Skip to main content

Full text of "Revaluations: historical and ideal"

See other formats


THE  LIBRARY 

OF 

THE  UNIVERSITY 
OF  CALIFORNIA 

LOS  ANGELES 


REVALUATIONS: 

HISTORICAL    AND    IDEAL 


REVALUATIONS: 

HISTORICAL    AND     IDEAL 


BY 


ALFRED  W.  BENN, 

ABTHOR  OF  "THE  HISTORY  OF  ENGLISH  RATIONALISM  IN  THE  NINETEENTH 
CENTURY,"  "  MODERN  ENGLAND,"  ETC. 


"  Zarathustra  has  found  no  greater  power  on 
earth  than  good  and  evil." — FR.  NIETZSCHE. 


[ISSUED  FOR  THE  RATIONALIST  PRESS  ASSOCIATION,  LIMITED] 


LONDON : 
WATTS  &  CO., 

17,  JOHNSON'S  COURT,  FLEET  STREET,  E.C. 
1909 


843 


TO 

VERNON  LEE 


CONTENTS 


PAGE 

THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM  (1901)                       -  i 

THE   INFLUENCE  OF    PHILOSOPHY    ON  GREEK    POLITICAL 

LIFE  (1894)                                                                    -  40 

THE  ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS  (1893)           -  80 

THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM  AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  (1895)  -  126 

PASCAL'S  WAGER  (1905)        -                                            -  151 

BUCKLE  AND  THE  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE  (1881)        -  177 

THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— FRIEDRICII  NIETZSCHE 

(1908)       -                                                                  -  228 

WHAT  is  AGNOSTICISM?  (1900)                               -           -  281 

INDEX  -                                                                     -  313 


PREFACE 


THE  title  of  this  volume  may  possibly  remind  some 
readers  of  an  expression — "  Umwerthungen,"  in 
English  "  Transvaluations  " — first  brought  into 
vogue  by  Nietzsche  ;  the  motto  of  the  book  is 
taken  from  Nietzsche  ;  and  one  of  the  essays  which 
it  contains  is  devoted  to  a  criticism  of  Nietzsche's 
ethics.  Under  less  provocation  than  this,  hasty 
or  superficial  reviewers  might  be  tempted  to  label 
me  as  a  Nietzschian.  Under  less  provocation  than 
this,  quite  friendly  reviewers  have  actually  labelled 
me  as  a  Hegelian.  If  I  know  anything  about  my 
own  opinion,  I  am  neither  the  one  nor  the  other. 
But,  if  I  had  to  choose,  of  the  two  I  had  rather  be 
called  a  Hegelian.  And  anyone  who  takes  the 
trouble  to  read  my  study  of  the  great  im  moralist 
will  find  that  he  is  treated  from  the  point  of  view 
of  one  who  accepts  in  principle  the  traditional 

morality — 

As  one  compelled  in  spite  of  scorn 
To  teach  a  truth  he  would  not  learn. 


t  PREFACE 

My  re-estimates,  in  fact,  where  they  depart  from 
the  views  generally  accepted,  relate  not  so  much  to 
standards  as  to  their  application,  and  not  so  much 
to  things  as  to  persons.  Thus  the  paper  which  has 
been  put  first,  and  which  in  some  ways  is  most 
diametrically  opposed  to  the  current  common- 
places, does  not  find  the  ethical  value  of  Hellenism 
in  any  opposition  to  the  highest  modern  ideals  of 
conduct,  but  in  its  approach  to  or  anticipation  of 
what  we  cherish  as  most  essential  to  modern 
civilisation.  Of  course,  I  am  prepared  to  hear  that 
there  is  nothing  new  about  what  I  claim  for  the 
Greeks,  that  every  scholar  knew  all  this  already. 
It  may  be  so  ;  but  I  am  not  aware  that  any  scholar 
has  said  it  in  so  many  words  ;  and  I  know  one 
scholar  who,  writing  some  time  after  the  first 
publication  of  my  essay,  dogmatically  stated  the 
exact  contrary.  Professor  De  Sanctis,  the  most 
recent  Italian  historian  of  old  Rome,  comparing 
together  the  different  branches  of  the  Aryan  race, 
finds  in  the  Greeks  "a  certain  atrophy  of  the  moral 
sense."  When  a  man  who  has  access  to  Homer 
and  the  tragedians  can  say  this,  neither  would  he 
be  persuaded  though  one  rose  from  the  dead.  It 
is  not,  therefore,  in  the  vain  hope  of  inducing 
Professor  De  Sanctis  to  reconsider  his  verdict,  but 
because  it  may  interest  my  less  prejudiced  readers, 


XI 

that  I  venture  to  lay  before  them  some  very 
striking  evidence  on  the  subject  derived  from  an 
unexpected  quarter — the  recently  disinterred 
comedies  of  Menander.  One  of  these,  called  The 
Arbitration,  has  for  its  argument  the  following 
story : — 

Charisios,  a  young  Athenian  of  good  family,  has 
recently  been  married  to  Pamphila,  a  girl  of  his  own 
class.  Four  months  after  the  wedding  Pamphila, 
unknown  to  her  husband,  gives  birth  to  a  child,  of  which 
Charisios,  although  unaware  of  his  paternity,  is  the 
father.  For  in  the  course  of  a  drunken  frolic  he  had  met 
and  done  violence  to  his  future  wife  one  dark  night  in  the 
streets  of  Athens.  Neither  of  them  had  seen  the  other's 
face,  but  in  the  struggle  Pamphila  had  possessed  herself 
of  and  retained  a  ring  belonging  to  Charisios.  On 
discovering  what  he  supposes  to  be  her  ante-nuptial 
frailty,  the  young  man  separates  from  his  wife  and 
returns  to  his  former  associates.  One  of  these,  a  slave- 
woman  named  Habrotonon,  with  whom  he  had  once 
cohabited,  gets  hold  of  the  ring  and  uses  it  to  persuade 
Charisios  that  she  has  become  the  mother  of  a  child  by 
him.  Her  story  reaches  the  ear  of  Pamphila's  father, 
who,  as  some  modern  readers  will  be  surprised  to  learn, 
is  so  scandalised  by  this  evidence  of  his  son-in-law's 
youthful  misconduct  as  to  propose  that  Pamphila,  of 
whose  misfortune  he  is  ignorant,  should  immediately 
demand  a  separation.  This,  however,  the  young  wife 
refuses  to  do,  declaring  that  it  is  her  wish  to  stand  by  her 
husband  in  good  and  evil  fortune  alike.  Charisios 
accidentally  overhears  the  conversation,  and  is  so 
conscience-stricken  by  the  contrast  between  his  own 
resentment  and  the  generous  fidelity  of  his  wife  as  in  his 


xii  PREFACE 

turn  to  forgive  her  supposed  lapse  from  virtue,  even 
before  everything  is  happily  cleared  up  by  a  disclosure  of 
the  real  facts  of  the  case. 

Professor  De  Sanctis  places  his  countrymen  at 
the  head  of  the  whole  Aryan  race  for  the  perfect 
balance  of  their  mental  qualities,  among  which,  of 
course,  moral  feeling  holds  a  leading  position. 
Now,  the  Latin  comic  poet  Terence  wrote  for  an 
Italian  audience,  and,  although  Julius  Caesar  called 
him  a  half  Menander,  we  do  not  find  in  his  plays, 
charming  as  they  are,  the  faintest  trace  of  the 
moral  delicacy  which  is  now  shown  to  have  been  a 
distinctive  trait  of  his  Greek  prototype. 

The  instance  quoted  does  not  stand  alone.  In 
another  comedy,  of  which  considerable  fragments 
have  recently  been  discovered,  Menander  intro- 
duces a  girl,  supposed  to  be  of  foreign  birth, 
who  as  a  consequence  of  her  inferior  social 
position  has  been  living  in  concubinage  with  a 
soldier,  and,  having  innocently  provoked  his 
jealousy,  experiences  very  rough  treatment  from 
him.  Being  subsequently  recognised  as  of 
Athenian  parentage,  her  first  impulse  is  to 
exclaim,  "  Then  I  shall  be  reconciled  "  ;  on  which 
her  father  observes : 

I  love  that  word  "  be  reconciled," 
Proving  in  thee  the  right  Hellenic  strain — 


PREFACE  xiii 

in    which,    as    would    seem,   the    forgiveness    of 
injuries  was  a  leading  trait. 

Depreciation  of  Hellenism  has  been  associated, 
in   such  writers  as   Matthew  Arnold   and   Ernest 
Renan,  with  an  exaggerated  and  distorted  estimate 
of  Hebraism,  of  the  values  represented  by  Israel 
as  a   factor   in   universal   history.     My  essay   on 
"  The  Alleged  Socialism  of  the  Prophets  "  has  for 
its  object  to  point  out  the  very  serious  misstate- 
ments  of  Renan  on  this  subject.     It  is  not  offered 
as  a  revaluation  of  my  own,  but  as  a  criticism  on 
a  revaluation  which,  in  my  opinion,  is  much  more 
remote   from   truth    than   the    generally   accepted 
view.     And  I  have  tried  to  show  in  another  essay, 
largely  based  on  the  researches  of  German  scholar- 
ship, that  Socialism  is  not  a  Hebrew  but  a  Greek 
idea,  subsequently  imported  from  Greek  philosophy 
into  the  teaching  of  the  early  Church — not,   as 
Renan  thinks,  taken  up  by  the  Gospel  from  the 
prophetic  tradition. 

My  essay  on  "  Pascal's  Wager "  goes  to  prove 
that  the  great  Jansenist's  celebrated  defence  of 
Christianity  is,  as  logic,  utterly  worthless ;  and 
that,  as  morality,  it  credits  God  with  proceedings 
for  which  the  most  audacious  Jesuitical  casuistry 
would  blush  to  apologise. 

When  the  essay  on  Buckle  first  appeared,  now 


xiv  PREFACE 

more  than  a  quarter  of   a  century  ago,    I   was 
privately  censured  by  an  eminent  living  critic  for 
wasting  my  time   in  exposing  the  fallacies  of  a 
philosopher    whose    memory   only   survived    "in 
half-educated    German    circles."    The    revival   of 
Buckle's  fame  and  the  diffusion  of  his  wonderful 
work  in  cheap  editions  during  the  last  ten  years 
will,    I   hope,  be  found  a  sufficient  apology  for 
reprinting    what,     I    believe,    is    still    the    only 
complete  explanation  of  his  system  ever  offered  to 
the  public.     I  may  mention  also  that,  as  the  literary 
executors  of  Lord  Acton  have  recently  thought  fit 
to  republish  two  most  bitter  and  pedantic  articles 
of   his  on    Buckle,   there   ought  to  be   room   in 
contemporary    literature    for    a    somewhat     more 
appreciative  estimate  of  one  who,   if  he  did  not 
equal    the    Roman    Catholic    historian    in    some 
branches    of    erudition,    far     surpassed     him     in 
speculative  genius. 

A  generation  has  passed  since  the  word 
"Agnosticism,"  originally  created  by  Huxley,  was 
first  put  into  general  currency  by  Leslie  Stephen. 
But  the  full  meaning  of  the  term,  instead  of  being 
elucidated  by  constant  use,  has  become  ever  more 
obscured.  I  cannot  hope  to  correct  the  evil ;  but 
I  shall  at  least  have  the  satisfaction  of  putting  on 
record  in  a  somewhat  more  permanent  form  my 


PREFACE  xv 

protest  against  the  misuse  of  what,  whether  it 
stands  for  truth  or  for  error,  serves  at  any  rate  to 
mark  off  in  contradistinction  from  older  forms  of 
rationalism  an  interesting  and,  it  may  be,  a 
permanent  phase  of  speculation. 

A.  W.  B. 

July,  igog. 


CORRECTIONS 

P.  47  :  "  Nicias  consummated  the  ruin  of  the  Sicilian  expedition 
by  postponing  his  retreat  a  whole  month  in  consequence  of  an 
eclipse  of  the  moon."  In  point  of  fact,  Nicias  was  compelled  to 
begin  his  retreat  a  few  days  after  the  eclipse  ;  but  his  wish  and 
intention  was  to  put  it  off  for  a  month,  and  the  delay  of  a  few 
days  proved  equally  fatal. 

P.  86  :  "Some  such  measure as  the  Licinian  Rogations." 

It  is  now  the  opinion  of  the  most  authoritative  Roman  historians 
that  the  Licinian  Rogations  included  no  agrarian  provisions. 

P.  in,  note  :  For  "  Emmanuel  "  read  "  Emanuel."  The  passage 
referred  to  occurs  on  p.  36  of  Deutsch's  Literary  Remains. 


REVALUATIONS 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

IF  we  are  to  judge  by  certain  estimates  current  in 
the  popular  literature  of  the  present  day,  the  ethical 
value  of  Hellenism  is  either  zero  or  a  minus 
quantity.  The  ancient  Greeks  were  Pagans  in  the 
sense  that  they  were  neither  Jews  nor  Christians  ; 
and  the  word  "  Paganism  "  is  commonly  used  to 
connote  the  complete  absence  of  moral  restraints, 
more  especially  of  those  which  are  imposed  on 
the  sexual  relations.  An  epigrammatic  novelist 
describes  a  group  of  young  people,  among  whom 
marriage  seems  to  have  been  replaced  by  con- 
nections of  a  more  transitory  character,  as  living  in 
a  world  of  Christian  names  and  Pagan  morals. 
Mr.  Shorthouse,  speaking  through  the  mouthpiece 
of  John  Inglesant,  refers  to  "the  old  world  of 
pleasure  and  art — a  world  that  took  the  pleasures 
of  life  boldly,  and  had  no  conscience  to  prevent  its 
cultivating  and  enjoying  them  to  the  full."  Appa- 
rently John  Inglesant  had  not  read  the  Epistle  to 
the  Romans.  Another  writer  of  fiction,  Mr. 
Benjamin  Kidd,  seems  to  think  that  altruism 
was  unknown  before  the  Christian  era.  Mr. 
W.  D.  Howells  implies  in  one  of  his  novels 
that  monogamy  only  dates  from  the  same  period. 


2  THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

And  a  far  higher  authority,  Matthew  Arnold, 
has  made  the  antithesis  between  Hellenism  and 
Hebraism  common  form  in  literature — Hellenism 
standing  for  science  and  art,  Hebraism  for  con- 
duct; that  is  to  say,  for  three-fourths  of  life. 

Before  inquiring  into  the  justice  of  this  summary 
and  wholesale  condemnation,  I  would  call  attention 
to  the  singular  circumstance  that  a  directly  opposite 
estimate  of  Pagan  virtue  prevailed  all  through  the 
Middle  Ages.  It  might  have  been  supposed  that 
during  the  centuries  when  Catholicism  reigned 
without  a  rival  over  the  Western  conscience,  and 
when  the  traditions  of  the  regime  which  it  had 
displaced  were  fresher  than  among  ourselves, 
observers,  especially  ecclesiastical  observers,  would 
have  been  still  more  deeply  impressed  by  the  moral 
regeneration  assumed  to  have  been  wrought  by  the 
Church.  Such,  however,  is  not  the  case.  Among 
mediaeval  authorities  there  seems  to  be  but  one 
opinion  as  regards  the  moral  superiority  of  classical 
antiquity  over  their  own  contemporaries.  "  The 
Gentiles,"  says  Abelard,  "who  had  no  scriptural 
law  and  heard  no  sermons,  put  us  to  shame  by  the 
example  of  their  virtue,  by  the  excellence  of  their 
precepts,  and  by  the  consistency  of  their  lives  with 
their  teachings.  Their  philosophers  boldly  rebuked 
wickedness  and  suffered  for  truth's  sake.  Nor  was 
it  their  philosophers  only  who  shone  so  brightly  in 
comparison  with  us.  There  is  abundant  evidence 
going  to  prove  that  the  same  virtues  were  practised 
by  the  worldly  and  the  unlearned,  and  by  women 
as  well  as  by  men."1  It  may  be  urged,  and, 

1  Opera,  ed.  Cousin,  II.,  p.  409. 


indeed,  it  has  been  urged,  that  Abelard  was  a 
freethinking  rationalist  who  sought  to  undermine 
Christianity.  A  much-scandalised  apologist  refers 
us  to  John  of  Salisbury  for  a  very  different  view  of 
the  matter.1  We  turn  to  the  pages  of  that  excellent 
prelate,  and  find,  to  our  surprise,  that  he  confirms 
rather  than  contradicts  his  master's  statements. 
Examples  of  every  virtue  are  to  be  found  among 
the  characters  of  antiquity.  The  perfect  model  of 
what  a  sovereign  ought  to  be  is  furnished  by  no 
Christian  prince,  but  by  the  heathen  Trajan.  The 
Socratic  teaching  is  a  well  of  morals  undefiled.  If 
people  find  the  Christian  religion  too  severe,  let 
them  go  to  the  Greek  philosophers  for  lessons  in 
chastity.  And,  indeed,  if  John  is  to  be  believed, 
they  were  in  sore  need  of  such  lessons,  for  nothing 
so  bad  has  been  written  about  imperial  Rome  as 
his  descriptions  of  court  society  in  the  Europe  of 
the  twelfth  century.  Doubtless  the  anarchy  that 
prevailed  under  Stephen  is  largely  responsible  for 
the  corruption  laid  bare  in  the  PolycraticusS  But 
no  such  extenuating  circumstances  can  be  pleaded 
for  the  ages  of  faith  and  chivalry  when,  a  century 
later,  we  find  Roger  Bacon  repeating  in  more 
definite  and  explicit  terms  Abelard's  exaltation  of 
Pagan  over  Christian  morals.  If,  says  the  great 
Franciscan,  we  cannot  emulate,  or  even  understand, 
the  wisdom  of  the  ancient  philosophers,  it  is  because 
we  do  not  possess  their  virtue.  Wisdom  is  incon- 
sistent with  sin,  and  demands  perfect  virtue  in  its 
professors.  And  of  all  sins  the  most  fatal  to 


1  Reuter,  Religiose  Aufklarung,  I.,  p.  317. 
3  Polycraticus,  Lib.  III.,  cap.  13. 


4  THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

learning  is  unchastity,  from  which  none  but  a  very 
few,  and  those  by  special  grace,  are  exempt  in  their 
youth.  Nor  is  this  a  mere  general  statement.  He 
proceeds  to  relate  how  a  number  of  professors  and 
students  of  theology  had  the  year  before  been 
expelled  from  Paris  for  the  practice  of  unnatural 
vices.  Such  was  the  state  of  morals  shortly  before 
the  death  of  St.  Louis,  at  the  very  climax  and 
flowering-time  of  mediaeval  Catholicism.1 

I  am  not  aware  that  any  such  clear  and  emphatic 
testimony  to  the  superiority  of  Pagan  morals  is 
given  by  Dante,  but  it  is  at  least  suggestive  of  the 
same  leaning  that  he  should  ascribe  what  little 
good  Florence  possessed  to  the  descent  of  some 
few  of  her  citizens  from  the  ancient  Romans.  And 
we  know  from  a  brilliant  chapter  in  the  Conmtto 
how  highly  he  rated  the  virtues  of  the  Romans, 
referring  them  even  to  divine  inspiration.  Whether 
he  had  an  equally  high  opinion  of  the  Greeks  cannot 
be  positively  affirmed,  but  there  is  a  significant 
passage  in  the  Inferno  pointing  in  that  direction. 
The  motive  to  which  Ulysses  appeals  when  urging 
his  companions  to  sail  beyond  the  Pillars  of 
Hercules  is  the  remembrance  that  they  were  not 
born  to  live  like  brutes,  but  to  pursue  virtue  and 
knowledge.  And  to  this  appeal  the  Greek  sailors, 
according  to  Dante,  readily  respond.2 

It  may  be  objected  that  Dante  was  a  poet  and  a 
scholar,  more  in  sympathy  with  the  old  than  with 
the  new  spirit ;  Roger  Bacon  a  man  of  science 
sheltering  himself  under  the  Franciscan  habit — 


1  Compendium  Theologia,  ed.  Brewer,  pp.  398  seq. 
1  Inferno,  Canto  xxvi.,  118  seq. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM  5 

both,  perhaps,  Christians  only  under  compulsion. 
There  is,  however,  one  more  authority,  to  which 
no  such  exception  can  be  taken — the  authority 
either  of  Aquinas  or  of  one  whose  speculations 
were  permitted  to  pass  under  his  name.  This 
writer,  while  confessing  a  preference  for  the 
republican  form  of  government,  admits  that  it  is 
"only  fitted  for  men  living  in  the  primitive  state  of 
sinlessness,  or  so  wise  and  virtuous  as  the  ancient 
Romans  were"1 — clearly  not  for  a  society  so 
corrupt  as  the  crusading  chivalry  of  France. 

To  what  cause  shall  we  ascribe  this  extraordinary 
revolution  in  Christian  opinion  as  to  the  moral 
value  of  classic  civilisation  ?  A  sufficiently  easy 
solution  suggests  itself  at  once.  The  mediaeval 
scholars  romanced  about  Pagan  virtue  because 
they  did  not  know  what  Paganism  was.  The 
Greeks  and  Romans  were  to  them  what  the 
Chinese  were  to  the  philosophers  of  the  eighteenth 
century  ;  and  they  used  them  just  like  those  philo- 
sophers, as  a  stick  to  beat  their  contemporaries 
with.  The  far  more  complete  knowledge  of  Pagan 
life  and  literature  that  we  owe  to  the  Renaissance 
and  to  modern  research  has  led  to  very  different 
conclusions,  and  it  is  on  these  that  the  estimates 
quoted  at  the  beginning  of  this  essay  are  based. 

But  the  suggested  explanation  seems  insufficient. 
If  the  schoolmen  knew  less  than  we  know  of  Pagan 
literature,  the  fact  remains  that  for  all  practical 
purposes  they  knew  enough.  If  they  had  not  read 
Aristophanes  and  Plato,  they  had  read  Aristotle's 
Politics^ Terence,  Horace, Ovid,  Juvenal,  Suetonius; 

1  Aquinas  (?),  De  Regimine  Principum,  II.,  9. 


6          THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

above  all,  they  had  read  the  first  chapter  of  the 
Epistle  to  the  Romans  ;  nor  does  there  seem  the 
smallest  reason  to  believe  that  a  wider  and  deeper 
study  of  the  Greek  authors  would  have  altered  their 
estimate  of  the  Greeks,  except,  perhaps,  to  raise  it 
still  higher,  by  making  them  more  familiar  with  the 
whole  range  of  Greek  virtue.  The  truth  is  that 
their  reading  of  classical  antiquity  was  not  biassed 
as  ours  is  by  an  apologetic  interest.  They  accepted 
Christianity  because  it  was  true,  not  because  it 
strengthened  the  hands  of  the  social  reformer,  the 
magistrate,  and  the  policeman.  Hence,  there  was 
no  particular  motive  for  exaggerating  its  services 
in  that  direction.  Religion,  no  doubt,  was  useful, 
but  its  utility  consisted  not  so  much  in  making 
people  better  members  of  society  as  in  saving  them 
from  eternal  damnation.  Baptism  gave  a  chance, 
absolution  in  articulo  mortis  gave  a  certainty  of 
escaping  from  that  dreadful  fate  ;  and  the  posses- 
sion of  so  precious  a  privilege  was  the  great  advan- 
tage that  the  Christian  possessed  over  the  Pagan. 
Otherwise,  as  we  have  seen,  he  had  nothing  to 
boast  of — rather  the  contrary.  Whatever  vices  the 
Church  condemned  had  been  condemned  by  Greek 
philosophy.  Whatever  vices  had  been  practised 
among  Pagans  were  repeated  with  aggravating 
circumstances  in  the  most  famous  seats  of  Christian 
learning  ;  and  those  whose  experience  had  familiar- 
ised them  with  the  cesspools  of  Paris  and  Bologna 
listened  with  more  blunted  sensibility  to  the  un- 
savoury records  of  Thebes  and  Athens. 

It  might,  indeed,  be  imagined  that  the  appalling 
penalties  inflicted  on  such  offences  in  this  world, 
and  imagined  for  them  in  the  next,  bore  witness  to 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM  7 

an  entirely  new  sense  of  their  flagitiousness  in  the 
mediaeval  conscience.  But  no  mistake  would  be 
greater  than  to  use  the  criminal  jurisprudence  of 
the  Middle  Ages  as  a  gauge  of  their  moral  sus- 
ceptibility. Difficulty  of  detection  for  one  thing, 
and  the  supposed  slight  cast  on  the  honour  of  an 
earthly  or  heavenly  sovereign  for  another,  counted 
for  incomparably  more  in  the  assessment  of  punish- 
ment than  the  actual  wickedness  of  an  offence  as 
measured  by  the  animosity  that  it  excited  in  the 
public  opinion  of  the  times.  Now,  of  that  public 
opinion  no  austerer  representative  can  be  quoted 
than  Dante  ;  and  what  Dante  really  thought  about 
the  vice  that  is  always  brought  up  as  the  special 
opprobrium  of  Greece  is  sufficiently  indicated  by 
his  extreme  cordiality  towards  the  lost  soul  of 
Brunette  Latini,1  and  by  the  fact  that  he  subjects 
all  sins  of  unchastity  to  an  equal  intensity  of 
torment  in  the  cleansing  fires  of  purgatory.2 
Evidently  the  great  Catholic  poet  was  no  more 
of  a  rigorist  than  the  Platonic  Socrates  whose 
half-tolerant  attitude  so  much  shocked  Professor 
Huxley. 

We  must,  then,  look  elsewhere  than  to  a  mere 
increase  of  knowledge  for  an  adequate  explanation 
of  that  great  revolution  in  the  historical  conscience 
which  has  led  many  of  our  contemporaries  to 
reverse  the  mediaeval  view  so  completely  that  in 
the  popular  imagination  Paganism,  or,  more  pre- 
cisely, the  Graeco-Roman  spirit,  has  become  identi- 
fied with  impurity,  while  Christianity  has  come  to 
be  regarded  even  more  as  the  chief  instrument  of 

1  Inferno,  Canto  xv.,  30  sqq.  *  Purgatorio,  Canto  xxvii. 


8  THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

moral   reform   than   as   the   God-given    means    of 
salvation. 

So  far  as  I  know,  the  change  began  with  Luther. 
If  in  one  way  the  Reformation  was  the  last  fruit  of 
the  Renaissance,  in  another  way  it  was  a  reaction 
against  the  Renaissance.  In  returning  to  the 
standpoint  of  primitive  Christianity  Luther  and 
his  successors  could  not  fail  to  become  imbued 
with  the  hostility  felt  by  the  first  Christians,  and 
above  all  by  St.  Paul,  towards  the  Pagan  world  ; 
and  all  the  more  so  as  the  worst  vices  of  Paganism 
were  being  resuscitated  under  their  eyes  in  papal 
Rome.  Moreover,  the  dogmas  that  Luther  attacked 
had  been  bound  up  in  a  peculiar  way  with  the 
philosophy  of  Aristotle,  and,  therefore,  the  Aris- 
totelian ethics  became  a  special  object  of  his 
animosity.  The  doctrine  of  moral  habits  seemed 
radically  inconsistent  with  the  doctrine  of  instan- 
taneous regeneration.  Men  do  not  become  just  by 
performing  just  actions  ;  they  perform  just  actions 
because  they  have  been  made  just.  Speaking 
generally,  Rome  had  apostasised  from  the  purity 
of.  the  gospel  by  incorporating  with  it  much 
that  was  Pagan  in  doctrine  and  ritual ;  there- 
fore with  Paganism  in  all  its  forms  war  must  be 
waged. 

Rome  naturally  enough  refused  to  accept  this 
account  of  her  parentage  ;  but  it  made  her  all  the 
more  anxious  to  disclaim  so  compromising  a  con- 
nection. Hence  both  great  divisions  of  western 
Christendom  have  united  in  vilifying  the  civilisation 
to  which  mediaeval  scholars  looked  back  with  fond 
regret  as  an  unattainable  standard  of  excellence. 
And  before  long  their  joint  hostility  was  still 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM  9 

further  aggravated  by  a  new  provocation.  Unde- 
terred by  the  double  tide  of  reaction,  the  Renais- 
sance continued  to  pursue  its  victorious  career. 
Taking  up  human  progress  at  the  point  where  it 
had  been  let  fall  by  Greek  culture,  the  modern 
mind  set  itself  to  replace  feudal  Catholicism  by  a 
new  art  and  a  new  science,  a  new  morality  and  a 
new  State.  Concurrently  with  this  great  enterprise 
it  carried  on  an  unceasing  criticism  on  the  existing 
regime,  its  institutions  and  its  beliefs.  Both  pro- 
cesses, the  constructive  and  destructive,  were  power- 
fully aided  by  principles  and  examples  derived  from 
classical  antiquity.  All  these  efforts  culminated  in 
the  French  Revolution,  whose  leaders  avowedly 
looked  for  their  models  to  Greece  and  Rome.  And 
as  the  Hellenic  spirit  had  shared  in  their  momen- 
tary triumph,  so  also  it  shared  in  the  ruin  and 
disgrace  that  speedily  overtook  their  cause.  For 
the  first  time  since  they  came  into  existence  the 
products  of  the  Greek  genius  were  systematically 
neglected  and  defamed  by  educated  men  ;  recourse 
being  had  to  mediaeval  art,  literature,  and  politics  for 
new  ideals  to  put  in  their  place.  The  Romanticists 
consciously  ranged  themselves  behind  the  forces  of 
reaction  in  Church  and  State ;  and  it  was  not  without 
reason  that  Byron,  the  glorious  standard-bearer  of 
European  progress,  directed  against  them  his 
fiercest  attacks.  So,  too,  the  cause  of  Greek  inde- 
pendence for  which  Byron  gave  his  life  became 
the  battle-cry  of  resurgent  Liberalism,  and  perhaps 
helped  to  win  back  Canning,  the  future  Liberal 
leader,  to  the  Liberal  principles  that  had  been  his 
first  love.  Conversely,  the  Holy  Alliance  thwarted 
Greek  aspirations  to  the  utmost  of  its  ability ;  and 


io         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

its  literary  agents  carried  the  war  into  historical 
literature.  Writing  in  1834,  J-  S.  Mill  observes 
that  "  the  most  elaborate  Grecian  history  which  we 
possess  [Mitford's]  is  impregnated  with  the  anti- 
Jacobin  spirit  in  every  line ;  and  the  Quarterly 
Review  laboured  as  diligently  for  many  years  to 
vilify  the  Athenian  republic  as  the  American."1 
Even  greater  bitterness  was  displayed  by  reac- 
tionary theologians.  The  Abbe  Gaume  in  France 
and  Dr.  W.  G.  Ward  in  England  joined  in  making 
the  grotesque  proposal  that  the  Greek  and  Latin 
classics  should  no  longer  be  taught  in  school,  their 
place  being  supplied  by  patristic  literature.2 

The  leaders  of  the  reactionary  movement  against 
the  French  Revolution  and  the  philosophy  of  the 
eighteenth  century  were,  in  truth,  anything  but 
Conservatives.  They  caught  the  spirit  of  innova- 
tion from  their  opponents,  and  even  sympathised 
to  a  certain  extent  with  their  aims.  Agreeing  with 
them  that  the  world  needed  to  be  reformed,  and 
agreeing  also  that  its  reformation  should  be  effected 
by  social  reconstruction,  by  education,  by  popular 
literature,  by  journalism — in  short,  by  all  the 
machinery  that  the  schools  of  enlightenment  had 
set  in  motion,  they  differed  from  them  chiefly  in 
holding  that  all  these  instruments  should  be  ani- 
mated by  religious  ideas,  used  for  religious  pur- 
poses, and  wielded  by  the  ministers  of  religion  or 
by  laymen  to  whom  their  confidence  had  been 
given.  This  is  not  the  place  to  expatiate  on  that 
vast  movement,  nor,  indeed,  has  the  time  come  for 

1  Dissertations  and  Discussions,  vol.  i.,  p.  113. 
a    W.  G.  Ward  and  the  Catholic  Revival,  pp.  114,  118,  194,  and 
454- 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         n 

its  history  to  be  written.  The  important  thing  for 
us  to  observe  is  that  it  led  to  a  new  interpretation 
of  Christianity,  of  the  Church,  and  of  the  Bible. 
In  rivalry  with  the  ideals  bequeathed  or  inspired 
by  Hellenism,  these  also  were  represented  as 
embodying  a  scheme  of  social  reform,  an  ideal 
polity,  a  new  reading  of  life.  Thus  it  came  about 
that  Pagan  and  Christian  morals,  ancient  and 
mediaeval  civilisation,  were  ranged  in  an  unreal 
opposition  and  unhistorically  contrasted  as  darkness 
and  light.  And  so  strong  was  the  prejudice  gene- 
rated by  the  unscrupulous  assertions  of  the  reac- 
tionary party,  so  skilful  were  the  rearrangements 
by  which  facts  were  disguised  or  set  in  a  false 
light,  that  a  generation  taught  to  discard  super- 
naturalist  metaphysics  has  continued  to  accept  a 
supernaturalist  version  of  history,  according  to 
which  the  highest  elements  of  human  nature,  intel- 
ligence and  conscience,  may  exist  and  be  developed 
in  complete  isolation  from  one  another. 

So  much  has  seemed  necessary  by  way  of  pre- 
amble in  order  to  clear  the  ground  for  a  candid 
consideration  of  the  thesis  I  am  prepared  to  sup- 
port, which  is  no  less  than  this — that  the  ethical 
value  of  Hellenism  fully  equals  its  intellectual  and 
artistic  value  ;  that  the  Greeks  were  as  great  in 
what  belongs  to  the  conduct  of  life  as  they  con- 
fessedly were  in  the  creation  of  beauty  or  in  the 
search  for  truth.  They  were,  what  Huxley  called 
them,  the  real  Chosen  People,  and  that  in  a  more 
absolute  sense  than  he  would  have  dared  to 
maintain. 

To  avoid  all  possible  misconstructions,  I  wish  to 
state  at  the  outset  that  I  accept  the  current  English 


12         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

and  American  estimate  of  morality.  I  have  no 
desire  to  be  classed  with  the  neo-Pagans — if  the 
persons  calling  themselves  by  that  name  still  exist 
as  a  class  ;  I  detest  their  theories,  and  I  believe 
that  in  most  ancient  Greek  communities  they 
would  have  been  summarily  lynched  had  they 
tried  to  put  those  theories  into  practice. 

It  must  be  further  understood  that  when  I  speak 
of  Hellenism  and  of  the  Greeks  I  speak  of  what 
was  highest  and  best  in  the  race  and  in  its  bequest 
to  posterity.  This  amounts  to  no  more  than  is 
assumed  in  estimating  the  claims  on  our  gratitude 
of  any  other  extinct  race  or  civilisation,  or  of  any 
religion  whether  extinct  or  not.  We  really  know 
little  more  than  this,  nor  does  it  concern  us  to 
know  more.  The  good  lives  on,  the  evil  dies. 
The  point  needs  emphasising  because  it  has  been 
particularly  neglected  in  discussing  the  subject  on 
which  we  are  engaged.  Instead  of  comparing 
Greek  practice  with  the  practice  of  other  communi- 
ties, Greek  ideals  with  other  ideals,  we  ignore  the 
ideals  and  compare  the  practice  with  our  own 
highest  theoretical  standards.  I  do  not  propose 
that  the  question  of  practice  should  be  left  out  of 
account ;  on  the  contrary,  I  wish  that  it  should 
figure  largely  in  the  estimate.  An  ideal  to  deserve 
the  name  must  sooner  or  later,  and  sooner  rather 
than  later,  influence  conduct ;  failing  that,  it 
becomes  worse  than  nothing,  mere  lying  cant  and 
hypocrisy.  At  the  same  time,  in  default  of  other 
evidence,  it  ought  to  count  for  something  that  a 
particular  ideal  should  have  been  entertained  in  a 
particular  society  ;  it  must,  we  may  argue,  have 
been  suggested  to  our  authority — poet,  orator,  or 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         13 

the  like — by  some  happy  experience  of  his  own  or 
by  the  tradition  of  a  better  age.  And  this  is  more 
especially  true  when  we  are  dealing  with  a  frank 
and  sincere  people,  as  the  Greek,  or  at  least 
the  Ionian  race,  will  presently  appear  to  have 
been. 

Another  point  also  should  be  borne  in  mind.  In 
placing  the  ethical  value  of  Hellenism  on  a  level 
with  its  intellectual  and  aesthetic  value  I  am  claim- 
ing for  it  no  chimerical  perfection.  The  art  of 
Hellas  was  not  perfect,  nor  was  its  philosophy  ; 
still  less  its  science.  In  all  three  the  Greeks  have 
been  surpassed  by  the  successors  who,  profiting  by 
their  lessons  and  their  example,  have  taken  up 
their  tradition  and  carried  it  to  a  higher  pitch  of 
excellence.  And  what  is  more  to  the  point,  other 
races,  working  simultaneously  with  them,  or  at  a 
later  period  in  complete  independence  of  their 
influence,  have  in  some  ways  shown  a  more 
delicate  aesthetic  perception,  a  truer  sense  of  objec- 
tive reality,  a  more  penetrating  reach  of  reflection, 
a  more  successful  ingenuity  in  devising  methods  of 
calculation.  So  also  with  morals.  The  virtue  of 
chastity  may  have  been  better  taught  and  more 
generally  practised  among  the  Jews,  self-devotion 
among  the  Romans,  personal  loyalty  among  the 
Germans,  sympathy  with  all  living  things  on  the 
banks  of  the  Ganges.  But  just  as  no  alien 
philosophy  and  no  alien  art,  taken  altogether, 
could  compete  with  the  philosophy  and  the 
art  of  Hellas,  so  neither  was  the  moral  life  of 
any  other  people  so  rich,  so  well  balanced,  so 
identified  with  its  inmost  nature,  yet  so  capable 
of  a  world-wide  diffusion  or  of  expansion 


i4         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

and   adaptation   to  altered   circumstances  in  after 
ages. 

That  the  Greeks  were  so  great  in  art  and  science 
turnishes  a  certain  presumption  that  they  attained, 
to  say  the  least  of  it,  some  eminence  in  morality. 
To  part  off  the  aesthetic  life  and  the  intellectual 
life  from  the  life  of  conduct,  as  Matthew  Arnold 
does,  is  a  mere  conventional  abstraction.  It  would 
be  little  to  say  that  there  is  no  hard-and-fast  line  of 
demarcation ;  there  is,  in  fact,  no  line  at  all. 
Conduct  is  co-extensive  with  activity,  and  falls 
under  different  laws  of  obligation  as  its  subject- 
matter  varies  ;  but  it  never  escapes  from  obligation 
altogether.  As  regards  fine  art,  this  truth  is  now 
widely  recognised,  and  finds  expression  in  such 
common  terms  as  "good  work,"  "conscience,"  and 
"sincerity"  in  connection  with  the  production  and 
the  criticism  of  aesthetic  objects.  And  as  regards 
scientific  investigation  it  is  almost  too  obvious  to 
need  emphasising.  Of  course  the  artist  and, 
although  more  rarely,  the  philosopher  may  be 
faithful  to  the  duties  of  his  special  calling  and 
faithless  to  the  ordinary  duties  of  a  citizen,  like 
Benvenuto  Cellini  or  Francis  Bacon.  But  the 
same  possibility  of  a  high  moral  development  in 
one  direction,  combined  with  grave  deficiencies  in 
another,  runs  through  the  whole  circle  of  human 
activity.  There  seems  to  be  no  solidarity  among 
the  virtues.  Sovereigns  exemplary  in  their  domestic 
relations,  and  ready  to  undergo  martyrdom  for  their 
religion,  have  been  false  to  their  word  like  Charles 
I.,  or  false  to  their  country  like  Louis  XVI.  And 
conversely  the  highest  public  loyalty  may  co-exist 
with  gross  private  vices  as  in  the  case  of  William 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM          15 

III.  A  keen  sense  of  beauty  may  have  its  tempta- 
tions in  the  direction  of  sexual  immorality  ;  and 
the  impersonation  of  Aprodite  Anadyomene  by 
Phryne,  so  picturesquely  described  by  Matthew 
Arnold,  may  indicate  a  weak  point  of  this  kind  in 
Hellenism.  But  Puritanism,  too,  has  its  tempta- 
tions in  the  direction,  among  others,  of  savage 
cruelty  towards  women,  abundantly  illustrated  in 
the  history  of  our  own  civil  wars. 

Intellectualism,  likewise,  may  have  its  moral 
dangers,  among  which  want  of  common  honesty 
will  probably  occur  to  most  readers  as  the  chief.  But 
as  this  deficiency  seems  also  to  accompany  every 
degree  of  stupidity  and  ignorance,  the  connection 
after  all  is  very  possibly  accidental.  However  this 
may  be,  love  of  knowledge,  as  represented  by  the 
Greeks,  has  one  great  and  characteristic  virtue — the 
love  of  truth.  The  claim  will  excite  some  surprise. 
From  Cyrus  to  Hobart  Pasha  the  enemies  of  that 
people  have  habitually  spoken  of  them  as  liars.  I 
cannot  say  that  my  own  small  experience  of  the 
modern  Greeks  has  given  me  that  impression.  On 
the  contrary,  they  struck  me  rather  as  a  frank  and 
straightforward  race,  very  inaccurate  certainly,  but 
without  any  intention  to  deceive.  Our  business, 
however,  is  not  now  with  the  average  Greek, 
ancient  or  modern,  but  with  the  elite  of  the  Pagan 
period  ;  and  of  these  it  may  be  said,  I  think,  that 
they  have  set  an  example  of  truthfulness  unequalled 
except  by  those  moderns  who  have  been  trained  in 
their  school.  "  Hateful  to  me  as  the  gates  of 
Hades  is  he  who  hides  one  thing  in  his  breast  and 
tells  another,"  says  the  Homeric  Achilles  ;  and 
Plato,  with  a  still  more  exacting  standard  of  veracity, 


16         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

censures  Achilles  for  uttering  threats  that  he  does 
not  mean  to  execute.1  Sophocles,  in  what  is, 
ethically  at  least,  the  noblest  of  all  his  tragedies, 
makes  Neoptolemus,  the  son  of  Achilles  and  the 
guardian  of  his  tradition,  quite  incapable  of  carry- 
ing out  the  scheme  of  deceit  into  which  he  has 
been  reluctantly  drawn.  "Tell  no  lies"  was  a 
maxim  of  Solon.  Thucydides,  himself  a  historian 
of  admirable  sincerity,  seems  to  cast  a  slight 
shade  of  censure  on  the  heroic  Brasidas  for  making 
a  statement  that  was  untrue,  although  useful  from 
the  diplomatic  point  of  view.2  Epaminondas  was 
famous  for  his  strict  adherence  to  truth  ;  and 
Marcus  Aurelius,  known  as  Verissimus,  ascribes  his 
hatred  of  falsehood  to  the  teaching  of  a  Stoic  tutor.3 
A  Roman  satirist  has  charged  the  Greek  his- 
torians with  mendacity  on  a  point  where  their 
accuracy  has  been  signally  confirmed  by  modern 
research.4  He  might  with  more  justice  have  ex- 
tended the  accusation  to  his  own  countrymen. 
Early  Roman  history  has  been  in  many  instances 
deliberately  falsified  by  national  or  family  vanity  ; 
nor  are  the  later  portions  altogether  trustworthy. 
We  are  told  of  Dr.  Arnold  that  "  the  falsity  and 
corruption  of  the  Latin  historians  was  for  ever 
suggesting  to  him  the  contrast  of  their  Grecian 
rivals."  And  if  Arnold  had  directed  his  studies 
more  systematically  to  what  is  called  "Sacred 
History,"  the  same  contrast  might  have  suggested 
itself  in  a  more  unpleasant  form.  If  we  are  to 
credit  the  Higher  Criticism — which  is  the  only 


1  Hippias  Minor,  370  A.  a  iv.,  108. 

3  Meditations,  i.,  15.  4  Juvenal,  x.,  174. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         17 

honest  criticism — whole  masses  of  ancient  Hebrew 
literature  are  deliberate  forgeries,  in  the  sense  in 
which  we  speak  of  the  forged  Decretals  of  Isidore  ; 
and  the  incidents  related  in  them  are  to  a  great 
extent  fictitious.  Theologians  tell  us  that  the 
fabrication  of  documents  purporting  to  contain  a 
divine  revelation  did  not  at  that  period  and  among 
Orientals  imply  the  same  guilt  that  a  like  proceed- 
ing argued  in  the  Middle  Ages  and  would  argue 
now.  If  so,  it  seems  rather  audacious  to  refer  us 
to  such  a  quarter  for  elementary  moral  instruction. 
However  that  may  be,  we  have  to  congratulate 
ourselves  on  the  fact  that  in  Attica,  at  any  rate, 
public  opinion  had  early  risen  to  a  stage  at  which 
truth  and  falsehood  were  more  accurately  discrimi- 
nated. Herodotus  has  preserved  an  anecdote  that 
well  illustrates  the  contrast  offered  by  Hellenism 
and  Hebraism  in  this  respect.  During  the  sixth 
century  B.C.  a  great  religious  revival,  now  known 
as  Orphicism,  sprang  up  in  the  Greek  world  and 
had  Attica  for  its  principal  seat.  One  of  the 
leaders  of  the  movement,  a  certain  Onomacritus, 
stood  high  in  the  favour  of  the  Peisistratid  Hip- 
parchus,  and  seems  to  have  been  employed  by 
him  in  editing  the  prophecies  of  Musaeus,  a  some- 
what mythical  authority  of  the  school.  Having, 
however,  been  detected  in  the  act  of  interpolating 
a  prediction  of  his  own  in  the  collection,  the 
unlucky  forger  was  summarily  expelled  from  the 
country  by  his  indignant  patron,  one  of  whose 
maxims,  engraved  where  every  passer-by  could 
read  it,  was,  "  Do  not  deceive  thy  friend."1 

1  Herodotus,  vii.,  6. 


i8         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

Hipparchus  was  not,  in  other  respects,  a  model 
of  virtue,  but  it  is  fortunate  that  in  this  matter  of 
pious  forgeries  we  have  been  brought  up  on  his 
principles  rather  than  on  Hilkiah's.  But  our 
excellent  training  has  its  occasional  inconveniences. 
It  makes  some  honourable  persons  too  reluctant  to 
admit  that  forgery  and  fabrication  on  a  great  scale 
were  actually  practised  by  holy  men  among  the 
Jews.  Moving  in  a  world  of  Hellenic  sincerity, 
and  not  without  the  simplicity  that  a  wise  Hellene 
has  called  the  principal  element  in  a  noble  nature, 
they  have  failed  to  realise  the  possibilities  of 
Hebraic  duplicity.  A  typical  example  of  this 
uncompromising  attitude  is  furnished  by  the 
manner  in  which  that  great  and  high-minded 
theologian,  F.  D.  Maurice,  was  impressed  by  the 
speculations  of  Colenso.  "  I  asked  him,"  writes 
Maurice,  "  if  he  did  not  think  Samuel  must  have 
been  a  horrid  scoundrel  if  he  forged  a  story  about 
the  I  AM,  speaking  of  Moses,  and,  to  my  unspeak- 
able surprise  and  terror,  he  said  '  No.  Many  good 
men  have  done  such  things.  He  might  not  mean 
more  than  Milton  meant.'  "  1  Most  educated  theo- 
logians have  come  to  agree  with  Colenso,  except 
that  they  would  place  the  composition  of  the 
Elohistic  narrative  considerably  later  than  the  time 
of  Samuel.  But  their  whole  tone  as  regards  the 
limits  of  truthfulness  in  religious  teaching  is  such 
as  to  inspire  plain  men  with  something  of  the 
"  surprise  and  terror  "  felt  by  Maurice. 

It  may  be  objected  that  Plato,  a  typical  Greek 
and  the  greatest  of  Greek  moralists,  took  similar 

1  Life  of  F.  D.  Maurice,  II.,  p.  423. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         19 

liberties  with  the  truth,  to  the  extent  even  of  leaving 
it  doubtful  whether  he  really  believed  in  any  God 
or  in  any  future  life.  The  fact  is  so  ;  and  his 
warmest  admirers  must  always  regret  that  it  should 
be  so.  Such  prevarications  show  the  mischief  that 
comes  of  trying  to  combine  mythology  with  philo- 
sophy. But,  at  any  rate,  Plato  knew  what  he  was 
doing.  Unlike  our  modern  theologians,  he  avoided 
what  he  called  the  "lie  in  the  soul,"  not  deceiving 
himself,  however  much  he  may  have  wished  to 
deceive  the  people.  Even  here  we  can  see  how 
admirably  well  Ruskin  has  said  of  the  Greeks, 
"they  have  not  lifted  up  their  souls  unto  vanity." 

From  the  consideration  of  veracity  as  practised 
in  Greece  we  pass  to  that  part  of  conduct  which  is 
more  directly  concerned  with  the  mutual  relations 
of  human  beings,  to  the  great  interests  of  justice 
and  beneficence. 

It  is  a  familiar  fact  that  the  people  of  whom  we 
are  speaking  divided  all  mankind  into  Greeks  and 
barbarians.  By  the  latter  they  originally  meant 
only  those  whose  language  they  could  not  under- 
stand. But  in  time  barbarian  came  to  mean  much 
more  than  this.  With  the  Greeks,  as  with  our- 
selves, it  stood  for  the  opposite  of  civilised.  But 
the  civilisation  with  which  they  identified  Hellenism 
was  no  mere  material  good.  The  barbarians  might 
have  better  roads,  more  accumulated  capital,  a  more 
highly  developed  industrial  system,  larger  and  even 
better  disciplined  armies  than  theirs.  In  the  eyes 
of  a  Greek  these  things  were  desirable,  but  they 
were  not  the  one  thing  needful.  That  one  thing 
without  which  there  could  be  no  real  civilisation 
was  the  reign  of  law  in  opposition  to  the  rule  of  a 


20          THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

despot  on  the  one  hand,  and  on  the  other  to  that 
anarchical  state  of  society  where  wrongs  are 
redressed,  or  rather  perpetuated,  by  private 
vengeance.  It  is  a  blessing,  says  the  Jason  of 
Euripides,  to  live  in  a  country  that  is  governed  not 
by  brute  force,  but  by  law.1  And  the  same  poet 
makes  Tyndareus  tell  his  son-in-law  Menelaus,  who 
has  been  excusing  the  matricide  of  Orestes,  that  he 
has  become  barbarised  by  living  out  of  Greece  so 
long.  Otherwise  he  would  see  that  the  right  course 
for  Orestes  was  to  bring  his  mother  before  a  court 
of  justice  on  the  charge  of  murdering  her  husband. 
For  when  one  homicide  is  requited  by  another  the 
blood-feud  goes  on  for  ever,  to  the  total  destruction 
of  orderly  and  peaceful  relations.2  Let  those  who 
expatiate  on  the  moral  superiority  of  Hebraism  to 
Hellenism  remember  that  this  barbarous  principle 
of  blood-vengeance  is  sanctioned  by  the  Priestly 
Code  promulgated  by  Ezra  in  the  middle  of  the  fifth 
century  B.C.,  and  that  it  was  in  full  force  at  the 
very  time  when  the  noble  verses  of  Euripides  were 
being  recited  before  the  assembled  people  of  Athens. 
And  this  suggests  another  contrast.  Thanks  to 
the  eloquence  of  Renan  and  the  still  more  fervid 
declamations  of  James  Darmesteter,  himself  a  Jew, 
much  attention  was  drawn  ten  years  ago3  to  the 
passionate  preaching  of  justice  by  the  Hebrew 
prophets.  It  was  well  that  this  should  be  done, 
and  done  so  well.  It  was  well  that  devout  readers 
of  Scripture  should  be  made  to'  realise  the  fact 
that  the  prophets  of  Israel  had  something  else  to 
do  than  to  mystify  their  hearers  by  discussing  the 

1  Medea,  536-38.          *  Orestes,  485  sqq.          3  Written  in  1901. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         21 

affairs  of  modern  Europe  between  two  and  three 
thousand  years  in  advance.  And  it  was  well  also 
to  remind  pious  company-promoters  and  guinea- 
pigs  that  subscriptions  to  missionary  societies 
would  not  have  purchased  absolution  for  wholesale 
robbery  from  Amos  and  Isaiah.  All  honour  to  the 
preachers  who,  whether  at  Samaria  and  Jerusalem 
or  in  London  and  Paris,  identify  religion  with 
justice  and  mercy  rather  than  with  dogma  and 
ritual !  But  let  not  our  recognition  of  their  services 
blind  us  to  the  still  greater  services  of  those  who, 
unaided  by  supernatural  promises  or  terrors, 
actually  accomplished  that  for  which  the  prophets 
vainly  strove — the  legislators,  magistrates,  and 
orators  who  established  and  carried  on  the 
righteous  governments  of  Greece  under  which 
the  poor  working  man  could  not  be  plundered 
with  impunity  as  he  was  plundered  in  the  Holy 
Land. 

Certain  historical  errors  die  hard,  and  one  has 
just  occurred  to  me  against  which  it  would  be  well 
to  enter  a  caution.  I  can  imagine  some  readers 
exclaiming,  "  There  were  no  paid  working  men  in 
Greece  ;  the  free  Greek  citizens  were  an  oligarchy 
living  in  idleness  on  the  produce  of  slave  labour." 
Such,  indeed,  seems  to  have  been  at  one  time  the 
prevalent  belief,  and  it  may  still  survive  in  certain 
circles.  To  assert  that  the  Greek  democracies  were 
not  democracies  at  all  in  our  sense  of  the  word,  but 
aristocracies  of  a  particularly  oppressive  kind,  was 
part  of  the  reactionary  and  anti-Hellenic  propaganda 
carried  on  after  the  French  Revolution,  to  which 
reference  has  been  already  made.  The  assertion 
is,  however,  untrue,  and  anyone  may  easily 


22         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

convince  himself  by  consulting  the  Greek  litera- 
ture of  the  fifth  and  fourth  centuries  B.C.  that  the 
bulk  of  the  Athenian  voters  consisted  of  petty  shop- 
keepers, peasants,  and  day  labourers.  Slaves  no 
doubt  there  were,  and  a  good  many  of  them, 
although  their  number  has  been  enormously 
exaggerated,  as  Professor  Beloch  shows  in  his 
brilliant  work  on  the  population  of  the  ancient 
world.1  But  slavery  existed  everywhere  in 
antiquity,  in  Judaea  as  well  as  in  Greece.  White 
slavery,  indeed,  lasted  far  down  into  the  Middle 
Ages,  with  the  partial  approval  of  the  Church,  and 
was  finally  extinguished  by  purely  economical 
causes  ;  while  black  slavery,  after  being  actively 
promoted  by  professing  Christians,  and  attaining 
portentous  dimensions  without  a  protest  from  the 
Christian  conscience,  owed  its  final  destruction  to 
a  movement  set  on  foot  by  freethinking  philosophers 
and  then  taken  up  by  that  most  rationalistic  of 
Christian  sects,  the  Society  of  Friends.  But  the 
original  impulse  to  abolitionism  came,  as  will 
presently  be  shown,  from  Greek  thought. 

Returning  to  the  contrast  between  the  Greeks 
and  other  nations,  it  has  to  be  observed  that  the 
barbarians,  too,  had  their  laws — a  fact  of  which  we 
cannot  suppose  Euripides  to  have  been  ignorant, 
as  it  was  already  familiar  to  Herodotus.  The  really 
important  distinction  was  that,  while  the  Greek  laws 
gave  a  far  more  effectual  protection  against  the 
arbitrary  will  of  the  rulers  and  against  the  passions 
of  private  individuals,  they  did  not  become,  as  with 


1  J.  Beloch,  Die  Bevolkerung  der  griechtsch-romischen  Welt,  pp. 
84  sqq. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         23 

the  Asiatics,  an  instrument  of  irremediable  bondage. 
Where  men's  habits  of  thinking  took  their  whole 
shape  and  colour  from  the  traditions  of  despotism 
the  law  itself  could  not  be  conceived  but  as  a  despot 
armed  with  divine  authority  and  raised  above 
criticism  or  emendation.  There  may  have  been 
something  of  the  same  feeling  in  Greece  also. 
But  at  a  comparatively  early  period  it  was  met  and 
overcome  by  the  idea  of  law  as  an  expression  of  the 
collective  will,  and  therefore  as  something  that 
might  be  altered  with  the  altered  needs  of  the 
community,  or  with  the  increase  of  general 
enlightenment.  Her  teachers  expressed  this  prin- 
ciple in  various  ways,  one  by  declaring  that  man 
was  the  measure  of  all  things,  another  by  con- 
tending that  the  measure  was  rather  supplied  by 
nature,  by  the  rules  of  conduct  that  experience 
showed  to  be  observed  at  all  times  and  in  all 
places. 

Either  of  these  methods  would  serve  to  accom- 
plish the  step  that  first  makes  morality  what  it  is, 
the  transition  from  the  letter  to  the  spirit  of  legal 
obligation.  We  owe  to  Rome  the  word  equity  by 
which  that  essential  element  of  law  is  ordinarily 
expressed  ;  but  the  notion  is  purely  Greek.  It  is 
that  iirteiiceia — rather  oddly  translated  "  sweet 
reasonableness "  by  Matthew  Arnold — which 
Aristotle  has  defined  in  a  manner  that  leaves 
nothing  to  be  desired.  He  tells  us  that  the 
equitable  man  fulfils  the  intention  of  the  legislator 
in  cases  for  which  the  legislator,  being  tied  to 
general  terms,  could  not  provide.  In  cases  of 
disputed  right  he  will  not  grasp  all  that  the  letter 
of  the  law  gives  him,  but  will  take  somewhat  less 


24         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

than  his  strict  right.  And  as  the  laws  must  be 
interpreted  in  the  light  of  their  original  intention, 
so  also  the  merit  of  the  obedience  paid  to  them,  or 
the  demerit  of  disobedience,  must  be  measured  by 
the  agent's  intention.  Involuntary  transgressions, 
according  to  Aristotle,  are  not  deserving  of  punish- 
ment, but  of  pardon,  and  sometimes  of  pity.  That 
anyone  can  justly  be  made  to  surfer  punishment 
for  a  wrong  committed  through  no  fault  of  his 
would,  from  this  point  of  view,  have  been  abso- 
lutely unintelligible.  So  also  would  be  the  theory 
that  crimes  can  be  expiated  by  the  sufferings  of 
the  innocent.  And  at  the  present  day  such  beliefs 
are  explicable  only  as  survivals  or  recrudescences 
of  Hebraic  barbarism,  quite  impossible  in  a  com- 
pletely Hellenised  society. 

A  spiritualised  morality  relieves  the  individual 
from  all  responsibility  for  actions  not  committed 
intentionally  by  him  or  through  any  negligence 
on  his  part.  But  within  the  sphere  of  individual 
life  it  extends  responsibility  from  overt  acts  to 
thoughts  and  desires.  A  Spartan  who  consulted 
the  Delphic  oracle  on  the  desirability  of  appro- 
priating a  deposit  that  he  had  sworn  to  return 
received  for  answer  that  his  very  question  amounted 
to  a  crime,  and  would  be  punished  as  such.1  When 
the  poet  Sophocles  dwelt  somewhat  too  rapturously 
on  the  charms  of  a  beautiful  stranger,  Pericles 
reminded  him  that  the  eyes  of  a  general  should 
be  as  pure  as  his  hands.2  And,  in  what  is  believed 
to  be  a  portrait  of  Aristeides,  Aeschylus  describes 
him  as  wishing  not  to  seem  but  to  be  the  best.3 

1  Herodotus,  vi.,  p.  86.  2  Plutarch,  Pericles,  chap.  viii. 

3  Seven  against  Thebes,  588. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         25 

An  intention  or  wish  may  be  made  the  subject  of 
human,  or  at  least  of  divine,  penalties,  as  we  saw 
in  the  case  of  the  fraudulent  Spartan,  and  may  be 
repressed  solely  through  the  fear  of  such.  There- 
fore, to  complete  the  spiritualisation  of  morality  it 
must  become  wholly  disinterested,  or  dependent  on 
none  but  internal  sanctions.  Greek  philosophy 
rose  to  this  height.  It  pronounced  the  distinguish- 
ing mark  of  a  sage  to  be  that  he  would  act  as 
before  if  the  laws  ceased  to  exist.  And  Plato 
pushed  the  principle  to  an  extreme  when  he  main- 
tained that,  even  if  the  just  man  should  live  in 
obloquy  and  die  in  torment,  he  would  have  chosen 
wisely  in  preferring  righteousness  to  prosperous 
iniquity.1 

The  sanction  of  disinterested  virtue  lies  in  the 
pain  given  by  a  wounded  conscience  to  those  who 
violate  its  dictates.  Both  the  notion  and  the  name 
of  conscience  are  Greek  creations,  and  first  received 
wide  currency  from  the  Stoic  philosophy,  whence 
they  passed  to  St.  Paul  and  became  so  thoroughly 
incorporated  with  Christian  theology  that,  in  the 
opinion  of  many,  the  existence  of  such  an  inward 
monitor  was  unknown  to  Paganism.  But  we  find 
it  distinctly  recognised  by  Isocrates 2  a  century  before 
Zeno  taught  at  Athens  ;  nor  can  we  suppose  that 
a  popular  rhetorician  was  the  first  to  formulate  so 
profound  a  thought.  Indeed,  the  thing  itself  goes 
back  to  Homer,  in  the  character  of  whose  Helen  it 
is  a  distinguishing  trait.  Alike  in  the  supreme 
triumph  of  her  beauty  on  the  walls  of  Troy  and  in 
the  dignity  of  her  rehabilitated  matronhood  at 

1  Republic,  p.  361.  2  Demonicus,  i.,  p.  16. 


26         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

Sparta,  the  sense  of  forfeited  female  honour  is  ever 
present  to  her  thoughts,  and  that  without  the  least 
admixture  of  supernatural  terror — for  the  goddess 
Aphrodite  is  offended  by  her  scruples — or  of 
shrinking  from  public  opinion,  for  no  voice  is 
raised  against  her  but  her  own. 

"In  justice,"  says  Phocylides,  "is  summed  up 
the  whole  of  virtue."  "Justice,"  says  an  unknown 
Greek  author,  "  is  more  beautiful  than  the  morning 
or  evening  star."  But  what,  after  all,  did  they 
mean  by  it?  Aristotle,  who  quotes  these  lyrical 
expressions,  gives  no  very  helpful  definition  ;  nor 
does  Plato,  although  his  Republic  was  written  to 
develop  the  idea  of  justice.  Here,  again,  we  may 
profitably  consult  Isocrates.  That  excellent  teacher 
tells  us  not  to  do  to  others  what  would  make  us 
angry  if  it  were  done  to  us1 — the  first  and  far  the 
more  important  part  of  the  golden  rule.  The  prin- 
ciple is  not  enunciated  as  if  it  were  particularly 
new ;  but  Isocrates  applies  it  elsewhere  in  a  way 
that  was  new  to  his  contemporaries,  that  had  not 
occurred  to  anyone  outside  Greece,  and  that  even 
now  is  not  universally  recognised.  He  tells 
husbands  that  they  have  no  right  to  exact  from 
their  wives  what  they  do  not  give,  and  that  the 
fidelity  which  they  demand  is  equally  obligatory 
on  themselves.2  Monogamy  had  been  a  law  with 
the  Greeks  so  far  back  as  we  can  trace  their  history, 
and  they  regarded  polygamy  with  abhorrence 
as  a  custom  of  the  Barbarians 3 — a  fact  which 
those  should  remember  who  set  the  Hebrews,  a 

1  Nicocles,  p.  61.  2  Ibid,  p.  40. 

3  Euripides,  Andromache,  177,  243,  464. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         27 

polygamous  people,  on  a  higher  moral  plane.  And 
we  see  by  this  passage  in  Isocrates  that  some,  at 
least,  among  the  Greeks  were  prepared  to  draw 
the  logical  consequences  of  monogamy.  Nor  was 
the  principle  here  enunciated  ever  quite  forgotten. 
Plato  also  in  his  last  period  enjoins  the  same  con- 
stancy on  husbands,  though  rather  on  grounds  of 
social  utility  than  of  justice;1  and  although  the 
first  Stoics,  like  some  moderns,  advocated  free  love 
for  both  sexes  alike,  Epictetus,  writing  four  centuries 
later,  returns  to  the  same  standard  of  conjugal 
fidelity,  with  the  recommendation,  which  is  also 
Platonic,  of  antenuptial  chastity  for  men  as  well  as 
for  women.2 

According  to  the  Greeks,  the  obligations  of 
equality  and  reciprocity  rested  on  natural  law. 
The  invariable  return  of  physical  phenomena  at 
equal  intervals  of  time,  the  co-existence  and  mutual 
limitation  of  the  everlasting  elements  that  make  up 
the  universe,  were  so  many  object-lessons  in  justice, 
so  many  silent  protests  against  the  abuse  of 
superior  strength  or  the  violation  of  sworn  pledges 
among  men.  And  unmeasured  indulgence  in 
sensual  gratifications  was  similarly  interpreted  as  a 
derogation  from  the  rationality  by  which  nature 
had  expressly  distinguished  men  from  brutes. 
Thus  the  maxim,  Follow  nature,  came  to  be 
accepted  as  the  great  constitutive  principle  of 
morals.  And  it  was  not  merely  used  as  a  general 
sanction  for  the  accepted  code  of  conduct,  but  still 
more  as  a  potent  engine  of  reform,  as  a  protest 
against  inveterate  abuses,  or  as  an  index  to  new 

1  Laws,  pp.  839-40.  2  Encheiridion,  xxxiii.,  p.  8. 


28         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

ideals  of  perfection.  We  have  not  now  to  discuss 
the  logical  value  of  the  physiocratic  method.  It 
may  be  used  at  all  times,  and  it  was  more  than 
once  used  at  Athens,  as  an  apology  for  anti-social 
egoism  on  the  part  of  individuals  or  of  States. 
Civilisation  itself  has  been  condemned  as  a  depar- 
ture from  nature  ;  and,  conversely,  nature  might  be 
denounced  as  the  great  enemy  of  civilisation,  with 
the  further  deduction  that  no  artificial  refinement 
on  our  original  pleasures  should  be  tabooed  merely 
on  the  ground  that  it  is  unnatural.  But  good 
causes  are  often  supported  by  bad  reasons  ;  and, 
whether  logical  or  not,  the  Greek  appeal  to  nature 
seems  on  the  whole  to  have  made  for  righteousness. 
Certain  detestable  vices  were  once  for  all  stigma- 
tised as  unnatural,  and  a  constant  warfare  kept  up 
against  them  by  the  philosophers  from  Prodicus  to 
Plotinus,  until  the  attack  was  taken  over  by  Chris- 
tianity to  be  prosecuted  with  more  drastic  methods, 
although,  if  we  are  to  believe  Roger  Bacon  and 
Dante,  for  a  long  time  with  no  greater  success. 

Another  application  of  the  same  principle  led  to 
the  denunciation  of  slavery  as  contrary  to  nature. 
The  cry  was  apparently  first  raised  to  justify  the 
revolt  of  Messenian  Helots  against  their  Spartan 
masters,  but  it  soon  received  a  far  wider  applica- 
tion. Certain  philosophers  struck  at  the  root  of 
what  was  not  then  a  "  peculiar  institution  "  by 
declaring  that  all  men  were  born  free.  This 
assumption  has  been  mercilessly  criticised  by 
Bentham,  and  more  recently  on  the  same  lines 
by  Huxley.  As  a  question  of  logic,  their  triumph 
is  complete  ;  but  the  crudeness  of  the  naturalistic 
formula  should  not  blind  us  to  the  truth  that  it 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         29 

contains.  To  enslave  a  human  being  is  to  treat 
him  like  a  brute,  or,  in  the  still  more  degrading 
phrase  of  Aristotle,  like  a  living  tool ;  and  no 
reasonable  being  will,  in  the  long  run,  submit  to 
such  treatment,  or  regard  it  as  anything  but  an 
outrage.  Reasonings  of  a  more  elaborate  and  far- 
reaching  character  show  that  the  exploitation  of 
one  class  by  another  leads  to  the  ruin  of  the  whole 
community  ;  but  nothing  so  surely  rouses  the 
oppressed  to  revolt,  or  the  brave  and  disinterested 
to  the  championship  of  their  cause,  as  an  appeal  to 
this  wounded  sentiment ;  and  it  is  part  of  our 
ethical  debt  to  the  Greeks  that  the  appeal  was  first 
made  by  them. 

To  assert  one's  own  rights,  and  to  respect  the 
rights  of  others,  is  much,  but  it  is  not  all ;  and, 
human  nature  being  what  it  is,  a  well-organised 
community  cannot  rest  on  the  single  virtue  of 
justice.  After  law,  and  the  spirit  of  law  which  is 
equity,  we  must  bring  in  the  third  and  completing 
element  of  morality,  which  is  love.  I  am  not  sure 
what  is  the  current  estimate  of  the  Greeks  in  this 
respect.  Perhaps  the  same  popular  writers  and 
preachers  who  deny  them  morality  and  conscience 
think  of  them  also — ad  majorem  Dei gloriam — as  a 
heartless  and  selfish  people,  wrapped  up  in  a  sense 
of  their  own  superiority  to  the  rest  of  the  world. 
Mr.  Stillman,  who  stood  up  for  the  modern  Greeks, 
called  their  Pagan  ancestors  (or  predecessors)  a 
cruel  and  bloodthirsty  canaille.  Burckhardt,  with 
more  scholarship  than  Stillman,  seems  to  have 
arrived  at  pretty  much  the  same  conclusion.  In 
fact,  they  suffer  from  being  so  very  modern.  We 
judge  them  not  by  comparison  with  the  Jews  or  the 


30         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

Romans,  or  even  with  mediaeval  Christendom,  but 
by  our  own  ethical  standards. 

Here  again  the  antithesis  between  Hellenes  and 
barbarians  may  prove  helpful.  In  English  and 
other  modern  languages  "  barbarous,"  as  we  know, 
has  the  secondary  meaning  of  inhuman  and  cruel. 
But  this  association  has  come  down  to  us  from  the 
Latin,  and  was  adopted  by  the  Latins  from  the 
Greeks.  In  Greek  literature  the  instances  where 
"  barbarous "  is  used  in  the  sense  of  cruel  are 
certainly  late  and  few,  but  they  are  sufficient  to 
show  that  cruelty  was  regarded  as  essentially  alien 
to  the  Greek  character.  Nor  was  the  belief 
unfounded.  History  and  literature  testify  to  its 
validity,  to  the  relative  humanity  of  the  Greeks, 
and  more  especially  of  those  among  them  in  whom 
the  Hellenic  type  most  perfectly  realised  itself. 
Homer's  Achilles  was  a  merciful  victor  until  the 
death  of  Patroclus  almost  extinguished  pity  in  his 
breast,  and  even  then  it  could  be  reawakened  by 
the  tears  of  Priam.  Euripides  tells  us  that  to  slay 
prisoners  of  war  was  against  the  laws  of  Athens.' 
The  Spartan  Gylippus  pleaded,  though  in  vain, 
for  the  lives  of  the  captive  Athenian  generals  at 
Syracuse;  and  another  great  Spartan,  Callicratidas, 
declared  that  no  Greek  should  be  sold  into  slavery 
with  his  consent.2  With  the  spread  of  philosophy 
this  feeling  received  a  wider  extension.  Agesilaus 
impressed  on  his  troops  the  duty  of  treating  their 
Persian  prisoners  with  humanity.3  Epameinondas 


'  Heracleidae,  961-66. 

2  Grote,  History  of  Greece,  vi.,  pp.  179  and  387. 

3  Op,  cit.,  vii.,  p.  429. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         31 

refused  to  participate  in  a  political  assassination.1 
Dion,  the  pupil  of  Plato,  declared  that  he  had 
learned  in  the  Academy  not  merely  to  be  loyal  to 
his  friends,  but  to  forgive  injuries  and  to  be  gentle 
to  transgressors  ;2  and  we  know  from  Plato's  Laws 
that  this  was  really  what  the  master  taught.  Philip 
and  Alexander  too,  though  ruling  over  a  semi- 
barbarous  people,  and  not  without  a  deep  taint  of 
barbarism  in  their  personal  habits,  showed  in  their 
hour  of  triumph  a  clemency  hitherto  unknown  to 
the  possessors  of  irresponsible  power. 

These,  it  may  be  admitted,  are  no  more  than 
individual  instances  of  a  merciful  disposition.  But 
language  may  fairly  be  quoted  in  evidence  of  its 
wide  diffusion.  The  very  word  humanity  is  of 
Greek  origin,  being  a  translation  (through  the 
Latin)  of  QiXavOpwiria,  which  conveys  the  same 
meaning  with  a  somewhat  warmer  tone.  And 
there  is  the  more  direct  evidence  of  Plato,  who  tells 
us  that  one  expects  the  inhabitants  of  a  Greek  city 
to  be  good  and  gentle.  Gentleness  and  humanity, 
says  Isocrates,  are  of  all  qualities  the  most  highly 
esteemed  among  men  ;  and  the  Athenians,  at  least, 
liked  to  be  complimented  on  their  possession.  But 
the  best  proof  of  their  prevalence  is  afforded  by  a 
passage  where  it  is  quite  incidentally  and  unin- 
tentionally disclosed.  In  what  is  meant  to  be  a 
very  satirical  picture  of  democratic  society, 
obviously  drawn  from  his  own  native  city,  Plato 
mentions  that  the  last  extreme  of  popular  liberty  is 
where  "the  slave  is  just  as  free  as  his  purchaser." 
Even  allowing  for  exaggeration,  where  so  much  as 

1  Op.  cit.,  viii.,  p.  78.  2  Plutarch,  Dion,  p.  979,  A. 


32         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

this  could  be  said  slaves  must  have  been  very  kindly 
treated.  And  it  is  a  fresh  tribute  to  Athenian 
humanity  when  Plato  adds  that  "  horses  and  asses 
have  a  way  of  marching  along  [in  the  streets  of  a 
democratic  city]  with  all  the  rights  and  dignities  of 
freemen."  He  also  mentions,  what  to  many  will 
sound  the  most  surprising  thing  of  all,  that  under 
an  extreme  democracy — i.e.,  at  Athens,  there  was 
complete  equality  between  the  sexes.1 

To  appreciate  fully  the  humanity  of  the  Greeks 
we  must  compare  them  with  the  other  leading 
nations  of  antiquity.  Little  need  be  said  of  the 
great  Oriental  monarchies.  Of  these  Egypt  seems 
to  have  been  the  least  barbarous  ;  yet  Egyptian 
sculptors  loved  to  represent  their  most  famous 
kings  in  the  act  of  butchering  a  crowd  of  defence- 
less captives,  and  their  labourers  as  fainting  under 
the  taskmaster's  stick.  The  Phoenicians,  with  their 
crucifixions  and  human  holocausts,  may  also  be 
summarily  dismissed.  If  the  early  annals  of  the 
Israelites  as  recorded  in  the  Hexateuch  were 
authentic,  we  could  no  more  ascribe  any  feeling 
of  humanity  to  such  a  sanguinary  and  fanatical 
horde  than  to  the  Huns  or  to  Abdul  Hamid. 
Happily,  and  to  the  no  small  satisfaction  of 
enlightened  modern  Jews,  the  wholesale  atrocities 
recounted  with  so  much  complacency  by  the 
priestly  historian  are  demonstrably  fictitious.  But 
the  fiction  has  a  historical  value.  It  shows  what 
were  the  ideals  of  the  Jewish  nation  in  the  fifth 
century  B.C.,  and  presumably  of  their  descendants 
for  many  centuries  afterwards  ;  and  the  impression 

1  Republic,  via.,  p.  563  (Jowett's  translation). 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         33 

thus  created  is  deepened  by  the  testimony  of  the 
equally  fabulous  book  of  Esther. 

The  only  people  of  antiquity  who  can  dispute 
the  moral  supremacy  of  Greece  are  the  Romans. 
They  had,  no  doubt,  their  good  qualities ;  but  of 
these  humanity  was  not  one.  In  reference  to  the 
political  struggles  of  the  early  Roman  republic, 
Macaulay  has  indeed  credited  them  with  a  tender- 
ness for  the  lives  of  their  fellow-citizens  unknown 
to  Greek  factions.1  But  Dr.  Arnold  has  conclu- 
sively vindicated  the  Greeks  from  this  aspersion. 
He  points  out  that  the  bloodless  struggles  between 
the  Patricians  and  the  Plebeians  are  more  properly 
paralleled  by  the  equally  bloodless  contest  of  the 
"  party  of  the  coast "  at  Athens  with  the  Eupatridas  ; 
while  the  more  sanguinary  faction-fights  of  later 
Greek  history  answer  to  the  proscriptions  of  Marius 
and  Sulla,  or  of  the  Triumvirs.2 

Apart  from  such  episodical  outbreaks  of  passion, 
we  have  indubitable  proofs  of  the  inhumanity  of 
the  Romans  in  the  barbarous  character  of  their 
punishments — especially  their  custom  of  flogging 
before  executing,  even  in  the  case  of  prisoners  of 
war — and  still  more  of  their  amusements.  It  must 
indeed  be  admitted  that  through  the  contagion  of 
Roman  example  the  gladiatorial  games  spread  at 
last  over  the  whole  Hellenic  world.  But  Greek 
philosophy  kept  up  a  steady  protest  against  this 
barbarity  ;  and,  when  it  was  proposed  to  introduce 
the  games  into  Athens,  Demonicus  the  Cynic 
called  on  the  people  to  begin  by  pulling  down  the 


1  In  the  Preface  to  his  Virginia. 
*  Arnold's  Thucydides,  i.,  p.  519. 

D 


34         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

altar  of  pity.     According  to  the  modern  writer  who 
has  studied   the   civilisation   of  the   Empire  most 
profoundly,    this    amusement  was    never   popular 
with  any  but  the  dregs  of  the  people  in  Greece;1 
and  it  was  finally  abolished  in  the  West  through 
the  heroic  self-sacrifice  of  a  Greek.     Everyone  has 
heard  how  the  monk  Telemachus  made  his  way 
from  the  heart  of  the  Eastern  Empire  to  protest 
against  the  cruel  exhibitions  still  kept  up  at  Rome; 
how  he  descended  into  the  arena  of  the  Coliseum, 
threw  himself  between  the  combatants,  perished  by 
their  swords,  and  produced  such  an  effect  by  his 
death  that  public  opinion  insisted  on  the  abolition 
of  the  gladiatorial  games.     But  how  few  think  of 
this  pathetic  story  except  as   redounding   to   the 
glory   of    Christianity !     Assuredly   the    death    of 
Telemachus  does  honour  to  his  religion.     But  it 
also   does   honour  to   his  race  and  to  that  philo- 
sophical  training  which   had    been    preparing    it 
through  long  ages  to  accept  with  enthusiasm  the 
new  faith  that  was  to  give  Greek  philanthropy  a 
mystical  consecration  and  a  world-wide  diffusion. 

Before  the  advent  of  Christianity  the  diffusion,  if 
not  the  consecration,  had  already  begun.  Renan, 
if  I  remember  rightly,  has  said  that  the  Greeks 
despised  the  Barbarians  too  much  to  embrace  them 
in  a  single  fraternity.  But  here,  as  elsewhere,  the 
great  French  critic  betrays  the  ineradicable  preju- 
dices of  a  seminarist.  No  ancient  race  was  so 
generous  to  its  neighbours  or  so  beloved  by  them 
as  the  Greeks.  Already  in  Homer  the  note  of 
generous  sympathy  with  a  foeman  is  struck,  and  it 

1  Friedlander,  Sittengeschichte  Roms,  ii.,  p.  384,  5th  ed. 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         35 

never  ceases  to  vibrate  through  the  hearts  of  his 
successors.  Cyrus  and  Anacharsis  were  Greek 
ideals  ;  even  Xerxes  obtained  a  meed  of  admira- 
tion ;  and  Rome  owes  much  of  her  glory  to  the 
rapturous  eulogies  of  Greek  historians.  It  was 
seen  that  the  superiority  claimed  —  and  justly 
claimed — over  the  Barbarians  did  not  belong  to 
the  Hellenic  race  as  such,  for  in  earlier  ages  there 
had  been  no  marked  difference,  and  the  primitive 
barbarism  still  survived  in  some  Hellenic  tribes, 
but  was,  as  we  should  say,  an  evolution  due  to 
favourable  circumstances.  Hellenism,  in  fact, 
meant  culture,  and  culture  could  be  communicated 
to  all  who  desired  it.  In  the  language  of  Hippias, 
the  distinctions  of  birth  are  conventional ;  by 
nature  all  like-minded  persons  are  kinsmen, 
friends,  and  fellow-citizens.1  In  the  language  of 
Isocrates,  the  partakers  of  Athenian  culture  should 
sooner  be  called  Hellenes  than  those  who  were 
merely  of  the  same  race.2  And  in  the  same  spirit 
a  doctrine  of  human  collectivism  was  subsequently 
preached  by  the  Cynic  and,  with  more  elaboration, 
by  the  Stoic  school.  Finally,  Eratosthenes,  followed 
by  Plutarch,  proposed  to  abolish  the  distinction 
between  Greeks  and  Barbarians,  and  to  replace  it 
by  a  classification  based  entirely  on  the  contrast 
between  virtue  and  vice.3 

Had  more  of  the  earlier  Stoic  literature  been 
preserved,  we  should,  doubtless,  have  more  such 
generous  sayings  on  record.  As  it  is,  the  philo- 
sophic writers  of  the  Empire — some  of  them 


Plato,  Protagoras,  p.  337.  "  Panegyricus,  p.  51. 

3  Quoted  by  Strabo,  I.,  9. 


36         THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

Romans — must  remain  our  principal  authorities 
for  the  idea  of  a  common  humanity  with  its  implicit 
obligations  of  mutual  service  and  love.  But  even 
if  Seneca  and  Marcus  Aurelius  did  not  directly 
copy  from  the  older  masters,  the  spirit  of  their 
teaching  remains  purely  Hellenic,  and  is  derived 
by  an  unbroken  tradition  from  the  schools  of 
Athens. 

Moral  reform  is  the  verification  of  ethics.  If  the 
lectures  delivered  at  Athens  exercised  no  regenera- 
ting influence  on  their  hearers,  then  they  were 
what  the  enemies  of  philosophy  called  them,  mere 
chatter,  sophistry,  waste  of  time,  at  best  an  abstract 
expression  for  what  had  been  felt  and  done  in  the 
uncorrupted  prime  of  Hellas.  And  this  is  what  we 
are  still — or  were  until  lately — taught  to  regard  as 
the  net  result  of  speculative  Paganism  by  theo- 
logians who  fail  to  see  that  as  good  a  case  might 
be  made  out  against  Christianity  if  its  enemies 
employed  the  same  logic.  But  the  facts  are  begin- 
ning to  be  more  impartially  studied  and  better 
understood.  A  brilliant  historian,  to  whom  I  have 
already  referred,  Professor  Beloch,  points  out  how 
much  more  humanely  war  was  conducted  by  Greek 
generals  in  the  fourth  century  B.C.  than  in  the  fifth, 
and  what  better  ideas  as  to  the  position  of  women 
were  beginning  to  make  their  way  in  the  society  of 
the  same  period.  And  he  has  no  hesitation  in 
ascribing  this  improved  tone  to  the  new  standards 
introduced  by  philosophy.  Nor  can  it  be  truly  said 
that  this  advance  was  paid  for  by  a  proportionate 
decline  in  the  manlier  virtues.  Courage  and 
patriotism  continued  to  be  displayed  when  circum- 
stances called  them  forth.  The  defence  of  Athens 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         37 

against  Demetrius,  against  Antigonus,  and,  much 
later,  against  Sulla,  was  not  inferior  to  the  deeds  of 
the  Persian  and  Peloponesian  wars;  and  numerous 
examples  of  a  like  heroism  are  to  be  found  in  the 
later  history  of  other  Greek  states.1 

Still  more  striking  is  the  evidence  offered  by  the 
history  of  the  third  century  A.D.  Alone  among  the 
inhabitants  of  the  Empire  the  Greeks  of  that  period 
spontaneously  took  up  arms  against  the  Gothic 
invaders  and  largely  contributed  to  their  destruc- 
tion. This  successful  resistance  is  significant  in 
more  than  one  way.  It  bears  witness  not  only  to 
a  revival  of  the  old  heroism,  but  also  to  the 
existence  of  an  abundant  and  vigorous  population. 
It  would  seem,  then,  that  there  had  been  a  cessa- 
tion or  decrease  of  those  immoral  practices  which 
in  the  classic  age  of  Greek  civilisation  made  war 
on  family  life.  The  improvement  has  been  ascribed 
to  the  spread  of  Christianity,2  but  there  seem  to  be 
no  grounds  for  such  an  assumption.  It  does  not 
appear  from  independent  evidence  that  the  new 
religion  had  made  the  advances  that  would  have 
been  necessary  to  account  for  so  great  a  change  ; 
nor  were  its  doctrines  favourable  either  to  family 
life  or  to  the  military  spirit.  And,  what  seems 
decisive,  the  most  vigorous  resistance  to  the 
invaders  was  offered  at  Athens,  the  last  city  in  the 
Empire  to  be  converted  to  Christianity.  But  even 
were  the  contention  true,  it  would  detract  little  if 
at  all  from  the  ethical  value  of  Hellenism.  Chris- 
tianity could  only  convert  the  Greeks  into  heroic 


1  Beloch,  Griechische  Geschichte,  II.,  p.  441. 

2  In  Sir  Richard  Jebb's  Modern  Greece, 


38        THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM 

patriots  by  acting  on  the  latent  possibilities  of  the 
Greek  genius  itself.  It  exercised  no  such  magic 
in  Gaul  and  Britain. 

If,  indeed,  the  question  of  obligation  be  once 
raised,  we  shall  have  to  ask  not  so  much  what  the 
Greeks  owe  to  Christianity  as  what  it  owes  to  them. 
The  answer  has  been  already  given  by  modern 
criticism.  Catholicism  in  its  original  and  only  true 
sense  is  but  the  theological  expression  for  universal 
Hellenic  humanity.  The  much-decried  Tubingen 
school  has  made  good  at  least  one  point — that  the 
Church  was  first  converted  from  a  Jewish  sect  into 
a  world-wide  society  by  the  Hellenist  St.  Paul, 
who  in  his  turn  owed  his  conversion  to  the  martyr- 
death  of  the  Hellenist  Stephen.  And,  quite  apart 
from  the  question  of  admission  to  church-member- 
ship, the  root-ideas  of  Pauline  theology  are  only 
intelligible  when  interpreted  in  the  light  of  Stoic 
metaphysics.  In  other  words,  where  Christianity 
differs  most  widely  from  Judaism  it  approaches 
most  nearly  to  Greek  thought.  And  this  applies 
not  only  to  faith,  but  to  morals.  The  antithesis 
between  Hebraism  and  Hellenism  still  remains 
valid,  though  in  a  sense  different  from  that 
assumed  by  Matthew  Arnold.  We  do  not  exactly 
go  for  lessons  in  veracity  or  in  justice,  in  gentle- 
ness or  in  breadth  of  sympathy,  to  the  Jewish 
Scriptures ;  if  we  want  them,  we  shall  find  them 
given  with  incomparable  charm  in  the  literature  of 
the  Ionian  race.  And  so  long  as  moral  training 
shall  be  imparted  through  Christian  agencies  it  is 
vitally  necessary  that  those  agencies  should  be 
kept  in  touch  with  the  sources  whence  the  early 
Church  derived  its  most  human  inspiration.  For 


THE  ETHICAL  VALUE  OF  HELLENISM         39 

present  purposes,  then,  the  ethical  value  of  Hel- 
lenism may  be  defined  as  its  influence  in  fixing 
attention  on  the  purely  moral  side  of  the  popular 
religion,  and  in  preparing  men's  minds  for  the 
eventual  reception  of  a  morality  independent  of 
religious  sanctions. 


THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY  ON 
GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE 

FOR  nearly  a  century  the  theories  of  ancient 
philosophy  have  been  studied  with  an  industry 
and  a  sagacity  that  leave  nothing  to  be  desired, 
and  the  results  have  been  not  incommensurate  with 
the  effort  put  forth.  We  know  early  Greek  thought 
better  than  it  was  known  to  Plato  and  Aristotle  ;  we 
understand  Plato  and  Aristotle  themselves  better 
than  they  were  understood  by  their  immediate 
disciples  ;  we  can  enter  into  the  mind  of  the  Stoics, 
Epicureans,  and  Sceptics  better,  perhaps,  than 
Cicero,  Plutarch,  or  Sextus  could.  More  recently, 
also,  attention  has  been  drawn  to  the  immense 
practical  influence  of  philosophy  on  the  life  of  the 
Roman  Empire  during  the  first  two  centuries  of  its 
existence,  as  revealed  in  literature,  religion,  and 
law.  Not  only  in  the  declamations  of  its  satirists, 
but  also  in  the  decorations  of  its  tombs  ;  not  only  in 
the  lives  of  its  most  virtuous,  but  also  in  the  rescripts 
of  its  most  vicious  rulers  ;  not  only  in  heathen 
polemics,  but  also  in  Christian  apologetics  and 
dogmatics,  the  same  all-pervasive  spirit  may  be 
traced.  But  what  philosophy  did  for  Greece, 
except  to  destroy  religion  and  to  undermine  public 
life,  is  a  question  that  has  not  been  very  deeply 
studied.  In  these  matters  most  of  us  bow  to  the 
authority  of  Zeller,  who  is  deservedly  considered 
the  greatest  master  of  the  subject.  From  him  we 

40 


PHILOSOPHY  AND  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE     41 

have  learned  to  look  on  Greek  speculation  as 
tending  to  detach  itself  more  and  more  from  the 
concrete  realities  of  life,  and  particularly  from 
political  life,  as  tending  more  and  more  to  seek 
refuge  from  the  lawlessness  and  oppression  of  the 
outer  world  in  the  inviolable  sanctuary  of  the  self- 
possessed,  self-enjoying  spirit.  This  isolating 
movement,  begun  during  the  Peloponnesian  war, 
is  supposed  to  have  been  consummated  after  the 
destruction  of  Greek  liberty  by  Macedon,  and  to 
have  realised  itself,  under  various  forms,  in  the 
doctrines  of  the  Porch,  the  Garden,  and  the  later 
Academy.  Except  in  the  negative  sense  there  can, 
it  would  seem,  be  no  question  of  any  social  influence 
exercised  by  such  a  philosophy  as  this. 

But  the  later  ages  of  Greek  history  may  have 
been  less  degraded  and  hopeless  than  we  imagine. 
In  estimating  the  relative  importance  of  men  and 
things,  our  judgment  is  apt  to  be  swayed  by  the 
prepossessions  of  a  classical  education.  To  know 
what  happened  in  the  sixth,  and  still  more  what 
happened  in  the  fifth,  century  B.C.  is  justly  deemed 
essential  to  liberal  culture.  That  period  is  filled 
with  some  of  the  greatest  events  in  human  history, 
and  illustrated  by  some  of  the  most  splendid  monu- 
ments of  human  genius  ;  to  make  them  more 
interesting,  some  of  the  events  may  be  studied  in 
the  narratives  of  eye-witnesses,  and  we  may  inspect 
some  of  the  monuments  for  ourselves.  But  after 
the  close  of  the  great  struggle  between  Athens  and 
Sparta  our  sources  flow  more  scantily  and  their 
purity  becomes  more  suspected.  The  great  stream 
of  lyric  and  dramatic  poetry  entirely  dries  up,  archi- 
tecture and  sculpture  become  weaker  in  themselves 


42  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

and  are  less  definitely  related  to  contemporary 
life.  Prose  composition,  indeed,  attains  the  greatest 
excellence  it  has  ever  reached,  but  the  very  beauty 
of  its  masterpieces  withdraws  the  attention  of 
scholars  from  their  historical  setting  by  lifting 
them  into  a  region  of  ideal  and  undated  perfection. 
-So,  too,  while  the  fourth  century  gives  us  some  of 
the  foremost  characters  of  all  time,  they  seem 
constructed  on  such  a  superhuman  scale  that  we 
cannot  think  of  them  as  being  what  Themistocles, 
Pericles,  and  Alcibiades  had  been,  the  leaders  and 
representatives  of  their  generation.  The  impression 
produced  is  that  of  a  few  colossal  figures  surrounded 
by  mediocrities,  and  projected  against  a  background 
of  petty  and  sordid  intrigue.  So  far  from  redeeming 
their  age,  they  seem  to  make  its  baseness  more 
evident,  and  the  widespread  conviction  of  its 
degeneracy  more  credible.  Indeed,  the  conviction 
is  one  that  originated  with  the  philosophers  and 
statesmen  of  the  time.  Those  who  hold  that 
Greece  succumbed  to  the  Macedonian  arms 
through  her  own  inherent  viciousness  may  quote 
Plato  and  Demosthenes  in  their  support. 

As  we  approach  the  third  century  matters  become 
far  worse.  If,  as  the  late  Professor  Freeman  used 
to  complain,  many  Greek  scholars  seem  to  think 
that  all  history  ends  with  the  sacrifice  of  Tissa- 
phernes,  the  number  of  those  must  be  few  who 
pursue  their  studies  beyond  the  Lamian  war. 
Henceforth  we  are  almost  entirely  without  the 
guidance  and  stimulation  of  contemporary  docu- 
ments, and  few  modern  historians  have  attempted 
the  ungrateful  task  of  piecing  together  a  connected 
narrative  out  of  the  fragmentary  materials  that  have 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  43 

survived.  Grote  breaks  off  his  work  in  disgust  at 
the  beginning  of  the  Hellenistic  period.  Thirlwall 
carries  his  down  to  the  destruction  of  Corinth,  but 
Thirlwall  is  out  of  print,  and  is  supposed  to  be  out 
of  date.  Freeman's  History  of  Federal  Government 
in  Greece,  though  abounding  in  eloquent  passages, 
is,  as  a  whole,  unreadable.  Droysen's  Geschichte 
des  Hellenismus  would,  both  for  style  and  scholar- 
ship, do  honour  to  the  literature  of  any  country  ; 
but  it  has  not,  I  believe,  been  translated  into 
English.  Adolf  Holm  has  recently  gone  over  the 
same  ground  in  the  fourth  volume  of  his  Griechische 
Geschichte,  an  English  translation  of  which  has 
appeared.  He  throws  fresh  light  on  some  important 
points,  but  his  closely  packed  summaries  will  be 
consulted  by  a  very  limited  class  of  readers.  And 
the  same  remark  applies  to  Professor  Julius  Beloch, 
whose  recently  published  volumes  (Griechische 
Geschichte,  III.  and  IV.)  represent  the  last  word 
of  scholarship  on  this  period.1 

This  lamentable  dearth  of  information  is  the  more 
to  be  regretted  because  the  Hellenistic  period  was  a 
time,  not  of  decay  and  death,  but  of  overflowing  and 
fruitful  life.  It  saw  the  seeds  of  a  higher  civilisa- 
tion scattered  over  a  region  extending  from  the 
Ganges  to  the  Atlantic.  Nor  did  the  universal 
diffusion  of  Greek  ideas  mean,  what  the  diffusion 
of  French  and  English  ideas  too  often  has  meant, 
the  effacement  of  national  differences,  the  world- 
wide triumph  of  a  single  not  very  elevated  standard 


1  In  writing  the  above  I  was  not  aware  that  Professor  Mahaffy's 
excellent  work  on  Greek  Life  and  Thought  from  Alexander  to  the 
Roman  Conquest  (and  ed.,  1896)  supplied  the  English  reader  with 
an  account,  at  once  popular  and  erudite,  of  the  period  in  question. 


44  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

of  opinion,  feeling,  taste,  and  manners.  On  the 
contrary,  what  was  vital  and  original  everywhere 
sprang  up  into  rejuvenated  activity  under  that 
electric  stimulus.  At  the  contact  of  Alexander's 
armies  all  India  united  herself  under  a  single  chief ; 
and,  as  a  consequence  of  that  union,  Buddhism  was 
carried  in  triumph  from  the  Himalayas  to  Ceylon. 
Persia  recovered  much  of  her  ancient  energy,  and 
her  religion  first  received  a  complete  literary 
expression  under  her  Philhellenic  Parthian  kings. 
Judcea,  while  clinging  more  passionately  than  ever 
to  the  Thora,  felt  her  imagination  swept  by  a  new 
whirlwind  of  apocalyptic  visions.  A  series  of 
colossal  temples  rose  along  the  banks  of  the  Nile, 
reared  by  the  munificence  of  the  Ptolemies,  as  if  to 
show  that  the  land  they  ruled  was  Egypt  for  the 
Egyptians  even  more  than  Egypt  for  the  Greeks. 
After  the  visit  of  a  single  Spartan  general,  Carthage 
enters  on  the  most  heroic  period  of  her  existence. 
Rome  first  develops  her  whole  potentialities  of 
greatness  in  the  light  of  Hellenic  thought. 

Our  own  civilisation  is  more  in  touch  with  the 
age  of  the  Diadochi  than  with  the  age  of  Pericles. 
The  form  of  our  tragic  drama,  the  form  and 
substance  of  our  comedy,  the  love-interest  of  our 
novel,  are  derived  from  Menander.  Our  poets  owe 
more  to  Theocritus  than  to  Pindar.  Before  the 
present  century  the  most  admired  statues  in  our 
museums  came,  without  exception,  from  the  later 
schools  of  sculpture.  Above  all,  our  science  has 
been  but  the  resumption  and  continuation  of 
methods  then  first  organised.  Euclid  systematised 
the  geometry  of  the  straight  line  and  the  circle ; 
Apollonius  worked  out  the  geometry  of  conies  ; 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  45 

Hipparchus  taught  men  how  to  construct  terres- 
trial and  celestial  maps  ;  Aristarchus  of  Samos 
discovered  the  heliocentric  system  of  astronomy  ; 
Archimedes  created  rational  mechanics. 

While  the  artistic  and  intellectual  powers  of  the 
Greek  genius  were  being  exercised  with  unabated 
vigour,  her  military  and  political  ability  had  not 
become  extinct.  Setting  aside  mythological  char- 
acters, one-third  of  Plutarch's  Greek  heroes  belong 
to  the  period  after  Alexander ;  and  there  were 
others  whose  lives  he  did  not  write.  It  seems 
incredible  that  this  could  have  been  an  age  of 
moral  degeneracy,  or  that  philosophy,  possessing 
such  an  organisation  as  it  had  never  enjoyed 
before,  should  not  have  been  interested  in  the 
systematic  reconstitution  of  society,  especially  since 
the  revolutionary  character  of  the  times  offered 
boundless  opportunities  for  experiment.  My  object 
is  to  show  that  such  an  influence  was  actually  exer- 
cised, proceeding  from  the  schools  of  Athens,  above 
all  from  Stoicism,  as  its  source  and  centre.  But  to 
make  this  intelligible  it  will  be  necessary  to  trace 
briefly  the  relations  that  had  connected  philosophy 
with  life  in  the  previous  course  of  its  evolution. 

With  the  Greeks  the  liveliest  curiosity  about  the 
world  was  ever  accompanied  by  the  desire  to  make 
that  world  a  worthier  habitation  for  man.  Their 
first  thinkers  were  noted  above  all  for  a  purely 
speculative  interest  in  the  constitution  and  origin 
of  nature.  Yet  Thales,  the  acknowledged  founder 
of  philosophy,  was  quite  as  famous  in  his  day  for 
practical  wisdom  as  for  reach  and  daring  of  thought. 
We  are  told  that  he  advised  the  twelve  Ionian  cities 
to  form  a  confederation  for  the  purpose  of  resisting 


46  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  aggressions  of  Croesus — advice  which,  un- 
happily for  themselves,  they  did  not  follow.  If 
Heracleitus  withdrew  in  disgust  from  public  life, 
none  the  less  did  he  recognise  an  identical  law  of 
existence  and  of  conduct,  a  wisdom  that  is  common 
to  all  things.  "  Those  who  speak  with  intelli- 
gence," he  declares,  "must  hold  fast  to  the 
common,  as  a  city  holds  fast  to  its  law,  and  even 
more  strongly  ;  for  all  human  laws  are  fed  by  one 
thing — the  divine."  *  How  he  thought  of  nature  as 
governed  by  an  essentially  moral  law  is  shown  by 
the  saying  that,  if  the  sun  were  to  transgress  his 
measures,  the  Erinyes — the  avenging  handmaidens 
of  justice — would  find  him  out.  In  the  same 
manner  his  predecessor,  Anaximander,  had  repre- 
sented the  transitoriness  of  all  individual  existence 
as  a  vindication  of  eternal  justice.  Nor  did  the 
more  mystical  form  assumed  by  Greek  thought  in 
Italy  and  Sicily  lead  to  quietism  or  to  paralysis  of 
the  moral  will.  Empedocles  headed  the  democratic 
party  in  Agrigentum  ;  Zeno  of  Elea  died  in 
attempting  to  deliver  his  native  city  from  a  tyrant ; 
Melissus  of  Samos,  who  also  belonged  to  the 
Eleatic  school,  defeated  the  Athenians  in  a  sea- 
fight.  Great  uncertainty  prevails  about  the  history 
and  teaching  of  the  original  Pythagorean  school  ; 
but  thus  much  seems  clear,  that  they  combined  an 
attempt  to  explain  the  universe  by  mathematical 
principles  with  an  attempt  to  carry  analogous 
principles  into  education  and  social  discipline. 
Plato's  scheme  of  social  reform  seems  to  have 
been  largely  suggested  by  their  example. 

1  Burnet's  Early  Greek  Philosophy,  p.  139. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  47 

In  all  these  instances  the  leading  inspiration  was 
evidently  ethical.  The  organisation  of  the  Greek 
city-state  gave  men  ideas  of  law  and  order  which 
they  read  into  the  physical  world,  conceiving  it  to 
be  animated  by  a  spirit  like  their  own.  But,  so 
far,  nature  taught  them  no  lessons  that  might  not 
equally  be  learned  in  the  Agora  and  the  Boule. 
An  independent  action  of  philosophy  on  life  sug- 
gests itself  to  us  for  the  first  time  in  the  relations 
between  Anaxagoras  and  Pericles.  For  one  thing, 
the  new  knowledge  tended  to  clear  the  mind  of 
superstition — no  trifling  advantage,  when  we  re- 
member how  Nicias  consummated  the  ruin  of  the 
Sicilian  expedition  by  postponing  his  retreat  a 
whole  month  in  consequence  of  an  eclipse  of  the 
moon.  It  is  quite  certain  that  Pericles,  who  had 
learned  the  cause  of  eclipses  from  Anaxagoras, 
would  not  have  let  his  movements  be  hampered  by 
any  such  scruple.  But,  if  Plutarch  is  to  be  trusted, 
the  mind  of  the  great  statesman  was  strengthened 
in  a  higher  and  more  positive  sense  by  his  inter- 
course with  the  Ionian  sage.  The  august  spectacle 
of  a  universe  where  Reason  reigned  supreme  gave, 
we  are  told,  a  certain  inflexible  majesty  to  the 
character  of  the  democratic  leader,  and  raised  him 
above  all  subservience  to  the  gusts  of  popular 
opinion.  Whether  it  be  historically  true  of 
Pericles  or  not,  the  idea  remains  important  and 
suggestive.  It  has  often  seemed  to  me  that  Posi- 
tivism, with  its  Religion  of  Humanity,  leaves  the 
individual  insufficiently  protected  against  the 
tremendous  pressure  of  the  race.  Adequately  to 
resist  that  pressure  we  need  the  conception  of  an 
existence  beside  which  humanity  itself  shrinks  into 


48  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

insignificance,  but  which,  so  far  from  crushing  or 
absorbing  our  own  personality,  fills  and  expands  it 
to  infinity.  The  enthusiasm  of  humanity  finds  its 
corrective  and  counterpoise  in  cosmic  emotion. 

Before  Pericles  was  dead,  a  revolutionary  idea, 
of  which  neither  he  nor  Anaxagoras  ever  dreamed, 
had  perhaps  been  already  evolved  from  the  Ionian 
philosophy.  This  was  the  idea  of  Nature,  con- 
sidered not  merely  as  the  indefeasible  order  of 
objective  existence,  but  as  the  original  and  supreme 
standard  of  social  equity,  the  ultimate  court  of 
appeal  against  whatever  seemed  arbitrary  or 
oppressive  in  positive  law,  custom,  tradition,  and 
temporary  fashion.  Each  speculative  thinker  had 
sought,  with  undoubting  confidence  that  it  was 
there  and  could  be  found,  for  a  primordial  reality 
at  the  root  of  things,  calling  it  water,  air,  fire, 
the  Infinite,  and  so  forth,  but  meaning  just  what 
persisted  or  periodically  reasserted  itself  in  a  world 
of  change.  This  constant  element  was  not  neces- 
sarily conceived  as  a  single  material  substance ;  it 
might  be  a  variety  of  substances,  or  simple  exten- 
sion, or  a  definite  relation,  or  a  process  ;  but  it  was 
always  what  we  call  a  phenomenon,  never  a  meta- 
physical abstraction  or  noumenon.  In  Kantian 
language,  it  lay  within  the  limits  of  a  possible 
experience.  Opposed  to  it  were  the  baseless, 
unstable,  illusory  opinions  of  the  vulgar.  Such  in 
its  first  intention  was  the  meaning  of  Nature,  the 
philosophical  equivalent  for  the  greater  gods  of  the 
old  religion.  As  scientific  curiosity  extended  itself 
from  the  material  to  the  moral  world,  to  the  human 
race  with  its  division  into  numberless  nations, 
each  speaking  a  different  language  or  dialect,  and 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  49 

characterised  by  infinitely  varying  institutions, 
customs,  and  laws,  yet  in  their  dealings  with  one 
another  appealing  to  a  common  standard  of  reason- 
ableness and  rectitude,  there  arose  the  obvious 
idea,  Have  we  not  here  also  to  ask  for  a  common 
principle  from  which  all  partial  and  local  customs 
are  so  many  ignorant,  it  may  be  mischievous,  aber- 
rations— in  a  word,  for  what  exists  by  nature,  as 
opposed  to  what  exists  by  convention  or  law  ? 

It  is  certain  that  the  question  was  asked  and  the 
distinction  drawn  between  ^uo-teand  vo/zoc,  but  when 
or  by  whom  the  distinction  was  first  drawn  we  do 
not  know.1  It  occurs  for  the  first  time,  unless  I 
am  mistaken,  in  the  Protagoras,  a  somewhat  early 
dialogue  of  Plato's,  where  we  find  it  put  into  the 
mouth  of  the  Sophist  Hippias  ;  and  the  evidence 
of  Xenophon's  Memorabilia  goes  to  prove  that  it 
was  associated  with  his  teaching  by  others  besides 
Plato.  Modern  historians  of  philosophy  speak  as 
if  this  distinction  was  the  common  property  of  all 
the  Sophists,  and  was  used  by  all  with  the  same 
implications.  In  their  opinion,  the  antithesis 
between  Nature  and  Law  was  a  mere  pretext  for 
invalidating  the  authority  of  Law,  for  releasing 
men  from  their  obligation  to  obey  the  ordinances 
of  the  State,  and  therefore  a  powerful  agent  in  the 
work  of  public  demoralisation,  at  least  when  the 
oppression  of  the  weak  by  the  strong  was  defended 
as  a  natural  right.  If  we  are  to  believe  Thucydides 
and  Plato,  such  a  justification  of  successful  violence 
was  actually  attempted  at  the  time  of  the  Pelopon- 
nesian  war  ;  but  to  make  Hippias  or  any  other  of 

1  It  has  been  ascribed  to  Archelaus,  the  disciple  of  Anaxagoras, 
on  the  very  doubtful  authority  of  Laertius  Diogenes. 

E 


5o  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

the  great  Sophists  responsible  for  such  a  perver- 
sion of  their  teaching  would  be  like  making 
Socrates  and  Plato  responsible  for  the  defence  of 
injustice  for  delivering  which  their  successor, 
Carneades,  was  expelled  from  Rome. 

Let  it  be  remembered  that  the  only  Sophists 
about  whom  we  have  any  right  to  speak  are  Pro- 
tagoras, Gorgias,  Prodicus,  and  Hippias.  The 
last  is  the  only  one  who  is  known  to  have  directly 
distinguished  nature  from  law  or  convention.  His 
words,  as  reported  or  imagined  by  Plato,  are  :  "  All 
of  you  who  are  here  present  I  reckon  to  be  kinsmen 
and  friends  and  fellow-citizens,  and  by  nature  and 
not  by  law  ;  for  by  nature  like  is  akin  to  like, 
whereas  law  is  the  tyrant  of  mankind,  and  often 
compels  us  to  do  many  things  which  are  against 
nature.  How  great  would  be  the  disgrace,  then, 

if  we  -who  know  the  nature  of  things should 

quarrel  with  one  another  like  the  meanest  of  man- 
kind."1 There  is  surely  nothing  sceptical,  cor- 
rupting, or  anti-social  about  the  sentiment  here 
expressed.  Further,  we  have  to  note  that  arith- 
metic, geometry,  and  astronomy  are  mentioned 
among  the  subjects  taught  by  Hippias2 — a  fact 
which  seems  to  show  that  he  studied  the  nature  of 
man  in  connection  with  the  nature  of  things.  So 
far  as  we  can  make  out,  a  somewhat  similar  method 
was  followed  by  Prodicus.  With  regard  to  this 
teacher  we  have  the  precious,  though  scanty,  con- 
temporary evidence  of  Aristophanes,  who,  in  the 
Clouds,  compliments  him  on  his  eminent  wisdom 
and  learning,  while  in  the  Birds  he  playfully 

1  Plato,  Protagoras,  p.  337  B. ;  Jowett's  trans. 
'  Ibid,  p.  318. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  51 

announces  a  new  theory  of  evolution  that  is  to 
send  Prodicus  away  howling — a  clear  proof  of  the 
interest  taken  by  the  Ceian  moralist  in  such 
inquiries.  How  far  he  attempted  to  connect  ethics 
with  physics  must,  in  the  absence  of  more  detailed 
information,  remain  uncertain  ;  but  his  own  well- 
known  apologue,  The  Choice  of  Hercules,  as  reported 
to  us  by  Xenophon,  affords  some  suggestive  hints  of 
a  tendency  in  that  direction.  The  word  "nature" 
itself  occurs  three  times  over  in  a  few  lines  ;  and 
throughout  there  is  a  genuinely  naturalistic  assump- 
tion that  pleasure  is  altogether  censurable  when  it 
has  not  been  purchased  by  a  corresponding  outlay 
of  effort  and  fatigue.  Here,  for  the  first  time,  we 
catch  sight  of  a  principle  pregnant  with  momentous 
and  far-reaching  consequences.  For,  by  parity  of 
reasoning,  it  might  be  urged  that  no  man  has  any 
right  to  wealth  that  he  has  not  earned  by  an 
equivalent  amount  of  useful  work,  which  is  the 
root-idea  of  socialism  ;  or,  again,  that  one  class  of 
the  community  should  not  receive  gratuitous 
benefits  at  the  expense  of  another  class,  which  is  the 
root-idea  of  Spencerian  individualism.  Plato,  who, 
for  reasons  unknown,  particularly  hated  Prodicus, 
only  mentions  him  to  ridicule  the  pedantic 
precision  with  which  he  insisted  on  the  accurate 
use  of  language.1  Altogether,  we  have  here  a  master 
of  encyclopaedic  range  —  physicist,  philologist, 
and  moralist — with  Hippias,  the  earliest  precursor 
of  Stoicism  and  of  modern  university  training. 


1  Curiously  enough,  the  late  Mr.  R.  H.  Hutton  dwells  on  the 
extreme  accuracy  and  precision  of  the  late  Professor  Maiden  as 
a  trait  of  distinction  between  that  scholar  and  the  ancient  Sophists 
(in  the  Memoir  prefixed  to  Bagehot's  Literary  Studies,  p.  xv.)« 


S2  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

We  gather  from  the  report  of  Xenophon  that 
the  moral  censure  of  Prodicus  was  directed  against 
the  vices  of  the  rich  and  luxurious,  special  emphasis 
being  laid  on  their  artificial,  unnatural  character. 
The  polemic  thus  begun  would  easily  extend  into 
an  attack  on  all  civilisation  considered  as  a  depar- 
ture from  the  state  of  nature,  from  the  innocence 
and  simplicity  of  savage  man  ;  and  it  would  be 
accompanied  by  a  tendency  to  hold  up  as  examples 
for  imitation  the  nations  who  had  remained  at  or 
near  the  primitive  condition  of  mankind.  We 
generally  associate  this  tendency  with  the  philo- 
sophy of  the  eighteenth  century ;  but  it  is  now 
known  that  Rousseau  and  Diderot  were  merely 
taking  up  the  tradition  of  Greek  thought.  Although 
it  may  be  traced  back  to  Hesiod,  the  theory  of  a 
golden  age  still  partially  surviving  among  savages 
did  not  reach  its  full  expansion  before  the  middle 
of  the  fourth  century  B.C.;  but  there  is  evidence 
that  it  was  already  eagerly  canvassed  in  the  circles 
which  gathered  round  the  great  Sophists,  and 
could  show  that  most  satisfactory  proof  of  vitality 
which  is  afforded  by  the  rise  of  an  antagonistic 
theory.  To  the  glorification  of  nature  was  opposed 
the  glorification  of  progressive  civilisation  ;  to  the 
study  of  astronomy  and  physics  was  opposed  the 
study  of  poetry,  eloquence,  modern  history,  and 
political  institutions  ;  to  the  ethical  standards  and 
sanctions  derived  from  the  healthy  balance  of  the 
organic  functions  were  opposed  other  standards 
and  sanctions  derived  from  the  exigencies  of  the 
social  state  and  the  steady  pressure  of  public 
opinion.  At  the  head  of  this  humanistic  school 
apparently  stood  Protagoras ;  and  nothing  can 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  53 

better  illustrate  the  sharp  antagonism  of  the  two 
ethical  methods  than  a  remark  put  into  his  mouth 
by  Plato,  so  unlike  anything  else  in  the  Dialogues 
that  we  must  accept  it  as  characteristic,  if  not  as 
the  reproduction  of  an  actual  utterance.  "  I  would 
have  you  consider  that  he  who  appears  to  you  to 
be  the  worst  of  those  who  have  been  brought  up  in 
laws  and  humanities  would  appear  to  be  a  just  man 
and  a  master  of  justice  if  he  were  to  be  compared 
with  men  who  had  no  education,  or  courts  of  justice* 
or  laws,  or  any  restraints  upon  them  which  com- 
pelled them  to  practise  virtue — with  the  savages, 
for  example,  whom  the  poet  Pherecrates  exhibited 
on  the  stage  at  the  last  year's  Lenaean  festival.  If 
you  were  living  among  men  such  as  the  man-haters 
in  his  Chorus,  you  would  be  only  too  glad  to  meet 
with  Eurybates  and  Phrynondas,  and  you  would 
sorrowfully  long  to  revisit  the  rascality  of  this  part 
of  the  world."1  A  somewhat  similar  vein  of 
hostility  to  barbarism  may,  I  think,  be  traced  in 
the  introduction  to  the  history  of  Thucydides.  It 
is  significant,  too,  that,  with  many  a  tale  of  Greek 
cruelty  to  relate,  his  strongest  expressions  of  horror 
are  reserved  for  the  savagery  of  the  Thracians,  and 
particularly  for  their  massacre  of  all  the  children 
in  a  large  boys'  school  at  Mycalessus. 

Greek  thinkers  habitually  sought  to  clothe  their 
principles  in  the  most  paradoxical  form  they  could 
devise.  Protagoras  and  Gorgias  were  not  content 
to  advocate  humanistic  studies  at  the  expense  of 
physical  science ;  they  tried  to  destroy  the  idea  of 

1  Plato,  Protagoras,  327  c  (Jowett's  Trans.).  Robert  Lowe 
once  quoted  this  passage  with  the  keenest  enjoyment. 


54  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

Nature,  root  and  branch.  Protagoras  taught  that 
"  Man  is  the  measure  of  all  things  ";  in  other  words, 
moral  obligations  and  distinctions  must  be  founded 
on  the  needs  of  a  progressive  society,  not  on  the 
abstraction  to  which  the  physiocratic  philosophers 
appeal.  Gorgias  set  to  work  in  a  still  more  radical 
fashion.  He  wrote  a  treatise  with  the  significant 
title,  On  Nature  or  frothing,  in  which  he  main- 
tained, first  that  nothing  exists  ;  secondly,  that  if 
anything  existed  it  could  not  be  known  ;  and 
thirdly,  that  if  anything  existed  and  could  be 
known,  the  individual  possessing  that  knowledge 
could  not  communicate  it  to  others.  This,  as  the 
worthy  Tiedemann  observes,  was  "  going  much 
farther  than  common  sense  permits ";  but  the 
Greeks,  as  I  have  said,  loved  paradoxical  state- 
ments ;  and  Gorgias  probably  meant  no  more  than 
Joseph  de  Maistre  when  he  asked  the  apostles  of 
"  la  Nature,"  "  Qui  est  done  cette  femme?"  or  than 
Alfred  de  Musset,  when  he  put  the  equally  difficult 
question,  "Le  cceur  humain  de  qui,  le  coeur  humain 
de  quoi?" 

Like  the  opposing  cosmologies  of  Heracleitus 
and  Parmenides  at  an  earlier  period  of  Greek 
thought,  the  rival  theories  of  the  physiocrats  and 
the  humanists  each  contained  an  element  of  truth, 
and  the  future  progress  of  ethics  depended  on  the 
recognition  and  combination  of  both.  Since  Pro- 
tagoras a  number  of  thinkers,  among  whom  Pro- 
fessor Huxley  may  be  mentioned  as  the  last,  but 
not  the  least,  have  shown  that  nature,  apart  from 
man,  is  anything  but  a  safe  moral  guide,  and  that 
what  she  seems  to  inculcate  is,  in  fact,  the  supre- 
macy of  brute  force.  On  the  other  hand,  the  great 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  55 

diversity  of  moral  codes  observed  at  different  times 
and  in  different  places  points  to  the  necessity  of 
some  objective  principle  by  which  they  must  be 
tested,  unless  we  are  to  resign  ourselves  to  complete 
scepticism  on  the  subject  of  right  and  wrong. 
Here  physical  science  comes  to  the  rescue  by 
teaching  us  to  look  at  things  rather  than  words, 
and  to  follow  the  lines  of  demonstrative  evidence 
rather  than  the  shifting  currents  of  popular  opinion. 
But  only  the  study  of  human  interests  as  such  can 
tell  us  what  things  we  should  look  at,  and  what  kind 
of  proof  the  nature  of  the  case  demands.  Socrates, 
Plato,  and  Aristotle,  by  creating  the  dialectic 
method  and  applying  it  to  ethics,  made  a  good 
start  in  this  direction — so  good,  indeed,  as  com- 
pletely to  overshadow  the  predecessors  whose  ideas 
they  appropriated  and  combined.  Worse  than 
this,  some  loose  declamations  of  Plato  and  some 
special  attacks  on  the  rhetoricians  and  oligarchs  of 
his  own  time  have  been  construed  into  a  distinct 
charge  of  immoral  teaching  brought  against  the 
great  Sophists  of  the  fifth  century.  Undoubtedly 
the  naturalistic  and  humanistic  principles  severally 
admit  of  being  pushed  to  anti-social  consequences. 
The  claim  of  the  strong  man — or,  as  he  would  call 
himself,  the  born  ruler  of  mankind — to  lord  it  over 
his  fellows,  and  to  gratify  all  his  appetites  at  their 
expense,  may  be  upheld  as  a  natural  right.  A 
misinformed  or  deluded  public  opinion  may  be 
erected  into  the  supreme  standard  of  truth  and 
justice,  while  the  art  of  misinforming  and  deluding 
it  may  be  inculcated  as  the  first  qualification  of  a 
statesman.  But  the  Socratic  dialectic,  with  its 
principle  that  the  germs  of  truth  exist  in  every 


56  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mind  and  in  every  belief,  is  also  capable  of  disease 
and  corruption.  We  owe  to  it — beginning  with 
Plato,  or,  perhaps,  even  with  Socrates  himself — the 
organised  hypocrisy  that  defends  the  public  pro- 
fession and  propagation  of  superstitious  beliefs  as 
the  only  form  under  which  philosophic  truth  can 
safely  circulate  among  the  ignorant  masses. 

It  would  be  a  great  mistake  to  suppose  that  the 
teaching  of  the  Sophistic  schools^  based  as  it  was 
on  principles  of  everlasting  validity,  possessed 
merely  negative  or  transitional  significance. 
There  is  reason  to  suppose,  from  incidental 
references  in  Plato  and  Aristotle,  that  it  continued 
to  win  adherents  through  the  two  generations  that 
followed  the  death  of  Socrates.  Above  all,  the 
note  of  naturalism  became  increasingly  dominant, 
and  powerfully  affected  the  Socratic  schools  them- 
selves. Plato's  writings  are  a  good  example  of 
the  tendency.  His  earliest  dialogues  are  almost 
entirely  humanistic,  with  only  slight  or  deprecia- 
tory references  to  nature ;  but  in  the  Republic 
physiocratic  considerations  are  already  prominent, 
and  in  the  Laws,  a  very  late  work,  they  meet  us  at 
every  step,  in  connection,  be  it  observed,  with  a 
very  high  and  pure  morality.  Aristotle  also  refers 
to  nature  as  a  moral  standard,  the  validity  of  which 
he  recognises,  although  he  cannot  accept  all  the 
consequences  drawn  from  it  by  some  other  philo- 
sophers. 

Authorities  are  still  divided  on  the  question 
whether  the  influence  which  we  have  seen  to  be 
so  potent  in  speculation  was,  or  was  not,  mis- 
chievous in  practice.  Most  German  historians 
continue  to  believe  that  a  decline  in  Greek  morality 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  57 

began  with  the  outbreak  of  the  Peloponnesian  war, 
and  continued  without  intermission  down  to   the 
advent  of  Christianity;  and  they  make  Sophisticism 
responsible  for  at  least  the  inception  of  the  process. 
Traditions  are  very  strong  in  German  universities, 
and  it  has  become  a   tradition   in   those   seats   of 
learning  that  to  take  fees  for  lecturing  and  to  throw 
doubt  on  the  popular  mythology  is  very  reprehen- 
sible conduct — when  practised  by  an  ancient  Greek. 
It  sometimes  actually  led  people  to  believe  in  the 
right  of  the  stronger  !     Fortunately  there  is  one 
German,  Professor  Julius  Beloch,  who,  having  the 
advantage  of  living  in  Italy,  has  dared  to  think  for 
himself.     This  brilliant  and  original  historian  not 
only  vindicates  the  Sophists,  as  Grote  and  others 
had  done  before  him,  but  makes  short  work  of  the 
whole  charge  of   demoralisation    brought  against 
the  Greeks.     There  is  no  surer  test  of  a  nation's 
moral  standing  than  its  conduct  in  time  of  war.     If 
there  is  a  virtue  admitting  of  ocular  and  statistical 
demonstration,    a    virtue     that     can     neither     be 
concealed  nor  assumed,   that  virtue  is  humanity. 
Now   Professor   Beloch   opportunely   reminds    us 
that  the  Greeks  of  the  fourth  century  were  much 
more  humane  than  the  contemporaries  of  Pericles.1 
Such   horrors   as   the   slaughter    of    the    Theban 
prisoners   by   the   Plataeans   and   of  the   Platsean 
prisoners    by    the    Thebans,    of    the    Corcyrasan 
aristocrats   by   the   opposite    faction    and    of    the 
Melians  by  the  Athenians,  for  no  other  crime  than 
having  refused  to  give  up  their  independence,  are 
justly  branded  with  execration  ;  but  it  is  unjustly 

1  Griechische  Geschichte,  I.,  p.  595. 


58  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

forgotten  that  they  find  no  counterpart  in  the  next 
generation.  We  do  not  again  hear  of  prisoners  of 
war  being  shut  up  to  die  by  thousands  of  slow 
torture  in  the  quarries  of  Syracuse,  nor  yet  of  their 
being  put  to  death  by  the  more  summary  method 
of  Lysander  at  Aigos  Potamoi.  The  historian 
knows  of  only  two  cases  in  the  wars  of  the  fourth 
century  where  the  storm  of  a  besieged  town  was 
followed  by  the  massacre  of  its  male  adult  citizens 
— the  capture  of  Orchomenus  by  the  Thebans  and 
the  capture  of  Sestus  by  Chares.1  The  outburst  of 
popular  passion  to  which  Phocion  and  his  friends 
fell  victims,  though  lamentable  enough,  is  not  to 
be  compared  with  that  which  wreaked  itself  on  the 
victorious  generals  of  Arginusae.  Whether  the 
persecution  and  exile  of  so  many  generals  and 
statesmen,  from  Miltiades  to  Alcibiades,  was  due 
more  to  ingratitude  mixed  with  envy  on  the  part  of 
the  people,  or  to  treason  on  the  part  of  its  leaders, 
may  be  doubted  ;  in  any  case  there  was  guilt  of  the 
blackest  kind  somewhere,  but  guilt  which  we  meet 
with  only  under  a  greatly  attenuated  form  in  the 
fourth  century. 

If  we  ask  what  was  the  cause  of  this  wonderful 
change,  the  only  possible  answer  is,  the  great 
revolution  that  philosophy  had  wrought  in  the 
minds  of  men.  The  mere  habit  of  looking  at 
things  from  a  universal  point  of  view  has  happily 
a  certain  power  to  enlarge  the  sympathies.  Thus 
the  rulers  of  Babylon,  surrounded  as  they  were  by 
a  learned  priesthood,  seem  to  have  been  much 
more  merciful  than  the  rulers  of  Assyria.  Further- 

1  Grtechtsche  Geschichte,  II.,  p.  441. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  59 

more,  the  three  great  ethical  schools  characterised 
above  must,  through  their  various  principles,  have 
exercised  a  still  more  direct  influence  on  the  social 
feelings.  The  physicists,  by  drawing  attention  to 
the  universal  elements  of  human  nature,  helped  to 
break  down  the  barriers  of  race,  language,  and 
nationality  that  so  powerfully  foster  feelings  of 
mutual  hostility  among  men.  The  humanists  saw 
with  perfect  clearness  that  a  state  of  nature  meant 
lawless  violence  ;  but  their  object  was  by  means 
of  systematic  instruction  still  further  to  develop 
the  tendencies  that  make  for  peace,  order,  mutual 
helpfulness,  and  elevated  enjoyment.  Such  of 
them  as  taught  rhetoric  or  the  art  of  persuasion 
by  words  must  have  looked  with  peculiar  horror 
on  the  regime  of  brute  force  ;  indeed,  it  is  impossible 
to  study  the  writings  of  Isocrates,  the  chief  teacher 
of  rhetoric  in  the  fourth  century,  without  recognising 
through  all  the  man's  vanity,  inconsistency,  and 
subservience  to  success  a  sense  of  justice  and  mercy 
utterly  alien  to  the  tone  of  the  Melian  Dialogue. 
Especially  significant  is  the  declaration  of  Isocrates 
that  Hellenism  is  a  privilege  not  of  race  but  of 
culture,  and  therefore  open  to  all  mankind.1 
Finally  the  Socratic  school,  with  its  willingness  to 
learn  from  every  one,  its  appeals  to  the  reason  that 
is  actual  or  latent  in  every  man  and  in  every  woman, 
its  exaltation  of  the  soul  above  the  body,  and  of  the 
higher  over  the  lower  psychic  activities,  must  have 
contributed  largely  to  the  good  work  of  humanisa- 
tion  that  was  going  on. 

In  attempting  to  trace  the  general   influence  of 

See  above,  p.  35. 


60  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

philosophy  on  the  spirit  of  the  age  we  have  been 
dealing  with  probabilities,  of  a  high  order  indeed, 
but  not  affording  the  satisfaction  of  absolute 
certainty ;  and  in  the  dearth  of  documentary 
evidence  no  more  can  be  expected.  But,  on 
passing  to  the  study  of  philosophy  as  an  influence 
on  the  character  of  individual  statesmen,  we  are  no 
longer  limited  to  conjecture  ;  we  have  definite  facts 
to  show.  Here  our  whole  case  might  be  staked  on 
the  name  of  Epaminondas,  whom  Professor  Mahaffy 
calls  "  far  the  noblest  of  all  the  great  men  whom 
Greece  ever  produced,  without  a  single  flaw  or 
failing."1  This  illustrious  patriot  was  a  pupil  of 
Lysis,  the  Pythagorean,  and  became  himself,  in 
turn,  a  teacher  of  the  whole  state,  devoting  himself 
for  years  to  the  moral  and  intellectual  elevation  of 
his  fellow-citizens.  But  what  speaks  most  for  the 
moral  earnestness  of  Epaminondas  is  his  refusal, 
after  all  those  years  of  preparation  for  the  deliver- 
ance of  Thebes,  to  take  part  in  the  secret 
assassination  of  the  oligarchs  who  were  governing 
her  as  the  servile  agents  of  Lacedaemonian  oppres- 
sion. Philosophy  had  taught  him  a  delicacy  of 
conscience  not  only  far  in  advance  of  the  best 
public  opinion  of  his  own  time,  but  also  in  advance 
of  the  sentiments  entertained  till  a  comparatively 
recent  period  by  some  Christian  moralists.  Another 
but  inferior  example  of  philosophy  in  action  is 
furnished  by  Dion,  the  friend  of  Plato,  and  the 
first  liberator  of  Syracuse.  I  am  well  aware  of  the 
prejudice  under  which  the  memory  of  this  unfortu- 

1  Rambles  and  Studies  in  Greece,  p.  227  (2nd  ed.).  I  do  not 
agree  with  the  last  words  quoted.  See  Plutarch,  Eroticus,  xvii. 
15  ;  Athenaeus,  Deipnosophistce,  xiii.,  Ixxxiii. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  61 

nate  patriot  must  suffer  in  the  minds  of  all  English- 
speaking  scholars.     There  is  nothing  in  Grote's 
History  of  Greece  to  equal  for  interest  and  pathos 
his   narrative   of  the   two   Sicilian   expeditions  of 
Dion  and  Timoleon  ;  and  the  total  effect  of  that 
narrative  unquestionably  is  to  make  the  ill-starred 
philosophic  aristocrat  play  the  part  of  a  foil  to  the 
higher  and  purer  glory  of  the  successful  Corinthian 
democrat.     It  is,  however,  only  fair  to  remember 
that  Timoleon  had  the  inestimable  advantage  of 
coming  after  Dion,  and  of  profiting  by  his  mistakes. 
We  have  also  to  note  that  the  one  blot  on  the  fame 
of  the  great  liberator,  his  not  interfering  to  save 
the  innocent  wives  and  daughters  of  Hicetas  from 
the  cruel  vengeance  of  the  Syracusans,   was  the 
very  last  sin  of  which  his  predecessor  would  have 
been  guilty.     When  pressed  to  put  a  treacherous 
enemy  to  death,  Dion  answered  that  his  prolonged 
studies  in  the  Academy  had  for  their  object  the 
conquest  of  anger,  envy,  and  all  contentiousness  ; 
that  it  was  not  enough   merely  to  reciprocate  the 
goodness  of  others,  it  was  necessary  also  to  forgive 
injuries  and  to  be  merciful  to  the  transgressor  ;  that 
for  the  person  who   is   first  attacked   to   revenge 
himself,  though  legally  justifiable,  is  by  nature  no 
less  censurable  than  the  attack,  as  springing  from 
the  same  root  of  ungoverned  passion  ;  that  human 
wickedness,  however  savage,  must  at  last  yield  to 
the  effect  of  unwearied  beneficence.1     For  us  the 
most  interesting  point  to  note  is  that,  as  Curtius 


1  Plutarch,  Dion,  p.  979  A.  The  distinction  between  nature  and 
law  seems  to  point  to  a  much  older  authority  than  Plutarch, 
probably  a  contemporary  of  Dion's.  I  have  slightly  paraphrased 
this  sentence  in  order  to  make  it  more  intelligible. 


62  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

says,  the  expedition  of  Dion  was  an  enterprise 
undertaken  by  the  whole  Academy  in  its  collective 
capacity — a  fact  quite  irreconcilable  with  the 
subsequent  statement  of  the  same  historian,  that 
philosophers  were  at  this  time  more  and  more 
withdrawing  themselves  from  the  repulsive  contact 
of  public  affairs.  Very  significant  also  of  the 
increased  power  now  exercised  by  ideas  is  the 
desire  shown  by  the  younger  Dionysius,  and  in 
a  less  degree  even  by  his  detestable  father,  to  stand 
well  in  the  opinion  of  Plato.  So  also  is  the  selection 
of  Aristotle  as  the  tutor  of  young  Alexander. 

Thus  far  we  have  seen  philosophy  occupied  in 
the  work  of  systematising  the  moral  law,  reducing 
it  to  simple  principles,  connecting  it  with  the  eternal 
constitution  of  the  universe,  and  developing  it  in  the 
direction  of  a  more  comprehensive  humanity.  We 
have  now  to  study  it  under  the  more  stirring  aspect 
of  a  reforming  and  revolutionary  force,  as  an 
endeavour  taken  up  by  serious  statesmen  to 
reconstitute  society  on  a  basis  of  economic  justice. 
In  this  connection  the  briefest  reference  to  Plato 
must  suffice,  as  that  master's  searching  criticism 
of  contemporary  life  and  his  twofold  attempt  to 
reconstruct  it  from  the  bottom  up  are,  or  ought  to 
be,  familiar  to  every  student,  if  only  for  the  un- 
rivalled literary  splendour  of  the  writings  in  which 
they  are  embodied.  Moreover,  the  subtlety  and 
complexity  of  his  genius  raise  Plato  so  high  above 
the  age  that  he  cannot  be  taken  as  representing  its 
general  philosophical  tendencies,  although  his 
works  may  be  used  as  affording  valuable  evidence 
of  the  direction  in  which  they  pointed.  The  great 
word  of  that  age,  as  of  our  own  eighteenth  century, 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  63 

was  "  Back  to  Nature  ! "  and  then  also,  as  with 
Rousseau,  the  ordinances  of  Nature  were  interpreted 
in  a  levelling,  democratic,  socialistic  sense,  quite 
remote  from  the  sharp  class-distinctions  of  Plato. 
We  have  seen  how  Hippias,  whom  the  young 
Plato  made  a  butt  for  his  ridicule,  implicitly 
proclaimed  the  natural  brotherhood  of  mankind. 
We  learn  from  a  fragment  of  Aristotle  that  a  later 
Sophist  named  Lycophron  declared  nobility  of  birth 
to  be  a  baseless  privilege,1  while  another  Sophist, 
Alcidamas,  vindicated  freedom  as  a  natural  right2 
— a  principle  which,  as  we  know  from  Aristotle's 
Politics,  was  unhesitatingly  pushed  on  to  the 
absolute  condemnation  of  slavery. 

Those  who,  like  these  generous  philosophers, 
have  persuaded  themselves  that  liberty,  equality, 
and  fraternity  are  natural  to  man,  easily  come  to 
believe  that  this  happy  state  was  realised  in  the 
primitive  condition  of  the  race.  We  get  a  glimpse 
of  their  belief  on  this  subject  from  the  Laws  of 
Plato,  who,  as  I  have  said,  came  very  much  under 
their  influence  in  his  old  age.  He  tells  us  that  the 
men  who  lived  immediately  after  the  Deluge  were 
"simpler,  more  manly,  more  temperate,  and  more 
just "  than  his  own  contemporaries  (Laws,  679  E)  ; 
and  he  attributes  their  superior  virtue  to  their 
undeveloped  industrial  condition,  to  the  absence 
alike  of  poverty  and  of  wealth.  The  next  step  was 
to  look  round  for  a  people  among  whom  these 
delightful  traits  of  primitive  humanity  had  been 
preserved.  It  was  found  in  the  Scythians. 
Ephorus,  a  pupil  of  Isocrates,  and  the  greatest 

1  Quoted  by  Stobaeus,  Florilegium ,  p.  494,  24. 
2  Oratores  Attici  (Didot),  II.,  p.  316. 


64  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

historian  of  later  Greece,  seems  to  have  constructed 
a  fancy  picture  of  that  barbarous  race,  which  was 
received  with  unquestioning  faith  through  the 
whole  of  antiquity,  and  in  a  revived  form  has  even 
affected  modern  thought.  Justice  was  represented 
as  the  most  essential  characteristic  of  these  nomads ; 
envy,  hatred,  and  fear  were  unknown  among  them ; 
such  was  their  horror  of  taking  even  animal  life 
that  they  subsisted  entirely  on  milk ;  and  they 
lived  in  a  state  of  perfect  communism,  holding 
property,  wives,  and  children  in  common,  so  as  to 
constitute  a  single  united  family.1 

Various  causes  combined  to  familiarise  Greek 
social  philosophy  with  the  idea  of  communism. 
To  a  certain  extent  it  had  no  doubt  prevailed  among 
the  Hellenic  tribes  before  they  left  the  nomadic 
state,  and  the  tradition  was  never  entirely  lost. 
When  they  settled  in  a  new  country  the  land  would 
be  most  naturally  distributed  in  equal  portions 
among  the  conquerors,  and  any  fresh  territory  that 
was  subsequently  annexed  would  be  similarly  dis- 
posed of.  The  rise  of  manufactures  and  commerce, 
with  the  accompanying  introduction  of  a  metallic 
currency,  brought  about  a  great  inequality  of 
wealth,  leading  to  violent  political  disorders,  which, 
in  the  case  of  Solon's  legislation,  necessitated  a 
forcible  remission  of  debts  by  the  State — a  prece- 
dent never  afterwards  forgotten.  Democracy, 
which  at  first  meant  deliverance  of  the  poor  from 
the  oppression  of  the  rich,  afterwards  came  to 
mean  a  more  or  less  disguised  distribution  of  the 
property  of  the  rich  among  the  poor,  and  of  the 

1  Pohlmann , Geschichte des antiken  Kommunisntns,  I. ,  pp.  1 1 7  sqq. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  65 

tribute  paid  by  the  subject  cities  among  all  classes, 
without  any  disguise  whatever.  Meanwhile  a  first 
rough  analysis  of  social  phenomena  had  led  philo- 
sophers to  the  conclusion  that  covetousness  was  the 
root  of  all  evil,  that  murder,  robbery,  and  other 
crimes  arose  from  the  unequal  distribution  of 
property,  or  rather  from  its  mere  existence,  for,  as 
Menander  said — 

With  naught  to  take  no  man  would  e'er  be  wicked. 

From  the  prevalent  view  of  marriage  it  followed 
that  wives,  like  any  other  kind  of  property,  were  to 
be  held  in  common.  Strange  as  it  may  seem,  the 
idea  of  such  a  revolution,  so  far  from  being 
regarded  as  a  degradation,  was  welcomed  with  joy 
by  the  women.  When,  in  392,  Aristophanes  took 
communism  as  the  subject  of  one  of  his  wittiest 
comedies,  the  Ecclesiazusce,  he  represented  it  as 
the  work  of  the  Athenian  women,  who  go  to  the 
poll  disguised  as  men,  and  change  the  institutions 
of  the  State  by  a  snatch  vote ;  and  Epictetus, 
writing  five  centuries  later,  attributed  the  enthu- 
siasm of  the  Roman  ladies  for  Plato's  Republic 
entirely  to  its  proposal  that  there  should  be  a 
community  of  wives.1 

Aristophanes  is  our  earliest  authority  for  the 
existence  of  communism  as  a  political  ideal.  It 
has,  indeed,  been  maintained  that  his  exhibition  of 
it  on  the  stage  was  intended  as  a  satire  on  the 
proposals  of  Plato.  But  it  seems  most  unlikely 
that  even  the  first  half  of  the  Republic  had  been 
completed  when  the  philosopher  was  only  thirty- 
four  ;  unlikely  also  that  Plato  should  not  have  been 

*  Didot,  Fragmenta,  p.  53. 


66  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

mentioned  by  name  in  the  play,  if  not  actually 
brought  on  the  scene.  Moreover,  in  the  Republic 
communism  is  carefully  restricted  to  the  governing 
class  ;  not  till  long  afterwards,  in  the  Laws,  is  it 
proclaimed  as  the  ideally  best  arrangement  for  all 
mankind.  I  have  already  called  attention  to  the 
remarkable  fact  that  the  Laws  is  saturated  with  a 
naturalism  quite  foreign  to  the  earlier  dialogues. 
What  is  the  inference  ?  Plainly,  that  communism 
(in  both  kinds)  was  a  standing  doctrine  of  the 
naturalistic  school,  and  that  it  probably  originated 
with  the  immediate  successors  of  Hippias  and 
Prodicus.  Most  unfortunately,  we  only  know  that 
such  persons  existed  through  incidental  references 
in  Plato  and  Aristotle ;  the  Cynics,  who  bore  the 
same  relation  to  the  philosophic  naturalists  that  the 
Franciscans  bore  to  the  Dominicans,  have  com- 
pletely superseded  them  in  the  notices  of  later 
compilers.  But,  even  in  the  scanty  utterances  of 
Antisthenes  and  Diogenes,  clear  traces  of  a  com- 
munistic theory  have  been  preserved ;  and  it 
emerges  full  blown  in  what  was  practically  by  far 
the  most  important  of  the  ancient  philosophies, 
Stoicism. 

We  are  apt  to  think  of  the  later  Athens  as 
divided  among  four  or  more  equally  serious  or 
equally  frivolous  schools  of  philosophy.  But  in 
reality  the  Lyceum  was  devoted  almost  exclusively 
to  physical  science  ;  the  Epicureans  were  a  small, 
uninfluential  group  of  recluses  ;  the  Academicians, 
after  abandoning  the  mathematical  mysticism  of 
Speusippus,  contented  themselves  with  a  negative 
criticism  chiefly  directed  against  the  doctrines  of 
the  Porch.  This  last  alone  gave  a  training  at  once 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  67 

positive,  encyclopaedic,  and  fruitful,  mingling  with 
every  honourable  pursuit,  delivering  its  message 
to  all  men,  and  holding  up,  by  the  example  of  its 
teachers,  no  less  than  by  the  rigour  of  its  tenets, 
such  a  standard  of  righteousness  and  purity  as 
none  but  the  prophets  of  Israel  had  raised  before. 
So  strong,  indeed,  are  the  traces  of  a  Semitic 
origin  among  the  chief  Stoics,  beginning  with  its 
founder,  Zeno,  that  their  moral  earnestness  has 
been  attributed  to  a  peculiar  quality  resident  in  the 
genius  of  the  race  to  which  the  prophets  also 
belonged.  But  this  seems  a  very  fanciful  explana- 
tion of  Stoicism.  Taking  them  altogether,  the 
Semites  have  never  been  remarkable  for  a  high 
moral  tone,  least  of  all  the  Phoenician  branch  to 
which  Zeno  belonged.  If  the  foreign  extraction  of 
the  early  Stoics  betrayed  itself  at  all,  it  was  in  a 
certain  absolute,  unconditional,  uncompromising 
tone  of  thought  common  to  all  Asiatics,  and  due 
less  to  any  racial  idiosyncrasy  than  to  the  habits 
inbred  by  immemorial  despotism.  How  little  race 
has  to  do  with  it  is  evident  from  the  reappearance 
of  a  precisely  similar  tone  among  the  Russian 
novelists  of  the  present  day,  who  have  imbibed  it 
from  the  same  environment.  As  a  consequence  of 
this  rigorous  absolutism,  the  Stoics  abolished  the 
distinction  between  mind  and  matter ;  they  placed 
the  world  under  the  unconditional  control  of  reason  ; 
they  asserted  the  unbroken  regularity  of  natural 
law  ;  they  substituted  determinism  for  free  will  ; 
they  insisted,  against  Aristotle,  that  virtue  con- 
stituted not  the  leading  element,  but  the  whole  of 
happiness ;  and  they  claimed  for  perception  an 
unerring  certainty.  But  in  every  point  of  their 


68  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

system  they  did  but  develop  ideas  long  familiar 
to  Greek  philosophy ;  and  in  their  love  of  para- 
doxical statement,  at  least,  they  were  entirely 
Greek.  As  a  means  of  drawing  attention,  their 
paradoxes  were  perfectly  successful,  so  much  so, 
indeed,  that  down  to  the  present  day  public  opinion 
assumes  almost  without  question  that  every  philo- 
sopher is  indifferent  to  pain  and  inaccessible  to 
emotion  ;  that  he  knows  everything  and  can  do 
everything,  provided  it  be  not  of  too  frivolous  a 
character  ;  and  that  he  is,  or  would  like  to  pass  for 
being,  impeccable  and  infallible — in  other  words, 
that  he  answers  to  the  ancient  caricature  of  a  Stoic. 
In  reality,  the  Stoics  never  professed  or  required 
insensibility  to  pleasure  and  pain  ;  they  merely 
asserted,  as  we  also  do,  the  supreme  and  incom- 
mensurable value  of  moral  goodness ;  and  in 
ascribing  all  manner  of  merits  and  accomplish- 
ments to  their  ideal  sage  they  merely  demanded, 
as  some  of  us  also  do,  the  systematic  application 
of  scientific  principles  to  the  whole  field  of  human 
activity.  But  that  the  ideal  sage  had  ever  been 
realised  on  earth  they  did  not  believe  ;  and  if  their 
principles  suffered  any  sense  of  humour  to  survive 
they  must  have  smiled  at  the  naivete  of  a  Mace- 
donian officer  who,  hearing  that  the  wise  man  was 
an  excellent  general,  joined  the  school  in  hopes  of 
becoming  one  himself.1 

At  the  moment  when  Zeno  first  proclaimed  his 
message  under  the  painted  portico  of  Athens  it 
seemed  as  if  all  free  and  noble  public  life  had  come 
to  an  end  in  Greece.  That  fourth  empire,  so  well 

1  Plutarch,  Arattis,  xxiii.,  p.  1037  f. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  69 

described  by  the  Book  of  Daniel  as  "a  beast  terrible 
and  powerful  and  strong  exceedingly  with  great 
iron  teeth,  devouring  and  breaking  in  pieces  and 
stamping  the  residue  with  his  feet,"  had  devoured 
her  last  patriots  and  trampled  her  liberties  into  the 
mire.  To  the  unexampled  clemency  of  Philip  and 
Alexander  had  succeeded  the  terrorism  of  their 
brutal  generals.  A  successful  military  adventurer, 
Demetrius  Poliorcetes,  remarkable  not  less  for  his 
frightful  profligacy  than  for  his  shining  abilities, 
was  lodged  in  the  Parthenon,  and  received  divine 
honours  from  the  servile  Athenians.  All  the  most 
virile  elements  of  the  community  were  drawn  off 
to  Asia  and  Egypt  by  the  lucrative  prospects  of 
mercenary  service.  It  would  not  have  been  sur- 
prising if,  in  the  circumstances,  no  lesson  but  that 
of  fatalistic  indifference  to  outward  events  had  been 
learned  by  the  degenerate  youths  who  divided  their 
time  between  the  boudoir  of  the  hetaira  and  the 
lecture-hall  of  the  sage.  Nevertheless,  Zeno  lived 
to  see  the  last  great  struggle  for  Greek  indepen- 
dence begin  ;  his  successors  saw  its  temporary 
victory  and  its  development  into  a  movement  that 
seemed  to  promise  the  realisation  of  their  own 
social  ideals. 

In  the  year  280  B.C.  a  Gallic  storm,  like  that 
which  had  devastated  Italy  more  than  a  century 
before,  broke  on  the  Hellenic  world.  Macedonia, 
whose  proud  boast  it  was  to  shield  civilisation 
against  barbarism,  succumbed  at  once  to  the 
shock,  and  her  usurping  king,  Ptolemy  Keraunos, 
fell  in  battle  with  the  invaders.  The  human  deluge 
poured  on,  but  was  arrested  and  flung  back  by  the 
unsupported  levies  of  central  Greece.  Their 


7 
o  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

heroism  still  lives  for  us  embodied  in  the  form  of 
the  Apollo  Belvedere,  the  marble  copy  of  a  bronze 
statue  erected  to  commemorate  the  repulse  of  the 
barbarians  from  Delphi,  and  representing  the  god 
in  the  act  of  shaking  his  shield  in  their  faces.1 
Other  famous  works  of  plastic  art  owe  their  inspira- 
tion to  the  same  desperate  conflict,  as  it  afterwards 
raged  in  Asia  Minor,  such  as  the  dying  Gaul  of  the 
Capitol  ;  the  group  of  a  Gaul  supporting  the  body 
of  the  wife  whom  he  has  just  slain,  and  plunging  a 
sword  into  his  own  breast,  in  the  Museo  delle 
Terme  at  Rome  ;  also,  perhaps,  those  Pergamene 
reliefs  which  are  now  the  glory  of  Berlin.  But  it 
was  not  merely  in  art  that  the  victorious  conscious- 
ness of  resurgent  Hellenic  life  found  expression. 
Sparta  exhibited  all  her  ancient  heroism  in  repelling 
an  attack  made  on  her  by  Pyrrhus,  the  greatest 
general  of  the  age  ;  a  few  years  afterwards  Athens 
made  a  desperate  but  unsuccessful  effort  to  shake 
off  the  Macedonian  yoke.  This,  which  Droysen 
calls  her  last  but  her  most  honourable  attempt  to 
recover  her  ancient  liberty — an  attempt  first  rescued 
from  oblivion  in  modern  times  by  the  great  historian 
Niebuhr — is  known  as  the  Chremonidean  war  from 
its  leader,  Chremonides,  a  friend,  perhaps  a  disciple, 
of  Zeno.  Droysen  has  no  doubt  that  the  movement 
was  inspired  by  Stoicism,  which  had  now  been 
taught  for  a  whole  generation  at  Athens,  and  was 
diffused  through  all  Hellas  by  the  students  who 
had  flocked  from  every  quarter  to  the  intellectual 
metropolis,  as  well  as  by  Arcesilaus,  the  high- 

1  According  to  Beloch  (III.,  p.  582),  the  Gauls  actually  took  and 
plundered  Delphi ;  but,  as  they  were  subsequently  defeated  by  the 
Greeks,  the  Apollo  retains  its  symbolic  value. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  71 

minded  scholarch  of  the  Middle  Academy.1  Not 
that  Zeno  himself  was  an  enthusiast  for  republican 
liberty ;  the  tenour  of  his  doctrine  was  rather 
favourable  to  monarchy,  and  he  was  personally 
the  friend  and  confidant  of  King  Antigonus 
Gonatas,  against  whom  this  rising  was  directed. 
But  the  lessons  of  moral  earnestness  and  zeal  once 
learned  cannot  be  appropriated  by  any  political 
party  ;  they  can,  however,  raise  partisanship  to  a 
higher  level  by  investing  it  with  the  authority  of  a 
divine  mandate  or  consecrating  it  to  the  service  of 
an  impersonal  ideal.  Thus  the  modern  Stoicism 
of  Carlyle2  gave  fresh  energy  to  aspirations  that  he 
misunderstood  or  despised ;  and  at  the  moment 
when  the  master  was  inditing  his  American  Iliad 
in  a  Nutshell  many  of  his  unknown  disciples  may 
have  been  dying  in  order  that  human  beings 
should  not  be  engaged  as  servants  for  life  against 
their  will. 

The  Chremonidean  war  only  served  to  rivet  the 
Macedonian  yoke  more  firmly  on  the  necks  of  the 
Athenians.  But  the  emancipating  movement 
spread  like  wildfire  in  the  Peloponnesus.  Two 
disciples  of  Arcesilaus,  Ecdemus  and  Demophanes, 
slew  the  unlawful  ruler  of  their  native  city  Megalo- 
polis, and  restored  it  to  freedom  ;  they  then  aided 
Aratus  in  achieving  the  still  more  glorious  deliver- 
ance of  Sicyon,  and  finally,  at  the  invitation  of 
Cyrene,  crossed  the  sea  to  give  that  great  African 
colony  the  blessing  of  an  orderly  republican 


1  Geschichte  des  Hellenismus ,  III.,  pp.  228  sqq. 

"  Of  course  this  is  not  to  be  understood  as  meaning  that  Carlyle 
was  a  Stoic  in  practice. 


72  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

government.1  Federation,  an  entirely  new  poli- 
tical experiment,  was  tried  with  success  by  the 
famous  Achaian  League ;  its  President,  Aratus, 
drove  the  Macedonian  garrison  from  Corinth,  and 
gave  Athens  the  independence  that  she  could  not 
achieve  for  herself.  How  high  the  tide  of 
enthusiasm  was  running  appears  from  the  story 
of  Lydiades,  a  noble  youth  who,  having  possessed 
himself  of  supreme  power  in  Megalopolis,  and 
exercised  it  some  years  for  the  public  good,  volun- 
tarily surrendered  his  autocracy  and  descended  to 
the  rank  of  a  private  citizen,  whence  he  was  soon 
raised  by  the  free  votes  of  the  people  to  the  presi- 
dency of  the  Achaian  League. 

So  far  philosophy  had  done  wonders,  but  its 
greatest  triumph  still  remained  to  win.  This  was 
the  reconstitution  of  the  Spartan  State.  One  of 
the  most  curious  chapters  in  the  history  of  specu- 
lation relates  to  the  use  made  of  Sparta  and  her 
institutions  in  the  schools  of  Athens.  Professor 
Edward  Caird  has  called  attention,  from  a  Hege- 
lian point  of  view,  to  the  remarkable  union  in 
Rousseau's  mind  of  faith  in  nature  with  faith  in 
education.2  Just  the  same  combination  was  ex- 
hibited by  Rousseau's  Greek  predecessors ;  and  as 
they  found  a  model  of  uncorrupted  natural  virtue 
in  Scythia,  so  they  found  an  equally  perfect  model 
of  artificial  training  in  Sparta.  It  was  supposed 
that  the  much-admired  system  which  produced  a 
Leonidas  and  a  Gorgo,  an  Argileonis  and  a 
Brasidas,  had  been  created  in  all  its  pieces  by  the 


1  Polybius,  X.,  22.    The  reference  is  wrongly  given  in  Droysen. 
*  Essays  on  Literature  and  Philosophy,  I.,  120  sqq. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  73 

legislator  Lycurgus  and  preserved  intact  during 
several  centuries  after  his  death.  But  in  truth  the 
educational  and  semi-socialistic  romance  that  we 
read  in  Plutarch,  while  it  embodies  some  features 
common  to  the  more  primitive  Dorian  tribes,  was 
in  great  part  evolved  out  of  their  own  moral  con- 
sciousness by  several  generations  of  philosophers. 
Lycurgus  is  a  pure  myth,  the  human  incarnation 
of  an  old  Spartan  god  ; I  the  equal  division  of  land 
attributed  to  him  no  doubt  represents  an  actual 
distribution  of  conquered  territory  among  the 
predatory  warriors  who  had  established  themselves 
by  the  Eurotas  ;  but  we  have  no  reason  to  believe 
that  a  permanent  equality  of  landed  property  was 
legally  provided  for  ;  at  any  rate,  in  the  historical 
period  we  find  the  distinction  between  rich  and 
poor  as  sharply  emphasised  at  Sparta  as  anywhere 
else.2 

The  Greeks  are  a  people  who  have  always  been 
more  influenced  by  memory  or  hope  than  by 
immediate  reality,  and  neither  the  complete  over- 
throw of  Sparta  by  Epaminondas  nor  her  subse- 
quent isolation  from  Panhellenic  politics  detracted 
anything  from  the  traditional  adoration  paid  her 
by  popular  rhetoricians  and  philosophical  historians 
who  continued  freely  adding  to  the  picture  of  her 
primitive  perfection.  At  last  the  glamour  that  she 
had  so  long  exercised  on  others  was  reflected  back 
on  herself,  and  the  fictitious  legislation  of  Lycurgus 
was  taken  up  in  all  seriousness  by  her  more 
educated  children  as  a  charter  still  claiming  their 

1  I  am  aware  that  an  attempt  has  recently  been  made  to  vindi- 
cate his  historical  reality. 

2  Pohlmann,  utantefp.  102. 


74  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

obedience  and  support.  A  reform  of  some  kind 
was,  indeed,  imperatively  needed,  for  the  concentra- 
tion of  property  in  a  few  hands,  everywhere  a 
pressing  evil,  had  been  carried  further,  perhaps, 
in  Sparta  than  in  any  other  Greek  state,  and  was 
eating  away  what  still  remained  of  her  defensive 
military  power.  A  modern  historian  has  explained 
this  economic  revolution  by  the  peculiar  position 
that  Sparta  occupied  as  an  emporium  for  what  was 
then  a  kind  of  merchandise  in  extensive  request — 
namely,  mercenary  soldiers.1  Then,  as  always, 
the  Peloponnesus  supplied  the  best  material  of  this 
description,  and  the  condottieri  who  dealt  in  it 
brought  enormous  sums  of  money  into  the  country. 
But  not  many  benefited  by  the  traffic.  While  the 
ruling  class  in  Sparta  had  dwindled  to  seven 
hundred  families,  only  a  hundred  of  these  possessed 
any  property  whatever.  The  young  -king  Agis 
proposed  to  remedy  this  state  of  things  by  abolish- 
ing debts  and  dividing  the  land  among  the  poorer 
citizens  and  the  Pericecians.  He  led  the  way  by 
surrendering  to  the  State  his  own  vast  estates, 
together  with  personal  property  to  the  value  of  six 
hundred  talents  (;£  150,000).  Some  members  of 
the  royal  family  and  some  leading  politicians  were 
won  over  to  the  scheme,  which  at  first  seemed  to 
carry  all  before  it.  But  Agesilaus,  the  young 
king's  uncle,  was  only  anxious  for  the  abolition  of 
debts,  in  which  he  was  personally  interested,  and 
found  means  to  postpone  the  division  of  land,  by 
which  he  would  have  been  a  loser.  Meanwhile  the 
Conservatives  rallied  their  forces,  a  reaction  set  in, 

1  Holm,  Griechische  Geschichte,  IV.,  p.  287. 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  75 

and  Agis  was  seized  by  the  Ephors  and  strangled 
in  prison,  together  with  his  mother  and  grand- 
mother. His  widow  Agiatis,  the  richest  heiress 
in  Sparta,  was  obliged  to  marry  Cleomenes,  son  of 
King  Leonidas,  the  official  head  of  the  reactionary 
party.  But  the  noble  Queen  contrived  to  inoculate 
her  young  husband  with  the  ideas  of  the  martyred 
Agis ;  and  the  teaching  of  his  heroic  mother 
Cratesicleia  was  doubtless  thrown  into  the  same 
scale.  Nor  was  his  mind  only  subjected  to  the 
passionate  impulses  of  feminine  affection  and  grief; 
a  higher  and  steadier  discipline  lent  its  aid  to  the 
great  work. 

If  in  the  case  of  Agis  we  can  only  assign  to 
philosophy  a  remote  and  general  influence,  in  so 
far  as  his  animating  ideals  were  a  creation  of 
thought,  in  the  case  of  Cleomenes  it  becomes  a 
direct  and  demonstrable  agency.  One  of  Zeno's 
most  eminent  disciples,  a  certain  Sphasrus,  was  at 
that  time  living  in  Sparta.  He  came  from  a  Greek 
colony  on  the  northern  shore  of  the  Euxine,  and 
had  grown  up  in  the  neighbourhood  of  those 
Scythians  whose  primitive  communism  excited 
such  admiration  in  the  schools  of  Athens.  Among 
his  numerous  treatises,  one  on  Socrates  and 
Lycurgus  and  another  on  The  Laconian  Constitution 
are  mentioned.  This  man  became  the  intimate 
friend  of  Cleomenes,  and  assisted  him  in  planning 
the  great  reforms  which  the  young  king,  on  gain- 
ing supreme  power,  pressed  through  with  relentless 
vigour.  For  details  I  must  refer  to  the  stirring 
narrative  of  Plutarch.  The  agrarian  reforms  are 
carried  out  in  the  teeth  of  all  opposition  ;  a  new 
body  of  stalwart  citizen-soldiers  is  created  ;  city 


76  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

after  city  opens  its  gates  to  the  champion  of  the 
poor  ;  Sparta  resumes*  her  old  place  as  the  leading 
state  in  Peloponnesus,  in  all  free  Hellas ;  her 
victorious  king  hopes  to  supersede  the  clever  but 
cowardly  Aratus  as  president  of  the  Achaian 
League.  Then  comes  the  fatal  reaction.  Those 
who  had  hoped  for  a  general  abolition  of  debt  turn 
against  the  reformer  whose  measures  were  dictated 
only  by  the  public  interest  ;  Aratus,  to  his  eternal 
shame,  purchases  the  help  of  a  Macedonian  army 
against  Cleomenes  by  surrendering  the  Acrocorin- 
thus  to  Antigonus  Doson.  Defeated  in  battle,  and 
already  heart-broken  by  the  loss  of  his  adored  wife 
Agiatis,  the  Spartan  king  refuses  to  end  his  suffer- 
ings by  suicide.  The  sayings  put  into  the  mouths 
of  great  men  are  generally  apocryphal ;  but  the 
sentiment  attributed  to  Cleomenes  on  this  occasion 
is  at  least  characteristic  of  the  Stoic  philosophy  in 
which  he  had  been  bred.  When  urged  to  choose 
death  rather  than  an  ignominious  flight  to  Egypt, 
he  answered,  as  Plutarch  tells  us,  that  it  is  dis- 
graceful either  to  live  or  to  die  for  ourselves  alone. 
But  Egypt,  as  usual,  proved  a  broken  reed,  and 
Cleomenes  perished  in  an  attempt  to  rouse  the 
Greek  population  of  Alexandria  against  its  effemi- 
nate tyrant.  The  reformed  constitution  of  his  beloved 
Sparta  had  already  been  destroyed  by  Antigonus. 

These  events  occurred  between  the  years  243  and 
221  B.C.  Less  than  a  century  later  a  series  of 
events  took  place  in  Rome  offering  such  a  close 
resemblance  to  the  agrarian  revolution  in  Sparta 
that,  were  not  the  historical  reality  of  both  proved 
by  irrefragable  evidence,  we  might  almost  suppose 
the  one  story  to  be  a  replica  of  the  other.  I  refer, 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  77 

of  course,  to  the  reforms  of  Tiberius  and  Gaius 
Gracchus.  Again,  we  find  a  generous,  enthusiastic, 
and  high-born  young  man  seeking  to  rescue  the 
pauperised  masses  from  their  degradation  by  the 
re-enactment  of  an  obsolete  law ;  again,  the  first 
reforming  effort  is  stifled  by  illegal  violence  in  the 
blood  of  its  originator ;  again,  it  is  resumed  by  a 
younger  and  far  stronger  successor,  the  transition 
being  this  time  also  effected  through  the  instru- 
mentality of  a  woman,  the  illustrious  Cornelia ; 
again,  after  a  brief  and  brilliant  period  of  success, 
the  democratic  autocracy  succumbs  to  an  energetic 
reaction  of  the  propertied  classes,  passively  aided 
by  a  fickle  populace.  But  what  interests  us  most 
of  all  is  to  observe  that  the  Gracchi  also  were 
prepared  for  their  generous  enterprise  by  a  Stoic 
philosopher,  the  Cuman  Blossius,  a  pupil  of  the 
great  school  of  Tarsus — "no  mean  city" — whose 
intellectual  atmosphere  was  destined  to  exert  an 
incalculable  action  on  the  Apostle  Paul.  Here, 
then,  we  have  a  signal  corroboration  of  the  his- 
torical deduction  that  seeks  in  Greek  philosophy, 
and  more  especially  in  Stoicism,  or  more  generally 
in  the  physiocratic  school,  for  a  key  to  the  sys- 
tematic socialistic  enterprises  of  antiquity. 

It  cannot  be  said  that  the  result  of  those  enter- 
prises was  in  any  way  satisfactory.  Discord, 
bloodshed,  anarchy,  and  despotism  were  their 
most  evident  fruits.  The  movement  set  on  foot 
by  Agis  was  followed  by  nearly  a  century  of  class- 
warfare,  that  at  last  necessitated  the  armed  inter- 
vention of  Rome  and  the  reduction  of  the  Pelopon- 
nesus under  her  sway.  In  Rome  itself  the  period 
of  civil  wars  dates  from  Tiberius  Gracchus.  In  so 


78  THE  INFLUENCE  OF  PHILOSOPHY 

far  as  they  contributed  to  the  foundation  of  the 
empire,  we  have  no  reason  to  complain  of  the 
result,  but  it  was  one  that  he  never  anticipated  ; 
while  the  distributions  of  cheap  corn  introduced  by 
his  brother  Gaius  proved  a  permanent  source  of 
demoralisation  to  imperial,  as  well  as  to  republican, 
Rome. 

Socialism  as  we  know  it  to-day  is  lineally  con- 
nected through  French  and  German  thought  with 
the  socialism  of  the  Greek  naturalists.  There  is, 
however,  at  least  one  marked  distinction  between 
the  two,  corresponding  to  the  different  forms  of 
society  that  gave  them  birth.  Ours  is  of  the 
industrial,  theirs  of  the  military  type.  Every 
ancient  city-state  was  more  or  less  in  the  position 
of  a  besieged  garrison  or  of  a  predatory  band,  and 
for  the  officers  to  appropriate  most  of  the  rations 
and  all  the  booty  was  not  only  unjust,  but  suicidal. 
Cleomenes  had  for  his  sole  object  to  restore  the 
military  supremacy  of  Sparta  ;  the  Gracchi  must 
certainly  have  wished  to  recruit  the  population,  and 
with  it  the  armed  strength  of  Italy.  Hence,  the 
redistribution  of  land  was  their  watchword,  capital 
being  associated  in  their  minds,  not  with  the  pay- 
ment of  low  wages  to  the  poor  by  the  rich,  but  with 
the  payment  of  high  interest  to  the  rich  by  the  poor. 
The  inference  is  obvious.  If  socialism  failed  to 
make  way  under  a  regime  with  which  it  had  a 
natural  affinity,  its  chances  must  be  still  weaker 
under  an  industrial  and  capitalist  regime. 

The  social  influence  of  philosophy  in  Greece  is 
far  from  being  exhausted  by  the  humanitarian 
tendencies  of  the  fourth  century  and  the  agrarian 
movement  of  the  third  century.  The  great  part 


ON  GREEK  POLITICAL  LIFE  79 

played  by  women  in  the  Spartan  revolution 
belongs,  I  think,  to  a  very  much  wider  move- 
ment, inaugurated  and  sustained  by  philosophy. 
But  this  is  a  subject  on  which  I  am  not  now 
prepared  to  enter. 


THE   ALLEGED  SOCIALISM    OF   THE 
PROPHETS1 

M.  ERNEST  RENAN'S  History  of  the  People  of  Israel 
is  a  disappointing  work.  Of  course,  it  has  great 
merits.  M.  Renan  can  write  well  on  any  subject, 
and  any  man  of  ability  can  write  well  about  the 
events  recorded  in  the  Old  Testament.  The  book 
contains  eloquent  passages,  masterly  sketches  of 
character,  flashes  of  profound  historical  insight, 
and  renderings  from  Hebrew  poetry,  such  as 
might  have  been  expected  from  the  pre-eminent 
translator  of  Job.  Some  at  least  of  the  results  of 
modern  criticism  are  distilled  into  as  easy  reading 
as  the  feuilleton  of  a  Parisian  newspaper.  Above 
all,  the  whole  subject  is  treated  with  a  freshness 
and  freedom  that  it  would  be  vain  to  expect  even  in 
the  most  unfettered  theological  professor.  Still, 
we  expected  something  more  from  M.  Renan.  As 
a  Semitic  specialist,  a  historian,  and  a  philosopher, 
he  might  have  added  somewhat  to  our  knowledge 
of  Hebrew  life  and  thought.  Not  only  has  he 
added  nothing,  he  has  not  shown  himself  on  a 
level  with  the  best  knowledge  of  the  age.  Accord- 
ing to  Professor  Robertson  Smith,  he  "simply 
ignores  the  more  modern  criticism."2  A  notion 
has  somehow  got  abroad  that  the  author  of  the 
Vie  de  Jesus  represents  the  extreme  of  negation 

1  Written  in  1893. 

a  The  Old  Testament  in  the  Jewish  Church,  2nd  ed.,  p.  392. 
80 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      81 

in  questions  connected  with  the  Biblical  narratives. 
In  fact,  the  leanings  of  M.  Renan,  like  those  of  his 
countrymen  generally,  are  to  the  conservative  side. 
It  will  be  remembered  how  through  a  dozen  editions 
of  the  Vie  de  Jesus  he  upheld  the  apostolic  author- 
ship of  the  Fourth  Gospel,  and  I  do  not  know  that 
he  has  ever  given  up  the  passage  about  Jesus 
Christ  in  Josephus.  There  is  in  truth  a  good  deal 
of  eighteenth-century  rationalism  about  this  author, 
a  summary  a  priori  rejection  of  the  miraculous 
element  combined  with  a  rather  uncritical  acceptance 
of  the  narratives  in  which  miracles  occur ;  hence 
the  effort  to  explain  miracles  as  natural  events,  and, 
where  this  method  cannot  be  successfully  applied, 
the  tendency  to  charge  the  narrators  of  such  events 
with  sheer,  deliberate  fraud. 

It  is  not,  however,  of  what  M.  Renan  has  left  out 
that  we  have  to  complain  so  much  as  of  what  he  has 
put  in  ;  or,  perhaps,  the  less  admirable  side  of  his 
work  might  be  summed  up  in  a  single  phrase, 
"playing  to  the  gallery."  His  audience  consists 
very  largely  of  persons  whom  I  desire  to  mention 
with  all  respect — persons  of  the  brightest  intelli- 
gence, and,  at  least  in  the  things  of  the  intellect,  of 
the  most  delicate  taste.  To  their  exacting  demands, 
to  their  keen  appreciation  of  what  is  excellent  in 
style  and  brilliant  in  ideation,  we  owe  the  lucidity 
of  French  prose,  the  ingenuity  and  grace  of  French 
literature.  Their  opinion  of  a  new  play  or  a  new 
novel  is  most  valuable,  and  even  on  subjects 
requiring  a  certain  amount  of  scholarship  it  is 
not  to  be  despised.  But  you  must  not  tell  them  to 
take  much  trouble ;  they  like  to  think  that  their 
author  is  deeply  read  and  laborious,  but  the  result 

G 


82      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

must  be  put  before  them  in  a  finished  form,  and  it 
is  only  in  their  appreciation  of  form  that  they  are 
severe.  Inaccurate  or  inconsistent  statements  are 
allowed  to  pass  under  cover  of  epigrammatic 
phrases,  and  the  critic  that  exposed  them  would 
forfeit  his  reputation  for  good  breeding. 

For  the  last  thirty  years  M.  Renan  has  been 
falling  more  and  more  under  the  influence  of  such 
a  public  as  I  have  described.  His  first  popularity 
was  won  by  no  unworthy  acts  ;  it  came  to  him 
unsought,  and,  one  fancies,  as  a  not  altogether 
agreeable  surprise.  As  a  seminarist  he  had  learned 
to  despise  the  lay  public,  and  he  has  recently  let  us 
know  that  his  sentiments  towards  them  still  savour 
of  sacerdotal  scorn.  As  a  professor  of  Hebrew  he 
has  never,  like  some  of  his  colleagues,  laid  himself 
out  to  attract  the  large  mixed  audiences  that  infest 
the  lecture-rooms  of  Paris.  It  was  not  his  fault  if 
he  wrote  in  a  style  of  unrivalled  delicacy  and 
distinction,  or  if  his  profoundly  disinterested 
historical  studies  supplied  new  weapons  to  the 
anti-clericalists  with  whom  he  sympathised  rather 
less  than  with  their  opponents.  But  no  man  can 
be  popular  with  impunity ;  common  politeness 
seems  to  require  one  to  take  into  consideration  the 
tastes  and  wishes  of  one's  most  numerous  admirers. 
M.  Renan  has  never,  I  think,  quite  equalled  either 
in  expression  or  in  thought  the  essays  published  a 
few  years  before  his  Vie  de  Jesus,  and  then  only 
known  to  a  select  few.  In  comparing  the  later 
with  the  earlier  volumes  of  his  great  work  on  the 
history  of  primitive  Christianity,  can  one  escape 
the  impression  of  an  increasing  vulgarity,  a 
growing  sensationalism,  and  a  tendency  to  enlarge 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      83 

on  scenes  of  lubricity  and  horror  ?  The  unfortunate 
series  of  dramatic  attempts  beginning  with  Caliban, 
and  culminating  in  U  Abbes  se  de  Jouarre,  are  only 
explicable  on  the  theory  that  the  great  religious 
historian  wished  to  win  the  applause  of  a  class  for 
whom  the  liveliest  work  on  religion  is  not  exciting 
enough.  In  the  work  of  which  I  write,  the  History 
of  Israel,  the  desire  to  please  les  honnetes  gens,  as 
they  are  called  in  France — not,  by  any  means, 
necessarily  "  honest  people,"  but  rather  what  we 
call  "  nice  people,"  accomplished  men  and  women 
of  the  world — has  produced  the  most  mischievous 
results.  Unlike  Carlyle's  horse,  M.  Renan  thinks 
that  his  first  duty  is  to  say  clever  things,  and  his 
efforts  in  this  direction  are  not  always  very  fortunate. 
At  his  best,  no  one  has  ever  shown  such  perfect 
delicacy  of  touch,  but  he  exercises  this  gift  only  on 
the  condition  of  treating  serious  subjects  in  a  serious 
manner.  The  gay  Voltairean  mockery  that  he 
sometimes  affects  does  not  seem  to  come  natural 
to  him  ;  it  sounds  like  the  light  talk  of  a  heavy 
man  ;  often  flippancy  has  to  do  duty  for  wit. 

This,  however,  is  a  mere  matter  of  taste,  and  has 
little  to  do  with  the  intrinsic  value  of  the  work. 
What  the  reader  has  to  complain  of  is  a  thorough- 
going perversion  of  history  in  the  interest  of  a  flimsy 
theory.  One  might  have  expected  from  M.  Renan 
a  satisfactory  treatment  of  the  prophets  of  Israel. 
He  is  fully  alive  to  their  importance.  He  fully 
accepts  the  modern  view  of  their  teaching  as  the 
veVy  soul  of  Hebrew  history,  and  its  highest 
documentary  evidence  as  the  first  proclamation  of 
absolute  monotheism,  the  first  ethical  interpretation 
of  religion,  the  immediate  and  adequate  antecedent 


84      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

of  Christianity.  To  many  his  account  of  the 
prophets  came  as  a  revelation.  Professor  James 
Darmesteter  tells  us  that  even  the  boulevardiers 
were,  for  a  moment,  thrilled  by  the  vision  of  those 
Titanic  figures  with  their  awful  denunciations  of 
idolatry  and  oppression,  of  selfish  luxury  and 
shameless  vice.  But  I  fear  that  the  historian  of 
Israel  caught  the  ear  of  the  boulevardier  by  accom- 
modating himself  freely  to  the  language  and 
sentiments  of  that  cheerful  and  pleasure-loving 
personage,  the  modern  Parisian  equivalent  of  "  the 
man  about  town."  M.  Renan  has  elsewhere  told 
a  certain  story  about  a  country  cure  who  preached 
on  the  Passion  of  Jesus  Christ  in  such  moving 
terms  that  the  whole  congregation  were  melted  into 
tears.  "  Do  not  weep,  my  children,"  exclaimed  the 
kind  old  man,  in  much  concern  at  their  grief;  "all 
this  happened  a  long  time  ago,  and  perhaps  it  is 
not  quite  true  either."  It  sometimes  looks  as  if  he 
had  taken  a  leaf  out  of  that  excellent  cure's  book. 
The  boulevardier  must  not  make  himself  too 
anxious.  Let  him  bear  in  mind  that  the  prophets 
were  very  uncivilised  persons,  without  a  notion  of 
politeness,  who  wrote  a  long  time  ago,  "when 
morality  needed  to  be  affirmed  and  established." 
It  will  relieve  him  to  hear  that  moral  rigorism, 
although,  after  all,  it  was  once  of  use,  "  now  does 
humanity  nearly  as  much  harm  as  good."1 
Professor  Darmesteter,  who  is  a  friend  and 
admirer  of  M.  Renan,  might  profit  more  by  the 
master's  example.  He  actually  quotes  Jeremiah's 
fierce  sarcasm  about  "every  man  neighing  after 

'  HI.,  P.  155. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      85 

his  neighbour's  wife  "  as  "  an  excellent  description 
of  the  drama  and  fiction  of  our  own  day." 

Not  only  did  the  prophets  live  a  long  time  ago 
(before  morality  became  superfluous),  but  the 
boulevardier  may  be  comforted  by  the  assurance 
that  what  they  said  was  not  quite  true.  "  There  is 
great  exaggeration  in  the  picture  drawn  by  Amos 
of  the  crimes  committed  in  the  palace  of  Samaria. 

His    ideas    about    rich    scoundrels,    thieving 

merchants,  men  of  business,  and  monopolisers  of 
corn,  are  those  of  a  man  of  the  people  without  any 
knowledge  of  political  economy"1  One  cannot 
help  being  reminded  of  the  same  writer's  remarks 
on  the  first  chapter  of  St.  Paul's  Epistle  to  the 
Romans  explaining  the  apostle's  terrible  picture  of 
heathen  vices,  by  his  complete  ignorance  of  good 
society.2  St.  Paul,  we  are  told,  entertained  much 
the  same  absurdly  exaggerated  ideas  about  the 
debaucheries  of  the  higher  classes  that  an  honest 
and  simple-minded  Socialist  working  man  entertains 
now.  I  should  not  give  much  for  the  morals  of 
good  society  in  our  own  time  if  they  at  all  resemble 
what  we  know  to  have  been  the  habits  of  Grseco- 
Roman  society  on  the  evidence  of  writers  who  had 
every  opportunity  for  observing  and  not  the 
slightest  motive  for  maligning  it.  The  secular 
literature  of  Samaria  has  perished,  nor  do  we  know 
what  sort  of  songs  those  were  that  her  nobles  sang 
on  their  ivory  couches  ;  but  the  testimony  of  the 
other  prophets,  some  of  whom  mingled  freely  in 
court-circles,  goes  to  confirm  the  denunciations 
of  Amos.3  When  the  shepherd  of  Tekoa  raises 

1  II.,  p.  432.  z  Les  Ap&tres,  p.  309. 

3  Cf.  Hosea  iv.  and  Isaiah  xxviii. 


86      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

his  voice  against  the  oppression  of  the  poor,  he  is 
silenced  in  the  same  off-hand  manner.     What  he 
describes  as  monstrosities  are,  it  seems,  simply  the 
plainest    social    necessities  —  lending    money   on 
security,  payment  of  debts,  and  taxation.     To  the 
boulevardier,    living    under    tolerably   just     laws 
tolerably  well  administered,  the  answer  may  seem 
conclusive  ;  but  a  scholar  and  an  Eastern  traveller 
ought  not  to  be  so  limited  in  his  ideas.     M.  Renan 
must  surely  know  that  taxation  may  be  so  adjusted 
as  to  become  an  instrument  of  the  most  hateful 
oppression,  and  that,  though  it  may  be  a  social 
necessity,  it  has  over  and  over  again  endangered 
the  very  existence  of  society.     We  know  no  more 
of  Ephraim  than  Amos  and  Hosea  tell  us  ;  but, 
fortunately,  we  are  in  a  position  to  study  the  early 
history  of  Athens  and   Rome,  the  late  history  of 
the  Roman  Empire,  the  antecedents  of  the  French 
Revolution,  and  the  contemporary  administration 
of  Asiatic  despotism — notably  of  Egypt  before  the 
English  occupation — in  the   light  of  information 
that  is  above  suspicion.    From  the  Eupatrides  to  the 
pashas,     every    governing    class     invested    with 
absolute  power  and  unrestrained  by  moral  scruples 
not  only  drains  the  people  of  their  life-blood,  it  also 
brings  the  State  to  destruction  unless  it  is  saved  by 
some  such  measure  as  Solon's  partial  cancelling  of 
debts,  the  Licinian  Rogations,  or  the  Revolution 
of  '89.     For  the  indebtedness  of  the  poorer  classes 
is  a   direct  consequence   of  the   exorbitant   taxes 
levied  on  them  by  the  rich,  to  meet  which  they 
have  to  borrow  money  at  usurious  interest,  at  first 
to  the  no  small  profit  of  their  oppressors,  who  con- 
tinue to  grow  richer,   while   their  subject  grows 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS       87 

poorer,  until  the  weakening  of  the  foundation 
involves  the  whole  edifice  in  ruin.  Thus  the 
artisan  or  peasant  sees  his  tools  and  household 
goods  wrung  from  him  bit  by  bit,  while  the  fruits 
of  his  industry,  exchanged  for  foreign  luxuries,  are 
wasted  in  unproductive  expenditure.  The  political 
economist  would  be  faithless  to  common  honesty 
if  he  condoned  the  rapine,  whether  lawless  or 
legalised,  by  which  the  wealth  of  the  Ephraimite 
nobles  was  acquired,  and  faithless  to  the  principles 
of  his  own  science  if  he  sanctioned  the  vulgar 
ostentation  and  the  vile  sensuality  to  gratify  which 
it  was  wasted.  Luxury  has  been  defended  in 
modern  times  on  the  ground  that  it  checks  the 
growth  of  population.  The  practices  described  by 
Amos  and  Hosea  would  assuredly  have  that  effect; 
but  to  check  the  growth  of  population  was  simple 
suicide  among  a  handful  of  highland  clans 
struggling  for  existence  against  the  armies  of 
Damascus  and  Assyria. 

So  far  there  is  no  difficulty  in  understanding  the 
attitude,  of  the  prophets  towards  the  rich  and 
powerful  class.  An  elementary  knowledge  of 
history  explains  it,  and  a  deeper  knowledge  can 
but  confirm  the  explanation.  But  M.  Renan  is 
quite  put  out  by  this  attitude  ;  this  is  not  exactly 
the  language  that  he  or  his  friend  the  boulevardier 
would  hear  uttered  in  a  fashionable  Parisian 
pulpit.  Strange  to  say,  the  spokesmen  of  God 
did  not  think  twice  before  they  damned  persons  of 
that  quality.  But  a  solution  of  the  mystery  is 
forthcoming.  "  The  most  deeply  rooted  idea  of 
those  old  times,"  he  informs  us,  "is  that  there  are 
poor  people  because  there  are  rich  people wealth 


88      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

being  always  the  fruit  of  injustice. " x  Only  a  single 
fact  is  cited  in  proof  of  this  sweeping  assertion. 
Travelling  in  the  East,  M.  Renan  was  once 
particularly  struck  by  the  goodness  of  the  inhabi- 
tants of  a  certain  village  where  he  had  spent  the 
night.  "It  is  because  they  are  poor,"  explained 
his  dragoman.3  Probably  the  dragoman  was  right. 
One  may  experience  the  same  contrast  without 
going  beyond  Southern  Europe.  But  to  say  that 
wealth  produces  wickedness  is  not  to  say  that 
wickedness  produces  wealth.  Of  all  authorities, 
the  Hebrew  Scriptures,  with  their  not  very  refined 
doctrine  of  material  and  temporal  rewards  and 
punishments,  seem  least  to  sanction  such  an  idea. 
The  Book  of  Job,  that  admirable  compendium  of 
Hebrew  philosophy,  furnishes  us  with  an  excellent 
test-instance.  Job  has  fallen  from  the  greatest 
prosperity  into  extreme  destitution  and  suffering. 
His  friends  are  most  anxious  to  prove  that  the 
catastrophe  is  due  to  some  fault  of  his  own.  What 
then,  on  M.  Kenan's  principle,  would  be  more 
natural  for  them  to  urge  than  that  the  very  fact  of 
his  having  been  so  rich  proves  him  to  have  been 
a  public  robber?  Now  it  is  true  that  Eliphaz  the 
Temanite  advances  an  argument  (Job  xxii.  5-10) 
tending  this  way  ;  but  Job  victoriously  asserts  his 
innocence  against  this  as  against  all  the  other 
purely  constructive  accusations  of  his  friends. 
Alike  in  the  stories  of  Abraham,  Isaac,  and  Joseph, 
written  down  shortly  before  the  appearance  of  the 
first  literary  prophets,  and  in  the  character  of  the 
virtuous  woman,3  composed  after  prophecy  had 

1  II.,  pp.  424,  425.  2  in.,  p.  38. 

3  Proverbs  xxxi.     The  character  of  the  successful  woman  of 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      89 

died   out,  we  find  the  same   intimate   association 
between  wealth  and  worth. 

If  the  East  can  supply  no  parallel  instances  of 
such  wanton  attacks  on  the  established  social  order, 
such  denunciations  of  the  rich  simply  because  they 
are  better  off  than  other  people,  as  the  oldest 
written  prophecies  are  here  interpreted  to  be,  the 
West  comes  to  the  rescue  with  illustrations  of  a 
kind  peculiarly  intelligible  to  a  Parisian  reader. 
The  prophets  were  "  radical  and  revolutionary 
journalists,  declaiming  their  articles  in  the  street. 

The  first  chapter  of  Amos  is  the  first  opposition 

leader  that  was  ever  published,"  and  Amos  himself 
the  father  of  all  such  as  contribute  to  the  subversive 
press.1  Like  the  modern  Nihilist,  the  Hebrew 
thinker  held  that  if  the  world  cannot  be  just  it  had 
better  not  exist.2  But  by  justice  the  prophets  mean 
Socialism,  and  "  Socialism  is  of  Hebrew  origin.  It 
has  regard  above  all  things  to  strict  justice,  and  to 
the  happiness  of  the  greatest  number."3  It  is  a 
point  of  honour  with  M.  Renan  to  contradict 
himself  frequently,  and  isolated  phrases  of  his 
must  not  be  taken  too  seriously  ;  but  here  he  carries 
on  the  same  idea  from  volume  to  volume,  and  when 
the  scene  changes  from  Samaria  to  the  Southern 
kingdom  we  are  again  assured  that  "  mutatis 
mutandis  Socialism  comes  to  us  from  Jerusalem."4 
"The  Jahvism  of  the  prophets  of  Judah  is  essentially 
a  social  religion  ;  its  object  is  the  reformation  of 
society  in  accordance  with  justice."5  "The  Judaism 


business,  in  that  very  bourgeois  novel,  Ohnet's  Serge  Panine,  seems 
to  have  been  taken  straight  from  this  Judaic  ideal. 

1  II.,  pp.  422,  425.  *  2bid.,  p.  438.  3  p.  54I. 

«   III.,  p.  2.  S  Ibid.,  p.  9. 


90      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

of  the  eighth  century  was  a  theocratic  democracy, 
a  religion  consisting  almost  entirely  in  social 
questions."1  "  The  party  that  supported  this  ideal 
of  religious  Puritanism  was  hostile  to  the  secular 
power  (I'etat  la'tque),  opposed  to  military  prepara- 
tions, and  would  hear  of  nothing  but  social  and 
religious  reforms."2  "Jeremiah  was  much  less 
interested  than  his  predecessors  in  the  social 
question,"3  but  he  certainly  contributed  his  share 
to  its  solution  if,  as  the  historian  bluntly  expresses 
himself,  he  was  "  the  soul  of  the  fraud  "  by  which 
Deuteronomy  was  palmed  off  on  Josiah  and  the 
people  as  the  last  Tora  of  Moses4 ;  and  Deutero- 
nomy was  an  attempt  to  put  the  new  ideas  into 
practice,  "the  programme  of  a  sort  of  theocratic 
Socialism,  merging  the  interest  of  the  individual 
in  that  of  the  collective  mass."5  I  cannot  say 
whether  we  are  to  understand  the  Levitical  law, 
framed  during  the  Captivity,  as  a  contrast  to  or  a 
continuation  of  Deuteronomy,  when  we  find  its 
object  stated  to  be  "  the  happiness  of  the  individual 
guaranteed  by  the  social  group  to  which  he 
belongs";6  nor,  again,  is  it  easy  to  see  how  the 
Semitic  thirst  for  justice  implies  egoism,7  if  ignor- 
ing the  individual  was  a  part  of  its  programme 
under  Josiah  ;  but  this  is  possibly  a  specimen  of 
the  noble  daring  with  which  a  man  of  genius  sets 
himself  above  logic. 

It  seems,  indeed,  very  hard  to  study  the  prophets 
in   a  disinterested,   historical  spirit.     For  a  long 


1  P.  41.  *  P.  96.  s  P.  154.  4  P.  209. 

s  P.  229.     The  exact  words  are:  " procddant  par  la  solidarity, 
ignorant  I' individu. " 

6    P.  427.  7    P.  496. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     91 

time  exegesis  was  thoroughly  perverted  by  the 
attempt  to  read  into  them  a  complete  system  of 
Christology,  including  both  the  biography  of  Jesus 
and  the  metaphysical  doctrines  of  his  followers. 
Then  followed  a  period,  the  last  days  of  which 
some  of  us  can  remember,  when  their  pages  were 
ransacked  for  predictions  of  a  future  that  never 
came  and  never  will  come,  or  when  the  events  of 
modern  history  were  read  out  of  symbols  that  find 
their  adequate  interpretation  in  reminiscences  of 
the  prophet's  own  experience.  It  is  said  that 
Wilberforce,  the  anti-slavery  statesman,  having 
ascertained  to  his  own  satisfaction  that  the  little 
horn  in  Daniel  meant  Bonaparte,  rushed  into  Pitt's 
cabinet  with  the  exciting  intelligence.  "  Good 
God,  sir,"  exclaimed  the  much-tried  Minister,  "  do 
you  call  Bonaparte  a  little  horn  ?"  More  recently, 
in  accordance  with  that  law  by  which  supernatural 
beliefs  become  ever  more  degraded  and  grotesque 
as  they  are  abandoned  to  a  lower  class  of  believers, 
.we  have  witnessed  that  monstrous  product  of 
ignorance,  fanaticism,  and  delirious  racial  vanity, 
the  derivation  of  the  Anglo-Saxon  people  from  the 
lost  tribes  of  Israel,  presented  as  the  clue  to 
prophetic  literature.  Scarcely  less  preposterous, 
and,  considering  the  scholarship  of  its  author,  still 
more  astonishing,  is  the  view  that  parallels  the 
preaching  of  righteousness  with  the  utterances  of 
that  sinister  press  which  begins  with  Henri 
Rochefort  and  ends  with  Ravachol.  No  doubt 
there  are  analogies  between  a  chapter  of  Amos  or 
Isaiah  and  an  anarchist  article.  Both  are  short, 
and  both  contain  violent  denunciations  of  the  rich. 
But  while  the  resemblances  go  no  farther,  the 


92      ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

contrasts  are  nearly  inexhaustible.  Let  us  begin 
with  the  most  obvious,  though  not  the  most  impor- 
tant. To  the  journalist  the  very  condition  of 
success  is  that  his  paper  shall  be  popular.  The 
prophet,  too,  had  to  draw  an  audience,  and,  as 
M.  Renan  points  out,  he  sometimes  attracted  it  by 
sufficiently  strange  methods  of  self-advertisement. 
But  he  depended  neither  on  their  plaudits  nor  on 
their  pence,  and  therefore,  unlike  the  democratic 
journalist,  he  could  speak  the  whole  truth,  or 
what  seemed  to  him  the  truth,  without  adulteration 
or  reserve.  In  this  respect  the  Neapolitan  capuchin, 
to  whom  M.  Renan  also  compares  him,1  occupies 
an  equally  independent  position  ;  but  there  is  the 
enormous  difference  that  the  capuchin  belongs  to 
a  vast  organisation  of  immense  antiquity.  He 
occupies  a  place  in  its  hierarchy,  and  is  amenable 
to  his  official  superiors  ;  he  fights  for  their  aggran- 
disement, and  his  successes  score  as  points  in  their 
game.  In  a  less  degree  the  same  remark  applies 
to  the  revolutionary  journalist.  He  also  has  an 
organised  party  behind  him,  who  shelter  him  in 
adversity  and  give  him  a  share  of  the  spoils  when 
they  win.  Any  day  he  may  be  carried  into  place 
or  power  by  a  wave  of  popular  feeling  as  Rochefort 
was  in  1870,  as  he  would  again  have  been  had 
General  Boulanger  triumphed  in  the  elections  of 
1889. 

The  great  prophets  were  essentially  independent 
of  all  such  corporate  obligations  and  party  ties, 
and  above  them.  It  was  the  fashion  not  long  ago, 
and  still  is  in  certain  quarters,  to  speak  of  them  as 

1  It,  p.  423. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     93 

an  organised  body  in  the  Israelite  or  Jewish  com- 
munity, actuated  by  a  spirit  of  jealousy  towards 
the  priesthood,  and  forming  a  centre  of  opposition 
to  its  claims.  All  such  ideas  have  been  finally 
dispelled  by  the  great  critical  discoveries  of  the 
last  generation,  which  prove  that  the  priesthood 
itself  as  a  powerful  hereditary  corporation  did  not 
exist  until  after  the  return  from  Babylon,  and  was 
then  rather  the  creation  than  the  opponent  of 
prophetism.  Schools  of  the  prophets  there  un- 
doubtedly were,  but  they  seem  to  have  resembled 
the  dancing  dervishes  of  our  own  day  rather  than 
the  great  writers  to  whom  we  now  give  the  name, 
and  who,  indeed,  included  them  in  a  common 
denunciation  with  the  corrupt  nobles  and  priests. 
Speaking  for  himself,  Amos  indignantly  repudi- 
ated all  connection  with  the  guild.  When 
Amaziah,  the  priest  of  Bethel,  bade  him  "  flee 
away  into  the  land  of  Judah,  and  there  eat  bread, 
and  prophesy  there  " — turn  an  honest  penny  by 
lecturing,  as  we  should  say — he  answered  :  "  I 
was  no  prophet,  neither  was  I  a  prophet's  son  ; 
but  I  was  a  herdsman  and  a  dresser  of  sycamore 
trees,  and  lahveh  took  me  from  following  the 
flock,  and  lahveh  said  unto  me,  Go,  prophesy 
unto  my  people  Israel."  In  like  manner  Isaiah, 
Jeremiah,  and  Ezekiel  describe  themselves  as 
receiving  individual,  unexpected,  and  even 
unwelcome  calls.  No  doubt,  like  the  journalist, 
the  capuchin,  the  socialist  agitator — one  may 
perhaps  add  the  temperance  lecturer — they  spoke 
and  wrote  as  the  mouthpieces  of  a  cause  infinitely 
higher  and  greater  than  themselves.  The  vital 
difference  was  that  they  bore  no  party  banner,  that 


94     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

they  preached  no  partial  reform.  They  were 
animated  and  borne  up  in  death-defying  courage 
and  faith  by  the  vital,  victorious  spirit  of  Israel  as 
a  nation  without  distinction  of  class  or  tribe,  and 
— mounting  higher,  further  still — by  the  spirit  of 
the  world  as  a  whole  without  distinction  of  imperial 
or  vassal  states. 

Hence  follows  another  fundamental  contrast. 
The  journalist  is  almost  always,  from  the  nature 
of  his  calling,  a  revolutionist — sometimes  of  the 
mild  and  sleepy  type  that  prefers  lying  on  the  left  to 
lying  on  the  right  side,  or  vice  versa;  sometimes 
of  the  violent  and  furious  type  that  would  turn  the 
house  upside  down  ;  but  always  a  revolutionist  in 
the  sense  of  desiring  a  transfer  of  power.  We  are 
all  unhappily  familiar  with  the  method  employed  for 
accomplishing  this  end — a  perpetual,  microscopic 
criticism  of  the  words  and  actions  of  the  office- 
holders for  the  time  being,  varied  by  corresponding 
puffery  of  their  rivals,  and  promises  of  the  great 
things  they  will  do  when  their  innings  comes,  and 
seasoned  by  appeals  to  the  lowest  passions  of 
human  nature,  to  the  impulses  of  destructiveness 
and  greed.  Far  otherwise  was  it  with  the  prophets. 
Like  true  Orientals,  they  recognise  only  one  form 
of  government,  an  absolute  monarchy,  and  their 
evident  wish  is  that  it  should  be  transmitted  by 
hereditary  succession.  I  speak  only  of  the  writing 
prophets,  not  of  those  earlier  half-legendary  seers 
— Samuel,  Ahijah,  Elisha — who  were  always 
pulling  down  one  king  and  setting  up  another. 
How  different  was  the  spirit  of  Hosea  ;  with  what 
feelings  he  contemplated  the  treacherous  massacres 
that  accompanied  the  overthrow  of  the  house  of 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     95 

Omri — massacres  evidently  condoned  or  approved 
by  Elisha — may  be  seen  from  the  name  given  to 
his  child  :  "  Call  his  name  Jezreel  ;  for  yet  a  little 
while,  and  I  will  avenge  the  blood  of  Jezreel  upon 
the  house  of  Jehu."  The  experience  of  two 
centuries  had  taught  the  prophets  the  uselessness, 
and  worse  than  uselessness,  of  merely  replacing 
one  dynasty  by  another  ;  and  they  were  deeply 
impressed  by  the  tranquillity  of  Judah  under  the 
legitimate  sceptre  of  the  house  of  David.  Nor  did 
they  believe  much  in  a  change  of  ministry.  Only 
on  a  single  occasion  did  Isaiah  interfere  to  effect 
the  substitution  of  one  high  official  for  another. 
Being  much  displeased  with  the  conduct  of  a 
certain  Shebna,  who  was  so  confident  of  holding 
office  for  his  whole  lifetime  as  to  begin  hewing  out 
a  sepulchre  for  himself,  apparently  within  the 
precincts  of  the  royal  palace,  the  prophet,  speaking 
in  the  name  of  lahveh,  recommended  that  he 
should  be  replaced  by  Eliakim.  M.  Renan  refers 
invidiously  to  this  passage  as  a  puffing  advertise- 
ment (reclame)  of  Eliakim  ;  yet  he  candidly  admits 
that,  if  Shebna  had  not  been  counterbalanced  by 
Isaiah,  Jerusalem  under  Hezekiah  would  probably 
have  shared  the  fate  of  Samaria.  We  shall  have  to 
consider  later  the  importance  of  the  part  played  by 
the  prophets  as  political  advisers.  We  are  dealing 
now  with  their  general  attitude  towards  the  com- 
munity and  the  state.  Here  Isaiah's  interference 
on  behalf  of  Eliakim  is,  as  I  have  said,  a  solitary 
exception  to  the  rule  they  generally  observed  of 
leaving  the  constitution  of  society  as  they  found  it, 
while  inculcating  on  all  classes  the  same  principles 
of  purity,  justice,  and  mercy.  To  speak  of  their 


96     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

ideal  as  in  any  sense  democratic  betrays  a  thorough 
confusion  of  Western  with  Eastern,  of  modern  with 
ancient  modes  of  thought  and  action.  Amos  and 
Isaiah  had  no  notion  of  setting  class  against  class, 
or  of  putting  themselves  at  the  head  of  a  popular 
faction  to  redress  the  wrongs  of  the  oppressed.  M. 
Renan  does  indeed  fancy  that  he  has  discovered 
the  existence  of  such  a  faction  under  Hezekiah, 
calling  themselves  the  anavtm,  or  poor  and  needy  ; 
he  quotes  long  passages  from  the  Psalter,  giving 
expression  to  their  enmities  and  their  griefs  j1 
but  here,  again,  we  see  the  danger  of  ignoring 
the  results  of  criticism.  In  the  opinion  of  the 
best  judges  the  Psalms  referred  to,  so  far  from 
belonging  to  the  age  of  Isaiah,  date  from  a 
period  not  less  than  two  hundred,  and  possibly 
three  or  even  four  hundred  years  later.  Indeed, 
M.  Renan  himself,  with  his  usual  candour,  reminds 
us  that  the  word  anavim  is  never  used  by  Jeremiah 
and  Ezekiel. 

Nothing  can  well  be  imagined  more  wearisome 
and  profitless  than  an  old  newspaper  article  ;  in 
many  instances  nothing  could  seem  more  hollow 
or  insincere.  To  this  rule  the  articles  of  an 
irreconcilable  French  journalist  offer  no  excep- 
tion. How  artificial  is  the  indignation  !  How 
shameless  the  misrepresentation  of  facts  !  How 
poisonous  the  misconstruction  of  motives  !  The 
words  of  the  prophets,  on  the  other  hand,  have 
continued  through  all  ages  as  fresh  as  when  they 
were  first  uttered,  and  even  now,  when  we  no  longer 
regard  them  as  magical  revelations  of  the  unseen 

1  III.,  pp.  41,45  sqq. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      97 

world,  they  are  studied  with  unabated  interest. 
This  is  a  point  on  which  I  need  not  enlarge, 
as  their  claim  to  a  superhuman  origin  is  now 
most  frequently  rested  on  their  marvellous  power 
over  the  conscience  and  the  imagination.  They 
have  earned  an  immortal  life  because  the  men  who 
uttered  those  words  rose  far  above  all  the  petty  and 
partial  and  transitory  antagonisms  by  which  the 
ingenious  French  historian  would  explain  their 
activity. 

M.  Renan  urges  that  the  prophets  resemble  the 
radical  journalists  of  our  day  in  the  vagueness  of 
their  charges  and  the  violence  of  their  decla- 
mations.1 Some  of  their  charges  sound  distinct 
enough,  and  are  reproduced  with  amplifications  by 
himself.  "  The  administration  of  justice  was  the 
greatest  curse  of  the  age  ;  false  witness  was  the 
commonest  thing  in  the  world  ;  thus  the  dominant 
party  held  the  lives  of  its  adversaries  in  its  hands." 
Very  true  ;  but  observe  what  follows :  "  The 
fanatical  party  (Isaiah  and  his  friends)  did  not  fail 
to  use  this  means  of  ridding  themselves  of  their 
enemies."2  Not  a  tittle  of  evidence  is  adduced  in 
support  of  this  accusation,  which  I  quote  only 
to  show  the  animus  of  the  writer.  On  two 
occasions  Jeremiah  specifies  the  grievances  of 
the  oppressed  poor  plainly  enough.  At  a  time  of 
utter  destitution  and  imminent  danger  of  complete 
national  ruin,  when  Pharaoh  Necho  had  stripped 
the  country  of  its  gold  and  silver,  King  Jehoiakim 
found  nothing  better  to  do  than  to  build  a  new 
palace  of  the  costliest  materials  and  on  the  largest 

1  II.,  p.  493.  *  in.,  p.  124. 

H 


98     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

scale.  He  either  employed  forced  labour,  or 
refused  to  pay  his  workmen  their  stipulated  wages, 
thereby  bringing  down  on  himself  a  stern  and  well- 
merited  rebuke  from  Jeremiah.  It  seems  incredible, 
but  it  is  a  fact  that  the  effeminate  tyrant  finds  an 
apologist  in  the  philosophical  historian,  to  whom 
ruinous  luxury  seems  meritorious  as  a  protest 
against  moral  rigour.  M.  Renan  is  good  enough 
to  admit  that  "  if  Jehoiakim  left  his  workmen 
unpaid  he  was  certainly  in  the  wrong,"  but  hastens 
to  add  that,  "  when  we  find  those  that  now  give 
work  to  the  people  habitually  spoken  of  as  robbers 
by  the  organs  of  the  democracy,  we  become  cautious 
about  putting  faith  in  such  allegations."1  This 
new  method  of  writing  history  savours  somewhat 
of  reasoning  in  a  circle.  First  the  prophets  are 
likened  to  radical  journalists,  and  then  they  are 
assumed  to  speak  according  to  the  same  standards 
of  veracity  and  good  sense.  The  contrast  drawn 
by  Jeremiah  between  Jehoiakim  and  his  father,  the 
great  reformer  Josiah,  gives  his  critic  occasion  for 
a  not  very  creditable  sneer.  "  Did  not  thy  father," 
says  the  prophet,  "  eat  and  drink  and  do  judgment 
and  justice?  Then  it  was  well  with  him.  He 
judged  the  cause  of  the  poor  and  needy  ;  then  it 
was  well."  How,  it  is  asked,  can  Josiah  be  called 
happy  when  he  was  killed  at  Megiddo  ?  Strange 
that  a  Frenchman  of  Athenian  culture  should  call 
any  life  unhappy  that  ended  with  a  heroic  death  on 
the  battlefield. 

Despite  repeated  warnings  from  Jeremiah,  who 
alone  had  courage  and  foresight  enough  to  speak 

1  III.,  p.  274. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     99 

unwelcome  truths,  Zedekiah  revolted  against  his 
lawful  suzerain,  Nebuchadrezzar,  and  speedily  found 
his  capital  invested  by  a  Babylonian  army.  The 
Jewish  king,  in  his  terror,  proclaimed  the  emancipa- 
tion of  all  the  Hebrew  men  and  women  who  were  at 
that  time  held  in  bondage.  It  appears  that  this 
was  no  more  than  the  remedy  for  a  grievous  wrong, 
for  the  year  of  Jubilee  was  passed,  and  by  the 
Deuteronomic  law  they  were  entitled  to  their 
freedom  ;  which,  however,  on  this  occasion  seems 
to  have  been  only  granted  on  condition  that 
they  should  join  in  the  defence  of  the  city.  The 
decree  was  obeyed ;  but  soon  afterwards  Nebu- 
chadrezzar raised  the  siege,  and  the  freedmen  were 
again  reduced  to  slavery  by  their  former  owners. 
Then  the  avenging  voice  of  the  prophet  made  itself 
heard  in  accents  of  terrific  sarcasm  :  "Thussaith 
lahveh  :  Ye  have  not  hearkened  unto  me  to  pro- 
claim liberty,  every  man  to  his  brother,  and  every 
man  to  his  neighbour;  behold  I  proclaim  unto  you 
a  liberty,  saith  lahveh,  to  the  sword,  to  the  pesti- 
lence, and  to  the  famine And  I  will  give  the 

men  that  have  transgressed  my  covenant when 

they  cut  the  calf  in  twain  and  passed  between  the 
parts  thereof,  the  princes  of  Judah  and  the  princes 
of  Jerusalem,  the  eunuchs,  and  the  priests,  and  all 

the  people  of  the  land I  will  even  give  them 

into  the  hand  of  their  enemies,  and of  them  that 

seek  their  life :  and  their  dead  bodies  shall  be  for 
meat  unto  the  fowls  of  the  heaven  and  to  the  beasts 
of  the  earth  "  (Jer.  xxxiv.  17-20).  It  is  admitted 
that  this  time  the  indignation  of  the  prophet  was 

'  III.,  p.  358. 


ioo    ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

perfectly  justified.1  Yet  one  fails  to  see  how,  on 
M.  Renan's  principles,  the  whole  story  is  to  escape 
suspicion,  or  why  the  breach  of  faith  should  not  be 
excused  on  grounds  of  State  necessity.  Meantime  I 
must  ask  the  reader  to  bear  in  mind  the  latter  part  of 
the  quotation,  as  it  will  be  referred  to  in  the  sequel. 

If,  however,  it  could  be  shown  that  the  prophets 
were  Socialists — if,  that  is  to  say,  their  quarrel  was 
not  with  the  abuses  and  corruptions,  but  with  the 
very  structure  and  foundation,  of  civilisation  as 
they  knew  it — then,  indeed,  our  estimate  of  their 
trustworthiness,  of  their  ethical  value,  and  of  their 
historical  importance  would  be  seriously  affected. 
More  than  this,  we  should  have  to  frame  a  new 
philosophy  of  history,  race,  and  religion — a  philo- 
sophy that  would  claim  for  Judaea,  for  the  Semites, 
for  monotheism,  what  has  hitherto  been  claimed 
for  republican  Athens  and  Rome,  for  the  Aryans, 
for  free  Hellenic  speculation.  So  great  a  change 
in  opinion  could  be  justified  only  by  the  strongest 
arguments.  But  M.  Renan,  after  his  manner, 
produces  no  arguments  at  all — gives  us  nothing 
more  than  repeated  assertions.  If  he  should  live 
to  write  the  history  of  Greece,  we  may  expect  to 
find  him  making  assertions  of  a  directly  opposite 
tendency,  which  will  then  have  the  advantage  of 
being  true.  For  we  are  in  a  position  to  show  that 
the  prophets  were  not  Socialists  in  any  sense  of  the 
word  ;  that  Socialism  had  never  dawned  on  their 
horizon  ;  that  it  was,  on  the  contrary,  a  creation  of 
the  Greek  genius,  and  an  outgrowth  of  democratic 
institutions. 

Socialism  is  now  generally  understood  to  mean 
the  abolition  or  restriction  of  private  property,  in 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     101 

order  to  the  more  equal  diffusion  of  wealth  and 
happiness  through  the  entire  community.1  The 
question  whether  such  an  arrangement  is  practicable 
or  desirable  need  not  delay  us  here.  The  important 
thing  is  that  we  should  distinguish  it  from  all  legis- 
lation directed  towards  the  protection  of  the  poor 
against  the  fraud  or  violence  of  the  rich,  and 
against  administrative  oppression,  as  well  as  from 
all  exhortations  to  private  charity.  A  very  little 
consideration  will  enable  us  to  perceive  that 
Socialism,  so  understood,  can  be  developed  only 
at  a  late  stage  of  civilisation.  Property  must  have 
come  to  be  clearly  distinguished  from  its  owners — 
not  such  an  easy  process  as  some  may  imagine  ; 
attention  must  have  been  called  to  the  moral  evils 
arising  out  of  its  appropriation  by  a  few,  a  high 
ideal  of  disinterestedness  must  have  been  framed,  if 
it  is  hoped  that  the  rich  will  voluntarily  surrender 
a  part  of  their  superfluities ;  or  a  high  degree  of 
concerted  action  must  have  become  possible  among 
the  poor  if  it  is  expected  that  they  will  possess 
themselves  by  force  of  what  is  wanting  to  them. 
By  a  still  harder  effort  of  abstraction,  men  must 
have  learned  to  distinguish  the  community  as  a 
whole  from  its  component  members,  and  they  must 
have  had  long  experience  of  a  centralised  adminis- 
tration successfully  managing  the  affairs  of  the 
nation,  before  they  feel  disposed  to  trust  it  with  the 
office  of  regulating  industry  and  distributing  its 
fruits  where  they  are  needed.  Only  in  the  centres 
of  Western  civilisation  has  such  an  elaboration  of 
ideas  ever  been  possible.  An  equally  important 

1  Written   in  1892.      The  word   most    generally   used  now  is 
"  Collectivism." 


102     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

consideration  is  that  entertainment  of  them  implies 
a  transformation  of  theological  beliefs  wholly  incon- 
sistent with  Eastern  habits  of  thought.  Men  must 
have  convinced  themselves  that  the  social  organism 
is  a  machine  that  they  have  created  for  themselves, 
and  can  alter  at  their  own  discretion,  rather  than 
a  divine  creation  to  be  altered  only  at  the  good 
pleasure  of  God.  The  more  primitive  faith  has 
hopes  of  its  own,  but  they  are  not  hopes  that  take 
the  direction  of  Socialism.  God  can  create  wealth 
to  any  extent ;  therefore  he  can  supply  the  wants 
of  the  poor  without  depriving  the  rich  of  their 
property.  According  to  the  Messianic  visions  of 
the  prophets,  this  is  exactly  what  he  will  do  at 
last.  Meantime  they  invoke  his  retributive  justice 
to  punish  the  rich  for  depriving  the  poor  of  their 
property.  For  there  comes  a  period  in  the  history 
of  every  community  when  this  worst  of  all  iniquities 
is  habitually  perpetrated — when  the  suppression  of 
it  is  the  one  engrossing  problem  of  human  thought. 
On  the  diverging  methods  adopted  for  its  solution 
the  future  courses  of  theology  and  politics  once 
depended. 

The  pinch  of  poverty  makes  itself  felt  at  an  early 
stage  of  social  progress.  But  the  remedy  first  tried 
is  the  occupation  of  more  fertile  land — a  process 
generally  accompanied  by  the  destruction  or  en- 
slavement of  its  previous  possessors.  When  the 
simultaneous  expansion  and  mutual  pressure  of 
the  various  tribes  has  restricted  each  within  certain 
limits,  government  and  religion  become  organised. 
Kings  and  gods  are  then  looked  on  as  a  refuge  for 
the  distressed,  and  are  freely  exchanged  for  others 
when  they  fail  to  give  satisfaction.  After  a  time 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     103 

the  notion  of  law  becomes  dissociated  from  its 
human  enactors,  and  is  placed  under  the  guardian- 
ship of  superhuman  beings,  who  are  credited  with 
the  origination  of  this  as  of  every  other  institution. 
The  divine  power,  being  plastic  to  reason,  is  thought 
of  as  perfectly  just ;  while  sad  experience  shows 
that  human  powers  are  too  often  the  contrary. 
When  the  military  class  has  become  differentiated 
from  the  industrial  class,  and  governmental 
functions  are  monopolised  by  the  former,  their 
increased  authority  is  pretty  sure  to  be  exercised 
for  their  own  profit,  and  the  more  so  as  the  king, 
whose  weight  is  ordinarily  thrown  on  the  side  of 
the  people,  sees  himself  overshadowed  or  reduced 
to  a  puppet  by  the  nobility,  and  his  jurisdiction  set 
at  naught  by  their  lawless  violence.  As  appeals 
were  formerly  carried  against  the  chiefs  to  the  king, 
so  they  are  now  carried  against  both  to  the  gods, 
or  to  God  conceived  as  the  supreme  ruler  of  the 
world.  Such  was  the  stage  of  social  evolution, 
and  such  also  the  moment  of  reflection  reached 
almost  simultaneously  by  Hesiod  in  Bceotia  and 
by  the  older  prophets  in  Samaria  and  Jerusalem. 
There  was  this  difference,  however  :  that,  as  the 
shadows  of  actual  iniquity  were  probably  much 
darker  in  Palestine,  the  splendours  of  idealised  and 
personified  justice  were  there  more  intense,  the  vision 
of  impending  retribution  more  imminent  and  appal- 
ling than  in  Hellas.  But  in  both  alike  oppression 
seemed  the  one  great  evil ;  and  no  more  appeared 
to  be  needed  to  make  men  happy  than  that  every 
one  should  possess  what  his  fathers  had  left  him, 
and  be  permitted  to  reap  the  fruits  of  his  labour  in 
peace. 


104    ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

After  this   the   paths  of  the  two   races  rapidly 
diverge.     In  the  elegies  of  Solon  we  find  much  the 
same  story  of  social  antagonism  as  in  Amos,  with 
the  same  protests  against  the  rapacity  of  the  rich. 
Solon's  touching  lamentations  over  the  Athenian 
citizens   who  were   sold   away   from   their  homes 
vividly   recall    the    organised    white    slave    trade 
between    Israel    and    Tyre.1      But    the    remedies 
adopted  differed  as  widely  as  the  European  differs 
from  the  Asiatic  character.    Solon  passed  an  ordin- 
ance relieving  the  oppressed  debtors  from  a  con- 
siderable portion  of  their  liabilities;  and,  by  giving 
the  people  a  large  share  in  the  government,  he 
guaranteed  them  against  injustice  for  the  future. 
So  much   for  M.   Renan's  assertion   that  "  social 
questions  were  severely  eliminated   in  the  Greek 
city-state."2    Had  such  been  the  case,  Greece  could 
not  have  "furnished  the  complete  model  of  a  civilised 
society."3    It  might  more  reasonably  be  maintained 
that  in  Greece  the  social  question  took  precedence 
of   every   other.     The  whole    object  of   a   Greek 
democracy  was  first  to  secure  the  poorer  classes 
against  oppression,  and  then  to  provide  for  them 
a  larger  share  of  material  advantages.     In  Athens 
not   only  was   the   principal  weight  of  necessary 
taxation  thrown  on  the  rich,  but  at  last,  under  the 
pretence  of  payment  for  the  performance  of  public 
functions,    the   poor  were   subsidised   out    of   the 
exchequer  and  supplied  with  amusements  free  of 
charge,  besides  being  frequently  settled  as  colonists 
on   conquered   territory.      Complete   Communism 
was  the  logical  outcome  of  such  tendencies  ;  and 

1  II.,  p.  427.  »  III.,  p.  43.  3  Ibid,  p.  91. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     105 

accordingly  we  find  Communism  ironically  sug- 
gested by  Aristophanes,  and  most  seriously  adopted 
by  Plato  as  part  of  a  comprehensive  scheme  for  the 
reformation  of  society.1  Religion  was  also  the 
subject  of  Plato's  most  anxious  consideration — a 
fact  which  M.  Renan  must  have  forgotten  when  he 
rashly  declared  that  "  social  and  religious  questions 
escaped  the  infantile  serenity  "  of  the  Greek  mind. 
Neither  is  it  true  that  no  protest  against  slavery 
came  from  Greece.2  On  the  contrary,  we  know, 
by  the  evidence  of  Aristotle,  that  certain  Greek 
philosophers  said  what  no  Hebrew  prophet  had 
said  before  them,  what  no  Christian  apostle  said 
after  them  :  Slavery  is  wrong,  because  all  men  are 
naturally  free.  If  we  cannot  so  peremptorily 
answer  the  allegation  that  "  Greece  did  not,  among 
her  other  great  achievements,  create  humani- 
tarianism  ;  she  despised  the  barbarians  too  much 
for  that,"3  it  is  simply  because  the  evidence  in  her 
favour,  if  adequately  presented,  would  fill  a  volume. 
Here  I  need  only  observe  that  the  Greek  contempt 
for  barbarians  opposed  no  insuperable  obstacle  to 
their  admission  into  the  ranks  of  Hellenism  ;  for, 
according  to  Isocrates,  what  made  a  Hellene  was 
not  race,  but  education.  Our  own  use  of  the  word 


1  I  am  aware  that  in  the  Republic  Communism  is  limited  to  the 
guardians  of  the  State,  who  are  necessarily  but  a  small  minority 
of  the  citizens  ;  but  in  the  Laws,  while  recognising  private 
property  as  the  only  practicable  arrangement  in  the  actual  con- 
dition of  civilisation,  Plato  pronounces  Communism  in  the  most 
absolute  sense  to  be  the  ideally  best  constitution.  And  Plato's 
scheme  is  always  criticised  by  Aristotle  in  reference  to  its 
universal  applicability. 

*  III.,  p.  91.  I  am  not  quite  sure  whether  Renan's  words  imply 
as  much.  In  form  they  are  limited  to  the  Homeric  age. 

3  Ibid,  p.  504.     Cf.  the  first  Essay  in  this  volume. 


106     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

"barbarous, "as  synonymous  with  inhuman,  shows 
how  we  identify  the  opposite  of  barbarism,  which 
is  Hellenism,  with  humanity  itself. 

The  history  of  the  social  question  in  Rome  runs 
for  a  time  much  the  same  course  as  in  Athens. 
There  is  at  first  the  same  oppression  of  the  poor  by 
the  rich,1  the  same  redress  of  grievances  through 
the  instrumentality  of  political  institutions,  and 
subsequently  the  same  wholesale  maintenance  of 
the  necessitous  classes  at  the  public  expense,  the 
chief  difference  being  that  what  was  done  by  a 
democratic  assembly  in  the  one  State  was  done  by 
a  democratic  despot  in  the  other. 

Far  different  was  the  method  followed  in  Judaea. 
There  the  prophets  sought  for  salvation  by  purify- 
ing the  lahveh  religion  from  every  vestige  of  poly- 
theism and  idolatry,  from  every  intermixture  with 
the  cruel  and  licentious  orgies  of  Syrian  super- 
stition. M.  Renan  does  full  justice  to  the  enlight- 
ened, beneficent,  and  progressive  character  of  the 
war  waged  against  heathenism  by  the  noblest 
spirits  of  Israel.2  "  In  no  Greek  city,"  he  observes, 
"was  the  struggle  against  idolatry  and  against 
selfish  priestly  interests  carried  on  with  such 
originality  as  at  Jerusalem."  At  the  same  time, 
it  should  be  remembered  that  nowhere  in  Greece 
were  those  evils  so  rampant  or  so  noxious.  How- 
ever this  may  be,  the  share  taken  by  Jeremiah  in 
the  great  conflict  of  the  higher  against  the  lower 
forms  of  religion  might,  one  would  think,  have 
saved  him  from  the  outrage  of  being  compared,  at 

1  This  remains  true  of  the  age  of  the  Gracchi,  whatever  we 
may  think  of  the  stories  told  in  Livy  and  accepted  by  Niebuhr. 
9  III.,  pp.  180-81. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     107 

least  for  one  side  of  his  character,  to  an  implacable 
Jesuit.1  But  the  experience  of  the  boulevardter, 
and  indeed  of  most  modern  Frenchmen,  stands  so 
far  from  the  prophetic  spirit  that  any  attempt  to 
illustrate  the  one  from  the  other  must  be  hopelessly 
misleading. 

Monotheism  in  the  abstract  is,  as  F.  D.  Maurice 
observed,  a  mere  negation,  and  not  more  refreshing 
than  any  other  negation.  The  first  commandment 
of  the  Decalogue,  in  dough's  cynical  version,  is  a 
particularly  easy  one  to  obey  : — 

Thou  shalt  have  one  God  only  ;  who 
Would  be  at  the  expense  of  two  ? 

The  real  value  of  monotheism  lies  in  its  relation  to 
ethics.  Unity  of  person  and  power  implies  unity 
of  will.  A  plurality  of  gods  may  pull  different 
ways,  what  is  a  virtue  to  the  one  being  a  vice  to 
the  other.  This,  as  Mr.  Shadworth  Hodgson  has 
well  observed,  gives  peculiar  interest  to  the  Hippo- 
lytus  of  Euripides,  where  the  hero  is  punished  by 
Aphrodite  for  his  obedience  to  Artemis.  A  single 
supreme  ruler  can  have  only  one  law — a  law  which 
tends  to  uphold  the  order  that  he  has  created,  and 
which,  so  far,  must  make  for  righteousness.  The 
Creator  of  the  universe  is  also  conceived  as  omni- 
potent, and  therefore  able  to  enforce  his  decrees 
by  irresistible  sanctions.  Thus  to  the  prophets 
every  calamity  that  befell  their  own  people,  or  the 
world  in  general,  was  a  punishment  for  sin.  Nor 
is  this  all.  Monotheism  promotes,  as  no  other 
religion  can,  the  idea  of  a  common  humanity,  or 
at  least  of  a  common  nationality,  with  its  accom- 
panying obligations  of  mutual  kindness  and  mercy. 

1  in.,  p.  350. 


io8     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

Among  the  Greeks  Zeus  was  looked  on  as  the  god 
of  suppliants  and  fugitives.  The  lahveh  worship 
supplied  a  common  ground  where  rich  and  poor 
could  meet.  The  foreign  cults  introduced  from 
Damascus  or  Assyria,  the  revivals  of  Canaanite 
heathenism,  or  the  survivals  of  ancestor-worship 
in  old  Israelite  families,  would  have  no  such  recon- 
ciling influence.  It  is  not  to  be  supposed  for  a 
moment  that  this  association  between  the  religion 
of  lahveh  and  the  practice  of  righteousness  was  the 
result  of  any  conscious  reasoning  in  the  minds  of 
the  prophets  or  of  their  disciples.  They  preached 
what  we  call  monotheism,  not  because  it  was  bene- 
ficent, but  because  it  was  true,  and  because  its 
observance  was  imposed  on  Israel  by  the  strongest 
obligations  of  gratitude  for  the  great  deliverance 
from  Egypt.1  But  a  connection  was  established  by 
the  logic  of  feeling,  more  potent  than  the  logic  of 
thought,  when  he  who  loved  lahveh  with  his  whole 
heart  was  drawn  through  that  high  affection  to 
love  his  neighbour  as  himself. 

In  all  this  there  was  nothing,  and  could  be 
nothing,  that  we  call  socialistic.  To  an  Israelite 
thinker  the  institution  of  property  must  have 
seemed  a  primordial  ordinance  of  God,  and  so  also 
must  the  inequality  of  its  distribution  among  men. 
In  fact,  what  the  prophets  condemn  is  not  wealth, 
but  wealth  procured  by  violence  or  fraud.  The 
Deuteronomic  legislation  is  generally  admitted  to 
have  been  compiled  under  prophetic  influence, 
however  alien  its  ritualistic  prescriptions  may  have 

1  I  am  not  assuming  that  the  Exodus  was  historical,  but  only 
that  it  was  believed  to  be  historical  when  the  great  prophets 
wrote. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     109 

been  to  the  spirit  at  least  of  Jeremiah.  Deuter- 
onomy assumes  at  every  step  the  existence  of 
private  property  and  the  distinction  between  rich 
and  poor,  and  virtually  sets  on  them  the  seal  of 
divine  approbation.  M.  Renan,  as  we  have  seen, 
has  the  hardihood  to  call  it  the  programme  of  a 
sort  of  theocratic  Socialism  ;  but  we  need  not  go 
beyond  his  own  pages  for  a  contradictory  instance. 
He  refers  with  approval  to  the  commandment 
bidding  the  employer  pay  the  hired  labourer  his 
wages  before  sunset,  "  for  he  is  poor,  and  setteth 
his  heart  upon  it."1  Evidently  the  Judaic  working 
man  had  no  thought  of  abolishing  the  capitalist,  or 
of  claiming  a  share  in  the  profits  exactly  equal  to 
the  amount  of  wealth  created  by  his  labour ;  he 
was  only  too  thankful  if  his  small  wages  were 
punctually  paid.  Nor  did  the  Deuteronomist  fore- 
see any  termination  to  this  state  of  things.  "  The 
poor,"  he  tells  his  hearers,  "shall  never  cease  out 
of  the  land"  (xv.  n);  and,  accordingly,  sundry 
provisions  are  made  for  relieving  their  wants — 
provisions  which  few  would  call  socialistic,  even 
if  they  were  enforced  by  the  authority  of  the  State, 
whereas  in  this  instance  they  were  more  probably 
rules  laid  down  for  the  guidance  of  private  charity. 
Had  there  been  any  germ  of  Socialism  in  Deuter- 
onomy, we  should  expect  to  find  it  still  further 
developed  in  the  Priestly  Code.  Such,  however, 
is  not  the  case.  The  Levitical  legislator  sanctions 
private  property  to  the  full  extent  of  permitting  it 
to  be  inherited  ;  he  regulates  sacrifices  according 
to  the  means  of  the  person  offering  them  ;  he  allows 

1  Deut.  xxiv.  14,  15  ;  Renan,  III.,  p.  230. 


no     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

the  very  poor  to  sell  themselves  to  the  rich,  pro- 
vided they  are  not  kept  in  perpetual  bondage  ;  and, 
reviving  a  very  ancient  recommendation,  he  bids 
the  judges  "not  respect  the  person  of  the  poor" 
any  more  than  they  are  to  "  honour  the  person  of 
the  mighty " — a  clear  proof  that  the  poor  were 
not  to  be  released  from  the  duty  of  fulfilling  their 
legal  obligations  (Lev.  xix.  15).  The  section  con- 
taining this  passage  is  supposed  to  date  from  the 
time  of  Ezekiel,  or  not  much  later,  and  therefore 
ought  to  show  more  immediate  traces  of  prophetic 
influence  than  the  rest  of  the  Priestly  Code.  In 
the  oldest  collection  of  laws  the  rule  runs:  "  Neither 
shalt  thou  favour  a  poor  man  in  his  cause  "  (Exod. 
xxiii.  3).  The  Deuteronomist  omits  it,  possibly 
because  in  his  time  there  was  no  danger  of  any 
such  partiality.1 

That  a  learned,  acute,  and  candid  historian 
should  pervert,  or  at  least  miscall,  patent  facts  to 
such  an  extent  is  a  phenomenon  demanding  some 
explanation.  One  cause  of  M.  Renan's  aberrations 
is,  as  I  have  already  said,  his  growing  appetite  for 
popularity.  Maurice  spoke  of  the  Vie  de  Jesus 
as  a  translation  of  the  language  of  the  Gospel 
into  the  language  of  the  boudoir.  We  have  it 
now  supplemented  by  a  translation  of  the  lan- 
guage of  the  prophets  into  the  language  of  the 
boulevard.  But  other  causes  have  also  been  at 


1  It  is  a  curious  instance  of  learned  ignorance  that  Emmanuel 
Deutsch,  the  great  rabbinical  scholar,  should  have  credited  the 
Talmud  with  the  subtle  observation  that  judges  are  liable  to  be 
prejudiced  in  favour  of  the  poor.  Readers  of  Charles  Reade's 
novel,  A  Simpleton,  will  remember  how  a  London  magistrate, 
taken  from  the  life,  will  not  listen  to  a  charge  of  theft  against  a 
servant-girl,  though  supported  by  the  clearest  evidence. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     in 

work  to  bias  the  judgment  of  the  eminent  writer. 
Regarding  as  he  does,  with  perfect  correctness, 
the  ethical  teaching  of  Jesus  as  springing  directly 
from  the  teaching  of  the  older  prophets ;  and  re- 
garding as  he  does,  with  less  correctness,  primitive 
Christianity  as  Socialism  put  into  practice,  he 
naturally  looks  for  a  germ  of  the  later  in  the  earlier 
morality,  and,  looking  for  it,  he  finds  it. 

But  it  is  by  no  means  certain  that  the  early 
Christians  had  their  goods  in  common,  or  con- 
demned the  possession  of  wealth.  No  such  idea 
is  to  be  found  in  the  writings  of  our  earliest  con- 
temporary authority,  St.  Paul ;  in  the  oldest  Gospel, 
that  of  Mark,  it  only  appears  on  a  single  occasion 
— the  story  of  the  young  man  seeking  salvation  ; 
while  the  third  Gospel  and  the  Acts,  in  which  it 
becomes  prominent,  are  considered  by  good 
authorities  to  be  idealising  works  of  later  date. 
Granting,  however,  that  the  early  Church  was 
communistic,  we  have  to  ask  under  what  inspira- 
tion the  tendency  arose  ;  and  the  answer  at  once 
suggests  itself  that  here,  as  in  other  points,  the 
influence  of  Essenism  is  apparent.  Now,  Zeller 
has,  with  great  plausibility,  traced  the  Communism 
of  the  Essenes,  as  well  as  some  other  practices  of 
theirs,  to  a  Pythagorean — that  is  to  say,  to  a 
Greek — source.1  And,  although  frequently  dis- 
puted, this  derivation  has  been  recently  fortified  by 
the  adhesion  of  no  less  a  scholar  than  Professor 
Schiirer.2  Thus  the  Socialism  of  Christianity, 
questionable  enough  in  itself,  affords  no  ground 

1  Zeller,  Philosophic  der  Griechen,  V.,  pp.  325  sqq.  (yA  ed.). 
*  Geschichte  des  jiid ischen  Volkes  im  Zeitalter  Jesu  Christi,  II., 
pp.  491  sq.  (and  ed.). 


ii2     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

for  ascribing  any  such  doctrine  to  the  prophets  of 
Israel. 

Perhaps  another  and  still  stronger  consideration 
operated  to  suggest  to  M.  Renan  what  seems  so 
utterly  mistaken  an  interpretation  of  Hebrew  pro- 
phecy. It  may  have  seemed  to  him  that  the 
demand  for  justice  so  powerfully  expressed  by 
Amos,  and,  in  a  less  degree,  by  the  prophets  of 
Jerusalem,  necessarily  carried  with  it  a  condemna- 
tion of  the  existing  system  of  property,  with  its 
resulting  inequalities  of  material  happiness.  We 
do  hear  it  sometimes  urged  that  for  one  man  to  be 
rich  and  another  poor,  when  the  former  works  no 
harder  than  the  latter,  or,  as  frequently  happens, 
does  not  work  at  all,  is  unjust  on  the  face  of  it. 
Again,  it  is  urged  that  it  is  unjust  to  pay  the 
labourer  less  than  the  exact  pecuniary  equivalent 
of  the  wealth  he  creates,  or  to  ask  interest  for  a 
loan.  Such  arguments  may  be  good  or  bad  ;  I 
have  no  wish  to  enter  into  a  discussion  of  their 
validity.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  very  few  Individu- 
alists would  accept  them.  Certainly  the  chief 
philosophical  representative  of  Individualism, 
Herbert  Spencer,  far  from  admitting  the  abstract 
iustice  of  Socialism,  would  call  it  the  negation  of 
justice.  But  on  this  point  M.  Renan  occupies  a 
very  peculiar,  perhaps  I  may  say  a  unique,  position. 
He  evidently  looks  on  Socialism  as  being  at  one 
and  the  same  time  perfectly  just,  perfectly  humane, 
and  perfectly  inexpedient.  Such  a  paradox  is  quite 
in  keeping  with  his  general  philosophy,  if  we  can 
dignify  with  that  name  his  cheerfully  ironical  way 
of  looking  at  things.  The  world,  he  has  told  us 
elsewhere,  is  essentially  unjust  (Vinjitstice  meme), 


"3 

and  the  thought  does  not  seem  to  cause  him  much 
distress.  Perhaps  it  will  be  set  right  some  day  ; 
perhaps  not.  Meantime  the  brilliant  intellectual 
culture,  the  decorative  adjuncts,  the  charm  of  high- 
bred manners  that  make  life  worth  living  for  him, 
are  rooted  in  social  inequalities.  But  Socialism 
also  has  its  aesthetic  side,  and  appeals  to  romantic 
imaginations.  Thus  through  his  very  culture  he 
can  admire  while  he  condemns  the  fanatics  who 
would  replace  it  by  a  measured  and  monotonous 
happiness. 

Fortunately,  we  are  relieved  from  entering  into  a 
discussion  of  this  alleged  antinomy  between  justice 
and  civilisation  ;  for  to  the  prophets,  at  any  rate, 
justice  did  not  mean  the  equalisation  of  social  con- 
ditions. It  meant  that  every  one  should  continue 
to  possess  his  own  in  peace,  his  own  being  what 
law  and  custom  entitled  him  to.  It  seemed  no 
hardship  to  Nathan  that  one  citizen  should  have 
exceeding  many  flocks  and  herds,  and  another  only 
one  ewe-lamb  ;  the  injustice  began  when  the  rich 
man  robbed  his  poor  neighbour  of  that  solitary 
possession.  Elijah  did  not  propose  to  nationalise 
Ahab's  ivory  house,  but  only  that  the  royal  family 
should  not  seize  Naboth's  vineyard,  and  do  its 
owner  to  death  through  the  agency  of  perjured 
witnesses.  Jeremiah  would  not  have  grudged 
Jehoiakim  the  pleasure  of  a  new  palace  if  he  had 
paid  the  masons  and  carpenters  for  building  it. 
However  strange  it  may  seem  to  the  present 
generation,  the  prophets,  and  indeed  all  good 
Israelites,  held  that  to  keep  one's  word  was  an 
essential  element  of  justice,  or  rather  its  very 
foundation.  To  the  Psalmist  the  man  who  "  walks 

i 


ii4     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

uprightly  and  works  righteousness "  is  also  the 
man  who  "swears  to  his  own  hurt  and  changes 
not."  Let  me  add  that  he  does  not  take  usury  ; 
but  on  this  point  Aristotle,  the  great  anti-Socialist 
thinker,  would  have  professed  the  same  opinion. 
Looking  back  now  to  Jeremiah's  denunciation  of 
the  faithless  nobles  who  re-enslaved  their  eman- 
cipated bondsmen,  we  are  able  to  appreciate  the 
full  significance  of  their  crime.  They  had  broken 
a  contract  made  according  to  the  most  ancient 
Semitic  custom,  by  cutting  the  sacrificial  victims 
in  two,  arranging  them  in  parallel  rows,  and  walk- 
ing between  the  severed  halves.  This  was  called 
"  cutting  a  covenant,"  and  the  parties  so  pledged 
invoked  on  themselves  the  fate  of  the  slaughtered 
and  divided  animals  should  they  be  faithless  to 
their  contract.  Next  to  kinship,  this  was  the 
firmest  bond  of  moral  obligation  between  man  and 
man,  and  eventually  it  seems  to  have  assumed  a 
higher  sanctity  even  than  the  ties  of  blood  ;  for, 
while  all  other  duties  were  placed  under  the  sanction 
of  religion,  the  binding  force  of  religion  itself  rested 
on  the  duty  of  fulfilling  the  covenant  made  on  Sinai 
between  Israel  and  lahveh. 

Emerson  has  finely  observed  that  it  is  the 
privilege  of  the  intellect  to  carry  every  fact  to 
successive  platforms.  The  things  of  the  intellect 
have  no  more  distinguished  living  representative 
than  M.  Renan.1  Let  us,  then,  grant  him  this 
privilege  to  its  utmost  extent.  Let  us  not  take  it 
amiss  if  he  smiles  with  tolerant,  good-humoured 
irony  at  our  attempts  to  tie  him  down  pedantically 

1  Written  in  1892. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     115 

to  the  accepted  meanings  of  words  ;  if  he  attributes 
our  excessive  logical  punctiliousness  to  a  lingering 
strain  of  the  Puritanism  that  we  profess  to  have 
disregarded  in  theology.  A  Socialist,  he  may 
observe,  is  not  necessarily. a  Communist,  with  a 
cut-and-dried  scheme  for  handing  over  land  and 
capital  to  the  State  ;  nor  did  he  ever  represent  the 
prophets  as  so  many  Fouriers  and  St.  Simons. 
It  is  enough  that  they  give  a  somewhat  dispro- 
portionate share  of  their  attentions  to  the  sufferings 
of  the  poor,  and  that  the  earlier  prophets  at  least 
treat  religion  and  government  mainly  as  instru- 
ments for  redressing  the  wrongs  of  the  oppressed, 
to  the  neglect  or  disparagement  of  other,  perhaps 
more  important,  considerations,  such  as  the  national 
defences,  the  adornment  of  life,  and  the  study  of 
pure  truth.  By  this  concentration  on  a  single  class 
of  interests,  and  by  the  violence  of  their  language, 
they  differ  from  the  Greeks,  while  to  the  same 
extent  they  resemble  the  modern  irreconcilable 
journalist.  Agreeing  to  use  the  word  "  Socialism  " 
in  this  extended  sense,  I  must  still  demur  to  the 
application.  For  what  we  call  the  social  question 
did  not  even  exist  for  the  prophets.  What  they 
demanded  was  the  enforcement  of  the  ordinary 
criminal  law,  the  expediency  of  which  is  no  longer 
a  question,  except  perhaps  among  the  irrecon- 
cilable journalists.  The  rest  of  us,  at  any  rate, 
hold  it  to  be  the  first  condition  of  existence  to  a 
civilised  community,  and  it  is  fairly  well  fulfilled 
by  the  modern  State.  Such  brigandage  as  the  pro- 
phets describe,  if  practised  at  all  now,  is  practised 
by  members  of  the  poorer  classes.  But  experience 
shows  that  social  order,  ever  so  well  maintained, 


n6     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

leaves  an  enormous  mass  of  human  misery  un- 
touched ;  the  problem  how  to  get  rid  of  this  misery 
is  precisely  what  we  call  the  social  question.  That 
it  should  be  asked  at  all  presupposes  a  rather  high 
standard  of  morality ;  it  assumes  that  the  well-to-do 
classes  are  seriously  interested  in  the  welfare  of 
their  less  fortunate  fellow-citizens.  But  neither 
morality  nor  religion  will  tell  us  how  to  solve  it, 
any  more  than  they  can  tell  us  how  best  to  reform 
the  Government,  or  to  organise  the  national 
defences.  Rather  must  social  organisation  help 
morality,  if  it  be  true,  as  some  insist,  that  our 
present  commercial  system  makes  honesty  impos- 
sible. In  other  words,  the  problem  is  not  moral, 
but  intellectual,  because  the  question  is  not  one  of 
ends,  but  of  means.  All  admit  that  the  welfare  of 
the  masses  is  supremely  desirable  ;  what  inquirers 
differ  about  is  the  way  in  which  to  set  to  work  in 
order  to  obtain  it.  The  Socialist  has  one  scheme, 
the  Individualist  another  ;  the  party  politician  says 
that  he  has  more  pressing  business  to  look  after. 
The  Hebrew  prophet,  could  we  consult  him,  would 
tell  us  to  be  very  good  and  religious,  and  lahveh 
would  make  everybody  happy.  He  saw  the  end, 
but  not  the  means. 

Thus,  if  we  cannot  say,  with  M.  Renan,  that 
the  abuses  denounced  by  the  prophets  are  social 
necessities,,  neither  can  we  say,  with  M.  James 
Darmesteter,  that  their  teaching,  reinforced  by 
modern  science,  suffices  to  meet  our  present  needs. 
In  the  first  place,  the  simple  injunction  of  morality, 
even  when  backed  up  by  any  amount  of  super- 
natural terrors  and  hopes,  seems  scarcely  enough 
to  make  men  good  ;  and,  in  the  second  place,  even 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     117 

if  men  were  all  individually  to  become  good,  the 
working  of  the  whole  industrial  machine  as  at 
present  arranged  would  not  necessarily  become 
beneficent  in  its  operation.  We  must  either  come 
to  recognise  a  large  residue  of  misery  as  inevitably 
resulting  from  the  constitution  of  things  in  them- 
selves, or  we  must  devise  a  scheme  for  getting  rid 
of  it  by  some  great  concerted  series  of  associated 
actions.  In  either  case  it  will  be  the  tradition  of 
Greek  philosophy,  not  of  Hebrew  prophecy,  that 
we  shall  continue.  Philosophy  teaches  us  to  under- 
stand the  eternal  concatenation  of  causes  and  effects, 
and  this  leads  to  resignation  ;  or  to  practise  the 
successful  adaptation  of  means  to  ends,  and  this 
brings  about  reform. 

The  prophetic  view  of  life  was  what  the  Germans 
call  "  unvermittelt " — unmediated — or,  to  use  a 
barbarous  but  expressive  word,  unmachined  ;  and 
the  void  the  prophets  left  was  destined  to  be  fatally 
supplied,  first  by  the  priests,  and  afterwards  by  the 
Scribes  and  Pharisees.  But  as  a  moral  programme 
it  was  complete.  No  one  virtue  is  favoured  at  the 
expense  of  the  rest.  Recent  critics  have  dwelt, 
with  excessive  emphasis,  on  their  inculcation  of 
justice  and  mercy  ;  but  the  prophets  give  quite 
as  much  prominence  to  truthfulness,  temperance, 
and  purity.  If  we  do  not  find  exhortations  to 
courage  and  patriotism,  the  reason  is  that  these 
virtues  could  take  care  of  themselves.  Like  all 
the  other  Semites,  the  Hebrews  were  ready  to  fight 
for  their  country  to  the  last  drop  of  their  blood  ; 
the  duty  of  wise  counsellors  was  rather  to  restrain 
than  to  urge  them  on. 

We  pass  to  the  charge  most  often  brought  or 


n8     ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

insinuated  by  M.  Renan  against  the  prophets, 
that  they  were  bad  citizens — factious  fanatics,  who 
habitually  obstructed  the  Government  in  providing 
for  the  national  defence.  Let  us  remember  what 
was  the  position  of  Judaea  during  the  last  century 
and  a  half  of  her  existence  as  a  kingdom.  She  was 
for  the  whole  of  that  period,  with  one  brief  interval 
of  subjection  to  Egypt,  a  vassal  State  of  the  great 
Mesopotamian  monarchy,  under  the  headship  first 
of  Nineveh,  and  afterwards  of  Babylon.  She  owed 
this  position  to  the  pusillanimity  of  Ahaz,  who, 
contrary  to  the  advice  of  Isaiah,  had  sought  the 
protection  of  Tiglath-pileser  against  the  combined 
forces  of  Israel  and  Damascus,  consenting  in  return 
to  become  his  tributary.  The  yoke  thus  volun- 
tarily assumed  seems  to  have  been  very  galling — 
at  least  to  the  Judaean  nobles,  who  were  constantly 
endeavouring  to  shake  it  off.  As  Judah  was  evi- 
dently far  too  weak  to  resist  Assyria  single-handed, 
their  invariable  policy  was  to  call  in  the  help  of 
Egypt.  This  step  was  resolutely  opposed  by  the 
prophets,  who  well  knew  into  what  a  decrepit  con- 
dition the  once  formidable  monarchy  of  the  Nile 
had  fallen,  and  how  untrustworthy  were  any 
promises  from  that  quarter.  We  may  well  believe 
also  that,  subjection  for  subjection,  they  preferred 
the  rule  of  their  ancient  kinsfolk  on  the  Euphrates 
to  that  of  their  ancient  taskmasters  in  the  Delta. 
At  any  rate,  their  advice  was  eminently  judicious, 
and  it  even  extorts  the  reluctant  approval  of  M. 
Renan,  who  allows  that,  "  on  the  whole,  Isaiah 
was  right,  notwithstanding  the  strangeness  of  his 
arguments.  Egypt  was  not  a  solid  support."1 

1  III.,  P.  14. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     119 

But  Isaiah  was  no  advocate  of  peace  at  any  price. 
When  Sennacherib  insolently,  and  it  would  seem 
in  defiance  of  sworn  treaties,  demanded  the  sur- 
render of  Jerusalem,  and  when  the  hearts  of  her 
defenders  were  failing,  the  prophet  at  that  decisive 
moment  confronted  the  emissaries  of  the  great  con- 
queror with  a  defiance  still  haughtier  than  their 
own,  and  saved  the  future  of  religion  by  his  timely 
assurance.  Here,  again,  M.  Renan  admits  that 
"the  conduct  of  Isaiah  seems  to  have  been  most 
correct."1  On  another  occasion,  when  Baladan, 
king  of  Babylon,  sought  to  draw  Hezekiah  into  a 
compromising  alliance,  the  prophet  is  said  to  have 
uttered  a  significant  warning  of  the  danger  involved 
in  such  a  scheme  ;  and  once  more  his  policy  is 
coldly  commended  by  the  historian.2 

The  part  imposed  on  Jeremiah  a  hundred  years 
later  differed  in  some  essential  respects  from  that 
played  by  his  great  predecessor.  He  had  not  to 
rouse  the  nobles  of  Judaea  from  a  state  of  careless 
frivolity  or  of  mournful  apathy,  but  rather  to  dis- 
countenance their  overweening  confidence  and 
spasmodic  energy.  It  would  seem  that  the  lahvistic 
movement,  with  its  accompanying  conception  of 
Zion  as  the  chosen  dwelling-place,  the  holy  and 
inviolable  temple  of  Judah's  God,  had  already  taken 
such  a  hold  on  men's  imaginations  as  to  inspire 
them  with  a  belief  in  its  impregnability  to  attack. 
On  the  other  hand,  the  overlord  of  Palestine  was 
no  mere  conqueror,  no  blind  destroyer  like  Sen- 
nacherib, but  probably  the  greatest  and  wisest 
ruler  that  the  East  has  yet  seen.  Nebuchadrezzar 

1  in.,  p.  107. 

2  "  Isaie  fut  encore  inspir£  par  un  politique  assez  sage  "  (p.  1 18). 


120    ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

united  distinguished  military  abilities  to  an  equal 
eminence  in  the  arts  of  peace;  all  that  later  genera- 
tions attributed  to  the  mythical  Semiramis  was 
really  done  by  him.  For  an  Oriental  despot  he 
showed  exceptional  clemency,  or  at  least  excep- 
tional moderation.  M.  Renan,  indeed,  says  that 
the  chief  men  of  Judah  were  scalped  after  the 
fashion  of  Red  Indians  in  the  presence  of  Nebu- 
chadrezzar before  they  were  put  to  death  at  Riblah.1 
The  Biblical  narrative  gives  no  support  to  this 
assertion.  The  only  evidence  adduced  in  its  favour 
is  a  figured  representation  on  an  Assyrian  bas- 
relief — as  if  the  Babylonians  had  the  same  customs 
as  their  savage  northern  neighbours!2  There  is 
every  reason  to  believe  that  Nebuchadrezzar  wished 
to  leave  Jerusalem  standing  as  an  ornament  and 
bulwark  of  his  empire.  In  such  circumstances  the 
repeated  attempts  of  her  nobility  and  priesthood  to 
shake  off  the  Babylonian  yoke  were  sheer  madness, 
closely  akin  to  the  revolt  of  the  Zealots  against 
Rome  long  afterwards  ;  their  faith  in  divine  assist- 
ance was  inspired  by  the  same  obdurate  fanaticism. 
Jeremiah,  alike  by  his  counsels  of  submission 
and  by  his  proclamation  of  a  purely  spiritual  reli- 
gion independent  of  sanctuaries  and  priesthoods, 
showed  himself  the  true  predecessor — more  than 
that,  the  master  and  model — of  Jesus.  Yet  M. 
Renan  is  so  misled  by  false  modern  analogies  that 
in  this  sober,  sagacious,  far-sighted  prophet  he 
can  see  nothing  better  than  a  howling  fanatic,  half 
a  Felix  Pyat,  half  an  implacable  Jesuit — a  monkish 

•  ill.,  P.  365. 

2  For  a  juster  appreciation  of  the  great  Chaldaean  king  see 
Eduard  Meyer's  admirable  Geschichte  des  Altherthums. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS      121 

soul  without  an  idea  of  military  honour.     In  order 

to  understand  him,  we  are  told  to  imagine  a  French 

political  writer  in  July,  1870,  calling  the  Prussians 

the   ministers  of  God.1     The   letters   that   passed 

between  the  Jewish  captives  in  Babylonia  and  the 

remnant  left  in  Jerusalem  are  compared  with  what 

we  may  suppose  the  correspondence  between  the 

transported   Communists   in   New   Caledonia  and 

their   friends   in  Paris  after  1871    to   have   been.2 

Most  probably  the  letters  from  a  Parisian  Socialist 

to  his  more  unlucky  fellow-conspirators  beyond  the 

sea  were  filled  with  hopes  of  a  fresh  revolution,  of 

a  speedy  and  triumphant  return  to  France,  of  signal 

vengeance  on  the  bloody  Versaillese.    There  were, 

indeed,  some  among  the  captive  Jews  who  cherished 

such  hopes  of  deliverance,  and  there  were  some 

among  the  priests  and  prophets  of  Jerusalem  who 

encouraged  them.    These,  however,  were  the  bitter 

enemies  of  Jeremiah,  and  nothing  incensed  them 

more  than  the  true  prophet's  advice  to  settle  down 

quietly  in  their  new  country,  building  houses  and 

planting  gardens,  as  they  and  their  posterity  were 

to  live  there  for  seventy  years,  but,  above  all,  to 

behave  as    law-abiding    citizens.      Consulted    by 

Zedekiah,  during  the  final  siege,  about  the   best 

course  to  pursue,  Jeremiah  advised,  what  was  in 

fact  the  only  rational  plan,  immediate  surrender ; 

as  if,  says  M.  Renan,  military  honour  was  nothing! 

The  historian  ought  to  know  that  honour  in  our 

sense  was  then  undiscovered,  and  that  even  now 

honour  does  not  require  that  an  untenable  position 

should  be  held  at  the   risk  of  utter  destruction. 

1  III.,  p.  289.  2  Ibid,  p.  319. 


122    ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

Zedekiah's  motive  was  really  not  honour  of  any 
kind,  but  moral  cowardice — the  fear  of  being  ridi- 
culed by  the  Jews  who  had  already  gone  over  to 
Nebuchadrezzar.  After  all,  M.  Renan  honestly 
admits  that  "  Jeremiah's  fierce  declamations,  had 
they  been  listened  to,  would  have  prevented  fright- 
ful massacres  ";*  but  his  supposed  case  of  a  French- 
man foreseeing  and  announcing  the  disaster  of 
1870  is  not  an  instructive  parallel.  France  was  no 
weak  vassal  State,  bound  by  solemn  engagements 
to  pay  tribute  to  the  king  of  Prussia,  but  an  inde- 
pendent Power,  and,  as  many  thought,  fully  the 
equal  of  Germany  in  military  strength  ;  nor  was 
there  any  danger  that  Paris,  in  the  event  of  capture, 
would  incur  the  fate  of  Jerusalem. 

To  represent  Jeremiah  as  a  religious  enthusiast, 
opposed  to  the  lay  element,  the  military  and 
political  leaders  of  the  Jewish  State,  is  an  entirely 
mistaken  view.  No  such  distinction  then  existed, 
for  the  simple  reason  that  all  parties  were  imbued 
with  religious  ideas  ;  the  only  difference  was  in  the 
relative  purity  and  enlightenment  of  the  faith  held. 
The  party  of  resistance  a  outrance  was  represented 
not  merely  by  selfish  and  treacherous  oppressors 
of  the  poor,  but  by  prophets  who  vehemently  pre- 
dicted that  the  foreign  yoke  would  be  broken  and 
the  sacred  vessels  brought  back  from  Babylon 
within  a  year,  by  priests  who  kept  shouting  that 
lahveh  would  not  permit  his  temple  to  be  destroyed. 
In  answer  to  their  chimerical  expectations  of  divine 
assistance,  Jeremiah  was  obliged  to  keep  on  repeat- 
ing that  a  people  so  plunged  in  immorality  and 

1  I".,  P.  333. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     123 

superstition  would  deservedly  be  abandoned  to  the 
doom  their  own  folly  had  incurred.  But  he  was 
not,  as  seems  to  be  popularly  supposed,  a  mere 
prophet  of  evil.  Taking  up  and  giving  a  still 
higher  development  to  Isaiah's  great  idea  of  the 
Remnant  that  was  to  be  saved,  he  trusted — as  the 
event  proved,  with  perfect  correctness — to  the  puri- 
fying influences  of  exile  for  the  filtering  out  of  a 
new  people  that  had  been  "  poured  from  vessel  to 
vessel,"  not  "left  standing  on  his  own  lees"  like 
Moab,  whose  "  taste  remaineth  in  him  and  his 
scent  is  not  changed."  Thanks  to  those  prophets 
whom  we  are  now  asked  to  look  on  as  a  subversive 
and  dissolving  force,  working  only  for  individual 
happiness  and  indifferent  to  great  public  interests, 
Israel  again  became  a  united  and  heroic  nation 
when  the  ruin  which  they  foretold  had  already 
long  overtaken  Edom  and  Moab,  Philistia,  Tyre, 
and  Damascus — if  by  ruin  we  may  understand  the 
forfeiture  of  their  political  existence.  To  say  that 
"  the  Hebrew  thinker,  like  the  modern  Nihilist, 
holds  that  if  the  world  cannot  be  just  it  had  better 
not  be  at  all,"  I  presents  an  unmeaning  alternative. 
The  Hebrew  thinker  held  that  justice  was  the 
foundation  of  all  stable  existence ;  that  when  the 
divinely  commissioned  forces,  ever  operating  for 
the  destruction  of  iniquity,  had  done  their  work  of 
denudation,  an  everlasting  core  of  righteousness 
would  remain  to  be  the  centre  of  a  new  world  of 
life  and  light  and  joy. 

One  more  charge  remains  to  be  noticed.     It  is 
said  that  the  victory  of  the  pietists  under  Josiah 

1  II.,  P.  438- 


124    ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS 

was  followed  by  a  literary  decline  ;  that  no  more 
such  works  as  the  Song  of  Solomon,  Job,  and 
Proverbs  were  produced.1  Here,  too,  we  see  the 
fatal  effect  of  ignoring  the  results  of  modern 
criticism.  There  is  a  growing  consensus  of  opinion 
in  favour  of  placing  Job  and  Proverbs  long  after 
Jeremiah  ;  and  more  than  one  critic  would  assign 
as  late  a  date  to  the  Song  of  Solomon.  In  fact,  we 
have  to  thank  the  monotheistic  movement  for  a 
great  literary  revival  succeeding  to  a  century  of 
almost  utter  sterility.  No  nation  could  have  gone 
on  for  ever  producing  such  wonderful  works  as  the 
old  heroic  and  patriarchal  legends,  the  cycle  of 
prophetic  narratives,  and  the  earliest  written 
prophecies.  An  age  of  reflection  could  do  nothing 
better  than  give  us  what  the  perfected  lahveh 
religion  actually  gave,  the  visions  of  Ezekiel,  the 
nameless  voices  of  the  Exile  and  the  Return,  the 
Psalter,  and — pace  M.  Renan — the  Book  of  Job. 

This,  then,  is  the  result  of  our  inquiry.  The 
prophets  no  more  anticipated  the  problems  of 
modern  society  than  they  predicted  the  events  of 
modern  history ;  but  if  we  desire  a  fitting  modern 
parallel  to  their  spirit  and  influence,  it  must  be 
sought  among  the  wisest,  calmest,  and  best 
balanced,  rather  than  among  the  flightiest  and 
most  feverish  heads  of  our  time.  Balance  and 
harmony  are,  in  truth,  the  most  pervasive  charac- 
teristics of  their  teaching,  by  whatever  tests  it  is 
tried,  with  whatever  order  of  interests  it  has  to 
deal.  In  the  existing  remains  of  their  discourses 
the  directly  anti-social  actions  are  not  more  severely 

•  III.,  P.  250. 


ALLEGED  SOCIALISM  OF  THE  PROPHETS     125 

condemned  than  the  vices  whose  deleterious  opera- 
tion is  less  obvious  and  immediate.  The  rights 
of  the  poor  are  vindicated,  but  without  prejudice 
to  other  rights  on  which  the  future  of  civilisation 
depended.  There  is  nothing  in  the  religion  of  the 
prophets  that  the  purest  morality  can  condemn  ; 
there  is  nothing  in  their  morality  that  the  most 
prudent  or  patriotic  statesman  need  ignore.  They 
wrote  both  for  an  age  and  for  all  time,  using  the 
utmost  exaltation  of  imaginative  sublimity,  the 
keenest  arrows  of  sarcasm,  the  tenderest  entreaties 
of  wounded  yet  unconquerable  affection,  and  the 
most  concentrated  energies  of  language  as  an 
embodiment  and  expression  of  the  highest  spiritual 
verities  then  attained.  No  minds  were  ever,  in 
T.  H.  Green's  sense,  more  truly  organic  to  the 
eternal  consciousness.  None  ever  placed  the 
divine  so  far  above  the  human,  but  none  ever 
wrought  more  surely  for  the  reunion  and  recogni- 
tion of  both  as  interdependent  elements  of  a  single 
absolute  existence. 


THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM  AND  THE 
SUPERNATURAL 

THEOLOGICAL  orthodoxy,  even  orthodoxy  of  the 
most  rigid  type — the  orthodoxy  of  the  Roman 
Catholic  Church — has  made  its  peace  with  physical 
science.  The  nebular  hypothesis,  the  antiquity  of 
the  earth,  the  antiquity  of  man,  the  development 
of  our  race  by  natural  selection  from  purely  animal 
ancestors,  the  intimate  connection  between  psychic 
and  nervous  processes — whatever,  in  short,  we  sum 
up  under  the  convenient  name  of  evolution — may 
be  accepted  and  taught  without  prejudice  to  the 
religious  belief,  whose  very  foundations  such 
theories  were  but  lately  supposed  to  threaten.  A 
cynic  might  observe  that,  if  it  takes  two  to  make  a 
quarrel,  it  also  takes  two  to  make  peace,  and  that, 
so  far,  science  has  received  the  overtures  of  her  old 
enemy  very  much  as  the  overtures  of  Darius  after 
the  battle  of  Issus  were  received  by  Alexander. 
Let  us  assume,  however,  that  the  conflict  is  at  an 
end,  or  that  the  abandonment  of  a  few  indefensible 
outworks  has  left  the  ecclesiastical  citadel  more 
secure  than  ever  against  assault.  Still,  the  con- 
flict, so  happily  concluded,  may  not  be  without  its 
warnings.  Was  it  not,  to  say  the  least,  ill-advised 
on  the  part  of  theology  to  provoke  such  a  conflict 
at  all,  and  still  more  so  to  stake  her  very  existence 
on  points  as  to  which,  by  her  own  admission,  she 
was  quite  in  the  wrong  ?  Is  the  present  moment  a 

126 


HIGHER  CRITICISM  &  THE  SUPERNATURAL    127 

well-chosen  one  for  renewing  the  conflict  in  another 
quarter,  with  at  least  an  appreciable  chance  of  seeing 
it  terminated  by  another  humiliating  surrender? 

These  are  questions  that  answer  themselves ; 
yet,  from  the  tone  habitually  employed  by  the 
accredited  defenders  of  orthodoxy  in  reference  to 
what  is  called  the  Higher  Criticism,  one  would 
imagine  that  they  had  never  been  asked.  With 
some  honourable  exceptions,  it  is  a  tone  marked  by 
the  same  curious  mixture  of  fear,  contempt,  ridicule, 
and  ignorance  that  characterised  the  official  denun- 
ciations of  Darwinism  in  the  last  generation,  and 
of  geology  in  the  generation  before  the  last.  To 
make  the  parallel  more  complete,  just  as  certain 
timid  or  jealous  or  retrograde  specialists  were 
acclaimed  by  the  religious  and  conservative  press 
as  the  only  genuine  or  authoritative  representatives 
of  physical  science,  so  in  our  own  time  scholars 
who  uphold  the  traditional  opinions  are  habitually 
spoken  of  by  the  same  press  as  if  they  had  a 
monopoly  of  learning,  honesty,  and  good  sense. 

But  among  the  controversial  devices  most  freely 
used  to  discredit  the  results  of  the  Higher  Criticism 
there  is  one  not  paralleled  in  the  old  warfare  against 
advanced  physical  science.  While  no  one  with  any 
pretensions  to  culture  ever  supposed  that  Laplace, 
Lyell,  Darwin,  Helmholtz,  Claude  Bernard,  and 
Berthelot  constructed  their  scientific  theories  in  a 
spirit  of  hatred  to  natural  religion,  and  in  order  to 
dispense  with  the  necessity  of  a  Creator  and  an 
immortal  soul,  it  is  assumed,  not  only  by  the 
vulgar  ruck  of  apologists,  but  also  by  many  among 
the  most  learned  and  highly-placed  teachers  of 
official  orthodoxy,  that  men  like  Baur  and  Renan 


lag  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

Kuenen  and  Wellhausen,  have  spent  their  lives  in 
the  study  of  the  Jewish  and  Christian  Scriptures 
only  that  they  might  destroy  the  documentary 
evidence  of  revealed  religion,  although  from  their 
point  of  view  the  disproof  was  wholly  unnecessary. 
For  these  critics,  it  is  said,  start  with  a  conviction, 
based  entirely  on  a  priori  reasoning,  that  the  super- 
natural does  not  exist,  or  cannot  be  known.  Divine 
omnipotence  never  intervenes  to  change  the  course 
of  nature ;  divine  omniscience  never  discloses  the 
secrets  of  futurity  to  man.  So,  when  the  exercise 
of  such  miraculous  powers  is  authenticated  by 
historical  evidence  that  would  be  enough  to  satisfy 
the  most  exacting  in  the  case  of  any  ordinary  event, 
the  evidence  is  rejected  as  insufficient,  or  as  anony- 
mous, or  as  of  late  date,  or  even  as  a  deliberate 
fabrication.  The  most  arbitrary  hypotheses  are 
put  forward  to  explain  how  the  narratives  came 
into  existence,  while  the  documents  embodying 
them  are  taken  away  from  their  reputed  authors 
and  assigned  in  part  or  wholly  to  late  dates,  with 
no  other  warrant  than  the  individual  caprice  of  the 
critic.  As  fast  as  one  such  hypothesis  is  refuted, 
another  succeeds  it,  and  is  proclaimed  with  equal 
confidence.  Their  production  is  limited  only  by 
the  ingenuity  of  unbelief,  which,  however,  exhausts 
itself  in  vain  efforts  to  undermine  the  "impregnable 
rock  "  of  traditional  faith. 

Such  is  the  uniform  reply  made  to  the  Higher 
Criticism  by  all  its  assailants,  lay  and  clerical, 
Catholic  and  Protestant.  One  and  the  same  note 
sounds  through  the  grave  and  guarded  admonitions 
of  Leo  XIII.,  the  smug  insular  self-satisfaction  of 
Bishop  Ellicott,  the  mild  jocularity  of  Dr.  Salmon, 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  129 

the  truculent  misrepresentations  of  Dr.  Wace,  the 
tortuous  evasions  of  Mr.  Gladstone,  the  super- 
cilious man-of-the-worldism  of  Mr.  Arthur  Balfour, 
and,  I  am  sorry  to  add,  through  the  efforts,  only 
too  successful,  of  the  dying  naturalist,  Romanes, 
to  sophisticate  away  his  own  scientific  conscience. 
Grant,  they  contend,  the  credibility  of  the  super- 
natural, and  the  Higher  Criticism  is  ruined,  the 
credibility  of  the  Biblical  narratives  restored. 

One  must  wonder  at  the  moderation  with  which 
so  irresistible  a  weapon  has  been  employed.  It 
might  be  wielded  with  equal  effect  in  other  fields 
than  that  of  Biblical  criticism.  Was  not  the 
acceptance  of  evolution  a  little  hasty?  Let  us  see 
whether  the  ground  abandoned  to  physical  science 
may  not  yet  be  regained. 

The  nebular  hypothesis,  as  originally  framed  by 
Kant  and  Laplace,  is  now,  I  believe,  universally 
abandoned.  A  spherical  body,  containing  the 
same  amount  of  matter  as  our  solar  system, 
and  filling  up  the  orbit  of  Neptune,  could  not 
revolve  on  its  own  axis  nor  throw  off  those  succes- 
sive rings  out  of  which  the  planets  were  once 
supposed  to  be  formed.  Indeed,  the  so-called  ring 
of  Saturn,  which  first  suggested  the  hypothesis,  is 
now  known  not  to  be  a  ring  at  all,  but  a  collection 
of  minute  satellites.  Nevertheless,  astronomers 
continue  to  hold  a  nebular  hypothesis  of  some  sort 
— that  is,  they  believe  that  the  stars  and  planets 
were  originally  formed  by  the  aggregation  of 
smaller  bodies.  Here,  then,  is  an  excellent  oppor- 
tunity for  the  theologian  to  intervene  and  to  taunt 
the  physicist  with  having  recourse  to  the  most 
desperate  shifts  in  order  that  he  may  escape  from 

K 


i3o  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

the  unpalatable  alternative  of  admitting  that  the 
celestial  orbs,  as  we  now  behold  them,  were  the 
work  of  a  Divine  Hand,  which,  in  the  poet's 
words,  "bowled  them  flaming  through  the  dark 
abyss." 

Turn  we  now  to  geology.  It  is  no  secret  that 
the  authorities  on  that  science  are  at  sixes  and 
sevens  with  regard  to  the  antiquity  of  the  globe, 
its  actual  consistency,  and  the  nature  of  the  forces 
by  which  its  crust  was  shaped.  But  all  are  agreed 
in  assuming  that  its  age  must  be  counted  by 
millions  of  years,  and  that  during  the  whole  of 
that  immense  period  none  but  material  agencies, 
such  as  fire,  air,  water,  and  ice,  have  been  at  work 
beneath  or  above  its  surface.  Here,  again,  there 
seems  to  be  an  admirable  opportunity  for  our 
orthodox  friends  to  come  to  the  rescue.  I  can 
imagine  them  exclaiming  :  "  You  are  struggling 
with  difficulties  of  your  own  creation  ;  accept  the 
miraculous,  and  they  will  disappear  by  enchant- 
ment. Only  prejudice  forbids  you  to  believe  that 
God  made  the  world  in  six  days.  The  story  of  the 
Deluge  is  perfectly  in  harmony  with  the  catas- 
trophic theory  of  Cuvier,  which  you  abandoned  for 
the  uniformitarianism  of  Lyell  merely  because  it 
necessitated  an  occasional  intervention  of  Divine 
omnipotence."  I  can  imagine  such  a  speech,  but 
I  do  not  hear  it. 

Many  of  my  readers  will  remember  the  contro- 
versy that  raged  some  time  ago  between  Herbert 
Spencer  and  Dr.  Weismann  on  the  question  whether 
natural  selection  alone  is  sufficient  to  account 
for  the  origin  of  species,  or  whether  it  should  be 
supplemented  by  the  transmission  of  acquired 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  131 

parental  qualities.  The  controversy  was  con- 
ducted with  conspicuous  ability  on  both  sides,  and 
other  physiologists  took  part  in  the  discussion, 
scarcely,  if  at  all,  inferior  to  the  original  disputants 
in  knowledge  and  reasoning  power.  Which  party 
got  the  better  of  the  argument  is  out  of  my  power 
to  decide,  and,  indeed,  it  is  not  yet  concluded  ;  but 
one  point  struck  me  very  forcibly  as  having  been 
established  beyond  the  reach  of  doubt,  to  judge  by 
the  unanimity  with  which  it  was  assumed  by  all 
who  expressed  an  opinion  on  either  side.  No  one 
seemed  to  question  for  a  moment  that,  however 
species  originated,  they  were  brought  into  exist- 
ence by  purely  natural  causes.  Again,  the  super- 
naturalistic  philosophers  had  an  opportunity  for 
urging  the  insufficiency  of  a  mere  physical  hypo- 
thesis, the  unreasonableness  of  rejecting  miracles 
where  their  aid  appeared  most  necessary ;  and 
again  the  opportunity  was  missed,  or  so  feebly 
used  that  public  opinion  remained  uninfluenced 
by  the  reminder. 

Among  various  explanations  of  this  strange 
anomaly  that  might  be  offered,  the  following  seems 
the  most  probable  :  Physical  science  is  understood 
to  proceed  solely  by  the  method  of  induction,  and 
it  is  as  a  result  of  induction  that  the  theory  of 
evolution  has  been  accepted  as  applicable  to  the 
whole  range  of  physical  phenomena.  Facts 
guaranteed  by  observation  and  experiment  go  to 
show  that  the  heavenly  bodies  either  are,  or  have 
been,  in  a  state  which  can  be  fully  accounted  for 
only  as  a  result  of  the  aggregation  of  diffused 
matter  moving  in  obedience  to  the  law  of  gravita- 
tion, while  opinions  may  well  differ  as  to  the 


i32  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

precise  manner  in  which  the  aggregation  took 
place.  An  examination  of  what  is  going  on  over 
the  earth's  surface  shows  it  to  be  subjected  to 
processes  of  upheaval,  subsidence,  denudation, 
erosion,  and  accumulation  of  fluviatile  deposits  ; 
the  prolonged  action  of  these  processes  would 
account  for  any  changes  known  to  have  ever 
occurred.  Other  inductive  evidence  justifies  us  in 
concluding  that  such  action  was  actually  exercised 
in  the  past;  although  the  modus  operandi  in  any 
particular  instance  leaves  room  for  considerable 
diversity  of  opinion.  Finally,  ascending  to 
biology,  the  anatomy  and  physiology  of  contem- 
porary plants  and  animals,  and  the  stratigraphical 
arrangement  of  extinct  species,  as  demonstrated  by 
geological  research,  carry  home  the  conviction 
that,  since  the  first  dawn  of  life,  no  species  has 
ever  come  into  existence  except  as  the  offspring  of 
some  different  and  older  species ;  and  all  that 
Darwinism,  or  any  rival  theory,  attempts  is  to 
account  for  this  admitted  fact.  To  put  the  point 
somewhat  differently,  in  those  sciences  that  deal 
with  the  material  universe  naturalism  holds  the 
field ;  supernaturalist  explanations  only  begin 
where  our  knowledge  ends,  and  perpetually  give 
way  as  it  progresses.  On  the  other  hand,  in  the 
case  of  documents  embodying  the  record  of  a 
revelation — assuming  that  a  revelation  has  actually 
been  given — the  relation  is  reversed.  Here  super- 
naturalism  occupies  the  positive  pole,  and  natural- 
ism the  negative  pole  ;  the  reference  to  ordinary 
causation  only  comes  in  when  our  faith  ends,  as 
the  expression  of  an  abstract  possibility,  the 
blank  form  of  a  scientific  explanation  where  the 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  133 

theological  explanation  has  been  arbitrarily  re- 
jected, and  nothing  definitely  convincing  can  be 
put  in  its  place. 

Let  us  assume  that  the  conservative  theologians 
would  accept  such  a  vindication  as  I  have  here 
suggested  of  their  very  tolerant  attitude  towards 
physical  science,  contrasting  so  vividly  with  their 
contemptuous  repudiation  of  the  Higher  Criticism  ; 
and  I  have  tried  to  put  the  case  for  them  as  strongly 
as  I  could.  Observe  what  its  adoption  implies. 
Simply  this,  that  when  criticism  employs  the 
methods  of  induction  it  is  entitled  to  the  same 
respect  as  any  other  inductive  science.  Now,  in 
point  of  fact,  the  Higher  Criticism  uses  no  other 
methods  and  makes  no  larger  assumptions  than 
any  physical  inquirer,  while  it  takes  much  less  for 
granted  than  the  conservative  theologians  them- 
selves. 

So  far  I  have  spoken  of  the  Higher  Criticism  as  if 
the  meaning  of  the  term  were  universally  under- 
stood. But,  in  truth,  there  are  many  worthy 
people  to  whom  it  conveys  nothing  more  than  a 
vague  emotional  association  of  mingled  dread  and 
contempt.  Very  often  we  find  the  mysterious 
bogey  shut  up  in  a  cage  of  quotation  marks,  as  if 
it  were  a  detected  impostor,  not  fit  to  go  at  large. 
Whether  it  is  intended  to  cast  doubt  on  the 
adjective  or  the  substantive,  or  both,  does  not 
appear.  We  may  talk  without  offence  of  the  higher 
education  and  of  the  higher  mathematics — nay, 
even  of  the  higher  theism  or  the  higher  pantheism; 
but  not,  it  would  seem,  in  any  serious  sense,  of  the 
higher  criticism.  Yet,  what  the  unfortunate  name 
denotes  is,  after  .all,  something  very  simple  and 


i34  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

very  necessary.  It  merely  means  an  inquiry  into 
the  composition,  authenticity,  and  date  of  ancient 
documents.  Such  criticism  is  called  "  higher  "  in 
contradistinction  to  the  "lower"  or  more  elementary 
criticism  which  deals  with  correct  readings  and  the 
exact  meanings  of  words.  No  claim  to  superior 
dignity  or  difficulty  is  necessarily  implied,  only 
that  the  one  criticism  rests  on  and  presupposes  the 
other,  just  as  the  upper  story  of  a  house  rests  on  its 
ground  floor. 

All  ancient  literature  is  amenable  to  the  Higher 
Criticism  ;  although,  from  the  language  sometimes 
employed,  one  would  think  that  it  had  never  been 
heard  of  except  in  connection  with  the  Bible.  The 
Vedas,  the  Zend  Avesta,  Homer,  Hesiod,  the 
Platonic  Dialogues,  and  some  patristic  writings, 
are  favourite  subjects  for  its  exercise,  often  with 
results  completely  subversive  of  pre-conceived 
opinions.  Certain  Biblical  critics  have  distin- 
guished themselves  in  profane  as  well  as  in  sacred 
literature.  Eduard  Zeller,  the  great  historian  of 
Greek  philosophy,  and  Albert  Schwegler,  one  of 
the  greatest  authorities  on  early  Roman  history, 
both  belonged  to  the  much-decried  Tubingen 
School.  Within  the  range  of  Biblical  studies, 
even  the  humblest  believers  must  sometimes 
become  higher  critics  in  their  own  despite,  at  least 
if  they  care  to  know  when  the  Book  of  Job  was 
written,  or  who  was  the  author  of  the  Epistle  to  the 
Hebrews. 

The  Book  of  Job  suggests  considerations  highly 
relevant  to  our  subject.  It  will  scarcely  be  pre- 
tended that  the  results  reached  by  a  critic  who  sets 
himself  to  determine  the  date  and  authorship  of 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  135 

that  wonderful  drama  need  in  any  way  be  affected 
by  his  opinions  about  the  supernatural.  Miracles 
are  related  in  it ;  but  the  most  rigid  conservatism 
does  not  insist  on  our  believing  that  they  actually 
happened.  The  story  may  be  a  parable,  and  not 
literally  true.  Accordingly,  when  the  higher  critics 
bring  it  down  to  the  Persian  period,  or  even  later, 
the  bitterest  intolerance  cannot  pretend  that  they 
are  actuated  by  sinister  motives.  Whether  we 
assign  it  to  the  age  of  Moses  or  to  the  age  of  the 
Maccabees,  its  doctrinal  value  remains  unaltered. 
So  with  regard  to  the  alleged  interpolations.  It 
would  be  monstrous  to  assert  that  the  critics  who 
consider  the  speech  of  Elihu  to  be  a  later  addition 
of  workmanship  inferior  to  the  rest  of  the  poem,  do 
so  because  they  find  that  it  stands  in  the  way  of 
their  private  theories.  The  question  is  one  of  pure 
literature,  of  artistic  taste,  not  of  theological 
dogma  at  all.  Of  course,  a  similar  remark  applies 
to  the  other  condemned  passages,  such  as  the 
descriptions  of  the  mines,  of  Leviathan,  and  of 
Behemoth. 

Another  good  instance  is  supplied  by  the  Book 
of  Ecclesiastes.  Not  long  ago  nearly  everyone 
believed  that  this  caustic  satire  was  what  it  pro- 
fesses itself  to  be — a  genuine  work  of  Solomon. 
Thackeray  would  have  been  greatly  surprised  to 
hear  that  his  favourite  Vanitas  Vanitatum  was  not 
really  written  by  "  King  David's  son  the  sad  and 
splendid."  Yet  few  scholars  would  now  care  to 
dispute  the  critical  verdictwhich  assigns  Ecclesiastes 
to  a  date  at  least  six  centuries  later  than  the  time 
of  Solomon.  Here  again  no  rationalistic  or 
a  priori  principle  was  involved.  Inductive 


136  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

evidence  alone  decided  the  question,  above  all 
the  late  and  debased  Hebrew  in  which  the  book  is 
written. 

All  the  Hagiographa  have  in  like  manner  been 
brought  down  to  post-exilian  times,  and  we  might 
go  through  them  all  without  finding  a  single 
instance  to  confirm  the  charge  brought  against 
criticism  of  arbitrarily  rejecting  whatever  testifies 
to  the  supernatural,  until  we  come  to  the  Book  of 
Daniel.  Here,  certainly,  are  miracles  and  prophe- 
cies of  the  most  astounding  description  which  must 
be  given  up  as  discredited  fictions  if  Daniel  is, 
what  free  inquiry  has  ever  since  Porphyry's  time 
pronounced  it  to  be,  a  Maccabean  forgery.  To 
a  Rationalist  the  prophecies  are  of  course  in  them- 
selves decisive.  But  the  inductive  evidence  is  quite 
strong  enough  to  carry  conviction  without  the 
rationalistic  argument,  and,  were  it  not  for  theo- 
logical prejudice,  would  long  since  have  been  found 
convincing.  The  charge  of  forgery  is  brought 
home  to  pseudo-Daniel  not  by  his  true  prophecies, 
but  by  his  false  history  ;  by  his  false  prediction  of 
the  coming  judgment ;  by  his  corrupt  Hebrew  ;  by 
the  silence  of  every  witness  who  might  have  been 
expected  to  allude  to  him  from  Ezekiel  to  Eccle- 
siasticus.1 

Travelling  backwards  through  the  Hebrew  Bible, 
we  find  ourselves  in  the  second  great  division 
known  as  the  Prophets,  and  embracing,  besides 
the  writers  now  exclusively  so-called,  Judges, 
Samuel,  and  Kings.  Here,  also,  the  Higher 


1  The  reference  in  Ezekiel  is  not  to  a  contemporary,  but  to 
a  very  ancient  celebrity. 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  137 

Criticism  has  played  havoc  with  old  traditions,  but 
only  one  of  its  achievements  has  excited  much 
attention  or  called  down  much  obloquy  on  its 
representatives.  I  refer  to  the  assignment  of  many 
portions  of  Isaiah,  and  more  particularly  of  chapters 
xl.-xlvi.,  to  exilian  or  post-exilian  authors.  Here, 
at  first  sight,  the  apologist  has  an  easy  game, 
and  can  triumphantly  carry  an  uninstructed 
audience  along  with  him.  "You  look  up  and 
down  the  book,"  he  will  say,  "for  predictions  of 
the  fall  of  Babylon  and  of  the  Return  from  the 
Captivity,  and  wherever  you  find  them  you  pro- 
nounce the  whole  chapter  or  section  containing 
them  to  be  a  late  interpolation  or  addition.  That 
may  be  what  you  call  scientific  criticism.  We, 
for  our  part,  call  it  arbitrary,  unscrupulous,  and 
'  tendentious,'  to  use  a  word  invented  by  your 
German  friends."  Those  who  use  such  language 
assume  the  possibility  or,  rather,  the  actual  occur- 
rence of  miracles  which  not  merely  transcend  the 
experience  of  life,  but  also  transgress  the  laws  of 
probability  and  reason.  If  God  ever  interferes 
with  the  order  of  nature  to  the  extent  of  revealing 
the  course  of  events  in  the  distant  future,  it  must, 
one  would  suppose,  be  as  a  warning  or  as  a 
consolation  for  those  to  whom  the  vision  is  vouch- 
safed, not  as  a  theatrical  exercise  of  superhuman 
power.  But  the  contemporaries  of  Isaiah  knew 
Babylon  only  as  a  subject  city  of  Nineveh  and 
a  possible  ally  of  its  enemies,  not  as  the  conqueror 
and  despoiler  of  Judah  ;  to  be  assured  of  its  down- 
fall some  two  centuries  later  would  neither  have 
purified  their  morals  nor  strengthened  their  faith, 
even  supposing  them  to  have  listened  to  the 


138  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

prophet,  which  they  most  certainly  would  not  have 
done.  But  what  gives  the  Higher  Criticism  a  solid 
inductive  basis  is  the  evidence  of  language,  and  by 
this  it  is  prepared  to  abide  in  every  instance  where 
a  received  date  has  been  changed. 

In  the  Hexateuch  we  have  a  series  of  narratives 
swarming  with  miracles  and  prophecies,  while  in 
the  higher  criticism  of  the  Hexateuch  we  have 
results  of  the  most  revolutionary  character  that 
Biblical  inquiry,  or  indeed  any  branch  of  ancient 
history,  has  ever  known.  But  neither  in  this 
instance  can  it  be  shown  that  the  criticism  was 
prompted  by  a  desire  to  get  rid  of  the  miracles  and 
prophecies,  nor  if  they  were  reduced  to  the  pro- 
portion of  ordinary  occurrences  would  the  con- 
vincing force  of  the  new  views  be  appreciably 
diminished.  The  literary  analysis  into  three 
distinct  series  of  documents  running  through  the 
whole  compilation  would  still  hold  good  ;  the 
evidence  of  Hebrew  historians  and  prophets  would 
still  prove  that  the  series  constituting  the  Priestly 
Code  was  unknown  till  long  after  the  Return  from 
Babylon,  and  that  the  Deuteronomic  series  was 
unknown  before  Josiah  and  Jeremiah ;  the  analogies 
of  legend  would  still  render  it  overwhelmingly 
probable  that  the  patriarchs  of  the  earliest  narratives 
were  eponymous  heroes  who  never  existed ;  physical 
science  and  ancient  history  would  still  prove  to 
demonstration  that  the  stories  of  the  Creation,  the 
Fall,  the  Deluge,  and  the  Tower  of  Babel  are 
simple  myths.  If  it  be  once  granted  that  these 
results  have  been  obtained  by  a  trustworthy  method, 
it  is  not,  I  think,  assuming  too  much  to  say  that 
such  prophecies  as  the  Blessing  of  Jacob  and  the 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  139 

Song  of  Moses  were  composed  after  the  event,  and 
may  be  used  for  dating  the  passages  in  which  they 
occur. 

When  Bishop  Colenso  entered  on  his  epoch- 
making  examination  of  the  Pentateuch  and  the 
Book  of  Joshua,  he  expressly  disclaimed  any  inten- 
tion of  assailing  the  credibility  of  the  miraculous 
narratives  as  such.  At  the  time  a  very  clever 
woman  observed  to  the  present  writer  that  the 
Bishop  resembled  a  man  who  should  say,  "  My 
dear  little  fish,  you  need  not  be  afraid  of  me,  I 
don't  want  to  catch  you  ;  I  am  only  going  to  drain 
the  pond  in  which  you  live."  At  the  present 
moment  the  water  is  very  low  not  only  in  the 
Hexateuch,  but  throughout  the  Old  Testament ; 
most  of  the  fish  are  dead,  and  the  rest  are  gasping 
for  breath.  Starting,  as  we  have  seen,  with  no 
prejudices  whatever  on  the  subject,  the  Higher 
Criticism  has  proved  far  more  fatal  to  super- 
naturalism  than  that  old-fashioned  rationalism 
which  was  content  to  strike  out  or  explain  away 
the  miraculous  portions  of  Biblical  history,  while 
leaving  their  reputed  authorship  and  general 
authenticity  intact.  Rather  I  should  say  that  the 
Higher  Criticism,  without  departing  from  the 
prudent  reserve  with  which  it  began,  has  furnished 
ample  materials  for  an  authoritative  judgment  to  a 
still  higher  science  for  whose  sake  alone  it  is  worth 
studying — the  science  of  historical  evidence.  This 
science  refuses  to  accept  any  story  not  intrinsically 
probable,  except  on  the  testimony  of  eye-witnesses, 
or,  at  the  very  least,  of  contemporaries.  If  a 
narrator  is  proved  to  have  made  false  statements 
on  matters  of  ordinary  experience,  his  testimony  to 


i4o  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

extraordinary  occurrences  has  no  value.  If  such 
occurrences  are  not  mentioned  by  older  and 
apparently  more  trustworthy  narrators  of  the  same 
history,  then  the  probability  that  they  did  not  take 
place  becomes  extreme.  If  two  narratives  of  equal 
value  give  inconsistent  accounts  of  the  same 
alleged  occurrence,  the  improbability  of  its  having 
taken  place  in  the  manner  described  is  propor- 
tioned to  the  extent  of  their  divergence.  One  need 
only  apply  these  canons  to  the  Hexateuch,  Judges, 
and  Samuel,  as  they  now  may  be  studied  in  the 
light  of  the  Higher  Criticism,  for  the  consequences 
to  become  at  once  apparent.  The  oldest  and  best 
"  Mosaic "  narratives  are  probably  at  least  five 
centuries  later  than  the  events  that  they  relate  ;  the 
most  recent  are  nine  centuries  later.  The  Priestly 
record  is  a  deliberate  wholesale  fabrication  ;  the 
Deuteronomist,  where  he  does  not  copy  his  prede- 
cessors, is  a  pious  romancer  ;  the  Elohist  and  the 
lahwist  differ  from  one  another,  in  some  respects 
rather  widely  ;  the  lahwist  document  itself  shows 
signs  of  being  a  disjointed  amalgam.  The  story 
of  Balaam  is  made  up  of  at  least  two  contradictory 
versions,  and  one  of  these  versions  excludes  the 
incident  of  the  talking  ass,  which  belongs  to  the 
lahwist.  Let  who  will  believe  in  the  abstract 
possibility  of  that  performance :  can  anyone 
seriously  believe  that  an  ass  was  endowed  with  a 
human  voice  in  order  to  rebuke  her  master  for 
doing  a  thing  which  he  had  been  divinely  com- 
manded to  do,  and  which,  when  he  did  it,  redounded 
to  the  glory  of  Israel  and  of  Israel's  God  ?  Literary 
analysis,  when  applied  to  the  story  of  Gideon,  leaves 
it  in  its  original  form  a  series  of  perfectly  natural 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  141 

incidents;  and  the  same  may  be  said  of  the  story  of 
Saul's  election  to  the  kingdom.  Professor  Cheyne 
has  shown  in  his  last  work  on  Isaiah  how  the  story 
of  the  moving  back  of  the  shadow  on  the  dial — one 
of  the  very  few  miraculous  incidents  in  the  history 
ofjudah — was  gradually  built  up  in  three  succes- 
sive redactions.  Of  the  Elijah  and  Elisha  group  of 
miracles  we  can  only  say  that  they  are  unsupported 
by  evidence  as  good  as  might  be  quoted  for  the 
most  extravagant  stories  of  the  mediaeval  saints. 

With  regard  to  prophecy  in  the  sense  of  super- 
natural prediction,  little  need  be  said.  As  we  have 
seen,  the  Higher  Criticism  shows  by  inductive 
evidence  that  the  Second  Isaiah  and  Daniel  spoke 
not  of  future  but  of  contemporary  events  ;  the  same 
is  true  of  the  Pentateuchal  prophecies ;  many 
alleged  predictions  of  the  literary  prophets  were 
not  offered  as  such  by  their  authors,  but  owe  their 
traditional  character  to  a  perverted  exegesis  ;  while 
the  announcements,  certainly  numerous  enough, 
of  Israel's  redemption  and  glorification  have  been 
signally  falsified  by  history.  As  to  the  pretended 
"Christology  of  the  Old  Testament,"  it  has  long 
been  dissipated  by  such  a  sober  interpretation  of 
the  texts  as  would  be  admitted  without  dispute  in 
the  case  of  any  other  document. 

I  fear  that  before  this  some  of  my  readers  may 
have  been  getting  a  little  impatient.  They  have 
perhaps  been  saying  to  themselves  :  "  Yes,  of 
course  this  is  all  very  true  of  the  Old  Testament, 
and  we  knew  every  word  of  it  before.  But  the  real 
question,  the  only  interesting  question,  is  about 
the  New  Testament,  and  especially  about  the 
Gospels.  They  stand  on  quite  a  different  footing 


i42  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

from  the  Hexateuch  and  Judges.  There  are  certain 
stories  in  the  latter  that  we  are  not  sorry  to  get  rid 
of.  The  revelation  of  Jesus  Christ  is  quite  another 
matter.  We  neither  wish  nor  are  we  obliged  to 
part  with  it.  And  why  should  we?  Because  some 
stories  are  mythical  does  it  follow  that  all  are? 
Because  the  heroic  legends  of  Greece  and  Rome 
are  worthless  as  history,  does  it  follow  that  we  are 
to  lose  all  confidence  in  Thucydides  and  Julius 
Caesar,  in  Demosthenes  and  Cicero?  Ought  not 
the  evidence  that  suffices  to  prove  an  ordinary 
event  suffice  to  prove  a  miracle  where  miracles 
were  to  be  expected,  as  in  this  instance  they  were? 
For  Christianity  is  itself  the  standing  wonder,  only 
explicable  by  reference  to  the  personality  of  Christ 
as  set  forth  in  the  Gospels.  And  then  " —  But 
this  is  not  a  dialogue,  and  I  am  not  a  thought- 
reader.  Let  me  recall  the  question  to  its  original 
limitations.  Our  object  was  to  inquire  into  the 
truth  of  a  grave  charge  brought  against  the  Higher 
Criticism — the  charge  of  preferring  a  less  to  a  more 
probable  explanation  of  the  same  facts,  because 
the  more  probable  explanation  would  involve  the 
admission  that  miracles  may  happen.  I  have 
tried  to  show  that,  so  far  as  the  Old  Testament 
goes,  this  charge  is  unfounded.  So  complete  an 
acquittal  of  the  critics  in  respect  to  so  important  a 
branch  of  their  activity  furnishes  at  least  a  strong 
presumption  that  in  dealing  with  the  documents  of 
early  Christianity  they  have  not  thrown  scientific 
method  to  the  winds.  Sometimes  the  same  men 
have  cultivated  both  fields,  as  Ewald,  Reuss,  and 
Samuel  Davidson  ;  in  all  cases  they  have  been 
trained  in  the  same  schools  and  are  animated  by 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  143 

the  same  spirit.  Suppose  it  true  that  they  have 
sometimes  gone  too  far  in  their  negations,  or  at 
least  farther  than  a  cautious  conservatism  would 
approve:  their  temerity  may  be  easily  paralleled  in 
the  labours  of  classical  scholarship  where  hostility 
to  the  supernatural  cannot  be  supposed  to  bias  the 
inquirer.  No  aspersion  is  ever  cast  on  the  scientific 
honour  of  a  Hellenist  who  holds  that  the  speeches 
in  Thucydides  are  entirely  manufactured  by  that 
historian,  or  that  Socrates  never  uttered  a  single 
sentence  that  is  put  into  his  mouth  by  Plato,  or 
that  several  of  the  Platonic  Dialogues  are  spurious. 
Not  long  ago  Xenophon's  Memorabilia  was 
generally  accepted  as  a  genuine  account  of  the 
Socratic  teaching.  Several  portions  of  it  are  now 
suspected  to  be  very  far  from  deserving  that 
character,  yet  no  outcry  has  been  raised. 

Again,  it  is  entirely  unwarrantable  to  assert,  as 
Dr.  Salmon  does,1  that  critics  who  disbelieve  in 
the  supernatural  are  on  that  account  interested  in 
denying  the  authenticity  of  the  books  where 
miracles  are  related.  I  should  like  to  ask  Dr. 
Salmon,  or  any  other  orthodox  Protestant  divine, 
whether  he  believes  in  the  miraculousness  of  that 
extraordinary  series  of  cures  related  in  full  detail 
by  St.  Augustine  at  the  end  of  his  treatise  De 
Civitate  Dei,  and,  if  not,  whether  his  incredulity 
has  ever  inclined  him  to  reject  the  treatise  itself,  or 
this  particular  part  of  it,  as  a  forgery.  I  have  little 
doubt  that  he  would  manage  to  combine  the  most 
absolute  disbelief  in  the  miracles  as  such  with  the 
most  unhesitating  acceptance  of  the  record  as 

1  Historical  Introduction  to  the  Books  of  the  New  Testament,  p.  8. 


144  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

coming  from  the  pen  of  the  great  Father.  At  any 
rate,  if  I  cannot  answer  for  Dr.  Salmon,  I  can 
answer  for  the  higher  critics.  If  the  evidence  of 
eye-witnesses  could  convert  rationalists  to  a  belief 
in  miracles,  incredulity  on  this  point  would  long 
ago  have  ceased  to  trouble  the  apologist,  and 
Protestantism  would  have  ceased  to  trouble  Rome. 
But,  as  I  have  said  before,  there  are  miracles 
that  the  Higher  Criticism  does  reject  in  a  very 
summary  manner — miracles  that  would  be  wonders 
without  being  signs ;  miracles  that,  so  far  from 
being  of  any  evidentiary  value,  would,  if  they  were 
established,  be  the  destruction  of  all  logical  evidence 
whatsoever ;  miracles  that  are  a  derogation,  not 
from  the  course  of  nature,  but  from  the  laws  of 
reason.  Now  these  are  miracles  that  apologetic 
orthodoxy  accepts,  and  attacks  the  critics  for  not 
accepting.  If  the  story  of  the  Virgin-birth  were 
true,  how  could  two  such  inconsistent  accounts  of 
it  as  those  given  by  the  first  and  the  third  Evan- 
gelist both  be  current  in  the  early  decades  of 
Christian  history?  How  could  St.  Paul  not  know 
it ;  or,  knowing,  not  allude  to  it?  If  the  raising  of 
Lazarus  is  a  historical  event,  how  could  it  escape 
the  notice  of  the  Synoptics?  How  could  the  same 
teacher  deliver  to  the  same  audience  during  the 
same  period  discourses  differing  so  widely,  both  in 
form  and  matter,  as  the  speeches  of  Jesus  in  the 
First  or  Third  and  those  in  the  Fourth  Gospel? 
How  could  one  so  gifted  with  supernatural  pre- 
science as  to  foretell  the  circumstances  of  the  siege 
and  capture  of  Jerusalem  in  the  minute  detail  of 
the  Third  Gospel,  be  so  utterly  mistaken  as  to 
declare,  in  the  words  of  the  Second  Gospel,  that 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  145 

the  end  of  the  world  would  come  within  the  life- 
time of  some  who  were  then  born  (Mark  xiii.  30)  ? 
Surely  modern  criticism  is  entirely  within  its  rights 
when,  just  as  in  the  case  of  Daniel,  it  uses  these 
two  predictions,  one  fabricated  and  the  other  falsi- 
fied, to  place  "  St.  Mark  "  and  "  St.  Luke  "  at  such 
a  distance  from  the  events  they  record  as  to  take 
them  out  of  the  category  of  eye-witnesses,  or  even 
of  those  who  derived  their  information  from  eye- 
witnesses. 

The  question  whether  the  Fourth  Gospel  was  or 
was  not  written  by  St.  John  is  often  ignorantly  or 
wilfully  confused  with  a  quite  different  question — 
the  value  of  Baur's  theory  as  to  the  evolution  of 
primitive  Christianity.     In  reality  the  two  are  quite 
distinct.     First,  the  untrustworthiness  of  the  gospel 
was  proved.     Then  and  only  then  did  there  arise 
the  necessity  of  asking  when  and  where  and  by 
whom  was  it  written.     It  would  no  doubt  be  highly 
satisfactory  if  these   points   could   be  cleared  up. 
But  no  constructive  solution  of  the  problem  could 
add  to  the  real  strength  of  the  destructive  criticism 
which    it    necessarily   presupposes,    nor    can    the 
fragility  of  any  particular  solution  take  away  from 
that    strength.     As   to   the    Tubingen    theory,    it 
probably   retains  as    much    value    as    any   other 
scientific    theory  that   has    now  been   before  the 
world  for  fifty  years.     Let  it  not  be  supposed  that 
science  alone  shares  with  woman  the  privilege  of 
changing    her    mind.     Orthodoxy   changes    also. 
Compare  Lux  Mundi  with  Aids  to  Faith;  compare 
the  present  attitude  of  Rome  towards  the  higher 
criticism  of  the  Old  Testament  with  her  attitude 
in    Kenan's    youth.      Of    course    I    know    what 

L 


:46  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

orthodox  theologians  will  say.  They  have  dis- 
covered that  propositions  once  supposed  to  be  de 
fide  are  really  open  questions.  But  that  is  enough. 
The  definition  of  faith  changes  with  startling 
rapidity,  and  perhaps  we  have  not  yet  reached  the 
limit  of  its  transformations. 

We  have  seen  that  the  higher  criticism  of  the 
Old  Testament,  although  it  did  not  begin  by  deny- 
ing the  miraculous,  ended  by  denying  it,  or  rather 
by  leaving  the  science  of  historical  evidence  free  to 
deny  it.  What,  then,  it  may  be  asked,  is  the  result 
towards  which  New  Testament  criticism  points? 
It  seems  to  me  that  the  final  verdict  must  be  the 
same.  That  miracles  should  go  on  increasing  in 
magnitude,  the  farther  we  go  from  the  place  and 
time  of  their  alleged  occurrence,  is  a  circumstance 
that  cannot  fail  to  awaken  suspicion.  Now  the 
miracles  of  the  Fourth  Gospel  are  the  most  astound- 
ing of  all,  and  are  related  with  the  strongest 
emphasis  on  their  supernatural  character  and  on 
their  evidentiary  value  as  manifestations  of  the 
divine  omnipotence.  There  is  something  particu- 
larly Hellenic  about  the  writer's  consciousness  in 
this  respect — his  extreme  anxiety  to  differentiate  the 
miraculous  sign  from  the  ordinary  course  of  nature, 
and  to  surround  it  with  every  guarantee  of  authen- 
ticity. What  we  find  is  a  wise  economy,  not,  as 
with  the  Synoptics,  a  rank  profusion  of  marvels. 
There  are  no  cases  of  diabolical  possession,  because 
the  Fourth  Evangelist,  believing  though  he  did  in 
a  supreme  power  of  evil,  belonged  to  a  society  that 
was  too  philosophical  to  explain  epilepsy  and 
hysteria,  as  the  lowest  savage  might,  by  the 
presence  of  malignant  spirits.  Now  it  is  just  this 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  147 

gospel  that  criticism,  for  quite  other  reasons, 
considers  last  in  order  of  time,  and  in  the  order 
of  ideas  most  remote  from  Jewish  or  Palestinian 
habits  of  thought. 

Criticism  has  disengaged  from  the  Acts  of  the 
Apostles  a  contemporary  document  of  high  value, 
supposed  to  be  written  by  a  companion  of  St.  Paul, 
and  known  as  the  "  we-source  ";  it  has  also  sub- 
jected the  earlier  portions  of  the  book  to  a  searching 
comparison  with  the  parallel  narratives  contained 
in  the  genuine  epistles  of  St.  Paul  himself.  Con- 
fining our  attention  to  the  supernatural,  we  find 
least  of  it  (if,  indeed,  there  be  any)  in  the  "we- 
source,"  and  most  in  the  legendary  narratives 
bearing  marks  of  a  comparatively  late  origin  ; 
while  the  Pentecostal  gift  of  tongues,  which  in 
Acts  offers  such  an  extraordinary  spectacle  of 
divine  power,  shrinks  in  St.  Paul  to  a  performance 
very  much  on  a  level  with  the  phenomena  of  the 
Irvingite  church. 

On  grounds  of  literary  analysis,  criticism  declares 
the  Second  Gospel  to  be  the  oldest  of  the  Synoptics. 
But  this  document  has  nothing  about  the  virgin- 
birth  of  Jesus,  and,  when  freed  of  later  additions, 
nothing  about  the  Ascension.  According  to  it, 
Jesus  died  with  an  exclamation  of  despair  on  his 
lips  quite  incompatible  with  the  prevision  of  his 
speedy  return  to  life.  His  reported  refusal  to  work 
miracles  is  probably  authentic,  as  there  would  have 
been  no  reason  for  inventing  it  at  a  time  when 
thaumaturgic  powers  were  freely  attributed  to  him  ; 
and  we  can  still  see  how  his  appeal  to  the  "  sign  of 
the  prophet  Jonah  "  was  afterwards  apologetically 
corrected  into  a  prediction  of  his  own  death,  burial, 


148  THE  HIGHER  CRITICISM 

and  resurrection.  The  words  "  three  days  and 
three  nights  in  the  heart  of  the  earth,"  by  the  way, 
point  to  a  variation  of  the  resurrection-story  not 
otherwise  recognised  in  our  gospels. 

My  object  in  the  foregoing  pages  has  not  been  to 
defend  the  methods  and  results  of  the  higher  Biblical 
criticism,  nor  even,  except  in  the  briefest  manner, 
to  recapitulate  them.  Nor  have  I  attempted  to 
discuss  the  general  problem  of  the  supernatural  in 
its  relations  to  the  order  of  nature.  My  object  has 
been  to  show  the  hollowness,  if  not  the  insincerity, 
of  a  plea  put  forward  for  the  purpose  of  suppressing 
discussion  by  denying  the  right  of  rationalistic 
critics  to  speak  at  all  about  subjects  to  which  they 
have  devoted  their  lives.  At  the  same  time,  I  have 
suggested  the  motive  that  lies  at  the  bottom  of  this 
discreditable  attempt.  Beyond  doubt,  many, 
perhaps  most,  of  the  higher  critics  disbelieve  in 
miracles  and  supernatural  predictions.  I  will  go 
further  still  and  freely  grant  that  with  some  of 
them,  such  as  Strauss,  Renan,  and  Mr.  Walter 
Cassels  (the  author  of  Supernatural  Religion),  the 
denial  is  based  on  philosophical  considerations. 
But  Renan,  at  any  rate,  combined  for  many  years 
with  his  absolute  disbelief  in  miracles  a  belief  that 
the  gospels  were  written  by  the  men  whose  names 
they  bear  ;  and  when  he  partially  abandoned  this 
position,  it  was  under  the  stress  of  historical,  not 
of  philosophical,  arguments.  Now  this  is  just  what 
the  enemies  of  criticism  find  so  irritating — that  the 
evidence  of  history  is  turning  against  them  ;  that 
the  documents,  when  scientifically  investigated, 
should,  as  it  were,  of  themselves,  fall  into  a  pro- 
gressive series  exhibiting  more  and  more  of  the 


AND  THE  SUPERNATURAL  149 

supernatural  the  farther  removed  they  are  from  the 
original  events,  and  a  decline  of  truthfulness  going 
along  with  an  increase  of  intellectual  culture  in  the 
narrators  the  farther  removed  they  are  from  the 
original  eye-witnesses.  Such  is  the  power  and 
flexibility  of  modern  philosophy  that,  once  released 
from  the  necessity  of  verification,  it  can  be  made 
to  prove  or  disprove  anything.  So  the  modern 
apologist  flies  to  speculation  whenever  he  has  the 
chance,  in  the  hope  that  his  ark  of  faith  may  ride 
triumphant  on  a  deluge  of  scepticism. 

Verachte  nur  Vernunft  und  Wissenschaft, 
Des  Menschen  allerhochste  Kraft, 
So  hab'  ich  dich  ! 

said  Mephistopheles  a  hundred  and  twenty  years 
ago.  The  new  Mephistopheles,  disguised  as  an 
angel  of  light,  sees  in  historical  reason  and  historical 
science  alone  the  barrier  that  separates  him  from 
his  victims.  "Thank  heaven  we  have  got  rid  of 
history !"  a  Jesuit  Father  is  reported  to  have 
exclaimed  when  Papal  Infallibility  was  voted.  His 
Protestant  brother  would  gladly  get  rid  of  it  also. 
As  good  a  device  for  the  purpose  as  any  other  is  to 
damage  the  reputation  of  the  laborious  inquirers 
who  clear  the  way  for  true  history  and  accumulate 
the  materials  for  its  edifice ;  to  substitute  for  the 
decisive  issues  of  experience  the  interminable 
wrangles  of  metaphysics  ;  above  all,  to  convert  an 
appeal  to  reason  into  an  appeal  to  authority. 
Perhaps  there  would  be  a  good  case  for  anyone 
who  chose  to  maintain  that  there  is  a  greater  weight 
of  learning  and  ability  and  disinterestedness  on  the 
progressive  side.  But  we  have  no  wish  to  exchange 
one  bondage  for  another.  Our  object  is  not  that 


ISO    HIGHER  CRITICISM  &  THE  SUPERNATURAL 

the  Higher  Criticism  should  be  reverenced,  but  that 
it  should  be  read.  Doubtless  the  official  apologists 
will  say  that  in  this  respect  they  have  done  their 
duty.  Let  them  then  prove  their  familiarity  with 
the  arguments  of  their  opponents  by  fair  statements 
and  fair  replies,  not  by  confusing  the  outcome  of 
an  inquiry  with  the  assumptions  from  which  it  sets 
out. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER1 

A  CERTAIN  rustic  moralist  in  Mr.  Thomas  Hardy's 
Far  from  the  Madding  Crowd  gives  his  opinion 
about  the  relative  chances  of  salvation  contingent 
on  attending  church  or  chapel  in  the  following 
homely  but  telling  terms  : — 

"  We  know  very  well  that  if  anybody  goes  to 
heaven  they  [chapel-folk]  will.  They've  worked 
hard  for  it  and  they  deserve  to  have  it,  such  as  'tis. 
I'm  not  such  a  fool  as  to  pretend  that  we  who 
stick  to  the  church  have  the  same  chance  as  they, 
because  we  know  we  have  not.  But  I  hate  a  feller 
who'll  change  his  old  ancient  doctrine  for  the  sake 
of  getting  to  heaven." 

So  far  the  excellent  Coggan,  for  such  is  the  name 
of  Mr.  Hardy's  pot-house  philosopher.  Whether 
churchmen  or  dissenters  should  be  credited  with 
the  better  chance  of  salvation  is  a  deep  question 
in  which  I  do  not  now  propose  to  enter.  The 
Conformist  and  the  Nonconformist  conscience  may 
safely  be  left  to  take  care  of  themselves.  But  the 
ingenuous  confidences  of  this  particular  churchman 
suggest  a  problem  of  wider  interest  on  which  I 

1  A  remarkable  passage  in  Dr.  McTaggart's  work  entitled 
Some  Dogmas  of  Religion  (pp.  213-16)  presents  so  close  a  parallel 
with  one  of  the  arguments  put  forth  in  the  following  pages  that 
I  might  incur  the  charge  of  borrowing  without  acknowledgment 
were  the  fact  not  mentioned  that  my  essay  was  originally 
published  in  the  International  Journal  of  Ethics  for  April,  1905, 
a  year  before  the  appearance  of  the  work  referred  to,  and  that 
Dr.  McTaggart  had  certainly  read  it,  as  is  proved  by  the 
quotation  from  Pascal  on  p.  213  of  his  book. 


iS2  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

propose  to  offer  a  few  remarks.  Is  there  any 
method  of  salvation  that  may  be  called  distinctly 
mean  ?  I  believe  there  is  at  least  one  such,  and  I 
am  sorry  to  say  that  it  is  a  method  recommended 
by  no  less  an  authority  than  Pascal. 

What  the  French  call  " le  pari  de  Pascal" — in 
English,  Pascal's  wager  or  bet — forms  the  theme 
of  one  of  the  most  celebrated  passages  in  his 
fragmentary  defence  of  Christianity,  published 
after  his  death  and  universally  known  as  the 
Pensdes.  A  very  elaborate  edition  of  this  work, 
filling  three  large  volumes  in  the  great  series  of 
French  classics,  which  is  one  of  the  glories  of 
French  bibliography,  has  recently  appeared.1 
Nearly  the  whole  of  the  first  volume  is  occupied  by 
an  elaborate  Introduction,  in  which  all  the  literary 
facts  necessary  for  the  full  understanding  of 
Pascal's  position  are  brought  together.  Then 
comes  a  presumably  immaculate  text  accompanied 
by  an  ample  array  of  critical  and  explanatory  notes, 
the  Thoughts  themselves  being  so  arranged  in 
sections  as  to  exhibit  themselves  to  the  best  logical 
advantage  ;  and  the  whole  is  completed  by  what  is 
rare  in  French  books,  an  excellent  index.  So  far 
as  externals  go,  we  cannot  expect  that  this  splendid 
and  sombre  genius  will  ever  make  a  better  appear- 
ance before  the  world  than  in  M.  Leon  Brunschvicg's 
edition. 

Pascal's  apologetics  are  as  obsolete  as  his  satire 
on  the  Jesuits  is  fresh  and  living.  The  Higher 
Criticism  has  ruined  his  theory  of  Christian 
evidences.  Evolution  has  ruined  his  theory  of  the 

1  The  references  in  this  essay  are  to  this  edition. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  153 

Fall.  And  what  some  modern  mathematicians 
defend  with  arguments  no  more  solid  than  his 
would  not  have  been  recognised  by  him  as  the  true 
faith.  But  one,  at  least,  of  his  points  has  secured 
an  undying  literary  interest  from  the  extraordinary 
energy  and  passion  with  which  the  case  is  put 
rather  than  from  any  peculiar  ingenuity  or  origin- 
ality in  the  thought  itself.  This  is  the  argument 
of  the  wager  to  which  I  have  already  referred. 

It  runs  as  follows.  Speaking  by  the  light  of 
nature,  says  Pascal,  God,  supposing  him  to  exist, 
must  be  out  of  relation  to  ourselves.  Being 
without  parts  or  limits,  he  is  infinitely  incomprehen- 
sible. We  can  neither  know  what  he  is,  nor  even 
that  he  is.  This  admission  goes  beyond  that  form 
of  modern  Agnosticism  according  to  which  we 
can  say  with  certainty  that  the  Unknowable  exists, 
but  not  what  it  is.  And,  of  course,  it  goes  very 
far  beyond  Herbert  Spencer's  affirmation  of  an 
Unknowable  which  is  infinite,  eternal,  an  energy, 
and  the  cause  of  all  things.  But  we  are  not  to 
take  so  sceptical  a  confession  as  defining  Pascal's 
own  position.  Being  a  Christian,  he  has  other 
sources  of  information  than  the  light  of  nature. 
His  supposed  sceptic — who  turns  out  to  be  a  very 
real  sceptic  with  a  place  in  French  literary  history 
— has  none.  But  the  sceptic's  ignorance  cuts  both 
ways.  It  leaves  the  non-existence  of  God  as  un- 
certain as  his  existence.  Reason  supplies  no 
means  of  choosing  between  the  two  alternative 
possibilities.  Nevertheless,  we  are  obliged  to  back 
one  side  or  the  other,  to  play  at  a  game  of  hazard 
in  which,  at  an  infinite  distance,  heads  or  tails  will 
turn  up.  "  But,"  answers  the  sceptic,  "  I  do  not 


154  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

want  to  play  at  all ;  in  such  a  doubtful  case  as  what 
you  describe  prudence  bids  us  abstain."  To  which 
Pascal  replies  :  "  You  must  bet ;  you  are  in  for  it ; 
it  does  not  depend  on  your  will."  For  as  his  Port 
Royalist  editors  put  it,  in  an  elucidatory  addition 
to  the  text,  "  Not  to  bet  is  to  bet  for  the  non- 
existence  of  God." 

Plato  observes,  in  the  Republic,  that  he  "  hardly 
ever  met  a  mathematician  who  could  reason " 
(531  E).  So,  at  least,  Jowett  translates  the  passage 
— not,  perhaps,  without  a  spice  of  malice.  Accord- 
ing to  some,  the  word  he  uses  (StaAeKrticot)  does 
not  exactly  imply  what  we  mean  by  ability  to 
reason.  But  I  think  it  will  be  admitted  to  imply 
the  power  so  signally  displayed  by  Plato  himself 
in  the  Parmenides — the  power,  that  is,  of  exhaus- 
tively enumerating  the  possible  issues  in  a  given 
question,  and  of  deducing  the  necessary  conse- 
quences in  each  instance.  And  it  seems  to  me 
that,  whatever  may  be  the  case  with  modern 
mathematicians  as  a  class,  Pascal  shows  himself 
remarkably  deficient  in  that  sort  of  dialectical 
ability — so  much  so,  indeed,  as  to  ruin  the  basis 
of  his  whole  argument  at  the  very  start.  The 
deficiency  may  or  may  not  be  connected  with 
his  great  mathematical  genius ;  anyhow  it  is 
there. 

Why  must  I  bet  ?  No  reason  whatever  is  given, 
but  it  needs  only  a  very  slight  acquaintance  with 
the  dogmatic  Christianity  of  Pascal's  time  to  supply 
what  he  leaves  unsaid.  To  be  saved  man  must 
believe  positively  in  the  existence  of  God  ;  to  leave 
it  an  open  question  is  to  incur  the  same  penalty  as 
complete  atheism — that  is,  eternal  damnation. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  155 

Here  we  come  at  once  on  a  flagrant  self-contra- 
diction, which,  even  if  it  stood  alone,  would  leave 
the  sceptic  triumphant.  Pascal  began  by  saying 
that  God,  as  infinite,  is  unrelated  to  us  (il  n'  a  nul 
rapport  a  nous).  But,  if  so,  he  can  neither  save 
nor  damn  us  :  our  future  fate  has  nothing  to  do 
with  his  existence  or  non-existence,  still  less  with 
our  opinion  or  absence  of  opinion  on  the  subject. 

I  do  not  profess  to  know  much  about  the  turf ; 
but  I  strongly  suspect  that  anyone  who  had  such 
loose  notions  as  Pascal  about  the  laws  of  betting, 
if  he  acted  on  them,  would  soon  be  cleared  out  of 
every  penny  he  possessed — that  is,  supposing  his 
ignorance  to  be  real  ;  while,  if  it  were  assumed  for 
the  purpose  of  eluding  payment,  he  would  before 
long  find  himself  turned  off  every  race-course  in 
England. 

However,  we  will  let  that  pass.  We  will 
suppose  that  the  words  "  out  of  relation  "  slipped 
in  by  an  unfortunate  oversight,  and  would  have 
been  deleted  had  the  author  lived  to  see  his  work 
through  the  press  ;  noting,  however,  that  they 
were  allowed  to  stand  by  the  logicians  of  Port 
Royal,  who  otherwise  made  free  enough  with  his 
manuscript.  Let  it  be  granted  as  not  impossible 
that  the  infinite  Being,  if  he  exist,  is  no  other  than 
the  God  of  Catholicism.  But  there  is  a  long  way 
from  possibility  to  certainty,  and  Pascal  himself 
has  warned  us  that  the  knowledge,  if  any,  of  God's 
existence  is  quite  distinct  from  the  knowledge  of 
his  attributes.  Assuming  there  to  be  a  God,  that 
bare  fact  leaves  us  in  absolute  ignorance  about  his 
character.  Now  it  might  fairly  be  contended  that 
the  number  of  different  characters  which  may 


156  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

possibly  be  ascribed  to  an  infinite  being  is  infinite, 
and  even  infinite  in  the  second  degree  on  account 
of  the  possible  permutations  and  combinations  of 
attributes.  Accordingly,  the  conditions  of  the 
wager  must  be  altered.  Pascal  has  appealed  to 
the  light  of  reason,  and  to  reason  he  must  go. 
Apart  from  objective  evidence,  of  which  there  is 
at  present  no  question,  the  chances  against  his 
theology's  being  true  are  at  least  infinity  to  one. 

It  is,  however,  on  the  cards  that  Pascal,  admit- 
ting so  much,  might  still  maintain  that  a  man  of 
sense  was  justified  in  staking  his  life  on  the  exist- 
ence of  God.  In  order  to  make  this  clear  we  must 
examine  the  conditions  of  the  wager. 

"  If  you  win,"  he  tells  us,  "  you  win  everything  ; 
if  you  lose,  you  lose  nothing."  In  the  more  con- 
crete language  of  religious  belief,  if  there  is  a  God 
and  you  have  faith  in  his  promises  you  gain  ever- 
lasting felicity ;  if  there  is  no  God,  death  ends  all. 
It  is  not  precisely  explained  what  is  meant  by 
staking  your  life;  but,  as  Pascal  is  addressing  him- 
self to  a  careless  worldling,  he  must  be  supposed 
to  mean  what  such  a  person  would  call  "  life  " — that 
is  to  say,  an  existence  of  sensual  and  social  enjoy- 
ment. The  author  of  the  Thoughts  would  not  admit 
that  the  abandonment  of  such  a  life  involved  any 
real  sacrifice ;  and  so  far  the  serious  moralist  of 
any  religion  or  of  no  religion  would  not  be  disposed 
to  quarrel  with  him.  But  in  fact,  as  we  shall  see 
presently,  there  is  much  more  involved — certainly 
more  than  the  sage  who  finds  life  "very  tolerable 
without  its  amusements  "  is  prepared  to  give  up. 

Of  course  no  Christian,  and  Pascal  less  than 
another,  believes  that  eternal  felicity  can  be  won  as 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  157 

the  fruit  of  such  a  cold-blooded  calculation,  such 
brutal  cynicism,  to  use  M.  Sully  Prudhomme's 
blunt  phrase,1  as  would  seem  to  be  implied  by  the 
aleatory  proceeding  recommended.  Simply  as  a 
bet  it  would,  to  the  Searcher  of  all  hearts,  be  no 
more  than  the  celebrated  short  prayer,  "  O  God,  if 
there  be  a  God,  save  my  soul,  if  I  have  a  soul !" 
In  fact,  it  is  only  the  first  step  towards  acquiring 
a  genuine  conviction.  And  Pascal  does  not  leave 
us  in  doubt  about  the  second  step.  His  sceptic  is 
made  to  reply  :  "  I  fully  acknowledge  the  force  of 
your  reasoning.  But  is  there  no  way  of  seeing  the 
faces  of  the  cards?"  "Yes,  there  are  the  Scrip- 
tures, etc."  "  But  what  if  I  am  so  constituted  that 
I  cannot  believe?"  "Do  what  others  in  your 
position  have  done  before.  Act  as  if  you  believed  ; 
take  holy  water,  attend  Mass,  etc.  The  natural 
effect  of  all  that  will  be  to  make  you  believe,  and 
to  stupify  you  (vous  abetira)."  "  But  that  is  just 
what  I  am  afraid  of."  "  Why  so?  What  have  you 
to  lose?" 

I  do  not  think  that  such  a  method  would  com- 
mend itself  to  the  ingenuous  mind  of  Mr.  Hardy's 
rustic.  I  fear  Coggan  would  "  hate  a  feller  "  who 
submitted  to  such  a  degradation  "  for  the  sake  of 
getting  to  heaven."  Even  the  Port  Royal  editors 
were  ashamed  to  print  this  precious  advice,  soften- 
ing it  down  into  a  harmless  recommendation  to 
imitate  the  conduct  of  believers.  Victor  Cousin 
was  the  first  to  publish  the  words  as  they  were 
originally  written.  That  brilliant  rhetorician  was 
neither  a  deep  nor  a  sincere  thinker  ;  but  he  still 

1  In  his  article  entitled  "  Le  Sens  et  la  Port^e  du  Pari  de  Pascal," 
in  the  Revue  des  Deux  Mondes  of  November  i5th,  1890. 


1 5«  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

retained  some  respect  for  truth  and  reason.  He 
asked,  Was  that,  then,  the  last  word  of  human 
wisdom,  and  can  we  only  approach  the  supreme 
Intelligence  by  the  sacrifice  of  our  own?  But 
nowadays,  among  orthodox  Frenchmen,  Victor 
Cousin  would  pass  for  a  dangerous  character — an 
"intellectual."  M.  Brunschvicg  defends  Pascal 
by  putting  a  sense  on  his  words  which  they  will 
not  bear.  S'abetir,  he  tells  us,  means  no  more 
than  that  we  should  get  rid  of  the  prejudices  which 
stand  in  the  way  of  faith.  Surely,  if  so  great  a 
writer  wanted  to  say  this,  he  had  command  enough 
of  the  French  language  to  say  it  for  himself.  A 
course  of  dogmatic  theology,  however  disagreeable, 
would,  one  might  suppose,  be  more  effective  against 
rationalistic  prejudices  than  a  course  of  holy  water. 
Pascal  was  a  shrewd  observer,  and  understood  the 
effect  of  mechanical  devotion  better,  perhaps,  than 
his  apologist.  One  need  only  study  the  faces  in  a 
Bavarian  Corpus  Domini  procession  or  at  a  Breton 
Pardon  to  see  what  "  abetissement "  means. 

Besides  a  natural  if  sinful  objection  to  part  with 
his  reason,  the  sceptic  has  still  a  difficulty.  The 
hope  of  salvation  is  all  very  well,  but  against  the 
happiness  it  gives  we  have  to  set  the  fear  of  hell. 
To  which  Pascal  replies,  sensibly  enough  from  his 
point  of  view  :  Which  has  more  reason  to  fear  it, 
he  who  remains  in  ignorance  if  there  be  a  hell, 
with  the  certainty  of  being  damned  if  there  is  one, 
or  he  who  is  certainly  persuaded  of  its  existence, 
with  the  hope  of  being  saved  if  it  does  exist? 

This  is  a  very  important  passage.  Both  Ernest 
Havet,  in  his  notes  to  the  Pensees,  and  M.  Sully 
Prudhomme,  in  his  essay  on  the  wager,  have 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  159 

assumed,  as  not  needing  discussion,  that  backing 
the  wrong  side  involves  not  only  the  loss  of  eternal 
felicity,  but  also  the  positive  payment  of  an  infinite 
penalty  under  the  form  of  everlasting  torment.  A 
more  recent  critic,  however,  repudiates  their  inter- 
pretation. The  eminent  philosopher  M.  Lachelier, 
writing  in  the  Revue  Philosophique*  declares  per- 
emptorily that  hell  has  no  place  in  the  wager.  As 
the  terms  are  first  stated  it  certainly  is  not  men- 
tioned ;  but  to  insist  on  the  omission  seems  more  like 
a  lawyer  than  a  philosopher.  And  even  from  the 
strictly  legal  point  of  view  M.  Lachelier's  contention 
seems  unjustifiable.  In  drawing  out  the  full  signi- 
ficance of  the  wager  we  have  a  right  to  interpret 
its  conditions  in  the  light  of  its  author's  known  and 
unconcealed  opinions  about  the  future  fate  of  un- 
believers. To  say  that  I  am  obliged  to  bet  must 
mean  that  my  refusal  would  entail  the  same  conse- 
quences as  if  I  betted  against  God's  existence  and 
lost.  And  that  must  be  more  than  the  mere  priva- 
tion of  eternal  felicity,  for  so  much  the  sceptic  is 
already  prepared  to  face  with  equanimity.  Besides, 
when  he  asks  to  see  the  faces  of  the  cards  played 
Pascal  refers  him  to  Scripture  for  information  ;  and 
we  know  that  in  the  eyes  of  a  seventeenth-century 
Catholic  Scripture  consigns  the  infidel  to  eternal 
torment. 

One  is  almost  ashamed  to  labour  so  obvious  a 
point.  But  it  is  a  question  of  some  interest  why 
the  chance  of  damnation  is  left  to  be  inferred  when 
it  might  have  been  made  to  figure  with  such 
tremendous  effect  in  the  wager  as  originally  stated. 

1  June,  1901,  p.  625. 


160  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

I  apprehend  that  the  reason  is  one  of  simple  polite- 
ness. Pascal,  as  Walter  Pater  reminds  us,1  was  a 
gentleman  ;  and  the  sceptic  for  whose  benefit  he 
started  the  whole  idea  of  making  the  supreme 
verities  a  subject  of  betting  was  also  a  gentleman 
and  a  dear  friend  of  his,  the  Chevalier  de  Mere,  a 
man  of  the  world,  and  apparently,  like  others  of  the 
kind,  a  gamester.  That  is  why  Pascal  addresses 
him  in  terms  borrowed  from  the  favourite  amuse- 
ment of  his  class  ;  and  that  is  also,  I  suggest,  why 
he  spares  him  words  not  suited  to  polite  ears. 
Both,  however,  understand  perfectly  what  the  truth 
of  the  Catholic  theory  would  imply.  A  losing 
bettor  not  only  misses  infinite  happiness,  but  has 
to  pay  the  stakes  by  suffering  infinite  misery.  And 
with  great  tact  the  first  reference  to  this  unpleasant 
aspect  of  the  wager  is  put  into  the  mouth,  not  of 
the  Christian  advocate,  but  of  the  hesitating  sceptic. 
Mere,  not  Pascal,  is  made  responsible  for  intro- 
ducing it  into  the  discussion.  To  convince  our- 
selves that  the  softening  down  of  the  risk  incurred 
by  infidelity  is  a  mere  concession  to  the  rules  of  per- 
sonal politeness,  we  need  only  turn  to  the  passages 
where  Pascal  has  to  deal  with  mankind  in  general. 
Here  the  loss  of  felicity  is  not  mentioned  as  a 
motive  for  belief.  With  his  usual  and  incompar- 
able splendour  of  rhetoric,  he  describes  death  as 
infallibly  destined  to  place  the  impious  and  in- 
different under  the  horrible  necessity  of  submitting 
either  to  eternal  annihilation  or  to  eternal  misery, 
without  knowing  which  of  these  eternities  has  been 
prepared  for  them  for  ever.2  And  this  alternative, 

1  Works,  VIII.,  p.  63.  »  II.,  p.  121. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  161 

such  as  it  is,  must  not  be  thought  of  as  existing 
objectively  in  the  nature  of  things,  or  rather  in  the 
unknown  purposes  of  Providence,  but  subjectively 
in  the  reasonable  apprehensions  of  the  doubter. 

Judged  by  Jesuit  or  modern  Ultramontane 
standards,  the  author  of  the  Provinciates  and  the 
Pensees  may  have  been  a  heretic.  But  he  was  far 
too  good  a  Catholic  to  entertain  for  a  moment  the 
idea  that  hell  could  mean  annihilation.  He  speaks 
ad  hominem.  If  you  are  right  in  your  unbelief, 
you  will  cease  to  exist  at  death  ;  if  you  are  wrong, 
you  will  certainly  be  tormented  for  ever. 

So  much  being  established,  let  us  return  to  the 
wager  and  its  implications.  It  was  presented  under 
the  form  of  an  even  chance,  with  nothing  to  lose 
(except  one's  reason)  on  the  one  event,  and  every- 
thing to  gain  on  the  other.  One  is  struck  by  the  sus- 
picious resemblance  to  a  plea  sometimes  advanced 
for  trying  a  quack  remedy.  It  may  do  good,  and 
it  can't  do  harm.  Now,  in  the  case  of  a  drug  about 
which  we  know  nothing — for  the  modesty  of  that 
"  may  do  good  "  is  really  a  confession  of  complete 
ignorance — the  possibility  of  harm  is  precisely 
measured  by  the  possibility  of  benefit.  For  us  the 
chances  are  equal,  because  neither  event  is  any- 
thing more  than  a  chance.  And  an  attentive 
examination  shows  that  Pascal's  reasoning  suffers 
from  the  same  fatal  flaw. 

From  respect  for  so  great  a  name  two  enormous 
assumptions  have  been  let  pass.  We  withdrew 
our  objection  to  the  logical  impossibility  that  a 
Being  out  of  all  relation  to  man  can  affect  man's 
future  fate.  And  we  accepted  as  an  even  chance 
the  infinitesimally  small  probability  that  an  infinite 

M 


162  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

personality,  supposing  it  to  exist,  has  exactly  the 
character  of  the  God  in  whom  Jansenist  Catholics 
believed.  But  our  concessions  must  end  here. 
What  security  has  Mere  that  in  accepting  the 
wager  he  sacrifices  no  more  than  his  reason  and 
the  healthy  enjoyment  of  life?  "  You  have,"  says 
his  friend,  "  the  word  of  God."  Is  that  so  certain  ? 
or  is  it  a  sufficient  guarantee  ?  It  will  not  do  to 
call  the  question  blasphemous,  for  our  moralist  has 
imbued  us  with  the  idea  that  truth  is  a  matter  of 
geography,  and  we  know  what  the  Nicene  Creed 
would  be  called  across  the  straits  of  Gibraltar. 

Here  we  have  the  nemesis  of  agnosticism  as  a 
method  of  faith.  A  universal  solvent  is  created 
and  then  poured  into  some  consecrated  chalice  in 
the  ingenuous  expectation  that  the  holy  vessel  will 
resist  its  corrosive  action.  In  a  series  of  brilliant 
aphorisms  congealing  the  loose  and  lazy  scepticisms 
of  Montaigne  into  a  hailstorm  of  diamond-pointed 
epigrams,  Pascal  had  denounced  the  supposed 
eternal  laws  of  human  morality  as  a  set  of  arbitrary 
expedients,  varying  from  country  to  country,  and 
merely  intended  to  win  respect  for  the  authority  of 
their  princes.  From  such  a  discordant  medley  of 
customs  no  fixed  moral  standard  or  natural  system 
of  ethics  can  be  elicited.  Still  less  can  our  ideas 
of  what  is  right  and  good  be  applied  to  the  criticism 
of  God's  ways  with  man.  Anterior  to  revelation 
we  cannot  predicate  morality,  more  than  any  other 
attribute,  of  the  infinite  Being ;  nor  can  a  self- 
revealing  Deity  be  expected  to  act  in  conformity 
with  human  notions  of  right  and  wrong  when  those 
notions  are  not  conformable  with  one  another. 

Pascal  accepts  the  consequences  of  his  sceptical 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  163 

theology  with  cynical  candour.  "  What,"  he 
exclaims,  "can  be  more  opposed  to  our  wretched 
rules  of  justice  than  the  eternal  damnation  of  a 
child  without  any  will  of  its  own  for  a  sin  in  which 
it  seems  to  have  had  so  little  share  that  it  was  com- 
mitted six  thousand  years  before  the  said  child 
came  into  existence?"1  In  fact,  moral  distinctions 
are  created  by  God  ;  and  "  the  sole  reason  why  sins 
are  sins  is  that  they  are  contrary  to  his  will."2 
Were  the  whole  human  race  to  be  eternally  damned, 
God  would  stand  acquitted  of  injustice.3 

Nevertheless,  with  an  inconsistency  not  un- 
common among  sceptics  Pascal  recognises  one 
kind  of  moral  obligation  as  universally  binding, 
so  much  so  as  even  to  impose  itself  on  God  in  his 
relations  to  man.  And  that  is  the  obligation  of 
keeping  a  promise.  It  is  mentioned  quite  naively 
as  a  self-evident  truth,  valid  apparently  on  both 
sides  of  the  Pyrenees.  "  There  is  a  reciprocal  duty 

between  God  and  man God  is  bound  to  fulfil 

his  promises."4  If  we  have  backed  the  winning 
card,  the  stakes  will  be  honestly  paid. 

I  know  not  what  answer  the  Chevalier  de  Mere 
made  to  the  aleatory  apologetics  of  his  illustrious 
friend  ;  but  his  conversion  was  delayed  so  long  as 
probably  to  have  been  effected  by  considerations  of 
a  different  order.  He  might  well  have  required  a 
better  security  for  the  divine  fidelity  than  Pascal's 
guarantee.  It  seems  rather  rash  to  infer  that, 
because  a  gentleman  keeps  his  word  and  pays  his 
debts  of  honour,  the  Jansenist  God  will.  A  Being 
who  is  wholly  unaccountable  may  mean  something 

1  II.,  p.  348.         2  in.,  p.  104.        3  I.,  p.  125. 
*  in.,  pp.  277-8. 


164  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

different  from  what  he  says,  or  the  exact  opposite, 
or  nothing  at  all.  An  irresponsible  despot  is 
generally  not  less  remarkable  for  perfidy  than  for 
cruelty.  He  who  predestines  little  children  to 
eternal  damnation  may  quite  possibly  be  reserving 
the  Sisters  of  Port  Royal  for  the  same  fate.  We 
were  told  that  the  whole  human  race  might  justly 
be  sent  to  hell,  and  how  do  we  know  that  the  full 
divine  right  may  not  after  all  be  exercised.  "  We 
have  the  word  of  a  King  for  our  Church,  and  of  a 
King  who  was  never  worse  than  his  word."  Such 
was  the  confident  answer  of  the  English  Bishops  to 
those  who  suspected  the  intentions  of  James  II. 
History  tells  how  their  credulity  was  rewarded. 

What  is  more,  Pascal's  interpretation  of  Scripture 
goes  to  prove  that  deceit  and  treachery  are  among 
the  revealed  attributes  of  his  God.  A  particularly 
nauseous  quality  of  that  personage  is  that,  not 
content  with  exercising  his  undoubted  privilege  of 
damning  human  beings  at  sight,  he  tries  to  manu- 
facture a  colourable  pretext  for  their  condemnation 
by  introducing  difficulties  into  the  Bible.  "  There 
is  obscurity  enough  to  blind  the  reprobate,  and 
clearness  enough  to  make  them  inexcusable."1 
"  Do  you  suppose  that  the  prophecies  quoted  in 
the  New  Testament  are  mentioned  to  make  you 
believe?  No,  it  is  to  prevent  you  from  believing."1 
The  whole  Jewish  people  were  purposely  blinded 
to  the  real  meaning  of  the  Messianic  prophecies  in 
order  that  their  rejection  of  Jesus  Christ  might 
render  them  unsuspected  witnesses  to  the  authen- 
ticity of  the  evidentiary  documents  committed  to 

1  in.,  P.  23-  •  HI.,  P.  is- 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  165 

their  charge.  Had  they  accepted  the  gospel,  it 
might  have  been  said  that  they  had  forged  the 
predictions  by  which  its  supernatural  origin  is 
attested,  and  of  whose  antiquity  their  word  is  the 
sole  guarantee.1 

It  would  surprise  me  to  learn  that  there  was  any 
greater  distortion  of  truth  and  justice  in  the 
casuistry  of  Escobar  than  in  the  sophistry  of  his 
Jansenist  satirist.  And  the  Jesuits,  if  they  erred, 
had  at  least  the  excuse  of  erring  on  the  side  of 
mercy.  They  constructed  fire-escapes  where  Pascal 
opens  oubliettes. 

Our  only  knowledge  of  God,  our  only  proof  that 
there  is  a  God,  comes  through  the  Messianic 
prophecies  of  the  Old  Testament  and  their  fulfil- 
ment in  Jesus  Christ.  But  it  is  of  the  very  essence 
of  these  prophecies  to  be  ambiguous  and  mislead- 
ing. We  asked  to  be  shown  the  cards  with  which 
that  awful  game  for  our  soul's  salvation  is  being 
played  "at  an  infinite  distance,"  and  our  wish  has 
been  gratified  :  the  cards  are  no  other  than  the 
pages  of  Scripture.  And  now  we  learn  that  their 
colour  and  value  depend  entirely  on  the  inscrutable 
will  of  the  dealer.  He  can  call  black  red  and  a 
king  a  knave.  He  can  change  trumps  at  pleasure 
and  count  an  ace  as  eleven  points  or  as  one.  That 
is  how  his  antitype,  Napoleon,  played  chess, 
moving  the  pieces  just  as  he  liked,  regardless  of 
rules.  Our  Ariel-souled  thinker  constructs  a  God 
meaner  if  not  more  malignant  than  the  Setebos  of 
Caliban,  in  that  wonderful  study  of  Robert  Brown- 
ing's which  is  also  such  a  scathing  satire  on  the 

1  II.,  p.  16  ff. 


166  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

creed  of  his  youth.  Granting  that  such  a  person 
exists,  our  conduct  cannot  be  affected  one  way  or 
the  other  by  the  fact.  Being  unable  to  take  his 
word  for  anything,  we  are  exactly  in  the  same 
position  as  if  he  had  never  spoken.  Perhaps  after 
all  he  is  less  amenable  to  the  charms  of  adulation 
and  submission  than  his  more  abject  adorers  would 
have  us  believe.  Our  moral  superiority  over  him 
may  at  last  make  its  ascendancy  felt.  Possibly  in 
that  case  his  first  impulse  would  be  to  wreak 
vengeance  on  the  reptile  souls  who  sought  to 
stupefy  their  reason  by  the  copious  use  of  masses 
and  holy  water.  Then  we  who  never  stooped  to 
that  degradation  will  intercede  with  the  converted 
Moloch  for  the  shivering  wretches,  who  may 
escape  with  no  worse  penalty  than  transmigration 
into  the  bodies  of  apes. 

Briefly,  then,  the  existence  of  an  infinite  Being 
out  of  relation  to  ourselves  cannot  possibly  influence 
our  future  fate.  In  the  absence  of  positive  evidence 
it  remains  infinitely  improbable  that  an  infinite 
Being  actively  related  to  us  should  have  a  character 
identical  with  that  of  the  Jansenist  deity.  Assum- 
ing such  a  deity  to  exist,  the  chances  are  precisely 
equal  that  he  will  or  that  he  will  not  behave  towards 
us  in  any  particular  manner.  Therefore,  so  far  as 
theology  goes,  Mere  is  rationally  justified  in  adopt- 
ing the  line  of  conduct  that  seems  most  agreeable 
to  his  own  desires.  When  the  door  of  death  opens 
it  is  even  betting  whether  the  lady  or  the  tiger  will 
receive  him. 

Metaphor  apart,  no  revelation  can  be  of  any 
practical  value  unless  it  is  assumed  to  come  from  a 
person  whose  word  we  can  trust.  But  the  veracity 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  167 

of  God  is  only  guaranteed  by  his  general  moral 
perfection,  and  such  perfection  can  only  be  con- 
ceived as  the  consummation  of  human  goodness. 
But  goodness  includes  justice  as  known  to  us  by 
earthly  examples,  and  these,  according  to  Pascal 
himself,  forbid  us  to  believe  that  innocent  little 
children  can  merit  eternal  torments — or,  we  may 
add,  that  Mere  could  merit  them  for  honestly  using 
his  reason  to  find  out  the  truth,  or  even  the  judges 
of  Galileo  for  suppressing  it.  In  theology  the 
method  of  Descartes  is  a  surer  guide  than  the 
method  of  Montaigne. 

The  idea  of  accepting  Christianity  (understood  in 
an  orthodox  sense)  as  a  probability  which  seems 
safer  to  believe  than  to  disbelieve  has  been  traced 
back  to  Arnobius,  from  whom  Pascal  is  supposed 
to  have  derived  it  through  Raymond  Sebond,  whose 
Natural  Theology  he  had  certainly  read.  But  the 
after  fortunes  of  the  argument  are  more  interesting 
than  its  origin.  It  had  the  singular  good  fortune 
to  be  taken  up  by  Butler  and  made  the  very 
keynote  of  his  Analogy,  whence  it  passed  to  the 
leaders  of  the  Tractarian  Movement,  betraying 
its  inherent  weakness  by  the  conflicting  interpre- 
tations respectively  put  on  it  by  Newman  and 
Keble. 

I  do  not  know  whether  Butler  had  or  had  not 
read  Pascal ;  but  his  theory  of  probability  as  applied 
to  the  evidences  of  Christianity  is  a  distinct  improve- 
ment on  the  wager,  in  so  far  as  it  encourages 
instead  of  abolishing  the  use  of  reason.  On  the 
other  hand,  his  appeal  to  the  most  degrading  of  all 
"  pragmatic  "  motives  is  considerably  more  explicit, 
and  will  hardly  be  denied  even  by  the  most 


168  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

unscrupulous  of  apologists.  After  detailing  the 
arguments  for  revealed  religion  based  on  the  per- 
formance of  miracles  and  the  fulfilment  of 
prophecy,  he  shows  an  uneasy  consciousness  of 
their  insufficiency,  but  urges  as  a  make-weight 
that  "  a  mistake  on  the  one  side  may  be,  in  its  con- 
sequences, much  more  dangerous  than  a  mistake 
on  the  other."1  Butler  alleges,  it  is  true,  that  he 
gives  this  ominous  warning,  not  to  influence  the 
judgment,  but  the  practice,  of  his  readers.  The 
distinction,  however,  is  not  easy  to  grasp,  nor  is 
any  attempt  made  to  illustrate  it.  If  his  sole  object 
was  to  strengthen  the  motives  for  virtuous  action 
irrespective  of  creed,  he  ought  to  have  made  his 
meaning  plainer.  Many  of  the  Deists  would  have 
agreed  with  him  in  recommending  a  high  and  pure 
standard  of  morality,  while  deprecating  the  attempt 
to  compromise  it  by  a  reference  to  selfish  hopes  or 
fears.  In  any  case,  judgment  and  practice  cannot 
be  isolated  from  one  another,  nor  made  amenable 
to  different  orders  of  motives,  least  of  all  when  we 
are  discussing  a  creed  most  of  whose  advocates 
consider  that  a  man  is  morally  responsible  for  his 
belief.  It  is  difficult  not  to  think  that  Butler  knew 
this,  although  he  avoids  committing  himself  to  an 
open  use  of  the  argument  ad  terrorem.  Nor  will 
any  reservation  make  his  theoretical  assumption 
anything  but  a  gross  fallacy.  There  is  no  safe 
side  in  religion,  for  there  is  no  experience  to  show 
where  safety  lies.  To  seek  safety  may,  for  aught 
we  know,  be  the  most  dangerous,  as  it  is  certainly 
the  most  pusillanimous,  of  choices. 

1  Analogy,  Part  II.,  chap,  vii.,  sub  fin. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  169 

In  the  controversy  between  theology  and  ration- 
alism it  requires  a  greater  effort  of  abstraction  than 
most  minds  are  capable  of  to  grasp  this  possibility, 
and  to  appreciate  its  bearing  on  the  aleatory  method 
of  belief.  And  as  between  Roman  Catholicism  and 
the  various  Protestant  sects  all  doubt  would  vanish. 
The  superior  safety  of  belonging  to  the  Church 
which  alone  claimed  to  monopolise  the  means  of 
salvation  was  constantly  urged  as  a  motive  for  sub- 
mitting to  its  pretensions,  and  proved,  in  fact,  a 
most  efficacious  method  of  proselytism.  Henry  of 
Navarre  is  said  to  have  put  the  argument  in  a 
particularly  pointed  form.  The  Protestant  divines 
whom  he  consulted  on  the  subject  reluctantly 
admitted  that  he  might  be  saved  if  he  became  a 
Catholic.  The  Catholic  divines  told  him  without 
hesitation  that  he  would  certainly  be  damned  if  he 
remained  a  Protestant.  He  therefore  chose  that 
side  which,  by  universal  agreement,  offered  the  best 
prospect  of  escaping  from  perdition.  What  the 
great  King  had  offered,  more  than  half  in  irony, 
as  an  excuse  for  his  politic  apostasy  was  accepted 
in  deadly  earnest  by  many  persons  of  quality  in 
England  under  Charles  I.  as  a  reason  for  deserting 
the  cause  of  the  Reformation.  Charles  II. 's  death- 
bed conversion  was  probably  dictated  by  the  same 
motive  ;  and,  if  so,  it  offers  a  crowning  example  of 
the  adroit  opportunism  by  which  his  whole  life  was 
guided.  In  this  as  in  other  respects  the  ablest  of 
all  the  Stuarts  bore  a  close  resemblance  to  his 
grandfather,  the  ablest  of  the  Bourbons.  When 
Butler  wrote  the  danger  from  Rome  had  greatly 
diminished,  but  had  not  wholly  disappeared,  as  we 
learn  from  Neal's  History  of  the  Puritans  (1732) 


170  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

and  Middleton's  Free  Inquiry  (I747).1  It  is  there- 
fore rather  surprising  that  he  did  not  observe  what 
consequences  might  be  drawn  from  an  argument, 
perhaps  derived  from  Pascal,  in  favour  of  Pascal's 
creed. 

If  English  churchmen  did  not  draw  the  logical 
consequences  of  their  greatest  champion's  apologetic 
method,  their  escape  is  due  not  only  to  the  happy 
inconsistency  of  the  theological  intellect,  but  also 
to  the  pervasive  influence  of  eighteenth-century 
rationalism,  extending  as  it  did  far  beyond  the 
small  circle  of  avowed  freethinkers.  Whatever 
else  Englishmen  might  believe,  their  own  Deists 
and  the  Voltairean  movement  abroad  gradually 
convinced  them  that  Popery  was  a  superstition  too 
absurd  for  even  a  Frenchman  to  accept — destined 
to  speedy  extinction,  Horace  Walpole  thought,  if 
the  ill-advised  abrogation  of  our  penal  laws  had 
not  given  it  a  new  lease  of  life.  It  would  have 
surprised  the  dilettante  of  Strawberry  Hill  to  hear 
that  his  own  experiments  in  Gothic  architecture 
had  rather  more  to  do  with  the  dreaded  revival  of 
mediaeval  faith  than  the  repeal  of  some  obsolete 
statutes.  Anyhow,  by  accident  or  otherwise,  he 
proved  a  true  prophet.  Whether  as  grim  wolf  or 
good  shepherd,  two  centuries  after  Lycidas  Rome 
once  more  put  in  play  the  arts  against  which 
Milton  had  raised  his  warning  voice.  Or  rather 
the  natural  magnetism  exercised  by  the  larger  on 
the  smaller  body  acted  without  the  help  of  any 
direct  proselytism  on  the  part  of  Jesuits  or  others 
to  disintegrate  the  Church  of  England  and  to  draw 

1  The  date  of  the  Analogy  is  1736. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  171 

its  detached  fragments  into  the  central  orb  of 
Christendom. 

Now  it  is  interesting  to  note  that  in  this  process 
the  method  of  Pascal  and  Butler  played  an  im- 
portant part,  and  was  appealed  to  with  confidence 
by  both  parties,  by  those  who  clung  to  the  Via 
Media  of  Anglicanism  and  by  those  who  scorned  it 
as  an  illogical  compromise  between  the  right  way 
and  the  wrong. 

Cardinal  Newman  briefly  refers  to  Butler's 
doctrine  of  probability  as  the  guide  of  life  as  that 
whence  his  own  theory  of  faith  took  its  rise.  Keble 
treats  it  at  much  greater  length,  and  in  particular 
connection  with  the  issue  on  which  he  and  his 
greater  friend  parted  company  in  a  very  interesting 
but  little  read  document,  the  preface  to  his  Sermons, 
Academical  and  Occasional,  published  in  1847, 
soon  after  Newman's  secession. 

The  principle  in  question  is  stated  as  follows  : 
"  In  practical  matters  of  eternal  import,  the  safer 
way  is  always  to  be  preferred,  even  though  the 
excess  of  seeming  evidence  may  tell  in  any  degree 
on  the  opposite  side.  Thus,  if  one  mode  of  acting 
imply  that  there  is  an  eternity  and  another  con- 
tradict it the  tremendous,  overwhelming  interest 

at  stake  ought  to  determine  a  man's  conduct  to  the 
affirmative  side.  He  should  act,  in  spite  of  seem- 
ing evidence,  as  if  eternity  were  true."1 

Keble  had  not  the  same  lingering  regard  for 
truth  as  such  that  still  distinguished  Butler ;  and 
the  context  clearly  shows  that  "  acting"  means  not 
merely  conformity  to  Christian  ethics,  but  also  that 

1  Op.  tit.,  p.  6. 


i72  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

adhesion  to  the  Catholic  creed  which,  in  the 
supposed  circumstances,  some,  among  whom  the 
present  writer  is  one,  would  call,  in  plain  language, 
cowardly  and  deceitful. 

Fortunately,  or  rather  inevitably,  systematised 
immorality  is  suicidal ;  and  a  recent  incident  has 
reminded  us  that  when  sailors  fall  into  a  panic  they 
are  apt  to  fire  into  their  own  ships.1  Keble  very 
frankly  admits  that  "  the  principles  of  Butler  and 
Pascal  "  cannot  be  limited  to  "  the  controversy  with 
unbelievers."2  And  if  personally  he  had  been 
disposed  so  to  limit  them,  Newman  would  not  have 
allowed  him  to  stop  short.  So  he  proceeds  to 
state  the  argument  for  going  over  to  Rome  in 
terms  which  I  shall  not  transcribe,  as  they  are 
substantially  identical  with  the  Bourbon  argument 
(white  plume  argument,  let  us  call  it)  already 
quoted. 

Keble's  way  of  getting  out  of  it  is  amazing,  and 
practically  amounts  to  an  abandonment  of  the 
whole  principle.  It  is  that  "  the  argument  put  in 
this  form  proves  too  much,  for  it  would  equally 
show  that  Puritanism  or  Mahometanism,  or  the 
ancient  Donatism,  or  any  other  exclusive  system, 
is  the  safer  way."3  And  he  also  goes  on  to  remark, 
rather  late  in  the  day,  that  there  seems  to  be  some- 
thing "cold  and  ungenerous"  about  the  method — 
in  short,  what  we  call  mean.  Accordingly,  it  is  to 
be  reserved  for  the  exclusive  benefit  of  unbelievers, 

1  The  reference  is  to  the  Dogger  Bank  incident  of  October 
22nd,  1904,  when  Admiral  Rozhdestvensky  mistook  the  Hull 
trawlers  for  Japanese  torpedo-boats.  On  that  occasion  some  of 
the  Russian  ships  are  reported  to  have  suffered  from  the  mis- 
directed fire  of  their  consorts. 

*  Op.  cit.,  pp.  7,  8.  3  Op.  tit.,  p.  14. 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  173 

and  not  mentioned  in  controversies  among  Chris- 
tians. But  we  have  seen  that  as  against  un- 
believers the  probabilist  method  is  quite  invalid. 
When  the  factor  of  inscrutable  and  irresponsible 
omnipotence  has  been  introduced  into  our  calcula- 
tions the  adoption  of  one  particular  alternative 
becomes  no  more  advisable  than  the  adoption  of 
another.  Whatever  creed  we  profess  or  reject,  the 
chances  of  our  being  saved  or  lost  remain  precisely 
equal.  For  a  Being  who  is  morally  capable  of 
damning  us  at  all  is  capable  of  damning  us  for 
taking  him  at  his  word.  Nor  has  the  orthodox 
believer  any  right  to  charge  those  who  advance 
such  an  argument  with  irreverence  or  flippancy. 
To  the  God  whose  existence  he  assumes  their 
reasoning  mayappear  perfectly  reverent  and  serious. 
Pascal's  method  was  destined  to  one  more 
singular  development  before  it  silently  took  its 
place  among  the  obsolete  weapons  of  religious 
controversy.  With  the  collapse  of  the  Tractarian 
Movement  the  rationalistic  movement  which  it  had 
temporarily  arrested  returned  in  a  flood,  and  before 
many  years  had  passed  became  predominant  at 
Oxford,  at  least  among  her  more  serious  and  intel- 
lectual residents.  To  meet  this  new  danger  Mansel 
delivered  his  famous  Bampton  Lectures  in  1858. 
He  does  not,  I  think,  ever  mention  the  argument 
ad  terrorem,  but  he  follows  Pascal  in  denying  that 
our  moral  distinctions  are  applicable  to  the  pro- 
ceedings of  an  infinite  Being  about  whose  real 
nature  we  are  totally  ignorant ;  and  he  follows 
Butler  in  contending  that  every  other  system  is 
open  to  as  many  objections  as  Christianity,  or  rather 
as  his  own  particular  version  of  Christianity. 


174  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

Mansel  was  hailed  by  his  admirers  as  a  second 
Butler  ;  but  the  reception  of  his  work  by  the  intel- 
lectual public  generally  showed  that  such  methods 
had  passed  out  of  date.  I  question  whether,  in  the 
controversy  that  it  provoked,  a  single  name  of  dis- 
tinction is  to  be  found  on  his  side.  Against  him  were 
such  writers  as  F.  D.  Maurice,  James  Martineau, 
R.  H.  Hutton,  and  Professor  Goldwin  Smith. 
Herbert  Spencer,  accepting  his  premises,  pushed 
them  to  the  length  of  an  Agnosticism  which 
absolutely  excluded  belief  in  revealed  religion,  and 
reduced  natural  religion  to  the  most  attenuated  of 
abstractions.  But  the  most  resounding  stroke  of 
all  came  from  John  Stuart  Mill.  In  the  course  of 
his  destructive  attack  on  the  philosophy  of  Mansel's 
teacher,  Sir  William  Hamilton,  the  great  thinker 
and  moralist,  then  at  the  very  height  of  his  fame 
and  power,  turned  aside  to  tear  up  the  flimsy 
pretences  under  which  the  Bampton  Lecturer  on 
the  Limits  of  Religious  Thoughts  had  attempted  to 
eliminate  morality  from  religion.  Pascal  is  not 
named  ;  but  here  at  last  Pascal's  method  receives 
its  final  quietus.  Convince  me,  says  Mill,  that  the 
world  is  ruled  by  an  infinite  Being  of  whom  I 
know  nothing  except  that  his  proceedings  are 
incompatible  with  the  highest  human  morality, 
"  and  I  will  bear  my  fate  as  I  may.  But  there  is  one 
thing  he  shall  not  do :  he  shall  not  compel  me  to 
worship  him.  I  will  call  no  being  good  who  is  not 
what  I  mean  when  I  apply  that  epithet  to  my 
fellow  creatures  ;  and  if  such  a  being  can  sentence 
me  to  hell  for  not  so  calling  him,  to  hell  I  will  go."1 

1  Examination  of  Sir  W.  Hamilton**  Philosophy,  p.  124  (3rd  ed.). 


PASCAL'S  WAGER  175 

Mansel  sneeringly  forbore  "  to  comment  on  the 
temper  and  taste  of  this  declamation."1  But  what 
he  said  or  did  not  say  mattered  equally  little.  The 
ghastly  idol  had  fallen  and  fallen  forever. 

It  has  been  said  by  some  who  are  in  full  sympathy 
with  Mill's  contention  that  the  sentiment  here 
expressed,  however  admirable,  is  irreconcilable 
with  his  utilitarian  ethics.  I  am  not  so  sure  of 
that.  The  moral  degradation  of  worshipping  an 
omnipotent  demon  through  eternity  might  con- 
ceivably be  more  painful  than  any  punishment  in 
the  demon's  power  to  inflict.  Or,  on  finding  him- 
self defied,  he  might  "tak'  a  thought  and  men'" — 
to  the  great  increase  of  the  general  felicity.  But 
there  seems  a  sort  of  pedantry  about  such  con- 
siderations. If  the  supreme  ironies  are  partly 
serious,  supreme  seriousness  may  well  be  a  little 
ironical.  There  is  such  a  phrase  as  "  I  bet  you  all 
to  nothing,"  and  as  the  language  of  the  gaming- 
table has  once  been  introduced  it  may  here  be 
appropriately  used  as  best  describing  Mill's  position. 
There  is  no  more  than  an  infinitesimally  small 
chance  that  Mansel's  non-moral  theology  may  be 
true  ;  but  neither  on  that  chance  nor  on  any  other 
will  a  high-principled  human  soul  forfeit  its  self- 
respect. 

My  object  has  been  to  show  that  to  incur  either 
intellectual  or  moral  degradation  on  a  calculation 
of  selfish  interest  would  be  not  only  mean,  but 
unavailing.  For  with  the  limitation  of  our  know- 
ledge assumed  by  the  theologians  who  appeal  to 
such  motives  there  is  no  safe  side,  the  chances 

1  Philosophy  of  the  Conditioned,  p.  168. 


176  PASCAL'S  WAGER 

either  way  being  precisely  equal  whatever  attitude 
towards  the  hidden  arbiter  of  our  destiny  we 
assume.  It  remains,  then,  that  our  conduct  should 
be  determined  by  considerations  equally  applicable 
whether  the  supernatural  does  or  does  not  exist. 


BUCKLE  AND  THE  ECONOMICS  OF 
KNOWLEDGE 

IT  seems  at  first  sight  like  a  satire  on  the  teaching 
of  Henry  Thomas  Buckle  that,  nearly  twenty  years 
after  his  death,1  public  interest  should  be  more 
attracted  by  the  pettiest  details  of  his  personal  life 
than  by  the  intellectual  achievements  but  for  which 
those  details  would  never  have  been  recorded,  or, 
had  they  been  recorded,  would  never  have  been 
studied.  It  might  be  urged  that  this  was  just  the 
sort  of  gossip  from  which  he  desired  to  set  history 
free,  and  to  substitute  for  it  an  inquiry  into  the 
general  laws  by  which  men's  actions  in  their  totality 
are  determined.  Yet  many  of  these  details  strik- 
ingly illustrate  a  peculiar  and  neglected  aspect  of 
his  philosophy.  For  he  held  that  moral  and  affec- 
tional  motives  are  all-powerful  with  the  individual, 
although  exercising  an  inappreciable  influence  on 
masses  of  men  acting  together.  Accordingly  he 
considered  that  much  which  ought  not  to  find  a 
place  in  history  might  very  properly  be  relegated 
to  biography,  regarding  the  latter,  indeed,  as  not 
susceptible  of  scientific  treatment.  His  life,  then, 
if  it  does  not  verify  his  entire  philosophy,  at  least 
does  not  contradict  it.  It  may  also  be  taken  as 
confirming  and  deepening  the  personal  impression 
made  long  ago  on  his  more  sympathetic  readers. 
There  are  passages  in  the  History  of  Civilisation 

1  Written  in  1880. 

'77  N 


i;8       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

which  show  plainly  enough  that  Buckle  was  full 
of  deep  tenderness  and  ardent  enthusiasm.  But 
without  Mr.  Huth's  biography1  we  should  not  have 
known  how  thoroughly  good  a  man  he  was.  Every 
page  exhibits  him  to  us  as  a  genial  companion,  a 
judicious  adviser,  a  devoted  friend.  But  we  learn 
little  more  about  his  peculiar  cast  of  intellect  than 
that  he  had  a  memory  even  greater,  if  possible, 
than  Macaulay's.  For  the  rest,  nothing  that  Mr. 
Huth  has  published  tends  to  elucidate  the  causes, 
whether  general  or  special,  which  made  his  philo- 
sophy what  it  was.  Fortunately,  however,  the 
information  required  for  that  purpose  is  easily 
accessible.  Next  after  his  country,  parentage,  and 
early  associations,  Buckle's  true  antecedents  and 
environment  are  to  be  found  in  the  school  of 
thought  to  which  for  the  most  part  he  belonged. 
The  object  of  this  essay  is  to  show  what  tendencies 
he  represented,  and  in  what  particular  directions 
he  attempted  to  work  them  out. 

The  English  thought  of  the  last  half  century,  so 
far  as  it  is  really  English  and  not  a  revival  of  old 
dogmas  or  an  importation  from  the  Continent,  has 
been,  under  its  most  general  aspect,  a  philosophy 
of  freedom,  individuality,  spontaneity,  experiment- 
alism.  Foreign  observers  often  take  it,  superficially 
enough,  for  mere  empiricism — the  fit  expression  of 
a  national  character  which  they  persist  in  regarding 
as  narrow,  selfish,  and  materialistic,  incapable  of 
wide  ideas  or  of  lofty  aspirations.  That  such  a 
people  should  also  have  created  the  richest  poetic 
literature  of  modern  times  is  an  anomaly  which 

1  Life  of  T.  H.  Buckle.  By  Alfred  Henry  Huth.  Two  vols. 
London,  1880. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       179 

they  do  not  feel  called  upon  to  explain.  Perhaps 
a  little  reflection  would  show  them  that  our  art  and 
our  philosophy,  so  far  from  being  opposed,  are 
products  of  the  same  imaginative  genius  working 
in  different  directions.  It  would  then  be  under- 
stood that,  if  we  appeal  to  experience,  the  enlarge- 
ment and  not  the  limitation  of  knowledge  is  what 
we  have  most  at  heart ;  and  that  our  utilitarianism 
is  not  the  substitution  of  a  low  for  a  high  standard, 
but  of  a  progressive  for  a  stationary,  a  social  for  a 
personal  morality.  Moreover,  the  English  habit 
of  individual  liberty  combines  with  the  restless 
English  imagination  in  leading  our  foremost  minds 
to  adopt  whatever  abstract  theories  offer  the  widest 
scope  to  spontaneity,  to  freedom  of  enterprise,  to 
variety  of  choice.  It  was  his  thorough  compre- 
hension of  this  tendency  and  the  consistent  manner 
in  which  he  brought  it  to  bear  on  speculation  that 
qualified  John  Stuart  Mill  to  be  for  so  many  years 
the  leader  of  English  thought.  His  Essay  on 
Liberty  only  expresses  more  briefly  and  clearly  the 
fundamental  aim  of  his  larger  works,  which  was 
to  show  that  existing  beliefs  and  customs,  resting 
as  they  did  on  experience,  might  be  superseded 
by  a  wider  experience.  He  has  told  us  himself 
that  this  was  the  aim  of  his  Logic ;  and  the  drift 
of  his  Political  Economy  is  evidently  to  exalt  as 
much  as  possible  the  part  played  by  free  and 
conscious  human  agency  in  the  distribution  of 
wealth.  That  the  system  of  Herbert  Spencer  is 
from  beginning  to  end  a  philosophy  of  liberty 
and  individualism  need  only  be  stated  to  be  per- 
ceived. We  know  from  his  own  declaration  that 
the  whole  series  of  works  composing  it  were 


i8o       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

undertaken  with  a  view  to  its  ethical  conclusion,  and 
we  know  also  that  his  ethical  ideal  is  a  society 
where  the  component  parts  interfere  to  the  least 
possible  extent  with  one  another.  Thinkers  of  a 
more  limited  scope  are  dominated  by  a  similar 
tendency.  Charles  Darwin  has,  so  to  speak,  pro- 
jected the  experimental  method  into  nature,  and 
shown  that  it  is  the  condition  not  only  of  scientific 
progress,  but  of  all  vital  progress  whatever.  Spon- 
taneous variation  and  natural  selection  correspond 
exactly  to  repeated  trial  and  failure  followed  by 
eventual  success ;  and  among  animals  also  those 
families  prosper  most  where  there  is  most  diversity 
developed — in  other  words,  where  originality  is 
least  trammeled.  The  same  idea  is  present  in 
Alexander  Bain's  theory  of  voluntary  action,  which 
offers  a  parallel  to  Darwin's  theory  of  organic 
evolution  the  more  remarkable  from  its  having 
been  worked  out  before  the  latter  was  published. 
According  to  it,  all  sorts  of  movements  are  spon- 
taneously set  up  by  young  creatures,  and  only 
those  muscular  combinations  survive  in  memory 
that  experience  proves  to  be  associated  with 
pleasurable  feeling,  or  with  relief  from  painful 
feeling.  Another  instance  of  the  prominence  given 
to  experimental  freedom  by  English  thought  is  the 
place  which  Stanley  Jevons  assigns  to  hypothesis 
in  his  Principles  of  Science,  particularly  in  the 
chapter  on  "  The  Character  of  the  Experimentalist," 
where  it  is  very  clearly  explained  that  scientific 
discoveries  are  not  made  by  divination,  but  by 
repeated  guesses,  most  of  which  are  utterly  wrong. 
The  two  greatest  works  of  modern  English  his- 
torical literature,  Crete's  Greece  and  Macaulay's 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       181 

England,  are  both,  but  the  former  more  especially, 
pleadings  in  favour  of  political  liberty.  Even  those 
writers  who,  like  Carlyle  and  Ruskin,  on  the  whole 
approve  of  despotism  rather  than  of  democracy 
cannot  avoid  doing  homage  to  the  English  spirit. 
For  the  attraction  of  arbitrary  power  to  Carlyle  was 
that  it  enabled  exceptionally  gifted  individuals  to 
carry  out  their  designs  without  let  or  hindrance  ; 
and  Ruskin  protests  against  machinery  because  it 
destroys  the  personality  of  the  workman,  his  free 
initiative  and  spontaneous  energy.  Even  the  breezy 
criticism  of  Matthew  Arnold  may  be  mentioned  in 
this  connection  as  a  help  to  the  emancipation  of 
thought  from  routine  methods  and  from  party  ties. 
Finally,  the  English  Positivists,  while  accepting 
a  Continental  philosophy,  distinguished  for  its 
animosity  to  many  forms  of  liberty,  are  so  far  faithful 
to  the  traditions  of  their  own  country  as  to  lay 
special  emphasis  on  that  part  of  Comte's  doctrine 
which  demands  the  liberation  of  the  spiritual  from 
the  temporal  power. 

This  general  tendency  of  English  thought  was 
most  fully  accepted  by  Buckle.  As  a  writer,  love 
of  liberty  was  his  ruling  passion  ;  as  a  philosopher, 
the  idea  of  liberty  was  the  centre  of  his  system. 
Although  a  devoted  student,  he  preferred  it  even  to 
knowledge. 

Liberty  [he  exclaims]  is  the  one  thing  most  essential 
to  the  right  development  of  mind  and  to  the  real 
grandeur  of  nations.  It  is  a  product  of  knowledge 
where  knowledge  advances  in  a  healthy  and  regular 
manner ;  but  if,  under  certain  unhappy  circumstances,  it 
is  opposed  by  what  seems  to  be  knowledge,  in  God's 
name  let  knowledge  perish  and  liberty  be  preserved. 
Liberty  is  not  a  means  to  an  end,  it  is  an  end  itself.  To 


182       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

secure  it,  to  enlarge  it,  and  to  diffuse  it  should  be  the 
main  object  of  all  social  arrangements  and  of  all  political 
contrivances.1 

But  the  necessity  for  choosing  between  know- 
ledge and  liberty  was  not  likely  to  present  itself  to 
him  in  a  practical  form.  Each  was  conducive  to 
the  other ;  each  in  its  way  was  a  realisation  of 
mind,  an  expression  of  inward  spontaneous  energy. 
He  conceived  that  the  love  of  knowledge  was, 
equally  with  the  love  of  wealth,  inherent  in  man, 
and  was  adequate  to  the  production  of  all  progress 
when  allowed  free  play  by  the  presence  of  favourable 
material  conditions  and  the  absence  of  artificial 
restraints.  This  notion  was,  in  truth,  a  generalisa- 
tion from  his  own  peculiar  circumstances.  The 
elder  Buckle  had  been  engaged  in  business,  and 
had  bequeathed  a  competence  to  his  son  which 
enabled  the  latter  to  devote  his  whole  time  to 
intellectual  pursuits.  Although  averse  from  office- 
work,  he  kept  up  the  traditions  of  business  and 
carried  them  into  philosophy.  Political  Economy 
supplied  a  natural  connection  between  the  basis 
and  the  superstructure  of  his  existence.  From  that 
science  as  from  a  centre  all  his  other  studies 
branched  out,  and  from  it  he  borrowed  the  method 
by  which  they  were  arranged.  It  was,  then,  quite 
natural  that  he  should  look  on  Adam  Smith  as  the 
greatest  man  that  Scotland  had  ever  produced,  and 
on  the  Wealth  of  Nations  as  the  most  important 
book  ever  published.  He  himself  aspired  to  be 
the  Adam  Smith  of  a  still  more  comprehensive 
science,  and  to  found  the  Economics  of  Knowledge. 

1  Miscellaneous  Writings,  I.,  44-45. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       183 

Buckle's  opinions  were  formed  at  a  time  when 
laisser-faire  was  the  undisputed  law  of  political 
economy,  and  his  early  manhood  coincided  with 
the  stirring  period  of  agitation  for  free  trade — an 
agitation  in  which  we  are  told  that  the  young 
student  was  intensely  interested.  Thus  at  a  very 
early  period  his  speculations  were  biassed  by  a 
strong  prejudice  against  governmental  interference; 
and  his  plan  for  extending  the  laws  of  wealth  to 
knowledge  required  that  something  analogous  to 
the  protective  system  should  be  discovered  in  the 
intellectual  sphere.  This  is  why  Buckle  tries  to 
bring  bad  government  of  every  kind  under  the 
heading  of  protectionism,  and  why  he  looks  on 
churches  in  particular  as  associations  invested 
with  a  kind  of  speculative  monopoly,  to  the 
great  detriment  of  scientific  industry.  Anti-clerical 
rather  than  anti-theological,  his  attitude  is,  in  this 
respect,  exactly  the  reverse  of  that  taken  up  by 
Auguste  Comte,  who  highly  approved  of  ecclesias- 
tical organisation,  but  wished  to  utilise  it  for  a  new 
sort  of  teaching. 

But,  over  a  large  part  of  the  globe,  human 
intelligence  had  to  contend  with  an  even  more 
formidable  enemy  than  the  protective  spirit — an 
enemy,  indeed,  to  whom  the  unconquerable  perti- 
nacity of  that  spirit  was,  in  most  instances,  due. 
Such  was  the  point  of  view  from  which  Buckle 
regarded  Nature.  He  speaks  of  her  as  carrying 
on  a  perpetual  warfare  with  man,  sometimes 
victorious,  sometimes  vanquished,  but  always 
tending  to  thwart  and  drag  him  back  to  her  own 
level.  It  is  astonishing  that  one  who  formulated 
this  fundamental  antithesis  so  sharply,  and  who  in 


184       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

other  respects  has  so  frequently  expressed  his 
adhesion  to  the  popular  metaphysics  of  the  'fifties, 
should  ever  have  been  charged  with  materialism. 
A  notion  has  somehow  gained  currency  that  Buckle 
proposed  to  deduce  the  history  of  every  country 
from  its  physical  geography.  Nothing  could  well 
be  more  unlike  the  truth.  He  distinctly  marks  off 
the  regions  where,  in  his  phraseology,  nature  was 
subordinated  to  man  from  those  where  man  was 
subordinated  to  nature  ;  and  it  was  with  the  former 
that,  as  a  historian  of  civilisation,  he  was  almost 
exclusively  concerned.  The  idea  that  human 
beings  and  human  societies  are  themselves  natural 
products  had  apparently  never  occurred  to  him. 
This,  however,  was  not  for  want  of  acquaintance 
with  the  theory  of  evolution,  the  basis  of  which  he 
had  fully  accepted.  Writing  some  years  before  the 
appearance  of  the  Origin  of  Species,  he  alludes  to 
fixity  of  species  as  an  "  old  dogma "  on  which 
successful  attacks  had  already  been  made  ;'  and  in 
the  same  passage  he  assumes  that  phenomena  of 
every  order  have  always  been  determined  by  their 
own  laws  without  any  interference  from  without. 
But  he  was  averse  from  accepting  the  absolute 
dependence  of  mind  on  brain,  nor  could  he  well 
have  done  so  consistently  with  his  passionate  faith 
in  its  immortality.  Hence  his  scornful  doubt  that 
the  human  mind  could  be  handed  down  like  an 
heirloom  ;2  his  opinion  that  the  intellectual  and 
moral  faculties  do  not  improve  ;  and  his  deliberate 


1  History  of  Civilisation  in  England,  Vol.  I.,  p.  806,  note.  The 
references  throughout  this  essay  are  to  the  original  edition  in  two 
volumes. 

*  Miscellaneous  Writings,  I.,  17. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       185 

omission  of  race  from  the  physical  conditions  which 
a  historian  has  to  consider.  Even  where  he  does 
admit  physical  influences  they  are  of  a  very  indirect 
character,  and  they  are  just  those  which  would  be 
picked  out  by  the  economist  and  the  literary  student 
rather  than  by  the  physiologist.  Nature  wars 
against  political  liberty  by  producing  over-popula- 
tion, and  so  enabling  landlords  and  capitalists  to 
concentrate  all  power  in  their  own  hands.  She  wars 
against  intellectual  liberty  by  the  multiplication 
of  extraordinary  and  terrifying  phenomena  which 
stimulate  the  imagination  at  the  expense  of  the 
understanding.  Buckle  seems  to  have  confounded 
an  originally  rapid  rate  of  increase  in  population 
with  its  final  increase  up  to  or  beyond  the  limit 
of  subsistence.  Over-population  is  theoretically 
possible  under  any  conditions  of  climate,  food,  and 
soil  ;  and  it  is  not  necessarily  involved  in  one  rate 
of  increase  more  than  in  another.  The  existence 
of  vast  plains  isolated  from  the  rest  of  the  world, 
whether  fertile  or  barren,  seems  a  likelier  cause  of 
despotism  than  any  other  that  can  be  named ;  while, 
conversely,  whatever  geographical  circumstances 
are  favourable  to  the  development  of  several  inde- 
pendent national  centres,  near  enough  for  active 
intercourse  with  each  other,  but  protected  by  natural 
frontiers  against  mutual  aggression,  and  similarly 
situated  with  regard  to  the  world  at  large — such 
regions,  in  short,  as  Greece,  the  basin  of  the 
Mediterranean,  and  Western  Europe  generally — 
are  also  favourable  to  liberty.  It  would  seem  also 
that  the  aspects  of  nature  have  much  less  to  do  with 
superstitious  beliefs  than  Buckle  supposed.  For 
such  beliefs  were  originally  diffused  over  the  whole 


186       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

earth  under  very  similar  forms ;  they  have  not 
remained  constantly  associated  with  awe-inspiring 
scenery  ;  and  where  such  an  association  does  exist, 
as  for  instance  in  South  America  or  the  East  Indies, 
it  can  be  better  explained  by  difficulty  of  communi- 
cation with  the  centres  of  enlightenment  than  by 
any  direct  influence  exercised  on  the  imagination. 

My  object,  however,  is  not  so  much  to  criticise 
Buckle's  views  as  to  show  in  what  modes  of  thought 
they  originated.  And  here  we  have  a  remarkable 
verification  of  the  guiding  principle  laid  down 
at  starting.  Following  the  true  English  method, 
our  philosopher  construes  universal  history,  not  as 
an  organically  connected  whole,  but  as  a  great 
collection  of  spontaneous  experiments  on  the  possi- 
bility of  human  progress.  Mind  is  scattered  broad- 
cast over  the  whole  earth,  but  in  only  a  few 
instances  does  it  meet  with  conditions  favourable 
to  its  development.  Everywhere  outside  Europe 
civilisation  has  been  arrested,  either  because  wealth 
could  not  be  accumulated  at  all,  or  because  it  could 
not  be  diffused  so  widely  among  the  masses  as  to 
enable  them  to  understand  and  act  on  the  ideas  put 
forward  by  men  of  genius.  In  Europe  a  new  set 
of  forces,  historical  instead  of  geographical,  come 
into  play,  and  a  series  of  eliminations  bring 
us  at  last  to  England  as  the  only  country  where 
mind  has  been  able  to  manifest  its  inherent  powers 
of  expansion  on  a  scale  wide  enough  to  furnish 
materials  for  determining  the  natural  law  of  all 
progress.  By  an  equally  ingenious  train  of  reason- 
ing Guizot  proves  that  civilisation  can  best  be 
studied  in  France  ;  a  country  which  Auguste 
Comte,  on  quite  different  grounds,  also  erects  into 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       187 

the  normal  type  of  intellectual  evolution.  No 
doubt  the  patriotic  bias  spoken  of  by  Herbert 
Spencer  has  something  to  do  with  these  prefer- 
ences ;  but  a  deeper  reason  will  be  found  in  the 
character  impressed  on  every  philosophy  by  the 
social  conditions  under  which  it  is  framed.  A 
thinker  who  translates  the  ideas  of  his  own  nation 
into  abstract  formula?  will  naturally  find  that  this 
same  nation  best  satisfies  the  requirements  of  his 
particular  system.  He  may  even  extend  the  method 
to  particular  periods,  and  imagine  that  the  world 
was  never  so  enlightened  as  when  his  theory  of 
what  it  ought  to  be  first  became  fixed. 

Besides  his  patriotic  feelings,  there  was  probably 
another  strong  motive  which  induced  Buckle  to 
select  a  single  country  for  the  application  of  his 
new  method.  This  was  the  desire  to  simplify  the 
hypothetical  science  of  history,  which,  but  for  some 
such  artifice,  threatened  to  become  unmanageably 
complex  and  difficult.  The  same  consideration 
throws  some  light  on  his  celebrated  rejection  of 
morality  as  a  factor  in  the  progress  of  civilisation. 
None  of  the  author's  theories  provoked  so  much 
hostile  criticism  at  the  time  of  their  first  publica- 
tion, nor  were  any  of  them  supported  by  such  weak 
and  inconsistent  arguments.  It  will  perhaps  be 
worth  while  to  glance  at  the  principal  assumptions 
which  those  arguments  involve.  They  are  as 
follows  :  (i)  The  innate  moral  dispositions  do  not 
change  ;  (2)  Moral  truth  is  not  progressive  ;  (3) 
Innate  disposition  and  knowledge  between  them 
account  for  the  whole  of  moral  conduct ;  (4)  Moral 
forces  exercise  no  great  or  lasting  effect  on  human 
affairs.  Of  these  four  propositions  three  are  refuted 


i88       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

by  the  history  of  slavery  alone.  It  was  not  always 
known  that  slavery  is  wrong,  nor,  in  fact,  was  it 
always  wrong ;  the  perception  of  its  iniquity  was 
made  more  active  by  religious  feeling ;  and  its 
abolition  was  in  great  part  due  to  the  excitement 
thus  produced.  With  regard  to  the  alleged  station- 
ariness  of  the  innate  moral  dispositions — by  which 
term  of  course  nothing  more  than  sympathy  need 
be  implied — everything  goes  to  prove  that  on  the 
average  civilised  children  are  born  with  a  better 
nature  than  savage  children,  or  than  their  own 
remote  ancestors.  It  is,  however,  conceivable  that, 
conceding  the  existence  of  moral  progress,  more 
may  have  been  done  for  human  happiness  by 
purely  intellectual  progress.  One  great  example 
of  a  benefit  due  entirely  to  the  latter  is,  according 
to  Buckle,  the  comparative  infrequency  of  war  in 
modern  times.  His  argument  is  a  perfect  nest  of 
fallacies.  The  stimulus  given  to  war  by  intellectual 
causes,  such  as  individual  genius  and  the  adoption 
of  new  beliefs  by  whole  nations  or  sections  of 
nations,  is  entirely  ignored.  It  is  taken  for  granted 
that  the  invention  of  gunpowder  localised  the 
military  spirit  in  a  separate  class  and  thereby 
weakened  it,  whereas  the  localisation  seems  to 
have  been  greater  before  gunpowder  came  into 
general  use;1  nor  was  it  likely  that  war  should 
become  less  popular  when  its  risks  were  confined 
to  a  particular  class  than  when  they  were  shared  by 
the  whole  community.  That  national  quarrels  are 
discouraged  by  the  diffusion  of  sound  economical 
doctrine  is  doubtless  true  ;  but  the  false  doctrines 

1  See  Macaulay's  Essay  on  Machiavelli. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       189 

from  which  those  quarrels  formerly  sprang  were 
equally  intellectual  forces,  only  made  possible  by  a 
great  development  of  reflection.  Buckle  gives  as 
a  reason  for  neglecting  the  influence  of  legislation 
on  progress,  that  the  best  laws  are  those  which 
have  been  passed  for  the  repeal  of  bad  ones  ;  he 
does  not  consider  how  easily  the  same  argument 
might  be  turned  against  his  own  favourite  theory 
of  social  dynamics — a  remark  which  applies  equally 
to  that  other  great  intellectual  triumph,  the  decline 
of  religious  persecution.  For,  so  far,  it  is  the  most 
intellectual  religions  that  have  been  the  most  in- 
tolerant ;  and  modern  thought  in  winning  liberty 
has  only  won  back  what  ancient  thought  enjoyed 
everywhere  except  at  Athens.  Nor  is  this  all. 
Another  influence  adverse  to  war  is,  we  are  told,  the 
great  increase  of  travelling  due  to  the  extension 
of  locomotion  by  steam.  Different  nations  are 
brought  into  closer  contact  with  one  another,  their 
mutual  esteem  is  thereby  increased,  and  their 
hostile  feelings  are  proportionately  diminished. 
Now,  what  is  this  mutual  esteem  if  not  a  moral 
motive,  brought  into  play,  indeed,  by  intellect,  but 
itself  the  determining  antecedent?  And,  to  make 
the  self-contradiction  worse,  we  learn  that  the 
reason  why  men's  respect  for  each  other  grows 
with  their  mutual  intimacy  is  that  the  good  in 
human  nature  considerably  outweighs  the  bad. 
If  so,  what  becomes  of  the  position  that  virtue  and 
vice  exactly  balance  and  neutralise  each  other's 
effects  ? 

Apart,  however,  from  these  obvious  objections, 
there  is  a  deeper  objection  to  the  theory,  which,  so 
far  as  I  know,  has  never  yet  been  pointed  out — 


190       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

namely,  the  indistinctness  of  the  whole  antithesis 
between  moral  and  intellectual  laws.  Buckle  saw 
clearly  enough  that  duty  is  partly  a  matter  of 
knowledge,  without  seeing  that  all  knowledge 
must,  as  such,  be  intellectual  ;  and  he  altogether 
failed  to  observe  that  the  pursuit  of  science  must 
equally,  as  a  mode  of  action,  come  under  moral 
laws.  A  life's  devotion  to  the  pursuit  of  truth 
demands  no  inconsiderable  amount  of  temperance 
and  courage  ;  while  candour  in  dealing  with  the 
opinions  of  others,  and  readiness  to  test  one's  own 
opinions  thoroughly,  imply  a  degree  of  fairness 
and  disinterestedness  not  inferior  to  that  which  may 
be  displayed  in  the  performance  of  any  other  duty. 
In  estimating  the  influence  of  religion,  literature, 
and  government  on  civilisation,  Buckle  finds  his 
task  greatly  simplified  by  the  previous  elimination 
of  morality  ;  the  immediate  effects  of  these  three 
agents  (to  which  art  should  have  been  added  as  a 
fourth)  being  exercised  on  action  rather  than  on 
knowledge  ;  while,  again,  the  consciousness  that 
morality  depends  upon  such  complex  conditions 
was  a  further  motive  for  leaving  it  out  of  account 
altogether.  Yet  even  so  the  questions  raised  in 
this  connection  are  most  inadequately  treated  in 
the  chapter  specially  devoted  to  them.  So  far  as 
literature  is  concerned,  Buckle  himself  subsequently 
took  up  a  totally  different  position,  expatiating 
eloquently  on  the  stimulus  which  poetry  gives  to 
scientific  discovery,  and  on  the  importance  of 
keeping  the  intellect  in  perpetual  contact  with  the 
emotions  ;'  for  which  purpose,  as  need  hardly  be 

1  II.,  p.  502. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       191 

observed,  literature  is  our  most  valuable  auxiliary. 
His  remarks  on  this  head  remind  us  of  what  Pro- 
fessor Tyndall  has  since  said  ;  and  a  little  farther 
reflection  might  have  led  him  to  anticipate  what 
the  same  authority  has  stated  with  respect  to  the 
moral  basis  of  intellectual  work. 

Such  considerations  would,  however,  have  been 
inconsistent  with  that  thoroughgoing  parallelism 
between  knowledge  and  wealth,  between  logic  and 
political  economy,  which  our  author  was  bent  on 
establishing  ;  for  the  laws  of  material  industry,  as 
he  had  learnt  them,  were  completely  dissociated 
from  morality  and  from  disinterested  emotion.  It 
is  not  a  little  curious  that  two  other  English  thinkers, 
Darwin  and  Herbert  Spencer,  should  almost  simul- 
taneously have  been  carrying  economic  principles, 
the  one  into  zoology,  and  the  other  into  all  philo- 
sophy. For  the  "  struggle  for  existence "  is 
avowedly  based  on  the  Malthusian  law  of  popu- 
lation ;  and  the  formula  of  evolution  grew  out  of 
an  attempt  to  place  the  doctrine  of  laisser-faire  on 
a  truly  scientific  foundation.  Buckle  uses  both 
principles,  although  on  a  much  more  limited  scale  ; 
he  explains  the  tropical  civilisations,  as  we  have 
already  seen,  by  the  advantage  which  an  unre- 
stricted multiplication  of  human  beings  gave  to 
land  and  capital  over  labour ;  he  explains  the 
European  civilisations  as  a  constant  struggle 
between  governmental  interference  and  the  natural 
development  of  intellect ;  and  we  shall  presently 
see  that  he  forces  deduction  and  induction  into  an 
analogy  with  the  production  and  distribution  of 
wealth. 

It  sometimes  happens  that  a  philosopher  errs, 


i92       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

not  by  following  his  own  ideas  too  far,  but  by  not 
following  them  far  enough  ;  and  I  cannot  help 
thinking  that  Buckle  would  have  been  better 
inspired  had  he  pushed  his  parallel  one  step 
further,  and  introduced  the  theory  of  exchange  into 
his  intellectual  economics.  He  would  then  have 
seen  that  the  importation  of  knowledge  from  one 
country  into  another  is  the  very  condition  of  its 
progress  ;  that  for  the  community  as  well  as  for 
the  individual  isolation  means  death ;  that  no 
nation,  however  gifted,  can  subsist  on  its  own 
mental  stores;  and  that  truth  acquires  an  altogether 
new  power  when  transferred  to  a  fresh  soil.  He 
would  not  then  have  held  that  the  laws  of  intel- 
lectual or  any  other  progress  are  best  ascertained 
by  studying  their  action  in  a  country  secluded,  so 
far  as  possible,  from  external  interference.  And 
he  would  also,  perhaps,  have  perceived  that  the 
decay  of  the  great  tropical  and  sub-tropical  civili- 
sations arose  partly  from  this  very  seclusion, 
partly  from  the  reaction  of  the  barbarism  by  which 
they  were  surrounded  on  every  side,  entailing  as 
it  did  an  ever-increasing  preponderance  of  the 
military  spirit,  together  with  a  crushing  burden  of 
taxation  within.  As  it  is,  he  unconsciously  bore 
witness  to  the  truth  whose  full  force  he  failed  to 
recognise.  England,  which  he  declares  to  be  the 
one  country  least  affected  by  foreign  influences, 
does  in  reality  owe  much  of  her  intellectual  great- 
ness to  those  very  influences.  The  circumstance 
that  we  did  not  formerly  travel  much  abroad  for 
pleasure,  or  receive  many  visitors  from  the 
European  Continent,  is  comparatively  insigni- 
ficant. We  traded  round  the  world  ;  we  received 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       193 

books,  inventions,  discoveries,  and  ideas  from  all 
quarters. 

When  Buckle  began  to  write  the  Renaissance 
had  not  yet  attracted  the  universal  attention  it  was 
destined  to  receive  a  few  years  after  his  death  ; 
still,  its  immense  importance  in  the  life  of  reason 
had  already  been  pointed  out  before  his  time,  and 
no  one  can  now1  help  noticing  what  a  void  is 
produced  by  its  total  absence  from  the  pages  of 
this  historian.  He  seems  to  think  that,  towards 
the  close  of  the  sixteenth  century,  men  suddenly, 
and  for  no  particular  reason  except  the  negative  one 
of  ecclesiastical  decay,  began  doubting  what  they 
had  hitherto  believed,  and  that  modern  enlighten- 
ment sprang  as  spontaneously  from  their  doubts. 
The  truth  is  that  they  questioned  one  set  of  beliefs 
because  they  had  become  familiarised  with  another 
and  contradictory  set,  embodied  in  the  classic  litera- 
ture of  Greece  and  Rome.  Nor  was  the  intellectual 
life  of  England  dependent  only  for  its  first  awaken- 
ing on  an  external  stimulus ;  it  was  sustained 
through  the  whole  seventeenth  century  by  con- 
tinual contact  with  the  minds  of  other  nations  ; 
while  no  sooner  was  their  influence  partially  with- 
drawn, as  happened  in  the  eighteenth  century,  than 
it  fell  into  a  speedy  decline.  Buckle  has  noticed 
the  dearth  of  speculative  genius  which  followed  the 
deaths  of  Locke  and  Newton,  but  he  has  failed 
adequately  to  explain  it.  Curiously  enough,  too, 
the  explanation  which  he  does  offer  is  inconsistent 
with  his  own  principles.  According  to  him,  it 
arose  from  the  diversion  of  the  national  genius 

1  Written  in  1880. 


194        BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

partly  into  practical  pursuits,  partly  into  political 
contests.1  Here,  then,  are  two  most  serious  dis- 
turbances, totally  unconnected  with  the  protective 
spirit,  not  allowed  for  in  his  general  philosophy  of 
history,  and  all  the  more  dangerous  that  they  are 
likely  to  gain  instead  of  losing  strength  with  ad- 
vancing civilisation.  That,  however,  he  exag- 
gerates their  effect  during  the  period  referred  to 
will  become  evident  when  we  consider  how  much 
greater  their  activity  has  since  become,  without 
proving  incompatible  with  a  brilliant  revival  of 
science  and  philosophy.  If  we  ask  what  was  the 
cause  of  that  revival,  Buckle  will  himself  supply 
us  with  the  answer.  He  attributes  it  first  to  the 
influence  of  the  Scotch  school,  and  then  to  the 
"  sudden  admiration  for  German  literature  of  which 
Coleridge  was  the  principal  exponent."2  Only 
prejudice  could  have  prevented  him  from  acknow- 
ledging our  obligations  to  France  as  well. 

When  we  turn  to  other  countries,  Buckle 
furnishes  fresh  evidence  of  the  same  truth — the 
intellectual  interdependence  of  nations.  He  tells 
us  that  France,  enervated  by  the  despotism  of 
Louis  XIV.,  was  only  saved  by  a  wholesale  impor- 
tation of  English  ideas ;  and  that  the  German 
intellect  was  raised  to  an  even  abnormal  activity  by 
contact  with  those  eminent  Frenchmen  who  flocked 
to  the  court  of  Frederic  the  Great.3  English  and 
Greek  literature  had,  by  the  way,  much  more 
to  do  with  that  extraordinary  fermentation  than 
Maupertuis  and  his  colleagues ;  but,  as  Buckle 
unhappily  did  not  live  to  sketch  the  history  of 

1  I.,  p.  808.  »  Ibid,  p.  809.  3  p.  2,7. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       195 

German  thought,  I  need  not  press  the  point. 
Another  striking  illustration  is  offered  by  the  history 
of  Spain.  Nothing  in  his  whole  work  is  more 
interesting  than  those  condensed  and  vivid  pages 
in  which  Buckle  shows  how,  after  having  been 
brought  to  the  lowest  ebb  of  misery  by  her  priest- 
hood and  her  government,  that  unhappy  country 
was  restored  to  something  of  her  former  prosperity 
by  the  efforts  of  a  foreign  dynasty.  Yet,  strange 
to  say,  he  seizes  on  this  opportunity  to  push  home 
the  lesson  that  "  no  progress  is  real  unless  it  is 
spontaneous."1  That  Spain  temporarily  fell  back 
from  the  position  won  for  her  by  Charles  III.  may 
be  true  enough.  But  did  she  become  again  what 
she  had  been  a  century  before  ?  And  has  she 
made  no  progress  since  then  ?  The  revolution  of 
1868  was,  comparatively  speaking,  a  failure,  as 
indeed  the  revolutions  of  England  and  France  at 
first  seemed  to  be  also  ;  but  at  any  rate  it  revealed 
the  existence  of  a  sceptical  feeling  diffused  through 
the  entire  Spanish  nation,  and  an  utter  decay  of 
the  old  loyalty,  which,  according  to  our  philo- 
sopher, are  the  most  essential  requisites  of  progress ; 
and  this  scepticism,  whatever  may  be  its  value,  is 
altogether  an  importation  from  France  and  Ger- 
many— in  other  words,  it  results  from  a  movement 
first  set  on  foot  by  the  reforming  zeal  of  the  Bour- 
bons. The  derivation  of  Scotch  philosophy  from 
England  and  France  is  not  noticed,  although  the 
influence  of  France  at  least  had  already  been  pointed 
out  by  Carlyle  in  his  essay  on  Burns.2 

1  II.,  p.  99. 

1  In  one  passage  Buckle  speaks  of  "  that  interchange  of  ideas 
which   is   likely   to    become    the   most    important    regulator   of 


196       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

The  preference  shown  by  Buckle  for  home-grown 
over  imported  knowledge  may  have  been  suggested 
by  Adam  Smith's  analogous  preference  of  agricul- 
ture to  manufactures,  and  of  native  industry  to 
foreign  trade.  But  when  he  declares  the  protective 
spirit  in  Church  and  State  to  be  the  great  enemy  of 
intellectual  progress,  and  therefore  of  all  civilisa- 
tion, the  very  form  of  the  expression  places  its 
economical  derivation  beyond  a  doubt.  Here  he 
is  quite  at  home,  and  here  his  whole  soul  is  thrown 
into  the  work.  The  polemic  against  protection 
occupies  the  larger  portion  of  his  history,  and  it 
was  this  that  won  for  it  such  a  far-reaching  and 
resonant  success.  From  a  literary  point  of  view 
that  success  was  well  deserved.  I,  at  least,  know 
of  nothing  in  any  work  of  the  kind  marked  by  such 
intense,  sustained,  victorious  passion — the  passion 
without  which,  as  Hegel  says,  nothing  great  can 
be  achieved,  and  which,  in  this  instance,  is  ren- 
dered more  formidable  by  the  imposing  array  of 
facts  brought  up  to  support  it  at  every  step.  To 
us  of  the  present  generation  Buckle's  words  have  a 
more  individual  distinctness  and  a  more  immediate 
interest  than  to  his  own  contemporaries.  For, 
since  they  were  written,  there  has  been  a  revival 
of  the  protective  spirit  under  a  new  form,  and  in 
many  quarters  it  is  proposed  that  the  old  authori- 
tative methods  should  be  used  to  consolidate  and 
extend  reforms  initiated  by  very  different  means. 
Endowment  of  research,  endowment  of  Catholic 
professorships,  compulsory  education,  compulsory 


European  affairs"  (I.,  p.  223).     Bui  he  omits  to  notice  that  it  has 
always  been  their  most  important  regulator. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       197 

temperance,  compulsory  thrift,  interference  with 
freedom  of  contract,  and  Socialistic  velleities  of 
every  kind — these  are  but  the  various  parts  of  a 
system  against  which  Buckle,  had  he  lived,  would 
have  protested  not  less  energetically  than  Herbert 
Spencer.1  It  behoves  us  then  to  examine  with 
especial  care  the  arguments  by  which  his  thesis  is 
supported,  and  the  historical  examples  by  which 
he  has  endeavoured  to  verify  them. 

The  protective  spirit,  as  has  been  already 
observed,  is  twofold.  It  may  either  interfere  with 
men's  actions,  or  with  their  beliefs,  or  with  both. 
In  France  it  chiefly  took  the  direction  of  political 
tutelage,  in  Scotland  of  ecclesiastical  intolerance, 
in  Spain  of  both  combined  ;  the  consequence  being 
that  in  the  last-named  country  progress  was  com- 
pletely arrested,  while  in  the  other  two  it  has  been 
irregular  and  unhealthy.  The  French  Revolution 
was  a  reaction  against  the  protective  spirit,  and  its 
destructive  violence  was  due  to  the  rigour  of  the 
repression  which  provoked  it.  Few  liberal  thinkers 
will  deny  that  Buckle's  criticisms  on  the  past  and 
present  condition  of  the  countries  just  enumerated 
contain  a  large  amount  of  truth.  It  is  quite 
another  question  whether  the  wide  generalisations 
founded  on  his  historical  survey  are  equally  to  be 
trusted.  To  begin  with,  it  seems  to  me  that  the 
assumption  of  a  fixed  antithesis  between  the  people 
and  their  rulers  is  eminently  misleading.  A  country 
may  be  governed  by  a  foreign  race,  possibly  for  its 
own  good,  but  at  any  rate  without  its  own  consent 


1  Written  in  1880,  when  the  agitation  against  Free  Trade  was 
only  just  beginning. 


198       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

or  co-operation,  like  India  at  the  present  moment ; 
or  again  it  may  be  dominated  by  a  priesthood 
sprung  from  its  own  ranks  and  speaking  its  own 
language,  but  to  all  intents  and  purposes  the 
soldiers  of  an  alien  power,  and  quite  out  of 
sympathy  with  its  real  opinions  ;  but  apart  from 
these  exceptions  every  government  is  really  repre- 
sentative, even  when  it  is  not  created  by  the 
popular  vote,  and  merely  gives  a  sharper  expres- 
sion to  the  collective  will  or  to  the  prevalent  beliefs 
of  the  people.  Sometimes  the  rulers  will  be  a  little 
in  advance  of  their  subjects,  and  sometimes  a  little 
behind  them  ;  but,  to  use  a  favourite  formula  of 
our  author's,  deviations  in  one  direction  will  be 
compensated  by  deviations  in  another.  Here  the 
government  will  be  too  interfering,  and  there  too 
remiss  ;  but  in  either  case  the  error  will  be  attended 
by  counterbalancing  advantages ;  and  probably  each 
nation  will  have  something  to  learn  from  the  other. 
Everywhere  there  will  be  obstacles  to  progress ; 
but  they  will  arise  far  more  from  the  natural 
inertia  of  the  human  mind,  varying  with  race  and 
geographical  position,  than  from  the  distribution 
and  application  of  political  power  ;  and  they  will 
equally  affect  all  classes  of  society. 

Again,  Buckle  seems  to  confound  under  the 
common  name  of  political  protection  five  distinct 
ideas  :  (i)  Despotism  of  any  kind  ;  (2)  the  concen- 
tration of  power  in  a  few  hands  ;  (3)  the  favouring 
of  one  class  at  the  expense  of  others ;  (4)  inter- 
ference with  individuals  for  their  own  good  ;  and 
(5)  the  feeling  of  personal  loyalty  towards  a  here- 
ditary chief.  He  even  goes  so  far  as  to  identify 
what  is  called  a  paternal  government  with  a 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       19$ 

"government  in  which  supreme  power  is  vested  in 
the  sovereign  or  in  a  few  privileged  classes."1  Yet 
surely  the  government  of  Turkey  is  not  paternal  ; 
nor  is  the  development  of  democracy  unfavourable 
to  benevolent  interference  with  private  interests, 
as  the  present  tendency  of  legislation  in  England 
proves.  Buckle  also  associates  economic  protec- 
tion with  political  absolutism  and  centralisation, 
although  in  the  United  States  it  flourishes  under 
conditions  the  very  reverse  of  these  ;  while  only  a 
few  years  after  the  publication  of  his  first  volume 
free-trade  was  imposed  on  France  by  a  despotic 
ruler. 

Undoubtedly  there  are  countries  where  the  prin- 
ciple of  authority  is  highly  developed,  and  others 
where  it  is  restricted  within  very  narrow  limits ; 
but  to  say  that  the  former  are  necessarily  animated 
by  a  spirit  unfavourable  to  scientific  progress  is 
probably  more  than  Buckle  would  have  ventured 
to  assert  in  so  many  words  ;  although,  on  putting 
his  various  expressions  together,  this  is  the  only 
interpretation  that  they  will  stand.  Yet  it  is 
notorious  that  science  has  received  great  en- 
couragement from  many  absolute  rulers  both  in 
ancient  and  modern  times.  In  France  it  made 
great  progress  under  the  old  regime.  In  Germany 
it  has  co-existed  with  a  complete  absence  of  political 
freedom.  Perhaps  he  would  have  held  that  mere 
knowledge  was  an  insufficient  return  for  the  sacri- 
fice of  individualism  and  spontaneity ;  but  we 
have  only  to  deal  with  his  clear  and  categorical 
assertions — (i)  "that  the  progress  of  mankind 

1  I-,  p-  557- 


200       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

depends  on  the  success  with  which  the  laws  of 
phenomena  are  investigated,  and  on  the  extent  to 
which  a  knowledge  of  these  laws  is  diffused " ; 
and  (2)  "that  the  great  enemy  of  this  movement 
is  the  protective  spirit."1  Now,  I  maintain  that, 
whatever  else  the  history  of  France  proves,  it 
does  not  prove  the  second  of  these  propositions. 
Let  us  consider  what  arguments  it  suggests  to 
Buckle.  He  does  not,  indeed,  discuss  the  endow- 
ment of  research  put  in  practice  on  a  large  scale 
by  Louis  XIV.,  but  he  censures  the  encouragement 
given  to  literature  by  that  monarch  on  grounds 
which,  if  they  are  worth  anything,  must  equally 
apply  to  science.  As  usual,  the  principles  invoked 
are  purely  economic.  We  are  told  that— 

Every  nation  which  is  allowed  to  pursue  its  course 
uncontrolled  will  easily  satisfy  the  wants  of  its  own 
intellect,  and  will  produce  such  a  literature  as  is  best 
suited  to  its  actual  condition.  And  it  is  evidently  for  the 
interest  of  all  classes  that  the  production  shall  not  be 
greater  than  the  want — that  the  supply  shall  not  exceed 
the  demand.  It  is,  moreover,  necessary  to  the  well-being 
of  society  that  a  healthy  proportion  should  be  kept  up 
between  the  intellectual  classes  and  the  practical  classes. 
It  is  necessary  that  there  should  be  a  certain  ratio  between 
those  who  are  most  inclined  to  think  and  those  who  are 
most  inclined  to  act.  If  we  were  all  authors,  our  material 
interests  would  suffer ;  if  we  were  all  men  of  business, 
our  mental  pleasures  would  be  abridged.  In  the  first 
case,  we  should  be  famished  philosophers  ;  in  the  other 
case,  we  should  be  wealthy  fools.  Now,  it  is  obvious 
that,  according  to  the  commonest  principles  of  human 
action,  the  relative  numbers  of  these  two  classes  will  be 
adjusted,  without  effort,  by  the  natural,  or,  as  we  call  it, 
the  spontaneous,  movement  of  society.3 

1  II.,  p.  i.  "  I.,  pp.  628-29. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       201 

The  obvious  fallacy  lies  in  supposing  that  literature 
is  useless  when  those  who  are  engaged  in  its  pro- 
duction cannot  live  on  the  sale  of  their  works. 
The  idea  of  doing  anything  for  posterity  is  quite 
ignored.  And  we  are  vainly  left  to  imagine  how 
the  book-market  is  to  provide  needy  philosophers 
not  only  with  the  necessaries  of  life,  but  also  with 
the  instruments  of  research,  such  as  libraries,  obser- 
vatories, laboratories,  and  collections  of  natural 
objects,  in  the  absence  of  state-aid,  and  even  of 
private  munificence,  for  that,  too,  must  be  excluded 
if  we  are  to  apply  the  law  of  supply  and  demand 
with  complete  consistency.  To  suppose  that  such 
aid,  even  when  granted  on  a  liberal  scale,  would 
impoverish  the  rest  of  the  community  is  absurd, 
especially  when  we  consider  how  largely  scientific 
discoveries  contribute  to  the  national  wealth.  Nor 
can  it  be  contended  that  the  energies  of  scientific 
men  are  weakened  by  the  receipt  of  public  assist- 
ance (as  those  of  other  producers  might  be),  so  long 
as  it  does  not  exceed  their  real  wants.  Had  our 
author  lived  to  write  his  promised  sketch  of 
American  civilisation,  he  would  perhaps  have  found 
that  the  want  of  accumulated  knowledge — which, 
according  to  him,  is  a  serious  obstacle  to  the  pro- 
gress of  the  United  States— may  be  traced  to  a 
want  of  endowments  for  the  support  of  learning  in 
that  country.1 

Buckle,  however,  in  the  chapter  to  which  I  have 
been  referring,  evades  the  real  issue  by  speaking 
at  one  time  as  if  the  interests  of  science  or  philo- 
sophy were  identical  with  those  of  literature,  and 

1  I.,  pp.  220-21.      It  will  be  understood  that  the  reference  is 
to  a  state  of  things  existing  fifty  years  ago. 


202       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

at  another  time  as  if  the  two  were  opposed.  The 
former  view  is  expressed  in  the  passage  just  quoted, 
the  latter  in  his  subsequent  arguments.  We  are 
told  that  Louis  XIV.,  by  encouraging  art  and 
poetry,  arrested  the  great  intellectual  movement 
which  had  been  in  progress  before  his  accession  to 
power.  It  may  be  doubted  whether  any  courtier 
ever  attributed  such  omnipotence  to  a  monarch  as 
this  republican  historian.  Here,  again,  an  econo- 
mical analogy  is  falsely  applied.  Because  capital 
can  be  readily  transferred  from  one  employment  to 
another,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  same  is  true 
of  brains.  It  is,  indeed,  evident  from  the  facts 
furnished  by  Buckle  himself  that,  before  Louis  XIV. 
assumed  the  direction  of  affairs,  the  French  intellect 
was  already  executing  the  evolution  ascribed  to  his 
mischievous  interference  with  the  natural  course 
of  thought.  For  "  the  poets,  dramatists,  painters, 
musicians,  sculptors,  architects,  were,  with  hardly 
an  exception,  not  only  born,  but  educated,  under 
that  freer  policy  which  existed  before  his  time."1 
A  fortiori,  their  career  must  have  been  already 
decided  before  his  majority.  That  epochs  of  scien- 
tific and  of  artistic  excellence  should  alternate  with 
one  another  is,  in  truth,  a  regular  law  of  history  ; 
and  the  same  phenomenon  has  repeated  itself  at 
other  periods  when  the  cause,  whatever  it  may  be, 
evidently  lay  deeper  than  the  vicissitudes  of  Court 
favour.  It  is  another  question  whether  the  intel- 
lectual sterility  which  marked  the  latter  half  of 
Louis's  reign  is  to  be  attributed  to  the  protective 
system.  Looking  at  our  own  Victorian  age  as  it 

1  I.,  p.  648. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       203 

now  is,  compared  with  what  it  was  twenty  years 
ago,  and  at  the  present  wretched  state  of  French 
literature  as  compared  with  the  generation  of  1830, 
I  am  inclined  to  think  that  here  also  we  are  in 
presence  of  some  mysterious  rhythm,  according  to 
which  many  more  great  writers  are  born  at  one 
time  than  at  another.1 

Passing  from  the  protective  spirit  in  politics  to 
the  protective  spirit  in  theology,  I  must  again  call 
attention  to  the  confusion  of  ideas  lurking  under 
a  style  of  exemplary  clearness.  The  somewhat 
heterogeneous  forces  represented  by  clericalism, 
asceticism,  intolerance,  and  superstition  are  lumped 
together  under  a  single  heading  ;  while  the  last  of 
these  terms  is  sometimes  used  to  denote  super- 
natural beliefs  lying  outside  theology,  and  some- 
times any  amount  of  supernaturalism  going  beyond 
Buckle's  own  theistic  creed.  Sometimes  the  clergy 
are  dangerous  because  they  teach  certain  doctrines  ; 
at  other  times  the  doctrines  are  only  dangerous 
because  of  the  authority  which  they  give  to  an 
organised  class  whose  interests  are  opposed  to 
progress.  Sometimes  the  study  of  theology  is 
attacked  as  a  waste  of  power,  because  theology 
deals  with  subjects  not  admitting  of  any  certain 
information  ;  at  other  times  because  it  propounds 
theories  inconsistent  with  experience.  Undercover 
of  such  ambiguities,  the  Scotch  and  the  Germans 
are  equally  spoken  of  as  being  more  superstitious 
than  the  English  ;  although  most  of  the  faults  with 
which  Scotland  is  reproached  are  present  in  England 
to  a  considerable  extent,  and  not  present  at  all  in 

1  Things  have  got  much  worse  since  the  above  was  written. 
Compare  the  concluding  chapter  of  my  Modern  England, 


2o4      BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

Germany.  Moreover,  the  evils  indiscriminately 
associated  with  the  protective  spirit  in  theology,  so 
far  from  being  always  combined,  are  often  found 
to  be  inconsistent  with  one  another.  Asceticism 
is  not  the  rule  of  established  Churches,  but  of  those 
religious  teachers  who  are  thrown  for  their  support 
on  the  voluntary  contributions  of  the  people.  It  is 
also  notorious  that  the  latter  class,  precisely  because 
they  are  not  protected— that  is  to  say,  not  educated 
at  the  public  expense,  nor  admitted  to  the  society 
of  the  higher  orders — are  generally  distinguished 
by  the  greater  illiberality  of  their  sentiments. 
Again,  a  real  theology,  however  largely  intermixed 
with  error  it  may  be,  is  widely  removed  from  the 
mere  popular  and  spontaneous  superstitions  with 
which  Buckle  habitually  confounds  it,  by  the  sys- 
tematic cohesion  of  its  dogmas,  and  by  the  severe 
intellectual  effort  implied  on  the  part  of  those  whose 
duty  it  is  to  assimilate  and  to  defend  them.  It  is 
no  accident  that  so  many  savants  should  be  the 
children  of  Protestant  clergymen,  and  that  so  many 
philosophers  should  have  been  theological  students 
in  their  youth.  Even  as  a  formidable  enemy, 
Catholicism  may  have  rendered  valuable  services 
to  freethought,  by  nerving  its  advocates  to  the  most 
strenuous  efforts,  and  obliging  them  to  find  counter- 
solutions  for  the  great  problems  to  which  the  Church 
had  already  provided  an  answer.  Buckle  knew 
well  that  industry  does  not  attain  its  highest 
development  in  regions  where  the  wants  of  life  are 
most  easily  supplied.  He  might  have  inferred  from 
that  significant  circumstance  that  the  intellectual 
energies  gain  fresh  strength  from  the  obstacles 
against  which  they  contend.  It  would  have  been 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       205 

worthy  of  an  English  philosopher  to  point  out  that 
in  the  intellectual  sphere  also  competition  is  needed 
to  secure  efficiency  ;  that  great  thought  has  always 
been  aggressive  and  defiant ;  and  that  the  weaken- 
ing of  its  antagonist  may  dangerously  react  upon 
itself. 

After  considering  the  causes  by  which  knowledge 
is  impeded,  we  pass  to  its  own  laws,  to  the  condi- 
tions under  which  it  is  extended.  Here  the  analogy 
between  intellectual  and  industrial  economics,  which 
throughout  has  been  our  guide,  is  completed.  We 
are  taught  to  consider  knowledge,  like  wealth, 
under  the  two  heads  of  accumulation  and  diffusion. 
By  the  former  progress  is  made  possible  ;  by  the 
latter  it  is  actually  effected.  Had  Buckle  been 
really,  what  so  many  writers  fancy  he  was,  a 
disciple  of  Auguste  Comte,  he  would  here  have 
availed  himself  of  the  results  already  reached  in 
the  Positive  Philosophy.  The  law  of  the  three 
stages  was  ready  to  hand,  together  with  the  classi- 
fication of  the  sciences  according  to  their  logical 
and  historical  order  of  evolution.  His  true  master, 
however,  among  contemporary  thinkers  is  not 
Comte,  but  Mill  ;  he  combines  the  System  of  Logic 
with  the  Principles  of  Political  Economy ;  he  looks 
on  deduction  as  the  great  instrument  by  which 
knowledge  is  accumulated,  and  on  induction  as  the 
great  instrument  of  its  diffusion.1  We  have  to 
lament  that  his  whole  case  is  not  before  us,  for  it 
was  in  the  unwritten  chapters  on  Germany  and 
America  that  these  two  processes  were  to  have  been 
more  particularly  studied.  I  believe,  however, 

1  I.,  p.  224;  II.,  pp.  &<)sqq. 


206       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

that  the  method  chosen  was  a  mistaken  one,  and 
that  its  inadequacy  may  be  demonstrated  from  the 
portions  which  he  lived  to  complete. 

It  would  appear,  to  begin  with,  that  Buckle  had 
either  no  clear  idea  of  what  is  meant  by  induction 
and  deduction,  or  ideas  which  were  the  reverse  of 
true.  And  here  let  us  pause  to  observe  that  our 
philosopher,  while  professing  to  discard  the  methods 
employed  by  metaphysicians  for  investigating  the 
laws  of  mind,  and  setting  very  little  value  on  the 
positive  results  which  they  have  attained,1  has  in 
fact  borrowed  the  whole  framework  of  his  system 
from  these  very  metaphysicians,  without  acknow- 
ledgment and  without  criticism.  He  justly  censures 
Reid  for  multiplying  unproved  assumptions.  Yet 
he  had  a  common-sense  system  of  his  own  ;  only 
he  never  got  so  far  as  Reid  ;  he  never  consciously 
formulated  it  to  himself.  Preoccupied  with  the 
idea  of  general  laws  as  the  one  great  object  of 
knowledge,  he  forgot  that,  before  laws  can  be  even 
looked  for,  a  preliminary  mental  analysis  is  needed, 
sometimes  of  infinitely  greater  difficulty  and  im- 
portance than  any  subsequent  part  of  the  inquiry. 
But,  as  nobody  can  move  an  inch  without  such  an 
analysis,  he  takes  for  granted  the  distinctions  of 
common  language  and  common  thought,  without 
perceiving  their  purely  relative  and  provisional 
value.  It  is  only  by  studying  the  history  of  these 
distinctions  that  we  can  free  ourselves  from  their 
tyranny.  Buckle,  apparently,  had  never  done  so, 

1  He  mentions  as  the  sum-total  "  a  very  few  of  the  laws  of  asso- 
ciation "  (one  would  like  to  know  how  many  there  are  altogether), 
"  and  perhaps  I  may  add  the  modern  theories  of  vision  and  of 
touch"  (I.,  p.  151).  Yet  out  of  these  materials  nearly  the  whole 
of  a  new  psychology  has  been  constructed. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       207 

and,  not  having  mastered  them,  they  have  mastered 
him.  They  are  perpetually  misleading,  or  tripping 
him  up,  or  gathering  in  a  hopeless  tangle  about 
his  steps.  So  it  is  with  the  antithesis  between 
nature  and  man  derived  from  the  Greek  Sophists  ; 
the  antithesis  between  the  intellectual  and  the 
moral  derived  from  Aristotle ;  the  Socratic  con- 
fusion of  dutifulness  with  knowledge  ;  and  the 
assumption  of  an  immemorial,  unchanging  moral 
code,  smacking  strongly  of  intuitionism.  Then, 
again,  we  have  the  scholastic  separation  of  the 
imagination  from  the  understanding  ;  and  on  it  is 
superimposed  a  theory  that  art  is  due  to  the  one 
and  science  to  the  other.  This  supplies  him  with 
a  ready  explanation  of  the  disproportionate  develop- 
ment of  art  in  Italy  and  Spain  ;  the  imagination 
being  stimulated  to  excess  in  those  countries  by 
the  more  imposing  aspects  of  nature  as  compared 
with  Northern  Europe.  It  seems  to  have  escaped 
his  notice  that  in  art  the  Belgians  far  surpass  the 
Swiss,  while  in  science  the  relation  is  reversed. 
Elsewhere,  as  I  have  already  observed,  he  does 
justice  to  the  scientific  uses  of  the  imagination,  but 
straightway  proceeds  to  confound  imagination 
either  with  a  knowledge  of  the  emotions  or  with 
the  emotions  themselves.  These,  he  incidentally 
declares,  "  are  as  much  a  part  of  us  as  the  under- 
standing " — which  has  never  been  denied — and 
adds  that  "  they  are  as  truthful  "  and  "  as  likely  to 
be  right  "  ;T  a  doctrine  which,  if  it  has  any  meaning 
at  all,  would  immediately  reopen  the  floodgates  of 
superstition,  and  reverse  the  conclusions  elsewhere 
maintained  by  its  author. 

1  II.,  p.  502. 


208       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

But  of  all  the  ideas  that  Buckle  has  borrowed 
from  the  "metaphysicians,"  he  has  used  none  so 
freely  as  their  theories  concerning  the  distinction 
between  induction  and  deduction  ;  nor  is  his  want 
of  philosophical  training  anywhere  more  painfully 
evinced,  and  this  in  three  different  directions  :  (i) 
as  regards  their  abstract  nature  ;  (2)  as  regards 
their  historical  exemplification  ;  and  (3)  as  regards 
their  connection  with  the  accumulation  and  diffusion 
of  knowledge.  His  account  of  the  two  methods  is, 
at  first  starting,  sufficiently  accurate,  though  rather 
vague.  "  Induction  is  from  particulars  to  generals, 
and  from  the  senses  to  the  ideas  ;  deduction  is  from 
generals  to  particulars,  and  from  the  ideas  to  the 
senses."1  But,  on  proceeding  to  explain  what  are 
the  general  propositions  from  which  deduction  sets 
out,  he  makes  the  following  extraordinary  asser- 
tion : — 

The  deductive  thinker  invariably  assumes  certain 
premisses,  which  are  quite  different  from  the  hypotheses 
essential  to  the  best  induction.  These  premisses  are 
sometimes  borrowed  from  antiquity  ;  sometimes  they  are 
taken  from  the  notions  which  happen  to  prevail  in  the 
surrounding  society  ;  sometimes  they  are  the  result  of  a 

man's  own   peculiar  organisation  ;  and   sometimes 

they  are  deliberately  invented,  with  the  object  of  arriving, 
not  at  truth,  but  at  an  approximation  to  truth. 

To  which  he  adds  that — 

a  deductive  habit,  being  essentially  synthetic,  always 
tends  to  multiply  original  principles  or  laws  ;  while  the 
tendency  of  an  inductive  habit  is  to  diminish  those  laws 
by  gradual  and  successive  analysis. 

Yet  we  had  been  previously  told  that— 

the  inductive  philosopher  is  naturally  cautious,  patient, 

1  II.,  p.  419. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       209 

and  somewhat  creeping  ;  while  the  deductive  philosopher 
is  more  remarkable  for  boldness,  dexterity,  and  often 
rashness.1 

One  need  only  look  at  the  mathematical  sciences, 
which  are  universally  admitted  to  be  deductive,  to 
see  the  absurdity  of  all  this.  To  ascend  from  the 
part  to  the  whole  must  always  be  cceteris  paribus  a 
more  daring  and  hazardous  process  than  to  descend 
from  the  whole  to  the  part.  The  truth  is  that  what 
Buckle  had  in  his  mind  throughout  was  not  the 
opposition  between  two  kinds  of  reasoning,  but 
between  reasoning  on  the  one  hand  and  observa- 
tion and  experiment  on  the  other.  For  he 
mentions  America  as  an  extreme  instance  of  the 
inductive  spirit,  and  Germany  of  the  deductive. 
Now,  the  Americans  are  well  known  to  be  excellent 
observers,  but  they  have  not  contributed  much  to 
our  stock  of  generalisations,  either  by  the  discovery 
of  new  or  by  the  resolution  of  old  laws  ;  while 
German  philosophy  is  remarkable  for  its  habit  of 
challenging  current  assumptions,  and  for  its  con- 
stant endeavour  to  construct  systems  out  of  the 
fewest  possible  first  principles.  Yet  this  interpre- 
tation, although  it  gives  an  intelligible  meaning  to 
some  passages,  is  irreconcilable  with  others  which 
seem  to  confound  induction  with  the  general  prin- 
ciple of  all  reasoning,  the  demand  of  a  proof;  while 
deduction  is  represented  as  the  submission  of  reason 
to  unsupported  authorities.  Accordingly,  the  one 
method  is  characterised  as  theological,  and  the 
other  as  anti-theological.2  The  distinction  cannot, 
in  my  opinion,  be  maintained.  Particular  facts 
may  be,  equally  with  general  propositions,  taken 

1  Loc.  cit.  2  Ibid.,  pp.  411  sqq. 

P 


210       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

for  granted  or  accepted  on  faith,  and  theological 
systems  not  only  may  be,  but  have  been,  built  up 
out  of  such  alleged  facts,  with  no  more  aid  from 
general  assumptions  than  is  necessary  to  any 
inductive  process  whatever.  And  the  errors  of 
such  a  system,  or  of  any  system,  may  often  be 
most  effectually  overthrown  by  showing  that  it 
involves  a  contradiction,  either  of  its  general  pro- 
positions with  each  other,  or  of  those  propositions 
with  their  logical  consequences — that  is  to  say,  by 
deductive  reasoning.  It  has  even  been  held  that 
the  function  of  syllogistic  logic  is  essentially 
negative,  that  it  only  amounts  to  the  complete 
elimination  of  self-contradiction  from  thought. 
Buckle  most  unfairly  opposes  the  rigorous  and 
scientific  employment  of  the  one  method  to  the 
loose  and  popular  employment  of  the  other,  thus 
altogether  missing  the  close  connection  which 
recent  logicians  have  shown  to  subsist  between 
them. 

When  Buckle  proceeds  to  illustrate  the  different 
types  of  reasoning  by  a  survey  of  the  literatures 
where  he  supposes  them  to  be  exemplified,  his 
original  misapprehension  is  continued  and  rein- 
forced by  other  misapprehensions  in  the  interpreta- 
tion of  those  literatures.  The  Scotch  intellect  in 
the  eighteenth  century  is  chosen  as  an  example  of 
the  deductive  spirit ;  and  the  tendency  of  Scotch 
metaphysicians  to  assume  the  existence  of  ultimate 
principles  in  the  human  mind  is  given  as  an 
especial  instance  of  its  operation.  An  historian 
might  perhaps  be  equally  justified  in  taking  Hume, 
Adam  Smith,  James  Mill,  and  Thomas  Brown, 
who  all  pursued  the  contrary  method,  as  the 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       211 

genuine  representatives  of  Scotch  philosophy. 
But,  passing  over  this  objection,  is  it  not  obvious 
that  we  have  here  a  confusion  of  psychology  with 
logic  ;  that  to  insist  (whether  rightly  or  wrongly) 
on  the  indecomposable  character  of  certain  mental 
phenomena ;  to  maintain  even  that  we  have 
internal  sources  of  knowledge  independent  of 
experience — is  an  entirely  different  thing  from 
preferring  one  kind  of  demonstration  to  another? 
It  might  as  well  be  said  that  the  chemist  who 
believes  in  the  indecomposable  character  of  the 
so-called  elements  is  more  deductive  than  he  who 
seeks  to  resolve  them  all  into  a  single  substance, 
as  that  the  a  priori  psychologist  is  so  distinguished 
from  his  analytical  rival.  Indeed,  of  the  two  I 
should  say  that  he  who  evolves  all  the  manifold 
varieties  of  consciousness  from  the  combinations  of 
a  few  simple  feelings,  approaches  nearest  to  the 
mathematical,  and  therefore  to  the  deductive, 
method.  The  common-sense  school,  as  their  very 
name  implies,  were  not  reasoners  at  all  ;  they 
never  went  beyond  a  superficial  description  and 
classification  of  the  mental  phenomena. 

In  dealing  with  the  origin  of  this  so-called  philo- 
sophy, Buckle  is  equally  at  fault.  According  to 
him,  its  method  is  theological,  its  results  are  secular 
and  liberal.  The  truth,  however,  is  that  Hutcheson, 
the  founder  of  the  school,  borrowed  his  innate 
principles  from  Shaftesbury  and  Butler,  who,  being 
English,  ought,  on  our  author's  view,  to  have 
taught  the  contrary  system  ;  while  the  habit  of 
assuming  their  existence,  once  introduced,  found 
high  favour  with  orthodox  Scotchmen,  because  it 
seemed  to  make  for  the  spirituality  of  the  soul  and 


212        BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

the  supernatural  origin  of  conscience  ;  thus  furnish- 
ing a  welcome  support  to  those  dogmas  by  which 
they  were  still  powerfully  affected.  We  are  told 
that  in  Scotland  the  intellectual  classes  have  long 
been  remarkable  for  "  boldness  of  investigation 
and  freedom  from  prejudice."1  I  believe  all 
continental  critics  will  agree  with  me  in  thinking 
that  they  have  been,  comparatively  speaking,  much 
more  remarkable  for  narrowness  and  timidity. 

It  is  quite  in  accordance  with  his  singular  view 
of  method  that  Buckle  should  declare  Hume's 
metaphysical  essays  an  exception  to  the  generally 
deductive  character  of  Scotch  philosophy.  For 
Hume  was  both  the  most  sceptical  of  all  thinkers 
and  the  one  who  carried  the  experiential  system 
farthest.  Yet,  looking  not  at  the  matter,  but 
at  the  logical  form  of  those  essays,  I  do  not  see 
how  they  can  be  distinguished  from  his  other 
writings.  For  reasons  already  suggested,  I  should 
be  inclined  to  consider  them  better  examples  of 
deduction  than  of  induction.  But,  properly  speak- 
ing, there  is  a  stage  at  which  speculation  is  so  little 
developed  that  it  cannot  be  brought  under  any 
strictly  defined  type  of  reasoning  at  all.  Its  method 
is  then  that  of  analogy,  a  rough  attempt  to  interpret 
the  unknown  in  terms  of  the  known.  The  Natural 
History  of  Religion  is  a  good  example  of  this 
process.  Hume,  without  investigating  the  evidence 
furnished  by  travellers,  declared  that  polytheism 
was  the  natural  religion  of  savages.  Does  it  follow 
that  his  conclusions  were  evolved  out  of  his  own 
mind  ?  By  no  means.  He  argued  from  the  widest 

1  I.,  P.  225. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       213 

experience  that  the  more  abstract  and  universal  a 
notion  is,  the  more  difficult  is  it  to  grasp  ;  and  that 
the  higher  manifestations  of  mind  follow,  instead 
of  preceding,  the  lower.  In  fact,  he  argued  from 
all  that  was  already  known  by  experience  of 
children,  of  uneducated  persons,  and  of  savages, 
to  what  still  remained  to  be  known  of  these  last. 
To  collect  the  facts  about  savage  belief,  and  then 
to  restate  them  in  abstract  terms,  would  not  have 
been  induction,  because  it  would  not  have  been 
reasoning  of  any  kind,  but  simply  description. 

Buckle's  account  of  Adam  Smith  is  open  both  to 
these  and  to  other  criticisms.  The  works  of  that 
great  thinker  are  represented  as  a  perfect  type  of 
the  deductive  method.  The  Theory  of  Moral  Senti- 
ments and  the  Wealth  of  Nations  are  interpreted  as 
complementary  portions  of  a  single  science,  having 
for  its  object  the  reduction  of  human  nature  to  law. 
The  peculiarity  of  the  scheme  is  that  the  two  grand 
motives  of  human  action  are  separately  considered, 
and  treated  apart  from  each  other's  disturbing 
action.  These  two  motives  are  sympathy  and 
selfishness ;  the  one  is  discussed  in  the  Moral 
Sentiments ',  the  other  in  the  Wealth  of  Nations. 
By  a  logical  artifice,  each  in  turn  is  assumed  to  be 
the  whole  factor  in  human  conduct ;  although,  in 
reality,  their  effects  are  always  conjoined.  Buckle 
exemplifies  what  he  supposes  to  have  been  the 
method  of  Adam  Smith  by  a  singularly  unlucky 
illustration  from  geometry.  Real  lines,  he  tells  us, 
always  have  both  length  and  breadth  ;  but  the 
geometrician,  in  order  to  avoid  insoluble  compli- 
cations, assumes  that  they  possess  the  former 
attribute  only.  We  are  not  informed  whether  he 


2i4       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

subsequently  rectifies  his  omission  by  postulating 
lines  which  have  breadth  without  length  ;  but  to 
complete  the  parallel  he  certainly  ought  to  do  so. 
A  much  more  pertinent  illustration  would  have 
been  furnished  by  dynamics,  which  really  does 
begin  with  the  effect  of  forces  taken  singly,  and 
afterwards  proceeds  to  study  them  in  combination. 
I  conceive,  however,  that  no  such  idea  ever  entered 
the  head  of  Adam  Smith  as  is  attributed  to  him  by 
his  admirer.  His  two  great  works  would,  indeed, 
according  to  Buckle's  theory,  serve,  not  to  complete, 
but  to  contradict  and  upset  each  other.  For,  be  it 
observed,  they  do  not  study  simple  tendencies,  but 
actual  concrete  facts  of  history  and  every-day  life. 
To  say  that  whatever  men  feel  and  think  and  do  is 
the  effect  of  their  sympathies,  and  then  to  say  that 
it  is  the  effect  of  their  selfishness,  would,  if  these 
two  forces  were  necessarily  opposed  to  one  another, 
be  simply  an  unintelligible  paradox.  But  the 
Theory  of  Moral  Sentiments  is,  as  its  very  name 
implies,  an  inquiry  into  the  origin  of  certain 
feelings,  which  are  nowhere  assumed  to  exercise  a 
paramount  influence  over  human  conduct ;  nor, 
although  they  are  derived  from  sympathy,  do  they 
exhaust  its  manifestations.  Neither  do  sympathy 
and  selfishness,  in  Smith's  view  of  them,  either 
divide  the  whole  field  of  human  nature,  or  recipro- 
cally exclude  one  another.1  The  tendency  to  give 
and  to  seek  for  sympathy  does  not,  in  its  original 
form,  imply  any  self-sacrifice,  and,  in  its  more 
complex  manifestations,  is  eminently  favourable  to 

1  That  is,  according  to  the  present  use  of  terms,  which  is  also 
Buckle's.  Adam  Smith  says  that  sympathy  is  not  a  selfish 
principle,  using  selfish  in  a  much  narrower  sense  than  ours, 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       215 

that  desire  for  wealth  which  Adam  Smith  regards 
as  the  principal  cause  of  economic  progress.  Thus 
the  Wealth  of  Nations,  so  far  from  taking  up  a 
psychological  position  opposed  to,  or  lying  outside, 
that  of  the  Moral  Sentiments,  simply  assumes  the 
existence  of  desires  which,  in  that  work,  had  been 
explained,  whether  rightly  or  wrongly,  as  a  par- 
ticular manifestation  of  our  social  feelings.  More- 
over, even  if  its  reasonings  were  based  on  the 
supposition  that  selfishness  (in  its  narrowest  sense) 
is  the  sole  spring  of  action,  they  would  not  give  a 
complete  account  of  it,  but  only  of  so  much  as  is 
concerned  with  the  production  of  economical  pheno- 
mena ;  while,  again,  the  analysis  of  those  pheno- 
mena embraces  a  variety  of  topics  with  which  the 
science  of  human  nature,  properly  so  called,  has 
nothing  whatever  to  do. 

But  if  Adam  Smith's  works  do  not,  when  taken 
together,  constitute  a  deductive  psychology,  can  it 
be  said  that  each  of  them  singly  is  an  example  of 
the  deductive  method?  Certainly  not  according  to 
Buckle's  own  definitions.  For  the  Theory  of  Moral 
Sentiments  makes  no  unsupported  assertions  ;  it 
perpetually  appeals  to  experience  ;  and,  instead  of 
multiplying  ethical  principles,  seeks  to  reduce  them 
to  one.  Neither  does  the  Wealth  of  Nations  reason 
down  from  causes  to  effects,  but,  contrariwise, 
ascends  from  effects  to  causes,  which,  we  are  else- 
where informed,  is  a  process  characteristic  of 
induction.1  We  begin  with  the  division  of  labour, 
and  are  gradually  led  on  to  exchange,  to  the  circu- 
lating medium,  and  to  the  different  elements  of 

1  H.,  P-  5'5- 


216       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

price.     Our  modern  systems  are  arranged  on  the 
opposite  plan  ;  they  follow  the  objective  order  of 
things,  not  the  subjective  order  of  thoughts.     It  is 
true  that  Adam  Smith  does  not  obey  the  rules  of 
induction  laid  down  by  Bacon  ;  but  then  no  science 
ever  was,  or  ever  could  be,  constructed  in  accord- 
ance with  those  rules.     The  same  remark  applies 
to  Scotch  physical  philosophy.     No  doubt,  it  was 
largely   hypothetical,   conjectural,   and  not  imme- 
diately  verified   by   experience.       But  when   was 
there  ever  a  physical  philosophy  of  which  the  same 
could  not  be  said  ?     Buckle  does,  indeed,  draw  a 
very  marked  distinction  between  the  literatures  of 
Scotland,  on  the  one  hand,  and  of  England  and 
France  on  the  other.     The  former  alone,  according 
to  him,  was  deductive ;  the  latter  two  were  inductive. 
But,  had  he  taken  pains  to  analyse  the  productions 
of  English  and  French  philosophy  from  the  logical 
point  of  view,  he  could  hardly  have  failed  to  notice 
how  little  they  differed,  in  that  respect,  from  the 
Scotch   systems.      He    admits    that    Harvey   and 
Newton  used  the  deductive  method.     But  Harvey 
and  Newton  between  them  represent  half  the  scien- 
tific English  intellect  of  their  century  ;  and  if  we 
add  Hobbes,  who  assuredly  reasoned  from  generals 
to  particulars  quite  as  much  as,  if  not  more  than, 
Adam    Smith,    the    balance   will    incline    heavily 
against  induction.      Observation   and   experiment 
were,  it  is  true,  the  favourite  occupations  of  English 
science  in  the  eighteenth  century  ;    but  these  are 
only  subsidiary  operations,  not  to  be  confounded 
with  the  generalising  process  itself. 

With  regard  to  the  French   philosophy  of  the 
same  period,  only  a  preconceived  theory  could  have 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       217 

made  anyone  blind  to  its  predominatingly  deductive 
character.  To  prove  this,  I  need  only  quote  what 
M.  Taine,  a  most  competent  authority,  has  stated 
on  the  subject : — 

Suivre  en  toute  recherche,  avec  toute  confiance,  sans 
reserve  ni  precaution,  la  mdthode  des  mathematiciens  ; 
extraire,  circonscrire,  isoler  quelques  notions  tres-simples 
et  tres-ge"n£rales,  puis,  abandonnant  1'expe'rience,  les 
comparer,  les  combiner,  et  du  compost  artificiel  ainsi 
obtenu,  de"duire  par  le  raisonnement  toutes  les  consd- 
quences  qu'il  enferme :  tel  est  le  proc£d6  naturel  de  1'esprit 
classique.  II  lui  est  si  bien  innd  qu'on  le  rencontre  e'gale- 
ment  dans  les  deux  siecles,  chez  Descartes,  Malebranche 
et  les  partisans  des  ide"es  pures  comme  chez  les  partisans 
de  la  sensation,  du  besoin  physique,  de  1'instinct  primitif, 
Condillac,  Rousseau,  Helve" ti us,  plus  tard  Condorcet 
Volney,  Sieyes,  Cabanis  et  Destutt  de  Tracy.  Ceux-ci 
ont  beau  se  dire  sectateurs  de  Bacon  et  rejeter  les  id£es 
inn^es  ;  avec  un  autre  point  de  depart  que  les  Carte"siens, 
ils  marchent  dans  la  meme  voie,  et  comme  les  Cartesiens, 
apres  un  leger  emprunt  ils  laissent  la  I'expe'rience.1 

It  may  be  added  that  pure  mathematics  and  astro- 
nomy, of  which  the  former  had  always  been  deduc- 
tive, and  the  latter  had  recently  become  so,  were 
the  sciences  most  successfully  cultivated  by  French- 
men at  this  period  ;  that  Haiiy,  the  great  mineral- 
ogist, was,  according  to  Buckle  himself,  indebted 
to  deduction  for  his  famous  discovery  ;  and  that 
the  igneous  and  aqueous  hypotheses  in  geology, 
which  are  given  as  instances  of  the  same  method 
when  respectively  employed  by  a  Scotchman  and  a 
German,  had  already  been  similarly  employed  by 
Buffon,  a  representative  French  thinker.  But  the 
syllogistic  character  of  the  French  intellect  is  so 

1  I* ' Ancien  Regime,  I.,  pp.  262-3. 


2i8       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

notorious  that  to  illustrate  it  at  greater  length  would 
be  a  waste  of  words. 

Such  a  profound  misconception  of  the  logical 
methods,  whether  considered  in  the  abstract  or  the 
concrete,  either  produced  or  originated  with  an 
equally  profound  misconception  of  their  socio- 
logical function.  In  order  to  carry  out  his  parallel 
between  the  economics  of  industry  and  the  economics 
of  intellect,  Buckle,  as  we  have  already  seen, 
associated  the  accumulation  of  knowledge  with  the 
use  of  the  deductive  method,  and  its  diffusion  with 
the  opposite  procedure.  Greece,  Scotland,  and 
Germany  'are  examples  of  the  former  ;  England, 
France,  and  America  of  the  latter.  The  nations 
belonging  to  the  first  group  are  remarkable  for 
great  breadth  and  boldness  of  speculation,  but  also 
for  the  deep  gulf  left  between  the  intellectual  classes 
and  the  mass  of  the  people ;  while,  in  nations 
belonging  to  the  second  group,  fewer  great  thinkers 
have  arisen,  but  enlightenment  has  been  more 
widely  diffused,  and,  in  England  at  least,  a  more 
regular  development  of  civilisation  has  been  secured. 
Three  distinct  grounds  are  offered  in  explanation 
of  this  alleged  fact.  Deductive  reasoning  rests  on 
unproved  assumptions.  So  also  does  theology, 
the  great  obstacle  to  intellectual  progress ;  therefore 
it  cannot  be  overthrown  by  a  method  partaking  so 
largely  of  its  own  spirit.  I  have  already  taken 
occasion  to  show  that  this  argument  is  invalid. 
The  assumptions  of  science,  not  being  accepted 
on  authority,  cannot  favour  authority  ;  and  false 
assumptions  may  be  dialectically,  as  well  as  experi- 
mentally, overthrown.  I  have  now  to  add  that, 
granting  the  French  philosophy  of  the  last  century 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       219 

to  have  been  both  deductive  and  sceptical,  the 
possibility  of  a  close  connexion  between  the  two 
characteristics  is  demonstrated  ;  and  a  further  proof 
will  be  found  in  the  circumstance  that  English 
scepticism  has  always  flourished  most  when  deduc- 
tion has  been  most  generally  employed.1 

Buckle's  second  explanation  is  much  more  plau- 
sible. Where  philosophers  are  removed  from  con- 
tact with  the  people,  they  will  remain  less  affected 
by  popular  prejudices  and  less  concerned  about  the 
consequences  of  their  teaching.  For  that  reason 
the  physical  schools  of  Ionia  and  Magna  Graecia 
were  far  more  daring  in  their  denials  than  the 
ethical  schools  of  Athens.  Nevertheless,  when  the 
people  have  once  become  thoroughly  sceptical  their 
sympathy  and  support  will  give  a  fresh  impetus  to 
advanced  thought  among  their  teachers.  That  is 
just  what  is  happening  in  Germany  now.2  On  the 
other  hand,  where  the  people  are  both  educated 
and  bigoted,  such  a  mere  trifle  as  logical  method 
will  not  prevent  them  from  exercising  the  sternest 
control  over  their  university  professors.  Hence 
the  official  science  of  Scotland  is  remarkable  for 
its  orthodoxy.  Even  Adam  Smith  was  obliged  to 
show  of  what  edifying  religious  applications  his 
moral  theories  admitted  ;  and  the  conservative 
tendencies  of  the  "  common-sense "  school  have 
already  been  mentioned. 

So  far  the  respective  influence  of  the  two  systems, 

1  In  1840-60  it  was  associated  with  the  first  entrance  of  German 
philosophy  ;  in  1860-80  with  deductive  theories  of  evolution  ;  and 
in  1880-1900  with  the  Hegelian  logic. 

2  Since  these  words  were  first  written  the  purely  intellectual 
evolution  of  German  thought  has  been  hampered  by  the  efforts 
of  the  rich  to  place  their    property  under  the   protection    of  a 
rehabilitated  Christianity. 


220       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

as  viewed  by  Buckle,  is  negative  rather  than  positive. 
The  one,  according  to  his  theory,  does,  and  the 
other  does  not,  remove  the  causes  of  popular  super- 
stition. The  one  does,  and  the  other  does  not, 
leave  the  foremost  minds  completely  free  to  work 
out  the  remotest  consequences  of  their  speculations. 
We  now  pass  to  the  positive  reason  why  induction 
should  contribute  more  powerfully  than  the  rival 
method  to  a  general  diffusion  of  knowledge.  We 
are  told  that  this  is  because  the  observations  on 
which  it  rests,  being  accessible  to  a  far  greater 
number  of  minds,  are  proportionately  better  appre- 
ciated and  more  readily  accepted  than  the  abstract 
reasonings  of  deduction.  Possibly  our  author  may 
have  had  in  his  mind  various  passages  where 
Aristotle  describes  induction  as  clearer,  more  per- 
suasive, and  more  popular  than  the  syllogism, 
which,  on  the  other  hand,  is  more  cogent,  and 
corresponds  better  to  the  order  of  natural  causation. 
Such  a  distinction,  however,  applies  rather  to  the 
loose  illustrative  induction  of  the  Greeks  than  to 
the  rigorous  observations  and  experiments  of 
modern  science,  where  the  facts  are  often  much 
more  abstruse  than  the  inferences  founded  upon 
them.  What  these  facts  are  can  only  be  known  to 
a  few ;  the  vulgar  either  remain  ignorant  of  their 
existence,  or  else  take  it  on  trust ;  and,  when  faith 
is  once  admitted,  all  kinds  of  conclusions  may 
profit  by  it  equally,  irrespective  of  the  evidence  on 
which  they  rest.  Again,  when  Buckle  says  that 
"  for  one  person  who  can  think  there  are  at  least  a 
hundred  persons  who  can  observe,  "'he  forgets  that 

1  ji.,  P.  582. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       221 

induction,  being  a  process  of  reasoning,  is  neces- 
sarily a  process  of  thought.  Nor  has  the  greater 
or  less  difficulty  of  understanding  and  practically 
applying  a  principle  when  once  discovered  anything 
to  do  with  the  kind  of  investigation  by  which  it  has 
been  reached,  or  with  the  kind  of  proof  by  which  it 
has  been  established.  It  might  also  be  easily  main- 
tained that,  while  the  tendency  of  generalisation  is 
to  lead  us  away  from  experience,  the  tendency  of 
deduction  is  to  lead  us  back  to  experience.  A  new 
truth  may  easily  commend  itself  to  the  popular 
mind  by  explaining  a  multitude  of  phenomena 
which  never  would  have  suggested  it  to  the  original 
discoverer.  Nothing  serves  to  extend  a  knowledge 
of  scientific  theories  so  much  as  the  inventions  by 
which  they  are  utilised.  But  both  the  making  and 
the  explaining  of  inventions  are  essentially  deduc- 
tive processes  ;  they  are  the  application  of  general 
laws  to  concrete  facts.  The  truth  is  that,  while  all 
knowledge  tends  spontaneously  to  spread,  the 
means  by  which  its  diffusion  can  be  hastened  have 
little  or  nothing  to  do  with  the  order  of  investiga- 
tions by  which  it  was  first  obtained.  The  remark 
may  seem  commonplace,  but  popular  education  is 
not  a  question  of  logical  method  at  all.  It  depends 
primarily  on  scholastic  machinery,  and  more 
remotely  on  religion,  literature,  and  government — 
that  is  to  say,  on  agencies  which  Buckle  has  sum- 
marily excluded  from  his  scheme  of  intellectual 
progress. 

The  theory  of  logical  economy  equally  breaks 
down  when  we  come  to  examine  its  historical  verifi- 
cation. It  is  not  true  that  Greek  philosophy  had 
no  power  to  diminish  popular  superstition.  One 


222       BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

need  only  compare  Euripides  with  ^Eschylus,  or 
even  Xenophon  with  Herodotus,  to  appreciate  its 
effect.  Without  it,  indeed,  the  conversion  of  the 
Roman  world  from  a  naturalistic  polytheism  to  an 
ethical  monotheism  could  never  have  been  accom- 
plished ;  without  it  Roman  jurisprudence  could  not 
have  been  rationalised ;  without  its  revival  mediaeval 
darkness  could  not  have  been  so  speedily  dissipated. 
The  case  of  Germany  is  still  stronger.  No  doubt 
the  state  of  German  middle-class  education  leaves 
much  to  be  desired,  and,  by  all  accounts,  is  rather 
deteriorating  than  improving.  No  doubt,  also, 
there  is  a  deep  division  between  the  intellectual 
classes  and  the  rest  of  the  people.  But  this  is  due 
far  more  to  the  literary  peculiarities  of  German 
philosophy  than  to  its  method  of  research.  The 
public  are  repelled  by  speculative  treatises,  not 
because  they  reason  from  first  principles,  but 
because  they  are  detestably  written.  A  profoundly 
speculative  work  like  the  Philosophy  of  the  Uncon- 
scious will  run  through  several  editions,  if  its  style 
be  but  tolerably  good.  For  the  same  reason 
Buckle's  own  book  has  had  a  great  success  in 
Germany — greater  even  than  in  England — although 
its  method  is  rather  deductive  than  inductive.  But 
whether  German  philosophy  be  popularly  studied 
or  not,  the  scepticism  now  diffused  through  every 
class  in  Germany  bears  witness  to  the  immense 
influence  which  it  exerts  on  public  opinion.  If  it 
is  to  be  taken  as  a  symptom  of  superstition  that  the 
Scotch  churches  are  "  still  filled  with  devout  and 
ignorant  worshippers,"1  it  must  surely  be  taken  as 

MI.,  pp.  589. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE       223 

a  symptom  of  the  contrary  that  the  German  churches 
are  so  scantily  attended.  Whatever  Buckle  says  of 
Scotland  is  just  what  a  continental  critic  would  say 
of  England,  and,  if  so,  every  such  charge  would 
redound  to  the  discredit  of  the  inductive  method 
which  is  supposed  to  have  regulated  our  civilisa- 
tion. Again,  one  would  suppose  from  Buckle's 
language  on  the  subject  that  the  northern  and 
southern  divisions  of  Great  Britain  were  sundered 
either  by  a  difference  of  language  or  by  an  im- 
passable frontier,  instead  of  reading  the  same 
books,  profiting  by  the  same  discoveries,  and 
carrying  on  an  uninterrupted  exchange  of  ideas. 
Whatever  our  literature  has  done  for  ourselves,  it 
ought  to  have  done,  although  perhaps  not  to  an 
equal  extent,  for  the  Scotch. 

A  less  ingenious  theorist  than  Buckle  would 
probably  have  been  contented  with  a  more  obvious 
explanation  of  whatever  bigotry  still  survives  in 
Scotland.  Having  once  struck  deeper  root,  the 
theological  or  puritanical  spirit  has  naturally 
remained  stronger  in  that  country  than  in  England 
or  France  ;  but  there  seems  no  reason  for  believing 
that  Scotland  compares  with  them,  in  that  respect, 
more  unfavourably  now  than  at  any  time  during 
the  last  three  centuries.  Granting  that  she  is  not 
yet  on  a  level  with  them,  it  does  not  follow  that  she 
has  not  made  equal  progress  in  the  same  period. 
And  if,  as  will  hardly  be  denied,  she  is  no  longer 
(for  good  or  evil)  in  the  religious  condition  of  the 
seventeenth  century,  why  should  not  the  change  be 
attributed,  at  least  in  part,  to  her  philosophy?  It 
is  no  little  matter  that  she  should  have  produced 
two  such  writers  as  Burns  and  Scott,  at  once  so 


224        BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE 

national,  so  popular,  and  so  filled  with  the  secular 
and  humanistic  spirit  of  modern  civilisation. 
Surely  their  appearance,  coming  when  it  did, 
together  with  that  of  the  numerous  minor  lumi- 
naries who  surrounded  them,  was  not  unconnected 
with  the  triumphs  already  won  by  their  prede- 
cessors in  the  more  abstract  spheres  of  thought. 
And  if  Scotch  literature  cannot  truly  be  said  to 
have  exercised  no  influence  on  the  national  spirit, 
neither  can  it  be  said  to  have  received  none  in 
return.1  If  the  Scotch  thinkers,  with  one  excep- 
tion, let  theology  alone,  this  was  not  from  any 
incapacity  on  their  part  to  call  in  question  its 
fundamental  assumptions,  but  because  they  either 
shared  its  beliefs,  or  were  deterred  by  the  strength 
of  public  opinion  from  openly  assailing  them. 
And  the  solitary  exception,  Hume,  differed  from 
his  contemporaries  not  because  he  employed  the 
inductive  method,  but  because  he  lived  a  good  deal 
abroad,  and  never  held  a  university  professorship 
at  home. 

We  have  seen,  then,  that  the  philosophy  of 
individualism,  when  carried  from  the  economics  of 
material  industry  into  the  more  complex  economics 
of  mental  energy,  gives  rise  to  misconceptions  and 
inconsistencies  at  every  step.  After  the  whole 
weight  of  human  progress  has  been  thrown  on 
advancing  knowledge,  the  basis  of  knowledge  itself 
is  so  isolated,  so  narrowed,  so  weakened  by  internal 
disintegration,  that  the  resulting  strain  terminates 
in  a  complete  collapse.  Where  the  analogy  of 
material  industry  might  have  been  profitably 

ML,  pp.  586. 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE      225 

employed,  it  is  neglected.  Where  the  laws  regulating 
production,  distribution,  and  governmental  inter- 
ference are  inapplicable,  they  are  forcibly  imposed 
on  the  phenomena.  Standing  by  the  ruined  edifice, 
we  ask  ourselves  on  what  other  plan  it  could  have 
been  built.  The  answer  is  that,  first  of  all,  the 
materials  which  our  architect  pushed  aside  must 
be  properly  utilised.  We  must  not  isolate  from 
each  other  forces  which  are  only  different  aspects 
of  a  fundamental  unity,  inseparable  in  the  com- 
pleted idea  no  less  than  in  the  living  fact.  We 
must  overcome  these  scholastic  antitheses  of  nature 
and  man,  morals  and  intellect,  imagination  and 
understanding,  emotion  and  reason,  induction  and 
deduction.  We  must  cease  to  look  on  the  govern- 
ing classes  as  eternal  blunderers  and  bullies.  In 
the  history  of  our  race,  everything  is  natural,  every- 
thing is  human,  everything  emotional,  imaginative, 
and  moral.  I  will  even  say  that,  using  the  word 
"  religion  "  to  denote  the  provisional  synthesis  of 
these  various  agencies,  and  extending  the  word 
"government"  to  all  forms  of  co-operation,  whether 
spontaneous  or  permanently  organised,  everything 
is  religious  and  governmental.  Still  more,  if 
possible,  must  we  recognise  within  each  depart- 
ment a  necessary  consensus  of  functions.  What- 
ever makes  for  the  accumulation  of  knowledge 
makes  also  for  its  diffusion,  and  reciprocally. 
Without  hypothesis  there  would  be  no  induction, 
and  without  experience  no  deduction.  The  one 
process,  as  Stanley  Jevons  has  shown,  is  an  inver- 
sion of  the  other.  Moreover,  the  generalisations 
with  which  our  inquiries  begin  are  partial  and 
precarious ;  their  growth  in  solidity  and  in  sweep 

Q 


is  proportioned  to  the  number  of  particulars  succes- 
fully  explained  by  their  application.  Neither  can 
the  intellect  of  any  nation  continue  to  advance 
without  perpetual  excitement  from  its  neighbours  ; 
and  it  is  here,  I  think,  that  we  can  learn  the  most 
valuable  lessons  from  Buckle.  He  was  right  in 
assigning  a  distinct  scientific  genius  to  each  of  the 
great  civilised  peoples  ;  but  the  narrowness  of  his 
own  economic  scheme  prevented  him  from  discern- 
ing what  were,  in  each  instance,  the  differential 
characteristics.  I  firmly  believe,  however,  that 
such  a  comparative  psychology  is  possible,  and 
that  even  now  its  outlines  might  be  traced.  For 
example,  at  the  beginning  of  this  essay  I  have 
attempted  to  show  that  there  is  a  unity  of  com- 
position running  through  the  most  divergent 
manifestations  of  our  modern  English  philosophy. 
But  this  is  a  vein  of  thought  which  cannot  be 
worked  out  any  farther  within  my  present  limits. 

It  would  have  been  impossible  to  tell  beforehand 
what  view  of  history  would  be  taken  by  the  studious 
son  of  an  English  merchant,  whose  opinions  were 
formed  during  the  great  agitation  for  free-trade. 
But,  when  we  know  by  experience  what  view  he 
actually  did  take,  the  theory  seems  to  be  in  perfect 
harmony  with  a  social  environment  of  which  it  was 
the  most  interesting,  though  not  the  most  highly 
organised  nor  the  most  enduring  expression.  In 
endeavouring  to  represent  Buckle's  philosophy  as 
something  more  than  a  mere  product  of  individual 
genius,  I  have  been  faithful,  amid  all  differences, 
to  that  most  general  principle  which  it  shares  with 
every  philosophy  worthy  of  the  name,  and  which  it 
has  contributed  so  powerfully  to  enforce.  Twenty- 


BUCKLE'S  ECONOMICS  OF  KNOWLEDGE      227 

five  years  ago  the  idea  of  law,  universal  and 
unbroken,  was  almost  a  paradox.  It  is  now  almost 
a  commonplace  ;  and  among  those  by  whose  efforts 
so  vast  a  change  in  public  opinion  was  accom- 
plished must  be  placed  the  name  of  this  noble 
thinker,  whose  learning  and  eloquence  have  not 
often  been  singly  equalled,  and,  in  their  combi- 
nation, have  never,  to  my  knowledge,  been 
approached. 


THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 
FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE 

GERMANY,  so  rich  in  every  other  kind  of  philo- 
sophical literature,  has  not  contributed  much  to 
ethical  thought.  Innumerable  Sittenlehren  have 
doubtless  flowed  from  the  laborious  pens  of  her 
professors ;  and  her  great  writers  have  given  utter- 
ance to  many  casual  thoughts  on  the  problems  of 
good  and  evil,  virtue  and  vice.  But,  with  the 
single  exception  of  Kant's  categorical  imperative, 
she  has  produced  nothing  that  the  world  in  general 
has  accepted  as  comparable  to  the  achievements 
in  the  same  field  of  Greece,  Rome,  and  Britain. 
Fichte  and  Schopenhauer  come  next  to  Kant  for 
interest  and  value.  They  cannot,  however,  be 
said  to  have  produced  much  impression  outside 
Germany ;  and  their  morality  is,  or  at  least  claims 
to  be,  so  closely  bound  up  with  their  metaphysics 
as  inevitably  to  suffer  by  detachment  from  their 
illusive  interpretations  of  existence.  And  even 
Kant  really  did  no  more  than  emphasise  and  pre- 
cisionise  the  idea  of  moral  obligation,  utterly  failing 
in  his  subsequent  attempt  to  fill  up  the  blank  form 
with  a  specific  sum  of  moral  prescriptions. 

This  speculative  weakness,  assuming  it  to  exist, 
is  not  easy  to  explain.  It  certainly  is  not  connected 
with  any  admitted  deficiency  on  the  practical  side. 
The  Germans  yield  to  no  other  great  nation  in 
moral  seriousness  and  dutifulness  ;  such  triumphs 

228 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  229 

as  they  have  achieved  in  war  and  peace  would  have 
been  impossible  to  a  selfish,  a  frivolous,  or  a  self- 
indulgent  race.  Nor  has  the  disposition  to  theorise 
on  what  they  do  ever  been  lacking  among  them  ; 
if  anything,  it  is  present  to  excess.  In  fact,  what 
one  misses  is  not  ethical  theorising,  but  originality 
and  life  in  the  theories. 

It  may  be  that  the  extreme  liberty  of  theological 
speculation  in  Germany,  combined  with  the  want 
of  political  liberty,  accounts  for  this  anomaly, 
as  the  reverse  conditions  account  for  the  extra- 
ordinary development  of  ethical  thought  in  the 
schools  of  Athens  and  in  Great  Britain.  For  at 
Athens  always,  as  among  ourselves  until  quite 
recently,  the  popular  religion  perverted  metaphysics 
into  an  abstract  mythology ;  while  the  popular 
respect  for  personal  liberty  gave  free  play  to  real 
or  ideal  reconstructions  of  life.  Plato  is  nearly  as 
cautious  as  Mill  when  he  touches  on  the  ultimate 
realities  of  nature  ;  Mill  is  nearly  as  bold  as  Plato 
when  he  sets  up  ultimate  standards  of  conduct. 
Whatever  freedom  of  thinking  for  ourselves  in 
cosmic  science  we  possess  is  due  to  Germany. 
Whatever  freedom  of  social  action  the  Germans 
possess  they  owe  to  us.  Their  Frauenbewegung  is 
there  to  prove  it. 

Within  our  own  memory  Germany  has  for  the 
first  time  produced  a  truly  ethical  genius — a  thinker 
with  whom  problems  of  conduct  constituted  from 
beginning  to  end  the  supreme,  if  not  the  sole, 
interest  of  life.  It  may  seem  strange  that  I  should 
say  so  much  of  the  daemonic  and  tragic  figure 
whose  name  stands  at  the  head  of  this  study. 
For  Friedrich  Nietzsche  habitually  posed  as  an 


230         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

immoralist,  an  emancipator  from  moral  restrictions, 
speaking  of  what  he  called  "  moraliri  "  as  a  deadly 
poison.  Nietzsche's  friends,  however,  a  most 
respectable  set  of  people,  were  not  in  the  least 
appalled  by  such  language,  nor  need  we  take  it  in 
very  deadly  earnest.  They  saw  in  it  no  more  than 
a  strong  way  of  saying  that  much  of  what  passes 
for  absolute  right  and  good  is  only  true  within 
certain  very  narrow  limitations,  and  that  there  are 
impulses,  supposed  to  be  very  virtuous,  which  tend 
on  the  whole  to  do  mankind  more  harm  than  good, 
as  well  as  impulses,  supposed  to  be  vicious,  that 
tend  to  exalt  it  in  the  scale  of  real  value. 

In  giving  this  paradoxical  form  to  his  morality 
Nietzsche  was  merely  following  the  constant  tradi- 
tion of  German  philosophy.  We  are  accustomed, 
and  for  that  matter  his  own  countrymen  are  accus- 
tomed, to  look  on  Hegel  as  a  quite  exceptional 
instance  of  what  may  be  done  in  the  way  of  setting 
common  sense  at  defiance.  But  Hegel,  with  his 
immanent  dialectic  of  self-contradictory  positions, 
reconciled  in  a  higher  synthesis,  only  brought  to  a 
point  what  had  been  more  or  less  the  method  of  all 
his  predecessors,  and  was  destined  to  be  the  method 
of  his  chief  successors  also.  Kant  naively  supposed 
that  he  was  dissipating  Hume's  scepticism  by  an 
audacity  of  negation  before  which  Hume  would  have 
shrunk  back  appalled  ;  and,  not  content  with  that 
performance,  he  proceeded  to  integrate  Free  Will 
with  a  system  which,  literally  to  all  appearances, 
left  Determinism  master  of  the  field.  Fichte,  after 
reducing  the  non-ego — that  is,  the  whole  objective 
world — to  an  assumption  of  the  ego,  sets  the  ego  the 
task  of  negating  its  own  negation,  which  is  at  the 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  231 

i"  -4 
same  time  the  condition  of  its  existence,  with  the 

comfortable  assurance  that  a  consummation  which 
would  be  fatal  to  both  parties  needs  all  eternity  for 
its  achievement.  More  impatient  than  his  master, 
Schelling  boldly  identifies  the  two  under  the  names 
of  "  object  "  and  "  subject,"  and  the  world  goes  on 
as  before — indeed,  according  to  him,  always  has 
gone  on  precisely  because  it  always  knew  that  there 
was  no  difference  between  them.  Schopenhauer, 
after  disdainfully  rejecting  the  systems  of  his  fellow 
metaphysicians  as  so  many  absurdities,  sets  up  a 
new  absolute,  which,  after  willing  -itself  out  of 
nonentity  into  existence,  learns  from  sad  experience 
the  desirability  of  willing  itself  back  from  existence 
into  nonentity  again.  And  to  this  contradiction, 
which  lies  at  the  very  basis  of  his  system,  he  adds 
another  not  less  serious  contradiction  in  working 
out  its  details.  While  asserting  the  substantial 
identity  of  all  our  individual  wills  with  one  another 
and  with  the  universal  will  of  which  they  are  so 
many  partial  manifestations,  he  yet  limits  the  self- 
negating  power  of  each  will  to  itself.  On  entering 
into  Nirvana  I  redeem  myself  alone  ;  the  infinite 
anguish  of  the  world  goes  on  as  before.  Yet  at 
the  same  time  the  short  cut  of  suicide  is  barred  to 
me  by  the  solemn  warning  that  self-inflicted  death 
amounts  to  a  rebellious  reaffirmation  of  the  will 
which  it  seems  to  deny. 

This  immanent  self-contradiction  of  German 
thought,  although  it  first  became  open  and  scan- 
dalous in  Kant's  criticism,  is  older  than  Kant. 
To  go  no  further  back,  it  already  afflicts  the 
monadology  of  Leibnitz.  Those  minute  individual 
existences  of  which  the  world  consists  have  no 


232         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

windows  opening  on  the  world,  nor  do  they  receive 
influences  of  any  kind  from  one  another ;  but  all 
go  on  developing  at  the  same  pace,  each  by  virtue 
of  an  evolutionary  principle  peculiar  to  itself. 
Thus,  although  every  monad  reflects  the  universe 
at  an  angle  of  its  own,  it  has  no  reason  to  believe 
that  this  phantasmagoria  represents  an  objective 
reality,  for  its  whole  experience  would  be  the  same 
supposing  no  such  reality  to  be  present ;  and 
although,  by  the  hypothesis,  solipsism  is  not  true, 
there  seems  to  be  no  evidence  of  its  untruth. 

It  appears,  then,  that  a  German  moral  philo- 
sophy, to  be  thoroughly  native  and  smacking  of 
the  soil,  must  at  once  affirm  and  deny  morality. 
We  shall,  therefore,  not  be  surprised  to  find  that 
Nietzsche,  while  offering  a  brilliant  exception  to 
the  rule  that  his  country  does  not  breed  pure 
moralists,  confirms  the  rule  that  her  philosophies 
willingly  assume  the  form  of  a  square  circle — that 
bold  construction  which  Professor  Meinong,  no 
doubt  on  the  strength  of  long  experience,  has 
recently  declared  to  be  quite  conceivable. 

Furthermore,  it  is  necessary,  or  at  least  tradi- 
tional, that  a  German  philosopher,  to  be  original, 
should  not  only  end  by  contradicting  himself,  but 
that  he  should  begin  by  contradicting  another 
German,  preferentially  his  own  master.  And  we 
shall  find  that  the  author  of  Zarathustra  was  quite 
up  to  the  mark  in  this  respect  also.  The  teacher 
to  whose  school  he  first  belonged,  and  who  after- 
wards became  the  chief  object  of  his  attacks,  was 
Schopenhauer.  Nietzsche  was  twenty  years  of  age 
and  a  university  student  when,  in  1865,  he  first 
came  across  the  great  pessimist's  writings,  at  that 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  233 

time  only  in  the  first  dawn  of  their  popularity. 
What  chiefly  attracted  him  seems  to  have  been 
their  high  literary  merit  and  the  sincerity  of  their 
author — a  sincerity  displayed  above  all  in  his 
attitude  towards  theology.  Schopenhauer  really 
stood  no  farther  from  the  central  beliefs  of  Chris- 
tianity than  Hegel,  if  as  far  ;  but  he  never  bowed 
down  in  the  temple  of  Rimmon  to  the  extent  of 
passing  himself  off  as  an  orthodox  Lutheran  or  other 
Churchman  of  any  kind.  He  venerated  the  figure 
of  Christ ;  but  there  could  be  no  doubt  that  his 
metaphysics  excluded  the  notion  of  a  God  and  of  a 
future  life  just  as  much  as  they  excluded  the  possi- 
bility of  a  happy  life  on  earth.  And  that  was  why 
the  bankruptcy  of  Hegelianism  after  1848  left  the 
system  of  Kant's  rival  continuator  in  a  position 
no  better  than  before.  For  to  the  pietistic  and 
obscurantist  reaction  that  succeeded  the  abortive 
revolution  free  thought  was  as  hateful  under  the 
form  of  atheistic  pessimism  as  under  the  form  of 
optimistic  pantheism.  We  are  apt  to  look  on 
Germany  as  the  great  emancipator  from  super- 
stition, and  I  have  already  acknowledged  the  great- 
ness of  our  own  indebtedness  to  her  delivering 
example ;  but  in  this  instance,  as  in  the  early 
eighteenth  century,  she  seems  to  have  been  led 
out  of  darkness  by  light  from  the  West,  by  the 
influence  of  Buckle  and  Darwin,  and  by  Kenan's 
Vie  de  Jesus,  followed  up  as  this  was  by  Strauss's 
second  Leben  Jesu.  At  any  rate,  a  far  more  liberal 
tone  prevailed  in  the  sixties  than  in  the  previous 
decade  ;  and  Schopenhauer's  philosophy  profited  by 
the  new  spirit,  which  it  also  stimulated  in  the  highest 
degree,  to  achieve  a  rapid  and  dazzling  success. 


234         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

Nietzsche  was  the  son  of  a  Protestant  pastor, 
and  belonged  on  his  mother's  side  also  to  a  clerical 
family.  Brought  up  on  strict  religious  principles, 
he  had  learned  to  set  a  particular  value  on  veracity, 
regarding  it,  rather  oddly,  as  a  specially  Christian 
virtue,  whereas,  in  theory  at  least,  it  is  more  Greek 
than  Christian.  He  also  was,  or  believed  himself 
to  be,  descended  from  a  noble  Polish  family  exiled 
on  account  of  their  religion  early  in  the  eighteenth 
century ;  so  that  in  his  case  the  obligation  of 
fidelity  to  truth  was  heightened  by  the  conscious- 
ness of  representing  an  aristocratic  and  martyr 
tradition.  Finally,  Nietzsche  had  chosen  classical 
philology  for  his  profession,  and  had  obtained  a 
chair  at  Basel  when  still  under  twenty-four,  so  that 
for  some  years  afterwards  his  life  was  chiefly  devoted 
to  the  study  of  Greek  literature  and  philosophy. 
Now,  while  giving,  as  I  have  said,  more  credit  to 
Christianity  than  it  deserves  as  a  discipline  in 
truthfulness,  he  still  acknowledges  that  "the  Greeks 
had  the  faithfulness  and  the  veracity  of  children."1 

At  a  much  later  period  our  immoralist  loved  to 
maintain  that  the  sincerity  which,  as  a  religious 
habit,  revolts  against  the  profession  of  a  false 
religion  is,  as  a  moral  habit,  destructive  of  the 
morality  which  is  no  more  than  a  convention. 
And  he  also  maintained,  in  contemptuous  reference 
to  George  Eliot,  that  to  believe  in  Christian  morality 
apart  from  Christianity  is  a  weak  inconsistency.2 
It  was  both  ungracious  and  unjust  to  taunt  our 

1  WW.,  IX.,  p.  104  ;  written  in  1871.  In  the  references 
W W.  —  Nietzsche's  Werke,  Leipzig-,  1895,  1904,  large  8vo  ed.  ; 
W.  a.  M.  —  Wille  zur  Macht,  Leipzig,  1901,  small  8vo  ed.;  Leben 
=Das  Leben  Fr.  Nietzsches,  von  Elizabeth  Forster-Nietzsche. 

>   WW.,  VIII.,  p.  120. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  235 

great  ethical  novelist  with  being  characteristically 
English  or  womanish  in  this  respect;  for  Schopen- 
hauer, who  was  Continental  and  virile,  had  made 
the  same  mistake,  if  mistake  it  is,  and  Nietzsche 
had  at  first  followed  his  master's  example.  Accept- 
ing pessimism  to  this  extent,  that  the  search  for 
happiness  must  be  abandoned  as  a  chimera,  in  his 
work  on  The  Origin  of  Tragedy  (published  1872),  he 
tells  us  that  a  chief  note  of  tragic  culture  is  "an 
attempt  to  make  the  sufferings  of  the  world  our  own 
by  an  effort  of  sympathetic  love."1  Greek  tragedy 
preaches  a  gospel  of  universal  harmony,  whereby 
everyone  feels  himself  not  merely  united,  fused, 
and  reconciled,  but  absolutely  one  with  his  neigh- 
bour.2 And  in  a  subsequent  work  on  The  Study  of 
History,  among  the  redeeming  representatives  of 
humanity,  he  names  not  only  those  who  have 
passed  through  existence  in  pride  and  strength,  or 
in  profound  meditation,  but  also  those  who  have 
come  "  to  pity  and  help."3  Later  again  he  tells  us 
that  "  there  is  not  enough  goodness  and  love  in  the 
world  to  let  them  be  wasted  on  imaginary  objects."4 
And  he  had  previously  made  the  perfectly  sane  and 
sufficiently  obvious  remark  that  goodness  and  pity 
fortunately  do  not  depend  on  the  decay  and  growth 
of  religion  ;  although  "practical  morality  will  suffer 
by  its  collapse."  At  the  same  time,  this  depen- 
dence of  action  on  religious  sanctions  deprives  it, 
in  his  opinion,  of  all  ethical  value.5 

Returning  to  Schopenhauer,  it  is  noticeable  that 
Nietzsche  accepted   his  teaching  not  only  on  the 


1    WW.,  I.,  p.  128.  2  Ibid.,  p.  24.  3  ibid.,  p.  2c 

4  Menschliches,  Allzumenschliches,  p.  129;    WW.,  II.,  133. 

5  WW..  X..  o.  214. 


236         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

ethical,  but  also  on  the  metaphysical,  side.  His 
work  on  The  Origin  of  Tragedy  is  a  bold  attempt  to 
read  the  philosophy  of  pessimism  into  the  Greek 
tragic  drama.  It  arose,  according  to  him,  from  a 
combination  of  the  worship  of  Dionysus  with  the 
worship  of  Apollo.  The  one  god  represents  the 
element  of  Will  and  the  other  the  element  of  Repre- 
sentation in  his  master's  great  work.  Dionysus 
stands  for  "  that  original  and  eternal  pain  which  is 
the  sole  substance  of  the  world,"  "  the  true  reality 
and  primordial  One  with  its  eternal  suffering  and 
self-contradiction,  seeking  for  deliverance  by  the 
creation  of  beautiful  appearance — the  Apolline 
element  of  Greek  tragedy."1 

Schopenhauer  had  conceived  music  as  a  direct 
interpretation  of  that  suffering  Will  which  is  the 
true  substance  of  the  world,  whereas  the  other  arts 
have  for  their  material  the  series  of  Platonic  Ideas, 
the  forms  and  forces  of  nature  which  are  one  degree 
farther  removed  from  its  absolute  reality.  And 
Nietzsche  conceives  Greek  tragedy  as  having 
originated  from  music  precisely  because  it  furnishes 
such  an  artistic  revelation  of  the  awful  secret  at  the 
heart  of  things.  Now,  Richard  Wagner  had  long 
before  him  enthusiastically  adopted  a  theory  so 
flattering  to  his  own  art ;  and,  partly,  no  doubt,  on 
the  strength  of  their  philosophical  agreement,  he 
and  the  young  professor  of  philology  at  Basel  had 
become  fast  friends,  the  two  frequently  spending 
their  week-ends  together  at  the  house  of  the  great 
composer  near  Lucerne.  Indeed,  Wagner  is  so 
glorified  as  a  modern  ^Eschylus  in  The  Origin  of 

'   WW.,  I.,  pp.  34  and  35. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  237 

Tragedy  that,  rather  to  its  author's  annoyance,  the 
general  public  regarded  that  work  chiefly  as  a 
rapturous  panegyric  on  the  music  of  the  future. 

As  an  interpretation  of  Greek  art  The  Origin  of 
Tragedy  has  no  value,  and  was  very  properly  con- 
demned by  one  destined  to  become  in  after  years 
the  foremost  Hellenist  of  his  age,  Wilamowitz- 
Mollendorff.  With  regard  to  Wagner,  no  more 
need  be  said  than  that  Nietzsche  soon  came  to  form 
a  very  different  opinion  of  his  performances,  giving 
music  a  much  lower  place  among  the  means  of 
culture,  and  a  much  lower  place  among  musicians 
to  that  particular  composer.  But  in  a  general  way 
Wagner's  influence  proved  of  decisive  importance 
for  his  philosophical  development.  Combined  with 
the  study  of  Schopenhauer  and  of  the  Greeks,  it 
led  him  to  conceive  the  promotion  of  genius  as  the 
highest  form  of  moral  effort.  This,  as  we  shall 
see,  was  by  no  means  identical  with  his  subsequent 
theory  of  the  superman,  although  it  led  the  way  to 
that  theory  ;  nor  was  it  at  first  inconsistent  either 
with  pessimism  or  with  the  common  morality. 
Assuming  that  the  contemplation  of  beautiful  and 
sublime  objects  is  the  chief,  if  not  the  sole,  refresh- 
ment available  in  a  world  of  universal  and  incurable 
misery,  the  power  of  creating  beauty,  which  we  call 
genius,  is  a  valuable  asset  for  humanity,  and  ought 
by  every  means  to  be  encouraged. 

Unfortunately,  the  moral  end  of  genius  has, 
so  far,  been  very  imperfectly  fulfilled.  "  Artists 
undoubtedly  create  their  works  for  the  benefit  of 
other  men  ;  and  yet  none  will  ever  understand  and 
love  their  works  as  they  did."  It  would  have  been 
a  better  arrangement  had  the  relation  been  reversed, 


238         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

so  that  the  effect  should  far  exceed  the  cause.1 
Such  blunders  are,  however,  to  be  expected. 
"  Nature  always  wills  the  common  good,  but  is 
incapable  of  choosing  the  best  means  for  that 
purpose.  She  shoots  philosophers  like  arrows  at 
the  human  race,  in  the  hope  that  they  will  strike 
and  stick  somewhere  " — whereas  they  are  mostly 
wasted.2 

Nature,  then,  must  be  taught  better — she  must 
receive  a  more  intelligent  direction  ;  and  here 
morality  intervenes,  although  not  quite  according 
to  the  highest  ideals  now  prevalent.  "  The  goal  of 
human  endeavour  has  hitherto  been  sought  in  the 
happiness  of  all  men  or  of  the  majority,  or  in  the 
development  of  great  communities  ;  and  under  this 
false  persuasion  people  will  be  found  ready  enough 
to  give  their  lives  for  the  State  ;  whereas  they 
would  hesitate  to  make  the  sacrifice  were  it 
demanded,  not  by  the  State,  but  by  an  individual. 
As  if  value  and  significance  were  to  be  determined 
by  counting  heads!"  A  much  mistaken  view, 
thinks  our  author,  with  the  old  bias  of  a  university 
teacher.  "  Humanity  must  be  ever  working  at  the 
production  of  great  individuals  :  that,  and  nothing 

else,  is  its  task a  consideration  suggested   by 

every  species  of  animal  and  plant."3  In  our  case 
education  must  supplement  nature.  Young  men 
should  be  taught  to  compensate  for  their  own 
imperfection  and  failure  by  contributing  to  the 
development  of  something  higher  and  more  human 
than  themselves.'4  But  the  hope  thus  awakened 
soon  droops.  "  It  is  hard  to  produce  such  a  state 

1    WW.,  I.,  p.  467  sq.  *  Loc.  cit. 

3  Ibid.,  p.  442.  «  P.  443. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  239 

of  mind,  for  love  alone  can  inspire  the  conscious- 
ness of  one's  own  imperfection  ;  and  love  cannot 
be  taught."1  Indeed,  things  are  tending  in  a 
directly  opposite  direction.  Writing  in  1874, 
Nietzsche  tells  us  that  "  the  world  was  never  more 
worldly,  never  poorer  in  love  and  goodness."2  A 
common  view  is  to  value  culture  as  a  means  for 
procuring  its  possessor  the  greatest  possible  amount 
of  earthly  happiness.3  Or  again,  the  selfishness  of 
the  State  demands  that  all  culture  shall  be  made 
instrumental  to  its  service  and  aggrandisement. 
Christianity  in  particular,  which  began  as  one  of 
the  purest  expressions  of  the  impulse  towards 
culture,  "  has  been  diverted  from  the  production  of 
saints  into  a  means  for  the  manufacture  of  useful 
citizens."4  Science  offers  no  help;  it  is  "  cold,  dry, 
loveless  ;  it  ignores  the  deep  sense  of  dissatisfaction 
and  longing."5  And  "  such  is  the  hatred  for  origin- 
ality now  prevailing  that  Socrates  could  not  have 
lived  among  us,  or  at  least  not  lived  to  seventy."6 

It  will  be  seen  from  the  above  extracts  that,  up 
to  the  age  of  thirty  at  least,  Nietzsche  still  accepted 
those  altruistic  ideals  which  in  later  life  he  was 
never  weary  of  denouncing.  In  this  respect  he 
followed  Schopenhauer,  who  contrived  to  combine 
the  most  absolute  disinterestedness  in  theory  with 
the  most  absolute  selfishness  in  practice.  A  really 
consistent  pessimism  would  remain  neutral  as 
between  egoism  and  altruism,  since  the  furtherance 
of  life  is  of  equally  little  value  to  myself  and  to 
others.  But  Nietzsche  had  never  been  a  pessimist 
in  the  complete  or  Hindoo  sense  of  cultivating  the 

'    P.  444.  »    P.   42I.  3  p.  447. 

*  P.  448.  s  P.  4S3.  &  P.  462. 


24o         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

will  not  to  live,  regarding  such  an  aspiration  as 
self-contradictory,  or  at  least  unthinkable.  And, 
apart  from  logic,  his  personal  experiences  were 
such  as  to  disgust  him  with  the  master's  ideal  of 
pleasure  as  what  alone  makes  life  worth  living. 
While  still  a  student  at  Leipzig  the  Prussian 
military  law  obliged  him  to  serve  for  a  time  in  the 
artillery.  His  career  as  a  gunner  did  not  last  long, 
for  a  rupture  of  the  thoracic  muscles,  caused  by  the 
attempt  to  mount  a  restive  horse,  resulted  in  an 
illness  that  incapacitated  him  from  continued  service 
in  the  ranks,  and  a  short  attendance  with  the 
ambulance  corps  before  Metz  in  1870  had  a  still 
more  ruinous  effect  on  his  constitution.  But  even 
so  much  of  a  soldier's  life,  chiming  in  well  with 
the  aristocratic  and  fighting  instincts  of  his  Polish 
blood,  gave  the  young  professor  a  new  idea  of  the 
possible  value  of  life.  If  existence  yielded  no 
happiness,  it  still  afforded  the  joy  of  victoriously 
resisting  the  assaults  of  pain  ;  and  from  that  heroic 
conflict,  continued  in  after  years  through  intense 
agonies  of  suffering,  he  came  forth  an  optimist, 
continuing  in  his  faith  to  the  end. 

Hellenic  studies  no  doubt  contributed  to  his  con- 
version. In  his  first  work,  when  still  under  the 
influence  of  Wagner  and  Schopenhauer,  Nietzsche 
had  falsely  interpreted  Greek  tragedy  as  a  pessim- 
istic manifesto, and,  by  a  strangely  perverted  reading 
of  literary  history,  he  had  ascribed  its  dissolution 
to  the  opposite  teaching  of  Socrates  and  Euripides. 
We  have  already  come  across  a  passage  indicating 
a  much  more  favourable  view  of  Socrates  ;  and  in 
another  passage,  written  about  1877,  a  good  time 
is  looked  forward  to  when  Xenophon's  Memorabilia 


NIfiTZSCrfE  24f 

will  be  substituted  for  the  Bible  as  a  manual  of 
rational  morality.1  Earlier  still  the  age  had  been 
referred  for  its  models  to  the  old  Greek  world,  "  so 
great,  so  natural,  and  so  human."2  It  was  through 
the  higher  power  of  their  moral  nature  that  the 
Greeks  were  victorious  over  all  other  civilisations.3 
Familiarity  with  Hellenic  ideals  inevitably  drew 
our  philosopher  away  from  Richard  Wagner's 
romanticist  views  of  art  and  life.  The  breach 
between  them  began  at  the  Bayreuth  festival  of 
1876,  when  some  traits  of  petty  vanity  and  selfish- 
ness in  the  master's  character  first  became  painfully 
apparent  to  his  young  admirer.  What  made  it 
irremediable  was  a  question  of  morality  and  religion. 
Up  to  1874  Wagner  had  been  a  declared  and  un- 
compromising atheist.  During  the  last  years  of 
his  life  he  developed  a  sort  of  mystical  Christianity, 
in  which  the  ideas  of  a  human  fall  and  recovery 
through  atonement  played  the  most  conspicuous 
part.  His  opera  Parsifal  was  intended  to  illus- 
trate the  new  departure,  and  the  plans  for  its 
composition  formed  the  subject  of  frequent  con- 
versations between  himself  and  a  group  of  friends 
at  Sorrento  in  the  autumn  of  1876.  Nietzsche, 
who  was  one  of  these,  listened  with  dismay  and 
disgust  to  what  he  considered  an  insincere  betrayal 
of  the  convictions  they  had  once  held  in  common,4 
all  the  more  offensive  because  it  was  symptomatic 
of  a  general  pietistic  reaction  set  up  by  the  higher 
classes  in  Germany,  with  a  view  both  to  consoli- 
dating the  new  Empire  and  resisting  the  spread  of 
Socialism. 

1  WW.,  III.,  P.  248.         2  ww.,  I.,  P.  352. 

3  Ibid.,  384.  «  Leben,  II.,  p.  857. 

R 


242         THE  MORALS  O£  AN  IMMORALIST— 

Wagner's  apostasy  seems  to  have  had  the  effect 
of  driving  Nietzsche  into  an  attitude  of  more  open 
hostility  towards  Christianity,  and,  indeed,  towards 
all  theism.  Since  religion  could  exercise  such  a 
fatal  effect  on  the  intellectual  integrity  of  genius,  it 
was  not  only  false,  but  dangerous,  and  ought  to  be 
destroyed.  His  next  work,  Menschlich.es,  Allzu- 
menschliches  (So  Very  Human),  appeared  in  1878, 
the  centenary  of  Voltaire's  death,  and  is  dedicated 
to  his  memory.  It  consists  of  loose  critical  notes 
couched  in  the  aphoristic  form  which  the  writer 
afterwards  came  to  handle  with  such  supreme 
mastery,  and  which  alone  suited  his  disconnected 
and  irresponsible  mode  of  thinking.  The  general 
trend  of  reflection  offers  a  series  of  striking  con- 
trasts to  the  writer's  earlier  points  of  view ;  although 
an  attentive  consideration  shows  that  the  transition 
was  already  being  silently  prepared  towards  the  close 
of  the  first  period.  In  dealing  with  so  very  per- 
sonal a  writer  we  shall  best  understand  the  evolu- 
tion of  his  ideas  by  constant  reference  to  the  events 
of  his  life. 

It  will  be  remembered  that  in  embracing  pessi- 
mism our  moralist  had  also  embraced  the  ethical 
ideal  of  universal  benevolence  associated  with  it  by 
Schopenhauer  and  the  Hindoos  ;  and  how,  under 
the  concurrent  influence  of  Wagner  and  the 
Greeks,  he  had  sought  to  concentrate  the  passion 
for  disinterested  self-devotion  on  the  systematic 
culture  of  genius.  Unfortunately,  the  only  two 
great  men  that  he  recognised  as  such  in  recent 
history  had  both  proved  false  guides ;  and  this 
seems  in  the  first  instance  to  have  made  him 
distrust  genius  as  a  social  danger.  Its  worship, 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  243 

he  remarks,  is  a  survival  of  the  adoration  formerly 
given  to  gods,  and  to  kings  as  their  representatives. 
"  The  elevation  of  individuals  into  superhuman 
beings  encourages  the  idea  that  large  sections  of 
the  people  are  baser  and  more  barbarous  than  they 
really  are."1  Genius  even  "acts  as  an  enemy  of 
truth  by  keeping  up  an  intense  ardour  of  conviction 
and  discouraging  the  cautious  and  modest  tone  of 
science";2  while  "never  to  have  changed  one's 
opinions  is  the  sign  of  having  remained  in  a 
belated  stage  of  culture."3 

As  a  consequence  of  the  new  departure,  science, 
so  lately  denounced  for  its  coldness  and  dryness, 
now  takes  the  place  of  art  as  the  leading  means  of 
culture.  Before  the  breach  with  Wagner  signs  of 
a  growing  preference  for  pure  knowledge  had  not 
been  wanting.  We  had  been  told  in  a  truly 
positivist  spirit  that  "  the  proper  question  for  philo- 
sophy is  to  determine  how  far  things  are  unalter- 
able ;  the  task  of  improving  them,  in  so  far  as  they 
can  be  improved,  may  then  be  fearlessly  under- 
taken."4 The  note  of  moral  enthusiasm  will  not 
be  overlooked.  It  had  already  been  associated 
with  a  higher  standard  of  intellectualism  in  the 
reminder  that  "  the  most  fearful  sufferings  have 
been  brought  on  mankind  by  the  impulse  to  be 
just  without  judgment  ;  so  that  nothing  is  more 
requisite  for  the  general  welfare  than  the  widest 
possible  dissemination  of  judgment."5 

Wagner  was  intensely  German,  intensely  anti- 
French  ;  and  Nietzsche,  when  he  wrote  about  the 

1  WW.,  II.,  p.  340.  2  Ibid.,  p.  41 1. 

3  ibid.,  P.  407.  4  ww.,  i.,  P.  514. 

s  Ibid.,  p.  329. 


244         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

origin  of  tragedy,  shared  his  patriotic  views.  He 
then  looked  forward  to  "  the  regeneration  of  the 
German  soul  by  the  elimination  of  every  Latin 
element  under  the  external  stimulus  of  the  last 
war,  and  inwardly  by  the  example  of  Luther, 
together  with  all  our  great  poets  and  artists."1 
His  expectations  were  not  fulfilled  ;  at  any  rate, 
Germany  was  not  regenerated,  but  the  contrary  ; 
and  it  is  remarkable  that,  on  looking  back  in  1878 
to  the  period  after  the  war,  what  most  offended  him 
was  the  moral  corruption  of  his  countrymen. 
Their  notions  of  right  and  wrong  were  unsettled  ; 
their  rage  for  luxury  and  enjoyment  knew  no 
bounds  ;  their  sensuality  was  disgusting  ;  nearly 
every  German  had  become  a  degree  more  dishonest, 
sycophantic,  avaricious,  and  frivolous  than  before.2 
A  general  lowering  of  intellectual  standards  is  also 
complained  of,  but  this  is  only  another  symptom  of 
moral  decay.  With  Wagner  the  last  hope  failed, 
and  Nietzsche  turned  to  foreign  countries,  especially 
to  England  and  France,  for  what  Germany  could 
not  supply. 

In  the  writings  of  the  second  period  the  refer- 
ences to  England  are  particularly  complimentary. 
She  is  "now  [1877-1878]  unmistakably  ahead  of 
all  other  nations  in  philosophy,  natural  science, 
history,  discoveries,  and  the  spread  of  culture." 
This  is  due  to  the  strength  of  individual  character, 
resulting  from  a  long  national  inheritance,  enjoyed 
by  her  great  men  of  science,  and  from  their  in- 
dependence of  learned  association.3  Furthermore, 
"  we  must  allow  English  writers  the  credit  of  having 

'  WW.,  I.,  pp.  164-65.  *  WW.,  XL,  pp.  94-95- 

3  Ibid.,  p.  68. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  245 

made  admirable  contributions  towards  an  ideal 
scientific  literature  for  the  people.  Their  hand- 
books are  the  work  of  their  most  distinguished 
scholars — men  of  whole-minded,  rich,  and  generous 
natures."1  Nor  is  it  only  among  men  of  learn- 
ing that  this  strength  of  character  is  exhibited. 
"  English  artisans  work  hard  at  their  trade  not 
merely  for  profit  but  for  power,  and  not  merely  for 
power  but  for  the  utmost  freedom  and  individual 
distinction."2  Schopenhauer  is  now  praised  for 
the  appreciation  of  hard  facts,  the  determination  to 
be  clear  and  reasonable,  that  often  make  him  seem 
so  much  of  an  Englishman  and  so  little  of  a 
German."3 

Everything  written  at  this  time  bears  what  on 
the  Continent  is  called  a  positivist  impress. 
Nietzsche  does  not  seem  to  have  read  Comte,  but 
he  refers  admiringly  to  him  as  "that  great  and 
honest  Frenchman  with  whom  no  German  or 
English  thinker  can  compare  for  comprehension 
and  mastery  of  the  exact  sciences,"  while  totally 
rejecting  the  religious  and  constructive  element 
of  his  teaching.4  For  himself  our  philosopher 
professes  to  know  little  about  the  results  of  science ; 
"  but  that  little  has  been  inexhaustibly  serviceable 
in  clearing  up  obscurities  and  abolishing  former 
modes  of  thought  and  action."5  As  the  quintes- 
sence of  our  positive  knowledge  three  propositions 
are  stated  :  (i)  There  is  no  God  ;  (2)  there  is  no 
moral  world — i.e.,  no  retribution  for  good  or  evil 
conduct ;  (3)  good  and  evil  are  determined  by  the 

1  WW.,  III.,  p.  102.  *  WW.,  II.,  p.  357. 

»  WW.,  V.,  p.  130.  *  WW.,  IV.,  pp.  348-49. 

s  WW.,  XL,  p.  402. 


246         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

ideals  and  directions  of  life,  the  best  part  of  these 
being  inherited,  but  with  a  possibility  that  the 
resulting  judgments  may  be  falsified  by  the 
demands  of  our  actual  ideals.1  With  the  disap- 
pearance of  theism  pessimism  ceases  to  have  any 
meaning.  The  world  is  neither  good  nor  bad  ; 
such  notions  apply  only  to  human  beings,  and  in 
their  ordinary  acceptation  cannot  rightly  be  applied 
even  to  these.2  For  "free  will  is  an  illusion";3 
"  that  intelligible  freedom  "  under  cover  of  which 
Schopenhauer  sought  to  rehabilitate  moral  respon- 
sibility is  a  fable;4  and  "the  thing  in  itself"  an 
illegitimate  inference  from  phenomena.5  In  fact, 
Schopenhauer's  metaphysic  was  simply  a  revival 
of  mediaeval  Christianity,  due  to  want  of  scientific 
knowledge.6 

At  first  the  new  ardour  for  destructive  criticism 
extends  to  morality,  which  we  are  told  in  so  many 
words  is  annihilated  together  with  religion  by  our 
way  of  looking  at  things.7  But  the  reason  given 
is  merely  that  science  can  admit  no  motives  except 
pleasure  and  pain,  usefulness  and  injury.8  Such 
an  arbitrary  restriction  seems  itself  to  be  a  survival 
of  theology  ;  and,  in  fact,  it  is  traceable  to  the 
French  freethinking  literature  of  the  seventeenth 
and  eighteenth  centuries,  which  Nietzsche  was  now 
studying  with  delight.  He  observes  truly  enough 
that  "  in  the  metaphysical  sense  there  are  no  sins, 
but  also  no  virtues,"9  without  remembering  that 
metaphysical  values  have  been  abolished.  His 
aphoristic  method  had  the  advantage  of  making 

1   WJF..XI.,  p.  134.     *   W W.,  II.,  p.  46.  3  ibid.,  p.  36. 

4    P.  63.  5    Pp.   3,   sq,  6    p    ^ 

i    WW.,  II.,  p.  52.        •  Loc.  cit.  9  Ibid.,  p.  77. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  247 

composition  easy  for  himself  and  fruitful  of  easy 
reading  for  others  ;  but,  combined  with  the  passion 
of  the  higher  German  intellect  for  self-contradiction, 
it  involves  him  in  hopeless  confusions  of  thought. 

In  accordance  with  this  mental  habit  the  destruc- 
tive criticism  of  morality  is  interspersed  with 
appeals  to  moral  motives  and  standards,  or  is  even 
carried  on  with  their  aid.  As  a  conclusive  argu- 
ment against  unselfishness  we  are  told  that  "  to  be 
always  acting  for  others  is  almost  as  mischievous 
as  to  act  against  them  :  it  is  a  forcible  intrusion  on 

their  sphere  of  action Not  to  think  of  others, 

but  always  to  be  acting  most  strictly  for  one's  self, 
is  a  high  sort  of  morality.  The  world  is  imperfect 
because  so  much  is  done  for  others."1  An  ex- 
gunner  might  have  remembered  that  the  way  to 
hit  a  distant  mark  is  not  to  aim  straight  at  it.  A 
false  and  fussy  altruism  is  not  the  alternative  to 
taking  exclusive  care  of  number  one.  "  Love  man- 
kind !  But  I  say,  rejoice  in  mankind,  and  there- 
fore help  to  produce  the  sort  of  people  in  whom  we 
can  rejoice  !  The  right  morality  is  to  seek  out  and 
encourage  those  who  delight  us,  and  to  fly  from 
the  others.  Let  the  wretched,  the  misshapen,  and 
the  degenerate  die  out.  They  should  not  be  kept 
alive  at  any  price."2  Our  fastidious  friend  must 
have  come  across  many  unlovely  sights  when 
serving  in  the  ambulance  corps  before  Metz  ;  we 
may  assume  that  they  did  not  impress  him  as  a 
reason  for  shirking  his  duty.  It  may  be  said  that 
wounded  soldiers  are  frequently  strong,  healthy 
men,  capable  of  returning  to  their  work  after 

1   WW,,  XI.,  pp.  310-11.  a  Ibid.,  pp.  313,  314. 


248         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

proper  treatment.  But  the  same  is  true  of  many 
patients  in  our  civil  hospitals  whose  services  would 
be  lost  to  the  community  but  for  modern  philan- 
thropy. No  hard-and-fast  line  can  be  drawn 
between  those  cases  and  the  case  of  those  whose 
continued  existence  is  altogether  undesirable. 
What  we  know  is  that  the  passion  of  pity,  on  the 
whole,  subserves  race-interests,  and  that  it  cannot 
be  kept  up  at  full  strength  unless,  as  with  other 
passions,  there  is  enough  to  overflow  and  go  to 
waste.  It  is  a  question  whether  Nietzsche  himself 
was  not  a  degenerate  ;  it  is  certain  that  he  had  to 
give  up  his  work  as  a  professor,  owing  to  ill-health, 
in  a  few  years  ;  and  that  his  literary  work  could 
hardly  have  been  continued  without  the  help  of  a 
small  retiring  pension  from  the  university.  Let 
me  add  that  he  had  been  a  singularly  devoted 
teacher,  among  other  things  gratuitously  preparing 
students  "from  the  interior  of  Switzerland  "  for  their 
examinations  in  philosophy.  In  private  life  his 
character  was  gentle,  kind,  and  sympathetic — to  a 
greater  extent,  indeed,  than  he  personally  would 
have  liked  it  to  be — and  his  attacks  on  altruism 
were,  perhaps,  inspired  by  a  consciousness  of  the 
injury  it  had  done  his  health.  We  may  also 
attribute  to  his  unfortunate  personal  experiences 
the  prophecy  that  hygienics  will  be  a  prime  interest 
in  the  society  of  the  future.1 

Throughout  the  second,  or  scientific  period, 
morality  continues  a  paramount  preoccupation. 
There  is  no  antithesis  between  increase  of  know- 
ledge and  increase  of  human  welfare  ;  on  the 

•  ww.,  XL,  p.  69. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  249 

contrary,  they  are  mutually  subservient.  Faith  in 
the  supreme  utility  of  science  and  of  its  possessors 
should  take  the  place  of  faith  in  mere  numbers.1 
But  the  observations  out  of  which  science  is  built 
are  themselves  conditioned  by  sincerity  and  recti- 
tude. "  Even  in  the  region  of  sense-perception 
there  are  none  but  moral  experiences."2  "The 
history  of  science  exhibits  the  victory  of  noble 
impulses ;  there  is  much  morality  concerned  in  its 
pursuit."3  "  It  is  a  mistake  to  estimate  philoso- 
phers as  artists,  leaving  out  of  sight  their  justice 
and  self-control."4  "  Unfortunately  we  shall  never 
know  the  best  thing  about  genius,  the  self-control  and 
self-discipline  exercised  in  bringing  its  powers  into 
play."5  "  Hurrah  for  physical  science,  and  a  double 
hurrah  for  the  honesty  that  forces  us  to  study  it !  "6 
As  may  be  gathered  from  some  of  the  passages 
just  quoted,  general  utility  is  the  end  of  moral 
action.  But  morality  need  not  therefore  be  imper- 
sonal. On  the  contrary,  we  best  serve  our  true 
advantage  by  moral  action.7  Benevolence  and 
beneficence  make  up  the  good  man — but  they 
should  begin  with  himself.8  The  greatest  wonders 
of  antique  morality,  Epictetus  for  instance,  knew 
nothing  about  that  altruism  which  is  so  fashionable 
nowadays.9  Nietzsche  as  a  professional  Hellenist 
was  fascinated  by  Greek  ethics,  and  the  influence 
of  its  masters  is  shown  in  more  than  one  refer- 
ence. Epicurus  counts  among  the  greatest  of 
men  ;10  we  have  not  advanced  beyond  him,  but  his 


1  WW.,  III.,  p.  155.     »  WW.,  V.,  p.  155.      3  WW.,  XL,  p.  204. 
*  Ibid.,  p.  408.  s  WW.,  IV.,  p.  357.     6  WW.,  V.,  p.  258. 

^  WW.,  II.,  p.  96.        8  WW.,  IV.,  p.  336.     9  Ibid.,  p.  133. 


250         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

dominion  has  been  infinitely  extended.1  Aristotle 
is  not  named  ;  but  we  find  his  doctrine  of  moral 
habit  passionately  reasserted  as  against  Luther's 
doctrine  of  justification  by  faith.2  And  it  is  made 
a  charge  against  our  system  of  classical  education 
that  we  are  exercised  in  no  single  antique  virtue 
as  the  ancients  were  exercised  in  it.3  As  the 
consolations  of  Christianity  evaporate  the  con- 
solations of  ancient  philosophy  are  revived  in  new 
splendour.4 

Ours  is,  indeed,  an  age  of  comparison  and 
selection,  an  age  which,  discarding  all  provincialism 
in  conduct  as  in  art,  bids  us  look  round  among  the 
historic  civilisations  with  a  view  to  constructing  a 
higher  morality  from  the  forms  and  habits  offered 
to  our  choice.5  Now  it  is  precisely  the  adherence 
to  an  unreasoned  tradition  that  mankind  have 
generally  regarded  as  the  distinctive  note  of 
morality ;  so  that  when  Nietzsche  first  called 
himself  an  immoralist,  what  he  meant  to  emphasise 
was  his  defiance  of  tradition  as  such,  his  demand 
for  a  reasonable  basis  of  action.  Such  a  basis  is 
not  supplied  by  an  appeal  to  our  moral  feelings, 
for  these  are  nothing  better  than  inherited  judg- 
ments. To  trust  them  is  to  trust  your  grandmother 
and  her  grandmother  rather  than  the  gods  within 
you,  your  reason  and  your  experience.6 

All  this  sounds  commonplace  enough  to  a  reader 
of  Bentham  and  Mill ;  just  as  Descartes  and 
Montesquieu  may  have  sounded  commonplace  to 
the  readers  of  Bacon  and  Locke.  And  when 
Nietzsche  proclaimed  the  supremacy  of  England  in 

1  WW.,  XL,  p.  168.      "  WW.,  IV.,  p.  30.      3  ibid.,  p.  187. 

l.,p.  168.      s  JFJF.,II.,p.4i.        6  WW.,IV.,P.  41. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  251 

philosophy  it  was  probably  to  English  ethics  that 
he  referred.  Universalistic  hedonism  is  not,  I 
think,  anywhere  stated  in  terms,  but  its  elements 
are  freely  scattered  through  his  notes.  There  is, 
he  tells  us,  no  instinct  of  self-preservation  ;  every 
action  interpreted  as  evidence  of  such  may  be 
explained  by  the  search  for  agreeable  and  the 
avoidance  of  disagreeable  sensations.  Speaking 
generally,  we  only  wish  for  objects  because  they 
are  associated  with  agreeable  states  of  feeling  in 
ourselves.1  Men  might  be  estimated  by  the  degree 
of  happiness  they  are  capable  of  experiencing  or 
communicating.2  One  of  the  charges  brought 
against  "  morality  "  is  that  it  has  represented  self- 
delight  as  offensive,  self-torment  as  acceptable  to 
the  deity.3  On  the  other  hand,  culture  is  an 
expression  of  happiness.4  The  joy  felt  in  absorb- 
ing new  ideas  should  be  carried  so  far  as  to  out- 
weigh all  other  kinds  of  pleasure.5  Noble  and 
magnanimous  natures  experience  some  feelings  of 
pleasure  and  pain  so  strongly  that  the  intellect  is 
either  silenced  or  made  instrumental  to  them.6 
Nor  is  happiness  by  any  means  so  rare  as 
pessimists  would  have  us  believe.  The  world 
abounds  in  good  will;  and  the  constant  little  every- 
day manifestations  of  this  impulse,  taking  the 
form  of  good  humour,  friendliness,  and  unaffected 
courtesy,  contribute  enormously  to  the  happiness 
of  life.7  "  It  needs  a  life  full  of  pain  and  renuncia- 
tion to  teach  us  that  existence  is  saturated  with 
honey."*  In  short,  "  there  is  no  life  without 

1  WW.,  XL,  pp.  253  and  292.  *  Ibid.,  p.  367. 

3  P.  263.          *  P.  316.  s  p.  403.          6  WW.,V.,  pp.  39,  40. 

i  WW.,  II.,  p.  71.  8  WW.,  XL,  p.  154. 


252         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

pleasure  ;  the  fight  for  pleasure  is  the  fight  for 
life."1  This  view  does  not  exclude  morality,  for 
each  one  is  called  good  or  evil  according  to  the 
way  in  which  he  carries  on  the  fight ;  and  that 
depends  on  the  degree  and  quality  of  his  intellect* — 
a  saying  elucidated  by  the  remark  made  elsewhere 
that  no  honey  is  sweeter  than  the  honey  of  know- 
ledge ;  so  that  he  who  has  spent  his  life  in  its 
acquisition  first  discovers  in  old  age  how  well  he 
has  obeyed  the  voice  of  Nature,  the  Nature  that 
governs  all  things  by  pleasure.3 

We  saw  how  Nietzsche  at  first  looked  on  the 
discovery  that  action  depended  absolutely  on 
pleasure  and  pain  as  destructive  of  morality.  But 
he  did  not  long  hold  to  that  crude  interpretation 
of  ethical  science  ;  for  we  find  a  passage  belonging 
to  the  same  period,  and  much  more  consistent  with 
its  general  tone,  in  which  he  tells  us  that  joy  must 
exercise  a  healthy  and  reparative  influence  on  man's 
moral  nature,  or  why  should  the  moments  when  we 
bathe  in  its  sunshine  be  just  those  when  the  soul 
involuntarily  pledges  herself  to  be  good  and  to 
become  perfect?4  And,  as  a  substitute  for  religious 
exercises,  he  proposes  immediately  on  wakening  in 
the  morning  to  think  how  we  may  give  pleasure  to 
at  least  one  human  being  in  the  course  of  the  day.5 

Assuming  happiness,  understood  as  pleasure  and 
the  absence  of  pain,  to  be  desired  by  all — to  be, 
indeed,  the  only  thing  desirable — it  would  seem 
to  follow  that  utilitarianism  is  the  only  rational 
method  of  ethics  ;  and  it  might  have  been  expected 
that  Nietzsche,  speculating  as  he  did  under  the 

1  WW.,  II.,  p.  107.  *  Loc.  dt.  3  p.  267. 

«   WW.,  III.,  p.  166.  s   WW.,  II.,  p.  385. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  253 

combined  influence  of  Greek  and  English  thought, 
would  have  frankly  accepted  its  principles,  pre- 
serving, of  course,  complete  liberty  with  regard  to 
the  adjustment  of  details.  What  prevented  him 
from  taking  that  step  was  the  pervadingly  sceptical 
and  negative  cast  of  his  intellect,  aggravated,  as  in 
the  case  of  Coleridge,  of  whom  otherwise  he  often 
reminds  one,  by  the  use  of  deleterious  drugs  and 
by  solitary  habits.  According  to  him,  there  can 
be  no  moral  law  binding  on  all  mankind  unless  we 
can  prove  that  there  is  some  universal  end  of  action  ; 
and  such  an  end  does  not  exist.  Pleasure  will  not 
supply  it,  for  the  pleasures  of  sensitive  beings  vary 
with  the  degree  of  their  development,1  and  happi- 
ness is  pursued  by  opposite  paths.2  Oddly  enough, 
the  second  of  these  considerations  is  directed  by 
name  against  Spencer,  than  whom  none  would 
have  more  cordially  accepted  it.  Soon  afterwards 
the  most  complete  development  of  individuality  is 
proposed  as  an  end,  characteristically  enough 
without  reference  to  the  priority  of  Spencer  and 
Mill  in  this  direction.  It  is  true  that  Mill  had 
certainly,  and  Spencer  probably,  taken  his  cue 
from  Wilhelm  von  Humboldt;  but  Nietzsche  never 
betrays  any  acquaintance  with  that  thinker,  and 
the  way  in  which  he  associates  his  own  indi- 
vidualism with  the  theory  of  evolution  seems  to 
place  Spencer's  leading  beyond  a  doubt.3 

After  all,  the  effort  to  get  rid  of  a  moral  law 
speedily  results  in  its  rehabilitation.  For,  as  a 
means  for  increasing  the  number  of  those  happy 
accidents  on  which  future  developments  depend,  it 

'    WW.,  IV.,  pp.  102  sq.  *  XL,  p.  233. 

3  Ibid.,  pp.  238  and  330. 


254         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST 

is  recommended  that  we  should  maintain  the  utmost 
variety  of  conditions  under  which  human  beings 
can  exist ;'  and  this  would  surely  necessitate  a  code 
of  social  justice  to  begin  with,  as  Spencer  pointed 
out  long  ago  in  Social  Statics,  and  as  Professor 
Juvalta,  of  Pavia,  is  never  weary  of  insisting  on 
at  the  present  day,  although  his  theory,  unlike 
Spencer's,  is  penetrated  with  socialistic  ideas. 

Nietzsche  himself,  when  he  has  to  combat 
socialist  demands,  is  not  slow  to  quote  justice  as  a 
recognised  social  obligation.  Admitting  that  the 
present  distribution  of  property  results  from  in- 
numerable acts  of  injustice  and  violence  in  the 
past,  he  deprecates  the  repetition  of  similar  acts  in 
modern  times,  setting  his  hopes  rather  on  a  general 
increase  in  the  sense  of  justice,  and  a  diminution  of 
violent  impulses  all  round.2 

As  a  last  homage  to  the  received  morality,  a  note 
dating  from  the  year  1880  may  be  mentioned,  in 
which  Napoleon  is  called  the  greatest  of  men,  if 
his  aim  had  been  the  good  of  humanity.3 

Not  long  after  abandoning  the  cultivation  of 
genius  as  a  universal  end,  Nietzsche  seems  to  have 
taken  up  and  substituted  for  it  the  idea,  so  prominent 
in  his  last  period,  of  breeding  a  superior  race. 
Here,  again,  the  Hellenic  influence  is  prominent. 
In  a  fragment  dating  from  1876  the  Greeks  are 
quoted  as  an  example  of  what  may  be  done  in  the 
way  of  intellectual  stimulation  by  the  self-conscious- 
ness of  such  a  race  in  the  midst  of  a  barbarous 
population.4  English  science  and  philosophy,  for 
which  so  much  enthusiasm  is  expressed,  would  no 

1  P.  239.  *   WW.,  1 1.,  pp.  334*0. 

3  ww.,  xi.,  P.  387-  4  P.  33- 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  255 

doubt  act  powerfully  in  the  same  direction  through 
the  doctrine  of  evolution,  which  is  known  to  have 
interested  Nietzsche  intensely  at  this  time.  In  this 
connection  much  has  been  made  of  his  debt  to 
Darwin  ;  but,  as  he  never  understood  the  theory 
of  natural  selection,  it  seems  more  likely  that  the 
decisive  influence  came  from  Spencer,  whose  psy- 
chology he  certainly  accepted  to  the  extent  of 
describing  knowledge  as  a  nervous  modification 
produced  by  the  action  of  external  objects  on  our 
organs  of  sense,  without  any  co-operation  from  the 
mind.1  Now,  Spencer  from  the  beginning  was 
interested  in  evolution  much  less  as  an  explanation 
of  the  past  than  as  a  promise  of  the  future — as  a 
pledge  that  human  life  might  rise  to  a  far  more 
perfect  harmony  between  organism  and  environ- 
ment than  any  yet  attained  ;  and  on  this  side  his 
philosophy  would  appeal  strongly  to  Nietzsche,  as 
also  on  its  individualistic  side,  with  which  we  have 
seen  him  to  be  in  complete  agreement.  Indeed,  he 
brings  the  two  into  direct  association  by  asking  : 
"  Is  not  every  individual  an  attempt  to  reach  a 
higher  species  than  man?"2  It  is  here,  rather 
than  in  the  youthful  worship  of  genius,  which  his 
disgust  with  Wagner  led  him  to  repudiate,  that  we 
can  lay  our  finger  on  the  genesis  of  the  superman. 

It  has  been  disputed  whether  the  superman  was 
intended  by  his  prophet  to  stand  for  a  new  animal 
species,  or  for  a  new  and  improved  variety  of 
human  being,  or,  finally,  for  a  sporadic  type  of 
individual  excellence,  cropping  up  occasionally  in 
the  existing  state  of  civilisation.  So  far  as  the 

1  P.  275.  *  P.  238. 


256        THE  MORALS  dF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

ftame  and  notion  have  become  popular,  it  seems  to"1 
be  generally  understood  in  the  last  sense.  The 
superman  is  commonly  identified  with  a  coxcomb 
whose  opinion  of  his  own  superiority  to  the  rest  of 
the  species  is  only  equalled  by  his  contempt  for  the 
ordinary  obligations  of  morality.  Such  pretensions 
are  not  new  ;  and  it  would  be  strange  if  Nietzsche 
had  no  higher  ambition  than  to  re-edit  them  under 
a  more  pompous  appellation.  In  fact,  it  very  much 
disgusted  him  to  find  that  the  watchword  of  his 
philosophy  should  be  used  to  procure  admittance 
for  degenerate  types,  with  whom  he  sympathised 
even  less  than  with  the  unregenerate  Philistine. 
Nothing  like  the  superman  had  ever  turned  up  in 
his  own  experience  ;  whether  history  had  offered 
any  examples  of  his  ideal  remains  doubtful.  On 
this  point  the  language  of  Zarathustra  is  perfectly 
explicit,  and  if  taken  alone  would  settle  the  ques- 
tion. According  to  the  prophet  under  whose  name 
Nietzsche  speaks,  when  the  greatest  and  the 
smallest  are  stripped  and  compared  they  show 
themselves  too  fatally  alike,  and  both  of  them  all 
too  human.  In  a  later  work  Napoleon  seems  to  be 
mentioned  as  an  exception,  but  an  exception  that 
proves  the  rule,  being  a  combination  of  the  super- 
man with  the  brute.1 

Napoleon,  in  fact,  embodied  the  formidable  alter- 
native confronting  us  at  the  present  day.  The 
human  race  represents  a  transitional  stage  of 
unstable  equilibrium.  We  must  either  go  back 
to  the  brute  or  on  to  the  superman.2  And  the 
choice  is  not  doubtful.  Our  very  first  article  of 

1  WW.,  VI.,  p.  133,  and  VII.,  p.  337.  "  WW.,  XII.,  p.  210. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  257 

faith  is  the  duty  of  not  relapsing  into  a  savage  and 
anti-social  state.1  Therefore,  the  new  beings  can 
only  be  conceived  as  a  multitude  ;  goodness  can 
only  be  developed  among  equals.2 

It  remains  to  be  decided  whether  we  are  to 
conceive  the  superman  as  a  new  animal  species, 
differing  not  less  from  the  actual  human  species 
than  that  differs  from  the  anthropoid  ape,  or  merely 
as  a  new  race,  related  to  the  modern  European 
somewhat  as  the  Greeks  were  related  to  the 
barbarians  among  whom  they  settled.  This  seems 
to  be  a  point  on  which,  as  on  various  others,  our 
prophet  had  no  scruple  about  changing  his  mind 
without  caring  to  acknowledge  the  change  either  to 
others  or  to  himself.  To  my  mind  at  least,  there 
cannot  be  the  faintest  doubt  that  when  he  wrote 
Zarathustra  his  wish  was  to  represent  the  super- 
man as  a  new  animal  species  to  be  evolved  by 
artificial  selection  from  man.  I  know  that  his 
sister  and  biographer,  Madame  Forster-Nietzsche, 
refuses  to  accept  this  interpretation  ;  but  it  is  signi- 
ficant that  she  can  only  get  rid  of  the  relevant 
texts  by  explaining  them  away  as  poetical  meta- 
phors. Unfortunately  for  her  interpretation,  when 
Nietzsche  talks  in  parables  he  makes  them  unmis- 
takably parabolical.  We  find  ourselves  among  a 
motley  assemblage  of  rope-dancers,  lions,  adders, 
tarantulas,  kings,  beggars,  and  other  mythical 
properties  needless  to  enumerate.  But  every  now 
and  then  this  rather  wearisome  entertainment  is 
relieved  by  the  expression  of  plain  ideas  in  plain 
language,  quite  familiar  to  us  from  their  recurrence 

1  WW.,  XII.,  P.  52.  *  P.  210. 


258         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

in  the  author's  other  works,  where,  as  Cassandra 
says,  the  oracle  looks  out  not  like  a  bride  behind 
her  veil,  but  like  wind-driven  waves  against  a 
rising  sun.  And  foremost  among  these  is  the  idea 
of  a  new  species,  a  superman  to  be  evolved  from 
man,  or,  in  the  still  more  telling  phrase  once  let 
fall,  a  super-race  from  the  race.1 

We  have  not  now  to  discuss  the  feasibility  of  the 
idea.  What  has  to  be  pointed  out  as  the  most 
interesting  and  attractive  element  in  the  work 
where  it  first  appeared  is  the  fire  of  moral 
enthusiasm  burning  through  the  prophecies  from 
beginning  to  end.  "  Zarathustra  has  found  no 
greater  power  on  earth  than  good  and  evil."2  But 
as  yet  this  power  has  been  wasted,  because  it  was 
not  directed  towards  the  attainment  of  a  single  ideal. 
"  There  have  been  a  thousand  aims  because  there 
have  been  a  thousand  peoples.  Humanity  is  still 
without  an  aim.  And  to  be  without  that  is  to  be 
without  itself."3 

That  all  men  should  combine  for  one  end  is  not 
hopeless,  for  they  already  combine  in  smaller 
groups.  "  Regard  for  the  interest  of  the  herd  or 
the  community  is  older  than  self-interest.  The 
individual  is  a  most  recent  creation.  So  long  as  a 
good  conscience  represents  the  herd,  only  the  bad 
conscience  says  'I.'  Truly  the  sly  and  loveless 
self  that  seeks  its  own  profit  in  the  profit  of  others 
is  not  the  beginning  but  the  end  of  the  herd."4 

At  no  time  of  life  did  his  Hellenism  make 
Nietzsche  an  admirer  of  the  modern  State  ;  and  at 
this  period  he  positively  foams  at  the  mouth  with 

1  WW.,  VI.,  p.  ii  i.  "  Ibid.,  p.  84. 

3  P.  87.  4  p.  86. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  259 

hatred  for  it.  The  people  and  the  herd  may  be  fit 
objects  of  faith  and  love  ;  never  the  State,  although 
it  impudently  claims  to  be  the  people,  which  is  not 
deceived,  but  hates  it  as  "  a  sin  against  morals  and 
rights."  There  are  many  languages  of  good  and 
evil,  but  it  lies  in  them  all.  "  All  that  it  says  is  a 
lie,  and  all  that  it  possesses  has  been  stolen."  Even 
those  who  vanquished  the  old  god  fall  a  prey  to 
the  snares  of  the  new  idol  that  promises  to  give 
them  all  if  they  will  worship  it ;  "  so  it  buys  the 
splendour  of  your  virtue  and  the  gaze  of  your  proud 
eyes."  The  State  must  cease  to  exist  before  real 
manhood  can  begin  ;  much  more,  before  the  way 
to  the  superman  can  be  prepared.1 

What  is  the  justification  of  this  violent  language  ? 
We  may  assume  that  the  State  discourages  the 
growth  of  individuality;  and  as,  according  to  Zara- 
thustra,  it  was  invented  for  the  benefit  of  the 
"  superfluous  classes,"  it  is  apparently  made  respon- 
sible for  their  continued  existence,  while  they  in 
turn  naturally  support  it. 

Evidently,  however,  what  Nietzsche  most  dreads 
and  detests  is  not  the  mischief  done  by  the  modern 
State  in  suppressing  individualism  and  favouring 
the  survival  of  degenerates,  but  the  fact  that  as  a 
real,  living,  visible,  attractive  unity  it  enters  into 
formidable  competition  with  the  glorified  indi- 
viduality of  his  imaginary  superman.  Michelet 
has  pointed  out  that  the  giant  Gargantua  was 
nothing  less  than  the  New  Monarchy  of  the  Renais- 
sance ;  and  one  has  only  to  think  of  him  as  coming 
into  conflict  with  Cassar  Borgia,  whom  Nietzsche 

1  Pp.  69-72. 


26o         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

regards  as  the  highest  individual  product  of  that 
age,  to  see  which  party  would  win.  Indeed,  the 
Duke  of  Valentinois,  like  another  and  greater 
Caesar,  was,  from  his  German  admirer's  point  of 
view,  a  traitor  to  the  individualistic  cause,  the 
great  ambition  of  his  life  having  been  to  establish 
the  New  Monarchy  in  the  Pontifical  States,  if  not, 
as  Machiavelli  hoped,  over  the  whole  of  a  reunited 
Italy.  Neither  he  nor  Alcibiades  nor  any  other  of 
the  same  class  has  ever  been  content  to  "exist 
beautifully  ";  nor  do  they  seem  inclined  to  tolerate 
the  existence  of  any  other  such  paragons  by  their 
side. 

Here,  then,  at  first  starting,  we  find  the  idea  of 
the  superman  afflicted  with  an  immanent  self-con- 
tradiction in  the  best  Hegelian  style.  Conceived 
as  an  individual,  he  at  once  establishes  a  levelling 
despotism,  thus  sublating  the  very  type  that  he 
represents.  Conceived  as  a  class,  he  perishes  by 
internecine  strife.1  And  close  behind  this  comes  a 
second  self-contradiction,  afflicting  the  means  pro- 
posed, or  rather  suggested,  for  bringing  the  ideal 
into  existence.  As  already  mentioned,  they  consist 
in  an  appeal  to  moral  motives,  in  the  proposal  to 
create  a  new  enthusiasm  of  humanity,  uniting  and 
directing  towards  a  single  end  all  the  tremendous 
forces  that  now  work  for  a  multitude  of  conflicting 
ends.  Now,  this  demand  assumes  the  existence  in 
the  human  race,  as  a  whole,  of  such  passionate 
self-devotion,  combined  with  such  cool,  unerring 
judgment,  as  no  example  of  has  been  found  in  the 

1  The  condottieri  whom  Caesar  Borgia  treacherously  massacred 
at  Sinigaglia  were  "  higher  men  "  of  a  sort,  though  not  so  high 
as  he  was. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  261 

past.  For  it  must  be  a  devotion  capable  of  sacri- 
ficing every  other  end  to  the  achievement  of  this 
one  end — an  end,  too,  of  which  as  yet  there  has 
been  no  experience,  and  an  end  involving,  as  no 
other  thing  sought  after  has  ever  involved,  the 
total  disappearance  of  the  race  that  has  brought  it 
about.  And  the  judgment  called  into  play  for 
that  purpose  must  find  the  means  for  evolving  a 
new  animal  species  —  a  task  to  which  human 
ingenuity,  operating  on  the  most  passive  and 
plastic  materials,  has  never  yet  found  itself  equal. 
Surely,  a  race  so  splendidly  endowed  with  the 
noblest  capacities  of  intellect,  heart,  and  will  as  to 
answer  Zarathustra'scall  would  deserve  a  better  fate 
than  such  self-annulment,  would  itself  have  antici- 
pated the  superman,  and  would  require  all  the 
running  it  could  make  to  keep  in  the  same  place. 

It  so  happens  that  we  can  lay  our  finger  on  the 
initial  error  whence  these  monstrous  consequences 
arose.  Much  as  Nietzsche  hated  Germany,  he 
hated  England  more  ;  and  with  the  rather  dis- 
creditable object,  I  fear,  of  depreciating  England 
and  her  great  naturalist,  he  tries  to  show  that 
without  Hegel  there  would  have  been  no  Darwin. 
For,  according  to  him,  the  German  philosopher, 
by  teaching  that  specific  notions  were  evolved  out 
of  one  another,  prepared  the  scientific  intellect  of 
Europe  to  entertain  the  idea  of  organic  develop- 
ment.1 Historically  there  is,  of  course,  no  founda- 
tion for  such  a  claim.  Evolutionism  was  hereditary 
in  the  Darwin  family,  and  goes  back  to  a  time 
before  Hegel ;  while  Hegel  himself  took  the  idea 

1   WW.,  V.,  p.  300. 


262         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

of  development  from  Schelling,  who  in  turn  owed 
it  to  the  naturalists  of  his  time.  What  I  wish  to 
point  out,  however,  is  not  the  historical  error,  but 
the  profound  misconception  of  organic  evolution 
that  it  betrays.  Hegel's  theory  of  logical  develop- 
ment is  determined  by  the  idea  that  the  lower  notion 
suffers  from  an  inherent  self-contradiction,  in  con- 
sequence of  which  it  falls  to  pieces  and  spon- 
taneously gives  birth  to  the  higher  notion.  With 
Darwin,  on  the  contrary,  the  decay  and  death  of 
the  old  species  are  not  the  antecedent,  but  the  con- 
sequence, of  its  having  given  birth  to  the  new 
species,  with  which  it  is  unable  to  compete.  And 
this  very  internecine  strife  is  another  point  of  dis- 
tinction between  the  two  processes.  Hegel's  notions 
only  perish  in  an  ideal  sense.  In  the  actual  life  of 
logic  they  survive  and  continue  to  play  a  useful 
part  in  the  economy  of  thought. 

Applying  the  result  to  Nietzsche's  philosophy, 
we  now  see  how,  under  an  illusive  show  of  Dar- 
winian biology,  he  really  evolves  superman  from 
man  on  the  lines  of  Hegelian  dialectic.  That  is  to 
say,  the  old  human  species,  in  awakening  to  the 
consciousness  of  its  degeneracy,  overcomes  and 
supersedes  itself,  thus  calling  the  new  superhuman 
species  into  being.  Thus  the  pessimism  of  his 
youth  becomes  unexpectedly  justified  as  an  ideal 
expression  of  race-suicide  preparatory  to  a  better 
state  of  things. 

I  have  said  that  Nietzsche  hated  England  ;  and 
it  may  be  thought  that  this  is  inconsistent  with  the 
praises  he  lavished  on  her  in  his  second  or  scientific 
period.  But  the  revulsion  merely  repeats  in  a 
much  less  excusable  form  his  earlier  revolt  from 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  263 

Wagner  and  Schopenhauer.  It  belongs  to  an 
unpleasant  habit  he  had  of  kicking  down  the  ladder 
by  which  he  had  climbed  up.  He  could  not 
forgive  the  English  thinkers  for  what  he  owed 
them  ;  and  the  "  profound  mediocrity  of  the  English 
intellect" — represented  presumably  by  Shakespeare, 
Newton,  Chatham,  and  Byron — is  charged  with 
having  caused  a  deep  depression  of  the  European 
intellect  as  a  whole,  but  more  particularly  of  the 
French  intellect.  This  very  mediocrity,  however, 
enables  the  English  to  perform  important  services 
for  which  men  of  genius  are  incapacitated  by  their 
splendid  disregard  of  facts.  Darwin,  Mill,  and 
Herbert  Spencer,  being  the  men  to  whom  he 
personally  owed  most,  are  particularly  mentioned 
in  this  connection  as  examples  of  useful  dulness.1 
Of  the  three  Spencer  seems  to  have  had  the  largest 
share  in  ultimately  determining  Nietzsche's  philo- 
sophy, and  so  he  is  never  mentioned  without 
some  expression  of  contemptuous  disagreement. 
English  utilitarianism  is  the  foundation  of  his 
ethics  ;  and  therefore  it  is  savagely  denounced  as 
a  canting,  hypocritical  attempt  to  secure  the  greatest 
happiness  of  England  under  pretence  of  pursuing 
the  greatest  happiness  of  all.  In  England  itself 
the  standard  of  happiness  among  moral  philo- 
sophers is  comfort,  fashion,  and  a  seat  in  Parlia- 
ment.2 Gizicki  once  congratulated  a  German  critic 
for  having  performed  the  rare  feat  of  attacking 
utilitarianism  without  forgetting  the  manners  of  a 
gentleman.  This  admirable  exception  could  not 
have  been  our  aristocratic  immoralist. 

1    WW.,  VII.,  p.  223.  »  Ibid.,  p.  184. 


264         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

Throughout  his  second  period  Nietzsche,  besides 
being  a  utilitarian  in  the  wide  sense  of  judging 
actions  by  their  consequences,  had  also  been  a 
hedonist — that  is,  he  had  considered  happiness  (or 
pleasure)  as  a  universally  desired  and  absolutely 
desirable  thing,  although  at  the  same  time  as  a 
thing  too  indefinite  to  be  made  a  standard  for  the 
unification  of  human  life.  The  desire  of  domina- 
tion, on  the  other  hand,  is  mentioned  in  a  note 
bearing  the  date  of  1880  as  often  a  symptom  of 
weakness.1  Within  a  year  we  find  the  first  intima- 
tion of  his  final  doctrine,  that  power  is  the  summum 
bonum  and  love  of  power  the  universal  motive,  in 
an  aphorism  setting  forth  (for  the  rest  without  an 
attempt  to  demonstrate  it)  that,  whether  we  give 
pleasure  or  pain  to  others,  it  is  solely  for  the 
purpose  of  satisfying  our  love  of  power.2  A  little 
later  still,  Zarathustra  proclaims  power  as  a  new 
virtue,  a  new  standard  of  good  and  evil.3  It  is  not 
so  very  new,  being  borrowed,  as  usual  without 
acknowledgment,  from  an  English  philosopher, 
Hobbes  ;  and  besides  that  Nietzsche,  in  his  later 
writings,  especially  in  the  uncompleted  Wille  zur 
Macht)  assumes  that  power  is  what  everyone  really 
wants  and  has  always  wanted.  Everyone — with  a 
single  striking  exception.  "  Men  do  not  strive  for 
happiness — only  Englishmen";*  though  elsewhere 
our  people  are  associated,  in  this  contemptible 
pursuit,  with  "  shopkeepers,  Christians,  cows, 
women,  and  other  democrats."5  Nevertheless, 
"every  healthy  morality  is  dominated  by  an 
instinct  of  life";6  "an  action  imposed  by  the  vital 

'  WW.,  XI.,  p.  405.     a  WW.,  V.,  p.  50  s(j.     3  WW.,Vl.t  p.  112. 
«  WW.,  VIII.,  p.  62.    5  ibid.,  p.  149.  6  P.  88. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  265 

instinct  is  proved  to  be  right  by  the  pleasure  it 
gives";1  "  everything  good  is  instinctive,  and  there- 
fore easy,  necessary,  free  ";2  "  pleasure  is  a  feeling 
of  power  ;  to  exclude  the  emotions  is  to  exclude 
those  conditions  which  give  the  feeling  of  power, 
and  therefore  of  pleasure  at  its  highest."3  Herbert 
Spencer  would  not  have  dissented  in  principle  from 
this  statement ;  but  then  he  would  not,  like  his 
critic,  have  distinguished  between  happiness  and 
pleasure,  which  two  other  Englishmen,  Words- 
worth and  Ruskin,  would  have  identified  with 
"vital  feelings  of  delight."  Can  Nietzsche  have 
been  ignorant  that  the  gospel  of  health,  with  its 
accompanying  condemnation  of  the  sickly  and 
helpless,  had  been  preached  before  him  in  The 
Data  of  Ethics  ? 

On  the  other  hand,  Spencer  would  have  emphati- 
cally dissented  from  such  a  statement  as  that 
"  egoism  belongs  to  the  essence  of  the  distinguished 
soul  ;  I  mean  the  immovable  belief  that  other 
beings  must  be  naturally  subject  to  a  being  like  us, 
and  have  to  sacrifice  themselves  to  it ;  a  relation- 
ship which  the  distinguished  soul  accepts  as 
founded  on  the  primary  law  of  things."4  Nor 
would  he  have  allowed  that  the  conquest  and 
spoliation  of  the  weaker  by  the  stronger  was  the 
very  principle  of  society  and  of  life  itself.5  But 
he  might  have  fairly  challenged  the  Prussian 
philosopher  to  reconcile  these  crudities  with  the 
admonition  given  elsewhere :  "  Learn  betimes  to 
discard  the  supposed  individual  ;  to  discover  the 
errors  of  the  ego  ;  to  feel  cosmically  about  the  me 

1  P.  226.  a  P.  93.  3    w.  z.  M.,  p.  240. 

«    WW.,  VII.,  pp.  251-52.  5  Ibid.,  pp.  237-38. 


266         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

and  thee."1  Or,  again,  why  should  Zarathustra 
compare  unfavourably  the  vulgar  who  want  to  live 
gratis  with  men  like  himself,  who  are  always 
thinking  what  best  thing  they  can  give  in  exchange 
for  the  life  they  have  received,  and  who  condemn 
the  wish  to  enjoy  without  giving  enjoyment  in 
return  ?2 

Among  his  other  adventures,  Zarathustra  falls  in 
with  an  imbecile  hedonistic  moralist,  who  is 
accosting  a  herd  of  kine  with  the  object  of  inducing 
them  to  disclose  the  secret  of  their  happiness. 3  It 
does  not  seem  to  have  struck  the  prophet  that  these 
cows  had  a  logic  as  well  as  an  ethic,  or  that,  if  the 
pasturing  animals  were  too  gentle  to  toss  him  on 
the  horns  of  a  dilemma,  a  savage  bull  might  have 
been  invited  in  for  the  purpose.  If  self-interest  is 
the  law  of  life,  with  what  right  can  the  present 
generation  be  called  on  to  sacrifice  themselves  for 
the  evolution  of  a  superior  race?  If  there  is  a 
moral  law  prescribing  self-devotion,  how  can  it 
be  our  duty  to  create  what  the  highest  of  our 
contemporaries  would  call  a  devil?4 

If  Nietzsche  ever  contemplated  the  idea  of 
evolving  a  higher  animal  species  than  man,  he 
soon  gave  it  up.  His  last  work,  The  Anti-Chris- 
tian, puts  the  problem  quite  clearly,  as,  not  "  what 
is  to  succeed  man?"  but — "what  kind  of  man 
ought  to  be  desired  and  bred  as  the  more  valuable, 
the  more  worthy  of  life,  the  more  certain  of  a 
future?"5  And  he  proceeds  to  state,  in  direct 
contradiction  to  Zarathustra,  that  the  desirable 
type  has  often  presented  itself  in  history,  but  never 

1   WW.,  XII.  .p.  74.  "   WW.,  VI.,  pp.  291  sq. 

3  Ibid.,  pp.  38957.  <  P.  213.  5  WW.,  VIII.,  p.  218. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  267 

as  the  result  of  a  conscious  effort,  while  the  effect 
of  prevalent  opinions  has  long  been  to  repress  or 
extinguish  it.  Two  agencies  in  particular  have 
hitherto  worked  with  fatal  effect  in  this  direction — 
morality  and  Christianity.  He  therefore  applies 
himself  with  a  holy  zeal  to  the  destruction  of  both, 
his  intellect  being  indeed  much  better  fitted  for  the 
work  of  pulling  down  than  for  the  work  of  build- 
ing up. 

The  attack  on  morality,  by  which  is  meant  the 
doctrine  of  universal  benevolence,  proceeds  on  the 
lines  of  the  historical  method,  and  rests  on  the 
false  assumption  that  a  belief  is  refuted  by  showing 
how  it  came  to  exist.  Such  a  method,  were  it 
generally  applied,  would  ruin  every  belief  without 
exception,  as  all  beliefs  have  a  history,  and  even 
the  scepticism  that  displaced  them  would  share 
their  fate.  As  it  happens,  however,  the  historical 
explanation  offered  of  the  current  distinction 
between  good  and  evil  in  conduct  is  entirely  false. 
It  is  the  work  of  a  mere  classical  philologist,  and  a 
very  imperfectly  informed  one  at  that.  His  thesis 
is  that  the  valuations  of  character  and  action  were 
originally  fixed  by  the  ruling  caste  in  society, 
those  qualities  of  health,  strength,  beauty,  courage, 
liberality,  and  truthfulness  which  were  most  con- 
spicuous in  its  members  being  approved  of,  while 
the  distinguishing  qualities  of  their  serfs  were 
proportionately  despised.  In  those  right-minded 
ages  to  be  strong  and  successful  was  the  great 
merit,  to  be  weak  and  a  failure  the  great  vice.  As 
the  subject  classes  had  become  enslaved  through 
their  weakness,  they  set  up  a  rival  scale  of  values 
in  which  pity,  the  correlative  and  consolation  of 


268         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

weakness,  occupied  the  highest  place,  while  the 
virtues  of  their  betters  were  disparaged,  their 
rightful  claims  on  the  labourers  treated  as  wicked 
spoliation,  and  their  favoured  position  assailed 
with  vindictive  envy. 

The  aristocratic  and  chivalrous  virtues  maintain 
their  ascendancy  during  that  chronic  state  of  war 
by  which  they  are  at  once  originated  and  preserved. 
Prolonged  peace,  on  the  other  hand,  creates  a 
fatal  split  in  the  ruling  body,  and  undermines  its 
ideals  by  favouring  the  development  of  a  priest- 
hood, and  enabling  it  to  dispute  the  supremacy  of 
the  warrior  caste.  For  a  priestly  life,  being  con- 
ducive to  physical  degeneracy,  breeds  all  the 
mental  characteristics  of  a  weak  race,  thus  throw- 
ing the  priests  out  of  sympathy  with  the  warriors, 
and  making  them  the  natural  allies  of  the  servile 
herd  whose  scale  of  values  they  adopt  and  syste- 
matise into  a  code. 

It  would  seem  that,  according  to  Nietzsche's 
reading  of  history,  which,  however,  is  nowhere 
given  as  a  connected  whole,  the  first  essay  towards 
organising  a  servile  or  gregarious  ethic  was  made 
in  Greece  by  Socrates,  himself  a  man  of  the 
people,  and  afflicted  with  the  characteristic  vices  of 
his  class,  one  of  these  being  a  morbid  disposition 
to  substitute  self-conscious  reasoning  for  instinct. 
Under  his  corrupting  influence  Plato,  an  aristocrat 
of  genius  but  born  with  the  soul  of  a  Semitic 
priest,  proceeded  to  work  out  a  theory  of  values 
based  on  supernatural  sanctions,  in  which  the 
right  of  the  stronger,  vigorously  but  vainly 
defended  by  those  genuine  champions  of  old 
Hellenic  ideals,  the  Sophists,  is  subordinated  to 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  269 

the  interest  of  the  masses ;  a  pestilent  doctrine 
which,  in  company  with  an  equally  morbid  asceti- 
cism, became  more  or  less  current  in  all  the  later 
schools  of  Greek  philosophy. 

More,  however,  was  needed  than  a  false  philo- 
sophy to  secure  the  final  victory  of  servile  over 
seignoral  values.  The  Jews,  a  race  of  slaves  and 
priests  combined,  managed  to  impose  their  degrad- 
ing morality  on  the  civilised  world  by  appealing  to 
the  instincts  of  the  lowest  classes  in  the  Roman 
Empire  under  the  name  of  Christianity.  This 
must  not  be  confounded  with  the  genuine  teaching 
of  Jesus,  a  religion  in  which  supernaturalism  had 
no  place,  and  which  perished  with  its  author  on 
Calvary.  What  carried  all  before  it  was  Paul's 
theology,  in  which  the  idyllic  domestic  morality  of 
the  Jewish  Diaspora  is  artfully  combined  with  a 
scheme  for  giving  envious  plebeians  their  revenge 
on  the  rich  in  another  world. 

In  modern  times  Christianity  has  transmitted  its 
moralin  virus  to  utilitarianism — an  essentially 
gregarious  ethical  system,  first  founded  by  the 
sickly  Jewish  artisan  Spinoza,  and  further  deve- 
loped by  the  plebeian  English  race,  of  which 
Buckle,  with  his  cheap  and  noisy  eloquence,  is  a 
characteristic  type.  For,  let  there  be  no  mistake 
about  it,  what  we  call  "  modern  ideas "  do  not 
come  from  the  essentially  aristocratic  French 
people,  but  from  the  plebeian  English.1 

As  we  learn  from  his  letters,  Nietzsche  was  in 
early  youth  a  careful  student  of  Theognis  ;*  and 
his  theory  of  the  two  moralities,  servile  and 

1  W W.,  VII.,  pp.  224 and  307.  3  Brief e,  I.,  p.  2. 


270         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST— 

seignoral,  or  gregarious  and  egregious  (taking 
the  second  word  in  its  Latin  or  Italian  sense), 
seems  to  have  been  suggested,  in  the  first  instance, 
by  that  aristocratic  elegist's  bitter  complaint  of  the 
change  in  language  brought  about  by  the  demo- 
cratic revolution  in  Megara.  An  improvement  in 
their  condition,  he  tells  us,  has  turned  the  ignorant 
rustics  from  bad  to  good  ;  while  reverses  of  fortune 
have  given  an  evil  name  to  the  quondam  nobles. 
In  reference  to  these  passages  Welcker,  quoted  by 
Grote,  observes  that  the  political,  as  distinguished 
from  the  ethical,  sense  of  good  and  bad,  fell  into 
desuetude  through  the  influence  of  the  Socratic 
philosophy,  which,  according  to  the  same  authority, 
first  popularised  those  terms  as  ethical  qualifica- 
tions.1 However  this  may  be,  there  is  no  evidence 
that  the  personal  revaluation  brought  a  change  of 
moral  values  in  its  train,  nor  that  either  then  or 
afterwards  a  change  in  the  relative  estimate  of  the 
different  virtues  took  place.  Least  of  all  does  it 
appear  that  either  pity  or  vindictiveness  was 
a  peculiar  characteristic  of  the  lower  orders. 
Theognis  is  thirsting  to  drink  the  blood  of  his 
enemies,  in  what  Nietzsche  would  call  a  truly 
plebeian  spirit ;  and  he  particularly  reproaches  his 
young  favourite  Cyrnos  for  not  grieving  long  over 
the  sufferings  of  his  friends.  Indeed,  Homer  alone 
would  prove  that  tenderness  and  sympathy  were 
qualities  highly  valued  among  the  best-born 
Greeks  ;  while  the  oath  taken  by  every  member  of 
an  oligarchic  club  during  the  revolutionary  period, 
"to  do  the  Demos  all  the  harm  he  could,"  is 

1  Crete's  History  of  Greece,  II.,  pp.  419  sq. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  271 

evidence  that  resentment  flourished  to  the  full  as 
much  among  the  hawks  as  among  the  lambs. 

It  would  be  more  true  to  say  that  different  classes 
have  different  and  contrasted  vices  than  that  they 
have  different  and  contrasted  virtues — or  values,  if 
the  latter  term  be  preferred.  And  we  may  admit 
that  insolence  and  cruelty  are  more  characteristic 
of  a  ruling,  meanness  and  mendacity  of  a  servile, 
class,  while  contending  that  the  permanent  public 
opinion  of  both  classes  makes  for  the  consecration 
of  courage  and  gentleness  all  round.  Indeed,  the 
very  word  "  gentleness "  is  a  historical  lesson  in 
itself,  proving  that  English  aristocratic  society,  at 
least,  discerned  a  peculiar  connection  between 
sweet  manners  and  good  birth. 

As  a  young  professor  at  Basel  Nietzsche  fully 
accepted  Grote's  vindication  of  the  Sophists, 
although  he  failed  to  see  that  a  far  better  case  than 
Grote's  might  be  made  out  for  them  as  ethical 
reformers.  In  his  latest  phase  he  peremptorily, 
and  without  reason  given,  goes  back  on  the  old 
view,  glorifying  them  as  apostles  of  brute  force.1 
In  this  connection  also  he  accepts  the  Melian 
Dialogue — that  masterpiece  of  tragic  irony — as  an 
expression  of  what  Thucydides  himself  thought 
about  public  morality.  There  is  no  direct  reference 
to  Plato's  Gorgias — a  wise  abstinence  ;  for  perhaps 
it  would  have  involved  him  in  the  necessity  of 
rinding  an  answer  to  the  unanswerable  Socratic 
argument  against  Callicles,  the  real  author  of 
Nietzsche's  distinction  between  gregarious  and 
egregious  morality.  For,  after  appealing  to  natural 

1  Cf.  WW.,  X.,  p.  129,  with  W.  s.  M.,  p.  235. 


2-J2         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

law  in  justification  of  the  claim  put  forward  by  the 
superior  man  to  subjugate  and  despoil  the  inferior, 
this  cynical  aristocrat  has  to  admit  that  the  many, 
by  banding  together,  may  and  do  gain  the  upper 
hand  so  decisively  as  to  impose  their  standards  on 
him.  Callicles  tries  to  get  out  of  the  difficulty  by 
falling  back  on  qualitative  distinctions  as  consti- 
tuting the  right  to  rule  ;  but  this  admission  re- 
admits moral  values  into  the  discussion,  with  the 
result  that  their  supremacy  over  the  whole  of  life 
has  to  be  conceded. 

Such  is  also  the  outcome  of  Nietzsche's  efforts 
to  get  beyond  good  and  evil.  His  objections  to 
the  received  morality  can  only  be  accredited  by  an 
appeal  to  moral  considerations  of  a  still  higher 
order.  His  polemic  against  pity  for  degenerates 
derives  its  whole  strength  from  the  argument  that 
their  survival  and  propagation  impairs  the  life- 
enhancing  qualities  of  the  race.  But  if  anyone 
chooses  to  say,  "What  do  I  care  for  the  race?" 
his  principles  leave  him  without  any  answer,  beyond 
a  torrent  of  unconciliatory  abuse. 

In  so  far  as  popular  religion  is  identified  with 
popular  morality,  the  attack  on  Christianity  lays 
itself  open  to  the  same  objection.  Nor  is  that  all. 
What  gives  such  lustre  to  the  whole  argument 
and  raises  it  as  literature  to  the  first  rank  among 
Nietzsche's  writings  is  the  moral  passion  displayed 
throughout  ;  the  constant  invoking  of  truth  as  a 
precious  thing  violated  by  the  Jewish  and  Christian 
priesthoods  at  every  step  in  the  propagation  of 
their  creed. 

Whether  his  charges  have  or  have  not  been 
made  out  is  a  question  irrelevant  to  the  present 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  273 

discussion.  What  interests  us  to  observe  is  that 
at  any  rate  it  did  not  lie  in  the  mouth  of  a  pro- 
fessed immoralist  to  make  them.  For  they  involve 
the  assumption,  to  which  he  is  not  entitled,  that 
there  is  such  a  thing  as  moral  obligation,  and  that 
part  of  it  is  to  speak  the  truth.  Nietzsche  had 
some  glimmering  of  the  difficulty  ;  but  he  never 
worked  out  a  consistent  theory  of  the  subject,  and 
his  language  when  he  touches  on  it  is  still  more 
illogical  than  elsewhere.  Even  before  the  days  of 
Zarathustra  some  of  his  reasonings  would  have 
discredited  a  Conservative  speaker  opposing  Brad- 
laugh's  claim  to  be  sworn. 

Our  whole  European  morality  falls  to  pieces  with  the 
death  of  God.  Now,  in  disclaiming  the  will  to  deceive, 
we  stand  on  moral  principle.  But  supposing,  as  seems 
very  probable,  that  all  life  rests  on  a  basis  of  deception — 
what  then  ?  Would  it  not  be  Quixotic,  and  even  worse 
to  insist  on  veracity  ?  Let  there  be  no  mistake  about  it ; 
what  fires  us  still,  unbelievers  and  all,  is  the  old  Christian 
belief,  which  was  also  Plato's  belief,  that  God  is  the 
truth — that  truth  is  divine.  How,  then,  if  this  should 
seem  every  day  more  incredible,  if  God  himself  should 
prove  to  be  our  oldest  lie  ?' 

At  this  rate,  philosophers,  whose  chief  business 
it  is  to  investigate  truth,  might  be  expected  to 
receive  the  news  of  their  only  guarantor's  death 
with  some  dismay.  On  the  contrary,  they  show  an 
exultation  which,  in  the  circumstances,  strikes  one 
as  rather  indecent.  "  Our  whole  heart  overflows 
with  gratitude,  wonder,  and  hopeful  expectation."2 
Zarathustra  is  one  of  this  jubilant  band  ;  but,  then, 
he  sees  no  connection  between  theism  and  intel- 
lectual honesty  ( Redlichkeit ) ;  on  the  contrary,  he 

1  WW.,  V.,  pp.  271-276.  2  Ibid.,  p.  272. 


274         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

describes  the  latter  as  the  latest  born  among  the 
virtues,  and  hated,  as  knowledge  also  is  hated,  by 
those  who  have  God  on  the  brain.  "Good,"  or 
what  we  call  "goody,"  people  "never  tell  the 
truth."1  A  note  dating  from  the  same  period 
suggests  the  rather  awkward  compromise  that  we 
should  have  no  conscience  in  respect  to  truth  and 
error,  in  order  that  we  may  be  able  again  to  spend 
life  in  the  service  of  truth  and  of  the  intellectual 
conscience.2 

In  the  mass  of  notes  collected  for  what  was  to 
have  been  his  magnum  opus,  the  Wille  zur  Macht, 
an  untranslatable  title  which  we  may  approximately 
render  by  The  Will  to  be  Strong,  Nietzsche  nearly 
anticipates  Pragmatism.  Indeed,  it  might  seem  to 
be  completely  anticipated  in  such  sayings  as  that 
"truth  is  what  exalts  the  human  type";3  "  perhaps 
the  categories  of  reason  express  nothing  more  than 
a  definite  advantage  for  the  race  or  the  species  : 
their  utility  is  their  truth";4  "our  confidence  in 
reason  and  its  categories  only  proves  that  their 
utility  for  life  has  been  shown  by  experience,  not 
that  they  are  '  true'  ";5  were  they  not  balanced  by 
other  passages  of  a  distinctly  intellectualist  type, 
such  as  the  assertion  that  "  it  is  absolute  want  of 
intellectual  honesty  to  estimate  a  belief  by  the  way 
in  which  it  works,  not  by  its  truth";6  "  intellectual 
honesty  is  the  result  of  delicacy,  valour,  foresight, 
temperance,  practised  and  accumulated  through  a 
long  series  of  generations";7  "[with  Christianity] 
the  question  is  not  whether  a  thing  is  true,  but  how 

1   WW.,  VI.,  pp.  44  and  293.  »   WW.,  XII.,  p.  63. 

»  P.  153.  4  P.  274  sg.  *  Leben,  II.,  p.  775. 

6    W.  *.  M.,  p.  no.  i  Ibid.,  p.  245. 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  275 

it  works — which  is  an  absolute  want  of  intellectual 
honesty."1 

On  the  whole,  it  would  seem  as  if  this  extreme 
regard  for  veracity  were  only  used  as  a  means  for 
discrediting  religion,  morality,  and  the  Socratic 
philosophy.  And  their  defenders  might  plausibly 
allege  that  they  only  used  deception — when  they 
used  it — for  a  good  end ;  that  is  to  say,  for  an 
augmentation  of  vital  power.  "  Everything  for  the 
army,"  as  Colonel  Henry  said.  It  would  have 
been  more  consistent,  not  to  say  honest,  on  the 
part  of  Nietzsche  had  he  attacked  the  popular  creed 
simply  on  the  ground  that  it  lowered  the  vitality  of 
the  species.  Even  on  so  narrow  a  basis  the  attack 
could  not  have  been  worked  without  an  appeal  to 
disinterested  motives  ;  in  other  words,  without  an 
appeal  to  morality.  For  a  selfish  religionist  might 
well  prefer  the  gratification  of  his  mystical  cravings, 
and  a  priest  his  ambition,  to  the  health  of  the  race. 
But  here  also  our  critic  has  thrown  away  his  whole 
case  by  two  most  serious  admissions.  We  have 
first  a  frank  acknowledgment  that  "there  is  nothing 
diseased  about  the  gregarious  human  being  as 
such  ;  on  the  contrary,  he  is  of  inestimable  value, 
but  incapable  of  self-guidance,  and  therefore  in 
need  of  a  shepherd,  a  need  perfectly  understood  by 
priests."2  "  Petty  virtues  are  needed  for  petty 
people  ";3  and  when  the  lower  strata  of  the  popula- 
tion are  decadent  "a  religion  of  self-suppression, 
patience,  and  mutual  help  may  be  of  the  highest 
value."4  Therefore,  we  "require  that  gregarious 
morality  should  be  held  absolutely  sacred."5  And, 

1  Leben,  II.,  p.  719.     *  W.  z.  M.,  p.  209.     3  WW;  VI.,  p.  246. 
4  Leben,  II.,  p.  734.  s  2bid.t  p.  809. 


276         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

secondly,  we  find  a  parallel  acknowledgment  that 
Christianity  deserves  great  praise  as  "  the  genuine 
religion  of  the  herd."1  "The  continued  existence 
of  the  Christian  ideal  is  most  desirable.  My  object 
in  making  war  on  that  chlorotic  ideal  was  not  to 
destroy  it,  but  to  put  an  end  to  its  tyranny,  and 
to  make  room  for  new  and  robuster  ideals."2 
"  Common  people  are  only  endurable  when  they 
are  pious."3  They  are  not  likely  to  remain  pious 
long  where  books  like  The  Anti-Christian  circulate 
freely. 

In  England  we  have  had  a  good  supply  of  those 
"robuster  ideals,"  for  which  the  German  moralist 
wishes  to  find  room  ;  nor,  by  all  accounts,  are  they 
wanting  in  America  ;  yet  he  does  not  seem  to  have 
looked  to  either  country  for  his  models.  His 
enormous  self-esteem  would  have  suffered  by  such 
a  reference.  It  also  affected  his  conception  of  the 
superman,  who,  in  Nietzsche's  last  writings,  no 
longer  figures  as  a  new  species  destined  to  succeed 
and  displace  the  human  species,  but  rather  as  a 
superior  race,  like  the  Greeks — with  himself,  one 
may  suppose,  as  the  most  conspicuous  example  of 
their  perfections.  At  first  supermen  are  thought 
of,  not  as  ruling  over  the  inferior  race,  but  as  living 
apart  from  them,  "like  the  gods  of  Epicurus."4 
But  this  view  was  soon  found  impracticable,  and 
abandoned.  Throughout  the  Wille  zur  Mac/it 
nothing  is  contemplated  but  a  new  aristocracy,  a 
ruling  race,  whose  sole  business  will,  however,  not 
be  to  rule,  offering  splendid  examples  of  beauty, 
strength,  and  intelligence  for  the  delectation  of 

•   WW.,  XIV.,  p.  336.  *  Leben,  II.,  p.  744. 

s  WW.,  XII.,  p.  206.  «  Ibid.,  p.  211. 


FRIEDR1CH  NIETZSCHE  277 

themselves  and  of  the  lower  orders.1  Owing,  pre- 
sumably, to  their  wise  administration,  the  labourers 
are  to  live  as  the  middle  class  live  now ;  but  the 
higher  caste  above  them  will  be  distinguished  for 
its  abstinence.2  This  elite  naturally  falls  into  two 
divisions :  a  small  body  of  supremely  intellectual 
men  performing  the  highest  functions  and  leading 
the  most  perfect  life,  and,  below  them,  an  executive 
of  soldiers  and  judges  to  relieve  them  of  the  rough 
work  of  government ;  while  men  of  science  and  the 
majority  of  artists  will  find  their  appropriate  place 
among  the  labouring  classes.3 

It  has  been  mentioned  how  dependent  Nietzsche 
was  on  the  English  moralists  in  his  positivist 
period,  and  under  what  studied  rudeness  his  sense 
of  obligation  was  afterwards  concealed.  In  his 
last  or  fourth  period  the  debt  to  Plato  is  even 
more  obvious,  and  his  resentment  is  conveyed  in 
the  same  way,  only,  as  befits  the  occasion,  with 
extraordinarily  virulent  abuse.  Plato  is  "a  great 
Cagliostro,"  an  example  of  "  the  higher  swindling," 
"a  moral  fanatic,"  a  "poisoner  of  heathen  inno- 
cence," and,  worst  of  all,  "tedious."4 

It  might  be  asked  how  a  race  of  born  rulers  can 
be  called  into  existence  by  suspending  all  the  laws 
of  morality,  whether  the  duties  of  government  are 
likely  to  be  better  performed  by  an  aristocracy 
permanently  emancipated  from  every  social  obliga- 
tion, and,  finally,  whether  these  "  dragon  warriors 
from  Cadmean  teeth  "  are  likely  to  keep  the  peace 
with  each  other  longer  than  their  fabled  prototypes. 

1  W.  z.  M.,  p.  414  ;  Leben,  p.  798. 

*  WW.,  XII.,  p.  214.       3  WW.,  VIII.,  pp.  302  sq. 

«  W.  s.  M.,  pp.  234  and  244  ;  WW.,  VIII.,  p.  168. 


378         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

But  the  Wille  zur  Macht  opens  a  question  of  more 
practical  importance  for  Nietzsche's  philosophy 
than  these.  The  theory  adumbrated  in  that 
unfinished  work  seems  to  be  that  nature  consists 
of  nothing  but  energy  ;  that  the  natural  process 
consists  in  the  appropriation  of  energy  by  one  body 
at  the  expense  of  another  ;  that  the  ascending  line 
of  organic  development  is  determined  by  a  con- 
tinual gain,  and  the  descending  line  by  a  continual 
loss,  of  energy  ;  that,  in  so  far  as  we  can  use  such 
expressions  as  right  and  wrong,  the  right  morality 
consists  in  preferring  the  qualities  that  make  for 
vital  energy,  and  wrong  morality  in  preferring 
those  that  make  for  its  decay. 

So  far  there  is  nothing  in  this  philosophy  incom- 
patible with  the  assumption  that  great  individuali- 
ties are  the  highest  products  of  nature,  and  that 
their  production  is  the  worthiest  object  of  human 
endeavour.  Of  course,  it  always  remains  open  for 
Socrates,  Plato,  the  present  reviewer,  or  any  other 
wretched  decadent,  to  ask  why  we  should  scorn 
delights  and  live  laborious  days  in  order  to  promote 
the  evolution  of  some  future  Caesar  Borgia.  Sup- 
posing, however,  that  we  accept  the  transvaluation 
of  all  values  to  that  extent,  a  remorseless  logic  will 
impel  us  to  go  further,  and  make  a  united  Italy, 
which  was  Borgia's  own  ambition,  or  a  united 
Europe,  which,  according  to  Nietzsche,  was  Napo- 
leon's ambition,  or,  finally,  a  united  world,  the 
object  of  our  activity.  I  can  quite  imagine  and 
sympathise  with  a  valuation  that  counts  human 
personality  as  the  supreme  thing,  that  says  with 
Heracleitus,  "one  man  is  worth  ten  thousand  if  he 
be  the  best."  Only  Nietzsche  bars  himself  out 


FRIEDRICH  NIETZSCHE  279 

from  that  valuation  by  his  repeated  assurances  that 
personality  is  an  illusion.1  And  it  was  by  no 
freak  of  paradox  that  he  took  up  this  position.  It 
was  an  essential  part  of  his  antitheistic  polemic. 
According  to  him,  the  ascription  of  phenomena  to 
a  personal  cause  arises  from  the  fallacious  gram- 
matical abstraction  of  subject  and  predicate,  noun 
and  verb.  There  is  really  no  such  break  in  the 
continuous  stream  of  becoming.  Nor  is  theism 
the  only  result  of  this  mischievous  error.  By  a 
still  more  fatal  perversion,  gregarious  and  Chris- 
tian moralists,  in  their  vindictive  hostility  to  the 
rich  and  powerful,  coined  the  false  notion  of  per- 
sonal responsibility,  on  the  strength  of  which  their 
oppressors  were  to  be  visited  with  everlasting 
punishment.2 

If  I  may  borrow  an  illustration  from  Schopen- 
hauer, Nietzsche  is  like  the  magician  who  sent  his 
familiar  spirit  to  draw  water,  but  knew  no  spell 
that  could  stop  him,  with  the  result  that  he  and 
the  whole  country  were  drowned.  Our  modern 
Callicles  has  reformed  himself,  discarding  the 
brutal  licentiousness  of  his  prototype,  and  even 
adopting  the  passwords  of  Plato's  Republic.  But 
it  is  all  in  vain.  The  terrible  Socratic  dialectic 
works  on  and  on  to  his  utter  and  overwhelming 
confusion.  He  appeals  to  Power,  and  to  Power 
let  him  go.  He  invokes  a  superman,  who  will  be 
found  in  the  modern  State  ;  that  State  so  decried 
by  Zarathustra  as  the  stronghold  of  the  weak  and 
defenceless.  "  By  value  is  to  be  understood  the 
conditions  under  which  complex  vital  structures 

1  See,  among  other  passages,  W.  z.  M.,  p.  369. 
*  WW.,  VII.,  pp.  327-31. 


280         THE  MORALS  OF  AN  IMMORALIST- 

are  maintained  and  exalted."1  So  says  morality 
also  ;  but  above  the  individual,  however  gifted,  she 
places  the  State,  and  above  the  State  a  universal 
society  whose  object  is  the  greatest  good  of  all  its 
members  ;  a  good  which  for  purposes  of  conve- 
nience may  be  variously  expressed  in  terms  of 
pleasure,  of  life,  of  health,  or  of  power,  but  in 
which  the  good  of  the  parts  ultimately  coincides 
and  identifies  itself  with  the  good  of  the  whole. 

I  think  something  of  this  had  begun  to  dawn  on 
the  noble  spirit,  to  whom  I  have  tried  to  be  more 
just  than  he  was  to  my  teachers,  before  it  went 
down  under  the  waves  of  insanity.  For  among 
his  later  utterances  this  passage  occurs  :  "In  the 
whole  process  I  find  living  morality,  impelling 
force.  It  was  an  illusion  to  suppose  I  had 
transcended  good  and  evil.  Freethinking  itself 
was  a  moral  action,  as  honesty,  as  valour,  as 
justice,  and  as  love."2  And  this  confession  might 
have  been  extended  with  equal  truth  to  his  whole 
polemic  against  morality,  involving  as  it  did  the 
re-affirmation  of  moral  values  in  their  full  binding 
authority  at  every  step  in  the  evolution  of  the 
dialectical  process  by  which  they  were  to  be 
undone. 


1  Leben,  p.  790.  *  WW.,  XIV.,  p.  312. 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

To  many — perhaps  to  most — readers  it  may  seem 
as  if  the  question  "  What  is  Agnosticism  ?"  admitted 
of  an  obvious  and  easy  answer.  They  will  say  that 
the  term  for  which  an  explanation  is  asked  was 
created  by  a  master  both  of  language  and  of  thought, 
the  late  Professor  Huxley  ;  that  he  took  pains  on 
more  than  one  occasion  to  define  its  significance, 
and  that  we  ought  to  abide  by  his  ruling. 

If  there  are  any  such  persons,  I  must  demur  to 
their  contention.  Words  have  a  life  of  their  own 
quite  independent  of  their  author's  intentions,  and 
they  frequently  come  to  bear  a  meaning  very 
remote  from  that  to  which  they  were  originally 
restricted.  This  is  especially  true  of  party  names 
and  controversial  terms.  The  mere  evolution  of 
opinion  is  enough  to  carry  them  through  an  ever- 
changing  series  of  associations.  Many  who  now 
call  themselves  Protestants  hold  few  beliefs  in 
common  with  the  confessors  of  Augsburg  ;  and, 
within  a  far  shorter  period  of  time  than  that 
which  separates  us  from  the  Reformation,  the  word 
"  Opportunism  "  has  come  to  designate  a  political 
attitude  almost  precisely  the  reverse  of  that  adopted 
by  its  first  great  sponsor,  Gambetta. 

Thus,  even  if  Professor  Huxley  had  supplied  a 
definition  briefly  and  satisfactorily  indicating  the 
position  of  the  school  of  thought  to  which  he 
belonged,  and  if  he  had  steadily  held  to  that 

281 


282  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

definition  through  life,  the  question,  "  What  is  now 
meant  by  Agnosticism?"  must  sooner  or  later  have 
come  up  for  reconsideration.  And  I  will  proceed 
to  show,  from  Huxley's  recorded  utterances  on  the 
subject,  that  such  a  definition  is,  unfortunately,  not 
forthcoming. 

According  to  the  late  Mr.  R.  H.  Hutton,  as 
quoted  in  the  New  English  Dictionary  (better  known 
as  the  Oxford  Dictionary),  the  following  definition 
of  "  Agnostic  "  was  suggested  in  his  hearing  by 
Professor  Huxley  "at  Mr.  James  Knowles's  house 

one  evening  in  1869":  "One  who  holds  that 

the  existence  of  anything  beyond  and  behind 
material  phenomena  is  unknown  and  (so  far  as  can 
be  judged)  unknowable,  and  especially  that  a  First 
Cause  and  an  unseen  world  are  subjects  of  which 
we  know  nothing."  It  was  taken,  Mr.  Hutton 
adds,  from  St.  Paul's  mention  of  the  altar  to  "  the 
Unknown  God." 

Hutton  was  not  remarkable  for  the  accuracy  of 
his  printed  statements  ;  and  one  might  hesitate  to 
make  Huxley  responsible  for  such  slovenly  phrase- 
ology as  is  here  put  into  his  mouth,  had  not  the 
quotation  been  published  during  his  lifetime,  and 
suffered  to  pass  uncontradicted  as  recording  in  a 
monumental  work  the  exact  expression  of  his 
opinion.  Anyhow,  the  definition  will  not  hold 
water.  A  leak  is  sprung  by  the  introduction  of 
the  qualification  "material"  affixed  to  "pheno- 
mena." No  one  knew  better  than  Huxley  that 
there  are  non-material  phenomena  also — mental, 
spiritual,  or  whatever  we  are  to  call  them  ;  in  short, 
thought,  feeling,  and  volition.  Are  we,  then,  to 
conclude  that  an  Agnostic  may  admit  the  existence 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM?  283 

of  something  "beyond  and  behind  "  these?  And, 
if  so,  what  are  his  reasons  for  drawing  a  line  of 
distinction  between  the  two  classes  of  phenomena? 
Again,  limiting  ourselves  to  material  phenomena, 
does  an  Agnostic,  as  such,  necessarily  exclude  the 
atomic  theory  and  the  undulatory  theory  from  the 
domain  of  knowledge,  or  does  he  count  the  sup- 
posed atoms  and  ether  among  phenomena?  As  to 
the  altar  at  Athens,  of  course  anything  may  suggest 
anything  else  ;  but  one  cannot  help  noting  that 
Huxley  went  a  long  step  further  than  the  Athenians. 
They  gave  practical  evidence  of  their  conviction 
that  the  god  to  whom  the  altar  was  dedicated 
existed,  although  of  his  attributes  they  were  wholly 
ignorant.  Our  Agnostic,  on  the  contrary,  does 
not  know,  and  holds  that  there  is  no  possibility 
of  knowing,  whether  a  First  Cause  exists  or  not. 
And,  what  is  still  more  remarkable,  Herbert 
Spencer,  the  acknowledged  chief  of  the  Agnostic 
school,  could  not,  under  this  definition,  claim  to  be 
considered  an  Agnostic  at  all.  So  far  from  declaring 
the  existence  of  anything  behind  material  pheno- 
mena to  be  unknown  and  unknowable,  Spencer 
proclaimed,  as  our  supreme  certainty,  the  existence 
of  "an  Unconditioned  Reality  without  beginning 
or  end,"  from  which  all  phenomena  are  derived.1 

While  Huxley's  definition  excludes  certain 
persons  calling  themselves  Agnostics,  it  comes 
perilously  near  to  including  others  who  would 
repudiate  the  name.  How  are  we  to  class  thinkers 
who  say  with  Nietzsche  that  the  apparent  world  is 
the  real  world — there  being  no  other ;  or  with  Mr. 

1  First  Principles,  p.  192. 


284  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

F.  II.  Bradley,  that  the  Absolute  has  no  assets  but 
appearances?  If  we  identify  the  existent  with  the 
knowable  and  the  knowable  with  phenomena,  then, 
indeed,  we  neither  do  nor  can  know  anything  behind 
phenomena,  simply  because  no  such  thing  exists. 

Turn  we  now  from  Huxley's  reported  conversa- 
tion to  the  printed  declarations  of  his  later  years. 
Writing  to  defend  his  philosophy  against  a  number 
of  attacks  proceeding  from  various  quarters,  he 
says  : — 

Agnosticism  is  not  a  creed,  but  a  method,  the  essence 
of  which   lies   in   the  rigorous  application   of  a  single 

principle the    great    principle    of     Descartes the 

fundamental  axiom  of  modern  science.  Positively  the 
principle  may  be  expressed  :  In  matters  of  the  intellect 
follow  your  reason  as  far  as  it  will  take  you  without 
regard  to  any  other  consideration.  And  negatively  :  In 
matters  of  the  intellect  do  not  pretend  that  conclusions 
are  certain  which  are  not  demonstrated  or  demonstrable.1 

It  will  be  seen  that,  logically,  this  definition  has 
not  a  note  in  common  with  that  reported  by  Hutton. 
There  is  here  no  reference  to  phenomena,  material 
or  otherwise,  or  to  a  First  Cause,  or  to  the  unknown 
and  unknowable.  The  author  may  well  call  his 
principle  one  "of  great  antiquity";  the  wonder  is 
that  he  should  have  gone  out  of  his  way  to  invent 
for  it  a  new-fangled  name — a  name,  moreover,  which 
does  not  by  its  etymology  give  the  slightest  hint 
of  its  meaning.  Huxley  had  quite  enough  Greek 
scholarship  to  be  aware  that  the  word  ayvworoc  in 
Greek  philosophy  bears  the  sense  of  "  unknowable  " 
as  well  as  of  "unknown  ";  and  this  was  just  what 

1  From  an  article  on  "  Agnosticism  "  originally  published  in  the 
Nineteenth  Century  for  February,  1889,  and  reprinted  in  Essays 
on  Controverted  Questions  (London,  1892),  p.  362. 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  285 

made  the  name  derived  from  it  so  felicitous  a  desig- 
nation for  the  metaphysical  theory  recently  set  forth 
in  the  introduction  to  First  Principles,  and  what 
speedily  won  for  it  the  unanimous  acceptance  of 
the  educated  classes  in  England.  Assuredly  it  was 
accepted  as  designating — to  reverse  its  author's  claim 
— a  creed  rather  than  a  method,  the  extreme  applica- 
tion of  a  principle  rather  than  the  principle  itself. 

For  that  method,  for  that  principle,  proclaimed 
by  Huxley  in  his  later  days  as  what  Agnosticism 
really  designated,  a  name  already  existed,  or 
at  least  there  was  a  name  which,  with  a  couple 
of  explanations,  might  have  been  made  to  fit  it 
exactly.  I  mean  the  word  "  Rationalism,"  which 
certainly  has  the  disadvantage  of  connoting  a  certain 
hostility  to  theology,  but  a  hostility  by  no  means 
amounting  to  that  complete  rejection  which  Agnos- 
ticism has  been  supposed  to  imply.  I  say  "  dis- 
advantage," not  because  I  am  writing  as  an  advo- 
cate of  theology — whose  pretensions  I  am  not  now 
concerned  either  to  uphold  or  to  impugn — but 
because  it  seems  to  me  that  principles,  from  which 
opposite  conclusions  continue  to  be  drawn  with 
complete  sincerity  by  thinkers  of  equal  ability, 
ought  not  to  be  given  names  committing  their 
supporters  to  either  side  of  the  controverted  issues. 
Huxley  himself  seems  to  have  felt  that,  in  propor- 
tion as  he  widened  the  meaning  of  the  word 
"Agnostic,"  he  raised  it  to  a  new  eminence  above 
the  disputed  dogmas  of  the  hour.  "  Agnosticism," 
he  assures  us,  "  has  no  quarrel  with  scientific 
theology."1  What,  then,  becomes  of  his  own 

1  Op.  dt.,p.  452. 


2S6 

famous  epigram,  penned  only  a  few  months  before  : 
"  If  Mr.  Harrison,  like  most  people,  means  by 
'  religion  '  theology,  then  in  my  judgment  Agnos- 
ticism can  be  said  to  be  a  stage  in  its  evolution 
only  as  death  may  be  said  to  be  the  final  stage  in 
the  evolution  of  life."1  If  the  Agnostic  has  no 
quarrel  with  the  scientific  theologian,  it  is  only  in 
the  same  sense  in  which  we  say  that  the  executioner 
has  no  quarrel  with  his  victim. 

It  need  hardly  be  observed  that  Huxley's  rather 
weak  attempt  to  back  out  of  his  earlier  and  far 
more  characteristic  attitude  of  mortal  enmity  to 
all  theology,  "  scientific  "  or  otherwise,  remained 
without  influence  on  the  common  use  of  the  word 
originally  created  to  express  that  attitude.  Launched 
at  first  starting  in  a  negative  direction,  it  soon 
received  a  new  impulse  in  the  same  sense,  from  a 
steadier,  and  in  this  instance  a  more  powerful,  hand. 
In  truth,  its  great  success  as  a  party  name  first 
dates  from  an  essay  entitled  "  An  Agnostic's 
Apology,"  contributed  by  Leslie  Stephen  to  the 
Fortnightly  Review  in  June,  1876.  In  that  deliver- 
ance of  conscience  there  was  a  note  of  poignant 
experience  that  riveted  attention,  and  an  accent 
of  sincerity  that  commanded  respect.  Here  was 
evidently  one  to  whom,  at  a  supreme  crisis,  the 
consolations  of  theology  had  once  more  been 
offered,  and  who  had  angrily  flung  them  aside  as 
not  merely  illusory,  but  as  adding  a  new  sting  to 
the  anguish  of  bereaved  affection.  For  the  rest, 
Leslie  Stephen  put  the  Agnostic  case  in  a  nutshell. 
There  are  limits  to  the  human  intelligence,  and 

1  Op,  dt.t  p.  366. 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  287 

theology  lies  outside  those  limits.  Mansel,  in  his 
Bampton  Lectures  on  The  Limits  of  Religious 
Thought,  had  adopted  this  position,  but  had  used 
it  to  screen  the  mysteries  of  orthodox  Christianity 
against  Rationalistic  criticism.  The  same  prin- 
ciples were  then  taken  up  and  pushed  to  their 
logical  conclusion  by  Herbert  Spencer,  whom 
Stephen  seems  to  regard,  with  justice,  as  the 
founder  of  modern  English  Agnosticism,  and  whose 
presentation,  I  may  add,  remains  the  most  complete 
and  systematic  form  of  the  doctrine.  It  must  be 
observed,  however,  that  with  Spencer,  as  with 
Mansel,  though  not  to  the  same  extent,  Agnos- 
ticism has  a  positive  side,  to  which  Leslie  Stephen 
does  not  call  attention.  The  object  of  his  "  apology  " 
was  not,  in  fact,  to  give  an  exhaustive  view  of  the 
subject,  but  rather  to  retort  on  believers  the  charge 
of  giving  up  the  attempt  to  solve  the  riddles  of 
existence. 

To  say  that  man's  intelligence  has  limits  is  not 
to  say  that  within  those  limits  it  is  impotent.  To 
declare  that  certain  problems  are  insoluble  is  not 
to  deny  that  other  problems  have  been  solved,  and 
that  many  more  may  be  attacked  with  good  hope 
of  success.  These  are  truisms,  but  apparently 
they  are  truisms  that  need  to  be  occasionally  re- 
stated and  enforced.  The  vulgar  are  not  quick  to 
draw  distinctions  ;  and,  hearing  that  Agnosticism 
had  something  to  do  with  not  knowing,  they  took 
it  to  imply  not  so  much  ignorance  of  the  Absolute 
as  absolute  ignorance.  Richard  Hutton,  with  his 
usual  inaccuracy,  translated  it  into  "a  sort  of  know- 
nothingism  ";  and  Laurence  Oliphant  makes  a  very 
modern  young  man,  in  his  novel,  Altiora  Peto, 


288  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM? 

say  to  the  heroine  :  "  We  neither  of  us  know  any- 
thing or  believe  anything  ;  in  other  words,  we  are 
both  Agnostics."  So,  also,  a  very  recent  writer  of 
high  philosophical  pretensions,  Dr.  Percy  Gardner, 
in  the  opening  pages  of  his  Exploratio  Evangelica, 
seems  to  use  "  Agnostic  "  and  "  Sceptic  "  as  synony- 
mous terms.  What  was  said  of  Huxley's  definition 
may  be  repeated  in  this  connection.  There  is  no 
need  to  coin  a  new  word  when  there  is  an  old  word 
of  the  same  value  in  general  circulation.  But  the 
popular  confusion  may  be  turned  to  good  account. 
From  one  point  of  view  nothing  throws  a  more 
vivid  light  on  the  meaning  of  Agnosticism  than  to 
contrast  it  with  Scepticism.  The  ancient  Sceptics 
doubted  everything,  and  were  at  last  driven  to  the 
pass  of  doubting  that  they  doubted.  This  paradox 
helps  us  to  understand  the  logical  difficulty  of  their 
position.  The  very  notion  of  doubt  would  be 
impossible  without  the  correlative  notion  of  certainty 
to  serve  as  a  standard  of  comparison.  But  the 
notion  of  certainty  can  be  acquired  only  by  the 
experience  of  knowledge.  It  may  be  said  that  our 
certainties  have  often  turned  out  to  be  illusory  ; 
but  that  is  only  because  the  standard  of  knowledge 
has  been  raised  :  our  very  disillusionment  proves 
that  we  have  a  standard  still.  Here  is  a  law  which 
the  Agnostic,  unlike  the  Sceptic,  has  recognised. 
He  claims  to  possess  knowledge  within  the  limits 
of  experience  so  abundant  in  quantity  and  so  good 
in  quality  that  it  furnishes  sufficient  material  for  an 
exhaustive  analysis,  by  which  he  succeeds,  at  least 
to  his  own  satisfaction,  in  determining  the  nature 
and  conditions  of  all  knowledge  —  in  framing  a 
concept  of  knowledge  in  general.  Briefly  stated, 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM?  289 

the  result  is  this  :  The  whole  content  of  conscious- 
ness resolves  itself  into  groups  of  phenomena 
arranged  according  to  certain  laws  of  resemblance, 
difference,  co-existence,  and  succession.  These 
groups  and  their  component  parts  severally  become 
associated  with  particular  signs,  generally  called 
names  ;  and  a  group  is  said  to  be  known  when  the 
order  of  its  components  is  accurately  reproduced 
by  the  order  of  the  signs  that  denote  them. 

Agnostics  contend  that  something  exists  inde- 
pendently of  phenomena — that  is,  independently  of 
our  states  of  consciousness — but  a  something  that 
cannot  be  known.  Their  arguments  may  be  con- 
veniently distributed  under  three  heads.  First  as 
regards  the  material  world.  Modern  science  leads 
us  to  the  conception  of  multitudinous  invisible 
atoms  attracting  and  repelling  one  another  in 
various  ways,  or,  as  some  would  prefer  to  state  the 
case,  of  minute  masses  moving  towards,  or  away 
from,  one  another.  But  it  seems  to  be  generally 
admitted  that  when  we  talk  of  forces  and  atoms,  or 
of  mass  and  motion,  we  are  only  using  convenient 
fictions  for  the  purpose  of  making  the  phenomena 
amenable  to  our  methods  of  calculation.  Even 
supposing  force  and  matter,  as  we  conceive  them, 
to  exist  independently  of  our  conceptions,  we 
should  not  know  what  they  are  in  themselves,  nor 
the  reason  of  their  behaviour.  We  cannot  get 
inside  them,  nor  can  our  analysis  extract  anything 
from  their  mutual  relations,  but  sequences  and 
co-existences,  which,  for  aught  we  can  tell,  might 
have  been  of  an  altogether  different  description. 
Still  less,  if  possible,  can  we  explain  the  existence, 
as  a  whole,  of  the  material  world.  It  can  neither 

u 


290  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

be  conceived  as  having  been  there  from  all  eternity, 
nor  as  having  had  a  beginning  before  which  there 
was  nothing,  nor  as  having  been  created  out  of 
nothing  by  an  immaterial  cause.  Finally,  our 
ignorance  on  these  points  altogether  precludes 
the  question  for  what  purpose  the  world  exists — 
excludes  even  the  assumption  that  it  has  any 
purpose  whatever. 

If  material  phenomena  consist  for  us  in  some  of 
the  fleeting  shows  of  consciousness,  it  is  incon- 
ceivable, according  to  the  Spencerian  Agnostic, 
that  they  should  be  the  mere  product  of  our  mental 
activity.  They  come  and  go  in  complete  inde- 
pendence of  our  volition ;  they  have  an  order  which 
is  not  that  of  our  thoughts  and  feelings ;  we  are 
convinced  that  they  stand  for  a  reality  which  is 
older  than  our  consciousness,  and  which  will 
survive  when  we  are  no  more. 

Passing  from  the  objective  to  the  subjective 
sphere,  from  material  to  mental  phenomena,  the 
limitations  to  knowledge  make  themselves  still 
more  painfully  felt.  Experience  shows  that  our 
only  data,  the  processes  of  consciousness,  are  dis- 
continuous. Never  was  a  more  unwarrantable 
dictum  than  that  "The  soul  always  thinks."  /,  at 
any  rate,  do  not  always  think  ;  nor  am  I  interested 
in  an  assumed  something  that  vicariously  performs 
that  office  for  me  in  the  hours  of  unconsciousness, 
and  that,  to  use  Fichte's  illustration,  is  no  more 
myself  than  is  a  piece  of  lava  in  the  moon.  If,  then, 
we  assume  an  enduring  substance  as  the  supporter 
of  thought  and  feeling,  it  must  have  a  possible  and 
very  frequently  an  actual  existence  apart  from  these 
manifestations  ;  that  is  to  say,  considered  in  its 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  291 

absolute  self-existence,  it  must  be  unconscious,  and 
therefore  inconceivable  to  us.  Equally  inconceiv- 
able is  the  materialistic  theory  that  thought  and 
feeling  are  the  products  of  molecular  changes  in  the 
nervous  tissue  ;  and,  even  were  it  conceivable,  we 
should,  by  accepting  it,  be  thrown  back  on  the 
ultimate  impossibility  of  interpreting  physical 
phenomena  in  terms  of  absolute  reality.  And,  as 
the  essence  of  mind  is  unknown,  so  neither  is  any 
complete  explanation  of  its  processes  forthcoming. 
Our  analysis  ends  with  empirical  sequences  for 
which  no  reason  can  be  given.  Equally  hopeless 
is  the  attempt  to  account  for  the  origin  of  con- 
sciousness in  time.  So  far  as  the  inhabitants  of 
this  planet  are  concerned,  we  know  that  conscious- 
ness had  a  beginning  ;  but  we  know  nothing  else. 
That  it  came  out  of  mechanical  movements,  or  that 
it  was  created  by  another  consciousness,  or  that  it 
was  uncaused,  seem  to  be  equally  inconceivable 
alternatives.  Thus,  if  there  is  a  reality  behind 
and  beyond  consciousness,  it  must  be  unknowable  ; 
but  for  the  existence  of  such  a  reality  we  have  the 
strongest  testimony  of  consciousness  itself. 

The  third  argument  for  Agnosticism  is  drawn 
from  considerations  of  a  highly  metaphysical 
character,  counting,  I  think,  for  much  less  at  the 
present  day  than  in  the  middle  decades  of  the 
last  century.  We  used  to  be  told  that  the  Finite 
implied  an  Infinite,  the  Relative  an  Absolute,  the 
Conditioned  an  Unconditioned  ;  that  we  could  not 
have  a  distinct  consciousness  of  the  one  without 
a  vague  consciousness  of  the  other ;  that,  while 
knowledge  involves  the  antithesis  of  subject  and 
object,  it  also  involves  their  synthesis  in  a  higher 


*9*  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

unity.  Perhaps  these  abstractions  will  not  look  so 
alarming  if  we  approach  them  from  a  less  dialectical 
point  of  view.  What  we  know  we  know  by  think- 
ing ;  and  to  think  is  to  condition,  to  limit,  to  bring 
into  relation.  The  most  universal  of  all  relations 
is  that  of  subject  and  object,  the  knower  and  the 
known.  The  subject-matter  of  knowledge  is  the 
whole  content  of  consciousness  ;  and  this,  as  we 
have  already  seen,  comes  to  be  arranged  under 
various  forms  which  it  is  the  business  of  the  intellect 
to  recognise,  some  states  of  consciousness  being 
referred  to  an  external  world,  and  the  remainder  to 
our  own  mind.  If  by  an  effort  of  abstraction  we 
think  away  the  forms  of  thought,  their  content  does 
not  disappear.  There  remains  an  indestructible 
reality  which  we  cannot  conceive  (for  to  conceive 
would  be  to  condition  and  relationise),  but  of  which 
we  are  vaguely  conscious — without  which,  indeed, 
the  developed  consciousness  called  knowledge 
would  be  impossible.  Being  without  relations, 
this  pure  existence  may  be  spoken  of  as  absolute  ; 
being  without  limit,  it  may  be  spoken  of  as  infinite  ; 
being  common  to  object  and  subject,  it  may  be 
said  to  transcend  their  distinction.  That  ultimate 
reality,  whose  presence  and  pressure  we  have 
already  felt  before  and  behind  phenomena,  now 
floods  the  barriers  of  the  outer  and  inner  sense, 
penetrating  and  filling  the  phenomenal  sphere 
itself. 

This  is  the  unknown  and  unknowable  that 
Agnostics  confess — at  least,  all  Agnostics  of  the 
Spencerian  persuasion  ;  and,  since  Huxley  devised 
a  name  that  so  admirably  hit  off  their  doctrine,  I 
submit  that  his  restriction  of  it  to  a  method  which 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  293 

might  conceivably  lead  to  quite  different  results  is 
not  justified  by  the  ordinary  usages  of  language, 
or  by  the  exigencies  of  scientific  phraseology. 
Indeed,  the  frank  admission,  contained  in  one  of 
his  later  essays,  that  he  did  "  not  very  much  care 
to  speak  of  anything  as  '  unknowable,'  "x  although 
he  certainly  did  so  speak  at  the  outset  of  his  philo- 
sophical career,  seems  to  show  that  his  meta- 
physical attitude  had  undergone  a  change  that 
made  the  word  under  discussion  no  longer  the 
fittest  to  express  it. 

If,  as  is  very  possible,  some  of  my  readers  do  not 
find  the  above  arguments  very  convincing,  I  must 
beg  them  to  believe  that  I  am  not  writing  as  an 
advocate  of  Agnosticism,  and  that  its  professed 
adherents  might  very  well  be  able  to  put  their  case 
in  a  stronger  manner.  Those  who  wish  for  a 
complete  and  authoritative  view,  presented  in  the 
best  possible  light,  will,  of  course,  find  it  in  the 
opening  chapters  of  First  Principles.  The  word 
"  Agnostic "  does  not  there  occur  ;  but  Herbert 
Spencer  adopted  it  in  subsequent  publications  as  a 
suitable  designation  for  the  school  which  he  repre- 
sented. My  present  purpose,  however,  is  to  fix 
attention  on  the  results  to  which  the  reasonings  of 
the  school  have  led  rather  than  on  the  reasonings 
themselves.  And  I  now  propose  to  consider  those 
results  in  reference  to  the  claims  of  theology  on 
belief. 

The  group  of  controversial  essays  in  which 
Huxley  set  forth  his  latest  opinions  on  this  question 
with  so  much  vigour,  but,  as  I  have  tried  to  show, 

1  "  Agnosticism  and  Christianity,"  op.  cif.,  p.  451. 


294  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

with   so  little  precision,  was  called  forth   by  the 
angry  utterances   of  some   English   divines,  who 
seemed  to  be  irritated  and  dismayed  by  the  general 
acceptance  of  a  party  name  which  could  be  applied 
to  their  opponents  without  giving  them   offence. 
Judging  with   perfect  accuracy  that   Agnosticism 
implied   the   rejection  of  Christianity,  and   being 
interested  in   it  only  to  that  extent,  they  declared 
that  Agnostics  were,  in  plain  language,  infidels, 
and  should  without  ceremony  be  branded  as  such. 
The  demand  showed  a  certain  want  of  urbanity, 
and  still  more  a  want  of  discrimination.      Even 
granting  that  the  rejection  of  the  Christian  faith — 
or,  rather,  of  all  the  somewhat  discordant  creeds 
clustered  together    under    that    appellation — is  a 
deplorable  error,  it  has  ceased  to  be  regarded  as  a 
crime ;  and  therefore  it  should  not  be  confounded 
under  the  same  denomination  with  what  is  criminal 
— the  violation  of  a  plighted  troth.     But,  waiving 
the  question   of  good   manners  and  the  undesir- 
ability    to    a    logical    understanding    of   classing 
Agnostics  with  adulterers  and  fraudulent  trustees, 
there  is,  perhaps,  something  to  be  said  for  the  pro- 
priety of  countenancing  the  distinctions  set  up  by 
Freethinkers  among  themselves.     If  all  Agnostics 
are  "infidels,"  all  "infidels"  are  not  Agnostics; 
and   some    would    abjure    communion   with    that 
particular  sect  as  heartily  as  any  Churchman,  nor 
would   they  meet  with   very   respectful   treatment 
from  its  devotees.     Carlyle  and  Francis  Newman, 
Emerson    and    Theodore    Parker,    perhaps    even 
James  Martineau,  certainly  Clifford,  were  all,   to 
the   Anglican   mind,    "infidels";   yet   not  one  of 
them  was  an  Agnostic.     Hegel,  who  was  never 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  295 

weary  of  denouncing  the  current  acquiescence  in 
ignorance  of  things  in  themselves,  used  to  pass,  I 
think  with  reason,  as  a  formidable  enemy  of  Chris- 
tianity ;  and  the  English  neo-Hegelians  may  be 
the  next  foe  with  whom  orthodoxy  will  have  to 
reckon.  There  is,  I  know,  a  good  deal  of  coquetry 
going  on  just  now  between  the  dialectic  philosophy 
and  the  higher  Catholicism  ;J  but  something  of  the 
same  sort  happened  at  Berlin  before  the  advent  of 
Strauss  and  Feuerbach. 

As  a  philosophical  system  Agnosticism  has 
much  that  is  unobjectionable,  or  even  acceptable, 
to  the  religious  believer.  Cardinal  Newman,  in 
defending  the  reasonableness  of  transubstantiation, 
urged  that  we  do  not  know  what  matter  is  in  itself; 
and  doubtless  he  would  have  avowed  the  same 
ignorance  about  the  essence  of  mind.  Of  course, 
no  Christian,  and,  indeed,  no  theist,  will  admit 
that  the  origin  of  the  world  or  of  our  own  con- 
sciousness is  unknown  ;  but  if  he  is  candid  he  will 
admit  that  to  adduce  the  will  of  a  divine  Creator  as 
a  sufficient  cause  for  either  is  merely  to  push  the 
difficulty  a  step  further  back.  That  a  self-conscious 
intelligence,  with  power  to  make  a  world  out  of 
nothing,  should  have  existed  from  all  eternity  is 
not  in  itself  a  proposition  of  axiomatic  evidence, 
nor  intrinsically  more  conceivable  than  its  con- 
tradictory ;  and  nothing  that  is  not  a  self-evident 
axiom  can  be  taken  as  ultimate  in  philosophy. 
Without  going  into  the  question  of  origins,  the 
incomprehensibility  of  God  has  long  been  a  theo- 
logical commonplace.  Like  Huxley,  the  religious 

1  Written  in  1900. 


296  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

believer  may  "  not   much   care  to   talk  about  the 
4  Unknowable ' "  (with  or  without  a  capital)  ;  but 
he  would  hardly  refuse  to  admit  that  the   divine 
nature,  being  infinite,  can  never  be  fully  understood 
by  a  finite  intelligence.     He  may  appeal  to  revela- 
tion, either  the  revelation  of  his  own  conscience  or 
the  revelation  given  by  inspired  writers,  as  affording 
some  certain  knowledge  of  God's  will ;  but,  so  far, 
his  knowledge  of  divine  things  amounts  to  no  more 
than  the  knowledge  of  nature   that  an   Agnostic 
professes  to  derive  from  the  study  of  material  and 
mental  phenomena.     This  also  may,  without  much 
straining,  be  called  a  revelation  ;  and  the  truth  of 
each  revelation  is  relative,  to  the  extent  of  being 
conditioned  by  the  capacity  of  its  recipient.      A 
Christian  may  plead  that  to  have  the  same  assurance 
of  God's  existence  that  a  Spencerian  Agnostic  has 
of  the  existence  of  an  objective  world,  or  of  his 
fellow-men,  or,  if  it  comes   to   that,  of  his   own 
existence,  is  a  sufficiently  solid  basis  for  hisTheistic 
faith.     He  may,  if  he  chooses,  draw  out  a  further 
parallel  between  the  workings  of  the  Power  mani- 
fested to  us  through  all  existence1  and  the  workings 
of  God  as  manifested  in  the  scheme  of  redemption. 
Agnosticism   and  Christianity  do  not,   then,  as 
some  seem  to  suppose,  form  a  sharply  contrasted 
and  mutually  exclusive  couple  ;  still  less  are  they 
alternatives  exhausting  the  possibilities  of  serious 
belief.     An   Agnostic  may  become   convinced  by 
reading  Hegel  that  "  the  universe  is  penetrable  by 
thought,"  and  yet  have  moved  to  a  greater  distance 
from  faith  in  a  personal  God  ;  and  a  Christian  may 

1  First  Principles,  p.  112. 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  297 

let  fall  every  article  in  his  creed  but  that  one, 
holding  it  as  a  truth  given  by  experience  and 
induction.  The  one  will  have  ceased  to  be  an 
Agnostic,  and  the  other  will  have  ceased  to  be  a 
Christian  ;  but  their  positions  will  not  have  been 
exchanged.  Indeed,  this  whole  system  of  alter- 
natives is  a  fiction  invented  by  brow-beating  con- 
troversialists, and  accepted  by  a  public  too  lazy  or 
too  impatient  for  the  exercise  of  that  private  judg- 
ment which  it  professes  to  prize  so  dearly. 

The  truth  is  that  the  Agnostic  rejects  Christianity 
on  grounds  quite  distinct  from  the  metaphysical 
considerations  by  which  he  has  become  convinced 
that  things  in  themselves  cannot  be  known.  A 
course  of  logical  and  ethical  analysis  has  led  him 
to  think  that  the  doctrines  held  in  common  by  all 
the  Churches  are  inconsistent  with  themselves  and 
with  the  morality  that  they  profess  to  teach.  A 
course  of  historical  criticism  has  led  him  to  think 
that  miracles  do  not  happen  ;  that  there  never  was 
a  revelation  ;  that  the  advent  of  Christianity  can 
be  explained,  like  any  other  phenomenon  in  the 
evolution  of  religion,  by  natural  causes.  The 
whole  process  is  well  exhibited  in  that  masterpiece 
of  mental  autobiography,  Francis  Newman's  Phases 
of  Faith — a  work,  in  my  opinion,  far  superior  to 
his  brother's  more  celebrated  Apologia. 

But  the  modern  Agnostic  does  not  find  rest, 
where  the  younger  Newman  found  it,  in  the  creed 
of  ethical  Theism.  Starting  in  early  youth  from  a 
much  more  advanced  position,  and  enjoying  much 
greater  liberty  of  thought  than  was  possible  in  the 
first  half  of  the  last  century,  he  attacks  the  supreme 
questions  of  theology  with  a  more  open  and  a  more 


298  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM? 

active  mind.  What  is  of  still  greater  importance, 
he  finds  himself  supplied,  by  the  advance  of  positive 
knowledge,  with  a  new  set  of  ideas — above  all,  with 
the  idea  of  evolution. 

Much  has  been  written  about  the  relations 
between  evolution  and  theology,  and  the  subject 
is  still  far  from  being  exhausted.  Only  a  few 
leading  points  can  be  touched  on  here.  The 
Darwinian  theory,  so  far  as  it  went,  was  adverse 
to  natural  Theism  because  it  tended  to  substitute 
mechanical  for  teleological  causation.  In  more 
familiar  language,  it  did  away  with  the  argument 
from  design  in  a  field  where  that  argument  had 
hitherto  reigned  supreme.  At  one  stroke  a  single 
volume  made  large  libraries  obsolete.  Even  if  it 
could  be  shown  that  natural  selection  had  not  the 
efficacy  attributed  to  it  by  Darwin,  and  still  more 
by  Weismann,  the  old  methods  of  reasoning  would 
not  recover  from  the  shock  they  received  when  it 
was  first  promulgated  ;  for  here  was  a  totally  new 
explanation  of  the  mechanism  by  which  organisms 
are  adapted  to  their  environment,  and  none  could 
tell  how  many  more  such  explanations  the  science 
of  the  future  holds  in  reserve,  "  one  sure  if  another 
fails."  Hence  the  rule,  now  generally  admitted, 
that  appeals  to  supernatural  intervention  do  not  lie 
in  the  region  of  physical  phenomena. 

Evolution  is  not,  however,  limited  to  the  region 
of  physical  phenomena.  Under  the  influence  of 
the  new  doctrine,  mental  phenomena  also — feeling, 
volition,  and  reason — came  to  be  interpreted  as  part 
of  the  vast  mechanism  by  which  organisms  are 
adapted  to  their  environment,  and  as  having,  like 
every  other  part,  grown  up  gradually  in  response 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  299 

to  the  demands  of  life.  How,  then,  could  such 
obviously  relative  qualities  be  legitimately  ascribed 
to  the  absolute  cause  or  substance  of  things?  Our 
moral  nature  in  particular,  which  had  long  been 
claimed  by  religious  teachers  as  a  peculiar 
revelation  of  the  transcendent  realities,  became  an 
adaptation  like  any  other — a  social  instinct,  a  racial 
heritage,  secured  by  the  survival  of  the  fittest. 
The  spiritual  experiences  confidently  appealed  to 
by  believers  could  be  explained  away  by  the  evolu- 
tionist as  survivals  of  the  hallucinated  states  known 
to  occur  with  far  more  intensity  among  primitive 
men. 

Behind  the  dynamic  law  of  evolution  our  Middle 
Victorian  inquirer  found  another  and  a  greater  law, 
more  luminous  in  its  evidence,  more  sweeping  in 
its  applicability,  more  inflexible  in  the  severity  of 
its  control — the  static  law  of  conservation,  the  prin- 
ciple that  the  quantity  of  energy  in  the  universe 
remains  unaltered  and  unalterable,  without  increase 
or  diminution,  through  all  time.  This  principle 
enabled  him  to  arrive  by  a  more  summary  process 
at  the  results  already  detailed.  Miracles,  which 
historical  criticism  had  shown  to  be  fictitious,  were 
fictitious  because  they  were  impossible — because 
their  performance  would  involve  a  creation  or  a 
destruction  of  energy.1  And  the  same  principle 
might  be  applied  to  the  whole  range  of  religious 
experiences  still  maintained  by  natural  Theism, 
including  the  efficacy  of  prayer  and  the  very 

1  In  view  of  the  ignorance  still  prevalent  on  this  subject,  I  must 
mention  that  to  give  energy  a  new  direction,  not  determined  by 
pre-existing  energy,  involves  either  the  creation  or  the  destruction 
of  energy. 


300  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

existence  of  human  free-will.  Theologians  might 
call  this  reasoning  in  a  circle.  They  might  say 
that  to  assume  that  the  law  of  conservation  held 
without  exception  was  to  assume  the  very  point  at 
issue,  whether  supernatural  intervention  was  possible 
or  not.  Herbert  Spencer  and  his  disciples  would 
reply  that  the  conservation  of  energy,  or,  as  they 
preferred  to  call  it,  the  persistence  of  force,  was, 
like  the  axioms  of  geometry,  a  truth  known  a  priori, 
and  verified  by  the  inconceivableness  of  its  contra- 
dictory. Thinkers  of  a  more  moderate  school 
would  be  content  to  argue  that  a  principle  found 
to  prevail  over  the  whole  field  of  phenomena 
accessible  to  exact  observation  and  experiment 
showed  the  highest  probability  of  being  true 
without  exception. 

Another  point  remains  to  be  noticed  as  illus- 
trating the  latent  hostility  between  Theism  and  the 
law  of  conservation.  I  refer  to  what  is  known  as 
the  order  of  nature  and  its  implications.  The 
subject  was  a  favourite  theme  with  the  Rev.  Pro- 
fessor Baden  Powell,  famous  for  his  epoch-making 
contribution  to  Essays  and  Reviews,  and,  what 
now  seems  forgotten,  a  fervent  evolutionist  before 
Darwin.  This  very  liberal  divine,  while  frankly 
abandoning  miracles,  insisted  on  the  order  of  nature, 
the  unbroken  supremacy  of  law,  as  the  one  all- 
sufficient  proof  that  the  world  was  ruled  by  a 
personal  God.  But,  according  to  Herbert  Spencer, 
order  and  law  simply  mean  that  the  quantity  of 
matter  existing  always  remains  the  same,  that  its 
properties  are  constant,  and  that  the  variations  in 
the  movements  of  its  particles  are  mutually  com- 
pensatory— all  consequences  of  the  conservation 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  301 

of  energy.1  What  we  call  the  order  of  nature  is 
merely  another  expression  for  that  ultimate  self- 
identity  of  the  universe  which  reason  is  not  needed 
to  explain,  for  it  first  makes  reasoning  possible  to  us. 
It  will  be  observed  that,  so  far,  the  case  has  been 
conducted  on  behalf  of  our  supposed  free  inquirer, 
without  any  reference  to  Agnostic  principles.  His 
appeal  has  not  been  to  the  new  nescience,  but  to 
the  new  science.  A  point  has  been  now  reached 
where  the  intervention  of  Agnosticism  can  be 
explained.  Left  alone  on  what  Carlyle  calls  the 
shoreless  fountain-ocean  of  force,  to  what  stars 
shall  we  turn  for  guidance  ?  The  position  was 
not  new.  The  philosophers  who  met  round  Baron 
D'Holbach's  dinner-table,  the  English  Benthamites, 
the  German  materialists,  had  reached  very  similar 
conclusions,  and  had  called  them  "  Atheism."  The 
disciples  of  Nietzsche  would  call  them  so  still. 
With  a  little  ingenuity  they  could  equally  well  be 
fitted  into  the  creed  of  Pantheism  more  or  less 
openly  professed  by  Goethe  and  Herder  at  Weimar, 
by  Schelling  and  Hegel  at  Jena,  by  Coleridge  and 
Wordsworth  at  Alfoxden.  But  it  so  happened  that 
England,  in  1860,  was  under  the  dominion  of  the 
Kantian  criticism  ;  not  that  many  students  read 
Kant  for  themselves,  but  the  chief  results  of  his 
philosophy  had  been  presented  in  what,  as  com- 
pared with  the  original,  might  be  called  a  popular 
form  by  Hamilton  and  Mansel.  Now,  it  is  inter- 
esting to  note  that  these  two  writers,  both  strong 
supporters  of  the  received  opinions,  were  particu- 
larly earnest  opponents  of  German  Pantheism, 

1  This  argument  was  pressed  against  Baden  Powell  by  G.  J. 
Romanes  in  his  non-theistic  days. 


302  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

at  that  time  a  great  bugbear  to  the  orthodox. 
Hamilton,  for  all  his  boasted  learning,  was  not 
very  deeply  read  in  German  philosophy,  and  his 
acquaintance  with  Schelling  and  Hegel,  the  latter 
especially,  seems  to  have  been  superficial;  his 
attack  is  directed  chiefly  against  a  flashy  combina- 
tion of  their  theories,  put  together,  with  more 
rhetorical  skill  than  sincerity,  by  the  Parisian 
sophist,  Victor  Cousin.  Mansel,  on  the  other 
hand,  knew  a  good  deal  about  Hegel,  and  seems 
to  have  anticipated  with  singular  prescience  the 
future  ascendancy  of  Hegelianism  at  Oxford, 
although  he  probably  did  not  foresee  that  it  would 
be  converted  by  some  professors  into  a  bulwark  of 
Anglican  theology.  To  him  Hegel  was  the  master 
of  Strauss  and  Baur,  the  author  of  a  method  for 
dissipating  dogma  into  mist ;  and  he  turned  for 
salvation,  as  Hamilton  had  already  turned,  to  Kant, 
with  whose  help  Atheism  also  could  be  refuted. 

To  some  persons  Pantheism  and  Atheism  are 
indistinguishable ;  to  others  they  stand  for  the 
widest  possible  contrasts  of  belief;  but  it  will  be 
generally  admitted  that  on  one  important  point 
they  are  agreed.  Both  alike  assume  that  things 
in  themselves  can  be  known.  The  philosophy  of 
Atheism  is,  as  a  rule,  materialistic  or  monadistic. 
Mass  and  motion  are  intelligible  conceptions  apart 
from  our  consciousness,  and  from  mass  and  motion 
all  phenomena  are  derived.  The  absolute,  in 
Diihring's  phrase,  is  under  our  feet.  In  the 
more  modern  refinements  of  the  system  a  certain 
amount  of  sensibility  is  supposed  to  accompany 
each  material  particle  or  centre  of  force  ;  and  con- 
sciousness is  explained  as  resulting  from  the  joint 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  303 

action  of  innumerable  monads  ;  or,  by  a  still  nearer 
approach  to  idealism,  the  elementary  sensibilities 
are  conceived  as  the  only  true  realities,  what  we 
call  matter  being  a  mere  objectivation  of  feeling. 
In  any  case,  a  plurality  of  substances  is  the  primary 
fact  beyond  which  we  need  not  go. 

Pantheism  is  much  less  easy  to  define ;  and 
perhaps  no  definition  can  be  framed  wide  enough 
to  embrace  the  various  forms  under  which  it  has 
been  professed  throughout  history  and  all  over  the 
world.  For  our  present  purpose  only  the  most 
recent  aspects  need  be  taken  into  account ;  and  of 
these  it  is  enough  to  say  that,  starting  from  a 
supreme  animating  principle,  the  centre  and  soul 
of  things,  they  work  down  to  the  particular  modes 
of  existence,  explaining  the  parts  by  the  whole 
rather  than,  as  in  the  materialistic  method,  the 
whole  by  the  parts.  Those  who  wish  to  avoid 
what  they  consider  confusing  theological  associa- 
tions may  call  the  result  spiritualistic  monism. 
For  us  the  important  thing  to  note  is  the  attempt 
here  also  to  render  existence  into  intelligible  terms, 
to  make  thought  conterminous  with  things. 

Agnosticism  regards  both  attempts,  the  pluralistic 
and  the  monistic,  as  alike  chimerical.  It  applies 
the  Kantian  or  Hamiltonian  criticism  to  their  logic, 
and  finds  it  wanting.  Not  from  any  lack  of  moral 
courage,  but  from  sheer  intellectual  honesty,  does 
the  Agnostic  refuse  to  call  himself  an  Atheist  or  a 
Pantheist.  In  truth,  it  is  against  Atheism  and 
Pantheism,  rather  than  against  Theism,  that  the 
point  of  his  philosophy  is  turned.  As  has  been 
already  observed,  he  may  have  much  in  common 
with  the  Theist,  who  generally  shares  his  contempt 


304  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

for  dogmatic  metaphysics.  Of  course,  he  has  no 
mercy  on  a  priori  attempts  to  "  construct  "a  per- 
sonal God  ;  but  of  these  we  hear  less  and  less  every 
day.  It  is  true  that  the  a  posteriori  or  inductive 
argument,  which  leads  up  from  the  contemplation 
of  nature  to  the  recognition  of  divine  intelligence 
and  will  before  and  beyond  nature,  fails  to  convince 
him ;  but  his  objections  to  it  are  based,  as  I  have 
said,  on  scientific  grounds  in  the  widest  sense  of 
the  word  "scientific,"  using  it  so  as  to  include 
psychology  and  historical  criticism.  At  the  same 
time,  the  Spencerian  Agnostic  admits,  or  rather 
contends,  that  Theism,  and,  indeed,  all  forms  of 
ontology,  whether  monistic  or  pluralistic,  spiritual- 
istic or  materialistic,  contain  a  certain  measure  of 
truth.  He  agrees  with  them  in  admitting  that 
phenomena  are  not  everything — that  they  are  the 
index  to  an  absolute  reality  ;  but  Kant  has  taught 
him  that  this  reality  is  beyond  the  reach  of  our 
knowledge. 

If  the  foregoing  analysis  is  correct,  the  late 
Bishop  Fraser  was  not  justified  in  saying  that  "the 
Agnostic  neither  denied  nor  affirmed  God,"  but 
"simply  put  him  on  one  side."  If  the  Bishop 
meant  by  "  God  "  what  most  of  his  co-religionists 
mean, thenthe  Agnostic  certainlydenies  the  existence 
of  such  a  being,  if  only  because,  like  Darwin,  he 
"  does  not  believe  that  there  ever  was  a  revelation  "; 
and  the  Christian  God  is  essentially  self-revealing. 
If  by  "God"  is  meant  a  Power  whence  all  things 
proceed,  then  the  Agnostic  no  more  puts  him  on 
one  side  than  Spinoza  did.  Of  course,  it  was 
open  to  Bishop  Fraser  to  contend  that  Spinozism 
amounts  to  a  denial  of  God  ;  and,  if  words  are  to 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  305 

retain  their  ordinary  meanings,  I  am  by  no  means 
sure  that  he  would  not  have  been  right ;  but  such 
a  denial  differs  widely  from  the  lazily  contemptuous 
attitude  implied  by  the  Bishop's  phrase. 

After  all,  the  final  issue  will  centre  in  the  question 
of  personality.  Evidently  the  Agnostic,,  refusing 
to  predicate  anything  of  the  absolute  reality,  cannot 
positively  say  that  it  is  a  person  ;  but  can  he  posi- 
tively say  that  it  is  not  a  person  ?  It  seems  to  me 
that  he  is  logically  bound  to  go  that  far  ;  for  the 
notion  of  personality  seems  to  involve  the  notion 
of  a  subject  and  object,  related  to  and  conditioning 
one  another,  which  excludes  the  notion  of  an 
absolute.  Accordingly,  the  chiefs  of  the  Agnostic 
school,  if  I  am  rightly  informed,  take  refuge  in  the 
supposition  that  there  may  be  something  infinitely 
higher  than  personality,  and  free  from  its  limita- 
tions. But  I  must  confess  that  to  me  at  least  such 
an  hypothesis  conveys  no  meaning  whatever. 
Inconceivable  is  not  the  word  for  it.  The  category 
of  quantity  is  out  of  relation  to  personality.  We 
may  talk  about  being  "  intensely  self-conscious  " 
or  the  reverse  ;  but  that  is  said  only  in  reference 
to  our  concrete  individuality  as  apparent  to  others. 
Pure  self -consciousness  admits  of  no  degrees. 
When  Jean  Paul,  at  five  years  old,  thought  to 
himself  "Ic/i  bin  ein  Ic/i,"  he  had  won  that  to  the 
perfection  of  whose  reality  no  experience  or  imag- 
ination or  philosophy  could  add  any  more  than 
the  centre  of  a  circle  can  be  modified  by  enlarging 
its  circumference.  My  present  business,  however, 
is  not  criticism,  but  exposition  ;  and  to  that  I 
return. 

To  some  minds  what  a  philosopher  thinks  about 

x 


306  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

human    immortality   marks    his   attitude    towards 
religion  even  more  decisively  than  what  he  thinks 
about  the  existence  and  nature  of  God.     To  others, 
on  the  contrary,  it  is  a  mere  matter  of  curiosity, 
possessing   little   or   no   religious  value.     At  any 
rate,   religious   history  and   the   course   of  recent 
speculation   have   made    it  abundantly   clear   that 
there  is  no  necessary  association  between  the  belief 
in  a   personal  God  and  the  belief  in  a  future  life. 
An   eminent  religious  genius,  Leo  Tolstoy,  holds 
the   latter  doctrine   to  be   incompatible  with   true 
Christianity.      A    very   independent    thinker,   the 
late  Edmund  Gurney,  seems  to  have  rejected  God 
while  keeping  immortality  ;  and  there  are  probably 
many  who   more  or  less   openly   hold   the   same 
opinion.      Theoretically  at   least  there   seems   no 
reason  why  a  similar  latitude  should  not  prevail 
among  Agnostics.     I  should  say  that,  in  practice, 
nearly  all  who  call  themselves  by  that  name  hold 
that  consciousness  becomes  extinct  with  the  destruc- 
tion of  what  our  ordinary  experience  shows  to  be 
its   physiological   conditions ;    but  they  hold  this 
conviction  as  Rationalists  rather  than  as  Agnostics. 
An   Agnostic   will   no   doubt  subject  the   alleged 
phenomena  of  spiritualism  to  a  more  severe  scrutiny 
than  the  ordinary  religious  believer,  and,  even   if 
he  accepts  them  as  genuine,  will  be  more  cautious 
about  making  them  the  basis  for  wide  inferences ; 
but,  even  if  he  accepts  them  for  what  they  profess 
to  be,  they  must  always  remain  phenomena — that 
is,  products  of  a  reality  the  absolute  nature  of  which 
is  unknown  and  unknowable.     However  dazzling 
the  prospects  of  futurity  opened  out  to  him  may 
be,  there  is  one  assurance  from  which  he  remains 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  307 

debarred.  He  cannot  say,  like  a  confident  young 
friend  of  mine,  "  I  know  that  the  soul  is  immortal." 
Not  only  can  he  not  say  it  in  this  life,  but  in  no 
circumstances  conceivable  to  us  could  he  say  it. 
Supposing  his  individual  consciousness  to  be  pro- 
longed for  any  length  of  time,  the  fatal  antithesis 
of  subject  and  object  would  still  remain,  shutting 
him  out  from  a  real  knowledge  of  things  in  them- 
selves and  of  the  possibilities  of  a  catastrophe  that 
infinite  time  may  contain. 

I  have  said  that  the  quarrel  of  the  Agnostic  is 
rather  with  the  Pantheist  and  the  dogmatic  Atheist 
than  with  the  Christian  Theist,  whose  belief  he 
rejects  on  grounds  common  to  all  Rationalists. 
Still,  one  quite  understands  the  peculiar  animosity 
with  which  Agnosticism  is  regarded  by  orthodox 
champions,  for  it  occupies  a  very  much  stronger, 
because  less  assailable,  position  than  that  held  by 
their  ancient  opponents.  Theological  controver- 
sialists like  to  carry  the  war  into  the  enemy's 
country,  to  lay  him  prostrate  with  a  tu  quoque,  or 
to  explode  his  magazines  with  a  well-directed  sneer. 
The  Atheist  is  asked  whether  he  can  compose  an 
epic  poem  by  shaking  up  a  quantity  of  type  in  a 
box.  The  Pantheist  is  taunted  with  believing  that 
the  table  is  God,  or  that  he  himself  is  God.  The 
Agnostic  offers  no  such  handle  for  attack.  He 
has,  to  use  Huxley's  expression,  "  made  a  desert 
of  the  unknowable,"  so  that  it  will  not  support  an 
invading  army.  Asked  what  explanation,  then, 
he  gives  of  the  origin  of  things,  he  calmly  replies 
that  he  has  none — that  the  problem  is  insoluble. 
"  What !  have  you  not  a  theory  of  the  universe?" 
said  a  clerical  friend  in  mild  surprise  to  Professor 


3o8  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM? 

Tyndall.  "  I  have  not  even  a  theory  of  magnetism," 
was  the  answer  of  the  great  physicist.  It  must  add 
to  the  discomfiture  of  polemical  divines  if  they  bear 
in  mind  that  the  trick  was  taught  by  one  of  them- 
selves. It  is  almost  pathetic  to  re-read  those 
wonderful  Bampton  Lectures  of  Dean  Mansel, 
masterly,  brilliant,  and  overwhelming,  and  then  to 
remember  how,  only  two  years  after  their  delivery, 
his  positions  were  outflanked  by  Herbert  Spencer, 
his  batteries  seized,  and  his  artillery  turned  with 
destructive  effect  on  the  retreating  ranks  of 
orthodoxy. 

The  Agnostic,  however,  gives  away  this  immunity 
from  attack  when,  with  Spencer,  he  exchanges  a 
purely  critical  for  a  constructive  attitude.  It  then 
appears  that,  in  endeavouring  at  once  to  reconcile 
and  to  supersede  the  various  forms  of  theology,  he 
has  borrowed  a  principle  from  each,  with  the  result 
of  putting  together  a  somewhat  heterogeneous  and 
unstable  edifice.  The  idea  of  a  necessary  antithesis 
between  appearance  and  reality,  of  a  hidden  power 
which  at  once  produces  phenomena  and  radically 
differs  from  them,  comes  from  natural  Theism,  and 
repeats  the  dualism  that  has  always  been  its  reproach 
in  the  eyes  of  philosophy,  which,  in  Emerson's 
phrase,  is  essentially  centripetal ;  while  the  manner 
in  which  phenomena  are  spoken  of  as  manifesting 
the  power  behind  them  sounds  like  a  reminiscence 
of  Christian  revelation.  When  the  ultimate  reality 
figures  as  an  infinite  and  absolute,  or,  what  comes 
to  the  same  thing,  a  non-relative  existence,  a  sub- 
stance for  ever  extricating  itself  even  in  our  con- 
sciousness from  the  conditions  and  limitations  of 
thought,  the  debt  is  still  more  obvious  to  Pantheism, 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  309 

to  the  indestructible  tradition  of  Parmenides  and 
Spinoza.  When  the  unknowable,  of  which  assur- 
edly neither  unity  nor  plurality  should  be  predicated, 
is  habitually  spoken  of  as  one,  Theism  and  Pan- 
theism have  contributed  in  equal  proportions  to 
that  extreme  definiteness  of  statement.  Finally, 
when  in  the  theory  of  evolution  the  teleological 
method  is  altogether  superseded  by  mechanical 
causation,  we  have  a  procedure  running  parallel  to 
the  atheistic  materialism  from  which  Agnostics  are 
most  sincerely  anxious  to  dissociate  their  cause.1 

There  is,  then,  some  truth  in  the  dry  remark  of 
a  subtle  critic,  the  late  Father  Dalgairns,  that  it 
seems  we  know  a  good  deal  about  the  unknowable. 
At  any  rate,  what  may  be  called  the  positive  and 
dogmatic  Agnosticism  of  First  Principles  seems 
to  contain  germs  of  decomposition  inherited  from 
parent  systems  which  must  eventually  lead  to  its 
dissolution.  But  the  philosophy  of  knowledge  (or 
ignorance)  represented  by  Spencer  is  older  than  his 
system,  and  will  survive  it.  He  would  himself 
have  been  the  first  to  admit  that  differentiation 
must  go  on  ;  and  an  attempt  to  indicate  roughly 
the  divergent  lines  along  which  Agnostic  specula- 
tion will  move  in  the  immediate  future  may  not  be 
premature. 

First  of  all,  we  may  expect  that  the  conceptual 
proofs  of  an  infinite  and  absolute  existence  beyond 
consciousness  will  be  given  back  to  the  exclusive 


1  In  the  profoundly  interesting  chapter  on  "  The  Dynamic 
Element  in  Life,"  added  to  the  last  edition  of  his  Principles 
of  Biology,  Spencer  himself  insists  on  the  insufficiency  of 
mechanical  causation  as  applied  to  the  explanation  of  vital 
phenomena  ;  and  some  will  probably  interpret  this  as  a  conces- 
sion to  teleology.  Cf.  vol.  i.,pp.  573-574,  of  the  same  edition. 


310  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ? 

keeping  of  the  Pantheism  whence  they  were 
derived.  Agnostics  will  content  themselves  with 
insisting  that  the  phenomena  of  consciousness 
must  be  produced  by  causes  beyond  consciousness, 
and  therefore  unknowable  ;  but  they  will  drop  the 
somewhat  mystical  phrase  "  the  Unknowable,"  if 
only  to  avoid  the  appearance  of  assuming,  what 
seems  highly  improbable,  that  the  endless  varieties 
of  sensible  existence  proceed  from  a  single  self- 
identical  Power ;  and  they  will  abandon  the 
chimerical  idea  that  the  recognition  of  such  in- 
definite and  indefinable  forces  can  be  made  the 
basis  of  a  final  religion,  or  has  anything  to  do 
with  religion  at  all,  seeing  that  religion  is  nothing 
if  not  the  revelation  of  a  supersensual  world.  Such 
a  course  would  involve  no  new  departure;  it  would 
be  merely  a  return  to  the  principles  of  Auguste 
Comte,  of  Mill's  Logic,  and  of  Lewes's  History  of 
Philosophy. 

Others,  again,  may  plausibly  maintain  that  to 
postulate  causes  of  phenomena  which  certainly 
exist,  and  as  certainly  cannot  be  known,  is  a  some- 
what self-contradictory  proceeding,  savouring  of 
the  old  metaphysics,  and  that  a  true  Agnostic  will 
decline  to  commit  himself  one  way  or  the  other. 
He  will  observe  that  our  notion  of  causation, 
whether  derived  from  the  sense  of  muscular  effort 
or  from  the  observation  of  invariable  sequences 
among  phenomena,  is  essentially  subjective,  and 
cannot  legitimately  receive  a  transcendental  appli- 
cation. When  asked  how  phenomena  are  to  be 
explained  without  assuming  an  external  cause,  he 
will  answer  :  "  I  don't  know.  Perhaps  phenomena 
as  a  whole  are  uncaused,  or  self-caused,  or  caused 


WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM  ?  311 

by  something  in  the  future.  If  I  am  talking  non- 
sense, it  is  your  fault  in  asking  nonsensical  questions 
about  things  to  which  our  categories  do  not  apply. 
Keep  your  catechism  for  the  Sunday  school." 

Finally,  there  will  be,  or  rather  there  are  even 
now,  a  few  patient  and  temperate  inquirers  who, 
convinced  of  their  own  ignorance,  convinced  also 
that  in  no  school,  past  or  present,  is  the  enlighten- 
ment they  desiderate  to  be  found,  will  yet  refuse  to 
restrict  the  future  development  of  thought.  In  their 
opinion,  the  possibilities  of  knowledge  are  them- 
selves among  the  things  that  cannot  now  be  known. 
With  Taine,  they  see  the  limits  of  their  own  mind, 
but  not  the  limits  of  the  human  mind.  With 
Huxley,  they  do  "  not  much  care  to  speak  about 
anything  as  'unknowable."  Yet  none  better 
deserve  the  name  of  "Agnostics,"  if  Agnosticism 
implies  the  irrevocable  condemnation  of  what  has 
been  proved  false,  coupled  with  the  resolute  refusal 
to  set  up  a  still  more  fragile  image  in  its  place. 
Theirs  is  not  the  facile  philosophy  which,  shamed 
out  of  its  old  via-mediaism,  instead  of  saying  that 
truth  lies  between  the  two  extremes,  pronounces 
with  a  still  more  oracular  air  the  dictum  that  con- 
tradictories are  equally  true.  They  hold  that  to  be 
always  turning  back  is  the  worst  possible  way  to 
reach  the  goal,  and  that  rubbish-heaps  are  the 
weakest  possible  foundations  for  a  new  building. 

I  have  no  great  faith  in  abstract  definitions. 
Experience  shows  that  the  best  of  them  are  open 
to  exception,  and  that  they  have  hampered  pure 
speculation  with  the  difficulties  of  legal  draughts- 
manship, without  the  excuse  of  those  practical 
necessities  by  which  lawyers  are  hemmed  in.  But, 


3i2  WHAT  IS  AGNOSTICISM? 

for  the  comfort  and  relief  of  those  persons  who  read 
only  the  beginning  and  end  of  an  essay,  I  conclude 
with  a  summary,  as  short  and  as  exact  as  I  can 
make  it,  of  the  results  to  which  the  foregoing 
exposition  has  led. 

Agnosticism  is  the  philosophy  of  those  who  hold 
that  knowledge  is  acquired  only  by  reasoning  on 
the  facts  of  experience ;  that  among  these  facts 
supernatural  events  have  no  place ;  that  facts,  if 
any,  lying  beyond  experience  are  inconceivable  ; 
and  that  no  theory,  theological  or  otherwise,  pro- 
fessing to  give  an  account  of  such  facts  has  any 
legitimate  claim  on  our  belief. 


INDEX 


ABDUL  HAMID,  32 

Abelard,  Peter,  on  Gentile 
virtue,  2  sq. 

Abolitionism  derived  from  Greek 
thought,  22 

Achilles,  30 

Acts  of  the  Apostles,  147 

^Eschylus,  222,  quoted,  24,  258 

Agiatis,  wife  of  Agis  and 
Cleomenes,  75,  76 

Agis,  king  of  Sparta,  73  sg. 

Agnosticism  as  defined  by  Hux- 
ley, 282  ;  criticism  of  his  defi- 
nition, 282  sqq.;  taken  up  by 
Leslie  Stephen,  286 ;  distin- 
guished from  scepticism,  288; 
arguments  for,  289  syy.;  how 
related  to  theology,  293  sqq. ; 
not  a  necessary  alternative  to 
Christianity,  296  sq. ;  distin- 
guished from  atheism  and 
pantheism,  303517.;  future  of, 
3095^. ;  provisionally  defined, 
312 

Alcibiades,  260 

Alexander  the  Great,  31 

Amos,  21 ;  85  ;  89 ;  93  ;  96 ;  104  ; 
112 

An  Agnostic's  Apology,  286 

Anarchists,  compared  by  Renan 
with  the  Hebrew  prophets, 
89  sq. 

Anavim,  Renan  on  the,  96 

Anaxagoras,  47 

Anaximander,  46 

Anti-Christian,  Nietzsche's, 
266  sqq. 

Antigonus  Doson,  76 

Apollo  Belvedere,  the,  70 

Aratus,  71,  72,  76 

Argileonis,  72 

Argument  from  design,  298 

Aristeides,  24,  26 


Aristophanes,  50,  105 

Aristotle,  23;  29;  55  sq.;  105; 
condemns  usury,  114;  on  in- 
duction, 220 ;  250 

Arnold,  Matthew,  on  Hellenism 
and  Hebraism,  2 ;  on  the 
place  of  conduct  in  life,  14  ; 
his  reference  to  Phryne,  15; 
on  sweet  reasonableness,  23  ; 
38  ;  against  routine  methods, 
181 

Arnold,  Dr.  Thomas,  quoted,  33 

Athens,  direction  given  to  philo- 
sophy at,  229 

Augustine,  St.,  miracles  re- 
ported by,  143 

BACON,  FRANTCIS,  250 

Bacon,  Roger,  on  pagan  and 
Christian  morals,  3  sq. 

Bain,  Alexander,  his  theory  of 
voluntary  action,  180 

Balfour,  Mr.  Arthur,  129 

Barbarians  and  Hellenes,  eva- 
nescent character  of  the  dis- 
tinction between,  35 

Baur,  F.  C.,  145,302 

Beloch,  Prof.  Julius,  on  the 
slave  population  of  Attica, 
22  ;  on  the  growth  of  human- 
ity among  the  Greeks,  36 ;  on 
the  alleged  degeneracy  of 
the  Greeks,  57  ;  70,  note 

Bentham,  Jeremy,  28,  250 

Bradley,  Mr.  F.  H.,  quoted,  284 

Brasidas,  72 

Brown,  Dr.  Thomas,  210 

Browning's  Caliban  on  Setebos, 

165 

Brunschvicg,  M.  Leon,  his 
edition  of  Pascal's  Pensjes, 
152  ;  on  the  meaning  of 

s'ahetir,  158 


313 


3'4 


INDEX 


Brunette  Latini,  7 

Buckle,  H.  T.,  on  the  distinc- 
tion between  history  and  bio-  ; 
graphy,  177  ;  prefers  liberty 
to  knowledge,  181  sq. ;  carries 
business  traditions  into  philo- 
sophy, 182;  prejudiced  against 
State  interference,  183;  his  at- 
titude the  reverse  of  Comte's, 
183;  not  a  materialist,  184; 
accepts  the  basis  of  evolution, 
184,  but  regards  Nature  as  a 
hostile  power,  185  sq. ;  treats 
universal  history  as  a  collec- 
tion of  experiments,  186 ; 
biassed  by  patriotism,  187, 
and  by  the  love  of  simplifica- 
tion, 187 ;  depreciates  the 
moral  element  in  civilisation, 
187  sqq.  ;  on  poetry  and 
science,  190  ;  applies  econo- 
mic laws  to  history,  191  ;  but 
neglects  the  analogies  of 
Exchange,  192,  and  misses 
the  meaning  of  the  Renais- 
sance, 193  ;  on  the  decline  of 
the  English  intellect  in  the 
eighteenth  century,  193  sq. ; 
on  Spanish  civilisation,  195  ; 
on  the  protective  spirit,  196  ; 
sets  up  a  false  antithesis  be- 
tween the  people  and  their 
rulers,  197,  and  entertains 
confused  ideas  about  the 
nature  of  protection  in 
general,  198  say. ;  fallacy  of 
his  criticisms  on  Louis  XIV., 
200  sqq. ,  whose  personal  in- 
fluence he  exaggerates,  202  ; 
on  the  protective  spirit  in 
theology,  203$^.;  a  disciple  | 
of  Mill  rather  than  of  Comte, 
205  ;  misinterprets  the  nature 
of  induction  and  deduction, 
206,  208  sqq. ;  uncritical  adop- 
tion of  the  popular  metaphy- 
sics, 206  sqq. ;  confuses  psy- 
chology with  logic,  211  ;  on 
Hume  and  Adam  Smith,  212 
sqq. ;  on  the  philosophies  of 
England  and  France,  2\6sqq. ; 
on  the  accumulation  and  diffu- 


sion of  knowledge,  218  sqq. 
his    popularity   in    Germany, 
222,  233  ;  general  summary  of 
his  intellectual  character,  226 
sq.,  269 

Burckhardt,  Jacob,  on  the 
Greeks,  29 

Burns,  Robert,  secular  spirit  of 
his  poetry,  223  sq. 

Butler,  Bishop,  on  probability  as 
an  aid  to  faith,  167  sq. 

Byron,  justification  of  his  hos- 
tility to  the  Romanticists,  9  ; 
263 

CESAR  BORGIA,  259  sq. 

Caesar,  Julius,  260 

Caird,  Prof.  Ed.,  quoted,  72 

Callicratidas,  30 

Canning, George, a  philhellene,9 

Carlyle,  Thomas,  71  ;  to  some 
extent  an  advocate  of  liberty, 
181  ;  294,  quoted,  301 

Carneades,  50 

Cassels,  Walter,  148 

Charles,  II.,  conversion  of,  169 

Chatham,  263 

Cheyne,  Prof.  T.  K.,  on  the 
dial  of  Isaiah,  141 

Chremonidean  War,  70 

Christianity,  early,  and  social- 
ism, in 

Christology  of  the  Old  Testa- 
ment, 141 

Cleomenes,  King  of  Sparta,  75 
sq. 

Clifford,  Prof.  W.  K.,  294 

Clough,  A.  H.,  quoted,  107 

Coleridge,  S.  T.,  253;  301 

Comte,  Auguste,  how  he  dif- 
fered from  Buckle,  183 ;  Nietz- 
sche on,  245,  310 

Conscience  first  recognised  and 
named  by  the  Greeks,  25 

Conservation  of  energy  and 
theism,  299  sq. 

Conversions  to  Rome  under 
Charles  I.,  169 

Cornelia,  mother  of  the  Gracchi, 

79 

Cousin,  Victor,  quoted,   159  sq. ; 

302 


INDEX 


Cratesicleia,  75 
Curtius,  Ernst,  quoted,  61  sq. 
"  Cutting  a  covenant,"  114 
Cuvier,  130 

DALGAIRNS,  FATHER,  309 

Daniel,  Book  of,  quoted,  69, 
136  ;  prophecies  of,  145 

Dante  on  the  moral  superiority 
of  the  ancients,  4  ;  his  attitude 
towards  Brunette  Latini,  7 

Darmesteter,  Prof.  James,  on 
the  prophets  of  Israel,  20,  84 
sq. ;  overestimates  their  value 
for  modern  needs,  116 

Darwin,  Charles,  projects  the 
experimental  method  into 
nature,  180;  carries  economic 
law  into  zoology,  191  ;  his 
influence  on  German  thought, 

233 ;  255 ;  263 ;  298 

Davidson,  Samuel,  142 

Definition,  311 

Demetrius  Poliorcetes,  69 

Democracy,  socialistic  tenden- 
cies of,  64 

Demonicus  the  Cynic,  33 

Demophanes,  71 

Descartes,  167 ;  250 

Deuteronomy,  Renan  on,  90 ; 
compiled  under  prophetic 
influences,  108  ;  assumes  the 
justice  of  private  property, 
109 

D'Holbach,  Baron,  301 

Diderot,  52 

Diogenes  the  Cynic,  66 

Dion,  Plato's  disciple,  31  ;  60 
sqq. 

Dionysius  the  Younger,  62 

Droysen,  J.  G.,  his  Geschichte 
des  Hellenismus,  43;  90 

Diihring,  Eugen,  302 

ECCLESIASTES,  Book  of,   135 

Ecdemus,  71 
Egyptian  inhumanity,  32 
Ellicott,  Bishop,  128 
Emerson,  R.  W.,  294  ;  quoted, 

114,  328 

Empedocles,  46 
Endowment  of  research,  201 


English  scepticism  and  the 
deductive  method,  219 

English  thought  in  the  Early 
and  Middle  Victorian  periods 
characterised,  lyS-syy. 

Epameinondas,  30  sq. ;  60  ;  73 

Ephorus  the  historian,  63  sy. 

Epictetus,  27;  249 

Epicureans,  66 

Epicurus,  249 

Equality  of  the  sexes  at  Athens, 

32 

Equity  defined  by  Aristotle,  23 
Eratosthenes    the   geographer, 

35 

Erinyes,  the,  46 

Essenism,  influence  of,  on 
Christianity,  1 1 1 

Esther,  Book  of,  33 

Euripides  quoted,  20,  22  ;  reli- 
gious conflict  in  his  Hippo- 
fytits,  109 ;  222 

Evolutionism,  bearing  of,  on 
theism,  298 

Ewald,  H.,  142 

Ezekiel,  93  ;  96  ;  reference  to 
Daniel  in,  136,  note 

Ezra,  20 

FiCHTE,  J.  G.,  228,  230  sq. ;  290 
Forster- Nietzsche,       Madame, 

259 
Fourth     Gospel,     question    of, 

145  sqq. 
Fraser,  Bishop,  on  Agnosticism, 

304 
Freeman's   History  of   Federal 

Government,  43 
French      intellect,        deductive 

character  of,  217  sq. 
Friedlander,  L.,  quoted,  34 

GALLIC  invasion  of  Greece,  69 
Gardner,  Dr.  Percy,  288 
Gaume,  the  Abbe\  opposed  to 

classical  studies,  10 
George  Eliot,  234  sq. 
Germany,  decay  of  superstition 
in,    222    sq.;     has    not    con- 
tributed    much     to      ethical 
thought,      228 ;      paradoxical 
character  of  philosophy  in,  230 


3i6 


IN7DEX 


Gladiatorial  games,  Greek  pro- 
test against,  33 

Gladstone,  W.  E.,  129 

God  bound  to  keep  his  promises 
according  to  Pascal,  163 

Goethe,  301  ;  quoted,  149 

Gorgias  the  Sophist,  50,  54 

Gorgias,  the,  of  Plato,  271  sq. 

Gorge,  72 

Gracchi,  the,  77 

Greek  history  after  Alexander, 
a  neglected  study,  41  sqq. 

Greek  ideas,  stimulating  effect 
of,  on  conquered  nations,  44 

Green,  T.  H.,  quoted,  125 

Grote,  George,  291 

Crete's  History  of  Greece,  43  ; 
a  defence  of  liberty,  180  sq. 

Gurney,  Ed.,  306 

Gylippus,  30 

HAMILTON,  SIR  W.,  301,  302 
Hardy,  Mr. Thomas,  quoted,  151 
Harrison,  Mr.  Frederic,  286 
Harvey,  216 
Havet,  Ernest,  on  the  meaning 

of  Pascal's  wager,  158 
Hegel,  G.  W.  F.,  230;  233;  261 

sq. ;  294  sq.;  301  ;  quoted,  196 
Helen,  25  sq. 
Henry  of  Navarre's  reason  for 

abjuring  Protestantism,  169 
Heracleitus,  46  ;  54 
Herder,  301 
Herodotus,  22  ;  story  from,  24  ; 

222 

Hesiod,  103 
Hexateuch,  the,  as  an  index  to 

Jewish  ideals,  32 
Higher  Criticism,  the,  attitude 

of  theology  towards,  127  sqq. ; 

meaning  of,    134  ;  applicable 

to  all  ancient  literature,  134  ; 

practised   by  every  believer, 

134  ;    illustrations  of  its  use, 

l&sqq. 
Hippias  the  Sophist,  49  sq. ;  63, 

66;  quoted,  35 
Historical  method,  the,  267 
Hobbes,  216 ;  264 
Hodgson,       Mr.       Shadworth, 

quoted,  107 


Holm,    Adolf,     his    Griechische 

Geschichte,  43 
Homer,  270 
Hosea,  86  ;  his  denunciation  of 

Jehu,  94  sy. 

Humanity  of  the  Greeks,  30 
Humboldt,  Wilhelm  von,  253 
Hume  David,  210;  Buckle's 

account  of,   212  sg.  ;  his  atti- 

tude towards  theology,  224, 

230 
Hutcheson,    Francis,    indebted 

to    Shaftesbury   and    Butler, 

211 
Huth,  A.  H.,  his  Life  of  Buckle, 

178 
Hutton,  R.  H.,  51,  note  ;  against 

Mansel,  174;  on  Agnosticism, 

282 
Huxley,  Prof.    T.    H.,    on    the 

Greeks,  10  ;  on  natural  rights, 

28,  54  ;   creates   and  defines 

the  word  "agnosticism,"  281 

sqq.  ;    later   views,    284,    287, 

292  sq.,  295,  309,311 

IMMORTALITY,  306  sq. 

"  Infidelity  "  not  identical  with 
agnosticism,  294 

Intellectual  interdependence  of 
nations,  194  sy. 

Isaiah,  21,  93  ;  his  opposition  to 
Shebna  justified,  95,  96  ; 
soundness  of  his  political 
counsels,  118  sg.  ;  prophecies 
of,  and  the  higher  criticism, 

137 

Isocrates,2s;  26;  27;  31;  35;  59; 
on  the  meaning  of  Hellenism, 


JAMES  II.,  164 

Jeremiah  on  the  modern  drama 
and  novel,  84  sg.  ;  part  as- 
cribed to  him  by  Renan,  90 
£^.,93;  his  condemnation  of 
Jehoiakim  justified,  97  sg.; 
not  a  Jesuit,  106  sg.  ;  connec- 
tion of,  with  Deuteronomy, 
109  ;  did  not  attack  private 
property,  113  ;  on  the  sanctity 
of  contracts,  114;  a  patriotic 


INDEX 


citizen,  120;  advised  surren- 
der of  Jerusalem,  121  ;  his 
policy  not  explained  by 
modern  analogies,  122  sg.; 
develops  Isaiah's  idea  of  the 
Remnant,  123 

Jerusalem,  alleged  prediction  of 
its  fall,  144 

Jesus,  oldest  account  of,  147 

Jevons,  Prof.  Stanley,  on  the 
character  of  the  experimen- 
talist, 180;  quoted,  225 

Job,  Book  of,  88  ;    134  sq. 

John  of  Salisbury  on  the  morals 
of  the  twelfth  century,  3 

Journalists,  modern,  charac- 
terised, 94 

Jowett,  Benjamin,  154 

Juvalta,  Prof.,  254 

KANT,  IMMANUEL,  129,  228,  230, 

231,  302 
Keble,  John,  167 ;  on  the  method 

of  probability,  191  sqq. 

LACHELIER  on  Pascal's  wager, 

159 

Lady,  the,  or  the  tiger?  166 

Laplace,  129 

Lazarus,  raising  of,  144 

Leo  XIII.,  128 

Leibniz,  231 

Leonidas,  72 

Levitical  legislation  and  private 
property,  109  sq. 

Locke,  John,  250 

Louis  XIV. ;s  influence  exag- 
gerated by  Buckle,  202 

Luther,  opposes  Aristotle,  8 ; 
250 

Lycophron  the  Sophist,  63 

Lycurgus  the  legislator  a  myth, 

73 

Lydiades,  72 
Lyell,  Sir  Charles,  130 
Lysander,  58 
Lysis  the  Pythagorean,  60 

MACAULAY,  quoted,  33 ;  his 
History  of  England  a  defence 
of  liberty,  180  sq. 

Machiavelli,  260 


McTaggart,  Dr.,  151,  note 
Mahaffy,  Prof.,  his    Greek  Life 
and  Thought,  43  ;  quoted,  60 
Maistre,    Joseph     de,    quoted, 

54 

Mansel,  Dean,  denies  the  applic- 
ability of  our  moral  distinc- 
tions to  God,  173 ;  on  The 
Limits  of  Religious  Thought, 
287,  301,  302,  308 

Marcus  Aurelius,  36 

Mark,  St.,  Gospel  of,  147 

Martineau,  James,  against 
Mansel,  174  ;  294 

Maurice,  F.  D.,  quoted,  109, 
no  ;  against  Mansel,  174 

Mediaeval  writers  on  the  mor- 
ality of  their  own  times,  2  sqq. 

Meinong,  Prof.,  232 

Melian  Dialogue,  the,  271 

Melissus  of  Samos,  46 

Menander,  quoted,  65 

MeVe,  the  Chevalier  de,  160 

Michelet  on  Gargantua,  259 

Middleton's  Free  Inquiry,  270 

Mill,  James,  210 

Milton's  Lycidas,  quoted,  170 

Miracles  in  Daniel,  136  ;  in  the 
Hexateuch,  139;  many  stories 
of,  discredited  by  the  higher 
criticism,  139  sqq. 

Mitford  wrote  Greek  history  in 
an  anti-Jacobin  spirit,  10 

Monogamy  a  Greek  institution, 
26  sq. 

Montaigne,  162  ;  167 

Montesquieu,  250 

"  Moralin,"  230 

Morality  necessary  to  intellec- 
tual progress,  190 

Musset,  Alfred  de,  quoted,  54 

NAPOLEON,  254,  256 

Natural  selection  and  the  trans- 
mission of  acquired  qualities, 
130  sq. 

Nature,  idea  of,  48  sq. 

Neal's  History  of  the  Puritans, 
169 

Nebuchadrezzar,  99  ;  character 
of,  1 19 

Nebular  hypothesis,  129 


INDEX 


New  English  Dictionary,  quoted, 
282 

Newman,  Cardinal,  167  ;  adopts 
Butler's  doctrine  of  probabi- 
lity, 191 

Newman,  F.  W.,  294 ;  his 
Phases  of  Faith,  297 

Newton,  Isaac,  216;  263 

Nicias,  47 

Nietzsche,  Friedrich,  an  ethical 
g-enius,  229 ;  parentage  and 
education,  234 ;  theory  of 
tragedy,  236  ;  friendship  with 
Wagner,  236 ;  never  a  pessi- 
mist, 239;  military  experience, 
240  ;  on  Socrates,  240  ;  breach 
with  Wagner,  241  ;  openly 
anti-religious  attitude  of,  242  ; 
distrust  of  genius  and  grow- 
ing preference  for  pure  know- 
ledge, 242  sq. ;  anti-German 
feeling,  244  ;  enthusiasm  for 
England,  244  sq. ;  in  praise  of 
Auguste  Comte,  245 ;  philo- 
sophical volte-face,  246 ;  at- 
tacks morality  under  cover  of 
moral  motives,  246  sqq. ;  ad- 
vocates utility  without  altru- 
ism, 249;  a  hedonist,  251  sq.; 
proposes  individuality  as  an 
end  of  action,  253 ;  against 
socialism,  254 ;  on  Napoleon, 
254 ;  interested  in  evolution, 
255  ;  doctrine  of  the  super- 
man, 255  sqq. ;  hostile  to  the 
modern  State,  259  ;  self-con- 
tradiction involved  in  his 
ideals,  260  sq. ;  confuses  Dar- 
winian with  Hegelian  evolu- 
tion, 261  sq. ;  inveighs  against 
English  writers,  263  ;  substi- 
tutes power  for  pleasure  as 
an  end  of  action,  264;  borrows 
the  gospel  of  health  from 
Herbert  Spencer,  265 ;  new 
view  of  the  superman,  266 ; 
the  Anti-Christian,  266  sqq.; 
inconsistency  of  his  attacks 
on  morality  and  Christianity, 
272  sq. ;  plans  an  ideal  State, 
276 sqq.;  on  the  illusoriness  of 
personality,  279  sq. ;  his  rela- 


tion to  Agnosticism,  283  ;  301 

Novelists,  modern  English,  on 

the  morality  of  the  ancients,  i 

OLIPHANT,  LAURENCE,  quoted, 
287  sq. 

PARKER,  THEODORE,  294 

Parmenides,  54  ;  309 

Pascal,  Blaise,  an  apologist  of 
Christianity,  152  ;  meaning 
of  his  wager,  153  ;  logically 
an  agnostic,  153 ;  looseness 
of  his  notions  about  betting, 
!55 »  a  gentleman,  160;  a 
moral  sceptic,  162  ;  on  the 
morality  of  God,  163,  164  sq. 

Pater,  Walter,  on  Pascal,  160 

Paul,  St.,  25;  Hellenistic  char- 
acter of  his  teaching,  38  ;  not 
a  socialist,  1 1 1  ;  does  not 
refer  to  the  Virgin-birth,  144  ; 
on  the  gift  of  tongues,  147  ; 
269 

Pergamene  reliefs,  70 

Pericles,  24  ;  47 

Personality,  305 

Philip  of  Macedon,  31  ;  69 

Philosophy,  humanising  ten- 
dency of,  58 

Phocion,  58 

Phocylides  on  justice,  26 

Phoenicians,  inhumanity  of,  32 

Plato,  26,  27  ;  31,  32  ;  46;  his 
Protagoras,  49;  55  sq.,  62,  63, 
65,  66  ;  on  communism,  105  ; 
143  ;  on  the  reasoning  powers 
of  mathematicians,  154;  refer- 
ence to  his  Parmenides,  154  ; 
268  ;  277,  278,  279  ;  influenced 
by  Athenian  religion,  229 ; 
quoted,  25,  50,  51 

Plotinus,  28 

Plutarch,  35  ;  47  ;  48  ;  75 

Pohlmann,  R.,  quoted,  64 

Popular  intelligence  and  free- 
thought,  219 

Porphyry's  criticism  on  Daniel, 
136 

Positivists,  English,  advocate 
the  liberation  of  the  spiritual 
power,  181 


INDEX 


Pragmatism,  Nietzsche  on,  274 

Priestly  code,  20 

Prodicus  the  Sophist,  28;  50  sq. ; 
66 

Prophets,  Hebrew,  20  ;  Renan's 
treatment  of,  83  sqq. ;  modern 
misinterpretations  of,  90  ;  did 
not  interfere  with  private 
property,  113;  were  good 
patriots,  118  sqq. ;  general 
character  of,  125 

Protagoras,  50 ;  52  sqq. 

Protective  spirit  revived  in 
modern  England,  196  sq. 

Ptolemy  Keraunos,  69 

Pyat,  Fe"lix,  120 

Pyrrhus,  70 

Pythagorean  school,  46 

RATIONALISM  confounded  with 
agnosticism  by  Huxley,  285 

Ravachol,  91 

Religion  of  Humanity,  danger 
of,  47 

Reuss,  Ed.,  142 

Renan,  Ernest,  20  ;  merits  and 
defects     of    his     History    of 
Israel,  80  sqq. ;   on  St.    Paul, 
85 ;     derives   Socialism   from 
the  Hebrew  prophets,  Sgsqq.; 
unjust   to    the    Greeks,    105  ; 
misrepresents  Jeremiah,  105  ; 
sympathises   with     socialism, 
112    sg. ;        defends      certain 
abuses,  116  ;  on  later  Judaean 
politics,   1 18  sqq.;  disparages 
post-exilian     Hebre%v    litera-  j 
ture,     124;      a     conservative  I 
critic,    148  ;    his  influence  on  j 
German  thought,  233 

Rochefort,  Henri,  91 

Romanes,  G.  J.,  129  ;  301,  note 

Romans,    the,    inhumanity    of, 

33 

Rousseau,  J.  J.,  52  ;  63  ;  72 
Ruskin,   John,    advocates   indi- 
vidual initiative,  185,  265 

SALMON,    Dr.,      128;     on     the 

higher  criticism,  143 
Scepticism    distinguished   from 

agnosticism,  288 


Schelling,  231  ;  262  ;  301 

Schoolmen,  their  knowledge  of 
classical  literature,  5 

Schopenhauer,  228  ;  231;  Nietz- 
sche's first  master,  232  sq. ; 
239  ;  245,  246  ;  263  ;  279 

Science,  physical,  in  relation  to 
the  supernatural,  132 

Scotland,  progress  of  enlighten- 
ment in,  223  sq. 

Scott,  Sir  Walter,  223  sq. 

Scythians,  the,  Greek  idealisa- 
tion of,  63 

Sebon,  Raymond,  167 

Seneca,  36 

Shakespeare,  263 

Shorthouse,  J.  H.,  quoted,  i 

Slavery,  Athenian,  did  not  ex- 
clude free  labour,  22 

Smith,  Adam,  210 ;  Buckle's 
account  of,  213  sqq. ;  his 
Theory  of  Moral  Sentiments, 

214  sq. ;     Wealth   of  Nations, 

215  sq. 

Smith,  Prof.  Goldwin,  against 
Mansel,  174 

Smith,  Prof.  Robertson,  quoted, 
80 

Socialism,  pedigree  of,  78 ;  a 
Greek  creation,  100 

Socrates,  55  sq.;  143;  239;  268; 
278 

Solon,  64  ;  ordinances  of,  104 

Sophists,  the,  55  ;  268 

Sophocles,  24 

Sparta,  later  history  of,  72  sqq. 

Spencer,  Herbert,  an  anti- 
Socialist,  112;  his  contro- 
versy with  Weismann,  1 30  sq. ; 
form  of  Agnosticism  professed 
b}'»  153;  a  philosopher  of 
freedom  and  individuality, 
179;  his  philosophy  a  general- 
isation of  the  current  political 
situation,  191  ;  his  protest 
against  State  -  interference, 
1975  253.  254.  255;  263; 
acknowledged  chief  of  the 
Agnostic  school,  283;  287;  293  ; 

3°9 

Sphaerus,  75 
Spinoza,  269  ;  304  ;  308 


320 


INDEX 


Stephen,  Sir  Leslie,  his  account  I 

of  Agnosticism,  286 
Stillman,  W.  J.,  quoted,  29 
Stoics  and  Stoicism,  66  sq.,  70     ' 
Strauss,  D.  F.,  148;  233;  302 
Sully-Prudhomme     on     Pascal,  j 
157 ;  on  the  meaning  of  the 
wager,  158  sq. 

Supernatural  predictions  dis- 
credited by  the  higher  criti- 
cism, 141 

TAINE,  H.,  quoted,  311 
Taxation   as  an    instrument  of 

oppression,  86 
Telemachus,  the  Greek   monk, 

and  the   gladiatorial  games, 

34 
Thales  as  a  practical  politician, 

45  sq. 

Theognis,  269  sq. 
Thirlwall's  History  of  Greece,  43 
Thucydides,  49  ;  53  ;   143  ;  271 
Timoleon,  61 
Tolstoy,  Leo,  306 
Tyndall,  Prof.  John,  191;  308 

VERACITY  of  God  only  guaran- 
teed by  his  moral  perfection, 
167 

WACE,  DEAN,  129 


Wagner,  Richard,  241;  255;  263 

Walpole,  Horace,  predicts  the 
Catholic  revival,  170 

Ward,  W.  G.,  opposed  to 
classical  studies,  10 

Wealth  not  necessarily  asso- 
ciated with  wickedness  in  the 
Hebrew  Scriptures,  88 

Weismann,  Prof.  Aug.,  his  con- 
troversy with  Spencer,  130  sq. 

Welcker,  270 

Wilamowitz,   237 

Wilberforce,  William,  identifies 
Bonaparte  with  the  little  horn 
in  Daniel,  91 

Wille  zur  Macht,  Nietzsche's, 
quoted,  274  sqq. 

Wordsworth,  William,  265  ;  301 

XENOPHON,  52,  222  ;  his  Memo- 
rabilia, 143 

Zarathustra,  Nietzsche's,  256, 
257,  quoted,  264,  266,  273 

Zedekiah's  faithlessness  de- 
nounced by  Jeremiah,  99 

Zeller,  Ed.,  on  the  history  of 
Greek  philosophy,  40 ;  on 
Essene  communism,  lit 

Zeno  of  Elea,  46 

Zeno  the  Stoic,  25  ;  67,  68,  69 ;  71 


FRINTEP  BY   WATTS   A.ND  CO.,    17.  JOHNSON'S  COt'RT,  Ft.'  2T  rTREST,  LONDON',  E.C 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 

Los  Angeles 
This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below. 


n  L9-50m-9,>60(B8610s4)444 


Ill  III    III    Illl  II"'  "'"  ""'  "'  

A  A      000009230    4 


B 
29