Skip to main content

Full text of "Psychologies Of 1925"

See other formats


go 



125369 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

POWELL LECTURES IN PSYCHOLOGICAL THEORY 

Second Edition 

By 
MADISON BENTLEY, PkD. 

University of Illinois 

KNIGHT DUNLAP, PLD. 

Johns Hopkins University 

WALTER S. HUNTER, Ph.D. 

Clark University 

KURT KOFFKA, PkD. 

University of Giessen 

WOLFGANG K6HLER, PLD. 

University of Berlin 

WILLIAM McDOUGALL, Sc.D, F.R.S. 

Harvard University 

MORTON PRINCE, M.D. 

Harvard University 

JOHN B. WATSON, Ph.D. 

Johns Hopkins University 

ROBERT S. WOODWORTH, Ph.D. 

Columbia University 



Edited by 

CARL MURCHISON, PLD. 

Clark University 

CLARK UNIVERSITY 

WORCESTER, MASSACHUSETTS 
1927 



PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION 



Having, during certain stages in my own student days, ex- 
perienced something of the futility resulting from unadmitted 
fundamental differences in theoretical presuppositions, I have 
grown more and more convinced that experimental methods 
are largely instances of the more or less systematic theories of 
the experimenter. Practically any publication from the Cor- 
nell Psychological Laboratory carries a majority of the ear- 
marks of Structuralism. One would look in vain for those 
ear-marks in any scientific article from Watson, Hunter, or 
Lashley, for the ear-marks of Behaviorism attract attention 
there. Any scientific publication from Berlin these days es- 
tablishes once more the Gestalt Theorie. The pedagogical 
danger here is caused by the tendency of each of these theo- 
retical groups to think of its rivals in terms of caricature, 
and so to describe them to the public and to young students. 
The result is that theoretical tradition becomes established in 
certain educational communities, and students are born struc- 
turalists or behaviorists just as one may be born a democrat 
or a presbyterian. 

Upon mentioning these matters to my father-in-law, Dr. 
Elmer Ellsworth Powell, I found him already thinking of the 
same difficulties. Shortly afterwards he made a financial gift 
to Clark University, initiating a series known as the Powell 
Lectures in Psychological Theory. The men who have lec- 
tured in this series are admitted by all psychologists to be true 
leaders in the theoretical provinces herein described. 



We have here a genuine cross-section of contemporary the- 
oretical psychology. Here are the norms with which future 
psychologies can be compared. Here are the principles which 
are up-to-date through the year 1925. We at dark hope that 
it is the beginning of a series of cross-sections appearing at 
five or ten-year intervals. If such proves to be the case, it is 
to be hoped that in the future the various fields of psychology 
may also be represented. 

CARL MURCHISON. 

CLARK UNIVERSITY, 
Worcester, Massachusetts. 
May 1, 1926. 



TABLE OF CONTENTS 

PART I. SCHOOLS OF BEHAVIORISM 

Chapter Page 

1. WHAT THE NURSERY HAS TO SAY ABOUT IN- 
STINCTS, John B. Watson 1 

2. EXPERIMENTAL STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF THE 
EMOTIONS, John B. Watson 37 

3. RECENT EXPERIMENTS ON HOW WE LOSE AND 
CHANGE OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT, John B. 
Watson 59 

4. PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY, Walter S. 
Hunter 83 

PART II. DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 

5. DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY, Robert 5. Woodworth Ill 

PART III. GESTALT 

6. MENTAL DEVELOPMENT, Kurt Koffka 129 

7. INTELLIGENCE OF APES, Wolfgang Kohler 145 

8. AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY, Wolfgang 
Kohler 163 

PART IV. PURPOSIVE GROUPS 

9. THREE FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIOR. 
ISTS AND THE RECONCILIATION OF THE PURPOS- 
IVE AND MECHANISTIC CONCEPTS, Morton Prince ... 199 

10. AWARENESS, CONSCIOUSNESS, CO-CONSCIOUSNESS, 
AND ANIMAL INTELLIGENCE. FROM THE POINT OF 
VIEW OF THE DATA OF ABNORMAL PSYCHOLOGY 
A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS, Morton 

-^Prince 221 

11. THE PROBLEM OF PERSONALITY: HOW MANY 
SELVES HAVE WE?, Morton Prince 245 

12. MEN OR ROBOTS? I, William McDougall 273 

13. MEN OR ROBOTS? II, William McDougaU 293 

PART V. REACTION PSYCHOLOGY 

14. THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY, 

Knight Dunlap 309 

15. THE EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY, 
Knight Dunlap T 331 

16. THE APPLICATIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO SOCIAL 
PROBLEMS, Knight Dunlap * 353 

PART VI. PSYCHOLOGIES CALLED "STRUCTURAL" 

17. HISTORICAL DERIVATION, Madison Bentley ! . . 383 

18. THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS, Madison 
Bentley 395 

19. THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ORGANISM, Madison Bentley . . 405 



TABLE OF ILLUSTRATIONS 

John B. Watson 1 

Walter S. Hunter 83 

Robert S. Woodworth Ill 

Kurt Koffka 129 

Wolfgang Kohler 145 

Morton Prince 199 

William McDougall 273 

Knight Dunlap 309 

Madison Bentley 333 



PARTI 

Schools of Behaviorism 




JOHN B. WATSON 



CHAPTER I 

WHAT THE NURSERY HAS TO SAY 
ABOUT INSTINCTS* 



BY JOHN B. WATSON 



I. GENERAL CONSIDERATIONS 

Introduction: In this brief course of lectures I wish to 
talk about how man is equipped to behave at birth a subject 
that touches the very heart of human psychology. 

When the array of facts about any subject is not very 
complete, it is only human nature to announce a thesis, that 
is, state what one is going to try to prove and then try to 
prove it by a logical argument. I am in that position tonight. 
I have not the full set of facts about the so-called "instinctive" 
nature of man I do not know who has; hence, please look 
upon these lectures both as logical presentations of what facts 
there are in the case and as a thesis which I am trying to 
defend. I shall present my thesis first. 

The Thesis Presented 

Man is an animal born with certain definite types of struc- 
ture. Having that kind of structure, he is forced to respond to 
stimuli at birth in certain ways (for example: breathing, heart 
beat, sneezing, and the like. A fairly full list I shall give you 
later on). This repertoire of responses is in general the same 
for each of us. Yet there exists a certain amount of variation 
in each the variation is probably merely proportional to the 
variation there is in structure (including in structure, of 
course, chemical constitution). It is the same repertoire now 
that it was when the genus homo first appeared many millions 
of years ago. Let us call this group of reactions, man's un- 
learned behavior. / 

In this relatively simple list of human responses there is 
none corresponding to what is called an "instinct" by present- 
day psychologists and biologists. There are then for us no 
instincts we no longer need the term in psychology. Every- 
thing we have been in the habit of calling an "instinct" today 
is a result largely of training belonging to man's learned 
behavior. 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan- 
uary 16, 1925. 



2 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

As a corollary from this, I wish to draw the conclusion that 
there is no such thing as an inheritance of capacity, talent, 
temperament, mental constitution and characteristics. These 
things again depend on training that goes on mainly in the 
cradle. The behaviorist would not say: "He inherits his 
father's capacity or talent for being a fine swordsman." He 
would say : "This child certainly has his father's slender build 
of body, the same type of eyes. His build is wonderfully like 
his father's. He, too, has the build of a swordsman." And 
he would go on to say : " and his father is very fond of him. 
He put a tiny sword into his hand when he was a year of age, 
and in all their walks he talks sword play, attack and defense, 
the code of duelling and the like." A certain type of struc- 
ture, plus early training slanting accounts for adult per- 
formance. 

The Argument In Its Defence 

Let me start by saying that man to the behaviorist is a whole 
animal. When he reacts he reacts with each and every part 
of his body. Sometimes he reacts more strongly with one 
group of muscles and glands than with another. We then say 
he is doing something. We have named many of these acts 
such as breathing, sleeping, crawling, walking, running, fight- 
ing, crying, etc. But please do not forget that each of these 
named acts involves the whole body. 

We must begin, too, to think of man as a mammal a primate 
a two-legged animal with two arms and two delicate, mobile 
hands; as an animal that has a nine months embryonic life, 
a long helpless infancy, a slow developing childhood, eight 
years of adolescence and a total life span of some three score 
years and ten. 

We find^ this animal living in the tropics almost without 
shelter; going naked; living upon easily caught animals and 
upon fruit and herbs that require no cultivation. We find 
him in temperate regions, but dwelling here in well-built, steam- 
heated houses. We find the male always heavily clad even in 
summer, wearing a hat upon his head the only naturally 
protected part of his body. We find the female of this species 
dressed in the scantiest of clothes. We find the male working 
frantically (the female rarely) at almost every kind of vocation, 
from digging holes in the ground, damming up water like 
beavers, to building tall buildings of steel and concrete. Again 
we find man in arctic regions, clad in furs, eating fatty foods 
and living in houses built of snow and ice. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 3 

Everywhere we find man, we find him doing the strangest 
things, displaying the most divergent manners and customs. 
In Africa we find the blacks eating one another ; in China we 
find men eating mainly rice and throwing it towards the mouth 
with dainty chopsticks. In other countries we find man using 
a metal knife and fork. So widely different is the adult be- 
havior of the primitive Australian bushmen from that of the 
dwellers in internal China, and both of these groups differ so 
widely in behavior from the cultivated Englishman, that the 
question is forced upon us Do all members of the genus homo, 
wherever they are found in biological history, start at birth 
with the same group of responses, and are these responses 
aroused by the same set of stimuli? Put in another way, is 
the unlearned, birth equipment of man, which you have been 
in the habit of calling instincts, the same wherever he is found, 
be it in Africa or in Boston, be it in the year six million B. C. 
or in 1925 A. D., whether born in the cotton fields of the 
South, in the Mavflower or beneath the silken purple quilts 
of European royalty? 

The Genetic Psychologists? Answer 

The genetic psychologist the student best qualified to an- 
swer this question hates to be faced with it because his data 
are limited. But since he is forced to answer, he can give 
his honest conviction. His answer is, "Yes, within the limits 
of individual variation, man is born with the same general set 
of responses (let us wait before we call them instincts, though) 
regardless of the station of his parents, regardless of the geo- 
logical age in which he was born and regardless of the geo- 
graphical zone in which he was born." 

But you say, is there nothing in heredity is there nothing 
in eugenics is there no advantage in being born an "F. F. V." 
has there been no progress in human evolution? Let us ex- 
amine a few of the questions you are now bursting to utter. 

Certainly black parents will bear black children if the line 
is pure (except possibly once in a million years or so when 
a sport or "mutant" is born which theoretically may be white, 
yellow or red). Certainly the yellow-skinned Chinese parents 
will bear yellow-skinned offspring. Certainly Caucasian parents 
will bear white children. But these differences are relatively 
slight. They are due among other things to differences in 
the amount and kind of pigments in the skin. I defy anyone 
to take these infants at birth, study their behavior, and mark 
off differences in behavior that will characterize white from 



4 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 

black, and white or black from yellow. There will be differen- 
ces in behavior but the burden of proof is upon the individual, 
be he biologist or eugenist, who claims that these racial dif- 
ferences are greater than the individual differences. 

Again you say, "How about children born from parents who 
have large hands, with short stiff fingers, with extra fingers 
or toes? It can be shown that children from these parents 
inherit these peculiarities of structure." Our answer is : "Yes, 
thousands of variations are laid down in the germ plasm and 
will always appear (other factors being equal) in the off spring." 
Other inheritances are color of hair, color of eyes, texture 
of skin, Albinism (very light individuals with little or no pig- 
ment in hair and eyes vision always being defective). The 
biologist, knowing the makeup of the parents and grandparents, 
can predict many of even the finer structural characteristics 
of the offspring. 

So let us hasten to admit yes, there are heritable differences 
in form, in structure. Some people are born with long, slender 
fingers, with delicate throat structure ; some are born tall, large, 
of prize-fighter build; others with delicate skin and eye color- 
ing. These differences are in the germ plasm and are handed 
down from parent to child. More questionable are the in- 
heritance of such things as the early or late graying of hair, 
the early _ loss of hair, the span of life, the bearing of twins, 
and the like. Many of these questions have already been an- 
swered by the biologists and many others are in the process 
of being answered. But do not let these undoubted facts of 
inheritance lead you astray as they have some of the biologists. 
The mere presence of these structures tell us not one thing 
about function. This has been the source of a' great deal of 
confusion in the subject we have under consideration tonight. 
Much of our structure laid down in heredity would never 
come to light, would never show in function, unless the organ- 
ism were put in a certain environment, subjected to certain 
stimuli and forced to undergo training. Our hereditary struc- 
ture lies ready to be shaped in a thousand different ways 
the same structure mind you depending on the way in which 
the child is brought up. To convince yourself, measure the 
right arm of the blacksmith, look at the pictures of strong men 
in our terrible magazines devoted to physical culture. Or turn 
to the poor bent back of the ancient bookkeeper. They are 
structurally shaped (within limits) by the kinds of lives they 
lead. ^ 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 5 

Are 'Mental' Traits Inherited? 

But every one admits this about bone and tendons and 
muscles "How about mental traits? Do you mean to say 
that great talent is not inherited? That criminal tendencies 
are not inherited ? Surely we can prove that these things can be 
inherited." This was the older idea, the idea which grew up 
before we knew as much about what early shaping throughout 
infant life will do as we know now. The question is often 
put in specific form : "Look at the musicians who are the sons 
of musicians; look at Wesley Smith, the son of the great 
economist, John Smith surely a chip off the old block if 
ever there was one." You already know the behaviorist's way 
of answering these questions. You know he recognizes no 
such thing as mental traits, dispositions or tendencies. Hence, 
to him, there is no sense to the question of the inheritance of 
talent as the question is ordinarily raised. 

Wesley Smith early in life was thrown into an environment 
that fairly reeked with economic, political and social questions. 
His attachment for his father was strong. The path he took 
was a very natural one. He went into that life for the same rea- 
son that your son becomes a lawyer, a doctor or a politician. If 
the father is a shoemaker, a saloon keeper or a street cleaner, or 
engaged in any other non-socially recognized occupation, the son 
does not follow so easily in the father's footsteps, but that is 
another story. Why did Wesley Smith succeed in reaching 
eminence when so many sons who have famous fathers fail to 
attain equal eminence ? Was it because this particular son in- 
herited his father's talent? There may be a thousand reasons, 
not one of which lends any color to the view that Wesley 
Smith inherited the "talent" of his father. Suppose John 
Smith had had three sons who by hypothesis all had equal 
abilities and all began to work upon economics at the age of 
six months^One was beloved by his father. He followed in 
his father's footsteps and, due to his father's tutorship, this 
son overtook and finally surpassed his father. Two years 
after the birth of Wesley, the second son was born, but the 
father was taken up with the elder son. The second son was 
beloved by the mother who now got less of her husband's 
time, so she devoted her time to the second son. The second 
son could not follow so closely in the footsteps of his father; 
he was influenced naturally by what his mother was doing. 

'lAnd by this statement we do not mean that their genetic consti- 
tution is identical. 



6 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

He early gave up his economic studies, entered society and 
ultimately became a "lounge lizard." The third son, born 
two years later, was unwanted. The father was taken up with 
the eldest son, the mother with the second son. The third 
son was also put to work upon economics, but receiving little 
parental care, he drifted daily towards the servants' quarters. 
An unscrupulous maid taught him to masturbate at three. 
At twelve the chauffeur made a homosexual out of him. 
Later, falling in with neighborhood thieves, he became a pick- 
pocket, then a stool-pigeon and finally a drug fiend. He died 
in an insane asylum of paresis. There was nothing wrong 
with the heredity of any one of these sons. All by hypothe- 
sis had equal chances at birth. All could have been the fathers 
of fine, healthy sons if their respective wives had been of 
good stock (except possibly for the third son after he con- 
tracted syphilis). 

You will probably say that I am flying in the face of the known 
facts of eugenics and experimental evolution that the geneti- 
cists have proven that many of the behavior characteristics of the 
parents are handed down to the offspring they will cite ma- 
thematical ability, musical ability, and many, many other types. 
My reply is that the geneticists are working under the banner 
of the old "faculty" psychology. One need not give very much 
weight to any of their present conclusions. Before the even- 
ing is over I hope to show you that there are no ''faculties" 
and no stereotyped patterns of behavior which deserve the 
name either of "talent" or "instinct." 

Differences in Structure and Differences in Early Training 

Will Account for All Differences in Later Behavior 
A while ago I said that, granting individual variation in 
structure, we could find no real proof that man's unlearned 
repertoire of acts has differed through the ages or that he has 
ever been either more or less capable of putting on complex 
training than in 1925. The fact that there are marked indi- 
vidual variations in structure among men has been known since 
biology began. But we have never sufficiently utilized it in 
analyzing man's behavior. Tonight I want to utilize still 
another fact only recently brought out by the behaviorists and 
other students of animal psychology, namely, that habit forma-' 
tion starts in all probability in embryonic life, and that even 
in the human young, environment shapes behavior so quickly 
that all of the older ideas about what types of behavior ore 
inherited and what are learned break down. Grant variations 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 7 

in structure at birth and rapid habit formation from birth, and 
you have a basis for explaining many of the so-called facts 
of inheritance of "mental" characteristics. Let us take up 
these two points: 

(1) Human Beings Differ in the Way They are Put Together 

Those of you who have physiological training have a good 
idea of the complexity of the material that goes into the human 
body. You realize the fact that there must be variation in the 
way these complicated tissues are put together. We have just 
brought out the fact that some human beings are born with 
long fingers, some with short; some with long arm and leg 
bones, some with short; some with hard bones, and some with 
soft; some with over-developed glands; some with poorly 
functioning glands. Again you know that we can identify 
human beings by differences in their finger prints. No two 
human beings have ever had the same finger prints, yet you 
can mark off man's hand and foot prints from the tracks of 
all other animals. No two human beings have bones exactly 
alike, yet any good comparative anatomist can pick out a human 
bone (and there are over 200 of them) from the bones of 
every other mammal. If so simple a thing as the markings 
on the fingers differ in every individual, you have absolute 
proof that general behavior will and must be different. They 
crawl differently, cry differently, differ in the frequency with 
which defaecation and urination occur, differ in early vocal 
efforts, in requirements for food, in the speed and rapidity 
with which they use their hands even identical twins show 
these differences because they differ structurally and differ 
slightly in their chemical makeup. They differ likewise in the 
finer details of sense organ equipment, in the details of brain 
and cord structure, in the heart and circulatory mechanisms, 
and in the length, breadth, thickness and flexibility of the 
striped muscular systems. 

Yet with all of these structural differences "a man's a man 
for a' that" all are made up of the same material and have 
the same general architectural plan regardless of habits. 

(2) Differences In Early Training Make Men Still More 

Different 

There are then admittedly these slight but significant differ- 
ences in structure between one human being and every other 
human being. Differences in early training are even more 
marked. I will not stop now to give much proof of this 



8 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the next two lectures will furnish it abundantly. We now 
know that conditioned reflexes start in the human child at 
birth (and possibly before) we know that there is no such 
thing as giving two children, even belonging to the same family, 
the same training. A doting young married couple have 
twins a boy and a girl they are dressed alike and fed alike. 
But the father pets and fondles the girl, surrounds her with 
love; the mother treats the boy in the same way, but the father 
wants the boy to follow in his own footsteps. He is stern 
with him he can't help shaping the boy his way. The mother 
wants the girl to be modest and maidenly. Soon they show 
great differences in behavior. They receive different training 
from infancy. The next children are born. Now the father 
is more taken up with affairs he has to work harder. The 
mother is more taken up with social duties; servants are 
brought in. The younger children have brothers and sisters; 
they are brought up in a wholly different world. One child 
falls ill. Strict training is abandoned; all rules are off with 
a sickly child. Again, one child gets badly frightened be- 
comes conditioned shows fear at everything; he becomes 
timid and his regular course of boyish activity is interfered 
with. Indeed we may take an actual case. Two girls, aged 
nine, live in adjoining houses. They have the "same" train- 
ing (mothers are close friends and bring up children accord- 
ing to the same rules). One day they took a walk. The girl 
on the left looked at the street and saw only street activity, 
the one on the right looked towards the houses and saw a man 
exposing his sex organs. The girl on the right was consider- 
ably troubled and disturbed and reached equanimity only after 
months of discussion with her parents. 

In this audience I am sure I do not need to multiply in- 
stances of early differences in training and conditioning. 

The Conclusion We Draw 

How will -these two things explain the so-called facts of 
inheritance _ of talent or mental characteristics. Let us take 
a hypothetical case. Here are two boys, one aged 7, the 
other 6. The father is a pianist of great talent, the mother 
an artist working in oil, a portrait painter of note. The 
father has strong, large hands but with long, flexible fingers 
(it is a myth that all artists have long, tapering, finely formed 
fingers). The ^ older son has the same type of hand. The 
father loves his first born, the mother the younger. Then 
the process of "creating he them in his own image" begins. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 9 

The world is brought up on the basis largely of shaping the 
young you are attached -to as you yourself have been shaped. 
Well, in this case the older becomes a wonderful pianist, the 
younger an indifferent artist. So much for different training 
or different slanting in youth. But what about different 
structure ? Please note this : The younger son, under ordinary 
conditions, could not have been trained into a pianist. His 
fingers were not long enough and the muscular arrangement 
of the hand was not flexible enough. But even here we should 
be cautious the piano is a standard instrument a certain 
finger span and a certain hand, wrist and finger strength are 
needed. But suppose the father had been fond of the younger 
child and said, "I want him to be a pianist and I am going to 
try an experiment his fingers are short he'll never have a 
flexible hand, so I'll build him a piano. I'll make the keys' 
narrow so that even with his short fingers his span will be 
sufficient, and I'll make different leverage for the keys so that 
no particular strength or even flexibility will be needed." 
Who knows? the younger son under these conditions might 
have become the world's greatest pianist. 

Such factors, especially those on -the training side, have 
been wholly neglected in the study of inheritance. We have 
not the facts to build up statistics on the inheritance of special 
types of behavior, and until the facts have been brought out 
by -the study of the human young, all data on the evolution 
of different forms of human behavior and eugenics must be 
accepted with the greatest caution. 

Our conclusion, then, is that we have no real evidence of 
the inheritance of traits. I would feel perfectly confident in 
the ultimately favorable outcome of careful upbringing of a 
healthy, well-formed baby born of a long line of crooks, mur- 
derers, thieves and prostitutes. Who has any evidence to the 
contrary? Many, many thousands of children yearly, born 
from moral households and steadfast parents, become way- 
ward, steal or become prostitutes, through one mishap or 
another of nurture. Many more thousands of sons and daugh- 
ters of the wicked grow up to be wicked because they couldn't 
grow up any other way in such surroundings. But let one 
adopted child who has a bad ancestry go wrong and it is used 
as incontestible evidence for the inheritance of moral turpi- 
tude and criminal tendencies. As a matter of fact, there has 
not been a double handful of cases in the whole of our civiliza- 
tion where records have been carefully enough kept for us to 



10 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

draw any such conclusions mental testers, Lombroso, and all 
other students of criminality to the contrary notwithstanding. 
All of us know that adopted children are never brought up 
as one's own. One cannot use statistics gained from observa- 
tions in charitable institutions and orphan asylums. All one 
needs to do to discount such statistics is to go there and work 
for a while, and I say this without trying to belittle the work 
of such organizations. 

I should like to go one step further tonight and say, "Give 
me a dozen healthy infants, well- formed, and my own specified 
world to bring them up in and I'll guarantee to take any one 
at random and train him to become any type of specialist I 
might select & doctor, lawyer, artist, merchant-chief and, yes, 
even into beggar-man and thief, regardless of his talents, 
penchants, tendencies, abilities, vocations and race of his an- 
cestors." I am going beyond my facts and I admit it, but so 
have the advocates of the contrary and they have been doing 
it for many thousands of years. Please note that when this 
experiment is made I am to be allowed to specify the way 
they are to be brought up and the type of world they have 
to live in. 

Where there are structural defects that are inherited, as 

apparently is the case in certain glandular diseases, in "mental" 

defectives, where there is intra-uterine infection as in syphilis 

and in gonorrhea, troublesome behavior of one kind or another 

may develop early and rapidly. But some of these children 

haven't the structural possibilities to be trained as when 

fundamental connections in body and brain arc lacking. 

Again, where there are structural defects more easily observed 

as m Deformities, loss of digits, extra digits, etc,, there is social 

inferiority competition on equal grounds is denied. The 

same ^is true when inferior races are brought up along with 

superior races. We have no sure evidence of inferiority in 

the negro race. Educate a white child and a negro child in 

the same school bring them up in the same family (theoreti- 

cally without difference) and yet when society begins to exert 

its crushing might, the negro cannot compete. 1 

The truth is society does not like to face facts. Pride of 



The g SSLSS. 1 * 6 h ? ritan ? e f t ac ^d bd^lor char- 





THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 11 

race has been strong, hence our Mayflower ancestry our 
Daughters of the Revolution. We like to boast of our ances- 
try. It sets us apart. We like to think it takes three gen- 
erations to make a gentleman (sometimes a lot longer!) and 
that we have more than three behind us. Again, on the other 
hand, the belief in the inheritance of tendencies and traits saves 
us from blame in the training of our young. The mother says 
when her son goes wrong ''Look at his father or his grand- 
father (whichever one she hates). What could you expect 
with that ancestry on his father's side?" And the father, when 
the girl shows wayward tendencies "What can you expect? 
Her mother has always let every man she came in contact 
with make love to her." If these tendencies are inherited we 
can't be much blamed for it. Traits in the older psychologies 
are god-given and if my boy or girl goes wrong, I as a parent 
can't be blamed. 

The behaviorist has an axe to grind, you say, by being so 
emphatic? Yes, he has he would like to see the presuppo- 
sitions and assumptions that are blocking us in our efforts to 
spend millions of dollars and years of patient research on 
infant psychology removed because then, and only then, can 
we build up a real psychology of mankind. 

Are There Any Instincts? 

Let us, then, forever lay the ghost of inheritance of apti- 
tudes, of "mental" characteristics, of special abilities (not 
based upon favorable structure such as throat formation in 
singing, hand in playing, structurally sound eyes, ears, etc.) 
and take up the more general question of what the world has 
been in the habit of calling instincts. 

It is not easy to answer this question. Up to the advent 
of the behaviorist, man was supposed to be a creature of many 
complicated instincts. A group of older writers, under the 
sway of the newly created theories of Darwin, vied with one 
another in finding new and perfect instincts in both man and 
animals. William James made a careful selection from among 
these asserted instincts and gave man the following list : Climb- 
ing, imitation, emulation and rivalry, pugnacity, anger, resent- 
ment, sympathy, hunting, fear, appropriation, acquisitiveness, 
kleptomania, const rue tiveness, play, curiosity, sociability, shy- 
ness, clemliness, modesty, shame, love, jealousy, parental love. 
James claims that no other mammal, not even the monkey, can 
lay claim to so large a list. 



12 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

The behaviorist finds himself wholly unable to agree with 
Tames and the other psychologists who claim that man has 
unlearned activities of these complicated kinds. But you who 
are here tonight have been brought up on James or possibly 
even on a worse diet, and it will be hard to dislodge his teach- 
ing. You say, "J ames says an instinct is f a tendency to act 
in such a way as to bring about certain ends without having 
foresight of those ends/ Surely this formulation fits a lot of 
the early behavior of children and young ^ animals/' You 
think you understand it, anyway. At first it looks convinc- 
ing. But when you test it out in terms of your own observa- 
tions on young animals and children, you find that you have 
not a scientific definition but a metaphysical assumption. You 
get lost in the sophistry of 'foresight' and 'end/ 

I don't blame you for being confused. No subject in psy- 
chology today is more written about than the so-called instincts. 
In the past three years more than a hundred articles have been 
written about instincts. The articles in general are of the 
armchair variety written by men who have never watched the 
whole life history of animals and the early childhood of the hu- 
man young. Philosophy will never answer any questions about 
instincts. The questions asked are factual ones to be an- 
swered 'only by genetic observation. Let me hasten to add 
that the behaviorist's knowledge of instinct also suffers from 
lack of observed facts but you cannot accuse him of going 
beyond natural science in his inferences. Before attempting 
to answer the question "What is an instinct?" let us take a 
little journey into mechanics. Possibly we may find that we 
do not need the term after all. 

A Lesson From the Boomerang 

I have in my hand a hardwood stick. If I throw it forward 
and upward it goes a certain distance and drops to the ground. 
I retrieve the stick, put it in hot water, bend it at a certain 
angle, throw it out again it goes outward, revolving as it 
goes for a short distance, turns to the right and then drops 
down. Again I retrieve the stick, reshape it slightly and make 
its edges convex. I call it a boomerang. Again I throw it 
upward and outward. Again it goes forward revolving as 
it goes. Suddenly it turns, comes back and gracefully and 
kindly falls at my feet. It is still a stick, still made of the 
same material, but it has been shaped differently. Has the 
boomerang an instinct to return to the hand of the thrower? 
No? Well, why does it return? Because it is made in such a 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 13 

way that when it is thrown upward and outward with a given 
force it must, return (parallelogram of forces). Let me call 
attention to the fact here that all well made and well thrown 
boomerangs will return to or near to the thrower's feet, but 
no two will follow exactly the same forward pathway or the 
same return pathway, even if shot mechanically with the same 
application of force and at the same elevation; yet they are 
all called boomerangs. This example may be a little unusual 
to you. Let us take one a little easier. Most of us have rolled 
dice now and again. Take a die, load it in a certain way, roll 
it, and the face bearing "six" will always come up when the 
die is thrown. Why? The die must roll that way because 
of the way it was constructed. Again take a toy soldier. 
Mount it on a semi-circular loaded rubber base. No matter 
how you throw this soldier, he will always bob upright, os- 
cillate a bit, then come to a steady vertical position. Has the 
rubber soldier an instinct to stand erect? 

Notice that not until the boomerang, the toy soldier and the 
die are hurled into space 'do they exhibit their peculiarities 
of motion. Change their form or their structure, or alter 
the material out of which they are made (make them of iron 
instead of wood r or rubber) and their characteristic motion 
may markedly change. But man is made up of certain kinds 
of material put together in certain ways. If he is hurled 
into action (as a result of stimulation) may he not exhibit 
movement (in advance of training) just as peculiar as (but 
no more mysterious than) that of the boomerang? 1 

Concept Of Instinct No Longer Needed In Psychology 
This brings us to our central thought tonight. If the boomer- 
ang has no instinct (aptitude, capacity, tendency, trait, etc.) 
to return to the hand of the thrower; if we need no mysterious 
way of accounting for the motion of the boomerang; if the 
laws of physics will account for its motions cannot psy- 
chology see in this a much needed lesson in simplicity? Can 

i-You wtll argue that in mechanics action and reaction are equal 
that the boomerang is hit with a force equal to so many ergs and 
that just that many ergs are used up in returning to the hand of the 
thrower (including the heat loss to the air) but that when I touch 
a man with ,a hair and he jumps two feet high, the reaction is out 
of all proportion to the energy in the stimulus. The reply is that 
in man the energy used in the reaction was stored. In dynamics 
you find the same thing when a match touches off a powder blast 
or a breeze blows from a cliff a rocking boulder that destroys a 
house in the valley. 



14 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

it not dispense with instincts? Can we not say, "Man is built 
of certain materials put together in certain complex ways, and 
as a corollary of the way he is put together and of the material 
out of which he is made he must act [until learning has re- 
shaped him] as he does act?" 

But you say : 'That gives your whole argument away you 
admit he does a lot of things at birth which he is^ forced to 
do by his structure this is just what I mean by instinct." My 
answer is that we must now go to the facts. We can no longer 
postpone a visit to the nursery. I think you will find there, 
in the two or three years we shall study the infant and child, 
little that will encourage you to keep sacred James? list of 
instincts. 

II. LABORATORY STUDIES ON THE GENESIS OF BEHAVIOR 

During the past 25 years the -students of animal behavior 
have been gathering a sound body of facts about the young 
of nearly every species of animal except that of man. We have 
lived with young monkeys, we have watched the growth of 
young rats, rabbits, guinea pigs, and birds of many^ species. 
We have watched them develop daily in our laboratories from 
the moment of birth to maturity. To check our laboratory 
results we have watched many of them grow up in their own 
native habitat in a natural environment. 

These studies have enabled us to reach a fair understanding 
of both the unlearned and learned equipment of many species 
of animals. They have taught us that no one by watching the 
performance of the adult can determine what part of a com- 
plicated series of acts belongs in the unlearned category and 
what part belongs in the category of the learned. Best of all, 
they have given us a method that we can apply to the study 
of the human young. Finally, animal studies have taught us 
that it is not safe to generalize from the data we gather on 
one species as to what will be true in another species. For 
example, the guinea pig is born with a heavy coat of fur and 
with a very complete -set of motor responses. It becomes 
practically independent of the mother at three days of age* 
The white rat, on the other hand, is born in a very immature 
state, has a long period of infancy; it becomes independent 
of the mother only at the end of thirty days. Such a wide 
divergence of birth equipment in two animal species so closely 
related (both rodents) proves how unsafe it is to generalize 
on the basis of infra-human animal studies as to what the 
unlearned equipment of man is. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 15 

Resistance to the Study of the Human Young 
Until very recently we have had no reliable data on what 
happens during the first few years of human infancy and 
childhood. Indeed there has been very great resistance to 
studying the behavior of the human young. Society is in the 
habit of seeing them starve by hundreds, of seeing them grow 
up in dives and slums, without getting particularly wrought 
up about it. But let the hardy behaviorist attempt an ex- 
perimental study of the infant or even begin systematic ob- 
servation, and criticism begins at once. When experiments and 
observations are made in the maternity wards of hospitals there 
is naturally also considerable misunderstanding of the behavior- 
ist's aims. The child is not sick, the behaviorist is not ad- 
vancing clinical methods therefore what good are such 
studies? Again, when the parents who have children under 
observation learn of it they become excited. They are ignorant 
of what you are doing and you have great difficulty in making 
them understand what you are doing. These difficulties at first 
confronted us in our work at the Johns Hopkins Hospital but, 
thanks to the broad-mindedness of Dr. J. Whitridge Williams, 
Dean of the Johns Hopkins Medical School, and of Dr. John 
Rowland, physician-in-chief of the Harriet Lane Hospital, a 
satisfactory condition for study was finally arranged. It was 
arranged in such a way that psychological examination of the 
infants became a part of the regular routine of the care of 
all infants born in the hospital. I mention this because if any 
of you ever attempt to make such studies you will be con- 
fronted, until the work has become more generally accepted, 
with a similar set of difficulties. 

Studying the Behavior of the Human Infant 
No one -should attempt to make studies upon the infant 
until he has had considerable training in physiology and in 
animal psychology. He should have practical training in the 
nursery of the hospital where the work is to be done. In this 
way he can learn what is safe to do with a baby and what is 
not. Before recording observations he should watch a few 
deliveries. By watching deliveries he will speedily learn that 
the human infant can stand considerable necessary hard usage 
without breaking under the strain ! 

What We Know About Intra-Uterine Behavior 
Our knowledge of the intra-uterine life of the human young 
is a very meagre indeed. Intra-uterine life begins with the 
fertilization of the ovum. Birth occurs usually at the end 



16 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of the tenth lunar month (280 days) thereafter. The heart 
of the foetus begins to beat around the 18th to 20th week, 
occasionally as early as the 14th week. The heart rate of the 
foetus is very rapid 120-140 beats to the minute. Movement 
of the striped muscular system of the foetus begins at the 
end of the 4th lunar month. There is some evidence that 
the stomach glands begin to function at the end of the 5th 
month. There is apparently very little support to the view 
that defaecation and urination occur in utcro. 

The position of the foetus in the uterus is not without signifi- 
cance since it affects the movements and posture of the infant 
for a considerable time after birth. Dr. J, Whitridge Wil- 
liams describes the intra-uterine position of the foetus as fol- 
lows: "Irrespective of the relation which it may bear to the 
mother, the foetus in the later months of pregnancy assumes 
a characteristic posture, which is described as its attitude or 
habitits; and, as a general rule, it may be said to form an ovoid 
mass, which roughly corresponds with the shape of the uterine 
cavity. Thus, it is folded or bent upon itself in such a way 
that the back becomes markedly convex, the head is sharply 
flexed so that the chin is almost in contact with the breast, 
the thighs are flexed over the abdomen, the legs are bent at 
the knee-joints, and the arches of the feet rest upon the ante- 
rior surfaces of the legs. The arms are usually crossed over 
the thorax or are parallel to the sides, while the umbilical 
cord lies in the space between them and the lower extremities. 
This attitude is usually retained throughout pregnancy, though 
it is frequently modified somewhat by the movements of the 
extremities, and in rare instances the head may become ex- 
tended, when a totally different posture is assumed. The char- 
acteristic attitude results partly from the mode of growth of 
the foetus, and partly from a process of accommodation be- 
tween it and the outlines of the uterine cavity." (Obstetrics, 
p. 180), The extent to which slight differences in the intra- 
uterine position of the foetus may possibly later influence or 
even determine right and left handedness of the individual is 
not known. Attention is called to the fact that the liver is 
on the right side in about 80fo of the observed cases. Whether 
this large organ may swing the foetus slightly so that the right 
side is constantly under less restraint than the left is not 
known. If this is true, the infants with the liver on the right 
side should be right-handed from birth. My records on hun- 
dreds of infants prove that this is not the case. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 17 

In general we get our best information on foetal structures 
ready to function by study of infants prematurely born. At 
six months (lunar) the infant may draw a few gasping breaths 
and make a few abortive movements. It never lives. From 
the 7th month on to full term, infants may live. At birth 
they display the usual birth equipment. This proves that from 
the beginning of the 7th month many structures exist in the 
foetus ready to function as soon as the appropriate stimulus 
is applied : e. g. breathing as soon as the air strikes the lungs ; 
complete and independent circulation and purification of the 
blood as soon as the umbilical cord is severed; independent 
metabolism showing that visceral system is ready to func- 
tion, etc. 

The Birth Equipment of the Human Young 

Almost daily observation of several hundred infants from 
birth through the first thirty days of infancy and of a smaller 
number through the first years of childhood has given us the 
following set of (rough) facts on unlearned responses: 1 

Sneezing: This apparently can begin in a full-fledged way 
from birth. Sometimes it appears even before the so-called 
birth cry is given. It is one of the responses that stays in the 
activity stream throughout life (see p. 35) ; habit factors ap- 
parently affect it very little indeed. No experiments so far 
have ever been made to see if the mere sight of the pepper box 
may not after a sufficient number of conditioning experiments 
call out sneezing. The normal intra-organic stimulus calling 
out sneezing is not very well defined* Sometimes it occurs 
when the baby is taken from a cooler room into an overheated 
room. With some babies carrying them out into the sunshine 
apparently will produce sneezing. 

Hiccoughing : This usually does not begin at birth but can 
be noticed in children from 7 days of age on with great ease. 
Over SO cases have been observed carefully. The earliest 
noted case of hiccoughing was six hours after birth. So far 
as is known, this response is rarely conditioned under the or- 
dinary conditions of life. The stimulus most commonly calling 
it out apparently is the pressure on the diaphragm coming from 
a full stomach. 

Crying : The so-called birth cry takes place at the establish- 
ment of respiration. The lungs are not inflated until the stim- 

^Mrs. Margaret Gray Blanton, working in the psychological labora- 
tory of the Johns Hopkins Hospital has given u-s our best data upon 
this subject (Psychological Review, Vol. 24, p. 466). 



18 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

ulus of the air is present. As the air strikes the lungs and 
mucous membranes of the upper alimentary tract, the mechan- 
ism of breathing is gradually established. To establish breath- 
ing the infant has sometimes to be plunged into icy water. 
Coincident with the plunge into the icy water, the cry appears. 
It usually appears during the vigorous rubbing and slapping 
of the infant's back and buttocks a method invariably em- 
ployed to establish respiration. The birth cry itself differs 
markedly in different infants. 

Hunger will bring out crying, noxious stimuli such as rough 
handling, circumcision or the lancing and care of boils will 
bring out cries even in extremely young infants. When the 
baby 'suspends itself with either hand crying is usually elicited. 

Crying as such very shortly becomes conditioned. The child 
quickly learns that it can control the responses of nurse, parents 
and attendants by the cry, and uses it as a weapon ever there- 
aft^r. Crying in infants is not always accompanied by tears, 
although tears can sometimes be observed as soon as ten min- 
utes iJfeer birth. Owing to the almost universal practice now 
of putting silver nitrate into the eyes shortly after birth, the 
normal appearance of tears is hard to determine. Tears have 
been observed usually, though, on a great many babies from 
the fourth day on. Tears, in all probability, are also condi- 
tioned very quickly, since they are a much more effective 
means of controlling the movements of nurses and parents 
than dry crying. 

Numerous experiments have been carried out to see whether 
the crying of one infant in a nursery will serve as a vStimulus 
to set off the rest of the children in the nursery. ( )ur results 
are entirely negative. In order to more thoroughly control 
the conditions, we made phonographic records of a lusty crier. 
We would then reproduce this sound very close to the ear of, 
first, a sleeping infant, then a wakeful but quiet infant. The 
results again were wholly negative. Hunger contractions and 
noxious stimuli (also loud sounds) are unquestionably the un- 
conditioned stimuli which call out crying. 

Colic, bringing a set of noxious stimuli, may ancl usually 
does call out a cry and apparently one slightly different from 
other types. This is due to the pressure in the abdominal 
cavity caused by the formation of gas. The full set of muscles 
used in the hunger cry is thus not available for the colic cry. 
The cries of infants are so different that at night in a nursery 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 19 

of 25 it does not take very long to be able to name the child 
which is crying regardless of its location in the nursery. 

Erection of Penis: This can occur at birth and from that 
time on throughout life. The complete set of stimuli calling 
out this response is not known. Apparently radiant heat, 
warm water, stroking of the sex organs, possibly pressure from 
the urine, are the main factors operative at birth. This, of 
course, is conditioned later on in life through visual stimula- 
tion and the like. The stimulus to the later appearing orgasm 
is possibly different. Short rhythmical contacts as in coition 
and in masturbation lead to the orgasm (and after puberty to 
its attendant ejaculation). Probably the orgasm itself both 
in men and women can be hastened or slowed through stimulus 
substitutions (through words, sounds, etc. a factor of the ut- 
most sociological importance). 

At what age tumescence becomes a conditioned response is 
not known. Masturbation (a better term with infants is 
manipulation of the penis or vagina respectively) can occur 
at almost any age. The earliest case I have personally ob- 
served was a girl around one year of age (it often begins 
much earlier). The infant was sitting up in the bathtub and 
in reaching for the soap accidentally touched the external open- 
ing of the vagina with her finger. The search for the soap 
stopped, stroking of the vagina began and a smile overspread 
the face. Neither in the case of infant boys nor of infant 
girls have I seen masturbation carried to the point where the 
orgasm takes place (it must be remembered that the orgasm 
can occur without ejaculation in the male before the age of 
puberty is reached). Apparently a great many of the mus- 
cular responses later to be used in the sex act, such as push- 
ing, climbing, stroking, are ready to function in the male at 
least at a very much earlier age than we are accustomed to 
think. In one observed case which came into the clinic, a 
boy of 3J^ years of age would mount his mother or nurse, 
whichever one happened to be sleeping with him. Erection 
would take place and he would manipulate and bite her breast ; 
then clasping and sex movements similar to those of adults 
would ensue. In this case the mother, who was separated 
from her husband, had deliberately attempted to build up this 
reaction in her child. 

V 'aiding of Urine: This occurs from birth. The uncon- 
ditioned stimulus is unquestionably intra-organic due to the 
pressure of the fluid in the bladder. Conditioning of the act 



20 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of urination can begin as early as the second week. Usually, 
however, conditioning at this age requires almost infinite pa- 
tience. Anywhere from the third month on, the infant can 
be conditioned easily by a little care. If the infant is ob- 
served closely at intervals of a half hour or so, it will occa- 
sionally be found dry. When this occurs, place it upon the 
chamber. If the bladder is quite full, the increased pressure 
which comes from putting the infant in a sitting position will 
be stimulus enough to release the act. After repeated trials 
the conditioned response is perfected. Young children can 
be so thoroughly conditioned in this act that the responses can 
be called without awakening them. 

Defaecation: This mechanism seems to be perfect from 
birth and in all probability the mechanism was perfected sev- 
eral weeks before birth. The stimulus probably is pressure 
in the lower colon. Pressing a clinical thermometer into the 
anus from birth often brings about the passage of faeces. 

Defaecation can also be conditioned at a very early age. 
One of the methods of course is to introduce a glycerine or 
soap suppository at the time the infant is placed upon the 
chamber After considerable repetition of this routine, contact 
with the chamber will be sufficient to call out the response* 

Early Eye Movements : Infants from birth when lying flat 
on their backs in a dark room with their heads held horizon- 
tally will slowly turn their eyes towards a faint %ht. Move- 
ments of the eyes are not very well co-ordinated at birth, but 
"cross eyes" are not nearly so prevalent as most people seem 
to believe. Right and left co-ordinated movements of the 
eyes are the first to appear. Upward and downward move- 
ments ^ of the eyes come at a slightly later period. Still later 
on a light can be followed when revolved in a circle over the 
baby's face. 

As is well known, habit factors almost immediately begin 
to enter into fixation and other eye responses. I have already 
brought out the fact that movements both of the lids and of 
the pupils can be conditioned. 

Smiling: Smiling is due in all probability at first to the 
presence of kinaesthetic and tactual stimuli. It appears as 
early as the fourth day. It can most often be seen after a 
full feeding. Light touches on parts of the body, blowing 
upon the body, touching the sex organs and sensitive zones 

of the skin ar< th^ nnrrmrh'tinri^rl cfimiili fha* will nr 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 21 

smiling, lidding under the chin and a gentle jogging and 
rocking of the infant will often bring out smiling. 

Smiling is the response in which conditioning factors begin 
to appear as early as the thirtieth day. Mrs. Mary Cover 
Jones has made an extensive study of smiling. In a large 
group of children she found that conditioned smiling that is, 
smiling when the experimenter smiles or says babyish words 
to the infant (both auditory and visual factors) begins to 
appear at around the thirtieth day. In her total study of 185 
cases, the latest age at which the conditioned smile first ap- 
peared was eighty days. 

Manual Responses : By manual responses hereafter in these 
lectures let us mean different movements of the head, neck, 
legs, trunk, toes, as well as of the arms, hands and fingers. 

Turning the Head : A great many infants at birth, if placed 
stomach down with chin on the mattress, can swing their 
heads to right or left and lift their heads from the mattress. 
We have noticed these reactions from thirty minutes of age 
on. On one occasion fifteen babies were tested one at a time 
in succession. All except one could make these head reactions. 

Holding^ up Head when the Infant is held in Upright Posi- 
tion: This seems to vary with the development of the head 
and neck musculature. Some newborn infants can support 
their heads for a few seconds. The infant is held in the ex- 
perimenter's lap with stomach and back supported. There 
seems to be a rapid improvement in this response due ap- 
parently to the development of structure rather than to train- 
ing factors. The head can be held up in most infants from the 
sixth month on. 

Hand Movements at Birth: Marked hand movements in 
many children can be observed even at birth, such as closing 
the hand, opening it, spreading the fingers, stretching the 
fingers with one or both hands at the same time. Usually in 
these hand movements the thumb is folded inside the palm 
and takes no part in hand response. It does not begin to 
participate in the movements of the hand until a much later 
period around the 100th day. I shall speak of grasping, 
which is also present at birth, later on (p. 25). 

Arm Movements: The slightest stimulation of the skin any- 
where will usually bring out marked arm, wrist, hand and 
shoulder responses. Apparently kinaesthetic and organic 
stimuli may bring out these responses as well as tactual, audi- 
tory and visual stimuli. The arms can be thrown up to the 



22 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

face and even as far as the top of the head and clown to the 
legs. Usually, however, the first movements of the arms, no 
matter where the stimulus is applied, is towards the chest and 
head (probably a remnant of the intra-utcrinc habit). One 
of the most characteristic ways of producing violent move- 
ments of arms and hands is to hold the nose. Fn a very few 
seconds one or the other or both arms fly upward until the 
hand actually comes in contact with the. hand of the experi- 
menter. If one hand is held, the other hand will go up just 
the same. 

Leg and Foot Movements i Kicking is one of the most pro- 
nounced movements to be seen at birth. It can he brought out 
by touching the soles of the feet, by stimulation with hot or 
cold air, by contact with the skin and directly through kin- 
aesthetic stimulation. One characteristic ways of producing 
leg and foot movements is to pinch the skin over the knee.. If 
the left leg is held out straight and the knee cup pinelicd, the 
right foot comes up and in contact with the experimenter's 
fingers. When the inside of the right knee is pinched, the 
left leg goes up and strikes the experimenter's fingers. "Plus will 
appear perfectly at birth. Sometimes it inkcs only a few sec- 
onds for the foot to be brought up as far as the experimenter's 
fingers. 

Trunk, Leg, Foot and Too Movements: When an infant 
is suspending itself with cither right or left hand, marked 
"climbing" motions in the trunk and hips are noticeable.. 
There seems to be a wave of contraction pulling the trunk 
and legs upward followed by a relaxation period, then another 
wave of contraction sets in. Tickling of the foot, stimulating 
the foot with hot water, will produce marked movements in 
foot and toes. Usually if the bottom of the fool is stimulated 
with a match stick, the characteristic Babmski reflex: appears 
in nearly all infants* This is a variable reflex. The usual 
pattern is an upward jump of the great toe (extension) and 
a drawing down of the other toes (flexion). Occasionally 
the Babinski takes the form merely of "fanning," that is, 
spreading of all the toes. The Babinski reflex usually dis- 
appears around the end -of the first year although it may con- 
tinue longer even in normal children. Infants cannot suspend 
themselves with their toes, A wire or other small round ob- 
ject placed under the toes will often produce flexion, that is, 
a closing of the toes, but the slightest pressure will release the 
rod or wire. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 23 

Many infants almost from birth can turn over from face to 
back when placed naked lying on the stomach on an unyielding 
surface. Mrs. Blanton describes one case as follows: Sub- 
ject T, at seven days of age, turned repeatedly from face to 
back when not impeded by clothing. Placed face downward 
on an unyielding surface, her arms outstretched in line with 
her body, she would immediately start crying. Relaxing and 
contracting of the muscles of the legs, arms, abdomen and 
back are natural accompaniments of crying. During the act 
she pulled her knees under her and contracted her muscles 
generally, then relaxed them. Gradually, owing to the un- 
equal activity of the two sides of the body, she would finally 
come to lie nearer to the one side of the body a final spasm 
of muscular effort would put her over. In one case it took 
ten minutes to effect the turn and nine separate spasms. 

Picture here all of the hundreds of partial responses called 
out in the general larger act of turning over. Here again, 
habit very quickly sets in and the response becomes sharper 
and -sharper with the dropping away of many of the part 
reactions. It takes many weeks and months to turn over 
quickly and with a minimum of muscular effort. 

Feeding Responses: Touching the face of a hungry baby 
at the corners of the mouth or on the cheek or on the chin 
will cause quick, jerky head movements which result in bring- 
ing the mouth near the source of stimulation. This has been 
observed many, many times from five hours of age onward. 
The lip or sucking reflex is another characteristic response. 
Tapping slightly with the tip of the finger below or above 
the corner of the mouth of a sleeping baby may bring the 
lips and tongue almost immediately into the nursing position. 
Suckling as such varies tremendously in young infants. It 
can be demonstrated in practically every infant within the 
first hour after birth. Occasionally when there is marked 
injury during birth suckling is retarded. The feeding response 
as such includes sucking, tongue, lip and cheek movements 
and swallowing. With most newborn infants this mechanism, 
unless there is birth injury (or possibly when the parents are 
"feeble-minded") is fairly perfect. 

. The whole group of feeding responses is most easy to con- 
dition. Conditioning can be most easily observed in a bottle 
fed baby. Even before reaching (occurring around the 120th 
day) the infant will get extremely active in its bodily "squirm- 
ings" the instant the bottle is shown. After reaching has de- 



24 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

veloped, the mere sight of the bottle will carry out the lustiest 
kind of bodily movements and crying begins immediately. So 
sensitive do infants become to the visual stimulus of the bottle 
that if it is shown from 12 to 15 feet away, the response begins 
to appear. There are many, many other conditioned factors 
in connection with feeding which I wish I had time to go into 
negative reactions to food, food tantrums and the like. Most 
of these, so far as I can judge, are purely conditioned responses. 
Crawling: Crawling is an indeterminate kind of response. 
Many infants never crawl at all, and all of them exhibit differ- 
ent behavior in crawling. After many experiments I am in- 
clined to believe that crawling comes largely as a result of a 
habit formation. When the infant is placed on its stomach, 
the contact and kinaesthetic stimuli bring out very general 
bodily activity. Oftentimes one side of the body is more active 
than the opposite side; circular (circus) motions result. In 
one 9 months infant turning in a circle resulted for clays but 
no forward progress could be observed. In this gradual twist- 
ing and turning of the body, the child sometimes moves right, 
sometimes left, sometimes forward, indeed, and sometimes 
backward. If, in these movements, it rnangages to reach and 
manipulate some object, we have practically a situation like 
that of the hungry rat in a maze that has food at its center. 
A habit of crawling toward objects results. It probably could 
always be taught if teaching were regularly instituted with the 
milk bottle as the stimulus. Our daily test is conducted as 
follows. The naked infant is placed on the carpet ITis legs 
are extended and a mark is set at the furthest reach of the 
toes. Then a nursing bottle or lump of sugar (previously 
conditioning him on sugar so that he will struggle far it) is 
put just out of reach of the hands. Five minutes is enough for 
the test. Sometimes at the end of the test if crawling* docs 
not appear an electric heater is placed a few feet behind him* 
This merely hastens general bodily activity. 

Standing and Walking: The whole complex mechanism of 
standing upright, first with support, then without support, then 
walking, then running, then jumping, is a very slowly develop- 
ing one. The start of the whole mechanism seems to lie in 
the development of the so-called "extensor thrust." The ex- 
tensor thrust is not usually present during the first few months 
of infancy. Some months after birth if the infant is grad- 
ually lifted up by the arms to nearly a standing position with 
a part of its feet in contact with the floor at all times, there 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 25 

comes, as weight falls on the feet, a stiffening of the muscles 
of both legs. Soon after the appearance of this reflex, the 
child begins to attempt to pull itself up. Between 7 and 8 
months of age many infants can pull themselves up with 
very little help and can support themselves in a standing posi- 
tion holding on to some object for a short space of time. After 
this feat has been accomplished, the next stage in the general 
process is walking around holding on to an object. The final 
stage is the first step alone. The first step alone occurs at 
very variable times, depending upon the weight of the baby, 
its general health, whether or not it has had serious mishaps 
through falling (conditioning and the like). Often the first step 
is taken at 1 year of age and sometimes slightly earlier. In the 
most completely observed case in my records the first step 
was taken at the end of 11 months and 3 days. After the 
first step is taken, the remainder of the act has to be learned 
just as the youths learns to "balance" himself in bicyde riding, 
swimming, skating and tight rope walking. Two factors seem 
to go hand in hand in the development of this mechanism. 
One is the actual growth of the body tissue, the other is habit 
formation. The act can be hastened by coaching (positive 
conditioning) ; it can be markedly retarded at almost any of 
these -stages if the infant falls and injures itself (negative 
conditioning). 

Vocal Behavior: The early sounds made by infants and 
the conditioning and organization of these sounds into words 
and speech habits need a longer treatment than we can give 
them tonight. I don't think I shall have to work hard to 
get you to believe every word is a conditioned response. 

Swimming: Swimming is very largely a process of learn- 
ing. By the time the child first attempts to swim, the well or- 
ganized habits of using arms, legs, hands and trunk are well 
established. "Balancing," breathing, removal of fear, etc., 
are the remaining important factors. 

When the newborn infant is placed in water at body tem- 
perature with head only supported above the water, almost 
no general response is called out. If plunged into cold water 
violent general body response is called out but no movements 
even approximating swimming appear. 

Grasping : With few exceptions infants at birth can support 
their full weight with either right or left hands. The method 
we use in testing them is to place a small rod about the diameter 
of a pencil in one or the other hand closing the fingers on 



26 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the rod. This stimulus causes the grasping reflex to appear. 
It usually starts crying at the same time. Then fingers and 
hands clamp tightly on the rod. During the reaction the 
infant can be completely lifted from the pillow upon which 
it lies. An assistant places her two hands hclow the infant 
ready to catch it as it falls back to the pillow. The length of time 
the infant can support itself varies all the way from a fraction 
of a second to more than a minute. The time in a given case 
may vary considerably on different days. 

The reaction is almost invariable from birth until it begins 
to disappear around the 120th day. The time of disappearance 
of this response varies considerably in observed cases from 
SO days to well over 150 days. There seems to be a continu- 
ance of the reflex in defective infants long after the normal 
period of disappearance. 

Prematurely born infants of 7 and 8 months exhibit the re- 
flex in a normal manner. Infants born without cerebral hemi- 
spheres exhibit the same reaction: in one observed case this 
was tested from birth to death 18 days later. 

How much more than their own weight the infants ran sup- 
port has never been tested out but we have made these 
tests when the infants were fully clothed and sometimes 
slightly weighted. 

This primitive reaction of course finally disappears from 
the 'stream of activity never to reappear. It gives place to the 
habit of handling and manipulation. 

Stinking: Any newborn infant will closes the lids when 
the eye (cornea) is touched or when a current of air strikes 
the eye. But no infant at birth will "blink" when a shadow 
rapidly crosses the eye as when a pencil or piece of paper 
is passed rapidly across the whole field of vision. The earliest 
reaction I have noted occurred on the 65th day. Mrs. Mary 
Cover JonevS noted the reaction in one infant at 40 days. 

It apparently appears quite suddenly it is at first easily 
"fatigued" and is quite variable. liven up to the ago of HO 
days some infants will not blink every time the stimulus is 
applied. Usually at 100 days the infant will blink whenever 
the stimulus is applied if at least one minute is allowed be- 
tween stimulations. This reaction stays in the activity stream 
until death. We cannot prove it yet but tins reaction looks 
to us very much like a conditioned visual eyelid response, as 
follows : 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 27 

(U)S (U)R 

Contact with cornea blink 

but objects which touch the eye often cast a shadow, hence 

(C)S (U)R 

Shadow blink 

If this reasoning is correct, blinking at a shadow is not an 
unlearned response. 

Handedness: We have already pointed out the possibility 
of handedness being due to the long enforced intra-uterine 
position of the child (really a habit). Studies of handedness 
can be made from birth on in several different ways. 

1. Measurements of right and left anatomical structures, 
such as width of right and left wrist, palm, length of fore- 
arm, etc. The measurements have been made, with specially 
devised instruments, upon several hundred children. The re- 
sults show that there is no significant difference in the right 
and left measurements. The average error of the measurement 
is greater than the observed difference. 

2. By recording the time of suspension (see grasping) 
with left and right hand. Care is taken in all such tests to 
begin work with the right hand on one day and with the 
left hand on the following day. Chart I (left two columns) 
shows that there is no constancy in time of suspension from 
day to day. 

3. By recording approximately the total amount of work 
done with right and left hands for a given period of time. 
For this work we use an especially devised work adder. This, 
in principle is an escapement wheel that works in such a way 
that no matter how the baby slashes its arms about, it turns 
the wheel always in one direction. As the wheel revolves, 
it winds up a small lead weight attached to the wheel by a 
cord. Of course there is a separate instrument in use for 
each hand. At the beginning of the work period, the two 
weights are let down until they just touch the table top. The 
hands of the baby are then attached. His slashing movements 
begin to wind the ball up. Usually the baby lies naked on 
his back, unstimulated by the observer. At the end of five 
minutes there the baby is taken out of the apparatus and the 
height in inches of the two weights above the table top is 
measured. 

Again when we face the records obtained in this way we find 
little significant difference between the work of the two hands. 



28 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



Chart I 1 


Showing daily record of results on the two hands : 
Age Time of suspension [in seconds] Work done on ad- 
i n dcrs [in inches] 


Days 
1 


Right 
1.2 


Left 
5.6 


Right 
16.16 


Left 
13.75 


2 


2.2 


3.0 


25.00 


15.00 


3 


.6 


1.4 


37.50 


36.25 


4 


.6 


1.4 


12.00 


15.00 


5 


1.2 


1.0 


15.00 


27.00 


6 


1.0 


1.6 


17.16 


16.00 


7 


.6 


3.2 


21.25 


29.37 


8 


1.0 


2.2 


24.16 


18.37 


9 


1.8 


1.8 


17.25 


13.00 


40 


1.4 


.6 


28.00 


9.00 


Average 


1.16 


2.08 


21.34 


19.27 


Longer with 


right 


3 


More work with right 


.... 7 


Longer with 


left 


6 


More work with left 


3 


Eciual 




,. 1 


Equal 


.... 



Chart I (right two columns) gives the record of one infant 
for the first ten days of its life. The table as a whole shows 
both the results obtained from the work adder and from sus- 
pension. Note that the average time of suspension for J. 
was with right hand 1.16 seconds; for the left 2.08 seconds. 
The average work done (average height weight was wound 
up) with right hand was 21.34 inches; with left hand 19.27 
indies. On 3 days he suspended himself longer with right 
hand; on 6 days with left hand; on 1 day the time of sus- 
pension was equal. Note, too, that he wound the weight up 
faster with right hand on 7 days and with lef t^ 3 days. 

Thus we see how handedness varies during the first few 
days of infancy. No dependence can be placed in the records 
of one child* We give one record here simply to show the 
type of results to expect. When a distribution curve is made 
by plotting a large number of such records, no significant dif- 
ference can be found between the hands, either when time 
of suspension is charted or when total work done on work 
adders is charted. Evidently habit (or some other hitherto 
undetermined structural factor) must come in to stabilize it, 

4. Testing handedness by presenting objects after the act 
of reaching has been established : At the age of approximately 
120 days you can begin to get the baby to reach for a stick 

Subject J. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 29 

or gaudily striped peppermint candy. You must first positively 
condition him to the candy. This can be done long before the 
habit of ^ reaching is established by visually stimulating the 
infant with the stick of candy and then putting the candy in 
the mouth or else putting it in the baby's hands. If the 
latter is done the baby puts the candy in its mouth. Usually 
by the 160th day the infant will reach readily for the candy 
as soon as it is exhibited. The infant is then ready to test 
for handedness. 

In all, I have worked with about 20 babies during this in- 
teresting period. In making the test, the baby is held in the 
mother's lap so that both hands are equally free. The ex- 
perimenter stands in front of the baby and extends the candy 
slowly towards the baby at the level of its eyes, using care to 
advance on a line between the two hands. When the candy 
gets just within reach (and usually not much before) the two 
hands get active, then one or the other or both are lifted and 
advanced towards the candy. The hand touching it first is 
noted. 

The results of all our tests of this nature, extending from 
the age of ISO days to one year, show no steady and uniform 
handedness. Some days the right is used more often, some 
days the left. 

The Conclusion We Draw 

Our whole group of results on handedness leads us to be- 
lieve that there is no fixed differentiation of response in either 
hand until social usage begins to establish handedness. Society 
soon thereafter steps in and says, "Thou shalt use thy right 
hand." Pressure promptly begins. "Shake hands with your right 
hand, Willy." We hold the infant so that it will wave "bye bye" 
with the right hand. We force it to eat with the right hand. 
This in itself is a potent enough conditioning factor to account 
for handedness. But you say, "Why is society right handed ?" 
This probably goes back to primitive days. One old theory 
often advanced is probably the true one. The heart is on the 
left side. It was easy enough for our most primitive ancestors 
to learn that the men who carried their shields with the left 
hand and jabbed or hurled their spears with the Bright were 
the ones who most often came back bearing their shields^rather 
than being borne upon them. If there is any truth in this 
it is easy enough to see why our primitive ancestors began to 
teach their young to be right handed. 



30 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Long before the shield was put aside, the day of manu- 
scripts and books had come ; and long before that, the strolling 
bards and minstrels had orally crystallized the tradition. The 
strong right arm has become a part of our legends of the 
hero. All of our implements candle snuffers, scissors and 
the like were and are made for right handed people. 

If handedness is a habit socially instilled, should we or 
should we not change over the left handcrs those hardy souls 
who have resisted social pressure? I am firmly convinced that 
if the job is done early enough and wisely enough, not the 
slightest harm results. I should want to do it before language 
develops very much. If I had the time I would attempt to 
prove tonight that from the beginning we begin to 'verbalize 
our acts that is put acts into words and rice verm. Now 
changing over a left handed, talking child suddenly into a 
right handed child is likely to reduce the child to a 6 months 
infant. By interfering constantly with his acts you break 
down his manual habits, and at the same time you may simul- 
taneously interfere with speech (since the word and the manual 
act are simultaneously conditioned). In other words, while 
he is relearning he will fumble not only with his bauds but 
also with his speech. The child is reduced to sheer infancy 
again. The unorganized (emotional) visceral control of the 
body as a whole again become predominant. It takes wiser 
handling to change the child over at this age than the average 
parent or teacher is prepared to give. 

The main problem is, I believe, settled: Iwndetlncss is not 
an "instinct." It is possibly not even structurally determined. 
It is socially conditioned. But why we have $% of out and 
out left banders and from 10-15% who are mixtures--- -e. g. 
using right hand to throw a ball, write or eat, but the left 
hand to guide an axe or lice, etc. is not known. 1 



lr rhere arc several factors which must be noU'd and followed 
through. Thumb, fingers and hand sucking arc present in infants and 
often unless very wisely handled last into late childhood. Usually 
but not -always one or the other hand is fairly steadily uwd, One 
would expect the hand not used in thumb sucking t.o btA'nmc, quickly 
more facile in the manipulation of objects. 

Again sometimes for months the infant reaching the standing stage 
holds on with one or the hand possibly indeed with the butter 
trained, stronger hand! During this period thft other hand is 
left free* It may overtake or even surpass the hand slowed up from 
non-use. Statistical studies upon adults and questionnaires will 
never throw any light upon the problem. 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 31 

Summary of Unlearned Equipment 

Although our studies of man's birth equipment have only 
begun, we can get a fair picture of the type of activity to be 
seen and of the method of studying this equipment by what 
I have said tonight. 

At birth or soon thereafter we find nearly all of the so-called 
clinical neurological signs or reflexes established, such as the 
reaction of the pupil to light, the patellar reflex and many 
others. 

We find the birth cry followed forever afterward by breath- 
ing, the heartbeat and all circulatory phenomena, such as vaso- 
motor constriction (decrease in diameter of vessels) and dila- 
tation, pulse beat, etc. Beginning with the alimentary tract 
we find sucking, tongue movements, and swallowing. We 
find hunger contractions, digestion, necessitating glandular 
reactions in the whole alimentary tract and elimination (de- 
faecation, urination, sweat). The acts of smiling, sneezing 
and hiccoughing belong in part at least to the alimentary canal 
system. We find also erection of the penis. 

We find general movements of the trunk, head and neck 
best observed, so far as the trunk is concerned, when the in- 
fant suspends himself with the hands. Rhythmical "climbing" 
movements then appear. We can see the trunk at work in 
breathing, when the infant cries, during defaecation and urina- 
tion, when turning over or when the head is raised or turned. 

We find the arms, wrist, hands and fingers in almost cease- 
less activity (the thumb rarely taking part until later). In 
this activity especially are to be noted: grasping, opening and 
closing hands repeatedly, "slashing" about of the whole arm, 
putting hand or fingers into mouth, throwing arm and fingers 
to face when nose is held. 

We find the legs, ankles, foot and fingers in almost ceaseless 
movement except in sleep and even during sleep if external 
(and internal) stimuli are present. The knee can be bent, leg 
moved at hip, ankle turned, toes spread, etc. If the bottom 
of the foot is touched, there is a characteristic movement of 
the toes (Babinski reflex) ; if the left knee is pinched the 
right foot is brought up to the point of stimulation and vice 
versa. 

Other activities appear at a later stage such as blinking, 
reaching, handling, handedness, crawling, standing, sitting up, 
walking, running, jumping. In the great majority of these 
later activities it is difficult to say how nwxh of the act as 



32 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

a whole is due to training or conditioning. A considerable 
part is unquestionably due to the growth changes in structure, 
and the rest is due to training and conditioning. 
What Has Become of Instincts? 

Are we not ready to admit that the whole concept of instinct 
is thus academic and meaningless ? Even from the earliest 
moment we find habit factors present present even in many 
acts so apparently simple that we used to call them physiological 
reflexes. Now turn to James' list of instincts or turn to any 
other list of instincts. The infant is a graduate student in 
the subject of learned responses (he is multitudinously con- 
ditioned) by the time behavior such as James describes 
imitation, rivalry, cleanliness and the other forms he lists 
can be observed. 

Actual observation thus makes it impossible for us any 
longer to entertain the concept of instinct. We have seen 
that every act has a genetic history. Is not the only correct 
scientific procedure then to single out for study whatever act 
is in question and to watch and record its life history? 

Take smiling. It begins at birth aroused by intra-organic 
stimulation and by contact. Quickly it becomes conditioned; 
the sight of the mother calls it out, then vocal stimuli, finally 
pictures, then words and then life situations either viewed, 
told or read about. Naturally what we laugh at, whom we 
laugh at and with whom we laugh are determined by our 
whole life history of special conditionings. No theory is re- 
quired to explain it only a systematic observation of genetic 
facts* All the elaborate pages the Freudians have written 
on humor and laughter are just so much chaff which will be 
blown aside as observation brings out the facts. 

Again take manipulation. It starts at 120 days and becomes 
smooth, sharp and facile at 6 months, Tt can be built up in 
a thousand ways, depending upon the time allowed for it, the 
toys the infant plays with, whether the infant is hurt by any 
of its toys, whether it is frightened by loud sounds often at 
the time it is handling its toys. To argue for a so-called 
"constructive building instinct" apart from early training fac- 
tors is to leave the world of facts* 

Again there is a similar printed collection of meaningless 
material in educative propaganda taking the form of * let the 
child develop its own inward nature/' Other phrases expres- 
sive of this mystical inner life of bents and instincts are "self- 
realisation/' "self-expression," "untutored life" (of the sav- 



THE NURSERY AND INSTINCTS 33 

age, for example), the "brute instincts/' "man's baser self," 
"elemental facts/' etc. Such writers as Albert Payson Ter- 
hune, Jack London, Rex Beach and Edgar Rice Burroughs, 
owe the response they call out from their public to- the organiza- 
tion laid down by social traditions (especially through taboos 
upon sex), aided and supported by the misconceptions of the 
psychologists themselves. 

In order that you may more easily grasp one of the cen- 
tral principles of behaviorism viz. that all complex behavior 
is a growth or development out of simple resources, I want 
to introduce here the notion of "activity stream." 

The Activity Stream as a Substitute for fames' "Stream 
of Consciousness" 

Most of you are familiar with William James' classic chap- 
ter on the stream of consciousness. We have all loved that 
chapter. Today it seems as much out of touch with modern 
psychology as the stage coach would be on New York's Fifth 
Avenue. The stage coach was pictureque but it has given 
place to a more effective means of transportation. Tonight 
I want to give you something in place of James' classical con- 
tribution ; less picturesque but more adequate to the facts. 

We have passed in review many of the known facts on the 
early behavior of the human infant. Let us draw a diagram 
to represent the whole increasing complexity of man's organ- 
ization. This picture will be very incomplete for several reasons. 
In the first place we have room on the chart to show only a 
few of those activities. In the second place our studies are 
not complete enough to draw an adequate chart even if we 
had the space, and finally we will not have the time to take 
up in these lectures man's visceral and emotional equipment, 
his manual habits and his language habits. 

In spite of these handicaps, though, try to think of a com- 
plete life chart of the ceaseless stream of activity beginning 
when the egg is fertilized and ever becoming more complex 
as age increases. Some of the unlearned acts we perform 
are shortlived they stay in the stream only a little time such, 
for example, as suckling, unlearned grasping (as opposed to 
learned grasping* and manipulation), extension of the great 
toe (Babinski), etc., then disappear forever from the stream. 
Try to think of others beginning later in life, e. g. blinking, 
menstruation, ejaculation, etc., and remaining in the stream 
blinking until death ; menstruation until, say, 45-55 years, then 



34 rSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

disappearing ; the act of ejaculation remaining on the chart 
of the male until the 70th-SOth years or even longer. 

But try hardest of all to think of each unlearned act as be- 
coming conditioned shortly after birth even our respiration 
and circulation. Try to remember, too, that the unlearned 
movements of arms, hands, trunks, legs, feet and toes become 
organized quickly into our stabilized habits, some of which re- 
main in the stream throughout life, others staying in only a 
short time and then disappearing forever. For example, our 
2-year habits must give place to 3 and 4-ycar habits. 

I should like to spend a whole evening upon this chart of 
human activity. It gives you quickly in graphic form the 
whole scope of psychology. Every problem the behnviorist 
works xipon has some kind of setting in this stream of definite, 
tangible, actually observable happenings. It gives you, too, 
the fundamental point of view of the behavionst viz. that 
in order to understand man you have to understand the life 
history of his activities. It shows, too, most convincingly that 
psychology is a natural science a definite part of biology. 

In our next two lectures we will see whether at the hands 
of the behaviorist the case for human emotions fares better 
than that of instincts. 



CHAPTER II 

EXPERIMENTAL STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF 
THE EMOTIONS* 



BY JOHN B. WATSON 



In my last lecture I told you that the current psychological 
view of instincts is not in harmony with the experimental 
findings of the behaviorist. Can the case for the present con- 
ception of emotions be made out any better? Probably no 
subject, unless it be that of instinct, has been more written 
about than emotions. Indeed the awe-inspiring number of 
volumes and papers and journals produced by Freudians and 
post-Freudians in the last 20 years would fill a good-sized 
room. And yet the behaviorist, as he reads through this great 
mass of literature cannot but feel in it a lack of any central 
scientific viewpoint. Not until his own genetic studies, started 
less than ten years ago, began to bear fruit, did it become 
apparent to the behaviorist that he could simplify the problems 
of emotion and apply objective experimental methods to their 
solution. 

THE BEHAVIORIST'S APPROACH TO THE PROBLEMS OF EMOTION 

During the past 10 years the behaviorist has approached the 
problem! of emotions from a new angle. In accordance with 
his usual procedure, he decided, before beginning work him- 
self, to consign to the waste basket the work of his predecessors 
and to start the problem over again. His observation of adults 
told him rapidly that mature individuals, both men and women, 
display a wide group of reactions which go under the general 
name of emotional. The negro down South whines and 
trembles at the darkness which comes with a total eclipse of 
the sun, often falling on his knees and crying out, begging the 
Deity to forgive him for his sins. These same negroes show 
fear in passing through graveyards at night. They show "awe" 
and "reverence" for charms and relics. They will not burn 
wood which has been struck by lightning. In rural communi- 
ties adults and children collect around the home as soon as dusk 
begins to fall. They often rationalize it by saying that they 
will get the "misery" from the night air. Situations of the 

^Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan- 
uary 17, 1925. 



38 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

most ordinary kinds judged from our more sophisticated stand- 
point arouse the strongest kinds of emotional reactions in them. 

But let us be even more specific and bring the matter closer 
home. Here is the list of things a 3-year-old youngster in New 
York fears: Darkness, all rabbits, rats, dogs, fish, frogs, in- 
sects, mechanical animal toys. This infant may be playing 
excitedly with blocks. When a rabbit or other animal is in- 
troduced, all constructive activity ceases. He crowds towards 
one corner of his pen and begins to cry out, "Take it away, 
take it away." Another child examined the same clay shows 
a different set. Another may show no fear reactions. 

The more the behaviorist goes about examining the sets of 
reactions of adults, the more he finds that the world of objects 
and situations surrounding people brings out more complex 
reactions that the efficient we or manipulation of the object 
or situation would call for. In other words, the object seems 
to be 'charged/ seems to bring out thousands of accessory 
bodily reactions which the laws of efficient habit do not call 
for. I can illustrate this by the negro's rabbit foot. For us 
the rabbit foot is something to be cut off from the carcass of 
the animal and thrown away. One might toss it to one's dog 
as a part of his food. But to many of the negroes the rabbit 
foot is not an object to be reacted to in this temple, way. It 
is dried, polished, put into the pocket, cared for and guarded 
jealously. He examines it now and then; when in trouble 
he calls upon it for guidance and aid, and in general reacts 
to it not as to a rabbit's foot but in the same way as a religious 
man reacts to a Deity. 

Civilization to some extent has stripped from man these 
superfluous reactions to objects and situations, but many still 
persist, especially in the realm of religion. Bread is something 
to be eaten when hungry. Wine is something to be drunk 
with meals or on festive occasions. But these simple objects 
when fed to the individual at church under the guise of com- 
munion, call out kneeling, prayer, bowing of the head, closing 
of the eyes, and a whole mass of other verbal and bodily 
responses. The bones and relics of the saints may call out in 
devout religious individuals a different but entirely homologous 
(from the standpoint of religion) set of reaction to those 
the rabbit foot calls out in the negro. The behaviorist even 
goes further and investigates his colleague's everyday behavior. 
He finds that a noise in the basement at night may reduce his 
nextcloor neighbors to reactions quite infantile; that many of 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 39 

them are shocked when the Lord's name is "taken in vain," 
giving as^a rationalization that it is irreverent, that punishment 
will be visited upon the individual so misbehaving. He finds 
many of them walking away from dogs and horses, even though 
they have to turn back or cross the street to avoid coming near 
them. He finds men and women picking out impossible mates 
without being able to rationalize the act at all in any way. In 
other words, if we were to take all of life's objects and situa- 
tions into the laboratory and were to work out a physiolo- 
gically sound and scientific way of reacting to them (experi- 
mental ethics may approach this some day) and call these forms 
the norm or standard, and were then to examine the man's 
everyday behavior in the light of such norms, we would find 
divergence from them the rule. Divergence takes the form 
of accessory reactions, slowed reactions, non-reactions (paraly- 
sis), blocked reactions, negative reactions, reactions not sanc- 
tioned by society (stealing, murder, etc.), reactions belonging 
to other stimuli (substitute). 1 It seems fair to call all of this 
group emotional without further defining the word at the pre- 
sent time. 

Now as you know, we haven't physiologically standardized 
norms of reactions as yet. There is some approach to it. Pro- 
gress in physical sciences has done much towards standardizing 

^-Examples : 

Of accessory reactions: The subject does the task quickly and 
correctly but he becomes pale, he may even cry, urinate or defaecate, 
his mouth glands may become inactive. He reacts steadily and 
correctly in spite of his emotional state. Other examples of accessory 
reaction are whistling, talking, singing while at work. 

Of negative reactions: He may show fear at food push it away 
creased he may fumble and drop his work, or react with too much 
or too little energy. Response to questions comes slowly or very 
rapidly. 

Of negative reactions: He may show fear at food push it away 
or run away from it himself. Instead of the ordinary reactions to 
dog or horse, the subject may walk away from them. Phobias belong 
in this group. 

Of reaction not sanctioned by society: The subject may in "heat 
of anger," for example, commit murder, injure property. I have in 
mind here all acts which the law punishes but where it tempers jus- 
tice with mercy because of emotional factors. 

Of reactions belonging to other stimuli: All homosexual reactions: 
all sex attacks by sons upon their mothers; all sex reactions to 
fetishes, etc. Emotional responses of parents to children masquerad- 
ing under the guise of natural affection. 

There are of course, legions of responses we call "emotional, 1 * that 
cannot be listed under any one of these headings. 



40 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

our way of reacting to day and night, the seasons, the weather. 
We no longer react to a tree struck by lightning as accursed. 
We no longer think that we have any advantage over our 
enemy when we come in possession of his nail parings, hair 
and excrement. We no longer react to the blue of the heavens 
above as a kingdom in which super-mundane beings dwell (at 
least some of us hardy souls do not!). We no longer react 
to distant and almpsi invisible mountains as being the homes 
of gnomes and fairies. Science, geography and' travel have 
standardized our responses. Our reactions to foods arc becom- 
ing standardized through the work of the food chemist. We 
no longer think of any particular form of food as being "clean" 
or "unclean." We think of it now as fulfilling or not fulfilling 
definite bodily requirements. 

Our social reactions, however, remain unstandardized. There 
is even no historical guide. Professor Sumnor, of Yale, has 
well pointed this out. According to him, every conceivable 
kind of social reaction has at one time or another been con- 
sidered the "normal" and unemotional way of acting. One 
woman could have many husbands ; one man many wives ; the 
offspring could be killed in times of famine ; human flesh could 
be eaten; sacrifice of offspring could be made to appease 
Deities; you could lend your wife to your neighbor or guest; 
the wife was acting properly when she burned herself on the 
pyre that consumed her husband's body. 

Our social reactions are not standardized any better today* 
Think of our 1925 accessory responses when we are in the 
presence of our parents, in front of our social leaders. Think 
of our hero worship, our veneration of the intellectual giant, 
the author, the artist, the church! Think of the way we behave 
in crowds, at masked parties (Ku Klux as well as social)- -at 
football and baseball games, at elections, in religions revivals 
(conversions, antics of the holy rollers, etc.), in grief at the 
loss of loved objects and people. We have a host of words to 
cover these accessory reactions reverence, love of family, of 
God, of church, of country; respect, adulation, awe, enthusiasm. 
When in the presence of many of these emotional stimuli we 
act like infants. 

How the Rchwioritrt Works : The complicated nature of 
all these adult responses makes it hopeless for the behaviorist 
io begin his study of emotion upon adults- He has to study 
emotional behavior genetically. 

Suppose we start with three-year-olds we will go out into 



STUDIES ON* THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 41 

the highways and byways and collect them, and then let us 
go to the mansions of the rich. We bring them into our 
laboratory. We put them face to face with certain situations. 
Suppose we first let a boy go alone into a well lighted playroom 
and begin to play with his toys. Suddenly we release a boa 
constrictor or some other animal. Next we may take him 
to a dark room and suddenly start a miniature bonfire with 
newspapers. I cannot take time tonight to tell you all of the 
stage settings used by the behaviorist in experiments of this 
type. As you can see we can set the stage so that we can 
duplicate almost any kind of life situation. 

But after testing him alone in all these situations we must test 
him again when an adult, possibly father or mother, is with 
him when another child of his own age and sex is nearby, 
when another child of the opposite sex accompanies him, 
when groups of children are present. 

In order to get a picture of his emotional behavior, we have 
to test separation from mother. We have to test him with 
different and uncustomary foods, with strange people to feed 
him, with strange nurses to bathe him, clothe him and put 
him to bed. We must rob him of his toys, of things he is 
playing with. We must let a bigger boy or girl bully him, we 
must put him in high places, on ledges (making injury im- 
possible however), on the backs of ponies or dogs. 

I am giving you a picture of how we work just to convince 
you of its simplicity, naturalness and accuracy that there is 
a wide field for objective experimentation. 

Brief Summary of Results of Such Tests 

One of the sad things we find by such tests is that even at 
three years of age many (but not all) of the children are shot 
through with all kinds of useless and actually harmful reactions 
which go under the general name emotional. 

They are afraid in many situations. 1 They are shy in dozens 
of others. They go into tantrums at being bathed or dressed. 
They go into tantrums when given certain foods or when a 
new nurse feeds them. They go into crying fits when the 

*Mrs. Mary Cover Jones reports that in the work with the older 
children at the Heckscher Foundation, the frog, especially ^when 
it suddenly jumps, is the most potent stimulus of all in bringing 
out fear reactions. The most pronounced reactions were called out 
from the children by an animal when it was come upon suddenly. 
For this reason the smaller animals were often left around the room 
concealed in boxes. General manipulation of objects in the room 
lead the child sooner or later to the sudden uncovering of the animal. 



42 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

mother leaves them. They hide behind their mother's dress. 
They become shy and silent when visitors come. A character- 
istic picture is to have one hand in the mouth and the other 
grasping the mother's dress. One rights every child that comes 
near. He is called a bully, a ruffian, sadistic. Another cries 
and runs away if a child half his size threatens him. His 
parents call him a coward and his playmates make him the 
scapegoat. 

Whence Arise These Varied Forms of Emotional 
Response? 

A child three years of age is very young. Must we conclude 
that emotional reactions arc hereditary? Is there an hereditary 
pattern of love, of fear, rage, shame, shyness, humor, anger, 
jealousy, timidity, awe, reverence, admiration, cruelty? Or 
are these just words to describe general types of behavior with- 
out implying anything as to their origin. Historically they 
have been considered hereditary in origin. To answer the 
question scientifically, we need new methods of experimenta- 
tion. 

EXPERIMENTS UPON THE ORIGIN AND GROWTH OF 
EMOTIONAL REACTIONS 

In our experimental work we early reached the conclusion 
that young children taken at random from homes both of the 
poor and of the well-to-do, do not make good subjects for the 
study of the origin of emotions. Their emotional behavior 
is too complex. Fortunately we have been able to study a 
number of strong healthy children belonging to wet nurses in 
hospitals, and other children brought up in the home under 
the eye of the experimenters. Several of these children were 
observed from approximately birth through the first year, 
others through the second year and two or three children 
through the third year. Tonight I wish to give you an account 
of these studies. 

In putting these hospital reared children through emotional 
situations we usually had the older ones sit in a small infant's 
chair. If the infant was very small too young to sit up we 
allowed it to sit in the lap of the mother or that of an attendant. 

Reactions to Animals (a) in the Laboratory: We first took 
the children to the laboratory and put them through the routine 
of tests with various animals. We had the laboratory so ar- 
ranged that they could be tested in the open room, alone ; with 
an attendant ; with the mother. They were tested in the dark 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 43 

room, the walls of which were painted black. This room was 
bare of furniture. It offered an unusual situation in itself. In 
the dark room we had conditions so arranged that we could 
turn on a light behind the infant's head or illuminate the room 
with the light in front of and above the infant. The infants 
were always tested one at a time. The following group of 
situations was usually presented: 

First, a lively black cat invariably affectionately aggressive, 
was shown. The cat never ceased its purring. It climbed over 
and walked around the infant many times during the course 
of each test, rubbing its body against the infant in the usual 
feline way. So many false notions have grown up around 
the response of infants to furry animals that we were sur- 
prised ourselves to see these youngsters positive always in their 
behavior to this proverbial 'black cat/ Reaching out to touch 
the cat's fur, eyes and nose was the invariable response. 

A rabbit was always presented. This, likewise, in every case 
called out manipulatory responses and nothing else. Catching 
the ears of the animal in one hand and attempting to put it 
in its mouth was one of the favorite responses. 

Another furry animal invariably used was the white rat. 
This, possibly on account of its size and whiteness, rarely 
called out continued fixation of the eyes of the infant. When, 
however, the animal was fixated, reaching occurred. 

Airedale dogs, large and small, were also presented. The 
dogs were also very friendly. The dogs rarely called out the 
amount of manipulatory response that an animal the size of 
the cat and rabbit called out. Not even when the children were 
tested with these animals in the dark room, either in full 
illumination or with a dim light behind their heads, was any 
fear response evoked. 

These tests on children not emotionally conditioned proved 
to us conclusively that the classical illustrations of hereditary 
responses to furry objects and animals are just old wives' tales. 

Next a feathery animal was used, usually a pigeon. The 
pigeon was presented first in a paper bag. This was a rather 
unusual situation even for an adult. The bird struggled and 
in struggling would move the bag around the couch. Often- 
times it would coo. While the pigeon was rattling and mov- 
ing the paper bag about, the child rarely reached for the bag. 
The moment, however, the pigeon was taken into the experi- 
menter's hands, the usual manipulatory responses were called 
forth. We have even had the pigeon moving and flapping its 



44 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

wings near the baby's face. This can be done easily by holding 
the pigeon by its feet, head down. Under these conditions 
even an adult will sometimes dodge and flinch a bit. When the 
wings fanned the infant's eyes, blinking was usually called 
out. Hesitation in response and failure to reach occurred. 
When the bird quieted down, reaching began. 

Another form of test which we have often made under these 
same conditions, was the lighting of a small newspaper bon- 
fire both out in the open room and in the dark room. In sev- 
eral cases when the paper first caught fire, the infant reached 
eagerly toward the flame and had to be restrained. As soon, 
however, as the flame became hot, reaching and manipulatory 
responses died down. At such times the infant may sit with 
hands partly up in a position that looks almost like, the start 
of the shading reaction that the adult uses when coming too 
close to a fire. There isn't much question Hint this type of 
habit would have developed if the experiment had been repeated 
often. It probably is entirely similar to the reaction animals 
and humans make to the sun. When the sun gels too hot and 
they are not active they move into whatever shade is available. 

(&) To animals in Zoological Parks: ( )n several occasions 
hospital reared children, and home reared children whose emo- 
tional history was known, have been taken to zoological parks 
always as a first experience. The children under observation 
were not pronounced in any of tlieir reactions in the zoological 
park. Every effort was made to give them a good presentation 
of those animals which apparently have played considerable 
part in the biological history of the human. For example, a 
great deal of time was spent in the primates' house, Consider- 
able time was spent also in the rooms where reptiles, frogs, 
turtles and snakes were kept. In such tests I have never got 
the slightest negative reaction to frogs and snakes, although 
the jumping frog, whore children have boon conditioned, is an 
extremely strong stimulus in bringing out fear responses as 
will be shown in the next chapter. 

In the summer of 1924, I took my own two children to the 
Bronx Zoological Park. The older child, tt, was a boy 2# 
years of age. The younger child, J, was a boy 7 months of age. 
The younger child was without conditioned emotional fear 
responses. The older child had been conditioned but in a 
known way. For example, the first time he was taken into 
water up over his neck, he showed fear (I am sun; that the 
so-called fear of the water is the same type of response that 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 45 

we get from loss of support). Before his trip to the Park 
he had seen horses, dogs, cats, pigeons, English sparrows, sea 
gulls, toads, worms, caterpillars and butterflies. He had de- 
veloped no negative responses to any of these animals except 
the dog. Once a dog had attacked him and thereafter he was 
partly conditioned to dogs, but this fear had not transferred 
to other animals or to woolly toys or mechanical animals. In 
everyday life he began immediately to play with every animal 
(other than the dog) as soon as it came within his ken. Much 
to the distress of his mother, he would often bring to her worms 
and caterpillars of every description. Even to the hoptoad he 
showed not the slightest negative response. 

In going to the Bronx Zoological Park, we had to take a 
ferry and this was his first experience on a large boat. Before 
this trip he had been in a canoe with me several times. The 
first time I took him out in the canoe, it was a little rough 
and the canoe was a tippy one. I got him out about 300 yards. 
A small wave struck us and he stiffened up a bit and said, 
"Daddy, too much water." I then took him closer in and 
paddled around the shore line for awhile. All fear responses 
to the canoe disappeared, although even now he sits pretty close 
and pretty tight when out in it. Shortly after his first trip 
in the canoe, he took the trip in question to the Zoological 
Park. On the ferry almost the same type of behavior de- 
veloped. We got about half way over. He was leaning down 
and looking at the passage of the water. Suddenly he looked 
up and said, "Mama, too much water ; Billy not afraid." But 
his general behavior belied his words somewhat. 

In the Zoological Park he showed a tremendous eagerness 
to go after every animal he saw and we took him religiously 
to every cage, pen and yard. The animals that brought out 
his greatest reluctance to leave were a pair of chimpanzees. 
They were having a gorgeous time. They were carrying 
armfuls of hay up the chains of the swing. After getting 
to the seat they tried to slip the hay underneath them. Then 
suddenly they would swing down and catch each others hands, 
drop and hit the floor with a bang. 

The animals calling out the most excited verbal response 
were the elephants ; and next came the gaudily colored tropi- 
cal birds. Every reaction to every animal was positive. 

The behavior of the 7-months old baby was that of resigned 
boredom throughout the whole afternoon. Not once was 
any response shown, either positive or negative. Now and 



46 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

then the set fixation of the eyes was noticed. The birds 
seemed to bring out the most prolonged fixation. 

We think that we have carried these experiments far enough 
on infants, the genesis of whose emotional behavior we know, 
to uphold our main contention that when fear responses occur 
in the presence of all objects and situations such as we have 
described they are always conditioned. 

Are we to conclude from this work that in infants there 
are no unlearned reactions of a kind that might give us a 
starting point for building up emotional behavior? 

Evidence for Three Types of Unlearned Beginnings 
of Emotional Reactions 

I feel reasonably sure that there are three different forms 
of response that can be called out at birth by three sets of 
stimuli. Don't misunderstand me if I call these responses 
"fear," "rage" and love." Let me hasten to assure you that 
while I use the words fear, rage and love, I want you to strip 
them of all their old connotations. Please look upon the re- 
actions we designate by them just as you look upon breathing, 
heart beat, grasping and other unlearned responses studied in 
the last chapter. 

The facts follow. 

Fear. Our work upon infants, especially those without cere- 
bral hemispheres, where the reaction is more pronounced, early 
taught us that 'loud sounds almost invariably produced a 
marked reaction in infants from the very moment of birth. 
For example, the striking of a steel bar with a hammer will 
call out a jump, a start, a respiratory pause, followed by more 
rapid breathing with marked vasomotor changes, sudden clos- 
ure of the eye, clutching of hands, puckering of lips. Then 
occur, depending upon the age of the infant, crying, falling 
down, crawling, walking or running away. I have never made 
a very systematic study of the range of sound stimuli that 
will call out fear responses. Not every type of sound will do 
it. Some extremely low pitched, rumbling noises will not call 
them out, nor will the very high tones of the Gallon whistle, 
In the half sleeping 1 infant of 2 or 3 days of age I have called 
them out repeatedly by suddenly crinkling a half of a news- 
paper near its car, and by making a loud, shrill hissing sound 
with the lips. Pure tones, such as those obtained from the 
tuning fork at any rate, are not very effective in calling them 
out. Considerably more work must be done upon the nature 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 47 

of the auditory stimulus as well as upon the separate part re- 
actions in the response before the whole stimulus-response 
picture is complete. 1 

The other stimulus calling out this same fear reaction is 
loss of support especially when the body is not set to com- 
pensate for it. It can best be observed in newborns just when 
they are falling asleep. If dropped then, or if the blanket 
upon which they lie is suddenly jerked, pulling the infant along 
with it, the response invariably occurs. 

In infants only a few hours old this fear reaction is quickly 
"fatigued." In other words, if the same sound or the same kind 
of loss of support stimulus is frequently applied, you can 
often call out the reaction only once. After a few moments' 
rest those same stimuli are again effective. 

Even in the case of the adult human and higher mammals, 
loss of support when the individual is not set for it calls out 
a strong fear reaction. If we have to walk across a slender 
plank, naturally as we approach it the muscles of the body 
are all set for it, but if we cross a bridge which remains per- 
fectly steady until the middle has been reached and then sud- 
denly begins to give way, our response is very marked. When 
this happens in the case of a horse, one can with difficulty 
get him to cross bridges again. There are many horses in the 
country bridge shy. I am sure the same principle is operarive 
when a child is rapidly let out into deep water for the first 
time. The buoyancy of the water actually throws him off his 
balance. Even when the water is warm there is a catching 
of the breath, clutching with the hands and crying. 

Rage. Have you ever had the never to be forgotten experi- 
ence, when proudly walking across a crowded street holding 
your two-year-old daughter's hand, of having her suddenly 
pull you in some other direction? And when you quickly and 
sharply jerked her back and exerted steady pressure on her 
arm to keep her straight did she then suddenly stiffen, begin 
to scream at the top of her voice and lie down stiff as a ram- 
rod in the middle of the street, yelling with wide open mouth 
until she became blue in the face, and continuing to yell until 



*I have found only one child out of many hundreds worked with 
in whom a fear response cannot be called out by loud sounds. She 
is well developed, well nourished, and normal in every way. There 
were no fear reactions to any other stimuli. The nearest approach 
to fear I saw was at the sight and sound of an opening and closing 
umbrella. I have no explanation to offer for this exception. 



48 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

she could make no further sound? If you have not, any 
picture of rage behavior must appear lifeless to you. 

Possibly you have seen the large village bully take some 
child, down him and hold his arms and legs so closely to his 
body that the child could not even struggle. Have you watched 
the youngster stiffen and yell until he became blue in the face? 

Did you ever notice the sudden changes that come into the 
faces of men when they are jostled and suddenly and unduly 
crowded in the street cars and railway trains ? Hampering of 
bodily movement brings out the series of responses we call 
rage. This can be observed from the moment of birth but 
more easily in infants 10 to IS days of age. When the head is 
held lightly between the hands; when the arms arc pressed 
to the sides ; and when the legs are held tightly together, rage 
behavior begins. The unlearned behavior elements in rage be- 
havior have never been completely catalogued. Some of the 
elements, however, are easily observed, such as the stiffening 
of the whole body, the free slashing movements of hands, 
arms and legs, and the holding of the breath. There is no cry- 
ing at first, then the mouth is opened to the fullest extent and 
the breath is held until the face appears blue. These states 
can be brought on without the pressure in any case being severe 
enough to produce the slightest injury to the child. The ex- 
periments are discontinued the moment the slightest blucness. 
appears in the skin. All children can be thrown into such a 
state and the reactions will continue until the irritating situ- 
ation is relieved, and sometimes for a considerable period there- 
after. We have had this state brought out when the arms are 
held upward by a cord to which is attached a lead ball not ex- 
ceeding an ounce in weight. The constant hampering 1 of the 
arms produced by even this slight weight is sufficient to bring 
out the response. When the child is lying on its back it can 
occasionally be brought out by pressing on each side of the 
head with cotton wool. In many cases this state can be ob- 
served quite easily when the mother or nurse has to dress the 
child somewhat roughly or hurriedly. 

Love. The study of this emotion in the infant is beset with 
a great many difficulties on the conventional side. Our ob- 
servations consequently fraye been incidental rather than di- 
rectly experimental. The stimulus to lorn responses apparently 
is stroking of the skin, tickling, gentle rocking, patting. The 
responses are especially easy to bring out by the stimulation 
of what, for lack of a better term, we may call the erogenous 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 49 

zones, such as the nipples, the lips and ths. sex organs. The re- 
sponse in an infant depends upon its state; when crying the cry- 
ing will cease and a smile begin. Gurgling and cooing appear. 
Violent movements of arms and trunk with pronounced laugh- 
ter occur in even 6-8 months old infants when tickled. It is 
thus seen that we use the term "love" in a much broader sense 
than it is popularly used. The responses we intend to mark 
off here are those popularly called "affectionate," "good na- 
tured," "kindly," etc. The term "love" embraces all of these 
as well as the responses we see in adults between the sexes. 
They all have a common origin. 

Are There Other Unlearned Responses of These Three 

General Types? 

Whether these three types of response are all that have an 
hereditary background we are not sure. Whetner or not there 
are other stimuli which will call out these responses we must 
also leave in doubt. 1 If our observations are in any way com- 
plete, it would seem that emotional reactions are quite simple 
in the infant and the stimuli which call them out quite few in 
number. 

These reactions which we have agreed, then, to call fear, 
rage and love, are at first quite indefinite. Much work remains 
to be done to see what the various part reactions are in each 
and how much they differ. They are certainly not the com- 
plicated kinds of emotional reaction we see later on in life, but 
at least I believe they form the nucleus out of which all future 
emotional reactions arise. So quickly do they become con- 
ditioned, as we shall show later, that it gives a wrong im- 
pression to call them hereditary modes of response. It is prob- 
ably better just to keep the actual facts of observation thus : 
(Ordinarily called Fear:) 

(U)S (U)R 

Loss of support Checking of breathing, "jump" 

Loud sounds or start of whole body, crying, 

often defaecation and urination 
(and many others not worked 
out experimentally. Probably the 
largest group of part reactions 
are visceral). 



1 For example, I am uncertain what the relationship is between the 
fear reactions we have been describing and the reactions called out 
by very hot objects, ice cold water, and other noxious stimuli. 



50 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



(Ordinarily called Rage:) 

(U)S (U)R 

Restraint of bodily move- Stiffening of whole body, 

tnent. screaming, temporary cessation 

of breathing, reddening of face 
changing to blueness of face, etc. 
It is obvious that while there are 
general over responses, the great- 
est concentration of movement is 
in the visceral field. Blood tests 
of infants so manhandled show 
that that there is an increase in 
blood sugar. This means prob- 
ably an increase in the secretion 
of the adrenal glands release of 
increased output of adrenalin. 

(Ordinarily called Love:) 

(U)S (U)R 

Stroking skin and sex or- Cessation of crying; gurgling, 
gans, rocking, riding on cooing and many others not de- 
foot, etc. termined. That visceral factors 

predominate is shown by changes 
in circulation and respiration, 
erection of penis, etc. 

If we think of these unlearned (so-called emotional) re- 
sponses in the terms of these simple formulae, wo cannot go 
very far wrong. 

How Our Emotional Life Becomes Complicated 

How can we square these observations with those which 
show the enormous complexity in the emotional life of the 
adult? We know that hundreds of children are afraid of the 
dark, we know that many women are afraid of snakes, mice 
and insects, and that emotions are attached to many ordinary 
objects of almost daily use. Fears become attached to persons 
and to places and to general situations, such as the woods, 
the water, etc. In the same way the number of objects and 
situations which can call out rage and love become enormously 
increased. Rage and love at first are not produced by the 
mere sight of an object. We know that later on in life the 
mere sight of persons may call out both of these primitive 
emotions. How do such "attachments" grow up? How can 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 51 

objects which at first do not call out emotions come later to 
call them out and thus greatly increase the richness as well 
as the dangers of our emotional life ? 

Since 1918 we have been at work upon this problem. We 
were rather loath at first to conduct such experiments, but the 
need of this kind of study was so great that we finally decided 
to experiment upon the possibility of building up fears in the 
infant and then later to study practical methods for removing 
them. We chose as our first subject Albert B, an infant weigh- 
ing twenty-tone pounds, at eleven months of age. Albert was 
the son of one of the wet nurses in the Harriet Lane Hospital. 
He had lived his whole life in the hospital. He was a won- 
derfully "good" baby. In all the months we worked with him 
we never saw him cry until after our experiments were made ! 

Before turning to the experiments by means of which we 
built up emotional responses in the laboratory, it is necessary 
for you to recall all that I tried to tell you on he conditioning 
of reflexes. I am going to assume that you know that when 
you establish a conditioned reaction, you must have a funda- 
mental stimulus to start with which will call out the response 
in question. Your next step is to get some other stimulus 
to call it out.- For example, if your purpose is to make the 
arm and hand jerk away every time a buzzer sounds, you 
must use the electric shock or other noxious stimulus each 
time the electric buzzer is sounded. Shortly, as you know, the 
arm will begin to jump away when the buzzer is sounded just 
as it jumps away when the electric shock is given. We already 
know now that there is an unconditioned or fundamental stim- 
ulus which will call out the fear reaction quickly and easily. It 
is a loud sound. We determined to use this just as we use 
the electric shock in experiments on the conditioned motor and 
glandular reflexes. 

Our first experiment with Albert had for its object the con- 
ditioning of a fear response to a white rat. We first showed 
by repeated tests that nothing but loud sounds and removal 
of support would bring out fear response in this child. Every- 
thing coming within twelve inches of him was reached for 
and manipulated. His reaction, however, to a loud sound was 
characteristic of what occurs with most children. A steel 
bar about one inch in diameter and three feet long, when 
struck with a carpenter's hammer produced the most marked 
kind of reaction. 



52 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Our laboratory notes 1 showing the progress in establishing 
a conditioned emotional response are given here in full : 

Eleven months, 3 days old. (1) White rat which he played with 
for weeks was suddenly taken from the basket (the usual routine) 
and presented to Albert. He began to reach for rat with left hand. 
Just as his hand touched the animal the bar was struck immediately 
behind his head, The infant jumped violently and fell forward, 
burying his face in the mattress. He did not cry, however. 

(2) Just as his right hand touched the rat the bar was again 
struck. Again the infant jumped violently, fell forward and began 
to whimper. 

On account of his disturbed condition no further tests were 
made for one week. 

Eleven months, ten days old. (1) Rat presented suddenly with- 
out sound. There was steady fixation but no tendency at first to 
reach for it. The rat was then placed nearer, whereupon tentative 
reaching movements began with the right hand, When the rat 
nosed the infant's left hand the hand was immediately withdrawn. 
He started to reach for the head of the animal with the forefinger 
of his left hand but withdrew it suddenly before contact. It is 
thus seen that the two joint stimulations given last week were not 
without effect. He was tested with his blocks immediately after- 
wards to see if they shared in the process of conditioning. He 
began immediately to pick them up, dropping them and pounding 
them, etc. In the remainder of the tests the blocks were given 
frequently to quiet him and to test his general emotional state. 
They were always removed from sight when the process of con- 
ditioning was under way. 

(2) Combined stimulation with rat and sound. Started, then 
fell over immediately to right side. No crying. 

(3) Combined stimulation. Fell to right side and rested on hands 
with head turned from rat. No crying. 

(4) Combined stimulation. Same reaction. 

(5) Rat suddenly presented alone. Puckered face, whimpered 
and withdrew body sharply to left. 

(6) Combined stimulation. Pell over immediately to right side 
and began to whimper. 

(7) Combined stimulation. Started violently and cried, but did 
not fall over. 

(8) Rat alone. The instant the rat was shown the baby began 
to cry. Almost instantly he turned sharply to the left, fell over, 
raised himself on all fours and began to crawl away so rapidly that 
he was caught with difficulty before he reached the edge of the 
mattress. 

Surely this proof of the conditioned origin of a fear response 
puts us on a natural science grounds in our study of emo- 
tional behavior. It is a far more prolific goose for laying 

3 See the original paper by Rosalie Rayner and John B, Watson, 
Scientific Monthly, 1921, p. 493. 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 53 

golden eggs than is James' barren verbal formulation. It 
yields an explanatory principle that will account for the enor- 
mous complexity in the emotional behavior of adults. We 
no longer in accounting for such behavior have to fall back 
upon heredity. 

The Spread or Transfer of Conditioned Responses 

Before the above experiment on the rat was made, Albert 
had been playing for weeks with rabbits, pigeons, fur muffs, 
the hair of the attendants and false faces. What effect will 
conditioning him upon the rat have upon his response to these 
animals and other objects when next he sees them? To test 
this we made no further experiments upon him for five days. 
That is, during this five day period he was not allowed to see 
any of the above objects. At the end of the 6th day we again 
tested him first with the rat to see if the conditioned fear 
response to it had carried over. Our notes are as follows : 
Eleven months, fifteen days old. 

(1) Tested first with blocks. He reached readily for them, playing 
with them as usual. This shows that there has been no general 
transfer to the room, table, blocks, etc. 

(2) Rat alone. Whimpered immediately, withdrew right hand 
and turned head and trunk away. 

(3) Blocks again offered. Played readily with them, smiling and 
gurgling. 

(4) Rat alone. Leaned over to the left side as far away from the 
rat as possible, then fell over, getting up on all fours and scurrying 
away as rapidly as possible. 

(5) Blocks again offered. Reached immediately for them, smiling 
and laughing as before. 

This shows that the conditioned response was carried over 
the five day period. Next we presented in order a rabbit, a 
dog, a sealskin coat, cotton wool, human hair and a false face : 

(6) Rabbit alone. A rabbit was suddenly placed on the mattress 
in front of him. The reaction was pronounced. Negative responses 
began at once. He leaned as far away from the animal as possible* 
whimpered, then burst into tears. When the rabbit was placed in 
contact with him he buried his face in the mattress, then got up 
on all fours and crawled away, crying as he went. This was a most 
convincing test. 

(7) The blocks were next given to him, after an interval. He 
played with them as before. It was observed by four people that 
he played far more energetically with them than ever before. The 
blocks were raised high over his head and slammed down with a 
great deal of force. 

(8) Dog alone. The dog did not produce as violent a reaction 
as the rabbit. The moment fixation of the eyes occurred the child 
shrank back and as the animal came nearer he attempted to get on 
all fours but did not cry at first. As soon as the dog passed out 



54 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of his range of vision he became quiet. The dog was then made 
to approach the infant's head (he was lying down at the moment). 
Albert straightened up immediately, fell over to the opposite side 
and turned his head away. He then began to cry. 

(9) Blocks were again presented. He began immediately to play 
with them. 

(10) Pur coat (seal). Withdrew immediately to the left side and 
began to fret. Coat put -close to him on the left side, he turned 
immediately, began to cry and tried to crawl away on all fours. 

(11) Cotton wool. The wool was presented in a paper package. 
At the ends the cotton was not covered by the paper. It was placed 
first on his feet. He kicked it away but did not touch it with his 
hands. When his hand was laid on the wool he immediately with- 
drew it but did not show the shock that the animals or fur coat 
produced in him. He then began to play with the paper, avoiding 
contact with the wool itself. Before the hour was up, however, he 
lost some of his negativism to the wool. 

(12) Just in play W. who had made the experiments, put his head 
down to see if Albert would, play with his hair. Albert was com- 
pletely negative. The other two observers did the same thing. He 
began immediately to play with their hair. A Santa Glaus mask 
was then brought and presented to Albert. lie was again pro- 
nouncedly negative, although on all previous occasions he had played 
with it. 

Our notes thus give a convincing proof of spread or transfer. 

We have here further proof in these transfers that con- 
ditioned emotional responses are exactly like other conditioned 
responses. If we condition a man or lower animal by regular 
conditioned reflex methods, say, to a tone A of a given pitch, 
almost any other tone will at first call out the response. By 
continuing the experiment say by always feeding when tone 
A is sounded but never when any other tone is sounded you 
soon get the animal to the point where it will respond only 
to A. This would be a differential conditioned response. 

I am sure that in these cases of transfer or vspread of con- 
ditioned emotional responses the same factors arc at work. 

I believe, although I have never tried the experiments, that 
we could set up just as sharp a differential reaction in the 
emotional field as we can in any other. I mean by this merely 
that if the experiment was long continued we could bring the 
fear reaction out sharply whenever the rat was shown but 
never when any other furry object was shown. If this were 
the case, we should have a differential conditioned emotional 
response. This seems to be what happens in real life. Most 
of us in infancy and in early youth are in the undiffcrcntiated 
emotional state. Many adults, especially women, remain in 
it. All primitive peoples remain in it (superstitions, etc,)* 
3ut educated adults by the long training they get in manipu- 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 55 

lating objects, handling animals, working with electricity, etc., 
reach the second or differentiated stage of the conditioned 
emotional reaction. 

There is thus, if my reasoning is correct, a thoroughly sound 
way of accounting for transferred emotional responses and 
for the Freudian's so-called "free-floating affects." When con- 
ditioned emotional responses are first set up, a wide range of 
stimuli (in this case all hairy objects) physically similar will 
at first call out the response and so far as we know will con- 
tinue to call it out unless experimental steps (or a very fortu- 
nate series of environmental settings) are taken to bring the 
undifferentiated conditioned response up to the differentiated 
stage. In the differentiated stage only the object or situation 
you were conditioned upon originally will call out the re- 
sponse. 

Summary 

We must see that there is just as little evidence for a whole- 
sale inheritance of those complicated patterns of response com- 
monly called emotional as there is for the inheritance of those 
called instinctive. 

Possibly a better way to describe our findings is to say that 
in working over the whole field of the human infant's reaction 
to stimuli, we find that certain types of stimuli loud sounds 
and removal of support produce a certain general type of re- 
sponse, namely, momentary checking of breath, a start of the 
whole body, crying, marked visceral responses, etc. ; that another 
type of stimulus, holding or restraint, produces crying with 
wide open mouth, prolonged holding of breath, marked changes 
in circulation and other visceral changes ; that a third stimulus, 
stroking the skin, especially in the sex areas, produces smiling, 
changes in respiration, cessation of crying, cooing, gurgling, 
erection and other visceral changes. Attention is called to the 
fact that responses to these stimuli are not mutually exclusive 
many of the part reactions are the same. 

These unconditioned stimuli with their relatively simple un- 
conditioned responses are our starting points in building up 
those complicated conditioned, habit patterns we later call our 
emotions. In other words, emotional reactions are built in an 
order like most of our other reaction patterns. Not only do 
we get an increase in the number of stimuli calling out the 
response (substitution) through direct conditioning and 
through transfers (thus enormously widening the stimulus 



56 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

range), but also we get marked additions to and modifications 
of the responses themselves. 

Another set of factors increasing the complexity of our 
emotional life must be taken into account. The same object 
(for example a person) can become a substitute stimulus for 
a f ear response in one situation and a little later a substitute 
stimulus for a love response in another, or even for a rage 
response. The increasing complexity brought about by these 
factors soon gives us an emotional organization sufficiently 
complicated to satisfy even the novelist and the poet. 

I am loath to close tonight until I have introduced, paren- 
thetically at least, one additional thought. The thought is 
that notwithstanding the fact that in all emotional responses 
there are overt factors such as the movement of the eyes and 
the arms and the legs and the trunk, visceral and glandular 
factors predominate. The "cold sweat" of fear, the "bursting 
heart/' "the bowed head" in apathy and grief, the "exuberance 
of youth," the "palpitating heart" of the swain or maiden, are 
more than mere literary expressions, they are bits of genuine 
observations. 

I want to develop the thesis sometime that society has never 
been able to get hold of these implicit concealed visceral and 
glandular reactions of ours, or else it would have schooled 
them in us, for, as you know, society has a great propensity 
for regulating all of our reactions* Hence most of our aclult 
overt reactions our speech, the movements of our arms, legs 
and trunk are schooled and habitized. Owing to their con- 
cealed nature, however, society cannot get hold of visceral 
behavior to lay down rules and regulations for its integration. 
It follows as a corollary from this that we have no names, 
no words with which to describe these reactions. They re- 
main unverbalized. One can describe in well chosen words 
every act of two boxers, two fencers, and can criticize each 
individual detail of their responses, because there arc verbal 
manuals of procedure and practice in the performance of these 
skillful acts. But what Hoyle has laid down the rules by 
which the separate movements of our viscera and glands must 
take place when in the presence of our lady love? 

Because, then, of the fact that we have never verbalized 
these responses, a good many things happen to us that we 
cannot talk about. We have never learned how to talk about 
them. There arc no words for them. The theory of the un~ 
verbalized in human behavior gives us a natural science way 



STUDIES ON THE GROWTH OF EMOTIONS 57 

of explaining many things the Freudians now call "uncon- 
scious complexes," "suppressed wishes" and the like. In other 
words, we can now come back to natural science in our study 
of emotional behavior. Our emotional life grows and develops 
like our other sets of habits. But do our emotional habits 
once implanted suffer from disuse? Can they be put away 
and outgrown like our manual and verbal habits? Until very 
recently we had no facts to guide us in answering these ques- 
tions. Some are now available. In my next lecture I shall 
attempt to present them. 



CHAPTER III 

RECENT EXPERIMENTS ON HOW WE LOSE AND 
CHANGE OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT* 



BY JOHN B. WATSON 



The experiments I reported at the close of my last lecture 
were completed in 1920. Until the fall of 1923 no further 
experiments were undertaken. Finding that emotional re- 
sponses could be built in with great readiness, we were all the 
more eager to see whether they could be broken down, and 
if so by what methods. No further tests could be made upon 
Albert B., the youngster in whom the conditioned responses 
had been built up, because he was shortly afterwards adopted 
by an out-of-town family. It was just at this time that my 
own work at Hopkins was interrupted. 

The matter of further experimentation rested until the fall 
of 1923. At that time a sum of money was granted by the 
Laura Spelman Rockefeller Memorial to the Institute of Edu- 
cational Research of Teachers' College, a part of which was 
used for continuing the study of the emotional life of children. 
We found a place for work the Heckscher Foundation. Ap- 
proximately 70 children are kept there ranging in age from 
3 months to 7 years. It was not an ideal place for our experi- 
mental work because we were not allowed full control of the 
children and because of the frequency with which work had 
to be stopped on account of unavoidable epidemics of one kind 
or another. In spite of these handicaps much work was done. 
While I spent considerable time there as consultant and helped 
to plan the work, Mrs. Mary Cover Jones conducted all of 
the experiments and wrote up all of the results. 1 

Tonight I wish to give you an account of this work. 

The Different Methods Used in Attempting to Eliminate 
Fear Responses 

Locating the Conditioned Fear Responses in Children: 
A number of children of different ages were put through a 
group of situations designed to bring out fear responses if any 

*Powell lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan- 
uary 17, 1926. 

a Partial report on this work has already appeared. See The Elim- 
ination ol Children's Fears, by Mary Cover Jones, Jr., Exp. Psychol- 
ogy, 1924, p.382. 



60 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

were present. As has already been mentioned, children brought 
up in the home show fear reactions. These we have every 
reason to believe are conditioned. By passing each individual 
through these situations we were able not only to locate the 
children possessing the most pronounced conditioned fear re- 
actions but also to locate the objects (and the general situations) 
that called out those reactions. 

We worked here of course under one disadvantage. We did 
not know the genetic history of their fear responses. Hence 
we did not know whether a given fear reaction when observed 
was directly conditioned or merely transferred^ This is al- 
ways a handicap an especially hard one in this work as I 
shall show you later. 

Elimination of Fear Responses Through Disuse: Having 
located a child with a fear response and the stimulus calling 
it out, our next step was to attempt to remove it. 

It has commonly been supposed that the mere removal of 
the stimulus for a sufficient length of time will cause the child 
or adult to "forget his fear," All of us have heard the ex- 
pressions "J ust k ee P h" 11 away from it and he'll outgrow it. 
He will forget all about it." Laboratory tests were made to 
determine the efficacy of this method. I quote from Mrs. 
Jones' laboratory notes: 

Case 1. Rose D, Age 21 months. General situation: sitting in 
playpen with other children none of whom showed specific fears. 
A rabbit was introduced from behind a screen. 

Jan, 19. At sight of the rabbit, Rose burst into tcars, her crying 
lessened when the experimenter picked up the rabbit, but again in- 
creased when the rabbit was put back on the floor, At the removal 
of the rabbit she quieted down, accepted a cracker, and presently 
leturned to her blocks. 

Feb. 5. After 2 weeks the situation was repeated. She cried and 
trembled upon seeing the rabbit, E. (the experimenter) sat on the 
floor between Rose and the rabbit; she continued to cry for several 
minutes. E. tried to divert her attention with the peg-board; she 
finally stopped crying, but continued to watch the rabbit and would 
not attempt to play, 

Case #. Bobby G. Age 30 months. 

Dec. 6. Bobby showed a slight fear response when a rat was pre- 
sented in a box. He looked at it from a distance of several feet, 
drew back and cried. A 3-day period of training followed bringing 
Bobby to the point where he tolerated a rat in the pen in which 
he was playing, and even touched it without overt fear indications. 
No further stimulation with the rat occurred until 

Jan. 30. ^ After nearly two months of no experience with the 
specific stimulus, Bobby was again brought into the laboratory. 
While he was playing m the pen, E. appeared, with a rat in her 
hand. Bobby jumped up, ran outside the pen, and cried. The rat 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 61 

having been returned to its box, Bobby ran to E., held her hand, 
and showed marked disturbance. 

Case 33. Eleanor J. Age 21 months. 

Jan. 17. While playing in the pen, a frog was introduced from 
behind her. She watched, came nearer, and finally touched it. The 
frog jumped. She withdrew and when later presented with the frog, 
shook her head and pushed the experimenter's hand away violently. 

Mar. 26. After two months of no further experience with animals, 
Eleanor was taken to the laboratory and offered the frog. When 
the frog hopped she drew back, ran from the pen and cried. 

These tests and many others similar in character incline us 
to believe that the method of disuse in the case of emotional 
disturbance is not as effective as is commonly supposed. It 
is admitted, however, that the tests were not extended over 
a long enough time to yield complete evidence. 

Method of Verbal Organization 

Most of the subjects in the Heckscher Foundation were 
under 4 years of age and the possibility of verbally organizing 
the children about the objects that called out fear responses 
was very limited. Naturally nothing can be accomplished 
by the use of this method until the child has a fairly wide 
language organization. One satisfactory subject Jean E., 
a girl in her Sth year, however, was found sufficiently well 
organized to use in an extended test. At the initial presentation 
of the rabbit, marked fear responses were shown. The rabbit 
was not shown again for some time, but ten minutes daily con- 
versation was given her on the subject of rabbits. The ex- 
perimenter introduced such devices as the picture book of Peter 
Rabbit, toy rabbits and rabbits modeled from plasticeone. Brief 
stories about rabbits were told. During the telling of these 
stories, she would say "Where is your rabbit?" or "Show me 
a rabbit" ; and once she said "I touched your rabbit and stroked 
it and never cried" (which was not true). At the end of 
one week of verbal organization, the rabbit was shown again. 
Her reaction was practically the same as the first encounter. 
She jumped up from her play and retreated. When coaxed 
she touched the rabbit while the experimenter held it, but 
when the animal was put down on the floor she sobbed "Put 
it away take it." Verbal organization when not connected 
with actual manual adjustments to the animal had little effect 
in. removing her fear responses. 

Method of Frequent Application of Stimulus 
While experiments with this method have not been extended, 
the results nave not been very hopeful. The routine adopted 



62 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

in applying this method is to have the animal calling out the 
fear reaction brought in many times each day. While in some 
cases no actual negative responses were made, this was the 
only form of improvement noted no positive reactions de- 
veloped from the use of this method. In some cases a sum- 
mation effect rather than an adjustment was obtained. 

Method of Introducing Social Factors 

Most of us are familiar both in the school and on the play- 
ground with what happens among groups of children. If one 
shows fear at any object to which the group does not show 
fear, the one showing fear is made a scapegoat and is called 
a "fraidy cat." We attempted to use this social factor in the 
case of some of the children. One case is given here in detail : 

Case 41. Arthur G. Age 4 years. 

Arthur was shown the frogs in an aquarium, no other children 
being present. He cried, said "they bite," and ran out of the play- 
pen. Later, however, he was brought into the room with four other 
boys; he swaggered up to the aquarium, pressing ahead of the 
others who were with him. When one of his companions picked 
up a frog and turned to him with it, he screamed and fled; at 
this he was chased and made fun of, but with naturally no lessening 
of the fear on this particular occasion. 

This is probably one of the most unsafe methods in com- 
mon use for eliminating fears. It tends to breed negative re- 
actions not only to the animal feared but to society as a whole. 

Where milder social methods are used, ordinarily called social 
imitation, better results are obtained. Mrs. Jones gives two 
cases which I quote : 

Case. $. J3obby O. Age 30 months. 

Bobby was playing in the pen with Mary and Laurel. The rabbit 
was introduced in a basket, Bobby cried "No, no," and motioned 
for the experimenter to remove it. The two girls, however, ran 
up readily enough, looked in at the rabbit and talked excitedly. 
Bobby became promptly interested, said "What? Me see," and 
ran forward, his curiosity and assertiveness in the social situation 
overmastering other impulses, 

Case 54. Vincent W. Age 21 months. 

Jan. 19 Vincent showed no fear of the rabbit, even when it was 
pushed against his hands or face, His only response was to laugh 
and reach for the rabbit's fur. On the same day he was taken into 
the pen with Rosey, who cried at the sight of the rabbit, Vincent 
immediately developed a fear response; in the ordinary playroom 
situation he would pay no attention to her crying, but in connection 
with the rabbit, her distress had a marked suggestion value. The 
fear transferred in this way persisted for over two weeks. 

Feb. 6. (Eli and Heitert were in the play-pen with the rabbit. 
When Vincent was brought in, he remained cautiously standing at 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 63 

gome distance. Eli led Vincent over to the rabbit, and induced him 
to touch the animal. Vincent laughed. 

As will be noted, however, there are difficulties in the way 
of the use of this method. Occasionally the children showing 
no fear to the object become conditioned by the behavior of 
the child showing fear reactions to the object. 

While all of these methods are suggestive and while none 
of them has been worked out to a final conclusion, none seems 
especially fruitful or free from danger. 

The Method of Re-Conditioning or Un-Conditioning 

The most successful method so far discovered for use in 
removing fears is the method of unconditioning or recon- 
ditioning. Reconditioning would be a little more satisfactory 
word to use except for the fact that it has been used by the 
physical culturists in various types of health propaganda. Un- 
conditioning seems the only other available word. 

I wish to go into the details of one case where unconditioning 
was attempted because it illustrates not only the method used 
but the various difficulties one is likely to encounter in such 
work. 

Peter was an active eager child of approximately 3 years 
of age. 1 This child was well adjusted to ordinary life situations 
except for his fear organization. He was afraid of white rats, 
rabbits, fur coats, feathers, cotton wool, frogs, fish and mechan- 
ical toys. From the description of his fears, you might well 
think that Peter was merely Albert B. of the last lecture 
grown up. Only you must remember that Peter's fears were 
"home grown," not experimentally produced as were Albert's. 
Peter's fears, though, were much more pronounced as the 
following description will show: 

Peter was put in a crib in a play room and immediately be- 
came absorbed in his toys. A white rat was introduced into 
the crib from behind. (The experimenter was behind a screen.) 
At the sight of the rat, Peter screamed and fell flat on his back 
in a paroxysm of fear. The stimulus was removed, and Peter 
was taken out of the crib and put into a chair. Barbara, a 
girl of two, was brought to the crib and the white rat intro- 
duced as before. She exhibited no fear but picked the rat 
up in her hand. Peter sat quietly watching Barbara and the 
rat. A string of beads belonging to Peter had been left in 

*A full report on Peter is given by Mrs. Jones in the December, 
1924 number of the Pedagogical Seminary. 



64 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the crib. Whenever the rat touched a part of the string, he 
would say "my beads" in a complaining voice, although he 
made no objections when Barbara touched them. Invited to 
get down from the chair, he shook his head, fear not yet sub- 
sided. Twenty-five minutes elapsed before he was ready to 
play about freely. 

The next day his reactions to the following situations and 
objects were noted: 

Play room and crib Selected toys, got into crib with- 
out protest. 

White ball rolled in Picked it up and held it. 

Fur rug hung over crib Cried until it was removed. 

Fur coat hung over crib Cried until it was removed. 

Cotton .Whimpered, withdrew, cried 

Hat with feathers Cried. 

White toy rabbit of rough 

cloth Neither negative nor positive re- 
action. 

Wooden doll Neither negative nor positive re- 
action. 

Training for removal of these fears in Peter was first be- 
gun by utilizing social factors as discussed on p. 62. There was 
considerable improvement, but before retraining was com- 
pleted the child fell ill with scarlet fever and bad to go to a 
hospital for a period of two months, When coming back from 
the hospital a large barking dog attacked him and the nurse 
just as they entered a taxicab. Both the nurse and Peter 
were terribly frightened. Peter lay back in the taxi ill and 
exhausted. After allowing a few days for recovery he was 
taken to the laboratory and again tested with animals. His 
fear reactions to all the animals had returned in exaggerated 
form. We determined then to use another type of procedure 
that of direct unconclitioning. We did not have control over 
his meals, but we secured permission to give him his mid- 
afternoon lunch consisting of crackers and a glass of milk. 
We seated him at a small table in a high chair, The lunch 
was served in a room about forty feet long. Just as he began 
to eat his lunch, the rabbit was displayed in a wire cage of 
wide mesh. We displayed it on the first day just far enough 
away not to disturb his eating. This point was then marked. 
The next day the rabbit was brought closer and closer until 
disturbance was first barely noticed. This place was marked. 
The third and succeeding days the same routine was main- 
tained. Finally the rabbit could be placed upon the table 
then in Peter's lap. Next tolerance changed to positive re- 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 65 

action. Finally he would eat with one hand and play with 
the rabbit with the other, a proof that his viscera zvere re- 
trained along with his hands! 

After having broken down his fear reactions to the rabbit 
the animal calling out fear responses of the most exaggerated 
kinds we were next interested in seeing what his reactions 
would be to other furry animals and furry objects. Fear re- 
sponses to cotton, the fur coat, and "feathers were entirely 
gone. He looked at them and handled them and then turned 
to other things. He would even pick up the fur nig and bring 
it to the experimenter. 

The reaction to white rats was greatly improved it had 
at least reached the tolerance stage but did not call out any 
very excited positive manipulation. He would pick up the 
small tin boxes containing rats and frogs and carry them 
around the room. 

He was then tested in an entirely new animal situation. A 
mouse which he had not hitherto seen was handed to him 
together with a cangied mass of earthworms. His reaction 
was at first partly negative but this gave way in a few minutes 
to positive response to the worms and undisturbed watching 
of the mouse. 

We suffer here as always in working with home grown 
fears by not knowing the primary situation upon which the 
child was conditioned (conditioned reflex of the 1st order). 
Possibly if we had had information upon this point and had 
unconditioned him on his primary fear, ' all of the "trans- 
ferred" responses would have evaporated at once. Not until 
we have had more experience with building up a primary 
fear, noting the transfers and then unconditioning for the 
primary, will we be working upon sure ground in this inter- 
esting field. It is just possible that there may be certain 
reaction differences (intensity) between the primary condi- 
tioned response, (1st order), the secondarily conditioned re- 
sponses (2nd and succeeding orders) and the various trans- 
ferred responses. If this is true, then we might be able to 
tell, by presenting widely varying situations to children whose 
emotional history is unknown, just which one any given child 
was originally conditioned upon. 

The whole field of emotions, when thus experimentally ap- 
proached, is a very thrilling one and one which opens up real 
vistas of practical application in the home and in the school 
even in everyday life. 



66 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

At any rate we have now seen grow up under our very eyes 
the experimental genesis of a fear response and at least one 
case where the fear response was uprooted by a safe experi- 
mental method. If fear can be handled in this way, why not 
all other forms of emotional organization connected with rage 
(tantrums) and love? I believe firmly that they can be. In 
other words, emotional organization is subject to exactly the 
same laws as other habits, both as to origin, as we have al- 
ready pointed out, and as to decline. 

The method we have sketched has a serious drawback, main- 
ly because we did not have control over all the meals of the 
child. (By the way, never start an experiment upon a child 
or infant unless you have full control). Probably if the 
child has been stroked, petted, and rocked (sexual stimulation) 
just as the fear object was presented, unconditioning might 
have taken place much more rapidly. 

Incomplete and unsatisfactory as is this preliminary report 
upon the work of unconditioning, there arc at present no fur- 
ther facts. We must leave the subject of conditioning and un- 
conditioning of emotional reactions until we can work upon 
a larger number of infants and work with them under better 
conditions of control. 
Home Factors Leading to Emotional Conditioning of Children 

Is is conceivable that some day we may be able to bring up 
the human young through infancy and childhood without cry- 
ing or showing fear reactions except when in the presence of 
the unconditioned stimuli (pain, noxious stimuli, loud sounds, 
etc.) calling out these responses. Since these unconditioned 
stimuli are rarely present, children ought practically never to 
cry. And yet look at them morning, noon and night they 
are at it! An infant has an honest right to cry when it has 
colic, when its diaper pin is sticking into its tender flesh, and 
to whimper a bit when hungry, when its gets its head in be- 
tween the slats of the bed, or falls clown between the mattress 
and the -side of the bed, or when the cat scratches it, or its 
bodily tissue is otherwise injured, or when loud sounds and 
loss of support assail it. But on no other occasion is the cry 
justifiable. This means that owing to our unsatisfactory train- 
ing 1 methods in the home, we spoil the emotional make-up of 
each child as rapidly as the twig can be bent. 

What Situations Make the Child Cry? 

In line with this thought, Mrs. Jones followed around a 
group of nine children from the time they first waked up in 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 67 

the morning until they were fast asleep at night. Every cry 
was noted, every laugh observed. The duration of laughing 
and crying was noted and the time of day it occurred and, 
most carefully of all, the general situations calling out these 
reactions were recorded and the after effects crying and laugh- 
ing had upon subsequent behavior. Children in the group 
ranged from 16 months to 3 years of age. These children were 
tested in the Heckscher Foundation, but they were living there 
temporarily. They had been brought up in the home. One 
month after the first set of observations was made another 
set was undertaken. The results of these observations have 
never been published by Mrs. Jones, but she has given me the 
main facts which I now present. 

The situations calling out cries are listed in the order of the 
number of cries elicited, as follows: 

1. Having to sit on the toilet chair. 

2. Having property taken away. 

3. Having the face washed. 

4. Being left alone in a room. 

5. Having the adult leave the room. 

6. Working at something which won't pan out. 

7. Failure to get adults or other children to play with 

them, or look at them and talk to them. 

8. Being dressed. 

9. Failure to get adults to pick them up. 

10. Being undressed. 

11. Being bathed. 

12. Having the nose wiped. 

These are only twelve of the most usual situations calling 
out such responses. More than 100 situations called out weep- 
ing or whining. Many of the responses to these situations can 
be looked upon as unconditioned or conditioned rage responses, 
for example : (1) sitting on the toilet chair, (2) having property 
taken away, (3) having its face washed, (6) working at some- 
thing that won't pan out, (10) being undressed, (11) being 
bathed, (12) having the nose wiped. On the other hand, (5) 
having the adult leave the room, (7) failure to get adults to 
play with them, and (9) failure to get adults to pick them 
U p would seem to belong more in the love conditioned re- 
sponses approaching somewhat the grief situation where the 
object or person to whom the attachment is formed is re- 
moved or else will not exhibit the customary responses (as 
where "love" has grown cold). Mrs. Jones states that there 



68 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

were a number of cases, too, where fears of both the con- 
ditioned and the unconditioned type, were responsible for a 
good deal of crying for example, when the children were 
made to stand on the top of the slides, sliding down the slide, 
standing on the tables. Possibly (4) and (5) of the above 
classification may have elements of the fear response in them. 

In making a study of this kind, it should be always borne 
in mind that crying may be due to organic factors, such as 
sleepiness, hunger, colic, and the like. Mrs, Jones found that 
tlie largest number of cries (probably) due to intra-organic 
causes occurred between 9 and 11 o'clock in the morning. As 
a result of this finding, the institution placed its rest hours 
before lunch instead of after lunch, with two rest periods 
for the very young children. This considerably lessened the 
amount of crying and disturbed behavior due to intra-organic 
factors, 

What Makes Children Laugh? 

The situations which call out laughter and smiling were 
recorded in the same way. The common causes of laughter are, 
in order, as follows : 

1. Being played with (playfully dressed, tickled, etc.). 

2. Running, chasing, romping with other children. 

3. Playing with toys (a ball was particularly effective). 

4. Teasing other children. 

5. Watching other children at play. 

6. Making attempts which resulted in adjustment (e. g. 

getting parts of toys or apparatus to fit together or 
work). 

7. Making sounds, more or less musical, at the piano, 

with a mouth organ, singing, pounding, etc. 
In all 85 situations were listed calling out laughter and smil- 
ing. Tickling, playfully dressing, gentle bathing, romping with 
other children, teasing (but always where there was a chance 
at a "comeback" probably a learned response sexually based 
since the comeback involved being gently handled, pummeled 
and tickled) were the most f rccjuent situations eliciting laugh- 
ter. It is hardly possible to attempt to discuss here to what 
extent these smiling reactions were unconditioned and to what 
extent conditioned. Attention is called to the fact that depend- 
ing on the way the situations are manipulated and upon the 
intra-organic condition of the youngsters, the same stimuli can 
at one time bring laughter and at another time bring out cry- 
ing, for example, although cries predominated in the bathroom 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 69 

when their faces were being washed or when they were being 
bathed, it was always possible to produce a laugh. On one 
occasion the introduction of a mouth organ altered the whole 
tenor of the room, changing distress into laughter. Where the 
youngsters are just being dressed by the ordinary procedure, 
that is, being pulled, twisted and turned, crying nearly always 
results, and where dressing is playfully done, smiles and laugh- 
ter instead of crying are the responses. Attention should be 
called to the fact, however, that we can very easily overdo the 
matter of amusing the child when it is doing the things it has 
to do. I have seen children, spoiled in this way, undergo 
torture when a new nurse is called in who does not or will 
not yield to their demand to be amused while being bathed, 
put to bed, dressed or fed. 

While our results again are very incomplete, we have gone 
far enough to show that it is very easy to substitute for a great 
many of the situations in the home which now call out cry- 
ing, situations that will call out smiling (and generally laugh- 
ter) instead, which, in moderation is unquestionably better 
so far as concerns the general metabolic state of the organism. 
Furthermore, when we have gone far enough to show by 
continual watching what the sticking points are in the child's 
environment, we can rebuild his environment and thereby 
keep an unfavorable organization from developing. 

Should We Implant Negative Responses in Our Children? 

There is a certain amount of sentimentality going the peda- 
gogical rounds in this country to the effect that no negative 
reactions should ever be forced on the child. I have never 
been very much in favor of this propaganda. In fact, I be- 
lieve that certain negative responses should be scientifically 
implanted as a matter of protection to the organism. I don't 
see any other way out of it. I think, though, we should make 
a distinction between conditioned fear responses and mere nega- 
tive responses. Negative responses conditioned upon the original 
(unconditioned) fear stimuli always apparently involve vast 
changes in the viscera possibly always disruptive to normal 
metabolism. Conditioned rage responses, while not necessarily 
negative in character (they include the positive responses in 
fighting, attack, etc.) apparently do the same thing. I have the 
simple facts in view here which Cannon has brought out, that 
in fear and rage behavior, digestion and absorption are often 
completely interfered with food is left in the stomach to fer- 
ment and to form a breeding ground for bacteria and for setting 



70 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

free toxic products. So there is some justice in the view that 
fear and rage behavior is in general harmful to the organism 
(yet the race possibly could not have survived if it had not 
reacted negatively to loud sounds and loss of support and had 
not struggled when movement was hampered). Love behavior, 
on the other hand, seems to heighten metabolism. Digestion 
and absoption apparently take place more rapidly. Questioning 
of husbands and wives leads to the disclosure of the fact that 
after normal sex intercourse hunger contractions begin in the 
stomach and food is very frequently sought. 

But to come back to negative reactions. It is at least an 
opinion of mine that where negative responses arc built into 
manual behavior (conditioned) such as withdrawal of hands, 
legs, body, etc., by the use of faint noxious stimuli, there is 
little involvement of the viscera. To make myself clear, let 
me cite a case: I can build in negative behavior to a snake in 
two ways. Just as I show the snake I can make a terrible 
noise and cause the child to fall down and cry out completely 
terror stricken. Soon the mere sight of the snake will have 
the same effect. Or I can present the snake several times 
and each time as the infant reaches for it I can tap its fingers 
with a pencil and gradually establish the negative reaction 
without shock. I have not tried this with a snake, but I have 
with the candle. A child can be conditioned by a severe burn 
with one stimulation, but this involves always a severe reaction* 
By presenting the candle flame many times and each time letting 
it just heat the finger enough to produce withdrawal of the 
hand, a negative conditioned response can be built up without 
the severe features of shock. Building in negative responses 
without shock requires time, however. 

I cannot tonight dwell too long upon the interesting psy- 
chological and social factors involved in the building in of 
negative reactions. 

May I just say dogmatically that our civilization is built 
upon "don't" and taboos of many kinds. Individuals living 
adjustedly in it must learn to heed thorn. Since the negative 
responses must be built in they should be built in as sanely 
as possible without involving strong emotional reactions. Chil- 
dren and adolescents must not play in the street, run in front 
of automobiles, play with strange clogs and cats, run up and 
stand under the feet of horses, point firearms at people, run 
any chance of catching venereal diseases or having illegitimate 
children; they must not do thousands of other things that I 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 71 

might mention. I am not saying that all the negative reactions 
demanded by society are ethically right (and when I say ethic- 
ally I mean the new experimental ethics that does not exist 
today). I don't know whether many of the taboos now ad- 
hered to are ultimately good for the organism. I am merely 
saying that society exists it is a fact, and if we live under 
it we must draw back when social customs say draw back, or 
we must get our adult hands slapped. There is, of course, 
an ever increasing number of people in the world whose hands 
are tough and who do many tabooed things and take the social 
chastisement that inevitably follows. This means of course 
that social trial and error experimentation is becoming possible 
the smoking of women, now tolerated in all restaurants and 
hotels and even in nearly every home, is a good example. As 
long as society rules every act through its agencies (such as 
political systems, church, family) no learning, no trying out 
of new social responses is possible. In the last 20 years we 
have seen marked changes in the social status of women, 
marked weakening of marriage ties, marked diminution in 
thoroughness of control of political parties (to wit, the over- 
throw of practically all monarchies), a marked weakening of 
the church's hold upon genuinely educated people, the lessen- 
ing of taboos upon sex. The danger, of course, comes now 
from too rapid lessening of control, too superficial trials of 
new forms of behavior, and from the acceptance of new 
methods without sufficient trial. 

Use of Corporal Punishment in Building in Negative Responses 
The question of corporal punishment in the bringing up of 
children at home and at school comes up periodically for dis- 
cussion. I believe our experiments almost settle the problem. 
Punishment is a word which ought never to have crept into 
our language. 

Whipping or beating the body is a custom as old as the race. 
Even our modern views on the punishment of criminals and 
children have as their basis the old religious masochistic prac- 
tices of the church. Punishment in the biblical sense of "an eye 
for an eye and a tooth for a tooth" honeycombs our whole 
social and religious life. 

Certainly punishment of children is not a scientific method. 
As parents, .teachers and jurists, we are or ought to be inter- 
ested only in setting up ways of acting in the individual that 
square with group behavior. You have already grasped the 
notion that the behaviorist is a strict determinist the child 



72 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

or adult has to do wfat he does do. The only way he can 
be made to act differently is first to untrain him and then to 
retrain him. Both children and adults do do things which 
do not correspond with the standards of behavior set up by 
the home or by the group. This deviation from social stand- 
ards is due to the fact that the home and the group have not 
sufficently trained the individual during the formative period. 
Since the formative period is coextensive with life, social 
training should be continuous throughout life. It is our own 
fault, then, that individuals (other than defectives and psy- 
chopaths) go "wrong," that is, deviate from set standards of 
behavior and by "our own fault" I mean the fault of the 
parent, the teacher and every other member of the group; 
we have neglected and are neglecting our opportunities. 

But to return to the question of whipping and beating. 
There is no excuse for whipping or beating ! 

First, because very often the deviating act occurs many hours 
before father or mother come home to engage in the act of 
chastising. Conditioned responses are not built up by this 
unscientific procedure. The idea that a child's future bad be- 
havior will be prevented by giving him a licking in the evening 
for something he did in the morning is ridiculous. Equally 
ridiculous from the standpoint of preventing crime, is our 
legal and judicial method of punishment which allows a crime 
to be committed in one year and punishment administered a 
year or two later if at all. 

Second, whipping is used more often than not to serve as 
an emotional outlet (sadistic) for parent or teacher. 

Third, often when the beating occurs immediately after the 
act (the only time for it if it is to take place at all) it is not and 
cannot be -regulated according to any scientific dosage. It is 
either too mild, therefore not a strong enough stimulus to es- 
tablish the conditioned negative response; or too severe, thus 
stirring up unnecessarily the whole visceral system of the child ; 
or the deviating act does not occur frequently enough, with 
attendant punishment, to meet the scientific conditions for 
setting up a negative response; or, finally, it is repeated so 
frequently that all effect is lost habituation comes in, leading 
possibly to the psychopathological condition known as "maso- 
chism," a condition in which the individual responds positively 
(sexually) to noxious stimuli. 

How, then, are we to build in the negative responses which 
I said above are necessary to build in ? I thoroughly believe in 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 73 

rapping a child's fingers when it puts them in its mouth, when 
it constantly ringers its sex organs, when it reaches up and 
pulls down glass dishes and trays, or turns on gas cocks or 
water hydrants, etc., provided the child is caught in the act 
<md the parent can administer the rap at once in a thoroughly 
objective way just as objectively as the behaviorist administers 
the faint electric shock when building up a negative or with- 
drawal response to any given object. Society, both the group 
and the immediate parents, uses the verbal "don't" to older 
children in place of the rap. It will of course always have 
to use "don't" but I hope some time we can rearrange the 
environment so that less and less negative reactions will have 
to be built in in both child and adult. 

One bad feature in the whole system of the building in of 
negative responses is the fact .that the parent becomes in- 
volved in the situation I mean by that becomes a part of the 
punishment system. The child grows up to "hate" the person 
who has most often to administer the beating usually the 
father. I hope some time to try out the experiment of having 
a table top electrically wired in such a way that if a child 
reaches for a glass or a delicate vase it will be punished, 
whereas if it reaches for its toys or other things it is allowed 
to play with, it can get them without being electrically shocked. 
In other words, I should like to make the objects and situations 
of life build in their own negative reactions. 

Present Methods of Punishment for Crime are Relics 
of the Dark Ages 

What we have said about punishment in the rearing of chil- 
dren holds equally well for adults in the field of crime. Since 
in my opinion only the sick or psychopaths (insane) or un- 
trained (socially untrained) individuals commit crimes, society 
should be interested in just two things: (1) Seeing that the 
insane or psychopathic individuals are made well if possible, 
and if not, placed in well run (non-political) institutions where 
no harm can come to them and where they can do no harm 
to other members of the group. In other words, the fate of 
those individuals should be in medical (psychiatric) hands. 
The question as to whether the hopelessly insane should be 
etherized has of course been raised time and time again. There 
can be no reasons against it except exaggerated sentiment and 
mediaeval religious mandates. (2) Seeing that the socially 
untrained individuals, not insane or psychopathological, are 



74 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

placed where they can be trained, sent to school, made to 
learn, regardless of their age, a trade, made to put on culture, 
made to 'become social. Furthermore, during this period they 
should be placed where they cannot harm other members of 
the group. Such education and training may take ten to fifteen 
years or even longer. Failing to put on the training necessary 
to fit them to again enter society, they should be restrained 
always, and made to earn their daily bread, in vast manufactur- 
ing and agricultural institutions, escape from which is im- 
possible. Naturally, no human being criminal or otherwise 
should be deprived of air, sunshine, food, exercise and other 
physiological factors necessary to optimum living conditions. 
On the other hand, strenuous work sixteen hours per day will 
hurt no one. Individuals put aside thus for additional training 
should of course be kept in the hands of the behaviorists. 

Naturally such a view does away completely with criminal 
law (but not with policing). It does away naturally with the 
criminal lawyer and with legal (criminal) precedent, and with 
courts for the trial of criminals. Many jurists of note agree 
substantially with this view. But until all law books are burned 
in some great upheaval of nature and until all lawyers and 
jurists suddenly decide to become behaviorists, I never expect 
to see the present retaliation or punishment theory ( a religious 
theory) of handling the deviant give place to a scientific theory 
based upon what we know of the establishing and breaking 
down of conditioned and emotional responses. 

What Are Some of the Most Important Forms of 
Built-in Emotional Befiaviorf 

In addition to the various forms of emotional behavior both 
learned and unlearned that we have discussed in this and the 
preceding lecture, there are several other types which interest the 
behaviorist very greatly. These are jealousy and shame. So 
far the behaviorist has had very little opportunity to make any 
study of them. I believe that both jealousy and shame are 
built in. 

Other forms of emotional behavior, popularly known as sor- 
row, grief, resentment, anger, reverence, awe, justice, mercy, 
seem to the behaviorist to be quite simple. He believes them 
to be vast super-structures built upon the very simple types 
of unlearned behavior that we have already abundantly dis- 
cussed. 

Jealousy and shame, however, require considerable further 
study. So far I have not had opportunity to observe the first 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 75 

appearance of shame and its genetic growth. I am inclined 
to think that shame is in some way connected with the first 
overt masturbation that involves the orgasm. The stimulus 
is the manipulation of the sex organs, the final responses are 
heightened blood pressure, superficial dilatation of the capilla- 
ries of the skin known as flushing, among many others. Almost 
from infancy the child is taught not to masturbate or is pun- 
ished if it masturbates. Consequently any situation, verbal or 
otherwise, connected with the touching of the sex organs or 
reference to the sex organs may condition the blushing and 
bowing of the head which nearly always takes place in masturb- 
ation. This, however, is purely speculative and I must lay 
it aside here for future observation. 

I have recently made some observations and experiments 
upon jealousy. 

Jealousy: Ask any group of individuals what they mean 
by jealousy what the stimulus is that produces it, what the 
pattern of the response is, and you only get the vaguest, most 
unserviceable kind of replies. Ask these same individuals 
what the unlearned (unconditioned) stimulus is that calls out 
the response; ask them what the unlearned (unconditioned) 
response pattern is? To both questions you get unscientific 
answers. Most individuals say, "Oh, jealousy is a pure in- 
stinct." If we diagram thus 

S R 



we have to put a question mark under both stimulus and 
response. 

And yet jealousy is one of the most powerful factors in the 
organization of present day individuals. It is recognized by 
the courts as one of the strongest of "motives" leading to action. 
Robberies and murders are committed because of it; careers 
are both made and unmade because of it; marital quarrels, 
separations and divorces are probably more frequently to be 
traced to it than to any other single cause. Its almost universal 
permeation through the whole action stream of all individuals 
has lead to the view that it is an inborn instinct. And yet the 
moment you begin to observe people and try to determine 
what kinds of situations call out jealous behavior and what the 
details of that behavior are, you see that the situations are 
highly complex (social) and that the reactions are all highly 



76 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

organized (learned). This in itself should make us doubt its 
hereditary origin. Let us watch people for awhile to see if 
their behavior will not throw light upon the situations and the 
responses. 

What Situations Call Out Jealous Behavior? 

In the first place, as we have said, the situation is always 
a social one it involves people. What people? Always the 
person who calls out our conditioned love responses. This may 
be the mother, father, or brother, sister or sweetheart, wife 
or husband, etc. The person may be of the same or the opposite 
sex. The wife-husband situation is second only to the sweet- 
heart one for calling out violent responses. This brief examin- 
ation helps us somewhat in our understanding of jealousy. The 
situation is always a substitutive one, that is conditioned. It 
involves the person calling out conditioned love responses. This 
generalization, if true, takes it out of the class of inherited 
forms of behavior at once. 

What are the Responses? 

The responses in adults are legion. I have taken notes on 
a great many cases among both children and adults. To vary 
our procedure let us take the responses of an adult first. Case 
A. A is a "very jealous husband/' married two years to a 
beautiful young woman only slightly younger. They go out 
frequently on parties. If this wife (1) dances a little close 
to her partner, (2) if she sits out a dance to talk to a man 
and talks in a low tone to him, (3) if in a moment of gaiety 
she kisses another man in the open light of the room before 
everyone, (4) if she goes out even with other women to lunch 
or tea or to shop, (5) if she invites her own group of friends 
for a party at home then jealous behavior is exhibited. Such 
stimuli bring out the responses (1) refusal to talk or dance 
with his wife, (2) increased tension of all his muscles, mouth 
shuts tightly, eyes seem to grow smaller, jaw "hardens." He 
next withdraws himself from other people in the room. His 
face becomes flushed, then black. This behavior may and 
usually does persist for days after the affair is started. He 
will talk to no one about the affair. Meditation is impossible, 
The jealous state seems to have tun itself down or out. The 
wife herself by no amount of assurance of love, of innocence, 
by no system of apology or obeisance can do anything towards 
hastening recovery. Yet his wife is devoted to him and has 
never been even in the slightest measure unfaithful, as he him- 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 77 

self admits verbally when not in the jealous state. In a per- 
son less well bred, less well schooled, it is easy to see that 
his behavior might become overt he might blacken his wife's 
eye or if there were a real male aggressor, might attack or 
murder him. 

Take the child's jealous behavior next. The first sign of 
jealousy was noted in child B at about two years of age. It 
shows whenever the mother embraces the father, clings to 
him, kisses him. At two and one-half years of age this child 
who had never been made the "scapegoat," who had always 
been allowed to be present and even welcomed into the family 
love-making, begins to attack the father whenever the mother 
embraces the father. He (1) pulls at his coat, (2) cries out 
"my mamma/' (3) pushes his father away and crowds in be- 
tween them. If the kissing continues, the child's reaction state 
becomes very marked and intense. Always in the morning 
Sundays especially, when he comes into the bedroom before 
his parents are up he is taken up and welcomed and made 
much of by both. And yet at two and three-fourths years of 
age he would say to his father, "you going to office, dada?" 
or else give the direct command, "y u go to office, dada," At 
three years of age this boy was sent with his infant brother to 
his grandmother's, in charge of a nurse. He was separated 
from his mother for one month. During this time his strong 
attachment for his mother weakened. When the parents 
visited the child (then thirty-seven months of age) no jealous 
behavior was exhibited when they made love in front of him. 
When the parents clung together for a considerable time, to 
see if jealous behavior would finally occur, he merely ran up 
and hugged first one and then the other. This test was re- 
peated for four days with the same results. 

The father then seeing that the old situation failed to call 
it out, tried next attacking the mother, striking her on the body 
and head and shaking her from side to side. She on her part 
simulated crying, but fought back. The youngster stood this 
for a few minutes, then started in for his father tooth and 
nail and would not let up until the fight was over. He cried, 
kicked, tugged at his father's leg and struck with his hand. 

Next the father 'remained passive while the mother attacked 
him. She inadvertently punched below the belt, causing the 
father to double up in no simulated way. Nevertheless, the 
youngster started his attack on his father again and continued 
it even after he was hors de combat. By this time the young- 



78 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

ster was genuinely disturbed and the experiment had to be 
discontinued. The next day, however, no jealous behavior 
was exhibited when mother and father embraced. 

How Early Does this Form of Jealousy against one or 
the other Parent Occur? 

To further test the genesis of this type of jealous behavior, 
a test was made upon an eleven months old infant boy. This 
infant was well nourished and wholly without conditioned 
fears, yet there was a strong attachment for the mother, but 
none for the father who often spanked his hand when he 
attempted to suck his thumb and otherwise broke in upon his 
quiet by trying various types of experiments. At eleven 
months he could crawl quickly and for considerable distances* 

When father and mother violently embraced, the youngster 
could not be made to keep his eyes on his parents. Love 
making between them was nothing in his young life. This 
was tested again and again. There was no tendency to crawl 
towards them, much less to crawl in between them. Jealousy 
was absent. 

Next the father and mother attacked one another. The 
floor was carpeted and the noise of the blows and the low 
whimper of the mother (or the father in turn) was not very 
loud. The fight immediately stopped his crawling about, 
brought prolonged fixation always of the mother and never 
of the father. As it continued, he whimpered and cried out 
aloud several times but made no effort to enter the fight on 
either side. The noises, shaking of the floor, and the sight 
of the parents' faces which offered the same visual stimulus 
to him when he himself got slapped and was made to cry, 
were sufficiently complex stimuli to call out the observed be- 
havior. His behavior was of the fear type partly visually 
conditioned. There was apparently no jealousy behavior in 
this infant, either when its parents made love or when either 
parent attacked the other. Eleven months seems to be too 
tender an age for jealousy to appear. 

Does Jealousy Appear Suddenly when an Only Child 
Has to Face His Infant Brother? 

Many Freudians insist that the beginning of jealousy be- 
havior very often dates back in the life of the child to the 
appearance of a brother or a sister. They claim that it starts 
practically full-blown even though the child in question is a 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 79 

year or less than a year of age. And yet, so far as I know, 
no Freudian has ever attempted to put his theories to practical 
experimental test. 

During my own observations on the origin of jealousy, I 
have had one favorable opportunity to observe the behavior 
of an only child when he received his newborn brother. B, 
whose jealous behavior directed against his father I have 
just told you about, was two and one-fourth years of age when 
the event occurred. He had formed a very strong attach- 
ment to his mother and to his own regular nurse. He had 
no organized reactions toward any youngster under a year of 
age. The mother had been absent in the hospital for two 
weeks. B was taken care of by his regular nurse during these 
two weeks. The day the mother returned, his own nurse 
Icept B busy in his room playing until the conditions for the 
test were all set. The test was made at noon in a well- 
lighted sitting room. The mother was sitting nursing the 
baby, with her breast exposed. B had not seen the mother 
during the two weeks. In addition to the mother with her 
infant, there were present a trained nurse new to B, a grand- 
mother, and the father. B was allowed to walk down the 
steps alone and into the room. Everyone had been instructed 
to remain absolutely quiet and to make the situation as nat- 
ural as possible. B walked into the room and up to his mother, 
leaned on her knee and said, "How do, Mama." He did 
not attempt to kiss her or hug her. He did not notice the 
breast, or the baby for thirty seconds. Then he saw the baby. 
He said, "Little baby." Then he took the baby's hands and 
gently patted them, rubbed its head and its face and began to 
say, "That baby, that baby." Then he kissed it without any 
prompting. He was very gentle and tender in all of his re- 
sponses. The trained nurse, who was unknown to him, took 
up the new baby. He reacted against this, at least verbally, 
saying, "Mama take baby." Thus the baby was reacted to 
really as a part of the mother situation and the first element 
of jealousy response was directed against the person who took 
something away from his mother (hampered his mother's 
movements). Surely this was as typically an un-Freudian 
reaction as could be imagined. This was the first sign of a 
jealousy response. But the response was positive for the in- 
fant and not against it notwithstanding the fact that the 
brother was usurping his place on his mother's lap. 

Then the new baby was taken by its nurse to its room and 



80 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

put to bed. B tagged along, top. When he came back, the 
father said, "How do you like Jimmie?" And he said, "Like 
Jimmie Jimmie sleeping." He did not notice at any time 
the exposed breast of the mother and really paid very little 
attention to the mother except when the nurse tried to take 
the baby away. During the whole setting, he reacted posi- 
tively to the baby for only two minutes and then turned to 
other things. 

The following day, B had to give up his own room which 
contained most of his toys, books, and the like, in preparation 
for the new baby. He was told that Jimmie had to have his 
room for a while. This situation called out only the most 
eager positive response in helping to push and pull all of his 
own furniture to the new room. He slept in the new room 
that night and every night until the trained nurse left. There 
was never the slightest sign of resentment, jealousy, etc., in 
his behavior directed against the new baby at any time.- 

The behavior of these two children has been under constant 
observation for one year now. Never has there been the 
slightest sign of jealousy. The three-year-old today is just 
as kind and considerate to the one-year-old infant as he was 
on his first introduction. Not even when nurse, mother or 
father takes the infant up and pets it is there any jealousy. 
Once a new nurse almost succeeded in establishing it by at- 
tempting to control the older child by saying: "You are a 
naughty boy. Jimmie is a nice boy I love him." For just 
a few days jealousy threatened, but the discharge of the nurse 
saved the situation. 

Although there is no attachment pronounced enough to cause 
airy disturbance of his daily routine, if the younger child is 
not around, the older youngster takes the part of the one- 
year-old if mother or father attempts to chastise the young- 
ster by spanking its hand. The moment the younger infant 
cries, the three-year-old will actually attack either one or both 
parents, saying "Jimmie good boy; you mustn't make Jimmie 
cry." 

Can We Draw Any Conclusions About Jealousy f 
So far our experiments on jealousy are merely preliminary. 
If any generalization at all can be made, it would seem to 
take the following form : Jealousy is a bit of behavior whose 
stimulus is a (conditioned) love stimulus the response to 
which is rage but a pattern of rage containing possibly the 
original visceral components but in addition parts of many 



CHANGE IN OUR EMOTIONAL EQUIPMENT 81 

habit patterns, (fighting, boxing, shooting, talking, etc.). We 
may use this diagram to hold our facts together: 

(C) S (U&C) R 

Sight (or sound) of loved Stiffening of whole body, 
object being tampered or in- clenching of hands, reddening 
terfered with. and then blackening of face 

pronounced breathing, fighting, 
verbal recrimination, etc. 

Naturally this is reduced to the barest schematism. The re- 
sponse may take many forms and the stimulus may consist of 
far more subtle factors than I have noted here, but I believe 
we are on the right track in trying to formulate jealousy in 
these terms. 

May I say in conclusion that the behaviorist in spite of his 
seeming dogmatism would like to inject a word of caution 
about his own views? All of his conclusions on the origin 
and growth of emotional life are based now upon too few 
cases and too few experiments. This will be remedied in the 
near future. More and more students are at work upon 
emotional behavior using behavioristic methods. No sane 
person can ever again use the old introspective method with 
which James and his immediate followers came so near wreck- 
ing this most thrilling part of psychology. 




WALTKR S. HUNTKK 



CHAPTER IV 

PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY* 



BY WALTER S. HUNTER c - 



Psychology for many years has been a discipline to intrigue 
the layman's fancy. It has stood for the scientist's attack upon 
the most subtle and experiment-defying portion of the uni- 
verse, the mind. As the psychologist has extended his methods 
of study from sensation to memory and finally to the com- 
plex processes of thought, he has applauded his own progress 
so vigorously that he has almost converted his scientific col- 
leagues to the belief that psychology knows what it is about. 
And yet dogging the heels of this successful science, there has 
always been an irritable congeries of dissenters, philosophers 
who have never thought highly of a scientific analysis of the 
conscious aspect of the universe, spiritualists, psychic research- 
ers, and Freudians, who object to the petty laboratory problems 
in terms of which the psychologist outlines his field and who 
resent deeply and religiously the tendency in psychology to 
eliminate the purposeful activity of mind. Into this field of 
dispute, where the mind-body problem casts its shadow over 
the formulation of points of view and the interpretation of 
experimental findings, and where scientific psychology con- 
cerns itself with the analysis of experience into elements and 
attributes, a new and refreshing influence has come. This in- 
fluence is that of behaviorism or, as I prefer to say, the in- 
fluence of anthroponomy. I use the term anthroponomy for 
the science of human behavior, and the term anthroponomist 
I shall use as synonymous with behaviorist. These terms are 
new and therefore distracting, and yet they have the great 
merit of reminding us constantly that- our problem is the study 
of man. The term behavior is too general to indicate precisely 
our field of investigation, and the term behaviorism suffers 
as a designation for a total science exactly because it is an 
"ism." The more detailed meaning of our new term will ap- 
pear as our discussion proceeds. 

It will be my purpose in this lecture to compare for you 
the respective merits of psychology and anthroponomy, to show 
you certain aspects of the two modes of attack upon the prob- 
lem of human nature, and thereby to formulate for you specif- 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, March 
11, 1926. 



84 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

ically the anthroponomist's attitude toward certain of the per- 
sistent problems of psychology. This endeavor we shall prose- 
cute upon a theoretical rather than upon an experimental level 
for the problems which concern us bear more upon the funda- 
mental issues of the science than upon matters of fact which 
are only to be settled by observation and experiment. A cer- 
tain amount of confusion has already been introduced into the 
discussions conducted by the psychologists and the behaviorists 
by the failure to keep disputes over problems of fact out of the 
consideration of the respective theoretical points of view. Thus 
Watson has denied the existence of centrally aroused neural 
processes to the great dismay of the students of immediate 
experience. And these latter have seized upon Watson's de- 
nial of instincts and individual differences as particularly 
atrocious bits of evidence showing the untenability of the be- 
haviorist's position. These problems are only to be settled by 
observation and experiment and are quite irrelevant to the 
fundamental differences between the students of immediate 
experience and the anthroponomists. It is my desire, as we 
proceed, to place a few of the fundamental principles of an- 
throponomy before you in such a manner that you may be 
able to discriminate between the fundamental and the inci- 
dental issues in the controversy which at the present time 
seems to dominate the study of human nature. 

There are two methods of approach to the study of human 
nature. One is the indirect, or psychological method, and the 
other is the direct, or anthroponomical, method. The psycholo- 
gist believes that human nature can best be understood by 
studying not the human animal itself but by studying the en- 
vironment in which this organism moves. To study the organ- 
ism would be to encroach upon the field of his fellow scientist, 
the biologist, unless the human organism were studied as an 
object in the environment of still another human organism. 
The environment, studied by the psychologist, lies not only 
without the animal but also within it. The psychologist's task 
is complete when he has, first, exhaustively described the total 
environing situation with reference to its least discriminable 
aspects, when he has, second, synthesized these aspects into 
such complex processes as trees, melodies, food-tastes, tickle, 
itch, and heat in the stomach, which seem to the layman to be 
the essential components of the environment which he calls 
Nature, and when he has, third, subsumed these complex pro- 
cesses under his fundamental categories of sensation, percep- 
tion, attention, imagination, memory, thinking, and will. The 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 85 

anthroponomist has a different method. He sees man working 
in the fields, bathing in the surf, and pursuing his intricate 
way in the great cities of Earth. "How wonderful is my 
opportunity," say the anthroponomist, "to investigate this com- 
plex organism and to add, to the knowledge which the biologist 
and the sociologist have, further definite information concern- 
ing those very fundamental and characteristic aspects of human 
nature, mz v language behavior (whether verbal or non-verbal), 
learning, and inter-stimulation and response. Theoretically I 
am willing to admit the possibility of understanding human 
nature by the indirect method of studying not man but the 
environment, because obviously man is the kind of a creature 
that can live in this earthly environment, and he must, there- 
fore, possess certain sensory, neural, and muscular equipment 
correlated with environmental conditions. My method of pro- 
cedure, however, will be to describe and analyse man's organic 
behavior itself with only such references to the environment 
as shall be necessary for this purpose. I am not like my 
fellow scientist, the psychologist, who would understand man 
by cataloging all of the discriminable colors, tones, pressures, 
feelings, Gestalten, etc., in the universe. When I study human 
nature, I do so directly by observing man's changing behavior."' 
In order to carry forward systematically the comparison of 
these two sciences, psychology and anthroponomy, it is neces- 
sary to single out certain important problems as the chief foci, 
of interest. These problems are as follows : 

(1) What is the subject matter and goal of the science?' 

(2) What are the chief methods employed? 

(3) What are the results, or products, of the science? 
Let us begin with the problem of the subject matter and 

goal of the two sciences under consideration. Both psychology 
and anthroponomy take as their goal the understanding of some 
aspect of the human individual, leaving other aspects or por- 
tions to such sciences as anatomy, physiology, and bio-chem- 
istry. The aspect of man which the psychologist studies is. 
that which is termed mental, or psychical, or experiential. Thus 
Bentley 1 says that psychology "seeks to describe and to under- 
stand experience and the activities of the total organism in 
which experience plays an essential part." And again he says 2 ' 
with reference to psychosomatic functions, "Always mental 
resources and always bodily resources of the organism are 

a Bentley, Madison. The field of psychology. New York, 1924, p. 15.. 
Ibid, p. 19. 



86 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

called into use for carrying out these functional performances. 
That is why the psychologist calls them 'psychosomatic' func- 
tions, thus distinguishing them from the purely bodily or 'so- 
matic' functions, such as the growth of bone and the operations 
of enzymes and ferments/' You cannot, of course, fail to see 
the implication in this latter statement that the somatic pro- 
cesses which have no accompanying psychic aspect lie beyond 
the domain of the psychologist. 

If we now ask what experience is, and experience is environ- 
ment, we are confronted by the psychologist's distinction be- 
tween an experience and a physical object or between the sci- 
ence of psychology and the science of physics. This distinction 
is stated by Wundt, Titchener and Bentley, as that between an 
object which exists independently of human experience and an 
object which exists only as experienced. Let us again consult 
Bentley on this point. "The objects and events of physics 
and of the rest are regarded as if they outlasted the exper- 
iencing of them and continued as independent of the act of 
apprehension . . . Animals, the earth's strata, the ocean's sub- 
stance, the planet's course, and the electron's oscillations 
are one and all regarded as if ordered, arranged, 
and preserved in existence wholly apart ' from the 
experiencing organism which discerns them. But what 
shall we say of the objects and the operations of the psy- 
chologist? We shall say of these that they are only when they 
are-in-experience." 3 In psychology, "When we proceed to the 
examination of our tones and noises, .... ; of our lights, 
colors, colds, warmths, sweets, sours, and the like, we must 
take care that we do not slip from experiencing to the things 
experienced, to noisy cities, to tuneful voices, to sunlight and 
shadows, to the chill of the night, the warmth of the noon, 
and so on to the other independent objects!'*" ....when I 
say that I listened last night to an orchestra composed of 
violins, 'cellos, double basses, wood-winds, brasses, and the 
rest, it is obvious that I am attempting a rough analytic de- 
scription of the orchestra and not of anything connected with 
my organism. It scarcely seems possible that such things as 
books and violins should be mistaken for the furnishings of 
the mind ; but this is precisely the first error that the beginner 
drops into in his quest for component qualities." 5 



Ibid, pp. 31-2. 
*Ibid, p. 35. 
Ibid, p. 36. 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 87 

Let me give one more quotation from Bentley with reference 
to "images" and to "sensations" from within the organism: 
" .... a moment's reflection will make it obvious to the reader 
that 'myself imagined as walking' or 'myself remembered as 
walking' is just as much an object of the physical order as 
'myself now perceived as walking'. . . . We all do say in the 
vernacular that an object which we remember or think about 
is only a 'mental object' ; but there we only mean that the ob- 
ject is not at the moment present to the senses. It is no more 
'mental' than the book now in your hand is 'mental/ " 6 "Many 
persons think that, when they announce such an interesting fact 
as palpitation and trembling in sudden fear or the dryness of 
the throat in continued thirst, they have observed and reported 
psychologically. They are mistaken. This is one of the nine 
hundred and ninety-nine wrong ways, of analysis! .... But 
although they may come to be known through processes of 
experience (a group of pressures of alternating intensities, in 
the one case ; a complex of warmth and dull massive pressure, 
in the other), the palpitation and the dryness are no more 
mental than the heart and the throat themselves are mental." 7 

I have quoted thus at length from one of the leading students 
of experience with much malice aforethought. I have pre- 
sented these quotations in order that you might have an ex- 
perientialist's own statement of the subject matter of his sci- 
ence before I proceeded to comment upon it. I think that one 
great reason for the continued, although apparently waning, 
popularity of psychology, lies in the belief that psychologists 
are conducting Cook's tours of experience. On these tours 
the traveler expects to see all things that the eyes can see, hear 
all that ears can hear, meet all memories, emotions, visceral 
strains, and other events that are found in the psychic world. 
This belief is not limited to the layman. It is also shared by 
many psychologists (those who believe that emotion, hunger, 
and pain in the leg are mental phenomena) to say nothing of 
the Gestalt psychologists who think that the patterns of figure 
and ground are matters of experience. But it does not de- 
volve upon my shoulders to resolve these controversies among 
the psychologists ! It is my responsibility rather to make clear 
the anthroponomist's position on this question of what is to 
be done with the "physical" environment as described by Bent- 
ley. Perhaps no other single question has so puzzled those 

*, p. 38. 
*, p. 38-9. 



88 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

who have sought to understand or to criticize the behavioristic 
positions. However, I must not pass on to this phase of the 
exposition of behaviorism until I am more certain that you 
have understood the points involved in my quotations from 
Bentley. 

Psychologists may be divided roughly into two camps on the 
basis of their treatment of meaning. One camp, represented 
by the Wundtian tradition, excludes meaning from observable 
mental phenomena. The other camp, represented by such di- 
verse tendencies as are present in the image-less thought psy- 
chologists, the functionalists, the purposivists, and the Gestalt 
psychologists, includes meaning. The result is that the Wundt- 
ians, speaking through Bentley, would say that the meaning- 
users are describing physical objects ; and the meaning-users re- 
tort that the Wundtians are dealing with non-existent artifacts. 
As for me, I almost agree with both schools ! I think nothing 
could be more barren than the Wundt-Titchener-Bentley psy- 
chology. It does not describe concrete things seen, heard, or 
felt as these exist in the inner, i.e., the sub-cutaneous, environ- 
ment. Nor does it give us a description of something mental 
which actually exists. And, if I agree that the Wundtian psy- 
chology is barren, I also agree that the other psychologists are 
not describing conscious processes, experience, when they des- 
cribe books, pains, hungers, tastes, colors, and melodies. Per- 
haps these phenomena are more properly labeled physical, but in 
any case they are the constituents of the inner and outer envir- 
onments as viewed by common-sense. Both groups of psycholo- 
gists are seeking to understand a phase of human nature by the 
indirect route of environment. Bentley and the other Wundt- 
ians abstract qualities, intensities, durations, and clearnesses 
(sometimes adding other attributes, sometimes dropping one 
or more) from the environment and call the material selected 
experience. The users of meaning take concrete objects from 
the environment and call these experience. If this is the path 
followed by the psychologists in attempting to throw light upon 
the nature of man, what is to be said of that followed by the 
students of behavior, the anthroponomists ? 

The anthroppnomist does not deny the existence of the com- 
mon-sense environment. He refuses, however, to be diverted 
from the direct study of man into the recording of environ- 
mental peculiarities. If you were to ask an anthroponomist to 
describe a certain room in the Clark laboratory, he would re- 
spond as follows: "The walls of the room are pale blue, the 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 89 

ceiling is white, and the floors are brown. A large grey-toned 
rug is upon the floor. The furniture is of a golden color ; it is 
heavy and hard. Upon entering this room in the morning, a 
stale odor is easily detected, and one is at times disgusted by 
this odor." It must not be assumed that I am the only student 
of behavior who would admit the existence of such an internal 
and external environment as I have just described. 
Would anyone venture to suggest that Weiss would 
deny hearing the tuning forks with which he has 
worked, or that Lashley would refuse to say that he had 
seen and touched the brains of white rats? If you will turn 
to an article written by Carr 8 in 1912, you will find that Wat- 
son is definitely on record as having seen environmental objects 
of the after-image type. Let me quote some extracts from 
Carr's account: "After serving as a subject in a test involving 
considerable eye fatigue, Professor Watson was engaged in 
carefully and steadily observing one of the writer's eyes 
throughout several periods of five to six minutes duration each. 
The room was pitch dark with the exception that the observed 
eye was illumined by a minature electric flashlight .... 

"After one of these observations, the flashlight was turned 
off for a period of rest Shortly afterwards there developed 
in the darkness an extremely vivid and realistic positive after- 
image of the eye .... All of the minor details of coloring 
and marking came out distinctly .... Just before the lights 
were turned on an added tinge of reality was produced" when 
the phantom eye actually winked. 

"Professor Watson has had considerable practice in the ob- 
servation of after-images and is, apparently, more than ordin- 
arily sensitive to the phenomenon." 

If these statements are not sufficient for you, a brief in- 
spection of the writings of any behavorist will convince you 
that he is neither blind, deaf, anosmic, ageusic, or anaesthetic. 
He lives, and admits quite frankly that he lives, in the same 
world of objects and events which the psychologist and the 
layman alike acknowledge. Let us, therefore, hear no more 
from the psychologist that his opponent denies the existence 
of these things. 

One of the objects in the environment which the anthropono- 
mist sees, hears, feels, and smells is called homo sapiens, man. 
The various members of this species differ in height, weight, 
color, cleanliness, race, religion, etc., etc., just as rocks differ 

8 Carr, H. A. Some novel experiences. Psych. Rev., 1912, 19, 60S1. 



90 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

in size, weight, density, chemical constitution, age, location, 
commercial value, etc. The anthroponomist takes man as his 
experimental material just as the other scientists select other 
objects in the environment for their experimental material. 
Now neither the anthroponomist, the psychologist, the chemist, 
the physicist, nor the biologist can tell you what a man or a 
rock is, for like all events in the world each is in some way 
unique. Various hypotheses have been proposed, but it is 
too early to separate those which are susceptible to scientific 
verification from those which are not. Bentley says that the 
rocks and the men which I see are physical objects. The 
meaning-users say these objects are experiences and therefore 
mental. But neither of the terms is really an answer to the 
question. They are merely names used in order to include 
or exclude certain phenomena from the science. You must 
never^ forget that, when the psychologists accuse the behavior- 
ists of denying the existence of a part of the world, the psy- 
chologists ignore certain facts: (1) that the behaviorist only 
denies that any one has shown the psychic, mental, character 
of the environment; and (2) that the behaviorist himself has 
offered at least three hypotheses concerning the nature of this 
environment. These three hypotheses are as follows: First, 
the electron-proton hypothesis of Weiss. 9 Weiss accepts and 
note that Bentley must follow, too, if he is logical the most 
recent advances in physics and chemistry which go to show 
that objects in our environment are electron-proton aggrega- 
tions. Stones, tables, books, storms, silver, and gold are ulti- 
mately electric charges. And so likewise is the human animal 
and the aggregations of human animals which make up so- 
ciety. If the phenomenon of a storage battery is a matter 
of electrons and protons, so is the phenomenon of family life 
unless the physicists are all wrong, or unless there is something 
in family life which is not an object in the external or in- 
ternal environment. Personally, I think that Weiss is un- 
doubtedly correct. I see no immediate way or need, however, 
to apply this principle to change our experimentation* All 
of our anthroponomical experimentation is in harmony with 
this theory. This, furthermore, is exactly the case in physics. 
Many problems in that science are attacked and solved with- 
out involving in any specific way the electron-proton conception 
of the nature of the universe. Even in physics it is still per- 

p Weiss, A. P. A theoretical basis of human behavior. Columbus, 
Ohio, 1925. 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 91 

missible to speak of steel and carbon and to make studies upon 
these substances without directly involving the question of the 
nature of the atom. The psychologist should, therefore, not 
reproach Weiss if the latter continues speaking of bio-social 
responses instead of attempting to state the molecular activities 
which make up these responses. 

The second hypothesis concerning the nature of the environ- 
ment is that of Lashley. 10 Lashley speaks of the environment 
as consciousness, conscious content, or quality, following an 
old tradition of the psychologist, and consciousness for him is 
"a complex integration and succession of bodily activities which 
are closely related to or involve the verbal and gestural me- 
chanisms and hence most frequently come to social expression." 
Lashley also stresses the ultimate physico-chemical nature of 
these bodily integrations. 

The third hypothesis concerning the nature of environmental 
objects is my own. 11 In a series of articles, I have recently 
elaborated the hypothesis that red, sweet, salt, emotion, books, 
trees, and storms are all cases of a particular stimulus-response 
relationship. This particular bit of behavior is the irreversible 
SP-LR relationship. (The letters stand for sensory process 
and language response.) The present lecture is hardly the 
place to offer you a resume of these papers. It will perhaps 
be worth our while, however, to give a brief explanation of 
the hypothesis inasmuch as it bears specifically upon our present 
problem, the subject matter of the science of psychology and 
anthroponomy, as well as upon the problem of the nature of 
the methods used in these disciplines. 

Let us apply our hypothesis to the case where new environ- 
mental objects make their appearance as this occurs when hith- 
erto undifferentiated overtones of a clang are "reported" by 
the subject. "The beginner in the psychology laboratory does 
not hear these overtones, although physics can demonstrate 
that correlated vibrations exist in the stimulus. The subject is 
not 'conscious* of the tones, at least he makes no verbal re- 
port of their presence and for scientific purposes he is said 

"Lashley, K. S. The foehavioristic interpretation, of consciousness, I 
and II. Psychol. Rev., 1925, 30, 237 and 329. 
n Hunter, W. S. The problem of consciousness. Psychol. Rev., 
1924, 31, 1-31. 

The symbolic process. Ibid, 1924, 31, 478-497. 
The subject's report. Ibid, 1925, 32, 153-170. 
General anthroponomy and its systematic prob- 
lems. Amer. Jour. Psychol., 1925, 36, 286-302. 



92 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

to be unaware of them. The experimenter now presents the 
vibration frequency of the first overtone (SP) by itself. This 
stimulus elicits response LR. SP is then presented as a part 
of a complex stimulus in order to see whether or not the same 
response, LR, will now appear. If it does not, the training is 
continued. Just as soon as the verbal response, LR, is made to 
the complex stimulus, just so soon does the subjectivist say 
that the 'consciousness of the overtone' is present . . . Why 
do we not say that LR is the subjectivisms 'consciousness 5 and 
not merely a criterion of its presence? Because LR, if it is to 
be rated as 'conscious/ must in its turn have a language re- 
sponse conditioned to it and so be the beginning part of [an 
SP-LR] situation. Only in the irreversible situation do we 
have 'consciousness.' It now becomes a fertile field of ex- 
perimentation to determine what stimulus aspects may be de- 
terminers of language responses and not merely of non-lan- 
guage responses. The irreversible relationships between these 
stimulus aspects and the language responses will then be 'states 
of consciousness/ 

"We have chosen the two cases of the lower limen of sensi- 
tivity and the discrimination of component aspects of a com- 
plex situation, as the most vital aspects of adult human nature 
upon which to base our formulation, for a very definite reason. 
If it were possible we should follow the truly genetic method 
in the establishment of our thesis as well as in its application. 
There are, however, no well established facts concerning the 
'consciousness* of infants and children, so that we must of ne- 
cessity test our conception upon adults. When, however, we 
examine that situation at this age level, it is found that the 
phenomenon termed 'consciousness/ although very generally 
conceded to exist, is very complex and has a long history in 
the individual's lifetime. We must therefore select for analy- 
sis the most definite, least ambiguous, and most experimentally 
inviting of the instances where 'consciousness' is extended or 
where new 'consciousness* arises. Having arrived at our formu- 
lation upon this basis, its adequacy and, therefore, its truth 
can be tested by examining its harmony with certain accepted 
data gathered from adults, children and infra-human animals 
and by observing the extent and vitality of the experimental 
implications of the conception. 

"In the two fundamental cases of conscious limen with which 
we have dealt, nothing has been found which does not come 
under our formulation. These cases, while convincing, may 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTKROPONOMY 93 

nevertheless not be thought crucial. If so, then the critical 
case for the formulation is the following : Can a receptor which 
does not normally condition 'consciousness' be made to do so? 
Stated from our point of view as a matter for scientific verifi- 
cation: Can activity in a receptor which does not normally 
condition a language response be made to do so by training? 
To be sure we have almost shown that this is possible to a 
limited degree, for the so-called subliminal receptor activities do 
not normally condition language activities. Perhaps the really 
crucial case comes with receptors all of whose activities psy- 
chology now treats as permanently subliminal to 'consciousness/ 
Can the receptors in the viscera which do not condition 'sensa- 
tion 3 be made to do so by training? Only positive results can 
be crucial, for the everyday training of the subject may have 
resulted in connecting with language responses all of the differ- 
ent kinds of receptors which it is possible to connect. All that 
training may be able to do may be of the order discussed above. 
This, however, is a matter for experiment and not for theory 
to decide. 12 - 13 

Such are the anthroponomists' hypotheses concerning the 
nature of environmental objects, hypotheses which are mutually 
supporting and not antagonistic one to the other. Let us turn 
now to a consideration of the subject matter of the science 
as this problem concerns the classification of the sciences of 
psychology and anthroponomy, on the one hand, and the sci- 
ences of physics, chemistry, mathematics, and biology, on the 
other hand. 

I have said that the environmental object, selected for study 
by the anthroponomist, is man. And yet the anthroponomist 
does not attempt to study all phases of man. Anthroponomy is 
the science of the behavior of the human organism as a whole. 
The problems of this science necessarily cover a wide range. 

"Psychol. Rev., 1924, 31, pp. 15-17. 

"Watson misinterprets this hypothesis when he says in "Behavior- 
ism," Peoples Institute Publishing Co., 1925, p. Ill, "Professor Wai- 
ter S. Hunter in his superhuman efforts to straddle the gulf that 
divides behaviorism from introspectionism uses the verb 'to be' in a 
.... mystical way when he says certain types of bodily response 
ARE consciousness." The hypothesis which I have sketched seeks 
to state the nature of the observable fact which the psychologists 
have called consciousness. This is no more mystical than saying 
that the voice of God as heard in the thunder storm is merely a 
series of air-waves produced by the sudden coming together of 
great masses of air. Nor is it more mystical than Watson's own 
identification of emotion with pattern reactions which terminate 
within the body. 



94 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Some are shared with the related sciences of sociology, physi- 
ology, neurology, physics, chemistry and mathematics, while 
other problems are studied little if at all outside of anthropon- 
omy. These latter problems concern the characteristics which 
most specifically define human nature, vis., the learning and 
use of new forms of response, language behavior, and social 
behavior, which latter we call the behavior of inter-stimulation 
and response. Anthroponomy thus takes its place among the 
sciences which study specific objects in the environment. Here 
also belong such disciplines as botany which studies plants, 
geology which specializes upon the inorganic structure of the 
earth, and physiology, where the functional activities of the 
various structures of the body become the subject matter for 
investigation. In contrast to this group of sciences, which is 
characterized by the study of specific environmental objects, 
stands the group specializing upon those fundamental and gen- 
eral characteristics which are thought to be essential to all 
environmental objects. Here belong at present only mathe- 
matics, physics, and chemistry. Chemistry and physics analyze, 
synthesize, weigh, and measure men, rats, rocks, gases, light, 
and other objects in search of the fundamental general proper- 
ties of nature. Mathematics seeks to write formulae for all 
processes whether they occur in the rat or in light. Geology, 
however, focuses its efforts upon the earth, and in attempting 
to solve this problem, it draws upon any science that offers the 
slightest help. Physics, chemistry, and mathematics are geolo- 
gy's most useful assistants, because in solving general problems 
of nature, they have incidentally solved many of the geologist's 
own problems. The science of anthroponomy, we have said, 
belongs in the group with geology, physiology, botany and 
the other specific sciences. Man's learned behavior, his lan- 
guage responses, and his social activities are events in nature, 
in the environment, and as such they are partially illuminated 
by the general laws of mathematics, physics, and chemistry* 
This illumination, to be sure, is less than is desirable, but this 
is true in the relation of each science of organic processes to 
the group of general sciences. 

I think we can now see the purport of those hypotheses con- 
cerning the nature of the environment which the students of 
human behavior have offered. Weiss's statement that such 
objects as white rats, red cows, tones, pains, and marital be- 
havior are electron-proton combinations is merely the recogni- 
tion that, if the contemporary general sciences of mathematics, 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 95 

physics, and chemistry are correct, we may ultimately write the 
results of anthroponomy in terms of mathematical formulas. 
Lashley's hypothesis and my own deal less with the future and 
more with the present. They, therefore, seek to state environ- 
mental happenings in relation to man's action system when this 
latter is viewed as another object in the common-sense envi- 
ronment. 

Let us now return to the subject of psychology and see , 
where its adherents would place it in relation to the other 
sciences. Titchener says that psychology and physics deal with 
the same world of experience, but from two very different 
points of view. Psychology studies the world with man left 
in it, i.e., it studies experience as dependent upon the nervous 
system, whereas physics studies experience as though existing 
independently of the nervous system. Psychology should, there- 
fore, be classified with the general sciences as a discipline lay- 
ing bare the general traits of mind, where mind is denned as 
"the sum-total of human experience considered as dependent 
upon a nervous system." 14 If we substitute the terms inner 
and outer environment for experience, the statement then reads : 
psychology studies the total environment viewed as existing 
only at the moment when it affects the (human) nervous sys- 
tem, whereas physics studies the total environment viewed as 
existing beyond the moment when it affects the (human) nerv- 
ous system. I have read statements of this point of view for 
many years, and I will confess that for a goodly portion of 
that time the statements seemed just and reasonable. I no 
longer think so. The statements now seem vague and full of 
doubtful implications even as a description of psychology. The 
reasonable aspect of the statement seems to me to come from 
the tacit recognition of the stimulus-response relationship 
which exists between the total environment and the human 
organism. 

So far I have yet to see psychologists engaged in studying 
thermometers, stones, water, oxygen, or the relation of accelera- 
tion to time in a falling body. And on the other hand, I have 
yet to read a physicist's account of the learning process. 
"Ah, but/' you say, "there is no reason why the psychologist 
may not study the one group of phenomena and the physicist 
the other." And I answer: When the psychologists begin to 
tudy the thermometers and other objects mentioned, except 
as stimuli determining man's behavior, their days will be even 
more definitely numbered than they are at present, for it will 

"Titchener, E. B. Textbook of psychology. New York, 1910, p. 16. 



96 PSYCHOLOGIES QF 1925 

no longer be so easy to convince us that this is the way to 
understand man. From the point of view which we are now 
considering, if I put a thermometer into a vessel and observe 
the consequent rise of the mercury, I am said to perform a 
physical experiment. On the other hand, if I put a pneumo- 
graph on a human subject and observe the changes in breath- 
ing while the subject does silent arithmetic, the psychologist 
claims the experiment. Why? Neither is a study of experience 
viewed as dependent upon the human nervous system. So far 
as the physicist is concerned, to revert to our above question, 
of course he may study the learning process since his is a 
general science of the fundamental laws of the environment, 
but he can study the learning process only as dependent upon 
the human nervous system because much of the learning pro- 
cess occurs there. Not even the physicist can describe the 
learning process as it might be independently of the "experi- 
encing organism/' i. e., the organism reacting to stimuli. But 
again you interrupt me to point out that the nervous system 
to be considered from Titchener's standpoint is not the one in 
which the learning-modifications occur, but the one possessed 
by the observer who is making the study. Can not the physi- 
cist, theoretically at least, be expected to describe the funda- 
mental changes in the organism which are involved in learning 
and would this description not be held valid even for an 
isolated man on an island in the Pacific Ocean ? How happy I 
am that you raised this question! Of course the physicist 
may solve this problem, but Titchener cannot incorporate such 
significant data into his science, whereas anthroponomy has a 
place waiting for just such results. What Titchener means by 
"dependent upon the nervous system" is something quite sub- 
tle and not at all the crude fact that practically all relations 
between man and his environment ("experience") are mediated 
by a nervous system. This is where the concept of "con- 
scious" processes slips into his psychology. "Experience 
viewed as dependent upon a nervous system" means, in fact, 
for him experience as observed and as conscious. As Titchen- 
er says: "We assume that everybody knows, at first hand,, 
what human experience is, and we then seek to mark off the 
two aspects of this experience which are dealt with respectively 
by physics and psychology. Any further definition of the sub- 
ject-matter of psychology is impossible. Unless one knows, 
by experience itself, what experience is, one can no more give 
a meaning to the term 'mind' than a stone can give a meaning 
to the term 'matter.' " 15 

"Ibid, p. 9. 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 97 

Even anthroponomy might be defined as a study of the 
environment with man left in, but we should want to place 
the emphasis upon man and not upon the environment. 
And we should not find it necessary to introduce any form of 
the conscious. 16 

We are thus brought back to the starting point of this lec- 
ture. Psychology is an indirect method of studying man, 
while anthroponomy is a direct method. The baffling ques- 
tions concerning the nervous system which we have discussed 
above belong, therefore, to psychology. They are not involved 
in anthroponomy, for anthroponomy is a specific science of 
man and not a general science of the mental aspect of a psy- 
chophysical world or of psychosomatic processes. 

Let us turn now to the second problem which we are to 
consider: What are the chief methods employed by the two 
sciences? Psychology has two methods uf gathering data. 
One is individualistic, and the other is social. One is held to 
be less, and the other more scientifically fruitful. The first, 
or individualistic, method is utilized whenever one person un- 
dertakes to observe experience and build a science upon these 
observations. This method has given rise to the old arm- 
chair variety of psychology, and yet the method has never been 
repudiated as is evidenced by such a statement as this from 
Calkins: "The method has obvious advantages. It makes no 
especial conditions of time and place ; it requires no mechanical 
adjunct; it demands no difficult search for suitable material; 
at any moment, in all surroundings, with no external outfit, 
one may study the rich material provided by every imaginable 
experience. In an extreme sense, all is grist that comes 
to the psychologist's mill/' 17 That the method has not 
been repudiated is due to the fact that the data gath- 
ered by it form the basis for the interpretation 

of the results secured by the social method. Remember 

_______ -___^_ ^ 

M The discussion of the subject matter of psychology has been, 
based upon the views of the Wundtians because they have stated 
their position on conscious processes, or experience, more clearly 
and specifically than others. All psychologists study conscious pro- 
cesses, but many of them mix the processes up with behavior in 
such an inextricable way that their writings do not offer _ clear- 
cut statements concerning experience. The fundamental criticisms 
which we have directed against psychology are aimed at all psychol- 
ogies, 'because all psychologies have in common the indirect method 
of studying man however much they may differ in the extent to 
which they also use behavioristic data. 

"Calkins, M. W. A first book in psychology. New York, 1914, p. 7. 



98 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

that the psychologist says : "We assume that everybody knows, 
at first hand, what experience is .... Unless one knows 

. . one can no more give meaning to the term 'mind* than a 
stone can give meaning to the term 'matter/ " 

The second, or social, method of psychology is utilized 
wherever an experimenter utilizes subjects other than himself. 
Let me illustrate this method in a simple way. First, I take 
one blue paper disc and one black paper disc. These I mount 
upon the spindle of a rotating wheel in the proportion of three 
blue to one black. The wheel is set in rapid rotation, and my 
subjects are called in one at a time. I point to the discs and 
say, "What color quality is that?" Each subject responds in 
turn. "A dark, poorly saturated blue." If I change the propor- 
tion of blue and black, my subjects report differently. These are 
the observable facts upon which both psychologists and anthro- 
ponomists can agree, and yet notice how different are the 
interpretations placed upon these facts. The anthroponomist 
says in a very matter of fact way, "It looks as though the 
behavior of your subjects was controlled by a change in the 
visual stimulus, when your instructions remained constant. 
This suggests to me that man reacts to blue light of various 
intensities. It might now be well to state the visual stimulus in 
physical terms of wave length and energy in order that we 
may know more exactly just what the visual stimulus is and 
thereby help some one else in his efforts to repeat our observa- 
tion." The psychologist interprets the experiment as follows : 
"Each subject has an immediate experience of color quality, 
intensity, and saturation. This inference is justified because 
we are all men and because I know that under the same con- 
ditions I have these experiences and use the same words to 
describe them. Let us by all means get the physical measure- 
ments suggested in order that later observers may be certain 
to get^this rare experience." This interpretation by the psy- 
chologist makes us more certain than ever that the task which 
he has undertaken is that of describing the total environment 
as it appears to man and not that of describing some funda- 
mental aspect of man himself. "But," you say, "if I know 
the complete description of the, inner and outer environment 
as experienced by each man, can I not draw important con- 
clusions concerning man?" Oh, the sly psychologist! This 
is another of the plausible arguments by which he seeks to 
convert the unwary! How can he know the experience of 
another subject? Philosophy, psychological definition, and 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 99 

poetry have dosed that door to us. Listen to the way in 
which the poet formulates the situation: 
"Yes: in the sea of life enisl'd, 
With echoing straits between us thrown, 
Dotting the shoreless watery wild, 
We mortal millions live alone. 

The islands feel the enclasping flow, 
And then their endless bounds they know. 
* * * * 

"A God, a God their severance rul'd; 
And bade betwixt their shores to be 
The unplumb'd, salt, estranging sea." 

And, then, if the psychologist wants to draw conclusions 
concerning man, why does he not study man directly without 
all this effort at reconstructing the environment as seen by 
another? Perhaps at one time in my lecture you thought it 
might be fascinating to go with a friend on a Cook's tour, 
conducted by a psychologist, through the realm of experience, 
there to try all things at least once and to learn how many 
wonderful melodies could be played upon the human organism. 
Alas, there is no chance, for you must see the world yourself. 
The world as seen by others is closed to you! 

The science of psychology is built upon inferences concern- 
ing the environment. These inferences are drawn from the 
observable facts gathered by the social method of that science. 
Against this method, and, therefore, against this science, I 
raise these objections: (1) An unnecessary and an impossible 
task is undertaken in attempting to reconstruct the environ- 
ment as it appears to adult man, to children, and to animals. 
(2) The genetic point of approach, which has already proved 
valuable in understanding nature, requires that our investiga- 
tion of man begin with the simpler stimulus-response prob- 
lems and extend to the more complex ones later when we have 
mastered our technique. (3) The psychologist limits himself 
to observing the language responses of his subjects because 
this behavior is bound up so closely with the discriminable 
aspects of the environment. These language responses are 
admittedly late in appearance in the animal world, and yet the 
psychologist utilizes the language responses of adult members 
of European cultures in his hypothetical reconstruction of the 
environment not only of man but of all animals. By thus 
Umiting himself to the language situation, the psychologist 
omits much that is valuable in understanding both man and 



100 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



the environment. (4) The psychologist persistently violates 
one of the great canons of science when he fails to harm'dnise 
his problem to be investigated with the methods to be em- 
ployed. 

This last point I consider of the very greatest importance 
for the revision of psychological science. I must, therefore, 
comment upon it at some length. Let us revert, first, to the 
experiment with the blue and the black discs. The psychologi- 
cal problem is this: How does the experience of blueness 
change with the alteration of the relative proportions of blue 
and black on the color wheel? The experimental method in- 
volves stimidating the subject auditorily with instructions and 
visually with the colored discs. The subject's report is then 
recorded as it is manifested in behavior. The psychologist 
draws his conclusions in terms of experience, whereas I sub- 
mit that the only conclusion justified is that the subject 
behaves in a certain manner when stimulated in a certain way. 



FIGURE 1 

We may again illustrate the criticism by an experiment as 
conducted by the Gestalt psychologists. The problem is how 
does the subject see the lines of Figure L The method of 
solving this apparently simple problem is as before. The sub- 
ject is brought into the room. I stimulate his eyes with the 
lines of Figure 1 and give him auditory instructions. As a 
result the subject says, "I see four groups of two lines each. 
At one moment the line on the right stands alone, and at 
another moment the line on the left is without a partner." 
The Gestalt psychologist now concludes that the subject has 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 101 

an experience of groups, or of figure and ground. The be- 
haviorist would say that, when stimulated in this manner, the 
subject responds in at least two different ways. In neither 
of these experiments, however, would the behaviorist rest con- 
tent with formulating his problem merely in such a manner 
that the method available would bear upon the problem formu- 
lated. In each case he would further insist upon checking 
up his results using some other form of behavior than the 
verbal response of the subject. 

Suppose we turn now from the external to the internal en- 
vironment. Let the psychologist again state his problem. 
This time it will be as follows : What is the influence of the 
simple affective processes upon the knee-jerk? 18 (Or the 
problem might have been, how many affective quali- 
ties are there? In this case, the method would differ from 
what we are about to describe, but the same type of criticism 
would be applicable.) The method selected involves the use 
of an apparatus for eliciting the knee-jerk and of certain "in- 
different, pleasant, and unpleasant" words. When the sub- 
ject's eyes are stimulated by the words and when he is stimu- 
lated auditorily in the proper way, he says, "Pleasant." We 
now proceed to apply the visual stimuli simultaneously with the 
tap on the patellar tendon. The results recorded indicate the 
magnitude of the knee-jerk under the several conditions. The 
psychologist thereupon concludes that pleasantness and un- 
pleasantness did or did not affect the response in question. 

Had a student of behavior used this method, the problem 
would have been formulated directly in terms of the method, 
as follows : What is the influence of visual word-stimuli upon 
the patellar tendon reflex under such and such conditions? 
The fundamental error in the psychologist's procedure is that 
the problems formulated and the conclusions drawn can have 
no real bearing upon the methods employed and the re- 
sults secured, since the psychologist takes as his general prob- 
lem the reconstruction of his subject's environment and not 
the study of his behavior. When problems are formulated 
in terms of available methods, the scientist is much less prone 
to spend his energies in the fruitless effort to solve problems 
which at the present moment lie far beyond the best available 
technique. The student of behavior is not altogether guilt- 
less here, for occasionally he also formulates problems which 

"Btirtt, H. E. and Tuttle, W. W. The patellar tendon reflex and 
affective tone. Amer. Jour. Psychol., 1925, 36, 553-561. 



102 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

are quite unrelated to the methods employed in their solution. 
The difference between such a mistake on the part of a be- 
haviorist and a similar mistake made by a psychologist lies 
in the fact that, by the definition of the subject matter and 
goal of his science, the psychologist is forever committed to 
this error, while in the case of the behaviorist only a momen- 
tary lapse from rigid scientific method has occurred. 

In the description and criticism of the psychologist's 
methods, we have by implication given many of the character- 
istics of the methods used by the anthroponomist. It is only 
fitting and proper, however, that we should describe certain 
characteristics of these methods more in detail. As in psycho- 
logy, so in anthroponomy, chief reliance is placed upon the 
social method as a method of gathering data. The anthropon- 
omist will at times work upon himself as subject, but he ap- 
preciates the great difficulty of controlling and checking many 
factors which influence behavior where the subject and the 
experimenter are one, and he absolutely refuses to use this in- 
dividualistic method as the basis for interpreting the results of 
his scientific labors. The methods of the anthroponomist al- 
ways involve the presentation of stimuli and the consequent 
arousal of behavior in the subject. Sometimes one stimulus 
is emphasized in the experimental situation so that this stim- 
ulus finally may be said to control the behavior. Sometimes 
the subject is merely placed in a general environmental situa- 
tion and his behavior observed. So far as is practical, the 
specific stimuli which determine the behavior are recorded and 
the experimenter notes what seem to him to be the important 
aspects of the response. Where the conclusion is drawn that 
the red stimulus, in a red-green discrimination experiment, 
e. g., controls the behavior, there is no implication that the 
red stimulus is effective by itself. Many other stimuli are co- 
operating, particularly stimuli from the stomach of the hungry 
subject and stimuli from the muscles and skin. The conclu- 
sion, in reality, is that, under these experimental conditions 
where the stimuli from the skin, muscles, viscera, ears, etc., 
are kept constant, the deciding factor in controlling the re- 
sponse is the wave-length difference between the two visual 
stimuli. To be sure there are configurations of stimuli at work 
and the organism does act as a whole, but under the conditions 
of the experiment described, the most significant conclusion 
to be drawn refers to the stimulus which plays the deciding 
role. Wherever it can be shown that the subject's behavior 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 103 

is controlled by a particular grouping of stimuli, that con- 
clusion should be drawn. Any other use of the Gestalt con- 
cept seems unnecessary. 

This brief discussion of the stimulus-response nature of be- 
havioristic experiments leads me to state three further points : 
( 1 ) The psychologist conducts exactly similar experiments, but 
he is so engrossed in his effort to reconstruct the subject's 
environment and so hypnotized by the significance of lan- 
guage behavior that he slurs over the essential character of 
his observed facts in his desire to attain the goal which he 
has set himself. If Burtt and Tuttle, for example, had real- 
ized that, in dealing with their so-called affective processes, 
they were dealing with a bit of behavior, the first step that 
would have been taken would have been to assure themselves 
that this particular bit of (visceral?) behavior was present. 
Having shown its presence as a result of the word stimuli, they 
could then have studied the f acilitory and inhibitory relations 
between this behavior and the knee-jerk. (2) Some psycholo- 
gists have said that the behaviorist, when he uses the stimulus- 
response concept, ignores the contribution which the organism 
makes to the nature of the behavior. This seems to me to be 
a remarkably uncalled-for accusation. Has not the behavior- 
ist always appealed to the results of heredity and previous 
training as factors which cooperate with present stimuli in de- 
termining behavior? Was there ever a behaviorist who ex- 
plained maze behavior without calling upon the retained effects 
of previous training for a part of his explanation, or a behav- 
iorist who ignored childhood peculiarities in accounting for 
adult behavior? (3) The third point concerns the psycholo- 
gist's criticism of the behaviorist's use of the stimulus-response 
category. By what right, so the criticism goes, does the an- 
throponomist say, "I used a red light as the stimulus/' or "I 
trained the subject using a cube and a sphere as stimuli." Since 
the behaviorist accepts the theories of physics and chemistry as 
adequate for the explanation of nature, it is said that all stim- 
uli should be stated by him in terms of these sciences. This 
criticism ignores the fact that the behaviorist, like the physi- 
cist, accepts a common-sense view of the environment as the 
milieu for his experimentation. This we have been at great 
pains to point out earlier in the present lecture. The anthro- 
ponomist has no more hesitancy in saying that he gave water 
to his chicks in order to see whether they would drink than 
a chemist has in saying that he has completed the analysis of 



104 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

water into H 2 O. The chemist does not find it necessary to drop 
the word water and substitute for it some electron-proton sub- 
stitute. Wherever the situation demands that the wave lengths 
of light, the vibration frequencies of sound, and the chemical 
constituents of odorous substances be stated, the behaviorist 
meets the demand, but not otherwise. As anthroponomy ad- 
vances to ever more and more rigorous experimentation, it is 
to be expected that such specifications of the stimuli and of 
the organic conditions will occur more and more frequently. 
Until that time, let us proceed in a matter of fact way, suit- 
ing our specifications to the practical needs of the moment. 

It would be a hopeless task to canvas in one lecture all of 
the points at issue between psychology and anthroponomy. 
We shall, therefore, limit ourselves in the remainder of our 
discussion to a brief statement concerning the third problem 
formulated above, "What are the results of the science?" 
With reference to anthroponomy it only need be said that the 
results secured bear directly upon the nature of the human in- 
dividual as he is found working in the fields, bathing in the surf, 
or pursuing his intricate way in the great cities of Earth. The 
anthroponomist himself specializes more upon language be- 
havior, learned responses, and the facts of inter-stimulation 
and response than any other scientist, and in addition he co- 
operates with others in the study of various additional aspects 
of man in so far as these affect organic behavior. All of 
these results are possible without omitting from the resulting 
picture of human nature any observable and verifiable datum. 
The anthroponomist even goes further and offers various hypo- 
theses concerning the nature of the inner and outer environ- 
ments as these are reported by his subjects. Nowhere is it 
necessary to introduce the concept of consciousness, or ex- 
perience, conceived as another mode of existence, or as an- 
other aspect of the physical world. 

The psychologist thinks that he secures two types of re- 
sults, one he assumes concerns consciousness, or experience, 
and the other we all agree is behavior. The behavioristic re- 
sults of the Wundtians have been deplorably slight in amount 
when one considers that most of their experiments have in- 
volved stimulus-response situations in a subject other than 
the experimenter. The adherents of biological functionalism 
have been more fortunate in their results in spite of their theory 
that mind is an instrument of adjustment in the struggle for 
existence. This outcome of their work has been possible 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 105 

because their systematic point of view has encouraged the 
direct study of man. It is only to be regretted that they have 
mixed up experience and behavior so thoroughly that the con- 
clusions which they have drawn from their experimental work 
must in many cases be rejected, and in many cases the work 
must be done over under the guidance of another systematic 
point of view. No combination of "experience" and behav- 
ior is necessary or possible in the accurate portrayal of human 
nature. If we consider the results secured by the most con- 
sistent and logical students of (so-called) consciousness, the 
followers of the Wundtian tradition, we see that these results 
consist of a vast array of least discriminable aspects of ex- 
perience, blueness, tonality, contact, pain, sweet, noisiness, in- 
tensity, clearness, duration, and others. 

When we turn to the new school of Gestalt psychologists, 
we find that experimental results are stated in terms of unique 
configurations and not in terms of the abstract and highly arti- 
ficial products of the Wundtian school. This is an advantage 
to the extent that new aspects of the environment are discov- 
ered, an advantage, i. e., if we think that the way to understand 
man is through a study of the environment. As yet the Ge- 
stalt movement has not worked far enough into the problems 
of systematic psychology to reveal just how it will treat these 
problems of general theory. The movement so far has been 
limited largely to the field of "perception" and to an elabora- 
tion of the concept of the organism as a whole. Sooner or 
later, however, it must face the many other problems of clas- 
sical psychology, as these appear in such questions as : the na- 
tures and inter-relations of "perception," "imagination," "af- 
fection," "attention," and "thinking." I can see no evidence 
as yet which would lead me to believe that Gestalt psychology 
as a science of "experience" will escape many of the cul-de- 
sacs into which the psychology of discriminable aspects of 
experience has fallen. After all, a Gestalt is merely another 
unique but more complex aspect of the environment. And it 
will be just as difficult for the adherents of that point of 
view to classify and synthesize unique Gestalten as for their 
opponents to synthesize unique elements or unique least dis- 
criminable aspects of the universe. 

It is sometimes said by Gestalt psychologists that the chief 
result to be obtained by their method of approach to psychology 
is an insight into the neural processes of man and that the 
study of Gestalten is merely a means to this end. Kohler in 



106 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

particular has emphasized this, and he has in addition sought 
in a brilliant way to apply the principles of physics to the 
problems of neural processes. There is much, therefore, in 
Kohler's psychology which is in harmony with Loeb's tradi- 
tion in biology and with Weiss's theories in anthroponomy. 
And yet, in spite of this, I cannot react optimistically toward 
such a program for two reasons: (1) Ever since the days of 
Wundt's physiological psychology, the students of psychol- 
ogy have sought neural correlates for complex as well as for 
simple experiences with little or no success. On what grounds, 
therefore, are we to expect better success from the attempt 
when made by the Gestalt psychologists? To be sure they 
will propose theoretical neural functions different from the 
ones proposed by the Wundtians. So much is certain, be- 
cause the Gestalt psychologists are seeking neural correlates 
for Gestalten and not for the least discriminable aspects of 
experience. (2) My second reason for pessimism with ref- 
erence to the attempt to dissect neural functions by means of 
environmental studies is the same as my reason for rejecting 
a science which studies human nature by means of analyses 
of the environment. Why all this indirectness? If one wishes 
to study neural functions, why not study them directly ? Why 
not begin where the physiologist has left off and carry on from 
that point? The work of Franz, Lashley, and Coghili will 
throw more light on neural functions than fifty years of spec- 
ulation by the Gestalt psychologists added to the fifty past 
years of Wundtian speculation, because Franz, Lashley, and 
Coghili are attacking their problems directly and in the light of 
the present -status of the sciences dealing with that problem. 
// the Gestalt psychologists are able to formulate an hypothesis 
which will be valuable in the understanding of neural function, 
it will be a result of the stimulus-response data which they will 
inevitably accumulate in their studies and not a result of the. 
experiential hypothesis with which they, like the Wundtians, 
burden their use of the social method of investigation. 

We have at last reached the end of the task assigned to us. 
So far as time has permitted, we have compared psychology 
and anthroponomy with reference to subject matter, methods, 
and results. The outcome, as I would have you see it, is that 
anthroponomy stands out as a common-sense, direct attack 
upon the problem of human nature, omitting no observable 
and verifiable datum from the picture. Psychology, on the 
other hand, is an indirect method of reaching the goal, an 



PSYCHOLOGY AND ANTHROPONOMY 107 

indirect method moreover which is inseparably bound up with 
the ancient philosophical concepts of mind and consciousness 
as aspects of the universe which differ from the physical. 
With this my work is done. It remains for you and those who 
follow to support the point of view which in your judgment 
offers the better possibility of reaching that intriguing goal, 
the understanding of human nature. 

"Our past is clean forgot, 
Our present is and is not, 
Our future's a sealed seedplot, 
And what betwixt them are we? 
We who say as we go, 

'Strange to think by the way, 
Whatever there is to know, 

That shall we know one day/ " 



PART II 

Dynamic Psychology 




ROIJERT S, Woonwoimi 



CHAPTER V 

DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY* 
BY ROBERT S. WOODWORTH 



The combination of words, "Dynamic Psychology," has not 
at present, and never has had, any great vogue. In compari- 
son with the "rational psychology" and "empirical psychology" 
of a century or two ago, with the "structural" and "function- 
al" psychology of twenty years ago, or with the "introspective" 
and "behavioristic" psychology, the "Gestalt" psychology or 
the "psychoanalysis" of the present time, "dynamic psychol- 
ogy" has an unfamiliar sound, and may well arouse the query, 
"What new iconoclasm is emerging into view?"In reality, how- 
ever, dynamic psychology is neither new nor revolutionary. 
It is an attempt to lay stress on certain problems which psych- 
ology has always regarded as belonging to it; or, in a more 
ambitious sense, is an attempt to characterize psychology as 
essentially a study in dynamics. 

Of the few authors who. have employed the phrase, some 
mean by "dynamic psychology" a part of the subject, while 
others mean to imply that psychology, when properly con- 
ceived, is- dynamic psychology. F. L. Wells has used the 
phrase as a convenient caption to cover studies of emotions, 
wishes, trends, conflicts and inhibitions. J. H. McCurdy has 
done the same. T. V. Moore limits the scope of his extensive 
and valuable treatment of "Dynamic Psychology" to the affec- 
tive and conative sides of mental life. 

On the other hand, C. L. Herrick, some twenty-five years 
ago, urged that psychology might well make use of dynamic 
concepts throughout its field of study. I myself, not many 
years since, while seeking to envisage psychology as a unitary 
enterprise, having a common aim in spite of great divergencies 
in the definitions proposed and the methods advocated, was led 
back to the now archaic phrase of the older psychologists, 
the "workings of the mind." That was what they said they 
proposed to study, and essentially the same, so it appears to 
me, is the aim of modern psychologists of all schools. We 
may dodge the futile questionings that attend the use of the 
word, "mind," and substitute "organism" or "individual." 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
December 12, 1925. 



112 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Then, to dodge physiology as well, we may simply explain 
that by organism we mean the organism as a whole, and per- 
haps we have reached as adequate a definition of our science 
as we can hope to attain for some time. At any rate, the 
phrase, "dynamic psychology" carries this notion of "work- 
ings/' and may serve as a reminder of the common aim of 
all psychologists. 

It is agreed on all sides that psychology studies processes.. 
What the behaviorist observes, and what the introspectionist 
observes, both come down to process, sequence of events.. 
Structure we observe only in the figurative sense in which a 
complex process may be said to have structure. We are con- 
cerned with antecedents and consequents, cause and effect, 
stimulus and response, the combination of factors and similar 
dynamic relations. 

Psychological dynamics is not limited to the study of feel- 
ing, emotion, conation and muscular and glandular action. We 
study also sensations as dependent upon their stimuli, we ana- 
lyze out the various factors in the perception of depth or dis- 
tance, we examine the process of learning, and formulate 
laws of association or recall. The whole subject is permeated 
with dynamics. 

Perception is a chapter in psychology that is especially in? 
need of dynamic concepts. A plurality of stimuli, as in a 
chord or clang or in McDougall's dot figure, gives rise to a 
unitary percept, such as recognition of the chord, hearing the 
timbre of an instrument, seeing a definite figure in a scatter 
of dots. Here is a real problem. How is the unitary percept 
related to the plurality of tones or dots? The associationists 
attempted a solution by introducing the concept of "simultan- 
eous association." Originally, association meant successive 
association, one idea calling up another, an antecedent event 
arousing a consequent. Simultaneous association means noth- 
ing more than that the elements are together. The dots are 
together in the field of view, the tones of the chord are heard 
together. Being together, they are said to be associated, and 
that is all there is to it. The explanation breaks down in face 
of the dot figure, since the assemblage of dots, when looked at 
steadily, takes on different groupings, one after another. The 
same is true of many other "ambiguous" figures. It is even 
true of the clang or chord, which may be heard in different 
ways, now centered about one of the constituent notes, now 
about another. There is more than a mere togetherness of 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 113 

the dots or notes ; there are groupings, and the same elements 
appear now in one grouping, now in another. The qualitative 
differences between the groupings are not accounted for by 
simultaneous associations. In fact, "association* does no 
more than call attention to the problem. Stimultaneous as- 
sociation is an undynamic concept, and part of the aim of 
dynamic psychology is to clear the decks of such concepts. 

Little, if anything, is gained by substituting the concept of 
synthesis, or of apperception, for that of association, Just a 
general synthetic activity of the subject, putting dots or tones 
together, really leaves the matter just as simultaneous associa- 
tion left it, and does not account in the least for the different 
perceptions that occur in face of the same assemblage of 
stimuli. What is needed is something specific, differing from 
moment to moment as the perception differs; 

The really dynamic concept to fit the case lies ready to hand, 
and is no other than the concept of stimulus and response. The 
dot figure, or other ambiguous figure, is a stimulus to which 
more than one response is possible. The plurality of stimuli, 
acting together, arouse the unitary response of seeing a parti- 
cular figure. Previous experience, and present internal condi- 
tions, are factors in determining which of the possible respon- 
ses shall be touched off at any moment. Here, as often in re- 
flex action, multiple stimuli converge upon a unitary response. 1 

This interpretation of perception evidently has much in com- 
mon with that of the Gestalt school. The figure or chord per- 
cept is conceived as a unit, almost as an element, and at least 
not as a sum or synthesis of elements. The dot figure percept 
is not composed of the dots .as elements, but can properly be 
called a unit in its own right. It can be prepared for as a 
unit, as when the subject looks for a certain figure in an as- 
semblage of dots; and, once present, it can function as a 
unit in suggesting something similar to itself or otherwise 
associated with itself. 

Mention should also be made of the important "complex 
theory" of Selz. 2 ("Complex" is here used in an entirely dif- 
ferent sense from that of the psychoanalysts). What func- 
tion as units in thinking and association are often not such 
"elements" as tones, colors, dots, or even words, but figures, 



*I have argued in the same vein in the Psychological Review. 
*Otto Selz, tJber die Gesetze des geordneten Denkverlaufs. Stutt- 
gart, 1913. 



114 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

chords, phrases and other similar "complexes." Selz proposes 
his complex theory as a substitute for the "constellation" 
theory. The difference, and the line of evidence which he 
adduces in favor of the complex theory, can be illustrated in 
the case of multiplication. 

When one is set to find products, the stimulus, "3 and 9," 
immediately arouses the response, "27," with no intrusion of 
the response "12," which, as the sum of the given numbers, is 
even more strongly associated with them than 27 is. The 
constellation theory explains that the actual response is the 
resultant of two tendencies, the associative tendency, which 
leads towards the sum, product, or any response habitually 
associated with the stimulus, and the determining tendency to 
find products. The explanation fails, since 12, which is firm- 
ly associated with the stimulus, "3 and 9," is also a product. 
The search for products would be satisfied with 12, since 12 
is the familiar product of 2 and 6, or 3 and 4 ; and the general 
associative tendencies would probably favor 12 over 27. Evi- 
dently 27 derives its advantage from the fact that it is, not 
simply a product, but the product of the given numbers. What 
the stimulus calls up, therefore, is, not simply numbers, but a 
"complex" such as "3 times 9 are 27." Such elementary parts 
of the multiplication table, though complex in a sense, are 
learned as units and function as units in the work of multipli- 
cation. The set to multiply puts into readiness, not numbers 
which happen to be products, but these elements of the multi- 
plication table. 

That figures, chords, and other such "complexes" are units, 
unitary responses, and function as units in perception and re- 
call, is essential to the dynamic theory of perception which I 
am trying to present. So far, this theory is in agreement with 
the Gestalt conceptions. But something more is essential to 
the dynamic theory. This something more may be made clear 
by reference to Dewey's critique of the doctrine of sensory 
elements. 

Dewey's criticism 8 follows the general line taken by James 4 
in his rejection of the analysis of sensations. James urged 
that when, by dint of previous training and by careful focus- 
ing of attention, an overtone is heard out of a clang, the clang 

John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct. New York, 1922. p. 31. 
*William James, Principles of Psychology, N. Y., 1890, I, pp. 602- 
504 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 115 

experience was not thereby analyzed, but a new experience 
was being obtained. The auditory stimulus remained the 
same, but a new response was made to this stimulus. One 
may admit that the stimulus has been analyzed, but not the 
sensation. Dewey adds this further consideration: the hear- 
ing out of the overtone, far from being a primitive type of 
reaction to the stimulus, is one that is only possible to a 
specially trained observer. How absurd, then, to take this 
highly sophisticated form of observation as furnishing the 
primitive elements of auditory experience! As experience, 
apart from the physical stimulus, the clang is more primitive 
than the overtones that are said to constitute the clang. 

Certainly this reasoning is cogent and pertinent. Yet one 
question remains: In the sequence of events that starts with 
the physical production of the fundamental and overtones, 
and ends in the perception of the clang, or of certain overtones 
in the clang, is there not an intra-organic stage equivalent to 
an indifferent assemblage of partial tones, a stage consequent 
upon the stimulation of the ear, and antecedent to perception? 
Let us follow the sequence of events. The several sets of 
waves, of differing vibration rates, are first compounded into 
a complex wave motion of the air, and it is in this form that 
the auditory stimulus reaches the ear. The ear seems not to 
respond to the wave form as such, but to break it up into its 
constituent simple waves. The ear is said to be an analytic 
organ, and the evidence for this analytic power of the ear as 
the fact that, after suitable training, the observer can hear the 
separate overtones out of the tonal mass. Probably the organ 
of Corti, and certainly some part of the auditory mechanism, 
possesses this analytic power, and furnishes as its stage in the 
sequence of events, an assemblage of tones, the fundamental 
and overtones. Without this stage to work from, to respond 
to, perception of the overtones would be impossible. It is an 
"indifferent" stage, in that it can lead either to the experience 
of the clang or to the hearing out of overtones. 

Much the same can be said with regard to the dot figure. 
The retinal image is an indifferent assemblage of dots, not 
grouped in one way rather than another. Presumably, the 
retina, and also the first receptive visual centers, respond 
pretty faithfully to the retinal image, and do not introduce the 
configuration which we find in the percept. 

It is at least a fair hypothesis that the first conscious stage 
in the process has this character of an indifferent assemblage, 



116 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

and that the figured percept is sequent in time to the indifferent 
stage. If we call this indifferent, unfigured stage the stage of 
sensation, then the seeing of the separate dots, or the hearing 
out of the overtones, is a genuine analysis of the sensory 
stage. It is not an analysis of the percept, but it is an analysis 
of the antecedent sensation. 

If the objection is raised that introspection affords no sup- 
port for this preliminary indifferent stage that the configura- 
tion is there as soon as the stimulus is seen or heard at all I 
would reply that there is some evidence, though none of it is 
well worked out as yet. The evidence is of several kinds. 

' (1) In looking at the dot figure, or at any ambiguous 
figure, though shifts occur from one configuration to another, 
the background or mass of the visual whole seems to remain 
constant. The dots or lines remain the same all through the 
shifts or grouping. This is as it would be if the configuration 
were superposed upon an indifferent sensation mass. 

(2) When the stimulus is unfamiliar and not very clear- 
cut, there is sometimes an interval of sensation before config- 
uration appears. This is as it should be. Unpracticed per- 
ceptual reactions should be relatively slow and halting, where- 
as much-practiced perceptions 'of familiar assemblages of 
stimuli would probably occur with a latency of not over a 
tenth of a twentieth of a second, an interval too short for in- 
trospective observation. 

(3) In object blindness, word deafness, and similar losses 
of function due to localized cerebral lesions, sensation remains, 
while configuration, at least of the normal type, is wanting. 
This is as it should be if configuration represented the activity 
of a different brain mechanism from that of the first recep- 
tive areas which, we may suppose, are active in sensation. 

(4) In recall, configuration often comes back clearly, 
while the sensory mass is vague and lacking in body. This is 
as it should be if configuration were a response separate from 
sensation, ordinarily aroused by the sensory stage, but capable 
of other attachments so as to be arousable in other ways and 
apart from sensation. 

The evidence ought to be sufficient to lend some respect- 
ability to the hypothesis of a sensation-perception sequence 
In fact the evidence is as good as could be expected in the ab- 
sence of intensive work on the problem. The promptness witi 
which the perceptual stage would probably supervene upon th< 
sensory, and the prolongation of the sensory stage (with con 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 117 

tinued stimulus) so as to overlap and blend with the percept, 
must necessarily make it difficult to demonstrate two separate 
stages in the process. 

This hasty consideration of a problem in perception may 
serve to indicate the broad scope of dynamic psychology, as 
covering topics quite apart from emotion and movement, and 
as operating with a variety of dynamic concepts, and not 
solely with impulse and similar principles. 

It will probably be clear without discussion that a dynamic 
psychology need not take sides in the controversy between 
introspectionists and behaviorists. It can utilize data obtained 
by either introspective or objective observation; sometimes the 
one and sometimes the other will serve to indicate the stages 
in a process going on within the organism. From its disin- 
clination to adhere definitely to either the behaviorist or the 
introspective wing of psychology, dynamic psychology is ex- 
posed to the accusation of being merely eclectic, of seeking to 
avoid extremes and preferring the "middle of the road." Such 
an accusation is not wholly fair, since dynamic psychology 
has its own problem and can rightfully seek light wherever 
trustworthy information is to be had. 

Behaviorism, as a set of taboos touch not, taste not, handle 
not the unclean thing, i.e.,, the sensation, the image, or any- 
thing with an odor of introspection about it tends to clog 
the works and hamper progress. On its positive side, how- 
ever, behaviorism is distinctly a study in dynamics, and it is 
doing much to force psychology to the use of dynamic con- 
cepts, and to cause those that have no dynamic value to become 
obsolescent. 

Phenomenological psychology appears to stand at the oppo- 
site pole from behaviorism, yet it too, by its efforts to get 
away from every-day modes of description and to describe 
sequences of events with a minimum of extraneous matter, 
may serve the purpose of dynamic psychology, so far as its 
descriptions are verified. What we need is a description of 
processes as they actually occur. The descriptions and con- 
cepts that satisfy us in daily life are apt to confuse and dis- 
tort the sequence of events. We need, specially, to be on our 
guard against valuation and teleology. When we say that a 
process occurs because it is useful to the organism, we have 
lost our sense of direction, and are putting the cart before the 
horse. To be sure, the outcome of an act may be the cause of 



118 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

further processes, but not of the process leading up to the act 
itself. 

But to say that dynamic psychology does not operate with 
concepts of value, as tools in its own work, is not to say that 
it must have nothing to do with the facts of preference, suc- 
cess and failure, likes and dislikes, loves and hates, purposes 
and fears, as they actually occur in life. All such events in 
the process of living are to be included; only, we need a 
straight, undistorted account of them. 

From what has already been said, the attitude of dynamic 
psychology to the purposivist and the mechanistic tendencies 
in psychology may be sufficiently clear; yet the matter de- 
serves somewhat closer attention. 

Purpose is a real fact in human life, and, if not purpose, at 
least striving towards a goal is a real fact of animal life as 
well. Quite apart from the philosophy of purpose and striv- 
ing and their place in the world process as a whole which is 
not a psychological question purpose is one of the phenomena 
which psychology must include in its story. A dynamic 
psychology must study purpose in relation to its antecedents 
and consequences, its causes and effects. 

Some authors, as especially McDougall, 6 appear to teach 
that any thoroughgoing causal interpretation of human be- 
havior and experience implies shutting one's eyes to the facts 
of purpose and striving. There is certainly some confusion 
here. There can be no contradiction between the purposive- 
ness of a sequence of actions and its being a causal sequence. 
A purpose is certainly a cause; if it had no effects, it would 
be without significance. Moreover, for anyone to harbor a 
purpose, he must believe in the causal nature of the stream of 
events in which he means to work. His purpose seeks to con- 
trol the course of events, by adopting means that can be re- 
lied on to produce the desired outcome. Without some ex- 
perience of dependable causes to be utilized as means, a pur- 
pose could scarcely take rise. 

Shall we say, then that a purpose, though a cause, is itself 
uncaused, that it has no genesis, no motivation, no stimulus? 
I know of no facts tending to such a conclusion. On the 
contrary, so far as it is possible for us to influence other 
people and control their behavior, it is by way of controlling 
their desires and purposes. We can control their hands and 

"Outline of Psychology. N. Y., 1923. 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 119 

feet and vocal organs, for the most part, only by controlling 
their desires. We make appeals to them, we appeal to their 
self-interest, their loyalty, their interest in this, their dislike 
of that, and by such means we excite in them purposes that 
eventuate in action. Animal behavior is similarly controlled 
by the use of suitable incentives. 

If man has certain native propensities, if these are awak- 
ened by certain stimuli, if they are the basis of sentiments 
and purposes, then, undoubtedly, every purpose has its cause 
in a double sense : it has its genesis in the life history of the 
individual, and, at any time, it has its exciting stimulus. The 
whole study of purpose would be futile, if purpose were not 
the effect of definite causes, as well as the cause of definite 
effects. 

Purpose is not belittled by recognizing it as the effect of 
antecedent causes. Every cause is itself the effect of antece- 
dent causes, and its own effectiveness as a cause is not thus 
diminished. Your purpose of giving somebody a happy sur- 
prise on Christmas Day is no less a purpose, and no less ef- 
fective, because it originated in your love for that person 
(which itself is the effect of causes lying back in your life 
history), and in your memory of joyful surprises on former 
Christmas Days. Your purpose would be futile if it had no 
effects, it would be incredible if it had no causes. It is a link 
in a causal chain, but it is just as fine a purpose for all that. 

Therefore, I say, there must be some confusion of ideas 
when the fact of purpose is brought up as if it made a dynamic, 
cause-and-effect psychology impossible or even wicked. Rather, 
this and similar facts are grist for the dynamic mill, and, when 
well ground, should produce the most valuable sort of knowl- 
edge for the understanding and control of human conduct. 

With purposivism, as a philosophy of all nature, or of all 
animate nature, dynamic psychology has nothing to do. In 
order to concentrate upon its own job, psychology needs to 
keep away from philosophy, or, at least, to maintain a clear 
distinction between what is psychology and what is the philos- 
ophy that happens to appeal most strongly to the particular 
psychologist. I contend that the injection of purposivism, or 
of animism, into a psychological discussion is irrelevant and 
distracting. Vitalism, indeed, can be treated as a scientific 
question, but it is not a question for psychology. It is a ques- 
tion for cellular physiology, since the crucial considerations 



120 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

refer to the life processes of the cells, not to the behavior of 
the individual as a whole. 

Psychology is not called upon to give its adherence either 
to vitalism or to a mechanistic conception of life. If a scien- 
tific decision between these two views is possible, it will be 
reached by physiology, not by psychology. Psychology is not 
mechanistic, any more than it is vitalistic; nor even is a dy- 
namic psychology mechanistic, though it deals with causes 
and effects. Dynamic psychology follows the course of events 
in the life of the organism as a whole. The self-same course 
of events can be followed by physiology, with its more refined 
or at least more microscopic technique. A chimpanzee, let us 
say, joints together two sticks of bamboo and uses the jointed 
pole for reaching a banana. This is a psychological descrip- 
tion ; much more and finer detail might be added and the des- 
cription still remain at the psychological level. Now the 
physiologist may undertake to describe this same series of 
events, in terms of the action of the different muscles, of 
separate muscle fibers, nerve fibers, synapses in localized nerve 
centers, and so on. He would be describing the same real 
process not a "parallel" process but his description would 
employ different concepts and would be, in general, very dif- 
ferent from the psychologist's description. It would be much 
more minute than the psychologist's description, but not neces- 
sarily any truer. It would not include the relationships ob- 
served by the psychologist, and would not be so useful for 
purposes of prediction and control, if we wished to know what 
the chimpanzee would do in a given situation. Still other ob- 
servers, as the physical chemist, might describe the same real 
process, analyzing it in still minuter detail, and working, we 
may say, at a still lower or deeper level of description. Now 
the physical chemist or the physiologist may approach a me- 
chanistic description of the chimpanzee's actions, but the 
psychologist does not come within shooting distance of such a 
description. It lies out of his level altogether. 

Both introspective and objective psychology, we may remark 
in passing, are working at the same general "level/' intermedi- 
ate between the level of the sociologist above and that of the 
physiologist below. Both are working at the level at which 
the actions of the individual as a whole come into view. Thus 
introspectionists and behaviorists logically belong within the 
confines of the one science of psychology. Though they may 
have their family jars, they are not likely to consent to a di- 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 121 

vorce. I would liken dynamic psychology to the child that 
holds this family together, were that not rather out of keeping 
with my insistence that dynamic psychology is essentially much 
older than either behaviorism or introspectionism, which have 
arisen recently, as a matter of fact, in the strife for more 
adequate methods in psychology. Dynamic psychology can 
use the data of both. I would go so far as to say that it is 
the dynamic point of view that gives significance to either 
introspective or behavior data. 

Dynamic psychology is not physiology; it is not, necessar- 
ily, physiological psychology. The latter works the two levels 
together, or correlates psychological with physiological find- 
ings a most valuable task. But it is one thing to recognize 
the value of such correlation, and quite another thing to teach 
that the only worth-while goal of psychology is a physiological 
description. Psychology is primarily responsible for its own 
level, and its own particular goal is such a generalized de- 
scription of the individual's activities, in causal sequence, as 
will make possible prediction and control within this field and 
level. Contact with the social and physiological levels, above 
and below, is extremely valuable for psychology, especially 
in a dynamic sense. 

If the aim of genetic psychology, in a general way, is to 
trace the course of events, and to seek for uniform sequences 
that may have the value of causal laws, this general problem 
can be seen to break up into a number of more special prob- 
lems, according as the course of events is followed over a 
long or over shorter periods of time. Genetic psychology, the 
life history of the individual, his curve of growth and sen- 
escence, are concerned with the sequence of events over long 
periods of time. The process of learning, the practice curve, 
the curve of forgetting, the curve of fatigue and the diurnal 
course of efficiency, follow the sequence of events over com- 
paratively short, but still considerable periods of time. Studies 
of reflexes, emotional responses, reaction times, and the de- 
pendance of perception upon sensory stimuli follow sequences 
that run their course in a few seconds at most, and illustrate 
the most detailed type of analysis which psychology has found 
it feasible to undertake. Because the more minute the an- 
alysis, the more searching and fundamental it appears 
though this is in part an illusion the concepts of stimulus and 
response, applicable to this minutest analysis of process, have 



122 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

come to have a dominant position in the array of dynamic con- 
cepts employed by psychology. 

Though the concepts of stimulus and response have long 
been employed, they have of late been more emphasized than 
formerly, and are beginning to awaken some rather trenchant 
criticism. Possibly no better use can be made of the present 
occasion than to attempt a slight contribution to this discus- 
sion, and to the clarification of these fundamental concepts. 

To some critics, these concepts have seemed too obvious to 
have much significance. We are challenged to make any gen- 
eral statements concerning stimulus and response that are not 
too trite and self-evident to merit any attention. Can any- 
thing at all surprising, and yet true, be said of stimulus and 
response ? 

Well, for a first attempt, let us notice that "stimulus" is not 
to be identified with "cause." The stimulus is decidedly not 
the adequate cause of the response. The response may reveal 
much more energy than was present in the stimulus. The 
same stimulus may, on different occasions, give rise to quite 
a variety of different responses. In these and other ways, 
the relation of stimulus and response is not the relation of 
cause and effect. 

The stimulus may be said to be part of the response, the 
other partial causes being the structures of the organism, its 
stores of energy, and in general its condition at the time when 
the stimulus affects it. The stimulus is related to the response 
as the blow of the trigger is related to the motion of the bul- 
let from the muzzle of the gun. The stimulus excites the 
response, but the energy and form of the response are deter- 
mined by the organization of the individual. 

So much, however, is an old story. Let us proceed to some- 
thing less obvious and more open to debate. The organization 
of the individual is often conceived as built up of units which 
may be named reflex arcs, or reaction arcs. Such a unit is 
conceived as extending all the way from the receptor through 
the center to the effector. In terms of activity or behavior, 
letting S stand for stimulus and R for response, we say, ac- 
cording to this conception of reaction-arcs, that behavior is 
composed of S-R units. S is not to be considered apart from 
R, nor R apart from S, for S-R is a functional unit. These 
S-R units are harnessed both abreast and tandem, and thus 
integrated into complex modes of behavior. Native equipment 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 123 

consists of a stock of such units, and learning consists in the 
integration of these units into acts. 

Though this conception has, and long has had, considerable 
vogue among psychologists, there are objections to it, which, 
in my opinion, are fatal Evidence at hand appears to show 
that: 

(1) No S-R unit is a unit in the full sense. There may be 
a few exceptions, such as the patellar reflex, where the R can 
be aroused only by one S. Other reflexes, however, are elicited 
by any one of a number of different stimuli. In the case 
of the pupillary reflex, the narrowing of the pupil is elicited 
either by increased illumination of the retina or by focusing 
of the eye upon a near object. Dilatation of the pupil is eli- 
cited by diminishing the light entering the eye, by turning the 
eyes from a near to a distant object, and by a variety of other 
stimuli, such as a sudden loud noise, a bitter taste in the mouth, 
a sudden touch on the skin, a sudden pain. Much the same is 
true of other reflexes. In Sherrington's terminology, 6 each 
reflex, such as the flexion reflex or the scratch reflex, has a "re- 
ceptive field" of greater or less extent, by stimulating any part 
of which the reflex can be obtained. Instead, then, of think- 
ing of S-R as a unit, we have to think of R alone as the real 
unit. This unit covers the activity of the peripheral motor 
organ and of the nerve center which directly controls it. Each 
R is accessible to several S's, more accessible to some than to 
others. Behavior is composed of R units, rather than of S-R 
units. Native behavior consists of an assortment of such 
R units, which can be elicited by a variety of stimuli, though 
not by any stimulus at random. 

(2) Even when a given S-R combination is functioning 
fairly regularly as a unit, the fact of conditioned response 
shows that this S-R unit can be broken up, and a substitute 
S attached to the R. This fact, which would be impossible if 
S-R were a genuine unit, is perfectly in line with the concep- 
tion of R as a unit, requiring some S to arouse it, but attached 
more or less loosely, more or less closely, to several S's, and 
capable of becoming more closely attached to an S with which 
it was only loosely attached at the outset. Integration of be- 
havior units would be very difficult, if not impossible, to con- 
ceive, if S-R were a genuine unit, fixed and indissoluble, for 
then all new connections between the units would have to be 



Integrative Action of the Nervous System, New York, 1906 



124 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

established at the periphery (where it is very doubtful if new 
connections can be formed), while a modifiable center would 
be of no service whatever. 

To reach a true picture of behavior, then, we should ideally 
start not with S but with R. Having made an inventory of 
the R's at the disposal of the organism, we should next inquire 
regarding the various S's by which each R could be aroused. 
We should note combinations of R's arousable as integrated 
totals by the same S, and also combinations of S's effective in 
arousing an R which perhaps is not readily aroused by any 
single S. 

Responses are integrated when two or more of them become 
attached to the same stimulus, so as to be aroused in combina- 
tion by this stimulus. Stimuli may perhaps be said to be in- 
tegrated when two or more of them become attached to the 
same response. Stimulus-response "units" do not, as such, be- 
come integrated, since every integration involves the break-up 
of pre-existing "units" of this sort. 

Finally, note should be taken of Thurstone's recent on- 
slaught upon the "stimulus-response fallacy in psychology." 
Paraphrasing his argument, in the light also of earlier discus- 
sions by Dewey 7 and by Sherrington, 8 we may say, and with 
good reason, that very seldom does a stimulus find the organ- 
ism in a completely resting, neutral and unpreoccupied state. 
Ordinarily, a stimulus breaks in upon some activity in pro- 
gress, some "incomplete reaction," to use Thurstone's expres- 
sion. This activity has a trend towards some goal, immedi- 
ate or remote. We have, then, not first stimulus, then ac- 
tivity of the organism; but first an activity going on, next an 
intercurrent stimulus, and then the activity modified in re- 
sponse to the stimulus. The response to the intercurrent 
stimulus is determined as much by the pre-existing activity as 
by the particular stimulus of the moment. If the incomplete 
activity is very intense, as in the case of two dogs fighting, 
such a stimulus as the master calling or even jumping in with 
a stick to separate the dogs may have scarcely any effect. At 
other times, a very faint stimulus, anticipated and prepared 
for, has a pronounced effect. 

The relations of stimulus and pre-existing incomplete ac- 
tivity are well illustrated in the process of reading. The reader 

'The Reflex Arc Concept in Psychology, Psychol. Rev., 1896, 3:357. 
8 Integrative Action of the Nervous System. 



DYNAMIC PSYCHOLOGY 125 

is in the midst of a story, and eagerly reaching forward to 
learn what is coming next. The successive stimuli from the 
printed page are seized with lightning rapidity and utilized for 
just one purpose, from among the many responses which these 
.stimuli are capable of arousing. The actual response is deter- 
mined, we say, by the context as well as by the word seen at 
any instant. More precisely, the actual response to each suc- 
cessive word and phrase is determined by the activity set in 
motion by what has already been read, and tending forward 
in a definite direction. The successive word stimuli do not 
deflect this motion from its course, but are so responded to as 
to further the motion already in progress. 

What has been said of reading could be said as well of 
hunger or sex activity or of fighting or flight from danger. 
Here the organism may be said to be in the throes of a need 
which is the controlling factor in the activity. Whether the 
concept of "need" is a useful dynamic concept is perhaps open 
to doubt; it smacks considerably of the sort of teleology that 
we do well to leave aside. In the actual process, what we call 
"need" is a prepotent activity, i.e., an activity not readily de- 
flected, moving forward without responding to stimuli dis- 
connected with itself. What we see is an activity going for- 
ward in a definite direction and rendering the organism un- 
responsive to certain stimuli, while unusually responsive to 
others. 

These considerations apply in the study of sensation and 
perception as well as in the study of motor activity. In the 
laboratory, when we wish to analyze behavior by isolating cer- 
tain responses and tracing out their antecedents and conse- 
quents, we try to do away, as far as possible, with pre-existing 
incomplete activities, and get the subject into a neutral, or at 
least a receptive state. Then we apply known stimuli and note 
the responses. Instead, however, of thus simplifying and stan- 
dardizing the pre-existing state of the organism to the maxi- 
mum, we may choose to apply a given stimulus when a known 
activity is in progress. What we then get are "false reactions," 
"illusions," and the like, knowledge of which is equally valu- 
able with the knowledge obtained under simplified conditions. 
But, evidently, a knowledge of responses, and their relations 
to stimuli, under the simplest conditions of pre-existing ac- 
tivity, furnishes a base line that is essential in any accurate 
survey of the whole field of activity; and thus it is that what 
we may call the "stimulus-response psychology," the most de- 



126 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

tailed form of dynamic psychology, is of genuine and funda- 
mental importance, in spite of the criticisms, revisions and 
elaborations of its concepts contained in recent discussions, 
and briefly presented in this lecture. The fact that such dis- 
cussions occur is evidence of the significance of the concepts of 
stimulus and response, and at the same time an indication that 
"dynamic psychology" is a fair characterization of much, at 
least, of the psychological enterprise of the present time. 



PART III 

Gestalt 




KURT KOFFKA 



CHAPTER VI 

MENTAL DEVELOPMENT* 



BY KURT KOFFKA 



That mind develops, individually during any person's life, 
racially in the history of mankind, and phylogenetically in the 
evolutionary series of the animal kingdom, is today a truism. 
What we are interested in is how this development takes 
place. To give concrete substance to our discussion of this 
problem we shall make a survey of the different stages of 
mind by considering what mind is able to do. In this attempt 
we find no great difficulty in grouping our material. Restrict- 
ing ourselves to the sphere of the vertebrates, we can roughly 
distinguish three types of behavior using this word without 
any theoretical bias and can exemplify these types by a num- 
ber of instances: 

Type I. (a). Sneezing and coughing; the reaction of 
the pupils of the eye to light; eye-move- 
ments of fixation. 

(b). The suckling of the new-born infant; the 
pecking of a chick just broken from the 
egg ; the building of nests ; lastly the entire 
life of ants or bees. 

Type II. The behavior of animals in certain kinds of ex- 
periments of the puzzle-box or maze-type, and in the tricks 
we see performed in vaudeville shows. 

Type III. The behavior of chimpanzees as observed in the 
experiments of Dr. Kohler; or to select another instance out 
of an indefinite number, your behavior in attending this lecture 
or mine in preparing and delivering it. Our classification, 
whatever its theoretical bearing may be, is not entirely arbi- 
trary; for psychology has named each of these three types. 
We call the first reflexive and instinctive activities, the second 
trained or drilled performances, and the third intelligent 
achievements. For brevity's sake I shall sometimes refer to 
them simply as reflexes and instincts, training, and intelligence. 
These three types evidently represent different ^ stages of 
mind and we may expand each of them so as to include all 
possible stages in our scheme. Then the problem of mental 
development reduces itself to the problem of the connection 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
April 29, 1925. 



130 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

between these three behavior types : which is the original type 
of behavior and how have the others grown out of it? We 
can, for our purposes, discriminate two main theories of men- 
tal development, one being Unitarian, and deriving all behavior 
from one fundamental type, that of the reflex (la), while the 
other is pluralistic and maintains an essential difference be- 
tween the three types ; the higher ones being, in the course of 
evolution, added to the lower ones. 

Let us examine the first of these theories. It starts with 
the assumption that our behavior type la, the reflex, is the 
original type and it uses a very popular description and ex- 
planation of the reflex. Reflexes as very simple and com- 
paratively regular responses to definite stimuli are explained 
by the hypothesis that they are the function of a very simple 
apparatus, the reflex arc, consisting of afferent and efferent 
neurones and the connection or bond between them, which in 
this way connects the situation and the response of the or- 
ganism. Thus this conception of the bond is the starting point 
of this view of mental development. But it is more : It is the 
supreme principle by which this theory achieves an admirable 
simplicity. For according to this view every action of an or- 
ganism is explicable in terms of such connections, in other 
words, every action carried out by an organism is determined 
solely by the bonds or connections involved. The original con- 
nections, and consequently, the original reaction-tendencies go 
far beyond the realm of mere reflex action, embracing the 
entire so-called instinctive activity. 

Now instinctive and even most of reflexive activity appears 
to be highly adjustive; the animal does what is good for it in 
its environment. But from the point of view of this theory 
this adaptiveness is not a property of these actions themselves, 
but is instead, a mere impression which they give to the on- 
looker. The actions are not determined in any way by the in- 
trinsic nature of the situation, but altogether by these pre- 
existing bond-devices. The situation enters only as the agency 
which turns the key, presses the button, makes the machine 
go. But, like a real machine, the animal can only act accord- 
ing to the pre-established system of bonds, whether such an 
action be adequate to the circumstances or not. 

The connection between situation and response is therefore 
purely contingent and consequently we do not know why a 
certain situation affects a certain pathway, we can only state 
that it does do so. We ought then to be able to change the 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 131 

response to a constant situation by merely changing the bonds 
involved in such a pathway. 

What this really implies will become evident when we take 
up a few of our initial instances. The theory means that a 
chick newly escaped from the egg pecks at a grain, seizes and 
swallows it, not because this is the sensible response to this 
particular situation, but because its neurones are connected 
with each other in such ways as to secure these reactions in 
this sequence. If we were able to change these connections 
the animal would, for instance, first make the swallowing and 
then the pecking movement. Or, another example, taken from 
Watson's experiments on babies : If in a dark room we intro- 
duce a bright spot, the baby turns its eyes towards this spot 
and fixates it. It does so, merely because of its innate connec- 
tions without regard to the situation, and again by shifting 
those connections we ought to be able to change this response 
in such a manner that, for instance, the baby would be made 
to look towards the left when the bright spot appears on the 
right. This experiment happens to have been performed, 
though, naturally, not with babies but with monkeys. Marina 
dissected the inner and outer muscles of the eyes of monkeys 
and connected them crossways. An impulse sent to contract 
the external muscle of the right eye ought now to result in 
a movement towards the left and vice versa. Consequently, 
in our experiment the monkey should react just as we have 
predicted ; it should look to the left when a bright spot appears 
at the right. Speaking more generally all the monkey's eye- 
movements in the horizontal should have been the reverse of 
normal. In reality, however, nothing of the kind took place. 
As soon as the wounds healed the animal moved his eyes just 
as normally as it did before the operation. That means that 
in spite of the changes made in the devices, the movements 
continued to be performed so as to produce the same sort of 
achievement. 

Thus the conception of a merely contingent connection be- 
tween situation and response breaks down even at the reflex 
level. And we are left with the problem: how can a certain 
result, rather than a reformed system of devices, determine 
organic movements? Without the slightest leaning towards 
vitalism we shall have to face this problem. But before we do 
so, let us turn to the explanation of our second type of be- 
havior, training, which according to this theory is the only 
way in which learning takes place. 



132 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

It is the pride of this theory that it has been able to explain 
acquired behavior in the same terms which it employs for 
original behavior. This extension of the explanation is not 
so difficult as it may appear at first sight. The only assump- 
tion required is that in animals which are able to learn^the 
original bonds are not absolutely fixed but may be modified 
according to specific laws. What this means is best explained 
by an example taken from Thorndike's experiments. He puts 
a hungry cat into a cage, the door of which is shut but can 
be opened by turning a lever, and before the cage he places 
some enticing food. The first time in the cage the cat will 
make all sorts of movements which have nothing to dp with 
the lever, but in the course of its aimless movements it may 
accidentally strike this lever, and by this action achieve its es- 
cape and the possession of the coveted food. In a later ex- 
periment, say the tenth or twentieth, the cat will turn the lever 
without any other movements, as soon as it has been placed in 
the cage. It therefore appears that the cat acquired a new 
reaction towards the old situation. But speaking strictly from 
the point of view of this theory, the effect of learning is 
rather of a negative than of a positive kind. For, according 
to this view, any one of the innumerable reactions which the 
animal made in the first experiment, was connected to this 
particular situation by bonds of neurones. We can not assume 
as a rule that a situation has only one set of bonds connecting 
it with one single response ; instead we must believe that every 
single situation possesses a great number of different connec- 
tions of varying strength and directness leading to very differ- 
ent reactions. The process of learning consists, then, merely 
in strengthening certain sets of bonds and weakening all the 
others. The chief laws by which this result is to be achieved 
are those of frequency, recency, and of effect. While the two 
first are readily understood, the law of effect requires a few 
words in explanation. It embraces the fact that it is the ap- 
propriate, the successful act that survives, and expresses this 
fact by saying that such connections as have led to satisfaction 
gain an advantage over such as have not done so. 

Like original behavior, acquired behavior, then, is deter- 
mined by devices, taking place over neurone-bonds which have 
undergone some change but which, this change once com- 
pleted, are determinants of action just as exclusive as were the 
originally effective bonds. Consequently the relation between 
situation and response remains contingent, and all learning 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 133 

proceeds by chance. Again we ought to be able to change the 
reactions by shifting the connections, but if we do so, we get 
the negative result previously reported because the acquired 
activity continues unaltered. Of course the law of effect was 
meant to modify this point and to account for progress in 
mental development. But as it stands it fails to achieve this 
task, since in reality it is not a law of effect, but a law of 
satisfaction which is a very different matter, because the satis- 
faction is not the satisfaction of success, but something which 
follows success without having any meaningful connection 
with it. Thus, according to Thorndike's own teaching, when 
in the previously described experiment the cat has learned to 
turn the lever it does so, not because it understands what the 
turning of the lever means, but because this particular move- 
ment, belonging among the original responses to the situation 
of being confined, in which situation the existence of the 
lever is absolutely immaterial, has in many cases led to satis- 
faction by giving the animal freedom and food. For this 
reason the movement is stamped in, and this particular set 
of bonds between the initial situation and the particular move- 
ment is therefore strengthened to the detriment of other con- 
nections which at start were just as ready as this one. Just 
as the existence of the lever was immaterial for the produc- 
tion of the movement to turn it so now this movement is im- 
material to the pleasure derived from the tasting of the food. 
Chance made the movement with the lever and chance, in the 
arbitrarily contrived situation of the puzzle-box, connects the 
striking of the lever with freedom and food. Thus this law 
of satisfaction is not a law of effect, for which reason it has 
been a sore point in the theory, even from the beginning. 
Satisfaction comes after the critical event, after the movement 
which it is assumed to stamp in; therefore it must have a re- 
troactive force. It is not only difficult to explain how such a 
backward force can be exerted, but once retroaction is granted 
we have to state how far back this force will reach. Why 
should it extend precisely to the really relevant movement 
when the animal does not know that this movement is re- 
levant? 

More recent observations have shown that it is the effect 
and not the subsequent satisfaction which is the determining 
factor in learning. In Kohler's experiments one of the apes, 
after solving a particularly difficult problem in order to secure 
some bananas, did not interrupt this newly invented procedure 



134 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

to taste his booty, but continued to fish with his new tool to 
get all sorts of useless things after all the bananas had been 
collected. Also in Kuo's experiment improvement of the 
achievement went on although the imperfect performance led 
to exactly the same ulterior satisfaction as did the improved 
act. But if the effect and not the added satisfaction is re- 
levant, we shall again have to discard the idea that the con- 
nection between situation and response is merely contingent. 

And yet this concept of the merely contingent relation has 
dominated our whole psychology of experience for it has even 
a wider application than we have so far pointed out. Bonds 
are not only formed between receptors and effectors, but also 
between ideas in the famous "associations." Again an asso- 
ciation connecting a perception with an idea, the sight of 
lightning with the expectation of thunder, would be purely 
contingent connection, based merely on the frequency of the 
concomitance of the events. No other connection being re- 
cognized, this means that originally there can be no order in 
our perceptions all order must come from experience as the 
chance repetition of contiguous events. From this point of 
view all our rational concepts would seem to be illusory, be- 
cause they imply more than contingent connections. But even 
if that were so, there remains one fact unexplained: for how 
does this illusion arise ? Even if it be an illusion, it is at least 
a datum, an undeniable fact. 

Just as the puzzle-box (and maze) experiments give experi- 
mental support to the first part of our theory, so the second 
rests upon very elaborate experiments on the learning of non- 
sense-syllables. Both these types of investigation, however, in- 
volve highly artificial conditions. In both cases the object of 
experimentation, the animal or the human observer, is con- 
fronted with a situation which is completely meaningless. 
There is, for instance, nothing in the syllable pum that indi- 
cates that the syllable dat is to follow it. In other words : no 
nonsense-syllable calls for its successor in the series. And the 
same argument applies to the puzzle-box; it is so constructed 
as to surpass all possible understanding on the side of the ani- 
mal, and therefore, though it may call for the expenditure of 
effort for freedom, it can call for no specific action to achieve 
this end. This again is in contradiction to the theory from 
which we started and which maintains that by inherited devices 
each ^ situation is connected with quite a number of specific 
reactions. 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 135 

We have used the phrase: a situation calls for a reaction. 
What does this mean? When before the eyes of an animal 
we put food inside an open box the animal will enter the box 
and fetch out the food. This situation does, so we may say, 
call for a certain reaction. But is this not simply an instinc- 
tive reaction? If we grant this, what have we gained? If we 
have given up our understanding of instinct as a ready made 
set of neurone-bond devices, how does this name help us in 
understanding these factors? But does our term, "the situa- 
tion calls for/' do any more? With this question in mind let 
us glance at certain experiments in which the animal solved 
problems under natural conditions in a situation that revealed 
openly all the parts necessary to the required achievement. 
Tomorrow Professor Kohler will report at length upon his 
experiments to which I have just referred. Therefore I shall 
only mention here some very general features of his results. 
His champanzees solved their problems not by trial and error; 
the correct solution was not slowly and painfully selected out 
of a number of inexpedient movements, the correct activity 
began abruptly from a stage of deliberation, continued in an 
unbroken curve and took place always with regard to the re- 
levant part of the situation. It was not a product of chance, 
neither were these actions instinctive. What then remains? 

Shall we have recourse to the pluralistic theory mentioned 
in the beginning and assume that a new factor, the intellect, 
must be the cause? To do so would, on the one hand, be 
equal to a renunciation of a theory of development; on the 
other hand, it would not even be an explanation of the facts. 
To ascribe an action of our first type to instinct is no more 
an explanation than to attribute an action of the third type to 
intellect. 

There remains but one other possibility : the situation forces 
the animal to act in a certain way, although the animal pos- 
sesses no pre-established special devices for the act. How is 
this possible? I shall develop the answer to this fundamental 
question by the help of a concrete and well known instance 
which has become precipitated into a proverb, viz., the burnt 
child shuns the fire. Fortunately Dr. Watson has taken this 
change of behavior out of the sphere of mere armchair psy- 
chology by providing us with experimental evidence on the 
subject. His experiments, which he" performed with an infant 
beginning the 150th day of his life, showed that at first the 
burnt child did not shun the fire at all, but would grasp for 



136 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

it again and again although it came so near the flame that it 
flexed its fingers and withdrew the hand. The change seems 
to have come very suddenly. On the 220th day the child, in- 
stead of grasping for the flame, slapped at the candle and 
afterwards reached for it but a single time. How can we 
understand this transformation in the response? To state that 
the stimulus, candle, is originally connected with several re- 
sponses, among them being those of grasping and of slapping, 
and that the first of these became weakened by dissatisfac- 
tion, is quite inadequate. The suddenness of the change and 
the new reaction which superseded the old one are left en- 
tirely without an explanation. In other words: why did this 
fortunate infant, instead of simply shunning the fire, slap at 
it? 

If we use common-sense psychology we would say: the in- 
fant slaps the candle, because he has learned to dislike it, just 
as he grasped for it at first because it looked so attractive to 
him. This common-sense explanation is essentially different 
from the behavioristic explanation in one point: it connects 
the action not with the stimulus but with the perception of the 
stimulus, and the change of reaction with a change in the per- 
ception. An attractive object calls for one kind of behavior, 
a repulsive object for another. Thus we meet again our initial 
problem: a situation calls for something. And now we see 
that the situation does call for, if at all, not as a stimulus, 
but as a perceived, phenomenal situation. We see further that 
the relation between stimulus and phenomenal situation is not 
univocal: because the same stimulus may evoke different per- 
ceptions. Since this fact is abundantly confirmed by scientific 
experimental psychology it would seem as though we could 
afford to accept our common-sense explanation. Couched in 
scientific terms, it would run like this: Our direct responses 
to stimuli are receptor processes which in many cases will be 
on the mental, perceptive level : such a direct response is, how- 
ever, only the beginning of the total response : the perception 
issues in action according to its constitution, the action is a 
natural continuation of the perceptive process and is deter- 
mined by it and not by pre-established connection-bonds. 
Change of response to a constant stimulus does not take place 
by alternation in the function of ready-made devices, but is a 
result of a change in the perceptive process produced by the 
stimulus. Lastly : a stimulus upsets an equilibrium on the re- 
ceptive side of the system; this upset equilibrium results in 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 137 

a movement which tends to bring the system to a new equili- 
brium and consequently the reaction must vary with the way 
in which the equilibrium was disturbed, that is with the re- 
ceptor process, with the phenomenal situation. 

From this follow, several important inferences: (1) re- 
sponses of our first type, reflexes and instincts, can not be ex- 
plained ultimately by the reflex arc. The organism has at 
birth a constitution such that some stimuli will upset the 
equilibrium in one direction, others in other directions: some 
situations will be attractive, others repulsive. To confine our- 
selves for the moment to this difference, from attractive situa- 
tions will result positive, approach reactions; from repulsive 
situations, negative, avoidance responses. (2) Learning con- 
sists in many cases primarily in a change of the perceptive 
process. It can, therefore, no longer be considered as an as- 
sociation, the mere tying together of two contingently con- 
tiguous ideas, or the selection of pre-established pathways by 
trial and error. This means that the perceptive process has 
its own constitution, shape, patterns; we must ask not only, 
and not even primarily, where, in which neurones or brain 
cells, does perception occur ; but chiefly : how does it occur and 
what is it like? When learning takes place, when such a pro- 
cess changes, we must ask: what sort of a change is this? 
Learning, then, is not merely a matter of memory, because 
before a process can be remembered, it must have occurred, 
and therefore in all learning we have to distinguish between 
two problems : (a) how is a process remembered and how is 
it forgotten? This problem of memory is the one problem to 
which the theories previously discussed have reduced all learn- 
ing, by explaining it in terms of association or selection, (b) 
How is the process, which is to be remembered achieved for 
the first time ? This problem of achievement is really the more 
important of the two. It brings us back to our question: 
How can the situation force the animal to do something which 
it has never done before? This is really the problem of 
achievement. 

(3) We also find an answer to a question raised in our 
first discussion of the reflexes, msr v how a certain result rather 
than a system of devices can determine organic movements 
and how it can call for a certain achievement. We see now 
that there is no mysticism, no vitalism involved in this. If 
we consider every response as the result of a disturbed equili- 
brium we can predict that such a response will be in the di- 



138 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

rection of a new equilibrium, since every process in nature 
must comply with this law. Our task is to establish the fact 
of the equilibria of an organic system, and the causes by which 
as well as the direction in which this equilibrium may be up- 
set. 

The problem of mental development now takes on an en- 
tirely new aspect. Instead of considering such development 
as a change in connections or associations we have to view it 
as a transformation of processes. Our next task will there- 
fore be to describe the nature of the original processes and of 
their various forms of transformation. This will finally lead 
us back to the causal problem: how the situation can enforce 
these changes. 

Our first two questions will be approached pari passu. The 
discussion of the change that takes place will also reveal the 
original properties that undergo change. Let us return then 
to our burnt child example. The transformation that took 
place in this case may be called one of meaning : the attractive 
candle became repulsive. By calling this change a change of 
meaning we designate the fact that the perception of the candle 
points beyond itself in one of two directions. Originally the 
flame was attractive, that is, it appeared to the child as an ob- 
ject towards which something had to be done; afterwards it 
became repulsive, that is, it appeared as an object against 
which action should be taken. In both cases the perception 
had the character of incompleteness, and a change has taken 
place in the specific nature of this gap. In other words : ex- 
perience, in this case, does not create meaning, but transforms 
meaning; which implies that meaning itself is not a product 
of experience mental development does not lead from the 
meaningless to the meaningful, but from one kind of mean- 
ing to another kind of meaning. Mind without a meaning 
we should never expect to encounter. 

It would transcend the limits of this lecture, were I to at- 
tempt to confirm this result by showing how, on the one hand, 
it is borne out by the facts of child psychology, and how, on 
the other hand, a purely empiristic explanation of meaning 
leads to a vicious circle. But in as much as my whole argu- 
ment seems to rely on this one experiment of Watson's, I may 
recall a much older observation made by Lloyd Morgan which 
is in all essentials similar to the instance from which we 
started. If we substitute for the child a chick and for the 
candle a cinnabar caterpillar which is conspicuous by its im- 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 139 

pressive black and yellow rings and apparently distasteful to 
the chick, we shall find a close analogy in the two instances of 
behavior. The chick at first pecks at the caterpillar as it will 
at any other object of appropriate size, after which it drops 
its victim with signs of disgust. Since very often this trans- 
formation takes place after the first experience and without 
the need of repetition, the next time this chick catches sight 
of such a caterpillar it will run away with signs of fright 
sounding the danger note. Lest my opponents should try to 
take the edge off my argument, and reproach me with anthro- 
pomorphism by contending that I have no earthly right to 
ascribe either desire or disgust and fright to a chick, I will 
discuss the same fact with another set of concepts. Let us 
dismiss the mind of the chick altogether. What we must re- 
tain, however, are the receptor-processes which are aroused in 
his system by the action of the caterpillar on his sense organs 
and which, according to the explanation we have established, 
are the direct causes of the movements that constitute the 
overt behavior of the animal. We should then have to say 
that at first a receptor-process in the visual organ of the chick 
is of such a nature that it issues in approach, whereas after 
the first pecking it issues in flight. In both cases the receptor- 
process was incomplete, as it continued into motor processes, 
and but the kind of incompleteness differed in the two cases. 
It seems therefore a natural and legitimate generalization if 
we apply our concept of meaning to these receptor-processes, 
quite apart from mind; meaning has then a very objective 
signification. And yet our explanation in the new terms is es- 
sentially the same as what it was in the old terms, where learn- 
ing consists in a transformation of meaning, I need only to 
indicate that just as the concept of meaning can be transferred 
from mental to neural behavior, so can the other concepts we 
have employed such as desire, disgust, fright, and ever so many 
others. This again means that the taunt of anthropomorphism 
has not hurt us. Furthermore it may be noted that both our 
examples are usually reckoned among achievements of train- 
ing. 

Returning now to the burnt child, this example has made us 
acquainted with the process of change of meaning. We have 
not yet exhausted this example for now we can raise the 
question of how this transformation came about. Why had so 
many repetitions of the experiment no effect and why did the 
result appear so suddenly when it did come? Again our an- 



140 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

swer is given in terms of a description of the event. What 
happens all along in the child's mind? or, if you prefer to 
ignore the existence of the mind, use instead the concepts we 
have just introduced in the case of the chick. At first the in- 
fant sees the attractive flame and reacts correspondingly; then 
the child feels pain and withdraws the hand. According to 
the theory of association and the law of dissatisfaction which 
is the reverse of the law of satisfaction this occurrence ought 
to be sufficient to establish in a very short time in the child's 
mind or in its organism an association between the sight of 
the flame and the withdrawing of the hand. But to all ap- 
pearances it does not do so. As long as the occurrences in the 
child's mind are not changed, no transformation of the re- 
sponse will take place, because the flame remains desirable. 
Only when the pain comes, not merely after reaching for the 
flame, but from the flame itself, can a transformation take 
place, Now the flame itself thwarts the wish of the child, it 
ceases to be an attractive and becomes a repulsive object. This 
transformation of meaning is therefore the consequence of an- 
other process of change. Flame and pain were at first two 
different things: one plus one. Afterwards they grow to- 
gether and become a unit. The two have ceased to be two 
and have become one. 

Here we find another process of transformation which we 
may well call unification. Another example of simple unifi- 
cation is furnished by an experiment performed by Biihler, 
with a method developed in animal psychology, upon his own 
child. A piece of rusk was placed slightly out of the infant's 
reach, with a string attached to it which came within reaching 
distance. Before the end of the 10th month, the child was 
not able to secure the rusk by means of the string. While 
vainly reaching for the rusk it would push the string aside. 
String and rusk were two different objects calling for differ- 
ent reactions. Later on, when the child pulls the string and 
secures the rusk, string and rusk are no longer one plus one, 
but now form a unity in which the string is a subservient part. 
This achievement has been ascribed not to training but to in- 
telligence. Change of meaning gave us the clue that meaning 
was an original property of the receptor processes. Can we 
take a similar clue from-, the process of unification? Or is 
unity of a manifold always the product of experience? 

Comparative and experimental psychology have provided us 
with abundant material for the proof that unitariness is like- 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 141 

wise an original property of perception. Instead of spread- 
ing out this material I shall approach the question from an- 
other angle by demonstrating a third kind of transformation: 
Just as two may become one, so may one become two. Dr. 
Kohler's ape experiments contain many pregnant examples of 
this. But as he will report upon them himself, I shall indicate 
an entirely different field of mental activity in which this kind 
of transformation, which we, appropriately, call analysis, has 
taken place. I refer to the field of magic and its relic super- 
stition. To destroy the original unity between a presage and 
the happy or unhappy event that followed it: to dissect this 
originally coherent unit, whose coherence was like that of the 
tones of a melody, meant a progress in cognition. How diffi- 
cult it may be to take two for two and not for parts of one, is 
shown by the many forms of superstition that still lead a 
vigorous life all about us. That analysis is a difficult process, 
even more so than unification, was also a result of Kohler's 
experiments. This is another indication that the unity of the 
manifold as such is not a product of experience, since the ef- 
fect of experience is that of breaking up such units. 

It should be stated that our unit is not the mental element 
of the association psychology, because being the unit of a mani- 
fold, it deserves to be called a whole. Inside of such wholes 
there occurs a new type of change which may be called artic- 
ulation. Again Kohler's experiments contain splendid speci- 
mens of such processes. To appeal to your own experience: 
Just recall the change that takes place in your idea of a new 
city or a part of the country during the first weeks of your 
stay there. The originally more or less chaotic field gets more 
and more organized, certain main directions develop, a few 
chief points determining the rest are singled out, and accord- 
ingly your behavior in the new surrounding changes. Can 
we infer that articulateness is original or is it altogether a 
product of experience? Again our answer must be that some 
kinds and degrees of articulation must be inherent in the 
original responses, for without this there would be complete 
chaos, in which none of the other properties could exist. 
A|ere chaos can neither be meaningful or unitary. To cut a 
Long story short, we find at the beginning, in our most ele- 
pentary reactions, even at the level of the reflexes and instincts 
and again in training and in intelligent performances, unitary, 
articulate, meaningful wholes; to which we apply the name of 
Gestalt, configuration, structure. Development starts, not with 



142 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

chaos or with a multitude of mental elements without order 
or meaning, but with structures, however primitive their char- 
acter may be. Development proceeds by transformation of 
such structures. Gradually, by a number of smaller or larger 
leaps and bounds, we achieve different orders, different arti- 
culations, different meanings. I have just tried to sketch a 
few of the main processes which occur in this development in 
very general outline. The picture has to be completed. We 
must apply our general principles to concrete cases, we must 
study the different achievements in this genetic sequence, and 
must learn to understand how one achievement facilitates or 
even makes possible another achievement. This task, though 
its actual execution is just in the beginning, falls outside the 
scope of this lecture. One problem, however, I must take up : 
What is the cause of these transformations? Our answer, 
naturally, can only be very general. Wherever change occurs 
the phenomenal situation aroused by the real situation is in- 
complete," unstable. It tends to become stabilized. But 
whether it can become so depends upon the kind of situation 
and upon the individual organism. We call an organism that 
succeeds in filling the gap clever, and one that does not stupid, 
but it is obvious that these terms are always relative to the 
situations; for there are many situations in which all of us 
are utterly stupid. 

The last reason then for all these changes lies in the original 
processes themselves. All processes not stationary exert pres- 
sure upon the system to become stable ; if the system can yield 
to this pressure, then the result is achieved. 

We can express these facts in still another way : Wertheimer 
was the first to state a law, which has served as a good guide 
in our experimental research and which has been given theo- 
retical support by Kohler. This law, the law of precision, 
maintains that any configuration will become as perfect as the 
prevailing cpnditions admit. Vague as it seems in this formu- 
lation, it has a definite meaning in several concrete instances 
and will become more and more defined the farther psychology 
progresses. In the closing words of this lecture I shall indi- 
cate an application of this law and thereby supplement in a 
casual way the picture I have drawn of mental development. 

So far I have been almost exclusively concerned with what 
may be called intellectual achievements. But what of the 
moral side of mind; what of a man's character and personal- 
ity? Must these escape our scheme of development? I think 



MENTAL DEVELOPMENT 143 

not. The behavior of an organism shapes configuration also 
in time. Not only the simultaneous but the successive is also 
structured. The larger these wholes and the greater their 
unity, articulation and meaning, the more perfect is their ges- 
talt, the more personality will they express. 

Is the theory so sketchily drawn before your eyes Unitarian 
or pluralistic? It is pluralistic in as much as it embraces an 
indefinite number of different structures and many forms of 
configurative changes; but it is not pluralistic in the sense of 
assuming a number of separate faculties like those of reflexes 
or instincts, training and intelligence. It is Unitarian, not in 
reducing every process to the mechanism of neural bonds or 
associations, but in its attempt to give ultimately an explana- 
tion of development by means of the universal law of Gestalt 




WOLFGANG KOHLER 



CHAPTER VII 

INTELLIGENCE IN APES* 



By WOLFGANG KOHLER 



The following pages contain the description of some types of 
anthropoid behavior and a few remarks intended to make us 
better realize what problems are given in those cases. That 
animal psychology has to be a science of behavior and that 
the introduction of animal consciousness as an acting factor 
in problems and explanations would only lead into confusion 
is my opinion as it is the axiom of behaviorism in this country. 
If, notwithstanding that, I frequently use terms which may 
suggest the heresy of assuming consciousness, the reason for 
it and my innocence will become apparent with time. I can 
not agree with Watson in his method of condemning all diffi- 
cult-looking problems in the nervous system as pure mysticism 
and after effects of the introspection time. That gives a 
simple science with only a few concepts; but a good deal of 
the world of behavior and its problems does not occur in this 
science. I therefore make a difference between a dogmatic 
behaviorism which narrows its own world of realities, prob- 
lems and theoretical possibilities as if knowing beforehand 
what kind of things can occur in an exact world, and another 
behaviorism which wants to see as many forms of behavior, 
problems and theoretical possibilities as possible, deeply con- 
vinced that even his amplest view of the world will probably 
come far short of the wealth of phenomena themselves. I 
prefer the second. 

If we observe the faces of anthropoid apes, of monkeys and 
of dogs, quite naively, we get the impression that those faces 
show very different degrees of "understanding" or "insight/* 
Observation of the animals in action and experimentation on 
them prove that our expectation was justified, at least with 
regard to the high place we would tend to give to the apes. 

Let us take as an example Hunter's method of delayed re- 
action 1 which I shall describe in a simplified form for our pur- 
poses. If one of the higher vertebrates sees in front of him- 
self three open doors and in one of them food, he will, if he 
is hungry and the circumstances allow it, move in the direction 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, April 
30, 1925. 
x Behavior Monographs II, 1. 1913. 



146 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of this food and eat it. If in different cases different doorf 
are used as "doors with food" the reaction will, of course, 
change its direction correspondingly. To choose the right door 
becomes more difficult, however, if the animal remains en- 
closed in a box at the time the food is presented to him in one 
of the doors, so that he can see the food through this obstacle 
but is released only after the food has disappeared in the box 
behind the door. Animals below the monkeys find great diffi- 
culties with this task. Even if the interval of delay between 
exposure of the food and reaction is of some seconds or a 
minute only, the after effect of the past perception (in human 
language: "It was that door!") seems to become confused, 
and in some cases one cannot be quite sure whether an after 
effect of this kind does exist at all or whether positive results 
are produced by quite a crude and low form of behavior. 2 

In experimenting with chimpanzees, I used a somewhat dif- 
ferent method. The ape was sitting behind the bars of his 
cage. On the other side of these bars I made a hole in the 
ground, put some fruit in it, and covered the hole and the 
surroundings with sand. The ape, who with great interest 
had observed what I did, could not reach the place of the food 
because it was too far away for his arm; but when I was 
careless enough to come too near his cage he immediately 
seized my arm and tried to push it in the direction of the hid- 
den food, as he would do whenever he could not find a method 
of approach towards his food himself. Of course this was 
already a delayed reaction. But as I wanted a larger delay 
I did not do him the favor, and the ape began soon to play 
in his room apparently not giving any attention to the place 
of the food. After three quarters of an hour a stick was 
thrown into his cage from the side farthest from the fruit. 
The ape accustomed to the use of sticks as instruments, in- 
stantly took it, went to the bars nearest the place of the food, 
began to scratch away the sand exactly in the right spot, and 
pulled the fruit toward him. Repetitions of the experiment 
with other positions of the food had the same result 

Since the reaction was always surprisingly correct I made 
the interval of delay much greater. I let the apes see how 



'With animals of a highly developed olfactory sense the utmost 
care is needed in order to avoid olfactory cues at the time of re- 
action. However, in the case of anthropoid apes this danger is not 
very serious, since their olfactory sense is, as one may easily prove, 
more or less at a level with our 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 147 

I buried the food somewhere in the earth of the very large 
playground and brought them, immediately afterwards, into 
their sleeping room so that they went on the playground not 
before the following day when more than seventeen hours 
had elapsed, more than half of them spent sleeping. One of 
the apes, when leaving the sleeping room, did not hesitate a 
moment but went straight to the place of the food and found 
it there after some searching. 3 

In another experiment a stick was hidden in the wooden 
framework of the roof, where the apes could not see it from 
the ground. Again they observed with great interest our un- 
usual action. But we at once brought them into their dormi- 
tory. The next morning, when one of them came back into 
the same room, he discovered some bananas on the ground 
outside the cage and too far away for his arm. As apes, ac- 
customed to the use of sticks, do under these circumstances, 
he looked around in exactly the way of a man seeking some- 
thing, but could not find such a tool. After some seconds, 
however, his eyes went up to the place where the stick was 
hidden the evening before. He could not see it, but he climbed 
at once in the shortest possible way up to that part of the ceil- 
ing where the stick was hidden, came down with it, and 
scratched the food towards him. I repeated the experiment 
with all the chimpanzees who had seen how we put the stick 
in its place in the roof. They all independently solved the 
problem in the same manner. 

"Memory" works in two different ways at least Many 
animals and men learn to react to a given situation in a speci- 
fied manner, i.e., they develop habits. There are great dif- 
ferences in the speed of learning, in the number of different 
situations for which a reaction may be learned, and in the 
complexity of reactions which are learned. But even the 
earthworm shows "memory" of this general type by acquiring 
a very simple habit of moving in a definite spatial form. In 
the second type of memory something more seems to be re- 
quired : An important part of a situation is not actually pres- 



*One might say that the place of the food attracted the ape not 
because he knew there was food but because, in consequence of my 
digging, this place looked unusual and was only therefore attractive 
to the ape. It did not look unusual to my eyes as I had covered 
the whole region with dry sand. However, to meet this criticism 
better I made several holes in the ground after the apes were en- 
closed in the house and filled them afterwards in the same manner 
as the right hole. But the ape went to the right one. 



148 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

ent in perception, but it was seen somewhere at another time, 
and its existence may be taken account of in the response, if 
that knowledge is still active or becomes active in the given 
situation. Where we have memory of this kind it makes the 
life and behavior of an animal look incomparably larger and 
freer than all habit formation can do. But there is not much 
evidence of it in most animals, and I do not know if even 
monkeys would show such a surprising behavior as I found 
in the champanzees. 4 

But perhaps these experiments do not examine intelligence 
in the strict meaning of the word. Therefore I describe an- 
other type of behavior which may have more to do with in- 
telligence proper. You must know one of the usual forms of 
experimentation with animals. The subject is confronted with 
two or more objects and learns to choose one of them, de- 
pending upon its position in space or its color or some other 
discriminating quality. This effect is produced by rewarding 
the animal each time it chooses the right object and perhaps 
punishing it whenever it chooses the wrong one. Learning of 
this kind is usually a slow process without any indication of 
higher processes being involved. The curve of learning which 
shows how the number of wrong choices decreases with time 
has an irregular but gradually descending form. One might 
expect an ape to solve simple tasks of this type in shorter time. 
But that is not always the case. Often the period of learning 
in anthropoids is at least as long as with lower animals. How- 
ever, the form of learning is sometimes quite different from 
what is found in the case of lower vertebrates. 

When Yerkes made experiments of the general type de- 
scribed 5 with an orang-utan, this ape did not make any real 



^"Delayed reaction" in animals lower than apes has seemed to 
some degree explainable by the fact that the animal, when the 
original stimulus (for instance, the food) is shown, quite naturally 
turns in the corresponding direction, and that it often remains in 
this bodily orientation by a kind of simple inertia after the stimulus 
is withdrawn, whereupon very probably it will go on in this right 
direction after release, if no other incentive makes it turn to the 
left or to the right. Of course, the chimpanzees did not remain in 
the right orientation, neither in three quarters of an hour nor in 
seventeen hours. Their delayed reaction cannot be explained so 
simply. To be sure, many cases of delayed reaction in lower ani- 
mals cannot either, 

6 It does not matter for our present discussion that the experiments 
were t dealing with "multiple choice" instead of the simpler sensory 
discrimination. 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES ' 149 



progress at all for a long time, whereas some animals much 
lower in rank solved the same problem without great difficulty. 
But finally, when the experimenter had almost lost hope of 
making the orang solve his task, the ape after one right choice 
suddenly mastered the problem completely, i.e., never again 
made a mistake. He had solved the problem in one lucky 
moment, his curve of learning showing an altogether abrupt 
descent. 6 Some of my experiences on the learning process in 
chimpanzees are very similar to this observation of Yerkes. 
Sometimes the same surprising fact is found in children, and 
one can hardly avoid the impression that this ape behaves like 
a man under similar circumstances who, after a while, in a 
certain individual experiment, would grasp the principle of 
the problem and say to himself, "Oh, that's the point! Al- 
ways the dark object!"; of course with the consequence that 
he, too, would never make a mistake again. 

We do not well describe experiments of this type by say- 
ing, as we usually do, that an animal in such a situation learns 
to connect certain stimuli with certain reactions and that this 
connection is "stamped in." This formulation of the process 
gives too much importance to the memory or association side 
of the problem, and it neglects another side of it which may 
be even more important and more difficult. 

Although so much has been said against "anthropomor- 
phism" in animal psychology, we have here a persisting case 
of this error, committed not by dilettants but by very eminent 
men of science. The experimenter is interested in a problem 
of sensory discrimination and builds an appropriate apparatus 
which shall present "the stimuli" to the animal in question. 
When he looks upon the situation which he has created him- 
self, this situation is completely organized for him, "the stim- 
uli" being the outstanding features of it, and all the rest form- 
ing an unimportant background. Consequently he formulates 
the animal's task as one of connecting "these stimuli" with 
certain reactions, reward and punishment enforcing this con- 
nection. But he is not aware of the fact that now he has 
credited the animal with the same organized situation whidb 
exists for himself, the experimenter, in consequence of his sci- 
entific aim and problem. Certainly the experimenter sees the 
stimuli as dominating the situation whenever he looks upon 
it. But why should the same organization exist in the sensory 
situation of the innocent animal? Experience shows that au 

'Behavior Monographs III, 1. 1916. 



150 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

objective situation may appear in very different organizations. 
Formation of groups and forms in the field is the na- 
tural outcome of many constellations of stimuli. Some part of 
the field may also have an accent, or be dominating, spontane- 
ously. However, under the influence of interests, of previous 
experiences, etc., this original organization tends to change 
into new ones. We have not yet studied these processes in 
the case of animals, but one thing appears evident from the 
first moment : It is altogether improbable that an animal, when 
confronted with a new situation of discrimination experiments, 
should at the outset have the same organization of the field 
which exists in the experimenter's thought and perception. 

Perhaps in this respect the animal's perception of the field 
is much more different from that of the experimenter than a 
young student's first perception of brain tissue in the micro- 
scope is different from that of the trained neurologist. This 
student cannot react immediately, and in a definite way, to the 
differences in the structure of tissues which dominate in the 
professor's microscopic field, because the student does not yet 
see the field in this organization. Even so, the student at least 
knows that in this situation his actual experiences of tempera- 
ture, touch, muscular sense, noises, smells, and the optical 
world outside the microscopic field shall be without any im- 
portance. Nothing of this eliminating knowledge is given to 
the animal, who is put in an apparatus and there shall learn 
"to connect the stimuli with the reactions," but who really 
is subjected to a world of sensory data in the surroundings 
and in himself. Whatever the first organization of these data 
may be it cannot possibly correspond to the very special or- 
ganization which the experimenter sees. Therefore the ques- 
tion arises as one of the greatest importance: What role does 
the actual manner in which the situation appears to the ani- 
mal play in his reactions and in the learning process? And 
further, is learning going on independently of this factor and 
of possible changes in the organization of the field? Or is re- 
organization, which would make "the stimuli" outstanding 
features in the field, perhaps an important part of the prob- 
lem? In this case, does the animal need so many trials as it 
really receives for the building up of a connection of stimuli 
and reaction, or does he need those trials for the right or- 
ganization of the field, so that eventually there is- the right 
thing to undergo the right connection? Finally, does the 
stress of reward and punishment exert any influence in the di- 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 151 

rection of such a reorganization? If not, how else is the re- 
organization produced? 

As yet we cannot answer these questions, so far as the 
lower vertebrates are concerned. But the observations of 
Yerkes and my own make it rather probable that in anthropoid 
apes at least the same thing may occur under favorable con- 
ditions that is so common in man: After some experience in 
a new situation he has to deal with, a sudden change into a 
reorganization appropriate to the task, with the accents on the 
right places. We may even suspect that afterwards not very 
much time is needed for a connection between the now out- 
standing stimuli and the reaction, if ever there was a real sep- 
aration of the two tasks. Animals often learn so surprisingly 
fast under the natural conditions of their life, when an object 
they are already attending to shows "good" or "bad" prop- 
erties. 

If there is something in these remarks, we may be com- 
pelled to make a revision of our theories of learning. But cer- 
tainly not without new experience! Because, though we al- 
ready know something about organization and reorganization 
of sensory fields in man, we know hardly anything about it in 
animals ; and therefore I propose to experiment about it. We 
have methods for it. Even so, however, we may at least ven- 
ture one simple hypothesis ; namely, that in animals, as in man, 
the manner of presentation of the stimuli in a field will have 
a strong influence on the forthcoming organization. A prac- 
tical consequence of this hypothesis is that we should be able 
to help the animals very much in their learning by presenting 
the stimuli in such a form and in such surroundings and gen- 
eral conditions that they tend to become the dominating fac- 
tors of the situation spontaneously. (It is not the place here 
to explain how that may be done.) 

But the situation consists of more than the sensory field 
only. There is reward and punishment in it; and in the ani- 
mal, as their consequence, there is presumably something like 
physiological stress as the working motor of the reorganiza- 
tion and learning. We speak of them as of separate things, 
but it is reward, punishment and stress in the reaction to the 
field which seems to bring about reorganization and learning. 
It might be, therefore, that a more intimate connection of 
stimuli and reward or punishment will shorten the period of 
learning considerably. The electric shock, for instance, ap- 
plied to the legs, is not intimately connected with the task of 



152 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

getting a red spot as "the negative stimulus." There is only 
a very loose connection between them in space and time. If 
that spot itself would make a sudden movement against the 
animal and so frighten it whenever it goes the wrong way, we 
should certainly have a situation much nearer the animal's 
learning in common life and a more efficient one because the 
negative stimulus is directly made outstanding thereby and at 
the same time immediately imbues itself with "negativity." 

With champanzees I went further. Clever apes can even 
be "taught." By all possible means you may draw their at- 
tention to the color of two boxes (or their difference) and 
you may show at the same time that inside the box of one 
color there is nothing ; whereas behind the walls with the other 
color there is a banana. Whenever I proceeded so, forgetting 
the rule that an experimenter shall not play any direct role 
in experiments with animals, a striking increase of right 
choices used to be the immediate effect. And why not forget 
that rule, provided our principal intention in the actual ex- 
periment is not the study of the most clumsy form of learning 
but to make the chimpanzee master his problem as fast as pos- 
sible ? We teach our children this way, and only a bad teacher 
would not be able to verify afterwards if the result of learn- 
ing is independent of himself. Nothing easier than to find 
out in a chimpanzee if afterwards the result is genuine or de- 
pends upon a wrong cue (the experimenter.) 7 

Since it seems to me of some importance for our science 
that animal psychologists acknowledge these new problems in 
the general field of learning, I wish to defend myself against 
one reproach. Do not these problems exist only if we intro- 
duce the consciousness of animals? So many of the expres- 
sions used in the description of experiments and in the ex- 
position of the problems seem to involve the assumption of 
consciousness. If that is so, the orthodox behaviorist will 
jump back and solemnly declare that he has nothing whatever 
to do with those rather mystical organizations and reorganiza- 
tions of the field or the situation and that as a man of natural 
science he will go on formulating his problems in terms of 
stimuli and reactions. 

My answer is that none of my expressions was meant to 
imply consciousness. Nobody can describe the behavior of 

In a new method which we found working well with apes, we 
eventually eliminated from the study of the sensory field all learn- 
ing by chance reactions. (Psychol. Forschung I, 390. 1922). 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 153 

higher animals in its rich and concrete reality without using 
terms which are ambiguous in so far as they mean behavior but 
may at the same time imply consciousness. I always use them 
in the first meaning. Let us take an example: "The ape ob- 
served with great interest what I did." Can an ape "observe," 
can an ape have "interest" without having consciousness? Can 
I state that his "observation" was directed upon my actions 
without assuming consciousness in the ape? I do not know 
whether in those cases the ape has consciousness or not. And 
I can go on without knowing it, because "to observe a thing" 
is a term which in everyday life, too, has a perfectly objective 
meaning, a certain visible and very characteristic behavior to- 
wards something being called so. I deny absolutely that we 
always or even often mean consciousness or think about con- 
sciousness of the people when we see the chemist, the police- 
man, etc., "observe" a chemical reaction, a suspicious car, etc. 
It is the same thing with "interest." A man or a chimpanzee 
looks "interested." A visible and again a highly characteristic 
attitude is meant in most of the cases where we use this word. 

But why not use terms which are free from all ambiguities 
and can only suggest objective attitudes and forms of be- 
havior ? Because we have no terms of this kind. Or, if 
there are some, they are not manifold and nuanced enough to 
suggest to readers all the many attitudes and forms of be- 
havior which are seen in the higher animals or man. To de- 
scribe the contraction of all the muscles which are employed 
when the chemist, the policeman, or a chimpanzee look "in- 
terested" would be beyond my forces. And, by the way, no- 
body would understand me, unless I added the remark: "You 
know, I mean those movements which, as a whole, produce 
the interested attitude," and there we would be again! On 
the other hand, if once for all the meaning of those terms is 
restricted to behavior, where is the danger in using them? 
And if we should decide never to use them, one consequence 
would be unavoidable: Our description of behavior would 
become extremely poor, not more than a meager rest of the 
concrete world of behavior would be accepted in our science; 
and our theoretical concepts would very soon be exactly as 
poor and meager as our material. 

However, this defense holds for the description of behavior 
only. The behaviorist would at once point out that in ex- 
plaining the alleged problem of organization I have mentioned 
the animal's perception of the field and laid much stress on 



154 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the organization in which the field appears to the animal. But 
I must answer again that for my use of these words it has no 
importance whether or not the animal has consciousness. 
Only two assumptions are contained in these formulations. 
The first is that in the higher animals some parts of the cen- 
tral nervous system are the place of sensory processes, cor* 
responding to the stimulation from without, just as certain 
fields of the brain in man are shown by an overwhelming 
evidence from pathology to be the stage of sensory processes. 
And I use the words "perception of the situation" when I 
mean the totality of these processes. One would be con- 
demned to clumsy and boresome forms of speech if con- 
venient terms of this kind were forbidden by the puritans of 
behaviorism. The second assumption, which introduces the 
physiological side of "Gestalt" psychology (as applied to the 
sensory field), is a working hypothesis about a general prop- 
erty of those sensory processes. Even the behaviorist who 
formulates his problems in terms of stimuli and reactions must 
assume that something happens between the former and the 
latter in the central nervous system. He tends to deny that 
any specific problems are to be solved in this region, between 
sense organs and reacting organs. But this also is an hy- 
pothesis and a rather vague one, to be sure. One problem at 
least must be accepted as such. We have conductors between 
the sense organ, the eye, for instance, and the reacting or- 
gans; and these conductors lead from one to the other as a 
kind of dense network. Either I assume that from one point 
of the retina one conductor goes absolutely isolated to one re- 
acting organ, a second conductor from another point of the 
eye again isolated to the same or to another reacting organ, 
and so on. In this case there is really not much to ask about 
the intermediate region. Or, I realize that the network is 
not very apt to be a sum of totally isolated conductors. And 
in this case I must admit that the simplest rules of physics 
are to be applied to the network, the processes in one con- 
ductor becoming functionally dependent on the processes in 
all the others, and vice versa. "Conduction" between the sense 
organ and the reacting organs means now a problem of speci- 
fic process distribution, in its most general aspects similar to 
problems of process distribution in physics. And the effect 
on the reacting organs, and therefore on behavior, will di- 
rectly depend on this process distribution. It is this dynamic 
distribution which I am alluding to when I speak about or- 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 155 

ganization of the sensory processes. And I cannot see that 
so conceived this term means anything mysterious; though the 
main thing about it is to discover the concrete properties of 
the distribution of which we know but little. Of course this 
organization depends upon the stimulation, but certainly not 
in the manner it would depend upon it if all conductors were 
isolated from each other. And to say that a study of behavior 
must be the investigation of reactions as dependent upon "the 
stimuli'* turns out now to be a somewhat confused program, 
very apt to hide this fundamental problem altogether : How do 
the sensory processes depend on a given set of stimuli ? How, 
therefore, the organization of the field, and how the reactions ? 
We shall speak about it later on. 

One may consider as a third assumption (though it is a 
necessary one) that the distribution or organization of sensory 
processes shall not depend upon the constellation of stimuli 
only but on the total interior situation in the animal, too, so 
that influences like hunger, fear, rage, fatigue and organiza- 
tion in earlier experience can produce changes in a given dis- 
tribution. But in this respect the behaviorist, if once he ad- 
mits the problem of organization at all, would certainly have 
the same opinion. 8 

More than one psychologist would say that an animal who 
(like Yerkes' orang) suddenly "grasps" the principle of a 
situation in learning experiments thereby shows a genuine type 
of intelligent behavior. But we can apply another test of per- 
haps more significance. An example frequently to be observed 
in the classroom will show you what I mean. 

I try to explain to my students a somewhat difficult demon- 
stration of a mathematical theory, putting all my sentences to- 
gether with the utmost care in the right sequence and with all 
possible clearness. I shall probably not have much success in 
my first performance. Something remains dull in the faces 
of my audience. So I repeat what I have said, and perhaps 
in the course of the third repetition one face here, another 
there, will suddenly undergo a marked change toward "bright- 
ness." Soon afterwards I may call the owner of one of those 
changed faces to the blackboard, and he will be able to give 

8 I shall not deny that the emphasis I lay upon this problem is 
largely determined by observations on man, even by observation 
of what I see. But why not? Most of tie best work done in 
animal psychology was suggested by experiences in man. So the 
experiments in color discrimination, on the Purkinje phenomenon, 
on contrast, on the effect of distribution in learning, etc. 



156 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the demonstration himself, we might say, to imitate what I 
performed before. Something has happened between the sen- 
tences of the demonstration in this clever student's mind, 
something important enough to become immediately visible in 
the change of his outer aspect and to make a new performance 
possible. 

If we try to apply this experience to experimentation with 
apes we can't, of course, make use of speech, in giving the 
model, and instead of mathematics, too, we have to choose 
another kind of problem. What is the effect on an ape if he 
sees another ape or a human being perform a certain action 
which, if imitated by the ape, would be of the greatest advan- 
tage for him? Here perhaps the objection may be raised that 
an ape imitating what he sees done by others does not at all 
show intelligence. Are not monkeys and apes endowed with 
a special instinct to imitate almost all acts which they see per- 
formed in their neighborhood? If, then, they do it under ex- 
perimental conditions, too, what can we conclude? 

But in this case a widespread opinion is an absolutely wrong 
one, and the idea or the belief that monkeys and apes are con- 
stantly imitating the behavior of others seems to have the 
following origin. Monkeys and apes make a strong impres- 
sion on us by some striking similarity between their behavior 
and the behavior of man. Don't they use their hands in the 
same manner as human beings ? Don't their faces show similar 
"expressions" to those of man in many states of emotion? 
All this is easily explained, if the primates find a special pleas- 
ure in copying, or are mechanically compelled to copy the at- 
titudes and the behavior of man. However, monkeys and 
apes who are caught somewhere in the woods of Central Africa 
or Asia show the same similarity with man's behavior from 
the first moment, before any experiences with the behavior of 
human beings could begin to have such an influence. The 
similarity with man is a natural one and does not prove at all 
the working of a strong "instinct of imitation." 

In fact, there is not such an instinct. Imitation is almost 
as difficult for apes and as rare in them as it is in lower ver- 
tebrates. One does observe imitation of different forms or 
types in apes, but not so very often, and only after certain 
conditions are fulfilled. One first type of imitation which I 
saw with surprise in chimpanzees is very well known from 
observation in children. When the workman has been in our 
house and the children have, of course, observed with greatest 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 157 

interest what he was doing, we may see, on the same or the 
following day, how the children with the help of some objects, 
.a book, a stone, or a wooden board, are copying what seemed 
to them essential in the performance of the man, in sawing, 
nailing or boring. Let me call this behavior of children a 
"serious play." It is a play, but it is serious at the same time, 
as many plays of our children are, the child feeling himself 
important in assuming the role of the artisan. If somebody 
"laughs about the play, the pleasure in it is usually spoiled. 

I would call the following behavior of a chimpanzee imita- 
tion of the "serious play" type. On the playground a man 
has painted a wooden pole in white color. After the work is 
done he goes away leaving behind a pot of white paint and a 
"beautiful brush. I observe the only chimpanzee who is pres- 
ent, hiding my face behind my hands, as if I were not paying 
attention to him. The ape for a while gives much attention 
to me before approaching the brush and the paint because he 
has learned that misuse of our things may have serious con- 
sequences. But very soon, encouraged by my attitude, he 
takes the brush, puts it into the pot of color and paints a big 
.stone which happens to be in the place, beautifully white. The 
whole time the ape behaved completely seriously. So did 
others when imitating the washing of laundry or the use of a 
torer. 

Our modern civilization has made us judge all things with 
special regard to their practical value I think, too much so. 
My chimpanzee's painting is just a play without such a value. 
Therefore we ask if the ape will also imitate when the model 
is an act of practical importance for him, i.e., will he do it in 
a form which is "more than play." There are cases of this 
kind. 

One day a chimpanzee was not fed in the morning, his food 
being fastened on the ceiling of the room. A box was put 
on the ground some yards apart, but the chimpanzee did not 
use it. Indeed he never had used a box as an instrument be- 
fore. In vain he tried to reach his food by jumping or by 
climbing up on the walls and along the ceiling. Eventually 
he became so fatigued that he went several times to the box 
to sit and relax a little, while his eyes looked sadly up to the 
food. After many hours in which no indication of the solu- 
tion of the simple problem became visible I took the box, put 
it under the food, climbed up and touched the food with my 
hands, then stepped down again and threw the box some yards 



158 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

away. In less than a minute the chimpanzee began to eat be- 
cause, now, he took the box and used it as I had done, only 
that he did take the fruit with him. 

Another example: when food was fastened in the ceiling 
near to the house of the animals, they would open the next 
door, turn it in the direction of the fruit, and climb up as in 
the case of the box. One day I made this trick more difficult 
by fastening the door on the wall by means of a hook and a 
ring, in order to see what a chimpanzee would do under these 
new conditions. The ape whom I chose for the experiment 
tried to open the door, but failed completely since he did not 
give any attention to the hook and the ring. Chimpanzees 
do not easily see that such a small object (hook and ring) can 
be of importance for the movements of a large one (the door). 
Finally, the animal gave up, but he watched me attentively 
when I approached the door, lifted the hook and turned the 
door a little. At this moment he gave a cry of surprise, very 
similar in chimpanzees to the corresponding emotional ex- 
pression in man, and I hardly had re-established the connection 
of hook and ring when the ape was already at my side, opened 
the hook, turned the door towards the food and solved the 
problem. 

These cases may easily produce an illusion as though imita- 
tion were really an easy matter and not an achievement of 
some significance. But we have only to repeat one of these 
experiments with a less intelligent ape in order to see that cer- 
tain conditions must be fulfilled before imitation becomes pos- 
sible. One of the chimpanzees at Teneriff e was almost stupid ; 
at least when compared with the other apes. He had been 
present a great many times when other chimpanzees had used 
the box as a tool for reaching objects in high places. So, 
eventually, I expected this animal to be able to do the same 
thing when left alone in such a situation, i.e., with a banana 
somewhere in the ceiling, a box some yards apart on the 
ground. The ape went to the box; but instead of moving it 
in the direction of the food, he either climbed up on the box 
and jumped from there vertically in the air, though the food 
was elsewhere, or he tried to jump from the ground and to 
reach the banana. The others showed him the simple per- 
formance a number of times, but he could not imitate them 
and only copied parts of their behavior which, without the 
right connection in the whole act, did not help him at all He 
climbed up on the box, ran from there under the banana, and 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 159 

jumped again from the ground. Decidedly the right connec- 
tion of box and food in this situation was not yet apparent to 
our chimpanzee. Sometimes he moved the box a little from 
its place, but as often as not away from the food. Only af- 
ter many more demonstrations of the simple act did he finally 
learn to do it in a manner which I cannot describe briefly. 
One sees there is a serious task in learning by imitation even 
for a less intelligent ape. An intelligent chimpanzee, observ- 
ing another in this little performance will, for instance, soon 
become aware that moving the box means from the first mo- 
ment moving it to a place underneath the food, the movement 
will be grasped as one with this essential orientation, whereas 
a stupid animal sees first the movement of the box, not re- 
lating it instantly to the place of the food. He will observe 
single phases of the whole performance, but he will not per- 
ceive them as parts related to the essential structure of the 
situation, in which alone they are parts of the solution. Of 
course this right organization is not simply given in the se- 
quence of retinal images which the action of the imitatee pro- 
duces. It is with imitation as with teaching. When teaching 
children we can only give some favorable conditions or 
"marks" for the new things which the child has "to learn/' 
and the child has always to furnish something from his side 
which we may call "understanding" and which sometimes 
seems to arise suddenly, corresponding to the marks given by 
us. Nobody can simply pour it into the child. 

If apes in some cases are able to "see" the necessary con- 
nection between the parts of a performance which they ob- 
serve and the essentials of the situation, the question naturally 
arises whether or not the same apes sometimes invent similar 
performances as solutions in a new situation. An ape who 
sees a box obliquely underneath some fruits hanging down 
from the ceiling will soon try to reach these fruits from the 
top of the box. Since the box is not quite correctly situated 
and therefore the ape perhaps cannot reach the food immedi- 
ately, does he "understand the situation" and move the box a 
little until it is more or less exactly below the food. I have 
described elsewhere how chimpanzees really solve simple prob- 
lems of this type without the help of teaching or the model 
performance of another. As this description is now translated 
into the English language there is no need of repeating it at 
this time. 

But let me mention one side of the ape's behavior in many 



160 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of these experiments. An ape who has often used a stick as: 
an instrument, when he found his food on the ground beyond 
the bars of his cage, finds it there again beyond the reach of 
his arms. But no stick is in his room, only a little tree is there, 
a stem dividing into two or three branches. For a long time 
the ape does not find a solution. He knows about sticks and 
their use, and now there is a tree. But he does not see parts 
of the tree as possible sticks. Later on he suddenly finds the 
solution, goes to the tree, breaks off one of the branches, and 
uses it as a stick. But it appears to me important that for 
quite a while the tree does not seem to have any connection 
with the problem. Human beings, accustomed to analyzing 
and reorganizing the structure of their surroundings with re- 
lation to a problem, would see the branches as possible sticks 
from the first moment. In order to understand the ape's be- 
havior from the human standpoint, we must take a somewhat 
more difficult structure than the simple tree with its branches. 
Let us suppose that for some reason or other you want a 
wooden frame of the following form: \ In your room 
there is not such a thing. Some other wooden frames namely : 



CT3 

do not look in the first moment as if they would be of any 
use in your situation, even if you apply the saw, which may 
be the only instrument available. To be sure, after I made 
the preceding remarks about the ape you begin to analyse 
these forms because you must suspect now that there I have 
"hidden" the frame you want. And so you find it very soon 
in the "j^. But wouldn't you give up, perhaps, in the case that 
such a suspicion were not aroused beforehand, those forms 
looking like casual parts of your surroundings? For the men- 
tal level of the chimpanzee, the tree seems to be, with regard 
to the stick (the branch), what the group of forms and es- 
pecially the ] is for us with regard to that frame : The part 
which we^ might use is not an optical reality as a part in the 
whole which is given originally. It may become such a reality 
by a transformation. Reorganization of the surroundings 
under the stress of a given situation would then again be an 
essential side of the task and at the same time its main diffi- 
culty. 



INTELLIGENCE OF APES 161 

I know that several psychologists will not easily believe that 
my description o intelligent behavior in apes is correct- An 
almost negativistic attitude has developed in animal psychology, 
so that we all are afraid of being criticized on account of an- 
thropomorphic tendencies if our description of animal behavior 
is not denying but showing some higher forms of processes. 
Therefore I have made moving pictures of some experiments 
of this type. They are much more convincing than all words 
and arguments which I might add in order to corroborate my 
statements ; but we have no technique to give this strongest ar- 
gument to the readers of a scientific journal. 



CHAPTER VIII 

AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY* 



BY WOLFGANG KOHLER 



What we call "Gestalt psychology" means a new point of 
view and a new procedure in various respects, and in several 
parts of psychology, so that it is far beyond my power to give 
a complete and adequate idea of it in one lecture. If I try 
to speak in general terms about it, my statements will needs 
sound vague and you cannot see how they are to be applied in 
concrete cases. And if I try to show how, in a more special 
field of our science, the problems and the procedure of Gestalt 
psychology develop, many sides and consequences of the new 
concepts cannot possibly become visible, and you shall probably 
take as a central position of Gestalt psychology what really 
is only one of its applications. Since, in my judgement, the 
second danger is less important than the possibility that very 
general statements would not give you any concrete idea at 
all, I prefer the risk which is the natural consequence of ex- 
emplification in a special kind of problem; and I shall try to 
show you how Gestalt psychology treats some sides of our sen- 
sory experience, more especially, how the new ideas deal with 
the visual field in a state of rest. 

One of the fundamental methods of natural sciences is 
analysis. The psychologist, therefore, confronted with a 
complex field of vision, for example, feels naturally inclined 
to analyze this field into smaller and simpler entities whose 
properties he may study with more ease and with more 
hope of clear results than an immediate consideration of the 
whole field would yield. Generally he does not ask himself 
what this procedure purports and if, perhaps, the term analysis 
has more than one connotation. He simply analyzes down to 
very small parts of the sensory field let us call them the "sen- 
sations" which do not contain differences, which show a min- 
imum of area, and so seem to constitute the simplest parts of 
the field. Only gradually do we now become aware of the 
fact that at this very starting point of investigation at least 
two ambiguities must be carefully avoided. 

Let us take an instance from the physical world: If we 
want to study the air which is surrounding us in this room, 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
May 1, 1925. 



164 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

we also shall feel inclined to analyze it. We may do that in 
different ways. Either our attention picks out a "differential" 
of this volume of air, i. e., an extremely small volume which 
may be regarded as homogeneous in density, temperature, etc. ; 
or we concentrate our attention on one molecule, say O 2 . In 
the first case, everybody knows he is not treating a real element 
of the air, he knows the differential is not defined by some 
objective physical properties, as if its interior were kept to- 
gether somehow, no such keeping together occuring beyond 
the limits of the differential between different differentials; 
he knows, therefore, that the limits of the differential are 
existing in thought only. On the other hand, when taking 
the molecule as the final product of our analysis, we mean 
exactly an element of the other character: It is well defined 
physically as a real unit; mutual inner forces which keep the 
interior of it together are not, in comparable degree, uniting 
parts of one molecule with those of another. In order to get 
differentials our thought imagines arbitrarily separating sur- 
faces in the medium; where a molecule is, begins and ends is 
a question which nature has made out; the molecule is an 
objective unit 

Does a sensation belong to the first or the second type? 
If we do not like to answer this question for the sensation as 
a supposed part of "consciousness", I will ask the same question 
for the physiological processes underlying the sensory field. It 
would hardly be indifferent for the sensation or the sensory field 
whether the process corresponding to the sensation must be 
treated as a differential or as a molecule of the total field. We 
should probably make different theories of sensory experience 
corresponding to our choice of one or the other of these fund- 
amental possibilities. In the psychological literature, however, 
this alternative is hardly mentioned. So far sensation is a 
vague concept, and the conquences of our use of this con- 
cept will correspond to this state of affairs. 

The second ambiguity of our concept, certainly related to 
the first, may again be made dear by an example from physics. 
I can connect two rooms by a number of tubes or pipes ; and I 
can, in one room, press water into each of them separately, 
so that in the other room jets of water come separately out 
of each pipe and fall in separate receptacles. In this case we 
have real elements before us, isolated streams of water, which 
are so totally independent of each other that from the stand- 
point of physics no problem is left referring to the whole of 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 165 

streaming water. On the other hand, I can connect two points 
of a network of wires with the two poles of a battery of gal- 
vanic elements. Immediately the electric current through this 
network is established, forming the so-called stationary dis- 
tribution in the net, in the wires connecting it with the battery, 
and in the battery itself. Nobody can prevent me from con- 
centrating my attention upon one small part of this conducting 
system and upon one small part of the physical process going 
on constantly in it. I may do that in my attempt at making 
the theory of the process. But the next step I have to make, 
if the theory shall agree with the facts at all, must consist in 
my admitting that the small part of the process I have in view 
is as it is, not for its own sake and independently, but only 
in so far as in the other parts of the system the corresponding 
processes are going on. The stationary distribution of elec- 
tric current in a given system is a dynamic equilibrium of the 
whole system, not to be reduced into independent branches of 
current. 1 What occurs in one wire of this system, therefore, 
cannot be compared functionally with the stream of water in 
one of the pipes of our other example. In this pipe I shall find 
the streaming absolutely unchanged, whatever may happen and 
be changed in the other pipes ; the streaming in one of them is 
a function of the local conducting properties in this pipe only. 
In the case of electric currents in a conducting network, any 
change in any place will immediately alter what happens in 
"the small part" of it which we were considering. If, there- 
fore, I like to analyze, in the case of the pipes, I may do it. 
No harm will be done, provided my analysis finds the real 
elements (independent stream in one pipe). But if my anal- 
ysis picks out a part of that stationary current distribution, I 
must confess in the next moment that here analysis cannot 
mean the same thing, since I find a local state of affairs which 
cannot be understood as long as I do not consider the whole 
process. It cannot be understood because it does not exist 
without the dynamic influences throughout the whole system 
(and vice versa). 

Is a sensation, or is a physiological process corresponding 
to it, like one of those streams of water in separate pipes, i.e., 
functionally independent? Or is it like that "small local 
process" in the network conducting the electric current, i.e., 

*It is instructive to know that in the early days of the investi- 
gation of currents this situation was exactly as embarrassing for 
physicists as the problems of Gestalt are now for us. 



166 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

does it exist in its actual state only as dependent upon the 
dynamic equilibrium distribution in a larger area? Evidently 
this alternative is at least as decisive for our theory of sensory 
experience as the former; but though dynamic equilibrium is 
a word mentioned in some of our more modern textbooks, we 
do not see as yet that the fundamental differences between the 
two assumptions were recognized and the concrete conse- 
quences worked out. For a long time we have all of us prac- 
tically applied the standpoint of the pipes when treating the 
sensory field. When, now, we are told that the contrary seems 
to be more probable for several reasons and that we should 
not go on with the pipes, we easily become angry and say that 
we never did formulate such a radical principle as that of the 
pipes. In this we are probably right, because we never had 
a clear idea of the functional alternative, no idea that there 
was something important to decide one way or the other, and 
rather unconsciously worked in that line only. But I think 
somebody should have stated that radical principle, because it 
is of so much higher scientific value to make a clean, clear mis- 
take, which is the best antecedent of progress, than to remain 
in that phase of vagueness where not even mistakes can be 
made and afterwards be displaced by something better. 

One remark may be needed here to show that the two al- 
ternatives are not simply identical. The molecule as rep- 
resentative of an objective unit and the independent stream in 
one pipe seems to be so similar ; yet we must not exaggerate the 
parallel between them, because though a molecule in the air 
is a physical unit held together by forces which do not connect 
in a comparable degree parts of one molecule with those of an- 
other, still what happens with the molecule may be determined 
by its being the "part" of a larger whole (and vice versa). 
If it has a charge (i. e. is an ion), for example, it will move 
in the electric field and influence other charges by its own field 
so that perhaps finally its movements will become one depen- 
dent little part of just such a whole process as we described 
above. Therefore a molecule or any other physically defined 
unit may either be an altogether independent unit like the 
stream in one separated pipe or it may, still retaining its pro- 
perty of more specific unitedness, have a life which can only 
be rightly understood if we consider a larger system in which 
we find it. 

Is a sensation of the molecule type? Let us try to answer 
with complete naivete as if there were no psychology already 
existent. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 167 

I look up to the homogeneous blue sky of today, and find 
it continuous. Not the slightest indication of its being com- 
posed of real units, nothing of limits or of any discontinuities. 
One may answer that my simple observation is not the method 
to decide this point, but I cannot agree with this argument 
since we need, first of all, concepts for the description and the 
understanding of our immediate experience; and the sensa- 
tion loses considerably of its importance as a fundamental con- 
cept, if, taking it as something of the molecule type, we find 
nothing to substantiate this idea in direct observation. The 
continuity of that region of the sky or any homogeneous field 
is a positive property of it. And we see that our fundamental 
theoretical concept in this form does nothing to make this pro- 
perty understood. On the contrary, a special hypothesis 
would be needed in order to explain how in spite of the exist- 
ence of sensation molecules the homogeneous field becomes a 
continuum. Therefore the only thing produced by this useless 
assumption is a complication of theory. And I lay the more 
stress on this fact as we shall see very soon that there do occur 
parts in sensory fields which are real objective units, though 
they certainly are not "sensations". The concept of sensation 
tends to hide for us the importance of these other realities and 
has done so for a considerable time, very much to the drawback 
of psychological progress. 

Since the concept of a differential does not mean anything 
like a real unit but only signifies the small uniform part of a 
medium, field, or process which our thinking regards more 
especially in a certain moment of our theoretical consideration, 
sensation as a differential can evidently not be verified in ex- 
perience. It has nothing to do with experience directly. Per- 
haps it does not help us very much in our thinking, but at least 
so long as we remain aware of its completely arbitrary nature 
it will not conduct us into errors. 

Having found that we may keep sensations in our system 
as differentials, if we want to, we have to ask whether these 
differentials we are considering in a quiet field of vision are to 
be regarded as independent or as dependent differentials in an 
equilibrium distribution of larger area. Feeling that this is 
the very kernel of our problem we should give our answer 
slowly, gradually approaching the decision by a series of ob- 
servations. Before starting we remember that our procedure 
shall be as naive as possible, so that it does not matter if our 
observations follow a line where psychologists do not usually 



168 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



search for anything fundamental. It does not matter either 
if, for a while, we seem to lose sight of our problem and seem 
to go in a new direction. 

One of Wertheimer's papers 2 describes observations of the 
following type: 

(1) You look on a series of spots (Fig. 1) whose dis- 



tances are alternately of a certain larger and smaller width. 
If I say that these spots appear spontaneously in groups of two 
(which "belong together") so that the smaller of the two dis- 
tances is always in the interior of one group, and that beyond 
the larger distance a new group begins, etc., you probably will 
not find the statement or the phenomenon very impressive. 

I therefore introduce a change substituting straight parallel 
lines for the spots (Fig 2), at the same time increasing the 



difference of the two distances a little. The phenomenon of 
group formation is now a little more striking. How "real" 
it is you can feel when trying to form other groups in the series ; 
namely, so that any two lines with the larger distance between 
them form one group and the shorter distance is the space 
between two consecutive groups. You see that this requires 
a special effort. To form one of the new groups may be rather 
easy; but to make the change for all of them i. e., for the 
whole series simultaneously, is more than I, for instance, can 
achieve. Most people never will get this other grouping as 
dear, stable and optically real as the former one; and in the 
first moment of relaxation or fatigue, you instantly see again 
the spontaneously existing groups as before. It is as if some 
forces were holding the pairs of nearer lines together, 
Is distance in itself the decisive factor? Two spots or 

*Psychologische Forschttng 4, pp. 301 fol. 1923. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 



169 



two parallel lines may be regarded as a rather poor boundary- 
enclosing space between them. In our figures they do so 
better when nearer together, so that we might perhaps form- 
ulate our principle in the sentence that the members of a series 
better enclosing space between them tend to form groups. 
This new principle seems to work because it covers the fact 
that the parallel straight lines form more striking and stable 
groups than the spots. Evidently they enclose space between 
them better than do the spots. And again, we can change our 
last figure by adding some short horizontal lines so that the lar- 
ger space between the more distant parallels begins to be better 
enclosed (Fig. 3), and the result is that it becomes easy to see 



the pairs of more distant lines with their annexes as groups, 
even before the open distance between those annexes is made 
smaller than the distances of the parallels nearer to each other. 
But let us be cautious. Perhaps we have two different prin- 
ciples, that of distance and that of "enclosing". 

(2) In the next figure all members of the series follow 
each other at equal distances, but there is a regular change in 
the properties of those members (Fig. 4). It does not matter 



whether the difference is of this type or a difference between 
yellow and black, for instance. Even in a case like this (Fig. 
5) you observe the same phenomenon, namely that the members 



170 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of the same "quality" (whatever it may be) form groups and 
that a new group begins where we have a change in the quality 
of members. Again you convince yourself of the reality of 
this observation by trying to see the series in another grouping 
than that. Probably you will not be able to see the series as 
solidly organized throughout when trying to enforce any of 
the other mathematically possible formations of groups. 

(3) The description of our observations is not yet complete. 
If we look back upon the series of parallels, we see that the 
formation of groups is not an affair of those parallels only. 
The whole area in a group, half enclosed between the parallels 
nearer to each other, white like the surrounding paper, still 
looks different from it and also different from the area be- 
tween two consecutive groups. In a group there is a certain 
aspect of "solidity", or we might even say : "there is something" ; 
whereas between the groups and around the whole series we 
have "emptiness" or "there is nothing". This difference, 
described and discussed very carefully by Rubin, 3 who calls it 
the difference between the characters of "figure" and "ground", 
becomes the more remarkable since the whole group, including 
its half enclosed white area, appears to "stand out" in space 
from the surrounding ground. At the same time we may re- 
mark that the parallels which, as it were, solidify the enclosed 
area and lift it a little from the ground, "belong to this area" 
in one more meaning: You see that they are the edges of this 
enclosed area, but are not in the same manner edges of the in- 
different ground outside the group. 4 

There is more to describe in the aspect of even such a simple 
field of vision. But, lest you might feel that I intend to lead 
you into unimportant details, I hasten to carry our observations 
on into a new direction. 

(4) The groups formed in the series of parallels included 
pairs of them. We add third parallels in the midst of each 
group and find, as one may have expected beforehand, that 
these three lines so close together still form groups and that 
the grouping is even much more striking now than before 
(Fig. 6). We may add two more parallels in each, group be- 
tween the three already drawn. Not much of white is left 

*Visuell wahrgenommene Figuren I. Kobenliaven, Christiania, 
Berlin, London: Gyldendal, 1921. 

'Similar laws are found to apply to the formation of units in 
temporal series (Wertheimer, Psychol. Forsch. 4; Koffka. The 
Psychol. Bull. 19, 1922). 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 171 



now in the group and the stability of group formation is still 
increased (Fig. 7). Some steps more and the areas of our 



groups are uniform black rectangles. There would be three of 
them ; everybody looking upon the page would see these "three 
dark forms." And our gradual procedure has taught us that to 
see the black content of each of those areas, as "one thing" 
united in itself, outstanding as one from the ground, is only 
a very extreme case of the formation of group units which 
we were observing first. It is not a geometrical truism it has 
nothing to do with pure geometry that continuous uniformly 
colored areas or spots in differently colored homogeneous sur- 
roundings appear as wholes, units ; it is a primitive experience 
in vision. And we have seen that it is an extreme example 
of the fact that, with neighbours of equal properties given, 
group units are formed. This principle was seen working 
with increased effect the denser we rilled the area of the group. 
It cannot stop working when the group becomes a continuum. 
(I hardly have to mention that our uniformly colored wholes 
might have thousands of different forms, usual ones like the 
rectangle, to which we are accustomed, or quite unusual ones 
like some spot of ink on the paper or a little cloud in the sky) . 
You see why I started showing the group formation in the 
case of separate members: It is easier to acknowledge the 
problem there as a problem. To be sure, the unit of our black 
rectangles is much more stable than that of our first spots 
and parallels; but we are so used to uniformly colored areas 



172 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

surrounded by other color "being one" that the problem here 
is not grasped so easily. Most of the observations of Gestalt 
psychology are of this kind : They touch facts of such a gen- 
eral occurence in every moment of our life that, therefore, we 
have difficulties in seeing anything remarkable in them. This, 
too, is the reason why they are scarcely mentioned in psy- 
chology. 

Again the progress of our observations obliges us to look 
back. We formed series of spots or straight lines and ob- 
served their grouping. Now we have learned that these mem- 
bers of our series themselves contain the same problem or 
phenomenon, in so far as they already are extended and uni- 
formly colored units. The consequence is that we find formation 
of units in different "order" or "rank", e. g., straight lines 
(lowest order) and groups of them (higher order). If a unit 
exists it may still become part of a larger unit or group of 
higher rank. Whether it remains exactly the same thing when 
undergoing this absorption is a question which shall occupy 
us later on. 

(5) With the "being one," the continuous unit has re- 
tained another property of the discontinuous group : It still 
has the "figure" character as something solid, outstanding from 
the empty ground. Imagine now that we substitute for the 
rectangle, printed in black, a black rectangular paper, covering 
the same area and carefully pressed against the page. Evi- 
dently nothing of importance is changed; this paper is "one" 
and has the character of something solid on account of similar 
reasons that the printed rectangle had before. Imagine further 
that this paper begins to grow in the direction at right angles 
to its surface and the surface of the page. It becomes thicker 
and is soon a black block or "thing" in space. Again nothing 
functionally important is changed. But we see that the ap- 
plication of our observations has become much larger. Where- 
ver "a thing" is visible as "one" and as something solid the 
same principles are concerned which we first became acquaint- 
ed with in the formation of groups. There are still other in- 
fluences working in our appreciation of things as units and as 
solid, but we have no reason to think that those principles of 
primitive group formation we were considering (and others I 
could not mention here) lose their force when we have to do 
with things in three dimensions instead of spots or rectangles. 5 

5 "Things" again may become members of groups of a higher order. 
Instead of spots we might have a series of men and still observe 
the formation of groups. In architecture one knows enough about 
that (compare the grouping of pillars, windows, statues, etc.). 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 173 

I am thoroughly aware of the fact that here we are con- 
fronted with a subject for thorough discussion. Why should 
such solid units in vision so generally correspond to real things 
in the practical meaning of the word? And every day ex- 
perience seems to show that this correspondence exists. What 
would be our life if it were not so! There are two answers 
to give. The first is that a great many objects or things in 
the practical meaning have objective properties which make 
them likely to be seen as optic units too. There is the world 
of objects which man has created himself for his practical 
purposes. Without much thinking he makes and has made them 
so that in color and other properties they are apt to appear as 
units. Of course, nobody gives his piano a painting which would 
make parts of it easily combine into optic units with different 
parts of the surroundings, making the piano disappear. Natural 
objects often follow the same principle, because what has one 
common origin in nature or belongs together in nature as one 
thing will rather likely show some common surface properties 
in color and otherwise, whereas the surroundings have dif- 
ferent surface properties as being of a different origin and 
different physical nature. So the mountain separates from 
the sky, a cloud again from the sky, the blackbird (even at 
rest) from the lawn, the stone from the sand, and the cliff from 
the sea. The second answer is that, wherever our primitive 
optic principles are not favorable to the formation of units in 
correspondence to real things, it becomes more and more dif- 
ficult to recognize, to find or to see these real things, until at 
last we do not see them at all. Who has never in his life stared 
upon an odd form at some distance which he could not explain 
to himself and which, after a slight change of standpoint 
(therefore change in arrangement of stimuli i. e. conditions 
for grouping) suddenly broke up into one well-known thing 
and perhaps parts of other well-known things? The moment 
before the primary optical unit formation had created an ab- 
solutely unknown optical thing, because the arrangement and 
the properties of stimuli happened to be so. Paint the pencil, 
the books, the ash tray, the eraser, the paper knife, the rule, 
and the desk each in some colors distributing them in irregular 
spots so as to have no relation to the total form of the object 
you will see that your accomplishments in life are a little slowed 
down because you are constantly seeking. Without painting: 
Observe under what circumstances you do not find your pencil 
for ten seconds, though it is openly before you on your desk. 



174 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

In most cases you will observe that the position of the pencil, 
relative to other objects, and some similarity of its surface 
properties to those of the objects at its side, had united it with 
them optically and so made it disappear as a relatively indepen- 
dent optic unit. The art of making puzzle pictures is an appli- 
cation of these facts the parts of a man, for instance, are ab- 
sorbed by the surroundings ,and the last war, with allots 
art of camouflage, has shown how far the optical destruction 
of real objects can go, even if nothing disturbs the projection 
of those objects on the retina. 

Most things are certainly known objects for the adult. This 
means, for instance, that when seeing a pipe we see it as some- 
thing with a specific function in smoking, and of course this 
"meaning" of that optical unit on our desk is brought into it 
by experience. It does not follow at all that the optic unit of 
it as such is a product of experience. As yet we have only 
seen that the existing unit may become imbued with some 
functional meaning by experience. On the other hand, I shall 
not deny that experience has an influence upon our seeing 
those units. But here we must avoid a circle. I saw a certain 
object often in earlier life and under conditions of surround- 
ings favorable for its being seen as a unit. The effect is that 
I find myself more likely to see it again as "one thing" even 
under conditions where the purely optical constellation is less 
favorable for it and optical absorption of it or its parts into 
other units would probably occur without the influence of pre- 
vious experience. So this influence of previous life, instead 
of showing how experience makes units out of something else, 
presupposes the existence of the unit as such in previous see- 
ing. It is an experience about those units which afterwards 
becomes effective. The more one avoids the rather common 
but dangerous phrase, that this or that thing "must of course 
be explained by experience", the more one tries, in our case, 
for instance, to consider concretely how experience might pro- 
duce units (and out of what?), the less plausible becomes this 
rather superficial statement. Recently we have made ex- 
periments on this question which are not yet published, and 
we are surprised to see how easily even that effect of experience 
which I have admitted is overcome by showing a well-known 
form in a constellation in which the primary tendencies of unit 
formation are working against our seeing that form. One 
example (not at all a very strong one) may demonstrate this 
fact (Fig. 8). The first aspect of this constellation of straight 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 175 





lines is usually: A drawing consisting of three parts, two 
irregular hexagons including a lengthy other form between 
them. There is a strong tendency to see closed surface-forms 
as against figures consisting of lines only. Therefore, the 
|^, whose constituents are openly given in the contour does not 
come into existence, one of its parts helping to form the first 
closed surface to the left and the rest limiting one end of the 
lengthy surface. When demonstrating cases of this kind I 
often hear the argument: You forget that we have not seen 
the well-known in such a connection before. But that is 
exactly what I say : The influence of experience is not strong 
enough to overcome spontaneously even such a simple ar- 
rangement which tends to be organized into other and less 
familiar forms. If nothing in the surroundings were changed, 
we would of course instantly see the letter as we saw it at other 
times ; but in this case no experience would be needed for ex- 
planation. (In this example one can see the [/ very easily, 
after being helped to. In other cases it becomes altogether 
impossible really to see a well-known form in a given con- 
stellation, even when one is absolutely certain about its con- 
stituents being geometrically and physically present). 

An observation showing that no experience is needed for a 
first formation of units in the visual field is given in cases 
where blind born persons gain their sight by operation. Psy- 
chology used to be interested in these cases because of the prob- 
lem of third dimension and of the correlation between space 
in touch and in vision. Whatever the outcome for these prob- 
lems, one point is quite obvious in the description of first 
vision under these circumstances, though very characterist- 
ically the investigators do not mention the problem as a prob- 
lem: It may be an open question whether the patient recog- 
nizes a square as a square which before he knew only by touch. 
But certainly he understands the investigator very well when 
asked what the form there is, showing thereby that he has there 
something outstanding as one in his field of vision at once. 

We began our observations intending to decide whether or 



176 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

not the sensation is an independent differential. Our first re- 
sult, however, has led us back to another concept, namely that 
of a'n objective unit. In order to show what I meant with this 
term, I mentioned the molecule in the atmosphere as a unit 
which is not arbitarily conceived in thought, but objectively 
given by the strong intercourse of interior forces, which hold 
the molecule together, in contrast to the comparatively low dy- 
namic interrelation between the molecule and its surroundings. 
I chose the very small molecule as a model because the question 
was if we had to regard sensations, supposedly small things, 
as similarly small objective units ; and we found no indication 
of their existence as such. But the concept of an objective 
unit in the defined meaning is not necessarily restricted to small 
things. A crystal, for instance, in the saturated solution in 
which it forms is an objective unit, in such a similar meaning 
as a molecule that some physicists have really called it an enor- 
mous molecule. Are there objective units in a field of vision? 
Yes, there are and we have been considering them now for 
some time. It is not arbitrary and abstract thinking that makes 
those groups or spots or rectangles or things in my visual field. 
I find them there as optical realities not less real than their color, 
black, or white or red, etc. As long as my visual field remains 
the same (is not changed by internal or external influences) 
there is little doubt about what belongs in one of those units 
and what not. And if we have found that in the visual field 
there are units of different rank, a group, for instance, con- 
taining several spots, the larger unit containing smaller ones 
of still stronger unitedness, exactly the same occurs in physics 
where the molecule as one larger objective unit (defined by a 
comparative break of interconnection at its limits) contains 
smaller objective units, the atoms, whose interior is again enor- 
mously stronger united than the molecule is. There is no 
contradiction and no vagueness in objective units containing 
smaller units. And as it remains an objective fact in the phy- 
sical material, where the boundaries of its units and perhaps 
of sub-units are, so in the visual field no arbitrary analyzing 
thought should interfere with observation: Experience is 
spoiled if we begin to introduce artificial sub-divisions where 
real units and boundaries of one or the other rank are open 
and clear before us. This is the principal reason why I think 
that a concept like sensation is almost a danger. It tends to 
absorb our attention, obscuring the fact that there are observ- 
able units and sub-units in the field. Because in the moment 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 177 

we give up our naivete in description and theory and think of 
the field in terms of unreal elements, these unreal little things 
appear to our thought side by side, indifferently filling space, 
some of one, some of another color or brightness, etc., and the 
observable units with their observable boundaries do not occur 
in this pseudo-description. I do not exaggerate. Look on the 
development of the psychology of vision: All the more im- 
portant observations relating to the real units, etc., began to be 
made in the last thirty years only, though the facts were before 
us thousands of years, wherever psychologists or other people 
looked into the world. Artificial theory made us a little blind 
for them. 6 

It will be worth while to mention here one more ambiguity 
of the term analysis in psychology. I may either consider in 
theory one little part of the visual field, i. e* when thinking 
about such a field about this we were speaking hitherto; or 
I may, looking on an actually given field, pioceed by actual 
analysis in vision. In the second case, when finding, for in- 
stance, the letter ^>) in Fig. 8, I really have changed the visual 
field, the units and the boundaries in it. There is a letter now 
which did not exist before in the field and the units which 
were given before are seriously changed. To really see the 
letter and the closed areas of that figure at the same time and 
undisturbed is more than I can achieve. Probably it is as 
impossible as to have the two really separate atoms of O and 
the molecule C>2 at the same time. Of course it is highly in- 
teresting to produce such a change in the field ; what happens 
or does not happen in such an actual operation may even give 
very valuable hints on the nature of the units we are operating 
upon. But in no case must one expect to find the whole truth 
about a given unit by transforming the field and creating new 
units in it. I would not find out all about a molecule C>2 when 
describing two atoms O which I have really separated; and 
also, the separate atoms O, which I describe, did not exist as 
really the same things in the molecule. This is a point we shall 
treat later on more thoroughly. 7 For the moment it is more 
important to mention that from the standpoint of Gestalt psy- 
chology there is after all one analysis which is perfectly gen- 
uine, allowed and productive in all cases: The simple de- 

*G. Humphrey, The Journal of Educational Psychology 15, 1924. 

7 The fact in itself that the change of subjective attitude toward 
the field can to a certain degree alter its properties, -units etc., must 
be regarded as being a very interesting problem, 4\s yet it has not 
been studied thoroughly enough (Kohler, Psychol Forsch. 6, 1925, 
pp. 396 fol.). 



178 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

scription of the field in terms of real units and sub-units as 
their real parts, in terms of their boundaries, sub-boundaries, 
etc. 

The question we wished to answer was whether or not the 
local state of affairs in a sensory field is an independent pro- 
cess, so that the whole field may be regarded as a mosaic of 
them. On our way we found something about extended units 
in the field, and the same facts we were considering there give 
an answer to our present question too. How can local pro- 
cesses which are independent of and indifferent to each other 
be at the same time organized into larger units of well observ- 
able extent in some areas? How, again, can relative break 
of continuity at the well observable limits of those areas be 
understood, since these limits are not limits everywhere be- 
tween little pieces of a mosaic, but only appear where one 
group or unit ends? The hypothesis of independent little 
parts is unable to give an explanation. All the concepts we 
found necessary above for the description of the field have 
no relation whatever to the conception of independent local 
elements. And more concretely: Where our groups or units 
are formed can certainly not be deduced by considering the 
conditions in one point, then independently in the next, etc. 
Only a consideration which takes account of how the local 
conditions for the whole field relate to each other begins to 
approach an understanding of those facts. Not the local 
white along a white line drawn on a black field makes this 
line a real optical unit in the field; there is no specific unit 
and no line before the surroundings have a different color or 
brightness. This difference of stimulation around as against 
equality of stimulation within the line must in the given ar- 
rangement be the fact which produces a specific unit. And in 
the same manner for units of higher order: Not the independ- 
ent or absolute conditions in one of our parallels, then the 
conditions in the next one, make them form one group, but 
that these lines are equal, different from the ground, and so 
near to each other three prerequisites which again show the 
decisive role of relations of local conditions. And let us be 
careful not to forget the ground. Because, if a certain group 
is formed, say two parallels, being half a centimeter from 
each other, I only have to draw two more parallels on the out- 
side of this group and much nearer to the first parallels than 
these are to each other, and the first group is destroyed, two 
other groups being formed by the parallels which are now 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 179 



nearest to each other (Fig. 9). Only so long as we had uni- 
form white in the neighborhood of our first group did this 
group exist. I change conditions in this neighborhood and 
what was the interior of a unit, now becomes a gap between 
two others. One consequence more follows immediately: The 
characters of "figure" and "ground" are so absolutely depend- 
ent upon the formation of units in the field that, since these 
units cannot be deduced from an aggregate of independent local 
states, the appearance of an area as "figure" or "ground" can- 
not either. And still another fact as argument : We draw two 
parallels and produce a group; we draw another congruent 
pair but considerably more distant from the first than the dis- 
tance between the first lines is, and go on increasing the length 
of our series. The result is that all the groups in the series 
become more solid than each of them would be when given 
alone. Even over distances of such an amount the conditions 
in one place have an influence on what happens in another, 
and vice versa. 

The fact that not the local properties of given stimuli but 
the relations of those properties to each other (the total con- 
stellation of stimuli, to use a better word) are decisive for the 
formation of units, suggests at once the idea that dynamic 
intercourse in the field decides about what becomes a unit, 
what is excluded from it, what is "figure," and what falls 
back as mere "ground." Indeed, at the present time not many 
psychologists will deny that, acknowledging those real units, 
etc., in the visual field, we have at once to draw the adequate 
consequences for that part of the brain whose processes are 
corresponding to our field of vision. The units, sub-units, 
boundaries, the difference of "figure" and "ground" must exist 
there as physiological realities. 8 There must be a unit of pro- 

*Wertheimer, Experimentelle Studien uber das Sehen yon Bewe- 
gung. Zeitschr. f. Psychol. 61, 1912. (Also: Wertheimer, Drei 
Abhandlungen ziir Gestaltheorie. Verlag der Philos. .Akad., Brian- 
gen 1925). Kohler, Die physichen Gestalten in Rulxe nnd im 
stationaren Zustand, pp. 173 fol. Verlag der philos. Akad, Brian- 
gen, 1920. 



180 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

cess containing three comparatively separate sub-units when 
we look on Fig. 8; and at least partially this unit of physio- 
logical process must be disturbed and give place to a new one 
not existing the moment before when we begin to see the K. 
Remarking now that relative distance and relation of quali- 
tative properties are the main factors determining the forma- 
tion of units, we remember that exactly such factors ought to 
be decisive for it if it were the effect of dynamic intercourse 
in the physiological process throughout the field. Most physi- 
cal and chemical interaction we know of depends upon the 
relation of properties and on mutual distance between the 
material in space. Now, differences of stimulation produce 
points, lines, areas, of different chemical reaction and in cer- 
tain spatial relations to each other on the retina. If there is 
transverse connection between the longitudinal conductors of 
the optic nerve somewhere in the optic sector of the nervous 
system, mutually dynamic intercourse ought to depend upon 
the relations of qualitative properties and space which are at 
a certain time existing in the total optic process, streaming up 
to or into the brain. No wonder, if we find phenomena of 
distribution, etc., showing direct dependence upon those rela- 
tions. 

But physiological conclusions of this kind will appear better 
founded if first we consider another side of our descriptive 
problems. Intimately related to the existence of real units 
and boundaries in the field of vision we find the fact that there 
are "forms?' in this field. It was practically impossible to ex- 
clude them from the foregoing discussion, because wherever 
we see those units they have forms, 9 this being the reason 
why in the German terminology those units are called "Ges- 
talten." Again, the reality of forms in visual space is a fact 
which cannot be understood from the standpoint that the visual 
field consists of independent local elements. If there were ele- 
ments of this kind forming a dense and perhaps continuous 
mosaic as the "stuff" of the visual field, then we should have 
no real forms in this field. Mathematically, of course, some 
aggregates of them might be considered together, but that 
would not correspond to the reality in which at a given time 
some concrete forms are simply there in vision, not less than 

*I do not ^think that the term "configuration" is quite adequate 
as a translation of the German word "Gestalt". The word configura- 
tion seems to mean elements put together in a certain manner, and 
this is a functional idea which we must carefully avoid. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 181 

colors and brightnesses. And first of all, mathematically, all 
imaginable patterns might be considered in such a field o in- 
dependent elements, whereas in vision always quite individual 
forms are before us under given conditions. 10 If, now, we 
examine these conditions upon which the real forms depend, 
we naturally find again the qualitative and spatial relations of 
stimulation. Naturally, because the now well-known units ap- 
pear in the individual forms we are seeing, and we had to 
realize previously that those units are somehow a function of 
those relations. I remember from my own slow development 
in this respect how difficult it is to make a sharp distinction 
between any aggregate of stimuli, i.e., geometrically existent 
patterns of them, and optic forms as realities. On this page 
there are certainly some black points which, considered to- 
gether, would be a large group of this real form, (Fig. 10). 



Do we therefore see such a form as visual reality? Certainly 
not. But let those stimuli be red and perhaps brought nearer 
together and all people who are not color blind or half blind 
for forms by brain lesion would instantly see this group as a 
form. Also, to use our old example : We first did not see the 
form of the letter K> but another with three separate units, 
and only when these units gave way at least partially there 
appeared at once the definite form of K- And do not think 
that these were some exceptional cases painfully sought for 
the purpose of my argumentation: There is no field of vision 
you have in everyday life in which you might not find thou- 
sands of geometrical patterns of all varieties; but you do not 
see such forms because other existing units with other forms 
have, as it were, spent and distributed the field amongst them. 
All this is not only true for forms in a plane or in the 
paper ; it is as much the truth for the things or objects in our 
surroundings. And so I wish to warn you against the mis- 
understanding that these problems of real units and their 

M Kohler, Komplextheorie and Gestalttheorie. Psychol. Forsch. 
6, pp. 386 fol. 1925. 



182 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

forms might perhaps have some importance for aesthetics or 
for other considerations of a supposedly higher level only 
whereas they were foreign to the practical stuff of everyday 
life. There is no object, no man you have to deal with, whose 
optical reality -is not a concrete demonstration of the same 
scientific situation. If, in thousands of years, people have 
never become fully aware of it, it is not astounding that we 
still have difficulties in realizing how full of problems one 
glance into the world is. 

"Perhaps you are right," somebody might say here, "in so far 
as your units and their forms have psychological reality and 
importance. It also seems probable that for units and their 
forms the constellation of stimuli is at least as important as 
the absolute stimuli themselves. But why not assume that 
some psychic factor, which we might look for, collects the 
local elements into units and gives them forms at the same 
time? Your tendency is to deny the existence of independ- 
ent sensory differentials and to consider those units and their 
forms as the outcome of dynamic intercourse in the total 
stream of the optic process itself. But you would not go so 
far as to assert that the real nature of a local process is de- 
termined by the relations of stimulation in a large area. Is 
not, after all, the color or brightness which is somewhere in 
the field the fundamental reality in it? And this color at 
least does depend upon its local stimulus. White is white, 
black is black on the surface of this paper, whatever may be 
the units and forms in which they occur. They are independ- 
ent local processes." 

There are two points to answer. That color is a more im- 
portant or more fundamental side of our visual field than the 
objects in which they appear or the forms of those objects 
would not be easy to prove. Our vital reactions are deter- 
mined by the objects, one single property of which the colors 
are. And if a color be ever so extended, but at the same time 
be the mere ground on which an object appears, what deter- 
mines our naive reactions from thinking down to eye move- 
ments will be the object in 99 out of 100 cases, though its color 
might be a poor gray. And the second point: Colors are de- 
pendent on the constellation of stimuli throughout the field. 
The black on this page is at once transformed into a bright 
white, the white around it into a black, a gray spot may be- 
come a red one, a red one white, without the slightest change 
in local stimulation, if only you change the total constellation 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 183 

or quality of stimulation around the spot sufficiently. Every- 
body knows that we have only to reduce the light reflected 
from the white on this page to a small amount and to keep the 
black letters reflecting exactly the amount of light they are 
reflecting now in order to get white letters on a black ground. 
No need to dwell upon the other cases. Because of simple 
physical reasons really strong changes of this kind in the sur- 
roundings of one smaller area which itself remains unaltered 
are rather rare, and so we do not easily become aware of these 
phenomena. Neither are we much struck by the more frequent 
fact that a change of stimulation, for instance, produced by 
change of illumination in a part of the field, leaves the white 
of an object there much more constant than the radically dif- 
ferent local stimulations can account for. Since the relation 
of stimuli is not changed when only the illumination becomes 
stronger or lower for our object and its surroundings at the 
same time, the nuance, the white of this area, does not change 
very much either. 

I know, you say : "But that is contrast 1" Whatever the name 
of it, we have to do with the facts behind the name and the 
type of functional interrelation involved. The facts are that 
local color also shows its dependence on a set of stimuli, when- 
ever we change the average properties of stimulation in the 
surroundings a little more than is usually the case. If we 
make the experiment with this printed page, for instance, the 
result shows clearly enough that the black of our letters is 
really black only under conditions of much higher brightness 
surrounding it. 

And there is one fact about the contrast which makes it 
altogether impossible to eliminate it from our discussion as 
something old, well-known, and not connected with this prob- 
lem. Quite a series of observations has recently shown that 
the tendency to treat the visual field as a mosaic of elements 
was particularly dangerous in the work on contrast. All of 
these new observations agree in one essential point, namely 
that the existence and the "amount" of contrast is in the high- 
est degree dependent upon the units or forms which appear in 
the field. We find contrast of various degrees, but we find 
also the opposite of contrast under different conditions of unit 
formation. , Even without any change in the constellation of 
stimuli, if by change of subjective attitude we produce a real 
change in the units of the field, the effects which are ascribed 
to contrast may suddenly appear in striking degree or alto- 



184 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

gather disappear as the case and the units may be. Apart 
from the contrast, and more generally, several investigators 
were able to show that it is easy thoroughly to alter local colors 
by making their area enter one group or another in the forma- 
tion of real units. 11 

Instead of small units of the type of molecules we have 
found larger units and forms in the visual field which come 
into existence and disappear, depending mainly on the actual 
conditions of stimulation. The manner in which stimulation 
determined those units showed that the physiological founda- 
tion of their existence must be dynamic intercourse in the 
optic stream, the units being dependent real parts in this 
stream, and every local process, if we want to consider it more 
especially, being a dependent differential. It follows that such 
a differential and its properties as we are considering in ab- 
stract theory, cannot be rightly understood without going back 
to the total sensory constellation in which they only are what 
they are. 

We draw a physiological consequence: If the local process 
in an extensive system is by dynamic intercourse in this sys- 
tem a dependent differential, it will change, and so will the 
process in the whole system, until equilibrium is reached in a 
stationary distribution without further change. We were treat- 
ing visual fields in the state of rest. They must be the psy- 
chological correlate to a stationary equilibrium distribution in 
the corresponding processes of the brain. There are enough 
cases in physics where a process originating in a system under 
a certain set of conditions develops its stationary distribution 
in extremely short time. The time in which the equilibrium 
of an optic process is developed must also be rather small. 
Because, if we give a set of stimuli suddenly, say by projec- 
tion, the phase of "something happening," which we observe, 
has an extremely rapid appearance, and in a moment we see 
the field, its units and their forms at rest. 

To avoid misunderstandings I may add that, in a state of 
stationary equilibrium, the field is by no means "dead." The 
mutual stresses in the phase of field formation (which of 
course are themselves interdependent) do not disappear when 
the stationary distribution is accomplished. They only have 
now (together with the processes) those intensities and direc- 

u Koffka, Zeitschr, f. Psycfcol. 73, 1915. Koffka, Psychol. Forsch. 4, 
1923. Fuchs, Zeitschr, f. Psychol. 91, 1925; 92, 1923. Benary, Psychol. 
Forsch. 5, 1924. Kohler, Psychol. Forsch. 6, 1925, pp. 411 fol. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 185 

tions everywhere in which they balance each other. The total 
process in stationary distribution is still a store of energy, 
distributed in the field. 

Physiological theory has to solve two different problems 
with regard to the described properties of the field of vision. 
These properties, as they really are, involving dependence of 
the local state on relative properties of stimulation in a wider 
range, including, further, the formation of units, their forms, 
etc., have appeared almost marvelous, so that they often were 
considered as the outcome of supernatural mental forces. The 
first task, then, must be to show that, in the general functional 
aspect, properties of this kind are far from unusual in physics. 
So the more general difficulty is removed, by demonstrating 
a corresponding type of processes in exact science, particularly 
if we can show that, under the circumstances given in the op- 
tic sector of the nervous system, processes of that general 
type are very likely to occur. If that is done, the second task 
will consist in finding that individual kind of physical (or, if 
you prefer, physiological) process which may be assumed to 
be the physiological reality underlying a field of vision. This 
second task is by far the more difficult, given our lack of 
physiological knowledge. We have hardly begun to seek our 
way towards a solution of it, and so I return here to the first 
problem. 

The main difference between the functional ideas which are 
usually applied to the central nervous system and the func- 
tional concepts of Gestalt psychology may perhaps be formu- 
lated as follows : A process starts somewhere independently 
and its way is determined by a well-conducting path pre-exist- 
ing by inheritance or formation in earlier life. The process, 
then, arrives somewhere, as a stone which I throw hits the 
window, and produces those effects which it must produce un- 
der the conditions given at this place of arrival. That is the 
prevailing f unctional idea of today. The conducting path de- 
termines the consequences of the process, since, with another 
connection, absolutely different results would be produced in 
quite another place, and the process between two places is in- 
dependent of the mutual relation of properties in these 
places, existing the moment before the process begins. So 
something "blind" is one of the principal characteristics of 
this functional concept, one place being influenced suddenly 
from without; it has "no vote" in the matter. If evolution or 
association has not built up the right conducting path, any- 



186 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

thing may happen in the central nervous system. Of course 
there are conductors in the theoretical ideas of Gestalt psy- 
chology, too ; but they play a very different role here, being 
in a sensory field, for instance a rather indifferent quasi- 
homogeneous network, which in itself does not prescribe what 
the outcome of nervous dynamics shall be, or where a process 
shall go. This is regarded as mainly determined by the rela- 
tion of actual physiological properties in the different places, 
and so is the distribution of conduction in the whole network. 
Our good will to find the "mechanism" or the "machinery" 
for special nervous processes has made us almost eliminate 
what is a dominating factor of a great part of physics : There 
differences of temperature, of pressure, of concentration, of 
potential, i.e., of relations of properties, throughout the sys- 
tem in its actual state, determine what part exerts what influ- 
ence on what other part in the next moment. No special con- 
straining and isolating conductors are responsible for the re- 
sult the medium in itself would conduct everywhere in every 
direction and the really occurrent distribution of process is 
itself depending upon those physical facts, as they are at a 
given time. Processes of this kind are not "blind" in the man- 
ner described above, since it is a mutual affair between places 
and their properties whether a process originates between them 
and what kind of a process it shall be. Neither must we ex- 
pect nature to produce a horrible confusion without special 
constraining arrangements for the "right" conduction ; because 
the outcome of this 'freer," though absolutely necessary, dy- 
namic interaction is everywhere in physics a very regular and 
orderly spontaneous distribution of process with very striking 
features, reminding one of biological phenomena. Since all 
places are dynamically interrelated with all others, even the 
interaction between two of them in a given moment is found 
dependent upon the actual state of the whole system ; and so we 
understand why the total process can and must obey one law 
for it as a whole: It approaches the equilibrium distribution, 
which is not an affair for its single parts but for the whole 
range of the system. For a long time we have believed in the 
predominant and almost exclusive importance of rigid arrange- 
ments in the nervous system which were supposed not to take 
part in the process or to be influenced by the actual situation, 
but only to enforce the right ways of nervous stream "from 
without." The above observations seem to suggest that we 
have overdone this principle. They tend to show that finally 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 187 

we must try also to apply the principles of direct and freer dy- 
namics, 12 as they are working in physics. To be sure, the 
usual older concept is not actually in contradiction with physics, 
but it corresponds to one possibility in physics only, omitting 
those types of physical systems altogether which are by far the 
richest in functional properties and consequences and behave a 
little like systems in biology. 13 

At least one glimpse on the more special way in which this 
general idea may be applied to the optic sector of the nervous 
system: In consequence of unequal stimulation in different 
areas of the retina, different areas of a cross section of the optic 
sector contain unequal chemical reactions and so contain un- 
equal chemical material in crystalloid and colloid form. If 
these unequal areas are in functional contact, they certainly 
are not in equilibrium. There is "energy able to work" in the 
system wherever areas of unequal properties have common 
borders. Here in the contours must be the main source of 
energy for dynamical intercourse. It would be so in physics 
or physical chemistry under corresponding circumstances. 14 

Our assumption gives a physiological correlate for form as 
an optic reality. From the standpoint of independent elemen- 
tary processes such a correlate could not be found. Their in- 
different mosaic would contain no real forms or, if you pre- 
fer, all imaginable but not real forms in each case, namely for 
a mind who would pick them out of the mosaic. Evidently 
only a kind of process which cannot be split up into independ- 
ent local elements would be 'acceptable as a correlate of real 
form. Now, the stationary equilibrium of the process which we 
assume to underly the field of vision is a distribution of stress 
and process in space, 15 which only maintains itself as this 
whole. Therefore we make it our working hypothesis that in 

"The word "free" is used here in a meaning which does not con- 
tradict strict necessity at all, exactly as a physicist speaks about 
different "degrees of freedom" in a system: A system has more or 
less freedom in physics, the lower or greater the number of special 
arrangements is which constrains the free dynamic intercourse of 
its parts. . In the usual hypothesis about the nervous system, we 
give its processes as little freedom as possible. 

"Kohler, Gestalprobleme und Anfange einer Gestalttheorie. Jahres- 
bericht iiber die gesamte Physiologic 1922. Berlin, Springer 1924. 

^Kohler, Die physischen Gestalten etc. pp. 1 fol., p. 185, pp. 195 fol. 

^he concept of space requires a special consideration here since 
in the brain it cannot simply be measured in cm, cm* and cm*. 
(Kohler, Die physischen Gestalten, p. 232 fol.) 



188 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

all cases this distribution is the physiological correlate to the 
space properties of vision and especially to form. Since our 
conception of a physiological unit is necessarily in so far rela- 
tive, as any sharp decrease in the intimacy of dynamic inter- 
course at the boundaries of an area shows its interior to be a. 
real unit, we can without contradiction treat the whole optical 
process as one for a given time, and still assert the formation 
of specific (mare intimately connected) units with their forms 
in it, depending on the spatial constellation of stimuli. 

We consider the case of such a real form and unit a little 
nearer. We said that the form of a unit is determined by the 
properties of stimulation in relation to each other. It is well 
known that many years ago Mach and von Ehrenf els drew the 
attention of psychologists to a property of forms (and more 
generally Gestalten) which is only a consequence of that fact. 
If we change the absolute properties of stimulation, the form 
of a unit remains the same for a wide range of the change, 
provided the total constellation of spatial and other relations 
of stimulation is not changed. On a homogeneous background 
the objective circle is seen as the same form though we change 
the fixation point considerably. A change of color does not 
matter if only the interior and the background remain homo- 
geneous and remain different from each other. We may re- 
duce the diameter or increase it; that does not matter either, 
so long as this change does not pass certain limits. Of these 
possibilities of "transposing a form" the first ones do not re- 
quire a special consideration in our physiological theory be- 
cause one sees at once that our physiological assumptions lead 
to the same results. But about "transposing in size" some 
words may be needed, and I give the example of a very simple 
equilibrium distribution in physics in order to show that there 
the same thing occurs and must occur. 

^A number n of condensers is only connected by very thin 
wires, and the direct mutual influence by the electrostatic field 
is practically excluded by very large distances between them. 
If we give this system a total charge of amount e, this charge 
will distribute itself spontaneously on the surface of the con- 
densers. Then, calling the electrostatic capacities of the con- 
densers Ci, C 2 ..C p ..C n in the equilibrium distribution, the 
charge e p of one of them will be: 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 189 



Ci o L .1. C* -i- i /^i 
1 "T" 2 " " " " o ~*~ * ~T~ n 

This charge remains in the condenser p as long as the other 
charges remain in the other condensers and vice versa. The 
simple formula shows that correspondingly this charge e is 
a function not only of the local conditions (C p ), but also of 
the conditions everywhere else in the system (C x etc. appear- 
ing in the denominator) as is the case with all equilibrium 
distributions and with units in the field of vision. Hence a 
change of conditions in one point of the system affects the 
distribution throughout. But there is one type of changing 
conditions which does not make the distribution react at all. 
Multiply or divide all capacities by the same factor which 
may be done in reality by increasing or diminishing their lin- 
ear dimensions in equal proportion and the local charges or 
the whole distribution do not change at all. e p is depending 

on etc., only. I might as well have written: 
C P 



C 2 



c p 



The relations of relevant properties (capacities) have not 
been altered, and so the distribution has remained invariable 
under the transposing of spatial properties. Invariability 
under transposing is therefore not at all a thing peculiar to sen- 
sory experiences. (For simplicity's sake I chose an example 
where the spontaneous distribution is one of rest. But we 
find quite similar facts in cases of spatial processes as depend- 
ing on spatial conditions.) 16 

"Our example may be used also as an illustration of a "freer" 
system. No previous isolating arrangement of conductors deter- 
mines what charge is conducted to what condenser. At any branch- 
ing point the current might take all open ways in all degrees of inten- 
sity. Still, in a given system, we have one equilibrium distribution 
only, because the current everywhere is fully determined by the 
mutual relations of actual properties (potential) throughout the 
system; so it streams and changes until all stresses are in balance 
for the whole. 



190 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

The application of the general principle to the optic sector 
of the nervous system will then consist in our assuming that 
stimulation and relations of stimulation produce the energy 
for a process in the optic sector. The distribution of this 
process will depend primarily on the retinal constellation of 
areas of different stimulation, on the general properties of the 
conducting net and on influences which are exerted upon the 
optic sector from other parts of the nervous system and the 
organism as a whole. You see from my last words that per- 
haps we are not allowed to treat the optic process as one pro- 
blem of Gestalt and not to include a still larger system. 

Eventually I should like to show, at least in some cases, 
how, with this standpoint in sensory psychology given, the 
consequences necessarily reach much farther. 

We have seen that the existence of a geometrical pattern of 
stimuli on the retina does not at all determine whether I see 
certain forms or not, because if we change the surrounding 
pattern or even our attitude only, the outcome may consist of 
quite different units and forms. Therefore "recognizing/' 
which in the majority of cases is not a recognizing of color 
or brightness but of the form of a unit, of an object, for in- 
stance, will one time occur, another time not, depending upon 
the principles we were discussing, i.e., upon the reality of units 
and forms. Rubin has shown that in very impressive experi- 
ments. 

It is the same thing with "meaning" and with "reproduc- 
tion" Certain stimuli and groups of stimuli will not reproduce 
anything at all before the right unit or form, which acquired 
in experience a meaning or a reproductive force, becomes a 
physiological and psychological reality. How should anybody 
pronounce the name of the letter K when looking on Fig. 8, 
before he sees this form as an optical reality? But, in other 
cases, one can show in an even more convincing way how de- 
cisive this existence or non-existence and the properties of 
real optical forms in the field are. I made experiments of this 
type: 

The subjects are shown pairs of figures like, e.g., Fig. 11, 
for a short time. After awhile reproduction experiments are 
made showing the subjects in one-half of the cases a real part 
of the original, for instance the straight line to the left in our 
example ; in the other half much more of the geometrical pat- 
tern is shown, but so that 'the part" shown does not correspond 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 191 




to an optical reality in the original, for instance Fig. 12. We 
are used to thinking that reproduction becomes easier the 
larger the fraction of the original is which we give. We might 
predict from our principles, and we find it proved by experi- 
mentation, that this purely quantitative factor does not mean 
very much and may easily be overcome by something more 
important. Which half of the cases yields more and more 
correct reproductions? The first one where "less? of the 
original is exposed! And why? Because there I show some- 
thing that did exist very nearly so in the original, whereas in 
the second case I show something that certainly did not occur 
in the original as a psychological and physiological reality and 
therefore did not acquire a reproductive force. The subject 
did not see the three straight lines more to the right in the 
group of four, and the first to the left, now forming one mem- 
ber of the group of four, has lost much of its relative inde- 
pendence and thereby has changed its character so far that it 
does not reproduce now as it reproduces when given alone. 
[Some experiments made by Shepard a*id Fogelsonger in this 
country seem to become explainable from the same principle.] 17 
This example will perhaps prove better than much description 
or discussion of "Gestalten" how essentially the understanding 
of mental life and of the corresponding physiological pro- 
cesses depends upon our discriminating between really exist- 
ing forms and elements arbitrarily analysed in thought. 

We further have evidence for believing that the coordina- 
tion of certain simple motor reactions to a visual field depends 
on our principles directly. If, in the stereoscope, one vertical 
line is exposed to one eye and a second to the other so that with 
a given degree of convergence of the two eyes the lines appear 
nearly parallel and at a rather short distance from each other, 

17 Psychol. Review 20, 1913. For the explanation Psychol. Forsch. 
6, pp. 379, foL 1925. 



192 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

we find them uniting into one line almost at once. It is well 
known that in this case our eyes turn without our intention into 
that degree of convergence which brings the two lines upon two 
corresponding verticals of the two retinae, the two physiologi- 
cal processes becoming probably more intimately united under 
these circumstances than with any other degree of convergence. 
But we have seen already that parallel lines near to each other 
[seen in a monocular field of vision, or both of them with both 
eyes] form a group or belong together as if under mutual at- 
traction. Doesn't it look as if, under the conditions given in 
our stereoscopic observation, these forces were accomplishing 
the same thing more thoroughly by really uniting the parallels ? 
An examination of the situation from the standpoint of phys- 
ics seems to show that such a thing might really occur. We 
saw that in the equilibrium distribution of process the field is 
still full of stresses which are for the moment in balance, but 
represent a store of energy. So in vision there seems to be 
stress tending to bring the two parallels together. In physics, 
if such a field is functionally connected with movable parts, 
amongst whose movements some definite form of motion would 
release the still existing stresses of the field, this movement 
will immediately occur, produced by the energy of those 
stresses. These only "waited'' as it were, for an opportunity 
to let their energy work, for instance influencing movable parts 
in the direction of a better equilibrium. The better equilibrium 
in physics lies always in the direction of those stresses which 
tend to produce some change, but which in our physiological 
case cannot do it directly in the field. If possible, then, they 
will do it by a detour influencing the muscles of the eyes as 
moveable parts in the direction of release of their energy. 
There is nothing supernatural in such an orderly physical pro- 
cess, no process with or without detour can ever produce 
changes which are not directed toward a more stable equili- 
brium of the whole system. We have only to adopt this view 
for the case of the optical part of the brain and its nervous 
connection with the muscles of the eyeballs in order to have a 
new explanation of fixation movements which is founded on 
principles of Gestalt theory and physics. 18 Of course the 
hypothesis needs a careful working out for the concrete con- 
ditions given in the nervous system and in the muscles of the 
eyes. But the more we work in this direction the more facts 
seem to show that we are on the right way. 

^Kohler, Jaliresbericht iiber dis gesamte Physiologic 1922, pp. 536 
fol. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 193 

About one other and far more important extension of Ges- 
talt psychology only some brief remarks are possible here. We 
dealt with forms or groups of very different degrees of solid- 
ity. There are cases in which all attemps of destroying, in 
actual analysis, a given form in favor of a certain other form 
are in vain. But distribute the furniture of a room in an ir- 
regular manner through this room: you will have rather solid 
and stable units, the single objects, but no equally stable and 
firm groups will be formed spontaneously with those objects 
as members. Still equality or similarity and dissimilarity of 
color and other properties, relative distances, etc., are tending 
to form groups; but you observe that one group formation is 
easily displaced by another, depending on slight changes of 
conditions, probably in yourself. It is evident that, under such 
circumstances, the influence of changes in the subjective atti- 
tude towards the field will be much higher than in the case of 
the solid units or stable groups. Even forces of no peculiar 
intensity will now be strong enough to produce new groups in 
a field which with the exception of the objects in it does not 
resist very much because its interior tendencies of group for- 
mation are too weak. [If we wish* to remain consistent in our 
form of theory, subjective attitude and change of it must also 
be represented in the physiological field as physical states or 
stresses and changes of them, which influence the formation 
of physiological groups.] 

The members of these groups, the objects, are however more 
than purely optical entities under most conditions of life. 
They commonly appear as imbued with "meanings," "func- 
tional properties/* and so on, by experience. And these sec- 
ondary properties, when actually present, must be almost in- 
herent now in the optic physiological process units of objects, 
because in extreme examples we have the strong impression 
of actually seeing the acquired properties in the objects, even 
if there is no possibility of their having a purely optical origin. 
I cannot tell you briefly how Gestalt psychology would treat 
this fact. For the moment we may state only that in practical 
life, of course, seen objects have more properties than we 
have had to treat as yet. Do not forget however that one 
necessary prerequisite (for seen objects being imbued with 
their functional properties) is always their real optical exis- 
tence as forms in the field. If you apply "camouflage" to them, 
or if the optical units do not actually exist for some other rea- 
son, the functional properties do not appear either. 



194 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Supposing now a field to be given, in which objects have 
no strong optical tendency towards formation of stable groups, 
our subjective attitude will often tend to group them with re- 
gard to acquired functional properties; not necessarily so that 
objects of equal functional value are grouped together, rather 
more frequently so that objects which belong together in one 
actual practical task of performance stand out together in the 
field. Here, however, we must be careful to avoid a mistake. 
The subjective attitude may easily be taken as something for- 
eign, acting from without like an independent power on the 
content of the field, for instance, forming groups in it. In 
real life quite a different thing usually happens. The chim- 
panzee behind the bars of his cage seeing a banana beyond 
them too far away for his arm is, when healthy and not over- 
fed, immediately in a well defined subjective attitude ; the ba- 
nana there "arouses his appetite/' that is, the relation between 
his inner conditions alluded to and the aspect of the fruit 
makes the banana outstanding in the field, makes the "func- 
tional value" of it very alive and produces the corresponding 
stress towards the fruit, both things being sides of one and the 
same fact. There is no arbitrary subjective attitude; the ap- 
pearance of this object and the animal's attitude towards it 
are changed correspondingly and at the same time, determined 
by the relation between the animal's inner condition and one 
real part of the field. If we consider, not the visual field 
separately, but the larger whole in which it really occurs, 
namely the total situation including the inner conditions of the 
animal, we find the subjective attitude as well as the functional 
value produced in mutual dependence. The subjective atti- 
tude, then, does not come more "from heaven" than changes 
which it produces in the visual field ; and we become aware of 
this fact when we do not restrict our consideration arbitrarily, 
that is again, if we do not make an artificial analysis. After 
a short while we see the chimpanzee looking around for a stick. 
Evidently this attitude is not less determined in the total situa- 
tion than was the direct tendency toward the food. But again 
this new attitude has remarkable consequences upon the objects 
of the field. A man can easily observe in himself in a similar 
situation and one can see in the behavior of the ape, that many 
objects which are not real sticks but something similar to them, 
appear very soon "as sticks" in the functional meaning of the 
word, if no real stick is found. 19 The tree with its branches 

"Kohler, The Mentality of Apes. p. 37, 1925. 



AN ASPECT OF GESTALT PSYCHOLOGY 195 

however may for a long time remain "one thing," too much 
a unit optically to let the functional value of a stick enter the 
branches, since these are not seen as optically real parts at 
least by the chimpanzee. If finally this unit is destroyed under 
the pressure of the subjective attitude of "seeking a stick/' 
we certainly have a case of a unit changed by the subjective 
attitude; but once more this attitude itself is changed at the 
same time and in a corresponding manner : as soon as the atti- 
tude of seeking makes the branch a real part of the field, that 
attitude itself undergoes the change from "seeking" to "break- 
ing off." After all we seldom have the subjective stress alone, 
it is a stress between man (or animal) and the field or some 
part of it, determined by the relative conditions of both sides 
in this total situation. Therefore, in principle, no change will 
occur on one side without a corresponding change on the other. 

I draw some conclusions: Reorganization of the field by 
subjective stress, if the field is not too stable, seems to be an 
important side of intelligent behavior. We suspected this be- 
fore when describing the behavior of apes. But the sub- 
jective stress is as much a function of the field as the field is 
of the stress, both being dependent sides in the total situation. 
And, of course, only if the subjective attitude is so concretely 
related to the actual field, can the corresponding stress have 
effects on the field which lead to the "solution of the problem" 
given in this field. In the total situation, including inner and 
outer conditions, the inner and outer sides of what happens 
seem to be in a similar functional interdependence as prevails 
for instance between the dependent areas of the visual field. 
If that is true, the dynamic intercourse between field and sub- 
jective stress must follow the same rule, that is, develop in the 
direction of equilibrium, which as yet I have only applied to 
the field, the eye movements, etc. 

With these remarks I return to my starting point: Though 
here I have mainly tried to explain the procedure of Gestalt 
psychology in its treatment of the visual field, this is by no 
means the only application which the functional concepts de- 
veloped above admit. They can be as well applied to the full 
reality of mental life and we are beginning to do it. But 
since we need firm ground under our feet we prefer to intro- 
duce our standpoint by showing how it works in vision, because 
there we have the best methods for concrete, experimental 
decisions. 



PART IV 

Purposive Groups 




MORTON PRINCE 



CHAPTER IX 

THREE FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE 

BEHAVIORISTS AND THE RECONCILIATION 

OF THE PURPOSIVE AND MECHANISTIC 

CONCEPTSf 



BY MORTON PRINCE 



Of course all students of Behaviorism cannot be shipped in the 
same boat for they would soon begin to quarrel like all other 
psychologists. There are several types differing from one an- 
other in their points of view and doctrines. Woodworth 
recognizes four different types*. Therefore I do not suppose 
it is possible to define Behaviorism or Behaviorists in terms 
to which all who claim to be good and true believers would 
agree. So it would not be fair to impute to one type an error 
that may only be true of another type. Nevertheless I think 
it is reasonably accurate to say that Behaviorism is an attempt 
to explain human (and of course animal) needs, motives, 
desires, impulses, emotions, thought in short conscious activ- 
ity and the resulting (as commonly supposed) bodily activity 
in terms, not of consciousness, but of the neural and glandular 
processes correlated with the former and of the bodily motor 
behavior which they admittedly induce. Accordingly it is 
not necessary to take account of consciousness at all, but only 
of the objective processes which are correlated with conscious- 
ness, and which enter into the chain of causal events event- 
uating in bodily behavior. Whether or not consciousness has 
anything to do with determining our actions, behavior conduct, 
bodily reactions can be adequately explained by the mechanisms 
of the nervous system considered as reflex processes organized 
into systems (patterns) and the resulting motor activities of 
the individual. Some behaviorists go so far as to hold that 
consciousness has nothing whatsoever to do with our bodily 
reactions and conduct. 

Thus, in his recently published book a leading and esteemed 
Behaviorist, after opening his exposition with the definition, of 
Psychology as "The Science which studies behavior and con- 
sciousness", lays down the principle that consciousness has 
nothing to do with determining behavior. It needs to be 

f Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, De- 
cember 15, 1924. 
*Psychological Review, July, 1921 



200 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

studied, of course, like any other biological event; "no 
scientist," he says, "can afford to ignore the circumstances 
attendant on the events (of behavior) he is observing. Intro- 
spection on conscious states is both interesting in itself and 
necessary for a complete account." ^ But, he maintains, for all 
that, consciousness does not explain behavior. It is only an 
epiphenomenon and apparently any given behavior would occur 
just as well without it as with it. "Consciousness", he goes on, 
<f is in no way a cause of the bodily reactions through which 
the needs are fulfilled. Explanation is not derived -from desire, 
feeling, will, or purpose, however compelling these may seem 
to our immediate awareness, but from the sequence of stimula- 
tion neural transmission and reaction. Consciousness often 
accompanies this chain of events; but it never forms a link m 
the chain itself"* 

Desire, feeling, will and even purpose are thus recognized 
as events, but they are useless events for all the good they 
do in determining our actions. Our actions may accomplish 
our will and fulfil our purpose but we are very foolish in 
believing that our willing or purpose had anything to do 
with them. So, also, Huxley taught just fifty years ago when 
he explained to us that consciousness was related to the 
mechanism of the body as the steam whistle to that of the 
locomotive engine. 

"The consciousness of brutes," said Huxley, "would appear to be 
related to the mechanism of their body simply as a collateral product 
of its working, and to be as completely without the power of 
modifying that working as the steam whistle, which accompanies 
the work of a locomotive engine, is without influence upon its 
machinery." Their volition, if they have any, is an emotion indi- 
cative of physical changes, not a cause of such changes. 

Again, "It seems to me that in men as in brutes there is no 
proof that any state of consciousness is the cause of change in the 
motion of matter of the organism. If these positions are well based, 
it follows that our mental conditions are simply the symbols in con- 
sciousness of the changes which take place automatically in lie 
organism: and that, to take an extreme illustration, the feeling we 
call volition is not the cause of a voluntary act, but the symbol 
of that state of the brain which is the immediate cause of that 
actf 

Huglings- Jackson* and Charles Mercier** taught the same 
doctrine; so the Behaviorists are harking back to the past 

*Italics mine. 

fFortnightly Review, November, 1874. 

*"Evolution and Dissolution of the Nervous System" and other 
papers. 
**"The Nervous System and the Mind." 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 201 

This is a very convenient principle up to a certain point, 
when, as I hope to be able to show, it lands us in a veritable 
and impenetrable jungle where we can no longer follow the 
course of the behavioristic reactions. For the "steam 
whistlers" very conveniently get rid of the parlous problems 
of both introspection and inferences from objective events in 
others, the only methods by which consciousness can be 
studied; but it may be doubted whether it is true, as our 
author maintains, that "a material advance has been made in 
psychology since the adoption of the mechanistic and behavior- 
istic viewpoint" by not "including consciousness or 'mental* 
entities in the sequence of cause and effect". It is certain 
that the behaviorist who adopts this principle cannot give 
in his own mechanistic terms, excepting in the simpler reflex 
actions, a complete and true explanation of behavior that is 
"accompanied" by conscious events. His explanation stops 
short just when it begins to be interesting. 

If he could give such a satisfying explanation, we should 
have presented to us a book in which behaviorism was ex- 
plained from beginning stimulus to the ending motor activity 
without a reference to such whistling events as emotion, or 
images, or imagination, or temperament, or intelligence, or 
will, or purpose. This would be Part I. Then for what he 
calls a "complete" but not causal account in Part II we should 
have a superfluous description of the epiphenomena the 
tootings of the whistle, the conscious processes. 

Such a book has never been written and, it is safe to say, 
never will be ; though "there are a few psychologists who main- 
tain that, since consciousness cannot explain events, it has no 
place in the science which studies behavior", and Watson has 
bravely written a partial "Psychology" trying to do without 
mind*. So far from this being a "serious mistake" from the 
point of view of steam-whistlers, as one leading behaviorist 
thinks, it seems to me to be the only logical attitude that can 
be taken if the "principle" be adopted ; but then it is not psy- 
chology. 

*Watson warns his readers that they "will find no discussion of 
consciousness and no reference to such terms as sensation, percep- 
tion, attention, will, image and like. These terms are in good 
repute, but," he says, "I have found I can get along without them 
both in carrying out investigation and in presenting psychology as 
a system to my students. I frankly do not know what they mean 
nor do I believe that any one else can use them consistently." Psy- 
chology from the standpoint of a Behaviorist; p. 8. 



202 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

I have purposely refrained from mentioning (perhaps I 
ought to say, my physiological processes have, through stimulus 
and response, adapted my pen to the present situation so as 
not to mention) the name of the clever author I have quoted, 
because I am not criticizing any one in particular and I hope 
he will so understand it. He happens to be for my purpose 
a happy and brilliant exemplar of the principle and has had 
the courage and clarity of thought to state explicitly and 
without reserve the doctrine he and other behaviorists adopt, 
just as Huxley did fifty years ago to say exactly what he 
means and to mean exactly what he says, a most admirable 
quality of mind. 

Now, to come at once to the point : one of the fundamental 
errors of the behaviorists (of one type) is the denial of con- 
sciousness as cause of bodily reactions. As I wrote a long, 
long time ago;* "How consciousness causes bodily change is 
one question and that it does so is another. We may not be 
able to say "how it does it, but tlwt it does it is beyond dispute". 
The how and the that are two different questions. I believe 
we can answer both. But even if I am mistaken in thinking 
we can answer the first, I still believe it is futile to deny that 
mental processes cause bodily processes. I may be permitted 
to quote what I wrote in 1891 as it expresses my view today : 

"Now I do not wish to speak except with the highest deference 
for those who hold opposing views. I know how easy it is for the mind 
to deceive itself in matters of this kind; how difficult it is to free 
one's self from the ideas which by long habit are connoted by 
language, and which consequently prevent our viewing a thing from 
a new aspect. But I do wish to emphasize the fact that any 
doctrine which ultimately leads to denial of volition as a cause 
of action is, as Mercier would say, 'nonsense*, and doomed to failure. 
If one is moved to sympathy at the misery of a beggar, and following 
one's sympathy one gives a dollar to that beggar, 'the giver is satisfied 
that his feelings of sympathy his states of consciousness directly 
controlled his muscular acts and moved his fingers to take a dollar 
bill^ out of his^ pocket and give it away. This is a fact of direct ex- 
iperience, and is worth a whole volume of scientific erudition. 

If, under the influence of anger, I strike a man, there is little use 
in my trying to shift the responsibility from my temper to the 
shoulders of my grey matter, and in my telling the world that my 
outburst of temper was only a sort of 'steanvwhistle'; that it 
told me what my right hand was going to do, but had no more 
to do with the hitting than has the judge on the bench who is 
going to try my case. 

Popular language correctly expresses the facts in such cases, and 
any scientific doctrine which attempts to explain the relation of 

*The nature of Mind and Human Automatism, p. 25, J. B. Lip- 
pincott Company, 1885. (Out of print). 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 203 

mind and body, and does not recognize this truth, will never be ac- 
cepted by common-sense people. The contention of those who 
hold the doctrine which will be developed later, is that the 'steam- 
whistle' advocates have been logically driven to their conclusion; 
but the reason for this is that though their logic is faultless, their 
premises are wrong; the conditions of the problem not being 
thoroughly understood. Well-known truths regarding the nature of 
so-called 'matter 1 have, in practice, been neglected, or their full 
bearing on the question been overlooked. That there is a solution 
of this question l which on the one hand does not disregard these 
truths, and on the other hand recognizes volition as a cause of 
muscular action, we believe. This solution thus far for the most part 
has been neglected; but the reason for this is plainly because it has 
not been understood, and not because any serious objection has been 
urged against its final conclusions*. 

I should like to hear a Behaviorist (of this type) arguing 
his case before the Judge and making the plea that he was only 
an automaton and that his "criminal intent" had nothing to do 
with his criminal act ; that it was his neurones, or his ductless 
glands, or his conditioned reflexes that did the crime. I would 
love to hear the Judge say; "Yes, quite so; five years in jail. 
Next case." and then humming to himself : (paraphrasing from 
Shylock) "Until thou canst rail the seal from off my bond, 
thou doest but offend thy lungs, young man, to speak so fool- 
ishly." 

I wonder why the counsel for Loeb and Leopold did not put 
a Behaviorist on the stand as an expert in psychology! Why, 
the whole of criminal law and criminal responsibility is based 
on "criminal intent" the doctrine that consciousness is the 
cause of bodily actions. It is the seal of "criminal responsibil- 
ity". Just imagine the Fifteen Judges of England in the 
famous McNaughton case, instead of laying down the time- 
honored (if not medically honored) test of responsibility ever 
since incorporated in common law: "Did he know the nature 
and quality of his act, or if he did not know it, did he 
know that what he was doing was wrong?", suppose, instead, 
they had laid down the test: "Were the conditioned reflexes 
of his neurones or ductless glands adjusted to the ethical codes 
of society? What a delightful opera bouffe Gilbert and Sul- 
livan would have made of it, rivalling Pinafore ! 

The Behaviorists may be certain of this: any psychology 
that does not recognize that consciousness is a cause of our 
actions, will be treated as nonsense and will never be accepted 
or seriously considered by common-sense people. 



*Morton Prince: Hughlings-Jackson on the Connection between 
The Mind and The Brain. Brain, 1891, vol. XIV, p. 250. 



204 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

II 

A second fundamental error of Behaviorists is to suppose, 
leaving the question of consciousness aside, that behavior 
can be today completely explained in terms of the correlated 
neural and other bodily processes alone. I am ready to agree 
it would be a great desideratum if it could be done. But it 
cannot be done for the simple reason that we have not even 
the rudimentary knowledge that will allow us to follow the 
reactions to any stimulus beyond the afferent receptors, through 
those cerebral pathways that are correlated with mental ex- 
periences. Possibly in the years to come we may be able to 
do this but it will be in the dim, dim future. Just imagine 
trying to follow the "adequate stimulus" through and pick 
out the systems of neurones neurograms, I have thought it 
useful to call them involved in any complicated mental process 
and determining behavior. And yet without doing so it would 
be impossible to explain the behavior. Take, for example, the 
comparatively simple case of going to market to purchase your 
dinner. You look over the different viands offered you, re- 
ject a beefsteak, and after considering different meats, select 
a fine brace of ducks. What neurograms or ductless glands 
determined your behavior culminating in your final choice? 
Your hunger stimulus and habit reactions may get you to the 
market. But even then, what particular neurograms were 
involved? But pass over that. Why did you reject the beef- 
steak? Was it a visual or olfactory, or gustatory stimulus? 
And if so, why did it result in rejection? What neural and 
other systems came into play? Did the stimulus awaken 
neural systems correlated with thoughts of excessive price 
and economical concepts, or conditioned gustatory reflexes of 
aversion, or some other? And if so, which? You can't even 
make a sporting guess. But psychological analysis (not 
psycho-analysis) would reveal what? Why, an unpleasant 
episode of childhood (long forgotten) by which beef-steak 
became linked, not with an unpleasant gastric experience of 
nausea and vomiting after eating a beef-steak, but with a 
person whose conduct towards you had shocked your suscepti- 
bilities. No objective laboratory technique could have possibly 
revealed this episode, though the "word-reaction" method 
might have allowed you to suspect the involvment of the person 
and to postulate a conditioned reflex, or pattern reaction. But 
what reflex and what system of bodily processes was in- 
volved? Well, pass again over the rejection of the beef-steak. 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 205 

What stimulus and neuronic systems determined your final 
behavior in choosing the ducks for your dinner? 

They looked tempting to be sure. Do you think it was 
only by reason of an awakened gustatory conditioned reflex? 
I do not suggest awakened pleasant gustatory images, that 
would be a too subjective explanation. Here again psychologi- 
cal analysis would reveal episodes of the past, episodes of duck 
shooting, outings on Chesapeake Bay when you bagged many a 
duck, sat for hours in a blind with intense excitement, lived 
in a shooting camp with convivial friends, before the days of 
prohibition, lived on ducks that you had shot yourself, etc., etc. 
All this experience was linked up with duck and made your 
eyes open wide when you saw (optical stimulus) the fine brace 
in the butcher's stall and determined your behavior to buy. 

It was the "setting" of these past experiences which was 
the efficient determining factor. Some, perhaps, would call this 
setting a "pattern". "Pattern" or "setting", you may introduce 
it into a mechanism of conditioned reflexes, if you like; but 
how could you have discovered these reflexes and pattern, or 
setting without psychological (introspective) analysis, and even 
now can you point out the particular pattern and reflex paths? 
Can you describe concretely and specifically the factors other- 
wise than in psychological terms? 

Take an actual case from my note book; a woman flies off 
into an extraordinary violent fit of anger ending in hysterics 
and other symptoms eventually landing her in my consulting 
room as a patient. The stimulus was the apparently innocent 
refusal of her husband to protest against the firing of fire- 
crackers under her window on a Fourth of July. Will you 
tell me what neurological and glandular pattern determined 
that behavior? I can tell you the cause in psychological terms 
for it was a setting of experiences dating back many years, 
but without introspective analysis you will search in vain. 
Even after being found, by introspective methods, you cannot 
put your finger on the particular physiological mechanisms 
(neurograms and glands) which, as conditioned reflexes or 
habits, did the job. 

The best you can do in all such cases is to find by intro- 
spective methods the experiences of which the residua became 
systematized (with glandular systems) into a "pattern" or 
"setting" as dispositions (innate and acquired) and then say, 
ex hypothesi, these residua functioning in mechanistic fashion 
after the manner of conditioned reflexes (or some other 



206 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

manner) determined the behavior, while the psychological 
elements were only "symbols in consciousness". 

If all this is true of such simple behavior as that of the in- 
stances I have used, how much more hopeless it would be to 
discover the bodily processes (neural, glandular, and others) 
involved in such behavior as working out a plan for a League 
of Nations, or the mathematics of the Einstein theory of 
relativity, or of the orbits of atomic electrons. 

Ill 

The third error of the behaviorists is in confining them- 
selves to only one method of observation and experimentation 
the objective method. For the successful solution of the 
problems of science, when any given method has been carried 
as far as it can and fails to be adequate to resolve the further 
intricacies of the problem, new problems that have been 
brought to view by the very successes of the method, then new 
methods have to be discovered that will be adequate for pur- 
suing the research along new lines to meet the new problems. 

Of course in physical science all methods are limited to 
objective ones because the physical sciences deal only with 
phenomena and cannot touch the ultimates as we can with 
conscious processes. The physicist finally, therefore, comes up 
against a stone wall and can go no further, as when he reaches 
the problem of the ultimate nature of energy, or of the electron. 
As Bertrand Russell points out, electricity "is not a thing, like 
St. Paul's Cathedral; it is a way in which things behave. 
When we have told how things behave when they are electri- 
fied, and under what circumstances they are electrified we have 
told all there is to tell . . . Electricity is not like red paint, a 
substance that can be put on to the electron and taken off 
again; it is merely a convenient name for certain physical 
laws". But, I may add, the physicist goes further than this. 
He says that the electron is electricity itself, but stops there, 
though, as a matter of speculation he may add it is the way 
something else behaves, e. g., the ether. 

Fromi one point of view this is a limitation of physical 
science, but even within his fields the physicist adopts new and 
many methods as called for. So it is with the problems of 
the medical and biological sciences. What would we think of 
the medical clinician should he say, "Oh! I am a stethescope 
doctor. I only use the stethescope to diagnose diseases of the 
body," though he runs up against a stone wall, when the 
problem of bacterial infection of the blood becomes the vital 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 207 

one? Or of another who should say, "I am a blood doctor. I 
only examine blood/* though the problem shifts to the kid- 
neys? Or of another who boasts, "I am a urinary doctor. 
I only examine the urine," though the problem shifts to the 
brain? Or of another, a psycho-analyst "I only use free- 
associations/' though free associations lead him away into 
philosophy and psychology? 

Plainly, different problems require different and often many 
methods, according to the nature of the problem. 

So when the Behaviorists inquire into the problems of psy- 
chology it may be pertinently asked, is the objective method 
adequate to resolve completely the problems involving con- 
sciousness. When he follows the "adequate stimulus" beyond 
the sensory receptors, does he not run up against a stone 
wall, or, at least, lose his path in a jungle. 

Let us take one of the least complex problems, or at least 
one that offers preeminently objective phenomena for research 
the behavior resulting from, or determined by, emotion. 
The occurrence, in conjunction with emotion, of bodily proces- 
ses (open, as they are, to physiological investigation and having 
given rise to the James-Lange theory) eventuating in certain 
types of behavior, has led to the formulation of the concept of 
so-called "heredity pattern-reaction," or mechanism, as an ex- 
planation of emotional, or emotional-instinctive behavior. But 
is this a complete explanation? Will the discovery of any par- 
ticular visceral, glandular or other bodily process in connection 
with particular behavior, explain the why of the behavior which 
subjectively appears to be not mechanistic but "purposive"; 
why in one situation the individual withdraws from a given 
stimulus, in another examines it intently, in another approaches 
it with an embrace, according as he experiences a sentiment 
of aversion, curiosity, or affection? 

Why are these pattern reactions so specifically (different? 
And why does the behavior seem to the individual to be 
purposive, if it is not? There would seem to be here some- 
thing over and above the visceral (etc.) process and which is 
of the order of consciousness. This something (the emotion 
and cognition) seemis at least to be a part of the reaction 
and to enter into the causal change of events, from stimulus 
to behavior, for given the emotion we can predict the ensuing 
behavior. If this be so, the behaviorist must at this point 
renounce his objective method and resort to some other that 
will allow him to deal with consciousness. 



208 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

The only answer the behaviorist can give is that the emotion 
(and cognition) is an epiphenomenon, the tooting of the steam- 
whistle that tells by its toots what particular visceral processes 
are involved in the causal pattern reaction, and that if our 
physiological knowledge were sufficiently intimate he could 
predict equally well the behavior ; or, as an alternative, that the 
conscious process and the bodily process are only different 
aspects of the same thing. As to the first alternative, of con- 
sciousness as an epiphenomenon I have already said enough. 
If the latter alternative be adopted the conscious experience is 
just as much a causal factor as the physical process and calls 
for a different method of research. 

Thus, if these points are well taken, the Behaviorist, whether 
he be a steam whistler or some other kind of parallelist, or 
an interactionist, or a panpsychist, or some other kind of 
monist, is compelled by the force of circumstances, by the 
hard facts of nature, willy or nilly, to shift to some other 
method after he has carried his objective method as far as he 
can. And the only method open to him that we know of now 
is the introspective method of which there are many kinds. 

The attempt to interpret all behaviour in physiological 
terms has led to most extraordinary statements on the part 
of some Behaviorists. 

Watson in his "Psychology from the Standpoint of 
a Behaviorist," would teach that "emotion is an heredity 
pattern-reaction involving profound changes of the bodily 
mechanism as a whole, but particularly of the visceral and 
glandular systems" (p. 195) ; and that "thought is the action of 
language mechanisms" (p. 316) ; is "highly integrated bodily 
activity and nothing more" (p. 325) ; and that "when we 
study implicit bodily processes we are studying thought". By 
this Watson does not mean to identify thought with the cor- 
related cortical activity of the brain, not at all ; but with all the 
bodily processes that are involved, implicitly and explicitly, in 
the production of spoken, written and sign language the 
muscular activity of the vocal apparatus, diaphragm, hands, 
fingers, eye-movements, etc. (p. 324). 

Now my dear Mr. Watson if you will do me the honor to 
allow me to address you personally I have the greatest respect 
for you and for your work. You have, at least, made the 
psychological world "stop, look and listen". You have made an 
impression on the thought of the day and have made your 
brother psychologists think and reconsider their basic under- 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 209 

standings, and in doing this have been a big influence in direct- 
ing thought and awakening interest in your points of view. If 
any one thinks this easy, let him try it himself. I have tried 
it in a modest field and cannot see that I have had any marked 
success ; so for this reason I take off my hat to you. But, Dr. 
Watson, don't you see that when you define "emotion as an 
heredity 'pattern-reaction' " of bodily mechanisms, you are 
talking just nonsense? You are putting together words that 
severally have meaning into a sentence that has no meaning. 
It is obvious that you are compelled to make some such defini- 
tion in order to consistently adhere to your scheme of a psy- 
chology described in terms of bodily reactions and mechanisms 
without consciousness. But emotion is not a pattern reaction 
of visceral and glandular systems or any other anatomical 
organs. Emotion is a mental experience, an event of con- 
sciousness. You may hold, if you like, that emotion is con- 
ditioned by pattern reactions of the visceral and glandular 
systems; or that it is a mental experience correlated with, 
or even, perhaps, the awareness of such reactions; but to say 
that it is such physiological reactions is nonsense. Emotion 
is emotion and nothing else, and certainly nothing like visceral 
and glandular activity. 

Likewise thought is nothing like muscular activity. Images, 
for example, are elements of thought. Just imagine my 
asserting that my images of this hall and this audience my 
visual pictures of your upturned faces, of the "fair women 
and brave men" I see before me, are muscular contractions. 
A queer sort of mental blindness, queer thinking, and not very 
flattering, you would say. But there is one sense in which you 
might be justified in employing this definition without writing 
nonsense, although I can not make out from the context 
that you have this meaning in mind. You could identify 
emotion and thought with the particular physiological processes 
of the body you mentioned, in the same sense that the physicist 
identifies sound with waves of the atmosphere, and light with 
electro-magnetic waves. But it is apt to be overlooked 
that when the physicist says that sound and light are such 
waves, he does not mean that literally. It is only a convenient 
form of expression. All he means is, that which the organism 
apprehends as sound is motion or waves of the atmosphere; 
and that which the organism apprehends as light is motion or 
electro-magnetic waves or ether waves. Sound and light are 
the reactions of the organism to these waves : the waves excite 



210 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the conscious reaction in us. If there were no beings with 
ears there would be no sound and the universe would be deathly 
still ; if there were no beings with eyes there would be no light 
in the universe : it would be pitch dark as it probably is for 
some insects and other living things. There would be waves in 
the atmosphere and waves in the ether but they would not be 
apprehended as sound or light, respectively, just as there are 
atmospheric waves going on all the time, above and below a 
certain "pitch" which we cannot hear; and there are electro- 
magnetic waves beyond each end of the spectrum, infra red and 
ultra violet, which we cannot see. But the universe is full 
of them all the same. There are living things for which the 
world is absolutely silent and others for which the world is 
absolutely dark. Some living things undoubtedly apprehend 
ether waves not as light but in some other mode; and 
atmospheric waves not as sound but by some other sense. So> 
what the physicist means is that sound and light are modes of 
consciousness by which the organism apprehends different 
kinds of motion in the universe. He is not so foolish as to con- 
fuse motion with sound. 

Now in this sense you can logically hold, if you like, that 
emotion is a conscious mode of apprehending by the organism 
the "heredity-pattern reactions of the visceral and glandular 
systems," or with James and Lange that the stream of sensory 
impressions from these systems become fused into an emotion, 
but this is not identifying the emotion with the visceral re- 
actions any more than is the wave theory of light an identifica- 
tion of visual perception with ether or electro-magnetic waves. 
Nor, does it help out the behavioristic concept. Unless 
emotion can be shown to be an epiphenomenon a steam 
whistle it remains to be shown that it does not enter into the 
causal chain of events inducing behavior; or lacking that, it 
remains for you to find, if you can, its correlated brain pro- 
cesses and show that they do not enter into this chain. 

Likewise you may logically maintain that thought is a mode 
of apprehending the kinetic sensations streaming brainwards 
from the activity of the muscular systems involved in 
language; but psycho-physiologically considered, it takes a 
pretty bold behaviorist to maintain, for instance, that a visual 
image, or an auditory image, or a tactile image, all of which 
are elements of thought, is a mode of apprehending kinesthetic 
sensations, or to identify such images with the muscular activ- 
ity itself. The only alternative would seem to be to take a 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 211 

novel monistic view and correlate thought with muscular activ- 
ity after the same fashion that psychology commonly correlates 
it with brain processes. Here we have parallelism, or pan- 
psychism with a vengeance. Brain processes seem to be chucked 
overboard, bag and baggage, to lighten the ship of behaviorism, 
or as useless stowaways. And as to images and wishes and 
motives and criminal and moral intents which we thought we 
had some reason for thinking had something to do with our 
behavior, they too are only delusions and if we want to know 
what our thoughts, wishes and motives really are, why, just 
study our muscular systems that subserve language ! 

IV 
THE IDENTIFICATION OF CONSCIOUS AND NEURAL PROCESSES 

Let us return now to the first error of the Behaviorists. If I 
am right in holding, as I believe I am, that consciousness is 
"a cause of the bodily reactions through which the needs of the 
organism are fulfilled", the error of those who deny it lies in 
the false major premise that mental processes and brain proces- 
ses are parallel events in the same organism and in the minor 
premise that parallel processes cannot act upon one another. 
Grant these premises and the conclusion is absolutely sound 
that consciousness cannot be a cause of bodily processes. But 
one or the other premise or both must be false because the 
facts of experience contradict the conclusion. The theory, 
therefore, is unsound. 

I recall that my aged professor of philosophy at Harvard, 
when I was a student there, many years ago, had a question 
which he used to put with great gusto, and a snort, to each 
class. When the time came he called me up. "Prince : Suppos- 
ing that fact and theory don't agree; what then"? he snorted. 
I knew the answer he wanted, but, student-like, wishing to 
tease the old man, I replied, "So much the worse for the theory, 
Sir". "No, no, no; Premble, Premble, Premble". Premble 
arose and with the tact of a good boy answered, "So much the 
worse for the fact, Sir." "Quite right, quite right," snorted 
again, the old professor. It seems to me that this is practically 
the standpoint of the Behaviorists (of one type) and con- 
stitutes a fourth error. 

It is obvious that the real question at issue is the old mind 
body problem. This problem, as I have long held and have argued 



212 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

in opposition to the usually held view* and will try presently 
to show, is, in my view, one of identification the identifica- 
tion of consciousness with the reality of brain processes, with 
the brain processes from within. Before arguing once more 
this contention, it will be well to set before ourselves exactly 
what the theory undertakes to identify. For this purpose we 
should think of the ultimate nature of matter from the point 
of view of the physicist and as revealed by modern researches. 
This modern conception of matter simplifies and clarifies the 
physical data involved in the problem, if not the problem itself. 
While formerly the atom was held to be the unanalyzable unit 
of matter, we are now taught that the atom is a microcosmic 
solar system of electrons and protons, units of negative and 
positive electricity, the former revolving in orbits with 
tremendous rapidity around a complex nucleus of electricity 
a unit of positive electricity in the case of hydrogen, a complex 
unit of negative and positive electricity in the case of other 
elements a sort of infinitely minute cosmos. All the physical 
and chemical properties of so-called "matter" are nothing but 
the activities of electricity. In other words and in sum and 
substance, matter, as we know it through our senses has 
disappeared, having been resolved into negative and positive 
electricity, or more specifically units of the same in motion, act- 
ing and reacting upon one another and associated with, or being 
in themselves, units of energy. 

This is a marvellous conception and a marvellous recon- 
struction of our knowledge. The properties of matter, such as 
mass, hardness, crystallization, atomic weight, chemical affinity 
and reactions, are resolved into the activity and manifesta- 
tions of units of electricity; while that which we apprehend 
directly as heat and light and indirectly as ultra violet rays, 
X-rays, radio rays, and other rays, are modes of electro-mag- 
netic motion, shot out by the energy of such electrical units. 

When we look out upon the world of objects about us we 
must recast our mode of viewing them and of thinking. We 
must learn to think in terms of those mysterious concepts, 
electricity and energy, if we would try to resolve the deeper, 
ultimate problems of life and mind, as well as those of the 
physical world. When we look out upon the rocks and houses 

*Op. Cit. (above) : also; Professor Strong on the Relation between 
the Mind and the Body, The Psychological Review, November, 1903; 
The Identification of Mind and Matter: Philosophical Review, July, 
1904. 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 213 

and trees and plants and animals, we must try to view them in 
terms of billions upon billions of negative and positive electrons 
electrical units in tremendous activity and motion, some- 
times sending out units of energy into the world of space and 
always acting upon our senses in such fashion that we appre- 
hend them all, not as they are but as material objects. The only 
known constituent of the ponderable matter of the universe is 
electricity. 

It is as if we were looking at one of those drop curtains at 
a theatre which an exhibitor, by an arrangement of lights, 
makes disappear by its becoming transparent, and allows us 
to see through upon a scene behind. At first we see before us 
houses and trees and people painted in realistic torm upon the 
curtain. Then all these things fade away; they and the cur- 
tain become so transparent that their places have been taken 
by little bullet-like objects, atoms of the elements, most of 
which are arranged in tiny, irregular shaped groups called 
molecules. Nowhere do these little objects coalesce into a 
continuous mass but everywhere they are separated from one 
another by relatively enormous spaces. If we could examine 
them closely, we would find that these atoms and molecules 
have the same properties as have their masses. Atoms of 
gold look and are just like a mass of gold ; a molecule of glass 
just like a mass of glass. 

Now, as we look, the illumination is again modified, so that 
we can see still deeper. The atoms and molecules have 
disappeared and their places are taken by innumerable, 
infinitely small "particles'* which are in constant motion, flying 
around and about, sometimes with almost infinite velocity. 
Many revolve in orbits about others, like the planets in the 
solar system, but here the orbits and the systems are re- 
stricted within the confines of what we a moment before saw 
was the atom. Others fly out of these confines in streams into 
adjoining space and send out waves of energy to even distant 
spaces (radio-activity). Some rush towards others, as if 
attracted by something; others rush away from the same 
"particles", as if repelled. Often there are head-on collisions 
and then we see waves of motion of enormous rapidity, like 
"rays", shooting out into space. Some of these waves stimulate 
our senses and are apprehended as light and heat ; and some do 
not and can therefore be recorded only by mechanical devices. 
These are X-rays, radium-rays, etc. 

Now, let us stop here and listen to our exhibitor who is a 



214 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

physicist. He explains that all the "particles" in their motions 
produce certain phenomena and obey certain laws and he calls 
these phenomena phenomena of electricity, and these laws, 
laws of electricity ; and so the particles are termed electricity, or, 
more specifically units of electricity in motion. And then, again, 
our physicist tells us he is compelled to postulate some kind of 
motive power that drives the electrical units into motion and 
sends out the waves of electro-magnetic motion into space. 
Realizing his own subjective feeling of exerting "force" when 
he pushes some resisting object into motion, he thinks of it 
anthropomorphically, perhaps correctly, as force or energy; 
and accordingly postulates the motive power of the electrical 
units as an entity and calls it energy. 

Now, at this point our exhibitor, the physicist, again changes 
his lights, but reverses the order of appearances. The world 
of electrons fades away and the world of atoms and molecules, 
the complex configurations of the electrons, reappears as larger 
spots where the electrons were. Then in turn these fade away 
and the world of material objects rocks, water, trees, animals 
reappear as configurations, where were the complex groups 
of atoms and molecules. So our exhibitor has allowed us to 
see deep within the world of objects and to recognize that this 
world is only the mode by which we apprehend through our 
senses, the actual physical world of electricity and energy. 

V 

But what about the brain processes of the physiologist, the 
brain processes which we apprehend as such in the same way 
as we apprehend the rest of our material world through our 
senses and which we conceive, as atomic or molecular activity, 
physical or chemical, to be correlated with consciousness? 
These, too, disappear under the analysis of the physicist. Let us 
not forget that we must likewise learn to think of these activ- 
ities as those of enormously complex groups (called atoms and 
molecules) of units of electricity, and groups of groups, motiva- 
ted by and associated with units of energy and, perhaps, radiating 
energy. As a recent writer on the atom from within has ex- 
pressed it : "Whether we are interested in speculative questions 
like those (of life and death), in less speculative but yet un- 
solved questions like the mechanism for the transmission of 
stimuli by nerves, or in the purely practical matter of the 
efficient organization and operation of the multiplicity of 
machines which condition our daily lives, we must seek ex- 
planations in terms of energy and electricity. 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 215 

"Widely different branches of science are now known to be 
dealing with the same fundamentals of electricity and energy. 
For the first time in centuries there exists the material which 
a genius could synthesize into a universal science, in which 
physics and chemistry, biology and geology, will lose their 
identities in a common set of principles.*" 

While waiting for such a genius perhaps I may be 
permitted, to try my hand, in a humble way at synthesiz- 
ing mind and matter into a common principle. 

It is, then, of such mysterious entities that we must think in 
trying to find a solution of the correlation of mind and brain. 
I say "mysterious" for what is this intangible entity elec- 
tricity? And what is the entity energy? These are the two 
fundamental entities of the new science and if we would follow 
its teachings, we must learn to think of all scientific problems 
in terms of these concepts. What is their ultimate nature? 
What is an electron from within? What is energy from with- 
in? The answer of the physicist is that that is beyond his 
province, that he only deals with phenomena, and the laws of 
their relations, and therefore cannot deal with the ultimate 
nature, the reality of anything. 

In a sense the terms electricity and energy are only word 
pictures. They are subjective concepts which we are obliged 
to postulate to explain the phenomena, to give the phenomena 
meaning. Thus, though energy is conceived and postulated 
as the motive power of the physical universe, the only way it 
is evidenced to our senses is as motion, or as changes in the 
form of motion of the electrical units (electrons and 
protons) and as "wave" motions in circumambient space (light, 
heat, etc.). What it is itself is unknown and by the objective 
methods of science it is unknowable. Nevertheless "to every 
moving particle, whether electron, proton, atom, molecule, or 
more evident mass, we ascribe a portion of this unknown."** 



*MHIs: Within the Atom; p. 9. 

**These principles have been clearly summed up by John Mills as 
follows: 

"When we cause a body to alter its state of motion, either by 
changing its speed or its direction, we are conscious of exerting what 
we are pleased to call a force. When we observe the gravitational 
.tractation of body and earth we speak of a force of gravitation as 
acting on the body. Bodies upon which the earth under similar con- 
ditions exerts equal forces we call equal in weight. Unfortunately 
weight is but a particular kind of force and force itself is an entirely 
subjective concept without any objective reality. Whatever may 



216 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Likewise, while the existence of "particles" has been demon- 
strated by physicists and these have been termed particles of 
electricity, or units of electricity, electricity itself is a concept, 
the ultimate nature of which is unknown and by the objective 
methods of science is unknowable. Science can only determine 
its laws of behavior. 

Even positive and negative electricity, (electrons and 
protons) may be only different manifestations of something 
else manifesting itself in these two different phenomena. Con- 
sequently, Bertrand Russell finds it necessary to utter a word 
of warning: 

"It may be found, however/' he says, "as a result of further re- 
search, that the aether is after all what is really fundamental, and 
that electrons and hydrogen nuclei (protons) are merely states 
of strain, in the aether, or something of the sort. If so, the two 
'elements' with which modern physics operates may be reduced 
to one, and the atomic character of matter may turn out to be not 
the ultimate truth. This suggestion is purely speculative; .... 
Our imagination is so incurably concrete and pictorial that we have 
to express scientific laws, as soon as we depart from the language of 
mathematics, in language which asserts much more than we mean, to 
assert. We speak of the electron as if it were a little hard lump of 
matter, but no physicist really means to assert that it is. We speak 
of it as if it had a certain size, but that also is more than we really 
mean. It may be something more analogous to a noise, which is 
spread throughout a certain region, but with diminishing intensity 
as we travel away from the source of the noise. So it is possible that 
an electron is a certain kind of disturbance in the aether, most intense 
at one spot, and diminishing very rapidly in intensity as we move 
away from the spot. If a disturbance of this sort could be discovered 
which would move and change as the electron does, and have the 
same amount of energy as the electron has, and have periodic 
changes of the same frequency as those of the electron, physics 
could regard it as what an electron really is without contradicting 
anything that present-day physics means to answer. And of course 
it is equally possible that a hydrogen nucleus (proton) may come 

be the character of the alteration in the relative motions of the 
bodies of a system the alteration is but the manifestation of a 
change in the disposition and availability of that tmcomprehended 
motive power of our universe which we call energy. 

"Energy and the electrical elements are the postulates of the new 
science, the entities in terms of which all explanations of scientific 
phenomena must be made. 

"To our senses, whether aided by apparatus or not, this motive 
power, or energy is evidenced only by changes in the state of motion 
of the electrical elements. To every moving particle, whether 
electron, proton, atom, molecule, or more evident mass, we ascribe a 
portion of this unknown. The amount which we assign to any 
particle depends upon the speed with which it is moving and upon 
its electrical composition." (Within the Atom, p. 30). 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 217 

to be explained in a similar way. All this is however, merely a 
speculative possibility; there is not as yet any evidence making it 
either probable or improbable. The only thing that is probable is 
that there will be such evidence, one way or another, before many 
years have passed."* 

As a matter of pure speculation I would add we may even 
go further and resolve units of electricity into units of energy 
or manifestations of the same. For a mass is a collocation of 
units of electricity, but mass as a consequence of the theory of 
relativity is energy itself. 

When we think, then, of brain processes, we must learn to 
think of processes, physical or chemical, in terms of their final 
analysis by the physicist; that is, processes of which the 
component factors are mysterious units of negative and positive 
electricity, or mysterious units of energy, or both. 

We are compelled, then, to say that a brain process that we 
are trying to correlate, or identify with consciousness is a 
phenomenon of electricity and energy. Beyond this we have 
not the faintest idea of what concretely a brain process is. 
We must not overlook that fact. Accordingly, t he problem of 
identifying consciousness with brain processes becomes the 
problem of identifying it with processes which are revealed to 
us through our senses as electrical units in activity and wave- 
motions of energy. But we must not forget, what the physicist 
sometimes does forget, that these are not ultimates. They are 
only phenomenal manifestations of an unknown something. 
The nature of this something the physicist cannot even guess 
at. He can only postulate concepts the immaterial entities 
electricity and energy to account for certain phenomena. But 
these entities are not only unknown but unknowable by the ob- 
jective methods of science. The postulated something may be 
spiritual (whatever that may be), or of the order of the psy- 
chical, or something else that is not matter, but is immaterial. 
Whatever it is it is not material in the sense of the material 
phenomenal world as known to physics and to account for 
which it is inferred. It is immaterial. 

VI 

We may now consider the problem itself. The theory for 
which I am arguing is this: that ultimate unknown something 
which reveals itself objectively to our senses, which we appre- 
hend through our senses as phenomena of electricity and as 
phenomena of energy, the unknown immaterial reality of elec- 

*The A B C of Atom, pp. 141-143. 



218 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

trical units and units of energy is the same in kind, is of the 
same nature as that which is known as conscious experience. 
Or, simplifying the statement as a generalization, that same im- 
material reality which, as a concept, is postulated in the objec- 
tive world (the brain process) as phenomenal units of energy 
becomes, under certain conditions of configuration and activity 
of its units, consciousness; just as under other conditions of 
this kind it manifests itself to our senses as atoms and mole- 
cules of electrical units with corresponding physical and chem- 
ical properties and as electro-magnetic motion. In other words, 
consciousness is the reality of a particular portion of energy 
the energy of the universe-in-itself,the unknowable of physics, 
the brain processes (of the physiologist) "from within." Thus 
the psychical becomes identified with that which is postulated 
by the physicist as the unknowable energy of the universe, by 
the physiologist as the brain process. 

Now, see how by this theory the real problem interestingly 
shifts. It is no longer the old problem of parallelism, or inter- 
actionism. Instead it becomes the question: How is it to be 
explained that consciousness a feeling, an image, a color, a 
pain, can appear under such a different form as units of 
electricity, electro-magnetic motions? Surely our experiences 
of the two are totally unlike. 

The answer would seem to be simple and obvious: Elec- 
tricity and energy are the mode in which the reality of the 
brain process consciousness is apprehended, actually (or 
ideally immaterial) through the senses by another organism, 
the reaction of this organism to the reality ; in fact it is the only 
mode by which, if apprehended by a second organism, it could 
be apprehended. For if apprehended through the senses it 
must be in terms of those senses; if through the visual sense, 
it must be apprehended as visual perception form and motion ; 
if through the auditory sense, as sound ; if through the tactile 
sense, as tactile perception; and so with the other senses. 

According to the theory, then, mind and matter become 
synthesized in a common principle ; for consciousness is identi- 
fied, not with electricity (and energy) as objectively appre- 
hended, but with the reality of these concepts, the unknowable 
of physics; or if you prefer, the brain process of the 
physiologist from-within. If the theory is sound, how clear 
it becomes that there are not two processes in the same organ- 
ism, parallel with one another, but only one process, the con- 
scious process. The brain process of the physiologist, and 



FUNDAMENTAL ERRORS OF THE BEHAVIORISTS 219 

electricity of the physicist, are the modes in which the conscious 
process is ideally apprehended by a second organism. 

A moment's thought is sufficient to see how the theory 
clarifies the parlous problem of parallelism, which has been 
the thorn in the flesh of psychological science, and relegates the 
epiphenomenalism of the steam whistle to that limbo where 
such absurdities belong. Interactionism, too, disappears as a 
problem, for, there being only one process, there ceases to be 
the question of how one kind of process, the mental, can act 
upon another of a different kind. 

VII 

We are now at last, you will be glad to hear, in a position to 
take up the main point of our thesis which we set out to 
elucidate namely, the reconciliation of the purposive and 
mechanistic concepts. Unfortunately it was necessary to lay 
this preliminary foundation. It ought to be self-evident how 
this reconciliation follows as a logical necessity. 

Brain processes, that is to say, neural processes, are reflex 
-processes. -That we can all agree to. It is the only way in 
which a neural process can be activated, can function and 
determine behavior. Reflex processes are by nature mechanis- 
tic. There is no doubt about that. But neural reflex processes 
are ex hypothesi, the mode in which conscious processes are 
apprehended through the senses by the methods of the 
physiologist. If that be the case, and if consciousness is the 
reality of neural reflex processes, then conscious striving and 
impulse, that which we call will and purpose, if apprehended 
objectively through the senses would necessarily be appre- 
hended by these methods as reflex and mechanistic processes 1 ^. 
It is the only form in which will and purpose could be mani- 
fested when so objectively apprehended. 

So, when we think in terms of mind, we must think in terms 
of will and purpose ; when in terms of physiology, in terms of 
mechanism and reflexes. In principle it is immaterial which 
terms we use. But we must not deny the former, will and 
purpose, as having equal validity with mechanisms and re- 
flexes, nor forget that consciousness is the real thing, while 
mechanistic processes are only symbols of the real. 



*This interpretation was worked out in my Nature of Mind and 
Human Automatism (1885) pp. 93-98. 



220 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Thus going a step further, Pan-psychism and Pan-material- 
ism are interchangeable terms**; and so purposive and 
mechanistic psychology may be reconciled. 

Practically, however, as we know almost nothing about 
brain-processes, nothing of their nature, and cannot possibly 
even guess the concrete brain process that is correlated with 
(identifiable with) any particular mental process; and as we 
cannot, therefore, follow a stimulus through its intricate and 
complex reflex course of complex brain processes until it 
emerges in motor and other pathways as behavior in view of 
all this ignorance we are perforce compelled to explain the 
causal antecedents of behavior in terms of mind, of will and 
purpose, and not of reflexes. 

It would, indeed, be a happy thing, if we could explain 
behavior in objective terms (brain processes), in view of the 
uncertainties and fallacies of the data derived by introspec- 
tion, open as they are to all sorts of interpretations, for we 
should then be able to use more exact quantitative methods 
of objective science. But it cannot be done. So, if we want a 
complete and causal explanation of behavior, we can only 
use mental terms and get over the difficulties of introspection 
as best we can. Will and purpose are facts of experience and 
as such facts determinants of behavior. They give us a com- 
plete and adequate explanation thereof, one upon which the so- 
cial organizations and sociology are founded, and upon which 
the explanations of behavior made use of by social psychology 
must be based, if it is to be recognized as entitled to a place 
amongst the sciences. Nevertheless, if we can reconcile two 
apparently conflicting points of view, as I have endeavored in 
this exposition to do, it will redound to the advantage of psy- 
chology, and perhaps it is not too much to say, of our con- 
ception of the universe. 

**Morton Prince: The Identification of Mind and Matter. 



CHAPTER X 

AWARENESS, CONSCIOUSNESS, CO-CONSCIOUS- 
NESS AND ANIMAL INTELLIGENCE FROM 
THE POINT OF VIEW OF THE DATA 
OF ABNORMAL PSYCHOLOGY! 

A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS* 



BY MORTON PRINCE 



My task is not an easy one, for psychologists are not at all times 
a happy family. They have not as yet learned to live harmoni- 
ously together on the basis of a common understanding of what 
they mean by such concepts as those which are presented in the 
title of this lecture, nor of the facts of experience for which 
they are supposed to stand. They should not consider it out of 
place, if they were reminded of the old proverb about "a house 
divided against itself*. But what is lacking in a common 
understanding is made up for by the positiveness of statement 
and the cock-sureness of opinion of each member of the family, 
leading sometimes to acrimonious discussions in matters of 
pure theory and making one think of the sects of the Donatists 
and Orthodox Christians of olden times who belabored one 
another with cudgels because they could not agree in matters of 
dogma and doctrine. I fear that psychologists, being human 
beings first and searchers after truth afterwards, are like all 
mortals, too often concerned with maintaining their own points 
to which they have committed themselves rather than discover- 
ing the truth. Perhaps after all we cannot expect the latter 
until "this mortal shall have put on immortality." 

So now to our task, but with as open a mind as we can mus- 
ter and, if possible with sustained dear thinking. 

At the very outset we are confronted with a technical diffi- 
culty, namely, ambiguity of terms. Both consciousness and 
awareness have several meanings in that each term is used in 
several different senses and interchangeably as well as ex- 
clusively. Thus, for example, consciousness is used to denote 
the being conscious, or aware of something of objects (en- 

fPowell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, De- 
cember 15, 1924. 

*An abstract of this lecture was read at the International Con- 
gress of Psychology held at Oxford, July 25 August 1, 1923. (See 
Proceedings and British Journal of Psychology.) 



222 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

vironment), or thought, sensations, perceptions, feelings, or of 
self by some thing, or some one, or self, or "I", as when I say 
I have a consciousness of such or such a thing; or, I have a 
consciousness of self ; or of my internal feelings. 

But it is also used to denote simply thought, sensation, per- 
ception, feelings, images, etc., i. e., a process, each by and of 
itself regardless of whether it is per se awareness of something 
by something : as when we speak of consciousness as contrasted 
with the physical world, or of thought, sensation, feeling, as 
elements of consciousness, or of the content of consciousness. 

Awareness is also used with the same two meanings, although 
that of awareness of something by something is by far the 
more common. Indeed some assert that awareness without a 
subject is a contradiction in terms. It connotes a subject who 
is aware. Consciousness, on the other hand, has no such neces- 
sary connotation in some folk's minds, though the contrary is 
asserted by others. 

Nevertheless, consciousness and awareness are often, if not 
commonly, used as synonyms, it being insisted by those who so 
use them that they have identical meanings. Cognition also is 
used as a synonym for awareness and consciousness and with 
similar double meanings. 

All this is bad enough, leading, as it does, to inevitable con- 
fusion owing to the fallacies resulting from using the same 
terms in different senses. But it is worse than this. There is 
no common understanding of the psychological facts for which 
the terms stand-in whichever sense the terms are used. Thus, 
for instance, it is held by some orthodox psychologists that, as 
a fact, there is and can be no consciousness that does not in- 
clude in its content both some thing, some subject, some person, 
some experiencer, some self, that is conscious and a conscious- 
ness of some thing. An elementary state of consciousness, or, 
more correctly, a conscious process that does not include these 
other elements does not, they say, in fact, occur. This con- 
cept^ of course, postulates consciousness as equivalent to and 
identical with awareness. 

The question plainly is one of fact which can only be deter- 
mined by investigation. It is one of the most important prob- 
lems of psychology and cannot be resolved by theoretical 
reasoning and logical deductions from the meanings of words. 
Its importance lies in the fact that it opens up, as I will 
presently explain, the whole question of the actual occurrence 
and nature, indeed the possibility of subconscious processes, 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 223 

that is, of consciousness of which we are not aware, and there- 
fore, of the structure, mechanisms and functioning of the mind. 
And more than this, upon the answer to this question hangs 
the possibility of forming a biological conception of conscious- 
ness. 

But first let me touch upon the more specific and narrower 
question as to whether the postulated experiencer involved in 
this notion of consciousness as awareness can be based on a 
demonstrated specific awareness of a self.* 

Psychologists are divided into three camps the self-psychol- 
ogists, the selfless-psychologists and the middle grounders. 
The first group maintain that the content of every conscious 
process includes a self an awareness of self, a self -conscious- 
ness. Hence that all consciousness is a consciousness or aware- 
ness of something by a self. 

The second group, the selfless ones, claim to be unable to find 
any self, or consciousness of self by introspection; deny its 
reality and hold that mental processes function without any 
such reality. The "I" and the "You" are merely compulsory 
expressions required by the necessities of language. 

The middle-grounders admit the self in that we are aware of 
self in, for instance, feeling and willing, but not in perceiving 
and imagining which may go on without any self or self- 
consciousness. I must class myself in principle with these last 
the middle grounders. 

Of course there are also the indifferent non-combatants who 
take no heed of the self at all a sort of plague-on-both-your- 
houses attitude and go on talking about awareness, and con- 
tent, and objects of awareness as if the question of by what, 
or by whom could be ignored. The implications of their 
language, however, are that something is aware though what 
is not defined. But this vagueness is also true, and specifically 
so, of the self-psychologists. These do not attempt to analyze 
the self, to define its structure, to say what it is, even whether 
it is animistic or psychological ; whether it is "an anima or an 
animus sitting", as you may remember Tristram Shandy's father 
used to say, "like a tadpole all day long both summer and 
winter", dabbling its feet in the fluid of the pineal gland. It 
has no analyzable psychological structure. For it is said to be 
an "ultimate datum"; to be "indefinable", "sui generis and 

*Compare Mary Whiton Calkins' admirable critical discussion of 
the problem: "The Self in Scientific Psychology;" Amer. Jour, of 
Psychology; Oct. 1915. 



224 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

therefore incapable of definition" ; it "is a kind of thing which 
one can merely indicate but which one can as little demonstrate 
to the I-blind as one can demonstrate color to the color-blind"* 
a veritable tadpole theory. 

Surely we must allow, in view of all this confusion, that the 
Behaviorists have some excuse for joining in the cry, "A plague 
on both your houses" ! and saying, "we will have none of con- 
sciousness ; away with it. We are going to disregard it entirely 
and explain behavior in terms of physiological processes alone", 
though they ought to add, "if we can". 

This question as to whether there can or cannot be conscious- 
ness that has no awareness by "some one who is conscious of 
some thing" some person, some subject, some self, that thinks 
and experiences and is aware, this question is, as I have already 
intimated, of fundamental importance to psychology. For, 
obviously, if consciousness (experience), when considered 
identical with awareness, always includes an I, and if "we can- 
not talk of experiencing without an I which experiences", as 
Dunlap, Mary Calkins, Oesterreich and others of that camp 
insist, then a sub-consciousness that is to say, a coconscious- 
ness ( as I prefer to term it) or coawareness, or an "uncon- 
scious", term it what you will, is a paradox and an absurdity. 
It is mere nonsense. Consciousness is conceived of as limited 
to and only what may be called our personal consciousness. 
And this many insist upon on this very ground, entirely ignoring 
the findings of abnormal psychology including therein 
artificially dissociated and activated mental processes. One 
must admit that logically they are right, if the premises be 
granted; but their premises, so abnormal psychology teaches, 
and as it seems to me, are unsound ; and abnormal psychology 
relies on precisely the same methods and the same kind of 
data and the same logic as does traditional normal psychology. 
I don't want to be one of those pestiferous friends who are 
always telling unwelcome, if wholesome, truths, "but our mutual 
friend and collaborator Abnormal Psychology insists on telling 
us a lot of disagreeable truths to which, as the easiest way out, 
the "normal Psychologist", taking a tip from Nelson with his 
blind eye at the battle of Copenhagen, finds it exceedingly con- 
venient to turn a deaf ear and to pretend he does not hear 
them. And among those truths, or at least claimed truths, are 

*0esterreich; quoted by Miss Calkins. It is fair to say, though, 
that the I is not considered as something having an existence be- 
yond and beside experience: "Experiences exist in the self." 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 225 

a lot of sensations and feelings and thoughts of which a given 
subject is not aware and which are therefore called caconscious. 
They are not in the content of his awareness. There is no 
use saying that they are not types, or orders of consciousness, 
for they are. They are certainly non-physical and they are 
both psychical and psychological. Nelson saved his skin by 
winning the battle, but I can't help thinking these psychologists 
of the normal are yet to win and save their skins. 

The data of abnormal psychology and of dynamic psychology 
include a large number of percepts and "ideas" and sensations, 
dissociated from the personal consciousness, from awareness by 
the self, and from any thing that thinks or perceives. They are 
processes, of course, and these processes are not synthesized 
with that other complex or process which is called a self, an "I" 
or a personality. Until these facts, as I believe them to be, are 
recognized and frankly utilized as data, I can't help thinking we 
shall never be able to understand consciousness as processes, 
nor biologically, and therefore animal intelligence and instinct. 

II 
CONSCIOUSNESS REGARDED AS COGNITION 

In venturing these criticisms on the negligent attitude of the 
self -psychologists of course I have only in mind that concept 
of consciousness which identifies it with awareness by a self, 
a subject, an experiencer, who (logically we can only say 
"who") is inherent in every conscious process. 

But there is another conception of awareness which is 
germane to the problem in hand and this we must take a few 
moments to consider. I am sorry and must ask you to bear 
with me a while longer before taking up our main theme. It 
is a much more subtle notion in that it means the identification 
of consciousness with a particular kind of awareness- You 
will see that it is a much more defensible notion in that it can 
be reconciled with the data furnished by subconscious processes 
as derived from experimental and abnormal psychology. This 
must now be examined. 

According to this subJe notion awareness is identical with 
cognition-of-something, but neither the one nor the other need 
involve a self that is aware ; the very simplest conscious process 
is in itself and by itself cognition of something. Therefore, no 
self or experiencer would seem to be required, unless it be the 
"organism". But to call it the organism, as I will presently 
insist, is the introduction of an objective and biological term 
in the psychological equation. 



226 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

I am not sure that this conception of awareness has been 
explicitly stated in these terms, but it is, at least, so implied in 
certain expositions of consciousness as set forth by well known 
writers. 

Thus it is maintained, for instance, by William McDougall, 
for whose work I have great admiration and with whom I am 
fundamentally in accord, it is maintained by him, with Mary 
Calkins' approval, that every sensation, every perception even 
of the simplest and most rudimentary kind in the simplest and 
most rudimentary organism conceivable, is cognition and there- 
fore awareness of "something there". 

"The simplest mind," he forcibly argues, "we can legitimately con- 
ceive is, then, one which would respond to a sense-impression, not 
merely by 'having a sensation 1 but by an act of knowing; this act 
we could only describe as becoming aware of something there, an 
object in space, no matter how completely undefined the nature of 
the object as thought of and the nature of its spatial relations. 
Such a mind, of simplest possible structure, must be conceived as 
consisting of one cognitive disposition linked with a single conative 
disposition. Such a mind would respond to every sense-impression 
that affected it at all (no matter what its nature) with simple 
awareness of something there and a vague undirected impulse of 
appetition, of striving towards the object/ 1 * 

This, if I understand him correctly, amounts to saying that 
every sensation is, itself, per se, cognition and awareness, but 
not by a self. 

Here cognition and awareness are robbed of one of their 
attributes and are given another and particular meaning. If 
this be true of the simplest mind in the simplest organism, then 
it must, also, be true of the simplest dissociated and coconscious 
sensation, or image, of the human mind, and of this, as I shall 
presently point out, there is some experimental evidence that 
may be adduced in support. 

This is the only meaning that I can conceive can be given 

*0utline of Psychology, p. 260. Bold face mine. 

It is difficult to reconcile this view, if I do not misunderstand 
him, with his argument for the substitution of the term experience 
for consciousness. Just as "All experiencing or thinking" he says, 
"is the experiencing or thinking of [-by] some one, some person, 
some organism," and "whenever we refer to a fact of experience 
we imply some one thinking of some thing/' so consciousness "stands 
for the fact of being conscious of something" and "implies some 
one who is conscious of something." 

These two conceptions of consciousness, one requiring a subject 
that is aware (conscious) of something, the other only awareness of 
something, the response of a simple cognitive disposition without 
an apparent subject, can hardly be reconciled. 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 227 

to cognition and awareness under this theory. Only on the 
adoption of such a meaning can consciousness and purposive 
behavior be attributed, as McDougall "provisionally at least" 
does, to such microbes as the protozoa (on the basis of Jenning's 
observations and conclusions) . Likewise a dissociated "prick" 
of a pin may be felt, and, according to the evidence, in fact is 
felt coconsciously by an anesthetic hysteric as a subconscious 
perception of "something there" and even as a pin there, but 
not by a self. And so with many coconscious, dissociated sen- 
sations, images and perceptions. It is difficult to reconcile this 
conception of consciousness with that for which McDougall 
has argued when adopting the term "experience" in place of 
consciousness; namely that "consciousness implies some one 
who is conscious of something". 

Undoubtedly he would further explain to us that the aware- 
ness of the "simplest mind", of a protozoan, and of a dissoci- 
ated bit of consciousness for "something there" is by the 
"organism", for he sometimes substitutes this term for the 
subject "who" (or I). But to say that the "who" is the 
organism is a poorly masked camouflage for it is substituting 
biological objective terms for psychological terms, and intro- 
ducing the ambiguous middle. If we are going to have a sub- 
ject, it is a high potentate, the psychological "who" to whom 
we want to be introduced and not a conglomeration of such 
common folk as the liver and gall bladder and muscles, or any 
material "who". 

After such a ruthless elimination of the self, the question of 
awareness would seem to become a purely academic, if not a 
philosophical one, and to be practically of no importance. 

It does seem queer, not to say paradoxical, that such a dis- 
sociated isolated conscious process as a simple sensation, or a 
complex of sensations (perception) of which the personal con- 
sciousness is not aware, can be a cognition of something in the 
environment without there being anything that cognizes a 
cognition that is not a cognition by something. How can we 
speak of a cognition that is not a cognition by something? If 
it is insisted that the cognition must be by a self or subject, then 
we may ask how many selves or subjects are there in a given 
personality. We may have any number of independent dis- 
sociated conscious processes, independent so far as aware- 
ness of each other is concerned. Does each one of them imply 
a self ? If so it would seem that there must be any number of 
selves. 



228 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

A way out of the difficulty may be found in the following 
considerations. Probably no sensation after the first experi- 
ence ( if not before) ever occurs as an isolated experience. It 
is always integrated with other sensory events kinesthetic and 
pressure sensations, visual and tactile images, sensory localizing 
impressions, etc., whether because of inherited integrations or 
acquired experiences. The whole of these are integrated into 
a complex which, as a setting, gives the sensation meaning. 
A prick from a pin, we will say, is integrated even with re- 
vived visual images of a pin, as well as with numerous other 
sensory impressions. It is this whole structural complex which 
functions when (the other senses being neglected) the skin is 
pricked. It is comprehensible that such a complex may well 
be in itself a specific cognition of something jihere of a pin, 
an apperception of the stimulus.* It is the pin for conscious- 
ness. 

At any rate, if all that is meant by "awareness" is that kind 
of, or so much consciousness or cognition as is presumed to be 
present in the protozoa and to determine its reactions, as so 
cautious and conservative an investigator as Jennings thinks 
justified ; or the kind that may be possessed by William James* 
theoretical polyp (quoted by McDougall with approval) which 
thinks, "Hello ! thingumbob again" ; or so much consciousness 
as may be present in higher animals, like the crawfish of Thorn- 
dike's and Yerkes' experiments, presumably without any self, 
or self-awareness, one can accept for all practical purposes the 
concept of consciousness that identifies it with cognition without 
a subject (save the material organism). 

Indeed, I think that the data from Abnormal Psychology I 
am going to marshal and the thesis I am presenting better 
supports the position of the purposive behaviorists against the 
mechanists, the tropists, the conditioned reflexers, and others, 
than that other insistence of McDougall that consciousness 
stands for and "implies some one who is conscious of some 
thing". 

The practical questions are : Are dissociated mental processes 
of which the self is not aware, themselves conscious processes? 
If so, are they devoid of a self, a subject, and self -awareness? 
And if the answer is affirmative, what can such simple con- 
scious processes by themselves as dissociated coconscious sensa- 

*I am not sure whether such a structural complex is not anal- 
ogous to, or identical with the Gestalt concept. 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 229 

tions, images, perceptions, etc,, devoid of self and all self- 
awareness do? How far are they capable of choice and can 
they adapt the organism to the situations of life and thus deter- 
mine so-called purposive behavior in short, exhibit intelligence 
of various sorts? And how far are they paralleled by such 
primitive types of consciousness as presumably occur in the 
animal world? If such processes are self -less and yet can 
determine purposive behavior and if they can be so paralleled 
by the primitive types of the animal mind, we shall be able to 
give a psychological interpretation of animal behavior and form 
a biological conception of consciousness. 

With the narrower question of the reality of a specific self 
in what I may call our every day "personal consciousness", let 
it be borne in mind, I am not concerned. 

In order to avoid the confusion from the double meaning of 
terms, I shall at once precisely define the meaning in which I 
shall use the terms "consciousness", "awareness" and "cogni- 
tion". 

I am going to use "awareness" in the first of its two common 
meanings and "consciousness" in the second of its meanings as 
defined at the beginning : that is to say 

By awareness I mean an awareness or cognition of something 
by something, (an "I", self, subject, experiencer, or something 
that is aware). 

By consciousness I simply mean thought, sensation, percep- 
tion, image, feeling, sentience, or anoetic consciousness without 
any implication of its being itself awareness, i*., cognition of 
something by something. Whether there is or is not such con- 
sciousness is a question of fact to be determined by investiga- 
tion. The evidence for the veridity of this concept I pro- 
pose to present 

Awareness thus becomes a type or order of consciousness and 
the two are not used as synonymous terms. 

By cognition I mean knowing or awareness of something 
there without necessarily there being a subject that knows, 
though of course there may be such. It is a modified and 
particular type of awareness. This subjectless cognition I hope 
to be able to justify. 

Ill 
THE EMPIRICAL DATA 

I propose now to examine the content and activities of the 
simplest conscious processes with a view to determining (a) 



230 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

whether they include anything that can be regarded as aware- 
ness by something a subject, an experience^ a self; (b) the 
character of the behavior, if any, which they determine, i. e., 
whether purposive or not; (c) the degree of intelligence ex- 
hibited by such simple processes; and (d) how far they may be 
regarded as analogues of the lower orders of the animal mind. 

Such simple conscious processes suitable for study are found 
in the dissociated and more or less segregated processes oc- 
curring in certain abnormal conditions, such as hysteria and 
dissociated personalities; in artificially produced conditions, 
such as suggested post-hypnotic acts ; and in normal states, like 
intense concentration of the attention and absentmindedness ; 
and in that no-man's land of dreams, automatic writing, etc. 

The very simple dissociated coconscious processes found in 
these and other allied conditions and the behavior which they 
determine enable us to study consciousness reduced to its 
simplest terms sentience, sensations, perceptions segregated 
from the complex self and from the highly complex order of 
conceptual thinking with which, as experienced probably only in 
man, sensations and perceptions are normally inextricably 
commingled and integrated. 

It is a fair assumption that such simple dissociated processes 
are analogues to primitive orders of mind and the simplest of 
them approximates McDougall's theoretical "simplest mind we 
can conceive . . , one single cognitive disposition linked with 
a single conative disposition". Of course such a mind is an 
abstraction for every mind is more complex than this ; and so 
is every dissociated process, and many may be very complex. 
Indeed dissociated processes may be of every degree of com- 
plexity from the simplest to the highest, approximating a wholly 
integrated mind. 

But many are exceedingly simple compared with the com- 
pletely integrated human mind, probably as simple as many 
types of primitive minds belonging to the lower forms of animal 
life. A study, then, of simple dissociated processes ought to 
throw light on the problem of awareness, and give an insight 
into the kind of behavior which can be determined by the 
simpler minds which, as we infer, are manifested in the lower 
orders of animals. 

Of course no dissociated process is completely isolated any 
more than is any conscious process of normal everyday think- 
ing. The one as much as the other is organized in a "setting" 
of dispositions deposited by past experiences in which it has 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 231 

its roots and which conditions the reactions of the process to 
given stimuli or a situation. Nevertheless, the same must be 
true of primitive animal minds. 

The phenomena I shall make use of are the inferred cocon- 
scious (subconscious) processes revealed in: 
1 : Hysterical anesthesia. 
2 : The fringe and ultra-marginal zone of consciousness during 

a) normal attention: 

b) certain types of absent-minded acts and impulsions: 

c) suggested post-hypnotic acts : 

d) phobic attacks. 

3 : Certain types of extremely dissociated personalities. 

4 : Coconscious images in various conditions. 

5 : Coconscious solutions of mathematical problems. 

6 : Coconscious somatic and coenesthetic sensations and anoe- 

tic consciousness. 
7: Tics and hysterical and suggested contractures. 

The method employed in all but the last of these conditions 
is chiefly introspection in states of repersonalization, i. e. t 
hypnosis, abstraction, so-called dissociated personalities etc., but 
in some observations, where it could be employed, introspection 
by the presumed Coconscious process itself was employed and 
described by subconscious writing. 

The fundamental principles underlying the method are: 

(1) that by introspection in these states memories of con- 
scious processes previously segregated and excluded from the 
awareness of the personal self can be brought within the aware- 
ness of the newly repersonalized subject; and also that com- 
munication can be established with these subconscious processes 
by means of automatic writing; or that they can be made to 
manifest themselves by other sorts of behavior of one kind or 
another. 

(2) The assumption that these segregated bits of conscious 
processes roughly correspond to the simpler types of conscious- 
ness and, therefore, to the theoretically simplest mind, and that 
the behavior they determine to that which such a mind 
determines. 

It will be well at this point to make clear what is meant by 
coconsciousness, or more correctly coconscious processes, and 
for this purpose give some examples of the data upon which 
this concept is based and which I also desire to make use of 
for a biological conception of consciousness. 



232 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

1. I cannot do better than begin with the old and classical 
phenomena of hysterical anesthesia. These have long been 
known to students of abnormal psychology. I prefer to begin 
with them, because they are as important as they are old and 
have not been as yet adequately analyzed ; and because psychol- 
ogists, who undertake to interest themselves in the problems of 
awareness and consciousness, rarely give any signs that they 
have heard of them and much less take cognizance of them as 
data, nor seem to realize that they may be possible factors in 
the problems. 

Hysterical anesthesia is a loss of sensation by the personal 
consciousness due to dissociation from functional causes. It 
may involve only some of the senses, or all of the senses, and 
only part of the body, or the whole of the body. 

Now, given an hysteric of a certain type with absolute anes- 
thesia of the skin, no tactile stimulus is felt, much less perceived, 
no matter how intensely the attention is concentrated on the 
stimulated area. The lack of awareness of the tactile stimulus 
is not due, therefore, to lack of focusing the attention ; i. e., to 
the unfelt sensation a prick of a pin, or the touch of a hand, 
or the burning of a hot iron, or whatever it may have been 
having been in the fringe of awareness. There was simply 
and plainly absence of awareness. 

Now put that hysteric into another state of mind, or person- 
ality, that is to say hypnosis, and he recalls, first, that there did 
actually occur the sensation of a "prick" or "touch"; and, 
second, that when it occurred he was unaware of it. He 
further insists that it was a veritable sensation-in-being. More 
than this he recalls and insists that there was a coconscious per- 
ception of which he was at the previous moment unaware, and 
in evidence thereof, when put to the crucial test, he describes 
accurately what the experimenter did that he pricked the hand 
five times, drew a figure on the skin, put a pair of scissors, a 
knife, a key in the hand, bent the third and fifth fingers, and so 
on. These he now claims to remember were true coconscious 
perceptions of which the hysteric was unaware in spite of con- 
centration of attention. 

Again modify the experiment. Instead of hypnotizing the 
hysteric try tapping the so-called unconscious dispositions by 
automatic writing at the moment of the tactile stimulus. The 
writing now describes accurately the tests and insists there are 
at the very moment coconscious sensations and perceptions ex- 
perienced synchronously with the tactile stimulus by that which 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

2. In absentminded acts there is commonly dim sub-aware- 
ness by the subject of the act, but there is a type in which no 
such awareness of it, or of the conscious process which deter- 
mines it, can be detected. But this process can afterwards, in 
hypnosis, be recalled to memory as having been a coconscious 
one, often rich in visual imagery. It may be quite complex 
and determine complicated purposive behavior, such as we all 
know absentminded acts may be, sometimes to our mortification. 
It exhibits cognition but not by the personal self as the ex- 
periencer. In this case consciousness or apperception itself, 
apparently, is cognition, unless some other self can be found. 
3. Of the various conditions in which dissociated cocon- 
scious processes are found, the one in which they are, perhaps, 
most beautifully studied by experimental methods is that of 
artificially suggested post-hypnotic acts. These, as you all 
probably know, are acts performed by a favorable subject in a 
waking state as a result of a suggestion given while he was 
hypnotized. The subject, for example, is told in hypnosis that 
after waking, at a given signal, he will arise from his chair, 
walk across the room, take down a certain book from the book- 
case, carry it to some part of the room and place it in a given 
place, and so on. If the subject is a good one the act will be 
performed as suggested in a sort of absentminded way with- 
out even, it may be, his being aware of what he is doing. In- 
deed such acts are in principle absentminded acts. 

Now, in experiments of this kind I have found that there is 
a conscious process of which the subject is unaware which 
determines the act. In the example I have cited there is at 
each step in the act a coconscious visual image of and preceding 
the next step to be performed. Thus there develops the image 
of the subject walking across the room whereupon he arises 
and absentmindedly walks across the room; an image of the 
bookcase he arrives at the bookcase; an image of a hand 
reaching for the designated book he reaches for and takes 
down the book, and so on. 

These coconscious images of which the subject is not aware 
are found in a good many conditions besides absentminded and 
suggested post-hypnotic acts. They occur in frankly repressed 
thoughts, in the subconscious perseveration of dreams after 
waking (e.g., automatic kleptomania), in artificially induced 
hallucinations, in automatic writing, in concentrated attention 
as when we are in a "brown study", and various other condi- 
tions. In some conditions they come and go repeatedly, or may 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 

writes, while at the same instant the subject testifies he is not 
aware of the stimulus. More specifically, that which writes 
feels and perceives while the subject is unaware. 

Now, unless we refuse to accept the psychological interpreta- 
tion and insist, as Miinsterberg used to hold, that the tactile 
stimulus is only recorded as a neurological disposition to be 
later awakened as a conscious memory,* we have here a very 
simple coconscious process a sensation, or a perception 
which is also a "cognition" of the environment; for the con- 
sciousness is not simply a sensation of pain, in the case of a 
pin-prick, but a realization that is is the prick of a pin, and in 
the more complicated tests a recognition of objects such as 
scissors, key, etc., as has been already mentioned. 

Is the coconscious cognition, revealed in such observations, 
that by a co-self, a co-subject, or co-experiencer, for such it 
would have to be in view of the unquestionable fact that the 
hysteric-subject is unaware of the co-experiences? This is a 
subtle problem. To so interpret the data would require the 
postulation of a plurality of coexisting selves, or a reconsidera- 
tion of our conception of the nature and structure of a self. 
It will be better to postpone giving an answer to the question 
until all the data are in hand. Assuming, however, provision- 
ally that the answer is negative, that such simple coconscious 
processes do not justify the postulation of a plurality of I's 
or selves, the significance of the phenomena in question for the 
problem of awareness and consciousness is that consciousness 
is not synonymous, coextensive or identical with self -awareness, 
or awareness 'by a self, or by a subject, or an experiencer or 
anything. If the residua left by the simplest coconscious ex- 
perience of the kind here cited is to be regarded as "one cogni- 
tive disposition linked with a single conative disposition" (Mc- 
Dougall), there remains the question, what kind of behavior 
can such dispositions determine? To answer this question we 
will examine dissociated coconscious processes occurring under 
other conditions. 

*The _ physiological interpretation lands us in a whole peck of 
difficulties. It does not get rid of the coconscious interpretation 
in principle because it would have to admit that the written mem- 
ory was an hallucinatory memory and, if so, as hallucinations are 
not neural but a conscious process, the theory postulates a cocon- 
scipusness, a co-hallucination. Further it would have to explain the 
writing itself as due to neurological processes. There are also a 
large variety of other subconscious phenomena which it would Jiave 
to explain. 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 235 

remain more or less stabile, or they may behave like cinema 
pictures and symbolically represent elaborate thoughts or ideas. 
Sometimes they erupt into the personal consciousness and then 
the individual becomes aware of them as hallucinations or 
visions. Indeed this is the psychological mechanism of the 
visions of saints and sinners; but saints and sinners are aside 
from the subject in hand. 

What I want to call attention to now is that further investi- 
gation has shown, as I believe, that, first, these images are ele- 
ments in a conscious process of which the personal conscious- 
ness is unaware a coconsciousness and which may be very 
simple in composition, or of greater or less complexity; and, 
secondly, this process may determine intelligent purposive 
behavior of various types varying from kleptomanic attacks to 
subconscious writing; and, thirdly, it has all the character- 
istics of intelligence and cognition. Whether or not this Co- 
consciousness is awareness in the sense I have used this term, 
i.e., by something, a subject, a self, is a question we shall 
presently consider. 

4. When we come to study coconscious perceptions in nor- 
mal every-day life, we have a mass of observations showing 
perceptions of the environment and of the body of which the 
personal consciousness is not aware auditory, visual, tactile, 
kinesthetic, coenesthetic, etc. These are of sounds in the 
street, voices, visual images of the environment, sensations of 
warmth, cold, and discomfort, of positions of the body, tension, 
and coenesthesis, generally, streaming in from the body, none 
of which enters the content of the personal consciousness at 
all. They are all comparable in principle to the perceptual 
phenomena I have already described of hysterical anesthesia. 

As to behavior, the coconscious bodily sensations may cause 
shifting of the position of the subject, or general restlessness, 
and sometimes discontinuance and change of occupation, or 
location without the subject realizing the reason therefor. 

In these three classes of phenomena, then, absentminded 
acts, suggested post-hypnotic acts and coconscious perceptions 
of normal every-day life we have dissociated bits of conscious- 
ness, *. e., conscious processes consisting of little more than 
simple perceptions dissociated from the personal self, but which 
nevertheless are manifestly cognition and determine behavior, 
not of a reflex order, but intelligent and adaptive to a purpose 
or end. If they can be shown to have no specific self of their 
own, they give an insight into the nature of a self -less con- 



236 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

sciousness like that which we imagine the lower animals pos- 
sess, and the sort of behavior it can determine. 

The phenomena I have cited are sufficient, I think, for my 
purpose without detaining you with a further recital of actual 
examples of the performances of coconscious processes in other 
normal and abnormal conditions I have referred to,^ such as 
automatic writing, mathematical calculations, subconscious per- 
severation of dreams after waking, phobias, tics, and other 
states. 

IV 
AWARENESS BY COCONSCIOUS PROCESSES 

Now, if the veridity of dissociated coconscious processes of 
the kind I have cited be accepted, the important question re- 
mains, is the ^consciousness self-less, and has it self-aware- 
ness, and does it involve an awareness by a self or subject, or 
experiencer, or something? Is, for example, the simplest dis- 
sociated and coconscious sensation or even perception of a 
pin-prick an awareness of something there by a coconscious 
self, even though the personal self feels nothing? In short, 
can it be said to have any real awareness, or is it per se self- 
less cognition? The last question is a very subtle one. 

Theoretically if there is a coconscious self an experiencer 
this self would have to be a second self differentiated from the 
personal self, for the latter is ignorant of the coconscious pro- 
cess, and there would have to be as many selves as there were 
differentiated dissociated experiences and of these there may 
be any number.* It looks to me as if we were going to get 
into hot water, or at any rate into very troublous waters, if we 
are going to attribute every dissociated conscious process, no 
matter how simple, of which the subject is unaware, every co- 
conscious perception, every bit of automatic writing, every 
motor-automatism, to an "I". Kipling's ape, Bimi, you will 
remember, got into terribly hot water because he had "too much 
ego in his cosmos", but our cosmos would be a whole universe 
of egos. 

But the problem is too important as well as difficult to be 
turned aside by a jest. Whether or not there is a self which 
is differentiated from the subject-self and may be called a co- 

*Of course I am excluding coconscious personalities, like "Sally" 
(case of Miss Beauchamp), which represents very complexly organ- 
ized coconscious systems with a veritable second self. They throw 
light on the structure of the self which, in my judgment, contrary 
to that of the self-psychologists, is analyzable and definable. 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 237 

experiencer who co-experiences the simplest dissociated co- 
sensation or co-image (assuming the fact of co-experience to 
be accepted as veridical as those who are familiar with the 
phenomena do accept it) of which the subject is unaware is a 
subtle question and one not easy to answer. It is a matter of 
interpretation dependent upon the evaluation of the evidence. 
An affirmative interpretation would require the postulation of a 
plurality of coexisting selves, and probably a recasting of our 
conception of the nature and structure of a self and a more 
exact knowledge than we now possess. 

A plurality of coexisting selves is theoretically possible, par- 
ticularly as we know that in the complex conditions of so-called 
multiple personality, dual (or more) selves occur, but if we 
are to ascribe a self to every dissociated conscious process, it 
looks as if the animistic psychologists are going to have a hard 
time of it. Perhaps we ought to have more exact knowledge 
of what a self is before reaching a conclusion on theoretical 
grounds, particularly on any theory of cognition. 

But we have considerable positive testimony though it must, 
of course, be evaluated as relating to the question at issue. 

The empirical evidence entirely denies self-awareness to such 
coconscious experiences. The introspective testimony of my 
dissociated subjects, who in that condition recalled vividly and 
precisely these subconscious experiences, has been unanimous 
that these experiences were without selfconsciousness, that in 
their content there was nothing that the personal pronoun "I" 
could be applied to. The subject could not say, and there was 
nothing that ^could say, "I saw this", "I felt that" ; the per- 
ceptions, feelings, etc., were not synthesized into a self or per- 
sonality. The conscious events were just sensations, percep- 
tions, images and "thoughts" and nothing more no agent, 
nothing that could be called a psychological "experiencer". 
This evidence contradicts Wm. McDougall's view alleging to be 
a "fact that there is only one agent in alfr forms of mental 
activity, you or I, he, she, or it, an agent that can properly be 
denoted only by a proper name or pronoun, or generally as the 
'subject'." Here was a type of mental activity in which no 
such agent could be discovered. 

If it be said that the organism was the agent, the experiencer 
that experienced, then it may be replied that this is using both 
the noun and the verb in a different sense in an objective and 
biological sense and not in a psychological one, and we are 

*Italics mine. 



238 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

guilty of the logical crime of the ambiguous middle term. To 
say that the "organism experiences" has no meaning for psy- 
chology, and it is a very different thing from saying that "I" or 
"you" experience the one is only biological and objective, the 
other is psychological. 

Now, please don't close your minds and go away with the 
opposing thought that such phenomena as I have cited are rare 
and therefore may be disregarded. Whether they are rare or 
not (and they are not), like "flowers that bloom in the spring, 
tra, la, la, has nothing to do with the case." They may be as 
rare as Dinosaurian eggs, or a tadpole sitting on top of the 
Washington Monument, but if a single dissociated selfless con- 
scious process can be established that is devoid of awareness 
and yet can determine intelligent purposive behavior, a funda- 
mental principle is thereby also established that becomes the 
basis for a biological concept of consciousness and the under- 
standing of animal behavior. 

The deeper significance of these findings is, first, that con- 
sciousness is not always to be limited to and therefore synony- 
mous and identified with the awareness of the every-day per- 
sonal self. Otherwise, a subconscious, or coconscious, or un- 
conscious process would be a paradox. 

Second, a self is not essential, as some maintain, for con- 
sciousness, nor, paradoxical as it may seem, for cognition, nor, 
as Ach implies and agrees, as a result of his experiments on 
normal subjects, does all personal experience involve conscious- 
ness of self. So the conclusion that conscious processes may 
function without there being any self-awareness or awareness 
by a self does not wholly rest on the findings of abnormal 
psychology. It also is in keeping with the studies of Michotte 
and Prum on themselves and four other normal subjects. 
These experimenters, who found direct introspective evidence 
of a self and self-activity, distinguished this experience from 
other sensational and affective experiences without self-con- 
sciousness. 

Third, another point of significance, especially for a biological 
conception of consciousness, is that a dissociated selfless con- 
sciousness of a primitive type, can determine intelligent purpo- 
sive adaptive behavior of a kind that parallels the behavior 
of the lower animals. 

V 

ANIMAL INTELLIGENCE AND BEHAVIOR 
In the course of our discussion of coconscious phenomena I 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 239 

have already called attention to the intelligent purposive be- 
havior which even the simplest coconscious process, without 
any self or self-awareness, can determine. This behavior, as 
we have seen, varies in complexity all the way from maintaining 
the posture of the body for a given purpose, or the adaptation of 
the posture and the relation of the subject to the immediate 
situation of the environment (if the evidence is accepted) to 
more complex purposive acts such as those called absent- 
minded behavior, the complicated actions following sugges- 
tion in hypnosis, defense behavior (in phobic attacks and con- 
flicts with the volition of the "conscious self") and impulsive 
actions such as kleptomanic behavior, to say nothing of solving 
mathematical and other problems and of constructive imagina- 
tion exhibited by a dissociated consciousness without self- 
awareness. 

Such behavior is commonly called automatic although it can 
be shown, as I believe, to be determined by conscious processes 
of which the self is not aware. This would seem to give some 
insight into what very possibly may be the central conscious 
factor in instinctive and other types of animal behavior. We 
are so accustomed from our intellectual experiences, to think of 
awareness by a self as essential for purposive and intelligent 
behavior, that it has been difficult to conceive of consciousness 
being involved in instinct and learning by experience in the 
lower animals. Hence the behaviorists, who are now having 
wild joy-rides in America, have sought a way out by con- 
ditioned reflexes. But the findings I have just cited, as well 
as a large variety of other findings in the field of the cocon- 
scious, discovered by abnormal psychology, show another way 
out; viz: that consciousness without any self, or "awareness" 
can determine behavior of an intelligent purposive kind. Such 
a dissociated consciousness may be regarded as a relatively 
primitive consciousness and it may well be the type of mental 
activity in animals. 

At any rate the resulting behavior which it motivates, as I 
will presently point out, is comparable to that of the lower order 
of animals; and therefore a study of the different orders of 
dissociated consciousness and the resulting behavior would 
reasonably seem to give an insight into the central conscious 
factor in animal behavior including cognition and the affective 
element in instinct. Indeed I think we may say that the be- 
havior of animals, from the lowest through intermediate levels 
to nearly the highest (where self consciousness may be devel- 



240 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

oped) can be paralleled by similar sorts of behavior carried out 
by dissociated conscious processes in man 5 whether they be of a 
normal, abnormal or artificially induced character. By such 
automatic conscious mechanisms, the "trial and error" behavior 
studied by animal psychologists may be better interpreted than 
by the mechanistic principles of conditioned reflexes, tropisms 
or other physico-chemical reactions. To this I will presently 
return. 

From this point of view we may say that examples of all the 
different types of animal behavior and of the inferred animal 
consciousness, according to the stage of evolutionary develop- 
ment reached, can be found recaptitulated under various 
conditions in man. 

The discovery, if I may be permitted to use so strong a term, of 
dissociated imagery and perceptions, which, through the pro- 
cesses of which they are elements, determine intelligent be- 
havior, without any awareness of processes, or pertaining to the 
processes (as in suggested post-hypnotic behavior and in vari- 
ous other types), offers an interpretation of the mechanism of 
animal behavior which has been so baffling. In animal be- 
havior I include the "trial and error" phenomena which have 
been the study of animal psychologists. Loath to interpret this 
as "intelligence" of the anthropomorphic sort, in which reason- 
ing and volition and an implied self are fundamental factors, 
mechanists, like Loeb, and behaviorists, like Watson, have 
sought to find an adequate explanation in tropisms or in pure 
conditioned reflex responses without intervention of conscious- 
ness an explanation which seems to be satisfactory to the 
mechanistic behaviorists but to nobody else. On the other 
hand it is difficult to accept the actuality of reasoning and its 
implications in so lowly an animal as the crawfish which learns, 
through "trial and error" to avoid obstacles and reach its goal 
by a selected path. I have in mind the experiments of Yerkes 
and Thorndike. But if it is true that in human beings con- 
scious processes involving perception and images, dissociated 
from the^psychological self and without anything that is aware 
of anything, can exhibit memory and determine complicated 
intelligent purposive behavior which fulfils an aim and reaches 
a goal, it would seem that we have here the analogue of a fairly, 
and relatively, primitive consciousness and that a similar though 
simpler sort of consciousness may well exist in lower animals 
that have organs of sensation, and may determine the behavior 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 241 

in "trial and error" experiments. Such an hypothesis is not 
only tenable but is of wide reaching significance. 

To be a little more explicit, if the data of abnormal psych- 
ology be accepted, the hypothesis derives considerable support in 
that the behavior of the lower animals, let us say the crawfish, 
is determined by a consciousness of a primitive type (without 
awareness) that is also found in man; namely, that has as com- 
ponents an assortment of sensory images of past experiences 
(or memory) of a simple sort and less specialized than in man, 
sensations of present experiences, feelings, and impulses, de- 
rived or not from innate mechanisms (instincts) the whole 
organized by experience into a complex without awareness, 
though it may be "cognition/' but capable of determining pur- 
posive adaptive behavior. Just such complexes in dissociated 
conditions have been reveded in man. 

The crawfish, for instance, has eyes and a gustatory and a 
tactile apparatus. If it has eyes we are compelled to infer 
that it has visual sensations, however vague or unsystematized ; 
and if it has visual sensations, it would seem to be a necessity 
that those sensations would be revived as "images" according to 
psychological -laws by associative experience or, in other terms, 
memory ; and so likewise with gustatory, coenesthetic, and tactile 
sensations and images, thus a complex of memorial images 
and the processes to which they belong would be organized by 
experience, and it is the complex as a whole that would function 
To take particular instances, the "trial and error" behavior of 
Thorndike's crawfish would be explained by the organization 
of kinesthetic and visual images of past trials with gustatory 
memories of the food finally obtained and feelings of appetite 
satisfied the whole complex providing the impulses to behavior 
and guiding the movements of the animal in a purposive 
fashion, The same mechanism would adequately satisfy the 
accomplishments of McDougall's white rat and Airedale ter- 
rier* to both of which he rightly, as I think, attributes intelli- 
gent puiposive behavior. Both animals learned by "trial and 
error" to accomplish what in man would be called "intelligent" 
acts. Analogous behavior we have in man manifested by the 
phenomena I have already described. To eliminate all con- 
sciousness as a causal factor is to make consciousness a pure 
epiphenomenon and to revert to the "steam whistle" theory of 
Huxley. 

*Outline of Psychology; pp. 190 and 196. 



242 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

No less an accurate observer and cautious authority than 
Jennings, whom McDougall pertinately cites, finds it impos- 
sible to explain the behavior of protozoa by the hypothesis of 
reflex response to stimuli and regards such behavior as requir- 
ing the intervention of some sort of consciousness analogous 
to that which we have to postulate in higher animals. 

"We have asked" he says, "merely whether there exists m the 
lower organisms objective phenomena of a character similar to 
what we find in the behavior of man. To this question we have 
been compelled to give an affirmative answer. So far as objec- 
tive evidence goes, there is no difference in kind, but a complete 
continuity between the behavior of lower and of higher organ- 
isms." 

As to the presence of consciousness in micro-organisms he 
concludes : 

"Paramoecium . . . makes such an impression that one in- 
voluntarily recognized it as a little subject acting in ways 
analogous" to our own. Still stronger, perhaps, is this impres- 
sion when observing an Amoeba obtaining food . . . The writer 
is thoroughly convinced, after long study of the behavior of this 
organism, that if Amoeba were a large animal, so as to come 
within the every-day experience of human beings, its behavior 
would at once call forth the attribution to it of states of pleasure 
and pain, of hunger, desire, and the like, on precisely the same 
basis as we attribute these things to a dog . . . We attribute 
consciousness to the dog, because this is useful; it enables us 
practically to appreciate, foresee, and control its actions much 
more readily than we could otherwise do ... I believe it be- 
yond question that we should find similar attribution to it 
[Amoeba] of certain states of consciousness a practical assis- 
tance in foreseeing and controlling its behavior. Amoeba is a 
beast of prey, and gives the impression of being controlled by 
the same elemental impulses as higher beasts of prey". 

In attributing consciousness to such low forms as the pro- 
tozoa of course we do not think in anthropomorphic concepts, 
in terms of human consciousness. We must rather try to con- 
ceive^ if we can, of psychical processes as contrasted with 
chemical and physical processes, but sufficiently specific and 
differentiated as sensibility to determine purposive adaptive 
behavior. By "sensibility" is to be understood, a primitive con- 
sciousness, or primordial consciousness without the attribute of 
thought or Reeling though it is sentience. But we may 
attribute to it the capacity of registration, conservation, and 



A BIOLOGICAL THEORY OF CONSCIOUSNESS 243 

reproduction of experience. According to the view of some, all 
living matter has these functions; which means of course, 
memory, which in turn, in the last analysis, means the capacity 
to adjust through experience to situations of the environment. 
By the theory then, if not demonstrated fact, of sensibility, the 
behavior which Jennings found in the protozoa might well be 
explained without attributing the more highly specialized 
anthropomorphic consciousness to these low forms of animal 
life. And we may be justified in correlating the introspective 
findings of vague coenesthetic consciousness, that I have cited, 
with the primitive and even anoetic consciousness of animals 
and interpret them as sentience. After all, this is only taking 
that other step that reaches monism ; is it not ? the identifica- 
tion of consciousness, or "mind stuff," with the ultimate reality 
of chemical and physical processes, the theory which I reached 
and elaborated in my first lecture. 

There is to be found, then, functioning in the human organ- 
ism all the different types of psychical and psychological pro- 
cesses which occur throughout the scale of the whole animal 
hierarchy at the various stages of evolution reached, from the 
dim sentience of the protozoa to that higher intellectual activ- 
ity which culminates in thought and self awareness; and, as a 
working hypothesis, it may be held that in man every evolution- 
ary stage of consciousness is recapitulated and represented, 
beginning with what is probably mere sensibility of the simple 
cell, through the highly specialized sensations and perceptions, 
without awareness, fo the more conscious processes of thought, 
and self awareness. Through such considerations we are led 
to that biological conception of consciousness which I have 
endeavored to unfold. 



CHAPTER XI 

THE PROBLEM OF PERSONALITY* 
How MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 



BY MORTON PRINCE 



The theory of personality is fundamental to the problems 
of Social Psychology and of Abnormal Psychology. It may 
be said that at least an elementary understanding of the psy- 
chology of the component traits of personality, if not of their 
dynamic mechanisms, is essential for poets, dramatists and 
other writers of fiction; ,and, above all, for biographers, if 
they would understand the apparently paradoxical and often 
contradictory traits manifested by their characters. For such 
an understanding involves an understanding of what is called 
human nature. I have therefore thought the problem ap- 
propriate for this lecture. 

The frequently advanced theories of personality are, to my 
way of viewing the problem, inadequate or incomplete in that 
they do not take into consideration and give an explanation 
of all the facts involved. Among such facts left out and 
there are many are those of the normal everyday alterations of 
character, those of the asocial personality, those involving the 
problem of character versus intelligence and those commonly 
called abnormal alterations , or phases of personality, but which 
are manifestly due not to abnormal but to the normal function- 
ing of mental processes under altered conditions. 

Furthermore, the theories most in vogue are predicated either 
on the one hand on the debatable premise of "instincts" hav- 
ing very specific functions and determining very specific pur- 
posive behavior concepts unacceptable to some; or, on the 
other hand, on the still more debatable premises of the naive 
modern Behaviorist who defines personality in terms of bodily 
reactions to the environment, without taking note of the psy- 
chological mechanisms involved, and thus would reduce every 
trait of personality to conditioned reflexes, relegating the mind 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
December 17, 1924. 

An abstract of this lecture was presented at the meeting of the 
British Association for the Advancement of Science, Psychological 
Section: Toronto, Canada, August 6-13, 



246 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

to the superfluous position of the steam whistle on the loco* 
motive, as Huxley did half a century ago. 1 

TRAITS OP PERSONALITY AS ENDURING DISPOSITIONS 
ORGANIZED IN SYSTEMS (NEUROGRAMS) 

Common, as well as psychological observation, teaches that 
every individual exhibits a greater or less number of native 
and acquired intellectual endowments, certain acquired mental 
traits, certain acquired habits of mind and body, certain moods 
and certain innate affective conative tendencies, which deter- 
mine his reactions to the situations of life and particular cir- 
cumstances of the environment. 

For example: Intellectual endowments would comprehend native 
capacity for and acquired knowledge of, mathematics, music, language 
and special fields of learning, capacity for constructive imagination, 
logical judgments, etc. Amongst acquired mental traits may be 
classed sentiments, ideals, and beliefs; amongst habits, modes of 
thought, opinions, prejudices, etc.; and amongst innate affective 
tendencies are to be found all those impulses and driving forces 
which are recognized as derived from or correlated with the emotions, 
feelings and appetites, and are generally called instincts or instinctive 
tendencies. 

Most of these components, those that are acquired by life's 
experiences are peculiar to and vary in each individual, but 
the innate instinctive tendencies are common to all individuals. 
The sum of the different components as a whole constitute 
personality; and according as the components vary in character 
and quality and the modes in which they are assembled, or 
integrated with one another, will characters differ. 

For convenience of description we may extend the meaning 
of the term "traits" to include all the different components 
and so I shall do. Now the individual traits of personality 
are to greater or less degree fixed and enduring those that 
are innate permanently so: others acquired by experience, like 
habits and^ sentiments, fixed and enduring until modified by 
new experience; and then as new formations this quality is 
still continued. 

It is ^obvious that this quality of fixed persistence implies 
some kind of enduring dispositions and these we are com- 

^Attempts have -been made to classify personalities (or more cor- 
rectly, characters) into types, such as the introverted, extraverted 
noetic, cyclothymic, autistic, etc. (Jung, Conklin, Rosanoff and 
others;. But such classifications do not touch the real problem 
They ^are merely descriptive of end results. They do not explain 
anything. What we want is an explanation of the Why and How 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 247 

pelled to formulate in physiological terms, in terms of corre- 
lated neural dispositions organized to a greater or less degree 
into potentially functioning whole or systems. An organized 
system of neural dispositions I have thought useful to denote 
by the term "neurogram" 1 a neural record of mental and other 
experiences. 

It is impossible to conceive of a mental experience, or process like 
a thought, or a sentiment, or a feeling, enduring, as such, after it 
has passed out of the awareness of the moment. We cannot think 
of it as stowed away somewhere, as you stow away a penknife in 
your pocket, or a book upon your -bookshelf. The very fact of 
it 'being a process indicates that it ceases to exist as such. We are 
compelled to conceive of it only as conserved by means of a corre- 
lated brain disposition potentially capable of being stimulated to 
activity and therewith reviving the original men-tal experience or 
process. The nature of the correlation depends upon what theory 
of the mind-body problem we adopt parallelism or monism. But 
in any case, if -we bear these concepts in mind, we may avoid 
pedan-ticism and speak, interchangeably and indifferently, of physio- 
logical dispositions or mental dispositions, as the functioning of the 
former ex hypothesi necessarily carries with it corresponding men- 
tal processes. But let us remember mental disposition is a figure of 
speech. 

The innate and acquired mental "traits" of personality, then, are 
conditioned by physiological dispositions. But just as physiological 
dispositions are (or may be) organized into systems, so of necessity 
the processes of the correlated mental experiences are correspondingly 
organized. As the one is, so must the other be. Accordingly mental 
"traits" (as I have defined them and aside from pure native endow- 
ments) comprehend, besides the innate instinctive tendencies-, sys- 
tems of potential or actual activities organized by experience within 
themselves and with the innate, instinctive conative activities and 
conserved as physiological dispositions. 

DEFINITION OF PERSONALITY 

We may, then, define Personality as the sum total of all the 
biological innate dispositions and tendencies of the individual 
and all the acquired dispositions and systems of dispositions; 
or, more specifically, as that psycho-physiological collocation of 
traits (meaning all the native and acquired intellectual en- 
dowments, all the habits, sentiments and other mental systems, 
plus the inherited emotional instincts, appetites and other tend- 
encies) by which the mind manifests, or may manifest itself, 
i. e., actually or potentially, and of which certain variable com- 
ponents determine the reactions of the individual to the cir- 
cumstances and situations of life. 



*The Unconscious, p. 109. 



248 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

I say "actually or potentially" because there are two facts that 
should be noted: First, there are many "traits" which though en- 
during components of the personality may be only rarely manifested. 
Potentially, however, they are there and may determine, given the 
situation and the circumstance, the reactions of the individual. This 
is particularly seen in the emotional tendencies, such as anger, fear, 
mirth, play, etc. That is to say, a person may be of such a placid 
temperament that he may almost never be known to manifest anger, 
which may seem to be absent from his personality, yet potentially 
the innate disposition is there and given some adequate _ circum- 
stance the anger reaction will be called forth. And so with fear 
and other emotional tendencies. 

Similarly with acquired sentiments. There may be organized 
within the structure of the personality sentiments which are rarely 
in activity; there may be even antagonistic sentiments involving 
the same "object and incompatible with each other love and hatred 
of, or aversion to one and the same person or thing, each having been 
created at different times under different conditions of the organism 
or by different experiences. Within habitual situations and con- 
ditions only one of such antagonistic pairs habitually functions but 
the other opposing sentiment, nevertheless, endures as a potential 
disposition capable of functioning. For let the situation and other 
conditions be sufficiently altered and it will be switched into activity. 
And so it is with the other components of personality. 

I would impress upon you and I beg you to hold constantly 
in mind, lest I be misunderstood, that for the moment I am 
concerned only with the structure of the mind and not with the 
dynamic forces contained in its traits the conscious and the 
subconscious strivings and urges, the "drives'* and conflicts 
nor with environmental situations as stimuli. These two fac- 
tors largely determine what variables or traits shall in any 
given situation be manifested as character. But the structure 
of the mind conditions these dynamic forces and the reaction 
to the environment. I shall later, in due time, consider these 
other dynamic factors. 

ALL NEUROGRAMS AND TRAITS NOT ASSEMBLED 
INTO A FUNCTIONING WHOLE 

Now a fact to be noted and which must be taken into con- 
sideration by any theory of personality, is that, of the various 
and many organized dispositions, or neurograms, compre- 
hended potentially in the whole personality and when func- 
tioning providing the traits, all are not assembled under all 
conditions and at all times into a functioning whole. The 
individual reacts at one moment with one set of traits and at 
another with another, perhaps of an opposite character. In- 
deed he may possess, as I have said, traits that are antagonistic 
to one another, such as sentiments of hatred and love, or in- 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 249 

terest and disinterest, for the same object; or he may mani- 
fest both charitableness and uncharitableness ; intelligence and 
stupidity ; etc. Obviously such opposing traits cannot be mani- 
fested at one and the same moment. But let the conditions 
of the organism be altered, such as occurs in fatigue, or illness, 
or intoxication, or states of dissociation, or moods ; or let the 
conditions of the environment be altered and one or the other 
of these opposing traits comes into functional activity. The 
dispositions underlying its opposite then may be said to be dis- 
sociated from the functioning systems of the personality, or 
be suppressed, or switched off. In other words, that which 
is the functioning part of the personality undergoes alterations 
from time to time, one set of traits being predominant at 
one time and another at another. There occurs a dissociation, 
or switching out, of some dispositions and re-synthesis, or 
switching in, of others. 

CHARACTER A PHASE OF PERSONALITY AND NOT 
A FIXED STABLE THING 

The terms "personality" and character are often loosely 
used interchangeably as synonyms. I am afraid I have done 
so myself. But it would be better to use "personality" in the 
comprehensive sense for the sum total of all the enduring traits 
and their underlying organized dispositions, potential and 
active, innate and acquired, possessed by the organism, and 
reserve "character" for those traits and dispositions which are 
predominant or characterize the personality at different 
moments, determining at such moments the reactions of the 
organism. From this point of view personality would 
change only as traits were modified by, or new traits were 
acquired by experience. The character would change not 
only in accordance with new experiences, but in accord- 
ance with changes in the internal conditions of the organism 
(strivings, conflicts, moods, intoxications, etc.) and with 
changes in the environmental situations. These character- 
changes are different phases of personality in that they repre- 
sent selected groups of the total of the variables of personality. 
It is a matter of dissociation and re-synthesis of variables 
that is, of organized systems of dispositions and corresponding 
reactions. 

The practical point is, the character of the personality is 
not^ a fixed stable thing, but may be altered from time to time. 
It is a variant of the personality. Some individuals are not 



250 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the same in character in the morning and evening; nor under 
adversity and prosperity; nor in sorrow and happiness; nor 
in sickness and health; nor in the different relations of life 
those of business and the home and society, etc.; nor, as is 
proverbial, in wine and sobriety as Mr. Volstead and Mr. 
Bryan, who would take all the joy out of life, would have us 
remember. Personality has many phases, or variants. 

So the functioning part of the personality is subject to alter- 
ations from time to time, manifested in changes of character 
and corresponding reactions. The resulting phases are nor- 
mally observed and in popular parlance are commonly spoken 
of as "sides" to the personality, or character. They are par- 
ticularly obtrusive under abnormal conditions, internal and 
external, and are then called abnormal alterations of per- 
sonality such as intoxications, trance, fugues, hypnosis, 
deliria, sleep, multiple personality, etc. But such _ abnormal 
states are only complex systems formed by dissociation and 
synthesis out of the variables various components of the 
whole personality. So they, too, are all phases of personality. 

MULTIPLE ALTERNATING PHASES IN EVERY 
DAY LIFE 

Yet nearly all writers of fiction and even biographers have 
failed to recognize what in these modern days the most ad- 
vanced criminologists and penologists have recognized that 
man is a many sided creature and woman, if I may venture to 
say it, particularly so. No one is wholly good or wholly bad ; or 
wholly hard or wholly sentimental ; or wholly self-centered or 
wholly altruistic; or wholly self-assertive and self-reliant or 
wholly shy and self-depreciative ; and I may even say wholly 
intelligent or wholly stupid. William James classified human 
beings as the "tough-minded and the tender-minded;" but no 
one is wholly tough or wholly tender. So every one has differ- 
ent sides, as we say, to his personality, each side manifesting 
its particular traits and conduct, which are the expressions of 
its particular interests and sentiments and ideals ; its instinctive 
emotions, and feelings; its impulses, and desires, and moods. 
And according as which side is uppermost will a person appear 
to his neighbors and to the world as a person of this kind of 
character or that kind. 

An acquaintance of mine, for example, is a practical busi- 
ness man, a steel manufacturer. In the management of his 
business he displays the characteristics of a capable executive 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 251 

and money maker. His character, expressing his interests 
and ideals and impulses at such times, is only that of a business 
man bent on industrial and financial success. 

But from time to time he shuts himself up in his room, bars 
out the world and his friends and even the enticements of 
every social pleasure, and alone with his violin as a companion 
loses himself in the land of dreams of music and emotion 
and sentiment until the wee sma' hours of the morning. At 
these times the business self disappears, and a dream self of 
emotion and sentiment, oblivious to all else, takes its place. 

So also will a person appear as a shrewd, hard, selfish, ruth- 
less egotist in his dealings with business competitors, when 
one side is uppermost; and to the public, when it is the other 
side, as a compassionate, generous, philanthropic altruist, in- 
terested in bettering the welfare of his fellow beings by the 
use of his millions. 

Or, again, in this country a type of political boss used to 
be not uncommon (and is still not as extinct as the dodo). 
When one side was uppermost, he would appear ambitious, 
unscrupulous, uncharitable to his opponents, and a grafter on 
the public treasury; and then, under different conditions and 
in a different environment, which called out the other side of 
his nature, he would exhibit in private life to his family and 
friends, a character of high ideals, honest in private dealings, 
exemplary in morals, kindly and charitable, beloved by all 
who knew him. 

Or again, may I take the personality of Abraham Lincoln 
which has been such a puzzle to his biographers, and is now 
puzzling a distinguished biographer, so he tells me, who is 
writing a new life. There were at least two sides to Lincoln's 
personality. There was the uncouth, coarse-minded hilarious 
Lincoln, constantly repeating the unprintable jests and language 
of the youths of the rough pioneer life that was the lot of 
the early settlers and of the sordid vulgar civilization of the 
primeval forest. And there was the sad Lincoln, the idealist 
whose thought was not only the manifestation of a sublime 
character, but embracing the loftiest concepts of human nature, 
was expressed in language that recalls in purity and beauty 
the most inspiring ethical and poetic imagination. No wonder 
his biographer, unversed in psychology, is puzzled. 

In the realm of fiction the dramatist is forced by the con- 
ventional canons of his art, if not by lack of wisdom, and for 
the purposes of dramatic effect, to depict but one side of the 



252 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

personalities of his characters. Consequently there is probably 
not a character of the drama, excepting possibly Dr. Jekyll and 
Mr. Hyde, of which the whole personality has been portrayed. 
lago, devil that he was, probably at home with his children, 
if he had a home and children, might have been the picture of 
an angel father. Melancholy Jacques, if he had had a couple 
of cocktails before dinner, might have forgotten his pessimism 
and shown, in vino veritas, another side of his personality and 
entertained his company as a hilarious jester. Even Hamlet, 
though a good subject for a psychopathic hospital, if he had 
returned to his University at Wittenberg would have probably 
forgotten for one night, at least, all about his philosophies of 
life and his lamented father and exhibited himself in that other 
joyous, rollicking mood or character for which he very likely 
was known in the congenial surroundings of his boisterous 
student days. 

The world still awaits the great dramatist who will draw, 
if it be possible, a complete picture of a human personality, 
true to nature and under the confining canons of art. 

It would be hazardous in me to draw examples from amongst 
the fair daughters of Eve, lest I might find it^ expedient to take 
the first train out of this good city after this lecture. But I 
venture the opinion that human nature is all the same in 
whichever sex it is incarnated. From such insight as has been 
vouchsafed me from the revelations within the confessional 
box of the physician's consulting room, I suspect that man 
and woman are pretty much of a muchness. The multiform 
sides of a woman's nature differ from man's only in form and 
their conventional expressions. 

The contrasting sides, however, of the gentler sex are much 
less conspicuous to the world than man's and are more easily 
overlooked. In woman, as every woman knows but few 
men, one or more sides of the character are by the necessity 
of social customs camouflaged. From childhood she is taught 
by the conventions of society, by the social tabu, to restrain 
and repress, often even from herself, many impulses and crav- 
ings^ which are born within her, as well as many thoughts and 
sentiments which she has acquired by experience, by contact 
with the world and therefore by riper knowledge. The re- 
pression under the social codes of these, the natural expressions 
of a part of her personality has belied her nature which has 
been confined for centuries in a cage hung with opaque cur- 
tains, like unto the spiritualist's dark cabinets. But within 
her social cabinet, all sorts of urges of human nature have 
been seething. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 253 

In these days we have the great movement for emancipation 
of the sex. Woman at last, after centuries of repression, is com- 
ing into her own and is being allowed to give free expression 
to her personality. We have already seen remarkable mani- 
festations of her abilities, her aspirations and her desires and 
her capacity to compete with man, and, I fear, expressions of 
her personality, hitherto unsuspected by naive man, in other 
unconventional directions. What may happen with complete 
emancipation of the sex I am not rash enough to prophesy. 

But to go back : in each of the examples, real and imaginary, 
above cited and I might draw in different individuals from 
life, dozens of contrasting and contradictory pictures it would 
appear that in the different relations of life the personality 
presents contradictory traits and conduct, and, in popular 
language, we might say different "selves" alternating with one 
another from moment to moment. But these "selves" are 
plainly only different sides or phases of the same personality. 

In which of these sides, or which of these characters is the 
personality the "Real Self?" Is either side the real self? Or 
is one more than the other? Would the individual himself 
know which he or she is ? Certainly no one is more real than 
the other. 1 

When a person uninterruptedly exhibits one fixed, strongly 
marked phase of his personality during a considerable 
period of time it would seem as if a cleavage, so to 
speak, had occurred, the cleft for the time being separat- 
ing certain groups of traits from the others without any 
bridge between them. And, as a matter of fact, this cleavage 
sometimes literally occurs, as I will presently demonstrate to 
you. 

Again, the contrasting phases of personality may be dis- 
tinguished by differences of mood, each mood being marked 
by its own strong feeling tone or emotion, or by exaltation 
or depression, with corresponding sentiments, habits, thoughts, 
ideals and resulting conduct. 

Strictly and precisely speaking such phases of personality cannot 
be described as "selves." The problem of the self is a narrower 
and special problem involving other and special factors. Yet it is 
true that a differentiated phase of personality .may include a self 
different in its psychological structure from the self of another 
phase; and this structure may be distinguished by a characteristi- 
cally different idea of self, self consciousness, self regarding sentiment, 
etc. As we shall presently see there may 'be two (or more) veritable 
alternating selves constructed out of the components of one per- 
sonality. 



254 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

That this differentiation of the personality into distinct 
phases or groups of traits, or sides of the character, express 
it as you will, is not a mere figure of speech, but an actual 
fact of the structure of the mind may be demonstrated ex- 
perimentally, and is often observed in everyday life when, as 
the result of emotional shocks and the internal forces of the 
mind, the personality is broken up into its component parts 
and one side split off from the other sides. I might cite many 
experiments and observations of my own, but to eliminate 
personal bias allow me to mention an interesting experiment 
by another observer. This experimenter, while engaged in 
some hypnotic experiments on a young man of twenty-two 
who was "essentially normal and responsible, of robust char- 
acter and of decided intellectual ability," found to his surprise 
that this young man fell, entirely independently of suggestion 
and as if by accident, into at least four distinct phases or moods 
each of which may be well characterized as a self. 

The first phase, the ordinary or quiet mood was very similar 
to his normal self when awake. He was of a nature quiet, 
speculative and restrained, well bred and courteous in demeanor 
and of a religious and idealistic temperament. If a suggestion 
was made not consonant with this character it was rejected at 
once and any amount of insistence would be in vain. 

In the second phase, called the "gay mood," into which, on 
its first appearance, he suddenly without warning and to the 
surprise of the experimenter, changed out of the first phase, 
the subject became extremely hilarious and absurd, jested in 
an easy way, displayed a tendency to practical jokes on the 
experimenter, kicked his clothes about the room and was gen- 
erally obstreperous and fantastic, both in speech and behavior. 
Then, of a sudden, without warning or suggestion of any kind, 
he reverted to his former quiet, gentle, restrained self. On 
other occasions in this gay mood, which frequently occurred, 
he showed himself to be a "gay Lothario," for he displayed 
an astounding lack of the ordinary conventions or proprieties, 
professed a contempt for either religion or morality, and a 
disregard for any responsibility in his actions, becoming in 
his^ own language, a child of nature, non-moral though not 
vicious. Any suggestion not consonant with this mood was, 
as in the first phase instantly rejected. 

The third phase was a "malicious" mood. In this he be- 
came a sort of "Jack-the-Ripper." He exhibited a strong wish 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 255 

to inflict pain and frequently asked permission to stab the 
experimenter in order to have the gratification of seeing blood 
flow. Indeed he was detected surreptitiously extracting a pen- 
knife from his pocket with a view to satisfying this inclination. 
He confessed to a wish to vivisect, or, failing that, to strangle. 
(These traits may sound to you preposterous, but permit me 
to say they are all well known and recognized by criminologists 
as frequently the basis of the horrible crimes that from time 
to time shock the public. They are the manifestations of 
sexual perversions and are known as Sadism. Jack-the- 
Ripper, whose frightful abominations killing and mutilating 
his victims shocked the world many years ago, was plainly 
a Sadist). 

The fourth phase into which the young man fell in the same 
way was a "depressed" mood, the very opposite of the gay 
phase. Now he exhibited himself as a melancholic a melan- 
choly Jacques utterly and beyond bounds miserable and ready 
for no reason that was apparent to burst into tears. 

Each of these moods, or so-called selves, carried its own 
different set of emotions, tastes and mental attitudes. As I 
have said, suggestions not consonant with the particular mood 
he was in were rejected. And the whole manner of the man 
in each exhibited an absolute contrast of expression, conduct 
and mode of speech, just as we all do in our different moods 
(not like those of this young man, I hope), according as we 
give expression to the gay traits of pur personality when, as 
the unwitting beneficiaries of a piratical little fleet of British 
steamers and the twelve mile limit, we still celebrate; or the 
vicious traits in a fit of anger, such as were deliberately taught 
to the Tommies, the Poilus and the Doughboys when they 
went over the top; or the sorrowful traits at the loss of a 
dear one; or the sedate, melancholic traits as when we listen 
to a lecture on the Problem of Personality. 

Now an interesting point is that there was no break in the 
continuity of memory for these different moods or selves any 
more than for our own. He remembered them all completely, 
and how he felt and thought and acted. Their appearance 
was beyond his control ; thus again resembling our own changes 
of mood, and they were independent of suggestion. He graphic- 
ally described them as if he were a magic lantern with many 
colored slides passing in sequence before his eyes and through 
which he looked; and as the world would be colored by those 
slides, so he felt and thought about it. 



256 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

I see no reason to hesitate to accept these findings because 
I have independently and often observed the same phenomena, 
though of course the psychological composition of the moods 
or phases was different As instances let me cite only three 
cases which I have intensely studied. 

A young woman whom I had frequently hynotized, but only 
for the purpose of therapeutic suggestion, one day spon- 
taneously changed from a reserved, depressed, respectful self- 
abased, saintly character, dominated by religious ideals and 
longings, to a gay, sprightly, childlike, saucy young girl, car- 
ing not a rap for religion or saints. Then later another phase, 
strongly contrasting with the previous two came into being. 
This phase represented a mature, practical woman of the 
world, a Realist, neither saintly nor childlike, but manifesting 
traits of ambition, self-assertion, and self-reliance, with an 
exceedingly bad temper and resentful of control, determined 
to dominate her environment. 

In the second case, leaving a subject hypnotized in the room, 
when I returned I found that a very serious-minded, depressed, 
self-reproachful lady, about forty years of age, overburdened 
with cares and anxieties and responsibilities, and a nervous in- 
valid, something of a Mrs. Gumidge-sort-of -person, had sud- 
denly changed to a mood in which she felt herself a care-free, 
gay, young girl, full of the joy and happiness of life, enjoying 
the full vigor of physical and mental health. These changes 
also occurred when awake. In this mood she would do, from 
a social point of view, all sorts of reckless but harmless things 
which she strongly reprobated in her customary mood. Then 
after this gay youthful mood passed off, there being no dis- 
continuity of memory, this lady would be much distressed at 
her previous behavior and could not understand why she had 
felt and .thought and acted as she did. 

The third case is that of a young woman with no very striking 
psychological characteristics except those of depression, a 
marked feeling of inferiority and dependence, vascillating in 
purpose, and an absolutely asexual temperament. But in an- 
other phase she became a person of an entirely different char- 
acter, self-assertive, and self-reliant to an obtrusive degree, am- 
bitious, voluptuous, conceited about her supposed musical and 
dramatic talents ; she regarded herself as the reincarnated soul 
of a Spanish courtesan and singer of the XIII Century, a 
sort of "Carmen" of the operatic stage. 
These phases or moods into which these three subjects of 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 257 

mine respectively passed must be regarded not only as differ- 
ent phases of the same personality, so different were they in 
feelings, and attitudes of mind, and sentiments, and conduct, 
but as different selves. 

For the variant phases also included in the integrations distinct 
psychological selves which respectively were specifically differentiated 
from the more habitual selves and characterized by very specifically 
different ideas of self, self-regarding sentiments and self-consciousness. 
Each phase in each case distinctly repudiated any unity of self-con- 
sciousness with the self of the other phase or phases of the personality 
and insisted on being consciously an independent self. Into this detail 
however, I cannot enter here. 

At any rate, psychological analysis of the minds of these three 
persons and a study of their life histories, revealed beyond 
any manner of doubt that the secondary phases, or moods, 
were compounds of traits, i. e., of systems of innate and 
acquired dispositions, which were components of the whole 
personality of each, but which had been repressed and sup- 
pressed by conflict because incompatible with the paths of life 
chosen by each. Now when the lid had been taken off, these 
components came to life and were split off from the rest of 
the personality, which in turn was suppressed, thus forming 
a new phase. (The mode in which this happens I will come 
to later.) 

Now on the basis of such cases and many of them have 
been studied and analyzed it is safe to say that if the young 
man I have just cited who showed the three moodu, the "gay" 
mood of Don Juan, the "malicious" mood of a Jack-the-Ripper, 
the "depressed" mood of a melancholy Jacques, besides his 
own natural goody-goody mood if he had been analyzed in 
a similar way, it would have been found that deep down in his 
nature there were longings to be a gay Lothario, without qualms 
of conscience ; that /there were also certain urges, impulses and 
desires of the sexual instinct to express themselves in sadism, 
i. e., cruelty and the shedding of blood ; and it is also dollars 
to doughnuts that there were good reasons for the depression, 
in tha/t life seemed to hold out little to him in the way of fulfill- 
ing his aspirations, and perhaps self reproaches for fancied 
failure to live up to his ideals. These traits and tendencies 
were all integral parts of his nature his personality, but to 
his credit had been controlled, repressed into the subconscious, 
if you like, and probably concealed even from himself. Bu/t 
now, through the dissociation that occurred from the hypnotic 
procedure, the lid had been taken off, and they sprung to life 
as different selves of his personality. No wonder he seemed 



258 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

to himself, as he said, to be looking through the colored slides 
of a magic lantern and saw the world as it was colored by 
the multiplicity of his different selves. 

These surmises may seem surprising and unbelievable to 
the uninitiated ; but when you begin to dig down into the roots 
of personality of any one, you never know what you will find. 
If Shakespeare had dug down deep into the hidden recesses 
of the minds of Hamlet, and lago, and Jacques, he would have 
been astonished at what he found. 

So nobody knows what will be found in any of us until you 
begin to dig. 

In actual everyday life, in healthy minded people, it is not dif- 
ficult to find examples of the same principle, even in men who 
have achieved positions of eminence in the world. There was 
William Sharp, the novelist, who, when one side of his character 
was uppermost, was the vigorous, practical man of business, 
the bread-and-butter winner, a masculine character as known 
to the world. And then there was the other side, a feminine 
side; a mystic that saw visions, lived within his imagination 
and intense emotions and sentiments, but unknown to the world, 
and wrote his novels under the feminine name of Fione Mac- 
leod, a secret kept until his death. Fione he considered his Real 
Self, so much so that as William Sharp he wrote letters to him- 
self as Fione, and Fione wrote to William Sharp. And yet 
William Sharp was a level headed man. Which was the real 
self? The masculine William or the feminine Fione? Or 
was one more than the other ? 

I could, if it were proper, cite similar examples from persons 
I have known. 

When the contrasting sides of personality are of a moral 
character, contrasting the good and the bad in human nature, 
the resulting effect is more striking and dramatic sometimes 
shocking. 

Robert Louis Stevenson, as every one knows, after pondering 
much on the duality of man's nature and the alternations of 
good and evil, for a long time cast about for a story to em- 
body this central idea. Finally he wrote the wonderful story 
of double personality "The Strange Case of Dr. Jekyll and 
Mr. Hyde." It was meant to be only an allegory to present 
the two sidedness of human nature, good and evil. Real cases 
of double personality were then not known in actual life, so 
Stevenson, in his imaginative creation, constructed better than 
he knew and anticipated the discoveries of psychological re- 
search. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 259 

I have recalled to you Stevenson's imaginary creation because, 
allowing for literary exaggeration, in all fundamentals and 
many details it is so true a picture of what is actually observed 
in cases of double personality that it can be used almost as 
well as an actual case from life. 1 

What sort of structure, then, has personality that such 
strongly contrasting phenomena as I have described can issue 
out of it? 

THEORY OF PERSONALITY 

By what theory can it be explained how it comes about that 
an individual can exhibit so many and such extreme and even 
seemingly paradoxical phases, or alterations of his character, 
and such contrasting, contradictory traits and behavior ? 

Let me clear the ground and premise by saying that the dual 
nature of man, so often moral in the contrasting traits, the fact that 
impressed Stevenson's imagination and upon -which he pondered, 
is easily explained psychologically. It would take me too far 
afield to go adequately into the explanation tonight. I will con- 
tent myself with simply outlining the general principles of purposive 
behavior for which we are chiefly indebted to William McDougall as 
the leading present day protagonist. Our motives are for the 
most part ^ primarily derived frocm our inherited primitive instincts 
or instinctive dispositions with which every child is born or which 
soon develop within him the instincts of pugnacity, and greed, 
and curiosity, and sex, and fear, and sympathy, and self-abase- 
ment, and self-assertion, and the tender parental instinct of love, etc. 
These instinctive dispositions are innate, born in us and inherited. 
Many are biological in that they are common to all the higher ani- 
mals and serve for the preservation and reproduction of the- species. 
If the fox did not possess the instinct of fear, by which he is driven 
to flight from danger, he would stand still in the presence of his 
enemy and all the foxes would soon be gobbled up and the species 
would die out. 

If the lion was not born with the instinct of pugnacity or anger, 
he would not have the driving force to fight and kill his enemies 
and the animals he devours. If he did not have the instinct of 
curiosity he would not be impelled to investigate every strange 
object that might be a dangerous enemy. And so on. 



!It is of psychological interest and instructive to those occupied 
with the problem of the mechanism of dreams that Stevenson 
dreamed this story and for his first draft simply wrote down the 
next morning at white heat the scenes as he dreamed them. Of 
course (he afterwards rewrote and elaborated. The dream, it can 
be assumed, was only the constructive working out in/ allegorical 
form of previous thoughts which very likely had their origin in 
personal mental conflicts. This feat does not stand alone in literature. 
Poe's "Ulalume" and Coleridge's "Kubla Khan" and "Ancient 
Mariner" are said to have been composed as dreams. 



260 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Each instinct, too, has a special aim, the fulfilment of which alone 
satisfies it: to escape from danger in the case of fear; to overcome 
opposition in the case of anger, and so on. 

All these primitive instincts, each one being characterized by an 
emotion of fear, anger, or wonder, or greed, or hunger, or love 
every child inherits. During early infancy ils motives are entirely de- 
rived from them and every act that is not simply a reflex one is de- 
termined by them. It has little more than emotions and feelings, and 
every so called purposive act is instinctive. We may say every child, 
during this period, is little more than a savage, governed only by 
instinctive motives. As he develops he is soon taught to bring these 
under control and to use them only in accordance with the social 
codes and those of ethics and manners. 

At first the infant is a thief; he stretches out -his hand, impelled 
by the instinct of greed, to seize and appropriate whatever he sees, 
your watch or your diamond pin. Then Mamma says "No, no, 
naughty, naughty" and ihe soon learns control. 

He is a would be murderer, for whenever thwarted he falls into 
a fit of anger and would kill his mother or nurse. Again he is taught 
control. 

He is a coward, for he has a panic of instinctive fear at the 
slightest noise, and again he is taught control, and so on. 

Then as the child develops he begins to acquire experiences of the 
world, of the persons and objects about him. He begins to have 
ideas and thoughts of this world, for he is taught the ideals and 
sentiments which the codes of morals, and ethics, adopted by society, 
demand; and by this education the primitive instincts are linked 
to these ideas and objects. Thus the instinct of love becomes at- 
tached to his mother, and to ideas of the good; the instincts of fear 
and aversion- are associated with the bad and evil thoughts, so 
that these are repelled. Thus on the one hand, our ideals, though 
they probably have a driving force of their own, are reinforced by 
the driving force of the instinctive emotions and, on the other hand, 
the instinctive tendencies are brought under control or repressed. 

So, starting in infancy, the whole of our social education, from the 
time of the nursery to adult age, is devoted, on the one hand, to the 
cultivation of the use of instincts in the service of right social coi> 
duct; to instilling ideas in the mind and linking them with these 
instincts and their emotions; to the development in this way of 
those sentiments, ideas and moral principles, and codes of ethics and 
manners and habits which society sets up as standards of good con- 
duct; and, on the other hand, to "the repression and modification 
and regulation and control of those instinctive tendencies, which, 
given free play, induce asocial conduct, like cruelty, and avarice, 
and greed, and dishonesty, and libertinage; but which when modified 
and controlled can be brought to the service of society as, for instance, 
when anger is aroused in the cause of righteousness, and the sex 
instinct in the cause of idealistic love and the perpetuation of the 
race. If this control were not so accomplished, we might all run 
amuck down^ the streets, impelled by our primitive instincts, as 
happens in times of political revolutions, such as in the Russian 
Bolshevik revolution, and in the days of Terror in the great French 
Revolution when the primitive instintets broke loose and men re- 
verted to barbarism. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 261 

It is easy to see, also, I think, how in this way our experiences, 
our ideas and instincts are organized into complexes, as -we tech- 
nically say, or systems, each pertaining to special subjects or objects, 
or to the satisfaction of special aims, or aspirations and longings. 
And these systems when fully developed become what we may call 
sides or character traits of the personality. 

Now it too often happens that in certain] individuals, and always 
to a certain extent in everybody, the social education has been in- 
adequate and failed. Then the barbaric, primitive instincts are not 
completely repressed and controlled and harnessed. On the con- 
trary, under the social influence of the environment they form aso- 
cial sentiments and ideals; or they still retain they independent ac- 
tivity, free from control, and when aroused, seek their aims and ac- 
complish the fulfillment of their desires. They then motivate asocial 
conduct and become an evil side of the personality. 

It may be that in such an individual we 'have an alternation of 
character traits. This happens when, under ordinary conditions and in 
one environment, the good instincts and the moral ideas and prin- 
ciples dominate and that side of the character is uppermost. The 
evil side is quiescent, or camouflaged and out of sight. Then we 
have one self, the moral self. But change the conditions and the 
environment and above all introduce a conflict between repressed 
desires and the moral self ,~ and the evil side of such a person, with 
its primitive instincts and desires, is aroused, the good is repressed 
and sinks out of sight, and we have that upon which Stevenson 
had so long meditated and finally presented in his allegory of Dr. 
Jekyll and \Mr. Hyde "the duafity of the man's nature and the 
alternation of Good and Evil." 

No sound theory of personality can disregard, as is usually 
done, the data derived from the study of cases of multiple 
personality. For the multiple nature of man, or to state it in a 
different form, the different selves, of which our minds and 
personalities are compounds, may be most clearly recognized, 
as I have already intimated in the frankly abnormal cases of this 
kind observed in actual life. They are not uncommon and 
many have been studied. They are of interest, not because of 
the dramatic phenomena they exhibit, but because of the light 
they thus throw on the structure and mechanisms of the human 
mind, on -the composite nature of man, and on the many little 
selves of which the mind is composed. In these cases the mind 
is analyzed much more clearly than any psychologist can do 
it. For by the internal conflicting forces of the mind itself, as 
I will later explain, and not by any artificial procedure like 
hypnotism, or suggested dissociation, the mind is split up. 
A cleavage takes place between its different mental complexes, 
or systems, or what I have called sides of the personality, re- 
sulting in the formation of different corresponding selves, each 
self living an independent life and alternating and sometimes co- 
existing with the other self or selves. But all are parts of the 
whole personality. 



262 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

In illustration simply of these principles the three cases of 
altered personality I have cited may be taken as examples. 
When they were submitted to intensive and prolonged analytic 
study it was revealed beyond a reasonable doubt that, to take 
one of them as an example, the youthful phase of the second 
case was in part a resuscitation of the traits of girlhood which 
had been outgrown in the course of life's mature experiences. 
These traits consisted of youthful sentiments of love, aversion, 
etc., for objects, persons, activities, etc., such as are character- 
istic of irresponsible youth. 

Amongst the sentiments were many which were the direct 
opposite of and antagonistic to those of the mature personality. 
Such, for example, as liking for objects, persons and activities 
for which the latter had intense aversion and even hatred ; while 
again some sentiments, such as those of maternal parenthood, 
were completely switched out and lost; and similarly with 
habits of thought and behavior. 

The traits of this phase, also, included habits of thought and 
behavior which could be identified with those of that early 
period of life to which they genetically dated back and belonged. 
These sentiments and habits were in large measure motivated 
by the instinctive impulses of play and longings for pleasure, 
joy and happiness. These different component instinctive tend- 
encies could be easily differentiated and recognized. All these 
traits were organized into functioning systems. On the other 
hand, many habits of the matured character were dissociated. 
The codes of social conduct and habits which governed the 
social behavior were those which belonged to youth, while the 
social codes which were intensely held and lived up to by the 
mature woman were completely dropped out of the altered 
character. 

Besides this regression to the traits of youth, this altered 
personality, or, more correctly character, exhibited a clearly 
differentiated and larger system, the genesis and growth of 
which could 'be distinctly traced. Beginning with a rebellious 
aversion to a certain condition of life, by successive accretions 
from the subsequent experiences of life, and the incubation 
and maturation of repressed desires, this primitive aversion be- 
came developed into a large complex of systematized habits of 
thought, sentiments, longings and impulses which finally be- 
came constellated with the youthful traits into a functioning 
whole, in rebellion against the previous mature sentiments, 
codes of ethics and behavior and social obligations of the per- 
sonality. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 263 

There was thus a constant succession of conflicts between 
mental systems the old and the new ending in disruption of 
personality and the evolution of a new character possessing 
traits of sentiments, habits of thought and behavior, and in- 
stinctive tendencies antagonistic to those of the original char- 
acter. There was even evolved a new self, with a different 
idea of self and self-regarding sentiment so different that 
this new formed self could not consciously identify itself 
with the previous self. There were two selves with one body. 

The conflicts were not motivated by subconscious wishes of 
a hypothetical "libido," but were between antagonistic systems 
motivated by various emotional instinctive tendencies. 1 

Studies of other cases of multiple phases of personality have 
yielded findings precisely similar in principle. 

Then, again, there are many phenomena in the field of ab- 
normal psychology, other than those of dissociated personality, 
that enable us to detect the organization of the structure of the 
personality in complexes and systems of complexes of innate 
and acquired dispositions. But the limits of time forbid the 
citation of these. 

The alterations of character manifested in multiple phases 
of personality (of which I have cited examples) and con- 
ditioned by the structural organization of the mind in units of 
innate and acquired dispositions, and complexes and systems 
of such units do not, as we have seen, stand apart from the 
normal. Though such alterations are called abnormal, they 
are determined by the normal activities of the units functioning 
normally, but under conditions that do not permit harmonious 
adjustment with one another and adaptation of the individual 
to the environment. The prototypes of such alterations are 
to be found in normal individuals under normal conditions in 
everyday life. Thus the alterations of character manifested 
normally in moods, in fatigue, under stress and strain of emo- 
tion and excitement, the so-called "brain-storms," etc., are pre- 
cisely the same in principle, are conditioned likewise by the 
structure of personality, and are the manifestations of a tem- 
porary variant -the formation of a new phase of a personality 
out of its numerous components. The process is that of 



a complete analysis of tMs case see: 'The Psychogenesis of 
Multiple Personality," Jour, of Abnormal Psychology , Oct. 1919; also 
my "The Unconscious" 2nd Ed. Lectures XVIII-XX. For a similar 
analysis of the Beauchamp case see "iMiss Beauchamp: theory of the 
Psychogenesis of Multiple Personality," Jour, of Abnormal Psychology* 
Vol XV, 191920. 



264 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

dissociation and synthesis, brought about by the internal forces 
of the dispositions of the mind. 

So it becomes evident that fundamental to all these 
problems is the conception of the structure of the mind 
and human personality. In the light of the findings of 
experimental and abnormal psychology we must abandon 
the older notion of the mind being a unity, at least in 
the sense that all active processes are unified in conscious- 
ness and that those processes of which we are conscious include 
all mental processes. Rather we must regard the mind as a 
complex of units, or, rather, of unitary systems of experiences 
and instinctive dispositions. Such systems become organized by 
the experiences of life and derive their most intensive driving 
force from the urge of the emotional dispositions organized 
within them. Sentiments of love and fear and aversion and 
curiosity and many others, derived from the linking of these 
dispositions and experience, are contained in the structural sys- 
tems and each has its own urge to find expression. The complex 
integration of all these systems into one composite whole is the 
mind's structure. 1 One might say that the mind is a composite 
of a lot of little minds, each concerned, however with its own 
business and its own interest and aim. Normally each little mind 
or unitary system enters the field of consciousness in orderly 
fashion, when called upon, according to the circumstances of 
the moment and the environment: and behaves in a way that 
adapts the individual to his environment; though with due re- 
gard for the interests and aims of the other little minds with 
which, after the fashion of compound reflexes, it is structurally 
integrated. But sometimes, under stress and strain, there is 
conflict between the unitary systems, one or more of these 
little minds are repressed by an autocratic Kaiserlich system 
so that it cannot enter consciousness, and then, impelled by 
its own uncontrollable urge, it may turn like the proverbial 
worm; or, to change the simile, take the bit in its teeth, 
and, taking on independent or so-called automatic activity, 
kick up a devil of a row in its subconscious prison cell, and 
do all sorts of horrid things. Then we have what we call 
symptoms due to conflict. Or, again, we may induce by tech- 
nical methods of experimentation, some of these units to func- 
tion subconsciously and independently. Ordinarily and nor- 
mally, however, the units of the mind behave harmoniously 

iFor a more extensive discussion of this theory see: "Tiie Struo 
fture and Dynamic Elements of Human Personality," Jour, of Ab- 
normal Psychology > t Vol. XV, 1919-20; also, .my "Tie Unconscious'* 
2nd Ed. Lecture XVII. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 265 

as dynamic elements of one large system. Some emerge into 
consciousness, some remain submerged in the subconscious 
storehouse of the mind to be called upon when wanted as sys- 
tematized memories ; while many, still remaining subconscious, 
become stimulated into active processes and act upon and mod- 
ify the processes of conscious thought and behavior. But 
all, the conscious and the subconscious, are one mind. Let us 
never forget that. 

THE DISRUPTING FORCE OF CONFLICTS 

What is it, then, you may again ask me, that makes the dif- 
ference between these cases that you call multiple personality 
and those which you describe as manifesting multiform, alter- 
nating and conflicting traits? 

Why is it that, if we all have multiform natures, or more cor- 
rectly speaking, two or more sides to our nature and if we are 
made up of a lot of little minds, why don't we all split up 
into separate personalities, each with its own self, bobbing in 
and bobbing out, alternating with one another like Dr. Jekyll 
and Mr. Hyde, if we have an evil side; or, if not, as I hope, 
only incompatible desires, into different contrasted selves 
serious minded or pleasure loving; worldly or saintly; gay 
or melancholic; practical or idealistic, like some of the cases 
I have told you about? 

The answer involves a principle of the mind that has oc- 
cupied all poets, dramatists, novelists and students of human 
nature since literature began, and of recent years has been 
accepted and made use of by all psychologists who have stud- 
ied the troubles of the human mind. 

It is the principle of mental conflicts the conflicts of antag- 
onistic and irreconcilable desires and urges and impulses which 
have distracted and always will distract and torment poor 
human beings, and which have been the basis of some of the 
greatest tragedies of literature and actual life. 

A person, let us say, is torn by two conflicting desires which 
means impulses, one belonging to one side of his nature and 
one to the other; one to be good and one to be bad one, to 
take a recent case of mine called "Mary Jane," to follow 
the puritanical path of dull, monotonous, prosaic, joyless vir- 
tue and morality, and one to kick over the traces and give 
rein to the joyful impulses of pleasure, of the primitive in- 
stinctive urges of a gay but forbidden life. 

Or, let us say, without introducing the moral question of 
good or evil, there is by the circumstances of life, as in the 



266 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

case of a Mrs. O. I have studied, a condemnation of the in- 
dividual to a dull, monotonous, banal life of duty and joyless 
work, and at the same time longings for a higher life, to give 
expression to the aspiration of the personality in art, or lit- 
erature, or on the stage. 

Or, if I may take a third example, a young life devoted, 
like that of Miss Beauchamp, to religious and moral perfection, 
seeking to develop the personality, literally and meticulously 
by the precepts of the highest moral and religious ideals of the 
teachings of Christ, renouncing, on the one hand, the natural, 
harmless joys and pleasures and excitements of youth, and, 
on the other, the natural realistic interests and ambitions of 
the grown up man or woman, while at the same time there 
is incomplete adjustment to all those renunciations. In spite 
of the religious and moral aspirations, there still persist un- 
acknowledged both the youthful desires and impulses, and the 
worldly ambitions and impulses making up two other sides of 
the personality. Obviously these various desires and impulses 
are in conflict and irreconcilable. 

These examples I have drawn from actual instances that 
I have known and studied. In each instance a rebellion has 
been started. Beginning with a rebellious group of wishes 
and ideas, this rebellion grows, like a rebellion in the social 
or political organization, drawing within itself more and more 
dissatisfied elements of thought and new wishes and new ideas 
of self, and fancies of a new life that might be, which would 
fulfil the aspirations of a new self. Thus a side to the 
personality is formed and the beginnings of another personality, 
another self come into existence. 

In each of these cases we have a conflict of irreconcilable 
desires. Both or all cannot be satisfied. The individual cannot 
adjust himself to the life he has chosen, or which has been 
forced by circumstances upon him, because of the unsatisfied 
desires; desires which are unacceptable because of moral 
or other scruples. 

The inevitable results, if the individual is of an unstable, 
over-conscientious, neurotic disposition. The dynamic force 
of the conflict, that is of the unacceptable desires and impulses 
that cannot be satisfied, represses or dissociates the other side 
and ruptures completely, or almost completely, the mind. There 
is a complete cleavage between the sides of the character, be- 
tween the rebellious side, or the rebellious self, and that side, 
or self, which is rebelled against. If the rebel wins the king 
is dethroned, the government is put out of business ; or, as we 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 267 

say in psychological language, the original self is dissociated 
and repressed, for the time being annihilated. Then the new 
rebellious self sits on the throne with a new government in 
power. So complete is the rupture and so powerful the re- 
pression that even memory may be repressed and lost for 
all the experiences of life antedating the rupture; that is to 
say, the new rebellious self can recall nothing of his previous 
self, or vice versa, or both. 

The new one differs of course from the old one. His conduct 
corresponds with the thoughts and feelings and sentiments and 
desires which constituted the rebellion and he proceeds to sat- 
isfy them; and so we say we have a second personality. This 
means that the traits the ideals, the sentiments, the impulses, 
etc., of the other side of his personality are dissociated or 
repressed. 

This goes on for a time it may be a few hours or days or 
months then something happens; something stimulates, that 
is, awakens the desires and sentiments and feelings of the old 
original side of the personality, the original self. There is 
again a conflict and if the old self wins, the new one is re- 
pressed in turn, and the old one appears and sits on the 
throne again. In political parlance the reactionaries have thrown 
the revolutionaries out of the window. And so it goes, one 
self alternating with another self and we have what we call 
a double personality. 

The answer, then, to the question you put to me, "Why do 
we not all split up into multiple personalities?" is plain: be- 
cause we have no mental conflicts between our opposing de- 
sires and impulses which we cannot satisfactorily adjust or 
control. Of course we all have conflicts, but the desires and 
impulses and tendencies which are unacceptable to the other 
side of our natures are not so intense that we cannot adjust 
them to our satisfaction, or control them; they are not so in- 
tense as to become a seething rebellion against the situations 
and conditions of life ; or against our accepted ideals and senti- 
ments ; or against those codes of ethics and morals which have 
been instilled in us in childhood which is to say our con- 
sciences. 

Or, it may be, that we h&ve no consciences that may be 
shocked by such desires and impulses. The codes of ethics 
and morals have failed to be instilled so deeply as to be "cate- 
gorical imperative" principles. Hence none of these de- 
sires are unacceptable. In fact they are accepted and 
there is a joy in satisfying them. The conscience is not 



268 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

shocked any more than was Dr. JekylTs, who intentionally 
changed himself by a drug. There is no conflict and the per- 
sonality is not disrupted. Indeed we have a way, even when, 
deep down in our hearts we know they mean forbidden fruit, 
of justifying them to ourselves. By a process of sophistical 
reasoning we justify self-indulgence, whether it be of play, 
or activities and modes of life which are incompatible with 
duties and responsibilities assumed. 

If, then, I have spoken truly, I think we can say that, al- 
though we have only one mind, out of its various elements 
there can be formed more than one character, and that we are 
entitled to call those different phases of the personality that 
alternate with one another different selves, whether they are 
actual independent, dissociated personalities, or only extreme 
and changing moods, or strongly contrasting groups of traits. 
The name that we give is, after all, a -verbal question. The 
practical facts are the important matter. So to illustrate once 
more : 

If there had been an irreconcilable conflict, and if it had 
been strong enough and could not be otherwise compromised, 
any of the characters I have described at the beginning might 
have been dissociated into two or more independent person- 
alities. The first, the music-loving business-man might have 
split into a money-making steel manufacturer robbed of his 
musical talent and into an idealistic unpractical dreaming mu- 
sician. The second into a hard, selfish miser and into an ideal- 
istic philanthropist. The third into a criminal boss politician 
and into a lovable moralist, and so on. But there were no 
conflicts, no consciences to be shocked, etc. ; and so they only 
manifested moods, or alternating traits. 

May we not, therefore, say, in answer to our question, we 
have as many selves as we have moods, or contrasting traits, 
or sides to our personalities? 

RECAPITULATION 

I may summarize the theory I am presenting in the follow- 
ing brief recapitulation. 

The personality is not a unity in the sense of being a func- 
tioning whole. It comprises many different components of 
which various ones and a varying number from time to time 
engage in activity as mental and physiological processes and 
manifest themselves as traits of character. These are the 
variables. Personality, accordingly, is not a stable thing but 
exhibits many alterations under changing conditions. 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 269 

Of the variables, all are not assembled under all conditions 
and at all times into a functioning whole. The individual re- 
acts at one moment with one set of traits and at another with 
another, perhaps of an opposite character. Indeed he may 
possess, as I have already pointed out at the beginning, traits 
that are antagonistic to one another, such as sentiments of 
hatred and love, or interest and disinterest, for the same ob- 
ject; or he may manifest both charitableness and uncharitable- 
ness ; intelligence and stupidity ; etc. Obviously such opposing 
traits cannot -be manifested at one and the same moment. But 
let the conditions of the organism be altered, such as occurs 
in fatigue, or illness, or intoxication, or states of dissociation, 
or "moods ;" or let the conditions of the environment be altered 
and one or the other of these opposing traits comes into func- 
tional activity. The dispositions underlying its opposite then 
may be said to be dissociated from the functioning systems of 
the personality, or be suppressed, or switched off. In other 
words, that which is the functioning part of the personality 
undergoes alterations from time to time, one set of traits 
being predominant at one time and another at another. There 
occurs a dissociation or switching out of some dispositions 
and re-synthesis or switching in of others. 

The different variables, manifested as "traits," are systems 
of dispositions, innate and acquired, integrated into lesser and 
larger functioning systems. 

The innate dispositions are those which condition and de- 
termine the reflexes, the native tendencies and appetites and 
the instincts, in which last I include the emotions. These are 
inherited psycho-physiological arrangements. 

I have purposely avoided getting entangled in the battle of 
the instincts. 

But everyone agrees that the dispositions which condition and 
upon which the native tendencies and emotions depend and which 
determine some sort of behavior, whatever that may be, are in- 
herited. And everyone agrees that these dispositions become in- 
tegrated by experience with the acquired dispositions deposited by 
the experiences of life. And nearly everyone will agree with Mc- 
Dougall and Shand that the conative force of these dispositions 
when excited to activity, provides impulses which give -driving force 
to the acquired dispositions with which they become integrated. 
And if this be so, it will be agreed that these impulses tend to carry, 
or to co-operate in carrying, the activated acquired dispositions, i e., 
our ideas, sentiments, wishes, etc., to fruition, whether or not (Wood- 
worth) they are the sole driving force, or purposive in character. 

You may call such inherited psycho-physiological arrange- 
ments "instincts" or instinctive tendencies, or "patterns" 



270 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

or what you please; that is a matter of concepts and 
terms. What matters is that there are inherited psycho- 
physiological arrangements which behave as units, determine 
impulsive behavior of some sort, become integrated with the 
deposited acquired experiences of life and organized with 
them, co-operate, at least, through their impulsive force in 
determining behavior. And if this be so, these^innate units are 
components of the structure of personality primary units they 
may be called. 

As to these acquired dispositions, such phenomena of dis- 
sociated personality as I have cursorily cited and the intrinsic 
forces of the mind dissect its structure far more accurately 
than can the psychologist such phenomena reveal that the 
enduring experiences of life are organized and conserved in 
complex systems in which are integrated the innate ^disposi- 
tions; acquired systems they are, which on the psychical side 
are experienced and re-experienced as sentiments and cogni- 
tions and beliefs and perceptions of objects and situations and 
memories and images, with their meanings; and as tendencies 
and desires, etc. (How they are acquired is a genetic 
question). 

The physiological basis of these are neural dispositions, or 
neurograms, which when activated are consciously experienced 
as systems of mental processes. Each system, in a way, 
functions as a psychic whole. 

These acquired systems may be termed secondary units and 
and all and each are necessarily, so long as they endure, com- 
ponents of the structure of the personality. These units, again, 
become further integrated with one another and more or less 
firmly knit into larger systems and constellations of systems to 
form what is popularly called the personality. In the course 
of life, from the cradle to the grave, under the genetic influence 
of so-called "culture/* a vast number of lesser and larger 
systems are organized and conserved. All of them, however, 
do not persist as active traits, or components of traits. Many 
fall into "innocuous desuetude" and lie fallow, having become 
unsuitable for the adjustment and adaptation of the organism to 
the ^ changed environment and situations of life. Others may 
be inhibited or be repressed by conflict with antagonistic sys- 
tems and in that case may take on further growth by sub- 
conscious incubation and maturation. In any case, however, 
so long as they are conserved, they are potentially capable of 
activity and, in fact, often do become activated under alteration 
of the conditions within and without the organism. This 



HOW MANY SELVES HAVE WE? 271 

switching out and switching in, suppression and repression 
and resuscitation of enduring systems result in the ephemeral 
normal alterations of character of everyday life; but, when 
the product of irreconcilable mental conflict of sufficient inten- 
sity they result in those abnormal alterations manifested as 
multiple phases of personality. 

Such, in brief, but without attempt at demonstration, is the 
theory of personality which I would offer for your considera- 
tion as best explaining all the phenomena manifested in both 
normal and abnormal conditions. 

We have little more than passed the threshold of the en- 
trance into that wonderful structure, the human mind. Great 
discoveries await us. That is the promise which the future 
holds out. But I believe that promise is based on the con- 
dition that we shall make use of those methods upon which 
science has depended for its discoveries in every field of 
knowledge experimentation and provisional hypotheses con- 
firmed by exact methodical observations. 




WILLIAM McDouGALL 



CHAPTER XII 

MEN OR ROBOTS?* 



By WILLIAM McDouGALL 



In the two lectures which I have the honor to give on the 
Powell foundation I am responding to an invitation to defend 
Purposive Psychology, or, in other words, to defend the pro- 
position that man's acting and thinking are purposive. I seem 
to be in a position analogous to that of an anatomist called 
upon to defend the proposition that man is a biped, or that of 
a physiologist required to prove that man breathes air. That 
is to say I am expected to support by argument a fact familiar 
to all men through first-hand experience, a fact so familiar 
and well established that it has become embodied in the very 
structure of all languages and is recognized and acted upon 
by all men in all the practical conduct of daily life. 

This is a strange and embarrassing position for any man of 
science. To demonstrate the obvious, to bring forward elabo- 
rate arguments in support of well recognized facts, must al- 
ways seem an ungrateful and somewhat absured procedure. 
Yet just such procedure is " a duty thrust upon me by the 
strange course of development of psychology, the science of 
human nature. 

It is necessary to clarify the situation ,and to define the 
task before me by referring briefly to this course of develop- 
ment. At a time which now seems remote, but which, re- 
garded in historical perspective, is comparatively recent, it 
was the prevailing tendency to class together all expressions 
of striving towards a goal, all purposive activities, and to at- 
tribute them to a single faculty, 'the Will.' This faculty was 
supposed to cooperate upon occasion with various other facul- 
ties, such as Memory and Reason. And it appeared that these 
other faculties frequently seemed to work independently of 
the Will. That fact seemed to justify the setting apart of the 
Will as a distinct faculty. Then came the revolt against faculty 



*Powett Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University 
December 10, 1925. 



274 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

psychology ; and in the main, under the influence of Locke and 
Hume, the ps3 7 chology of Ideas prevailed. The followers of 
this 'new way of ideas' claimed that all the processes of the 
mind, and all human behavior, might be adequately described 
and explained in terms of Ideas, or impressions and Ideas. 
It was claimed that we need to make only three fundamental 
assumptions about the nature of mind, or the mental nature of 
man: first, that he is capable of receiving impressions, i.e., 
sense-impressions; secondly, that he naturally retains these 
impressions in the form of Ideas; thirdly, that these Ideas, 
retained in the storehouse of the mind, are linked together 
according to certain simple rules, the so-called 'laws of asso- 
ciation/ and are apt to reappear in consciousness, one after an- 
other, in a manner determined wholly by these associative links 
and by intercurrent new sense-impressions. 

Throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, many 
psychologists and philosophers were intoxicated by the seem- 
ing success of these principles. It seemed to them that the 
new principles, so charmingly simple, enabled them to dispense 
entirely with the faculties, and especially with the faculty of 
the Will. All instances of purposive activity, they said, could 
be adequately described and accounted for by recognizing a 
peculiar kind of Idea, called an Idea of an end or goal. Ideas 
of this kind, however, were not essentially different from 
other Ideas. They were supposed to work or function in just 
the same way as Ideas of other kinds ; that is to say, the Ideas 
of goals were implanted by sense-impressions and, like all 
other Ideas, faithfully obeyed the Laws of Association and 
associative reproduction. 

Confidence in the all-sufficiency of psychology of this kind 
was greatly increased by the discovery that, as knowledge of 
the structure and functions of the nervous system increased, 
all descriptions in terms of Ideas could be plausibly translated 
into terms of brain-processes; the Ideas were assumed to be 
locked each in its separate brain-cell or group of cells; and 
the links of association were conceived as material links 
between such brain-cells. Then at last it seemed that a real 
explanation of mental life became possible, an explanation in 
terms of the physics and chemistry of the brain. Recent 
studies of the "conditioned responses" have given a new con- 
fidence to those who regard the principle of association as 
capable of explaining every manifestation of skill and knowl- 



MEN OR ROBOTS 275 

edge. For these observations seem to them to give more pre- 
cision and a more definitely mechanistic meaning to the princi- 
ple of association. 

This is the line of thinking which, beginning with Hartley, 
has culminated in the mechanistic behaviorism of Dr. Watson 
and his followers. Those who accept it say that we do not 
need to trouble about Ideas; but only need concern ourselves 
with physical impressions and physical responses. For they 
imagine that they can adequately imagine all the brain-pro- 
cesses that intervene between sense-stimulus and motor res- 
ponse, without seeking any aid from introspection. It is the 
alarming popularity in this country of this new way without 
Ideas that lays upon those of us who cannot accept it the em- 
barrassing obligation to appear as champions of the simple 
obvious and commonplace truth that man is a purposive being, 
that, from the cradle to the grave, his life is one long round 
of purposive strivings, of efforts to attain, to make read, those 
things which he imaginatively conceives to be good or desir- 
able. The spread of that other way of thinking among psy- 
chologists has gone so far that those few of us who do not ac- 
cept it are regarded as cranky persons wedded to mediaeval 
metaphysics, queer survivors from the dark ages who, by 
reason of some twist in the brain, are incapable of joining in 
the triumphant march of modern science. 

The author of a recent amusing play has imagined the con- 
struction of machines in the shape of human beings, machines 
so ingeniously put together that they can be set to perform 
much of the routine labor now performed by men. And he 
has called such machines Robots. He has supposed a Robot 
to be so delicately responsive to stimuli, that you could dictate 
a letter to it, and the Robot would proceed to write it out on 
the typewriter. Now there is, in principle, nothing absurd or 
impossible in this supposition. The mechanists in psychology 
ask us to assume that men are such Robots, carried to a higher 
degree of responsiveness than that depicted by the author of 
the play. And the view that men are merely such improved 
Robots is now being dogmatically taught to thousands of 
young students in the psychological departments of the uni- 
versities of this country. The question before us is then Is 
the assumption that men are Robots a good or useful one? 
Is it at the present time a profitable working hypothesis? 

My own view is that it is not a good working hypothesis 



276 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

in the present state of knowledge. I propose to try to show 
you good grounds for that view. Let me first say that I have 
no desire to defend the psychology of Ideas. In my estima- 
tion the word 'idea' is one that has long outlived its usefulness 
in science, however convenient it may be for popular usage. 
No doubt, the word served a useful purpose in the hands of 
Locke and Hume (and its German equivalent 'Vorstellung' 
played a similar part in the hands of Herbart and others) in 
enabling them to lead psychology away from the errors of the 
older faculty psychology. But what an Idea may be no one 
has been able to say : no one has been able to use the word in 
a way that is not essentially misleading. For the word 'idea' 
implies a thing or entity; and all the theory of association of 
Ideas, as well as the psychology of Herbart, was permeated 
and distorted by the influence of this implication, that our 
mental life, that all thinking, consists in the successive appear- 
ance of these entities, Ideas, before the footlights called 'con- 
sciousness/ and in their disappearance into a mysterious un- 
known region called the unconscious. 

Very early in my career as a psychologist, I planned to 
write a psychology without Ideas, a feat now accomplished in 
my 'Outline of Psychology/* 

For every form of the idea-psychology, not only suffers 
from the misleading implication that Ideas are entities that 
somehow exist in their own right, but also suffers from another 
grave defect, namely, it leaves us without any intelligible 
theory of action, it cannot relate the Ideas with the bodily 
activities in which our mental life expresses itself. It inevit- 
ably leaves the Ideas up in the air ; it cannot find any way of 
planting their feet among the solid facts of cerebral currents 
and muscular contractions. It is true that the theory of ideo- 
motor action was an attempt to remedy this defect; but, as is 



*I believe and have long believed that the next important ad- 
vance of logic will consist in the banishment of Ideas and their 
equivalent, Concepts, from that discipline. 

In this respect, as in several others, I am happy to find myself 
in agreement with leaders of the Gestalt school. Prof. Wertheimer 
has recently written: "Wenn man sich recht uberlegt, was im leben- 
digen Denken ein Begriff ist, was das wirkliche Kapieren eines 
Schhisses ist, wenn man sich uberlegt, was das Entscheidende bei 
eimem mathematischen Beweisgang ist, bei dem Ineinderhangen, 
dann sieht man, dass mit den Kategorien der traditionellen Logik 
hier nichts gemacht ist." (Ueber Gestalttheorie, Symposion, 1925.) 



MEN OR ROBOTS 277 

now pretty generally recognized, that theory failed hopelessly, 
if only for the reason that it flew in the face of obvious facts. 
It is of interest to note that Dr. Watson and I have been 
led by our perception of the same fact, the unsatisfactoriness 
of the idea-psychology, to two very different positions. Both 
of us became acutely conscious of the fact that the idea-psy- 
chology was unable to render any acceptable interpretation or 
explanation of human conduct, that it propounded no intelli- 
gible theory of action. Both of us were impressed by the fact 
that the psychology of the nineteenth century neglected un- 
duly the facts of behavior, and that, in calling itself the science 
of consciousness, it was turning its back upon the more im- 
portant problems of human nature, the problems of conduct. 
As long ago as 1905 I began my attempt to remedy that state 
of affairs by proposing to define psychology as the positive 
science of conduct, using the word 'positive* to distinguish it 
from ethics, the normative science of conduct. I hoped in 
this way to draw more attention to the neglected problems of 
behavior. And in 1908 I went further with this program by 
publishing my Social Psychology. In that book the problems 
of conduct were given first place; the purposive or goal-seek- 
ing nature of all human activity was emphasized; and the 
hormic theory of action was developed in some detail. Wat- 
son took up the same cue some years later, and, being pri- 
marily interested in animal psychology, in which field there is 
no possibility of any direct observation of conscious activity,, 
and in which the student is inevitably confined to the observa- 
tion of bodily behavior, he proposed to effect the needed re- 
form, not by redressing the balance in psychology between the 
introspective and the objective methods of study, but by the 
simple expedient of upsetting the balance completely. He 
proposed to throw overboard as useless the introspective meth- 
ods of study and all that we had learnt in that way ; and, hav- 
ing absorbed the dogma that all events are mechanically ex- 
plicable and that all human and animal action is merely me- 
chanical reflex action more or less compounded, a dogma which 
owing largely to the influence of Herbert Spencer was then 
fashionable, he proposed to ignore completely all those features 
of behavior which imply its purposive nature and which can 
only be stated or described in terms which imply the direction 
of action towards ends, the seeking of goals, the striving to 
bring about a change. Thus, by repudiating one half of the 
methods of psychology and resolutely shutting his eyes to 



278 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

three quarters of its problems, he laid down the program of 
Behaviorism and rallied to its standard all those who have a 
natural distaste for difficult problems and a preference for 
short, easy, and fictitious solutions. 

Let us notice that the psychologists of this group, who call 
themselves 'Behaviorists', are not propounding any new doc- 
trine of a positive kind. The view that all events are me- 
chanically explicable is as old as Democritus; the view that 
animals are purely machines is at least as old as Descartes; 
the view that all human conduct is explicable on the theory of 
the compounding of reflexes was developed in great detail, 
and with an assurance as complete as Dr. Watson's, by Her- 
bert Spencer more than sixty years ago. The only novel fea- 
ture is the proposal to ignore completely a very large range of 
facts of the utmost interest and importance, facts of two 
orders : first, the fact that each of us consciously perceives the 
world about him, consciously desires to modify it in ways 
which he consciously conceives, consciously strives and plans 
to effect such changes; secondly, the fact that almost all hu- 
man and animal behavior, considered strictly objectively, seems, 
with various degrees of clearness, to express such perception, 
such desiring, such conscious planning and striving, such con- 
scious concern with the future. All that is positive in the 
methods and principles of Behaviorism has been actively prac- 
tised and taught by many biologists for many years, by such 
men as Albrecht Bethe, Jacques Loeb, Bechterew, Pavlov, 
Uexkiill, aiid others. All that is novel in the behaviorist pro- 
gram is the resolute pretense that the facts of human con- 
sciousness are of no interest to the student of human nature, 
present no problems worthy of consideration and may profit- 
ably be ignored. 

Let us notice next that the school of avowed behaviorists has 
very quickly split into two rival parties. The one party, that 
led by Dr. Watson, which we may conveniently call the party 
of strict behaviorists, or the S.B.. party, adheres to the origi- 
nal program; it is characterized by its refusal to recognize both 
the facts of conscious activity and the fact that behavior can 
not be adequately described, and still less intelligibly inter- 
preted, without using language which recognizes the goal- 
seeking nature of all behavior. 

The other and smaller group is best represented by Prof. 
E. C. Tolman. The behaviorists of this group refuse to recog- 
nize, or to be interested in, only one of the two great classes 



MEN OR ROBOTS 279 

of facts ignored by the S. B. party, namely, the facts of con- 
scious activity. They recognize fully the facts of the second 
order ignored by the S. B. group, the objectively observable 
fact that behavior is obviously a goal-seeking process. They 
mark their separation from what I have called strict behavor- 
ism by contemptuous reference to it as behaviorism of the 
Watsonian variety, and by devising for it the elegant and ex- 
pressive designation "muscle-twitchism." 1 This group of 
behaviorists may be conveniently distinguished as teaching 
purposive behaviorism or P.B. 

The situation is further complicated by a third group of 
psychologists who, while showing much sympathy with the S.B. 
party, belong neither to it nor to the P.B. party. They are 
well represented by Prof. F. A. Allport 2 They are separated 
from the S. B. by the fact that they neither deny nor totally 
ignore the facts of conscious activity. They give the impres- 
sion that they would much like to do this, but have not the 
courage of their desires. They see that to deny the whole realm 
of introspectively observable facts is too flagrantly absurd and 
that to ignore them may be a little dangerous. But they are 
allied with the S.B. party by their neglect to make use of the 
introspectively observable facts and by their acceptance of 
its "muscle-twitchism." For them every instance of human 
conduct or animal behavior is merely a mechanical reflex re- 
sponse to a sensory stimulus; and they resolutely shut their 
eyes to all the objective (as well as the subjective) evidences 
that behavior is a goal-seeking process. Thus, in spite of their 
recognition of the fact that human beings are consciously 
active, the psychologists of this group are in practice and 
procedure very near to the strict behaviorists; they may well 
be called the exponents of 'Near Behaviorism' or N.B. 

Purposive psychology may best be vindicated by showing 
the inadequacies of these three types of behaviorism. Strict 
Behaviorism, Near Behaviorism and Purposive Behaviorism. 3 

*Prof. Tolman speaks of '^behaviorism of the proper sort" as be- 
ing "not a mere Muscle* Twitchism of the Watsonian variety." "Be- 
haviorism and Purpose." Journal of Philosophy, Vol. XXII, 1925. 

In his 'Social Psychology/ 

1 say nothing about the type of psychology which confines it- 
self to the study of the introspectively observable facts, and ignores 
the problems of behavior. Psychology of this type,however, interest- 
ing and important may be its contributions to our knowledge of 
human nature, can never be more than one part or specialized 



280 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Strict Beliaviorism 

Strict Behaviorism denies to itself all acquaintances with a vast 
range of most interesting facts and problems. It abolishes, 
by the simple process of refusing to look at them, all the old 
and fascinating problems of the relations between the mental 
and the physical, including all the vast field of psycho-physics, 
all that part of psychology which is concerned more particu- 
larly to study and to formulate exactly the relations between 
sensory stimuli and sensory experience. For the S.B. all the 
monumental work in this line of Thomas Young, Johannes 
Miiller, Weber, Helmholtz, Hering, and a multitude of others 
is a closed book. S.B. equally debars itself from taking^any 
notice of dreams, crystal visions, hallucinations, delusions, 
pains and subjective symptoms of every kind, all the multitu- 
dinous departures from normal modes of experience which 
are only revealed by introspective reports ; and thus shuts itself 
off from all possibility of learning anything from the psycho- 
analytic movement, which, whatever its errors, has proved to 
be a movement of the first importance. 

The hardy S.B. replies "What of that? If I refuse to be 
interested in all these topics, you can't force me to be inter- 
ested/' And he dismisses all the schools of psycho-analysis 
with a few contemptuous words. He contends that only the 
bodily movements which constitute outward behavior are of any 
practical importance ; and he believes that two very simple con- 
ceptions suffice for the explanation of every instance of beha- 
vior, namely the reflex and the conditioned reflex. He pretends 
that, armed with these alone, he can penetrate every secret of 
the human heart and mind. Why then should he countenance 
any laborious study of the disordered feeling and thinking of 
the neurotic and the madman; why seek to elicit, why ponder 

branch of the science of human nature, one that restricts itself to 
very special * methods and problems. Though some of its exponents 
are inclined to claim for it that it is the whole of psychology, they 
represent a viewpoint which is fast passing away. I will make only 
one comment in the form of a .citation from a recent article of 
Dr. Max Wertheimer; "es gibt psychologische Theorien und recht 
viele psychologische Lehrbucher sogar, die, trotzdem sie dauerend 
nttr von Bewusstseins-elemente sprechen, materialistischer, durrer 
sinnloser, geistloser sind als ein lebendiger Baum, der vom 
Bewusstsein auch vielleicht nichts in sich hat. Nicht darauf kann 
es ankommen, woraus materialiter die Stuckchen des Geschehens 
bestehen, sondern auf den Sinn des Ganzen, die Art des Ganzen, 
muss es ankommen/' Tiber Gestalttheorie, Symposion, 1925. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 281 

over, interminable reports of his phantasies, his dreams, his 
internal struggles, his torments, his terrors, his impulsions, de- 
lusions and obsessions? All such experiences, so long as the 
patient does not allow them to gain expression in bodily action, 
are barred by the S.B. Wait till the internal tumult expresses 
itself in a homicidal act; then the behaviorist will step in and 
explain the whole affair with the magic words "badly con- 
ditioned reflex." 

The S.B. and the N.B. are misled by their dogma into such 
monstrous error, not only in their dealings with human beings 
in the practical exigencies of social life, but also in their ex- 
perimental procedures. Thus Dr. Watson, obsessed by his 
doctrine, experiments with new-born infants, and, failing to 
find in them any clearly marked tendencies and capacities 
beyond a few very simple ones which can plausibly be de- 
scribed as reflexes, triumphantly jumps to the conclusion that, 
as regards all innate mental endowment, all men of all races 
are exactly alike. He utters the final word upon the question 
of racial differences (one of the most difficult and important 
questions confronting us and one which can only be settled 
by the prolonged research of many workers, research which is 
only just begun) by saying : "I defy anyone to take these in- 
fants at birth, study their behavior, and mark off differences 
in behavior that will characterize white from black and white 
or black from yellow." 1 In the light of his profound observa- 
tions on new-born infants he denies not only the existence of 
all the instincts of the human species, but also all hereditary 
mental traits, capacities, talents or characteristics of every 
kind, other than the few reflexes he finds in those new-born 
infants. "Our conclusion then, is that we have no real evidence 
of the inheritance of traits Let us then, forever lay the ghost 
of inheritance of aptitudes, of 'mental* characteristics, of spec- 
ial abilities." 2 

Animal behavior is the chosen ground of the behaviorist; 
it was through studies in that field that he was misled into his 
perverse unfortunate endeavor. There, if anywhere, (or in 

Pedagogical Seminary Vol. XXXII, p. 296. 

s Dr. Watson's defiance is magnificent, as magnificent as the similar 
defiance of the late Mr. Bryan in face of the evidence for human 
evolution. It is disconcerting and portentous that a man whose 
reasoning processes are habitually of the kind illustrated above 
should be widely acclaimed in this country as a leader in a great 
field of science. The fact gives furiously to think. 



282 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

relation to the new-born babe, his other favorite object) his 
descriptions and interpretations should appear plausible and 
adequate. But, even there, he cannot describe, much less in- 
terpret, the facts in any useful and profitable manner without 
departing from his principles. 1 His simplest experiments postu- 
late the animal's purposive or goal-seeking tendencies. He 
puts a hungry animal in a cage or a maze and places food 
just beyond his reach; or puts the food in a box, knowing or 
assuming that the animal will try, will strive, to get at it. And 
all the successive actions of the animal are intelligible only 
in terms of this assumption. It is true that it is possible to 
describe the successive movements of the animal in purely 
objective terms, just as it is possible to make a Kinemato- 
graphic record of them. But such a description, no matter 
how minute and exact, leaves the actions quite unintelligible 
so long as all references to the goal and the striving towards 
it are really excluded. The behaviorist pretends that each 
movement displayed is a reflex reaction to some sense-stimu- 
lus; and it is perhaps true that sense-stimuli play a part in 
determining the particular form of each movement. But all 
the successive movements have a meaning, a significance, for 
us, and are intelligible to us as behavior, only when we regard 
them as incidents of one process' of striving, a process that 
has conative unity. No matter how carefully the behaviorist 
may exclude from his descriptions and interpretations all im- 
plication of this aspect of the movements, he does not exclude 
it from his thinking ; he implicitly makes the assumption which 
explicitly he professes to repudiate. 

It is worth while noting that even the movements of the 
parts of a machine cannot be profitably or intelligibly described 
and interpreted in purely objective terms, i.e., without refer- 
ence to the purpose of the man who designed and made the 
machine. Take any machine, even the simplest : We may des- 
cribe in the greatest detail, its structure and the sequences of 
movements of its parts, without either understanding the 
machine or leading the hearer of our description to under- 
stand it. We cannot understand the machine and its move- 
ments without knowing what the machine is designed to do, 
what its function is, what it is there for, in short, what pur- 
pose it is designed to serve, in what goal-seeking process it 

*I recognize that interpretation or explanation is only description 
in more generalized terms: but the distinction is useful and valid. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 283 

forms a link. The machine, in a sense, embodies a human 
purpose ; it is designed, constructed, and put in action in order 
to facilitate the accomplishment of some purpose, some plan, to 
satisfy some desire, to make easier and more certain the at- 
tainment of some goal. It is for that reason, and that reason 
only, that we naturally and properly speak of the machine as 
being in order or out of order. No purely physical inorganic 
structure in the construction of which human design has played 
no part, can properly be said to be in order or out of order; 
unless we regard it as embodying the purpose of, and as de- 
signed by, some non-human intelligence, some non-human 
mental being. The solar system in many respects resembles 
a machine ; but, unless we regard it as designed and constructed 
in order to render the earth habitable for men, or for some 
other purpose, there can be no meaning in describing it as in 
order or out of order. If, through collision with a star or a 
comet, the course of the planets were changed in some radical 
fashion, there would be no sense in saying that the system was 
out of order. And so with a machine, say a typewriter or a 
linotype machine : if pressure on a key does not bring down the 
right letter, we say the machine is out of order ; but the state- 
ment has meaning only in virtue of its implicit reference to 
the purpose which the machine is designed to serve. 

If, then, we cannot understand or intelligibly describe the 
movements of the machine without reference, implicit or ex- 
plicit, to the purpose it serves; how much less can we intelli- 
gibly describe the movements of men or of animals without 
such reference, whether in particular or in general terms. 1 

*One of the sources of confusion in this matter is the two-fold 
sense in which the words 'purposive' and 'teleologies!* are used, the 
intrinsic and the extrinsic meanings. There is the intrinsic sense 
in which human conduct is purposive, teleological, or goal-seeking; 
and there is the extrinsic sense in which the movements of the 
parts of a machine are purposive, teleological, or goal-seeking. The 
most mechanically minded man does not scruple to ask What is 
the purpose of this lever, or of that cog or switch, in a machine? 
And in the same way he does not scruple to ask What is the pur- 
pose of this bone or that muscle in an animal's body? But he 
uses this language without reflecting upon the significance or im- 
plication of his words. If the question of his meaning is forced upon 
"bJTrt, he is likely to reply that his words are merely a convenient, 
but incorrect, form of speech; that of course he does not mean that 
the starting lever foresees and intends the starting of the machine, 
or that the bone or muscle of the animal foresees or intends the 
movements in which it plays a part. And he is confident that in 



284 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Yet just this is the program, the goal, the purpose of the S JB. 
and the N.B. Their purpose is to achieve general descriptions 
of behavior in language which shall exclude all reference to 
purpose; the goal they seek is description of behavior without 
reference to its goal-seeking nature; they strive toward a 
description which shall exclude all reference to, all implication 
of, striving. Thus they cannot move a step, cannot even lay 
down their program, without stultifying themselves. 

The supreme and final test of any scientific principle or 
hypothesis is the pragmatic test. How does it serve as a guide 
to observation and experiment? This test, when applied to 
the principle or hypothesis of the S.B., at once reveals its in- 
adequacy, its falsity, its misleading nature. 

As a matter of fact, the S.B. does not in practice abide by 
his principles. When he sets out to make experimental obser- 
vation of a man or animal, he does not ignore the purposive 
nature of behavior; he puts his subject under such conditions 
as he believes will induce it to strive towards some goal. He 
puts the animal in a maze or a cage from which, he believes, 
it will strive to escape; or he offers it some incentive to 

both cases all the movements are mechanically explicable: and 
that therefore the word 'purpose 1 in all cases of both classes im- 
plies a fallacy. In the older discussions of teleology, the words "pur- 
posive" and "teleological" were chiefly used in the sense in which 
we apply them to a machine. It was asked Is the solar system, 
are volcanic eruptions, lightning, and the flow of rivers purposive? 
The question meant Are these things or processes designed, con- 
structed, or set in action, as our machines are, in order to serve 
some purpose? And the answer of science was No, they are not 
The same question was asked of the structures and processes of 
the animal body. And for a long time science accepted the posi- 
tive answer; regarded the animal body as a machine cunningly 
designed to realize the purpose of its Designer and Creator. Then 
came the Darwinian theory: and science saw that it was no longer 
necessary to regard the structure of each animal species as the 
product of a designing Creator, and said The structures and move- 
ments of the animal body are not teleological or purposive. When 
the teleological interpretation of bodily movements in the extrinsic 
sense of the words was thus rejected, the other kind of teleological 
interpretation, the intrinsic meaning, fell also into disrepute, owing 
largely to the failure to distinguish between the two meanings of 
the words, between intrinsic and extrinsic teleology. It should be 
noted that intrinsic and extrinsic teleology do not imply one an- 
other. They do not stand or fall together. Rather they may be 
regarded as alternatives. The more fully we accept intrinsic pur- 
posiveness in organisms, the less do we need to postulate extrinsic, 
purpose and conversely. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 285 

strive, food, or a mate, or a rival, or a terrifying object. He 
has some general notion of its striving tendencies; and his 
experimental procedure is guided by that knowledge, while 
he pretends to proceed without reference to such tendencies. 

Much experimental work, both on men and animals, has 
been far less productive than it might have been, if the striv- 
ing aspect of behavior, the purposive nature of all our activi- 
ties, had been recognized frankly and explicitly, instead of 
implicitly and furtively. For in very many experiments the 
question of supplying adequate incentives to striving is all- 
important. I might illustrate this fact at great length from 
the records of experiments made by many psychologists. It 
must suffice to point out that in quite recent years the impor- 
tance of the incentive to striving has begun to receive practical 
recognition in both human and animal experimental psychol- 
ogy, with much profit to the procedures adopted and to the 
results attained. 1 The common conclusion arrived at, being 
that which common sense has accepted for long ages, is that 



*A few references must suffice: W. Koehler, The Mentality of 
Apes, p. 65. 

Simmons, The Relative Effectiveness of Certain Incentives in 
Animal Learning, Comp. Psychol. Monog, 1924. 

E. B, Hurlock, The Effect of Incentives upon the constancy of 
the I.Q. Pedagog. Seminary, Sept. 1925. 

H. P. Whiting and H. B. English, Fatigue Tests and Incentives, 
Journ. Exp. Psychology, Feb. 1925. 

W. F. Book and L. Norvell, The Will to Learn, an Experimental 
Study of Incentives, The Pedagog. Seminary, Dec. 1922. 

I may add that in my own prolonged experiments with rats, 
realizing the primary importance of incentives that will evoke strong 
striving towards a goal, I have adopted the plan of putting the 
animals into a tank of water in which is a single island or platform. 
The rat placed in water at once swims vigorously to and fro, ex- 
ploring the boundaries and all available channels of the tank. And 
careful observation of the behavior on repetition of the situation 
will convince any impartial observer that, after the rat has found 
the platform a few times, the platform becomes for him a goal 
which he actively seeks. I venture to claim that a due regard to 
the importance of incentives has in this case led me to a method 
of great value in animal experiment, one which, by standardizing 
the incentive and evoking constantly a maximal energy of striving 
toward a goal, greatly shortens the duration of each experiment 
and renders the successive performances of the same animal, and 
of different animals, much truer indices of the animal's capacity 
to learn than the performances under the commonly used method 
of rewarding the animal with food and making food the incentive 
of its behavior. 



286 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the more effective the incentive, i.e. the stronger the urge, or 
impulse, or striving, evoked, the more rapidly and efficiently 
does the animal or the human being overcome difficulties and 
attain its goal. 

The demonstration of the inadequacy, the relative futility, 
of all attempts to ignore the purposive, the goal-seeking, nature 
of all behavior may best be taken from the mouth of the pur- 
posive behaviorist Two of my colleagues stand out as leaders 
of this group, namely Profs. R. B. Perry and E. C. Tolman. 
The latter has recently published a series of articles concerned 
with this topic, basing his conclusions on the careful observa- 
tion and analysis of animal behavior under experimental con- 
ditions. 1 

In the first of these articles, Prof. Tolman sets out by re- 
jecting decisively the proposal to abolish instincts and the en- 
deavor to interpret instinctive behavior as merely the result of 
setting in action a chain of reflexes. After referring to count- 
less instances of animal behavior which exhibit extreme vari- 
ability of action, variations not attributable to variations of 
the sense-stimuli, Tolman writes : "Indeed these and countless 
like observations have given the pure reflex pattern theory its 
final coup de grace." He rejects equally decisively the view 
that what we call instincts can be identified with habits. "In- 
stinct behavior is fundamentally different from habit-behavior. 
For, although undoubtedly inheritance plays its part in both 
and environment plays its part in both, still variations in 
heredity are primarily responsible for the differences to be 
observed in the one and variations in environment for the dif- 
ferences to be found in the other." He shows that most of 
those authors who profess to avoid all reference to goal-seek- 
ing do not in reality do so, but rather introduce it surrep- 
tiously. He rightly insists that the instincts or, as he alter- 
natively calls them, the "innate determining adjustments," are 
to be "recognized by the teleological patterns of the final goals 
which they achieve. The subordinate movements and objects 
involved may be all acquired, but the general pattern of the 
goal is innate and constant." 

In the third article, Tolman rightly insists on the goal-seek- 
ing character of animal behavior, and writes : "It appears that 

1M The Nature of Instinct" in the Psychological Bulletin April, 
1923; "Behaviorism and Purpose," in the Journal of Philosophy, 
Jan. 1925; "Purpose and Cognition.: the Determiners of Animal 
Learning" in Psychological Review, July, 1925. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 287 

goal-seeking must be defined not only as a tendency to persist 
in more or less random fashion until food is reached but also 
as a tendency to select within limits the shorter (and probably 
also the easier and pleasanter) of two or more alternative 
ways." And he shows that such goal-seeking is initiated, not 
merely by sense-stimuli, but by the animal's appreciation of 
the situation in which it finds itself, what Tolman prefers to 
call its "initial cognitive hunches;" and that in turn the goal- 
seeking is guided and terminated, not merely by some new 
sense-stimulus, but by the animal's appreciation of the nature 
of the new situation brought about by its activity. All this 
is based upon minute and exact experimental observation and 
analysis of animal behavior; and it leads Tolman to the con- 
clusion that we cannot hope to make progress in the study of 
animal behavior unless we frankly apply to animal learning 
"some sort of purposive (goal-seeking) and cognitive (object- 
adjustment) categories;" and that "practically, it seems that 
the current tendency to talk and think primarily in terms of 
such inadequate and premature physiological concepts as are 
now on hand is in part responsible for some of the barrenness 
of our present animal research." 

These conclusions of Prof. Tolman's are perfectly in line 
with the work and conclusions of Professors Koehler and 
Koffka, two leaders of the Gestalt school. Both, basing them- 
selves upon intimate studies of animal behavior, have shown 
by the most careful and elaborate reasoning how hollow and 
misleading is the pretense of the S.B. to be able to describe 
and interpret the actions of animals either as series of reflex 
responses to sense-stimuli or as habit responses; they have 
shown that those observers of animal behavior who pretend to 
demonstrate the absence of all intelligence and purpose in ani- 
mals merely prove their own domination by a perverse purpose, 
namely the purpose to demonstrate the adequacy of mechanical 
categories. They show conclusively that you cannot describe 
intelligibly and adequately the behavior of animals without 
using language which implies that the animals do not merely 
respond to stimuli, but that they seek goals and appreciate the 
several factors of a complex stiuation in their relations to one 
another and to the goals they seek. For example, Koehler 
describes the following behavior of a chimpanzee. "Sultan 
grabs at objects [food] behind the bars and cannot reach them 
with his arm; he thereupon walks about searchingly, finally 
turns to a shoe-scraper, made of iron bars in a wooden frame, 



288 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

and manipulates it until he has pulled out one of the iron bars ;. 
with this he runs immediately to his real objective, at a dis- 
tance of about ten metres and draws it toward him!' I have 
italicized the words of this description which imply the pur- 
pose and refer to the goal of the animal in accordance with 
common sense and good sense. The consistent S.B. would 
have to describe this simple bit of behavior very differently,. 
as a series of disconnected movements, movements each of 
which is a response to some sense-impression of the moment 
and is unconnected with the other movements of the sequence 
by any reference to, or implication of, the connection of them 
all in one sequence as steps in a single goal-seeking process, a 
single continued striving towards the objective, sustained by 
the animal's desire for food. Of course such a description 
is possible, but not only would it be long-winded and clumsy, 
but also it would be inadequate and positively misleading. 
Koehler goes on to say: "In this case it is pretty dear that 
the whole proceeding, part by part, contains several constitu- 
ents which are meaningless when isolated. (1) Instead of 
keeping to his objective, Sultan goes away from it; this is quite 
senseless when taken by itself. (2) He breaks up one of the 
station's iron shoe-scrapers, and this, taken by itself, has noth- 
ing whatever to do with his objective. (1) The animal by no 
means strides away from the objective in the free careless 
way which we are used to, in him and the others at times when 
they are seeking nothing, but goes away like some one who has 
a task before him. And here again, I wish to warn against 
anyone speaking of 'anthropomorphism' of 'reading into' the 
animals etc., where there is not the least ground for such 
reproaches. I merely ask whether it does not look different 
from somebody strolling about idly. Of course it looks differ- 
ent. Whether we can exactly analyze our total impression in. 
both cases, has nothing whatever to do with the case. Now 
all I wish to state is that the two general impressions that are 
contrasted here occur in chimpanzees, exactly as in man; and 
it is these 'impressions' which are not at all 'something that 
has been read into* the chimpanzees, but which belongs to the 
elementary phenomenology of his behavior, that are meant 
when we say, for instance, 'Sultan trotted about gaily* or 
'he went over the ground looking for something/ If this is 
an anthrophomorphism, so then is this sentence: 'Chimpanzees 
have the same tooth formula as man.' So as to leave no doubt 
whatever as to the meaning of the expression, 'Walking about 



MEN OR ROBOTS 289 

searchingly,' I should like to add that nothing is said therein 
as to the 'consciousness' of the animal, but only as to its 'be- 
havior/ (2) While playing with the shoe-scraper Sultan's 
activity is concentrated exclusively on loosening one of its bars; 
but even when described more precisely thus, this action re- 
mains irrelevant with reference to the real purpose as long as 
it is considered in isolation." Prof. Koehler thus brings out 
clearly the fact that the train of action described has a cona- 
tive unity, is a sequence of actions, all of which are steps in one 
continued process of seeking a goal, of striving to attain the 
objective, and that any description which ignores this fact, 
any consistent description by the strict behaviorist, must be 
useless ; and worse than useless, because positively misleading. 

The particular instance described above is only one of a 
multitude of similar instances in which the animals obviously 
take steps in order to attain their goals ; instances such as pil- 
ing up boxes in order, by climbing upon the pile, to be able to 
reach bananas hung high on the ceiling; or joining two pieces 
of bamboo in order to make a stick long enough to reach a 
banana lying outside the cage. 

Again, in criticizing the S.B. theory that all learning or im- 
provement of action is merely a process of habit-formation, by 
the chance succession of movements and the mechanical asso- 
ciation of such movements as are most frequently repeated to 
form a habit, Koehler writes: "the facts we are speaking of, 
by the way, seem to represent almost a reversal of what the 
theory we have discussed regards as the effect of repetitions. 
According to it, procedure developed by accident becomes 
smoother through practice, and more like a genuine solution. 
This may be true, where the theory applies; the chimpanzee's 
genuine solutions, at any rate, do not become more valuable 
in themselves through constant repetition, even if they appear 
more quickly. For one who has actually watched the experi- 
ments, discussions like the above have something comic about 
them. For instance, when one has seen for oneself, how in 
the first experiment of her life, it did not dawn on Tschego 
for hours to push the obstructing box out of the way, how she 
merely stretched out her arm uselessly, or else sat down quiet- 
ly, but then, fearing the loss of her food, suddenly seized the 
obstacle, and pushed it to one side, thus solving the task in a 
second when one has watched that, then to 'secure these facts 
against misinterpretation* [the misinterpretation of the S.B.] 



290 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

seems almost pedantic." 1 And in general Koehler says of the 
S.B. interpretation of the learning process "No single experi- 
ment fulfils this requirement, as practically none is performed 
twice over in the same way, indeed the movements by which 
any single one is performed vary very much the only limit 
is the sense of the proceeding. For this reason no observer, 
even with the best of efforts, can say: 'the animal contracts 
such or such a muscle, carries out this or that impulse' this 
would be to accentuate an unessential side-issue, which may 
change from one case to another; which muscles carry out 
which action is entirely immaterial." 

Further, criticizing a common illegitimate extension of the 
S. B. theory, which we owe originally to Thorndike, and which 
asserts that success stamps in (in the brain) the accidental 
associations of movements that have led to success, Koehler 
writes: "the animals produce complete methods of solution 
quite suddenly, and as complete wholes which may, 4n a cer- 
tain sense, be absolutely appropriate to the situation* and yet 
cannot be carried out. They can never have had any success 
with them, and, therefore such methods were certainly never 
practiced formerly. After all this, as far as I can see, even 
an adherent of that theory must recognize that the reports of 
experiments here given do not support his explanation. The 
more he tries to advance more valuable data than the general 
scheme of his theory, and really think out and show how he 
would explain and interpret all the experiments in detail, the 
more will he realize that he is attempting something impos- 
sible." 2 

Koehler does not hesitate to attribute the actions of the 
animals to their desire for the attainment of their goals, to 
assume that they perform certain actions as indirect means to 
the attainment of the goal, that they even construct implements 
for the sake of, for the purpose of, facilitating the attainment 
of a goal. 3 And he shows that we cannot properly describe 
many of their actions without using language which implies 
such goal-seeking; e.g. an animal on successive occasions 
pushes away a box which obstructs her approach to her goal, 

1 Op. Cit. p. 207. 

a Op. Cit. p. 227. 

*e.g. piling up of boxes to form a platform on which to climb 
nearer to the goal, and constructing a long stick by fitting two 
sticks together and even gnawing away the end of one stick in 
order to make it fit into the cavity of the other. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 291 

and on each occasion she handles it in a different manner : the 
behavior cannot be adequately described by saying that she 
made such and such movements which, on each occasion re- 
sulted in the removal of the box. In order to describe the be- 
havior adequately, we have to say that she removed the ob- 
struction in the course of her efforts to attain her goal. 1 

Professor Koffka 2 also, by a careful analysis of the facts of 
animal behavior, refutes the theory of learning by association 
of purely random reflex acts or of reflex acts evoked simply 
as direct responses to sensory stimuli. He concludes that "the 
theory of an entirely meaningless learning is simply untenable." 
He freely realizes the purposive or goal-seeking character 
of animal behavior ; and he does not scruple to use the words 
'purpose' and 'intention' and to speak of "what is going on in 
the phenomental world of the chimpanzee's mind." He also 
insists that instinctive process is radically different from the 
working of a reflex mechanism. 

I may add that my own experiments on dogs and rats 
(briefly reported in my Outline of Psychology) illustrate the 
same facts, the extreme variation of movements in any one 
attempt to solve a problem and in successive struggles with 
the same problem, movements which nevertheless are all inci- 
dents of one process, a striving towards the goal, and which 
can only be intelligibly described as such. In the same work 
I have shown in some detail the failure of all the attempts 
of the S.B. to interpret and explain as mechanical responses 
to stimuli behavior of two types: first, the simplest possible 
instances of obtaining food by escape from a maze; secondly, 
the more complex behavior of returning home, a form of be- 
havior exhibited by a multitude of species some of which are 
comparatively low in the evolutionary scale. 

1 KoeHer writes: "Her manner of removing the obstacle was quite 
different from the first occasion. I wish to stress this point for the 
enlightenment of students who have not observed chimpanzees 
carefully. What Chica did this second time was to clear away 
the cage from the fruit, not to make this or that series of move- 
ments." He might well have said that it is necessary to stress this 
point for the enlightenment of students obsessed and blinded by the 
mechanistic dogma. 

In his "The Growth of the Mind." 



CHAPTER XIII 

MEN OR ROBOTS?* 



BY WILLIAM Me DOUGALL 



II 

It is necessary to say a few words about the conditioned 
reflex or conditioned response. I have no desire to belittle 
the importance of the beautiful experiments of Pavlov and 
others which have built up a new method of great value for 
the study of the nervous system. Prof. Burnham of this uni- 
versity has shown us in his book, "The Normal Mind," that 
the results obtained by this method can be of much value for 
human psychology, can be incorporated in a sane psychology 
which does not pretend to ignore the all-important facts of 
striving, of motivation, of goal-seeking, of incentives and 
ideals. The experiments on the conditioned response do un- 
questionably carry us nearer to an understanding of the pro- 
cess of association. And no one denies that association is a 
process of great importance in our mental life. But all the 
history of psychology since Locke shows how detrimental to 
its progress was the overweening faith of the associationist 
school in the all-sufficiency of its one great explanatory prin- 
ciple. The physiologists of the present time who are enthusi- 
astically exploiting the conception of the conditioned reflex 
as the one sole and all-sufficient master-key to the secrets of 
human nature, these physiologists, obstinately blind to the les- 
sons of the past, are repeating the error of the Associationists. 
James Mill, with a dogmatic confidence which now seems ridi- 
culous, declared that the principle of association of ideas made 
all our mental processes as obvious as the road from Ludgate 
Circus to St. Paul's Cathedral. Many of the enthusiasts for 
the conditioned reflex are making for it the same daim, and 
are thus repeating his error, with far less excuse. James 
Mill's error is pardonable in view of the scanty knowledge 
and insight of his time; but now, when the labors of a multi- 
tude of workers throughout well nigh a century have con- 
clusively shown the inadequacy of the association-principle to 
explain all human activity, there is no excuse for the wilful 
ignoring of all this improvement of our insight and the repeti- 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, De- 
cember 11, 



294 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

tion of the old error in a slightly modified and accentuated 
form. 

The principle of association is valid and important. The 
mistake of the extreme associationists was to imagine that it 
rendered all other principles unnecessary, to believe that by a 
little juggling with words, by the use of such phrases as "the 
idea of an end or goal," they explained away all the facts of 
motive, striving, volition, conation, constructive activity. The 
principle of the conditioned response is equally valid and im- 
portant ; it is the principle of association in an improved form. 
But the mistake of so many of its exponents is to believe that 
the demonstration in the laboratory of elementary instances of 
conditioning of responses proves such responses to be merely 
mechanical processes that imply no forward striving towards 
a goal. When Prof. Koehler's ape, Sultan, had learned to 
reach, with the long rod he had constructed, the banana that 
la}' beyond the reach of a short rod, he may be said to have 
acquired a conditioned response; just as every instance of the 
acquisition of skill or knowledge may be so described. The 
error of the conditioned response enthusiasts is the assump- 
tion that Sultan's desire for the banana, his striving towards it, 
was an irrelevant fact, one which may safely be ignored when 
we attempt to understand the way in which the new response 
was acquired and subsequently displayed. 

Near Behaviorism 

The strict behaviorists do not trouble themselves about the 
social life of men ; they are sufficiently occupied with the self- 
imposed task of proving that animals and new-born babies are 
merely machines. But some near-behaviorists have undertaken 
to write on Social Psychology, basing it on the Watsonian 
dogma of the absence of all innate endowment other than a 
limited number of mechanical reflexes. How then do they 
deal with the complexities of social conduct? There are two 
pieces of verbal sleight-of-hand on which they chiefly rely in 
order to conceal from their readers the impossible nature of 
the tasks they essay, the utter inadequacy of the suppositions 
with which they set out. 

First, they create the false appearance of bringing all social 
conduct under the stimulus-response formula by aid of a very 
simple verbal trick, rendered possible by the ambiguity of com- 
mon speech. The stimulus-response formula of the behavior- 
ist asserts that every action is a response to a stimulus; the 



MEN OR ROBOTS 295 

word "stimulus" in this formula clearly meaning a physical 
stimulus applied to a sense-organ or afferent nerve. When, 
then, they find a man whose conduct is largely governed by 
his devotion to his country, to an ideal, or to the religion of 
Christ or Buddha, they describe such things, the country or 
nation, the ideal, the religion, or the founder of the religion, 
as a stimulus ; and thus all patriotic, or moral, or religious 
conduct becomes merely a response or series of responses to 
stimuli. 

Secondly, having rejected "instincts," in the interest of the 
mechanical reflex-theory and on such trivial grounds as Dr. 
Watson's failure to see evidence of instincts in new-born in- 
fants, they introduce the essential notion of a tendency to- 
wards an end, an urge towards a goal, surreptitiously by a back 
door, disguised under all sorts of names chosen to convey as 
much mechanical implication as may be possible; the favorite 
terms being drive, determining tendency, prepotent reflex, pre- 
potent habit, determining set, motor-set. 

Dr. Allport, for example, is not so blind to the facts of na- 
ture as Dr. Watson. He sees the plain evidence that matura- 
tion of instincts takes place after birth in the young of 
many animal species; but, seeing also (like Watson) that it 
is impossible to prove the reality of such maturation in the 
child by any simple experiment, he concludes: "In view of 
the uncertainty regarding the maturation hypothesis it seems 
better to adopt the genetic viewpoint, and beginning at birth 
with the simple reflexes, which are demonstrably innate, pro- 
gress with no further assumptions than the well-known facts 
of the learning process." 1 But, knowing well that human con- 
duct cannot be interpreted in terms of Watson's array of re- 
flexes, Allport very soon introduces and makes great play with 
the "prepotent reflex." "The human being has inherited a 
number of prepotent reflexes which are fundamental not only 
in their original potency, but in the control which they exert 
over habit formation throughout life. Indomitable restless- 
ness of movement in carrying out prepotent activities in the 
face of difficulties is universal in the animal kingdom. The 
imperativeness of the prepotent reflex is Nature's provision 
that adaptation and survival will be achieved." 2 
Allport, having thus provided himself with something less 

1 Social Psychology, p. 81. 
Ibid, p. 57. 



296 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

sterile than the simple mechanical reflexes, having added to his 
stock of explanatory principles the "prepotent reflex" which 
has a potency for control, which is indomitable in the face of 
difficulties, and imperative in its service of the ends of adapt- 
ation and survival, is able to assert : "the intricacies of human 
conduct arise as modifications of these simple prepotent re- 
sponses;" and, without arousing the critical tendency of most 
of his readers, he can introduce such terms as incentive, end, 
sanction, drive, urge, desire, motive, 'wish, selection, choice, 
means to an end, in order to, struggle, interests, satisfaction, 
autonomic drives, struggle for satisfaction, settings, attitudes, 
striving, craving, aims, ideals, values, efforts, success, seeking, 
conflict and even purpose. 

Thus, without gross appearance of inconsistency, he is able 
to write: "Hunger is the supreme drive of the learning pro- 
cess. Sex is a close rival. Other important factors, such as 
rivalry, desire for social approval and the like, are incentives 
derived from these two." 1 In fact, as the book advances to 
deal with the actual facts of human life, it falls into the 
language of good common sense, which everywhere recognizes, 
implicitly and explicitly, the purposive, the forward striving 
character of all our activities. 

Purposive Behaviorism 

We may next examine the procedure of the purposive be- 
haviorist, as exemplified by Professors Perry and Tolman. 

Tolman fully recognizes and insists upon the goal-seeking 
nature of most animal behavior. "Whenever, in merely de- 
scribing a behavior, it is found necessary to include a state- 
ment of something either towards-which or from^-which the 
behavior is directed, there we have purpose. But we may 
analyze further. Just when is it we find a statement of a 
'toward-whichness* or of a *fron>whichness' thus necessary? 
We find it necessary, whenever, by modifying the various at- 
tendant circumstances, we discover that the same goal is still 
there and still identifying the given response. Thus, when we 
make minor changes in the position or nature of the intervening 
objects and the behavior readjusts so as to again come to the 
end-object, the case is one of purpose. Or finally when we re- 
move the goal-object entirely and behavior thereupon ceases, 
purpose must again have been a descriptive feature. In short, 
purpose is present, descriptively, whenever a statement of the 

^Social Psychology. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 297 

goal-object is necessary to indicate (1) constancy of goal-ob- 
ject in spite of variation in adjustment to intervening obstacles, 
or (2) variations in final direction corresponding to differing 
positions of the goal-object, or (3) cessation of activity when 
a given goal-object is entirely removed." Again: "wherever 
the purely objective description of either a simple or complex 
behavior discovers a 'persistence-until' character there we have 
what behaviorism defines as purpose." 

And Prof. Tolman also recognizes that these purposive ac- 
tivities are initiated, guided, and terminated by cognitions, by 
appreciation of the nature of the goal-object, of the route to be 
followed for its attainment, and of the new situation which 
constitutes attainment. In what then does his behaviorism 
consist?- Merely in this that when we use such terms as 
purpose, goal-seeking, cognition, knowing, appreciation of, 
imputing, intents, noetic aspects of behavior, knowledge, desire 
and purpose, (all of which terms are freely used by Tolman), 
we must (in order to be scientific and to avoid the dreaded 
spectre of anthropomorphism) carefully explain that all these 
words are used in a purely objective sense, that they imply, 
on the part of the creature whose behavior is described, no 
experience, no awareness of the goal-object or of the inter- 
vening obstacles, no felt impulse or desire for it, no satisfac- 
tion on attaining it or coming nearer to it, no dissatisfaction, 
distress, or urge, on continued failure to attain it. 

Now these prohibitions of the behaviorist are intended to 
apply, not only to descriptions and interpretations of the be- 
havior of animals, but also to all descriptions and interpreta- 
tions of human behavior. Suppose you see a boy trying to 
reach an apple on the end of a branch. He reaches up, stands 
on tiptoe, jumps at it again and again. Then he takes a stick 
and with it shakes the bough or strikes at the apple; or he 
runs away, and returns presently with a box or ladder by the 
aid of which he reaches the apple. Tolman will allow you to 
say that the boy seeks the apple, that the apple is the goal of 
his seeking, that the use of the stick or box is a cognitive 
hunch on the boy's part, that he imputes to the stidc the 
property of extending his reach to the apple, and so on. But 
if you wish to be scientific, you may not say or imagine that 
the boy sees the apple and consciously desires to reach and to 
eat it; still less may you say that he foresees that, by using the 
stick, he may cause the apple to fall, or that by climbing on the 
box he may be able to reach it. Nor may you use such language, 



298 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

even if the boy tells you with all the honest naivety of boy- 
hood that all these suppositions of yours are true. To use 
such language, to allow yourself to suppose that the boy sees 
and desires and foresees, would be grossly anthropomorphic. 
The apple stimulates the boy to put out his hand towards it; 
and when he runs to fetch a stick or a ladder, he is making 
random movements, or he formerly made such random move- 
ments and these have become associated, as a conditioned re- 
flex, with the act of stretching out the arm without subsequent 
contact with the apple. And the ray from the apple then in- 
duces another conditioned reflex, the striking with the stick or 
the climbing of the ladder. 

That or something like it must be the interpretation of the 
S. B. Prof. Tolman is more lenient. He will allow us to say 
that it was the purpose of the boy to obtain the apple and 
that he had a cognitive hunch that the ladder would facilitate 
his goal seeking; provided that we repudiate all such implica- 
tion as that the boy sees the apple and foresees its fall. Even 
if he gets another boy to shake the branch, and himself stands 
holding his hands beneath the apple ready to catch it, you still 
may not say that he foresees its falL And Tolman seems in- 
clined to attach much importance to the fact that by using the 
words of common speech (such words as desire, purpose, 
striving, cognition, perception and memory and anti- 
cipation) you can describe the event and yet can avoid what 
he calls the 'mentalisf implications, if you carefully explain 
that you don't mean to use the words in the ordinary sense, 
but merely as words which are convenient for the description 
of the objective event you observe. He assigns to Prof. Perry 
the credit for pointing out that you can thus describe purposive 
actions while repudiating one-half of the common meaning of 
the terms. 

If now we turn to Prof. Perry's discussion of behavior, we 
find that, like Tolman, he freely admits that human and ani- 
mal action is commonly purposive or goal-seeking and cannot 
be effectively described in words which do not imply this fun- 
damental character. But he would have us interpret these 
terms as implying, not any foresight of the goal, but only some 
hypothetical neural arrangement which he calls a "determin- 
ing tendency." Perry's behaviorism then is like Tolman's a 
purposive behaviorism; consisting in so defining the common 
terms as to repudiate their mentalist implications. 



MEN OR ROBOTS 299 

What inducements, then, do Tolman and Perry hold out to 
us in order to persuade us to use words in this peculiarly 
mutilated fashion ? What advantages do they claim will result 
from such usage? I must confess that I do not know. So 
far as I can discover, they do not tell us at all dearly. Perry 
seems to suggest that the profit or advantage will be the avoid- 
ance of all language that implies some difference between men- 
tal events and physical events, as all our ordinary speech does. 
For he is an exponent of a peculiar metaphysic, known as New 
Realism, which seeks to abolish that distinction. But this is 
an inducement only for those select few who have accepted 
that very peculiar philosophy of New Realism. To the major- 
ity of us, who regard that philosophy as quite untenable, he 
offers no inducement. Tolman, so far as I can see, offers us 
no inducement of any kind. He merely seems to feel that the 
feat of describing behavior in purely objective terms, terms 
rendered objective by carefully stripping away their common 
subjective meaning, is so great an achievement that it is worth 
doing merely as a display of verbal skill. 

Tolman does, however, give one slight cue to his very pecu- 
liar attitude in this matter. He remarks : "Although we agree 
with Professor McDougall in finding his first five marks of be- 
havior characteristic of purpose, we disagree with him in sup- 
posing such 'purpose* to be something added on to the mere 
objective description of the behavior itself." I gather that 
Tolman means to say that I suppose a purpose to be a peculiar 
something added to the bodily process. 1 And here, as it seems 
to me he reveals a difficulty over which many are inclined to 
boggle, though it arises purely from an unfortunate usage of 
words; namely, we speak of a purpose as though it were a 
thing, and then, when we ask what sort of a thing it can be, 
we can find no intelligible answer. 

If, instead of speaking of a purpose, we confine ourselves 
to the adjective purposive and speak merely of purposive ac- 
tion or activity, we avoid this difficulty. Purposive is then the 
adjective which we may use if we wish to describe purely ob- 
jectively processes of a special kind, namely, the peculiar forms 
of bodily action we observe in men and animals, the goal-seek- 
ing actions. But we may use it, as we do in common speech, 
to imply also that such actions are accompanied by some f ore- 



not (as Tolman says) to the description, but to the pro- 
cess described. 



300 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

sight of the goal and some desire to attain it. And the justi- 
fication for so doing is (1) that, when I myself so act, I know, 
if I stop to reflect, that I foresee the god and desire it; and 
(2) that, if I question other intelligent persons, they tell me 
that, when they act in this objectively purposive fashion, they 
also foresee the goal and desire it. This subjective accompani- 
ment of purposive action is so constantly reported that we are 
justified in supposing it to be the rule; we can assume it with 
a high degree of probability. The question, then, is Can 
we with advantage put aside this knowledge of the sub- 
jective aspect of purposive action: can we better un- 
derstand and control behavior without the aid of this knowl- 
edge? I confidently suggest that we cannot; that it is advan- 
tageous to use such knowledge, and for the following reasons : 

(1) It is surely hazardous and against all scientific prin- 
ciples to put aside any knowledge of an obscure event when we 
seek to understand and control it. 

(2) When we use this knowledge, we do understand the 
event better, we are in a better position to influence or control 
it, than if we put it aside. This is true of both human and 
animal behavior. We are more familiar with, have much bet- 
ter acquaintance with, foreseeing and desiring, than we have 
with hypothetical structures in the nervous system called "de- 
termining tendencies" or "motor sets" or what not. And this, 
the practical or pragmatic test, is the supreme test of the value 
of any assumption. Now I take it, that, in relation to human 
behavior, the superior convenience and effectiveness of the 
mentalist description and interpretation is beyond dispute. 
When the boy fetches a stick and with it knocks down the 
apple, we all unhesitatingly interpret his conduct by assuming 
that he sees the apple, desires to obtain it, foresees its fall, and 
fetches and uses the stick in order to obtain it. And, when 
the chimpanzee behaves in a very similar manner, fetching and 
using a stick to knock down a banana hung above his reach 
(Koehler, Op. Cit p. 146), we all interpret and understand 
his behavior in similar mentalist terms. Such interpretation is 
not only natural, but it is also profitable; it is far more ef- 
fective as a guide to our action than any forced unnatural in- 
terpretation achieved by disciplining ourselves to repudiate the 
mentalist implications of the words we inevitably use. The 
man who sympathetically understands animals will manage 
them far more effectively than he who interprets their actions 



MEN OR ROBOTS 301 

mechanically, even when it is a question of planning and con- 
ducting experiments with them. 

And this is true not only when we study men and animals 
under experimental conditions in the laboratory; it is also true 
and vastly important in the immense experiment which mod- 
ern industry is making and on the success of which the pros- 
perous development of our civilization depends, namely the 
experiment of keeping vast numbers of men working at tasks 
and under conditions that are very unnatural, very different 
from those to which human nature has become adapted by 
long ages of development under natural conditions, the con- 
ditions of life of the hunter, the warrior and the farmer. 

It is just because modern industry has treated the workers 
as Robots rather than as men that the modern world is so 
full of strife and unrest, of strikes and lock-outs, and bitter 
conflicts of all kinds. All these disharmonies and inefficiencies 
of the industrial world can only be overcome by recognizing 
far more dearly than has yet been done the complexity of the 
motives, the desires and the purposes of the workmen, and by 
delicately adjusting incentives and satisfactions in accordance 
with these complex desires of every human heart. The theory 
and practise of modern industry have been vitiated by the 
tendency to treat men as though the stimulus-response for- 
mula of the behaviorist were true. The mechanical arts of 
industrial production have been developed with astonishing 
speed and success, by the aid of the magnificent discoveries of 
the physical sciences; while the art of managing men has re- 
mained undeveloped, largely because psychological science, the 
science of human nature, has remained undeveloped, especially 
that most important part of it which is concerned, or should 
be concerned, with human motives and purposes. 

Fortunately, many leaders of the industrial world and many 
students of its problems are now beginning to recognize this 
truth and are taking thought how to remedy these defects. 
But they can find no help in any psychology that is not 
thoroughly and frankly of the purposive type. 1 

*A most interesting book published only last month (Mainsprings 
of Men t by Whiting Williams) illustrates my point vividly. Mr. 
Williams, from a rich store of intimate contact with working men, 
shows the complexity and astonishing power of motives commonly 
ignored by economists. 

I cite a few passages. "No one," he writes, "can expect to secure 
or maintain his leadership except as he promises fulfillment for the 
wishes, yearnings, hopings of his workers whose delight is that we 



302 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

To all this reasoning the mechanist will reply that primitive 
men interpret inorganic events in the ideological way ; that the 
savage regards the flow of the river, volcanic eruptions and, 
still more, the working of mechanical contrivances, as purpos- 
ive activities, and that the advance of science has consisted in 
progressively getting rid of all such mentalist implications in 
our dealings with natural processes. And he maintains that, 
though in dealing with animal and human behavior such ex- 
trusion of mentalist implications may be at present difficult 
and even practically unprofitable, yet we must attempt the 
task, if we are ever to understand the causation of human 
and animal actions. 

This brings us right up against the fundamental question at 
issue. The true ground of the behaviorist effort is the belief 
that animal and human behavior are truly and wholly mechani- 
cal, that they are of the same nature as all other processes in 
nature and that, therefore, the truest, the only true, interpre- 
tation of it must be in the terms we use in the inorganic sci- 
ences; that, though such interpretation may be difficult and 
even relatively unprofitable at the present time, yet we must 
persist in this effort with faith that ultimately it will prove 
profitable in the long run. 



are not only workers, but also fathers, worshippers, voters, lovers, 
whole men. Even in the factory the hopeful contestant will, ac- 
cordingly, do well to examine some of those satisfactions which we 
long for, not because we are workmen, but because we are human 
beings and persons .... let us take a moment's look at the hank- 
erings which appear to bother all of us in the midst of our daily 
job of just being human." 

He finds that "the wish for worth," the desire to be able to feel 
oneself of real use in the world, is one of the great forces that must 
be taken account of in any adjustment of the conditions of work 
that is to secure harmony and efficiency. "The prime influence in 
all of us today is our wish to enjoy the feeling of our worth as 
persons among other persons. This feeling can hardly exist with- 
out a corresponding recognition, respect on the part of others . . . 
The connection between this desire and most of the instincts can 
easily be seen . . . This desire does not require the sense of domina- 
tion or superiority over others except as such a feeling in certain 
fields offsets a feeling of inferiority in others. 

"First, then, the initial demand within us to be 'worthwhile' and 
second, the encouraging approval and the opposing disapprovals of 
others to whom we give attention these two forces and the con- 
stant interplay between them we must understand if we are to 
know the mainspring of our neighbors and ourselves." 



MEN OR ROBOTS 303 

To this the mentalist reply is threefold. First, even if the 
faith of the mechanist were well grounded and justified, even 
if we had some impossible, some supernatural, assurance of 
this, it would still be more profitable now and for a long time 
to come to make use of the mentalist, the truly purposive, 
interpretations of behavior; for we are very very far from 
any adequate mechanical interpretations; and we may hope 
to arrive at them most rapidly by continuing to use and to 
improve our mentalist interpretations, to formulate laws of 
behavior in mentalist terms, postponing the translation of 
them into terms of mechanism until such time as such interpre- 
tation may be a possibility and not merely a misleading pre- 
tense, as at present it is. 

Secondly, it may be that the faith of the mechanist is alto- 
gather ill-based and illusory. To all appearance the life-pro- 
cesses of living things are fundamentally different from in- 
organic processes; and we have no guarantee, no adequate 
ground for believing, that this appearance is illusory. And, 
if we uncritically adopt this mechanistic faith, and under its 
influence elaborate a picture of the world in mechanistic terms, 
we inevitably arrive at an absurd position, as the history of 
thought abundantly shows; we find we have created a picture 
of the world which leaves out of the picture entirely that men- 
tal process, that purposive striving, that creative activity, 
which has produced the picture ; our conscious striving to con- 
struct the picture, our conscious appreciation and understand- 
ing of it when constructed, remain outside it as something 
whose reation to the picture is entirely unintelligible. And 
so we have to start all over again, and strive to "remould it 
nearer to the heart's desire," the desire to understand man's 
place in the universe. 

Thirdly, the faith of the mechanist implies two assump- 
tions which we must carefully distinguish; for one of them 
may be false, though the other be true. These two assump- 
tions are (1) that all processes in the world kre fundamen- 
tally of one kind only (2) that all these processes are of the 
kind commonly assumed by the physical sciences in their in- 
terpretations of inorganic nature; namely mechanistic, or 
strictly determined and therefore strictly predictable, events. 

It may well be, I say, that the former assumption is true, 
but that the latter is false. And, if we accept the former as- 
sumption as a working hypothesis and reject the second, we 
can hope to avoid the absurdity which, as we have just now 



304 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

seen, inevitably results from accepting both assumptions. At 
the present time there are indications in various fields of sci- 
ence of a tendency in accordance with this very permissible 
selection of our fundamental working hypothesis; namely, a 
tendency to bridge the gap between the organic and the inor- 
ganic, not by forcing the organic under the type of strictly 
mechanistic interpretation that has long been very generally 
accepted in the physical sciences, but by revising that interpre- 
tation in such a way as to render it less rigidly exclusive of and 
opposed to the purposive interpretation. Physicists are mak- 
ing their assumptions less rigidly deterministic; philosophers 
and biologists are speculating along these lines. Even Prof. 
Tolman shows himself hospitable to this possibility. And, 
when we reflect upon such physical facts as gravitation, chemi- 
cal affinities, electrical attraction and repulsion, and when we 
find how varied and how lacking in precision and finality are 
the physicists interpretations of such phenomena, we cannot 
refuse to admit that here is an interesting possible line of 
scientific development. 1 

The most interesting and promising of such efforts is, I 
venture to think, that of Prof. Koehler, now of this university. 
With some hesitation and subject to correction, I submit that 
the essence of his endeavor is to show that some physical phe- 
nomena express true tendencies, that they tend towards cer- 
tain ends. The physical configuration (or Gestalt) on which 
he so strongly insists is something that cannot be adequately 
described in terms of a spatial collocation : it is something that 
can only be described in terms of a tendency towards an end 
or, as he prefers to say, a closure. Thus a soap-bubble has 
a tendency to assume the spherical form; and that tendency 
cannot be described or interpreted in terms of its mechanical 
structure, the ^ spatial arrangement and motions of its parts; 
the tendency is a dynamic fact which can only be described 
and interpreted in dynamic terms, in terms of forces; and if 
you seek to analyze the phenomenon, to reduce it to constitu- 
ent processes, these again can only be conceived in terms of 
tendencies. 

The mechanist in psychology lightly postulates tendencies, 
determining tendencies, and implies that in so doing he is pro- 
viding a mechanical substitute for purposive tendencies and 

x ln this connection I refer the reader to Prof. A. W. Whitehead's 
newly published volume of Lowell Lectures, "Science and The 
Modern World." 



MEN 01 ROBOTS 305 

strivings. But, in so doing, he begs the whole question m dis- 
pute. He concedes the essence of the purposive psychologists, 
contention, the contention that human and animal behavior 
can be understood only in terms of tendencies towards ends of 
goals; and then he disguises the fact from himself by a mere 
change of names. 

Whether the present highly interesting and promising ten- 
dency in science to bridge the gap between the organic and the 
inorganic, between life and mechanism, by recognizing in the 
inorganic realms real tendencies, whether this tendency is 
destined to be successful we cannot yet say. But we can say, 
I think, that if it should prove successful, it will be by assimi- 
lating the inorganic to the organic and by recognizing the 
source of our understanding of processes and tendencies of 
all kinds in our own experiences of purposive striving, the 
most developed and intelligible form of that which we see 
more obscurely expressed in animal behavior and in the pro- 
cesses of the inorganic realm. 

We say, then, to our behaviorist friends Put aside your 
ill-founded fear of anthropomorphism. That fear is at the best, 
premature; and, at the worst, it may drive you far astray, 
seeking as your goal a mere will-o'-the-wisp. Do not continue 
to deny yourselves the great advantages of using the mentalist 
and purposive ways of thinking in your dealings with human 
and animal behavior. The anthropomorphic way of thinking 
is highly profitable at present in our sphere; and it may weU 
be that it will prove to be the ultimately profitable way for all 
science, the only way that leads to a deeper understanding of 
Nature. 

I conclude, then, that at present we stand to gain no advan- 
tage by assuming that men are Robots, mere pieces of ma- 
chinery. Without presuming to assert that men are, or are 
not, Robots, let us continue to use the working hypothesis that 
they are not; let us cheerfully go on assuming that men are 
what they seem to be, namely purposive intelligent agents, 
striving with some success to improve themselves and the 
conditions of their life in this strange world. And let us con- 
tinue to assume that children and animals exhibit in their 
lower degrees the same principles of action. For that is the 
profitable way, the way of progress in psychology. 



PARTY 

Reaction Psychology 




KNIGHT BUNLAP 



CHAPTER XIV 

THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY* 



By KNIGHT DUNLAP 



A discussion of "psychology" at the present time must, of 
necessity, be prefaced by a careful explanation of the signifi- 
cation in which the term is used; for this is an era of "psy- 
chologies," that is, of systems of philosophy, systems of medi- 
cine, systems of delusion and systems of graft, each of which 
assumes the title of "psychology" or of "the new Psychology." 
The announcement of a new book on The new psychology and 
the preacher might, so fas as anyone could predict in advance, 
be a treatise based on the Freudian or some other psychoana- 
lytic system; it might be an exposition of "new thought" or 
some other vagary of the Quimby brood; it might be an ap- 
plication of the theories and methods of "intelligence testing;" 
it might be propaganda for the doctrines and practices of M. 
Coue; it might be one of the numerous embodiments of 
phrenology under its more recent name of "character an- 
alysis;" it might be a book on psychic research concerning 
spooks and other magical notions; or it might be one of the 
less easily nameable nostrums which strut before the public in 
borrowed plumage, calling themselves "the new psychology/' 

In spite of all these phantasies, there is a serious and legi- 
timate psychology, which has had a steady growth and devel- 
opment, and which endures and bears fruit in spite of the 
vicissitudes to which it is subjected by all these pseudo-psy- 
chologies, which do, in fact, injure it and retard it, but which 
are not able to destroy it nor to prevent its growth. And it is 
this legitimate psychology, which, in its present day develop- 
ments, well merits the name of scientific psychology, that I am 
about to discuss. 

Psychology began in Hellenic days as a study of the con- 
scious processes of the organism, and it is today more ade- 
quately described in those terms than in any other way. It 
belongs, in other words, with the biological sciences, to two 
of which it is closely related, namely, to biology and anthro- 
pology. Biology deals with the fundamental features of the 
life processes as they appear in animals and plants; anthro- 
pology with the concrete results of the life processes in the 
human being ; and psychology with those important manifesta- 
tions of life in which consciousness appears. No one of these 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
April 20, 1925. 



310 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

three sciences includes the others ; but each of them necessarily 
overlaps and combines with the others. 

Each of these sciences deals with life from two aspects; 
those of growth and behavior. The particular aspects of ani- 
mal growth and behavior with which psychology is concerned 
are conscious behavior, and the growth or development of the 
systems of conscious reaction which constitute this conscious 
behavior. Psychology, like anthropology and biology, has 
therefore a threefold aspect: general, individual, and genetic; 
and it has another aspect which perhaps these others also pos- 
sess, namely: a social aspect In biology great progress has 
been made in the study of development. In psychology, how- 
ever, little progress ha's been made along the genetic line, and 
it is chiefly of general psychology that I shall speak today, 
not excluding references to progress in individual and social 
psychology. 

Whatever may have been the metaphysics of Aristotle on 
other points, in psychology his position is clear. He was to all 
intents and purposes a "common sense realist/* who assumed 
as one of the conditions of science, that there is a world of 
real objects and that we may be really conscious of them. On 
this basis, it was possible to ask the question: How does the 
process of perception come about? and the other question: 
How does that other conscious process, the process of think- 
ing about things, come about? And, Aristotle proceeded to 
discuss these questions in the light of such information as was 
then at hand. His discussions, furthermore, assumed these 
processes to be processes of the organism; and if he dragged 
in the theory of a psyche, that psyche was no mystical prin- 
ciple, but an energy supposed to reside in the organism; an 
energy as "physical" as the heat, light and electricity of mod- 
ern physics. It is true, Aristotle went beyond these practical 
assumptions, and contrived a theory of the relation of "mat- 
ter" and "energy" which was mathematical rather than em- 
pirical. But in that respect, his method was not far removed 
from those of modern mathematical physicists, however much 
he may have erred in his detailed hypotheses. In short : Aris- 
totle, in his psychology, was working along the lines of mod- 
ern scientific psychology, and this modern science may well 
be called a return to Aristotle, in spirit if not in detail. 

It is doubtful whether, aside from the invention of the name 
""psychology," any useful contributions were made to psy- 
chology during the first 1500 years of the Christian era. I 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 311 

say it is doubtful, because we have no clear knowledge of any 
such contributions. But the thought of the schoolmen is to- 
day pretty much a closed book to modern readers and will re- 
main closed until a lot of very bad Latin shall have been 
translated. Contributions, not evident to us, may have been 
made through Descartes and others who were instructed in the 
lore of the philosophers, and who read with ease the bad 
Latin to which I have referred. 

Descartes, who is rated as the first of the modern doctors 
of psychological theory, built up the subject with his right 
hand, while with his left hand, perhaps unintentionally, he 
pulled out the foundations, and gave the structure a decided 
list to the starboard, which it retained for a long period of 
further growth. In his Treatise on the passions of the soul 
he laid the cornerstone of physiological psychology, and for 
the modern reaction theory; although his particular reaction 
theory has been discarded. In his Discourse on Method, how- 
ever, and in his Principles, he weakened the common sense 
foundation of the subject and prepared the way for the perni- 
cious doctrines of psychophysical parallelism and epistemo- 
logical dualism which were immediately elaborated by Male- 
branche, from whom they were taken over by Locke, and 
which were the architectural plans for the development of psy- 
chology for the next three hundred years. These doctrines, in 
fact, in spite of Huxley and a number of other critics, became 
gradually adopted by the unscientific world as "common 
sense/* and have been accepted by the world of physical sci- 
ence as good psychology. At the present time, there is an 
enormous amount of routine teaching and perfectly futile 
teaching of this time-wcm philosophy under the guise of psy- 
chology; and the most difficult part of the teacher of scientific 
psychology is to disabuse the student of these notions, and to 
get him to look at the problems of psychology as they really 
are. We may put the simple facts of the mental life in sci- 
entific, (that is, in common sense,) form; but the student, 
trained in this now popular philosophy of Malebranche, mis- 
understands them in his old familiar terms, and hence fails to 
grasp the facts at all. More striking direct results of this 
Malebranchian miasma are the popularly attractive Freudian 
and other theories of the "unconscious mind/' and doctrines 
of certain schools of less popular psychology which fit in with 
the popular notion of the mind. 

The influence of Locke and his English successors was pro- 



312 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

foundly felt in Germany; and although the psychology of 
Herbart and Wundt was presumably founded in the philosophy 
of Leibnitz, derived from that of Descartes, the Malebranchian 
influence was really the strongest in the constructions of these 
and other German psychologists. The German psychology, 
again, influenced English psychology through Ward and Stout, 
uniting its influence with that transmitted from Locke through 
the Scottish school and was passed on to the United States 
through a number of psychologists of German training. I 
am justified, therefore, in calling this general current the "An- 
glo-German Psychology," a name which is sufficiently distinc- 
tive, and sufficiently representative of the real history of the 
current. But, lest my terms should seem to have an ethnologi- 
cal rather than the merely historical reference intended, I shall 
refer hereafter to this general school of psychological theory 
as Malebranchian, or introspectionaL 

The Malebranchian psychology is characterized toy, and 
limited by, a certain striking conception: the conception of the 
"mind" as something distinct from, but miraculously related 
to the body, and as made up out of certain objective elements, 
which, although in constant flux, are definitely observable. 
The mind, that is to say, is conceived as made up of psychic 
objects, and the physical world of physical objects, made of 
a different stuff or sort of material from the psychic object. 

The relation between the two worlds so conceived has been 
in the past assumed to be that of "parallelism," illustrated by 
the likeness to two clocks which keep time together, so that 
they correspond exactly, but with no influence of one on the 
other. The further question as to how the two docks get 
that way, has either been answered by assuming a divine 
clockmaker; or else the question has been simply ignored. 
There has been always, however, a minority group of psychol- 
ogists who have held the theory of interaction (which was 
Descartes' real theory), namely: that the two worlds do in- 
fluence one another, and that the correspondences may there- 
fore be explained causally. 

The discussion between the parallelists and the interaction- 
ists is now merely of historical interest, and a contribution on 
the subject would probably be rejected by any of the psycho- 
logical journals. I think we may safely say that the remain- 
ing psychologists of the introspectional school are theoretically 
parallelists, but practically interactionists ; and harmonize their 
theoretical and practical interests by avoiding the mention of 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 313 

the point at issue. The issue vanishes when the modern view- 
point is adopted. 

The general conception or presupposition of the Malebran- 
chian psychology involves several specific minor conceptions, 
namely: the non-observability of relations; the conception of 
ideas, sensations and images; and a characteristic conception 
of introspection. Since the issue between this older psychol- 
ogy and the later scientific psychology has turned on these 
specific conceptions, I shall briefly outline them. 

It may seem strange to say that relations are not observable, 
since the noting of relations is the most important detail in 
practical life. But we are forced to the conclusion that the 
older psychology considered them psychologically non-observ- 
able, at least, for the orthodox introspectional analysis of the 
"mind" gave only sensations, images, and feelings. Hence, 
while the sensational facts of the world were given abundant 
treatment in the psychological texts, no space was given to 
relations. If relations were considered, it was merely for the 
purpose of showing that they turned out to be, on examination, 
merely sensations; and not even sensations of a distinctive 
kind. On the other hand, since psychologists were compelled 
to talk somewhat rationally at times, the perceptibility of rela- 
tions was implied in the discussion of Weber's law, and in 
the comparison of pitches, colors and other sense-data. Per- 
haps the intention was to class relations with physical stimuli, 
which, although entirely different from sensations, were in a 
way implied as perceptible. This logical inconsistency, which 
was never straightened out, was based on an oversight of Male- 
branche's. Malebranche postulated a mental object for each 
physical object, but failed to provide a mental relation to cor- 
respond to a physical relation. And Malebranche's system 
was never remodeled. 

Malebranche, and Locke after him, assumed that man can 
never perceive anything except his own mind. Effectively, 
man was supposed to move in a little world of his own, for- 
ever out of perceptual contact, not only with his fellows, but 
with the physical world. What does he see? Nothing but his 
own color sensations. What does he hear? Nothing but his 
own sound sensations. Color, tone, and all the other sensuous 
qualities, are no features of the real world about us. They are 
merely parts of our own minds. Physical stimulations falling 
upon a physical nervous system have no mental nature at all, 
but, in some mysterious way, sensations in the mind are 



314 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

aroused, and then we can observe those sensations, Leibnitz, 
in his doctrine of monads, made this doctrine pictorially clear. 
To many physicists today, this metaphysical theory of four 
hundred years ago seems perfectly sound. 

The philosophers who constructed this remarkable theory- 
saw its obvious difficulty and went further. Man is forever 
shut off from the physical world, so far as knowledge is con- 
cerned: How, then, can we talk seriously about it? How can 
we talk about other persons? And they found the answer in 
faith in God. God must have made a "real" world, since we 
have our little worlds. Therefore, he must have made a real 
world to agree with our little one, or else he is a deceiver. 
But the later psychologists have dispensed with God, and kept 
the faith : a faith, therefore, in nothing whatever ! 

On this Malebranchian assumption we have a field for psy- 
chological study. Physics deals with the big, real world (how, 
has not been explained, since the physicist can no more per- 
ceive the physical world than can the psychologist), and the 
psychologist should busy himself about his little world, and 
try to analyse the objects therein. And in this psychic world, 
the introspectional psychologist found nothing but "sensa- 
tions," "images," "feelings," and various compounds of these. 
The study of perception, therefore, turned out to be a study of 
"sensations;" the study of thought and memory, a study of 
"images." 

We can manage with the concept of "sensations" very well, 
since we can apply that name to lie colors, sounds, tastes, and 
other sense data which we observe in the world, and can for- 
get the philosophical speculations on which the name is based. 
By the use of this concept, however, a serious cause of con- 
fusion was introduced, since the term "sensation" became slip- 
pery, meaning now the sense datum itself, now the process 
of observing the sense datum. But even that confusion might 
have been avoided. 

"Images" offer a serious difficulty. For the fact has been 
evident since the time of Aristotle that in thinking of some- 
thing, we are usually, (and perhaps always), being conscious 
of something which we perceived at some earlier time. But, 
according to Malebranche, we never perceive the thing: we 
observe only our "sensations" in the one case and our "im- 
ages" in the other. In what sense, therefore, can we say we 
are thinking of that which we perceived? Where is the iden- 
tity of the thing perceived and the thing thought of ? 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 315 

The answer is : the "image" must be the "sensation," in an- 
other form : changed somewhat, but essentially the same. The 
nature of the changes the "sensation" underwent in becoming 
an "image" was a point on which various conflicting views 
were held ; but the fundamental statement was the same on all 
these theories: the "image" is a reproduced "sensation." And 
the "idea," which is a complex of "images," is, of course, a 
reproduced percept the percept being the complex of "sen- 
sations" which the human observer foolishly assumes to be an 
object outside him. 

On this basis, the study of images and imagery occupied a 
considerable part of the older psychological work and their 
discussion occupied a considerable part of the psychological 
texts. It was even believed that the determination of imagery- 
types might be an important matter for pedagogy. But scep- 
tics, (of whom I happened to be one of the worst), appeared, 
and expressed doubts whether the "image" were anything but 
a confusion of terms. We recognize quite readily the facts 
called "sensations" when bits of colored papers are displayed, 
or a violin is bowed : and we recognize certain facts that might 
be called either "images" or "sensations" when the eyeball is 
pressed with the thumb, or an electric current passed through 
the region of the ear: but the reproduced "sensation" is an- 
other matter. Can such phenomena really be demonstrated? 
I came to the conclusion that they could not be. Others have 
come to the same conclusion. 

Now, it must be pointed out, that these sceptical persons, 
or many of them at least, before they considered the matter 
carefully, apparently had as vivid "images" as any of those 
who still held to the image-doctrine ; and, by the usual criteria, 
their imagery could be classified in the usual modal categories. 
I myself, under the sway of the doctrine originally taught me, 
had vivid and distinct visual and auditory "images," and "im- 
ages" of other modes also. It is not probable that my mere 
change of belief destroyed my "images." The change that oc- 
curred was in the critical analysis I made. What I find is, 
that in "haying" a visual "image," I am distinctly thinking of 
a visual object: that is, an object which, when I perceived it, 
had light and color. Hence, uncritically, I may still describe 
my experience as "having a visual image." This is a con- 
venient figure of speech, quite analogous to the speaking of 
"sunrise," which does not commit me to any theory as to the 
ultimate nature of the phenomenon. But there is in no sense 



316 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



"present" anything that could be considered a copy or repro- 
duction of the original object, whether I consider calling that 
object a "sensation" or a sense datum. I find also, (and many 
others have found the same), that when I am thinking of an 
object, such as an automobile, which has both visual and au- 
ditory aspects, it is sometimes impossible to decide, on the old 
basis, whether the imagery is visual or auditory. This is a 
striking fact, since it is not, in general, difficult to discriminate 
visual "sensations" from auditory "sensations." Moreover, I 
find that in such cases, modal characterization may be effected 
by actual muscular activities while thinking: that movements 
of the eyes may conduct to the characterization of the think- 
ing as "visual," while certain movements of the head, and con- 
tractions of the internal muscles of the ear, conduce to the 
characterization as "auditory," although the thinking is not 
essentially changed otherwise. From these and other con- 
siderations, the conclusion is not far that the "image," as de- 
scribed by the older psychology, is a myth ; that is, a name ap- 
plied to the fact that I think of objects of different modalities, 
just as the name "Zeus" or "Thor" applied to the fact that 
thunder and lightning occur. 

The discarding of the introspectional doctrine of "images" 
means the abandoning of the fundamental conception of the 
Malebranchian psychology; since without an "image" as an 
object ^ of thought-consciousness, the whole mental world, 
which is supposed to represent or parallel the real world,- goes 
to pieces. That the image has been discarded effectively in 
American psychology is no secret. The publication of re- 
search on imagery has sunk to a negligible stage, and although 
certain psychologists still talk in terms of "images," such dis- 
cussion is largely figurative. A clear indication of the situa- 
tion is given by the small space given to the discussion of 
"images" _in even those recent texts which officially follow the 
old doctrine. In fact, my own text gives more emphasis to 
"images" than do certain of those texts : a matter which has 
been extremely puzzling to the introspectionalists. But the 
most important indication of a change of viewpoint is the 
rapid development of the type of psychology which proceeds 
without reference to the philosophy on which the image-doc- 
trine was based. 

m 'Introspection," in the older psychology, meant the observa- 
tion of consciousness." But since "consciousness" has been 
very generally used in a double sense, this statement needs 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 317 

supplementation. "Consciousness" means, in popular parlance 
and in scientific usage also, the observing of something. In 
the Malebranchian psychology, it means the thing observed, 
which, in that psychology, could only be a "sensation," an 
"image," a "feeling," or a complex of these. It is true that 
all the older psychologists, and many today, use the term 
"consciousness" in both ways, and hence commit many logical 
fallacies, as well as heap up confusions; but when technically 
exact, the introspectional psychology has meant by "conscious- 
ness," the "sensations," "images" and "feelings" as they were 
defined, namely: as mental objects, to be observed (that is, 
"sentienda"). But, of course, these mental psychic objects 
were supposed to be observed; and that observation was 
called introspection. 

Now, it might be supposed, on the basis of the principles 
laid down, that introspection is the only sort of observation 
possible, since the only thing which can really be observed is 
"consciousness," that is, the complex of "sensations," "im- 
ages" and "ideas." Hence, the physicist would use introspec- 
tion in his work just as much as the psychologist does in his. 
At this point the Malebranchian psychology undeniably had 
difficulty, and became correspondingly vague. An early ten- 
dency was to admit external observation, as well as internal 
observation or introspection. Observing the physical world 
is external observation ; observing "consciousness" is introspec- 
tion. This admission was fatal, for if the direct observation 
of the physical world were possible without the intervention 
of psychical objects, then the whole construction of the world 
of "images" and "sensations" and "feelings" would be super- 
fluous, and the Malebranchian psychology would commit sui- 
cide. Those later psychologists of this school who were 
troubled by logical scruples, therefore defined "introspection" 
in another way. It is true, they said, that the physicist, just 
as much as the psychologist, observes "sensations." (We may 
omit consideration of "images" and "feelings" since they are 
not supposed to trouble the physicist.) But he observes them 
for a different purpose, namely, the purpose of constructing, 
or at least of referring to, the real (and by hypothesis imper- 
ceptible) external world. "Introspection," then, at least so 
far as it concerns "sensations," was assumed to differ from 
"external observation" in purpose only: not in the nature of 
the objects observed, nor in the nature of the observation 
itself. 



318 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

There have been, however, other views on the matter of 
introspection, aside from these orthodox ones I have described. 
Stout, for example, and a considerable following of his, have 
meant by "introspection" the direct observing of observing. 
Assuming, with the rest of the older school, that the things 
observed in ordinary observation are "sensations," "feelings/* 
and "images," they claimed that by a trick of the mind, the 
observing itself could be observed. For example : after having 
observed a "sensation of red," one could observe the preceding 
observation: this statement not meaning that one could ob- 
serve the red again, but meaning that one could observe that 
which was not, at the previous moment, an object, but was 
the observing of an object. The American School of introspec- 
tionists, however, have generally repudiated Stout's position, 
and have never insisted that observing could be observed. In 
fact, some of them have directly denied that possibility. 

The position of Stout and his followers is an important one, 
and it was against that position that I directed an early paper 
of mine. 1 Stout's position is not dependent on the Malebran- 
chian assumptions, and is upheld by certain present day phil- 
osophers who reject Malebranchism and all its works. Hence, 
this position is the really critical one, and the attack and de- 
fense can by no means be considered ended. 

While my own conclusion still is that consciousness, (by 
which I mean the fact or act of observing), cannot itself be 
observed, proof to the contrary would not in any wise upset 
any other conclusion of mine, nor change in any essential way 
the postulates of scientific psychology. 

"Introspection" as the observation of psychic objects: of 
"sensations," "images," and "feelings;" does not offer much 
interest in the way of discussion. It is a^simple terminological 
corollary from the general Malebr^ncfiian theory, and aside 
from that theory, merely . jneaas that when the psychologist 
makes an observation, it is to be called "introspection;" and 
when the physicist makes an observation perhaps an observa- 
tion of the same facts the psychologist has observed, it is to 
be called something else, such as "external observation." The 
only criticism I should make of this is that it involves the 

*The Case against introspection, 1912, Psychol. Rev., XIX, 404413. 
Tins was merely an introduction to another paper, The nature of 
perceived relations, 1912, Psychol. Rev., XIX, 415446; which was a 
thorough discussion of the fundamental 'points at issue 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 319 

waste of a perfectly good term, 2 which ought to be retained 
for another signification, in which, in our common language, 
we do use it. 

Introspection, as used in every-day language, means literally 
an inward vision: a paying attention to, or observing of the 
processes of the organism itself: the feelings, emotions, and 
organic processes of other kinds organic sensations, if you 
want to cling to that term ; and in scientific psychology we can 
most usefully employ the term in practically the same way; 
to signify the awareness of things inside the body; of feel- 
ings, emotions, organic changes, and muscular activities. 

I have so far emphasized the inadequacies of the Malbran- 
chian viewpoint in psychology in order to bring out, by con- 
trast, the characteristics of the modern science. On the other 
hand, it is necessary to point out the continuity of the modern 
developments with past progress. For it would be a mistake 
to assume that the scientific psychology of today is a new psy- 
chology. Along with the declining influence of the postulates 
of the Malebranchian metaphysics, there had been t for half 
a century, a steadily growing experimental psychology whose 
problems have been less and less formulated in relation to the 
old viewpoint, and whose interests have gradually been broad- 
ening. Many of the results of the early experimental work 
are invalidated by the postulates which are included in the 
data from which they were drawn, and many of the data are 
inadequate because of the bad planning of the work due to the 
philosophical postulates; but in both Germany and America 
these conditions steadily improved, and a psychology developed 
which was independent of the old philosophical bonds, while 
not formally disowning them. By 1900 an iconoclastic spirit 
was abroad; an impatience with the restriction of investiga- 
tion and interests to the examination of an artificial "mind" 
whose living prototype could not be found. The introduction 
of experimental methods into the study of animal behavior; 
the placing of the study of children on the basis of conscious 
behavior by Binet and Ebbinghaus ; and the rise of interest in 
social psychology; all contributed to the growing tendency of 
psychology to return to Aristotle and face its problem clearly 
as the problem how we perceive, how we think, how we act, 



"In another form of this criticism, I would point out that, the 
assigning of "introspection" as the distinctive method of the psy- 
chologist is a needless circle of terms, if "introspection" is defined 
as merely the method the psychologist uses. 



320 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

how we feel ; instead of the old substitute problem of what we 
perceive, what we think of, and what we feel ; that is, the old 
analysis of a world of "mental objects." Into this growing 
movement the notion of mental activity as dependent _on, or 
a part of, not mere action of brain cells, but on reaction, or 
complete sensori-motor response; a notion whose origins and 
mode of percolation into psychological thought are still ob- 
scure; entered as the great synthetizing factor, and the be- 
ginnings of scientific psychology were in existence. This syn- 
thesis was made possible by the new conception of the think- 
ing process, first suggested by Max Muller, as dependent on 
motor activities; a conception which has now become funda- 
mental in scientific psychology. 3 

The result of these changes was apparently a lessening of 
the emphasis on consciousness; but it was also an increase in 
the emphasis on consciousness. Consciousness in the Male- 
branchian sense, (mental objects or mental data or mental 
stuff) ceased to interest psychologists; and consciousness as 
the process of observing anything whatever; that awareness 
which the older psychologists, even James, had refused to ad- 
mit to psychology, came to its own. It is true, the psycho- 
analysts have temporarily salvaged the Malebranchian con- 
sciousness from the junk heap, and by a continuation of the 
confusion of the two meanings of the word, have continued 
Janet's repudiated invention of "unconscious consciousness." 
But even this revamped form of the old and rusty materials 



*My own pioneering work in the introduction of this conception 
into the fundamentals of psychology may be traced in Images and 
Ideas, Johns Hopkins Circular, 1914, no. 3, pp. 2541 (reprinted in 
part in the Biological Basis of the Association of Ideas, Psycho- 
biology, 1920, vol. ii, pp. 29-53) ; An Outline of Psychobiology, 1st edi- 
dition, 1914, The Johns Hopkins Press, chapter IX, p. Ill; Thought 
Content and Feeling, Psychological Review, 1916, vol. xxiii, pp. 49- 
70; and Elements of Scientific Psychology, 1922, the C. V. Mosby Co., 
chaps, x and xiv. While I had really committed myself to the gen- 
eral position in my System of Psychology, 1912, Charles Scribners 
Sons, by my treatment of ideas and images, I had not then broken 
away from the concept of "brain states" as the basis of conscious- 
ness, nor from the old doctrine of perception as involving imagina- 
tion, (which is not the same as images). 

The conception was of necessity adopted by the behaviorists, and 
has been of late unduly exaggerated by practically limiting the 
thought-reaction to the language-reaction, and by assuming that 
complete reaction is in all cases necessary for thought: neither of 
these assumptions is as yet justified. 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 321 

is breaking down, and the spread of the more scientific doc- 
trine is rapidly progressing. 

It was not to be expected that this transformation, rapid as 
it has been, should have been consummated without some off- 
shoots of a radical sort. The re-emphasis on the study of be- 
havior as the fundamental method of psychology, together 
with the ejection of consciousness in its Malebranchian mean- 
ing, furnished a starting point for behaviorism, which proposed 
to reduce psychology to mere physical anthropology. But the 
study of behavior is as old as Aristotle, and the only novelty 
in behaviorism was what it omitted in its experimental meth- 
ods ; not what it retained. By successive steps to which it has 
been forced, behaviorism has returned from its meteoric flight, 
and now differs only verbally from the more conservative 
schools of psychology, and in the difficulties its verbal inhibi- 
tions inflict upon it. In fact, only the acute psychologist can 
distinguish the behaviorist from the non-behaviorist in these 
days, except by the labels affixed ; and the truth is that some 
who have labeled themselves have mistaken their own labels. 
Behaviorism was, a few years ago, a distinctive movement, 
with unique theories and methods. But it has found itself 
constrained to abandon its distinctive methods, and its theories, 
in so far as these are distinctive, are distinctive in terminology 
only. 

We turn now from the survey of the recent past to the 
consideration of the psychology of today. We have indicated 
already some of its characteristics, among which the most im- 
portant is the adherence to the view of the organism as a re- 
sponse mechanism, and the assimilation of the conscious re- 
sponses to the other responses. This is, in fact, a simplifica- 
tion, rather than an addition, for we have long known that 
the organism, whatever else it might be, is a response mechan- 
ism, and is primarily that. What we have done is merely to 
extend this necessary biological conception to the psychologi- 
cal field, displacing there the additional hypotheses which had 
in the past seemed requisite additions. In other words, we 
have made one well developed hypothesis to grow where sev- 
eral unnecessary ones grew before. This simplification has 
meant, among other things, a definite break with the phreno- 
logical conceptions of brain function which ruled physiologi- 
cal psychology for so long a time, and which the work of Marie 
and the work of Franz showed to be so inadequate. 

The laws of habit, and the laws of heredity have conse- 



322 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

quently been extended from the biological field to the psycho- 
logical. This extension has been the easier because the most 
anciently known laws of habit, the laws of the association of 
ideas, so-called, were discovered in the psychological field. 
But with this extension, the problems of mental habit have 
been vastly simplified, and the knowledge of mental operations 
have been greatly extended. .-Ontogenetic psychology has be- 
come a possibility; and phylogenetic psychology will also be 
possible when the subject of genetics has reached a more stable 
ground. 

Another biological concept, specifically a physiological no- 
tion, has also been extended to the psychological field as a 
necessary consequence of the response hypothesis ; the concep- 
tion of integration, which is so intimate a part of the modern 
concepSoh of Kafeit and learning. With the conception of in- 
tegration, the tendency to look upon the reaction pathways (or 
arcs) as simple and distinct elements in the neural mechanism, 
has vanished. The conception of reflexes as merely one variety 
of reaction, differing from the more complicated responses 
only in degree; and of the "pure reflex" as only an analytic 
fiction, non-existent in the normal human animal, although 
obtainable under abnormal conditions, has been a necessary 
consequence of the integration conception, and has eliminated 
a great deal of troublesome theory which had been built up 
concerning the relation of reflex action to random action, to 
impulsive action, and to instinctive tendencies. 

With the simpler conception of the relation of so-called re- 
flexes and more complicated reactions, new problems open up. 
It is no longer possible to "explain" instinctive or hereditary 
reaction tendencies by referring them to a "chain of reflexes" 
or even by contrasting them sharply with reflexes. All reac- 
tion now seems to be of the same essential type, within which 
the most important variation is in degree of integration. 
Other variations are too numerous to permit of any simple 
classification on this basis. The problem of the interrelation 
of heredity and environment, nature and nurture, instinct and 
habit, endowment and acquisition, concerns action generally, 
and perception and thought as well. The older and simpler 
solution of this problem, by reference to "instincts" has gone 
by the board, and in its place we have the growing hypothesis 
that all action is inherited, and all is acquired; that heredity 
can no longer be contrasted with environment, but that neither 
has any significance except in terms of the other. It is no 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 323 

longer possible to settle the question as to the future of war 
by saying that man has a hereditary "pugnacious tendency/' 
or "tendency to conflict." We have to inquire first what this 
tendency, which may be described as pugnacious in one envir- 
onmental condition, will be in other environmental conditions. 
Psychology today bases its conceptions of hereditary tenden- 
cies squarely on the biologists' conception of a tendency to 
react to one stimulus pattern in one way, and to other stimulus 
patterns in other ways; that is, not as an independent action 
tendency, but as a response tendency. And we include in the 
conception of a hereditary tendency a great deal of that which 
we also call "habit." That is to say, a tendency to react to a 
certain stimulus pattern in a certain way, is, at the same time, 
a tendency to react to that pattern in a quite different way 
after a certain other series of reactions have occurred. If we 
dub the new-born calf's tendency to suck the cow's nipple or 
suck your finger, as "instinctive" or "hereditary;" then we 
must also dub as "instinctive" his tendency to drink milk out 
of a pail; a tendency which he "acquires" through the reac- 
tions of sucking your fingers when you have immersed them 
and his nose in the milk. 

The factors which have contributed to this great and rapid 
change in the conception of instinct and habit, aside from the 
fundamental response hypothesis, into harmony with which 
the conceptions have been brought, have been the growing 
comprehension of the arbitrariness and unworkableness of the 
old "instinct" doctrine, and the realization of the fact that if 
the doctrine of the inheritance of complicated reaction tenden- 
cies, in magic independence of habit formation, were really 
true, there would be reason to suspect the inheritance of think- 
ing tendencies too; since the thinking tendencies are reaction 
tendencies also, and probably not a whit more complicated than 
the other reaction tendencies which are included under the 
old category of "instincts." Thus, the Lockian doctrine of 
no innate ideas would go by the board, along with the schol- 
astic doctrine: nihil est in intellects, quod non fuerit prius in 
sensu, which psychology has heretofore so completely accepted. 

The most gratifying result of all these changes has been a 
renewed enthusiasm for experimental research on the prob- 
lems of mental heredity, including research on the problem 
raised by Preyer long ago, and later ignored ; the problem of 
the behavior of the embryo in utero. The old notion that we 
can accept the animal at the moment of birth as a machine 



324 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

prepared entirely through heredity ; and assume that the opera- 
tion of the laws of habit-formation begins to operate only 
then, has passed away along with other arbitrary and useless 
assumptions. 

Another problem on which experimentation has hardly be- 
gun, but on which we may definitely expect searching investi- 
gation, is the problem of the relative modifiability of the in- 
tegratively different grades of reaction. "It was assumed once 
on a time that there are reflexes which are unmodifiable by the 
process of habit formation as ordinarily conceived. Now, 
however, there is a tendency to assume that these reflexes are 
relatively easily modifiable. But it is admitted that the evi- 
dence so far is rather naive and inconclusive ; and the question 
of the relative modifiability of so-called reflexes looms as one 
of the most important questions bearing on the whole theory 
of reactions. 

One highly important feature of modern scientific psychol- 
ogy is the emphasis on patterns. This emphasis is the "result 
of many influences, ancTITTs "Impossible to ascribe it to- any 
single author or any single preceding development. But it is 
an emphasis which would naturally be produced by the con- 
ception of integration, and the development of this emphasis 
has been, as a matter of fact, a detail in the development of the 
integration concept. 

James, over thirty years ago, warned us against the treat- 
ment of analytical details as actually isolable facts, and the 
more scientific treatment he recommended has gradually pre- 
vailed. But with the change of psychology from a philoso- 
phical to a biological basis, the tendency to treat the analyti- 
cally discernible reaction pathways as separable elements in 
the response mechanism asserted itself, and the tendency to 
treat of ^ stimuli as if some restricted detail of stimulation 
could of itself bring about this or that specific reaction, was car- 
ried over from the earlier psychology. The conceptions of re- 
flexes, in particular, as separable elements in the total re- 
sponses was one manifestation of this psychological attitude. 
The conception of instincts as central forces or plural psyches, 
harmonizing and controlling these assumed individual reaction 
tendencies, was another manifestation. 

The consideration of action as an effective force in the 
world, however^ calls "attention to the -enormous significance 
of pattern, that is, to the interrelationship, temporally and spa- 
tially, of the analytically discriminable details of animal acts. 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 325 

The fact that seemingly slight changes in the relationships of 
details may change the practical effects of the whole act is un- 
deniable. A thousand details may be rightly related, but a 
single detail out of the right relationship may ruin the effect. 
Obviously, the temporal pattern, or succession of details, is 
at least as important as the spatial pattern at any moment. 

At the other end of the response, the efficacy of stimulation 
is equally dependent upon pattern. No one reacts to single 
stimuli, and the analytically distinct detail, such as a descrip- 
tively single color stimulus, or single note, may produce, at 
different times, quite different reactions, depending upon the 
concurrent and preceding stimulation. Or, rather, these ana- 
lytical details do not produce the reactions ; they are mere de- 
tails in a total stimulus pattern which, and which only, can be 
said to initiate the reaction. 

Between this stimulus pattern and the resulting action pat- 
tern, there is, of course, a neural pattern which is different 
for each response which differs in action pattern or in stimulus 
pattern from any other response. Given a stimulus pattern, 
the action pattern ultimately resulting must be dependent on 
the neural pattern, or transit pattern evoked. The formation 
of habits is, therefore, essentially the formation of tendencies 
to integrate the nervous transit activities into certain transit 
patterns. In the conscious reactions, the type of conscious 
process depends on the type of transit pattern, and not on 
mere spatial pattern of brain cell function, as older theories 
assumed. On this basis, the ontogenetic development of per- 
ception is understandable as a building up of reaction patterns 
so that eventually certain stimulus patterns, or stimulus pat- 
terns of a certain type, come to produce more and more speci- 
fic reaction patterns; and these patterns take on progressively 
more useful forms, so that the actions and the perceptions in- 
volved in them become better and better adapted to the en- 
vironment. We can see also the reason for the resemblance 
between the thinking process and the perceiving process; and 
also the difference between them. If thinking does depend on 
previous perception, perception must have built up patterns of 
reaction to external stimuli, and the terminal action patterns 
are partially repeated later to internal stimuli. But since the 
stimulus patterns in the two cases are different, the neural 
patterns are different in spite of the partial identity of the ac- 
tion patterns. Briefly, we can say that the greater or less 
identity of the perception of anything- and the subsequent 



326 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

thinking of the same thing lies in the greater or less identity 
of the terminal acts of the two reactions; and that the essen- 
tial difference between the two processes lies in the difference 
in the stimulation patterns. 

_Attention, once a formidable problem for psychology, so 
formidable that it was generally erected into a separate "fac- 
ulty" of the mind, (the usual way of disposing of something 
wluch can not be taken into the general explanatory system), 
is still a problem. But it is a problem of patterns of integra- 
tion and future solutions are to be worked out on that basis. 

The perception of relations was too hard a nut to crack 
for the Malebranchian psychology, as I have earlier pointed 
out. But for the modern scientific psychology it is just one 
nut among the others, all of which are to be gradually un- 
shelled together. In the little world of mental objects, there 
were no mental objects provided to represent the actual re- 
lations between objects in the big real world. Furthermore, 
in the phrenological system of the brain there were no "cen- 
ters" for relations as there were for "sensations/' Hence, 
there was nothing for psychology to do but to soft-pedal the 
problem of relations and the perception of relations. In mod- 
ern psychology, however, we have no microcosmic mental 
world to deal with, and in our psychobiology we have no brain 
"centers" for the production of mythical mental objects. Re- 
lations between external objects we do perceive; and having 
perceived them, we think of them. That which we perceive is 
always a pattern, in which relations are always involved; and 
the selective emphasis on these, or attention to these is a mat- 
ter of differential integration of the responses, just as is the 
attention to this or that sense datum. The problems concern- 
ing the perception of relation are, therefore, no different from 
the problems of perceiving sense data, and in so far as the 
problems of one group is solved the others are ipso facto 
solved. 

In what I have called scientific psychology, there can be no 
reasonable doubt that we have come to a permanent basis for 
psychology. By permanent, I do not, of course, mean perfect 
or final. If the science does not die, there must always be pro- 
gressive improvement in its fundamental conception. But no 
science can be considered established until it has a basis which 
is permanent in the sense that whatever further is added, it 
will remain* Chemistry became an established science with 
the adoption of the atomic hypothesis, and although the ion 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 327 

and electron theories, and the discoveries of radio activity and 
of the transformation of elements have vastly extended the 
basis o-f the science, and entirely reinterpreted the atomic hy- 
pothesis, the hypothesis has not really been superseded. Cer- 
tain notions as to its finality and sufficiency have been swept 
away, but in so far as the atomic hypothesis was a useful basis, 
it still endures. Comparing the atomic hypothesis in chemistry 
and the Copernican theory in astronomy with the reaction hy- 
pothesis in psychology shows significant likenesses in the rela- 
tions of the three hypotheses to the subject matter of the three 
sciences in the stage at which they have been introduced. Com- 
prehensive in their scope, leaving nothing out to be a skeleton 
in the closet; simplifying what previously was excessively 
complicated ; and enormously fertile in regard to further work, 
these hypotheses are foundations of sciences. 

With the responses hypothesis as the basis, the future of 
experimental psychology is bright. We have our popular psy- 
chologists to combat; but the chemists had their alchemists 
and the astronomers had their astrologers. Perhaps, if we 
devote ourselves to research as industriously as have the as- 
tronomers and the chemists, our character analysts, psycho- 
analysts and other pseudo-psychologists will be reduced to the 
same innocuous condition. 

Of course, there are many philosophical questions left un- 
solved by the present psychological position, and the progress 
of scientific psychology has been rather around them than 
through them. If I am asked by an acute philosopher: How 
can you assume the occurrence of consciousness, if you do 
not assume that consciousness is observable? I have to reply: 
Well, why not? Consciousness seems to be a fact, and the 
assumption that it isn't a fact destroys not only psychology 
but physical science. For it is futile for the physicist to- pres- 
ent his observation if he assumes that he hasn't made any ob- 
servations. On the other hand, I don't think I can observe con- 
sciousness; consciousness seems to be always the observing of 
something. If you can prove that consciousness can be ob- 
served, then I will accept the proof ; but I can't see that that 
would make any difference in my psychology otherwise. In the 
meantime, therefore, psychology need not worry over the ques- 
tion. 

Furthermore, the ancient epistemological question may still 
be brought up. I may be asked by the same acute philosopher: 
How can you possibly observe something outside your mind? 



328 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

And, again I should answer, Why not? It would seem to me 
just as difficult to explain how I can observe something inside 
my mind; and I prefer to let the metaphysical question rest, 
and stand on the fact that something is observed, a^id that it 
frequently is something which is also called the outside world. 
Further, I should point out that the creation of an internal 
world to represent the external doesn't solve the problem, for 
the question remains in the form : How do we get from this 
microcosm to the macrocosm we are after? 

Perhaps the one philosophical question which does directly 
concern the psychologist's work is the question as to the re- 
lation between perceived objects and stimuli. For the prac- 
tical development of psychological work, even this question 
is no obstacle, but the psychologist, like all other men, likes to 
have his logical problems ironed out, even if those problems 
do not have a practical bearing on his work. The dualistic 
hypothesis did not solve this problem, although it was pre- 
cisely the problem that epistemological dualism has contrived 
to solve. While I have my own solution which is quite satis- 
factory to me, and which is precisely the solution to which 
many physical scientists have come, the matter is so far enough 
detached from the main business of psychology that it is not 
advisable to drag it into the present discourse. 

The philosophical conflict between mechanism and vitalism 
interests certain psychologists intensely today, but I cannot 
help feeling that however interesting the problem may be to 
them personally, it is of no concern to their psychology. The 
practical solution of this problem is attributed to Lotze, and 
that solution, although philosophically comic, is really a formu- 
lation of a useful practical attitude. Lotze, I believe, taught 
that before a decision between two alternative courses of ac- 
tion is made, we should regard the future act as free, that 
is, undetermined; but that in looking back on it, we should 
regard the course taken as having been rigidly determined. 

There is, in short, no conflict between the mechanism which 
as scientists we all assume, whatever our speculative views, 
and the effectiveness of purposes which likewise we all as* 
sume. What may be the limits of mechanism, and what the 
limits of purposive effects, is another matter which, it is pos- 
sible, will some day be of importance to both psychological 
and physical science, but whose importance is not yet evident. 
Tills question, too, we can wisely leave to the philosophers, 



THE THEORETICAL ASPECT OF PSYCHOLOGY 329 

although among the philosophers we may include ourselves in 
our leisure moments. 

In conclusion, I should like to emphasize again the contin- 
uity of psychological progress, and the indebtedness of the 
viewpoints that seem revolutionary to the viewpoints they 
supplant. Many, perhaps all, of the positions which we have 
had to revise have been positions which were true in some fun- 
damental respect, and we have merely made use of them in 
revised and reinterpreted forms. It is clear that the psycholo- 
gist has to deal with a world of private content, with which 
the natural sciences have no dealings directly, just as the Male- 
branchians assumed. But this world is not the sort of a world 
they believed it to be. It is merely the world of our own 
bodies, which we perceive through kinesthesis and organic 
sensitivity (including feelings and emotions), and which no 
one else can perceive in that way. This bodily world is the 
world of actual introspection. Many other conceptions of sci- 
entific psychology are reinterpretations of older viewpoints, or 
directly derived from them. But important as is that which is 
passed on from previous generations, that which is added by 
succeeding generations is equally important. The way to our 
present conclusion has been prepared and made plain by the 
labor of those who by no means have always agreed to the 
conclusions to which they have contributed. Acknowledging 
our indebtedness to them, we cannot but regret that they are 
sometimes unwilling to consummate their work by advancing 
with us. And very probably the next generation will be mak- 
ing the same remark about many o>f us. 



CHAPTER XV 

THE EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF 
PSYCHOLOGY* 



BY KNIGHT DUNLAP 



Psychology, in its period of transformation, had apparently 
an experimental method all its own ; the so-called introspective 
method, which was contrasted with the method of the physical 
sciences. With the development of psychology into a science 
on what appears to be a permanent basis, this methodological 
distinction has passed away. Introspection in the sense of 
observation of one's own bodily processes remains as a neces- 
sary part of experimental method; but, like the observation 
of external things, it is ruled by more general experimental 
methods and technique. It might seem, therefore, that the 
methods of psychology are simply those of natural science in 
general, and differ from those of biology, chemistry, and 
physics only in the same way in which the methods of each 
of these sciences differ from those of the others. It is, of 
course, obvious that although the methods of science may be 
general, and apply to all sciences alike, neverthless they are 
also particular; and the applications of the general methods 
in the different sciences will be determined by the specific 
problems of those sciences. 

To a large extent, this conclusion is justified. The funda- 
mental principles of scientific method which rigidly control 
the physical sciences, control also experimental psychology; 
and no procedure which does not conform to those general 
principles is either justifiable or worthy of consideration in 
psychology. 1 

Obviously, the application of methods and the forms of 
technique are different in individual psychology as dis- 
tinguished from general psychology. Animal psychology has 
its own special techniques, as it has its specific problems. Ab- 
normal psychology and child psychology also have their highly 
specialized methods or techniques, and the psychologist trained 
in only one of these various fields is not prepared to enter an- 
other until he has become familiar with its peculiar problems 
and difficulties and mastered its techniques. 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
April 21, 1925. 

*The variations in method which are necessary in psychology may 
well be described as variations in technique rather than in method; 
but the delimitation of terms in this precise logical way is not 
essential 



332 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

The fundamental scientific methods of psychology are four- 
fold. They require, first: the recognition of all data as oc- 
curring in situations which are describable as observations. 
That is, its fundamental data are data to consciousness. Data 
which are not observed data are not data for experimentation. 
The essential starting point, therefore, for psychological ex- 
periment includes the acknowledgment of consciousness, and 
of something of which the consciousness is. 

Second: the methods require the formation of competent 
hypotheses derived either from previous experimental work 
or from less formal observations. Without hypotheses, ex- 
perimentation is impossible. The competence of the hypotheses 
depends both on their adaptability for experimental test, and 
their vital relation to further hypotheses or to applications. 
Hypotheses are useless unless they are competent. 

Third: the hypotheses must be subjected to test, to deter- 
mine their truth or falsity. Experimentation, in effect, is 
just the subjection of hypotheses to crucial test, and no other 
procedure is called by that name. Although the great mass 
of technical procedure centers about the performance of the 
test, the test itself is no more vital to experimental work than 
the formulation of the hypotheses to be tested. Both are re- 
quisite, and defects in either may be equally fatal. 

Fourth: The proof established by the test must have a 
specific form, namely, repeatability. The issue of the experi- 
ment must be a statement of the hypothesis, the conditions of 
test, and the results, in such form that another experimenter, 
from the description alone, may be able to repeat the ex- 
periment. Nothing is accepted as proof, in psychology or in 
any other science, which does not conform to this requirement. 
The psychologist must carefully consider these principles 
of method and view each special technique and application in 
their light, until they become a part of his habitual method 
of thought. Only then can he be certain of not applying his 
time and energy wastefully and of not being caught in eddies 
and back-currents of experimentation from which there is no 
progressive issue. What I have to say in the following dis- 
course will, therefore, center about these four fundamentals 
of scientific method, although I shall not attempt to develop 
these four principles in a discreet systematic way. 

The field of psychology, however, is so broad that it can- 
not be said that in all of its extensions the principles of na- 
tural science are its sufficient chart and guide, although in 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 333 

every province of psychology they are valid and necessary. 
There is, undoubtedly, a field of educational psychology which 
will some day be cultivated, and in which already a few slight 
beginnings have been made. The name, indeed, has long been 
familiar, but has so far been almost altogether applied to those 
fragments of general and individual psychology which depart- 
ments of education have chosen to take over into their cur- 
ricula; and the fragments have not, so far, been selectively 
restricted to any particular part of psychology, but cover 
broadly the whole field. 

An examination of the courses offered under the name of 
"educational psychology" in colleges and universities through- 
out the United States shows the interesting fact that some of 
these courses contain one group of psychological topics, some 
another; and frequently when two courses are compared it 
will be found that neither contains anything that the other 
contains. Altogether, these courses scatter over the entire 
field of psychology, although since the introduction of intelli- 
gence tests the courses in educational psychology tend more 
and more to that topic, and many courses contain nothing but 
a routine training in the scoring of intelligence tests. In the 
field of research the same condition obtains. Practically, all 
of the research articles found in the journals and monographs 
of educational psychology are, in their scope and topics, such 
as are common in general and individual psychology. 

Yet, a real educational psychology will be developed, and 
when it is, its methods may be somewhat different from those 
of the general science. The newly developed subject of social 
psychology is manifestly waiting for the development of ex- 
perimental methods of its own, and some of them may be 
available for educational psychology. Whether racial psy- 
chology, when it appears, will have its methods, will deter- 
mine the possibility of racial psychology being experimental; 
but in any event, the experimental method of the general sci- 
ence will probably not be sufficient in this field either. 

For the present, our greatest concern is with the experi- 
mental methods of general psychology, not only because they 
are fundamental, but also because for all of the special fields 
of psychology the greatest need is for the application of ex- 
perimental results from the general field. This is the case, 
for example, in the psychology of religion, where the inter- 
pretation of the data of ancient and savage peoples is, of 
course, impossible of direct experimental approach, but de- 



334 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

pends for its interpretation on the experimental data which 
may be brought to it. 

The rapid transformation of psychology in the early part 
of the 19th century, in its successful attempt to become ex- 
perimental led to the application to its data of ^certain mathe- 
matical methods taken over directly from physics, and astron- 
omy, and which are quite appropriate to physical science, and 
fruitful therein. These mathematical methods are based on 
the method of least squares as applied to the theory of proba- 
bility of errors in observation and chance variations of other 
sorts ; and assume as fundamental the distribution of measure- 
ments which are subject to "chance" variation solely, in a 
form which can be represented by a symmetrical curve which 
has a definite equation, known as the Gaussian curve, or curve 
of error. Or more accurately: the distribution approximates 
the form of the Gaussian curve in proportion as the number 
of measurements increases, and in proportion as the errors 
due to other than what is called "chance" are eliminated. 
For this reason, the Gaussian curve is called the "normal 
curve" and distributions are said to be "normal" in so far 
as they approximate reasonably close to the Gaussian form. 
For the sake of clearness, I shall throughout the following 
discussion designate the statistical method which depends upon 
the method of least squares as the higher statistical method, 
(by analogy with the term "higher mathematics"), and cer- 
tain other statistical methods not depending on Gaussian pos- 
tulates as the simpler statistical methods. 

It seemed to many of the nineteenth century psychologists 
that if the higher mathematical methods, which are useful in 
physical science, could be applied to psychological data, psy- 
chology would ipso facto become a science. The methods had 
been developed in the first place with regard to errors of ob- 
servation, and are used in physics today, primarily to correct 
for errors in observation. Psychology deals primarily with 
observations; and if the variations in observation could be 
considered as "errors" or chance variations from a true meas- 
ure, the physicist's methods should be directly applicable. 

In that period of psychology, threshold observations and 
threshold determinations played a relatively more prominent 
part than they do today; so that it is but natural that the first 
application of the higher statistical method should have been 
to the technique of determining thresholds. This application 
reached its heights in the "Method of Rierht and Wron? Cases" 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 335 

which occupies a prominent place in the literature of the latter 
quarter of the 19th century. By mathematical calculation, 
tables were prepared by which thresholds were computed with 
great mathematical exactness from relatively few observa- 
tions. The practical procedure amounted to this: from data 
obtained by presenting only one, or only a few, stimulus dif- 
ferences, a prediction was made as to what would have hap- 
pened if a larger series of differences had been presented for 
observation: and this prediction was named the "threshold." 

Fortunately, this practice of giving crude, and often few, 
data a refined mathematical treatment has practically passed 
from experimental psychology. In fact, what many students 
today learn as the "Method of Right and Wrong Cases" is an 
absolutely different and far simpler method than the original 
one to which I refer. 

The most unfortunate assumption involved in the mathe- 
matical threshold methods, was the assumption that the 
"threshold" is a fixed and definite value, and that the diverse 
readings obtained in a properly designed series of measure- 
ments are of the nature of "errors" or chance variations from 
the true value which should have been obtained, whereas, as 
a matter of fact, each of these is as true a threshold as any 
other. This assumption is embodied in a different form in 
the assumption that the normal curve of distribution of psy- 
chological data, (judgments of difference, in this case), is a 
"normal" curve in the Gaussian sense; and that the distinctly 
different forms actually obtained for certain types of data are 
variations from the true form, and can be corrected for. As 
a matter of fact, we know that the really normal distribu- 
tions for many sorts of psychological data are far from Gaus- 
sian; and that in these cases an approximation to the Gaus- 
sian form would be direct evidence of either gross experi- 
mental error, or unjustifiable statistical juggling. 

The most serious practical effect of the mathematical method 
was a lessening of the emphasis on the value of the data itself. 
Not only were refined calculations made from data too few to 
be a basis for the simplest mathematical treatment, but the 
data often were obtained under conditions of planning and 
execution of the work which were seriously inadequate. Why 
this effect should have been produced may not be entirely 
clear, but it manifestly was produced; and with the abandon- 
ment of the higher statistical method has come about' a great 
improvement in other respects, principally an increased em- 



336 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

phasis on the reliability of the data itself, and increased care 
in disposing the experimental work to the end of securing 
data of the maximal quality and adequate quantity. The fun- 
damental difficulties in the way of the application of the higher 
statistical method to psychological data may be illustrated from 
reaction-time measurements. Here the normal distribution is 
distinctly skewed, that is, it is not "normal" at all in the ar- 
bitrary Gaussian meaning of the term. Actually, the proba- 
bility of a positive deviation from the median is greater than 
the probability of an equal negative deviation, and there is 
no probable error of the distribution, but two measures which 
might be called probable errors, namely: the median deviation 
above the average and the median deviation below the aver- 
age. No calculations based on the formula of the Gaussian 
curve can be made, therefore, unless the difference in the 
probabilities of the positive and negative deviations can be ac- 
curately computed and corresponding corrections introduced 
in the formulae. Theoretically, this might be done for a given 
collection of data. But the data required for the purpose 
would be so copious that there would be no gain in the appli- 
cation of the higher statistical methods, since the results there- 
of, in so far as valid, would have been already obtained. 

But there is still another difficulty which cannot be over- 
come even in theory. The physical applications of the higher 
statistical methods depend on the assumption that the con- 
ditions of measurement are throughout the same except for 
the so-called chance variations, that is, the variations which 
in the long run follow the Gaussian law of error. That which 
is measured is assumed to have a fixed value, which is inde- 
pendent of the measurements, and is not affected by the meas- 
uring process. The length of a bar of steel, for example, at 
a constant temperature, is assumed to be a fixed definite quan- 
tity, and the measurements which the physicist makes are as- 
sumed not to affect this length, which is therefore the same 
throughout the series of measurements. But in psychological 
measurements the conditions are quite different. That which 
is measured in the reaction time experiment, for example, is 
not a fixed quantity, but a variable, and the measurements 
themselves affect its magnitude. If we obtain a hundred re- 
actions from a given reactor under external conditions as 
usual as possible, the last measurements differ from the first 
not merely by chance errors of measurement, but also because 
that which is measured is itself different. In other words, 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 337 

practice effects are involved, and practice effects continue to 
manifest themselves even after thousands of reactions have 
been made. Theoretically, the law of practice effects for a 
given subject under constant conditions might be computed, 
and correction made for this: practically, no such corrections 
would be useful. The higher statistical methods would at this 
point become so "high" that they would be unwieldy. 

The fact is, that after habituation, the reactions become 
changed in complex ways, involving not only habit formation, 
but changes in attitudes of the reactor. If we are interested 
in the type of reactions made in ordinary life, we do not get 
these after long mechanical practice in a fixed condition. The 
representative values obtained from higher mathematical treat- 
ment of series of reaction times are no more significant at best 
than the results of the simpler treatment which experimental 
psychology gives them; and they may be entirely misleading. 
Similar conclusions obtain for almost all the data of experi- 
mental psychology. 

At the present time, experimental psychology tends to em- 
ploy no mathematical methods in the treatment of data beyond 
simple addition, subtraction and division. In this respect, at 
least, experimental psychology is distinguished from educa- 
tional psychology and mental measurements. Averages, medi- 
ans, and modes as representatives of series of measurements; 
and mean variations and percentage variations as measures 
of variation from these representative values, have been es- 
tablished, or are at least accepted, as practically useful and 
justifiable. 1 Any results and conclusions depending upon more 
elaborate mathematical treatment of data are under suspicion, 
and are not accepted unless confirmed by the simpler method. 
Even the probable error of an average is under the ban, since 
it really has no significance in most cases, and in every case 
gives a misleading appearance of a significance which it does 
not possess. 

It was not to be expected, however, that the statistical 
method would be so easily routed from psychology. It offers 
an easy method for the obtaining of "results," and the results 
have an impressive appearance due to the profundity of the 
mathematical principles involved. The fact that these prin- 
ciples are above the comprehension of the person doing the 
research, and that the results, therefore, seem to come as gifts 

a This is not intended as a complete list of accepted measures, nor 
to exclude graphic representation and analysis. 



338 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

from the gods to the humble turner of the wheel, ^ by no means 
lessens the impressiveness. Furthermore, one is enabled to 
turn out a piece of research which has a considerable magni- 
tude by virtue of the amount of statistical work done on a 
very little data. And then, the method is sometimes applicable 
to problems for which no really experimental methods have 
been yet devised. 

For this reason, the methods of correlation introduced by 
Pearson and improved by Yule and others, have had a great 
vogue in individual psychology, and coefficients of correlation 
are being widely applied, not to the solution of various and 
sundry problems, but applied as the solutions; which is quite 
a different matter. Now it is true, the correlation method 
has very important uses, and may have such even in psychol- 
ogy, when applied to a collection of data which really has a 
Gaussian distribution or whose deviations from this distribu- 
tion are such as can be corrected. But I fear that most of 
those who use the method would not know how to determine 
whether a given distribution were Gaussian or not, for it is 
apparent that to many the term "normal distribution" means 
merely "symmetrical distribution." 

The difficulty in the interpretation of a coefficient of cor- 
relation is very great; I suppose there is no other representa- 
tive value obtained from data which offers greater difficulty. 
The difficulty is strikingly illustrated by a survey of the litera- 
ture embodying it, in which almost any coefficient is calmly 
assumed to prove not merely that there is a relation between 
the arrays correlated, but that the particular relation the seeker 
hoped to find is there. In order to avoid what might seem 
to be personal attack, I shall refrain from the citation of the 
really humorous cases of this kind which appear in some of 
our most serious journals. 

The disastrous effects of the higher statistical methods on 
the experimental work of those dazzled by the methods has 
been apparent in the correlational work, as it was in the earlier 
psycho-physical investigations. Much of the data of intelligence 
testing which has been subjected to mathematical elaboration 
of this sort has been data so crudely gathered, with so little 
attention to the principles of scientific method, that it would 
be worthless for even the simplest statistical treatment. Il- 
logical as it may seem, the assumption appears to be that data 
gathered by utterly incompetent persons, sometimes under un- 
known conditions, sometimes under conditions actually known 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 339 

to be pernicious, is in some miraculous way validated, and 
made reliable, when the magic method of correlation is applied 
to it. It must be said, however, that it is not the mental test- 
ers alone who have committed these abominations. In the 
field of vital statistics, so-called, some especially flagrant cases 
have recently cropped up. However dangerous the higher 
statistical method may be when applied to data gathered with 
due experimental precaution and sagacity, it becomes distinctly 
a public nuisance in the hands of those ignorant or careless 
of experimental technique. 

History repeats itself, occasionally at least. Although we 
may expect to see the mushroom growth of the higher statis- 
tical method as applied to individual psychology shrivel as 
did its earlier applications to the problems of general psy- 
chology, we need not fear that the subject of individual psy- 
chology, and its experimental phase in mental measurements, 
will die with the method. General psychology survived the 
blow: individual psychology will, too. The vast extension of 
intelligence testing, which has been largely based on uncritical 
correlation work, with little actual experimental basis, already 
shows signs of being a psychological boomerang; but individual 
psychology will survive even the blow of this back-stroke. 

It is interesting to note that the Binet-Simon tests, the fore- 
runners of the later crop of intelligence tests, were not de- 
pendent upon the higher statistical methods either for their 
elaboration or validation. Some of the later group intelligence 
tests also have had their usefulness for certain purposes estab- 
lished by careful analytical work, quite apart from the method 
of correlation. Where any test has not been established for a 
given purpose by other than "correlational" methods, its appli- 
cation is little more than guess work. The establishing of edu- 
cational and social projects and programs on mere "coefficients " 
is something which psychology might view merely with com- 
passion, were it not for the fact that such establishment is be- 
ing made brazenly in the name of psychology; and the public 
credits the failures to the experimental psychologists who pro- 
test against the methods. 

The higher statistical method has a place in experimental 
psychology as a means of preliminary survey, from the re- 
sults -of which indications may be drawn which are helpful in 
the formulation of problems. It is, in other words, one of the 
means of prospecting for a problem, and like other means of 
prospecting its indications may be fallacious. A coefficient of 



340 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

correlation is, in psychology, at the most only the beginning of 
research; a suggestion for a theory which may be formulated 
and put to experimental verification. The fallacy which has 
been committed is considering it the end of a research prob- 
lem. 

Experimental psychology cannot make use of the statistical 
methods of the physicist and astronomer because its data is 
not of the sort that makes elaborate mathematical treatment 
significant, and its problems are not of the sort that receives 
real illumination from the results of the treatment, even where 
the treatment is justified. If educational psychology should 
follow some of the present tendencies in that arbitrarily mapped 
out field, and become a system based entirely on correlation, it 
would thereby become a separate field, no longer confused 
with experimental psychology, at any rate. Individual psy- 
chology, which has been carried away by the mathematical fas- 
cination, and which has made its mental measurements so 
largely matters of correlation, can regain its balance and jus- 
tification by returning to the fold of experimental psychology 
and profiting by its experiences, disillusionments, and achieve- 
ments. 

So far, we have been discussing those aspects of method 
which are determined by the treatment of data. The way in 
which data are to be treated is not merely important in itself ; 
it determines to a large extent the data to be obtained for 
treatment. No one makes measurements without a considera- 
tion of what he will do with the data, in way of treatment, 
after they are obtained. The actual planning and carrying 
through of a piece of genuine experimental work must be, and 
should be, influenced by the treatment which is to be given 
the data after it is obtained. But there are other considera- 
tions of far more importance in the planning and elaboration. 

In planning an investigation the most frequent mistake into 
which experimenters fall is in making the scope of the problem 
too wide, or including too many problems. This mistake may 
be made in either of two ways. Often, the program of the 
research, as laid out, includes so many points that no thorough 
investigation can be made on any one of them in the time al- 
lotted. Not infrequently, a doctoral investigation covering 
three years or more of work suffers from this sort of plan- 
ning. As a result, the next investigator must start precisely 
where the first investigator did, instead of being able to start 
where he left off. Investigations on reaction times, learning 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 341 

problems, and a great variety of other topics might be in- 
stanced as showing this type of work. In the beginning of 
investigation on any topic, superficial exploratory work of this 
character is necessary to uncover the various specific problems 
involved ; and young investigators always find it difficult to re- 
strict themselves to a problem or detail of a problem, so small 
that it can be actually settled. But not all of the scattering of 
labor that comes under this category can be attributed to youth, 
either of the investigator or of the topic. In some cases, the 
scattering is due to lack of grasp on the real problems in- 
volved. Without a sufficient grasp the fundamental small prob- 
lems which ought to be attacked cannot be determined with 
clearness. A great deal of the impulse to scatter is due, how- 
ever, to the fact that the lengthy and copious working out of 
a single small point is extremely tedious, and nobody likes 
tedious work. The covering of a large topic superficially is 
much more thrilling. 

Another motive to work of insufficient thoroughness is de- 
rived from the strong interest we all take in application. A 
large part of the research in psychology is necessarily the 
fashioning and shaping of tools; tools which are then applic- 
able either to practical affairs of life, or else to the shaping 
and fashioning of still more tools. In fashioning these tools, 
it is inevitable that the use or application should be more or 
less in view, and the urge to hurry on to the application before 
the tool is really complete is frequently too strong to be with- 
stood. 

An illustration which comes to my mind, but which is just 
one case among many, is the work with the simple and fam- 
iliar tapping board, the applications of which to the testing of 
motor functions are practically useful, but which would be 
much more useful if we really knew more definitely the details 
of the tapping process itself. We can even see very clearly 
the exact problems which have to be worked out in regard to 
the tapping board; but each of these problems would require 
several years' work, and demand a high mastery of psycho- 
logical instrumentation and technique. Consequently, investi- 
gators balk at the problems, and prefer the more entertaining, 
although far less important, problems of application of the un- 
developed tool. 

The case of intelligence tests would be just as good on illus- 
tration. Application of tests is interesting and seems urgent, 
and moreover requires little scientific ability. On the other 



342 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

hand, the painstaking work of making intelligence tests more 
worth applying is appalling in its^vastness, its lack of thrill, 
and its requirements of psychological skill. 

What we really need in psychology is more of the spirit of 
Sylvester, who exclaimed, when he had made a discovery in 
higher mathematics, that he thanked God he had discovered 
something no one could ever use. What he apparently meant 
was that he was thankful for the opportunity and ability to 
work on a problem without reference to the further usefulness 
of its solution; for that is the way in which great advances 
in science are really made. 

The practical urge to lay hasty foundations and use them 
prematurely is not entirely the fault of the psychologist. Every 
psychologist knows how difficult it is to get appropriations and 
maintenance for purely scientific work, and how much more 
impressive to the powers that control money is something 
which is "practical," however flimsy and evanescent its "prac- 
ticality." The amount of money wasted in practical work 
which might be saved if more were available for the funda- 
mental scientific work on which eventual practical applications 
depend, is, of course, enormous, and even in psychology it is 
relatively large. 

In addition to the failure to narrow problems sufficiently in 
the general planning and laying out of experimental work, 
there has been a failure to limit sufficiently the specific re- 
quirements on the psychological subject or reactor. This fail- 
ure, however, lies rather in the past, having been peculiar to 
the introspectional psychology. The essential point of ultimate 
experimental method as applied to the conditions of the psy- 
chological observer himself is, that he shall be required to ob- 
serve only one point at a time ; a point being something which 
in the ideal case can be reported upon by a "yes" or "no" 
judgment. Obviously, preliminary work will always be 
needed ; work in which the judgment will be of broader scope ; 
in order that the final experimental conditions may be so ar- 
ranged that the simpler judgment for final purposes can be 
obtained. In some cases, even the final conditions will not be 
ideal; but the nearer they approximate to this ideal, the 
sounder the work. For this is just the difference between sci- 
entific observation and mere testimony, opinion, or guess work: 
that in scientific observation the conditions are either prear- 
ranged or foreseen so that the observer knows what to look 
for, and the definite time at which to look for it. 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 343 

A large part of the introspective work reported in the psy- 
chological literature of the past flagrantly transgresses this rule. 
Even when the observer has been introspecting in the sense in 
which the term is used in modern scientific psychology, that 
is, has been observing bodily processes, he has been required 
to cover a large range of observation in a brief period of time, 
or at least to try to. The result is sometimes distinctly hu- 
morous : the observer, after the critical moment of the observa- 
tion is past, will spend fifteen minutes or more detailing the 
various things he has observed. Emotions, feelings of pleas- 
ure or the reverse, feelings of tension, kinesthetic processes in 
breast, arms, legs, throat; and sometimes changing details of 
imagery as well, are solemnly reported as a part of the intro- 
spective observation. 

The unreliability of such observation, in which the observer, 
instead of concentrating on a single prearranged point, ob- 
serves as Charles Dudley Warner shot the bear by aiming 
at it generally has been abundantly demonstrated by the 
work on the psychology of testimony, and the type of obser- 
vation is being eliminated, or at least relegated to the limbo 
of the anecdotal animal psychology and the reports of the so- 
ciety for psychical research. For all types of psychological 
observation, the principle of concentration is now upheld, re- 
gardless of the school of the psychologist. 

Perhaps the most important point in psychological method 
is the formulation of the problem to which research is to be 
applied. For the evaluation of the importance of problems 
one against the other there are perhaps certain formal criteria ; 
but over and above these, the final evaluation must be in terms 
of the experimenter's interests and competence. Certain prob- 
lems are important because their results are foreseen as deter- 
mining further research or applications. Certain others are 
important because of their intimate relation to general hypo- 
theses, which may be either confirmed, modified or extended 
as the results of the research. But importance in any of these 
respects is not directly comparable with importance in any 
other. The relative importance of an investigation into the 
effects of alcohol on thought processes as compared with the 
investigation into the detailed features of tapping is to be de- 
termined only by the interest and the technical skill the inves- 
tigator brings to either, and the success in formulating the 
problems as a distinct hypothesis, the truth or falsity of which 
the experimenter is to test. Only when this formulation is 



344 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

achieved is the work which follows really experimental. Ex- 
ploratory work, without distinct hypotheses, is useful at times; 
but its value is low as compared with experimental work. 
The most serious obstacle to the extension of knowledge is 
the difficulty of formulating the hypotheses on which experi- 
mental work depends. When the problem is once f ormulated, 
the devising of apparatus to suit the problem is possible, and 
the carrying out of the work itself is largely a matter of in- 
dustry and careful technique. The formulation of the prob- 
lem demands scientific imagination, long study of the materials 
in which the problem is to be found, and general familiarity 
with the field of psychology in which the materials lie. The 
present undeveloped state of the psychology of the emotions, 
for example, is due to the difficulty in the formulation of 
specific hypotheses capable of experimental test. Broad hy- 
potheses exist, and draw our attention; but these are not 
capable of experimental test as such. Specific hypotheses, 
definitely related to the general hypothesis, must be discovered, 
and these specific hypotheses must not only be such that their 
confirmation or destruction will throw light on the general 
problem, but they must be such as can actually be solved. 
Many specific problems can be formulated, which are not ac- 
cessible to experimentation. Some hypotheses concerning 
emotions have been put to the test (e.g., Sherrington's experi- 
ment on the dog and Watson's experiments on children) . But 
it turns out in many cases that the hypothesis actually settled 
has no ascertainable bearing on the larger general conclusions 
of the experimenter. 

For the discovery of vital problems, there are no rules. This 
part of scientific work is in the same class as the writing of 
poetry and the creation. of paintings. There are principles to 
which the productions must conform; but these principles do 
not suffice to make the production possible; they merely dif- 
ferentiate between the successful and unsuccessful produc- 
tions. Curiously enough, therefore, the starting point of psy- 
chological experimentation is not itself a science, but an art; 
and this is true, of course, of all experimental work. We can 
lay down rules for the would-be artist to follow in developing 
his artistic ability; but we cannot create it. By study, direc- 
tion of interest, and arrangement of circumstances, we can 
prepare the nest in which the egg is to hatch; but the egg 
must be supplied to science. 

An essential point in experimental method, therefore, is to 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 345 

be something of an artist : to have a creative imagination along 
the lines of psychological hypotheses. Having that, and in- 
tellectual capacity to discriminate the useful creations from 
the useless, the materials for these to work upon may be sup- 
plied by study of the data and existing hypotheses, by techni- 
cal training, and by proper emotional application to the prob- 
lems. 

The methods of experimental science all lead to proof or 
disproof. The progress of any science is the confirmation or 
rejection of minor hypotheses, one by one. Scientific proof 
is, in theory, a definite accomplishment; but in practice the 
limit between probability and certainty can never be exactly 
set. Proof in science is merely repeatability. The funda- 
mental scientific assumption is of a uniformity in nature, such 
that what has occurred once under given conditions will oc- 
cur again if the same conditions are established. Theoretically, 
therefore, the results of one experiment constitute proof. The 
famous single experiment of Stratton on the effects of in- 
verted vision may be said to have proved his hypothesis, or 
disproved the contrary. In fact, in that particular case the 
results of the single experiment have been accepted, and the 
former discussion of the causes of correct vision has com- 
pletely ceased. Yet, in the strict sense of the term, there is 
as yet no real proof at all. Proof will be accomplished when 
other experimenters, establishing the condition on which the 
conclusions are based, find the same phenomena occurring. In 
this case, we accept the proof partly on faith, on account of 
our belief in the extreme competence of Stratton, both as an 
observer and as a technician, and partly because the conclu- 
sions fit so perfectly into the general hypotheses of reaction 
psychology. 

The general principle of the uniformity of the laws of na- 
ture compel us to assume that if the conditions of Stratton's 
experiment are repeated, the results obtained must necessarily 
be obtained again. If this were not true, then no science would 
be possible. The only question, therefore, concerns the ac- 
curacy and completeness of the statement of the conditions 
and the results. Were the essential conditions those described 
by him? Were the essential results those described by him? 
If, in the conditions, some essential point was overlooked, 
then the results obtained do not apply to the experiment de- 
scribed, but to an actually different experiment, which per- 
haps may not bear on the hypotheses at issue, or may have an 



346 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

altogether different bearing from that of the purported ex- 
periment. If the described results were not the actual results ; 
that is, if the observation was inaccurate, then again, the ac- 
tual bearing of the results on the hypotheses at issue is differ- 
ent from the purported bearing. 

The importance of repetition as a part of proof is, then, 
due to the necessity, in general, of certifying that the descrip- 
tions of conditions and results are accurate to the requisite 
degree. When another experimenter, setting up the condi- 
tions from the description of the first experimenter, obtains 
results which he describes in the same way as that in which 
the first experimenter describes his, the presumption of ac- 
curacy is enormously increased. Repetition of the experiment 
by the same experimenter does not have as great demonstra- 
tive value because of the possibility that the experimenter in 
the second experiment may not be actually following his own 
description, but may be following his first procedure, and 
therefore may vary from the description in the same way. 

There is no assignable limit to the number of repetitions of 
an experiment which must be made before the results are to 
be finally accepted. In the case mentioned, no repetitions have 
been thought necessary. In other cases, many repetitions have 
been made. In some celebrated instances, the second experi- 
menter has obtained different results because he did not ac- 
tually repeat the conditions as described by the first experi- 
menter, but performed a different experiment. This was the 
case when a well-known German psychologist attempted to 
repeat one of Ebbinghaus' experiments on the relation of the 
quantity of material learned to the labor learning it. The 
same experimenter went astray again in attempting to repeat 
one of Munsterberg's experiments. This persistent bungler 
finally gave up psychology and went into education. Another 
psychologist, in attempting to repeat one of my early experi- 
ments, obtained different results because he included conditions 
which I had specifically excluded. Mere failure to obtain the 
first results by repeating the experiment does not disprove the 
results; and, likewise, success does not constitute proof, since 
it is conceivable that two different experimenters might make 
the same errors. In any case, proof is not begun until the 
conditions of the experiment, as well as the results, are so 
accurately described that another person, from the description 
alone, can repeat the experiment. 

The elaborate techniques of the psychological laboratory, 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 347 

which cannot be reduced to general rules, but which must be 
learned by actual work in the laboratory upon the problems 
to which the techniques apply, are devices which are designed 
to contribute to the certification that the conditions described 
were the actual conditions of the experiment, and the results 
described were the actual results. They are vitally important 
because of the fact that in so far as the descriptions are ac- 
curate, the results are conclusive, since the actual results of a 
single experiment are universally valid for the actual condi- 
tions of the experiment. 

The experimental work of the psychical researchers is not 
credited, because of the signal failure of these persons to de- 
scribe accurately either their conditions or their results. If 
the results described were obtained under the actual conditions 
described, they would be conclusive. But every thorough ex- 
amination of such experiments has shown that the descriptions 
are vitally inaccurate, or else important conditions are un- 
known, and every similar experiment under competent psy- 
chological direction has failed to show the results claimed. 

I come now to a series of distinctions in psychological 
method which have given rise in the past to serious confusions 
and striking theories. This series is included under the name 
of subjective and objective methods; a pair of terms which 
designates, unfortunately, not a single distinction, but four 
quite different distinctions, from the confusion of which end- 
less speculative fallacies have arisen. 

In the first place, the terms have been applied to the dis- 
tinction between the observation of the bodily processes of the 
observer himself, and the observation of the bodily processes 
of others. If I may observe my own eye movements, in any 
way, the observation, on the basis of this distinction, would be 
said to be subjective. If, on the other hand, I observe the eye 
movements of another man, or of a dog, the observation would 
be said to be objective. 

In the second place, the distinction is drawn between ob- 
servation through the "external" senses and observation 
through the "internal" senses ; that is to say, between observa- 
tion depending on teleoceptors, on the one hand, and observa- 
tion depending on interoceptors and proprioceptors on the other. 
My direct observation of my eye movements would still be 
subjective; since I can observe my own eye movements only 
through the so-called muscular sense. (Visual observation of 
my eye movements, even with the aid of a mirror, happens to 



348 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

be impossible.) The observation of the eye movements ^of an- 
other man may be visual, however, and is therefore objective. 
I can visually observe the movements of my hand ; this would 
be objective observation. But if I observe my hand move- 
ments as I observe my eye movements, that would be subject- 
ive observation. My observation of my pains, fatigue, and 
other feelings, would also be subjective, although from the 
physiological point of view the type of perceptual reaction is 
the same in all cases, the only difference being in the classifi- 
cation of receptors. 

In the third place, the distinction is made between the direct 
observation of a process or object, either in myself or another, 
and the observation of a record mechanically derived from the 
process. Thus, the observation of my own eye movement or 
hand movement, and the observation visually of the eye move- 
ment of a rabbit or another man, are subjective; but if a mo- 
tion picture of the eye movement be secured, or, in the case 
of the rabbit, a kymographic record be secured through the at- 
tachment of a writing lever to the rabbit's eyeball, the observa- 
tion becomes objective. 

In the fourth place, those who recognize the possibility of 
"introspection" as the observation of observation, as Stout 
does ; or as a unique form of observation of any objects what- 
ever, distinguish subjective observation as introspection, ob- 
jective observation as non-introspective observation. The ap- 
plication of the terms subjective and objective actually com- 
menced in this theoretical distinction, which still largely in- 
fluences the vague meanings of the terms. Behaviorism had 
its start in this distinction, and in so far as it retains in any 
form its original metaphysical basis, it is still a branch of the 
introspectional or Malebranchian psychology, since without 
adherence to the older theory of introspection, it has no basis 
for distinguishing itself from regular psychology. If it aban- 
dons the introspectional hypothesis, and if it adopts rigorously 
the experimental methods which psychology has laboriously 
evolved, behaviorism becomes scientific psychology and should 
abandon also the now misleading term "behaviorism." 

All forms of self styled "objective" psychology depend for 
their characterization more or less on this older flavor of the 
two terms subjective and objective, yet in their illustrations 
and arguments, they are constantly committing themselves to 
one or more of the other distinctions. Some "objective" psy- 
chologists may, perhaps, be willing to define the terms in this 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 349 

traditional way : none of them would be willing to define them 
in one of the only other possible ways which I have outlined. 
All objective psychology, therefore, stands or falls on the ac- 
ceptance or rejection of Father Malebranche's metaphysics. 

When properly analyzed, the distinctions between subjective 
and objective observation furnish no basis for methodological 
distinction other than that between what I have called "intro- 
spectional" psychology and "scientific" psychology. Yet the 
first three distinctions do supply us with important side lights 
on the methods which scientific psychology employs. 

There is no question concerning the superiority of mechani- 
cally derived records as material for scientific study. The his- 
tory of experimental psychology during the nineteenth cen- 
tury is a history of persistent and fruitful attempts to obtain 
"objective" records in place of the observation of the pro- 
cesses themselves. The slow accumulation and adaptation of 
apparatus during the last fifty years, and the progressive re- 
sults of scientific imagination in devising new ways in which 
apparatus can be applied and records obtained, are substantial 
evidences of the emphasis which psychology has placed on the 
value of records and the study of records. The store of avail- 
able apparatus is now being rapidly increased, but the string 
galvanometer, the motion picture camera, the audion tube, and 
improved light sources, are no more eagerly welcomed as gifts 
to our equipment for objective research than were the chrono- 
scope, the spectroscope, and the electric motor by our predeces- 
sors in the science. The sudden interest in "objective" psy- 
chological methods of experimentation shown by some groups 
of psychologists and physiologists are, in large measure, noth- 
ing more than the effects of a sudden realization that the sci- 
ence had progressed beyond their conceptions; and the com- 
motion they have made is a cloud of dust raised in their be- 
lated effort to catch up with the procession. 

It would be a mistake, however, to suppose that records 
have in any sense displaced, or will displace, direct observa- 
tion of human organic processes. Not merely in the pre- 
liminary observations which must be made before records can 
usefully be made, but also in the obtaining of records, the sci- 
entific application of direct observation is imperatively neces- 
sary. The records obtained, even in the simple reaction-time 
experiment, are worthless, unless based on a competent ex- 
amination of the reactor's behavior: not only observation of 
the extent to which he is following instructions, but observa- 



350 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

tion of the surrounding conditions which are essential to the 
interpretation of the records. The employment of mechanical 
records does not involve a lessening of direct observation, nor 
a relaxation of the technical care requisite to making such ob- 
servations effective. "Objective" methods do not even lessen 
the need and importance of self-observation on the part of 
the observer or reactor, although the type and form of such 
observations may be modified. Animal psychology does, in- 
deed, have to proceed without such observations, but that is 
just what makes the procedure of animal psychology so diffi- 
cult, and the interpretation of its results so hazardous. ^ Since 
not all the conditions of the experiment can be specified in 
animal work, the conclusions are not valid for the conditions 
which are specified, except on the assumption that unspecified 
conditions are irrelevant. And this is an assumption difficult 
to defend in almost every case. Human psychology can, in- 
deed, be reduced to the level of difficulty of animal psychology ; 
but the procedure is analogous to the crippling of a Packard to 
reduce it to the performance level of a Ford. 

In human psychology, the difficulties of experimental ob- 
servation are maximal in those phases in which the observa- 
tion is through the internal sense, as determined by the intero- 
ceptors and proprioceptors. Here, the obtaining of objective 
records is less easy. But mere difficulty does not daunt the 
psychologist. Just as in animal psychology, where he must 
dispense with the observations of the reactor, he struggles 
along, under extreme difficulty, but not unprofitably; so in 
problems of feeling and emotion, where he has mainly the 
reactor's observation to depend upon, with little help from 
records, he must struggle along also, and not deny that the 
problems exist because he has difficulty in solving them. In 
this field, every step made in the achievement of objective 
records is of great assistance to the experimental work, but 
in this field, even more strikingly than in other fields, im- 
provement in the objective method does not lessen the direct 
observational work, but rather increases it as it makes it more 
profitable. 

Throughout experimental psychology, in short, the depend- 
ence on consciousness is definite and marked. Even in the 
use of objective records, the same observation which is re- 
quired for the direct study of the processes directly is required 
for the study of the records. That visual perception is the 
primary form of observation depended upon in the study of 



EXPERIMENTAL METHODS OF PSYCHOLOGY 351 

records, does not mean that it is in some mysterious way holy 
and reliable, whereas auditory, tactual, kinesthetic and organic 
observation are to be cast out. All forms of observation de- 
pend upon the same type of reaction process, and there is 
nothing about the visual receptors which can give them an 
exclusive sanctity. If kinesthetic observation is fundamentally 
unreliable, then visual observation is likewise ineffectual, and 
no science, psychological or physical, is possible. The re- 
liability of any form of observation depends on the conform- 
ing of the observation to the canons of experimental procedure. 
Experimental psychology began to shake of! the methodo- 
logical trammels of introspectionalism twenty-five years ago 
and has practically completed the process. It has now freed 
itself from the bonds and limitations of behaviorism and other 
forms of so-called "objective" psychology. It has never ad- 
opted the mystical freedom from experimental methods of- 
fered by psycho-analysis. It is established on a methodological 
foundation which is secure and permanent; and its further 
progress is conditioned by the degree to which psychologists 
recognize and devote themselves to the established scientific 
methods of the laboratory, and by the intelligence and industry 
of psychologists in applying those methods. 



CHAPTER XVI 

THE APPLICATIONS OF PSYCHOLOGY TO 
SOCIAL PROBLEMS* 



By KNIGHT DUNLAP 



I have said in my first lecture that social psychology, as a 
definite field within the larger science, is now established. This 
claim may be disputed. It may be pointed out that nearly 
twenty-five years ago the same claim was made; and that 
looking back from our present orientation we can see clearly 
that the claim was not valid, and did not become valid for 
twenty years at least, in spite of the increasing number of 
text-books and articles appearing under the name of the al- 
leged subject. It is not unreasonable, therefore, to be scep- 
tical still on this point, and to doubt whether the idea of what 
ought to be is not confused with the idea of what is. That 
the mere use of the name, and the collection of miscellaneous 
materials under the name in texts and college courses does not 
establish the subject, is to be freely admitted. It is not with- 
out importance, in this connection, that so far as college 
courses are concerned, the greater number of those offered in 
the past have been offered in departments of education, phil- 
osophy, and sociology; and we can now see that the reluc- 
tance of psychologists to admit them as a part of psychology 
was justified. These courses, and the texts on which they 
were based, may have been good education, or philosophy, or 
sociology; we may readily leave the experts in those depart- 
ments to judge of that ; but they were not psychology, in spite 
of their use and misuse of psychological terms and conceptions. 

I shall not insist, therefore, on the present changed condi- 
tion in the alleged subject of social psychology, although my 
own conviction has been strong enough to impel me to pre- 
pare a text and issue it boldly as Social Psychology. There 
are many points of application of scientific psychology to so- 
cial problems, whether these applications are to be considered 
as lying in a special department of the science, or as being 
merely an aspect of psychological application in a general de- 
velopment which it is useless to classify in any technical way. 

The social problems to which the application of psychologi- 
cal results, methods and principles is necessary may, for con- 
venience, be grouped under four heads: (1) Problems of the 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, 
April 22, 1925. 



354 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

sex life and the family organization and functions ; (2) Prob- 
lems of religion and religious organization; (3) Problems of 
what may be briefly called civic and martial organization; (4) 
Problems of race and population. 

To the solution of the problems gathered under these four 
heads must be brought in great wealth the results of general 
and individual psychology; and the main contributions, it 
seems to me, will be of five general groups. _(1) General psy- 
chology must contribute information concerning the nature of 
the sex impulses, and the psychological factors involved in 
sex relationships ; genetic psychology must supply the facts of 
the development of sex impulses and sex ideas in infancy, 
childhood, and youth; and individual psychology must con- 
tribute adequate information concerning individual differences 
in the nature and development of these factors. (2) The 
fundamental nature of religion must be determined with refer- 
ence to the basis in human capacities, activities, desires, and 
other feelings on which religion develops. This contribution 
involves an analysis of the conditions and effects of faith; 
the psychological foundations and efficacy of ritual; and the 
nature and significance of symbols. (3) The psychological 
factors in groups generally must be determined, and also the 
specific factors or variations in factors peculiar to the different 
sorts of groups: temporary and permanent groups; groups of 
low and high organization; groups of greater or less spatial 
contiguity; and groups of varying temporal extension. We 
must determine the psychological details of the individual 
which make these organizations possible; we must determine 
the forms and varieties of organization; and also the effects 
which these types of group life have on the individual. (4) 
The principles and facts of social control must be worked out 
and systematized. The nature of conventions, of laws, and of 
standards of taste and of morals must be determined, and the 
methods of conserving, modifying, and abolishing these im- 
portant controlling forces must be embodied not only in rules 
of an art, but also in principles of science. (5) In pursuance 
of the foregoing objectives, information must be at hand con- 
cerning the means of communication between man and man; 
information of a scientific character concerning language and 
its extension into culture. 

A vast jprogram is therefore mapped out for general, gen- 
etic, and individual psychology before anything that could be 
called social psychology in a final sense can be an actual 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 355 

achievement. Frankly, what we may call social psychology 
in the immediate future is but a propaedeutic to the real sub- 
ject: a marshalling of the facts and principles of scientific 
psychology into new formations, directed towards a specific 
purpose, namely: their application to social problems. Since, 
however, the marshalling does have this specific purpose in 
view, the process and immediate results really belong more 
to the subject that is to be, than to the topic of general psy- 
chology, and it is in this sense that I should claim that social 
psychology has begun its work, and can be now assigned its 
name and rank. 

A survey of the program I have laid out emphasizes the 
scarcity of the essential psychological materials for applica- 
tion to social problems. Under all of the five headings I have 
listed, we have a wealth of speculative opinions contributed 
by non-psychologists; but scientifically determined facts are 
few. The labor which experimental psychology has to per- 
form towards the final establishment of social psychology is 
vast. The reasons for the slow development of the subject 
are apparent. Not until psychology became really scientific 
did it begin to accumulate the materials. But the path of de- 
velopment is now open, and the issue depends only on the 
usual pre-conditions of psychological productiveness: intelli- 
gence, industry, material provisions, and the tenacious cling- 
ing to scientific psychological methods. 

Sex and the Family 

The problems of the family constitute a large group of our 
social problems, and another large group consists of prob- 
lems which are closely associated with these, and which have 
their source in those tendencies and characteristics on which 
the family is based. The family is, and will always be, our 
most important social institution, and it is also the most 
highly organized. Although the genetic function of the fam- 
ily has materially diminished with the progress of civilization, 
and the economic function even has lessened considerably, the 
psychological functions have increased, and there is every 
prospect that the family will continue to gain in social im- 
portance, whatever the economic and genetic changes of the 
future. The social problems arising from the family, and the 
problems surrounding it, become more complicated and more 
urgent as general social organization increases. 

The problems of divorce, of sexual promiscuity, of sex per- 
versions, and of prostitution, (really a form of sex perver- 



356 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

sion), appear to be the most outstanding in these groups. At 
the present time divorce occupies the public attention more or 
less constantly, and we are being subjected to continuous pro- 
paganda based on a recognition of the importance of the prob- 
lems involved, and a total misunderstanding of the nature of 
these problems. Amazing propositions are made from pulpit 
and press ; propositions for the solution of the problems by the 
panacea of legislative action, made with entire disregard of the 
actual conditions of family life and with no knowledge of the 
actual effects of legislative interference with family and per- 
sonal life. In past ages, the problems of divorce and marriage 
may have been largely genetic and economic. Religious atti- 
tudes and moral attitudes have, as a matter of fact, been based 
entirely on genetic and economic grounds. At the present 
time, the problems are predominantly psychological, and the 
moral, religious and political considerations which ignore the 
psychological factors in sex life are not only futile, but dis- 
tinctly vicious. Economic factors may, by proper efforts, be 
brought into harmony with psychological facts; but psycho- 
logical facts cannot be abolished, and the attempt to force them 
into forms prescribed by unfortunate economic conditions re- 
sults in perversion. Problems of promiscuity are so essen- 
tially bound up with the problems of marriage and divorce 
that they must be solved with and through the solution of the 
family problems. 

Aside from the family problems which have a legal aspect, 
there are problems of married life which largely enter into 
these more obvious problems, but which are hidden from all 
but the gaze of the specialist who is called upon to adjust do- 
mestic disharmonies. These concrete problems, unfortunately, 
often fall into the hands of persons who have little psycho- 
logical background, but who try to solve them on the basis of 
religious prejudices, or pseudo-psychological medical theories. 
Unfortunately, also, the psychologist who is drawn into these 
problems is seriously handicapped by the present lack of pre- 
cise information concerning sexual desires, emotions, and ten- 
dencies, of normal human beings, and concerning the way in 
which these psychological factors are controlled and modified. 
Sweeping theories concerning sex needs and sex instincts are 
rife ; but the actual facts for the support of these theories are 
scarce. 

In the past, theories have been built on clinical observations, 
but the attempts to apply these theories have resulted in mis- 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 357 

fortune and misery. Today, we recognize that the data on 
which dependence has been placed in these thories involves the 
pathologist's fallacy throughout. No one would attempt to 
evaluate normal intelligence by the use of data drawn ex- 
clusively from the insane. Yet we have attempted to evalu- 
ate normal sex life in terms of data drawn almost exclusively 
from the cases of abnormal sex life who come to physicians 
for treatment. Such collections as those made by Havelock 
Ellis, for example, are extremely valuable masses of data con- 
cerning the pathology of sex life; but tell us very little about 
the normal man or woman. 

The high organization of the family is based on the com- 
plementariness of man and woman ; a complementariness which 
is not merely physiological, but which is equally striking in the 
psychological realm. Although details are lacking, it is clear 
that essential differences of a complementary sort exist not 
only in the sexual desires and the emotional processes of an 
immediately sexual sort, but also in more general emotional 
attitudes of life. That other differences, not of the com- 
plementary sort, exist, is fairly clear; for example, the cyclic 
emotional changes which accompany the menstrual cycle in 
woman, and from which man is entirely exempt. Whether 
any important sensory or intellectual differences, as such, exist 
or not, is not clear ; but since the whole process of mental life 
is so strongly dependent on the emotional factor, we cannot 
expect that woman's total thought processes, or her general 
achievement in life will be parallel with man's, whatever her 
analytically considered intellectual capacities, since her desires, 
her emotions, and her interests are so different. 

As an instance of the general unreliability of information 
concerning sex differences in the past, we may consider two 
rather general comparisons. It has been widely believed and 
taught that woman "matures" sexually a little earlier than 
man, and it has also been widely held that man varies more 
from his mean than does woman in respect to many charac- 
teristics. On the former assumption, apparently, have been 
based our laws and customs regarding age of marriage and age 
of citizenship ; the latter assumption has been embodied in the 
catch phrase that woman is the conservative sex, man the 
variable. 

With the beginning of exact mental measurements applied 
to the problem of sex differences, the 'first outstanding indi- 
cation has been that, contrary to the catch phrase, man is less 



358 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

variable than woman, at least in regard to his mental capacities. 
While this cannot be considered as finally demonstrated, it 
has the weight of experimental evidence so far. Considera- 
tion of sexual desires and sexual responsiveness shows an 
even more marked difference in the same direction ; and it is 
now believed that even in physical measurements the same 
relationship holds. This does not mean, of course, that the 
range of variation is wider for women; we cannot say any- 
thing about that as yet; but it does mean that the average 
variation of a group compared with respect to a given char- 
acteristic is greater for women; that men, on the whole, lie 
closer to the mean. 

Further examination of the question of sexual maturity has 
shown, first, that the term "maturity" is exceedingly vague, 
and, second, that the comparisons made in the past have been 
made on quite different lands of sexual maturity for the two 
sexes. So far as any really comparable measures are con- 
cerned, there is at present no evidence that either sex "ma- 
tures" earlier than the other, although the surface indications 
would seem to be that the male "matures" the earlier. 

The whole situation clearly shows that conclusions as to 
sex differences must wait on actual experimental work and 
upon the results of information collected by scientific methods 
on points not subject to experimentation. Even on the 
side of sex behavior, conclusions cannot be drawn until we 
have further experimental evidence. Even in respect to the 
final physiological process of coitus, while we may reasonably 
conclude that there is only one normal type of this specific 
sex reaction of the male, we do not know at present whether 
the wide variations shown by the female are pathological, or 
due to habit, or are based on several distinct normal types of 
response. 

Within the last two or three years it has been shown that 
the accumulation of precise information on mental sex differ- 
ences is possible by the methods of experimental psychology. 
The outstanding difficulty in this field is merely the lack of 
financial provision for the necessary lengthy labor of deter- 
mination. Scientifically, the way is prepared; but scientific 
preparation is not the only essential condition. The most 
important psychological problems of the family and of sex 
relations lie now in the experimental field. 

There are, however, other points to which the data and 
methods of psychology must be applied. The general con- 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 359 

ditions of married life, which are not capable of experimental 
approach, must be studied. The effects of divorce and divorce 
laws on the family and on extra-marital sex life must be in- 
vestigated and given proper statistical treatment. This latter 
problem, simple as it may seem, offers great difficulty and 
demands exceptional skill. It is not sufficient to show that 
the states with the most rigid and mediaeval laws on marriage 
and divorce exhibit also the greatest degrees of family diffi- 
culty and the gravest conditions of extra-marital sexual life. 
These conditions must also be analysed with regard to differ- 
ences in economic and social conditions of other sorts, and 
finally, in the light of the experimental evidence concerning 
the actual psychology of sex, without which no useful con- 
clusions are possible. 

Religion and Religious Organisation 

Religion and the organization growing out of religion pres- 
ent a group of our most serious social problems. Scientifi- 
cally, we are perhaps too much inclined to look at religion as 
merely a problem of scientific and social inhibition, that is, 
as offering serious obstacles to the advancement of science, 
and to social progress. The recent events in the Southern 
states undoubtedly have accentuated this view of religion. 
Some scientists, at least, look upon religion as a malevolent 
growth upon society, which might be removed with beneficial 
results, and with no harmful sequellae after the shock of the 
operation should be over. This view, I think, is unfortunate, 
and adopted without due consideration of the nature of re- 
ligion and its relation to general and social psychology. 

In the past, the study of religion has taken three general 
forms: theology, the history of religion (including Compara- 
tive religion) , and the psychology of religion. The psychology 
of religion, however, has been a rather restricted topic con- 
sidering mainly the religious experience as ft occurs in living 
man. That is to say, the psychology of religion has been and 
is a part of general psychology, along with the psychology of 
music and the psychology of fatigue, and is to be treated as 
such. The usual experimental methods have not been fully 
applied, but their applications have been indicated, and there 
is no doubt that experimental work in this field can and should 
be carried out. But the results of the preliminary work so far 
have not been fertile. The topic remains still without vital re- 
lations to problems in other fields, and it seems to me evident 
that it must be fertilized by other than the general psycho- 



360 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

logical methods if it is to bear fruit. What I shall here dis- 
cuss is, therefore, not the psychology of religion in the ac- 
cepted significance of the term, but rather what I should call 
the social psychology of religion. 

It appears to me that the psychology of religion gives us 
little information concerning the nature of religion, its foun- 
dations in human life and experience, or its relations to our 
social problems. It is, in short, a subject which is in the same 
stage as zoology prior to the introduction of the hypothesis 
of evolution, and if we are to obtain useful information 
concerning the religious motives, tendencies and results, we 
must add to it the methods of comparative religion and archae- 
ology. From this cross-fertilization, I believe a useful social 
psychology of religion may be developed. 

I am not unmindful of the fact that attempts in this direc- 
tion have been made. The historical interpretation of religion 
in terms of sex, for example, has been attempted at various 
times, and the efforts two generations ago of a group of men 
among whom Thomas Inman and Payne Knight are perhaps 
most familiar to American readers, reached its most spec- 
tacular point in a system of symbolism which has been bodily 
adopted and popularized more recently by the psycho-analysts 
as something new. These early attempts have been of great 
value, although based on feeble psychology and inadequate 
archaeology and anthropology. Although the conclusions are 
discredited and the specific theories must be abandoned, the 
social psychology of religion is a continuous development from 
the efforts of these pioneers. Perhaps the greatest damage 
which the Freudian movement has done has been to inhibit 
this development somewhat, by fostering old misconceptions 
and creating new ones. To be specific: while we can no 
longer hold the theory of Inman and Knight that religion has 
its basis peculiarly in the sex life, it is a fact that sex plays 
an important role in the development of religion, as it does 
in life as a whole; and while the interpretation of religious 
symbols by these early investigators was superficial and has 
not stood the test of archaeological facts, the study of symbols 
is nevertheless a highly important part of the social psychology 
of religion. When the psychologist begins to consider sym- 
bolism and sex in religion, he seems to those ignorant of the 
historical development, to be adopting Freudian methods and 
hypotheses, and he is discredited by the absurd developments 
to which the theories they adopted have been carried. 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 361 

It is necessary on this point to free ourselves from such 
prejudices. The analyses and conclusions of Inman, Knight 
and the other early sex symbolists have not proved correct, 
but they are nevertheless important and useful, because these 
authors were making a serious attempt to combine psychology 
and archaeology, and their attempts must be carried forward. 
The fact that the Freudians adopted the theoretical conclu- 
sions of these men and proceeded to develop them fantasti- 
cally in disregard of both psychology and archaeology, should 
not be allowed to dim the lustre of these early workers, nor 
detract from the usefulness of their work. 

Perhaps I may indicate the problems and methodological 
requirements of psychology in the field of religion by an il- 
lustration. It is well known that in the evolution of the con- 
ception of divinities, female divinities come first, and that male 
divinities come next, and sometimes suppress the goddesses. 
Concerning the reasons for this order of development there 
are divergent views, two of which are directly opposed, name- 
ly: the theory that the elements of religion which have per- 
sisted were first developed by women, who would naturally 
(it is assumed) develop the conception of female divinities; 
and opposed to this, the theory that the essentials of religion 
were developed by men, who, (it is assumed) would naturally 
develop female divinities. Here we have off-handl interpreta- 
tion running riot. 

When we consider religion from the point of view o-f hu- 
man desires in general, and not from an arbitrarily exclusive 
reference to a single type of desire, we find reason to suspect 
that food would play an enormous part in the development 
of religious conceptions and religious attitudes. When, fur- 
ther, we examine the historical and archaeological material, 
we find impressive support for this suspicion. Hereupon, 
the relation between food and sex that many students of re- 
ligion have pointed out become deeply significant, and the 
problem of the female divinity is seen in a new light. When, 
in this light, we study the development of religion and of re- 
ligious symbols in Mesopotamia and other regions in which 
the date palm was of such economic importance, we find both 
ancient and modern religion brightly illuminated, and begin to 
see what religion really means in human life. 

But even by these discoveries, the problem of male and 
female divinities is only partly solved. We can see how the 
female divinities arose; but the crushing out of the goddesses 



362 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

by the gods requires further psychological and archaeological 
investigation. And the fact that the female divinity does 
not remain in the discard, but continually reenters religion, 
requires new consideration of those emotional attitudes and 
tendencies of men and women to which I earlier referred. 
These sex differences which are not opposed but comple- 
mentary seem to throw new light on the goddess problem. 

The goddess problem is, however, but one of the many prob- 
lems which the social psychology of religion faces, and to 
which it must bring the results and methods of scientific psy- 
chology to apply to the data which the archaeologists have 
provided in increasing measure. No progress in the psychol- 
ogy of religion can be made except through the study of its 
development in its earliest ascertainable phases, and this de- 
velopment cannot adequately be traced except by psychologi- 
cal applications. 

If we divide the phenomena and problems of religion into 
two groups; those of faith and those of "works" (i.e., ritual), 
we find a new direction for investigation in which the most 
important pioneer has been Robertson Smith. Here, again, 
we may not incontinently accept Smith's conclusion that ritual 
is the primary factor, and that religious faith develops from 
it; but nevertheless we have to accept his problem as vital, 
his method as productive, and his hypotheses as useful steps 
towards the final development. Here, again, the problem re- 
quires the application of all the psychological material we can 
muster. The desires and tendencies to which ritual appeals 
today require analysis. The effects of ritual on further psy- 
chological processes also requires investigation, if we are to 
understand the development of the past, and through it the 
significance of the present. 

In the social psychology of religion, as in many other psy- 
chological fields, a vast amount of work has already been 
done by those who are not primarily psychologists. I need 
only to add to the name of Robertson Smith those of Andrew 
Lang, Marett Frasier, Jevons, Budge, and Tiele, to suggest 
at once a whole glorious company who have analyzed data 
and supplied hypotheses, ideas, and methods of approach which 
are waiting to be welded into a vital foundation for the sub- 
ject. 

Religion, and especially, organized religion, is important in 
its effects on all social pheonmena. No constructive program 
in regard to the family, education or any other feature of 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 363 

social organization can be taken up without discovering" that 
the church has to be considered and its influence taken into 
practical account. But beyond this, religion has a social im- 
portance, because it is apparently founded on permanent ten- 
dencies of the human mind. It supplies something that man 
apparently needs. Whether these needs can be supplied better 
than they are at present; that is, whether religion itself can- 
not be improved psychologically; or whether, as some think, 
the needs can be cured, are matters that can be decided only 
after the real nature of religion has become better understood 
than it is at present. 

General Social Organization 

The general principles of social organization are fairly well 
understood at present. The age of glittering generalities has 
passed away, and we no longer make the attempt to explain 
social life by merely classifying activities under such heads 
as imitation, suggestion, crowd mind, and instincts. Spencer 
and Schaffle have done their work; and while we avoid their 
conclusions, we have made use of their methods. As we study 
the interrelation of details in the animal organization and at- 
tempt to arrive at an understanding of its integrative action 
without falling back on a single magic life principle; so we 
attempt to study social groups, in which the total activity of 
the integrated mechanism is understood from the characteris- 
tics and potentialities of the component individuals, without 
falling back on a magic principle in this case either. Without 
committing the error of considering social groups as exactly 
analogous to animal organisms, we have not neglected to make 
use of the partial analogy. We have not been carried away 
by the doctrine of McDougall that the group is more than the 
sum of its constituent members, and we recognize no social 
minds except the minds of individuals in the social groups. 
In other words, we apply to group psychology the results and 
principles of general psychology, studying the conscious re- 
actions of the individual to the group environment as we study 
his reactions to any other environment, and finding in these 
reactions at least all the complexity we find in his reactions to 
inanimate objects. 

We find grades of social organization corresponding some- 
what to grades of organization of animal bodies. We find 
those in which all the individuals have much the same func- 
tions; and we find "higher" forms of organization in which 



364 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

specialization of function brings about greater dependence of 
one member on the others and greatly increases the efficiency 
of total action of the group. We find continuous gradations 
of types from the temporary and fortuitous crowd to the more 
permanent states, armies, and industrial organizations. I think 
we may say that the basic principles of group development 
and group function are well established, and there is left only 
the vast amount of detailed data to be gathered on the speci- 
fic action of these principles in specific cases. Here there is 
plenty of room for the application of psychological principles, 
but the main interest is in the ascertaining of the way in which 
these principles work out. And in this field the hasty applica- 
tion of principles without knowing the exact conditions to 
which they are applied is especially dangerous. I shall illus- 
trate my points here by two examples only. 

Group action is controlled in part by conventions, which 
are in some instances made the basis for laws. I shall not 
attempt to show the place of a convention in our fundamental 
scheme of reaction-psychology, into which it fits without diffi- 
culty. I shall consider the effects of laws which are broken, 
that is, which do not represent a convention actually accepted 
by the individual. 

Americans are notoriously a lawbreaking people. Among 
the vast mass of statutes which we legally adopt and contemp- 
tuously disregard, the Volstead act is a mere minor detail. 
Fish and game laws are notoriously intended for the other 
fellow. In some states elaborate Sunday laws exist, and are 
unanimously broken, even publicly broken by many of the 
individuals who are active in keeping the laws on the statute 
books. Speed laws are mere joyous scraps of paper, and auto- 
mobile manufacturers do not hesitate to boost their wares by 
advertising them as capable of speeds much higher than any 
state legalizes. Some states have recently passed laws requir- 
ing all motor cars to come to a full stop at all railroad cross- 
ings ; and in those states I have not yet heard of any one who 
stops if he does not think a constable is in view. Laws against 
gambling in various forms are common ; and are not regarded 
by anyone who has no conscientious scruples against taking 
a chance. 

All this seems to constitute a serious situation. And it is 
doubly serious in that many of these dead laws are enforced 
occasionally on those who are poor and without influence. 
Negro crap games are raided; but not the bridge and poker 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 365 

games of well-to-do people. Foreigners and poor folks are 
from time to time arrested and fined for working on Sunday; 
but not their wealthier or better-class fellow citizens. The oc- 
casional speeder arrested is impressed principally by the fact 
that hundreds of others get away with their joyriding. It may 
be argued that a contempt for law and for the rights of other 
people is built up by these laws which are unjustly enforced. 
But there is another factor in this general lawbreaking which 
must be considered, even when the attempted enforcement of 
law is as impartial as possible. Do we form habits of law 
breaking which are transferred from one law to another? 
Does the practice of breaking speed laws, game laws, Sunday 
laws, and numerous other laws, make us more liable to break 
laws against theft, malicious mischief, and adultery, than we 
would be if these generally infracted laws did not exist? Cer- 
tain publicists claim that this transfer of the law-breaking 
habit actually occurs. But as a matter of fact, this question 
cannot be so simply settled. We have no basis for the appli- 
cation of simple laws of habit to complicated situations without 
a comprehensive study of the situation itself, and in regard 
to this particular situation no study as yet made is sufficient 
for the validation of the conclusion. Here is really a problem 
for experimental solution. 

Another problem or series of problems is to be found in the 
field of propaganda. An important part of social control is 
in the transmission of ideas; in the causing of other men to 
adopt or accept ideas which are presented to them. This 
transmission of ideas, or propaganda, is important in the 
whole field of social relations. It is essential in religious pro- 
selyting, political campaigning and commercial advertising. It 
is the method of modifying conventions, and bringing about 
the passage of laws. It extends to fashions of dress and moral 
principles. We know already the general principles underly- 
ing propaganda; we know the mental processes in the indi- 
vidual through which the copying and acceptance of ideas are 
possible; we know the forms in which ideas must be presented; 
we know the general methods of obtaining the necessary at- 
tention to the ideas with the minimal arousal of opposing 
ideas. We know that logic and reasoning play but minor parts 
in this whole process. All these factors are reducible to rules 
as definite as the rules of composition in printing, and the 
rules can be illustrated point by point from the accepted pro- 
cedure in advertising. Nevertheless, we do not know the 



366 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

exact extent to which reasoning is effective^ in propaganda, 
nor do we know the exact conditions, in relation to other fac- 
tors, under which reasoning is best applied to the work. Un- 
doubtedly the detailed methods of propaganda which are most 
effective with certain classes of society are not the most 
effective with other classes. But precision in planning and 
application of programs of propaganda to these different 
classes is not yet possible. Here again are very definite points 
for experimental and analytical research; research which it is 
by no means simple to plan and carry out. 

But there is another sort of problem of propaganda which 
has as yet been hardly touched. Under present conditions we 
are continually subjected to propaganda of a great variety of 
types. Obviously, the public needs orientation in the methods 
of withstanding this propaganda. Even commercial adver- 
tising has reached the stage of a social nuisance, and is a seri- 
ous drain on the economics of trade and industry. The appli- 
cation of psychological principles has reached a level of effi- 
ciency at which psychologists are scarcely justified in offering 
courses in the psychology of advertising, but should rather 
offer courses in how to withstand the appeal of advertisements. 

In all social organization, the means of communication be- 
tween man and man are of the utmost importance. The most 
important means is, of course, language. Language, as we 
have seen, is the vehicle of thought as well as of communica- 
tion, and hence psychology has much to offer on the various 
problems concerning the use of language. But language is not 
merely a matter of words with accepted meanings that is, 
with standardized reaction patterns to them. Verbal language 
is a step to culture, and we may with a few words convey 
richer and more precise meaning to those who share a com- 
mon culture than we could communicate with a vastly greater 
verbiage to those who lack the culture. History, art, and 
literature, are instruments of culture; mediums of communi- 
cation between man and man, and important solely for that 
reason. Cultures differ in different levels of society, and cul- 
ture changes from age to age. Latin and Greek are no longer 
the cultural topics they once were ; chemistry and biology have 
risen enormously in cultural value. But not all portions of 
these ^subjects have the same cultural value, and the deter- 
mination of the maximal cultural efficiency which can be ex- 
tracted from them is a serious and worthy problem. More- 
over, it is probable that the maximum of cultural efficiency 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 367 

can be attained by certain combinations of these different 
topics; which particular combinations, we ought to determine. 
College courses and school courses are today largely matters 
of guesswork, so far as their cultural aspects are concerned, 
whatever may be the case with their vocational aspects. It 
should be the business of psychology to make these needed 
determinations, and psychology ought to be in a position to 
assume this business, now that it has brought thinking and 
communication together and illuminated each with the other. 

Population 

Problems of population have harassed the human race since 
its earliest history, and it is evident that these problems run 
back into the legendary period of human development. In the 
past, these problems were the concern of priests and rulers; 
but of late they have become a part of the concern of scien- 
tific men. The interests of the priesthood are today as active 
as ever in the original phase of the problem, and ecclesiatical 
attitudes are by no means a negligible factor in the more re- 
cent phases. The church, from the ancient Greek, Roman 
and Jewish times, has asserted its right to control human sex 
relations, and has increased rather than diminished its claims 
in the modern Christian period. In these matters the church 
is still so powerful in the very quarters where the practical 
handling of the population problem is most difficult, that it is 
really one of the major considerations for any program which 
may be contemplated. The program which succeeds in gaining 
ecclesiastical approval has the best chance for immediate ex- 
tension. 

Rulers and governmental authorities are as much concerned 
with population problems as ever they were, and the forms of 
their problems have become more complex. The operations of 
governmental agencies in these matters have been so futile; 
and government itself is so subject to the influence of plain 
facts, that the civic power offers little obstacle to progress, 
and much possibility of assistance, except in so far as ecclesi- 
astical power dominates the government, which it still does to 
a considerable extent. 

The problems which may usefully be classed under the gen- 
eral head of problems of population are capable of distribu- 
tion in two groups, namely: problems of eugenics and prob- 
lems of over-population. The psychological aspects of these 
problems are intimately connected with the more general prob- 



368 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

lems of group psychology, and specifically, with racial psy- 
chology, and it is the last topic that I propose to discuss first. 

Racial psychology is, at the present time, largely a pious 
wish, and the imposing contributions which have been made 
to the subject so far are fairly well described by the Freudian 
cant term : "wish fulfillment" These contributions, we should 
note, are numerous and extensive. Many of them have been 
made by sociologists and others, including a few psychologists, 
under the specific title of race psychology; but vastly more 
numerous are the contributions which have been made by his- 
torians under the plausible caption of history. Reassured by 
their success in writing psychology under the name of history, 
some of the historians come out boldly and write more, and 
worse, under the name of psychology, or the name of some 
topic drawn from that subject. But any school teacher, doc- 
tor, minister, employment manager, novelist, character-analyst, 
newspaper writer, psycho-analyst, sociologist, spiritualist or 
real estate agent may confer on himself the title of psycholo- 
gist in these days, so that it must be understood that the racial 
psychology I am attempting to discuss is "psychology" only 
as understood by a relatively small group of persons who are 
dubbed in derision "Academic" psychologists by the larger 
group self-styled "psychologists" who occupy a much larger 
share of the public interest and who make practically all the 
profits. 

I am not unmindful of the small but growing body of ex- 
perimental work which has quietly been done by the real psy- 
chologists towards the analysis of racial characteristics. I 
shall not allude specifically to any piece of this, however, since 
my purpose is a somewhat wider one. 

The problems of racial psychology are two-fold. First, we 
want to know how the minds of the various races actually 
work. This involves, of course, the examination of the sen- 
sory processes, as well as of the thinking processes, feelings 
and emotions, learning, and motor control. In addition, we 
want to know the hypotheses or beliefs, and the ideals or stan- 
dards held by these races, for these are not only results of 
psychological processes, but actual determiners of those pro- 
cesses. 

Some of these facts may be gleaned from the literatures and 
from the languages themselves, if we can actually subject 
these data to psychological analysis. For some of the ancient 
peoples, such as the Greeks and Egyptians, materials for study 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 369 

exist, and may be made use of by the proper combination of 
psychology, archaeology and philology. For the so-called 
primitive peoples, who have left no literatures, the materials 
do not exist. 

The other source of information is manifestly the careful 
observation, measurement, and experimental study of the 
peoples themselves. For the rapidly vanishing savage races, 
theoretically this might still be done, although such study 
would, of course, give us little information, except in the field 
of anthropometry, of the characteristics of these races before 
they were so largely modified by the white man; and the ob- 
servations recorded by explorers, missionaries, and commercial 
agents of the past, we know are of little real value. But such 
opportunity as may exist will, in all probability, pass away 
before any use can be made of it, and we shall probably not 
know the mental characteristics of even the American Indian, 
although we may know the worthlessness of the vast amount 
of junk that has been written about him. 

Leaving out the savage and so-called primitive races as 
hopeless problems, it would seem that we might at least ac- 
quire some information about the races which exist in Europe 
and Asia, and adhere to their own methods of life in spite of 
contacts with others, and which promise to persist as races 
for many years to come perhaps even longer than we shall. 
But how long it will be before we acquire any useful informa- 
tion, and whether it will be useful by the time we get it, are 
open questions. 

The magnitude of the problem of obtaining an actual com- 
parison of the mentality of two races is almost appalling. As- 
suming that we had developed measures for the mental factors 
in which we are interested and this is a bold and pretentious 
assumption the program of applying such measures on a 
scale comprehensive enough to be of real significance is so 
great that no organization capable of carrying it out is in ex- 
istence, nor can the means of bringing it about be foreseen. 
But let us make another large assumption, and assume that 
even this obstacle has been overcome. What we would then 
have would be a comparison of the two races under the con- 
ditions of their physical and social environments. We would 
know, for example, how the French in present day France 
compare with the English in present day England. An im- 
portant and interesting stage of information, it is true, but not 
the information which is most desired. We would not know 



370 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

how these races would compare when subjected to the same 
physical and cultural environments for a complete generation; 
and this is what we really want to know for purposes of im- 
migration, of eugenics, and of social progress generally. We 
would not even know how they would compare physically un- 
der such uniform conditions. 

It would have been of little use to compare the Romans with 
the British in the period from 50 B. C. to 50 A. D., unless 
the total conditions of human development were so well known 
that it could be predicted what changes would be wrought by 
changes in food, in other modes of life, and by the absorption 
of the Roman and Greek cultures by the British. And we can 
as little tell from the reactions of the French people today 
what the reactions of their descendants will be when the 
French modes of life and culture may have been greatly 
modified. 

It would seem, however, that in America there is a chance 
to study the mental development (and the physical develop- 
ment, too) of diverse races under the same physical and cul- 
tural conditions. And perhaps something may be accomplished 
along this line, if a sufficiently large number of trained work- 
ers can be secured, along with sufficiently gigantic sums of 
money. Theoretically, we should be able to measure the minds 
of groups of American born and bred of pure Italian, Irish, 
Scandinavian, Czecho-Slovakian, Greek, Turkish and other 
blood (in so far as any of these races are pure), who have 
grown up in sufficiently similar physical and social environ- 
ments ; and so we might arrive at the solution of the question 
as to what may be accounted for by racial differences alone. 

Practically, it would not be possible to do anything of the 
kind. We know that the peoples of different races in the 
United States live under essentially different conditions of 
food, occupation, and culture for several generations ; and that 
as the essential conditions become uniformized these races 
intermarry, and so the racial "purity" is lost. That the en- 
vironment of the different races in the United States is differ- 
ent so long as they remain separate races is most dearly shown 
by reference to the Jews, who are born, reared, and grow old 
in an essential atmosphere of Jewishness which makes it pos- 
sible to say that any "J ew * s h" mental trait, if such can be 
demonstrated, is racial in the hereditary sense, or merely cul- 
tural, that is, hereditary in the social sense only. 

Or, take the negroes, on whom several excellent studies of 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 371 

mentality have been made in a small way. Even if it were 
possible to make the comprehensive and exact studies we are 
assuming to be possible, we would have as a result the pattern 
of the negro's mind as he is : reared, and trained, and his ideals 
developed, in a physical and social environment distinctly dif- 
ferent from that in which the whites are developed. It may per- 
haps be predicted by some one that at some time in the future 
it will be possible to study a large body of negroes whose es- 
sential environment has, from birth up, been practically the 
same as that of a large body of whites with whom they may 
be compared. But it is necessary to bear in mind that if such 
a condition is realized in any group the "negroes" in the group 
will not be negroes; they will not even be half breeds. 

But all this is speculation on the basis of an assumption that 
requires detailed consideration. Manifestly we have no such 
measures as those we have been assuming. When will they 
be developed? I myself am an optimist on this point: I 
think that we will develop a reasonably adequate battery of 
such measures relatively soon perhaps in a hundred years or 
so. We have a few simple tests now, and these can be ex- 
tended and added to progressively if we can manage to keep 
some psychologists on the job of development for a sufficient 
time. But my optimism begins to rip at the seam when I con- 
sider the fact that is hard to keep even a small body of com- 
petent investigators at scientific work along this line. The 
workers who might be laboring in the field are lured away by 
the siren of application and waste their time and energies in 
efforts to extend the application of measures which are well 
enough as clinical expedients, but which should be merely 
stepping stones to the end in view. 

Some people actually seem to think, in short, that the vast 
problems we face are adequately to be solved by intelligence 
tests. Now, the intelligence test is all well enough as a means 
of grading people roughly for certain purposes, when the tests 
are devised for the specific practical ends to which they are to 
be applied, and standardized empirically. And the intelligence 
test might have been a valuable tool with which to carve out 
other tools of service for the measure of attainments with 
respect to actual mental standards. What the intelligence 
test does, when sagaciously applied to a group who have been 
all trained for a certain purpose (such as banking or entering 
college), is to measure (very roughly) the extent to which 
the training for that purpose has been successful. In short, 



372 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the intelligence test is a trade test, and^nothing more, and is 
most efficient when developed and applied with reference to 
trades as specific as possible, whether the trade is that of be- 
ing a college student or a typesetter. But because the intelli- 
gence test measures directly only the results of training, and 
measures with adequacy only training of very specific and 
limited sorts, its possibilities as an instrument for the solving 
of problems of racial psychology are ^ very limited, and it can 
never be more than a minor aid in this work. It seems prob- 
able, however, that in the immediate future there will be a 
considerable flood of supposed contributions on racial differ- 
ences based on intelligence tests, which will make necessary a 
painful and dangerous cleaning-up process later. 

The problem of psychology, in regard to the field of racial 
psychology, is not difficult to find, but it hardly lies in that 
field as yet. We must keep on with the difficult work of de- 
veloping measures of mental function, and set our faces against 
the naive and hasty applications of the undeveloped measures 
as firmly as we set against the conclusions from the simple 
and uncritical observations with which treatises on racial psy- 
chology have hitherto been filled. ;On a basis of sound ex- 
perimental work and sound mental measurements, racial psy- 
chology may some day be established. 

The psychological problems of eugenics and the psychologi- 
cal problems of overpopulation are essentially connected, and 
both are complicated by the situations we have just discussed. 

Eugenics has a positive and a negative program: the pro- 
motion of the reproduction of the fit, and the repression of the 
reproduction of the unfit. But apparently, the positive pro- 
gram is a failure, since no means have been found for the pro- 
motion of propagation beyond the rate at which it progresses 
without encouragement, except the promotion brought about 
by a reduction of the total population relative to its natural 
resources and cultural ideals. Propaganda and bonuses, and 
all other artificial stimulations, are apparently entirely ineffec- 
tual. The reasons for this ineffectualness are fairly obvious 
and we need not pause on them. The relief of the pressure 
of population, on the other hand, affects all classes, and prob- 
ably the unfit especially, so that the negative program is 
doubly important. Moreover, any increase of reproductive rate 
might be at the present time an evil in itself, since it would 
add to the present overpopulation. 

Since eugenic fitness is a matter of mentality as well as of 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 373 

physique, one problem for the psychologist is outlined: the 
determination of mental fitness. And here the problem is 
largely yet to be solved. One class of the unfit, the feeble 
minded may well be detected by the Binet-Simon tests. But 
no one could reasonably maintain that the feeble minded are 
the only mentally unfit from the eugenic point of view. And 
the determination of the other types, if any, is yet to be made, 
and the means for their detection developed. It is not merely 
a matter of the development of measures for emotional and 
moral deficiency, and for instability, for example : but the de- 
termination of the types of deficiency which are fatally hered- 
itary. In this determination the psychologist and the gen- 
eticist must work hand in hand, and the psychologist must 
avoid the genetic use of crude and hastily constructed tests or 
mere casual observation, such as have, unfortunately, been ap- 
plied in the genetic field. 

At the other end of the scale, the problem is more difficult, 
if not impossible. The really superior mentality is much more 
difficult to determine than the really defective. Moreover, if 
the really superior in some one line is determined, it may not 
be the fittest eugenically: for it may carry with it defects in 
some other line. That we should breed through "genius" is by 
no means established; perhaps we should breed around it. 
Happily, this problem of the "fittest" is of no serious con- 
sequence eugenically, since the positive program, as I have 
said before, is impractical. 

But having determined, let us assume, the unfit, the matter 
of their elimination from reproduction is now the question. 
The lethal method we may consider inapplicable. Steriliza- 
tion has also turned out to be impracticable, at least in the 
present social condition. Segregation covers but a fraction of 
the problem. Prohibition of marrying is merely a form of 
legal humor, and prohibition of mating can be enforced only 
on the most unfit and by segregation, sterilization, or death. 
What, then, is the possibility *f or an actual eugenic program? 
Apparently nothing but contraception. And here we run up 
against psychological problems of a new sort, and of great 
difficulty. 

The problems concerning contraception are of two sorts: 
those which concern the actual effects of the practice, and those 
concerning the undoubtedly strong popular feeling against it* 
The physical problems of the effects of the practice are simple, 
and the difficulties uncovered by the analysis of the problems 



374 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

are relatively simple also; and there is today no serious doubt 
that these difficulties could be overcome. On the psychological 
side the problems are more complicated. The psychological 
effects of the practice are not definitely known, but are matters 
still for conjecture and biased belief. This problem is one 
not to be solved in an easy way, but it must be solved. The 
question, moreover, as to how different classes of society will 
react to a fuller knowledge of more efficient and physiologi- 
cally harmless methods of birth control, is one which must 
be settled by expert psychological analysis. We know what 
classes today are practicing family limitation, but we have 
only theories as to which sections of the classes not practicing 
it today will practice it to a relatively greater extent than 
others under conditions of more general extension. We know 
that among other classes, the feeble minded are not practicing 
contraception, and will not practice it under present condi- 
tions. To what extent they would practice it under improved 
conditions of cheapness and convenience is the question. I 
may believe that the eugenically inferior classes will tend to 
eliminate themselves through contraception, if conditions are 
made easy for them; but I may be entirely wrong. Actual 
experimentation would be possible in this field only through 
embarking blindly on a supposed eugenic problem in order to 
determine by the results whether it would be actually eugenic, 
dysgenic, or neither. It is possible, however, that informa- 
tion concerning the reproductive desires of various classes of 
the population can be obtained in advance of the entering 
upon such a social program. If so, the information must be 
gathered by psychologists. 

It must be admitted, I think, that the present experimental 
methods of psychology are inadequate for these problems. 
As a substitute, the questionary method has been adopted to 
a certain extent, and I think that some useful material may 
actually be gathered in this way, although such materials will 
never be final data, but merely orientational and suggestive. Ob- 
viously, some method must be devised that will be of the type 
which is designated by the vague and misleading term "ob- 
jective": I have earlier suggested the use of the theatre in 
such problems, and I think that "objective" material may be 
gathered which can be statistically treated; but the planning 
and ordering of the work will require much preliminary an- 
alysis. Furthermore, the problem turns on the question of 
there being a really fundamental distinction between two 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 375 

classes of desires, both sexual in the broad sense, which I have 
called "reproductive" and "amatory." It does not turn on the 
question as to the ultimate nature of these or of any other 
desires. 

Another problem, fundamentally involved in the one just 
outlined, concerns the relation of reproductive desire to stock 
values. I have an idea that there is a rather definite connec- 
tion here; that the tendency to reproductive desire is inherit- 
able (in the usual sense of the term) ; and that the stocks 
which have the stronger reproductive desire are fundamentally 
the best stocks in several respects. This, however, is a psycho- 
genetic assumption which must be tested. 

The problem of the relation of amatory desire to stock 
values is a different, but essentially related problem. As I 
understand it, the notions of some stock breeders are strongly 
in accord with such an assumption. But among the lower 
animals, the effective force of reproductive desire is not sep- 
arable from the effective force of amatory desire; and the 
same condition largely holds for the human race, so long as 
contraception is not practiced. But as soon as contraception 
is introduced, the effects of these desires is dissociated, and 
the merely amatory desire becomes negligible as a reproductive 
factor. In fact, it is probable that the reproduction tendency 
would be lessened, with increasing strength of amatory desire, 
even if the reproductive desire were not weakened. This pos- 
sibility introduces a serious eugenic problem, since we do not 
know whether or not the amatory desire is linked with other 
tendencies which are of value to the stock, or whether certain 
valuable tendencies may not even be directly based on the 
amatory tendencies. 

The second group of problems I mentioned above must also 
be solved if contraception as a eugenic measure is to be seri- 
ously considered. The extent and force of the prejudice 
against contraception are manifestly great. These prejudices 
would have to be overcome or circumvented, if the practice of 
contraception were to have eugenic effects. Here, the work 
of the psychologists would be distinctly in the applied field, 
and would depend upon an adequate analysis of the causes of 
the prejudice. 

Admittedly, the basis of the prejudices is fear, of two sorts. 
First : a fear that one's group will be overcome by other groups 
that reproduce more rapidly; overcome either in war, or else 
by a more gradual crowding out. This is distinctly a phase 



376 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

of group psychology, dependent on group pride and group 
feeling of more general sorts. Second: a religious fear of 
punishment in another world for disobeying a command of the 
church. The church, however, in promoting this fear, is mo- 
tived by the same group feelings which are powerful in all 
other groups. That church whose members reproduce most 
rapidly has the best chance of survival and growth. This 
organized opposition of a powerful group which is fighting 
for its life is admittedly the most serious obstacle to eugenic 
contraception. 

The "will-to-live" of a group (I use this philosophical term 
with apologies) is a remarkable thing, but is something to be 
reckoned with. It is manifested in groups of all kinds, and 
sets the interests of the group above the more strictly individ- 
ual interests, even where these are in conflict. Aside from 
the religious groups, its most striking manifestation is in civic 
groups. The denizens of the modern great cities are proud of 
their cities' over-growth, and will foster it even at serious in- 
dividual expense. In spite of the rapid increase in taxes, in 
rentals and other prices, and the decrease in the general com- 
forts of living which are entailed by overgrowth, the people 
want it. The inhabitants of Baltimore, for example, outside 
of a small class of real estate dealers, and speculators whose 
specific interests are in the exploitation of overgrowth, would 
benefit very largely if the city should actually shrink a little: 
yet they are unanimously anxious for rapid growth, and are 
cast down if their city grows less rapidly than some rival city. 

When, to this group mania, you add the religious notion 
of an other-worldly value in the growth of an organization, 
the dangerous side of group spirit becomes accentuated. Here 
is a psychological problem of extreme difficulty, in the face 
of which one may almost despair. 

On the hopeful side, however, we may note that this group 
tendency has no moral foundation; no basis in the essential 
necessity of regarding the rights of others, the obligation 
which binds man to man in all groups above the lowest stage 
of organization. This is the weak spot in group pride at which 
the tendency can be attacked. 

Every member of the group is anxious for his group to 
grow, but is perfectly willing that the growth shall be at the 
expense of other individuals in the group rather than at his 
own cost Few opponents of contraception feel a personal 
duty to reproduce, but feel, rather, a strong desire that other 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 377 

members of the group shall do the reproducing. This fact 
is strikingly exemplified in the practices of the religious monks 
and nuns, who, while teaching the sin of non-reproduction, 
produce no children themselves. Of course, this apparent in- 
consistency is defended by making a distinction between not 
marrying, and not marrying reproductively ; but this bit of 
sophistry deceives no one, and general failure of the group- 
members to mate would exterminate the group as rapidly as 
would mating contraceptively, and would be as definitely de- 
nounced if it threatened. 

The same separation of personal practice from group feel- 
ing is just as evident outside the church. And inside of the 
church, as well as out, individuals practice contraception in 
complete disregard of their group principles and group preju- 
dices. In so far as they are inhibited in the practice they 
are Inhibited by just three things. First: by the individual 
reproductive desire in its relations to economic status and cul- 
tural ideals. Second: by the lack of information, or lack of 
the means, of contraception. Third: by the personally ob- 
jectionable features of such means as the individuals may 
possess. 

The prejudices against contraception are therefore more 
largely to be circumvented than to be overcome, if contracep- 
tion does turn out to be a commendable eugenic measure. 
The circumvention is possible through the devising of means 
of contraception which have not the actual physiological and 
psychological objections which attach to present day means; 
and through methods of popular education which are slowly 
possible in spite of religious prejudices. The first problem 
must be solved first; but there is no doubt of the success of 
the experimental work now under way in foreign countries. 
Even in this problem, the psychological factors are paramount ; 
and the second problem is distinctly one in which applied 
psychology must play a large role, if the program is really 
desirable. 

All these problems lead to, and in part depend upon, the 
problem of overpopulation. Years ago, Malthus pointed out 
the fatal dangers of overpopulation, but his views were shortly 
discredited through the opening up of vast tracts of land pre- 
viously unavailable for the support of European peoples. 
These tracts were opened up by the invention of the steamboat, 
the locomotive, and modern harvesting and manufacturing 
machinery. Now that the pressure of population is again 



378 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

acute, and white men are getting a bit squeamish about 
slaughtering inferior peoples in order to take their lands, 
and there is clearly no New World to conquer, the im- 
portance of Malthus' contribution has been recognized, and 
the fact, rather than the danger, of overpopulation is ad- 
mitted. We know that war is caused almost entirely by over- 
population, and that future war is inevitable if the pressure 
of population is not relieved. We know that our problems 
of crime and vice are accentuated by overpopulation. We 
know that while the land may be made to produce vastly more 
than it does, the labor required for the increase, increases in 
a much higher ratio than the produce. We know that the 
culture of a crowded population must decline, even if war is 
miraculously averted. Specifically, we know that the social 
problems of the United States would be greatly lessened, and 
the value of life to the individual inhabitants greatly increased, 
if the total population could be materially decreased in the 
next ten years, instead of increased. Worse yet, we know 
that the available mineral resources of the world are approach- 
ing definitely a time of exhaustion, and the soil itself wasted 
through too extensive cultivation and denuding of forests. 
And knowing all this, we are beginning to take a tardy in- 
terest in the ways and means of reducing population. 

The changed methods of warfare which make the prospect 
of the next war appalling are important influences in deter- 
mining the new interest in the problems of population: yet I 
should like to point out that these new methods of warfare 
are the only means which could delay the final catastrophe, if 
we do not take other intelligent measures. 

In the past, warfare has been necessarily attended by, and 
based on, vast destruction of natural resources. The destruc- 
tion of human life has been of little consequence, if any, ex- 
cept to the individuals themselves. But the natural resources 
destroyed are not replaceable. 

When the Assyrians, urged on by over-population of their 
territories, slaughtered the inhabitants of other lands which 
they needed, they not only destroyed the buildings and other 
accumulations of culture, but cut down the vital date palm 
trees and even the forests. That this was an essential detail 
of their method of warfare, numerous linscriptions show. 
Similar methods of destruction were employed by all ancient 
nations, so that not only the easily replaceable population but 
also the accumulations of culture were destroyed. And this 
in many cases was an irreplaceable loss. In the recent con- 



PSYCHOLOGY AND SOCIAL PROBLEMS 379 

flict, the destruction of mines and machinery and noble speci- 
mens of architecture was an essential practical detail of war, 
and the loss to the world if the Germans had succeeded in de- 
molishing London can hardly be grasped. But still more seri- 
ous was the irreplaceable loss of metals, especially copper, 
sunk in the sea and blown into fragments in munitions. This 
one war took an enormous amount from the steadily shrinking 
inheritance of our descendants. 

But all this will be changed. In another war, by the use 
of gas, a great city will be taken by the poisoning or asphyxi- 
ation of its inhabitants without the injury of a fresco or a 
linotype machine, and with slight loss of metals. The next 
war will reduce the pressure of population by mass destruc- 
tion; but the resources and the accumulations of man will be 
but slightly diminished. In this respect, chemical warfare will 
be of incalculable benefit. But on the other hand, war is in- 
evitable so long as the over-population is not alleviated in some 
other way. The advances of humanitarianism and medical 
science have but made the conditions worse and accelerated the 
coming of conflict. Plagues and pestilences, formerly of such 
service in keeping population down, are being brought under 
control, and the yellow peril and the perils of all other colors 
thereby exaggerated. It is a serious question whether the ex- 
tension of "public hygiene" to Asiatic and African countries 
is something to be proud of, or another social crime. 

I have touched on but a few of the social problems which 
demand the attention of the psychologist and which depend 
upon the applications of psychology for their solution. In 
attacking these problems, we need to make use of the methods 
and results of general, experimental and individual psychology. 
In other words, the foundations must be laid in that psychol- 
ogy which is distinctly a biological science. But as we go on 
towards the solution of our problems we need other concep- 
tions and other methods. The work passes rapidly out of 
the field of the natural sciences, and becomes more and more 
affiliated with what are sometimes called the social sciences, 
and the methods of philology, ethics, political science, and so- 
cial anthropology become more and more essential. Yet the 
work is so definitely dependent on its psychological founda- 
tions that it still remains psychology. If, in the light of the 
foregoing discussion, we again ask whether social psychology 
is a real and distinct subject, the answer, it seems to me, must 
be in the affirmative. Social psychology is to be distinguished 
from the more fundamental parts of psychology in that it is 
a social science, rather than a biological science. 



PART VI 

Psychologies Called "Structural" 




MADISON BENTLEV 



CHAPTER XVII 

THE PSYCHOLOGIES CALLED ''STRUCTURAL*: 
HISTORICAL DERIVATION* 



BY MADISON BENTLEY 



My earliest memory of the newspaper cartoon represents a 
wide circle of men, all facing outward and each pointing to his 
neighbor on the right. The cartoonist meant to represent, as 
I recall, a ring of Tammany politicians surrounding "Boss 
Tweed." Each is charged with the theft of the city's treasury 
and each denies his own culpability, pointing to his neighbor 
as the guilty man. If we ask today who represents the psy- 
chology of 'structure/ I doubt whether we shall find anyone 
to acknowledge that his own brand is of that kind ; though the 
epithet will often be accompanied by a gesture of indication 
toward a fellow-psychologist. We should all agree that no 
one in this country has done so much to expound the doctrine 
as Professor Titchener has; but he has not for some time re- 
searched or written under its rubrics and he explicitly remarked 
some time ago that, in his opinion, "both 'f unctionaF and 'struc- 
tural/ as qualifications of 'psychology/ are now obsolete 
terms." 1 

Notwithstanding the fact that the concept of structure, as it 
has been used to designate a point of view and a method in 
psychology, is no longer to be regarded as current in our 
phraseology, the contributions made to the science under its 
name, as well as the influence which it has exerted upon psy- 
chology at large, seem to justify a serious consideration of its 
meaning and its value. Thus I have accepted your generous 
invitation to add the psychologies called 'structural* to the 
other species and varieties which you have already considered 
in earlier lectures. 

In a brilliant essay in 1884 2 the late William James was 
urging the importance of what he called the transitive (as set 
against the more permanent substantive) parts of the stream 
of consciousness. The transitive parts had been overlooked, as 
he thought, in the English and German conceptions of the idea 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan- 
uary 5, 1926. 

*Amer. J. PsychoL, 1921, 32, 533. 
S 0n some omissions of introspective psycholc>gy, Mind, 1884, 9, 1-26. 



384 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

or Vorstellung. Instead of gluing ideas together by some out- 
side force or principle, such as 'reason/ 'intelligence/ 'associ- 
ation' or the 'ego/ James proposed to make the stream real 
and to complete it by filling in such transitive parts as the 
feeling of 'and 5 and the feeling of 'but'; in short, by adding 
to consciousness something like Herbert Spencer's 'feelings of 
relation/ "There is no evidence whatsoever (he says) for sup- 
posing the pure atomic ideas of red and yellow, and the other 
elements of mental structure, to exist at all no one of them 
is an actual psychic fact." They are only qualities of the outer 
world; the mental vehicle by which we think them is a 
"feeling representing a highly complex object, that quality in 
relation with something else" (p. 9). Instead of separate and 
discrete elements James proposes to account for the continuity" 
and coherence of our knowledge by a like fluent continuity in 
the conscious 'stream' or the stream of 'feelings.' Thus he 
comes to the distinction between the 'subjective constitution' of 
the 'stream' and the 'cognitive functions' which the 'feelings' 
subserve (p. 11). The contrast between feeling, on the one 
hand, and thought or knowledge, on the other, is not a differ- 
ence between passive sense and creative intellect. The con- 
trast is rather (to quote James's phrase) "between two aspects, 
in which all mental facts without exception may be taken, 
their structural aspect, as being subjective, and their functional 
aspect as being cognitions. In the former aspect, the highest 
as well as the lowest is a feeling, a peculiarly tinged segment. 
This tingeing is its sensitive body, the wie ihm zu Muthe 
ist, the way it feels whilst passing. In the other aspect, 
the lowest mental fact as well as the highest may grasp 
some bit of truth as its content, even though that truth were 
as relationless a matter as a bare unlocalized and undated qual- 
ity of pain. From the cognitive point of view (he continues), 
all mental facts are intellections. From the subjective point 
of view all are feelings. Once admit that the passing and 
evanescent are as real parts of the stream as the distinct and 
comparatively abiding; once allow that fringes and halos, in- 
articulate perceptions, whereof the objects are as yet unnamed, 
mere nascencies of cognition, premonitions, awarenesses of di- 
rection, are thoughts sui generis, as much as articulate imagin- 
ings and propositions are; once restore, I say, the vague to 
its psychological rights, and the matter presents no further 
difficulty. 

"And then we see that the current opposition of Feeling to 



HISTORICAL DERIVATION 385 

Knowledge is quite a false issue. If every feeling is at the 
same time a bit of knowledge, we ought no longer to talk of 
mental states differing by having more or less of the cognitive 
quality; they only differ in knowing more or less, in having 
much fact or little fact for their object. The feeling of a 
broad scheme of relations is a feeling that knows much; the 
feeling of a simple quality is a feeling that knows little. But 
the knowing itself, whether of much or of little, has the same 
essence, and is as good knowing in the one case as in the other. 
Concept and image, thus discriminated through their objects, 
are consubstantial in their inward nature, as modes of feeling. 
The one, as particular, will no longer be held to be a relatively 
base sort of entity, to be taken as a matter of course, whilst 
the other, as universal, is celebrated as a sort of standing 
miracle, to be adored but not explained. Both concept and 
image, qua subjective, are singular and particular. Both are 
moments of the stream, which come and in an instant are 
no more. The word universality has no meaning as applied 
to their psychic body or structure, which is always finite. It 
only has a meaning when applied to their use, import, or refer- 
ence to the kind of object they may reveal" (pp. 18-19, foot- 
note). 

It is a curious fact that this locus classicus for the psychol- 
ogical distinction between structure and function should be 
lodged in a footnote and should be reproduced in the same form 
in the chapter on Conception in the Principles of Psychology 
of 1890 (vol. i. 478-479). I do not remember that James 
elsewhere makes use in his psychological writings of the term 
'structure' ; although his whole descriptive account of 'feelings' 
and 'thoughts/ of unf ringed and fringed segments of conscious- 
ness, of the 'psychic body' and its cognitive meaning or func- 
tion, is logkally constitutive of his entire treatment. This neglect 
of an important pair of terms which he seems to have intro- 
duced into our literature, appears to be explained by the fact 
that his own main interest lay in cognition and in epistemologi- 
cal problems. James excelled, as we all know, in a keen, flash- 
ing kind of observation (though continued and consistent scru- 
tiny under experimental conditions irked him) ; and we owe to 
him a large amount of inspective information upon the transi- 
tive and fleeting aspects of experience. But, even here, the 
'feelings' chiefly interest him for the cognitive functions which 
they carry and much less for their own existential form or, as 
he puts it, their "substantive mental kernel-of-content," their 
"psychic body" or "structure." It is also worth noting, as we 



386 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

pass, that the men stamped and impressed by James's teachings 
have seldom made use of this fundamental distinction and still 
more rarely have they added to the structure or the existential 
side of experience. Only Angell, as I recall, has taken seriously 
the distinction; though he used it, as we shall presently see, 
in quite a different context. 

Now if we turn toward the progress of psychology upon the 
continent, we shall find still earlier than James a distinction 
which bears as directly upon our approach to the psychologies 
called 'structural' as does James. The setting of the two dis- 
tinctions, however, is different. Instead of the two parallel 
aspects, structural and functional, we now find psychology tak- 
ing, at the hands of different psychologists and within the 
framework of different systems, the two general directions 
which we might expect from James's distinction. This diver- 
gence appears in Brentano's empirical psychology of act and 
Wundt's experimental psychology of observed process? Bren- 
tano's fundamental facts are, as you know, activities, the 
activities of ideating, judging and loving-hating. The differ- 
entia of these psychical activities is their reference to an object, . 
a relation to a content. This 'immanent objectivity' is never 
to be found in physical phenomena. Wundt's fundamental 
facts, on the other hand, are directly drawn from the observa- 
tion of the processes of life. Physiology views life, so to say, 
from the outside ; but psychology from the inside. The psychi- 
cal side of life, as it is immediately given, is complex; and 
the primary function of psychology is therefore to analyse it 
into its simpler ultimately into its elementary parts or pro- 
cesses. So far as logic goes, this psychical side of life is 
James's existential or structural side ; though James was quick 
to contend that it was no more subject to dismembering by 
analysis than is the fluent water in the stream. To dismember 
was, for him, to destroy. At most only moments or phases 
or coloring could be distinguished as they flash by. For 
Wundt, on the other hand, observation was able to distinguish 
sensations, which differed among themselves both in quality 
and in intensity. In fact, those were the only attributive 
characteristics of the simple processes. The sensations as so 
observed and so described made no reference in any direction, 

'Brentano's Psychologie^ vom empirischen Standpunkte and Wundt's 
Grundzuge der physiologischen Psychologic (first edition) both ap- 
peared in the year 1874. Cf. E. B. Titcfcener, Amer. J. Psychol., 1921, 
32, 10&-120. 



HISTORICAL DERIVATION 387 

neither to the agents and energies of stimulus, nor to the 
bodily organs themselves, nor to the objects of knowledge or 
of desire. They were purely existential. Such matters as 
judgment, conception and emotive attitude toward objects lie 
outside and beyond this observable region of the mental. 
Actual experience always contains formations and complexes 
of the simple processes; but those formations, when existen- 
tially regarded, are psychical just as their constituent processes 
are, and the forms and laws of their construction suggest one 
of the major problems of psychology. The acts of Brentano, 
on the other hand, with their immanent objectivity lead us at 
once to the functional relation of the individual to the objects 
of apprehension, to the truths and acknowledgments reached 
in judgment, and to the objects of emotive likes and dislikes, 
of desire and interest. All this is not to say that Brentano 
works out his functional view of consciousness as James works 
out his doctrine of cognition; it is only to say that the same 
functional aspect of experience as meaning or reference char- 
acterizes that side of James's psychology as it does Brentano's. 

Neither do I mean to contend that Wundt, on the other side, 
succeeded, when he came to attention, to action and to thought, 
in maintaining his existential and descriptive view of mind, 
which was doubtless suggested, in large measure, by his earlier 
studies in sense-physiology. But that was his point of de- 
parture and it was a view which both led him toward the 
direct experimental attack upon psychological problems and 
led his pupils and followers to a more explicit, and possibly 
more consistent, "structural" view in the Jamesian sense. His 
psychology, then, with all its frailties and limitations, looks 
distinctly toward a scientific future of exploration and discov- 
ery in the laboratory. 4 

One of the first attempts made by the pupils of Wundt to 
bring together experimental facts, with as little general theory 
and philosophical bias as possible, was Kiilpe's Grundriss of 
1893. Since this Grundiss or Outline was "based upon the re- 
sults of experimental investigation" we may expect to find in it 

*0f course we must not think of either point of view as originating 
with these two men. Both are much older. Of. Titchener, op. cit., 
p. 119. We need not follow the differences between the non-struc- 
tural psychologies of function and of act. Titchener has written 
critically of this distinction in his articles upon Functional psychology 
and the psychology of act (Amer. J. PsychoL 1921, 32, 519-542; 1922 
33, 43-83). He is here inclined to read into "function" a biological 
and teleological sense which does not accord with James's meaning. 



388 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

a strong emphasis placed upon the analytical observation of ex- 
perience. By limiting this observation to those properties which 
are dependent upon the physical organism Kiilpe followed 
Wundt to an examination of the elementary processes and of the 
modes of their interconnection. One of the virtues of Kiilpe's 
psychology was the simplicity and the directness of its logic. 
Another was its success in bringing together in a natural, 
coherent and empirical way, most of the laboratory studies 
then extant. Both virtues were destined to exert an influence 
in later "structural" envisagements of the psychological field. 

From Kiilpe we must turn to Ebbinghaus, who likewise ap- 
proaches psychology from the controlled observation of the 
laboratory. The first edition of his Grwndzuge began to ap- 
pear (I. Halbband) in 1897. For him the immediate experi- 
ence of the living being furnishes the materials of psychology. 
But this material is both extensive and complicated and, like 
the body, it displays a high degree of unity and integrity. The 
mental life is organized even as the body is organized. How 
then is it to be studied and known ? We are accustomed, says 
Ebbinghaus, 5 to approach any complicated set of phenomena 
from three different directions and thus to regard it in turn 
from three points of view. First we regard it existentially, 
for what it is. Here we analyse the complex into simpler 
parts, work out the structure (Ban) and the properties of 
these parts, and the mode of their combination; secondly, we 
consider the occurrences and changes to which these parts are 
subjected, and thirdly, we regard the developmental history of 
both structure and changes. 

These three ways-of -regarding appear, for example, in the 
sciences of organic nature as (1) morphology, which seeks 
the laws of structure of living things, (2) physiology, the 
description of the life-processes, the functions of the organs, 
a,nd (3) the embryological or racial history of form and func- 
tion. No one of these modes of approach to natural phen- 
omena is better or more complete than the others. Each is 
abstract; but each is necessary to the understanding of organic 
nature. The mental life, too, has its temporal development 
and transformation. Each aspect must be studied in its place. 
Mind is, to be sure, unitary and total ; but we shall know little 
about it unless we examine its rich variety, its on-goings and 
its genetic changes. Our examination must not of course 

B H. Ebbinghaus, Grundsuge der Psychologie, 1905, (2nd ed.), vol. i, 
176-182. 



HISTORICAL DERIVATION 389 

reduce the totality to a sum or to an aggregate of parts or 
of separate functions. Thus Ebbinghaus proceeds in his own 
exposition, first treating his material anatomically or struc- 
turally, then advancing to the functional view, and ending with 
the facts and laws of development. Although the logic of the 
exposition is by no means so clear-cut as in Kiilpe, the three- 
fold treatment is sufficiently exemplified. He always keeps 
within sight, however, of his living organic totality. 6 

In his article of 1898 7 upon The postulates of a structural 
psychology Titchener repeats Ebbinghaus's analogy with the 
biological sciences, applying the tripartite division also to tax- 
onomy, ecology and phylogeny. The analogy is, as he thinks, 
complete. "We can represent modern psychology" so he de- 
clares "as the exact counterpart of modern biology. There 
are three ways of approaching the one as there are three 
ways of approaching the other." (450). "The primary aim 
of the experimental psychologist has been to analyse the struc- 
ture of mind; to ravel out the elemental processes from the 
tangle of consciousness. . . . His task is a vivisection. . . . 
He tries to discover, first of all, what is there and in what 
quantity, not what it is there for" (450) . Mind thus becomes 
"a complex of processes, shaped and moulded under the con- 
ditions of the physical organism" (451). 

But "descriptive" psychology the psychology of memory, 
recognition, judgment, volition and so on Titchener dis- 
covers to be "chiefly occupied with problems of function" or 
of "mental physiology." Here there is "much of value" as 
he admits; but the functional point of view cannot "lead to 
results of scientific finality." The revolt from a philosophical 
treatment of faculties rather leads straight toward a scientific 
morphology, which is well designed to supply a foundation to 
the new science. Our author predicts "a long period of ana- 
lytical research, whose results .... shall ultimately serve as 
basis for the psychology of function" (454). He then goes 
on to describe the elementary structures in the attributive 
terms which are familiar to all of you and the complex mor- 
phological formations, the structural "organs," in the classes 
worked out by Wundt and Kiilpe from the logic of John Stuart 

*See, e. g., his treatment of the general attributes of sensation: form, 
magnitude, interval, movement, identity, similarity, difference, and 
the like. The recent psychology of the Gestalt lies much nearer to 
this type of psychology than to the systems of Wundt and Kulpe. 

7 E. B. Titchener, Philos. Rev., 1898, 7, 449465. 



390 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Mill. He ends by the anticipation that the psychology of func- 
tion may have "a great future ;" but also with the conviction 
that "the best hope for psychology lies today in a continuance 
of structural analysis." 

In estimating the importance of this paper, which is some- 
times referred to as marking the entrance of the structural 
point of view into psychology, we must observe that its main 
result was to clarify, as by a refined process of the etcher, the 
distinction which had already been made. It is very much 
cleaner-cut than Ebbinghaus, if only because Titchener was 
throwing up a substantial wall of partition behind which he 
obviously meant to labor and to give battle ; while Ebbinghaus 
was laying out the wide psychological domains into great fields 
in which he proposed freely to pass from place to place with 
only a formal recognition of inside boundaries. However im- 
portant or trivial we shall find the accomplishments of struc- 
turalism to be, we must recognize the gain in clear thinking 
which accrued to Titchener's sharply drawn distinction between 
the analytical psychology of structure and the descriptive psy- 
chology of mental operation and functional performance. 

Within analytical observation itself, he made it clear that 
much that passes for an introspective photography of mind 
was a presentation of logical meanings and of ethical and 
social values; the "unschooled introspection" of the mental 
"Is-for," he called it, as set against the schooled observation 
of what consciously "Is" (1899, 29 Iff). While he tended con- 
stantly to speak of the former as the "besetting sin of the 
descriptive psychologist" and of the latter as the truly psy- 
chological method, he does admit a psychology of psychophysi- 
cal (as distinguished from logical, ethical and social) functions, 
in which value-to-the-organism shall be the basal concept (1899, 
293). Taken as a doctrine and as a fundamental mode of 
procedure in psychological observation, then, the structural 
point of view in Titchener seeks to perpetuate and to clarify 
the contention of James, Wundt, Kiilpe, Ebbinghaus, and many 
others, that the ultimate materials of psychology are Erlebnisse, 
not Erfahrungen; that is to say, the fluent processes of concrete 
experiencings, not those crystallized and logicized ideas of 
Hume, Spencer and the Mills, under which he had been reared. 
In the light of subsequent events in psychology, it is worth 
noting that so early as 1899 our author had regarded his dis- 
tinction of structure and function as "no more than a working 
schema by which one's present knowledge may be temporarily 



HISTORICAL DERIVATION 391 

arranged a schema to be ruthlessly discarded so soon as a 
better is proposed" (297). 

Now is is almost a truism that no one understands himself 
until he understands his opponent. We can hardly expect, 
therefore, to recover the structural point of view of that time 
unless we consider the counter doctrine of function against 
which it contended. Talk as they would in polite terms of pa- 
rallel advance, dividing the field and complementing each the 
other, the underlying conviction of each. party was that it was 
itself the main reliance of psychology. Sharpening and narrow- 
ing the concept of a dissecting kind of analysis only tended to 
establish more firmly those who went in for mental functions. 
We have seen the influence of biology in modeling the newer 
science of psychology. We must also observe that biology 
threatened to absorb psychology, as well as to set it models. This 
threat came through the functionalists. Mind is, so they said, 
but an organic device. It is one of the means of subsistence 
and of adjustment to the environment. Perceiving, valuing, 
appreciating, acting and knowing are devices for survival. They 
are fuctional resources. Such a view appeared soon after 
Titchener's article in J. R. Angell's espousal of function.* 
Structure, for him, bore only upon the discernment of com- 
plexity in fragments of consciousness. It was not otherwise 
comparable to the cellular members of a living body or to the 
physical and chemical elements. Function, on the contrary, 
was the main aspect of our common experiences. It was. 
the "how" and the "why" of our processes of conscious adjust- 
ment; and since it included cognition, conation, affective ap- 
preciation, and much besides, it led straight into all the prob- 
lems of logic, ethics, aesthetics and the other philosophical dis- 
ciplines. 

An interesting variation in the existential or structural treat- 
ment appeared in the writings of Mtinsterberg near the be- 
ginning of the century. In his Presidential Address of 1898 9 " 
before the American Psychological Association Miinsterberg 
distinguished psychology from history, contending that psy- 
chology, like physics, regards its objects as complexes of ele- 
ments, while history deals with the will-attitudes and the pur- 

^The relations of structural and functional psychology to philoso- 
phy. Univ. of Chicago Decennial PubL, 1903, ser. 1, vol. vi, pt. 2,, 
55-73; also Philos. Rev. t 1903, 12, 243-271. The actual contents of a 
functional psychology based upon evolutionary conceptions are set 
forth by Angell in his Psychology ; an introductory study of the: 
structure and function of human consciousness, 1904. 

Psychol. Rev., 1899, 6, 1,31. 



392 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

poses of a person. But later 10 he came to distinguish within 
psychology itself both causal and purposive varieties. The 
first studied consciousness by way of analysis, reducing it to 
simplest parts, which were then causally explained by reference 
to neural processes. The second sought to understand in terms 
of value the purposes of man. Both taken together gave Miin- 
sterberg a basis for his psychology of applications. The first 
appears roughly to represent the structural point of view ; but, 
in reality, it is a mixture of process and function. Sensations 
and their associated components appear along with such mat- 
ters of performance as action, perception, and the activities of 
the social mind. Where, therefore, Miinsterberg speaks of 
"the world of mental processes" (1914, 285), we are not to 
take the phrase in the sense of Titchener's anatomical descrip- 
tion. It soon became the fashion to 'reconcile* structure and 
function, just as it is now the fashion to reconcile behaviorism 
and introspection. Among these attempts at reconciliation of 
the two standpoints may be mentioned the Presidential Address 
of Professor Calkins before the same Association in 1905. 11 
Carrying over George Darwin's distinction between the biolo- 
gist's functional relationship of the organism to the environ- 
ment and the physicist's analytic interest in the ultimate struc- 
tures of matter, Calkins attempted to show that the postulates 
of a self -psychology could well make use of analysis (which 
she held to be the essential point of the structuralists) and at 
the same time make use of the category of function. The self, 
that is to say, is to be at once structurally analysed and func- 
tionally set into relation with the physical and social environ- 
ment. This view, which regarded with disfavor the biological 
trend of the times among the functionalists, depended, of 
course, upon its basal conception of a conscious "self." Its al- 
leged merit is, in this connection, the ackowledgment of an 
inescapable self, which demands for its description both an 
analysis into structures and the recognition of outside func- 
tional relations. 

From the turn of the century, and especially after the rival 
claims of the structural and the functional psychologies had 
been set forth by Titchener and Angell, vigorous and wide- 
spread discussions upon the distinction sprang up on all sides. 12 

IO E. g., in Psychology, general and applied, 1914. 

n M. *W. Calkins, Psychol. Rev., 1906, 13, 61-81 ; cf . Psychology as 
science of selves, Philos Rev., 1900, 9, 490-501. 

"Among the earliest attacks upon structuralism stand those of 
W. Caldwell in Psychol Rev., 1898, 5, 401-408; 1899, 6, 187-191. 



HISTORICAL DERIVATION 393 

Out of these discussions grew a very well marked partisan 
difference which was destined to play a prominent part in the 
writings and in the laboratories of American psychology for 
the next two decades. Let me emphasize the reference to the 
laboratories, for structuralism has laid great weight upon its 
own suitability for the experimental attack upon psychological 
problems. By its contributions to experimental research its 
value may then fairly be judged. Next time we shall begin 
here and go on to consider the fruits of the structural view and 
try to estimate their importance for our subject. 



CHAPTER XVIII 

THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS* 



BY MADISON BENTLEY 



A convenient starting-point for our examination of struc- 
turalism, as it actually worked itself out in the laboratories, 
may be set by a summary of the problems of experimental 
psychology which was made in 1904 by Professor Titchener 
for the International Congress in St. Louis. 

The materials for this summary Titchener gathered, as he 
tells us, 13 from five representative periodicals, two German, 
one French and two American, and all of them at that time 
of several years standing. 

After drawing a distinction between the "psychological" and 
the "psychophysical" experiment (the former aiming at an 
"introspective acquaintance with the processes and formations 
of a given consciousness" ; the latter at a "numerical determin- 
ation"), the reviewer goes on to give the result of his survey. 
He finds (1) that the recent course of experimental psychology 
had been away from psychophysics and toward introspection; 
(2) that studies upon sensation, attention, perception, memory, 
association and action had been abundant, and (3) that the 
trend had been from the simple in mind toward the complex. 
His counsel for future work lays stress, as we might expect, 
upon those fields where the structural mode is most at home; 
first upon sensation, affection and attention, designated as the 
three fundamental departments of psychology, and afterwards 
upon the analytical side of memory, association, action and 
the higher intellectual processes. He is obviously troubled 
by the functional terms "perception" and "imagination" which 
he would like to banish or discard. In the one topic he finds "no 
very pressing problem," and, in the other, experiment "hardly 
over the threshold." Finally, the conquest of the total con- 
sciousness, the "ultimate goal" of experiment, appears to be 
remote. At the end Titchener considers briefly and with some 
diffidence the experimental problems of the non-structuralist, 
the man who is not "enamored of introspection." Though he 
obviously tries to be non-partisan, he virtually drives the non- 
structuralist from the study of the normal, human adult. Ex- 
periment here "must take the form of introspective analysis." 

*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan- 
uary 6, 1926. 
"Amer. J. PsychoL, 1905, 16, 208-234. 



396 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

He has "little sympathy or patience" with others. Their mode 
is inherently "vicious/ 5 and so on. A sort of tolerance is 
shown for outsiders in animal and child psychology and in the 
treatment of the abnormal ; and the claims made for structural 
analysis in those domains are decidedly weak. 

Here we have, then, twenty years ago, a very fair intimation 
of what we may expect of a structural psychology, as well as 
a statement of its past conquests in the experimental field. 
Now let us turn the page to a later time and look for ful- 
filment. 

When, in the autumn of 1909, Clark University celebrated 
its twentieth anniversary, Professor Titchener was asked to 
review the past decade in experimental psychology, 14 a period 
which was long enough, as he thought, to warrant an inventory. 
Let us see what the claims of structuralism were at this time. 
The speaker prefaced his inventory by a high tribute to Ebbing- 
haus, recently dead, and by an anticipation that only "a small 
minority" in his audience would adopt his standpoint of un- 
applied or "pure" science and would accept his conclusions. 

By way of review Titchener found heavy inroads of practi- 
cal interest, mentioning Meumann and pedagogy, Stern and 
Aussage, Jung and diagnosis, Miinsterberg and psychotherapy. 
He hints that such men are casual visitors to psychology, dwell- 
ing for a time at the psychological cross-roads and passing on 
with the gratitude and the "godspeed" of the faithful. In 
this implied canon of criticism you see now, as some of us saw 
then, the parti pris, the logical petitio, and confusion of struc- 
tural analysis with psychology ueberltaupt; and you will be pre- 
pared for the standards of criticism by means of which the 
decade's fruitfulness was judged. Good energy has been "di- 
verted," as we are told, into practical channels which might 
otherwise have been expended in the service of science, while 
non-psychological "temperaments," attracted to the laboratory, 
whether "by curiosity, by mere chance of novelty," or in a 
"serious mood," have "placed positive hindrances in the way 
of scientific advance." 

The topical review is the same as before. Knowledge of 
sensation has increased, though theory there is still unsatisfac- 
tory. The psychophysics of sensation has most strikingly ad- 
vanced. We well remember that our author has himself, in 
the meantime, made (especially by way of critical and clarified 

"Amer. /. Psychol, 1910, 21, 404r421. 



THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS 397 

exposition) a very large contribution in his Quantitative Psy- 
chology. 15 In simple feeling the reviewer found much product 
but not much gain. The problem is still "upon the regular 
waiting list," where it remains, as I venture to think, in this 
year of grace 1926. The subject of attention has gained by 
"many systematic treatises and laboratory studies" upon the 
measurement of clearness. Perception again troubles Titchener 
as a "field of vast range and uncertain limits." Certain spatial 
and temporal perceptions have been advanced, notably by Be- 
nussi and other members of the Austrian school of Meinong; 
while biology and motor theories have run riot in America. 
Memory and association have profited more in the psychophysi- 
cal and practical directions than in their pure, analytical prob- 
lems. Of the four researches mentioned, two authors (Kuhl- 
mann and Whipple) had been connected with your own Uni- 
versity. Action has taken strides in the way of structural analy- 
sis, Ach and Watt making noteworthy contributions. Imagina- 
tion is still "virgin territory." The emotions await agreement 
upon the affective qualities ; but the experimental studies of the 
thought-processes have, more than any one line of investigation, 
"characterized the decennium." You know as well as I the 
works of Wiirzburg and of Binet, Bovet, and Woodworth to 
which reference is made, and you also know the clear-cut ex- 
position of all these works in Titchener's own "Experimental 
psychology of the thought processes" (1909). 

For the extensions of experiment outside these preferred 
headings of the structuralist, Titchener has time as before 
for "only a word or two." Individual psychology is increasing 
in importance, while the study of the abnormal has fallen below 
expectations. The psychology of the animals is growing; but 
the mental endowment of the animals can be profitably studied 
"only by men trained in human psychology." Titchener closes 
his review by the declaration that "to approach the study of 
mind without analysis would, in fact, be nothing less than 
ridiculous; and, in fact, no one does it," a statement which 
would scarcely have been made ten years later. 

I have dwelt upon these reviews of 1905 and 1910 less 
because they represent achievements in the field of psychology 
at large than because they may fairly be supposed to give a 

"In another connection I have questioned the logic of bringing the 
psychophysical metric methods under sensation instead of under the 
rubrics of function. (The field of psychology, 1924, 400413.) 



398 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

favorable view of structuralism during the years when that 
form of psychological activity was especially vigorous and pro- 
ductive. In the later review (the earlier is chiefly based upon 
a general survey of a few of the journals) Titchener cites over 
60 articles and books as making contributions to his brand of 
"pure science." But we must remark that a dozen of these are 
psychophysical (most of them works on Methodik) and of 
these only two can be said to be chiefly analytical in his sense. 
Moreover, this whole dozen would appear to be at least as con- 
tributive to other brands of psychology; while several of the 
works can scarcely be called "structural" at all, either in aim or 
intent. These include Bering's Lehre, Nagel's Handbuch, 
Wundt's Bemerkungen, Pillsbury's Attention, Burr's Auf- 
merksamkeit, Woodworth's Imageless Thought, and the whole 
list of Gottingen studies of Association. To be sure many of 
these works have been found to be useful to men working under 
what Titchener calls the "temperament" of the structuralist. But 
all who know the psychological literature of those times will 
see that, from most of them, the non-structuralist however 
"impure" his temperament has been able to abstract a good 
deal of comfort. Nothing could be more useful, for example, 
to a certain "functional temperament" than G. E. Miiller's 
Komplex, Pillsbury's and Diirr's Attention, and Messer's and 
Woodworth's Gedanken; while the debt of Gestaltpsychologie 
to Hering and Ebbinghaus is actually as great as it would be if 
it were frankly acknowledged. 

The same selective appropriation from sources common to 
all psychologies appears in Ruckmick's review in 191 5. 16 By 
counting titles in certain sections 17 of the Psychological Index 
(1905-1915) this historian discovers "roughly two-and-a-half 
times as many introspective as non-introspective experimental 
papers." Again we must make allowance for the outlying 
provinces of psychology (intensively cultivated during this de- 
cade) and also for the fact that "introspective" covers a multi- 
tude of meanings and is by no means coincident with the 
"structural" variety. The outcome may supply a hard nut for 
the behaviorist to crack; but I doubt whether anyone, no 
matter what his "temperament/' can extract much consolation 
from the ratio. 

The logical maturity of our doctrine was within sight whea 

**C. A. Ruckmick, The last decade of psychology in review, Amer. 
Psychol. Ass., Dec., 1915, and Psychol. Bull., 1916, 13, 109-120. 
"Coincident, in the main, with Titchener's range. 



THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS 399 

Kulpe and his pupils approached the citadel of thought by 
way of the analytical method. Not daunted by Marbe's meagre 
results with the simpler "judgments" or by Binet's divinatory 
distinctions in the field of the intellect, Kiilpe set out upon the 
direction indicated in Ach's studies of action by the method of 
"systematic experimental introspection." We know the gen- 
eral issue of the work. Wundt thought the method employed 
(Ausfragemethode} logically imperfect, and he himself had 
resorted to the genetic method of the Volkerpsychologie. Titch- 
ener, who was presently to undertake these problems in his 
own laboratory by way of structural analysis, finds 18 in 1909 

the "three most tangible things characteristic and new" in 

the outcome to be "a specific problem set: a principle of ex- 
planation discovered: a volume of untrimmed introspections 
offered in evidence." 

There are many opinions upon the contribution made to 
thinking by the 'structural' methods. I doubt, however, 
whether anyone who has tried to write a coherent psychology 
of thinking would contend that these methods have either sup- 
plied the materials for this difficult chapter or so much as in- 
dicated a usable means toward its experimental conquest. We 
have, to be sure, various raw Gedankenelemete and the pro- 
cesses of the sensationalists; but, since thinking is a mode of 
performance and not any specific set of processes, the method 
of structural analysis would appear to be at most a preliminary 
reconnaissance of new territory and not a means of conquest. 

Clark University has played its part in the history of struc- 
tural examination. The careful and meticulous researches of 
the late Professor Baird represent, as it seems to me, the most 
persistent attempt to resolve the subtlest and most refrac- 
tory problems of experience by the methods of analysis. If 
they did not succeed in storming the citadels of thinking, they 
stand, nevertheless, as notable instances of refined scientific 
procedure in the laboratory, and they have, moreover, produced 
factual materials with which every student of thought must 
hereafter acquaint himself. 

It is impossible, at this time, to place a final value upon the 
standpoint which we have been examining. If I set down 
what seem to me to be its psychological virtues and its limita- 
tions, I do this principally by way of an individual opinion 
when complete objectivity is still out of the question. But 

"Lectures en the experimental psychology of the thought Processes, 
1909, 165. 



400 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

opinion at least challenges divergent opinion, and it also stands 
the chance of containing a partial truth. 

In the first place, structuralism was timely. It stood for 
high standards of research when a multitude of new problems 
appeared for which psychology had no canons and no adequate 
procedures. Philosophy, physiology, general biology, and the 
arts of application all stood at the door demanding admittance. 
By setting off a definite and circumscribed area our doctrine 
demanded the best empirical tools and means available. It took 
over, notably from physiology, certain definite problems and 
these it made really and clearly psychological. The immediate 
formulation of functionalism and the gradual emergence of an 
"objective" point of view naturally followed. These proposals 
had, at the least, something definite against which to protest. 
Protestantism is never a primary movement in human thought. 
It presupposes some current doctrine, creed, or method to pro- 
test. The more definite and aggressive the entrenched doc- 
trine, the better for the protestants. 

In the second place, structuralism had the scientific virtue 
of reducing logical concepts and of setting free certain prob- 
lems which demanded an experimental solution. When we 
examine psychology at the opening of this century we see that 
this was not a superfluous or merely academic virtue. 

In the third place, structuralism set a premium upon his- 
torical studies and upon an historical continuity within psy- 
chology. Other types of psychology might but so far as I 
know no other type does insist so effectively upon historical 
coherence. The first generation of psychologists (the genera- 
tion responsible for the opening of the laboratories and the es- 
tablishment of academic departments) knew their antecedents. 
Had they not, I doubt whether they could have made their 
way with presidents, trustees, and the great public. Such 
historical knowledge has not been the rule in the succeeding 
generations. Flagrant instances of ignorance of antecedents, 
and of present rival doctrines as well, lead one to wonder 
what mental age would be indicated by an intelligence test 
applied to psychologists upon their own subject. You will 
agree, as I think, that no single individual has done so much 
to cultivate this historical knowledge of psychology as has Pro- 
fessor Titchener. 

Again, and finally, the great productivity in certain branches 
of psychology under the standpoint of structural analysis is 
acknowledged by everyone who knows the literature of the 



THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS 401 

last quarto-century. Who can here estimate relative values? 
It would be a wise psychologist, much more objective than the 
most ardent of the "objectivists," who could accord to each 
school its just due; and, once accorded, what school would be 
convinced ! 

Upon certain general points, however, we may, as I think, 
look for agreement among those who are accustomed to keep 
the run of psychological production here and abroad. 

First, it is obvious that research under the category of "struc- 
ture" has been most productive in certain limited fields of 
adult human psychology. These fields include sensation, simple 
feeling, attention and action. Here description in "process" 
(or its equivalent) has greatly added to our knowledge. While 
not inventive or revolutionary the methods here have been 
as I should say sounder and more productive than any other 
methods in psychology. But wherever the facts and the con- 
cepts have called for an account of operation or performance, 
as in perception, memory and thinking, the structural methods 
have shown themselves to be inadequate. In the fields of the 
abnormal, the genetic and the individual, not much has been 
contributed from this direction. 

In the second place, the revival and extension of quantitative 
problems and procedures owe much to structuralism, or, at 
the least, to certain advocates of that doctrine. Titchener's 
Quantitative Psychology was almost encyclopedic in its pro- 
portions. It has greatly advanced what we may call the psy- 
chologization of the metric methods. But whether measure- 
ment in psychology is really mental measurement, as some 
structuralists have argued, I have had occasion to doubt; for 
I have thought that what we actually measure by the psycho- 
physical methods is functional output and not anything which 
can be turned into "process." However that may be, our debt 
to the strict methodology of the structuralists is here very 
great ; and it will appear greater as the promise of the present 
is gradually fulfilled. 

On the other side of the ledger, too, certain entries must be 
made. In the first place, structuralism has, to my mind, never 
justified its dogmatic assertion that first-hand observation of 
human experience was synomynous with structural observation. 
Neither has it justified its contention that the main method 
of science was analysis. It is, as I think, not much less than 
a caricature of the sciences of nature to say that the physicist, 
the chemist, and the zoologist are always and only analysing. 



402 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

Koehler has, as we know, recently given very definite indica- 
tions to the contrary; but outside the range of this dogma it 
has, for some time, been generally conceived to be a formal 
and logical not a realistic view of science which has brought 
into relief the typical chemist or physicist as forever breaking 
down his substances into constituent elements. Analysis, surely ! 
but not simply analysis; and, for many problems, not analysis 
at all. 

Once more. The dogma of the simple has tempted the struc- 
turalist to confuse his province with the general range of psy- 
chological problems and methods. What this doctrine can do 
has been abundantly shown. Its genius is expressed in the 
range of its actual accomplishments. But what lies beyond 
must also be considered. It succeeds best, as it seems to me, 
in its description of the qualitative variety within experience. 
There it is very strong where the doctrine of the Gestalt is 
weak. But it needs to be complemented and supplemented by 
many other characterizations of experience, to say nothing of 
those problems of organic performance in which experience 
is only implied. I do not hold with those who believe that 
a simple verbal formula (e.g., the formula of stimulus-re- 
sponse), with only a general and hypothetical conception of 
bodily mechanisms, will enable the psychologist to meet the de- 
mands both of science and of the various forms of practice 
from animal training to sociology. That savors of science 
by the attachment of labels. But I see no reason why all the 
knowledge we can muster should not be used by those interested 
in the arts of practice. In reflecting upon the call to adminis- 
trative duties of your late Professor Sanford, Titchener re- 
marked 19 that experimental results must justify themselves by 
some sanction, some principle of co-ordination, and that, in ex- 
perimental psychology, he could see but two sanctions; the 
first "system, the applied logic of general psychology, and the 
second application." Surely, if we justify the research of our 
laboratories by way of these two sanctions, we shall discover 
not one single experimental road to follow, but many. 

There is still another defect which, while it is not peculiar 
to structuralism alone, deserves to be set down in this list 
with considerable deliberation. It appears in the assumption 
that the parts or members of experience run a course parallel 
to that of excitatory processes in the receptor. In the struc- 
tural accounts of sensation each element has its own specific 

"Amer. J. PsychoL, 1925, 36, 159. 



THE WORK OF THE STRUCTURALISTS 403 

antecedent, and the 'theories' of sensation (visual, auditory, 
and the rest) attempt to set forth the antecedent term in this 
invariable sequence. A corollary of this one-to-one relation 
between sensation and neural process appears in the emphasis 
laid by the structuralist upon "stimulus." 20 We see, then, how 
naturally sensationalism has tended toward a peripheral and 
sensory theory of bodily substrates. Again, in Angell's bio- 
logical functionalism consciousness confesses its dependence 
upon physical antecedents within and without the organism. 
While the one-to-one correlation is less rigidly carried out here, 
the same principle of determination is evident. Only in the 
selective powers of attention and volition does consciousness 
wear the appearance of an originator and director. Nowhere, 
however, does this principle appear so fundamental to any psy- 
chological doctrine as in the stimulus-response hypothesis of 
behaviorism. There the consequent term is not sensation and 
not conscious function, but movement. As the organism is 
stimulated so does it move. Without this one-to-one parallel- 
ism behaviorism falls to the ground, or else it becomes (as 
we now frequently see it becoming) something different, though 
wearing the same label. 

I have spoken of this common tendency as a 'defect.' There 
is, as I think, enough evidence to sanction the statement. The 
upholders of the Gestodt-theorie have not minimized as we 
all know the deficiencies of this hypothesis of a constant re- 
lation of psychological antecedent and consequent (Konstanz- 
hypothese). For them stimulus is not the real determiner of 
experience. As the latter is always a unitary whole or totality, 
so does it depend upon a similar kind of total-function in the 
body. Stimulus is the more or less incidental occasion of the 
experience, not the model or pattern of its integral charac- 
teristics. While an allied tendency to forsake local functions 
and neuronal tracts in the brain appears in the cerebral studies 
of Franz, Lashley and others, as well as in much current work 
among the neurologists von F&ch. Now the sequences "stimu- 
lus-sensation" and "stimulus-movement" rest upon the old con- 
ceptions of local excitation and of the reflex-arc as the repre- 
sentative functional unit of the nervous system; conceptions 
which have, as it seems to many, lost (in spite of their 
simplicity) most of their former usefulness in psychology. On 

The study of the affective qualities has always been more diffi- 
cult. Structural analysis has vacillated between the views of re- 
ceptors and no-specific receptors for the simple feelings. 



404 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

the one -hand, structuralism and behaviorism have laid too 
much emphasis upon stimulus and its direct organic effects 
at the receptor, in the brain, in experience, and in movement. 
Configurationism, on the other, goes too far in making stim- 
ulus and receptor merely incidental to experience. In hold- 
ing to an intermediate position I should say that stimulus and 
the integral and functionally tuned body are co-determiners, 
which must be taken into strict account whether we seek the 
essential antecedents of experience, of the structural attributes, 
or of the organic movement. 

Thus our adverse criticisms tend rather toward the pretenses 
and the inherent limitations than toward the actual procedures 
of structuralism. There is no doubt, moreover, that the criti- 
cisms should be tempered by reflection upon the complementary 
frailties and limitations of competing standpoints. If this creed 
does ultimately rest upon a certain kind of "temperament," as 
we have heard that it does, and upon a preference for prob- 
lems of a certain restricted type, as we have seen that it does, 
then its claim to supply the one substantial foundation for our 
subject or to represent a "purer" and more desirable set of 
scientific principles than others would seem to stand with no 
more justification than do the similar pretensions of rival doc- 
trines. 

In our final estimation of this standpoint we must consider, 
as we observed at the beginning, that it represents a closed 
chapter in psychological history. 21 - We take the past as it 
stands. We act foolishly when we try to ignore it; and we 
proceed with wisdom when we acknowledge the substantial con- 
tributions which the doctrine of mental structures has made 
to the subject of our common study and our common regard. 

^In a remark upon the passing of the structure-function antithesis, 
Titchener has recently referred to the "radical change wrought over 
the whole field of the science since it turned to phenomenology" 
(Amer. J. PsychoL, 1925, 36, 323). How emphatically his own en- 
visagement of psychology has been modified is indicated .by the 
catholic range of articles published in the American Journal of Psy- 
chology under his competent editorship of the last five years. 



CHAPTER XIX 

THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ORGANISM* 



BY MADISON BENTLEY 



Within the last three decades the influence of the biological 
sciences upon our subject has been very great. Especially in 
America have these disciplines deeply impressed psychology 
both by way of their general point of view and by way of their 
methods of procedure. This deep impress of the biological 
pattern is to be first ascribed, as we may suppose, to the rapid 
advancement of physiology and of the evolutionary studies 
of the organism at a time when psychology was forsaking its 
ancient philosophical allies and seeking an alliance with the 
sciences of nature. The impress itself is plainly to be seen in 
the trend of our animal studies, in genetic accounts of the 
human being, in the adaptive and adjustive types of functional- 
ism, and in various behavioristic writings of the last two 
decades. 

To many this inclination in psychology to merge with the 
biological group is wholly admirable. Those who encourage 
the tendency are content to adopt the concepts and the prob- 
lems of the zoological sciences; though they generally limit 
themselves to certain problems of anatomy and physiology 
or to certain phases of the dynamic relations of the animal to 
its surroundings. 

Anyone who is familiar with our current books and periodi- 
cals will have observed that this biological point of view has 
been productive. It has been productive, that is to say, within 
a fairly limited range of problems; a range which covers 
many inquiries into neural functions, the movement systems 
of the body, and the active ecological adjustments of the organ- 
ism. But we must also observe that many facts of psychologi- 
cal import naturally lie without this range; though they are 
sometimes forced within it by a strained and illogical inclusion. 
Such an effort to biologize facts which lie outside the realm of 
the active body and its functions appears, for example, in the 
attempts of the behaviorist to write "objectively" of memory, 
imagination, thinking and the like, in terms of "responsive'* 
adjustments of the body to its environment. 



*Powell Lecture in Psychological Theory at Clark University, Jan* 
nary 7, 1926. 



406 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

It is this logical and factual failure of biological concepts 
and principles within a relatively large part of ^ psychology 
which suggests the distinction between the biological and the 
psychological organism; or between what we may more ac- 
curately describe as the psychologist's conception as set over 
against the biologist's conception of the living being. The pro- 
posal to start fresh with a new view of the organism is cer- 
tain to meet with resistance; but with resistance which rests 
upon nothing more secure, as I venture to believe, than the 
temporal priority and the scientific prestige of a group of dis- 
ciplines firmly established in the intellectual life of European 
and American cultures. We can well conceive that a funda- 
mental and rapid development of psychology fifty or seventy- 
five years ago, out of which a biological group might gradually 
have come, would have found us with as strong a contrary 
bias against a mere anatomy or a mere treatment of bodily 
functions. At all events it is worth our while to neglect, for 
the moment, the biological abstractions from the totality of 
our lives and to encourage a view of the organism which shall 
be distinctively psychological. 

To be sure, such phrases as "the totality of life" or "the 
total process of living" should be qualified by any form of 
psychology which hopes to escape the charge that it seeks to 
embrace the whole round of human life. No one of the sciences 
treats exhaustively and at large its objects of study. Much is 
known and written about the surface of the earth which does 
not fall under geography; much about animals which is not to 
be found within the zoological treatises, and so with all the 
others. It is only quite special and restricted views and as- 
pects of objects and processes which fall within the compass 
of any of the sciences of nature. Psychology orients itself in 
just the same way. The self-styled psychology of the romantic 
magazine and of the character analyst may capitalize anything 
which brings in the "human element" or the "inner life" of 
man; but any psychology which makes its peace with logic, 
which is constituted of principles, and which respects facts, must 
restrict itself to a point of view just as rigorously as do botany, 
physics, geology, and all the rest. 

When we propose the "total" or "psychological" organism 
as the object of our study and investigation we only mean to 
psychologize those facts of life which include at once 
tjbe experiences which we commonly call "thinking," "wishing/* 
"remembering/' and the like, and also certain zoological de- 



THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ORGANISM 407 

tails of the body and its operations. The proposal lays em- 
phasis neither upon a "consciousness" which inhabits or shadows 
the body nor upon a self-sufficient mechanism of flesh and blood 
which suffers from and reacts to the agencies of the physical 
environment and which is only attended by an adventitious 
and half-real mind or spirit. Instead of two "aspects," then 
one of them real and efficacious, the other epiphenomenal we 
have one unitary organism, described in part in experiential, 
and in part in bodily, terms. Thus we advance one step from 
the abstract, cellular organism of the anatomist, physiologist, 
and student of genetics, from which all experience has been 
strained away, toward the concrete creature of our everyday 
lives. Only one step, for we still abstract, in psychology, from 
the personal, social, economic and political affairs where value, 
not description, plays the chief role. 

Let us observe how an inquiry into such a psychological 
organism would stand related to some of the conceptions which 
we find current in our field today. 

As regards, first, the behavioristic forms of doctrine we 
notice a difference with respect to the environment. The basal 
relation of stimulus to response implies that the environment 
is primary. The physical milieu affects itself by way of the 
organism, which it essentially controls. Since movement and 
some other vital activities are ultimately determined by the 
function of the receptors, and these latter organs by the ener- 
gies of the stimulus, it follows that, for the behaviorists, the 
organism is more or less secondary to these physical systems 
which lie without. In our view, on the other hand, the total 
organism 'is central. It is the main object of study. It is no 
more absolutely independent of other systems than other ob- 
jects of the universe are; but it is regarded for its own sake 
and other systems are treated in their relation to it. It is 
relatively independent. 

With respect to the historical doctrine of structuralism our 
proposal shares the concept of experience. But whereas ex- 
perience was there regarded as a complex which was to be 
described first of all by an analysis into elementary processes 
having assignable properties or attributes, experience is here 
to be considered as an integral part of the organism, and it is 
to be described in such subdivisions or aspects as its own nature 
suggests and to be treated as a part of the activity of the total 
elementary qualities upon stimulus here gives way to the total 
organic system. Furthermore, the alleged dependence of the 



408 



PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 



organism, which stands as the real temporal antecedent. One 
but only one of the determinants of experience is stimulus, 
which stands among an entire congeries of physical agents 
momentarily affecting the organism. Where experience is iso- 
lated for its own separate description, both its qualitative va- 
riety and patterning and its inherent unities have to be con- 
sidered: where the organism is to be viewed functionally, ex- 
perience merges with other factors and moments in the total 
performance. 

From configurationism, taken in the sense of the Ge stall, 
we should chiefly dissent where that doctrine exaggerates the 
importance of the "total" side of experience, contending for 
the primacy of the whole and subordinating the part, together 
with its antecedent conditions, to a structure (Struktur) which 
is frequently ambiguous and conspicuously undeterminable. Its 
neglect of qualitative variety should be replaced by a more em- 
pirical and a more catholic description. 

While psychoanalysis takes a direction divergent from the 
psychological view which we here sustain, certain fundamental 
similarities may be made out. There, too, emphasis is laid 
upon the integrity, especially the temporal integrity, of the 
living being. The individual is to be understood, according to 
the psychoanalyst, only by an inquiry into its past and with a 
prediction into its future. Whether it is made or marred depends 
upon its past, and its destiny likewise rests upon its reconstitu- 
tion and re-organization in course. The divergent path of 
psychoanalysis begins with the assumption of conflicting psy- 
chical forces which are designed to explain the nature of human 
experience and of human character. Here the mental or the 
"spiritual" is made primary. Libido, the unconscious, com- 
pensation, sublimation, and the like, are causal agents which 
engender and mould the life-course of the individual and of 
society. This infringement of the total psychological organism 
and this creation of mental forces stand, of course, against the 
principles and the point of view here suggested. 

These relations and distinctions may be set forth by the aid 
of_the following simple diagram. 




THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ORGANISM 409 

The section of the figure bounded by solid lines is de- 
signed schematically to represent the course of events within 
the psychological organism during a small segment of time. 
The dotted lines suggest that the segment is to be taken as an 
artificially limited moment within a continuous course. The 
zig-zig line from "stim" to "mvmt" stands for the alleged 
coupling of the behaviorist. Its course suggests that the real 
connection between a specific stimulus and a certain move- 
ment is (a) a continuous and constantly modified series of 
events, (b) determined in part by a large number of stimulus 
elements and in part by the total state and functional tendency 
of the entire psychological organism. The whole figure is 
meant to emphasize the fact that the organism is for us an 
integer ; i. e., a relatively independent system which is, in spite 
of its constant interplay with other systems, taking its 
course and making its changeable, but individual, way across 
its life-span. Here the psychological emphasis is upon the 
organism; not upon an environment which bounds and deter- 
mines the organism from the two sides of stimulus and response. 
As against the structuralist's parallelism formulated between 
process (or attribute) and stimulus (or property of stimulus) 
the figure represents the natural coherences of experience and of 
bodily function as these are decreed by the total antecedent 
state, the functional trend, and the stimulus^patterns upon many 
receptors. As set against the psychical agencies which are 
postulated by the psychoanalyst to explain the "mental" pe- 
culiarities of a "physical" organism, the schema proposes a 
total and integral organism whose functions flow from a long 
and varied past under the modifying influences of a constantly 
changing present. 

We may, at the end, indicate the way in which the conception 
of pur psychological organism contributes to the solution of the 
main problems of psychology. 1 

I. Performance and character of the adult human being. 
Description, which is here the primary mode of procedure, 
takes two directions. The first looks toward the phenomeno- 
logical depiction of experience, both as regards its qualitative 
characteristics and other details and as regards the functional 
description of its performance and operations. In so far as 
character can be made independent of past history and genetic 

'The problems here distinguished have 'been more explicitly dis- 
cussed by the author in PsychoL Rev.> 1926, 33 t 71-105. 



410 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

continuity, it -becomes, under this heading, the empirical prob- 
lem of the general and generic features of the individual or 
"person." 

II: The comparative study of animals. As in all applica- 
tions of the comparative method to the sciences, the psychologi- 
cal description of individuals is made as intensive and as 
exact as possible. Upon the basis of the individual descriptions 
a legitimate use of inference leads toward a sound comparison 
of unlike but related organisms. Here the logic of the pro- 
cedure is exactly the same as it is in astral physics, paleontology 
and many other natural sciences. The only distinguishing fea- 
ture of the comparisons here proposed is that the objects com- 
pared are psychological organisms and not the organisms of 
the embryologist and the geneticist. 

III. . Psychological history of the individual, of human kbiti? 
and of the animal series. The threefold problem of genesis 
and development is here wholly determined by the underlying 
conception of the organism. Zoological histories, whether onto- 
genetic or phylogenetic, are used only to this end, as are also 
studies of the behavior of the child, of the cultural levels of 
man, and of other animals. The primary aim is to establish, 
by all feasible means and methods, genetic continuities and dis- 
junctions of a psychological kind within the individual and 
among blood relations. 

IV. Individual, class and racial differences. Here all the 
facts and principles derived from the three preceding subdi- 
visions are brought together and made to bear upon the discov- 
ery of a differential psychology. The psychological conception 
of the individual seems to be especially appropriate in this 
group of problems. ; For it is plain that neither 
somatic factors nor mental factors are adequate, when 
taken alone, to the description of the differentiating character- 
istics of the individual. The essential similarities and dis- 
similarities seem, on the contrary, to inhere in the total organ- 
ism. Even the quantitative distinctions drawn between human 
beings as of "intelligence" or of "character" rest upon func- 
tional capabilities which express, not the body alone or the 
mind alone, but the total organism. Furthermore, the failure 
of many attempts to typify by a single "measure" these char- 
acteristics of the individual suggests that the entire history 
of the organism must be considered in this branch of psy- 
chology. The same necessity for depicting 4he entire person 



THE PSYCHOLOGICAL ORGANISM 411 

or individual appears in drawing distinctions between classes, 
races and ethnic groups. 

V. Psychological deficiencies and disorders. Those defects, 
diseases, and abnormalities which the psychologist seeks to 
describe and to understand rest, for the greater part, upon a 
disturbance or an eccentricity of functions which express the 
total organism. The deficiency or disorder appears therefore in 
memory, perception, understanding, action, emotion, and the 
like; and these are precisely the functional modes of the psy- 
chological individual. 

VI. Social psychology. Since every empirical psychology 
has had to reject such fictions as "the social consciousness," 
"the group mind," "the consciousness of kind/' and other like 
social faculties, the actual realities of socialization itself and 
the concrete display of socialization in observed human groups 
and relationships have appeared to be of primary importance, 
in the study of the social life of man and of other animals. 
And here it appears that man is socialized only as he exercises 
the functions of the total organism. It is the significance of the 
object or person perceived, the emotion suffered, the common 
action undertaken, and so on, that is socialized and that thus 
socializes the individual and the group. It is not any mysterious 
instinct or innate power which draws men together. Of course 
it is necessary in social studies to go behind the actual moment 
of socialization to its conditions and causes; but here again 
whatever makes the psychological organism and makes it change 
and develop underlies the socialized experience and the con- 
duct of the human individual. The integral character of the 
whole individual likewise suggests an integration of these con- 
ditions as well. Hence we have, instead of a bundle of in- 
stincts, a dozen springs of human action, or the coercion of 
"social institutions," the development of the socialized person 
unfolding as the product (not the sum) of (1) racial stock, 
(2) the sheer processes of growth, (3) the moulding influence 
of the physical surroundings, (4) intercourse with other be- 
ings, and (5) the impress of institutions, traditions and cus- 
toms. No one of these factors is to be exalted above the 
others, and no combination of them is to be regarded as ex- 
ternal and merely summative. 

We have proposed, in fine, to set out upon the road toward 
psychological description and explanation under the logical guid- 
ance of a psychologist's organism or of a psychological organ- 
ism; discounting, on the one hand, the philosopher's notion of 



412 PSYCHOLOGIES OF 1925 

an independent mind or consciousness, and, on the other, the 
biologist's abstraction of an organized and self-sufficient body 
of flesh and blood. With this approach, pur main problems con- 
cern those active and experiencing individuals which we our- 
selves are day by day and moment by moment. Only we must 
leave aside for separate and non-psychological consideration' 
all concerns of "human nature" which are private, valuational 
and normative. The organism so regarded has seemed to us 
to offer a promising and suitable approach to the main fields, 
of psychological exposition and research.