child  actually  did  in  the  work  as  a  whole.     Her  achieve- 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  81 

ments  are  much  obscured,  however,  by  such  a  presentation, 
inasmuch  as  poor  incentives  and  position  factors  frequently 
dragged  her  total  percentages  down.  Here,  e.  g.,  is  the  diary 
record  for  the  ten  tests  made  November  12.  (Data  included 
in  Table  I.)  The  delays  were  all  above  20  sees.,  and  7  trials 
of  10  were  successful.  Where  the  word  'distracted'  is  used, 

TABLE  IV 

Box  with  Toy                                     Delay                                     Behavior 
20  sees,  distracted a 


a 

22       ' 

«                ii 

bed 

c 

21 

« 

.  .  .  .abc 

c 

2O 

« 

.  .  .  .  c 

b  
d 

35 

22 

« 

stood  her  up  .  .  . 

.  .  .  .b  very  slow  and  *  careful.' 
...  .a 

c 

26 

distracted 

c 

b  
c  

c  .  . 

20 
22 

.  .24. 

« 
stood  her  UD  .  . 

....b 
.  .  .  .c 

.  .ac 

Thayer's  eyes  were  covered  and  her  body  was  shaken  back 
and  forth;  or  she  was  induced  to  look  up  at  the  ceiling  and 
listen  to  me  count  while  I  waved  her  arms  about.  The 
letters  in  the  last  column  indicate  to  which  box  the  reactions 
were  made.  In  every  case  the  subject  was  oriented,  body  and 
face,  to  b  at  the  moment  of  reaction.  This  day's  record  is 
better  than  any  that  preceded  it.  Two  weeks  previously, 
she  had  succeeded  with  intervals  between  n  and  19  sees. 
But  during  those  two  weeks  that  followed,  she  was  largely 
the  victim  of  position  habits.  The  day  following  the  above 
diary  record,  she  again  fell  back  into  position  habits.  I  kept 
holding  pretty  well  to  15  and  20  sec.  delays  with  an  occasional 
one  at  30  sees.  The  task  was  too  difficult,  however,  and  she 
shifted  from  one  position  habit  to  another. 

Work  was  discontinued  for  a  month.  By  the  end  of  this 
time,  the  following  changes  had  occurred  in  the  child:  (i)  old 
position  habits  were  temporarily  lost;  (2)  new  interest  was 
taken  in  the  problem;  (3)  greatly  increased  control  of  her 
own  body  appeared — shown  mostly  in  walking  and  balanc- 
ing; and  (4)  a  stronger  aversion  to  being  held  during  distrac- 
tions had  developed. 


82 


WALTER  S.  HUNTER 


Table  III.  above  summarizes  the  results  for  this  period. 
It  also  understates  the  subject's  behavior.  On  January  5, 
she  made  the  entire  day — 9  trials — at  15  sees,  without  error 
and  with  no  correlation  between  orientation  and  direction  of 
response.  She  now  fell  into  a  position  habit,  but  recovered 
and  made  20  sees,  delay  correctly  5  times  in  succession,  again 
with  no  dependence  upon  orientation. 

Thayer's  best  delays  may  be  recorded  as  20-24  secs-  The 
child  F.  used  in  the  earlier  work  reached  a  delay  of  50  secs. 
F.'s  record  would  probably  have  been  higher  had  she  been 
tested  with  a  method  similar  to  the  one  here  employed,  i.  e., 
a  method  where  the  satisfaction  is  derived  from  the  stimulus 
object  and  not  from  an  associated  food  supply.  The  gap 
between  Thayer  and  F.  would  undoubtedly  be  bridged  in  a 
gradual  manner  by  a  continuous  increase  in  periods  of  delay. 
Greatest  interest  now  centers  on  children  of  less  than  one 
year  of  age.  How  early  ontogenetically  does  this  ability  to 
react  independently  of  orientation  appear? 

It  remains  to  comment  upon  the  position  habits  and 
errors  that  appeared.  The  frequency  with  which  these 
stereotyped  forms  of  response  interfered  with  the  work  and 
the  j act  that  the  child  if  permitted  would  watch  the  box  containing 
the  toy  during  the  interval  of  delay,  indicate  the  great  import- 
ance of  kinaesthesis  in  the  response.  Position  habits  occurred 
with  each  of  the  three  boxes  so  that  during  a  particular  posi- 
tion habit  period  Thayer  always  chose  a  particular  box  first. 
I  made  no  tests  where  the  choice  lay  between  two  boxes  as 
opposed  to  three.  Time  is  limited  both  by  the  speed  with 
which  a  baby  grows  and  even  more  by  the  necessity  of  staying 
within  the  limits  of  the  child's  interest  and  patience.  Table  V 

TABLE  V 


Total  Reactions 
Made 

Order  of  response 

cba 

cab 

CO, 

cb 

No  made 

17 

11 

8 

28 

66 

Order  of  response  .......... 

abc 

acb 

ac 

ab 

No.  made  

6 

3 

2 

II 

22 

Order  of  response  

bac 

bca 

be 

ba 

No.  made  

7 

3 

7 

9 

26 

THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  83 

analyses  all  incorrect  responses  and  gives  the  relative  number 
of  times  the  subject  followed  the  different  possible  orders. 
Thus  when  an  error  was  made,  17  times  Thayer  first  opened  c, 
then  b  and  then  a.  The  table  shows  that  three  times  more 
errors  were  made  beginning  with  box  c  than  with  any  of 
the  others.  When  the  subject  opened  c  first,  she  opened  b 
next  45  times  out  of  66,  or  68  percent  of  the  time.  When 
she  opened  a  first,  she  chose  b  next  15  times  out  of  20,  or  75 
percent  of  the  time.  When  b  was  opened  first,  a  was  chosen 
next  1 6  times  out  of  26,  or  6 1  percent  of  the  time.  In  other 
words,  when  the  reaction  began  at  the  end  of  the  apparatus 
the  tendency  was  to  take  the  boxes  in  order  until  the  solution 
was  reached.  Only  six  times  in  all  did  the  subject  go  to  the 
same  box  twice  in  the  same  trial.  These  cases  are  distributed 
throughout  the  entire  period  of  experimentation.  The  fol- 
lowing is  a  record  of  the  order  of  the  boxes  chosen: 

cccab 

bcba 

cacb 

cacb 

bcba 

cacacab. 

Of  the  114  errors  recorded  in  Table  V.,  32  (28  percent)  oc- 
curred when  the  box  containing  the  toy  on  the  last  previous 
trial  was  re-selected.  Inasmuch,  however,  as  such  a  mode  of 
response  often  led  to  success  the  percentage  is  very  low. 
This  form  of  behavior  as  well  as  that  of  the  six  instances  above 
given  is  apparently  far  less  current  in  the  present  subject 
than  in  Hamilton's  dog.1  The  later  study  made  by  Hamilton2 
reports  the  case  of  a  child  26  months  old.  Out  of  38  trials, 
60.53  percent  (34.21  plus  26.32)  of  the  reactions  involved  the 
type  of  behavior  given  just  above  as  occurring  but  6  times 
during  the  present  work,  264  trials.  Since  Thayer  missed 
120  trials  (66  plus  22  plus  26  plus  6),  her  percentage  is  5. 

1  Hamilton,  G.  V.  T.,  'An  Experimental  Study  of  an  Unusual  Type  of  Reaction 
in  a  Dog,'  /.  of  Comp.  Neur.  PsychoL,  1907,  17,  329-341. 

2  Hamilton,  G.  V.  T.,  'A  Study  of  Trial  and  Error  Reactions  in  Mammals,'  /.  of 
Animal  Behav.,  1911,  i,  p.  51. 


84 


WALTER  S.  HUNTER 


This  extreme  difference  in  behavior  is  undoubtedly  due  to 
one  or  both  of  the  following  causes:  (i)  the  guiding  influence 
of  the  absent  stimulus  in  the  delayed  reaction  tests;  and  (2) 
the  fact  that  only  three  boxes  were  used  here  as  opposed  to 
Hamilton's  four.  It  would  be  very  interesting  to  determine 
whether  a  variation  in  the  number  of  boxes  would  result  in  a 
corresponding  variation  in  *  reaction  tendencies.'  If  this 
were  true,  the  possibility  of  phyletic  correlations  would  be 
pushed  still  farther  back  than  appears  in  Hamilton's  work. 

It  will  be  valuable  to  put  beside  this  work,  similar  data 
gathered  on  rats  and  raccoons  in  1910-1912.  The  records 
here  given  are  representative  and  include  only  tests  made 
with  three  boxes  on  periods  of  delay.  The  following  indicates 
the  maximal  delays  attained  by  the  animals  whose  records 
are  used  in  this  paper: 

Rat  No.  9,  maximal  delay  10  sees. 

Rat  No.  2,        "  "        i     " 

Dog  Blackie,         "  "        5  mins. 

Raccoon  Bob,       "  "      30-35  sees.1 

Table  VI.  summarizes  the  errors  made  by  these  four 
animals.  It  includes  for  comparative  purposes  the  data  for 
Thayer.  The  raccoon's  records  include  delays  from  I  sec. 
through  20  sees.;  those  for  the  dog,  from  i  sec.  through  7  sees.; 

TABLE  VI 


Animal 

No.  of 
Trs. 

Total  No.  of 
Errors  A 

3  Place 
Errors  B 

Persistent 
Errors  C 

Percent,  of 
A  toC 

Percent,  of 
.gto  C 

Thayer  

264 

1  2O 

CA 

6 

c 

II 

Raccoon,  Bob  
Dog,  Blackie  
Rat  No.  9 

720 

570 

cyr 

209 
127 
14-4. 

78 
75 

4.2 

29 

25 
j-j 

13 
19 

37 
33 
•?o 

Rat  No.  2  

345 

152 

69 

47 

32 

60 

those  for  rat  No.  9,  from  the  third  stage  of  delay  (turning 
light  off  just  as  animal  was  released)  through  7  sees.;  and 
those  for  rat  No.  2,  from  the  third  stage  of  delay  through 
I  sec.  I  have  included  the  data  represented  by  *  percent  of 
B  to  C'  because  Hamilton's  percentages  are  based  only  on 
those  reactions  that  included  all  the  boxes  of  his  apparatus. 

1  These  data  are  taken  from  my  'Delayed  Reaction,'  pp.  35-38. 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  85 

The  column  '3  place  errors'  includes  the  trials  that  involved 
a  testing  by  the  animal  of  each  of  the  three  boxes.  By 
4  persistent  errors/  I  mean  all  errors  that  involve  trying  any 
one  box  more  than  once  each  trial.  These  were  all  3  place 
errors.  This  column  corresponds  to  reactions  belonging  to 
Hamilton's  types  D  and  E. 

The  only  one  of  Hamilton's  human  subjects  whose  per- 
centage in  D  plus  E  rose  above  6.45  percent  was  a  26-months- 
old  child  whose  grade  was  60.53  percent.  Of  the  animals 
below  man,  the  lowest  grade  (best  record)  was  22.58  percent 
made  by  a  dog.  Hamilton's  results  and  my  own  here  pre- 
sented indicate  a  marked  difference  between  man  and  other 
animals  in  reactive  tendencies,  i.  e.,  in  forms  of  kinaesthetic 
habits.  (There  is,  I  think,  no  clear  evidence  as  yet  that  the 
tendencies  are  instinctive.)  Whether  this  is  caused  by 
phyletic  factors,  or  by  experimental  and  environmental  con- 
ditions is  a  matter  undecided.  My  infra-human  animals  are 
essentially  on  a  par.  And  so  I  think  are  Hamilton's  in  that 
practically  all  of  them  made  their  highest  percentages  in 
what  I  here  term  '  persistent  errors.'  (His  curves  would  be 
quite  different,  naturally,  if  D  and  E  were  combined  and  if 
B  and  C  were  combined.1)  Much  work  is  undoubtedly 
needed  to  determine  how  minute  a  classification  of  reaction 
tendencies  can  be  and  still  be  significant  for  animal  ability. 

THEORETICAL  CONSIDERATIONS 

There  is  very  little  in  the  way  of  interpretative  comments 
that  I  can  add  to  what  has  already  been  said  in  other  papers.2 
The  delayed  reaction  problem  can  be  solved  at  least  in  two 
ways:3  (i)  by  the  maintenance  of  bodily  orientation  in  whole 

1  Hamilton,  op.  cit.,  1911,  p.  54. 

2  'Delayed  Reaction,'  pp.  62-79  an^  Hunter,  W.  S.,  'A  Reply  to  Some  Criticisms 
of  the  Delayed  Reaction,'  /.  of  Phil.  PsychoL,  t3c.y  1915,  12,  38-41.     See  also  Watson 
J.  B.,  'Behavior,'  1914,  pp.  224-227;  and  Ch.  X. 

8  If  there  is  a  present  determining  external  stimulus,  the  reaction  is  not  delayed. 

A.  C.  Walton,  'The  Influence  of  Diverting  Stimuli  during  Delayed  Reaction  in 
Dogs,'  /.  Animal  Sehav.,  1915,  5,  259-291,  has  shown  that  dogs  can  react  successfully 
to  three  boxes  after  delays  of  30  sees,  when  they  have  been  distracted  during  the 
intervals.  This  is  better  than  I  had  been  able  to  show.  Before  deciding  that  the 
dog  belongs  in  a  class  with  the  raccoons — as  perhaps  he  does — it  will  be  necessary  to 


86  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

or  in  part  during  the  interval  of  delay  or  by  the  chance 
recovery  of  the  proper  orientation  just  at  the  moment  of 
release;  and  (2)  by  the  use  of  some  intra-organic  factor  which 
is  wow-observable  by  the  experimenter.  In  the  first  method, 
the  animal  always  responds  in  accordance  with  orientation; 
in  the  second,  he  does  not.  The  cue  used  in  the  second 
method  may  or  may  not  be  retained  in  the  focus  of  neural 
activity  during  the  delay.  It  is  highly  improbable  that  such 
retention  occurs  under  conditions  of  distraction.  What  one 
has,  then,  is  a  system  of  processes  or  cues  which  'stand  for' 
certain  differential  responses  as  a  result  of  association. 
These  cues  are  susceptible  to  selective  re-arousal  and  subse- 
quent successful  functioning  in  initiating  responses.  This  is 
the  condition  which  I  have  previously  found  in  raccoons  and 
in  one  child,  F.,  2|  years  old.  It  is  the  condition  here  pre- 
sented by  Thayer,  ages  13-16  months.  This  second  method 
of  solution  which  I  am  describing  may  be  mediated  by  any 
type  of  intra-organic  process  which  can  be  re-aroused  with- 
out the  presence  of  the  external  stimulus,  toys  as  used  in 
the  present  study.  Inasmuch  as  kinaesthetic  factors  can  be 
so  aroused,1  and  inasmuch  as  they  have  been  demonstrated 
to  have  great  importance  not  only  in  animal  reactions  in 
general  but  in  the  delayed  reaction  in  particular  (position 
habits  and  maintenance  of  orientation),  it  is  most  probable 
that  the  intra-organic  factors  are  kinsesthetic  in  nature. 
(The  genetic  relations  of  sensation,  image  and  imageless 
thought  are  discussed  in  'The  Delayed  Reaction/  pages  cited.) 
In  certain  cases  this  type  of  process  has  its  locus  in  the  vocal 
organs  with  frequent  resulting  audible  sounds.  This  we 
term  vocal  language  as  it  occurs  in  normal  human  adults  and 
in  children  of  a  certain  development.  In  other  cases  the 
observance  of  the  sounds  and  their  accompanying  behavior 

have  data  on  the  animals'  orientations  at  the  moment  of  response.  This  Walton 
unfortunately  does  not  give.  The  only  facts  that  we  have  are  that  the  animals  did 
not  maintain  their  orientations  during  the  delays.  If  it  should  appear  that  the  animal 
is  able  to  recover  the  proper  orientation  in  a  large  number  of  instances  after  a  thorough 
distraction  and  can  then  react  correctly,  this  fact  will  itself  be  ofjjreat  significance  and 
will  require  careful  analysis. 

1  See  the  all  too  brief  comments  in  my  review  of  Calkins'  'First  Book  in  Psy- 
chology,' PSYCHOL.  BULL.,  1915,  12,  189-190. 


THE  DELAYED  REACTION  IN  A  CHILD  87 

does  not  indicate  that  the  organism  uses  either  the  sound  or 
the  parallel  kinsesthesis  as  a  substitute  of  the  type  above 
described.  This  is  the  situation  in  all  animals  that  indulge 
in  vocalization.  But  this  intra-organic  kinaesthetic  factor 
may  arise  elsewhere  than  from  the  throat.  Some  part  of  the 
general  bodily  musculature  may  be  the  origin.  Here,  when 
the  behavior  is  overt,  we  speak  of  gesture  language.  When 
it  is  not  overt,  the  delayed  reaction  method  has  proved 
serviceable  in  detecting  it.  Language  is  ideational  in  func- 
tion. So  also  are  the  cues  which  function  in  many  responses 
of  raccoons,  of  children  and  possibly  of  dogs  (Walton).  The 
resulting  conception  of  these  cues  is  that  they  are  kinaesthetic 
sensory  ideas.  This  line  of  reasoning  leads  one  to  conclude 
that  a  true  language  non-vocal  in  character  appears  phylo- 
genetically  and  ontogenetically  prior  to  vocal  language. 
Such  language,  although  undoubtedly  of  great  service  to  the 
individual  in  controlling  his  reactions,  is  of  little  social 
significance. 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  2  March,  1917 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


THE   LAWS  OF   RELATIVE   FATIGUE1 

BY  RAYMOND  DODGE 

Wesleyan  University 

The  temerity  that  ventures  to  speak  of  fatigue  laws  may 
well  arouse  a  critical  attitude.  But  I  shall  not  be  quite  so 
indiscreet  as  the  title  might  be  misconstrued  to  imply.  For 
reasons  that  will  presently  appear  in  detail,  I  have  no  ex- 
pectation that  the  laws  of  mental  fatigue  will  be  formulated 
in  the  immediate  future.  Oeffner's  so-called  laws  of  fatigue 
are  obviously  only  empirical  generalizations  and  summaries. 
My  subject  is  really  much  less  pretentious.  It  concerns  only 
the  relativity  of  fatigue.  The  laws  of  relative  fatigue  that 
we  shall  discuss  might  with  equal  propriety  have  been  called 
the  laws  of  fatigue  relativity. 

My  excuse  for  selecting  so  threadbare  a  matter  as  fatigue 
for  the  subject  of  the  presidential  address  is  largely  personal. 
As  some  of  you  know,  I  have  been  working  on  various  phases 
of  mental  fatigue  experimentally  for  a  number  of  years — too 
long  for  self  complacency.  More  than  once  it  has  seemed  to 
me  that  I  was  following  a  clear  experimental  path  out  of  the 
maze  of  fact,  only  to  find  myself  back  again  at  the  starting 
point,  facing  the  same  fundamental  questions.  But  however 
personal  my  interest  in  fatigue  may  be  it  certainly  is  not  ex- 
ceptional. I  venture  the  guess  that  there  is  not  a  member  of 
this  Association  but  has  made  fatigue  the  subject  of  direct, 
indirect,  or  projected  investigation.  Certainly  few  psycho- 
logical subjects  have  so  widely  interested  investigators  in  the 
allied  sciences.  Few  seem  to  have  at  once  such  far-reaching 

1  Address  of  the  President  before  the  American  Psychological  Association,  New 
York  Meeting,  December,  1916. 


90  RAYMOND  DODGE 

bearings  on  psychological  theory  and  the  conduct  of  human 
affairs.  Few  present  such  a  bewildering  literature,  with 
such  an  array  of  apparently  mutually  contradictory  experi- 
mental results.  None  is  more  confused  with  an  equal  pres- 
sure for  practical  working  rules.  Confusion  and  eagerness 
for  practical  results  make  a  situation  fraught  with  grave 
peril  to  science.  If  anything  could,  they  justify  this  attempt 
to  clarify  and  systematize  the  fundamental  concept  of  mental 
fatigue. 

It  would  be  an  impracticable  as  well  as  an  uncongenial 
task  for  me  to  attempt  a  review  of  the  literature  of  fatigue, 
even  if  this  were  a  fitting  occasion.  Our  time  limits,  our 
precedents,  and  my  personal  interests  persuade  me  rather  to 
attempt  what  I  hope  may  prove  to  be  a  more  generally  useful 
undertaking,  namely,  a  substantive  analysis  of  the  problem. 
The  first  part  of  that  task,  as  I  apprehend  it,  is  to  clear  the 
problem  of  some  misleading  assumptions  by  which  faulty 
analogy  and  practical  interests  have  confused  the  real  issues. 
Thus  simplified  we  shall  try  to  redefine  the  psycho-physical 
problem  on  a  scientific  rather  than  on  a  practical  basis. 

Mental  fatigue  is  one  of  those  scientific  problems  that  has 
suffered  from  too  much  practical  importance.  In  the  enor- 
mous number  of  investigations  that  have  appeared  since  the 
publication  of  Mosso's  "epoch-making"  book,  just  a  quarter 
of  a  century  ago,  educational,  medical,  and  more  recently 
social  and  economic  interests  have  given  the  dominant  motifs. 
It  was  indeed  an  alarming  arraignment  of  the  schools  that 
they  ruined  the  health  and  impaired  the  eyes  of  pupils  by  their 
excessive  demands.  An  investigation  of  such  charges  was  a 
direct  obligation  on  experimental  pedagogy.  Scarcely  less 
important  than  the  school  problems  is  a  just  determination 
of  the  proper  duration  of  an  industrial  day,  with  a  fair  con- 
sideration for  the  welfare  of  the  laborer  and  for  the  exigencies 
of  competition.  None  of  us,  moreover,  is  entirely  free  from 
more  personal  practical  difficulties  in  our  desire  to  exploit 
most  effectively  the  time  and  energy  at  our  disposal.  Now 
I  would  not  for  a  moment  be  misunderstood  to  depreciate  the 
importance  of  these  practical  studies.  My  only  contention 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  91 

with  respect  to  them  is  that  they  all  suffer  more  or  less  from 
an  inadequate  scientific  basis.  But  in  spite  of  all  the  con- 
fusion of  alleged  fact,  all  the  premature  and  unverifiable 
pronouncements,  most  of  us  still  believe  that  an  adequate 
answer  to  such  practical  questions  is  both  desirable  and 
possible. 

Less  insistent  and  obvious,  but  none  the  less  real  and 
important,  are  the  scientific  problems  of  mental  fatigue. 
For  the  present  at  least  it  may  be  of  some  advantage  to  keep 
separate  the  two  lines  of  investigation,  the  practical  and 
the  scientific.  The  former  is,  in  the  main,  quite  independent 
of  the  latter.  However  the  questions  as  to  the  nature  and 
laws  of  mental  fatigue  may  finally  be  answered,  careful 
generalization  from  experience  as  to  the  expediency  of  certain 
work  and  relaxation  sequences  will  deserve  and  will  receive 
careful  consideration  in  planning  the  day's  work.  So  too 
the  most  advisable  length  and  distribution  of  recesses  may 
be  settled  purely  empirically,  entirely  without  reference  to 
any  of  the  underlying  bio-chemical  processes.  For  all  such 
practical  purposes  the  concept  of  fatigue  is  an  accident.  Its 
function  is  not  to  recall  the  implications  that  it  has  in  bio- 
chemical science;  but  merely  to  serve  as  a  vehicle  for  practical 
maxims,  a  class  name  for  all  sorts  of  unanalyzed  hindrances 
to  effective  work.  The  hindrances  would  be  just  as  real  and 
the  practical  maxims  just  as  valuable  even  if  it  were  proven 
that  fatigue  had  nothing  to  do  with  them.  The  scientific 
problems  as  to  the  real  nature  and  conditions  of  a  supposi- 
titious mental  fatigue  are  quite  independent  of  all  such  ques- 
tions of  practical  expediency.  Scientifically  we  must  know 
the  differential  characteristics  by  which  mental  fatigue  can 
be  distinguished  from  the  other  limitations  of  the  work  curve; 
as  well  as  its  elementary  forms  and  their  interrelations.  We 
must  follow  its  implications  as  an  indicator  of  the  relationship 
between  mind  and  body;  and  correlate  it  with  other  bio- 
chemical facts.  It  is  these  latter  problems  that  appeal  to 
me  personally  with  especial  emphasis.  Mental  fatigue  if  it 
exists  in  the  physiological  sense,  must  be  connected  in  some 
direct  way  with  the  energy  transformations  in  nervous  tissue, 


92  RAYMOND  DODGE 

and  the  fundamental  problems  of  inner  psycho-physics.  The 
great  problem  whether  our  mental  life  conforms  like  the  rest 
of  the  organism  to  the  underlying  postulate  of  thermo- 
dynamics, the  conservation  of  energy,  must  be  answered  if  at 
all  by  the  psycho-physics  of  work  and  fatigue.  While  I 
sincerely  hope  that  adequately  equipped  attempts  to  explore 
these  fundamental  questions  are  not  too  far  distant,  there  are 
related  problems  that  can  be  examined  by  simpler  techniques. 
Again  mental  fatigue  if  it  exists  ought  to  furnish  us  with  an 
instrument  of  dynamic  analysis  of  the  mental  complexes, 
reaching  the  inner  mechanisms  of  our  mental  life.  To 
estimate  its  possible  usefulness,  one  has  only  to  think  of  the 
analogous  use  of  fatigue  or  adaptation  in  sense  analysis;  when 
we  adapt  out  one  sense  quality  and  note  the  effect  of  its  loss 
on  the  other  qualities,  or  on  perception  in  general.  So,  for 
example,  the  relative  composition  of  two  purples  might  be 
shown  even  if  we  had  no  other  method,  by  adapting  out 
spectral  blue,  and  comparing  their  resulting  appearance. 
It  would  seem  that  a  similar  process  ought  to  be  applicable 
to  mental  experiments  when  we  have  no  other  means  of  ex- 
perimentally eliminating  the  various,  factors.  One  might 
even  outline  the  working  postulates  of  such  an  analysis  as 
follows:  I.  Whenever  in  mental  processes  fatigue  of  one  is 
regularly  accompanied  by  fatigue  of  another  there  must  be 
some  dynamic  factor  common  to  both.  II.  Conversely, 
whenever  the  fatigue  of  one  mental  process  does  not  show  as 
fatigue  of  another,  the  two  must  depend  on  different  dynamic 
conditions.  III.  Whenever  fatigue  in  one  process  is  accom- 
panied by  the  improvement  of  another  process  then  the  two 
are  probably  related  in  the  sense  that  the  fatigued  factor  in 
the  former  was  inhibitory  to  the  second.  That  such  postu- 
lates have  borne  little  fruit  hitherto,  is  not  due  to  any  inherent 
logical  unsoundness,  but  rather  to  our  misapprehension  of  the 
character  of  mental  fatigue.  At  present  their  application  to 
the  problems  of  analysis  would  be  handicapped  by  the  very 
richness  of  the  alleged  correlations.  It  has  proven  embarrass- 
ing to  more  than  one  of  us  to  teach  our  students  on  one  oc- 
casion the  very  slight  correlation  between  mental  processes 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  93 

that  seem  very  much  alike;  and  on  another  occasion  to  teach 
them  how  mental  fatigue  in  general  may  be  measured  by  the 
pulse,  the  ergograph,  addition,  reaction  time,  the  dermal 
threshold,  and  other  apparently  disconnected  events  through 
a  long  list  of  accredited  extrinsic  tests.  To  be  sure  the  relia- 
bility of  these  and  other  so-called  tests  is  not  universally 
admitted.  But  the  gross  discrepancies  between  genetic  and 
dynamic  correlations  might  well  be  taken  a  little  more  seri- 
ously. Before  any  of  these  scientific  tasks  can  be  undertaken 
with  promise  of  success,  we  must  know  what  mental  fatigue 
really  is,  if  there  is  any  such  thing,  and  how  it  is  conditioned. 

THE  CONCEPT  OF  MENTAL  FATIGUE 

The  concept  of  mental  fatigue  is  so  familiar  that  a  precise 
analysis  of  its  differentia  has  seldom  seemed  necessary. 
Statements  of  its  meaning,  when  they  occur,  regularly  em- 
phasize a  diminution  of  some  product  of  mental  activity  per 
unit  of  time,  incident  to  continued  activity,  and  as  Thorndike 
insists,  recoverable  through  rest.  Actual  recovery  or  the 
capacity  to  recover  through  rest  seems  to  me  to  be  irrelevant. 
On  the  one  hand  it  excludes  extreme  fatigue;  on  the  other 
hand  it  fails  to  exclude  all  sorts  of  intercurrent  disturbances. 
But  the  diminution  of  production  consequent  to  continuous 
work  with  or  without  recoverability,  is  I  believe  an  untenable 
criterion  of  fatigue. 

If  the  word  fatigue  has  any  scientific  propriety  in  connec- 
tion with  our  mental  life,  it  seems  to  me  that  it  should  refer 
to  the  metabolic  conditions  of  mental  action,  not  to  any 
predetermined  characteristic  of  its  consequences.  This  is 
very  much  the  same  point  that  I  made  recently  concerning 
mental  work.  While  that  was  not  received  with  the  una- 
nimity that  I  had  hoped,  in  the  case  of  fatigue  at  least,  failure 
to  realize  the  dynamic  implications  must  lead  to  gross  con- 
fusion. Obviously  psychology  or  pedagogy  is  entirely  com- 
petent to  ignore  the  physiological  concept  of  fatigue  and  to 
develop  its  own  empirical  concept  as  decreased  returns  of 
mental  work.  But  if  it  ignores  the  metabolic  implications 
at  the  beginning,  it  may  not  assume  at  the  end  that  physio- 


94  RAYMOND  DODGE 

logical  and  pathological  fatigue  processes  parallel  the  de- 
creased returns.  It  is  such  gratuitous  assumptions  concerning 
matters  of  fact  that  make  psycho-physical  parallelism  a 
dangerous  working  hypothesis.  Moreover,  such  an  inde- 
pen.dent  psychological  concept  would  be  scientifically  de- 
fensible only  to  the  degree  that  work  decrements,  consequent 
to  work  and  eliminated  by  rest,  prove  to  be  homologous 
processes  with  regular  and  definable  antecedents.  If  on  the 
contrary  work  decrements  show  a  large  variety  of  types,  or 
follow  any  considerable  variety  of  conditions,  it  would  seem 
to  be  good  sense  and  sound  science  to  enquire  whether  any 
of  the  varieties  of  mental  work  decrement  correspond  to 
physiological  fatigue  processes.  These  alone  would  then 
seem  to  have  a  natural  right  to  the  name  mental  fatigue. 
From  this  standpoint  other  decrements  would  be  regarded  as 
pseudo-fatigues. 

In  order  to  conserve  our  time  let  me  be  quite  direct  and 
frank.  I  regard  it  as  improbable  that  any  of  the  mental  work 
decrements  so  commonly  treated  as  mental  fatigue,  are  ever 
simply  conditioned  by  true  fatigue  processes  in  nervous  tissue. 
Conversely  real  fatigue  may  not  appear  as  a  decrement  at  all. 
Some  of  the  evidence  for  this  position  can  only  be  indicated 
here.  Some  of  it  must  be  given  in  more  detail. 

First  one  must  note  the  physiological  fact  that  nervous 
tissue  in  situ  has  been  found  quite  resistant  to  fatigue  and 
exhaustion  under  normal  cirumstances.  The  axis  cylinders 
apparently  never  fatigue  except  under  experimental  conditions 
when  their  environment  is  freed  from  oxygen,  or  when  they 
are  narcotized  so  that  they  are  unable  to  use  the  oxygen  that 
is  present.  Cell  bodies  are  likewise  resistant  to  fatigue  under 
normal  circumstances.  They  can  be  exhausted  in  experi- 
mental animals  only  under  strychnine  poisoning,  after  the 
withdrawal  of  normal  blood  supply.  Langfeld  has  shown  that 
in  humans  prolonged  fasting  produces  no  correlated  decrease 
of  neural  efficiency.  Reflexes  like  the  knee-jerk  and  the 
protective  lid  reflex  show  no  decrement  after  long  series  of 
elicitation,  if  care  be  taken  to  prevent  intercurrent  general 
depression  of  the  nervous  system.  In  those  cases  where 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  95 

fatigue  decrement  of  the  reflexes  does  occur,  there  is  evidence 
that  neither  the  muscles,  the  nerves,  nor  the  nervous  centers 
have  lost  their  irritability  except  to  the  particular  stimulus  to 
which  they  have  become  adapted.  On  the  contrary  hyper- 
excitability  is  a  common  if  not  a  regular  phenomenon  of 
extreme  so-called  mental  fatigue.  At  any  rate  it  would  seem 
that  the  complete  cessation  of  mental  processes,  like  the 
inability  to  recall  an  opposite,  to  complete  a  sentence,  to 
recite  a  series  of  nonsense  syllables,  or  to  multiply  four-place 
numbers  by  mental  arithmetic  cannot  possibly  mean  the 
fatigue  of  nervous  tissue  to  the  corresponding  degree  of  com- 
pleteness. 

A  second  ground  against  the  traditional  differentiae  of 
fatigue  is  their  failure  to  exclude  normal  psycho-physical 
rhythms.  In  more  than  one  respect  it  was  an  unfortunate 
accident  that  the  paradigm  for  the  interpretation  of  the 
phenomena  of  mental  fatigue  was  the  fatigue  of  a  nerve- 
muscle  preparation.  Undoubtedly  there  are  many  and  im- 
portant analogies  between  the  action  of  lower  spinal  arcs  and 
cerebral  processes.  But  after  all  the  main  task  of  physio- 
logical psychology  begins  when  it  seeks  to  understand  the 
differences  between  the  simpler  processes  and  cerebral  action. 
Similarly,  in  connection  with  a  supposititious  mental  fatigue 
the  regularly  increasing  work-paralysis  of  nerve-muscle  prepa- 
ration may  be  and  in  some  respects  must  be  a  misleading 
model.  One  of  the  great  differences  is  that  while  the  extir- 
pated preparation  changes  only  slowly  under  experimental 
conditions  when  unstimulated,  normal  mental  life  precludes 
unchanging  neural  conditions.  In  the  complex  intercon- 
nections of  human  cortical  processes  the  one  statement  that 
can  be  made  with  completest  conviction  is  that  the  experi- 
mental subject  never  remains  constant,  quite  apart  from  the 
intended  experimental  changes.  Even  under  the  best  possible 
experimental  conditions,  the  experimental  change  is  only  one 
of  the  changes  that  we  know  to  be  occurring.  The  consti- 
tution of  these  non-experimental  changes  in  any  given  case 
we  know  only  in  part.  We  believe  that  consciousness  itself 
is  a  process  which  involves  more  or  less  continuous  inherent 


96  RAYMOND  DODGE 

change.  We  know  that  there  are  also  various  intercurrent 
physiological  rhythms,  cardiac,  vascular,  respiratory,  in- 
testinal, glandular,  and  muscular.  Cortical  action  may  also 
initiate  non-rhythmic  changes  in  the  glandular,  circulatory, 
and  respiratory  systems  with  far-reaching  reactions  of  those 
changes  on  the  cortical  action  that  originated  them. 

From  the  standpoint  of  the  importance  of  the  accompany- 
ing mental  changes,  perhaps  the  most  significant  of  the 
rhythms  is  sleep.  The  fatigue-hunting  enthusiasm  that  finds 
in  sleep  the  daily  climax  of  fatigue  is  without  physiological 
justification.  On  the  contrary,  we  have  learned  from  experi- 
mental investigations  that  for  some  persons  evening  may  be 
the  time  of  most  effective  mental  work.  Moreover,  it  is 
neurological  commonplace  that  in  serious  extreme  fatigue, 
sleep  may  be  impossible.  Physiologists  would  welcome  any 
insight  that  we  could  give  them  into  the  causes  of  sleep.  The 
fatigue  climax  assumption  simply  is  not  tenable.  Whatever 
they  may  be,  we  know  that  the  conditions  of  sleep  are  not 
simple.  Habit,  the  absence  of  stimuli,  probably  widespread 
inhibitions,  and  possibly  gland  products  and  vaso-motor 
changes  cooperate  in  its  production.  Sleep  may  come  from 
restriction  of  activity  quicker  than  from  over-exertion. 
Lecturers  never  go  to  sleep.  The  audience  may.  In  view  of 
such  complication  of  the  conditions  of  continuous  work  dec- 
rement the  assumption  that  all  diminished  returns  conse- 
quent to  work  and  eliminated  by  rest  are  fatigue  seems  to  me 
utterly  untenable. 

A  third  ground  of  suspicion  against  the  true  fatigue 
character  of  most  so-called  mental  fatigue  is  found  in  the 
means  that  are  commonly  used  to  induce  it.  In  nerve-muscle 
fatigue  experiments  one  isolates  a  specific  tissue  and  stimulates 
it  successively  in  the  same  manner.  In  mental  fatigue  experi- 
ments, on  the  contrary,  repetition  of  the  same  stimulus  is 
systematically  avoided.  The  more  carefully  one  analyses 
the  assumptions  of  this  anomalous  technique,  the  more  in- 
congruous it  appears.  Let  us  take  a  concrete  instance  from 
what  Thorndike  has  taught  us  to  regard  as  one  of  the  purest 
forms  of  mental  work,  mental  arithmetic.  If  we  strictly 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  97 

followed  the  analogy  of  physiological  fatigue  experiments  some 
association  in  mental  arithmetic,  say  the  multiplication  of 
two  times  two,  should  be  repeated  until  work  decrement  or 
paralysis  indicated  fatigue  of  the  association  process.  As 
far  as  I  know  that  is  never  done.  It  seems  absurd.  The 
experimental  device  of  constantly  changing  the  stimulus  in 
fatigue  experiments  is  defensible  only  on  the  assumption 
that  all  multiplication  processes  affect  the  same  general  group 
of  tissues,  and  that  continuous  multiplication  of  different 
digits  increases  the  sum  of  the  fatigue  of  the  whole.  But 
neurologically  the  assumption  is  certainly  a  strange  one  that 
the  nervous  tissue  which  was  involved  in  one  association 
fatigued  more  when  a  variety  of  different  associations  were 
made  than  it  did  when  all  the  burden  fell  on  the  same  asso- 
ciative elements,  operating  continuously  or  in  rapid  succession. 
Moreover,  there  are  no  facts  available  to  show  that  restriction 
to  a  single  field  like  multiplication  will  produce  greater  work 
decrement  than  rapid  change  from  one  field  to  another.  On 
the  contrary  there  is  evidence  that  the  greater  the  complexity 
of  the  mental  task  the  more  pronounced  is  the  decrement. 
Such  decrement,  however,  is  more  probably  due  to  a  confusion 
between  different  paths  of  discharge  than  to  fatigue  of  any 
particular  path.  That  confusion  is  real  and  a  common  ex- 
perience every  introspective  account  is  evidence.  The- 
oretically it  should  be  expected  from  the  operation  of  the 
known  laws  of  association.  Suppose,  for  example,  that  after 
adding  various  digits  to  seven  we  come  to  the  task  of  adding 
four.  The  right  associate  is  by  hypothesis  well  known  and 
thoroughly  practiced.  But  if  other  numbers  have  recently 
appeared  in  the  series  they  also  tend  to  be  reproduced  on  the 
basis  of  recency.  It  is  at  least  conceivable  that  the  true 
associate  in  such  a  case  might  be  difficult  to  recall,  not  at  all 
from  fatigue  of  the  corresponding  tissue  but  from  effectual 
inhibition  because  a  more  recent  associate  appears  in  its 
stead.  The  necessity  for  inhibiting  irrelevant  and  false  asso- 
ciates is  certainly  a  common  experience  in  the  elementary 
mathematics  of  some  of  us.  But  the  tendency  of  recent 
ideas  to  recur  is  not  in  any  sense  a  fatigue  or  exhaustion 


98  RAYMOND  DODGE 

process,  but  is  probably  a  matter  of  residual  excitation  and 
summation.  Such  work  decrement  then  is  not  fatigue  but 
mere  association  rivalry. 

A  fourth  ground  against  identifying  work  decrement  and 
fatigue  may  be  found  in  the  operation  of  incidental  inhibitions. 
Theoretically,  every  mental  operation  arouses  more  or  less 
widespread  associated  reverberations  which  manifest  them- 
selves in  the  sequences  of  actual  associative  recall,  and  may 
on  occasion,  as  we  have  just  seen,  operate  to  confuse  the 
regular  sequence  of  work  by  a  kind  of  associative  rivalry. 
Theoretically  also,  every  actual  association  process  involves 
more  or  less  widespread  inhibitions  of  undesirable  associations. 
Now  it  is  conceivable  that  these  useful  inhibitions  of  the  irrele- 
vant might  operate  to  produce  a  pseudo-fatigue  work  decre- 
ment in  any  extrinsic  test.  For  example,  I  have  published 
experimental  evidence  that  the  most  intense  mental  work  of 
an  examination  period  commonly  follows  the  first  reading 
of  the  examination  questions.  It  is  the  period  of  adjustment 
to  the  examination  as  a  whole,  when  widespread  association 
systems  are  being  organized.  Such  activities  are  not  possible 
in  fullest  degree  without  corresponding  inhibitions.  Ordi- 
narily distracting  stimuli  pass  unnoticed.  Even  physical 
discomfort  and  pain  may  for  a  time  be  ignored.  Now  it  is 
conceivable  that  if  at  such  a  time  the  fatigue  tester  should 
request  the  examinee  to  add  digits  for  two  minutes  as  rapidly 
as  possible,  the  response  might  show  a  degree  of  work  decre- 
ment that  bordered  on  total  incapacity.  Or  again,  suppose 
we  would  measure  the  fatigue  of  a  Wall  St.  broker,  hour  by 
hour,  with  the  aesthesiometer  test.  And  supposing  as  the 
hour  struck  we  should  interrupt  a  selling  campaign  that  was 
taxing  his  skill  as  a  broker  by  the  request  that  he  submit  to 
our  compass  point  test.  The  chances  are  in  favor  of  some 
rather  vigorous  verbal  defensive  reactions  with  no  discrimi- 
nation at  all.  But  if  we  were  able  to  hold  him  to  a  promise 
and  actually  start  the  test,  is  there  any  guarantee  that  gross 
decrements  in  the  measured  function,  all  due  to  previous  work 
and  remediable  by  rest,  might  not  be  due  to  his  inability  to 
give  his  attention  to  our  petty  tests  while  his  fortune  was  at 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  99 

stake  on  the  floor?  Of  course  the  whole  situation  is  absurd. 
The  most  enthusiastic  believer  in  space  threshold  tests  would 
hesitate  to  use  such  results  as  an  indication  of  the  broker's 
general  mental  fatigue  at  that  time. 

We  freely  admit  that  these  are  extreme  cases,  and  that 
they  break  the  most  elementary  rules  for  experimentation. 
But  have  we  any  guarantee  that  similar  discriminations 
against  some  seemingly  unimportant  task  might  not  occur 
just  after  recess,  or  just  before  school  lets  out,  when  the 
afternoon's  escapades  are  in  the  making,  or  any  time  at  the 
interruption  of  seemingly  important  processes?  Conversely 
is  there  any  guarantee  that  the  interruption  of  annoying  or 
even  fatiguing  work  by  a  few  moments  of  trivial  testing  might 
not  be  a  joyous  relief,  giving  results  that  might  entirely  hide 
a  supposititious  real  mental  fatigue  of  the  interrupted  work? 
I  am  not  arguing  that  such  inhibitions  would  not  be  very 
much  worth  knowing;  but  merely  that  it  confuses  their  real 
bearings  to  call  them  all  fatigue. 

In  addition  to  these  specific  inhibitory  processes  which  are 
commonly  classed  in  psychology  as  phenomena  of  attention, 
we  are  acquainted  with  secondary  inhibitions  through  a  dim- 
inution of  the  supporting  organic  processes,  glandular  or 
circulatory.  Of  the  glandular  changes  I  have  no  direct 
knowledge.  The  initial  increased  pulse  frequency,  whenever 
complete  relaxation  is  interrupted  by  any  mental  activity,  is 
commonly  followed  by  a  gradually  decreasing  heart  rate  in 
any  prolonged  experimental  task.  We  may  regard  this  as  a 
kind  of  adaptive  process,  an  habituation  to  the  task  at  hand. 
It  is  difficult  to  conceive  of  it  without  reference  to  the  gradual 
elimination  of  extrinsic  excitations,  in  which  an  initial  general 
excitation  is  followed  by  an  inhibition  which  restricts  the 
excitement  to  selected  processes.  I  have  been  able  to  dem- 
onstrate that  something  of  this  sort  occurs  in  every  normal 
reading  pause.  That  continuous  fixation  of  a  trivial  object 
is  inhibitory  is  shown  by  its  familiar  hypnagogic  tendencies. 
It  is  one  of  the  methods  of  producing  hypnosis.  With  some 
probability  we  can  predict  a  diminution  in  the  organic  condi- 
tions for  metabolism  in  all  relatively  unused  neural  centers 


loo  RAYMOND  DODGE 

during  monotonous  mental  work.  In  extreme  cases  continu- 
ous disuse  leads  to  atrophy,  muscular,  neural,  and  glandular. 
To  regard  work  decrement  which  is  due  to  more  or  less 
complete  atrophy  of  unused  paths  as  fatigue  would  be  a 
manifestly  absurd  confusion  of  concepts.  But  work  decre- 
ment from  secondary  trophic  deficiency,  as  in  unused  parts, 
is  just  as  surely  not  fatigue.  Just  as  in  periods  of  excitement 
and  important  readjustment,  there  are  undoubtedly  vascular 
and  glandular  changes  which  increase  the  activity  of  the 
whole  neural  mechanism,  reflexly  reinforcing  the  processes 
that  initiated  them;  so  it  is  probable  that  general  depressions 
of  glandular  or  vascular  origin  accompany  monotonous  mental 
work,  in  which  even  the  centers  that  are  most  active  finally 
participate.  But  this  again  is  not  fatigue  in  any  physio- 
logical sense. 

In  as  far  as  these  various  processes  represent  work  decre- 
ments or  decreased  returns  that  might  be  mistaken  for 
neural  fatigue  they  may  properly  be  called  pseudo-fatigues. 
We  have  described  pseudo-fatigues  of  intercurrent  rhythms, 
of  residual  excitation  and  rivalry,  and  of  specific  and  trophic 
inhibition.  The  pathological  evidence  that  Work  decrement 
is  no  true  indicator  of  nervous  fatigue  is  not  new.  Even  to 
summarize  it  would  extend  our  paper  too  far.  But  I  think 
that  without  it,  we  have  established  the  thesis  that  decreased 
returns  resulting  from  work  and  recoverable  by  rest  if  you 
will,  cannot  be  employed  as  simply  and  directly  in  the  higher 
neural  systematizations  as  it  can  in  simpler  tissues.  Ar- 
bitrarily to  define  mental  fatigue  as  work  decrement  is  effec- 
tual self-banishment  from  physiological  tradition  as  well  as 
from  clearly  defined  fields  of  investigation  of  the  utmost 
importance. 

Having  divested  the  mental  fatigue  concept  of  its  irrele- 
vant content  as  vehicle  of  the  various  work  decrements,  it  is 
now  in  order  to  inquire  whether  there  is  in  our  mental  life  a 
real  fatigue  phenomenon.  I  believe  that  there  is,  but  its 
manifestations  differ  from  the  paradigm  of  nerve-muscle 
fatigue  in  two  important  particulars.  These  are:  first,  the 
inconstancy  of  the  stimuli  in  mental  work;  and  second,  the 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  101 

interaction    of    competing    paths.     These    two    differences 
combine  to  emphasize  the  relativity  of  all  mental  fatigue. 

THE  RELATIVITY  OF  FATIGUE 

In  the  nerve-muscle  fatigue  experiment,  the  stimulus  is 
always  simple,  and  usually  constant  in  intensity,  given  at 
regular  time  intervals.  For  a  variety  of  reasons  the  stimulus 
that  is  most  used  is  the  faradic  current.  It  is  capable  of  fine 
adjustment,  may  be  held  at  constant  intensity  over  long 
periods,  and  is  exceedingly  effective  in  quantities  that  do  not 
damage  the  tissue.  No  physiologist  would  start  a  fatigue 
experiment  with  stimuli  of  unknown  and  variable  intensity. 
Unfortunately,  that  seems  to  be  the  only  practicable  method 
at  present  in  so-called  mental  fatigue  experiments.  Nobody 
knows  the  relative  stimulus  value  of  two  different  mathe- 
matical sums.  But  what  is  vastly  more  embarrassing,  nobody 
knows  how  to  follow  or  to  evaluate  the  ever-changing  inner 
factors  in  the  total  mental  stimulus,  such  as  the  force  of  the 
instructions,  the  personal  interest  of  the  subject  in  the  scien- 
tific aspect  of  his  task,  in  its  bearing  on  the  particular  exi- 
gencies of  his  academic  career,  and  so  forth.  It  was  one  of 
the  great  services  of  Kraepelin  in  his  analysis  of  the  work 
curve  to  show  how  these  inner  stimuli  may  change  during  an 
experimental  period.  The  meaning  of  that  analysis  as  I 
apprehend  it  is  not  given  in  the  precise  variables  or  spurts 
that  he  found,  nor  in  the  assumption  that  they  are  always 
present,  but  rather  in  the  demonstration  that  variables  in 
the  inner  stimuli  may  occur  and  must  be  reckoned  with.  It 
would  not  take  us  long  to  add  to  his  objectively  defined  list 
many  others  taken  from  our  experimental  experience,  such 
as  competition  and  personal  pride,  repetition  of  the  instruc- 
tions, encouragement  and  persuasion,  the  presence  of  the 
instructor,  rewards  and  penalties  of  various  sorts,  and  the 
unanalyzed  mass  of  obligations. 

I  am  not  unaware  that  this  matter  of  the  inner  stimuli 
to  mental  work  is  packed  with  problems  that  we  have  no 
adequate  techniques  to  investigate.  But  that  is  no  excuse 
for  ignoring  them.  It  is  our  business  as  scientists  to  try  to 


102  RAYMOND  DODGE 

see  things  as  they  are,  even  if  they  are  complex.  There  is  at 
least  some  ground  for  the  suspicion  that  most  if  not  all  our 
real  mental  fatigue  of  the  work  decrement  type  is  really  a 
fatigue  of  the  inner  stimuli  rather  than  of  the  capacity  to 
react.  This  at  least  would  account  for  the  extraordinary 
correlations  in  the  fatigue  of  the  most  diverse  functions.  In 
many  so-called  mental  fatigue  experiments  the  only  common 
factor  discernible  to  introspective  analysis  is  the  intent  to 
keep  working  as  fast  as  possible  to  the  neglect  of  competing 
interests. 

Now  in  the  physiological  experiment  fatigue  may  be 
shown  in  two  ways,  either  by  a  rising  threshold  or  by  decreased 
response  to  a  constant  supra-threshold  stimulus.  Only  in  the 
latter  case  is  there  an  obvious  work  decrement.  The  former 
case  implies  a  constant  work  output  with  a  gradually  increas- 
ing stimulus  intensity.  In  mental  work  we  are  often  distinctly 
aware  of  similar  changes  in  the  intensity  of  the  inner  stimuli 
that  keep  us  at  a  disagreeable  or  monotonous  task.  Mere 
interest  in  the  task  may  lose  its  force  comparatively  early. 
Then  the  task  is  continued  from  stubbornness,  the  dislike  to 
fail,  sense  of  obligation,  honor,  fear  of  ridicule,  or  hope  of 
reward,  etc.  All  of  these  may  operate  in  succession.  In  the 
end  all  of  them  may  lose  their  force  and  we  say,  "  I  do  not  care 
what  happens,  I  cannot  go  on  with  this  thing  any  longer 
to-night."  There  may  have  been  no  important  work  de- 
crement until  the  break,  as  Yoakum  calls  it.  But  the  process 
is  none  the  less  a  real  fatigue  if  the  continuation  of  work 
depends  on  a  change  of  the  stimuli. 

All  of  this  emphasis  on  the  importance  of  the  neglected 
factor  of  changing  stimuli  in  the  fatigue  concept  is  probably 
sufficient  to  justify  the  formal  statement  of  a  necessary 
correction  in  the  traditional  definition  of  mental  fatigue.  We 
may  call  it  the  first  law  of  relative  fatigue,  neglected  rather 
than  new.  Without  pretending  to  give  it  final  formulation 
we  may  express  it  as  follows:  Within  physiological  limits,  all 
fatigue  decrement  in  the  results  of  work  is  relative  to  the 
intensity  of  the  stimulus. 

Education  and  society  have  a  very  practical  interest  in 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  103 

this  phase  of  the  fatigue  problem.'  They  make  use  of  a  large 
number  of  incentives  in  which  as  Thorndike  wisely  points  out 
the  changes  in  satisfyingness  may  be  a  real  cause  of  work 
decrement.  The  adequate  adjustment  of  stimuli  to  the 
development  of  the  individual  and  the  needs  of  the  case  would 
seem  to  be  a  very  real  problem  in  the  training  of  backward 
and  gifted  as  well  as  normal  children.  It  seems  strange  that 
we  have  so  little  experimental  knowledge  of  the  relative  value 
of  available  reinforcements.  Autogenic  reinforcement  is,  I 
believe,  at  least  one  factor  in  the  underlying  psycho-physics 
of  James's  ' reservoirs  of  power'  which  may  be  quite  as  sig- 
nificant for  psychology  as  the  action  of  adrenin  to  which 
Cannon  has  introduced  us.  That  continuous  activity  under 
the  reinforcement  of  emotion  or  even  in  the  educational  use 
of  play  may  be  a  source  of  serious  fatigue  we  have  been 
warned  by  Kraepelin.  Some  other  reinforcements  are  con- 
spicuous for  their  insistence.  Such  a  one  is  worry.  It  would 
seem  to  be  no  accident  that  this  is  so  closely  connected  with 
exhaustion  psychoses. 

I  believe  that  the  relative  value  of  the  various  inner  stimuli 
would  repay  the  closest  study.  Just  now  it  seems  to  be  inter- 
esting the  abnormal  rather  than  the  normal  psychologist. 
Practical  experience  is  full  of  rough  approximations.  Their 
refinement  by  experimental  techniques  would  not  seem  to  be 
an  impossible  task. 

It  is  possible  that  we  can  study  relative  fatigue  not  merely 
by  the  changes  that  occur  during  long  series  of  repetitions  but 
more  expeditiously  in  the  relative  refractory  phase  which  the 
genius  of  Verworn  proved  to  be  identical  with  the  fatigue 
process.  Since  the  relative  refractory  phase  is  common  to  all 
nervous  tissue,  I  have  asked  the  question  whether  we  can 
find  in  mental  processes  a  similar  phenomenon.  This  is 
undoubtedly  the  case.  In  fact  every  mental  process  shows 
something  analogous.  Repetitions  of  all  sorts  seem  to  be 
avoided  whenever  practicable.  The  repetition  of  questions, 
courses,  lectures,  phrases,  and  even  words  is  possible  enough, 
but  except  for  special  reinforcing  circumstances,  it  is  post- 
poned until  the  effect  of  the  initial  case  is  somewhat  worn  off. 


104  RAYMOND  DODGE 

The  routine  is  regularly  less  alluring  than  the  unusual. 
Mankind  in  general  prefers  new  scenes,  new  plays,  new  walks, 
new  jokes,  new  styles,  new  investigations.  Possibly  the 
decreased  effectiveness  of  over-memorization  is  a  case  in  point. 
Possibly  even  the  loss  of  attention  to  frequently  repeated 
processes,  which  is  commonly  regarded  teleologically  as  a 
freeing  of  consciousness  for  new  adjustments,  may  be  caused 
by  the  longer  refractory  phase  of  the  more  complex  systema- 
tizations  of  attention,  so  that  the  rapidly  repeated  task  is 
dynamically  excluded  from  conscious  emphasis. 

Works  of  art  on  the  contrary  are  characteristically  resistant 
to  the  refractory  phase.  Possibly  this  results  in  some  way 
from  their  origin.  Certainly  one  of  the  marks  of  good  art  is 
the  constancy  of  its  appeals.  The  popular  song,  the  clever 
phrase,  the  good  joke,  soon  finds  us  refractory  to  the  point 
of  desperation,  though  it  is  notable  that  we  become  refractory 
to  their  reception  much  quicker  than  to  their  execution.  We 
like  to  tell  old  jokes  better  than  to  hear  them.  But  the  great 
classics  in  music  and  literature  may  be  heard  over  and  over 
with  increasing  satisfaction.  It  is  not  impossible  that  Aris- 
totle's catharsis  by  dramatic  representation  of  suffering  and 
evil  really  operates  by  developing  a  refractory  phase,  and  a 
kind  of  relative  fatigue.  How  far  this  principle  operates  in 
habituation  to  environment,  indifference  to  shocking  condi- 
tions of  poverty  and  morals,  to  suffering,  and  to  the  horrors  of 
war,  as  well  as  to  luxuries  "when  the  novelty  has  worn  off," 
I  am  not  prepared  to  estimate. 

It  would  seem  that  some  of  these  or  analogous  phenomena 
ought  to  yield  data  for  a  scientific  study  of  the  intensity  of  the 
inner  stimuli  in  connection  with  fatigue  if  we  only  knew  how 
to  use  them.  But  the  very  difficulties  of  technique  emphasize 
how  far  we  are  from  a  real  knowledge  of  relative  mental  fatigue. 

The  simplicity  of  the  nerve-muscle  paradigm  of  mental 
fatigue  is  further  misleading  in  that  it  gives  no  indication  of 
certain  important  complications  which  are  characteristic  of 
higher  systematizations,  and  which  Sherrington  called  their 
competition.  In  a  nerve-muscle  preparation  the  impulse  has 
only  one  possible  path.  In  the  higher  nervous  system  on  the 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  105 

contrary  any  afferent  impulse  may  theoretically  activate 
every  efferent  path.  Just  which  motor  process  it  finally 
initiates,  is  determined  by  a  kind  of  competition.  Competi- 
tion appears  in  the  spinal  reflexes  though  less  conspicuously 
than  in  cortically  conditioned  action,  where  it  is  the  rule. 
Unfortunately,  however,  just  where  it  is  most  significant  it 
can  seldom  be  followed  objectively  by  our  present  means  of 
investigation.  But  there  are  clear  evidences  of  its  operation 
in  associative  thinking,  in  attention,  and  in  perception  as  well 
as  in  conduct. 

The  relatively  fixed  tendencies  of  competition  in  the  cord 
are  probably  determined  very  simply  by  neural  growth  and 
development.  In  higher  systematizations  the  outcome  of 
competition  tends  to  follow  habitual  patterns  which  have 
originated  in  the  varying  life-history  of  the  several  competi- 
tors. At  any  given  moment  in  a  developed  system  of  this 
sort,  the  outcome  may  be  modified  by  a  variety  of  reinforcing 
and  inhibiting  accidents.  Among  the  latter  we  must  count 
fatigue.  In  closely  balanced  competition  the  absolute  de- 
gree of  fatigue  need  not  be  high  to  make  it  a  deciding  factor. 
Indeed  it  is  conceivable  that  if  the  balance  of  the  other  factors 
is  close  enough,  an  infinitesimal  fatigue,  or  the  slightest 
trace  of  a  refractory  phase  may  totally  change  the  character 
of  the  response,  just  as  intrinsically  trivial  reinforcements  or 
accidental  inhibitions  may  be  the  arbiters. 

This  relation  of  fatigue  to  balanced  competition  gives  us 
a  second  type  of  fatigue  relativity.  Fatigue  is  relative,  not 
only  in  the  relation  of  apparent  work  decrement  to  stimulus, 
as  expressed  in  our  first  law;  it  is  also  relative  in  the  sense  of  a 
proportionate  fatigue  of  the  various  factors  in  a  competing 
group.  We  may  tentatively  express  this  second  type  of 
fatigue  relativity  in  the  form  of  a  law  which  for  want  of  a 
better  name  we  may  call  the  Second  Law  of  Relative  Fatigue, 
because  it  implies  a  higher  systematization  than  the  first  law. 
In  any  complex  of  competing  tendencies  the  relatively  greater 
fatigue  of  one  tendency  will  tend  to  eliminate  it  from  the 
competition  in  favor  of  the  less  fatigued  tendencies. 

Unfortunately  the  mechanism  of  competition  cannot  be 


io6  RAYMOND  DODGE 

studied  at  all  in  simple  preparations  and  only  imperfectly  in 
the  reflexes.  The  most  characteristic  systems  are  the  least 
accessible.  In  the  search  for  accessible  human  systems  of 
greater  complexity  than  the  reflexes,  it  occurred  to  me,  some- 
thing over  ten  years  ago,  that  the  motor  apparatus  of  the 
eyes  offered  some  unique  advantages.  There  we  may  study 
twelve  intimately  related  and  delicately  adjusted  final  paths 
which  are  directly  connected  with  reactions  of  considerable 
biological  importance.  Furthermore,  every  variation  of  their 
interaction  is  capable  of  being  recorded  on  a  single  plane, 
without  complicated  mechanical  devices,  and  without  the 
distortions  incident  to  the  moving  of  heavy  masses,  like  the 
limbs.  Since  that  time  the  eye-movements  have  proved  to 
be  unusually  valuable  indicators  of  neural  conditions  in  some 
forms  of  insanity  and  under  the  action  of  alcohol.  In  ex- 
periments that  are  now  in  progress  they  give  promise  of  being 
the  most  consistent  indicators  of  general  neural  conditions. 
In  the  early  hopes  of  using  them  for  an  analysis  of  fatigue 
phenomena,  I  took  a  considerable  number  of  binocular  records 
of  rapid  successions  of  eye-movements  after  the  model  of  the 
ergograph.  Though  reported  on  informally  from  time  to 
time  these  records  have  never  been  published  before  because 
of  my  inability  to  account  for  some  of  their  most  conspicuous 
peculiarities.  As  these  difficulties  have  gradually  been  ex- 
perimentally cleared,  the  records  have  been  seen  to  illustrate 
in  a  remarkable  way  some  of  the  characteristic  phenomena  of 
mental  fatigue,  and  pseudo-fatigue.  In  particular  they  ad- 
mirably schematize  the  second  law  of  relative  fatigue  and 
the  "breaks"  that  it  conditions. 

Let  me  assume  your  familiarity  with  the  technique  of 
photographically  recording  the  eye-movements  from  the 
corneal  reflection.  For  the  present  records  the  eyes  moved 
horizontally  through  an  arc  of  sixty  degrees,  fixating  success- 
ively two  knitting  needles  which  were  situated  thirty  degrees 
on  either  side  of  the  primary  position  of  the  line  of  regard. 
Each  dot  or  dash  on  the  records  represents  one  phase  of  the 
alternating  current,  and  a  time  interval  of  about  eight  thou- 
sandths of  a  second. 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  107 


sz 

*". 


io8  RAYMOND  DODGE 

The  succession  of  eye-movements  in  the  records  that  are  here 
reproduced  was  as  rapid  as  practicable  with  subjectively 
adequate  successive  fixation  of  the  two  fixation  marks.  Some 
of  the  more  characteristic  fatigue  phenomena  which  they 
show  are:  (i)  The  speed  of  movement  becomes  less  towards 
the  end  of  the  series;  (2)  the  fixations  become  less  accurate; 
(3)  and  finally  the  line  of  movement  itself  becomes  more 
irregular.  Fig.  2  shows  the  climax  of  these  processes  in  a 
break.  The  gradual  decrease  in  angle  velocity  corresponds  to 
the  work  decrement  of  extirpated  muscle.  But  in  this  case, 
in  view  of  Sherrington's  demonstration  of  the  reciprocal  in- 
hibition of  antagonistic  eye-muscles,  it  doubtless  involves 
something  more.  The  greatest  angle  velocity  of  eye-move- 
ment could  only  occur  when  the  relaxation  of  the  antagonistic 
was  perfectly  coordinated  with  the  contraction,  of  the  agon- 
istic muscle.  The  pseudo-work-decrement  in  this  case  then 
is  not  purely  muscular  but  is  in  part  a  matter  of  defective 
coordination.  The  increasing  errors  of  coordination  have  a 
similar  origin.  That  is,  the  total  elaboration  of  the  con- 
traction impulse  and  the  corresponding  relaxation  of  the 
antagonistic  becomes  less  exact  in  successive  repetitions  of 
the  act  of  fixation.  But  the  coordination  is  not  limited  to  the 
internal  and  external  recti  as  one  might  expect  them  to  be  in 
horizontal  movements  of  the  eyes.  All  the  records  of  60" 
eye-movements,  which  I  have  ever  seen,  show  a  vertical 
factor.  In  all  my  records  this  vertical  factor  results  in  an 
elevation  of  the  line  of  regard.  But  it  varies  from  movement 
to  movement.  That  these  vertical  components  are  not  acci- 
dents of  purely  muscular  origin  is  shown  by  binocular  records. 
Since  the  disturbances  are  homologous  for  both  eyes,  their 
origin  must  lie  in  the  central  nervous  system.  While  occa- 
sional gross  disturbances  occur  early  in  the  series  of  move- 
ments, they  become  more  and  more  conspicuous  as  the 
series  progresses.  The  vertical  components  represent  the 
intercurrent  action  of  related  and  competing,  but  this  is  a 
case  of  non-inhibiting  systems.  When  they  become  extreme 
they  tend  to  interrupt  for  a  moment  the  main  rhythm  of 
horizontal  movements.  In  some  cases  these  various  disturb- 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  109 

ances  produce  a  moment  of  confusion  and  a  break  in  the 
process,  which  in  ordinary  mental  fatigue  experiments  would 
be  interpreted  as  complete  fatigue  or  exhaustion. 

Our  eye-movement  schema  for  the  relative  fatigue  of 
competing  systems  is  particularly  free  from  complications 
through  extrinsic  facilitations  and  inhibitions.  Retinal  fa- 
tigue or  adaptation  is  reduced  to  a  minimum  by  the  eye- 
movement  itself,  and  the  consequent  shift  of  the  area  of 
stimulation.  The  homologous  fixation  marks,  under  constant 
illumination  present  the  same  stimulus  for  each  reaction  in 
the  same  direction.  Cortical  conditions  of  the  successive 
reactions,  such  as  interest,  attention  and  motives  to  continue 
at  work,  cannot  of  course  be  guaranteed  to  remain  constant. 
But  the  experiment  itself  introduces  no  obvious  distractions 
like  the  physical  discomfort  of  the  ergograph.  Moreover,  all 
our  relative  fatigue  phenomena  appear  during  short  experi- 
mental periods. 

In  order  to  protect  our  conclusions  from  the  dangers  in- 
herent in  a  single  line  of  experimental  evidence,  I  sought  other 
similarly  complicated  coordination  systems.  While  thus  far 
no  other  has  been  found  with  all  the  advantages  of  the  hori- 
zontal eye-movements,  those  movements  of  the  index  finger 
which  Bergstrom  recommended  for  ergographic  work  show  a 
similar  complication.  Undoubtedly  the  strongest  and  best 
practiced  oscillatory  movements  of  the  index  finger  are  the 
flexion-extension  movements.  Considerably  less  easy  for 
most  of  us  are  movements  of  the  finger  sideways  in  the  plane 
of  the  hand.  In  any  event,  rapid  oscillation  of  the  finger  in 
this  direction  is  always  disturbed  by  intercurrent  action  of  the 
flexors  and  extensors.  Their  action  prevents  rectilinear 
movement,  decreases  the  angle  velocity,  and  finally  may  so 
confuse  the  process  as  to  produce  a  break  in  the  sequence  of 
oscillations,  quite  like  the  disturbances  of  the  eye-movements. 

It  was  the  phenomena  of  these  relatively  accessible  com- 
plex systematizations  that  forced  me  to  a  re-analysis  of  the 
mental  fatigue  concept.  I  believe  that  our  eye-movement 
paradigm  gives  us  the  clue  not  only  for  a  more  intelligent 
experimental  investigation  of  mental  fatigue,  but  also  for  the 


no  RAYMOND  DODGE 

interpretation  of  previous  investigations.  The  very  irre- 
gularity of  the  traditional  results  may  be  an  expression  of  the 
laws  of  relativity.  But  I  hope  that  the  time  has  passed  when 
an  experimenter  will  be  content  to  give  us  only  the  work  dec- 
rement as  datum  for  the  measure  of  fatigue.  Certainly  the 
break  can  no  longer  be  regarded  as  a  temporary  exhaustion  of 
a  function.  Perhaps  the  least  expected  change  that  the  new 
paradigm  will  make  in  our  tradition  is  the  place  of  the  inter- 
fering sensations  of  weariness.  These  may,  after  all,  turn 
out  to  be  subjective  indicators  of  real  fatigue.  Their  effect 
in  apparent  work  decrement,  however,  will  be  determined 
by  their  relative  importance  in  the  group  of  competing  tenden- 
cies. Under  normal  conditions  at  least  I  doubt  if  we  should 
call  weariness  a  pseudo-fatigue. 

It  will  be  noted  that  the  eye-movement  paradigm  is  still 
much  too  simple  to  apply  directly  to  our  mental  processes. 
In  place  of  its  anatomically  restricted  competition  to  the 
nuclei  of  the  third,  fourth,  and  sixth  cranial  nerves,  we  have 
reason  to  believe  that  cortical  competitions  are  as  indef- 
initely complicated  as  the  various  active  association  ten- 
dencies. That  a  variety  of  tendencies  to  associative  repro- 
duction are  normally  aroused  as  the  effect  of  a  mental  stimulus 
is  indicated  by  the  facts  of  the  association  experiment.  This 
normal  spread  of  excitation,  coupled  with  the  effect  of  psycho- 
physiological  rhythms,  and  the  complication  of  simultaneous 
stimuli  from  the  different  receptor  fields,  gives  the  com- 
petition in  mental  operations  an  almost  chaotic  complexity. 
But  in  addition  to  all  that,  we  must  extend  our  notion  of 
competition  and  relative  fatigue  to  those  more  slowly  changing 
inner  determinants  of  action  that  we  call  motives,  controls, 
and  the  like.  Indeed  it  seems  probable  that  these  inner 
factors,  in  so  far  as  they  are  the  only  continuously  acting 
factors  in  mental  work,  are  more  apt  to  be  the  locus  of  abso- 
lute fatigue  than  the  several  discrete  association  tendencies 
which  are  involved  only  occasionally  in  the  mental  task. 

But  aside  from  the  obvious  differences  in  complexity  our 
paradigm  adequately  represents  the  fundamental  processes. 
However  long  a  mental  process  may  be  continued  and  how- 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  T  1 1 

ever  insignificant  the  decrement  in  returns,  there  comes  a 
moment  when  it  stops.  It  may  be  interrupted  by  demands 
for  food,  for  sleep,  or  by  some  competing  task.  It  may  be 
interrupted  by  the  gradually  increasing  insistence  of  inhibiting 
sensations  like  thirst,  eye-strain,  muscle  pains,  or  pressure 
pains  from  sitting  still.  In  any  case,  the  work  decrement  of 
the  consequent  break  can  never  be  fully  understood  if  we 
regard  it  as  a  direct  product  of  fatigue,  but  only  in  connection 
with  the  intercurrent  competing  tendencies.  Fatigue  may 
be  a  contributing  factor,  but  the  apparent  decrement  of  the 
break  will  bear  no  regular  relation  to  the  degree  of  absolute 
fatigue  in  the  tissues  which  performed  the  discontinued  task. 
This  enables  us  to  understand  why  in  pathogenic  nervous 
exhaustion,  the  physician  in  search  of  a  therapeutic  measure 
may  seek  to  strengthen  some  competing  interest.  He  may 
even  try  to  develop  some  fad,  philanthropy,  golf,  the  calcu- 
lation of  food  calories,  or  what  not,  to  compete  with  the  old 
system  and  its  emotional,  business,  or  religious  reinforce- 
ments. Most  normal  lives  seem  too  full  of  competing  ten- 
dencies. In  my  own  case  I  have  been  interested  in  observing 
how  every  prolonged  period  of  monotonous  work  like  correct- 
ing papers,  for  example,  finds  before  its  close  some  insistent 
demand  for  interruption.  If  I  successfully  suppress  one 
demand,  more  insistent  ones  arise,  until  finally  effective 
voluntary  reinforcement  of  the  main  task  suddenly  ends. 
The  voluntary  reinforcements  may  have  developed  such  sen- 
sations of  strain  that  the  surrender  to  a  competing  impulse 
brings  great  relief.  I  know  that  the  interruption  is  not  per- 
manent. I  consent  to  it  to  get  the  lesser  matter  off  my  mind, 
expecting  to  return  presently  to  the  main  task,  freed  from  the 
incubus  of  that  particular  competitor.  In  very  much  the 
same  way,  after  lying  awake  for  a  time  on  one  side  we  turn 
over,  not  because  we  could  not  lie  on  that  side  longer,  not 
because  we  expect  any  great  improvement  from  the  change, 
certainly  not  because  we  expect  to  lie  on  the  other  side  for- 
ever. The  displacement  of  the  body  mass  is  scarcely  the 
product  of  fatigue.  But  in  the  complex  of  competing  ten- 
dencies a  little  relative  fatigue  becomes  the  occasion  for  an 


112  RAYMOND  DODGE 

entirely  disproportionate  result.  Possibly  social  unrest  fol- 
lows a  similar  course.  They  seek  a  change  in  the  govern- 
ment, or  the  social  and  labor  conditions,  not  because  the 
present  is  really  unendurable,  not  because  they  expect  a  per- 
manent betterment.  In  many  cases  at  least,  they  act  from 
relative  fatigue,  to  shift  the  pressure.  I  suppose  all  the 
phenomena  of  restlessness  and  the  corresponding  attractive- 
ness of  change  finally  reduce  to  competition  and  the  relative 
refractory  phase.  They  operate  in  work  and  play,  in  social 
and  economic  activities,  in  politics  and  in  religion.  Without 
their  interference  in  our  lives,  unwelcome  as  it  often  is,  we 
must  have  continued  indefinitely  in  the  direction  of  our  first 
activity,  with  the  consequent  loss  of  that  vital  equilibrium 
on  which  the  organism  as  a  unit  of  different  parts  depends  for 
its  continued  existence.  Without  their  interference  the  initial 
process  must  always  work  itself  out  to  the  final  collapse  of 
complete  exhaustion. 

Relative  fatigue,  then,  is  not  a  mere  limitation  of  human 
efficiency.  It  is  not  exhaustion,  but  prevents  it.  It  is  a 
conservator  of  organic  equilibrium,  as  well  as  a  condition  of 
organic  development.  The  incapacity  of  the  young  child 
for  long-continued  monotonous  tasks  may  be  a  symptom  of 
an  active,  developing  mind.  Lack  of  competition  would 
result  in  mental  deformity,  or  absolute  exhaustion,  just  as 
truly  as  the  lack  of  stable  reinforcing  systems  in  the  adult 
would  mean  perpetual  infantilism.  Thus  it  seems  to  me 
that  the  principles  of  relative  fatigue  have  a  direct  bearing 
on  the  practical  problems  of  education  which  the  traditional 
doctrine  of  fatigue  as  apparent  work  decrement  entirely 
missed.  The  development  of  the  capacity  to  sit  still,  to  con- 
tinue long  at  routine  work,  the  adequate  response  to  all  formal 
discipline  demands  more  than  the  strengthening  of  the  cor- 
responding neural  bonds.  It  demands  the  weakening  or 
elimination  of  competing  tendencies.  At  least  one  of  the 
perils  of  routine  education  arises  from  this  depression  of  spon- 
taneity. But  I  have  expressly  disclaimed  any  right  or 
intent  to  discuss  the  practical  side  of  the  problem. 

I  cannot  quite  resist  the  temptation,  however,  in  closing, 


THE  LAWS  OF  RELATIVE  FATIGUE  1 13 

to  point  a  methodological  moral.  There  has  seemed  to  me 
to  be  something  almost  humiliating  in  the  eagerness  with 
which  tests  of  mental  fatigue  have  been  sought,  while  there  is 
still  so  much  that  is  uncertain  in  our  knowledge  of  the  funda- 
mental nature  of  the  process  that  we  would  test.  If  it  is  not 
too  great  a  strain  on  presidential  license  at  a  meeting  like 
this,  when  the  program  is  so  largely  devoted  to  the  matter 
of  tests,  I  would  sound  a  note  of  warning  that  in  my  opinion 
any  tendency  to  supplant  psychological  investigation  by 
tests  would  contain  a  serious  menace  to  the  future  of  psy- 
chology. Both  have  their  proper  place.  But  it  can  only 
lead  to  confusion  and  work  to  the  discredit  of  our  science  if 
the  search  for  practical  tests  blinds  us  to  the  necessity  for 
studying  the  dynamics  of  the  processes  that  we  hope  to  test. 
We  cannot  afford  to  develop  a  new  phrenology. 


MORE  CONCERNING  THE  TEMPORAL  RELATIONS 
OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY 

BY  EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 

Northwestern  University 

The  controversy  between  the  imageless  thought  adherents 
and  their  opponents  has  been  lent  a  new  aspect  by  the  work 
of  Dr.  T.  V.  Moore.1  He  has  ingeniously  devised  a  simple 
but  most  fruitful  method  for  investigating  the  temporal  rela- 
tions of  meaning  and  imagery.  By  the  use  of  this  method, 
he  has  brought  forward  striking  evidence  which  seems  to 
support  the  contentions  of  the  imageless  thought  school. 
The  present  investigation  makes  use  of  Dr.  Moore's  method, 
but  by  applying  it  to  a  greater  number  of  subjects  has  ob- 
tained data  which  point  to  a  qualification,  if  not  a  contra- 
diction, of  Dr.  Moore's  conclusions. 

In  the  part  of  Dr.  Moore's  work  which  directly  concerns 
us,  he  presented  to  his  subjects  the  names  of  easily  visualizable 
common  objects,  such  as  Zange,  Fernglas,  Pfeil,  Messer, 
Lampe,  etc.,2  and  asked  them  to  react  according  to  either 
one  of  two  instructions.  One  time  he  would  instruct  them 
to  react  just  as  soon  as  they  had  obtained  the  meaning  of  the 
word,  another  time  just  as  soon  as  they  had  obtained  a  visual 
image  of  the  object  which  the  word  named.  Nonsense  words 
were  occasionally  introduced  as  a  check  to  make  sure  that 
the  subject  was  reacting  to  real  meanings.  By  averaging  up 
the  times  separately  for  the  two  kinds  of  reaction,  he  found 
whether,  on  the  average,  the  subject  could  obtain  meaning 
or  visual  image  in  shorter  time. 

Of  the  9  subjects  to  whom  he  applied  the  method,  all 
but  one  gave  unambiguously  shorter  average  reaction  times 
for  meaning  than  for  visual  image.  In  the  case  of  the  one, 

XT.  V.  Moore,  'The  Temporal  Relations  of  Meaning  and  Imagery,'  PSYCHOL. 
REV.,  1915,  22,  177-225. 

2  The  work  was  performed  at  Prof.  Kxilpe's  laboratory  in  Germany. 
114 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        "5 

the  figures  showed  a  tendency  in  the  opposite  direction.  The 
average  reaction  times  were  slightly  shorter  for  visual  image 
than  for  meaning.  The  trustworthiness  of  these  figures  was, 
however,  called  into  question  by  the  fact  that  this  subject 
was  never  cured  of  a  habit  of  reacting  to  nonsense  words  as 
readily  as  to  real  words.  This  fact  led  Moore  to  reject  the 
figures  of  this  subject  as  inconclusive,  and  to  draw  all  his 
conclusions  from  the  results  of  the  8  subjects  who  agreed. 

Introspections  were  asked  for  after  each  reaction  and  it 
was  found  that  the  introspection  of  these  subjects  bore  out 
the  testimony  of  their  objective  reaction  times.  They  all 
agreed,  that  is,  in  reporting  an  awareness  of  simple  meaning 
which  appeared  in  every  case  prior  to  the  image.  Further 
introspection  indicated  that  this  awareness  of  meaning  was  a 
totally  different  kind  of  content  from  image. 

From  these  facts,  combined  with  similar  ones  obtained 
from  experiments  on  the  time  relation  of  meaning  and  verbal 
imagery,  in  which  pictures  of  objects  were  shown  the  subject, 
and  he  was  sometimes  instructed  to  react  when  he  obtained 
the  meaning  of  the  picture,  and  sometimes  when  he  obtained 
a  verbal  image  of  the  name  of  the  object,  Dr.  Moore  con- 
cludes that  meaning  as  a  psychological  content  is  sui  generis 
and  independent  of  imagery. 

The  present  writer  was  led  to  question  these  conclusions 
because  of  the  conviction  that  his  own  consciousness  of 
meaning  depended  in  no  small  part  upon  visual  imagery. 
With  that  conviction  in  mind,  he  attempted  by  a  method 
essentially  similar  to  Dr.  Moore's  (to  be  described  below) 
to  put  the  matter  to  test.  Great  was  his  surprise,  however, 
to  discover  that  he  himself,  when  the  experimental  conditions 
were  thus  controlled,  substantiated  the  results  of  Dr.  Moore's 
subjects,  in  that,  on  the  average,  he  obtained  meaning  in  less 
time  than  he  did  visual  image.  In  the  course  of  more  or  less 
haphazard  experimenting,  however,  the  writer,  largely  by 
accident,  discovered  a  subject  who  did  fulfill  the  prediction 
he  had  made  for  himself;  a  subject,  namely,  who  obtained 
visual  image,  on  the  average,  in  as  short  a  time  as  she  ob- 


Ii6  EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 

tained  meaning,  and  who  declared  that  introspectively  the 
image  was  a  part  of,  or  essential  to,  the  meaning. 

This  purely  chance  discovery  suggested  to  the  writer  that, 
if  a  large  enough  number  of  subjects  were  to  be  examined,  a 
small  proportion  might  be  found  whose  results  would  agree 
with  those  of  the  subject  just  mentioned  rather  than  with 
those  both  of  the  writer  himself  and  of  Dr.  Moore's  8  subjects. 
In  pursuance  of  such  a  possibility,  an  investigation  was  under- 
taken of  as  many  Northwestern  University  students  as 
possible  who  were  at  the  time  taking  either  the  introductory 
course  in  psychology  or  the  laboratory  training  course. 

The  method  employed  was  slightly  different  from  that 
used  by  Dr.  Moore.  Instead  of  presenting  a  purely  chance 
list  of  names,  names  of  black  or  of  white  objects  only  were 
presented.  The  subject  was  given  two  keys,  one  for  the 
right  hand  and  one  for  the  left,  and  instructed  to  react  with 
the  right  hand  if  the  object  were  black,  and  with  the  left 
hand  if  the  object  were  white.  The  following  typewritten 
instructions,  which  were  read  by  the  subject  before  the  be- 
ginning of  the  experiment,  will  make  the  method  clearer: 

"You  will  either  be  shown  the  name  of  something  which 
is  black  or  of  something  which  is  white.  If  it  is  black,  you 
are  to  press  the  right-hand  key;  if  white,  the  left-hand  one. 
Sometimes  you  will  be  told  beforehand  that  you  are  to  react 
(i.  e.j  press  the  appropriate  key)  the  instant  you  know  whether 
the  object  is  black  or  white,  irrespective  of  how  you  know  it. 
Other  times  you  will  be  told  beforehand  that  you  are  to  react 
the  instant  you  see  from  your  visual  image  whether  the  object 
is  black  or  white.  Introspection  will  be  asked  for  from  time 
to  time  during  the  course  of  the  experiment." 

Each  word  was  typewritten  on  a  slip  of  paper  which  could 
be  fastened  to  a  piece  of  black  cardboard;  the  latter  was  cut 
so  as  to  slip  into  place  directly  behind  a  pair  of  shutters. 
These  were  made  to  swing  open  towards  the  subject  by  means 
of  a  camera-bulb.  When  opened,  they  exposed  a  black  field 
in  the  center  of  which  appeared  the  slip  of  paper  with  the 
typewritten  word. 

A  Bergstrom  pendulum  chronoscope  was  used.1     This  was 

1  Described  as  Model  No.  2  in  PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1910,  17,  1-18. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        117 

arranged  so  that  the  opening  of  the  shutters  closed  a  circuit 
which  by  means  of  a  magnet  released  the  pendulum.  The 
pressing  of  either  reaction  key  closed  another  circuit,  which 
by  means  of  another  magnet  stopped  the  pointer  carried  by 
the  pendulum.  The  scale  over  which  the  pointer  passed  was 
calibrated  to  be  read  directly  to  thousandths  of  a  second. 
The  complete  swing  of  the  pendulum  lasted  2  seconds  only;  any 
time  longer  than  2  seconds  could  not,  therefore,  be  recorded. 

The  chronoscope  was  tested  by  means  of  a  seconds  pendu- 
lum before  the  beginning  of  the  investigation,  and  the  strength 
of  the  currents  in  the  two  magnet  circuits  were  found  such 
that  a  complete  swing  on  the  seconds  pendulum  registered  on 
the  chronoscope  correctly  to  within  0.005  °f  a  second.  These 
strengths  of  current  were  noted  and  established  throughout 
the  course  of  the  experiments  by  means  of  rheostats  which 
were  included  in  each  of  the  two  circuits. 

Each  subject  was  presented  the  same  list  of  24  words. 
The  reaction  times  of  the  first  4  were  rejected.  The  remain- 
ing 20,  the  times  for  which  were  counted,  were  the  following: 
coffee,  lime,  steam,  snow,  mud,  coal,  swan,  iron,  diamond, 
crow,  plaster,  negro,  cinders,  raven,  milk,  print,  teeth,  jet, 
cement,  lard. 

It  will  be  observed  that  10  of  them  are  names  of  white 
objects,  and  10  names  of  black  objects. 

The  programme  was  arranged  so  that  for  5  of  the  'white' 
words  the  subject  was  instructed  to  react  to  meaning,  and 
for  5  instructed  to  react  to  image;  the  same  held  for  the 
*  black'  words.  But  different  sets  of  5  were  used  for  meaning 
and  image,  respectively,  in  presenting  this  same  list  to  suc- 
cessive subjects. 

The  testing  of  each  subject  took  about  30  minutes,  and 
49  subjects  in  all  were  tested.1  In  Table  I.  we  present  the 
final  results  for  all  the  subjects. 

1  The  writer  wishes  to  express  his  indebtedness  to  Mr.  Leslie  B.  Bunch  and  to 
Mr.  Wilbert  C.  Keiser,  who  helped  as  experimenters  throughout  this  part  of  the 
investigation,  and  to  the  latter  also  for  his  assistance  in  the  preliminary  experiments 
and  in  setting  up  the  apparatus. 

If,  for  any  reason,  there  was  a  slip  on  the  part  either  of  the  experimenter  or  of 
the  subject,  so  that  no  reaction  was  obtained  for  one  of  these  words,  this  was  usually 
rectified  by  making  the  subject  react  in  the  same  way  to  another  word  of  the  proper 
color  at  the  end  of  list. 


n8 


EDWARD  GRACE   TOLMAN 


TABLE  I 


Men 

Women 

Subject 

M. 

V.  I. 

Subject 

M. 

V.I. 

Mr.  Bark.. 
"    Bu  

•823 
I.I99 

'.617 

.868 

.796 
.764 
•7942 

'.887 

•843 
.884 
.792 
.617 

'ill 
.8n 

.972 
.816 

.893 
i.  060 

.888 
1.136 

1-385; 
1.7841 
1.014 
.684 

1.051 
1.027 

2.OOO3 
1.289 

•932 
.918 
1.047 
1.044 

1-457 
I-4391 

1.014 

•757 
.724 
.802 
.761 
•975 

Miss  C  

.742 
1-378 

778 
Could  not 
visual 
•834 
•983 
1.058 
.892 

1.003 
.756 

•654 
.916 

I-I93 

.682 
.870 

.717 
•784 
•775 
•561 
.827 
-736 
.820 
.862 

•752 
I.8881 
1.056 

obtain 
images. 
.942 
.266 

•145 
.266 

•247 
.770 
.841 
-335 
•9731 
.891 
.890 
.889 

.719 
•743 
•734 
.528 
.821 
.698 

•754 
.912 

"      E  

"    Ca 

"     Go  
"     Gr 

"    Co  

"    De  

"     Gu 

::  £:::::  

"     H 

"     Ed   T 

"    M 

"     El  T 

"    N   . 

"     S.  T  
"     Ka 

"    O 

"    Pa 

"     LI  
'     Mas  
'     Mi 

"    Ril  
"    Rit  

"    Si... 

'     Pa 

"    St 

'     Pe 

«        rp 

'     Po 

"    We  

'     Rea 

"    Bart*.. 

'     S  
"     A* 

"    L.*  

"     B* 

"    Mi*  
"    Milln*  

"     Ki.*  

"     Kn  *  
"     Li* 

"    Pe.*  

"    Wa*  

"     Mac* 

"     Rei  * 

"     V*  

1  Some  of  the  individual  reaction-times  from  which  this  mean  was  computed  were 
over  2  sees.     But,  since,  as  before  mentioned  (see  above  p.  117),  the  maximum  range 
of  the  chronoscope  used  was  only  2  sees.,  we  reckoned  them  at  only  2  sees,  each  in 
computing  the  mean.     The  direction  of  the  results,  it  will  be  noted,  however,  were 
not  obscured  by  this  method. 

2  In  the  case  of  Mr.  N.,  two  of  the  individual  reaction-times  for  "  meaning " 
exceeded  2  sees.,  but  were  reckoned  at  only  2  sees,  in  computing  the  mean. 

3  In  the  case  of  Mr.  N.,  all  of  the  individual  reaction-times  for  "  visual  image  " 
exceeded  2  sees.,  but  were  reckoned  at  2  sees,  in  computing  the  mean. 

The  second  column  on  each  side  gives  the  arithmetical 
mean  time  for  the  subject's  reaction  to  meaning;  and  the 
third  column  the  arithmetical  mean  time  for  his  or  her  reac- 
tion to  visual  image. 

It  will  be  observed  that  by  far  the  greater  majority  of 
the  subjects  (those  whose  names  are  not  starred)  showed  a 
decidedly  shorter  reaction  time  for  meaning  than  for  visual 
image.  And  this  holds  in  about  equal  proportions  for  men 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        119 


and  women.  They  belong,  in  short,  to  the  type  represented 
both  by  Dr.  Moore's  8  subjects  and  by  the  writer  himself. 
Their  introspections  also  bear  out  this  conclusion.  They  all 
agree  in  reporting  a  meaning  which  appeared  before  visual 
image. 

Turning  now,  however,  to  the  subjects  whose  names  are 
starred,  we  find  a  group  for  whom  the  results  are  quite  differ- 
ent. All  but  two  of  them,  Mr.  Bart,  and  Miss  V.,  gave  mean 
reaction  times  which  were  actually  longer  for  meaning  than 
for  visual  image,  and  these  two  gave  introspections  of  a 
character  which,  combined  with  the  closeness  of  their  reaction 
time,  suggested  that  a  longer  and  more  careful  examination 
of  them  might  have  resulted  in  their  cases  also,  in  a  longer 
reaction  time  for  meaning  than  for  visual  image. 

GROUP  i 
TABLE  II 

SUBJECT  Miss  B. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Fork  

I.O^O 

.092 

Square  

I.4QO 

.3-27 

Turkey  

.88c 

•0^3 

Ring  

7^ 
.6q2 

•jj/ 
.4.61 

Banjo                   .  . 

.800 

.138 

Lion     

I.O2C 

.128 

Rose 

I.34.C 

•4-O7 

Candle 

.co8 

.CCC 

Fly 

872 

.066 

Steamer 

.872 

.281 

Book 

814. 

.124. 

Circle 

I  362 

2OO 

Nest  

.014 
.61;  I 

•*T* 

.287 

Sofa  

1.  17O 

.217 

Boot  

.822 

.116 

Tree  

•9  IS. 

.238 

Heart  

.04.  e 

.OO7 

Stocking    

I.37O 

.217 

Tug.  .  . 

.6c8 

.280 

Stairs 

*o/~ 
.006 

.24.7 

Oven  .... 

.782 

.IC6 

Crown 

.QQO 

.163 

Knife 

.7C2 

.186 

Tower 

I  23O 

077 

Cat 

•O-* 
.06  c 

O27 

Spoon 

I  COC 

•7  C2 

Cradle 

6QO 

.24.8 

Cherry 

I  3  CO 

107 

Rooster  

I.C2C 

.587 

Brush  

*-55« 

I.  OOo 

.147 

Mouse  

.772 

.166 

Drum          .  . 

.960 

.193 

Snake 

OI2 

O74. 

i  308 

ICC 

Sled  

.356 

.4.18 

Pear 

I.IJ.O 

.OI3 

Mask  

.12? 

.187 

Peacock 

.078 

.175 

Flag. 

.c8o 

.1*8 

Skull 

I  708 

.CCC 

J.  lag 

Letter    .  . 

•772 

.166 

Flask 

I  620 

•033 
.467 

Rabbit 

.268 

-5-7Q 

Chain 

868 

.28c 

Anchor 

^oo 

362 

I  24.O 

.087 

782 

•!>V4 

I  Co 

.13U 

Tntal 

f 

Tntal 

20.503 

5-75° 

22.503 

4.991 

Mean  = 

Median  = 

•938 
.847 

.208 

Median  = 

I.I52 
I.I40 

.250 

I2O 


EDWARD  CHACE   TOLMAN 


TABLE  III 

Miss  L. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Turkey   

.c6o 

.044. 

Square 

7IO 

1^6 

Banjo                   .... 

.C72 

.1^4. 
.OIO 

Ring 

;i8 

.l^U 

QCO 

Rose 

_rjT 

ooc 

Lion 

•bl° 
6cc 

081 

Candle 

3QI 

I2C 

Steamer 

•»55 

60  c 

Q-J  T 

Flv 

6^? 

117 

Circle 

723 

I4.Q 

Nest  

.330 

.186 

Book  

.C2O 

.OC4. 

Boot  

.4.82 

.O34 

Sofa  

.660 

.086 

Heart  

-4-O4. 

.112 

Tree     .  . 

.c8o 

.QIC 

TUR  .  . 

.478 

.o-?8 

Stocking 

c6o 

OI4. 

Oven  . 

.COC 

.on 

Stairs 

•bvu 
^60 

.214. 

Knife  . 

.4.QC 

.III 

Crown 

.JWW 

482 

OQ2 

Tower 

•3QQ 

126 

Cat 

568 

OO6 

Cradle  

.CQO 

.074 

Spoon  

.630 

.<x6 

Rooster  

.q82 

.066 

Cherry  

•VJW 

.620 

•^3^ 

.04.6 

Hat  

••y" 
.60; 

.080 

Scissors 

.TIC 

.OCQ 

Mouse  

,C4.c 

.020 

Brush 

C-72 

.O4.2 

Snake  .  . 

OtO 
.672 

7 
.ICO 

Drum 

cic 

.OCQ 

Sled 

.66  c 

14.0 

Hammer 

7OC 

I-5I 

Peacock 

CIO 

.i^y 
OOO 

Mask 

c  TO 

064. 

Ladder  

.C2O 

.OO4. 

Flag  

.rcc 

.OIQ 

Skull 

•w»y 

062 

Total 

.51^ 

.490 

Total 

,  , 

PT/q 

12.044 

•47* 

Median  = 

.510 

.516 

•°7S 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•574 
.560 

.070 

To  make  sure  of  this  result,  however,  we  subjected  these 
14  subjects  to  further  tests,  and,  in  doing  so,  we  decided  to 
copy  Mr.  Moore's  method  exactly,  rather  than  to  use  the 
preceding  *  discrimination  between  black  and  white'  method.1 

The  words  presented  to  the  subjects  were  one  and  two 
syllable  names  of  common  objects.  The  subjects  were  some- 
times instructed  to  react  as  soon  as  they  obtained  the  meaning 
of  the  word,  sometimes  as  soon  as  they  obtained  a  visual  image 
of  the  object  which  the  word  named.  The  instructions  'react 
to  meaning,'  and  'react  to  visual  image'  were  in  the  case  of 
any  one  subject  distributed  irregularly,  but  with  approxi- 
mately equal  frequency.  A  majority  of  the  same  words 

1  The  black  and  white  method  was  adopted  originally  with  the  idea  that  it  would 
set  a  more  definite  check,  in  the  case  of  reaction  to  meaning,  by  making  sure  that  the 
subject  really  understood  and  not  merely  recognized  the  word.  The  results,  how- 
ever, were  so  exactly  similar  to  those  obtained  from  Mr.  Moore's  method,  that  it  was 
thought  as  well  to  adopt  the  latter. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        121 


were  used  over  again  for  the  successive  subjects  in  such  a  way 
that  the  same  word  would  with  one  subject  call  for  the  in- 
struction 'react  to  meaning,'  and  with  another  that  of  'react 
to  visual  image.'  Introspections  were  asked  for  after  about 
half  the  reactions  only,  owing  to  insufficient  time,  as  each 
subject  could  spare  but  a  little  over  an  hour,  and  it  was 
desired  to  obtain  from  each  as  long  an  objective  series  as 
possible.  Nonsense  words,  introduced  occasionally,  served 
as  checks  to  make  sure  that  the  subject  was  reacting  fairly. 
The  results  of  the  first  few  reactions  in  the  case  of  each  subject 
were  discarded.  The  writer  served  as  sole  experimenter 
throughout  this  series. 

Tables  II.-XV.  inclusive  present  the  results  for  the 
different  subjects.  In  the  first  column  are  the  words  on 
which  the  subjects  received  the  instruction  'react  to  mean- 
ing'; in  the  second  column  are  the  reaction  times  for  these 
words;  and  in  the  third  column  are  the  deviations  of  these 

TABLE  IV 

MR.  MILLN. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Turkey  

.96? 

.OC2 

Fork  

.968 

.022 

Banjo  

.74.8 

«*3« 

.161: 

Square 

1.  172 

.226 

Lion  .    . 

.8t;6 

.OC7 

Ring 

.04-2 

.OO4. 

Candle. 

86c 

•*o/ 

O4.8 

Rose 

OCX 

O4.  1 

Circle 

93O 

OI7 

Flv 

818 

128 

Book 

QC2 

O3Q 

Steamer 

QQC 

O4.Q 

Sofa  

I.OAO 

.127 

Nest  

.992 

•U4y 

.04.6 

Tree  

.7OI 

.212 

Boot   .    . 

.872 

.074. 

Stocking  

•/T* 

.Q62 

•O4.Q 

Heart 

.072 

•w/*f 
.026 

Stairs  

.QCQ 

.O37 

TUJJ 

0.6  c 

OI9 

Crown  .... 

.017 

OO4. 

Oven 

QCK 

O4.  1 

Knife 

024. 

OI  I 

Cat 

I  I  O2 

ic6 

Tower 

868 

O4.C 

I  OCK 

QCQ 

Cradle 

i  086 

17-7 

818 

•*OjJ 

128 

Snake  

1.28-? 

.370 

Rooster 

.84.0 

.106 

Hammer  

.700 

.123 

Scissors 

"*TT 

I.OIO 

.070 

Sled  

.QCO 

•O37 

Hat 

.814. 

.132 

Mask  

^J 

.6O2 

.221 

Brush 

.873 

.073 

Peacock                 .    . 

,QJ.O 

O27 

Mouse 

98  c 

.O3O 

Letter 

.8l8 

O7  c 

Drum 

O7O 

O24, 

Flask 

•y4° 

.027 

Total 

Total 

IO  177 

1'4"J 

,  , 

f. 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•913 
•930 

.091 

Median  = 

.940 

.967 

.073 

122 


EDWARD  GRACE   TOLMAN 


GROUP  2 

TABLE  V 

MR.  L. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Banjo 

6q8 

O2  1 

Ring 

78  C 

Q-2Q 

680 

O3Q 

Fly 

•/  •> 

O4.O 

IIC 

Rose  

•75° 

.OTI 

Circle  

,8lO 

.occ 

Candle  

.660 

.CKQ 

Book  

.722 

.0^3 

Steamer 

.760 

.O4I 

Nest  

.Q2C 

.170 

Sofa 

.027 

.2O8 

Boot  

.718 

037 

Tree 

768 

O4.Q 

Heart 

I  378 

623 

Stocking 

773 

OCA 

Ear 

77C 

O2O 

TUR.  .  . 

.720 

.OOI 

Stairs  

•//!> 
.64.0 

.IIC 

Oven  

.7-7C 

.Ol6 

Crown  

.812 

•OC7 

Hen  

•/  J3 
.6OO 

.110 

Snail  

.760 

.00  c 

Basket 

.Sio 

.III 

Eve 

62O 

.I-zc 

Table 

.713 

.OO6 

Bae 

6c<? 

IO2 

Star 

665 

OC.4. 

Horse 

7  7O 

OI  C 

Nose  

.658 

JT- 
.OOI 

Trunk  

.620 

.I'jr 

Spade  

.748 

.O2Q 

File  

.co8 

.IC7 

Shoe       

.7^0 

.O3I 

Picture 

.628 

.127 

Balloon 

•I,* 

.611; 

.IO4. 

Scissors 

822 

'  ~.' 
.067 

Egg 

.CC.4. 

~:T 
.i6t; 

Rooster 

672 

08  1 

Cha  iV  ' 

•78? 

nfi? 

•7°^ 

.003 

Total 

1A  "JAR 

2  08  1 

Total 

I±  ?86 

*4o4° 

14.300 

A/r 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.719 

.728 

.063 

Median  = 

•755 

.722 

times  from  the  mean.  Similarly,  in  the  fourth,  fifth,  and 
sixth  columns  are  the  words,  times,  and  deviations  for  the 
instruction  'react  to  visual  image.' 

Examining  these  tables  we  discover,  first,  a  group  of  3 
subjects,  Group  I,  Tables  II.,  III.,  and  IV.,  who  appear  to 
belong  after  all  to  the  type  represented  by  Dr.  Moore's  8  sub- 
jects. For  all  3  both  the  mean  and  the  median  times  for 
reaction  to  meaning  are  shorter  than  for  reaction  to  visual 
image.  Next,  we  note  3  subjects,  Group  2,  Tables  V.,  VI., 
and  VII.,  whose  figures  begin  to  point  in  the  opposite  direction, 
in  that,  whereas  their  median  times  are  shorter  for  meaning, 
their  mean  times  are  shorter  for  visual  image.  Finally,  we 
note  8  subjects,  Group  3,  Tables  VIII.  to  XV.  inclusive,  who 
substantiate  our  original  hypothesis,  in  that  for  them  both 
median  and  mean  times  are  shorter  for  visual  image  than  for 
meaning. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY       123 


In  order  to  be  sure  of  these  results,  however,  we  must 
compare  the  introspections.  In  parenthesis,  be  it  noted  that 
our  subjects  were  untrained,1  and  hence  the  value  of  their 
introspection  is  subject  to  qualification.  The  attempt  was 
made,  however,  to  make  their  introspective  task  as  definite 

TABLE  VI 

Miss  MAC. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Square 

.600 

.on 

Fork  

,«8o 

.Oil 

Ring 

;8o 

O22 

Turkey    ... 

CCQ 

.043 

Rose 

C'?  C 

076 

Banjo 

.781 

.188 

Candle  

.CIO 

.O8l 

Lion  

.640 

.047 

Fly.  . 

•4-7Q 

.IT2 

Steamer  

.^98 

.ooc 

Circle.  .  , 

7'  * 
.621 

.OI2 

Book  

.489  • 

.104. 

Nest 

.070 

.-JCQ 

Sofa  

.861 

.268 

Boot 

.COI 

.no 

Tree 

.CA.2 

.OCX 

Heart 

•i^A 
£-4.6 

06  c 

Stairs 

C42 

.OCI 

Stocking 

-JQO 

221 

Oven 

6^  <? 

O4O 

Jug  

.C22 

.089 

Crown  

.710 

.117 

Knife  

.C^O 

.O8l 

Cat  

.462 

.I'll 

Tower.  .  . 

•4-4-1 

.168 

Spoon  

.trie. 

.078 

Cradle 

.778 

.167 

Cherry   . 

.4.4.7 

.ICO 

Scissors 

,CJC 

' 
.O3O 

Rooster 

.CQO 

.OO'? 

Brush 

760 

I4.Q 

Hat 

4-4-2 

.1^1 

Mouse  

.71-5 

.122 

Drum  

.600 

.007 

Snake  

.7'?  2 

.121 

Hammer  

.478 

.nt: 

Sled  

.740 

.I2Q 

Pear  

.660 

•"O 

.067 

Mask  

.qiS 

.OQ"? 

Peacock  . 

rqg 

.ooc 

Flag  

.qSo 

.031 

Ladder 

ovu 
,6cc 

•WJ 

.062 

Skull    .  .  . 

•4-01 

.I2O 

Letter 

.c6i 

.O32 

Rabbit 

.717 

.IO2 

Flask 

648 

.occ 

Anchor 

.781; 

.174. 

Tiger 

POO 

OQ? 

Apple 

i,  •> 

.6-jc 

0^4. 

Hand 

608 

QIC 

$rrK  
Hen  

.656 

.04  c 

Basket. 

.633 

.040 

Snail  

£ 

.60  c 

•WT3 
.OO6 

Table 

.696 

.lO'? 

Eve 

«"P 

c6o 

•"-•ye  

•5«J 

.U^)l 

Total 

Total 

Z.UJ4 

i/.iiy 

••7V7 

_  . 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.611 
.585 

.100 

Median  = 

•593 
/S98 

.075 

and  easy  as  possible.  The  method  we  chose  was  to  ask  them 
such  specific  questions  as:  "Did  you  get  a  visual  image?" 
(in  case  of  reaction  to  meaning).  "Did  you  get  a  meaning?" 
(in  case  of  reaction  to  visual  image);  and  "Which  came 
first?"  Occasionally,  in  the  case  of  a  subject  who  seemed  to 

xThe  great  majority  of  them  were  but  just  finishing  their  first  course  in  psy- 
chology.   See  above,  page  116. 


I24 


EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 


show  native  aptitude  for  introspection,  he  was  asked  to 
describe,  if  he  could,  his  consciousness  of  meaning;  i.  e., 
whether  it  seemed  to  him  reducible  to  images  or  something 
unique  and  not  further  analyzable.  Descriptions  of  the 
visual  images  obtained  were  also  asked  for  from  time  to  time. 
Any  other  specific  questions  put  to  the  subjects  will  be  noted 
along  with  the  answers  obtained. 

TABLE  VII 

Miss  REI. 


Meaning 

T. 

v. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Fork 

.808 
.908 
.790 
.632 
.663 
.680 
.685 
I.OI2 
.748 
.678 
I.OO2 
•90S 

& 

.690 

.630 

•745 
.900 
.698 
.682 
•590 

.061 
.161 
•043 
•"5 

.084 
.067 
.062 
.265 

.001 

.069 

.255 

.158 

.167 

.087 

.057 
.117 

.002 

•153 
.049 
.06S 
.157 

Turkey 

.910 

I.I32 
.704 
.716 
.620 
.762 
.620 
.603 
•538 
.695 
.872 

•755 
•772 
•5" 
.728 
.920 
.722 
.601 
.700 

•232 

•454 
.026 
.038 
.058 
.084 
.058 

•075 
.140 
.017 
.194 
.077 
.094 
.167 
.050 
.242 
.044 
.077 

.022 

Square 

Banjo 

Rine 

Rose 

Lion         

Fly  

Candle      

Circle  

Steamer             .    ... 

Nest  

Book 

Boot      .  .  . 

Sofa 

Tree 

Heart 

Stairs 

Stocking 

Oven 

Tug.  .  . 

Crown  

Cat  

Knife  

Cherry     

Spoon  

Rooster   .        

Sled  

Hat 

Pear  

Brush 

Mask      .  . 

MXDUSC 

Peacock 

Drum 

Flag 

Letter  

Ladder  

Flact 

Rabbit  

Total  

12.881 

2.149 

Total 

15.686 

2.195 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.678 
.716 

•"3 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•747 
.690 

.105 

Turning  to  the  three  subjects,  Group  I,  whose  results 
agreed  with  those  obtained  by  Dr.  Moore,  we  find  substantial 
agreement  between  their  introspection  and  that  of  his  sub- 
jects. When  instructed  to  react  to  meaning,  our  three  sub- 
jects reported,  almost  without  exception,  that  a  consciousness 
of  meaning  appeared  first,  and  that  a  visual  image  did  not 
come  until  after  this  meaning.  An  interesting  thing  is, 
however,  that  with  these  three  subjects  the  visual  image 
almost  always  did  come  finally.  Miss  B.  reported  only 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        125 


3  cases,  Miss  L.  one  case  and  Mr.  Milln.  no  cases  in  which  a 
visual  image  did  not  follow  the  meaning.  This  shows  what 
ready  visualizers  the  three  subjects  were,  and  how  near  they 
were  to  crossing  the  border  beyond  which  visual  image  comes 
before,  or  at  least  simultaneously  with,  meaning.  When 
instructed  to  react  to  visual  image,  their  introspections  were 

GROUP  3 
TABLE  VIII 

Miss  A. 


Meaning 

T. 

v. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Spoon 

ceo 

.020 

Tower  

•  32C 

.087 

Cradle 

SlS 

O-J2 

Cherry  

•  37O 

.042 

Hat 

rOC 

02? 

Brush 

.4.22 

.010 

Mouse 

•5QO 

1  80 

Snake 

.681 

.269 

Drum 

OV^ 

erg 

OI2 

Pear 

.QOO 

.488 

Hammer.  . 

I.OOO 

•43O 

Mask  

.392 

.020 

Sled    .  . 

.4.84. 

.086 

Peacock  

.4.CC 

.043 

Flag 

.C7Q 

.OOQ 

Skull  

•  t»O4 

.092 

Flask 

.COC 

.wv/y 

.06  c. 

Letter  

.-24.1: 

2 
.067 

Rabbit 

c6o 

OIO 

Chain 

.C4.e 

.Ml 

Tiger 

C72 

OO2 

Apple 

.4.08 

,OO4 

Hen 

•51* 

cg2 

OI2 

Eve 

.<?66 

7: 

.O4O 

Hand  

.=;8q 

.029 

Table  

.-?oc 

.107 

Snail  

'yy 

.602 

.122 

Crab  

.770 

.O<?  -? 

Basket 

•4-QI 

.O7Q 

Nose  

.212 

.2OO 

Bae 

.8cx 

.23C. 

Spade  .  .  . 

.-37C 

•O37 

Star 

.uw^ 

.670 

.IOO 

Pig 

.2J.C 

->' 
.167 

Horse 

4.17 

.151 

Balloon 

.-2  JC 

.OQ7 

Trunk 

4.0,8 

O72 

File 

278 

.134. 

^hnp 

Ao~ 

noo 

Egg.  . 

.402 
.560 

.OIO 

Total  

7.822 

2.076 

Chair 

•4*7 

^bj 

A  , 

Total    . 

I2.C34. 

I.Q24. 

.412 

.109 

,.  ,   ,. 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•570 

•559 

.087 

•375 

practically  the  same  as  those  just  discussed.  They  reported  a 
consciousness  of  meaning  which  came  first,  and  a  visual 
image  which  came  afterwards. 

Below  we  give  sample  introspections  for  both  kinds  of 
instructions. 


126 


EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 


Instruction:  Meaning. 


INTROSPECTION — GROUP  i 

Instruction:  Visual  image. 


Subject  Miss  B.1 

Cat:  "Thought  of  cat  at  home  and  then       Tower:  "I  thought  of  the  meaning  be- 
saw  it."  fore  I  saw  it." 


Snake:    "Thought    of    crawling    thing, 
visual  image  afterwards." 


Spoon:   "I   got   meaning   before   image. 
I  think  I  always  do  get  meaning  first." 


Subject  Miss  L. 

Banjo:     "An   idea  of  a   banjo.      After       Steamer: 
pressing  key  saw  an  image." 


Saw  the  one  I  have  so  often 
seen  on  the  lake.  Had  a  general  idea 
of  a  steamer  first.  I  think  the  general 
idea  always  comes  first." 


Rose:  "No  image  until  long  afterwards." 
Nest:  "An  idea  of  a  nest.     Then  image 
of  a  nest  in  a  tree." 


Scissors:  "A  general  idea,  then  saw  all 
sorts  of  scissors,  then  selected  one  of 
those,  a  pair  of  embroidery  scissors." 


TABLE  IX 

MR.  Mi. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Square 

.662 

.087 

Fork  

.460 

.040 

Banjo 

.4.80 

•OQC 

Turkey  

.370 

.I3Q 

CQ'J 

.018 

Ring      

.C43 

.O34. 

Candle 

CQ-7 

.018 

Rose 

•  2QQ 

.2IO 

OVJ 
4.18 

137 

Fly 

.4.IO 

.OQQ 

Book 

.C7O 

.00  c 

Circle  

•f 

.650 

.141 

Nest 

.43O 

.I4C 

Sofa  

.3IO 

.199 

Tree 

7J 
.OIO 

•O^C 

Boot  

.41  C 

.094 

Stocking 

.680 

.IOC 

Heart  

/• 
.632 

.I23 

Stairs 

.576 

.001 

Tug 

•wj- 

.670 

•*~j 
.l6l 

Crown 

o/v 

c6c 

.OIO 

Oven 

.CQ2 

.083 

Cat 

£  •> 

64.2 

.067 

Knife 

ov* 

.OIO 

.101 

Hat      

633 

.058 

Scissors  

.562 

.053 

Mouse 

.865 

.290 

Brush  

.430 

.079 

Mask 

•vvy 

.6OO 

.02  c 

Sled  

.468 

.041 

Flae 

.C28 

.047 

Peacock  

.682 

.173 

i:  Ia°  
Letter 

.«8 

.037 

Skull  

.C2I 

.OI2 

Rabbit 

rcc 

.020 

Flask 

•4-7$ 

.034 

Tieer 

O33 
.162 

.213 

Chain 

"rt  J 

.c6c 

•~yt 

.0^6 

Total           

IO.92O 

1.413 

Total  

9.664 

1.881 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•575 
.576 

.074 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.509 
.521 

.099 

1  This  subject  and  Mr.  Milln.  did  report  a  few  cases  in  which  they  seemed  to  get 
the  image  first,  but  the  majority  of  their  introspections  were  like  these  quoted. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY         127 


TABLE  X 

MR.  PE. 


Meaning 

T. 

v. 

Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Basin  

.8qi 

.078 

Fork  

.608 

.130 

Square 

,7ir 

.008 

Banjo  

.700 

.0-58 

Turkey 

.814. 

.001 

Ring  

.562 

.176 

Lion 

OIO 

OQ7 

Candle    

.948 

.210 

Rose 

QIO 

OQ7 

Fly    

•yv* 

.620 

.118 

Steamer 

688 

I2C 

Circle      .  . 

.882 

.144 

Book 

7OO 

ll"i 

Nest          .    . 

.742 

.004. 

Sofa   

.Q7O 

.IC7 

Boot  

.678 

•^1- 

.060 

Tree 

.728 

.08  c 

Heart  

.718 

.020 

«2C 

OI2 

Tus? 

.84.0 

.120 

Stairs 

.8oc 

.008 

Oven  

.704 

.034 

Crown 

671 

.I4.O 

Cat  

.680 

.oc8 

Knife 

•WJ 
OQO 

123 

Spoon  

.769 

.031 

Tower 

QIC 

IO2 

Cherry  

•74-1 

.OO3 

Cradle 

7QO 

O2"? 

Scissors 

.778 

.O4.O 

Rooster 

Q2C 

112 

Drum 

,773 

.03  c 

Hat     .  . 

.088 

.lye 

Snake  

.658 

.080 

Brush 

.84.0 

.027 

Hammer  

.970 

.232 

Mouse   . 

.84.8 

.03  c 

Pear  

.829 

.091 

Sled 

.708 

.IOC 

Peacock  

.688 

.oco 

Mask 

7Q8 

.QIC 

Ladder  

.621 

.117 

Flag  

.836 

.023 

Letter  

.706 

.032 

Skull    

•7^O 

.063 

Rabbit  

.752 

.014 

Flack 

Chain          .... 

.904 
.708 

.091 

.IOC 

Total  

16.967 

1.837 

Total 

2O  3  20 

2.OIO 

^Mean  = 

.738 

.080 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.813 
.814 

.080 

Median  = 

.718 

TABLE  XI 

MR.  BART. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

v. 

Basin                       .  . 

.800 

.172 

Fork  

.603 

.004 

Square 

.660 

.032 

Turkey  

.882 

•  27C 

Banjo 

.672 

.04.4. 

Ring                   

.522 

.08  c 

Lion 

,-JIO 

-u8 

Candle 

.768 

f 
.l6l 

Rose 

.702 

.164. 

Steamer 

' 

.62  c 

.Ol8 

Flv 

•/y* 

ci6 

112 

Book 

.C-2O 

.077 

Circle  

.680 

.OC2 

Sofa  

•573 

.034 

Nest     

.608 

.O2O 

Tree    

•445 

.162 

Boot           

.648 

.O2O 

Ear        

.co8 

.099 

Heart              .  . 

•~t*-' 
.610 

.Ol8 

Tus? 

.613 

.006 

Stocking 

.622 

.006 

Oven                  .    ... 

.602 

.005 

Stairs 

.623 

.ooc 

Crown               

.615 

.008 

Total 

7.S4-I 

.963 

Total 

7.286 

.934 

Mean  = 

Median  = 

.628 
.636 

.080 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.607 
.603 

.078 

128 


EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 


TABLE  XII 

Miss  Ki. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

CIO 

.04.  c 

Finger 

4.  CO 

.077 

.^iu 

4.6  C 

OQO 

Fork 

4C2 

07  c 

Ring   

.1QO 

.165 

Square  

.CIO 

•v/9 

.008 

Lion       

.7CO 

.IQC 

Banjo  

•j'-y 
.612 

.08  c 

Fly            

.4.08 

.14-7 

Rose  

.087 

Circle 

.C7O 

.OI  C 

Candle  

460 

.oc8 

Boot 

.<?4.C 

.2IO 

Steamer   

6oc 

.168 

Tree 

.CQ4. 

.O^Q 

Book 

.C2O 

.007 

Ear 

OV4- 

480 

O7C 

Nest 

.708 

.181 

Tue 

•T-UW 

08  c 

4.3O 

Bear 

.c^o 

OO'? 

Crown  

.6c8 

.IO3 

Heart.  

.CQO 

.063 

Hen   

•«3w 

.6OQ 

.OC4 

Stocking  

'J?~. 
•4QO 

.O^I 

Hand 

.730 

.I7c 

Stairs    

.C73 

.WJi 
.046 

Snail 

.4.72 

.083 

Oven 

•3/3 

.c6/? 

T^;: 
.o^o 

Basket 

•W* 

co6 

.O4.O 

Eve 

AQC 

.032 

Crab  

.V)U«J 

.c6q 

.014. 

Cow  

.698 

.171 

Glove  

.C82 

.027 

Table  

.482 

.045 

Star  

.4-CO 

.IOC 

Leaf  

.482 

.04  c 

Horse  

.4.82 

•O7'? 

Bag  

.2CO 

.277 

Trunk 

.ceo 

.00  c. 

Nose  

.Ci8 

•OQQ 

Total 

11.105 

2  OQO 

Total 

IO.C4.2 

I.CO4 

Mean  = 

Median  = 

•535 
•530 

.105 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•527 
•519 

•075 

Subject  Mr.  Milln.1 


Hammer:  "Thought  of  hammer  as  some- 
thing to  drive  nails,  then  saw  a  ham- 
mer, no  specific  hammer." 

Mask:  "Thought  right  away  of  mask  as 
something  to  prevent  detection,  then 
a  visual  image  of  black  mask  that 
covered  about  half  the  face." 


Mouse:  "Thought  of  mouse  as  disagree- 
able, then  saw  a  little  mouse  on  the 
floor." 

Hat:  "Meaning  that  hat  was  to  cover 
head,  then  saw  a  felt  hat." 


We  may  conclude  that  these  3  subjects,  both  from  their 
objective  results  and  their  introspections,  belong,  generally 
speaking,  to  the  type  represented  by  Mr.  Moore's  8  subjects. 

Let  us  turn  now  to  the  three  subjects,  Group  2,  whose 
results  did  not  point  definitely  in  either  of  the  two  directions. 
In  the  cases  of  two  of  them,  Mr.  L.  and  Miss  Mac.,  this 
inconclusiveness  of  the  objective  results  is  supported  by  their 
introspections.  In  the  case  of  the  third,  Miss  Rei.,  the 
introspection  does  not  bear  out  this  inconclusiveness  of 

1  This  subject  and  Miss  B.  did  report  a  few  cases  in  which  they  seemed  to  get  the 
image  first,  but  the  majority  of  their  introspections  were  like  those  quoted. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        129 


TABLE  XIII 

Miss  KN. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Cradle 

.690 

.067 

Cat  

.732 

.152 

Rooster 

.c88 

.01  c 

Tower  

.690 

.no 

Scissors 

.608 

.07  c 

Spoon          .        .... 

.470 

.no 

Brush 

6K 

.008 

Cherry 

.4QO 

.090 

Blouse 

.ui^ 

76  c 

14.2 

Hat 

.472 

.108 

Snake 

T\  C 

112 

Drum 

.663 

.083 

Sled  

SI 

.00  c 

Hammer  

.748 

.168 

Pear 

.860 

.2^7 

Flag  

-653 

.073 

Mask 

.62C 

.OO2 

Ladder  

.568 

.012 

Peacock 

C78 

.04.  c 

Skull  

.581 

.001 

Flask 

CQO 

•O1  3 

Letter  

.663 

.083 

Chain 

c.22 

.101 

Rabbit        

.   ^j 
.OC.O 

.070 

Tiger 

C-7Q 

OQ3 

Anchor      ... 

.zoo 

.080 

Finger 

78O 

I  C.7 

Apple 

.480 

.100 

06l 

34O 

Kev 

.'ico 

.230 

Easel      . 

.7C.I 

OT-' 
.128 

Fork  

.708 

.128 

Banjo 

.co'? 

.I2O 

Square  

.780 

.200 

Rose 

42O 

.20"? 

Turkey  

.£,£,2 

.028 

Candle 

74O 

.117 

Ring      .  . 

.?2O 

.060 

Steamer 

6QT 

O7O 

Lion 

.q28 

.OC.2 

Book 

CQO 

127 

Fly 

.478 

.IO2 

Nest  

•y~»u 
.640 

.OI/ 

Circle  

.iJ./U 

.670 

.090 

Bear  

.616 

.OO7 

Sofa  

.670 

.090 

Heart    . 

.cSo 

.04.  ^ 

Boot  

.C7I 

.OO9 

Stocking 

.JUW 

.6^2 

.OOO 

Tree  

.482 

.098 

Stairs 

44Q 

.174. 

Ear 

.662 

.082 

Oven 

CQO 

on 

Jug 

.c,82 

.OO2 

Eye  

,c,oo 

.I2/? 

Crown  

.525 

.055 

Table  

.4.80 

•  14"? 

Hen  

.645 

.065 

Crab  

.eye 

.048 

Hand  

.498 

.082 

Glove  

.4.82 

.IAI 

Snail  

.CIO 

.O7O 

Racket 

O  V" 

/ifio 

1  2O 

Tntal 

•4UU 

ly.juo 

^.951 

Tntpl 

n    Q/-.7 

\M 

fai 

lo-SS1 

Median  = 

.023 
.6lS 

•°9S 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

.580 

•570 

.088 

objective  results,  but  suggests  rather  that  the  subject  belongs 
with  the  last  group,  i.  e.,  those  for  whom  visual  image  defin- 
itely comes  before  instead  of  after  meaning.  We  will  reserve 
the  introspection  of  this  third  subject  to  consider  in  that 
connection,  and  will  examine  now  the  introspections  of  Mr.  L. 
and  Miss  Mac.  only. 

Mr.  L.'s  introspection  is  unique  in  that  for  him  the 
question  seemed  to  be  one  not  so  much  of  meaning  vs.  visual 
image  as  of  some  sorts  of  images  vs.  other  sorts  of  images. 
When  instructed  to  react  to  meaning,  he  never  obtained 


130 


EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 


TABLE  XIV 

Miss  V. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Finger         ,  . 

.7CQ 

.120 

K.ev 

Q'l  f 

IO7 

Basin           . 

I  14.2 

.263 

Fork 

7O2 

126 

Square 

760 

110 

Turkey 

&I1 

OI  C 

Ring 

84.6 

Q'l'l 

Banjo 

861 

O'J'J 

Lion  

•7QO 

•VJJ 

.080 

Candle  

I.O4.C 

.217 

Rose  

.913 

.034. 

Circle  

.C.O2 

*L 

.•?2O 

Fly.. 

*~*J 

.q6o 

.081 

Nest. 

.712 

O^" 
.Il6 

Steamer  

.Q1O 

.OCI 

Sofa 

L*'" 

.6C2 

.176 

Heart  

.870 

.000 

Boot 

.732 

006 

Scissors    .  . 

1:4.0 

•77Q 

Tug 

I  O4.C. 

217 

Book 

JT- 
OO2 

•joy 
187 

Hand 

6qo 

i^?8 

Tower 

7C.2 

127 

Bae 

I  O4.C 

217 

Crown  

I.2QO 

.4.11 

Star.  . 

.8C2 

.024. 

Horse  

.Ql8 

.ocq 

Nose 

I.OOO 

.172 

Trunk 

j^ 

Tjfi 

Total 

TT  rRfi 

Total 

13.17O 

^.057 

A/r 

0^0 

Mean  = 

Median  = 

.879 
.870 

•137 

Median  = 

.833 

TABLE  XV 

MR.  WA. 


Meaning 

T. 

V. 

Visual  Image 

T. 

V. 

Key.  . 

I.24.O 

.24.7 

Finger 

84.0 

06  1 

Fork.  .    .      . 

I.2OO 

.207 

Basin 

860 

08  1 

Square 

.780 

213 

Turkey 

c.84. 

TQC 

Ring 

I  OO8 

QIC 

Banjo 

712 

•*y5 

067 

Lion  

I.I48 

.ICC 

Steamer  

.QT.Q 

.ici 

Rose  

.8OO 

.IO"? 

Circle  

.8o<? 

.024. 

Candle  

•0-8  ? 

.OO8 

Book 

.UWJ 

.6c,2 

.127 

Fly.  . 

•V^3 

I.OoC 

.072 

Nest 

.7J.C 

QT.A 

Boot  

1.108 

.lie 

Sofa 

808 

O2Q 

Tree 

.Ql8 

.07  c 

Heart 

800 

02  1 

Bear 

.8qq 

.004. 

Stocking 

71  C 

064. 

Tug 

.uyy 
.6Q2 

.<2QI 

Ear 

80O 

Ill 

Oven  

•975 

.Ol8 

Stairs.  .  .    . 

.788 

.000 

Total  

12.908 

I.  623 

Total 

10  127 

.074. 

Mean  = 

Median  = 

•993 
.985 

.125 

Mean  = 
Median  = 

•779 
.800 

•075 

anything  imageless,  but  merely  images  of  one  kind  or  another; 
sometimes  visual,  but  often  cutaneous  or  kinesthetic.  When 
instructed  to  react  to  visual  images,  he  obtained  visual  image. 
The  following  are  typical  introspections : 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        13* 

INTROSPECTION — GROUP  2 

Subject  Mr.  L. 

Instruction:  Meaning.  Instruction:  Visual  image. 

Steamer:  "Visual  image  of  white  steamer  Heart:   "A  feeling  of  tension  or  strain, 

out  on  lake.     Feeling  of  tension,  i.  f.,  then  visual  image.     No  consciousness 

a    kind    of    mental    muddle    before  of  meaning  before  the  image." 

image." 

Stocking:  " Kinaesthetic  image,  followed  Horse:  "Saw  a  dappled  gray  horse." 

by  visual  image.     They  came  almost 

simultaneously.      Meaning  not  really 

made  clear  until  the  visual  image." 

Spade:   "Combination  of  visual   kinaes-  Turkey:   "A  feeling  of  tension  then   a 

thetic  image.     Visual  came  first."  visual  image." 

Occasionally  for  *  meaning'  he  did  report  the  presence  in 
consciousness  of  the  'idea'  of  the  object  named.  When 
asked,  however,  to  analyze  this  'idea,'  he  invariably  reduced 
it  to  images;  kinsesthetic,  cutaneous,  or  even  visual,  but  in 
that  case  an  image  of  something  other  than  the  immediate 
object  itself.  The  following  are  typical: 

Instruction:  Meaning. 

Nose:  "Idea  of  sniffing  (seemed  kinsesthetic  and  cutaneous)." 

Star:  "Idea  of  star  as  a  source  of  light.     (This  idea  a  visual  image  of  light.)"     "Visual 
image  of  a  star  after  reacting." 

We  conclude  that  as  far  as  his  introspection  goes  meaning 
for  this  subject  was  always  image,  of  one  sort  or  another. 
If  this  be  true,  it  suggests  that  the  reason  his  objective  time 
for  meaning  averaged  about  the  same  as  that  for  visual  image 
might  be  due  to  the  fact  that  the  various  kinds  of  images 
which  he  got  for  'meaning'  took  on  an  average  about  the 
same  time  to  develop  as  the  purely  visual  images  which  he 
got  when  reacting  to  'visual  image.'  In  addition,  however, 
to  suggesting  an  explanation  of  his  objective  reaction  times, 
this  introspective  testimony  to  the  effect  that  meaning  was 
always  image  of  one  kind  or  another,  would  carry,  of  course, 
a  direct  answer  to  our  original  problem.  It  would  settle  it 
against  the  adherents  of  imageless  thought.  We  cannot, 
however,  be  certain  of  this  decision  until  we  are  sure  of  the 
absolute  reliability  of  this  subject's1  introspection.  And  for 

1  This  particular  subject  happened  to  be  one  of  the  better-trained  (as  well  as  one 
of  the  most  intelligent)  students,  since  at  the  date  when  the  test  was  performed  he 
had  just  completed  a  year's  course  in  laboratory  psychology,  in  addition  to  having 
had  two  previous  courses  in  psychology. 


132  EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 

that  we  lack  proof.  We  will  not,  therefore,  attempt  to  make 
any  final  statement,  but  simply  draw  attention  to  this  sub- 
ject's introspection  and  to  the  way  in  which  it  points. 

Turning  now  to  the  introspection  of  Miss  Mac.,  the 
second  subject  for  whom  the  objective  time  appeared  approxi- 
mately the  same  for  both  meaning  and  visual  image,  we  find  a 
somewhat  different  state  of  affairs.  This  subject  did  not 
succeed  in  analyzing  her  consciousness  of  meaning.  The 
presumption  was,  therefore,  that  it  was  unanalyzable  because 
imageless.  The  approximate  equality  of  her  times  for  mean- 
ing and  visual  image,  however,  is  explainable  by  the  fact 
that,  introspectively,  this  awareness  of  meaning  appeared 
sometimes  before  the  visual  image  and  sometimes  afterwards. 
Out  of  1 6  times  in  which  she  was  asked  to  introspect  upon 
reaction  to  meaning,  she  reported  6  times  in  which  meaning 
came  before  the  visual  image,  and  10  times  in  which  image 
came  before  meaning.  When  instructed  to  react  to  visual 
image,  she  reported  8  times  in  which  meaning  came  before 
the  visual  image  and  8  times  in  which  the  visual  image  came 
before  the  meaning.  Below  are  typical  introspections: 

INTROSPECTION — GROUP  2 

Miss  Mac. 

Instruction:  Meaning.  Instruction:  Visual  image. 

Snake:  "Image  first,  then  knew  what  it       Drum:  "Knew  what  it  was,  then  saw 

was,   knowing  a   sort  of  memory  of  drum  being  carried  in  a  parade." 

snakes  that  I  have  seen." 
Cradle:  "Knew  what  it  was  when  I  saw       Peacock:  "Saw  it,  then  meaning." 

it." 
Hen:  "Visual  image  first;  then  recog-       Ladder:  "Knew    what    it    was,     then 

nized  the  image.     I  remembered  that  image." 

I  had  seen  things  before  that  looked 

like  that." 

This  subject's  introspection,  as  far  as  it  goes,  substantiates 
her  objective  results  and  we  see  why,  in  her  case,  reaction  to 
meaning  and  reaction  to  visual  image  required  about  equal 
average  times. 

Combining  her  results  with  those  of  Mr.  L.,  we  note  that 
these  two  subjects  taken  together  constitute  a  transition 
group  in  that  for  them  both  reaction  to  meaning  seems  some- 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        133 

times  though  not  always  to  depend  upon  visual  image. 
In  Mr.  L.'s  case  meaning  sometimes  actually  was  visual 
image;  in  Miss  Mac.'s  case  it  sometimes  followed  the  visual 
image  and  was  dependent  upon  the  latter. 

We  may  turn  now  to  the  introspection  of  the  third  and 
last  group  of  subjects,  the  group  for  whom  reactions  to 
meaning,  as  we  shall  see,  did  always  depend  upon  a  visual 
image.  Miss  Rei.,  it  will  be  remembered,  belonged  intro- 
spectively  to  this  group.  In  considering  the  introspection  of 
these  9  subjects  (including  Miss  Rei.)  we  find  it  possible  to 
divide  them,  roughly  speaking,  into  two  subgroups:  first,  a 
subgroup,  A)  composed  of  subjects  who,  as  a  rule,  tend  to 
make  a  distinction  between  meaning  and  visual  image;  and 
second,  a  subgroup,  B,  made  up  of  subjects  who,  as  a  rule, 
do  not  tend  to  make  such  distinction,  but  for  whom  meaning 
is  visual  image. 

Subgroup  A  comprises  Miss  A.,  Mr.  Mi.,  Mr.  Pe.,  and 
Miss  Rei. 

Subgroup  B  comprises  Mr.  Bart.,  Miss  Ki.,  Miss  Kn., 
Miss  V.,  and  Mr.  Wa. 

The  following  are  typical  introspections  for  subgroup  A. 

GROUP  3 — SUBGROUP  A 
Instruction:  Meaning.  Instruction:  Visual  image. 

Subject  Miss  A. 

Rabbit:  "Saw  a  rabbit  hopping.     Real-  Letter:  "I  saw  a  letter  lying  open.    No 

ized  it  was  a  small  animal,  then  re-  particular  letter." 

acted." 

Drum:  "First  saw  a  picture  of  a  man  File:   "Saw  both  a  letter  file,  and  a  file, 

beating  drum  in  orchestra,  and  then  the  tool." 

thought,  'it  is  a  musical  instrument.'  " 

Subject  Mr.  Mi.1 

Tree:    "Saw    a    bunch    of   trees,    then       Scissors:  "Image     first;     didn't     think 
thought  what  a  tree  really  is."  what  it  meant  till  after  I  pressed  the 

key." 

Stairs:  " Saw  stairs,  then  got  a  meaning,       Skull:   "Image  and  that  was  all." 
i.  e.,  stairs  something  that  you  go  up 
on." 

1  This  subject  reported  some  instances  in  which  he  thought  he  obtained  a  mean- 
ing without  a  preceding  image.  His  introspection  tends,  therefore,  to  class  him  to 
some  extent  in  group  2  with  Miss  Mac  rather  than  here  in  group  3. 


134  EDWARD  CHACE   TOLMAN 

Subject  Mr.  Pe. 

Cradle:  "  Saw  a  cradle  first,  and  then  the  Scissors:  "  Saw  scissors  lying  on  a  sewing- 
idea  to  rock  came  on."  table,  that  belonged  to  my  mother." 

Rooster:  "Saw  a  big  black  rooster  we  Snake:  "Visual  image  of  a  little  green 
used  to  own,  and  then  thought  of  him  garter  snake  running  through  the 

as  something  to  eat."  grass." 

Subject  Miss  Rei. 

Cherry:   " Saw  a  red  cherry,  then  thought  Mask:  "Saw    a    black    mask,    nothing 

of  it  as  something  to  eat."  besides  the  image." 

Drum:  "Saw  a  drum  and  then  thought  Ladder:   "Saw  a  tall  painters'  ladder,  no 

of  it  as  being  a  musical  instrument."  consciousness  of  meaning." 

(In  answer  to  question)  "I  think  the  Peacock:   "Saw  a   peacock  going  up   a 

image  is  an  aid  to  meaning."  hill.     It  was  at  Lincoln  Park." 

Examining  these  introspections,  we  note  that  in  the  case 
of  Subgroup  A  visual  image  was  always  a  precursor  of  mean- 
ing, and  that  the  meaning  itself  seemed  to  depend  upon  the 
image.  Turning  now  to  Subgroup  .5,  the  following  are  typi- 
cal introspections: 

GROUP  3— SUBGROUP  B 
Instruction:  Meaning.  Instruction:  Visual  image, 

Subject  Mr.  Bart. 

Lion:  "A  mixed  image  of  the  zoo,  i.  <?.,  Finger:   "Image   of  a   finger  with   ring 

the  line  of  cages  in  Lincoln  Park.     No  upon  it  (no  particular  finger)." 
other  process  in  consciousness  detect- 
able." 

Fly:  "Visual  image  of  fly  paper  with  flies  Ring:  "Image  of  a  key  ring  (no  par- 
stuck  on  it."  ticular  key  ring)." 

Subject  Miss  Ki. 

Fly:  "First  saw  a  black  fly,  then  some-  Nest:  "Image  of  a  nest  which  I  saw  this 
thing  flying."  morning  and  then  of  other  nests  of  all 

different  kinds." 

Basket:   "Saw  image  of  basket  at  same       Bear:   "Image  of  a  bear  in  a  cage." 
time  that  I   got  meaning.    Meaning 
to  me  is  image." 

Crab:  "I  saw  a  single  crab  and  the  beach  Book:  "Image  of  a  red  book  seen  at  an 
behind  him  filled  in."  angle." 

Subject  Miss  Kn. 

Nest:  "I  said  the  word  to  myself.  I  Hen:  "Image  of  a  black  and  white  hen." 
realized  it  wasn't  a  nonsense  syllable; 

then  I  obtained  a  visual  image  of  a       Snail:   "A   greenish   brown   snail   shell, 
nest  on  a  tree  (not  any  particular  nest);  Nothing  previous  to  this  image, 

then  I  reacted." 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        135 

Oven:  "Got  an  image  first  thing.     As  if       Basket:   "A  market  basket;  nothing  be- 

looking  into  an  open  oven."  fore  the  image." 

Stocking:   "An   image   of   a    new   black 

stocking  the  first  thing  in  conscious- 
ness.      Nothing    between   image   and 

reacting." 

Subject  Miss  V. 
Eye:   "Made  up  my  mind    beforehand       Candle:   "First  I  saw  a  candle,  no  par- 

that  this  time  I  would  get  a  meaning  ticular  candle.      Then  I  saw  a   par- 

before  image,  but  got  an  image  of  an  ticular   candle,    viz.,    the   one    I    saw 

'eye'  almost  before  I  saw  the  word."  last." 

Snail:   (N.  B.  reaction  to  this  word  took       Nest:   "Image  of  the  nest  which  I  saw 

over  two  seconds  and  was  discarded  last  Sunday." 

but  the   introspection   is   significant.) 

"Could  not  get  an  image  for  a  long       Bag:   "Image  of  travelling  bag,  also  of 

time.      Had  no  meaning  until  I  got  paper  bag." 

the  image.     Felt  just  as  if  I  were  look- 
ing at  a  nonsense  syllable." 

Subject  Mr.  Wa. 
Ring:  "  Visual  image  of  ring  on  my  finger.       Heart:  "  Visual  image  of  a  human  heart." 

Nothing     previous     to     this     image. 

Afterwards  an  image  of  a  circle  on  the 

ground." 

(In  answer  to  specific  question)  "I  feel  that  I  go  through  the  same  process  each 
time  no  matter  whether  meaning  or  visual  image  is  asked  for." 

In  the  case  of  Subgroup  B  the  testimony  seems  to  be 
unanimous  that  the  visual  image  was  the  meaning.  No  other 
process  which  might  play  the  part  of  meaning  was  ever 
detected  either  before  or  after  the  image. 

The  common  point  in  the  introspection  for  both  sub- 
groups, it  will  be  noted,  is  that  visual  image  was  the  first 
thing  which  came.  The  two  subgroups  disagree,  however, 
as  to  the  extent  to  which  this  visual  image  was  important  for, 
or  a  part  of,  the  meaning.  Subgroup  B  declared  that  it  was 
the  whole  of  the  meaning.  Subgroup  A  reported  merely 
that  it  always  came  before  the  meaning  but  that  meaning 
itself  was  something  more.  This  disagreement,  together 
with  the  fact  that  for  the  vast  majority  of  subjects  visual 
image  is  entirely  unneeded  for  meaning,  sets  us  a  problem. 

Three  solutions  suggest  themselves.  We  may  try  either 
an  out-and-out  imageless  position,  an  out-and-out  image 


136  EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 

position,  or  some  sort  of  a  compromise.  The  out-and-out 
imageless  position  would  have  to  contend  that  no  matter 
what  were  the  objective  reaction  times  to  the  contrary,  nor 
what  the  apparent  introspective  evidence,  the  visual  image 
can  never  have  been  really,  in  any  true  sense,  a  part  of  or 
even  necessary  for  the  meaning.  Such  a  position  would  have 
to  claim  that  the  objectively  shorter  reaction  times  for 
visual  image  in  the  case  of  both  subgroups  did  not  prove  that 
the  visual  image  was  necessary  to  the  meaning,  but  that  it 
was  merely  an  adventitious  circumstance.  It  would  have 
to  claim  also  that  the  introspective  testimony  from  both 
subgroups  as  to  the  subjective  precedence  in  time  of  the 
visual  image  was  no  additional  proof  of  the  prerequisiteness 
of  the  image.  The  out-and-out  imageless  position  would, 
in  short,  have  to  deny  every  one  of  the  evidences  afforded 
by  the  results  of  our  third  group  of  students.  In  support,  it 
would  have  only  the  results  of  the  non-visual1  subjects,  i.  e., 
of  Mr.  Moore's  8  subjects  and  those  of  our  investigation  who 
were  like  his.  But  since  the  method  we  have  used  is  one 
which  traces  the  importance  of  the  visual  image  only,  the 
support  of  the  not  extremely  visual  subjects  carries  little  or 
no  weight.  We  feel  justified  in  concluding,  therefore,  that 
our  results  render  the  out-and-out  imageless  position  unten- 
able. 

We  turn  now  to  the  out-and-out  'image'  position.  Re- 
sults which  directly  support  it  are  the  introspections  of 
Subgroup  5,  that  meaning  is  image,  and  image  is  meaning. 
For  it  to  be  completely  supported,  however,  two  further 
demands  would  have  to  be  satisfied.  The  objective  reaction 
times  for  meaning  and  visual  image  in  the  case  of  Subgroup  B 
would  have  to  be  the  same.  This  demand  was  not  fulfilled; 
the  reaction  times  for  meaning  averaged  longer  than  for 
image,  which  implies  that  meaning  for  Subgroup  B  as  for 
Subgroup  A  involved  something  more  than  mere  image. 
Second,  all  cases  of  'meaning'  reported  ought  to  be  analyzable 
by  better  introspection  into  images.  This  would  demand 
that  the  'meaning'  of  Mr.  Moore's  8  subjects  and  of  the 

1  Using  'non-visual '  in  a  merely  relative  sense. 


TEMPORAL  RELATIONS  OF  MEANING  AND  IMAGERY        13? 

majority  of  our  own  original  subjects,  i.  e.,  the  *  meaning' 
which  came  before  visual  image,  must  really  have  been 
imaginal.  It  must  have  been  made  up,  that  is,  of  verbal, 
organic,  kinsesthetic,  or  other  images,  which  these  subjects 
failed  to  recognize.  It  would  demand,  similarly,  that  Miss 
Mac.'s  *  meaning,'  which  came  sometimes  before  and  some- 
times after  the  visual  image,  must  have  been  made  up  of 
images.  And,  finally,  it  would  demand  that  the  'meaning' 
of  Subgroup  A)  which  came  after  the  visual  image,  and 
which  was  often  similar  to  an  awareness  of  definition  must 
likewise  have  been  made  up  of  images.  None  of  these 
demands  would  be  insurmountable,  if  we  were  strongly 
prejudiced  in  favor  of  an  out-and-out  'image'  position.  It 
would  be  possible  to  assume,  as  has  been  done  before,  that 
better  introspection  would  eventually  show  images  in  proc- 
esses where  as  yet  nothing  but  imageless  awarenesses  have 
been  discovered.  Such  an  assumption,  however,  has  at  the 
present  stage  of  psychology  little  but  theoretical  precon- 
ceptions to  support  it.  So  that  at  present  we  consider  it 
safer  to  conclude  that  our  results,  while  they  do  not  com- 
pletely contradict  an  out-and-out  'image'  doctrine,  do 
nothing  actively  to  support  one. 

Finally,  we  may  turn  to  the  consideration  of  an  inter- 
mediate doctrine  which  would  both  allow  an  essential  im- 
portance to  the  image,  and  yet  admit  an  imageless  component 
as  also  necessary.  Such  a  doctrine  is  directly  suggested  by 
the  results  of  Subgroup  A.  They,  it  will  be  remembered, 
obtained  first  of  all  the  visual  image  and  then  a  'meaning.' 
It  appeared  that  for  them  the  visual  image  was  a  prerequisite 
of  the  'meaning,'  but  that  the  'meaning'  itself  was  something 
different  from  image.  It  does  not  seem  improbable  that  a 
similar  situation  may  have  existed  also  in  the  cases  of  the 
other  groups.  With  the  subjects  of  the  Group  I  who  obtained 
'meaning'  first,  this  'meaning'  may  have  come  after  kinaes- 
thetic  or  organic  images  which  were  not  identified.  And  in 
the  cases  of  Subgroup  B  the  doctrine  would  explain  the 
longer  reaction  times  obtained  for  meaning  than  for  image. 
We  would  simply  have  to  assume  that  the  'meaning'  which 


138  EDWARD  CHACE  TOLMAN 

followed  the  visual  image  was  not  recognized  by  this  sub- 
group, as  it  was  by  Subgroup  A,  as  something  distinct  from 
the  image,  but  was  confused  with  the  visual  image  itself. 
Such  an  assumption  does  not  seem  at  all  a  difficult  one. 
Further  experiments  with  subjects  of  the  type  of  Subgroup  B, 
i.  e.j  those  who  introspectively  declare  meaning  to  be  identi- 
cal with  visual  image  but  who  objectively  require  a  longer 
reaction  time  for  meaning  than  for  image,  ought  to  throw 
light  upon  the  matter.  We  hope  to  be  able  in  the  near 
future  to  report  the  results  of  such  experiments. 

We  may  sum  up.  The  results  of  the  y1  subjects  for  whom 
both  objectively  and  subjectively  visual  images  came  first, 
render  an  out-and-out  imageless  position  untenable.  But 
the  fact,  on  the  other  hand,  that  for  2  of  these  7  (Miss  A. 
and  Mr.  Pe.,  Subgroup  A)  meaning  was  distinct  from  the 
visual  image,  as  well  as  that  for  the  great  majority  of  all 
subjects  'meaning'  appears  as  something  not  analyzed  into 
images,  gives  no  direct  support  to  an  out-and-out  *  image' 
position.  A  compromise  position,  therefore,  which  assumes 
that  'meaning'  depends  upon  image  but  is  itself  distinct 
from  the  latter,  is  the  one  most  nearly  suggested  by  our 
results. 

In  conclusion,  let  us  emphasize  that  the  value  of  the 
present  investigation  has  lain  not  so  much  in  the  direction 
of  a  positive  proof  of  one  or  the  other  theory,  as  in  showing 
that,  if  a  large  enough  sample  of  subjects  be  taken.  Dr.  Moore's 
method  in  no  way  lends  support  to  the  out-and-out  image- 
less  position. 

1  This  excludes  Miss  Rei.  and  Mr.  Mi.  The  former's  objective  times  and  the 
latter's  introspection  left  it  doubtful  whether  they  really  belonged  in  this  third  group 
or  in  Group  2.  See  pp.  128-9,  and  footnote,  p.  133. 


EXPERIMENTS  ON  THE   RELATIVE   EFFICIENCY 

OF  MEN  AND  WOMEN   IN  MEMORY 

AND   REASONING1 

BY  ARTHUR  I.  GATES 

The  majority  of  psychologists  and  educators  who  have 
expressed  themselves  on  the  subject  are  of  the  opinion  that 
women,  as  a  rule,  are  considerably  more  efficient  than  men 
in  memory  work  and  less  efficient  in  applying  the  facts  learned, 
in  self-expression,  and  in  reasoning  power.  For  example 
one  writer  says:2  "Girls  excel  in  learning  and  memorization 
accepting  studies  on  suggestion  or  authority,  but  are  often 
quite  at  sea  when  set  to  make  tasks  or  experiments  that  give 
individuality  and  a  chance  for  self-expression,  which  is  one 
of  the  best  things  in  boyhood." 

Opinions  similar  to  these  seem  to  prevail  generally  among 
psychologists,  educators,  and  laymen.  Many,  moreover,  are 
of  the  opinion  that  women,  in  addition  to  having  quicker  and 
more  tenacious  memories,  are  as  a  rule  more  diligent  and 
painstaking  in  their  work;  the  boy  may  often  be  satisfied  with 
a  fair  knowledge  of  the  general  principles  underlying  a  lesson, 
while  the  girl  seeks  a  more  detailed  and  exact  knowledge. 
If  such  is  the  fact  it  should  be  taken  into  account  in  any 
attempt  to  determine  the  sex-differences  in  memory,  for  obvi- 
ously the  differences  in  the  time  spent  on  the  work  might 
easily  account  for  the  differences  in  the  reproduction  of  the 
ideas. 

The  experiments  to  be  described  presently  were  performed 
first  in  1913  and  were  repeated  in  1914  and  1915,  using  as 
subjects  a  class  in  elementary  psychology  consisting  of  from 
158  to  275  students  of  both  sexes  of  the  sophomore,  junior, 
and  senior  years  in  the  University  of  California. 

1  From  the  Psychological  Laboratory  of  the  University  of  California. 

2  Hall,  G.  S.,  "Youth:  its  Education,  Regimen,  and  Hygiene."    New  York,  1912, 
p.  287. 


ARTHUR  I.  GATES 


The  data  were  obtained  from  the  answers  to  three  sets  of 
questions.  Each  set  of  two  questions  comprised  the  regular 
weekly  examination  of  the  class.  The  first  set  called  for  a 
somewhat  detailed  reproduction  of  facts  presented  in  the 
lectures  of  the  week  preceding.  The  second  set  called  for  the 
application  of  facts  or  principles  given  in  the  lectures,  the 
purpose  being  to  call  into  action  a  mental  process  as  closely 
as  possible  identical  with  that  involved  in  reasoning.  All  the 
questions  were  framed  by  Professor  Stratton,  who  was  in 
charge  of  the  classes,  and  who  endeavored  to  make  the 
tests  as  nearly  as  possible  adequate  to  the  purpose  of  the 
experiment.  The  papers  in  all  cases  were  graded  on  a  basis 
of  ten,  but  the  averages  below,  for  the  sake  of  clearness,  are 
made  on  the  basis  of  one  hundred.  All  papers  were  corrected 
by  the  regular  *  readers,'  who  were  in  no  case  aware  that  the 
results  were  to  be  used  for  experimental  purposes.  It  hap- 
pened, moreover,  that  each  of  the  nine  sets  of  papers  was 
graded  by  a  different  'reader.' 

The  following  table  shows  the  results  in  the  case  of  memory 
questions. 

TABLE  I 

MEMORY 


*9'3 

1914 

I9i3 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

Women                                 .  • 

QC 

77 

l62 

89.2 

1C  A 

86.4 

Men 

CO 

73 

IO2 

85.0 

Q8 

81.0 

Diff.  in  favor  of  women  

4.0% 

4-2% 

5-4% 

The  women  show  a  slight  superiority  in  memory  work, 
amounting  on  the  average  to  4.5  percent.  While  the  per- 
centile  difference  is  rather  small,  its  reliability  is  indicated 
by  the  fact  that  it  appears  in  all  cases,  although  different 
questions  were  given  at  different  times  to  three  entirely 
different  groups  of  individuals. 

Table  II,  shows  the  average  grades  obtained  by  men  and 
women  to  questions  that  involved  reasoning. 

The  evidence  indicates  a  slight  superiority  of  the  men 
in  this  sort  of  work.  The  average  difference  is  approximately 


EFFICIENCY  IN  MEMORY  AND  REASONING 


141 


TABLE  II 

REASON 


19*3 

1914 

1915 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Grade 

Women  

QO 

77.  c 

153 

83.3 

154 

88.4 

^/fen     

58 

79-5 

IO-? 

86.4 

99 

89.2 

Diff.  in  favor  of  men  

2.0% 

3-1% 

0.8% 

2  percent,  a  difference  which  is  so  small  as  to  have  but  little 
significance  were  it  not  for  the  fact  that  it  is  repeated  by  the 
three  separate  groups. 

Table  III.  shows  the  results  of  tests  in  which  the  subjects 
were  given  free  choice  between  a  memory  and  a  reason  ques- 
tion. The  two  questions,  constituting  the  regular  weekly 
examination  as  before,  were  presented  and  the  students  were 
permitted  to  take  their  choice. 

TABLE  III 

ONE  MEMORY  AND  ONE  REASON  QUESTION 
1913 


Memory  Question 

Grade 

Reason  Question 

Grade 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Percent  of 
Individuals  of 
That  Sex 

No.  of 
Individuals 

Percent  of 
Individuals  of 
That  Sex 

Women  
Men  
Diff  

60 
19 

72.3 
28.8 

43-5 

85 
82 

3 

23 
47 

27.7 
71.2 

43-5 

86 

87 
i 

1914 


Women    .  . 

I2Q 

84.8 

7O.4. 

23 

1C  2 

77 

Men 

80 

78.4. 

64..  c 

22 

21  6 

80 

Diff  

70.4. 
6.4 

5-9 

6.4 

3 

1915 

Women  
Men  

144 

85 

91.8 
74.2 

88.4 
87.0 

\l 

8.2 

15.8 

87.2 
89.8 

Diff  

17.6 

1.4 

ij.^ 

7.6 

2.6 

Although  both  sexes  show  a  distinct  preference  for  the 
memory  question,  the  preference  is  much  greater  in  the  case 
of  women.  The  men  show  more  willingness  than  do  the 
women  to  take  the  reason  questions,  although  the  actual 
number  of  either  sex  that  take  these  questions  is  small.  In 


142  ARTHUR  I.  GATES 

1913  and  1915  twice  as  great  a  ratio  of  men,  and  in  1914  a 
ratio  one  third  greater  of  men  than  of  women  chose  the 
reason  question.  The  grades  received  in  the  memory  tests 
confirm  the  earlier  finding  that  the  women  excel  in  this  kind 
of  work.  The  women  excel  in  every  case,  although  in  two 
(1913  and  1915)  the  differences  in  their  favor  are  very  small. 
The  grades  received  on  the  reason  questions  also  confirm 
the  earlier  finding  that  the  men  excel  slightly  in  this  type  of 
work.  Although  the  superiority  of  the  men  is  small  it 
appears  in  every  case. 

Our  general  conclusions  from  the  experiment  thus  far  are 
as  follows: 

1.  The  women  excel  the  men  in  memory  work. 

2.  The  men  excel  the  women,  but  to  a  less  degree,  in 
reason  work. 

3.  Both  sexes  prefer  memory  work  but  more  men  show  a 
willingness  to  do  reason  work  in  lieu  of  memory  work. 

To  let  the  experiment  remain  as  it  stands  and  to  accept 
without  further  question  the  conclusions  just  enumerated 
would  be  hazardous  and  would  certainly  not  take  into 
account  all  of  the  factors  which  have  an  influence  here. 
There  is  at  least  one  possibility  which  if  proven  to  be  a  reality 
would  force  us  to  modify  the  conclusions  at  which  we  have 
just  arrived.  It  is  possible  that  the  apparent  superiority  of 
the  women  in  reproduction  from  memory  is  due  merely  to  a 
greater  amount  of  study  and  not  to  an  innate  superiority  of 
memory. 

To  take  into  account  this  possibility  the  following  test 
was  employed.  The  news  item  given  below  was  read  to  the 
class  at  the  beginning  of  the  lecture  hour,  the  students  being 
warned  to  pay  particular  attention  to  the  contents,  without 
being  informed,  however,  of  the  purpose  of  the  test.  The 
item  follows: 

THREE  HOUSES  BuRNED1 

Boston,  September  5.  A  serious  fire  last  night  destroyed  three  houses  in  the 
center  of  the  city.  Seventeen  families  are  without  a  home.  The  loss  exceeds  fifty 
thousand  dollars.  In  rescuing  a  child,  one  of  the  firemen  was  badly  burned  about 
the  hands  and  arms. 

1  See  Whipple,  G.  M.,  'Manual  of  Physical  and  Mental  Tests,'  Baltimore,  1910, 
p.  504. 


EFFICIENCY  IN  MEMORY  AND  REASONING 


'43 


3- 

4- 

5- 
6. 

7- 


The  students  were  first  requested  to  write  down  all  the 
facts  they  could  recall  from  the  article.  Following  the  free 
account,  they  were  asked  to  answer  the  following  questions: 

1.  In  what  city  did  the  fire  occur? 

2.  What  was  the  date  of  the  item?    J*^ 
When  did  the  fire  break  out?   Kv»^ 
How  many  houses  were  destroyed? 

In  what  part  of  the  city  were  these  houses  ? 
How  many  families  were  left  homeless  ? 
What  was  the  total  loss  (in  dollars)  ? 

8.  Who  was  burned? 

9.  On  what  part  or  parts  of  the  body  was  this  individual  "•' 
burned? 

10.  What  was  this  individual  doing  when  the  burns  were 
received  ? 

The  data  used  were  obtained  from  the  answers  to  the  ten 
definite  questions,  for  it  was  found  that  the  additions  or 
alterations  of  these  answers  from  the  free  accounts  were  so 
slight  as  to  be  negligible.  The  papers  were  graded  on  a  basis 
of  ten,  one  unit  being  allowed  for  the  correct  answer  to  each 
question.  Table  IV.  gives  the  average  results. 

TABLE  IV 


Percentage 
Reported 

Percentage 
Correct 

Percentage 
Positive  Errors 

Ratio  of  Pos. 
Errors  to  Amt. 
Reported 

Ratio  of  Pos. 
Errors  to  Pos. 
Errors  Plus 
Amt.  Not 
Reported 

1913 

Women     

97-4- 

84.4 

11.  O 

.111 

.833 

^£en  

QO.O 

8O.O 

IO.O 

.IOO 

•COO 

1914 
W^omen          

98.4. 

86.4. 

12.  0 

.121 

.888 

^len 

04..  2 

81.  i 

II  O 

.116 

.6co 

I9IS 
Women 

Q.1.  1 

82  c 

II  6 

121 

.662 

Men 

880 

«^o 

76  4. 

10  6 

1  2O 

.44-1 

Average  of  above. 
Women  

96.6 

84.4 

12.2 

.I2C 

.782 

ft^en  

90.7 

79.8 

IO.C 

.112 

.qiQ 

Diff  

c.o 

/y.o 

4.6 

1.7 

.OI  1 

.263 

The  women  in  every  case  report  a  greater  amount  of  the 
content  of  the  item,  as  well  as  a  greater  amount  of  it  cor- 
rectly. On  the  average  the  women  report  96.6  percent  of  the 


144  ARTHUR  I.  GATES 

item  and  84.4  percent  of  it  correctly  while  the  men  report 
but  90.7  percent  with  79.8  percent  correct.  The  men,  how- 
ever, make  fewer  mistakes.  The  actual  number  of  errors 
made  by  the  women  is  greater  in  every  case,  although  the 
differences  between  the  sexes  is  small.  The  ratios  of  the 
number  of  errors  to  the  total  amount  reported  show  even 
smaller  differences  because  of  the  fact  that  the  women  in  all 
cases  report  a  larger  amount.  But  the  ratios  of  the  amount 
of  positive  errors  to  the  total  amount  of  positive  errors  plus 
the  amount  not  reported — i.  e.,  to  the  field  in  which  suggestion 
and  kindred  forces  could  operate  because  the  ideas  were  not 
correctly  remembered — were  much  larger  for  the  women. 
That  is  to  say,  the  women,  much  more  than  the  men,  were 
likely  to  make  erroneous  statements  rather  than  mere  omis- 
sions. This  ratio  is,  on  the  average,  about  one  third  larger 
for  the  women. 

The  general  conclusion  from  this  test  is  that  the  women 
in  immediate  memory  tests  can  correctly  reproduce  more  of 
the  detail  of  a  given  group  of  facts  but  at  the  same  time  make 
more  mistakes. 

A  question,  however,  may  be  raised  with  regard  to  the 
application  of  the  results  gained  by  this  method  to  the  deter- 
mination of  the  relative  ability  shown  by  men  and  women 
in  the  tests  first  considered,  because  the  present  method 
tests  immediate  memory,  or  immediate  reproduction,  rather 
than  delayed  memory  which  is  the  function  operative  in  the 
examinations. 

Accordingly,  the  same  students  were  requested,  one  week 
or  five  weeks  after  the  immediate-memory  test,  to  write, 
without  previous  warning,  all  that  they  could  remember  of 
the  news  item  given  above.  The  same  set  of  ten  questions 
as  before  was  used.  Table  V.  gives  the  results. 

In  delayed  as  well  as  in  immediate  memory  the  women 
have  a  greater  range  of  report,  a  greater  number  of  details 
are  reported  correctly,  and  more  positive  errors  are  made. 
The  amount  by  which  the  sexes  differ  is  about  the  same  in 
both  types  of  memory. 

The  experiments  with  the  news  item  justify  the  following 
conclusions: 


EFFICIENCY  IN  MEMORY  AND  REASONING 


'45 


TABLE  V 

DELAYED  MEMORY 
1913.    After  5  Weeks 


Ratio  of  Positive 

Percentage 
Reported 

Percentage 
Correct 

Percentage 
Positive  Errors 

Ratio  of  Posi- 
tive Errors  to 
Amount 

Errors  to  Posi- 
tive Errors  Plus 
Amount  Not 

Reported 

Reported 

W^omen 

82  o 

64.  o 

18.0 

.210 

.COO 

Men  

72.0 

S7-o 

15.0 

.208 

•349 

After  5  Weeks 


Women  
Men  

89.0 
79.0 

68.0 
60.0 

2I.O 
I9.O 

.236 

.240 

.655 

•475 

1915.     After  I  Week 

Women  
Men  

944 
89.8 

80.7 
75-8 

13-7 
12.0 

.145 

.137 

.650 
•495 

Average  of  Above 

Women 

88.5 
80.3 

8.2 

70.9 

6ti 

17.9 

M-| 

2.6 

.200 

.195 
.005 

.602 
.440 
.162 

Men 

Diff  

1.  The  women  excel  the  men  in  tests  of  immediate  or 
delayed  memory,  at  least  in  so  far  as  the  amount  of  material 
correctly  reproduced  is  concerned. 

2.  The  women,  however,  make  more  positive  errors   in 
reporting. 

The  results  obtained  by  other  investigators  are  for  the 
most  part  in  harmony  with  the  present  findings.  A  summary 
of  such  experiments  will  be  found  in  Whipple1  who  concludes : 
"  Sex  differences  in  this  test  [memory  for  ideas],  as  in  the  rote 
memory  test,  are  in  favor  of  girls."2 

A  final  consideration  is  the  possibility  that  the  women 
employed  in  these  experiments  constitute  a  more  select  group 
than  the  men.  It  is  possible  that  these  women  are  on  the 
whole  more  capable,  or  that  their  previous  training  has 
better  adapted  them  to  the  particular  subject  of  psychology. 
There  is  no  obvious  reason  why  this  should  be  the  case,  but 
in  order  to  throw  some  light  upon  it  the  average  grade  in 
the  course  has  been  computed  for  each  sex. 

1  Whipple,  G.  M.,  'Manual  of  Mental  and  Physical  Tests,'  Part  II.,  17-43,  149" 
223. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  213. 


146  ARTHUR  I.  GATES 

TABLE  VI 


i9J3 

1914 

1915 

The  women  received  an  average  grade  of 

77  o 

yr  r 

74.  O 

The  men  received  an  average  grade  of  

75-5 

75-0 

72.0 

The  women  have  slightly  the  higher  grade.  The  mass  of 
experimental  evidence  from  other  investigations,  however, 
indicates  that  in  groups  of  men  and  women  of  equal  endow- 
ment and  training,  the  women  usually  excel  in  memory  work. 
We  have  found  that  in  the  three  groups  just  considered,  the 
women  excel  in  memory.  It  seems  that  the  small  amount 
by  which  the  women  excel  the  men  in  the  grades  received  in 
the  course  may  be  accounted  for  by  the  great  predominance 
of  memory  work  in  the  weekly  and  final  examinations  on 
which  the  grades  are  based.  The  women  who  apparently 
excel  in  memory  work  should  in  a  long  series  of  tests  of  that 
nature,  come  out  with  a  somewhat  better  average. 

The  three  main  conclusions  that  the  investigation  seems 
to  justify  are  as  follows: 

1.  The  women  excel  the  men  noticeably  in  either  immedi- 
ate or  delayed  memory  work. 

2.  The  men  excel  the  women,   but  to  a  less  degree,  in 
reason  work. 

3.  Both  sexes  prefer  memory  work,  but  a  greater  relative 
number  of  men  show  a  willingness  to  do  reason  work  in  lieu 
of  memory  work. 

Results  obtained  by  other  investigators  and  the  supple- 
mentary tests  for  possible  sources  of  error  have  brought 
forth  no  evidence  contradictory  to  the  conclusions  we  have 
reached. 


INDIVIDUAL   DIFFERENCES    IN   JUDGMENTS   OF 
THE   BEAUTY  OF   SIMPLE   FORMS 


BY  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

Teachers  College,  Columbia  University 

Students  of  esthetic  appreciation  have  commonly  been 
especially  interested  in  the  general  drift  or  average  tendency 
toward  this  or  that  preference  and  have  perhaps  given  an 
impression  of  greater  uniformity  than  exists.  The  diversity 
of  the  judgments  whose  average  favors  the  golden  section, 
for  example,  is  really  very  great.  It  seems  worth  while 
therefore  to  report  certain  rather  extensive  measurements  of 
esthetic  preference  which  I  have  made. 


The  subjects  of  the  experiment  were  college  juniors  and, 
with  few  exceptions,  of  the  female  sex.  The  judgments 
made  were  of  the  order  of  esthetic  merit  (the  question  being, 
"Which  rectangle  do  you  like  the  looks  of  most?  Next 
most?  etc.")  of  (A)  rectangles  22-33,  (&)  triangles  41-52, 
(C)  Crosses  61-66  and  81-86,  (D)  designs  A-L  and  (E) 

147 


148 


EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 


the  24  unnumbered  designs.  Each  set  was  shown  as  here 
save  that  the  dimensions  were  in  each  case  double  those 
here  (quadrupling  the  areas). 


(C) 

I  give  the  facts  for  from  100  to  250  individuals  who  made 
the  judgments,  in  the  form  of  the  percent  of  them  assigning 
a  given  form  to  a  given  position. 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  IN  JUDGMENTS  OF  BEAUTY      149 


In  the  case  of  the  rectangles  it  will  be  observed  that  27, 
28,  and  29,  those  most  liked,  still  have  some  ratings  in  the 
lowest  position  of  all;  and  that  33,  the  one  least  liked,  still 
has  ratings  in  the  highest  position.  In  only  3  cases  out  of 
144  do  over  25  percent  of  the  ratings  give  a  rectangle  the 
same  position. 


II 


II  II 


(D) 


(D) 


In  the  case  of  the  triangles  there  is  a  pronounced  drift  of 
opinion  against  the  tall  triangles,  but  even  so  almost  every 
position  has  votes  in  the  case  of  each.  This  is  still  more  the 
case  with  the  crosses. 

In  the  case  of  the  designs  where  the  sequence  by  propor- 
tions is  more  hidden,  the  variability  becomes  enormous. 


EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 


Although  any  one  person  may  feel  very  decided  preferences, 
these  are  never  shared  by  enough  of  his  fellows  to  make 


TABLE  I 

FREQUENCIES  OF  EACH  POSITION  FOR  EACH  RECTANGLE  COMPUTED  FROM  ORDERS  OF 
MERIT  REPORTED  BY  200  INDIVIDUALS:   IN  PERCENTS 


Rectangles 


Positions 

22 

23 

24 

25 

26 

27 

28 

29 

3° 

31 

32 

33 

I 

4-5 

5 

3-5 

8.5 

6.5 

IS 

10.5 

IS 

16 

6-5 

4-5 

4-5 

2 

i-5 

7 

6 

7-5 

H 

7 

16 

17 

II 

8 

3-S 

i-S 

3 

4 

2-5 

8 

ii 

9-5 

15 

IS 

ii 

8.5 

7 

5-5 

3 

4 

2-5 

3-5 

ii 

12 

10 

16.5 

I3-S 

7-5 

II 

7 

4-5 

2 

5 

2 

4 

5-5 

12 

18 

iS-S 

8-5 

12 

8 

7 

4 

3 

6 

2 

4-5 

9 

14-5 

22 

9 

12.5 

10 

7-5 

5-5 

3 

i-5 

7 

5-5 

7-5 

12 

15 

4 

14-5 

9-5 

6.5 

9 

ii 

4-5 

i-S 

8 

6 

9 

IS-S 

6 

12.5 

2-5 

5-5 

ii 

8 

ii-S 

10 

i-S 

9 

9-5 

15 

12 

10 

i-5 

2 

2 

5 

IS 

ii-S 

ii 

5-5 

10 

ii-S 

18.5 

H 

i-5 

i-5 

2-5 

I 

i-5 

4-5 

22 

H 

7 

ii 

IS 

21 

3 

2 

3 

2 

i-5 

3 

35 

14-5 

12 

36 

2-5 

0-5 

o-S 

0-5 

3 

i-5 

o-S 

54-5 

anything    like    universal    agreement.     In    the    series    of    12 
designs,  not  one  has  25  percent  of  ratings  in  any  one  position. 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  IN  JUDGMENTS  OF  BEAUTY      I51 


In  the  series  of  24  designs,  in  only  about  one  case  out  of 
thirty  are  there  10  percent  or  more  of  ratings  in  any  one 
position. 

TABLE  II 

FREQUENCIES  OF  EACH  POSITION  FOR  EACH  TRIANGLE  COMPUTED  FROM  ORDERS  OF 
MERIT  REPORTED  BY  250  INDIVIDUALS:  IN  PERCENTS 


Positions 

Triangles 

4* 

42 

43 

44 

45 

46 

47 

48 

49 

So 

51 

52 

I 

26.0 

14.0 

21.2 

14.0 

7.2 

4.8 

3-6 

2.O 

1.2 

3-2 

.8 

1.6 

2 

10.8 

31.2 

16.8 

12.0 

7.6 

6.8 

7-2 

2.8 

2.8 

1.6 

.8 

3 

80 
.0 

14.8 

30.4 

l6.4 

12.0 

3-6 

3-6 

3-6 

3-2 

2.O 

1.2 

.8 

4 

9.6 

7.2 

6.8 

33-2 

14.0 

II.  2 

8.0 

4.0 

1.6 

3.6 

.8 

4 

5 

6.4 

S.6 

7-2 

7.2 

36.0 

12.0 

9-2 

8.0 

4.0 

2.4 

1.6 

.8 

6 

7.2 

3-2 

4-4 

6.4 

6.4 

41.2 

12.0 

7-6 

7-2 

4 

2.4 

1.6 

7 

44 

1-2 

3-2 

24 

4.8 

6.8 

4S-6 

12.4 

6.8 

2.8 

2.4 

2.8 

8 

2.4 

4.8 

1.2 

1.2 

6.8 

4.8 

4.8 

49-2 

I2.O 

8.0 

2.4 

1.6 

9 

•5.6 

4.8 

2.4 

4.8 

2.4 

2.8 

1.6 

S-6 

.IJ2.0 

IO.O 

4.0 

3-6 

10 

5.2 

2.0 

44 

1.2 

1.2 

3.6 

2.0 

2.0 

4-8 

61.2 

9.2 

4.0 

ii 

6.8 

4.8 

1.2 

4 

.8 

2.0 

1.6 

.8 

3-2 

4.8 

67.6 

44 

12 

5.6 

?8 

0.8 

4 

.8 

4 

.8 

1.2 

16 

5.6 

76.8 

? 

I  2 

4 

.8 

No  great  value  attaches  to  the  general  drift  of  the  con- 
sensus, since  the  responses  to  the  objects  displayed  as  they 
were  and  with  criteria  of  symmetry  so  strongly  suggested 

TABLE  III 

FREQUENCIES  OF  EACH  POSITION  FOR  EACH  CROSS  COMPUTED  FROM  ORDERS  OF 
MERIT  REPORTED  BY  140  INDIVIDUALS:  IN  PERCENTS 


Crosses 


Positions 

61 

62 

63 

64 

65 

66 

81 

82 

83 

84 

8s 

86 

I 

2.1 

•7 

IO.O 

15.0 

24-3 

7-i 

64 

19-3 

5-7 

2.1 

2.1 

S-o 

2 

2.1 

3-6 

IO.O 

22.1 

!6.4 

4-3 

S-o 

14-3 

12.9 

1.4 

7-i 

1.4 

3 

64 

8.6 

15-7 

IO.O 

11.4 

4-3 

18.6 

8.6 

10.7 

1.4 

4-3 

4 

3.6 

3.6 

IO.O 

15.0 

9-3 

5.0 

iS-o 

13.6 

15.0 

2.1 

64 

1.4 

5 

7-9 

15.7 

7-i 

10.7 

6.4 

13.6 

iS-o 

15.0 

4-3 

3-6 

1.4 

6 

'  V-6 

8.6 

11.4 

9-3 

5-7 

8.6 

13.6 

7-9 

12.  1 

11.4 

3-6 

4-3 

7 

1.4 

5-o 

11.4 

3-6 

11.4 

12.9 

12.  1 

4-3 

15-7 

10.7 

5-7 

S-o 

8 

S-o 

IO.O 

3.6 

2.1 

6.4 

17.9 

10.7 

3.6 

2.9 

24-3 

9-3 

5-7 

9 

2.1 

11.4 

S-o 

64 

2-9 

9-3 

7-i 

2.1 

6.4 

17.1 

24-3 

4-3 

10 

II.4 

IO.O 

13.6 

2.9 

5-0 

57 

•7 

4-3 

8.6 

17.1 

20.7 

ii 

IS.O 

32.1 



•7 

2.1 

5-7 

S-o 

•7 

1.4 

3-6 

17.1 

iS-7 

12 

53-6 

0.7 

•7 

•7 

6-4 

1.4 

3.6 

2.1 

30.7 

may  be  different  from  the  responses  to  the  same  objects  in 
isolation  or  in  different  surroundings.  However,  it  may  be 
of  interest  to  some  to  record  that:  The  most  liked  rectangles 


152 


EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 


TABLE  IV 

FREQUENCIES  OF  EACH  POSITION  FOR  EACH  LETTERED  DESIGN  COMPUTED  FROM 
ORDERS  OF  MERIT  REPORTED  BY  100  INDIVIDUALS:  IN  PERCENTS 


Positions 

Designs 

A 

B 

C 

D 

E 

F 

G 

H 

I 

J 

K 

L 

I 

14 

6 

12 

9 

2 

S 

6 

2 

IS 

13 

7 

10 

2 

12 

8 

12 

8 

2 

2 

i 

9 

13 

16 

S 

II 

3 

16 

2 

12 

IO 

IO 

5 

3 

5 

12 

H 

4 

9 

4 

16 

II 

II 

II 

9 

10 

3 

2 

5 

9 

5 

9 

5 

H 

9 

12 

II 

10 

7 

3 

ij 

7 

6 

4 

12 

6 

8 

6 

13 

i<; 

6 

17 

5 

6 

5 

9 

i 

IO 

7 

II 

13 

7 

6 

7 

IO 

ii 

7 

6 

6 

7 

8 

8 

5 

9 

ii 

13 

8 

8 

7 

IO 

4 

ii 

6 

7 

9 

i 

6 

6 

7 

19 

12 

13 

6 

7 



10 

12 

10 

2 

7 

2 

5 

12 

16 

7 

19 

10 

ii 

3 

5 

ii 

I 

10 

c 

II 

C 

17 

22 

1C 

-j 

7 

12 

13 

2 

4 

3 

24 

7 

I 

2 

41 

2 

TABLE  V 

FREQUENCIES  OF  EACH  POSITION  FOR  EACH  UNNUMBERED  DESIGN  OF  THE  FIRST 

Two  Rows  COMPUTED  FROM  ORDERS  OF  MERIT  REPORTED  BY  250 

INDIVIDUALS:   IN  PERCENTS.    THE  RESULTS  FOR  THE  OTHER 

Two  Rows  SHOW  THE  SAME  VARIABILITY 


Positions 


Designs 


Row 

i 

I 

i 

i 
4 

I 

i 

2 

2 

2 

2 

2 

2 

Number 

i 

2 

3 

5 

6 

I 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

I 

2.8 

10.0 

12.8 

2.8 

1.2 

4.4 

2.O 

.8 

•4 

7.2 

2.4 

1.2 

2 

4.0 

9.6 

8.8 

2.0 

.8 

5-2 

6-4 

4.4 

3-2 

4.0 

4-4 

1.2 

3 

3-6 

9-2 

8.8 

3-6 

6.8 

4.4 

2.8 

2.8 

4.8 

2.8 

•4 

4 

5-6 

IO.2 

7.2 

2.4 

'  i  '.6  ' 

3-6 

4-4 

3-2 

3.6 

3-6 

4.0 

3.6 

6.0 

8.0 

4.0 

2.4 

•4 

8.0 

3-6 

6.8 

5-6 

3-2 

2.O 

1.6 

6 

4.8 

8.4 

3-6 

2.4 

3-6 

8.4 

9.2 

7-2 

7-2 

2.8 

1.6 

2.4 

8 
9 

8.0 

g 

4-4 

3-2 

4-4 

7-2 
2.0 

1.6 

3-6 

2.8 

3.6 

4.8 
4.4 
4.8 

4-4 
8.4 
7-6 

7-6 
7.2 
4.8 

4-8 
6.0 
4.0 

4-8 
6.0 

4.8 

4.8 

it 

2.8 

4.8 
6.0 

3.6 

2.8 
3-2 

10 

3-2 

3-6 

2.8 

4.0 

6.0 

5-2 

4.8 

6.8 

10.0 

4.0 

5-6 

3.6 

ii 

5-2 

2.4 

2.8 

4.8 

5.2 

4.8 

4.8 

4-4 

7.2 

6.0 

4.0 

44 

12 

3-2 

4.4 

4.0 

2.8 

6.0 

3-6 

5-2 

4.4 

6.4 

7.2 

6.4 

5-2 

13 

5-2 

4.8 

2.8 

6.4 

4.0 

4-4 

4.8 

3-6 

2.8 

3-2 

6.0 

6.0 

H 

4.8 

3.6 

3-2 

2.8 

4.0 

3-2 

5-2 

2.8 

3-6 

n   o 
O.O 

5-6 

6.4 

IS 

4.0 

1.6 

2.8 

3-2 

4.0 

3-6 

3.6 

5-2 

4.0 

4-8 

IO.O 

4-4 

16 
17 

4.4 

2.8 

1.6 

2.0 

1.2 

3-2 

4.0 
2.4 

4.8 
4.8 

Ii 

6-4 
4-4 

4.8 

3-2 

4.0 
5-6 

I8 

6.0 

6.0 
3-6 

44 

2.4 

18 

2.0 

1.6 

3-2 

5.6 

6.8 

1.6 

2.0 

6.0 

2.8 

1.2 

5-2 

44 

19 

3-2 

2.0 

4.0 

4.8 

8.4 

4.0 

1.2 

3-2 

3-2 

4.0 

3.6 

4.0 

20 

2.O 

1.6 

3-2 

8.4 

5.6 

1.6 

1.6 

4-4 

3-2 

1.6 

4.0 

8.4 

21 

2.8 

1.2 

3.6 

10.8 

6.8 

2.0 

2.8 

5-2 

2.0 

2.4 

2.4 

IO.O 

22 

3.6 



1.2 

II.  2 

3-2 

1.6 

2.0 

4-4 

.8 

1.2 

3.6 

IO.O 

23 

1.6 

.8 

3-2 

1.6 

3-6 

2.4 

.8 

1.2 

1.2 

.8 

2.4 

2.4 

24 

4.0 

.8 

1.2 

1.2 

4.4 

.8 

.8 

•4 

4-4 

•4 

•4 

4.0 

INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  IN  JUDGMENTS  OF  BEAUTY     153 


TABLE  VI 

ORDER  OF  MERIT  ASSIGNED  BY  THE  CONSENSUS  OF  COLLEGE  STUDENTS 


Unnumbered  De- 

signs.   The  Num- 

Rectangles 

Triangles 

Crosses 

Lettered  Designs 

bers  Here  Follow 

the  Order  of 

Printing* 

29 

43,44 

64,  82,  65 

28 

42 

81,  83,  66 

A 

14 

27  and  30 

4i,4S 

84,63 

J 

2 

26 

46 

62,  85 

CDIL 

3 

25  and  31 

47 

61,  86 

BF 

6  15 

24 

48 

E 

i     7,  13 

23  and  32 

49 

G.H. 

8     9,  10,  20 

22  and  33 

50 

K. 

II    17,  22,  24 

Si 

4     5,  12,  18 

52 

16  23 

19    21 

*  That  is,  the  first  design  in  the  second  row  is  7,  the  next  is  8;  the  first  design  in 
the  third  row  is  13,  the  next  is  14,  etc. 

had,  as  the  ratio  of  altitude  to  base,  1.83  to  I.  The  most 
liked  triangles  had,  as  similar  ratios,  1.6  to  I  and  1.7  to  I 
(43  and  44  being  equally  well  liked).  The  most  liked  of 
the  crosses  had  a  bar  half  of  the  length  of  the  upright  and 
such  a  bar  is  best  liked  when  it  cuts  the  upright  so  as  to  leave 
one  fourth  above  and  three  fourths  below.  A  bar  two  fifths 
of  the  length  of  the  upright  is  nearly  as  well  liked.  The 
most  liked  of  the  unnumbered  designs  is  the  second  one  of 
the  third  row.  The  first  and  third  of  the  fourth  row  are  the 
most  disliked.  In  the  lettered  designs  the  space  relations 
may  vary  widely  so  long  as  the  design  remains  obvious, 
and  so  long  as  neither  bareness  nor  crowdedness  is  suggested. 
A  and  /  are  liked  about  equally;  G,  H  and  K  are  disliked 
about  equally. 

The  order  of  merit  of  the  consensus  is  given  for  each 
group  of  designs  in  Table  VI. 


PRELIMINARY  REPORT  ON  THE   RELATIVE   IN- 
TENSITY OF   SUCCESSIVE,   SIMULTANEOUS, 
ASCENDING,  AND   DESCENDING  TONES 

BY  A.  P.  WEISS 

Ohio  State  University 

The  attribute  of  tone  intensity  has  been  relatively  neg- 
lected in  experiments  in  audition  because  of  the  technical 
difficulty  in  producing  pure  tones  which  may  be  varied  in 
their  loudness  or  intensity  in  a  definite  and  measurable 
manner. 

The  apparatus  with  which  the  experiments  in  this  paper 
were  performed  was  developed  at  the  University  of  Missouri 
under  the  guidance  and  suggestions  of  Dr.  M.  F.  Meyer. 
The  extended  report  showing  the  details  of  the  apparatus 
construction  and  the  manner  in  which  the  experiments  were 
conducted  is  being  published  as  a  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 
MONOGRAPH. 

The  apparatus  makes  it  possible  to  produce  tuning-fork 
tones  which  meet  the  following  conditions : 

1.  The  tones  are  pure  in  the  sense  that  no  lower  or  upper 
harmonics  can  be  detected. 

2.  The  tones  can  be  quickly  varied  from  weak  to  strong 
in  any  number  of  steps  and  each  degree  of  intensity  can  be 
repeated  as  often  as  necessary. 

3.  The  tones  'come  in'  and  'go  out'  at  their  full  intensity 
without  disturbing,  starting,  or  stopping  noises. 

4.  The  phase  relations  of  the  tuning  forks  is  under  control. 
The  nature  of  the  experiments  may  be  understood  from 

the  following  illustrations. 

I.  Relative  intensity  of  successive  and  simultaneous  tones: 
Suppose  we  have  the  tone  200  which,  during  a  given  trial,  is 
always  sounded  at  a  medium  and  constant  intensity.  An- 
other tone  250  can  be  easily  varied  from  weak  to  strong 


RELATIVE  INTENSITY  OF  TONES  '55 

(ascending  order)1  or  from  strong  to  weak  (descending  order). 
Suppose  we  sound  200  and  250  alternately  and  vary  the 
intensity  of  250  (either  ascending  or  descending)  until  it 
seems  to  have  the  same  intensity  as  200;  the  question  now 
arises,  if  200  and  250  are  sounded  simultaneously,  are  they 
still  of  the  same  intensity? 

2.  Relative  intensity  of  ascending  and  descending  tones: 
Suppose  200  is  kept  constant  in  intensity  and  250  is  varied 
in  descending  order,  will  the  point  at  which  250  is  considered 
equal  to  200  be  the  same  as  when  250  is  varied  in  ascending 
order? 

The  tones  used  in  this  experiment  were  the  four  tones 
150,  200,  250,  300.  Each  tone  was  compared  with  each  of 
the  other  three  tones  in  four  ways. 

1.  Successively,    with    the   comparison   tone   varying   in 
ascending  order. 

2.  Successively,    with    the    comparison    tone   varying   in 
descending  order. 

3.  Simultaneously,  with  the  comparison  tone  varying  in 
ascending  order. 

4.  Simultaneously,  with  the  comparison  tone  varying  in 
descending  order. 

Both  the  lower  and  the  higher  tones  were  used  as  standard 
in  each  pair.  Each  pair  of  tones  was  further  compared  for 
ten  degrees  of  intensity  ranging  from  a  weak  tone  which  was 
nevertheless  clearly  heard,  to  a  strong  tone  which  was  not, 
however,  so  loud  that  it  became  disagreeable.  That  is,  the 
range  of  conveniently  obtainable  intensities  was  divided  into 
ten  steps  and  the  various  tone  combinations  were  compared 
for  each  of  these  steps. 

The  method  of  making  the  judgments  was  that  of  "  Selbst- 
einstellung."  One  tone  (the  standard)  was  kept  at  constant 
intensity  while  the  observer  varied  the  intensity  of  the  com- 
parison tone  until  it  seemed  equal  in  intensity  to  the  tone 
which  was  being  used  as  the  standard. 

xThe  numbers  200  and  250  refer  to  the  vibration  rates.  Ascending  order  or 
ascending  tones  refer  to  tones  which  are  varied  from  silence  to  weak  to  strong.  De- 
scending order  or  descending  tones  refer  to  tones  whose  intensity  is  varied  from  strong 
to  weak. 


150  A.  P.   WEISS 

The  tones  were  produced  by  resonators  suspended  over 
silently  vibrating  tuning  forks  of  constant  amplitude  and  the 
objective  intensity  of  the  tone  was  measured  by  the  distance 
of  the  mouth  of  the  resonator  from  the  prongs  of  the  tuning 
fork. 


FIG.  i. 

The  above  diagram  shows  the  results  obtained.  The 
number  in  the  right  arm  of  each  brace  indicates  the  intensity 
relations  between  the  series  connected  by  the  brace.  Thus 
the  number  .86  in  the  brace  connecting  the  circles  of  the 
successive-ascending  and  successive-descending  series,  means 
that  when  a  tone  of  constant  intensity  was  compared  suc- 
cessively, first  with  an  ascending  tone,  and  second  with  a 
descending  tone,  the  descending  tone  was  made  .86  step 
stronger  than  the  ascending  tone.  Subjectively  this  implies 
that  the  descending  tone  was  actually  heard  weaker  than  the 
ascending  tone,  since  if  it  had  been  set  at  the  intensity  of 
the  ascending  tone  it  would  have  been  judged  weaker  than 
the  standard  tone. 

A  negative  sign  in  the  diagram  means  that  the  series  was 
made  weaker  (objectively)  than  the  companion  series.  In 
subjective  terms  this  means  that  the  tone  was  actually  heard 
stronger.  This  opposition  between  "made  stronger  objec- 
tively" and  "heard  weaker  subjectively"  is  rather  confusing 
and  it  was  thought  worth  while  to  add  the  subjective  impli- 
cations parenthetically  in  the  statement  of  the  conclusion. 

Each  of  the  conclusions  which  follow  are  based  on  at 
least  4,800  judgments  or  reactions.  The  term  'step'  refers 
to  one  tenth  the  total  range  of  intensities  used  in  the  experi- 
ments, or  one  tenth  of  the  range  of  conveniently  obtainable 
intensities. 


RELATIVE  INTENSITY  OF  TONES  157 

1.  When  compared  successively  with  a  tone  of  constant 
intensity,  descending  tones  are  made  .86  step  stronger  (or 
heard  .86  step  weaker)  than  ascending  tones. 

2.  When  compared  simultaneously  with  a  tone  of  constant 
intensity,  descending  tones  are  made  .92  step  stronger  (or 
heard  .92  step  weaker)  than  ascending  tones. 

3.  When   compared  with   a  tone  of  constant  intensity, 
ascending  tones,  when  compared  simultaneously,  are  made  .52 
step  weaker  (or  heard  .52  step  stronger)  than  when  compared 
successively. 

4.  When  compared  with   a   tone   of  constant  intensity, 
descending  tones,  when  compared  simultaneously,  are  made 
.55  step  weaker  (or  heard  .55  step  stronger)  than  when  com- 
pared successively. 

5.  When  compared  with  a  tone  of  constant  intensity  in 
mixed  simultaneous  and  successive  order,  descending  tones 
are  made  .86  step  stronger  (or  heard  .86  step  weaker)  than 
ascending  tones. 

6.  When  compared  with  a  tone  of  constant  intensity  in 
mixed  ascending  and  descending  order,  simultaneous  tones 
are  made  .34  step  weaker  (or  heard  .34  step  stronger)  than 
successive  tones. 

The  deviations  of  one  half  of  the  intensity  judgments 
above  or  below  the  objective  intensity  was  .74  step.  This 
seems  to  indicate  that  within  the  range  of  conveniently  ob- 
tainable intensities  used  in  this  experiment  15  steps  might 
have  been  discriminated.  Taking  very  weak  and  very  loud 
tones  it  seems  that  25  steps  should  be  possible. 

The  value  .74  is  also  an  indication  of  the  reliability  with 
which  intensity  judgments  can  be  made.  This  is  about  the 
same  for  all  the  intensities  used,  being  somewhat  less  for  the 
medium  intensities  than  for  the  extremes,  as  might  have  been 
expected. 

The  variability  of  the  intensity  judgments  is  not  influenced 
as  much  by  difference  in  vibration  rates  as  was  expected. 
The  greatest  difference  between  any  of  the  tones  of  this  ex- 
periment was  an  octave  (150  vibrations)  and  the  comparisons 


158  A.  P.   WEISS 

between  these  two  tones  were  no  more  variable  than  where 
the  difference  was  50  vibrations.  This  seems  to  show  that 
even  between  tones  whose  vibration  difference  is  considerable, 
the  intensity  judgments  can  be  made  with  a  degree  of  accuracy 
which  promises  well  for  an  experimental  analysis  of  the  sound 
intensity  reaction. 


DISCUSSION 

A   NEW   METHOD    OF    HETEROCHROMATIC   PHOTOM- 
ETRY—A REPLY  TO   DR.   JOHNSON 

In  the  September  number  of  this  journal  appears  a  discussion 
entitled  'A  Note  on  Ferree  and  Rand's  Method  of  Photometry,'  by 
Dr.  H.  M.  Johnson,  of  the  Nela  Park  Laboratory.  This  discussion, 
we  may  perhaps  be  pardoned  for  noting,  is  remarkable  chiefly  for 
its  numerous  mistakes  and  incorrect  or  misleading  representations, 
a  few  of  which  we  take  opportunity  here  to  rectify.  The  net  service 
of  the  discussion  is  to  call  the  authors'  attention  to  the  omission  of  a 
decimal  point  in  the  original  article,  for  which  they  duly  acknowledge 
their  debt. 

1.  In  his  opening  paragraph  Dr.  Johnson  says:  "The  authors 
claim  for  their  method  that  with  respect  both  to  sensitivity  and 
reproducibility  it  surpasses  the  equality  of  brightness  method,  even 
when  the  photometer  head  used  is  of  the  best  Lummer-Brodhun 
type."     In  regard  to  this  statement  we  beg  to  point  out  that  Dr. 
Johnson  has  omitted  from  what  was  actually  said  all  that  makes  a 
difference  between  a  reasonable  and  an  absurd  claim.     We  had 
claimed  in  our  paper  greater  reproducibility  of  setting  for  the  method 
in  question  as  compared  with  the  equality  of  brightness  method 
only  in  case  of  hetero chromatic  photometry,  in  which  respect  as  is 
well  known  the  equality  of  brightness  method  is  notably  deficient. 
The  possibility  of  a  service  to  heterochromatic  photometry  alone 
is  the  reason  given  in  the  paper  for  applying  to  the  rating  of  artificial 
lights  a  principle  formerly  used  by  us  for  an  entirely  different  pur- 
pose.     Also  the  special   reference  to  heterochromatic  photometry 
was  featured  in  the  title. 

2.  Dr.  Johnson  next  says:  "The  authors  assumed  that  the  two 
elements  making  up  the  photometer  screen  '  received  equal  amounts 
of  light  from  the  source  to  be  measured.'     Even  if  the  elements 
were  equidistant  from  the  lamp  .  .  .  the  truth  of  this  assumption 
does  not  follow  from  the  data  given,     In  some  of  the  work  the 
results  of  which  are  presented  in  the  authors'  table,  the  angular 
separation  of  the  compared  elements  was  14°  to  15°  at  the  source. 
Now  the  radiation  from  a  carbon  or  tungsten  lamp  is  not  equal  in 

159 


160  c.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

all  directions  as  is  that  from  an  ideal  point  source.  In  fact,  for 
lamps  of  such  types,  differences  of  several  per  cent,  in  different 
directions  normal  to  the  long  axis  of  the  lamp  are  the  rule,  and  a 
considerable  difference  might  occur  in  a  range  of  15°." 

With  reference  to  the  above  statements  we  wish  to  note  in  the 
first  place  that  it  was  never  assumed  by  us  that  there  were  only  two 
elements  in  the  photometer  screen.  This  erroneous  interpretation 
of  the  principle  on  which  the  method  is  based  can  be  attributed  to 
Dr.  Johnson  only.  Secondly,  that  when  the  angular  separation  of 
the  elements  referred  to  (the  stimulus  patch  and  the  measuring 
disc),  is  correctly  computed  from  the  data  contained  in  the  original 
article  it  is  found  to  vary  between  4.5°  and  II0,1  and  not  to  have  a 
range  of  15°.  And  thirdly,  that  when  the  question  of  the  influence 
of  the  distribution  curve  on  the  general  applicability  of  the  method 
to  working  practice  was  raised  by  us  in  a  paper  presented  to  the 
Philadelphia  Section  of  the  Illuminating  Engineering  Society  in 
February,  I9I4,2  it  was  the  consensus  of  opinion  in  the  discussion 
that  followed  that  the  possibility  of  error  from  this  source  is  of  neg- 
ligible consequence  in  a  field  presenting  so  many  difficulties  as 
heterochromatic  photometry,  and  that  the  effective  check  on  these 
and  many  other  points  which  were  raised  by  us  at  that  time — in 
addition  to  those  now  raised  by  Dr.  Johnson — must  come  in  a 
comparison  of  the  results  with  those  obtained  by  the  equality  of 
brightness  method.  Because  of  this  confirmatory  opinion  of  a  group 
of  specialists  fully  familiar  with  all  the  technical  and  working  details 
of  photometry  and  because  of  the  check  experiments  we  had  run  on 
the  point  to  convince  ourselves  of  the  negligible  influence  of  the 
factor  for  the  conditions  under  which  we  worked  (see  this  paper, 
p.  165),  we  had  not  considered  it  necessary  to  raise  the  discussion 
in  the  preliminary  exposition  of  the  principles  on  which  the  pro- 
posed method  is  based,  contained  in  the  article  in  question.  How- 
ever, since  the  point  has  been  raised  by  Dr.  Johnson,  the  following 
comments  may  not  be  out  of  place. 

1  It  is  assumed  here  of  course  that  Dr.  Johnson  referred  to  the  angle  for  the  colorless 
light.    There  can  have  been  no  reasonable  doubt  in  his  mind  that  the  colored  light  was 
not  obtained  from  the  naked  carbon  or  tungsten  lamps  to  which  his  comments  on 
distribution  refer.     (See  footnote,  original  article  p.  9). 

2  With  reference  to  the  foregoing  point  and  to  others  taken  up  in  this  discussion  it 
is  scarcely  needful  to  state  that  principles  and  descriptions  of  conditions  of  a  technical 
nature  were  taken  up  in  a  fuller  and  more  detailed  way  when  a  statement  of  the  method 
was  presented  to  auditors  technically  interested  in  photometry  than  was  done  in  the 
article  criticized  by  Dr.  Johnson. 


HETEROCHROMATIC  PHOTOMETRY 


161 


(a)  A  general  statement  of  the  type  which  Dr.  Johnson  has 
made  about  the  inequality  of  distribution  of  carbon  and  tungsten 
lamps  is  incomplete  to  the  point  of  being  somewhat  misleading. 
As  is  well  known,  the  distribution  curve  of  an  incandescent  fila- 
ment lamp  depends  upon  the  shape  of  the  filament.  While,  for 
example,  the  single  oval  filament  of  the  ordinary  carbon  lamp 
gives  considerable  unevenness  of  distribution,  if  wide  enough  angles 
are  considered,  the  single  loop  tungsten  filament  of  the  Mazda 
lamp,  series  type,  gives  a  curve  which  deviates  so  little  from 


FIG.  I.  Showing  the  distribution  curve  in  the  horizontal  plane  of  a  5O-watt 
carbon  lamp,  single  oval  filament — readings  taken  at  5  ft.  radius;  lamp  operated  at 
6.8  horizontal  cp.;  watts  per  horizontal  cp.,  2.97. 

a  circle  as  to  be  scarcely  detectable  with  the  exception  of  a  very 
small  region  in  the  plane  of  the  filament.  The  curves  for  these 
lamps  are  appended  in  Figs.  I  and  2.  In  Fig.  3  is  given  also  the 
curve  for  the  ordinary  type  B  Mazda  lamp.1  This  curve  shows 
more  variation  than  the  series  lamp  but  it  is  so  nearly  uniform  as 
to  be  considered  circular  for  practical  purposes.  However,  neither 
this  nor  the  single  oval  filament  carbon  lamp  have  ever  been  used 

1  The  determinations  represented  in  these  curves  were  made  by  the  photometric 
laboratory  of  the  General  Electric  Co.,  Schenectady,  N.  Y. 


1 62  c.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

by  us  in  connection  with  the  method  of  photometry  in  question 
without  some  device  to  secure  greater  uniformity  of  distribution  of 
light.  In  case  a  naked  lamp  were  used  at  all  it  has  always  been  of 
the  series  type,  single-loop  tip-anchored  filament,  and  care  has  been 
taken  to  have  the  lamp  set  on  the  bar  so  that  the  light  was  taken  at 
right  angles  to  the  plane  of  the  filament  or  from  the  most  uniform 
part  of  the  curve.  But  even  were  a  carbon  lamp  used  and  the  arrow 


FIG.  2.  Showing  the  distribution  curve  of  a  60  cp.  series  Mazda  lamp  (clear), 
single  loop  tip  anchored  filament,  6.6  amps. — readings  taken  at  5  ft.  radius;  lamp 
operated  at  60  horizontal  cp.;  watts  per  horizontal  cp.,  1.18. 

or  'fiducial'  mark  scratched  in  a  plane  at  right  angles  to  the  plane 
of  the  filament,  the  distribution  would  fall  off  so  evenly  on  either 
side  (see  Fig.  i)1  that  the  difference  in  the  illumination  of  the 
stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc,  not  exceeding  5.5°  on  either 
side,  should  be  negligible. 

1  It  should  be  noted  that  in  making  the  cuts  for  the  curves  in  Figs.  I  and  3  the 
true  deviations  from  uniformity  have  been  exaggerated  by  small  but  considerable 
amounts. 


HETEROCHROMATIC  PHOTOMETRY  163 

(b)  So  far  as  the  question  of  uniformity  of  angular  distribution  of 
light  is  concerned,  stress  seems  to  be  laid  in  the  criticism  on  the 
equality  of  illumination  of  the  stimulus  patch  and  the  measuring 
disc  alone  from  the  lights  to  be  photometered.  This  is  not  at  all 
in  keeping  with  a  correct  interpretation  of  the  method,  for  the 
photometric  balance  does  not  consist  in  the  judgments  of  the  actual 
amounts  of  light  falling  on  the  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc. 


FIG.  3.  Showing  the  distribution  curve  in  the  horizontal  plane  of  a  4O-watt  G.  E. 
Mazda  lamp  (clear),  regular  type  small  bulb,  no  volts — reading  taken  at  5  ft.  radius; 
lamp  operated  at  32.5  horizontal  cp.;  watts  per  horizontal  cp.,  1.23. 

The  apparent  brightness  of  the  stimulus  patch  is,  for  example,  the 
result  of  three  factors:  the  actual  amount  of  light  falling  on  the 
stimulus  patch,  the  amount  falling  on  the  surrounding  screen  (rather 
in  both  cases  the  amount  reflected  to  the  eye),  and  the  physiological 
induction  caused  by  the  difference  in  the  brightnesses  of  these  two 
surfaces.  Dr.  Johnson,  however,  as  indicated  above,  in  considering 
the  question  of  the  distribution  of  the  illumination  and  its  probable 
effect  on  the  results  of  the  method,  seems  throughout  his  discussion 


164  C.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

to  take  into  account  only  the  relative  amounts  of  light  received  by 
the  stimulus  patch  and  the  measuring  disc,  and  in  so  doing  shows  a 
fundamental  misunderstanding  of  the  principle  on  which  the  method 
is  based.  The  illumination  of  the  field  surrounding  the  stimulus 
patch  is  just  as  important  as  the  illumination  of  the  stimulus  patch 
itself,  for  it  is  an  equal  factor  in  producing  the  induction  and  is,  so  far 
as  any  one  knows,  effective  for  induction  up  to  the  measuring  disc; 
and  there  is,  it  is  scarcely  needful  to  point  out,  not  an  angular 
separation  of  if  between  this  screen  and  the  measuring  disc.  The 
important  point  is  rather  that  there  shall  be  no  effective  difference 
in  the  collective  situation  influencing  the  induction  and  its  measure- 
ment for  the  standard  and  the  comparison  lamp.  That  is,  although 
the  two  surfaces  are  compared  in  each  judgment,  the  comparison 
of  the  two  light  sources  is  based  on  the  results  of  two  judgments, 
and  if  there  is  no  difference  in  the  collective  situation  influencing  the 
two  judgments,  no  injustice  is  done  to  the  lights  compared.  If, 
therefore,  we  were  considering  with  Dr.  Johnson  the  relative  illu- 
mination of  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  to  the  exclusion 
of  other  factors,  and  to  what  degree  this  relative  illumination  is 
influenced  by  the  distribution  curve  of  the  light  source,  the  impor- 
tant item  is  not  that  there  is  an  angular  separation  between  them 
of  a  given  number  of  degrees  and  a  possible  difference  of  illumination 
in  consequence,  but  how  much  this  varies  for  the  position  of  the 
standard  and  comparison  lamps  on  the  photometer  bar.  For  the 
nearest  position  of  the  standard  lamp,  the  difference  in  the  angular 
separation  for  the  two  lamps  was  11°;  for  the  farthest  position  for 
the  distances  as  given  in  the  table,  the  difference  would  have  been 
4.5°.  However,  for  the  greater  distances  that  would  have  been 
required  for  the  standard  lamp  from  the  screen  to  establish  a  balance 
with  the  less  intense  colored  lights,  a  part  of  the  reduction  was 
produced  by  sectored  discs,  because  in  the  form  and  set-up  of  ap- 
paratus employed  for  that  work,  distances  of  light  from  screen  of 
134-160  cm.  (Table  I.,  original  article,  p.  9)  could  not  conveniently 
be  attained  owing  to  the  angle  of  the  shadow  cast  by  the  observer's 
head.  This  reduction  was  converted  into  terms  of  the  law  of 
squares  to  make  the  results  comparable  in  the  table  with  those 
obtained  by  the  equality  of  brightness  method.  The  actual  setting 
of  the  lamp  on  the  photometer  bar  for  the  greatest  of  these  distances 
was  104  instead  of  160  cm.  The  difference  between  the  angular 
separation  of  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  was  in  this  case, 
therefore,  7°.  The  actual  range  of  variation  of  angular  separation 


HETEROCHROMATIC  PHOTOMETRY 


165 


of  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  was  thus  only  from  7°  to  11°. 
There  is,  it  is  obvious,  considerable  difference  between  these  values 
and  the  15°  with  which  Dr.  Johnson  confronts  us.  Furthermore,  in 
the  course  of  the  original  work  we  ran  a  series  of  check  experiments 
to  determine  whether  this  difference  in  angular  separation  in  case 
of  the  standard  and  comparison  lights  produced  any  significant 
error.  That  is,  in  these  check  experiments  both  lights  were  kept 
in  the  same  position  and  the  light  for  the  more  intense,  the  standard, 
was  reduced  by  means  of  sectored  discs  very  accurately  cut  from 
sheet  aluminum,  the  open  sectors  of  which  were  measured  with  a 
protractor  provided  with  a  Vernier  scale  reading  to  minutes.  The 
results  of  these  experiments  are  given  in  Table  I. 

TABLE  I. 

SHOWING  A  COMPARISON  OF  THE  RESULTS  OBTAINED  FOR  THE  LIGHTS  REPRESENTED 
IN  THE  ORIGINAL  TABLE  WHEN  THE  PHOTOMETRIC  BALANCE  WAS  MADE  (a)  BY 
CHANGING  THE  SETTING  OF  THE  LIGHTS  ON  THE  PHOTOMETER  BAR;  AND  (b)  BY  THE 
USE  OF  THE  SECTORED  Disc 


Value  of 

Dis- 

Open Sec- 

tance of 

tor  Giving 

Source  of  Colored  Light 

Color 

White 
Light 
Giving 
Equal- 
ity of 
Illumi- 

Ratio of 
Candle- 
power. 
Color: 
White 

Equality 
of  Illumi- 
nation with 
Distance 
of  White 
and  Col- 

Ratio of 
Candle- 
power. 
Color; 
White 

Differ- 
ence in 
Ratio 

Differ- 
ence in 
Per 
Cent. 
Candle- 
power 

nation 

ored 

Cm.' 

Lights 

Equal 

87    cp.    41   cm.   distant 

Red 

66.6 

0-379 

137-5° 

0.382 

0.0030 

0.785 

from  photometric 

screen  

Blue-green 

ro.r 

O.4.74.8 

I72,O 

o  4.778 

O.OO3O 

0.628 

52   cp.   38   cm.   distant 

Red 

37  0 

82.2 

T"/TU 
0.2137 

A  /  **W 

77-75 

\J.£^j  1  <J 

0.2160 

O.OO23 

1.  06 

from  photometric 

screen  .  . 

Blue-green 

7O  C 

O  2QO£ 

IOC  C 

O  2Q3  1 

O.OO26 

0.887 

13  cp.  38    cm.    distant 

Red 

i    -> 
160.0 

w.^yw.j 

0.0564 

•*OO 

20.5 

^-^yj  L 

0.05694 

O.OOO54 

0.948 

from  photometric 

screen  

Blue-green 

134-9 

0.0793 

28.85 

0.08014 

O.OOO79 

0.985 

Moreover,  so  far  as  inequalities  of  illumination  of  stimulus  patch 
and  measuring  disc  are  concerned,  we  may  point  out  that  a  naked 
lamp  was  not  even  used  in  the  experiments  the  results  of  which  are 
given  in  the  original  table.  Partly  because  the  colored  light  was 
secured  by  means  of  colored  filters,  and  partly  as  a  precaution 
against  unevenness  of  illumination  of  stimulus  patch,  measuring 
disc,  and  surrounding  field  for  a  height  and  breadth  sufficient  for 
the  purpose  of  the  experiment,  the  light  was  placed  in  a  lamp-house 


166  c.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

(see  original  article,  footnote  p.  9).1  This  lamp-house  was  24  cm. 
high,  14  cm.  wide  and  14  cm.  deep.  At  the  lower  end  of  the  lamp- 
house  was  an  opening  5  cm.  square  through  which  the  light  passed 
to  the  screen.  The  lamp-house  was  lined  with  mat  white  paper  so 
shaped  as  to  round  off  the  edges  and  corners  and  to  give  as  much  as 
possible  in  the  lower  part  of  the  enclosure  the  effect  of  the  segment 
of  a  sphere.  No  light  passed  directly  from  the  lamp  to  the  screen 
as  the  tip  of  the  lamp  was  for  the  different  lamps  used  from  2  to  9 
cm.  above  the  opening  for  the  emission  of  the  light.  Owing  to  the 
high  absorption  of  the  Wrattan  and  Wainwright  filters  the  light 
from  the  lamp  used  to  establish  a  balance  with  that  transmitted 
from  the  filters  had  to  be  greatly  reduced  at  the  opening  of  the  lamp- 
house  by  means  of  colorless  absorbing  screens,  which  served  further 
to  diffuse  the  light.  To  determine  whether  or  not  any  serious  dif- 
ference in  the  distribution  of  light  to  measuring  disc  and  stimulus 
patch  was  present  in  case  of  this  device,  the  light  was  photometered 
at  stimulus  patch  and  at  measuring  disc  for  each  position  of  the 
lights  on  the  bar.  No  difference  could  be  detected  for  these  two 
positions  by  the  equality  of  brightness  method.  Also  the  distribu- 
tion curve  for  the  light  coming  through  this  opening  was  found  to  be 
circular  through  an  angle  greater  than  the  n°  in  question.  Our 
statement  in  the  original  article  then  was  correct  that  the  equality 
of  distance  of  the  measuring  disc  and  stimulus  patch  on  either  side 
of  the  photometer  bar  guaranteed  that  they  receive  equal  illumina- 
tion from  the  light  source  employed.  It  would  also  be  true  within 
any  reasonable  margin  of  error  for  the  single  loop  filament  series 
lamp  set  as  described  above  (without  a  lamp  house),  and  even  for 
the  single  oval  carbon  filament  within  a  margin  of  error  quite  ac- 
ceptable for  work  in  heterochromatic  photometry. 

3.  In  a  later  paragraph  (p.  394)  Dr.  Johnson  conveys  the  im- 
pression that  we  claim  an  agreement  between  the  results  of  the 
new  method  and  those  of  the  equality  of  brightness  method  within 

1  The  lamp-house  is  not  shown  in  the  photograph  of  apparatus  given  in  the  original 
article.  The  photograph  was  a  part  of  the  general  description  of  the  method  and  the 
apparatus  that  might  be  used  with  it.  In  making  this  photograph  the  apparatus 
was  regrouped,  the  object  being  merely  to  show  the  type  of  bar  used,  the  screen  and 
the  measuring  disc.  In  this  photograph  it  will  also  be  noted  that  the  apparatus  was 
not  even  shown  in  the  position  in  which  it  is  used  in  making  the  determinations.  The 
use  of  a  lamp-house  is  mentioned  in  another  part  of  the  article,  namely  the  part  treating 
of  the  results  that  were  given  as  a  sample  of  what  might  be  obtained  with  the  method. 
In  the  first  photographs  that  were  made  the  lamp-house  was  included,  but  its  size  and 
position  in  the  foreground  made  it  appear  so  disproportionately  large  that  it  was  decided 
to  omit  it  and  to  give  the  photograph  the  general  character  mentioned  above. 


HETEROCHROMATIC  PHOTOMETRY  167 

a  fraction  of  one  per  cent.1  Of  this  we  have  to  say  that  no  numerical 
value  whatever  was  assigned  to  the  agreement  in  the  original  article 
nor  was  any  general  statement  made  that  would  warrant  the  infer- 
ence that  we  claimed  an  agreement  within  so  small  a  margin.  All 
that  appears  in  the  article  in  this  connection  is  a  very  brief  table  of 
results  containing  no  reference  whatever  to  the  point  in  question 
accompanied  by  an  8-line  paragraph  stating  that  the  table  is  ap- 
pended as  a  sample  of  the  results  obtained,  that  the  results  are 
averages  from  25  determinations,  etc.  It  is  the  custom  in  photom- 
etry when  a  numerical  expression  is  made  of  agreements,  mean 
deviations,  etc.,  to  give  these  in  per  cent,  illumination  or  per  cent, 
candlepower.  When  this  is  done  for  the  table  in  question,  the 
agreement  shown  by  the  data  given  falls  within  1.5  per  cent,  instead 
of  'within  a  fraction  of  I  per  cent.'  as  is  stated  by  Dr.  Johnson. 
And  this  it  will  be  remembered,  is  an  agreement  in  the  average. 
When  the  individual  determinations  are  compared,  the  deviations 
reach  values  of  the  order  of  +  10  and—  12  per  cent.  Some  idea  of 
this  may  be  had  from  an  inspection  of  the  per  cent,  mean  variations 
appearing  in  the  table  for  the  results  obtained  by  the  equality 
of  brightness  method.  Thus  it  will  be  seen  that  the  actual 
closeness  of  agreement  of  results  is  not  surprising.  It  has  been 
made  to  appear  so  only  by  our  critic's  method  of  presentation. 

1  On  p.  393  Dr.  Johnson  says:  "The  authors  do  not  describe  their  mode  of  pro- 
cedure in  making  their  measurements  by  the  method  of  direct  comparison.  I  assume, 
therefore, ....  Under  these  conditions  and  working  with  the  lamps  beyond  certain  mini- 
mal distances  from  the  photometer  head,  the  luminous  intensities  of  the  compared 
sources  would  be  inversely  [italics  ours]  as  the  squares  of  their  distances  from  the  photom- 
eter screen  at  valid  settings  for  equality  of  brightness  on  the  two  halves  of  the  photometer 
field."  We  did  not  suppose  that  in  an  article  on  photometry  it  was  necessary  to  give 
a  description  of  the  equality  of  brightness  method  over  100  years  after  its  principles 
were  laid  down  for  all  time  (Pierre  Bouguer,  1760,  and  Sir  Benjamin  Thompson, 
Count  of  Rumford,  1793).  However,  we  do  wish  to  say  now  that  Dr.  Johnson  has 
raised  the  question  that  we  conformed  to  all  that  is  essential  in  his  very  elementary 
directions  with  the  exception  that  we  chose  rather  to  follow  the  custom  to  which  we 
know  of  no  exception  either  in  practice  or  recommendation,  of  calculating  the  luminous 
intensities  of  the  light  sources  on  the  basis  of  the  direct  squares  of  the  distances  of  these 
light  sources  from  the  photometer  head,  instead  of  the  inverse  squares.  In  replying 
to  an  advanced  criticism  on  photometric  method,  one  should  not  have  to  point  out 
that  the  law  of  inverse  squares  applies  to  the  intensity  of  illumination  at  different 
distances  from  a  given  source;  while  the  converse  of  this  relation,  namely,  the  direct 
squares,  applies  to  the  comparative  intensities  of  two  sources  which  produce  equal 
illumination  on  a  given  screen  or  photometer  head.  That  is,  the  former  is  used  in  the 
computations  of  intensity  of  illumination:  foot-candles,  meter-candles,  etc.;  and  the 
latter  in  the  computation  of  the  relative  intensities  of  light  sources :  candlepower,  lam- 
berts,  millilamberts,  etc. 


1 68  c.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

4.  Also  on  p.  394  Dr.  Johnson  presents  a  table  in  which  it  is 
represented  that  the  measuring  disc  in  the  work  for  which  our  table 
of  results  was  submitted  was  3  cm.  nearer  to  the  observer  than  the 
plane  of  the  screen  containing  the  stimulus  patch.  Applying  the 
law  of  inverse  squares  he  demonstrates  that  the  illumination  of  the 
stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  was  in  case  of  each  light  source 
unequal.  Since  the  colored  lights  were  all  nearer  the  screen  and 
measuring  disc  than  the  standard  white  light  in  proportions  varying 
from  41  /59  to  387  160  (actually  417  59  to  387  106  because,  as  stated 
earlier,  a  sectored  disc  was  used  for  the  lights  requiring  the  greater 
distance  of  setting  from  the  screen),  the  3  cm.  caused  a  greater 
difference  between  the  illumination  of  the  measuring  disc  than  of 
the  stimulus  patch  for  the  colored  lights  than  for  the  white  light  by 
percentages  ranging  from  5.4  to  15.5.  From  the  showing  of  this 
table  without  further  inquiry  into  causes,  it  was  concluded  that 
'the  authors'  procedure  in  making  the  settings  was  faulty,'  the 
*  method  is  insensitive'  and  that  the  evidence  of  agreement  of  the 
two  methods  is  *  spurious,'  for  the  explanation  of  which  latter  point 
there  seems  to  have  been  no  hypothesis  worthy  of  mention  but  that 
the  settings  of  one  method  were  biased  by  a  knowledge  ofthe  settings 
of  the  other — a  smashing  and  uncompromising  arraignment  truly! 
However,  we  beg  in  passing  to  say  a  word  of  this  table  ourselves. 
In  the  first  place,  as  a  matter  of  only  minor  consequence  to  the 
present  discussion,  we  wish  to  point  out  that  in  all  of  the  compu- 
tations given  by  Dr.  Johnson  of  the  deviations  in  per  cent,  from 
proportionality  of  illumination  of  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc, 
errors  have  been  made,  and  that  in  5  out  of  a  total  of  6  cases  ap- 
pearing in  his  table  these  errors  have  ranged  from  1.8  to  1 1  per  cent, 
of  the  correct  value,  with  a  leaning  in  some  of  the  most  important 
cases  towards  the  advantage  of  the  critic.  This,  we  may  be  par- 
doned for  noting,  is  under  the  circumstances  somewhat  surprising, 
and  is  of  value  perhaps  chiefly  in  demonstrating  that  it  is  possible 
for  mistakes  to  occur  even  in  a  critique  levelled  at  the  accuracy  of 
the  work  of  others  without  furnishing  a  justification  for  the  im- 
pugning of  motives  and  integrities.  And  secondly  we  wish  to  state 
that,  as  might  have  been  suspected  by  our  critic  himself,1  the  3  cm. 

xThe  above  statement  is  made  for  the  following  reasons,  (a)  It  is  obvious  on 
a  priori  grounds  to  one  having  even  the  least  rudimentary  knowledge  of  the  principles 
on  which  photometry  is  based,  that  a  just  balance  could  not  be  established  between  the 
colored  and  white  lights  involving  so  wide  a  difference  in  setting  on  the  bar  if  the 
measuring  disc  was  3  cm.  in  front  of  the  photometer  screen.  And  (b)  even  an  approxi- 
mate set-up  of  the  apparatus  with  the  lights  in  position  demonstrates  at  a  glance  that 


HETEROCHROMATIC  PHOTOMETRY  169 

was  a  typographical  error.  In  the  original  data  still  in  our  posses- 
sion, the  distance  of  the  measuring  disc  from  the  screen  is  given  as 
.3  cm.1  When  the  law  of  inverse  squares  is  applied  to  this,  the  dis- 
crepancy of  illumination  of  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  for 
the  distances  used  by  Dr.  Johnson  in  his  computations  ranges  from 
.464  to  1.22  per  cent.,  and  for  the  actual  distances  used,  from  .464 
to  1.03  percent. — an  amount  which  the  experienced  photometrist 
will,  we  think,  grant  is  relatively  negligible  among  the  much  greater 
sources  of  error  present  in  heterochromatic  photometry. 

We  have,  however,  been  sufficiently  curious  to  know  what  results 
would  be  obtained  with  the  measuring  disc  placed  3  cm.  in  front  of 
the  screen  to  repeat  the  work  represented  in  the  original  table  for 
the  four  highest  intensities  with  this  change  in  the  set-up.  Dif- 
ferences from  the  results  quoted  in  the  original  tables — also,  as  it 
happens  for  the  cases  tested,  the  amount  of  deviation  from  agree- 
ment with  the  equality  of  brightness  results — ranged  from  13.5  to 
25  per  cent,  when  the  determination  was  begun  with  the  weaker 
light,  and  from  18.6  to  29  per  cent,  when  the  determination  was 
begun  with  the  stronger  light.2  These  figures  indicate  that  rather 
than  being  remarkable  for  its  insensitivity,  as  is  charged  by  Dr. 
Johnson  on  the  basis  of  too  narrow  a  consideration  of  possibilities 
and  apparently  no  first-hand  knowledge  whatever  of  the  facts  in 
question,  the  method  shows  by  still  another  test  a  very  high  degree 
of  sensitivity. 

5.  The  error  in  our  critic's  final  conclusion  (pp.  395-6)  should  by 
this  time  be  so  obvious  as  to  need  no  comment.  We  will,  therefore, 
rest  our  case  so  far  as  we  recognize  that  a  case  has  existed,  until 
space  can  be  had  for  a  further  presentation  of  results.  In  this 
regard  it  is  hardly  necessary  to  mention  that  we  do  not  consider, 

the  conditions  produced  are  not  compatible  with  the  principles  on  which  the  method 
of  making  the  balance  is  based.  For  example,  when  illuminated  directly  from  the 
lamp  on  the  bar  a  sharp  shadow  is  cast  by  the  disc  on  the  screen,  which  is  plainly 
in  the  view  of  the  observer  at  the  angle  at  which  the  observation  is  made.  This  is  the 
equivalent  of  surrounding  the  disc  with  a  black  band  which  varies  in  width  as  the 
position  of  the  lamp  on  the  bar  is  changed.  This  is  obviously  not  permissible.  In 
fact  the  error  is  of  a  kind  which  is  usually  handled  in  a  note  of  inquiry  to  the  authors. 

1  Also  there  are,  we  might  mention,  a  number  of  witnesses  to  the  set-up  of  the 
apparatus  used  by  us  in  the  work  on  heterochromatic  photometry. 

2  On  account  of  the  limited  space  allowed,  an  explanation  of  why  such  excessive 
deviations  are  obtained  with  this  incorrect  set-up  will  have  to  be  deferred  until  later 
work;  also  the  very  obvious  explanation  of  why  a  greater  distance  of  measuring  disc 
from  screen  was  permissible,  in  fact  pf  advantage,  in  the  work  in  which  the  method 
was  used  to  detect  changes  in  the  diffuse  illumination  of  an  optics-room  (PsvcHOL. 
BULL.,  1913,  10,  p.  371)  than  when  it  was  applied  to  the  rating  of  lights  on  a  bar. 


170  C.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

as  our  critic  seems  to  have  thought,  that  a  place  has  been  won  for 
our  method  among  those  hoary  and  worn  with  service  on  the  basis 
of  a  single  sample  table  appended  to  a  preliminary  description  of 
method  and  apparatus  and  representing  the  results  of  only  one 
observer  for  two  colors  and  only  six  of  the  possible  settings  on  the 
photometer  bar.. 

NOTE. — Dr.  Johnson  mentioned  the  use  of  a  rotator  toequalize  the  light  radiation  in 
different  directions;  also  the  deviations  found  by  Wright  from  Lambert's  law  of  re- 
flection for  mat  surfaces.  Since  neither  of  these  points  was  raised  in  the  original  article, 
it  might  be  inferred  that  they  were  not  known  and  taken  into  account  by  the  authors. 
It  will  probably  not  be  prejudicial  to  either  side  of  the  case  to  mention  here  that  one  of 
the  writers  supervised  the  construction  of  his  first  lamp  rotator  for  work  in  photometry 
in  1901  while  a  teacher  of  physics,  and  is  well  acquainted  with  the  uses  and  need  of  a 
rotator.  Also  in  1903  while  a  graduate  student  of  physics  he  was  assigned  a  study  of 
the  reflection  from  mat  surfaces  as  a  problem  for  investigation,  the  object  being  to 
continue  along  the  lines  mapped  out  by  Wright.  Both  from  his  reading  and  in- 
struction with  regard  to  the  work  of  Wright  and  others,  however,  he  is  totally  unable 
to  concur  in  a  single  comment  that  Dr.  Johnson  has  made  on  the  subject  of  diffuse  re- 
flection in  the  footnote  on  p.  392.  Dr.  Johnson  says:  "Another  source  of  error  which 
the  authors  appear  not  to  have  taken  into  account  may  be  worthy  of  mention.  The 
angles  at  which  the  light  was  diffusely  reflected  into  the  eye  from  the  stimulus  patch 
and  the  disc  at  the  fixation  point  were  not  the  same.  The  percentage  of  incident  light 
reflected  into  the  eye  would  have  been  different,  therefore,  even  if  the  two  surfaces  had 
been  of  the  same  material.  Furthermore,  the  difference  in  percentage  of  incident  light 
reflected  in  the  direction  of  the  eye  is  not  constant  for  any  two  positions  of  the  source. 
Cf.  Wright,  H.  R.,  'Photometry  of  the  Diffuse  Reflection  of  Light  on  Matt  Surfaces,' 
Philos.  Trans.,  1900,  49,  Ser.  5,  pp.  199-216."  Of  the  sentences  quoted  the  second  is 
the  only  one  that  can  be  said  to  be  true.  The  angle  of  emission  e  from  the  stimulus 
patch  in  relation  to  the  eye  was  approximately  o°;  while  for  the  measuring  disc  it  was 
25°.  The  reflection,  therefore,  in  the  direction  of  the  eye  from  a  given  point  or  unit 
surface  in  the  area  fixated  of  the  measuring  disc  was  less  than  that  from  the  stimulus 
patch  by  an  amount  equal  to  the  cosine  of  25°.  Dr.  Johnson,  however,  neglects  to  take 
into  account  in  considering  the  case  presented  by  our  method  that  the  observation  is 
not  confined  to  a  single  point  or  unit  of  area  and  that  the  area  of  surface  viewed  increases 
as  the  secant  (the  reciprocal  of  the  cosine)  of  the  angle  at  which  the  surface  is 
viewed  measured  from  the  normal.  That  is,  the  increase  of  the  area  viewed  just 
compensates  for  the  lessened  amount  of  reflection  from  unit  area.  Nutting,  for  ex- 
ample, says:  "A  red  hot  metal  plate  is  of  the  same  brightness  viewed  at  any  angle  since 
the  foreshortening  of  the  area  just  compensates  for  the  variation  in  the  radiation  from 
a  given  area.  Lambert's  law  holds  for  mat  surfaces  for  both  emitted  and  reflected 
radiation."  Even  the  author  referred  to  by  our  critic,  in  discussing  the  two  possible 
methods  of  making  the  photometric  determination  in  his  investigation  of  the  reflection 
from  mat  surfaces,  says  in  effect  the  same  thing  (cf.  Wright,  p.  205),  so  without  exception 
does  every  other  author  after  whom  we  have  read.  Therefore  when  two  mat  surfaces 
are  observed  whose  areas  are  not  limited,  the  apparent  brightness  of  these  surfaces  is 
the  same  for  different  angles  of  observation  provided  that  the  angle  of  incidence  and 
amount  of  incident  lignt  are  the  same  for  both  surfaces  as  was  the  case  for  the  stimulus 
patch  and  measuring  disc  in  our  work  for  any  one  setting  of  the  light  on  the  bar;  for 


HETEROCHROMAT1C  PHOTOMETRY  1 7 l 

although  the  reflection  from  unit  area  decreases  as  the  cosine  of  the  angle  of  reflection, 
the  area  from  which  the  eye  receives  its  light  increases  as  the  secant  of  the  same  angle; 
from  which  it  follows  that  the  amount  of  light  entering  or  reflected  in  the  direction  of 
the  eye  is  independent  of  the  angle  at  which  the  surface  is  viewed. 

It  is  obvious,  then,  that  Dr.  Johnson's  statement  that  the  percentage  of  incident 
light  reflected  in  the  direction  of  the  eye  would  have  been  different,  even  if  the  two 
surfaces  had  been  of  the  same  material,  is  not  true.  From  this  it  is  equally  obvious 
that  his  next  statement  also  is  not  true,  namely,  that  the  difference  in  the  percentage 
of  incident  light  reflected  in  the  direction  of  the  eye  is  not  constant  for  any  two  posi- 
tions of  the  source,  for  as  shown  above  there  is  no  difference  in  the  percentage  of 
incident  light  reflected  to  the  eye  from  the  two  surfaces  for  any  given  setting  of  the 
light  on  the  bar.  In  other  words,  the  possible  bearing  of  Lambert's  law  and  Wright's 
results  with  regard  to  this  law,  is  not  what  Dr.  Johnson  has  stated  it  to  be.  Just 
what  this  bearing  is  will  be  discussed  further  on  in  this  note.  What  we  wish  to  do 
at  this  point  is  to  show  that  even  if  it  were  true  that  the  percentage  of  incident  light 
reflected  to  the  eye  were  different  for  any  one  setting  of  the  light  on  the  photometer 
bar,  this  would  make  no  difference  whatever  in  the  results  obtained  by  our  method. 
That  is,  if  less  light  were  reflected  to  the  eye  from  the  measuring  disc  than  from  the 
stimulus  patch  for  the  first  light  set  upon  the  bar,  it  would  mean  merely  that  the  coef- 
ficient of  reflection  of  the  measuring  disc  would  have  to  be  reduced  by  a  corresponding 
amount  to  obtain  the  match.  Then  when  the  comparison  light  was  placed  on  the 
bar  and  its  distance  adjusted  until  as  much  light  was  given  to  the  screen  as  was  re- 
ceived from  the  first  light,  the  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc  would  again  match, 
for  neither  the  difference  in  angle  of  reflection  to  the  eye  nor  the  reflection  coefficients 
would  have  been  changed.  Dr.  Johnson's  point,  granting  its  verity,  would  have  appli- 
cation only  if  the  stimulus  patch  were  illuminated  alone  by  one  of  the  lights  and  the 
measuring  disc  by  the  other  and  the  method  of  balancing  consisted  in  bringing  these 
two  surfaces  to  equality — then  it  would  be  necessary  that  each  reflect  to  the  eye  the 
same  percentage  of  the  light  received  by  it;  but  the  point  is  clearly  quite  irrelevant  to  the 
method  described  by  us  in  which  the  two  surfaces  are  illuminated  for  each  judgment  by 
only  one  of  the  lights,  and  the  balance  consists  in  so  adjusting  the  distance  of  the  two 
lights  in  the  successive  judgments  that  the  match  for  the  one  based  on  the  amount  of 
induction  produced  at  the  stimulus  patch  holds  also  for  the  other.  In  this  case  it  is 
important  only  that  the  physical  situation  and  other  factors  be  kept  the  same  for  both 
judgments — not  that  they  be  equal  each  to  each  for  the  single  judgment — for  the  balance 
is  based  on  the  principle  that  if  all  the  factors  are  kept  constant  the  amount  of  induction 
at  the  stimulus  patch  will  always  be  the  same  when  the  same  amounts  of  light  are  re- 
ceived on  the  screen.  It  is  obvious  also  that  the  same  considerations  are  true  with 
regard  to  the  materials  forming  the  stimulus  patch  and  measuring  disc.  Moreover, 
with  reference  to  this  point,  it  may  also  be  said  that  there  was,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  very 
little  difference  in  the  materials  forming  the  two  surfaces;  for  one  sector  of  the  measuring 
disc  was  identical  with  the  stimulus  patch  and  the  other  sector  was  a  darker  gray  of  the 
same  series  of  papers  (Hering's  series  of  standard  grays). 

In  concluding  our  comments  on  this  footnote  which  has  revealed  so  much  of  our 
critic's  point  of  view,  we  will  indicate  briefly  and  only  in  a  general  way  the  relation  of 
Lambert's  law  of  reflection  from  mat  surfaces  and  Wright's  findings  with  regard  to  this 
law  to  the  practical  working  of  our  method.  As  already  shown,  Dr.  Johnson's  criticism 
was  based  both  on  an  erroneous  understanding  of  this  law  as  applied  to  the  making  of 
the  photometric  judgment  by  any  method  whatsoever  and  on  a  wrong  conception  of 


172  C.  E.  FERREE  AND  GERTRUDE  RAND 

the  principles  of  the  method  criticized.  Our  actual  chance  of  error  in  terms  of  Lam- 
bert's law  is  that  the  angle  of  incidence  (Johnson's  'difference  in  angle  of  reflection' 
has  nothing  whatever  to  do  with  photometry  from  mat  surfaces)  on  the  stimulus  patch 
and  its  surrounding  field  is  different  for  the  light  from  the  standard  and  comparison 
lamps  when  they  are  of  different  intensities  and  a  different  setting  on  the  bar  is  required 
to  establish  the  photometric  balance.  That  is,  according  to  Lambert's  law  the  intensity 
of  the  illumination  of  the  stimulus  patch  and  its  surrounding  field  is  proportional  to 
the  cosine  of  the  angle  of  incidence  (the  cosine  i ). 

Now  considering  for  the  sake  of  simplicity  the  stimulus  patch  alone,  the  variation 
in  the  cosine  of  the  angle  of  the  incident  light  for  the  entire  range  covered  in  the  work 
criticized  from  the  least  to  the  greatest  distance  of  the  source  of  light  from  the  screen, 
falls  within  I  per  cent.  While  this  would  mean  only  a  comparatively  slight  difference 
in  the  induction  situation  from  the  lights  compared,  we  have  from  the  beginning  in 
our  own  thinking  frankly  faced  it  as  a  small  source  of  error  in  case  the  reductions  of  the 
light  on  the  screen  are  produced  by  changing  the  position  of  the  lamps  on  the  bar. 
However,  it  would  not  enter  in  at  all,  as  will  be  readily  seen,  if  the  reduction  of  light  is 
produced  by  means  of  a  sectored  disc  or  any  device:  absorbing  screen,  Nicol's  prism, 
grating,  etc.,  which  does  not  change  the  distance  of  the  source  of  light  from  the  screen 
and,  therefore,  the  angle  of  incidence  of  the  light  on  the  stimulus  patch.  In  this 
regard  it  should  be  remembered  too  that  our  photometer  is  no  more  at  fault  in  physical 
principle  than  the  equality  of  brightness  photometer  after  Rumford  as  ordinarily  con- 
structed, in  which  also  the  angle  of  incidence  is  changed  with  a  change  of  the  position  of 
the  light  on  the  bar — not  so  much  at  fault  perhaps,  for  compensating  factors  operate 
in  our  method  of  getting  the  balance  which  are  not  present  in  the  Rumford  method. 
The  relation  of  Wright's  results  to  the  situation  described  here  is  that  he  found  that 
there  are  certain  small  deviations  from  the  law  of  the  cosine  i  as  the  angle  of  incidence 
is  changed.  Now  just  how  great  the  chance  of  error  is  in  our  method  from  the  law  of 
the  cosine  i  considered  in  relation  with  the  results  of  Wright  it  is  utterly  impossible  to 
estimate  with  any  acceptable  degree  of  precision  from  the  principles  involved  for  the 
following  reasons:  (a)  The  surrounding  field  as  well  as  the  stimulus  patch  must  be 
taken  into  account  in  applying  the  law  of  cosines.  The  difference  in  the  angle  of  in- 
cidence for  the  different  points  in  this  field  vary  for  any  two  positions  of  the  light  on  the 
bar — towards  zero  as  a  limit,  for  example,  for  the  points  between  the  stimulus  patch 
and  the  end  of  the  bar,  and  differently  in  other  directions.  (£)  The  effect  is  not  direct 
but  operates  through  induction,  the  quantitative  relations  of  which  are  not  definitely 
known.  And  (c)  Wright  apparently  considered  it  worth  while  to  make  no  change  of 
angle  of  incidence  smaller  than  20°,  while  the  entire  range  of  variation  of  this  angle  in 
our  work  from  greatest  to  least  distance  of  lamp  from  screen  was  for  the  colorless 
light  2°  and  for  both  the  colored  and  colorless  lights  5°. 

Rather,  therefore,  than  indulge  in  bootless  speculation  in  regard  to  the  possibilities 
of  error  from  these  sources,  it  is  obviously  much  more  to  the  point  to  get  some  empirical 
measure  of  their  effective  importance.  The  effective  importance  of  this  factor  along 
with  others  not  mentioned  by  Dr.  Johnson  may  be  checked  up  (a)  by  a  comparison  of 
results  in  the  average  with  those  obtained  by  the  equality  of  brightness  method  (see 
table  in  original  article,  p.  9);  and  (b)  still  more  definitely  and  directly  by  comparing 
the  results  obtained  by  the  method  when  the  reductions  of  the  light  on  the  screen  are 
produced  by  changing  the  distances  of  the  sources  from  the  screen  and  when  the  dis- 
tance of  the  source  and,  therefore,  the  angle  of  incidence  of  the  light  is  kept  constant 
and  the  reductions  are  made  by  means  of  a  sectored  disc  (see  Table  I.  of  this  discussion). 


HE  TEROCHROMA  TIC  PHO  TOME  TRY  1 73 

Even  had  these  comparisons  not  been  made,  the  probable  relative  unimportance  of 
these  sources  of  error  as  compared  with  the  high  variable  error  obtained  for  one  or  any 
small  number  of  determinations  by  the  equality  of  brightness  method,  should,  we 
think,  be  obvious  to  all  who  have  a  working  familiarity  with  the  latter  method  in  hetero- 
chromatic  photometry.  On  the  point  of  sureness  of  principle,  moreover,  it  is  instructive 
to  compare  the  agreements  of  the  induction  and  equality  of  brightness  methods  shown 
in  the  tables  referred  to  above  with  those  obtained  for  the  equality  of  brightness  and 
flicker  methods,  for  example,  for  lights  presenting  the  same  amount  of  color  difference. 
BRYN  MAWR  COLLEGE, 

C.  E.  FERREE, 
GERTRUDE  RAND. 

[The  above  discussion,  which  exceeds  our  usual  limits,  has  been 
accepted  by  the  Editors  in  order  that  the  authors  might  have  ample 
opportunity  to  clear  up  the  points  raised  in  Dr.  Johnson's  NOTE. 
The  questions  at  issue  are  so  specialized  and  technical  that  we  be- 
lieve it  unprofitable  to  continue  the  discussion  in  the  pages  of  the 
REVIEW.  A  committee  of  experts  acceptable  to  both  parties  may 
be  suggested  as  the  best  means  of  settling  any  differences  which  re- 
main between  the  writers  and  their  critic. — THE  EDITORS.] 


THE   STANFORD   (1915)   AND  THE  VINELAND   (1911) 
REVISIONS   OF  THE   BINET  SCALE 

A  brief  analysis  of  the  Stanford  and  Vineland  revisions  is  here 
attempted  in  order  to  indicate  a  few  of  the  chief  points  of  dif- 
ference. 

A  hasty  review  of  the  Stanford  revised  scale  gives  one  the 
impression  that  it  is  much  more  difficult  throughout.1  The  exten- 
sion of  the  scale  to  age  19%  (superior  adult)is  certainly  a  commend- 
able advance. 

The  scale  begins  at  age  three  and  each  age  contains  six  tests, 
in  addition  to  from  one  to  three  alternate  tests  for  each  year  up  to 
age  ten.  The  placing  of  six  tests  in  each  year  permits  assigning  a 
two  months'  value  to  each  test.  There  are  no  tests  for  age  n,  the 
only  other  ages  listed  being  12,  14,  16,  and  18.  Since  there  are  no 
tests  for  age  n,  the  eight  tests  in  age  12  are  each  made  to  count 
toward  three  months  mental  age,  yielding  a  total  value  of  two 
years.  By  this  means  tests  for  14,  16  and  18,  six  per  year,  are 
made  to  cover  without  break  the  range  of  mental  development 
from  12  to  19^. 

The  Vineland  revision  consists  of  49  tests  for  the  ages  between 
3  and  12.  Covering  the  same  period  in  the  Stanford  revision  they 
number  56,  with  13  additional  questions  which  may  be  used  as 
alternates. 

In  the  following  tables  the  evolution  through  which  the  Vine- 
land  revision  passes  is  indicated  test  for  test.  Tests  not  in  the 
Vineland  (1911)  are  printed  in  italics. 

VINELAND  (1911)  STANFORD  (1915) 

Age— Test 

Age  III.    Test  I — Pointg.  eyes,  etc.. .  .remains,  .becomes III-i 

"     2 — Rpts.  6  syll remains,  .becomes III-6 

"     3 — Rpts.  2  nos omitted 

"     4 — Enumer.  of  pic remains .  .becomes III-3 

"     5 — Knows  name remains . .  becomes IH~5 

Vineld.IV-i  becomes.... III-4 
"       IV-2        "       ....III-2 
"       IV-3        "       ....III-A.  i 
1  See  foot-note,  p.  179. 

'74 


REVISIONS  OF  THE  BINET  SCALE  175 

VINELAND  (1911)  STANFORD  (1915) 

Age  IV.    Test  I — Knows  sex. .  shifted  to  III-4 
"     2— Recog.  key, 

etc "       "  III-2 

"     3— Rpts.snos..      "       "III-A.i 

"    4 — Comprs.  lines remains . .  becomes IV-i 

Klmns.  Form  Discr.. . .  =  IV-2 

Vineld.V-4 =  IV-3 

"      V-2 =IV-4 

Binet  Compr.  I  deg =  IV~S 

Stanfd.  4  digits =  IV-6 

Vineld.  V-3 =  IV-A.  I 

Age  V.    Test  i — Compares  wts remains . .  becomes V-i 

"     2 — Copies  sq..  .  .shifted  to  IV~4 
"    3— Rpts.  ii  syll.     "       "  IV-A.  i 
"    4— Counts  4c...      "       "  IV-3 

"    5 — "Patience" remains,  .becomes V-g 

Vineld.  VII-s =  V-2 

"      VI-s =  V-3 

"      VI-2 =  V-4 

"      VI-3 =  V-6 

Binet,  age =  V-A.  i 

Age  VI.    Test  I — A.  M.-P.  M remains . .  becomes VI-A.  i 

"     2 — Definit'ns,  use . .  shifted  to  V~4 

"     3— 3  direct'ns "       "V-6 

"     4 — R.  hand,  L.  ear remains . .  becomes VI-I 

"    5 — Aesthet.  Comp.. shifted  to  V-3 

Vineld.  VII-3 =  VI-2 

"      VII-i =  VI-3 

"       X-4(istser.).  =  VI-4 

"       X-i(part)....  -VI-S 

Stanfd.  16-18  syll =  VI-6 

Age  VII.    Test  i— Counts  I3c.  .  .shifted  to  VI~3 

!     2 — Descr.  pic remains . .  becomes =  VII-2 

"     3 — Unfin.  pic shifted  to  VI-2 

"    4 — Copies  Diamd remains .  .becomes =  VII-6 

"     s— Colors shifted  to  V-2 

Binet,  fingers =  VII-I 

Vineld.  VIII-5 =  VII-3 

Stanfd.  bow-knot =  VII-4 

Vineld.  VIII-i =  VII-S 

"      VIII-3 =  VII-A.  i 

Stanfd.  rpt.  3  no.  bkwd.  =  VII-A.  2 


1 76  SAMUEL  C.  KOHS 

VINELAND  (1911)  STANFORD  (1915) 

Age  VIII.    Test  I— Differences .  shifted  to  VII-S 

"     2 — 20-1,  bkwds remains,  .becomes VIII-2 

"     3 — Rpts.  days, 

shifted  to  VII-A.  i 
"     4 — Counts  stamps, 

shifted  to  IX-A.  2 
"    5 — Rpts.  5  nos., 

shifted  to  VII-3 

Stanfd.  ball-fid =  VIII-i 

Vineld.  X-4  (2d.  sr.)  .  =  VIII-3 

Binet,  similar =  VIII-4 

Vineld.  IX-2 =  VIII-5 

Stanfd.  vocab.  20 =  VIII-6 

Vineld.  X-i  (part). . . .  =  VIII-A.  i 
Binet,  dictation =  VIII-A.  2 

Age  IX.    Test  I — Change  20-4 remains . .  becomes IX~3 

"     2 — Superior  def . .  shifted  to  VIII-5 

1     3 — Date remains . .  becomes IX-i 

"     4— Months "       ..       "       IX-A.i 

"     s— Arrange  wts "       ..       "       IX-2 

Stan.  rpt.  4  no.  bkwd.  .  =  IX~4 

Vineld.  X-$ =  IX-5 

"      XI-4 =IX-6 

"      VIII-4 =  IX-A.  2 

Age  X.    Test  I — Money  (part) .  .  shifted  to  VI~5 
(part) 

shifted  to  VIII-A.  i 

(part) omitted 

c     2 — Design remains . .  becomes =  X~3 

"     3— Rpts.  6  nos "      . .       "       =  X-A.  i 

'     4 — Comprh.  1st.  ser., 

shifted  to  VI~4 
pt.  2nd.  ser., 

shifted  to  VIII-3 

pt.  2nd.  ser remains . .  becomes =  X— 5 

"     5 — Sentence shifted  to  IX-$ 

Stanfd.  vocab.  30 =  X-i 

Vineld.  XI-i =  X-2 

Binet,  8  memor =  X~4 

Vineld.  XI-3 =  X-6 

"      XII-3 =  X-A.  2 

Healy  Constr.  Puz =  X-A.  3 

Age  XL    Test  I — Absurdity —  shifted  to  X-2 
"     2 — Simple  sent.  .      "       "  IX~5 

«    3_6o  wds "       "  X-6  No  XI 

"     4— Rhymes "       "  IX-6 

"     5 — Dissected  sent.    "       "  XII-4 


RE V 1 SI 'ON S  OF  THE  BINET  SCALE 


177 


VINELAND  (1911)  STANFORD  (1915) 

Age  XII.    Test  I— Rpts.  7  nos., 

shifted  to  XIV-A.  i 

:     2 — Abstract  def remains,  .becomes XII-2 

"     3— Rpts.  23  syll., 

shifted  to  X-A.  2 

'    4 — Line  suggest omitted 

"     5— Problems. . .  shifted  to  XIV-4 

Stanfd.  vocab.  40 =  XII-i 

"      ball-fid,  sup.  . .  =  XII-3 

Vineld.XI-5 =  XII-4 

Stanfd.  fables =  XII-s 

"       rpt.sno.bk...  =  XII-6 

Vineld.XV-i =XII-7 

Stanfd.  sim.  3  thgs =  XII-8 


Age  XIV. 


No  TESTS  FOR  XIV 


Stanfd.  vocab.  50 =  XIV-i 

"  induct,  test =  XIV-2 

Vineld.  Adult-4 =  XIV-3 

"  XII-s =  XIV-4 

Stanfd.  arith.  prob =  XIV~5 

Vineld.  XV-2 =  XIV-6 

"  XII-i =  XIV-A.  i 


Age  XV.    Test  i — Interp.  pic. .  shifted  to  XII-7 
"     2— Clock  hands     "       "  XIV-6 

"     3— Code "       "  XVI-6 

"    4 — Opposites omitted 

Age  XVI.     (Average  Adult) 


Adult- 


Test  I— Ctg.  paper. . .  shifted  to  XVIII-2 
"     2 — Reversed  triang omitted 


3— Diff.  abstr.  wds.  shifted  toXVI~3 
4— Diff.  pres.  kg.  shifted  to  XIV-3 
5— Sense  select. .      "       "  XVIII-4 


No  TESTS  FOR  XV 

Stanfd.  vocab.  65 =  XVI-i 

"       interp.  fables..  =  XVI-2 

Vineld.  Adult-3 =  XVI-3 

Stanfd.  enclsd.  boxs.. . .  =  XVI-4 

"       rep.  6  no.  bk...  =  XVI-5 

Vineld.  XV-3 =  XVI-6 

Stanfd.  rep.  28 syll..  =  XVI-A.  i 

"     comp.phys.rel.  —  XVI-A.  2 


Age  XVIII.     (Superior  Adult)  Stanfd.  vocab.  75 =  XVIII-i 

Vineld.  Adult-i =  XVIII-2 

Stanfd.  rept.  8  no =  XVIII-3 

Vineld.  Adult-s =  XVIII-4 

Stanfd.  rep.  7  no.  bk...  =  XVIII-5 

"       ingen.  test =  XVIII-6 

Summarizing  the  above  tables: 
In  age  3,  four  tests  remain  and  one  is  omitted. 
In  age  4,  one  test  remains  and  three  are  shifted  to  an  earlier  age, 

being  too  easy  for  four-year-olds. 


i78 


SAMUEL  C.  KOHS 


In  age  5,  two  tests  remain  and  three  are  shifted  to  age  4,  being  too 

easy  for  children  of  five. 

In  age  6,  two  tests  remain  and  three  are  shifted  to  age  5. 
In  age  7,  two  tests  remain,  two  are  shifted  to  age  6,  and  one  to 

age  5. 
In  age  8,  one  test  remains,  three  are  shifted  to  age  7,  and  one  to 

age  9. 

In  age  9,  four  tests  remain  and  one  is  shifted  to  age  8. 
In  age  10,  two  tests  and  a  portion  of  a  third  remains,  one  test  is 

shifted  to  age  9,  one  part  each  of  two  tests  is  shifted  to  age  6, 

and  one  part  each  of  two  tests  is  shifted  to  age  8. 
In  age  n,  all  the  tests  are  shifted,  there  being  no  corresponding 

n-year  group  in  the  Stanford  revision:  two  are  shifted  to  age  9, 

two  to  age  10,  and  one  to  age  12. 
In  age  12,  one  test  remains,  one  is  omitted,  and  three  are  shifted: 

one  to  age  10,  and  two  to  age  14. 
In  age  15,  one  test  is  omitted  and  the  other  three  are  shifted  as 

follows:  one  to  age  12,  one  to  age  14,  and  one  to  age  16. 
Of  the  "Adult"  tests,  one  is  omitted,  one  becomes  a  test  for  age 

14,  one  a  test  for  age  16,  and  two  are  tests  in  age  18. 

The  above  changes  are  indicated  in  the  following  table: 

TESTS 


Shifted 

Age 

No  Change 

Omitted 

Earlier 

Later 

Total 

i 

2 

3 

4 

i 

2 

3 

4 

I 

4 

i 

3 

s 

2 

3 

6 

2 

3 

7 

2 

2 

I 

8 

I 

3 

I 

9 

4 

i 

10 

| 

i 

1 

1 

ii 

— 

2 

2 

I 

12 

i 

I 

I 

2 

IS 

— 

I 

I 

I 

I 

Adult1 

3 

I 

1 

Total  

22i 

41 

19 

5l 

I 

I 

3 

2 

58 

Percent.  .  .  . 

38.5 

7-5 

32.8 

9-8 

i-7 

I.I 

5-2 

3-4 

IOO.O 

1(16-18)! 

It  will  be  observed  that  between  3  and  7  years  twelve  tests 
have  been  removed  to  earlier  years,  and  no  tests  to  later  years. 


REVISIONS  OF  THE  BINET  SCALE  179 

These  changes  will  dispose  of  the  criticism  that  the  lower  end  of 
the  scale  is  too  easy.  But  between  8  and  12  years  143  tests  have 
been  removed  to  earlier  years,  and  only  five  tests  to  later  years, 
thus  making  the  scale  still  more  difficult  at  its  upper  end.1 

38.5  percent  of  the  scale  remains  unchanged.  7.5  percent  of 
the  tests  in  the  Vineland  revision  are  omitted.  45.4  percent  of  the 
tests  are  found  too  easy  for  their  respective  ages  and  are  shifted  to 
earlier  years,  32.8  percent  being  placed  in  the  next  earlier  age. 
7.6  percent  of  the  tests  are  found  too  difficult  for  their  respective 
ages  and  are  consequently  placed  in  later  years. 

No  test  is  placed  more  than  four  years  below  its  original  position. 
No  test  is  placed  more  than  two  years  above  its  original  position. 

It  might  be  well  to  keep  in  mind  that  the  tests  appearing  only 
in  the  Stanford  revision  have  not  been  considered  in  the  above 
tabulation  and  in  the  summarization  of  the  test  data.  For  that 
reason  some  of  the  statements  made  need  not  be  regarded  as 
seriously  critical. 

Using  the  Stanford  revision,  Terman  and  his  collaborators 
found  that  (a)  by  using  the  intelligence  quotient  one  can  transform 
the  'age  grade  scale'  into  a  *  point  scale'  automatically,  should  one 
prefer  expressing  the  development  of  intelligence  in  that  manner. 
"As  such  it  would  seem  to  be  greatly  superior  to  the  Yerkes- 
Bridges  scale,  for  it  includes  a  much  larger  number  of  tests  and  its 
points  have  definite  meaning  and  equal  value."  (b)  Sex-differ- 
ences are  found  to  be  so  small  as  to  be  negligible  for  practical 
purposes,  (c)  The  younger  the  children  the  greater  the  influence 
of  social  status  on  intelligence. 

The  Stanford  revision  is  to  be  welcomed  in  its  effort  toward  a 
scale  free  from  those  objections  which  are  still  being  quixotically 
hurled  against  it.  SAMUEL  C.  KOHS 

STANFORD  UNIVERSITY 

1  The  following  article,  however,  "  L.  M.  Terman  and  H.  E.  Knollin:  Some  Problems 
Relating  to  the  Detection  of  Borderline  Cases  of  Mental  Deficiency"  /.  Psycho- 
Asthen.  1915,  20:  1-15,  coming  to  the  notice  of  the  writer  after  the  above  was  in 
type,  shows  the  reverse  to  be  true.  Tabulating  the  reactions  of  borderline  subjects 
(mental  ages  by  the  Stanford  Revision  between  12  and  14,  — 104  adults)  they  found 
that  by  the  Vineland  Revision,  weighted  for  tests  above  12,  the  median  age  for  these 
subjects  was  reduced  as  much  as  one  and  one-half  years,  and  with  the  tests  unweighted 
the  reduction  was  greater,  namely  two  years.  It  ought  also  be  mentioned,  in  this 
connection,  that  the  procedure  and  scoring  of  quite  a  number  of  tests  have  been 
changed  in  the  Stanford  Revision.  Consequently  a  strict  analysis  of  test  displacement 
must  take  these  facts  into  consideration.  Change  of  procedure  or  scoring  may  so 
modify  the  statistical  data  obtained  for  a  test  as  to  warrant  its  transfer  to  some  lower 
year  without  necessarily  increasing  the  difficulty  of  the  scale  at  that  particular  point. 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  3  May,  1917 


THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


THE   NATURE  OF  MENTAL  PROCESS 

BY  HARVEY  CARR 

University  of  Chicago 

This  paper  proposes  the  somewhat  unorthodox  view  that 
the  mental  functions  with  which  psychology  concerns  itself 
are  in  reality  psychophysical,  and  at  times  neural,  activities^ 
and  that  psychology  shall  study  and  attempt  to  comprehend 
these  functions  in  their  entirety.  The  author  adopted  this 
conception  of  the  nature  of  mental  process  several  years  ago 
and  is  convinced  from  his  teaching  experience  that  such  a 
mode  of  treatment  possesses  certain  distinct  advantages. 

The  conception  may  be  contrasted  with  the  more  ortho- 
dox *  subjective'  view  which  postulates  psychophysical  paral- 
lelism but  which  confines  its  efforts  exclusively  to  a  compre- 
hension of  the  conscious  or  subjective  aspect  of  these  psycho- 
physical  events.  Such  a  psychology  studies  color,  sound, 
taste,  and  pain  as  experiential  results  but  contends  that  the 
neural  correlates  of  these  sensory  experiences  belong  to  the 
domain  of  physiology.  An  emotion  as  a  psychological  phe- 
nomenon is  described  and  defined  in  terms  of  sensational  and 
affective  processes  subjectively  regarded;  the  neural  events 
involved  in  an  emotion  are  relegated  to  the  domain  of  physi- 
ology. The  acts  of  memory,  imagination,  reasoning  and  will 
in  so  far  as  psychology  is  concerned  with  them  consist  merely 
of  those  aspects  which  can  be  immediately  experienced;  the 
neural  events  involved  in  the  acts  are  quite  important  but 
their  consideration  involves  a  trespass  into  domains  right- 
fully belonging  to  another  science.  Psychology  thus  deals 
exclusively  with  the  purely  conscious  or  psychic  as  opposed' 
to  the  nervous  and  material-  Psychology  is  differentiated 

181 


1 82  HARVEY  CARR 

from  the  material  sciences  in  virtue  of  a  peculiar  subject 
matter  and  a  peculiar  method  of  apprehending  its  data. 

Our  conception  also  accepts  psychophysical  parallelism  as 
a  working  hypothesis;  it  contends  that  psychology  shall  study 
psychophysical  processes  in  their  entirety,  and  that  it  shall 
include  within  its  domain  activities  which  lie  outside  the  field 
of  consciousness.  Psychology  will  study  emotions,  and  acts 
of  reasoning,  memory  and  will,  but  it  will  define  and  envisage 
these  acts  as  psychophysical  processes,  and  attempt  to  com- 
prehend the  neural  events  involved  as  well  as  those  aspects 
immediately  experienced. 

The  conception  allows  a  division  of  the  field  of  organic 
functions  between  the  sciences  of  biology,  physiology  and 
psychology  along  natural  lines  of  cleavage  based  upon  differ- 
ences of  interest,  training  and  technical  procedure.  Irre- 
spective of  definitions,  psychology  has  been  concerned  with 
an  ultimate  comprehension  of  those  operations  by  which  an 
organism  in  virtue  of  its  previous  experience  is  enabled  to 
adapt  itself  to  a  complex  and  variable  environment.  Phys- 
iology and  biology  have  been  interested  in  other  types  of 
functional  activity — different  in  character,  evolutionary  his- 
tory, and  biological  significance.  The  three  sciences  represent 
distinctions  which  appeal  to  radically  different  types  of  human 
motive  and  scientific  interest,  and  which  necessitate  different 
sorts  of  training  and  technical  equipment.  This  paper  is  not 
concerned  with  the  formulation  of  an  exact  definition  de- 
limiting the  boundaries  of  the  three  sciences. 

The  conception  is  unorthodox  only  in  relation  to  prevailing 
definitions  of  psychology.  To  my  mind  it  is  essentially  in 
harmony  with  the  dominant  point  of  view  of  the  science,  and 
it  is  not  wholly  inconsistent  with  much  of  current  practice. 
Sciences  have  a  way  of  developing  and  outgrowing  their  def- 
initions. Practice  and  attainment  often  fail  to  square  with 
theory  and  definition.  The  subjective  conception  of  the 
nature  of  mental  process  (mental  as  opposed  to  material) 
originated  from  philosophical  interests  at  a  time  when  a  dual- 
istic  conception  of  the  human  organism  prevailed.  At 
present  the  prevailing  point  of  view  in  the  science  is  biological, 


THE  NATURE  OF  MENTAL  PROCESS  i§3 

— a  view  which  emphasizes  the  essentially  unitary  character 
of  the  human  organism.  The  science  is  interested  in  certain 
modes  of  adjustment,  and  any  adequate  understanding  of 
these  processes  of  adjustment  must  necessitate  a  compre- 
hension of  the  acts  in  their  entirety.  A  division  of  any  act  of 
adjustment  into  its  material  and  conscious  aspects  with  the 
consequent  treatment  of  but  one  component  certainly  gives  a 
very  inadequate  comprehension  of  the  phenomenon  in  ques- 
tion, and  introduces  a  distinction  which  is  not  only  without 
value,  but  which  is  likely  to  involve  the  student  in  many  dis- 
tracting perplexities.  Our  proposition,  however,  will  neces- 
sitate no  radical  changes  in  much  of  current  modes  of  pro- 
cedure. As  a  matter  of  fact,  many  psychologies  treat  mental 
operations  as  psychophysical  processes  with  only  occasional 
lapses  into  a  consistency  with  their  subjective  definitions  of 
the  science.  It  is  our  definitions  that  need  revision,  a 
revision  in  harmony  with  current  tendencies  and  ideals. 

The  conception  allows  of  a  matter  of  fact  treatment  of  the 
cause  and  effect  relations  in  mental  activity.  One  can  assert 
that  behavior  is  influenced  by  previous  acts  of  memory  or  will 
and  mean  exactly  what  we  say  and  what  the  unsophisticated 
mind  understands  by  the  statement.  Psychologists  will  not 
be  compelled  to  add  for  the  benefit  of  the  sophisticated  quali- 
fying phrases  to  the  effect  that  although  they  asserted  a 
causal  influence  of  a  mental  act,  yet  they  really  did  not 
mean  it,  but  were  forced  to  employ  such  statements  by  certain 
inadequacies  of  language.  Any  conception  which  allows  of  a  I 
natural  and  matter  of  fact  treatment  of  the  causal  category  in  I 
mental  operations  is  at  least  deserving  of  respect.  The  new' 
definition  of  the  mental  will  permit  a  restatement  and  a 
solution  of  the  mind-body  problem  more  in  accordance  with 
common  sense.  Interactionism  is  logically  possible;  in 
accordance  with  popular  belief  we  may  say  that  our  mind  is 
influenced  by  bodily  conditions  and  that  our  mind  is  also  an 
effective  influence  upon  bodily  activities,  for  mind  and  body 
have  been  so  conceived  and  defined  in  relation  to  each  other 
that  such  statements  are  no  longer  logically  or  factually  im- 
possible. With  our  definition  the  distinction  of  mind  and 
body  is  merely  a  distinction  of  two  systems  of  organic  function. 


184  HARVEY  CARR 

Our  definition  will  include  within  the  domain  of  psychology 
I  the  non-conscious  components  of  mental  life.  I  refer  to  such 
phenomena  as  retention,  memory  disintegration,  conflict  of 
impulses,  Aufgabe,  unconscious  motivation,  the  concept  of 
habit,  and  the  wealth  of  subterranean  activities  brought  to 
notice  by  the  investigations  of  abnormal  psychology.  The 
subjective  psychologies  have  assumed  several  attitudes  toward 
these  phenomena.  Some  are  logically  consistent  with  their 
presuppositions  and  attempt  to  ignore  such  intruders.  Others 
admit  the  significance  of  these  data  for  their  purposes,  but 
consistently  remind  their  readers  that  after  all  these  phe- 
nomena really  belong  to  the  domain  of  physiology.  Others 
include  these  events  within  the  domain  of  their  science,  but 
feel  compelled  by  motives  of  consistency  to  impose  upon  these 
processes  some  sort  of  a  *  conscious  label.'  Witness  such 
terms  as  unconscious,  subconscious,  co-conscious,  psychical 
dispositions,  etc.  These  are  not  merely  negative  terms, 
equivalent  to  neural;  they  have  a  positive  significance. 
Since  these  activities  have  a  mental  significance  and  since  the 
mental  must  also  be  conscious,  these  acts  must  be  conceived  in 
such  a  way  as  to  possess  certain  positive  characteristics  of 
conscious  process.  For  my  part,  I  prefer  the  remaining 
possible  mode  of  procedure,  viz.,  to  revise  my  definition  of  the 
nature  of  mental  process  in  such  a  way  as  to  include  such  data. 
The  subjective  conception  of  mental  process  as  something 
immaterial  constitutes  an  inadequate  tool  for  the  physician 
in  his  attempt  to  comprehend  the  nature  of  the  mental,  or 
functional  disorders.  Watson,  in  a  recent  article,1  has  as- 
serted his  inability  to  understand  the  medical  concept  of 
mental  disease.  He  cites  a  case  which  was  diagnosed  as 
being  ( purely  mental,'  and  which  was  described  and  defined 
wholly  in  conscious  terms.  Watson  gives  the  impression 
that  the  physician  was  of  the  opinion  that  this  disorder  could 
not  in  any  manner  be  stated  in  neural  terms,  that  it  was  a 
disorder  exclusively  on  the  conscious  plane  without  neural 
counterpart.  Such  a  conception  of  the  nature  of  the  so-called 
mental  diseases  is  of  course  foreign  to  current  psychological 

1  'Behavior  and  the  Concept  of  Mental  Disease,'  /.  of  Phil.,  Psychol.,  &c.t  1916, 
13,  589- 


THE  NATURE  OF  MENTAL  PROCESS  i§5 

doctrines,  and  I  doubt  very  much  that  such  a  view  is  uni- 
versally prevalent  in  the  medical  profession.  I  am  willing 
to  admit  that  this  and  similar  crude  and  preposterous  con- 
ceptions are  to  be  met  with,  but,  unlike  Watson,  I  am  inclined 
to  place  the  blame  for  this  unfortunate  state  of  affairs  upon 
psychology  rather  than  upon  medicine.  Medicine  has  merely 
adopted  current  conceptions.  Psychology  must  be  held  re- 
sponsible forthe  factthat  betterand  more  adequate  conceptions 
were  not  available.  Given  a  conception  of  mind  as  something 
non-nervous  and  non-material,  crude  notions  of  the  nature  of 
a  mental  disease  must  result.  The  mental  will  be  distin- 
guished from  other  diseases  in  terms  of  immaterial  vs.  ma- 
terial instead  of  functional  vs.  organic.  The  conception 
needlessly  introduces  into  the  discussion  of  mental  disease 
and  its  treatment  the  old  philosophical  question  of  the 
relation  of  mind  and  body  stated  again  in  terms  of  the  con- 
scious vs.  the  physiological,  or  neural.  Certainly  the  in- 
jection of  such  philosophical  questions  in  discussions  of  the 
treatment  of  mental  disease  adds  nothing  of  any  positive  value, 
introduces  a  perplexing  distraction,  and  to  my  mind  is  wholly 
unnecessary.  The  old  philosophical  problem  vanishes  at 
once  if  we  start  out  with  the  assumption  that  the  disordered  ^- 
mental  functions  are  in  reality  psychophysical  events. 

The  psychophysical  conception  of  mental  process  offers  a  \ 
mediating  point  of  contact  for  the  two  extremes  of  subjectiv-  \ 
ism  and  behaviorism.  Such  a  view  permits  the  widest 
latitude  as  to  methods  of  approach;  it  permits  mental  processes 
to  be  studied  from  the  standpoint  of  immediate  experience,  of 
objective  observation,  or  of  clinical  data.  This  suggestion 
of  a  common  ground  for  the  subjectivists  and  the  objectivists, 
I  am  well  aware,  will  evoke  no  approval  from  either  of  the 
warring  camps.  This  phase  of  the  argument  is  designed 
exclusively  for  the  benefit  of  the  neutrals.  Our  program  will 
differ  from  that  of  the  subjectivists  in  allowing  an  objective 
mode  of  approach  to  the  problems  of  psychology;  it  will  differ 
from  behaviorism  in  two  respects:  it  admits  that  the  study  of 
conscious  data  has  given  us  much  useful  knowledge  of  the 
nature  of  mental  operations  and  that  further  progress  is 


1 86  HARVEY  CARR 

possible  in  the  future.  Behaviorism  as  defined  logically 
includes  the  whole  field  of  organic  function.  Psychology 
should  be  content  with  a  more  modest  program  and  make  a 
more  reasonable  division  of  the  field  of  functional  activity 
among  the  sciences  of  psychology,  biology,  and  physiology. 

The  conception  will  modify  our  attitude  toward  the  pur- 
poses and  methods  of  comparative  psychology.  The  sub- 
jectivist  to  be  consistent  must  define  the  object  of  comparative 
psychology  as  a  reconstruction  of  the  inner  life  of  an  animal. 
Such  a  program  appeals  to  some  minds;  to  other  minds  it  is 
repellent.  The  latter  are  impressed  with  the  insuperable 
difficulties  and  limitations  of  the  interpretative  process,  and 
are  inclined  to  regard  any  results  achieved  as  somewhat  futile 
even  if  logically  valid.  Our  conception  makes  possible  for 
those  who  prefer  it  a  purely  objective  or  behavioristic  science 
of  comparative  psychology,  and  yet  permits  others  to  recon- 
struct the  conscious  life  of  organisms  if  they  so  desire. 

An  exclusively  subjective  psychology  is  prone  to  meet 
certain  needless  difficulties  in  its  presentation.  The  psycho- 
logical discussion  of  a  mental -event  is  usually  followed  by  an 
explanation  in  terms  of  neural  mechanisms  which  are  labelled 
physiological.  The  psychological  process  viewed  by  itself 
impresses  the  mind  of  the  student  as  a  peculiarly  inert  and 
unimportant  thing.  When  the  neural  mechanism  is  now 
added,  the  process  takes  on  life  and  significance;  mental 
processes  can  now  do  things  and  be  effective  instruments  of 
organic  adjustment.  Moreover,  the  neural  chain  of  events  is, 
by  hypothesis,  more  complete  than  the  conscious  aspect  for 
not  all  neural  events  are  represented  in  consciousness.  It  is 
small  wonder  that  many  students  decide  that  they  must 
look  to  physiology  for  any  complete  and  real  explanation  of 
mental  life.  This  sceptical  attitude  of  the  student  toward 
psychology  is  not  wholly  unjustified,  nor  is  it  confined  entirely 
to  immature  students;  as  a  matter  of  fact  this  attitude  toward 
our  science  is  quite  prevalent  among  the  physiologists.  I  do 
not  contend  that  it  is  impossible  to  meet  such  a  position  in  a 
satisfactory  manner;  the  significant  point  is  that  this  atti- 
tude of  scepticism  is  wholly  unnecessary  and  exceedingly 


THE  NATURE  OF  MENTAL  PROCESS  187 

detrimental.  No  science  can  afford  to  be  placed  in  a  de- 
fensive and  apologetic  position.  The  dual  presentation 
further  raises  such  distracting  questions  as  the  relative  values 
of  the  neural  and  conscious  components  in  an  act  of  adjust- 
ment, their  causal  interrelations,  and  the  necessity  for  a 
double  treatment  of  mental  events.  All  these  are  valid 
problems  but  they  are  philosophical  in  character  and  have 
no  place  in  an  empirical,  matter  of  fact,  science.  Psychology  , 
generally  recognizes  the  philosophical  character  of  these 
questions  and  their  tendency  to  distract  the  mind  of  the 
student  from  the  main  task  at  hand,  and  the  usual  method  of 
attempting  to  ignore  them  is  by  the  adoption  of  parallelism 
as  a  working  principle.  To  my  mind  this  method  fails  utterly 
to  achieve  its  purpose.  Such  philosophical  questions  must 
necessarily  obtrude  with  a  dualistic  mode  of  presentation;  in 
fact  this  method  was  developed  at  a  time  when  psychology 
was  studied  primarily  as  an  introduction  to  philosophical 
problems,  and  a  better  method  for  this  purpose  would  be  hard 
to  devise.  These  difficulties  are  at  least  minimized  if  not 
eliminated  by  adopting  the  conception  of  this  paper.  Paral- 
lelism is  adopted  as  a  working  hypothesis  in  a  matter  of  fact 
way  without  calling  the  student's  attention  to  it.  The  total 
activity  is  made  the  object  of  study;  the  dichotomy  involved 
is  not  one  of  process,  but  one  of  method  of  approach  or  appre- 
hension. 

In  conclusion  we  may  say  that  there  are  no  fixed  and  im- 
mutable boundary  lines  between  sciences.     Any  science  in- 
cludes within  its  domain  whatever  is  pertinent  to  its  primary 
interest.     If  mental  acts  are  means  of  organic  adjustment, 
then  these  acts  must  be  conceived  and  studied  as  such  devices. 
If  neural  events  are  essential  parts  of  the  act,  the  conception 
of  the  mental  must  be  broadened  so  as  to  include  them.  * 
There  is  no  a  priori  necessity  for  defining  the  mental  in  non- 
material  terms,  except  habit  and  the  force  of  tradition.     The  j 
concept  of  the  mental  must  be  adapted  to  further  the  primary  j 
task  of  psychology  as  it  is  now  conceived. 


A  REFORMULATION  OF  THE   LAW  OF 
ASSOCIATION 

BY  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

University  of  Kansas 

I 

The  reformulation  that  this  paper  undertakes  is  to  render 
explicit  certain  facts  and  points  of  view  that  the  writer  finds 
implicit  in  current  psychological  thinking.  The  'law  of  asso- 
ciation' as  formulated  and  discussed  by  British  psychologists 
concerned  itself  with  ideas  and  sequences  of  thoughts  and 
not  with  sequences  of  conscious  states  in  general  (which 
would  have  included  sequences  of  sensory  data).  Such  was 
the  case  with  Aristotle  also  and  with  the  intervening  writers. 
Observation  was  warped  primarily  by  the  prevailing  interests 
in  logic  and  epistemology  and  by  the  tendency  to  overestimate 
the  importance  of  vision  in  consciousness. 

Aristotle  says,  e.  g.:  "Hence,  when  we  are  recollecting  we 
keep  stimulating  certain  earlier  experiences  until  we  have 
stimulated  one  which  the  one  in  question  is  wont  to  succeed. 
And  just  so  we  hunt  through  the  sequence,  thinking  along 
from  the  present  or  some  other  [thought],  and  from  similar  or 
contrasted  or  contiguous."1 

In  Berkeley's  writings  much  use  is  made  of  association,  or 
suggestion  as  he  terms  it.  And  it  is  particularly  to  be  noted 
that  sequences  of  sensations  as  opposed  to  sequences  of  ideas 
are  produced  by  the  Deity.  In  David  Hartley  there  is  a 
thoroughgoing  physiological  as  opposed  to  a  logical  associ- 
ationism.  Hartley's  classical  formulation  is  as  follows:  "Any 
sensations  A,  B,  C,  etc.,  by  being  associated  with  one  another 
a  sufficient  number  of  times,  get  such  a  power  over  the  cor- 
responding ideas  a,  b,  c,  etc.,  that  any  one  of  the  sensations  A^ 

1  Quoted  from  H.  C.  Warren,  'Mental  Association  from  Plato  to  Hume,'  PSYCHOL. 
REV.,  1916,  23,  p.  210. 
188 


THE  LAW  OF  ASSOCIATION  189 

when  impressed  alone,  shall  be  able  to  excite  in  the  mind 
by  r,  etc.,  the  ideas  of  the  rest."1  Hartley's  physiological 
interests  led  him  to  apply  the  law  specifically  and  in  detail 
to  habit  formation.  Obviously  here  the  cases  described — 
particularly  the  speech  habit  (see  below), — must  furnish  data 
in  harmony  with  our  present  contention;  but  Hartley  never 
realized  it.  Had  he  or  other  writers  done  so,  they  must  have 
recast  their  general  law. 

The  point  of  view  of  these  writers  and  even  their  formu- 
lations of  the  law  have  persisted  into  current  writing  in  spite 
of  the  fact  that  a  constantly  increasing  growth  in  the  knowl- 
edge of  habit  and  thought  has  been  making  the  conventional 
law  inadequate.  The  following  quotations  from  current 
textbooks  will  indicate  the  present  general  attitude. 

In  Calkins2  we  find :  "  Successive  association  is  the  sequence 
of  an  imagination  on  a  perception  (or  another  imagination),  a 
sequence  which  is  attributed  (in  after-reflection)  to  the 
previous  occurrence,  simultaneously  or  in  swift  succession, 
of  the  two  experiences."  This  is  repeated  in  the  table  on 
page  359- 

Titchener3  says:  "We  then  find  this:  that  whenever  a 
sensory  or  imaginal  process  occurs  in  consciousness,  there  are 
likely  to  appear  with  it  (of  course  in  imaginal  terms)4  all  those 
sensory  and  imaginal  processes  which  occurred  together  with 
it  in  the  earlier  conscious  present.  This  we  may  term  the 
law  of  association." 

Angell5  formulates  the  matter  as  follows:  "The  law  of 
association  asserts  that  whenever  two  images,  or  ideas,  have 
been  at  any  time  juxtaposed  in  the  mind,  there  is  a  tendency, 
if  the  first  of  them  recurs,  for  the  other  to  come  with  it." 
Judd  and  Thorndike  state  the  law  in  a  very  general  form  which 
could  be  interpreted  to  cover  our  present  point;  but  the  con- 
text in  each  case  indicates  clearly  that  it  is  the  old  view  of  the 

1  Priestly,  Jos.,  'Hartley's  Theory  of  the  Human  Mind.'      London,  1775,  P-  I4> 
Prop.  5. 

2  Calkins,  M.  W.,  'First  Book  in  Psychology/  4th  Ed.,  1914,  p.  116. 
•Titchener,  E.  B.,  'Textbook  of  Psychology,'  1910,  p.  378. 

4  Italics  mine. 

6  Angell,  Jas.  R.,  'Psychology,'  4th  ed.,  1908,  p.  206. 


190  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

nature  of  the  second  term  of  the  association  which  is  in  their 
minds.     The  present  thesis  receives  no  consideration. 

Since  the  Greeks  it  has  been  recognized  that  the  principle 
of  association  is  the  principle  of  habit  formation.  But  the 
development  and  interrelations  of  the  two  thoughts  has  ended 
there  because  of  the  interests  above  mentioned.  At  the 
present,  behavior  studies  and  the  critical  literature  on  thought 
afford  us  the  ground  for  and  even  require  a  recasting  of  the 
doctrine  of  association.  The  revised  version  needs,  I  believe, 
but  to  be  stated  in  order  to  carry  conviction  in  many  minds: 
//  A  and  B  are  experienced  together  in  space  or  time  and  if  later 
one  is  experienced  either  in  sensory  or  in  imaginal  form,  it 
tends  to  arouse  the  other  either  in  sensory  or  in  imaginal  form. 
In  other  words  the  second  member  of  an  association  may  be 
and  often,  if  not  usually,  is  a  sensory  process.  By  the  term 
sensory  process  I  would  include  both  sensation  and  perception. 
The  essential  point  is  that  the  conscious  state  which  forms 
the  second  term  of  the  association  is  often  conditioned  by  a 
present  and  on-going  peripheral  (sensory)  activity.  It  is 
passing  strange  that  this  has  not  been  explicitly  stated  and 
systematically  incorporated  before  now.  Ever  since  Eb- 
binghaus's  tests  on  nonsense  syllables  *  associations'  have 
been  studied  which  have  involved  the  reproduction  or  recall 
of  sensory  material  (auditory- vocal-motor).  Even  sub-lim- 
inal  associations  have  been  tested  by  the  saving  method  and 
otherwise  with  the  constantly  present  purpose  of  making 
possible  the  recall  in  sensory  form  of  certain  material.  The 
present  formulation  does  not  attempt  to  explain  the  fact  of 
association,  nor  does  it  attempt  to  analyze  the  factors  in- 
volved in  the  formation  of  associations  (habits).  It  proceeds 
on  the  assumption  that  fundamentally  'associationism' 
cannot  be  outgrown  and  left  behind  any  more  than  neural 
habits  and  the  setting  of  synaptic  connections  can  be  so 
treated.  It  is  therefore  important  that  the  'law'  be  made 
adequate  and  general. 

II 

When  psychologists  from  Hartley  to  the  present  time  have 
attempted  to  sketch  the  neural  side  of  the  'law  of  association' 


THE  LAW  OF  ASSOCIATION  I91 

they  have  talked  in  brain  terms  and  not  in  terms  of  the  nervous 
system  as  a  whole.  This  has  followed  by  virtue  of  the  as- 
sumption that  the  second  term  of  an  association  must  be  an 
image  (or  a  centrally  aroused  process).  Hear  James1  on 
the  neural  side:  "I  shall  try  to  show,  in  the  pages  which 
immediately  follow,  that  there  is  no  other  elementary  causal 
law  of  association  than  the  law  of  neural  habit.  All  the 
materials  of  our  thought  are  due  to  the  way  in  which  one  ele- 
mentary process  of  the  cerebral  hemispheres  tends  to  excite 
whatever  other  elementary  process  it  may  have  excited  at 
some  former  time.  The  number  of  elementary  processes 
at  work,  however,  and  the  nature  of  those  which  at  any  time 
are  fully  effective  in  rousing  the  others,  determine  the  char- 
acter of  the  total  brain  action,  and,  as  a  consequence  of  this, 
they  determine  the  object  thought  of  at  the  time.  According 
as  this  resultant  object  is  one  thing  or  another,  we  call  it  a 
product  of  association  by  contiguity  or  of  association  by 
similarity,  or  contrast,  or  whatever  other  sorts  we  may  have 
recognized  as  ultimate."  "Let  us  then  assume  as  the  basis 
of  all  our  subsequent  reasoning  this  law:  When  two  elementary 
brain-processes  have  been  active  together,  or  in  immediate  suc- 
cession, one  of  them,  on  reoccurring,  tends  to  propagate  its 
excitement  into  the  other."  In  the  last  sentence  James  indi- 
cates that  the  'law  of  neural  habit,'  essential  for  association 
to  his  mind,  is  one  dealing  with  central  processes. 

All  that  this  does  is  to  read  over  into  neural  terms  the 
faulty  formulation  of  the  law  as  indicated  above.  Intro- 
spection can  at  the  best  only  note  the  sequences  of  conscious 
states.  If  these  can  be  traced  to  a  prior  contiguity,  they  are 
cases  of  association.  On  the  basis  of  the  introspective  report 
on  the  nature  of  the  associated  contents,  one  can  then  proceed 
to  formulate  the  neural  changes  involved.  The  following 
illustrations  make  clear  that  such  neural  changes  involve  far 
more  than  the  cortex, — that  we  are  dealing  with  peripherally 
and  not  with  centrally  aroused  processes:  I  see  (A)  and 
touch  (B}  an  object  which  results  in  my  drawing  back  (C), 
trembling  (D),  screaming  (E),  or  swearing  (F).  Later  I  see 

1  James,  Wm.,  'Principles  of  Psychology,  1890,  vol.  I.,  p.  566. 


192  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

(A)  or  touch  (B)  the  object  (or  do  both)  and  at  once  C,  Z),  Ey 
or  F  appear.  And  they  may  and  do  appear  in  sensory  form. 
Here  belong  the  so-called  cases  of  emotional  and  affective 
memory  which  were  so  much  discussed  some  years  ago.  I 
see  (A)  an  object  and  it  gets  bound  up  with  unpleasantness 
(B).  Later  when  I  have  A  or  its  image  ay  the  unpleasantness 
returns  as  B  in  the  concrete  with  all  its  organic  and  motor 
changes.  Or  again  I  see  a  word  and  hear  it  at  the  same  time, 
later  I  see  or  think  of  the  word  and  the  sound  is  again  pro- 
duced by  my  vocal  organs.  It  is  hardly  necessary  to  point 
out  how  in  these  cases  the  nervous  impulses  shuttle  back  and 
forth  between  the  brain  and  the  periphery  of  the  body.  Cen- 
tral arousal  and  images  do  not  monopolize  these  situations. 
On  the  conscious  side  we  have  had  a  succession  of  sensations 
whose  connection  reflection  can  trace  to  a  prior  contiguity. 
This  is  what  we  mean  by  "mental"  association  and  this  is 
where  the  law  starts  or  gets  its  basis.  Neurally  we  have  had 
widespread  activity  unconfined  to  the  hemispheres. 

Current  writing  is  emphasizing  the  relation  of  language  and 
the  vocal  processes  to  thought.  It  seems  clearly  established 
that  thinking  can  go  on  without  detectable  imagery.  The 
'meanings'  to  most  psychologists  (and  I  agree)  are  not  'pure 
thoughts,'  but  accompany,  among  other  things,  the  kinsesthe- 
tic  sensations  (sensory  processes)  of  the  vocal  organs.  These 
language  cases  are  functionally  the  most  important  instances 
where  the  second  member  or  succeeding  members  of  an  as- 
sociative train  are  sensations  (as  I  should  say),  or  peripher- 
ally initiated  processes  (as  others  would  say). 

It  should  not  be  objected  that  with  the  increasing  auto- 
matism these  peripheral  processes  become  short-circuited  and 
drop  from  consciousness.  The  same  could  be  said  of  the 
imaginal  members  of  the  association  possibly  even  more 
truly.  It  is  doubtlessly  the  case  that  with  both  sorts  of 
material  the  meaning  is  usually  the  clearest  and  most  promi- 
nent feature;  but  that  again  is  a  point  for  any  formulation  of 
the  law  of  association  and  not  alone  for  the  present  one. 
The  essential  thing  for  us  here  is  that  the  meaning  can  be 
carried,  and  is  carried,  as  well  by  sensory  as  by  imaginal  proc- 


THE  LAW  OF  ASSOCIATION  193 

esses  and  that  by  virtue  of  the  internal  control  of  their 
stimuli  these  sensory  processes  may  constitute  the  second 
terms  of  an  associative  sequence. 

Nor  should  it  be  objected  that  the  present  account  fails 
to  consider  simultaneous  association  or  persistent  association, 
where  one  part  of  an  associated  complex  persists  over  into 
the  succeeding  moment.  The  explanation  of  such  cases 
need  be  no  easier  with  images  than  with  sensory  processes. 
The  play  of  muscles  from  moment  to  moment  offers  perhaps 
the  clearest  illustration  of  this  type  of  event.  Muscles  i-io, 
let  us  say,  are  active  at  a  given  moment  and  by  their  activity 
lead  to  the  contraction  of  muscles  8-15.  A  common  element, 
muscles  8-10,  is  found  in  each  activity.  If  we  speak  from  the 
conscious  side,  we  have  a  core  of  kinaesthetic  (and  cutaneous) 
sensory  experiences  persisting  through  two  successive  mo- 
ments of  time.  Practically  this  situation  is  always  present 
and  gives  us  our  feeling  of  bodily  presence  and  of  the  con- 
tinuity of  the  self.  Here  again  our  account  could  be  much 
more  complete  if  we  could  formulate  the  causes  of  the  setting 
of  associations  (synaptic  connections).  Such  incompleteness, 
however,  does  not  affect  our  essential  point,  nor  is  it  a  dif- 
ficulty peculiar  to  the  present  thesis. 

Ill 

Sensory  processes  have  their  functional  significances  in  the 
responses  that  they  initiate.  And  so,  stated  the  other  way 
round,  what  adaptive  movements  shall  take  place  depends 
very  largely  upon  the  sensory  processes  available.  Certain 
of  these  sensory  processes  are  practically  beyond  the  organ- 
ism's control.  Certain  others  on  the  contrary  are  very  much 
within  the  control  of  certain  organisms  and  to  a  variable 
degree  within  the  control  of  all.  An  animal's  control  of  its 
own  movements  or  responses  is  to  a  large  extent  dependent 
upon  the  sensory  processes  that  it  can  itself  initiate.  Self- 
initiated  stimuli  in  most  animals  are  those  of  hearing,  cuta- 
neous sensitivity  (pain  excluded?),  and  kinaesthetic,  organic 
and  static  sensitivity.  Those  that  are  not  self-initiated  are 
taste,  smell,  and  vision.  The  last  statement,  of  course,  needs 


194  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

much  qualification.  Many  animals  produce  odors  and  others 
have  phosphorescent  organs  which  emit  light.  The  same  may 
be  true  also  of  taste,  particularly  with  aquatic  animals.  In 
man  the  qualification  that  I  feel  it  most  necessary  to  urge  is 
that  of  visual  sensations  produced  by  intention  and  probably 
initiated  by  the  efferent  optic  fibers. 

Wherever  we  find  sequences  of  habits,  there  we  should 
expect  to  find  stimuli  under  the  organism's  control.  Other- 
wise in  order  to  have  a  habit  sequence  such  as  speech,  running 
a  maze,  or  solving  the  delayed  reaction,  it  would  be  necessary 
that  some  non-controlable  stimulus  initiate  each  link  in  the 
response.  But  the  contraction  of  one  set  of  muscles  stimu- 
lates receptors  which  arouse  the  succeeding  muscular  activity. 
If  this  sequence  is  essentially  constant  and  if  the  receptors 
condition  consciousness,  we  have  a  typical  case  where  an 
associative  sequence  is  sensory  in  its  entirety.  Writers  on 
association  at  the  time  the  law  was  fixed  upon  psychology 
were  too  fascinated  by  vision  (and  logic) — and  vision  is  a 
sense  whose  stimulus  (light)  is  practically  non-producible  by 
man's  own  activity.  What  more  natural  then  than  that  in 
formulating  a  rule  of  sequences,  they  should  have  said  that 
the  second  terms  of  associations  could  not  be  sensory  but 
must  be  imaginal.  Indeed  the  last  sentence  is  misleading. 
The  question  was  not  clearly  enough  considered  for  them  to 
use  the  terms  'could  not  be'  this  or  'must  be'  that.  But 
this  error,  I  believe,  proceeded  from  tacit  assumptions  as  I 
have  indicated.  And  the  same  assumptions,  tacitly  made, 
still  persist  and  lead  to  our  conventional  formulations,  al- 
though such  formulations  are  as  wide  of  the  mark  as  I  have 
tried  to  indicate.  It  is  true  that  where  writers  come  to  con- 
sider kinsesthetic  habits,  e.  g.,  they  give  essentially  the  account 
that  I  have  sketched  above.  But  at  the  same  time  they  forget 
that  so  far  as  the  conscious  side  is  concerned  they  are  dealing 
with  genuine  cases  of  the  law  of  association;  and  when  for- 
mulating that  law,  they  forget  the  other  situation.  Nowhere 
do  they  bring  the  two  into  working  union.  Suggestive  state- 
ments are  alone  to  be  found.  I  cite  three  instances: 

First,  Hartley's  account1  of  the  growth  of  the  speech  habit: 

1  Priestley,  op.  cit.,  pp.  33-34. 


THE  LAW  OF  ASSOCIATION  195 

"About  the  same  time  .  .  .  the  muscles  of  speech  act  occa- 
sionally in  various  combinations,  according  to  the  associations 
of  the  motory  vibratiuncles  with  each  other.  Suppose  now 
the  muscles  of  speech  to  act  in  these  combinations  at  the  same 
time  that  sound  is  produced  from  some  agreeable  impression, 
a  mere  sensation,  or  a  slight  associated  cause,  which  must  be 
supposed  to  be  often  the  case,  since  it  is  so  observable  that 
young  children,  when  in  a  state  of  health  and  pleasure,  exert 
a  variety  of  actions  at  the  same  time.  It  is  evident,  that  an 
articulate  sound,  or  one  approaching  thereto,  will  sometimes 
be  produced  by  this  conjoint  action  of  the  trunk,  larynx, 
tongue,  and  lips;  and  that  both  these  articulate  sounds,  and 
inarticulate  ones,  will  often  recur,  from  the  recurrence  of  the 
same  accidental  causes.  After  they  have  recurred  a  sufficient 
number  of  times,  the  impression  which  these  sounds,  articu- 
late and  inarticulate,  make  upon  the  ear,  will  become  an 
associated  circumstance  (for  the  child  always  hears  himself 
speak,  at  the  same  time  that  he  exerts  the  action)  sufficient 
to  produce  a  repetition  of  them.  And  thus  it  is  that  children 
repeat  the  same  sounds  over  and  over  again,  for  many  suc- 
cessions, the  impression  of  the  last  sound  upon  the  ear  exciting 
a  fresh  one,  and  so  on,  till  the  organs  be  tired." 

Miss  Calkins  also  comes  near  making  the  essential  point 
when  she  points  out  that  any  state  of  consciousness  plus  a 
feeling  of  generality  is  a  concept.  (".  .  .  when  I  think  of 
fear,  the  consciousness  of  generality  accompanies  a  genuine, 
though  certainly  faint,  experience  of  that  emotion."1)  Now 
since  thinking  consists  in  a  sequence  of  concepts,  or  their 
physiological  equivalents,  she  should  have  added  that  it  is 
possible  to  have  a  sequence  of  internally  controlled  but  peri- 
pherally initiated  states  of  consciousness.  And  this  would 
have  forced  her  to  re-state  the  law  of  association  whose 
phrasing  I  have  quoted  above. 

James,  too,  came  perilously  near  discovering  the  point 
that  I  am  making.  There  is  one  sentence  in  the  very  chapter 
on  Association  that  gives  a  beautiful  illustration  of  the  fact 
that  the  second  term  of  an  association  may  be  sensory. 

1  op.  dt.,  p.  147. 


196  WALTER  S.  HUNTER 

".  .  .  probably  every  one  who  bathes  himself  in  a  certain 
fixed  manner  is  familiar  with  the  fact  that  each  part  of  his 
body  over  which  the  water  is  squeezed  from  the  sponge 
awakens  a  premonitory  tingling  consciousness  in  that  portion 
of  skin  which  is  habitually  next  to  be  deluged."1  Surely  only 
the  momentum  of  historical  usage  and  the  absence  of  the 
new  psychology  of  thought  could  have  prevented  James  from 
correlating  his  discussions  of  Habit,  Association  and  Will  with 
reference  to  this  point! 

I  would  once  more  call  attention  to  the  semi-behavioristic 
background  of  the  present  discussion.  Studies  of  the  delayed 
reaction  in  young  children  and  in  raccoons  (possibly  also  in 
dogs2)  have  indicated  the  functional  presence  of  internal 
factors  which  can  initiate  responses  in  the  absence  of  the 
accustomed  external  stimulus.  These  internal  factors  may 
theoretically  be  either  centrally  or  peripherally  aroused 
processes  which  are  called  up  by  the  sensory  stimulation  due 
to  operating  the  release  box  of  the  apparatus.  Elsewhere3 
I  have  given  reasons  for  deciding  in  favor  of  the  peripheral 
processes.  The  importance  of  the  appearance  in  the  animal 
series  of  this  ability  to  control  adaptive  muscular  response  by 
internal  stimuli  which  need  not  be  constantly  present  can 
hardly  be  overestimated.  Man's  language  sequences  are 
but  the  development  of  the  animal  form  of  sensory  associa- 
tions— a  development  which  is  centralized  more  and  more  in 
the  vocal  apparatus. 

1  James,  op.  cit.t  p.  555. 

2  Walton,  A.  C,  'The  Influence  of  Distracting  Stimuli  during  Delayed  Reaction  in 
Dogs.'    /.  of  Animal  Behav.,  1915,  5,  259-291. 

3  Hunter,  W.  S.,  'Delayed  Reaction  in  Animals  and  Children,'  Behav.  Mon., 
1913,  2,  No.  i. 


THE   SCIENTIFIC  PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMER- 
ICAN PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS 

BY  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

Within  the  past  few  years  there  have  appeared  reviews  of 
the  progress  of  psychology  for  different  periods  of  time.1 
That  general  progress  has  been  made  is  evident.  That  in 
America  progress  has  been  made  is  shown  by  the  inauguration 
and  rapid  increase  in  the  membership  of  the  American  Psy- 
chological Association,  by  the  foundation  of  journals  devoted 
to  the  publication  of  psychological  discussions  and  researches, 
by  the  appearance  in  numbers  of  psychological  books  and 
articles,  by  the  great  popular  interest  which  has  been  aroused, 
by  the  birth  and  growth  of  numerous  laboratories  for  teaching 
and  investigation,  by  the  creation  of  special  university  chairs 
apart  from  those  for  allied  disciplines  (especially  philosophy 
and  education),  and  by  the  establishment  of  special  research 
laboratories  for  applied  psychology.  It  is  also  pertinent  to 
remark  that  during  this  developing  period  of  psychology  there 
have  been  begun  and  continued  several  lines  of  investigation 
which,  although  not  entirely  American,  have  continued  in 
mass  and  in  importance  to  be  due  to  workers  in  this  country. 

Although  there  is  abundant  evidence  of  advance,  those 
historians  who  have  recounted  the  progress  have  dealt  with 
their  theme  in  an  impersonal  way.  They  have  reported  the 
number  and  the  character  of  the  published  investigations, 
the  establishment  of  independent  departments,  and  the 
number  of  conferred  doctorates.  They  have  not  dealt  with 
an  equally  important  subject  which  is  germane  to  the  one 
regarding  which  they  have  written.  We  have  not  been 
informed  by  whom  the  psychological  advances  have  been 
made,  or  whether  or  not  in  view  of  the  increasing  number  of 

1  See  C.  A.  Ruckmich,  'The  Last  Decade  of  Psychology  in  Review,'  PSYCHOL. 
BULL.,  1916,  13,  109-120.  This  contains  references  to  previous  reviews  of  like  char- 
acter. 

197 


198  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

professional  psychologists  there  has  been  a  corresponding 
increase  in  the  number  or  in  the  value  of  the  published  in- 
vestigations. In  other  words,  although  it  is  admitted  that 
advance  has  been  made,  we  are  as  far  from  knowing  whether 
or  not  the  advance  has  been  satisfactory  and  corresponds  with 
the  number  of  psychologists. 

The  estimation  of  the  value  of  an  individual's  contributions 
has  been  attempted  from  time  to  time  and  in  a  variety  of 
ways.  There  is  the  well-known  attempt  to  grade  psychol- 
ogists by  votes  of  a  few  selected  individuals.  The  general 
results  of  this  grading  have  been  reported.1  There  has  also 
been  a  negative  grading  of  psychologists  in  general  in  the 
elections  to  the  National  Academy  of  Sciences.  Of  the  five 
so-called  psychologists  who  have  been  members,  three  at  the 
time  of  their  election  were  professors  of  philosophy  and 
primarily  interested  and  concerned  in  the  teaching  and  pub- 
lication of  philosophical  (ontological,  epistemological,  and 
logical)  doctrines.  There  has  also  been  a  continuing  selection 
(and  promotion)  of  men  for  professorships  and  other  academic 
positions,  which  selection  acts  as  a  grading  of  a  less  obvious 
kind.  The  last  kind  of  selection  brings  about  two  adverse 
conditions,  one  of  them  being  that  an  individual  selected  for 
a  position  because  of  time-serving  or  personal  recommendation 
has  automatically  acquired  a  claim  to  a  grade  to  which  his 
previous  position  and  work  did  not  apparently  entitle  him, 
the  other  being  that  because  of  this  there  has  been  a  consider- 
able amount  of  time-serving  and  inbreeding  in  some  of  our 
institutions.2 

All  of  these  methods  of  estimating  the  relative  ranks  of 
individuals  have  obvious  and  with  respect  to  even  their  tem- 
porary value  perhaps  vital  defects.  Much  the  same  may  be 

1  'American  Men  of  Science.'     Ed.  by  J.  McK.  Cattell.     2d  ed.  1910.     See  es- 
pecially pp.  537-596.    The  results  have  been  given  in  only  a  general  way;  the  names 
of  the  judges  are  not  mentioned,  and  we  must  depend  upon  the  editor's  word  that  they 
were  competent. 

2  While  it  may  not  apply  to  psychologists  it  is  not  unknown  in  scientific  circles 
that  some  individuals,  because  of  personal  charm  or  characteristics  such  as  self-appre- 
ciation and  a  hypercritical  attitude  toward  others,  have  been  able  to  attract  students 
and  have  been  able  to  persuade  others  of  their  importance  and  to  get  a  self-enhanced 
reputation  spread. 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  *99 

said  regarding  methods  now  in  use  for  the  determination  of 
the  value  of  a  published  research  or  other  contribution.  If 
the  different  methods  were  used  in  combination  and  subjected 
to  safeguards  respecting  individual  interests  they  would 
probably  give  better  estimates  than  have  hitherto  been  made. 
To  take  individuals  at  a  given  time  and  settle  upon  values  or 
grades  may  be  necessary,  but  it  should  be  recognized  that  the 
grades  shift  at  different  times.  The  same  holds  true  with 
regard  to  estimated  grades  or  values  of  performed  work.  The 
supposed  values  of  the  nineteenth  century  do  not  hold  for  the 
twentieth,  nor  do  those  of  today  hold  for  tomorrow.  It  is, 
however,  possible  to  determine  whether  or  not  a  given  in- 
dividual or  a  group  has  carried  out  some  of  its  functions,  and 
to  determine  whether  or  not  certain  individuals  have  fallen 
short  or  have  done  more  than  their  normal  or  expected  share. 
We  may  assume  as  proven  that  in  psychology  there  has  been 
satisfactory  advance  in  general,  both  in  character  and  in 
quantity  of  the  work,  and  we  may  inquire:  "By  whom  have 
the  advances  been  made,  and  in  what  manner  have  individuals 
or  groups  contributed  to  the  advance?" 

It  has  already  been  said  that  if  we  wish  to  deal  with  ab- 
solute value  it  is  not  possible  to  make  satisfactory  judgments, 
and  answers  to  the  questions  could  not  be  given.  No  one 
psychologist  has  sufficient  knowledge  of  methods  and  results 
in  all  branches  of  psychology  to  be  considered  a  sufficiently 
expert  judge.  Nor  has  any  one  the  confidence  of  all  or  of  a 
majority  of  psychologists.  Each  judge  of  values  is  influenced 
in  making  his  judgments  by  considerations  of  training,  of 
knowledge,  and  perhaps  of  special  personal  interest.  There 
is  no  absolute  impartiality.  The  introspectionist  does  not 
hesitate  to  say  that  behavior  studies  are  not  truly  psycho- 
logical. The  behaviorist  may  reply  that  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  the  introspection  that  is  talked  about  so  much.  He 
who  does  not  hesitate  to  teach  and  write  about  the  functions 
of  the  parts  of  the  nervous  system  may  never  have  performed 
or  seen  any  of  the  classical  cerebral  experiments;  by  some 
psychologists  the  realm  of  the  abnormal  has  never  been  visited 
and  by  them  it  is  known  only  like  uncharted  parts  in  a  geog- 


200  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

raphy;  and  the  remainder  of  applied  psychology  is  for  many 
like  a  prostitute  whose  acquaintance  is  not  desired  and  who  is 
to  be  shunned  because  of  fear  of  infection. 

Notwithstanding  the  limitations  of  value  of  individual 
opinion,  much  might  be  gained  by  taking  a  consensus  of 
opinion  of  those  of  divergent  special  interests  and  of  those 
who  are  admitted  to  be  fair  jurymen.1  But  we  can  also  do 
something  very  definite  by  determining  that  a  certain  in- 
dividual has  or  has  not  made  any  published  contribution 
towards  psychological  advance.2  This  is  a  comparatively 
easy  method  giving  positive  results.  It  admits  of  little  or 
no  discussion  of  a  judge's  partiality,  it  rests  solely  upon  the 
admission  of  published  material  as  the  facts  with  which  to  deal. 
We  may  also  determine  that  one  has  contributed  by  books, 
or  by  the  publications  of  investigations,  or  by  any  other  means 
which  we  may  select.  And  there  is  also  the  possibility  of 
answering  the  question,  "Has  the  progress,  as  measured  by  the 
number  of  publications,  corresponded  with  the  number  of 
individuals  who  have  become  professional  psychologists?"3 

1  Not  related  academically  to  the  individuals  to  be  judged,  supplied  with  all  the 
data  respecting  the  individuals  (not  with  only  a  part  as  was  done  in  Cattell's  'American 
Mec  of  Science'  classification),  and  of  sufficiently  diverse  individual  interests  to  form 
a  jury  representative  of  all  branches  of  psychology. 

2  There  is  little  possibility  of  determining  the  value  to  psychology  of  the  indi- 
vidual's college  or  university  teaching.     Some  indication  might  be  obtained  by  the  de- 
termination of  the  academic  antecedents  of  psychologists  and  of  those  who  have  taken 
advanced  courses  in  psychology  but  who  have  not  become  professional  psychologists. 
This  does  not  mean  the  determination  of  the  number  of  conferred  doctorates.     It  is 
often  forgotten  that  the  interest  of  the  individual  has  been  created  before  he  has  known 
of  the  possibility  of  advanced  work,  and  the  doctorates  give  in  the  main  only  a  clue 
to  the  institutions  which  are  recommended  by  those  who  have  created  the  interest,  or 
which  are  selected  because  of  material  advantages.     Another  method  of  determining 
the  value  of  the  individual  teacher  would  be  that  of  estimating  the  average  value  and 
the  amount  of  published  work  which  his  students  put  forth  after  leaving  him.     Not  all 
of  their  subsequent  work  is  due  to  his  influence  but  an  estimate  could  be  made. 

3  The  consideration  of  these  matters  has  been  somewhat  forced  upon  me  in  con- 
nection with  editorial  duties  during  the  past  few  years,  since  it  was  necessary  to  know 
what  lines  of  work  were  being  investigated  and  by  whom.     During  a  longer  period  of 
time  I  have  not  infrequently  been  asked  to  offer  suggestions  regarding  possible  candi- 
dates for  positions,  and  having  had  very  few  students  fitted  for  such  positions,  I  have 
taken  the  opportunity  to  recommend  those  who  have  exhibited  some  accomplishment 
(publication)  rather  than  those  who  were  known  to  me  as  individuals  of  'promise'  in 
their  advanced  work.     The  results  of  some  of  these  casual  inquiries  regarding  accom- 
plishment were  so  different  from  what  I  had  expected  that  it  led  to  the  consideration 
of  a  larger  group. 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  201 

We  have  available  for  the  purpose  well-known  yearly  bib- 
liographies, and  the  present  article  has  been  made  possible 
because  of  them.  The  membership  list  of  the  American 
Psychological  Association  was  consulted  to  obtain  a  list  of 
our  *  professional'  psychologists.  Since  membership  in  the 
Association  is  not  limited  to  those  who  are  instructors  or 
professors  of  psychology,  only  those  whose  official  positions 
consisted  solely  in  relation  to  psychology  were  considered  to 
be  the  professional  psychologists.1  Since  those  few  who  hold 
only  research  positions  can  not  be  dealt  with  in  the  same  man- 
ner as  teachers,  I  decided  to  omit  their  names  from  the  list 
to  be  investigated.  This  left  87  names,  of  which  three  were 
omitted  because  of  the  lack  of  certain  data  which  I  thought 
essential.  The  84  individuals  represent  48  institutions,  45  as 
professors,  26  as  assistant,  associate  or  adjunct  professors, 
and  13  as  instructors.  The  academic  titles  mean  little  but 
they  are  mentioned  only  to  indicate  the  range  or  the  number 
of  departments  of  psychology.  Five  individuals  were  con- 
nected with  one  institution,  four  with  another,  there  were 
three  in  each  of  nine  institutions,  there  were  two  in  each  of 
eleven,  and  one  in  each  of  twenty-six  institutions.  Half  of  the 
men  had  received  their  doctorate  during  the  decade  as  follows : 
1906,  2;  1908,  6;  1909,  6;  1910,  4;  1911,  2;  1912,  10;  1913,  7; 

1914,  4;  1915,  i. 

Since  my  immediate  interests  have  been  connected  with 
recent  publications  I  selected  the  past  ten  years,  1906  to 

1915,  inclusive,  and  have  tabulated  the  contributions  of  each 
of  the  84  individuals  for  each  year.     The  contributions  which 
have  been  listed  were  found  in  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  INDEX.2 

xThe  1916  membership  list  was  used.  This  contains  the  titles  of  positions  as 
supplied  by  the  members,  and  is  presumably  correct.  I  am  convinced  that  some  of  the 
titles  are  incorrect,  but  the  mistakes  are  relatively  unimportant.  I  have  not  gone 
beyond  the  official  returns.  Some  professional  psychologists  who  are  not  members  of 
the  Association  are  not  included.  Some  of  them  are  known  to  the  writer,  but  it  seemed 
unfair  to  include  them,  since  they  are  not  members  of  the  national  body  of  professional 
psychologists. 

2  This  bibliography  does  not  give  references  to  all  of  the  publications  of  psychol- 
ogists, some  contained  in  inaccessible  periodicals  are  not  given,  some  which  are  not 
psychological  are  not  noted,  but  the  failure  to  list  all  the  psychological  publications  of 
any  one  individual  rests  solely  with  that  individual,  since  the  INDEX  asks  that  omissions 


202  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

The  different  kinds  of  contributions  have  been  listed  under 
the  following  titles:  Monographs,  Original  Articles,  Discus- 
sions, Books,  General  Reviews,  Reports  of  Meetings.  A  few 
translations  of  American  books  into  foreign  languages  were 
omitted,  on  the  ground  that  the  original  authors  had  already 
made  the  contribution  and  the  work  of  translation  was  that  of 
another.  Translations  of  foreign  books  into  English  were 
also  omitted  from  consideration.  In  some  cases  it  is  difficult 
to  decide  whether  a  certain  publication  is  a  discussion  or  an 
original  article,  in  other  cases  whether  a  publication  be  an 
original  article  or  a  monograph,  or  a  monograph  or  a  book. 
Some  periodicals  publish  long  articles  which  in  other  series 
would  be  published  as  monographs,  but  they  have  been  dealt 
with  as  they  stood.  When  doubt  arose  as  to  the  character  of 
the  publication  the  contributor  was  given  the  benefit  of  the 
doubt.1  The  inclusion  of  general  reviews  and  reports  of 
meetings  may  need  justification.  They  have  appeared  to  me 
to  be  legitimate  methods  of  advancing  psychology  because 
they  may  create  interest  to  investigate  certain  matters  or  give 
facts  to  others  which  would  not  ordinarily  be  discovered,  etc. 
Their  value,  however,  must  be  considerably  less  than  those  of 
publications  containing  the  results  of  personal  investigations. 
Somewhat  similarly  with  books,  since  they  are  largely  com- 
pilations of  the  work  of  others. 

Table  I.  gives  the  results  of  the  examination  of  the  INDEX 
for  the  individuals  and  the  decade  under  consideration. 
Here  there  are  shown  the  numbers  of  each  kind  of  publication 
for  each  year  and  for  the  ten-year  period.  It  will  be  seen  that 
with  the  exception  of  a  few  lean  years  (1907,  1914)  the  number 

and  corrections  be  supplied.  A  few  mistakes  were  noted,  when  they  were  obvious 
they  were  taken  account  of  in  the  tabulations.  The  tabulations  by  years  are  not  always 
exact  on  account  of  the  inability  of  the  INDEX  compilers  to  secure  all  the  references  for  a 
particular  year  at  the  time  of  publication,  but  titles  omitted  in  one  year  are  found  in 
the  next  number. 

1  That  is,  as  will  be  noted  below,  an  artificial  value  was  assigned  to  each  kind  of 
publication,  and  when  doubt  arose  the  higher  value  was  assigned.  At  the  same  time  a 
'joint'  article,  etc.,  was  assigned  to  both  individuals,  and  given  in  each  case  its  full 
value.  I  was  at  first  inclined  to  reduce  the  article  value  for  'minor  contributions,' 
but  I  concluded  to  let  the  above  consideration  hold.  The  recent  publication  of  the 
Proc.  Nat.  Acad.  of  Sciences  was  another  difficult  matter.  The '  articles '  in  that  journal 
are  in  reality  abstracts  or  summaries  (Auto-refer ate). 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS 


203 


TABLE  I 

KINDS  OF  PUBLISHED  CONTRIBUTIONS  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS  FOR  THE 
DECADE,  1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE 


1906 

1907 

1908 

1909 

1910 

1911 

1912 

i9»3 

1914 

1915 

Totals 

Monographs  

I 

•i 

2 

2 

C 

C 

5 

IO 

6 

6 

45 

Articles  

16 

36 

4-1 

49 

42 

44 

59 

58 

39 

76 

492 

Discussions  

7 

4' 

c 

7 

2 

8 

9 

12 

9 

3 

66 

Books  

2 

i 

IO 

6 

•2 

6 

8 

5 

9 

5 

55 

Reviews  ... 

4" 

i 

4" 

•j 

4. 

29 

12 

25 

76 

33 

161 

Reports 

I 

o 

4" 

•7 

4, 

6 

7 

2 

5 

32 

Totals  

61 

45 

68 

70 

6O 

98 

116 

112 

93 

128 

851 

of  research  articles  and  monographs  has  not  differed  very 
greatly  from  year  to  year  and  there  is  a  fairly  gradual  increase. 
There  is  a  slight  increase  in  1912  and  1913  over  the  preceding 
years  and  a  greater  increase  in  1915  over  1913  and  1912. 
The  notable  decrease  in  1914  is  not  explained.1  It  may  be 
that  the  increase  of  interest  in  the  subject  of  tests  is  re- 
sponsible, those  who  had  taken  up  this  line  of  work  being 
occupied  in  1913  and  1914  with  the  accumulation  of  facts 
which  were  published  in  191  £.2  When  we  look  at  the  yearly 
totals  we  note  that  the  increase  began  in  1911,  and  this  was 
coincident  with  the  inauguration  of  the  series  of  general 
reviews  in  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  BULLETIN. 

Table  II.  shows  the  distribution  of  the  contributors  over 
the  ten-year  period.  It  is  a  remarkable  fact  that  the  first 
five  years  are  almost  constant  in  number  of  contributors  and 
that  the  increase  in  the  number  of  contributors  has  taken 

1  A  writer  in  the  New  York  Times  book  review  supplement  has  mentioned  that  in 
general  literature  1914  was  a  lean  year.    The  reason  is  not  obvious  in  that  case  or  in 
the  case  of  our  psychological  publications,  since  the  European  war  could  not  have  its 
effect  on  production  until  very  late  in  the  year.     In  connection  with  psychological 
journals  this  effect  should  have  been  more  noticeable  in  1915  if  it  existed  because  of 
the  war. 

2  Ruckmich  reports  over  800  original  articles  for  the  decade  1905-1914.    Probably 
the  number  in  1905  was  nearer  that  for  1906  than  that  for  1915  of  the  present  table. 
On  that  assumption  we  would  have  about  500  titles  of  original  articles  and  monographs 
for  that  decade  by  professional  psychologists.     Not  all  of  these  have  appeared  in  the 
magazines  listed  by  Ruckmich,  and  in  comparison  with  the  'over  800'  noted  by 
Ruckmich  it  is  apparent  that  fully  3/8  of  the  grand  total  was  contributed  by  the 
non-professional  psychologists,  or  by  those  whose  loyalty  was  divided  between  psy- 
chology and  philosophy,  education,  etc. 


204 


SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 


TABLE  II 

GROUPING  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS  ACCORDING  TO  YEARLY  NUMBER  OF 
PUBLICATIONS,  FOR  THE  DECADE,  1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE 


1906 

1907 

1908 

1909 

1910 

1911 

1912 

19I3 

1914 

i9IS 

I  contribution  

1C 

TlS 

12 

II 

17 

2O 

17 

19 

?R 

2  contributions  
3  contributions  

IO 

•J 

7 

-z 

8 

c 

8 
6 

8 
•z 

9 
7 

13 

c 

13 

c 

13 

12 

6 

4  contributions  

o 

o 

I 

2 

HP 

o 

2 

c 

2 

6 

C  contributions  .... 

2 

o 

I 

I 

2 

6 

I 

•j 

2 

i 

6  contributions 

o 

I 

o 

2 

o 

o 

2 

2 

I 

2 

7  or  more  contributions  

I 

0 

2 

0 

0 

2 

4 

I 

0 

2 

Totals  

31 

27 

29 

30 

32 

38 

47 

46 

45 

57 

place  during  the  past  five  years.  The  greatest  number  of 
contributors  is  found  in  1915,  the  year  of  the  greatest  number 
of  contributions.  This  table  also  shows  what  may  be  termed 
the  scientific  activities  of  psychologists  for  it  gives  the  number 
of  publications  of  groups  of  individuals.  For  the  past  five 
years  about  30  per  cent,  of  those  who  contributed  published 
three  or  more  articles,  etc.,  each  year.  This  is,  of  course, 
not  to  be  taken  to  mean  that  the  same  individual  did  this 
from  year  to  year,  although  it  may  be  mentioned  that  the 
tabulation  of  the  material  indicates  that  the  man  who  does 
it  one  year  is  more  apt  to  repeat  with  more  than  a  single  con- 
tribution for  the  following  years. 

Since  not  all  of  the  individuals  on  our  list  have  been,  nor 
could  they  be  expected  to  be,  active  in  publication  during  the 
whole  of  the  decade  it  is  of  interest  to  compare  the  figures 
which  are  given  in  Table  II.  with  the  examination  of  the 
years  of  the  doctorate  or  other  higher  degree  which  is  held. 
There  were  42  individuals  who  had  obtained  their  higher 
degree  anterior  to  I9O6.1  The  other  42  could  not  be  expected 
to  publish  work  before  their  doctorate,  although  some  did  so. 
Counting  the  date  of  the  doctorate  as  the  date  when  publi- 
cation might  reasonably  be  expected,  the  numbers  of  indi- 
viduals expected  to  publish  were  obtained  by  adding  the  new 
doctors  to  the  original  42  at  the  beginning  of  the  decade.  It 
has  already  been  mentioned  that  some  published  before  the 
doctorate,  the  number  being  14  (out  of  a  total  of  42),  and  a 
few  published  more  than  one  article. 

1  Two  individuals  on  the  list  hold  the  Master's  degree  only. 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS 


205 


When  now  we  compare  the  number  of  expected  contri- 
butors with  the  actual  number  of  contributors  we  find  an 
interesting  condition.  Table  III.  gives  the  data.  Although 
the  number  of  expected  contributors  increased  during  the 
first  five  years  the  yearly  number  of  actual  contributors 
did  not  increase.  The  increase  in  contributors  came 
during  the  second  half  of  the  decade,  but  the  percentage  of 
expected  contributors  who  published  is  the  same  (68  per  cent.) 
at  the  beginning  and  at  the  end,  there  being  a  decrease  in  the 
percentage  up  to  the  year  1910  and  an  increase  thereafter. 
If  we  separate  out  those  contributions  which  are  intended  to 
convey  new  facts  or  new  interpretations,1  which  would  limit 
us  mainly  to  articles  and  monographs,  we  find  an  even  more 

TABLE  III 

THE  PUBLICATION  ACTIVITIES  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS  FOR  THE  DECADE, 
1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE:  THE  NUMBERS  OF  EXPECTED  CONTRIBUTORS,  OF  ACTUAL 
CONTRIBUTORS,  OF  THOSE  CONTRIBUTING  ARTICLES  AND  MONOGRAPHS,  AND 
THOSE  CONTRIBUTING  PREVIOUS  TO  DOCTORATE 


1906 

1907 

1908 

1909 

1910 

60 
29 

28 

3 

1911 

1912 

1913 

1914 

83 
45 

35 

o 

1915 

Expected  contributors  

44 
30 
28 

I 

44 
26 
24 

i 

S? 
26 

23 
3 

56 
28 
26 

2 

62 

37 
27 

i 

72 
43 
30 

4 

79 
45 
34 

i 

84 
57 
40 

0 

Actual  contributors  

Contributors  of  articles  and  monographs  
Contributors    previous    to    doctorate    (addi- 
tional)   

interesting  comparison.  At  the  beginning  of  the  decade 
there  was  a  total  of  44  individuals  expected  to  contribute. 
Of  this  number  28  made  contributions  of  articles  and  mono- 
graphs (64  per  cent.).  The  percentage  (actual  contributors 
in  relation  to  expected  contributors)  decreased  in  the  follow- 
ing years  as  follows:  55,  46,  46,  47,  44,  42,  43,  42,  48.  The 
contributions  anterior  to  the  doctorate  by  those  who  con- 
tributed previous  to  their  doctorate  are  not  included  in 
these  calculations.  It  is  to  be  observed,  therefore,  that  the 
percentage  of  original  contributors  has  decreased  and  the 
percentage  of  total  contributors  at  first  decreased  and  later 
reached  its  original  figure.  The  great  differences  in  the  per- 
centages from  1911  to  1915  inclusive  are  to  be  understood 

1  It  is  not  intended  to  say  that  books,  discussions,  reports  or  reviews  do  not 
contain  new  facts  and  new  explanations,  but  that  they  are  less  apt  to  do  so. 


206  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

primarily  as  the  result  of  the  publication  of  general  reviews 
and  an  apparent  satisfaction  of  the  authors  of  these  reviews 
in  their  accomplishment. 

The  subject  of  books  deserves  a  separate  paragraph. 
These  were  mainly  the  work  of  the  group  of  older  men,  for  of 
the  55  books  which  have  been  published  in  the  decade  only 
five  have  been  written  by  those  whose  doctorates  were  granted 
in  1906  and  subsequently.  Two  men  were  responsible  for 
one  book  each,  two  for  two  books  each,  four  for  three  books 
each,  one  for  four  books,  and  one  for  fifteen  books.  The  years 
of  publication  of  the  55  books  are  shown  in  Table  I. 

Mention  has  already  been  made  of  the  increase  in  the 
expected  contributors  owing  to  the  granting  of  the  doctorate. 
The  original  42  names  have  had  added  to  them  an  equal 
number.  Of  these  additional  42,  14  published  previous  to 
the  doctorate.  The  first  publication  after  the  doctorate,  in 
most  cases  dissertations  or  parts  of  dissertations,  of  18  was 
made  in  the  year  of  the  doctorate,  of  10  the  first  publication 
was  in  the  year  following  the  doctorate,  of  9  in  the  second 
year,  of  i  in  the  third  year,  of  2  in  the  fourth  year,  and  of  I 
in  the  fifth  year  after  the  granting  of  the  doctorate.  No 
publication  by  one  who  received  the  doctorate  in  1913  had 
been  made  up  to  and  including  1915.  These  figures  show  that 
either  our  means  of  publication  are  insufficient,  or  that  the 
dissertations  presented  in  partial  satisfaction  of  the  doctorate 
are  not  nearly  ready  for  (or  are  not  worthy  of)  publication, 
or  both.1 

The  42  individuals  who  had  received  the  doctorate  prior 
to  I9062  might  each  have  contributed  something  in  each  of  the 
ten  years  under  consideration,  but  only  seven  did  so.  Seven 
others  contributed  in  9  of  the  ten  years;  4  in  8;  4  in  7;  6  in  6; 
I  in  5;  2  in  4;  3  in  3;  2  in  2;  2  in  only  one  of  the  years;  and  4 
had  no  publications.  Those  who  received  the  doctorate  in 
1906  and  subsequently  can  not  be  dealt  with  in  the  same  man- 

1  It  might  be  well  for  university  authorities  to  deal  a  little  more  strictly  with  the 
matter  of  publication.    The  publication  of  a  dissertation  in  part  or  as  a  whole  is  the 
only  evidence  to  the  world  outside  of  the  particular  university  that  the  individual  has 
shown  a  capacity  for  investigation,  one  of  the  main  doctorate  requirements  in  all  in- 
stitutions of  which  I  have  knowledge. 

2  Including  the  two  who  have  not  taken  the  doctorate. 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  207 

ner,  but  the  groups  in  accordance  with  the  percentage  of  years 
in  which  contributions  were  made,  counting  the  total  of 
years  since  the  doctorate  as  the  expected  total,  are  as  follows : 
o,  i;  from  I  to  10  per  cent.,  7;  n  to  20  per  cent,  5;  21  to  30,  4; 
31  to  40,  5;  41  to  50,  13;  51  to  60,  I ;  61  to  70,  i;  71  to  80,  3; 
100  per  cent.,  8.  The  number  of  older  men  who  averaged  at 
least  one  contribution  for  every  two  years,  or  more  often,  is 
double  that  of  the  younger  men.  The  younger  men  had 
more  than  two  thirds  of  their  number  who  did  not  publish 
as  much  as  one  contribution  for  every  two  years.  It  should 
further  be  stated  that  of  the  younger  men  placed  in  the  most 
regular  class  (100  per  cent.)  one  contributed  original  work  in 
only  one  of  8  years,  a  second  in  only  two  of  6  years,  a  third  in 
six  of  7  years,  and  a  fourth  in  two  of  3  years.  The  other  4 
contributed  an  article  or  monograph  in  each  of  the  expected 
years.  Of  the  older  men  in  the  100  per  cent,  class,  one  failed 
to  report  original  work  in  only  one  of  the  ten  years,  one  did 
not  report  such  work  for  two  of  the  years,  and  two  for  three 
of  the  years.  Three  contributed  at  least  one  article  or  mono- 
graph in  each  of  the  ten  years. 

Comparing  the  two  groups  we  find  that  of  the  420  ex- 
pected individual  years  of  publication  of  the  older  group  (10 
years  each  for  42  individuals)  there  were  only  257  individual 
years  of  publication,  a  percentage  of  61;  of  the  younger  group 
there  were  214  expected  years  and  an  actual  total  of  109,  a 
percentage  of  51.  This  difference  is  entirely  accounted  for  by 
the  long  delay  in  publication  after  the  doctorate,  for  if  the 
delay  periods  be  subtracted  from  the  total  there  is  a  percentage 
of  6 1  for  the  younger  men.  Although  there  is  not  a  sufficient 
number  of  years  to  make  the  conclusion  certain,  the  figures 
would  lead  to  the  belief  that  when  the  younger  men  start 
there  is  not  a  great  difference  in  total  productivity  between 
them  and  the  older  men.  My  impression  previous  to  tabu- 
lation was  the  reverse,  probably  because  of  some  notable 
examples  of  productivity  of  the  older  men.  The  latter  is 
counterbalanced  by  the  fact  that  there  are  five  of  our  pro- 
fessional psychologists,  four  of  the  older  group  and  one  of  the 
younger  group  (the  latter  case  mentioned  above),  who  have 


208 


SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ, 


not  published  anything  worthy  of  citation  in  the  PSYCHO- 
LOGICAL INDEX  in  ten  years. 

The  individual  differences  which  have  been  mentioned  are 
better  shown  when  we  compare  the  totals  and  yearly  averages 
for  the  individuals  of  the  groups.  It  would  not  be  expedient 
to  mention  names  of  individuals,  or  to  designate  them  in 
recognizable  terms,  so  that  we  must  fall  back  upon  generalities 
of  individual  differences.  Of  the  older  group  there  are  four 
who  did  not  make  a  scientific  contribution  of  such  a  character 
or  in  such  a  journal  as  to  be  deemed  worthy  of  mention  in 
the  INDEX  in  the  decade;  there  is  only  one  of  the  younger 
group.  In  addition  the  contributions  of  one  of  the  older 

TABLE  IV 

DISTRIBUTION  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS  ACCORDING  TO  THE  NUMBERS  OF 
CONTRIBUTIONS  IN  THE  DECADE,  1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE 


Number  of  Publications 

Total  Publications 

Articles  and  Monographs 

Older 

Younger 

Older 

Younger 

o 

4 

14 

12 

5 
7 

I 

35 
4 
i 

i 

,1 

16 

4 
i 

I 

38 
2 
I 
O 

I  tO  IO 

II  tO  2O 

21  tO  30 

3  1  and  over  

TABLE  V 

COMPARISON  OF  TOTALS  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  CONTRIBUTIONS  BY  THE  OLDER  AND 

YOUNGER  GROUPS  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS  FOR  THE  DECADE, 

1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE 


Articles 

Mono- 
graphs 

Books 

Discus- 
sions 

General 
Reviews 

Reports 

Totals 

Older  
Younger  

369 
123 

19 

26 

50 
5 

55 
II 

109 
52 

18 

14 

620 

231 

group  consisted  exclusively  of  the  class  of  general  reviews  and 
reports.  The  accompanying  tables  show  the  distribution 
of  the  men  in  accordance  with  their  scientific-literary  pro- 
ductivity. In  Table  IV.  there  are  shown  the  numbers  of 
individuals  in  each  group  in  relation  to  the  total  number  of 
publications  and  in  relation  to  the  publications  of  articles 
and  monographs.  In  Table  V.  there  are  shown  the  different 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  209 

kinds  of  publications  (articles,  monographs,  books,  etc.) 
according  to  the  groups.  The  average  total  number  of  con- 
tributions for  the  decade  by  the  older  men  is  14.8,  for  the 
younger  men  it  is  5.5;  the  average  of  articles  and  monographs 
by  the  older  men  is  9.2,  and  by  the  younger  men  only  3.5. 
These  figures  may  be  somewhat  misleading  if  taken  as  they 
stand,  on  account  of  the  difference  in  the  total  number  of 
years  that  might  be  expected  for  scientific  publication.  The 
total  years  for  the  older  group  has  already  been  said  to  be 
420  (42  individuals  for  10  years),  and  214  for  the  younger 
group.  When  the  comparison  is  made  of  total  publications 
and  of  original  (monograph  and  article)  publications  of  the 
older  group  and  of  the  younger  group  in  relation  to  the  ex- 
pected number  of  years  it  is  also  found  that  the  older  group 
outranks  the  younger.  Thus  the  individual  yearly  average 
for  total  contributions  for  the  older  group  is  1.5,  and  only  I.I 
for  the  younger  group;  and  the  individual  yearly  averages  for 
articles  and  monographs  are  respectively  .92  and  .69  for  the 
older  and  the  younger  men. 

It  is  interesting  to  speculate  on  the  reasons  for  these  dif- 
ferences. Doubtless  in  most  institutions  the  younger  men 
are  employed  a  greater  part  of  the  time  in  preparation  of 
materials  for  the  laboratory  work  of  students  and  in  the 
grading  of  themes,  etc.  In  the  smaller  and  less  well  endowed 
institutions  there  is  less  aid  for  the  prosecution  of  investiga- 
tions, and  if  aid  can  be  obtained  it  takes  an  exorbitant 
amount  of  time  to  get  the  administrative  machinery  in 
running  order.  At  the  same  time  the  younger  group  has  to 
take  considerable  time  in  the  preparation  of  material  for  their 
courses  of  instruction,  and  they  are  more  frequently  called 
upon  to  act  as  subjects  or  assistants  for  other  research  workers. 
On  the  whole  the  older  group  has  the  advantage  of  long  estab- 
lished policies,  of  equipment,  and  of  professional  and  me- 
chanical assistance.  At  the  same  time  the  labor  of  teaching 
is  correspondingly  less  on  account  of  the  previous  experiences. 
Perhaps  if  we  should  compare  the  work  of  the  older  group,  or 
of  as  many  of  them  as  held  positions  in  the  decade  of  1891 
to  1900,  with  that  of  the  present  younger  group  we  should 
not  find  as  great  differences  as  now  exist. 


210  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

On  account  of  the  differences  in  time  opportunity  it  is  to 
be  expected  that  the  younger  group  would  publish  less  in  total 
and  that  the  individual  total  would  be  less  than  many  of 
those  of  the  older  group.  Thus  we  find  that  nearly  one  half 
(19)  of  the  older  group  reached  or  exceeded  the  average  of  1.5 
publications  per  year,  and  that  only  one  third  (12)  of  the 
younger  group  equalled  or  exceeded  the  yearly  average  for 
that  group  (.5  publications  per  year).  Table  IV.  gives  the 
results  of  the  groupings.  This  shows  that  more  than  one 
half  of  the  older  men  averaged  one  publication  per  year, 
seven  having  more  than  three  per  year  The  figures  for  the 
younger  group  must  be  read  in  the  light  of  the  total  yearly 
expectation  (214  instead  of  420).  Each  individual  should  be 
considered  in  relation  to  the  total  of  his  expected  years  of 
publication.  Thus  the  six  individuals  of  the  younger  group 
who  exceeded  ten  publications  had  a  total  publication  ex- 
pectation of  44  years.  The  total  of  publications  was  124, 
which  gives  a  yearly  average  less  than  3. 

The  data  with  regard  to  the  character  of  the  publications 
of  the  two  groups  are  given  in  Table  V.  The  difference  in 
the  number  of  books  has  already  been  mentioned.  Mono- 
graphs are  apparently  the  prerogative  of  the  younger  man, 
the  newly  created  doctor,  for  he  has  in  proportion  to  the 
expected  years  two  and  one  half  times  as  many  as  his  older 
colleague.  The  older  men  publish  33  per  cent,  more  articles, 
as  has  been  mentioned,  they  take  part  in  more  controversies 
as  judged  by  the  number  of  discussions,  and  they  contribute 
an  equal  share  of  the  general  reviews.  With  regard  to  the 
last  the  remark  may  be  necessary  that  the  general  review  is 
most  frequently  due  to '  request'  and  not  infrequently  a  request 
to  the  elder  is  declined  in  favor  of  a  younger  colleague. 

Since  the  different  kinds  of  contributions  are  so  varied  no 
direct  comparison  may  be  made  of  individuals  except  in  terms 
such  as  have  already  been  used  (total  number  of  contribu- 
tions, number  of  monographs  and  articles,  and  the  relation  of 
these  to  the  expected  years  of  publication).  An  indirect 
comparison  may,  however,  be  made  if  we  assign  to  the  differ- 
ent classes  of  publications  an  arbitrary  numerical  value.  This 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  2 1 1 

must  be  very  arbitrary  on  account  of  the  impossibility  of 
making  good  comparisons  of  values,  as  has  already  been  ex- 
plained.    It  is  also  to  be  kept  in  mind  that  no  arbitrary  value 
for  a  class  can  be  defended  in  particular  cases,  for  if  we  con- 
sider two  articles  we  may  immediately  note  that  one  deals 
with  an  investigation  in  which  some  new  methods  have  been 
used  and  the  analysis  of  factors  appears  to  be  well  wrought 
out,  and  we  may  also  find  that  the  second  consists  of  a  con- 
firmation of  previous  work  by  the  use  of  the  same  methods 
which  had  previously  been  used.     Even  in  two  articles  which 
contain  new  facts  or  demonstrate  new  methods  we  may  find 
similarities  and  divergencies  of  completeness  or  of  apparent 
originality.     It  favors  the  majority  of  low  grade  (if  we  may  use 
such  a  term)  publications  if  we  assign  the  same  arbitrary  value 
to  all  of  one  class,  and  this  I  haveidone.    The  values  which  I  have 
selected  for  the  different  classes  of  publications  are  as  follows : 
Reports  of  Meetings,  i;  General  Reviews,  2;  Discussions,  3; 
Books,  6;  Articles,  6;  Monographs,  9.     No  justification  of 
these  arbitrary  values  will  be  attempted,  but  the  following 
were  in  mind  when  the  values  were  assigned.     A  discussion  is 
often  of  no  observable  value  in  adding  to  our  knowledge,  and 
scientifically  is  worse  than  useless  when  it  takes  on  the  char- 
acter of  a  personal  attack.     On  the  other  hand,  it  may  tend 
to  clear  up  doubtful  points,  bring  up  new  ways  of  viewing  a 
situation,  and  at  the  same  time  by  pointing  out  gaps  in  our 
knowledge  indicate  lines  of  investigation.     In  so  far  as   a 
discussion  does  any  of  the  latter  things  it  appeared  that  it 
has  a  real  value  beyond  that  of  a  report  of  a  meeting,  and 
since  a  discussion  also  tends  at  times  to  inter  in  a  suitable 
manner  some  supposed  facts  which  very  generally,  but  er- 
roneously, have  been  accepted  it  was  thought  worthy  of  a 
greater  value  than  that  of  a  general  review.     It  is  assumed 
that  all  of  our  psychological  discussions  are  of  the  good  char- 
acter mentioned.     Differences  exist  in  general  reviews.     Some 
are  summaries  of  a  few  contributions  of  others.     Some  give  a 
fairly  complete  account  of  current  work  with  an  evaluation 
of  the  material  and  thus  help  others  who  are  not  specializing 
in  the  subject  to  obtain   a  better  view  than  would  be  ob- 


2 1 2  SHEPHERD  IVOR Y  FRANZ 

tained  by  looking  over  the  mass  of  details  which  the  original 
sources  contain.  Some  of  the  general  reviews  which  we  are 
considering  here  may  be  worthy  of  a  higher  value  than  some 
of  the  discussions,  but  many  might  bear  a  reduction  of  the 
general  value  figure.  Here  again  it  became  necessary  to 
decide  for  the  majority  rather  than  for  the  few.  Much  the 
same  may  be  said  with  regard  to  books.  Although  the  writer 
does  not  pretend  to  have  the  specialist's  critical  ability  in 
every  branch  of  psychology  he  is  satisfied  that  many  books 
published  during  the  period  are  nothing  more  than  general 
reviews,  and  at  times  poor  ones.  Some  of  the  books  have 
brought  out  new  facts  and  explanations,  they  have  added 
considerably  to  our  psychological  advance.  But  because  of 
their  general  character  it  is  thought  that  a  value  double 
that  of  a  discussion  and  triple  that  of  a  general  review  would 
be  an  ample  average  value.  The  original,  or  research  article 
(whether  experimental  or  otherwise)  was  assigned  a  value 
equal  to  that  of  a  book,  and  the  monograph  (but  only  on 
account  of  its  length  and  supposed  completeness)  was  assigned 
a  value  fifty  per  cent,  higher.  The  remark  previously  made 
regarding  monographs,  that  some  monographs  would  be 
articles  in  other  publication  series,  is  a  point  against  such  a 
valuation,  and  the  valuation  is  not  insisted  upon.  The 
increase  in  value  is  on  the  side  of  the  younger  men,  who 
most  need  the  extra  count. 

Having  selected  the  arbitrary  values  which  have  been 
mentioned  it  becomes  possible  to  make  comparisons  of  the 
output  of  different  individuals  without  making  special  refer- 
ence of  an  identifying  character.  At  the  same  time  it 
becomes  possible  to  make  comparisons  of  the  groups  since  the 
heterogeneity  of  the  different  kinds  of  publications  has  been 
translated  into  a  homogeneity. 

The  calculation  of  the  individual  values  for  the  ten-year 
period  shows  that  the  range  is  from  zero  to  244.  This  means 
that  some  have  contributed  nothing  and  that  others  range 
from  the  zero  point  up  to  a  valuation  of  24.4  points  per  year. 
It  is  necessary  to  translate  all  the  total  valuations  of  the 
younger  group  into  *  expected'  values,  or  average  yearly 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS 


213 


values  in  accordance  with  the  number  of  expected  years  of 
publication.  When  this  is  done  for  all  individuals  we  find 
that  there  is  a  general  average  of  6.7  points  per  year  for  the 
group  as  a  whole,  and  a  median  of  4.2.  When  the  five  in- 
dividuals who  have  not  contributed  even  as  much  as  a  report 
of  a  meeting  during  the  decade  are  omitted  the  average  is 
7.2  and  the  median  is  4.5.  The  distribution  of  the  84  in- 
dividuals in  respect  to  average  yearly  values  of  publications 
is  given  in  Table  VI.  Eighteen  of  the  older  group  and 
twenty-five  of  the  younger  group  are  below  the  median  of 
all  values;  22  of  the  older  and  30  of  the  younger  groups  are 
below  the  average  of  the  total.  Arranging  all  in  sequence  of 
average  yearly  values  and  dividing  into  four  equal  parts,  each 
containing  21  men,  we  find  the  following  distribution  of  the 
older  and  younger  respectively  in  the  groups  from  lowest  to 
highest:  older,  10,  7,  n,  14;  younger,  II,  14,  10,  7. 

TABLE  VI 

GROUPING    OF    PROFESSIONAL    PSYCHOLOGISTS    ACCORDING    TO    AVERAGE    YEARLY 
"VALUES"  OF  CONTRIBUTIONS  FOR  THE  DECADE,  1906-1915,  INCLUSIVE 


I.O 

Values 

and 

I.I— 

2.1- 

3-1- 

4.1- 

5-1- 

6.1- 

7.1- 

8.1- 

9.1- 

IO.I- 

15.1- 

Under 

2.O 

3-° 

4.0 

5-0 

6.0 

7.0 

8.0 

9.0 

10.0 

15-0 

*5-o 

Number  of  men 

Q 

14. 

Q 

Q 

Q 

2 

o 

c 

c 

4. 

The  older  group  on  account  of  time,  material  equipment, 
academic  relations,  and  other  conditions  has  advantages  which 
make  it  of  special  interest.  All  of  the  individuals  had  attained 
their  higher  degrees  previous  to  1906,  about  three  quarters 
are  heads  of  departments,  and  about  the  same  number  are 
connected  with  well-equipped  and  long-established  labor- 
atories. This  group  furnished  four  individuals  who  did  not 
make  a  published  contribution  of  any  kind  to  psychological 
advancement  in  the  decade.  Six  of  the  group  contributed 
one  original  article  or  monograph  during  the  ten-year  period; 
two  contributed  two  original  contributions;  two  contributed 
three;  and  three  contributed  four.  We  have  in  this  group, 
therefore,  forty  per  cent,  who  have  not  averaged  an  original 
contribution  once  in  two  years.  Some  of  these  seventeen 


214  SHEPHERD  IVORY  FRANZ 

individuals  did  contribute  in  other  directions  besides  mono- 
graphs and  articles,  for  they  published  5  books,  33  general 
reviews,  2  discussions,  and  wrote  one  report  of  a  meeting. 
Besides  the  four  who  did  not  make  any  kind  of  a  contribution 
there  were  four  additional  who  made  no  contribution  beyond 
the  original  articles  and  monographs  published.  On  the 
whole  the  younger  group,  while  not  as  productive  as  the 
older,  show  better  results  with  respect  to  the  publication  of 
individuals.  Only  one  (duration  three  years)  has  not  pub- 
lished, as  is  mentioned  above.  Ten  others  have  not  published 
as  frequently  as  once  in  three  years;  there  is  a  total  of  sixteen 
who  have  not  published  as  frequently  as  once  in  two  years. 

Since  the  older  group  had  the  opportunity  to  publish  for 
ten  years  we  need  not  deal  with  averages  entirely,  but  may 
consider  totals  as  well,  on  account  of  the  homogeneity  of  the 
series.  It  is  of  interest  to  know  that  seven  of  the  group 
(17  per  cent.)  contributed  a  total  of  159  articles  and  mono- 
graphs (41  per  cent.);  the  highest  half  of  the  group  (21) 
contributed  eighty-seven  per  cent,  of  all  the  articles  and 
monographs  of  the  group  (337  articles  and  monographs). 
This  leaves  for  fifty  per  cent,  of  the  older  men  only  thirteen 
per  cent,  of  the  articles  and  monographs  published  by  the 
group. 

The  majority  of  older  men  who  have  contributed  little  in 
the  way  of  articles  and  monographs,  and  also  to  the  total, 
have  held  their  present  positions  for  many  years,  and  have 
apparently  *  grown  up'  in  their  present  locations,  they  are 
located  in  some  of  our  better  endowed  institutions,  and  in 
those  with  good  laboratory  facilities,  they  have  colleagues 
teaching  in  the  same  lines,  and  they  occupy  what  may  be 
properly  called  positions  of  prominence  in  their  respective 
institutions.  They  have  not  the  apparent  disadvantages  of 
isolation,  or  of  having  to  carry  the  burden  of  the  psycho- 
logical world  upon  their  shoulders  since  there  are  colleagues 
to  help  in  teaching  and  perhaps  in  research.  But  these  are 
some  of  the  men  who  are  representing  psychology  as  a  science 
in  their  respective  university  niches.  Those  of  the  younger 
group  who  are  least  productive,  and  have  given  little  evidence 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  2 1 5 

of  interest  in  psychological  advance  by  publication,  are 
mostly  located  in  the  smaller  institutions,  where  there  are  no 
colleagues  of  sufficient  training  or  productiveness  to  be  elected 
members  of  the  American  Psychological  Association.  There 
are  in  the  younger  group  exceptions  to  this,  several  notable 
cases  being  evident  when  the  list  is  inspected.  Without 
going  into  the  figures  for  total  or  original  publications,  since 
the  number  of  men  at  the  different  institutions  is  small,  it 
may  be  stated  that  those  younger  men  who  have  the  oppor- 
tunity to  remain  at  a  long-established  department  have  done 
better  than  those  in  the  more  recently  created  departments. 
But  this  does  not  hold  for  particular  cases,  since  there  are 
surprising  exceptions  of  individuals  with  apparently  all  the 
advantages  which  can  be  obtained  in  the  better  endowed 
institutions  doing  little  or  nothing  which  is  prepared  for  the 
edification  of  their  scientific  colleagues. 

It  should  not  be  assumed,  and  it  is  here  stated  to  the 
contrary  in  order  that  there  may  be  no  misunderstanding, 
that  these  men  are  doing  nothing  for  psychological  advance. 
Some  may  have  editorial  duties,  some  may  conceal  themselves 
in  the  work  of  their  students,  and  some  (like  Herbert  Spencer) 
may  be  reserving  their  energies  for  some  magna  opera  which 
will  be  given  to  the  world  in  due  time.  It  seems  unlikely, 
however,  that  as  many  as  40  per  cent,  of  the  older  group  are 
engaged  in  the  accumulation  of  material  for  the  development 
of  a  cosmology,  or  of  a  system  of  psychology,  or  of  an  ex- 
haustive history  of  the  science,  or  of  other  large  projects  which 
should  not  be  laid  aside  in  favor  of  the  minor  contributions 
such  as  articles  and  monographs.  It  is  apparent  that  a  few 
of  those  who  hold  chairs  of  psychology  are  contenting  them- 
selves with  teaching  and  the  carrying  out  of  the  social  obli- 
gations which  fall  to  the  lot  of  every  scientific  man,  who  must 
meet  his  colleagues  and  take  part  in  the  life  of  the  university 
with  which  he  is  connected.  Whether  or  not  there  are  more 
psychologists  who  are  doing  these  things  than  scientific  men 
in  other  lines  can  not  now  be  determined.  And,  the  other 
view  may  be  expressed  that  those  who  are  contributing  much 
do  so  without  proper  scientific  care  and  because  of  reportorial 


2 1 6  SHEPHERD  IVOR  Y  FRANZ 

tendencies.  The  character  of  the  work  of  many  of  our  most 
productive  men  shows  that  they  have  not  done  their  work  at 
the  expense  of  care.  But,  the  writer  feels  that  some  of  the 
so-called  'professional'  psychologists  should  be  classed  with 
dilettantes;  they  are  not  scientific  professionals  in  the  sense 
that  they  are  forging  ahead  and  that  they  are  succeeding 
because  of  their  efforts  in  scientific  work. 

Much  has  been  written  recently  about  university  positions  and  university  control; 
the  professor  always  being  the  oppressed  and  the  university  as  represented  by  the 
president  being  the  oppressor.  I  have  a  feeling  that  part  of  the  dissatisfaction  may 
be  due  to  the  'great  promise'  for  which  candidates  have  been  recommended  never 
showing  up  in  practice.  A  president  of  one  of  our  leading  institutions  has  been  criti- 
cized for  saying  that  every  man  on  the  faculty  may  be  expected  to  publish  at  least  one 
article  every  two  years.  It  may  be  that  he  had  had  experience  with  those  of  'promise' 
and  not  of  performance.  Much  has  also  been  written  about  academic  tenure,  as  if 
that  was  a  sacred  right  (or  rite),  but  the  critic  might  well  imagine  a  better  state  of 
affairs  to  follow  in  some  of  our  universities  if  there  was  a  power  of  recall  for  those 
members  of  the  faculty  who  do  not  measure  up  to  the  expected  or  to  the  average  amount 
of  performance.  If  the  present  methods  of  filling  positions,  from  the  grade  of  professor 
down  to  that  of  instructor,  be  continued  we  shall  always  have  some  of  little  or  no  ac- 
complishment (the  dilettantes)  filling  important  chairs,  especially  if  there  be  the  added 
conditions  that  promotions  be  made  as  vacancies  occur.  It  is  the  writer's  belief  that 
much  of  the  inconsistencies  would  be  eliminated  if  every  vacancy  were  advertised  as 
open  to  application,  stating  that  applicants  were  expected  to  send  in  the  accounts  of 
their  academic  careers,  copies  of  publications,  etc.,  and  that  these  would  be  graded  by 
a  non-interested  committee  of  specialists  (advisory  board)  who  would  report  to  the 
faculty  or  to  trustees  the  results  of  their  findings.  We  should  probably  escape  the 
absurdity  of  having  in  one  year  two  young  men  recommended  from  one  university  as 
'geniuses  of  the  first  water.'  This  has  happened,  and  the  writer  is  not  certain  which  is 
to  be  the  more  pitied,  the  university  which  permitted  its  'geniuses'  to  go  to  other  in- 
stitutions, or  the  universities  which  would  accept  men  who  were  recommended  as  such. 

Another  matter  may  be  worth  considering  briefly.  This 
is  the  relation  of  productivity  to  the  institutions  from  which 
the  higher  degrees  were  received.  In  pointing  to  psycho- 
logical advances  in  institutions,  we  have  hitherto  been 
content  to  mention  the  number  of  doctorates  which  have 
been  granted.  But  it  is  obvious  that  numbers  count  for 
very  little  in  progress,  unless  one  is  going  to  play  a  mass  game 
or  overrun  a  weak  nation.  What  should  be  considered  is  the 
question:  What  have  the  doctors  done  after  leaving  an  in- 
stitution? And  we  may  also  ask:  Has  the  training  which  is 
supposed  to  fit  the  man  for  research  been  effective  in  stimu- 
lating him  to  efforts  in  that  direction?  Part  of  these  ques- 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS 


217 


tions  may  be  answered  by  considering  the  performance  of 
those  granted  higher  degrees  by  different  institutions.  Of  the 
84  men  on  the  present  list  17  were  scattering  with  respect  to 
institutions,  but  the  remainder  were  distributed  over  seven 
institutions.  Only  one  institution  is  mentioned  by  name 
(Leipzig),  the  other  individual  institutions  (American)  are 
represented  by  letters.  The  17  scattering  cases  are  grouped 
together  as  'other  foreign'  and  'other  American.'  Table  VII. 

TABLE  VII 

COMPARISON  OF  PUBLICATIONS  OF  ALL  KINDS  AND  OF  ARTICLES  AND  MONOGRAPHS, 
BY  GROUPS  OF  PROFESSIONAL  PSYCHOLOGISTS,  ARRANGED  ACCORDING  TO  IN- 
STITUTIONS CONFERRING  DOCTORATES.  (Two  INDIVIDUALS  WHO  HAVE  NOT 
RECEIVED  THE  DOCTORATE  ARE  INCLUDED  UNDER  THE  INSTITUTIONS  WHICH 
CONFERRED  THEIR  HIGHER  DEGREES) 


Institutions 

Leipzig 

A 

B 

c 

D 

E 

F 

Other 
Foreign 

Other 
American 

Numbers  of  men 

8 

78 

859 

1  1.0 

3-6- 
18.6 

603 
7-7 

II 

79 

674 

8.8 

1-5- 
19-3 

Sio 
6-5 

7 
54 

421 

7.8 

i.i- 
23.0 

360 
6.7 

15 

132 

884 
6.7 

o.o- 

24.4 
708 

54 

II 

74 

38i 
5-i 

1.4- 
14.0 

312 
4.2 

8 
58 

226 
3-9 

0.6- 
"•3 

198 
3-4 

7 
42 

103 

2-5 

o.o- 

7.5 

96 
2.3 

6 

57 

422 
7-4 

0.6- 
9-4 

348 
6.1 

II 

60 

269 

4-5 
o.o- 

10.2 

222 

3-7 

Total  expected  years 

All  publications: 
Total  credits 

Credits  -T-  years  

Range    of    average    yearly 
credits  of  individuals  

Articles  and  monographs: 
Credits      

Credits  -f-  years  

gives  the  numbers  of  men  from  different  institutions,  the  total 
years  under  consideration  (the  total  *  expected'  years  of  all 
in  the  special  group),  the  total  credits,  the  relation  of  credits 
to  the  total  expected  years  of  publication,  and  the  minimum 
and  maximum  average  yearly  credits  by  the  individuals  in  the 
groups. 

Probably  the  total  expected  years,  rather  than  number 
of  individuals,  is  a  better  means  of  comparison  with  the  totals 
of  publications,  and  the  relation  of  these  two  are  shown  in  the 
fifth  line.  Here  it  will  be  observed  that  the  8  men  from  Leip- 
zig far  surpass  the  groups  from  the  other  universities.  They 
have  the  highest  minimum,  showing  that  each  is  publishing 
fairly  regularly,  and  although  they  are  surpassed  in  maxima 
by  three  other  institutions  this  is  largely  due  to  a  few  very 


2 1 8  SHEPHERD  I  FOR  Y  FRANZ 

productive  men.  The  men  from  Leipzig  have  mostly  been 
of  the  older  group,  as  indicated  by  the  average  of  expected 
years  (9.8),  but  the  average  is  not  much  greater  than  that 
(9.5  years)  for  the  group  from  Other  Foreign  Institutions. 
Leipzig  also  closely  approaches  the  total  of  C,  although  the 
number  of  men  is  only  slightly  over  half,  and  the  total  number 
of  expected  years  is  about  60  per  cent,  of  this  American 
university.  The  order  of  institutions  in  total  credits  divided 
by  expected  years  is  as  follows:  Leipzig,  A,  B,  Other  Foreign, 
C,  D,  Other  American,  E,  and  F.  When  now  we  compare 
the  performance  of  the  doctors  from  the  different  institutions 
in  relation  to  publication  of  articles  and  monographs  we  find 
the  results  shown  in  the  last  two  lines  of  Table  VII.  Here 
again  Leipzig  shows  a  great  superiority.  The  order  of  in- 
stitutions in  credits  divided  by  years  has  not  materially 
changed,  there  being  a  reversal  of  the  order  for  B  and  A.  The 
remainder  of  the  table  speaks  for  itself. 

One  matter  remains  to  be  briefly  considered.  This  is  the 
relation  of  administrative  work  to  the  carrying  on  of  scientific 
production.  Our  group  contains  five  individuals  who  have 
given  their  occupation  as  partly  that  of  dean  or  president. 
Two  of  these  individuals  notwithstanding  their  arduous 
administrative  duties  have  managed  to  carry  on  investiga- 
tions and  to  publish  the  results  of  them.  At  the  same  time 
they  have  both  for  total  and  for  original  publications  managed 
to  be  in  the  more  productive  class.  The  other  three  probably 
have  their  administrative  duties  as  reasons  for  their  relative 
non-performance.  In  the  group  there  are  also  eleven  who 
have  greater  or  less  editorial  duties  in  connection  with  the 
publication  of  periodicals.  Of  this  group  two  have  been 
below  the  average  in  performance.  Both  of  these  extra- 
scientific  duties  (administration  and  editing)  have  not  inter- 
fered with  the  production  of  an  average  amount  of  scientific 
articles  by  two  thirds  of  the  men  thus  engaged,  and  it  may 
be  that  these  added  functions  have  been  beneficial  rather  than 
the  reverse.  In  the  estimation  of  productivity  of  individuals 
editorial  functions  have  been  omitted  and  had  these  been 
added  to  the  totals  in  some  numerical  way  it  is  quite  likely 


PRODUCTIVITY  OF  AMERICAN  PSYCHOLOGISTS  219 

that  more  of  the  group  of  editors  would  have  approached  the 
top.  As  the  arrangement  now  stands,  counting  only  articles, 
books,  reviews,  etc.,  we  find  that  two  thirds  are  in  the  higher 
half  of  the  distribution,  and  of  these  most  are  in  the  higher 
quarter. 

It  is  pertinent  to  remark  that  psychology  appears  to  be 
getting  from  those  whose  chief  interests  are  not  in  its  de- 
velopment (from  the  non-professional  psychologists,  in  other 
words)  as  much  as,  if  not  more  than,  from  many  of  its  own 
men.1  From  some  of  its  own  psychology  is  receiving  much 
less  than  should  be  expected,  and  there  is,  perhaps,  some 
reason  for  the  assertion  that  "were  it  not  for  an  academic  title 
it  would  be  difficult  to  discover  the  reason  why  certain  in- 
dividuals are  called  psychologists."  In  conclusion  the  at- 
tention of  the  reader  is  called  to  the  consideration  of  the 
wisdom  of  the  action  of  certain  scientific  societies  which 
require  that  a  member  shall  retain  membership  in  them  only 
as  long  as  he  continues  to  show  an  active  interest  in  the 
advancement  of  his  science  by  publication,  provided  con- 
tinued ill-health  or  other  disabling  conditions  (old  age  and 
the  like)  do  not  prevent.2 

1 1  expect  to  deal  with  the  psychological  contributions  of  these  non-professional 
members  of  the  Association  in  another  article. 

2  A  constitutional  amendment  of  this  character  was  recommended  by  its  council 
to  the  American  Psychological  Association  at  one  of  its  meetings,  and  at  the  subsequent 
meeting  the  council  reversed  its  recommendation  (see  the  Proceedings  of  the  Associ- 
ation for  the  years  1906  and  1907). 


THE   PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE   CASE 
OF   READING 

BY  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

Teachers  College,  Columbia  University 

If  a  person  is  presented  with  a  paragraph  to  read  and 
questions  about  it,  his  responses  provide  useful  material  for 
studying  some  of  the  facts  and  laws  of  thinking.  Consider, 
for  example,  the  following  task  and  the  following  responses 
made  to  the  first  question  by  pupils  of  grades  5  and  6: 

/ 

Read  this  and  then  write  the  answers  to  I,  2,  3, 4,  and  5.  Read  it  again  as 
often  as  you  need  to. 

Nearly  fifteen  thousand  of  the  city's  workers  joined  in  the  parade  on 
September  seventh,  and  passed  before  two  hundred  thousand  cheering  spec- 
tators. There  were  workers  of  both  sexes  in  the  parade,  though  the  men  far 
out-numbered  the  women. 

1.  What  is  said  about  the  number  of  persons  who  marched  in  the  parade? 

2.  Which  sex  was  in  the  majority? 

3.  What  did  the  people  who  looked  at  the  parade  do  when  it  passed  by? 

4.  How  many  people  saw  the  parade? 

5.  On  what  date  did  the  event  described  in  the  paragraph  occur? 


Two  hundred  people  About  two  thousand 

Three  thousand  Maybe  No.  12 

Thousand  About  2700 

Eighteen  thousand  Two  hundred  thousand  spectators  workers 

Two  thousand  in  the  parade 

Five  thousand  Two  hundred  thousand  spectators 

Ninety  thousand  Two  hundred  cheering 

Twenty-five  thousand  Nearly  115000  on  Sept.  of  people 

About  thirty-five  thousand  Nearly  sixteen  thousand 

Nearly  twenty  thousand  Hundred  thousand  spectators 

More  than  ten  thousand  It  is  said  about  the  number  or  group  of 

There  were  about  25000  people 

200,000  It  is  said  that  they  are  great 

It  was  200,000  A  very  great  deal 
220 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING  221 


A  lot  of  people 

Congregation 

There  were  a  great  lot  of  men 

The  men  outnumbered  the  women 

The  men  were  more  than  the  women 

There  were  more  men 

They  outnumbered  the  women 

There  the  par  on  number  the 

The  men  were  far  ahead  of  the  women 

Men  and  woman 

Citizens 

They  were  workers 

There  were  workers  of  both  sexes 

Workmen  in  the  parade 

Of  all  the  working  men 

That  the  city  workers  joined  the  parade 

Workers  joined  the  parade 

That  they  rejoin  in  the  parade 

They  were  joined 

A  number  of  workers  joined  the  parade 

Joined  the  parade 

Workers  join 

They  joined 

They  pass  two  hundred  spectators 

Before  the  spectators 

Passed  before  two  hundred  thousand  spec- 
tators 

They  two  hundred  thousand  cheering 
spectators 

Passed  before  200000  and  15000 


They  passed  nearly  5000 

Passed  before  two  hundred  spectators 

They  marched  before  cheering  spectators 

Three  thousand  cheering  them 

People  of  both  sexes  cheering  them 

They  are  cheered 

Parade  before  two  hundred  spectators 

Parade  spectators 

They  marched  nice 

They  marched  very  nice 

They  kept  in  step 

They  marched  very  straight 

They  did  good  or  bad 

They  look  so  nice 

They  clap  their  hands  when  they  see  the 

American  flag 

They  keep  their  step  and  many  others 
There  character 
Honorable  and  good 
The  people  said  the  parade  large 
Most  of  them  were  old 
They  are  soldiers  and  marched 
They  say  halt 
The  captain  says  march 
There  was  a  lot  of  floats 
The  people  are  killed  by  the  war 
The  meddles 
September  seventh 
Irish 


The  variety  of  responses  to  this  one  fairly  unambiguous 
question  is  a  challenge.  There  is  a  challenge  also  in  the 
relative  frequency  of  the  different  responses. 

I  shall  report  here  some  general  facts  which  are  displayed 
by  some  hundreds  of  responses  to  each  of  a  dozen  or  more 
sets  of  questions  upon  a  paragraph,  which  I  have  examined. 
The  first  is  that: 

When  a  question  on  a  paragraph  is  answered,  any  one 
word  may  be  over-potent  in  determining  the  response.  As  a 
limit  we  have  the  case  where  a  word  produces  a  response  due 
to  that  word  alone  irrespective  of  all  else  in  the  situation.  Or, 
more  generally,  any  element  in  a  situation  may  be  over-potent 
to  any  degree. 

The  evidence  supporting  this  claim  is  the  existence  of 


222  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

answers  or  elements  in  answers  which  could  come  as  probable 
results  or  over-potent  action  of  single  words,  but  whose  oc- 
currence otherwise  is  highly  improbable.  For  example,  in 
the  case  of  the  words  of  the  paragraph  such  influence  is  seen  of: 

thousand,  in  this  answer  to  3:  "The  people  cheered  thousands.'* 
city,  in  this  answer  to  2:  "City  workers." 

workers,  in  these  answers  to  2:  "Workers,"   "Workers  of  sex"; 
and  in  this  answer  to  3:  "There  were  workers." 

In  what  follows  a  number  in  parentheses  preceding  a 
response  designates  the  question  as  an  answer  to  which  the 
response  was  given. 

joined,  in  (i)  "They  joined,"  (i)  "They  were  joined,"  (3)  "They 

joined  in,"  (3)  "They  were  joined  in  the  parade,"  (3)  "They 

cheered  then  joined  in." 
parade,  in  (2)  "in  the  parade,"  (2)  "Both  in  parade,"  (2)  "Sexes  in 

the  parade." 

September,  in  (2)  "There  were  workers  of  the  September." 
seventh,  in  (2)  "Seventh,"  (3)  "September  seventh,"  (3)  "Seventh 

Avenue." 

Lest  the  bizarre  nature  of  some  of  these  errors  lead  the 
reader  to  fancy  that  they  are  fragments,  or  answers  misplaced 
a  line  too  high  or  too  low,  I  may  note  here  that  every  quota- 
tion that  has  been  or  will  be  given  in  this  article  is,  unless 
specially  noted  at  the  time,  a  complete  answer,  as  given  by 
some  pupils,  and  undoubtedly  intended  for  the  question  whose 
number  it  bears.  Quotations  are  exact  except  that  the  first 
word  is  capitalized  whether  or  not  this  was  done  by  the  pupil. 

passed,  in  (3)  "Two  hundred  thousand  cheering  spectators  passed." 
spectators  in  (i)  "Parade  spectators,"  (i)  "Cheering  spectators," 

(1)  "Two  hundred  thousand  spectators  workers  in  the  parade," 

(2)  "Spectators  and  working,"  (3)  "The  people  who  looked 
cheered  the  spectators,"  (3)  "The  people  looked  and  cheered 
the  spectators,"  (2)  The  sex  spectators. 

cheering,  in  (2)  "Cheering." 

both,  in  (2)  "There  were  both  workers,"  (3)  "There  were  workers  in 

both  spectators." 
sexes,  in  (3)  "Six  in  the  parade,"  (3)  "Sixes,"  (3)  "Cheered  the  sex 

in  the  parade." 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING    223 

though,  in   (2)   "Though  the  men  marched  in  the  parade,"   (2) 
"Though  the  men  far  outjoined  parade." 

men,  in  (3)  "They  cheered  the  men  in  the  parade." 

far,  in  (2)  "Far  out  women." 

out,  in  (3)  "They  counted  out  how  many  women." 

numbered,  in  (3)  "The  men  numbered  women,"  (3)  "Numbered  the 
women,"  (3)  "They  numbered  the  people." 

out-numbered,  in  (2)  "Sex  out  numbered  of   women,"  (2)  "Out- 
numbered." 

women,  in  (2)  "Sexes  of  women,"  (2)  "Men  and  women,"  (3)  "The 
women." 
Any  phrase  or  other  part  of  a  sentence  tends  in  a  similar 

manner  to  produce  a  response  due  to  that  phrase  per  se. 
Thus,  fifteen  thousand  appears  as  an  answer  to  questions  2, 

3  and  4  and  (in  "Passed  before  200,000  and  15,000")  as  an 

answer  to  question  I.     The  following  are  responses  probably 

explainable  by  the  independent  action  of  phrases  or  other 

groups  of  words. 

the  city's  workers,  (2)  "  City  workers." 

joined  the  parade,  (i)  "Joined  the  parade,"  and  (2)  "They  joined 

the  parade." 

September  seventh,  (i)  "September  seventh." 
passed  before  two  hundred,  (3)  "Passed  before  two  hundred." 
two  hundred,  (i)  "Passed  before  200  spectators,"  (2)  "Two  hundred 

spectators,"  and  (4)  "Two  hundred." 
hundred  thousand,  (4)  "About  a  hundred  thousand." 
two  thousand,  (i)  "Two  thousand,"  and  (4)  "Two  thousand." 
two  hundred  thousand,   (i)   "Two  hundred  thousand,"   (2)   "Two 

hundred  thousand,"  and  (3)  "Two  hundred  thousand." 
There  were  workers,  (2)  "There  were  workers." 
of  both  sexes,  (i)  "People  of  both  sexes  cheering  them,"  and  (5) 

"Sept.  yth  both  sexes." 
There  were  workers  of  both  sexes,  (i)  "There  were  workers  of  both 

sexes,"  and   (3)   "There  were  workers  of  both  sexes  in  the 

parade." 
though  the  men,  (3)  "Though  the  men  far  out  joined  parade,"  and 

(5)  "Thought  the  man  fat  out." 
outnumbered  the  women,  (i)  "They  outnumbered  the  women,"  and 

(2)  "Sex  outnumbered  of  women." 

In  the  same  way  it  can  be  shown  that  every  word  and  every 


224  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

word  group  in  a  question  tends  to  produce  a  response  due  to 
that  word  or  word-group  per  se.  Consider  for  example  the 
responses  from  pupils  in  grades  7  and  8  to  Test  M. 

M 

However  certain  it  may  seem  to  be  that  men  work  only  because  they 
must,  and  would  avoid  labor  except  for  the  food,  clothing  and  luxuries  that 
are  its  rewards,  the  facts  may  well  be  to  the  contrary.  It  can  hardly  be  the 
case  that  men  dislike  work  because  they  wish  to  be  utterly  idle.  For  mere  rest, 
mere  inactivity,  is  not  commonly  enjoyed.  To  have  nothing  to  do  is  not  what 
men  seek.  Were  that  so,  we  should  envy  the  prisoner  shut  up  in  his  cell.  If 
men  had  to  choose  between  a  life  spent  at  eight  hours  of  work  daily  in  a  factory 
and  a  life  spent  at  eight  hours  of  sitting  on  a  throne  without  moving  hand  or 
foot,  many  of  them  would,  after  trying  both,  choose  the  former.  Activity  of 
body  or  mind,  at  which  a  man  can  succeed,  is,  in  and  of  itself,  rather  enjoyed 
than  disliked. 

1.  What  is  it  that  this  paragraph  says  may  seem  sure,  but  probably  is  false? 

2.  In  what  respect  is  a  prisoner  in  his  cell  like  a  man  with  a  million  dollars? 

3.  If  the  absence  of  any  activity  were  what  we  wished  for,  what  would  be  our 

attitude  toward  a  prisoner  in  his  cell? 

4.  What  is  stated  in  the  paragraph  to  be  really  liked  and  not  objected  to? 

5.  What  choice  is  described  in  the  paragraph  as  an  argument  that  work, 

merely  as  such,  is  not  always  avoided? 

In  question  I  the  influence  of  Paragraph  is  seen  in  such 
responses  as: 

"Work," 

"Labor," 

"Idle  men  and  working  men," 

"Idleness  and  wealth,"  and 

"Men  that  do  not  work." 

The  influence  of  Paragraph  says  is  seen  in: 

"It  says  that  men  should  not  avoid  labor," 

"It  says  that  some  men  work  and  some  of  them  would  be  idle,"  and 

"Some  men  envy  prisoners  in  a  cell  rather  than  work." 

The  influence  of  Sure  is  seen  in: 
"For  mere  rest  mere  inactivity  is  not  enjoyed." 

Similar  evidence  in  the  case  of  questions  2,  3,  4  and  5  is  as 
follows : 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING    225 

QUESTION  2 

prisoner  in  his  cell — "Because  he  is  shut  up  in  a  cell,"  and  "A  man 
in  prison  is  sitting  8  hours  daily  with  chains." 

QUESTION  3 

activity — "Is  rather  enjoyed   than  disliked,"  "For  mere  rest,  mere 

inactivity  is  not  enjoyed,"  and  "A  man  succeed  or  rather 

enjoyed  than  disliked." 
absence  of  activity — "Sluggish,"  "To  have  nothing  to  do  is  what 

men  seek,"  and  "Idleness." 
prisoner  in  his  cell — "He  would  not  be  there  unless  do  something 

wrong,"  and  "  Because  it  is  not  a  good  thing  to  be  a  prisoner." 

QUESTION  4 

is  stated — "Men  who  work,"  and  "That  the  American  man  wants 

to  work." 
really  liked — "Good  clothing  and  luxuries,"  and  "A  hard  work  man 

should  be  liked." 
objected  to — "Mere  rest  mere  inactivity  is  not  commonly  enjoyed," 

"Inactivity,"  and  "To  have  nothing  to  do." 

QUESTION  5 

choice — "The  man  who  works  and  the  one  who  does  not." 
described — "Why  men  work." 

avoided — "They  would  avoid  labor  if  it  was  for  food." 
work  avoided — "Idle  and  stealing." 

Consider  also  the  following  responses  to  questions  I,  2,  3 
and  4  on  paragraph  /. 

/ 

In  Franklin,  attendance  upon  school  is  required  of  every  child  between 
the  ages  of  seven  and  fourteen  on  every  day  when  school  is  in  session  unless 
the  child  is  so  ill  as  to  be  unable  to  go  to  school,  or  some  person  in  his  house 
is  ill  with  a  contagious  disease,  or  the  roads  are  impassable. 

1.  What  is  the  general  topic  of  the  paragraph? 

2.  On  what  day  would  a  ten-year-old  girl  not  be  expected  to  attend  school? 

3.  Between  what  years  is  attendance  upon  school  compulsory  in  Franklin? 

4.  How  many  causes  are  stated  which  make  absence  excusable? 


226  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

5.  What  kind  of  illness  may  permit  a  boy  to  stay  away  from  school,  even 

though  he  is  not  sick  himself? 

6.  What  condition  in  a  pupil  would  justify  his  non-attendance? 

7.  At  what  age  may  a  boy  leave  school  to  go  to  work  in  Franklin? 

1.  "Every  paragraph  must  have  a  period "")    , 

"A  group  of  complete  sentences"  }  due  tO 

2.  "Monday"       1 
"Wednesday"  ^due  to  day. 
"Friday"          j 

"The  ten  year  old  girl  will  be  5a,"  due  to  ten-year-old  girl. 

3.  "It  was  a  great  inventor"  \,  r       LJ. 
,,n                                .           .     ,.  r  due  to  /  ranklin. 
"Because  its  a  great  invention    J 

"Because  it  is  a  small  city,"  due  to  Franklin. 

4.  Twenty  five  ^ 

about  ninety  L  due  to  How  many. 
2000  J 

A  boy  should  bring  a  note"!    , 

Tr         ,    .  }•  due  to  absence  excusable. 

If  you  bring  a  note  J 

In  the  illustrations  given  so  far  the  action  of  the  element 
has  been  accompanied  usually  by  some  vague  action  of  the 
situation  as  a  whole,  but  cases  may  be  found  where  this 
reduces  to  about  as  near  zero  as  is  possible,  provided  the  pupil 
writes  any  answer  whatever. 

Consider,  for  example,  the  following  response  to  questions 
I,  2,  and  5  on  paragraph  /  (on  page  220). 

QUESTION  i 

"Most  of  them  were  old,"  which  shows  almost  no  effect  of  anything 

save  the  "persons." 
"There  were  a  lot  of  floats,"  which  shows  almost  no  influence  save 

of  "parade." 
"Irish,"  which  could  fit  any  paragraph  or  any  question  provided 

parade  or  persons  or  both  occurred  therein,  almost  as  well  as  it 

fits  this. 

QUESTION  2 

"  The  chief  commander  of  all "  and  "  Captain  and  lieutenant"  seem  to 
show  no  influence  save  the  major  of  majority  plus  a  faint  effect 
of  parade. 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING    227 

QUESTION  5 

"  1492"  and  "  1776"  seem  the  products  of  date  in  total  neglect  of  all 
else  in  the  question  and  paragraph. 

Some  of  the  cases  above,  if  taken  alone,  are  perhaps  as 
explainable  by  other  causes  as  by  the  tendency  of  each  word 
to  act  irrespective  of  the  total  of  which  it  is  an  element,  but 
no  one,  I  think,  will  assume  that  the  collection  can  be  well 
explained  save  by  supposing  that  the  single  words  do  have 
that  tendency.  We  must  then  think  of  the  pupil  who  ex- 
amines the  paragraph  and  the  questions  as  beset  by  a  tendency 
to  answer  each  question  by  each  word  in  the  paragraph  and 
have  each  word  in  the  questions  evoke  a  response  that  is 
bound  to  it  alone.  Most  of  these  tendencies  are  of  so  nearly 
zero  strength  that  they  almost  never  compete  successfully 
with  other  tendencies;  and  most  of  the  resulting  thoughts  are 
so  absurd  that  if  they  come  to  mind  they  are  promptly  dis- 
missed. But  a  sound  theory  must  accept  their  existence, 
traces  of  which  we  have  illustrated  in  the  case  of  Paragraphs  7, 
/  and  M.  Every  element  in  a  situation  tends  to  arouse  the 
response  which  is  connected  with  it. 

Just  as  any  element  of  the  situation  may  be,  relatively  to 
others,  far  too  potent  in  determining  the  response,  so  also  it 
may  be  not  nearly  potent  enough.  Calling  Pa  the  potency 
of  element  a  and  Pb  the  potency  of  element  b,  Pa/Pb  may 
vary  between  o  and  oo  as  limits. 

The  following  are  some  cases  of  under-potency  in  the  case 
of  /  (page  220) : 

QUESTION  i 

nearly — (Failure  to  include   this  in  the  response  to  I  is  of  course 

very,  very  common.) 
fifteen— "Thousand" 
what  is  said  about  the — "Honorable  and  good,"  "They  march  very 

nice,"  "They  marched  very  straight,"  "They  did  good  or  bad," 

and  many  similar  responses. 
number  of  persons — "They  were    workers,"  "Men  and  women," 

"That  they  rejoin  in  the  parade,"  "Passed  before  cheering 

spectators." 


228  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

who   marched  in  the  parade — The   many   responses   of   "200000," 

"They  cheered  them,"  etc. 
All  of  question  I  except  parade  is  under-potent — "There  were  a  lot 

of  floats." 

QUESTION  2 

the  "out"  of  outnumbered — "A  number  of  women." 
which — "Both  sexes  was  in  the  parade,"  "There  were  both  sexes 
there,"  "Workers  of  both  sexes,"  "Men  and  women,"  "Two 
sexes,"  "Two  of  them." 

sex— "City  workers,"  "City  workers  of  N.  Y.,"  "The  chief  com- 
mander of  all,"  "Working,"  "The  front  ones,"  "Spectators," 
"Cheering,"  "Fifteen  thousand." 

in  the  majority — "Women,"  "Sex  outnumbered  of  women." 
which  .  .  .  was   in   the   majority — "The   sex   spectators,"    "Sexes," 
"In  the  parade,"  "Sexes  in  the  parade,"  "There  were  men  of 
other  sex  in  the  parade." 

QUESTION  3 

what  did  the  .  .  .  do — "They   were   cheered  by  the  people,"  "Two 

hundred." 

people— "Tip  his  hat." 
people  who  looked  at — "Passed  before  two  hundred,"  "Passed  before 

a  number  of  cheering  spectators." 
when  it  passed  by — "Two  hundred  thousand  cheering  spectators 

passed." 

it—  "They  saluted  them,"  "They  cheered  them." 
cheering — "Inspected  the  parade,"   "They  were  glad  to  see  it," 

"They  talked  about  it"  (and  many  others). 
All   save   parade   underpotent — "September    seventh,"    "Seventh 

Avenue." 

QUESTION  4 

saw  the  parade — "The  men  outnumbered  the  women,"  "Far  out- 
numbered." 

two — "About  100000,"  "One  hundred  thousand,"  "Three  hundred 
thousand." 

hundred—  "Two  thousand." 

thousand — "Two  hundred." 

two  hundred  [thousand] — "Fifteen  thousand,"  "Nearly  fifteen 
thousand,"  "Over  25000,"  "Over  five  hundred,"  "About 
10000,"  "About  5000,"  "About  1000." 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING    229 

QUESTION  5 

what  date — "There  were  workers  of  both  sexes  in  the  parade," 
"Thought  the  man  fat  out/'  "Described,"  "Sexes  of  the  pa- 
rade,"  "The  parade,"  "And  outnumbered  women." 

event  described  in  paragraph — "March  4,  1915,"  "March  17," 
"April  23,  1903,"  "November^"  "December^"  "On  Friday," 
"March  17,"  "March  18,"  "St.  Patrick's  day,"  "On  the 
twenty-second  of  February,"  "St.  Pattac,"  "1492,"  "1776," 
"1820." 

Seventh — "September  seventeenth"  (a  common  error,  often  due  to 
misperception  or  memory,  probably)  "September." 

In  any  situation  we  may  distinguish  in  a  rough  way 
between  words  meaning  things,  qualities  and  events  on  the 
one  hand  and  words  meaning  relations  between  them  on  the 
other.  Thus  we  may  think  of  question  2  below  as: 

[(Use  of  a  gas  range)  instead  of  (use  of  a  coal  range)] 
effect  upon 


temperature  of  the  kitchen 
H 

You  need  a  coal  range  in  winter  for  kitchen  warmth  and  for  continuous 
hot-water  supply,  but  in  summer  when  you  want  a  cool  kitchen  and  less  hot 
water,  a  gas  range  is  better.  The  xyz  ovens  are  safe.  In  the  end-ovens  there 
is  an  extra  set  of  burners  for  broiling. 

1.  What  two  varieties  of  stoves  does  the  paragraph  mention? 

2.  What  effect  has  the  use  of  a  gas  range  instead  of  a  coal  range  upon  the 

temperature  of  the  kitchen? 

3.  What  is  needed  to  provide  a  supply  of  hot  water  all  day  long? 

4.  For  what  purpose  is  the  extra  set  of  burners? 

5.  In  what  part  of  the  stove  are  they  situated? 

6.  During  what  season  of  the  year  is  a  gas  range  preferable? 

These  relating  elements  are  subject  to  over-potency  and 
under-potency  like  any  others,  but  especially  to  under- 
potency.  Thus  in  the  question  quoted,  we  have  as  re- 
sponses due  to  under-potency  of  the  instead  of: 


230  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

"The  stove  makes  heat"  and  "You  need  a  coal  range  in  winter  and 
a  gas  range  in  summer." 

As  responses  due  to  under-potency  of  effect  upon,  we  find: 

"You  can  cook  better,"  "Heats  quicker,"  "Because  it  is  summer," 
and  "Because  we  need  no  coal." 

As  responses  showing  under-potency  of  both  instead  of  and 

effect  upon,  we  have: 

"Gas  to  cook  and  coal  to  get  warm,"  and  "Gas  range  in  summer." 

Elements  may  act  in  substantially  correct  potency  but  out 
of  their  proper  relations.  Responses  to  arithmetical  problems 
will  illustrate  this  richly.  In  reading  we  have  such  cases  as 
"A  cool  kitchen  is  used  for  a  gas  range"  in  response  to  What 
effect  has  the  use  of  a  gas  range  instead  of  a  coal  range  upon  the 
temperature  of  the  kitchen? 

The  connections  leading  from  any  element  or  group  of 
elements  may  be  wrong  whether  the  element  is  under-potent, 
of  correct  potency,  or  over-potent.  They  may  be  wrong  in 
toto  in  the  sense  of  leading  to  unserviceable  responses  to  that 
element  for  any  purpose,  or  wrong  for  any  defined  set  of 
purposes,  or  wrong  for  the  test's  purpose  in  the  sense  of  leading 
to  responses  unserviceable  for  the  particular  need  or  problem. 
Thus  "A  complete  sentence"  is  wrong  for  almost  all  purposes 
as  a  response  to  paragraph;  "Commas  and  periods"  is  perhaps 
even  more  universally  futile;  "A  group  of  sentences"  is 
wrong  for  the  particular  purpose  of  answering  the  question 
of /i. 

Inadequacy  may  be  considered  as  a  special  case  of  wrong- 
ness  by  lack  or  insufficient  connections,  and  failure  of  response 
as  the  limiting  case  of  inadequacy. 

Incorrect  thinking  due  to  wrong  or  inadequate  bonds  lead- 
ing from  one  or  more  elements  of  the  situation  is  a  simple 
consequence  of  the  general  facts  of  connection-forming  that 
does  not  need  demonstration  here.  We  know  a  priori  that 
every  element  tends  to  call  up  what  has  followed  or  accom- 
panied it. 

I  will  report  only  three  illustrations.     The  paragraph  being 

John  had  two  brothers  who  were  both  tall.    Their  names  were  Will  and 
Fred.    John's  sister,  who  was  short,  was  named  Mary.    John  liked  Fred 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING  231 

better  than  either  of  the  others.    All  of  these  children  except  Will  had  red 
hair.    He  had  brown  hair. 

and  the  questions  being 


5.  Who  had  brown  hair?, 

6.  Who  had  red  hair?.. 


there  are  with  pupils  of  all  grades  from  the  third  to  the  eighth 
a  large  per  cent,  number  of  responses  of  "John"  and  "Fred" 
to  "Who  had  brown  hair?"  and  30  per  cent,  of  responses  of 
"Will"  to  Who  had  red  hair?  Under-potency  of  All  the 
children  except  caused  the  formation  of  the  connection  of  Will 
with  red  hair.  This  wrong  connection  not  only  produced  the 
large  crop  of  errors  to  question  6,  but  also  worked  back  to 
prevent  the  correct  answer  to  question  5. 

To  question  I  on  paragraph  /  we  find  the  following  an- 
swers, all  being  more  or  less  wrong  connections  leading  from 
the  element  paragraph. 

'The  sentence,"  "Subject  and  predicate," 

'A  sentence  that  made  sense,"  "A  letter," 

'  Period,"  "  In  every  paragraph  must  have  a  period," 

'Capital,"  "Capital  letter  in  the  first  letter," 

'A  capital  letter,"  "Commas  and  periods," 

'To  begin  with  a  capital,"  "The  paragraph  man  was  marsh." 

To  the  question,  on  paragraph  7",  What  do  you  think 
61 heaven's  azure"  means?  we  find  the  following  answers  from 
college  freshmen,  in  whom  right  bonds  leading  from  azure 
are  either  absent  or  so  weak  as  to  be  suppressed  by  the  wrong 
(for  the  purpose)  bonds  leading  from  heaven  or  from  the  general 
sense  of  glorified  moralizing  which  the  passage  establishes. 
Only  about  one  college  freshman  in  three  thinks  of  so  plain 
a  thing  as  the  blue  sky! 

T 

But  it  is  to  you,  ye  Workers,  who  do  already  work,  and  are  as  grown  men, 
noble  and  honorable  in  a  sort,  that  the  whole  world  calls  for  new  work  and 
nobleness.  Subdue  mutiny,  discord,  widespread  despair,  by  manfulness, 
justice,  mercy  and  wisdom.  Chaos  is  dark,  deep  as  Hell;  let  light  be,  and 
there  is  instead  a  green  flowery  world.  Oh,  it  is  great,  and  there  is  no  other 
greatness.  To  make  some  nook  of  God's  creation  a  little  fruitfuller,  better 
more  worthy  of  God;  to  make  some  human  hearts  a  little  wiser,  manfuller, 
happier, — more  blessed,  less  accursed!  It  is  work  for  a  God.  Sooty  Hell  of 
mutiny  and  savagery  and  despair  can,  by  man's  energy,  be  made  a  kind  of 
Heaven;  cleared  of  its  soot,  of  its  mutiny,  of  its  need  to  mutiny;  the  ever- 
lasting arch  of  Heaven's  azure  overspanning  it  too,  and  its  cunning  mechan- 


232  EDWARD  L.  THORNDIKE 

isms  and  tall  chimney-steeples,  as  a  birth  of  Heaven;  God  and  all  men  looking 
on  it  well  pleased. 

"The  everlasting  rainbow,"  "God's  love," 

'"Peace,"  "God's  influence," 

"Peace,  universal,"  "God's  approval  of  work," 

'Peace  progress  and  justice  one  to  an-  "God's  creation," 

other,"  "A  world  in  which  +," 

"Peace  and  the  world  purged  of  strife,"  "A  place  where  men  +," 

"Peace  and  happiness  love  and  manli-  "The  light  of  the  world," 

ness,"  "The  light  of  a  new  method — of  freedom 

"The  peace  and  love  of  man's  fellow  men,"  and  happiness," 

"The  peacefulness  one  sees  in  a  God-  "Man's  outlook  on  life," 

fearing  community,"  "High  ideal  +," 

"Harmony  in  life,"  "The  clearing  of  mutiny," 

"Themillenium,"  "Perfect  condition  of  things  with  every 

"Appreciation  of  the  beauty  of  nature,"  one  happy  and  working  for  the  best," 

"Wisdom  mercy,"  "The  work  that  man  has  accomplished," 

"Happiness,"  "Eternity," 

"Enjoyment,"  "Eternal  life," 

"The  happiness   and   contentment  that  "Eternal  blessing," 

comes-}- "    (-}-   here   and   later  means  "Love  your  neighbor  as  yourself -}-," 

that  more  was   contained   in  the  re-  "God   is   love.     Do  unto  others   as   ye 

sponse;  but  nothing  correct),  would  have  others  do  unto  you." 

We  must  then  think  of  a  pupil  who  answers  the  questions 
concerning  a  paragraph  as  beset  by  tendencies  of  each  word 
and  word  group  in  the  question  to  assume  undue  potency,  to 
become  dislocated  from  its  proper  relations,  and  to  call  up 
its  past  accompaniments  and  sequents.  For  him  to  answer 
rightly  means  that  an  elaborate  hierarchy  of  bonds  is  active 
and  that  an  intricate  set  of  forces  maintains  a  balance  of 
power.  One  may  become  directly  aware  of  at  least  a  part  of 
this  complex  coordination  and  subordination  of  tendencies  if 
he  will  note  just  what  it  implies  to  respond  correctly  to  this 
question  on  paragraph  T:  What  does  the  author  refer  to  as  a 
" Sooty  Hell  of  mutiny  and  savagery  and  despair"?  One  may 
infer  it  less  directly  but  more  adequately  by  surveying  the 
hundreds  of  different  tendencies  to  respond  which  a  paragraph 
and  question  evokes  in  a  thousand  pupils  and  realizing  that 
almost  or  quite  all  of  these  tendencies  were  present  as  truly 
in  any  one  successful  pupil,  but  were  prevented  from  deter- 
mining final  response  by  some  organization  within  them- 
selves or  by  some  guiding  tendencies  from  without. 

Sometimes  the  correct  balance  or  organization  reduces  to 


THE  PSYCHOLOGY  OF  THINKING  IN  THE  CASE  OF  READING    233 

the  simple  case  of  letting  one  element  be  as  potent  as  it  may 
and  reducing  the  potency  of  all  other  elements  to  negligible 
amounts.  We  then  have  the  case  of  reasoning  of  which 
James  has  given  the  classic  description.  But  the  task  of 
thought  is,  it  seems,  not  usually  to  choose  only  one  element  in 
the  situation  for  potency,  or  to  accept  one  only  of  the  facts 
evoked  by  that  element.  Usually  there  are  many  elements 
to  be  let  work  together  and  many  evoked  facts  to  be  used  for 
the  purpose  at  hand.  In  our  illustration,  the  "workers," 
"sooty,"  "mechanisms"  and  "tall  chimney"  all  need  to  be 
given  potency  to  secure  the  response  of  "a  region  of  fac- 
tories," "a  manufacturing  community,"  "a  factory  town  dis- 
turbed by  labor  troubles,"  or  the  like,  and  the  "God," 
"chaos,"  "Hell"  and  "Heaven"  of  Carlyle's  grandiloquence 
all  need  to  be  somewhat  tempered  in  their  tendencies  to  call 
up  the  world,  human  nature  or  other  things  of  vast  scope  and 
great  moral  importance. 

Elaborate  as  are  the  compositions  of  forces  which  give 
thought  its  final  motion  and  direction,  the  forces  themselves 
are  of  simple  nature,  being  elements  in  situations  and  con- 
nections leading  from  these  elements  to  responses  which  use 
and  (in  my  opinion)  satisfying  accompaniments  have  yoked 
to  each  element. 

Three  simple  mechanisms — under-potency  and  over-po- 
tency of  elements,  dislocation  or  disrelation  of  elements,  and 
wrongness  or  inadequacy  of  connections — seem  to  be  all  that 
are  needed  to  explain  errors  in  thinking.  Conversely,  proper 
balance  and  organization  of  elements  and  right  bonds  there- 
with seem  to  explain  correct  thinking,  no  matter  how  elaborate 
or  subtle.  Thinking  and  reasoning  do  not  seem  to  be  in  any 
useful  sense  opposites  of  automatism,  custom,  or  habit,  but 
simply  the  action  of  habits  in  cases  where  the  elements  of  the 
situation  compete  and  cooperate  notably. 

It  is  of  course  the  case  that,  along  with  the  balanced 
action  of  elements,  there  goes  an  inspection  and  validation  of 
them  and  the  ideas  or  acts  they  evoke,  whereby  each  suc- 
ceeding situation  is  often  amended  by  increasing  or  reducing 
the  potency  of  certain  of  its  elements,  and  whereby  certain 


234  EDWARD  L.  THORN  DIKE 

futile  ideas  may  be  cast  away  entirely.  These  welcomings 
and  rejectings,  retainings  and  letting  go,  are  however  them- 
selves nothing  more  than  situation-response  bonds,  where  the 
response  is  attending  to  or  turning  from,  cherishing,  repeating, 
saying  no  or  yes  to,  or  the  like.  It  is  also  the  case  that  the 
"set"  or  adjustment  of  the  organism  plays  a  more  striking 
role  in  reasoning  than  it  does  in  mere  day-dreaming  or  routine 
habit-action,  but  not  a  different  sort  of  a  role. 

I  conclude  therefore  that  the  general  laws  of  human  be- 
havior which  explain  why  a  pupil  puts  his  clothes  on  or  off  and 
eats  or  leaves  uneaten  his  breakfast  explain  why  he  succeeds 
or  fails  in  making  geometrical  demonstrations  or  scientific 
researches,  and  that  there  exists  no  fundamental  physiological 
contrast  between  fixed  habits  and  reasoning. 


THE  SIMILARITY  OF  BROTHERS  AND  SISTERS  IN 
MENTAL  TRAITS1 

BY  DANIEL  STARCH 

University  of  Wisconsin 

In  this  study,  information  was  sought  on  two  questions: 
(i)  To  what  extent  are  adult  siblings  (children  of  the  same 
parents)  alike  in  mental  characteristics  and  (2)  is  the  similar- 
ity greater  in  those  mental  traits  which  are  directly  affected 
by  training  in  school  work  than  it  is  in  those  traits  which  are 
not  directly  affected  by  school  work? 

Some  experimental  work  has  been  done  on  these  problems 
with  siblings  and  twins  of  various  ages  below  adult  life.2  The 
purpose  of  the  present  study  was  to  investigate  the  mental 
resemblance  of  adult  siblings,  and  with  these  problems  in 
mind  two  series  of  tests  were  carried  out. 

I.  For  measuring  mental  functions  which  are  directly 
affected  by  school  work,  the  following  tests  were  used :  Speed 
and  comprehension  of  reading  ability,  size  of  reading  voca- 
bulary, speed  and  quality  of  hand-writing,  and  ability  in 
spelling.     These  tests  were  made  in  exact  accord  with  the 
methods  described  elsewhere3  and  hence  no  further  details 
will  be  given  here.     Abilities  in  the  four  fundamental  oper- 
ations in  arithmetic  were  measured  by  the  Courtis  tests, 
Series  B.*    Ability  in  arithmetical  reasoning  was  measured 
by  the  writer's  scale  ('  Educational  Measurements,'  p.  114). 

II.  For  measuring  mental  functions  which  are  not  directly 
affected  by  school  work,  the  following  tests   were  selected: 
Two  perception  tests  were  used:  (a)  The  well-known  A-test 

1  This  investigation  was  planned  by  the  writer.    The  tests  themselves  and  the 
computation  of  the  results  were  made  very  carefully  by  Clara  Fuller  Taylor. 

2  Thorndike,  E.  L.     'Measurements  of  Twins,'  Archiv.  of  Phil,  PsychoL,  t3c.,  No.  I. 
Starch,  D.     'The  Inheritance  of  Abilities  in  School  Studies,'  School  and  Soc.,  2, 

608-610. 

3  Starch,  D.,  'Educational  Measurements'  (Macmillan),  pp.  20,  38,  60,  and  89. 

4  Courtis,  S.  A.,  'Manual  of  Instructions'  (Detroit),  p.  58. 

235 


236  DANIEL  STARCH 

which  determines  the  number  of  A's  cancelled  in  one  minute, 
and  (b)  a  geometrical  form  test  which  determines  the  number 
of  a  certain  geometrical  figure  cancelled  in  one  minute  on  a 
page  of  similar  forms.  Memory  was  measured  by  the 
number  of  words  that  could  be  recalled  after  hearing  a  series 
of  ten  monosyllabic  nouns  read  at  the  rate  of  one  word  per 
second.  Motor  capacity  was  tested  by  the  tapping  test  in 
which  the  task  consisted  in  tapping  with  the  right  hand,  as 
rapidly  as  possible  for  thirty  seconds. 

Each  test  was  carried  out  twice  on  two  different  days  with 
a  group  of  eighteen  pairs  of  adult  siblings  who  were  students 
in  the  University  of  Wisconsin.  The  ages  of  these  persons 
ranged  from  nineteen  to  thirty-two.  The  tests  were  repeated 
so  as  to  obtain  more  reliable  measurements  of  the  capacities 
involved  than  a  single  test  would  yield. 

The  results  may  best  be  presented  in  the  accompanying 
table  of  coefficients  of  correlation  computed  according  to  the 
formula 

6  sum  d2 

r  =  *^r-—r 

In  arranging  the  pairs  of  siblings,  the  older  ones  of  the  dif- 
ferent pairs  were  placed  on  one  side  and  the  corresponding 
younger  members  were  arranged  on  the  other.  The  scores 
made  by  each  person  in  each  test  were  then  tabulated  opposite 
each  person's  name.  The  older  members  of  the  various 
pairs  were  then  ranked  by  themselves  in  each  test  and  the 
younger  ones  were  likewise  ranked  by  themselves.  On  the 
basis  of  these  ranks  the  coefficients  of  correlation  were  com- 
puted and  found  to  be  as  follows: 

Reading — speed 51 

Reading — comprehension 64 

Writing — speed 72 

Writing — quality 46 

Size  of  reading  vocabulary 07 

Spelling 05 

Arithmetical  reasoning 38 

Addition — attempts 71 

Addition-  -rights 44 

Subtraction — attempts 43 

Subtraction — rights 29 


THE  SIMILARITY  OF  BROTHERS  AND  SISTERS  *37 

Multiplication — attempts 37 

Multiplication — rights 25 

Division — attempts 46 

Division — rights 56 

Average 42 

Memory 31 

A-Test 50 

Geometrical  form  test 07 

Tapping 65 

Average 38 

Coefficients  based  on  ranks  in  all  rests  combined 73 

Several  interesting  results  appear  in  this  table,  (i)  The 
resemblance  of  siblings  is  apparently  no  greater  in  those 
mental  traits  which  are  directly  affected  by  school  work  than 
in  those  which  are  not  so  affected.  The  average  correlation 
in  the  former  group  of  tests  is  .42  and  in  the  latter  .38.  This 
seems  to  indicate  that  the  mental  similarities  of  children  of 
the  same  parents  are  due  primarily  to  heredity  rather  than 
to  similarity  of  environment  since  the  resemblance  is  no 
greater  in  those  traits  which  are  more  directly  affected  by 
environment. 

(2)  The  resemblance  of  siblings  is  approximately  as  great 
in  mental  traits  as  in  physical  traits.     Pearson  found  the 
correlation  between  brother  and  brother  in  height  to  be  .50 
and  in  cephalic  index  (ratio  of  length  to  width  of  head)  .49. 
These  correlations  for  physical  traits  are  a  little  larger  than 
the  ones  found  here  for  mental  traits  taken  separately.     The 
correlation,  however,  calculated  on  the  basis  of  a  combined 
rank  for  each  person  in  all  mental  tests  together  was  found  to 
be  .73.     This  greater  correlation  for  all  tests  combined  as 
compared  with  the  correlations  for  single  traits  is  due  partly 
to  the  variation  of  the  correlations  among  the  single  traits 
and  partly  to  the  imperfections  in  the  separate  tests,  which  are 
counterbalanced  to  some  extent  in  a  combined  ranking. 

(3)  Apparently  the  resemblance  is  greater  in  some  traits 
than  in  others.     Spelling  ability,  range  of  vocabulary,  and 
perception  of  geometrical  forms  seem  to  be  correlated  very 
slightly;  whereas  speed  in  writing,  speed  in  tapping,  and  speed 
in  addition  seem  to  be  correlated  very  closely.     To  what 


238  DANIEL  STARCH 

extent  different  mental  traits  are  correlated  by  greater  or  less 
amounts  can  not  be  stated  with  confidence  on  the  basis  of 
the  present  tests.  Further  measurements  are  necessary. 

The  chief  significance  of  the  present  results  consists  in 
further  corroborating  the  notion  that  the  mental  make-up  of 
human  beings  is  as  much  a  matter  of  heredity  as  their  physical 
make-up  and  that  environment  plays  a  relatively  small  part 
in  producing  the  resemblance  of  closely  related  individuals. 


A  METHOD  OF  RECORDING  ERRORS  IN  FORM 
BOARD  TESTS 

BY  E.  K.  STRONG,  JR.  AND  EDWARD  P.  GILCHRIST 

George  Peabody  College  for  Teachers 

The  length  of  time  required  to  perform  a  Form  Board 
Test  has  been,  in  most  cases,  the  principal  element  in  measur- 
ing the  performance.  Various  efforts  have  been  made  to 
utilize  the  error-element  also.  But  most  of  these  have  not 
led  to  anything  of  real  value  except  to  the  originator  of  the 
scheme,  himself.  Yet  all  who  have  used  form  board  tests 
have  come  to  realize  that  they  learned  as  much,  if  not  more, 
from  the  way  the  test  was  performed  as  from  the  time  it 
required.  The  reason  the  errors  have  not  been  used  more 
has  been  due  to  the  difficulty  of  recording  them  in  the  few 
seconds  one  has  at  his  disposal. 

Miss  Schmitt1  has  recently  very  vigorously  protested 
against  using  time  as  a  measure  of  efficiency  and  has  substi- 
tuted in  its  place  an  analysis  of  the  '  method  of  attack.'  She 
reduces  the  child's  method  to  one  of  three  types:  'planned,' 
'trial  and  error,'  and  'chance.'  The  writers  believe  that 
this  analysis  should  lead  to  some  very. desirable  additions  to 
our  present  methods  of  evaluating  a  child's  ability,  but  they 
are  not  prepared  as  yet,  to  accept  Miss  Schmitt's  rather 
arbitrary  method  of  determining  what  is  a  'planned'  or  'trial 
and  error'  performance.  However,  her  position  raises  again 
the  great  need  of  devising  a  method  by  which  one  can  keep 
track  of  the  various  movements  by  which  a  child  solves  the 
form  board  test.  The  following  method  has  been  found  use- 
ful in  this  connection  and  is  recorded  here  as  a  possible  help 
to  others  who  have  been  confronted  by  the  same  problem. 

Suppose  we  are  working  with  the  Healy-Fernald  Con- 
struction Test  A.  This  test  can  be  solved  by  making  five 

1  Schmitt,  C.,  "Standardization  of  Tests  for  Defective  Children,"  PSYCHOL. 
MONOG.,  No.  83,  1915. 

239 


240 


E.  K.  STRONG  AND  EDWARD  P.  GILCHRIST 


moves  and  in  three  seconds  (our  best  record):  or  it  may  be 
solved  after  a  great  number  of  moves  and  after  a  long  period 
of  time.  Ordinarily  five  or  ten  minutes  is  considered  suf- 
ficient time  in  which  to  test  the  child's  capacities.  Now,  if 
one  uses  coordinate  paper,  illustrated  in  the  plate,  he  may 
draw  a  diagonal  line  upwards  and  to  the  right  for  every 
*  placement';  a  horizontal  line  to  the  right  for  every  're- 
arrangement'; a  diagonal  line  downward  and  to  the  right  for 
every  'removal.'  The  record  illustrated  in  the  plate  tells 
this  following  story.  Three  blocks  were  picked  up,  one  after 
the  other,  and  placed  in  the  rectangle:  two  rearrangement 
moves  followed;  one  block  was  removed  from  the  frame; 


333"* 


FIG.  i.  Showing  Method  of  Recording  Movements  in  Solving  Healy-Fernald 
Construction  Test  A.1 

two  rearrangements  of  the  two  remaining  blocks  followed; 
another  block  was  placed  in  the  rectangle;  three  rearrange- 
ments followed;  the  last  two  blocks  were  placed  in  position. 

1  The  lower  cut  should  have  been  so  prepared  that  the  two  numerals  "  2  "  in  the 
center  of  the  cut  and  the  three  uumerals  "  3  "  near  the  right  of  the  cut  should  be 
placed  on  their  respective  horizontal  lines  instead  of  above  them.  If  this  had  been 
done  the  distinction  between  a  numeral  on  a  diagonal  and  one  on  a  horizontal  line 
would  appear  more  clearly  to  the  eye. 


A  METHOD  OF  RECORDING  ERRORS  IN  FORM  BOARD  TESTS    241 

This  record  can  be  summarized  as  follows:  Placements — 6; 
Removals — i;  Rearrangements — 7;  Total — 14. 

If  one  cares  to  go  into  further  detail  in  his  analysis  of 
the  movements,  he  may  write  a  number  from  one  to  five 
instead  of  drawing  the  horizontal  or  diagonal  lines;  each 
number  standing  for  a  block.  In  this  way,  just  what  block 
was  involved  in  the  movement  may  be  recorded.  Such  a 
record  will  appear  as  in  the  lower  part  of  the  figure. 

Note:  The  blocks  are  numbered  in  accordance  with  their 
length;  blocks  four  and  five  being,  of  course,  identical.  From 
the  record  it  is  clear  that  block  I  was  correctly  placed;  block  2 
was  not  correctly  placed;  block  3  was  also  not  correctly 
placed;  it  was  moved  twice  and  then  removed  from  the 
rectangle;  block  2  was  then  moved  twice,  the  second  time 
being  placed  correctly;  then  block  3  was  replaced  incorrectly 
and  moved  three  times,  when  it  was  finally  correctly  placed; 
then  blocks  4  and  5  were  placed  correctly. 

A  slight  amount  of  practice  enables  one  to  think  the 
correct  number  when  a  block  is  touched;  also  to  write  the 
numbers  uphill  when  they  are  being  placed,  downhill  when 
being  removed,  and  on  the  line  when  they  are  being  moved 
about.  And  all  of  this  can  be  done  while  keeping  the  eyes 
for  the  most  part  upon  the  subject. 


DISCUSSION 
INTROSPECTION  VERSUS  THE  SUBCONSCIOUS 

Do  not  the  following  experiments  show  that  an  assumption  lies 
at  the  base  of  the  conclusions  drawn  from  certain  introspective 
data  regarding  the  mental  processes  involved: 

1.  An  experienced  observer  is  given  a  number,  say  6,  to  multiply 
by  3,  and  he  answers  18,  having  had  no  visual  nor  auditory  images 
nor  indeed  any  thing,  so  far  as  he  could  determine,  to  give  to  pro- 
tocal.     But  if  he  is  previously  told  to  observe  the  steps  of  the  process 

9 

in  multiplying  9  by  4  he  often  reports  a  visual  image    4  and  perhaps 

36 

also  auditory  and  other  images  in  connection  with  the  solution  of 
the  problem.  That  is,  in  conducting  the  experiment  in  the  second 
way  the  steps  of  the  process  appear. 

2.  Something  similar  is  also  observed  often  when  an  experienced 
observer  is  instructed  to  reverse  the  hands  of  a  clock,  that  is,  he 
has  nothing  to  report  except  the  correct  answer  until  he  has  been 
told  to  observe  the  steps  of  the  process  with  greater  attention. 

3.  The  same  thing  came  out  in  a  striking  way  when  a  student 
investigating  recognition  once  complained  to  me  that  an  experienced 
reagent  with  whom  he  was  working  was  evidently  a  very  careless 
observer  as  he  had  little  or  nothing  to  give  to  protocal.     After  the 
reagent  had  been  told  of  the  complaint  and  instructed  to  observe 
more  carefully  the  experimenter  informed  me  that  this  reagent's 
introspections  had  become  more  detailed,  as  regards  the  steps  of  the 
process. 

4.  In  reaction  time  experiments  the  introspections  are  usually 
much  fuller  after  the  observer  has   been  told   to  observe  what 
occurred  in  the  Vorperiode,  etc.,  that  is,  when  instructions  have  been 
given  similar  to  those  given  by  Ach  in  his  reaction  time  experi- 
ments.    That  is  to  say,  in  the  above  experiments,  the  steps  of  the 
process  were  observable  only  after  the  reagent  had  been  directed 
to  note  them,  that  is,  after  they  had  been  drawn  from  under  the 
threshold  of  consciousness  through  the  method  employed. 

As  to  whether  the  steps  of  the  process  as  they  appear  in  the 
242 


INTROSPECTION  VERSUS  THE  SUBCONSCIOUS  243 

second  mode  of  conducting  the  experiments  just  mentioned  are  the 
same  as  in  the  first  mode,  one  may  suppose,  (i)  they  are  or  (2)  they 
are  not  or  (3)  may  have  no  definite  opinion  regarding  the  matter. 
If  one  supposes  the  processes  are  the  same,  he  is  assuming,  is  he 
not,  that  the  processes  above  and  below  the  threshold  of  conscious- 
ness are  the  same,  that  is,  that  the  conscious  and  the  subconscious 
are  fundamentally  one;  if,  on  the  other  hand,  he  rejects  this  idea 
altogether  he  holds  the  opposite  view  regarding  the  relation  between 
the  conscious  and  the  subconscious;  if  he  does  not  know  what  con- 
clusion to  draw  from  the  data  obtained  by  the  two  different  methods 
he  has  no  definite  opinion  regarding  the  relation  of  the  conscious  to 
the  subconscious.  It  would  seem,  would  it  not,  from  the  data  given 
that  the  opinion  one  holds  regarding  the  relation  between  the  con- 
scious and  subconscious  has  a  somewhat  greater  significance  in  intro- 
spective work  than  has  been  generally  supposed?  In  short,  that 
our  opinion  of  the  value  of  some  introspective  data  depends  upon 
our  view  of  the  relation  between  the  conscious  and  the  subconscious, 
in  fact,  of  the  subconscious  itself. 

LILLIEN  J.  MARTIN 
LEIAND  STANFORD  JR.  UNIVERSITY 


THE  MNEMONIC  FEAT  OF  THE  'SHASS  POLLAK' 

Some  years  ago,  through  the  kindness  of  my  friend  Professor 
Hollander,  of  the  Johns  Hopkins  University,  my  attention  was 
directed  to  a  special  achievement  in  memorizing  which  I  venture  to 
report;  since,  so  far  as  I  know,  it  has  remained  unnoticed  by 
psychologists,  and  yet  should  be  stored  among  the  data  long  and 
still  richly  gathering  for  the  study  of  extraordinary  feats  of  memory. 

The  facts  of  the  case  I  can  hardly  do  better  than  to  allow  the 
witnesses  themselves  to  state.  And  first  the  Reverend  Dr.  David 
Philipson,  of  Cincinnati,  to  whom  I  was  first  referred  by  Professor 
Hollander. 

"The  Babylonian  Talmud"  he  has  been  good  enough  to  write 
me,  "consist  of  twelve  large  folio  volumes  comprising  thousands  of 
pages.  All  the  printed  editions  of  the  Talmud  have  exactly  the 
same  number  of  pages  and  the  same  words  on  each  page.  This 
must  be  borne  in  mind  in  order  to  understand  the  remarkable  feat 
of  memory  about  to  be  described.  There  have  been,  as  there 
undoubtedly  still  are,  men  who  know  the  whole  text  of  the  Talmud 
by  heart.  Some  years  ago  one  of  these  men,  a  native  of  Poland, 
was  in  this  country.  I  witnessed  his  remarkable  feats  of  memory. 
Thus,  one  of  us  would  throw  open  one  of  the  volumes  of  the  Talmud, 
say  the  tractate  Berakhot,  at  page  10;  a  pin  would  be  placed  on  a 
word,  let  us  say,  the  fourth  word  in  line  eight;  the  memory  sharp 
would  then  be  asked  what  word  is  in  this  same  spot  on  page  thirty- 
eight  or  page  fifty  or  any  other  page;  the  pin  would  be  pressed 
through  the  volume  until  it  reached  page  thirty  eight  or  page  fifty 
or  any  other  page  designated;  the  memory  sharp  would  then  mention 
the  word  and  it  was  found  invariably  correct.  He  had  visualized 
in  his  brain  the  whole  Talmud;  in  other  words,  the  pages  of  the 
Talmud  were  photographed  on  his  brain.  It  was  one  of  the  most 
stupendous  feats  of  memory  I  have  ever  witnessed  and  there  was 
no  fake  about  it.  In  the  company  gathered  about  the  table  were  a 
number  of  Talmudic  experts  who  would  readily  have  discovered 
fraud  had  there  been  any.  The  technical  name  which  was  used  by 
the  Jews  of  aforet;mes  to  designate  these  memory  experts  was 
Shass  Pollak;  Shass  is  the  abbreviation  for  the  Hebrew  terms  for 
the  Talmud,  and  Pollak  is  Pole;  nearly  all  these  memory  experts 
244 


MNEMONIC  FEAT  OF  THE  'SHASS  POLL  A  K'  245 

came  from  Poland;  a  Shass  Pollak  then  is  a  Pole  who  has  memorized 
the  entire  contents  of  the  Talmud  and  is  able  to  give  exhibitions  of 
his  mnemonic  powers  like  those  mentioned  above." 

And  next  let  me  quote  from  Judge  Mayer  Sulzberger,  of  Phila- 
delphia, who  in  answer  to  my  inquiry,  wrote  as  follows: 

"I  have  met  but  one  'Shass  Pollak'  in  my  life.  He  was  brought 
into  my  library  one  evening  by  a  friend.  I  conversed  with  him  and 
experimented  upon  him. 

"After  he  had  been  introduced  as  the  expert  in  question  I 
expressed  some  curiosity  with  perhaps  a  mien  of  incredulity.  He 
was  eager  for  the  fray. 

"You  are  of  course  aware  that  all  (or  nearly  all)  modern  editions 
of  the  Talmud  are  paged  alike  and  printed  alike,  each  page  beginning 
and  ending  with  the  same  word  in  all  the  editions. 

"I  went  to  the  case  and  took  out  a  volume  of  the  first  edition 
which  has  its  own  paging  not  followed  by  the  other  editions.  He 
made  an  automatic  dive  for  a  word  in  a  particular  part  of  the  page, 
and  lo!  it  was  not  there. 

"Confounded  by  this  unexpected  event,  he  thought  at  first 
that  this  was  not  a  Talmud  I  was  showing  him;  and  when  convinced 
finally  that  it  was,  seemed  to  bear  it  some  resentment  for  its  im- 
proper behavior. 

"I  then  brought  out  the  corresponding  volume  of  an  ordinary 
edition  and  he  undoubtedly  made  good. 

"He  would  take  a  pencil  and  merely  glancing  at  the  page  put 
it  down  anywhere  and  without  looking  told  the  word  on  which  his 
pencil  had  lighted.  This  he  did  over  and  over  again.  There  is 
no  reasonable  ground  for  the  suspicion  that  he  saw  the  words.  I 
watched  him  closely  and  am  convinced  that  he  did  not.  He  had, 
I  feel  sure,  a  perfect  image  of  the  page  and  the  position  of  every 
word  on  it  in  his  'head.'" 

Finally,  let  me  give  the  testimony  of  Dr.  Schechter,  of  New  York, 
the  late  President  of  the  Jewish  Theological  Seminary  of  America — 
testimony  the  more  interesting  in  that  while  it  depends  upon  the 
recollection  of  an  experience  many  years  ago,  yet  it  is  an  independent 
account  of  the  same  kind  of  testing  which  Dr.  Philipson  reports 
— namely,  by  pricking  through  the  pages — and  consequently  con- 
firms the  opinion  of  Judge  Sulzberger  that  the  success  of  the  'Shass 
Pollak'  who  was  tested  merely  by  pencil  was  not  due  to  a  sly  catch- 
ing of  the  word  by  eye. 

President  Schechter  stated  to  me  by  letter  that  once  he  had 


246  GEORGE  M.  STRATTON 

come  across  a  'Shass  Pollak'  but  that  it  was  too  long  a  time  ago 
to  give  an  account  of  him  with  definiteness.  "It  is  at  least  forty- 
five  years  since  the  incident  occurred,"  he  wrote.  "What  I  re- 
member was  that  he  could  tell  you  the  contents  of  every  page  of 
the  Talmud  by  heart.  I  remember  also  that  the  people  amused 
themselves  by  prying  a  needle  into  any  volume  of  the  Talmud, 
and  he  could  tell  exactly  the  word  on  which  the  needle  touched.  But 
I  also  recollect  distinctly  that  it  was  nothing  more  than  a  verbal  or 
rather  local  memory,  the  students  all  maintaining  that  he  knew 
very  little  about  the  meaning  of  the  contents,  their  interpretation 
and  application.  I  heard  afterwards  of  many  similar  '  Shass  Pollaks,' 
but  it  is  a  fact  that  none  of  them  ever  attained  to  any  prominence 
in  the  scholarly  world." 

This  absence  of  any  scholarly  grasp  of  the  contents  thus  memor- 
ized, of  which  President  Schechter  speaks,  also  appears  in  the 
judgment  of  Dr.  Philipson.  "I  looked  upon  his  achievement  at 
the  time  I  witnessed  it  as  purely  mechanical,"  he  writes.  "It  is 
quite  likely  that  he  could  not  interpret  the  Talmud  though  he  knew 
its  contents  by  heart."  And  Judge  Sulzberger,  when  proposing  to 
his  'Shass  Pollak'  that  he  use  his  knowledge  to  some  scientific  or 
literary  end,  was  listened  to  with  respect,  but  nevertheless  received 
the  impression  that  such  proposals  were  deemed  by  his  man  to  be 
nonsensical. 

All  of  which  confirms  the  oft-repeated  observation,  that  such 
extraordinary  powers  of  memory  may  exist  in  a  kind  of  intellectual 
disproportion  where  there  is  no  corresponding  development  of 
other  powers — where,  indeed,  there  may  be  an  actual  stunting  of 
other  powers  and  interests;  as  though  the  mind  had  'run'  to  mem- 
ory, and  been  enlarged  here  at  the  expense  of  other  functions. 

As  to  the  more  precise  amount  of  matter  that  was  memorized, 
it  should  be  noted  that  a  page  of  the  Babylonian  Talmud  consists, 
as  my  colleague  Dr.  Popper,  has  pointed  out  to  me1,  of  the  text 
proper,  called  the  Gemarah,  and  printed  as  a  more  central  portion 
on  the  page,  and  of  a  commentary  printed  below  and  around  this 
text.  Upon  special  inquiry  whether  the  mnemonic  feat  applied 
only  to  the  Gemarah  or  included  also  the  Commentary,  Dr.  Philipson 

1  Professor  Popper  has  also  referred  me  to  the  articles  "Talmud"  and  "Mnemo- 
nics" in  The  Jewish  Encyclopedia  for  evidence  that  at  one  period  the  Talmud  was 
handed  down  solely  by  memory.  The  feat  of  the  Poles  here  recounted  may  therefore 
be  regarded  perhaps  as  the  survival  of  a  custom  among  early  Jewish  students  in  many 
and  widely-separated  communities.  The  work  of  Briill,  Die  Mnemotechnik  des  Tal- 
muds,  Vienna  1864,  should  also  be  cited. 


MNEMONIC  FEAT  OF  THE  'SHASS  POLL  A K'  *47 

states  that  the  test  which  he  witnessed  was  upon  the  Gemarah  only; 
and  Judge  Sulzberger  is  of  the  opinion  that  this  was  also  true  in 
the  case  that  came  under  his  observation.  Even  so,  the  task  must 
have  been  a  stupendous  one;  the  amount  of  reading-matter  upon 
each  page  is  still  great,  and  the  number  of  pages  is  enormous. 

In  closing  may  I  express  my  thanks,  in  which  other  students  of 
psychology  will  certainly  unite  with  me,  to  the  gentlemen  who  have 
so  generously  given  the  facts  above  recorded. 

GEORGE  M.  STRATTON 

UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  4  July,  1917 

THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE1 

BY  JOSEPH  JASTROW 

University  of  Wisconsin 

A  commemorative  occasion  justifies  a  retrospective,  though 
hardly  a  reminiscent  mood.  The  personal  justification  lies 
in  the  fact  that  I  speak  as  one  of  a  small  group — in  this  and 
all  countries — who  have  held  a  monogamous  professorship 
of  psychology  for  a  quarter  century.  The  contrast  of  then 
and  now  stands  forth  partly  as  a  shift  in  intellectual  temper- 
ament, partly  as  a  diverging  succession  of  interests.  Both 
are  responsible  for  the  historical  moving-picture,  which  to 
our  near  vision  still  flickers  by  reason  of  imperfect  fusion. 

The  dominant  interest  under  which  I  began  to  profess 
psychology  was  clearly  the  experimental  one;  it  set  a  novel 
and  a  positive  programme.  Equally  assertive  was  the 
physiological  plank.  The  two  stamped  one's  alliance,  in  a 
sense  made  one  a  partisan.  The  emblem  of  the  one  was  the 
laboratory,  of  the  other  an  evolutionary  faith  and  a  sense  of 
the  reality  of  the  body  in  the  affairs  of  mind.  They  might 
have  been  emblazoned  as  a  Hipp  chronoscope  rampant,  and  a 
copy  of  Darwin  couchant.  The  bearer  of  this  coat-of-arms 
was  in  many  quarters  under  suspicion.  He  was  more  than  a 
radical,  less  than  a  renegade.  By  implication  he  was  chal- 
lenging the  accredited  "mental  science"  of  the  colleges, 
which  was  a  branch — in  some  cases  a  stunted  twig — of 
philosophy,  and  a  perquisite  of  the  president.  At  educational 
gatherings — even  more  inconsequential  and  vaporous  then 
than  now — he  was  asked  to  defend  the  superiority  of  experi- 

1  Address  given  on  the  occasion  of  the  celebration  of  the  twenty-fifth  anniversary 
of  the  American  Psychological  Association,  New  York,  December  28,  1916. 

249 


250  JOSEPH  JASTROW 

mental  over  rational  psychology;  also  to  indicate  what  was 
the  fate  of  the  soul  under  the  new  regime.  To  the  philoso- 
phers the  psychologists  seemed  needlessly  young  and  irre- 
sponsible; to  the  men  of  science  they  seemed  out  of  focus  or 
tangential.  Now  that  the  philosopher  and  the  biologist  have 
become  our  ready  allies,  the  attitude  toward  us  as  militant 
invaders  is  almost  forgotten,  and  may  well  remain  so. 

The  credentials  upon  which  psychology  added  a  star  to 
the  united  sciences  were  significant  ones;  it  advanced  from 
territorial  governorship  to  statehood  by  patent  of  ancient 
right  reestablished  under  successful  pioneering.  It  was  not 
— as  in  the  case  of  sociology — a  squatter  settlement  in  un- 
occupied land  where  the  adjoining  sciences  failed  to  meet,  but 
the  declaration  of  independence  of  a  domain  quite  too  large 
and  distinctive  for  colonial  status.  The  first  insistence  was 
naturally  upon  technique.  The  novel  sight,  which  to  some 
was  amusing,  was  not  the  philosopher  descended  to  earth 
from  his  mythical  habitat  in  the  clouds,  but  actually  donning 
overalls  and  using  his  hands.  The  garb  seemed  strange  and 
lowly,  even  grimy.  But  rapidly  enough  the  new  psychology 
— like  the  new  woman — became  a  more  familiar  and  less 
forbidding  Erscheinung,  even  revealing  the  eternally  human 
traits.  Problems  followed  the  eclectic  clue  of  technique. 
The  early  Wundt  was  compilational  rather  than  systematic, 
though  the  Teutonic  Grundlichkeit  extended  to  architectural 
plan  as  well  as  building  material.  Wundt  set  the  interests  of 
the  first  group  of  American  students  of  modern  psychology, 
in  which  ancient  and  honorable  body  I  may  claim  a  place. 
The  rallying  point  was  the  Johns  Hopkins  University — itself 
as  new  as  psychology — under  the  leadership  of  the  author  of 
"Aspects  of  German  Culture,"  G.  Stanley  Hall.  He,  how- 
ever, found  a  small  group  of  students  already  waiting;  he 
quickly  attracted  others,  and  then  (after  five  years)  trans- 
ferred his  influence  to  Clark  University.  Stanley  Hall's 
doctorate  was  the  first  given  in  psychology;  Harvard  Uni- 
versity, 1878.  My  own  was  the  second  and  the  first  given  at 
Johns  Hopkins  specifically  in  psychology. 

In  so  far  as  American  psychology  was  a  native  product,  it 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  251 

reflected  the  pioneering  spirit,  the  spirit  of  William  James. 
No  speaker  on  a  commemorative  occasion  would  forego  the 
privilege  of  placing  a  wreath  upon  his  monument.  He  was 
the  first  among  us  to  bear  the  title  professor  of  psychology; 
he  holds  that  position  not  by  priority  but  by  preeminence. 
He  stands  as  the  exponent  of  the  value  of  varieties  of  psycho- 
logical experience.  He  made  clear  in  his  own  person  the 
intimate  dependence  of  pursuit  upon  temperament.  It  was 
peculiarly  fortunate  for  the  recognition  of  the  new  psychology 
that  its  academic  status  was  assured  by  the  acknowledged 
leadership  of  so  commanding  an  academician,  so  distinguished 
a  scholar,  so  great  a  man.  It  was  equally  fortunate  for  the 
career  of  psychology  in  America  that  the  stamp  of  the 
Jamesian  genius  pervaded  its  progress  and  directed  its  un- 
foldment  to  the  desirability  of  seeing  psychology  steadily  and 
seeing  it  whole. 

The  development  of  a  new  discipline  in  a  new  country 
encounters  directly  the  social  situation.  Of  first  consequence 
was  the  accredited  recognition  by  the  universities  and  colleges  ; 
which  meant  the  establishment  of  courses  that  could  play  a 
worthy  part  in  the  curriculum.  In  the  conflict  of  classics  and 
science,  which  in  the  days  I  am  recalling  was  reaching  its 
declining  and  conciliatory  stage,  psychology  occupied  an 
advantageous  position,  though  it  was  exposed  to  the  danger  of 
falling  down  between  two  stools:  the  unrecognized  stool  of  the 
laboratory,  the  exalted  throne  of  philosophy.  Yet  the  trend 
of  opinion  was  pacifist  and  not  militant.  In  the  readjustment 
of  the  curriculum  psychology  may  more  frequently  have  been 
offered  as  a  compromise  than  as  a  solution.  But  all  this  was 
helpful;  the  method  of  intelligence  would  have  been  better; 
but  the  method  of  trial  and  error  was  acceptable.  Prag- 
matically the  situation  offered  positions  to  those  who  would 
undertake  the  new  training.  In  the  words  of  the  college  song: 

"One  day  the  summons  came  out  of  the  West; 
'Get  Ph.D's  and  come,'  rang  the  request." 

I  may  readily  indicate  the  status  of  teaching  at  that  time 
by  mentioning  that  when  I  responded  there  was  no  elementary 


252  JOSEPH  J  AST  ROW 

text  available.  Carpenter's  ' Mental  Physiology'  both  in 
title  and  content  was  about  the  only  widely  read  book  that 
reflected  the  new  data  and  the  new  interpretation.  The 
pioneer  contribution  was  the  invaluable  work  of  Professor 
Ladd;  and  this  celebrated  its  quarter  century  a  few  years  ago 
by  the  appearance  of  the  Ladd-Woodworth  edition.  The 
text  implied  a  more  generous  course  and  a  better  type  of 
preparation  than  the  college  curriculum  afforded.  To  the 
teacher  of  psychology  this  monumental  work  was  a  daily 
support,  and  to  the  ablest  students,  often  of  nearly  the  same 
age  as  the  teacher,  a  guide,  philosopher  and  friend.  The 
work  of  James  appeared  three  years  later.  With  the  labor- 
atory and  seminar  the  lecture  and  research  and  the  training 
course,  and  then  the  American  Journal  of  Psychology,  at 
Johns  Hopkins;  with  the  large  personal  influence  and  the 
.systematic  work  at  Yale,  the  decisive  prominence  of  psy- 
chology in  the  graduate  work  in  philosophy  at  Harvard, 
American  psychology  was  launched.  The  auspices  could  not 
have  been  more  favorable.  The  varieties  of  psychological 
experience  represented  by  these  creative  personalities  assured 
the  development  of  psychology  in  this  country  a  breadth  of 
outlook,  a  soundness  of  technique,  and  a  vital  contact  with 
the  dominant  intellectual  interests,  which  have  been  most 
important  assets.  They  may  well  stand  central  in  our  com- 
memorative respect,  a  tribute  to  Hall,  Ladd  and  James. 

For  a  time  the  development  of  courses,  the  preparation  of 
texts,  the  establishment  of  academic  positions  kept  the  small 
band  of  psychologists  busy;  also  many  of  them  could  secure 
their  positions  only  by  a  willingness  to  share  the  responsibility 
for  allied  teaching,  mainly  in  philosophy,  logic  and  ethics. 
Indeed  these  disciplines  as  commonly  represented  the  major 
preparation,  to  which  psychology  was  added.  But  the  out- 
ward and  visible  sign  of  the  psychologist  was  his  laboratory; 
and  the  growth  of  these  both  for  instruction  and  research 
represents  the  most  distinctive  American  contribution. 
There  is  no  parallel  to  it  elsewhere.  In  a  direct  sense  the 
laboratory  is  responsible  for  the  largest  increase  in  varieties  of 
psychological  experience.  It  set  the  experimental  attitude 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  253 

in  inquiry,  and  this  of  all  the  several  independent  factors  un- 
mistakably shaped  the  career  which  we  are  passing  in  review. 
It  has  always  been  true  in  the  history  of  science  that  the  kind 
of  questions  men  ask  is  determined  by  the  facilities  which  they 
have  acquired  in  answering  them;  though  it  is  equally  true 
that  the  sense  of  limitation  of  facilities  has  been  the  motive 
force  in  extending  them  to  the  inclusion  of  larger  interests 
and  newer  problems. 

I  propose  to  touch  only  upon  the  larger  varieties  of  psy- 
chological experience  thus  furthered.  They  may  be  sum- 
marized under  five  overlapping  waves.  The  first  is  the  direct 
exploration  of  the  intimate  structure  of  mental  process,  the 
direct  analytical  interest  of  the  man  of  the  laboratory.  It 
immerses  him  in  technique  and  device  and  the  envisagement 
of  problems;  it  immerses  him  unduly  unless  it  carries  with  it 
the  poise  conferred  by  interpretation. 

The  second  is  the  comparative  interest,  which  in  recent 
years  has  almost  entirely  reconstructed  the  view  of  animal 
behavior,  and  has  yielded  its  interpretative  product  in  the 
"behaviorist"  position.  Its  high-power  study  of  the  begin- 
nings of  mind  gives  it  the  apect  of  psychological  histology; 
but  its  far-reaching  conclusions  extend  to  the  entire  evolu- 
tionary programme  of  the  mental  life.  It  forces  upon 
psychology  the  problem  of  the  distinctive  nature  of  the 
human  endowment,  and  the  stages  of  differentiation  in  the 
onward  series. 

One  may  place  third  and  thus  in  the  central  position  the 
growth,  almost  the  overgrowth,  of  applied  psychology.  This 
reflects  the  practical  stress  of  the  environment  and  the  prag- 
matic temper  of  the  American  Weltanschauung.  It  was  born 
in  the  laboratory.  The  term  l mental  test'  is  so  distinctive  of 
English,  which  in  this  case  is  American  usage,  that  it  has  been 
adopted  in  German,  French  and  Italian  literature.  It  arose 
from  the  consideration  that  analysis  is  not  only  of  the  factors 
of  a  process  but  of  their  place  in  the  individual  psychology. 
The  work  of  Galton  should  be  recalled  on  this  occasion  for  the 
reason  that  while  the  biological  aspects  of  his  versatile  studies 
attracted  most  attention  in  England,  the  psychological  sig- 


254  JOSEPH  J  AST  ROW 

nificance  of  his  methods  and  results  was  more  influential  on 
this  side.  He  emphasized  the  application  of  psychological 
tests  in  combination  with  anthropological  traits.  He  es- 
tablished the  first  laboratory  for  such  purpose;  and  it  may  be 
recorded  that  the  first  installation  on  this  side  was  in  connec- 
tion with  the  World's  Columbian  exposition  in  Chicago,  1893, 
where  also  the  visible  embodiment  of  experimental  psychology 
was  shown  to  the  public. 

In  applied  psychology  two  aspects  of  psychological  ex- 
perience were  involved:  the  first  emphasized  that  the  training 
of  mind  could  proceed  wisely  only  upon  a  knowledge  of  mind; 
and  the  teacher  was  referred,  not  without  misgivings,  to 
psychology.  The  second  aspect  was  focused  upon  the  ability 
of  the  tests  to  reveal  individual  capacity.  Thus  were  laid  the 
foundations  of  educational  psychology  which  in  the  present 
outlook  looms  so  momentously  large  that  it  heralds  the  divid- 
ing line  of  further  specialization.  It  is  making  for  a  competi- 
tive share  in  professional  status;  the  future  division  of  function 
is  indicated,  though  localization  is  somewhat  uncertain. 
With  the  present  expansion  of  departments  one  exponent  is 
likely  to  assume  responsibility  for  the  analytical,  theoretical 
disciplines,  and  another  for  their  applications.  Upon  the 
warmly  disputed  question  whether  pedagogy  is  a  science  or  an 
imposition,  and  its  pursuit  a  profession  or  a  misfortune,  we 
may  maintain  an  impeccably  neutral  position.  We  cannot 
overlook  the  fact  that  the  psychology  of  the  schooling  proc- 
esses, by  sheer  force  of  practical  importance,  is  entitled  to  a 
commanding  place  in  the  training  of  teachers;  while  collater- 
ally the  investigations  thus  resulting  give  promise  of  rounding 
out  the  analyses  of  the  learning  processes  to  the  great  benefit 
of  general  problems  of  primary  import.  Here  lie  varieties  of 
psychological  experience  of  sterling  value.  To  some  the 
field  has  the  appearance  of  extensions  of  city  plots  in  unborn 
suburbs,  neatly  staked  out  in  building-lots,  with  cement 
sidewalks  but  no  habitations.  The  promoter  in  psychology  is 
not  unknown;  but  the  new  settlement  seems  less  speculative 
to  one  who  has  a  retrospective  standard. 

A  distinctly  settled  section  is  that  of  tests  of  capacity,  the 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  255 

Binet-Simon  addition.  Applied  individually  the  test  invites 
a  diagnostic  use.  The  vocational  pressure  is  intense;  it  should 
be  encouraged  and  only  its  premature  and  cock-sure  decisions 
resisted.  It  is  characteristic  that  the  sins  of  commission  and 
omission  alike  are  far  more  common  among  the  practical 
cultivator  of  trees  than  among  the  more  theoretical  con- 
servator of  forests.  Get-wise-quick  methods  offer  the  most 
lucrative  rewards  to  the  needy  psychologist.  At  the  moment 
we  are  besieged  by  requests  to  enlighten  men  of  affairs  how  to 
choose  employees,  how  to  detect  capacities,  and  by  individuals 
how  to  increase  mental  efficiency.  Only  one  who  is  blind  to 
the  lessons  of  history  can  fail  to  see  the  dangers  in  this  great 
white  way  of  psychology.  One  cannot  look  upon  phre- 
nology, physiognomy  and  the  reading  of  character  as  merely 
the  slums  of  psychology.  Whatever  the  rating  of  the  fakir, 
his  customers  come  from  all  shades  and  grades  of  education. 
Here  may  be  gathered  interesting  varieties  of  psychological 
experience;  and  a  candidatus  philosophicus  in  psychology  may 
find  a  promising  thesis  by  illuminating  the  psychology  of 
fraud.  Yet  psychology  will  be  shirking  its  social  responsi- 
bilities if  it  declines  to  cross  an  unsavory  threshold.  It  is  not 
a  sign  of  virtue  to  fear  to  tread,  just  because  frauds  rush  in. 
Too  proud  to  investigate  is  not  a  proper  attitude.  The  prob- 
lem of  vocational  and  individual  fitness  is  a  wholly  legitimate 
and,  for  the  cautious  and  modest  psychologist,  an  engaging 
pursuit.  The  reputation  of  the  psychologist  will  depend 
upon  the  restraint  with  which  he  exercises  authority,  and 
pronounces  judgments. 

The  practical  varieties  of  psychological  experience  are 
worthy  of  respect  in  their  own  right.  We  all  know  that  the 
road  from  theory  to  practice  is  the  more  indirect  the  more 
complex  the  situation.  Qualities  are  far  more  generic  than 
their  applications.  We  must  insist  upon  the  legitimacy  of 
the  psychological  perspective  and  decline  to  assume  while 
yet  we  respect  that  of  the  practical  inquirer  with  a  narrower 
interest.  A  man  will  become  a  persuasive  salesman,  or  a 
shrewd  employer  or  a  good  teacher  far  more  regularly  upon 
the  basis  of  a  general  equipment  than  of  correspondence 


256  JOSEPH  JASTROW 

courses.  At  all  events  it  is  in  the  interpretation  of  the  under- 
lying qualities  of  men  that  psychology,  pragmatically  dis- 
posed, finds  its  metier,  however  ready  to  utilize  the  trends  of 
employment,  and  to  direct  inquiry  to  practically  significant 
relations.  The  two  perspectives  must  differ.  The  variety 
of  experience  is  valuable;  the  forms  of  experience  imposed  by 
modern  conditions  acquire  a  peculiar  importance;  but  none  of 
these  interests  should  distort  the  far  more  significant  varieties 
of  an  historically  larger  and  intrinsically  deeper  experience. 
In  precisely  the  same  sense  in  which  the  sociologist,  fixing  his 
attention  upon  modern  conditions,  will  be  handicapped  by  a 
narrow  vision  if  he  forgets  that  what  he  is  studying  with  a 
specialized  interest  is  in  reality  a  transferred  biological  situ- 
ation to  be  interpreted  under  the  principles  of  biological  re- 
lations, will  the  applied  psychologist  become  a  mere  trained 
craftsman  if  his  sense  of  design  is  unilluminated  by  the  inter- 
pretative insight  conferred  by  long  immersion  in  the  principles 
of  psychology. 

I  have  chosen  deliberately  to  enlarge  upon  the  practical 
varieties  of  psychological  experience,  for  the  reason  that  in 
this  vista  the  retrospective  view  directs  the  enterprise  which 
will  plan  the  highways  of  the  future.  The  attitude  of  Ameri- 
can psychologists  toward  the  possible  and  desirable  applica- 
tions of  their  pursuits,  even  the  mode  of  capitalization  of  their 
personal  value  for  public  consumption,  seems  to  me  so  pe- 
culiarly important  that  I  have  chosen  to  project  an  "insert" 
on  a  larger  scale  in  the  moving  picture  which  I  am  unreeling. 
The  psychologist,  I  repeat,  must  insist  upon  complete  author- 
ity as  an  architect  of  his  science;  what  consideration  shall  he 
give  to  the  expressed  needs  and  wishes  of  a  possible  clientele? 
The  practical  and  the  theoretical  perspectives  are  distinct; 
how  shall  they  be  made  to  converge,  and  yet  retain  that 
singleness  of  vision  which  is  indispensable  to  a  solid,  realistic, 
stereoscopic  effect? 

It  requires  no  prophetic  but  only  a  presbyopic  vision  to 
foresee  that  the  insistent  demands  of  practice  will  form  a 
league  to  enforce  attention.  The  psychological  practitioner 
is  coming;  upon  us  rests  the  responsibility  that,  when  he  comes 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  257 

he  shall  be  in  no  measure  a  quack  or  an  opportunist,  neither 
papal  nor  encyclopedic,  nor  pretend  to  be  all  things  to  all 
men.  The  training  of  psychologists  cannot  undertake  the 
development  of  geniuses,  who  as  a  rule  have  found  the 
academic  environment  unstimulating.  A  scientifically  minded 
sense  of  proportion  is  the  central  equipment;  with  it  must 
be  combined  a  clinical  sense  for  the  recognition  of  vari- 
eties of  experience  when  encountered.  I  resent  the  implica- 
tion that  because  a  large  amount  of  money  is  spent  in  ad- 
vertising, the  psychology  of  advertising  thereby  gains  in  sig- 
nificance or  importance.  I  welcome  the  fact  that  the  actual 
interest  in  advertising  supplies  a  variety  of  psychological 
experience  which  we  may  utilize  to  the  full.  Problems  that 
loom  large  in  application  may  have  but  slight  illumination  in 
principle,  and  be  rather  barren  in  enlightenment.  The 
analysis  of  a  practical  occupation  into  its  underlying  factors 
is  the  legitimate  work  of  the  psychological  practitioner; 
advice  will  gain  in  value  as  it  strikes  root  in  a  soil  enriched  by 
scientific  cultivation.  The  tendency  which  most  I  deplore 
is  the  neglect  of  the  wider  and  the  truer  interpretation,  because 
in  some  of  its  aspects  it  is  less  amenable  to  the  rigid  technique 
of  the  quantitative  method.  Falling  in  love  with  technique 
may  be  a  pleasant  but  is  hardly  a  rational  indulgence.  It 
forms  one  of  the  temptations,  the  idols  of  the  practical  mind. 
You  see  it  pitiably  at  work  in  the  pursuit  of  efficiency,  with 
the  result  that  there  is  more  attention  paid  to  cost-accounting 
than  to  the  value  of  the  article  when  produced.  You  see  its 
menacing  shadow  thrown  across  the  academic  portals  in  the 
impertinent  attempt  to  measure  service  by  unit-hours  and 
neglect  quality  and  all  the  finer  values  incommensurate  with 
the  crude  and  irrelevant  yardstick.  If  the  method  is  con- 
tinued, education  will  have  but  one  purpose,  ambitious  and 
charitable  at  once:  to  make  people  efficient  though  incom- 
petent. My  plea  is  for  the  recognition,  selection  and  culti- 
vation of  a  psychological  competency  for  practitioner  and 
theorist  alike;  which  is  a  plea,  in  an  expert  sense,  for  the  vari- 
eties of  psychological  experience. 

I  have  referred  to  the  danger  of  mistaking  a  quantitative 


258  JOSEPH  JASTROW 

result  for  an  important  one,  of  supposing  that  what  is  measur- 
able is  significant;  likewise  to  the  danger  of  supposing  that 
what  is  practically  demanded  is  by  that  right  entitled  to  a 
large  place  in  a  scientific  perspective.  With  these  is  combined 
the  danger  of  proceeding  to  far-flung  battle  lines  of  conclusions 
upon  a  slender  campaign  of  experimental  results.  None  of 
these  dangers  operates  simply;  they  combine  subtly  and 
intrude  subconsciously,  as  is  the  manner  of  fallacy  and  her 
tribe.  I  can  point  the  moral  most  quickly  by  using  a  tale  for 
adornment,  though  I  run  the  risk  of  stepping  upon  toes,  the 
owners  of  which  I  respect.  The  extent  of  my  hardihood  will 
be  clear  when  I  say  that  I  shall  illustrate  in  terms  of  that 
vexed  question  of  the  mental  differences  of  men  and  women. 
On  the  basis  of  well-designed  experiments  one  observer  con- 
cludes that  women  are  less  disposed  than  men  to  be  affected 
by  argument.  In  deciding  whether  one  aggregation  of 
markings  contains  more  or  fewer  individual  components  than 
another,  the  women  proved  more  tenacious  of  their  original 
opinions  (whether  this  is  consistency  or  obstinacy  is  an  unwise 
question)  than  did  the  men.  Ergo  women  are  less  desirable 
than  men  as  members  of  a  jury.  In  citing  this  bit  of  evidence 
I  am  fortunate  in  that  I  agree  with  the  significance  of  the 
findings;  but  I  remain  wholly  unconvinced  by  the  conclusion. 
The  second  illustration  finds  me  in  the  reverse  attitude. 
On  the  basis  of  a  painstaking  and  well-devised  series  of  sen- 
sory and  mental  tests,  the  convergence  of  results  measuring 
specific  capacities  proves  to  be  far  more  striking  than  the 
divergences  of  men  and  women.  Upon  these  data  is  based  the 
conclusion  that  intellectual  distinctions  among  the  sexes  do 
not  exist;  they  are  either  the  result  of  imposition  of  masculine 
dominance  upon  femine  complacency,  or  the  prejudiced  views 
of  tradition.  The  comprehensive  evidence  of  the  varieties 
of  psychological  experience  embodied  in  the  history  of  culture 
is  cavalierly  disregarded.  Everything  is  ruled  out  of  court 
except  the  findings  of  the  laboratory  in  parallel  columns  of 
figures.  The  contributions  to  the  subject  are  disposed  of  as 
belonging  either  to  the  literature  of  fact  or  the  literature  of 
opinion;  which  to  my  view  is  at  once  a  specious  and  destruc- 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  259 

tive  distinction.  Your  quantitative  fact,  however  exactly 
determined,  must  pass  the  judgment-seat  of  interpretation, 
personified  in  the  venerable  and  wordly-wise  figure  of  ex- 
perience; then  only  will  its  contributive  value  appear.  On 
the  other  hand  opinion  may  be  as  valueless  as  gossip,  and  as 
important  as  any  brand  of  truth  accessible  to  the  present 
generation.  More  particularly,  the  best  of  opinion  is  founded 
upon  exactly  the  same  appreciation  of  precise  investigation, 
is  imbued  with  precisely  the  same  scientific  method,  reflects 
a  parallel  training  and  allegiance  to  accredited  principles,  as 
that  which  guides  the  experimental  devotees.  To  disregard 
such  contributions  and  to  ignore  historical  experience  on  the 
strength  of  data  authentic  in  their  own  province  but  only 
modestly  significant  outside  of  it,  is  to  violate  conspicuously 
the  appreciation  of  varieties  of  psychological  experience, 
which  constitutes  the  most  important  equipment  for  the 
loyal  psychologist. 

Not  to  court  misunderstanding,  let  me  explain  that  I  have 
properly  selected  instances  of  unquestioned  authority,  and 
also  that  the  questionings  which  I  have  raised  are  directed 
with  unbiased  neutrality  to  point  out  the  prejudice  that  is 
invited  by  generic  interpretation,  and  by  the  neglect  thereof. 
If  we  enlarge  small  findings  to  large  conclusions  we  exceed 
our  warrant.  If  the  experimentalist  insists  upon  the  supreme 
value  of  his  experience  above  all  other  varieties,  proposes  to 
disregard  scientifically  rigorous  thinking  expended  in  other 
problems  than  his,  is  convinced  that  the  quantitative  pattern 
is  the  only  authentic  one,  that  amenability  to  measurement  is 
the  indispensable  passport  for  psychological  citizenship,  the 
future  of  psychology  faces  an  undesirable  and  unnecessary 
impoverishment.  Moreover  it  is  just  because  the  promising 
growth  of  the  applied  field  favors  so  largely  the  sharply  defined 
and  technically  interesting  varieties  of  psychological  ex- 
perience, that  the  pure  experimentalist  should  safeguard  the 
comprehensive  and  broader  aspects  of  his  function. 

With  pardonable  overemphasis  I  have  cited  the  logical  pro- 
cedures leading  to  an  agreement  with  Mme.  de  Stael:  les  dmes 
n'ont  pas  des  sexes.  According  to  this  view  minds  have  no  sex; 


260  JOSEPH  J  AST  ROW 

according  to  Freud  they  have  little  else.  And  thus  we  reach 
a  further  variety  of  experience  in  the  abnormal.  The  as- 
cendency of  the  Freudian  movement  occupies  the  head-line 
in  this  section  of  the  revue;  whether  by  reputation  or  by  no- 
toriety critics  cannot  agree.  Either  view  pointedly  illustrates 
the  complex  significance  of  varieties  of  psychological  experi- 
ence and  of  the  attitudes  that  lead  to  their  favor  or  disfavor. 
Freudian  psychology  must  be  saved  even  more  persistently 
from  its  friends  than  from  its  detractors.  As  I  grasp  its 
bearing,  it  forms  an  important  and  essentially  true  contribu- 
tion made  by  the  wrong  men;  its  germinal  ideas  are  sound 
despite  the  loosely  woven  evidence.  To  some  the  Freudian 
orchestra  makes  unseemly  noise  and  nothing  else;  others  hail 
it  as  the  music  of  the  future.  Personally  I  am  convinced  that 
the  acceptable  Freudian  sonata  remains  to  be  written;  it  will 
be  composed  by  one  imbued  with  the  spirit  of  its  method  and 
possessed  of  a  rare  sense  of  the  value  of  phrasing.  The  sex 
motif  will  be  less  insistent  and  strident,  not  silenced  or 
ignored  but  sublimated.  I  have  every  sympathy  with  those 
who  are  nauseated  by  its  seemingly  cherished  obscenity,  and 
irritated  by  its  seemingly  malicious  slander  of  the  human 
mind.  But  my  logical  conscience  rebukes  me  by  a  reminder 
that  any  such  attitude  is  irrelevant.  The  Freudian  principles 
and  the  Freudian  mechanisms  must  be  considered  for  their 
value  as  varieties  of  psychological  experience,  quite  apart  from 
the  bad  form  and  bad  taste  and  bad  logic  of  their  support 
and  supporters;  the  merit  of  the  cause  or  the  campaign  and  of 
the  tactics  or  munitions  must  be  judged  separately.  The 
Freudian  reconstruction — for  a  time  obscurely  and  disparag- 
ingly received,  and  only  recently  advancing  to  a  conspicuous 
place — has  vitalized  a  large  realm  of  observation  bearing 
upon  the  abnormal  but  equally  valid  for  the  normal  experi- 
ence. In  every  future  retrospective  view  its  place  is  secure. 
For  the  moment  it  may  impress  us  as  a  capricious,  disorderly 
vers  libre,  a  libel  upon  the  fair  name  of  poetry  or  psychology; 
when  the  exotic  and  chaotic  and  neurotic  elements  have 
given  way  to  fairer  expression  its  contributions  will  be  more 
fairly  judged  and  seen. 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  261 

My  concern  with  the  abnormal  is  limited  to  its  extension 
of  the  varieties  of  experience,  and  their  interpretation  for 
normal  use.  This  the  Freudian  doctrine  attempts,  ifi 
attempts  it  practically  in  the  method  of  psychoanalysis,  but 
confines  the  procedure  to  the  disclosure  of  entanglements  and 
disqualifications  that  impede  and  distress  normal  functioning. 
Yet  psychoanalysis  is  a  broader  practical  procedure,  related 
to  an  applied  psychology  and  the  allied  interest  of  diagnosis 
in  all  difficult  situations.  It  embraces  the  experimental 
methods  in  its  use  of  the  association-material.  It  brings  to 
the  fore  the  province  of  the  subconscious  which  constitutes 
one  of  the  most  significant  enlargements  of  psychological 
experience,  but  one  readily  misinterpreted  in  favor  of  unas- 
similated  hypothesis.  The  inclusion  of  the  domain  of  the  sub- 
conscious stands  as  one  of  the  most  significant  annexations 
in  the  retrospect — a  distinct  settlement  of  territory  wrested 
by  a  difficult  exploration  in  an  uncertain  jungle. 

Going  back  twenty-five  years,  one  comes  upon  the  thick  of 
a  fray  that  almost  threatened  a  world-war  in  psychology. 
For  the  first  five  or  ten  years  of  my  professional  experience  the 
popular  view  of  a  psychologist  was  a  ghost-hunter.  Psychical 
research  held  the  field  of  popular  favor;  that  a  laboratory  was 
anything  else  than  a  seance-chamber  seemed  incredible.  The 
psychologist  had  to  listen  to  inane  stories  of  coincidences,  that 
spoiled  many  a  promising  dinner-party.  When  he  couldn't 
explain  a  lame  and  distorted  tale,  his  inconsequence  was  made 
shamelessly  and  publicly  evident.  Scepticism  was  considered 
a  mask  for  ignorance,  and  an  unpleasant  substitute  for  the 
lie  direct.  But  the  most  remarkable  aspect  of  the  movement 
was  the  hold  it  gained  upon  men  eminent  in  science — but  not 
in  psychology — through  whose  advocacy  psychical  research 
attained  a  prestige  far  beyond  that  accorded  to  psychology 
as  we  know  it.  Indeed  in  many  quarters  the  interest  in  psy- 
chology was  prompted  by  a  hope  that  it  would  solve  questions 
foremost  in  the  minds  of  psychic  researchers — such  as  telepa- 
thy and  the  survival  of  personality.  That  in  some  sense 
significant  varieties  of  psychological  experience  pervaded 
that  racially  old  field  of  belief,  that  persistent  recurrence  of 


262  JOSEPH  J  AST  ROW 

reversal  of  orderly  mental  sequence,  was  a  position  variously 
defended.  All  this  has  in  these  days  the  flavor  of  dried  me- 
mentos. Yet  it  was  only  a  half  a  dozen  years  ago,  in  these 
scientifically  dedicated  precincts,  that  a  small  group  of  us 
found  it  necessary  to  allay  popular  and  learned  unrest  in 
regard  to  the  specific  mechanism  by  which  a  homemade  bass- 
wood  table  defied  the  law  of  physics  in  the  presence  of  a 
much  heralded  and  sponsored  Neapolitan  and  of  a  company 
sufficiently  impressed  to  pay  handsomely  for  each  levitation 
of  a  skillful  foot.  The  experience  was  at  once  humiliating 
and  enlightening.  Fraud-hunting  as  an  indoor  sport  may 
have  some  zest  if  not  value;  or  it  may  become  a  social  obliga- 
tion. It  has  helped  to  dissipate  the  surviving  myth  that  the 
man  of  the  academy  is  wholly  lost  in  the  mazes  of  a  wicked 
world.  Those  of  us  who  in  the  older  days  protested  against 
the  profanation  of  psychology,  and  were  often  snubbed  for  our 
insolence,  may  properly  indulge  in  a  moment  of  congratu- 
lation to  the  younger  psychologists  who  have  not  this  role 
to  play.  Yet  the  true  interpretation  of  the  phenomena  that 
psychical  research  attempted  to  invite  to  unlawful  secession 
remains  a  part  of  the  gain  of  abnormal  psychology. 

The  concluding  phase  of  the  composite  psychological  wave 
is  represented  by  the  psychology  of  social  relations.  Its 
pursuit  obviously  requires  a  capacity  for  broad  interpretation, 
for  the  analysis  of  the  deepest  motives  of  human  conduct,  for 
the  envisagement  of  underlying  similarity  of  situation  despite 
complexity  of  circumstance,  for  catching  psychology  on  the 
hoof,  and  sensing  its  living  products  and  pulsating  throbs; 
my  cental  plea  for  catholicity  of  experience  receives  here  its 
most  direct  justification.  The  laboratory  with  its  simplified 
and  scheduled  analyses  finds  its  corrective  in  the  intricate 
worldly  composite  of  conflicting  forces.  Social  psychology 
represents  the  most  elaborate  phases  of  an  applied  science. 
It  is  applied  in  the  tests  of  life.  It  quickens  every  interest 
that  is  entrusted  to  the  psychologist,  and  justifies  as  it  am- 
plifies his  problems.  For  it  makes  clear  in  how  many  direc- 
tions psychology  has  a  voice  with  other  concerns,  makes  it 
clear  that  to  be  a  psychologist  implies  a  capacity  to  seize  the 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  263 

psychological  value  of  experience  which  to  other  interests 
presents  different  aspects  and  appeals, — to  single  out  the  psy- 
chological instruments  in  the  orchestration  of  life.  All  life 
is  of  one  living;  the  psychologist,  far  less  than  the  devotee  of 
other  specialties  can  afford  to  diagram  or  artificialize  his  Fach. 
He  should  be  in  the  world  and  of  it,  in  the  best  sense  an  inter- 
preter of  human  values,  capacities,  enterprises;  for  his  is  the 
duty  of  directing  and  safeguarding  the  precious  mechanisms 
upon  which  all  living  proceeds.  Such  must  be  his  insight  and 
his  training  that  he  may  be  rewarded  by  the  respect  of  his 
fellows  in  science,  his  cooperators  in  practical  affairs. 

I  look  to  the  increasing  study  of  social  psychology  for  a 
redemption  from  too  restricted  specialization,  for  a  balance  to 
the  dangers  of  absorption  in  technique,  for  a  compensation 
for  the  limitations  of  the  quantitative  method.  A  sense  of 
the  reality,  of  the  richness  and  fullness,  the  complexity  and 
conflict,  the  growths,  changes  and  transformations  of  the 
mind's  products  permeates  this  field  as  no  other.  In  a  measure 
it  projects  the  culmination  of  psychological  experience;  it 
projects  culture  and  the  vaster  problems  of  political  and  social 
striving  as  a  psychological  evolution,  testifying  to  the  great- 
ness of  the  forces  of  mind.  And  we  of  to-day  are  witnessing 
the  largest  and  most  appalling  issues  of  estrangement  in 
ideals,  sentiments,  allegiances,  that  the  world  has  faced;  the 
psychology  of  war  must  be  considered  in  the  establishment  of 
enduring  human  relations.  The  world  is  going  to  be  wisely 
ruled,  the  endeavors  of  organized  men  more  sanely  directed, 
the  errors  of  the  past  less  disastrously  repeated,  if  a  body  of 
men  find  participation  in  the  direction  of  affairs  possessed  of  a 
psychological  discernment;  for  this  insight  is  as  indispensable 
to  modern  conditions  in  certain  relations  as  is  an  economical, 
a  political,  or  a  business  sense  in  others. 

Lying  close  to  this  domain  and  making  a  parallel  appeal 
is  a  body  of  knowledge,  engaging  in  itself  and  vital  in  its 
applications,  which  I  select  for  special  consideration.  I  do 
so  because  it  sets  forth  so  amply  and  so  pointedly  the  quali- 
fications of  the  psychologist;  also  because  it  presents  manifold 
relations  to  all  the  several  divisions  of  the  present  review, 


264  JOSEPH  J  AST  ROW 

and  thereby  points  the  moral  of  my  thesis.  Dessoir  in  his 
"History  of  Psychology"  recognizes  it  as  one  of  the  three 
great  interests  in  the  science  of  mind,  with  ancient  antecedents 
and  constant  influence;  he  calls  it  psychognosis.  In  modern 
relations  it  may  be  viewed  as  an  oblique  or  irregular  section 
through  the  entirety  of  interests  that  form  the  composite  of 
psychology;  the  specific  disciplines  consider  the  several  fields 
more  directly  and  disinterestedly.  The  nature  of  individual 
differences,  the  sources  of  these  in  human  trends,  their  ex- 
pression and  emphasis  in  historical  circumstance,  their 
liabilities  and  possibilities  in  cultivation  and  decay,  their 
contributions  to  human  institutions — are  all  involved  in 
psychognosis.  The  directions  of  temperament,  the  founda- 
tions of  character,  the  total  determinations  of  capacity  and 
career  form  its  subject  matter.  The  temper  of  its  pursuit  is 
practical,  but  always  with  that  wider  and  deeper  foundation 
in  varieties  of  human  experience,  which  sends  it  back  for 
analysis  and  authority  to  one  and  another  discipline  of 
psychology.  It  develops  congenially  under  the  type  of 
interest  that  supports  social  psychology,  has  its  strongest 
affiliations  there;  but  it  utilizes  the  entire  range  of  psycho- 
logical science  and  requires  a  catholic  interpretation  of  the 
psychologist's  function.  Its  restatement  under  the  tremen- 
dous enrichment  of  the  last  twenty-five  years  of  psychological 
investigation  is  an  urgent  desideratum  of  the  present;  and 
this  obligation  will  do  much  to  invite  psychologists  to  that 
attitude  toward  their  province  which  shall  not  be  provincial 
but  in  the  worthiest  sense  cosmopolitan. 

The  prospective  and  the  prophetic  venture  is  more  en- 
gaging than  the  retrospective;  commemorative  occasions 
invite  a  Janus-faced,  judicial  attitude.  The  westward  course 
of  empire  returning  upon  itself  sets  the  gaze  upon  the  east 
once  more;  with  the  rounding  of  the  circle  the  conquests  of 
the  future  turn  to  an  inward  advancement,  to  the  perfection 
of  the  human  equipment  that  comes  from  a  comprehension 
of  its  nature,  origin  and  history.  In  this  vast  reconstruction 
the  psychologist  comes  to  his  own.  He  expresses  and  confers 
upon  his  disciples  an  interpretative  sense,  which  in  the  be- 


VARIETIES  OF  PSYCHOLOGICAL  EXPERIENCE  265 

wilderment  of  change  traces  the  orderly  relations  of  law. 
Whatever  the  progress  of  the  future,  he  recognizes  in  Kipling's 
words,  that 

We  can  bring  no  more  to  living, 
Than  the  powers  we  bring  to  life. 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY1 

BY  JOHN  DEWEY 

Columbia  University 

On  the  surface  it  is  just  coincidence  that  the  foundation 
of  this  association  and  the  publication  of  the  'Principles  of 
Psychology'  of  William  James  were  so  nearly  contemporan- 
eous, their  respective  dates  being,  as  you  know,  1891  and 
1890.  In  view,  however,  of  the  depth  and  breadth  of  the  in- 
fluence of  James,  we  who  are  celebrating  to-day  our  twenty- 
fifth  anniversary  are  at  liberty,  I  think,  to  consider  the  coin- 
cidence as  more  than  chronological,  and  to  date  back  by  one 
year  the  gestation  of  our  association.  At  all  events,  it  would 
be  ungrateful  to  engage  in  any  discussion  of  the  past  and 
future  of  social  psychology  without  recalling  the  few  rich 
pages  of  the  'Principles'  which  are  devoted  to  the  social  self, 
and,  in  the  discussion  of  instincts,  to  the  native  reactions  of 
human  beings  in  the  presence  of  one  another.  Big  books 
have  been  written  since  which  are  hardly  more  than  an  am- 
plification of  suggestions  found  in  these  few  pages.  When, 
for  example,  a  few  years  later,  the  Socius  became  the  hero  of  a 
psychological  drama,  not  many  recalled  that  he  had  already 
been  introduced  under  that  very  name  in  the  pages  of  James. 

Again  it  is  outwardly  a  mere  coincidence  that  the  work  of 
Tarde  on  the  'Laws  of  Imitation'  was  published  in  the  year 
in  which  the  'Principles'  saw  the  light  of  day,  and  that 
practically  all  of  Tarde's  work  fell  within  the  decade  lying 
between  1890  and  1900.  But  behind  the  pure  coincidence 
there  was  the  recognition  of  the  need  for  social  ends  of  a  more 
scientific  treatment  of  collective  human  nature,  and  the 
important  role  of  psychology  in  building  up  the  new  social 
science.  While  James  confined  himself  to  pregnant  sugges- 
tions concerning  the  new  forms  which  human  experience  and 

1  Address  given  on  the  occasion  of  the  celebration  of  the  twenty-fifth  anniversary 
of  the  American  Psychological  Association,  New  York,  December  28,  1916. 
266 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  267 

selfhood  take  on  because  of  the  presence  of  other  human 
selves,  Tarde  attempted  an  ambitious  interpretation  of  almost 
all  facts  of  social  organization,  progress  and  degeneration  in 
terms  of  certain  rubrics  to  which  he  gave  a  psychological 
quality.  For  more  than  a  decade  his  work  and  that  of  his 
followers  in  France  and  in  the  United  States — among  whom 
we  may  cite  in  diverse  directions  Baldwin  and  Ross — domi- 
nated social  psychology  and  almost  sociology.  I  shall  not 
rehearse  the  old  discussions  about  Imitation  as  a  psychological 
fact  and  a  social  force.  I  shall  assume  with  most  of  contem- 
porary psychological  critics  that  as  a  descriptive  and  explana- 
tory conception  it  misplaced  emphasis  and  tended  to  distort 
facts.  But  nevertheless  we  cannot  minimize  the  immense 
power  of  this  stage  of  social  science  in  popularizing  the  idea  of 
social  psychology,  and  in  bringing  into  recognition  many 
facts,  such  as  the  importance  of  prestige,  fashion,  sensitive- 
ness to  the  beliefs  of  others,  the  difficulties  which  innovation, 
no  matter  how  reasonable,  has  to  meet,  etc.,  facts  which  are 
permanently  imbedded  in  social  science.  Tarde  himself  was 
certainly  one  of  the  most  stimulating  and  varied  of  writers, 
and  I  do  not  think  we  shall  ever  outgrow  some  of  his  contri- 
butions, although  to  my  mind  they  are  found  rather  in  logic 
than  in  psychology — such  as  the  necessity  for  reducing  the 
gross  phenomena  of  social  life  into  minuter  events  which  may 
then  be  analyzed  one  by  one.  The  most  fruitful  of  his  psy- 
chological conceptions  was  ahead  of  his  time  and  went  almost 
unnoted.  It  was  that  all  psychological  phenomena  can  be 
divided  into  the  physiological  and  the  social,  and  that  when 
we  have  relegated  elementary  sensation  and  appetite  to  the 
former  head,  all  that  is  left  of  our  mental  life,  our  beliefs, 
ideas  and  desires,  falls  within  the  scope  of  social  psychology. 
I  hope  I  may  find  general  agreement  in  pointing  to  the 
work  of  McDqugall  and  Thorndike  respectively  as  indicative 
of  the  next  great  force  in  social  psychology,  together  with  such 
writings  as  those,  upon  the  social  side,  of  Graham  Wallas. 
Aside  from  valuable  contributions  in  detail,  the  significance 
of  these  contributions  lies,  to  my  mind,  in  ^recalling  social 
psychology  from  the  wrong  track  in  which  the  Imitation  and 


268  JOHN  DEWEY 

Suggestibility  schools  had  set  it  going.  For  those  schools 
gave  the  dawning  science  a  wrong  twist  in  carrying  over  into 
science  the  old  popular  and  practical  antithesis  of  the  indi- 
vidual and  the  social,  and  thus  setting  up  two  independent 
and  even  contrary  sciences — individual  and  social  psychology. 
As  a  concrete  illustration  of  the  absurd^results  to  which  this 
antithesis  led,  it  is  perhaps  sufficient  to  refer  to  those  bizarre 
writings  on  the  psychology  of  the  crowd  in  which  it  was 
assumed  that  the  psychology  of  the  individual  left  to  himself 
is  reflective  and  rational,  while  man's  emotional  obsessions 
and  irrationalities  are  to  be  accounted  for  by  the  psychology 
of  association  with  others.  From  the  root  of  all  such  aber- 
rations we  were  recalled  the  very  moment  the  problem  was 
presented  not  as  one  of  the  relationship  of  a  mythical 
psychology  of  an  isolated  individual  mind  to  the  even  more 
mythical  psychology  of  a  mass  or  crowd  or  public  mind,  but 
as  the  problem  of  the  relationship  of  original  or  native  ac- 
tivities to  acquired  capacities  and  habits.  Henceforth  our 
social  psychology  is  placed  upon  the  sure  ground  of  observa- 
tion of  instinctive  behavior;  it  can  develop  upon  the  basis  of 
fact  undistorted  by  the  requirement  of  meeting  preconceived 
notions  imported  from  without.  The  whole  question  of 
imitation,  for  example,  reduces  itself  to  one  of  fact:  Is  imi- 
tativeness  one  of  the  original  tendencies  of  human  nature. 
If  so,  what  is  its  intensity  and  mode  of  working  in  conjunction 
with  the  other  unlearned  activities? 

The  popularizers  of  science  will  doubtless  remain  half  a 
generation  behind  this  as  well  as  other  scientific  advances,  but 
for  those  who  have  learned  the  lesson  of  recourse  to  funda- 
mental responses,  the  way  is  opened  for  emancipation  from 
the  greatest  foe  with  which  social  science  has  had  to  contend 
— which  I  shall  take  the  liberty  of  calling  the  monistic.  How 
often  have  we  been  invited  to  build  up  our  social,  political,  and 
ethical  explanations  in  terms  of  some  single  and  supposedly 
dominant  mental  constituent!  How  often  discussions  and 
disputes  have  been,  at  bottom,  only  a  question  as  to  which 
of  rival  single  claimants  we  shall  yield  allegiance.  Instincts 
to  power,  to  control  of  others,  fear  of  authority,  sex,  love  of 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  269 

pleasure,  of  ease,  all  have  been  appealed  to,  and  explanations 
constructed  in  terms  of  one  or  another  exclusively.  Hence- 
forth it  is,  I  submit,  pure  wilfulness  if  any  one  pretending  to 
a  scientific  treatment  starts  from  any  other  than  a  pluralistic 
basis:  the  complexity  and  specific  variety  of  the  factors  of 
human  nature,  each  operating  in  response  to  its  own  highly 
specific  stimulus,  and  each  subject  to  almost  infinite  shadings 
and  modulations  as  it  enters  into  combination  and  competition 
with  others.  The  conception  of  social  psychology  resulting 
from  this  mode  of  approach  becomes  essentially  one  with 
that  set  forth  by  Professor  W.  I.  Thomas  in  his  paper  on  the 
province  of  social  psychology  at  the  St.  Louis  Congress  of 
Arts  and  Science  in  1904,  On  the  one  hand  our  problem  is 
to  know  the  modifications  wrought  in  the  native  constitution 
of  man  by  the  fact  that  the  elements  of  his  endowment  operate 
in  this  or  that  social  medium;  on  the  other  hand,  we  want  to 
know  how  control  of  the  environment  may  be  better  secured 
by  means  of  the  operation  of  this  or  that  native  capacity. 
Under  these  general  heads  are  summed  up  the  infinity  of 
special  and  difficult  problems  relating  to  education  on  the 
one  hand  and  to  constructive  modification  of  our  social  in- 
stitutions on  the  other.  To  form  a  mind  out  of  certain 
native  instincts  by  selecting  an  environment  which  evokes 
them  and  directs  their  course;  to  re-form  social  institutions 
by  breaking  up  habits  and  giving  peculiar  intensity  and 
scope  to  some  impulse  is  the  problem  of  social  control  in  its 
two  phases.  To  describe  how  such  changes  take  place  is  the 
task  of  social  psychology  stated  in  generalized  terms. 

I  hope  I  do  not  need  to  disclaim  an  attempt  to  give  in  even 
the  barest  summary  the  history  of  social  psychology  during 
the  past  twenty-five  years.  My  object  has  been  quite  other. 
I  have  only  wanted  to  refer  to  some  salients  in  the  intellectual 
fortifications  constructed  during  this  period  for  the  sake  of 
pointing  out,  in  equally  general  terms,  something  of  what  now 
confronts  us,  waiting,  nay  demanding,  to  be  done.  Before 
passing  on  to  this  point,  I  feel  I  must  avert  possible  misunder- 
standing by  mentioning  two  allied  factors  which  have  also 
influenced  the  development  of  which  I  have  spoken.  One  is 


270  JOHN  DEWEY 

the  application  of  statistical  methods  to  psychological  re- 
search; the  other,  the  behavioristic  movement.  Neither  was 
devised  primarily  in  the  interests  of  social  psychology.  The 
requirements  of  education  have,  however,  been  a  powerful 
agency  in  promoting  the  former,  while  education  presents, 
of  course,  one  phase  of  the  problem  of  social  control.  Speak- 
ing more  broadly,  social  phenomena  are  of  a  kind  which  demand 
statistical  mathematics  rather  than  the  type  of  mathematics 
which  has  been  evolved  especially  for  use  in  dealing  with 
physical  facts.  Condorcet's  great  essay  on  'The  Progress  of 
the  Human  Mind'  forecasts  a  future  in  which  human  arrange- 
ments would  be  regulated  by  science.  In  dealing  with  the 
influence  of  mathematical  science  he  points  to  the  newly 
developing  theory  of  probabilities  as  that  branch  of  mathe- 
matics which  is  fraught  with  infinite  potentiality  for  control 
of  social  progress.  I  think  it  is  only  fair  to  see  in  statistical 
psychology  a  step  forward,  short  and  halting  though  it  be 
for  the  immediate  present,  in  the  realization  of  Condorcet's 
prophecy. 

The  behavioristic  movement  inevitably  tends  to  confirm 
the  tendency  of  which  I  have  already  spoken  in  connection 
with  the  writings  of  James,  McDougall,  and  Thorndike.  It 
transfers  attention  from  vague  generalities  regarding  social 
consciousness  and  social  mind  to  the  specific  processes  of 
interaction  which  take  place  among  human  beings,  and  to  the 
details  of  group-behavior.  It  emphasizes  the  importance  of 
knowledge  of  the  primary  activities  of  human  nature,  and  of 
the  modifications  and  reorganizations  they  undergo  in  asso- 
ciation with  the  activities  of  others.  It  radically  simplifies 
the  whole  problem  by  making  it  clear  that  social  institutions 
and  arrangements,  including  the  whole  apparatus  of  tradition 
and  transmission,  represent  simply  the  acquired  transforma- 
tions of  original  human  endowments. 

This  provides  the  possibility  of  a  positive  method  for 
analyzing  social  phenomena.  I  shall  avoid  engaging  in  passing 
in  the  disputed  question  of  the  value  of  an  introspective 
psychology.  But  it  seems  almost  self-evident  that  even  if 
introspection  were  a  valid  method  in  individual  psychology, 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  271 

so  called,  it  could  not  be  of  use  in  the  investigation  of  social 
facts,  even  though  those  facts  be  labelled  social  mind  or 
consciousness.  Yet  one  has  only  to  look  at  the  writings  of 
the  Austrian  and  German  school  of  "folk-psychologists" 
(say  of  Wundt,  obviously  the  most  important)  to  see  how  this 
treatment  has  been  affected  by  an  assumed  need  of  making 
the  method  and  results  of  social  psychology  conform  to  the 
received  categories  of  introspective  psychology.  From  such 
deforming  of  facts  the  behavioristic  outlook  immediately 
redeems  us;  it  represents  not  an  improvement  in  detail  but  a 
different  mode  of  attack.  It  is  not  as  yet  possible  to  estimate 
the  significance  of  this  alteration.  In  my  opinion,  however, 
the  chief  cause  of  the  backwardness  of  social  psychology  has 
resided  in  the  artificiality  of  the  endeavor  to  adapt  the  rubrics 
of  introspective  psychology  to  the  facts  of  objective  associated 
life.  The  opening  of  another  road  of  approach  may  therefore 
be  expected  to  emancipate  inquiry. 

I  thus  come  to  the  explicit  statement  of  the  purpose  of  my 
reminiscent  sketch.  The  aim  was  to  justify  the  presentation 
of  the  conviction  that  the  quarter  century  in  which  this 
Association  has  existed  marks  just  the  emancipation  of  social 
psychology  from  influences  which  prevented  its  development 
on  its  own  feet  and  its  own  merits,  while  the  work  done  on 
lines  which  (as  it  seems  to  me)  must  be  abandoned,  have 
nevertheless  done  the  great  service  of  enforcing  the  vast 
field  open  to  a  social  psychology,  and  the  great  need  it  has  to 
serve.  I  turn  accordingly  from  the  past  to  the  future,  or  if 
you  will  from  prophecy  taking  the  guise  of  history  to  prophecy 
frankly  avowing  itself  as  such. 

I  foresee,  then,  a  great  reflex  wave  from  social  psychology 
back  into  general  psychology.  An  important  conclusion  in 
the  psychology  of  native  activities  does  not  seem  to  have  been 
drawn  as  yet  by  those  who  would  base  a  scientific  psychology 
upon  this  foundation.  The  conclusion  seems  inevitable  that 
since  'mind'  does  not  appear  in  the  original  list  of  instincts, 
it  represents  something  acquired.  It  represents  a  reorgan- 
ization of  original  activities  through  their  operation  in  a 
given  environment.  It  is  a  formation,  not  a  datum;  a  pro- 


272  JOHN  DEWEY 

duct,  and  a  cause  only  after  it  has  been  produced.  Now 
theoretically  it  is  possible  that  the  reorganization  of  native 
activities  which  constitute  mind  may  occur  through  their  exer- 
cise within  a  purely  physical  medium.  Empirically,  however, 
this  is  highly  improbable.  A  consideration  of  the  dependence 
in  infancy  of  the  organization  of  the  native  activities  into 
intelligence  upon  the  presence  of  others,  upon  sharing  in  joint 
activities  and  upon  language,  make  it  obvious  that  the  sort 
of  mind  capable  of  development  through  the  operation  of 
native  endowment  in  a  non-social  environment  is  of  the  moron 
order,  and  is  practically,  if  not  theoretically,  negligible. 

The  net  outcome  of  the  newer  type  of  psychological 
method  is  thus  an  unexpected  confirmation  of  the  insight  of 
Tarde  that  what  we  call  'mind'  means  essentially  the  working 
of  certain  beliefs  and  desires;  and  that  these  in  the  concrete — 
in  the  only  sense  in  which  mind  may  be  said  to  exist — are 
functions  of  associated  behavior,  varying  with  the  structure 
and  operation  of  social  groups.  Speaking  in  general  terms, 
there  is  no  more  a  problem  of  the  origin  of  society  than  there 
is  of  the  origin  of  chemical  reactions;  things  are  made  that 
way.  But  a  certain  kind  of  associated  or  joint  life  when 
brought  into  being  has  an  unexpected  by-product — the  for- 
mation of  those  peculiar  acquired  dispositions,  sets,  attitudes, 
which  are  termed  mind.  This  by-product  continually  gains 
in  relative  importance.  It  increasingly  becomes  the  signi- 
ficant acquisition  among  all  the  varied  reorganizations  of 
native  tendencies.  That  anything  which  may  properly  be 
called  mind  or  intelligence  is  not  an  original  possession  but  is 
a  consequence  of  the  manifestation  of  instincts  under  the 
conditions  supplied  by  associated  life  in  the  family,  the 
school,  the  market  place  and  the  forum,  is  no  remote  inference 
from  a  speculative  reconstruction  of  the  mind  of  primitive 
man;  it  is  a  conclusion  confirmed  by  the  development  of 
specific  beliefs,  ideas  and  purposes  in  the  life  of  every  infant 
now  observable. 

On  the  face  of  it,  this  conclusion  has  implications  only  for 
the  theory  of  psychology.  But  slight  scrutiny  makes  obvious 
its  consequences  for  the  struggle  to  gain  control  of  the  forces 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  273 

forming  society.  The  ultimate  refuge  of  the  standpatter  in 
every  field,  education,  religion,  politics,  industrial  and 
domestic  life,  has  been  the  notion  of  an  alleged  fixed  structure 
of  mind.  As  long  as  mind  is  conceived  as  an  antecedent  and 
ready-made  thing,  institutions  and  customs  may  be  regarded 
as  its  offspring.  By  its  own  nature  the  ready-made  mind 
works  to  produce  them  as  they  have  existed  and  now  exist. 
There  is  no  use  in  kicking  against  necessity.  The  most 
powerful  apologetics  for  any  arrangement  or  institution  is  the 
conception  that  it  is  an  inevitable  result  of  fixed  conditions  of 
human  nature.  Consequently,  in  one  disguise  or  another, 
directly  or  by  extreme  and  elaborate  indirection,  we  find  the 
assumed  constitution  of  an  antecedently  given  mind  appealed 
to  in  justification  of  the  established  order  as  to  the  family, 
the  school,  the  government,  industry,  commerce  and  every 
other  institution.  Our  increased  knowledge  of  the  past  of 
man  has,  indeed,  given  this  complacent  assumption  a  certain 
shock,  but  it  has  not  as  yet  seriously  modified  it.  Evolution 
in  the  sense  of  a  progressive  unfolding  of  original  potencies 
latent  in  a  ready-made  mind  has  been  used  to  reconcile  the 
conception  of  mind  as  an  original  datum  with  the  historic 
facts  of  social  change  which  can  no  longer  be  ignored.  The 
effect  on  the  effort  at  deliberate  social  control  and  construction 
remained  the  same.  All  man  could  do  was  to  wait  and  watch 
the  panorama  of  a  ready-formed  mind  unroll.  The  French 
school  of  imitation,  and  its  present  successor,  the  Durkheim 
school  of  collective  mind,  has  practically  the  same  outcome 
as  the  German  school  of  Volk-geist  in  this  respect.  All  are 
engaged  in  explaining  the  past  and  present,  and  (if  they  predict 
at  all)  in  predicting  the  future  on  the  basis  of  the  past.  The 
new  point  of  view  treats  social  facts  as  the  material  of  an 
experimental  science,  where  the  problem  is  that  of  modifying 
belief  and  desire — that  is  to  say  mind — by  enacting  specific 
changes  in  the  social  environment.  Until  this  experimental 
attitude  is  established,  the  historical  method,  in  spite  of  all 
the  proof  of  past  change  which  it  adduces,  will  remain  in 
effect  a  bulwark  of  conservatism.  For,  I  repeat,  it  reduces 
the  role  of  mind  to  that  of  beholding  and  recording  the  oper- 


274  JOHN  DEWEY 

ations  of  man  after  they  have  happened.  The  historic 
method  may  give  emotional  inspiration  or  consolation  in 
arousing  the  belief  that  a  lot  more  changes  are  still  to  happen, 
but  it  does  not  show  man  how  his  mind  is  to  take  part  in 
giving  these  changes  one  direction  rather  than  another. 

The  advent  of  a  type  of  psychology  which  builds  frankly 
on  the  original  activities  of  man  and  asks  how  these  are 
altered,  requalified  and  reorganized  in  consequence  of  their 
exercise  in  specifically  different  environments  brings  with  it- 
self the  experimental  attitude,  and  thereby  substitutes  the 
interest  in  control  for  the  interest  in  merely  recording  and 
what  is  called  'explaining.'  If  mind,  in  any  definitely  con- 
crete sense  of  that  word,  is  an  offspring  of  the  life  of  associ- 
ation, intercourse,  transmission,  and  accumulation  rather 
than  a  ready-made  antecedent  cause  of  these  things,  then  the 
attitude  of  polite  aloofness  or  condescending  justification  as 
to  social  institutions  has  its  nerve  cut,  and  with  this  the  in- 
tellectual resources  of  sanctified  conservatism  disappear. 
Instincts  become  mind  when  they  are  organized  and  directed 
with  reference  to  the  ends  of  attention,  esteem,  and  endeavor 
which  are  supplied  by  the  shared  life  of  the  place  and  time. 
The  kind  of  mind  they  become  depends  upon  the  kind  of 
objects  of  attention  and  affection  which  the  specific  social 
conditions  supply.  The  task  of  unravelling  the  arrangements 
which  exist  into  elements  of  native  instinct  and  past  acquisi- 
tions is  indeed  an  infinitely  complex  and  difficult  one;  not  the 
less  hard  and  extensive  is  the  job  of  showing  how  this  and  that 
association  with  other  persons  develops  this  and  that  intel- 
lectual and  emotional  disposition — or  mind — in  this  and  that 
individual  having  his  own  peculiar  original  endowment.  But 
if  the  history  of  human  achievement  in  knowledge  proves 
anything,  it  is  that  the  all-decisive  discovery  is  that  of  an 
effective  and  fruitful  method.  When  men  once  hit,  after 
endless  awkwardness,  upon  the  right  road,  the  rest  takes  care 
of  itself.  Scientific  movement  becomes  orderly  and  cumu- 
lative in  the  very  process  of  occurring.  Social  and  mental 
phenomena  become  intelligible  because  they  come  within  the 
scope  of  the  experimental  method  of  attack.  And  again  the 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  275 

history  of  science  testifies  to  a  conclusion  which  may  also  be 
arrived  at  theoretically — the  introduction  of  the  experi- 
mental method  is  all  one  with  interest  in  control — in  modi- 
fication of  the  future. 

There  is  a  genuine  modesty,  and  there  is  a  stupid  simu- 
lation of  modesty  which  is  only  a  mask  for  lazy  complacency. 
No  science  has  so  much  cause  to  be  humble  about  its  actual 
achievements  as  has  social  science,  including  social  psy- 
chology. But  in  prospect,  in  possibility,  social  science  seems 
to  me  to  stand  about  where  physical  science  stood  three 
centures  ago  in  the  early  years  of  the  seventeenth  century. 
There  is  the  same  halting  and  obstructed  tendency  to  move 
from  the  attitude  of  the  outside  spectator,  classifier  and 
justifier  of  things  as  they  are  outwardly  given  to  that  of  the 
active  participant  and  modifier,  from  that  of  wholesale  or- 
ganization to  that  of  retail  reorganization.  The  experimental 
method  in  physical  matters  brought  with  it  a  technique 
of  control — a  technique  of  invention  and  construction. 
Specific  desired  ends  can  be  formulated  in  specifically  ana- 
lyzed terms;  the  conditions  of  their  attainment  stated;  these 
conditions  subdivided  into  known  and  unknown  factors,  and 
some  definite  estimate  made  as  to  the  praticability,  at  the 
given  time,  of  attacking  the  problem.  That  we  are  without 
any  such  technique  in  social  matters  is  self-evident.  That 
the  attainment  within  reasonable  time  of  a  similar  technique 
stands  and  falls  with  the  possibility  of  developing  a  human 
psychology  which  shall  be  experimentally  applicable  to  the 
understanding  of  social  affairs  is  not,  however,  self-evident, 
and  is  my  excuse  for  reiteration. 

I  venture  accordingly  to  repeat  a  thought  which  I  had  the 
honor  of  presenting  before  this  association  some  years  ago. 
The  need  of  social  control  is,  of  course,  as  old  as  associated 
life  itself.  But  the  need  of  that  control  at  the  present  time 
is  tremendously  accentuated  by  the  enormous  lack  of  balance 
between  existing  methods  of  physical  and  social  direction. 
The  utilization  of  physical  energies  made  possible  by  the 
advance  of  physics  and  chemistry  has  enormously  complicated 
the  industrial  and  political  problem.  The  question  of  the 


276  JOHN  DEWEY 

distribution  of  economic  resources,  of  the  relationships  of  rich 
and  poor  was  never  so  acute  nor  so  portentous  as  it  is  now;  and 
this  state  of  affairs  is  as  much  the  result  of  progress  in  physical 
science  as  is  the  recognition  of  the  Copernician  astronomy. 
The  present  war  is  too  vast  and  too  tragic  to  permit  one 
lightly  to  summon  it  as  evidence  for  any  merely  theoretical 
thesis.  But  is  it  not,  I  ask,  a  demonstration  made  to  order  of 
those  old  words  of  Thomas  Hobbes?  "The  utility  of  moral  and 
civil  philosophy  is  to  be  estimated,  not  so  much  by  the  com- 
modities we  have  from  knowing  those  sciences  as  from  the 
calamities  we  receive  from  not  knowing  them."  Such  a 
conception  is  not  fashionable  just  now;  it  is  easier  to  place 
blame  upon  fate  or  upon  the  innate  wickedness  of  human 
nature  as  seen  in  this  or  in  that  set  of  human  beings.  But 
the  ultimate  fate  is  the  fatality  of  ignorance,  and  the  ultimate 
wickedness  is  lack  of  faith  in  the  possibilities  of  intelligence 
applied  inventively  and  constructively. 

Physical  science  has  got  to  the  point  of  bringing  even  the 
ends  of  the  earth  into  physical,  forceful  relations  with  one 
another,  and  to  the  point  of  mobilizing  all  its  resources  for  a 
contest  in  aggression  and  endurance.  We  are  overwhelmed 
by  the  consequences  of  the  very  sciences  into  which  have  gone 
our  best  thought  and  energy  for  these  last  few  hundred  years. 
We  apparently  do  not  control  them;  they  control  us  and  wreak 
their  vengeance  upon  us.  Yet  how  infantile  and  pusil- 
lanimous are  those  who  talk  about  the  bankruptcy  of  science 
and  who  blame  the  increase  of  knowledge  for  our  situation. 
Physical  knowledge,  and  the  consequent  technique  of  control 
of  physical  forces,  has  far  out-run  social  knowledge  and  its 
technique.  The  recourse  of  a  courageous  humanity  is  to 
press  forward  in  the  latter  until  we  have  a  control  of  human 
nature  comparable  to  our  control  of  physical  nature. 

From  the  point  of  view  of  the  psychology  of  behavior  all 
psychology  is  either  biological  or  social  psychology.  And  if  it 
still  be  true  that  man  is  not  only  an  animal  but  a  social 
animal,  the  two  cannot  be  dissevered  when  we  deal  with  man. 
Hence  it  is  that  subsequent  years  have  enabled  me  to  find 
added  meaning  in  words  which  I  spoke  before  this  association 


THE  NEED  FOR  SOCIAL  PSYCHOLOGY  277 

years  ago,  and  which  in  conclusion  I  venture  to  repeat.  "  We 
are  not  called  upon  to  be  either  boasters  or  sentimentalists 
regarding  the  possibilities  of  our  science.  .  .  .  But  we  are 
entitled  in  our  daily  work  to  be  sustained  by  the  conviction 
that  we  are  not  working  in  indifference  to  or  at  cross  purposes 
with  the  practical  strivings  of  a  common  humanity.  The 
psychologist  in  his  most  remote  and  technical  occupation 
with  mechanism  may  be  contributing  his  bit  to  that  ordered 
knowledge  which  alone  enables  mankind  to  secure  a  larger 
and  to  direct  a  more  equal  flow  of  the  values  of  life." 


THE  CASE  OF   SELF  AGAINST  SOUL1 

BY  MARY  WHITON  CALKINS 

Wellesley  College 

Most  contemporary  psychology  tacitly  ignores  that  con- 
cretely real  being,  the  self  or  I.  Psychologists  experiment  on 
mental  processes  of  varying  sorts,  percepts,  images,  and 
emotions;  they  dispute  about  the  attributes  of  sensation,  the 
occurrence  of  imageless  thought,  the  dimensions  of  affection. 
Rebels  from  the  orthodox  school  have  a  new  set  of  abstrac- 
tions :  psychophysical  functions  and  modes  of  behavior  which 
constitute,  in  their  view,  the  proper  object  of  psychological 
investigation.  In  the  meantime,  the  self  which  perceives  and 
feels  and  thinks,  which  functions  and  behaves,  though  so 
obviously  cast  by  nature  for  the  title  role,  plays  no  part  at 
all  on  the  stage  of  most  psychological  systems.  More  liter- 
ally stated:  instead  of  studying  concrete  wholes — namely, 
knowing,  feeling,  willing,  functioning,  and  behaving  selves, 
persons  or  /'s — the  psychologist  is  wont  to  concern  himself 
with  one  or  another  part  or  aspect  of  this  concrete  whole, 
often  with  a  schematized,  artificial  construct,  invented  for 
purposes  of  easy  description  or  in  order  to  bring  psychological 
method  into  artificial  correspondence  with  that  of  the 
physical  sciences. 

The  chief  reason  for  this  ominous  neglect  of  the  self  in 
psychology  is  unquestionably  the  fact  that  I  am  always 
conscious  of  myself  and  that  I  am  therefore  inattentive  to  this 
"ubiquitous"  self.  "Just  as,  if  I  were  asked  to  report  fully 
my  sensational  experience  at  a  given  moment,  I  might  well 
forget  to  name  the  sensations  of  pressure  from  my  clothing 
simply  because  they  are  so  constant"2  so  in  my  introspection 

1  A  paper  read  November  24,  1916,  before  the  Philosophical  Union  of  the  Uni- 
versity of  California.    Part  IV.  has  been  enlarged  and  rewritten  and  the  paper  has 
been  revised. 

2  Quoted  from  a  paper  by  the  writer,  'The  Self  in  Scientific  Psychology,'  Amer.  /. 
of  Psychol.,  1915,  26,  p.  521. 

278 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  279 

I  simply  forget  to  name  myself.  A  second  explanation  of  this 
deplorable  tendency  to  ignore  the  fundamental  fact  of 
psychology  is  found  in  the  traditional  confusion  of  'self 
with  'soul.'  The  chief  business  of  this  paper  is  to  compare 
and  to  distinguish  the  two  concepts. 

It  is  necessary  at  the  outset  to  agree,  roughly  at  least,  on 
the  meaning  of  our  terms.  By  'self  I  denote  the  object  of 
the  observation  expressed  in  the  words  'I  am  conscious  of 
myself.'  Obviously,  this  statement  is  no  definition,  and  for 
the  best  of  reasons:  the  self,  or  I,  is,  in  truth,  indefinable, 
since  it  is  sui  generis,  in  a  class  by  itself.  But  though  inde- 
finable it  is  not,  therefore,  elemental  and  indescribable.1  On 
the  contrary,  the  self  is  a  highly  complex  being  which  may  be 
described  by  an  enumeration  of  its  characters.  Among  these 
characters  of  the  self  the  following  are  surely  fundamental: 
First,  the  self  of  each  of  us  to  some  extent  persists:  I  am  in  a 
true  sense  of  the  word  the  'same'  self  who  cut  a  philosophy 
class  in  her  senior  days  at  college  in  order  to  take  a  drive 
behind  a  pair  of  Vermont  horses.  In  the  second  place, 
however,  the  self,  with  all  its  persistence,  truly  changes, 
develops:  though  an  outgrowth  from  that  frivolous  self,  and 
identical  with  her,  I  am  yet  a  changed  self.  Third,  and  very 
significantly,  I  am  a  unique  self:  there  is  only  one  of  me;  I  am 
an  individual;  no  one,  however,  closely  she  resembles  me,  is  I. 
The  possibility  of  this  enumeration  shows,  in  the  fourth  place, 
that  I  am  a  complex  self,  a  unity  of  present  with  past — yes, 
and  with  future — self  and  a  totality,  also,  of  many  differ- 
ent experiences;  I  am  a  perceiving  and  remembering  and 
thinking  and  feeling  self.  These  different  experiences  or 
aspects  of  me  do  not,  however,  exist  apart  from  me;  I  ob- 
viously am  not  what  Hume  called  me,  a  bundle  of  perceptions, 
but  each  of  the  perceptions  or  emotions  or  thoughts  is  the 
expression  of  me  who  am  inclusive  of  them.  Finally,  I  am  a 
self  related  to  the  world  in  which  I  seem  to  myself  to  be  placed; 
my  fundamental  relation  to  the  world  I  call  my  consciousness 

1  For  the  unjustified  implication  that  the  indefinable  must  therefore  be  elemental 
cf.E.B.  Holt 'The  Concept  of  Consciousness,3  pp.  73-74:  "Either  consciousness  is  a  com- 
plex entity  not  fundamental  but  definable  in  terms  of  simple  entities  that  are  not 
consciousness  ...  or  else  consciousness  is  fundamental  and  simple." 


280  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

of  it,  and  within  my  consciousness  I  distinguish  different 
forms  of  relation,  as  activity  and  passivity,  and  different 
complexes  of  relation,  as  perception,  emotion,  and  the  rest. 
All  these  characters,  it  must  be  added,  are  immediately  ex- 
perienced. The  self,  thus  described,  is  observed  and  not 
merely  inferred;  is,  therefore,  a  psychological  datum  which  is 
taken  over  into  philosophy  when  reflection  discloses  that  it  is 
the  unique  fact  which  can  neither  be  denied  nor  even  doubted 
without  being  at  the  same  time  asserted. 

We  have  next  to  distinguish  the  concept  of  'soul*  from 
that  of  the  immediately  perceived,  the  persisting,  changing, 
unique,  complex  and  related  '  self.'  And  here  we  find  ourselves 
involved  in  great  difficulties  of  interpretation.  For,  whereas 
the  relatively  late  term  'self  is  primarily  psychological,  the 
word  'soul'  is  common  to  many  philosophies  and  to  pre- 
philosophic  levels  of  civilization;  so  that  the  attempt  to  un- 
ravel its  meaning  is  fraught  with  subtlest  difficulties. 

Among  these  varying  meanings  are  three  of  commanding 
importance  which  for  convenience  we  may  designate  as  the 
biological  (or  vitalistic),  the  metaphysical  (or  immaterialistic), 
and  the  psychological  conceptions  of  the  soul.  The  first  two 
are  alike  in  that  both  define  the  soul  with  reference  to  the 
body,  but  they  conceive  the  relation  of  soul  to  body  in  sharply 
opposed  fashions,  (i)  According  to  the  earlier,  the  vitalistic, 
view  soul  is  equivalent  to  life.  Every  reader  of  early  liter- 
ature knows  that  the  soul  is  often  virtually  identified,  now 
with  the  blood,  now  with  one  or  another  of  the  vital  organs, 
and  again  with  the  breath.  This  conception  of  the  soul  as 
breath  differs,  it  must  be  noted,  from  the  identification  of 
soul  with  blood  or  heart  or  kidneys.  For  the  breath  though 
it  gives  life  to  the  body  leaves  the  body  at  death.  In  truth, 
the  doctrine  of  the  soul  as  animus  or  spiritus  forms  a  sort  of 
bridge,  or  transition,  between  the  'vitalistic'  view  and  the 
immaterialistic  conception  of  the  soul.  (2)  This  'metaphysical,' 
or  immaterialistic,  doctrine  regards  the  soul  no  longer  as  in 
positive  relation  to  the  body  but  rather  as  negatively  related 
to  it,  contrasted  v/ith  it,  opposed  to  it.  The  early  conception 
of  the  soul  as  shade,  or  ghost,  is  an  approach  to  this  meta- 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  281 

physical  doctrine,  the  Orphic,  Platonic  doctrine  which  persists 
to  our  own  day,  that  the  soul  is  an  immaterial,  simple,  un- 
changing being.  These  characters,  it  will  be  noted,  are  the 
bare  opposites  of  the  materiality,  the  compositeness  and  the 
constant  flux  of  the  body  so  that  the  soul,  thus  metaphysically 
conceived,  may  well  be  defined  as  not-body.  Along  with  this 
theoretical  distinction  of  soul  from  body  there  goes  a  change 
in  valuation.  Whereas  the  Homeric  shade  is  an  insubstantial 
and  a  pitiable  being,  the  immaterial  soul  of  the  philosopher  is 
regarded  as  immeasurably  more  worthy  than  the  body. 
(3)  The  third  conception  of  the  soul  is  as  conscious  being,  as  a 
something  which  perceives,  feels  and  thinks.  In  truth,  by 
this  psychological  conception  soul  and  self  are  virtually 
identified.  It  is  significant,  therefore,  to  find  that  frdm  ear- 
liest days  men  seem  to  have  held  this  view  of  the  soul  along 
with  one  or  both  of  the  other  conceptions.  Thus,  the  Homeric 
^uxi?,  primarily  a  vital  phenomenon,  has  sense  experiences, 
and  the  Homeric  %t6s  knows,  feels  and  wills;  [the  Platonic 
soul,  though  predominantly  immaterial,  unites  sense  experi- 
ences and  apprehends  ideas  and  loves  wisdom;  and  Descartes's 
very  *  metaphysical'  soul  has  the  principal  'attribute'  of 
thought,  that  is,  of  consciousness.  This  fusion  of  concepts 
occurs,  as  will  later  be  shown  in  detail,  even  when  the  char- 
acters of  the  soul,  for  example,  changelessness  and  simplicity, 
are  exact  contraries  of  the  observed  characters  of  the  self. 
Our  immediate  task  is  to  compare  and  to  distinguish  these 
three  conceptions  as  they  appear  and  reappear  in  the  history 
of  thought.  It  will  be  necessary  to  make  rigorous  selection 
from  a  great  mass  of  material;  and  we  shall  profitably  begin 
by  a  study  of  the  soul  of  Plato's  'Dialogues.'1 

I 

Plato's  doctrine  of  the  soul,  like  all  the  philosophical  and 
scientific  conceptions  of  the  'Dialogues,'  is  presented  to  us  not 
in  systematic  form  as  an  articulated  body  of  doctrine  but 
almost  incidentally.  One  can  hardly  re-read  the  dialogues  in 

1  This  paper,  in  its  first  form  one  of  a  series  of  lectures  on  Plato,  treats  his  doc- 
trine at  what  may  seem  disproportionate  length. 


282  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

any  unbiased  way  without  noticing  the  relative  rarity  and 
usual  fragmentariness  of  Plato's  references  to  the  soul.  We 
are  wont  to  stress  these  passages  because  later  discussions 
have  lent  them  such  transcendent  significance,  but  an  unpre- 
judiced study  of  the  dialogues  always  leads  us  to  reaffirm 
Paul  Shorey's  assertion  that  Plato  is  a  dramatic  artist  and  an 
impassioned  moral  and  religious  teacher,  not  a  scientist  or  a 
metaphysician.  Yet  in  spite  of  the  incidental  character  of 
Plato's  philosophical  and  psychological  teaching,  we  may, 
I  think,  gain  a  fairly  accurate  notion  of  his  conception  of  the 
soul;  and  we  shall  find  that  it  contains  all  three  of  the  factors, 
already  noted,  of  the  traditional  soul-doctrine.  That  is  to 
say:  Plato  somewhat  confusedly  combines  the  vitalistic,  the 
immaterialistic,  and  the  psychological  conceptions  of  the  soul. 
This  summary  account  of  his  position  has  now  to  be  justified. 

I.  The  Homeric  concept  of  soul  as  a  bodily  principle  or 
activity  was,  of  course,  familiar  to  Plato.  He  obviously  takes 
over  this  primitive  view  when  he  makes  Socrates  say,  in  the 
'Cratylus':  "I  should  imagine  that  those  who  first  used  the 
name  tyvxq  meant  to  express  that  the  soul  when  in  the  body 
is  the  source  of  life,  alnov  rov  £rjv,  and  gives  the  power  of 
breath  and  revival  (ava\l/vxov)  and  that  when  this  reviving 
power  fails  then  the  body  perishes  and  dies."1  Here  we  have 
a  conception  of  the  soul  as  specifically  the  breath-giver,  a 
notion  which  is  strongly  redolent  of  primitive  thought. 

Closely  connected  with  this  is  the  repeated  teaching  that 
the  soul  is  mover  of  the  body.  This,  again,  is  a  theory 
adopted  not  invented  by  Plato.  Thales,  as  we  learn  from 
Aristotle,  endowed  magnets  with  souls  on  the  ground  that  the 
magnets  occasion  the  movement  of  attracted  particles;  and 
doubtless  the  restless  motion  of  fire  fits  it,  in  the  view  of 
Heracleitus,  to  define  the  soul.  Thus,  Plato  is  following  an 
accepted  tradition  by  his  constant  description  of  the  soul  as 
moving  principle  and — he  adds — self-moved.  "The  soul," 
Plato  says,  in  the  'Phaedrus,'  "is  ever  in  motion.  The 
body,"  he  continues,  "which  is  moved  from  without  is  soul- 
less but  that  which  is  moved  from  within  has  a  soul."2  And 

1  'Cratylus,'  399,  D-E. 
2<Phaedrus,'  245,  E. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  283 

this,  it  may  be  noted,  is  the  teaching  of  the  'Phaedrus,'  a 
dialogue  which  can  not  well  fall  later  than  in  the  early-middle 
period  of  Plato's  thought.  But  proof  of  the  permanence 
of  the  conception  is  not  lacking.  For  it  reappears  in  Plato's 
latest  dialogue,  the  Laws,  in  which  the  Athenian  stranger 
speaks  thus  to  Cleinias: 

"Let  us  assume,"  he  says,  "that  there  is  a  motion  able  to 
move  other  things  but  not  to  move  itself — that  is  one  kind; 
and  another  kind  is  that  which  can  move  itself  as  well  as 
other  things.  .  .  .  And  which  .  .  .  ought  we  to  prefer  as  the 
mightiest?" 

"I  must  say,"  Cleinias  replies,  "the  motion  which  is  able 
to  move  itself  is  ten  thousand  times  superior  to  all  the 
others." 

"If  then,"  the  Athenian  resumes,  "as  most  of  these 
philosophers  have  the  audacity  to  affirm,  all  things  were  at 
rest,  which  of  the  .  .  .  principles  of  motion  would  first 
spring  up  among  them?" 

"Clearly  the  self-moving,"  Cleinias  says,  "for  there  could 
be  no  change  in  them  arising  out  of  any  external  cause:  the 
change  must  first  take  place  in  themselves." 

"Let  us  put  a  question,"  the  Athenian  continues,  "If  we 
were  to  see  this  power  existing  in  any  earthy,  watery  or  fiery 
substance  .  .  .  how  should  we  describe  it?" 

"You  mean  to  ask,"  Cleinias  replies,  "whether  we  should 
call  such  a  self-moving  power  life.  .  .  .  Indeed,  we  should." 

"And  when  we  see  soul  in  any  thing,"  the  Athenian  in- 
sists, "must  we  not  .  .  .  admit  that  this  is  life?  .  .  .  The 
soul,"  he  concludes,  "is  the  first  origin  and  moving  power  of 
all  that  is,  or  has  become  or  will  be."1 

These  last  words  of  the  Athenian  stranger  and  their 
omitted  context,  as  well  as  that  of  the  passage  quoted  from 
the  'Phaedrus,'  indicate  the  content  of  Plato's  cosmological 
theory  that  the  stars  and  "the  whole  heavens  and  all  creation" 
are  moved  by  soul.  But  our  discussion  is  limited  to  the  study 
of  the  human  soul  and  must  utterly  reject  the  lure  of  this 
reference  to  "all  that  is  or  has  become  or  will  be."  On  the 

1  'Laws/  X.,  894,  £-895,  C,  896,  A. 


284  MARY  W,  CALKINS 

other  hand  it  must  stress  the  emphatic  and  repeated  identi- 
fication of  'soul'  with  'life'  as  proof  that  Plato — here  as 
often  the  unacknowledged  precursor  of  Aristotle — holds  a 
genuinely  vitalistic  conception  of  the  soul. 

2.  Clearly  distinguished  from  the  vitalistic  concept  of  the 
soul  as  life,  and  often  in  the  main  inconsistent  with  it,  is  the 
doctrine  cherished  and  stressed  by  Plato,  which  I  am  des- 
ignating as  the  'metaphysical'  concept  of  the  soul.  This 
is  the  theory  that  the  soul  is  utterly  unlike  the  body,  in- 
corporeal or  immaterial.  The  soul,  Plato  always  asserts  in 
opposition  to  the  "vain  opinion"  of  the  "physical  investig- 
ators," is  not  formed  of  fire  and  water  and  earth  and  air  as 
its  first  elements;  rather  the  soul  is  the  "first,"  not  last,  "and 
before  all  bodies."1 

It  follows,  Plato  always  assumes,  that  the  inherently  in- 
corporeal soul  is,  as  it  were,  a  prisoner  in  the  body  or  entombed 
within  it.2  Evidently,  this  is  a  perpetuation  of  the  Pytha- 
gorean teaching  that  "for  a  punishment  the  soul  is  yoked 
with  the  body  and  buried  in  it  as  a  tomb."3  And  Plato's 
assertions  that  the  soul  is  separable  from  the  body  are  simi- 
larly related  to  that  Orphic  belief  which  traces  its  source  to 
the  ecstatic  Dionysiac  rites  in  which  "the  possessed  devotee 
was  set  free  for  the  moment  from  the  tangled  net  of  daily  life, 
gained  for  a  brief  time  new  and  superhuman  powers"4  so  that 
the  soul  seemed  to  be  loosed  from  the  body.  Now  the  Orphic 
and  Pythagorean  doctrine  of  the  soul's  immaterial  nature 
formed  an  inextricable  part  of  the  belief  in  the  preexistence 
of  the  soul.  Both  of  these  doctrines  are  enforced  by  Plato's 
teaching,  but  he  supplements  their  early  ethical  and  religious 
content  by  more  narrowly  metaphysical  considerations.  In 
the  Orphic  Fragments  the  doctrine  of  the  preexistence  and  the 
reincarnation  of  the  soul  enforces  ethical  exhortation  by 
promising  a  period  of  reward  or  punishment  in  which  "they 
who  are  righteous  beneath  the  rays  of  the  sun  when  they  die 

^Laws,'  891,  £-892,  A. 
2<Phaedrus,'  250. 

3  Quoted  by  Clement  of  Alexandria,  Stromata,  III.,  17.    (Diels,  '  Fragmente  der 
Vorsokratiker,'  I.,  p.  245,  Philolaos,  B,  14.) 

4  C.  H.  Moore,  'Religious  Thought  of  the  Greeks,'  p.  50. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  285 

have  a  gentler  lot  in  a  fair  meadow  by  deep-flowing  Acheron. 
.  .  .  But  they  who  have  worked  wrong  and  insolence  beneath 
the  rays  of  the  sun  are  led  down  beneath  Cocytus's  watery 
plain  into  chill  Tartarus."1  The  myths  of  Plato  perpetuate 
this  teaching  and  stress  the  individuality  of  the  soul.  Stripped 
of  the  body  which  is  "interposed  as  a  veil  before"  his  own 
soul,  the  judge  of  the  Gorgias  "with  his  naked  soul  shall 
pierce  the  other  naked  souls"  who  have  left  their  brave 
attire  strewn  upon  the  earth."2  Those  who  have  "already," 
in  the  words  of  the  '  Phsedrus,'  "  begun  the  heavenly  pilgrimage 
may  not  go  down  again  to  the  darkness."3  But  all  the  souls 
suffer  for  the  wrong  which  they  have  severally  done. 

Plato's  ethical  soul-doctrine,  it  should  be  observed, 
consists  not  merely  in  an  exhortation  to  the  soul  to  escape 
the  prison  house  of  the  body  but  in  an  emphasis  of  the  domi- 
nation of  soul  over  body.  "When  the  soul  and  body  are 
united,"  he  says,  "then  nature  orders  the  soul  to  rule  and 
govern  and  the  body  to  serve."  The  soul  is  the  pilot  of  the 
body;  is  at  variance  with  the  affections  of  the  body;  "coerces 
the  bodily  elements  ...  as  if  talking  to  a  thing  which  is  not 
herself."  But  Plato,  though  he  thus  emphasizes  the  ethical 
aspects  of  the  earlier  soul  doctrine,  strengthens  the  conviction 
of  the  soul's  freedom  from  the  body's  mortality  by  a  philo- 
sophical (in  a  way  a  psychological)  consideration.  We  are 
constantly,  he  points  out,  estimating  people  and  things  as 
good  or  beautiful  or  equal;  and  in  our  estimate  we  presuppose 
an  absolute  standard  of  goodness,  beauty,  equality  and  the 
like.  Yet  the  objects  we  meet  with  in  our  actual  human 
experience  are  never  more  than  relatively  good,  beautiful  or 
equal.  It  follows,  Plato  insists,  that  the  soul  must  have 
existed  without  the  body,4  that  "every  soul  of  man  has  in 
the  way  of  nature  beheld  true  being:  this  was  the  condition 
of  her  passing  into  the  form  of  man."5 

1  Fragment  154  A.     (Quoted  by  C.  H.  Moore,  op.  cit.,  p.  56,  from  Abel's  edition 
of  the  Orphic  fragments.) 

2  'Gorgias,'  523,  D-E. 
8  'Phsedrus,'  256,  D. 


6  'Phsedrus,'  249,  £-250,  A. 


286  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

So,  the  Platonic  teaching  about  immortality  preserves  the 
ethical  and  religious  coloring  of  the  Orphic  and  the  Pytha- 
gorean beliefs,  on  a  background  of  philosophical  conception 
and  argument.  Some  of  the  arguments  for  immortality  are, 
to  be  sure,  drawn  from  that  vitalistic  theory  of  the  soul  with 
which,  as  will  later  appear,  the  immaterialistic  concept  is  not 
actually  to  be  harmonized.  Thus,  that  latest  argument  of 
the  'Phsedo'  which  Socrates  brought  forward  like  "a  general 
rallying  his  defeated  and  broken  army"  is  based  on  the  ad- 
mitted truth  that  "whatever  the  soul  possesses,  to  that  she 
comes,  bearing  life."1  And  in  the  'Phaedrus'  immortality  is 
argued  from  the  self-motion  of  the  soul:  the  self-moving  soul, 
Socrates  asserts,  as  true  beginner  of  motion  cannot  itself  be 
begotten.2 

For  the  most  part,  however,  the  'Phsedo'  argues  immor- 
tality from  the  immateriality  of  the  soul,  its  unlikeness  to  the 
body.  Thus,  when  Cebes  begs  Socrates  to  argue  them  out 
of  their  fears,  to  persuade  the  "child  within"  them  "not  to 
t>e  afraid  when  he  is  alone  in  the  dark,"  Socrates  answers  thus  :3 

"The  composite  may  be  supposed  to  be  naturally  capable 
of  being  dissolved;  but  that  which  is  uncompounded  and  that 
•only  must  be  ...  indissoluble.  And  the  uncompounded 
may  be  assumed  to  be  ...  unchanging,  whereas  the  com- 
pounded is  always  changing.  Now  .  .  .  equality,  beauty- 
are  these  essences  always  what  they  are  ...  not  admitting 
of  variation  at  all?" 

"They  must  be  always  the  same,"  Cebes  answers.  And 
Socrates  continues: 

"Let  us  suppose  that  there  are  two  sorts  of  existences — one 
seen,  the  other  unseen.  The  seen  is  the  changing  and  the 
unseen  is  the  unchanging.  Further,  one  part  of  us  [is]  body 
and  the  other  soul.  And  to  which  class  may  we  say  that  the 
body  is  more  alike  and  akin?" 

"Clearly  to  the  seen — no  one  can  doubt  that,"  Cebes 
replies;  and  Socrates  asks: 

14Phsedo,'  105. 

2  'Phsedrus,'  245. 

3  Condensed  from  the  'Phaedo,'  78-80,  with  the  omission  of  most  of  the  brief 
replies  of  Cebes. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  287 

"Is  the  soul  seen  or  not  seen?" 

"Not  by  man,  Socrates,"  Cebes  answers. 

"Then,"  Socrates  says,  "the  soul  when  using  the  body  as 
an  instrument  of  perception  is  dragged  by  the  body  into  the 
region  of  the  changeable.  .  .  .  But  when  returning  into  her- 
self she  reflects,  then  she  passes  into  the  other  world,  the 
abode  of  purity,  and  eternity,  and  immortality,  and  unchange- 
ableness.  .  .  .  And  consider  the  matter  in  another  light. 
When  the  soul  and  the  body  are  united,  then  nature  orders 
the  soul  to  rule  and  govern  and  the  body  to  obey  and  serve. 
Which  of  these  two  functions  is  akin  to  the  divine?  and  which 
to  the  mortal?" 

"The  soul,'  Cebes  agrees,  "resembles  the  divine  and  the 
body  the  mortal."  And  Socrates  concludes: 

"Then  .  .  .  the  soul  is  in  the  very  likeness  of  the  divine, 
and  immortal,  and  intellectual,  and  uniform,  and  indissolu- 
able,  and  unchangeable;  and  the  body  is  in  the  very  likeness 
of  the  human,  and  mortal,  and  .  .  .  multiform,  and  dis- 
soluble, and  changeable." 

We  are  not  at  all  concerned  with  the  force  of  the  argument 
nor  with  the  difficult  problem  of  the  relation  of  soul  to  the 
essences  or  ideas.  What  we  have  to  note  are  the  characters 
of  uncompoundedness  and  unchangingness  here  attributed 
by  Plato  to  the  soul — regarded,  in  metaphysical  fashion,  as 
immaterial  being — predicates  which  are  sharply  opposed,  or  at 
least  unrelated,  to  the  characters  of  life  and  self-motion  which 
are  basal  to  Plato's  vitalistic  concept  of  the  soul. 

3.  We  have  thus  summarily  outlined  two  Platonic  con- 
ceptions of  the  soul,  distinguishable  if  often  uncontrasted : 
first,  his  conception  of  the  soul  as  vital  principle  of  the  body, 
its  breath,  inciter  to  its  movements,  and  second,  what  we 
have  named  his  metaphysical  conception  of  the  soul  as  a 
changeless  uncompounded  individual  being,  radically  dif- 
ferent from  body  and  variously  thought  of  as  dominating  the 
body  or  as  marred  and  hampered  by  communion  with  it. 
But  Plato  conceives,  or  at  any  rate  treats,  the  soul  in  still  a 
third  fashion  as  a  conscious  being,  as  subject  of  experience. 
To  begin  with,  the  soul  recollects.  For  Plato's  well-known 


288  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

doctrine  of  reminiscence  is  not  merely  a  metaphysical  specu- 
lation about  reincarnation  and  an  epistemological  doctrine 
about  absolute  knowledge,  but  a  psychological  study  of  rec- 
ognition and  memory.  In  other  words,  the  soul  not  only 
"calls  to  mind  all  she  ever  knew"1  as  the  'Meno'  has  it,  but, 
in  the  words  of  the  'Philebus,'  she  has  "the  power  ...  of 
recovering  when  by  herself  some  feeling  which  she  experienced 
when  in  company  with  the  body"2 — that  is  to  say,  the  soul 
remembers  sense-experiences.  The  soul  also  conceives  and 
compares  and  reflects.  "  By  a  power  of  her  own,"  Socrates  is 
made  to  say,  in  the  These tetus,3  "the  soul  contemplates  the 
universals  .  .  .  comparing  in  herself  things  past  and  present 
with  the  future."4  And  Plato's  conception  of  the  conscious 
soul  is  not  purely  intellectualistic.  The  soul,  he  teaches, 
feels  pleasure  and  pain,  and  " pleasure  and  desire"  may 
"exist  in  the  mind  only  apart  from  the  body."5  The  soul 
finally  aspires*  and — as  figured  in  all  the  myths  of  judgment 
— makes  genuine  choice.  Moreover,  the  soul  which  perceives 
the  physical  and  understands  universals  has  also,  Plato  im- 
plies, a  knowledge  of  itself.  Thought  is  the  conversation  of 
the  soul  with  herself;  the  knowledge  of  universals  is  a  recol- 
lection of  her  former  experience;  her  character  is,  as  we  have 
seen,  the  outcome  of  her  own  choice.  The  soul,  finally, 
through  her  '  instruments/  the  senses,  perceives.  In  the  words 
of  the  'Philebus'  there  is  in  perception  "union  of  soul  and 
body  in  one  feeling  or  motion";7  and  there  are  affections 
(irad-findTa)  which  vibrate  through  both  soul  and  body  and 
impart  a  shock  to  both  and  each  of  them.8  It  is  significant 
to  find  in  this  account  of  the  perceiving  soul  a  denial  of  the 
sharp  opposition  of  soul  to  body. 

The  fundamental  protest  of  this  paper,  it  will  be  remem- 
bered, is  against  the  confusion  of  the  concepts  of  soul  and 

l'Meno,'8i,  C. 
2'Philebus,'34,  B. 
''Theaetetus,'  185,  E. 
4  Ibid.,  1 86,  B. 
« 'Philebus,'  34,  C. 
e  'The<etetus,'  186,  A. 
7 'Philebus,'  34,  A. 
'Ibid.,  33,  D. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  289 

self.  If,  however,  philosophical  convention  is  to  be  trusted, 
there  is  no  room  for  the  confusion  in  Plato's  teaching  since — 
so  we  are  told — the  concept  of  the  self  dawns  late  on  the 
metaphysical  horizon,  and  is  descried  at  the  earliest  in  the 
speculations  of  Plotinus.  But  whatever  may  be  true  of  the 
term  '  self/  however  long  the  period  before  the  self  was  formally 
introduced  in  metaphysical  circles,  philosophers,  as  well  as 
other  men,  were  conscious  of  themselves  though — also  like 
other  men — they  often  forgot  to  mention  the  fact  precisely 
because  they  were  so  accustomed  to  it.  To  return  to  Plato. 
Unquestionably,  he  uses  the  reflexive  pronoun  eavros-eavrd 
to  refer  to  impersonal  as  well  as  to  personal  realities;  and 
certainly  he  does  not  explicitly  refer  to  ego  or  self;  but  on  the 
other  hand  he  over  and  over  again  refers  to  the  man  (avQpuiros) 
or  to  ourselves  (i7/zeTs)  as  being  conscious.  Thus,  in  'Phi- 
lebus,'  36,  A,  Socrates  inquires  whether  one  of  us  (TLS  I?/KOJ>) 
who  is  hungry  may  not  at  one  time  have  a  sure  hope  of  being 
fed  and  at  another  time  feel  in  despair.  "Each  of  us,"  he 
says  in  'Republic,'  III.,  "has  many  wants."  Indeed, 
throughout  the  discussion  of  the  virtues  in  the  'Republic,' 
the  state  is  contrasted  not  with  the  soul  but  with  the  man 
(avrjp)  or  with  the  individual  (ftccurros);  whereas  the  soul  is 
referred  to  only  incidentally  and  conventionally.1  In  these 
allusions  to  'a  man'  and  to  'us'  it  is  at  least  possible  to  descry 
the  germ  of  a  psychological  concept  of  the  experienced  self, 
no  longer  wholly  overlaid  by  the  conventional  soul-concept. 
And  if  we  are  right  in  this  interpretation  we  have  here  an 
early  illustration  of  the  greater  empirical  accuracy  of  state- 
ments about  the  self.  Influenced  by  his  dualistic  prepos- 
session to  stress  the  contrast  between  soul  and  body,  Plato, 
as  we  have  already  noted,  scruples  to  say  that  'the  soul' 
perceives,  whereas  he  clearly  realizes — as  everyone  who, 
simply  and  without  metaphysical  bias,  observes  himself 
must  realize — that  'we'  perceive  as  surely  as  we  think. 

The  estimate  of  self  and  soul  doctrines  is,  however,  best 
postponed  to  a  point  further  on  in  our  discussion. 

1  Cf.  'Republic,'  435,  C.  r6v  tva  .  .  .  TO.  avra  fldij  tv  T%  avr 


290  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

II 

1.  The  conception  of  the  soul  most  emphasized  by  Aris- 
totle is,  as  everybody  knows,  the  biological  or  vitalistic.     The 
soul  he  says  is  the  first  entelechy,  or  realization,  of  an  organic 
body — in  a  word  it  is  the  body's  capacity  for  life.     It  follows, 
Aristotle  teaches,  that  there  are  animal  souls  as  well  as  human 
souls.     And  by  this  he  does  not  mean  to  attribute  conscious- 
ness to  plants  and  animals  but  rather  to  attribute  to  them 
life.     Like  Plato  and  the  earlier  Greek  thinkers,  Aristotle  also 
makes  of  soul  "the  source  of  local  movement."1 

2.  Of  the  traditional  immaterialistic  conception  of  the 
soul  Aristotle,  on  the  other  hand,  shows  hardly  a  trace.     "We 
should  no  more  ask,"  he  observes,2  "whether  soul  and  body 
are  one  than  ask  whether  the  wax  and  the  figure  on  it  are 
one."     Yet  the  conception  of  soul  as  life  is  an  integral  part 
of  Aristotle's  metaphysical  system — the  theory  of  the  universe 
as  ascending  from  primitive,  unformed  matter  (pure  poten- 
tiality) through  successive  stages  (of  which  each  is,  viewed 
from  below,  realization,  or  form,   and  viewed  from  above 
itself  potentiality)  until  at  the  end  pure  activity  is  attained: 
completely  realized  being,  mind  in  contemplation  of  itself, 
mind  which  is  principle  of  all  motion  in  that  it  is  goal  of  all 
desire  and  ultimate  object  of  all  yearning.  The  discussion  of  the 
Aristotelian   philosophy,   thus    baldly   suggested,   would,   of 
course,  lead  us  far  afield.     What  is  important  to  our  purpose 
is  to  notice  that  there  is  here  no  hint  of  the  specifically  im- 
materialistic conception  of  soul — no  description  of  it  as  simple 
and  uncompounded.     And,  so  far  from  conceiving  the  soul 
as  unchanging,  Aristotle  explicitly  defines  it  as  the  progressive 
realization  of  growing  capacities,  or  possibilities. 

3.  That  Aristotle,  beside  conceiving  the  soul  in  the  manner 
of  the  vitalists,  certainly  regards  it  after  the  psychologist's 
fashion,  is  shown  by  the  slightest  examination  of  the  contents 
of   *De  Anima.'     In   Book   II.,   he   distinguishes   from   the 
vegetable   soul   (ri  6ptimK.ii)   the    animal   soul  which  he  here 
forthwith  describes  as  perceptive  (mo-flrjriKi?).     The  remainder 

1  'De  Anima,'  II.,  Chap.  4,  20,  415  b. 

2  Ibid.,  Chap.  I,  7,  412  b. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  291 

of  the  treatise  is  given  over  to  the  discussion  of  the  senses, 
sight,  hearing,  touch,  and  the  others ;  of  imagination  (<pavTaala)  j1 
of  conception  (uTroXry^ts) ;  thought  (vo£v)-,  desire  (TO  bp^rinbv)  .2 
All  these  are  over  and  over  again  referred  to  in  terms  common 
to  Aristotle's  zoological  and  ethical  as  well  as  to  his  psycholog- 
ical writings  as  either  parts  (ju6pux)  or  capacities  (dwd/zeis)  of  the 
soul.  Thus,  the  discussion  of  reason  (TO  voelv)  in  Book  III., 
Chapter  IV.,  of  the  'Psychology'  is  introduced  by  the  words: 
"We  must  next  investigate  that  part  (popiov)  of  the  soul  by 
which  it  knows  and  reflects  (vpoveiv) ."  These  capacities  or  parts 
are  differently  enumerated  in  different  passages;  those  most 
often  named  are  the  perceptive,  the  thinking  (Xoyio-ruoj'  or 
KOV  or  diavoriTLKov)  and  the  impulsive  or  voluntary  (TO 
or  povXtvTiKov  or  tiridvMTiKov).  More  than  once,  indeed, 
Aristotle  says  that  the  soul  is  defined  by  thinking,  judging, 
and  perceiving,  and  that  both  by  thought  and  by  sense  "  the 
soul  distinguishes  and  knows  real  things."  3  The  simplicity 
and  precision  of  the  words  just  quoted  ("the  soul  distin- 
guishes," "the  soul  knows")  bring  into  clear  relief  the  arti- 
ficiality of  Aristotle's  more  frequent  descriptions  of  conscious 
experience  in  terms,  very  often  reproduced,  of  personified  (yet 
to  the  end  more  or  less  fictitious)  'faculties' — imagination, 
reason,  and  the  rest.  More  frequent  than  Aristotle's  simple 
statements  that  the  soul  knows  or  thinks  are  his  references 
to  the  man  (avdpuiroi)  who  hears,  smells  or  thinks;  and  still 
more  frequent  are  his  assertions  that  'we'  see  and  touch 
and  perceive;4  that  images  present  themselves  to  'us,'  that 
'we'  judge  (KpLvonev) ,  affirm  or  deny  (aKydevofjiev  ij  ^evdofieda) , 
feel  fear.5  Here,  as  in  Plato's  parallel  expressions,  we  may 
perhaps  fairly  conclude  that  Aristotle  is  forgetting  the  sup- 
posed necessity  to  record  his  experience  in  terms  of  his  phi- 
losophical doctrine  and  is  conceiving  a  self,  rather  than  a 
soul,  which  is  conscious. 

It  should  be  noted  that  Aristotle's  profound  doctrine  of 

1  'De  Anima,'  III.,  Chap.  3,  7,  428*. 

2  Ibid.,  III.,  Chap.  9,  3,  4326. 
•Ibid.,  III.,  Chap.  3,  i. 

4  Ibid.,  III.,  Chap.  3,  6,  4280. 
6  Ibid.,  5,  427^. 


292  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

substance,  as  elaborated  in  the  *  Metaphysics/  plainly  con- 
nects itself  with  the  conception  of  the  soul.  To  trace  the 
connection  would  be  to  involve  ourselves  in  a  long  dis- 
cussion, but  we  can  not  avoid  the  conclusion  that  Aristotle, 
for  whom  the  ultimately  real  was  always  neither  matter  nor 
form  but  the  individual,  meant  to  endow  the  soul  with  this 
character:  uniqueness  or  individuality. 

Ill 

By  Stoic,  Judeo-Alexandrian,  Neo-Platonic,  Patristic,  and 
Scholastic  thinkers  the  triple  conception  of  the  soul  has  been 
handed  down  to  modern  psychologists  and  metaphysicians. 
The  soul-doctrine  of  the  pre-Christian  schools  belonged,  as 
is  well  known,  to  a  pantheistic  philosophy.  The  soul  was 
regarded  by  the  Stoics  as  part  of  the  Universal  Reason,  by 
the  Neo-Platonists  as  emanation  through  the  world-soul  from 
the  One.  But  all — Hellenic,  Jewish,  Alexandrian  and  Christian 
thinkers — united  to  emphasize  the  worthlessness  of  the  body 
and  the  supremacy  of  the  'soul  burdened  with  a  corpse.'1 

It  is  not  necessary  to  consider  in  detail  most  of  these 
theories  but  it  would  be  impossible  to  pass  over  Augustine's 
teaching.  The  conception  of  soul  and  self  are,  as  everyone 
knows,  central  in  his  philosophy;  and  he  conceives  the  soul 
in  each  one  of  the  three  traditional  ways,  (i)  Although  he 
repudiates  the  essential  materialism  of  the  primitive  vitalistic 
conception  which  identifies  the  soul  with  the  blood  he  yet 
everywhere  insists  that  the  conscious  soul  is  a  living  being. 
And  from  the  attribute  of  life  he  argues,  in  Plato's  fashion, 
the  immortality  of  the  soul.  "Those,"  he  says,  "who  have 
held  [the  soul's]  substance  to  be  some  kind  of  life  .  .  .  have 
striven  also  to  prove  it  immortal,  since  life  can  not  be  without 
life."2 

(2)  More  often,  however,  Augustine  sets  forth  the  im- 
materialistic  theory  of  the  soul.  His  teaching  is  very  close 
to  that  of  Plato.  The  soul,  he  asserts,  in  words  perpetuated 
for  centuries,  is  a  spiritual  substance:3  it  is  incorporeal — and 

1  Attributed  to  Marcus  Aurelius  (quoting  Epictetus). 

2'DeTrinitate,'  X.,  7. 

3  'De  Trinitate,'  XL,  i;  'De  Quantitate  Animse,'  Chaps.  II.,  III. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  293 

he  argues  this,  as  Plato  has  argued  it,  on  the  ground  that  the 
soul  discerns  incorporeal  things  (cernit  incorporea),1  such,  for 
example,  as  mathematical  quantities.  The  incorporeal  nature 
of  the  soul,  Augustine  also  teaches,  implies  its'unextendedness — 
a  negative  character  which  he  stresses  very  likely  in  opposition 
to  Tertullian's  materialistic  view.  Over  and  over  again,  in 
1  De  Quantitate  Animae  '2  and  in  '  De  Immortalitate,'  Augustine 
repeats  the  statement  that  the  soul  feels  throughout  the  body 
(per  totum  corpus)  but  not  with  the  body  (cum  cor  pore).  The 
reiterated  statement  that  the  soul  is  simple  has  the  same 
meaning,  that  the  soul  acts  as  a  whole  (tota  operatur).  And 
from  its  unextendedness  and  its  simplicity  he  deduces,  after 
the  traditional  fashion,  its  unchangingness,  imperishability 
and  immortality.  He  argues  in  detail  that  though  the  soul 
seems  to  grow,  to  develop  with  the  body,  it  is  none  the  less 
unchanging.  Non  mutatur,  he  reiterates  in  passage  after 
passage.3  Finally,  in  his  account  of  the  relation  between 
soul  and  body  Augustine  follows  Plato  with  especial  fidelity. 
The  soul,  he  everywhere  asserts  and  implies,  is  the  ruler  of  the 
body  (rationis  particeps  regendo  corpori). 

(3)  Up  to  this  point  we  have  nothing  radically  new.  The 
vitalistic  doctrine  of  the  soul  is  set  forth  less  convincingly  by 
Augustine  than  by  Aristotle;  the  immaterialistic  doctrine  in 
no  wise  advances  upon  Plato's.  But  Augustine's  treatment  of 
the  soul  as  subject  of  consciousness  or  knowledge  is  like  new 
wine  in  new  bottles — an  outpouring  of  first-hand  observations, 
a  formulation  of  acute  and  independent  reasonings.  The 
pages  in  which  he  discusses  loving  and  knowing,  remembering 
and  attending,  thinking  and  willing,  seem  to  me,  though 
written  so  long  before  the  rise  of  scientific  psychology,  com- 
parable only  with  the  introspective  passages  of  William 
James  for  their  luminousness,  their  revealing  quality,  their 
ability  to  cleave  asunder  the  most  tortuously  intertwined 
human  experiences. 

The  most  emphasized  and  most  truly  novel  contribution 

1  'De  Trinitate,'  X.,  7;  'De  Quantitate  Animae,'  Chaps.  XIII.,  XV. 

2  Cf.  Chaps.  XXIIL,  XXX. 

3<De  Immortalitate,'  Chap.  I.  Cf.  'De  Quantitate  Animae,'  Chaps.  II.,  XV., 
XVI. 


294  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

of  Augustine  to  this  psychological  conception  of  the  soul  is  his 
insistence  on  the  fact  that  the  soul  knows  itself.  We  are  not 
here  concerned  with  the  implications  of  this  fact  for  philosophy 
— the  significance  of  the  discovery  of  this  one  reality,  myself, 
which  is  self-evident  because  in  doubting  or  denying  it  I 
assert  it.  What  we  are  here  remarking  is  the  enlargement  of 
the  concept  of  knowing  soul  by  the  explicit  recognition  of  its 
self-knowing  character.  " '  Know  thyself,' "  Augustine  asserts, 
"is  not  said  to  the  mind  as  is  'Know  the  cherubim  and  the 
seraphim';  for  they  are  absent,  and  we  believe  concerning 
them.  .  .  .  Nor  yet  as  it  is  said 'Know  the  will  of  that  man'; 
for  this  it  is  not  within  our  reach  to  perceive  at  all,  either  by 
sense  or  understanding,  unless  by  corporeal  signs  actually  set 
forth;  and  this  in  such  a  way  that  we  rather  believe  than 
understand.  Nor  again  as  it  is  said  to  a  man,  'Behold  thy 
own  face';  which  he  can  only  do  in  a  looking-glass.  For  even 
our  own  face  itself  is  out  of  the  reach  of  our  own  seeing  it. 
.  .  .  But  when  it  is  said  to  the  mind,  Know  thyself:  then  it 
knows  itself  by  that  very  stroke  by  which  it  understands  the 
word  'thyself;  and  this  for  no  other  reason  than  that  it  is 
present  to  itself."1 

With  equal  subtlety  Augustine  discusses  all  forms  of 
knowledge.  At  times,  but  only  apparently  by  accident,  or 
in  theological  exigency,  he  follows  Aristotle  in  apotheosizing 
the  abstractions  'memory,'  'thought'  and  'will.'  Usually, 
however,  he  says  concretely  that  the  mind  remembers,  thinks, 
judges,  wills;  or  else  he  says  even  more  concretely,  I  remember, 
/  will.  For  the  truth  is  that  Augustine  uses  the  self-words, 
'I,'  'he,'  'self,'  'man,'  nearly  if  not  quite  as  often  as  he  uses 
the  terms  'soul'  or  'mind,'  and  seemingly  he  employs  the  two 
sets  of  terms  interchangeably.  An  example  of  this  inter- 
change is  selected  at  random  from  Chapter  XI.  of  Book  X. 
of  '  De  Trinitate.'  Augustine  is  arguing  that  though  memory, 
understanding  and  will  are  three  yet  each  is  contained  by 
each.  He  begins  with  the  statement  that  "The  mind  is 
certain  of  these  three  things  concerning  itself  .  .  .  memory, 
understanding  and  will,"  but  ends  with  the  assertion:  "  What- 

i 'De  Trinitate,' X.,  9. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  295 

ever  I  understand  I  know  that  I  understand  and  I  know  that 
I  will  whatever  I  will  and  whatever  I  know  I  remember." 
Here  the  term  'I'  replaces  the  term  'mind*  within  one  and 
the  same  closely  argued  proof. 

But  though  Augustine  thus  identifies  soul  with  self  he  does 
not  criticize  the  one  conception  by  the  other.  He  never 
turns  upon  the  obscure  conventional  attributes  of  the  soul 
the  searchlight  of  introspective  observation;  he  never  recon- 
ciles the  divergence  between  the  teaching  of  Augustine,  the 
observer,  "When  the  human  mind  knows  and  loves  itself  it 
does  not  know  and  love  anything  unchangeable"1 — and  the 
dogma  which  Augustine,  the  theologian,  uncritically  takes 
over  from  Plato  and  the  Fathers,  "The  soul  is  unchanging  and 
simple." 

Mediaeval  philosophers,  so  far  as  I  know  them,  neither 
make  important  contributions  to  the  conception  of  soul  nor 
markedly  diverge  from  it.  Two  instances  will  suffice  for  our 
purposes.  Alcuin,  as  quoted,  compresses  an  assertion  of  all 
three  of  the  soul's  traditional  attributes  into  a  brief  sentence: 
"The  soul  is  a  rational  spirit  ever  in  motion,  ever  living, 
capable  of  good  and  evil."  St.  Thomas  also  expressly  rec- 
ognizes all  three  characters  of  the  soul.  He  describes  it  as 
principle  of  life  and  of  bodily  movement — a  clearly  vitalistic 
description.  He  also  asserts,  in  accord  with  Plato's  doctrine, 
that  the  soul  is  simple  substance;  and  he  argues  elaborately2 
(here,  as  in  his  doctrine  of  the  individuality  of  souls,  following 
Aristotle)  that  in  spite  of  being  the  mover  of  the  body,  the 
soul  is  itself  unmoved.  Finally,  St.  Thomas  teaches,  in  the 
second  Article  of  this  same  Question  75, that  "the  soul  knows" 
or  rather  (he  corrects  himself)  "man  knows  through  the  soul." 
Questions  77  through  80  develop  this  doctrine  of  the  knowing 
soul  by  enumerating  and  analyzing,  somewhat  in  Aristotelian 
fashion,  the  *  powers  of  the  soul,'  that  is  to  say,  the  five  senses, 
the  intellect,  memory,  appetite  and  will.  Like  his  predeces- 
sors, Thomas  obviously  uses  the  three  time-honored  concepts 
of  the  soul  in  unharmonized  juxtaposition. 

KDeTrinitate/IX.,  6. 

2  'Summa  Theologise,'  Pars  Prima,  Question  75,  first  Article. 


296  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

IV 

The  soul  makes  its  way  into  modern  thought  encumbered 
with  its  three  more  or  less  conflicting  duties :  to  be  life-giving, 
to  be  immaterial,  and  to  be  conscious.  It  is  not,  however, 
left  undisturbed  in  the  quiet  possession  of  these  traditional 
characters.  At  the  very  outset  Descartes  threatens  to  deprive 
it  of  one  of  them  by  destroying  its  pretension  to  be  the  life 
and  mover  of  the  body.  For  Descartes  formulates  the  me- 
chanistic conception  of  life  and  effectively  marshals  the 
evidence,  from  physiological  observation  and  experiment,  for 
this  mechanistic  theory.  Thus,  he  says  that  the  circulation 
"follows  as  necessarily  from  the  very  arrangement  of  the 
parts  of  the  body  and  from  the  heat  which  may  be  felt  with 
the  fingers  and  from  the  nature  of  the  blood  ...  as  does  the 
motion  of  a  clock  from  the  power,  the  situation,  and  shape  of 
its  counterweights  and  wheels."  "The  body,"  he  repeats  in 
every  possible  connection,  "is  nothing  more  than  a  machine."1 
Descartes,  to  be  sure,  is  not  daring  enough  to  treat  the  human 
body  as  a  perfect  mechanism  He  (i)  still  conceives  the 
human  soul  as  vitally  related  to  the  body  though  he  allows  it 
but  a  precarious  seat  in  the  pineal  gland  and  tries  to  hold  it 
down  to  the  function  of  mere  direction,  not  initiation,  of  the 
body's  motions.  In  entirely  uncritical  fashion,  (2)  in  the 
second  place,  Descartes  adopts  the  immaterialistic  doctrine, 
asserting  after  the  manner  of  Plato,  Antoninus,  Philo,  Augus- 
tine, and  Thomas  the  simplicity  of  the  immortal  soul  and  its 
utter  unlikeness  to  the  body.  But  he  (3)  also  stresses  the 
psychological  conception  of  the  soul  as  conscious  being;  and 
here,  once  more  in  agreement  with  his  predecessors  and  in 
particular  with  Augustine,  he  uses  the  term  'soul'  as  virtual 
synonym  for  'self  or  'I.'2  Even  more  often,  however,  he 
describes  the  self,  or  I,  purely  as  a  conscious  being,  without 
reference  to  the  traditional  characters  of  the  soul.  Thus  he 
says,  in  reply  to  the  question:  "What  then  am  I?"  "I  am  a 
thinking  thing  .  .  .  that  doubts,  understands,  affirms,  denies, 

1  'Discourse  on  Method,'  V. 

2 'Meditation,'  II.,  paragraphs  4,  7;  et  al.  For  Descartes's  narrower  use  of  the 
term  'think'  cf.  paragraph  5  of  'Meditation?  II;  et  al. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  297 

wills,  refuses,  that  imagines  also  and  perceives."1  There  is 
here  no  mention  of  'motive  power'  or  simplicity  or  imma- 
teriality: I  am  conscious  self. 

This  divorce  of  self  from  soul,  as  will  presently  appear, 
becomes  explicit  in  the  teaching  of  Locke,  (i)  Locke  follows 
Henry  More2  in  stressing  the  conception  of  the  soul  as 
"capable  of  motion,"  as  "changing  distance"  and  as  "moving 
or  quieting  corporeal  motion."3  He  argues  simply  that 
"every  day's  experience  clearly  furnishes  us  with"  instances 
of  "will  or  a  power  of  putting  body  into  motion  by  thought."4 
This  is,  of  course,  a  mere  reassertion  of  the  classic  vitalistic 
doctrine  of  soul.  (2)  The  immaterialistic  soul  of  the  meta- 
physicians is  subjected  by  Locke  to  more  radical  treatment. 
He  resolutely  strips  it  of  all  the  characters  of  consciousness 
and  then  he  rightly  insists  that  the  "substance  of  spirits," 
thus  abstractly  conceived,  "is  unknown  to  us."  "If  any 
one,"  he  repeatedly  asserts,  "will  examine  himself  concerning 
his  idea  of  *  substance'  he  will  find  he  has  no  other  idea  of  it  at 
all  but  only  a  supposition  of  he  knows  not  what  support  of 
qualities."5  "Our  idea  of  substance,"  he  says  in  another 
passage,  referring  definitely  to  spiritual  substance,  or  soul, 
"is  but  a  supposed  I-know-not-what  to  support  ideas."6 
(3)  To  the  self,  or  I,  Locke  now  gives  over  explicitly  most  or 
all  the  concrete  characters  which  soul  and  self  (before  his  time 
uncritically  identified)  once  shared  between  them:  conscious- 
ness, moral  responsibility,  and  even  identity.  "The  Self," 

1  Descartes,  '  Meditations,'  II.,  paragraph  7. 

2  More  breaks  sharply  with  tradition  by  insisting  that  the  soul,  though  immaterial, 
is  not  therefore  unextended.     There  are  two  kinds  of  extension,  More  teaches :  the  first* 
material  and  impenetrable,  the  second  a  penetrable,  "subtle  and  immaterial  extension 
.  .  .  whereof  we  have  an  innate  ingrafted  idea."    The  soul  is,  therefore,  a  thinking, 
extended  substance  ('Enchiridion  Metaphysicum,  Chap.  XXVIIL,  3  et  al.)  and  is 
"intrinsically  endowed  with  Life  and  the  Faculty  of  Motion." 

8 'Essay  Concerning  Human  Understanding,'  Book  II.,  Chapter  XXIII.,  para- 
graphs 20,  19,  15  et  al. 

4  More,  on  the  contrary,  with  his  conception  of  spirit  as  extended  and  penetrable, 
finds  nothing  impossible  in  the  view  that  a  spirit  may  literally  and  "easily  pass  through" 
and  influence  "anybody." 

»  'Essay,'  Book  II.,  Chapter  XXIII.,  2. 

*Ibid.,  Chapter  XXIII.,  15.  Locke  accords  with  More  in  this  doctrine.  Cf. 
More's  'The  Immortality  of  the  Soul,'  Lib.  I.,  Axiom  8:  "The  subject  or  naked  essence 
or  substance  of  a  thing  is  utterly  inconceivable  to  any  of  our  faculties." 


298  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

he  declares,  is  "that  conscious,  thinking  thing  (whatever 
substance  made  up  of,  whether  spiritual  or  material  it  matters 
not)  which  is  sensible,  conscious,  capable  of  happiness  or 
misery,  concerned  for  itself."1  And  by  'person' — a  term 
which  he  uses  as  synonym  for 'self ' — Locke  means  f  a  think- 
ing, intelligent  being  that  .  .  .  can  consider  itself  as  the 
same  thinking  being  in  different  times  and  places.' 

To  speculate  on  the  curious  tenacity  with  which  Locke 
clings  to  his  empty  shell  of  a  soul  (expressly  reduced  to  an 
'I-know-not-what'  and  replaced  by  a  self  to  which  he  attri- 
butes persistence,  individuality,  and  consciousness)  is  irrel- 
evant to  our  main  purpose.  Evidently,  even  Locke's  inde- 
pendent spirit  could  not  withstand  the  force  of  the  traditional 
doctrine  which  received  from  Plato  its  classic  form — the 
conception  of  a  being  endowed  with  chiefly  negative  char- 
acters, a  not-body,  uncompounded,  unchanging,  immortal; 
and  he  seems  also  to  have  clung  to  the  soul  as  a  resource  in  the 
self's  frequent  lapses  of  forgetfulness;2  but  modern  students, 
unhampered  by  the  classic  convention,  have  not  scrupled  to 
take  the  step  from  which  Locke  instinctively  recoiled:  they 
have  rejected  altogether  the  merely  inferred,  'immaterial,' 
'life-giving'  soul — but  unhappily  most  of  them  have  failed 
to  take  the  preliminary  precaution  of  transferring  from  the 
soul  to  the  self  the  actually  experienced  characters  of  per- 
sistence, individuality,  and  consciousness. 

It  is  thus  evident  that  our  study  of  the  concept  of  soul  has 
provided  us  with  an  answer  to  the  question  from  which  we  set 
out:  why  do  not  all  psychologists  (and  philosophers)  ac- 
knowledge the  existence  of  the  self?  One  answer  to  this 
question  was  suggested  in  the  beginning:  psychologists,  like 
other  men,  are  naturally  inattentive  to  the  permanent 
background  of  all  experience;  but  a  second,  a  historical,  ex- 
planation of  this  pertinacious  prejudice  emerges  from  our 
study.  From  the  very  start  the  self  has  been  confused  with 
the  soul;  that  is  to  say,  the  soul  has  been  conceived  not  only  as 
life  and  as  immaterial  substance  but  also  as  conscious  being. 
Now  when  modern  biologists,  following  Descartes's  lead,  hold 

1 '  Essay,'  Chapter  XXVIL,  17. 
2  Ibid.,  Chapter  XXVIL,  10. 


THE  CASE  OF  SELF  AGAINST  SOUL  299 

that  organic  processes  can  be  mechanically  explained — these 
mechanists  in  rejecting  the  concept  of  soul  as  life,  reject  with 
it  the  wholly  different  conception  of  the  conscious  being.  And 
when  psychologists  and  philosophers  alike  discard  the  partly 
mythical,  partly  empty  conception  of  the  soul  as  simple,  im- 
material substance  they  too  reject  also  the  conscious  being. 
In  their  justified  but  undiscriminating  attack  on  vitalism  and 
immaterialism  many  scientists  have  thus  unwisely  rejected 
the  basic  fact  of  psychology:  the  directly  experienced,  changing 
yet  persistent,  individual,  and  complex  conscious  self.  And, 
in  similar  fashion,  the  philosophic  critics,  from  Hume  down,1 
have  been  wont  to  attack  not  the  experienced  self  but  the  soul. 
The  remedy  is  obvious  and  has  already  been  suggested.  The 
reinstatement,  imperatively  needed,  of  the  self  in  psychology 
requires,  first,  that  the  self  take  over  from  the  soul  the  ex- 
perienced characters  which  comport  so  oddly  with  the  in- 
ferred attributes  of  soul;  and  second,  that  the  soul  thus 
despoiled  of  consciousness,  be  dismissed  from  psychology — 
unless,  indeed,  the  term  be  retained  as  mere  synonym  of 
conscious  self  or  I.2  The  reasons  for  this  expulsion  of  the 
soul  from  psychology — and  indeed  from  philosophy — need 
hardly  be  re-stated.  The  metaphysical  soul  or  incorporeal, 
simple,  unchanging  being  is  clearly  unjustified  by  experience, 
an  empty  abstraction  except  for  the  characters — persistence 
and  individuality — which  as  truly  belong  to  the  self.  With 
equal  vigor,  the  vitalises  soul,  or  guiding  entelechy, — opposed 
by  Descartes  but  warmly  upheld  in  our  own  day — must  be 
rejected.  For  some  of  the  facts  on  which  vitalism  rests  its 
case,  the  occurrence,  for  instance,  of  life-furthering  instincts, 
may  be  mechanically  conceived;  and  the  rest  are  not  vital 
phenomena  at  all  but  experiences  of  the  conscious  self.3 

1  Yet  Hume  distinguishes  soul  and  self.    Cf.  'Treatise,'  Book  I.,  Part  IV.,  Sections 
V.  and  VI. 

2  In  this  sense,  for  the  most  part,  Leibniz  and  Berkeley  use  the  term  (cf.  the  phrase 
"mind,  spirit,  soul  or  myself"  in  'Principles  of  Human  Knowledge/  II.)     In  the  doc- 
trines of  Wolff,  Baumgarten  and   other  rationalists  of  the  eighteenth   century  the 
vitalistic  and  the  immaterialistic  conceptions  of  soul  recur.     Cf.  Baumgarten,  'Meta- 
physica,'  III.,  II,  I,  §  750,  Wolff,  'Psychologia  rationalis,'  §§  48,  49. 

3  It  is  interesting  to  find  that  some  of  the  modern  biologists  who  challenge  the 
extreme  claims  of  mechanism,  virtually  identify  vitalism  with  idealistic  and  personal- 


300  MARY  W.  CALKINS 

There  is,  in  a  word,  no  middle  term  between  the  mechanical 
phenomenon  and  the  self.  This  study,  therefore,  culminates 
in  one  insistent  conclusion:  the  soul  must  go.  As  a  historic 
concept  of  immense  influence  it  will  always  retain  its  prom- 
inent place  in  the  history  of  ideas;  as  a  term  of  modern 
psychology  it  has  outlived  any  use  it  may  once  have  had  and 
has  become  a  source  of  mischievous  confusion. 

istic  philosophy.  Thus,  H.V.  Neal  writes:  "Biologists  must  .  .  .  accept  the  idealistic 
assumption";  and  again  "the  organic  individual  is  in  reality  spiritual,"  ('The  Basis 
of  Individuality  in  Organisms;  a  Defense  of  Vitalism.'  Address  before  the  American 
Society  of  Zoologists,  Science,  N.  S.,  XLIV.,  pp.  82  if.)  Other  biologists,  of  whom 
J.  A.  Haldane  may  serve  as  type,  reject  conventional  vitalism  along  with  pure  me- 
chanism and  count  themselves  with  the  personalists  ('Mechanism  and  Personality'). 


RELATION   BETWEEN   STRUCTURAL  AND 
BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY 

BY  A.  P.  WEISS 
Ohio  State  University 

The  purpose  of  this  paper  is  to  show  that  the  problems  in 
the  stud/  of  mind  which  are  ordinarily  the  problems  of  the 
structural  psychologist,  may  be  studied  from  the  behavioristic 
point  of  view,  in  accordance  with  the  methods  employed  in 
the  natural  sciences  and  with  a  greater  degree  of  simplicity 
than  is  possible  from  the  structuralistic  point  of  view.  No 
attempt  will  be  made  to  determine  whether  behaviorism  is  or 
is  not  psychology.  The  title  of  this  paper  might  also  have 
been  'The  Value  of  the  Objective  as  Compared  with  the  Sub- 
jective Method  in  Psychology'  were  it  not  for  the  fact  that 
the  terms  'objective'  and  'subjective'  because  of  their  un- 
certain connotation,  are  in  evil  repute  both  in  psychology  and 
in  all  the  social  sciences. 

PROBLEM  OF  STRUCTURAL  PSYCHOLOGY 

To  state  the  structuralists'  problem  is  not  an  easy  one  if 
justice  is  to  be  done  to  all  the  psychologists  who  are  repre- 
sentative of  this  school.  There  are,  however,  certain  funda- 
mental conceptions  which  are  characteristic  of  structuralism 
that  are  generally  accepted,  and  it  is  to  these  that  the  dis- 
cussion will  be  limited. 

By  the  term  structural  psychology  is  meant  the  type  of 
investigation  which  assumes  that  there  is  an  existential  datum 
called  mind  or  consciousness,  within  the  totality  of  which 
ultimate  differences  may  be  discriminated  which  are  given  the 
names  of  (i)  sensations,  (2)  images,  (3)  affections.  These  are 
usually  regarded  as  the  elements  into  which  consciousness  may 
be  analyzed.  The  aim  of  the  structural  psychologist  who 
accepts  this  analysis  is  to  describe  consciousness,  in  all  its 

301 


302  A.  P.  WEISS 

complexity,  in  terms  of  these  three  fundamental  classes  of 
consciousness.  There  is,  of  course,  considerable  difference  of 
opinion  between  structuralists  as  to  just  how  these  classes  are 
to  be  defined,  and  indeed,  whether  there  are  no  more  and  no 
less  than  three  elementary  categories.  But  for  our  purpose 
these  details  may  be  disregarded.  It  is  also  irrelevant  for 
us  whether  it  is  held  that  consciousness  is  present  in  a  situation 
in  which  sensations,  images  and  affections,  as  such,  are  absent. 
It  is  sufficient  if  we  recognize  clearly  that  the  structuralist 
aims  to  describe  the  structure  of  the  mind  or  consciousness, 
under  the  manifold  conditions  of  present-day  life,  in  terms  of 
whatever  elements  he  may  have  set  up,  and  that  he  considers 
the  descriptive  phase  of  his  investigation  as  complete  when 
he  has  done  this.  The  explanatory  phase  of  the  structuralist 
problem  is  the  determination  of  the  neural  correlates  of  the 
conscious  states  which  his  analysis  reveals. 

The  direct  method  by  which  the  structuralist  analyzes  a 
conscious  complex  into  its  elements  is  that  of  introspection. 
This  cannot  be  done  satisfactorily  under  normal  conditions. 
It  is  therefore  customary  to  create  an  experimental  situation 
similar  to  the  one  to  be  analyzed,  in  which  the  observer  is 
asked  to  report  in  language  the  mental  states  that  were 
present  during  the  experiment.  These  reports  of  the  mental 
states  are  then  treated  statistically.  The  experimenter 
assumes  that  the  verbal  reports  of  mental  states  are  not  the 
mental  states  which  the  observer  introspected,  but  that  the 
reports  are  merely  expressions  which  describe  the  character 
of  these  mental  states. 

There  is  considerable  difference  of  opinion  among  struc- 
turalists themselves  as  to  whether  introspection  gives  equally 
valid  results  in  all  cases  where  it  may  be  used.  Some  maintain 
that  even  the  most  complex  mental  states  may  be  analyzed 
by  the  introspective  method,  while  others  maintain  that  in- 
trospection modifies  complex  conscious  experiences  so  that 
the  elements  which  it  reveals  may  not  be  present  in  the  actual 
experience  which  is  being  investigated. 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3°3 

ORIGIN  AND  PROBLEM  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY 

As  the  applications  of  structural  psychology  became  more 
numerous  in  the  various  applied  fields  of  psychology  such  as 
education  and  medicine,  the  question  as  to  the  relation 
between  conscious  states  and  action  arose.  An  increasing 
number  of  psychologists  believed  that  sensations,  images, 
memories,  thought,  emotion,  affection,  etc.,  were  the  causes  or 
invariable  antecedents  of  certain  forms  of  human  behavior. 
This  naturally  led  to  the  question  as  to  how  consciousness  was 
related  to  changes  in  the  form  of  human  behavior.  Now, 
since  no  one  denied  that,  in  order  to  modify  behavior,  a  cor- 
responding change  in  the  neural  correlates  of  consciousness 
must  take  place,  this  inquiry  necessarily  came  to  be  stated  as 
follows:  How  can  consciousness  change  the  direction  of  a 
nervous  process?  In  its  most  general  form  this  question  is 
an  inquiry  into  the  relation  between  mind  and  body.  In 
animal  psychology  the  mind-body  problem  is  not  an  acute 
one  for  the  zoologist-psychologist  who  studies  animal  be- 
havior; and  the  success  which  these  investigators  have  had  in 
explaining  some  of  the  most  complex  forms  of  animal  be- 
havior in  purely  neural  terms  (tropisms,  reflexes,  instincts) 
has  led  some  of  the  psychologists  to  ask  whether  human 
behavior  could  not  be  placed  in  the  same  category  with  animal 
behavior  and  explained  without  the  introduction  of  a  mental 
or  conscious  factor. 

The  attempt  to  answer  this  question  by  the  application  of 
the  behaviorist  point  of  view  to  such  relatively  simple  forms  of 
human  behavior  as  reflexes  and  automatic  action  was  crowned 
with  considerable  success,  but  for  the  more  complex  behavior 
of  learning  the  strictly  neural  explanation  is  not  readily 
accepted  by  psychologists.  It  will  not  be  necessary  at  this 
stage  to  state  the  behaviorist  problem  in  detail  except  to 
indicate  that  the  behaviorist  is  concerned  with  determining 
the  properties  and  laws  of  the  neuro-muscular  system,  of 
which  the  introspective  reaction  is  a  part. 

Briefly,  we  may  state  the  problem  of  the  structuralist  as 
an  attempt  to  answer  the  question:  What  are  our  mental  states 


304  A.  P.  WEISS 

and  how  do  they  come  about?  while  the  behaviorist  problem  is: 
What  are  our  actions  and  how  do  they  come  about? 

The  following  paragraphs  are  devoted  to  a  discussion, 
from  the  behaviorist  point  of  view,  of  those  factors  of  struc- 
tural psychology  which  give  it  its  distinctive  character: 
namely,  the  relation  between  mind  and  body  or  the  character 
of  consciousness;  and  the  character  of  introspection. 

BEHAVIORISM  AND  THE  MIND-BODY  PROBLEM 

Discussion  by  psychologists  of  the  mind-body  problem  has 
led  to  the  formulation  of  the  three  following  positions : 

1.  Consciousness  does  not  enter  as  a  causal  agent  into 
such  actions  as  reflexes  and  instincts,  but  it  does  function  in 
what  is  usually  known  as  intelligent  or  voluntary  action. 

2.  Consciousness  cannot  be  regarded  as  the  invariable 
antecedent  to  any  kind  of  action  whatsoever. 

The  first  position  is  the  one  usually  taken  by  popular 
psychology  and  the  group  of  psychologists  known  as  "func- 
tionalists," while  the  second  position  is  the  one  maintained  by 
behaviorists.  The  position  of  the  structuralists  is  usually 
known  as  the  double-aspect  view,  in  which  there  is, 

3.  Parallelism   between   conscious   processes    and    neural 
processes  without  a  causal  relationship  between  them. 

This  position  is  best  described  by  the  following  quotation : 

"Our  own  position  has  been  that  mind  and  body  .  .  .  are  simply  two  aspects  of 
the  same  world  of  experience.  They  can  not  influence  each  other  because  they  are 
not  separate  or  independent  things.  For  the  same  reason,  however,  whenever  the  two 
aspects  appear,  any  change  which  occurs  in  the  one,  will  be  accompanied  by  a  corre- 
sponding change  in  the  other."1 

The  third  view  may  be  regarded  as  an  intermediate  posi- 
tion between  I  and  2.  That  is  to  say  a  functional  re- 
lationship does  exist  between  mind  and  body  but  only  in  the 
mathematical  sense  of  the  term  function,  as  when  we  speak 
of  the  volume  of  a  sphere  as  a  function  of  its  radius. 

If  this  functional  relationship  between  consciousness  and 
behavior  is  a  simple  one  it  would  be  useful  for  the  behaviorist, 
because  consciousness  could  then  be  used  as  a  measure  of 

1  Titchener,  E.  B.,  'A  Text-Book  of  Psychology,'  1912,  p.  9. 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  305 

behavior,  no  matter  what  the  ultimate  connection  between 
mind  and  body  might  be. 

Setting  aside  all  speculation  about  this  connection  we  find 
that  the  facts  in  the  case  may  be  stated  in  the  following 
propositions: 

1.  Consciousness  (the  totality  of  our  sensations,  images 
and  affections)  is  a  purely  personal  experience  and  has  no 
scientific  value  or  validity  unless  it  is  expressed  in  some  form 
of  behavior,  such  as  speech  or  other  form  of  representation. 

2.  Many  forms  of  behavior  (reflexes,  automatic  action)  are 
not  accompanied  by  consciousness  which  can  be  unambigu- 
ously analyzed. 

3.  The  consciousness  which  does  accompany  a  given  form 
of  behavior  varies  from  one  observer  to  another,  and  at  dif- 
ferent times  for  the  same  observer. 

4.  Complex  mental  processes,  such  as  reasoning  and  in- 
vention, are  more  than  the  mental  states  into  which  they  may 
be  analyzed.     They  have  a  social  reference  which  no  amount 
of  introspection  will  reveal.     This  social  reference  is  measured 
by  the  comparison  of  the  individual's  behavior,  either  with 
his  ordinary  behavior  or  with  that  of  other  individuals. 

From  the  above  propositions  the  behaviorist  feels  justified 
in  making  certain  deductions: 

From  proposition  I :  If  consciousness  must  be  expressed  in 
some  form  of  behavior  before  it  becomes  a  scientific  datum, 
then  consciousness  is  in  the  last  analysis  a  classification  and  a 
study  of  behavior. 

From  proposition  2:  If  there  are  many  forms  of  behavior 
(reflexes,  automatic  action)  which  are  important  from  a  social 
or  individual  standpoint,  which  are  not  accompanied  by 
consciousness,  then  consciousness  is  not  a  function  (mathe- 
matical) of  all  forms  of  behavior. 

From  proposition  3:  If  the  consciousness  which  does  ac- 
company a  given  form  of  behavior,  varies  from  one  person  to 
another,  or  for  the  same  person  at  different  times,  then  con- 
sciousness is  either  an  independent  variable  of  the  behavior, 
or  a  dependent  variable  of  highly  complex  formula.  In 
neither  case  is  it  any  better  measure  of  behavior  than  the 


306  A.  P.  WEISS 

behavior  itself,  and  consciousness  then  becomes  superfluous 
as  a  means  for  predicting  behavior. 

From  proposition  4:  If  complex  mental  processes  such  as 
reasoning  or  invention  are  more  than  the  mental  states  into 
which  they  may  be  analyzed,  then  in  this  case  too  the  analysis 
of  consciousness  does  not  make  it  possible  to  predict  the  in- 
dividual's behavior. 

In  view  of  the  above  implications,  the  very  simplest  as- 
sumptions as  to  the  quantitative  relations  between  sensations, 
images  and  affections  which  characterize  an  individual's  con- 
scious complexes,  it  is  impossible  to  predict  what  his  mental 
states  will  be  after  an  hour.  An  individual's  behavior, 
however,  can  be  predicted  with  much  greater  certainty  than 
can  the  character  of  the  conscious  processes  which  go  with  it. 
A  daily  photographic  record,  for  example,  will  show  greater 
uniformities  in  the  behavior  of  a  given  individual  so  far  as 
the  socially  significant  factors  are  concerned,  than  will  the 
daily  introspective  descriptions  of  the  consciousness  which 
accompanies  his  behavior. 

It  would  seem  then  that  the  sensations,  images  and  affec- 
tions which  one  experiences  are  more  variable  than  is  be- 
havior, since  by  the  term  behavior  we  usually  refer  to  only 
the  grosser  bodily  movements  and  to  the  speech  reactions. 
The  finer  changes  in  muscle  contractions,  as  in  respiration, 
digestion,  vascular  and  glandular  changes,  are  ordinarily  not 
considered  as  socially  significant. 

For  the  behaviorist,  then,  the  double-aspect  view  of  the 
structuralist  is  of  no  value,  since  the  function  (consciousness) 
of  the  behavior  is  more  variable  than  the  behavior  itself. 

CONSCIOUSNESS  AN  INFERENCE  DERIVED  FROM  THE  INTRO- 
SPECTIVE REACTION 

The  structuralist  is  usually  disposed  to  consider  the  in- 
vestigations of  the  behaviorist  as  quite  outside  of  his  field, 
because  consciousness  or  mind  is  something  entirely  distinct 
from  the  contraction  of  a  system  of  muscles.  In  the  last 
analysis,  however,  the  consciousness  of  his  observer  which 
the  structuralist  regards  as  the  unique  phase  of  his  investi- 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3°7 

gallon,  is  only  an  inference  from  the  verbo-motor  behavior 
which  is  called  introspection.  Structuralists'  experiments  are 
controlled  reactions  to  stimuli  just  as  in  any  behavior  experi- 
ment. The  sensations,  images  and  feeling  that  are  described, 
are  not  experienced  by  the  structuralist.  They  are  inferred 
from  the  behavior  of  his  observers. 

When  for  instance,  an  introspective  reaction  reads,  "My 
attention  fell  upon  the  central  projection,  and  vocal-motor 
imagery  of  'Gosh,  that's  ugly'  occurred.  I  was  aware  of  con- 
traction of  my  brows  and  unpleasantness."  The  structuralist 
infers  that  these  speech  reactions  are  descriptions  of  the  con- 
sciousness that  he  has  when  he  makes  the  same  speech  re- 
actions. To  every  introspective  report  of  his  observer,  the 
structuralist  adds,  at  least  implicitly,  the  speech  reaction, 
namely:  "The  introspective  report  of  my  observer  completely 
describes  certain  conscious  processes  of  which  I  am  myself 
conscious  or  aware,  when  I  make  the  same  speech  reactions." 

In  other  words,  psychologists  have  agreed  among  them- 
selves that  an  introspective  report  is  more  than  a  reaction;  it 
is  a  verbal  reaction  plus  some  kind  of  a  conscious  process, 
which  may  be  either  sensorial,  imaginal  or  affective.  The 
behaviorist  may  well  ask  of  what  scientific  value  is  this  habit 
of  supplementing,  in  a  methodological  sense,  the  observer's 
reaction  by  another  reaction  of  an  entirely  different  type 
(consciousness)  which  the  observer  did  not  report.  By  in- 
ferring a  conscious  correlate  to  the  introspective  report — the 
experimenter  is  not  able  to  derive  anything  more  from  the 
report  than  is  expressed  in  it.  The  manual  and  introspective 
reactions  of  the  observer  in  a  psychological  experiment  can  be 
classified  just  as  minutely  and  scientifically  without  inferring 
a  conscious  correlate,  as  they  can  with  it. 

BEHAVIORISM  AND  INTROSPECTION 

From  the  behavioristic  standpoint,  introspection  may  be 
regarded  as  an  example  of  habit  formation  or  learning.  An 
untrained  observer  cannot  make  these  introspective  speech 
reactions  in  a  manner  which  is  constant  and  uniform  enough 
to  permit  of  statistically  treating  the  results.  In  order  that 


308  A.  P.  WEISS 

these  supplementary  speech  reactions  may  become  uniform 
enough  to  admit  of  statistical  analysis,  two  methods  of 
simplifying  the  results  are  usually  employed: 

1.  The  observer  passes  through  a  preliminary  period  of 
training  in  which  the  reaction  time  of  relevant  speech  reac- 
tions (report  of  imagery,  kinesthesia,  etc.)  is  reduced  to  the 
experimental  requirements,  and  those  speech  reactions  which 
are  irrelevant  are  given  an  opportunity  to  disappear.     The 
relevancy  of  a  given  speech  reaction  is  usually  determined 
beforehand  according  to  the  specific  aim  of  the  experiment. 

2.  The  experimental  situation  is  so  modified  by  supple- 
mentary situations  in  the  form  of  instructions,  questions  or 
other  controls  that  the  required  uniformity  of  the  introspec- 
tive reactions  is  secured. 

The  first  method  is  the  one  with  which  we  will  especially 
concern  ourselves  in  the  following  discussion. 

As  already  indicated,  the  total  reaction  of  an  organism  to 
even  the  simplest  situation  is  very  complex.  Respiration, 
secretion,  circulatory  effects,  incipient  and  minute  bodily  and 
visceral  movements,  are  always  added  to  the  particular 
reaction  (the  discrimination  of  two  points,  for  instance)  which 
might  be  called  the  major  reaction  of  the  experiment.  The 
minor  reactions  by  themselves  would  escape  notice,  but  the 
speech  mechanism  is  a  rather  sensitive  index  as  to  the  char- 
acter of  these  minor  reactions.  Permitting  a  free  verbal 
report  after  each  trial  or  series  of  trials  in  an  experiment, 
reveals  more  as  to  the  character  of  the  total  reaction  than  can 
be  learned  from  the  major  reaction  alone. 

Organic  and  kinesthetic  reactions  which  would  escape 
observation  entirely  are  thus  easily  revealed  by  the  speech 
reaction.  If,  for  instance,  an  observer  who  has  been  trained 
according  to  method  (i)  reports  a  *  kinesthetic  sensation  of 
movement  of  the  neck'  that  report  from  the  behaviorist 
point  of  view  would  mean,  'an  incipient  or  slight  movement 
of  the  head,'  provided  his  methods  of  measuring  such  move- 
ments were  accurate  enough.  In  this  way  the  verbal  reaction 
*  kinesthetic  sensation  of  neck  movement'  really  indicates 
that  the  receptors  in  this  case  are  located  in  the  neck  muscles. 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  309 

The  speech  reaction  may  therefore  be  regarded  as  a  function 
of  particular  kinesthetic  and  organic  reactions  which  ordi- 
narily would  escape  observation. 

To  report  kinesthetic  and  organic  conditions  through 
speech  is  really  a  highly  specialized  example  of  habit  forma- 
tion. Indeed  introspection,  whatever  its  kind,  from  this 
point  of  view  may  be  regarded  as  a  continual  process  of 
training  in  the  formation  of  habits.  For  this  reason  many 
years  of  training  are  necessary  even  for  those  who  have 
special  aptitude  in  this  direction,  and  many  persons  never 
learn  to  introspect  well. 

The  training  of  an  individual  in  introspection  is,  therefore, 
a  process  of: 

1.  Training  in  discrimination  so  that  weak  stimuli  in  ob- 
scure receptors  lead  to  verbal  reactions. 

2.  Substituting  for  the  usual  anatomical  and  physiological 
descriptions   (head,  neck,  arms,   muscles,  viscera,   etc.)   the 
special  terminology  of  the  structuralist  (sensations,  images 
and  affections). 

The  relation  of  these  obscure  receptors  to  the  major  re- 
action of  the  experiment  may  be  of  a  highly  adventitious 
character.  A  trained  observer  does  not  react  exclusively  to 
the  experimental  situation — one  is  almost  tempted  to  say 
that  he  reacts  to  everything  but  the  experimental  situation. 
An  experiment  with  trained  observers  measures  principally 
the  training  of  the  observers,  it  does  not  necessarily  reveal 
what  the  normal  individual  could  be  expected  to  do  under 
similar  situations  or  conditions. 

From  the  behavioristic  standpoint,  then,  introspection 
may  be  regarded  as  a  greatly  augmented  reaction  to  a  given 
situation.  The  observer  not  only  reacts  to  the  situation,  for 
example,  by  pressing  a  key,  but  he  is  also  asked  to  react  by 
speech  to  the  stimulation  of  many  secondary  and  obscure 
receptors,  to  which,  under  normal  conditions,  no  such  reac- 
tion is  made. 


310  A.  P.  WEISS 

HEURISTIC  VALUE  OF  INTROSPECTION 
When  the  structuralist  experiment  is  stripped  of  its  con- 
scious reference  and  regarded  from  the  standpoint  of  objective 
science,  its  twofold  character  immediately  comes  to  light  as 
may  be  seen  from  the  following  quotation  which  is  part  of  the 
conclusion  of  a  long  and  painstaking  series  of  experiments 
"On  the  Analysis  of  a  Phase  of  the  Process  of  Classifying." 

"The  essence  of  the  process  of  classifying,  as  this  process  occurred  in  our  experi- 
ments, consisted  in  the  manner  of  our  observer's  perceiving  the  object  which  he  had 
been  instructed  to  classify.  This  manner  of  perceiving  consisted  in  the  fact  that  the 
region  of  essential  group  features — were  stressed  in  consciousness,  and  these  regions 
behaved  in  consciousness  in  a  fashion  which  depended  upon  their  resemblance  or  lack 
of  resemblance  to  the  corresponding  features  in  the  group  members.  In  the  former 
event,  the  regions  in  question  passed  in  and  out  of  consciousness  in  rapid  and  ready 
fashion,  without  retarding  the  course  of  attention.  In  the  latter  case,  on  the  other 
hand,  the  course  of  attention  was  arrested  sharply;  these  regions  often  persisted  in 
consciousness,  and  they  were  frequently  accompanied  sooner  or  later  by  more  or  less 
focal  and  intensive  kinesthetic,  organic  and  affective  contents  which  functioned  in  their 
conscious  settings  as  definite  rejectings  of  the  figure."1 

Will  the  above  conclusions,  we  may  ask,  enable  a  botanist 
or  zoologist  to  classify  his  specimens  more  effectively,  or  will 
the  scientist  know  any  more  about  classifying  than  he  did 
before  he  read  the  article?  The  question  may  even  be  asked, 
whether  this  particular  experiment  is  really  an  investigation 
of  the  process  of  classifying.  From  the  behavior  point  of 
view  at  least,  the  investigation  would  be  regarded  as  an  ex- 
periment in  discrimination  and  habit  formation,  carried  out 
under  the  following  conditions: 

An  experimental  situation  was  created  which  approached 
the  conditions  under  which  people  make  classifications,  except 
that  the  classifications  are  rather  more  than  ordinarily  dif- 
ficult. A  number  of  observers  who  had  been  carefully  trained 
to  respond  verbally  to  the  weak  stimulation  of  obscure  re- 
ceptors, were  asked  to  perform  a  double  task;  to  classify  the 
cards,  and  also  to  react  to  the  obscure  receptors  by  verbal 

1  Fisher,  Sara  C.,  'An  Analysis  of  a  Phase  of  the  Process  of  Classifying,'  Am.  J.  of 
Psychol.,  1917,  28,  p.  115. 

I  have  chosen  this  particular  illustration  because  I  regard  it  as  one  of  the  best 
structuralist  experiments  that  has  appeared  for  some  time  and  I  need  hardly  say  that 
no  criticism  is  intended  either  of  it  or  the  method  by  which  the  investigator  carried  it 
to  completion. 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3" 

reactions  which  conformed  to  a  more  or  less  uniform  termin- 
ology. An  analysis  of  the  author's  conclusion  quoted  above, 
in  behaviorist  terms,  may  be  stated  in  the  following  proposi- 
tions : 

1.  The  observers  were  able  to  classify  the  cards. 

2.  The  observers  reacted  either  to  the  similar  or  to  the 
dissimilar  features  of  the  cards.     The  reactions  to  the  similar 
features  were  relatively  simple;  the  reactions  to  the  dissimilar 
features  were  supplemented  by  verbal  reactions  to  obscure 
kinesthetic  and  organic  receptors. 

The  whole  emphasis  of  the  experiment  is  placed  upon  what 
the  behaviorist  would  call  the  reactions  to  obscure  receptors. 
The  actual  process  of  classifying  the  cards  was  merely  a  device 
to  obtain  some  degree  of  uniformity  in  the  verbal  reactions  to 
these  obscure  receptors.  From  these  considerations  we  can 
see  why  the  experiment  has  so  little  significance  for  the  sci- 
entist who  really  wishes  to  increase  his  classifying  efficiency. 
The  development  of  the  ability  to  react  to  the  weak  stimu- 
lation of  obscure  receptors  may  be  of  value  in  the  above  ex- 
periment as  a  means  of  determining  when  the  investigation 
of  the  classifying  process  was  being  supplanted  by  the  minor 
reactions  which  have  no  direct  bearing  on  the  process  of 
classifying. 

That  is  to  say,  the  presence  of  sensations,  images  and 
affections,  indicate  that  there  is  something  wrong  with  the 
experiment. 

In  ordinary  scientific  observation,  the  aim  is  to  eliminate 
the  unessential  or  obscure  so  that  the  effect  of  the  major  con- 
dition can  be  observed  in  isolation.  Under  behavioristic 
methods,  however,  if  it  is  desired  to  investigate  the  minor 
reactions  independently,  then  every  effort  is  made  to  isolate 
them  and  they  of  course  then  become  the  major  reactions. 
But  the  introspective  reactions  in  this  particular  experiment 
would  be  regarded  by  the  behaviorist  as  a  disturbing  factor. 

In  our  effective  adjustments  to  our  environment,  we  do  not 
have  sensations,  images  or  affections.  When  we  stop  to 
introspect  as  to  the  character  of  our  consciousness  in  a  given 
situation,  our  reactions  to  that  situation  become  to  this 


312  A.P.WEISS 

extent  irrelevant.  The  writer  has  frequent  occasions  to 
design  modifications  in  apparatus  used  by  the  students 
working  on  original  problems.  Having  also  some  episte- 
mological  interest,  it  often  happens  that  he  begins  to  intro- 
spect on  the  method  by  which  the  designing  process  is  going 
on.  When  this  happens,  he  might  as  well  stop.  Introspec- 
tion seriously  interferes  with  the  designing  activity.  The 
reactions,  incipient  though  they  be,  which  are  called  intro- 
spections, change  the  character  of  the  designing  activity  to 
such  an  extent  that  it  can  no  longer  be  called  the  designing 
activity.  This  is  gone;  he  is  merely  reacting  to  a  new  situ- 
ation by  making  aimless  sketches  and  many  incipient  verbo- 
motor  processes  which  if  recorded  might  read,  "Bronze 
contact,  visual  image  of  tuning  fork,  kinesthetic  sensations  of 
neck  muscles,  slight  unpleasantness,  image  of  Mr.  M.  before 
chronoscope,  visual  image  of  Prof.  X.  rushing  upstairs,  etc." 
None  of  these  reactions  would  have  occurred  had  he 
actually  completed  the  original  design.  This  is,  of  course,  not 
a  unique  situation.  Under  the  ordinary  conditions,  sensa- 
tions, images  and  affections  are  absent.  The  average  man 
probably  never  has  them;  he  must  be  trained  to  have  them 
in  the  same  way  that  we  must  be  trained  to  read  and  write. 
Introspection  is  only  one  of  the  ways  by  which  we  may 
react  to  a  situation.  How  the  reactions  themselves  originate, 
or  what  the  conditions  are  under  which  they  become  modified, 
is  not  revealed  by  introspection. 

TAUTOLOGICAL  CHARACTER  OF  INTROSPECTION 
By  selecting  a  somewhat  simpler  activity  than  that  of 
"classifying"  it  can  be  shown  that  the  introspective  records 
are  merely  special  terms  for  particular  classes  of  reactions. 
Suppose  we  take  the  process  of  recognition  from  the  struc- 
turalist standpoint.  We  may  assume  that  the  recognitive 
consciousness  is  made  up  of  a  characteristic  pattern  of  sen- 
sations, images  and  affections.  Suppose  the  experiment  is 
one  in  which  we  are  to  select  a  card  (A)  which  has  been  pre- 
viously examined,  from  a  series  of  similar  cards  which  have 
not  been  previously  examined.  We  wish  to  know  whether 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3*3 

the  card  (A)  has  been  recognized.  To  do  this,  the  behaviorist 
would  inspect  the  introspective  reactions  of  the  observer. 
Suppose  the  verbal  reactions  to  the  card  (A)  to  be  the  follow- 
ing. "I  have  seen  it  before;  I  have  a  visual  image  of  it  as  it 
appeared  when  I  saw  it  for  the  first  time;  I  have  the  feeling  of 
familiarity;  I  have  organic  and  kinesthetic  sensations 
(images?),  which  mean  that  I  am  handling  it  in  a  more  ener- 
getic and  discriminative  fashion  than  the  other  cards;  etc." 
To  the  new  cards  the  verbal  reactions  might  be  as  follows: 
"I  have  never  seen  these  cards  before;  the  kinesthetic  and 
organic  sensations  are  different  than  for  card  (A);  they  do 
not  carry  the  meaning  of  familiarity;  the  visual  and  auditory 
imagery  is  different  than  for  card  (A)',  etc."  It  is  not  sup- 
posed that  this  is  the  complete  introspective  record,  and  we 
disregard  for  the  present  such  objective  measures  as  the 
reaction  time,  or  of  the  bodily  movements  which  might  have 
been  made. 

If  we  regard  the  introspections  from  the  purely  objective 
side  as  being  muscle  contractions  of  the  speech  mechanism 
which  produce  the  various  sounds  which  we  call  words  or 
speech,  we  can  immediately  see  that  the  observer  has  reacted 
differently  to  the  card  (A)  than  to  the  other  cards.  It  is  not 
necessary  to  interpolate  a  conscious  process  (of  recognition) 
in  order  to  see  this.  The  fact  is,  that  if  the  observer  has  used 
the  identical  words  to  describe  both  the  (A)  and  the  new  cards, 
we  should  be  obliged  to  conclude  that  there  was  no  difference 
in  the  observer's  consciousness  of  the  (A)  and  the  other 
cards.  That  is  to  say,  a  difference  in  consciousness  can  only 
be  inferred  from  a  difference  in  behavior.  Moreover,  the 
interpolation  of  consciousness  does  not  explain  how  it  came 
about  that  the  card  (A)  was  reacted  to  in  a  manner  dif- 
ferent from  that  of  the  other  cards.  The  introspective  record 
merely  reiterates  the  fact  that  the  observer  did  react  differ- 
ently. This  could  have  been  seen  directly  by  regarding  the 
report  of  the  introspective  reactions  as  what,  in  fact,  they 
are — objective  reactions  of  the  speech  type.  Because  the 
observer  reacted  differently  to  the  (A)  than  to  the  other 
cards,  the  experimenter  says  he  has  given  a  recognizing 


314  A-P-  WEISS 

reaction.  We  cannot  say  he  reacted  differently  because  he 
recognized,  but  that  he  recognized  because  he  reacted  dif- 
ferently. In  this  sense  the  inference  of  the  conscious  process 
of  recognition  is  tautological. 

STRUCTURALISM  A  PHASE  OF  BEHAVIORISM 
The  structuralist  point  of  view  can,  of  course,  be  con- 
sistently maintained.  There  is  a  justification  for  inferring 
the  existence  of  a  conscious  correlate  for  at  least  some  of  our 
actions,  but  the  heuristic  value  of  this  assumption  seems 
doubtful  when  it  is  shown  that  behaviorism  is  not  less  dis- 
criminative or  descriptive  than  structural  psychology,  and  in 
addition  it  has  the  promise  at  least  of  a  system  whose  parts 
are  causally  related  to  each  other  in  the  sense  that  a  temporal 
description  of  a  given  form  of  behavior  is  more  uniform  than 
the  temporal  description  of  the  conscious  states  which  are 
said  to  go  with  it.  If  this  is  true  then  the  law  of  Parsimony 
will  operate  to  eliminate  the  unnecessary  assumption  of  a 
conscious  correlate  for  behavior  (implied  by  introspection). 
When  we  recall  how  we  are  being  exhorted  to  recognize  the 
unconscious,  subconscious,  higher  thought  processes,  unan- 
schaulichen  Bewusstseinsinhalt,  one  wonders  whether  this 
process  of  elimination  has  not  gone  further  than  we  suspect. 
For  the  behaviorist  the  structuralist's  classifications  do  not 
lead  to  a  solution  of  the  problem,  What  are  our  actions  and 
how  do  they  come  about?  or  How  do  the  manifold  social 
adjustments  of  the  adult  grow  out  of  the  relatively  simple 
reactions  of  the  child  ?  Even  if  the  objective  side  of  the  struc- 
turalist problem  be  further  developed,  the  neural  correlate  of 
conscious  processes  will  only  be  a  very  special  problem  in 
behavior.  Sensations,  images,  affections,  emotions,  will,  the 
self,  recognition,  etc.,  so  far  as  science  is  concerned  are  only 
special  instances  of  receptor-effector  activity.  While  this  is 
of  course  very  generally  recognized  by  psychologists,  the 
further  assumption  that  these  forms  of  receptor-effector 
activity  are  highly  significant  for  our  understanding  how  man 
is  able  to  make  his  effective  adjustment  to  his  environment,  is 
not  warranted,  because  the  analysis  and  isolation  of  such  a 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3*5 

neural  correlate  does  not  indicate  how  the  neural  correlate 
itself  came  to  have  the  configuration  that  it  has. 

This,  of  course,  can  only  be  done  by  a  genetic  study  of  the 
particular  type  of  reaction.  For  example,  when  the  structur- 
alist has  determined  the  neural  correlate  for  the  process  called 
"recognition,"  his  explanation  is  complete.  For  the  be- 
haviorist  this  is  merely  a  type  of  reaction  whose  effector- 
receptor  phase  is  described  by  the  proposition:  To  objects 
to  which  we  have  reacted  once,  we  do  not  react  in  identically 
the  same  way  the  next  time  they  are  presented,  even  though 
the  stimulus  conditions  approach  identity  for  both  occasions. 
This  is  merely  a  statement  of  fact  which  becomes  valuable 
only  when  stated  quantitatively. 

The  more  important  scientific  question:  How  does  this 
action  come  about,  can  only  be  answered  by  increasing  our 
knowledge  of  neural  function. 

It  is  in  the  above  sense  that  we  may  regard  the  intro- 
spective reaction  of  the  structuralist  as  only  a  part  of  the 
total  problem  of  determining  how  man  makes  his  manifold 
adjustments  to  his  environment. 

BASIS  OF  BEHAVIORISM 

In  order  to  state  the  position  of  the  behaviorist  more  con- 
cretely, the  following  assumptions  as  to  the  explanation  of 
human  behavior  are  presented. 

1.  The  resistance  of  neurons  varies  with  function. 

2.  Every  receptor  is  directly  connected  by  a  neural  chain 
with  a  restricted  effector  system,  and  through  varying  degrees 
of  indirectness  to  many  other  effector  systems. 

3.  One  nervous  process  will  modify  the  character  of  other 
nervous  processes  that  occur  together  with  it. 

4.  Certain  configurations  of  neural  connections  between 
receptors  and  effectors  are  inherited,  some  are  acquired. 

These  assumptions  are  not  essentially  different  than  those 
formulated  by  Max  F.  Meyer.1 

From  these  four  laws  or  assumptions  it  is  evident  that 
there  is  a  possibility  of  greater  variations  in  the  response  of  an 

1  'The  Fundamental  Laws  of  Human  Behavior,'  1911. 


316  A.  P.  WEISS 

organism  than  is  usually  included  under  what  the  structur- 
alists call  the  study  of  mind. 

Each  of  the  four  propositions  represents  a  series  of  problems 
which  may  be  experimentally  handled  in  the  same  manner 
that  an  experiment  in  any  other  science  would  be  conducted. 
There  need  be  no  quarreling  about  consciousness  or  as  to 
whether  there  is  or  is  not  such  a  thing,  since  it  will  make  no 
difference  in  the  effectiveness  of  the  work  of  the  behaviorist 
or  any  scientist  how  the  question  may  finally  be  settled.  In 
their  present  form  the  propositions  represent  little  more  than 
a  program  for  future  work.  Each  proposition  will  be  divided 
and  subdivided  and  coefficients  will  be  supplied  to  the  various 
derived  propositions.  How  fruitful  the  analysis  will  be 
cannot  of  course  be  predicted,  but  if  structural  'psychology, 
with  all  the  painstaking  and  careful  work  that  has  been  done 
on  sensorial  and  imaginal  processes,  has  not  yet  developed  a 
definition  of  sensation  upon  which  two  psychologists  will 
.agree,  then  behaviorism  can  expect  a  considerable  degree  of 
tolerant  good  will. 

SUMMARY 

1.  The   close   academic   relationship   between   structural 
psychology  and  behaviorism  is  due  to  the  popular  belief  that 
mind  and  body  are  related  in  such  a  way  that  mind  produces 
or  modifies  behavior. 

2.  A  conscious  state  which  is  not  expressed  in  some  form 
of  behavior  is,  so  far  as  science  is  concerned,  non-existent. 
The   inference   of  consciousness   is,   therefore,   unnecessary, 
since  in  the  last  analysis  behavior  is  the  only  thing  that  can  be 
classified. 

3.  For  the  behaviorist  the  introspective  reaction  is  only 
the  habit  of  being  able  to  react  by  speech,  more  or  less  adven- 
titiously, to  the  weak  stimulation  of  obscure  receptors. 

4.  Even  if  it  is  admitted  that  the  special  introspective 
habits  are  correlated  with  conscious  processes,  the  latter  are  so 
variable  that  they  cannot  be  used  as  an  index  from  which  to 
predict  behavior  which  is  socially  or  scientifically  significant. 

5.  The  method  of  introspection  favors  the  reactions  to 
obscure  stimuli  and  in  a  corresponding  degree  decreases  the 


STRUCTURAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  317 

reliability  of  the  major  reaction  for  the  investigation  of  which 
the  experiment  is  designed. 

6.  Behaviorism  presents  as  manifold  possibilities  of  an- 
alysis and  classification  as  does  structuralism,  and  has  the 
added  advantage  that  its  phenomena  can  be  represented  as 
a  causal  series  in  the  same  sense  as  we  now  speak  of  causal 
relationship  in  the  natural  sciences. 

7.  When  the  behaviorist  solves  the  problem:  How  do  our 
actions  come  about?  all  the  problems  of  the  structuralist  will 
also  be  solved. 

8.  The  relation  between  structuralism  and  behaviorism  is 
such  that  they  may  exist  side  by  side.     This  will  occur  only 
when  the  fundamental  conceptions  underlying  both  methods 
are  not  very  closely  scrutinized  or  where  the  individual  is  not 
particularly  interested  in  the 'theoretical  implications  of  either 
the  one  or  the  other  method. 


DISCUSSION 

MEANING  AND   IMAGERY 

In  the  discussion  of  imageless  thought  one  must  bear  in  mind 
the  fact  that  there  is  more  than  one  way  in  which  it  might  be  held 
that  thought  is  imageless. 

1.  One  might  for  instance  say  that  thought  is  not  only  not 
identical  with  imagery,  but  that  it  is  always  and  under  all  circum- 
stances independent  thereof,  that  imagery  is  in  all  subjects  and  at 
all  times  subsequent  to  thought  and  never  helps  in  the  solution  of 
problems  that  can  be  thought  about.     This  would  be  an  "out  and 
out  imageless  position,"  but  one  which,  so  far  as  I  know,  no  one  has 
yet  taken,  though  some  approach  it.     It  would  also  contradict 
various  pieces  of  experimental  work.1 

2.  One  might  hold  that  thought  is  imageless  in  the  sense  that  it 
is  a  mental  process  sui  generis,  distinct  from  imagery,  but  never 
imageless  in  the  sense  that  it  is  ever  present  in  the  mind  unaccom- 
panied by  imagery.     One  taking  this  stand  might  even  maintain 
that  the  thought  process  is  dependent  on  previous  mental  imagery — 
in  the  sense  that  the  image  is  the  source  from  which  the  thought 
process  is  derived. 

Such  seems  actually  to  have  been  the  theory  of  Aristotle  who, 
while  distinguishing  between  and  even  contrasting  kirurriiijai  and 
ctla6f}<nsi  maintained  that  the  mind  never  thinks  without  (pavraffiJiaTce. 
In  fact  whenever  the  mind  sees,  it  is  necessary  for  it  to  behold 
imagery — OTOLV  re  Oeupfi  avajKfj  a/za  (pavraff^a  n  Oeuptiv.  The  next 
sentence  shows  that  he  is  really  speaking  of  imagery  rather  than 
the  forms  of  sense  perception :  ra  yap  (pavraffnara  axnrep  alffdrjuaTa 
kffTL  ir\fiv  avev  vArjs. 

So  also  St.  Thomas  maintains  that  the  human  intellect  cannot 
actually  understand  anything  without  recourse  to  images.  It  is 
interesting  to  note  that  this  position  was  taken  on  the  following 
empirical  grounds: 

(a)  When  cerebral  lesions  are  sufficiently  serious  to  affect  mem- 

1  Cf.,  for  example,  George  Herbert  Betts,  'The  Distribution  and  Functions  of 
Mental  Imagery,'  Teachers  College,  Columbia  University,  New  York,  1909. 

2  Trepi  tvxw,  III.,  viii,  §3. 

318 


MEANING  AND  IMAGERY  3  1 9 

ory  and  imagination  they  also  interfere  with  the  orderly  course  of 
thought. 

(&)  An  appeal  to  introspection — "quia  hoc  quilibet  in  seipso 
experiri  potest" — viz.,  "when  one  attempts  to  understand  some- 
thing he  forms  to  himself  certain  images  by  way  of  example." 
Likewise  when  we  want  to  explain  a  matter  to  someone  else  we  give 
examples  from  which  he  can  derive  images  that  will  lead  to  under- 
standing.1 

3.  Without  adopting  either  of  these  positions,  one  might  say 
that  while  the  image  is  frequently  very  useful,  nevertheless,  a  thought 
process  can  be  present  to  the  mind  without  simultaneous  imagery 
and  that  it  is  not  necessary  for  us  to  draw  all  our  meanings  and 
thoughts  from  the  contemplation  of  imagery.  Thus  thought  would 
be  imageless  in  the  sense  that  it  is  distinct  from  the  (pavTaffnara. 
It  would  often  be  imageless,  too,  in  the  sense  that  it  would  not  be 
dependent  on  the  ipavracr^ara.  or  preceded  or  accompanied  by 
them. 

That  the  extent  to  which  one  makes  use  of  images,  and  the 
rapidity  with  which  they  come,  should  be  subject  to  individual 
variations  is  certainly  to  be  expected. 

In  an  article  on  the  'Temporal  Relations  of  Meaning  and 
Imagery,' 2  I  pointed  out  that  with  eight  out  of  nine  subjects  I  found 
that  meaning  preceded  visual  and  kinsesthetic  imagery  in  the  per- 
ception of  printed  words,  but  that  in  memory,  on  the  contrary, 
imagery  precedes  meaning.  I  was  thus  led  to  adopt  the  last  of  the 
three  positions  I  have  above  outlined. 

I  did  not  maintain  that  this  relationship  of  meaning  and  imagery 
in  perception  was  universal.  I  was  nevertheless  inclined  and  still 
am  inclined  to  believe,  mainly  on  empirical  grounds,  that  it  will  be 
very  rare  that  individuals  will  be  found  who  present  genuine  excep- 
tions. The  one  subject  who  proved  an  exception  in  my  experi- 
ments, did  not  learn  to  refrain  from  reacting  to  nonsense  words, 
so  that  one  could  not  be  sure  of  just  what  he  was  reacting  to,  when 
supposed  to  be  responding  to  the  task  meaning  or  imagery. 

I  remember  talking  the  matter  over  with  Biihler,  who  thought 
that  exceptions  would  prove  more  frequent  than  I  supposed. 
Since  then,  I  have  often  wondered  what  experiments  on  a  larger 
number  of  subjects  would  reveal. 

In  the  March  issue  of  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW,  Edward  C. 

1  Cf.  'Summa  Theologica,'  I.,  Q.  Ixxxiv,  §  7. 

2  PSYCHOL.  REVIEW,  May,  1915. 


320  T.   V.  MOORE 

Tolman  has  undertaken  such  an  investigation  on  49  subjects.  He 
attempts  a  preliminary  sorting  out  by  having  his  subjects  react  to 
words  representing  black  or  white  objects:  (a)  when  they  knew 
whether  it  was  black  or  white  irrespective  of  the  way  in  which  this 
was  known;  (#)  when  they  could  see  it  from  their  visual  image.  All 
but  fourteen  of  the  subjects  gave  shorter  times  for  knowing  than 
for  visualization.  I  regret  that  this  modification  was  made  use  of, 
because  it  changes  the  whole  situation.  It  introduces  a  new  problem 
and  one  in  which  visual  imagery  might  be  very  useful  and  would, 
therefore,  be  more  likely  to  be  used  than  in  the  former  situation. 
I  am  inclined  to  believe  that  I  would  be  ranged  among  the  visualizers 
in  attempting  its  solution. 

Unfortunately  this  preliminary  sorting  cannot  be  compared  to 
the  word  perception  test  and  we  thus  still  lack  evidence  of  the  rel- 
ative frequency  of  the  cases  in  which  imagery  precedes  meaning  in 
the  process  of  perceiving  printed  words. 

Having  selected  fourteen  subjects  by  this  preliminary  experi- 
ment as  likely  to  prove  an  exception  to  the  usual  order  he 
subjected  them  to  the  same  type  of  experiment  that  I  used  in 
Munich.  He  finds,  nevertheless,  that  three  of  these  gave  the 
same  order  of  sequence  that  I  found  in  Munich.  Three  subjects 
gave  doubtful  results.  Eight  gave  results  distinctly  (?)  pointing 
to  the  opposite  sequence,  so  that  with  them  reaction  time  to 
meaning  was  longer  than  to  imagery.  In  the  last  group  he  finds 
two  subdivisions.  The  first  comprises  those  who  as  a  rule  tend  to 
distinguish  between  meaning  and  imagery. 

Let  us  consider  this  group  a  moment  and  see  why  their  reaction 
times  to  meaning  are  longer  than  to  imagery.  In  every  one  of  the 
introspections  given  (pp.  133-134)  the  meaning  is  analyzed  and  more 
or  less  roughly  defined  and  does  not  correspond  to  the  'simple 
meaning'  spoken  of  in  my  paper.  Sometimes  the  meaning  is  evi- 
dently a  'concept  of  purpose'  for  which  I  also  found  much  longer 
reactions.  I  have  not  time  here  to  discuss  'analyzed'  and  'un- 
analyzed'  meanings,  but  hope  to  do  so  soon  in  a  monograph  on 
'Perception  and  Memory'  now  almost  ready  for  publication. 

Meaning  is  a  process  which  undergoes  development.  It  is  not 
surprising  that  some  subjects  wait  until  it  has  developed  and  they 
feel  sure  of  a  definite  analyzed  meaning  before  reacting.  In  these 
subjects  one  is  likely  to  get  reaction  times  that  are  longer  than  those 
for  visual  imagery.  This  expectation  seems  to  be  realized  in  the 
reaction  times  of  this  set  of  Dr.  Tolman's  subjects  and  confirmed  by 
their  introspections. 


MEANING  AND  IMAGERY  $21 

The  second  subgroup  of  subjects  did  not  distinguish  between 
meaning  and  imagery  and  their  introspections  show  that  when 
reacting  to  what  they  called  *  meaning'  they  were  as  a  matter  of  fact 
reacting  to  images.  In  only  one  member  of  this  group  is  the  dif- 
ference between  the  averages  greater  than  the  mean  variations. 
In  none  of  the  others  is  it  even  half  as  great.  It  might  be  safer, 
therefore,  to  place  all  but  one  of  these  subjects  in  the  doubtful 
group.  Whether  the  task  is  meaning  or  imagery  they  react  to  one 
and  the  same  thing  and  naturally  give  in  either  case  about  the  same 
results.  The  general  slight  tendency  to  a  longer  reaction  time  with 
meaning  and  the  single  pronounced  tendency  in  that  way  with  one 
subject  might  readily  be  accounted  for  by  their  being  called  upon 
to  pick  out  what  they  have  not  been  accustomed  to  label. 

Dr.  Tolman's  assumption  that  with  them  meaning  is  imagery 
supposes  too  great  a  distinction  of  types.  It  is  possible,  but  scarcely 
probable,  that  one  set  of  normal  men  understand  and  visualize, 
whereas  the  other  visualize  but  never  understand.  I  do  not  doubt 
that  other  experiments  would  show  that  these  subjects  were  not 
wholly  devoid  of  understanding  as  something  distinct  from  imagin- 
ing. 

Dr.  Tolman's  study  does  little  more  than  raise  the  question:  Are 
there  really  any  genuine  exceptions  to  the  hitherto  observed  relation 
in  the  sequence  of  meaning  and  imagery?  But  what  would  be  the 
import  of  finding  exceptions — and,  let  us  say,  even  numerous  ex- 
ceptions to  the  rule?  I  do  not  see  that  the  demonstration  of  even 
a  large  number  of  exceptions  would  weaken  the  argument,  drawn 
from  temporal  sequence,  to  establish  a  distinction  between  meaning 
and  imagery. 

Let  us  suppose  that  two  events  moved  usually  with  the  same 
velocity,  so  that  we  could  scarcely  ever  detect  one  without  the 
other.  If,  however,  under  certain  circumstances  one  moved  more 
slowly  or  more  rapidly  than  the  other,  so  that  we  could  observe 
one  without  the  other  these  cases  alone  would  enable  us  to  say  that 
the  two  things  are  not  really  identical. 

If  meaning  is  identical  with  imagery  then  the  two  events  must 
always  come  together.  If  it  is  not  then  you  will  find  some  subjects 
in  whom  their  rate  of  development  is  not  identical  and  one  will 
come  before  or  after  the  other. 

If  meaning  is  dependent  on  imagery,  e.  g.,  in  the  Aristotelian 
sense,  then  imagery  will  always  precede  meaning. 

We  find  on  the  contrary  that  meaning  as  a  rule  precedes  imagery. 


322  DISCUSSION 

It  is,  therefore,  not  identical  with  it  and  as  a  rule  does  not  depend 
upon  it  in  the  process  of  the  perception  of  printed  words  representing 
objects  easily  visualized. 

Dr.  Tolman's  paper  confirms  this  very  important  fact.  At  the 
same  time  it  presents  no  absolutely  conclusive  proof  of  subjects 
who  constitute  an  exception  to  the  rule.  It  is  quite  possible, 
however,  that  some  subjects  will  be  found  capable  of  distinguishing 
between  meaning  and  imagery,  in  whom  the  development  of  images 
is  so  rapid  that  their  mental  pictures  will  usually  precede  their 
simple  unanalyzed  meanings.  Such  a  fact  would  be  significant  in 
the  study  of  types  of  individuals,  but  would  have  little  bearing  on 
the  more  theoretical  problem  of  the  existence  of  imageless  thought. 

THOMAS  VERNER  MOORE 
CATHOLIC  UNIVERSITY  OF  AMERICA 


SOME  EXPERIMENTS  IN  MOTOR  REPRODUCTION  OF 
VISUALLY  PERCEIVED   FORMS. 

Some  little  time  ago  I  had  occasion  to  observe  experimentally 
certain  cursive  figures  of  an  unusual  type  while  engaged  in  an  ex- 
periment along  lines  quite  different  from  that  of  the  experiment 
here  reported.  These  figures  were  presented  by  means  of  the 
Whipple  tachistoscope.  They  were  to  be  learned  by  means  of 
frequent  repetitions,  so  that  they  could  be  reproduced  with  pencil 
on  paper.  The  experiment  had  to  do  with  the  relative  advantages 
of  learning  figures  by  means  of  copies  in  strong  relief  traced  by  the 
fingers  of  blindfolded  subjects,  and  by  means  of  copies  of  similar 
figures  exposed  to  visual  perception  by  the  tachistoscope.  I  acted 
as  a  subject  for  both  forms  of  learning,  and  had  opportunities  to 
observe  closely  other  subjects  at  work. 

Early  in  the  course  of  this  experiment  I  became  interested  in  the 
fact  that  the  behavior  of  the  subject  at  the  time  of  attempting  to 
reproduce  the  figure  was  an  important  factor  in  determining  the 
accuracy  of  the  reproduction.  I  found  it  to  be  true  of  myself,  and 
it  seemed  to  be  true  of  other  subjects,  that  if  one  watched  what  he 
was  doing  while  attempting  to  make  the  reproduction  it  seldom 
happened  that  the  result  was  as  satisfactory  as  if  the  reproducing 
was  done  with  eyes  shut  or  averted.  After  casual  inspection  I 
found  that  practically  all  the  subjects  concerned  were  far  more 
satisfied  that  their  reproductions  resembled  the  model  closely  when 
these  reproductions  were  made  without  the  subjects  seeing  what 


MOTOR  REPRODUCTION  OF  VISUALLY  PERCEIVED  FORMS    3*3 

they  were  doing.  The  point  seemed  to  me  to  be  of  sufficient  interest 
to  warrant  some  investigation. 

One  may  have  a  pretty  definite  idea  of  just  what  he  wishes  to 
draw,  and  may  take  his  pencil  in  hand  with  absolute  certainty  that 
he  will  draw  it  quickly  and  easily.  But  as  he  draws  it  his  eyes 
follow  the  outline  being  reproduced.  Does  the  sight  of  what  he  is 
drawing  aid  him  in  completing  the  figure  accurately?  Or  do  the 
visual  perceptions  interfere  with  and  destroy  the  guiding  memory 
images?  It  is  to  be  understood  that  the  figure  which  serves  as 
model  is  not  in  sight  during  the  reproducing  process. 

The  problem  finally  assumed  the  following  form:  "If  one  is 
reproducing  on  paper  an  outline  which  he  has  just  memorized  what 
effect  does  the  visual  perception  given  by  the  figure  in  process  of 
being  reproduced  exert  on  the  visual  or  kinaesthetic  images  which 
are  directing  the  process?" 

A  series  of  figures  was  made  which  could  be  presented  on  the 
tachistoscope.  It  was  not  particularly  easy  to  find  figures  which 
were  sufficiently  new  to  really  require  memorization.  It  would  not 
do  to  have  the  figures  so  made  that  one  could  easily  describe  them 
to  himself  in  terms  of  association  with  other  forms  or  objects.  We 
had  recourse  to  the  Arabic  alphabet,  and,  by  adaptation  and 
combination,  constructed  therefrom  several  figures  suitable  for  our 
use.  There  were  ten  of  these  figures  finally  selected,  and  they  were 
arranged  in  two  groups  of  five  each.  In  each  group  these  figures 
were  arranged  in  order  of  difficulty;  or  rather,  we  attempted  so  to 
arrange  them.  We  did  not  discover  any  principles  which  would 
give  an  adequate  measure  of  difficulty,  and  were  forced  to  be  content 
with  arranging  them  according  to  the  general  complexity  of  the 
figures,  their  number  of  curves,  loops  and  line  crossings.  We  were 
careful  to  vary  the  order  of  presentation  of  the  figures  so  that  if  any 
were  markedly  harder  than  others  that  fact  would  not  influence  the 
results  in  one  direction  more  than  another. 

There  were  two  methods  of  reproducing  the  figures  after  they 
were  learned.  In  the  first  method,  hereafter  called  the  "sight" 
method,  the  subject  would  watch  what  he  was  doing  while  drawing 
the  figure.  In  the  second  or  "blind"  method  a  screen  was  inter- 
posed between  the  eyes  of  the  subject  and  the  paper  so  that  he  would 
not  see  what  he  was  doing  while  trying  to  draw  the  remembered 
figure. 

The  following  directions  were  given  to  subjects  before  reacting 
according  to  the  sight  method: 


324  G.  R.  WELLS 

Fixate  cross.  Observe  the  figure  which  appears,  and  after  the  smallest  possible 
number  of  exposures  draw  it  on  the  paper  in  front  of  you.  Try  to  get  both  direction 
of  turns  and  general  proportions  of  figure  correct. 

Subjects  about  to  react  according  to  the  blind  method  were 
instructed  as  follows: 

Fixate  cross.  Observe  the  figure  which  appears,  and  after  the  smallest  possible 
number  of  exposures  draw  it  on  the  paper  in  front  of  you,  but  keep  eyes  on  the  screen 
between  you  and  the  paper  while  you  are  drawing  it.  Try  to  get  both  direction  of 
turns,  and  general  proportions  of  figure  correct. 

One  half  of  the  subjects  followed  first  the  sight  method  on  one  set 
of  figures,  and  then  the  blind  method  on  the  other  set  of  figures. 
The  other  half  of  the  subjects  used  the  blind  method  first  and  then 
the  sight  method.  In  half  the  cases  the  figures  used  for  the  sight 
process  were  those  of  Set  L,  and  in  the  other  cases  the  figures  were 
those  of  Set  II.  So  that  it  is  true  that  the  same  figures  were  some- 
times used  for  reproduction  with  sight  and  sometimes  without  sight. 
Also,  the  same  set  was  at  times  presented  first,  and  sometimes  second. 
It  does  not  seem  that  the  results  could  have  been  influenced  by  any 
possible  differences  in  difficulty  between  individual  figures,  nor  that 
any  possible  practice  effect  was  exerted  on  one  reproducing  process 
more  than  another. 

The  exposure  time  averaged  65/roo1  of  a  second  in  length.  The 
subject  was  told  that  he  could  have  as  many  exposures  as  he  wished, 
but  was  urged  to  request  as  few  as  possible.  It  was  made  very 
plain  that  he  must  make  every  effort  to  keep  the  number  of  exposures 
few  in  number. 

There  were  twenty  subjects.  All  but  one  were  students  in 
Oberlin  College,  the  exception  being  an  instructor  in  economics.  All 
but  three  were  taking  courses  in  the  psychological  laboratory.  The 
exceptions  were  the  instructor  just  mentioned,  and  two  students  who 
had  had  a  good  deal  of  training  in  art.  The  fact  that  they  had  done 
practical  work  in  drawing  suggested  that  their  inclusion  in  the  list 
of  subjects  might  furnish  some  interesting  variations  in  results. 
In  point  of  fact  their  reactions  were  in  no  respect  different  from 
those  of  the  other  subjects. 

1  The  working  time  of  the  Whipple  tachistoscope  varies  quite  a  good  deal,  but  this 
was  the  average  time.  In  the  tachistoscope  in  the  Oberlin  laboratory  we  have  replaced 
the  usual  cardboard  discs  with  light  metal  (ordinary  sheet  tin)  discs,  and  we  time  the 
length  of  exposure  by  means  of  two  make-and-break  contacts,  so  arranged  that  when 
the  disc  revolves  a  circuit  is  broken  at  the  point  at  which  the  exposure  begins.  This 
circuit  is  remade  when  the  disc  reaches  the  place  at  which  the  exposure  is  completed. 
A  magnetic  marker  is  arranged  in  series  with  these  contacts.  This  method  may  leave 
something  to  be  desired  from  the  physical  standpoint,  but,  after  all,  it  furnishes  one 
with  some  real  information  concerning  the  exposure  time. 


MOTOR  REPRODUCTION  OF  VISUALLY  PERCEIVED  FORMS     325 

Eleven  subjects  used  the  sight  method  of  reproduction  for  the 
figures  of  Set  I.,  and  the  blind  method  for  Set  II.  Nine  subjects 
used  Set  II.  for  the  sight  method,  and  Set  I.  for  the  blind  method.  It 
was  merely  accidental  that  there  were  not  ten  subjects  in  each 
group. 

When  the  time  came  to  sum  up  the  result  of  the  trials,  it  was 
necessary  to  find  some  method  of  determining  the  relative  accuracy 
of  the  figures  as  reproduced.  No  completely  satisfactory  method  of 
measuring  occurred  to  me  and  I  finally  arranged  arbitrary  principles 
of  scoring,  and  applied  them  to  all  the  figures  alike.  The  rules 
which  governed  the  scoring  were  as  follows: 

1.  Score  I  for  each  exposure  required  for  learning. 

2.  Score  i  for  a  curve  in  the  wrong  direction. 

3.  Score  I  for  very  great  error  in  the  proportion  of  parts. 

4.  Score  I  for  the  insertion  of  any  marked  alteration. 

5.  Score  i  for  omission  of  an  essential  part  of  figure. 

(Do  not  score  2  if  an  essential  omission  has  been  part  of  the  result  of  a  curve  in  the 
wrong  direction.) 

It  can  be  seen  that  on  this  scheme  the  lowest  score  is  the  best, 
that  there  can  be  no  score  lower  than  one,  and  that  there  is  no 
maximum  score.  It  should  also  be  noted  that  the  number  of  ex- 
posures required  plays  an  important  part  in  the  final  score. 

The  total  score  made  by  the  twenty  subjects  when  seeing  what 
they  were  drawing  was  381.  This  gives  an  average  of  19.05  for 
each  person,  or  of  38.1  for  each  figure. 

The  total  score  made  by  the  twenty  subjects  when  drawing 
without  seeing  what  they  were  drawing  was  326,  an  average  of 
16.3  for  each  person,  and  32.6  for  each  figure. 

It  may  be  objected  that  the  number  of  exposures  should  not  have 
counted  in  the  summing  up  of  the  results.  Some  of  the  subjects  may 
have  asked  for  more  exposures  than  they  needed,  or  might  have 
made  equally  good  reproductions  with  fewer  exposures  than  they 
actually  requested.  I  feel  that  the  number  of  exposures  must  have 
had  some  effect  upon  the  accuracy  of  reproduction,  though  I  am  not 
quite  satisfied  with  the  particular  method  used  for  exposing  the 
figures,  that  is,  by  means  of  the  tachistoscope.  But  if  we  sum  up  the 
results  and  neglect  the  number  of  repetitions  entirely,  the  relations 
of  the  figures  for  sight  and  blind  methods  is  not  thereby  changed, 
although  the  values  of  the  figures  alter  somewhat. 

The  total  score  for  the  sight  method,  not  taking  the  number  of 
exposures  into  account,  is  130,  and  the  total  for  the  blind  method, 
under  the  same  conditions,  is  120.  The  average  in  the  first  case  is 


326  G.  R.  WELLS 

6.5,  and  in  the  second  case  6.  The  difference  between  the  two 
methods  is  not  so  great  as  when  the  number  of  exposures  is  included 
in  the  score,  but  in  both  cases  the  score  for  reproducing  the  figures 
without  sight  is  lower,  that  is,  is  better  than  when  sight  is  used. 
That  is  to  say,  the  scoring  methods  used  show,  beyond  doubt,  a  some- 
what marked  difference  between  the  accuracy  of  reproductions  made  with 
vision  and  those  made  without  vision,  in  favor  of  the  latter. 

Furthermore,  the  opinions  of  the  subjects,  recorded  at  the  time 
of  the  experiment,  largely  agree  that,  on  the  whole,  it  is  easier  to 
record  the  remembered  figures  without  vision  than  with  vision. 
This  agreement  was  recorded  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  many  of  the 
subjects  were  sure  that  the  records  made  without  vision  were  far  less 
accurate  than  those  made  with  vision,  although  the  final  results  did 
not  bear  out  this  conclusion  at  all. 

Thirteen  subjects  agree  that  the  method  of  reproducing  without 
sight  is  easier  than  with  sight,  and  a  small  minority  of  them  feel  that 
it  is  the  more  accurate  method.  Sometimes  subjects  would  try  to 
explain  the  greater  ease  of  one  method,  usually  the  blind  method,  by 
saying  that  one  set  of  figures  was  easier  than  another.  But  it  is  in- 
teresting to  note  that  in  just  one  half  of  the  cases  where  this  state- 
ment was  made  one  set  was  found  to  be  harder,  and  in  the  other  half 
of  the  cases  it  was  the  other  set  which  was  found  to  be  more  difficult. 
Evidently  it  was  not  the  figures  which  were  difficult,  but  the  method 
of  reproduction. 

Seven  subjects  found  that  reproducing  the  figure  with  vision 
was  easier  than  without.  Several  of  these  subjects  referred  particu- 
larly to  a  difficulty  of  getting  the  proportions  of  the  figure  correct 
when  they  could  not  see  what  they  were  drawing.  It  is  probably 
true  that  it  is  easier  to  get  proportions  correct  by  the  sight  method 
than  by  the  blind  method. 

But  of  the  seven  subjects  who  felt  that  the  easier  method  was  the 
sight  method,  two  essentially  modified  their  statements,  if  they  did  not 
actually  contradict  them,  as  follows:  One  said,  "The  sight  method 
is  easier  than  the  blind  method,  because  it  is  easier  to  visualize  when 
you  can  see  where  the  hand  is  going."  But  during  the  course  of  the 
experiment  he  had  been  heard  to  say  in  slight  exasperation,  while 
working  according  to  the  blind  method,  "Pshaw,  I  looked  under- 
neath it  (i.  e.,  the  screen)  and  lost  it." 

Another  subject  summarizes  the  situation  by  saying:  "It  is  easier 
to  see  what  one  is  doing,  one  gets  an  idea  of  where  one  has  gone. 
But  in  the  blind  method  I  did  it  quicker,  and  drawing  with  sight  the 


MOTOR  REPRODUCTION  OF  VISUALLY  PERCEIVED  FORMS    327 

distraction  caused  the  image  to  be  lost."  It  is  significant  that  "dis- 
traction" should  be  the  word  used  to  describe  the  effect  of  seeing  the 
figure  he  is  reproducing  while  the  reproducing  is  in  progress. 

In  its  results  the  experiment  seemed  to  indicate  that  in  reproduc- 
ing such  cursive  forms  as  I  used,  to  see  what  one  is  doing  is  a  hin- 
drance, rather  than  a  help.  This  conclusion  is  established  in  several 
ways.  Scoring  the  results  in  terms  of  their  accuracy  shows  an 
undoubted  greater  accuracy  in  the  cases  of  the  reproductions  made 
without  sight.  This  would  be  true  with  any  fair  scoring  method, 
I  think,  but  it  becomes  extremely  evident  if  the  number  of  exposures 
of  the  figures  used  as  models  be  taken  into  account  as  well  as  the 
accuracy  of  reproduction.  Further,  the  large  majority  of  the 
subjects,  after  working  with  both  methods,  definitely  prefer  the 
method  without  sight. 

The  observations  here  reported  are  part  of  a  more  extensive  study 
being  made  in  the  Oberlin  laboratory  of  the  comparative  ease  and 
accuracy  of  learning  cursive  forms  by  visual  and  by  kinsesthetic 
perception.  This  experiment,  still  in  progress,  seems  to  show  that 
ease  and  accuracy  of  learning  stand  in  nearly  direct  ratio  to  the 
amount  of  movement  which  is  involved  in  the  learning  process. 
This  may  mean  that  kinsesthetic  imagery  has  peculiar  advantages  as 
regards  retention  over  visual  or  other  imagery,  at  least  for  many 
people. 

If  this  should  prove  true,  it  is  further  true  in  all  probability  that 
the  distracting  effect  of  observing  the  result  of  one's  effort  while 
trying  to  reproduce  a  figure  recently  seen  is  due  to  the  substitution 
of  visual  for  kinaesthetic  guidance. 

GEORGE  R.  WELLS 
OBERLIN  COLLEGE 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  5  September,  1917 

THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


AN  ATTEMPTED   FORMULATION  OF  THE   SCOPE 
OF   BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY1 

BY  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

The  Johns  Hopkins  University 

COMMON  SENSE  PROCEDURE 

Psychology  a  Science  of  Behavior. — Psychology  is  a  division 
of  science  which  deals  with  the  functions  underlying  human 
activity  and  conduct.  It  attempts  to  formulate  through 
systematic  observation  and  experimentation  a  series  of 
principles  or  laws  which  will  enable  it  to  tell  with  some  degree 
of  accuracy  how  an  individual  or  group  of  individuals  will 
adjust  themselves  to  the  daily  situations  of  life  as  well  as 
to  the  uncommon  and  unusual  situations  which  may  con- 
front them.  It  is  equally  a  part  of  the  function  of  psychology 
to  establish  laws  or  principles  for  the  control  of  human  action 
so  that  it  can  aid  organized  society  in  its  endeavors  to  prevent 
failures  in  such  adjustments.  It  should  be  able  to  guide 
society  as  to  the  ways  in  which  the  environment  may  be 
modified  to  suit  the  group  or  individual's  way  of  acting;  or 
when  the  environment  cannot  be  modified,  to  show  how  the 
individual  may  be  moulded  (forced  to  put  on  new  habits) 
to  fit  the  environment.  It  must  be  understood  at  the  out- 
set, though,  that  psychology  at  present  has  little  to  do  with 
the  setting  of  social  standards  of  action  and  nothing  to  do 
with  moral  standards.  It  does  lie  within  her  province  to  tell 

1  The  material  presented  in  this  article  is  essentially  that  which  will  be  used  in 
the  first  chapter  of  my  forthcoming  book,  'Human  Psychology.'  It  is  published 
now  in  the  hope  that  helpful  criticism  will  be  furnished  the  writer  both  as  regards 
the  level  of  presentation,  that  is,  its  textual  fitness,  and  as  regards  the  completeness 
with  which  the  scope,  as  here  outlined,  touches  the  main  points  of  interest  in  modern 
psychology. 

329 


330  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

whether  the  individual  can  act  in  accordance  with  such  stand- 
ards and  how  we  may  control  him  or  lead  him  to  act  in  harmony 
with  them.  These  laws  of  control  or  training  must  be  general 
and  comprehensive  since  social  standards  are  constantly 
changing.1 

Psychology  when  looked  at  in  this  way  is  seen  to  be  some- 
thing which  everyone  has  been  using  more  or  less  all  his  life 
without  calling  it  psychology.  We  learn  by  failures  and 
successes  how  to  run  our  business,  how  to  get  along  with  our 
colleagues  and  associates.  We  teach  our  children  to  act  in 
certain  ways.  They  must  eat  with  a  fork,  learn  to  dress 
themselves,  to  treat  their  playmates  as  they  themselves  like 
to  be  treated,  to  master  the  three  R's,  and  then  later  a  trade 
or  profession.  We  skillfully  or  bunglingly  steer  them  on 
their  course  from  infancy  until  they  no  longer  need  our 
guidance. 

The  Ancient  Origin  of  Psychology. — Indeed  a  glance  at 
the  mythology,  folk-lore,  or  history  of  any  given  race  will 
show  that  the  practical  psychology  of  control  began  as  soon 
as  there  were  two  individuals  on  the  earth  living  near  enough 
together  for  the  behavior  of  one  to  influence  the  behavior 
of  the  other.  The  serpent  controlled  Eve's  behavior  by 
offering  her  the  delectable  apple.  Eve  learned  her  lesson 
quickly  and  tempted  Adam  in  the  same  way.  Atalanta,  the 
swiftest  of  runners,  was  beaten  not  through  the  superior 
agility  of  Hippomenes  but  by  the  fact  that  she  could  not 
resist  the  temptation  to  stop  and  pick  up  the  golden  apples 
thrown  by  her  suitor.  The  taboo  system,  the  initiation 
ceremonies  and  the  machinations  of  the  medicine  men  all 
serve  to  illustrate  progress  towards  the  control  of  group 
and  individual  behavior. 

Common  Sense  Procedure  in  Securing  the  Control  of  Be- 
havior.— Long  before  the  dawn  of  modern  scientific  psy- 
chology society  found  that  by  roundabout,  hit-and-miss 
methods  she  had  secured  a  fairly  serviceable  body  of  data 
as  to  what  man  can  do — his  complement  of  acts;  the  appro- 
priate situation  for  calling  out  any  given  act;  and  crude 

1  For  a  more  scientifically  worded  discussion  of  the  province  of  psychology  see  p.  336. 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  331 

training  methods  whereby  the  repertoire  of  the  acts  them- 
selves might  be  enlarged.  A  brief  glance  at  the  practical 
procedure  in  securing  control  of  individuals  and  groups 
may  serve  to  illustrate  both  how  such  data  are  obtained  and 
how  they  are  used. 

The  situations  or  devices  for  drawing  crowds  for  whatever 
purpose  show  the  greatest  development  of  skill  in  practical 
psychology.  If  one  or  two  individuals  happen  by  chance 
to  gather  around  a  patent  medicine  vendor  the  vendor's 
momentary  success  is  assured.  The  small  crowd  is  an 
irresistible  stimulus  and  soon  gathers  unto  itself  a  larger 
crowd.  For  this  reason  initial  buyers,  listeners,  applauders, 
and,  yes,  even  sometimes  suitors  and  mourners  are  provided 
and  paid  for  before  the  public  is  allowed  to  act.  The  adver- 
tisement of  a  'fire  sale'  is  likewise  an  ancient  and  honorable 
device  for  gathering  a  crowd.  The  announcement  at  James- 
town of  a  shipload  of  virtuous  women  to  be  sold  as  wives 
apparently,  if  historical  report  can  be  trusted,  brought  out 
the  whole  of  the  unmarried  able-bodied  male  population  of 
Virginia. 

After  the  crowd  has  collected >  devices  for  controlling  the 
individual  are  numerous.  Chief  among  these  we  find  the 
various  lottery  schemes;  many  individuals  will  not  give 
twenty-five  cents  for  a  charitable  purpose,  but  at  any  charity 
gathering  they  will  eagerly  take  one  of  a  dozen  twenty-five- 
cent  chances  on  almost  any  object  the  total  value  of  which 
need  not  be  greater  than  the  cost  of  a  single  chance.  So 
uniform  is  the  response  to  lottery  schemes  that  they  have 
oftentimes  become  national  mediums  for  raising  government 
funds. 

Organized  society  displays  much  ingenuity  in  devising 
situations  for  the  control  of  reaction:  the  clergymen,  having 
found  empty  pews  under  an  orthodox  type  of  routine,  and 
that  the  young  people  were  not  engaging  in  church  activities, 
began  to  try  out  in  a  similar  way  what  could  be  done  by 
altering  the  old  austere  situation  and  by  creating  for  the 
church  entirely  new  situations.  The  exteriors  of  the  churches 
were  vastly  modified,  the  interiors  decorated,  rest  and  play 


332  JOHN  S.  WATSON 

rooms  added  as  well  as  gymnasia  and  playgrounds.  A  certain 
type  of  action  was  expected  and  the  church  arranged  a  situ- 
ation to  bring  it  about.  We  see  the  same  attempt  at  control 
illustrated  in  governing  bodies:  state  legislatures,  depressed 
by  the  prevalence  of  drunkenness  and  crime,  establish  a  new 
situation  by  prohibiting  the  sale  of  drugs  and  spirituous 
liquors  in  the  hope  that  legislation  will  prevent  such  conduct. 
Finally,  mention  may  be  made  of  recent  changes  in  prison 
methods.  The  more  advanced  prisons,  becoming  dissatisfied 
with  the  amount  of  insubordination,  vice,  sloth,  and  ignorance 
of  all  forms  of  government  among  the  inmates,  are  trying  a 
new  situation  with  good  results,  viz.,  that  of  letting  the 
inmates  establish  a  miniature  republic.  This  republic  makes 
its  own  laws  and  metes  out  its  own  punishments.  Society  has 
developed  a  system  of  standards  of  action  but  it  does  not  know 
just  what  situations  will  produce  the  needed  responses.  The 
situations  are  set  up  in  the  social  field  by  trial  and  error; 
they  are  modified,  changed,  etc.,  until  the  desired  reactions 
take  place,  or  until  they  are  despaired  of. 

Watching  the  Act  to  Obtain  Data  on  the  Situation. — We 
thus,  as  we  see,  get  a  part  of  our  knowledge  of  the  factors 
underlying  behavior  by  the  trial  and  error  method  of  manipu- 
lating the  situation  and  noting  the  reactions  that  take  place. 
This  gives  us  a  body  of  usable  data  on  what  to  expect  of  men 
when  they  are  placed  in  certain  situations.  We  deal  here 
with  situations  of  our  own  contrivance.  Equally  serviceable 
results  are  obtained  by  taking  an  individual  who  is  performing 
some  act  (action  not  regulated  by  the  observer)  and  ex- 
amining immediately  into  the  situation  which  led  to  that 
act — the  act  is  known,  the  situation  which  led  to  it  must  be 
investigated.  This  method  is  of  course  supplementary  to 
the  first.  It  extends  our  knowledge  of  situations  and  what 
to  expect  from  them,  and  at  the  same  time  adds  to  our 
knowledge  of  man's  repertoire  of  acts.  Illustrations  of  the 
results  of  this  type  of  practical  procedure  are  numerous; 
it  is  hard  to  convince  a  mother  that  she  cannot  predict1  what 

1  By  prediction  we  mean  nothing  but  the  common-sense,  scientific,  and  logical 
use  of  material  gathered  from  observation  and  experimentation.  The  planet  Neptune 
was  predicted,  Mendelian  ratios  are  predictable,  coat  color  or  eye  color  of  animals 
can,  within  certain  limits,  be  predicted  before  the  birth  of  the  animal. 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  333 

the  situation  is  which  leads  her  baby  to  give  a  certain  cry. 
Depending  upon  the  variations  in  the  cry  she  will  say  that 
the  'baby  is  hungry,  wet,  or  has  colic'  (her  conclusions  are 
often  wrong,  be  it  said).  Advancing  somewhat  in  the  age 
scale  we  see,  in  passing  through  a  forest,  a  youth  trained  to 
hunt  firing  upward  into  a  tree,  and  we  note  that  the  dog  he 
has  with  him  has  '  treed.'  An  observer  responds  to  this 
picture  by  telling  his  companion  that  the  boy  is  hunting 
squirrels.  But  if  he  sees  the  boy  fire  in  another  way,  say 
horizontally,  and  sees  a  dog  in  the  act  of  pointing,  he  will 
state  that  the  lad  is  hunting  quail.  If  the  boy  fires  towards 
the  ground  and  has  a  hound  with  him,  he  is  shooting  rabbits. 
Finally,  if  he  is  seen  in  the  hunting  fields  on  horseback,  with 
no  gun  but  accompanied  by  a  pack  of  hounds,  in  full  cry, 
our  observer  remarks  that  the  boy  is  hunting  a  fox.  Watching 
his  actions  and  taking  note  of  all  attendant  circumstances 
enables  anyone  to  predict  with  some  degree  of  probability 
the  immediate  situation  leading  to  the  boy's  actions.  Our 
ability  to  observe  an  act  and  predict  the  possible  or  probable 
stimulus  to  that  act  depends  upon  the  fact  that  often  during 
our  past  life,  when  we  have  seen  individuals  doing  certain 
things,  we  have  immediately  investigated  the  situations 
which  led  to  the  acts. 

Need  of  Acquaintanceship  with  an  Individual' 's  Past. — 
When  we  come  to  deal  practically  or  scientifically  with  in- 
dividuals too  much  emphasis  cannot  be  laid  upon  the  extent 
to  which  acquaintanceship  with  their  past  life  will  gradually 
afford  the  basis  for  making  serviceable  predictions  as  to 
their  probable  ways  of  acting  and  as  to  the  situations  which 
will  call  out  any  given  act.  This  can  possibly  be  most  easily 
illustrated  in  the  animal  world.  We  soon  come  to  the 
prediction  stage  with  our  horses  and  dogs  and  can  map  out 
with  some  certainty  what  they  would  do  under  the  various 
situations  which  might  confront  them.  After  watching  two 
monkeys  for  several  years  I  found  after  repeated  observation 
that  B  would  not  touch  food  until  /  had  finished  and  left  the 
dish,  and  that  /  would  eat  and  stuff  three  bananas  into  his 
cheek  pouches  and  drag  off  another  with  his  right  forefoot; 


334  JOHN  B.   WATSON 

that  /  would  attack  a  problem  box  rapidly  and  in  a  rough 
and  harum  scarum  way — pulling  the  box  towards  him, 
turning  it  over  and  maltreating  it  generally;  that  B  would 
approach  cautiously,  moving  the  parts  slowly  and  with  no 
violence;  but  as  a  rule  would  solve  the  problem  before  /. 

But  with  an  organism  so  highly  developed  as  man's,  the 
prediction  of  his  actions  is  not  always  so  easy.  An  individual's 
actions  in  everyday  situations  depend  upon  such  complex 
factors  as  his  heredity,  his  past  success  in  adjustments  and 
his  failures  of  adjustment,  the  responses  he  has  just  had  to 
make,  as  well  as  upon  the  permanent  and  temporary  con- 
ditions of  his  organic  mechanisms  (digestion,  circulation, 
sleep,  etc.).  A  badly  cooked  dinner,  an  insufficient  amount 
of  food  (as  in  the  case  of  a  person  who  is  dieting),  extreme 
heat,  etc.,  may  so  change  the  state  of  the  organism  that  the 
response  reasonably  expected  is  not  forthcoming.  A  forth- 
comin^jnarriage,, _  gradujlicin^__£epa  ra  tiojij^joffer  ^situations 
which ,  b^M^iejLr in^iil^^  t 

completely  disrupt  forjthe  timejbeing  the  everyday  systems 
oTTesponses  which  are  customary  with  a  givenindividual. 
In  such  a  complex  setting  a  man  may  show  a  temporary 
breakdown;  he  may  make  blunders  or  show  a  general  in- 
ability to  go  through  with  his  ordinary  routine.  A  bad 
dream  or  a  slight  rebuff  at  the  hands  of  a  friend  likewise 
may  upset  a  man's  reactions  for  a  whole  day.  Further  on  we 
shall  see  that  many  of  the  habits  formed  in  childhood  and  in 
adolescence,  now  long  since  discarded,  such,  e.  g.,  as  attach- 
ments to  early  playmates,  to  members  of  the  family,  early 
love  affairs,  may  have  had  a  prepotent  influence  in  shaping 
the  whole  course  of  adult  acquisitions. 

If  we  are  called  upon  to  predict  what  a  stranger  of  twenty- 
five  years  of  age  will  do  when  confronted  in  a  dark  alley  by  a 
burglar,  we  are  almost,  but  not  quite,  helpless  so  far  as 
prediction  is  concerned.  Now  give  us  an  opportunity  of 
systematically  studying  the  make-up  of  the  man,  of  knowing 
something  of  his  reactions  in  past  dangerous  situations,  the 
stability  of  his  emotional  tendencies,  and  we  shall  be  able 
at  least  to  make  a  crude  but  serviceable  prediction,  viz., 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAFIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  335 

that  he  will  quietly  throw  up  his  hands  and  let  the  burglar 
go  through  his  pockets.  He  will  neither  become  hysterical, 
attempt  to  attack  the  burglar,  nor  will  he  suffer  any  severe 
after-effects  by  reason  of  his  experience.  The  chances  are 
good  that  he  will  report  his  mishap  to  the  police,  confess  to 
his  wife  or  friends  that  he  has  been  held  up,  and  then  will 
cease  to  be  further  troubled  by  the  experience.  In  another 
type  of  individual,  whose  heredity  is  questionable,  whose 
reactions  are  unstable,  who  is  generally  excitable  and  liable 
to  over-reaction,  we  venture  the  prediction  that  even  if  he 
does  throw  up  his  hands  (which  he  does  not  always  do) 
and  allow  himself  to  be  robbed,  he  will  go  to  pieces  after 
the  experience  and  may  suffer  some  serious  and  lasting  conse- 
quences. 

Common  Sense  a  Crude  but  Genuine  Psychology. — Most  of 
our  illustrations  have  involved  little  or  no  technical  psy- 
chology and  yet  they  do  illustrate  a  genuine  psychological 
procedure.  The  business  man,  the  artist,  and  the  artisan 
have  built  for  themselves  rather  definite  rules  of  psycho- 
logical procedure  without  ever  calling  it  psychology.  The 
church  and  the  theater  illustrate  this  equally  well.  It  is 
possibly  even  a  debatable  question  whether  common  sense 
has  not  kept  closer  to  the  fundamental  truth  underlying  the 
psychology  of  reaction  than  has  the  too  detached  psychology 
of  the  laboratory.  But  even  those  who  are  the  best  practical 
psychologists  realize  that  common  sense  methods  can  never 
produce  universal  or  widespread  progress  in  psychology. 
Our  great  military  leaders,  our  great  religious  leaders,  the 
demagogues  and  the  politicians  have  accomplished  their 
results  by  their  very  wide  acquaintanceship  with  the  reaction 
tendencies  in  man  and  by  their  happy  accidents  in  creating 
the  situations  which  will  call  out  such  reactions.  By  reason 
of  the  fact  that  occasional  success  has  been  obtained  by 
crude  methods  and  happy  accidents,  we  must  not  conclude 
that  psychology  should  not  attempt  to  discover  and  analyze 
and  bring  under  scientific  control  the  factors  which  have 
occasionally  made  such  successes  possible.  Because  there 
has  been  an  occasional  business  leader  who  knew  how  to 


336  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

pick  out  and  keep  good  men,  we  are  offered  no  reason  why 
we  should  not  seek  to  understand  and  control  the  processes 
involved  in  picking  and  keeping  good  men.  The  same  may 
be  said  of  the  factors  involved  in  keeping  men  out  of  crime, 
keeping  them  honest  and  sane,  and  their  ethical  and  social 
life  upon  a  high  and  well-regulated  plane. 

This  brief  summary  of  the  everyday  uses  of  psychology 
should  convince  us  of  two  things;  first,  that  common  sense, 
while  a  reasonable  method  so  far  as  it  goes,  does  not  go 
far  enough  and  never  can;  and  secondly,  that  in  order  to  make 
progress,  the  phenomena  of  human  behavior  must  be  made 
an  object  of  scientific  study.  We  shall  attempt  next,  then, 
to  gain  some  impression  of  this  systematic  psychological 
procedure. 

SCIENTIFIC  PROCEDURE 

The  Detailed  Subject  Matter  of  Scientific  Psychology. — As  a 
science  psychology  puts  before  herself  the  task  of  unravelling 
the  complex  factors  involved  in  the  development  and  regu- 
lation of  human  behavior  from  infancy  through  old  age. 
At  first  sight  it  may  seem  that  this  program  leaves  out 
many  of  the  factors  with  which  psychology  ought  to  be 
concerned.  Historically  considered  this  is  true,  but  when  we 
are  confronted  both  with  the  practical  and  scientific  needs 
of  life  we  are  ready  to  admit  that  after  all  what  we  seek  to 
have  psychology  busy  herself  with  is  just  this  matter  of 
environmental  adjustment;  what  can  man  do  apart  from  his 
training;  what  can  he  be  trained  to  do,  and  what  are  the 
best  methods  for  training;  and  finally,  how,  when  the  varied 
systems  of  instincts  and  habits  have  sufficiently  developed, 
can  we  arrange  the  conditions  for  calling  out  appropriate 
action  upon  demand?  To  answer  such  questions  we  must 
necessarily  study  the  simple  and  complex  things  which  call 
out  action  in  man;  how  early  in  life  he  can  react  to  the 
various  simple  and  complex  sense  stimuli;  at  what  age  he 
can  put  on  the  various  instincts  and  what  are  the  situations 
which  call  them  out.  Just  what  are  the  patterns  of  his 
instinctive  acts,  that  is,  does  the  human  being,  apart  from 
training,  do  any  complex  acts  instinctively  as  do  the  lower 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  337 

animals?  If  so,  what  is  man's  full  equipment  of  instincts? 
When  does  emotional  activity  manifest  itself  and  what  are 
the  situations  which  call  it  out,  and  what  special  acts  can  be 
observed  in  emotional  behavior?  How  soon  can  we  observe 
the  beginnings  of  habit  in  infants?  What  special  methods 
can  we  develop  for  rapidly  and  securely  implanting  and 
retaining  the  body  and  speech  habits  which  society  demands? 
Do  we  find  special  and  individual  equipments  in  infants  and 
do  these  develop  and  later  form  the  basis  for  their  entering 
one  kind  of  vocation  or  another,  or  developing  into  one  or 
another  type  of  personality?  Are  there  such  factors  as 
habit  and  instinct  conflicts,  distortion  of  habits  and  emotions? 
How  do  they  manifest  themselves,  and  is  it  possible  to 
develop  methods  for  shaping  the  environment  of  the  indi- 
vidual so  that  such  conflicts  will  not  arise? 

Stimulus  and  Response. — This  general  description  of  the 
subject  matter  of  psychology  helps  us  very  little  as  regards 
the  analysis  of  particular  problems  in  conduct  and  behavior. 
In  order  to  plan  an  experimental  attack  upon  any  problem 
in  psychology  we  must  first  reduce  it  to  its  simplest  terms. 
If  we  look  over  the  above  list  of  subject  matter  and  at  our 
practical  examples  we  see  that  there  are  common  factors 
running  through  all  forms  of  human  acts.  In  each  adjust- 
ment there  is  always  both  a  reaction  or  response  and  a  stimulus 
or  situation  which  calls  out  that  response.  Without  going 
too  far  beyond  our  facts  it  seems  possible  to  say  that  the 
stimulus  is  always  .provided  by  the  environment,  external 
to  the  body,  or  by  the  movements  of  man's  own  muscles 
and  the  secretions  of  his  glands:  finally,  that  the  responses 
always  follow  relatively  immediately  upon  the  presentation 
or  incidence  of  the  stimulus.  These  are  really  assumptions, 
but  they  seem  to  be  basal  ones  for  psychology.  Before  we 
finally  accept  or  reject  them  we  shall  have  to  examine  both 
the  nature  of  the  stimulus  or  situation,  and  of  response. 
If  we  provisionally  accept  them  we  may  say  that  the  goal 
of  psychological  study  is  the  ascertaining  of  such  data  and 
laws  that,  given  the  stimulus,  psychology  can  predict  what  the  / 
response  will  be;  or,  on  the  other  hand,  given  the  response,  it 
can  predict  the  nature  of  the  effective  stimulus. 


33  8  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

Use  of  the  Term  Stimulus. — We  use  the  term  stimulus  in 
psychology  as  it  is  used  in  physiology.  Only  in  psychology 
we  have  to  extend  somewhat  the  usage  of  the  term.  In  the 
psychological  laboratory  when  we  are  dealing  with  relatively 
simple  factors  such  as  the  effect  of  ether  waves  of  different 
lengths,  the  effect  of  sound-waves,  etc.,  and  are  attempting 
to  isolate  their  effects  upon  the  adjustments  of  men,  we 
speak  of  stimuli.  On  the  other  hand,  when  the  factors 
leading  to  reaction  are  more  complex,  as,  for  example,  in  the 
social  world,  we  speak  of  situations.  A  situation  is,  of 
course,  upon  final  analysis,  resolvable  into  a  complex  group 
of  stimuli.  As  examples  of  stimuli  we  may  name  such  things 
as  rays  of  light  of  different  wave-lengths;  sound-waves  differ- 
ing in  amplitude,  length,  phase  and  combination;  gaseous 
particles  given  off  in  such  small  diameters  that  they  affect 
the  membrane  of  the  nose;  solutions  which  contain  particles 
of  matter  of  such  size  that  the  taste  buds  are  thrown  into 
action;  solid  objects  which  affect  the  skin  and  mucous  mem- 
brane; radiant  stimuli  which  call  out  temperature  response; 
noxious  stimuli  such  as  cutting,  pricking,  and  those  injuring 
tissue  generally.  Finally,  movements  of  the  muscles  and 
activity  in  the  glands  themselves  serve  as  stimuli  by  acting 
upon  the  afferent  nerve  endings  in  the  moving  muscles 

(P-  341)- 

It  must  be  emphasized  here  that  only  under  the  rarest 
experimental  conditions  can  we  stimulate  the  organism  with 
a  single  stimulus.  Life  presents  stimuli  in  confusing  combina- 
tions. As  you  write  you  are  stimulated  by  a  complex  system 
— perspiration  pours  from  your  brow,  the  pen  has  a  tendency 
to  slip  from  your  grasp.  The  rays  of  light  reflected  from 
the  paper  focus  the  physical  image  of  the  words  upon  your 
retinae.  The  chair  offers  stimulation — the  noises  from  the 
street,  etc.  But  far  more  important,  delicate  instruments 
would  show  that  though  you  are  not  speaking  aloud  your 
vocal  mechanisms — tongue,  laryngeal  muscles,  etc.,  are  in 
constant  motion:  moving  in  habitual  trains,  these  laryngeal 
movements  serve  largely  as  the  stimuli  for  releasing  the 
writing  movements  of  the  hands.  The  fact  that  you  are 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  339 

here  in  the  lecture  room  facing  your  instructor  and  surrounded 
by  your  classmates  is  still  another  very  important  element. 
The  world  of  stimulation  is  thus  seen  to  be  exceedingly 
complex.  It  is  convenient  to  speak  of  a  total  mass  of  stimu- 
lating factors,  which  lead  man  to  react  as  a  whole,  as  a  situ- 
ation. Situations  can  be  of  the  simplest  kind  or  of  the 
greatest  complexity.  It  should  be  noted  here  finally  that 
there  are  many  forms  of  physical  energy  which  do  not  directly 
affect  our  sense  organs.  As  examples  we  may  cite  the  facts 
that  ether  waves  longer  than  760  juju  or  shorter  than  440  juju 
do  not  lead  to  visual  reactions,  and  that  many  of  the  wave 
motions  in  the  air  are  of  such  length  or  amplitude  that  they 
do  not  produce  auditory  stimulation.  The  inability  of  the 
human  organism  to  respond  to  many  possible  forms  of  stimu- 
lation will  be  discussed  later. 

The  General  Nature  of  Response. — In  a  similar  way  we 
employ  in  psychology  the  physiological  term  response,  but 
again  we  must  slightly  extend  its  use.  The  movements 
which  result  from  a  tap  on  the  patellar  tendon,  or  from 
stroking  the  soles  of  the  feet  are  *  simple'  responses  which 
are  studied  both  in  physiology  and  in  medicine.  In  psy- 
chology our  study  too  is  sometimes  concerned  with  simple 
responses  of  these  types,  but  more  often  with  several  com- 
plex responses  taking  place  simultaneously.  In  the  latter 
case  we  sometimes  use  the  popular  term  'act'  or  adjustment, 
meaning  by  that  that  the  whole  group  of  responses  is  inte- 
grated in  such  a  way  (instinct  or  habit)  that  the  individual 
does  something  which  we  have  a  name  for,  that  is,  *  takes 
food,'  *  builds  a  house,'  'swims,'  'writes  a  letter,'  'talks,' 
etc.1  In  working  over  the  distinctions  among  the  various 
types  of  acts  the  speculative  psychologists  have  introduced 
many  needless  technicalities  and  metaphysical  concepts, 
such  as  purpose,  end,  etc.  Psychology  is  not  concerned 

1  But  it  should  be  well  understood  that  whatever  the  man  does  under  stimulation 
is  a  response  or  adjustment — blushing,  increased  heart  beat,  change  in  respiration, 
etc.,  are  definite  adjustments.  We  have  names  for  only  a  few  thousands  of  the  total 
possible  number  of  such  adjustments.  The  term  adjustment  is  used  by  most  writers 
to  refer  to  the  doing  of  one  of  these  named  acts.  In  this  volume  the  terms  adjustment, 
response,  reaction,  etc.,  are  used  almost  interchangeably. 


34°  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

with  these  distinctions.  Because  a  man  fails  by  his  separate 
acts  to  get  his  food,  to  build  his  house,  to  work  out  his  mathe- 
matical problem,  or  to  live  in  harmony  with  his  wife,  is  no 
reason  for  rejecting  him  as  a  psychological  subject.  We  study 
him  for  his  reaction  possibilities  and  without  prejudice-:'  the 
discovery  of  the  fact  that  he  will  make  only  abortive  attempts 
to  meet  and  control  certain  aspects  of  his  environment  is  an 
important  part  of  our  task;  just  as  important  as  being  able 
to  state  that  he  can  make  certain  other  types  of  adjustment. 
'Successful'  adjustments,  'good'  acts,  'bad'  acts,  are  terms 
really  which  society  uses.  Every  social  age  sets  up  certain 
standards  of  action,  but  these  standards  change  from  cultural 
epoch  to  cultural  epoch.  Hence  they  are  not  psychological 
standards.  Reaction  possibilities,  however,  on  the  average 
probably  remain  about  the  same  from  eon  to  eon.  It  lies 
well  within  the  bounds  of  probability  that  if  we  were  able 
to  obtain  a  newborn  baby  belonging  to  the  dynasty  of  the 
Pharaohs  and  were  to  bring  him  up  along  with  other  lads  in 
Boston,  he  would  develop  into  the  same  kind  of  college  youth 
that  we  find  among  the  other  Harvard  students.  His 
chances  for  success  in  life  would  probably  not  be  at  all  differ- 
ent from  those  of  his  classmates.  The  results  obtained  from 
the  scientific  analysis  of  reaction  in  the  human  being  should 
fit  any  cultural  age.  It  is  part  of  the  function  of  the  psycholo- 
gist to  tell  whether  a  given  individual  has  the  reaction  possi- 
bilities within  him  to  meet  the  standards  of  that  cultural 
age,  and  the  most  rapid  way  of  bringing  him  to  act  in  ac- 
cordance with  them.  The  fact  that  social  values  (group 
mores)  change  puts  ever  new  burdens  upon  the  psychologist 
because  every  change  in  the  mores  means  a  different  situa- 
tion to  which  man  has  to  respond  by  a  different  combination 
of  acts,  and  any  new  set  of  acts  must  be  incorporated  into 
and  integrated  with  the  rest  of  the  action  systems  of  the 
individual.  The  problems  put  up  to  psychology  are  those 
of  deciding  whether  the  individual  can  meet  the  new  standards 
and  for  determining  and  developing  methods  of  instructing 
him. 

Motor  and  Glandular  Indicators  of  Response. — What  is  it 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  34* 

that  the  psychologist  can  observe?  Behavior  of  course.  But 
behavior  on  analysis  is  the  separate  systems  of  reactions 
that  the  individual  makes  to  his  environment.  When  we 
come  to  study  the  mechanics  of  such  adjustments  we  find 
that  they  depend  upon  the  integrations  existing  among  the^ 
receptors  and  the  muscles  and  glands. 

The  unicellular  organisms  have  no  separate  muscular  or 
nervous  systems.  Yet  a  part  of  their  one  cell  must  be 
specialized  in  a  motor  as  well  as  in  a  sensory  way,  since  these 
organisms  do  move  in  response  to  stimuli — to  light,  gravity, 
heat,  cold,  electricity,  etc.  As  you  pass  higher  in  the  scale 
special  sense  organ  tissues  (receptors)  develop  and  along  „ 
with  them  both  motor  or  effective  organs,  and  neurones 
connecting  receptors  and  effectors.  Action  in  such  cases 
becomes  sharper,  more  localized,  more  immediate,  and  at  the 
same  time  more  sustained.  Furthermore,  as  we  pass  still 
further  up  the  scale,  glands  begin  to  develop.  Glands  like 
muscles  are  responsive  organs  and  special  glandular  action 
takes  place  whenever  motor  action  takes  place.  The  activity 
of  the  glands  in  turn  reacts  back  upon  the  muscular  system 
and  affects  its  functioning  (p.  338).  Furthermore,  there  are 
two  kinds  of  muscles,  striped  and  unstriped.  The  striped  ' 
muscles  move  the  arms,  legs,  trunk,  tongue,  larynx,  etc. 
The  unstriped  muscles  control  largely  the  blood  vessels, 
intestines,  lungs,  etc.  Usually  when  we  speak  of  response 
we  mean  that  the  organism  goes  forward  to  right  or  left, 
or  retracts  as  a  whole,  that  it  eats,  drinks,  fights,  builds 
houses,  or  engages  in  trade.  But  these  patent  and  easily 
observable  changes  do  not  exhaust  the  term  response,  as 
we  pointed  out  on  p.  339.  We  should  mean  by  response  J 
the  total  striped  and  unstriped  muscular  and  glandular 
changes  which  follow  upon  a  given  stimulation.  Our  problem 
of  the  moment  determines  which  movement  shall  be  studied 
in  relative  isolation;  in  man,  though,  interest  has  been 
largely  centered  in  the  integration  of  separate  responses; 
in  getting  him  to  form  some  habit — that  is,  to  do  something 
with  arms  or  legs  or  vocal  cords.  It  is  important  to  get  at 
the  outset  a  comprehensive  notion  of  response.  A  child  or 


342  JOHN  S.  WATSON 

animal  may  stand  stock  still  under  stimulation,  but  we 
should  not  say  that  there  was  no  response.  Close  observa- 
tion shows  that  there  are  changes  in  the  tension  of  the  muscles, 
in  respiration,  in  circulation,  and  in  secretion. 

General  Classification  of  Responses. — The  various  possi- 
bilities of  reaction  are  thus  seen  to  be  vast;  so  vast  indeed 
that  it  would  seem  at  first  sight  as  though  any  classification 
would  be  impossible.  We  can  at  least  find  a  convenient 
grouping  which  will  serve  us  well  both  for  discussion  and  for 
setting  experimental  problems.  Most  reactions  may  be 
looked  upon  as  falling  into  one  of  four  main  classes : 

1.  Explicit  habit  responses:  as  examples  we  cite  unlocking 
a    door,    tennis    playing,    violin    playing,    building    houses, 
talking  easily  to  people,  staying  on  good  terms  with  the 
members  of  your  own  and  the  opposite  sex. 

2.  Implicit  habit  responses:   ' thinking,'  by  which  we  mean 
subvocal  talking,  general  body  language  habits,  bodily  sets 
or  attitudes  which  are  not  easily  observable  without  instru- 
mentation or  experimental  aid;  the  system  of  conditioned 
reflexes  in  the  various  glands  and  unstriped  muscular  mechan- 
isms, as,  for  example,  conditioned  salivary  reflexes. 

3.  Explicit  instinctive  responses:  including  man's  observ- 
able instinctive  and  emotional  reactions  as  seen,  for  example, 
in  grasping,  sneezing,  crawling,  walking,  etc.,  and  in  fear, 
rage,  love. 

4.  Implicit  instinctive  responses:  this  includes  of  course 
the  whole  system  of  endocrine  secretions,  changes  in  circu- 
lation, etc.,  so  largely  studied  by  physiology.     Here  again 
instrumentation    or    experimental    aid    is    necessary    before 
observation  can  be  made. 

These  various  types  of  response  will  be  studied  in  detail 
in  later  chapters.  The  classification  as  a  whole  should  be 
clear  with  the  possible  exception  of  2,  implicit  habit  responses. 
This  group  is  so  important  and  so  generally  neglected  in 
discussion  that  we  shall  single  it  out  here  for  brief  mention 
in  advance  of  the  chapter  in  which  it  is  entered  into  with 
some  care. 

What  Man   is  Doing   when  Not  Overtly  Acting. — With  a 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  343 

highly  specialized  organism  like  man  even  careful  observa- 
tion often  fails  to  show  any  overt  response.  A  man  may 
sit  motionless  at  his  desk  with  pen  in  hand  and  paper  before 
him.  In  popular  parlance  we  may  say  he  is  idle  or  'thinking,' 
but  our  assumption  is  that  his  muscles  are  really  as  active 
and  possibly  more  active  than  if  he  were  playing  tennis. 
But  what  muscles?  Those  muscles  which  have  been  trained 
to  act  when  he  is  in  such  a  situation,  his  laryngeal,  tongue, 
and  speech  muscles  generally.1  Those  muscles  are  as  active 
and  are  carrying  out  as  orderly  a  system  of  movements  as 
if  he  were  executing  a  sonata  on  the  piano — they  are  doing 
it  well  or  ill  depending  upon  the  training  he  has  had  along 
the  particular  lines  which  engage  him.  While  we  cannot 
at  present  watch  the  play  of  this  implicit  stream  of  words 
there  is  no  reason  for  hypothecating  a  mystery  about  them. 
Could  we  bring  ' thinking'  out  for  observation  as  readily 
as  we  can  tennis  playing  or  rowing,  the  need  of  'explaining' 
it  would  disappear.  We  shall  see  later  that  efforts  have 
been  made  to  bring  such  responses  under  experimental  control. 
But  entirely  apart  from  our  present  unreadiness  to  make 
observation  on  implicit  habits,  we  find  a  certain  way  of  ar- 
riving indirectly  at  the  same  end :  implicit  language  habits,  v 
by  methods  which  we  shall  study,  come  to  issue  finally  in 
overt  action.  By  watching  the  easily  observable  explicit 
habits  and  instincts  of  an  individual  keenly  enough,  and  for  a 
sufficient  stretch  of  time,  and  under  varying  enough  con- 
ditions, we  can  obtain  the  necessary  data  for  most  psycho- 
logical requirements. 

Scientific  Methods  Contrasted  with  Practical  Procedure. — 
Having  now  examined  at  some  length  into  the  general  nature 
of  both  stimulus  and  response,  we  should  be  prepared  to 
understand  the  object  of  a  psychological  experiment  and  to 
contrast  the  scientific  procedure  with  the  common  sense  or 
practical  procedure  which  we  discussed  at  the  beginning  of 
the  chapter.  We  shall  take  up  almost  at  random  some 
definite  illustrative  psychological  problems  and  the  methods 
of  solving  them.  Our  first  problem  is  to  find  out  what  the 

1  Indeed  the  whole  glandular  and  muscular  systems  are  contributory. 


344  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

reactions  of  a  six-months-old  infant  are  to  living  furry  animals. 
We  first  arrange  the  situation  (complex  group  of  stimuli). 
The  infant  is  held  by  its  mother  in  a  well-lighted  room.  We 
observe  first  that  the  infant  is  smiling  and  comfortably  dis- 
posed. Then  one  after  another  we  present  a  white  rat,  a 
dog,  a  cat,  a  white  rabbit,  beetles,  and  a  snake.  We  next 
record  accurately  and  separately  the  responses  to  these  ob- 
jects. The  infant,  which  has  only  learned  to  reach  out  for 
objects  a  short  time  before,  slowly  puts  out  first  one  hand 
and  then  the  other.  The  smile  leaves  his  face  but  no  crying 
or  withdrawing  of  the  hands  or  external  secretions  follow. 
These  are  only  the  more  easily  observed  responses.  Other 
changes  take  place  undoubtedly,  in  the  internal  glands, 
circulation,  respiration,  etc.  It  depends  upon  our  immediate 
problem  as  to  where  the  emphasis  in  observation  shall  fall  in 
our  record  of  reaction  changes.  In  this  case  our  problem 
was  to  determine  whether  there  were  any  overt  instinctive 
tendencies  on  the  baby's  part  to  react  against  or  withdraw 
the  hands  or  whole  body  from  live  animals.  Our  problem 
might  very  well  have  led  us  into  observing  the  changes  in 
the  eyes,  respiration,  blood  pressure,  salivation,  or  in  the 
endocrine  glands,  or  in  several  of  these  at  once.  Again  it 
should  be  noted  that  our  problem  is  not  so  simple  as  it  seems 
at  first  sight.  Suppose  we  had  found  that  the  baby  did  with- 
draw from  the  objects,  began  to  cry,  void  urine,  or  attempt  to 
hide  behind  the  mother's  clothing — could  we  have  concluded 
that  there  was  an  instinctive  reaction  against  live  furry 
animals?  Not  without  delving  into  the  baby's  past.  If  we 
had  had  the  child  under  constant  observation  and  found  no 
record  of  previous  acquaintanceship  with  live  animals,  our 
answer  would  be  that  the  observable  responses  were  probably 
instinctive.  But  if  on  the  other  hand  we  found  that  the  child 
had  been  severely  bitten  by  a  cat  only  two  days  before  our 
test,  our  conclusions  would  have  to  wait  upon  more  extended 
observation.  Nor  can  we,  from  the  behavior  of  this  one  child, 
draw  any  conclusions  as  to  what  other  children  of  the  same 
age  will  do,  or  what  this  child  might  do  at  a  slightly  different 
age  or  when  tested  under  different  conditions;  before  general- 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  345 

izations  can  be  made  many  children  should  be  brought  under 
systematic  observation. 

As  another  example  of  a  somewhat  more  restricted  type, 
let  us  take  the  case  of  a  man  whose  everyday  behavior  has 
led  us  to  suspect  the  normality  of  his  responses  to  mono- 
chromatic  (colored)  light.  Common  sense  has  nothing  to 
say;  it  can  give  no  adequate  report  upon  him.  His  mistakes 
may  be  due  to  one  or  many  things.  We  take  him  into  the 
laboratory  where  monochromatic  light  is  under  control  and 
we  put  him  in  situations  where  he  has  to  react  to  the  lights  in 
pairs,  and  where  each  one  of  the  lights  can  be  widely  varied 
in  energy.  In  the  course  of  the  investigation  we  find  that 
when  there  is  a  certain  energy  relation  obtaining  between 
the  red  and  the  green  lights  he  can  no  longer  react  to  them 
differentially  (that  is  to  say,  they  do  not  offer  different 
stimulating  values).  We  note  further  that  we  can  find  a 
white  light  of  a  certain  intensity  to  which  he  reacts  as  he 
does  to  either  of  the  monochromatic  lights.  But  at  no 
energy  relation  between  any  other  two  colors  can  we  break 
down  his  differential  responses.  We  conclude  after  this 
careful  study  that  the  man  is  red-green  blind,  that  is,  that 
he  reacts  to  red  and  green  as  he  does  to  certain  intensities 
of  white  light.1  Let  us  take  another  example,  and  this  time 
from  the  field  of  vocational  psychology.  Suppose  that  the 
telephone  directory  of  a  large  city  is  getting  entirely  too 
bulky  and  complex  for  men  to  handle  easily.  What  is  the 
best  method  for  obviating  this?  The  telephone  people  and 
the  psychologists  work  together.  The  psychologist  may 
suggest  printing  in  smaller  type  and  four  columns  to  the 
page  instead  of  three.  These  and  many  possible  suggestions 
may  lead  to  a  solution  of  the  problem.  But  the  matter 
has  to  be  put  under  severe  trial  both  before  individuals 
trained  to  look  up  names  in  a  directory  and  before  individuals 
having  no  more  training  than  has  the  general  public.  Syste- 

1  If  we  find  by  repeated  tests  that  the  anomaly  is  more  than  temporary,  we  are 
right  in  advising  this  man  that  he  will  be  handicapped  if  he  enters  certain  occupations, 
e.  g.,  locomotive  and  marine  engineering,  geology,  advertising,  etc.  In  other  words, 
the  results  of  psychological  experimentation  are  as  immediately  practicable  as  are 
results  in  any  other  scientific  field. 


346  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

matic  trial  and  error  is  the  procedure  here  with  statistical 
treatment  of  the  results.  In  the  end  it  is  found  that  a  four- 
column  page  with  a  certain  amount  of  spacing  between  the 
lines  of  print  makes  the  directory  not  only  20  per  cent, 
less  bulky  but  also  one  in  which  the  subscribers  can  find 
names  10  per  cent,  more  rapidly. 

THE  DIVISIONS  OF  PSYCHOLOGY  AND  THE  RELATION  OF 
PSYCHOLOGY  TO  THE  OTHER  SCIENCES 

The  Various  Fields  of  Psychology. — It  is  just  as  difficult  to 
draw  a  hard  and  fast  line  between  the  different  branches 
of  psychology  as  between  the  different  branches  of  biology 
and  physics.  Practical  and  theoretical  interests  determine 
where  a  man  will  throw  the  emphasis  of  his  observation. 
All  scientific  psychology  is  experimental,  or  is  at  least  carried 
out  under  such  conditions  that  rigid  and  controlled  observa- 
tion is  possible.  All  psychology  is  'genetic'  in  the  sense 
that  we  have  to  go  back  to  the  child  and  contrast  it  with 
animals  in  order  to  determine  what  native  systems  of  inte- 
grations belong  peculiarly  to  man.  For  purposes  of  special- 
ization we  speak  of  human  psychology  as  being  made  up  of 
individual,  vocational,  child,  folk,  educational,  legal,  pathological, 
and  social  psychology.  For  our  purposes  we  need  not  enter 
into  a  separate  characterization  of  these  special  branches. 
The  remaining  chapters  in  this  book  attempt  to  deal  generally 
with  the  simpler  results,  problems,  and  methods  in  common 
use  in  psychology.  We  shall  not  emphasize,  except  here  and 
there,  the  particular  branch  to  which  such  material  belongs. 

Relation  of  Psychology  to  Physics. — Both  physiology  and 
psychology  are  dependent  (as  is  every  other  science  at  bottom) 
upon  physics  for  the  control  of  apparatus  and  of  stimulus. 
It  is  essential  for  a  research  student  in  psychology  now  to 
know  the  general  facts  about  wave  motion;  as,  for  example, 
heat,  sound,  and  light.  It  is  important  to  know  how  to 
install  and  use  simple  electrical  instruments,  galvanometers, 
thermal  couples,  and  photometers. 

Relation  to  Neurology. — It  might  be  supposed  that  psy- 
chology would  lean  most  heavily  upon  neurology.  Indeed 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  347 

this  has  been  the  general  assumption  in  the  past.  Psycho- 
logical texts  have  been  overburdened  with  cuts  and  descrip- 
tions of  the  nervous  system  and  we  have  many  works  which 
claim  on  their  title  pages  to  be  physiological  psychology. 
Gradually  we  are  gaining  the  point  of  view  that  the  psycho- 
logical laboratories  cannot  teach  both  psychology  and 
neurology.  Where  a  neurological  laboratory  is  at  hand 
training  in  neurology  should  certainly  be  included,  but  it  is 
doubtful  if  much  can  be  gained  by  a  psychological  student 
from  merely  looking  over  cuts  and  listening  to  lectures  on 
the  subject.  Some  notion  of  the  elements  involved  in  reflex 
arcs  is  certainly  essential — the  way  sense  organs  are  con- 
nected with  the  central  nervous  system  and  the  central 
nervous  system  with  the  muscular  and  glandular  systems. 
In  a  later  Chapter  we  touch  upon  some  of  the  more  elementary 
features  connected  with  the  arrangement  and  functioning  of 
reflex  pathways. 

Relation  of  Psychology  to  Physiology. — It  has  been  claimed 
by  some  that  psychology  is  really  physiology.  That  this 
is  not  the  case  appears  from  even  a  casual  examination  of  the 
respective  scopes  of  the  two  provinces.  Physiology  teaches 
us  concerning  the  functions  of  the  special  organs.  For 
purposes  of  experimentation  and  exposition  the  heart,  liver, 
lungs,  circulation,  respiration,  etc.  are  isolated,  or  are  at 
least  discussed  as  isolated  functions.  All  of  the  functions 
of  the  bodily  organs  are  gone  over  in  this  way.  Muscle-nerve 
preparations  are  taken  out  and  their  properties  investigated. 
It  is  not  meant  to  assume  that  physiologists  deal  wholly 
with  organs  in  isolation.  Certain  combined  processes  are 
studied,  such  as  metabolism,  digestion,  effects  of  poisons, 
etc.,  but  nowhere  in  physiology  do  we  get  the  organism,  as  it 
were,  put  back  together  again  and  tested  in  relation  to  its 
environment  as  a  whole. 

From  our  discussion  of  the  scope  of  psychology  we  are 
now  prepared  to  see  what  when  the  physiologist  has  learned 
all  that  he  can  about  the  functioning  of  the  separate  organs 
of  the  body  of  man,  he  has  encroached  upon  our  field  only 
in  a  very  slight  degree.  Our  task  begins  only  when  the 


348  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

physiologist  puts  the  separate  organs  together  again  and 
turns  the  whole  (man)  over  to  us.  The  physiologist  qua 
physiologist  knows  nothing  of  the  total  situations  in  the 
daily  life  of  an  individual  that  shape  his  action  and  conduct. 
He  may  teach  us  all  there  is  to  know  about  the  mechanism 
of  stepping,  but  it  is  not  his  task  to  determine  whether  man 
walks  before  he  crawls,  the  age  at  which  walking  begins, 
whether  walking  begins  earlier  in  boys  than  in  girls,  or 
whether  defective  children  walk  at  a  later  age  than  normal 
children.  Again,  he  may  teach  us  a  great  deal  about  the 
functions  of  the  kidneys,  the  bladder,  and  of  the  sphincter 
control  of  the  latter;  but  of  the  special  situations  (outside  of 
disease  entities)  which  may  lead  to  incontinence  in  children, 
his  science  teaches  him  nothing,  nor  of  methods  of  controlling 
this  mal-adjustment.  In  studying  psychological  functions, 
for  example,  the  emotions,  it  does  not  help  him  very  much 
to  try  to  picture  what  chemical  and  neural  processes  go  on 
in  the  brain.  It  has  often  been  asserted,  e.  g.,  that  the 
thalamus  is  operative  in  emotional  disturbances.  We  do 
not  get  very  far,  though,  by  trying  to  picture  such  activi- 
ties, or  by  speaking  of  what  goes  on  in  the  individual 
neurones.  We  get  a  very  incomplete  but  a  somewhat  better 
view  if  we  consider  what  goes  on  in  glandular  action 
during  emotional  states.  But  even  glandular  action  is 
not  easily  observed  by  methods  which  are  known  today. 
We  can,  however,  study  the  reaction  states  we  popularly 
call  sadness,  elation,  moroseness,  rage,  fear,  love,  etc.,  from 
the  standpoint  of  what  the  organism  can  do  in  these  states 
and  as  to  whether  the  smooth  running  of  the  general  system 
of  organized  habits  is  facilitated  or  disturbed  by  the  presence 
of  emotional  activity.  We  can,  further,  often  determine 
by  a  study  of  the  life  history  of  the  individual  how  fre- 
quently such  disturbances  come  about  and  can  trace  out 
the  causes  or  factors  leading  to  their  onset.  Physiology  has 
nothing  to  tell  us  of  the  character  and  personality  of  different 
individuals  nor  of  their  emotional  stability  or  lack  of  emo- 
tional control,  nor  as  to  what  extent  their  present  place  in 
life  is  dependent  upon  their  upbringing.  Physiology  tells 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  349 

us  nothing  of  man's  capacity  to  form  and  retain  habits  nor 
of  the  complexity  of  man's  habit  organization.  Hence  if 
we  wish  to  predict  whether  an  individual  is  capable  of  rising 
above  the  environment  to  which  he  is  not  adjusted,  we 
should  have  to  go  to  psychology  and  not  to  physiology  for 
our  answer.  In  thus  emphasizing  the  entire  theoretical 
independence  of  the  two  fields  let  us  not  set  up  a  false  im- 
pression of  antagonism.  Physiology  is  psychology's  closest 
friend  among  the  biological  sciences.  We  can  hardly  move  a 
step  in  psychology  without  using  physiological  data.  But 
in  this  we  are  not  different  from  the  other  biological  sciences, 
or  indeed  from  medicine  itself. 

Overlapping  of  the  Two  Fields. — Occasionally  we  find 
physiologists  who  have  dealt  with  functions  which  overlap 
the  field  of  human  behavior.  As  examples,  we  cite  the 
work  of  Cannon  on  the  bodily  effect  of  violent  emotional 
disturbances,  and  of  Carlson  and  others  on  the  question  of 
the  reactions  which  are  present  in  the  stomach  in  the  absence 
of  food.  Where  the  two  fields  overlap  most,  however,  is 
probably  in  the  study  of  the  nervous,  muscular,  and  glandular 
systems,  and  in  the  realm  of  sensory  physiology.  This  latter 
topic  no  longer  seems  seriously  to  interest  the  physiologists, 
and  where  they  have  shown  interest  in  it,  in  this  country 
at  least,  it  has  been  mainly  pedagogical.  Most  of  the  work 
in  sensory  physiology  has  been  done  by  psychologists.  Until 
the  recent  work  of  Pavlow  and  Bechterew  and  their  students 
physiologists  have  shown  little  interest  in  the  study  of  habit 
formation,  which  general  topic  is  one  of  our  central  ones. 
In  general  it  may  be  said  that  there  is  some  overlapping  in 
the  two  fields,  but  that  this  does  not  keep  them  from  being 
separate  disciplines.  In  cases  where  there  is  an  overlapping 
the  methods  and  points  of  view  of  the  two  sciences  in  no 
wise  differ. 

Relation  of  Psychology  to  Medicine. — Up  to  the  present 
time  psychology  has  been  of  only  slight  service  to  psychiatry 
and  medicine  generally.  It  should  form  a  background  for 
the  whole  field  of  medicine.  But  it  has  dealt  hitherto  so 
largely  with  speculations  and  with  philosophical  considera-^ 


350  JOHN  B.   WATSON 

tions  that  its  usefulness  for  this  purpose  has  been  seriously 
restricted. 

The  physician,  whether  medical  specialist  or  general 
practitioner,  would  like  to  know  something  about  the  method 
of  approaching  and  handling  his  patients.  He  must  en- 
counter— and  he  must  be  prepared  to  encounter — such  things 
as  stubbornness  and  unyieldingness  in  his  human  subjects, 
and  he  must  learn  to  study  his  patients  in  relation  to  their 
present  environment,  and  to  go  back  into  their  life  history 
for  an  understanding  and  explanation  of  such  attitudes.  He 
must  learn  how  to  size  up  his  patients  and  to  get  at  the 
details  of  their  individuality  and  characteristics.  He  must 
be  able  to  tell  whether  the  patient  can  do  what  he  is  told 
to  do,  and  whether  he  has  sufficient  assets  to  meet  the  en- 
vironment in  which  he  has  to  live,  and  whether  he  has  suf- 
ficient assets  to  rise  out  of  the  environment  which  is  un- 
satisfactory to  him.  These  facts  on  character  adaptation 
cannot  be  expressed  in  any  other  terms  than  behavior  terms. 
These  are,  to  be  sure,  factors  which  concern  everyone  who 
has  to  deal  with  his  fellow-man,  but  on  account  of  the  intimate 
relationship  existing  between  the  patient  and  his  physician 
they  are  of  especial  importance  to  the  latter.  The  psychi- 
atrist has  not  neglected  these  factors;  indeed,  it  has  been  due 
to  him  that  they  have  been  emphasized  at  all,  and  it  is  largely 
through  his  efforts  that  we  have  a  well-developed  and  syste- 
matic technique  for  isolating  the  factors  of  importance  in 
the  life  history  of  the  patient.  In  so  far  as  psychiatry  is 
concerned  I  think  we  can  say  that  the  psychology  the  psychi- 
atrist uses  is  not  different  from  the  psychology  we  are  trying 
to  study.  The  psychiatrist  has  to  be  both  a  physician  with  a 
specially  developed  therapeutic  technique,  and  a  psychologist 
with  special  interests  in  certain  divisions  of  psychology. 
Psychiatry  has  no  special  need  for  detailed  studies  on  reac- 
tions to  sensory  stimuli.  Much  of  the  detailed  work  on 
habit  formation  and  on  the  separate  analysis  of  instincts 
is  not  of  special  use  to  him.  On  the  other  hand,  any  of  the 
material  which  the  psychologist  may  offer  on  the  subjects 
of  attachment  and  detachment  of  the  emotions,  on  the 


SCOPE  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  35 1 

genesis  of  instincts  and  habits  and  their  interrelations,  on  the 
effect  of  age,  drugs,  etc.,  on  habit  formation  and  retention, 
upon  false  reactions  and  failures  in  reactions,  on  the  effect 
of  lesions  of  the  central  nervous  system  in  trained  animals 
and  the  resultant  success  that  comes  from  retraining  them, 
can  be  utilized  by  the  psychiatrist  at  once,  both  in  a  specific 
way  and  by  reason  of  its  value  in  helping  him  to  size  up  his 
patients.  Most  psychiatrists  will  admit  that  when  the 
proper  kind  of  psychology  is  developed  they  can  utilize 
directly  a  large  part  of  both  of  our  methods  and  of  our 
materials.  This  appears  clearly  when  we  examine  the  various 
tests  which  have  been  devised  by  psychologists  for  evaluating 
the  general  behavior  levels  of  individuals.  Such  tests  in  one 
or  another  form  are  in  common  use  in  every  psychiatric  clinic. 
Topics  such  as  *  general  behavior,'  *  stream  of  talk,'  'attitude,' 
'orientation,'  'retention'  of  recent  and  past  happenings, 
'general  information,'  the  emotional  level  at  which  acts  can 
be  carried  out,  etc.,  are  discussed  in  relation  to  every  patient 
admitted  to  a  psychiatric  clinic. 

Preparation  for  Psychology. — In  dealing  with  the  native 
equipment  of  man  the  student  of  human  psychology  will 
find  a  background  of  study  of  animal  behavior  a  helpful  one. 
As  a  further  preparation  for  this  part  of  his  work  he  will 
find  that  he  needs  some  equipment  in  physiology  and  experi- 
mental zoology.  His  work  in  habit  formation  leads  him 
again  into  physiology  and  pharmacology  for  such  factors  as 
the  effect  of  age,  drugs,  etc.,  upon  the  human  organism.  The 
consideration  of  habit  and  instinct  conflicts,  abortive  reac- 
tions and  failures  of  adjustments  generally  which  we  see  so 
well  emphasized  in  tics,  sympathetic  chorea,  hysteria,  ob- 
sessions, etc.,  leads  the  psychologist  into  the  psychiatric 
clinic  if  he  wishes  to  prepare  himself  to  the  fullest  extent. 
Business  and  law  are  making  ever  and  ever  larger  demands 
upon  him.  Some  familiarity  with  legal  and  business  problems 
is  almost  essential.  Finally,  in  order  to  handle  adequately 
experimental  data  some  training  in  the  use  of  statistical 
methods  is  needed.  If  a  start  is  made  early  enough  by  the 
student  who  is  preparing  for  psychology  he  can  obtain  the 


352  JOHN  B.  WATSON 

above  related  branches  before  he  begins  his  special  study  of 
psychology.  While  today  is  a  day  of  specialists  it  should 
not  be  a  day  of  narrow  specialists.  The  tendency  to  have 
information  about  one  small  corner  of  psychology  should 
not  be  encouraged.  It  leads  to  such  anomalies  as  pure 
"mental  testers,"  psychotechnicians,  and  the  like. 


RELATION   BETWEEN   FUNCTIONAL  AND 
BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY 

BY  A.  P.  WEISS 
Ohio  State  University 

The  concept  of  evolution  in  biology  supplemented  the 
purely  descriptive  and  systematic  accounts  of  plants  and 
animals  by  the  introduction  of  a  genetic  and  developmental 
factor.  So  fruitful  did  this  new  outlook  prove  to  be  and 
with  such  audacity  and  effectiveness  did  it  probe  into  the 
cherished  beliefs  of  orthodoxy  that  even  man's  mind  became 
the  object  of  prying  research.  Psychology  was  no  longer 
content  to  study  the  structure  of  mental  states,  but  its 
interests  expanded  so  as  to  include  the  development  and 
genesis  of  mind.  As  experimental  methods  became  more 
prevalent,  the  practical  needs  of  pedagogy  stimulated  interest 
in  the  relationship  between  mind  and  action,  and  this  in 
turn  resulted  in  a  more  critical  analysis  of  behavior  or  con- 
duct. Finally  the  axiomatic  character  of  the  proposition 
'Mind  controls  action'  was  challenged  and  this  introduces 
one  of  the  controversial  points  of  modern  psychology. 

PROBLEM  OF  FUNCTIONAL  PSYCHOLOGY 
The  causes  which  led  to  the  point  of  view  called  func- 
tional psychology  were  the  need  for  a  more  dynamic  principle 
in  the  explanation  of  human  behavior  than  was  offered  by 
the  descriptive  and  systematic  accounts  of  the  nature  of 
mind  as  given  by  the  structural  psychologists.  That  the 
study  of  the  mind  was  of  great  value  in  understanding  human 
behavior  had  never  been  questioned,  but  the  lack  of  uni- 
formity in  terminology  and  the  controversies  on  methodology 
made  it  practically  impossible  to  formulate  the  problem  of 
the  relationship  between  mind  and  action  in  such  a  way 
that  it  could  be  critically  discussed  by  any  considerable 
number  of  psychologists.  As  the  investigations  of  the  sense 

353 


354  A-  P-  WEISS 

organs  and  of  the  nervous  system  increased  the  body  of 
fact  available  for  the  development  of  hypotheses,  the  original 
definition  of  psychology  as  the  science  of  consciousness  was 
extended,  in  spirit  at  least,  to  include  the  neural  correlates 
of  conscious  processes. 

William  James1  was  one  of  the  earlier  psychologists  in  the 
country  who  clearly  foresaw  that  the  investigations  into  the 
relationship  between  the  psychological  faculties  and  human 
conduct  had  been  neglected.  The  shift  of  the  emphasis  from 
the  systematic  treatment  of  consciousness  to  the  investiga- 
tions of  the  conditions  under  which  consciousness  manifested 
itself,  may  be  regarded  as  the  starting  point  of  the  functional 
point  of  view. 

Briefly,  the  problem  of  functional  psychology  may  be 
expressed  in  the  question:  How  does  consciousness  function 
in  human  behavior  or  conduct? 

PROBLEM  OF  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY 
The  origin  of  behavior  psychology  was  largely  due  to  the 
fact  that  functionalism  failed  to  indicate  the  manner  in  which 
a  conscious  process  could  be  regarded  as  controlling  behavior. 
Neither  the  parallelism  nor  the  interaction  of  conscious 
processes  and  physiological  processes  did  more  than  indicate 
a  possible  relation.  These  theories  did  not  show  how  behavior 
was  actually  modified.  The  question,  whether  an  idea  or 
conscious  state  could  bring  about  action  appropriate  to  the 
idea  was  denied  by  many.  Some  psychologists  even  con- 
cluded that  no  form  of  consciousness  whatever  could  alter 
the  direction  of  a  neural  flux,  and  consequently  mere  con- 
sciousness was  not  a  factor  in  behavior  or  conduct.  This 
inevitably  led  to  the  question  as  to  how  human  behavior  did 
actually  come  about  and  those  psychologists  who  questioned 
the  causal  effectiveness  of  consciousness,  formulated  their 
problem  in  the  following  manner:  How  may  the  behavior 
of  man  (or  animals)  be  described  as  solely  due  to  receptor- 
effector  processes  in  the  neuro-muscular  system. 

1  'The  Principles  of  Psychology,'  1890,  Vol.  2,  p.  I. 

"They  (sensations  and  perceptions)  are  therefore  names  of  different  cognitive 
functions  not  for  different  sorts  of  mental  fact." 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  355 

CONSCIOUS  PROCESSES  AS  METAPHORS 

The  lack  of  precision  and  accuracy  in  the  terminology  of 
the  functionalists  was  one  of  the  contributing  causes  in 
differentiating  behaviorism  from' functionalism.  The  func- 
tion of  consciousness  in  behavior  was  accepted  as  a  self- 
evident  fact  that  needed  no  proof.  "That  they  (mental 
phenomena)  lead  to  acts  is  of  course  the  most  familiar  of 
truths,  etc."1  This  was,  of  course,  merely  a  modified  form 
of  faculty  psychology  in  which  the  term  mind  or  conscious- 
ness was  substituted  for  the  term  faculty.  The  following 
quotation  is  representative  of  the  attitude  of  many  function- 
alists so  far  as  the  practical  applications  of  psychology  are 
concerned. 

"The  formation  of  the  elements  of  the  process  of  knowledge 
and  the  inauguration  of  the  control  of  our  movements  in 
accordance  with  the  mandates  of  experience — these  are  the 
two  great  functions  of  perception."2 

If  this  quotation  is  taken  literally,  then  "perceptions" 
must  be  regarded  as  entities  which  inaugurate  and  control 
our  movements.  A  faculty  of  *  perception'  is,  however, 
just  as  unscientific  as  were  the  entities  of  reasoning,  poetry, 
foresight,  etc.,  of  the  faculty  psychologists. 

We  are  warned,  however,  that  the  quotation  is  not  to  be 
taken  literally  but  that  the  faculty  implication  is  merely 
assumed  to  avoid  an  involved  and  cumbersome  terminology. 

"Let  it  be  understood  once  and  for  all  that  wherever  we 
speak,  as  occasionally  we  do,  as  though  the  mind  might  in  a 
wholly  unique  manner  step  in  and  bring  about  changes  in 
the  action  of  the  nervous  system,  we  are  employing  a  con- 
venient abbreviation  of  expression  which  harmonizes  with 
ordinary  everyday  methods  of  thinking  and  speaking  about 
these  relations.  The  real  fact  appears  to  be,  that  whenever 
we  have  mental  activity  we  also  have  neural  activity  in  the 
cerebral  cortex.  The  basal  distinction  in  the  two  kinds  of 
nervous  action  to  which  we  are  referring  in  this  chapter 
(mind,  neural  action  and  habit)  is,  therefore,  not  primarily 

1  James,  Wm.,  'Principles  of  Psychology,'  1890,  Vol.  I,  p.  5. 

2  Angell,  J.  R.,  'Psychology,'  New  York,  1908,  p.  171. 


356  A.  P.  WEISS 

between  a  form  in  which  the  mind  suddenly  produces  changes 
in  the  nerves  as  against  one  in  which  it  does  not,  but  rather  a 
distinction  between  certain  kinds  of  neural  activity  overtly 
involving  consciousness,  e.  g.,  cortical  activity  of  the  cerebrum, 
and  certain  other  kinds  not  overtly  involving  it,  e.  g.,  spinal 
reflexes.  To  use  on  every  occasion  the  long  modifying  phrases 
necessary  to  precise  accuracy  on  this  matter  would  evidently 
be  unduly  cumbrous,  and  so  the  commoner  modes  of  ex- 
pression are  employed,  but  the  fundamental  facts  which  lie 
behind  these  convenient  metaphors  must  not  be  forgotten."1 

One  might  very  well  condone  a  lapse  from  the  "long  modi- 
fying phrases  necessary  to  precise  accuracy"  into  the  "oc- 
casional use  of  convenient  metaphors,"  but  when  the  precise 
accuracy  is  restricted  to  a  few  paragraphs  and  the  occasional 
metaphors  make  up  the  body  of  the  book,  one  is  led  to  wonder 
whether  the  principle  of  faculty  psychology  may  be  con- 
sidered repudiated. 

Passing  aside  the  question  as  to  whether  a  textbook 
written  in  metaphors  can  be  said  to  present  its  subject  matter 
scientifically,  the  more  important  question  as  to  what  are  the 
principles  which  underlie  the  functional  point  of  view  as 
implied  in  the  preceding  quotation,  may  be  formulated  as  two 
propositions: 

1.  There  are  certain  neural  processes  which  overtly  in- 
volve consciousness;  e.  g.,  cortical  activity  in  the  cerebrum. 

2.  There  are  certain  neural  processes  which  do  not  overtly 
involve  consciousness;  e.  g.,  spinal  cord  reflexes. 

It  is  difficult  to  see  how  these  two  propositions  may  be 
used  to  convert  the  metaphors  of  the  following  quotation  into 
the  precise  accuracy  that  is  necessary  for  scientific  under- 
standing. 

"Perception  enables  its  possessor  to  register  in  conscious- 
ness the  particular  object  momentarily  presented  to  the 
senses.  But  if  consciousness  never  advanced  beyond  the 
merely  perceptual  stage  it  is  apparent  that  we  could  never 
develop  any  highly  systematized  and  intelligent  movements 
of  response  to  environmental  demands  and  opportunities. 

1  Angell,  J.  R.,  'Psychology,'  New  York,  1908,  p.  59. 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  357 

Intelligent  deliberation  would  be  impossible.  We  should 
always  live  in  the  immediate  present  and  our  minds  could 
consciously  look  neither  backward  nor  forward.  Now  it  is 
in  the  image  with  its  ability  to  carry  such  prospective  and 
retrospective  meanings  that  we  find  the  psychical  mechanism 
for  accomplishing  both  these  highly  important  functions."1 

The  writer  does  not  wish  to  imply  that  the  functionalists 
are  the  only  group  of  psychologists  who  write  essays  rather 
than  scientific  expositions.  On  the  contrary  the  preceding 
quotation  on  the  function  of  perception  is  considerably  clearer 
than  many  of  the  explanations  of  the  functions  of  mental 
activity  which  are  to  be  found  in  the  literature  of  educational 
and  applied  psychology.  Nevertheless,  just  as  long  as  we 
excuse  ourselves  on  the  plea  that  others  do  it,  and  persist  in 
substituting  rhetoric  for  science,  we  should  not  complain  if 
our  work  is  regarded  with  suspicion  by  the  biologists. 

CONSCIOUSNESS  AND  BEHAVIOR 

Returning  again  to  the  fundamental  principle  underlying 
functional  psychology,  namely,  'that  it  is  mental  activity 
rather  than  mental  structure  that  is  of  immediate  significance 
for  thought  and  conduct'  we  will  make  an  attempt  to  illustrate 
just  what  sort  of  a  relationship  must  exist  between  conscious- 
ness and  behavior  if  the  claims  of  the  functionalists  are  to  be 
substantiated  by  science. 

The  form  of  representation  in  the  following  figure  is 
that  usually  used  to  illustrate  the  theory  of  psychophysical 
parallelism  in  which  action  is  the  result  of  the  stimulation  of 
a  receptor  (S)  of  some  sort.  The  nervous  excitation  which 
results  is  transmitted  over  neurons  indicated  by  solid  lines 
in  the  direction  of  the  arrows,  to  effectors  (M)  which  may  be 
either  muscles  or  glands.  When  the  nervous  excitation 
reaches  these  effectors  contraction  occurs  in  the  case  of  a 
muscle,  and  secretion  in  the  case  of  a  gland.  Consciousness 
in  the  form  of  sensations,  images,  affections,  volitions,  emo- 
tions, etc.,  are  indicated  by  the  dotted  lines.  This  conscious- 
ness is  thought  of  as  accompanying  the  neural  processes. 
10p.  cit.t  p.  215. 


358  A.  P.  WEISS 

The  illustration  thus  represents  the  neural  processes  and  the 
conscious  processes  which  are  said  to  be  correlated  with  them. 
The  diagram  below  represents  the  neural  and  conscious 
conditions  in  the  following  situation:  The  subject  is  passing 
along  a  familiar  road  and  suddenly  comes  upon  a  loose  wire 
dangling  from  a  telegraph  pole.  Let  the  solid  lines  between 
Sa-Ma  represent  the  neurons  which  connect  the  eyes  with 
the  muscles  that  bring  about  the  activity  of  walking.  The 
conscious  processes  which  may  occur  with  the  walking  are 
represented  by  the  dotted  line  parallel  with  Sa-Ma.  If  the 


Wire  Stopping 


Sight  of  Road  WalKing 


FIG.  i 

activity  of  walking  is  completely  habituated  there  may  be 
no  conscious  processes  which  can  be  readily  analyzed.  Let 
the  solid  lines  Sb-Mb  represent  the  neural  processes  from  the 
eyes  to  the  muscles  which  result  in  stopping,  supposing  this 
is  what  happens  as  soon  as  the  wire  is  seen.  These  muscles 
may  of  course  be  partly  the  same  as  those  used  in  walking, 
but  since  walking  and  stopping  represent  different  forms  of 
behavior,  they  have  been  differentiated  in  the  diagram. 
The  dotted  line  parallel  to  Sb-Mb  again  represents  the 
conscious  processes  which  are  correlated  with  the  neural 
processes.  For  any  given  individual  the  elementary  con- 
stituents (sensations,  images  and  affections)  of  the  conscious- 
ness will  vary  but  by  referring  to  it  as  the  'idea  of  danger' 
(from  an  electric  shock)  its  characteristics  are  sufficiently 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  359 

described  for  our  purpose.     Let  this  'idea'  be  represented 
by  (d)  on  the  diagram. 

If  consciousness  controls  behavior  the  functionalist  must 
show  how  the  idea  (d)  acts  on  the  neural  processes  Sa-Ma 
and  Sb-Mb  so  that  most  of  this  neural  flux  will  go  to  Mb 
instead  of  Ma  as  was  the  case  before  the  'idea'  appeared  in 
consciousness.  To  do  this  (d)  must  be  regarded  as  acting 
on  the  neural  processes  at  some  point,  say  at  (c).  The 
problem  is  simply  this:  What  is  the  character  of  the  psychical 
mechanism  which  will  enable  us  to  understand  how  a  psychi- 
cal process  (the  idea)  can  influence  or  change  a  neural  process. 

The  functionalist  cannot  consistently  accept  the  principle 
of  psychophysical  parallelism  in  which  the  conscious  process 
merely  accompanies  a  neural  process  without  acting  on  it, 
since  this  would  repudiate  the  possibility  of  consciousness  in- 
fluencing action.  Some  of  the  functionalists  accept  the 
principle  of  psychophysical  interaction  and  believe  that  the 
4  idea'  does  in  some  way  *  switch'  the  neural  processes,  though 
they  frankly  confess  that  they  do  not  know  how  it  is  done. 

It  might  be  well  to  call  attention  to  the  fact  that  the 
diagram  is  general  in  character  and  that  (d)  may  represent 
any  conscious  process  whatever.  In  the  illustration  (d) 
is  regarded  as  a  perceptual  process,  but  some  functionalists 
maintain  that  the  affective  processes  (satisfaction  and  annoy- 
ance) are  the  only  ones  which  modify  behavior;  others  would 
ascribe  this  modifying  capacity  to  the  emotions  (fear,  rage, 
sentiments,  etc.);  while  still  others  substitute  volitional 
processes  (will,  desire,  wishes).  The  problem,  however,  to 
show  just  in  what  way  these  conscious  processes  act  upon 
the  neural  processes  is  the  same  for  all  and  for  us  it  is  only 
necessary  to  call  attention  to  the  solidarity  with  which  they 
one  and  all  agree  that  they  do  not  know  how  this  interaction 
takes  place. 

The  most  comprehensive  attempt  to  show  that  conscious 
processes  should  be  regarded  as  having  the  power  to  modify 
or  control  neural  activity  has  been  made  by  Wm.  McDougall, 
who  finally  reached  the  conclusion  that  "Of  the  limits  of  the 
power  of  mental  control  over  organic  processes  of  the  body 


360  A.  P.   WEISS 

we  are  altogether  ignorant,  and  new  evidence,  much  of  it 
ill  reported  and  therefore  valueless,  but  much  of  it  above 
suspicion,  repeatedly  warns  us  against  setting  up  any  arbi- 
trary limit  as  to  what  may  be  effected  in  this  way."1 

Most  psychologists  would  be  content  to  determine  the 
limits  of  the  power  of  mental  control  over  organic  processes 
after  it  had  been  demonstrated  that  such  control  was  an 
actual  fact.  It  seems  strange  that  the  functionalists  have 
never  recognized  clearly  that  they  cannot  expect  any  con- 
siderable degree  of  scientific  recognition  until  they  have 
developed  a  working  hypothesis  which  will  enable  them  to 
analyze  any  experience  into  those  mental  and  physical  com- 
ponents which  are  the  essential  condition  of  the  experience. 

This  has  been  a  rather  difficult  task  for  those  who  have 
tried  it  and  a  few  functionalists  have  gone  so  far  as  to  re- 
pudiate psychophysical  interaction.  For  the  latter  only  two 
alternatives  remain:  First,  the  investigation  of  conscious 
processes  as  such,  without  reference  to  behavior;  or  the  point 
of  view  of  structuralism.  Second,  an  investigation  of  be- 
havior independently  of  consciousness;  or  the  viewpoint  of 
behaviorism.  Functionalism  can  only  claim  an  independent 
point  of  view  when  it  has  shown  how  a  mental  process  may 
act  upon  a  neural  process. 

THE  NEURAL  CORRELATES  OF  CONSCIOUSNESS  AND 
BEHAVIOR 

The  relationship  between  consciousness  and  action  toward 
which  functionalism  seems  to  be  moving  regards  the  neural 
correlate  of  consciousness,  rather  than  consciousness  as  such, 
as  the  factor  that  modifies  action.  In  other  words,  when  the 
functionalist  states  that  the  function  of  perception  is  to  con- 
trol action,  this  means  that  it  is  the  neural  correlate  of  per- 
ception that  controls  action. 

Referring  to  the  diagram  of  Fig.  I,  this  would  mean  that 
the  individual  does  not  stop  because  the  'idea  of  danger' 
(d)  acts  on  the  neural  processes  so  that  most  of  the  flux 
reaches  Mb  (stopping)  but  that  the  'idea  of  danger'  had  as 

-  1McDougall,  Wm.,  'Body  and  Mind,'  New  York,  1911,  p.  375. 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  3^1 

its  neural  correlate  the  processes  Sb-Mb  and  it  is  this  neural 
process  (not  the  idea)  which  brought  about  the  stopping. 
This  is  more  clearly  illustrated  in  that  phase  of  functionalism 
in  which  the  affective  processes1  (satisfaction  and  annoyance) 
rather  than  the  perceptual  functions  are  regarded  as  sig- 
nificant for  behavior.  The  neural  correlate  for  satisfaction 
is  held  to  be  the  *  readiness  of  a  neuron  to  conduct'  and  the 
degree  of  conductivity  is  measured  by  the  "  relief  of  inter- 
ference with  the  life  processes  of  the  neurons  concerned."2 
This  theory  seems  to  imply  rather  clearly  that  it  is  the 
neural  correlate  of  satisfaction  (readiness  of  the  neuron  to 
conduct  a  nervous  process)  rather  than  the  subjective  satis- 
faction that  modifies  the  behavior. 

It  is  rather  difficult  to  represent  this  view  on  a  diagram 
such  as  Fig.  I.  The  conscious  process  of  satisfaction  may  be 
represented  by  (d)  and  the  *  readiness  to  conduct'  would  then 
refer  to  the  reduced  resistance  over  the  path  Sb-Mb.  How- 
ever, that  there  is  a  "  relief  of  interference  with  the  life  proc- 
esses of  the  neurons"  can  only  be  maintained  when  it  has 
been  demonstrated  that  the  reaction  Mb  does  actually  occur. 
Since  we  have  no  direct  way  of  predicting  the  metabolic 
conditions  of  the  neurons,  to  infer  from  the  reactions  that 
there  has  been  a  "  relief  of  interference  with  the  life  processes 
of  the  neurons "  does  not  help  us  to  understand  how  the 
increased  *  readiness  to  conduct'  has  been  brought  about. 
This,  of  course,  is  the  problem. 

Whether  we  regard  the  neural  correlate  of  either  cognition 
or  affection  as  significant  for  behavior,  the  fact  remains  that 
the  conscious  processes  themselves  cannot  be  regarded  as 
significant,  because  they  cannot  occur  until  the  neural  con- 
ditions have  been  prepared.  That  is,  at  best  the  conscious 

1Thorndike,  E.  L.,  'Animal  Intelligence,'  New  York,  1911,  pp.  244. 

This  quotation  has  been  selected  because  it  represents  a  point  of  view  which 
ascribes  causal  effectiveness  to  the  conscious  processes  of  pleasantness  and  unpleasant- 
ness rather  than  to  perceptual  processes.  The  actual  working  hypothesis  of  Thorn- 
dike  is  however  much  better  expressed  by  the  following  quotation,  which  is  however 
behavioristic  rather  than  functional  in  principle: 

"Every  response  or  change  in  response  of  an  animal  is  then  the  result  of  the 
interaction  of  its  original  knowable  nature  and  the  environment,"  op.  cit.,  p.  242. 

2  Thorndike,  E.  L.,  'Original  Nature  of  Man,'  1913,  p.  225. 


362  A.  P.  WEISS 

processes  merely  indicate  that  the  neural  conditions  for  action 
have  already  been  established.  The  mental  processes  them- 
selves are  no*  assurance  that  the  appropriate  action  will 
actually  take  place  nor  do  they  indicate  how  the  neural 
conditions  for  the  action  which  actually  does  take  place 
have  been  prepared. 

In  other  words,  the  conscious  processes  follow  the  neural 
processes,  they  do  not  lead  them. 

To  learn  how  the  neural  correlates  of  conscious  processes 
come  to  have  the  configuration  which  they  do,  can  only  be 
done  by  considering  the  properties  of  the  neuro-muscular 
system. 

Some  of  the  functionalists  recognize  this  clearly  enough 
as  a  general  principle,  but  in  the  actual  development  of  their 
subject  matter  they  drop  into  the  terminology  of  psycho- 
physical  interaction  so  naturally  and  with  such  abandon 
that  one  cannot  help  but  feel  that  the  introductory  emphasis 
on  neural  function  is  a  protective  measure  against  criticism 
rather  than  a  working  hypothesis. 

THE  NEURAL  CORRELATE  OF  CONSCIOUSNESS  AND  THE 
NEURAL  CORRELATE  OF  BEHAVIOR 

The  element  of  greatest  confusion  in  the  relationship  be- 
tween consciousness  and  action  is  probably  the  fact  that 
consciousness  has  always  been  regarded  as  an  existential 
datum  entirely  distinct  from  action  or  behavior.  Whatever 
may  be  the  metaphysical  principles  involved  in  the  mind- 
body  problem,  from  the  standpoint  of  science,  consciousness 
must  be  regarded  as  a  reaction.  When  an  observer  reports 
that  he  is  conscious  of  *  danger'  this  only  means  that  the 
muscles  of  his  speech  mechanism  have  contracted  in  such  a 
way  that  sounds  which  we  call  words  and  sentences  are 
produced.  If  the  observer  does  not  react  in  some  way,  we 
cannot  infer  that  he  is  conscious.  That  is,  unless  the  mental 
process  is  expressed  by  speech  (or  some  equivalent  action) 
this  mental  process  can  never  become  available  for  science. 

Consciousness,  as  a  scientific  concept,  may  be  regarded 
as  merely  a  supplementary  reaction  of  a  specific  type  to  a 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  363 

given  situation.  If  for  instance  I  am  asked  "What  is  seven 
times  sixteen?"  I  may,  after  some  hesitation,  simply  pro- 
nounce the  words  "One  hundred  twelve."  If  then  I  am 
asked  to  give  my  introspections,  I  may  add:  "I  had  a  visual 
image  of  the  figures  7  X  10  followed  by  the  visual  image 
of  70  written  on  a  blackboard;  this  was  followed  by  the 
auditory  imagery  —  seven  times  six  ...  forty  two  .  .  .  ; 
then  I  had  auditory  images  with  kinesthesis  of  the  speech 
mechanism  —  seventy  .  .  .  forty  .  .  .  hundred  ten  .  .  .  two 
.  .  .  hundred  twelve  .  .  .  visual  image  of  112  written  on  the 
blackboard." 

We  must  note  that  there  are  two  sets  of  stimuli:  (i)  What 
is  seven  times  sixteen,  (2)  Give  your  introspections.  We 
should  therefore  expect  two  different  reactions.  Why  should 
we  say  that  the  second  reaction  (introspection)  is  of  an 
altogether  different  type  than  the  first?  Every  one  will 
immediately  admit  that  it  is  absurd  to  say  that  the  response 
to  the  second  stimulus  controlled  the  reaction  to  the  first. 
The  facts  in  the  case  are  more  scientifically  stated  when  we 
merely  regard  the  introspective  reaction  as  only  one  of  the 
responses  which  might  be  expected  in  a  situation  of  this 
kind.  It  no  more  controls  or  determines  the  many  other 


Sight  of  Wire  Speech  "Danger"        Stopping 

^  * 


Speech 
Sight  of  Road  \|v)x    Description    WdlKing 

FIG.  2 

responses  that  might  have  been  made,  than  they  control  it. 
The  above  diagram  (Fig.  2)  shows  the  road-wire  situation 
illustrated  in  Fig.   I,  but    drawn  as  a  number  of  reactions 
without  any  hypothetical  conscious  processes. 


364  A.  P.  WEISS 

When  the  stimulus  is  Sb  the  observer  not  only  stops  walk- 
ing (Mb)  but  he  may  also  say:  "That  wire  looks  dangerous, 
I  have  had  one  electric  shock;  last  summer  Mr.  X  was  killed 
in  this  way;"  as  indicated  by  the  speech  reaction  Md.  It  is 
not  necessary  to  conclude  that  being  able  also  to  react  by 
speech  (introspection)  has  anything  to  do  with  stopping 
(Mb).  The  only  essential  condition  for  stopping  is  the 
stimulus  Sb.  The  speech  reaction  Md  has  nothing  to  do 
with  it. 

Before  showing  the  relationship  between  the  neural  corre- 
late of  consciousness  and  the  neural  correlate  of  behavior  we 
will  consider  the  terms  ' major'  and  'minor'  reaction.  We 
will  assume  that  every  stimulus  or  situation  to  which  an 
organism  adjusts  itself,  may  result  in  more  than  one  reaction. 

Major  reaction:  In  the  first  place  we  have  the  reaction 
which  is  regarded  as  the  appropriate  reaction  or  adjustment 
to  the  particular  situation.  In  our  illustration  this  would 
be  'stopping'  (Mb)  when  the  wire  is  seen. 

Minor  reaction:  Secondly,  there  are  also  other  reactions 
such  as  vasomotor;  respiratory;  changes  in  the  accommoda- 
tion of  the  sense  organs;  speech  reactions,  both  actual  and 
incipient;  etc.  In  our  illustration  these  minor  reactions  may 
be  a  verbal  exclamation  or  introspection  (Md);  decrease  in 
respiration  rate;  increase  in  pulse  rate;  or  any  of  the  many 
bodily  and  visceral  changes  which  might  be  described. 

Simply  stated  the  major  reaction  is  the  one  which  is  sig- 
nificant for  behavior,  while  the  minor  reactions  are  those 
which  are  usually  disregarded.  In  this  sense  the  introspec- 
tive report  would  be  called  a  minor  reaction.  In  the  diagram 
Fig.  2,  Ma  and  Mb  are  major  reactions;  while  MX,  Me,  Md, 
are  minor  reactions.  The  difference  between  Fig.  I  and 
Fig.  2  lies  in  the  fact  that  the  dotted  lines  in  Fig.  I  which 
are  supposed  to  represent  hypothetical  conscious  processes 
have  been  replaced  by  neural  processes.  In  Fig.  2  the 
conscious  process  of  the  'idea  of  danger'  (d,  Fig.  i)  is  repre- 
sented as  the  speech  reaction  Sb-Md.  That  it  must  be 
some  kind  of  a  reaction  if  it  is  to  be  regarded  from  the  sci- 
entific standpoint  seems  clear  when  we  reflect  that  conscious- 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY  365 

ness  which  is  not  expressed  in  some  form  of  reaction,  can 
never  become  available  for  science.  It  is  absurd  to  say 
that  we  may  have  conscious  states  to  which  we  do  not  react. 
The  statement  itself  is  a  reaction.  If  we  admit  this,  then 
every  conscious  state  or  process  is  a  reaction.  The  state- 
ment that  I  have  the  'idea  of  danger'  or  am  *  conscious  of 
danger'  only  means  that  in  addition  to  reacting  to  the  sight 
of  the  wire  by  stopping  I  also  react  to  it  by  saying,  "  I  must 
be  careful;  that  wire  may  be  charged;  etc." 

That  this  speech  may  not  actually  take  place  is  due  to 
the  fact  that  under  ordinary  conditions  we  do  not  react  by 
speech  when  we  are  alone.  If  we  have  some  one  with  us,  a 
child  perhaps,  the  reaction  would  take  place  as  a  warning 
or  protective  movement  of  some  sort.  The  minor  speech 
reaction  Sb-Md  (which  is  the  only  way  in  which  the  term 
consciousness  can  have  a  scientific  meaning)  need  have  no 
control  or  influence  over  the  major  reaction  Sb-Mb.  In  fact 
either  Md  or  Mb  might  very  well  occur  independently. 
They  are  related  only  through  the  receptor  Sb. 

From  the  preceding  we  can  conclude  that  every  stimulus 
which  effects  the  organism  results  in  more  than  one  reaction. 
Only  one  group,  however,  is  usually  regarded  as  socially 
significant  (behavior)  and  we  have  called  it  the  major  reac- 
tion. Along  with  this  major  reaction  there  are  many  minor 
reactions  and  those  of  the  speech  type  are  very  numerous. 
There  is  no  need,  however,  to  believe  that  these  minor  reac- 
tions are  necessary  for  the  adequate  functioning  of  the  major 
reaction. 

CONSCIOUSNESS  AND  INTROSPECTION 

From  what  has  preceded,  introspection  is  merely  a  name 
for  a  group  of  speech  reactions  which  conform  to  a  particular 
terminology.  While  we  are  introspecting  we  not  only  react 
to  a  given  situation  in  a  manner  appropriate  to  the  situation 
(pressing  a  key  for  instance)  but  we  also  react  by  speech  in 
the  terminology  of  psychology.  The  functionalists  have  not 
recognized  that  the  introspective  reaction  is  a  minor  reaction. 
The  social  significance  of  the  major  reaction  has  obscured 
the  fact  that  introspection  itself  is  only  one  of  the  reactions 


366  A.  P.  WEISS 

to  the  particular  situation.  They  have  assumed  that  in 
some  way  it  reveals  what  is  taking  place  in  the  neural  corre- 
late of  the  major  reaction.  The  development  of  this  intro- 
spective reaction  is  a  process  of  habit  formation  just  as  any 
other  variation  of  response.  It  is  not  the  expression  of  a 
metaphysical  entity  (consciousness)  that  has  been  added  to 
the  major  reaction. 

The  only  difference  between  psychological  observation  and 
observation  in  the  natural  sciences  lies  in  the  fact  that  in 
psychology  the  introspective  reaction  is  regarded  as  the  major 
reaction,  while  in  the  natural  sciences  it  is  regarded  as  a  minor 
reaction  or  ignored  entirely.  However,  neither  the  major 
nor  the  minor  reactions  can  be  said  to  control  or  modify  each 
other  and  in  this  sense  there  is  no  mind-body  problem. 

FUNCTIONALISM  OBSCURES  THE  NATURE  OF  THE  PSYCHO- 
LOGICAL PROBLEM 

It  is  not  supposed  that  the  nature  of  the  preceding  dis- 
cussion will  be  considered  especially  new  by  the  function- 
alists. Their  excellent  experimental  work  in  pedagogy  and 
the  emphasis  they  place  upon  habit  formation  irrespective 
of  any  subjective  implication,  indicates  that  practically  at 
least  they  are  following  behavioristic  methods. 

The  importance  for  general  psychological  theory  as  to 
whether  human  behavior  is  regarded  as  the  result  of  the 
interaction  between  a  hypothetical  consciousness  and  neural 
processes  or  as  the  result  of  neural  mechanism  only,  lies 
primarily  in  the  fact  that  the  experimental  program  will 
reflect  which  of  these  points  of  view  is  adopted. 

If,  as  the  functionalists  assume,  consciousness  can  modify 
behavior,  then  to  bring  about  socially  acceptable  behavior 
in  the  child,  for  instance,  it  is  only  necessary  to  bring  about 
those  forms  of  consciousness  which  are  effective.  The  prob- 
lem then  becomes  one  of  teaching  *  ideals.'  From  the  peda- 
gogical standpoint  an  ideal  must  be  regarded  as  a  plan  of 
action  or  conduct.  If  the  expressions  of  consciousness  are 
used  as  a  test  as  to  whether  a  given  set  of  ideals  has  been 
established  there  will  be  a  tendency  to  place  undue  emphasis 


FUNCTIONAL  AND  BEHAVIOR  PSYCHOLOGY 

upon  verbal  expression,  since  where  a  serious  attempt  is 
made  to  determine  the  character  of  consciousness  intro- 
spection must  play  an  important  part.  The  problem  of 
teaching  ideals  then  becomes  one  primarily  of  establishing 
formal  speech  reactions  to  given  situations.  While  for  many 
situations  in  life  a  speech  reaction  is  the  adequate  reaction 
there  are,  however,  many  other  situations  in  which  speech 
alone  is  inadequate,  as  for  instance  in  many  ethical  relations. 
In  such  instances  the  verbal  expressions  of  the  ideals  are  no 
assurance  that  the  socially  valuable  reaction  has  been  learned. 
On  the  other  hand  the  socially  desirable  reaction  cannot  be 
learned  by  merely  establishing  the  speech  reaction  which 
describes  the  appropriate  behavior.  JThe  behaviorist  main- 
tains that  it  is  better  to  disregard  the  concept  of  conscious- 
ness altogether  and  the  pedagogical  problem  then  becomes 
one  of  determining  exactly  how  socially  acceptable  behavior 
is  developed  directly  from  the  properties  of  the  neuro- 
muscular  system.  If  a  verbal  reaction  is  part  of  the 
appropriate  adjustment,  well  and  good;  it  must  be  learned. 
However,  after  it  has  been  learned  there  is  no  advantage 
in  assuming  that  this  verbal  reaction  is  the  function  of  a 
hypothetical  psychical  process. 

BEHAVIORIST  PROGRAM 

Perhaps  the  distinguishing  difference  between  the  func- 
tionalist and  the  behaviorist  lies  in  the  fact  that  the  behavi- 
orist disregards  the  entity  which  the  functionalist  calls  con- 
sciousness. This  does  not  mean  that  the  behaviorist  ignores 
those  problems  in  behavior  with  which  the  concept  of  con- 
sciousness is  usually  associated.  On  the  contrary  by  regard- 
ing man  as  an  organism  he  believes  that  even  the  most 
complex  problems  can  be  described  and  explained  without 
assuming  the  existence  of  any  causes  which  are  not  already 
accepted  by  science  in  general.  The  behaviorist's  principal 
interest  will  be  the  movements  of  man  whether  these  move- 
ments are  of  the  skeletal  muscles  which  carry  his  body  from 
place  to  place  or  the  movements  which  result  in  the  com- 
position of  a  symphony.  He  regards  the  neuro-muscular 


368  A.  P.  WEISS 

system  as  the  means  by  which  the  organism  adjusts  itself 
to  its  environment,  just  as  the  heart,  the  lungs,  digestive 
tract,  are  means  to  keep  the  organism  alive.  To  withdraw 
the  hand  from  the  scorching  candle  is  a  movement  of  only 
less  complexity  than  the  movements  of  the  pen  that  signs  a 
treaty  between  nations.  The  real  object  of  worth  for  the 
behaviorist  is  not  the  thrilly,  fascinating,  esoteric,  pseudo- 
problems  of  the  mystic,  but  the  permanent,  measured  and 
describable  adjustments  of  the  race. 

SUMMARY 

1.  The  axiomatic  character  of  the  statement  'Mind  Con- 
trols Action'  is  questioned  by  the  behaviorists. 

2.  The   metaphorical   explanations   of  the   functionalists 
obscure  the  'faculty'  character  of  their  'mental  activity.' 

3.  The    functionalists    have    never    shown    how    mental 
activity  may  control  action. 

4.  The  conscious  processes  of  the  functionalists  actually 
follow  the  conditions  which  bring  about  a  modification  in 
behavior  and  hence  cannot  be  said  to  control  behavior. 

5.  Consciousness  and  introspection  to  have  any  scientific 
value  must  be  regarded  as  speech  reactions  which  are  re- 
stricted to  the  terms  used  in  psychology.     The  presence  or 
absence  of  these  classes  of  verbal  reactions  in  no  way  influence 
the  socially  significant  reactions. 

6.  The  difference  between  the  natural  sciences  and  psy- 
chology lies  in  the  fact  that  psychology  restricts  its  observa- 
tions to  those  special  speech  reactions  (introspections)  that 
conform  to  the  terminology  of  psychology.     In  the  natural 
sciences  this  class  of  verbal  reactions  is  ignored. 

7.  The  concept  of  a  hypothetical  conscious  process  ob- 
scures the  real  problems  of  psychology. 

8.  Behaviorism  regards  the  introspective  reaction  as  only 
one  of  the  ways  in  which  an  individual  may  react  to  a  situ- 
ation. 


THE    RELATION    BETWEEN    EMOTION    AND    ITS 
EXPRESSION 

BY  HARVEY  CARR 

University  of  Chicago 

This  paper  proposes  a  conception  of  the  nature  of  an 
emotion  in  relation  to  its  expression  which  constitutes  some- 
what of  a  compromise  between  the  theory  of  James  and  the 
older  view  which  it  displaced. 

The  popular  view  assumed  that  some  inner  or  central 
emotional  experience  follows  the  act  of  perception,  and  that 
this  emotion  is  succeeded  by  a  complex  series  of  organic 
disturbances.  The  inner  activity  is  the  emotion  and  the 
resulting  organic  change  is  the  expression  of  that  emotion. 

James  denied  the  existence  of  any  centrally  conditioned 
process  intervening  between  the  perception  and  the  organic 
activities  which  may  properly  be  termed  an  emotion.  James 
asserted  that  the  terms  emotion  and  expression  must  refer  to 
distinctions  within  the  series  of  organic  activities  aroused  by 
the  perception,  and  that  these  activities  are  sensory  and  peri- 
pheral in  character.  As  is  well  known,  James  dichotomized 
these  psychophysical  activities  into  their  conscious  and  their 
material  aspects.  The  experiential  or  non-material  aspect  is 
termed  the  emotion,  while  the  material  or  physiological  aspect 
is  the  expression  of  that  emotion.  As  a  consequence  of  this 
usage  of  terms,  and  of  the  acceptance  of  the  prevalent  doc- 
trine as  to  the  relation  of  consciousness  to  afferent  and  effer- 
ent nervous  impulses,  James  was  forced  to  the  paradoxical 
conclusion  that  the  emotion  is  not  the  cause  but  the  result  of 
its  expression. 

Our  view  agrees  with  that' of  James  in  maintaining  that 
the  terms  emotion  and  expression  must  refer  to  distinctions 
within  the  total  series  of  organic  activities,  and  that  these 
processes  are  peripheral  and  sensory  in  character.  We 

369 


370  HARVEY  CARR 

shall,  however,  adopt  a  radically  different  mode  of  division 
from  that  employed  by  James. 

These  organic  activities  may  first  be  divided  into  three  sets 
of  psychophysical  processes — the  act,  the  emotion,  and  in- 
cidental by-products  of  the  emotion.  In  anger,  the  term  act 
is  applied  to  those  activities  immediately  concerned  in  combat 
— the  fighting  activities.  Flight  or  running  away  is  the  act 
in  fear.  The  term  emotion  refers  to  all  those  prior  and  ac- 
companying organic  processes  whose  function  it  is  to  render 
the  act  more  efficient.  The  emotion  and  the  act  are  to  some 
extent  independent  variables;  theoretically  one  can  fight 
without  being  mad,  and  one  can  become  angry  without 
fighting.  Likewise  one  can  run  away  without  being  afraid, 
and  fear  without  indulging  in  flight.  The  nature  of  the 
emotion  and  its  functional  relation  to  the  act  have  been  well 
depicted  by  Cannon.  In  general  the  emotion  consists  of 
those  processes  by  means  of  which  the  total  energy  of  the 
organism  is  mobilized  and  concentrated  for  the  service  of  the 
act.  The  function  of  anger  is  to  increase  the  efficiency  of 
the  fighting  activities.  A  cause  and  effect  relation  obtains 
between  the  emotion  and  the  act.  The  increased  efficiency 
and  sometimes  the  initiation  of  the  act  are  thus  a  result  of  the 
emotion.  The  total  series  of  processes  involved  in  the  organic 
disturbance  may  also  contain  other  components  which  are 
to  be  regarded  as  the  incidental  but  necessary  by-products 
of  the  emotion  or  the  act,  but  which  contribute  in  no  way  to 
the  efficiency  of  either.  The  trembling  of  anger  or  certain 
digestive  and  nutritive  disturbances  incident  to  the  vasomotor 
shift  may  be  adduced  as  hypothetical  examples. 

These  three  groups  of  activities — the  act,  the  emotion, 
and  their  by-products — constitute  the  whole  of  the  organic 
processes.  There  is  no  fourth  class  which  can  be  termed  the 
act  of  expression.  The  term  expression  implies  a  dichotomy 
of  the  same  organic  activities  from  another  standpoint,  viz., 
their  relation  to  some  observer.  An  emotion  can  express 
itself  only  by  producing  some  effect  upon  an  observer.  With- 
out an  observer  the  term  expression  is  without  meaning. 

The  emotion  can  express  or  manifest  itself  to  an  observer 


RELATION  BETWEEN  EMOTION  AND  ITS  EXPRESSION       37* 

in  three  ways:  (a)  It  expresses  itself  indirectly  through  its 
observable  effects  upon  the  act.  Such  characteristics  as  the 
determination,  vigor,  and  persistence  of  the  fighting  act  are 
observed  and  become  the  sign  and  symbol  of  the  emotion 
of  anger  which  produced  them.  The  increased  efficiency  of 
the  act  thus  constitutes  both  a  result  and  an  expression  of 
the  emotion,  (b)  Any  of  the  observable  by-products  of  the 
emotional  situation  also  constitute  a  mode  of  expression. 
To  an  observer  they  may  symbolize  the  existence  of  the  inner 
emotional  disturbance  of  which  they  are  a  result,  (c)  The 
emotion  also  manifests  itself  to  an  observer  in  a  more  direct 
fashion.  Certain  essential  components  of  the  emotional 
processes,  such  as  the  flushed  face,  the  frown,  and  the  deeper 
breathing  in  anger,  are  directly  observed  and  constitute 
another  mode  of  expression.  The  emotional  process  as  a 
whole  is  not  observed;  only  certain  surface  aspects  of  the 
total  process  are  perceived.  These  perceived  aspects  are 
interpreted  by  an  observer  in  terms  of  his  experience  and 
knowledge  and  hence  become  the  visible  symbols  or  mani- 
festations of  the  emotion  as  a  whole.  A  part  thus  becomes 
the  symbol  of  the  whole,  and  a  symbol  is  a  mode  of  expression. 
Good  usage,  I  think,  will  justify  this  meaning  of  the  term. 
We  may  thus  legitimately  assert  that  the  emotional  activity 
manifests  or  expresses  its  nature  to  an  observer  by  means  of 
these  surface  or  observable  features. 

Our  conception  may  now  be  compared  with  that  of  James. 
Both  are  actuated  by  the  same  purpose.  Both  attempt  an 
expository  definition  of  the  popular  meaning  of  two  terms. 
Both  attempt  a  definition  of  emotion  and  expression  in  de- 
scriptive and  empirical  terms.  Both  agree  that  emotion  and 
expression  must  refer  to  certain  aspects  of  the  organic  activi- 
ties involved  in  the  emotional  situation.  The  two  views 
ascribe  radically  different  contents  to  these  terms.  James's 
analysis  was  dominated  by  the  subjective  conception  of  the 
province  of  psychology  which  prevailed  at  that  time.  An 
emotion  as  a  psychological  phenomenon  must  be  defined  in 
purely  conscious  terms;  the  physiological  aspect  of  the  process 
must  be  discarded.  This  subjective  emotional  experience 


37 2  HARVEY  CARR 

can  naturally  express  itself  to  an  observer  only  through  be- 
havior or  physical  means;  the  behavior,  material,  or  physio- 
logical aspect  of  the  process  must  then  constitute  the  only 
avenue  of  expression.  With  this  conception,  emotion  and 
expression  must  refer  to  the  psychic  and  the  physical  aspects 
respectively  of  the  organic  reaction  to  the  emotional  stimulus, 
and  in  virtue  of  these  definitions  the  emotion  must  be  a  result 
and  not  a  causal  antecedent  of  its  expression.  Our  hypothesis 
rejects  the  purely  subjective  point  of  view  in  psychology,  and 
consequently  discards  this  psychophysical  dichotomy  of 
James.  Both  emotion  and  expression  are  regarded  as  psycho- 
physical  processes,  or  rather  they  are  regarded  as  real  func- 
tional activities  of  a  human  organism  irrespective  of  the  fact 
whether  they  do  or  do  not  contain  a  conscious  component. 
According  to  our  analysis,  these  terms  have  been  so  defined  in 
relation  to  each  other  that  one  can  say  that  the  expression  is 
a  result  of  the  emotion. 

James's  theory  of  emotion  contains  two  more  or  less 
distinct  doctrines  whose  validity  must  be  separately  esti- 
mated. One  of  these,  to  my  mind,  is  correct,  and  the  other 
fallacious.  The  first  doctrine  asserts  that  the  term  emotion 
refers  to  certain  aspects  of  the  organic  activities  and  that  these 
activities  are  essentially  sensory  in  character.  We  have  sub- 
scribed to  this  feature  of  the  theory,  and  we  believe  that  it 
constituted  a  genuine  and  important  contribution  to  the  psy- 
chological thought  of  the  time.  This  aspect  of  the  theory, 
it  is  well  to  note,  is  open  to  empirical  verification;  James's 
various  factual  proofs  and  the  recent  experimental  attempts 
at  a  disproof  are  relevant  to  this  aspect  of  the  Jamesian 
doctrine.  Needless  to  say,  we  believe  that  the  factual 
evidence  at  the  present  confirms  James's  contention. 

The  second  aspect  of  James's  doctrine  consists  of  the 
following  features:  (i)  the  assumption  that  emotion  and  ex- 
pression refer  to  the  psychic  and  the  physiological  components 
respectively,  (2)  the  acceptance  of  the  prevalent  assumption 
as  to  the  relation  of  the  psychic  to  its  physiological  correlates, 
and  (3)  the  final  conclusion  that  the  emotion  is  the  result  of 
its  expression. 


RELATION  BETWEEN  EMOTION  AND  ITS  EXPRESSION       373 

It  must  be  at  once  admitted  that  this  conclusion  is  logically 
valid  and  unassailable  from  the  standpoint  of  the  prior  assump- 
tions. Neither  is  the  proposition  susceptible  to  experimental 
proof  or  disproof.  James's  formidable  list  of  factual  proofs 
is  not  relevant  to  this  phase  of  the  argument.  His  conclusion 
is  logically  implicit  in  his  assumptions;  it  represents  merely 
the  result  of  a  deductive  analysis  of  what  was  contained  in 
his  premises.  James  assumed  the  truth  of  this  conclusion 
when  he  made  his  preliminary  definitions.  A  rejection  of 
one  of  these  assumptions  constitutes  the  only  avenue  of 
escape  for  those  who  dislike  the  final  conclusion. 

This  aspect  of  James's  theory  contains,  to  my  mind,  two 
essential  defects,  (i)  The  conclusion  contradicts  common 
sense,  and  this  contradiction  is  due  to  the  fact  that  James 
ascribes  to  the  term  *  expression'  a  meaning  which  is  directly 
antagonistic  to  the  significance  usually  attached  to  it.  As 
previously  noted,  the  term  expression  popularly  signifies 
some  effect  of  the  emotion  upon  an  observer,  and  James  has 
arbitrarily  so  defined  the  term  as  to  reverse  this  causal 
relation.  (2)  James's  analysis  and  conclusion  are  also  lacking 
in  pragmatic  value.  His  mode  of  treatment  gives  us  no 
analytical  comprehension  of  the  functional  interrelations 
between  the  various  constituents  of  the  organic  activities, 
nor  of  their  nature  and  significance  in  relation  to  mental  life 
and  conduct.  The  conclusion  resulting  from  James's  mode 
of  analysis  is  logically  true  and  valid,  but  the  knowledge  it 
represents  lacks  genuine  significance  and  worth. 

In  spite  of  varied  criticism,  James's  theory  has  enjoyed  an 
enviable  reputation  for  many  years.  Several  factors  have 
probably  contributed  to  this  result,  (i)  Unless  the  two 
phases  of  the  argument  are  differentiated,  one  is  compelled 
either  to  adopt  or  reject  the  theory  in  toto,  and  undoubtedly 
to  many  minds  the  advantages  of  the  theory  outweigh  its 
deficiencies.  (2)  As  we  have  noted,  James  was  driven  to  his 
psychophysical  distinction  by  the  adoption  of  the  subjective 
conception  of  the  province  of  psychology.  Likewise,  James's 
theory  will  of  necessity  make  a  strong  appeal  to  those  whose 
thought  is  dominated  by  this  attitude  of  mind,  and  the 


374  HARVEY  CARR 

conventional  definitions  of  the  subject  matter  of  psychology 
have,  until  recent  years  at  least,  been  couched  in  subjective 
terms.  If  emotion  is  a  psychological  phenomenon,  it  must  be 
defined  in  conscious  terms.  Expression,  on  the  other  hand, 
must  be  conceived  in  behavioristic  or  physiological  terms, 
because  expression  must  refer  to  some  effect  upon  an  observer. 
(3)  The  paradoxical  character  of  the  conclusion  is  a  third 
factor.  The  popular  mind  is  somewhat  prone  to  judge  the 
value  and  worth  of  a  science  upon  the  basis  of  the  novelty 
and  startling  character  of  its  discoveries.  The  wonders  of  a 
science  are  paraded  in  proof  of  its  amazing  progress  in  attain- 
ing its  ends.  These  discoveries  are  frequently  wonderful  and 
startling  simply  because  of  their  novelty  and  unexpectedness, 
—because  they  contradict  or  modify  prevailing  conceptions 
and  opinions.  Psychology  as  a  young  and  growing  science 
must  also  produce  its  miracles  in  order  to  secure  popular 
acclaim  to  its  worth  and  greatness,  and  what  can  be  more 
wonderful  and  miraculous  than  the  discovery  and  labored 
empirical  demonstration  of  a  truth  which  directly  contradicts 
the  common  sense  opinion  of  mankind?  As  psychologists, 
I  fear,  we  have  been  somewhat  susceptible  to  this  influence, 
and  this  suggestible  attitude  of  mind  has  probably  been  streng- 
thened to  some  extent  by  our  experience  in  the  classroom.  I 
know  of  no  doctrine  in  psychology  which  is  comparable  with 
that  of  James's  theory  of  emotion  from  the  standpoint  of 
inculcating  in  the  mind  of  the  average  undergraduate  a 
wholesome  awe  and  respect  for  the  achievements  of  our 
science.  This  chapter  of  James  almost  invariably  makes  a 
profound  impression  upon  the  student  mind,  and  the  reason 
is  not  far  to  seek,  for  it  consists  of  a  very  clever  and  brilliant 
exposition,  and  a  persuasive  logical  and  empirical  demon- 
stration of  the  truth  of  a  proposition  which  many  students 
accept  with  some  degree  of  mental  reservation. 

In  place  of  James's  psychophysical  analysis,  this  paper 
suggests  a  threefold  division  of  the  organic  activities  on  the 
basis  of  their  causal  interrelations.  The  act  refers  to  those 
processes  of  adaptation  to  the  objective  situation.  The 
emotion  refers  to  those  activities  which  increase  the  effective- 


RELATION  BETWEEN  EMOTION  AND  ITS  EXPRESSION       375 

ness  of  the  act.  The  remaining  processes  consist  of  incidental 
by-products  of  the  emotion  or  the  act.  There  is  no  coordinate 
fourth  group  of  processes  which  can  be  termed  the  expressive 
activities.  The  term  expression  implies  a  dichotomy  of 
these  same  activities  from  a  different  standpoint — their 
relation  to  an  observer.  The  larger  and  more  important 
portion  of  the  emotional  group  of  processes  can  not  be  directly 
observed;  their  nature  and  existence  must  be  inferred  from 
those  aspects  of  the  organic  activities  which  are  susceptible 
to  immediate  observation.  Certain  aspects  of  all  three  of  the 
previously  enumerated  classes  constitute  a  sign  or  symbol  of 
the  existence  of  these  hidden  operations,  and  consequently 
become  the  means  by  which  these  latter  manifest  or  express 
themselves  to  an  observer. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE   SOCIAL  FORCES 

BY  H.  G.  KENAGY 

University  of  Minnesota 

It  has  been  said  that  "the  corner  stone  of  sociology  must 
be  a  sound  doctrine  of  the  social  forces."1  With  certain 
limitations  this  statement  may  be  allowed  to  stand.  In  the 
first  place,  pure  science,  as  such,  does  not  admit  of  the  use 
of  the  term  *  force'  in  the  sense  of  the  sufficient  cause  of 
any  phenomena,  physical  or  social.2  Taken  to  mean,  how- 
ever, only  an  active  factor  in  a  given  situation,  'force'  is  in 
common  usage  in  the  physical  sciences  and  has  been  borrowed 
by  the  social  sciences  for  want  of  a  better  term.  At  best  it 
is  only  a  helpful  analogy.  In  the  second  place,  a  'sound 
doctrine'  of  the  social  forces  must  not  be  taken  to  mean 
or  imply  an  'exhaustive,  logical  or  psychological  classifica- 
tion' of  the  factors  active  in  social  life  (as  has  generally 
been  done  by  the  older  sociologists),  for  the  progress  of 
scientific  knowledge  of  human  society  is  not  dependent  upon 
success  in  any  such  classification.  Indeed,  as  Dr.  Bernard 
has  pointed  out,  "the  most  accurate  possible  classifications 
[of  social  forces]  mark  only  the  most  elementary  stage  in  the 
analysis  of  social  phenomena."3  Professor  Ross's  statement, 
therefore,  interpreted  or  limited  in  these  respects,  comes  to 
mean  simply  that  an  understanding  of  what  are  the  active 
factors  in  social  life  is  necessarily  basic  in  any  scientific 
study  or  discussion  of  social  situations  and  institutions- 

What  are  the  active  factors  in  social  life?  Some  sociolo- 
gists would  limit  them  to  forces  which  are  social  in  their 
origin;  others  would  include  all  factors,  whatever  their  origin, 
which  are  socializing  in  their  effects.  Professor  Baldwin 

1  Ross,  E.  A.,  'Foundations  of  Sociology,'  p.  181. 

2  See  article  by  Prof.  E.  C.  Hayes,  'The  Social  Forces  Error,'  in  Amer.  J.  of  Soc., 
16,  613-625. 

3  Bernard,  L.  L.,  'The  Transition  to  an  Objective  Standard  of  Social  Control,' 
p.  74. 

376 


"HE   THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCED 

limits  his  definition  to  'only  those  psychical  products,  called 
desires,  which  influence  individuals  in  their  social  relations';1 
Professor  Ellwood,  much  more  sanely,  uses  the  term  to  in- 
clude *  every  factor  which  has  some  degree  of  active  influence 
in  shaping  and  molding  the  forms  of  association  and  the  inter- 
action of  individuals.'2  Accepting  this  latter  definition,  as 
the  more  adequate  of  the  two,  we  are  forced  to  include  among 
the  social  forces  such  physical  factors  as  climate,  soil,  and 
other  geographical  conditions.  To  primitive  men  these 
environmental  conditions  were  much  more  important  than 
they  are  today,  for  civilized  man  has  brought  his  environment 
largely  under  his  control.3  Heredity  and  variation  must  also 
be  included  as  active  factors.  True,  they  are  not  direct 
factors,  and,  assuming  a  strict  psychological  interpretation 
of  society,  they  become  factors  in  the  organization  of  society 
only  by  setting  up  conditions  or  limits  within  which,  and 
only  within  which,  the  more  strictly  social  forces  may  act.4 
At  any  one  moment,  perhaps,  the  forms  of  social  life  seem 
to  depend  much  more  upon  mental  elements  than  upon 
physical  factors,  but  when  one  surveys  human  groups  over 
long  periods  of  time  the  influence  of  physical  factors  is  more 
apparent.  The  environment  has  acted  indirectly,  selectively, 
upon  man's  hereditary  equipment,  but  also  directly,  through 
such  agencies  as  temperature  for  example,  to  modify  instinc- 
tive and  habitual  responses  of  masses  of  individuals  and  the 
interaction  between  individuals. 

Coming  now  specifically  to  a  discussion  of  the  psycho- 
logical factors  or  forces  in  association,  we  may  agree  at  once 
with  Dr.  Ellwood  that  these  consist  of  man's  innate  impulses 
(instincts),  his  feeling  states,  and  his  cognitive  or  intellectual 
processes.5  This  assumes,  apparently,  the  existence  of  a 

1  Baldwin,  J.  M.,  'Social  and  Ethical  Interpretations,'  p.  484. 

2  Ellwood,  C.  A.,  'Sociology  in  its  Psychological  Aspects,'  p.  278. 

3  Thomas,  W.  I.,  'Social  Origins,'  pp.  130  ff. 

4  See  Baldwin,  op,  cit.,  Appendix  H  v,  p.  573. 

8  Op.  cit.,  p.  282.  The  feelings  and  intellectual  processes  may  enter,  however, 
only  in  their  physical  aspects  as  attitudes  called  out  by  stimuli  and  thereby  influencing 
other  responses  in  the  same  individual  and  in  others.  They  cannot  function  in  this 
connection  purely  as  feelings  and  as  awareness.  We  can  know  of  psychic  states  in 
others  only  by  the  behavior  of  those  individuals.  These  facts  will  be  borne  out  later. 


378  H.  G.  KENAGY 

Asocial  mind'  and  therefore  'social  feeling'  and  'social 
thought'  which  have  the  same  functional  relationship  to 
social  activity  which  individual  feeling  and  thought  have 
to  individual  activity — since  social  activity  is  due  simply 
to  the  interaction  and  coordination  of  individual  activities. 
Necessarily,  therefore,  we  must  decide  first  what  is  the  func- 
tional relation  of  feeling  and  thought  to  individual  activity. 
First  of  all,  however,  we  must  assign  to  instinct  its  proper 
role  in  determining  activity.1  Here  there  is  more  or  less 
agreement.  The  instincts  are  of  first  importance  because 
they  are  primary  in  man  and  serve  in  the  initiation  of  action. 
Human  conduct  can  never  exceed  the  limits  of  these  native 
proclivities  which  assign  for  man  the  ends  of  action  and 
alone  make  any  action  worth  while.2  Man's  native  dis- 
positions to  activity,  however,  do  not  remain  long  unmodified, 
but,  through  interaction  with  the  environment  and  by 
training,  become  overlaid  with  a  mass  of  habits  which  come 
to  function,  under  proper  stimulation,  as  readily  and  as 
actively  as  did  the  original  propensities  to  activity. 

The  moot  point  of  the  whole  theory  of  social  forces  enters, 
however,  at  this  point  of  the  discussion.  The  issue  centers 
around  the  part  which  feeling  plays  in  determining  the  direc- 
tion and  extent  of  the  modification  of  man's  instinctive 
impulses  to  activity.  The  older  view,  held  by  the  hedonists 
from  the  time  ol  Hobbes  to  the  present,  assigns  to  feeling  the 
function  of  a  primary  force,  as  lying  behind  these  instinctive 
activities.  All  action,  individual  and  social,  was  explained 
on  a  basis  of  pleasure  and  pain,  as  the  springs  of  activity 
were  to  be  found  in  calculations  of  agreeable  or  disagreeable 
sensations.3  The  late  Professor  Ward,  the  father  of  Ameri- 

1  By  instinct  is  meant  the  inherited  disposition  to  respond  in  certain  ways  when 
appropriately  stimulated.    This  definition  is  used  so  that  instinct  may  be  taken  as 
synonymous  with  the  whole  "original  nature  of  man,"  and,  for  the  purpose  in  hand, 
is  sufficiently  exact. 

2  See  Veblen,  T.  B.,  'The  Instinct  of  Workmanship,'  Introduction. 

3  See  Hobbes,  'Leviathan,'  Works,  III.,  p.  42;  Locke,  'Essay  Concerning  Human 
Understanding,'  Book  II.,  Ch.  XXL,  Sec.  33,  41;  Bentham,  'Principles  of  Morals 
and  Legislation,'  Chap.  I.,  Sec.  I.;  Spencer,  'Principles  of  Psychology,'  II.,  p.  541; 
Baldwin,  'Handbook  of  Psychology,'  pp.   301-303;  Angell,  'Psychology,'  p.   273; 
Patten,  'Theory  of  the  Social  Forces,'  Chap.  I.,  Sec.  I.;  Ward,  'Psychic  Factors  in 
Civilization,'  pp.  52,  S4>  ^6,  and  'Pure  Sociology,'  p.  132. 


THE   THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  379 

can  sociology,  was  particularly  at  fault  in  this  regard.  To 
quote  short  passages  from  his  works:  "The  dynamic  agent 
consists  wholly  of  feeling;"1  "Feeling  is  a  true  cosmic  force 
.  .  .  and  constitutes  the  propelling  agent  in  man  and  ani- 
mals."2 "In  the  associated  state  of  men,  it  (feeling)  is  the 
true  social  force."3  "The  thinking  faculty  is  not  a  force; 
but  feeling  is  a  true  force  and  its  various  manifestations  con- 
stitute the  social  forces."4  True,  Ward  speaks  of  the  desires 
also  as  a  true  social  force,  but  he  uses  ' desire'  in  the  ' feeling' 
sense,5  saying  that  desire  is  a  form  of  pain. 

There  are  two  other  types  of  writers,  only  partially  or 
not  at  all  hedonistic,  but  individualistic  for  the  most  part, 
who  treat  of  social  forces  as  causes  of  activity  in  one  way 
or  another.  One  class  regards  feeling  as  one,  but  only  one, 
of  the  determining  factors  in  activity.  Those  of  the  other 
type  hold  that  feeling  can  never  be  such  a  cause.6 

What  then  is  the  actual  part  which  feeling  plays  in 
initiating  activity?  The  answer  must  first  of  all  settle  the 
question  of  what  part  consciousness  plays,  if  any,  in  the 
process.  The  better  psychology  at  present  holds  that  mental 
processes  are  conditioned  by  changes  within  the  organism, 
notably  within  the  nervous  system.7  The  more  immediate 
physical  qualities  of  mind  lie  within  the  brain  and  are  deter- 
mined (i)  by  stimulus  and  (2)  by  disposition  or  tendency, 
which  latter  indicates  that  the  "neural  functions  are  deter- 
mined by  the  residues  of  earlier  function  (impressional, 
associative,  determining  and  habitual  tendencies,  and  general 
cortical  set)."8  The  facts  of  perception  are  mainly  to  be 

1 '  Pure  Sociology,'  p.  256. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  39. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  99- 

4  Ibid.,  p.  101. 

5  'Psychic  Factors  in  Civilization,'  pp.  53-54. 

6  Among  writers  of  the  first  class  are  Titchener  (see  his  'Outlines  of  Psychology/ 
p.  250),  Thorndike  (see  his  'Elements  of  Psychology,'  p.  284).     Among  writers  of  the 
second  type  are  James  (see  his  'Psychology,'  II.,  pp.  559,  580),  Dewey  (see  Dewey 
and  Tufts,  'Ethics,'  p.  270),  McDougall  (see  his  'Introduction  to  Social  Psychology,' 

P-  43)- 

7  Bentley,  Madison,  'A  Preface  to  Social  Psychology,'  in  one  of  a  series  of  articles 
entitled  'Studies  in  Social  Psychology,'  in  PSYCHOL.  MONOG.  No.  92,  June,  1916, 
pp.  10  ff. 

s  Ibid.,  p.  10. 


380  H.  G.  KENAGY 

explained  by  stimulus  and  associative  tendency;  passive 
memory  and  imagination  by  associative  and  impressional 
tendencies;  emotion  and  action  by  stimulus  and  determining 
tendency;  skillful  performance  by  habitual  tendency;  and 
thought  by  dispositions  of  the  determining  sort.  In  view  of 
these  facts  we  cannot  admit  that  imagery  is  necessary,  in 
any  causal  way,  even  to  voluntary  activity.  Neither  can 
we  regard  it  as  a  superfluous  or  parallel  process.  Rather, 
imagery  is  the  evidence  of  associations  and  neural  activity 
between  stimulus  and  response.  It  is  these  processes  self- 
aware  in  a  fashion.  The  complete  determinant  of  voluntary 
activity  is  nothing  more  or  less  than  the  total  set  of  the 
nervous  system  of  the  moment,  plus  the  stimuli.  The  total 
cause  of  any  act  is  certainly  more  than  the  conscious  part 
of  it.  A  percept  or  image,  coming  about  when  the  neural 
pathway  or  the  act  is  forced  by  interference  to  run  probably 
through  the  more  complex  channels  in  the  cortex,  is  not  the 
cause  of  the  act  but  only  the  sign  of  the  whole  act  of  which 
it  is  a  part. 

The  same  is  true  of  feeling — it  is  not  the  cause  of  the 
act  but  only  the  sign  of  the  whole  act  of  which  it  is  a  part. 
Says  Dr.  Bernard:  "Feeling  modes  are  resultants  of  internal 
neural  adjustments,  .  .  .  which  correlation  probably  is  made 
in  the  cortex  only  when  feeling  is  experienced.  It  is  absurd 
to  speak  of  these  feeling  modes  as  the  cause  of  such  neural 
correlations."1  Again:  "Feeling  ...  is  the  result  of  the 
correlation,  that  is,  the  supplementation  or  interference,  of 
nervous  processes  in  such  a  way  as  to  increase  the  neural 
activity  along  a  ...  given  pathway.  Where  a  nervous 
process  is  augmented,  pleasantness  is  experienced,  and  where 
a  nervous  process  is  weakened  or  diminished,  there  is  un- 
pleasantness."2 

Professor  Ellwood  professes  to  be  in  sympathy  with  these 
views  as  being  simply  more  exact  statements  than  the  crude 
evolutionary  view  of  feeling  which  he  advances,  and  recon- 

1  Op.  dt.,  p.  37. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  1 8.    This  theory  is  only  a  more  accurate  statement  of  the  theory  of 
feeling  given  by  Max  Meyer  in  his  articles  on  'The  Nervous  Correlate  of  Pleasantness 
and  Unpleasantness,'  in  PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1908,  15. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  3Sl 

cilable  with  it.1  Feeling  to  him  is  however  'an  organic 
valuation  of  our  activities.'2  He  says:  "Society  is  made  up 
of  biological  and  psychological  individuals,  and  these  indi- 
viduals are  thinking,  feeling  men  whose  actions  are  mediated, 
guided  and  controlled  by  feelings  and  ideas."3  Again:  "Feel- 
ings and  ideas  are  not  coextensive  with  activity,"  but  'rela- 
tively new  and  independent  elements'  which  'appear  within 
physiological  activities  at  certain  points  to  evaluate  them, 
mediate  and  control  them.'4  Finally:  "...  social  phe- 
nomena are  in  the  nature  of  responses  to  stimuli,  and  these 
responses  are  modified,  in  the  mature  individual  at  least, 
by  complex  series  of  feelings  and  ideas."5 

To  such  statements  must  be  raised  the  fundamental 
objection  that  they  do  not  in  any  tangible  way  explain  how 
feeling  operates  to  accomplish  its  evaluating  function.  Why, 
for  example,  does  the  pleasurable  act  survive  over  the  other 
acts?  Can  a  successful  result  act  backwards  and  strengthen 
the  impulses  leading  up  to  it  and  stamp  out  the  unsuccessful 
impulses?  Hardly.  Rather,  it  happens  that  "by  the  actual 
overlapping  of  many  tendencies  to  respond  in  diverse  ways 
the  erroneous  tendencies  are  directed  into  the  successful  ones 
and  the  latter  are  strengthened  by  reinforcement.  Without 
such  overlapping  of  various  impulses  in  the  same  general 
response,  the  inhibiting  effects  of  the  successful  upon  the 
unsuccessful  or  irrelevant  tendencies  are  incomprehensible."6 
The  pleasure  accompanying  the  successful  act  as  a  com- 
plete response  is  not  itself  a  cause  or  natural  antecedent  of 
the  surviving  act  but  only  the  inner  or  'felt'  aspect  of  it  and 
therefore  valueless  in  explanation.  The  selectiveness  of  the 
organism,  which  Ellwood  would  call  'feeling  control,'  is 
simply  its  more  easy  adaptation  to  certain  direct  and  indirect 
stimuli  than  to  others,  due  to  inherited  and  acquired  nervous 
correlations.  The  pleasurable  tone  accompanying  certain 

1  Op.  cit.,  footnote  on  pp.  112-13. 

2  Op.  cit.,  Chapter  X.,  p.  247. 

3  Op.  cit.,  p.  250. 

4  Op.  cit.,  p.  250. 

5  Ibid.,  p.  251. 

6  Peterson,  J.,  'Completeness  of  Response  as  an  Explanation  Principle  in  Learn- 
ing,' PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1916,  23,  153-162. 


382  H.  G.  KENAGY 

activities  is  only  a  subjective  indication  that  the  response, 
up  to  a  certain  limit,  follows  the  line  of  least  resistance. 
Certain  acts  are  'chosen,'  because  they  are  on  the  whole  the 
most  natural  to  the  organism  under  the  circumstances,  not 
because  they  are  pleasant.  That  they  are  pleasant,  in  the 
main,  indicates  subjectively  that  the  response  is  relatively 
'complete'  and  in  harmony  with  one's  inherited  and  acquired 
organization. 

As  has  been  shown  experimentally,  some  acts  may  be 
both  pleasureable  and  painful,  painful  alone,  or  without 
conscious  results.  We  may,  again,  experience  pleasantness 
from  higher  sensory  or  ideational  processes  at  the  same 
time  with  pains  from  lower  neural  processes.  Finally,  any 
act  may  be  made  pleasant  or  unpleasant  through  habit. 
Consequently  feeling  modes  cannot  be  effective  guides  to 
individual  or  social  adjustment  and  control.  Ideas,  images 
or  other  subjectivistic  criteria  are  not  always  valid,  says 
Bernard,  and  are  only  dependable  when  checked  up  by  ob- 
jective reference.  "Feeling,"  he  states,  "as  the  conscious 
part  of  mere  correlation,  i.  e.,  supplementation  and  inter- 
ference of  neural  processes,  is  the  least  able  to  be  so  checked 
up  and  is  consequently  the  least  reliable  of  all  subjective 
criteria  or  evaluations  of  action  in  an  objective  and  social 
world."1  Feeling  is  a  purely  personal  and  individualistic 
phenomenon. 

A  similar  problem  to  that  of  determining  the  function  of 
feeling  in  connection  with  the  forms  of  association  and  indi- 
vidual interactions  is  presented  in  establishing  the  role  which 
the  intellect  or  the  cognitive  elements  of  mind  play  in  these 
processes.  Professor  Ellwood  holds  that  "the  distinctive 
character  of  our  social  life  is  due  to  the  modifying  influence 
of  intellectual  elements,"2  and  he  maintains  that  the  intellect 
plays  a  decisive  role  not  only  in  adapting  the  individual 
organism,  in  man  at  least,  to  his  environment,  but  also  in 
bringing  about  those  'higher  adaptations  which  characterize 
civilized  societies.'3  Again,  he  says  that  the  intellect,  the 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  zS,     Practically  the  same  view  is  set  forth  by  Dr.  A.  F.  Bentley. 
See  his  'The  Process  of  Government,'  Chapters  I.  and  II. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  261.  3  Op.  cit.,  p.  261. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  383 

cognitive,  objective  side  of  mind,  'evaluates  activities  with 
reference  to  the  environment  and  functions  to  mediate  and 
control  them  with  reference  to  environmental  factors.'1 
And  finally:  "While  the  intellect  seems  to  have  been  de- 
veloped chiefly  as  an  aid  in  carrying  out  the  instincts  and  in 
satisfying  the  demands  of  feeling,  in  its  higher  reaches  it 
can  and  does  act  more  or  less  independently  of  them."2  By 
this  last  statement  he  means  that  the  intellect  modifies 
instincts,  substituting  habits  for  them  which  become  as 
strong  as  the  original  instincts.3 

Such  passages  seem,  almost,  to  set  up  the  human  mind 
as  a  separate,  supernatural  entity  which  acts  as  a  sort  of 
dictator  to  instinct  and  feeling  and  to  motor  responses. 
This  idea  is  brought  out  more  forcibly  when  he  says  that 
"  more  and  more  the  process  of  living  together  needs  the 
interference  of  reason."4  What  Professor  Ellwood  means, 
however,  seems  to  be  only  that  ideas  have  come  largely  to  be 
the  stimuli  to  activity  among  civilized  peoples.  Reflective 
thought,  which  played  an  insignificant  role  in  primitive 
society,  is  now,  he  thinks,  the  decisive  element  because 
"upon  it  depends  the  control,  not  only  of  the  forces  of  physi- 
cal nature  but  also,  ...  of  the  feelings  and  impulses  of 
human  nature."5  For  this  reason,  and  in  this  sense,  he 
argues  that  ideas  are  entitled  to  be  called  forces,  "since  they 
at  any  rate  become  active  factors  in  the  later  stages  of  social 
evolution  and  absolutely  decisive,  ...  in  the  making  of 
the  more  complex  adjustments."6  These  ideas,  in  civilized 
man  at  least,  come  in  time  to  constitute  for  the  individual 
and  society  a  sort  of  'subjective  environment '  and  to  this 
environment  "the  mass  of  individuals  respond  quite  as  they 
do  to  stimuli  in  the  objective  environment."7  Professor 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  263. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  263. 

3  Practically  the  same  view  of  the  function  of  the  intellect  was  held  by  Ward. 
See  'Pure  Sociology,'  Chapter  XVI. 

4  Op.  cit.,  p.  264. 

6  Op.  cii.,  p.  264. 
« Ibid.,  p.  277. 

7  Ibid.,  p.  265.    The  same  position  is  argued  at  length  in  his  recent  article:  'Ob- 
jectivism in  Sociology,'  in  the  Amer.  J.  of  Soc.,  December,  1916. 


382  H.  G.  KENAGY 

activities  is  only  a  subjective  indication  that  the  response, 
up  to  a  certain  limit,  follows  the  line  of  least  resistance. 
Certain  acts  are  *  chosen,'  because  they  are  on  the  whole  the 
most  natural  to  the  organism  under  the  circumstances,  not 
because  they  are  pleasant.  That  they  are  pleasant,  in  the 
main,  indicates  subjectively  that  the  response  is  relatively 
'complete'  and  in  harmony  with  one's  inherited  and  acquired 
organization. 

As  has  been  shown  experimentally,  some  acts  may  be 
both  pleasureable  and  painful,  painful  alone,  or  without 
conscious  results.  We  may,  again,  experience  pleasantness 
from  higher  sensory  or  ideational  processes  at  the  same 
time  with  pains  from  lower  neural  processes.  Finally,  any 
act  may  be  made  pleasant  or  unpleasant  through  habit. 
Consequently  feeling  modes  cannot  be  effective  guides  to 
individual  or  social  adjustment  and  control.  Ideas,  images 
or  other  subjectivistic  criteria  are  not  always  valid,  says 
Bernard,  and  are  only  dependable  when  checked  up  by  ob- 
jective reference.  "Feeling,"  he  states,  "as  the  conscious 
part  of  mere  correlation,  i.  e.,  supplementation  and  inter- 
ference of  neural  processes,  is  the  least  able  to  be  so  checked 
up  and  is  consequently  the  least  reliable  of  all  subjective 
criteria  or  evaluations  of  action  in  an  objective  and  social 
world."1  Feeling  is  a  purely  personal  and  individualistic 
phenomenon. 

A  similar  problem  to  that  of  determining  the  function  of 
feeling  in  connection  with  the  forms  of  association  and  indi- 
vidual interactions  is  presented  in  establishing  the  role  which 
the  intellect  or  the  cognitive  elements  of  mind  play  in  these 
processes.  Professor  Ellwood  holds  that  "the  distinctive 
character  of  our  social  life  is  due  to  the  modifying  influence 
of  intellectual  elements,"2  and  he  maintains  that  the  intellect 
plays  a  decisive  role  not  only  in  adapting  the  individual 
organism,  in  man  at  least,  to  his  environment,  but  also  in 
bringing  about  those  'higher  adaptations  which  characterize 
civilized  societies.'3  Again,  he  says  that  the  intellect,  the 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  28-     Practically  the  same  view  is  set  forth  by  Dr.  A.  F.  Bentley. 
See  his  'The  Process  of  Government,'  Chapters  I.  and  II. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  261.  8  Op.  cit.,  p.  261. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  383 

cognitive,  objective  side  of  mind,  'evaluates  activities  with 
reference  to  the  environment  and  functions  to  mediate  and 
control  them  with  reference  to  environmental  factors.'1 
And  finally:  " While  the  intellect  seems  to  have  been  de- 
veloped chiefly  as  an  aid  in  carrying  out  the  instincts  and  in 
satisfying  the  demands  of  feeling,  in  its  higher  reaches  it 
can  and  does  act  more  or  less  independently  of  them."2  By 
this  last  statement  he  means  that  the  intellect  modifies 
instincts,  substituting  habits  for  them  which  become  as 
strong  as  the  original  instincts.3 

Such  passages  seem,  almost,  to  set  up  the  human  mind 
as  a  separate,  supernatural  entity  which  acts  as  a  sort  of 
dictator  to  instinct  and  feeling  and  to  motor  responses. 
This  idea  is  brought  out  more  forcibly  when  he  says  that 
"  more  and  more  the  process  of  living  together  needs  the 
interference  of  reason."4  What  Professor  Ellwood  means, 
however,  seems  to  be  only  that  ideas  have  come  largely  to  be 
the  stimuli  to  activity  among  civilized  peoples.  Reflective 
thought,  which  played  an  insignificant  role  in  primitive 
society,  is  now,  he  thinks,  the  decisive  element  because 
"upon  it  depends  the  control,  not  only  of  the  forces  of  physi- 
cal nature  but  also,  ...  of  the  feelings  and  impulses  of 
human  nature."5  For  this  reason,  and  in  this  sense,  he 
argues  that  ideas  are  entitled  to  be  called  forces,  "since  they 
at  any  rate  become  active  factors  in  the  later  stages  of  social 
evolution  and  absolutely  decisive,  ...  in  the  making  of 
the  more  complex  adjustments."6  These  ideas,  in  civilized 
man  at  least,  come  in  time  to  constitute  for  the  individual 
and  society  a  sort  of  'subjective  environment'  and  to  this 
environment  "the  mass  of  individuals  respond  quite  as  they 
do  to  stimuli  in  the  objective  environment."7  Professor 

1  Op.  cit.,  p.  263. 

2  Op.  cit.,  p.  263. 

3  Practically  the  same  view  of  the  function  of  the  intellect  was  held  by  Ward. 
See  'Pure  Sociology,'  Chapter  XVI. 

4  Op.  cit.,  p.  264. 

6  Op.  cit.,  p.  264. 
« Ibid.,  p.  277. 

7  Ibid.,  p.  265.    The  same  position  is  argued  at  length  in  his  recent  article:  'Ob- 
jectivism in  Sociology,'  in  the  Amer.  ].  of  Soc.,  December,  1916. 


3 86  H.  G.  KENAGY 

If  the  mind  is  conditioned,  as  was  shown  above  (p.  5), 
by  stimulus  and  disposition  or  tendency,  the  use  of  such 
expressions  in  connection  with  social  activity  as:  "mind 
'influenced'  by  another  mind,"  "Man  is  *  suggestible'  or 
*  imitative,'"  "one  mind  'rules'  or  'dominates'  and  another 
'acquiesces,'"  etc.,  is  wholly  outside  the  plane  of  scientific 
explanation.  A  stimulus,  as  said  before,  is  a  physical  agent 
and  sets  up  a  series  of  concrete  organic  processes.  'Sug- 
gestion,' 'imitation'  cannot  be  accounted  such  agents  when 
used  to  explain  the  destructive  activities  of  a  mob,  nor  can 
'domination'  or  'sense  of  power'  be  given  as  the  cause  of 
the  acts  of  a  railway  trainmen's  union.  Used  in  such  a 
fashion  such  terms  are  wild  abstractions  used  as  forces,1 
and  are  closely  akin  to  the  'faculties'  of  two  centuries  back. 

'Faculties,'  of  course,  is  unacceptable  for  the  purposes  of 
scientific  explanation,  but  we  also  lack  a  concrete  meaning 
for  'mental  dependence'  or  'mental  interaction'  in  such  a 
statement  as  "individuals  tend  to  believe  and  to  think  and 
to  feel,  etc.,  in  mutual  dependence."  "It  is  obvious,"  says 
Bentley,  "that  the  mind  of  my  neighbor  is  not  to  be  added, 
as  a  condition  of  my  mental  processes,  to  the  sober  and 
authenticated  facts  of  stimulus  and  disposition.  If  my 
neighbor  speaks  with  the  voice  of  authority  and  decision 
and  so  convinces  me  that  I  should  attend  the  meeting  of 
the  Municipal  League,  my  mental  processes  are  set  up, 
after  all,  just  as  they  would  be  if  I  found  a  blight  upon  my 
fruit  trees  and  decided  to  destroy  the  orchard.  Auditory  or 
visual  stimuli  and  associative  tendencies  account  for  the 
perceptual  part  of  either  experience,  and  determining  and 
habitual  tendencies  for  the  performance. 

"The  only  thing  that  is  unique  about  the  conditioning 
factors  in  social  or  mental  dependence  is  the  fact  that  the 
presence  of  other  persons  ...  or  the  assumption  of  them 
.  .  .  touches  off  certain  dispositions  or  neural  tendencies, 
giving  to  our  'social  experiences'  a  certain  kind  of  sig- 
nificance. The  sight  of  the  blighted  fruit  trees  and  the  sight 
and  sound  of  my  persuasive  neighbor  are  psychological 

1  Illustrations  of  this  are  to  be  found  in  Ellwood,  op.  cit.,  pp.  283  ff.,  288;  Ward, 
'Pure  Sociology,'  pp.  256  ff.,  457  ff.;  Ross,  'Social  Psychology,'  p.  13. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  387 

events  of  the  same  order.  There  is  not,  in  the  one  instance, 
the  mere  apprehension  of  an  object;  in  the  other,  the  opera- 
tion of  a  subtle  and  mysterious  force  through  the  agency  of 
which  my  mind  is  wrought  upon  by  my  neighbor's.  Because 
of  my  constitution  and  my  history  the  two  things  are  differ- 
ently apprehended,  have  different  significance,  and  lead  to 
unlike  performances."1 

Classifications  of  the  social  forces  have  been  attempted 
by  sociologists  from  Hobbes,  Fourier  and  Spencer  to  many 
present-day  writers,  and  the  majority  unite  in  placing 
emphasis  upon  the  psychic  factors  or  forces,  though  the 
later  writers  reject  the  old  hedonistic  criteria  and  adopt  the 
functional  view.  However,  with  only  one  important  ex- 
ception,2 all  classifications  have  been  subjective  in  that  the 
content  is  lodged  in  the  individual  consciousness  as  the  source 
of  activities.  What  is  needed  is  a  classification  of  social 
forces  which  does  not  stop  with  consciousness,  real  or  imagin- 
ary, and,  in  so  doing,  cover  up  the  real  and  objective  sources 
of  stimulation  to  activity. 

The  most  complete,  accurate,  and  objective  classifications 
of  the  social  forces  must  constantly  aim  to  point  out,  according 
to  Bernard,  (i)  how  the  individual  acts  or  behaves,  the 
organs  he  uses  and  how  he  uses  them  when  stimulated  in 
known  or  unknown  ways,  and  (2)  how  a  group  acts  or  be- 
haves, the  types  of  control  which  are  exercised  over  individual 
activities  or  behaviors,  in  known  or  unknown  ways.  In  the 
individual  these  may  be  instinctive  or  acquired  (habitual) 
tendencies;  in  the  group  they  may  have  grown  up  uncon- 
sciously through  custom,  or  they  may  have  been  consciously 
legislated  into  existence,  or  taken  on  through  the  pressure 
of  public  opinion,  or  as  a  result  of  scientific  investigation.3 
The  *  causes'  of  activity  under  (i)  have  been  called  'social 

1  Bentley,  op.  cit.,  pp.  11-12. 

2  Recently  a  very  valuable  and  suggestive  inventory  or  classification  of  the  re- 
sponses of  the  original  tendencies  in  man  to  various  classes  or  types  of  stimuli  has 
been  made  by  Professor  E.  L.  Thorndike  in  'The  Original  Nature  of  Man,'  1914.    He 
regards  this,  however,  as  only  a  beginning — as  indicating  the  direction  which  further 
inquiry  must  take  and  the  subject-matter  with  which  truly  objective  classifications 
will  have  to  deal. 

3  See  his  discussion,  op.  cit.,  p.  73  ff. 


388  H.  G.  KENAGY 

forces'  and  the  subjectivists  have  traced  them  back  to  the 
individual  consciousness  and  lodged  them  there,  *  because  the 
individual  is  usually  conscious  of  his  socially  most  con- 
spicuous acts,  and  when  he  is  not  thus  conscious,  conscious- 
ness is  ...  assumed.'1  Thus  the  early  sociologists  stopped 
at  the  sacred  threshold  of  consciousness  and  ended  their 
search  for  social  forces  in  the  forms  of  consciousness.  Only 
recently  has  psychology  pointed  out  that  consciousness  is 
not  ultimate,  but  is  caused,  and  is  only  one  factor  in  adjust- 
ment. The  social  behaviors  under  (2)  have  also,  by  analogy, 
and  with  the  same  subjective  emphasis,  been  called  'social 
forces,'  being  abstracted  for  this  purpose  from  the  unified 
social  situation  and  made  the  product  of  individual  activity. 
The  distinction  was  not  made,  between  'interests'  and  'de- 
sires,' nor  was  it  recognized  that  the  latter  type  of  behaviors 
is  to  be  termed  'social  forces'  with  more  reason  than  the 
former,  since  they  necessarily  go  behind  the  individual 
consciousness  to  some  extent. 

The  passage  from  an  introspective  to  an  experimental  and 
biological  psychology,  with  its  analysis  of  the  conditions  of 
consciousness  and  its  functional  activities  in  making  adjust- 
ments to  the  environment,  has  caused  us — forced  us — to 
look  back  of  the  mere  forms  of  consciousness  in  studying 
social  causation.  Our  search  for  'social  forces'  must  under- 
take to  account  objectively  for  the  activities  of  the  individual 
and  of  the  social  group.  In  actual  practice  we  have  adopted 
this  method.  Thus,  for  example,  we  have  'ceased  treating 
disease  on  a  demonistic  basis,  or  attempting  to  cure  national 
ills  by  public  prayer.'  We  still,  however,  practice  retaliatory 
methods  in  our  criminological  procedures,  and  limit  morality 
in  general  to  the  scope  of  consciousness  or  intention.2 

The  old  classificationists  present  the  subjective  social 
forces  as  only  forms  of  consciousness  by  which  the  conscious 
person  is  made  aware  of  his  own  activities,  while  their  formu- 
lations of  objective  social  forces  are  only  abstractions  for 
presenting  to  ourselves  the  social  processes.  Says  Bernard, 

1  Ibid.,  p.  74. 

2  For  a  critical  discussion  of  this  point  see  Bernard,  op.  cit.,  Introduction. 


THE  THEORY  OF  THE  SOCIAL  FORCES  389 

in  speaking  of  these  abstractions:  "They  are  not  forces;  at 
the  most  they  are  partial  indices  of  social  *  forces'  or  processes. 
Nor  have  they  constant  equivalents;  for  conscious  processes 
and  our  statements  of  social  processes  have  at  different  times 
different  activity  equivalents.  .  .  .  They  are  qualitative 
rather  than  quantitative  indices.  They  merely  invite  to 
always  further  analysis  and  re-analysis  of  the  objective 
social  situation;  and  it  is  on  the  bases  of  these  analyses  that 
all  our  problems  are  to  be  comprehended  and  effectively 
solved.  When  a  situation  is  once  adequately  analyzed, 
when  the  forces  lying  back  of  the  forms  of  consciousness  or 
the  abstracted  and  generalized  types  of  social  and  individual 
activity  are  understood,  the  method  of  the  solution  of  the 
problem  is  simply  that  of  the  application  of  common  sense. 
The  only  mystery  that  there  is  about  the  treatment  of  social 
problems  is  that  which  we  make  by  being  content  to  stop 
with  the  forms  of  consciousness  in  our  analysis.  We  talk 
about  the  riddle  of  personality  as  an  impregnable  barrier  to 
an  adequate  understanding  of  social  conditions,  because  we 
are  attempting  to  work  out  a  logic  of  forces  and  activities 
from  the  kaleidoscopic  presentations  of  our  conscious  proc- 
esses."1 

The  problem  ahead  of  the  sociologists,  then,  according  to 
Bernard,  "  is  to  push  farther  back  the  analysis  of  objective 
phenomena."  Until  sociology  abandons  its  subjective  criteria 
it  cannot  attain  to  true  scientific  efficiency.  "As  psychology 
retreats  from  its  introspective  analysis  of  the  solipsistic  self, 
and  as  ethics  gives  up  mere  intention  as  the  criterion  of 
morality,  so  sociology  must  turn  from  a  subjective  classi- 
fication of  'social  forces'  and  study  the  functioning  of  objec- 
tive social  processes  as  they  operate  in  individuals  and 
groups."2 

SUMMARY 

Sociology,  ethics,  and  the  other  social  sciences  are  in 
need  of  more  tangible  explanations  of  individual  and  social 
action  than  are  commonly  given,  and  they  have  a  right  to 
look  to  psychology  for  a  true  statement  of  the  facts  so  that 

1  Op.  cit.,  pp.  75-6. 

2  Ibid.,  p.  76. 


39°  H.  G,  KENAGY 

all  can  work  on  the  same  plane.  The  terminology  now  in 
common  use  implies  or  postulates  the  possibility  of  stimula- 
tion by  such  subjective  factors  (frequently  referred  to  as 
'forces')  as  'feelings'  and  'ideas,'  though  the  way  in  which 
they  become  stimuli  has  never  been  satisfactorily  explained. 
This  conception  seems  to  have  failed  in  the  explanation  of 
behavior  as  much  as  the  'faculties'  now  supposed  to  be 
discarded  from  psychology. 

All  tangible  stimuli  must  be  of  such  a  nature  as  to  set 
up  nerve  impulses.  They  may  come  from  within  or  from 
without  the  individual.  He  may  be  stimulated  by  external 
things — by  other  persons,  by  spoken  or  written  words  of  his 
language,  by  books,  etc., — or  by  organic  processes  and 
muscular  changes  within  his  own  body.  Organized  stimulus- 
response  systems  as  developed  by  habits  are  important  in 
determining  the  direction  and  the  extent  of  his  responses. 
It  is  inconceivable,  therefore,  how  conscious  states  can  serve 
as  stimuli;  for  all  conscious  states  are  but  imperfect,  sub- 
jective representations  of  stimuli  in  the  objective  world. 
The  customary  usage  thus  involves  one  in  a  vicious  circle. 

In  group  relations,  therefore,  explanations  must  hark 
back  to  stimulus,  disposition,  and  response  instead  of  halting 
upon  the  plane  of  'mental  interaction,'  'suggestion,'  'social 
consciousness'  and  the  like.  The  uniform  action  of  indi- 
viduals in  society  is  due  to  common  sources  of  stimulation, 
to  common  associative  tendencies,  and  to  common  habits, 
overlapping  in  the  generations.  Divergent  reactions  are 
due  to  differences  in  organic  set  or  total  nervous  organiza- 
tion, which  are  the  products  of  more  or  less  unlike  heredity 
and  experiences.  Finally,  the  'intellect'  can  not  be  set  up 
as  a  separate  entity  operating  as  a  force  or  cause  in  inducing 
action  or  in  mediating  activity.  As  an  aspect  of  the  sum 
total  of  nervous  correlations  in  the  higher  brain  centers,  the 
intellect  can  not  be  considered  as  a  causative  agent,  nor  can 
an  idea,  which  is  always  the  outcome,  though  remotely  so, 
of  sensory  stimulation,  be  used  as  the  cause  of  individual  or 
group  activity. 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE 

BY  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

University  of  Wisconsin    Ohio  State  University 

Practically  all  studies  in  the  field  of  mental  work  and 
fatigue  have  employed,  in  one  form  or  another,  one  of  two 
general  methods  of  investigation.  According  to  one  method 
the  subject  is  required  to  perform  certain  tests  at  the  begin- 
ning and  again  at  the  close  of  a  period  of  work,  or  at  intervals 
during  its  progress.  The  differences  between  the  successive 
applications  of  the  tests  are  regarded  as  measures  of  the  effect 
of  the  intervening  work.  According  to  the  second  method 
instead  of  making  comparisons  of  the  results  of  short  tests  at 
the  beginning  and  at  the  end  of  the  period  of  work,  a  study  is 
made  of  the  progress  of  the  work  itself,  and  the  factors  which 
affect  its  progress. 

Instead  of  regarding  these  two  methods  as  different  ways 
of  dealing  with  the  same  general  problem,  they  should  rather 
be  regarded  as  two  distinct  problems,  since  they  differ  not 
only  in  procedure,  but  also  in  the  result  sought.  The  former 
tries  to  secure  results  that  shall  be  free  from  the  influence  of 
such  factors  as  practice,  "warming  up,"  and  variation  in 
attention  and  interest  and  to  obtain  an  index  of  fatigue  only 
as  it  is  developed  in  the  course  of  the  work.  The  latter, 
instead  of  trying  to  eliminate  the  influence  of  these  factors, 
tries  to  take  particular  account  of  them  and  to  assign  to  each 
its  specific  value  in  the  work  curve. 

It  is  very  essential  in  studies  of  the  latter  type  that  the 
task  done  be  of  uniform  difficulty  throughout  the  entire 
period  of  work.  Otherwise  we  shall  not  know  whether  the 
variations  in  the  curve  are  due  to  conditions  in  the  work  or 
in  the  worker.  It  is  likewise  very  desirable  to  employ  a  form 
of  activity  which  involves  a  minimum  of  physical  effort  and 
sensory  strain,  so  that  the  mental  factors  may  be  isolated  as 
fully  as  possible.  The  kind  of  work  which  has  proved  most 

391 


392  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

satisfactory,  and  which  has  been  most  extensively  used,  is 
some  form  of  mental  computation. 

The  Experiments. — In  a  recent  study  of  mental  fatigue1 
results  were  secured  from  forty-five  hours  of  mental  calcula- 
tion done  under  uniform  experimental  conditions  and  care- 
fully checked  both  as  to  the  number  of  errors  made  and  the 
amount  of  work  done  in  each  successive  half-minute.  Twenty- 
three  persons  took  part  in  the  experiment.  The  work  was 
done  in  forty-one  periods  varying  in  length  from  thirty 
minutes  to  two  hours  and  a  half.  The  type  of  work  done  was 
that  devised  by  one  of  the  writers  and  described  elsewhere.2 
This  method  was  essentially  as  follows: 

The  subject  was  seated  comfortably  in  a  quiet  room.  The 
experimenter  began  by  giving  him  a  number  consisting  of 
two  digits.  The  subject  added  mentally,  six  to  this  number, 
then  seven  to  the  sum  thus  secured,  then  eight  to  this  last 
sum,  and  then  nine  to  this  result,  and  then  again  six,  seven, 
eight,  and  nine  in  rotation,  adding  in  every  case  to  the  sum 
resulting  from  the  previous  addition.  The  subject  spoke  his 
answers  aloud.  At  the  end  of  thirty  seconds  the  experimenter 
announced  a  new  number  and  the  subject  immediately 
dropped  the  series  on  which  he  was  working  and  began  with 
this  new  number  by  adding  six,  seven,  eight,  and  nine  in 
rotation  as  before,  for  another  thirty  seconds  when  another 
starting  number  was  given,  and  so  on  without  interruption  for 
the  entire  period  of  work.  The  advantages  of  this  type  of 
addition  are  that  it  reduces  all  physical  and  sensory  elements 
to  a  minimum,  that  it  taxes  mental  effort  to  its  full  extent,  as 
was  witnessed  by  every  person  who  took  part  in  the  experi- 
ment, that  it  is  almost  perfectly  continuous,  giving  no  op- 
portunity for  relaxation,  and  that  it  is  composed  of  small  and 
fairly  uniform  units  of  work  in  terms  of  which  the  results  can 
be  measured  accurately.  Even  adding  columns  on  paper 
involves  more  muscular  and  sensory  activity  than  the  present 
type  of  addition  involves.  The  subjects  were  usually  allowed 

1Ash,  I.  E.,  'Fatigue  and    Its  Effects  upon  Control/    Archives  of  Psychology. 
Vol.  V.,  No.  31.    The  results  here  discussed  were  not  presented  in  that  monograph. 
2  Starch,  D.,  'Experiments  in  Educational  Psychology,'  pp.  172-181. 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE  393 

to  make  two  or  three  practice  series  of  the  additions  before 
the  regular  experiment  was  begun. 

When  the  sum  of  successive  additions  had  reached  one 
hundred  or  more  the  hundreds  digit  was  dropped  and  the 
additions  continued  with  the  units  and  tens  digits.  Thus,  if 
the  number  first  given  was  72,  then  the  successive  sums  should 
be  78,  85,  93,  102,  108,  115,  etc.,  but  instead  of  giving  these 
last  sums  as  102,  108,  115,  they  were  given  simply  as  2,  8, 
15,  etc. 

To  enable  the  experimenter  to  keep  the  results  accurately 
mimeographed  sheets  of  paper  were  prepared  in  advance 
which  contained  all  the  numbers  used  as  starters1  and,  in 
columns  directly  under  them,  the  correct  sums  of  twenty 
additions.  Whenever  the  subject  gave  an  incorrect  sum,  the 
experimenter  wrote  it  down  beside  the  correct  sum.  A  line 
was  drawn  under  the  sum  resulting  from  the  last  addition 
in  each  thirty-second  period,  so  that  an  exact  record  was 
kept  of  the  amount  and  accuracy  of  the  work  done.  During 
the  experiments,  the  subjects  either  closed  their  eyes  or  sat 
in  such  a  position  as  to  be  unable  to  see  the  experimenter  in 
order  to  avoid  distractions  and  to  concentrate  to  the  fullest 
extent  upon  the  task  of  the  experiment.  Neither  subject 
nor  experimenter  spoke  a  word  during  the  experiment  except 
the  "starting  numbers"  which  were  given  by  the  latter,  and 
the  results  of  the  successive  additions  by  the  former.  No 
time  was  allowed  to  elapse  between  series. 

Results. — The  data  afforded  by  these  experiments  may  be 
treated  from  several  different  angles,  and  will  throw  light  on 
a  number  of  important  phases  of  the  problem  of  mental 
work  and  fatigue.  The  first  questions  to  suggest  themselves 
very  naturally  related  to  the  general  form  of  the  curve  for 
work  periods  of  varying  lengths.  How  soon  after  beginning 
work  does  one  reach  his  maximum  efficiency,  and  how  long 
will  he  be  able  to  maintain  it?  How  closely  will  the  curve 
of  work  for  one  day  represent  that  of  another?  How  widely 

1  The  numbers  used  as  starters  comprised  all  the  numbers  between  10  and  100  except 
those  whose  right-hand  digit  is  o  or  which  will  produce  sums  whose  right-hand  digit  is  o. 
All  these  were  omitted  since  the  additions  in  such  cases  are  decidedly  less  difficult. 


394  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

do  different  persons  vary  with  respect  to  the  form  of  their 
work  curves?  How  greatly  and  in  what  general  respects  do 
the  work  curves  of  those  who  work  slowly  differ  from  the 
curves  of  others  who  work  rapidly? 

The  results  are  shown  graphically  in  Figs.  I  to  4.  The 
points  in  the  curves  represent  the  average  number  of  additions 
made  in  each  five  successive  thirty-second  series.  The  curves 
for  the  errors  are  shown  in  the  lower  part  of  each  figure. 
Fig.  I  shows  the  composite  curves  for  three  two-hour  records 
obtained  from  two  subjects.  Two  records  were  obtained 
from  one  subject.  Fig.  2  gives  the  results  for  nine  one-and-a- 
half  hour  records  obtained  from  eight  subjects.  Fig.  3  re- 
presents twenty-one  one-hour  records  obtained  from  fourteen 
subjects.  Fig.  4  represents  eight  half-hour  records  obtained 
from  four  subjects. 

These  figures  show  that  the  number  of  additions  per  unit 
of  time  gradually  increases  during  the  first  twenty-five  to 
thirty-five  minutes,  when  the  maximum  speed  is  attained. 
This  maximum  speed  is  maintained  for  another  thirty  or 
thirty-five  minutes,  at  which  time  the  number  of  additions 
begins  gradually  to  decrease  and  continues  to  do  so  until 
the  work  ceases.  The  curve  of  errors  takes,  on  the  whole,  the 
opposite  direction  to  that  of  the  work  curve.  That  is,  the 
number  of  errors  is  the  largest  when  the  number  of  additions 
is  the  smallest.  There  is  greater  "zigzagging"  or  irregularity 
in  the  work  curves  when  the  rate  of  addition  is  highest.  The 
initial  period  of  increase  in  the  rate  of  additions  is  not  found 
in  Fig.  I.  That  is,  the  rate  at  the  beginning  of  the  experiment 
is  as  high  as  at  any  time  during  its  progress.  This  is  probably 
due  to  the  fact  that  the  subjects  were  quite  familiar  with  the 
work  of  the  experiment  since  they  had  made  shorter  records 
before. 

While  the  curves  in  Figs.  I  to  4  show  clearly  that  there 
are  fewer  additions  made  in  those  periods  in  which  the 
number  of  errors  is  greatest,  they  do  not  show  the  full  differ- 
ence in  the  number  of  additions  made  in  those  series  in  which 
errors  occurred  and  those  in  which  no  errors  occurred.  In 
order  to  determine  just  how  great  this  difference  was,  the 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE 


395 


396  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

number  of  additions  in  those  series  which  contained  errors, 
and  in  those  which  contained  no  errors  was  counted. 

Before  doing  this,  however,  the  data  of  all  the  experiments 
were  divided  into  two  groups.  Group  I.  included  those 
experiments  in  which  the  subjects  averaged  more  than  twelve 
additions  in  each  half-minute  period  or  series.  Group  II. 
included  all  those  records  in  which  the  average  was  less  than 
twelve.  The  experiments  of  Group  I.  covered  25  hours  of 
work  and  therefore  included  3,000  half-minute  series  of  addi- 
tions. In  2,333  °f  these  series,  no  errors  were  made;  while  in 
the  other  667  series  920  errors  were  made.  The  average 
number  of  additions  per  half-minute  period  in  the  series  in 
which  no  errors  were  made  was  17.2.  The  average  for  the 
667  series  in  which  errors  were  made  was  n.8.  In  other 
words,  an  average  of  46.2  per  cent,  more  additions  were 
made  in  those  series  in  which  no  errors  occurred  than  in  those 
in  which  errors  did  occur. 

The  experiments  of  Group  II.  covered  20  hours  of  work 
and  included  2,400  half-minute  series  of  additions.  In  1,441 
of  these  series,  no  errors  occurred.  In  the  remaining  959 
series,  1,784  errors  occurred.  In  this  group,  the  average 
number  of  additions  per  thirty-second  period  for  the  series 
which  contained  no  errors  was  9.71  and  for  those  in  which 
errors  did  occur  the  average  was  7.8.  In  this  group  there 
were,  on  an  average,  only  23.8  per  cent,  more  additions  made 
in  those  series  in  which  no  errors  occurred  than  in  those  in 
which  errors  occurred,  as  against  46.2  per  cent,  in  Group  I. 
These  results  indicate  that  those  who  worked  rapidly  worked 
more  accurately  than  those  who  worked  slowly.  The  more 
significant  fact,  however,  brought  out  in  these  results  is  that 
it  requires  a  longer  time  for  any  one,  whether  he  work  rapidly 
or  slowly,  to  make  an  incorrect  addition  than  a  correct  one. 
This  fact,  overlooked  by  many  investigators,  obscures  the 
signs  of  fatigue,  which  have  been  sought  by  the  method  of 
continuous  work.  Fatigue  is  unquestionably  developed  in  all 
such  experiments  but  it  is  not  shown  in  the  actual  output  of 
work. 

These  figures,  however,  do  not  express  the  real,  or  full 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE  397 

differences  between  the  number  of  correct  additions  made  in 
any  unit  of  time  and  the  number  of  incorrect  additions  for 
the  same  time;  or  the  effects  which  an  error,  or  those  factors 
which  cause  one  to  make  an  error,  have  upon  one's  speed  in 
mental  work.  In  order  to  show  the  full  significance  of  the 
errors,  or  of  the  factors  which  caused  them,  in  slowing  up  the 
work,  a  computation  was  made  of  the  number  of  additions  in 
those  half-minute  series  which  contained  errors,  before  any 
errors  were  made,  and  also  of  the  number  including  and  fol- 
lowing the  first  error  in  each  of  the  different  series.  In  all 
of  the  667  series  of  Group  I.  which  contained  errors,  the  total 
number  of  additions  before  the  errors  occurred  was  5,714. 
The  total  number  of  those  including  and  following  the  errors 
for  all  the  series  was  2,177.  We  may  reasonably  assume  that 
the  rate  for  those  additions  which  were  made  before  any 
errors  occurred  would  be  the  same  as  for  those  series  which 
contained  no  errors.  If  this  assumption  be  correct,  then  the 
amount  of  time  required  to  make  these  5,714  additions  which 
were  made  before  the  errors  took  place  would  be  about  equal 
to  331  thirty-second  periods,  leaving  336  periods  to  make  the 
2,177  additions  which  included  and  came  subsequent  to  the 
errors.  This  would  make  an  average  for  these  additions  of  6,5 
per  thirty-second  period,  or  slightly  more  than  one  third  the 
rate  when  no  errors  occurred.  In  the  959  series  of  Group  II. 
which  contained  errors,  3,846  additions  were  made  before 
any  errors  occurred,  while  the  number  including  and  following 
the  errors  was  3,665.  Treating  these  numbers  as  we  did  those 
in  the  preceding  group  we  find  the  average  rate  for  the  in- 
correct additions  and  those  subsequent  to  them  in  the  series 
in  which  they  occur  to  be  6.5  per  thirty-second  period,  or 
about  two  thirds  the  rate  for  those  series  in  which  no  errors 
occurred. 

That  the  assumption  is  substantially  correct  is  indicated 
by  a  special  record  made  on  one  subject  in  which  the  exact 
time  was  noted  when  the  first  error  in  each  series  occurred. 
In  this  record  the  time  per  addition  after  the  error  occurred 
was  3.78  seconds,  or  31  per  cent,  longer. 

Still  another  factor  in  the  distribution  of  errors  and  the 


DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 


effect  of  this  distribution  on  the  rate  of  additions  is  the 
relative  number  of  series  containing  errors  at  different  stages 
in  the  experiment  and  the  number  of  errors  in  each  of  these 
different  series.  This  distribution  is  shown  in  the  following 
tables.  (Table  I.  giving  the  results  of  Group  L;  Table  II. 
those  of  Group  II.)  The  top  horizontal  row  gives  the  suc- 

TABLE  I 

GROUP  I 


I..  . 

i 

2 

3 

4 

5 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

II 

12 

13 

14 

IS 

2.  . 

20 

2O 

20 

20 

20 

20 

7 

7 

7 

2 

2 

2 

i 

I 

i 

3-  • 

4-  • 

400 
i«;6 

400 
129 

400 
116 

400 

IOO 

400 
84 

£ 

I40 

,40 

140 
5 

40 
O 

40 
I 

40 
I 

20 
o 

20 
I 

20 
O 

I:: 

159 

1.0+ 

129 
1.0 

127 
i.i  — 

129 
1.3 

124 
i.")- 

/.& 

40 

5-° 

& 

39 

7-8 

o 
o.o 

6 
6.0 

6 
6.0 

o 
o.o 

7 
7.0 

O 
O.O 

7-  • 

39 

32 

29 

25 

21 

IS 

5-7 

4-3 

3.6 

0.0 

2-5 

2-5 

o.o 

5 

O.O 

TABLE  II 

GROUP  II 


I  

i 

2 

•: 

4 

c 

6 

7 

8 

9 

10 

n 

12 

2  

21 

21 

21 

M 

i-z 

M 

5 

5 

5 

i 

i 

I 

•5  .  . 

42O 

42O 

42O 

7*0 

760 

265 

IOO 

IOO 

IOO 

20 

20 

2O 

A.  . 

2O2 

T*" 
176 

I7O 

106 

ICK 

no 

74 

77 

17 

i 

i 

2 

I::-::::: 

7  

342 
1.7- 

48 

324 

1.8+ 
42 

347 

2.0+ 

40+ 

165 
4i- 

1  68 
1.6- 

40+ 

194 

1.8- 
42- 

61 

1.8- 
34 

2+ 

33 

60 
3-5+ 
17 

n 

3-7- 
iS 

8 
8 
5 

II 

5-5 

10 

cessive  ten-minute  work  periods.  The  second  row  gives  the 
number  of  records  concerned  in  the  experiment;  the  third  row 
gives  the  total  number  of  half-minute  addition  series  made  in 
the  successive  ten-minute  periods;  the  fourth  row  gives  the 
number  of  half-minute  series  in  which  error  occurred; 
the  fifth  row  gives  the  total  number  of  errors;  the  sixth  row 
gives  the  average  number  of  errors  in  those  series  in  which 
errors  occurred;  and  the  seventh  row  gives  the  percentage  of 
series  containing  errors  out  of  the  total  number  of  series  made. 
The  reason  why  the  numbers  in  the  second  row  decrease 
from  left  to  right  is  that  not  all  records  were  of  equal  length. 
Twenty  records  in  Group  I.  extended  through  the  first  six 
ten-minute  periods,  seven  through  the  next  three,  etc. 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE  399 

It  will  be  seen  from  the  foregoing  tables  that  not  only 
does  the  number  of  errors  decrease  as  the  work  proceeds, 
row  5,  but  more  particularly  does  the  number  of  the  series 
which  contain  errors  decrease,  rows  4  and  7,  while  the  number 
of  errors  in  those  series  increases,  row  6. 

These  facts  very  naturally  raise  the  question:  What  causes 
these  errors  in  the  additions,  and  why  should  they  become 
fewer  as  the  work  proceeds?  It  is  clearly  evident  that  these 
errors  did  not  occur  because  the  subjects  did  not  know  the 
sums  of  certain  numbers  to  be  added.  The  errors  undoubt- 
edly resulted  from  a  kind  of  interruption.  Some  other 
thought,  coming  into  the  focus  of  consciousness,  momentarily 
crowded  out  the  number  to  be  added,  or  the  previous  sum  to 
which  this  number  was  to  be  added. 

Now  if  we  take  mental  fatigue  to  mean  (as  we  have  shown 
in  the  article  previously  referred  to)1  a  loss  of  control  over  the 
direction  which  any  particular  nervous  excitation  within 
the  brain  shall  take,  and  a  growing  inability  to  inhibit  or 
repress  irrelevant  or  obtruding  ideas  and  suggestions,  and 
analyze  the  work  from  that  point  of  view,  we  may  see  how 
fatigue  can  be  developing  all  the  time  during  the  work  and 
yet  the  gross  results  show  little  or  no  effects  of  it.  At  the 
beginning  of  the  work  all  one's  faculties  are  alert  and  ready 
to  respond  to  the  slightest  suggestions,  or  the  intrusion  of 
any  idea  or  impression.  But  as  the  work  proceeds  the  facul- 
ties become,  as  it  were,  insulated  to  extraneous  suggestions 
and  intruding  impressions.  While  from  two  fifths  to  one 
half  the  series  of  additions  at  the  beginning  of  the  work 
contained  errors,  at  the  end  of  an  hour  and  a  half  or  two 
hours  only  about  one  twentieth  to  one  sixth  contained 
errors.  At  the  beginning  of  the  work  we  are  required  not 
only  to  make  the  additions  but  also  to  combat  the  host  of 
intruding  ideas  which  are  striving  for  a  place  in  the  focus  of 
consciousness.  Every  one  who  engages  extensively  in  mental 
work,  especially  if  it  be  varied  in  character,  knows  that  a 
certain  amount  of  time  is  required  to  "get  settled"  to  any 
particular  kind  of  work.  We  say  we  can  not  concentrate  at 

1  'Archives  of  Psychology,'  No.  31. 


400  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

the  beginning  of  work,  which  is  only  another  way  of  saying 
that  we  cannot  successfully  combat  irrelevant  ideas  which 
are  seeking  to  intrude  themselves  into  consciousness. 

To  attempt  to  measure  mental  fatigue  by  such  experi- 
ments as  are  usually  employed  in  those  studies  which  employ 
the  methods  of  continuous  work  is  like  having  the  subject  do 
a  number  of  things  at  the  same  time  and  then  measure  his 
efforts  by  what  he  accomplishes  in  one  of  them.  Such  a 
method  would  not  be  very  far  wrong  if  the  relative  difficulty 
of  the  different  activities  remained  constant  throughout  the 
work  period.  But  if  the  unmeasured  activities  can  be  shown 
to  grow  constantly  less  difficult  as  the  work  progresses,  then 
it  is  evident  that  more  could  be  accomplished  of  that  which  is 
being  measured  without,  on  the  whole,  the  expenditure  of 
greater  effort  or  more  energy,  or  the  same  could  be  accom- 
plished with  the  same  expenditure  of  effort. 

It  has  been  shown  in  muscular  work  and  fatigue  that,  as 
the  muscles  become  fatigued,  there  is  developed  a  resistance 
to  motor  impulses  in  the  nerve  tracts  leading  to  the  fatigued 
muscles.  This  resistance  protects  the  muscles  from  complete 
exhaustion  which  would  occur  if  every  motor  impulse  reached 
the  muscles  without  having  any  of  its  force  or  strength  neu- 
tralized by  this  nervous  resistance  which  arises  as  fatigue  of 
the  muscles  develops.  Just  so  in  mental  fatigue.  As  the 
mind  becomes  fatigued  by  mental  work  its  "receptive" 
faculties  become  less  responsive.  Fewer  impressions  and 
suggestions  enter  the  mind,  and  as  a  result  fewer  demands  are 
made  upon  it  as  fatigue  develops,  and  more  of  our  mental 
energies  can  be  devoted  to  dealing  with  those  ideas  and 
impressions  which  we  are  consciously  and  purposely  in- 
troducing. 

The  question  may  have  arisen:  Why  is  it  that  there  are 
fewer  errors  at  the  close  of  a  period  of  work  than  at  its  be- 
ginning, if  fatigue  means  the  loss  of  control  over  the  processes 
of  mental  associations  and  mental  elaborations?  Adding 
two  numbers  is  simply  making  an  association  between  two 
numbers  to  be  added  and  a  third  which  is  their  sum.  The 
answer  is  that  this  loss  of  control  affects  first  the  most  recent 


THE  MENTAL  WORK  CURVE  4O1 

and  hence  the  least  familiar  forms  of  mental  associations. 
In  the  matter  of  adding  simple  numbers  the  associations  are 
old  and  well  formed.  The  association  is  so  completely  formed 
that  the  stimulus  of  the  former  will  naturally  bring  forth  the 
response  of  the  latter  or  the  sum,  unless  that  stimulus  be 
confused  by  the  presence  of  another  idea  or  impression. 

That  these  irrelevant  thoughts  and  impressions  are  less 
easily  controlled  when  the  mind  is  fatigued,  if  they  succeed 
in  entering  the  focus  of  consciousness,  is  shown  by  the  fact 
that  near  the  end  of  our  experiments,  when  an  error  did  occur 
in  an  addition  series,  it  was  usually  followed  by  four  or  five 
more.  In  other  words,  when  the  intruding  impression  got 
into  the  focus  of  consciousness  and  hence  crowded  out  the 
numbers  to  be  added,  it  required  a  longer  time  and  more 
effort  to  suppress  the  former  and  recall  the  latter. 

SUMMARY 

1.  The  number  of  additions  per  unit  of  time  gradually 
increases  during  the  first  twenty-five  to  thirty-five  minutes 
of  work.     This  maximum  is  maintained  for  approximately 
thirty  to  thirty-five  minutes.     Then  the  number  of  additions 
gradually  decreases  until  work  ceases. 

2.  The  curve  representing  the  errors  has  in  general  the 
opposite  course.     The  number  of  errors  decreases  as  the  speed 
of  addition  increases,  and  then  increases  again  as  the  speed 
decreases.     An  incorrect  addition  occupies  considerably  more 
time  than  a  correct  addition  does. 

3.  The  half-minute  periods  in  which  errors  occur  becomes 
considerably  less  numerous  during  the  progress  of  work  even 
toward  the  end  of  long  work  periods,  when  the  speed  of  adding 
again  decreases. 

4.  But  when  an  error  does  occur  it  is  followed  immediately 
by  other  errors  more  and  more  frequently  as  the  period   of 
work  continues. 

5.  The  explanation  offered  for  this  fact  is  that  as  work 
continues  the  mind  and  the  neural  processes  involved  become 
more  and  more  insulated  against  distracting  stimuli  accom- 
panied by  a  decrease  in  controlling  the  direction  of  mental 


402  DANIEL  STARCH  AND  I.  E.  ASH 

energy.  The  decrease  in  the  occasion  of  errors  would  seem 
to  indicate  the  former  and  the  increase  in  the  number  of 
errors  in  immediate  succession  would  seem  to  indicate  the 
latter. 

6.  Slow  workers  make  relatively  more  errors  than  rapid 
workers  make.     The  difference  is  considerable. 

7.  In  some  respects  the  most  striking  fact  brought  out 
by  these  experiments  is  that  mental  work,  even  of  a  difficult 
nature,  and  when  continued  without  interruption  for  as  long 
as  two  and  a  half  hours,  seems  to  produce  a  much  smaller 
lowering  in  speed  or  accuracy  than  is  commonly  supposed. 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES   IN  A  NORMAL 
SCHOOL  CLASS 

BY  ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 

State  Normal  College,  Bowling  Green,  Ohio 

The  data  which  form  the  basis  of  this  article  were  obtained 
in  connection  with  an  advanced  course  in  educational  psy- 
chology given  at  the  Bowling  Green,  Ohio,  State  Normal 
College  during  the  summer  session,  1916. 

TABLE  I 

PHYSICAL  DATA 


No. 
Pupil 

Age 

Sex 

Weight 

Vital 
Capacity 

Vital 
Index 

Height 
Standing 

Height 

Sitting 

Relation 

Ave.. 

60.8 

3  600 

CQ.2 

165.6 

87.7 

52  3 

I 

28 

M 

59-0 

j  >wwv"/ 
4,700 

j  y  ~ 
80 

*V3  *v 

178 

v/  •/ 

93 

52 

2 

30 

F 

57-7 

3,600 

62 

163 

89 

54 

3 

39 

M 

75-5 

4,800 

64 

169 

93 

55 

4 

32 

M 

70-5 

4,800 

65 

172 

88 

Si 

5 

25 

F 

52.5 

3,000 

153 

83 

54 

6 

28 

F 

45-2 

3,000 

66 

159 

82 

52 

7 

31 

F 

52.7 

2,600 

50 

161 

83 

52 

8 

28 

F 

59-5 

3,400 

58 

161 

88 

54 

9 

19 

F 

69.6 

3,800 

55 

171 

89 

52 

10 

29 

F 

56.7 

3,200 

56 

171 

93 

54 

ii 

35 

F 

62.2 

3,100 

So 

156 

84 

47 

12 

25 

M 

63.0 

3,900 

63 

170 

90 

52 

13 

31 

F 

66.0 

2,900 

44 

169 

87 

Si 

No. 
Pupil 

Head 
Girth 

Head 
Length 

Head 

Width 

Cephalic 
Index 

Grip  R.  H. 

Grip  L.  H. 

Relation 

Strength 
Pull 

Ave..  .  . 

55.6 

I8.S 

14.8 

80.2 

89 

81.8 

81.6 

60.8 

i 

54-o 

18.5 

14.0 

76 

IOO 

IOO 

IOO 

70 

2 

57-o 

19.0 

IS.O 

79 

70 

66 

94 

55 

3 

56.0 

18.5 

IS.O 

82 

148 

133 

90 

no 

4 

56.5 

18.5 

IS-0 

81 

120 

IOO 

83 

62 

5 

55-o 

18.0 

IS-0 

83 

67 

58 

87 

58 

6 

54-5 

18.5 

14-5 

78 

70 

65 

93 

40 

7 

56.5 

19.0 

15-0 

80 

80 

65 

75 

S3 

8 

55-5 

19.0 

14.0 

73 

IOO 

80 

80 

58 

9 

58-5 

19-5 

15-5 

79 

85 

88 

103 

60 

10 

55-o 

18.0 

IS.O 

83 

70 

65 

92 

So 

n 

55-5 

18.5 

I4.S 

78 

72 

75 

103 

58 

12 

54-5 

17-5 

16.0 

IOO 

IOO 

IOO 

70 

13 

54-5 

17-5 

14.0 

80 

75 

68 

9i 

48 

403 


4°4 


ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 


The  great  variation  among  the  members  of  this  class  with 
respect  to  age,  experience,  physical  inheritance,  etc.,  offered 
an  exceptional  opportunity  to  illustrate  some  of  the  more 
essential  facts  of  individual  differences  by  the  measurement 
of  the  class  itself. 

Then,  too,  it  was  desired  to  demonstrate  to  the  class  the 
value  of  the  experimental  method  of  teaching  a  subject  like 

psychology. 

TABLE  II 

PSYCHOLOGICAL  DATA 


No.  Pupil 

Log. 

Mem. 

Rote 

Mem. 

Digit- 
Symbol 

Symbol- 
Digit 

Free 
Asso. 

Oppo- 
sites 

Add.  O. 
I 

Add.  O. 
II 

Add.  O. 
Ill 

Genus- 
Species 

Ave  

38.3 

93-o 

29.2 

29.9 

24.2 

26.O 

27.7 

27.7 

H 

I5.8 

i 

25 

89 

28 

27 

23 

24 

26 

26 

12 

16 

2 

40 

9i 

31 

42 

24 

28 

28 

2O 

16 

H 

3 

44 

85 

21 

23 

23 

26 

2O 

28 

22 

22 

4 

25 

82 

24 

32 

24 

22 

2O 

26 

14 

14 

5 

28 

91 

27 

24 

24 

26 

28 

36 

4 

IO 

6 

43 

93 

38 

33 

27 

30 

30 

32 

18 

22 

7 

44 

112 

31 

30 

30 

34 

34 

32 

20 

22 

8 

30 

83 

32 

35 

17 

30 

34 

30 

8 

4 

9 

43 

IOI 

27 

28 

2O 

28 

30 

28 

18 

20 

10 

49 

I  O2 

31 

32 

28 

18 

24 

28 

10 

18 

ii 

39 

1  08 

30 

32 

30 

26 

30 

26 

10 

10 

12 

30 

62 

24 

24 

2O 

18 

22 

2O 

12 

14 

13 

58 

109 

36 

27 

25 

28 

34 

28 

18 

20 

Av.  men 

38  3 

866 

2Q.-2 

a« 

4.2.2 

22.1 

1C.  I 

Av.  worn.  . 

juo 
40.1 

87.4 

"*r*J 

32.2 

j  j 
31-3 

T*^    ~ 
38.3 

22.4 

3 

IS-5 

(These  averages  taken  from  data  of  Professor  Pyle.) 


No.  Pupil 

Add. 
G.-S.  I 

Part- 
Whole 

Add. 
P.-W.  I 

Ink  Blot 

Cancel- 
lation 

Cane. 

Accur. 

Word- 
Build. 

Add. 
W.-B.  I 

Puzzle 
Box 

Ave.  .  .  . 

21.8 

I9-S 

26.3 

II-7 

21.4 

93 

17.2 

15-2 

5-07 

i 

24 

16 

22 

10 

26 

99 

14 

IS 

5-00 

2 

3 
4 

3 

26 

20 

% 

28 
32 
24 

II 
12 

16 

32 
2O 
13 

92 

IOO 

94 

19 
19 
13 

10 
21 
13 

3-19 

2-00 
5-06 

5 

20 

26 

26 

8 

IS 

92 

18 

16 

2-45 

6 

28 

24 

32 

ii 

29 

98 

17 

19 

H-54 

7 

26 

30 

30 

17 

29 

98 

22 

18 

6-35 

8 

14 

H 

22 

4 

19 

87 

17 

IO 

14-00 

9 

26 

24 

28 

14 

23 

98 

IO 

12 

3-06 

IO 

22 

18 

26 

19 

23 

86 

2O 

IS 

1-07 

ii 

16 

14 

28 

10 

23 

92 

18 

16 

1-25 

12 

14 

18 

5 

7 

74 

IS 

IS 

2-10 

13 

28 

24 

26 

IS 

19 

98 

21 

18 

5-00 

Av.  men. 

18  c 

10  6 

22.2 

18.6 

22  7 

Av.wom. 



io'5 
19.7 

9.8 

23.0 



21.  1 

22.O 



(These  averages  taken  from  data  of  Professor  Pyle.) 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES 


405 


Table  I.  exhibits  the  physical  data  for  the  13  members 
of  the  class  through  the  traits  named,  Table  II.  gives  the 
psychological  data,  while  Table  III.  gives  the  data  for  an 
experiment  in  the  learning  process  and  the  transfer  of  training 
with  the  same  class. 

TABLE  III 

SHOWING  DATA  FOR  INITIAL  AND  FINAL  TESTS  IN  ADDITION  AND  DIVISION,  WITH 
THE  AVERAGES  FOR  THE  CLASS.    THE  AMOUNT  OF  GAIN  is  ALSO  SHOWN 


Speed 

Accuracy 

No.  Pupil 

Addition 

Division 

Addition 

Division 

Init. 

Final 

Init. 

Final 

Init. 

Final 

Init. 

Final 

Test 

Test 

Test 

Test 

Test 

Test 

Test 

Test 

I 

53 

71 

108 

137 

81 

91 

96 

98 

2 

30 

47 

91 

89 

89 

IOO 

99 

95 

3 

32 

41 

61 

91 

84 

87 

96 

97 

4 

37 

48 

97 

126 

82 

90 

98 

99 

5 

25 

24 

44 

78 

83 

72 

IOO 

IOO 

6 

42 

61 

82 

88 

92 

95 

97 

98 

7 

45 

62 

122 

127 

98 

IOO 

IOO 

IOO 

8 

20 

27 

32 

49 

93 

99 

IOO 

9 

39 

43 

114 

115 

88 

93 

95 

95 

10 

44 

77 

92 

90 

88 

95 

99 

ii 

31 

5i 

66 

94 

95 

96 

97 

12 

21 

26 

45 

56 

43 

75 

93 

13 

70 

88 

90 

IOO 

96 

IOO 

IOO 

Av.. 

37-2 

48.0 
10  8 

78.3 

94-5 

84.6 

88.8 

A    2 

95-8 

98.0 

2  2 

Gross  gain.  .  . 

Per  cent  

29.0 

22.O 

Inasmuch  as  all  the  measurements  and  tests  are  described 
in  detail  in  various  publications,  it  is  not  deemed  necessary 
to  offer  here  more  than  a  brief  explanatory  sentence  con- 
cerning each. 

Age — Recorded  to  the  nearest  birthday. 

Sex — 'F'  represents  female  and  "M"  represents  male. 

Weight — Taken  in  the  metric  system  and  recorded  to  the  nearest  tenth  of 

a  kilogram. 
Vital  Capacity — Taken  with  a  wet  spirometer  and  recorded  to  the  nearest 

hundred  cubic  centimeters. 
Vital  Index — Computed  as  the  ratio  between  the  vital  capacity  and  the 

weight. 
Height  Standing — Taken  in  the  metric  system  and  recorded  to  the  nearest 

centimeter. 

Height  Sitting — Taken  and  recorded  the  same  as  height  standing. 
Relation — The  ratio  of  the  sitting  height  to  the  standing  height,  recorded 

in  terms  of  per  cent. 


406  ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 

Head  Girth    -. 

Head  Length  ?• — All  taken  in  the  metric  system  and  recorded  to  the  nearest 

Head  Width  one  half  centimeter. 

Cephalic  Index — The  ratio  of  the  width  of  the  head  to  the  length,  expressed 
in  terms  of  per  cent. 

Grip,  Right  Hand  1 — Taken  in  the  English  system  and  recorded  to  the 

Grip,  Left  Hand    j          nearest  pound. 

Relation — The  ratio  of  the  grip  of  the  left  hand  to  that  of  the  right,  expressed 
in  terms  of  per  cent. 

Strength,  Pull — The  number  of  pounds  the  subject  can  pull  with  both  hands, 
the  dynamometer  being  held  near  the  chest,  but  not  touching 
the  body. 

Logical  Memory — The  material  used  was  "The  Marble  Statue." 

Rote  Memory — The  material  used  was  that  given  in  Professor  Pyle's  manual. 
The  score  is  the  average  for  the  concrete  and  the  abstract  lists 
of  words  taken  together. 

Digit-Symbol,  Symbol-Digit,  Free  Association,  Opposites,  with  the  addi- 
tional tests  I,  II  and  III,  Genus-Species,  with  additional  test  I, 
Part-Whole,  with  additional  test  I,  are  all  described  in  Pyle's 
manual. 

These  tests  were  all  given  according  to  the  instructions  given 
in  the  manual,  the  score  recorded  being  the  average  for  one 
minute. 

Ink  Blot — The  material  used  was  the  set  of  20  ink  blots  by  Whipple.  The 
score  recorded  being  the  number  of  suggestions  written  down  in 
two  minutes. 

Cancellation — The  material  used  was  the  standard  test  beginning  with  the 
letters  h,  p,  1,  g.  The  score  recorded  being  the  number  of  a's 
cancelled  in  one  minute,  with  the  per  cent,  of  accuracy  recorded 
in  the  next  column. 

Word-Building — The  material  used  was  composed  of  the  letters  a,  e,  o,  b, 
m,  t,  with  the  letters  e,  a,  i,  r,  1,  p,  for  the  additional  test.  The 
score  recorded  is  the  number  of  words  made  in  2|  minutes. 

Puzzle  Box — The  Healy  puzzle  box  was  used  in  this  test.  None  of  the  mem- 
bers of  the  class  had  ever  seen  the  box.  Each  one  was  allowed 
two  minutes  to  examine  the  box  and  was  then  given  the  button 
hook  and  directed  to  open  the  box  as  quickly  as  possible.  The 
time  recorded  is  the  number  of  minutes  and  seconds  required  to 
perform  the  task. 

In  Table  I.  the  averages  at  the  top  are  for  the  entire  class, 
men  and  women  taken  together. 

In  Table  II.,  in  addition  to  our  own  averages,  the  averages 
found  by  Professor  Pyle  for  adults  are  also  included  at  the 
bottom,  insofar  as  these  are  comparable. 

The  slight  discrepancy  between  the  adult  averages  given 
by  Pyle  and  those  obtained  from  our  class  in  the  case  of  free 
association  was  noted  by  the  class  at  the  time  and  this  test 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  4°7 

was  re-checked,  but  with  no  better  results.  It  will  be  noted 
that  the  class  showed  no  better  ability  upon  the  whole  in 
writing  words  from  free  association  than  was  shown  in  writing 
easy  opposites.  This  fact  may  be  explained  upon  the  ground 
that  in  either  case  the  test  was  not  a  test  of  ability  to  asso- 
ciate ideas  so  much  as  it  was  a  test  of  ability  to  write  down 
words,  i.  e.j  a  test  in  motor  speed. 

In  the  experiment  in  the  learning  process  the  materials 
used  were  the  Thorndike  addition  sheets  (single  column 
addition  examples  of  ten  digits  each,  no  zeros  or  ones  in- 
cluded) and  the  division  sheets  of  Thorndike,  which  were 
used  by  Kirby  in  his  experiment  with  pupils  in  the  Children's 
Aid  Schools  of  New  York. 

These  examples  consist  of  columns  of  division  problems 
arranged  as  follows:  "48  equals  ...  55  and  .  .  .  remain- 
der," the  task  being  to  fill  in  the  blanks  with  the  proper 
numbers,  in  this  case  the  numbers  being  9  and  3. 

In  the  initial  test  10  minutes  were  allowed  for  addition 
and  5  minutes  for  division,  the  score  being  the  number  of 
examples  done  correctly  in  the  time  given,  which  is  called 
the  speed.  The  score  for  accuracy  represents  the  per  cent, 
of  the  total  number  of  examples  done  that  was  done  correctly. 

The  final  tests  were  given  in  the  same  way  as  the  initial 
tests,  but  after  an  intervening  daily  practice  of  5  minutes  at 
addition  for  eight  successive  days,  Sundays  being  omitted. 
There  was  no  practice  in  the  case  of  division. 

RESULTS  OF  THE  EXPERIMENT 

The  class,  composed  of  4  men  and  9  women,  showing  an 
average  age  of  29.2  years  to  the  nearest  birthday,  showed 
an  average  initial  ability  of  37.2  columns  added  correctly  in 
10  minutes,  with  an  average  accuracy  of  84.6  per  cent. 

As  a  result  of  40  minutes  of  practice  distributed  over  8 
days  the  class  showed  a  gross  gain  in  speed  of  10.8  columns 
added  correctly  in  10  minutes,  or  a  percentile  gain  of  29.0 
per  cent.,  with  a  gain  of  4.2  per  cent,  in  accuracy. 

The  average  ability  of  the  class  in  division  in  the  initial 
test  was  78.3  examples  done  correctly  in  5  minutes,  with  an 
average  accuracy  of  95.8  per  cent. 


ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 

The  final  test,  with  no  intervening  practice  in  division, 
but  with  40  minutes  of  practice  in  addition,  showed  a  gross 
gain  in  speed  of  16.2  examples  done  correctly  in  5  minutes, 
or  a  percentile  gain  of  22.0  per  cent.,  with  a  gain  of  2.2  per 
cent,  in  accuracy. 

SUMMARY  AND  CONCLUSIONS 

1.  Individual  differences  due  to  heredity  are  best  illus- 
trated in  a  study  like  this  by  such  traits  as  height,  weight 
and  other  traits  not  here  recorded,  as  for  example,  color  of 
hair,  color  of  eyes,  shape  of  features,  complexion  of  skin,  etc. 

2.  Individual  differences  due  to  sex  are  best  shown  by 
such  traits  as  vital  capacity,  strength  of  grip,  strength  of 
pull,  together  with  certain  tests  of  motor  capacity  such  as 
tapping,  not  here  recorded. 

3.  Individual   differences   between   persons   of  the   same 
sex  are  often  greater  than  the  difference  between  groups  of 
opposite  sex.     This  appears  in  the  case  of  imagination  as 
tested  with  the  ink  blots,  hard  opposites,  and  the  genus- 
species  tests. 

4.  Individual  differences  due  to  school  training  are  well 
illustrated  by  the  addition  and  division  tests,  as  it  was  evi- 
dent that  certain  members  of  the  class  had  mastered  these 
combinations,  while  others  evidently  had  not  done  so.     In  a 
general  way  it  may  be  said  that  equal  amounts  of  school 
training  will  produce  somewhat  the  same  results  in  a  number 
of  individuals,  as  for  example,  three  years  of  school  training 
will  enable  the  majority  of  a  class  to  read  with  the  same 
general  ability  from,  say  the  third  reader,  yet  if  the  same 
class  were  tested  with  psychological  tests  it  might  be  found 
that  individual  differences  had  been  augmented  by  the  three 
years  of  school  training  and  experience. 

5.  Individual  differences  due  to  other  causes  are  not  so 
well  shown  in  this  particular  class,  since  they  were  all  of  one 
race,  one  occupation,  one  nationality,  and  none  was  possessed 
with  any  defect  of  body  or  mind  due  to  accident. 

6.  One  of  the  most  striking  and  perhaps  the  most  sig- 
nificant examples  of  individual  differences,  from  the  stand- 
point of  the  teacher,  was  brought  out  in  the  puzzle  box  test. 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  4°9 

The  puzzle  box  designed  and  used  by  Dr.  Healy  in  con- 
nection with  his  work  at  the  Psychopathic  Institute  in 
Chicago,  was  the  one  used  in  this  experiment.  The  origin, 
improvement,  construction  and  use  of  this  puzzle  box  are 
set  forth  in  detail  by  the  above  author  in  an  article  appearing 
in  Vol.  XIII.,  No.  2  of  the  PSYCHOLOGICAL  MONOGRAPHS. 

The  puzzle  box  is  about  six  inches  square  by  five  inches 
deep.  The  lid  is  glazed  and  is  hinged  and  fastened  with  a 
hasp,  which  in  turn  is  held  in  place  with  a  bolt  hook  and  this 
is  made  fast  with  a  ring  attached  to  a  string,  and  so  on  with 
a  series  of  strings  and  rings  fastened  to  metal  pins  within  the 
box.  By  proper  manipulation  the  fastenings  may  all  be 
removed  by  means  of  a  button  hook  and  thus  the  box  may 
be  opened  without  the  necessity  of  forcing  at  any  point. 

The  following  paragraph  from  the  monograph  of  Dr. 
Healy  will  give  a  fair  understanding  of  the  operation  of 
opening  the  box:  "The  color  of  the  strings  is,  of  course, 
arbitrary  and  is  made  different  in  order  to  facilitate  the 
tracing  the  sequence  of  events  necessary  in  opening  the  box. 
One  removes  first  the  ring  over  the  post  K  and  pulls  out  the 
staple  from  its  holes  in  the  back  of  the  box,  releasing  the 
attached  ring.  Next  the  ring  over  the  post  G  is  lifted  off, 
which  loosens  the  short  orange  colored  string  so  that  the 
ring  on  the  arm  of  post  D  can  be  readily  removed.  This 
then  so  loosens  the  blue  string  that  the  final  ring  can  be 
pushed  over  the  curved  arm  of  the  bolt  hook  and  the  latter 
may  be  withdrawn,  the  hasp  lifted  and  the  box  opened." 

With  regard  to  the  purpose  and  the  significance  of  this 
test,  Dr.  Healy  says:  "The  purpose  of  the  test  is  obvious. 
It  may  bring  out  abilities  or  defects  in  the  manipulative 
powers,  in  the  ability  to  analyze  a  slightly  complicated 
situation,  in  powers  of  attention  and  continuity  of  effort. 
...  It  is  obvious  that  the  general  results  obtained  from  this 
test  must  vary  greatly,  but  there  seem  to  be  three  main 
types  of  approach  to  the  problem:  first,  random  trials; 
second,  intelligent  profiting  by  the  experiences  of  trials 
and  successes  or  failures;  third,  conscious  analysis  of  the 
puzzle  as  a  whole  with  recognition  of  the  relation  of  the 


410  ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 

parts.  Of  course,  on  account  of  the  differences  in  strength 
and  manipulative  power  there  would,  other  things  being 
equal,  be  considerable  difference  in  the  times  taken  by  the 
subjects.  Indeed,  altogether  it  has  seemed  to  us  that  the 
method  employed  by  the  subject  is  of  more  significance  than 
the  time.  Most  of  our  twelve-year-old  subjects  have  opened 
the  box  in  from  one  and  a  half  to  nine  minutes,  but  a  certain 
number  have  finally  failed." 

While  the  above  test  was  designed  especially  for  use  in 
the  classification  of  juvenile  delinquents,  yet  it  seems  evident 
that  it  tests  the  same  abilities  in  any  one  who  might  under- 
take to  open  it.  The  individual  differences  brought  out  in 
our  class  of  thirteen  adults  were  vastly  more  significant  than 
might  be  inferred  from  the  examination  of  the  data  pre- 
sented in  the  table  accompanying  this  article,  since  we  have 
here  only  recorded  the  time  that  was  required  for  each  person 
to  open  the  box. 

Observation  of  the  efforts  made  by  the  different  members 
of  the  class  in  trying  to  open  the  box  showed  that  no  one 
of  the  thirteen  worked  out  the  solution  of  the  problem  by 
the  use  of  reason  before  attempting  to  open  it.  Most  of 
them  began  by  random  trials.  Two  or  three  of  them  made 
definite  moves  which,  as  they  thought,  were  correct,  although 
most  of  these  efforts  were  useless. 

One  significant  fact  was  that  most  of  the  class  failed  to 
profit  by  mistakes  made  until  the  same  mistake  had  been 
made  over  a  number  of  times,  in  one  case  as  high  as  seven 
times.  The  one  step  in  the  solution  of  the  puzzle  that  caused 
most  trouble  was  the  removing  of  the  staple  at  the  back  of 
the  box  after  the  first  ring  had  been  removed.  In  their  own 
words,  they  "did  not  think  that  the  staple  would  come 
out." 

The  experiment  was  carried  a  little  further  and  each  person 
was  asked  to  retrace  all  the  steps  and  thus  lock  up  the  box, 
after  having  succeeded  in  opening  it.  In  almost  every 
instance  an  effort  was  made  to  replace  some  of  the  rings  or 
other  fastenings  without  first  closing  ike  lid!  Now  no  one  but 
a  child  would  fall  into  the  error  of  locking  a  trunk,  for  ex- 


INDIVIDUAL  DIFFERENCES  411 

ample,  before  closing  the  lid,  and  when  this  fact  was  called 
to  their  attention,  then  each  one  recoiled  with  chagrin  that 
he  had  not  been  able  to  think  of  that  himself. 

One  member  even  replaced  the  bolt  hook  and  all  the  rings 
and  fastenings  complete  and  failed  to  notice  that  the  hasp 
had  not  been  placed  over  the  staple!  Subsequent  experi- 
ments upon  a  number  of  adults  at  random  have  brought 
similar  results  in  almost  every  instance. 

7.  Insofar  as  comparisons  will  admit  between  our  data 
and  that  reported  by  Professor  Pyle,  there  appears  to  be  a 
very  close  correspondence,  with  the  exception  of  the  free 
association  test. 

An  irregularity,  however,  in  our  data  which  could  hardly 
be  due  to  the  small  number  of  subjects,  is  that  our  subjects 
make  a  better  showing  in  writing  the  additional  tests  in 
restricted  association  and  invention  than  in  the  first  tests 
given.  The  additional  tests  are  supposed  to  be  more  difficult, 
hence  one  would  naturally  expect  the  record  to  be  lower. 
Our  explanation  of  this  reversal  of  expectation  is  that  the 
influence  of  practice  in  the  first  tests  more  than  offsets  the 
difference  in  the  difficulty  of  the  tests. 

8.  The  outcome  of  this  experiment  tends  to  confirm  the 
writer's  contention  that  the  experimental  method  of  teaching 
psychology  is  the  best  method,  even  for  short  term  courses. 
Of  course  it  is  understood  that  the  regular  textbook  and 
reference  reading,  together  with  systematic  notebook  work 
were  all  carried  on  by  the  class. 

9.  In   the   experiment   in   the   learning  process   and   the 
transfer  of  training  the  improvement  shown  by  the  class 
was  about  the  same  as  that  reported  by  other  investigators 
and  corresponds  very  closely  to  unpublished  results  obtained 
by  the  writer  from  a  group  of  157  adults. 

10.  The  apparent  transfer  of  ability  from  the  function 
of  adding  to  that  of  dividing  is  partly  explained  by  the  fact 
that  the   division  examples  were  arranged   in  a  novel  way 
which  of  course  means  a  lower  initial  score  and  a  higher 
score  in  the  final  test,  due  largely  no  doubt  to  the  influence 
of  the  practice  in  the  tests  themselves. 


413  ROBERT  A.  CUMMINS 

On  the  other  hand,  a  part  of  the  gain  in  division  may  be 
accounted  for  by  reference  to  improved  habits  of  work 
brought  about  by  the  practice  in  addition,  since  none  of  the 
members  of  the  class  had  been  practicing  with  such  material 
just  iirthis  way. 


VOL.  XXIV.  No.  6  November,  1917 

. 

THE  PSYCHOLOGICAL  REVIEW 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR 

BY  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

St.  Louis,  Mo. 

In  the  study  of  behavior  we  find  that  the  animals  that 
have  the  most  highly  organized  nervous  systems  are  the  best 
adapted  to  changes  in  their  environment.  When  we  observe 
behavior  that  is  adapted  in  advance  to  changes  in  the  en- 
vironment, we  call  it  purposive  behavior.  It  is  thought  that 
from  the  behaviorist  point  of  view  it  would-be  more  con- 
sistent to  call  it  '  advance  adaptation,'  but  purpose  and 
purposive  are  very  convenient  expressions.  We  shall  there- 
fore use  these  terms  in  this  discussion.  It  is  to  be  under- 
stood, however,  that  this  does  not  mean  that  we  recognize 
consciousness  as  a  factor  in  the  operations. 

A  study  of  the  broader  aspects  of  purpose  in  behavior  has 
recently  been  presented  in  a  series  of  articles  by  Prof.  Howard 
C.  Warren.1  The  following  extracts  from  them  will  serve 
in  some  measure  as  a  basis  for  our  arguments:  "For  some 
biologists  purposive  activity  remains  an  insuperable  obstacle 
to  the  complete  acceptance  of  the  mechanistic  standpoint." 
"The  vitalists  .  .  .  assert  that  a  nonmechanistic  factor  .  .  . 
is  needed  ...  in  purposive  phenomena."  "It  remains  to 
be  seen  whether  the  mechanistic  interpretation  is  adequate 
to  account  for  the  purposive  character  of  behavior."2 

Let  us  consider  now  what  part  of  purposive  behavior  can 
be  traced  to  nervous  mechanisms.  Recent  writers  on  be- 
havior have  shown  how  we  may  account  for  such  behavior 

1  Howard  C.  Warren,  'A  Study  of  Purpose,'/,  of  Phil. ,  Psychol.t&c.t  1916,  13, 
Nos.  i,  2  and  3. 

2  Loc.  cit.,  pp.  31  and  32. 

413 


4H  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

as  performing  a  definite  series  of  movements.  They  have 
shown  that  each  movement  of  the  series  excites  kinesthetic 
impulses  which  follow  certain  paths  in  the  nervous  system 
because  those  paths  have  been  opened  up,  as  it  were,  by 
frequent  or  recent  use.  In  this  way  these  impulses  excite 
the  next  movement  of  the  series.1 

In  order  to  provide  a  good  foundation  for  a  discussion  of 
the  subject  before  us,  let  us  try  to  get  a  further  understanding 
of  such  behavior  as  performing  a  definite  series  of  movements 
and  of  the  nerve  mechanisms  that  account  for  such  behavior. 
As  already  stated,  movements  make  impulses  that  excite 
other  movements.  Such  impulses  play  a  most  important 
part.  In  many  cases  impulses  from  the  environment  assist 
in  exciting  the  particular  movement.  When  a  man  takes 
his  accustomed  morning  bath,  he  makes  movements  in  a 
definite  order,'  each  being  prompted  by  the  joint  action  of 
the  environment  and  the  preceding  movements  through  the 
medium  of  the  nerve  paths. 

When  the  movements  are  repeatedly  made  in  a  certain 
order,  the  lot  may  be  termed  a  memorized  series.  The  nerve 
paths  or  fibers  that  determine  the  movements  may  be  dis- 
tinguished as  association  fibers.  They  are  developed  by 
practice.  Movement  A  may  send  kinesthetic  impulses 
through  association  fibers  to  the  muscles  that  cause  move- 
ment B,  or  movement  A  may  make  a  change  in  the  environ- 
ment and  the  change  may  affect  some  receptor  which  sends 
impulses  that  provoke  movement  E.  In  either  case  we 
may  say  that  a  counter  signal  from  movement  A  excites 
movement  B. 

Each  movement  of  a  series  is  excited  by  a  counter-signal 
and  each  produces  counter-signals  for  movements  to  follow. 
That  is  not,  however,  the  whole  story.  Let  us  suppose  that  a 
soldier  has  been  trained  to  make  a  series  of  movements 
which  we  will  call  A  B  C  D  E  F  G,  each  letter  representing  a 
movement.  Counter-signals  from  movement  A  will  directly 
cause  movement  B.  Moreover,  counter-signals  from  A  will 
tend  to  excite  C  and  more  faintly  D  and  still  more  faintly  E, 

1  Watson,  John  B.,  'Behavior,'  New  York,  1914,  p.  275. 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR  415 

and  so  on.  In  the  same  way  each  movement  will  partially 
excite  every  movement  that  follows  in  its  train.  Now  when, 
for  example,  a  counter-signal  from  A  reaches  the  nerve  path 
leading  to  the  motor  ending  for  Z),  it  in  some  way  facilitates 
the  later  impulse  from  C  to  D.  It  opens  the  common  path 
or  lowers  the  resistance  so  that  movement  D  is  thereby 
insured. 

To  explain  further,  we  will  assume  that  there  is  a  dual 
common  path  that  is  open  to  impulses  from  A  and  C  only 
and  which  leads  to  the  motor  ending  for  movement  D. 
This  path  has  been  developed  further  each  time  an  impulse 
from  C  has  followed  in  the  wake  of  an  impulse  from  A. 
As  a  result  of  this  path-making,  an  impulse  from  A  leaves  the 
path  so  wide  open  for  a  time  that  an  impulse  from  C  can 
effectively  reach  the  motor  ending  for  movement  D.  This 
explains  why  movement  D  follows  after  A  and  C.  In  like 
manner  each  other  movement  makes  counter-signals  that 
facilitate  each  movement  that  follows  in  its  train.1 

To  express  it  another  way,  each  movement  makes  a  certain 
impression  on  or  change  in  the  nervous  system  which  takes 
part  in  determining  what  movements  shall  follow.  This 
impression  must  last  a  considerable  time,  but  gradually 
diminishes.  Let  us  now  suppose  that  these  impressions 
on  the  nerve  fibers  remain  after  the  whole  performance  is 
completed  and  last  until  the  performance  is  repeated.  We 
see  that  new  impressions  will  be  imposed  on  old  ones. 

In  passing  on  these  theories  of  nervous  operations  it  is 
well  to  remember  that  the  simplest  movement  is  caused  by 
the  contraction  of  one  or  more  muscles  and  that  each  muscle 
is  a  group  or  community  of  muscle  fibers.  Leading  to  these 
muscle  fibers  is  a  nerve  made  up  of  nerve  fibers.  Many  of 
these  fibers  are  motor  fibers.  A  single  motor  fiber  may 
branch  to  a  number  of  muscle  fibers.  We  know,  of  course, 
that  a  muscle  contracts  with  varying  strength  when  stimu- 
lated by  impulses  coming  through  the  nerve.  On  the  other 
hand,  physiologists  have  made  experiments  in  recent  years 

1 A  discussion  of  this  theory  is  given  by  the  writer  in  an  article  on  '  Compound 
Substitution  in  Behavior,'  PSYCHOL.  REV.,  1917,  24,  62-73. 


4J6  5.  BENT  RUSSELL 

which  indicate  that  in  an  individual  nerve  fiber  the  size  of 
the  propagated  disturbance  does  not  vary  with  the  strength 
of  the  stimulus.1  In  this  connection,  the  great  number  of 
nerve  fibers  that  may  be  concerned  in  each  operation  has 
an  important  bearing. 

Modern  behaviorist  theories  of  nervous  mechanisms  rest 
on  the  principle  that  recency  and  frequency  of  previous 
excitations  determine  the  extent  that  the  resistance  is 
lowered  in  a  given  nerve  path,  to  the  passage  of  an  impulse. 
It  may  be  noted  here  that  a  memorized  series  is  learned  by 
one  lesson  after  another.  In  the  first  lesson  the  situation 
is  more  or  less  new  or  unfamiliar.  With  each  additional 
lesson,  of  course,  the  situation  becomes  more  familiar.  In 
childhood  man  learns  a  vast  number  of  movement  series, 
i.  e.,  he  acquires  numerous  habits.  In  maturity  his  behavior 
is  largely  governed  by  habits.  Language  habits  and  other 
social  habits  are  important  factors  in  man's  daily  life.  In 
new  situations  behavior  may  be  largely  instinctive,  in  familiar 
situations  habit  governs.  Let  us  put  it  down  as  an  established 
fact  that  such  behavior  as  performing  a  memorized  series 
of  movements  can  be  satisfactorily  explained  in  terms  of 
nervous  mechanisms  made  up  of  association  nerve  fibers. 

The  object  of  this  article  is  to  show  that  purposive  be- 
havior can  just  as  well  be  explained  in  the  same  terms.  At 
least,  we  can  show  that  some  forms  of  behavior  that  would 
be  considered  purposive  can  be  so  explained.  We  shall  begin 
our  demonstration  by  pointing  out  what  behavior  may  be 
termed  purposive.  We  shall  then  call  attention  briefly  to 
the  correspondence  in  the  growth  of  purposive  behavior  with 
the  growth  of  habits  and  language  movements,  and  move- 
ments associated  with  measurement  of  time.  The  part 
played  by  teaching  will  be  pointed  out.  The  effect  of  reward 
upon  actions  will  be  discussed.  Recognition  of  purpose  will 
be  considered.  We  shall  then  take  up  the  development  of 
forethought,  so  to  speak.  It  will  be  pointed  out  that  mem- 
orized movement  series  and  series  of  incipient  movements 
may  be  combined  so  as  to  provide  for  and  give  rise  to  pur- 
posive behavior. 

1  Adrian.  /.  of  Physiol.,  1914,  47,  460-474. 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR  4'7 

In  looking  back  over  a  series  of  behavior  phenomena,  we 
see  that  some  of  the  changes  in  the  environment  were  pro- 
vided for  in  advance  just  as  "Coming  events  cast  their 
shadows  before."  For  example,  we  see  that  Mr.  Gray, 
who  went  out  for  a  walk  at  three  o'clock,  at  starting  borrowed 
an  umbrella.  At  four  he  returned  in  the  rain,  sheltering 
himself  with  the  umbrella.  We  see  that  the  act  of  borrowing 
the  umbrella  at  three  was  adapted  to  the  need  for  shelter 
at  four.  It  is  therefore  advance  adaptation  or  in  common 
terms  purposive  behavior.  Let  us  take  another  case.  We 
see  that  Dick  said  to  Ralph,  "I  want  to  get  a  canoe  and  go 
paddling.  Will  you  come  too?"  Ralph  replied,  "Yes,  I 
will  go  with  you,"  and  later  on  we  find  them  on  the  water  in 
their  canoe.  The  question  and  reply,  we  find,  were  adapted 
to  later  conditions  when  they  arrived  at  the  dock.  So  this, 
too,  is  purposive  behavior.  Let  us  take  a  third  case.  A  boy 
saw  a  strange  dog  and  stooped  and  picked  up  a  small  stone. 
The  dog  saw  the  movement  and  dashed  around  the  corner 
of  the  house  so  that  he  escaped  the  flying  missile.  We  see 
that  the  dog's  action  was  adapted  in  advance  to  the  boy's 
act  of  throwing.  This,  too,  is  then  purposive  behavior. 
To  compare  with  this,  let  us  think  of  a  boy  that  slipped  and 
fell  on  a  briar  and  hurriedly  got  up.  This  is  not  purposive 
behavior,  as  there  is  no  anticipation  in  it. 

We  may  here  observe  that  the  acts  of  an  educated  man 
are  usually  compounded  of  purposive  and  nonpurposive 
elements.  It  is  in  the  educated  man  that  we  find  advance 
adaptation  the  most  highly  developed.  The  best  measure 
of  the  degree  of  advance  adaptation,  it  is  thought,  will  be 
found  in  the  precision  and  definiteness  of  the  correspondence 
of  the  behavior  with  the  ensuing  changes  in  the  environment. 
Let  us  call  this,  for  convenience,  the  degree  of  purpose.  As 
an  illustration,  a  man  who  composes  the  score  of  a  grand 
opera  is  giving  a  good  example  of  behavior  having  a  high 
degree  of  purpose.  No  argument  is  needed  to  show  that  in 
the  human  species,  the  degree  of  purpose  develops  side  by 
side  with  the  accumulation  of  knowledge,  i.  e.,  with  the 
formation  of  memory  associations.  The  same  rule  seems  to 


4i8  5.  BENT  RUSSELL 

hold  with  the  brutes.  The  fox  that  has  been  hunted  before 
is  harder  to  capture  because,  as  we  say,  he  is  more  wary. 
On  consideration,  we  find  good  reason  to  believe  that  in  race 
development  and  in  individual  development,  the  growth 
of  purposive  behavior  has  been  in  proportion  to  the  growth 
of  habits. 

Let  us  now  enquire  briefly  into  the  effect  of  language  upon 
purposive  behavior.  In  considering  adaptation  in  animals 
we  must  take  account  of  their  social  environment  as  well  as 
of  their  physical  environment.  The  individual  must  adjust 
his  behavior  to  meet  the  actions  of  others  of  his  species  and 
also  those  of  his  natural  enemies  and  it  may  be  those  of  the 
creatures  he  preys  upon.  If  the  animal  has  even  the  most 
primitive  nervous  system,  it  will  be  affected  by  the  move- 
ments of  other  animals.  Natural  selection  brings  about  the 
evolution  of  language  habits  in  many  species.  The  sense  of 
hearing  must  have  been  developed  mainly  by  the  demands 
of  social  environment.  By  means  of  sound  waves  there  is 
communication  between  animals  so  that  the  movements  of 
one  individual  will  excite  a  response  in  another  individual. 
When  a  quail  is  flushed,  the  sound  of  his  wings  provokes  the 
flight  of  the  rest  of  the  covey.  The  senses  of  touch,  smell 
and  sight  are  also  used  for  communication.  It  is  probable 
that  sign  language  is  much  used  in  many  species.  Dogs 
and  cats  show  by  the  movement  of  their  tails  what  their 
feelings  are  and  no  doubt  their  companions  are  observant 
of  the  movements  and  are  guided  accordingly.  When  a  big 
dog  growls  at  little  dogs,  he  says  in  dog  language,  "Keep 
away,  or  I  will  bite  you,"  and  when  the  little  dogs  retreat, 
they  say  with  their  tails,  "Come  away  or  he  will  hurt  us." 
On  consideration,  we  find  that  the  evolution  of  language 
habits  must  have  proceeded  side  by  side  with  the  evolution 
and  differentiation  of  species  and  with  their  social  evolution. 
In  the  individual  we  find  that  language  habits  develop  from 
birth  up.  In  this  connection  let  us  note  that  nerve  paths 
are  lines  of  communication  from  sense  organs  to  muscles 
and  from  muscles  and  joints  to  other  muscles.  Let  us  note 
furthermore  that  by  means  of  distance  receptors  the  lines 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR  4*9 

of  communication  are  extended  into  the  environment. 
Language  movements  serve  for  communicating  with  other 
individuals.  Hence  the  excitation  of  a  sense  organ  of  one 
individual  is  conveyed  to  another  one  and  the  latter  responds 
accordingly.  This  control  of  one  creature  by  another  must 
have  been,  from  the  beginning  of  its  evolution,  concerned 
with  advance  adaptation. 

In  the  human  species  we  find  that  the  degree  of  purpose 
keeps  step  with  the  increasing  use  of  language.  The  naval 
architect  making  plans  and  specifications  for  a  submarine 
boat,  is  employing  language  movements  and,  at  the  same 
time,  is  behaving  with  high-degree  purpose.  In  fact  high- 
degree  purpose  seems  almost  dependent  on  language.  Let  us 
remember  that  language  movements  in  man  are  the  result 
of  training,  i.  e.,  of  the  development  of  habit  mechanisms  in 
the  nervous  system. 

For  high-degree  purpose,  a  knowledge  of  the  meaning  of 
time  is  necessary.  Until  a  child  has  learned  the  meaning 
of  time,  his  actions  show  little  definite  purpose.  He  must 
be  taught  to  note  the  passage  of  time.  He  must  learn  that 
it  takes  a  minute  to  walk  to  the  barn  and  it  takes  an  hour 
to  walk  to  the  railroad  station.  He  is  taught  to  count  the 
days  of  the  week  and  the  weeks  before  vacation.  Let  it 
be  remembered  that  such  knowledge  of  time  is  largely  due 
to  the  development  of  association  or  habit  mechanisms  in 
the  nervous  system.  By  these  mechanisms,  certain  move- 
ments come  to  be  associated  with  the  measurement  of  time. 

When  the  individual  has  acquired  language  habits  and 
time  measuring  habits  so  to  speak,  he  begins  to  take  part 
in  the  joint  activities  of  the  family  and  other  social  groups. 
More  purposive  behavior  in  the  individual  is  favorable  to 
greater  adaptation  of  the  social  group  to  its  environment. 
It  follows  that  natural  selection,  acting  through  the  group, 
brings  about  the  evolution  of  purposive  behavior.  We  can 
say  then  that  man  owes  his  purposive  powers  to  his  social 
position. 

In  highly  cultured  communities,  the  children  are  trained 
up  to  purposive  behavior.  This  is  done  by  means  of  language 


420  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

mechanisms  and  habit  mechanisms.  A  child  is  made  to 
tell  what  he  is  going  to  do  and  what  good  will  come  of  it. 
He  is  trained  to  plant  the  seed  so  as  to  get  the  flowers  or 
fruits  in  due  season.  As  a  result  the  individual  not  only 
comes  to  be  highly  purposeful  but  he  also  comes  to  think  of 
human  behavior  as  being  largely  purposeful.  Hence  he  is 
apt  to  think  that  he  himself  or  another  man  is  guided  by 
purpose  when  he  is  really  guided  by  habit.  He  is  apt  to 
think  also  that  the  purpose  that  guides  his  movements  is 
created  spontaneously  within  him,  quite  independently  of 
his  organs  of  sense  or  movement. 

Let  us  now  go  back  to  more  primitive  behavior.  The 
animal  trainer  rewards  his  dog  with  a  tempting  bit  of  food. 
Every  time  the  dog  performs  well,  he  gets  the  reward.  So 
the  dog  associates  the  reward  with  the  movements  that 
make  up  the  trick.  Hence  we  may  say  that  this  behavior 
is  purposive  in  a  sense.  He  responds  to  the  trainer's  signal 
so  as  to  secure  the  reward.  Now  it  can  be  shown  that 
association  mechanisms  will  account  for  such  behavior. 
Experiments  by  PawlowV  method  prove  that  after  proper 
experience,  a  dog's  mouth  can  be  made  to  water  at  the  sight 
of  a  green  light  or  other  stimulus.  Such  a  response  is  known 
as  a  conditioned  reflex.  It  is  plainly  a  case  of  association 
mechanism.  The  sight  of  food  by  a  hungry  dog  has  a 
decidedly  animating  effect.  The  effect  on  his  nervous  system 
is  evidently  widespread.  By  means  of  association  mechan- 
isms, other  kinds  of  stimulus  may  be  substituted.  An  animal 
will  run  to  the  feed  box  when  it  hears  the  keeper  coming. 
Any  stimulus  that  frequently  occurs  a  short  time  before  the 
getting  of  food  will  soon  establish  a  sort  of  conditioned  reflex, 
so  that  the  stimulus  will  have  a  marked  animating  effect 
on  the  animal.  So  when  the  trainer  gives  the  signal  for  a 
trick,  it  has  much  the  same  effect  on  the  trained  animal  as 
if  food  were  shown  it.  The  animal  is  alert  and  responds 
readily  to  the  accustomed  signals  according  to  the  estab- 
lished habit.  It  then  receives  a  bit  of  food  as  its  accustomed 
reward. 

1 J.  B.  Watson,  'Behavior,'  Holt,  1914,  p.  65. 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR  421 

Now  it  may  be  while  the  brute  is  performing  that  he  has 
something  in  mind  like  an  image  of  the  food  that  is  to  come 
after  the  trick,  but,  whether  he  has  or  not,  we  see  that  the 
association  nerve  paths  provide  for  the  proper  responses. 
We  see  then  that  although  the  animal's  behavior  is  in  some 
degree  purposive,  there  is  no  active  power  that  comes  from 
within,  as  it  were.  There  is  nothing  beyond  the  impulses 
aroused  by  the  environment  and  by  the  trainer's  signal. 
The  association  nerve  paths  govern  the  behavior.  The 
trained  animal  is  then  only  a  piece  of  machinery,  although 
we  must  admit  that  it  is  in  advance  of  the  machinery  built 
by  man,  for  as  yet  no  machine  has  been  constructed  by  art, 
even  in  appearance,  that  will  be  influenced  by  a  reward  to 
follow  its  operations.  It  is  probable  that  the  most  intelligent 
behavior  of  animals  is  governed  by  past  experience  and 
present  environment  and  not  by  what  is  going  to  be.  So 
far  as  animals  go  then,  purpose  is,  in  one  sense,  only  a  name, 
as  it  were.  And  yet  the  dog  that  goes  after  a  stray  sheep 
and  drives  it  back  to  the  flock  seems  to  have  as  much  purpose 
as  there  is  in  most  actions  of  a  human  child. 

Let  us  now  observe  that  purposive  behavior  in  animals 
includes  what  we  may  call  the  faculty  of  recognition  of 
purpose  in  others.  When  you  pick  up  a  stone  to  throw  at  a 
dog,  he  appears  to  know  what  you  are  about  to  do  and 
slinks  off.  People  used  to  say  that  such  behavior  was  due 
to  association  of  ideas.  There  is  no  way  to  tell  when  the 
response  is  due  to  association  and  when  it  is  due  to  conscious 
recognition  of  purpose.  When  a  hunter  takes  down  his 
gun  from  the  rack,  his  bird  dog  shows  by  her  demonstration 
of  joy  that  she  knows  her  master  is  preparing  to  take  her 
out  for  a  hunt  in  the  field.  A  critical  view,  however,  indi- 
cates that  it  is  another  case  of  association  mechanisms.  Just 
as  the  sight  of  food  can  cause  increase  of  animation,  so  can 
the  sight  of  her  master's  preparations,  by  virtue  of  con- 
ditioned reflexes,  do  the  same.  The  dog  wags  her  tail, 
leaps  and  perhaps  barks,  thus  saying  in  dog  language  that 
she  is  delighted  at  the  prospect. 

Let  us  now  review  briefly  what  progress  we  have  made. 


422  S.  BENT  RUSSELL 

We  have  considered  the  effect  of  language  habits  and  time- 
measuring  habits  upon  purposive  behavior.  We  have  found 
that  men  are  taught  to  have  purpose.  We  have  considered 
the  way  reward  acts  in  advance  adaptation.  In  all  these 
items,  we  have  found  that  associative  memory  is  a  most 
important  factor.  In  view  of  these  relations,  we  may  allow 
that  purposive  behavior  is  underpinned  on  all  sides  by 
association  nerve  mechanisms.  Let  us  now  enquire  how 
the  central  foundation  of  such  behavior  is  constituted. 

When  an  animal  or  child  has  learned  to  go  through  a 
certain  series  of  movements  in  a  given  order,  the  performance 
is,  as  before  stated,  a  memorized  series.  We  have  already 
established  that  such  a  series  is  the  operation  of  nerve  mechan- 
isms and  that  kinesthetic  impulses  link  the  movements 
together.  Each  one  of  the  movements  in  turn  is  provoked 
by  a  volley  of  effective  nervous  impulses  coming  by  way  of 
converging  association  fibers,  located,  we  will  say,  in  the 
cerebral  cortex.  These  fibers  have  been  recently  prepared 
by  scout  impulses,  as  it  were,  that  came  from  the  receptors 
in  the  muscles  that  made  the  movements  which  went  before 
in  the  series.  Each  association  fiber  received  a  stimulus  or 
scout  impulse  from  a  certain  movement  which  lowered  its 
resistance  for  a  time.  It  was  thus  prepared  for  the  effective 
impulse  that  came  soon  after.  In  this  way,  we  see  how  each 
movement  in  the  memorized  series  is  determined  by  the 
movements  that  go  before,  by  means  of  association  fibers 
which  have  been  developed  by  previous  training.  Let  us 
now  think  of  the  series  so  modified  that  each  movement  is 
incipient  only,  but  that  it  causes  afferent  impulses  that  excite 
other  incipient  movements  in  order,  so  that  the  incipient 
movements  correspond  to  the  actual  movements  in  the  pri- 
mary series.  Let  us  for  convenience  call  this  modified  form  a 
secondary  series.  We  see  that  a  secondary  series  is  some- 
thing like  a  train  of  thought. 

As  above  stated,  we  must  presuppose  that  an  incipient 
movement  can  in  some  way  provoke  an  appropriate  afferent 
nerve  fiber,  so  that  we  shall  have  an  impulse  that  corresponds 
to  a  kinesthetic  impulse  provoked  by  an  actual  movement. 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAVIOR  423 

To  explain  more  definitely  what  takes  place,  we  will  recognize 
two  alternative  assumptions.  The  first  one  is  that  an  im- 
pulse is  conducted  by  a  motor  nerve,  although  it  is  too  weak 
to  cause  contraction  of  the  muscle  and  is  then  conducted 
slowly  through  the  muscle  to  a  sensory  terminal  of  an  afferent 
nerve  fiber.  Hence  a  faint  discharge  from  the  brain  to  a 
muscle  is  followed  by  a  counter-signal  from  the  muscle  to 
the  brain.  As  an  alternative  the  assumption  is  that  at  some 
nerve  junction  or  synapse  there  is  a  short  circuit  from  the 
motor  nerve  to  an  afferent  nerve  fiber  and  that  the  impulse 
is  delayed  appreciably  at  this  junction.  Hence  a  faint  motor 
discharge  is  followed  by  a  counter-signal  that  reaches  the 
cortical  centers  and  serves  in  place  of  a  kinesthetic  impulse 
from  an  actual  movement.  With  either  assumption,  we 
see  how  one  incipient  movement  will  provoke  another  one 
and  there  will  be  a  series  of  impulses  running  back  and  forth, 
from  and  towards  the  cerebral  cortex.  As  in  the  case  of  the 
primary  series,  the  counter-signals  will  follow  the  common 
nerve  paths  where  the  resistance  has  been  lowered  by  recent 
or  frequent  previous  impulses. 

We  now  have  a  fair  understanding  of  both  the  memorized 
series  and  the  secondary  series  and  the  relation  between 
them  in  behavior.  Let  us  therefore  attack  the  main  question 
before  us  and  determine  whether  such  behavior  mechanism 
operations  will  account  for  responses  that  are  adapted  in 
advance  to  changes  in  the  environment. 

Let  us  take  a  definite  memorized  series  made  up  of  move- 
ments which  we  will  call  ABCDEFGHI,  and  suppose 
that  it  is  sometimes  replaced  by  a  secondary  series,  a  b  c  d  e 
f  gh  i.  When  a  child  has  learned  these  series,  if  he  is  induced 
to  make  the  movements  A  B  C,  the  other  movements  D  E  F 
G  H  I  will  be  made  from  habit  and  if  he  is  induced  to  make 
the  incipient  movements  a  b  c,  the  other  incipient  movements 
d  e  f  gh  i  will  tend  to  follow.  We  may  believe  that  the  same 
association  mechanisms  are  concerned  in  both  series.  When 
the  primary  series  is  followed  by  the  secondary  series,  we 
may  term  it  a  recall.  On  consideration  we  see  that  it  may 
sometimes  happen  that  the  secondary  series  will  come  in 


424  BENT  RUSSELL 

between  the  movements  of  the  primary  series  like  this : 
A  B  C  D  E  abc  def  ghiFGH  I. 

We  see  too  that  here  we  have  something  resembling  fore- 
thought, for  the  incipient  movements  /  g  h  i  show  a  corre- 
spondence with  the  actual  movements  F  G  H  /,  made  after- 
wards. In  this  way  we  find  that  an  elementary  case  of 
forethought  can  be  accounted  for  by  simple  association 
mechanisms.  It  is  the  first  step  that  counts,  so  it  is  not  an 
unfair  presumption  to  claim  that  we  could  advance  by 
degrees  and  account  for  all  purposive  behavior  by  association 
nerve  mechanisms.  It  will  be  seen  that  where  there  is  a 
series  of  incipient  movements  that  corresponds  with  a  series 
of  actual  movements  to  be  made  later,  a  foundation  is  pro- 
vided for  advance  adaptation. 

The  intelligent  animal  knows  the  future  by  the  past. 
What  was  the  future  yesterday  morning  is  now  the  past. 
Looking  back  one  sees  what  he  might  have  looked  forward 
to  yesterday  morning.  From  this  he  may  conclude  what 
he  may  look  forward  to  this  morning.  Hence  the  experience 
of  yesterday  becomes  the  forethought  of  today.  The  en- 
trance to  the  path  that  led  to  food  yesterday  will  suggest 
the  best  path  to  take  today  to  the  hungry  animal.  If  he 
takes  the  path  and  it  leads  to  food  again  we  have  a  case  of 
advance  adaptation.  In  considering  the  effect  of  reward, 
we  saw  that  such  behavior  as  that  is  explained  by  association 
mechanisms. 

Let  us  now  think  of  a  child  that  makes  the  incipient 
movements  /  g  h  i,  as  a  result  of  previous  operations.  Sup- 
pose that  the  afferent  impulses  from  these  movements  pro- 
voke associated  language  movements  as  in  uttering  the  words, 
"I  am  going  upstairs."  Then  the  actual  movements  F  G  H  I 
of  the  memorized  series  are  made,  such  as  proceeding  up- 
stairs. We  see  that  the  uttered  words  exhibit  advance 
adaptation.  Let  us  note  that  this  demonstrates  how  a 
secondary  series  together  with  association  accounts  for 
purposive  behavior.  In  a  similar  manner  it  is  thought  that 
behavior  equally  purposive  but  not  including  language 


ADVANCE  ADAPTATION  IN  BEHAPIOR  425 

movements  can  be  accounted  for.  For  example,  taking  a 
key  out  of  your  pocket  to  unlock  a  trunk.  Of  course  the 
necessary  common  nerve  paths  must  be  there. 

We  may  conclude  from  this  demonstration  that  the 
secondary  series  provides  a  foundation  for  advance  adapta- 
tion. It  is  obvious  then  that  purposive  behavior  can  be 
explained  as  due  to  association  nerve  mechanisms.  On 
further  examination  we  shall  find  in  very  many  cases,  espe- 
cially with  man,  that  the  secondary  series  is  made  up  of 
incipient  language  movements.  A  man  who  is  given  to 
talking  will  hold  a  silent  conversation  with  himself,  before 
acting  in  a  situation  that  is  not  quite  familiar.  From  our 
point  of  view,  it  is  all  due  to  nervous  impulses  that  follow 
the  paths  most  open  to  them  as  determined  by  previous 
nerve  muscle  operations.  We  shall  also  find  in  human  be- 
havior many  cases  where  movements  or  incipient  movements 
that  are  associated  with  measurements  of  time,  constitute 
the  secondary  series  that  anticipates  the  future  situation,  so 
to  speak.  One  can  as  easily  plan  for  next  Christmas  as  for 
his  next  meal.  The  same  kind  of  nerve  mechanisms  are 
employed  in  either  case,  and  in  both  the  responses  are  deter- 
mined by  one's  past  experience.  It  should  be  remembered, 
however,  that  thanks  to  the  advantages  of  spoken  and 
written  language  and  to  education,  a  man  can  make  the 
experience  of  others  serve  as  his  own.  That  is  where  the 
social  environment  comes  in. 

The  more  highly  developed  the  nervous  system  and  the 
greater  the  number  of  association  nerve  fibers,  the  more 
precise  and  definite  will  be  the  anticipation  of  future  needs. 
An  old  fox  is  warier  than  a  young  one.  An  educated  man  is 
more  purposeful  than  a  savage. 

To  sum  up  our  conclusions  briefly,  if  habit  forming  can 
be  explained  as  due  to  association  nerve  mechanisms,  advance 
adaptation  can  be  accounted  for  in  the  same  way.  If  our 
view  is  the  right  one,  mechanistic  interpretations  are  adequate 
to  account  for  the  purposive  character  of  behavior. 


RELEVANT  AND   IRRELEVANT  SPEECH 
INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS 

BY  P.  F.  SWINDLE 

Research  Fellow  in  Psychology,  Harvard  University 

INTRODUCTION 

The  audible  vocal  responses  of  certain  birds  and  of  the 
human  being  will  be  the  matter  of  chief  concern  in  this  paper; 
but  in  order  to  discuss  these  responses  intelligently,  and  in 
order  to  include  all  the  movements  which  may  be  used  as 
means  of  social  communication,  it  will  be  necessary  to  in- 
vestigate a  number  of  other  bodily  movements.  Excepting 
the  vocal  responses,  the  most  important  ones  for  speech 
are  the  mouth  movements  which  modify  the  vocal  responses 
directly.  Movements  of  minor  significance  are  those  of 
the  hands,  feet,  head,  eyes,  wings,  tail,  and  the  like,  which 
may  influence  in  any  way  the  vocal  responses,  or  which  may 
themselves  serve  as  gestures. 

All  of  these  responses  are  instinctive,  and  all  of  them 
may  be  at  the  same  time  habitual;  a  habit  is  an  instinct  which 
occurs  more  frequently  than  originally.  The  frequency  of 
occurrence  of  an  instinct  is  necessarily  increased  if  it  is 
associated  with,  and  is  regularly  conditioned  by,  at  least  one 
other  response  of  the  same  individual. 

Relevant  speech  instincts  and  habits  are  those  responses 
of  the  individual  which  serve  as  stimuli  to  call  forth  pre- 
dictable responses  in  other  individuals.  Some  speech  re- 
sponses are  at  the  outset  relevant,  while  others  are  made  so 
through  a  process  of  training  of  the  individuals  who  are  to 
produce,  perceive,  and  respond  to  them.  In  other  words, 
many  irrelevant  speech  responses  must. become  convention- 
alized, if  they  are  not  to  remain  superfluous  expressions  in 
ordinary  speech. 

For  the  sake  of  simplicity  in  dealing  with  vocal  responses, 

426 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  427 

I  shall  make  use  of  the  vowel  names,  a,  e,  i,  o,  and  u,  as 
abbreviated  means  of  speaking  of  the  very  large  number  of 
vowel  sounds  which  an  organism  in  question  may  utter. 
The  qualitative  nature  of  any  given  vocal  sound  could  be 
indicated  by  marking  diacritically  one  of  these  five  letters, 
but  it  would  be  unnecessary  and  perhaps  confusing  if  the 
attempt  should  be  made  in  the  following  pages.  It  will  be 
necessary,  however,  to  indicate  in  a  limited  number  of  cases 
the  specific  qualitative  nature,  e.  g.,  of  an  a\  but  in  general 
the  reader  will  be  privileged  to  image  or  utter  any  a  sound 
which  occurs  to  him  at  the  time. 

In  discussing  the  consonants,  I  shall  also  speak  primarily 
of  some  of  the  simpler  consonant  names  of  the  alphabet  as 
the  most  familiar  representatives  of  the  very  large  number  of 
consonant  sounds  which  the  organisms  utter. 

EXPERIMENT  AND  DISCUSSION 

To  understand  conventional  speech,  it  is  advisable  to 
study  carefully  some  simple  forms  of  speaking  organisms. 
I  shall  for  this  purpose  begin  with  the  barbet,  or,  as  it  is 
usually  called,  the  *  bearded  bird.'  It  frequently  speaks,  or 
more  strictly  sings  the  letter  a  somewhat  as  in  art.  When 
the  bird  is  not  molested  it  utters  a  succession  of  #'s  approxi- 
mately in  the  tempo  of  0.2  sec.  These  sounds  form  a  great 
number  of  <z-groups,  the  largest  one  of  which  contains  not 
less  than  five  hundred  <z's  as  its  elements.  When  the  group 
is  very  long  an  observer  can  become  aware  of  a  progressive, 
qualitative  change  of  the  a's.  The  change  is  usually  so 
gradual  that  it  is  not  apparent  in  the  shorter  groups.  Often 
the  mouth  closes  at  the  end  of  a  group  in  such  a  way  that 
the  final  a  is  converted  into  a  sound  resembling  the  English  r. 
When  an  <2-group  is  thus  terminated,  I  shall  speak  of  an 
ar- group-compound,  or  simply  of  an  flr-compound.  The 
a- group-complex,  or  the  <z-complex,  which  is  the  summation 
of  the  quantitatively  identical  and  different  ^-groups,  is  the 
most  essential  one  which  the  vocal  apparatus  of  this  bird 
manifests. 

The  mouth  movement  which  occurs  regularly  at  the  end 


428  P.  F.  SWINDLE 

of  a  given  fl-group  and  converts  the  final  a  into  an  r  sound, 
is  a  specific  activity  which  at  some  previous  time  interrupted 
a  series  of  a*s  and  became  permanently  associated  with  the 
final  a  of  the  a-group  which  it  isolated  from  the  longer  series. 
This  mouth  movement  became  the  permanent  conclusion 
or  final  accent  of  the  isolated  tf-group.  The  following 
experiment  makes  this  view  plausible. 

Observing  the  bird  carefully,  I  struck,  whenever  possible, 
the  glass  of  its  cage  at  the  fourteenth  a.  This  stimulus  called 
forth  the  mouth  movement  which  interrupted  the  series  of 
<z's  and  served  to  convert  the  fourteenth  a  into  an  r.  It 
became  eventually  so  well  associated  with  the  final  element 
of  the  i4-<2-group  that  I  no  longer  had  to  apply  any  stimulus 
to  the  bird  at  this  point  of  the  series.  The  ^/--compound 
which  thus  came  to  be  uttered  as  regularly  as  the  i4~<2-group 
occurred,  consisted  in  all  of  fifteen  perceptible  elements: 
first,  thirteen  stutters,  that  is,  the  a's  which  were  unnecessary 
for  the  perfect  pronunciation  of  the  r\  secondly,  the  significant 
a,  the  only  one  necessary  for  the  r\  and,  thirdly,  the  mouth 
movement  which  made  the  audible  difference  between  the 
fourteenth  a  and  the  preceding  ones.  The  bird  was  also 
taught  by  the  same  method  to  utter  an  <2r-compound  con- 
sisting of  thirty-three  stutters  and  the  r  which  was  a  modi- 
fied a.  No  other  habits  were  acquired  by  this  animal  under 
experimental  conditions. 

The  particular  training  to  which  the  bird  was  subjected 
habitualized  the  mouth  movement;  that  is,  it  caused  this 
movement  to  occur  more  frequently  than  originally.1  After 
the  training,  the  mouth  closed  not  only  when  the  glass  of 
the  bird's  cage  was  struck,  but  also  whenever  the  final  a  of 
either  the  14-  or  the  34-<2-group  occurred.  No  portion  of  an 
<2-series  was  caused  to  occur  more  frequently  than  originally, 
and  consequently  not  even  the  14-  and  34-a-groups  can  be 
called  habits.  This  training,  at  least,  did  not  make  them 
habits. 

1  For  a  more  detailed  discussion  of  instinct  and  habit,  see  my  article,  'Ueber 
einfache  Bewegungsinstinkte  und  deren  kiinstliche  Beeinflussung,'  Z.  /.  Sinnesphysiol., 
Bd.  49,  1915.  See  especially  pp.  247-248  for  my  definitions  of  instinct  and  habit. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  429 

The  training  did,  however,  cause  certain  a's  to  occur  less 
frequently  than  originally.  For  example,  in  the  case  of  the 
series  from  which  the  i4-<z-group  became  isolated,  the  four- 
teenth a  conditioned  the  mouth  movement  instead  of  the 
fifteenth  a;  and  with  the  mouth  closed  the  bird  could  not 
continue  the  series.  This  does  not  mean  that  the  latter 
part  of  the  original  series  vanished  completely,  but  only  that 
the  fourteenth  and  fifteenth  #'s  became  dissociated.  The 
most  significant  result  of  this  complete  dissociation  was  the 
addition  of  one  more  group  to  the  <z-group-complex. 

The  cockatoo  is  a  bird  whose  speech  instincts  outnumber 
those  of  the  barbet.  Its  vocal  apparatus  functions  in  various 
tempi,  as  is  indicated  by  the  differences  in  pitch  of  the  many 
tones;  and  the  mouth  moves  in  various  tempi,  directions, 
and  amplitudes.  A  large  number  of  group-complexes  is 
manifested  by  the  vocal  apparatus  and  mouth  parts.  The 
cockatoo,  like  the  barbet,  stutters;  but  the  succession  of  the 
elements  of  an  audible  series  is  usually  so  rapid  that  only  a 
continuous  tone  is  perceived.  It  is  sometimes  a  whistling 
tone.  The  mode  of  whistling  is,  however,  quite  different 
from  that  of  the  human  being;  for,  while  the  human  being 
whistles  mainly  with  his  lips,  the  cockatoo,  which  is  almost 
void  of  soft  lips,  produces  these  tones  primarily  with  its  vocal 
cords. 

When  any  one  of  the  vocal  responses  of  the  cockatoo  is 
interrupted  by  a  mouth  movement  a  compound  almost 
invariably  results  which  might  well  be  used  in  conventional 
speech.  Many  mouth  movements  are  of  such  slight  ampli- 
tudes that  a  vocal  series  which  is  in  progress  at  the  time  may 
not  be  interrupted  completely,  but  only  slightly  modified 
by  them  at  the  points  of  the  series  where  they  occur.  Further, 
these  movements  are  often  of  considerable  duration.  I 
learned  that  I  could  call  forth  a  large  number  of  these  move- 
ments in  a  desired  order,  and  took  advantage  of  the  situa- 
tion to  teach  a  yellow  crested  cockatoo  to  whistle  recognizably 
a  certain  simple  portion  of  'The  Wearing  of  the  Green.' 
The  cockatoo  had  never  heard  this  melody  until  it  itself 
produced  it.  The  stimulus  I  used  to  modify  the  monotones 


43°  P.  F-  SWINDLE 

which  the  bird  for  some  unknown  reason  frequently  whistled, 
was  a  burning  candle  which  I  moved  in  various  directions 
and  with  various  speeds  before  the  animal.  In  whatever 
direction  the  candle  was  moved,  the  cockatoo  threw  its  head 
or  even  its  entire  body  toward  the  flame.  For  example, 
when  the  candle  was  moved  to  the  left,  the  bird  often  raised 
only  the  left  foot  and  thrust  its  body  in  that  direction. 
Many  of  these  thrust-like  movements  were  accompanied  by 
alterations  in  the  size  of  the  mouth  cavity.  Thus  the  tone 
could  be  modified  successively  in  various  ways.1  The  method 
used  to  cause  the  cockatoo's  tones  to  become  melodious,  also 
caused  it  to  dance  to  the  movements  of  the  flame.  At  other 
times,  i.  e.,  in  the  absence  of  the  candle,  it  danced  as  if  to  the 
tune  it  produced.  At  these  odd  times  the  thrusts  of  the 
head  or  entire  body  were  not  quite  so  pronounced  and  sudden 
as  when  I  called  them  forth  with  the  flame,  and  the  dancing 
was  accordingly  more  graceful  and  the  whistling  more 
melodious. 

I  also  used  various  other  stimuli  which  called  forth  the 
desired  responses  when  properly  moved  before  the  bird, 
but  the  candle  was  the  most  useful  one  I  found.  Some  of 
the  others  were  a  piece  of  ermine  fur,  a  bundle  of  feathers,  a 
frog,  and  a  dead  mouse.  The  burning  candle  was  especially 
adapted  for  this  investigation,  not  merely  because  the  flame 
was  a  stimulus  which  the  bird's  eyes  generally  followed,  but 
because  its  shape  and  size  could  be  varied  with  the  velocity 
of  movement.  When  moved  rapidly,  the  flame  became  very 
small  and  then  flared  when  the  movement  ceased.  I  could 
make  the  flare  of  the  flame  so  disturbing  to  the  bird  that  the 
tone  would  be  interrupted  completely,  which  event  I  avoided 
in  this  particular  experiment. 

There  are  some  very  brief  mouth  movements  manifested 
by  the  cockatoo  which  do  not  interrupt  a  vocal  series  com- 

1  This  particular  bird  was  the  most  suitable  subject  I  found  for  this  experiment. 
Other  cockatoos  responded  to  the  flame  in  a  similar  way,  but  their  movements  toward 
it  were  not  so  pronounced,  and  the  tones  were  not  altered  in  the  same  degree.  I  also 
worked  in  the  same  way  with  a  small  owl,  whose  vocal  utterances  were  more  similar 
to  those  of  the  barbet,  and  determined  that  its  vocal  responses  became  slightly  modified 
at  many  turns  of  the  head. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  43 l 

pletely,  but  only  alter  the  tempo  slightly  and  become  inserted 
between  two  of  the  elements.  Such  a  compound  would  be 
aaapaaaa,  or  eeetee.1  Any  such  mouth  movement  which  can 
be  caused  to  occur  once  in  a  vocal  series,  may  be  caused  to 
occur  twice,  and  if  the  bird  in  a  given  environment  is  stimu- 
lated to  insert  a  p  in  an  ^-series,  it  will  very  probably  be 
stimulated  in  the  same  way  soon  again.  This  is  a  form  of 
natural  training  which  is  evidently  responsible  for  many  of 
the  compounds  spoken  by  wild  cockatoos.  Some  of  the 
more  frequent  of  these  are:  aaapaapaa,  aaaamaaamaa, 
aakaaakaaa,  uutuuutu,  eeemeemeee?  These  activities  are 
not  necessarily  rhythmical,  because  the  mouth  movements 
in  any  case  do  not  necessarily  occur  at  absolutely  regular 
intervals.3 

It  is  not  necessarily  the  case  that  a  vocal  response  becomes 
thus  slightly  modified  two  or  more  times  by  the  same  mouth 
movement.  The  mouth  is  capable  of  executing  a  great 
variety  of  movements,  and  it  is  scarcely  conceivable  that  the 
stimulus  for  only  one  of  these  should  be  present  in  any  given 
environment.  Further,  if  the  bird  should  take  a  step  or 
perhaps  turn  the  head  after  the  mouth  has  moved  the  first 
time,  and  while  the  vocal  response  is  still  in  progress,  such 
an  act  might  create  a  sufficiently  new  environment  for  the 
animal  that  it  would  now  be  exposed  to  a  stimulus  for  a 
decidedly  different  mouth  movement.  Some  of  the  resulting 
compounds  might  be:  aaaa-paaataaaaa,  aaaaaapaaateeeeeee, 

1  Any  series  of  like  letters  not  separated  by  commas  are  meant  to  indicate  ele- 
ments of  a  vocal  response  which  is  only  apparently  continuous. 

2  Perhaps  Binet  and  Simon  had  such  compounds  in  mind  while  investigating 
the  child's  language.     Alfred  Binet  et  Th.   Simon,   'Langage  et  Pensee,'  Uannee 
Psychologique,  1908,  p.  310:    "Comment  pourrait-il  prononcer  des  mots  qu'il  n'a 
jamais  entendu,  et  si  on  ne  les  lui  a  pas  appris  par  une  autre  voie?     II  existe  done, 
au  moment  de  1'elaboration  des  fonctions,  des  relations  nombreuses  entre  les  fonctions 
naissants." 

3  Wundt  calls  special  attention  to  the  fact  of  the  repetitions  in  the  child's  utter- 
ances, but  he  seems  to  think  the  phenomenon  is  due  to  its  appreciation  of  rhythm. 
Wilhelm  Wundt,  'Die  Sprache  und  das  Denken,'  Essays,  Leipzig,  1906,  2.  Aufl.,  S. 
281:    "Eine  primitivste  Ausserung  des  Gefallens  am  Rhythmus  ist  wohl  auch  die 
Neigung  zur  Wiederholung  der  Laute,  durch  die  beinahe  alle  Worter  der  Kinder- 
sprache  zu  Verdoppelungsformen  geworden  sind.     Urspriinglich  sind  aber  die  Wieder- 
holungen  fast  immer  mehrfache,  und  erst  allmahlich  sind  diese  zu  den  gelaufigen 
Verdoppelungen,  Papa,  Mama,  Wau-wau,  u.  dergl.,  verkiirzt  worden." 


43 2  P>  F.  SWINDLE 

eeeteeeepaaa,  aaaaakaaakaaaatuuuu,  and  the  like.  In  the 
last  instance,  e.  g.,  the  w's  follow  the  t  because  the  initial  u 
of  the  w-group  became  at  some  previous  time  associated  in 
this  order  with  the  mouth  movement  responsible  for  the  t; 
and  if  the  bird  does  utter  the  w's,  it  cannot  utter  the  a's  at 
the  same  time.  The  ^-compound,  or  whatever  is  responsible 
for  it,  which  in  this  case  inhibited  a  number  of  a's,  served  the 
same  purpose  as  the  mouth  movement  of  the  barbet:  the 
barbet  was  unable  to  pronounce  the  a's  while  the  mouth  was 
closed,  and  the  cockatoo  was  unable  to  pronounce  the  a's 
while  uttering  the  u's. 

One  reason  why  so  many  of  these  words  more  often  start 
with  a  consonant  than  with  a  vowel,  is  that  the  very  move- 
ment which  opens  a  closed  mouth  to  utter  a  vowel  group  is 
quite  frequently  one  which  is  indispensable  for  many  of  the 
consonants.  If  the  bird  should  be  stimulated  to  utter  the 
series  uuuu  at  a  time  when  the  mouth  is  not  already  in  the 
proper  position  for  this  act,  it  might  be  opened  suddenly 
and  thus  permit  the  cockatoo  to  say  tuuuu,  puuuu,  or  some 
other  consonant.  We  should  look  upon  the  last  three  of  the 
u's  in  either  of  these  cases  as  stutters,  because  they  are  not 
necessary  for  the  perfect  pronunciation  of  the  t  or  p.  The 
letter  t,  as  it  appears  on  paper,  is  only  a  symbol  for  some  one 
of  the  many  forms  of  a  vowel  which  is  modified  by  a  mouth 
movement.  We  can  write  the  letter  t  without  the  vowel 
of  which  it  is  a  modification,  but  while  this  exists  as  a  visual 
stimulus,  it  is  an  impossibility  in  audible  speech.  The 
written  t  of  the  alphabet  signifies  the  ^-compound.  Another 
reason  for  the  fact  that  vocal  responses  so  frequently  start 
with  a  consonant  is  that  the  brief  mouth  movements  essential 
for  the  pronunciation  of  many  of  the  consonants  occur 
much  more  frequently  than  the  vocal  responses;  no  animal 
speaks  every  time  it  opens  its  mouth.  This  means  that  the 
proper  mouth  movement  for  a  given  consonant  often  occurs 
and  modifies  a  vowel  sound,  provided  that  upon  the  opening 
of  the  mouth  there  occurs  a  vocal  response  to  be  thus  modified. 

Many  speech  compounds,  however,  must  start  with  a  vocal 
response.  For  instance,  any  one  of  the  consonants  of  our 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  433 

alphabet,  which  is  not  one  or  another  of  the  vowel  forms 
initiated  by  and  modified  by  at  least  one  mouth  movement, 
is  initiated  by  some  vocal  response,  the  last  element  of  which 
is  modified  by  the  mouth  movement.  This  means  that  some 
of  our  consonants  would  be  impossible  in  verbal  speech  if 
certain  vocal  responses  could  not  be  in  progress  when  the 
significant  mouth  movements  occur.  These  consonants  of 
the  alphabet  are  the  ef-,  ah-,  el-,  em-,  en-,  ar-,  es-,  and  ex- 
compounds.  The  existence  of  such  compounds  as  these 
and  many  other  similar  ones  which  do  not  appear  in  the 
alphabet,  illustrate  clearly  the  impossibility  of  starting  a 
rather  large  number  of  our  conventional  speech  compounds 
with  mouth  movements,  for,  in  these  cases,  the  mouth 
merely  moves  and  modifies  vocal  responses  already  in  prog- 
ress. 

The  vocal  and  mouth  movements  of  the  cockatoo  can  be 
associated  under  controlled  conditions  to  produce  not  only 
the  various  consonant  names,  but  also  great  numbers  of  our 
monosyllables,  and  these  can  in  turn  be  associated  with  one 
another  to  form  larger  compounds  such  as  our  polysyllabic 
words.  A  monosyllable  is  for  the  speaking  organism  just 
as  simple  as,  or  at  least  not  much  more  complex  than,  most 
of  our  consonant  names.  A  monosyllable  in  speech  is  merely 
a  more  or  less  compound  utterance  that  maintains  its  identity 
when  associated  with  other  speech  compounds,  more  often 
than  do  our  consonants,  which  are  also  compounds.  In 
other  words,  a  monosyllable  is  ordinarily  hot  as  variable 
as  a  consonant  name,  and  is  usually  just  as  easily  spoken. 
The  consonant  names  consist  of  a-,  e-,  i-,  o-,  or  ^-groups 
which  are  either  preceded  or  succeeded  by  a  mouth  move- 
ment that  modifies  at  least  one  element  of  the  group.  This 
mouth  movement  is  of  such  magnitude  and  brevity  that  the 
resulting  audible  effect  is  usually  an  explosive  one.  The 
monosyllables  consist  of  like  vowel  groups,  which  may,  how- 
ever, be  preceded  and  also  succeeded  by  the  distinct  mouth 
movements. 

The  vowels,  too,  are  groups  which  are  often  modified  by 
mouth  movements;  the  mouth  frequently  moves  before  as 


434  P>  F-  SWINDLE 

well  as  after  each  vowel  group,  but  these  movements  do  not 
produce  such  explosive  effects  as  in  the  cases  of  the  con- 
sonants and  monosyllables.  Various  tendencies  which  mani- 
fest themselves  when  we  attempt  to  pronounce  the  vowels, 
deserve  emphasis.  In  uttering  a  or  i,  the  a-group  or  z-group 
is  frequently  terminated  in  each  case  by  an  ^-group,  while 
the  ^-group,  on  the  other  hand,  instead  of  being  terminated 
by  an  ^-group,  is  frequently  preceded  by  it.  In  the  face  of 
these  facts  we  are  not  justified  in  writing  for  the  vowels  only 
the  a-,  e-y  i-,  o-,  and  ^-groups,  but  we  must  add  the  ae-^  ie-, 
and  ^-compounds,  as  well  as  others.  These  compounds 
represent  only  three  of  the  so-called  diphthongs  of  speech; 
and  even  they,  depending  in  general  on  whether  they  occur 
at  the  beginning,  in  the  middle,  or  at  the  end  of  our  larger 
speech  compounds  called  words,  are  under  conditions  differ- 
ently pronounced. 

While  the  majority  of  the  mouth  movements  are  such 
as  can  modify  vocal  responses,  it  is  to  be  borne  in  mind  that 
there  are  a  great  number  of  other  bodily  activities  which 
neither  completely  interrupt  nor  modify  in  any  observable 
way  the  audible  vocal  responses.  Some  of  these  are  the 
movements  of  the  tail,  wings,  hands,  feet,  head,  and  eyes. 
True  enough,  these  may  carry  the  body  through  space  and 
cause  the  speaking  organism  to  become  affected  by  a  number 
of  different  stimuli  which  call  forth  various  mouth  move- 
ments. An  eye  movement  may  sometimes  appear  to  alter  a 
vocal  response  which  is  in  progress  when  the  eye  moves,  but  a 
safer  supposition  is  that  it  conditions  a  mouth  movement 
which  interrupts  the  vocal  response  or  modifies  it  in  one 
of  the  other  ways  previously  discussed.  Any  movement  of 
the  body  can  become  associated  either  directly  or  indirectly 
with  a  vocal  response  and  condition  it,  be  conditioned  by  it, 
or  merely  accompany  it;  but  the  mouth  movements  alone 
can  interrupt  it.1  Many  of  the  larger  movements  of  the 
body  which  are  associated  with  vocal  responses,  and  which 
appeal  primarily  to  the  visual  sense,  are  called  gestures;  but 

1  For  reasons  that  ohould  be  obvious,  I  am  considering  only  those  vocal  responses 
which  occur  during  the  period  of  exhalation. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  435 

there  is  really  no  fundamental  distinction  to  be  made  between 
these  and  the  movements  of  the  vocal  cords,  or  of  the  very 
slight  movements  of  the  various  parts  of  the  mouth.  Any 
given  perceptible  response  of  an  animal  organism  becomes  a 
means  of  social  communication  when  it  stimulates  other 
beings  to  behave  in  a  predictable  way.  Some  of  these 
movements  may  be  perceived  with  the  ear,  some  with  the 
eye,  and  some  with  both  eye  and  ear.  It  is  a  matter  of 
insignificance  what  sense  organ  they  affect.  Those  per- 
ceptible movements  which  do  not  call  forth  predictable 
responses  in  other  individuals,  since  they  have  not  become 
conventionalized,  are  nonsense  expressions.  The  process  of 
conventionalizing  responses  for  means  of  communication  is 
nothing  more  nor  less  than  a  process  of  training  the  indi- 
viduals who  are  to  utilize  them  to  stimulate  one  another  for 
calling  forth  predictable  responses.1 

The  human  being  often  stutters  in  a  manner  similar  to 
the  barbet,  but,  as  does  the  cockatoo,  in  such  a  very  rapid 
tempo  that  for  the  hearing  organism  an  apparently  con- 
tinuous tone  results.  He  stutters  thus  either  before  the 
interrupting  mouth  movement  occurs  or  after  it.  The 
tendency  of  the  human  being  to  stutter  in  this  way  is  indeed 
very  great,  as  is  illustrated  by  the  manner  in  which  the 
infant  *  coos'  and  by  the  way  it  later  utters  such  words  as 

m 
maaaaaaaaaa,  or  paaaapaaaaaaaaa.     In  the  earliest  stages  of 

infancy  the  child  does  not  often  begin  these  words  with  m  or  p, 
but,  as  the  cockatoo  often  does,  with  a.  They  should  accord- 

m      m 
ingly  be   written  somewhat  as   follows:   aaaaaaaaaaaaaaaa^ 

aaaaaaapaaaaapaaaaaaaaa.  The  mouth  movement  of  the 
child  which  is  responsible  for  the  m  sound  within  an  ^-series 

1  While  this  point  seems  obvious,  it  has  not  been  given  due  attention  by  the 
investigators  of  speech.  Wundt,  for  example,  in  his  'Physiologische  Psychologic,' 
III.,  S.  285,  says:  "Alle  Ausdrucksbewegungen  geschehen  selbst  beim  Menschen  im 
Anfang  des  Lebens  unwillkiirlich;  sie  sind  teils  Triebhandlungen,  teils  reflectorische 
Bewegungen.  Allmahlich  erst  werden  einzelne  willkurlich  gehemmt,  andere  hervor- 
gebracht,  und  es  entstehen  auf  diese  Weise  willkurliche  Ausdrucksformen;"  and  also, 
S.  452:  "Auch  die  Sprache  ist  in  gewissem  Sinn  eine  form  der  Geberde.  Sie  entwickelt 
sich  wahrscheinlich  teils  als  affectartige,  teils  als  nachahmende  Bewegung." 


43 6  P.  F.  SWINDLE 

merely  occurs  simultaneously  with  one  or  more  #'s  and  does 
not  even  alter  the  tempo  of  the  series  as  does  that  movement 
responsible  for  the  p.  When  the  m  is  uttered  the  ^-series 
continues  as  a  nasal  sound,  which  does  not  occur  with  the 
cockatoo. 

Other  prevalent   compounds    spoken   by   the   child    are: 

m 
aaaapaaakeeeee,    aaaaaaaameeeee,    aaapaapeeee,    aadaaadeeee, 

aaaabaabeee,  aaaaapaaapuuus,  and  the  like.  And  in  reading, 
the  child  says  "Whaat  iiis  thiis?  liit  iiis  aaaaa  hooorse 
aaaand  aaaaa  cooolt.  Caaaan  youuu  riiide  theeee  cooolt? 
Oooh,  no!  liit  iiis  toooo  Kittle."  Stimulate  the  child  by 
telling  it  to  read  more  rapidly,  and  it  will  very  often  pro- 
nounce the  words  so  indistinctly  that  they  can  be  under- 
stood only  with  difficulty.  One  child  which  was  thus  stimu- 
lated seemed  to  read  the  words  as  follows:  "Wat  is  sis? 
It  is  a  hog  and  a  shoat.  Can  you  wide  de  shoat?  Oh,  no! 
It  is  too  witte." 

There  is  moreover  a  second  variety  of  stuttering  which 
is  quite  closely  related  to  stammering.  An  adult  once  asked: 
"I,  i,  i,  i,  is  ti,  ti,  ti,  this  the  ti,  ti,  train  for  A,  A,  A,  A,  A,  A,  A, 
Aurora?"1  If  one  tries  to  stutter  in  this  manner  in  pro- 
nouncing Aurora,  one  easily  observes  that  these  are  not  the 
same,  but  qualitatively  and  quantitatively  different  A's 
which  succeed  one  another;  each  of  these  is  in  reality  an 
y^-group,  seven  of  which  are  nonsense  or  superfluous  ex- 
pressions. The  eight  different  A's  may  be  indicated  as 
follows:  A  A,  AAAAA,  A,  A  A,  AAAA,  A  AAAAA,  A, 
A  A  Aurora,  or,  as  follows:  2-A-,  $-A-,  1-A-,  1-A-,  \-A-, 
6-A-,  i-A-,  3-^-group.  Although  each  group  has  its  accent 
which  is  either  a  mouth  movement  or  a  movement  of  the 
respiratory  muscles,  the  final  accent  of  the  3-^-group  is 
most  easily  observed.  The  speech  compound  represented  by 
the  letters  ro  was  not  associated  with  the  2-,  5-,  I-,  4-,  or  6-, 
but  with  the  final  element  of  the  3-^-group,  and  other 
^-groups  merely  preceded  this  one.  The  expectation  arising 
from  this  view  that  the  individual  would  occasionally  not 

1  As  the  word  Aurora  was  spoken  the  u  was  silent,  and  the  initial  A  was  pro- 
nounced in  the  same  way  as  the  a  of  the  alphabet. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  437 

stutter  in  the  indicated  fashion  in  speaking  Aurora,  is  realized: 
he  does  not  stutter  thus  when  the  3-^-group  is  the  first  one 
of  the  possible  ^-groups  to  occur. 

The  same  fundamental  statements  can  be  made  con- 
cerning the  ti's  that  were  uttered  before  the  word  this  was 
pronounced.  In  this  case  the  mouth  movements  which 
resulted  in  modifying  the  initial  element  of  each  of  the 
^-groups  was  more  pronounced  than  any  of  those  which 
accompanied  the  ^-groups.  When  the  compounds  are  as 
distinct  and  as  explosive  as  these  ta's,  I  shall  call  them  stam- 
mers. There  is  not  the  ^-compound  in  the  word  this,  and 
the  stammerer  who  has  an  image  of  the  word  simply  has  to 
wait  until  he  is  properly  stimulated  to  utter  the  compound 
which  begins  with  the  very  peculiar  mouth  movement  re- 
sponsible for  the  th  sound.  He  would  have  no  trouble  in 
speaking  the  word  if  he  would  in  the  attempt  either  sneeze 
or  imitate  a  sneeze.  All  of  the  various  compounds  which 
appear  as  stammers,  involve  at  least  one  vocal  response  and 
at  least  one  distinct  mouth  movement.  The  failure  to  recog- 
nize the  fact  that  even  the  simplest  stammers  involve  in  each 
case  at  least  one  form  of  a  vowel  group  which  is  modified  by  a 
mouth  movement,  has  led  investigators  of  speech  to  very 
serious  errors.1 

Many  stammers  are  conventionalized  compounds  which 
either  merely  occur  at  inappropriate  times,  or  which  are 
unnecessarily  repeated.  They  are  accordingly  not  only 

1The  following  quotation  taken  from  C.  S.  Bluemel's  'Stammering  and  Cognate 
Speech  Defects,'  L,  p.  187,  is  one  of  many  cases  which  I  could  choose  to  illustrate  this 
point.  "  The  stammerer's  difficulty  is  transient  auditory  amnesia:  he  is  unable  to  recall 
the  sound  image  of  the  vowel  that  he  wishes  to  enunciate.  This  then  is  the  thesis  of 
the  present  monograph.  .  .  .  His  futile  struggles  with  the  initial  consonant  are 
directed  solely  by  his  kinsesthetic  imagery,  but  he  cannot  pass  to  the  vowel  because 
he  cannot  recall  its  sound,  its  peculiar  or  characteristic  quality — in  short,  the  vowel- 
color.  When  he  attempts  to  speak  the  word  ten,  he  produces  the  t  entirely  by  feeling; 
but  he  cannot  mentally  hear  the  sound  e,  and  is  hence  unable  to  proceed."  My  criti- 
cism of  the  thesis  of  the  monograph  is  that  the  stammerer  utters  the  vowel  whether 
or  not  he  recalls  its  sound;  for,  in  his  attempt  to  pronounce  the  word  ten,  his  stutters 
are  generally  a  number  of  ^-compounds.  The  t  which  the  author  has  written,  is 
only  a  visual  stimulus  symbolizing  the  vowel  which  is  modified  by  a  mouth  move- 
ment. The  compound  te  can  be  spoken,  as  the  stutterer  does,  but  we  cannot  utter 
a  t  apart  from  the  e,  e,  or  some  other  vocal  sound. 


43 8  P-  F>  SWINDLE 

often  superfluous,  but  even  harmful  in  speech,  in  so  far  as 
they  distort  the  compounds  which  the  stammerer  is  at- 
tempting to  use  to  call  forth  predictable  responses  in  other 
individuals.  Take,  for  example,  the  compound  'you  know.' 
When  one  says,  "Do  you  know  the  name  of  that  mountain?" 
or,  "You  know  what  I  mean,"  there  is  no  violation  of  a 
conventionality  of  speech;  but,  when  one  says,  "Did  you 
ever,  you  know,  smoke  a  cigar  in  the  wind?"  the  superfluous 
'you  know'  is  a  non-conventionalized  or  stammering  expres- 
sion. Other  common  superfluous  utterances  are  'Well,' 
'Oh,'  'Now  look,'  'Now  listen,'  'Now,'  'Don't  you  think?' 
'Don't  you  know?'  'Isn't  it?'  'Yes  sir!'  and  so  forth.  We 
often  hear  such  meaningless  expressions  before  or  after  a 
sentence,  or  indeed  often  after  mere  phrases  of  it. 

The  simple  fact  that  a  speech  compound  is  at  one  time  a 
nonsense  and  at  another  time  a  sense  expression,  means  that 
our  training  methods  are  not  adequate  to  enable  us  to  use 
all  the  speech  manifestations  of  the  organism  in  all  the 
combinations  they  so  frequently  help  form.  It  is  important 
that  any  nonsense  expression  can  become  conventionalized 
by  training  the  individuals  of  the  social  group  to  respond  in  a 
definite  way  when  stimulated  by  the  expression.  Our  con- 
ventional speech  is  accordingly  reduced  to  a  form  of  stuttering 
and  stammering,  the  stammers  being  the  more  pronounced 
elements.  Some  stutters  and  stammers  are  common  to  a 
greater  number  of  individuals  than  are  others  and  are  conse- 
quently more  highly  conventionalized.  Generally,  only  the 
more  idiosyncratic  utterances  are  superfluous  in  ordinary 
speech. 

A  bald-eyed  cockatoo  was  taught  to  stutter.  It  was  taught 
to  repeat  after  me  the  word  'Kakadu,'  the  German  for 
cockatoo;  but  it  did  not  say  'Kakadu'  immediately:  first  it 
said  'What,'  'Jako,'  'Kak,'  'Kak,'  and  then  'Kakadu.' 
While  the  bird  frequently  uttered  various  compounds  before 
saying  'Kakadu,'  the  training  to  which  I  subjected  it  estab- 
lished this  particular  order.  It  was  also  trained  to  stammer 
in  certain  very  definite,  but  silent  ways  after  the  word 
'Kakadu'  was  spoken.  My  primary  interest  was  in  the 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  439 

speaking  of  the  word  'Kakadu,'  and  I  accordingly  called  all 
those  compounds  which  were  uttered  or  produced  in  any 
other  way  before  and  after  this  word,  stammers.  For  a 
second  observer  the  word  'Kakadu'  might  have  been  only 
one  of  the  stammers  which  regularly  occurred  after  the  word 
'Jako.'  A  wild  cockatoo  may  utter  a  series  of  compounds 
which  become  established  through  self-training;  but  any  one 
of  these  may  be  of  the  same  interest  to  us  as  any  other  one. 
If  we  should  become  able,  by  training  ourselves  for  the 
purpose,  to  respond  in  a  definite  way,  or,  in  other  words, 
to  attribute  a  definite  meaning  to  the  whole  of  such  a  series  of 
compounds,  we  should  be  inclined  to  consider  no  element  of 
it  a  stammer.  Also,  if  the  cockatoo  should  be  taught  a  con- 
ventional sentence  with  a  subject,  a  predicate,  and  so  forth, 
tradition  would  scarcely  permit  us  to  speak  of  stammering 
activities,  in  spite  of  the  fact  that  the  cockatoo  may  not 
have  been  taught  to  use  the  sentence  in  the  conventional  way. 
It  is  a  noteworthy  fact  that  well-established,  convention- 
alized sentences  of  the  human  being  become  frequently  dis- 
torted with  stutters  and  stammers.  It  is  peculiar,  but 
interesting,  that  students  of  ancient  languages,  who  use 
their  knowledge  of  these  to  speak  a  more  correct  English,  do 
not  as  a  rule  speak  fluently;  they  often  pause  in  the  middle 
of  a  sentence  and  insert  a  few  stammering  expressions  before 
going  further.  These  stammers  are  activities  which  inter- 
rupt the  established  series  of  conventionalized  compounds 
and  become  associated  with  some  of  their  elements  just  as 
the  mouth  activity  of  the  barbet  interrupted  a  long  series  of 
innately  associated  a's  and  became  associated  with  the 
fourteenth  or  final  a  of  the  14-^-group.  Those  Greek  and 
Latin  scholars  who,  according  to  their  introspections,  do  not 
attempt  to  use  their  knowledge  of  these  languages  while 
speaking  their  mother  tongue,  may  speak  as  fluently  as  other 
people.  The  fact  that  our  Greek  and  Latin  scholars  may  and 
usually  do  speak,  provided  we  neglect  their  non-convention- 
alized stammers,  a  more  grammatical  English,  and  also  that 
they  may  possess  an  extraordinarily  large  and  varied  vocabu- 
lary, has  nothing  to  do  with  our  present  problem.  A  student 


44°  P.  F.  SWINDLE 

of  logic  may  make  fewer  fallacies  in  his  reasoning;  that  is, 
his- responses  may  conform  more  with  convention,  by  having 
studied  logic;  but  a  logician  who  attempts  to  apply  his 
principles  of  logic  and  to  speak  fluently  at  the  same  time  will 
acquire  habits  of  stammering.  Stimuli  which  may  cause 
a  person  to  stammer  thus,  may  have  many  sources. 

A  non-excited  person  may  say  Aurora,  but  when  in  a 
state  of  excitement  he  may  say  A,  A,  A,  A,  A,  A,  A,  Aurora. 
These  A's  represent  eight  qualitatively  different  ^-groups 
which  became  isolated  from  different  parts  of  an  ^-series 
which  can  be  represented  as  follows  with  the  potentially 
adequate  stimulus  for  each  A  underneath  it:  A  A  A  A  A  A 

a1  a2  a3  a4  a5  a6 

AAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAAA.  When 
a7  a8  a9  a10  a11  a12  a13  a14  a15  a16  a17  a18  a19  a20  a21  a22  a23  a24 
the  stimulus  a1  is  presented  the  first  A  is  conditioned  by  it, 
the  second  A  is  conditioned  by  the  first,  the  third  by  the 
second,  and  so  on.  If  a1  should  be  removed  as  soon  as  the 
first  A  is  conditioned,  the  after-response  would  consist  of 
the  remaining  twenty-three  A's.  If  a5  were  the  stimulus 
presented,  the  fifth  A  would  be  conditioned  by  it,  and  the 
after-response  would  consist  of  the  last  nineteen  A's.  There 
are  experimental  and  also  theoretical  reasons  for  asserting 
that  a5  can  be  presented  repeatedly  without  bringing  about  a 
dissociation  of  the  fourth  and  fifth  A's,  but  in  this  discussion 
we  do  not  need  to  consider  why  it  should  be  the  case.  If  the 
24-^-series  appears  more  frequently  than  any  of  its  parts, 
this  means  either  that  a1  is  a  stimulus  which  affects  the 
organism  more  frequently  than  does  any  one  of  the  other 
stimuli,  or  that  the  first  A  is  conditioned  not  only  by  a1,  but 
also  by  one  or  more  frequently  occurring  responses  which 
have  become  associated  with  and  precede  the  first  A.  It 
may  well  be  the  case  that  of  the  potentially  adequate  stimuli 
here  represented  for  the  different  A's,  a1  is  the  only  one 
present  in  a  given  environment.  If  then,  while  the  series 
is  in  progress,  a  mouth  movement  should  occur  and  isolate 
the  first  three  A's  from  the  remainder  of  the  series,  the 
3-y^-group  only  will  occur  as  long  as  the  person  remains  in 
the  given  environment. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  44 l 

If  the  individual  should  shift  to  a  new  environment  and 
become  affected  by  a4,  the  2i-^-series  will  occur  and  become 
habitualized,  because  the  initial  A  of  this  series  will  become 
associated  with  and  later  be  conditioned  by  the  response 
which  happened  to  occur  immediately  before  it.  This  acci- 
dental response  will  now  serve  as  a  substitute  for  the  ^-A- 
group  which  became  previously  isolated  from  the  original 
series.  We  could  proceed  in  the  same  way  until  we  get 
the  series  broken  up  into  a  number  of  fragments  or  unitary 
groups  each  of  which  maintains  its  identity  in  many  different 
environments  by  occurring  more  frequently  as  a  whole  than 
in  parts.  These  unitary  fragments  of  the  original  series 
may  be  the  3-^-,  5-^-,  i-A-,  2-A-,  4-^-,  6-A-,  2-A-,  and 
l-^-groups.  If  it  should  be  such  a  compound  activity  as 
rora  (I  omit  the  u  because  it  is  silent  in  the  spoken  word 
Aurora),  which  isolated  the  3-^-group  from  the  original 
series  and  became  associated  with  the  final  element  of  this 
group,  the  individual  would  be  able  to  pronounce  the  word 
Aurora  only  when  the  3-^-group  occurs.  If  it  should  happen 
that  while  he  has  an  image  of  the  word  he  should  be  stimu- 
lated to  produce  the  5-^-group,  which  is  not  associated  with 
the  3-y^-group,  at  least  one  more  effort  would  have  to  be 
made  before  the  word  could  be  pronounced. 

Let  us  suppose  that  the  individual  happens  to  be  in  an 
environment  in  which  the  stimulus  for  only  the  3-^-group 
is  present.  He  would  succeed  at  the  first  effort  to  pronounce 
the  word.  If  he  should  pass  to  a  new  environment  which 
contains  the  stimuli  for  all  the  groups,  he  might  by  chance 
have  to  make  many  efforts.  Now  it  does  not  matter  whether 
he  actually  passes  into  a  new  environment  or  whether  these 
stimuli  are  introduced  into  the  old  one,  leaving  it  otherwise 
unchanged.  It  would  be  the  same  if  they  should  be  secreted 
by  his  own  body.  Perhaps  they  are  under  certain  conditions 
secreted  by  some  of  the  ductless  glands  of  his  body.  Perhaps 
some  of  the  hormones  secreted  under  conditions  of  excitement 
are  adequate  stimuli  to  condition  a  number  of  the  super- 
fluous ^-groups  while  he  has  an  image  of  the  word  Aurora. 
It  is  thinkable  that  the  hormone  secretion  could  be  of  such  a 


443  P-  f.  SWINDLE 

nature  that  if  it  should  not  call  forth  all  the  ^-groups  simul- 
taneously, it  might  cause  them  to  occur  in  very  rapid  suc- 
cession. In  the  first  case  a  'boisterous'  A  sound  of  relatively 
short  duration  would  result,  and,  if  the  final  accents  of  the 
superfluous  ^-groups  should  be  relatively  insignificant  for 
the  hearing  organism,  it  might  seem  in  the  second  case  as 
if  one  long  A  were  being  uttered  before  the  word  Aurora  is 
pronounced.  A  hormone  which  is,  under  certain  conditions 
of  stimulation,  thrown  into  the  blood,  may  be  analogous  to 
a  response  which  a  training  in  logic,  Greek,  or  Latin  has 
caused  to  occur  quite  frequently  and  necessarily  interrupt  at 
times  either  an  instinctive  vocal  series  or  an  habitualized 
series  of  speech  compounds. 

Out  of  the  previous  discussions  arises  the  practical  problem 
as  to  the  surest  and  most  economical  means  of  breaking  an 
individual  of  stuttering  or  stammering.  In  order  to  solve 
this  problem  we  should  become  thoroughly  acquainted  with 
the  process  of  teaching  a  subject  to  stammer.  I  noticed 
that  when  I  stepped  noiselessly  to  the  bald-eyed  cockatoo's 
room  and,  before  opening  the  door,  said  'Kakadu,'  the  bird 
said  'What,'  and  when  I  said  'What,'  the  bird  said  'Kakadu.' 
When  I  rattled  the  door  knob  or  opened  the  door  without 
showing  myself,  the  cockatoo  said  'Jako,'  when  I  jerked  its 
cage  with  a  string  it  said  'Kak,'  and  when  I  suddenly  ap- 
peared in  the  room  before  the  bird,  it  said  'Kakadu,'  after 
which  it  began  beating  a  horizontal  bar  of  the  cage  with  its 
beak,  becoming  then  active  in  a  number  of  other  ways. 
In  the  course  of  time  I  found  many  stimuli  which  called  forth 
the  mentioned  responses;  but  I  made  use  only  of  the  par- 
ticular ones  here  given.  Before  the  bird  was  aware  of  my 
presence  outside  its  door  I  called  out  'Kakadu!,'  opened  the 
door  without  showing  myself,  jerked  the  cage  twice  in  suc- 
cession, and  then  entered  the  room  suddenly.  After  each 
stimulus  the  bird  made  a  verbal  response,  the  entire  series 
of  which  was  'What,  Jako,  Kak,  Kak,  Kakadu,'  after  which 
it  beat  the  horizontal  bar  with  its  beak.  It  was  necessary 
for  me  to  carry  out  this  program  several  times  each  day  for 
about  three  weeks  before  the  bird  pronounced  the  series 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  443 

regularly  without  error  when  I  spoke  the  word  'Kakadu.' 
I  discovered  that  after  the  series  was  well  established  I  no 
longer  had  to  go  through  with  the  ordeal  of  stimulating  the 
bird  by  calling  out  the  word  'Kakadu'  while  still  outside  the 
door;  I  could  remain  in  the  bird's  room  for  some  time  and 
then  utter  the  word  'Kakadu,'  and  the  series  would  be  spoken 
just  as  perfectly  as  when  I  called  through  the  door. 

At  the  end  of  two  months  I  employed  the  following  means 
to  break  up  completely  this  series  of  associated  speech  com- 
pounds. I  said  'Kakadu'  repeatedly  and  as  rapidly  as  I 
could  for  several  minutes  during  each  period,  and  after  about 
three  days  this  stimulus  no  longer  served  to  instigate  the 
series.  However,  when  I  rattled  the  door  knob,  the  cockatoo 
omitted  'What'  and  began  the  series  with  'Jako.'  I  then 
presented  this  stimulus  repeatedly  without  long  pauses  until 
it  likewise  became  ineffective.  As  soon  as  this  task  was 
accomplished,  I  repeatedly  jerked  the  cage  with  the  string 
until  this  stimulus  was  no  longer  effective.  Of  the  three 
tasks,  the  last  one  was  the  most  difficult  to  accomplish. 
When  the  series  was  thus  completely  broken  up  and  I  spoke 
the  word  'Kakadu,'  the  bird  generally  said  something,  but 
not  always  'What,'  as  it  did  before  the  training,  and  it  said 
'Kakadu'  no  more  frequently  than  it  did  'Jako,'  'Kak,' 
'Ohoh,'  'Adieu,'  or  almost  any  of  the  many  other  sense  or 
nonsense  words  which  it  could  utter.  Now,  when  it  said 
anything  other  than  'Kakadu,'  I  repeated  the  stimulus  for 
some  time,  and  as  soon  as  the  bird  said  'Kakadu,'  I  made  a 
long  pause  before  restimulating  it  in  the  same  way.  This 
procedure  was  necessary  in  order  to  make  the  cockatoo  act 
as  if  it  were  imitating  me.  Before  I  could  bring  about  this 
apparent  imitation  it  was  necessary  for  me  to  cause  the 
rather  complex  stimulus  used  to  become  ineffective  for  a 
considerable  number  of  stammers.  I  have  applied  this 
method  of  dissociation  with  equal  success  in  various  other 
fields  of  behavior. 

If  we  now  desire  to  apply  the  method  to  the  human 
stutterer  or  stammerer,  we  should  proceed  somewhat  as 
follows.  Paradoxical  as  it  may  sound,  we  should  present  in 


444  P-  F-  SWINDLE 

rapid  succession  the  adequate  stimuli  for  the  undesired 
activities.  If  we  cannot  find  or  cannot  control  the  most 
adequate  ones  for  these  responses,  we  should  use  those  less 
adequate  ones  which  we  do  have  at  our  command.  For 
example,  when  a  person,  attempting  to  speak  a  word,  stutters 
or  stammers,  we  should  simply  stimulate  him  by  telling  him 
to  do  that  same  thing  again  and  again,  perhaps  a  hundred 
or  a  thousand  times  in  rapid  succession.  But  care  must  be 
taken  that  he  does  the  same  thing  and  not  something  which 
may  be  only  very  similar  to  the  particular  undesired  act. 
After  he  has  repeated  the  act  a  great  number  of  times,  he 
should  then  be  stimulated  to  pronounce  the  word  which  was 
previously  preceded  by  the  undesired  activity.  It  is  essential 
that  he  should  make  a  pause  of  at  least  a  minute  each  time 
before  he  repeats  the  word;  otherwise,  this  word,  too,  will 
appear  less  frequently  and  will  not  always  be  recalled  at  the 
significant  places  for  it  in  ordinary  speech.  This  process  of 
dissociation  will  not  effect  an  absolute  forgetting  of  the 
undesired  responses,  but  will  cause  them  to  occur  less  fre- 
quently at  the  inappropriate  places. 

It  is  to  be  emphasized  that  this  dissociation  does  not  mean 
an  absolute  forgetting  of  any  activity.  In  the  case  of  the 
cockatoo,  for  instance,  each  of  the  relatively  forgotten  or 
dissociated  elements  of  the  series  of  speech  compounds,  was 
later  spoken  at  times  just  as  perfectly  as  previously.  Ex- 
cepting the  word  'Kakadu,'  each  of  the  compounds  occurred 
less  frequently  than  before  the  dissociations  were  accom- 
plished. This  relative  forgetting  brought  about  by  con- 
tinued stimulation  is  sometimes  spoken  of  as  'forgetting 
with  experience.'1  We  have  no  reason  for  supposing  that 
any  of  the  organic  structures  involved  in  the  so-called  for- 
gotten responses  became  annihilated.  Owing  to  the  fact 
that  the  recuperation  pauses  were  made  as  short  as  possible, 
certain  structures  involved  became  at  least  temporarily 
simplified  to  such  an  extent  that  they  later  functioned  only 
upon  the  presentation  of  very  particular,  and,  naturally,  a 
smaller  number  of  stimuli;  the  structures  became  'immuned' 

1  See  for  example,  H.  Pieron,  'L'oubli  chez  la  Limnee,'  Archives  de  Psychologie, 
No.  33,  Tome  IX.,  1909. 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  445 

to  certain  stimuli.  The  simple  fact  that  a  person  can  stutter 
and  stammer  when  properly  stimulated  to  do  so  is  significant 
in  this  connection.  The  fact  that  an  expert  rope  walker 
returns  to  an  amateur  level  of  performance  the  very  moment 
he,  as  we  ordinarily  say,  'gives  serious  thought  to  what  he 
is  doing/  is  a  phenomenon  of  the  same  category.  The 
simplification  of  certain  of  the  organic  structures  involved 
in  a  given,  desired  response  to  bring  about  its  dissociation 
from  other  undesired  responses,  is,  I  believe,  the  fundamental 
principle  underlying  the  facts  of  dissociation  or  relative 
forgetting,  the  automaticity  of  certain  responses,  and  a  few 
other  related  phenomena;  but  it  would  not  be  appropriate  to 
attempt  the  explanation  in  this  paper.  I  have  merely 
inserted  this  view  as  a  suggestion  that  my  method  of  breaking 
up  such  undesired  activities  as  those  of  stuttering  or  stammer- 
ing can  be  explained  without  assuming  the  annihilation  or 
permanent  exhaustion  of  any  of  the  structures  involved. 

CONCLUSION 

Speech  instincts  and  habits  are  the  perceptible  responses 
manifested  by  an  individual  which  serve  primarily  as  auditory 
and  visual  stimuli  to  call  forth  responses  in  other  individuals. 
These  stimuli  are  vocal  utterances,  mouth  movements  which 
modify  audibly  the  vocal  responses,  and  the  larger  bodily 
movements  which  affect  primarily  the  visual  sense. 

A  vocal  instinct  is  a  series  of  innately  associated  elements 
which  presents  a  gradual,  qualitative  change  from  the  initial 
to  the  final  element.  Any  vocal  instinct  may  be  called  a 
vowel  series.  There  exist  besides  the  a-,  e-,  i-,  o-,  and  u- 
series,  a  number  of  vocal  instincts  which  may  be  indicated 
by  appropriate  diacritical  markings  of  the  vowels  of  the 
alphabet.  But  a  marking  which  designates  the  sound  of 
the  first  few  elements  of  a  series  is  often  quite  inappropriate 
for  the  last  few  elements  of  the  same  series.  For  this  reason, 
diacritical  markings  should  also  be  employed  to  symbolize, 
e.  g.,  the  different  a  sounds  which  can  frequently  be  detected 
between  the  initial  and  final  elements  of  a  given  ^-series. 
Theoretically,  if  the  anatomy  were  such  that  an  a-series 


446  P-  F-  SWINDLE 

would  not  be  prematurely  interrupted  by  exhalations,  there 
should  occur  within  this  series  all  the  a  sounds  which  the 
organism  can  utter.  The  gradual,  qualitative  changes  of  the 
fl's  within  the  longest  <2-series  of  the  barbet  support  this 
supposition. 

A  vocal  response  is  a  habit,  as  well  as  an  instinct,  when 
it  is  caused  to  occur  more  frequently  than  originally.  The 
process  of  habitualizing  a  vocal  response  is  a  process  of 
training  which  causes  the  instinct  to  become  the  final  accent 
or  conclusion  of  one  or  more  responses  which  originally  did 
not  regularly  precede  and  did  not  condition  the  initial  ele- 
ment of  the  vocal  instinct.  The  whole  or  any  fragment  of 
an  instinct  is  not  necessarily  a  habit,  but  a  habit  is  invariably 
an  instinct. 

Vocal  responses  are  essential  for  audible  speech  and  are 
accordingly  speech  instincts  and  habits. 

Mouth  movements  serve  to  interrupt  vocal  instincts  and 
habits  and  isolate  fragments  or  unitary  groups  of  elements 
from  them.  A  given  mouth  movement  which  isolates  a 
unitary  group  from  a  longer  series  of  a's  becomes  at  the  same 
time  associated  with  the  final  a  of  the  isolated  group  and  is 
later  conditioned  by  it.  This  instinctive  mouth  movement 
which  becomes  the  final  accent  or  conclusion  of  the  isolated 
fl-group,  is  thus  caused  to  occur  more  frequently  than  origin- 
ally and  is  accordingly  a  habit  as  well  as  an  instinct. 

There  are  many  mouth  movements  of  such  slight  ampli- 
tude and  of  such  brief  duration  that  they  may  not  completely 
interrupt  a  vocal  response,  but  merely  modify  it  slightly. 
Such  mouth  movements  may  only  modify  slightly  the  tempo 
of  certain  elements  of  a  vocal  series  and  become  inserted 
between  two  of  them,  as  in  aaaaaaapaaaaa,  or  they  may 
occur  simultaneously  with  one  or  more  of  the  elements,  as  in 

m 
aaaaaaaaaaaaaaa. 

Mouth  movements  are  as  essential  for  audible  speech 
compounds  as  are  the  vocal  responses  and  should  likewise  be 
reckoned  among  the  speech  instincts  and  habits. 

Larger  movements  of  the  hands,  feet,  head,  and  body  in 
general,  serve  to  carry  the  organism  through  space  and  cause 


SPEECH  INSTINCTS  AND  HABITS  447 

it  to  become  affected  by  a  variety  of  stimuli  which  may  not 
occur  in  any  given  environment.  Many  of  these  stimuli 
call  forth  mouth  movements  and  vocal  responses  which  be- 
come the  final  accents  or  conclusions  of  the  movements  of 
transportation  and  are  later  conditioned  by  them.  Further, 
the  less  perceptible  movements  of  the  eyes  serve  the  same 
purpose. 

All  of  the  bodily  movements  which  cause  mouth  move- 
ments and  vocal  responses  to  occur  more  frequently,  should 
also  be  called  speech  instincts  and  habits. 

Any  instinctive  or  habitual  response  of  an  organism  is  a 
means  of  social  communication  if  it  is  used  to  stimulate 
individuals  of  known  training  to  behave  in  a  way  which  can 
be  predicted  from  the  nature  of  the  stimulus.  In  discussing 
speech  instincts  and  habits,  it  was  necessary  to  discuss  some 
problems  of  stuttering  and  stammering,  because  our  con- 
ventional speech  is  only  a  form  of  behavior  of  which  stutters^, 
stammers,  and  larger  bodily  movements  are  the  elements^ 
When  these  elements  of  speech  are  conventionalized,  tLey 
are  ordinarily  called  letters,  monosyllables,  words,  sentences, 
and  gestures.  A  series  of  innately  associated  stutters  which 
is  modified  by  one  or  more  mouth  movements  to  produce 
such  a  speech  compound  as  a  consonant  or  a  monosyllable, 
is  a  stammer.  A  number  of  like  or  unlike  stammers  may  be 
combined  through  association  to  form  larger  speech  com- 
pounds, such  as  polysyllabic  words  and  series  of  words;  but 
these  are  merely  stammers  of  a  higher  order.  The  process  of 
conventionalizing  a  stutter,  a  stammer,  a  number  of  associ- 
ated stammers,  or  any  other  simple  or  compound  response, 
is  a  process  of  training  the  individuals  who  are  to  utilize 
these  to  call  forth  predictable  responses  in  one  another. 

Any  artificially  combined  series  of  speech  compounds  can 
be  interrupted  in  the  same  way  as  can  an  innately  associated 
series  of  simple  elements;  and  a  response  which  either  com- 
pletely interrupts  a  conventional  series  or  merely  becomes 
inserted  between  two  of  its  compound  elements,  is  analogous 
to  a  mouth  movement  which  either  completely  interrupts  or 
merely  changes  slightly  the  tempo  of  movement  of  a  vocal 


448  P-  F-  SWINDLE 

instinct.  Those  responses  which  occur  most  frequently  are 
most  likely  to  interrupt  the  conventional  series.  A  training 
in  ancient  languages  or  in  logic  may  cause  them  to  occur 
frequently.  A  hormone  secretion  may  affect  the  speaking 
organism  in  a  similar  way. 

It  seemed  appropriate  to  present  a  method  to  diminish 
the  frequency  of  superfluous  utterances,  which  are  undesired 
stutters  and  stammers.  This  method  consists  in  presenting 
appropriate  stimuli  to  cause  the  patient  to  produce  a  given 
nonsense  or  superfluous  expression  repeatedly  without  the 
intervention  of  long  pauses  until  at  least  a  large  number  of 
the  stimuli  for  the  superfluous  act  cease  to  call  it  forth. 
This  results  not  in  an  absolute,  but  only  in  a  relative  for- 
getting of  the  undesired  response.  It  was  finally  suggested 
that  the  fact  of  relative  forgetting  of  the  superfluous  response 
is  due  to  a  dissociation  of  certain  organic  structures  involved; 
that  this  dissociation  is  in  turn  a  result  of  a  simplification 
or  purification  of  the  structures;  and  that  these  phenomena 
can  be  consequently  explained  without  assuming  the  anni- 
hilation or  even  the  permanent  exhaustion  of  any  of  the 
structures  which  function  to  produce  the  nonsense  expression. 


A  PRELIMINARY  REPORT  ON   'WORK  WITH 

KNOWLEDGE  VERSUS   WORK  WITHOUT 

KNOWLEDGE   OF   RESULTS' 

BY  GEORGE  F.  ARPS 

Ohio  State  University 

The  primary  purpose  of  this  study  is  to  secure  a  quanti- 
tative statement  of  the  influence  of  awareness  as  a  factor  in 
work.1  To  this  end  three  sets  of  experiments  were  conducted 
by  means  of  the  Bergstrom  ergograph.  In  each  of  the  sets 
the  observer  at  one  time  remains  in  comparative  ignorance 
(complete  so  far  as  it  is  possible  to  make  it  so)  of  the  amount 
and  character  of  the  work  he  is  doing;  at  another  time  he  is 
given  every  opportunity  to  observe  his  work  as  it  proceeds 
and  to  study  the  results  ad  libitum.  Each  set  of  experiments 
is  therefore  divided  into  two  series,  designated  'unknown' 
and  'known'  respectively.  A  series  is  made  up  of  work 
periods. 

The  mental  complexes,  antecedent  to  the  work  response 
in  the  various  series  of  experiments,  are  sufficiently  diverse 
to  prompt  an  inquiry  concerning  the  meaning  of  this  diversity 
in  terms  of  work  units. 

Three  observers,  M,  /  and  W,  functioned  in  the  experi- 
ments; in  the  case  of  M,  experimentation  continued  over 
the  greater  part  of  three  years.  The  method  common  to 
ergographic  work  prevailed.  In  our  case  the  hand  and  arm 
of  the  observer  were  strapped  into  the  machine  in  such  a  way 
as  to  secure  maximum  freedom  for  the  middle  finger  (the 
work-finger  of  our  experiments)  of  the  right  hand. 

The  instructions  given  each  observer  were  simple.  In  the 
first  work  period  he  was  instructed  to  pull  the  ergographic 
load  on  every  beat  of  the  metronome,  sixty  to  the  minute. 
This  load  was  4  kilograms  for  the  first  two  sets  of  experiments 

1  The  study  will  in  no  wise  concern  itself  with  the  theoretical  aspects  of  the  con- 
troversial question  of  the  relation  of  the  psychical  to  the  physical. 

449 


45°  GEORGE  F.  ARPS 

and  6  kilograms  for  the  third  set.  The  observer  was  re- 
peatedly instructed  to  make  each  lift  represent  his  maximal 
pull  and  to  continue  the  lifting  until  he  was  no  longer  able 
to  budge  the  load.  The  work  period  closed  when  the  ob- 
server failed  to  move  the  load  in  two  successive  attempts. 
In  the  second  work  period,  forty-eight  hours  later,  the  ob- 
server was  instructed  to  lift  the  load  for  ten  successive  beats 
of  the  metronome  and  then  to  rest  for  one  second  (one  beat) 
then  to  lift  again  for  ten  beats  followed  by  another  rest  of 
one  second.  This  process  was  repeated  until  the  observer, 
as  in  the  first  work  period,  was  unable  to  budge  the  load. 
The  third  work  period  of  this  series  differed  from  that  of  the 
second  in  that  the  rest  period  was  increased  by  one  second 
(one  beat).  In  each  successive  work  period  of  this  series 
the  rest  increased  by  one  second.  There  are  eleven  work 
periods  in  each  series.  This  procedure  prevailed  as  well  for 
the  work  periods  in  which  the  observer  was  relatively  un- 
aware of  his  accomplishments  as  for  those  periods  during 
which  he  was  fully  aware.  The  procedure  for  any  ascending 
series  may  be  algebraically  represented  by  the  following 
formula: 


/F+£o'     W+RS    W  +  R^  W +  Rlo' 

in  which  P  represents  ten  ergographic  lifts;  W  +  R^  a  work 
period  without  rest;  W  +  jRi,  one  second  rest,  etc.,  until  the 
number  of  lifts  and  the  number  of  rests  are  equal. 

A  'set'  of  experiments  is  made  up  of  (a)  an  ascending 
series  of  work  periods  in  which  the  periods  differ  increasingly 
by  one  second  of  rest  up  to  ten  as  a  maximum,  and  (b)  a 
descending  series  in  which  the  periods  differ  decreasingly  by 
one  second  until  there  are  no  rests.  Graphically  they  may 
be  represented  as  follows: 

->  Ascending  Series,  Known. 
Rests  =  o,  i,  2,  3,  4,  5,  6,  7,  8,  9,  10. 

->  Ascending  Series,  Unknown. 

— >  Descending  Series,  Unknown. 
Rests  =  10,  9,  8,  7,  6,  5,  4,  3,  2,  i,  o. 

->  Descending  Series,  Known. 


WORK  WITH  AND  WITHOUT  KNOWLEDGE  OF  RESULTS     45 l 

Care  was  taken  to  distribute  as  equitably  as  possible  the 
effect  of  practice.  The  disadvantage,  for  example,  accruing 
to  the  known  in  the  ascending  series  of  the  first  set  was 
practically  neutralized  by  beginning  the  second  set  of  experi- 
ments with  an  unknown  ascending  series.  Other  advantages 
and  disadvantages  are  similarly  neutralized,  as,  for  example, 
the  disadvantage  of  the  so-called  phenomenon  of  ' breaks' 
which  occurs  between  the  conclusion  of  certain  of  the  series 
and  the  beginning  of  certain  other  series.  It  will  be  seen 
from  the  above  graphically  represented  series  that  the  con- 
cluding work  period  of  the  ascending  known  series  contains 
an  equal  number  of  ergographic  pulls  and  rests.  The  be- 
ginning work  period  of  the  immediately  succeeding  series 
contains  no  rests.  This  transition  from  a  work  period  con- 
taining ten  rests  in  each  of  its  subdivisions  to  a  period  con- 
taining no  rests  is  termed  a  *  break.'  Obviously  it  is  im- 
portant to  distribute  such  breaks  equally  to  the  known  and 
unknown  series. 

In  the  three  sets  of  experiments  there  are  six  unknown 
and  six  known  series,  which  together  constitute  112  work 
periods.  In  the  third  set  of  experiments  the  number  of  work 
periods  in  each  series  is  six.  Each  of  these  periods  has  an 
absolute  and  a  unit  efficiency  value.  Both  values  are  ex- 
plained under  the  tables  given  below. 

Tables  I.  and  II.  set  forth  the  two  values  of  the  twenty- 
two  work  periods  of  two  of  the  series  and  other  data  which 
may  serve  in  presenting  a  survey  of  this  study. 
Some  of  the  important  results  are  as  follows : 

1.  The  final  average  of  the  absolute  efficiency  values  of 
all  the  known  series  of  the  first  and  second  sets  of  experi- 
ments exceeds  that  of  the  unknown  by  .2  per  cent. 

2.  The  final  average  of  the  unit  efficiency  values  of  all 
the   known  series,  excepting  the  third  set  of  experiments, 
excels  that  of  the  unknown  by  7  per  cent.     In  the  known 
work  periods  the  observers  work  at  a  higher  rate  of  speed. 

3.  The  average  absolute  efficiency  value  of  all  the  known 
series  exceeds  that  of  the  unknown  by  10  per  cent. 

4.  The  average  absolute  efficiency  value  of  the  known 


45  2 


GEORGE  F.  ARPS 


series  of  the  first  and  second  set  of  experiments  exceeds  that 
of  the  corresponding  unknown  by  10  per  cent. 

5.  The  average  absolute  efficiency  value  of  the  known 
series  of  the  third  set  of  experiments  exceeds  that  of  the 
corresponding  unknown  by  10  per  cent.  (The  ergograph 
load  in  this  set  is  6  kilograms.) 

TABLES  I.  AND  II. 

FIRST  ASCENDING  KNOWN.    LOAD  4  KILOGRAMS  (OBSERVER  M) 


c 

III 

C+III 

B 

0 

i 

0 

<n 

7 

a* 

S 

8 

</> 

a 
§ 

J 

z> 

w 

w 
~c 

w 

MWJ 

WP 

C+III 

I 

i 

57 

o 

0 

0 

I 

57 

1.665 

6.66 

.0569 

.0569 

•0595 

•0595 

12 

i 

53 

i 

0 

ii 

2 

4 

2.073 

8.29 

.0733 

.0669 

.0805 

.0737 

II 

i 

46 

2 

o 

20 

2 

6 

2.330 

9-32 

.0879 

.0740 

.0878 

•0735 

12 

i 

56 

3 

o 

33 

2 

29 

2.276 

9.10 

.0785 

.0610 

.0854 

•0338 

21 

3 

37 

4 

I 

24 

5 

I 

4.877 

19-51 

.0899 

.0649 

.0828 

.0605 

24 

3 

59 

5 

I 

55 

5 

54 

5-710 

22.84 

•0954 

.0646 

.0883 

.0614 

23 

3 

49 

6 

2 

12 

6 

i 

5-447 

21.79 

.0949 

.0603 

.0859 

•0549 

32 

5 

16 

7 

3 

37 

8 

53 

6.144 

24-57 

.0776 

.0461 

.0789 

.0481 

32 

c 

27 

8 

4 

8 

9 

3<5 

8.482 

33-93 

.1008 

.0589 

.0908 

.0627 

54 

8 

59 

9 

7 

57 

16 

s6 

13.921 

55-68 

.1003 

.0548 

.0917 

•0497 

55 

9 

17 

10 

9 

o 

18 

17 

13-693 

54-77 

.0985 

.0500 

.0917 

.0465 

FIRST  ASCENDING  UNKNOWN.    LOAD  4  KILOGRAMS 


I 

I 

20 

0 

0 

o 

I 

20 

2.162 

8.65 

.1008 

.1008 

.0705 

.0725 

II 

I 

54 

I 

0 

IO 

2 

4 

2.642 

10-57 

.0926 

.0851 

.0893 

.0788 

13 

2 

18 

2 

o 

24 

2 

42 

2.905 

11.62 

.0843 

.0717 

.0876 

•0793 

15 

2 

25 

3 

o 

42 

3 

7 

3.101 

12.40 

.0856 

.0664 

.0747 

•0595 

21 

3 

35 

4 

i 

20 

4 

55 

4.382 

17-53 

.0816 

•0593 

.0707 

•0579 

33 

5 

26 

5 

2 

40 

8 

6 

5-734 

22.94 

.0703 

.0471 

.0714 

.0479 

21 

3 

35 

6 

2 

0 

5 

35 

4-339 

17.36 

.0806 

.0518 

.0708 

•0454 

40 

6 

37 

7 

4 

33 

ii 

10 

6.746 

26.98 

.0679 

.0402 

.0677 

.0407 

64 

10 

40 

8 

8 

24 

19 

4 

9.781 

39-12 

.0612 

.0342 

.0624 

•0350 

101 

16 

52 

9 

IS 

o 

3i 

52 

19.528 

78.11 

.0771 

.0408 

.0658 

•0350 

90 

15 

o 

10 

15 

o 

30 

o 

17-584 

70.34 

.0781 

.0407 

.0692 

•0354 

B 
C 
/ 

Ill 

C  +  III 
D 
W 


W 


,       TTT 

Cx   -p  111 

MWJ 
WP 


Number  of  subdivisions  of  work  periods. 

Total  time  at  work. 

Length  of  rest  period  in  seconds  and  number  of  the  period. 

Total  rest  time. 

Total  time  of  work  and  rest. 

Distance  load  travels  in  meters. 

Work  done  in  kilogram  meters. 

Unit  value  per  second  of  work  done  each  period. 

Rate  of  work  including  the  rest  time. 

Average  unit  value  (WIC}  of  all  observers. 

Average  rate  of  work  per  second  for  each  period  including  the  rest  time. 


WORK   WITH  AND   WITHOUT  KNOWLEDGE  OF  RESULTS     453 


6.  The  average  unit  value  of  the  known  series  of  all  sets 
of  experiments  shows  a  higher  rate  of  work  by  18  per  cent, 
over  the  corresponding  value  of  the  unknown  series. 

7.  The   average   unit  value  of  the   known   series  of  the 
first  and  second  sets  of  experiments  shows  a  higher  rate  of 
work  (speed)  by  5  per  cent,  over  its  corresponding  value  of 
the  unknown  series. 

8.  The   average   unit  value  of  the   known  series  of  the 
third  set  of  experiments  shows  a  higher  rate  of  work  by  35 
per  cent,  over  the  corresponding  value  of  the  unknown  series. 


\  / 


\T\ 


C'mt  nts- 


Rest  Periods . 

INVOLUNTARY  SUBSTITUTION  OF  IMAGERY  FOR  PERCEPTUAL 

CONTENTS 

The  curious  appearance  of  imagery  during  the  work 
periods  of  certain  of  the  unknown  series  is  an  interesting 
phenomenon  in  that  it  clearly  indicates  the  observer's  ten- 
dency to  avoid  working  blindly.  The  point  of  definite  appear- 
ance of  imagery  may  be  seen  by  reference  to  the  curve  given 
above. 

The  relation  of  the  unit  values  of  the  known  and  unknown 
second  ascending  series  of  the  second  set  of  experiments  is 


454  GEORGE  F.  ARPS 

especially  interesting  in  that  the  fact  of  overlapping  of  the 
curves  is  referred  to  the  apparent  functioning  of  imagination. 
From  the  introspections  it  appears  that  the  condition  of 
'ignorance  of  results'  prevailed  more  completely  in  the  first 
set  of  experiments  than  in  the  second  set. 

The  unknown  series  of  work  periods  of  the  second  set  of 
experiments  approach  that  of  the  known  through  the  em- 
ployment, without  set  purpose  on  the  part  of  the  observer, 
of  visual  and  kinesthetic  imagery  reproductive  of  the  per- 
ceptual and  kinesthetic  experiences  of  the  work  periods  of 
the  preceding  known  series.  In  the  third  work  period  of  the 
second  set  of  experiments  (see  curve),  the  following  intro- 
spections are  recorded:  "The  task  of  this  period  proceeded 
with  a  fair  degree  of  definiteness,  with  a  comfortable  degree 
of  orientation  hardly  comparable  to  any  of  the  preceding 
unknown  periods.  Certain  individual  lifts  I  pictured  vividly; 
in  certain  other  cases  I  compared  successive  lifts.  The  com- 
parisons were  especially  pronounced  when  the  first  evidence 
of  fatigue  appeared."  In  the  sixth  period  of  the  same  series 
the  observer  remarked  that  he  "seemed  to  sense  the  efficiency 
of  the  entire  period  in  perspective  more  or  less  tangibly." 

Imagery  is  also  involved  in  the  more  or  less  abrupt  closing 
of  the  unknown  period  as  contrasted  with  the  gradual  taper- 
ing off  closing  of  the  known  periods.  On  this  point  one  of 
the  observers  remarks  as  follows:  "In  closing  an  unknown 
period  I  seem  to  let  down  suddenly  in  spite  of  all  efforts  to 
avoid  it.  Short  lifts  have  little  meaning  in  that  I  fail  to 
image  the  pen  marks  which  support  me  in  the  long  lifts." 

In  all  these  cases  evidently  imagery  of  the  sort  here  de- 
scribed acts  as  an  incentive  to  work.  The  presence  of 
imagery  was  first  detected  in  the  first  work  period  of  the 
second  unknown  ascending  series  of  the  second  set  of  experi- 
ments. It  is  probable  that  the  overlapping  of  the  curves 
of  this  set  of  experiments  finds  an  explanation  in  the  definite 
presence  of  imagery.  For,  as  the  imagery  content  of  con- 
sciousness peculiar  to  the  work  periods  of  the  unknown  series 
approximates  that  of  the  perceptual  content  characteristic 
of  the  work  periods  of  the  known  series,  the  differences  in 


WORK  WITH  AND  WITHOUT  KNOWLEDGE  OF  RESULTS      455 

the  awareness  of  results  diminish.  It  is  probable  that  the 
more  essential  features  of  the  perceptual  experiences  acquired 
in  the  first  set  of  experiments  function  in  imagination  in  the 
work  periods  of  the  unknown  series  of  the  second  set  of 
experiments.  If  the  mental  complex  operative  in  the  second 
set  of  experiments  forms  a  close  resemblance  to  that  complex 
functioning  in  the  first  set,  and,  if  the  efficiency  differences  of 
the  known  and  unknown  work  periods  are  primarily  due 
to  the  degree  of  *  knowledge  of  results,'  then  we  have  an 
explanation  for  the  crossing  back  and  forth  of  those  parts 
of  the  curve  representing  the  unit  values  of  the  work  periods 
of  the  second  set  of  experiments.  This  means  that  we  have 
here  phases  of  the  process  of  habituation  in  which  the  estab- 
lished habits  of  response  under  perceptual  conditions  tend  to 
subordinate  responses  operating  under  imaginal  conditions. 
That  the  organism  tends  to  gravitate  towards  its  more  ac- 
customed channels  of  behavior  is  clearly  indicated  in  succeed- 
ing work  periods.  Each  succeeding  set  of  experiments  shows 
an  increasing  amount  of  crossing  of  the  '  unknown '  and 
'known'  curves  (see  graph). 

From  the  general  character  of  the  curves  and  the  intro- 
spective statements  it  appears  that  work  carried  on  under 
conditions  of  partial  awareness  of  results  loses  in  efficiency 
and  that  such  conditions  are  extremely  difficult,  if  not  im- 
possible, to  maintain  when  such  work  is  followed  or  preceded 
by,  work  of  identical  character  under  conditions  of  complete 
awareness.  Without  set  purpose  the  observers  employ  cer- 
tain mental  complexes  during  work  under  the  former  con- 
ditions, which  parallel  in  function  certain  essential  features 
of  the  mental  complexes  operative  during  work  under  the 
latter  conditions. 


THE   BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT 

DURING  THE   FIRST  THIRTY 

DAYS  OF  LIFE1 

BY  MARGARET  GRAY  BLANTON 

Madison,  Wisconsin 

In  view  of  the  fact  that  a  large  amount  of  experimental 
work  is  being  done  by  the  psychological  laboratory  upon  the 
reflex  and  instinctive  equipment  of  the  babies  in  the  maternity 
ward  of  the  Johns  Hopkins  Hospital,  it  seemed  worth  while 
to  make  a  preliminary  observational  study  of  them  under 
the  conditions  actually  obtaining  in  the  nursery.  Most  of 
the  studies  now  in  the  literature  are  of  this  character  and 
the  present  one  has  also  the  object  of  checking  up  others  of 
the  same  character.  The  present  observations  have  been 
made  upon  a  very  large  number  of  infants  and  a  thoroughly 
objective  viewpoint  has  been  maintained  throughout. 

BUCCOPHARYNGEAL 

I.  Sneezing. — The  earliest  reflex  noted.  It  was  present 
on  one  occasion  while  the  infant  was  being  lifted  from  the 
mother.  Subject  L.  sneezed  before  the  birth  cry  appeared, 
and  Subject  G.  at  5  hours,  from  which  time  on  it  is  common. 
It  was  frequently  noted  on  taking  the  babies  into  an  over- 
heated room  where  observations  were  made.  It  was  not 
noticeable  on  bringing  them  again  into  a  cooler  atmosphere. 

Preyer2  says:  "It  demonstrated  the  existence  of  a  very 
firm  connection,  long  hereditary,  of  the  nasal  branches  of 
the  trigeminus  with  the  motor  expiratory  nerves."  He  also 

1This  work  was  undertaken  under  the  direction  of  Professor  John  B.  Watson, 
director  of  the  psychological  laboratory  of  Johns  Hopkins  University.  Through  the 
courtesy  of  Dr.  J.  Whitridge  Williams  and  Dr.  Daniel  Davis,  the  material  in  the 
nursery  of  the  maternity  ward  was  placed  at  our  disposal.  I  am  also  much  indebted 
to  Miss  Liphart  and  to  Drs.  McKee,  Harris,  and  Sperry  for  many  privileges  on  the 
ward. 

2  Preyer,  'The  Mind  of  the  Child,'  p.  214. 

456 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  457 

quotes  Darwin  as  saying  that  many  healthy  children  at  their 
coming  into  the  world  do  not  cry,  but  sneeze. 

2.  Hiccoughing. — Subject  Sp.  at  6  hours  hiccoughed  for 
three   minutes.     Subjects   7,    10,    n,   and    14  days  old   hic- 
coughed  after  feeding.     This   list   might   be   continued,   for 
over  50  cases  were  noted.     It  seems  so  well  developed  at  6 
hours  that  there  is  little  reason  to  believe  that  the  possibility 
of  it  does  not  exist  at  birth  did  conditions  call  it  out.     The 
condition   most  commonly  calling  it  out  is   a   full  stomach 
(producing  pressure  on  the  diaphragm). 

3.  Yawning. — I    have    noted    yawning    twice    within    5 
minutes  after  birth  and  relatively  few  times  during  the  first 
month.     Subject  S.  yawned  at  5  hours,  eyes  tightly  shut. 
Subject  F.,  ii  days,  yawned  6  times  in  I  hour;  her  eyes  were 
squeezed  tight  and  her  chin  trembled  as  she  shut  her  mouth. 
Subject  R.,  5  days,  yawned  so  like  a  sigh  that  the  movement 
barely  fell  within  the  definition  of  a  yawn.     It  was  the  only 
occasion  on  which  the  remotest  resemblance  to  a  sigh  was 
observed. 

4.  The  Beginning  of  Speech  and  Emotional  Reactions. — 
Crying,  less  than  any  other  manifestation  of  a  baby's  exist- 
ence, can  be  considered  separately.     During  the  birth  proc- 
esses  the    connection  between  the  mother  and    infant  are 
made  less  efficient  by  the  gradual  displacement  of  the  pla- 
centa.    The    concentration    of   the    blood    increases,    which 
stimulates  the  respiratory  centers  and  causes  the  intake  of 
air  to  the  lungs.     The  birth  cry  takes  place  at  this  point. 
Occasionally  the  nerve  endings  of  the   mucous   membrane, 
affected  by  the  unaccustomed  stimulation  of  the  air,  may 
cause  a  light  breath  to  be  taken  in  and  expelled  in  what  we 
know  as  a  sneeze.     In  four  observed  cases  in  which  hot  and 
cold  plunges  were  necessary  to  stimulate  breathing  there  was 
also  a  sharp  movement  of  the  arms.     The  cry  observed  came 
on  the  plunge  into  icy  water  and  was  sharp  and  short  and 
on  an  inspiration  as  in  an  adult  under  similar  conditions. 
The  birth  cry  is  rarely  spontaneous,  as  the  technique  of  the 
delivery  is  to  stimulate  it  at  once  by  vigorous  rubbing  and 
slapping  on  the  back  and  buttocks.     This  cry,  as  I  observed 


458  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

it,  differed  in  no  way  in  timbre,  pitch,  etc.,  from  other  cries 
of  the  first  few  days.  The  birth  cries  of  different  infants 
were  not  alike,  ranging  from  simple  a  (as  in  at)  to  u  (as  in 
cut).  Most  of  them  were  compound  u  (as  in  cut)  followed 
by  wok  (as  in  at);  uh  (cut);  nga  (at);  and  variations  just  as 
in  the  later  cries  of  infancy.  This  was  true  also  of  the  three 
spontaneous  cries  which  I  heard.1 

Major2  says:  "The  beginnings  of  language  are  usually 
traced  to  the  reflex  crying  of  the  newly  born  babe."  Both 
Major  and  Preyer  assert  that  "they  are  produced  as  well  by  a 
child  without  a  cerebrum  as  a  child  with  one."  I  was  not 
present  at  the  birth  of  Subject  B.,  mentioned  elsewhere,  but 
I  was  told  by  the  surgeon  that  this  infant  did  not  cry  out. 
Only  4  cries  were  noted  during  its  entire  10  days  of  life,  all 
of  them  taking  place  during  a  deep  examination  to  determine 
the  extent  of  displacement  of  the  bones  of  the  skull.  The 
birth  cry  which  is  followed  by  an  interval  of  quiet  is  rarely 
followed  by  an  interval  of  stillness. 

Crying  has  been  observed  under  the  following  conditions: 
(i)  hunger;  (2)  in  response  to  noxious  stimuli  (including 
rough  handling,  circumcision,  lancing  and  care  of  boils,  sores, 
etc.),  and  (3)  possibly  from  fatigue  or  lack  of  exercise.  In 
the  subjects  with  which  I  worked  I  did  not  find  the  cries  of 
hunger,  to  noxious  stimuli,  to  fatigue,  and  so  forth,  uniform. 
There  were  differences  of  vowels  and  consonants,  of  timbre 
and  degree,  but  no  one  was  used  as  response  to  one  set  of 
circumstances  that  was  not  at  some  time  used  to  others. 
For  example  the  cry  in  response  to  noxious  stimuli  was  in 
many  cases  an  exaggeration  of  the  cry  usual  when  hunger 
was  present. 

The  cry  of  colic  was  the  one  exception.     Starting  abruptly 

1  The  dramatic  element  of  the  first  cry  has  led  to  a  most  amusing  amount  of 
poetic  license.     Kant's  famous  saying  that  "the  outcry  that  is  heard  from  a  child 
scarcely  born  has  not  the  tone  of  lamentation  but  aroused  wrath,"  has  been  subjected 
to  many  and  various  comments.     Preyer  in  quoting  him  says,  "Kant  wrote  without 
having  himself  observed  children  and  animals  just  born."     Dr.  William  A.  White 
quotes  Adler  as  saying:  "It  is  an  expression  of  its  overwhelming  sense  of  inferiority 
on  thus  suddenly  being  confronted  by  reality,  without  ever  having  had  to  deal  with 
its  problems." 

2  Major,  'First  Steps  in  Mental  Growth,'  p.  282. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  459 

about  3  to  5  octaves  above  the  adult  female  voice  it  slid 
through  a  modified  chromatic  scale  to  within  the  range  of 
the  middle  octave.  It  was  made  with  an  accompanying 
rigidity  of  the  abdominal  walls  and  thus  of  necessity  varied 
from  the  cry  which  included  the  activity  of  these  muscles. 
Subject  L.,  15  days,  often  started  with  a  few  short  rapid 
breaths,  a  few  of  which  sounded  like  an  *  affected'  cough  and 
ended  with  a  two  syllable  cry,  a  (at),  and  yow  (owl),  long  and 
on  a  falling  inflection.  The  whole  is  much  like  the  word 
meow  with  the  m  replaced  by  a.  The  cries  did  not  vary  so 
much  with  the  ages  of  the  infants,  during  the  first  five  or 
six  days,  as  with  the  weight.  A  baby  of  2,300  grams  at  one 
day,  and  2,300  grams  at  5  days  will  show  little  difference. 
However,  a  baby  of  4,000  grams  first  day  and  4,000  grams 
fifth  day  would  show  more  difference,  probably  because 
4,000  grams  weight  would  indicate  a  better  physical  condi- 
tion. In  such  a  large  group  of  babies  any  vowel  or  consonant 
can  at  some  time  or  other  be  heard  on  the  first  day  of  life 
that  will  be  heard  on  any  other  day  during  the  first  month. 
A  (what)  will  be  heard  in  a  first  syllable,  but  I  have  not 
heard  it  in  a  second  syllable  excepting  in  a  series  of  short 
grunts.  This  I  suppose  is  because  a  maximum  of  activity 
is  reached  on  the  second  syllable,  and  the  maximum  activity 
in  the  infant  is  accompanied  with  an  open  mouth  and  a  con- 
traction of  those  muscles  which  draw  the  inferior  maxillary 
inward  and  downward.  This,  it  is  seen,  precludes  the  making 
of  the  ah  sound. 

The  crying  of  one  baby  can  be  distinguished  with  some 
practice  from  the  cries  of  another  even  in  a  nursery  of  25, 
the  overtones  varying  just  as  in  older  people.  Subject  M., 
first  day,  u  (cut),  nah  (at)  accent  on  last  syllable,  u  (cut), 
wah  (at),  wuh  (cut),  ha  (at).  The  *  hunger  cry'  has  generally 
a  well  marked  rhythm,  the  first  syllable  of  preliminary  sound 
coming  on  the  first  part  of  the  first  beat,  the  second  or  ac- 
cented syllable  on  the  second  part  of  the  first  beat  and  a 
quick  intake  of  breath  as  the  third  beat.  This  measure  is 
most  often  repeated  in  groups  of  5  or  6,  each  slightly  more 
forceful  than  the  preceding  ones  until  the  fourth  or  fifth, 


460  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

the  last  one  being  softer.  Thus  also  will  the  groups  be 
repeated.  Each  measure  is  also  a  trifle  higher  in  pitch  than 
the  one  preceding. 

Sounds  Heard  during  the  First  50  Days. — Consonant 
sounds  commonly  heard  are  m  in  conjunction  with  a  as  ma 
(at),  n  as  nga  (nat),  g  as  in  gah,  h  as  in  ha  (at),  w  in  wok  (at), 
r  as  in  rah  (at),  r  as  in  burr,  very  slight  sound,  and  y  as  in 
yah  (at). 

Vowel  sounds  are  o  as  in  owl,  e  as  in  feel,  oo  as  in  pool, 
a  as  in  an,  and  a  as  in  father  (relatively  rare). 

Of  interest  was  the  variety  of  animal  cries  simulated  in 
the  nursery.  The  l pot-rack'  of  the  quail,  the  cry  of  the 
goat,  the  whine  of  the  young  pig,  and  the  wail  of  the  wild 
cat,  each  had  a  close  imitation. 

PELVIC 

5.  Erection   of  Penis. — Subjects   Le   S.    and    R.    had   an 
approximate  erection  of  50°  at  birth,   Subject  F.   80°,   and 
Subject  Sch.  at  birth,  a  complete  erection  against  the  stomach 
wall.     These  babies  were,  of  course,  lying  on  their  backs. 
Subject  M.   at  4  days,   also  lying  on  back,   had   complete 
erection. 

6.  Voiding  of  Urine. — This  occurs  at  birth  in  about  30 
per  cent,  of  the  male  infants  observed. 

7.  Defecation. — This  of  course  occurs  often  before  birth, 
as   the   condition   of  the   amniotic  fluid   shows.     It  is   also, 
possibly,    an   occasional   cause   of   suffocation,   which   would 
seem  to  indicate  that  it  occurs  some  time  before  birth^     In 
Subjects  S.  and  R.  it  was  persistent  and  profuse  immediately 
after  birth.     The  passage  is  of  course  the  usual  meconium. 
If  it. does  not  occur  then  the  usual  time  is  from  18  to  24 
hours.     No  norms  were  kept,  however.     When  the  tempera- 
ture  thermometer   is   pressed   into   the   anus   there   is   very 
often  a  resultant  passage  of  feces.     On  five  sets  of  observa- 
tions the  results  were:    (a)  7  positive,  8  negative,  (b)  4  posi- 
tive, 15  negative,  (c)  13  positive,  II  negative,  (d)  5  positive, 
4  negative,   (e)   8   positive,    16  negative,   making  out  of  91 
observations  a  total  of  37  positive  and  54  negative. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  46* 

OCULAR 

8.  Eye-movements. — While  an  inequality  of  eye-move- 
ments is  not  uncommon  it  is  not  the  rule.  Subject  J.,  5,600 
gr.  birth  weight,  often  had  a  hint  of  'cross-eyes.'  At  25  days 
he  occasionally  had  an  unusual  condition — his  eyes  being 
entirely  open  he  would  drop  the  balls  in  such  a  way  as  to 
show  much  more  of  the  sclerotic  coat  above  one  pupil  than 
the  other.  In  other  subjects,  6,  7,  10,  n  and  15  days  of 
age,  the  sclerotic  was  noted  as  visible  above  the  iris.  Sub- 
ject H.,  whose  entire  system  of  reflexes  was  markedly  different 
(the  one"baby  examined  whose  hands  would  not  clasp  on  a 
small  round  rod),  had  peculiarly  symmetrical  use  of  his  eyes, 
but  his  eyes  were  never  seen  to  fixate  the  light  nor  to  follow  a 
hand  moved  in  front  of  him.  Subject  W.'s  eyes  worked  inde- 
pendently: starting  to  the  left  in  unison  the  right  eye  would 
move  more  rapidly  than  the  left,  and  starting  to  the  right 
the  left  eye  would  move  more  rapidly  than  the  right.  A 
large  percentage  of  the  babies  fixated  on  the  light  at  birth. 
Subject  S.  continued  to  do  so  when  removed  to  the  side 
of  the  room.  When  we  turned  her  head  away  she  turned 
it  back  at  once,  bringing  the  light  into  her  line  of  vision. 
She  would  also  fixate  on  the  figure  of  a  person  who  inter- 
rupted the  light.  At  8  days  of  age  she  would  gaze  steadily 
at  the  electric  light  in  the  nursery,  rolling  her  eyes  up,  when  a 
change  of  position  necessitated  it,  keeping  the  light  in  her 
line  of  vision.  An  interesting  'by-product'  was  the  per- 
sistent paddling  of  her  hands  at  such  times  and  a  recurrent 
spasmodic  smile.  Subject  M.  at  birth  gazed  without  blink- 
ing until  her  face  was  covered.  Subject  L.,  34  days  old, 
held  by  mistake  in  bright  sunlight,  first  shut  her  eyes,  then 
opened  them,  fixating  directly  on  the  sun.  Her  pupils  con- 
tracted to  the  size  of  pin  heads.  At  30  days  of  age  she  would, 
when  carried  down  the  corridor,  gaze  at  a  high  light  on  the 
painted  wall,  arching  her  back  and  finally  throwing  back  her 
head  as  she  was  carried  away.  She  would  also,  while  holding 
her  head  still,  follow  the  figure  of  the  nurse  around  the  room. 
At  32  days  of  age  her  eyes  caught  a  red  velvet  bag  held  in 
bright  sunlight,  and  followed  it,  with  her  head  held  still, 


462  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

around  the  nearly  complete  half  circle  of  her  vision.  The 
eyes  of  many  of  the  infants  followed  a  slowly  moving  hand  a 
few  moments  after  birth.  Subject  S.  would  follow  a  hand 
moved  slowly  8  or  9  inches  from  her  face  without  any  accom- 
panying movement  of  the  head. 

Subjects  S.,  A.,  M.,  F.,  and  J.  gazed  at  the  light  above 
the  birth  bed  and  also  followed  a  moving  hand.  Subjects  F. 
and  K.,  neither  of  whom  gazed  at  light  or  followed  hand  at 
birth,  were  seen  to  do  both  on  the  8th  day.  Subject  K.  at 
8  days,  Subject  R.  at  10,  and  Subject  L.  at  26  days  focused 
first  on  one  and  then  another  face.  Subject  S.,  13  days, 
fixated  a  large  paper  bag  which  was  being  handled.  A  dim 
light  moved  slowly  at  half  a  meter  was  followed  by  subjects 
8  hours,  18  hours,  36  hours,  and  3,  4,  5,  6,  14,  15,  21,  and  30 
days  of  age.  Subjects  which  did  not  follow  were  aged  9  hours, 
3,  5,  and  14  days;  17  in  all  were  tested. 

Preyer  observed  in  two  cases,  n  and  13  days,  a  turning 
of  the  eyes  from  one  bright  light  to  another.  Miss  Shinn's 
niece1  fixated  her  eyes  on  a  face  first  at  25  days.  Preyer, 
Rochlman,  and  Wilkowski  observed  'real  fixation'  on  the 
tenth  day.  Dearborn2  notes  seeing  the  eyes  of  a  child  13 
days  old  follow  a  slow-moving  desk  light  at  18  inches,  and 
says  had  he  the  courage  of  his  convictions  he  should  say  he 
saw  the  baby's  eyes  follow  a  hand  slowly  on  the  first  day. 
Preyer's  baby  followed  a  desk  light  at  one  meter  at  23  days, 
much  to  his  surprise,  as  he  says  "other  children  do  not 
follow  a  moving  light  until  after  many  months."  According 
to  him,  however,  Lacy  saw  this  the  second  week  and  Darwin 
the  45th  day — but  a  majority  of  investigators  say  the  5th, 
6th  and  7th  days. 

9.  Eyes  during  Nursing. — These  babies,  as  a  rule,  had 
their  eyes  open  at  the  beginning  of  nursing.  As  they  began 
to  get  enough  food  the  eyes  would  close.  Some  babies,  how- 
ever, were  most  active  after  nursing. 

The  following  observations  were  made: 

1  Shinn,  Millicent,  'Notes  on  the  Development  of  a  Child,'  Book  No.  I,  p.  30. 

2  Dearborn,  G.  V.  N.  '  Moto-Sensory  Development.' 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  463 

Sub  ect  O.  K.,  5  days  old right  eye  open,  left  shut, 

H.         3     "      " eyes  partially  closed, 

R.        7     "      " near  end  of  feeding,  shut, 

W.        7    "      " near  end  of  feeding,  shut, 

R.       14    "      " both  eyes  open, 

and  subjects  4,  5,  5,  5,  9,  15,  20,  21,  and  25  days  old  with  eyes 
open.  Miss  Shinn1  says:  "I  have  watched  and  enquired 
about  several  other  babies  and  found  none  that  nursed  with 
eyes  open." 

FACIAL 

10.  Tears. — On  the  testimony  of  Miss  Liphart,  Subject  P. 
cried  tears  at  birth.     Subject  C.,  whom  I  saw,  had  tears  in 
her  eyes   at  ten   minutes   after  birth.     As   silver  nitrate  is 
administered   as   a   routine   measure   some   time   during  the 
first  two  hours,  a   reliable  record  of  the  activity  of  these 
glands  was  not  obtainable.     Subject  B.,  birth  weight  5,600 
gr.,  at  4  days  cried  profusely  with  right  eye.     He  was  an 
overdue  baby,  breach  delivery  and  with,  consequently,  no 
head    moulding.     Subject    B.,    an    exceedingly    cross-eyed 
baby,  cried  tears  on  his  6th  day.     They  were  not  observed  in 
him  again,  however,  in  the  remaining  4  days  he  was  in  the 
institution.     Subject  S.  showed  dampness  in  corner  of  eyes, 
uniformly,  on  the   I3th  day,   Subject  L.  on  the   I5th,  and 
crying  with  tears  seemed  well  developed  with  her  on  the 
34th    day.     The    first    average   normal    show   of    dampness 
was  13  to  16  days.     The  first  regular  flow  of  tears  28  to  34. 

11.  Smiles. — Spontaneous  smiles  at  an  early  age  are  rare. 
Subject  S.,  4  days,  smiled  spontaneously  while  at  the  breast 
after  feeding;  Subject  O'K.,  7  days,  at  end  of  bottle  feeding; 
Subject  S.,  13  days,  while  looking  at  bright  light;  Subject  K., 
8   days,   smiled   and   immediately  regurgitated;   Subject   C., 
28  days,  smiled  repeatedly  after  feeding  at  the  breast,  but 
the  first  smile  had  followed  a  light  touch  of  the  mother's 
nipple  on  his  cheek.     Subjects  I,  2,  4,  and  6  days  old  smiled 
slightly  to  a  tickling  touch  under  the  chin  when  awake  and 
comfortable. 

12.  Facial  Expression. — According  to  Preyer,  the  corners 
of  the  mouth  are  not  drawn  down  until  the  eighteenth  week. 

1  Shinn,  op.  cit.,  Book  I,  p.  12. 


464  MARGARET  GRAY  B LAN TON 

He  quotes  Darwin  as  noting  it  in  the  6th  week  to  the  2d  and 
3d  month.  Subject  M.,  10  minutes,  pulled  the  corners  of 
her  mouth  down.  Subject  S.,  30  minutes,  rolled  the  lower 
lip  so  as  to  show  the  inside  surface,  pulled  the  corners  of 
his  mouth  down,  and  after  remaining  in  this  typical  pouting 
attitude  for  a  minute  started  crying.  Subject  J.  did  this 
constantly  as  a  preliminary  to  crying,  sometimes  accom- 
panying it  with  a  whimper-like  grunt  which  made  him  seem 
remarkably  mature.  He  had  also  the  square  box-shape 
mouth  in  crying,  as  had  Subject  L.  on  the  7th  day  and  again 
on  the  I4th,  lyth,  and  23d  days. 

Subject  G.,  6  days,  had  a  horizontal  line  directly  across 
his  nose  from  corner  to  corner  of  his  eyes.  In  crying  he 
would  pull  down  the  inner  corners  of  his  brows  making 
wrinkles  that  radiated  from  the  horizontal  cross  line.  Sub- 
ject C.  at  birth  had  the  horizontal  line  between  his  eyes. 
Horizontal  lines  across  the  forehead  are  not  exceptional 
when  an  infant  looks  up.  It  was  seen  in  Subject  M.,  6  days, 
Subject  P.,  15,  19,  21,  and  Subject  L.,  yth  day,  and  often 
thereafter. 

HEAD 

13.  Turning  Head  (when  Lying  on  Face). — The  ability  to 
turn  the  face  (when  the  nose  is  firmly  planted)  in  such  a 
manner  as  to  get  air  is  a  disputed  point.  Preyer1  says: 
"Newborn  children  cannot  so  much  as  free  the  face  by  turning 
the  head  when  one  lays  them  on  a  pillow  with  face  down- 
ward." In  making  the  experiment  I  used  a  pillow  only  once, 
but  as  I  had  no  way  of  ascertaining  how  hard  the  pillow  was 
which  Preyer  had  used  I  made  my  tests  on  the  lap  of  a  nurse 
and  tallied  each  test  on  a  hard  table.  In  the  one  case  of 
the  pillow  a  female  child  of  3  days  freed  her  face  at  once  and 
held  her  head  upright  for  several  seconds.  The  tests  made 
on  lap  and  table  did  not  differ  in  results  nor  did  those  on 
the  birth  bed.  Subject  C.,  30  minutes  old,  rotated  her  head 
in  such  a  way  as  to  leave  her  mouth  and  nose  free.  Subject 
G.,  if  hours,  Subject  B.,  ij  hours,  and  Subject  M.,  9  hours, 
could  do  equally  well.  On  one  occasion  15  healthy  babies 

1  'The  Mind  of  the  Child,'  p.  266. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  465 

were  tested  and  all  were  positive  but  one — Subject  G.,  8  days 
old,  who  lay  until  turned.  Subject  L.,  8  days  old,  not  only 
turned  her  head  but  raised  it  in  the  air  also,  entirely  un- 
supported, and  held  it  so  for  30  seconds  by  stop-watch, 
when  she  was  interrupted.  At  15  days  the  same  baby  held 
her  head  so  for  5  minutes.  This  test  was  repeated  time  and 
time  again.  Even  the  sickest  babies  could  do  it  when  the 
air  supply  was  cut  off. 

14.  Holding   Up  the  Head  (when  Held  in   Upright  Posi- 
tion).— Preyer1  says:    "During  the  first  ten  weeks  no  trace 
could  be  discovered,  in  the  case  of  my  boy,  of  an  attempt  to 
hold  the  head  in  equilibrium."     "In  this  important  step  is 
expressed  an  unquestionable,  vigorous  act  of  will."     There 
has  been  some  confusion  among  the  different  writers,  due  I 
think  to  the  fact  .that  the  exact  test  conditions  were  not 
given.     In  my  tests  the  subjects  were  held  on  an  open  lap, 
not  against  the  body,  were  supported  back  and  front  for 
two  inches  above  the  umbilicus.     Subjects  2,  6,  7,   10,   10, 
n,   13,   13,  and   15  days  old  could  support  their  heads  for 
times  varying  from   I   to  6  seconds.     Subject  L.,  22  days, 
held  her  head  quite  erect  for  3  minutes,  turning  it  from  right 
to  left.     Subject  F.  made  numerous  attempts  with  only  the 
shortest  periods  of  success.     Subject  Y.,  22  days  old,  badly 
underfed  and  weak,  made  no  apparent  effort.     Subject  W., 
22  days  old,  child  of  retarded  parents  who  is  also  weak  and 
undernourished,  failed  likewise.     Any  weakness  in  the  neck 
muscles  must  be  in  those  which  draw  the  head  forward,  as 
numerous  and  successful  attempts  were  made  on  the  ability 
to  lift  the  head  when  laid  on  the  face  (see  turning  head,  when 
lying  on  face). 

ARM  AND  HAND 

15.  Hand  Movements  at  Birth. — Subject  E.  at  birth  spread 
his  fingers  and  closed  his  hand,  repeating  this  4  consecutive 
times.     Subject  S.  stretched  his  fingers  with  first  joint  of 
first,   second   and   third  fingers   bent.     This   was   with   both 
hands  at  the  same  time. 

1 6.  Grasping   Reflex. — Reflex   closing   of  the   hand   to   a 

1  'The  Mind  of  the  Child,'  p.  264. 


466  MARGARET  GRAY  BLANTON 

touch  on  the  palm  has  been  noted  a  very  few  moments  after 
birth  as  in  the  case  of  Subject  C.  who  grasped  the  artery 
clamps  which  held  his  umbilical  cord.  It  was  seen  in  Sub- 
ject K.'s  gripping  of  the  doctor's  finger  to  the  degree  of 
slowing  up  the  entire  operation  of  caring  for  his  umbilical 
cord.  Experimentally  of  course  the  first  step  was  putting 
a  small  rod  into  the  hands  of  the  infant  to  excite  the  reflex 
and  then  to  lift  the  rod  so  that  the  full  weight  would  be 
supported.  My  apparatus  was  a  small  skirt  hanger  with  a 
rod  about  a  quarter  of  an  inch  in  diameter  bound  with  a  very 
thin  wrapping  of  gauze.  The  prevailing  custom  of  oiling  a 
baby  at  birth  was  counteracted  by  giving  the  hands  of  the 
baby  a  good  cleansing  with  alcohol.  This  reflex  has  been 
described  as  one  which  is  most  pronounced  at  birth  and 
which  diminishes  rapidly  afterwards.  I  have  not  found 
this  to  be  so.  For  whereas  a  baby  inside  of  the  first  few  hours 
of  life  will  cling  I  or  2  seconds,  Subject  Sm.  on  her  23d  day, 
weighing  4,260  grams,  held  on  for  20  seconds  and  was  then 
laid  down  still  gripping  the  rod.  This  reaction  is  very  hard 
to  elicit  from  a  quiet  baby,  very  easy  from  a  crying  one, 
.-and  the  crying  when  set  up  has  the  sound  of  what  is  called 
in  the  nursery  an  *  angry  cry.'1  Subject  A.,  20  hours  old, 
clung  2  seconds  and  10  seconds,  Subject  L.,  at  52  days, 
supported  herself  with  one  hand  on  the  rod  for  42  seconds. 

Abnormalities  either  mental  or  physical  affect  this  reac- 
tion less  than  any  other.  Subject  B.  clung  tenaciously  at 
10  days  even  when  life  was  practically  extinct.  He  would 
grip  a  rod  put  into  his  hand  so  strongly  that  it  was  necessary 
to  undo  his  fingers.  Subject  Q.,  5  weeks  old,  dying  of  mal- 
nutrition, lifted  his  entire  weight  and  only  relaxed  on  being 
laid  again  on  a  solid  support.  An  interesting  by-product  was 
the  climbing  movement  of  the  legs  occasionally  noted. 
But  these  alternation  movements  of  the  legs  are  also  the 
movements  of  kicking. 

17.  Grasping  during  Nursing. — Major  found  in  his  child 
that  the  finger  clasp  was  firmest  when  the  child  was  nursing. 

1  Robinson  says  in  "Darwinism  and  the  Nursery"  that  at  the  beginning  he  found 
that  babies  had  grip  and  muscle  power  to  sustain  their  own  weight  on  a  horizontal 
bar,  and  he  adds  the  comment  that  they  even  delight  in  the  process. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  467 

My  examination  of  15  babies  before,  during  the  beginning  of, 
and  after  nursing  did  not  seem  conclusive.  Subject  W.  gave 
definitely  harder  pulls  at  the  breast,  according  to  the 
mother,  as  the  pull  of  my  finger  in  his  hand  made  him  grip 
firmer.  One  subject's  grip  was  better  before  nursing;  2  were 
the  same  all  3  times;  2  were  the  same  before  and  during 
nursing,  and  poorer  after;  I  was  negative  before  and  after 
and  only  very  poor  during  nursing;  I  pulled  only  slightly 
during  and  after  but  had  about  the  same  grip  on  both  occa- 
sions; i  was  definitely  better  during  nursing  and  was  absent 
after  nursing;  4  were  best  during  nursing;  and  3  were  best 
after  nursing.  No  one  baby  was  poorer  during  nursing 
than  before  or  after,  but  as  will  be  noted  in  3  cases  it  was  no 
better  during  nursing  than  at  one  of  the  other  trials;  and  in 
4  cases  it  was  definitely  poorer  than  on  one  of  the  other  trials. 

LEG  AND  FOOT 

1 8.  Creeping. — In  one  case  (aged  7  days)  there  was  a 
creeping  movement  in  which  a  backward  movement  of  six 
inches  was  accomplished  in  twenty  minutes'  time.  By 
marking  the  position  of  the  head  at  the  beginning  and  end 
of  the  period  the  amount  of  movement  was  ascertained. 
On  each  occasion  the  contracting  and  relaxing  seemed  mainly 
of  the  abdominal  and  back  muscles.  The  great  hindrance 
to  successful  movement  in  each  trial  seemed  to  be  the  insuf- 
ficiency of  the  muscles  of  the  arm  used  to  draw  the  arm 
from  a  position  on  a  line  parallel  with  the  body  to  one  at 
right  angles  to  it.  The  legs  often  at  any  time  after  birth 
assume  the  crawling  position.  The  head  (see  turning  head) 
can  be  held  up  out  of  the  way,  but  the  relaxed  position  and 
relative  weakness  of  the  shoulder  muscles  make  forward 
progress  impossible.  This  condition  lasts  beyond  the  3Oth 
day  and  certainly  well  into  the  3d  month,  probably  longer. 
An  interesting  accompaniment  of  this  creeping  movement  is 
the  opening  of  the  mouth  and  the  bumping  of  the  head,  set 
up,  it  seems  to  me,  by  the  well-organized  face  and  mouth 
reflexes.  The  accidental  touching  of  cheek  and  chin  to  the 
unyielding  surface  of  the  table  and  his  inability  to  get  any 


468  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

part  of  it  into  his  mouth,  seemed  elements  in  the  arousal  of 
his  crying. 

19.  Foot  Movements  and  Reflexes. — Subject  S.,  at  birth, 
held  the  foot  rigid,  raised  all  5   toes  uniformly  and  pulled 
them   down   uniformly  4   times.     The   Babinski   reflex  was 
found  present  in  10  cases  tested,  and  apparently  absent  in 
one.     Subject  S.,  when  tickled  on  the  center  of  her  foot, 
drew  the  two  outside  edges  towards  each  other.     The  state- 
ment is  frequently  made  that  babies  can  cling  with  their 
feet.     I  have  never  seen  this.     Placing  a  fine  wire  under  the 
toes,  a  reflex  movement  downward  caught  the  wire  between 
the  pads  of  fat  on  the  toes  and  the  ball  of  the  palm,  but  the 
slightest  pull  would  remove  it. 

20.  Kicking  and  to  a  less  extent  moving  of  the  arms  is 
almost  continuous  for  from  15  to  30  minutes  after  delivery, 
which  period  is  commonly  followed  by  a  sleep  of  from  6  to 
8  hours.     The   kicking  was  greatest  on  the  side  to  which 
there  had  been  a  rotation  of  the  head,  this  rotation  appar- 
ently being  decided  by  the  position  of  the  child  in  utero  for 
the    last    period    before    birth.     For    instance    Subject    M., 
whose  head  rotation  was  to  the  right  contrary  to  the  usual 
rule,  was  a  remarkably  active  child,  and  kicked  excessively 
with  her  right  leg  and  waved  her  right  arm.     Her  reflex  to 
the  tying  of  the  cord  and  to  alcohol  was  however  with  the 
left  side  of  the  body.     After  delivery  it  was  noted  that  she 
had  a  preferential  side,  which  in  this  case  was  the  left  side, 
and  this  preference  for  the  left  continued  for  the  term  of 
observation.     Her  right-side  activity  immediately  after  birth 
might  be  explained  by  the  cramp  of  the  right  side  in  utero 
and  the  relatively  free  position  of  the  left. 

GENERAL  RESPONSES 

21.  Turning  Over. — Subject  M.  at  10  minutes  after  birth 
given  a  slight,  unintentional  advantage  by  the  slanting  of 
the  mattress  on  which  she  lay,  turned  from  her  face  to  her 
back.     Subject  T.,  at  7  days,  turned  repeatedly  from  face  to 
back  when  not  impeded  by  clothing.     Placed  face  downward 
on  an  unyielding  surface  her  arms  outstretched  in  line  with 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  469 

her  body,  she  would  immediately  start  crying.  In  crying, 
relaxing  and  contracting  of  the  legs,  arms,  abdomen,  and 
back  muscles  are  natural  accompaniments.  Pulling  her 
knees  under  her  and  contracting  her  muscles  generally,  she 
would,  when  relaxed,  have  her  arms  nearer  by  a  fraction 
of  an  inch.  In  10  minutes,  after  9  repetitions  of  this  general 
maneuver,  her  arms  would  be  sufficiently  near  her  side  so 
that  with  a  final  contraction  she  would  roll  over. 

22.  Reflex  to  Stimulation  of  Umbilical  Cord. — There  was 
apparently  a  reflex  to  the  clamping,  cutting  and  tying  of 
the  umbilical  cord.     There  is  no  direct  nervous  connection 
between  this  and  the  body.     There  are  of  course  nerves  in 
the  opening  surrounding  the   cord   at  the  end   where   it  is 
attached  to  the  skin  of  the  abdomen.     The  findings  were 
not  uniform.     I  should  say  that  the  deliveries  which  I  wit- 
nessed were  divided  between  three  surgeons.     Subject  L.-i 
straightened   leg   at   clamping  of   cord   with    artery   clamp. 
Subject  L.-2  (twin  to  L.-i)  same;  Subject  S.  straightened 
leg  to  tying,  not  to  clamping.     Subject  C.  kicked  at  tying 
of  cord,  no  reflex  to  clamping;  Subject  B.  kicked  lustily  at 
tying  at  i|  hours  (I  did  not  see  clamping);  Subject  R.,  no 
reaction  to  clamp,  positive  to  tying;  Subject  R.,  positive  to 
tying;    Subject   S.,   positive   to   clamp   only.     Three   babies 
kicked    vigorously    when    clamping    and    tying    were    done; 
Subject   F.    and   Subject  M.   were   negative   to   both.     The 
only  explanation  was  that  in  clamping  and  tying  there  was 
some  pulling  and  the  reaction  was  from  nerves  lying  next  to 
the  umbilical  opening.     One  of  the  surgeons  kindly  undertook 
to  hold  the  cord  much  laxer  in  all  the  operation  than  even 
the  technique  called  for.     There  was  no  reaction  to  clamping 
but  a  distinct  doubling  up  of  the  legs  to  the  tight  tying  of 
the  tape. 

23.  To  Dropping. — The  best  example  of  this  reaction  was 
mentioned  in  the  section  on  grasping.     Watson  and  Morgan1 
have  described   dropping  as   a  stimulus   to  fear  as  follows: 
"To  suddenly  remove  from  them  all  means  of  support,  as 

14  Emotional  Reaction  and  Psychological  Experimentation,'  by  John  B.  Watson 
and  J.  J.  B.  Morgan,  Amer.  J.  PsychoL,  1917. 


47°  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

when  one  drops  them  from  the  hand  and  allows  them  to  be 
caught  by  the  assistant,  the  child  being  held  over  a  bed  on 
which  has  been  placed  a  feather  pillow."  Additional  evi- 
dence of  reaction  to  dropping  appeared  in  the  course  of  this 
study.  On  3  occasions  when  the  box  in  which  newborn 
babies  lay  was  suddenly  lowered  there  was  a  marked  move- 
ment of  the  arms  and  in  one  case  brief  holding  of  the  breath. 
This  same  thing  occurs  repeatedly  when  the  infants  are 
being  weighed.  After  the  removal  of  a  big  weight  the  scale 
pan  in  which  the  infant  lies  may  drop  suddenly;  the  result  in 
many  cases  was  the  same  upward  movement  of  the  arms. 
In  this  case  the  jar  of  the  pan  hitting  the  support  is  to  be 
taken  into  consideration. 

24.  Stretching. — This  movement  varies  from  the  mere  full 
raising  of  the  arms  and  a  complete  stretching  of  the  legs 
and  toes,  to  arching  of  the  back  and  abdomen  and  pushing 
the  arms  until  they  trembled,  accompanied  by  the  bending 
of  the  end  flanges  of  the  fingers.     There  was  in  one  case  a 
movement  of  the  neck  and  pulling  forward  of  the  shoulders. 
The  inferior  maxillary  was  drawn  inward   and   downward, 
giving  a  most  adult  cast  to  the  countenance.     Infants  stretch 
with  the  greatest  freedom  at  the  removal  of  the  clothing 
and  especially  at  the  removal  of  the  diapers   now  in  use. 
Subject  L.,  25  days,  crying  for  a  late  feeding  and  very  wet, 
was  hushed  at  once  by  being  held  to  the  fire  with  feet  un- 
covered.    Here  she  stretched  her  legs  into  muscular  combina- 
tion after  combination  and  finally  juxtaposed  the  palms  of 
her  feet  and  went  to  sleep.     She  accompanied  every  marked 
change  of  position  and  tension  of  the  muscles  with  an  opening 
of  the  mouth,  and  each  relaxing  with  a  closing  of  it.     Sub- 
ject S.  stretched  on  being  put  with  a  bright  light  in  her  line 
of  vision.     This  was  repeated  6  times,  each  time  giving  the 
same  result. 

25.  Response  to  Sound  Stimuli. — The  reaction  to  sounds  im- 
mediately after  birth  is  unusual.     Subject  M.,  lying  in  a  high- 
walled  tin  box,  on  a  metal  table,  resting  on  tiles  set  in  cement, 
reacted  vigorously  when  one  of  the  doctors  in  passing  hit  a 
metal  stool,  a  foot  or  so  away,  with  the  heavy  door.     The 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  47 l 

baby  was  covered  with  a  blanket.  The  stool  did  not  hit  the 
table,  and  the  only  vibrations  reaching  him  were  through  the 
tiled  floor  or  through  the  usual  air  vibrations.  He  threw 
his  arms  forward  forcibly  enough  to  dislodge  the  covering, 
at  the  same  time  moving  his  entire  body.  It  seems  reason- 
able to  conclude  that  his  reaction  was  to  sound.  At  two 
days  this  baby  jumped  similarly  when  a  metal  tray  was  hit 
with  a  fountain  pen  at  a  distance  of  one  meter.  The  tray 
was  held  stationary.  Three  other  subjects  the  same  number 
of  days  old  gave  no  response.  Subject  H.,  6  days  old,  batted 
his  eyes  when  metal  disk  was  struck  with  a  hammer  behind 
his  head.  She  responded  thus  the  first  two  times,  and  the 
third  time  she  did  not  respond.  Subject  H.,  6  days  old,  and 
Subject  T.,  5  days  old,  were  tested  with  tuning  forks.  The 
forks  were  struck  and  the  boxes  held  opposite  the  ear  of  each 
baby  when  they  were  crying.  There  seemed  to  be  a  slight 
diminution  in  the  crying  each  time.  Subject  L.,  also,  at  7 
days,  seemed  to  be  quieted  by  the  big  forks.  Subject  L., 
20  days,  and  Subject  H.,  16  days,  did  not  react  to  the  Galton 
whistle  at  any  pitch.  Subject  P.,  29  days  old,  turned  her 
face  5  times  in  the  direction  in  which  I  was  whistling  softly — 
about  half  a  meter  from  her  head.  There  were  several  ele- 
ments to  be  considered,  however,  as  I  was  sitting  on  the 
side  of  her  next  an  open  fire,  and,  also,  my  breath  may  have 
touched  her  face.  Her  general  movements,  her  expression, 
and  the  immediateness  with  which  she  turned  each  time 
as  soon  as  I  began  whistling,  incline  me  to  believe  that  there 
was  localization  as  well  as  auditory  response.  She  was 
also  seen  to  turn  three  times  in  the  direction  of  the  basin 
into  which  water  had  suddenly  and  forcibly  been  turned. 
Subject  S.,  13  days,  as  mentioned  under  eye-movements, 
turned  at  once  in  the  direction  of  a  heavy  paper  bag  which 
was  being  folded.  Her  face  was  away  from  the  bag,  turned 
towards  a  mild  fire,  and  her  movement  in  turning  was  de- 
cisive, her  eyes  catching  the  bag  unhesitatingly  and  holding 
it  steadily.  It  was  a  very  interesting  example  of  the  co- 
ordination of  audition  and  vision.  Repeated  experiments 
showed  that  babies  showing  no  reaction  to  other  sounds  would 


472  MARGARET  GRAY  BLANTON 

react  positively  to  these  rattling  paper  bags.  In  13  trials 
with  subjects  4  to  14  days  old,  12  were  positive.  Four  were 
hushed  in  crying,  4  turned  in  the  direction  of  the  bag,  and  2 
in  the  opposite  direction,  but  since  the  movement  of  body 
and  eyes  was  markedly  different  to  what  it  was  when  the 
experiment  started,  those  turning  away  were  considered  as 
giving  a  positive  reaction.  Subject  B.,  on  the  second  day, 
would  jump  at  a  whistle  or  the  sudden  sound  of  a  voice  on 
the  far  side  of  the  room.  The  sudden  dropping  of  the  scales, 
6  feet  away,  would  cause  marked  convulsive  movements. 
This  condition  persisted  until  about  the  4th  day,  when  his 
response  gradually  became  less  marked,  until  on  the  7th 
he  would  not  respond  at  all. 

RESPONSE  TO  Noxious  STIMULI 

26.  To  Deep  Pricking  of  Big  Toe. — For  laboratory  pur- 
poses it  was  necessary  to  draw  blood  from  3  babies  at  2  times. 
Two  of  the  babies  were  pricked  2  times  on  the  left  big  toe, 
one  once  on  the  left  and  once  on  the  right.     At  each  time 
the  other  foot  went  up  at  once  with  a  pushing  motion  against 
the  other  ankle.     As  this  motion  is  also  one  of  the  motions 
of  kicking  no  conclusion   could   be  drawn.     There  was   no 
pronounced  cry  but  one  of  them  was  crying  when  taken  up, 
and  all  were  given,  between  the  two  operations,  a  lifting  test 
which  always  elicits  crying. 

27.  To  Lancing  of  Infected  Finger. — Subject  Le  S.,  crying 
with  hunger,  had  to  undergo  the  lancing  of  a  badly  swollen 
and  infected  finger.     It  was  necessary  also  to  hold  the  arms 
firmly,  which  very  uniformly  has  the  effect  of  making  the 
subjects  cry.     His  cry  during  the  lancing  and  cleaning  of 
the  finger  continued  to  be  of  the  same  character,  but  much 
exaggerated. 

28.  Circumcision. — Unfortunately   the   time   selected   for 
circumcision   was   immediately  before   a   feeding.     The  ele- 
ment of  hunger  had  therefore  to  be  taken  into  consideration 
as  well  as  that  of  pain.     A  small  gauze  sponge  dipped  in 
whiskey  and  sugar  or  wine  and  sugar  was  given  the  baby  by 
the  Hebrew  physician  who  performed  the  operation.     The 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  473 

crying  seemed  loudest  while  preparation  was  being  made, 
stopped  slightly  at  handling  of  the  penis,  began  again  at 
manipulation  of  the  foreskin,  and  was  slightly  accelerated 
after  the  cutting.  The  babies  were  in  every  case  quiet  during 
the  ceremony  which  followed,  but  this  was  insured  by  the 
amount  of  alcohol  administered. 

RESPONSE  TO  DERMAL  STIMULI 

29.  To  Prick  on  Wrist. — On  one  occasion  I  tested  21  sleep- 
ing infants  by  lightly  pricking  the  wrist.     I  attempted  to 
use  the  same  pressure  on  the  pin  each  time,  making  it  just 
hard  enough  so  that  when  tried  on  my  own  wrist  it  aroused 
a  pain  response.     Thirteen  gave  a  movement  of  the  hand 
or  forearm  in  response  to  the  pin  touch  and  8  did  not  respond. 
Subjects  giving  positive  results  were  2,  2,  2,  3,  6,  7,  8,  8,  8, 
16,  17,  17,  19  days  old.     Those  giving  negative  were  2,  2,  3, 
6,  6,  8,  9,  and  26.     As  an  interesting  note  on  the  experiment 
it  is  worth  mentioning  that  of  the  8  giving  no  response  6  were 
the  children  of  either  one  or  two  defective  parents. 

30.  To  Being  Rubbed. — The  cleaning  of  the  newborn  with 
oil  affords  a  most  interesting  opportunity  for  the  observa- 
tion of  dermal  and  deep  pressure  reactions.     The  rubbing 
of  the  head,  and  especially  the  rubbing  of  the  back,  brings 
out  the  most  active  reactions  which  in  all  probability  the 
baby  will  be  called  on  to  make  in  the  first  month  of  life. 
The  screaming  which  invariably  ensued  was  of  such  a  volume 
as  is  hardly  attained  in  the  first  6  weeks  under  ordinary 
conditions.     During   the   scrubbing   of  the   head    15   of  the 
babies  which  I  saw  delivered  impeded  the  progress  of  the 
operator  to  a  greater  or  less  degree  by  a  constant  moving 
of  the  hands.     Subject  K.  caught  the  hands  of  the  operator 
through  the  whole  of  the  cleaning  process.     Since  the  vernix 
caseosa  is  most  heavily  deposited  on  the  back,  rubbing  the 
back  brings  out  a  response  of  the  lustiest  crying,  and  in  3 
cases,  when  the  infant  was  supported  by  the  left  hand  of 
the  surgeon  in  a  crawling  position  with  hands   and   knees 
touching   the   bed,   crawling   movements   were   elicited.     In 
neither  of  these  cases  of  course  is  the  stimulus  entirely  dermal, 


474  MARGARET  GRAY  BLANTON 

since  a  good  deal  of  pressure  is  exerted  on  the  muscles  and 
deeper  structure;  and  certainly  the  squeezing  of  the  body 
as  well  as  the  pressure  on  the  unattached  skull  bones  un- 
doubtedly introduced  kinaesthetic  factors.  The  cry  elicited 
is  identical  with  the  ' angry  cry'  of  the  nursery  and  is  in 
fact  so  called  by  a  great  many  operators  and  nurses. 

Subject  F.,  13  days,  raised  her  right  arm  at  each  of  seven 
strokes  of  her  nose,  but  did  not  approach  the  hand  to  the 
nose.  Subject  S.,  at  30  minutes,  moved  both  hands  to  her 
nose  when  it  was  held,  but  on  the  second  trial  moved  them 
in  the  opposite  direction. 

31.  To    Dampness. — Immediately    after    the    voiding    of 
urine    the    napkin    has    a    higher    temperature    than    usual. 
After  a  certain  length  of  time  the  wet  diaper  becomes  colder 
than  usual.     When  the  element  of  temperature  is  eliminated 
there  is  little  evidence  to  show  that  babies  up  to  6  weeks 
show  any  particular  response  to  wetness  or  dryness  of  their 
diapers.     In  a  nursery  in  which  there  were  16  wet  babies, 
10  were  quiet  and  6  crying.     A  few  minutes  after  changing, 
10  were  crying  and  6  were  quiet.     Substantially  the  same 
results  were  obtained  in  another  group  of  19  infants.     In 
the   course  of  these   observations   enough   cases   have   been 
investigated  to  show  that  it  is  extremely  difficult  to  predict 
whether  a  baby  is  wet  or  dry  because  of  its  cry.     There  are 
nursery  saws  to  the  effect  that  babies  'cry  because  they  are 
wet'  and  are  still  'because  they  are  dry.'     Rounds  of  the 
nursery  will  often  show  that  neither  conclusion  is  justified, 
as  babies  under  30  days  void  frequently,  and  out  of  a  nursery 
of  25,  15  to  20  wet  babies  can  be  found  at  any  time  within 
30  minutes  of  changing.     It  is  not  uncommon  to  have  them 
void  immediately  on  changing,  stimulated  perhaps  by  the 
coolness  of  the  fresh  diaper.     Subjects  4,  6,  10,  and  14  days 
old  were  on  one  occasion  crying  and  wet,  but  the  diapers 
were  quite  cold  to  the  touch  as  well,  and  subjects  4,  5,  9, 
n,  and  21  were  wet  and  quiet  and  the  diapers  seemed  about 
body  temperature. 

32.  To  Warmth  and  Cool. — Preyer1  says:    "Sensibility  to 

1  'The  Mind  of  the  Child,'  p.  183. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  475 

contact  is,  in  the  first  hour  of  life,  much  inferior  to  what  it 
is  later;  the  sense  of  temperature  does  not  exist."  I  have 
noted  6  occasions  on  which  there  was  marked  shivering 
within  15  minutes  of  birth,  on  two  occasions  it  persisted 
until  the  infant  had  been  brought  near  to  a  hot  water  bottle 
for  some  time.  The  skin  of  this  baby  was  cold  to  the  touch. 
The  shivering  was  so  pronounced  as  to  make  a  marked 
movement  of  the  toothless  lower  jaw  which  under  other 
conditions  we  call  'chattering.'  The  reaction  to  warmth 
during  the  second  day  of  life  was  marked.  Uncovering  the 
lower  part  of  the  infant's  body  to  the  heat  of  a  mild  fire 
caused  curling  of  the  toes  both  upward  and  downward. 
Subject  L.,  7  days,  when  she  had  been  some  time  with  the 
outside  of  her  right  leg  next  a  rather  hot  fire,  crossed  it  over 
her  left  and  thus  away  from  the  fire.  Subject  S.,  at  9  days, 
when  placed  in  a  warm  tub,  moved  her  arms  outward  and 
downward,  palms  backward,  elbows  straightened,  and  on 
the  forward  movement,  bent — much  as  in  swimming.  She 
opened  her  mouth  wide,  with  her  tongue  over  the  surface 
of  her  lower  lip;  her  breathing  became  noisy  and  accelerated, 
the  air  being  forced  out  of  her  nose  in  what  might  be  called 
a  snort. 

33.  Alcohol. — An  excellent  test  of  the  reaction  to  cold  of 
the  skin  of  the  very  young  was  offered  by  the  application  of 
alcohol  dressings  to  the  stump  of  the  umbilical  cord.     The 
surgeons  delivering  obligingly  dropped  small  amounts  where 
I  indicated.     When  dropped  on  the  lower  half  of  the  ab- 
domen kicking  resulted  uniformly;  dropped  on  the  lower  left 
part  of  the   abdomen   the  left  leg  would   respond;  on   the 
lower  right,  right  leg;  lower  center,  both  legs  or  either  right 
or  left.     Above  the  umbilicus  the  reaction  was  not  so  certain 
but  when  obtained  was  a  movement  of  the  legs. 

RESPONSE  TO  KINJESTHETIC  STIMULI 

34.  Kincesthetic   Sense. — Dearborn1   says:    "It  is   one  of 
the  anomalies  of  psychology  and  of  physiology,  that  kinses- 
thesia,  most  basal  and  important  of  the  senses,  has  been  so 

1  'Moto-sensory  Development,'  p.  i. 


476  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

relatively  neglected.  Without  it  no  infant  could  become 
more  humanly  efficient  than  a  plant."  This  sense  is  prob- 
ably the  earliest  of  all  developed,  coming  as  may  reasonably 
be  supposed  before  kicking  does  in  the  fourth  or  fifth  months 
of  life  in  utero.  Miss  Shinn1  refers,  under  Rhythm,  to  the 
*  superior  quieting  influence  of  a  monotonous  jarring  as  com- 
pared with  a  smooth  motion.'  Experiments  on  placing 
infants  to  the  breast  to  quiet  them  were  made  as  early  as 
the  third  day  of  life,  and  as  the  amount  of  milk  gotten  up 
to  that  time  is  negligible  it  is  fair  to  assume  that  changes  in 
the  position  or  pressure  was  the  cause  of  the  resulting  quiet. 
Walking  with  the  babies  quieted  them  as  early  as  the  first 
day.  Ten  subjects  under  4  days  responded  by  ceasing  to 
cry.  One  of  these  was  crying  with  every  symptom  of  ab- 
dominal pain.  It  was  noted  that  babies  crying  in  the  corridor 
were  exceedingly  rare  and  the  approximate  number  of  trips 
daily  through  the  corridor  with  infants  was  120.  Of  the 
many  dozens  of  trips  made  to  and  from  the  laboratory  only 
one  child  was  known  to  cry  the  entire  distance;  one  cried 
the  first  third  of  the  way  and  was  quieted.  Subjects  at 
6  hours,  18  hours,  i,  3,  3,  4,  6,  6,  7,  7,  9,  n,  14,  and  18  days 
who  were  crying  in  their  cribs  were  quieted  by  lifting  and 
gentle  pressure.  Subjects  at  10  hours,  4,  6,  and  9  days  were 
quieted  by  pressing  the  infant's  body  between  the  hands. 
Subjects  I,  3,  and  6  days  were  quieted  by  pressure  on  chest. 
Subjects  at  6,  8,  and  10  days  were  quieted  by  firm  pressure 
around  head. 

REFLEXES  CONNECTED  WITH  FEEDING 
35.  Cheek  and  Chin. — This  test  was  a  light  touch  on  either 
cheek  in  a  straight  line  parallel  with  the  mouth  and  about 
an  inch  removed  from  the  corners,  and  a  light  touch  on  the 
chin  exactly  above  the  center.  The  subjects  giving  a  positive 
reaction  moved  their  mouth  in  the  direction  of  the  touch. 
Subject  M.,  5  hours,  positive;  Subjects  Mon.,  5!  hours,  K., 
at  7  hours,  H.,  at  8f,  and  D.,  at  9  hours,  were  all  positive. 
Subject  F.  at  9  hours  was  positive  to  right  cheek,  negative 

1  Note  book  II.,  Miss  Milicent  Shinn. 


BEHAVIOR  OF   THE   HUMAN  INFANT  477 

(did  not  react  to  touch)  on  left  cheek  and  chin.  Subject  B. 
(microcephalic  in  dying  condition),  10  days,  positive  to  right 
cheek  and  negative  to  left  and  chin.  Two  hours  later  Sub- 
ject H.  (positive  in  above  list)  gave  a  complete  negative 
when  in  a  very  deep  sleep.  After  feeding  this  reaction  is 
hard  to  elicit.  During  hunger  it  is  easy  and  the  infant 
often  moves  with  surprising  quickness,  catching  the  testing 
finger  in  its  mouth.  One  infant  giving  a  positive  reaction 
at  5  hours  showed  a  complete  negative  at  7.  Inquiry  showed 
that  through  a  mistake  in  routine  the  baby  had  been  put 
to  the  breast  in  the  interim. 

36.  Lip  Reflex  (Thompson's).1 — This  is  gotten  by  tapping 
lightly  with  the  tip  of  the  finger  below  or  above  the  corner 
of  the  mouth  of  a  sleeping  baby.     The  result  is  a  closing  and 
pouting  of  the  lips  into  a  nursing  position.     Tests  were  made 
on    14  sleeping  babies   an  hour  before  feeding.     The   most 
marked  result  was  Subject  R.,  7  days,  who  pursed  his  lips, 
protruded  the  tip  of  his  tongue  between  them  and  sucked 
it  vigorously.     Subjects  16  hours,  4,  5,  7,  9,  10,  n,  19,  and 
21  days  old  pursed  the  lips  and  protruded  the  tongue  but  did 
not  suckle.     Subject  M.,  9  days,  pulled  his  head  back  quite 
markedly  and  rolled  out  his  under  lip.     There  was  no  sug- 
gestion of  pursed  lips  or  suckling.     Two  subjects  at  10  days 
jerked  the  head  slightly  but  gave  no  other  response.     Sub- 
ject Y.  at  19  days  gave  no  reaction.     This  baby  was  markedly 
malformed  and  the  child  of  retarded  parents. 

37.  Tongue    Reflexes,    at    birth    and    later.     Movements 
similar  to  the  movements  and  position  of  the  tongue  and 
lips  in  the  lip  reflex  (Thompson)  may  be  seen  immediately 
after  birth.     These  movements  which  appear  to  be  merely 
unrelated  and  random  are  related  to  suckling.     The  tongue 
protrudes  from  the  mouth  and  the  edges  are  curled  upward 
and  over  in   such   a  way  as   to  make  the  partial  vacuum 
essential  to  sucking,   much  easier  than  if  the  back  part  of 
the  tongue,  only,  was  depended  on.     The  use  of  the  muscles 
in  the  back  of  the  mouth  apparently  requires  a  higher  type 

1  Thompson,  John,  'On  the  Lip-reflex  of  Newborn  Children,'  Rev.  of  Neurology 
and  Psychiatry,  Vol.  I.,  1903,  p.  145. 


478  MARGARET  GRAY  BLANTON 

of  coordination  (see  suckling  and  swallowing  below).  The 
forming  of  the  tongue  into  this  protruding  tube  can  be  seen 
in  infants  up  to  30  days,  at  the  time  of  feeding.  If  the  food 
is  removed  before  satiety  is  reached  there  is  often  an  active 
sucking  of  the  protruded  tongue. 

38.  Sucking  Fingers. — This   seems   to  vary   mainly  with 
the  manner  in  which  the  fingers  are  gotten  into  the  mouth. 
Subject  M.  at  20  minutes  put  his  thumb  directly  into  his 
mouth  and  began  sucking  it.     Subject  S.  during  the  first  2 
hours  of  life  put  his  right  first  finger  into  his  mouth  6  times. 
His  action  was  not  fumbling.     He  touched  his  face  either 
below  or  above  his  mouth,  which  set  up  the  sucking  reflex 
noted  under  lip  reflexes  (36)  and  the  finger  was  pulled  directly 
into  the  mouth.     Once  the  sucking  had  been  started  there 
was    rarely   any    fumbling.     Three   exceptions    to    this    rule 
also  showed  weak  swallowing  reflexes  and  each  of  them  had 
either  one   or   two   retarded   parents.     Subject   S.,   child   of 
imbecile    mother    and    retarded    father,    attempted    for    15 
minutes  to  get  her  finger  in  her  mouth,  but  did  not  succeed. 
These   babies'   mouth    reflexes   are   given   more   fully   under 
swallowing  and   suckling  below.     Subject  G.,  a  'blue  baby' 
two  hours  old,  put  his  fingers  directly  into  his  mouth.     Sub- 
ject D.,  2  days  old,  Caesarian  delivery,  very  feeble,  was  seen 
sucking  two  fingers  so  vigorously  that  it  required  a  decided 
effort  to  remove  them.     She  put  them  back  in  at  once  with- 
out trouble.     She  was    also   seen   with   all  4  fingers   in   her 
mouth.     Subject    B.,    a    mal-formed    baby    mentioned    else- 
where, 10  days  old,  in  dying  condition,  put  his  finger  in  his 
mouth    after    4    trials.     Both    his    sucking    and    swallowing 
reflexes    were    moderately    good.     The    former    were    better 
than  the  latter. 

39.  Suckling  and   Swallowing. — A  demonstration   of  the 
presence  of  the  ability  to  suckle  immediately  after  birth  was 
attended   by  many  practical   difficulties   on   account  of  the 
sterile   operating   field    surrounding   the    subject.     A    sterile 
nipple  was  supplied  at  each  delivery  and  the  surgeons  very 
kindly  held  them  in  the  babies'  mouths.     As  the  process  of 
obtaining  sterile  nipples  became  difficult  on  account  of  some 


I  BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  479 

local  conditions  the  expedient  was  devised  by  one  of  the 
surgeons  of  cleansing  his  gloved  hand  in  sterile  water  and 
letting  the  baby  suck  his  finger.  Subject  S.,  immediately 
after  spontaneous  cry,  was  given  the  nipple.  The  reflex 
faintly  present  was  perceived  as  a  slight  movement  of  the 
lips  as  in  sucking,  and  as  a  swallowing  movement  in  the 
throat.  Subject  O'K.,  aged  23  minutes,  suckled  slightly. 
Subject  Sc.,  very  blue,  and  with  umbilical  cord  around  neck 
at  birth,  at  10  minutes  sucked  well,  at  25  minutes  sucked  so 
violently  that  it  was  necessary  to  hold  the  unattached  nipple 
with  an  artery  clamp.  Subject  Le.  S.  sucked  definitely  but 
not  vigorously  at  15  minutes.  Subject  M.,  6  minutes,  sucked 
vigorously  and  at  30  minutes  sucked  very  hard.  Subject  R. 
sucked  vigorously  at  10  minutes.  Subject  S.  sucked  definitely 
at  13  minutes  and  vigorously  at  25.  This  list  continues  with 
little  variation  through  the  whole  series.  Occasionally  it 
was  not  practicable  to  get  the  trial  immediately  after  birth, 
but  in  no  case  did  the  baby  refuse  definitely  to  suckle  during 
the  first  hour  of  life.  Nothing  but  the  most  marked  retarda- 
tion or  injury  seems  to  affect  this  reflex.  Swallowing,  with 
sucking,  tongue,  lip  and  cheek  reflexes  go  to  make  up  the 
feeding  reflex.  The  evidence  is  strongly  in  favor  of  the 
fact  that  weakness  in  the  ability  to  swallow  is  at  least  sug- 
gestive of  mental  retardation  whereas  sucking  is  present  at 
birth  in  most  infants.  Interesting  in  connection  with  this 
is  the  fact  that  certain  forms  of  retardation  which  are  accom- 
panied by  speech  defects  show  a  lack  of  coordination  in  the 
same  muscles  which  seem  defective  in  swallowing — namely, 
the  control  of  the  soft  palate  and  back  part  of  the  tongue 
and  throat.  Going  back  over  this  list,  Subject  S.  was  the 
child  of  healthy  and  mentally  well  developed  parents.  Both 
her  swallowing  and  sucking  reflexes  were  good.  She  was 
dismissed  at  the  end  of  10  days  and  was  considered  excellent 
in  every  way.1  Subject  O'K.,  child  of  intelligent  parents, 
dismissed  in  14  days,  rated  excellent.  Subject  Sc.  sucked 
violently  at  nipple  but  did  not  swallow  well  and  was  not 

1  A  discharge  was  not  given  these  patients  until  the  best  possible  feeding  habits 
had  been  established. 


48°  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

dismissed  until  21  days  old  with  a  rating  of  moderately  good. 
Her  mother  was  a  high-grade  moron.  Subject  L.,  whose 
mother  was  graded  as  12  years  by  the  Binet-Simon  intelligence 
test,  was  dismissed  at  18  days.  This  infant's  swallowing 
reflexes  were  very  poor.  Subject  M.,  child  of  mother  rated  as 
10  years  mental  age  and  who  also  showed  a  marked  tendency 
to  certain  psychopathic  conditions,  fed  moderately  well,  but 
at  2  months  is  not  thriving  as  well  as  at  2  weeks.  Subject  R. 
(child  of  deaf  and  dumb  primipara  of  32,  who,  on  account 
of  her  deafness,  was  not  given  a  mental  test,  but  whose 
practical  ability  for  learning  was  poor  and  who  showed  a 
marked  tendency  to  cruelty  to  her  baby)  left  at  the  end  of 
3  weeks,  her  swallowing  still  faulty,  with  a  grading  of  poor. 
Subject  S.  whose  sucking  at  birth  was  vigorous  enough  left 
at  the  end  of  3  weeks  without  having  learned  to  swallow 
at  all.  The  only  food  that  this  baby  obtained  was  that 
which  went  down  when  it  was  carefully  moved  in  such  a 
way  as  to  assist  gravity.  This  baby  sucked  actively  but 
ineffectually  with  his  lips.  At  2  months  he  was  little  more 
than  a  skeleton  and  could  not  swallow.  The  mother  of  this 
child  was  a  low-grade  imbecile  who  could  not  even  put  on 
her  own  clothing  and  who  had  to  be  fed  with  a  dull-edged 
spoon.  Subject  P.  (not  on  the  list  above)  who  possessed 
the  sucking  reflex,  but  in  whom  the  habit  of  regurgitation 
was  most  marked,  had  an  intelligent  mother  but  the  father 
was  cruel,  a  drunkard  and  an  habitual  deserter,  who  had 
never  been  able  to  finish  the  lower  grades  at  school.  Twin 
babies  K.,  whose  mother's  mental  age  was  10,  had  to  be  fed 
with  'Boston'  feeders  which  push  the  milk  into  the  mouth. 
It  was  exceedingly  hard  to  get  them  to  swallow.  Subject  K. 
remained  in  the  hospital  2  months.  He  was  the  child  of 
incestuous  relations,  the  mother  a  low-grade  imbecile  and 
the  father  the  same.  In  this  baby  even  the  sucking  reflexes 
were  absent  and  tube  feeding  was  necessary.  At  4  months 
he  was  just  alive.  Subjects  W.,  Y.,  and  K.,  whose  swallowing 
reflexes  were  exceedingly  weak,  had  each  been  in  the  hospital 
more  than  the  usual  time.  Each  regurgitated  constantly. 
The  mothers  of  these  three  did  not  exceed  10  years  mental 
age. 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  4Sl 

Of  value,  in  this  connection,  will  be  a  study  of  the  eating 
and  speech  habits  of  older  children  of  retarded  mentality. 

SOCIAL   BEHAVIOR 

40.  As  the  subjects  were  often  found  crying  in  groups, 
observation  was  made  to  determine  social  influence  as  an 
element.  Note  was  made  of  each  baby  that  cried  whether 
in  a  group  or  singly  through  a  number  of  hunger  periods. 
There  were  28  in  groups  of  two  or  more,  and  35  who  cried 
singly.  In  observation  L,  two  babies  were  kept  together 
in  a  quiet  room,  and  both  slept.  In  observation  II.,  Subject 
W.,  10  days,  slept.  Subject  Sm.,  7  days,  cried  20  out  of 
the  60  minutes.  Finding  nursery  conditions  not  under 
control,  graphophone  records  were  made  of  Subject  L.  when 
crying  with  hunger.  These  records  were  then  played  for  6 
infants  from  I  to  14  days  of  age.  The  results  were  negative. 
In  observation  IX.,  Subject  L.,  8  days  old,  and  Subject  W., 
9  days  old,  were  placed  on  a  couch  so  that  the  conditions 
would  resemble  the  nursery  with  regard  to  vibrations.  Sub- 
ject W.  cried  but  Subject  L.  remained  quiet,  and  later 
Subject  L.  cried  and  Subject  W.  remained  quiet  (and  awake). 
Observation  X.,  Subject  M.,  7  days  old,  quiet  and  awake 
(during  graphophone  record)  made  some  suckling  movements 
with  mouth  and  tongue  and  his  breathing  became  a  trifle 
irregular — but  afterwards,  in  an  interval  of  quiet  he  made 
the  same  movements.  Result  negative.  Observation  XL, 
a  final  trial  was  made:  smoked  drum  records  of  breathing 
were  taken  on  several  infants  while  the  phonograph  crying 
record  was  being  run  through.  The  resulting  breathing 
curves  differed  in  no  way  from  those  made  of  breathing  in  a 
quiet  dark  room.  Conclusion:  there  seems  to  be  no  positive 
evidence  of  social  influence  of  this  character  on  babies  under 
15  days  of  age. 

SUMMARY  OF  RESULTS 

In  summing  up  the  observations  it  will  be  seen  that  the 
reflex  and  instinctive  equipment  of  the  child  at  birth  is  more 
complex  and  advanced  than  has  hitherto  been  thought.  This 


482  MARGARET  GRAY  B  LAN  TON 

discrepancy  is  due  perhaps  to  the  rarity  of  the  opportunity 
for  unrelated  persons  other  than  nurses  or  physicians  to  ob- 
serve during  this  period. 

During  the  first  twenty  minutes  of  life  may  be  observed 
sneezing,  yawning,  tears,  sucking  at  nipple,  fixating  on  light, 
putting  thumb  in  mouth,  jumping  to  loud  sounds,  grasping, 
crying  with  box-shaped  mouth,  crying  with  the  corners  of 
the  mouth  pulled  down,  following  a  moving  hand  with  the 
eyes,  turning  of  the  head  in  such  a  way  as  to  get  air  when 
placed  on  the  face,  turning  over  when  given  a  very  slight 
advantage,  complete  erection  of  penis,  and  most  indicative, 
perhaps,  the  cry  of  so-called  anger  immediately  after  birth, 
justifying  perhaps  Kant's  oft  denied  statement  that  the 
cry  of  a  child  just  born  has  not  the  tone  of  lamentation  but 
of  aroused  wrath. 

The  responses  of  the  child,  under  twenty-four  hours,  to 
pressure  and  the  completeness  and  effectiveness  of  the  food 
reflexes  as  well  as  the  value  of  the  response  to  kinaesthetic 
stimuli  to  this  complex  of  food  reflexes  are  most  interesting, 
and  the  possibility  of  a  direct  relation  between  the  intelligence 
of  the  parent  and  the  swallowing  ability  of  the  child  hinted 
at  in  topic  39  suggests  a  field  for  further  research  which 
would  be  of  direct  value  to  those  interested  in  the  develop- 
ment of  speech. 

INDEX  OF  REFLEXES   (Topic  NUMBERS) 

Alcohol  (33);  Arm  and  Hand  (15,  16,  and  17). 

Buccopharyngeal  (i,  2,  3,  and  4). 

Cheek  and  Chin  (35);  Circumcision  (28);  Creeping  (18). 

Dampness,  to  (31);  Deep  pricking  of  big  toe  (26);  Defecation  (7);  Dermal  Stimuli, 
response  to  (29,  30,  31,  32,  33);  Dropping,  to  (23). 

Eye  movements  (8);  Eyes  during  nursing  (9). 

Facial  (10,  u,  and  12);  Facial  expression  (12);  Feeding,  reflexes  connected  with 
(35,  36,  37,  38,  and  39);  Foot  movements  and  reflexes  (19). 

General  responses  (21,  22,  23,  and  24);  Grasping  during  nursing  (17);  Grasping 
reflex  (16). 

Hand  movements  at  birth  (15);  Head  (13  and  14);  Hiccoughing  (2);  Holding  up 
head  when  held  in  upright  position  (14). 

Kicking  (20);  Kinaesthetic  Stimuli,  response  to  (34). 

Lancing  of  infected  finger,  to  (27);  Leg  and  foot  (18,  19,  and  20);  Lip  reflex 
(Thompson's)  (36). 

Noxious  Stimuli,  response  to  (26,  27,  and  28). 


BEHAVIOR  OF  THE  HUMAN  INFANT  483 

Ocular  (8  and  9). 

Pelvic  (5,  6,  and  7);  Penis,  the  erection  of  (5);  Prick  on  wrist,  to  (29). 

Rubbed,  to  being  (30). 

Smiles  (u);  Sneezing  (i);  Social  behavior  (40);  Sound  stimuli,  response  to  (25); 
Speech  and  emotional  reactions,  the  beginning  of  (4);  Stretching  (24);  Sucking 
fingers  (38);  Suckling  and  swallowing  (39). 

Tears  (10);  Tongue  reflexes  (37);  Turning  head,  when  lying  on  face  (13);  Turning 
over  (21). 

Umbilical  cord,  reflex  to  stimulation  of  (22). 

Voiding  of  urine  (6). 

Warmth  and  cool  (32). 

Yawning  (3). 


DISCUSSION 

A    CRITIQUE    OF    THE    YERKES-BRIDGES-HARDWICK 

COMPARISON  OF  THE   BINET-SIMON  AND 

POINT  SCALES1 

The  readers  of  this  journal  are  doubtless  well  enough  acquainted 
with  the  Yerkes-Bridges  Point  Scale  to  make  unnecessary  an 
extended  descriptive  account.  It  consists  of  twenty  tests,  nine- 
teen of  which  are  selected  or  adapted  from  the  Binet-Simon  series, 
but  arranged,  like  the  1905  Binet  series,  in  general  order  of  diffi- 
culty, without  being  grouped  by  ages.  The  score  is  given  by 
points,  so  many  points  being  allowed  for  success  in  each  test  or 
part  of  test.  Much  emphasis  is  laid  on  the  fact  that  degrees  of 
success  in  meeting  the  several  tests  are  distinguished,  and  some 
credit  given  for  lesser  degrees  of  success,  as  distinguished  from  the 
so-called  'all  or  none'  procedure  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale.  The 
highest  score  which  can  be  obtained  is  100.  The  score  of  any 
individual  is  to  be  interpreted  by  comparison  with  a  norm  which 
has  been  determined  by  the  examination  of  a  group  of  individuals 
of  the  same  sex,  race  and  social  level.  Further  details  will  be 
commented  on  in  connection  with  the  comparison  between  this 
scale  and  the  Binet-Simon  Scale. 

Since  the  justification  of  the  Point  Scale  rests  confessedly  on  a 
criticism  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale,  and  since  this  criticism  is  severe, 
and  if  it  is  accepted,  must  cause  the  abandonment  of  the  Binet- 
Simon  Scale,  it  is  worth  while  to  consider  this  criticism  in  detail 
and  follow  out  the  comparison  of  the  two  scales. 

The  criticisms  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  are  by  implication 
statements  of  advantages  of  the  Point  Scale,  and  the  advantages 
of  the  Point  Scale  are  by  implication  faults  in  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale;  hence  we  may  bring  under  the  same  head  the  disadvantages 
of  the  one  and  the  advantages  of  the  other.  They  make  the  fol- 
lowing long  list: 

I.  The  Binet-Simon  Scale  falsely  assumes  that  the  mental  develop- 
ment of  all  individuals  proceeds  by  similar  stages. 

1 '  A  Point  Scale  for  Measuring  Mental  Ability,'  by  Robert  M.  Yerkes,  James  W. 
Bridges  and  Rose  S.  Hardwick.     Baltimore,  Warwick  and  York.     1915. 
484 


COMPARISON  OF  BINET-SIMON  AND  POINT  SCALES       485 

There  has  been  a  good  deal  of  criticism  of  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale  on  the  score  of  the  assumptions  which  the  critics  find  to 
underlie  it.  The  authors  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  do  not  tell  us 
that  these  assumptions  are  involved,  and  even  if  some  such  assump- 
tions as  are  laid  down  do  seem  to  be  involved  it  is  most  natural  to 
regard  them  as  working  assumptions  and  the  scale  as  a  working 
instrument  rather  than  a  highly  precise  and  accurate  engine  to 
apply  a  precisely  known  law.  It  is  perhaps  no  exaggeration  to 
say  that  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  and  the  results  of  its  application 
has  given  us  more  information  regarding  the  actual  course  of 
intellectual  development  than  all  the  other  testing  of  children  put 
together. 

But  take  the  assumptions  themselves.  Must  not  any  scale 
which  uses  age  norms  make  some  such  assumption  as  is  indicated 
in  the  first  criticism?  The  very  purpose  of  the  scale  is  to  measure 
the  deviation  of  an  individual  from  a  norm,  and  if  there  is  no  norm 
the  deviation  has  no  significance.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  Point 
Scale  makes  this  assumption  in  exactly  the  same  degree  as  does 
the  Binet-Simon  Scale. 

2.  The   Binet-Simon   Scale  falsely   assumes  that  the   correlation 
between  different  functions  is  the  same  for  all  individuals  at  a  given 
stage. 

If  no  flexibility  in  scoring  were  allowed  in  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale  the  second  objection  would  have  some  force,  for  there  would 
then  be  no  opportunity  to  make  up  for  a  deficiency  in  one  mental 
function  by  unusual  performance  in  another;  but  the  possibility 
of  gaining  advanced  credits  at  least  in  part  overcomes  this  ob- 
jection. Besides,  the  probability  is  that  the  correlation  in  rapidity 
of  development  of  the  different  functions  is  fairly  close. 

3.  The  Binet-Simon  Scale  falsely  assumes  that  each  stage  of  mental 
development  corresponds  in  turn  to  a  certain  physical  age,  and  that 
there   is   a   'correlation   between   the   different  functions   at  different 
stages  of  development' 

Since  any  norm  must  be  based  on  physical  age,  unless  the  age 
principle  is  entirely  excluded  by  finding  functions  which  do  not 
develop  with  age,  it  does  not  seem  possible  to  avoid  the  third 
assumption — that  is,  the  first  part  of  it.  The  second  part  of  the 
statement  is  not  amplified  and  the  writer  is  not  able  to  tell  what 
it  means. 

4.  The  Binet-Simon  Scale  falsely  assumes  that  the  mental  develop- 
ment of  the  Paris  school  children  follows  the  above-mentioned  course 
of  development. 


486  F.  N.  FREEMAN 

The  fourth  assumption  is  not  fundamental  to  the  scale,  but 
only  to  its  first  form.  It  can  be  obviated,  and  has  been  obviated 
by  revision. 

5.  As  a  consequence  of  these  false  assumptions  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale  employs  the  erroneous  principle  of  age  grouping  of  tests. 

It  follows  from  the  above  statements  that  the  age  grouping  of 
tests  is  not  a  fundamental  point  of  difference  between  the  Binet- 
Simon  Scale  and  the  Point  Scale,  since  both  scales  involve  the  age 
principle,  but  that  it  is  only  one  of  the  possible  devices  by  which 
the  age  principle  may  be  applied.  The  Binet-Simon  Scale  uses 
the  age  principle  in  the  classification  of  the  tests,  and  the  Point 
Scale  uses  it  in  the  construction  of  the  norm.  The  issue  is  purely 
one  of  convenience.  •  If  many  norms  are  needed  it  is  easier  to  have 
them  independent  of  the  classification  of  the  tests.  Otherwise  not. 
This  question  we  shall  discuss  in  a  moment. 

6.  As  a  further  consequence  of  the  age  grouping  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale  employs  the  crude  all-or-none  method  of  scoring. 

Considerable  emphasis  is  laid  on  the  distinction  between  the 
all-or-none  scoring  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  and  the  partial  scores 
of  the  Point  Scale.  Here  again  the  issue  is  not  fundamental,  and 
the  Binet-Simon  not  only  can,  but  does  use  the  device  of  partial 
scoring  by  including  several  grades  of  difficulty  of  the  same  test 
and  putting  them  at  different  ages.  This  is  done,  for  example, 
with  memory,  interpretation  of  pictures,  and  weight  discrimination. 
The  same  type  of  organization  could  easily  be  extended  without  in 
the  slightest  degree  altering  the  general  structure  of  the  scale. 
In  passing  it  may  be  remarked  that  the  Point  Scale  in  its  present 
form  assumes  that  the  weighting  of  the  various  tests  which  it  adopts 
is  correct  without  giving  it  an  experimental  basis. 

7.  Because  of  the  age  grouping  of  tests  the  Binet-Simon  Scale 
cannot  make  due  allowance  for  different  rates  of  development  due 
to  sex,  race  and  social  or  educational  advantages. 

The  bearing  of  the  seventh  objection  depends  on  the  interpre- 
tation which  is  made  of  the  degree  or  basis  of  the  sex,  racial  or 
social  differences.  If  these  differences  require  different  norms  the 
point  scale  method  furnishes  an  easier  device  than  the  age  grouping 
method.  But  if  sex,  race  and  social  level  all  are  factors  which 
necessitate  separate  norms,  the  task,  as  we  shall  see  in  a  moment, 
is  a  very  considerable  one.  Let  us  first  ask  concerning  the  necessity. 
It  seems  to  the  writer  that,  instead  of  a  case  being  made  out  for 
the  necessity  of  sex  norms,  the  results  of  the  application  of  the 


COMPARISON  OF  BI NET-SIMON  AND  POINT  SCALES       487 

Point  Scale  indicate  that  no  distinction  of  any  clear  sort  can  be 
made  out.  The  lines  which  represent  the  scores  cross  and  recross, 
and  the  crossing  points  in  the  English-speaking  group  are  different 
from  those  of  the  non-English-speaking  group.  The  race  com- 
parison which  is  reported  brought  entirely  negative  results,  so  far 
as  total  scores  are  concerned.  Even  if  marked  race  differences 
had  been  found,  the  question  might  at  least  be  raised  whether  it 
does  not  suit  the  practical  purpose  of  an  intelligence  scale  better 
to  measure  different  race  groups,  at  least  within  the  same  com- 
munity, by  a  single  norm  than  by  separate  norms.  For  classification 
in  the  school  it  would  seem  certainly  better;  and  if  feeble-minded- 
ness  is  conceived  in  functional  terms  it  would  seem  better  for  the 
selection  of  feeble-minded  individuals  also.  With  reference  to 
social  groups  the  chief  question  is  whether  the  differences  are 
inherent  or  the  product  of  environment.  If  inherent,  no  separate 
norm  is  needed;  otherwise  it  is.  The  probability  is  that  the  differ- 
ences are  at  least  in  part  inherent.  In  so  far  as  they  are  not,  the 
application  of  different  norms  would  be  exceedingly  difficult.  How 
many  groups  would  be  distinguished,  what  would  be  the  basis  of 
the  distinction,  how  would  a  particular  child  be  placed  in  the 
proper  group,  etc.  ? 

Let  us  assume  that  we  do  have  norms  for  sex,  race  and  social 
level,  as  the  authors  propose,  and  that  we  have  scales  for  the  four 
types  of  mental  function.  A  short  calculation  will  show  that  the 
number  of  norms  that  would  be  necessary  is  sufficient  to  daunt  the 
hardiest  investigator.  If  we  provide  for  three  races  only,  and  for 
three  social  levels,  no  less  than  seventy-two  norms  would  be  neces- 
sary. We  start  with  four  scales.  The  sex  distinction  necessitates 
eight,  the  racial  distinction  twenty-four  and  the  social  distinction 
seventy-two.  The  derivation  of  these  norms  would  require  the 
examination  of  at  least  seventy-two  thousand  children. 

8.  Since  in  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  * later  and  more  difficult  tests 
have  no  more  weight  in  making  up  the  score  than  do  earlier  and  easier 
ones,  the  same  mental  age  may  correspond  to  records  far  from  equiva- 
lent* (p.  33). 

The  feature  which  is  criticized  in  the  eighth  article  is  given 
as  one  of  the  chief  advantages  of  the  Point  Scale.  It  certainly  is 
true  of  that  scale,  and  is  the  direct  opposite  of  the  characteristic 
which  is  criticized  in  the  second  article. 

9.  In  its  present  form  the  Binet-Simon  Scale  does  not  give  uniform 
opportunity  to  the  various  mental  functions  at  different  levels. 


488  F.  N.  FREEM4N 

The  ninth  article  is  similar  to  the  second,  and  does  hold  true 
of  the  original  Binet-Simon  Scale,  but  is  not  essential  to  it. 

10.  The  Point  Scale,  as  contrasted  with  the  Binet-Simon  Scale, 
is  capable  of  giving  results  of  ever-increasing  reliability  and  precision 
as  data  accumulate  and  norms  are  established. 

Theoretically,  the  tenth  point  is  well  taken.  Practically,  the 
establishment  of  a  norm  is  not  a  very  extensive  process,  after  the 
choice  of  tests  has  been  made,  and  for  practical  purposes  it  is 
desirable  not  to  defer  the  establishment  of  a  norm  too  long.  It  is 
probable,  for  example,  that  the  present  Point  Scale  norm  will  be 
used  for  some  time,  since  ideal  programs  are  frequently  long  deferred 
in  realization. 

11.  There  is  less  influence  of  the  personal  equation  of  the  examiner 
in  using  the  Point  Scale. 

If  the  examiner  has  a  constant  bias  in  the  direction  either  of 
undue  conservatism  or  liberality  in  scoring  the  child's  responses  it 
is  clear  that  the  error  is  greater  the  larger  the  units  which  are 
represented  in  each  judgment,  and  the  larger  the  number  of  judg- 
ments which  are  made.  A  judgment  which  determined  a  large 
share  in  the  child's  rating  would,  if  in  error,  cause  a  greater  dis- 
placement of  his  rank  than  one  which  had  a  small  share  in  his 
rating.  Thus  the  breaking  up  of  the  Binet  tests  into  subsidiary 
tests  in  the  Point  Scale,  by  making  each  unit  smaller,  reduces  the 
error  which  is  due  to  constant  bias  in  either  direction  on  the  part  of 
the  examiner.  As  was  pointed  out  in  discussing  the  all-or-none 
method  of  scoring,  this  difficulty  can  be  overcome  in  the  Binet 
scheme  by  breaking  up  the  tests  and  placing  the  constituent  parts 
at  different  appropriate  ages.  The  size  of  each  error  being  deter- 
mined by  the  value  of  the  unit  upon  which  it  is  based,  the  size  of 
the  total  error  will  be  determined  by  the  number  of  the  individual 
errors.  An  error  can  occur  only  in  the  case  of  those  tests  in  which 
the  judgment  of  the  examiner  varies  from  the  true  judgment. 
In  the  Binet  Scale  the  range  of  such  tests  is  confined  to  those  of  a 
few  ages  immediately  adjacent  to  the  child's  mental  age.  In  the 
Point  Scale,  because  of  the  partial  credit  system  and  the  scoring 
by  points,  the  range  of  tests  from  which  the  child's  score  is  made 
up  is  much  greater.  Hence  the  number  of  judgments  which  are 
factors  in  his  rating  is  relatively  larger.  For  this  reason  there  are 
more  opportunities  for  error  which  will  affect  the  score.  It  would 
appear  from  these  considerations  that  theoretically — and  thus 
far  we  have  no  other  basis  for  judgment — there  is  one  respect  in 


COMPARISON  OF  BI NET-SIMON  AND  POINT  SCALES       489 

which  the  Point  Scale  offers  less  opportunity  for  error  on  account 
of  a  constant  bias  on  the  part  of  the  examiner,  and  one  in  which 
the  Binet  Scale,  even  as  at  present  constituted,  offers  less  oppor- 
tunity for  error.  If  this  (admittedly  hazardous)  reasoning  is 
correct  the  situation  is  about  a  *  stand-off.' 

12.  The  Point  Scale  'works  with  a  smaller  amount  of  testing 
material,  and  thus  makes  possible  a  better  choice  of  the  same.9 

The  twelfth  point  is  not  self-evident,  particularly  since  the 
program  of  the  Point  Scale  calls  for  the  multiplication  of  the 
present  number  of  tests  four  fold. 

13.  The  Binet-Simon  Scale  cannot — and  by  implication  the  Point 
Scale    can — diagnose    moral    imbecility,    dementia    and    intellectual 
degeneration,  and  occasional  phenomena  of  degeneracy  such  as  im- 
pulsions, obsessions  and.  delirium. 

The  present  Point  Scale  cannot  diagnose  moral  imbecility, 
etc.,  any  better  than  can  the  Binet-Simon  Scale,  and  no  proposals 
are  made  which  promise  to  make  such  diagnosis  possible. 

14.  The  statistical  results  of  the  application  of  the  Binet-Simon 
Scale  are  unsatisfactory,  and  a  comparison  of  the  results  of  the  ex- 
amination of  the  same  100  cases  by  the  two  scales  are  favorable  to  the 
Point  Scale. 

The  comparison  of  the  statistical  results  of  the  application  of 
the  two  scales  to  the  same  100  children  do  not  seem  to  the  writer 
to  be  conclusive.  In  the  first  place,  these  100  children  were  part 
of  the  group  the  examination  of  whom  formed  the  basis  of  the 
Point  Scale  norms,  and  their  Point  Scale  ratings  were  to  some 
degree  tested  by  a  comparison  with  themselves.  Furthermore,  the 
mode  of  selection  of  the  cases  is  not  stated,  and  when  the  two 
ratings  do  not  agree  we  have  no  means  of  knowing  which  is  more 
nearly  right.  They  are  apparently  not  random  selections,  since 
only  one  individual  is  rated  as  normal  by  each  scale. 

15.  The  Point  Scale  can  be  developed  so  as  to  give  differential 
rating  in  the  different  kinds  of  mental  processes,  namely,  receptivity, 
imagination,  affectivity  and  thought. 

The  development  of  differential  scales  is  highly  desirable,  but 
the  essential  problem  concerning  it  is  the  selection  of  tests,  and 
when  this  is  done  they  can  be  arranged  either  on  the  age  principle  or 
on  the  point  scale  principle,  after  the  manner  of  the  present  scales. 

This  review  does  not  attempt  to  pass  judgment  on  the  com- 
parative merits  of  the  two  scales,  but  only  to  criticize  the  com- 
parison which  is  made  by  the  authors  of  the  Point  Scale.  If  this 


49°  F.  N.  FREEM4N 

criticism  is  drastic  it  is  not  more  so  than  the  criticism  of  the  Binet- 
Simon  Scale  on  which  it  comments.  These  comments  may  be  sum- 
marized in  the  statement  that  the  criticisms  of  the  Binet-Simon  Scale, 
which  are  made  by  the  authors  of  the  Point  Scale  are  for  the  most 
part  not  essential  and  may  be  obviated  by  revision,  or  are  equally 
applicable  to  the  Point  Scale  itself. 

FRANK  N.  FREEMAN. 
UNIVERSITY  QF  CHICAGO. 


ucari.   HUU 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
SUPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET