Skip to main content

Full text of "The science of ethics"

See other formats


This  book  is  DUE  on  the  last  date  stamped  below 


Oct  kn 
ore  0 


0 

1011 


m^ 


;.Ar  i  4  1931 


1^30 


WAR  1  9  1935 

\ 


m 


^  •'  1^^?^ 


SEP  13  19§f< 


E-ir 


JAN  1  2  196C 


THE    SCIENCE    OF    ETHICS. 


BALLANTYNE,    HANSON    AND   CO. 
EDINBURGH    AND    LONDO.V 


^   ?  Y 


THE 


SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS, 


BY 


LESLIE   STEPHEN. 


jjj  j^  JJ5  J. 


J  > 


» ,• 


M        *        ^  >     'i      t  •» 


J    '   > 

3         3 


NEW  YORK: 

G.  P.  PUTNAM'S  SONS, 

27  &  29  WEST  TWENTY-THIRD  STREET. 

1882. 
^5^        . 


t     t      (  c  c 


3J" 
looi 


PREFACE. 


A  PREFACE  is  generally  the  most  interesting,  and  not  seldom 
the  only  interesting,  part  of  a  book.  It  is  useful  to  the  hasty 
critic  who  wishes  to  avoid  the  trouble  of  reading  at  all,  and 
to  the  more  serious  student  who  wishes  to  have  the  clue  to 
the  author's  speculations  put  into  his  hands  at  the  earliest 
possible  period.  I  should  be  glad  to  be  useful  to  both  classes, 
to  save  some  readers  the  trouble  of  getting  through  more 
than  a  couple  of  paragraphs,  and  to  point  out  to  others  what 
is  the  kind  of  result  which  they  may  expect  from  a  perusal  of 
the  whole  work. 

My  ethical  theory,  then,  when  I  first  became  the  conscious 
proprietor  of  any  theory  at  all,  was  that  of  the  orthodox 
utilitarians.  J.  S.  Mill  was  the  Gamaliel  at  whose  feet  I 
sat,  and  whose  authority  was  decisive  with  me  on  this  as 
on  other  matters.  In  this,  of  course,  I  was  simply  following 
the  example  of  the  majority  of  the  more  thoughtful  lads  of 
my  own  generation.  At  a  later  period  my  mind  was  stirred 
by  the  great  impulse  conveyed  through  Mr.  Darwin's  Origin 
of  Species.  I  shall  always,  I  hope,  be  proud  to  acknowledge 
the  great  intellectual  debt  which  I,  in  common  with  so  many 


vi  PREFACE. 

worthier  disciples^  owe  to  his  writings,^  So  far  as  ethical 
problems  were  concerned^  I  at  first  regarded  Mr.  Darwin's 
principles  rather  as  providing  a  new  armoury  wherewith  to 
encounter  certain  plausible  objections  of  the  so-called  In- 
trusionists^  than  as  implying  any  reconstruction  of  the  utili- 
tarian doctrine  itself.  Gradually^  however,  I  came  to  think 
that  a  deeper  change  would  be  necessary,  and  I  believe  that 
this  conviction  came  to  me  from  a  study  of  some  of  Mr. 
Herbert  Spencer's  works.  It  became  stronger  during  a 
subsequent  attempt  at  a  brief  historical  examination  of  the 
English  moralists  of  the  eighteenth  century.  Whilst  I  was 
finishing  that  task,  I  read  Mr.  Henry  Sidgwick's  Methods  of' 
Ethics,  then  just  published.  As  I  differ  upon  many  points 
from  Mr.  Sidgwick,  and  especially  upon  the  critical  point  of 
the  relation  of  evolution  to  ethics,  I  am  the  more  bound  to 
express  my  sincere  admiration  for  his  book.  It  set  me  think- 
ing when  it  failed  to  make  me  think  with  him.  The  result 
of  my  thinking  was  a  resolution  to  set  down  as  systematically 
as  I  could  a  statement  of  the  ethical  theory  which  had  com- 
mended  itself  to  me.  I  resolved  to  begin  at  the  beginning 
as  well  as  I  could,  and  trudge  steadily  through  the  alternate 
platitudes  and  subtleties  into  which  every  moralist  must 
plunge.  My  views  were,  of  course,  more  or  less  modified 
in  the  process,  and  though  they  have  not  substantially 
changed,  I  hope  that  they  have  gained  in  consistency  and 
clearness.     At  any  rate,  my  labours  are  embodied   in  the 


^  It  is  with  a  pang  of  deep  regret  that  I  must  add  to-day  (April  24th,  1882) 
that  I  can  no  longer  cherish  the  hope  of  fully  acknowledging  it  to  Mr.  Darwin 
himself.  I  was  withheld  from  speaking  formerly  by  the  feeling  that  anything 
like  a  compliment  (sincere  though  it  might  be)'seemed  incongruous  in  presence 
of  that  exquisitely  simple  and  modest  nature.  Yet  I  could  wish  that  I  had 
been  less  diffident. 


PREFACE.  vii 

following  pages,  which  may  be  briefly  described  as  an 
attempt  to  lay  down  an  ethical  doctrine  in  harmony  with 
the  doctrine  of  evolution  so  widely  accepted  by  modern  men 
of  science. 

To  this  statement  it  would  be  desirable  to  add  an  acknow- 
ledgment of  my  debt  to  other  writers.     I  find  it  impossible 
to  do  so_,  for  the  simple  reason  that  I  am  altogether  ignorant 
of  the  extent  of  my  obligations.     It  has  happened  to  me,  as, 
I  presume,  to  almost  all  writers  upon  such  topics,  to  discover 
that  arguments  which  had  apparently  sprung  up  spontaneously 
in  my  own  mind  had  really  been  expressly  stated   by  my 
predecessors,  and,  moreover,  stated  in  books  with  which  I 
had  been  familiar;    and  were,  therefore,  in  all  probability, 
intellectual  waifs  and  strays  upon  which  I  had  unconsciously 
laid  hands.     In  less  direct  ways,  I  have,  of  course,  been  influ- 
enced to  a  degree  which  I  am  quite  unable  to  estimate.     I 
have  no  fear  that  my  obligations  to  writers  belonging  to 
what  I  may  call  my  own  school,  to  Hume,  Bentham,  the 
Mills,  G.  H.  Lewes,  and  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer,  will  be  over- 
looked or  underrated  ;  and  I  would  gladly  name  others  to 
whom  I  am  more  opposed,  were  it  not  that  in  many  cases 
an  acknowledgment    would    look   like   a   claim   to  affiliate 
my  speculations  upon  men  who  would  regard  the  claim  as 
offensive.     I  can,  however,  obviate  any  objection  which  may 
be  made  to  want  of  fuller  acknowledgment  by  the  explicit 
and  perfectly  sincere  admission  that  I  do  not  believe  (though 
ajrain  I  cannot  be  certain  even  of  this  negative  statement) 
that  there  is  a  sin2;le    ori2:inal    thou2;ht  in  the  book  from 
beginning  to  end.     By  original,  I  mean  of  course  a  thought 
which  has  not  occurred  to  others;  though  I,  of  course,  also 
claim  to  have  made  every  thought  which  I  utter  my  own 
by  reflection  and  assimilation. 


viii  PREFA  CE. 

I  am  the  more  bound  to  make  this  statement  because  I 
have  made  it  a  rule  never  to  mention  proper  names.  I  have 
done  so  partly  because  I  think  that  any  book  which  aims 
at  scientific  method  should  contain  within  itself  all  that 
is  necessary  to  the  immediate  issues^  and  should  avoid  the 
appearance  of  anything  like  an  appeal  to  authority ;  and 
still  more  because  I  have  observed  that,  as  a  matter  of  fact, 
any  such  references  are  apt  to  introduce  digressions,  and  to 
lead  one  aside  into  disputes  as  to  the  rightful  interpretation 
or  correct  affiliation  of  the  principles  of  other  writers,  which, 
however  interesting,  really  involve  irrelevant  issues. 

Another  question  may  be  suggested  by  this  avowal.  Why 
publish  a  fresh  discussion  of  so  ancient  a  topic  if  you  have 
nothing  new  to  say?  The  general  answer  is  simple  enough, 
namely,  that  problems  of  this  kind  require  to  be  dis- 
cussed in  every  generation  with  a  change  of  dialect,  if  not 
with  a  corresponding  change  of  the  first  principles ;  and, 
further,  that  it  is  desirable  that  all  points  of  view  should  be 
represented.  This  last  remark  may  suggest  some  answer  to 
the  more  special  question,  whether  my  book  has  not  been 
made  superfluous  by  the  discussion  of  the  same  topic  upon 
the  same  assumptions  by  the  leading  exponent  of  the 
philosophy  of  evolution  in  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer's  Data  of 
Ethics.  To  this  I  reply  that  I  differ  from  Mr,  Herbert  Spencer 
in  various  ways ;  and  moreover,  that  we  really  stand  at 
different  points  of  view.  Mr.  Spencer  has  worked  out  an 
encyclopaedic  system,  of  which  his  ethical  system  is  the 
crown  and  completion.  T,  on  the  contrary,  have  started 
from  the  old  ethical  theories,  and  am  trying  to  bring  them 
into  harmony  with  the  scientific  principles  which  I  take  for 
granted.  My  aim  is  more  limited,  though  we  ought  to 
coincide  in  results  so  far  as  we  cover  the  same  ground.     I 


PREFACE.  ix 

have^  as  it  were,  surveyed  the  province  from  within,  without 
attempting  to  pass  the  frontiers,  whilst  he  reaches  the  pro- 
vince after  surveying  the  whole  empire  of  scientific  thought ; 
and  therefore  I  have  laid  stress  upon  some  matters  which 
he  treats  with  comparative  lightness,  whilst  in  other  cases 
the  relation  is  reversed. 

In  fact,  however,  I  hold  that  there  is  ample  room  for  any 
number  of  labourers  in  this  field ;  nay,  that  there  will  be 
room  for  the  labourers  of  many  generations  to  come.  I 
have  no  doubt  that  ethical  problems  will  be  debated  long 
after  I  (it  would  be  impertinent  to  consider  the  case  of  Mr. 
Spencer)  am  dead  and  forgotten.  It  is  enough  and  more 
than  enough  if  one  can  communicate  the  very  slightest 
impetus  to  the  slowly  grinding  wheels  of  speculation.  At 
times,  I  have  been  startled  at  my  own  impudence  when 
virtually  sitting  in  judgment  upon  all  the  deepest  and  acutest 
thinkers  since  the  days  of  Plato.  But  I  easily  comfort  myself 
by  remembering  that  the  evolution  of  thought  is  furthered 
by  the  efforts  of  the  weak  as  well  as  of  the  strongest ;  and 
that  if  giants  have  laid  the  foundations,  even  dwarfs  may 
add  something  to  the  superstructure  of  the  great  edifice  of 
science.  So  far  as  my  reading  has  gone,  I  have  found  only 
two  kinds  of  speculation  which  are  absolutely  useless — that 
of  the  hopelessly  stupid,  and  that  of  the  hopelessly  insincere. 
The  fool  who  does  not  know  his  own  folly  may  be  doing 
nothing,  and  the  philosopher  who  is  trying  to  darken  know- 
ledge may  be  doing  worse  than  nothing ;  but  every  sincere 
attempt  to  grapple  with  real  difficulties  made  by  a  man  not 
utterly  incompetent  has  its  value.  I  claim  to  come  within 
that  description,  though  I  claim  nothing  more.  And  I  have 
the  satisfaction — not  a  very  edifying  one,  it  may  be  said,  for 
a  professed   moralist — to  reflect  that  if  my  book   does  no 


X  PREFACE. 

good  to  anybody  else^  it  has  provided  me  with  an  innocent 
occupation  for  a  longer  time  than  I  quite  Hke  to  remember; 
whilst  I  hope  that  there  is  nothing  in  it — if  I  may  apply 
to  myself  what  a  discerning  critic  has  said  of  Dr.  Watts' 
sermons  — "  calculated  to  call  a  blush  to  the  check  of 
modestv." 

LESLIE  STEPHEN. 

London,  April  18S2. 


CONTENTS. 


CHAPTER  I. 

Purpose  and  Limits  of  the  Inquiry. 

I.    The  Starting-Poijit. 


PAGE 


1.  Nature  of  ethical  controversy  .....  i 

2.  Conciliation  requires  a  right  method       ....  2 

3.  And  a  postponement  of  metaphysical  problems         .  .  3 

4.  Metaphysical  doubts  are  irrelevant  in  the  sphere  of  science  4 

5.  Including  the  moral  sciences  .....  5 

6.  Truths  in  moral  science  independent  of  metaphysics  .  6 

7.  The  sphere  of  science  ......  7 


II.   Difficulty  of  Moral  Science. 

8.  The  free-will  difficulty  irrelevant     .....  9 

9,  Moral    science,    though    not    self-contradictory,    may    be 

unattainable    .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .10 

10.  Imperfecti6irx)f  science  generally  .  .  .  .  .11 

11.  Hopeless  complexity  of  the  problem  of  individual  conduct         12 

12.  Even  average  conduct  too  complex  for  calculation    .  .        13 

13.  Absence  of  a  scientific  psychology  .  .  .  .14 

14.  Special  difficulties  from  varying  character  and  motive       .        15 

15.  Intermittent  action  of  consciousness        ....        16 

16.  Sociology  as  vague  as  psychology  .  .  ,  .  .17 

17.  Narrow  limits  of  moral  sciences     ...  .         .        20 

III.  A  ttainable  Results. 

18.  Empirical  knowledge  of  conduct    .  .  .  .  .21 

19.  Its  relation  to  scientific  knowledge  ....        22 

20.  Difficulty  of  obtaining  definitive  rules      ....        23 


xii  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

21.  Statistical  method  insufficient         .....        24 

22.  Method  of  political  economy  insufficient  ...        26 

23.  Appearance  of  fatalism  due  to  false  assumptions      .  .        28 

24.  The  permanent  social  structure      .  .  .         .         .30 


IV.    Theory  of  Social  Evohction. 

25.  Importance  of  study  of  social  structure  .  .  .  .        31 

26.  New  significance  of  phenomena  when  regarded  as  indi- 

cative of  organic  growth    .  .  .  ...        32 

27.  The  true  statement  of  the  problem  of  sociology        .  .        t^t^ 


V.    The  Ethical  Problem. 

28.  Our  problem  is  to  discover  the  scientific  form  of  morality  35 

29.  Distinction  between  actual  and  ideal  morality  .  .  36 

30.  Actual  morality  here  concerned      .....  39 


CHAPTER  II. 

The  Theory  of  Motives. 

I.    The  Problem. 

1.  An  examination  of  first  principles  necessary    ...        40 

2.  Excluding,  however,  the  metaphysical  principles       .  .        40 

II.    77^1?  Emotions  as  Deiermining  Conduct. 

3.  Happiness  determines  conduct  in  a  scientific  sense            .  42 

4.  Some  common  objections  are  irrelevant            ...  42 

5.  The  formula,  though  vague,  is  not  meaningless         .          .  43 

6.  It    excludes    an     erroneous    theory,    but    requires    more 

precision  ........  44 

7.  Theory  of  happiness  as  the  sole  end  of  conduct        .  .  46 

8.  Supposes  a  strictly  inconceivable  process         ...  47 

9.  And  in  many  important  cases  gives  an  erroneous  formula 

— Objective  and  subjective  ends         ....        47 

10.  Misrepresents  the  inseparable  connection  of  emotion  and 

reason    .........        49 

11.  Pain  and  pleasure  as  ultimate  determinants  of  conduct     .        50 

12.  In  all  cases  pleasure  corresponds  to  stable  and  pain  to 

unstable  equilibrium  .         .  .  .         .  .51 


CONTENTS.  xiii 

Page 

13.  Analogy  of  least  resistance    ,  .  .  .  .  .52 

14.  Nature  of  an  act  of  choice     ......  53 

15.  Difficulty  of  discovering  the  sphere  of  volition  .         .  54 

16.  And  of  knowing  our  own  desires    .....  56 

17.  True  statement  of  the  greatest-happiness  formula — The 

■   province  of  reason    .  .  .  .  ,  .  .56 


III.   T/ie  Reason  as  Determining  Conduct. 

18.  All  conduct  "  reasonable  "  so  far  as  giving  an  assignable 

law 58 

19.  Senses  in  which  conduct  may  be  more  or  Iq^s  reasonable  59 

20.  Reason  not  opposed  to  feeling  as  such    ....  60 

21.  Sense  in  which  it  may  dispense  with  feeling    ...  61 

22.  Latent  feeling       .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .61 

23.  Feeling  by  signs  ........  62 

24.  Reason  and  feeling  are  mutually  involved,  and  naturally 

develop  together       .  .  .  .  ,  .  .63 

25.  But  may  be  considered  separately — Reason  as  implying 

accuracy  of  judgment        ......  64 

26.  And     consistency    of    motive     insufficient    to    determine 

conduct 65 

27.  Frohlem  o{  the  su7nmie?n  ionum     .  .  .  .  .67 

28.  Given  a  single  end  of  conduct,  the  problem  is  definite      .  67 

29.  But  men  have  in  fact  many  partially  inconsistent  ends      ,  68 

30.  The  unity  of  the  agent  implies  di:  facto  commensurability 

of  ends    .........  69 

31.  Reasonableness  thus  implies  harmony  and  consistency  of 

conduct  .........  70 

32.  But  as  character  varies,  the  end  is  still  indeterminate       .  71 
2)1.    So  far,  therefore,  no  sole  end  follows  from  reasonableness  73 


\Y.    Types. 

34.  IMeaning  of  "  type"  illustrated       .... 

35.  A  typical  instrument  implies  the  solution  of  a  problem 

36.  And  a  maximum  efficiency  of  given  means  to  a  given  end 

37.  Esthetic  value  of  types  .... 

38.  The  same  principles  apply  to  a  living  organism 

39.  What  corresponds  in  this  case  to  the  "end"  , 

40.  The  evolutionist  theory  suggests  an  answer 

41.  The  evolution  of  vitally  efficient  types     . 

42.  Extreme  intricacy  of  any  accurate  statement  . 


74 
11 
IS 
76 
76 
78 
7S 
80 
80 


xiv  CONTE^WTS. 


V.    T/ie  Principle  of  Utility. 


PAGE 


43.  Conduct  may  be  useful  as  "  pleasure-giving  "  as  to  "  life- 

preserving  :"  the  two  must  tend  to  coincide        .          .  82 

44.  Habits  and  instincts  may  be  considered  in  either  aspect  .  83 

45.  Necessity  of  distinguishing  between  organisms  and  aggre- 

gates      .........  84 

46.  Utility    must    be    understood    with    reference    to    whole 

organism  ,  .  .  .  .  .  .  .85 

47.  Ultimate  theory  of  pain  and  pleasure  irrelevant        .          .  86 

48.  They  must  be  functions  of  working  condition  of  organism  86 

49.  Correlation  of   painful   and   pernicious,  pleasurable    and 

beneficial          ........  88 

50.  Presumption  in  favour  of  more  essential  instincts     .          .  89 

VI.   Social  and  Individual  Utility. 

51.  Instincts  essential  to  the  race  may  be  prejudicial  to  the 

individual         ...  .....        90 

52.  Hence  necessity  of  considering  relation  of  race  to  indi- 

vidual    .........        92 


CHAPTER  III. 

Theory  of  Social  Motives. 

I,    The  Individual  and  the  Race, 

1.  Importance  of  the  distinction         .  .         .  .  •        93   '^ 

2.  Properties  of  the  organic  whole  not  inferable  from  pro- 

perties of  constituent  units         .  .  .  .  •        93       . 

3.  Dependence  on  race  an  essential  property  of  man    .  .        95  \/ 

4.  There  must  be  a  tacit  or  express  reference  to  this  in  every 

theory  of  human  nature    .  .  .  .  .  .        96  v/ 

5.  Some  properties  may  admit  of  independent  variation         .        97 

6.  In  simplest  case,  the   organism   may  vary  whilst   social  a 

organisation  is  constant    .  .  .  .  .  .98 

7.  In  most    complex,  organic    variation   implied  by  change 

in  social  organisation        .  .  .  .  .  -99 

8.  The  most  complex  social  organisation  varies  whilst  indivi- 

dual organisation  is  constant     .  .         .  .         .100 


CONTENTS. 


XV 


1 1.   Society  atid  Men. 

9,   The  last  is  true  of  human  societies 

10.  Social    development    may    take    place 

variation  .... 

11.  The  accumulation  of  experience     . 
12. 

13- 


without    orjranic 


Inheritance  of  capital  and  skill 
Changes  implied  in  language  as  a  product  of  the 
factor      ....... 

14.  Necessity  of  considering  the  social  factor 

1 5.  The  mutual  dependence  of  the  members  of  society 

16.  The  omnipresent  social  discipline  . 

17.  Society  to  be  regarded  as  an  organic  growth  . 


social 


PACE 
lOI 

103 
104 

105 
107 
108 
109 
I  10 


III.   Social  Organisation. 

18.  Social  organs       .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .112 

19.  Corporate  sentiment  implied  in  an  organ  .  .  .113 

20.  Various  developments  of  corporate  sentiment  .  .  .      115 
2  I.  Every  such  sentiment  implies  the  existence  of  more  general 

sentiments       .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .116 

22.  The  hierarchy  of  social  instincts    .  .  .  .  .117 

23.  The  constitution  of  each  organ  dependent  upon  contingent 

circumstances  .  .         .  .         .  .         .119 


IV,  Social  Tissue. 


24, 

2$. 


"  Social  tissue  "  is  the  substratum  of  social  organs  . 

Theory  of  evolution  requires  definition  of  units 

Relation  of  this  to  problems  involving  reference  to  social 

factor      .  .  . 

Social  development  spread  laterally  as  well  as  lineally 
How  this  affects  the  struggle  for  existence 
The  unit  of  operation  cannot  be  the  state 
30.   Otherwise  our  problem^ would  be  the  evolution  of  typical 

states      ........ 

Nature  of  the  social  tissue     ..... 

Malthusian  competition  ..... 

Complex  nature  of  the  actual  process       ... 
The  vitality  of  the  tissue  has  conditions  capable  of  inde 

pendent  statement    ...... 

35.   No  precise  test  of  identity  of  tissue 


26. 

27. 
28. 
29 


3t. 
32. 
33. 

34. 


120 
120 

121 
122 
123 
123 

125 

126 
127 
127 

129 


xvi  CONTENTS. 

V,    T/ie  Family. 


PAGE 


36.  The  family  not  co-ordinate  with  other  forms  of  association      131 

37.  It  corresponds  to  more  intimate  and  underlying  order  of 

forces      ......... 

38.  It  represents  the  forces  of  cohesion  of  the  social  tissue     ,      134 

39.  Recapitulation  to  show  necessity  of  these  distinctions        .      135 


132 


CHAPTER  IV. 
Form  of  the  Moral  Law. 

I.  Law  and  C^istom. 

1.  Customs  and  habits       .  .  .  .  .  .  .137 

2.  They  are  "laws  of  nature  "  in  the  making       .  .  .137 

3.  Positive  laws  imply  custom,  including  a  potential  element      138 

4.  They  must  rest  ultimately  upon  custom,  not  upon  coercion      140 

5.  Every  society  must  have  organic  laws,  intelligible  only 

through  itself.  .  .  .  .  .  ,  ,142 

6.  It  is  dependent  upon  the  vitality  of  corresponding  social 

instincts  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .143 

7.  We  must  therefore   study  the  conditions  of  this  vitality 

separately         .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .145 

II.  The  Moral  Law. 

8.  The  moral  law  must  be  an  approximate  statement  of  these 

conditions         .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .147 

9.  This  does  not  necessarily  give  the  reason,  but  only  the 

cause  of  morality      .  .  .  .  .  .  .148 

III.   The  Moral  Law  is  Natural. 

10.  Hence  we  may  deduce  certain  attributes  of  morality — It 

is  "natural"  ........      149 

11.  Possibility  of  an  artificial  development  of  actual  morality       150 
~I2.   Morality  must  be  a  function  of  the  organic  instincts  .      150 

13.  In  what  sense  it  can  be  affected  by  a  moral  legislator      .      151 

14.  Morality  only  susceptible  of  secular  variations  .  .152 

15.  The   "immutability"  and   "eternity"   of  the  moral  law 

deducible  from  this  .  .  .  .  .  .153 


CONTENTS.  xvii 


IV.  Morality  is  Natural. 


PAGE 


1 6.  Change  of  form  from  "  Do  this  "  to  "  Be  this  "         .  -155 

17.  Why  is  the  change  important  ?        .  .  .  .  -155 

18.  The  external  and  internal  rules  may  approximate  but  can- 

not be  coincident     .  .  .  .  .  .  .156 

19.  A  general  rule  of  conduct  must  be  a  rule  of  character       .      157 

20.  Extrinsic  and  intrinsic  motives       .  .  .  .  .158 

21.  Some  classes  of  conduct  without  intrinsic  motive     .  .      159 

22.  Most  rules  imply  a  variety  of  possible  motives  .  .160 

23.  Possibility  of  external  rules  due  to  habit  and  actual  incon- 

sistency .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .160 

24.  They  may  correspond  approximately  to  constant  motives       161 

25.  The    extrinsic    motive    of  respect    for    authority    implies 

occasional  deviations  .  .  .  .  .  .162 

26.  Hence  reference  to  authority  or  extrinsic  motive  must  be 

eliminated  from  a  true  moral  law        .  .  .  .163 

27.  The  development  of  such  laws  is  a  process  of  induction    .      164 

28.  Hence  the  attribute  of  ^f^y^riT/f?  "  supremacy  "  of  moral  law      166 

V.  Basis  of  Morality. 

29.  Recapitulation      ,  .  .         .  .         ,  .         .167 

30.  Possible  deduction  of  moral  law     .  .  .  .  .168 

31.  Many  laws  which  satisfy  these  conditions  not  moral  .      169 

32.  The  distinction  of  the  organism  and  aggregate  to  be  borne 

in  mind  ,  .  ,  .  .  .  ,  .170 

33.  Hence  we  have  to  seek  for  the  difference  of  the  moral  law      17  i 


CHAPTER  V. 

Contents  of  the  Moral  Law. 

I.   The  Law  of  Nature  and  Morality. 

1.  The  law  of  nature  includes  prudence  and  morality  .         .      172 

2.  Deduction  of  special  virtues  .  .  .  .  .  .173 

3.  The  cardinal  virtues      .  .  .  .        '".  .  .174 

1 1.    Virtue  of  Courage, 

4.  Social  welfare  dependent  upon  strength,  and   especially 

upon  courage  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .175 

5.  Development  of  chivalrous  sentiment      .  .  .         .      'i^77 


XVIU 


CONTENTS. 


PAGE 

6.  Development  of  "  moral  courage "  .         .         .  .178 

7.  Limitations  to  utility  of  courage     .  .  .  .  .179 

8.  Question  whether  courage  is  properly  a  virtue  .  .      1 80 

9.  Courage  regarded  by  common  sense  with  a  quasi  moral 

approval  ,  .  .  ,  .  .  .  .181 

It  is  regarded  as  a  necessary  but  not  sufficient  condition 

of  virtue  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .182 

The  development  as  a  process  of  implicit  induction  .      183 

Question  whether  approval  implies  perception  of  utility  of 

courage  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .184 

The  distinct  perception  emerges  in  later  stages         .  .185 

Approval  of  conduct  as  useful  must  itself  be  useful  ,  .186 

Possible  non-fulfilment  of  this  condition  .  .  ,  .187 

16.  Tendency  to  its  complete  fulfilment         .  .  .  .188 

17.  Application  to  other  virtues  of  strength  .  .  .  .189 


10. 

1 1. 
12. 

13. 
14. 
15- 


III.    Viftue  of  Tempera7ice. 

18.  Temperance  either  prudential  or  strictly  virtuous      .  .190 

19.  Change  from  external  to  internal  rule     .  .  .  .191 

20.  The  antisocial  quality  of  sensuality  produces   the  moral 

disapproval      .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .192 

21.  The  sentiment  goes  beyond  the  utilitarian  perception  of 

"consequences"       .  .  .  .  .  .  .195 

22.  The  development  of  the  ascetic  theory    .  .  .  .195 

23.  Ascetic  theory  implies  a  one-sided  but  sometimes  accurate 

assumption      .  .  .  .  .  ,  .  .196 

24.  Ordinary  and  heroic  virtues  ,  .  .  .  .  .197 

25.  A  tacit  recognition  of  utiUty  implied  in  these  theories       .      198 

26.  In  what  sense  all  "consequences"  are  to  decide  morality      199 

27.  The  whole  organic  constitution  must  be  taken  into  account     200 

28.  Physiological  element  in  the  moral  sentiment.  .  .201 


IV.    Virtue  of  Trjcth. 

Social  welfare  dependent  upon  truthfulness      .          .          .  202 
Slow  development  of  toleration       .          ,          .          ,          .204 
Possibility  of  an  absolute  statement  of  moral  law  of  truth- 
fulness   .........  205 

Still  the  virtue  is  based  upon  social  welfare     .          .          .  206 

Casuistical  difficulties  from  an  absolute  statement    .          .  207 
34.  The  development  of  truthfulness  resembles  that  of  other 

virtues    .........  208 


29. 
30. 
31. 

32. 
33 


CONTENTS.  xix 


V.   T/ie  Social  Viriues. 


PAGE 


35.  These  virtues  developed  in  the  same  way  and  based  upon 

social  welfare  ,  .  .  .  .  .  .  .210 

36.  Justice  and  benevolence  distinguished     .  .  .  .211 

37.  Justice  means  acting  on  sufficient  reason  .  .  .212 

38.  The  sufficient  reason  means  social  welfare       .  .  .213 

39.  Hence  the  duties  really  consistent  are  a  development  of 

the  same  principle   .  .  .  .  ,  .  .214 


VI.    The  Social  Definition  of  Virtue. 

40.  Recapitulation  of  the  principles  asserted  .  .  .215 

41.  Origin  of  problem  of  obligation       .  .  .  .  .     217  ^_^ 


CHAPTER  VI. 

Altruism. 
I.  Esioisfic  Instincts. 


'<b^ 


1.  The  possibility  of  self-sacrifice  disputed  .  .  .219 

2.  The  egoist  denies  the  possibility  of  conscious  self-sacrifice     220 

3.  Beneficial  consequence  does  not  necessarily  imply  benevo- 

lent intention  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .221 

4.  Gradual  development  of  truly  benevolent  intention  .  .     222 

5.  Doctrine  of  "  association  "  gives  an  apparently  inadequate 

explanation      ,  .  .  .  .  .  .  .223 

6.  Egoistic  theory  that  the  happiness  of  others  can  never  be 

an  ultimate  end        .  .  .  .  .  .  .224 

7.  Implied  truth  that  all  motives  may  be  stated  objectively 

or  subjectively  .  .  .  .  .  .  .225 

8.  The  objective  statement  must  express  some  condition  of 

the  subject      ,  .  .  .  .  .  .  .226 

9.  If  it  includes  the  happiness  of  others,  some  further  analysis 

is  needed 227 


II.  Sympathy. 

10.   "  Objective"  is  that  which  exists  for  you  as  well  as  for  me  228 

I  I.  To  think  of  another  man  is  to  have  representative  feelings  229 

12.  Sympathy  has  a  logical  as  well  as  an  emotional  value       .  230 

13.  This  is  obscured  by  the  ambiguities  of  ordinary  language  230 


XX 


CONTENTS. 


14.  Nor  does  it  giv'e  a  full  account  of  the  process 

15.  Cruelty  as  identified  with  stupidity 

16.  Or  as  inattention  to  implicit  consequences 

17.  Complications  introduced  by  antipathy  . 

18.  Sympathy  the  fundamental  fact 

19.  Pleasure  in  pain  as  pain 

20.  Normally  sympathy  means  self-identification  with  others 
2T.  The  difficulty  is  to  understand  the  reverse  feeling    . 


PAGE 


236 

237 
238 


III.  Altr7iis7n. 

22.  Sympathy  the  condition  of  altruism 

23.  All  conduct  conditioned  by  the  agent's  feelings 

24.  It  is  not  therefore  selfish       .... 

25.  Association  does  not  explain  it       . 

26.  It  must  be  conditioned  by  the  agent's  knowledge  of 

men's  feelings ...... 

27.  But  is  not  therefore  removable  at  pleasure 

28.  The  ideal  conditions  as  fixed  as  the  non-ideal 

29.  An  egoistic  interpretation  still  possible  . 


other 


239 

239 
240 
241 

242 
243 
245 
245 


IV.    The  Rule  of  Conduct. 

30.  The  true  question,  what  is  the  law  of  feeling  ? 

31.  The  "  greatest-happiness  "  principle  of  conduct 

32.  Virtual  altruism  of  unreasoning  instincts 

33.  How  affected  by  intellectual  development 

34.  The  purely  prudential  maxim   never  absolutely  observ- 

35.  But  approximately  observable  when  sympathy  is  neglected 

36.  Sympathetic  motives  are  not  necessarily  divergent  . 

37.  But  can  only  conform  fully  so  long  as  sympathy  is  dormant 

or  factitious      ........ 

38.  Systematic  disregard  of  sympathetic  virtues  implies  idiocy 

39.  Their  law   implies  regard  to  happiness  of  others  as  an 

ultimate  motive         ....... 

40.  The  prudential  maxim  is  taken  up  into  the  higher  as  society 

develops  ........ 

41.  Fallacies  involved  in  egoistic  statement . 

42.  The  true  meaning  of  "  disengagement  "  . 

43.  Every  end  must  correspond  to  a  real  motive  . 

44.  Benevolence  not  explicable  by  a  tacit  reference  to  self 

45.  Hence  comparison  of  sympathetic   and  non-sympathetic 

agents     ......... 


246 
247 
248 
249 

250 
251 
252 

253 
255 

256 

257 

259 
260 
260 
261 

262 


CONTENTS. 


XXI 


CHAPTER  VII. 
Merit. 

I.    T//e  Conception  of  Merit. 

1.  Virtue  implies  more  than  simple  benevolence  . 

2.  Approval  of  virtue  implies  more  than  gratitude 

3.  Hence  the  various  problems  of  obligation 

4.  Merit  is  proportioned  to  the  intrinsic  goodness  of  the  agen 

5.  It  represents  a  claim  upon  the  universe  . 

6.  The  value  set  upon  virtues  varies  with  their  utility  . 

7.  Analogy  in  this  respect  to  economical  theory  of  value 

8.  Merit  applies  only  to  voluntary  conduct 

9.  And  to  qualities  capable  of  training 

10.  The  merit  of  an  action  means  the  virtue  proved  by  it 

1 1.  Morality  cannot  be   independent  of   motives   when   true 

morality  is  developed         ..... 

12.  Difficulties  of  distinguishing  material  and  formal  morality 
I  3.   The  genuine  moral  law  must  classify  actions  by  motives 
14.   Recapitulation      ....... 


I'AGE 
264 
265 
265 
266 
267 
268 
270 
27  I 
272 

274 
275 
276 
277 


II.   Free-will. 

15.  The  nature  of  the  free-will  difficulty        ....      278 

16.  The  merit  must  depend  upon  the  motive  .  .  .      279 

17.  Hence  "voluntary"  means  free  from  coercion,  not  from 

determination.  .  .  .  .  .  .  .280 

1 8.  Free-will  theory,  so  far  as  separating  motive  from  conduct, 

is  destructive  of  merit       ,  .  .  .  .  .281 

19.  This  includes  responsibility  .  .  .  .  .  .282 

20.  The  statement  that  we  can  form  our  own  characters   is 

irrelevant         .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .283 

21.  T\\&  causa  causcB  argument    .  .  .  .  .  .284 

22.  Causation  does  not  lessen  responsibility  .  .  .      285 

23.  The  difficulty  arises  from  a  false  interpretation  of  causation      286 

24.  Cause  and  effect  imply  mutual  dependence,  and  therefore 

implication,  but  not  coercion  as  something  additional.      287 

25.  Necessity  is  the  antithesis  of  chance,  and  both  subjective.     290 

26.  Fore-knowledge  is  consistent  with  responsibility        .  .291 

27.  Thus  the  ^rt^ifji^  ^ra/^i'iS?  argument  is  really  irrelevant  .  .292 


III.   Effort. 

28.  Merit  implies  discipline  .  .  .  .  • 

29.  A  standard  of  action  and  membership  of  a  class 

30.  The  change  of  the  standard  gives  rise  to  ambiguities 


294 
294 
295 


xxii  CONTENTS. 


PAGE 


31.  Difficulty  of  deciding  the  Standard  applicable  to  infants   .      296 

32.  And  to  madmen  ;   but  motive  in  all  cases  the  criterion      .      297 

33.  The  difficulty  arises  from  the  complexity  of  the  facts,  not 

from  ambiguity  of  principle        .  ,  .  .  .299 

34.  Hence  the  fallacy  of  measuring  merit  by  effort   without 

distinguishing  the  cases    .  .  .  .  ,  .299 

35.  The  man  is  most  meritorious  to  whom  virtue  is  easiest, 

provided  that  he  belongs  to  the  class  .  .  .301 

36.  Hence  the  problem  whether  essential  instincts  can  be  bad      301 

37.  Development  implies  more  than  moral  development  .      302 

38.  Effort  so  far  essential  to  virtue  that  liability  to  temptation 

is  essential      ........      303 


IV.  Knowledge. 

39.  The  love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake         ....      304 

40.  How  far  does  conformity  to  a  law  imply  a  recognition  of 

law?       ......... 

4 1 .  Reason,  and  therefore  knowledge  of  law,  implied  in  develop- 

ment      .........      306 

42.  But  the  implicit  obedience  to  law  may  precede  conscious 

acceptance  of  law     .......      306 

43.  Thus  the  problem  becomes  one  of  fact,  not  of  principle    ,      308 

44.  Transition  and  recapitulation  .....      309 


305 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

The  Conscience. 

I.   Theories  of  Conscience. 

1.  Merit  implies  intrinsically  virtuous  motive  or  conscience  .      311 

2.  Difficulty  of  explaining  the  nature  of  conscience       .  .311 

3.  The  deduction  from  pure  reason  ambiguous     .  .  -313 

4.  The  theory  of  a  primitive  faculty  implies  a  wrong  psycho- 

logy          314 

5.  The  moral  judgment  is  a  function  of  the  whole  character       315 

6.  Love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake  must  be  understood  con- 

sistently with  this     .  .  .  .  .  .  ,316 

7.  A  separate  faculty  not  a  conscience,  but  a  conscientious  man     317 

8.  Conscience  is  therefore  derivative,  and  not  the  less  real 

though  generally  weak  in  point  of  fact         .  .  .319 


CONTENTS.  xxiii 

II.  Sense  of  Shame. 


PAGE 


9.   Conscience  implies  an  intellectual  and  emotional  factor    .      319 

10.  The  sense  of  shame  seems  to  be  one  element  .  .      3-i 

11.  Shame  is  excited  by  offences  other  than  moral         ,  .      322 

12.  By  simply  ridiculous,  and  even  by  right  conduct       .  .      323 

1 3.  The  general  law  depends  upon  heightened  self-conscious- 

ness       .......••      3-3 

14.  Hence  implicated  in  conscience,  but  the  relation  to  con- 

science variable        .  .  .  .  .  .  -3-4 

15.  The    law   of  the  feeling   is   not   deducible    from    logical 

definition         .  .  .  .  .  .  .  -3-5 

16.  It    gives  rise   to    quasi    intuitions,    which,   however,    are 

variable  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  -3-6 

17.  Its  possible  variation  limited  by  individual  organisation    .      327 

18.  And  by  the  law  of  the  social  organism    ....      3-8 

19.  Hence  it  is  involved  in  moral  development      .  .  .      329 

20.  Its  law  and  its  utility  definable  only  through  social  factor      330 

III.   Esthetic  Judgments. 

21.  This  distinctive  quality  of  the  ethical  judgment  consistent 

with  its  composite  character      .  .  .  .  -33- 

22.  Esthetic  judgments  are  equally  composite       .  .  .      332 

23.  An  aesthetic  judgment  may  involve  every  primitive  instinct     333 

24.  It  is  differenced  by  form  of  gratification,  not  by  instincts 

gratified  ........      334 

25.  Hence    the    moral   judgment    must    include   an   £esthetic 

element  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  -335 

26.  The  assimilation  of  the  moral  law  impHes  the  growth  of 

such  a  sensibility      .......      33^ 

27.  Hence  the  so-called  moral  sense,  which  outruns  the  direct 

moral  judgment        .......      337 

28.  Questions   of    "taste"    include   a   reference   to   objective 

facts        .........      33S 

29.  The  moral  judgment  an  implicit  judgment  of  types  .  .      339 

IV.   The  Conscience. 

30.  The  conscious  ground  of  morality  may  vary  widely  from 

the  cause         .  .  .         .  .  .  .  .339 

31.  Every  association   implies  the   development  of  a  highly 

complex  instinct  of  loyalty  .  .  .  .  -341 

32.  The  sense  of  duty  as  the  corporate  instinct  of  the  '-social 

virtue"  is  necessarily  vague       .....      34- 

33.  But  it  is  definite  because   all   organisations  involve   the 

fundamental  instinct  ......      343 


xxlv  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

34.  And  because  the  true  school  of  morahty  is  the  family        .  344 

35.  The    reference   to    the   virtue    itself  unconscious   though 

essential           ........  345 

36.  Morality  is  rooted  in  family  sentiment,  though  divergence 

is  possible        ........  346 

37.  Two  points  of  view  are  thus  necessary    ....  348 

38.  The  conflict  of  duties   possible,  though  the   question    is 

more  of  fact  than  morality          .....  349 

39.  Conscience  is  thus  a  modification  of  all  primary  instincts  349 

40.  Application  to  the  case  of  maternal  love           .          .          •  35i 

41.  Transition  to  problem  of  happiness         ....  352 


J 


CHAPTER  IX. 

Happiness  as  a  Criterion. 

I.    Utilitarianism. 

From  the  cause  we  infer  the  reason  of  morality        .  .      353 

Problems  of  the  criterion  and  sanction  of  morality  .  .      354 

The  utilitarian  criterion  .  .  .  .  .  -355 

4.  Irrelevant  objections     .......      356 

5.  Relevant  objections  to  uncertainty,  lowness,  externality, 

expediency  of  code  .  .         .  .  .         .  -358 


II.  Limits  of  the  Method. 

6.  Utilitarianism  based  on  the  empirical  philosophy     .  .      359 

7.  Theory  of  "  lots"  of  happiness        .....      360 

8.  Tendency  to  regard  society  as  an  aggregate,  not  as  an 

organism  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .361 

9.  Inadequacy  of  method  to  give  a  scientific  formula  .  .  363 
10.  It  makes  a  wrong  assumption  as  to  constants  .  .  364 
I  I.   The  analogy  of  sanitary  rules  which  refer  to  health  instead 

of  pleasure       ........      365 

I  2.   The  evolutionist  morality  makes  the  same  change  in  the 

moral  criterion  .......      366 

13.  And  thereby  makes  a  code  flexible  and  rigid  in  the  right 

places     .........      367 

14.  Utilitarianism  represents  instantaneous  morality,  but  re- 

quires correction  when  the  organism  varies  .  .      368 

15.  Analogy  of  individual  and  social  growth  .  .  .      370 

16.  Importance  of  similar  considerations  elsewhere         .         .     370 


CONTENTS. 


XXV 


III,    Variability  of  Morality. 

1 7.  The  standard  must  be  affected  by  the  average  estimate  of 

happiness         ........ 

1 8.  But  does  not  assume  the  desirability  of  a  maximum  of 

such  happiness         ....... 

19.  This  imphed  in  the  nature  of  moral  development     . 

20.  The  moral  law  implicitly  commands  an  elevation  of  ideal 

happiness         ........ 

21.  Another  cause  for  lowness  of  utilitarian  standard 


PAGE 

373 
374 

375 

375 


IV.  Extrinsic  Morality. 

22.  The  utilitarian  rule  tends  to  be  external 

23.  The  egoistic  utilitarian  explains  benevolence  by  extrinsic 

motives  .......•• 

24.  Illustration  of  the  miser  ...... 

25.  External  morality  thus  explicable,  but  not  internal  . 


j/ 


76 


377 
378 

379 


27. 
28. 


34. 
35- 
36. 
37. 
38. 

39- 
40. 


V.  Expediency. 

The  altruistic  utilitarianism  is  still  said  to  rest  on  expe 

diency     ..... 
It  cannot  make  the  conscience  absolute 
Importance  of  observing  general  rules  as  understood  by 

the  utilitarian 
Consequences  are  in  fact  relevant 
A    "  categorical   imperative "   not   applicable   to   external 

morality  ....... 

The  sphere  of  casuistry  when  facts  are  not  disputed 

Utilitarian  theory  generally  regarded  as  insufficient . 

The  analogy  of  military  duty 

Hence  true  principle  in  this  case 

Which  applies  to  the  moral  law 

The  case  of  suicide 

Moral  pedantry    . 

In  what  sense  "  expedieney ''  must  be  recognised 

A  fixed  criterion  still  remains 

Transition  to  problem  of  sanction 


380 
382 

383 

384 

384 
386 

387 
3881^ 

390 
390 
391 
392 
393 
394 
395 


xxvi  CONTENTS. 

CHAPTER  X. 

Morality  and  Happiness. 

I.    T/ie  Sanction, 

PAGE 

1.  Why  should  a  man  be  virtuous  ?     .....  396 

2.  Morality  unconditionally  useful  to  the  society,  not  to  the 

individual         ........  397 

3.  The  problem  of  Job       .......  397 

4.  Presumption  that  virtue  gives  happiness  to  the  virtuous     .  398 

5.  The  standard  of  the  virtuous  not  a  standard  for  others      .  399 

6.  Nor  is  it  possible  to  lay  down  an  absolute  and  uniform 

standard          ........  400 

7.  Various  senses  of  question     ......  402 

8.  Assumption  that  honesty  is  the  best  policy       .          .          .  403 

II.   Happiness  and  Virtue. 

9.  The  temptation  to  exaggerate  the  coincidence           .         .  404 

10.  Health  the  primary  condition  of  happiness       .          .          .  404 

1 1.  Extension  of  the  principle  beyond  bodily  health       .          .  405 

12.  Deduction  from  correlation  of  painful  and  pernicious         .  406 

13.  Equally  true  of  the  socially  pernicious    ....  407 

14.  It  suggests  the  line  of  argument     .....  408 

1 5.  Happiness  rewards  obedience  to  law  of  nature,  not  to  moral 

law  simply       .          .          .          .          .    ■      .          .          .  408 

16.  A  neglect  of  this  leads  to  many  of  the  perplexities    .          .  409 

17.  This  consistent  with  coincidence  of  happiness  and  virtue  410 

18.  A  man  cannot  be  too  virtuous  for  happiness  normally       .  411 

19.  Confirmation  from  particular  moral  rule  of  temperance     .  412 

20.  The  extension  of  the  principle  to  other  moral  rules  .  .413 

21.  This  applies  equally  to  sympathetic  and  non-sympathetic 

motives  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .  .414 

22.  Question  of  virtue  in  advance  of  actual  standard       .  .416 

23.  The  coincidence  less  perfect  in  this  case  .  .  .417 


III.   Moral  Discipline. 

24.  Natural  aptitude  for  virtue    .  .  .         .         .  .418 

2  5.  The  fact  that  virtue  has  to  be  acquired  is  generally  irrelevant     4 1 9 

26.  Moralisation  part  of  a  process  which  has  other  advantages     419 

27.  Extension  of  the  ordinary  prudential  argument         .  .421 

28.  Unity  of  virtue     ........     422 


CONTENTS. 


XXV 11 


29.  Moral  idiocy  possible   .... 

30.  No  external  morality  possible  in  such  cases 

31.  The  prudential  argument  still  valid 

32.  A  moral  world  generally  desirable  for  all 


PAGE 
423 
423 

425 


33. 

34. 
35. 
36. 
37. 


IV.  Self-Sacrijice. 

Self-sacrifice  sometimes  a  necessary  consequence  of  virtue  : 
the  case  of  Regulus  ...... 

No  argument  but  the  gallows  available  in  some  cases 

This  too  follows  from  admission  of  real  altruism 

The  ultimate  discord     ....... 

The  general  statement  limits,  but  does  not  include  it 


426 
429 
430 
431 
432 


I. 
2 

3. 
4. 

5. 
6. 

7. 
8. 

9- 
10. 

II. 
12. 

13. 

14. 

15- 
16. 

17. 
18. 

19- 
20. 
21. 


CHAPTER  XL 

Conclusion. 

Further  controversies    .... 

The  insoluble  difficulty 

The  art  and  practice  in  other  sciences     . 

In  ethics  both  a  science  and  an  art 

"  Ought  "  and  "  is  "      . 

Beliefs  about  conduct  imply  laws  of  conduct 

The  scientific  theory  of  positive  laws 

And  of  the  moral  law    .... 

The  belief  to  become  effective  must  stimulate  the  emotion: 
Morality  not  universally  binding  de  facto ^  but  only  dc  ju}\ 
Scientific  ideal  of  a  perfect  correlation   . 
Progress  implies  discord        ..... 

Can  the  limits  of  the  scientific  inquiry  be  transcended? 
Futility  of  ontology       ...... 

Importance  of  disentangling  the  scientific  question  . 
Metaphysical  inquiry  means  the  elimination  of  ultimate 

fallacies,  not  the  discovery  of  facts 
Metaphysics  related  to  ethical  as  to  other  sciences  . 
The  moral  code  is  formed  by  scientific  observation  . 
INIetaphysics  cannot  affect  this  conclusion 
The  ontological  and  metaphysical  theories  are  irrelevant 
The  theological  theory  adds  nothing  to  the  scientific  theory 

of  permanence  of  morality         .         .  ,  .  . 


434 
435 
435 
436 
437 
438 

439 
440 

441 

442 

443 
444 
446 

447 
447 

448 
450 
450 

451 
452 

455 


XXVUl 


CONTENTS. 


22.  The  denial  of  the  reality  of  evil      .  .  .  .  , 

23.  The  science  of  morality  does  not  give  the  art,  nor,  there 

fore,  the  sanction  of  morality    .... 

24.  Religion  and  morality  ...... 

25.  Belief  affects  conduct,  but  not  the  ultimate  condition 

26.  The  cause  of  belief  must  be  considered  . 

27.  Change  of  dialect  not  a  change  of  ultimate  belief     . 

28.  The  basis  of  morality  unalterable   .... 


PAGE 
456 

456 

457 
458 

459 
460 

460 


THE   SCIENCE   OF    ETHICS. 


CHAPTER  T. 

PURPOSE    AND    LIMITS    OF    THE    INQUIRY. 
I.   The  Starting-Point. 

I.  At  the  outset  of  any  inquiry  it  is  proper  to  take  stock 
of  the  results  obtained  by  previous  explorers  of  the  same 
field,  and  in  particular  to  ask  how  far  they  have  reached  that 
unity  of  doctrine  which  affords  a  presumption,  though  not  a 
conclusive  proof,  of  the  attainment  of  definitive  truth.  If 
we  examine  the  history  of  ethical  speculation  for  this  purpose, 
we  are  confronted  by  a  fact  which,  were  it  not  so  familiar, 
might  appear  to  be  anomalous.  In  one  sense  moralists  are 
almost  unanimous ;  in  another  they  are  hopelessly  discordant. 
They  are  unanimous  in  pronouncing  certain  classes  of  con- 
duct to  be  right  and  the  opposite  wrong.  No  moralist  denies 
that  cruelty,  falsehood,  and  intemperance  are  vicious,  or  that 
mercy,  truth,  and  temperance  are  virtuous.  Making  every 
deduction  from  this  apparent  unanimity  —  allowing  that 
similar  names  may  be  interpreted  in  very  different  senses; 
that  the  general  outlines  of  a  moral  code  may  be  the  same 
whilst  its  spirit  varies  widely ;  and  that  the  moral  codes 
accepted  at  different  times  and  places  have  been  as  different 
as  has  ever  been  seriously  maintained — yet  it  remains  true 
that  there  is  an  a})proximation  to  unity.  The  difference 
between  different  systems  is  chiefiy  in  the  details  and  special 
application  of  generally  admitted  principles.       It  is  not  such 


2  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

as  we  might  anticipate  from  a  radical  opposition  both  of 
method  and  principle.  But  if  we  turn  from  the  matter  to 
the  form  of  morality;  if,  instead  of  asking  what  actions 
are  right  or  wrong:,  we  ask,  what  is  the  essence  of  rio;ht 
and  wrong?  how  do  we  know  right  from  wrong?  why 
should  we  seek  the  right  and  eschew  the  wrong;  ? — we  are 
presented  with  the  most  contradictory  answers ;  we  find 
ourselves  at  once  in  that  region  of  perpetual  antinomies, 
where  controversy  is  everlasting,  and  opposite  theories  seem 
to  be  equally  self-evident  to  different  minds. 

2.  This  remark  has  long  been  familiar,  but  perhaps  we 
have  not,  even  yet,  familiarised  ourselves  with  some  of  its 
consequences.  We  must  consider  this  protracted  antagonism 
in  the  light  of  a  principle  which  grows  more  prominent  with 
the  advance  of  historical  methods  of  inquiry.  Every  widely- 
spread  opinion  deserves  respect  by  the  bare  fact  of  its  exist- 
ence. It  is  itself  a  phenomenon  which  requires  to  be  taken 
into  account.  We  can  no  long^er  be  content  with  refuting; 
our  opponents;  we  are  also  bound  to  explain  them.  The 
vitality  of  any  doctrine  supposed  to  be  erroneous  proves  that 
it  cannot  be  entirely  erroneous.  It  must  have  an  element  of 
truth  for  which  it  is  necessary  to  provide  accommodation  in 
any  satisfactory  system.  It  is  a  recognised  criterion  of 
successful  speculation  that  it  should  explain  not  only  the 
phenomena  considered,  but  the  illusions  due  to  a  partial  view 
of  the  phenomena.  The  fact  that  the  Ptolemaic  system  of 
astronomy  can  be  fitted  into  the  Copernican  system  as  re- 
presenting an  imperfect  view  of  the  facts,  whilst  the  relation 
cannot  be  reversed,  is  itself  part  of  the  evidence  on  behalf  of 
the  more  comprehensive  system.  The  necessity  of  applying 
this  reflection  to  ethical  doctrine  has  been  widely  recognised, 
though  the  dif^culty  of  applying  it  is  still  enormous.  Some 
writers  aim  at  the  desired  conciliation  by  eclectic  systems, 
which  turn  out  to  be  mere  tessellations  of  inconsistent  frag- 
ments, instead  of  being;  harmonious  wholes  which  absorb  into 
themselves  the  partial  and  so  far  erroneous  doctrine.  More 
frcquentlv,  writers  who  try  to  explain  the  theories  of  their 


THE  STARTING-POINT.  3 

antagonists,  explain  only  their  own  version  of  those  theories; 
\vhich  is  apt  to  be  a  very  different  thing.  And  this  suggests 
that,  in  order  to  attempt  a  satisfactory  conciliation,  we  have 
first  to  raise  a  preliminary  question  as  to  the  most  promising 
method  for  reaching  such  a  conciliation. 

3.  Now,  if  we  ask  what  is  necessarily  implied  in  the 
attainment  of  a  theory  at  once  satisfactory  in  itself  and  wide 
enough  to  exhibit  all  preceding  theories  as  imperfect  and 
one-sided  views  of  the  whole  truth,  the  prospect  is  rather 
alarming.  For  ethical  controversies  spring  from  the  ultimate 
problems  of  all  thought.  Full  conciliation  can  only  be  reached 
when  we  have  attained  a  definitive  system  of  philosophy. 
To  reconcile  moralists,  we  have  to  solve  the  problems  which 
have  ac^itated  without  beino-  set  at  rest  ever  since  men  beran 
to  reflect  upon  the  nature  of  truth  in  general.  We  have  to 
decide  upon  controversies-  where  the  advance  to  unanimitv, 
if  it  exists  at  all,  is  foreshadowed  not  so  much  in  the  un- 
equivocal triumph  of  either  partv,  as  in  the  gradual  modifica- 
tion of  the  old  issues  in  such  a  sense  that  mutual  understand- 
ing is  becoming  rather  more  possible.  The  problems  are 
hardly  being  answered,  but  perhaps  are  being  put  into  a  form 
in  which  they  may  some  day  admit  of  an  answer.  If  an 
agreement  between  moralists  is  to  be  adjourned  until  the  day 
in  which  all  metaphysical  puzzles  will  have  been  solved,  we 
must  be  content  to  hand  them  over  to  a  future  generation ;  and 
to  say  the  truth,  I  believe  that  our  hopes  of  a  perfect  conciliation 
must  be  adjourned  till  that  indefinitely  distant  millennium. 
But  another  less  disheartenino;  conclusion  is  also  suo-o-ested 
by  the  reflection  that,  in  spite  of  these  difficulties,  there  has 
been  in  other  respects  so  much  agreement.  Is  it  not,  in  fact, 
conceivable  that  we  may  so  disentangle  the  perplexing  threads 
of  controversy  a\  to  separate  the  questions  which  admit  of 
some  approximate;  answer  from  those  which  we  must  be 
content  not  only  to  leave  unsolved,  but  to  consider  as  of 
such  a  nature  that  even  the  method  of  solution,  and  the  kind 
of  solution  possible  and  desirable,  must  be  regarded  as  hither 
to  unsettled  problems  ^ 


4  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

4.  This  will  be  clearer  if  we  remark  that  the  difficulty 
in  question  is  by  no  means  peculiar  to  ethical  speculations. 
On  the  contrary,  we  may  say  that  it  is  common  to  all 
branches  of  knowledge.  We  possess  a  large  body  of  estab- 
lished scientific  truths — established,  that  is,  in  such  a  sense 
that  their  validity  would  be  questioned  by  no  school 
of  metaphysicians.  Geometry,  for  example,  includes  a 
vast  body  of  propositions,  which  are  admitted  by  all 
reasoners  to  possess  the  highest  degree  of  certainty.  Yet 
geometry  involves  the  conception  of  space,  and  the  true 
nature  of  that  conception  is  precisely  one  of  the  problems 
upon  which  metaphysicians  have  disputed  most  eagerly  and 
interminably.  The  geometrician  proceeds  without  troub- 
ling himself  in  the  least  about  such  argumentation,  and 
in  the  judgment  of  the  metaphysicians  themselves  he  is 
perfectly  right.  Space,  according  to  some  thinkers,  has  only 
a  phenomenal  reality ;  if  so,  the  truths  of  the  geometer  are 
only  applicable  to  phenomena.  Space,  as  we  know  it,  may 
perhaps  be  only  one  out  of  various  possible  kinds  of  space. 
If  so,  the  doctrines  of  geometry  can  only  be  regarded  as 
certain  for  that  kind  of  space  with  which  we  are  conversant. 
The  geometer  postulates  space,  and  (it  may  be)  one  particu- 
lar kind  of  space  ;  but  the  validity  of  his  reasoning,  so  long 
as  that  postulate  is  granted,  remains  unaffected.  He  is  not 
concerned  to  inquire  whether,  in  a  different  universe  or  in 
some  transcendental  world,  his  theorems  mav  require  modifica- 
tion or  mav  cease  to  be  in  any  way  applicable.  It  is  fortu- 
nate that  this  is  so,  for  otherwise  we  should  have  no  know- 
ledge until  we  had  reached  the  ultimate  jroal  of  kn()wledg:e. 
Similar  remarks  are  applicable  to  all  the  physical  sciences. 
We  mav  say,  in  mathematical  language,  that  the  formulae 
obtained  by  the  scientific  reasoner  include  constants  reo;arded 
by  him  as  ultimate  elements,  though  the  metaphysician 
may  discover  that  these  constants  themselves  require  further 
analysis,  and  are  possibly  dependent  upon  some  further 
condition  for  their  apparent  constancy.  But  the  formulae 
may  be    equally   valid   within   the   sphere   of  science   what- 


THE  STARTING-POINT.  5 

ever  may  be  the  metaphysical  interpretation  of  these  con- 
ceptions. The  relation  holds  though  the  nature  of  the 
things  related  mav  be  uncertain.  If  space  be  only  phenome- 
nal, the  limitless  properties  will  not  hold  in  the  noumenal 
world ;  but  in  this  world,  where  phenomena  are  of  so  much 
importance,  they  will  serve  as  well  as  ever  for  our  guidance. 
Thus  we  may  sav,  in  legal  metaphor,  that  the  man  of  science 
does  not  go  behind  the  record.  He  takes  the  authority  of 
his  immediate  perceptions  as  final,  and  leaves  it  to  the  meta- 
physician to  discover,  if  he  can,  some  further  justification  of 
the  proceeding. 

5.  I  am  content,  for  the  present,  to  assume  this  much,  with- 
out attempting  to  define  more  accurately  the  relation  between 
metaphysical  and  what  are  generally  called  scientific  reason- 
ings. However  that  line  may  be  drawn,  we  may  admit  that, 
in  the  case  of  the  physical  sciences  at  least,  we  can  obtain 
knowledge  which,  within  its  own  sphere,  is  entirely  indepen- 
dent of  the  metaphysician's  theories.  Is  not  this  true  in  all 
cases,  and  therefore  in  those  cases  in  which  the  science  is 
concerned  with  the  conduct  and  character  of  human  beings? 
May  we  not  discover  propositions  about  the  relations  of  men  to 
each  other  and  the  internal  relations  of  the  individual  human 
being  which  will  be  equally  independent  of  metaphysical 
disputes?  As  we  assign  the  relations  between  parts  of  space 
without  asking  what  is  space  in  itself,  mav  we  not  determine 
rules  about  men  without  asking  what  is  meant,  for  example, 
by  personal  unity,  or  what  is  the  true  mode  of  distinguish- 
ing object  from  subject?  It  is  true  that  in  these  more  com- 
plex investigations  we  are  constantly  on  the  verge  of  meta- 
physical abysses.  The  inquiry  into  the  laws  of  thought  is 
very  apt  to  complicate  itself  with  inquiry  into  the  nature  of 
thinking  beings.  The  difficulty  has  given  rise  to  many 
controversies.  From  one  point  of  view,  metaphysics  has 
seemed  to  be  merely  a  department  of  psychology,  as  the 
nature  of  men's  thoughts  seems  to  be  dependent  upon  the 
constitution  of  the  men  who  think.  From  another  point  of 
view,  the  opposite  extreme  seems  to  be  more  tenable,  as  the 


6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

laws  of  particular  modes  of  thought  must  form  a  special  de- 
partment of  the  inquiry  into  the  laws  of  thought  in  general; 
and  thus  psychology  must  be  taken  up  into  and  absorbed  in 
metaphysics.  And,  in  fact,  as  the  case  of  ethical  speculation 
itself  proves,  it  is  very  difficult  to  reason  about  any  question 
involving  psychology  without  gliding  into  the  ultimate  meta- 
physical problems.  And  yet  a  discrimination  of  the  two 
elements,  though  harder  to  maintain,  may  be  as  conceivable 
here  as  in  the  physical  sciences.  For  it  is  a  fact — and  a 
fact  for  which  we  may  again  appeal  to  these  ethical  specula- 
tions— that  there  are  a  large  number  of  propositions,  which 
we  are  daily  and  hourly  using,  which  refer  to  human 
nature,  and  which  are  presumably  independent  of  meta- 
physical speculation.  Like  the  geometrical  truths,  they 
involve  elements  which  may  require  further  analysis^  but, 
like  the  geometrical  truths,  they  will  hold  good,  or  at  any 
rate  hold  good  within  a  very  wide  sphere,  whatever  the 
results  of  such  analysis. 

6.  Take,  for  example,  any  one  of  those  theorems  of  which 
we  constantly  assume  the  truth.  Most  mothers,  we  say,  love 
their  children.  That  is  a  statement  which  conveys  a  distinct 
meaning,  and  a  statement  of  which  we  can  discover  and  test 
the  truth  without  appealing  to  any  metaphysical  system.  In 
order  to  express  it  at  all,  we  have  to  use  some  conceptions  which 
the  metaphysician  professes  to  explain.  We  tacitly  assume  a 
distinction  between  subject  and  object,  a  distinction  between 
persons,  a  causal  relation  between  certain  phenomena,  and  so 
forth  ;  and  metaphysicians  will  proceed  to  deal  with  these  dis- 
tinctions and  relations  after  their  own  fashion.  They  may  tell 
us,  for  example,  that  we  can  transcend  the  distinction  of  subject 
and  oljjcct;  that  persons,  though  phenomenally  different,  are 
different  manifestations  of  an  identical  substance;  that  the  rela- 
tion of  cause  and  effect  is  a  mere  illusion,  or  that  it  implies  a 
transcendental  power  behind  the  phenomena.  But  all  such 
statements,  true  or  false,  have  not  the  very  slightest  influence 
upon  our  belief  in  the  asserted  fact.  They  state  some- 
thing supposed  to  be  implied  in  the  fact;  but  something  also 


THE  STARTING-POINT.  7 

remains  unaltered,  whatever  be  implied.  Nor  is  there  the 
least  reason  to  suj)pose  that  the  phrase  in  question  conveys 
a  different  meaning  to  metaphysicians  of  opposite  schools. 
Solomon's  famous  experiment  upon  motherly  love  was  not 
suggested  by  nor  did  it  require  to  be  reinterpreted  by  metaphy- 
sical theorems.  The  follower  of  Hegel  means  in  all  probability 
precisely  the  same  thing  as  the  follower  of  Hume  when  he 
says  that  a  mother  loves  her  child;  though  when  they  come 
to  reflect  upon  certain  ulterior  imports  of  the  phrases  used, 
they  may  come  to  opposite  conclusions.  The  formula 
remains  the  same ;  for  all  purposes  of  conduct  it  evokes  the 
same  impressions,  sentiments,  and  sensible  images,  and  it  there- 
fore represents  a  stage  at  which  all  theories  must  coincide, 
though  they  start,  or  profess  to  start,  from  the  most  opposite 
bases. 

7.  I  say,  therefore,  that  without  making  anv  metaphysical 
assumptions,  there  is  a  region  in  which  all  metaphysical  tenets 
are  indifferent.  This  is  the  recrion  of  science:  and  thoucrh 
I  cannot  here  attempt  to  define  its  limits,  I  consider  that 
there  is  at  least  a  presumption  that  some  of  the  moral  ques- 
tions of  which  we  are  to  speak,  fall  fairly  within  this  region, 
and  thus  within  a  region  to  which  the  ordinary  scientific 
methods  are  applicable.  In  order  that  we  may  reach  a 
scientific  conclusion  in  the  sense  here  suggested,  two  con- 
ditions are  necessary.  The  first  is  that  with  which  we  have 
been  dealing,  namely,  that  we  should  be  able  to  discover  rela- 
tions that  are  unaffected  by  the  metaphysical  elements  which 
they  contain,  which  shall  be  true  so  far  as  they  go,  whatever 
our  metaphysical  theories.  I  do  not  dwell  longer  upon 
this  question,  because  the  most  satisfactory  way  of  showing 
that  it  can  be  complied  with,  is  to  comply  with  it;  that  is, 
to  lay  down  propositions  to  which,  in  fact,  metaphysical 
inquiries  are  plainly  irrelevant.  And  this  I  shall  attempt  in 
the  following  pages.  But  there  is  another  condition  upon 
which  I  must  dwell  more  fully.  Scientific  knowledge  means 
simply  that  part  of  knowledge  which  is  definitive  and 
capable  of  accurate  expression.     It  is  merely  the  crystallised 


8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

core  of  the  vagi;ue  mass  of  indefinite  and  inaccurate  knovvlcdire. 
It  reaches  the  highest  or  most  strictly  scientific  stage  when  it 
admits  of  being  stated  in  precise  propositions  of  unconditional 
vaUdity.     By  unconditional,  I  mean,  of  course,  that  the  con- 
ditions  under  which  it  holds  are  given  in  the  proposition 
itself.     It  may  be  as  much  a  scientific  truth  that  all  mam- 
malia are  air-breathing  animals  as  that  all  particles  of  matter 
gravitate  to  each  other.     It  is  not  necessary  for  the  scientific 
character  of  the  proposition  that  the  existence  of  mammalia 
should  be  unconditional,  but  only  that  the  existence  of  one 
property  should  be  the  sole  and  sufHcient  condition  for  the 
existence  of  the  other.     But  this   unconditionality  and   pre- 
cision represents   an  ideal  which  is  seldom  if  ever  realised; 
and  propositions  are  generally  called  scientific  which  make 
some  approximation  to  this  quality.    They  are  approximately 
scientific  when  they  are   precise  enough   to  afford  a  gener- 
ally reliable   rule,  and    require   conditions  which   are  gener- 
ally fulfilled ;  or,    in  other   words,  when   they   do  not  fully 
reveal   and   formulate   a  "law   of  nature,"   but  make   some 
approximation    to    that   completeness    of    statement.      We 
should  not  call  the  proposition  "  Mothers  love  their  children  " 
a  scientific   proposition   in   the   highest  sense,  because   it   is 
incapable   of  precise   statement   as  an   unconditional    truth. 
Some   mothers   do   not   love   their  children.     We   have   no 
means  of  giving  any  quantitative  measure  of  the  passion  of 
love,  and  when  we  compare   this  statement  with  a  purely 
scientific  statement — as,  for  example,  that  gravitation  varies 
inversely  as    the    square    of  the    distance — we  are  at  once 
sensible  that  our  formula  falls   altogether  short  of  the  re- 
quirements of  science  as  we  understand  it  in  other  branches 
of  inquiry.     Still  the  statement  presumablv  includes  an  ap- 
proximation to  son)e  scientific  truth,  and  it  is  worth  while 
to  consider  how   far  it   may    be   rendered   scientific,  for  in 
the  endeavour  we  shall  throw  some  light  upon  the  problem 
before  us. 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE. 


II.  Difficulty  of  Moral  Science. 

8.  I  shall  only  touch  in  the  briefest  way  upon  one  objection 
to  the  possibility  of  a  scientific  treatment  of  moral  questions 
which  would  be  fatal,  could  it  be  sustained.  I  refer  to  the 
objection  founded  upon  the  doctrine  of  the  so-called  freedom 
of  the  will.  I  must  decline  to  enter  upon  a  controversy 
already  thrashed  out  to  the  very  last  fragments  of  chaff.  It 
is  enough  in  such  a  case  to  indicate  one's  own  position,  and 
to  refer  for  the  arguments  by  which  it  may  be  supported  to 
the  innumerable  writers  who  have  considered  it  at  length. 
Hereafter,  indeed,  I  shall  be  obliged  to  say  something  of 
the  questions  under  another  aspect.  For  the  present,  I 
may  observe  that  the  theory  of  free  will  is  relevant  so  far 
as  it  affects  or  is  supposed  to  affect  what  has  been  called 
the  universal  postulate.  In  all  reasoning  about  facts,  this 
postulate,  whatever  its  true  nature,  must  be  invariably 
assumed.  Whether  we  speak  of  the  uniformity  of  nature, 
or  of  the  principle  of  sufficient  reason,  or  of  the  universality 
of  causation,  we  are  adopting  different  phrases  to  signify  the 
same  thing.  To  me,  indeed,  it  appears  that  the  theorem,  in 
whatever  form  it  may  be  most  fitly  expressed,  is  not  so  much 
a  distinct  proposition,  the  truth  or  falsehood  of  which  can  be 
discussed,  as  an  attempt  to  formulate  the  intrinsic  process  of  all 
such  reasoninjr.  Unless  we  assume  that  identical  inferences  can 
be  made  from  identical  facts  we  are  simply  unable  to  reason 
at  all.  The  alternative  to  making  the  assumption  is  not  to 
admit  some  other  possibility,  but  to  cease  to  think.  If  there 
is  nothing  arbitrary  in  nature;  if  a  thing  can  at  once  be  and 
not  be ;  or  if  the  same  cause  may  produce  different  effects,  the 
very  nerve  of  every  reasoning  process  is  paralysed.  We  can 
no  more  argue  as  to  phenomena  than  we  can  make  a  formal 
svllogism  if  we  suppose  that  contradictory  propositions  are 
not  mutually  exclusive.  Further,  I  can  see  no  ground  what- 
ever for  excluding  the  case  of  human  conduct.  I  infer  a 
man's  actions  from  his  character  and  circumstances,  or  his 


lo  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

character  from  his  actions  with  the  same  confidence  as  I  infer 
the  path  of  a  planet  from  the  known  determining  forces,  or  the 
forces  from  the  path.  If  two  men  act  differently  there  must 
be  some  corresponding  difference  in  the  character  or  circum- 
stances, as  if  two  bodies  produce  different  reactions  there 
must  be  some  corresponding  difference  in  their  chemical  com- 
position. Now,  if  the  doctrine  of  free  will  be  inconsistent 
with  this  theory,  I  must  simply  say  that  I  reject  it.  If  it  be 
consistent  with  the  theory,  I  have  at  present  nothing  more 
to  do  with  it:  for  it  is  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  inconsistent  that 
it  affects  the  possibility  of  a  scientific  treatment  of  ethics.  1 
shall  only  add  that,  in  any  case,  to  reason  about  conduct  is  to 
assume  that  it  is  determinate.  If  actions  be  intrinsically 
arbitrary,  or  in  so  far  as  they  are  arbitrary,  a  theory  of  action 
must  be  a  contradiction  in  terms.  And  thus,  as  it  has  been 
said,  that  whether  we  are  or  are  not  free,  we  must  act  as 
though  we  were  free,  I  may  say  that  whether  conduct  be  or 
be  not  determinate,  we  must  reason  about  it  as  though  it 
were  determinate. 

9.  Passing  over  this  difficulty,  the  question  still  remains, 
\vhether  any  science  of  human  nature  be  possible  in  any  other 
sense  than  this :  that  its  existence  does  not  imply  a  contradic- 
tion in  terms.  We  have  already  the  names  of  such  sciences 
as  sociology  and  psychology.  Are  they  anything  more  than 
names,  or  is  there  any  reason  to  suppose  that  they  will  ever 
be  anything  more  ?  These  problems  are  not  impossible  in 
the  sense  in  which  the  problem  of  perpetual  motion  is  im- 
possible; for  there  is  an  answer  to  them,  if  only  we  could 
find  or  express  it;  but  they  may  be  impossible,  in  the  sense  in 
which  it  is  impossible  for  an  infant  just  learning  arithmetic 
to  calculate  the  movements  of  a  planet.  It  can  be  made 
intelligible  to  him  that  the  proposed  operation  has  a  meaning 
and  an  answer  for  more  developed  minds ;  but  even  an 
approximate  calculation  is  altogether  beyond  his  powers. 
At  present  the  so-called  sciences  consist  of  nothing  more 
than  a  collection  of  unverified  guesses  and  vague  generalisa- 
tions, disguised  under  a  more  or  less  pretentious  apparatus  of 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE.  n 

quasi-scientific  terminology.     Can  they  ever  be  made  precise 
and  certain  ? 

lo.  It  is  easy  to  show  how  far  we  are  at  present  from  any 
such  consummation.  The  accepted  test  of  true  scientific 
knowledge  is  a  power  of  prediction.  In  the  typical  science  of 
astronomy  that  test  has  been  satisfied.  We  can  trace  back- 
wards and  forwards  through  many  ages  the  series  of  pheno- 
mena of  the  solar  system.  That  we  can  do  so  is  owinci-  to 
the  simplicity  of  the  data  and  the  conditions.  Given  the 
law  of  gravitation  and  the  masses  and  initial  position  of  two 
moving  bodies,  we  can  apply  our  formulae  and  work  out  their 
movements.  Yet  even  for  this  typical  science  it  required 
a  vast  genius,  and  such  a  genius  inheriting  the  labours  of 
many  generations  of  careful  observation  and  acute  reasoning, 
to  work  out  the  elementary  problem.  Complicate  the  con- 
ditions in  the  slightest  deo-ree,  add  the  attraction  of  another 
body,  and  the  problem  becomes  so  unmanageable  that  the 
severest  labours  of  the  acutest  minds,  during  generations  of 
unparalleled  progress,  are  unable  to  give  us  more  than  an 
approximate  solution.  The  law  which  is  embodied  in  the 
movements  of  a  planet  lies,  so  to  speak,  on  the  surface  of 
things;  it  is  given  in  the  greatest  simplicity  with  the 
minimum  of  over-ridino;  and  conflictino-  influences:  and 
therefore  it  is  that  we  are  able  so  far  to  disentangle  the 
phenomena  and  reach  an  applicable  result.  In  other  cases, 
we  have  to  perform  a  process  of  abstraction  which  is  here 
done  to  our  hands.  Elsewhere  we  can  obtain  simple  rules  only 
by  disregarding  the  heterogeneous  mass  of  modifying  circum- 
stances with  which  the  simple  process  is  inextricably  involved 
hi  concrete  cases.  And  therefore  we  can  only  obtain  cer- 
tainty of  prediction  when  we  can  ourselves  so  modify  circum- 
stances as  to  make  them  correspond  to  our  ideal  constructions. 
We  can  make  a  conditional  prediction  in  regard  to  many 
concrete  events;  we  can  say  that  such  and  such  processes 
will  develop  themselves  if  no  interference  takes  place  from 
without ;  or  we  can  predict  if  we  are  able  to  obviate  the  risk 
of  such  interferences.     We  can  be  sure  of  an  experiment  in 


12  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

a  laboratory,  but  our  knowledge  in  regard  to  any  series  of 
events  not  voluntarily  prepared  is  limited  by  the  constant 
possibility  of  the  interference  of  conditions  which  we  have 
not  foreseen  or  are  unable  to  appreciate.  And,  thus,  even 
where  science  is  most  perfect,  our  powers  of  proving  it  are 
as  a  rule  bound  within  narrow  limits. 

II.  Is  it  not,  then,  a  mockery  to  join  in  one  phrase  such 
■words  as  science  and  human  nature?  Will  Caesar  cross  the 
Rubicon  ?  The  problem  is  as  determinate  as  the  problem. 
Will  a  projectile  fall  on  the  hither  or  the  further  bank  ?  But 
consider  for  a  moment  the  conditions  which  must  be  taken 
into  account  in  a  solution.  We  must  know  the  whole  range 
of  operative  forces  which  will  allow  play  for  his  will  to  act,  and 
therefore  have  some  neoative  information  at  least  as  to  the  uni- 
verse  at  large ;  we  must  know  what  are  the  political,  social, 
geographical  circumstances  which  may  possibly  affect  his  de- 
cisions; we  must  know,  again,  how  these  complex  facts 
mirror  themselves  in  his  mind;  what  are  his  calculations,  his 
ambitions,  prejudices,  hopes  and  fears;  we  must  know  even 
what  freaks  of  memory  or  sudden  associations  of  names 
and  incidents  may  stir  the  current  of  his  meditations;  we 
must  understand  the  laws  of  his  character,  and  how  it 
depends  upon  the  state  of  his  liver,  his  digestion  and  the 
electric  tension  of  the  atmosphere ;  for  "  character "  is  the 
name  of  an  undecipherable  mass  of  sensibilities,  inherited  and 
acquired  habits  of  reasoning  and  feeling,  changing  from  day 
to  day,  baffling  all  calculations  and  eluding  the  shrewdest 
observer.  The  wiliest  diplomatist  trusts  to  crude  generalisa- 
tions, which  fail  as  often  as  they  are  verified;  our  most 
confident  anticipations  of  the  friend  whom  we  knew  to  his 
heart's  core  are  put  out  by  a  toothache  or  a  grain  of  sand  in 
the  wrong  place ;  history  is  a  record  of  "  fears  of  the  brave 
and  follies  of  the  wise,"  of  confident  anticipations  falsified, 
and  revelations  of  character  which  astonish  no  one  more 
than  the  agent  himself.  Is  it  not  as  futile  to  apply  the  name 
of  science  to  our  guesses  about  the  shifting  and  uncompre- 
hensible  network   of  thouoht   and    feeling  which   makes  a 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE.  13 

character  as  to  give  it  to  the  vague  guesses  of  a  shepherd  who 
hopes  a  fine  morrow  from  a  red  sunset?  Even  the  "scien- 
tific" meteorologist  can  scarcely  foretell  a  day's  weather;  and 
vet  his  problem  is  simple  and  his  knowledge  accurate  when 
compared  with  the  vague  surmises  which  we  dignify  by  the 
name  of  sciences  of  human  nature. 

13.  But  let   us  look   a  little  closer.     We  are  pitching  our 
standard  too  high.     The  test   of  predicting  the  result  of  any 
concrete  set  of  processes  is,  as  I  have  said,  rarely  if  ever  satis- 
fied.   There  is  always  the  tacit  condition,  that  no  interference 
will  take  place  with  our  assumed  data.     I  know  that  a  stone 
thrown  into  the  air  will  descend  ;  I  can  calculate  its  path 
with    minute    accuracv,  and    define  its    range    and  velocity. 
But  this  is,   of  course,  upon   the   hypothesis  that   it  meets 
with    no    obstruction.       As    every    event    in    the    universe 
may  be  said  to  be  more  or  less  connected  with   every  other 
event,  it  is   plain  that  this    condition  can  rarely  be  secured 
with   absolute    certainty.      But    I    do    not  refuse  the  name 
of  science  to  the  general    propositions  which  enable  me   to 
make  this  conditional    prediction.       On  the  contrary,   they 
form  the  great  mass  of  scientific  knowledge.    We  must,  there- 
fore, consider  more  closely  how  far  we  can  discover  such  rules 
about    human    conduct.      It   is    impossible   to   say   whether 
Ceesar  will  or  will  not  pass  the  Rubicon.      It  may  be  pos- 
sible   to    sav  that    most  men    would   or    would  not    cross ; 
or,  asrain,  to  sav  that  Caesar  will  cross  under  certain  conditions, 
which  again  may  correspond   to   the  conditions   most    com- 
monly fulfilled,  and  which  may  therefore  give  a  certain  de- 
gree of  very  useful   knowledge.     We  may  make  some  such 
statements  with  absolute  confidence.      Man,  so  far  as  he  is  a 
ump  of  matter,  obeys  certain  mechanical  laws.     Throw  him 
out  of  a  window,  and  he  will  fall  as  though  he  were  a  lump 
of  lead  or  a  corpse.     Chemical  changes  may  be  worked  in 
his  tissues  as  assignable  as  though  he  were  simply  a  gas  or  a 
salt.     So  far  as  he  is  a  living  organism,  we  have  to  consider 
another  set  of  conditions.     He  is  the  embodiment  of  a  set  of 
processes  which  are  always  taking  place,  and  which  are  not 


14  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tlcduciblc  from  the  external  circumstances.  To  know  how  he 
will  act,  we  must  sometimes  know  at  what  stage  they  happen 
to  be.  When  he  is  thrown  out  of  a  window,  this  considera- 
tion is  irrelevant.  If  we  want  to  know  how  he  will  act  when 
food  is  presented  to  him,  they  become  relevant.  We  must 
know  whether  he  is  hungry  or  satisfied,  awake  or  asleep,  and 
so  forth.  But  further,  as  he  reasons  and  has  motives,  he  res- 
ponds to  any  external  stimulus  after  a  more  complex  fashion. 
His  actions  are  regulated  not  only  by  the  immediate  action  of 
his  senses,  but  by  innumerable  anticipations  of  the  future, 
recollections  of  the  past,  and  inferences  as  to  distant  objects. 
So  far  as  he  is  a  thing  or  an  animal,  it  is  comparativ^ely  easv 
to  determine  his  conduct.  Given  a  starvino;  doo-  and  a 
lump  of  meat  in  contact,  and  vou  can  predict  the  result. 
But  to  determine  the  behaviour  of  a  human  being  with  a  glass 
of  water  presented*  to  his  parching  lips,  vou  must  be  in  posses- 
sion of  an  oro;anon  for  calculating;  the  action  of  human  motive, 
and  be  able  to  unravel  the  tanoled  skein  of  thought  and  feel- 
ing  which  varies  enormously  from  one  man  to  another,  and 
is  determined  by  innumerable  subtle  influences,  each  of  which 
sets  all  calculation  at  defiance. 

13.  7\)  attack  such  problems  as  these,  we  require  some 
tenable  psychology.  We  may  say  that  conduct  is  determined 
by  pain  and  pleasure.  W^e  may  repeat  all  the  little  maxims 
which  have  been  made  popular  by  the  observers  of  human 
character.  But,  to  gain  anvthing  like  scientific  knowledge, 
we  require  some  mode  of  estimating  these  pains  and  pleasures, 
and  the  faculties  to  which  they  appeal.  If  we  had  but  a 
sincrle  passion,  if  we  were  only  locomotive  stomachs  like  a 
polyp,  the  problem  would  be  simple.  But  man  is  a  complex 
of  numerous  passions,  a  little  hierarchy  of  conflicting,  co- 
operating, mutually  interacting  emotions,  which  it  is  simply 
impossible  to  tabulate  and  measure.  Numerous  classifica- 
tions have  been  made  by  acute  observers.  Yet  I  do  not 
suppose  that  anv  of  these  can  be  regarded  as  more  than  a 
rouah  account  of  the  most  obvious  facts.  To  ask  which  are 
the  primitive  and  elementary  passions,  how  they  are  related. 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE.  15 

and  how  the  derivative  passions  are  compounded,  is  to  ask 
questions  which  admit  of  no  definite  answer.  We  are  simply 
feeling  about  in  the  dark  ;  putting  rough  guesses  into  preten- 
tious shapes,  or  dressing  poetical  symbols  in  the  language  of 
science;  but  we  are  far,  indeed,  from  anything  which  can 
for  a  moment  deserve  our  confidence  as  a  scientific  analysis. 

14.  If,  again,  we  could  rely  upon  any  such  analysis,  we 
should  still  be  at  the  very  outset  of  our  task.  Who  can  say 
what  is  the  relative  importance  of  the  various  parties  in  the 
little  internal  parliament  which  determines  our  policy  from 
one  moment  to  another,  or  by  what  subtle  and  inscrutable 
ties  they  are  connected?  Take,  for  example,  the  simple 
physical  appetite  of  hunger.  No  doubt  hunger  determines 
many  human  activities,  and  we  have  a  strong  probability  that 
a  hungry  man  will  eat  when  he  has  a  chance.  But  how  are 
we  to  say  what  felt  hunger  will  play  in  any  given  organisa- 
tion? What  are  the  conditions,  external  or  internal,  which 
determine  its  strength  and  its  influence  upon  our  actions? 
It  depends  upon  innumerable  and  indefinable  conditions ; 
upon  the  state  of  the  constitution  ;  the  condition  of  the  palate, 
and  upon  the  various  habits  which  we  have  acquired.  It 
may  be  suspended  entirely  by  grief,  or  by  the  affection  of 
some  bodily  organ  not  obviously  or  normally  concerned  in 
deteijmining  its  strength.  Under  certain  conditions  it  be- 
comes an  overpowering  impulse,  capable  of  overcoming  every 
moral  and  prudential  restraint.  It  causes  mothers  to  desert 
their  children,  and  breaks  up  the  bonds  of  the  discipline  which 
has  become  a  second  nature.  Under  other  circumstances,  it 
loses  all  power.  The  glutton  turns  with  loathing  from  the 
food  which  enthralled  him  a  moment  before,  not  merely  if  he 
is  satiated,  but  in  obedience  to  some  accidental  association 
which  has  called  up  a  spasm  of  disgust.  What  is  true  of 
hunger  is  even  more  obviously  true  of  the  higher  and  intel- 
lectual emotions,  of  which  we  can  only  say  that  their  com- 
position is  apparently  complex  in  the  highest  degree,  and  the 
relation  to  other  parts  of  the  system  vitally  important  and 
yet  hopelessly  obscure.     So,  again,  if  we  know  something  of 


-16  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  constituent  passions,  we  should  still  have  to  investigate 
the  laws  of  what  may  be  called  mental  perspective.  It  is  a 
familiar  fact,  that  the  intensity  of  a  passion  varies  in  some 
way  with  the  proximity  of  the  appropriate  object.  The 
prospect  of  a  pain  at  a  certain  distance  scarcely  affects  us  at 
all,  though  we  may  be  perfectly  convinced  of  its  approach; 
and  the  immediate  prospect  of  the  same  pain  may  be  over- 
powering. A  man  may  be  utterly  indifferent  when  he  knows 
that  he  is  to  be  hanged  to-morrow,  and  yet  be  a  hopeless 
coward  on  the  gallows.  His  neighbour  may  tremble  at  the  re- 
mote prospect,  and  yet  meet  death  with  all  imaginable  courage. 
The  law,  according;:  to  which  distance  diminishes  the  corre- 
sponding  feeling  is  inscrutable  In  itself,  and  varies  according 
to  inscrutable  differences  of  temperament.  And  again, 
pains  and  pleasures  of  different  classes  vary  in  this  intrinsic 
power  of  calling  up  the  premonitory  foretaste.  A  purely 
physical  enjoyment,  intense  at  the  moment  of  fruition,  Is 
often  unintelligible  in  the  absence  of  the  immediate  condi- 
tions. A  drunkard  can  easily  deny  himself  his  pleasures  in 
prospect,  and  yet  may  be  impotent  in  the  presence  of  tempta- 
tion. At  a  distance  the  dlssfrace  of  drunkenness  is  strono-er 
than  the  appetite  for  drink.  When  the  drink  Is  at  hand 
the  appetite  overpowers  the  most  vivid  sense  of  degrada- 
tion. The  same  is  equally  true  of  the  higher  motives. 
A  man  habitually  careless  of  duty  and  little  inclined  to 
benevolence  may  be  capable,  at  moments  of  excitement,  of 
heroic  self-sacrifice.  He  may,  like  Falstaff,  make  a  mock  of 
honour  when  he  is  cool,  and  yet  when  under  the  stress  of 
immediate  shame  may  throw  away  life  rather  than  break  a 
code  of  honour  which  he  regards  as  ridiculous. 

15.  To  mention  one  more  familiar  difficulty — for  I  am 
saying  nothing  which  has  not  been  a  commonplace  with  all 
observers — I  have  hitherto  spoken  as  though  we  always  acted 
upon  some  conscious  motive.  But  in  a  large  part  of  our  lives 
we  are  mere  automata.  We  go  through  many,  perhaps 
most,  of  our  dally  occupations  with  little  more  consciousness 
than   a  machine;  and   therefore  it    is  impossible  to  foretell 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE.  17 

whether  a  given  passion  will  or  will  not  operate  under  certain 
circumstances.  Were  a  man's  consciousness  always  awake  to 
all  the  consequences  of  his  actions,  we  could  say  that  he 
would  act  in  a  certain  way.  But  consciousness  acts  fitfully ; 
it  goes  to  sleep  or  rouses  itself  in  obedience  to  conditions 
which  we  are  unable  to  assign.  A  man  would  act  in  one 
way  if  the  results  of  the  action  were  present  to  his  mind,  but 
he  acts  in  another  way  simply  because  it  is  easiest  for  him  to 
act  to-day  as  he  happened  to  act  yesterday,  l^he  momentum 
of  his  past  life  causes  him  to  continue  in  the  groove  in  which 
he  has  placed  himself.  We  are  therefore  unable  to  infer 
conduct  from  character  unless  we  know  what  are  those 
accidental  chains  by  which  it  is  bound.  A  man  gives  money 
or  savs  his  prayers,  not  because  he  is  charitable  or  devout, 
but  because  he  has  been  brought  up  to  do  so.  Thus  the 
data  from  which  his  conduct  must  be  calculated  include  not 
only  his  true  character  but  the  special  circumstances  of  his  life. 
His  conduct  is  probably  a  kind  of  diagonal  between  that 
which  would  be  dictated  by  his  instincts  when  fully  conscious 
and  that  which  is  determined  by  another  independent  set  of 
causes.  If  he  were  purely  mechanical  or  purely  rational  in 
his  actions,  we  could  predict  his  behaviour;  but  he  is  alter- 
nately one  and  the  other,  and  passes  fitfully  from  the  automatic 
to  the  conscious  stage  in  obedience  to  conditions  which  alto- 
gether elude  our  powers  of  observation. 

16.  The  conduct  of  man  is  as  much  dependent  upon  his 
moral  and  mental  orcjanisation  as  the  various  reactions  of  a 
body  upon  its  chemical  composition.  To  make  this  general 
admission  the  ground  of  a  science,  we  must  know  something 
more.  We  must  know  what  are  the  elementary  faculties; 
what  their  relative  stren2;th ;  what  relations  hold  amonirst 
them  in  virtue  of  the  unity  of  the  subject ;  and  what  are  the 
laws  by  which  they  respond  to  any  given  stimulus,  come 
into  the  foreground  of  conscious  motive,  and  again  pass  for  a 
time  out  of  sight,  to  leave  blind  habits  to  occupy  their  vacant 
places.  And  upon  such  points  we  are  in  ignorance  so  profound, 
that,  far  from  knowing  the  answers  to   our  questions,  we 

B 


1 8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

scarcely  know  how  to  put  them  intelligibly.  If  our  psycho- 
logical armoury  is  so  scantily  provided,  can  we  find  effective 
weapons  in  the  nascent  science  of  sociology?  Can  we  reach 
certainty  by  studying  the  social  instead  of  the  individual 
organism  ?  We  do  not,  as  might  at  first  seem  probable,  find 
that  the  difficulties  increase  in  proportion  to  the  extent  of 
the  field  of  observation.  We  can  often  lay  down  trustworthy 
propositions  in  regard  to  an  aggregate  or  an  organic  whole 
when  we  know  little  of  the  sejmrate  parts.  We  can  deter- 
mine the  properties  of  a  body  though  we  should  find  it  hope- 
less to  trace  the  movements  of  a  particular  molecule;  and  the 
idiosyncrasies  which  make  the  study  of  individual  character 
so  perplexing  neutralise  each  other,  or  become  unimportant 
when  we  are  dealing  with  a  whole  society.  But  this  only 
proves  that  the  difficulties  do  not  increase  in  a  compound 
ratio;  it  does  not  show  that  they  are  actually  less.  In 
truth,  when  we  have  to  deal  with  a  societv,  and  try  to 
tabulate  and  to  measure  the  forces  by  which  it  is  held  to- 
gether, we  find  ourselves  in  presence  of  perplexities  resem- 
bling those  which  beset  our  psychology,  whilst  the  vastness 
of  the  data  required  and  the  indefinite  possibilities  of 
:hange  introduce  other  and  apparently  insoluble  problems. 
What  is  the  relation,  for  example,  between  the  religious 
creed  of  a  nation  and  its  political  sentiments?  What  is  the 
force  of  the  selfish  or  antisocial  passion,  and  the  force  which 
restrains  it  within  such  bounds  as  are  consistent  with  order  ? 
What  are  the  conditions  of  moral  and  intellectual  progress, 
and  what  will  be  the  probable  action  of  any  new  belief,  or  of 
a  chanjre  introduced  in  the  material  conditions  of  life?  To 
ask  such  questions  is  to  suggest  the  extreme  vagueness  of  all 
our  guesses  and  the  immense  complexity  of  the  problem.  I 
need  not  say  how  shortsighted  are  the  ablest  statesmen,  and 
how  constantly  that  which  happens  is  precisely  the  one  thing 
which  nobody  foresaw,  but  which,  after  the  event,  appears  to 
have  been  just  what  every  one  should  have  foreseen.  What 
will   be   the  effect  of  tcachinc;  readino;  or  writino;  ?     If  the 


DIFFICULTY  OF  MORAL  SCIENCE.  19 

question  be  asked  in  regard  to  an  individual,  we  are  perplexed 
because  the  variability  of  character  and  understanding  makes 
it  difficult  to  judge  of  the  effect  upon  a  given  intellect.  We 
can  speak  more  confidently  of  the  average  effect,  because  the 
individual  variations  will  correct  each  other  when  we  are 
dealing  with  a  mass.  But  when  we  ask  the  further  question, 
in  what  way  this  ascertainable  effect  (we  suppose  it  to  be 
ascertainable)  will  react  upon  the  whole  social  structure?  we 
have  another  set  of  problems  of  the  most  intricate  kind. 
Will  the  increase  of  knowledge  make  men  content  or  dis- 
contented ?  Will  it  confirm  or  shake  the  beliefs  upon  which 
the  social  order  depends?  Will  it  simply  strengthen  the 
impulse  towards  a  higher  culture,  or  will  it  also  increase  the 
tendency  to  self-indulgence  and  weaken  the  bonds  of  discip- 
line ?  If  we  can  give  some  vague  answer  to  such  questions, 
it  is  clearly  not  such  an  answer  as  can  be  called  scientific,  or 
as  enables  us  to  give  any  definite  prediction  of  results.  It  is 
difficult  to  predict  what  will  be  the  effect  of  special  circum- 
stances upon  an  individual;  but  if  the  society  of  which  he  is 
a  member  remains  approximately  unaltered,  we  can  give  a 
fair  guess  as  to  the  probable  consequences  of  an  ascertained 
modification  of  his  character.  But  that  which  is  a  very  slight 
change  in  each  individual  may  involve  a  vast  and  incalcul- 
able alteration  in  the  social  equilibrium  when  we  suppose 
that  a  whole  class  is  affected  and  the  conditions  of  national 
life  modified  through  its  whole  extent.  When  we  reflect 
upon  the  extreme  difficulty  of  obtaining  the  necessary  know- 
ledge, of  appreciating  the  state  of  mind  of  millions  of  men, 
of  discovering  the  latent  passions  which  may  be  smouldering 
amonirst  them,  their  state  of  accessibilitv  to  new  ideas  and 
new  conditions  of  life,  we  may  well  feel  the  untrustworthiness 
of  our  so-called  scientific  methods.  The  discovery  of  a  new 
principle  in  mechanics  or  the  promulgation  of  a  new  reli- 
gious creed  may  alter  the  whole  social  state  or  bring  about 
political  and  social  convulsions.  But  how  can  we  predict 
new  discoveries  or  new  creeds  ?  To  foretell  a  discovery  is  to 
make  the  discovery  yourself,  and  to  make  it  before  its  time. 


20  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

To  foretell  the  new  creed  is  to  be  yourself  the  potential  religious 
reformer ;  and  to  foretell  the  effect  of  both  upon  the  society 
in  which  they  are  promulgated  is  to  trace  out  a  complex  series 
of  actions  and  reactions,  to  appreciate  the  state  of  mind  of 
masses  of  men,  and  the  mode  in  which  they  will  be  affected 
by  a  given  thought,  and^  moreover,  to  be  provided  with  a 
quantity  of  information  as  to  facts  for  which  there  can  hardly 
be  room  in  any  individual  brain.  Any  one  who  should  have 
prophesied  the  history  of  the  present  century  at  its  beginning 
with  any  precision  would  have  had  himself  to  foresee  the 
course  of  science,  the  attitude  taken  by  the  greatest  thinkers, 
the  influence  upon  men's  imaginations  of  new  conceptions  of 
the  world,  and  to  have  traced  out  an  incalculable  series  of 
chang-es  in  the  relations  of  classes,  and  to  determine  the  effect 
of  all  these  changes  upon  the  material  conditions  of  existence. 
Any  shortcoming  might  omit  some  essential  point.  In  short, 
the  prediction  of  the  course  of  history,  even  in  general  terms 
and  for  a  brief  period,  would  require  an  intellect  at  least  as 
much  superior  to  that  of  a  Socrates  as  the  intellect  of  a 
Socrates  is  superior  to  that  of  an  ape.  Indeed,  we  may  say  the 
greater  the  intellectual  development,  the  greater  is  the  difficulty 
of  foreseeincr  the  results  which  the  intellect  will  obtain.  And 
therefore  there  is  a  kind  of  natural  limit  to  the  development 
of  the  powers  of  human  nature.  For  as  the  intellect  becomes 
more  capable  of  grappling  with  the  old  problems,  the  com- 
plexity of  the  problems  presented  tends  itself  to  increase. 

17.  I  have  dwelt  upon  such  considerations  partly  to 
illustrate  the  nature  of  the  difficulty,  and  partly  to  obviate 
the  impression  that  in  using  the  word  "  science  "  I  supposed 
that  a  science  of  human  nature  could  either  now  or  at  any 
future  time  make  any  approach  to  the  accuracy  or  certainty 
of  the  physical  sciences.  A  shorter  road  to  the  same  con- 
clusion might  have  been  taken  by  simply  challenging  be- 
lievers, if  such  there  be,  in  such  sciences,  to  produce  any  pro- 
position which  possesses,  or  even  claims,  the  same  sort  of 
authority  as  belongs  to  the  doctrines  of  a  fully  constituted 
science,  or  to  justify  such  claims  by  adducing  any  instance 


ATTAINABLE  RESULTS.  21 

of  scientific  prevision.  But  I  do  not  anticipate  any  serious 
objections  to  this  part  of  the  argument,  and  it  is  perhaps 
more  important  to  consider  the  more  positive  results.  We 
have  briefly  surveyed  the  ground  upon  which  our  super- 
structure is  to  be  reared,  with  the  result,  so  far^  that  it  is  too 
treacherous  and  unstable  to  bear  any  solid  edifice.  Let  us 
consider  next  whether  anv  trustworthy  space  is  left  after  all 
these  deductions,  and  what  kind  of  confidence  may  fairly  be 
challenged  for  any  philosophic  construction. 

III.  Attainable  Results. 

1 8.  After  all  that  has  been  said,  it  must  be  admitted,  as  I  have 
incidentally  admitted,  that  we  do  in  fact  possess  a  consider- 
able deo-ree  of  knowled<re  as  to  the  conduct  of  our  fellow- 
creatures.     A   confidence  that    our   neighbours  will    act   in 
accordance  with  certain  anticipations  is  essential  to  almost 
every   part  of  our   conduct.     I    do    not    carry  weapons   in 
London  now,  as  I  should   carry  them  in  barbarous  towns, 
because   I   am   as    certain    that   the   passengers  will   behave 
peaceably  as  I  am  that  the  houses  will  not  fall  on  my  head. 
I  trust  my  whole  fortune  with  complete  confidence  to  my 
bankers  or  lawyers,  because,  though  I  know  that  there  are 
such  thincTs  as  knavish  men  of  business,  the  risk  is  not  ereat 
enough  to  afiect  my  conduct.     I  act  as  confidently  upon  the 
assumption  that  mothers  love  their    children  as   upon  the 
assumption  that  London  Bridge  will  bear  the  weight  of  the 
passing  crowds.     I  have  as  little  doubt  that  a  toothache  or 
a  liver  complaint  will  diminish  a  man's  happiness  as  I  have 
that   a   stone   is    indigestible.     Moreover,    such    knowledge 
sometimes   reaches  a    hioh    decree   of  discrimination.     The 
great  dramatist,  we  say,  knows  the  human  heart ;  he  does  not 
know  it  as  the  man  of  science  knows  the  properties  of  a 
chemical  compound;  that  is,  he  cannot  draw  out  any  specific 
set  of  propositions  to  express  his  knowledge — he  cannot  give 
chapter  and  verse  for  his  conclusions;  but  he  can  feel,  though 
he  cannot  explain,  how  a  selfish  or  a  heroic  character  will 


22  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

think  and  act  under  given  circumstances.  His  power  over 
our  sympathies  is  proportioned  to  the  truth  of  his  divinations, 
and  therefore  to  the  degree  in  which  we  too  recognise  the 
truth  of  his  portraiture.  So  the  diplomatist  or  the  attorney 
who  watches  every  phrase  and  gesture  of  his  antagonist 
draws  conchisions  as  to  their  feelincrs  and  character  which 
are  often  of  startHns;  accuracy.  He  relies,  it  may  be,  too 
much  upon  certain  principles  which  are  frequently  inaccurate 
and  never  infallible.  He  can  assign  them  and  consider  them 
collectively  to  embody  a  knowledge  of  the  world.  And 
though  the  shrewdest  of  such  men,  statesmen,  courtiers, 
solicitors,  or  confessors,  is  liable  to  innumerable  blunders, 
the  very  capacity  of  reasoning  upon  such  matters  implies 
that  there  is  some  such  knowledo-e.     There  is,  in  fact,  a  vast 

O  7  7 

difference  in  the  acuteness  with  which  men  judge  of  character; 
and  as  some  are  acuter  than  others,  it  must  be  that  they 
have  at  least  implicit  canons  of  judgment  which  are  not 
entirely  valueless. 

19.  The  knowledge  thus  assumed  does  not  differ  in  kind 
from  scientific  knowledge.  There  is,  in  truth,  only  one 
kind  of  knowledge;  and  knowledge  gradually  passes  into  the 
scientific  state  as  it  becomes  more  definite  and  articulate. 
We  can  hardly  distinguish  in  respect  of  certainty  between 
much  of  the  knowledge  called  scientific  and  much  of  this 
floating  and  indefinite  knowledge.  A  very  vague  proposition 
may  often  give  rise  to  certai-nty  inasmuch  as  it  excludes  many 
conceivable  hypotheses.  I  do  not  know  exactly  how  long 
a  man  may  live,  but  I  am  quite  certain  that  he  will  not  live 
for  a  thousand  years.  If  I  know  a  man  to  be  a  coward, 
I  cannot  say  exactly  what  will  frighten  him,  but  I  can  be 
very  certain  that  he  would  run  away  from  a  fiery  flying 
dragon.  But  knowledge,  however  certain,  remains  in  the 
unscientific  stage  so  long  as  a  proposition  is  of  such  a  nature 
that  I  cannot  define  the  conditions  under  which  it  will  hold 
true.  My  certainty  that  a  boat  into  which  I  am  about  to 
step  will  support  my  weight  is  not  greater  than  my  certainty 
that  a  mother  will  try  to  save  her  child  from  drowning.     In 


ATTAINABLE  RESULTS.  23 

both  cases  my  knowledge  as  to  the  particular  fact  is  imme- 
diately founded  upon  a  rough  estimate  of  the  facts  before  me. 
I  rehearse  the  events  in  imagination,  and  my  imagination 
may  be  able  to  rehearse  them  accurately.  But  there  is  this 
difl'erence  :  that  in  the  case  of  the  boat  I  can  state  the  general 
conditions  of  floating  and  sinking  with  an  accuracy  which 
may  pass  for  absolute.  I  know  that  the  result  will  depend 
upon  the  relations  between  the  weight  of  the  boat  and  the 
weight  of  the  water  displaced,  and  upon  other  precisely  mea- 
surable and  ascertainable  conditions.  I  cannot  make  a  similar 
statement  in  the  case  of  the  mother.  My  psychology  aifords 
me  no  tenable  analysis  of  the  passions  called  into  play,  and 
no  measure  of  their  intensity.  There  are  such  things  as  "  un- 
natural "  mothers,  and  I  cannot  say  what  innate  sensibilities 
or  what  subsequent  culture  are  required  in  order  to  develop 
the  more  normal  intensity  of  feeling.  Thus,  though  the 
strength  of  my  conviction  in  a  given  case  may  be  fully  justifi- 
able, it  does  not  afford  a  safe  generalisation.  I  know  that 
the  rule  will  fail  occasionally,  and  I  cannot  tell  when.  If, 
therefore,  I  try  to  discover  a  principle  of  universal  validity 
under  which  the  particular  case  may  be  ranged^  I  am  at  a  loss. 
I  may,  in  my  ignorance,  be  omitting  the  essential  conditions 
and  retaining  those  which  are  contingent.  I  explain  the  sink- 
ing or  floating  of  the  boat  by  referring  to  a  theory  which,  upon 
whatever  grounds,  the  man  of  science  holds  to  be  immutably 
or  unconditionally  true.  But  I  cannot  regard  the  principle. 
Mothers  love  their  children,  as  having  this  degree  of  validity, 
as  it  is  liable  to  exceptions  and  to  limitations  dependent  upon 
some  hitherto  unknown  principle.  Thus  the  highest  degree 
of  certainty  obtainable  is  represented  by  the  assertion  that 
most  mothers,  and  not  that  all  mothers,  love  their  children. 

20.  Now  for  many  practical  purposes  this  conclusion  is 
amply  sufficient,  and  I  must  refer  for  its  logical  justification 
of  the  belief  which  it  represents  to  works  upon  the  theory  of 
induction.  In  any  case,  it  represents  one  of  those  beliefs 
upon  which  we  are  in  daily  and  hourly  reliance.  But  the 
difficulty  which   I   have  noticed  is  one  which  must  be  felt 


24  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

when  we  try  to  give  any  scientific  theory  of  human  conduct, 
and  which,  as  I  need  hardly  observe,  is  constantly  brought 
forward  against  all  empirical  systems  of  morality.     For  the 
scientific  reasoner  must  endeavour  to   show  not  only  that 
things  are  so  and  so,  but  that  they  could,  not  have  been 
otherwise.     I  do  not  mean  by  this  that  he  is  called  upon  to 
give  an  a  priori  deduction  of  the  laws  which  he  investigates. 
It  is  clear  enough,  after  my  previous  remarks,  that  this,  in 
the  case   of   psychological    inquiries    at   least,    would  be  to 
demand   impossibilities.      But   he   must  at  least  give  some 
answer  to  the  question  why  are  things  so  and  so  ?     So  long 
as  his    generalisation  merely  amounts    to   a  statement    of 
average  behaviour  of  the  phenomena,  it  does  not  give  us 
a  law.      It  does  not  tell  us  under  what  circumstances  the 
rule  will  hold  good,  or  what  would  be  the  consequences  of  a 
deflection  from   the  rule.     In  the  assumed  case,  it  is  only 
when   a  man   can   tell  us,  however  va2:uelv,  what  are  the 
conditions  of  maternal  love,  or  what  organic  change  is  im- 
plied by  its  absence,  that  we  approach  a  scientific  theory  of 
the  passions.     It  is  just  this  question  which  is  made  so  diffi- 
cult by  the  absence  of  any  tenable   psychology.     The  bare 
fact  that,  according  to  our  experience,  maternal  love  is  the 
rule,  does  not  enable  us  to  say  whether  it  is  a  mere  accident, 
or  fashion,  something  which   might   be    present   or  absent 
without  any  material  difference,  or,  on   the   other  hand,  a 
passion  rooted  in  deepest  grounds  of  human  nature,  and  only 
to  be  removed  by  a  radical  alteration  in  the  whole  organic 
system.     In  short,  human  nature,  vipon  this  first  superficial 
examination,  seems  to  be  a  mere  aggregate  of  faculties  which 
take  one  form  at  one  moment  and  another  at  the  next,  but 
which  does  not  afford  a  sufficiently  plain  ground  for  scientific 
inquiry. 

31.  Without  asking  at  present  how  far  this  affects  any 
ethical  system,  I  may  next  observe  that  the  diflSculty  is 
sometimes  attacked  by  simply  extending  the  area  of  observa- 
tion  or  increasing  its  accuracv.     The  facts  of  conduct  are, 


it  is  suggested,  determinable,  and  determinable  with  a  great 


ATTAINABLE  RESULTS.  25 

dcoree  of  accuracy.  Little  as  we  know  of  the  psvcho- 
lo'TV  of  maternal  love,  we  may  discover,  by  simply  counting, 
what  proportion  of  mothers  commit  infanticide  in  a  given 
space  of  time,  and  we  may  prophesy  as  to  the  number  who 
will  commit  infanticide  in  a  similar  period  of  the  future. 
Relying  upon  such  facts,  we  may  pass  over  the  psychological 
difficulties  already  noticed,  or  the  metaphysical  puzzles  about 
free  will;  for  we  have  a  definite  basis  of  objective  fact,  which 
at  any  rate  supplies  us  with  many  necessary  data.  I  do  not 
for  a  moment  desire  to  under-estimate  the  importance  of  such 
a  procedure,  and  yet  it  must  be  noticed  that  it  does  not  help 
us  very  far  towards  a  solution  of  our  problem.  The  general 
fact  which  is  revealed  by  such  observations  is  one  which  we 
have  already  taken  for  granted.  It  is  proved,  for  example,  that 
the  number  of  infanticides  bears  a  fixed  proportion  to  the 
population.  If  it  were  proved,  as  people  sometimes  seem  to 
fancy,  that  this  proportion  is  always  observed  whatever  the 
social  condition  in  other  respects,  we  should  indeed  be  in 
presence  of  a  very  startling  fact.  But  it  need  hardly  be  said 
that  this  is  not  proved,  and  that  the  very  purpose  of  statistical 
inquiries  implies  a  belief  that  it  is  not  a  fact  at  all.  What 
is  proved  is  what  we  have  taken  for  granted,  namely,  that 
under  the  same  circumstances — including  both  external  cir- 
cumstances and  the  character  of  the  race — human  conduct  will 
not  alter.  This  is  the  doctrine  of  the  uniformity  of  nature, 
already  assumed  in  all  our  arguments;  and  the  utmost  that 
can  be  said  is  that  statistical  inquiry  proves  that  circumstances 
are  more  constant  than  we  might  have  supposed.  There  is 
nothing  strange  in  the  fact  of  our  guesses  on  such  matters 
turnino-  out  to  be  more  or  less  erroneous.  Our  problem, 
however,  lies  beyond  this.  We  count  the  number  of  infan- 
ticides because  we  hope  to  find  the  law  according  to  which 
the  number  varies;  to  show  how  it  depends  upon  the  density 
of  the  population,  its  comfort  or  misery,  its  state  of  civilisa- 
tion or  barbarism,  and  so  forth.  Unluckily  the  facts  which 
we  have  thus  ascertained  with  numerical  precision  only 
briniT  us  in  face  of  new  difficulties.     We  are  trying  to  find 


26  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

an  answer  to  a  very  complex  problem,  and  are  applying  what 
is  called  the  method  of  "  concomitant  variations."  It  appears, 
let  us  suppose,  that  the  number  of  infanticides  is  greater  in 
one  place  and  period  than  in  others.  Then  we  have  to  ask, 
why  is  it  greater?  And  we  immediately  discover  that  the 
relevant  conditions  are  so  numerous  and  intricate  that  we  are 
scarcely  further  advanced  than  before.  The  religious  convic- 
tions of  a  race,  its  social  arrangements,  its  state  of  material 
prosperity,  and  so  forth,  may  all  exercise  an  influence,  and  we 
are  generally  left  to  conjectures,  every  one  of  which  mio:ht 
excite  controversy.  It  may  certainly  be  doubted  whether 
any  plausible  theory  has  really  been  suggested  or  confirmed 
by  this  method ;  nor  will  this  cause  surprise  if  we  consider 
how  numerous  and  varied  are  the  experiments  necessary  to 
reveal  a  new  property  in  some  substance  capable  of  scientific 
treatment,  and  how  exceedingly  limited  is  our  power  of  trying 
scientific  experiments  upon  human  society.  The  difficulty, 
in  fact,  is  so  great,  that  the  ablest  representatives  of  empirical 
methods  have  agreed  to  give  up  the  effort  as  impracticable. 

32.  They  have  sometimes  professed  to  meet  the  difficulty 
by  a  method  illustrated  by  the  case  of  political  economy. 
We  may,  it  is  said,  discover  certain  truths  by  an  indirect 
method,  though  the  application  of  direct  methods  is  im- 
practicable. Political  economy  is  said  to  be  founded  on 
the  hypothesis  that  human  beings  are  actuated  by  the  desire 
for  wealth,  and  thus  involves  conclusions  which  are  true  so 
far  as  that  assumption  is  true.  Inversely,  therefore,  we  may 
discover  from  the  conformity  of  our  deductions  to  observed 
facts  how  far  our  primary  assumptions  were  justifiable.  To 
me  it  appears  that  the  statement  is  inaccurate.  Economists 
undoubtedly  assume  that  most  men  prefer  a  guinea  to  a 
pound  in  commercial  transactions;  but  they  also  assume 
beyond  this  that  men  are  influenced  by  all  those  passions, 
whatever  they  may  be,  which  enable  them  to  live  together 
peaceably,  to  co-operate  in  innumerable  ways,  and  to  put  con- 
fidence in  each  other's  dealings.  This  implies  far  more  than  a 
desire  for  wealth — as,  for  example,  respect  for  property — and 


ATTAINABLE  RESULTS.  27 

therefore  the  existence  of  all  that  complex  system  of  regula- 
tions which  prevents  the  desire  for  wealth  from  manifesting 
itself  in  cutting  throats;  and  thus  the  science — if  it  deserve 
the  name — may  give  results  which  are  valid  so  long  as  the 
existing  organisation  holds  together,  that  organisation  being 
manifestly  dependent  upon  countless  instincts,  beliefs,  and 
so  forth,  which  lie  altogether  beyond  the  scope  of  the 
economist.  But  the  organisation  may  change,  and  has  in 
fact  changed  within  historical  times,  in  consequence  of  the 
development  of  processes  upon  which  he  can  throw  no  light. 
Thus  his  power  of  dealing  with  any  series  of  social  pheno- 
mena is  confined  within  narrow  limits.  It  is  concerned,  I 
should  say,  with  the  external  and  mechanical  relations 
between  different  parts  of  the  social  organisation,  not  with 
the  principles  of  vital  growth.  The  economist  can  investi- 
gate with  great  advantage  such  problems  as  the  incidence  of 
a  tax  or  the  effects  of  free  trade.  He  can  show  what 
are  the  channels  alonec  which  wealth  circulates  whilst  the 
existing  system  is  unaltered ;  but  as  soon  as  he  goes  further, 
he  is  in  presence  of  the  old  difficulties.  He  shows,  for 
example,  that  an  increased  population  means  a  diminished 
share  of  wealth  to  each  person,  and  that  an  increase 
of  wages  means  a  diminution  of  employers'  profits.  For 
short  times,  and  assuming  no  correlative  social  change, 
his  doctrine  may  be  unassailable;  but  if  we  ask  what  will 
really  be  the  effect  of  limiting  the  population  or  of  a 
sudden  rise  of  wages,  we  have  to  ask  other  questions  of  most 
vital  importance.  Will  the  increased  prudence  mean  a 
general  lowering  of  energy?  Will  it  imply  the  adoption 
of  practices  fatal  to  national  morality,  and  therefore  to 
its  industry  ?  Will  an  increase  of  wages  increase  drunken- 
ness or  stimulate  saving?  and  if  so,  within  what  limits  and 
with  what  results  ?  These  problems,  again,  involve  innumer- 
able moral,  social,  and  religious  questions,  to  which  the  eco- 
nomist, as  such,  has  no  answer  to  give  ;  and  yet,  if  unable  to 
answer  them,  he  cannot  fully  solve  even  the  economical 
question.      These  considerations  are  enough  to  show  the 


28  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

feebleness  of  the  supposed  attempt  to  isolate  a  particular  im- 
pulse and  consider  its  consequences  apart.  The  intricate 
actions  and  reactions  between  different  elements  of  the  indi- 
vidual and  the  social  organisation  set  all  such  attempts  at 
defiance.  The  economist  is  really  forced  to  consider  as  con- 
stant precisely  those  forces  which  the  sociologist  has  to  regard 
as  incessantly  changing,  and  whose  mutual  relations  are  the 
very  subject-matter  of  his  inquiry.  And  thus  the  results  of 
economical  inquiry,  however  valuable  in  themselves,  are 
restricted  to  a  limited  sphere,  and  take  for  granted  the  very 
points  which  we  are  concerned  to  investigate. 

23.  Meanwhile,  however,  the  establishment  of  the  fact  that 
such  laws  are  ascertainable,  even  if  their  significance  be 
exaggerated,  has  undoubtedly  been  of  great  service  towards 
advancing  scientific  methods.  The  remark  generally  elici- 
ted by  their  enunciation,  though  founded  on  a  miscon- 
ception, explains  their  real  value.  They  are  regarded,  in 
fact,  as  tending  to  confirm  a  fatalistic  theory.  If  murders, 
it  is  said,  are  constant  in  number,  and  yet  murderers  are 
not  moved  by  any  desire  to  make  up  a  given  tale  of  crimes, 
the  observed  uniformity  must  be  due  to  some  mysterious 
agency.  Some  dark  fate  must  pick  out  a  certain  number  of 
men  every  year  and  order  them  to  cut  (or,  as  we  must  add  in 
equity,  to  abstain  from  cutting)  their  neighbours'  throats. 
And  the  criticism  would  be  just  if  it  were  asserted  that  the 
number  was  constant  whatever  the  social  state.  The  paradox 
results  from  the  fact  that,  on  the  one  hand,  a  regularity  in  a 
number  of  events  implies  that  the  events  have  a  direct  influ- 
ence upon  each  other,  whilst,  on  the  other  hand,  it  seems 
clear  that  in  the  supposed  cases  each  man  acts  in  complete 
independence  of  his  neighbour.  There  would  be  nothing 
strange  in  the  fact  of  a  fixed  number  of  murders  if  there 
was  such  a  relation  between  the  events  that  each  murder 
successfully  achieved  diminished  the  temptations  in  some 
given  proportion;  if,  for  example,  there  was  a  limited  number 
of  tyrants  who  united  together,  and  the  murder  of  one  enabled 
the  others  to  guard  themselves  more  effectually.     But  it  is 


ATTAINABLE  RESULTS.  29 

easy  to  remark  that  uniformity  of  this  kind  may  equally  well 
result  where  each  event  is  a  collateral  and  independent  eflect 
of  certain  fixed  causes.  One  mother  does  not  commit  in- 
fanticide, nor  does  another  give  birth  to  a  blind  child,  because 
another  has  murdered  her  child  or  had  a  blind  babv.  But 
the  numbers  will  be  uniform  so  long  as  the  predisposing 
causes  are  uniform  and  act  upon  similar  material.  If  cer- 
tain unhealthy  conditions  of  life  remain  constant,  so  will 
the  diseases  which  they  produce.  Where  there  is  a  certain 
quantity  of  undrained  marsh,  there  will  be  a  certain  quan- 
tity of  agU'';,  and  (as  some  philosophers  have  urged)  a  cer- 
tain quantity  of  belief  in  hell-fire,  until  the  discovery  of  the 
virtues  of  bark  may  eradicate  both  evils.  Now  the  condi- 
tions which  produce  murder  are  not  of  this  palpable  and 
material  kind,  but  it  does  not  follow  that  thev  are  not 
equally  fixed.  Society,  in  fact,  is  a  structure  which,  by  its 
nature,  implies  a  certain  fixity  in  the  distribution  and  relations 
of  classes.  Each  man  is  found  with  a  certain  part  of  the  joint 
framework  which  is  made  of  flesh  and  blood  instead  of  bricks 
or  timber,  but  which  is  not  the  less  truly  a  persistent  structure. 
There  is  room  for  so  many  rich  and  so  many  poor,  for  such 
and  such  fixed  numbers  of  lawyers,  and  clergymen,  and 
scavengers.  The  structure  can  be  modified,  and  is  always 
being  gradually  modified;  but  it  can  only  change  gradually, 
for  each  change  involves  the  reorganisation  to  some  extent 
of  the  rest  of  the  body,  and  a  complex  system  of  action  and 
reaction.  The  social  body  is  no  more  liable  to  arbitrary 
chancres  than  the  individual  body,  thoucrh  its  oraanlsatlon  is 
not  so  extern-ally  conspicuous ;  and  it  is  really  no  more 
surprising  that  there  should  be  throughout  long  periods  a 
fixed  proportion  of  paupers  than  that  through  much  longer 
periods  animals  should  be  produced  with  the  same  bodily 
proportions.  Whilst  this  is  so  there  will  be  an  approximately 
constant  number  of  persons  in  the  same  bodily  and  mental 
state,  exposed  to  the  same  conditions  and  temptations;  and 
therefore,  again,  there  will  result  a  number  of  minor  uni- 
formities which  appear  surprising  so  long  as  we  take  each 


30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

man  separately  and  regard  him  as  a  being  independent  of 
his  neighbour,  but  which  are  perfectly  intelligible  in  so  far  as 
they  are  the  natural  products  of  many  underlying  uniformities 
due  to  the  social  structure.  Consider  each  atom  of  a  tree  bv 
itself,  as  the  plaything  of  an  intricate  chaos  of  forces  of 
bewildering  perplexit)^,  and  you  may  wonder  that  the  same 
number  of  leaves  is  produced  every  year;  but  when  you 
remember  that  each  atom  is  part  of  a  structure  bound  to- 
gether by  a  number  of  mutual  relations,  the  wonder  vanishes. 
And  it  is  equally  true  of  that  more  obscure  structure  which 
we  call  human  society. 

24.  Thus  our  previsions  as  to  human  conduct  are  not  simply 
statements  of  an  averacre  result.  If  I  know  that  there  are 
ninety-nine  blanks  in  a  lottery  and  one  prize,  I  am  certain  that 
only  one  of  a  hundred  drawers  will  be  successful,  though  quite 
uncertain  as  to  which  it  will  be.  I  could  know  only  if  I  knew 
a  number  of  details  as  to  the  distribution  of  tickets  and  the 
movements  of  men's  hands  of  which  I  know  nothing.  In 
regard  to  manv  social  phenomena,  I  have  the  same  kind  of 
knowledge.  I  know  that  there  must  be  a  fringe  of  destitute 
people  hanging  upon  the  skirts  of  society,  a  small  number 
of  prizes  to  be  won  by  the  most  energetic  or  fortunate,  and 
a  number  of  intermediate  places  into  which  the  remainder 
will  be  distributed  by  mutual  pressure.  There  are  so  many 
officers,  privates,  and  hangers-on  to  an  army,  though  I 
carmot  say  which  place  will  be  occupied  by  a  given  man.  The 
members  of  a  given  society  are  forced  to  accommodate  them- 
selves to  certain  fixed  conditions  as  much  as  the  iron  which 
is  poured  into  a  given  mould.  There  is  a  causal  connection 
underlying  the  apparently  arbitrary  movements  of  the  indi- 
vidual. The  social  struggle  is  thrusting  down  the  weaker 
into  the  position  where  want  of  food  is  most  felt  and  stealing 
most  tempting;  and  character  is  being  determined  in  count- 
less indirect  ways  by  the  mutual  pressure  of  the  various 
classes.  Men  are  not  only  more  or  less  alike,  and  so  far  approxi- 
mate to  a  certain  average,  but  they  are  also  being  constantly 
educated  in  a  thousand  ways  by  the  persistent  conditions  of 


THEORY  OF  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION.  31 

the  social  organism;  and  thus  there  are  secondary  or  derivative 
laws  of  conduct  dependent  upon  these  conditions  and  pro- 
ducing uniformities  not  affected  by  the  variation  of  indi- 
vidual idiosyncrasy. 

IV.   Theory  of  Social  Evolution. 

25.  A  full   realisation   of  this  truth,  which  is  of  course 
a  very  old  truth  in  substance,  a  perception  that  society  is 
not  a  mere  aggregate  but  an  organic  growth,  that  it  forms 
a  whole,  the  laws  of  whose  growth  can  be   studied   apart 
from    those    of    the    individual    atom,    supplies    the   most 
characteristic    postulate    of    modern    speculation,    and    we 
may   note   its    general    bearing    upon   the    problem    before 
us.     The  explicit  and  constant  recognition   (for  there   has 
always  been  a  kind  of  recognition)  that  society  forms  such 
an    organic    growth,    that    its    properties    can    be   studied 
separately,    and    cannot     be    inferred    directly    from    the 
characters    of    the    component    individuals,    does    not    in- 
deed   relieve    us    from    the    difficulties    already   noted — for 
by  recognising  that  the  laws  are  there  we  certainly  do  not 
discover  what  the  particular  laws  are — nor  does  it,  in  any 
case,  suggest  the  possibility  of  any  a  priori  theory  upon  the 
subject.     We   cannot  say,   previously   to   any   study  of  the 
oro-anism,   that   it  is   so,   and   that   it  could   not  have  been 
otherwise.      On  the  contrary,  we  may  suppose  that  many 
other  forms   of   society   besides    those    with    which    we  are 
acquainted   may  be  possible,  and   may   be  actually  realised 
under  difierent  conditions.     If  anybody  should  maintain  that 
in  some  other  planet  the  propagation  of  the  inhabitants  may 
be  carried  on  by  a  totally  different  method,  and  that  there 
may  be  no  distinction  of  the  sexes,  I  do  not  see  how  it  would 
be  possible  to  confute  him,  and  under  such  circumstances  the 
whole  social  structure  would  be  organised  upon  very  different 
principles.     The  utmost  to  which  we  can  aspire  is  to  show 
how  different   parts  of  the   structure   mutually  imply  each 
other;  so  that,  given  the  whole,  we  may  see  that  any  particular 


32  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

part  could  not  be  otherwise ;  and  this,  though  a  less  ambitious 
conclusion,  would  be  amply  satisfactory  for  scientific  purposes. 
I  know  of  no  a  priori  proof,  and  for  my  part  I  cannot  con- 
ceive one,  which  should  establish  the  necessity  for  a  human 
being  consisting  of  just  so  many  organs,  of  a  stomach,  lungs, 
heart,  legs,  and  so  forth ;  still  I  am  quite  able  to  show  that 
under  existing  circumstances  each  part  of  the  framework  is  a 
highly  convenient  part  of  the  whole,  and  I  can  more  or  less 
determine  the  conditions  which — still  upon  that  understand- 
ing— best  fit  it  for  playing  its  part.  Nor,  again,  has  the 
assumption  which  we  are  considering  enabled  us  to  acquire 
that  degree  of  knowledge  which  would  enable  us  to  predict 
the  future  course  of  history,  nor — if  I  am  ri<rht  in  what  I 
have  already  said — ^made  it  even  conceivable  that  such  know- 
ledge will  ever  be  attainable. 

26.  What  advantage,  then,  is  gained  by  accepting  this 
theory?  The  first  gain  is  the  simple  recognition  that  there 
must  be  laws,  and  that  there  may  be  discoverable  laws  of 
social  growth  which  are  essentially  relevant  to  our  inv^esti- 
gation,  but  which  previous  methods  of  inquiry  have  tended 
to  ignore.  So  long  as  reasoning  has  been  conducted  upon  the 
tacit  assumption  that  social  phenomena  can  be  satisfactorily 
explained  by  studying  their  constituent  atoms  separately, 
attention  was  diverted  from  some  most  important  principles. 
If  we  could  have  studied  the  body  on  the  assumption  that 
each  organ  had  an  independent  vitality  which  required  no 
reference  to  the  other  organs  to  make  its  laws  of  growth 
intelligible,  we  should  gain  a  good  deal  by  simply  recognising 
the  existence  of  the  whole  orc-anism.  There  are  cases  in 
which  we  may  study  a  number  of  units  separately,  and 
thence  infer  the  properties  of  a  whole  figured  from  such  units. 
There  are  other  cases  in  which  the  properties  of  each  part 
are  so  dependent  upon  the  whole  that  it  is  impossible  to 
understand  them  separately  without  reference  to  the  proper- 
ties of  the  whole.  If  the  problems  of  human  conduct  really 
fall  under  the  second  category,  and  if  at  the  same  time  we 
assume    them    to    belong    to    the   first,   we   shall   manifestly 


THEORY  OF  SOCIAL  EVOLUTION.  33 

neglect  some  essential  conditions.  The  symptom  of  the  error 
will  be,  that,  as  we  have  omitted  a  reference  to  certain 
regulative  principles,  some  of  our  data  will  appear  to  be 
arbitrary,  simply  because  we  have  not  attended  to  the  condi- 
tions by  which  they  are  actually  determined.  My  statement 
must  necessarily  be  vague  at  this  stage  of  the  argument,  but 
I  shall  endeavour  to  work  it  out  hereafter.  I  may,  however, 
add  already,  that  the  assumption  in  question  gives  a  new 
sio-nificance  to  the  facts  before  us.  It  shows  how  facts 
which  we  w^ere  previously  content  to  leave  unexplained,  and 
perhaps  to  set  down  as  ultimate  and  inexplicable  data  of  the 
problem,  may  be  important  embodiments  of  the  principles  to 
be  discovered.  Vast  importance  has  been  given  to  many 
apparently  trifling  facts  by  the  theory  of  evolution,  as  applied 
to  all  the  sciences  which  have  to  do  with  organised  beings. 
What  was  formerly  set  down  as  a  freak  of  nature,  or 
dismissed  from  the  sphere  of  the  explicable  by  some  verbal 
reference  to  a  special  creation,  turns  out  to  be  an  important 
link  in  a  chain  of  evidence  as  to  past  conditions  of  organic 
life.  And  so  in  sociological  inquiries,  we  find  that  some 
apparently  trifling  and  arbitrary  custom,  wliich  to  certain 
observers  passed  for  a  mere  barren  curiosity,  gives  a  sudden 
and  effective  illustration  of  remote  social  states.  And  what 
is  true  of  exceptional  peculiarities  is  equally  true  of  the 
more  permanent  properties  of  social  organisation.  I  am 
now  enabled  to  see  that  a  statement  which  seemed  only  to 
describe  the  averao-e  mode  of  behaviour  of  independent  beings 
has  really  a  vast  significance  when  considered  as  describing 
a  quality  of  a  persistent  organism.  For  the  theory  of  evolu- 
tion brings  out  the  fact  that  every  organism,  whether  social 
or  individual,  represents  the  product  of  an  indefinite  series  of 
adjustments  between  the  organism  and  its  environment.  In 
other  words,  that  every  being  or  collection  of  beings  which 
forms  a  race  or  a  society  is  part  of  a  larger  system  -,  that  it  is  a 
product  of  the  continuous  play  of  a  number  of  forces  con- 
stantly shifting  and  rearranging  themselves  in  the  effort  to 
maintain  the  general  equilibrium,  and  that  consequently  every 

C 


34  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

permanent  property  represents,  not  an  accidental  similarity, 
but  a  correspondence  between  the  organism  and  some  per- 
manent conditions  of  life. 

27.  It  may  thus  be  said  that  the  whole  history  of  the 
world  and  its  inhabitants  represents  a  problem  of  stupendous 
magnitude.  A  being  of  vastly  superior  powers  might  con- 
ceivably work  out  that  problem,  if  he  were  acquainted  with 
the  data  at  any  particular  moment,  and  capable  of  unravel- 
ling all  the  inconceivably  complicated  forces  which  are  con- 
flicting and  co-operating,  and  calculating  their  resultants.  To 
us,  who  are  only  infinitesimal  parts  of  the  system,  the  im- 
possibility of  any  such  attempt  is  almost  ludicrously  obvious. 
We  work  out  the  problem  bv  living,  or  rather  we  work  out 
our  own  little  bit  of  the  problem.  We  are  utterly  incompe- 
tent to  grasp  the  whole,  or  to  rise  above  it  and  say  why  such 
and  such  data  must  have  been  given,  and  what  will  be  the 
further  stages  of  the  process.  But  when  we  once  recognise 
the  fact  that  the  problem  is  being  worked  out,  we  see  also 
that  an  answer  is  actually  given  in  some  degree  by  the  very 
facts  before  us.  Our  own  lives  are  the  answer.  We  can 
thus  obtain  certain  results,  a  posteriori,  by  recognising  the 
sense  in  which  the  evolution  of  history  is  really  the  solution  of 
the  problem.  If  we  can  succeed  in  putting  the  question  fairly, 
we  shall  find  the  answer  to  it  ready  written  upon  the  facts. 
This  is  really  the  nature  of  the  change  in  the  point  of  view 
implied  in  the  acceptance  of  the  evolution  theory.  It  tells  us 
what  is  the  proper  mode  of  interrogating  nature.  When  we 
know  the  laws  of  gravitation  we  can  prove  that  planets  must 
move  in  ellipses.  If  we  knew  nothing  of  the  law  of  gravitation 
or  were  unable  to  calculate  its  effects,  but  yet  knew,  in  general 
terms,  that  there  was  some  such  law,  and  that  it  was  the  sole 
law  in  operation,  we  might  be  able  to  infer  that  elliptical  move- 
ment was  a  necessary  consequence  of  its  action.  The  planets, 
it  has  been  said^  are  constantly  engaged  in  working  out  complex 
differential  equations.  They  give  us  the  answer  to  a  set  of 
problems  which  no  human  brain  may  be  sufficiently  com- 
prehensive to  solve  without  such  experience,     lliis  kind  of 


■STATE  NOfiMAi  SCHOOL. 

THE  ETHICAL  PROBLEM,    'os  Angeles,  €3135 

solution  is  equally  given  by  the  incomparably  more  complex 
phenomena  of  human  life ;  and  when  we  fully  recognise  the 
fact  that  a  problem  is  being  solved,  we  have  only  to  gain 
some  appreciation  of  its  general  nature  and  conditions  in 
order  to  obtain  some  important,  though  it  may  be  very 
limited,  conclusions  as  to  the  meanino-  of  the  answer  which 
may  fairly  be  called  scientific.  They  are  not  scientific  in 
the  sense  of  giving  us  quantitative  and  precise  formulae,  but 
they  may  be  so  far  scientific  as  to  be  certain  and  verifiable. 

V.  The  Ethical  Problem. 

28.  We  may  apply  this  briefly  to  the  special  problem  before 
us.  That  problem  is,  in  fact,  to  discover  the  scientific  form 
of  moral itv,  or,  in  other  words,  to  discover  what  is  the 
general  characteristic,  so  far  as  science  can  grasp  it,  of  the 
moral  sentiments.  The  difficultv  by  which  we  were  met 
was  the  apparently  arbitrary  and  fluctuating  nature  of  all 
human  instincts.  We  could  see  our  way  to  saying  that,  as  a 
general  truth,  and  in  the  average,  people  did  in  fact  have 
such  and  such  feelings.  But  the  uncertainty  of  the  data 
seemed  to  paralyse  any  further  inferences.  We  had  no 
apparent  reason  for  saving  why  they  might  not  have  an 
entirely  different  set  of  feelings.  And,  in  one  sense,  the 
difficulty  is  irreconcilable,  or  at  least  unanswerable  from  the 
purely  scientific  point  of  view ;  for  I  do  not  now  ask  how 
far  it  mav  be  met  by  an  assumption  of  transcendental  or 
metaphysical  principles.  But  the  conception  which  I  have 
just  endeavoured  to  explain  may  show  how,  when  we  consider 
human  beings  to  be  the  product  of  a  long  series  of  processes 
of  adaptation  or  adjustment,  acting  either  upon  the  individual 
or  the  social  organism,  we  may  hope  to  discern  that  anv  giv'en 
set  of  instincts  corresponds  to  certain  permanent  conditions, 
and  how  one  part  of  the  organism  implies  another,  or  how, 
the  whole  being  given,  the  relation  between  its  facts  follows, 
and  thus  how  the  general  system  hangs  together.  We  can 
attack  the  problem,  what  part  do  the  moral  instincts  play  in 


^6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  general  system  of  human  society,  which  is  itself  part  of 
the  wider  system  of  the  world  in  which  we  live  ?  And  this 
brings  us  back  to  a  proposition  from  which  I  started.  For, 
in  fact,  it  is  obvious  that  the  variation  in  moral  beliefs  which 
presented  itself  as  a  great  difficulty  must  be  a  part  of  the 
problem  to  be  solved.  We  have  not  to  consider  a  number 
of  different  and  irreconcilable  opinions  held  by  equally  compe- 
tent persons,  and  to  strike  a  rough  balance  between  them,  and 
arbitrarily  exclude  some  from  a  hearing.  We  must  ask,  in  fact, 
what  is  the  cause  of  these  opinions,  which,  again,  is  some- 
thing very  different  from  the  reason  as  perceived  by  those 
who  hold  them.  The  evolution  of  opinion  is  part  of  the 
whole  evolution;  and  it  mav  appear  upon  further  investiga- 
tion that  opinions  which  present  themselves  as  radically 
opposed,  are,  when  properly  considered,  nothing  more  than 
the  partial  views  of  the  truth  which  have  commended  them- 
selves to  persons  under  different  conditions.  The  true  law 
of  belief  will  account  for  the  erroneous  as  well  as  for  the 
accurate  opinions.  If  the  evolution  of  moral  sentiment  is 
a  work  in  which  manv  minds  in  many  generations  co-operate, 
it  is  plain  that  the  opinions  held  at  any  given  period  will 
correspond  in  some  way  to  the  corresponding  stage  of  evolu- 
tion, and  that  the  variation  will  appear  not  as  arbitrarv, 
but  as  confirmino-  the  o;eneral  law. 

29.  It  must  be  the  work  of  the  following  chapters  to  give 
more  precision  to  these  general  remarks.  One  observation, 
however,  must  be  premised,  of  which  I  have  had  to  feel  the 
importance.  Starting,  as  I  profess  to  do,  from  the  scien- 
tific point  of  view,  it  follows  that  I  have  to  deal,  in  the  first 
place,  with  facts  of  observation.  I  have,  that  is,  to  con- 
sider the  moral  sentiments  which  have,  as  a  historical  fact, 
exercised  an  influence  in  the  world,  and  to  ask  what  part 
they  play  in  the  general  process  of  evolution.  I  hav^e,  there- 
fore, nothing  to  do,  in  the  first  instance,  with  those  moral 
principles  which  are  or  profess  to  be  deduced  from  transcen- 
dental considerations  or  from  pure  logic  independent  of 
any  particular  fact.     The  distinction,  which  cannot  be  fully 


THE  ETHICAL  PROBLEM.  37 

considered  at  this  stage,  is  one  which  must  yet  be  noticed, 
because  I  am  convinced  that  a  neglect  of  it  leads  to  a  vast 
amount  of  ambiguity  and  misunderstanding.  That  there 
is,  upon  any  theory,  a  great  difference  between  actual  and 
ideal  moralitv,  I  take  to  be  an  admitted  fact.  In  anv  given 
society  there  are,  as  a  rule,  several  moral  standards :  there  is 
that  which  is  tauirht  in  churches ;  that — not  alwavs  identical — 
which  actually  determines  our  approval  or  disapproval ;  that 
which  is  current  in  the  most  cultivated,  and  that  which  is 
held  by  the  most  barbarous  classes;  that  which  is  approved 
by  the  advanced  thinkers,  and  that  which  commends  itself  to 
the  thorouo-ho-oino-  conservatives,  and  so  forth.    The  difference 

COO  '' 

is    universally    allowed    to    exist.     The    utilitarian    moralist 

considers  that  to  be  moral  which  makes  for  happiness,  but 

he  admits  that  the  average  calculation  of  happiness  is  often 

very  wrong.     His  opponent  holds  that  moral  principles  are 

deducible  from  pure  reason,  but  he  admits  that  most  men 

are  very  poor  hands  at  pure  reasoning.     Perhaps  he  appeals 

to  the  voice  of  conscience,  but  he  does  not  assert  that  the 

voice  is  not  capable  of  misinterpretation.     The  distinction  is 

recognised  on  all  hands,  but  the  ordinary  mode  of  recognition 

leads  to  much  confusion.     Each  man  thinks  that  his  own 

moralitv  is  the  rio-ht  moralitv,  and  that  the  ordinary  standard 

is  mistaken  and  immoral  so  far  as  it  deflects  from  it.     He 

does  not  say  that  your  moralitv  is  erroneous,  but  denies  it 

to  be   morality  at  all.     I   do  not  object  at  present  to  this 

mode  of  speech,  but  it  may  lead  to  misunderstanding.     Thus, 

for  example,  one  moralist  asserts  that  the  moral  code  varies, 

whilst  another  says   that  it  is   fixed.     Yet    they  mav,  and 

sometimes  do,   mean   the   very  same   thing;   for  both   may 

allow  that  the  actual  code  varies,  and  both  may  agree  that,  if 

men  were  better  reasoners  or  better  calculators  of  happiness, 

the  code  would  be  fixed  :  the  variability  is  predicated  of  the 

actual,  the  fixity  of  the  ideal  code.     Thus  the  question  of 

what  ought  to  be  moral  (if  I  may  be  allowed  the  phrase)  is 

often  confused  with  the  question  of  what  actually  is  moral. 

The  various  controversies  as  to  international  law  illustrate 


38  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  confusion.  When  a  writer  holds  that  a  certain  custom 
ought  to  be  observed  by  different  nations,  he  at  once  declares 
that  it  is  the  law.  He  attributes  to  it  a  kind  of  potential 
existence,  though  he  allows  that  it  is  not  actually  operative. 
His  opponent  denies  it  to  be  the  law,  because  he  gives  that  name 
only  to  laws  which  are  actually  observed,  though  he  may  be 
willing  to  admit  that  it  is  desirable  that  it  should  be  the  law. 
A  similar  misunderstanding  perplexes  many  problems  in 
casuistry.  So,  for  example,  we  ask  what  judgment  we  are  to 
form  of  conduct  which  is  "materially"  wrong  but  "formally" 
right;  or,  as  the  words  are  sometimes  interpreted,  of  conduct 
which  is  in  conformity  with  the  moral  law  as  accepted  by  the 
agent,  but  not  in  conformitv  with  right  moralitv.  A  man 
deserts  his  wife,  sincerely  believing  that  marriage  should  not 
be  permanently  binding.  Such  cases  are  often  perplexing; 
and  at  present  I  have  only  to  remark  that  the  perplexity  is 
increased  by  the  ambiguity  in  question.  If  we  understand 
that  by  7'ight  we  mean  right  according  to  the  ideal  code,  and  if 
the  ideal  code — however  constructed — implies  indissolubility 
of  marriage,  then  the  man  clearly  acts  wrongly.  We  may 
still  ask  whether  his  non-recognition  of  the  true  principle 
makes  his  conduct  better  or  worse;  whether  a  man  who 
knowingly  breaks  the  law  from  conviction  is  better  or  worse 
than  a  man  who  breaks  it  unknowingly?  This,  in  my 
opinion,  amounts  to  asking  which  man  would,  on  the  whole, 
observe  the  genuine  moral  code  with  fewest  exceptions. 
And  this,  again,  is  a  question  of  fact  to  be  settled  by  psycho- 
logists and  direct  observation.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  by 
right  we  mean  simply  conformity  to  the  moral  code  which  is 
actually  operative  at  the  given  time,  it  is  simply  a  question 
of  fact  whether  that  code  does  or  does  not  prescribe  indis- 
solubility of  marriage.  The  further  question  then  remains, 
whether  the  new  rule  upon  which  the  man  acts  is  a  better 
or  a  worse  rule  than  the  accepted  rule  ?  And  this  is  to  ask 
whether  it  would  or  would  not  form  a  part  of  the  ideal  code, 
however  that  is  to  be  constrvicted  ?  The  problem  is  then  of 
necessity  complicated,   but  it  becomes   hopelessly  perplexed 


THE  ETHICAL  PROBLEM.  39 

^vhen  we  have  not  settled  as  to  the  sense  in  which  we  use  tlic 
word  moral,  for  the  man  may  be  right  in  one  of  the  senses 
and  wrono;  in  the  other. 

30.  It  is  desirable  to  avoid  this  ambiguity  as  much  as  pos- 
sible ;  and  therefore  I  give  notice  of  the  fact  that,  until  I 
state  the  contrary,  I  wish  to  be  understood  as  referring  in  all 
cases  to  the  actual  law.  I  mean  by  the  moral  code  that  set  of 
rules  which,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  is  respected  in  a  given  society, 
and  so  far  determines  the  ordinary  approvals  and  disapprovals 
as  to  be  an  effective  force  in  governing  conduct.  It  will  be 
an  important  inquiry  at  a  future  period,  what  is  the  relation 
of  this  to  the  ideal  code,  and  what  it  precisely  is  that  I 
understand  by  the  ideal  code.  I  mention  the  fact  explicitly, 
because  I  think  that  few  ambiguities  in  the  whole  inquiry 
have  been  more  fruitful  of  misunderstanding. 


(     40     ) 


CHAPTER  II. 

THEORY     OF     MOTIVES. 

I.  The  Problem. 

1.  Ethical  speculation  must,  as  thus  understood,  be  Impli- 
cated in  psychological  and  sociological  inquiries;  that  is  to 
say,  its  foundations  must  be  laid  In  the  treacherous  region 
where  the  vague  doctrines  of  common  sense  have  not  yet 
crystallised  into  scientific  coherence.  Perplexing  ambiguities 
beset  the  simplest  primary  propositions.  We  accept  from 
the  language  of  ordinary  life  some  statement  which  serves 
well  enough  for  a  working  maxim.  As  soon  as  we  apply  It 
to  purposes  of  accurate  inquiry,  we  find  that  it  savs  too  mvich 
or  too  little ;  that  it  causes  a  hopeless  ambiguity  or  pushes  an 
undeniable  truth  into  obvious  error.  We  are  trying  to  split 
hairs  with  a  carving-knife.  We  must,  therefore,  look  closely 
to  our  initial  steps,  and  scrutinise  some  apparently  obvious 
and  harmless  propositions. 

2.  We  have  to  deal  with  human  conduct.  So  far  as  a 
man  is  a  material  thing,  his  conduct.  If  It  can  properly  be 
called  conduct,  is  determined  by  purely  mechanical  conditions; 
so  far  as  he  Is  a  sentient  being,  his  feelings,  and  so  far  as  he 
is  a  rational  being,  his  reasoning  powers,  must  be  taken  into 
account.  We  are  already  in  presence  of  a  difficulty.  How 
are  we  to  conceive  of  the  relation  between  reason  and  feel- 
ing, or  of  the  relations  between  the  vital  and  the  mechanical 
forces?  As  we  understand  these  words,  in  one  sense  or 
another,  we  find  ourselves  impelled  towards  one  of  the  two 
opposite  poles  to  which  all  ethical  speculations  converge. 
According  to  the  principles  already  stated,  wc  must  distinguish 


THE  PROBLEM.  41 

between  the  scientific  and  the  underlying  metaphysical  pro- 
blems.    The  metaphysical  are,  for  my  purpose,  irrelevant.     I 
do  not,  for  example,  enter  into  the  discussion  between  the 
materialist  and  the  idealist.     The  materialist  regards  man  as 
an  automaton  worked  by  mechanical  forces,  which,  accord- 
ino"  to  him,  are  the  sole  realities,  and  considers  consciousness 
to  be  in  some  sort  a  superfluous   spectator.     Without  dis- 
cussing the  tenability  of  such  a  theory,  I  take  it  for  granted 
that  pains  and  pleasures  have  an  influence  upon  human  con- 
duct; that  men  eat  because  they  are  hungry,  strike  because 
they  are  angrv,  and  act   upon   reasoned  plans  because  they 
have  certain  convictions  as  to  the  nature  of  the  world  and  the 
consequences  of  their  actions.     The  materialist  may  show,  if 
he  can,  that  all  the  processes  thus  described  have  a  mechanical 
aspect;    that  hunger   corresponds    to  certain  organic   states 
which  involve  certain  cerebral  changes,  transforming  impulses 
received  from  the  nervous  system  into  messages  determining 
mechanical  changes  in  the  various  organs  of  the  body.     In 
any  case,  however,  we  are  in  complete  darkness  as  to  the 
nature  of  these  mechanical  changes,  and  are  long  likely  so  to 
remain ;  and,  moreover,  in  any  case — according  to  my  con- 
tention— a  statement  of  them  will  not  supersede  the  other 
mode  of  statement.     The  proposition,  that  is,  that  hunger 
makes  men  eat,  will  express  a  truth  whatever  material  impli- 
cations may   be   involved   in   that  simple  statement.      The 
ultimate  reality  may  be  something  different,  but  at  least  the 
formula  gives,  and,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  is  always  likely  to  give, 
an   intelligible   and  simple  account   of  the   facts.     And   the 
same  will  be  true  if  we  adopt  the  opposite  theory  of  idealism, 
and  in  some  sense  deny  reality   to  the   mechanical  entities 
called  brain  and  stomach  and  food.     They  may  be  simply 
clusters   of  sensations,  but  the   formula  will   still   express  a 
relation  which  will  hold  good  as  to  their  reciprocal  action. 
We  have  to  inquire  what  is  the  most  general  formula  of 
this  kind  discoverable. 


42  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 


II.   The  Emotions  as  Determining  Conduct. 

3.  After  emerging  from  the  purely  metaphysical  regions,  we 
have  still  to  look  carefully  to  our  footing.  Conduct,  I  have 
said,  is  determined  by  feeling 5  we  fly  from  pain;  we  seek 
pleasure;  life  is  a  continuous  struggle  to  minimise  suffering 
and  to  lay  a  firm  grasp  upon  happiness ;  "  good  "  means  every- 
thing which  favours  happiness,  and  "  bad "  everything  that 
is  conducive  to  misery;  nor  can  any  other  intelligible  mean- 
ing be  assigned  to  the  words.  To  some  minds  these  pro- 
positions appear  to  be  self-evident;  they  cannot  be  denied 
without  self-contradiction;  the  difficulty  of  proving  them  is 
the  difficulty  of  proving  any  of  those  primary  doctrines  for 
which  we  must  appeal  to  what  is  called  the  direct  testimony 
of  consciousness.  Yet,  in  laying  them  down,  I  have  already 
made  assertions  which  seem  to  beg  the  question,  and  the 
appeal  to  consciousness  may  be  rejected  as  virtually  an  appeal 
to  common  sense,  or,  in  other  words,  to  unreasoning  prejudice. 
I  shall,  however,  venture  to  assume  that  the  assertions  are 
in  some  sense  valid ;  and  I  make  that  assumption  upon  the 
ground  already  taken — the  ground,  namely,  that  no  meta- 
physician would  really  deny  that  they  express  truths,  though 
he  may  deny  that  they  express  ultimate  truths.  The  only 
real  question  is  in  what  sense  they  are  valid.  Nobody  who 
has  ever  had  a  toothache — nobody,  one  might  rather  say, 
who  has  ever  had  a  sensation — will  deny  that  he  avoids  pain 
as  such  and  seeks  pleasure  as  such.  And,  in  fact,  if  we 
examine  the  ordinary  criticisms  of  these  simple  propositions, 
we  shall  find  that  the  critics  deny  not  so  much  the  propositions 
themselves  as  certain  interpretations  which  tacitly  introduce 
some  further  and  more  questionable  assertion. 

4.  Thus,  for  example,  it  is  frequently  admitted  that  pain 
deters  and  pleasure  attracts,  but  it  is  at  the  same  time  denied 
that  pain  and  pleasure  are  the  sole  deterrent  or  attractive 
qualities.  We  shrink  from  fire  or  the  knife,  but  some  other 
motive  may  overpower  our  spontaneous  dread.    What,  then. 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        43 

is  the  nature  of  this  different  motive?  It  must,  by  the 
argument,  be  something  which  admits  of  a  comparison  with 
pain  and  pleasure,  which  has  its  equivalent  in  terms  of 
feeling,  and  which  represents,  therefore,  a  force  of  the  same 
order.  Is  this  not  virtually  to  admit  that  it  is  still  a  pleasure 
or  a  pain  ?  The  dread  of  shame  or  remorse  overcomes  the 
martyr's  dread  of  the  fire.  Is  not  that  because  shame  and 
remorse  are  themselves  painful,  and  in  some  men  more 
exquisitely  painful  than  physical  torment?  The  pain  and 
pleasure  may  be  higher  in  kind,  but  it  is  still  a  pleasure  or  a 
pain.  The  true  statement  is  that  one  emotion  may  be  over- 
come, not  by  a  something  which  is  altogether  disparate  from 
emotion,  but  by  an  emotion  of  a  different  kind ;  and  this  is 
of  course  indisputable.  It  does  not  traverse  the  proposition 
that  emotion  can  be  limited  by  nothing  but  emotion.  Or, 
again,  the  conclusion  is  sometimes  evaded  by  showing,  not 
that  pain  or  pleasure  do  not  determine  conduct,  but  that 
conduct  is  not  determined  by  certain  modes  of  estimating 
pain  and  ])leasure.  A  man,  it  is  often  said,  may  deliberately 
prefer  a  life  of  pain  to  annihilation,  and  in  so  doing  he 
would  choose  a  clear  balance  of  painful  sensation.  But  if  we 
look  closer,  this  is  simply  to  say  that  the  prospect  of  annihila- 
tion is  more  painful  at  the  moment  than  the  prospect  of 
future  misery.  This,  indeed,  is  highly  probable.  The 
instinct  which  revolts  ao;ainst  the  thought  of  annihilation  is 
so  powerful  that  the  imagination  of  future  evils  is  unable  to 
overcome  it.  Perhaps  this  proves  that  the  instinct  is  a 
foolish  one;  but  who  ever  denied  that  we  had  foolish  instincts — 
instincts,  that  is,  which  lead  us  to  sacrifice  a  great  future  to 
a  small  present  pleasure,  or  to  choose  an  evil  rather  than 
make  the  effort  to  wield  the  bare  bodkin  ?  All  that  is 
proved  is  that  we  are  not  always  determined  by  a  calculation 
of  pleasure  to  come ;  or,  again,  that  the  estimate  of  future 
pleasure  does  not  always  produce  a  corresponding  pleasure; 
and  this  will  be  admitted  on  all  hands. 

5.  We  have  to  meet  these  objections  by  the  sacrifice  of 
much  of  the  apparent  import  of  our  statement.    We  are  com- 


44  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

pelled  to  widen  the  significance  of  our  words  until  we  admit 
every  conceivable  form  of  agreeable  or  disagreeable  feeling ; 
and  we  are  forced  to  allow  that  pain  and  pleasure  may  deter- 
mine us  to  act  so  as  in  the  long-run  to  sacrifice  happiness 
and  court  misery.  And  hence  arises  another,  and  in  some 
ways  a  more  formidable,  criticism.  Granting,  it  is  said, 
that  happiness  is  the  sole  aim  of  all  human  conduct,  what 
are  we  the  wiser  ?  The  proposition  is  valueless  unless 
universally  true;  and  if  universally  true,  it  is  nugatory. 
Happiness  is  known  to  us  solely  as  that  which  men  desire : 
to  say,  then,  that  they  desire  happiness  is  to  say  that  they 
desire  what  they  desire.  The  force  of  this  familiar  argu- 
ment is  undeniable.  The  proposition,  I  agree,  is  nothing  if 
not  universal ;  it  must  cover  all  the  actions  of  all  human 
beings,  at  every  moment  of  their  lives  and  throughout  their 
whole  range  of  conscious  motive;  it  must  be  equally  true  of 
our  sensual  appetites,  our  purest  emotions,  and  our  intellec- 
tual activities.  Happiness  guides  us  when  we  are  eating 
our  dinners,  or  studying  metaphysics,  or  feeding  the  hungry; 
when  we  sacrifice  all  prospects  of  future  happiness  to  the 
loftiest  or  to  the  most  grovelling  motives;  when  we  destroy 
our  health  and  ruin  our  families  for  a  glass  of  gin,  or  walk 
up  to  a  battery  to  buy  one  more  chance  of  victory  for  a  good 
cause.  The  love  of  happiness  must  express  the  sole  possible 
motive  of  Judas  Iscariot  and  his  Master ;  it  must  explain  the 
conduct  of  Stylites  on  his  column,  of  Tiberius  at  Capreae, 
of  A  Kempis  in  his  cell,  and  of  Nelson  in  the  cockpit  of 
the  Victory.  It  must  be  equally  good  for  saints^  martyrs, 
heroes,  cowards,  debauchees,  ascetics,  mystics,  cynics,  misers, 
prodigals,  men,  women,  and  babes  in  arms.  Truly  it  must 
be  an  elastic  principle.  Can  it  be  more  than  this  that  men, 
so  far  as  they  act  from  motives,  have  some  motives  for  their 
action  ? 

6.  I  admit  that  the  proposition  is  one  which  would  have 
been  scarcely  worth  an  explicit  assertion  had  it  not  been 
explicitly  denied.  But  it  is  not  an  empty  proposition.  It 
asserts,  in  the  first  place,  the  general  proposition  already  laid 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        45 

down,    that    human    actions    are    no    more    the   product  of 
chance  than  any  other  observable  phenomena.     But  beyond 
this,  it  makes  another  assertion  which  it  is  essential  to  bear 
in  mind.     To  assert,  in  fact,  that  the  quality  of  any  conscious 
state  in  respect  of  its  pain  or  pleasure  is  the  essential  con- 
dition of  its  being  desired  or  dreaded,  is  to  deny  that  the  con- 
dition of  conduct  can  be  found   in  anything;  which  has  no 
relation  to  pain  or  pleasure.     And  as  attempts  have  been 
made  to  find  the  condition  elsewhere,  it  becomes  necessary 
to  deny  the  possibility  of  their  success.     To  say  that  action 
is  determined   by  feeling  is  not  to   enable  us  to  determine 
which  particular  feeling  will  be  most  efficient.     As  the  state- 
ment is  true  of  all   motives,  it  throws  no  light  upon   the 
relation  between  different  motives.     Nor,  again,  does  it  lead 
us  to  any  fertile  proposition  as  to  the  nature  of  conduct  in 
general.     Pain  and  pleasure  are  words  which  it  is  impossible 
to  define ;  as  they  are  names  of  the  highest  class  and  not  a 
species  of  some  more  general  class,  we  can  no  more  define 
them  by  genus  and  difference  than  we  can  define  light  and 
darkness,  or  subject  and  object,  or  past  and  future :  but  we 
can  still  know  what  they  mean ;  and  it  is  conceivable  that 
we  might  be  able  to  assign  the  physiological  conditions  of 
their  existence,  in  which  case  we  might  be  able  to  advance  to 
some  fertile  conclusions  from  a  statement  which  is  at  present 
nugatory  by  its   excessive  generality.     At   present,  we   can 
only  say  that  psychologists  distinguish — and  their  distinction 
has  at  least  a  scientific  if  not  a  metaphysical  validity — between 
the    emotions    and    the    intellect,    or    between    feeling    and 
reasoning.     We  assert  that  conduct  is   determined   by  the 
feelincrs,  not  as  denyino;  that  it  is  also  in  some  sense  deter- 
mined  by  the  reason,  but  as  maintaining  that  a  state  of  con- 
sciousness which  is  neither  painful  nor  pleasurable  cannot  be 
an  object  either  of  desire  or  aversion,  and  that,  so  far  as  it  is 
painful  or  pleasurable,  it  will  produce  one  or  the  other.     We 
shall,  I  think,  see  that  this  doctrine,  however  vague,  is  by  no 
means  without  an  important  bearing  upon  ethical  specula- 
tion 5  but   it   also   suggests   the   necessity   of  entering  more 


46  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

fully  into  the  meaning  of  the  distinction  in  question.  Since, 
as  I  have  said,  man  is  both  a  sentient  and  a  reasoning  being, 
we  have  to  ask  how  we  are  to  conceive  of  the  mode  in  which 
these  separable,  or  at  least  verbally  distinguishable,  faculties 
co-operate  in  determining  conduct.  The  inquiry  will  lead  to 
a  fuller  answer  to  the  difficulties  upon  which  I  have  briefly 
touched  in  the  last  paragraph. 

7.  Moralists  who  regard  happiness  as  the  sole  aim  of  all 
conceivable  action  have  accepted  a  simple  analysis  of 
reasoned  conduct.  Conduct,  as  the  old  reasoners  said,  fol- 
lowed the  "last  act  of  the  judgment."  Though  men  fre- 
quently, perhaps  generally,  act  without  much  conscious  choice, 
the  typical  and  fully  developed  act  of  decision  consisted  in  a 
judgment  that  one  action  would  produce  more  happiness 
than  another.  The  intellect,  to  use  the  ordinary  metaphor, 
weighed  different  "lots"  of  happiness  in  its  balance;  the 
will  inevitably  inclined  to  that  conduct  which  weighed  the 
heaviest  in  these  scales.  Reasoned  conduct  differed  from 
merely  instinctive  conduct  in  that  it  implied  an  adaptation 
of  means  to  ends,  and  therefore  a  possibility  of  following 
courses  of  conduct  not  agreeable  in  themselves,  but  promising 
a  greater  total  of  happiness.  The  characteristic  of  the  reason- 
ing being  was  the  power  of  acting  with  a  view  to  distant  ends, 
instead  of  being  the  slave  of  immediate  impulse.  Now  I  do 
not  deny  that  it  may  be  possible  to  use  this  phraseology  so  as 
to  express  the  facts  with  tolerable  accuracy.  But  I  think 
that  it  is  apt  to  sanction  certain  erroneous  hypotheses  which 
have  done  much  to  perplex  the  whole  subject. 

8.  We  may  have  to  consider  some  of  these  hereafter.  For 
the  present  I  may  observe  that  at  the  very  outset  there  is 
apparently  one  defect  in  the  statement.  It  seems  to  assume 
that  a  deferred  pleasure  is  as  potent  as  an  immediate  pleasure. 
So  long  as  "I  "am  to  have  the  pleasure,  it  matters  not,  so 
far  we  have  gone,  whether  it  be  the  "  I  "  of  to-day  or  the  "  I" 
of  next  year.  The  influence  of  mental  perspective  appears 
therefore  to  be  entirely  ignored  ;  and  yet  there  can  be  no 
doubt,  so  long  as  we  are  dealing  with  facts,  that  this  influence 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        47 

is  of  the  highest  importance,  and  that  every  removal  of  a 
pleasure  in  time  and  place  has  an  immense  effect  upon  its 
power  of  determining  conduct.  But  if  we  try  to  rectify  our 
formula  so  as  to  allow  for  this  difficulty,  we  become  aware 
that  it  is  of  the  very  essence  of  the  statement.  The 
happiness  which  determines  the  will  is  always  regarded  as 
future,  though  it  may  be  in  the  immediate  future.  The 
normal  state  of  man  is  that  of  the  proverbial  ass,  who  con- 
stantly pursues  and  never  obtains  the  wisp  of  hay  fixed  at 
the  end  of  the  shaft.  The  popular  maxim,  "  Man  never  is, 
but  always  to  be  blest,"  is  converted  into  a  scientific  formula. 
Conduct,  you  say,  is  always  determined  by  feeling;  but  the 
doctrine  consistently  applied  is  fatal  to  the  analysis  assumed. 
For  on  this  analysis,  reason,  regarded  as  a  faculty  altogether 
distinct  from  the  emotions,  determines  conduct  by  reference 
to  a  feeling  which  does  not  yet  exist,  or,  in  other  words,  does 
not  exist  at  all.  The  actual  feeling  is  taken  to  be  a  mere 
consequent  which  does  not  affect  conduct.  The  feeling  which 
is  hereafter  to  be  is  the  sole  determining  influence. 

9.  To  express  ourselves  accurately,  and  to  carry  out  con- 
sistently our  initial  assumption,  we  must  modify  the  state- 
ment. No  feeling  can  affect  us  except  so  far  as  it  is  felt. 
An  unfelt  feeling  is  a  nonentity.  Many  of  our  feelings,  it 
is  true,  are  regarded  by  us  as  prophetic  foretastes  of  a  feeling 
to  come.  We  shudder  at  the  edge  of  a  cliff  because  we  fore- 
see the  consequences  of  a  fall,  and  thus  the  shudder  implies 
the  belief  in  those  consequences.  But  though  this  intellectual 
perception  is  an  essential  part  of  the  process,  it  would  not 
affect  our  conduct  if  it  were  a  perception  entirely  divorced 
from  feeling.  It  affects  us  because  the  perception  is  itself 
painful,  because  it  involves  an  anticipatory  realisation  of  an 
approaching  pain.  It  is  more  accurate  to  say  that  my  con- 
duct is  determined  by  the  pleasantest  judgment  than  to  say 
that  it  is  determined  by  my  judgment  of  what  is  pleasantest. 
And  though  in  such  cases  the  remark  may  seem  to  be 
hypercritical,  and  one  formula  to  be  equivalent  to  the  other, 
there  are  many  cases  of  the  highest  importance  in  which  it 


48  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

is  essential  to  any  intelligible  account  of  the  process.  A 
man,  for  example,  acts  in  a  given  way  under  the  influence 
of  vanity.  Although  he  knows  that  he  would  be  happier 
in  the  long-run  if  he  abandoned  some  burdensome  honour, 
his  self-esteem  nails  him  to  his  post.  He  is  governed  by 
the  instantaneous  feeling,  by  the  immediate  sense  that  a 
resignation  would  expose  him  to  ridicule  or  contempt.  And 
though  this  generally  includes  a  foretaste  of  future  suffering, 
he  is  determined  by  the  actual  painfulness  of  the  choice, 
not  by  the  belief  that  he  is  choosing  something  which  will 
produce  pain.  This  is  equally  true  of  all  the  feelings  which 
we  may  roughly  call  aesthetic  feelino-s — feelings  which  contain 
no  special  reference  to  the  future,  but  which  are  prompted 
by  immediate  perception.  The  same,  again,  may  be  said 
of  a  large  class  of  actions  which  seem  puzzling  to  many 
observers,  and  which  is  conveniently  illustrated  by  the  case 
of  games.  When  we  speak  of  conduct  as  determined  by  the 
pursuit  of  ends,  it  seems  to  be  contradictory  that  a  man 
should  take  a  keen  pleasure  in  the  pursuit  of  an  end  admit- 
tedly trifling,  the  slaughter,  for  example,  of  a  fox,  or  the 
solution  of  a  conundrum.  The  true  explanation,  however, 
seems  to  be  different.  The  pleasure  of  a  game,  speaking 
generally,  is  the  pleasure  of  a  discharge  of  accumulated 
energy.  We  are  "bored,"  that  is,  we  suffer  a  painful  sensa- 
tion, if  we  do  nothing  when  we  are  in  vigorous  health,  and 
therefore  we  receive  pleasure  in  doing  anything,  even  if  that 
anything  brings  us  no  additional  pleasure  in  itself.  The 
so-called  end  is  pleasant  simply  because  the  pursuit  affords 
a  convenient  pretext  for  a  regulated  discharge  of  energy. 
The  life  and  death  of  a  fox  is  absolutely  indifferent;  the 
exercise  of  the  powers  necessary  for  catching  and  killing  him 
may  be  momentarily  delio-htful.  The  stimulus  comes  from 
within,  not  from  without;  from  a  change  m  our  state,  not 
from  a  change  in  our  circumstances.  We  might  try  to 
describe  the  difference  by  distino-uishiniT  between  "  sub- 
jective"  and  "objective"  ends.  In  some  cases,  we  should 
then  say,  we  wish  to  relieve  our  feelings;  in  others,  to  bring 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        49 

about  some  state  of  things  which  does  not  at  present  affect 
our  feelings.  The  distinction  would  be  erroneous,  because 
every  end  must  be  at  once  objective  and  subjective.  It  must 
be  objective,  because  in  all  cases  our  conduct  has  certain 
objective  consequences,  that  is,  consequences  other  than  a 
state  of  our  own  consciousness;  and  it  must  be  subjective, 
because  it  cannot  be  an  end  unless  we  desire  it.  But  the 
distinction  corresponds  to  a  real  difference.  In  every  case  of 
rational  action  we  foresee  a  certain  set  of  consequences  as 
dependent  upon  our  conduct.  The  "intention"  of  the  agent  is 
defined  by  these  foreseen  consequences.  His  "end"  is  defined 
by  that  part  of  the  foreseen  consequences  which  he  actually 
desires,  and  the  end  defines  the  "motive,"  that  is,  the  feeling, 
which  actually  determines  conduct.  Now  it  is  true  that  in 
some  cases  the  immediate  feeling  is  all  that  is  consciously  opera- 
tive, and  we  care  comparatively  little  for  the  consequences 
in  any  other  relation,  though  we  may  distinctly  foresee  them, 
and  even  call  them  our  end.  In  other  cases,  on  the  contrary, 
the  conduct  is  only  adopted  in  view  of  certain  pleasures  to 
be  obtained  hereafter.  But  even  in  that  case  we  adopt  it 
because  the  foretaste  of  the  pleasure  is  itself  pleasurable. 
We  like  the  labour  which  is  to  bear  fruit  hereafter.  Hence 
we  easily  speak  of  ends  in  the  latter  case,  because  we  over- 
look the  existing  pleasure  which  exists  only  as  a  foretaste  of 
the  future  pleasure,  whilst  in  the  former  case  the  reference 
to  an  end  seems  to  involve  a  desire  for  an  end  not  in  itself 
desirable.  In  fact,  however,  though  one  element  or  the 
other  may  be  more  or  less  prominent,  though  the  motive 
may  be  more  easily  definable  in  objective  or  subjective 
languao-e,  and  the  pleasure  be  dependent  or  independent 
upon  the  representation  of  future  states  of  feeling,  the  two 
elements  must  always  be  present,  and  the  motive  be  an 
actually  existing  feeling. 

10.  I  think,  then,  that  the  metaphor  of  the  balance  is 
misleading,  and  that  the  conception  to  which  it  corresponds 
leads  to  many  fallacies.  It  is  misleading  because  it  implies 
an  erroneous  analysis,  and  separates  different  aspects  of  a 


so  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

single  process,  as  though  they  were  different  processes  succeed- 
ino;  each  other  in  time  instead  of  beino^  mutually  involved. 
The  intellect  and  the  emotion  are  in  reality  related  as  form  and 
substance,  and  cannot  be  really  divided.  To  judge  of  plea- 
sures is  to  feel  the  pleasures  themselves,  or  to  feel  represen- 
tative pleasures.  The  process  is  at  once  feeling  and  think- 
ing, and  may  be  regarded  from  either  point  of  view.  The 
emotion  is  something  determinate,  and  therefore  its  logical 
formula  may  be  given,  but  the  logic  without  the  feeling 
would  be  a  mere  blank  nonentity,  a  form  without  substance. 
This  is  equally  overlooked  when  we  regard  the  pleasure  as  a 
kind  of  independent  thing  which  the  intellect  weighs  and 
measures,  or  whether  we  try  to  resolve  it  into  a  perception  in- 
stead of  regarding  it  as  bound  up  in  the  perception.  It  seems 
to  me,  for  example,  inaccurate  to  say  that  vanity  is  the  belief 
that  we  are  superior  to  our  neighbours.  It  is  equally  inaccu- 
rate to  say  that  it  is  a  pleasure  which  results  from  that  belief 
as  a  consequent  in  time  following  an  antecedent.  It  is  the 
emotional  side  of  a  process  which,  upon  its  intellectual  side, 
is  a  belief;  it  is  a  feeling  evolved  by  bringing  together  in 
certain  ways  a  perception  of  our  own  qualities  and  those  of 
our  neighbours,  and  implies  equally  a  conviction  and  an 
emotion. 

II.  Falling  back,  then,  upon  the  original  principle,  I  repeat 
that  pain  and  pleasure  are,  according  to  me,  the  determining 
causes  of  action.  It  may  even  be  said  that  they  are  the  sole 
and  the  ultimate  causes.  They  are  the  sole  causes  in  this 
sense,  that  where  two  courses  of  conduct  are  otherwise  pos- 
sible, and  the  choice  of  one  depends  upon  the  agent's  own 
decision,  his  will  is  always  determined  by  the  actual  painful- 
ness  or  pleasantness  of  the  choice  at  the  moment  of  choos- 
ing, and  that  there  is  no  different  kind  of  motive.  They  are 
ultimate  in  this  sense,  that  it  is  impossible  to  analyse  pain  and 
pleasure  into  any  simpler  elements.  We  might  conceivablv 
find  the  physiological  causes  of  pain  and  pleasure;  we  might 
show,  that  is,  that  each  state  corresponded  to  certain  organic 
conditions;  but  such  a  discovery,  however  important,  would 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        51 

not  alter  the  fact  that  the  pain  and  pleasure  are  the  imme- 
diate causes  of  conduct,  and  that  they  admit  of  no  further 
analysis  from  the  subjective  point  of  view,  whatever  may  be 
the  physical  correlates.  We  mav,  again,  investigate  the  his- 
torical causes  of  the  pain  and  pleasure,  that  is,  we  may  trace 
the  previous  stao-es  throu2;h  which  the  sentient  bsino-  has 
come  to  be  what  it  is.  But  this,  thoucrh  a^rain  a  most  inter- 
esting  inquiry,  would  not  alter  the  fact  that  at  the  given 
moment  the  feelino-s,  beino-  such  as  thev  are,  determine  the 
conduct.  If  we  could  analyse,  in  short,  the  forces  which 
maintain  the  existing  order,  the  feelings  considered  as  painful 
or  pleasurable  would  represent  the  ultimate  elements  in  the 
analysis.  Any  attempt  to  analyse  further  only  lands  us  in 
contradiction  and  confusion.  The  fact  that  any  state  of  con- 
sciousness is  painful,  is  so  far  a  sufficient  reason  for  avoiding 
it — a  reason  which  may  be  overpowered  by  others,  and  which 
may  in  its  turn  admit  of  explanation;  but  so  far  as  it  goes, 
it  represents  a  true  cause,  and  one  which  must  always  operate. 
I  admit  that  so  far  as  the  act  of  choice  implies  a  weighing  of 
pains  and  pleasures,  the  pains  and  pleasures  are  alwavs  repel- 
lent and  attractive,  and  the  sole  measure  of  the  repulsion  and 
attraction.  I  only  deny  that  this  gives  an  adequate  account 
of  the  intimate  nature  of  the  process. 

13.  How,  then,  must  we  conceive  of  the  mode  of  action 
of  these  forces?  The  most  obvious  fact  seems  to  me  to  be 
that  in  all  cases  pain  as  pain  represents  tension,  a  state  of 
feeling,  that  is,  from  which  there  is  a  tendency  to  chano-e; 
pleasure  represents  so  far  equilibrium,  or  a  state  in  which 
there  is  a  tendency  to  persist.  Some  such  statement  repre- 
sents most  nearly  the  characteristic  of  all  emotional  states, 
from  the  lowest  upwards.  The  worm  writhes  on  the  hook, 
and  we  inevitably  interpret  the  writhing  as  indicative  of  ao-onv. 
The  mind  (if  I  may  say  so)  writhes  under  a  painful  emotion. 
It  makes  an  effort  to  writhe  into  some  more  tolerable  posture. 
Fear  implies  an  effort  to  get  away  from  the  painful  state  of 
anticipated  pain,  and  as  it  becomes  intense,  the  spasmodic 
struggle  becomes  so  desperate  as  to  render  any  definite  action 


52  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

impossible,  even  though  we  know  that  our  only  hope  lies  In 
cool  and  regulated  effort.  The  pain  of  continuous  illness 
produces  a  restlessness,  a  vague  unguided  effort  to  secure 
some  change,  even  though  no  specific  change  presents  itself 
as  desirable.    Similar  remarks  miirht  of  course  be  made  about 

O 

the  inverse  case  of  content  and  satisfaction.  When  I  choose 
I  go  through  a  process  of  a  complex  but  still  similar  kind. 
Two  modes  of  feeling  are  more  or  less  distinctly  present  to 
my  mind.  Each  is  recognised  perhaps  as  the  foretaste  of 
a  feeling  about  to  become  actual.  So  far  as  my  power  of 
volition  goes,  I  am  decided  by  the  relative  painfulness  or 
pleasurableness.  I  try  each  mode  ideally,  and  settle  down 
into  that  which  is  on  the  whole  the  easiest.  What  in  the 
actual  feeling  is  the  "writhing"  and  spasmodic  struggle  is, 
in  the  representative  feeling,  a  difficulty  in  admitting  the 
suggested  course  of  conduct.  When  I  am  satisfied,  my  mind 
acquiesces  and  slides  into  that  mode  of  action  which  causes 
the  least  disturbance. 

13.  The  analogy  which  naturally  offers  itself  and  seems  to 
give  the  best  account  of  the  facts  is  the  mechanical  principle  of 
least  resistance.  A  body  under  the  influence  of  several  forces 
moves  in  that  direction  in  which  the  resultant  of  the  opposing 
forces  is  a  minimum.  Similarly  the  various  desires  operate 
in  such  a  way  that  the  volition  discharges  itself  along  that 
line  in  which  the  balance  of  pleasure  over  pain  is  a  maximum. 
The  pleasurable  state  is  one  of  stable,  the  painful  one  of  un- 
stable equilibrium.  Alter  the  conditions  slightly  in  the  latter 
case,  and  the  agent  spontaneously  adopts  a  new  attitude, 
like  a  spring  relieved  from  pressure.  Alter  them  in  the  first 
case,  and  there  is  a  tendency  to  revert  to  the  previous  state. 
In  one  case  we  have  a  body  balanced  on  a  ridge  by  external 
forces,  and  ready  to  fall  at  once  if  the  supports  be  removed; 
in  the  other  we  have  a  body  so  balanced  that  after  a  slight 
change  it  will  always  tend  to  fall  back  to  the  original  position. 
It  is,  perhaps,  not  superfluous  to  remark,  in  order  to  avoid 
possible  misconstruction,  that  the  volition  may  exercise  a  very 
small  influence,   even   when  the    limiting  conditions  are   in 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        53 

great  part  ideal.  The  more  painful  is  not  necessarily  the 
less  permanent  condition.  It  is  one  in  which  there  is  an 
additional  chance  against  permanence.  A  painful  thought 
may  fascinate  the  attention.  Terror  sets  up,  as  I  have  said, 
so  disturbed  a  condition  that  the  mind  cannot  settle  into  any 
definite  course  :  the  hand  shakes  when  it  would  aim  the 
necessary  blow.  To  determine  even  the  subjective  conditions 
of  conduct  we  have  to  consider  the  fascination  as  well  as  the 
mere  painfulness  and  pleasurableness  of  the  emotions.  We 
can  no  more  alter  arbitrarily  the  circumstances  of  our  micro- 
cosm than  of  the  external  world.  The  painful  thought  cannot 
be  included  simplv  as  painful  if  it  excites  an  intense  emotion 
and  is  associated  by  many  links  with  all  our  habitual  objects 
of  thought,  even  though  we  may  know  that  the  pain  can- 
not suggest  a  remedy.  It  is  as  difficult  to  avoid  brooding 
over  vain  regret  as  to  evade  a  physical  constraint.  The  will 
becomes  paralvsed,  and  the  brave  man  feels  that  the  best 
course  is  to  face  the  pain  till  his  sensibility  becomes  deadened 
by  persistent  familiarity. 

14.  To  explain  the  theory  fully  it  would  thus  be  necessary 
to  consider  the  sphere  of  volition,  or  to  analyse  what,  accord- 
ing to  one  theory,  is  called  an  act  of  Free  Will.  I  have 
to  make  some  simple  choice,  say,  between  a  glass  of  wine 
and  a  glass  of  water.  The  process,  according  to  me,  consists 
essentiallv  in  rehearsing  the  two  modes  of  conduct  which  pre- 
sent themselves  to  my  mind.  I  am  moved  by  the  foretaste 
of  the  pleasure  of  drinking,  the  difficulty  of  reaching  either 
crlass,  the  dislike  to  expense,  the  moral  and  medical  scruples 
in  which  T  indulge,  and  so  forth  ;  and  the  decision  takes 
place  according  to  the  principle  of  least  resistance.  To 
analyse  all  the  operative  motives  may  be  impossible  even 
in  so  simple  a  case;  to  weigh  and  compare  their  importance 
in  general  terms  may  be  impossible ;  but  in  any  case,  I 
decide  by  the  simple  process  of  feeling  one  course  to  be  the 
easiest.  It  often  happens  that  each  course  will  be  the  easiest 
if  it  happens  to  be  the  one  most  directly  contemplated  ;  and 
it  will  in  that  case  be  a  matter  of  chance — that  is,  it  will 


54  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

depend  upon  other  circumstances  than  my  will — whether  I 
take  the  wine  or  the  water.  If  now  I  am  desh'ous  to  know 
what  will  be  the  result  of  some  process  entirely  independent 
of  my  volition — sa}'',  the  choice  of  another  person  in  the  same 
case — I  shall  equally  rehearse  all  approaching  signs  of  events. 
But  in  the  latter  case  my  mind  works  automatically  upon 
the  data  provided.  It  takes  certain  facts,  arranges  them 
according  to  logical  rules,  and  brings  out  a  conclusion  which 
does  not  follow  with  more  or  less  certainty  because  the  result 
is  painful  or  pleasurable.  My  volition  determines,  of  course, 
whether  I  shall  or  shall  not  reason.  If  I  choose  to  reason,  I 
apply  a  fixed  rule  which  (if  rightly  applied)  brings  out  a  fixed 
conclusion.  One  and  only  one  result  can  follow  from  the 
one  set  of  data.  In  the  other  case,  my  intellect  shows  two 
courses  to  be  equally  possible.  The  sequence  of  events  which 
terminates  in  wine  is  as  consistent  with  all  the  facts  as  the 
sequence  which  terminates  in  water.  One  of  the  series  then 
follows  by  introducing  the  additional  fact  that  it  is  the 
pleasantest.  I  may  say  that  it  follows  because  I  know  or 
perceive  it  to  be  the  pleasantest.  But  this,  as  I  have  explained, 
seems  to  me  to  be  a  roundabout  way  of  saying  that  I  feel 
it  to  be  pleasantest,  or,  more  simply,  that  it  is  the  pleasantest 
to  me ;  for  the  knowledge  is  here  the  very  same  thing  as  the 
feeling  in  a  reflective  mind ;  or,  if  knowledge  be  used  in  a 
wider  sense  to  include  the  represented  feeling,  the  feelino-  is 
the  fundamental  fact,  and  the  knowled<re  the  reflected  feelinjr. 
We  may  then  say  that  in  this  case  the  prediction  fulfils  itself. 
In  the  other  case,  I  foresee  a  fact  because  it  is  about  to 
happen.  In  this  case,  it  is  about  to  happen  because  I  foresee 
it.  My  anticipation  is  the  essential  condition  of  its  happen- 
ing; and  in  this  case  the  foresight  becomes  a  volition. 

15.  The  believer  in  free  will  (according  to  me)  misinterprets 
these  facts.  The  foresio-ht  of  events  is  of  the  same  nature 
in  the  two  cases  up  to  a  certain  point,  and  at  that  point  a 
further  condition  is  required  in  one  case  which  does  not  apply 
in  the  other.  As  this  condition  depends  upon  the  person 
who  foresees,  it  appears  to  be  arbitrary,  although  in  fact  it  is 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        55 

simply  an  expression  of  his  constitution.    When  we  see  another 
man  about  to  act,  we  assume  his  taste  to  be  one  of  the  data, 
and   calculate  his  action  as  we  calculate   any  other  future 
event.     When  it  is  our  own,  we  fancy  in  some  obscure  sense 
that  it  is  in  our  power  that  it  should  exist  or  not  exist,  and 
therefore  regard  the  whole  decision  as  arbitrary.     I  do  not 
wish,  however,  to  dwell  upon  this  argument,  but  to  point 
out  another  fact  which  is  sometimes  neglected — the  difficulty 
we  have  in  drawing;  the  distinction  between  the  two  kinds  of 
foresight  accordingly.     Slow  experience  teaches  us  what  is 
the  true  sphere  of  volition.    Our  prevision  of  our  own  conduct 
is  exceedinfrlv  fallible.     Nothing:;  is  more  common  than  to 
mistake  wishes  for  anticipations  and  dislikes  for  disbelief.     A 
perfectly  logical  mind  would  draw  conclusions  unbiassed  by 
pain  and  pleasure.     The  hatred  of  error  would  overbalance 
the  painfulness  of  anticipation.     Its  emotions  would  decide 
it  to  add   up  its  accounts;   but  they   would   be   unable  to 
persuade  it  that  two   and   two   make  five.     But  nothing  is 
easier  than  to  find  a  mind  which  never  permits  its  anticipations 
to  intrude  beyond  their  proper  sphere.    The  logical  mill  once 
set  going  must  grind  out  results  irrespective  of  their  pain  or 
pleasure;  but  we  dread  to  set  it  going  or  tamper  with  its 
action.    We  are  apt,  in  vulgar  phrase,  to  "cook"  our  accounts. 
The  reluctance  of  the  mind  to  gaze  upon  painful  facts  prevents 
us  from  setting  the  sum  precisely;  and  as  we  tamper  with  the 
materials  at  every  stage  of  the  process,  we  end  with  that  mass 
of  contradictions  and  baseless  prejudices  which  we  know  as 
human  beliefs.     It  is  only  by  long  experience,  in  short,  that 
we  learn  what  are  the  predictions  which  can  fulfil  themselves, 
and  those  which  have  no  effect  upon  the  future.     If  it  is  still 
hard  to  resist  the  illusion  that  a  thing  will  happen  because 
wc  desire  it,  it  is  intellio-ible  how  all  the  reli(2;ions  which  are 
rooted  in  early  stages  of  mental  development  sanction  the 
propensity  to  hold  that  fate  can  be  conquered  by  will,  and 
that   prayers — the   embodiment   of  desires — can   govern   the 
stars  in  their  courses.     Anticipation  and  volition  spring  from 
the  same  root,  and  it  is  by  a  very  gradual  and  difficult  process 


56  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

that  we  learn  to  assign  to  each  its  proper  sphere  in  our  inental 
operations. 

1(5.  The  difficulty  of  knowing  what  we  desire  is  as  great  as 
the  difficulty  of  estimating  the  efficacy  of  our  desires.  The 
play  of  motive  is  beyond  measure  complicated.  We  may 
meet  even  with  apparently  contradictory  cases,  such  as  the 
apparent  delight  of  many  people  in  contemplating  the  darkest 
probabilities.  The  full  explanation  must  be  left  to  psycho- 
logists. It  is  partly  perhaps  that  there  is  an  actual  pain  in 
trying  to  reconcile  the  belief  in  a  particular  form  of  good 
fortune  with  a  general  reputation  of  evil.  It  requires  a 
painful  effort  to  shake  off  doubts  and  fears  which  have  become 
familiar.  More  frequently  perhaps  it  is  the  shrinking  by 
anticipation  from  the  shock,  so  trying  to  a  sensitive  nature, 
which  follows  the  disturbance  of  a  pleasant  dream  ;  we  would 
rather  have  bad  dreams  than  encounter  the  possible  jar  of  a 
sudden  awakening ;  or  vanitv,  for  some  reason,  makes  the 
effort  to  throw  off  the  painful  emotion  still  more  painful 
than  persistence ;  or  perhaps,  most  frequently,  we  are  simply 
making  a  convenient  pretext  for  a  display  of  bad  temper  or 
melancholy  which  has  been  generated  by  some  other  cause. 
To  follow  out  such  arijuments  would  lead  me  too  far.  I  must 
conclude  this  discussion  by  repeating  once  more  the  main 
conclusion  which  I  have  sought  to  establish;  for  it  seems  to 
me  that  a  clear  theory  of  ethics  can  only  be  attained  by  a 
clear  understanding  of  a  proposition  which,  as  misunderstood, 
contains  the  ererms  of  countless  fallacies. 

17.  The  true  proposition,  then,  that  conduct  is  determined 
by  the  feelings,  has  been  constantly  confounded  with  the 
erroneous  proposition  that  it  is  determined  by  the  agent's 
judgment  of  his  happiness.  This  is  expressed  in  the  form 
that  the  will  is  determined  bv  a  kind  of  syllogism.  The 
major  premiss  is  invariably — I  will  adopt  the  course  of  con- 
duct which  will  j^roduce  the  greatest  balance  of  happiness. 
I  am  unable  to  admit  the  accuracy  of  this  statement, 
although  I  do  not  deny  that  in  many  cases  it  is  an 
approximate    statement  of   the  case.       So  far  from    admit- 


THE  EMOTIONS  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.        57 

ting  the  second  proposition  to  be  an  expansion  of  the 
first,  I  hold  them  to  be  really  inconsistent.  The  feeling 
which  determines  conduct  is  not  a  judgment  at  all,  though 
it  is  inseparably  bound  up  with  serious  judgments.  It  is  a 
simple  unanalysable  fact.  If  we  would,  not  define,  but  de- 
scribe the  feelino-  in  other  words,  we  should  rather  call  it  a 
psychical  force.  Love  and  hatred,  desire  and  aversion,  deter- 
mine our  conduct  as  physical  forces  determine  the  move- 
ments of  a  bodv.  Thev  have  a  definite  more  or  less  ascer- 
tainable  value,  of  which  we  can  form  a  judgment,  but  which 
is  not  itself  a  judgment.  The  sense  of  fatigue,  for  example, 
puts  an  absolute  limit  upon  my  energies,  and  implies  no 
direct  reference  to  any  future  pains  or  pleasure.  It  is 
there  in  such  and  such  a  degree,  and  we  can  say  no  more 
about  it.  It  is,  or  may  be,  the  subjective  correlate  of 
certain  objective  phenomena  which  might  be  described  in 
terms  of  nervous  force,  muscular  tension,  and  so  forth,  and 
is  equally  definite  in  its  relations.  The  same  is  equally  true 
with  all  the  direct  emotions  and  sensations.  They  are 
what  they  are,  and  underlie  all  judgments,  instead  of  being  a 
product  of  those  judgments.  The  possibility  of  forming  any 
judgment  as  to  future  pains  or  pleasures  presupposes  their 
existence  as  the  existence  of  forces  is  presupposed  in  calculat- 
ing their  actions  and  reactions.  So  far,  again,  there  is  no 
ground  for  supposing  that  our  pains  and  pleasures  are  in  any 
way  regulated  with  a  view  to  future  enjoyments  or  suffer- 
ino-s.  This  consideration  beg-ins  to  su^rgcst  itself  so  flir  as  our 
immediate  pains  and  pleasures  are  recognised  as  foretastes  of 
pains  and  pleasures  to  come.  In  that  case,  which  is,  of  course, 
more  or  less  the  case  of  nearly  all  the  actions  of  reasoning 
beings,  the  actual  enjoyment,  and  therefore  the  conduct,  is 
more  or  less  affected  by  our  previsions  of  the  future.  A 
secondary  action  is  set  up  which  tends  to  regulate  the  play 
of  the  passions.  It  may  happen,  but,  so  far  as  we  have  gone, 
it  may  also  not  happen,  that  the  passions  may  be  so  regulated 
that  the  conduct  dictated  by  our  immediate  feelings  may  coin- 
cide with  that  which  would  be  dictated  by  a  judgment  of  our 


58  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

total  happiness.  And  this  leads  us  to  the  next  problem  to  be 
attacked.  We  can  only  be  affected  by  the  prospect  of  the 
future  in  so  far  as  we  are  reasoning  beings.  We  must,  there- 
fore, consider  in  what  sense  the  mere  blind  action  of  imme- 
diate feelino;  is  o;overned  and  reo-ulated  bv  the  reason:  for 
the  principles  hitherto  considered  do  not  imply  a  conscious 
regard  to  general  rules.  A  man's  action  at  each  point  is 
determined  by  his  feelings,  and  therefore  his  whole  course  de- 
pends upon  the  varying  feeling,  or,  in  other  words,  upon  its 
law.  But  this  is  equally  true  of  man  and  beast,  and  does  not 
show  what  is  implied  in  the  acceptance  of  a  general  rule. 


III.   The  Reason  as  Determining:  Conduct. 

18.  We  have  therefore  to  consider  in  what  sense  the 
conduct  of  every  man  is  determined  by  his  reason.  I  must 
begin  by  taking  note  of  one  obvious  but  important  distinction. 
There  is  a  sense  in  which  we  all  admit  that  the  universe  is 
reasonable  throughout — the  sense,  namely,  in  which  we  simply 
assert  the  validity  of  the  universal  postulate ;  a  sense  in  which 
there  is  no  distinction  in  point  of  reasonableness  between  the 
fill  of  a  stone  and  the  workino:  of  a  loo-ician's  brain.  As  we 
rise  from  the  inoro;anic  to  the  oro-anic,  and  a2:ain  from  the 
lowest  to  the  highest  organism,  the  working  formula,  if  I 
may  give  that  name  to  what  is  generally  called  the  law  of 
the  phenomena,  becomes  continually  more  complex,  and 
soon  surpasses  all  our  powers  of  statement.  Every  conceiv- 
able event  is,  however,  in  this  sense  reasonable;  which  is 
only  to  endorse  once  more  the  familiar  assertion  that  chance 
is  but  a  name  for  ignorance.  In  this  sense,  again,  no  conduct 
could  be  more  or  less  "reasonable"  than  any  other.  The 
most  foolish  vagaries  of  the  most  illogical  mind  have  their 
cause,  and  would  be  explained  if  we  could  look  into  the 
mind  of  the  agent.  The  errors  of  the  puzzleheaded  have 
their  ^' reason "  as  much  as  the  soundest  judgments  of  the 
clearest  thinker.  It  is  plain,  therefore,  that  we  must  use  the 
word  in  a  different  sense  when  we  make  it  the  basis  of  a 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  59 

distinction  between  one  thing  and  another.  When  we  sav 
that  the  conduct  of  Plato  is  reasonable,  and  that  the  dog  or 
the  stone  acts  instinctivelv  or  mechanicallv,  we  incan  that 
Plato  has  a  mind  capable  of  apprehending  a  general  rule,  and 
carrying  on  certain  logical  processes,  and  that  these  circum- 
stances determine  his  conduct.  He  is  a  conscious  and 
reasoning  subject  as  well  as  an  object;  and  the  distinction 
might  perhaps  be  expressed  by  saying,  that  whereas  everv 
conceivable  phenomenon  is  objectively  reasonable,  or,  in  the 
common  phrase,  has  an  assignable  "  law,"  intelligent  beings 
alone  are  subjectively  reasonable,  or  determined  in  their 
conduct  bv  perceptions  and  inferences.  In  this  latter  sense 
men  may  be  reasonable  or  unreasonable  in  the  most  varying 
degrees.  In  the  former,  the  unreasonable  is  the  contradictory, 
or,  in  other  words,  the  non-existent. 

19.  Taking  reason,  then,  in  the  only  sense  in  which  it 
affords  a  basis  of  distinction,  we  shall  find,  I  think,  that 
conduct  is  generally  called  reasonable  in  several  connected 
but  not  identical  senses.  Sometimes  we  are  told  that  a  man 
is  reasonable  in  so  far  as  his  reason  controls  his  passions.  The 
reason  is  a  separate  faculty  which  in  some  way  rules  or  sup- 
plants the  other  faculties.  A  man,  again,  mav  be  called 
reasonable  so  far  as  he  possesses  the  faculty  in  a  high  degree, 
as  he  apprehends  certain  general  rules,  and  as  they  affect  his 
conduct;  and  this,  again,  may  imply,  on  the  one  hand,  that 
he  reasons  accurately,  and  so  has  conceptions  of  the  world 
corresponding  to  the  realitv,  or,  on  the  other  hand,  that  his 
judgment  of  what  is  most  desirable  is  fixed  and  consistent. 
In  this,  too,  it  is  implied  that  he  acts  in  such  a  way  as  really 
to  brino;  about  what  he  desires,  or  that  he  knows  how  to 
proportion  means  to  ends.  And,  finally,  we  may  mean 
something  beyond  all  this,  namely,  that  his  ultimate  ends 
are  "reasonable"  or  worthy  in  some  sense  not  yet  defined. 
Reason,  in  short,  may  be  opposed  to  passion  or  to  want  of 
thought,  or  to  want  of  proportion  between  mean  and  ends,  or 
may  indicate  consistency  and  loftiness  of  purpose.  The  animal, 
the  man   of  sudden   and   incontrollable  impulse,  the  simple 


6o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

dunce,  or  the  consistent  and  calculating  man  who  yet  aims 
at  some  purely  sensual  or  selfish  end,  may  each  be  called 
unreasonable.  In  trying  to  answer  the  question  before  us, 
what,  namelv,  are  the  characteristics  of  reasoned  as  dis- 
tinguished from  unreasoned  action  ?  we  shall  incidentally 
consider  these  various  senses. 

30.  The  supposed  conflict  between  reason  and  passion  is,  as 
I  hold,  meaningless  if  it  is  taken  to  imply  that  the  reason 
is  a  faculty  separate  from  the  emotions,  and  contemplating 
them  as  an  external  spectator.  Reasoning  and  feeling  are, 
according  to  me,  bound  together  in  an  inseparable  unity. 
Every  act  of  choice  is  a  struggle  between  passions  involving 
more  or  less  reasonins:,  but  not  resolvable  into  an  emotionless 
process.  The  man  who  is  distracted  between  the  charms  of  gin 
and  duty  is  not  divided  between  passion  and  reason,  but 
between  a  sensual  pleasure  and  the  love  of  home,  or  the  fear 
of  hell,  or  the  diso;ust  of  conscious  degradation.  If  resistance 
to  these  emotions  gave  him  no  pain  he  would  not  resist. 
There  must  be  emotion  on  both  sides,  as  well  as  reason  on 
both  sides,  or  a  struggle  would  be  impossible.  It  may  be 
that  a  reasonable  man  is  more  likely  than  an  unreasonable 
to  resist  the  temptation  to  drunkenness — that  is,  that  the 
greater  the  development  of  the  reasoning  faculties  the  less 
the  love  of  gin — as  the  inverse  proposition  is  pretty  generally 
true.  But  this  is  a  very  different  statement,  and  points  to  a 
different  process  of  indisputable  reality.  Reason,  in  short, 
whatever  its  nature,  is  the  faculty  which  enables  us  to  act 
.  with  a  view  to  the  distant  and  the  future.  Consequently, 
in  so  far  as  a  man  is  reasonable,  he  is  under  the  influence  of 
motives  which  would  not  be  otherwise  operative.  The 
immediate  bodily  appetite  is  held  in  check  by  a  number  of 
motives  to  which  only  the  reasoning  being  is  accessible.  His 
mind's  eye  sees  not  only  the  public-house  but  the  absent  wife. 
The  reason  so  far  leads  a  man  to  multiply  the  data  from 
which  his  conduct  is  calculable,  or  the  more  reasonable  a 
man  may  be  the  greater  the  variety  of  ways  in  which  his 
feelinsrs  will  be  interested. 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  6i 

2T.  The  impression,  however,  which  leads  us  to  oppose 
feeling  to  reason  is  partly  due  to  another  fact.  A  large  part 
of  our  conduct  is  automatic;  it  is  either  not  detcraTiined  by- 
conscious  motives,  or  it  is  determined  by  motives  which, 
though  they  rise  for  a  moment  to  the  surface  of  consciousness, 
are  forgotten  as  soon  as  felt.  Of  our  conscious  conduct, 
again,  part  may  be  caljed  instinctive  and  part  reasonable, 
according  as  the  motive  does  or  does  not  include  some  refer- 
ence to  ulterior  ends.  These  modes  of  action  pass  into  each 
other  by  imperceptible  degrees.  We  say  that  the  bird 
building  a  nest  acts  instinctively,  meaning  to  denv  that  it 
has  any  view  of  the  consequences,  and  to  assert  that  it  builds 
because  the  act  of  building  is  in  itself  pleasant  or  the  not 
building  painful.  A  man  may,  in  the  same  wav,  eat  his 
dinner  instinctively,  that  is,  without  contemplating  the  con- 
sequences to  his  health,  and  the  same  act  may  be  reasoned 
when  those  consequences  are  taken  into  account;  w^hen, 
for  example,  he  eats  purposely  to  gain  strength  for  a  special 
contingency.  The  instinct  may  be  converted  into  reason  as 
the  consequences  become  manifest,  and  the  reasoned  action 
become  instinctive  as  the  consequences  are  left  out  of  account. 
So,  again,  the  instinctive  action  becomes  automatic  when  it 
is  done  without  leaving  any  trace  upon  consciousness.  It 
raav  still  be  voluntarv  in  the  sense  that  the  ag^ent  may  be 
able  to  refrain  if  his  attention  happens  to  be  aroused. 
Habitual  actions  pass  through  all  these  gradations.  We  do 
a  thing  first  with  some  conscious  motive;  we  come  to  do 
it  without  reference  to  other  consequences,  and  even  without 
consciousness;  and  the  difference  is,  that  w^hereas  the  action 
previously  required  some  effort,  it  now  requires  an  effort  to 
refrain  from  the  action.  We  are  like  a  man  walkino-  in 
chains,  who  for2:ets  their  existence  until  somethins:  leads 
him  to  diverge  from  the  line  imposed,  and  consequentlv  to 
be  galled  by  the  restraint.  The  motive  is  thus  a  latent  force 
which  only  manifests  itself  in  consciousness  under  some 
opposing  action. 

22.  Let  us  now  return  to  our  gin-drinker.     He  feels  the 


62  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

desire,  we  may  suppose,  but  the  desire  is  instantly  quenched 
by  the  bare  thought,  say,  of  duty,  or  of  the  injury  to  his  family. 
We  say,  in  popular  language,  that  his  passion  has  been 
quelled  by  reason.  The  mere  intellectual  perception,  however, 
could  have  no  effect  if  the  sense  of  duty  and  love  of  family  did 
not  represent  a  strong  fund  of  emotion  capable  of  being  called 
into  vigorous  operation.  His  conscience  or  his  family  affec- 
tions have  generated  a  habit.  He  has  become  an  intellectual 
automaton.  He  acts  by  a  certain  rule  without  calling  into  active 
play  the  feelings  by  which  the  habit  was  orginally  generated. 
It  now  reqnires  an  effort  to  break  through  that  rule  as  it 
formerly  required  an  effort  to  act  in  accordance  with  it.  The 
thought  of  family  or  duty  is  enough  to  convert  the  act  of 
drinking,  which  just  before  was  simply  the  satisfaction  of  a 
natural  instinct,  into  a  breach  of  a  settled  rule.  The  habit 
probably  acts  without  converting  more  of  the  latent  force  into 
an  active  form  than  is  necessary  for  the  purpose  of  counter- 
acting the  temptation.  The  intellectual  operation  brings  his 
action  under  a  new  category,  and  so  far  it  is  quite  true  that 
his  passion  is  conquered  by  reason  ;  but  it  is  not  in  virtue  of 
the  purely  logical  operation,  but  of  the  fact  that  the  reason 
reveals  a  new  set  of  forces  ready  to  spring  into  action  to  the 
necessary  degree. 

23.  We  may  thus  be  said  to  feel  by  signs  as  well  as  to  reason 
by  signs.  When  we  are  conducting  a  logical  operation  we 
easily  call  up  the  full  meaning  of  the  symbols  by  which  the 
operation  is  conducted.  Symbols  are  useful  precisely  because 
they  enable  us  to  dispense  with  that  laborious  process.  In 
the  same  way  our  feelings  are  determined  without  callino- 
into  active  operation  the  full  meaning  which  they  may  con- 
vey. The  sight  of  a  red  flag  may  deter  me  from  crossing  a 
rifle  range  without  calling  up  to  my  imagination  all  the 
effects  of  a  bullet  traversing  my  body.  If  the  motive  which 
prompts  me  to  run  the  risk  be  strong,  it  may  be  necessary  to 
convert  a  greater  volume  of  latent  into  active  emotion;  and 
as  we  frequently  fail  to  do  this,  we  often  run  risks  which  we 
should  avoid  were  the  consecjuences  distinctly  contemplated- 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  63 

We  steer  our  course  bv  au  apparcutly  insiguificant  rudder,  and 
only  call  out  forces  sufficient  to  overcome  the  actual  resistance. 
But  it  would  be  a  great  error  to  assume  that  the  mere  call 
would  be  sufficient  if  the  force  were  not  at  hand  and  ready  to 
supply  the  necessary  assistance.  And  thus,  if  I  may  say  so, 
the  game  is  generally  decided  as  experienced  players  decide 
games,  bv  a  simple  show  of  cards  on  both  sides  without 
actuallv  playing  out  the  moves. 

24.  No  theory  can  be  tenable  which  virtually  asserts  reason 
and  feeling  to  be  two  separate  and  independent  faculties,  one 
of  which  can  properly  be  said  to  govern  the  other.  The 
reason  is  not  something  superinduced  upon  the  emotions  as 
something  entirely  new.  There  is  no  absolute  gap  between 
the  lower  and  the  higher  organisms.  The  animal  instinct 
may  be  regarded  as  implicit  reason,  or  the  reason  as  a  highly 
developed  instinct.  Instinct  is  reason  limited  to  the  imme- 
diate, and  incapable  of  reflecting  upon  its  own  operations ; 
and  reason  an  extended  instinct,  apprehending  the  distant 
and  becoming  conscious  of  its  own  modes  of  action.  The 
development  of  the  whole  nature  implies  a  development  both 
of  the  intellectual  and  the  emotional  nature.  The  growth  of 
new  sensibilities  implies  a  power  of  detecting  new  qualities 
and  new  relations  between  phenomena;  and  the  growth  of 
mechanical  power  implies  the  capacity  of  bringing  things  into 
fresh  combinations,  and  so  developing  new  sentiments.  The 
increased  range  of  thought  due  to  the  power  of  forming 
abstract  conceptions  and  reasoning  by  symbols  is  associated 
with  an  equal  growth  in  the  complexity  and  variety  of  the 
corresponding  emotions.  That  we  may  have  a  nature  capable 
of  being  stirred  by  such  words  as  patriotism,  philosophy,  and 
religion,  we  must  not  only  have  an  intellect  capable  of  opera- 
tions utterly  beyond  the  reach  of  the  lower  being,  but  we 
must  also  have  sensibility  capable  of  a  vast  variety  of  equally 
new  sensibilities.  It  is  natural,  however,  that  we  should 
look  upon  the  intellectual  development  as  constituting  the 
essence  of  the  change,  and  interpret  the  finer  methods  by 
which  the  conflict  of  feeling  is  decided  in  the  more  developed 


64  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

nature  as  implying  that  feeling  is  superseded  by  reason. 
This  interpretation,  however,  is  really  as  erroneous  as  would 
be  the  opinion  that  the  finer  instruments  which  enable  us  to 
attain  great  mechanical  results  by  a  trifling  expenditure  of 
force  enable  us  to  dispense  with  force  altogether.  A  child 
can  raise  a  vast  weight,  with  the  help  of  certain  machinerv, 
by  touching  a  spring  or  starting  an  electric  current.  We  do 
not  infer  that  the  effort  is  produced  without  force.  Similarly, 
the  delicate  and  complex  mechaiiical  operations  of  a  highly 
oro-anised  intellect  may  govern  the  conduct  of  the  a(»;ent 
without  evolving  any  great  expenditure  of  emotion.  But  it 
is  not  that  he  acts  without  emotion,  only  that  his  emotions 
act  by  more  complex  and  refined  methods.  A  word  governs 
them  where  the  duller  mind  would  require  the  actual  stimu- 
lus of  a  powerful  passion. 

25.  Our  problem,  then,  is  not  how  does  a  reasoning  differ 
from  an  unreasoning  being,  but  how  does  the  being  at  a 
higher  stage  of  development,  both  intellectual  and  emotional, 
differ  from  the  being  who  is  in  both  respects  at  a  lower 
stage?  But  it  must  also  be  observed  that,  in  spite  of  the 
close  connection  between  the  two  elements,  it  is  possible  to 
consider  them  separately.  The  intellectual  faculties,  for  ex- 
ample, may  vary,  whilst  the  emotional  remain  constant.  It 
is  common  to  speak  as  though  the  reason  might  grow  at  the 
expense  of  the  emotions,  and  vice  versa  :  and  though  we 
may  criticise  the  form  of  the  statement,  it  represents  the 
undeniable  fact  that  emotional  activity  is,  in  particular  cases, 
vuifavourable  to  certain  forms  of  intellectual  activity.  In- 
capacity for  certain  modes  of  fueling  must  limit  our  sphere  of 
experience  in  the  matter  of  knowledge,  but  great  excitabilitv 
of  the  same  feelings  may  hinder  us  from  performing  the 
logical  operations  which  always  require  a  certain  calm.  The 
most  obvious  measure  of  intellectual  power  is  the  accuracy 
with  which  our  ideal  constructions  represent  the  actual  world 
outside,  and  this  may  vary  greatly  in  different  moods  with- 
out a  corresponding  variation  in  its  emotional  quality.  We 
may  conceive,  for  example,  that  two  beings  might  be  equally 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  65 

absorbed  by  the  passion  of  hunger;  both  might  regard  the 
world  as  a  gigantic  kitchen,  and  arrange  all  possible  objects 
under  the  simple  categories  of  eatable  and  non-eatable.  But 
one  mi<j;ht  difl'er  widely  from  the  other  in  the  accuracy  of  his 
judgments  as  to  what  was  and  what  was  not  eatable,  and  his 
skill  in  devising;  means  for  conveying;  the  eatable  into  his 
stomach.  The  reasoning-  being;  lives  in  a  larg;er  world  than 
the  unreasoning,  and  he  is  so  far  more  reasonable  as  his  world 
is  more  real.  The  height  of  unreason,  in  this  sense,  is  repre- 
sented by  the  case  in  which  a  man  is  under  an  illusion,  and 
supposes  his  limbs  to  be  glass,  or  fancies  that  he  can  hold  a 
fire  in  his  hand  by  thinking;  on  the  Caucasus.  Still  the  most 
perfect  sanity  and  the  most  delicate  adjustment  of  means  to 
end,  though  it  includes  certain  modes  of  conduct,  leaves  a 
very  wide  margin  of  character;  and  men  may  be,  in  this 
sense,  equally  reasonable  whilst  varying  indefinitely  in  con- 
duct. 

2,6.  The  same  considerations  apply  if  we  take  a  different  test. 
The  accurate  representation  of  the  world  implies  an  accurate 
representation  of  our  own  feelings.  A  reasonable  man,  we 
say,  knows  his  own  mind,  a  knowledge  which,  as  satirists 
and  philosophers  agree,  is  of  the  rarest.  The  sentiment 
excited  by  any  general  name  should  represent  that  which  is 
actually  excited  in  each  particular  case.  If  I  accept  the 
principle  of  loving  all  men,  I  am  inconsistent  in  hating  any 
individual  of  the  class  man.  It  would  be  extravagantly  "  un- 
reasonable "  to  be  charitable  to  every  sufferer  unless  he  had, 
say,  red  hair  or  a  black  skin.  In  many  such  cases  the  eccen- 
tricity amounts  to  a  temporary  change  of  character.  The 
sight  of  some  hated  symbol  has  a  kind  of  physiological  influ- 
ence which  rouses  the  wild  beast  within  the  man,  and  for  the 
time  turns  the  philanthropist  into  a  ruffian.  The  man,  as 
the  phrase  goes,  is  no  longer  himself.  So,  in  other  cases,  the 
man  who  is  a  stoic  in  his  ideal  world  gives  way  to  senti- 
ment in  the  world  of  realities.  This  is,  of  course,  possible 
and  common  enough,  and  the  development  of  reason  will 
tend   to   restrain   such   oscillations,  as   the   widened   area   of 


66  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

observation,  the  increased  tendency  to  view  the  world  as  a 
connected  whole,  and  to  bring  all  observations  under  general 
principles  must  give  continuity  and  consistency  to  the  conduct 
of  life.  We  perceive  that  we  act  at  different  moments  upon 
different  principles;  that  at  one  time  our  conduct  is  deter- 
mined by  such  purely  superficial  considerations  as  the  dislike 
to  a  particular  colour,  whilst  at  another  we  go  beyond  the 
superficial  consideration  to  the  interests  of  the  human  being 
which  are  independent  of  such  trifles.  Reason  will  tend  to 
make  such  real  inconsistencies  vanish.  But  it  does  not  ap- 
pear that  the  bare  condition  of  logical  consistency  is  suffi- 
cient to  eliminate  eccentricities.  There  is  always  some  cause 
for  the  wildest  vagary  or  the  most  unreasonable  prejudice. 
To  give  a  merely  formal  consistency  to  my  conduct,  it  is  suffi- 
cient that  this  cause  should  become  a  reason;  that  the  motives 
by  which  I  am  actually  determined  should  be  represented  in 
the  general  rules  which  I  frame.  If  hatred  to  the  red-haired 
actually  influences  me,  I  have  only  to  dislike  the  red-haired 
man  in  theory  as  much  as  I  dislike  him  in  fact  to  make  my 
conduct  consistent  in  a  formal  sense.  It  is,  of  course,  true  that 
this  process  of  conscious  representation  of  my  actual  character 
will  tend  to  modify  the  character  itself;  for  it  may  be  that 
the  motives  by  which  I  am  in  fact  prompted  will  no  longer 
commend  themselves  when  I  try  to  generalise  the  principles 
which  they  embody  and  to  fit  them  with  a  code  of  conduct. 
Still  it  would  seem  that  the  most  eccentric  set  of  pre- 
judices might  be  stated  coherently  inasmuch  as  they  do 
in  fact  represent  real  qualities  of  a  single  individual.  In 
other  words,  the  bare  condition  of  logical  consistence,  of  the 
absence  of  direct  contradiction  from  the  feelings  by  which 
I  am  prompted  in  my  ideal  constructions,  and  in  the  actual 
occurrence  of  the  case  represented,  does  not  suffice  to  define 
my  conduct  any  more  than  the  accuracy  with  which  my 
ideal  constructions  correspond  to  the  outside  world.  And 
for  this  reason,  as  it  seems  to  me,  it  is  impossible  to  deduce 
laws  of  conduct  frovn  the  bare  condition  of  consistency. 
Any  kind  of  conduct  will  satisfy  that  condition  if  the  objective 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  67 

reason  or  course  of  actioii  be  converted  into  the  subjective 
cause  or  reason  for  action. 

27.  But  the  development  of  our  reason  doubtless  implies 
more  than  a  mere  process  of  formulating  our  existing  senti- 
ments— something  beyond  a  mere  superioritv  in  the  adapta- 
tion of  means  to  ends  or  in  the  knowledge  of  our  own 
characters  and  the  external  world,  l^hat  this  must  be  so 
follows,  indeed,  from  the  connection  between  the  intellectual 
and  the  emotional  development.  The  man  differs  from  the 
beast,  not  simply  by  the  addition  of  a  faculty  which  enables 
him  more  effectually  to  gratify  the  same  passions,  but  by  the 
growth  of  a  new  set  of  emotions,  which  only  exist  in  germ, 
if  they  exist  at  ail,  in  the  inferior  beings.  We  have  to  ask, 
then,  how  far  this  consideration  will  help  to  determine  the 
nature  of  reasoned  conduct.  We  come  upon  the  track  of 
the  old  discussion  as  to  the  siimmum  bonum,  that  chief  o-ood 
which,  it  was  conceived,  must  be  desired  by  every  one  in 
virtue  of  his  being  reasonable.  If,  in  fact,  it  were  possible  to 
define  any  such  end  as  is  implied  in  all  reasoned  conduct,  we 
should  be  at  least  on  the  way  to  a  highly  important  conclu- 
sion. Let  us  see  how  the  difficulty  presents  itself  at  this 
point  of  the  inquiry. 

28.  We  will  assume  for  a  moment  that  we  may  consider  all 
human  conduct  as  determined  by  some  single  end ;  that  there 
is  some  constant  and  definable  object  towards  which  all 
desires  converge,  and  which  is  common  to  all  men.  This  is 
to  assume,  if  we  look  at  the  problem  from  the  other  side, 
that  all  the  feelings  by  which  we  are  prompted  may  be  reo^arded 
as  modifications  of  some  single  instinct.  Man  will  resemble 
the  conventional  miser  whose  sole  object  in  life  is  to  make 
money,  or,  in  the  other  mode  of  statement,  whose  sole  passion 
is  avarice.  So  far  as  this  can  be  re<rarded  as  at  all  representing- 
the  facts  of  the  case,  the  influence  of  increased  rationality 
will  be  obvious.  For  it  is  plain  that  so  far  as  the  man 
becomes  more  reasonable,  all  his  activities  will  be  brouo-ht  to 
converge  upon  a  single  line  of  action.  Since  the  various 
subsidiary  ends  have  a  common  measure,  his  reason  will  enable 


68  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

him  to  compare  them,  as  the  miser  compares  different  courses 
of  action,  simply  in  respect  of  the  pecuniary  profit.  This 
increased  rationality  will  thus  manifest  itself  in  an  increased 
skill  in  proportioning  means  to  ends,  and  in  a  more  com- 
plete knowledge  of  his  own  character.  He  will  have  to  learn 
by  experience  how  far  new  combinations  of  circumstances 
will  gratify  his  ruling  (or  rather  his  sole)  passion,  which  is 
the  same  thing  as  discovering  what  is  the  law  of  the  passion. 
He  is  comparing  modes  of  feeling  identical  in  kind,  and  to 
discover  how  he  feels  under  given  circumstances  is  to  discover 
what  circumstances  he  prefers.  This  may  often  be  difficult, 
inasmuch  as  it  mav  be  difficult  to  brins;  tocrether  in  thouo-ht 
two  different  states;  but  the  criterion  is  always  simple, 
namely,  the  balance  of  gratification  in  one  way  or  the  other. 
Finally,  the  fullest  development  of  the  reason  would  not,  so 
far,  serve  to  determine  the  problem  what  is  this  sole  or 
master  passion.  That  still  remains  as  an  arbitrary  or  entirely 
undetermined  element  in  the  problem ;  though  if  it  could 
once  be  fixed,  the  remainder  of  the  problem  would  be  deter- 
minate. Given  the  love  of  money,  or  of  any  other  definite 
object  as  determining  all  the  activities,  and  the  rest  is  a 
question  of  calculation.  All  the  rules  of  action  would  appear 
as  co-ordinated  into  a  systematic  whole  as  different  applica- 
tions of  the  one  fundamental  principle,  "  Get  money ; "  as  in 
scientific  inquiries  all  the  particular  cases  appear  as  em- 
bodying (and  in  that  sense  obeying)  certain  simple  universal 
rules. 

29.  Here,  then,  the  criticism  recurs  that  the  happiness 
which  all  men  desire  is  not  a  simple  end,  but  a  name  for 
many  and  radically  different  forms  of  gratification.  The  de- 
scription just  given  would  hold  good  in  strictness  of  nothing 
but  a  polyp,  an  organism  swayed  by  a  single  desire,  say,  a 
love  of  warmth  and  a  dread  of  cold,  and  representing  not  a 
whole  composed  of  parts  but  an  indivisible  atom.  If  such  a 
beinti^  could  be  supposed  to  be  endowed  with  reason,  its 
actions  would  lu)  doubt  have  a  single  end,  and  there  could 
be  no  dispute  as  to  its  siunmum  honum.     But  as  the  growth 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  (g 

of  reason  implies  the  development  of  a  vast  complexity  of 
feeling,  this  apparent  unity  is  illusory.  Man,  in  fact,  is  a 
microcosm  as  complex  as  the  world  which  is  mirrored  in 
his  mind ;  he  is  a  federation  incompletely  centralised,  a 
hierarchy  of  numerous  and  conflicting  passions,  each  of 
which  has  ends  of  its  own,  and  each  of  which,  separately 
considered,  would  give  a  different  law  of  conduct.  He  is  in 
some  sense  a  unit,  but  his  unity  is  such  as  to  include  an 
indefinite  number  of  partly  independent  sensibilities ;  and 
consequently  it  is  impossible  to  lay  down  any  single  end, 
even  for  the  individual,  and  still  more  obviously  impossible  to 
lay  down  such  an  end  as  that  which  is  in  fact  desired  by  all 
individuals  whatever  their  constitution.  Whether  we  can 
lay  down  such  an  end  as  that  which  all  "  ought "  to  desire  is 
at  present  not  the  question;  for  we  are  simply  dealing  with 
the  facts,  and  have  not  come  within  view  of  the  meaning  to 
be  attributed  to  "  ought." 

30.  Now  the  difficulty  thus  suggested  undoubtedly  makes 
it  difficult  to  lay  down  any  simple  formula  of  conduct :  it 
rather  tends  to  prove  that  any  formula  which  professes  to  be 
simple  must  be  illusory.  And,  moreover,  we  have  this  diffi- 
culty, that  our  psychology  is  at  present  utterly  inadequate  to 
decide  what  are  the  elementary  passions  of  which  the  organic 
federation  is  composed,  or  in  what  sense  they  can  be  regarded 
as  distinct.  We  must  be  content  with  the  vaguest  and  most 
general  propositions  upon  the  subject.  We  feel  that  the 
different  physical  appetites  are  in  some  sense  distinct,  and 
perceive  them  to  correspond  to  different  bodily  organs.  Yet 
thev  are  not  independent ;  for  each  organ  and  each  appetite 
depends  at  every  moment  upon  the  whole  organism,  or  upon 
the  state  of  the  other  organs  of  which  it  is  composed.  The 
difficulty  becomes  still  greater  when  we  come  to  the  higher 
or  intellectual  instincts,  whose  limits  and  differences  are  so  ill 
defined,  and  which  have  no  distinct  physical  correlates.  Leav- 
ing it  to  the  psychologists  to  describe  as  well  as  they  can  the 
complex  constitution  of  this  mysterious  federation,  we  may  here 
be  content  with  one  or  two  remarks.     We  may  assume  that  we 


yo  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

are  roughly  describing  facts  when  we  say  that  the  man,  consi- 
dered upon  the  emotional  side,  is  built  up  of  a  certain  small 
number  of  primary  sensibilities,  each  of  which  may  be  stimu- 
lated in  a  vast  variety  of  ways,  and  is  subject  to  a  number  of 
intricate  actions  and  reactions  from  its  neighbours.     More- 
over, it  is  the  very  condition  of  organic  unity  that  they  form 
in  some  sense  a  whole,  so  that  the  action  of  each  is  dependent 
at  every  moment  upon   the  state  of  the  others.     A  superior 
being  who  could  examine  our  characters  would  be  able  to  lay 
down  the  formula  of  our  conduct,  in  which  the  determining 
instinct  would  appear  as  the  resultant  of  various  subordinate 
instincts,  each  actino;  according  to  the  stimulus  of  external 
circumstances,  and  limited  by  its  dependence  upon  the  other 
constituent   parts  of  the  organism.     However  different  the 
feelings  may  be  in  kind,  they  must  be  commensurable  :  they 
have  a  certain  value  in  terms  of  each  other,  and  as  parts  of  a 
single  whole  they  have  a  single  and   (by  the  superior  being) 
definable  resultant.     The  formula  would   be  beyond  measure 
complex  :  it  would  not  depend  upon  the  conditions  of  grati- 
fication of  a  single  instinct,  but  upon  the  gratifications  of 
several   instincts,  themselves  connected   by  complex  laws  ex- 
pressing the  organic  constitution  of  the  agent.     Instead  of 
supposing,  according  to  my  former  illustration,  that  a  man's 
conduct  is  determined  simply  by  the  love  of  gold,  we  should 
have  to  suppose  that  he  wished  for  gold  and  silver  and  any 
other  metals  in  certain  varying  proportions,  dependent  upon 
the  laws  of  his  own  character,  whilst  the  pursuit  of  each  in- 
volved more  or  less  incon'sistent  modes  of  action.     But  how- 
ever complex  the  resulting  formula,  and   of  course  it  would 
be  indefinitely  more  complex  than  the  illustration  suggests? 
it  would   still  give  determinate  rules;  and  though  the  end 
would  be  harder  to  define,  it  would  be  still  definite. 

31.  Hence,  when  we  return  to  the  question  of  rationality, 
we  may  say  that  the  general  result  is  not  affected.  For  the 
operation  of  reason  will  still  tend  to  bring  about  a  certain 
unity  in  the  result.  So  far  as  any  instinct,  whether  simple 
or  complex,  is  dominant,  the  reason  will  tend  to  proportion 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  71 

means  to  ends,  and  so  far  to  bring  about  unity  of  action  and 
purpose.  The  various  actions  directed  to  the  gratification  of 
that  instinct  will  form  parts  of  a  coherent  and  intelligible 
system.  Further,  as  the  emotions  are  closely  connected,  as 
they  blend  with  each  other,  and  the  whole  process  of  develop- 
ment is  a  process  of  forming  a  certain  hierarchy  in  which  the 
separate  and  special  instincts  are  subordinated  to  the  more 
central  and  massive,  the  reason  will  develop,  if  not  a  unity,  at 
least  a  harmony  of  action.  For,  so  far  as  we  reason,  the  action 
of  each  separate  instinct  is  controlled  by  a  constant  reference 
to  the  requirements  of  others.  We  may  act  like  the  lower 
animals  under  the  immediate  impulse  of  hunger,  but  our 
huno-er  is  restrained,  not  onlv  by  the  foresight  of  to-morrow's 
appetite,  but  by  the  knowledge  that  this  indulgence  may  be 
at  the  expense  of  other  pleasures.  The  passion  is  regulated 
and  restrained  bv  our  desire  of  a  more  intellectual  or  emotional 
enjoyment.  Reason  supplies,  if  we  may  say  so,  the  flywheel 
which  makes  every  part  of  the  machinery  act  under  the  in- 
fluence of  the  other  parts  with  which  it  is  organically  con- 
nected. A  caprice — such  as  the  dislike  to  the  red-haired — is 
checked,  because  such  a  caprice  implies  obedience  to  the 
sincrle  emotion  without  reference  to  other  considerations. 
We  act  absurdly  because  we  forget  that  the  redness  of 
hair  is  not  inconsistent  with  the  persistence  of  the  same 
feelings  and  svmpathies  which  determine  our  conduct  in 
the  case  of  men  of  a  different  complexion.  So  far  as  we 
are  reasonable  we  are  able  to  consider  our  conduct,  and 
to  consider  in  anv  given  case  all  that  is  implied  in  it.  In- 
stead of  being  guided  exclusively  by  the  superficial  considera- 
tion, we  see  in  the  mind's  eye  all  the  deeper  and  more  im- 
portant circumstances  which  it  involves;  and  therefore  the 
strongest  feelings,  whatever  they  may  be,  the  most  permanent 
emotions,  are  being  constantly  called  into  play  to  correct  and 
dominate  the  trifling  ones.  Each  instinct  has  its  voice  in 
determining  the  action  of  the  federal  government,  but  no  one 
is  allowed  to  take  the  command  exclusively  without  reference 
to  the  wishes  of  the  others. 


72  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

32.  But  such  considerations,  which  might  be  expanded 
to  much  greater  length,  and  which  would  require  expansion 
in  a  psychological  treatise,  still  leave  the  important  question 
open.  The  reason  brings  the  whole  conduct  into  harmony 
and  unity;  it  forbids  us  to  pursue  trifling  objects  at  the 
expense  of  important;  for  instead  of  allowing  each  instinct 
to  operate  exclusively  in  turn,  it  subjects  each  to  the  implicit 
and  explicit  control  of  the  others.  And  the  very  mode  by 
which  our  rational  and  emotional  nature  is  evolved  implies 
this  constant  centralisation  proceeding  pari  passu  with  our 
reason  in  the  complexity  of  thought  and  feeling.  The  great 
central  emotions  become  stronger  as  the  discovered  laws, 
whether  of  our  own  or  of  external  nature,  become  ranged 
into  a  consistent  hierarchy  of  principles.  But  we  may  still 
ask,  how  is  the  relation  between  the  different  instincts  de- 
termined ?  What  settles  the  influence  exerted  by  each  member 
of  the  federation  ?  What  do  we  mean  when  we  speak  of  one 
interest  as  trifling  and  another  as  important?  One  passion, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  is  less  powerful  than  another  under  given 
circumstances,  but  the  weaker  is  not  therefore  suppressed. 
Hunger  will  still  overcome  love  under  certain  conditions, 
though  the  relative  importance  of  the  part  which  it  plays  in 
the  whole  organism  will  be  diminished  (let  us  assume)  as 
the  reasoning  power  increases.  The  character  is  determined 
for  each  individual  by  its  original  constitution,  though  the 
character  is  modified  as  the  reason  acts,  not  only  because 
reason  accumulates  a  constant  reference  to  certain  motives, 
and  so  gives  them  greater  influence  in  determining  conduct, 
but  because  it  enables  us  after  a  time  to  judge  even  of  our  own 
character  as  a  whole,  to  rehearse  not  only  particular  acts  but 
moods,  and  so  become  spectators  of  ourselves,  and  regard  our 
own  feelings  with  disgust  or  complacency.  Every  such  reflec- 
tion tends  to  modify  future  action  by  revealing  to  us  more  dis- 
tinctly its  social  consequences,  and  by  investing  it  with  cer- 
tain associations  of  approval  or  disapproval.  But,  after  all, 
we  start  with  a  certain  balance  of  feeling,  with  certain  fixed 
relations  between   our  various  instincts;  and  however  these 


THE  REASON  AS  DETERMINING  CONDUCT.  73 

may  change  afterwards,  our  character  is  so  far  determined 
from  the  start.  Again,  it  is  plain  that  this  varies  greatly 
with  different  people  and  gives  rise  to  different  types.  In 
one  man  the  sensual  passions  have  a  greater  relative  import- 
ance than  in  his  neighbour,  and  so  forth.  And  the  question 
arises,  whether  we  can  determine  which  of  these  types,  or 
anv  of  them,  is  most  reasonable  ? 

^^.  So  far  as  we  have  gone,  I  do  not  see  how  any  conclu- 
sion of  this  kind  can  be  drawn.  Assuming  a  certain  end,  as 
I  have  said,  we  may  say  what  is  the  most  reasonable  mode 
of  conduct,  and  what  therefore  will  be  the  conduct  of  the 
most  reasonable  man  with  a  view  to  that  end.  But  nothing 
hitherto  stated  will  enable  us  to  define  the  end  which  is  itself 
most  reasonable,  or  to  give  any  meaning  to  the  phrase.  And 
this  argument  becomes,  if  anything,  stronger  when  we  admit 
that  the  end  is  exceedingly  complex,  instead  of  being  simple 
and  uniform.  Each  tvpe  of  character  has  its  own  end,  which 
may  determine  the  persistent  and  harmonious  action.  The 
sensualist  has  purposes  as  definite  and  intelligible  from  his 
point  of  view  as  the  ascetic.  The  rule,  "  Let  every  one  care  for 
me,"  is  quite  as  simple,  and,  in  a  logical  point  of  view,  defines 
conduct  as  consistently  and  reasonably,  as  the  rule,  "Love  your 
neighbour  as  yourself."  That  motive  is  most  important  for 
any  man  which  corresponds  to  his  strongest  and  most  fre- 
quently stimulated  instinct;  but  we  have  so  far  no  means  of 
saying  why  reason  should  determine  any  particular  relation 
between  the  instincts,  or  why  any  one  character  should  not 
be  just  as  reasonable  as  any  other.  In  short,  there  is  so  far 
an  arbitrary  element  in  our  data  which  we  have  found  no 
means  of  determining.  Man  is  both  a  reasoning  and  a 
feeling  animal.  We  can  say  what  it  is  to  be  more  reason- 
able, in  so  far  as  reason  implies  a  conformity  between  the 
actual  world  and  the  ideal  world  by  which  it  is  represented ; 
and  this  holds  good  whatever  the  precise  meaning  attributed 
to  those  words  by  the  metaphysician.  We  are  still  at  a  loss 
to  determine  the  other  element  of  the  problem :  what  is 
that  criterion,  if  any,  by  which  we  can  judge  of  feelings? 


74  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

They  exist,  and  so  far  cannot  be  called  true  or  false.  They 
are  actual  or  they  are  nothing.  If  actual,  in  what  sense  is 
one  feeling,  or  set  of  feelings,  or  one  type  of  character,  better 
than  another  ?  That,  of  course,  is  the  vital  problem  of  all 
ethical  speculation,  which  will  recur  in  various  forms  here- 
after. To  answer  it  at  all,  we  must,  as  I  hold,  have  recourse 
to  a  different  set  of  considerations,  and  they  must  be  those 
already  indicated  in  the  previous  chapter,  where  I  have 
pointed  out  that  the  arbitrariness  of  our  data  is  corrected  by 
the  theory  of  evolution. 


IV.  Types. 

34.  Every  reasoning  agent,  I  have  said,  represents  a  certain 
tvpe.  Since  his  conduct  is  regulated  in  each  particular  by  a 
certain  regard  to  the  purposes  of  his  life,  and  his  sentiments 
are  constantly  correcting  and  blewding  with  each  other,  there 
is  a  certain  unity  of  character  in  spite  of  the  complex  consti- 
tution of  his  nature.  Each  impulse  is  subordinated  to  the 
whole,  and  there  is  a  subjective  unity  of  sentiment  corre- 
sponding to  the  objective  unity  of  organisation.  The  phrases 
thus  used  are  necessarily  vague,  and  a  kind  of  mystical  sense 
has  been  sometimes  imported  into  them.  We  must  try  to 
give  them  a  little  more  precision;  and,  in  particular,  we  must 
ask  what  is  meant  by  a  "  type,"  an  expression  which  fre- 
quently recurs  in  these  discussions.  Consider,  for  example, 
a  simple  mechanical  contrivance,  such  as  a  bow.  The  bow 
was,  we  mav  suppose,  originally  discovered  by  some  simple 
experience  which  revealed  to  some  primitive  savage  the 
properties  of  a  special  combination  of  wood  and  sinew. 
Successive  experiments  gradually  led  to  improved  forms,  by 
some  such  process,  it  may  be,  as  that  which  is  illustrated  in 
Lamb's  philosophical  apologue  of  roast  pig.  Every  improved 
form  would  be  used  because  it  saved  trouble.  To  have  the 
best  form  of  bow  was  a  matter  of  importance  to  each  tribe 
for  use  against  beasts  or  enemies.  The  tribe  which  had  the 
best  bow  would  have  an  advantage  in  the  struggle  for  exist- 


TYPES.  75 

ence.  Whenever  accident  revealed  an  improvement,  it 
would  be  adopted  whenever  the  powers  of  observation  w^ere 
keen  enouo-h  to  note  the  savings  of  labour  required  for  a 
given  effect.  As  men  became  intelligent,  experiments 
would  be  tried  with  more  conscious  and  deliberate  purpose, 
and  in  time  they  might  be  carried  out  upon  system,  and 
general  formulae  would  be  laid  down.  Discovery  w^ould 
become  invention  as  the  foresight  and  powers  of  calculation 
developed,  and  in  time  mechanical  theorists  would  become 
able  to  lay  down  general  rules,  stating  the  relation  between  the 
power  and  the  materials  of  bows  and  arrows,  and  the  range, 
accuracy,  penetration,  and  so  forth,  of  the  weapons. 

^^.  Without  pursuing  this  conjectural  history,  it  is  clear 
that  in  any  case  there  is  a  definite  problem  to  be  solved. 
Given  the  materials  and  the  purpose  to  be  attained,  one  form 
of  bow  would  represent  the  maximum  of  efficiency.  If,  for 
example,  the  archer  has  at  his  disposal  a  particular  kind  of 
wood  and  has  to  pursue  a  particular  kind  of  game,  he  will 
have  to  satisfy  a  particular  set  of  conditions  which  might  be 
expressed  in  mathematical  formulae.  Whether  he  has  to  work 
out  the  best  form  of  bow  by  rule  of  thumb,  or  whether  he 
is  able  to  apply  general  rules,  the  process  is  essentially  the 
same,  though  in  the  latter  case  he  can  reason  about  whole 
classes  of  cases  as  well  as  about  particular  cases,  and  can 
understand  more  precisely  what  he  is  about,  and  be  guided 
against  attempting  impossibilities  or  satisfying  contradictory 
conditions.  Even  in  so  simple  a  case  the  complexity  of  the 
data  is  so  great  that  it  might  exceed  the  powers  of  the  most 
skilful  mechanist  to  deduce  the  result  from  general  principles. 
But  in  any  case  the  problem  is  determinate.  The  bow,  we 
may  say,  is  there ;  and  in  some  way  or  other  it  may  be  formed, 
however  tentative  or  systematic  the  method. 

;^6.  The  bow,  then,  which  represents  the  best  solution  of 
the  problem  may  be  called  the  typical  bow.  It  is  that  form 
to  which  bows  approximate  so  far  as  perfect,  and  every  devia- 
tion from  which  implies  a  defect.  The  actual  may  differ, 
either  as  simply  worse  in  all  respects,  or  as  gaining  some 


76  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

advantage  at  the  price  of  others,  such  as  a  longer  range  with 
less  accuracy.  The  problem  as  to  the  degree  in  which  it  is 
worth  while  to  sacrifice  range  to  accuracy  can  only  be  deter- 
mined by  its  use,  and  presumably  by  a  series  ot"  experiments. 
And  assuming  the  use  and  the  materials  to  be  constant,  we 
may  regard  the  evolution  of  bows  as  a  long  series  of  attempts, 
extending,  it  may  be,  over  many  generations,  to  solve  the 
jKoblem.  The  discovery  of  a  new  material  or  the  applica- 
tion of  the  bow  to  fresh  purposes  would  set  up  a  new  process 
of  development.  No  bow  is  an  actual  realisation  of  the 
type,  for  every  bow,  like  every  man,  has  its  faults;  nor  is 
the  average  the  same  as  the  typical  bow,  for  deviations  may 
take  place  more  frequently  in  one  direction  than  another. 
But  the  tvpical  and  ideal  bow  represents  that  maximum  of 
efficiency  to  which  the  bow  tends  to  approximate,  either  by 
the  direct  perception  of  its  utility  by  the  archers,  or  by  the 
fact  that  the  archers  who  have  the  best  bows  are  likely  to 
exterminate  the  others. 

37.  It  is  not  irrelevant  to  observe  that  an  instrument 
which  thus  approximates  to  a  type  as  the  product  of  a  slow 
elaboration  has  a  special  beauty.  The  idea  of  the  bow  has 
been  rolled  in  countless  minds  till  it  is  rounded  to  perfection, 
like  the  pebble  on  the  sea-beach.  Everything  superfluous 
has  been  removed,  as  the  trained  athlete  gets  rid  of  super- 
fluous tissues.  It  is  exquisitely  adapted  to  its  purpose;  and 
the  pleasure  of  contemplating  it  implies  that  we  can  perceive 
this  adaptation  and  derive  from  it  that  subtle  sense  of  harmony 
which  governs  our  intellectual  emotions.  The  pleasure,  in 
,  fact,  is  another  aspect  of  the  skill  implied  in  the  so-called 
"rule  of  thumb."  Though  we  cannot  calculate,  we  can  feel 
the  utilitv.  The  recognition  of  the  perfect  adaptation  reveals 
itself  to  our  feelino^s  as  aesthetic  satisfaction.  The  instinct 
outruns  our  power  of  scientific  statement  of  the  conditions; 
for,  in  fact,  the  scientific  knowledge  corresponds  only  to  that 
small  part  of  our  knowledge  which  is  capable  of  definite 
articulate  statement. 

38.  We  may  trace  a  similar  principle  in  forms  infinitely 


TYPES.  77 

more  complex.  A  Greek  statue,  we  say,  represents  a  type 
of  physical  excellence.  We  cannot  explain  precisely  how 
the  sculptor  discovered  the  type,  nor  how  we  recognise  it 
when  presented;  but  we  do,  in  fact,  recognise  the  solution 
of  an  amazingly  complex  problem.  The  anatomist  can  tell 
us,  within  certain  limits,  why  one  combination  of  bone  and 
muscle  is  more  efficient  than  another.  The  artist  is  able  to 
present  us  directly  with  the  form  which  represents  the  maxi- 
mum of  strength  and  agility  possible  to  human  flesh  and 
blood.  The  figure,  we  say,  is  perfectly  graceful,  because  it 
can  perform  any  given  task  with  the  least  expenditure  of 
strength,  or  make  a  given  amount  of  strength  do  the  most 
work.  Nothing  is  superfluous  and  nothing  deficient. 
The  being  represented  could  leap  a  given  height  with  the 
least  exertion,  or  leap  the  greatest  height  with  a  given 
exertion.  And  here  too  we  see  that  the  form  is  the  best  rela- 
tively to  certain  conditions.  The  Hercules  or  the  Apollo 
may  each  be  the  best  form  as  we  require  the  greatest  possible 
strength  to  wield  a  club  or  the  greatest  possible  activity  of 
locomotion.  So,  in  fact,  every  athlete  is  generally  best 
at  some  particular  exercise,  or  in  some  special  department 
of  that  exercise.  The  typical  athlete  represents  rather  a 
typical  group  than  a  single  form.  Most  defects  are  disquali- 
fications for  every  kind  of  excellence,  but,  as  between  diff'erent 
representatives  of  the  typical  group,  we  cannot  say  positively 
that  one  is  best  unless  we  can  define  the  function  excellence  in 
which  is  to  supply  the  criterion.  And  when  this  function 
is  determined,  we  have  equally  to  assume  certain  data.  If 
the  best  athlete  is  to  be  the  best  runner,  or  say  the  best  runner 
for  a  given  distance,  we  still  have  to  remember  that  the  athlete 
has  not  only  to  be  a  runner,  but  a  breathing,  thinking,  digest- 
ing animal,  to  have  lungs,  brains,  and  stomach;  and  we  tacitly 
assume,  in  speaking  of  the  typical  form,  that  the  resulting 
conditions  have  to  be  satisfied.  We  do  not  speak,  or  rather 
we  cannot  speak  with  any  intelligible  meaning,  of  the 
greatest  speed  absolutely,  but  of  the  greatest  speed  obtainable 


78  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

consistently  with  the  general  conditions  implied  in  the  other 
wants  of  the  human  frame. 

39.  We  can  give,  then,  a  precise  meaning  to  the  word 
"  type  "  so  long  as  the  end  and  the  conditions  can  be  regarded 
as  fixed.  The  bow  has  to  bring  about  a  certain  result  under 
certain  conditions.  It  is  part  of  a  whole,  and  may  be  con- 
sidered as  a  supplementary  limb  discharging  a  given  function 
in  the  organism.  But  when  we  take  the  whole  organism, 
the  meaning  requires  modification.  The  eye  is  useful  to  the 
hand  and  to  the  whole  organic  system;  the  hand,  again,  to 
the  organism,  including  the  eye.  Each  part  is  good  or  bad 
relatively  to  the  whole;  but  what  is  implied  by  the  whole? 
When  there  is  some  external  criterion  the  answer  is  easy. 
We  can  say  what  is  the  typical  sheep  from  the  point  of  view 
of  the  butcher,  or  again  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  wool 
merchant;  but,  what  is  the  typical  sheep  considered  ab- 
solutely ?  If  the  word  "  absolutely  "  be  used  in  such  a  sense 
as  to  exclude  a  reference  to  any  conditions  whatever,  the 
question  ceases  to  have  any  meaning.  It  is  intelligible  to  ask 
what  is  the  greatest  speed  of  an  animal,  or  of  a  steam-engine, 
or  of  an  electric  message,  because  in  each  case  I  assign  a 
limit  of  possibility;  but  to  ask  what  is  the  greatest  speed 
possible  for  anything  is  to  ask  a  question  which  by  its  nature 
has  no  answer.  What  then  is  the  criterion  bv  which  the 
sheep  is  to  be  judged?  We  may  say  that  it  is  the  sum  total 
of  all  the  sheep's  relations  to  the  external  world,  for  we  have 
no  means  of  regarding  one  relation  either  than  another. 
Again,  each  form  of  sheep  plays  its  own  part  in  the  general 
system,  and  the  judgment  of  butcher,  wool  merchant,  or  hunter 
will  differ  according  to  his  particular  needs.  How  are  we  to 
decide  which  judgment  is  right  or  in  what  sense  we  can  apply 
risrht  or  wrons;  to  such  estimates? 

40.  The  answer  to  this  question,  which  I  must  accept,  for 
I  cannot  inquire  into  the  ultimate  grounds,  is  that  supplied 
by  the  evolutionist.  That  theory,  I  take  it,  implies  the 
following  statements.  The  organism — sheep  or  man — is  not 
a  simple  aggregate  of  independent  parts  which  might  be  put 


TYPES.  79 

toc-cthcr  accordins:  to  one  confio-uration  or  another.     In  that 
case  all  that  we  could  say  of  it  would  be,  that  an  organism 
was  composed  of  such  and  such  parts  or  that  a  conscious  being 
had  such  and  such  instincts;  but  that,  for  anything  we  could 
say,  the  same  elements  might  be  put  together  in  any  other 
way.     The  ultimate  constitution  would  remain  as  a  perfectly 
arbitrary  set  of  data.     We  should  be  unable  to  get  beyond 
the  difficulty  in  which  we  have  been  already  landed.     But 
we  learn  from  the  theory  of  evolution  that  as  the  individual 
organism  is  composed  of  mutually  dependent  parts,  and  that 
its  existence  involves  the  maintenance  of  a  certain  equilibrium, 
so  each  organism  supports  itself  as  a  part  in  a  more  general 
equilibrium,    and    that   its    constitution    depends    at    every 
moment  upon  a  process  of  adaptation  to  the  whole  system 
of  the  world.     And  this  may  be  expressed  by  saying  that 
every  animal  represents  the  solution  of  a  problem  as  well  as 
a  set  of  data  for  a  new  problem.     As  the  bow  is  felt  out,  the 
animal  is  always  feeling  itself  out.     The  problem  which  it 
solves  is  how  to  hold  its  own  against  the  surrounding  pressure 
and  the  active  competition  of  innumerable  rivals.     A  species, 
indeed,  does  not  simply  adapt  itself  to  absolutely  fixed  con- 
ditions, like  wax  poured  into  a  rigid  mould.     In    altering 
itself  it  alters  to  some  extent  its  environment.      By  extir- 
pating a  rival   race  it   sets  up  a  whole  series  of  actions  and 
reactions,  implying  a  readjustment  of  the  whole  equilibrium 
amonffst  all  the  races  with  which  it  is  in  contact,  and  to 
some  extent  an  alteration  of  the  inorganic  world.     A  new 
state  of  things  slowly  substitutes  itself  for  the  old,  but  in 
such  a  way  that  each  species  is  continuous  with  the  preceding, 
and   has    been   slowly  remoulded  by  an  incessant  series  of 
unconscious  experiments  conducted  under  the  constant  con- 
dition that  failure  means  extirpation.       Hence,  though  we 
cannot  say  that  either  the  end  or  the  conditions  are  absolutely 
constant,  and  though  any  full  statement  would  have  to  be 
unendingly  complex  in  consequence,  the  whole    process  is 
describable  as  a  slow  elaboration  of  types.     The  material  at 
any  moment  is  a  species,  a  group  of  organised  beings,  capable 


So  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

of  varying  within  certain  limits,  placed  under  conditions 
which,  for  the  moment,  are  apparently  fixed,  and  succeeding 
in  so  far  as  it  realises  the  condition  of  maximum  total 
efficiency.  The  capacity  for  holding  its  own  replaces  the 
condition  of  fitness  for  a  fixed  external  end. 

41.  We  assume,  then,  that,  although  we  cannot  apply  an 
d  priori  method,  although  we  cannot  define  the  materials 
of  which  men  are  made,  or  the  end  which  they  have  to 
fulfil,  we  can  determine  to  some  extent  their  typical  excel- 
lence. Recognising  the  general  nature  of  the  great  prob- 
lem which  is  being  worked  out,  we  can  discov'er  what  is 
implied  in  some  of  the  results.  The  process  of  evolution 
must  at  every  moment  be  a  process  of  discovering  a  maxi- 
mum of  efficiency,  though  the  conditions  are  always  varying 
slowly,  and  an  absolute  maximum  is  inconceivable.  At 
every  point  of  the  process  there  is  a  certain  determinate 
direction  along  which  development  must  take  place.  The 
form  which  represents  this  direction  is  the  typical  form,  any 
deviation  from  which  is  a  defect.  This  typical  form,  again, 
so  long  as  evolution  continues,  cannot  represent  an  ultimate 
result ;  it  is  not  (if  I  may  say  so)  at  the  summit  of  a  peak, 
but  on  the  summit  line  of  a  perpetually  ascending  ridge. 
The  actual  forms  are  almost  always  more  or  less  defective ; 
the  individual  is  below  the  ridge,  not  at  a  higher  point  of  a 
ridge.  Gradually,  indeed,  if  development  continues,  the  type 
itself  will  improve ;  one  particular  form  will  differ  from  the 
previous  variations  by  being  at  a  higher  point  of  the  ridge, 
and  in  that  last  it  will  represent  the  advance  towards  a  new 
species. 

43.  To  take  into  account  all  the  corrections  which  would 
be  necessary  for  an  accurate  statement  would  be  very  diffi- 
cult, and  for  my  purpose  the  task  would  be  superfluous. 
The  exposition  and  establishment  of  the  theory  of  evolution 
lies  beyond  the  ethical  problem,  and  is  one  of  the  data 
which  we  must  be  content  either  to  repudiate  or  (as  I  do) 
take  for  granted.  I  will  merely  add  one  remark  which 
may  indicate  some  of  the  difficulties  involved  in  a  complete 


TYPES.  LosAtiguu^      8 1 

statement.  I  have  said  that  every  type  must  be  relative  to 
the  assumed  end.  As  one  form  of  athletic  excellence  is  best 
for  one  exercise  and  another  for  a  different  exercise,  so  in 
the  higher  qualities  there  is  room  for  an  indefinite  variety 
of  qualities,  each  of  which  may  be  best  in  certain  relations. 
There  may,  indeed  probably  there  must  be,  properties  com- 
mon to  all  the  typical  forms,  but  they  must  be  such  as  to 
be  reconcilable  with  great  individual  variation.  So,  for  ex- 
ample, a  man  may  be  a  poet,  a  philosopher,  a  statesman,  and 
so  forth,  and  we  may  say  that  to  each  function  there  corre- 
sponds an  appropriate  type.  Now  it  is  conceivable  that  the 
highest  excellence  in  different  departments  of  conduct  may 
imply  consistent  conditions.  The  greatest  philosopher  may 
also  be  the  greatest  athlete  and  the  greatest  poet.  It  is 
equally  clear  that  there  is  no  necessary  connection.  Brains 
of  abnormal  power  may  be  associated  with  puny  muscles. 
The  sensibility  of  a  poet,  the  preoccupation  with  abstract 
principles  of  a  philosopher,  may  unfit  either  for  business. 
The  statement,  indeed,  is  always  ambiguous ;  for  it  does  not 
follow  that  the  poetic  sensibility  might  not  be  combined 
with  the  qualities  of  a  man  of  business,  as  (apparently)  was 
the  case  of  Shakespeare.  It  seems,  however,  to  be  a  highly 
general  rule,  that  great  excellence  has,  as  it  were,  to  be  bought 
at  a  price,  and  that  efficiency  in  one  direction  implies  de- 
ficiency in  others.  Here,  then,  occurs  the  question — only 
to  be  solved  by  experiment — What  is  the  relative  value  of 
different  kinds  of  efficiency  ?  And  a  complete  answer  might 
bring  out  the  fact,  which  seems  on  other  grounds  probable, 
that  it  is  an  advantage  to  a  race  to  include  a  great  variety 
of  different  types.  To  take  this  into  account  would  require 
a  new  complexity  of  statement.  It  is  enough,  however,  to 
say  here,  that  by  speaking  of  a  type  I  do  not  mean  to  assert 
that  there  is  one  special  constitution,  conformity  to  which 
by  any  individual  of  a  race  is  a  condition  of  efficiency,  but 
simply  that  the  process  of  evolution  is  always  the  working 
out  of  a  problem  which  implies  the  attainment  of  general 
efficiency  by  the  acquisition  of  certain  general  qualities. 

F 


82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 


IV.   The  Principle  of  Utility. 

43.  These  considerations^  however,  lie  rather  outside  of 
the  relevant  argument.  Before  proceeding,  it  may  be  well 
to  call  attention  to  the  nature  of  the  position  here  adopted. 
I  have,  in  fact,  shifted  my  point  of  view.  Speaking  of 
motives,  I  have  argued  that  conduct  is  determined  by  pain 
and  pleasure.  The  painfulness  of  a  state  is  a  sufficient,  ulti- 
mate, and  sole  reason  for  avoiding  it.  But  in  speaking  of 
the  elements  of  character,  I  have  substituted  for  the  considera- 
tion of  pain  and  pleasure  the  consideration  of  conditions  of 
existence.  The  fact  is  simply  that  the  constants  in  one 
problem  are  variables  in  the  other.  Given  a  certain  char- 
acter, the  agent  does  what  gives  him  pleasure.  But  if 
we  ask  how  he  comes  to  have  that  character,  the  only  mode 
of  answering  is  by  referring  to  the  conditions  of  existence. 
His  character  must  be  such  as  to  fit  him  for  the  struggle  of 
life.  The  reason  of  conduct  is  always  its  quality  in  terms 
of  pain  or  pleasure.  The  cause  of  its  being  painful  or 
pleasurable  is  the  constitution  of  the  agent ;  and  for  this 
constitution  we  can  only  account,  so  far  as  we  can  account 
for  it  at  all,  by  considering  it  as  a  variable,  dependent  upon 
the  conditions  of  life.  Only  in  this  way  does  the  problem 
from  which  we  started  become  determinate.  If  we  take 
character  as  fixed,  the  development  of  reason  can  only  imply 
a  harmony,  an  adaptation  of  means  to  ends,  and  so  forth, 
leaving  the  end  or  the  dominating  instinct  in  itself  a  positive 
or  arbitrary  datum.  As  character  varies,  so  will  the  ends 
vary;  and  from  the  simple  consideration  of  consistency,  or 
of  pain  and  pleasure,  we  cannot  by  any  ingenuity  determine 
what  will  be  the  general  law  of  conduct.  Hence  the  neces- 
sity and  the  importance  of  the  other  mode  of  investigation, 
as  enabling  us  to  assign  more  or  less  precisely  the  conditions 
of  this  constitution,  which,  from  the  other  point  of  view, 
must  be  taken  for  granted.  This  double  mode  of  reasoning 
involves,  therefore,  no  inconsistency,  and  is  forced  upon  us 


^-^ 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  UTILITY.  83 

by  the  conditions  of  the  case.  We  may  regard  conduct 
either  as  painful  and  pleasurable,  or  as  conducive  or  not 
conducive  to  the  permanent  existence  of  the  agent.  And 
hence  we  have  the  consideration  that  there  must  be  a  corre- 
lation between  painful  and  pernicious  actions  on  the  one 
hand,  and  pleasurable  and  temporal  on  the  other.  A  man 
will  do  what  pleases  him,  and,  if  he  is  to  live,  must  do  what 
is  good  for  him,  or  at  least  what  is  not  destructive.  The 
"  useful,"  in  the  sense  of  pleasure-giving,  must  approximately 
coincide  with  the  "  useful "  in  the  sense  of  life-preserving. 
This  is  a  fundamental  doctrine  from  the  evolutionist  point 
of  view,  and  requires  a  little  further  consideration. 

44.  We  may  remark,  in  the  first  place,  that  all  conduct 
may  be  considered  as  a  set  of  habits,  to  each  of  which^  so  far 
as  it  is  voluntary,  there  is  a  corresponding  instinct.  I  use 
both  words  in  the  widest  possible  sense.  By  a  habit  I  mean 
any  mode  of  conduct  which  can  be  brought  under  a  general 
rule,  and  this,  of  course,  would  include  the  automatic  as  well 
as  voluntary  actions.  I  use  instinct,  again,  to  include  all 
conscious  impulses  to  action,  whether  including  more  or  less 
reasoned  choice,  and  whether  innate  or  acquired.  Some 
mode  of  feeling  conditions  all  conscious  action.  Whether 
the  immediate  action  is  pleasant  in  itself,  or  pleasant  because 
regarded  as  part  of  a  whole  system  of  actions,  involving 
remote  consequences  discoverable  by  refined  calculations,  it 
still  involves  in  the  last  result  some  pleasurable  emotion. 
The  operative  instinct  may  be  an  animal  instinct,  such  as 
hunger,  or  an  instinct  involving  high  intellectual  develop- 
ment, such  as  patriotism  or  religion.  Where  an  action  is 
simply  an  end  to  some  remote  purpose,  and  absolutely  in- 
different in  other  respects,  it  is  the  foretaste  of  the  pleasure 
derivable  from  the  remote  consequences  which  determines 
the  action;  and,  of  course,  it  is  often  difficult  to  decide 
what  may  be  the  true  motive.  But  in  any  case,  there  is 
some  motive,  and  the  instinct  means  the  sensibility  to  that 
class  of  motive.  We  may  then  compare  habits  and  their 
corresponding  instincts,  in  respect  of  their  painfulness  and 


84  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

pleasurableness,  or  in  respect  of  their  utility,  so  far  as  they 
imply  total  efficiency  or  the  reverse;  which  means,  again 
(when  we  consider  the  organism  primarily  and  not  the  con- 
sequences of  action),  in  respect  of  their  essentiality  or  super- 
ficiality. 

45.  There  are,  in  fact,  some  habits  which  are  essential  to 
the  organisms — such  habits  (if  the  word  may  be  used  in 
so  strained  a  sense)  as  breathing  or  digesting.  They  are 
the  processes  which  constitute  life  rather  than  maintain  it, 
and  are,  for  the  most  part,  automatic,  or  beyond  the  direct 
reach  of  our  volition.  We  can  kill  ourselves  as  we  can  kill 
another  man,  and  so  suspend  digestion;  but  our  volition 
does  not  immediately  affect  the  digestive  process  in  our 
own  more  than  in  another  man's  stomach.  From  this  point 
of  maximum  necessity  the  habits  graduate  to  the  most  super- 
ficial and  transitory.  Some  may  be  changed  or  abolished 
by  a  transitory  change  of  feeling,  whilst  others  can  only  be 
altered  by  a  reconstruction  of  our  whole  character.  And 
this  suggests  a  remark,  familiar  enough,  but  worth  the 
explicit  statement,  because  many  fallacies  spring  from  its 
neglect.  It  is  simply  this  :  that  every  theory  about  an  organ 
or  any  property  of  an  organism  must  be  understood  with  a 
reference,  tacit  or  express,  to  the  mutual  interdependence 
of  every  part  of  the  organic  whole.  If,  for  example,  I  say 
that  a  certain  habit  is  pleasant  or  painful,  useful  or  perni- 
cious, I  must  remember  that  the  habit  cannot  be  simply 
deducted  as  from  a  sum  total  of  independent  wholes,  and 
that,  on  the  contrary,  its  removal  must  involve  to  some 
extent  a  readjustment  of  the  whole  organic  equilibrium.  It 
is  therefore  essential  to  take  into  account  all  the  indirect  or 
underlying  consequences  involved  in  this  consideration,  as 
well  as  to  strike  an  average  of  the  good  or  bad  effects  of  the 
habit  itself.  In  order  that  the  proposition,  ''This  habit 
is  a  bad  one,"  may  have  any  real  meaning,  we  must  assume 
that  the  organism  can  exist  without  the  habit.  If  this  be 
possible,  then  wc  must  take  into  account  all  the  differences 
necessarily  involved.     Wc  must  compare  the  whole  man  as 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  UTILITY.  85 

he  exists  with  a  certain  quahty  to  the  whole  man  as  he  exists 
without  it.  To  suppose  that  any  given  characteristic  can 
be  simply  subtracted,  is  to  argue  as  though  cutting  off  a  leg 
had  no  other  consequence  than  removing  a  crutch.  In 
one  case  the  whole  character  of  the  man  is  affected,  in  the 
other  it  remains  constant.  The  fallacies  which  result  from 
an  oversight  of  this  obvious  truth  are  so  common  and  pesti- 
lent, that  it  is  necessary  to  take  note  of  their  nature.  We 
are  always  tempted  to  assume  that  we  can  take  off  a  habit 
as  we  can  take  off  a  coat,  and  to  suppose  that  some  political 
or  social  evil  can  be  remedied  by  simply  removing  the  most 
obvious  source  of  the  mischief  without  troubling  ourselves 
to  ask  what  other  organic  changes  will  be  set  up.  This 
error  is  indeed  so  common  as  to  be  almost  the  master-error 
of  a  crude  sociology,  and  it  may  be  described  as  a  virtual 
confusion  between  oro;anic  and  merelv  mechanical  wholes. 

46.  It  is  important  to  remember  this  in  considering  the 
principle  just  laid  down  of  the  correlation  betweeen  painful 
and  pernicious  habits.  Some  such  process,  I  have  said,  is 
necessarily  implied  in  the  evolutionist  theory,  and  is  implied 
at  every  stage.  The  highest  organism  has  been  built  up  from 
the  lowest  under  the  constant  stress  of  this  condition.  From 
the  vague  wriggle  of  the  worm  who  acts  upon  the  implicit 
formula,  "Any  change  may  be  for  the  better,"  though  one 
wriggle  may  save  and  another  slay,  as  it  takes  him  into  or 
out  of  the  beak  of  the  bird,  up  to  the  most  refined  motives 
and  delicate  calculations  of  the  philosopher  or  statesman 
who  meets  a  danger  by  a  specific  series  of  carefully  co- 
ordinated actions,  the  general  principle  must  still  be  the 
same.  So  far  as  the  instincts  of  any  agent  lead  him  into 
danger,  they  are  a  point  against  him;  so  far  as  they  lead  him 
into  safety,  a  point  in  his  favour  in  the  ceaseless  competition. 
In  every  case,  too,  we  must  consider  the  total  effect.  The 
growth  of  a  new  instinct  brings  fresh  dangers  as  well  as  fresh 
advantages.  The  problem  which  is  always  being  worked 
out  is  whether  the  new  form  is  on  the  whole  more  or  less 
capable  of  holding  its  own.     It  does  not  simply  drop  out  one 


86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

instinct  and  insert  another^  but  is  more  or  less  modified 
throughout,  so  as  possibly  to  develop  unsuspected  qualities 
in  directions  very  remote  from  that  which  is  most  conspi- 
cuously concerned. 

47.  This  suggests  the  problem  as  to  the  true  theory  of 
pain  and  pleasure.  Granting  the  general  truth  of  this  prin- 
ciple of  correlation  between  the  two  kinds  of  utility,  we 
may  ask  whether  it  cannot  be  pushed  further?  May  it  not 
be  possible  to  show  from  the  nature  of  the  case  that  pain 
and  pleasure  are  necessarily  connected  with  pernicious  and 
beneficial  processes  respectively?  It  has  in  fact  been  main- 
tained, and  with  a  considerable  show  of  evidence,  that  there 
is  some  intimate  connection  between  pleasure  and  a  state  of 
heightened  vitality  on  the  one  hand,  and  between  pain  and  a 
state  of  lowered  vitality  on  the  other.  I  will  not  go  into  an 
argument  which  is  not  strictly  relevant  to  my  case,  and 
which  would  lead  me  far  beyond  the  limits  of  my  knowledge, 
and,  as  I  imagine,  beyond  the  limits  of  all  established  science. 
The  connection,  whatever  it  may  be,  can  only  be  discovered 
by  careful  and  prolonged  investigations;  it  takes  us  into  the 
perplexing  region  of  obscure  physiology;  it  gets  mixed  up 
with  controversies  as  to  the  ultimate  metaphysical  problem 
of  the  relation  between  subject  and  object.  I  will  only  venture 
one  observation,  bearing  upon  the  limits  within  which  the 
principle  is  applicable.  We  may  certainly  say,  in  general 
terms,  that  there  is  as  close  a  connection  between  health 
and  happiness  as  between  disease  and  misery,  and  that  the 
anomalies  which  present  themselves  in  attempting  to  gene- 
ralise this  theory  might  be  cleared  up  by  a  more  accurate 
investigation.  But  this  does  not  tend,  properly  speaking, 
to  explain  the  connection,  nor  docs  it  show  with  any  pre- 
cision how  close  the  connection  must  be.  The  principle 
may  reveal  a  tendency  and  as  exhibiting  certain  conditions 
of  organic  life,  but  it  does  not  in  any  sense  explain  the 
existence  and  the  intimate  nature  of  pain  and  pleasure. 

48.  Thus,  in  the  first  place,  if  we  use  the  word  "utility" 
in  the  subjective  sense,  it  means,  as  I   have  said,  nothing 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  UTILITY.  87 

but  painful  and  pleasurable.  Every  pleasure  is  so  far  good, 
every  pain  so  far  bad;  and  it  is  a  contradiction  in  terms  to 
speak  of  a  pain  as  useful.  The  only  admissible  meaning  of 
such  a  phrase  emerges  when  we  regard  the  system  as  a  whole, 
and  admit  that  a  certain  pain  is  useful  because  a  loss  of  the 
susceptibility  to  the  pain  in  question  would  involve  a  greater 
pain  on  the  whole.  The  being  enjoys  the  maximum  happi- 
ness possible  under  its  conditions  of  life,  although  its  con- 
stitution involves  a  certain  admixture  of  pain.  If,  again,  we 
speak  of  utility  in  the  other  and  objective  sense,  a  pain  may 
be  useful  so  far  as  it  determines  to  preservative  actions, 
although  this,  again,  only  implies  utility  in  the  first  sense 
so  far  as  preservation  implies  a  balance  of  happiness.  Now 
we  must  assume  that,  in  some  way  or  other,  painful  or 
pleasurable  states  are  dependent  upon  the  material  conditions 
of  the  organism,  and,  moreover,  dependent  upon  its  actual 
state  at  each  moment,  and  upon  its  mode  of  working,  not 
upon  its  absolute  strength  or  ability.  The  absolute  strength, 
in  fact,  means  its  potential  capacity  of  resisting  any  strain 
to  which  it  might  be  subjected.  If  the  strain  is  not  actually 
present,  the  capacity  to  bear  it  may  not  be  required.  Many 
diseases  are  painless;  weak  lungs,  for  example,  often  give 
little  pain  unless  the  patient  is  called  upon  for  some  exertion. 
The  healthy  lung,  we  must  suppose,  has  great  reserves  of 
power;  but  so  long  as  they  are  not  called  into  action,  it 
matters  not  whether  they  exist  or  not.  It  is  the  right  work- 
ing of  the  machinery  which  is  relevant,  not  the  power  of 
the  machinery  to  bear  work  under  different  circumstances. 
Till  the  crash  comes,  the  weak  fibre  which  does  all  that 
is  needed  is  as  useful  and  produces  no  more  pain  than  the 
strong  fibre.  And  so,  again,  the  fact  that  any  mode  of  conduct 
may  lead  to  bad  consequences  hereafter  does  not  of  itself 
produce  either  pain  or  pleasure,  though  to  the  reasoning 
animal  the  anticipated  evil  is  already  an  evil.  In  the  absence 
of  that  anticipation  we  have  only  to  ask  whether  the  organic 
equilibrium  is  maintained,  and  have  no  concern  with  results. 
I  walk  with  equal  comfort  whether  I  am  advancing  to  a 


88  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

pitfall  or  along  a  firm  path,  or  whether  I  am  or  am  not 
weakening  some  vital  part,  so  long  as  I  am  not  weakening  it 
in  such  a  way  as  to  interfere  with  the  maintenance  of  a  cer- 
tain equilibrimn. 

49.  We  must  suppose,  then,  that  pain  and  pleasure  are 
the  correlatives  of  certain  states  which  may  be  roughly 
regarded  as  the  smooth  and  the  distracted  working  of  the 
physical  machinery,  and  that,  given  those  states,  the  sensa- 
tions must  always  be  present.  So  far  we  do  not  come  in 
sight  of  any  question  of  utility  or  of  any  sense  in  which 
pain  can  be  regarded  as  useful.  We  reach  that  point  of 
view  where  we  take  into  account  the  principle  already  stated, 
but  incapable  (as  it  seems  to  me)  of  any  proof  except  that 
of  observation,  that  pain  corresponds  to  unstable  and 
pleasure  to  stable  states  of  equilibrium.  So  far,  that  is^  as 
our  feelings  determine  our  conduct,  they  determine  us  to 
avoid  pain  and  retain  pleasure.  And  this  is  quite  enough 
to  show  that  there  is  a  tendency  to  correlate  painful  and 
pernicious,  pleasurable  and  beneficial.  The  agent  which 
delights  in  states  which  generally  love  pernicious  conse- 
quences is  so  far  self-destructive.  An  animal  which  liked 
poisonous  food  would  be  unable  to  exist  when  the  food  was 
easily  obtainable.  And  it  is  clear  that  this  condition,  which 
has  been  always  operative  from  the  earliest  stages  of  evolu- 
tion, must  maintain  the  correlation  within  certain  limits. 
It  is  equally  clear  that  the  correlation  is  very  far  indeed 
from  perfect.  The  growth  of  a  new  taste  involves  new 
dangers  as  well  as  new  advantages,  and  may  establish  itself  if 
the  new  animal  as  a  whole  is  better  than  the  old  as  a  whole. 
If  external  circumstances  change,  new  relations  are  developed 
which  may  bring  out  new  evils.  The  taste  of  a  savage  for 
stron<i"  drink  may  be  harmless  because  dormant  until  the 
civilised  man  introduces  firewater.  There  is,  again,  no 
obvious  reason  why  a  perfectly  useless  pain  may  not  endure 
indefinitely.  The  agony  caused  by  certain  diseases  must 
remain  as  Ions;  as  the  constitutional  state  which  it  reflects  is 
producible  under  actual  circumstances;  and  to  bring  about 


THE  PRINCIPLE  OF  UTILITY.  89 

such  a  change  in  the  organism  as  would  make  this'  state 
impossible  may  involve  such   a  total   change  in  its  whole 
construction,  involving  all  manner  of  collateral  changes,  as 
may  never  be  realised,  or  be  realisable  only  at  the  price  of 
developing   other    evils.     And,    again,    many   actions    once 
pleasurable   tend    to    become    automatic,    and    so    there    is 
apparently  at  least  a  loss  of  happiness  without  any  obvious 
compensation.     We  may  perhaps  guess  that  there  is  even 
in  this  case  an  advantage,  inasmuch  as  the  automatic  per- 
formance of  any  action  tends,  so  to  speak,  to  set  the  con- 
sciousness free  for  other  purposes;  and  thus,  although  the 
most  highly  developed  agent  is  the  most  perfect  automaton, 
he  has  also  for  that  very  reason  a  greater  range  of  conscious 
thought   and   feeling.     Such   considerations  are  enough  to 
remind  us  how  limited  is  our  knowledge  and  how  rapidly  we 
are  reduced  to  vague  conjectures.    This  only  may  be  said,  that 
the   correlation   in    question    does    not    imply  that    all   our 
pleasures  and  pains  are  useful  in  the  sense  of  tending  to 
self-preservation,   as    indeed    such    a    correlation    would    be 
manifestly  contradictory  to  all  our  experience;  and,  again, 
it    does    not    tend    to    explain    in    any   way   whatever    the 
existence  of  pain  and  pleasure,  for  this  existence  is  presup- 
posed, and  is  presumably  dependent  upon  a  direct  relation 
between   the  feelings  and   the  organic   processes,  which  is 
to   us  absolutely  inscrutable ;  but  at  the  same  time  it  re- 
presents a  highly  important  condition,  which  must  regulate 
at  every  stage  the  process  of  evolution.     It  only  justifies  us 
in  saying,  that  so  far  as  any  agent  takes  pleasure  in  things 
conducive  to  his   preservation,   he  has  a  better  chance  of 
survival,   and,   therefore,   that   we  may   regard    compliance 
with  this  condition  as  one  cardinal  point  in  the  theory  of 
organic  development. 

50.  How  much  further  can  we  proceed  ?  One  remark  is 
of  course  obvious.  So  far  as  any  instinct  is  deeply  seated, 
so  far,  that  is,  as  a  being  would  require  a  complete  recon- 
struction to  exist  w^ithout  it,  we  may  consider  that  it  has  a 
presumption  in  favour  of  its  utility.     It  may  be  absolutely 


90  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

essential  to  the  existence  of  the  organism ;  and  even  if 
plainly  non-essential,  we  may  fairly  argue  against  its  being 
pernicious.  An  institution  which  has  flourished  in  many 
different  ages  and  races  under  the  most  various  conditions 
must  presumably  fulfil  some  want  and  correspond  to  some 
deeply  seated  instinct.  So,  to  take  a  familiar  example,  it  is 
possible  that  the  taste  for  stimulants  may  be  injurious,  but 
it  has  in  its  favour  the  number  of  healthy  and  vigorous  races 
in  which  it  is  found,  showing  that  at  least  it  cannot  be 
destructive  of  vigour  under  all  circumstances ;  and,  again, 
we  must  admit  that  it  satisfies  a  very  widely  spread  desire, 
which  may  be  dependent  upon  a  profound  constitutional 
necessity,  and  which  will  have  to  find  its  satisfaction  in 
one  way  or  another.  The  problem,  therefore,  is  not  solved 
by  a  simple  summation  of  good  and  bad  results,  but  involves 
an  inquiry  as  to  the  place  filled  by  a  desire  for  stimulants 
in  the  whole  economy  of  life.  Whether  any  conclusions 
assuming  to  be  called  scientific  can  be  reached  by  such 
methods  need  not  be  considered  at  present.  The  illustra- 
tion may  at  any  rate  give  some  general  indication  of  the 
true  import  of  the  question  to  be  put  and  the  data  required 
for  a  satisfactory  answer. 

V.  Social  ajid  Individual  Uiiliti/. 

51.  I  have  spoken  of  instinct,  habit,  and  so  forth,  as  being 
essential  or  non-essential  to  the  organism,  and  have  added 
that  between  these  two  relations  there  may  be  an  indefinite 
number  of  gradations.  What,  then,  is  precisely  meant  by 
*^' essential "  in  this  connection?  At  a  2;ivcn  moment  anv 
instinct  may  be  essential  in  this  sense,  that  the  agent 
could  not  exist  without  it.  A  man's  life  may  depend  upon 
his  possessing  abnormal  speed,  strength,  and  eyesight.  The 
life  of  the  organism  depends  at  every  instant  upon  his  rela- 
tion to  the  surrounding  world,  and  by  varying  them  we  may 
vary  the  requirements  indefinitely.  In  speaking,  therefore, 
of  any  organism  generally,  we  tacitly  assume  the  existence 


SOCIAL  AND  INDIVIDUAL  UTILITY.  91 

of  the  appropriate  medium.  A  capacity  is  only  essential  if 
it  is  essential  under  these  normal  conditions.  A  power 
of  breathing  air  is  essential  to  certain  classes  of  animals. 
They  cannot  live  in  any  other  medium,  and  they  cannot 
live  in  air  if  they  are  incapacitated  for  this  function.  The 
bare  existence  of  the  animal  implies  the  existence  of  certain 
conditions  and  of  certain  corresponding  powers,  and  those 
faculties  are  properly  essential  without  which  it  could  not 
live  anywhere,  not  those  without  which  it  could  not  liv^e  in 
some  particular  set  of  cases.  Admitting  this,  there  occurs 
another  difficulty.  The  process  by  which  the  correlation 
of  pernicious  and  painful  states  is  worked  out  is  one  which, 
by  its  very  nature,  must  take  a  considerable  number  of  genera- 
tions. Races  survive  in  virtue  of  the  completeness  of  this  cor- 
relation. But  the  quality  which  makes  a  race  survive  may 
not  always  be  a  source  of  advantage  to  every  individual,  nor 
even,  if  we  look  closer,  to  the  average  individual.  Since 
the  race  has  no  existence  apart  from  the  individual,  qualities 
essential  to  the  existence  of  each  unit  are  of  course  essential 
to  the  existence  of  the  whole.  If  one  animal  cannot  live 
without  lungs,  a  million  cannot.  But  the  converse  proposi- 
tion does  not  hold.  In  fact,  there  is  a  large  and  important 
group  of  instincts  in  regard  to  which  it  is  manifestly  untrue. 
The  sexual  and  parental  instincts  are  essential  to  the  race, 
for  without  them  the  race  would  cease  in  a  single  generation. 
It  is  equally  certain  that  they  are  not  essential  to  the  indi- 
vidual. An  animal  deprived  of  them  may  not  only  live  and 
thrive,  but  will  avoid  many  dangers  to  which  it  is  exposed  by 
possessing  them.  The  "  unnatural  "  mother  has  the  great 
advantage  that  she  will  not  give  her  life  for  her  young.  And 
it  is  at  least  conceivable,  though  it  may  not  happen  actually, 
that  some  creatures  thus  devoid  of  passions  upon  which  the 
continuance  of  the  race  absolutely  depends  may  be  not  only 
happier  under  certain  special  conditions,  but  may,  on  the 
averas:e,  enjoy  more  happiness  than  their  neighbours.  In  such 
cases,  the  parents  virtually  sacrifice  themselves  for  the  good 
of  the  race.     They  may  be  unconscious  of  the  sacrifice,  and 


92  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

we  cannot  call  them  unselfish.  They  are  rather  in  a  state 
of  mind  in  which^  as  devoid  of  all  prevision  of  consequences, 
the  question  of  selfishness  and  unselfishness  has  not  yet  pre- 
sented itself.  They  act  in  a  way  not  calculated  to  bring  in 
the  greatest  amount  of  happiness,  but  they  act  in  obedience 
to  an  instinct  not  guided  by  any  calculation  as  to  the  fall  of 
the  balance. 

53.  Here  then  is  a  case,  and  one  of  the  very  highest 
importance,  for  it  concerns  the  germ  of  all  social  life,  in 
which  we  see  that  the  correlation  between  the  benefi- 
cial and  the  pernicious  must  be  interpreted  in  a  sense 
different  from  that  which  we  miijht  at  first  siijht  take  for 
granted.  An  instinct,  that  is,  grows  and  decays  not  on 
account  of  its  effects  on  the  individual,  but  on  account 
of  its  effects  upon  the  race.  The  animal  which  on  the 
whole  is  better  adapted  for  continuing  its  species  will 
have  an  advantage  in  the  struggle,  even  though  it  may 
not  be  so  well  adapted  for  pursuing  its  own  happiness. 
Here,  then,  it  becomes  desirable  to  attempt  to  bring  into 
greater  distinctness  the  true  meaning  of  the  contrast  between 
the  individual  and  the  race,  in  order  that  we  may  endeavour 
to  determine  in  what  sense  there  can  or  cannot  be  a  conflict 
between  the  individual  who  is  the  product  of  the  race,  and 
the  race  which  is  itself  formed  of  individuals,  and  in  what 
way  the  principle  already  laid  down  must  be  explained  or 
modified  when  we  take  this  distinction  into  account. 


(    93     ) 


CHAPTER  in. 

SOCIAL     MOTIVES. 
I.    The  Individual  and  the  Race. 

I.  The  last  chapter  has  brought  us  to  a  distinction  of 
vital  importance.  We  have  had  to  distinguish  between  the 
effects  of  the  interests  of  societies  and  the  interests  of 
individuals.  An  action  or  an  instinct  may,  it  seems,  be  of 
essential  importance  to  the  whole,  and  of  little  or  none  to 
the  individual,  and  this  distinction  will  obviously  affect 
our  reasoning  at  many  points.  If  we  assert  that  the  survival 
of  an  instinct  is  determined  by  its  utility^  we  must 
further  decide  how  the  utility  is  to  be  measured,  whether 
we  are  to  consider  the  utility  to  the  individual  or  the  utility 
to  society,  and  in  what  sense  any  distinction  is  possible. 
Other  difficulties  may  reveal  themselves  as  we  proceed.  We 
will,  therefore,  begin  by  attempting  to  define  as  clearly  as 
we  can  the  true  meaning  of  the  distinction  in  question. 
We  may  thus  be  able  to  understand  the  nature  of  the  social 
bond  so  far  as  is  necessary  for  our  purpose,  and  to  consider 
what  language  will  be  best  adapted  to  express  the  relations 
involved. 

■2.  It  is  of  course  obvious  that  the  individual  and  the  race 
are  not  two  separate  things  capable  of  coming  into  collision. 
The  individual,  as  I  have  said,  is  the  product  of  the  race ; 
and  the  race  the  sum  of  the  individuals.  And  the  fact  that 
the  immediate  interests  of  an  individual  may  be  incom- 
patible with  those  of  the  race  does  not  necessarily  affect 
our  statement.  The  existence  of  such  incompatibility  is 
of  course   only   too   familiar  a   fact.     The  prosperity  of  a 


94  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Napoleon  may  involve  the  degradation  of  his  country.  But 
when  I  speak  of  "  the  individual  "  as  being  better  or  worse 
adapted  to  his  circumstances,  I  am  not  speaking  of  any 
particular  person,  but  of  the  average  person.  A  Napoleon 
may  conceivably  thrive  by  possessing  qualities  which  are 
injurious  to  his  fellows.  But  it  would  be  something  very 
like  a  contradiction  to  suppose  that  the  average  man  might 
be  improved  by  conferring  upon  each  qualities  prejudicial 
to  the  rest.  If  the  average  person  is  more  intelligent  and 
richer,  the  whole  of  which  he  forms  a  part  ,^ssesses  a 
greater  sum  of  intelligence  and  wealth.  If  the  qualities  of 
any  society  may  be  regarded — and  in  some  sense  it  seems 
that  they  must  be  regarded — as  the  sum  of  the  qualities  of 
its  constituent  units,  it  follows  that  whatever  strengthens  or 
weakens  the  average  unit  must  also  weaken  or  strengthen 
the  whole.  This,  indeed,  would  be  accurately  true  if 
we  were  justified  in  considering  each  unit  as  so  far  inde- 
pendent that  what  is  true  of  each  might  be  applied  to 
all  by  direct  multiplication.  The  difficulty  begins  to  show 
itself  when  we  regard  society,  not  as  a  mechanical  aggregate, 
but  as  an  organic  whole.  In  that  case,  we  cannot  regard 
the  efficiency  of  the  whole  as  a  simple  sum  of  separate 
efficiencies.  The  qualities  of  each  unit  may  then  be  depen- 
dent for  their  nature  and  for  their  efficiency  upon  their 
relations  to  the  organism.  Thus,  for  example,  if  we  take 
an  army,  its  efficiency  will  depend  partly  upon  the  strength 
of  the  soldier,  and  partly  upon  his  discipline.  Double  the 
marching  power  of  each  soldier,  and  you  will  double  the 
length  of  marches  possible  for  the  army.  But  an  increase 
in  the  spirit  of  discipline  produces  an  effect  upon  the  army 
which  cannot  be  determined  by  simple  multiplication ;  for 
not  only  may  the  efficiency  of  the  army  be  enormously 
increased  by  a  slight  increase  in  the  spirit,  but  such  an 
increase  may  operate  very  differently  under  different  states 
of  the  army.  It  might  diminish  its  efficiency  in  warfare 
which  required  separate  action,  as  it  might  enormously 
increase  it  where  the  first  necessity  was  unity,  and   there- 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  AND  THE  RACE.  95 

fore  blind  obedience.  A  quality  useful  to  the  whole  when 
acting  together  might  be  prejudicial  to  the  individual  mem- 
ber when  acting  independently.  Hence,  it  would  seem, 
we  have  in  this  case  a  datum  which  could  not  be  determined 
without  some  knowledge  of  the  total  organism,  as  well  as  of 
its  separate  parts.  The  distinction,  therefore,  between  the 
race  and  the  individual,  though  not  a  distinction  as  of  two 
separate  things,  may  be  of  great  importance  as  correspond- 
ing to  a  distinction  in  the  mode  in  which  the  efficiency  is 
affected  hy^ different  qualities.  For  some  purposes  a  body 
may  be  regarded  as  an  aggregate,  whilst  for  others  it  can 
only  be  understood  as  an  organic  whole.  And  this  has 
evidently  an  important  bearing  upon  our  reasoning. 

3.  Let  us  see  how  this  difference  must  be  expressed  upon 
the  theory  already  laid  down.  I  have  spoken  of  qualities, 
instincts,  organs,  and  so  forth,  as  being  either  essential  or 
non-essential  to  an  organism.  It  is  plain  that  it  w-ould  be 
idle  to  ask  what  any  organism  would  be  without  any  of  its 
essential  qualities.  We  should  in  that  case  be  referring  to 
a  mere  nonenity.  When  we  say  inan,  we  mean,  amongst 
other  things,  a  living  being  with  a  stomach,  and  environed 
by  eatable  matter.  To  say  that  a  man  would  be  better  or 
worse  if  he  had  no  stomach,  is  to  put  together  words  which 
have  no  real  meaning  whatever,  or,  in  any  case,  to  speak  of 
some  creature  so  radically  different  from  a  man  for  most 
purposes,  that  it  would  lead  to  mere  confusion  to  apply  the 
same  name  to  it.  You  might  describe  a  statue  as  a  man 
without  organs,  but  this  is  simply  to  play  with  words, 
unless  we  confine  our  reasoning  to  properties  dependent 
exclusively  upon  external  forms.  By  "man,"  we  mean  a 
being  belonging  to  a  given  class,  and  varying  within  the 
limits  determined  by  the  essential  properties  of  the  class ; 
and  amongst  these  essential  properties  we  must,  of  course, 
reckon  dependence  upon  a  race.  Man  means  a  being  born 
of  woman,  and  perhaps  a  being  ultimately  descended  from  a 
monkey.  It  would,  therefore,  be  sheer  nonsense  to  speak 
of  a  man  as  if  he  either  might  or  might  not  be  in  some 


96  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

respects  independent  of  society.  He  may  be  in  the  position 
of  a  Robinson  Crusoe,  and  living  in  a  desert  island  ;  but 
even  so  he  must  have  been  begotten,  born,  kept  alive 
through  infancy,  and  have  inherited  whatever  qualities  are 
implied  in  those  processes.  A  man  not  dependent  upon  a 
race  is  as  meaningless  a  phrase  as  an  apple  that  does  not 
grow  upon  a  tree.  The  words  have  no  sense  in  a  purely 
arbitrary  sense.  And  further,  it  is  equally  clear  that  the 
best  type  of  man  must  mean  the  best  type  of  man  developed 
under  those  conditions.  The  best  kind  of  bread  means  the 
best  food  that  can  be  made  out  of  grain;  and  though  a  lump 
of  granite  might  have  some  qualities  which  in  a  different 
relation  are  better  than  those  of  bread,  it  would  be  a  mere 
juggle  if  we  said  that  the  bread  least  likely  to  spoil  was 
"  bread  "  made  of  granite. 

4.  It  follows  that  the  distinction  drawn  between  the 
social  and  the  self-regarding  qualities,  or^  again,  between 
qualities  as  useful  to  the  race  and  useful  to  the  individual, 
cannot  possibly  be  ultimate  distinctions.  Every  man  is 
both  an  individual  and  a  social  product,  and  every  instinct 
both  social  and  self-regarding.  To  say  that  a  man  is  an 
organism  is  to  say  that  each  of  his  organs  is  so  dependent 
upon  all  the  others  that  it  cannot  be  removed  without  alter- 
ing the  whole  organic  balance ;  or,  as  I  have  said,  that  a  leg 
is  not,  or  is  not  solely,  a  crutch.  If  we  speak,  then,  of  one 
instinct  as  referring  to  the  society  and  another  as  referring 
to  the  individual,  we  must  always  remember  that  each  of 
necessity  implies  the  other.  In  speaking  of  them  apart,  we 
are  using  the  artifice  of  the  mathematician  who  considers 
one  set  of  symbols  to  be  variable  and  another  as  constant, 
not  as  meaning  that  the  quantities  which  they  represent  are 
really  fixed  or  in  reality  independent,  but  simply  as  enabling 
him  to  calculate  more  easily  by  disentangling  separate  sets 
of  consequences.  The  social  qualities  are  developed  on  the 
invariable  condition  that  the  self-regarding  qualities  exist,  and 
vice  versd,  and  the  "  best "  qualities  mean  the  best  consistent 
with  this  condition.     We  may,  as  I  have  already  said,  con- 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  AND  THE  RACE.  97 

sidcr  any  organ  by  itself,  and,  for  example,  say  that  one  man 
has  perfect  lungs  ;  but  the  perfection  is  relative  to  their  form- 
ing part  of  an  organism  which  has  also  a  stomach,  whilst  the 
best  form  of  stomach  means  also  the  best  for  a  man  with 
lungs.  And  precisely  the  same  reasoning  applies  also  to  the 
mental  or  emotional  faculties.  Whatever  distinctions  may 
afterwards  be  drawn  between  them,  we  must  never  ignore 
their  necessary  connection  or  mutual  implication.  As  the 
man  is  an  individual,  the  process  by  which  he  is  developed 
is  a  single  process;  and  in  speaking  of  any  one  instinct, 
property,  organ,  or  faculty,  there  is  always  a  tacit  or  express 
reference  to  the  whole  organisation. 

5.  How,  then,  does  the  distinction  arise  ?  The  answer 
may  be  suggested  by  the  illustration  just  vised.  The  depend- 
ence of  an  apple  upon  a  tree  is  absolute.  It  admits  in  this 
sense  of  no  degrees.  I  cannot  say,  therefore,  that  an  apple 
owes  certain  qualities  to  the  fact  of  its  growing  upon  a  tree, 
for  it  owes  all  its  qualities  to  that  fact.  The  non-tree-grown 
apple  is  a  nonentity.  But  it  is  equally  plain  that,  in  another 
sense,  the  dependence  admits  of  many  degrees,  for  the 
possibility  of  distinguishing  between  the  two  classes  implies 
that  for  some  purposes  they  are  separable.  And  this  must 
mean  that  the  apple  has  certain  qualities  which  are  inde- 
pendent of  its  relation  to  the  tree,  not  in  the  sense  that  they 
would  exist  if  that  relation  were  abolished,  but  in  the  sense 
that  they  may  vary  whilst  that  relation  remains  approxi- 
mately constant.  In  some  respects  I  may  treat  of  the  apple 
as  though  it  were  an  independent  unity,  because  it  may 
change  without  a  corresponding  change  in  the  tree ;  in 
other  respects,  I  can  only  understand  the  changes  in  the 
apple  by  taking  into  account  its  dependence  upon  the  tree. 
And  hence,  as  these  properties  and  the  proportion  between 
them  may  vary  in  different  kinds  of  apples,  I  may  say  that 
some  apples  are  more  dependent  upon  the  tree  than  others ; 
not  as  denying  that  in  every  case  the  dependence  is  absolute, 
but  simply  as  asserting  that  in  some  cases  the  qualities 
which  are   only  intelligible    through    that    dependence,   or 

G 


98  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

which  vary  directly  with  its  variation,  are  more  prominent 
than  others.  The  comparison  is  not  drawn  between  an 
apple  growing  on  a  tree  and  others  not  growing  upon  trees, 
but  between  the  apple  in  which  these  properties  immediately 
dependent  upon  that  relation  are  more  prominent,  and 
others  in  which  they  are  less  prominent.  And  this  general 
statement  will  hold  equally  true  in  regard  to  the  essential 
properties  of  any  organism  whatever. 

6.  Let  us  see,  then,  how  this  applies  to  the  general  pro- 
blem of  the  relation  between  the  individual  and  the  race. 
There  are,  or  there  may  be,  organisms  in  which  the  distinc- 
tion so  far  disappears  that  we  need  not  take  it  into  account. 
Every  living  thing  must  be  capable  of  propagating  its  kind, 
and  must  so  far  have  a  property  useful  to  the  race.  But  we 
may  suppose  the  existence  of  organisms  in  which  the  rela- 
tion between  individuals  is  limited  to  this  reproduction.  The 
insect  may  lay  eggs  which  come  to  life  in  the  next  season ; 
the  successive  generations  may  inosculate  without  overlap- 
ping ;  whilst  during  life  each  insect  may  exist  in  complete 
independence  of  its  fellows.  If  we  further  suppose  that  the 
production  of  eggs  be  essential  to  the  insect  life — which, 
whether  an  actual  case  or  not,  is  a  conceivable  case — we 
should  have  a  case  in  which  the  interests  of  the  race  and  the 
individual  would  be  identical.  The  successive  individuals 
would  be  so  many  links  in  a  chain,  and  each  would  potentially 
contain  the  whole  series  of  descendants.  Whatever  hurt  the 
individual  would  necessarily  so  far  hurt  the  race.  Now,  it 
is  to  be  observed  that  even  in  such  a  case  the  dependence 
of  the  individual  upon  the  race  is  absolute.  Without  repro- 
ductive powers  the  race  would  not  exist.  And,  further, 
since  an  insect  with  superior  powers  of  reproduction  would 
so  far  be  more  efficient,  the  type  must  be  elaborated  with 
reference  to  this  condition ;  an  increased  power  of  locomo- 
tion might  be  a  disadvantage  on  the  whole  if  it  involved  a 
diminished  power  of  reproduction.  But  we  may  be  justified 
in  supposing  that  a  variation  In  the  locomotive  faculties  may 
take  place,  whilst  the  reproductive  power  remains  approxi- 


THE  INDIVIDUAL  AND  THE  RACE.  99 

mately  constant.  This  is  expressed  by  saying  tliat  the  insect 
would  be  better  so  far  as  it  could  fly  better.  We  do  not  for 
the  moment  attend  to  the  collateral  results ;  and  so  far  the 
efficiency  due  to  better  flying  is  measurable  by  the  results 
to  the  individual  insect.  Supposing  the  occurrence  of  a 
new  form  with  greater  powers  of  flight,  it  would  so  far  be 
a  superior  insect  as  those  powers  adapted  each  insect  better 
for  obtaining  food,  avoiding  its  enemies,  and  so  forth. 

7.  To  advance  a  step,  we  may  take  the  famous  case  of  bees, 
which  has  afforded  so  many  parallels  to  poets  and  philo- 
sophers. In  such  a  case  the  sexual  relations,  though  they 
cannot  be  more  essential — for  essential  does  not  strictly 
admit  of  degrees — are  more  prominent.  The  queen-bee,  the 
drones,  and  the  workers  are  each  dependent  upon  the  others 
for  their  continued  existence.  The  individual  insect  is  not 
intelligible  by  himself.  The  race  can  only  be  continued  by 
the  co-operation  of  different  individuals  with  corresponding 
differences  of  organisation.  The  best  insect  must  now  mean 
the  best  relatively  to  the  society  of  which  it  forms  a  part. 
That  form  of  bee  will  flourish  which  forms  the  most  efficient 
hives.  The  hive,  in  other  words,  will  be  the  unit  which 
must  be  taken  into  account  in  considering  the  general  pro- 
blem of  surviv^al.  It  would  be  therefore  as  idle  to  ask  which 
would  be  the  best  form  of  bee  considered  apart  from  the 
hive,  as  it  would  be  in  the  previous  case  to  ask  which  would 
be  the  best  form  of  insect  considered  apart  from  its  power 
of  reproduction;  for  in  either  case  we  are  abstracting  from 
an  essential  property.  Here,  again,  as  in  the  former  case, 
we  have  certain  faculties  which  may  be  supposed  to  vary 
whilst  the  social  qualities  remain  fixed.  The  bees  which  fly 
better  are  so  far  better,  assuming  the  power  of  flight  to  be 
gained  without  a  compensating  loss  of  the  qualities  which 
fit  the  bee  for  society.  The  difference  is  that  we  now  have  to 
consider  an  organism  which  has  more  functions  dependent 
immediately  upon  the  whole  of  which  it  forms  a  part,  and 
intelligible  only  through  that  whole.  The  hive,  we  may  say, 
is  at  once  an  aggregate  and  an  organic  whole,  and  we  may 


loo  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

consider  it  in  either  character  for  purposes  of  analysis, 
though  we  must  not  overlook  the  tacit  implication  that 
each  set  of  qualities  is  valuable  only  by  reference  to  its  com- 
patibility with  the  others. 

8.  At  this  point,  however,  occurs  a  consideration  which 
is  of  vital  importance  to  the  argument.  The  individual 
bee,  I  have  said,  is  intelligible  only  through  its  relation 
to  the  hive.  Its  properties,  the  individual  as  well  as  the 
social,  are  developed,  either  indirectly  or  directly,  by  refer- 
ence to  the  constitution  of  the  hive.  Now,  in  every  case, 
every  quality  of  the  organism  is  intelligible  only  through  the 
environment.  The  environment  of  the  queen-bee  consists 
partly  of  the  drones  and  working  bees,  and  partly  of  the  air, 
flowers,  and  so  forth.  It  is  dependent  upon  the  one  just  as 
it  is  dependent  upon  the  other.  What,  then,  is  the  reason 
for  distinguishing?  The  answer  is,  that  the  distinction  may 
or  may  not  be  of  vital  importance,  according  as  we  are 
considering  one  or  other  problem.  Given  the  organisation 
of  bees,  the  behaviour  of  the  queen-bee,  for  example,  will 
depend  partly  upon  the  flowers  and  partly  upon  the  drones 
and  working  bees  amongst  which  it  is  placed.  So  long  as 
the  organisation  remains  fixed,  we  may  count  both  the 
remainder  of  the  society  and  the  surrounding  objects  as  parts 
of  the '^environment"  between  which  it  is  unnecessary  to 
make  any  distinction.  And  for  many  purposes  this  assump- 
tion is  accurate.  But  if  we  consider  the  organisation  as 
variable,  as  we  must  do  if  we  are  considering  the  problem  as 
to  the  merits  of  a  particular  kind  of  bee,  the  distinction 
at  once  becomes  important.  For  in  that  case  an  organic 
variation  in  the  queen-bee  necessarily  supposes  a  correlative 
variation  in  the  organisation  of  all  other  members  of  the 
hive.  Wc  cannot,  for  example,  suppose  the  queen-bee  to 
acquire  better  wings,  without  supposing  a  correlative  change 
to  take  place  in  the  wings  of  all  its  descendants.  We  may, 
on  the  other  hand,  suppose,  and  in  some  cases  we  must 
suppose,  the  flowers  to  remain  unaltered,  and  to  be  part 
of  the  fixed  conditions  to  which  the    swarm  adapts  itself. 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  loi 

And  hence  the  distinction  is  needless,  or  is  vitally  impor- 
tant, according  as  we  are  dealing  with  changes  which  do  or 
do  not  imply  a  fixed  organisation.  At  any  given  moment 
the  organisation  is  fixed  ;  if  we  speak  of  periods  dnring  which 
evolution  introduces  sensible  changes,  it  is  not  fixed.  But 
there  is  yet  a  further  case.  If  it  were  admissible  to  suppose 
that  the  hive  was  capable  of  acquiring  new  properties  whilst 
the  organisation  of  its  members  remained  fixed,  we  should 
be  forced  to  introduce  a  reference  to  this  varying  condition 
also.  To  determine  the  conduct  of  the  bee,  we  must  know 
not  merely  its  organisation  and  its  environment,  but  the 
state  of  the  hive.  We  might,  again,  deal  with  problems  into 
which  this  fresh  datum  entered  either  as  a  constant  or  a 
variable,  and  we  should  in  each  case  have  to  decide  before 
we  could  lay  down  a  satisfactory  formula  of  bee  life,  which 
new  theory  did  or  did  not  involve  a  reference  to  this  vari- 
ability of  this  element.  Now,  as  we  shall  see  directly,  this  is 
a  consideration  of  essential  importance  in  theories  of  human 
society. 

II.   Society  and  Man. 

9.  This  follows  from  a  consideration  of  some  very  familiar 
truths.  We  have  sufficiently  shown  that  we  cannot  make 
a  comparison  between  man  in  a  social  state  and  the  nonentity 
man  independent  of  society,  the  real  comparison  being  be- 
tween man  at  an  early  and  man  at  a  comparatively  late 
stage  of  social  development.  So  it  would  be  idle  to  discuss 
the  effect  of  light  upon  the  eye  by  comparing  an  eye  which 
is  sensitive  with  an  eye  which  is  not  sensitive  to  light,  for 
such  an  insensitive  eye  would  not  be  an  eye  at  all;  but 
we  may  determine  very  profitably  how  the  eye  which  is 
highly  sensitive  difi'ers  from  the  eye  which  is  but  slightly 
sensitive;  and,  in  the  parallel  case,  we  have  to  compare 
men  at  remote  stages  of  social  development  in  order  to 
determine  the  eflfect  of  this  element  in  their  constitution. 
Now  two  assumptions  may  be  made ;  we  may  in  the  first  place 
take  for  granted  that  between  the  savage  and  the  civilised 


102  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

society  there  is  a  vast  difference^  including,  amongst  other 
things,  the  presence  of  a  recognised  and  formulated  moral  law. 
It  is,  indeed,  a  question  for  the  philosophical  observer  how 
far  rudimentary  systems  of  morality  may  be  recognised  even 
amongst  the  rudest  savages;  and  we  may  assume  that,  as 
will  hereafter  be  stated,  germs  of  moral  sentiment,  the  feel- 
ings and  instincts  which  in  a  more  highly  developed  state  give 
rise  to  the  moral  law,  are  to  be  found  not  only  amongst 
savages,  but  in  some  sense  even  at  a  far  lower  stage  of  develop- 
ment than  the  human.  I  assume  simply  that  the  explicit 
recognition  of  certain  general  rules  of  conduct^  the  observ- 
ance or  breach  of  which  is  attended  with  moral  approval 
or  disapproval,  is  comparatively  a  recent  phenomenon.  The 
relations  of  man  to  woman,  of  parents  to  children,  of  the 
individual  to  the  primitive  social  unit,  whatever  it  may  be, 
exist  at  the  lowest  point  of  the  scale,  and  no  doubt  corre- 
sponding modes  of  conduct  were  regarded  with  some  kind  of 
sentiment  as  far  back  as  we  need  go  in  the  history  of  the 
race.  But  a  distinct  recognition  of  general  regulative  prin- 
ciples is  only  possible  when  the  reflective  and  reasoning  powers 
have  become  developed  and  some  sort  of  theory  of  human 
life  has  gained  acceptance.  And,  in  the  next  place,  we  may 
take  for  granted  that  this  difference  does  not  imply  a  cor- 
responding difference  in  organisation.  There  is  no  reason 
to  suppose  that  the  innate  faculties  of  a  modern  European 
differ  essentially,  or  that  they  differ  very  greatly,  from 
those  of  the  savages  who  roamed  the  woods  in  prehistoric 
days.  There  is  clearly  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  brain 
of  a  modern  English  baby  is  intrinsically  more  developed  than 
that  of  an  ancient  Athenian  baby.  Yet  there  is  a  vast 
difference  in  many  ways  between  the  morality  of  the  adult 
Englishman  and  that  of  the  adult  Athenian,  and  still  more 
between  the  morality  of  the  Englishman  and  that  of  the 
Scandinavian  pirate  or  the  wielder  of  flint  implements.  It 
is  presumable,  therefore,  that  the  moral  development  is  not 
to  be  explained  solely  as  corresponding  to  any  organic  change 
in  the  individual. 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  103 

10,  Hence,  for  a  historical  solution  of  the  problem  of  the 
moral  instincts,  it  would  be  necessary  to  compare  man  and 
society  as  it  now  exists  with  that  which  existed  previously 
to  the  evolution  of  a  distinct  moral  system,  and  to  show  how 
the  social  change  had  been  brought  about  without  a  corre- 
sponding change  in  the  individual  organisation.  In  other 
words,  we  may  for  this  purpose  consider  man — that  is,  the  in- 
dividual as  born  with  certain  capacities  and  characteristics — 
as  approximately  a  constant,  and  then  show  how  the  society 
which  is  constituted  of  similar  raw  material  comes  to  differ 
so  materially  in  the  properties  of  the  manufactured  article. 
To  trace  the  process  fully  would  be  to  give  a  complete  history 
of  morality,  which  is  both  beyond  my  powers  and  irrelevant 
to  my  immediate  purpose.  It  will  be  sufficient  if  I  consider 
briefly  how  such  a  process  is  conceivable,  and  what  is  implied 
in  its  realisation. 

11.  Social  development  takes  place  without  a  correspond- 
ing change  of  individual  organisation.  A  modern  gunboat 
could  crush  the  fleets  which  fought  at  Salamis,  and  a  modern 
child  could  solve  problems  which  bewildered  Archimedes; 
and  in  whatever  way  we  may  explain  this  change,  we 
certainly  cannot  interpret  it  as  implying  that  the  average 
child  of  to-day  is  born  with  faculties  radically  superior  to 
those  of  Archimedes  or  of  Themistocles.  The  change  ob- 
viously depends  upon  the  ancient  and  familiar  truth  that 
man  can  accumulate  mental  and  material  wealth;  that  he 
can  learn  by  experience,  and  hand  over  his  experience  to 
others.  It  may  be  that  germs  of  this  capacity  are  to  be 
found  in  the  lower  animals,  but  we  shall  make  no  sensible 
error  if  we  regard  it,  as  it  has  always  been  regarded,  as  the 
exclusive  prerogative  of  humanity.  An  unreasoning  animal 
can  only  adapt  itself  to  new  circumstances,  except  within 
a  very  narrow  range,  by  acquiring  a  new  organisation,  or, 
in  other  words,  by  becoming  a  difiercnt  animal.  Its  habits 
and  instincts  may  therefore  remain  fixed  through  countless 
generations.  But  man,  by  accumulating  experiences,  can 
virtually  alter  both  his  faculties  and  his  surroundings  with- 


I04  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

out  altering  his  organisation.  When  this  accumulation 
extends  beyond  the  individual^  it  implies  a  social  devclop- 
mentj  and  explains  the  enormous  changes  wrought  within 
historical  times^  and  which  define  the  difference  between  the 
savage  and  the  civilised  man.  Let  us  consider  for  a  moment 
some  of  the  conclusions  which  may  be  inferred  from  this 
cardinal  fact. 

12.  Imairine  an  exhaustive  statement   of  the   differences 

O 

between  modern  England  and  the  England  of  thirty  cen- 
turies back  —  of  the  England    inhabited    by  twenty  mil- 
lions of  civilised   beings   and  the  England   which  was   the 
hunting-ground  of  a  few  tribes  of  wandering  savages.     We 
should  have  to  begin  by  noticing  vast  material  changes — 
rivers  embanked^  marshes  drained^  forests  felled,  roads  con- 
structed,  houses  built,   fields  tilled,   wolves    supplanted    by 
sheep — and  making  a  calculation  of  the  industrial  capital 
and  the  artistic  treasures  accumulated.     All  this,  we  should 
have  to  observe,  implies  the  possession  not  only  of  different 
materials,  but  of  a  new  set  of  tools.     The  modern,  though 
not  inheriting  greater   faculties    at   his   birth,   can    compel 
material  force  to  co-operate  with  him.     He  has  gunpowder, 
steam-engines,  and  printing-presses  where  a  wheeled  carriage 
or  an  iron  nail  would  have  astonished  his  predecessor  as  a 
miracle  of  art,  and  would   have  been  unattainable  bv  an 
equal  expenditure  of  intellectual  energy.    This,  again,  implies 
the  inheritance,  not  only  of  materials  and  of  tools,  but  of 
skill.     To  the  savage  a  telegraph  or  a  book  would  be  so  much 
iron  wire  and  rags.     The  modern  has  at  his  disposal  vast 
accumulations  of  knowledge.     He  knows  the  properties  of 
substances,  the  form  and   character   of  his   dwelling-place, 
the  history  of  his  race ;  innumerable  products  of  previous 
intellectual    energy    in    the   shape    of    discovered    laws    of 
nature,  mathematical  formulas,  philosophical,  religious,  and 
political    speculation,   are  at   his    service.     The    knowledge 
existing  in  different  times  has  become  incomparably  too  vast 
for  any  single  brain.     Much  of  it,  we  may  even  say,  exists 
in  no  brain,  and  yet  is  potentially  there.     It  is  externalised 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  105 

in  countless  books  and  papers  laid  up  in  accessible  places. 
We  inherit  not  merely  the  tangible  products  of  labour  but 
the-methods  of  labour.  Our  ancestors  transmit  to  us  both 
results  and  the  means  of  obtaining  fresh  results ;  they  trans- 
mit their  mechanical  skill  and  their  logic,  although  they 
do  not  transmit  any  modification  of  structure.  The  infant 
always  starts  at  the  same  point  of  intelligence,  but  the  path 
has  been  cleared  for  him,  so  that  he  can  reach  an  enormously 
more  distant  goal.  A  child  is  not  born  a  clockmaker  now 
any  more  then  he  was  three  thousand  years  ago,  but  not 
the  less  does  he  inherit  the  power  of  making  clocks. 

13.  The  most  striking  illustration  of  this  process  is  to  be 
found  in  language.  Language  is  clearly  a  product  of  the 
social  organism  in  this  sense,  that  its  development  does  not 
imply  any  essential  change  of  the  organs,  but  a  social  develop- 
ment. It  was  not  bestowed  upon  men  from  without,  nor 
is  it  a  necessary  product  of  our  organisation,  or  worked  out 
by  each  man  for  himself.  It  has  been  gradually  elaborated 
from  some  simple  germ  by  the  race  under  the  pressure  of 
social  needs;  and  each  child  accepts  it  as  a  ready-made  instru- 
ment from  his  nurse  and  transmits  it  to  his  successors,  impress- 
ing upon  it  at  rare  intervals  some  relatively  trifling  improve- 
ment. If  we  notice  how  much  a  child  learns  in  simply  learn- 
ing to  speak,  we  shall  see  how  much  it  owes  to  the  society  in 
which  it  is  placed.  To  learn  to  speak  is  to  learn  a  number 
of  signs  with  which  to  fix  in  the  memory  a  number  of  things 
or  aspects  of  things  which  would  else  be  forgotten,  and  to 
enable  ourselves  to  recall  them  easily  to  the  memory  of  others, 
and  to  have  them  recalled  by  others.  It  is,  again,  to  have 
both  outward  objects  and  the  emotions  which  they  excite 
arranged  in  groups,  so  as  to  facilitate  the  reproduction  of  old 
impressions  and  to  render  accurate  and  speedy  the  complex 
processes  involved  in  every  act  of  reflection.  Language  is 
so  essential  an  instrument  of  learning,  that  it  is  very  difficult 
for  the  mature  mind  to  conceive  of  any  but  the  simplest 
process  of  thought  taking  place  without  it.  Thus  in  learning 
a  language  we  learn  a  logic;  for  the  structure  of  language  is 


v-» 


io6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

determined  by  the  elementary  methods  of  reasoning,  which 
in  its  turn  determines  the  methods  of  those  who  speak  it. 
As  every  instrument  supposes  certain  methods  of  using  it, 
the  mechanism  of  language  implies  the  acquisition  of  corre- 
sponding mental  habits.  Thus,  again,  language  implies  the 
unconscious  absorption  of  a  philosophy,  as  is  abundantly 
clear  to  any  one  who  will  trace  the  use  of  such  words  as 
matter,  form,  suhstance,  spirit,  and  so  forth,  and  observe  how 
all  speculation  has  started  from  the  attempt  to  analyse  what 
was  already  implicitly  given  by  words  embodying  previous 
results  of  thought.  We  are  metaphysicians  in  the  cradle, 
and  distinguish  object  and  subject  by  methods  instilled  into 
us  by  our  nurses.  We  start  with  an  implicit  psychology, 
as  the  names  of  the  various  emotions  imply  a  rough  classi- 
fication of  the  primary  elements  of  character.  The  same  is 
true  to  some  extent  of  every  branch  of  inquiry.  The  child 
learns  the  Ptolemaic  system  of  astronomy  as  soon  as  he  can 
talk  about  the  moon  and  the  stars.  A  philosopher  who 
wishes  to  introduce  a  new  conception  has  to  invent  a  new 
terminology,  which  is  yet  always  a  modification  of  the  old 
symbols,  and  in  the  very  act  imposes  fetters  on  his  own  mind, 
and  provides  moulds  in  which  thought  is  to  run  hereafter. 
Often,  it  need  hardly  be  said,  he  introduces  some  insidious 
sophistry  from  which  it  is  very  difficult  to  escape.  Philosophy 
is  in  great  measure  a  series  of  attempts  to  escape  from  the 
erroneous  conceptions  thus  tacitly  introduced  in  the  very 
earliest  forms  of  speech.  And,  finally,  it  may  be  observed 
that  language  naturally  affects  our  feelings  as  well  as  our 
conceptions.  Words  not  merely  denote  an  object,  but 
associate  it  with  certain  emotions.  We  catch  the  subtle  con- 
tagion of  prejudice  from  the  language  which  it  has  impreg- 
nated. We  hate  a  race  because  its  name  has  been  used 
as  a  term  of  abuse.  Papist  amongst  Protestants,  heretic 
amongst  Catholics,  Jew  amongst  Christians,  are  words  which 
have  been  used  to  propagate  bitter  hatred  combined  with  an 
almost  complete  ignorance  of  the  hated  object.  Briefly,  to 
teach  a  child  to  speak  is  to    educate    it,  to  prepare  it  for 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  107 

association  with  others^  to  lay  it  open  to  all  manner  of 
influences,  to  start  it  with  a  mass  of  knowledge  already 
elaborately  organised,  to  teach  it  methods  of  thinking  and 
imagining,  to  insinuate  into  its  mind  philosophical  and 
religious  principles,  and  to  inoculate  it  with  innumerable 
associations  which  must  be  important  elements  in  the 
development  of  its  character. 

14.  The  child,  then,  starts  with  an  organisation  for 
thinking  and  speaking  as  the  bird  leaves  the  egg  with  the 
organs  of  flying  or  swimming.  Whether  and  in  what  sense 
this  organisation  is  the  product  of  a  previous  elaboration  is 
not  at  this  point  a  relevant  question.  In  each  case,  at  any 
rate,  the  infant  starts  with  certain  faculties.  But  the 
essential  diiference  is  clear.  llie  eagle  learns  to  fly,  the 
duck  to  swim,  the  child  to  walk  as  eagles,  ducks,  and  children 
have  flown,  swaim,  and  walked  since  the  species  appeared ; 
from  the  organisation  we  can  safely  infer  the  function; 
but  in  the  case  of  language  this  is  no  longer  true.  The 
child  as  it  grows  up  inherits  not  only  the  faculties,  but  the 
modifications  and  elaborations  of  its  faculties  which  have 
been  developed  by  the  society  in  which  it  lives.  Its  organs 
of  speech,  its  intellectual  powers,  might  be  equal  to  those 
of  Homer  or  Plato ;  but  if  Homer  or  Plato  had  been  born 
amongst  the  Hottentots,  they  could  no  more  have  composed 
the  "Iliad"  or  the  ^'Dialogues"  than  Beethoven  could  have 
composed  his  music,  however  fine  his  ear  or  delicate  his  or- 
ganisation, in  the  days  when  the  only  musical  instrument 
was  the  tom-tom.  The  instrument,  whether  it  has  or  has  not 
a  material  embodiment,  is  equally  essential  in  both  cases.  The 
analogy  of  vocal  music  would  serve  as  well  as  that  of  instru- 
mental. The  art  of  singing  has  to  be  created  by  the  labours 
of  successive  generations  of  musically  endowed  generations, 
whether  the  instrument  be  the  human  throat  or  the  fiddle. 
Hence,  the  activity  of  the  individual  is  essentially  conditioned, 
not  merely  by  his  individual  organisation,  but  by  the  social 
medium.  His  predecessors  have  created  a  new  world.  The 
physical  basis  may  be  the  same,  but  the  man  develops  under 


io8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

a  set  of  influences  which  profoundly  affect  his  intellect,  his 
emotions,  and  his  activities.  The  material  world  is  not  more 
altered  by  cultivating  fields  and  manufacturing  tools  than 
the  world  of  thought  by  the  development  of  language  and 
all  that  system  of  logically  organised  methods  of  reasoning 
which  determine  the  lines  of  discharge  of  intellectual  energy. 
15.  Human  conduct,  then,  depends  essentially  upon  the 
social  factor;  we  must  study  the  properties  of  the  social  as 
well  as  of  the  individual  organism  in  order  to  understand  it ; 
and  in  this  is  already  implied  a  further  condition  of  vital 
importance.  The  individual,  that  is,  is  dependent  at  every 
moment  upon  his  contemporaries  as  well  as  upon  his  ances- 
tors. When  I  have  learnt  a  language,  I  have  an  instrument 
which  will  serve  me  in  solitude.  I  can  sit  down  in  my 
study  and  speculate  or  imagine  as  I  please.  My  thoughts, 
it  is  true,  are  modified  at  every  instant  by  the  instrument 
elaborated  by  others,  but  the  instrument  remains,  when  once 
acquired,  a  constant  factor.  But  this,  of  course,  is  an  in- 
finitesimal part  of  the  ordinary  use  of  language.  As  it 
has  been  developed  by  the  need  of  communication,  it  also 
serves  at  every  moment  as  a  means  of  communication,  and 
it  is  as  governing  my  relation  to  my  fellows  that  it  exercises 
themost  palpable  and  continuous  influence;  and  this  isequally 
true  of  all  the  other  social  faculties.  Almost  every  action  of 
my  life  is  dependent  more  or  less  directly  upon  the  co-opera- 
tion of  others,  and  the  more  so  as  I  become  more  civilised. 
I  cannot  think  without  assuming  the  knowledge  attained  by 
others.  I  see  that  my  fire  is  low;  I  feel  that  I  am  too  cold ; 
I  infer  that  I  should  put  on  coals.  Even  in  so  simple  a  case  I 
use  inherited  results  of  the  experience  of  others,  and  especially 
of  the  great  discovery  of  fire  and  its  properties.  But  I  am 
also  dependent  upon  the  continued  co-operation  of  others. 
I  could  not  arrange  the  details  of  a  day's  work  without 
taking  into  account  the  conduct  and  the  continuous  action, 
for  example,  of  those  processes  which  determine  my  supply 
of  coal.  I  cannot  think  to  any  purpose  without  taking  for 
granted  the  veracity  and  intelligence  of  innumerable  fellow- 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  109 

men,  and  fitting  my  own  results  into  the  vast  mass  of  results 
attained  by  others.  Each  individual,  in  whatever  depart- 
ment he  labours,  assumes  that  others  are  labouring  in  tacit 
or  express  co-operation.  If  millions  can  live  in  a  region 
which  formerly  supported  a  few  thousands,  it  is  because  each 
of  the  millions  has  millions  of  co-operators.  If  I  can  devote 
myself  to  write  an  ethical  treatise,  it  is  because  thousands  of 
people  all  over  the  world  are  working  to  provide  me  with 
food  and  clothes,  and  a  variety  of  intellectual  and  material 
products.  If  another  man  lives  by  putting  one  brick  on 
another,  it  is  because  he  can  trust  the  discharge  of  other 
essential  functions  to  the  numerous  classes  who  are  contri- 
buting more  or  less  directly  to  his  support,  protection,  and 
instruction.  Briefly — for  it  is  useless  to  dwell  upon  this 
familiar  topic — the  growth  of  society  implies  that  division  of 
functions  which  has  been  more  or  less  recognised  by  every 
one  who  has  considered  the  question  since  the  dawn  of 
speculation.  This  vast  social  organisation  is  the  work  of  a 
vast  series  of  generations  unconsciously  fashioning  the  order 
which  they  transmit  to  their  descendants.  It  is  only  neces- 
sary to  take  note  of  the  familiar  fact,  because  some  of  the 
consequences  which  it  implies  have  been  neglected  or  insuffi- 
ciently emphasised.  Briefly,  society  exists  as  it  exists  in 
virtue  of  this  organisation,  which  is  as  real  as  the  organisa- 
tion of  any  material  instrument,  though  it  depends  upon 
habits  and  instincts  instead  of  arrangements  of  tangible  and 
visible  objects. 

16.  It  is,  again,  obvious  that  as  every  man  is  born  and 
brought  up  as  a  member  of  this  vast  organisation,  his  char- 
acter is  throughout  moulded  and  determined  by  its  pecu- 
liarities. It  is  the  medium  in  which  he  lives,  as  much  as  the 
air  which  he  breathes  or  the  water  which  he  drinks.  And 
this  implies  not  merely,  from  the  facts  already  noted,  that 
his  intellectual  furniture,  his  whole  system  of  beliefs,  pre- 
judices, and  so  forth,  are  in  a  great  degree  acquired  by 
direct  transference,  and  that  consciously  or  unconsciously  he 
imbibes  the  current  beliefs  and  logical  methods  of  his  fellows. 


no  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

but  also  that  he  is  educated  from  infancy  by  the  necessity 
of  conforming  his  activities  to  those  of  the  surrounding 
mass.  If  his  feeHngs  or  behefs  bring  him  into  conflict  with 
his  neighbours,  he  is  constantly  battered  and  hammered 
into  comparative  uniformity.  To  deviate  from  the  beaten 
track  is  to  expose  oneself  to  incessant  collisions.  If  it  is  the 
custom  to  keep  to  the  right  in  a  street,  I  can  only  go  to  the 
left  at  the  risk  of  being  trodden  under  foot.  And  thouirh 
some  results  of  this  process  are  lamented  by  many  reasoners, 
it  is  clear  that  in  some  degree  it  is  a  necessary  condition  of 
all  progress.  It  is  as  necessary  to  conform  to  certain  rules 
as  to  accept  certain  beliefs.  If  I  insisted  upon  trying  for 
myself  the  effect  of  every  kind  of  food,  I  should  not  survive 
my  first  crucial  experiment  upon  arsenic.  If  I  deviate  from 
ordinary  rules,  I  so  far  deprive  myself  of  the  advantages  of 
co-operation,  because  my  neighbours  are  unable  to  foresee 
my  conduct  or  to  act  in  harmony  with  me.  If  I  insist  upon 
dining  only  in  the  middle  of  the  day,  I  am  so  far  debarred 
from  society  ;  if  I  object  to  the  ordinary  forms  of  worship,  I 
cannot  have  the  stimulus  of  common  prayer.  If  to  gain 
the  advantages  I  accept  the  rules,  my  character  is  modified 
accordingly.  Be  the  result  bad  or  good,  all  organisation 
implies  uniformities  of  conduct,  and  therefore  continuous 
discipline.  We  are  born,  not  into  a  chaotic  crowd,  but  into 
an  organised  army,  and  we  must  learn  to  keep  step  and  rank 
and  to  obey  orders.  But  to  appreciate  more  clearly  the 
nature  of  the  discipline,  we  must  consider  some  broad  facts 
as  to  the  constitution  of  the  army. 

17.  Sociology  treats  of  the  social  organism,  and  those  con- 
siderations already  set  down  may  serve  to  show  what  is 
meant  by  this  statement,  and  how  far  the  word  is  used  in 
the  same  sense  when  we  speak  of  the  individual  and  the 
social  organism.  It  is  enough  to  say  here,  that  it  implies  at 
least  that  some  important  rules  are  equally  applicable  in  both 
cases.  It  is  as  true  that  man  is  dependent  upon  his  fellows 
as  that  a  limb  is  dependent  upon  tlie  body.  It  would  be 
as  absurd  to  ask  what  would  be  the  properties  of  a  man 


SOCIETY  AND  MAN.  ill 

who  was  not  a  product  of  the  race,  as  to  ask  what  would  be 
the  properties  of  a  leg  not  belonghig  to  an  animal ;  or  to 
ask  what  would  be  the  best  type  of  man  without  considering 
his  place  in  society,  as  to  ask  what  would  be  the  best  kind 
of  leg  without  asking  whether  it  belonged  to  a  hare  or  a 
tortoise.  And  in  the  next  place,  it  is  true  that  the  proper- 
ties of  a  society  cannot  be  deduced  from  the  independent 
properties  of  its  members  in  the  same  sense  as  it  is  true  that 
the  properties  of  any  living  body  cannot  be  deduced  from 
the  mechanical  and  chemical  properties  of  the  elements  of 
which  it  is  composed.  Destroy  the  life  in  either  case,  and 
the  remaining  properties  of  the  dead  materials  do  not  enable 
us  to  assign  their  properties  when  forming  an  associated 
whole.  We  cannot  infer  the  properties  of  a  society  by 
supposing  it  to  be  an  aggregate  of  beings  independent  of 
society,  because  such  beings  are  mere  nonentities.  The 
residue,  when  you  had  abstracted  from  it  all  social  qualities, 
would  in  any  case  be  merely  the  material  elements,  the 
hydrogen,  carbon,  and  so  forth,  to  which  the  body  may  be 
reduced;  and  from  these  you  could  infer  neither  the  indi- 
vidual nor  the  society.  But  further,  any  given  society  has 
properties  of  its  own  which  cannot  be  deduced  from  those 
properties  of  the  individual  which  are  common  to  men  in 
all  social  states,  for  those  properties  may,  as  we  have  seen, 
remain  constant  when  the  social  organisation  varies.  The 
inference  from  the  part  to  the  whole  would  be  as  impossible 
as  the  inference  to  the  properties  of  any  given  animal  from 
the  tissues  which  it  possesses  in  common  with  other  animals. 
The  properties  depend  upon  the  way  in  which  they  are 
combined,  and  we  therefore  require  other  data  to  determine 
the  results  of  the  combination.  It  is,  therefore,  necessary 
to  speak  of  society  as  an  organism  or  an  organic  growth 
which  has  in  some  sense  a  life  of  its  own.  And  this,  it  is 
to  be  repeated,  implies  no  mystical  or  non-natural  sense. 
Society  is  not  an  organism  with  a  single  centre  of  conscious- 
ness. It  is  not  something  which  has  any  existence  apart 
from  the   existence   of  the  individual  members.     But  the 


112  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

name  marks  the  essential  fact,  that  although  at  any  time 
the  properties  of  the  constituted  whole  are  the  product  of  the 
constituting  units,  those  vniits  have  gained  their  proper- 
ties in  virtue  of  belonging  to  this  whole.  The  society  as  a 
whole  acquires  new  characteristics  at  different  stages  of 
growth  which  are  only  explicable  through  its  history ;  and 
therefore,  though  we  may  properly  speak  of  any  particular 
social  phenomena  as  resulting  solely  from  the  character  of 
the  individual  agents,  we  must  also  tacitly  assume  that  their 
character  is  to  be  dependent  upon  their  relations  to  a  society 
at  the  given  stage  of  growth.  We  may  no  doubt  try  to 
explain  this  fact  by  assuming  that  latent  properties  have 
existed  in  the  individual  at  earlier  stages,  as  we  may  suppose 
that  the  material  elements  of  a  body  have  latent  properties 
which  only  reveal  themselves  through  the  vital  union.  But 
since  we  can  only  know  them  as  they  are  manifested,  we 
can  only  give  an  intelligible  account  of  the  society  by 
regarding  them  as  properties  of  the  social  organism.  The 
phrase  "latent  property"  is  only  intelligible  as  marking  the 
fact  that  a  man  (or  a  baby),  if  transplanted  from  one  society 
to  another,  would  acquire  the  corresponding  characteris- 
tics, which  is,  indeed,  assumed  in  our  statement.  So  that, 
whatever  the  ultimate  facts,  we  must  be  prepared  to  find 
qualities  developed  through  the  social  union  which  are  not 
immediately  deducible  from  the  properties  of  the  individual 
without  reference  to  that  union.  The  necessity  of  this  as- 
sumption and  of  the  corresponding  terminology  will  appear 
as  we  proceed. 

III.  Social  Organisation. 

1 8.  An  organism  implies  organs.  The  society,  like  the 
individual,  has  its  organs  of  self-defence  and  nutrition,  its 
apparatus  corresponding  to  the  brain,  the  stomach,  and  so 
forth,  though  it  would  be  absurd  to  press  the  analogy  too 
far.  There  is  this  much  resemblance,  at  any  rate,  that  the 
society  develops  associations  each  of  which  has  its  separate 


SOCIAL  ORGANISATION.  113 

function^  and  implies  the  development  of  corresponding 
associations  with  other  functions.  Political,  ecclesiastical, 
and  industrial  oro;ans  become  more  distinct  and  more  inter- 
dependent  as  society  advances.  These  organs,  indeed,  are 
neither  mutually  exclusive  nor  generally  conterminous  in 
respect  of  the  individuals  who  compose  them.  Every  man 
may  be,  and  generally  is,  a  member  of  several  organs.  He 
may  belong  to  a  church,  a  state,  a  commercial  company, 
and  so  forth.  Sometimes  membership  of  one  may  be  in- 
compatible with  membership  of  another,  especially  of  the 
same  kind ;  but  the  various  associations  overlap  in  complex 
ways,  and 'do  not  imply,  so  to  speak,  a  fissure  down  to 
the  foundations.  Industrial  associations  may  be  formed 
of  the  subjects  of  different  states.  The  map  of  Europe 
would  diifcr  according  as  we  marked  the  ecclesiastical  or  the 
political  divisions.  Englishmen  belong  to  many  churches, 
and  the  Catholic  Church  includes  subjects  of  many  states. 
And,  of  course,  each  organ,  though  it  may  be  regarded 
as  a  unit  for  some  purposes,  is  for  others  a  highly  com- 
plex structure ;  as,  for  example,  the  state  includes  mili- 
tary, judicial,  and  administrative  organs,  each  of  which  is 
again  an  organised  structure. 

19.  Now,  although  this  division  into  organs  or  associa- 
tions does  not  correspond  to  a  division  of  society  into  sepa- 
rate groups,  but  to  a  division  of  the  various  activities  of 
a  single  group,  it  is  equally  true  that  each  organ  may  be 
regarded  as  havins:  in  some  sense  a  life  of  its  own.  It 
persists  as  a  body  persists  in  spite  of,  or  rather  in  virtue 
of,  a  continuous  change  in  the  constituent  particles.  The 
associations  graduate  by  indefinite  degrees  from  the  most 
ephemeral  and  accidental  up  to  the  most  permanent  and 
essential.  Man,  according  to  the  old  formula,  is  naturally 
a  social  animal.  Whenever  two  men  meet  there  is  the 
germ  of  a  possible  alliance  or  antagonism.  The  most  trivial 
bond  may  serve.  Two  travellers  who  happen  to  meet  in 
crossing  a  ferry  have  already  a  certain  community  of 
interest.     They  are  liable  to  common  dangers  and  have  a 

H 


114  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

certain  sympathy.  If  they  are  passed  by  another  boat,  they 
will  regard  the  other  travellers  as  rivals,  and  be  prepared  to 
take  a  pride  in  the  success  of  the  embryo  society,  even  in 
defiance  of  the  reflection  that  their  own  merits  have  no 
influence  upon  its  success.  Johnson's  hatred  of  the  "dockers," 
when,  for  the  moment,  he  adopted  the  local  prejudices  of 
Plymouth,  is  a  humorous  illustration  of  a  general  principle. 
The  germs  of  association  are  everywhere  present,  and  every 
temporary  cohesion  supplies  the  necessary  medium  for  their 
rapid  development.  There  are,  indeed,  two  cases  which 
correspond  to  very  different  kinds  of  association.  We  may 
regard  the  human  organisation  with  no  more  interest  than 
we  should  feel  for  a  material  instrument.  We  may  regard 
a  servant,  as  we  regard  the  bell  which  summons  him,  as  a 
food-brin^ino;  machine.  A  master  may  re2;ard  his  slaves 
with  the  same  feeling  as  he  regards  his  horses  or  his  ploughs. 
They  are  simply  means  to  an  end,  and  the  association  would 
vanish  if  the  end  were  no  longer  desirable.  In  the  opposite 
case,  we  sometimes  reverse  the  process,  and  come  to  entertain 
for  material  instruments  some  of  the  affection  which  is 
normally  the  product  of  sympathy;  but  the  feeling  springs 
up  naturally,  and  acquires  importance  when  we  have  to  do 
with  our  fellows.  In  such  cases  the  corporate  feeling  ceases 
to  have  any  accurate  proportion  to  our  desire  for  the  osten- 
sible end  of  the  association.  The  man  loves  the  school  in 
which  he  has  been  brought  up  with  very  little  reference  to 
its  merit  as  an  educational  institution.  We  come  to  love  a 
corporate  body  as  though  it  were  a  real  person.  We  speak 
of  a  church  or  a  state  as  "  she,"  and  when  we  are  told  that 
a  corporation  has  no  soul,  the  remark  strikes  us  as  if  it  were 
the  revelation  of  a  new  and  unsuspected  truth.  The  osten- 
sible end  of  an  association  is  often  the  least  part  of  its  value 
for  us.  We  really  love  it  because  it  supplies  us  with  a 
means  of  cultivating  certain  emotions  and  of  enjoying  the 
society  of  our  fellows ;  and  it  would  be  an  entirely  inadequate 
account  of  the  whole  statement  if  we  regarded  it  as  simply 


SOCIAL  ORGANISATION.  115 

the  means  of  attaining  that  pleasure  which  has  given  the 
pretext  for  its  formation. 

20.  The  corporate  sentiment  thus  developed  is  more 
complex  and  less  capable  of  analysis  in  those  associations 
of  which  we  have  become  members  without  any  conscious 
volition.  When  we  have  been  brought  up  from  our  infancy 
as  members  of  a  state  or  churchy  or  have  been  made  members 
of  some  society  before  the  age  of  reflection^  our  emotions 
and  activities  become  so  thoroughly  identified  with  those  of 
the  body,  that  we  are  incapable  of  assigning  any  specific  end 
as  supplying  the  dominant  motive.  The  sentiment^  for 
example^  of  patriotism  is  one  which  defies  analysis.  The 
state,  we  may  say,  discharges  a  certain  social  function. 
According  to  some  theorists^  it  is  useful  simply  as  a  means 
of  protecting  its  members  against  violence.  Even  upon 
this  supposition  the  corresponding  sentiment  would  be 
complex^  inasmuch  as  a  desire  for  protection  implies  a 
desire  for  gratifying  any  of  the  instincts  which  might  expose 
us  to  danger.  But  the  bare  desire  for  protection  would  be 
a  very  inadequate  explanation  of  the  emotion  roused  by  the 
thought  of  a  man's  native  country,  which  possesses  a  com- 
plexity of  a  far  higher  order^  and  seems  to  be  an  instinct 
in  which  every  part  of  his  nature  is  more  or  less  directly 
concerned.  It  may  possibly  be  true  that  if  the  need  of 
protection  could  be  removed  the  instinct  would  decav,  but 
in  any  case  it  has  an  independent  vitality,  the  conditions 
and  nature  of  which  could  only  be  unravelled  by  elaborate 
psychological  and  historical  investigation.  At  the  opposite 
end  of  the  scale  are  generallv  the  industrial  associations, 
which  generate  very  little  corporate  sentiment.  The  actual 
co-operation  which  exists  between  different  parts  of  the 
industrial  mechanism  calls  out  very  little  distinctive  senti- 
ment towards  the  whole  association.  The  end  alvvavs 
remains  distinct.  A  bank,  for  example,  is  a  highly  im- 
portant part  of  the  machinery  by  which  one  set  of  people 
are  enabled  to  co-operate  in  the  industrial  occupations  of 
another  set.     But  although  the  utility  of  the  bank  is  the 


Ii6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

cause  of  its  persistence,  the  banker  and  his  customers  on 
both  sides  are  not  induced  to  carry  on  their  operations  by 
any  conscious  desire  for  their  neighbours'  advantage,  but 
simply  by  a  desire  for  their  own  comfort.  Each  man  con- 
fines his  view  of  consequences  to  himself.  His  intention  is 
simply  to  keep  or  acquire  wealth.  By  doing  so  he  facilitates 
the  operations  of  his  neighbours  for  the  same  purpose ;  but 
he  does  not,  or  need  not,  think  of  that  result  at  all,  any 
more  than  the  farmer  in  clearing  the  ground  considers 
the  interests  of  the  cattle  which  he  is  about  to  raise.  Their 
interests  coincide  with  his  own  up  to  a  certain  point,  at  any 
rate ;  but  he  is  not  prompted  by  any  sympathy  with  their 
feelings. 

21.  But  this  difference  does  not  necessarily  or  generally 
affect  the  power  of  such  persistence  of  the  organ.  An  elabo- 
rate industrial  organisation  is  necessary  to  the  life  of  a 
civilised  nation,  and  each  member  of  the  nation  is  interested 
in  maintaining  it ;  and  thus  it  is  maintained,  although  it  may 
be  that  no  man  feels  any  more  enthusiasm  about  a  bank  or 
a  railway  company,  considered  as  a  factitious  person,  than 
he  does  about  a  steam-engine  or  a  printing  machine.  Though 
merely  machines,  they  are  necessary  machines.  In  any 
case,  too,  another  conclusion  is  equally  manifest.  Every 
association,  that  is,  to  whatever  type  it  belongs,  necessarily 
implies  the  existence  of  certain  more  general  instincts 
dependent  upon  the  whole  social  development.  If  any 
social  organ  were  or  could  be  conditioned  by  a  separate 
instinct;  if  it  supplied  the  means  by  which  alone  one  specific 
faculty  of  our  nature  could  find  its  gratification,  then  a  study 
of  that  instinct  or  faculty  would  be  the  study  of  the  corre- 
sponding organ.  Or  rather,  the  study  of  one  or  the  other 
would  be  stated  as  inner  and  outer,  as  being  objective  and 
subjective  .theories  of  the  same  phenomena.  But  it  is  plain 
that  this  does  not  correspond  to  the  facts.  The  church, 
for  example,  depends  upon  the  religious  instinct.  It  will 
flourish  or  decay  with  the  rise  and  fall  of  all  that  is  implied 
in  that  name.     But  the  religious  instinct  is  the  name  of  a 


SOCIAL  ORGANISATION,  117 

highly  complex  set  of  scnthnents  which  have  other  mani- 
festations than   that  of  the  ecclesiastical  organisation,  and 
depend  upon  much  wider  conditions  than  those  to  which 
it  is  subject  in  that  capacity.     The  religion  of  a  country  de- 
pends, amongst  other  things,  upon  the  growth  of  specula- 
tion, upon  the  philosophical  and  scientific  conceptions  which 
have  established  themselves,  and  which  react  in  countless 
ways  upon  the  beliefs  which  we  call  religious,  and  the  prac- 
tices to  which  those  beliefs  give  rise.     So,  again,  the  state 
depends  upon  the    loyalty  of  its  members;  but  the  senti- 
ment which  we  call  loyalty  is  again  involved  in  innumerable 
ways  with  all  the  other  modes  of  social  development.     It  is 
closely  bound  up  with   religious  beliefs,  as  the  decay  of  a 
religion  may  involve  a  decay  of  the  political  order  which 
shares  its  sanctity.  Every  political  change  has  an  ecclesiastical 
reaction;  whilst  in  the  other  direction,  again, the  development 
or  decay  of  political  institutions  is  closely  connected  with 
the  changes  in  the  industrial  organisation.     The  existence  of 
complex  industrial  mechanism  implies  necessarily  the  exist- 
ence of  a  mutual  confidence.     It  could  not  exist  unless  men 
were  ready  to  trust  their  fortunes  to  their  neighbours,  and 
to    rely  in  various  ways    upon    their    co-operation.      This 
implies  the  existence  of  a  political  order  in  which  peace  will 
be  preserved  and  contracts  enforced.     And  further,  there  is 
a  close  connection  between  the    industrial    state    and    the 
political  and  religious  condition  of  a  country,  as  the  state  of 
prosperity  or  misery  of  the  mass  of  the  population  has  a 
direct  and  vitally  important  bearing  upon  their  relations  to 
their   rulers  and   teachers.     Briefly,  therefore,  we  may  say 
that  the  existence  of  any  specific  organ  implies  the  existence 
of  an  organism  provided  with  other  organs  discharging  cor- 
relative functions;  and    therefore   it  implies  the  existence, 
not  onlv  of  a  certain   instinct  to  which   it  owes   its    own 
vitality,  but  the  existence  of  more  general  instincts  to  which 
it  is  related  as  a  special  manifestation  to  a  general  sentiment. 
23.  Let  us  recapitulate  these  conclusions  for  a  moment, 
with  a  view  to  their  bearing  on  our  problem.      We  have 


ii8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS, 

seen    that    the  various  properties    characteristic  of  a  given 
social  state  may  be  regarded  as  corresponding  to  three  suc- 
cessive degrees  of  generaHty.       For,  in  the  first  place,  we 
have  those  properties  which  belong  to  a  society  in  so  far  as 
it  consists  of  men,  that  is,  of  men  organised  as  men  are  now 
organised,   or,   since   we    have   assumed    that   this    may    be 
regarded  as  a  constant   element,  of   the    properties    which 
belong  to  all  societies  since  a  period  antecedent  to  the  growth 
of  an  explicit  moral  system.     In  the  second  place,  we  may 
consider  the  properties  of  a  society  at  any  given  stage — and 
of  course  I  shall  speak  generally  of  the  civilised  man  of  the 
present  day — in  so  far  as  they  depend  upon  these  primary 
instincts^  when  modified  and  converted  into  a  virtually  new  set 
of  instincts  by  social  development  and  inheritance.     These 
instincts  must  be  common  to  all  societies  at  that  stage,  and 
to   the  members   of  such    societies   whatever    their  special 
relations  to  the  society.     And,  thirdly,  we  have  yet  another 
set  of  properties  which  belong  to  the  society  as  organised, 
and  which  are  still  modifications  of  the  more  general  instincts, 
but  which  correspond  to  the  particular  organs  into  which 
the  society  is  distributed.    Thus,  to  take  a  particular  example, 
we  may  consider  a  man  in  so  far  as  he  is  born  with  certain 
sensibilities  which  render    him  capable  of   sympathy   with 
his  neighbours.     These  sensibilities,  by  the  hypothesis^  may 
be  found  in  the  rude  as  well  as  in  the  more  civilised  state; 
but  in  the  higher  state  they  will  give  rise  to  what  may  be 
called  a  new  set  of  faculties  and  instincts  in  virtue  of  the 
process  already  described:  the  savage  chief  is  transformed  into 
the  civilised  statesman.     But,  in  the  next  place,  the  instincts 
so  developed  will  qualify  him  for  being  a  member  of  various 
forms  of  association,  political,  ecclesiastical,   and  so  forth; 
and,  as  acted  upon  by  the  special  circumstances  in  which  he 
is  placed,  will  again  determine  his  fitness  for  one  of  these 
functions  rather  than  another,  and  further  for  some  parti- 
cular type  of  ecclesiastical,  political,  or  industrial  organisation. 
And  in  each  case,  it  nuist  be    observed,  the  more    special 
form  of  instinct  must  be    regarded  as    conditioned  by  the 


SOCIAL  ORGANISATION.  119 

more  general;  not  as  if  they  were  separate  forces,  one  of 
which  must  be  conceived  as  controlHng  the  other,  but  simplv 
as  implying  that  the  particular  is  an  embodiment  of  the 
general  under  certain  specific  circumstances,  and  that  the 
general  rule  must  therefore  be  stated  independently  of  the 
particular  case,  as  including,  not  as  controlling  it;  and 
further,  that  the  conditions  upon  which,  in  fact,  the  exist- 
ence of  the  general  instinct  depends  must  always  be  more 
general  than  those  which  are  given  in  the  particular  mani- 
festation. 

23.  The  grounds  for  this  distinction  have  perhaps  been 
sufficiently  indicated;  the  reason  for  insisting  upon  them 
may  appear  more  clearly  by  introducing  another  consider- 
ation. It  is  impossible,  as  has  been  sufficiently  said,  to 
determine  the  properties  of  any  given  society  directly  from 
the  innate  properties  of  the  individual  members.  We 
must  regard  its  properties,  and  thus  the  special  characteristics 
of  its  various  organs,  as  determined  by  those  properties  which 
are  developed  through  the  social  union.  But,  again,  we 
cannot  determine  these  organs  directly  from  the  social 
properties  of  the  individual;  for,  in  fact,  it  is  plain  that 
the  organs  are  differently  constituted  according  to  the 
special  environment.  In  other  words,  the  existence  of  a 
particular  political  order  implies  necessarily  the  existence  of 
a  certain  stage  of  social  development;  but  the  inference 
cannot  be  inverted.  Each  social  stage  is  compatible  with 
many  forms  of  political  organisation  according  to  the 
circumstances  in  which  it  is  placed.  Under  one  set  of 
circumstances  there  is  a  greater,  and  under  others  a  less 
degree  of  centralisation;  in  one  country  the  democratic, 
and  in  another  the  aristocratic,  element  may  be  more 
prominent,  and  this  without  any  important  difference  in  the 
intimate  or  underlying  social  constitution.  The  various  forms 
of  political  organisation  possible  at  a  given  stage  are  related 
as  varieties  to  a  species,  which  may  differ  slightly,  though 
by  altering  the  circumstances  each  might  be  transformed 
into  the  other.     The  deeper  and  more  permanent  charac- 


I20  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

teristics  are  manifested  under  certain  relations  in  the  political, 
under  others  in  the  industrial  organs,  and  so  forth;  and, 
again,  they  may  be  compatible  with  varying  conformations 
in  each  particular  manifestation. 


IV.  Social  Tissue. 

24.  In  order  to  mark  this  distinction,  I  will  venture  to 
speak — applying  an  obvious  analogy — of  social  "tissue." 
The  tissue  is  built  up  of  men,  as  the  tissue  of  physiology  is 
said  to  be  built  up  of  cells.  Every  society  is  composed  of 
such  tissue;  and  the  social  tissue  can  no  more  exist  apart 
from  such  associations  than  the  physiological  tissue  exist 
apart  from  the  organs  of  living  animals.  The  distinction 
does  not  correspond  to  things  separable  as  concrete  pheno- 
mena, nor  can  it  be  compared  to  the  distinction  between 
a  coat  and  the  cloth  of  which  it  is  made ;  for  unorganised 
social  tissue  does  not  exist,  and  the  tissue  develops  new 
properties  according  to  the  mode  in  which  it  is  arranged. 
Thus,  if  you  will,  the  distinction  may  be  regarded  as 
merely  a  logical  device ;  and  yet,  without  taking  into  account 
in  some  form  or  other  the  facts  which  it  is  intended  to 
describe,  it  seems  impossible  to  give  an  adequate  account  of 
the  process  which  we  have  to  consider. 

25.  The  process  is  the  social  evolution.  The  typical 
organism  is  by  our  assumption  that  organism  which  is  best 
fitted  for  all  the  conditions  of  life,  or  in  other  words,  which 
has  the  strongest  vitality.  Now  the  difficulty  which  meets 
us  in  attempting  to  extend  to  human  society  the  principle 
which  may  be  accepted  as  regulating  the  evolution  of  infra- 
human  species  is  the  difficulty  of  determining  the  units. 
The  theory  of  evolution  cannot  be  clearly  apprehended  or 
applied  to  this  case  until  this  point  is  settled ;  for  every 
such  theory  supposes  a  double  set  of  processes.  Every  change 
involves  on  the  one  hand  a  readjustment  of  the  organic 
equilibrium  within  the  organism  and  a  readjustment  of  its 
relations  to  the  internal  world.     The  two  processes  are  in 


SOCIAL  TISSUE.  121 

constant  correspondence,  and  each  Is  regulated  by  the  other. 
But  we  should  manifestly  fall  into  hopeless  confusion  if  we 
did  not  know  what  was  the  unit  of  operation.  Since  the 
process  is  one  in  which  certain  changes  are  mutually 
implied,  so  that  to  suppose  one  to  take  place  without 
another  is  to  suppose  impossibilities,  it  is  obviously  essential 
to  determine  as  far  as  we  can  the  limits  of  the  organic 
solidarity.  We  might  otherwise  fall  into  the  absurdity  of  con- 
sidering the  evolution  of  legs  without  taking  into  account 
the  correlative  changes  of  the  rest  of  the  organism. 

26.  Now  the  difficulty  scarcely  reveals  itself  in  the  evolu- 
tionist theories  as  applied  to  the  lower  species.  We  assume 
an  organic  change  to  occur — no  matter  how — in  certain 
individuals  of  a  species,  and  that  change  to  be  inherited  by 
their  descendants ;  and  thus  two  competing  varieties  to 
arise,  one  of  which  may  be  supplanted  by  the  other,  or  each 
of  which  may  supplant  the  other  in  a  certain  part  of  the 
common  domain.  Some  such  process  is  clearly  occurring 
in  the  case  of  human  variations.  Everywhere  we  see  a 
competition  between  different  races,  and  the  more  savage 
tribes  vanishing  under  the  approach  of  the  more  civilised. 
Certain  races  seem  to  possess  enormous  expansive  powers, 
whilst  others  remain  limited  within  fixed  regions  or  are 
slowly  passing  out  of  existence.  So  far  as  human  develop- 
ment supposes  an  organic  change  in  the  individual,  we  may 
suppose  that  this  process  is  actually  going  on,  and  that,  for 
example,  the  white  man  may  be  slowly  pushing  savage  races 
out  of  existence.  I  do  not  ask  whether  this  is  the  fact, 
because  for  my  purpose  it  is  irrelevant.  We  are  considering 
the  changes  which  take  place  without  such  organic  develop- 
ments, not  as  denying  the  existence  of  organic  developments, 
but  simply  because  they  are  so  slow  and  their  influence  so 
gradual  that  they  do  not  come  within  our  sphere.  They 
belong,  as  astronomers  say,  to  the  secular,  not  to  the  periodic 
changes.  Confining  ourselves,  therefore,  to  the  changes 
which  are,  in  my  phrase,  products  of  the  ''  social  factor,"  and 
which  assume  the  constancy  of  the  individual  organism,  we 


122  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

have   to  ask  what  is  the  unit  ?     And    here    the    theory    of 
variation  just  stated  seems  to  require  some  modification. 

27.  Suppose,  in  fact,  that  an  individual  acquires  a  new 
instinct  or  faculty  in  the  sense  already  explained.  He 
makes,  let  us  suppose,  a  scientific  discovery  which  gives  a 
fresh  command  over  the  natural  forces.  Or  we  may  suppose 
that  a  change  is  brought  about  in  the  social  machinery 
which  substitutes  friendly  co-operation  for  a  state  of  anta- 
gonism, and  therefore  of  wasted  energy.  What  will  be 
the  effect  of  such  a  change  upon  the  society  in  which  it 
occurs  ?  Obviously  it  will  have  an  effect  strictly  analogous 
in  one  respect  to  that  of  the  organic  change.  Improved 
artillery,  like  improved  teeth,  will  enable  the  group  to  which 
it  belongs  to  extirpate  or  subdue  its  competitors.  But  in 
another  respect  there  is  an  obvious  difference.  For  the 
improved  teeth  belong  only  to  the  individuals  in  whom 
they  appear  and  to  the  descendants  to  whom  they  are 
transmitted  by  inheritance ;  bvit  the  improved  artillery 
may  be  adopted  by  a  group  of  individuals  who  form  a 
continuous  society  with  the  original  inventor.  The  inven- 
tion by  one  is  thus  in  certain  respects  an  invention  by  all, 
though  the  laws  according  to  which  it  spreads  will  of  course 
be  highly  complex.  It  may  be  confined  to  a  particular  class 
or  nation,  or  it  may  spread  through  the  whole  race  so  far  as 
it  has  reached  the  necessary  stage  of  development.  To  find 
an  analogy  in  the  case  of  the  individual,  we  must  imagine 
some  molecular  change  to  occur  in  one  part  of  the  organism 
and  to  spread  by  some  kind  of  fermentation  or  contagion 
throughout  the  whole  frame.  And  further,  it  may  briefly 
be  noted  that  any  such  change,  like  the  organic  change, 
involves  a  whole  series  of  correlative  changes,  as  the  inven- 
tion of  artillery  had  a  profound  efi'ect  upon  the  social  and 
political  organisation  of  Europe,  or  as  the  development  of 
more  effective  teeth  more  or  less  alters  the  whole  constitution 
of  the  animal  race  in  which  it  occurs.  And  this  suggests  that, 
for  certain  purposes  at  least,  the  whole  race,  or  the  whole 
race  which  has  arrived  at  a  certain  stage,  must  be  regarded 


SOCIAL  TISSUE.  123 

as  a  single  organism,  or  rather  a  continuous  organic  growth, 
and  that  any  modification  arising  in  one  part  is  propagated 
throughout  the  whole  system. 

.  28.  It  is  indeed  clear  that  this  process  does  not  exclude 
the  action  of  the  "  struggle  for  existence."  An  invention, 
that  is  to  say,  is  propagated,  in  part  at  least,  because  the 
possession  gives  an  advantage  to  the  possessors.  When  one 
people  has  big  guns  or  effective  steam-engines,  another 
people  makes  them  in  order  to  hold  its  own  in  the  com- 
mercial and  political  competition.  But  there  is  the  impor- 
tant difference  that  the  other  race  ca?i  make  them.  If  some 
animals  acquire  better  teeth,  their  rivals  cannot  at  once 
improve  their  teeth  in  order  to  meet  the  new  difficulty; 
but  men  in  the  same  social  state  can  adopt  the  same  inven- 
tions. And,  moreover,  the  process  takes  place  in  great  part 
by  a  direct  method.  A  new  discovery  spreads  through  the 
social  tissue  as  a  fermentation  spreads  through  a  continuous 
fluid.  It  is  always  regulated  by  the  struggle  for  existence. 
Beliefs  which  give  greater  power  to  their  holders  have  so 
far  a  greater  chance  of  spreading  as  pernicious  beliefs  would 
disappear  by  facilitating  the  disappearance  of  their  holders. 
This,  however,  expresses  what  we  may  call  a  governing  or 
regulative  condition,  and  does  not  give  the  immediate  law 
of  diffusion.  A  theory  spreads  from  one  brain  to  another 
in  so  far  as  one  man  is  able  to  convince  another,  which  is  a 
direct  process,  whatever  its  ultimate  nature,  and  has  its 
own  laws  underlying  the  general  condition  which  determines 
the  ultimate  survival  of  different  systems  of  opinion. 

29.  This,  at  any  rate,  is  enough  to  show  that  it  is  of  vital 
importance  to  understand  what  are  the  conditions  of  this 
mutual  accessibility.  In  so  far  as  one  part  of  the  race  is  con- 
tinuous with  another,  and  can  directly  receive  any  modifica- 
tions which  may  arise  elsewhere,  the  race  must  be  considered 
as    forming   for   some   purposes    a   unit,  though  for   other 

purposes  it  may  still  be  a  multitude  of  mutually  competing 
individuals.      The    problem    would    be    simple  if  we    were 

entitled   to  regard  the  race  as  broken  up  into  independent 


124  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

groups — a  case  partly  noticed  in  the  case  of  some  savage 
tribes.  In  this  case  nations  would  be  only  related  as  hostile 
units,  the  existence  of  each  being  maintained  by  a  constant 
struo:o;le  aerainst  its  nei2:hbours,  and  new  inventions  or  beliefs 
being  incapable  of  spreading  beyond  its  borders.  A  modifi- 
cation due  to  the  social  factor  would  be  for  our  purposes 
in  the  same  position  as  an  organic  modification.  The  dis- 
covery of  a  new  weapon  or  the  growth  of  stronger  teeth 
w'ould  equally  give  an  advantage  to  the  group  in  which  it 
occurred  (assuming  it  to  be  diffused  through  that  group)^  and 
we  might  regard  the  group  as  a  unit  in  our  reasoning.  Those 
groups  would  survive  in  either  case  which  were  the  most 
powerful  in  the  struggle  for  existence,  or  in  relation  to  all 
external  circumstances,  including  its  hostile  neighbours.  Now 
it  is  impossible  to  regard  political  states  as  forming  in  this 
sense  ultimate  social  units.  It  is  true  that  the  struggle  for 
existence  of  the  race  which  corresponds  to  a  general  regu- 
lative condition  may  occasionally  lead  to  an  internecine 
struggle  between  nations.  One  survives  by  extirpating  its 
neighbour.  But  this  is  no  longer  the  case  in  any  moder- 
ately civilised  state  of  the  world.  War  is  there  a  com- 
paratively subordinate  phenomenon.  It  is  part  of  a  larger 
series  of  events.  War  decides  how  races  are  to  be  grouped, 
not  which  race  is  to  survive;  or  sometimes  it  merely  de- 
cides what  are  to  be  the  commercial  and  other  relations 
between  different  groups.  A  conquest  is  the  extinction  of  a 
political  organisation,  and  the  commonest  result  is  that  the 
qualities  of  the  resulting  group  are  determined  as  much  by 
those  of  the  conquered  as  by  those  of  the  conquerors.  The 
race  is  not  extirpated  but  incorporated.  The  struggle  for 
existence  still  necessarily  implies  the  supplanting  of  the 
weaker  by  the  stronger,  and  is  therefore  not  represented  by 
the  international  struggle,  which  must  be  taken  rather  as 
the  means  by  which  certain  relatively  superficial  organisa- 
tions arc  determined,  though  this  organisation,  again,  will 
have  a  bearing  upon  the  general  process  of  which  it  is  a 
part. 


SOCIAL  TISSUE. 


125 


30.  This,  again,  falls  in  with  a  remark  already  made.  If, 
in  fact,  we  could  take  states  for  units,  and  regard  their 
struggles  as  the  manifestation  of  the  struggle  for  existence, 
it  would  follow  that  the  problem  worked  out  by  that  struggle 
would  be  identical  with  the  problem  of  the  best  form  of 
state.  I  do  not  mean  to  say  that  even  upon  this  hypothesis 
the  qualities  of  the  group,  considered  under  its  political 
aspect,  would  give  an  exhaustive  statement  of  its  character- 
istics ;  for,  in  any  case,  its  relation  to  other  groups  would  be 
in  every  case  only  a  part  of  its  relations  to  the  whole  external 
world,  and  its  power  of  maintaining  itself  would  also  depend 
upon  its  power  of  obtaining  food  and  so  forth.  But  the 
military  power  would  always  be  the  essential  criterion  of  its 
efficiency,  since  its  life  would  depend  at  every  moment  upon 
its  power  of  satisfying  the  condition  of  military  efficiency. 
Its  capacity  for  holding  its  own  in  the  struggle  would  be 
the  central  faculty  round  which  all  others  would  cluster. 
Butthis,  it  is  plain,  would  give  a  totally  inadequate  result.  For 
the  best  form  of  state,  like  the  best  form  of  army,  is  relative 
to  the  general  stage  of  social  aevelopment,  as  the  best  form 
of  leg  is  relative  to  the  organism  in  which  it  is  included; 
and  thus  the  external  pressure,  though  it  may  always 
supply  one  condition,  supplies  only  one  amongst  many.  To 
state  the  case  fully,  we  should  require  to  know  many  other 
properties  of  equal  importance,  and  directly  dependent  upon 
an  entirely  different  set  of  conditions,  such  as  the  industrial 
capacity  of  the  state,  its  geographical  position,  and  so  forth. 
A  state,  in  fact,  may  be  developed  when  the  external  pres- 
sure is  little  or  nothing.  The  English  constitution  has  no 
doubt  been  profoundly  modified  by  the  relation  to  foreign 
states ;  but  if  for  a  certain  period  all  communication  with 
the  outside  world  had  been  absolutely  prohibited,  the  English 
people  would  still  have  developed  under  different  conditions 
to  some  different  result.  The  conditions  which  would  have 
determined  their  organisation  are  still  of  the  highest  impor- 
tance, and  require  to  be  taken  into  account  when  con- 
trolled or  modified    by  the  influence  of  external  relations. 


126  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Hence — though  it  may  be  superfluous  to  insist  upon  a 
tolerably  obvious  conclusion — we  should  be  led  into  hopeless 
confusion  if  we  identified  the  so-called  social  organism  with 
states^  regarded  them  as  the  units  in  our  calculation,  and 
considered  that  the  special  modifications  were  all  directly 
determined  and  moulded  under  the  influence  of  the  mutual 
competition. 

31.  We  may  thus  consider  the  race  as  forming  what  is 
called  a  social  organism,  or,  as  T  have  preferred  to  sav,  as 
forming  social  tissue.  The  reason  for  preferring  the  latter 
phrase  is  simply  that  it  implies  a  different  kind  of  unity. 
To  use  the  word  '^oro;anism"  is  to  sua;g-est  that  the  whole 
body  is  capable  of  combining  its  efforts  in  order  to  bring 
about  some  common  end;  as  we  may  say  (with  certain 
reservations)  that  a  whole  nation  may  combine  to  carrv  on 
a  war  or  a  single  society  to  build  a  house.  We  cannot  in 
this  sense  predicate  unity  of  the  so-called  organism.  It  is  con- 
tinuous but  has  not  this  unity.  Its  limits  are  fixed  not  by  its 
internal  constitution  but  by  external  circumstances.  It  there- 
fore is  not  analogous  to  the  higher  organism  which  forms  a 
whole  separated  from  all  similar  wholes,  but  to  an  organism 
of  the  lower  type,  which  consists  of  mutually  connected 
parts  spreading  independently  in  dependence  upon  external 
conditions  and  capable  of  indefinite  extension,  not  of  united 
growth.  The  unity  which  we  attribute  to  it  consists  in  this, 
that  every  individual  is  dependent  upon  his  neighbours,  and 
thus  every  modification  arising  in  one  part  is  capable  of  being 
propagated  directly  in  every  other  part.  The  so-called  organs, 
again,  correspond  to  special  combinations  of  parts  of  the 
tissue,  the  configuration  of  which  is  determined  by  the 
special  circumstances  in  which  it  is  placed,  the  physical 
geography  of  its  habitat,  and  so  forth,  but  which  do  not  so 
break  it  up  into  distinct  fragments  as  to  destroy  its  continuity. 
The  organs  which  we  call  states  correspond  to  the  most 
prominent  and  most  deeply  marked  lines  of  distinction;  but 
even  this  demarcation  is  still  relatively  superficial.  The  rela- 
tions between  members  of  different  states  are  bv  no  means 


SOCIAL  TISSUE.  127 

those  of  simple  antagonism^  but  also  of  direct  sympathy 
and  cohesion. 

32.  If,  now,  we  ask  how  the  struggle  for  existence  will 
manifest  itself,  the  answer  follows  from  the  considerations 
already  set  forth.  There  is,  in  the  first  place,  a  constant 
competition,  more  or  less  overt,  between  different  parts  of 
the  race,  which  may  or  may  not  coincide  with  the  struggle 
between  different  nations.  If  we  limit  ourselves  for  a 
moment  to  a  fixed  area  inhabited  by  a  strictly  homogeneous 
race,  implying,  therefore,  a  particular  "social  tissue,"  we 
have  the  case  of  what  may  be  called  Malthusian  competition. 
Given  the  faculties  and  character  of  the  race,  there  is  room 
for  a  certain  quantity  of  population.  It  resembles  an  elas- 
tic body  pressing  steadily  against  fixed  limits.  So  far  as  it 
accumulates  capital  or  acquires  new  capacities,  there  is  room 
for  a  larger  population.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  suppose 
its  sensibilities  to  increase  or  its  standard  of  comfort  to  be 
raised,  or,  in  other  words,  that  it  refuses  to  accept  existence 
except  upon  higher  terms,  there  will  be  room  for  a  smaller 
population.  And  perhaps  I  may  add — though  I  cannot 
here  discuss  the  importance  of  the  consideration — that  an 
inverse  rule  may  sometimes  hold  good.  The  increase  of 
population  in  a  given  area  may  sometimes  be  an  advantage, 
in  so  far  as  it  facilitates  a  more  elaborate  organisation.  A 
million  people  may  be  able  to  live  better  in  a  given  space 
than  a  thousand,  because  they  will  be  able  to  establish  a 
better  division  of  labour,  and,  so  to  speak,  to  tell  off  more 
labourers  to  some  essential  purpose.  Still,  however  intricate 
the  problem,  the  data  are  determinate.  It  is  usually  a  question 
of  the  maintenance  of  an  equilibrium  of  a  certain  kind  and 
quantity  of  social  tissue,  that  is,  of  men  endowed  with  certain 
faculties,  amongst  which  this  power  of  forming  organised 
associations  is  one  of  the  most  important,  under  fixed  external 
circumstances. 

^^.  When  we  extend  the  hypothesis  to  represent  the 
actual  race,  when  we  suppose  the  possibility  of  extension 
into  different  areas  and  the  competition  with  different  races, 


128  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  conditions  increase  in  complexity.     Considering  only  the 
question  of  the  competition  of  races,  which  is  the  problem 
which   concerns  us,  it  may  obviously  take  various  forms. 
Thus,   if    we    suppose    the    competing    races    to    represent 
different  stages  of  social  development  or  to  be  composed  of 
different  tissue,  the  competition  may  be  one  of  extermina- 
tion.    The  feebler  race  may  vanish  before  the  approach  of 
its  stronger  rivals,  as  savage  tribes  vanish  from  Australia 
and  America.      Such  extermination,  it  may  be  added,  need 
not  imply  direct  slaughter,  but  simply  the  gradual  asphyxia- 
tion of  a  race  by  confinement  within  narrower  limits,  and 
the  loss  of  energy  which  seems  to  result  when  the  power  of 
expansion  is  destroyed  ;  but  it  may  be  one  of  subordination, 
as  weaker  races  have  become  the  slaves  of  their  superiors, 
or,  in  some  cases,  their  dependants  without  being  in  the  full 
sense  slaves ;  or,  finally,  it  may  be  one  of  assimilation,  which 
is  manifested  in  the  relations  between  races  at  nearly  equal 
stages  of  civilisation.     For,  as  in  this  case,  we  may  suppose 
the  innate  faculties  to  be  approximately  identical,  and  pro- 
bably the  acquired  faculties  to  be  not  very  widely  different, 
the  race  which  is  put  under  a  stress  by  the  competition  of 
its  neighbours  will  end  by  acquiring  their  capacities,  and 
the  equilibrium  will  be  restored  instead  of  one  being  extir- 
pated.     The  varieties  of  circumstance  are,  of  course,  in- 
definite, and  may  modify  the  result  in  a  thousand  ways. 
For  us,   however,  it  is  enough  to  note  one  essential  fact, 
namely,  that  to  give  any  intelligible  account  of  the  process, 
we  are  forced  to  bear  in  mind  the  distinction  already  drawn 
between  the  fundamental  properties  in  virtue  of  which  the 
race  belongs  to   a  certain  kind  of  social  tissue,  and  those 
relatively  superficial    properties  which    are   implied    in  the 
particular  organisation.     Wherever  there  is  mutual  pressure 
lietwecn  two  parts  of  a  race,  we  should  first  have  to  consider 
how   far  they  consisted  of  the  same  or  of  different  social 
tissue ;  for  upon  this  it  would  depend  whether  the  struggle 
should  be  one  of  extirpation  or  assimilation ;  and,  secondly, 
if  the   issue  of  the  strugsrle  should   in  any  particular  case 


SOCIAL  TISSUE.  129 

depend  upon  various  conditions,  amongst  which  of  course 
must  be  reckoned  the  special  organisation  of  the  competing 
societies.  Thus  a  nation  inferior  in  its  intrinsic  quahties 
may  be  able  to  extirpate  its  superiors  because  it  has  great 
advantages  of  numbers  and  of  geographical  position.  Or, 
again,  the  industrial  organisation  may  determine  whether  a 
particular  group  will  be  absorbed  by  its  neighbours  or 
remain  in  an  isolated  position.  Now,  in  any  case,  we 
can  oflly  speak  of  the  merits  of  any  particular  organ  with  a 
tacit  or  explicit  reference  to  the  qualities  of  the  constituent 
tissue.  The  military  power  is  due  not  simply  to  the  fact 
that  a  nation  has  numerous  armies,  but  that  it  has  the 
qualities  which  enable  it  to  organise  numerous  armies ;  and 
thus  its  military  power  is  always  relative  to  the  more  intrinsic 
and  general  qualities.  And,  secondly,  we  may  assume  that, 
although  in  many  particular  cases  the  more  civilised  may  be 
supplanted  by  the  less  civilised,  the  race  of  higher  intrinsic 
qualities  by  that  of  lower  qualities,  these  accidental  and 
contino;ent  advantao;cs  will  be  eliminated  on  the  averao;e, 
and  the  general  tendency  will  be  to  the  predominance  of 
those  races  which  have  intrinsically  the  strongest  tissue. 

34.  And  now,  putting  aside  this  question  of  competi- 
tion between  races  at  a  different  stage  of  development, 
we  may  observe  that  the  same  principles  apply  in  the  case 
where  we  assume  a  perfect  continuity  or  homogeneity  of 
tissue.  We  must  still,  that  is,  distinguish  between  the 
tissue  and  the  organ;  for  in  every  case  we  assume  that 
some  evolution  is  and  has  been  taking  place.  Manv  races, 
perhaps  the  numerical  majority  of  all  races,  are  indeed  in  a 
stationary  state ;  but  in  any  case  where  any  morality  exists 
we  must  suppose  that  there  has  been  an  evolution  of  the  kind 
in  question  (that  is,  independent  of  organic  changes  in  the 
individual)  in  the  past,  as  there  may  be  in  the  future.  Such 
evolution,  it  is  possible,  may  have  its  limits.  There  mav  be 
a  period,  though  for  many  reasons  it  would  seem  to  be  inde- 
finitely distant,  at  which  everything  has  been  made  out  of 
the  given  materials  which  is  possible^  and  at  which  further 

I 


I30  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

progress  is  therefore  possible  only  on  the  hypothesis  of  an 
organic  change.  In  any  case,  and  whatever  the  stage  of 
evolution  or  the  rapidity  with  which  it  is  proceeding,  the 
changes  which  have  occurred  or  are  occurring  are  made 
possible  through  the  inheritance  of  instincts  and  faculties 
from  our  ancestors,  used  for  application  to  new  purposes. 
Intellectual  growth  is  conceivable  so  long  as  we  are  able  to 
acquire  the  knowledge  already  formulated,  and  to  extend  it 
over  fresh  provinces ;  and  it  seems  impossible  to  fix  any 
limits  to  this  process^  especially  when  we  take  into  account 
the  division  of  intellectual  labour  made  possible  by  the  social 
factor.  In  every  case,  again,  the  race  considered  as  a  whole 
has  to  maintain  its  equilibrium  in  the  general  system  of 
nature,  and  the  particular  organisation  which  is  the  neces- 
sary condition  of  maintaining  as  well  as  of  extending  the 
dominion  of  the  race  at  large  must  always  be  considered 
relatively  to  those  properties  which  have  already  become 
organic  in  the  race.  The  efficiency  of  any  given  organ 
whatever  must  be  estimated  relatively  to  the  organic  pro- 
perties which  are  the  product  of  a  previous  evolution,  though 
at  any  given  period  they  may  be  stationary ;  and  to  deter- 
mine the  laws  of  variation,  which  include  the  case  in  which 
the  equilibrium  is  simply  preserved  without  being  altered, 
we  must  always  distinguish  between  these  intrinsic  qualities 
and  their  more  special  modes  of  application.  This  is  a  logical 
necessity,  in  whatever  sense  it  may  correspond  to  phenomena 
separable  in  fact. 

^^.  There  remains  an  important  question  upon  which 
somethins:  must  be  said.  For  it  may  be  asked,  what  are  the 
characteristics  in  virtue  of  which  we  should  declare  that  two 
races  are  or  are  not  of  identical  social  tissue  ?  The  question 
is  one  which  does  not  admit  of  a  precise  answer  any  more 
than  the  parallel  question,  what  amounts  to  a  specific  dif- 
ference as  distinguished  from  mere  individual  differences  or 
differences  between  varieties  ?  It  is  a  question  of  fact,  where 
the  facts  graduate  by  imperceptible  degrees.  We  might 
perhaps  accept  as  a  sufficient  criterion  the  capacity  of  dif- 


THE  FAMILY.  131 

ferent  races  to  blend  with  each  other.  The  organisatiou 
of  individuals  would  be  regarded  as  identical  when  one 
individual  could  be  transplanted  into  another  race  with 
perfect  facility.  The  same  test  should  be  applicable  to  the 
organic  social  organism.  The  experiments  which  have 
been  tried  upon  a  vast  scale  in  America  would  afford  ample 
illustrations.  When  streams  of  population,  all  drawn  from 
ev^ery  part  of  the  European  continent,  are  poured  into  a 
common  receptacle,  they  rapidly  blend  together,  so  that  all 
distinction  rapidly  disappears.  The  difference  is  maintained 
for  a  time  by  such  differences  as  those  between  modern 
languages,  which  we  may  call  accidental  because  they  corre- 
spond to  no  essential  social  difference.  They  can  speedily 
be  removed,  and  each  race  readily  accepts  the  political  and 
other  modes  of  organisation  which  it  finds  in  the  existing 
organism.  On  the  other  hand,  the  process  is  exceedingly 
slow  in  the  case  of  some  races  separated  by  more  funda- 
mental distinctions.  The  Chinese  and  the  negro  remain 
side  by  side  with  the  other  populations  instead  of  speedily 
losing  their  separate  identity.  In  such  cases  there  is  pre- 
sumably a  difference  of  tissue,  although  it  must  be  observed 
that  so  long  as  there  is  no  organic  difference  sufficient  to 
make  fusion  impossible,  the  acquired  instincts  may  gradually 
be  adopted  by  one  stream  of  population,  and  thus  they  may 
be  assimilated  to  their  neighbours,  with  the  result  either  of 
supplanting  one  kind  of  tissue  by  the  other,  or  of  forming 
a  third,  differing  in  some  respects  from  both  of  the  parent 
stocks. 


V.   The  Famihj. 

'^6.  This,  however,  is  a  question  into  which  I  need  not 
enter  further.  But  one  remark  has  still  to  be  made  which 
is  of  vital  importance  towards  giving  a  clear  statement  of 
the  case.  I  have  spoken  of  the  state,  the  church,  and  in- 
dustrial bodies  as  presenting  different  kinds  of  social  organ?. 
They  are,  in  fact,  the  most  conspicuous  cases,  and  of  the 


132  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

highest  importance  in  any  theory  of  society.  But  there  is 
another  form  of  association,  namely,  the  family,  which  is 
frequently  mentioned  as  though  it  were  another  co-ordinate 
group.  This  mode  of  speech,  though  it  may  be  admissible 
for  some  purposes,  seems  to  me  to  lead  to  much  confusion ; 
and  until  we  have  recognised  the  essential  differences,  I  do 
not  think  that  we  can  have  a  clear  conception  of  the  bearings 
of  our  theorv. 

37,  The  distinctions,  indeed,  between  the  family  and 
other  forms  of  associations  are  too  obvious  to  be  neglected ; 
for,  in  the  first  place,  we  have  here  to  do  with  a  simple  and 
primitive  instinct  which  is  presupposed  in  all  associations, 
instead  of  being  in  any  sense  a  product  of  them.  The 
sexual  and  parental  passions  are  not  only  present  at  every 
stage  of  human  society,  but  their  germs  at  least  must  be 
present  in  the  lower  animals.  The  sentiment  of  loyalty 
to  a  state  is  clearly  a  deriv^ative  sentiment ;  it  is  the  product 
of  many  instincts  or  modes  of  feeling,  each  of  which  has  its 
own  laws,  independently  of  this  special  application.  It  is 
not  a  separate  instinct  with  a  definite  object.  The  family, 
on  the  contrary,  depends  at  once  upon  the  most  primitive 
iiistincts  of  our  nature,  which  are  the  direct  products  of  our 
organic  constitution.  The  love  of  man  and  woman  or  of 
mother  and  child  constitutes  a  bond  which  requires  and 
admits  of  no  further  explanation  by  reference  to  other  emo- 
tions. It  is,  of  course,  true  that  other  instincts,  and  indeed 
every  instinct  of  which  we  are  capable,  come  to  group  them- 
selves round  this  central  instinct  and  strengthen  the  primi- 
tive tie.  But  that  tie  is  more  or  less  the  ground  of  every 
other,  an  antecedent  assumption  in  all  human  society,  and 
therefore  not  explicable  as  a  product  of  other  modes  of 
association.  Again,  not  only  the  association  but  its  form 
is  determined  within  narrow  limits  by  the  organic  structure 
of  the  individual.  The  state  or  the  church  is  an  organism 
capable  of  indefinite  growth  ;  it  may  consist  of  any  number 
of  individuals,  as  its  limits  are  not  fixed  by  the  nature  of  the 
units,  but  l)y  various  contingent  circumstances.    A  man  is  not 


THE  FAMILY.  133 

born  a  king  or  a  subject^  or  in  any  other  social  group,  but 
the  parts  arc  indefinitely  interchangeable — a  statement  which 
is  obviously  not  predicable  of  husbands  and  wives,  mothers 
and  children.  Hence,  although  the  form  of  the  family 
group  has  varied  in  such  important  respects,  it  is  relatively 
constant.  The  same  form  of  family  association  has  con- 
tinued through  many  ages,  and  extends  through  many 
different  races.  And  from  one  point  of  view  this  implies 
the  important  distinction  that  whereas  a  given  state  of  the 
social  tissue  is  compatible  with  a  vast  variety  of  forms  of 
government,  with  large  or  small  associations,  with  despotic, 
aristocratic,  or  democratic  systems,  a  change  in  the  family 
associations  implies  a  corresponding  change  of  vast  import- 
ance in  the  very  intimate  structure  of  society,  or  in 
other  words,  in  the  social  tissue  itself.  The  change,  for 
example,  from  a  society  in  which  polyandry  or  the  forcible 
capture  of  women  was  the  rule  to  a  state  of  monogamy  and 
comparative  sexual  equality  marks  one  of  the  greatest  con- 
ceivable changes  of  social  growth ;  and  thus,  from  a  scien- 
tific point  of  view  at  least,  the  family  is  not  in  any  case  the 
product  of  the  political  arrangement,  but  rather  one  of  the 
primitive  conditions  which  determine  the  nature  of  the 
state.  A  state  may,  of  course,  make  a  marriage  law,  and 
the  society,  acting  through  the  political  organ,  may  affect 
the  nature  of  the  family  association.  But  though  the  law 
determines  certain  rules  about  the  family  tie  which  may  be 
of  great  importance,  it  cannot  create  it  or  modify  it  beyond 
certain  narrow  limits.  For,  in  the  first  place,  the  state  being 
itself  the  product  of  individuals  associated  in  families,  its 
action  will  always  be  determined  by  the  existing  sentiment ; 
and,  secondly,  the  influence  of  any  law  must  always  be  subor- 
dinate. Chastity  and  fidelity  are  not  to  be  made  by  any  law. 
No  state  can  force  men  and  women  to  marry,  or  really  put 
down  licentious  habits,  even  if  it  makes  the  attempt;  and, 
on  the  other  hand,  the  marriage  tie  might  be  equally  re- 
spected in  fact  even  if  there  were  no  law  in  regard  to  it. 
The  law,  in  fact,  recognises  one  kind  of  association  of  the 


134  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

sexes,  and  bestows  certain  privileges  upon  those  who  are  so 
associated,  but  it  would  be  a  hopeless  inversion  of  consequent 
and  antecedent  to  suppose  that  it  can  really  originate  it. 
It  may  be  added,  again,  that  we  need  not  suppose  any  other 
form  of  association  to  be  essential.  It  is  quite  possible  to 
suppose  men  living  together  without  any  political  associa- 
tion; and  according  to  some  theorists  this  is  not  only  possible, 
but  represents  the  ideal  state  of  things.  But  some  associa- 
tion between  the  sexes,  however  temporary  and  casual  it 
might  be,  and  some  protection  of  infants  by  parents  is 
absolutely  necessary  to  the  continuance  of  the  race  beyond 
a  single  generation — that  is,  some  sort  of  family  union  must 
always  exist.  It  need  hardly  be  added  here,  that,  as  a  fact, 
the  family  represents  that  kind  of  association  which  is 
beyond  all  comparison  the  most  vitally  connected  with  the 
happiness  of  the  individual,  and  the  condition  of  which 
most  immediately  affects  the  gratification  of  all  his  strongest 
instincts.  For  a  great  part  of  every  one's  life  the  family  is 
the  whole  world. 

38.  If,  then,  we  look  at  society  as  a  whole,  we  see  that 
the  division  into  families  does  not  properly  represent  a  mode 
of  organisation  co-ordinate  with  the  other  social  organs. 
It  represents,  on  the  contrary,  the  immediate  and  primitive 
relation  which  holds  men  together.  The  family  affections 
are  the  bonds  which  hold  individuals  together,  and  the 
primitive  cohesions  in  virtue  of  which  society  becomes 
possible,  the  molecular  forces  which  form  the  separate  cells 
into  a  continuous  tissue,  the  elementary  property  in  virtue 
of  which  society  is  woven  together,  to  be  afterwards  formed 
into  different  groups.  The  larger  organs  are  relatively  few, 
and  their  conformation  depends  partly  upon  the  contingent 
circumstances  in  each  case,  and  partly  upon  the  mutual 
competition  which  leads  to  the  survival  of  some  and  the 
blending  together  of  others.  They  survive  the  individuals 
of  which  they  are  composed,  as  every  organic  group  lives 
by  the  continuous  elimination  of  some  particles,  and  their 
replacement  by  others.     Such  statements  are  obviously  quite 


THE  FAMILY.  135 

inapplicable  to  families.  They  are  multitudinous;  and  as 
they  represent  the  primitive  cohesion  of  the  constituent 
particles,  they  represent  a  cross  division  running  through  all 
the  other  groups  into  which  societies  may  be  formed,  and 
constantly  disappear  with  the  death  of  the  member,  though, 
as  it  breaks  up,  new  families  are  incessantly  formed  ;  and  the 
social  competition  affects  the  institution,  not  through  the 
competition  between  rival  families,  but  in  so  far  as  the  for- 
tunes of  the  whole  group  are  constantly  dependent  upon  its 
structure,  which  is  determined  in  a  very  great  degree  by  the 
nature  of  its  family  unions. 

39.  A  brief  recapitulation  of  the  principal  conclusions 
will  now  suggest  the  conclusion  which  is  relevant  to  our 
inquiry.  For  I  have  tried  to  show,  in  the  first  place,  that  to 
determine  the  "law^'  or  ''form"  of  any  instinct  developed 
through  the  social  factor,  it  is  necessary  to  go  beyond  the 
individual  to  the  organism  of  which  he  is  a  member.  A 
man  acts  from  patriotic  instinct;  we  may  explain  the  force 
of  this  instinct  in  any  given  case  partly  by  his  innate  quali- 
ties and  partly  by  his  circumstances.  The  latter  considera- 
tion necessarily  introduces  the  social  factor  ;  for  the  instinct 
has  been  elaborated  by  the  evolution  of  the  social  organism, 
and  its  force  and  nature  are  determined  by  conditions  not 
given  when  the  innate  character  is  given,  and  therefore  not 
deducible  from  the  individual  organisation.  So  long,  there- 
fore, as  we  regard  that  organisation  by  itself,  we  must  have 
an  arbitrary  datum,  the  "  law  "  of  which  is  only  ascertain- 
able by  introducing  the  wider  considerations.  Secondly,  we 
have  observed  that  we  have  to  classify  the  various  social 
instincts  by  reference  to  the  complex  structure  of  society, 
which  implies  a  distribution  into  mutually  dependent  organs, 
each  of  which  has  its  own  conditions  of  persistence,  and  dis- 
charges a  more  or  less  definite  function ;  and  further,  that 
any  examination  of  such  organs  shows  that  their  laws  of 
growth  and  vitality  are  always  relative  to  the  underlying 
properties  of  the  "  social  tissue,"  each  representing  a  special 
modification  of  that  tissue  in  view  of  some  particular  func- 


136  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tion,  and  varying  in  its  structure  according  to  various  con- 
tingent circumstances.  Again,  whilst  such  organs  may  be 
adapted  to  a  specific  end,  and  may  therefore  be  regarded 
simply  as  instruments  for  gratifying  some  independent  in- 
stinct, and  their  existence  is  proportioned  to  their  efficiency 
in  securing  the  gratification,  they  always  tend  to  become 
something  more ;  they  acquire  a  vitality  independent  of  any 
special  end,  and  become  organs  discharging  a  complex  func- 
tion, and  imply  the  existence  of  a  correspondingly  complex  set 
of  instincts;  whilst,  finally,  the  social  tissue  is  its  own  end, 
or  depends  upon  the  whole  system  of  instincts  possessed  by 
man  as  a  social  and  rational  creature.  And  hence,  thirdly, 
since  the  social  tissue  represents  the  general  material  or  all- 
pervading  substance  from  which  the  subordinate  associations 
are  constructed,  w^e  must  consider  the  conditions  of  its 
vitality  independently ;  and  therefore  we  see  that  it  is  the 
primary  unit  upon  which  the  process  of  evolution  impinges. 
The  social  evolution  means  the  evolution  of  a  strong  social 
tissue ;  the  best  type  is  the  type  implied  by  the  strongest 
tissue ;  and  the  correlation  between  painful  and  pernicious, 
pleasurable  and  beneficial,  is  to  be  understood  by  interpret- 
ing the  pernicious  and  beneficial  with  reference  to  the  tissue, 
whilst  painful  and  pleasurable  refer  to  the  instincts  gener- 
ated in  the  socialised  being.  It  is  the  vigorous  tissue  which 
prevails  in  the  struggle,  and  fitness  for  forming  such  tissue  is 
therefore  the  criterion  of  a  successful  elaboration  of  the 
type.  This,  it  may  be  noted,  applies  equally  to  the  qualities 
in  respect  of  which  society  is  an  aggregate,  and  those  in 
respect  of  which  it  is  an  organism ;  those  which  cannot  vary 
without  a  corresponding  variation  of  social  structure,  and 
those  which  vary  so  as  to  imply  a  change  in  the  average 
faculties.  For  the  process  of  evolution  is  simple,  and  each 
set  of  properties  is  always  developed  with  reference  to  the 
other.  This  statement,  however  defective,  will,  I  hope,  have 
cleared  the  ground  sufficiently  to  enable  us  to  consider  more 
fully  what  is  implied  as  to  the  nature  of  those  social  in- 
stincts which  gave  rise  to  the  moral  law. 


^37 


CHAPTER  IV. 

FORM    OF    THE    MORAL    LAW. 

I.  Law  and  Custom. 

1.  Society  is  an  organic  structure,  dependent  for  its 
existence  upon  the  maintenance  of  certain  relations  between 
its  members,  more  complicated  in  proportion  to  the  com- 
plexity of  the  whole.  /Its  development  implies,  therefore, 
the  development  of  customs  in  the  race  and  habits  in  the 
individuals.  There  must  be  certain  rules  of  conduct  which 
are  observed  by  all  in  order  that  corresponding  rules  may  be 
observed  by  each.  To  trace  the  development  of  the  society 
is  at  the  same  time  to  trace  the  development  of  the  custom, 
and  conversely  to  trace  the  custom  is  to  trace  the  social 
development. 

2.  I  use  these  words  "custom"  and  "habit"  without 
meaning  to  imply  what  perhaps  is  generally  implied  by 
those  words,  that  the  modes  of  conduct  designated  are 
variable  or  indefinite.  We  oppose  a  custom  to  a  "law  of 
nature"  because  it  is  not  unconditionally  observed,  and  we 
oppose  it  to  the  positive  law  of  a  state  because  its  observance 
is  not  enforced  by  the  policeman.  But  the  difference  is 
not  fundamental.  A  habit  may  often  be  regarded  as  a  law 
of  nature  in  the  making.  It  passes  into  such  a  law  by 
imperceptible  degrees.  We  do  not  say  that  living  men  have 
a  habit  of  breathino;,  because  we  hold  it  to  be  somethino; 
more  than  a  habit;  it  is,  as  we  hold,  a  law  of  nature  that 
living  men  should  breathe.  We  hold,  that  is,  that  the  group 
of  phenomena  denoted  by  human  life  inseparably  and  un- 
conditionally includes  the  phenomena  of  breathing.  We 
speak  of  habit  only  in  cases  where  the  continuance  of  tlie 


138  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

conduct  depends  in  some  degree    upon  the  control  of  the 
will,  and  can  be  suspended  in  cases  where  it  becomes  painful 
beyond  a  certain  point.     But  the  degree  in  which  the  co- 
operation of  the  will  is  a  condition  may  vary  indefinitely 
and  become  a  vanishing  quantity,  as  the  habit  becomes  a 
definitely  organised  mode  of  conduct.     If  we  could  extend 
habit  to  cover  any  mode  of  conduct  which  can  be  brought 
under  any  general  formula  and  is  practised  under  assignable 
conditions,  we  might  apply  it  both  to  conduct  which  must 
continue  as  life    continues    and  to    that    which  implies    in 
addition  to  life  a  particular  state  of  desire  and  aversion  in    ^ 
the  living  being.     The  latter  is  essential  not  to  all  men,  but 
to  all  men  under  given  conditions,  which  may,  of  course,  be 
rare,  or  may  be  all  but  universal.      What  is  true  of  habits    - 
is  of  course  also  true  of  customs.     I  will  only  repeat  that 
customs  may  be  essential  to  a  society  which  do  not  corre- 
spond to  a  habit  essential  to  the  individual.     The  existence 
of  a  given  stage  of  social  development  is  dependent  upon 
certain  customs  which  are  not  exemplified  in  every  member 
of  the  society.     The  most  civilised  country  includes  nume- 
rous savages,  who  are  in  it  but  not  of  it,  foreign  matters  con- 
tained in  the  organism,  and  such  that  it  would  fall  to  pieces 
were  it  not  for  their  restraint  by  the  more  civilised  mem- 
bers of  the  community. 

^3.  Customs,  again,  have  a  relation  to  positive  laws  which 
has  led  to  some  perplexities.  In  primitive  states  of  society 
the  distinction  is  imperceptible.  A  tribe  or  clan  is  bound 
together  by  certain  customs  which  are  regarded  by  its 
members  as  ultimate  and  indefeasible.  They  are  observed ; 
but  it  has  not  yet  been  asked  how  they  acquired  nor  why 
they  should  retain  authority.  In  an  early  stage  of  reflec- 
tion they  are  perhaps  regarded  as  imposed  by  the  authority 
of  the  gods,  which  really  supposes  the  question  may  be 
asked,  but  implies  that  it  cannot  be  answered.  As  they  do 
not  change,  or  change  only  by  imperceptible  degrees,  there  is 
no  question  as  to  the  mode  in  which  they  can  be  changed, 
or,  in  other  words,  of  the  authority  which  imposes  them.^ 


LAW  AND  CUSTOM.  139 

Historical  inquirers,  for  example,  find  the  traces  of  such  a 
state  in  regard  to  the  system  of  customs  which  regulate  the 
possession  of  land.  The  mode  in  \\  hich  the  various  mem- 
bers of  a  tribal  community  arc  to  cultivate  its  domains  or  to 
distribute  the  fruits  of  cultivation  is  settled  by  a  system  of 
rules  which;  in  so  far  as  they  persist  without  reflection  upon 
their  utility  and  the  possibility  of  changing  them,  have 
somethino-  of  the  character  of  animal  instincts.  Thev  are 
analogous  to  the  tacit  agreement  by  which  different  herds 
of  gregarious  animals  may  divide  a  district  between  them, 
yriiere  is  a  continuous  progress  from  this  social  condition  to 
one  in  which  the  land  laws  form  an  elaborate  code  or  an 
intricate  mass  of  regulations,  the  provisions  of  which  are 
expounded  by  judges  and  altered  from  time  to  time  by  the 
legislature.  Now,  however  great  may  be  the  difference 
between  the  two  stages  of  development,  we  have  at  every 
stage  a  social  organisation  dependent  upon  custom.  The 
custom,  indeed,  has  gained  a  new  order  of  complexity.  For, 
in  the  first  place,  the  law  actually  obeyed  is  not  a  simple  set 
of  rules  understood  and  spontaneously  accepted  by  every 
one  concerned.  It  contains  what  we  may  call  a  potential 
element.  For  there  are  a  vast  number  of  regulations  which 
are  only  brought  into  play  upon  rare  contingencies  and 
which  are  known  only  to  a  few  specialistsX^  It  would  be 
straining  words  improperly  to  speak  of  a  custom  which  is 
absolutely  unknown  to  ninety-nine  in  a  hundred  of  the 
persons  concerned,  and  which  perhaps  does  not  determine 
conduct  once  in  a  generation.  ,>The  custom  which  is  essential 
at  all  times  is  that  which  directly  governs  conduct  from 
day  to  day,  and  which  is  implied  in  the  mutual  confidence 
of  proprietors  and  respect  for  the  known  rights  of  property, 
and,  moreover,  that  of  obedience  to  certain  constituted 
authorities  when  called  upon  to  settle  disputes./;  I  can 
hardly  be  said  to  be  in  the  habit  of  observing  certain  rules, 
the  very  existence  of  which  never  enters  my  head,  but  I 
may  be  in  the  habit  of  accepting  the  decisions  of  certain 
persons  who,  on  occasion,  tell    me   what   are   those   rules. 


I40  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

This,  it  may  be  observed,  is  a  general  principle  already 
noticed.  As  knowledge  becomes  too  elaborate  for  any 
single  head,  we  acquire  a  kind  of  potential  knowledge.  We 
do  not  know  the  rule,  but  we  know  where  it  is  to  be  found. 
We  are  not  guided  simply  by  our  instinct  of  locality,  but  by 
our  confidence  in  the  Nautical  Almanac.  A  judge  has  the 
same  use  in  the  social  organism  as  a  general  word  in 
language.  'We  accept  the  general  rule  that  we  are  to  fulfil 
contracts.  In  most  cases  this  may  be  sufficient,  but  to 
mark  out  the  rule  in  a  complex  case  we  have  to  accept  the 
results  obtained  by  persons  specially  qualified.  Thus  a 
custom  may  regulate  conduct  in  cases  where  it  does  not 
imply  a  corresponding  instinct  in  the  minds  of  the  agent, 
because  there  is  this  elaboration  of  the  potential  element, 
which  he  can  call  into  play  by  appealing  to  the  authorities4(^^ 

4.  The  authority,  however,  must  itself  rest  upon  custom, 
which,  again,  is  far  more  elaborate  than  in  the  primitive 
state.  For  the  chief  or  elders  of  the  primitive  tribe  we  have 
the  whole  complex  organisation  of  a  modern  state.  The 
custom  of  obedience,  again,  carries  with  it  much  more  than 
is  actually  present  to  the  mind  of  the  average  citizen.  He 
obeys  the  king,  the  judge,  and  the  policeman,  and  has  pro- 
bably a  very  vague  conception  of  the  precise  relations 
between  their  various  privileges  and  the  relations  of  their 
offices  and  functions.  There  must,  however,  be  a  certain  cus- 
tom of  obedience  to  constituted  authorities,  without  which  the 
whole  state  would  be  a  rope  of  sand.  And  in  this  sense  the 
law  is  not  something  more  than  custom,  but  simplv  a  par- 
ticular case  of  custom.  A  law,  as  jurists  tell  us,  is  the  com- 
mand of  a  sovereign  enforced  by  a  sanction ;  and  the  essence 
of  law,  therefore,  depends  upon  the  ultimate  appeal  to 
coercion,  or,  in  other  words,  upon  the  circumstance  that,  if 
you  do  not  obey  the  law,  you  may  be  made  to  obey  it.  A 
custom,  on  the  other  hand,  depends  always  upon  voluntary 
obedience,  and  exists  only  so  long  as  people  choose  to 
comply  with  it.  Now,  for  purposes  of  jurisprudence,  the 
distinction  may  be  important,  but  it  is  not  ultimate  from 


LAW  AND  CUSTOM.  141 

the  scientific  point  of  view.     It  explains  only  one  collateral 
result  from    the   general    system.       The    lawyer    takes    for 
granted  the  constitution  of  the  state ;  he  is  satisfied  that  a 
rule  is  a  law  when  certain  legislative  processes  have  taken 
place,  and  he  is  content  with  the  conclusion  that  ultimately 
the  judge    can  appeal  to  the  hangman.     He  does  not  go 
further,  nor  ask  how  the  state  holds  together,  nor  in  virtue 
of  what  principle  the  judge  can  depend  upon  the  hangman's 
fulfilment  of  his  duty.     When  we  ask  that  question — as  we 
are  bound  to  do  for  scientific  purposes — we  see  at  once  that 
this  possibility  of  physical  coercion  cannot  give  an  ultimate 
answer.     How  is  coercion  possible?     What  will  happen  if 
the  hangman  does  not  obey  the  judge  ?     We  may  go  for  our 
answer  to  the  nursery  rhyme  about  the  old  lady  who  could 
not  drive  her  pig  to  market.     When  the  butcher  would  not 
kill  the  pig  and  the  rope  would  not  hang  the  butcher,  she 
had  to  appeal  to  the  fire  to  burn  the  rope,  and  so  forth.     She 
depended  upon  coercion  at  some  point  because  she  had  to 
deal  with  a  pig,  but  to  get  the  coercion  she  had  to  find  some 
agency  set  in  motion  without  coercion.     Now  in  the  case  of 
the  state,  it  not  only  may  happen,  but  it  is  undoubtedly  true 
in  all  cases,  that  coercion  must  be  at  hand,  so  to  speak,  to 
maintain  order  in  case  of  necessity  ;  and  by  coercion  I  mean 
the  application  of  physical  force,  or  the  reduction  of  a  man 
to  a  mere  thing,  so  that  his  condition  is  determined  by  forces 
entirely  independent  of  his  own  volitions.     In  that  case  the 
theory  of  the  state  is  the  theory  of  the  man  whose  actions 
determine  the  action  of  his  neighbours.  The  hangman  and  the 
jailer  are  doubtless  necessaries  so  long  as  men  are  what  they 
are,  and  savages  form  a  part  of  a  civilised  community.     But 
it  is  equally  true  that  other  forces  are  essential  to  anything 
like  a  civilised  society.     A  temporary  association  may  be 
formed  where  one  man  treats  another  simply  as  if  he  were  a 
tool,  or  rules  him  by  the  threat  of  so  treating  him.     And, 
again,  a  race  may  be  ruled  from  without  by  oppressors  who 
appeal  only  to  motives  of  this  class.     But  this  fact  does  not 
prove  that  physical  force,  or  the  dread  of  its  application,  is 


142  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

in  any  special  sense  essential  to  political  society.  For  every 
society,  beginning  from  the  simplest  germ  of  social  union, 
where  the  state  is  not  yet  differentiated  from  the  family, 
requires  the  action  of  all  the  social  instincts.  The  more 
elaborate  the  structure,  the  greater  the  number  and  force  of 
the  instincts  which  must  be  called  into  play.  All  that  is 
implied  in  loyalty,  patriotism,  respect  for  order,  mutual  con- 
fidence between  man  and  man,  is  essential  to  the  vitality  of 
a  complex  social  organisation.  A  bond  which  rested  solely 
upon  fear  would  give,  not  an  organic  compound,  but  a  tem- 
porary association,  ready  to  collapse  at  every  instant.  Coer- 
cion itself  is  only  possible  by  virtue  of  the  co-operation 
which  implies  the  existence  of  every  other  social  motive. 
We  may  say  of  any  stone  in  an  arch  that  it  is  the  keystone, 
if  by  abstracting  it  the  arch  would  fall  into  ruin,  and 
coercion  is  in  that  sense  a  keystone  in  the  social  structure; 
but  so  are  all  the  other  forces  which  are  essential  to  the 
structure  so  soon  as  it  attains  any  permanence  or  magni- 
tude. A  power  of  flogging  may  be  essential  to  the  discipline 
of  an  army,  but  an  army  held  together  solely  by  dread  of 
the  whip  would  be  comprised  within  a  circle  defined  by  the 
smart  of  the  lash.  It  is  so  little  essential,  indeed,  that  a  state 
of  society  is  conceivable  in  which  its  actual  application 
should  disappear  altogether.  Men  might  be  willing  to  obey 
their  rulers  simply  from  respect  and  affection ;  judges  might 
be  arbitrators  whose  decisions  would  always  be  accepted  by 
mutual  consent.  The  power  of  applying  coercion  in  case  of 
need  must  no  doubt  increase  as  the  strength  of  the  social 
bond  increases ;  but  that  bond  is  also  the  stronger  in  propor- 
tion as  the  need  of  applying  it  becomes  less. 

5.  The  whole  social  structure,  then,  must  rest  in  the  last 
resort  upon  the  existence  of  certain  organic  customs,  which 
cannot  be  explained  from  without.  They  depend  for  their 
force  and  vitality  upon  the  instincts  of  the  individual  as 
modified  by  the  social  factor;  and  it  would  be  a  fallacy  to 
single  out  any  one  of  these  instincts  as  the  essential  one 
when  the  co-operation  of  all  is  necessarily  implied.     From 


LAIV  AND  CUSTOM.  143 

this  point  of  view,  therefore,  it  is  necessary  to   distinguish 
between  the  organic  instincts  of  a  state  and  the  correspond- 
ing customs  on  the  one  hand,  and  the  derivative  and  secondary- 
instincts  which  are  the   product  of  that  state  on  the  other 
hand ;    otherwise    we    fall    into    the  absurdity,  not  rare  in 
political  speculations,  of  implicitly  assuming  that    a    state 
can  somehow  make  itself.      A  legal  sanction  may  of  course 
be  added  to  any  custom  whatever,  and  thus  it  may  seem 
that  a  state  can  make  its  own  constitution  and  define  its  own 
organic  laws.     In  reality,  however,  the  power  of  making  a 
constitution   presupposes    a  readiness    to  act   together    and 
accept  certain  rules  as  binding,  and  thus  again  implies  a 
whole  set  of  established  customs,  such  as  are  necessary  to  the 
constitution  and  authority  of  a  representative  body.     Law- 
yers are  apt  to  speak  as  though  the  legislature  were  omnipo- 
tent, as  they  do  not  require  to  go  beyond  its  decisions.     It 
is,  of  course,  omnipotent  in  the  sense  that  it  can  make  what- 
ever laws  it  pleases,  inasmuch    as  a  law   means    any   rale 
which    has    been    made   by  the  legislature.     But  from  the 
scientific  point  of  view,  the  power  of  the  legislature  is  of 
course  strictly  limited.     It  is  limited,  so  to  speak,  both  from 
within  and  from  without ;  from  within,  because  the  legis- 
lature   is    the    product    of  a  certain    social  condition,  and 
determined  by  whatever  determines  the  society ;  and  from 
without,  because  the  power  of  imposing  laws  is  dependent 
upon  the  instinct  of  subordination,  which  is  itself  limited.     If 
a   legislature    decided    that    all    blue-eyed  babies  should  be 
murdered,   the   preservation  of  blue-eyed  babies    would  be 
illegal ;  but  legislators  must  go  mad  before  they  could  pass 
such  a  law,  and  subjects  be  idiotic  before  they  could  submit 
to  it. 

6.  Considering,  therefore,  any  society  as  a  natural  growth, 
or,  in  other  words,  regarding  it  from  the  scientific  point  of 
view,  we  see  what  is  implied  in  a  law.  We  assume  that 
certain  organic  instincts  have  been  formed,  corresponding, 
in  my  language,  to  a  given  state  of  the  social  tissue;  and 
involving  a  certain  body  of  customs  essential  to  the  life  of  the 


144  T^I^E  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

society,  and  giving  rise  to  a  special  organisation  according 
to  the  various  internal  circumstances.  We  may,  then,  trace 
the  manifestations  of  the  social  properties  in  two  ways — 
either  as  implying  a  certain  social  structure,  or  as  implying 
a  certain  type  of  character  in  the  members  of  the  society. 
There  is,  on  the  one  hand,  a  political  organisation  which 
acts  in  certain  definable  ways,  and,  for  example,  has  an 
apparatus  for  hanging  convicted  murderers.  The  "law" 
may  be  regarded  either  as  a  statement  of  the  relations  exist- 
ing between  the  various  parts  of  the  political  organism,  or 
may  be  viewed  as  a  command  and  a  threat,  implying  a 
notice  to  murderers  that  they  will  be  hanged  if  caught.  The 
same  facts,  regarded  from  the  other  side,  necessarily  imply 
the  existence  of  an  internal  law.  The  individual  must 
acquire  certain  instincts  in  virtue  of  which  he  respects  the 
authorities  and  dislikes  murderers.  He  must  acquire  them, 
that  is,  in  order  to  be  an  efficient  part  of  the  social  organisa- 
tion ;  and  the  law  may  be  expressed  as  threatening  him  with 
whatever  consequences — other  than  the  legal  consequences 
— result  from  imperfect  harmony  with  his  social  medium. 
The  society  exists  by  virtue  of  the  vitality  of  these  instincts. 
Both  kinds  of  law  are  expressions  of  the  same  general  fact ; 
the  essence  of  the  former  being  that  the  individual  is  subject 
to  a  pressure  tending  to  enforce  a  correspondence  between 
his  actions  or  feelings  and  those  of  his  neighbours.  Some 
such  process  must  take  place  in  every  association,  from  a 
state  to  a  gang  of  thieves,  whatever  the  method  by  which 
conformity  is  produced;  and  wherever  it  is  produced  we  may 
speak  of  a  social  law.  It  may  not  be  possible  to  consider 
the  two  modes  of  action  separately.  Every  law  of  conduct 
more  or  less  affects  the  character  of  the  persons  subject  to  it, 
so  long  as  it  is  enforced ;  and  necessarily  every  variation  in 
the  character  more  or  less  affects  the  sentiments  from  which 
the  external  law  derives  its  force.  The  correspondence, 
however,  is  not  so  intimate^that  one  mode  of  statement  can 
always  be  rendered  into  the  other.  For,  as  I  have  said,  laws, 
and    indeed    elaborate    codes    of  law,  arc  developed  which 


LA]V  AND  CUSTOM.  145 

scarcely  aflect  the  general  character  of  the  underlying  cus- 
toms, and  which  represent  latent  modifications  of  the  social 
structure  not  implying  any  sensible  modification  of  the 
instinct  of  order.  And  in  the  same  way  the  instincts  may 
vary  widely  without  producing  any  normal  change  in  the 
external  order,  though  they  may  in  some  degree  affect  the 
mode  in  which  it  works.  The  change  may  be  too  fine  to  be 
expressed  in  terms  of  external  relation. 

7.  If,  then,  the  essence  of  any  law  is  in  the  mutual  pres- 
sure of  the  different  parts  of  the  social  structure,  by  what- 
ever means  it  is  carried  out,  and  to  whatever  process  it  owes 
its  vitality,  we  have  still  to  consider  how  the  various  codes  of 
law  must  be  classified  from  our  point  of  view.  To  every  kind 
of  association,  even  the  most  ephemeral,  there  corresponds,  as 
I  have  said,  some  kind  of  custom,  and  therefore  of  law.  And 
what  has  been  said  in  the  last  chapter  will  give  a  sufficient  clue 
to  the  right  mode  of  regarding  these  various  associations  and 
the  external  processes.  If,  in  fact,  we  take  any  association  with 
a  given  end  or  function,  its  structure  and  the  laws  of  con- 
duct and  character  imposed  upon  its  members  will  be  deter- 
mined by  reference  to  that  end  and  to  the  society  of  which 
it  forms  a  part.  An  army,  for  example,  may  be  called  the 
fighting  organ  of  a  given  nation.  It  resembles  a  machine 
constructed  from  given  materials  for  a  given  end.  From 
such  data  we  could  determine  its  structure,  the  discipline 
necessary  to  its  existence,  and  thus  the  various  regulations 
by  which  the  external  relations  of  the  whole  are  defined, 
and  the  corresponding  instincts  in  the  units.  The  statement 
showing  how  men  could  be  compounded  into  a  fighting 
machine  would  show  also  how  they  could  be  most  efficiently 
combined  for  a  particular  kind  of  fighting  or  from  a  par- 
ticular kind  of  social  organisation  ;  and  the  question  of  how 
far  any  particular  army  fulfilled  these  conditions  would  be 
determined  by  the  specific  conditions  of  time  and  place. 
When  we  pass  from  the  organ  to  the  "tissue,"  the  problem 
changes.  We  still  have  an  organic  structure  with  certain 
rules  of  conduct  and  corresponding  instincts,  but  we  have  no 

K 


146  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

longer  a  definite  end  nor  a  fixed  material.  The  material, 
that  is^  is  to  he  regarded  as  developing  and  determining  the 
development  of  the  subsidiary  organs.  The  organ  is  intel- 
ligible by  its  relation  to  the  organism,  and  the  end  or  the 
function  is  assigned  by  that  relation ;  but  the  organism 
itself  is  at  once  means  and  end;  every  part  depends  upon 
every  other  part,  and  the  end  is  intelligible  only  as  the  sum 
of  all  the  correlated  instincts.  The  statement,  therefore, 
beccmes  different.  We  now  have  to  remember  that  the 
organism  develops  without  any  change  (or  any  correspond- 
ing change)  in  the  constituent  units.  It  develops  pro- 
perties, therefore,  which  are  not  essential  to  the  individual, 
for  he  can  exist  in  a  ruder  state  without  them ;  and  which, 
therefore,  imply  the  growth  of  a  social  law — that  is,  of  quali- 
ties developed  in  him  through  the  social  pressure.  And 
further,  we  see  that  some  of  these  properties  are  essential  to 
the  society.  Its  growth  is  a  process  of  developing  such  pro- 
perties ;  and,  as  we  have  seen  that  the  most  efficient  society 
is  that  which  normally  survives,  we  may  inversely  infer  from 
the  survival  of  a  society  that  it  has  developed  the  properties 
upon  which  its  efficiency  depends.  For  the  end,  as  before 
understood,  we  have  now  to  consider  the  society  as  capable 
of  maintaining  itself  in  the  general  equilibrium,  whether  by 
competition  with  weaker  societies,  or  as  supporting  itself  by 
its  direct  action  upon  the  external  world,  and  as  capable  of 
doing  so  by  virtue  of  the  social  properties  which  have  been 
developed.  We  may  regard  them,  therefore,  either  as  the 
conditions  of  the  social  vitality,  or  as  imposing  a  certain  law 
upon  its  individual  members.  In  order  that  the  society  may 
exist  or  develop  it  must  have  certain  qualities  and  customs, 
and  must  in  some  way  impress  the  corresponding  instincts 
and  habits  upon  its  members.  Hence  we  have  to  find  the 
qualities  which  are  essential  to  the  society  at  a  given  stage  of 
development,  though  not  essential  to  the  individual,  and  we 
may  then  state  them  either  as  conditions  of  the  vitality  of 
the  social  tissue,  or  as  constituting  the  law  imposed  upon  the 
individual  as  a  member  of  society,  that  is,  as  a  constituent 


THE  MORAL  LAW.  147 

part  of  that  tissue.  The  actual  law,  again,  may  not  represent 
the  greatest  degree  of  efficiency  possible  for  a  certain  stage  of 
social  growth ;  for,  as  we  have  observed,  the  qualities  may 
vary  within  certain  limits  consistently  with  the  persistence 
of  the  society,  but  they  must  be  an  approximate  statement 
of  the  essential  conditions. 


II.   The  Moral  Law. 

8.  Hence,  without  further  elaboration,  we  may  approach 
to  a  definition  of  the  moral  law.  This  much  at  least  is 
obvious:  the  morality  of  a  society  or  of  an  individual  im- 
plies at  least  a  certain  modification  of  the  most  important 
relations  and  instincts.  We  may  say  of  any  suggested 
regulation  that  it  is  too  trifling  to  have  any  moral  signifi- 
cance; we  cannot  possibly  say  that  it  is  too  important. 
Morality,  it  may  be,  is  not  interested  in  a  mere  question  of 
manners  and  fashions ;  but  rules  which  affect  the  very 
existence  of  a  society  or  a  human  being  do  not,  by  that 
circumstance,  lie  beyond  the  sphere  of  morality.  Another 
principle  closely  connected  with  this  is  equally  undeniable. 
"^  The  moral  law  is  understood  as  applying  to  all  men,  in  so 
far  as  they  have  reached  a  certain  stage  of  development,  not 
in  so  far  as  they  belong  to  any  particular  class  of  society. 
The  same  moral  law  is  applicable  to  all  adult  men  and 
women,  whether  they  are  rich  or  poor,  in  one  or  other 
profession,  or,  briefly,  belonging  to  any  category  compa- 
tible with  a  full  development  of  their  faculties.  Of  course, 
each  man  has  special  duties  corresponding  to  his  particular 
position  in  life,  and  in  some  positions  there  is  a  greater 
demand  for  certain  kinds  of  morality  than  in  others.  But 
this  means  simply  that  the  same  general  principle  is  appli- 
cable in  an  indefinite  variety  of  relations.  The  moral  law  is 
alwavs  capable  of  being  stated  in  the  form,  "All  men  must 
do  so  and  so,"  not  all  lawyers,  or  soldiers,  or  sailors  must 
do.  You  come  within  its  operation  in  so  far  as  you  have 
the  fundamental  qualities  common  to  all  members  of  the 


1 48  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

society,  not  in  so  far  as  you  have  this  or  that  particular 
contingent  quahty.  This,  then,  is  to  say  that  morality 
defines  some  of  the  most  important  qualities  of  the  social 
tissue.  It  does  not  apply  to  those  qualities  which  are 
essential  to  the  life  of  the  individual,  for  immoral  people 
clearly  exist,  and  the  law,  in  this  sense,  implies  the  pos- 
sibilitv  of  disobedience.  On  the  other  hand,  it  does  not 
apply  to  the  more  special  and  superficial  qualities  which  fit  a 
man  for  this  or  that  position  without  affecting  his  fitness  to 
be  a  member  of  society  in  some  position;  and  therefore 
we  may  assume,  from  our  previous  statement,  that  the  moral 
law  is  under  one  aspect  a  statement  of  the  conditions,  or 
of  part  of  the  conditions,  essential  to  the  vitality  of  the 
social  tissue.  It  may  be  more  than  this  in  various  ways ; 
but  it  must  be  this,  whatever  else  it  is.  The  process  by 
which  society  has  been  developed  implies  that  the  most 
important  characteristics  developed  in  the  individual  by  the 
social  pressure  correspond  to  the  conditions  of  existence  of 
the  society.  The  moral  law  defines  some  of  the  most  im- 
portant characteristics  so  developed,  and  is,  therefore,  a 
statement  of  part  of  the  qualities  in  virtue  of  which  the 
society  is  possible.  It  is  not  an  exhaustive  statement,  for 
other  qualities  may  be  essential ;  nor  an  absolutely  accu- 
rate statement,  for  societies  exist  in  which  the  morality 
varies  within  wide  limits.  But  so  far  as  it  goes  it 
must  be  an  approximate  statement  of  part  of  the  condi- 
tions.y 

9.  In  saying  this,  I  do  not  mean  either  to  assert  or  deny 
that  this  gives  the  form  in  which  the  moral  law  presents 
itself  to  the  members  of  the  society  in  which  it  inheres.  I  am 
considering  the  cause,  not  the  reason,  of  our  moral  senti- 
ments. Our  moral  judgment  must  condenm  instincts  and 
modes  of  conduct  which  are  pernicious  to  the  social  vitality, 
and  must  approve  the  opposite ;  but  it  does  not  necessarily 
follow  that  it  must  condemn  or  approve  them  because  they 
are  perceived  to  be  pernicious  or  beneficial.  The  question 
indeed  remains,  how  it  comes  to  pass  that  we  condemn  what 


THE  MORAL  LAW  AS  NATURAL.  149 

is  pernicious  if  \vc  do  not  think  it  to  be  pernicious ;  and 
this  cannot  be  fully  answered  at  the  present  stage  of  the 
argument.  Here  I  will  only  observe,  that  there  is  no 
absurdity  in  supposing  that  the  cause  of  our  likes  and  dis- 
likes may  in  some  sense  be  the  fact  that  they  are  useful  to 
us,  although  we  may  not  be  conscious  of  their  utility.  7'his, 
indeed,  must  be  to  some  extent  the  case  with  all  beings  below 
the  reasoning  stage. 


III.   The  Moral  Law  as  Natural. 

10.  The  same  principle  accounts  for  the  qualities  most 
obviously  connoted  by  the  term  "moral."  The  moral  law  is 
often  distinguished  from  other  groups  of  law  on  the  ground 
that  it  is  divine,  not  human,  natural,  not  artificial,  or  that 
it  grows  instead  of  being  made.  The  distinction  is  not  an 
ultimate  one.  Art  to  the  scientific  observer  is,  as  Shakespeare 
says,  a  part  of  nature;  everything  springs,  mediately  or  im- 
mediately, from  the  divine  power  as  here  understood,  and 
all  human  development  is  a  kind  of  growth.  The  distinction 
is  only  relevant  at  a  lower  stage  of  analysis.  We  mean  bv 
it  this  much  at  least,  that  whereas  the  law  of  the  land  is 
determined  by  the  will  of  the  legislature,  the  moral  law  is  as 
independent  of  the  legislature  as  the  movements  of  the 
planets.  King,  lords,  and  commons,  bv  going  through  certain 
forms,  may  determine  whether  theft  or  lying  shall  be  criminal; 
they  cannot  in  any  degree  decide  whether  it  shall  or  shall  not 
be  wicked.  This  seems  to  be  in  one  sense  equally  evident 
in  all  conceivable  moral  systems.  If,  with  one  set  of 
thinkers,  you  resolve  morality  into  reason,  a  law  to  alter 
morality  would  be  as  absurd  as  a  law  to  repeal  a  proposition 
in  Euclid ;  if  you  adopt  the  utilitarian  theory,  such  a  law 
would  be  as  absurd  as  a  law  to  alter  the  pleasure  derivable  from 
the  consumption  of  stimulants.  Upon  the  doctrine  here  advo- 
cated, it  would  be  as  absurd,  let  us  say,  as  a  law  to  make  in- 
toxication healthv.  The  action  of  anv  set  of  people  can  no 
more  change  the  nature  of  facts  than  of  logical  necessities. 


ISO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

11.  Bat  this  does  not  entirely  meet  the  case;  for  I  am 
here  deahng  with  moraHty  as  it  actually  exists,  not  with 
morality  as  it  ouo-ht  to  be.  So  far  as  morality  either  is  or 
necessarily  implies  a  statement  of  certain  facts,  it  is  of  course 
true  that  morality  cannot  be  made;  but  actual  morality 
corresponds  to  men's  theories  about  facts,  and  varies  in 
proportion  as  they  are  fallible.  It  may  therefore  deviate 
from  that  which  would  be  the  code  if  they  were  incapable  of 
error,  and  we  may  ask  how  it  is  possible  to  define  the  possible 
amplitude  of  their  oscillations.  .  May  not  the  code  of  rules 
by  which  our  moral  judgments  are  guided  vary  as  widely  as 
any  other  code  of  rules?  May  it  not  be  swayed  by  prejudices 
or  altered  by  respect  for  some  constituted  authority  ?  Though 
a  legislative  enactment  could  not  make  murder  rio-ht,  mio-ht 
it  not  as  a  fact  determine  the  sentiment  about  murder  ?  This 
is  necessarily  a  question  of  fact  to  be  settled  by  historical 
inquiry,  but  the  principles  laid  down  may  suggest  some  limit 
to  the  possible  oscillations. 

12.  It  is  plain,  in  fact,  that  though  morality  varies,  it  must 
vary  within  incomparably  narrower  limits  than  other  systems 
of  law,  because  its  variation  is  determined  by  far  more  general 
conditions.  It  is  the  variation  of  the  most  intimate  struc- 
ture and  the  deepest  instincts,  not  of  the  superficial  senti- 
ments or  of  the  special  modifications  of  society.  In  the 
earliest  stages  of  growth,  when  certain  rigid  customs  represent 
the  germs  both  of  moral  and  other  codes,  the  custom  develops 
in  all  cases  by  a  slow  growth  rather  than  by  constant  modi- 
fication; and  even  in  the  most  civilised  periods  a  similar 
process  may  take  place  in  regard  to  certain  rules  as  modified 
imperceptibly  by  judicial  interpretation.  But  as  the  difference 
becomes  more  palpable,  the  moral  law  alone  retains  the 
characteristics  of  divine,  indefeasible,  and  so  forth.  The 
diflerence  then  appears  between  the  organic  laws  of  the 
tissue  and  the  special  laws  of  any  particular  organisation. 
One  class  of  laws  maintains  itself  by  the  direct  action  of  the 
organic  instincts;  others  by  the  application  of  these  instincts 
to  special  circumstances,  or  by  respect  for  the  authority  which 


THE  MORAL  LAW  AS  NATURAL.  151 

developed  by  such  application.  In  a  given  case  the  two 
kinds  of  motive  may  be  inextricably  blended.  I  may  obey  a 
given  law  either  because  of  the  authority  which  enforces  it  or 
on  its  own  account.  I  may  keep  a  promise  because  I  think 
it  right,  or  because  I  am  afraid  of  the  penalties  imposed  upon 
a  breach  of  contract,  and  in  the  latter  case  I  keep  it  for  the 
same  reasons  which  would  induce  me  to  wear  a  prescribed 
costume.  But  the  instincts  which  induce  me  to  act  morally 
are  co-ordinate  with  those  which  induce  me  to  obev  authority, 
and  can  only  be  altered  by  a  radical  alteration  of  my  whole 
character.  The  others  are  derivative,  and  may  therefore  vary 
as  the  particular  action  of  the  authority  varies.  And  thus 
we  mav  assume  that  the  organic  variations  belong  to  an 
entirely  different  order,  and  are  relatively  strong  compared 
with  those  of  the  secondary  or  derivative  instincts. 

33.  This  applies  to  the  case  in  which  we  may  regard 
even  a  moral  law  as  beincr  in  some  dcQ-ree  made  by  a  process 
not  unlike  that  of  actual  legislation.  Such  a  case  is,  in 
fact,  more  or  less  illustrated  by  every  great  moral  teacher. 
If  the  Gospels  revealed  a  new  system  of  morality,  their  pro- 
mulgation may  be  regarded  as  a  case  of  moral  legislation. 
It  would  be  admitted,  indeed,  by  every  believer,  that  for  such 
a  case  nothing  less  is  needed  than  a  divine  interposition  ;  the 
direct  intervention  of  a  power  which  can  modify  the  organic 
as  easily  as  the  secondary  instincts.  But  the  question,  so  far 
as  it  comes  within  the  sphere  of  scientific  inquiry,  is  simply 
one  of  facts — how  far,  namely,  the  promulgation  of  a  new 
moral  principle  can  alter  the  accepted  moral  code?  If  we 
could  conceive  of  the  moral  chano-e  wrouo"ht  by  Christianity 
as  a  case  of  obedience  to  a  power  revealed  by  miracles,  the 
immediate  change  would  not  be  so  much  a  change  of  morality 
as  a  change  in  the  sanctions  of  morality.  It  would  be  re- 
vealed  to  men  that  certain  kinds  of  conduct  had  consequences 
of  which  they  were  not  previously  aware.  Such  a  change 
might,  no  doubt,  affect  indirectly  their  whole  moral  character. 
But  it  is  needless  to  discuss  such  a  theory,  except  to  take  note 
of  the  virtual  assertion  that  nothing  short  of  supernatural 


152  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

interference  could  bring  about  such  a  result.  So  long  as  we 
remain  within  the  limits  of  scientific  inquiry,  we  must  admit 
that  the  influence  of  the  greatest  moral  teacher  depends, 
not  upon  his  authority,  but  upon  the  congeniality  of  his 
teaching  to  the  sentiments  by  which  the  social  medium  is 
already  permeated.  He  succeeds  in  so  far  as  his  teaching  is 
in  harmony  with  the  prevailing  instincts.  He  could  not 
teach  if  he  were  not  in  advance  of  his  fellows,  nor  find  a 
hearing;  unless  he  were  ffivino-  articulate  shape  to  thoughts 

O  DO  I  O 

obscurely  present  to  countless  multitudes.  Like  Socrates,  he 
must  be  something  of  a  "midwife;"  he  facilitates  the  birth 
of  the  new  ideas  with  which  the  world  is  already  in  travail, 
and  is  reallv  the  interpreter  and  the  mouthpiece  of  thought 
seeking  for  utterance,  and  representing  a  slow  process  of 
elaboration.  The  poet  and  the  philosopher,  and  the  religious 
teacher  no  less  than  these,  depend  for  their  power  upon  this 
unconscious  co-operation ;  and  the  more  men  study  the  history 
of  the  world,  the  more  importance  thev  come  to  attach  to 
this  occult  process  of  dumb  preparation. 

14.  When  we  sav,  then,  that  morality  grows  and  is  not 
made,  we  really  point  to  this  fact,  that  it  is  the  fruit  of  a 
gradual  evolution  of  the  orjzanic  instinct  continued  through 
many  generations.  Each  individual  imbibes  the  moral  senti- 
ments as  he  grows  up  and  regards  them  as  primitive  because  he 
has  accepted  them  without  conscious  reflection.  To  alter  the 
code  thus  elaborated  is  to  alter  the  most  deeply  rooted  modes 
of  thought  and  feeling,  which  are  imbedded  in  the  whole 
scheme  of  life,  and  accepted  bv  the  race  as  its  theory  of  the 
external  world.  The  reformer  must  start  with  these  senti- 
ments ingrained  in  his  character,  and  must  sympathise  with  his 
fellows  before  he  can  influence  them.  New  discoveries  about 
the  external  world,  new  wants  due  to  the  growth  of  society, 
the  gradual  accumulation  of  natural  and  intellectual  wealth, 
may  necessitate  some  modification  of  the  organic  instincts,  but 
such  changes  must  always  be  slow,  and  involve  many  blind 
gropings  after  a  solution  before  any  tolerable  equilibrium  can 
be   reached.      At  each   particular  stage  of  the  process,  the 


THE  MORAL  LAW  AS  NATURAL.  153 

ordinary  mind  resists  any  change  in  the  principles  instilled 
into  it  from  birth,  and  is  only  induced  to  revolt  by  some  very 
sensible  evil.  To  alter  a  speculative  opinion  is  hard  enough 
v^'hen  its  alteration  involves  any  deeply  seated  change  in  our 
system  of  thousrht,  but  it  is  far  harder  to  alter  the  opinions 
which  have  a  direct  bearing  upon  our  conduct,  and  still  more 
to  modify  profound  prejudices  in  the  sluggish  minds  of  the 
e:reat  mass  of  mankind  ;  and  therefore  even  in  the  case  where 
the  supposed  change  involves  a  real  improvement  in  the  social 
adjustment,  and  has  all  the  advantages,  direct  and  indirect, 
resulting  from  that  fact,  it  implies  modifications  so  far-reaching 
in  their  character,  and  requiring  the  tacit  co-operation  of  so 
many  minds,  that  it  must  resemble  one  of  the  slow  natural 
processes  rather  than  the  sudden  change  which  may  be 
wrought  by  a  single  discovery  in  a  particular  department  of 
thouQ;ht,  or  the  change  produced  in  comparatively  superficial 
arrano-ement  by  a  leeislative  action. 

15.  From  this  observation,  too  familiar  to  require  further 
exposition,  we  may  pass  to  the  cognate  attribute  of  the  moral 
law,  its  eternity  and  immutability.  From  our  point  of  view, 
these  phrases  must  be  understood  in  a  sense  compatible  with 
the  admission  of  evolution.  The  actual  moral  law  develops, 
and  therefore  changes,  whatever  may  be  said  of  the  ideal  law. 
We  must  recrard  the  moral  instincts  as  dependent  upon 
human  nature  or  human  society,  and  therefore  liable  to 
vary  in  so  far  as  their  subject  is  liable  to  vary.  When 
the  older  school  of  metaphysicians  speak  of  the  immutability 
of  the  law,  they  may  either  mean  that  the  law  will  always  be 
the  same  under  the  same  conditions,  which  is  no  doubt  true, 
but  gives  us  no  real  information ;  or  that  it  would  be  in 
some  sense  the  same  even  if  the  conditions  of  human  life 
were  radically  altered,  which  is  either  false  or  refers  to  a 
transcendental  region  of  real  existences  altogether  separate 
from  the  phenomenal  world,  and  therefore  has  no  intelli- 
gible bearing  upon  scientific  theories.  We  cannot  mean  by 
eternity  or  immutability  that  the  moral  law  will  remain 
unaltered   even   if  the    conditions    upon   which    it  depends 


154  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

be  altered;   but  only  that  these  are  the  most  fundamental 
conditions  assignable,   the   permanent    conditions    of   social 
vitality,  which  remain  constant  through  an  indefinite  series 
of  more   superficial   changes  in  the  social  organisation.     If 
we  assume  that  these   conditions  may  be  entirely  different 
in  some  different  world,  the  morality  in  that  world  would 
presumably  be   also   different.       If   in    some   distant   planet 
Ivino-  were  as   essential   to    human   welfare    as   truthfulness 
is  in  this  world,  falsehood  might  there  be  a  cardinal  virtue. 
The  possibility  of  such  a  state  of  things  may  be  denied  by 
those,  at  least,  who  profess  omniscience ;  but  if  you  admit  the 
possibility  of  such  a  change,  you  must  admit  also  the  possi- 
bility of  the  correlative  change  in  the  morality.    The  morality 
then  is  as  permanent  as  the  conditions  of  existence,  though 
there  may  be  a  dispute  as  to  the  permanence  of  those  condi- 
tions.    A  being  radically  different  from  man  would  no  doubt 
have  a  different  code  of  behaviour.     The  degree  of  constancy 
which  we  attribute  to  the  moral  code  will  appear  more  plainly 
when  we   come   to   a  more  direct  deduction  of  the  specific 
virtues.     At  present,  we  may  say  that  any  change  must  be 
relatively   small   in    proportion    to    the    permanence   of  the 
deepest  organic  instincts  as  compared  with  their  modification 
under  particular  conditions.     But  we  may  also  go  one  step 
further.     The  variation,  we  may  say,  whatever  it  is,  must 
correspond  to  a  process  of  evolution,  not  to  what  could  be 
called  arbitrary  modification.     If  one  form  of  living  being  is 
evolved  from  another,  there  must  be  a  certain  community 
of  plan.      Though  the  two  may  differ,  certain  fundamental 
properties  are  exemplified  in  both.     Similarly,  when  a  code 
of  law  is  developed  from  a  simpler  code,  the  latter,  though 
richer  in  content  and  more  varied  in  application,  must  contain 
certain  first  principles  already  given  in  the  first,  and  extend 
them  by  generalising  instead  of  repealing  them.     There  is  a 
continuity  though  not  an  identity  of  sentiment.     The  type 
of  character  which  is  approved  at  one  stage  must  be  always 
on  the  line  towards  the  type  approved  at  a  more  advanced 
stao-e.     And  therefore,  although  we  may  raise  our  standard, 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  135 

and  consider  the  good  man  of  one  period  as  an  average,  or 
less  than  an  average  man  in  a  higher  period,  we  may  always 
so  far  approve  of  the  standard  which  we  have  left  behind  as 
to  consider  that  its  relative  judgments  were  always  correct. 
The  qualities  approved  may  have  been  in  everything  better 
than  the  qualities  disapproved,  though  the  highest  qualities 
conceivable  were  not  equal  to  those  now  demanded.  But  a 
clearer  view  of  the  principle  follows  from  another  characteristic 
of  morality,  which  appears  from  a  historical  point  of  view 
to  be  of  primary  importance. 


IV.  Morality  as  Internal. 

16.  The  clear  enunciation  of  one  principle  seems  to  be  a 
characteristic  of  all  the  great  moral  revolutions.  The  recogni- 
tion amounts  almost  to  a  discovery,  and  would  seem  to  mark 
the  point  at  which  the  moral  code  first  becomes  distinctly 
separated  from  other  codes.  It  may  be  briefly  expressed  in 
the  phrase  that  morality  is  internal.  The  moral  law,  we  may 
sav,  has  to  be  expressed  in  the  form,  "  be  this,"  not  in  the 
form,  "  do  this."  The  possibility  of  expressing  any  rule  in 
this  form  may  be  regarded  as  deciding  whether  it  can  or 
cannot  have  a  distinctively  moral  character.  Christianity 
gave  prominence  to  the  doctrine  that  the  true  moral  law 
says  "  hate  not,"  instead  of  "  kill  not."  The  men  of  old 
time  had  forbidden  adultery ;  the  new  moral  legislator 
forbade  lust ;  and  his  greatness  as  a  moral  teacher  was 
manifested  in  nothinsi;  more  than  in  the  clearness  with  which 
he  gave  utterance  to  this  doctrine.  It  would  be  easy  to  show 
how  profoundly  the  same  doctrine,  in  various  forms,  has  been 
bound  up  with  other  moral  and  religious  reformations  in 
many  ages  of  the  world. 

17.  What,  then,  is  implied  in  the  change?  Conduct  may 
be  regarded  as  a  function  of  character  and  circumstance.  An 
adjustment  of  internal  to  external  relations  is,  it  is  said,  the 
very  definition  of  life.  It  follows,  hence,  that  every  law  as  to 
conduct  carries  with  it  a  rule  as  to  character,  and  vice  versa. 


156  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Reofulate  a  man's  feelings  or  his  actions,  and  you  necessarily 
affect  his  actions  or  his  feelincrs.  Induce  a  man  not  to  hate 
his  brother,  and  he  will  be  slow  to  kill  him;  and  if  you 
persuade  him  not  to  kill,  vou  necessarily  limit  to  some  degree 
the  force  of  his  hatred.  As  it  is  easier  for  the  primitive  mind 
to  accept  the  objective  than  the  subjective  definition  of  con- 
duct, the  primitive  rule  takes  the  corresponding  form,  and 
only  prescribes  qualities  of  character  indirectly  by  prescribing 
methods  of  conduct. 

18.  Where,  then,  is  the  importance  of  making  the  distinc- 
tion ?  If  to  every  mode  of  feeling  there  corresponded  a 
definite  mode  of  conduct,  the  two  rules  would  imply  each 
other.  It  is  possible  to  suggest  certain  cases  in  which  this 
would  be  approximately  true.  It  seems,  at  least,  to  hold  true 
of  the  appetites  as  distinguished  from  the  intellectual  emo- 
tions ;  for  while  every  appetite  has  a  definite  physical  organ 
to  correspond  to  it,  the  mode  of  feeling  and  the  mode  of 
acting  are  mutually  implied.  To  regulate  thirst  is  to  regulate 
drinkino-;  but  this  fails  to  hold  crood  so  soon  as  we  deal  with 
the  emotions  which  do  not  discharge  themselves  by  a  fixed 
or  narrow  channel.  If  I  try  to  define  any  mode  of  action 
solelv  by  its  objective  characteristics,  that  is,  solely  by  .those 
qualities  through  the  perception  of  which  I  recognise  the 
existence  of  a  world  external  to  myself,  I  find  that  the  coin- 
cidence cannot  be  maintained.  Any  action  so  defined  may 
be  due  to  the  most  varvino;  motives,  and  the  same  motive 
prompt  the  most  various  actions.  Killing  generally  implies 
hatred,  but  in  certain  cases  I  may  kill  from  a  sense  of  duty, 
from  a  desire  of  monev,  or  even  from  love  of  the  person 
killed;  when  I  wish,  for  example,  to  "put  him  out  of  his 
misery."  Therefore,  though  the  prohibition  of  killing  gene- 
rally forbids  the  same  acts  as  are  forbidden  by  a  prohibition 
of  hatred,  the  two  prohibitions  will  diverge  in  an  indefinite 
number  of  cases.  If  I  wish  to  forbid  all  the  actions  which 
spring  out  of  hatred,  the  definition  by  the  internal  character- 
istic is  simple  and  exhaustive,  whereas  the  other  kind  of  de- 
finition must  be   indefinitely  complex,  and  must  always  be 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  JS7 

more  or  less  defective.  I  may  modify  the  prohibition  of  kill- 
ing by  permitting  it  in  particular  cases,  as,  for  example,  in 
war;  and  again  by  adding  a  number  of  subsidiary  prohibi- 
tions, forbidding  other  means  of  gratifying  hatred,  such  as 
mere  insult  or  the  production  of  conditions  indirectly  un- 
favourable to  life.  But,  after  all,  it  would  of  course  be 
idle  to  attempt  to  sum  up  all  the  indefinite  variety  of  ways 
by  which  one  man  can  inflict  pain  upon  his  neighbours. 
The  difference  between  the  two  methods  is  like  the  difference 
between  marking  a  circle  by  the  revolution  of  a  fixed  line 
round  a  given  centre  and  trying  to  make  an  approximate  circle 
by  causing  a  number  of  other  figures  drawn  from  external 
points  to  intersect  in  such  a  way  as  more  or  less  to  indicate 
the  circumference  of  the  circle.  If,  in  short,  I  wish  to  forbid 
all  conduct  which  is  the  fruit  of  a  certain  disposition,  I  shall 
do  so  at  once  by  forbidding  that  disposition ;  and,  in  that 
case,  the  rule  of  conduct  will  tend  to  become  simpler  as  I 
briny;  new  classes  of  action  under  this  oreneral  rule.  IL  on 
the  other  hand,  I  proceed  by  the  opposite  method,  and  try  to 
give  the  external  characteristics  of  the  same  conduct,  my  rule 
will  become  constantly  more  complex  as  I  endeavour  to  make 
it  applicable  to  the  indefinite  variety  of  possible  cases. 

19.  Now  every  conceivable  rule  of  conduct  must  be  a  rule 
of  character.  Since  action  is  (upon  my  assumption)  alwavs 
determined  by  pain  or  pleasure,  a  uniform  rule  implies  uniform 
feelino-  in  regard  to  the  conduct  prescribed.  Rules  of  action 
imply  a  classification  of  things  in  general  according  to  their 
relation  to  the  feelinirs  of  the  assent,  and  thus  the  formation 
of  primary  rules  corresponding  to  his  primitive  sensibilities 
and  harmonised  by  the  unity  of  the  organisation  constituted 
by  those  sensibilities.  These  primary  rules  must  be  capable 
of  statement  as  rules  of  character,  and  for  this  reason,  as  we 
have  just  seen,  cannot  be  adequately  stated  as  rules  of  external 
conduct;  for  a  man,  considered  as  an  agent,  must  be  re- 
garded as  simply  an  organised  group  of  feelings.  The  calculus 
of  motive  cannot  include  anv  other  data  besides  the  feelings. 
The  universe  only  comes  into  consideration  in  fixins;  certain 


158  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

internal  conditions  of  feeling,  whilst  the  character  is  the  ex- 
pression of  the  internal  conditions.  Now,  in  anv  given  case, 
the  conduct  will  of  course  depend  upon  the  special  stimulus 
which  comes  from  without  as  well  as  upon  the  character. 
To  know  how  the  character  acts,  we  must  know  what  in- 
fluences are  operative;  we  must  understand  the  instrument, 
and  we  must  also  know  what  are  the  movements  of  the 
external  player.  But  to  obtain  the  general  rule  we  abstract 
from  all  those  particular  accidents,  and  consider  only  what  is 
essential.  We  want  to  know  what  are  the  conditions  imposed 
by  the  structure  of  the  instrument  itself,  whatever  conditions 
may  be  imposed  from  without.  But  this  is  to  take  into 
account  only  those  external  circumstances  which  are  constant, 
and  whose  existence  is  assumed  when  we  assume  the  exist- 
ence of  the  agent.  The  organism  implies  the  environment  as 
a  persistent  and  universal  condition,  to  which  therefore  no 
explicit  reference  need  be  made.  If  breathino-  is  necessary  to 
life,  air  must  be  necessary  ;  but  I  can  define  the  laws  of  breath- 
ing, its  relation  to  other  functions,  and  its  place  in  the  whole 
organic  equilibrium,  without  making  any  further  reference  to 
this  implied  condition.  So  a  psychologist  might  regard  a  man 
as  a  compound  of  certain  primitive  emotions,  and  give  their 
relations  as  constituting  his  character  without  any  reference 
to  the  external  conditions  which  are  necessary  to  the  exist- 
ence of  such  a  being.  The  general  rules  so  given  would  be 
implied  in  every  particular  action  and  their  mode  of  operation, 
and  each  case  would  depend  upon  the  special  stimulus  applied  ; 
but  the  rules  would  not  themselves  include  any  datum  of 
external  fact.  In  the  special  cases  where  a  given  mode  of 
feeling  has  a  fixed  external  correlative,  the  two  modes  of  stat- 
ing the  rule  would  be  interchangeable;  but  as  in  the  general 
case  no  such  equivalent  presents  itself,  we  must  necessarilv 
state  the  rule  in  the  direct  and  only  possible  form,  namely, 
as  a  rule  of  character.  And  since  morality  is,  as  we  have 
said,  concerned  with  these  general  rules,  the  onlv  mode  of 
stating  the  moral  law  must  be  as  a  rule  of  character. 

20.  The  point  niav  be  made  clearer  by  takino;  Into  account 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  159 

another  consideration.  If  we  consider  any  given  class  of  ac- 
tions, we  may  sav  that  the  intrinsic  motive,  instinct,  or  mode  of 
feeling  is  that  which  being  given,  the  action  follows,  or  which, 
if  the  action  takes  place,  must  be  present.  Hunger  we  may 
say  (without  taking  note  of  possible  exceptions)  implies  eating 
under  certain  circumstances,  and  vice  versd  the  consumption 
of  food  under  these  circumstances  implies  hunger.  And,  again, 
there  will  be  a  true  intrinsic  motive  if  certain  conditions 
always  produce  a  given  desire,  even  when  other  conditions 
may  prevent  the  desire  from  leading  to  action.  That  is  the 
case  if  hunger  is  always  produced  by  certain  conditions, 
alth  ough  other  considerations,  e.g.,  the  fear  of  poison,  may  pre- 
vent eatin  2:.  For  a  volition  we  then  have  only  a  velleitv.  There 
is,  on  the  other  hand,  an  extrinsic  motive  when  the  conduct  is 
desired  solely  with  a  view  to  some  further  result,  which  may 
or  may  not  be  present,  and  is  therefore  not  desired  when  that 
result  is  not  anticipated.  In  such  a  case  the  motive  is  not 
only  overcome,  but  entirely  suppressed  by  a  change  of  circum- 
stances, and  the  apparent  end  turns  out  to  have  been  only 
desirable  as  a  means  to  some  further  end. 

21.  Assuming  this,  we  may  say  that  there  are  many  classes 
of  conduct  to  which  there  is  no  possible  intrinsic  motive. 
This  is  true  of  all  classes  of  conduct  which  can  be  defined  in 
purely  objective  terms;  for  I  must  understand  by  such  terms, 
terms  which  have  no  direct  singificance  for  the  feelings  what- 
ever,  or,  in  other  words,  which  refer  solely  to  the  mathematical 
relations  of  the  object.  I  have  no  intrinsic  motive  for  going 
east  rather  than  west,  up  rather  than  down,  or  round  two 
sides  of  a  triangle  rather  than  along  the  third.  The  physio- 
logist considers  all  phenomena  from  this  point  of  view  and 
classifies  them  entirely  by  reference  to  changes  in  time  and 
place.  But  when  we  are  speaking  of  conduct,  it  is  plain  that 
the  rules  so  obtained  are  only  interesting  in  so  far  as  they  can 
be  used  by  our  feelings.  They  enable  us  to  calculate  what 
will  be  the  consequences  of  conduct,  and  reveal  their  whole 
significance  when  we  apply  them  to  calculate  such  conse- 
quences.    The  knowledge  that  one  side  of  a  triangle  is  less 


i6o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

than  the  two  others  has  no  interest  in  itself,  but  as  soon  as  I 
am  in  a  hurry  to  reach  a  given  point,  or  wish  to  avoid  reach- 
ing it  too  soon_,  it  of  course  determines  the  mode  in  which  my 
feelings  will  prompt  my  conduct. 

22.  In  the  general  case,  however,  the  statement  will  be 
different.  A  given  class  of  actions  will  be  pleasant  or  painful, 
and  may  therefore  sugirest  a  rule  of  conduct  of  one  kind  or 
other.  Now,  generally  speaking,  we  may  say  of  a  certain 
class  of  conduct  partly  defined  by  external  considerations, 
that  it  must  correspond  more  or  less  closely  to  some  intrinsic 
motive.  It  may  be  such  that  one  kind  of  conduct  alone  will 
be  desirable  on  the  assumption  that  the  agent  is  accessible 
to  certain  motives.  That  is,  if  we  have  a  certain  character, 
we  shall  act  in  the  way  supposed.  But  it  will  also  generally 
be  true  that  the  same  conduct  may  be  prompted  by  other 
motives;  so  that  we  cannot  certainly  infer  the  motive  from 
the  conduct.  And  besides  this,  it  will  generally  be  true  that 
the  desirability  of  the  conduct  depends  to  some  extent  upon 
circumstances  not  expressed  in  the  rule.  So  that  some  kinds 
of  conduct,  although  falling  within  the  class  definition,  do 
not  present  themselves  as  desirable.  That  is  to  say,  it  has  no 
intrinsic  motive  precisely  corresponding  to  it.  So,  to  repeat 
the  former  illustration,  certain  actions  are  Q:enerallv  the 
result  of  kindness.  So  long  as  I  am  kindly  I  shall  not  kill ; 
but  the  abstinence  from  killing  may  be  the  result  of  many 
other  motives,  such  as  fear  of  the  gallows ;  and  in  some  rare 
cases  kindliness  might  even  prompt  to  killing.  To  say 
this  is  only  to  repeat  the  previous  statement  of  the  impossi- 
bility of  making  the  external  and  internal  codes  precisely 
coincident. 

23.  We  may  ask,  then,  how  any  external  rule  of  conduct 
is  possible;  for  if  all  conduct  is  conditioned  bv  feeling,  and 
uniform  conduct  implies  uniform  feeling,  whilst  external 
uniformity  could  only  be  secured  in  practice  by  internal 
variation,  and  vice  versa,  it  would  seem  that  no  external  rule 
can  express  a  real  rule  of  conduct.  In  one  sense  this  seems 
to  be  rigidly  true,     'iliat  is,  there  is  no  rule  which  a  human 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  i6i 

being  will  obey  under  all  circumstances  in  spite  of  all  conceiv- 
able conflicting  motives.  This  is  simply  an  admission  that 
the  strength  of  the  will  is  finite.  It  merely  asserts  that  other 
motives  may  override  those  implied  in  the  observance  of  the 
rule ;  the  rule  may  still  be  an  operative  force,  though  not  the 
sole  or  dominant  force.  But  the  question  is  how  any  rule 
of  the  external  kind  can  express  even  a  uniform  desire,  and 
if  not,  whence  it  can  derive  any  permanent  influence?  To 
this  we  may  say,  that,  in  the  first  place,  the  observance  of 
such  a  rule  may  become  a  habit.  The  essence  of  a  habit  is, 
as  we  have  seen,  that  I  act  in  a  certain  way  in  obedience  to 
certain  signals,  without  calling  up  all  the  feelings  implied. 
If  I  am  in  the  habit  of  getting  up  to  breakfast  when  a  bell 
rings,  I  may  get  up  when  a  bell  rings  which  I  know  to  be 
the  indication ;  but  I  must  suppose  that  in  this  case  the 
knowledge  is  more  or  less  of  the  potential  kind;  that  is,  that 
I  mio-ht  know  if  I  reflected  or  brouo-ht  into  vivid  conscious- 
ness  all  the  thoughts  connected  with  the  given  symbol.  And, 
in  the  second  place,  the  observance,  and  still  more  frequently 
the  breach  of  a  rule,  may  be  due  simply  to  the  fact  that  I  am 
an  unreasonable  and  inconsistent  being.  This  means  virtually, 
as  we  have  already  seen,  that  I  may  have  a  different  character 
at  different  times,  and  perhaps  allow  a  set  of  feelings  which, 
on  other  occasions,  are  relatively  superficial,  to  overpower 
feelings  which  are  at  other  times  the  most  powerful.  I  have, 
however,  spoken  sufficiently  of  this,  which  In  fact  is  part  of 
the  general  problem  as  to  the  reasonableness  of  action.  So  far 
as  I  become  reasonable  this  kind  of  irregularity  will  disappear, 
and  I  shall  be  governed  in  the  same  cases  by  the  same 
motives,  and  cease  to  apply  rules  in  cases  where  they  are  not 
applicable. 

24.  Let  us  suppose,  then,  that  I  act  reasonably  in  the  sense 
that,  as  I  always  judge  by  the  same  principles  or  am  actuated 
by  the  same  set  of  feelincrs  brouQ-ht  into  harmony  and  sub- 
ordination,  and  therefore  that  a  uniform  rule  does  in  fact 
correspond  to  a  uniform  mode  of  feeling,  then  I  may  accept 
the  rule  as  affording  a  sufficient  presumption  under  ordinary 

L 


1 62  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

circumstances.  It  serves  as  an  indication  that  the  facts  are 
such  as  would  determine  me  to  act  in  a  given  way.  So, 
for  example,  my  objection  to  killing  may  be  founded  upon  a 
dislike  to  giving  pain.  That  is  the  intrinsic  motive  of  a  class 
of  actions  which  cannot  be  defined  by  any  absolutely  coin- 
cident, external,  correlative.  Still  it  gives  me  a  strong  pre- 
sumption against  killing,  because  in  almost  all  cases  killing 
gives  pain.  If  I  see  a  man,  therefore,  and  know  nothing 
about  him  beyond  the  fact  that  he  is  a  man,  I  shall  refrain 
from  killing  him.  I  shall  again  refrain  unless  the  presump- 
tion is  rebutted  by  evidence  that  killing  will  diminish  pain ; 
and  in  that  case,  I  shall  kill  if,  in  fact,  the  dislike  to  giving 
pain  is  the  intrinsic  and  sole  applicable  motive  of  my  conduct 
in  relation  to  my  neighbours.  On  this  supposition  the  general 
rule  is  a  conditional  one,  although  the  conditions  may  not  be 
distinctly  formulated. 

25.  Again,  the  rule  may  be  accepted  from  an  extrinsic 
motive  ;  that  is  to  say,  from  a  motive  not  implied  in  the 
definition  of  the  class  of  conduct  commanded  or  prohibited. 
This,  of  course,  is  the  case  wherever  the  rule  is  accepted,  not 
for  itself,  but  from  regard  to  the  authority  by  which  it  is 
imposed.  In  this  case  I  do  not  object  to  killing,  but  to  some 
consequence  not  necessarily  or  invariably  connected  with  it. 
I  may  object  to  kill  because  killing  leads  to  the  gallows  or 
because  it  leads  to  damnation.  Were  I  certain  to  escape  the 
hangman  and  to  obtain  spiritual  absolution,  I  might  still 
be  ready  to  kill.  This,  of  course,  is  a  highly  important  case 
in  practice.  The  legislator  is  forced  to  classify  conduct  by 
its  objective  manifestations.  He,  therefore,  is  necessarily 
limited  by  the  considerations  already  suggested.  He  can- 
not forbid  all  the  possible  manifestations  of  a  passion  such 
as  hatred,  but  only  those  which  produce  certain  tangible 
and  visible  consequences.  However  elaborate  his  code,  there 
will  still  be  iimumerable  devices  by  which  a  man  whose 
character  prompts  him  to  take  the  forbidden  courses  can 
gratify  his  passions  by  indirect  methods.  And  where  the 
moralist  and  the  religious  teacher  is  misled  by  the  analogy, 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  163 

and  instead  of  forbidding  the  passion  tries  to  classify  all  the 
modes  of  conduct  to  which  it  may  lead,  he  gets  into  the  same 
difficulty.  lie  permits  what  he  does  not  prohibit,  and  is 
therefore  in  danger  of  producing  hypocrisy  instead  of  virtue, 
and  stopping  a  few  holes  in  a  sieve  instead  of  stopping  the 
stream  at  its  source.  And  here  we  have  the  secret  of  the 
immense  importance  attributed  by  all  the  higher  moralists 
to  the  other  mode  of  statement. 

26.  Hence  we  may  define  the  spheres  to  which  rules,  which 
have  or  have  not  an  external  reference,  are  necessarily  limited. 
So  long  as  any  external  element  is  present  in  the  formula,  it 
must  be  a  formula  of  the  organ,  not  of  the  organism,  appli- 
cable under  particular  conditions  or  circumstances,  and  not 
belonging  to  the  man  simply  in  respect  of  his  intrinsic 
motives.  For  if  the  respect  for  the  law  is  really  a  case  of 
respect  for  the  imposing  authority,  that  authority  is  itself  a 
product  of  the  primary  instincts  acting  under  special  con- 
ditions, and  determined  by  them  and  by  the  properties  of  the 
''tissue"  of  which  it  is  a  modification.  Therefore  a  rule 
of  conduct  which  tacitly  or  implicitly  depends  upon  some 
principle  of  authority  must  by  its  nature  define,  not  a  property 
of  the  tissue,  but  of  some  special  product,  determined  by  exter- 
nal circumstances  and  variable  from  time  to  time.  And  if 
we  take  the  case  of  any  rule  which  does  not  coincide  through- 
out as  to  the  motive  and  the  conduct,  it  can  only  give  a 
conditional  rule  of  conduct,  the  condition  being  not  the 
general  conditions  implied  in  the  existence  of  the  agent,  but 
in  some  special  set  of  facts  which  may  vary  whilst  those  con- 
ditions are  fixed.  In  either  case,  the  rule  virtually  implies 
acting  by  some  criterion  according  to  which  we  classify  the 
particular  case  before  us.  To  have  some  such  criterion  is  of 
course  an  essential  in  all  conduct,  since  conduct  of  every 
kind  involves  some  set  of  external  events.  Now,  if  the 
criterion  shows  that  the  case  belongs  to  a  class  of  events 
corresponding  to  a  certain  kind  of  feeling,  there  are  always 
points  at  which  it  fails  us.  If  through  hai)it  or  inattention 
we  continue  to  observe  it,  we  act  inconsistently;  if  we  are 


1 64  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

fully  consciovis  of  what  we  are  doing  and  are  guided  by 
uniform  principles^  we  shall  not  observe  it.  Therefore  the 
rule^  properly  stated^  does  not  give  a  law  of  the  character, 
but  only  of  the  character  as  affected  by  certain  special  and 
variable  circumstances.  If,  again,  the  criterion  marks  the 
case  as  belonging  to  a  class  of  actions  forbidden  by  a  certain 
authority,  we  do  not  ask  whether  the  classification  itself 
depends  upon  any  intelligible  principle  or  implies  anything 
beyond  a  classification  by  external  characteristics.  We 
are  consistent  in  obeying  the  law,  whatever  it  prescribes, 
even  though  the  classification  assumed  by  the  law  be  from 
other  points  of  view  inconsistent.  In  this  case,  therefore, 
the  true  rule  is  in  the  form:  Do  as  you  are  bid  by  somebody. 
And  as  here,  again,  the  instinct  of  obedience  to  any  authority 
whatever  is  necessarily  dependent  upon  the  particular  cir- 
cumstances under  which  the  authority  has  grown  up,  and  is 
a  deduction  from  the  primary  instincts  in  a  particular  appli- 
cation, not  the  principle  from  which  they  can  be  deduced, 
we  still  have  a  rule  of  character  as  affected  by  special  con- 
ditions, not  a  rule  which  corresponds  to  the  organic  relations 
of  character.  Hence  any  external  law  whatever  fails  to  give  a 
law  of  character  simply  ;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  the  organic 
law  must  also  transcend  all  these  special  applications,  however 
general  some  of  them  may  be.  The  moral  law  as  a  law  of  social 
*' tissue/'  or  as  a  law  concerned  only  with  the  development  of 
character  by  the  intrinsic  properties  of  the  social  organism  in 
presence  of  fixed  external  conditions,  can  only  be  adequately 
expressed  in  terms  which  have  no  external  reference. 

27.  The  process,  then,  by  which  the  moral  law  (or  rather 
the  law  of  conduct  of  men  considered  simply  as  constituting 
the  social  tissue,  for  this  law  includes  but  is  not  coincident 
with  the  moral  law)  is  developed,  is  a  process  of  generalisa- 
tion. It  corresponds  to  a  vast  induction  carried  on  by  the 
race  as  organised  in  society.  It  is  a  gradual  disengagement 
of  certain  primary  instincts,  and  a  distinct  perception  of  their 
value  and  mutual  relations  from  the  perplexing  complexity 
of  their  particular  manifestations — a  process  which  is  more 


MORALITY  AS  INTERNAL.  165 

complex  because  it  involves  a  modification  of  the  emotions 
and  of  the  whole  character^  as  well  as  a  simple  intellectual 
process.  Certain  modes  of  conduct  are  seen  to  be  bad,  that 
is,  they  are  disliked  for  some  reason  or  other  by  the  persons 
concerned.  Society  tries  to  put  them  down  as  it  tries  to 
extirpate  dangerous  animals.  It  develops  in  proportion  to 
its  success  in  this  undertaking,  which  implies,  again,  a 
development  of  the  feelings  hostile  to  such  practices,  and  at 
the  same  time  of  a  social  structure  capable  of  applying 
effectual  restraints.  Now,  so  far  as  the  growth  of  a  certain 
body  of  sentiment  is  implied,  the  question  emerges.  What  is 
the  common  principle  in  virtue  of  which  this,  that,  and 
the  other  bad  practice  is  hateful  ?  As  men  grow  more  rea- 
sonable, they  are  constantly  comparing  and  correlating  their 
feelings;  some  such  process  is  involved  in  all  conscious  action; 
they  are  thus  classifying  the  various  external  phenomena 
in  respect  of  the  feelings  excited.  Gradually,  it  appears 
that  this  process  leads  to  a  necessary  divergence  of  the 
two  methods  of  classification.  The  same  feeling  is  excited 
in  countless  wavs  according:;  to  the  endless  combination  of 
external  facts.  No  definite  class  of  external  facts  can  be 
assigned  which  precisely  corresponds  to  one  intrinsic  feeling. 
Hence,  as  the  ultimate  principle  of  classification  must  for  all 
purposes  of  conduct  be  by  the  primary  feelings,  we  find  that 
the  most  general  rules  of  conduct  must  be  expressed  in  terms 
of  character,  and  the  other  rules,  which  contain  the  appli- 
cation of  those  general  rules  to  more  special  cases,  must  take 
a  subordinate  position,  and  be  regarded  as  being  only  of  con- 
ditional value.  This,  again,  is  the  same  thing  as  to  say  that 
these  general  rules  express  the  properties  of  the  social  tissue, 
or  those  properties  of  the  organic  growth  which  underlie 
all  the  special  arrangements  which  can  only  be  regarded  as 
comparatively  superficial  products  of  the  tissue,  determined 
by  its  necessary  external  relations.  Finally,  it  may  be  re- 
peated that  they  must  necessarily  correspond  within  narrow 
limits  to  a  statement  of  the  conditions  of  vitality  of  the 
tissue  which  they  characterise. 


1 66  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

28.  This,  agaiu^  gives  an  intelligible  sense  to  another  sense 
in  which  we  may  understand  another  predicate  frequently 
attributed  to  the  moral  law.  Moralists  frequently  assert  its 
supremacy,  and  appear  in  so  doing  to  fall  into  a  vicious  circle. 
A  legislator  orders  me  to  lie,  and  the  moral  law  orders  me 
to  tell  the  truth.  Then,  it  is  said,  I  ought  to  obey  the  moral 
law.  But  if  ^^ouoht"  means  it  is  rio-ht,  and  rio;ht  means  in 
conformity  to  the  moral  law,  this  appears  to  be  equivalent  to 
saying  that  I  ought  to  do  what  I  ought  to  do.  It  is  difficult 
if  not  impossible  to  escape  from  this  dilemma  so  long  as  we 
are  speaking  of  a  supremacy  de  jure;  but  if  we  speak  of  a 
supremacy  de  facto,  the  statement  may  bear  a  tenable  inter- 
pretation. It  is  conceivable,  in  fact,  that  any  law  belonging 
to  a  given  association  may  be  regarded  as  more  or  less  con- 
ditional. I  may  agree  to  obey  its  rules  so  long  as  those  rules 
do  not  conflict  with  the  laws  of  a  higher  authority.  We 
might  conceivably  have  a  state  which  in  this  way  did  in  fact 
recognise  the  moral  law,  so  that  no  law  would  actually  be 
enforced  when  it  conflicted  with  the  moral  sense  of  the 
community.  How  far  this  is  the  case  in  any  really  exist- 
ing state  I  do  not  presume  to  say.  It  is  undoubtedly  very 
difficult  to  enforce  laws  when  they  palpably  oflend  the 
recognised  morality  of  a  country ;  and  the  conceivable  reply 
of  a  lawyer,  that  they  are  still  laws,  is  a  mere  verbal  reply 
when  we  are  dealing  with  facts.  But  however  this  may  be 
in  particular  cases,  the  general  principle  remains  true.  The 
laws  of  a  state,  along  with  all  its  other  arrangements,  are, 
generally  speaking,  the  product  of  the  social  medium  from 
which  it  springs,  and  generally,  therefore,  reflect  the  preva- 
lent moral  feeling.  And  further,  the  moral  feeling  is  itself 
dependent  upon  conditions  of  a  higher  and  more  general 
order  than  those  by  which  the  political  organisation  is  deter- 
mined. We  may  therefore  say  briefly  that  the  morality  of 
a  race,  as  it  depends  upon  the  most  permanent  conditions, 
represents  its  fundamental  characteristics,  and  that  the 
subordinate  rules  of  conduct,  whatever  they  may  be,  must 
be   regarded   as   springing  from   them,  and   not  vice  versa. 


BASIS  OF  MORALITY.  167 

Many  laws,  indeed,  exist  which  arc  regarded  as  more  or  less 
immoral  by  large  classes  of  the  persons  bound  by  them. 
The  law  does  not  cease  to  be  a  law  because  it  is  immoral, 
but  certainly  it  has  less  chance  of  being  anything  but  a  law 
in  name ;  and  the  only  general  principle  must  be  that  the 
characteristics  which  are  most  deeply  seated  and  dependent 
upon  the  most  permanent  conditions  must  tend,  however 
long  the  process,  to  override  those  which  are  relatively  super- 
ficial and  contingent.  Further,  it  may  be  added  that,  in  an 
ideal  state  of  society,  every  general  principle  would  also  be 
recognized  in  every  particular  rule.  This  is  a  result,  indeed, 
to  which  we  must  expect  a  gradual  approximation  rather 
than  anticipate  its  actual  attainment.  So,  for  example,  if 
the  moral  law  commands  kindliness  and  some  particular 
rule  prescribes  a  cruel  action,  we  may  say  that  if  the 
society  is  progressive  (a  condition  which  is  of  course  neces- 
sary) some  uniform  rule  must  be  worked  out.  Then,  by 
hypothesis,  kindliness  has  been  discovered  to  be  a  quality 
characteristic  of  social  vitality,  and  the  rule  can  be  laid  down 
absolutely ;  whereas  the  rule  which  prescribes  cruelty  is  the 
product  of  some  particular  combination  of  circumstances, 
and  can  only  be  stated  conditionally.  Hence  we  may  say 
that  the  general  tendency  must  be  to  bring  about  such  a 
modification  of  sentiment  that  the  superficial  and  excep- 
tional rule  may  be  superseded  by  one  consistent  with  the 
general  principle.  The  statement,  however,  as  to  the  supre- 
macy of  morality  and  the  conscience  is  generally,  as  I  think, 
understood  in  a  different  sense,  and  as  applicable  to  particular 
cases  of  conduct  rather  than  to  the  position  occupied  by  the 
moral  sentiments  in  the  general  process  of  evolution.  We 
shall  come  to  this  in  a  later  chapter. 


V.  Basis  of  Morality. 

29.  So  far,  then,  the  argument  has  justified  some  of  the 
predicates  most  generally  applied  to  the  moral  law,  though 
it  imposes  a  certain  interpretation  upon  them.     By  saying 


1 68  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

that  a  law  is  moral,  we  mean  that  it  belongs  to  human  beings 
as  such,  and  not  as  belonging  to  any  special  class.  This,  in 
my  view,  amounts  to  saying  that  the  moral  law  defines  a 
property  of  the  social  tissue.  Hence  it  must  be  natural,  not 
artificial ;  it  must  grow,  and  not  be  made ;  for  these  pro- 
perties are  the  intrinsic  and  underlying  properties  implied 
in  all  special  societies,  incapable  of  being  abruptly  altered 
by  the  action  of  any  particular  person,  or  in  obedience  to 
any  subordinate  series  of  events,  and  gradually  developed  as 
the  society  grows  instead  of  being  the  fruit  of  special  con- 
tingencies. The  law  must  be  eternal  so  far  as  anything 
human  can  be  eternal,  for  it  must  be  an  approximate  expres- 
sion of  the  conditions  of  social  vitality,  as  the  instincts  to 
which  it  corresponds  are  the  instincts  by  which  the  life  of 
the  society  is  maintained ;  and  it  must  therefore  be  as  per- 
manent as  those  conditions  themselves.  It  varies  only  by 
development,  as  each  step  in  the  social  evolution  represents 
a  fuller  solution  of  the  problem  of  adapting  a  society  formed 
of  given  materials  and  acting  under  fixed  conditions  to  the 
needs  which  those  conditions  impose.  Again,  it  must  be 
capable  of  expression  as  a  law  of  internal  character,  not  as  a 
law  of  external  facts ;  for  the  only  variable  element  is  the 
character,  and  the  problem  to  which  it  supplies  an  answer  is 
the  determination  of  the  most  effective  qualities  of  character 
which  can  be  developed  in  a  given  agent  to  make  him  an 
efficient  member  of  society.  In  the  infinite  variety  of  cir- 
cumstance,  these  qualities  may  manifest  themselves  in  a 
corresponding  variety  of  methods,  which  can  never  be 
adequately  summed  up  or  classified  by  external  character- 
istics. And,  finally,  since  these  qualities  represent  the  most 
general  rules  of  action,  such  alone  as  can  be  stated  absolutely 
— that  is,  without  reference  to  varying  circumstances — the 
law  must  be  supreme.  It  deals  with  the  first  principles,  the 
primary  reasons  to  which  every  particular  case  must  present 
a  special  application. 

30.  Supposing  this  to  be  admitted,  we  have  still  the  critical 
problem  before  us.     For  the  natural  method  would  now  be 


BASIS  OF  MORALITY.  169 

to  deduce  from  the  general  principle  the  particular  rules 
of  conduct,  and  to  show  that  they  do  in  fact  lead  to  the 
recognised  moral  law.  There  is,  as  I  began  by  saying,  a 
tolerable  agreement  as  to  the  contents  of  that  law,  however 
wide  mav  be  the  divergence  as  to  its  form.  This  being  so, 
it  would  be  absurd,  as  it  would  be  really  misleading,  to  affect 
the  method  of  an  a  priori  deduction.  We  know  what  are 
the  conclusions  to  be  reached,  and  need  not  speak  as  though 
we  had  before  us  nothing  but  the  premisses.  It  will  be 
enough  to  show  that  the  general  principles  of  morality  can 
in  fact  be  deduced  from  the  theory  laid  down,  without  sup- 
posing that  we  are  starting  from  that  theory  with  perfectly 
unprepossessed  minds,  in  search  of  any  principles  that  may 
turn  up.  Certain  general  remarks,  however,  may  be  pre- 
mised, to  elucidate  the  nature  of  the  investigation.  We  are 
to  see  how  certain  rules  have  been  reached  by  the  evolution 
of  society  from  a  period  at  which,  as  we  assume,  though  attribu- 
ting to  our  assumption  no  more  than  an  approximate  accuracy, 
the  individual  man  had  his  present  organisation,  but  at  which 
societv  existed  only  in  germ,  and  the  custom  upon  which  it 
depends  had  not  been  distinctly  elaborated  nor  consciously 
accepted.  We  have  to  deal,  then,  only  with  the  rules  which 
have  been  created  by  society,  or  rather  which  have  been 
evolved  as  society  has  evolved,  the  internal  and  the  external 
processes  being  necessarily  correlated,  and  not  related  as  though 
one  had  appeared  first  and  the  other  been  moulded  upon  it. 

31.  Hence  we  have  nothing  to  do  with  certain  rules  of 
conduct  which  are  implied  in  the  very  constitution  of  the 
race,  and  which  would  certainlv  have  to  be  stated  as  primary 
conditions  of  existence.  Men  must  have  certain  appetites, 
hunger,  the  sexual  instinct,  and  so  forth,  without  which  the 
race  could  not  survive  for  a  day.  They  are,  again,  implied  in 
every  later  development;  but  we  have  only  to  do  with  the 
later  modification,  and  not  with  the  initial  state.  But,  in 
the  next  place,  it  is  clear  that  we  might  lay  down  many  rules 
of  conduct  as  necessarv  to  the  existence  of  society  which 
cannot  be  regarded  as  properly  moral.     Thus,  for  example. 


I70  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  most  obvious  condition  of  the  social  or  individual  vitality 
is  what  we  may  roughly  call  the  instinct  of  self-preservation. 
If  men  had  no  instinct  which  kept  them  from  walking  over 
precipices  or  swallowing  fire,  they  would  have  a  very  pre- 
carious tenure  of  life.  Nobody  would  be  called  moral  for 
obedience  to  the  rules  formed  from  such  instincts,  nor  even 
for  obedience  to  the  higher  rules  which  are  developed  from 
them  as  society  grows.  The  instinct  of  self-preservation 
becomes  finer  and  more  sensitive  as  the  emotional  and  intel- 
lectual faculties  are  developed.  We  become  aware  of  a  greater 
number  of  conditions,  measure  them  by  more  delicate  tests, 
and  are  more  sensitive  to  remote  consequences.  For  the  mere 
avoidance  of  fire,  precipices,  poisons,  and  so  forth,  we  come 
to  observe  with  more  or  less  regularity  a  complex  set  of  rules 
calculated  to  preserve  our  bodily  health ;  but  such  rules  are 
not  generally  regarded  as  moral  at  all.  We  do  not  say  that 
a  man  is  good  because  he  takes  care  of  his  digestion  or  makes 
it  a  principle  to  take  a  certain  quantity  of  exercise  daily. 
Such  conduct  is  denied  to  be  moral,  although  we  may  call 
it  prudent,  because  it  is  consistent  with  selfishness,  cruelty, 
falsehood,  and  other  bad  qualities.  Briefiy,  it  is  admitted 
that,  in  some  sense  or  other,  morality  implies  action  for  the 
good  of  others;  but  to  define  that  sense  accurately  is  to  solve 
some  of  the  most  vital  moral  problems.  We  may  ask,  in 
fact,  whether  it  is  or  is  not  possible  for  any  man  to  aim  at 
the  good  of  others  as  an  ultimate  end  ?  and,  again,  whether 
it  is  necessary  to  moral  conduct  that  the  good  of  others  should 
be  consciously  intended,  or  whether  it  is  sufficient  that  it 
should  be  a  natural  consequence  of  the  conduct  in  question  ? 
To  give  some  answer  to  these  and  the  allied  questions  will  be 
one  object  of  the  following  pages. 

32.  We  may  first  recall  a  distinction,  already  stated,  which 
will  be  relevant  to  this  inquiry.  Society,  as  I  have  said,  may 
be  regarded  both  as  an  asfo-recrate  and  as  an  oro;anism.  There 
are  certain  qualities  which  we  may  suppose  to  vary  in  the  in- 
dividual without  necessarily  involving  a  change  in  the  social 
structure.     71ie  relations  of  the  parts  may  remain  sensibly 


BASIS  OF  MORALITY.  171 

the  same  although  the  general  vigour — the  sum-total  of  the 
enero-ies  involved — is  increased  or  diminished.  On  the  other 
hand,  there  are  qualities  in  respect  of  which  the  reverse  is  true. 
No  change  can  take  place  in  them  without  implying  a  corre- 
sponding change  in  the  character  of  the  social  union.  The 
distinction  is  not  absolute;  for  every  change  in  anv  part  of 
the  organism  must  have  some  reaction  upon  all  its  other 
parts ;  but  the  distinction  may  be,  or  rather  must  be,  made  for 
purposes  of  classification.  We  must  distinguish,  that  is,  be- 
tween such  a  quality  as  loyalty,  which  cannot  be  supposed  to 
increase  or  diminish  without  alterino;  the  essential  character- 
istics  of  the  social  tie,  and  such  a  qualitv  as  mere  personal 
prudence,  which  would  no  doubt  have  a  great  influence  upon 
the  whole  social  organism,  but  which  may  be  considered  apart 
from  that  set  of  consequences  and  which  immediatelv  affects 
the  total  power  of  the  community  rather  than  the  relation 
between  its  members.  Some  reference,  whether  erroneous  or 
not,  to  this  distinction  seems  to  be  implied  in  the  criterion  by 
which  we  judtre  whether  a  given  rule  does  or  does  not  belon*)- 
to  morality  proper  after  we  have  admitted  it  to  be  a  rule  of 
social  vitality.  And  this  distinction  may  be  made  without 
considering  the  further  and  most  important  question  how  far 
the  quality  which  is  actually  and  permanently  essential  to 
society  considered  as  an  organism,  rather  than  to  societv  con- 
sidered as  an  affo-reg-ate,  does  or  does  not  involve  anv  conscious 
reference  to  the  welfare  of  the  societv,  or  of  others  besides 
the  agent.  This  is  a  question  which  demands  a  special 
discussion,  and  which,  therefore,  it  is  desirable  to  reserve  as 
much  as  possible. 

^^.  The  question,  therefore,  which  now  has  to  be  considered 
is  the  deduction  of  the  moral  rule  from  the  general  principle 
of  social  vitality,  and  with  a  reference  to  the  question  how 
they  are  distinguished  from  other  rules  deducible  from  that 
principle.  If  we  have  rightly  assigned  the  germs  to  which 
the  moral  law  belongs,  we  have  still  to  consider  how  these 
germs  may  be  divided  into  species,  and  what  is  the  specific 
difference. 


(       1/2      ) 


CHAPTER  V. 

CONTENTS     OF     THE     MORAL     LAW. 

I.   The  Law  of  Nature  and  Morality. 

1.  The  law  of  nature  has  but  one  precept,  "Be  strong." 
Nature  has  but  one  punishment,  decav,  culminating  in  death 
or  extirpation^  and  takes  cognisance  of  but  one  evil,  the 
weakness  which  leads  to  decay.  From  this,  the  most  general 
point  of  view,  we  can  make  no  distinction  between  the  various 
instincts  except  in  so  far  as  they  do  or  do  not  imply  the 
vitality  of  the  organism  to  which  they  belong.  But  when 
we  regard  the  individual  as  an  organism  within  an  organism, 
the  law  takes  different  forms  and  requires  to  be  diff'erentlv 
stated,  according  to  its  mode  of  impact.  In  one  great  class  of 
cases  it  applies  to  the  instincts  in  respect  of  which  society  is 
an  aggregate,  and  the  conduct  of  each  individual  may  varv 
without  implying  a  corresponding  variation  in  the  social 
organisation.  In  the  other  class  it  applies  to  those  instincts 
which  are  the  vital  forces  of  that  association,  and  cannot  varv 
without  a  corresponding  variation  in  it.  In  one  case  the 
effect  upon  the  individual  is  the  primary  efl^ect,  and  the  society 
is  affected  through  its  constituent  units;  in  the  other  case, 
the  units  are  affected  through  the  soqiety,  and  the  law  cannot 
be  intelligibly  stated  without  taking  the  social  factor  into 
account.  This  may  be  expressed  again  by  saving  that  the 
great  law,  "Be  strong,"  has  two  main  branches,  "Be  prudent " 
and  "Be  virtuous."  To  assio;n  the  mutual  relations  of  these 
resulting  codes,  which,  although  distinguishable  in  abstract 
analysis,  are  so  closely  connected  in  the  concrete,  is  the  task 
upon  which  we  must  now  enter.    By  some  thinkers  morality 


THE  LAW  OF  NATURE  AND  MORALITY.  173 

has  been  resolved  into  a  particular  case  of  prudence ;  according 
to  others,  prudence  may  be  resolved  into  morality,  or  both 
into  right  reason  or  into  a  desire  for  happiness.  Let  us 
consider  how  the  case  must  be  stated  from  our  point  of 
view. 

2.  This  statement  takes  for  granted  the  general  nature  of 
the  distinction.     It  is,  in  fact,  admitted  that  by  the  moral 
code  we  mean  to  refer  not  merely  to  the  predicates  already 
noted,  such  as  the  eternity,  supremacy,  and  so  forth,  of  the 
code,  but  also  to  its  havino;  in  some  sense  or  other  a  reference 
to  the  welfare  of  the  society.     What  we  have  now  to  do  is  to 
substitute  for  that  "some  sense  or  other"  a  more  precise 
definition;  and  the  task  would  be  accomplished  if  we  could 
deduce  the  particular  laws  of  conduct  from  the  laws  of  nature, 
and  then  show  which  of  these  laws  coincide  with  the  moral 
law  and  why?    There  is  here  the  difficulty  tliat  the  moral  law 
has  not  been,  and,  if  I  am  right,  cannot  be  accurately  codified, 
even  if  the  agreement  as  to  its  contents  were  still  closer  than 
is  actuallv  the  case.     If  we  classify  conduct  by  external  marks, 
we  have  a  variety  of  general  rules,  none  of  which  are  precise  or 
unconditional.     Thus,  for  example,  we  have  such  virtues  and 
vices  as  generosity  and  avarice,  which  refer  to  a  particular  class 
of  actions,  namely,  in  this  case,  to  dealings  in  money  matters. 
If  we  proceed  to  ask  for  a  more  explicit  account  of  what  is 
meant  by  avarice,  we   find    that  moralists  do  not  mean  to 
condemn  the  love  of  money  sim p licit er  ;  for  money  represents 
every  material  object  of  human  desire,  and  to  condemn  them 
all   would   be   to   condemn   life   in   the  world.      Thev   really 
condemn  certain  excesses,  and  more  especially  those  which 
imply  selfishness.     Avarice  is  the  love  of  money  so  far  as  it 
implies  a  disregard  of  the  claims  of  others,  or,  again,  so  far  as 
it  implies  a  defective  appreciation  of  the  higher  enjoyments. 
To  condemn  avarice,  then,  is  to  condemn  one  kind  of  selfish- 
ness, and  bv  implication  to  condemn  it  in  many  relations  of 
life  which  have  no  relation  to  money.     A  classification  pro- 
ceeding by  the  various  external  applications  of  the  internal 
principle  would  be  endless,  and  involve  repetitions  and  cross 


174  T^HE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

divisions.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we  take  the  other  mode  of 
defining  morahty,  we  find  that  the  law  reduces  itself  to  one 
or  two  simple  principles — to  the  statement,  for  example,  that 
we  should  love  God  and  our  neighbour;  that  we  should  hurt 
no  one,  and  do  to  others  as  we  would  that  they  should  do 
to  us.  But  such  statements  are  too  general  to  be  available  for 
our  present  purpose. 

3.  To  find  a  classification  of  the  virtues  which  will  not  run 
into  infinite  detail  or  be  a  simple  affirmation  of  the  general 
principle,  we  may  observe  that  the  internal  mode  of  classifica- 
tion suggests  a  method  which  will  be  sufficient  for  our  purposes, 
and  which  corresponds  to  the  ancient  doctrine  of  the  cardinal 
virtues.  We  may  begin  by  considering  the  qualities  which 
belong  to  the  individual  primarily,  and  ask  how  far  they  have 
any  moral  significance.  The  general  formula  of  such  virtues 
is,  "  Be  strong,"  or,  as  we  may  put.it,  "  All  weakness  is  an  evil." 
The  simplest  organism  may  be  considered  in  respect  of  its 
strength  or  weakness,  that  is,  its  power  of  preserving  its  life 
under  the  various  conditions  of  existence,  and  that  before 
any  complexity  of  social  organisation  has  been  reached.  As 
the  social  development  affects  these  qualities  as  well  as  the 
others  more  directly  involved,  the  social  pressure  constitutes 
a  law  which  may  have  some  moral  character.  In  the  next 
place,  the  development  is  of  two  kinds,  or  may  be  regarded 
under  two  main  aspects — the  emotional  and  the  intellectual. 
To  each  of  these  there  belongs  a  characteristic  moral  law; 
for  as  soon  as  we  can  regard  the  individual  as  a  complex 
organism,  made  up  of  different  instincts  and  capacities  for 
feeling,  one  main  condition  of  vitality  must  refer  to  the 
strength  and  mutual  relation  of  those  instincts.  Hence  we 
have  the  virtues  of  which  the  general  formula  is,  "Be  tem- 
perate," or  the  correlative  statement  that  all  excess  is  an 
evil.  These  qualities,  again,  however  modified  in  the  higher 
phases  of  development,  must  exist  in  germ  even  before  the 
animal  is  capable  of  anything  that  can  be  called  reasoning,  or 
of  a  conscious  reference  to  the  distant  or  the  future.  When 
we  consider  the  intellectual  development,  we  have  a  third  class 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  175 

of  virtues  refcrrino;  to  the  conditions  of  intellectual  efficiency, 
the  jrcneral  formula  beinsi;  in  this  case,  "Be  truthful,"  and 
"  All  falsehood  is  evil."  And,  finally,  as  the  social  organisation 
becomes  developed,  and  has  special  moods  of  sentiment  corre- 
sponding to  it,  we  have  the  virtues  which  correspond  directly 
to  a  condition  of  social  vitality.  The  formula  may  be  ex- 
pressed in  the  social  or  commn  assertion  that  all  injury  to  our 
fellows  is  an  evil.  I  will  not  inquire  whether  this  classification 
can  be  regarded  as  accurate  or  exhaustive.  It  will  give  us,  at 
any  rate^  a  clue  to  the  inquiry  quite  sufficient  for  our  purpose  ; 
that  is,  in  fact,  for  showing  how  the  specific  difference  under- 
stood by  the  word  '^  moral  "  is  brought  out  in  the  code  actually 
formed  by  our  approvals  and  disapprovals,  and  what  is  the 
nature — so  far  as  it  can  be  defined — of  the  process  by  which 
the  development  is  effected. 


II.   Virtue  of  Courage. 

4.  "  Be  strong  "  is,  I  have  said,  the  general  precept  of  the 
law  of  nature.  The  strength  of  the  society,  again,  is  in- 
creased by  the  strength  of  its  individual  members.  So  far  as 
each  unit  is  stronger,  braver,  more  energetic,  and  more  in- 
dustrious, more  capable,  therefore,  of  holding  his  own  against 
external  enemies  or  material  disadvantages,  so  far  is  the 
society  composed  of  such  individuals  stronger.  This,  indeed, 
must  always  be  understood  with  reference  to  a  tacit  condition. 
If  an  increase  of  courage  necessarily  involved  an  increase  of 
insubordination,  we  should  have  to  ask  whether  the  increased 
power  of  the  individual  soldier  was  cheaply  or  dearly  bought 
by  the  weakened  discipline  of  the  army  to  which  he  belongs. 
But  there  is  no  necessary  divergence  between  the  two  qualities. 
Increased  energy  may  go  along  with  increased  power  of  co- 
operation ;  and  therefore  the  rule,  "  Be  strong,"  may  be  stated 
without  referring  to  a  condition  which  is  generally  latent, 
though,  under  particular  circumstances,  it  may  assert  itself 
and  demand  attention.  Ceteris  paribus,  we  may  say  the 
increase  of  individual  energy  is  an  advantage  to  society  3  and. 


176  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

as  a  matter  of  feet,  we  find  that  the  civilised  society  differs 
conspicuously  from  the  ruder  by  stimulating  more  vigorously 
and  systematically  the  various  energies  of  its  members.     The 
most  conspicuous  virtue  of  this  class  is  the  virtue  of  courage. 
The  deduction  of  courage  from  the  general  condition  of  social 
vitality  is  manifest.     In  cases  where  a  society  has  to  strucrirle 
against  external  enemies,  military  excellence  is  the  most  obvious 
guarantee  for  its  security,  and  in  rude  societies,  military  ex- 
cellence is  proportional  to  courage.     Savage  tribes  may  often 
be  said  to  hold  life  at  every  moment  upon  the  tenure  of  military 
prowess.     And,  moreover,  it  is  plain  that  the  same  principle 
would  hold  good,  not  only  where  it  is  directly  exemplified, 
but  where  there  are  apparent  deflections  from  the  rule.    That 
is  to  say,  that  in  cases    where  the  external   conditions  are 
such  as  to  give  less  importance  to  the  military  energies,  courage 
is  less  highly  estimated ;  and  so,  again,  the  particular  kind  of 
courage  most  in  demand  varies  as  fraud  or  force  is  the  most 
effective  weapon  for  the  particular  race  and  purpose.     The 
most  familiar  instance  is  in  the  very  different  estimate  which 
is  placed  upon  courage  in  the  two  sexes.     Moralists  would 
hardly  admit  that  the  rule  ought  to  be  different;  but  they 
admit  that,  in  point  of  fact,  want  of  courage  in  men  provokes 
contempt  in  most  modern  nations,  and  a  want  of  chastity 
is  regarded  with  comparative  indifference;  whilst  in  the  case 
of  women,  the  rule  is  altered :  unchastity  is  held  to  be  the 
most  unpardonable  of  crimes,  whilst  cowardice,  in  some  rela- 
tions at  least,  is  thought  to  be  rather  graceful  than  otherwise. 
Practical  moralists  lament  these  inconsistencies,  and  theorists 
have  invented  more  or  less  ingenious  hypotheses  to  account 
for  them.    The  historical  explanation  is,  within  its  own  limits, 
simple  and  obvious.    We  may  state  that  in  early  social  stages 
fighting  power  was  the  critical  or  essential  power  for  each  race ; 
that  those  in  which  it  flourished  most  conquered,  and  often 
exterminated   the   rest;  and    thus   that  a  cultivation  of  the 
military  qualities,  the  most  conspicuous  of  which  was  bravery, 
was  a  characteristic  of  the  dominant  races.     7'he  warrior  was 
the  natural  leader,  and  the  best  warrior  had  the  first  choice 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  177 

of  spoil,  or  the  greatest  chance  of  gratifying  his  passions. 
Naturallv  excellence  in  war  was  coveted  and  admired  by  every 
one.  The  estimate  once  fixed  tends  to  prolong  itself  even 
when  some  of  these  conditions  disappear.  Every  male  child 
in  a  certain  rank  in  England  is  still  brought  up  from  its 
cradle  to  value  itself  on  being  "a  gentleman;"  and  to  be  a 
gentleman  is,  amongst  other  things,  to  be  ready  to  take  one's 
own  part  with  sword  or  fist.  To  women,  on  the  other  hand, 
has  been  assigned  from  the  earliest  period  of  the  division  of 
labour  the  class  of  social  functions  for  which  military  excel- 
lence was  not  required.  The  savage  acquired  his  wife  by 
knocking  her  down;  to  him,  therefore,  the  ideal  feminine 
character  must  have  included  readiness  to  be  knocked  down, 
or  at  least  unreadiness  to  strike  again ;  and  as  some  of  the 
forms  of  marriage  recall  the  early  system,  so  in  the  senti- 
ments with  which  it  is  reirarded  there  mav  still  linger  some- 
thing  of  the  early  instinct  associated  with  striking  and  being 
struck. 

V  K.  Thus  we  mav  sav  that  courage  is  a  necessary  condition  of 
the  vitality  of  a  society  so  long  as  it  depends  upon  militarv 
activity;  and  this  implies  that  every  man  is  in  such  a 
society  trained  to  be  brave  in  so  far  as  his  possession  of  that 
quality  entitles  him  to  respect  and  the  advantages  of  being 
respected;  and,  again,  in  so  far  as  he  imbibes  the  current 
opinion  bv  which  the  standard  is  fixed  from  his  earhest  period 
of  conscious  thought.  The  development  of  society  implies  a 
corresponding  modification  of  this  sentiment.  The  military 
virtues  become  less  prominent  as  war  occupies  a  smaller  part 
of  the  total  activities  and  is  a  less  essential  part  of  social 
efficiency.  But  there  is  simultaneously  a  change  in  the  whole 
mode  of  thought.  In  an  early  social  stage,  we  may  suppose 
that  the  warrior  who  shrinks  from  dano-er  is  reoarded  with 
contempt  and  dislike;  since  the  life  of  every  member  of  the 
tribe  may  depend  at  any  moment  upon  the  prowess  of  his 
fellows,  the  whole  social  group  is  closely  interested  in  the 
success  of  every  one  of  its  members.  But,  as  society  develops, 
new  cases  present  themselves  for  classification.     For,  in  the 

M 


\p:LMili-j 


178  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

first  place,  there  are  brave  enemies  as  well  as  brave  champions 
of  our  own.    What  is  the  sentiment  which  they  create?    We 
may  conceive  it  possible  that  a  brave  enemy  might  be  con- 
sidered simply  as  a  more  dangerous  antagonist.    He  might  be 
regarded  with  greater  antipathy,  just  as  a  big  wolf  would  be 
worse  than  a  little  one.     But  in  the  more  civilised  race  the 
chivalrous  sentiment  begins  to  manifest  itself  in  imperfect  and 
frao-mentary  ways.     In  a  comparatively  civilised  state,  people 
still  hate  enemies  at  a  distance  in  proportion  to  their  courage, 
and  set  it  down  as  more  or  less  diabolical ;  whilst  at  the  same 
time  they  are  capable  of  a  true  chivalry  towards  those  with 
whom  they  are  more  nearly  allied.     The  English  and  Scotch 
Borderers  might  respect  each  other's  courage,  and  be  the  better 
friends  when  the  fin-htino;  was  over.    They  mifjht,  at  the  same 
time,  regard  courage  in  a  Saracen  as  a  bad  quality,  demanding 
a  more  undying  antipathy.     This  growth  of  the  chivalrous 
feelino-  implies,  on  the  one  side,  a  growth  of  sympathy,  inas- 
much as  we  are  now  capable  of  admiring  the  man  who  was 
bevond  the  pale  of  any  common  feeling;  and,  on  the  other 
hand,  it  may  be  regarded  as  involving  an  implicit  generalisa- 
ion.     We  say  implicitly  that  we  regard  the  brave  enemy  as 
intrinsically  admirable  in  so  far  as  he   has  shown  a  good 
quality,  and  objectionable  only  from  the  accidental  circum- 
stances which  have  made  his  interests  incompatible  with  our 
own.     We  thus  have  virtually  reached  the  general  principle 
that  courage  in  war  is  a  valuable  quality  for  its  owner  and 
his  side,  and  therefore  one  which  we  can  admire,  although  it 
may  or  may  not  be  valuable  to  ourselves. 
V   6.  The  increased  intellio-ence  or  scnsibilitv  which  makes 
such  a  judgment  possible  carries  along  with  it  other  changes. 
In   the   early  state,  attention   is   fixed  exclusively  upon  the 
simple  case   of  military  excellence.     The  warrior  who  runs 
away  is  doing  me  an  injury,  for  the  tribe  has  its  interests  so 
much  in  common  that  the  bad  conduct  of  one  necessarilv 
injures  others.     But  as  men   become  more   intelligent  and 
society  more  complex,  this  simple  observation  requires  to  be 
modified.     For,  in  the  first  place,  it  must  come  to  be  per- 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  179 

ceived  that  courage  pei-  se  is  not  necessarily  a  good  quality. 
If,  that  is,  courage  be  defined  as  simple  insensibility  to  danofcr, 
it  may  obviously  be  carried  to  excess;  and  we  imply  this  by 
the  condemnatory  phrase  "  rashness."  Indeed  it  is  so  little 
a  virtue,  that  cases  may  certainly  be  imagined  in  which  what 
we  call  cowardice  would  be  a  virtue.  There  are  races  of 
animals  which  owe  their  safety  to  a  lively  perception  of  danger. 
The  excellence  of  a  hare  consists  in  running  away,  and  those 
hares  which  were  best  at  runnino-  and  also  quickest  at  takino- 
alarm  would  tend  to  survive,  and  set  the  standard  of  hare- 
morality.  If  this  is  not  the  case  with  man,  we  can  only 
explain  it  by  the  fact  that,  in  the  conditions  of  human  life, 
inilitary  excellence  is  the  necessary  condition  of  success,  and 
that  military  success  requires  courage.  But  courage,  as 
we  see,  requires  to  be  more  accurately  defined.  "Moral 
courage,"  as  it  is  called,  tends  to  take  the  place  of  "  physical 
courage."  By  moral  courage  we  must  understand  not  simple 
insensibility  to  danger,  which  is  consistent  with  idiocy,  but 
a  power,  as  we  say,  of  "  keeping  our  heads,"  or,  in  other 
words,  of  reasonino:  as  deliberately  and  actino;  as  coolly  under 
danger  as  when  there  is  no  danfrer.  This  quality  would  be 
as  useful  to  hares  as  to  men,  and  indeed  is  implied  in  the 
intellectual  development;  for  it  is  simply  a  statement  that  a 
power  of  reasoning — that  is,  of  consulting  all  relevant  cir- 
cumstances and  actintr  in  accordance  with  a  sound  judgment 
— is  an  essential  part  of  practical  reason.  Courage,  there- 
fore, changes  its  quality  to  some  extent,  and  we  admire  the 
kind  of  courage  which  is  manifested  by  the  general  com- 
manding under  stress  of  great  danger  and  heavy  responsibility 
more  than  the  simple  courage  of  a  soldier  who  Avalks  up  to  a 
battery,  or  of  a  hunter  who  confronts  a  tiger  in  his  jungle. 
X  \^  7.  This,  again,  involves  another  process  of  implicit  reason- 
/  ing;  it  becomes  manifest,  in  short,  that  courage  cannot  be 
considered  by  itself.  We  must  determine  its  relations  to  the 
whole  character,  or  we  shall  be  admiring  it  in  cases  where 
it  is  absolutely  prejudicial.  Fighting,  however,  and  so  far 
courage,  has  been  from  an  early  period  an  essential  condition 


I  So  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

of  social  vitality^  and  therefore  the  internal  relations  of  the 
tribe  and  the  various  propensities  of  its  members  must  have 
been  developed  with  reference  to  this  condition.  It  has 
always  been  a  prominent  condition,  as  in  early  times  it  was 
the  most  conspicuous  and  predominant  condition;  but  as 
peaceful  instincts  have  developed  there  must  have  been  some 
correlatinir  and  harmonisino;  influence.  The  militarv  instinct 
is  not  necessarily  incompatible  with  the  industrial,  but  at 
any  given  period  the  one  may  be  developed  to  the  prejudice  of 
the  other.  Where  the  race  has  been  constantly,  though  in 
part  unconsciously,  occupied  upon  the  great  problem  how  to 
reconcile  the  two,  and  to  secure  at  once  efficiencv  in  war  and 
efficiency  in  peace,  one  quality  or  the  other  may  be  in  excess ; 
as  there  are  races  which  are  easily  conquered,  but  which  have 
great  capacity  for  thriving  and  extending  themselves  when 
not  encountered  by  enemies,  and  others  in  which  the  military 
spirit  is  so  strongly  developed  tliat,  although  they  can  resist 
direct  attacks,  they  are  weak  in  adapting  themselves  to  the 
material  conditions  of  life.  The  races  which  survive  are 
those  in  which  there  has  been  such  a  development  that,  on 
the  whole,  a  maximum  of  efficiency  has  been  reached  by  the 
best  adaptation  to  divergent,  though  not  naturally  antagonistic, 
conditions  of  development.  The  distinction  appears  in  the 
internal  relations  of  any  community;  for  as  peaceful  relations 
become  more  prominent,  it  is  evident  that  excellence  of  the 
militarv  kind  may  be  combined  with  bad  qualities  of  another 
kind — that  the  bravest  man  or  the  best  soldier  may  be  lazy, 
dissolute,  or  tyrannical  in  his  other  relations,  and  that  we 
must  therefore  substitute  some  more  discriminating:  mode  of 
judgment  for  that  which  was  previously  sufficient. 

8.  Hence  arises  the  problem  whether  courage  can  be  con- 
sidered as  a  moral  quality  at  all ;  for  it  mav  be  as  well  to  make 
the  remark,  which  will  be  frequently  exemplified,  that  although 
we  speak  of  the  moral  law  as  though  it  corresponded  to  a 
perfectly  distinct  mode  of  thinking  and  feeling,  we  are  by  no 
means  entitled  to  assume  that  the  actual  demarcation  is  so 
sharp  as  our  use  of  language  suggests.     In  fact,  we  shall  find 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  iSi 

that  it  is  often  exceedinglv  difiicult  to  decide  at  what  point 
we  are  to  trace  that  special  shade  of  feehng  which  may  be 
called  distinctly  moral.  The  difficulty  is  the  greater  because 
there  is  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  same  sentiment  exists 
in  all  members  of  a  eiven  society.  The  feelings  with  which 
they  regard  an  admittedly  wrong  action  may  vary  greatly 
according  to  individual  idiosyncrasies,  even  though  they  agree 
in  condemning  the  same  actions  or  admiring  the  same  quali- 
ties of  character.  This  appears  to  be  the  case  in  the  present 
instance.  When  asked  whether  courage  is  or  is  not  a  moral 
quality  in  the  strictest  sense,  we  must  reply  that  at  some 
periods  it  has  been  considered  as  not  only  a  virtue,  but  the 
typical  and  cardinal  virtue,  whilst  at  others  it  begins  to  be 
more  or  less  doubtful  whether  it  is,  properly  speaking,  a 
virtue  at  all;  while,  again,  very  different  answers  would  pro- 
bably be  given  upon  this  point  by  different  classes  of  persons. 
9.  Remembering  this,  let  us  ask  what  are  the  facts  as  to 
the  existino;  social  code.  If  coura(i;e  is  intrinsically  virtuous 
— if,  that  is,  the  bare  fact  that  a  man  is  brave  entitles  him  to 
be  called  virtuous  so  far — we  should  have  to  admit  that  every 
manifestation  of  courage  was  virtuous,  and  we  should  call  a 
man  o;ood  because  he  met  a  ticjer  unfiinchingly  when  he  was 
simply  engaged  in  sport.  This,  I  think,  would  be  rather  a 
strained  use  of  lan^uacre,  and  we  should  decline  to  admit  the 
goodness  unless  the  quality  was  exerted  for  benevolent  pur- 
poses; as,  for  example,  in  saving  the  life  of  one  of  the  tiger's 
victims.  But  in  the  latter  case  it  seems  that  it  is  not  in 
respect  of  his  courage  that  the  man  is  called  virtuous,  but  in 
respect  of  his  unselfishness  or  benevolence.  Thus,  to  take  a 
further  case,  we  feel  it  to  be  a  perfectly  justifiable  form  of 
expression  when  Clarendon  speaks  of  Cromwell  as  a  "  bold, 
bad  man."  Courage,  we  admit,  may  be  combined  with 
objectionable  qualities,  such  as  tyranny  and  hypocrisy.  Shall 
we  then  consider  courage  is  to  be  in  itself  a  morally 
neutral  qualitv,  which  is  good  or  bad  according  to  the  other 
qualities  with  which  it  is  associated,  and  thus  as  simjily  an 
intensitive?     In   that  case,  we  ouo:ht  in  consistency  to  dis- 


1 82  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

like  the  bad  man  more  in  proportion  to  his  courage,  in  so 
far  as  it  makes  him  a  more  mischievous  person.  This 
certainly  does  not  represent  our  ordinary  mode  of  feeling. 
The  admission  of  courage  qualifies  our  dislike.  We  respect 
the  brave  man,  so  far  as  brave,  not  only  if  he  is  an  enemy  by 
virtue  of  accidental  circumstances,  but  even  if  he  is  a  bad 
man  by  the  intrinsic  quality  of  character.  Thus,  if  our 
judgment  of  Cromwell  coincides  with  Clarendon's,  we  feel 
that  our  moral  disapproval  is  tempered  by  a  certain  admira- 
tion; we  feel  that,  as  brave,  he  is  less  hateful,  even  though  he 
may  be  more  mischievous  than  if  he  had  combined  his  other 
bad  qualities  with  cowardice.  We  regret  that  he  had  not 
better  principles  instead  of  regretting  that  he  had  so  much 
vio;our.  This  is  virtually  to  admit  that  in  so  far  as  a  man  is 
brave  he  is  approved  by  the  general  feeling,  although  the 
approval  is  not  exactly  of  the  kind  which  we  call  moral.  If 
we  speak  of  some  distinctly  moral  quality,  the  implicit 
reasoning  would  be  different.  Charles  I.,  let  us  assume,  was 
chaste  but  tyrannical.  In  so  far  as  he  was  chaste  he  deserves 
moral  approval,  and  in  so  far  as  tyrannical,  moral  disapproval. 
We  have  to  settle  the  balance  by  conflicting  considerations. 
But  in  the  case  of  a  Cromwell,  the  respect  which  we  feel  for 
his  courage  does  not  serve  to  qualify  the  moral  verdict,  but 
to  represent  a  feeling  which  is  intermediate  between  that  of 
moral  approbation  and  simple  admiration  for  an  endowment, 
physical  strength  and  beauty,  for  example,  which  has  no 
definite  relation  to  moral  judgment  at  all.  It  may  be  just 
worth  while  to  add,  that  the  difference  cannot  be  explained 
by  saying  that  courage  is  a  simple  property  which  does  not 
involve  "  free  will,"  or  is  incapable  of  being  modified  by  the 
approval  of  others.  How  far  this  consideration  affects  our 
moral  judgment  need  not  be  considered  here,  inasmuch  as  it 
obviously  does  not  apply  to  this  case.  There  is  no  quality 
which  is  more  imminently  amenable  to  opinion.  The  special 
characteristic  of  the  warrior  has  always  been  taken  to  be  his 
thirst  for  <rlory,  and  the  fact  that  courage  can  be  generated 
by  discipline  is  one  of  the  most  familiar  of  observations. 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  183 

10.  It  is,  in  factj  easy  to  put  a  logical  interpretation  upon 
the  verdict  of  common  sense;  for  it  virtually  asserts  that 
courage  is  a  quality  which  is  useful  to  society;  that  it  there- 
fore forms  a  part  of  the  good  man's  character;  and  thus 
that  to  call  a  man  a  good  coward  involves  some  inconsis- 
tency, although  it  is  not  inconsistent  to  speak  of  a  bad  brave 
man.  Hence  courage  may  be  regarded  as  one  of  the  neces- 
sary conditions  of  ideal  excellence,  though  its  possession  does 
not  necessarily  imply  the  fulfilment  of  any  other  conditions. 
To  be  good,  you  must  be  brave ;  but  you  may  be  brave 
without  being  good.  And  therefore  when  we  see  courage 
united  to  wickedness,  we  reo;ard  the  a2:ent  as  in  some  degree 
qualified  for  our  approval,  though  for  a  kind  of  approval 
differino;  from  that  reserved  for  what  we  call  virtue  in  the 
most  eminent  degree.  And  the  principle  involved  is  ob- 
vious, namely,  that  courage  does  not  imply  necessarily  a 
use  of  faculties  for  the  good  of  others.  In  rude  states  of 
society,  as  we  have  seen,  this  is  necessarily  (or  almost  neces- 
sarily) the  case,  inasmuch  as  the  individual  is  so  closely  iden- 
tified with  his  tribe,  the  objects  of  his  animosity  are  so  certain 
to  be  the  objects  dangerous  to  his  fellows,  that  to  be  brave  is 
to  be  socially  useful.  But  as  society  develops  we  see  that 
the  necessity  is  external ;  that  is,  dependent  upon  a  state  of 
things  which  does  not  always  exist  in  the  higher  stages ;  and 
hence  we  make  a  distinction,  and  whilst  still  admiring 
courage,  we  scarcely  regard  it  with  that  specific  kind  of 
admiration  reserved  for  qualities  which,  by  their  verv  nature, 
must  be  useful  to  others  than  the  ag-ent. 

11.  Let  us  now  consider  for  a  moment  the  nature  of  the 
process  thus  described.  It  supposes  the  development  of  a 
complex  organisation  and  the  growth  of  correlative  instincts. 
The  primitive  society  depends  at  every  instant  upon  the 
military  prowess  of  its  members.  Respect  for  the  good 
fighter  and  contempt  for  the  bad,  respect,  therefore,  for 
courage  and  contempt  for  cowardice,  as  the  most  obvious 
conditions  of  good  and  bad  fighting,  appear  as  soon  as  the 
simplest  reflection  is  possible.     And  this  sentiment  tends  to 


1 84  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

persist,  however  formed  originally,  inasmuch  as  every  one 
from  childhood  imhibes  the  habitual  modes  of  thought  and 
feeling  of  the  social  medium.  But  social  development  im- 
plies a  process  of  at  least  implicit  reasoning,  which  modifies 
the  early  assumptions.  The  chivalrous  sentiment  grows  as 
hostilities  cease  to  be  internecine  and  sympathy  extends 
beyond  the  limits  of  the  community.  Courage,  again,  takes 
a  different  form  as  men  come  to  reco2;nise  the  distinction 
between  the  higher  and  lower  forms  of  the  quality,  and  feel 
the  advantage  of  discipline  and  subordination.  Again,  as 
the  demand  for  warlike  excellence  declines,  courage  is  valued 
so  far  as  it  can  be  combined  with  the  full  development  of 
peaceful  eneroies  and  instincts.  Finally,  as  men  come  to 
distinguish  between  the  qualities  which  are  essentially  useful 
to  society  and  those  which  may  be  combined  with  anti-social 
qualities,  they  regard  courage  with  a  sentiment  differing  from 
that  which  is  reserved  for  the  more  directly  social  virtues. 
The  process  may  therefore  be  regarded  as  a  prolonged  induc- 
tion, starting  by  a  condemnation  of  certain  actions  plainly 
mischievous  to  the  society,  and  ending  by  the  recognition  of 
a  certain  type  of  character  as  admirable,  which  includes 
amongst  its  attributes  a  capacity  for  the  conduct  actually 
admired,  but  which  also  includes  fitness  for  conduct  of  a 
different  kind.  Courage  is  now  regarded  as  one  manifestation 
of  a  character  which  is  fitted  for  all  the  requirements  of  social 
existence.  But  as  it  may  be  turned  against  society,  we  scarcely 
regard  the  brave  man  as  therefore  virtuous,  but  rather  as 
satisfying  one  of  the  conditions  necessary  to  virtue.  Thus 
the  process  implies  the  elaboration  of  a  more  complete  defini- 
tion of  the  type  necessary  to  the  constitution  of  a  vigorous 
society,  and  thus  the  recognition  of  certain  external  rules  of 
conduct, — that,  for  example,  which  prohibits  running  away 
in  battle,  as  defining  particular  manifestations  of  the  typical 
character  under  specified  conditions,  and  deriving  their  validity 
from  the  more  general  condition  of  social  fitness. 

13.  Hence  this  statement  suggests  a  question  which  requires 
a  distinct  answer.     Courage  in  all  its  phases  is  a  condition 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  185 

of  social  vitality.  The  spirit  in  which  a  race  confronts  danger 
must  be  always  one  criterion  of  its  power  of  holding  its  own. 
But  we  may  still  ask  how  far  the  approval  is  generated  by  a 
perception  of  this  fact.  Is  courage  admired  simply  because 
it  is  useful  or  because  it  is  seen  to  be  useful  ?  We  have 
obviously  no  right  to  assume  a  perception  in  all  cases.  The 
average  man  accepts  without  reflection  the  standard  of  his  race. 
The  warrior  may  hate  the  coward  as  he  hates  the  harmless 
necessary  cat,  without  seeking  a  reason  for  his  aversion.  We 
may  therefore  explain  the  sentiment  in  any  given  case  by 
savinor  that  the  man  has  derived  it  from  his  neighbours.  But 
thisj  of  course,  is  no  explanation  of  the  whole  phenomenon. 
To  explain  this  we  must  go  back  to  the  history  of  the  race. 
The  courage  of  an  animal  is  "explained"  by  the  fact  that  it 
is  necessary  under  the  conditions  of  his  life.  The  courage 
of  the  bulldog  is  a  blind  instinct;  the  blindness  implying, 
not  that  he  is  without  feeling  of  pain,  or  even  perception  of 
danger,  for  otherwise  we  could  hardly  speak  of  him  as  brave, 
but  that  danger  or  pain  does  not  affect  him  as  it  affects  a 
cur,  and  that  he  holds  fast  when  the  cur  lets  go.  Such  an 
instinct  may  of  course  exist,  and  must  exist,  in  the  unreason- 
ing animal  in  the  absence  of  any  reasoned  calculation  of 
consequences.  The  creature  survives  by  reason  of  his  instinct, 
but  not  because  he  forms  any  conscious  judgment  of  the 
advantages  of  this  mode  of  conduct.  And  when  we  rise  to 
the  reasoning  agent,  we  may  still  ask  whether  the  utility  of  a 
given  character  implies,  or  in  what  sense  it  implies,  a  percep- 
tion of  the  utility?  The  distinction  requires  to  be  noticed, 
inasmuch  as  certain  ambiguities  result  from  a  neglect  to  take 
it  into  account. 

13.  Now  it  seems  necessary  to  suppose  that  races  owed 
their  survival  to  military  prowess  when  reflection  was  still  in 
the  most  rudimentary  stage.  The  utility  of  courage,  indeed, 
must  have  been  a  very  obvious  discovery  as  soon  as  any 
reflection  became  possible.  No  condition  of  the  preservation 
of  a  community  could  be  so  palpable  or  pressed  by  such 
constant  and  repeated  experience  upon  the  attention  of  its 


i86  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

iiienibers.  They  could  see  every  day  that  their  existence 
depended  upon  the  readiness  to  confront  danger.  But  the 
quahty  must  have  existed  in  some  degree  before  it  could  be 
discovered,  and  therefore  it  would  be  inaccurate  to  speak  as 
though  the  approved  of  courage  were  the  result  of  an  antecedent 
perception  that  certain  advantages  were  attainable  by  courage. 
Men  came  to  recognise  the  advantages  already  obtained  by 
the  brave,  and  the  recognition  tended  to  intensify  as  also  to 
modify  the  sentiment  already  implicitly  existing.  Every 
increase  of  reasoning  power  would  bring  out  more  fully  the 
importance  to  the  race  and  to  the  individual  of  courage, 
coolness,  and  resource  in  danger.  The  existence  of 'any 
distinct  moral  sentiment  doubtless  implies  some  reflection, 
and  there  could  hardly  be  a  social  approval  or  disapproval 
until  men  were  capable  of  observing  consequences.  The 
approval  may  be,  in  that  sense,  the  product  of  the  per- 
ception ;  but,  on  the  other  hand,  the  perception  implies 
that  the  instinct  approved  was  already  in  existence.  The 
race  has  a  certain  deg:ree  of  coura^'e,  and  must  be  so  constituted 
that,  in  point  of  fact,  the  courage  of  one  is  useful  to  others, 
before  the  conscious  recognition  of  the  fact,  and  before  the 
definite  emergence  of  a  social  approval.  The  difference  is 
that  in  the  higher  stages  of  development  the  fact  becomes  a 
recotrnised  fact.  The  other  instincts  are  not  only  interested, 
but  their  interests  are  perceived.  Formerly  they  were  interested 
as  slaves  may  be  interested  in  the  success  of  their  owner ;  now 
as  free  men  whose  opinions  have  to  be  consulted.  As  reflec- 
tion develops,  men  come  to  have  a  wider  perception  of  the 
bearing  of  their  conduct  in  every  direction,  and  this  per- 
ception modifies  the  actions  and  instincts ;  but  it  must 
always  start  from  a  pre-existing  organisation  of  character 
and  society. 

14.  And  hence  we  mav  state  more  precisely  the  sense  in 
which  the  notion  of  courage  is  a  statement  of  the  general 
conditions  of  social  vitality.  The  problem  is  more  complex 
than  appears  at  first  sight.  It  has,  we  may  say,  a  double 
aspect.      The  "  utility  "  of  courage,  meaning  by  utility  the 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  187 

fact  that  the  braver  race  is  so  far  the  better  qualified  for  the 
struLi'o-le  of  existence,  is  in  all  cases  the  cause  of  the  survival- 
of  the  instinct.  That  is  equally  true  whether  we  speak  of  a 
blind  or  a  reasoned  instinct,  of  the  bulldog  or  of  the  hero, 
and  gives  the  general  principle  applicable  at  every  stage  of 
the  process  of  evolution.  The  principle  applies  to  the  parti- 
cular case  of  the  reasoned  instinct  developed  through  the 
social  factor,  and  sioverns  it  as  the  general  rule  governs  the 
special  application.  The  instincts  of  any  race  must  comply 
with  the  conditions  of  its  existence,  and  this  must  be  true 
as  well  of  the  instincts  which  imply  a  perception  of  utility. 
The  approval  of  any  conduct  as  useful  must  itself  be  useful, 
if  the  race  is  to  survive. 

15.  The  necessity  of  calling  attention  to  this  distinction  is 
already  manifest.  For,  in  the  first  place,  the  conditions  do 
not  at  present  appear  to  be  necessarily  coincident.  Courage, 
we  say,  is  useful;  or  is,  in  other  words,  a  condition  of  the 
existence  of  the  race.  So  far  as  the  race  becomes  conscious 
of  this  fact,  the  same  condition  applies  to  this  consciousness. 
The  consciousness,  that  is,  that  courage  is  useful  to  the  race 
must  stimulate  courage.  Now  it  may  appear  that  this  is 
not  a  necessary  result  of  .increased  intelligence.  If,  in  fact, 
we  suppose  the  intellect  to  become  keener  without  any 
increased  desire  for  social  welfare,  which  is  clearly  possible  in 
individual  cases,  the  clearer  perception  of  the  social  utility  of 
courage  could  onlv  stimulate  it  in  cases  where  the  interest  of 
the  individual  was  identical  with  that  of  his  fellows.  It 
might  then,  on  the  average,  produce  cowardice,  or  a  desire  of 
each  to  save  himself  whenever  he  could  do  so  at  the  expense 
of  his  fellows.  In  that  case,  increased  intelligence  would 
operate  so  far  to  the  disadvantage  of  the  race,  as  the  stupider 
and  therefore  bolder  races  would  have  a  better  chance  of 
survival.  Something  of  this  kind  seems  occasionally  to 
happen.  Looking,  indeed,  at  the  facts,  and  observing  that 
the  more  intelligent  races  have  an  advantage,  and  not  least 
in  this  quality,  we  must  infer  that  the  general  principle 
operates   differently.      Evolution   affects   the   whole   nature  3 


l88  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

and  we  may  suppose  that  those  races  are  most  successful 
which  are  so  constituted  that  a  perception  of  the  vitaHty  of 
courage  goes  along  with  an  increase  of  courage.  This,  how- 
ever, seems  to  imply  an  additional  condition.  The  race 
must  not  simply  become  more  intelligent,  but  become  more 
intelligent  in  such  a  way  that  its  social  qualities  improve 
along  with  its  intellectual.  The  bare  extension  of  a  percep- 
tion of  consequences  might  of  itself  tend  only  to  more 
calculated  selfishness,  and  therefore  a  diminished  disposition 
to  fulfil  the  conditions  of  social  welfare.  It  may  appear  that 
in  the  normal  case,  at  least,  the  intellectual  advance  implies  a 
development  of  the  social  sympathies;  but  that  cannot  be 
taken  for  granted  at  present. 

i6.  There  is,  however,  in  the  second  place,  a  further  con- 
sideration. It  is  clear  from  the  nature  of  the  process  described 
that  there  must  be  a  close  coincidence  between  the  qualities 
which  are  valued  and  those  which  are  actually  useful.  Each 
man  and  generation  of  men  starts  with  a  sentiment^  elabo- 
rated bv  the  race  and  embodied  in  the  accepted  rules  of 
conduct.  The  most  important  are  worked  into  the  very  struc- 
ture of  the  lantruaofe  and  inG;rained  in  the  organic  customs 
of  society.  Respect  for  courage,  in  particular,  has  become 
part  of  the  general  inheritance  and  profoundly  influences 
the  character  of  every  member  of  a  society  which  has  passed 
through  a  military  stage.  Now,  on  the  one  hand,  it  is  clear 
that  any  sentiment  thus  transmitted  through  the  social  factor, 
must  have  a  reference  to  the  conceptions  of  social  vitality. 
All  men  could  not  agree  to  admire  courage  unless  they  thought 
that  courage  was  useful, — useful,  that  is,  in  the  second  or 
subjective  sense,  namely,  of  generally  tending  to  procure 
happiness.  The  process  by  which  any  such  sentiment  is 
transmitted  and  diffused,  so  as  to  be  part  of  the  general  in- 
heritance of  the  race,  is  a  sufficient  guarantee  for  this.  Men 
may  agree  to  admire  qualities  which  make  their  possessor 
unhappy,  but  not  at  once  to  admire  a  quality  and  to  think 
that  it  diminishes  happiness  in  general.  The  perception 
that  a  quality  is  in  this  sense  useful  ov  feUcjJic  must  nearly 


VIRTUE  OF  COURAGE.  189 

coincide  with,  if  it  docs  not  generate,  the  admiration  felt  for 
the  quaUty;  and,  on  the  other  hand,  it  is  clear  that  the 
actual  utility  of  courao;e  will  n;enerate  admiration  as  soon  as 
the  fact  is  perceived.  If  the  existence  of  a  tribe  really  depends 
on  the  courage  of  its  members,  it  must  become  apparent  that 
in  numberless  special  cases  courage  preserves  the  lives  and 
happiness  of  all,  whilst  cowardice  is  fatal.  What  is  useful  as 
preservative  must  also  be  useful  in  the  sense  of  happiness-giving. 
Within  certain  limits  men  mav  reason  badlv,  and  even  the 
collective  reasoning  may  be  bad.  Courage  may  be  the  object 
of  an  extravagant  admiration  from  the  survival  of  prejudices 
generated  under  special  conditions,  or  a  temporary  absence  of 
danger  may  lower  the  estimate;  but  any  wide  deviation  from 
the  correct  judgment  will  be  rectified,  if  not  by  the  reason 
of  the  society,  then  by  the  operation  of  the  general  principle 
of  utility,  and  the  tendency  of  the  erring  society  to  disappear. 
This  principle,  therefore,  must  be  regarded  as  working,  not 
only  through  the  blind  and  more  or  less  unconscious  instinct 
of  the  lower  races,  but  upon  the  conscious  and  reflective 
judgments  of  the  most  highly  organised  society.  In  an  ideal 
state  there  would  be  an  absolute  coincidence.  The  society 
would  not  only  possess  those  instincts  which  are  necessary  to 
its  survival  and  vigour,  but  would  understand  precisely  how, 
in  what  respects,  and  under  what  conditions  or  limitations, 
they  were  necessary;  whilst  its  judgment  of  what  was  useful 
as  giving  happiness  would  precisely  coincide  with  its  judgment 
of  what  was  useful  as  preservative  of  its  existence. 

17.  These  remarks  are  of  course  applicable,  mutatis  mutandis, 
not  only  to  courage,  but  to  other  qualities,  such  as  industry, 
energy,  and  so  forth,  which  belong  to  the  same  class;  and, 
moreover,  as  we  shall  presently  see,  to  the  virtues  in  general. 
And  it  may  be  as  well  to  make  one  remark  before  finishing. 
The  ultimate  and  governing  principle  is  in  all  cases  the 
utility  of  the  quality,  in  the  sense  in  which  utility  means  fit- 
ness for  the  conditions  of  life.  The  scientific  explanation,  at 
any  rate,  cannot  get  beyond  an  exposition  of  the  essential  im- 
plication of  courage  in  the  general  conditions  of  social  life. 


I90  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

And  this  general  principle  may  operate  through  an  nnreason- 
ing  or  a  reasoned  instinct;  that  is,  through  the  instincts  of  a 
beino-  conscious  or  unconscious  of  their  value.  Now,  although 
morality  proper  is  only  possible  when  reflection  and  a  power 
of  o;rasping  general  rules  has  been  developed,  this  has  still  an 
application  even  to  the  higher  stages  of  social  growth.  For 
a  man,  or  even  a  race,  may  be  content  to  accept  the  instinct  as 
justifying  itself  without  seeking  to  discover  its  origin.  And, 
again,  a  moral  development  may  be  brought  about  either  by 
a  reasoning  or  unreasoning  process;  either  bv  a  process  of 
generalisation  and  the  conscious  aim  at  some  social  ideal 
implying  an  accurate  perception  of  the  conditions  of  life  ;  or, 
on  the  other  hand,  bv  some  "  accidental  "  change,  that  is,  by 
a  chano-e  orio-inatino;  in  other  conditions  than  those  of  in- 
tellectual 'growth,  as  when  the  extension  of  an  empire  forces 
peaceful  habits  upon  previously  hostile  tribes,  and  so  favours 
the  growth  of  tastes  and  pursuits  previously  impossible.  I 
need  not  now  inquire  which  is  the  normal  and  most  important 
case. 

III.   Virtue  of  Temperance. 

1 8.  Proceeding  to  the  virtues  typified  by  chastitv  and 
temperance,  we  have  first  to  remark  that  they  occupy  an 
intermediate  position  between  the  virtues  of  strenjrth  and  the 
directly  social  virtues.  Some  of  them  are  a  part  of  the 
prudential,  and  others  of  the  directly  moral  code.  Thus,  for 
example,  it  is  prudent  to  be  temperate  because  temperance 
is  necessarv  to  health.  Anv  rules  deduced  from  that  con- 
sideration  are  primarily  concerned  with  the  individual,  and 
interest  the  society  through  the  individual.  The  primary 
objection  to  drunkenness  is  that  it  injures  the  constitution, 
and  if  I  prove  from  purely  medical  considerations  that  certain 
drinks  are  injurious  and  others  innocuous,  the  rule  deduced 
is  a  law  of  prudence  and  consequently  a  part  of  morality.  It 
is  my  dutv,  it  mav  be  said,  to  maintain  my  health  unless 
some  other  moral  duty  accidentally  conflicts,  and  thus  the 
rules  for  framing  health  may  be  taken  up  into  the    moral 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  191 

code ;  but  they  are  deduced  without  reference  to  the  society 
from  the  simple  principle  that  whatever  increases  the  health 
of  each  man  is  so  far  a  matter  of  prudence.  The  society 
composed  of  healthy  men  is  so  far  better^  but  the  rule  is 
deduced  from  a  direct  consideration  of  the  individual,  and 
the  sanitarv  rule  coincides  with,  because  it  is  assumed  by, 
the  moral  rule.  That  is  right  which  is  health-preserving. 
But  another  class  of  these  virtues  is  directly  social.  In  fact, 
society  is  dependent  from  its  very  germ  upon  the  sexual  and 
parental  instincts  j  its  most  intimate  structure  depends  at 
every  moment  upon  the  way  in  which  they  are  regulated ; 
and  conduct,  which  from  the  sanitary  point  of  view  may  be 
perfectly  indifferent,  may  have  the  most  important  effects 
upon  the  social  organisation.  Temperance  in  eating  and 
drinking  is  a  dictate  of  simple  prudence,  which  has  no  need 
to  take  into  account  the  consequence  to  others;  but  chastity 
is  a  virtue  which  is  only  intelligible  when  we  take  into  account 
its  bearing  upon  the  vitality  of  the  social  organism. 

]  9.  Hence  we  have  a  moral  evolution  similar  to  the  former. 
Chastitv,  that  is,  some  modification  of  the  sexual  instincts 
imposed  by  the  social  sentiment,  is  implied  in  the  earliest 
sta<i;es  of  social  growth.  Society  is  constituted  by  the  develop- 
ment of  an  organic  custom  which  defines,  amongst  other 
things,  the  relations  of  the  sexes.  The  marriage  law  of  primi- 
tive times  differs  in  strange  and  unexpected  ways  from  that  of 
civilised  races,  but  it  implies  at  every  step  the  existence  of 
some  restraining  sentiment.  Sexual  rivalry  is  the  great  cause 
of  hostilitv  araoncrst  Yahoos;  whilst  the  state  and  the  familv 
are  barely  distinguished,  the  disputes  about  women  are  a 
main  cause  of  war.  The  formation  of  the  social  bond  implies 
the  formation  of  some  modus  vivendi  in  regard  to  such 
matters,  and  a  complex  system  of  rules  is  developed  at  a  very 
early  date.  Hence  the  external  rule  is  formed  before  a  more 
general  theory  of  the  passions  has  obtained  acceptance.  The 
first  law  is,  "  Thou  shalt  not  commit  adultery."  Little  atten- 
tion is  aroused  by  conduct  not  so  clearly  injurious.  The 
savage  sees  no  evil  in  gluttony,  and  intoxication  appears  to 


192  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

him  as  a  new  pleasure  revealed  by  the  civilised  man.  In  the 
higher  law  the  rule  is  extended,  and  applies  to  the  motive  as 
well  as  to  the  specific  action.  Lust  is  condemned  as  well  as 
adultery.  The  man  who  would  sin  if  he  could  is  seen  to  be 
as  objectionable  as  the  man  who  sins  because  he  can.  And 
the  condemnation  extends  itself  to  all  forms  of  sensuality  in 
virtue  of  the  general  principle  thus  elaborated,  as  their  effect 
upon  the  character  of  the  agent  and  their  remoter  conse- 
quences to  others  are  better  understood. 

20.  To  the  savage,  as  to  the  animal,  gluttony  scarcely 
appears  to  be  objectionable.  The  conduct  of  either  is  regu- 
lated by  his  appetite  without  any  conscious  reference  to 
general  principles.  The  force  and  the  nature  of  these  appetites 
are  determined  by  the  general  principle  of  utility.  The 
savage,  like  the  dog,  eats  when  he  is  hungry  and  drinks  when 
he  is  thirsty  without  regard  to  consequences.  If  his  appetites 
were  such  as  to  be  inconsistent  with  his  permanent  survival, 
he  would  die  out.  Therefore  his  instincts  are  correlated  by 
a  process  which  has  nothing  to  do  with  conscious  reflection. 
But  when  the  man  acquires  new  powers  by  incipient  civilisa- 
tion, the  conditions  of  his  life  are  altered.  He  is  able  if  he 
pleases  to  eat  and  drink  more  than  is  good  for  him.  If  the 
old  instincts  survived  and  were  not  restrained,  he  would 
speedily  eat  and  drink  himself  to  death.  They  may  grow 
weaker  in  virtue  of  some  physiological  principle,  but  they 
may  also  be  held  in  check  by  his  clearer  perception  of  the  evil 
consequences  of  indulgence.  In  the  latter  case  we  have  the 
arowth  of  a  moral  and  a  prudential  law.  The  reasoning  man 
does  not  require,  we  may  sav,  to  lose  the  appetite  because  he 
is  able  to  counterbalance  its  action  by  calling  other  forces 
into  plav.  He  sees  that  the  present  gratification  will  have  to 
be  paid  for  at  a  certain  rate  of  future  pain.  But  the  moral 
quality  of  the  rule  only  becomes  marked  when  there  is 
some  recognition  of  the  effects  to  others  than  himself.  Now 
it  becomes  evident  that  sensuality  generally  has  a  direct  bear- 
ing upon  the  social  qualities,  even  in  those  forms  which  are 
primarily  objectionable  on  prudential  grounds.     Courage  and 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  193 

enersrv  crenerallv  are  of  course  clearly  connected  with  tern- 
perance;  and  so  far  as  courage  is  regarded  as  a  virtue,  the 
slothfulness  and  indifference  which  spring  from  all  forms  of 
intemperance  incur  a  share  of  the  contempt  bestowed  upon 
the  quality  which  is  their  natural  fruit.  But,  on  the  other 
aspect,  they  have  a  more  intrinsic  bearing  upon  social  vitality 
than  the  virtues  of  streng-th.  The  brave  man  may  still,  as  I 
have  said,  be  a  thoroughly  bad  man ;  he  may  use  all  his 
energy  to  oppress  his  neighbours.  To  some  extent  this  is 
also  true  of  the  temperate  man,  but  the  connection  with 
the  social  qualities  is  more  direct  and  invariable.  So  far 
as  a  man  is  a  drunkard,  he  is  almost  necessarily  a  bad 
husband  and  father;  so  far  as  temperate,  he  is  free 
from  some  of  the  weaknesses  which  must  generally  dis- 
qualify him  from  acting  in  that  capacity.  Courage  and 
energy  may  often  be  essential,  and  are  generally  useful,  in  the 
discharge  of  the  duties  resulting  from  every  social  relation, 
but  they  are  not  so  closely  implicated,  and  for  a  reason  which 
becomes  obvious  as  men  become  more  intelligent.  Sensuality, 
that  is  to  say,  implies  selfishness.  A  man's  love  of  his 
bottle  is  so  much  deducted  from  his  love  of  his  wife  and 
children.  So  far  as  he  is  taken  up  with  the  gratification  of 
his  appetites,  there  is  less  room  for  the  development  of  his 
affections.  A  coward  and  a  sluggard  may  be  affectionate, 
though  his  affection  will  be  comparatively  useless  to  its 
objects,  but  in  a  sensual  character  the  affections  are  killed 
at  the  root.  He  is  incapable  of  really  loving  as  well  as  of 
beincj  useful  to  those  whom  he  loves.  And  thus  we  may  ex- 
plain  the  moral  verdict  passed  upon  certain  kinds  of  conduct 
which,  on  the  ordinary  judgment  of  common  sense,  are  classi- 
fied as  "  self-regarding."  The  most  conspicuous  evils  caused 
by  some  actions  are  produced  upon  the  man  himself.  People 
are  inclined  to  regard  them  as  breaches  of  prudence  rather 
than  of  morality.  The  intemperate  man,  according  to  the 
common  phrase,  is  an  enemy  to  no  one  but  himself.  We 
have,  as  we  fancy,  no  right  to  object  to  him  so  long  as  he 
only  makes  a  beast  of  himself  in  private.     In  some  cases, 

N 


194  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

again,  this  leads  to  the  production  of  a  kind  of  spurious 
moral  code.  People  admire  the  "  good  fellow "  as  thev 
admire  the  spendthrift,  because  the  immediate  and  obvious 
consequences  of  his  conduct  are  agreeable  to  his  neio;hbours. 
Convivial  relationship  generates  a  sort  of  law  of  its  own,  in 
virtue  of  which  the  person  who  drinks  fair  and  takes  his 
wine  like  a  man  is  admired,  partly  because  his  prowess  is  taken 
as  a  proof  of  vigour,  and  partly  because  he  is  "  sociable  "  in 
the  lower  sense  of  the  word,  and  is  therefore  assumed  to  be 
sociable  in  a  higher  sense.  As  the  reason  develops  it  be- 
comes clear  that  both  the  spendthrift  and  the  drunkard  are 
really  mischievous,  and  that  the  prevalence  of  the  conduct 
which  they  practise  is  a  mark  of  social  decav.  And,  more 
generally,  it  appears  that  we  make  a  false  estimate  when  we 
confine  our  attention  to  the  immediate  consequences  of  a 
man's  actions.  It  is  impossible  really  to  maintain  the  dis- 
tinction assumed.  A  man  whose  vice  injures  only  himself 
in  the  first  place,  becomes  also  by  a  necessarv  consequence 
incapable  of  benefiting  others.  If  he  is  an  enemy  to  himself 
alone,  he  is  also  a  friend  to  himself  alone.  The  opium-eater, 
for  example,  paralyses  his  will ;  so  far  as  he  becomes  in- 
capable of  energetic  action,  he  is  unfitted  for  every  social 
duty,  and  so  far  as  he  becomes  the  slave  of  his  appetite, 
becomes  also  unfitted  for  the  social  sentiments.  Thus  a 
distinctly  moral  sentiment  exists,  and  its  verdict  is  justified 
by  logic  in  cases  where  the  primary  effect  of  conduct  tells 
upon  the  agent  himself.  In  some  cases,  the  feeling  of 
disgust  and  abhorrence  is  perhaps  more  strongly  excited  bv 
such  vices  than  by  others  more  directly  anti-social.  And 
this  is  justified  by  the  consideration  already  explained  in 
a  different  connection.  As  we  condemn  the  man  whose 
character  is  bad,  whether  external  circumstances  do  or  do  not 
give  him  an  opportunity  for  displaying  it,  so  we  object 
logically  to  the  man  who  is  destroying  his  social  qualities, 
whether  the  immediate  effect  of  his  conduct  tells  upon  him- 
self or  upon  others.  He  must  be  defective  in  characteristics 
essential  to  the  moral  type. 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  195 

21.  So  far  the  case  seems  to  be  clear;  that  is,  the  moral 
law  does  in  fact  come  to  condemn  those  qualities  in  respect 
of  which  the  individual  deviates  from  the  type  prescribed 
by  the  conditions  of  social  welfare.  But  there  is  another 
characteristic  of  the  virtues  of  temperance  which  requires  a 
little  more  consideration.  In  the  first  place,  the  disgust 
which  we  feel  for  some  conduct  seems  to  be  inadequately 
explained  by  the  considerations  just  offered.  Undoubtedly 
the  condemnation  of  sensuality  goes  along  with  a  percep- 
tion of  the  many  and  complicated  social  evils  which  spring 
from  it,  and  implies  a  recognition  that  a  tendency  to  such 
indulgence  is  a  fatal  symptom  of  social  decay.  But  the 
feeling  of  disgust  seems  to  be  a  direct  product  of  what  we 
may  call  physiological  causes.  As  the  intellectual  sensibility 
becomes  keener,  a  pure-minded  person  is  revolted  by  the 
sensual  indulgence  of  the  grosser,  and  resents  the  attempt  to 
explain  his  disgust  by  a  simple  perception  of  the  mischiefs 
produced.  The  feeling  which  exists  in  a  healthy  state  of 
society  is  so  strong  and  immediate  that  it  seems  to  precede 
any  utilitarian  calculation  ;  and  I  may  add  that,  as  a  matter 
of  fact,  utilitarians  have  found  a  special  difficulty  in  account- 
ing for  or  justifying  the  strength  of  the  prevailing  sentiment, 
and  are  sometimes  inclined  to  relax  the  severity  of  the  code. 
Many  people  object  to  any  attempt  even  to  discuss  the 
question,  partly  because  they  feel  that  there  is  a  moral  danger 
in  even  talking  about  certain  subjects,  and  partly,  perhaps, 
because  they  are  afraid  that  their  prepossessions  may  not  be 
fully  justified. 

22.  This,  again,  seems  to  be  connected  with  another  pecu- 
liarity of  the  moral  judgment  in  this  direction.  I  speak  of 
the  ascetic  theories  which  at  different  times  acquire  so  much 
strength,  and  which  may  in  some  forms  appear  to  be  a  nega- 
tion of  the  very  principle  of  morality  as  I  have  stated  it. 
In  some  cases  the  natural  morality  of  a  race  appears  not  only 
to  condemn  intemperance — that  is,  an  excessive  addiction  to 
sensual  pleasures — but  condemns  sensual  pleasure  in  itself. 
It  regards  every  pleasure  of  the  kind  as  in  itself  bad^  although 


196  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

indulgence  may  be  permitted  under  certain  restrictions  as  a 
safecvuard  against  worse  evils.  Now  if  this  were  to  be  taken 
in  the  fullest  sense,  it  is  plain  that  it  would  condemn  conduct 
which  is  not  only  productive  of  pleasure,  but  which  is  abso- 
lutely essential  to  the  preservation  of  the  species;  and,  in  fact, 
men  are  admired  and  regarded  as  entitled  to  special  reverence 
for  a  complete  abstinence  from  some  of  the  functions  on 
which  society  depends.  The  virgin  and  the  hermit  are  re- 
garded as  admirable  because  they  withdraw  from  direct  parti- 
cipation in  social  and  domestic  pleasures  and  duties;  and 
thus,  though  moralists  have  laid  it  down  as  a  universal  rule 
of  morality  that  every  man  should  act  so  that  his  conduct 
may  be  a  rule  for  all,  yet  some  moralists  regard  action  as 
specially  admirable  which  cannot  be  a  rule  for  all.  It  would 
be  easy,  of  course,  to  reply  that  such  morality  is  really  im- 
moral;  that  it  implies  erroneous  reasoning,  and  would  there- 
fore be  condemned  by  the  right  reason;  or  that,  as  it  would 
diminish  happiness,  it  cannot  be  conducive  to  the  greatest 
happiness,  and  is  therefore  not  moral  according  to  the  proper 
definition  of  the  word.  But,  from  my  point  of  view,  this  is 
to  evade  the  question,  inasmuch  as  I  find  it  impossible  to 
deny  that  such  sentiments,  whether  right  or  wrong,  mis- 
chievous or  beneficial,  are  a  part  of  actual  morality — that  is, 
of  the  fundamental  rules  of  conduct  impressed  upon  the 
individual  by  the  race — and  therefore  require  to  be  explained 
instead  of  being  simply  denounced. 

•  23.  There  is  this  difficulty  in  every  explanation,  that  it  is 
by  no  means  easy  to  say  what  is  the  actual  judgment  in  such 
cases.  The  common  opinions  often  differ  widely  from  those 
of  authorised  expositors,  and  there  are  innumerable  devices 
by  which  doctrines  apparently  absurd  may  be  accommodated 
to  the  dictates  of  common  sense.  This  much,  however,  may 
perhaps  be  taken  for  granted  :  the  ascetic  theory  is  the  pro- 
duct of  a  luxurious  state  of  society — that  is,  of  a  state  in 
which  the  abuses  of  sensual  indulgence  have  become  specially 
prominent.  The  growth  of  a  rich  and  powerful  class  which 
uses  its  power  exclusively  for  its  own  enjoyment,  in  which 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  197 

great  men  plunge  themselves  into  sensuality  with  indifll-rence 
to  the  sufferings  of  their  dependants,  suggests  the  doctrine 
that  sensuality  is  the  great  enemy  of  mankind,  and  naturally 
suggests  an  exaggerated  statement  of  the  advantages  of  the 
opposite  character.  The  hest  teachers  see  that  the  passions 
are  strong  enough,  so  to  speak,  to  take  care  of  themselves ; 
there  is  not  the  least  danger  that  men  will  be  too  little  sen- 
sitive to  downright  animal  enjoyment;  and  therefore  they 
denounce  that  evil  unsparingly,  and  think  that  they  can  cut 
it  up  bv  the  roots  by  denouncing  the  source  of  mischief, 
without  supplying  those  qualifications  which  will  be  suffi- 
ciently supplied  by  the  facts. 

'  24.  Further,  it  is  to  be  remarked,  there  seems  to  be  a  kind 
of  tacit  recognition  of  the  flict  that  the  principle  has  a  limited 
application.  The  virtues  are  divided  into  two  classes — the 
ordinary  and  the  heroic,  A  man  is  held  to  have  fulfilled  the 
law  if  he  is  chaste  and  temperate  enough  not  to  indulge  in 
adultery  and  intoxication ;  but  he  has  done  something  more 
if  he  is  so  chaste  and  temperate  as  to  suppress  all  indulgence 
of  one  kind,  and  to  confine  the  other  within  the  limits  neces- 
sary for  the  support  of  life.  He  is  then  not  only  good,  but 
good  enough  for  two.  This,  again,  is  implied  in  the  theory 
of  merit.  Whatever  else  may  be  intended  by  that  word — 
which  will  have  to  be  considered  hereafter — it  recognises  in 
some  shape  a  certain  normal  standard  applicable  to  every 
man,  but  which  some  men  may  transcend,  and  by  transcend- 
ing acquire  merit.  Now  in  the  theological  doctrines  generally 
associated  with  the  theory  it  is  supposed  that  the  merit  thus 
acquired  is  in  some  way  useful  to  the  race.  It  propitiates 
the  gods,  and  makes  them  look  more  kindly  upon  the  followers 
of  the  saint.  The  man,  therefore,  who  possesses  heroic  virtue 
is  not  anti-social,  althou<rh  his  conduct  is  such  as,  if  universally 
adopted,  would  destroy  society.  He  is  rather  to  be  compared 
to  a  man  who  sacrifices  life  and  health  in  the  pursuit  of  some 
philanthropic  purpose,  and  in  this  sense  his  conduct  might  be 
approved  by  other  moralists.  We  may,  for  example,  think 
that  a   Howard    is  admirable,   although   he   neglects  duties 


198  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

which  must  be  performed  in  the  ordinary  case.  He  does 
more  good  in  this  particular  instance  by  improving  the  con- 
dition of  prisoners  than  by  attending,  for  example,  to  his  own 
affairs.  This,  however,  merely  admits  that  the  general  moral 
rule  of  benevolence  prescribes  different  conduct  according  to 
a  man's  special  opportunities  and  talents.  So  it  might  be 
admitted  by  all  moralists  that  in  special  cases  a  man  of  pecu- 
liar temperament  might  find  it  right  to  suppress  instincts 
which  should  generally  be  allowed  to  regulate  his  conduct. 
The  difference  would  only  be  that  such  suppression  would 
not  be  re2;arded  as  unconditionally  rioht,  or  as  establishin<r 
by  itself,  a  title  to  superior  respect. 

25.  It  seems,  therefore,  to  be  quite  possible  to  express  the 
ascetic  theory  in  a  form  which  is  consistent  with  a  reasonable 
conception  of  social  needs.  We  have,  in  fact,  only  to  say 
that,  in  a  condition  of  society  characterised  by  sensuality  and 
selfishness,  the  existence  of  men  capable  of  refusing  all  sensual 
gratification  may  be  of  the  highest  value,  if  only  as  a  demon- 
stration of  the  possibility  of  conquering  the  prevailing  passions. 
Further,  it  may  well  be  that  in  such  a  state  the  best,  and, 
so  far,  the  most  meritorious  men,  and  those  who  are  most 
sensitive  to  the  social  evils  of  the  time,  may  show  by  their 
lives  the  possibility  of  such  conquest,  and  may,  so  far,  deserve 
the  respect  of  their  fellows.  As  the  Red  Indian  proved  his 
courage  by  submitting  to  tortures,  the  saint  may  prove  his 
temperance  and  chastity  by  refusing  all  indulgence;  and 
such  examples  of  transcendent  virtue  may  tend  to  raise  the 
average  standard.  They  are  a  forcible  protest  in  flesh  and 
blood  against  the  tyranny  of  the  grosser  natures.  It  is  need- 
less to  dwell  upon  the  dangers  of  the  doctrine,  upon  the 
erroneous  assumptions  with  which  it  is  associated,  or  upon  the 
limitations  within  which  it  should  be  confined.  I  only  say 
that  it  is  so  far  perfectly  compatible  with  a  view  deduced 
from  general  considerations  of  social  welfare,  and  that  it 
errs  in  attributing  an  absolute  value  to  conduct  valuable  only 
under  certain  conditions.  So  lono;  as  these  conditions  are 
fulfilled  in  fact,  the  error  of  neglecting  their  importance  will 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  199 

not  lead  to  immediate  error ;  and  thus  an  instinct  which 
seems  to  neglect  all  reference  to  the  conditions  of  social  wel- 
fare mav,  in  fact,  be  the  direct  product  of  those  conditions. 
It  corresponds  to  the  disgust  produced  by  certain  evils  which 
arises  spontaneously,  and  does  not  imply  an  accurate  recog- 
nition of  the  true  nature  of  the  evils,  and  thus  condemns 
absolutelv  what  is  only  relatively  bad. 

26,  Hence  follows  a  conclusion  which  has  been  already 
noticed,  namelv,  that  the  general  condition  of  the  utility  of  a 
moral  sentiment  cannot  be  identified,  except  under  certain 
limitations,  with  the  condition  of  a  perception  of  utility  of 
the  corresponding  rule.  Thus,  when  we  speak  of  the  disgust 
produced  bv  certain  conduct,  and  proceed  to  ask  whether  the 
distrust  can  be  justified  by  the  presumed  consequences,  we 
sometimes  fall  into  a  perplexity.  Are  we  or  are  we  not  to 
take  into  account  as  amongst  those  consequences  the  disgust 
itself?  Is  the  offended  faculty  entitled  to  a  seat  on  the  bench, 
or  is  it  only  entitled  to  a  hearing  as  a  witness  ?  In  the  former 
case,  we  seem  to  be  falling  into  a  circular  argument  and 
makino-  the  instinct  its  own  justification.  In  the  latter,  we 
may  ask  whv  this  particular  kind  of  pain  should  be  less  re- 
garded than  any  other  in  estimating  the  total  consequences. 
The  answer,  I  think,  is  simple  from  a  right  point  of  view. 
When  we  say  that  conduct  or  instinct  is  bad,  we  clearly  make 
one  assumption,  namely,  that  it  can  be  eliminated,  and  that 
the  conduct  or  instinct  which  takes  the  place  of  that  con- 
demned "will  be  better.  When  I  say  that  vice  is  mischievous, 
I  must  mean  that,  on  the  whole,  and  taking  in  everything 
implied  in  a  change  assumed  to  be  possible,  the  temperate 
man  is  better  fitted  for  social  duties,  or,  which  is  the  same 
thincr,  that  a  society  formed  of  the  temperate  is  better  adapted 
for  persistence  than  a  society  formed  of  the  vicious.  It  is  a 
manifest  fallacy  if  I  compare  the  two  things  only  in  respect 
of  a  particular  set  of  differences  which  happen  to  be  con- 
spicuous on  the  surface,  or  if  I  fail  to  make  a  real  comparison 
between  possible  states,  and  therefore  make  a  false  assumption 
as  to  the  true  alternatives. 


200  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

27.  Now,  in  the  case  before  us,  let  us  consider  some  vice, 
sav  gluttony,  which  is  specially  contemptible,  but  which 
would  perhaps  generally  be  classed  as  self-regarding,  inasmuch 
as  it  does  not  imply  the  existence  of  malice  and  direct  attacks 
upon  others.  To  estimate  the  evil  of  gluttony  fairly,  I  must 
compare  the  gluttonous  man,  including  all  that  is  implied  in 
glutton,  with  the  temperate  man.  If  I  try  to  sum  up  the 
consequences  of  gluttony,  I  shall  probably  think  first  of  the 
evils  to  health,  of  the  consequences  in  the  shape  of  gout, 
indigestion,  and  so  forth.  But  this  gives  a  very  imperfect 
measure  of  the  social  evils  of  gluttony.  The  difference  be- 
tween the  glutton  and  the  temperate  man  is  not  that  one  is 
more  exposed  than  the  other  to  certain  diseases,  or  that  in 
consequence  of  the  diseases  he  is  less  capable  of  strenuous 
activity.  It  is  also  that  the  man  who  is  a  slave  of  his  belly 
is  less  capable  of  all  the  higher  affections,  of  intellectual 
pleasures  or  aesthetic  and  refined  enjoyments,  and  presum- 
ably selfish  and  incapable  of  extensive  sympathies.  If^  then, 
my  disapproval  of  gluttony  is  measured  by  the  first  set  of 
consequences  alone,  it  is  manifestly  inadequate.  It  is  as 
though  my  estimate  of  the  evils  due  to  a  disease  were  con- 
fined to  certain  special  symptoms,  and  not  to  the  total  con- 
stitutional state  implied.  As  a  matter  of  fact,  the  senti- 
ment actually  entertained  for  the  gluttonous  man  includes 
an  element  which  is  not  measurable  by  the  estimate  of  the 
imprudence  implied  in  gluttony,  nor  of  the  general  incapacita- 
tion which  may  be  the  most  conspicuous  result.  It  is  rather 
an  intrinsic  feelino;  due  to  the  conflict  between  the  hioher  and 
the  lower  type,  a  spasm  of  disgust  which  is  produced  as 
directly  as  the  rising  of  the  gorge  at  any  offensive  object.  The 
sight  of  the  human  hog  revolts  us,  as  we  should  sav,  simply 
because  he  is  a  hog,  and  the  smell  of  the  stye  turns  our 
stomachs.  Wherever  such  an  intrinsic  feelino;  exists,  it 
cannot  be  justified  by  summing  up  the  "  conse(juences"  in 
the  manner  described.  It  is  a  feeling  as  much  as  any  other 
which  so  far  justifies  itself,  that  the  pains  and  pleasures  due 
to  it  must  be  reckoned  in  our  calculation.     But  this  does  not 


VIRTUE  OF  TEMPERANCE.  201 

imply  that  this  intrinsic  feeUng  or  instinct  is  not  to  be 
measured  bv  a  standard  derived  from  the  general  principle  of 
utility.  When  we  ask  whether  it  is  useful,  we  do  not  mean 
to  ask  whether  it  implies  a  right  estimate  of  the  other  conse- 
quences of  the  conduct — that  is,  of  the  collateral  results  which 
are  offensive  to  other  instincts ;  for  this  is  virtually  to  assume 
that  it  has  no  independent  existence,  but  is  only  a  special 
application  of  those  instincts  to  the  foreseen  consequences. 
We  must  also  ask  whether  it  is  useful  in  the  sense  of  being 
a  necessary  part  of  the  higher  type  of  character.  As  men 
become  more  intellectual,  sympathetic,  and  so  forth,  they 
gain  fresh  sensibilities,  which  are  not  simple  judgments  of 
consequences  hitherto  improved,  but  as  direct,  imperative, 
and  substantial  as  anv  of  the  primitive  sensibilities.  Hence 
the  justification  of  the  instinct  is  not  that  it  implies  a  judg- 
ment of  what  is  useful,  but  rather  that  it  is  a  useful  judgment. 
To  get  rid  of  the  sensibility  you  must  lower  the  whole  tone 
of  the  character  or  destroy  the  perception  of  consequence. 
Therefore  some  such  sentiment  is  essential  to  social  develop- 
ment, though  it  is  difficult  or  impossible  to  obtain  any  accurate 
measure  of  the  desirable  strength.  That  is  a  problem  which 
can  onlv  be  worked  out  by  actual  experiment. 

28.  This  would  appear  to  follow  psychologically  from  the 
fact  that  the  excess  in  question  (and  this  is  of  course  equally 
applicable  to  other  sensual  excesses)  is  itself  prompted  by  a 
direct  instinct.  It  is  a  morbid  development  of  a  certain 
appetite ;  and  it  would  seem  that  the  disgust  which  we  feel 
for  the  excesses  of  others  is  a  direct  result  of  the  correlative 
impulse  in  ourselves.  We  are  shocked  by  the  excess  of  the 
glutton,  because  our  imagination  is  revolted  when  we  put 
ourselves  in  his  place,  and  fancy  ourselves  consuming  the 
same  monstrous  masses  of  food.  The  question  of  the  degree 
in  which  it  is  desirable  to  cultivate  this  instinct  must  be  diffi- 
cult, because  every  direct  instinct  is  in  its  nature  incapable 
of  such  measurement.  When  we  are  estimating  the  conse- 
quences of  conduct  in  the  ordinary  sense,  we  may  sometimes 
have  an,available  test.    We  are  asking  whether  the  pain  given. 


202  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

for  example,  by  an  attack  of  gout  is  greater  or  less  than  the 
pleasure  of  a  series  of  good  dinners,  and  we  may  conceive  at 
least  that  in  some  cases  the  sum  is  fairly  easy,  and  admits  of 
some  approximate  estimate.  But  when  we  ask  whether  a 
certain  instinct  is  on  the  whole  useful,  and  in  what  degree,  we 
are  really  asking  the  enormously  complex  problem  whether 
the  man  who  has  it,  together  with  all  that  is  implied  in  it,  is 
on  the  whole  a  better  or  worse  member  of  society  than  the 
man  who  has  it  not,  together  with  all  that  is  implied  in  its 
absence.  It  is  clearly  impossible  to  reduce  the  comparison 
between  two  organisms  to  any  direct  process  of  calculation, 
though  we  may  at  least  attempt  to  calculate  the  quantities 
of  happiness  in  two  different  sets  of  actions ;  and  hence  it 
follows  that  the  strenirth  of  the  instinctive  emotions  of  dis- 
o-ust  which  we  have  been  considering-  mav  varv  widely  with- 
out  being  capable  of  immediate  regulation  by  any  reasoning 
process.  This  may  go  to  explain  why  the  disgust  excited  by 
particular  vices,  or,  again,  the  admiration  for  their  contraries 
implied  in  the  aesthetic  theories  of  morality,  is  apt  to  deviate 
very  widely  from  any  assignable  measure  of  immediate  utility. 

IV.  Virtue  of  Truth. 

29.  I  may  now  proceed  to  the  virtues  which  are  in  some 
respects  at  the  opposite  pole.  It  needs  no  demonstration  that 
some  regard  for  truth  is  implied  in  the  simplest  social  state. 
Lano-uao-e  is  at  once  the  product  of  society,  and  essential  to 
anvthing  that  can  be  called  society.  No  mutual  understand- 
ino-  can  exist  without  a  communication  of  thought  of  which 
language  is  the  most  perfect  and  the  indispensable  instru- 
ment. To  say  that  language  is  necessary  is  to  say  that  truth 
is  necessarv,  for  otherwise  we  should  speak  of  signs  which 
have  no  signification.  Lving  itself  is  only  possible  when 
some  degree  of  mutual  understanding  has  been  reached,  and 
truthfulness  is  therefore  an  essential  condition  of  all  social 
development.  Yet  even  the  virtue  of  truth  is  often  recog- 
nised sraduallv  and  with  many  limitations.     As  tlie  law  of 


VIRTUE  OF  TRUTH.  203 

chastity  takes  the  form,  "  Thou  shalt  not  commit  adultery," 
the  law  of  truth  appears  in  the  form,  "  Thou  shalt  not  bear 
false  witness."  l^hose  lies  are  forbidden  which  are  palpably- 
injurious  to  our  neighbours.  The  imperfect  respect  enter- 
tained for  truth  in  general  is  indicated  by  the  practice  of 
judicial  oaths.  This  seems  to  imply  a  kind  of  tacit  assump- 
tion that  the  duty  requires  some  extrinsic  sanction.  We 
might  suppose  the  wickedness  of  taking  away  a  man's  life  by 
a  false  statement  to  be  so  obvious  that  a  man  restrainable  by 
no  other  motive  would  hardly  be  influenced  by  the  sanctity  of 
an  oath.  The  fact,  therefore,  that  oaths  are  regarded  as  effica- 
cious in  such  cases  shows  the  faintness  of  the  average  sen- 
sibility to  the  virtue.  Lying  to  an  enemy,  again,  is  often 
regarded  as  at  least  pardonable,  even  when  cruelty  is  seen  to 
be  wrono-.  The  obliiration  to  truthfulness  is  limited  to  rela- 
tions  with  members  of  the  same  tribe  or  state;  and,  more 
generallv,  it  is  curious  to  observe  how  a  kind  of  local  or 
special  morality  is  often  developed  in  regard  to  this  virtue. 
The  schoolboy  thinks  it  a  duty  to  his  fellows  to  lie  to  his 
master,  the  merchant  to  his  customer,  and  the  servant  to  his 
employer;  and,  inversely,  the  duty  is  often  recognised  as 
between  members  of  some  little  clique  or  profession,  as  soon 
as  it  is  seen  to  be  important  for  their  corporate  interest,  even 
at  the  expense  of  the  wider  social  organisation.  There  is 
honour  among  thieves,  both  of  the  respectable  and  other 
varieties.  So  the  agreement  of  gamblers  to  pay  debts  of 
honour  and  the  respect  paid  to  hospitality  in  rude  countries 
are  familiar  instances  of  the  growth  of  a  partial  morality, 
wherever  it  is  plainly  the  interests  of  a  class  to  have  a  mutual 
understanding.  Finally,  it  may  be  noticed  that  truthfulness 
in  the  highest  sense  must  be  of  slow  development  because 
only  partially  intelligible.  The  child  cannot  lie  because  it 
cannot  speak  the  truth;  so  long,  that  is,  as  it  is  unable  to 
distinguish  bet\Veen  the  creations  of  its  own  fancy  and  the 
facts  perceived  in  the  external  world.  Telling  stories  has 
for  it  the  ambio;uous  sense  of  Ivino;  or  relatino;  avowed  fiction. 
In  the  same  way  it  appears  that  the  infantile  man  produces 


204  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

myths  and  fables,  and  all  manner  of  superstitious  beliefs, 
without  a  distinct  perception  of  the  diiference  between 
imaci"ination,  hypothesis,  and  historical  statement.  Fiction 
in  the  modern  sense  and  downriirht  Ivino;  have  the  same  root, 
and  only  come  to  be  clearlv  differenced  at  a  comparatively 
advanced  stage.  The  inheritance  of  such  figments,  especially 
in  the  matter  of  religious  belief,  continues  to  perplex  men's 
minds.  The  virtue  of  philosophical  truthfulness  is  only  now 
obtaining  recognition,  and  the  process  by  which  it  has  won 
recoirnition  is  an  interestino;  illustration  of  the  general 
principle. 

30.  It  is  easily  perceived   that  an  erroneous  belief  is  in- 
jurious to  society,  and  there  is  a  tacit  recognition  of  this  in 
the  conviction  that  a  man  who  insults  the  god  of  his  tribe 
mav  bring  down  evil  upon  his  tribesmen.     As  moral  rules 
are  implicated  with  theological  beliefs,  indifference  to  either 
implies  indifference   to   the   other;    nothing,   then,   is  more 
natural  than  the  hatred,  and  consequently  the  persecution, 
of  the  heretic.     The  chan<re  is  chiefly  brou2:ht  about  bv  the 
slow    perception    that   a   man's    beliefs    are    accidental    and 
dependent  upon  his  social   surroundings,  and  that  the  man 
himself,  therefore,  is  estimable  so  far  as  he  is  sincere,  not  so 
far  as  his  conclusions  are  right.     Even  at  a  very  late  period 
the  enunciation  of  that  simple  principle  was  regarded  with 
horror,  and  it  has  come  to  be  admitted  only  by  the  accunui- 
latins:  evidence  which  has  demonstrated   that  the  difference 
between  the  orthodox  and  the  heterodox  does  not  coincide 
with  that  between  good  and   bad.     Yet  the  process  is  still 
so  imperfect  that  the  virtue  of  toleration  is  still  considered 
rather  as  an  external  than  an  internal  rule.     It  is  generally 
admitted  that  persecution  is  a  blunder,  as  it  is  admitted — 
by  many  people,  at  least — that  protection  is  a  blunder;  but 
everybody  allows  that  a  good  man  may  be  a  protectionist, 
inasmuch  as  the  evil   consequences  are  not*  so  manifest  to 
all  understandings  that  an  advocacy  of  protection  necessarily 
implies  indifference  to  the  welfare  of  the  race.     In  the  same 
way  the  persecutor  may  have  been  deluded  as  to  the  eflect 


VIRTUE  OF  TRUTH.  205 

of  his  measures  rather  than  deficient  in  sympathy  with  his 
kind.  The  growth,  however,  of  an  adequate  perception  of 
the  value  of  truthfuhiess  in  its  highest  sense  would  make  this 
impossible.  A  thorough  conviction  that  the  welfare  of  the 
race  depends  upon  its  intrinsic  character,  and  not  upon  the 
special  results  attained  in  any  given  stage  of  inquiry,  would 
show  that  persecution  was  necessarily  injurious  to  the  inte- 
rests of  the  society,  and  therefore  confine  the  practice  to  those 
who  were  indifferent  to  such  injurv.  As  the  respect  paid  to 
courajre  comes  to  be  sjiven  equallv  to  the  man  who  fi(::hts  on 
our  side  or  against  us,  in  consequence  of  the  accidents  of 
position,  so  we  should  respect  truthfulness  whether  the  results 
obtained  were  in  asrreement  or  not  in  agreement  with  our 
own  opinions. 

31.  So  f^ir,  then,  we  may  say  of  truthfulness,  as  we  have 
said  of  other  classes  of  virtue,  that  the  morality  emerges  in 
the  form  of  a  condemnation  of  particular  kinds  of  conduct 
seen  to  be  pernicious  to  the  societv,  and  gradually  passes  into 
the  recognition  of  a  certain  quality  as  implied  in  the  realisa- 
tion of  the  highest  social  type.  But  we  have  now  to  consider 
a  respect  in  which  it  differs  from  the  other  virtues.  We 
may  notice  in  the  first  place  that  the  obligation  to  a  certain 
definite  external  mode  of  conduct  is  generally  stated  as  abso- 
lute. Philosophers  have  deduced  all  virtues  from  truth,  and 
this  absoluteness  of  the  statement  is  favourable  to  the  method; 
for  though  puritv  and  courage  give  rise  to  rules  which  are 
almost  invariable,  such  as  fidelity  in  marriage  or  to  military 
obedience,  still  they  seem  to  include  an  empirical  element. 
The  particular  marriage  law,  for  example,  may  vary,  and  it 
is  conceivable  at  least  that  polygamy  may  be  the  rule  in  one 
period  and  monogamy  in  another,  whilst  the  decision  as  to 
the  superiority  of  either  rule  would  depend  upon  variable 
conditions  of  human  life.  The  rule  of  truthfulness,  on  the 
other  hand,  seems  to  possess  the  a  priori  quality  of  a  mathe- 
matical axiom.  It  seems  possible  to  say  that  it  is  always 
right  to  speak  the  truth,  as  it  is  always  true  that  two  and  two 
make  four.     Truth,  in  short,  being  always  the  same,  truth- 


2o6  THE  SCIENCE  OE  ETHICS. 

fulness  must  be  unvarvinc;.  Thus  "Be  truthful"  means, 
"  Speak  the  truth  whatever  the  consequences,  whether  the 
teller  or  the  hearer  receives  benefit  or  injury."  And  hence, 
it  is  inferred,  truthfulness  im))lies  a  quality  independent  of 
the  oro-anisation  of  the  aijent  or  of  society.  The  aa:ent 
should  act  as  if  he  were  a  pure  intellect.  Nothing  is  so 
truthful  as  a  calculating  machine,  which  grinds  out  the  same 
results,  whether  they  give  pleasure  or  pain.  The  preceding 
virtues  imply  a  certain  equilibrium  between  the  passions; 
we  cannot  define  "excess"  without  takins;  into  account  the 
constitution  of  the  persons  affected ;  but  the  rule  of  truth- 
fulness is  independent  of  any  such  considerations  and  under- 
lies them  all.  A  conception  of  truth  is  implied  in  all  rea- 
soning, for  reasoning  is  nothing  but  a  perception  of  truth 
and  error.  Thus  to  convey  truth  to  others  is  apparently  the 
simplest  possible  rule,  and  capable  of  the  most  absolute  state- 
ment; and  thus,  it  is  supposed,  we  may  reach  the  rule, 
"  Be  truthful,"  without  more  reference  to  society  than  we 
make  in  asserting  a  geometrical  or  a  logical  axiom. 

33.  We  must  ask,  then,  whether  this  absoluteness  of  the 
rule  really  affects  the  doctrine  that  it  expresses  a  condition  of 
social  welfare.  Moralists  agree  approximately  in  the  admis- 
sion that  truthfulness  is  an  essential  condition  of  the  welfare 
of  society  as  known  to  us.  This,  according  to  me,  is  the 
ultimate  ground,  in  a  scientific  sense  at  least,  of  its  moral 
value.  The  attempt  is  still  made  to  represent  the  principle 
as  possessing  an  authority  independent  of  any  social  conside- 
ration. A  different  rule,  it  is  said,  would  not  only  be  mis- 
chievous— that  is,  inconsistent  with  social  development — but 
self-contradictory.  So  far  as  this  asserts  anything  more  than 
this,  that  even  a  slight  social  advance  implies  some  degree  of 
truthfulness,  it  appears  to  me  to  be  erroneous,  or  at  least 
unprovable.  If  for  the  rule,  "  Speak  the  truth,"  we  could 
substitute  the  rule,  "  Tell  lies,"  it  is  quite  true  that  neither 
language  itself  nor  the  simplest  of  existing  social  institutions 
could  have  been  developed.  'J'o  invert  the  rule  of  truth 
would  imply  such  a  change  as  would  necessitate  a  modifica- 


VIRTUE  OF  TRUTH.  207 

tioii  of  some  of  the  apparently  most  essential  attributes  of 
humanitv.  Yet  even  in  this  case  the  rule,  "  Deceive,"  is  not 
in  a  formal  sense  more  contradictory  than  the  rule,  "  Do  not 
deceive,"  and  perhaps  it  would  be  possible  to  imagine  con- 
ditions under  which  mutual  deception  might  be  profitable  to 
a  race.  Undoubtedly  such  a  race  would  have  to  do  without 
lang^uao-e,  and  without  many  other  thino;s  which  are  essential 
to  society  as  we  know  it.  The  state  of  truthfulness  is  as 
essential  to  society  as  you  please,  but  it  is  illegitimate  to 
confound  this  doubtless  important  statement  with  the  state- 
ment that  the  opposite  rule  is  logically  impossible.  Universal 
Iving  is  not  self-contradictory;  it  is  only  impossible  within 
the  whole  rano;e  of  our  knowledge. 

^^.  In  the  next  place,  the  fact,  if  it  were  a  fact,  that  the 
direct  inversion  of  the  rule  was  contradictory,  would  not 
prove  the  rule  itself  to  be  necessary.  The  moral  rule  might 
conceivably  be,  "  Speak  truth  to  your  friends  and  lie  to  your 
cnemie?,"  or,  "Speak  truth  when  it  is  not  plainly  inconvenient;" 
just  as  the  moral  rule  may  be,  "Kill  not,  unless  in  war  or  bv 
due  form  of  law,  and  do  not  drink  more  than  is  good  for  you." 
This  is  not  only  conceivable,  but  is  a  fact  of  actual  morality. 
The  rule  of  truthfulness,  as  I  have  said,  is  understood,  in  fact, 
with  many  limitations,  and  is  still  far  from  being  universally 
and  thoroughly  carried  out ;  and  these  limitations  correspond 
to  the  limitations,  real  or  apparent,  of  its  social  value. 
And,  finally,  even  in  the  highest  moral  stages  there  remain 
certain  limitations.  Just  because  the  rule  can  be  so  absolutely 
expressed,  it  gives  rise  to  various  casuistical  problems  when 
applied  to  the  varying  facts  of  life.  Exceptions  are  recognised, 
and  these  exceptions  still  obey  the  general  rule  of  conformity 
to  the  conditions  of  social  welfare.  Such,  for  example,  are 
the  familiar  cases  of  tellino;  the  whereabouts  of  his  victim  to 
a  murderer,  telling  patients  in  certain  cases  of  their  true 
condition  of  health,  and  revealing  secrets  which  it  is  thouglit 
right  to  preserve,  even  when  Iving  alone  can  preserve  them. 
These  are  generally  cases  in  which  the  internal  diverges  from 
the  external    law,   and,   however    rare,   arc   therefore   worth 


2o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

notice.  The  rule,  "  Lie  not,"  is  the  external  rule,  and  corre- 
sponds approximately  to  the  internal  rule,  "Be  trustworthy." 
Cases  occur  where  the  rules  diverge,  and  in  such  cases  it  is 
the  internal  rule  which  is  morally  approved.  Truthfulness 
is  the  rule  because  in  the  vast  majority  of  cases  we  trust  a 
man  in  so  far  as  he  speaks  the  truth  ;  in  the  exceptional  cases, 
the  mutual  confidence  would  be  violated  when  the  truth,  not 
when  the  lie,  is  spoken.  In  such  cases,  therefore,  the  moral 
law  admits  of  an  apparent  exception,  though  there  are  manv 
difficulties  npon  which  I  must  touch  hereafter  in  the  way  of 
definino;  them. 

34.  Now,  without  going  farther  at  present,  we  see  that 
truthfulness  is  a  fresh  exemplification  of  the  principles  already 
laid  down  ;  for  truthfulness,  so  far  as  it  is  a  virtue,  implies 
trustworthiness.  Trustworthiness,  again,  is  clearly  a  quality 
the  development  of  which  is  essential  to  all  such  social  growth, 
at -least,  as  we  can  conceive  to  exist.  It  is  an  essential,  and 
the  most  obviously  essential,  condition  of  social  development. 
The  growth  of  a  sentiment  of  mutual  confidence  is  so  clearly 
necessary  that  it  seems  to  have  been  virtually  regarded  bv 
theorists  who  dealt  in  social  contracts  and  so  forth  as  the 
essential  element  or  ultimate  basis  of  morality.  The  develop- 
ment, however,  of  the  sentiment  implies  a  correlative  develop- 
ment of  the  whole  nature  of  men  and  society — a  development 
so  slow  as  to  be  very  inadequately  realised  even  in  the  highest 
societies  or  existence,  and  generally  limited  by  very  incomplete 
confidence  between  the  members  of  different  classes.  So  far 
from  implying  any  suppression  of  passions  or  of  the  emotions 
as  such,  it  implies  the  cultivation  of  all  the  qualities  by  which 
society  is  held  toother,  so  that  the  man  who  is  trustworthy 
in  the  highest  sense,  who  has  in  all  cases  a  self-respect  which 
makes  it  impossible  for  him  to  lie,  is  the  final  outcome,  the 
ripest  fruit,  of  the  healthiest  social  conditions.  Nothing  is 
rarer,  even  in  the  best  societies,  than  an  exquisite  sensitiveness 
upon  such  points,  and  a  morbid  social  condition  which  implies 
a  defect  of  the  true  social  sentiment  is  marked  by  nothing 
more  clearly  than  the  existence  of  partial  codes  of  truthful- 


VIRTUE  OF  TRUTH.  209 

ness  and  the  small  importance  attributed  to  lying  between 

different  classes.     But  this  is  to  sav  nothins;  else  than  that 

truthfulness  or  trustworthiness  is  one  of  the  essential  qualities 

of  the  true  social  type,  only  to  be  generated,  and  indeed  only 

to  be  fully  appreciated,  as  the  result  of  a  long  elaboration  and 

a  slow  growth  of  harmonious  relations.     It  implies,  doubtless, 

though  it  is  not  necessarily  implied,  by  the  narrower  quality 

which  rather  belongs  to  the  prudential  qualities  of  a  hatred 

for  error.     The  man,  indeed,  who  hates  error  will  generally 

hate  falsehood. 

"To  thine  own  self  be  true, 
And  it  must  follow,  as  the  day  the  night, 
Thou  canst  not  then  be  false  to  any  man." 

This  kind  of  virtue  would  belong,  however,  in  the  highest 
degree  to  the  man  who  approximates  as  closely  as  possible  to 
the  calculating  machine.  Such  a  man  no  doubt  would  have 
what  may  be  called  a  purely  intellectual  love  of  truth  ;  but'of 
truth  as  opposed  to  error  or  equiv^alent  to  accurate  knowledge, 
not  of  truth  as  implied  by  trustworthiness.  He  would  be 
like  the  calculating  machine,  equally  at  the  service  of  the 
rogue  or  the  honest  man,  unless  he  had  also  the  social  qualities 
summed  up  by  a  high  sense  of  honour.  It  would  give  him 
no  pain  to  know  that  he  had  deceived  others,  so  long  as  his 
knowledge  of  their  error  was  accurate.  To  know  is  to  avoid 
error;  a  desire  for  knowledge  and  a  love  of  being  deceived 
are  doubtless  incompatible;  and  the  man  who  felt  the  desire 
would  be  self-contradictory  if  he  did  not  desire  to  be  "  true  to 
himself"  in  the  sense  of  thinkino;  and  observino;  accurately. 
But  he  might  be  as  great  a  liar  as  any  one,  as  willing,  that  is, 
to  use  knowledge  selfishly,  unless  we  suppose  that  he  also 
possesses  the  qualities  implied  in  the  social  type.  And  there- 
fore we  may  assume  here,  as  before,  that  the  moral  law  means 
simply  a  statement  of  the  conduct  characteristic  of  the  most 
vigorous  vitality. 


2IO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

V.   The  Social  Virtues. 

^^.  We  come,  in  the  last  place,  to  the  directly  social  vir- 
tues. It  needs  no  demonstration  that  the  existence  of  a 
society  and  its  maintenance  at  a  certain  stage  of  civilisation 
are  dependent  upon  the  instincts  which,  whatever  their  ulti- 
mate nature,  imply  the  readiness  of  the  individual  to  identify 
himself  with  his  fellows,  and  to  seek  his  own  happiness  in  or 
through  their  happiness.  The  question  is  not  whether  such 
qualities  are  virtuous,  but  whether  they  are  not  the  sole  vir- 
tues. Accordingly,  some  moralists  hold  benevolence  to  be 
the  single  virtue,  as  others  deduce  all  the  moral  principles 
from  prudence,  or  purity,  or  truthfulness.  It  is  equally  clear, 
again,  that  these  virtues,  like  the  others,  are  developed  through 
a  gradual  process  of  generalisation;  that  so  long  as  each  tribe 
is  an  independent  whole,  the  mutual  goodwill  of  its  members 
is  often  limited  to  the  little  section  which  represents  the 
whole  world  for  them,  and  that  even  in  highly  developed 
communities  the  limitations  of  benevolence  are  such  as  to 
show  little  recognition  of  external  claims.  The  gradual 
extension  of  the  sphere  of  morality  may  be  due  to  the  gene- 
ralising faculty  itself — to  any  process  by  which  the  vmder- 
standing  becomes  enlightened  and  the  sympathies  more  sen- 
sitive, or  it  may  be  the  indirect  result  of  such  a  change  in 
external  conditions  as  is  implied  by  the  absorption  of  many 
communities  into  a  larger  whole,  with  a  consequent  recog- 
nition of  a  wider  community  of  interest.  We  are  still  very 
far  from  an  unqualified  recognition  of  the  virtue.  Patriotism 
often  takes  the  narrow  and  contemptible  form  of  a  desire  for 
the  extension  of  our  own  political  organisation,  in  complete 
indifference  to,  or  rather  with  a  contemptuous  refusal  to 
attach  any  importance  to,  the  welfare  of  the  outside  world. 
I  will  only  observe,  without  dwelling  farther  upon  sufficiently 
obvious  considerations,  that  the  change  may  be  regarded  in 
two  aspects.  The  difference  between  the  morality  of  military 
savages  and  tliat  of  a  civilised  country  is  not  necessarily  so 
great  as  it  seems.     The  actual  rule  of  conduct  niav  be,  in  one 


THE  SOCIAL   VIRTUES.  21  r 

case,  to  knock  a  stranger  on  the  head,  and,  in  the  other,  to 
ask  him  to  dinner.  But  then  it  must  be  admitted  that  the 
difference  may  correspond  simply  to  a  difference  in  the  facts 
to  which  the  rule  applies,  not  in  the  rule  itself.  Stranger,  in 
one  sense,  means  a  being  who  will  presumably  kill  me  if  he 
can;  in  the  other,  a  being  who  will  presumably  be  friendly. 
Thus  the  most  civilised  beins;  would  have  to  sro  armed  in 
a  reo'ion  where  no  mutual  understandino;  had  been  reached. 
The  difference  would  be  that  he  would  there  anticipate  from 
every  one  the  behaviour  which  in  his  own  country  he  would 
only  anticipate  from  an  exceptional  person.  Unless  his 
morality  forbade  self-defence — which  is  hardly  the  case  in  any 
accepted  code — it  would  therefore  allow  or  prescribe  hostility 
towards  strangers  presumably  hostile.  Thus  the  growth  of 
morality  implies  the  development  of  this  mutual  understand- 
ing. It  may  be  obvious  that  such  an  understanding  would 
be  useful  if  attainable,  and  so  far  its  establishment  does  not 
imply  a  change  in  the  moral  sentiment,  but  only  in  the  facts 
to  which  it  is  applied.  On  the  other  hand,  it  may  also  be 
said  that,  to  attain  the  understanding,  we  require  not  simply 
a  perception  of  its  utility,  but  a  greater  development  of 
emotional  sensibility,  and  so  a  greater  power  of  sympathy, 
which  must  go  along  with  the  purely  intellectual  process. 

'J^6.  This  remark  suggests  one  other  which  must  be  taken 
into  account.  The  virtues  of  which  I  am  speaking  are  often 
reo-arded  as  fallinir  under  the  two  heads  of  justice  and  bene- 
yolence.  These  two  are  sometimes  described  as  so  far  from 
coincident  that  they  may  occasionally  come  into  conflict, 
and  morality  is  to  prescribe  a  course  which  is  a  kind  of  dia- 
gonal between  the  two  diverging  rules.  The  justice  of  the 
Supreme  Being,  we  are  told,  is  tempered  by  his  mercy,  and 
vice  versa.  It  is  plain  that  the  distinction  corresponds  to 
that  already  drawn  between  the  intellect  and  the  emotions. 
Temperance,  so  far  as  it  is  strictly  virtuous  rather  than  pru- 
dential, implies,  as  I  have  said,  a  restriction  upon  selfishness, 
and  the  instincts  by  which  the  society  is  held  together  may 
be  regarded  as  a  development  from  the  sexual  and  parental 


212  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

instincts.  Truthfulness,  on  the  other  hand,  so  far  as  it  too 
is  strictly  virtuous,  must  be  regarded  as  implying  a  distinc- 
tively social  quality,  and  so  far  a  fitness  to  act  in  accordance 
with  social  demands.  Thus  we  may  regard  temperance  as 
included  in  the  duty  of  benevolence,  though  it  has  also  a 
prudential  aspect ;  and  truthfulness,  with  the  same  limita- 
tion, as  included  under  the  virtue  of  justice.  And  hence, 
again,  it  must  be  repeated  that,  although  there  may  be  a  dis- 
tinction, there  can  be  no  proper  opposition.  If  benevolence 
means  a  desire  to  see  others  happy,  it  defeats  its  own  end 
if  it  tries  to  promote  happiness  of  some  at  the  expense  of 
others;  and  justice  ceases  to  be  just  when  it  implies  the 
observance  of  a  rule  imposed  for  the  good  of  all  in  such  a 
way  as  to  be  injurious  to  all. 

37.  It  seems  desirable,  however,  to  put  this  rather  more 
precisely.  What,  in  fact,  is  meant  by  justice?  The  spe- 
cial case  in  regard  to  which  the  virtue  first  emerges  is  that 
of  a  partial  judge,  and  the  same  principle  will  apply  of 
course  to  all  other  persons  intrusted  with  power  by  the 
organisation  of  the  community.  The  judge,  again,  is  unjust 
so  far  as  he  acts  from  any  other  considerations  than  those 
which  are  recognised  as  legitimate  by  the  legal  constitution. 
He  has  to  declare  the  law,  and  to  apply  it  to  particular  cases 
without  fear  or  favour.  He  must  therefore  give  the  same 
decision  whether  the  persons  interested  be  friends  or  foes, 
relations  or  strangers,  rich  or  poor.  And  so,  extending 
the  same  principle,  we  say  that  a  minister  is  unjust  who  dis- 
tributes offices  from  other  considerations  than  the  fitness  of 
the  applicants,  except  in  certain  cases  where  it  is  understood 
that  the  power  of  appointment  is  an  indirect  mode  of  re- 
warding the  appointee.  A  parent  is  unjust  who  does  not 
distribute  his  property  to  his  children  equally,  whether  they 
are  clever  or  stupid,  and  even,  within  wide  limits,  whether 
good  or  bad.  And,  on  the  other  hand,  considerations  which 
are  held  to  be  irrelevant  in  one  case  are  regarded  as  essen- 
tially relevant  in  another.  The  man  is  unjust  who,  in  his 
judicial   capacity,  distinguishes   between   a  friend   and    an 


THE  SOCIAL   VIRTUES.  213 

enemy,  a  relation  and  a  stranger;  he  is  equally  unjust  if,  in 
his  domestic  capacity,  he  fails  to  distinguish.  It  would  be 
grossly  unjust  in  a  judge  to  favour  a  Tory  as  against  a 
Whig;  in  a  minister,  it  might  be  grossly  unjust  not  to  con- 
sider the  claims  of  party.  The  judge  would  be  unjust  who 
showed  favour  to  his  own  son,  and  the  parent  would  be 
unjust  who  did  not  give  his  money  to  his  own  children. 
The  essence  of  justice,  therefore,  seems  to  be  the  uniform 
application  of  rules  according  to  relevant  circumstances ;  or, 
as  we  may  put  it,  it  is  an  application  to  conduct  of  the  prin- 
ciple of  sufficient  reason.  Every  difference  in  my  treatment 
of  others  must  be  determined  by  some  principle  which  is  in 
that  case  appropriate  and  sufficient.  In  this  sense^  therefore, 
justice  means  reasonableness. 

38.  From  this,  again,  we  see  in  what  way  justice  is  implied 
in  social  development.  How  are  we  to  say  what,  in  any  case, 
is  the  sufficient  reason  ?  What  set  of  rules  is  relevant,  and  in 
what  relations  of  life  are  we  or  are  we  not  to  attend  to  par- 
ticular kinds  of  claims?  To  this  we  must  replv,  in  general 
terms,  that  all  social  development  implies,  as  we  have  seen,  a 
distribution  of  functions,  and  the  possibility  of  any  permanent 
organisation  depends  upon  a  corresponding  perception  of  the 
implied  duties.  The  royal  power,  for  example,  has  been  de- 
veloped by  certain  social  needs,  such  as  the  necessity  of  a 
centralised  military  power.  If  a  particular  king  uses  the 
power  not  so  as  to  discharge  his  function  in  the  most  efficient 
wav,  but  for  some  other  purpose,  such  as  the  gratification  of 
his  appetites,  the  social  organ  ceases  to  be  efficient,  and  the 
society  is  so  far  in  a  state  of  degeneration.  The  due  perfor- 
mance of  the  function  is  suspended,  and  the  organ  becomes 
an  encumbrance  instead  of  a  useful  part  of  the  system.  The 
function  of  the  criminal  judge  is  the  suppression  of  certain 
offences;  if  he  only  punishes  criminals  not  related  to  him  or 
receives  bribes,  and  even  if,  as  a  judge,  he  gives  undue  weight 
to  qualities  which  in  another  capacity  he  might  properly 
regard,  the  administration  of  justice  is  so  far  corrupted.  The 
same  principle  of  course  applies  in  every  conceivable  case,  and 


214  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

is  analogous  to  the  statement  that  in  a  living  organism  the 
welfare  of  the  animal  depends  upon  his  eyes  seeing  and  his 
ears  hearing  according  to  certain  rules.  So  far  as  the  king 
is  a  tyrant  or  the  judge  corrupt,  each  is  hindering  the  due 
performance  of  an  important  function,  and  injures  the  country 
as  the  distorting  eye  or  ear  injures  the  organism. 

39.  Hence,  when  we  say  that  a  judge  is  to  be  passionless, 
we  use  the  word  in  the  same  sense  as  in  the  case  of  truthful- 
ness.    He  must  be  inaccessible  to  certain  passions  when  they 
are  out  of  place ;  the  ruling  passion  which  must  govern  him 
in  his  judicial  capacity  is  the  passion  for  justice;  and  that, 
as  before,  whether   acting  justly  has  become  a  habit  or  is 
prompted    by  a   constant   sense  of  the  vital  importance  of 
judicial  impartiality  to  society  in  general.     He  should  apply 
the  rule  with  the  precision  of  a  calculating  machine;    but 
he  must  have  a  motive  for  setting  his  intellect  to  work  im- 
partially; and,  of  course,  such  motives  are  sufficiently  nume- 
rous and  powerful  in  a  healthy  social  state  to  make  judicial 
purity  a  second  nature.     When,  again,  we  speak  of  mercy 
as  conflicting  with  justice,  we  mean  generally  to  imply  that 
either  the  benevolence  is  ill-guided,  or  that  a  rule  founded 
upon  some  important  considerations  is  being  applied  in  cases 
when  an  exception  should  be  made.     Benevolence  conflicts 
with  justice  in  the  case  of  misguided  charity  or  excessive  leni- 
ency, where  the  desire  of  giving  pleasure  to  some  one  immedi- 
ately before  us  causes  us  to  overlook  the  indirect  consequences 
of  demoralisation,  and  so  forth,  to  the  person  benefited,  and  the 
injury  done  to  others  who  have  equal  claims,  but  who  do  not 
happen  to  be  in  so  conspicuous  a  station.     There  is  a  conflict, 
again,  when  a  rule  is  pedantically  applied,  so  as  to  injure  a 
man  whose  conduct  is  forbidden  because  it  belongs  to  a  class 
generally  mischievous,  though  we  are  quite  certain  that  in  the 
particular  case  it  had  not  the  objectionable  characteristics  of 
that  class;  as,  for  example,  if  a  man  is  punished  for  homicide 
in  a  case  where  homicide  was  evidently  conmiitted  in  self- 
defence.     But  in  all  such  cases  it  is  not  properly  a  conflict 
between  justice  and  benevolence,  but  between  a  benevolence 


THE  SOCIAL  DEFINITION  OF  VIRTUE.  215 

which  takes  into  account  all  the  relevant  circumstances,  and 
one  which  fails  to  do  so ;  between  a  justice  which  applies  a  rule 
with,  and  one  which  applies  it  without  due  consideration. 
There  are,  of  course,  many  casuistical  cases  which  may  be 
suggested,  and  which  often  present  real  difficulty — cases,  for 
example,  such  as  have  afforded  materials  for  the  most  striking 
tragical  situations,  where  a  man  is  distracted  between  demands 
made  upon  him  in  two  capacities, — between  the  claims  of  his 
family,  for  example,  and  the  claims  of  the  state,  as  in  the  story 
of  Brutus  and  his  sons.  Of  such  cases  it  is  enough  here  to 
say  that,  on  whatever  principles  they  may  be  settled,  they  do 
not  involve  any  proper  conflict  between  benevolence  and 
justice.  The  same  criterion  is  ultimately  implied  in  both 
cases,  though  w^e  may  lay  more  stress  upon  one  or  other 
aspect.  The  command,  "  Be  benevolent,"  carries  with  it  the 
condition  that  your  benevolence  should  be  regulated  by  reason, 
and  therefore  should  not  benefit  one  man  at  the  expense  of 
the  society.  The  command,  "Be  just,"  carries  with  it  in 
the  same  wav  the  condition  that,  whatever  function  you  are 
discharging  or  in  whatever  capacity  you  are  acting,  vou 
must  be  animated  bv  public  spirit,  that  is,  by  motives  coin- 
cident with  the  dictates  of  a  reasonable  benevolence ;  and 
thus,  in  any  case,  the  conclusion  is  that  the  moral  law 
prescribes  a  type  of  character  which  includes  amongst  its 
manifestations  a  desire  to  discharge  all  the  social  functions, 
and  which  therefore  implies  fitness  to  form  part  of  a  sound 
social  state. 


VI.   The  Social  Definition  of  Virtue. 

40.  This  brief  survey  of  the  main  divisionsof  morality,  which, 
as  I  have  shown,  run  into  each  other,  and  to  some  extent 
mutually  imply  each  other,  may  justify  the  conclusion  as  to 
the  social  definition  of  virtue.  Society,  I  have  said,  may  be 
considered  as  an  organism,  implying  what  I  have  called  a 
social  tissue,  modified  in  various  w^ays  so  as  to  form  the 
organs  adapted  to  various  specific  purposes.     The  existence 


2i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

of  the  social  tissue  at  any  stage  of  development^  and  its 
power  of  maintaining  itself,  either  as  a  part  of  the  special 
order  or  as  against  other  societies,  depends  essentially  upon 
the  fulfilment  of  certain  conditions.  Since  the  qualities 
by  which  societies  differ  do  not  depend  upon  the  innate 
qualities  of  its  constituent  members^  which  remain  constant 
(or  approximately  constant)  through  long  periods  of  social 
development,  but  upon  these  qualities  as  modified  and  de- 
veloped by  means  of  the  social  factors,  it  follows  again  that 
the  society  grows  on  condition  of  impressing  a  certain  char- 
acter upon  its  members.  This  takes  place  in  the  earlier 
stages  by  the  development  of  a  social  sentiment  unfavour- 
able to  certain  specific  modes  of  conduct.  As  the  society 
becomes  more  reasonable,  more  capable  of  understanding 
and  applying  general  principles,  the  sentiment  develops  into 
an  approval  of  a  certain  type  of  character,  the  existence  of 
which  fits  the  individual  for  membership  of  a  thoroughly 
eflBcient  and  healthy  social  tissue.  To  state  the  main  qualities 
thus  impressed  is  to  lay  down  what  I  have  called  the  "  law 
of  nature."  This,  as  we  see,  has  the  two  poles  of  prudence 
and  virtue,  corresponding  to  the  distinction  of  the  qualities 
which  are  primarily  useful  to  the  individual  and  those 
which  are  primarily  useful  to  the  society.  Thus,  whatever 
strengthens  the  individual,  increases  his  courage,  energy, 
industry,  and  so  forth,  must,  other  things  being  equal, 
strengthen  the  society.  Hence  the  law  of  prudence,  which 
corresponds  rather  to  a  precedent  condition  of  morality  than 
to  morality  itself.  Then  the  individual  is  stronger  and  the 
society  is  stronger  so  far  as  his  passions  are  regulated  in  a 
certain  way,  and  including  alike  the  passions  which  have  a 
direct  bearing  upon  the  individual  life  and  those  which  have 
a  direct  bearing  upon  the  social  bond  ;  whence  the  virtues  of 
temperance  and  chastity.  Thirdly,  the  individual,  so  far  as 
reasonable,  must  avoid  error  on  his  own  account,  and  must 
avoid  the  propagation  of  error  for  the  welfare  of  the  society, 
whence  the  virtues  of  wisdom  and  trustworthiness.  And, 
finally,  since  the  social  union  implies  a  direct  interest  of  the 


THE  SOCIAL  DEFINITION  OF  VIRTUE.  217 

individual  in  the  welfare  of  the  society,  wc  have  the  directly 
social  virtues,  which  imply  at  once  benevolence  and  justice, 
accordino;  as  wc  attend  to  the  motive  or  to  the  rcirulatcd 
action  of  motives.  And  these  four  classes  of  excellence, 
which  by  the  mode  of  development  are  necessarily  recon- 
cilable and  mutually  implicatory  of  each  other,  seem  to 
constitute  all  that  is  meant  by  the  general  moral  law, 
though  admitting,  of  course,  an  indefinite  variety  of  special 
applications. 

41.  Briefly,  then,  we  may  say  that  morality  is  a  statement 
of  the  conditions  of  social  welfare ;  and  morality,  as  dis- 
tinguished from  prudence,  refers  to  those  conditions  which 
imply  a  direct  action  upon  the  social  union.  In  other  words, 
morality  is  the  sum  of  the  preservative  instincts  of  a  society, 
and  presumably  of  those  which  imply  a  desire  for  the  good 
of  the  society  itself.  And  so  far,  as  I  may  observe,  moralists 
w^ould  c;enerallv  asjree  as  to  the  fact,  howev^er  difFerentlv  thev 
might  state  it  or  account  for  it.  That  is  to  say^  no  moralist 
of  any  school  would  deny  that  the  health  of  the  society,  its 
power  of  persistence,  and  its  harmony  with  the  happiness 
of  its  members,  depends  essentially  and  primarily  upon  its 
condition  in  respect  of  morality  and  prudence.  Lower  the 
average  standard,  and  the  society  is  so  far  in  danger  of  stag- 
nation, decay,  and  actual  extermination ;  raise  it,  and  the 
society  is  so  far  better  calculated  to  preserve  itself  and  to 
develop  new  and  richer  life.  But  difiiculties  and  disputes 
arise  when  we  go  farther.  That  which  I  am  specially  con- 
cerned to  meet  concerns  the  mode  in  which  virtue,  the 
nature  of  which  can  be  clearly  and  simply  expressed  when 
we  speak  of  the  social  organism,  presents  itself  when  we 
change  our  point  of  view,  and  ask  how  it  comes  to  be  im- 
pressed upon  the  individual.  Virtue  is  a  condition  of  social 
welfare;  but  why  should  I  be  virtuous,  or  what  are  the 
motives  by  which  the  conformitv  of  the  individual  is  or  mav 
be  secured  ?  In  order  to  answer  this,  and  the  many  pro- 
blems which  arise  from  or  are  intimately  connected  with  it, 
it  is  necessary  to  consider  what  may  be  called  the  '^  theory  of 


2i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

obligation."  This,  accordingly,  will  form  the  topic  of  the 
next  three  chapters.  What  is  the  quality  in  respect  of 
which  the  individual  is  susceptible  to  the  social  pressure? 
What  is  the  form  taken  by  that  pressure  ?  What  is  the 
nature  of  the  character  which  must  be  impressed  upon  the 
individual  ?  These  are  the  problems  of  altruism,  of  merit, 
and  of  conscience,  upon  each  of  which  I  shall  have  something 
to  sav. 


(      219      ) 


CHAPTER  VI. 

ALTRUISM. 

1.  Egoistic  Instincts. 

I.  The  last  chapter  has  brought  us  to  the  problem  which 
is  at  the  root  of  all  ethical  discussion.  The  definition  of 
morality  is  perfectly  simple  so  long  as  we  fix  our  attention 
upon  the  social  organism ;  the  moral  law  is  a  statement  of 
certain  essential  conditions  of  the  vitality  of  the  society,  and 
specifically  of  those  conditions  which  apply  primarily  to  the 
society,  and  only  in  a  secondary  sense  to  the  individual. 
The  individual  then  must,  so  far  as  moral,  be  capable  of 
aiming  at  the  social  welfare  before  his  own.  In  every  moral 
system,  action  for  the  good  of  others  is  regarded  as  virtuous, 
if  not  as  the  only  action  entitled  to  be  called  virtuous.  But 
how  is  such  action  conceivable?  Can  any  man  really 
sacrifice  himself?  Is  not  the  admission  of  the  possibility  of 
self-sacrifice  inconsistent  with  the  assertion  that  all  conduct 
is  determined  by  the  feelings  of  the  agent,  and  therefore,  as 
it  would  seem,  by  his  own  pain  or  pleasure  ?  The  egoistical 
theory  which  accepts  this  conclusion  is  the  favourite  bug- 
bear of  ethical  writers.  By  fixing  upon  an  antagonist  the 
imputation  of  egoism  you  give  him  a  bad  name,  and  have 
an  easy  opportunity  for  a  rhetoric  which  reflects  credit  upon 
the  assailant.  Only  a  cynic  or  a  satirist  here  and  there 
maintains  the  thesis  of  universal  selfishness,  or  a  rare  philo- 
sopher propounds  it  in  words,  whilst  carefully  explaining 
that  he  does  not  mean  what  he  says.  I  am  half  ashamed  to 
join  in  the  hue  and  cry  against  an  outcast  doctrine  so  often 
repudiated,    and    so  often  pronounced  to  have    been   slain 


220  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

outright.  Yet  Its  singular  vitality,  in  spite  of  repeated 
assaults,  shows  it  to  possess  some  real  plausibility.  If  it  be 
erroneous,  we  must  be  careful  in  laying  down  the  positions 
of  which  it  is  a  perverted  statement ;  and  as  even  the 
egoist  admits  that  altruism,  though  a  mere  mask,  is  yet  a 
mask  invariably  adopted  by  the  virtuous,  it  is  equally  neces- 
sary, upon  his  assumption,  to  examine  its  true  nature,  though 
at  the  expense  of  painfully  retracing  some  familiar  ground. 

3.  Where  does  the  puzzle  arise?  Common  sense  finds  no 
difficulty.  A  man  is  altruistic  who  loves  his  neighbour  as 
himself;  who  gives  money  to  the  poor  which  he  might  have 
spent  in  luxury;  who  leaves  house  and  home  to  convert 
savages;  who  sacrifices  health  to  comfort  prisoners  or  sufTerers 
in  a  plague-stricken  city.  Sir  Philip  Sidney  was  altruistic 
when  he  gave  the  cup  of  water  to  the  wounded  soldier  in- 
stead of  slaking  his  own  dying  thirst.  Such  deeds  make  our 
nerves  tingle  at  the  hearing,  and  ennoble  the  dreary  wastes  of 
folly  and  selfishness  recorded  in  history.  But  the  egoist  has 
an  easy  explanation.  Sidney's  conduct  only  proves  that  his 
vanity  was  stronger  than  his  thirst,  and  vanity  is  one  of 
the  meanest  of  motives ;  the  charitable  man  is  repaid  by  a 
glow  of  self-complacency;  the  missionary  hopes  for  a  reward 
in  heaven;  the  physician  in  the  plague-stricken  city  is  eager 
for  praise  and  shrinks  from  general  contempt.  In  all  cases, 
and  however  skilfully  disguised,  some  personal  gratification 
supplies  the  cogent  motive.  Everywhere  we  find  the  con- 
viction, tacit  or  express,  that  the  conduct  adopted  will  secure 
the  greatest  happiness  of  the  agent.  Nobody,  indeed,  can 
deny  that  men  act  so  as  to  destroy  their  own  happiness; 
if  vanitv  causes  a  man  to  sacrifice  his  best  chances,  so  mav 
the  desire  of  a  brief  sensual  pleasure.  One  man  goes  to  a 
public-house,  another  leads  a  forlorn  hope;  each  throws 
away  life  for  a  brief  enjoyment,  whether  mischievous  or 
beneficial  to  others.  The  egoist  may  explain  both  cases 
with  equal  facility.  Each  act  iniplies  a  temporary  error  of 
judgment ;  the  love  of  gin  or  the  love  of  glory  overpowers 
the  reflective  faculties.     Let  a  man  call   up  all  the  conse- 


EGOISTIC  INSTINCTS.  221 

quences  of  his  action,  and  he  will  cease  to  be  imprudent, 
and  therefore  to  throw  away  his  chances  of  future  happiness, 
whether  his  happiness  is  bound  up  with  or  absolutely  irre- 
concilable with  the  happiness  of  others.  A  man  may  con- 
ceivably be  unselfish,  but  so  far  as  really  unselfish  he  is  a 
fool  for  his  pains.  He  will  only  do  good  to  others,  if  a  wise 
or  a  thoroughly  enlightened  man,  so  far  as  he  expects  to 
derive  some  benefit  for  himself.  Thus  the  statement  that 
altruism  is  impossible  does  not  mean  that  it  is  impossible  in 
fact,  but  only  in  deliberate  intention.  No  man,  it  is  argued, 
can  sacrifice  himself  knowingly  and  intentionally. 

3.  To  unravel  these  arguments  as  well  as  I  can,  I  must  begin 
by  recalling  some  considerations  already  noticed.     All  con- 
duct has  an  indefinite  series  of  consequences ;  that  is  to  say, 
any  act  may  be  taken  as  the  starting-point  of  a  series  of 
events  continuing  for  an  indefinite  period,  all  of  which  would 
be  different  had  the  action  been  different.     The  agent  can 
of  course   contemplate  only  a  small   part  of  these   conse- 
quences.    It  is  his  intention  to  produce  those  events  which 
he  sees   to  be  dependent   upon   his  actions,  and   from   the 
intention  we  may  infer  the   motive — that    is,   the  feeling 
which  is  gratified  by  the  realisation  of  the  intention.     Now 
conduct  may  be  beneficial  to  others  without  any  benevolent 
intention,  and  not  only  by  accident,  but  from  its  intrinsic 
nature.    This,  for  example,  is  true  of  the  sexual  and  parental 
instincts  of  animals.     The  instinct  which   leads  a  stag  to 
form  a  harem  and  propagate  his  race  is  of  essential  utility 
to  the  herd,  but  does  not  imply  that  the  stag  has  the  least 
sympathy  for  the  hinds  or  their  fawns.     The  hen  sacrifices 
herself  for  her  chicken,   but   it   does    not   follow — perhaps 
it  is  only  our  anthropomorphic  tendencies  which  suggest  the 
inference — that  she  considers  her  chickens  as  anything  more 
than   soft,   warm  lumps   of  down,   which   are    comfortable 
furniture  in  the  nest.     She  sacrifices  herself  to  save  them, 
it  may  be,  just  as  she  would  run  into  equal  risk  if  tempted 
by  a  particular  kind  of  food.     The  apparent  love  may  be 
(one  hopes  that  it  is  not)  simply  a  physical  appetite. 


2'>'> 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 


4.  It  is,  then,  unsafe  to  infer  altruistic  intentions  from 
altruistic  consequences.  In  human  beings  the  sexual  appetite 
appears  to  be  the  most  purely  selfish  of  impulses,  in  so  far  as 
it  prompts  to  conduct  often  ruinous  to  its  objects.  On  the 
other  hand,  it  is  at  the  root  of  all  the  social  virtues.  The 
passion  cannot  be  gratified  without  important  consequences 
to  others,  and  yet  in  its  lower  form  implies  no  recognition 
whatever  of  those  consequences.  The  purely  sensual  appe- 
tite remains  in  the  reasonable  beins;  who  can  recoffnise  the 
consequences  to  others.  If  he  still  gratifies  the  passion 
without  reference  to  those  consequences,  he  is  prompted  to 
the  grossest  selfishness ;  if,  on  the  other  hand,  the  sensual 
impulse  is  so  regulated  that  others  are  not  injured  bv  its 
gratification,  it  may  become  the  nucleus  of  the  most  un- 
selfish affection.  Before  the  agent  is  enlightened  by  reflec- 
tion it  is  hardly  proper  to  call  him  either  selfish  or  unselfish  ; 
he  does  not  repudiate  the  claims  of  his  fellows — he  is  inca- 
pable of  perceiving  their  existence.  Selfishness  or  unselfish- 
ness is  developed  as  the  intellect  becomes  capable  of 
contemplating  the  happiness  of  others  besides  the  agent, 
llie  same  change  is  manifest  in  other  relations.  The  master 
of  slaves  may  regard  them  simply  as  convenient  instruments  ; 
he  may  risk  life  and  limb  to  defend  them,  as  he  would  run 
the  same  risk  in  defence  of  inanimate  property.  So  far  as 
his  interest  is  furthered  by  their  health  and  safety,  his  rela- 
tion to  them  may  have  beneficial  consequences  although 
there  is  no  benevolent  intention ;  but  so  far  as  he  can 
increase  his  own  comfort  by  giving  them  pain,  he  may  be 
as  willing  to  inflict  pain  as  to  give  pleasure.  He  might,  for 
anything  we  can  see,  be  as  willing  to  feed  his  pigs  on  slaves 
as  to  feed  his  slaves  upon  pork,  if  the  price  of  the  two  com- 
modities should  vary.  In  this  case  the  relation  remains  purely 
external ;  the  slaves  are  considered  simply  as  things,  not  as 
human  beings.  But  where  external  circumstances  enforce  a 
certain  identity  of  interest  upon  a  particular  group,  there  is 
room  for  the  development  of  genuine  altruism.  The  mother 
may  be  stimulated  to  actions  which  are  de  facto  beneficent 


EGOISTIC  INSTINCTS.  223 

and  self-sacrificing  in  their  consequences  by  the  pleasant 
sensations  connected  with  suckling  and  nursing;  as  soon  as 
she  becomes  aware  that  she  is  furthering  the  happiness  of 
her  offspring,  the  happiness  may  itself  become  a  motive 
for  conduct.  There  is  already  a  framework  provided  within 
which  the  affections  have  room  to  expand.  The  purely 
sensual  pleasure  is  now  so  blended  with  the  pleasure  derived 
from  a  perception  of  the  happiness  conferred  that  it  may 
be  impossible  to  discriminate  between  them.  In  the  normal 
case  they  operate  in  the  same  direction,  and  there  is  no 
conflict  so  long  as  they  do  not  dictate  diverging  lines  of 
conduct.  The  same  change  (as  I  have  already  argued) 
takes  place  in  regard  to  social  relations  generally.  The 
connection  between  husband  and  wife,  which  implied  origi- 
nally the  subordination  of  one  being  to  the  sensual  appetites 
of  the  other,  becomes  the  ground  of  the  most  perfect  sym- 
pathy and  the  strongest  mutual  affection.  A  slave-holding 
community  may  develop  into  one  in  which  the  employer  and 
the  employed  have  friendly  domestic  relations,  and  each 
desires,  or  at  least  respects,  the  pleasure  of  the  other ;  and  the 
point  at  which  this  becomes  possible  must  be  at  that  stage 
of  intellectual  development  in  which  we  are  able  to  recognise 
the  happiness  of  others  than  ourselves.  Till  that  is  possible, 
each  beine;  can  be  at  most  the  instrument  of  the  other's 
pleasure,  and  regarded  with  feelings  not  differing  in  kind 
from  those  excited  by  any  lifeless  object.  So  soon  as  we 
realise  the  fact  that  we  cause  pain  and  pleasure  to  others, 
their  pain  or  pleasure  may  supply  a  motive.  Till  that 
period,  the  agent  is  not  so  much  selfish  or  unselfish  in  the 
full  sense  as  incapable  of  any  feeling  in  the  matter.  There 
must  already  be  beneficent  conduct,  but  there  can  be  no 
benevolent  or  malevolent  intention. 

5.  This  change  is  sometimes  explained  as  a  product  of 
association.  The  truth  or  falsehood  of  this  doctrine  in 
general  depends  upon  principles  which  lie  beyond  the  present 
inquiry;  but  it  may  be  observed  already  that  there  is  at 
least   a  prima  facie  objection    to   the   completeness   of  the 


2  24  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

explanation.  The  simple  association  of  a  particular  object, 
material  or  animated,  with  certain  pleasures,  may  doubtless 
make  us  value  it  as  a  useful  instrument,  but  we  do  not  see 
how  it  can  change  the  instrument  to  an  object  of  sympathy. 
The  child  may  regard  its  mother  as  a  fountain  of  agreeable 
drink,  and  the  mother  may  regard  the  child  as  affording  a 
pleasant  relief;  but  so  far  there  is  nothing  in  the  associa- 
tion which  should  lead  the  child  to  distinguish  between  the 
mother  and  the  bottle,  or  the  mother  to  distino-uish  between 
the  child  and  some  mechanical  contrivance,  except  in  so  far 
as  one  may  be  more  efficient  than  the  other.  Undoubtedly, 
the  pleasant  association  prepares  the  way  for  the  higher 
sentiment.  The  fact  of  the  mutual  convenience  provides  a 
necessary  condition  for  satisfaction  in  conferring  mutual 
pleasure.  But  the  condition  is  obviously  insufficient,  for  it 
suggests  no  account  of  the  distinction  which  arises  between 
the  sentiment  excited  by  a  mother  or  that  excited  by  a 
comfortable  garment.  It  might  happen  that,  by  throwing 
away  broken  meat  which  was  a  nuisance  to  me,  I  was 
contributing  to  the  support  of  a  poor  family  or  to  the 
support  of  the  crows.  So  long  as  I  regard  both  simply 
as  conveniences  for  the  removal  of  my  refuse,  I  shall 
simply  prefer  one  or  the  other  as  it  discharges  that  func- 
tion most  efficiently.  If  I  am  better  pleased  to  benefit 
the  poor  family  than  the  crows,  whilst  the  conduct  in 
other  respects  produces  the  same  effect  upon  me,  I  am  so 
far  "altruistic;"  and  this  implies  that  I  am  capable  of 
sympathising  with,  and  therefore  of  at  least  recognising,  the 
happiness  conferred  upon  the  human  beings.  The  bare 
convenience  to  me,  being  by  hypothesis  the  same,  would 
not  lead  to  any  distinction  by  mere  force  of  association. 

6.  I  assume,  then,  that  altruism,  whatever  its  meaning  or 
analysis,  begins  at  the  point  at  which  I  am  capable  of 
benevolent  intentions ;  or,  in  other  words,  where  conferring 
pleasure  upon  others  becomes  a  possible  motive.  And  here 
the  egoist  meets  us  by  denying  that  this  can  ever  be  an 
ultimate  motive.      The  desire  to  give   happiness  is  always 


EGOISTIC  INSTINCTS.  225 

capable  of  a  further  analysis^  which  shows  it  to  inckide  a 
desire  of  happiness  for  ourselves.  Nobody  denies  that  the 
wish  to  give  happiness  may  be  part  of  my  motive^  and  it 
may  be  at  a  given  moment  the  only  part  of  which  I  am 
distinctly  conscious.  I  till  a  field  in  order  that  I  may  reap 
the  harvest,  but  whilst  I  am  tilling  I  mav  be  thinkino;  onlv 
of  the  plough ;  the  means  become  a  temporary  or  conditional 
end.  So  I  may  be  kind  to  you  in  order  that  you  may  here- 
after be  kind  to  me,  and  at  a  given  instant  of  kindness  I 
may  not  be  distinctly  conscious  of  the  ultimate  end.  But, 
according  to  the  egoist,  such  an  end  must  always  exist.  The 
goal  of  every  conceivable  desire  is  some  state  of  agreeable 
consciousness  of  my  own.  I  may  not  look  to  the  end  of 
the  vista  of  intended  consequences,  but,  if  I  look,  I  shall 
always  see  my  own  reflection.  This,  again,  is  taken  to  be  a 
self-evident  truth.  To  suppose  genuine  altruism,  that  is,  a 
desire  of  which  the  ultimate  end  is  the  happiness  of  some 
other  person,  is  to  suppose  a  contradiction. 

7.  This  statement  appears  to  me  to  convey  a  palpable 
truth  or  a  great  error  according  to  our  mode  of  interpreting 
it.  Every  motive,  as  I  have  already  said,  may  be  described 
either  in  objective  or  subjective  language.  I  may  either 
state  the  external  conditions  of  gratifying  my  desire  or  the 
desire  which  is  gratified.  It  is  almost  the  same  thing  to  say 
that  I  desire  food  or  that  I  am  hungry,  and  it  depends 
upon  the  particular  circumstances  whether  it  is  more  con- 
venient to  use  one  or  the  other  form  of  expression.  Though 
"almost,"  indeed,  it  is  not  quite  the  same  thing,  for  the 
reason  that  the  external  condition  never  corresponds  abso- 
lutely to  the  internal  state.  A  given  desire  may  be  gratified 
in  various  ways,  and,  again,  a  given  set  of  conditions  may 
gratify  various  desires.  The  statement  that  I  want  a  fire 
expresses  something  more  and  also  something  less  than  the 
statement  that  I  want  to  be  warmed ;  for  I  may  want  a  fire 
in  order  to  cook  my  dinner,  and  I  may  preserve  warmth 
by  putting  on  a  greatcoat.  Hence  it  may  not  be  simply 
tautologous  to  say,   "  I   want  a  fire  because  I  want  to  be 

p 


226  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

warmed/'  for  the  statement  specifies  the  particular  relation 
out  of  several  possible  relations  in  which  a  fire  is  desirable ; 
though  it  would  be  tautologous  to  say,  ''  I  want  the  condi- 
tions of  warmth  because  I  want  to  be  warmed."  I  may, 
indeed,  give  a  reasonable  meaning  even  to  this  latter  state- 
ment, if  the  question  be  whether  the  immediate  cause  of  the 
desire  be  a  change  in  the  external  or  the  internal  conditions. 
I  may,  for  example,  have  a  desire  to  take  food  because  I  am 
hungry,  or  be  hungry  because  the  food  stimulates  my  appetite. 
It  may  be  said  that  in  the  first  case  the  desire  is  an  inde- 
pendent cause,  as  it  arises  from  organic  changes  which  take 
place  independently  of  the  internal  changes,  whilst  in  the 
other  case  the  desire  itself  arises  from  those  changes.  I  may 
ask  how  it  comes  to  pass  that  I  have  certain  feelings,  in 
which  case  I  may  of  course  trace  back  the  series  of  events  as 
far  as  I  please,  and  call  any  one  "  the  cause,"  which  being 
altered,  the  subsequent  events  would  be  altered ;  but  at  the 
time  of  action  the  desire  itself,  to  whatever  it  may  be  due, 
must  be  the  cause  of  conduct. 

8.  Now  the  assertion  that  there  is  both  a  subjective  and  an 
objective  condition  of  conduct  tells  us  nothing  whatever  as 
to  the  nature  of  the  objective  conditions  of  gratification. 
We  gain  nothing  by  changing  from  one  mode  of  statement 
to  the  other.  It  is  idle  to  say  that  I  want  a  thing  because  I 
want  a  thing,  or  to  modify  statements  by  emphasising  in 
one  case  the  want  and  in  the  other  the  thing,  or,  again,  by 
laying  a  special  stress  upon  the  "  I."  Of  course  my  con- 
duct, whatever  it  is,  must  be  conditioned  by  my  desire ;  but 
the  objective  condition  may  be  anything  which  can  affect 
my  desire.  There  is,  therefore,  no  prima  facie  objection  to 
the  hypothesis  that  these  objective  conditions  may  include 
the  happiness  of  others.  There  is  no  more  reason  for  denying 
that  we  may  receive  pleasure  from  the  pleasure  of  another 
man  than  for  doubting  that  we  may  receive  it  from  the 
combustion  of  coal.  The  only  condition  which  we  have  so 
far  assumed  is  tiic  obvious  one  that  I  can  only  desire  that 
which  has  some  relation  to  me,  for  this  is  doubtless  implied 


EGOISTIC  INSTINCTS.  227 

in  saying  that  I  desire  it.  A  desire  for  warmth,  for  example, 
could  not  prompt  a  desire  for  such  a  change  in  the  atmos- 
pheric conditions  as  would  not  affect  my  bodilv  org-anisation. 
The  desire  could  not  be  gratified  by  a  change  in  the  tempera- 
ture of  Sirius  or  a  fire  in  a  desert  island,  for  that  would  be 
to  desire  a  warmth  which  did  not  warm.  In  short,  I  must 
not  so  state  the  objective  conditions  as  to  suppose  that  I  can 
desire  them  when  they  necessarily  part  company  with  the 
subjective  condition.  To  say  that  I  desire  something  is  to 
say  that  the  something  has  an  influence  upon  me,  since  it  has 
an  influence  upon  my  happiness;  and  this  condition  must 
be  noticed,  because,  for  the  reasons  already  noticed,  the 
objective  statement  generally  is  too  wide,  and  includes  other 
conditions  besides  those  which  gratify  my  desires. 

9.  Hence  we  reach  the  problem  which  has  to  be  considered. 
Conduct,  I  have  said,  is  determined  by  feeling,  or,  in  other 
words,  by  happiness  and  unhappiness.  My  happiness,  again, 
depends  at  every  moment  upon  my  relation  to  the  external 
world,  and  this  external  world  is  constituted  partly  of  thing^s 
which  I  assume  to  possess,  and  partly  of  things  which  I  do 
not  assume  to  possess  a  consciousness  analogous  to  my  own. 
I  may  or  may  not  take  into  account  this  external  conscious- 
ness. I  may  regard  an  oyster,  as  I  regard  a  peach,  simply  as 
a  toothsome  morsel,  or  I  may  suppose  him  to  have  a  certain 
capacity  for  pain  or  pleasure.  I  may  regard  my  fellow-men 
in  either  of  these  ways — as  parts  of  a  mechanism  or  as 
sentient  organisms.  It  may  happen  that,  in  the  former 
case,  the  conditions  of  my  happiness  are  identical  with  the 
conditions  of  yours.  I  may  be  unable  to  get  my  own 
dinner  without  by  the  same  action  getting  a  dinner  for  you. 
If  so,  there  is,  we  may  say,  an  external  identity  of  interest 
and  my  conduct  may  be  beneficial  to  you  without  implyino- 
the  existence  in  me  of  any  desire  for  your  happiness  as  such. 
If,  however,  the  knowledge  of  your  happiness  has  an  essential 
and  unconditional  tendency  to  promote  my  happiness,  the 
case  is  so  far  altered.  I  shall  then  make  a  distinction  between 
cases  which  previously  appeared  to  be  identical.     I  shall  not 


228  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

hold  it  to  be  the  same  thing  whether  I  walk  up  a  ladder  of 
wood  or  a  ladder  of  sentient  bodies.  There  is,  as  I  have  said,  no 
a  priori  objection  to  the  hypothesis  that  one  kind  of  feeling 
may  be  as  real  as  the  other;  that  the  object  of  desire  may 
include  the  feelings  of  others,  as  well  as  changes  in  external 
objects  which  do  not  involve  feeling.  But  there  is  the  differ- 
ence that  the  former  kind  of  feeling  admits  of  some  further 
analysis  in  a  sense  not  possible  in  the  other  case,  though  not, 
as  I  think,  in  the  sense  supposed  by  the  egoist.  Given  the 
feeling  of  hunger,  for  example,  I  can  go  no  further  in  the 
subjective  analysis,  though  I  may  assign  the  correlative 
physiological  processes.  It  exists  as  an  ultimate  fact,  and 
so  gives  the  only  sufficient  explanation  of  my  conduct.  But 
if  I  sympathise  with  your  hunger,  there  is  another  process 
implied,  of  which  it  may  be  possible  to  give  some  account.  I 
suffer  because  you  suffer ;  and  he  may  fairly  be  asked  whether 
this  fact  can  be  made  more  intelligible  or  the  conditions  of  its 
occurrence  explained  more  precisely.  Having  done  what  we 
can  in  that  direction,  we  may  be  able  to  return  to  the  original 
problem. 

II.   Sympathy. 

lo.  Now,  in  the  first  place,  the  recognition  that  there  are 
other  centres  of  consciousness  besides  my  own  is  bound  up  in 
the  closest  way  with  the  recognition  of  what  is  called  an 
objective  world.  A  thing  is  held  to  be  objective — in  one 
sense,  at  least,  of  a  most  ambiguous  word — when  I  hold  that 
it  is  perceptible  by  you  as  well  as  by  me,  and  subjective  when 
I  hold  that  it  is  perceptible  by  me  alone.  I  do  not  assert  or 
deny  that  this  is  the  sole  meaning;  but  at  least,  in  assert- 
ing the  objective  existence  of  anything,  I  assert  it  to  exist 
for  others  as  well  as  for  me.  The  statement  is  bound  up  in 
the  process  by  which  my  world  is  constituted.  It  is  the 
power  of  so  regarding  the  world  which  gives  it,  if  I  may  say 
so,  a  stereoscopic  solidity.  Each  person  sees  only  one  aspect 
of  surrounding  realities.  He  holds  it  to  be  real  in  so  far  as 
he  holds  that  other  aspects  are  visible  to  his  neighbours.    The 


SYMPATHY.  229 

actual  sensations  of  every  moment  are  completed  and  held 
together  in  the  mind  by  a  whole  system  of  ideal  perceptions 
more  or  less  distinctly  present  in  actual  consciousness.  The 
room  in  which  I  sit  is  part  of  the  house,  the  house  of  the  city, 
and  so  forth  ;  and  such  statements  summon  into  comparative 
vividness  a  set  of  perceptions  not  actually  present  at  the 
moment,  but  present  to  others,  and  which  would  be  present 
to  me  if  I  changed  my  position. 

II.  To  think  of  anything  as  real  is  to  call  up  a  system 
of  such  ideal  perceptions.     It  is  to  rehearse  a  set  of  sensa- 
tions which  are  somehow  (the  "  how  "  is  a  problem  of  meta- 
physics) regarded  as  representative  of  others  not  actually  pre- 
sent.     If  I  have  to  do  with  simple  relations  of  time  and 
space,  no  assignable  emotion  is  produced.     I  complete  my 
picture  of  the  exterior  of  my  room  by  imagining  what  I  should 
see  from  outside,  and  so  I  may  build  up  a  picture  of  the  whole 
world.     But  the  world  is  interesting  to  me  so  far  as  it  is  the 
dwelling-place  of  myself  and  of  beings  analogous  to  myself. 
The  man  as  directly  revealed  by  my  senses  is  simply  an  object 
of  certain  colours  and  dimensions,  but  the  relations  in  which 
he  is  really  interesting  to  me  are  those  in  which  he  is  moved 
bv  passions  like  my  own.     I  do  not  really  think  of  a  man 
till   I   have  interpreted  the  external  signs  by  the  emotions 
which  they  signify.     Till  I  do  that,  he  is  for  me  merely  a 
coloured  and  moving  statue.     I  know  not  whether  he  will 
be  a  friend  or  an  enemy,  one  who  will  save  or  destroy  my 
life.    To  complete  the  picture,  I  must  therefore  represent  his 
feelings.     I  must  put  myself  in  his  place,  feel  what  he  feels, 
and  measure  his  conduct  by  the  analogy  of  my  own  behaviour 
under  similar  circumstances.    The  process  is  the  same  which 
is  implied  in  every  intellectual  process.     I  imagine  a  state  of 
consciousness  not  actually  present,  and    besides    imagining 
mere  sensations  and  perceptions  of  mechanical  relations,  I 
imagine  a  set  of  emotions  and  reasoning  processes  analogous 
to  my  own.     I  complete  my  picture  of  the  house  by  putting 
myself  outside  in  imagination  ;   I  add  the  imagined  feelings 
of  standing  in  the  rain  and  cold,  and,  in  virtue  of  some  in- 


230  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tellectual  process  not  here  to  be  discussed,  I  take  those  feel- 
ings to  be  representative  of  those  of  the  beggar  at  my  door. 
Till  I  have  rehearsed  those  feelings  I  am  not  really  thinking 
of  the  beo-o-ar,  but  only  of  a  lay-fig-ure  of  certain  dimensions 

CO        ^  -  y  O 

and  colours.  Through  this  mental  operation  alone  is  that 
knowledge  of  the  external  world  conceivable  which  is  yet 
necessary  to  give  coherence  to  our  own  series  of  sensations 
or  to  frame  them  into  anything  that  can  properly  be  called 
knowledge. 

12.  Hence  it  would  appear  that  sympathy  is  not  an 
additional  instinct,  a  faculty  which  is  added  when  the  mind 
has  reached  a  certain  stage  of  development,  a  mere  incident 
of  intellectual  growth,  but  something  implied  from  the  first 
in  the  very  structure  of  knowledge.  I  must  be  capable  of 
representative  ideas  in  order  to  think  coherently  or  to  draw 
the  essential  distinction  between  object  and  subject.  I  must 
be  able  to  regard  certain  modes  of  thought  and  feeling  as 
symbolic  of  modes  present  in  other  minds,  and  to  my  own  in 
other  positions.  To  realise  the  world  as  a  material  whole,  I 
must  have  representative  perceptions  of  time  and  space.  To 
realise  the  world  of  thought  and  feeling,  that  world  upon 
which  my  life  and  happiness  depend  at  every  instant,  I  must 
have  representative  emotions.  "  Put  yourself  in  his  place  " 
is  not  merely  a  moral  precept ;  it  is  a  logical  rule  implied  in 
the  earliest  germs  of  reason  as  a  description  of  reasoning 
itself,  so  far  as  it  deals  with  other  sentient  beings.  To  know 
that  a  man  has  certain  feelings  is  to  have  representative  feel- 
ings, not  equal  in  intensity,  but  identical  in  kind.  Sympathy 
and  reason  have  so  far  an  identical  factor — each  implies  the 
other.  I  cannot  reason  about  another  man  except  in  so  far 
as  I  can  rehearse  his  motives ;  I  cannot  feel  for  him  except 
in  so  far  as  I  can  regard  my  feelings  as  representative.  The 
two  processes  are  mutually  involved,  and^  whatever  difficulties 
may  be  suggested,  it  seems  clear  that  I  cannot  properly  know 
what  another  man  feels  v^ithout  in  some  degree  feeling  what 
he  feels, 

13.  Although  I  must  take  for  granted  the  metaphysical 


SYMPATHY.  231 

implications  of  this  statement,  whatever  they  may  be,  I  must 
dwell  for  a  moment  upon  certain  difTiculties  which  obscure 
it  even  from  the  scientific  point  of  view.  The  mechanism  of 
language  tends  to  introduce  certain  perplexities ;  for  it  is, 
as  I  have  said,  one  main  use  of  language  that  it  enables  us  to 
reason  by  symbols  without  calling  into  distinct  consciousness 
all  the  feelings  which  are  symbolised.  The  arithmetician  per- 
forms his  processes  without  evoking  a  distinct  vision  of  the 
numbers  with  w'hich  he  deals,  or  recalling  the  primary  intui- 
tions which  satisfied  him  of  the  truth  of  his  rules.  We  say 
"  men  "  without  attempting  to  call  up  more  than  a  very  small 
part  of  all  the  thoughts  which  may  at  diflerent  times  be 
suggested  by  the  word.  I  may  say,  "  My  servant  is  ill,  there- 
fore I  will  give  him  a  holiday,"  and  may  act  accordingly, 
though  a  vcrv  faint  image  of  illness,  holidays,  or  servants 
presents  itself  to  my  mind.  When  I  say  that  a  man  has 
been  hanged,  the  expression  is  thus  liable  to  many  ambiguities. 
It  may  suggest  to  me  simply  that  a  figure  of  a  certain  wxight 
and  shape  has  been  suspended  in  a  certain  way.  It  may  call 
up  merely  certain  affections  of  the  senses  of  sight  and  touch ; 
or,  again,  it  may  suggest  certain  visible  signs  of  vital  processes, 
struggling  limbs,  the  gradual  cessation  of  motion,  and  the 
conversion  of  a  moving  and  coherent  into  a  motionless  and  de- 
caying body  ;  or  it  may  further  suggest  the  painful  sensations, 
the  despair,  horror,  and  remorse  which  I  suppose  the  man  to 
have  felt.  I  may  stop  at  the  external  signs,  and  I  may  pass 
beyond  them  to  the  emotions  signified.  And  thus  the  same 
words  may  call  up  the  mental  images  which  would  be  gene- 
rated in  the  most  and  in  the  least  sympathetic  witness,  and 
serve  equally  to  suggest  certain  mechanical  relations  as  to 
stimulate  the  deepest  and  most  complex  emotions.  When, 
therefore,  I  say  that  knowledge  implies  sympathy,  I  of  course 
do  not  mean  to  deny  that  we  may  have  a  knowledge  of  the 
external  fact,  which  is,  for  many  purposes,  all  the  knowledge 
actually  present  to  our  minds,  and  which  implies  no  sympathy 
at  all.  I  need  not  go  beyond  the  feelings  wdiich  would  be 
called  up  by  hanging  a  dead  body,  even  when  I  am  said  to 


232  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

know  that  a  man  has  been  put  to  death  by  hanging.  In 
every  case,  a  large  part  of  the  possible  emotion  remains 
unrealised. 

14.  It  is  more  important,  perhaps,  to  remark  that  I  do  not 
profess  to  give  a  complete  account  of  the  process.  Undoubt- 
edly it  must  be  held  that  the  knowledge  of  the  feeling  is 
something  different  from  a  simple  rehearsal  of  the  feeling. 
The  representative  feeling  may  differ  not  only  in  intensity 
but  also  in  quality  from  that  which  it  represents.  The 
knowledge  that  another  man  is  suffering  gives  rise  to  com- 
plex or  varying  emotions.  Nothing,  of  course,  is  more  com- 
mon than  to  find  that  men  take  pleasure  in  humiliating 
and  mortifying  their  neighbours.  The  critic  rejoices  in  tor- 
menting a  sensitive  poet ;  the  child  delights  in  teazing  his 
playfellows  and  his  animals ;  and  it  is  an  undeniable  though 
a  hideous  fact  that  there  is  such  a  thing  as  a  voluptuous 
pleasure  in  cruelty.  Milton's  "lust  hard  by  hate"  expresses 
a  profound  psychological  truth.  And  such  facts  demand  a 
brief  consideration  in  order  to  show  that  they  are  not  incon- 
sistent with  the  theory  just  stated.  They  are  rather,  as  I 
think,  examples  of  the  danger  which  besets  any  one  who 
tries  to  translate  emotional  laws  into  logic,  and  to  pronounce 
any  variety  of  human  character  impossible  because  it  seems 
to  involve  an  implicit  contradiction. 

15.  Much  cruelty,  in  the  first  place,  means  simple  insen- 
sibilitv.  The  defect  of  sympathy  is  also  an  intellectual  defect. 
The  child  tormenting  an  insect  or  the  savage  abandoning 
his  infant  is  simply  not  capable  (in  the  common  phrase)  of 
enterino;  into  the  feelins^s  of  his  victim.  The  child  is  amused 
by  the  spinning  of  the  cockchafer  as  he  is  by  the  spinning  of 
a  top  ;  it  is  simply  a  curious  bit  of  mechanism.  The  savage 
may  throw  away  a  baby  when  its  cries  are  tiresome  because 
he  does  not  think  of  its  sufferings  at  all.  Cruelty  of  this 
kind  is  therefore  nothing  but  intellectual  torpor,  an  inca- 
pacity for  projecting  oneself  into  the  circumstances  of  others, 
and  therefore  inability  even  to  think  about  the  most  impor- 
tant set  of  conditions  of  the  happiness  of  more  developed 


SYMPATHY.  233 

beings.  The  dulness  which  incapacitates  a  l)Oor  for  appre- 
ciating the  feelings  of  the  refined  nature  is  so  far  a  disquali- 
fication for  all  the  more  complex  social  activities.  And  so 
we  may  observe,  that  as  a  society  becomes  more  civilised,  as 
the  reasoning  faculties  become  quicker  and  wider,  and  the 
power  of  observing  many  relations  between  living  beings 
increases,  there  is  an  improvement  in  the  virtue  of  humanity 
if  in  nothing  else.  To  think  about  other  beings  is  to  stimu- 
late our  sympathies,  and  our  sensibility  is  quickened — to 
the  regret  of  some  people — by  the  same  power  which  implies 
intellectual  progress.  Men  may  be  as  licentious,  and  in 
some  w^ays  as  selfish,  in  the  most  as  in  the  least  civilised 
countries,  but  they  also  become  more  reluctant  to  inflict 
pain,  and  open  their  ears  to  lamentations  which  were  once 
interpreted  as  idle  sound. 

16.  Pleasure,  again,  in  the  sufferings  of  an  enemy  suggests 
more  complex  considerations,  but  we  may  still  distinguish 
between  taking  pleasure  in  pain  simply  as  pain,  and  that  in 
which  pain  is  regarded  as  a  necessary  concomitant  of  some 
other  circumstances.  When  a  man's  interests  are  opposed 
to  my  own,  I  wish  for  something  which  involves  disappoint- 
ment or  vexation  to  him.  Christians  find  pleasure  in  the 
knowledge  that  their  countrymen  have  killed,  mangled,  and 
humiliated  a  large  number  of  foreigners ;  but  the  pain  may 
be  imperfectly  realised,  or,  if  realised,  realised  as  a  drawback. 
The  generous  enemy  becomes  capable  of  the  true  chivalrous 
sentiment,  and  may  desire  a  victory  at  the  smallest  possible 
cost  to  his  enemy.  The  barbarous  sentiment  implied  in  a 
Roman  triumph  may  have  implied  rather  a  want  of  the  per- 
ception that  other  people  had  feelings  than  a  delight  in 
their  suff'ering;  and  in  an  age  when  sympathy  is  wider  this 
delight  becomes  inexpressibly  revolting.  The  most  brutal 
John  Bull  would  hardly  have  wished  to  expose  Napoleon  to 
insult  as  well  as  humiliation.  It  is  simply  reasonable  in  this 
sense  to  love  one's  enemies.  I  might  wish  to  prove  a  rival 
controversialist  to  be  a  fool,  because  a  conviction  of  his 
folly  is  necessary  to  my  vanity,  but  I  should  be  sorry  to 


234  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

hear  that  my  bitterest  or  most  successful  antagonist  was 
suffering  from  a  toothache.  Antagonism,  of  course,  reconciles 
us  to  the  pain  of  our  adversaries,  and  even  allows  the  thought 
of  that  pain  to  be  part  of  a  pleasurable  emotion.  The  sym- 
pathetic pang  which  it  produces  as  represented  by  our 
imagination  is  swallowed  up  by  a  multitude  of  associated 
feelings.  We  desire,  again,  that  a  man  should  suffer  when 
we  feel  that  our  security  is  dependent  upon  his  suffering ; 
and  this  sentiment  enters  for  something  into  the  moral  desire 
of  retribution.  It  is  a  part,  at  least,  of  that  sentiment  that 
the  moral  order  would  be  out  of  joint  if  wrong-doing  did 
not  lead  to  pain.  But  this  sentiment  is  compatible  with, 
though  it  is  not  necessarily  combined  with,  a  horror  of  inflict- 
ing useless  pain  upon  any  one.  Wherever  the  pain,  that  is, 
is  not  essential  as  a  deterrent,  we  have  so  far  less  desire  for 
its  infliction.  I  should  be  heartily  glad  to  know  that  the 
most  detestable  criminal  had,  by  some  accident,  become 
insensible  to  the  punishment  which  I  think  it  right  should 
be  inflicted.  I  do  not  assert  that  this  is  a  necessary  or  even 
the  general  feeling ;  but  so  far  as  we  regard  punishment  as 
useful,  that  is,  as  having  consequences  productive  of  happi- 
ness to  others,  we  do  not  desire  pain  in  itself.  Whatever 
other  motives  may  be  operative,  this  is  one  ingredient  in 
tbc  desire  for  justice,  and  even  to  some  extent  in  the  desire 
or  vengeance ;  and,  so  far  as  it  exists,  we  must  admit  that 
pain  is  only  desired  for  extrinsic  motives.  It  is  not  considered 
as  a  good  thing  in  itself,  but  as  part  of  the  conditions  of 
good  to  others  than  the  sufferer. 

17.  Fresh  complexities  are  introduced  when  we  come  to 
the  enmity  which  implies  not  a  mere  antagonism  of  interests 
but  a  personal  dislike  to  others.  Sympathy,  in  the  sense  in 
which  I  am  using  the  w^ord,  may  give  rise  to  antipathy. 
We  are  led  to  detest  a  man's  character  because  we  can  partly 
share  his  feelings.  The  saint  and  the  sensualist  can  each 
enter  into  the  motives  of  the  other.  The  saint  is  still 
accessible  to  the  brutal  passions  which  it  has  been  the  labour 
of  his  life  to  master.     It  is  the  wild  beast  within  him  which 


SYMPATHY. 


-JS 


he  sees  incarnated  in  another  agent,  and  which  awakes  his 
horror  and  disirust.  Conversely  the  sensuahst  mav  see  in 
the  saint  the  triumphant  conscience  which  can  still  inflict 
pangs  of  remorse  upon  himself,  though  it  cannot  restrain  his 
conduct.  There  are  conflictino;  elements  in  the  character 
of  every  man,  and  parts  of  ourselves  which  we  regard  with 
horror  in  memory,  though  under  some  special  stimulus  they 
may  overpower  all  restraining  motives.  We  can  sympathise 
with  other  men,  that  is,  realise  their  feelings  in  imagination, 
because  their  character  contains  the  same  primary  instinct ; 
and  this  sympathy  gives  rise  to  admiration  or  contempt  as 
the  consciousness  of  our  own  qualities  gives  rise  to  vanity  or 
humiliation,  when  the  action  shows  that  the  dominating 
motives  differ  in  certain  ways  from  those  which,  at  the  time 
of  reflection,  appear  to  us  to  be  natural  and  becoming.  We 
may  thus  come  to  regard  a  man  as  a  mischievous  agency  in 
the  world,  as  predestined  by  his  very  constitution,  and  not 
from  mere  accidents  of  circumstance,  to  thwart  and  humiliate 
us,  and  as  embodying  those  sentiments  which  we  detest  the 
more  heartily  as  we  can  realise  them  the  more  vividly.  He  is 
a  nuisance  to  be  abated,  a  corrupting  or  discordant  element 
in  the  general  system  of  things ;  and  therefore  we  must  take 
pleasure  in  conditions  which  necessarily  involve  his  suffering 
or  destruction. 

1 8.  I  do  not  attempt  to  give  any  analysis  of  such  cases. 
It  is  enough  to  say  that  in  the  complex  mechanism  of  human 
motives  we  may  often  come  to  results  which  apparently 
conflict  with  the  principles  from  which  they  are  deduced. 
Even  in  such  personal  antipathies  the  sympathy  is  the 
fundamental  fact.  The  hatred  which  is  generated  is  always 
a  more  or  less  painful  emotion,  because  our  spontaneous 
sympathy  leads  in  any  case  to  some  conflict  of  motives.  We 
cannot  hate  the  man  without  feeling  that  some  of  our  own 
feelings  are  taking  part  against  ourselves.  And,  further,  the 
feeling  of  hatred  is  perfectly  compatible  with  an  entire  absence 
of  anything  like  delight  in  pain.  We  may  simply  desire  to 
keep  the  disagreeable  person  at  a  distance,  to  restrain  his 


236  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

activity  or  divert  it  into  a  harmless  channel^  to  convert  him 
to  better  modes  of  feeling  and  so  forth.  It  is  only  when  we 
are  so  related  that  our  satisfaction  necessarily  implies  his 
misery  that  we  are  tempted  actually  to  desire  his  suffering. 
The  distinction  between  hating  the  sin  and  hating  the  sinner 
is  often  hvpocritical  enough^  but  it  also  expresses  the  rational 
conviction  that  all  pain  is  in  itself  bad  aiid  painful  to  con- 
template, though  it  may  be  inseparably  connected  with  desir- 
able results. 

19,  But  it  remains  to  be  admitted  that  there  is  apparently 
such  a  thing  as  pleasure  in  the  pain  of  others — pure  malignity, 
which  we  call  devilish,  to  mark  that  it  is  abnormal  and  signi- 
ficant of  a  perverted  nature.  The  existence  of  such  a  feeling 
is  a  puzzle  such  as  that  which  psychologists  have  discussed 
under  the  name  of  the  ^Muxury  of  grief."  Sentimentalists 
seem,  at  any  rate,  to  delight  in  cultivating  sorrow,  which  is 
apparently  a  still  more  contradictory  state  of  mind  than 
delight  in  the  sufferings  of  others.  The  explanation,  so  far 
as  it  need  be  considered  here,  seems  to  depend  upon  the  fact 
that  there  is  a  certain  pleasure  in  almost  every  kind  of  excite- 
ment. We  like  what  relieves  the  dulness  of  our  lives  and 
provides  some  channel  for  emotional  discharge.  The  sluggish 
and  brutal  nature  delights  in  the  stimulus  of  horror ;  in  spec- 
tacles of  blood  and  death,  even  though  it  would  appear  at 
first  siffht  that  heio-htened  excitement  meant  necessarilv  a 
heightening  of  disgust.  Men  apparently  humane  and  sensitive 
have  taken  delight  in  executions.  The  Romans  took  pleasure 
in  the  sight  of  dying  gladiators ;  Spaniards,  in  the  sight  of 
mangled  bulls  and  horses ;  an  English  mob  is  fascinated  by 
a  sickening  accident  in  the  streets ;  and  possibly  we  may 
trace  a  remnant  of  the  same  feeling  in  the  pleasure  given  by 
the  horrible  in  tragedies  or  by  "sensational"  incidents  in 
modern  romance.  We  have,  again,  the  more  hideous  cases 
in  which  cruelty  seems  to  afford  a  kind  of  voluptuous  delight, 
as  in  some  historical  monsters  who  made  an  art  of  torture. 
Almost  any  pungent  sensation,  though  provocative  of  sheer 
disgust  to  the  sensitive,  seems  to  yield  a  kind  of  pleasure  to 


SYMPATHY.  237 

some  natures.  The  problem  must  be  left  to  the  psychologist. 
It  is  enough  here  to  say^  first,  that  in  all  such  cases  the  pain, 
whether  original  or  reflected,  is  but  one  strand  in  a  highly 
complex  thread  of  feeling,  and  may  produce  its  efl'ect  as  a 
counter-irritant,  or  as  heightening  other  sensations  which  are 
in  alliance  with  it ;  and,  secondly,  that  it  is  in  any  case  a 
comparatively  rare  and  abnormal  phenomenon,  due  to  some 
morbid  condition  of  the  faculties,  or  perhaps  to  the  survival 
of  ferocious  instincts  from  times  when  the  intellect  and 
the  sympathies  were  comparatively  dormant.  Sympathy  is 
the  natural  and  fundamental  fact.  Even  the  most  brutal 
of  mankind  are  generally  sympathetic  so  far  as  to  feel  rather 
pain  than  pleasure  at  the  sight  of  suflering.  The  scum  of  a 
civilised  population  gathered  to  pick  pockets  on  a  racecourse 
would  be  pained  at  the  sight  of  a  child  in  danger  of  being 
run  over  or  being  brutally  assaulted  by  a  ruffian,  and  would 
be  disposed  to  rescue  it,  or  at  least  to  cheer  a  rescuer,  luiless 
their  spontaneous  emotion  were  overpowered  by  some  ex- 
trinsic sentiment. 

20.  If  this  account  of  the  sympathetic  emotions  be  approxi- 
mately accurate,  we  see  that  sympathy  is  implied  in  all 
thoughts  about  others.  Though  it  generates  antipathy  and 
discord  in  numberless  cases,  the  underlying  and  governing 
process  is  sympathetic.  We  may  say  that  we  think  about 
other  men  by  becoming  other  men.  We  appropriate  pro- 
visionally their  circumstances  and  emotions.  Metaphysicians 
and  mystics  have  expressed  this  by  denying  the  ultimate 
validity  of  individuality,  and  by  saying  that  in  some  trans- 
cendental sense  a  man  is  his  neighbour,  or  that  all  men  are 
manifestations  of  one  indivisible  substance.  The  lantjuao'e, 
though  to  my  mind  untenable,  may  serve  to  express  the  fact. 
So  far  as  I  svmpathise  with  you  I  annex  your  conscious- 
ness. I  act  as  though  my  nerves  could  somehow  be  made 
continuous  with  yours  in  such  a  w'ay  that  a  blow  which  fell 
upon  your  frame  would  convey  a  sensation  to  my  brain. 
Undoubtedly  we  must  add  that  this  current,  so  transmitted, 
is  greatly  enfeebled  in  almost  all  cases.     The  reflex  feeling  is 


238  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

normally  far  less  acute  than  the  direct.  The  thought  of  the 
pains  of  starvation  does  not  produce  a  pain  at  all  comparable 
to  starvation  itself.  And  as  the  represented  object  is  distant 
in  time  and  space,  the  sensibility  becomes  rapidly  dulled. 
Most  men  have  great  difficulty  in  forming  any  vivid  repre- 
sentation of  distant  suffering.  The  actual  sight  of  a  stranger  in 
agony  gives  a  keener  feeling  at  the  moment  than  the  image 
of  a  brother  dying  at  the  antipodes ;  and  the  most  bene- 
volent of  men  hears  with  great  composure  of  the  destruction 
of  millions  in  China.  It  may,  on  the  other  hand,  be  remarked 
in  passing,  that  the  suffering  of  another  person  may  stimulate 
a  sympathetic  person  under  certain  conditions  more  forcibly 
than  similar  sufferings  of  his  own.  The  image  may  inci- 
dentally set  in  motion  a  whole  current  of  accumulated  feeling. 
A  man  who  has  been  watching  the  sickbed  of  a  wife  may 
be  more  moved  by  an  accident  to  her  than  by  one  to  himself, 
not  because  the  sight  of  her  pain  is  keener  than  his  own 
pain  in  itself,  but  because  it  fires  a  whole  train  of  anxieties, 
hopes,  and  fears  already  prepared  for  explosion.  So  I  may 
take  enormous  trouble  to  give  a  very  slight  pleasure  to  a 
man  whom  I  like,  not  because  I  feel  his  pleasures  more  than 
my  own,  but  because  the  desire  to  do  him  honour  is  so  strong 
that  I  am  glad  to  find  any  vent  for  it,  however  trifling  in 
itself. 

21.  Finally,  if  this  be  the  true  account  of  the  process,  the 
difficulty  is  not  to  understand  why  the  thought  of  your  pain 
!-hould  give  me  pain,  but  to  understand  how  it  should  ever 
give  me  pleasure.  It  is  not  more  true  that  to  think  of  a  fire 
is  to  revive  the  sensations  of  warmth,  than  it  is  true  that 
to  think  of  a  man  is  to  revive  the  emotions  and  thou2;ht 
which  we  attribute  to  him.  To  think  of  him  in  any  other 
sense  is  to  think  of  the  mere  doll  or  statue,  the  outside 
framework,  not  of  the  organised  mass  of  consciousness  which 
determines  all  the  relations  in  which  he  is  most  deeply  in- 
teresting to  us.  llie  primary  sympathy  is  of  course  modified 
in  a  thousand  ways — by  the  ease  or  difficulty  with  which  wc 
can  adopt  his  feelings ;  by  the  attractiveness  or  repulsive- 


ALTRUISM.  239 

ness  of  the  feelings  revealed  ;  by  the  degree  \n  which  circum- 
stances force  us  into  co-operation  or  antagonism ;  and  by 
innumerable  incidental  associations  which  make  it  pleasant 
or  painful  to  share  his  feelings.  Tf  by  sympathy  we  mean 
this  power  of  vicarious  emotion^  it  may  give  rise  to  anti- 
pathv,  to  hatred,  rivalry,  and  jealousy,  and  even  to  the 
diabolical  perversion  of  pleasure  in  others'  pain  ;  but  the 
direct  and  normal  case  is  that  in  which  sympathy  leads  to 
genuine  altruism_,  or  feeling  in  conformity  with  that  which 
it  reflects. 

III.  Altruism. 

22.  We  may  now  return  to  the  original  problem,  what 
is  implied  in  unselfish  or  altruistic  conduct?  Sympathy,  in 
the  sense  explained,  is  not  identical  with  altruism,  but  it  is 
the  essential  condition  of  altruism.  I  cannot  be  truly  altru- 
istic, that  is,  until  the  knowledge  of  another  man's  pain  is 
painfid  to  me.  That  is  the  groundwork  of  the  more  complex 
sentiments  which  are  involved  in  all  truly  moral  conduct, 
morality  implying  the  existence  of  certain  desires  which  have 
for  their  immediate  object  the  happiness  of  others.  I  have 
tried  to  consider  briefly  the  nature  of  this  underlying  senti- 
ment. We  have  now  to  say  precisely  in  what  sense  it  leads  to 
self-sacrifice ;  but  we  have  still  to  get  rid  of  certain  ambigui- 
ties which  perplex  the  discussion  before  giving  the  answer, 
which  is  in  itself,  as  I  hold,  sufficiently  clear. 

23.  How  does  altruistic  conduct  differ  from  that  which  is 
not  altruistic?  Obviously  (if  my  theory  be  sound)  it  does 
not  differ  in  any  sense  which  would  imply  that  my  conduct 
can  ever  spring  from  anything  but  my  own  feelings.  So  far  as 
my  actions  can  be  said  to  be  determined  by  anything  else,  they 
are  not  properly  my  actions.  I  am  in  such  cases  part  of  the 
mechanism  set  in  action  by  some  external  force,  whether  it 
be  the  will  of  another  agent  or  some  mechanical  circumstance. 
Mv  limbs  arc  for  the  time  part  of  another  man's  limbs. 
Voluntary  action,  or  action  determined  by  the  motives  of  the 
agent,  is  the  definition  of  what  is  strictly  conduct.    I  may  be 


240  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

prompted  by  pains  and  pleasures  which  represent  those  of 
another  man,  but  they  must  not  the  less  be  my  pains  and 
pleasures.  Hence  we  must  exclude  two  alternative  errors 
resulting  from  the  neglect  either  of  the  objective  or  the  sub- 
jective conditions  of  conduct,  and  therefore  of  the  fact  that 
both  must  always  be  present.  We  may  speak,  for  example,  of 
a  man  as  preferring  the  pleasure  of  another  to  his  own.  We 
must  in  such  a  case  be  understood  to  mean,  not  that  the 
motives  of  the  other  take  the  place  of  his  own  motives, 
which  is  as  absurd  as  to  say  that  the  food  eaten  by  the  other 
nourishes  his  own  organs,  but  that  the  sympathy  is  stronger 
than  other  conflicting  motives.  When,  for  example,  Sidney 
gives  the  water  to  the  soldier,  it  is  not  because  Sidney 
actually  feels  the  soldier's  thirst,  but  because  Sidney's  sym- 
pathy for  the  soldier's  sufferings  is  a  stronger  motive  than  his 
own  thirst.  Sidney's  conduct,  as  that  of  the  most  selfish 
man,  is  always  determined  by  his  own  feelings ;  but  in  his 
case  the  sympathetic  feelings  have  so  great  a  share  in  de- 
termining conduct,  that  his  compassion  is  stroiiger  than  his 
thirst.  Normally,  indeed^  we  may  say  that  the  reflected  feel- 
ing will  be  weaker  than  the  original,  the  feeling  produced 
by  the  thirst  of  another  than  the  feeling  due  to  my  own 
thirst ;  but  this  direct  sympathy  may  be  enforced  by  others, 
by  a  sense  of  duty,  justice,  and  so  forth,  so  as  to  have  a 
greater  effect  upon  the  conduct.  In  any  case,  so  far  as  it  is 
operative,  it  must  be  a  feeling  of  the  agent,  and  does  not 
imply  that  he  acts  without  feeling  or  is  moved  by  another 
man's  motives,  but  that  the  feeling  which  is  due  to  his 
knowledge  of  another  man's  feelings  is  abnormally  strong. 

24.  On  the  other  hand,  it  is  equally  erroneous  to  speak  of 
motives  as  being  '' selfish"  in  any  other  sense  than  that 
already  implied,  simply  because  they  are  my  own.  This  fallacy 
has  already  been  noticed.  If  I  say,  "  I  dislike  the  taste  of 
wine  because  it  is  unpleasant  to  me/'  I  either  say  the  same 
thing  twice  or  I  use  words  in  different  senses.  I  may  mean 
to  imply  that  I  dislike  the  taste  because  the  immediate  sensa- 
tion is  disagreeable,  and  to  exclude  the  hypothesis  that  I  dis- 


ALTRUISM.  241 

like  the  taste  because  I  think  it  an  indication  of  unwhole- 
some qualities,  or  have  some  accidental  association  which 
overpowers  the  pleasantness  of  the  taste.  In  that  case,  I  use 
'^dislike"  to  include  feeline^s  different  from  the  immediate  sen- 
sation,  and  '^ unpleasant ^^  to  denote  the  sensation  alone;  and 
so  far  my  statement  may  be  reasonable,  though  ambiguously 
expressed.  Now  the  egoist  sometimes  falls  into  a  similar 
ambiguity  in  discussing  the  question  of  altruism.  To  say,  "  I 
dislike  your  pain,"  and  to  say,  "  Your  pain  is  painful  to  me," 
is  to  say  the  very  same  thing  in  different  words ;  but  the 
second  statement  is  something  given  as  an  explanation  of 
the  first,  and  not  as  a  simple  inversion.  The  inference  thus 
insinuated  is  that  I  dislike  your  pain  because  it  is  painful  to 
me  in  some  special  relation.  I  do  not  dislike  it  as  your  pain, 
but  in  virtue  of  some  particular  consequence,  such,  for 
example,  as  its  making  you  less  able  to  render  me  a  service. 
But  this  is  really  to  assert  that  your  pain  does  not  give  me 
pain  except  as  a  link  in  a  chain  of  events  which  brings  about 
some  other  disagreeable  consequence.  In  that  case,  I  do  not 
really  object  to  your  pain  so  far  as  it  is  your  pain,  but  only 
by  some  removable  and  accidental  consequence.  What  I 
really  dislike  is  that  consequence,  whatever  it  may  be;  and 
thus  the  statement  that  I  dislike  your  pain  becomes  perverted 
into  the  assertion  that  I  dislike  something  else ;  or,  in  other 
words,  it  is  inferred  that  sympathy  is  a  mere  delusion. 

25.  This,  indeed,  is  expressly  asserted  by  some  psychologists, 
who  resolve  sympathetic  emotions  into  a  product  of  associa- 
tion, and  explain  regard  and  dislike  to  the  suffering  of  others 
as  a  case  of  dislike  to  the  means  which  survives,  when  we 
have  forgotten,  for  a  time  at  least,  the  ends  to  which  they 
originally  owed  their  attractiveness.  If  I  am  right  in  the 
foregoing  argument,  that  is  a  totally  inadequate  explanation 
of  the  phenomenon.  The  pain  due  to  the  pain  of  others  is  a 
direct  and  necessary  result  of  the  very  process  of  thinking 
about  others.  A  process  of  association  is  no  doubt  implied, 
in  so  far  as  it  is  only  by  association  (so  at  least  I  should  say)  that 
we  can  learn  to  interpret  certain  sounds,  sights,  and  so  forth, 

a 


242  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

as  indicative  of  the  emotions  of  others.  But  we  must  so 
interpret  them  in  order  to  reason  at  all  about  the  world  of 
thought  and  feelings  and  in  so  interpreting  them  we  learn  to 
sympathise.  Your  pain  is  not  painful  to  me  because  I  infer 
that  some  other  consequence  will  result  to  me^  but  because 
the  thought  of  your  pain  is  itself  painful. 

26.  This^  indeed,  introduces  another  consideration  which 
must  be  taken  into  account.     It  is,  in  fact,  true  that  vour 
pain  can  only  be  painful  to  me  under  a  certain  condition ; 
the  condition,  namely,  that  I  must  know  of  it  or  believ^e  in 
it.     The  sympathetic  emotions,  in  other  words,  are  clearly 
dependent  upon  a  reasoning  process,  which  cannot  be  said 
of  some  other  feelings ;  and  we  may  ask  how  far  this  may 
suggest  any  distinction  between  the  altruistic  and  the  non- 
altruistic  emotions.     It  does  obviously  suggest  a  distinction 
which  is  ofttimes  of  great  importance,  and  which  shows  that 
there  is  a  gap  between  simple  sympathy  and  fully  developed 
altruism.     We  may,  in  fact,  admit  that  your  pain  may  be 
intrinsically  painful  to  me  without  admitting  that  I,  there- 
fore, become  altruistic  in  the  fullest  sense.     Sympathy  may 
establish  only  a  temporary  coincidence,   not  a    permanent 
identity  of  interest.     You  and  I  are  at  one  so  far  as  it  is  true 
that  the  relief  of  your  suffering  would  relieve  me ;  but  we  are 
not  really  one,  and  therefore  my  suffering  may  be  relievable 
by  means  which  would  not  relieve  yours.     If  we  were  in- 
separably united ;  if,  for    example,  we   were  confined  in  a 
single  cell,  so  that  I  necessarily  had  your  sufferings   con- 
stantly before  my  eyes,  and  could  not  get  rid  of  the  svm- 
pathetic  pain  without  getting  rid  of  its  cause,  the  original 
pain,  our  interests  would  be  so  far  identical,  and  it  would 
seem  to  be  an  unimportant  subtlety  to  consider  whether  my 
desire  for  your  comfort  were  properly  to  be  called  selfish  or 
altruistic.     The  same  conduct  would  be  dictated  on  either 
hypothesis,  as  our  interests  would  Ijc  virtually  identical.     It 
is  clear,  however,  that  this  identity  can  never  be  perfectly 
realised.     The  pain  given  by  your  pain  may  simply  induce 
me  to  shut  my  eyes.     The  Pharisee  who  passed  by  on  the 


ALTRUISM.  243 

other  side  may  have  disHked  the  sldit  of  the  wounded 
traveller  as  mueh  as  the  good  Samaritan.  Indeed  the  sight 
of  suffering  often  directs  irritation  against  the  sufferer. 
Dives  is  often  angry  with  Lazarus  for  exposing  his  sores 
before  a  respectable  mansion ;  and  sometimes  goes  so  far  as 
to  think^  illogically  perhaps^  that  the  beggar  must  have  cul- 
tivated his  misery  in  order  to  irritate  the  nerves  of  his  neigh- 
bours. To  give  the  order,  "Take  away  that  damned  Lazarus/' 
may  be  as  natural  an  impulse  as  to  say,  '^Give  him  the  means 
of  curing  his  ailments." 

27.  The  fact  thus  stated  is  undeniable.  It  must  be 
observed  that  the  limitation  which  it  implies  does  not  apply 
to  the  sympathetic  motives,  but  to  every  instinct  of  our 
natures,  in  so  far  as  they  involve  a  belief  in  the  distant  or 
the  future.  We  do  not  wonder  that  a  man  should  continue 
to  suffer  from  a  disease  because  we  see  at  once  that  he  cannot 
help  it;  but  we  think  of  a  sympathetic  emotion  as  some- 
thing which  can  be  helped.  We  can,  we  say,  dismiss  or 
entertain  a  thought  at  our  pleasure.  It  is  painful  to  think 
of  a  neighbour's  disease.  Then  cease  to  think  of  it.  The 
remedy  is  in  every  one's  hands.  Why  not  adopt  it  ?  To 
this  we  may  answer,  in  the  first  place,  that,  as  a  matter  of 
fact,  it  is  very  generally  adopted.  People  reconcile  them- 
selves very  quickly  to  the  misfortunes  of  others,  and  pre- 
cisely by  ceasing  to  think  about  them.  Not  only  so,  but 
in  many  cases  the  remedy  is  not  only  common,  but  often 
irresistible,  and  often  (though  I  am  perhaps  anticipating) 
perfectly  consistent  with  morality.  I  do  not  worry  myself 
about  the  bad  government  of  Timbuctoo  much  more  than  I 
worry  mvself  about  the  uninhabitable  condition  of  the  moon, 
and  for  the  same  reason — that  I  can  do  nothing  to  improve 
either.  It  would  seem  to  be  a  general  law  that  feelings 
which  do  not  or  cannot  produce  any  effect  upon  conduct 
tend  to  become  faint,  and  ultimately  to  disappear.  And, 
morally  speaking,  deliberate  indulgence  in  emotions  of  the 
painful  kind  at  least,  which  bear  no  fruit  in  action, 
is  so  much  w-astc  of  power,  and  so  far  condemnable.      If 


24+  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

I  am  dreaming"  about  the  millennium  or  fretting  about  the 
evils  of  Chinese  despotism,  I  am  throwing  away  energies 
which  might  improve  the  pauperism  of  London  or  contribute 
to  the  social  enjoyments  of  my  next-door  neighbours.  But 
to  say  generally  that  I  can  annihilate  my  sympathies  because 
they  give  me  pain  is  clearly  untrue.  I  can  only  abolish 
thoughts  when  there  is  a  sufficient  motive  to  lead  me  into  a 
different  train  of  thought.  I  can  perhaps  get  rid  of  the 
thought  of  my  neighbour's  suffering  more  easily  than  I  can 
get  rid  of  certain  material  conditions.  But  the  simple  fact 
that  a  particular  emotion  is  dependent  for  its  existence  upon 
an  intellectual  state  does  not  enable  men  to  suppress  it.  I 
should  perhaps  be  happier  if  I  could  forget  that  a  surgeon 
was  in  the  next  room  ready  to  operate  upon  me  in  an  hour, 
but  I  cannot  therefore  fix  ray  mind  upon  a  novel.  The 
general  who  broods  over  possible  defeat  after  giving  his 
orders,  the  speculator  who  has  a  foretaste  of  ruin  which  he 
cannot  avoid,  are  on  the  highroad  to  suicide.  Yet  the 
actual  pain,  added  to  the  knowledge  that  the  reflection  only 
aggravates  the  evil,  leaves  men  unable  to  distract  their 
minds,  or  to  refrain  from  drinking  the  bitter  cup  by  antici- 
pation as  well  as  in  reality.  The  sympathetic  emotions  are 
equally  potent.  When  a  blow  is  hanging  over  my  familv, 
when  I  see  symptoms  of  deadly  and  incurable  disease  in  wife 
and  child,  I  cannot  dispel  my  melancholy,  however  clearly  I 
know  it  to  be  useless.  It  must  be  added  that,  although  I 
have  spoken  of  sympathy  with  pain,  partly  because  it  is  the 
keenest  and  most  conspicuous  phenomenon,  it  is  also  true 
that  great  part  of  our  pleasure  is  dependent  upon  sympathy, 
and  that  the  two  are  inseparably  associated.  If  I  am  to  live 
with  my  friends,  I  must  share  both  their  joys  and  sorrows; 
and  the  real  question  which  I  have  to  decide  is  not  whether 
I  will  drop  a  particular  pain,  but  whether  I  will  or  will  not 
live  the  wider  or  the  narrower  existence.  If  I  can  abstract 
my  mind  from  thoughts  of  danger  to  my  wife  and  child,  I 
also  must  give  up  all  the  enjoyment  which  is  involved  in  the 
close  companionship. 


ALTRUISM.  245 

28.  The  true  statement  would  therefore  recognise  the  fact 
that  emotions  are  inevitable,  whether  sympathetic  or  not, 
in  proportion  not  simply  to  the  pain  and  pleasure  at  the 
moment,  but  to  the  intensity  and  to  the  degree  in  which 
they  form  part  of  my  world — the  world  which  is  constituted 
not  by  the  mere  sensations,  but  by  the  whole  system  of 
thoughts  and  emotions  sustained  by  the  framework  of  per- 
ception. I  can  no  more  strike  out  at  will  a  fragment  of  the 
world  which  is  recos^nised  throutrh  the  intellect,  than  of  that 
which  is  directly  revealed  through  the  sensations.  The  two 
form  a  continuous  whole,  which  is  only  modified  in  a  sub- 
ordinate degree  by  the  shrinking  from  pain  or  the  absorption 
in  pleasure.  An  emotion  closely  bound  up  with  some  vivid 
sensation  or  perception  from  which  I  cannot  free  myself 
is  so  far  the  more  inevitable.  This  is  equally  true  whether 
sympathetic  feeling  is  present  or  absent.  As  a  fact,  it  is 
generally  easier  to  get  rid  of  a  sick  friend  than  of  a  tooth- 
ache; but  the  pain  of  suffering  with  him  may  generate  the 
desire  to  relieve  his  sufferings  rather  than  the  desire  to  forget 
them,  if  his  life  is  so  bound  up  with  my  own  that  the  selfish 
remedy  is  in  fact  impossible  under  existing  conditions,  or  if 
the  action  of  desertion  appears  to  me  as  so  repulsive  in  itself 
that  the  pain  of  the  sympathy  is  overpowered  by  the  pain- 
fulness  of  actino;  badlv. 

29.  This  consideration  shows  that  the  degree  in  which  our 
happiness  is  associated  with  the  happiness  of  others  is  closer 
than  we  might  at  first  sight  suppose.  It  may  be  necessary^ 
to  my  happiness  that  I  should  relieve  Lazarus,  not  only 
when  he  is  actually  present,  or  when  I  foresee  some  ill  con- 
sequences to  me  from  his  misfortunes,  but  also  when  I  am, 
for  any  reason,  unable  to  dismiss  the  thought  of  his  suffer- 
ings. In  many  cases  this  may  be  impossible  without  such 
a  dislocation  of  my  whole  system  of  thought  and  feeling  as 
may,  for  some  reason,  be  impossible.  But  we  cannot  yet 
say  that  my  conduct  is  altruistic  until  wc  know  what  is  the 
condition  which  makes  it  impossible  for  me  to  separate  my 
interests    from    those  of  the  other.     I  am  still,  it  mav  be 


246  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

ur2;ed,  as  selfish  in  desiring  relief  from  the  vicarious  as  from 
the  original  pain.  I  desire  a  fire  as  warming  and  a  friend's 
happiness  as  cheering ;  the  desire  for  warmth  could  not 
prompt  a  desire  for  a  fire  which  could  not  warm — say,  a 
fire  in  the  moon — except  by  a  mistaken  inference  or  an 
arbitrary  association  of  ideas ;  and  similarly  it  may  be  said 
that  sympathy  can  only  prompt  the  desire  for  a  friend's 
happiness  in  so  far  as  it  cheers  me.  That  is  to  say,  it  is  still 
my  own  happiness  which  I  desire.  The  association  of  my 
own  happiness  with  that  of  my  friend's  is  still  extrinsic.  I 
am  sympathetic  but  not  truly  altruistic.  If  and  wherever 
they  can  be  separated,  therefore,  I  shall  be  decided  simply 
by  the  consideration  of  the  consequences  to  me.  Wherever 
it  is  possible  to  obtain  relief  from  the  sympathetic  pain  by 
abolishing  Lazarus  instead  of  making  him  happy,  I  shall 
abolish  him.  This,  it  may  be  said,  remains  equally  true 
whether  the  tie  which  binds  me  to  Lazarus  is  such  as  does 
or  does  not  involve  conditions  dependent  upon  any  intel- 
lectual inferences  and  beliefs.  I  shall  always,  in  any  case, 
prefer  that  course  of  conduct  which  is  possible  (and  that  of 
course  is  always  a  condition),  and  which  promises  the  greatest 
happiness. 


IV.   The  Rule  of  Cofidud. 

30.  This  is  the  question,  then,  which  must  be  discussed  in 
order  to  bring  out  the  real  meaning  of  the  question  at  issue. 
So  far,  in  fact,  as  we  have  hitherto  gone,  we  have  not  recog- 
nised any  difference  between  the  conduct  which  does  and  that 
which  docs  not  imply  the  presence  of  sympathetic  motive. 
In  both  cases  there  is  a  subjective  and  an  objective  condition  ; 
in  both  cases  I  am  prompted  by  my  own  feelings  to  do  what 
is  pleasantest  to  myself.  I  do  so  equally  whether  I  drink 
the  water  myself  or  give  it  to  the  sufferer  by  my  side. 
Where,  then,  is  the  difference  ?  Since  it  cannot  be  in  the 
fact  that  in  one  case  I  have  and  in  the  other  I  have  not 
feelings,  it  can  only  be  in  the  different  law  of  the  feeling. 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  247 

In  both  cases  I  do  what  makes  me  happy^  but  that  which 
makes  me  happy  is  very  different  in  the  two  cases.  A  desire 
for  warmth  can  only  prompt  a  desire  for  the  fire  which 
warms,  and  a  desire  for  the  happiness  of  another  only  the 
happiness  which  cheers.  The  statement  is  the  precise  equi- 
valent of  the  other,  if  we  keep  strictly  to  the  same  meaning. 
But  when  we  ask  what  will  be  the  law  of  the  feeling,  we  see 
at  once  that  there  is  an  important  difference.  What  happi- 
ness will  cheer  me  ?  Any  happiness  in  which  I  believe  and 
which  I  can  realise.  Time  and  distance  have  no  significance 
to  me  except  as  diminishing  the  vividness  of  the  impression. 
If  it  is  painful  to  me  to  realise  your  suffering  when  I  see  the 
knife  cutting  your  flesh,  it  is  painful  to  me  in  a  certain 
proportion  to  think  of  the  same  torture  to  you  in  a  distant 
region.  As  non-sympathetic,  I  can  desire  only  the  fire 
which  warms  me  and  which  will  warm  me ;  as  sympathetic, 
I  desire  the  fire  which  warms  you  in  the  arctic  regions  or 
provides  warmth  for  a  distant  posterity.  My  feelings  are  still 
my  own  in  either  case,  but  in  the  latter  case  they  may  prompt 
me  to  conduct — such,  for  example,  as  economy  in  fuel  for 
the  sake  of  my  grandchildren's  hearths — from  which  I  shall 
derive  no  benefit.  Hence,  so  far  as  sympathy  is  real,  it  obeys 
a  law  which  has  no  necessary  reference  to  any  future  state 
of  my  own ;  it  may  operate  powerfully  even  in  opposition  to 
any  prospect  of  my  happiness  to  come.  The  present  pain  is 
the  reflection  of  pain  which  depends  upon  conditions  which 
have  no  definite  or  uniform  relation  to  my  future  happiness, 
nor,  therefore,  to  the  total  happiness  which  I  contemplate 
from  a  given  course  of  conduct. 

31.  With  these  explanations  we  may  come  to  the  direct 
issue.  Admitting  that  my  conduct  must  always  be  con- 
ditioned by  my  feelings — by  my  aversion  to  painful  and 
attraction  to  pleasurable  states — are  my  feelings  necessarily 
determined  by  the  balance  of  anticipated  pain  and  pleasure  ? 
Does  the  conviction  that  a  certain  course  of  conduct  will 
obtain  for  me  the  maximum  of  pleasure  determine  me  neces- 
sarily to   adopt   it  ?      Does  that  action  always    make   me 


248  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

happiest  which  promises  most  happiness  to  me?  If  these 
statements  are  mutually  equivalent^  it  would  seem  that 
sympathy  must  be  an  illusion,  and  that  I  can  really  desire 
another  man's  happiness  only  so  far  as  it  is  a  means  to  my 
own  happiness.  I  hold  that  the  inference  is  wrong,  and  that 
the  two  statements  which  are  regarded  by  the  egoist  as 
identical  are  really  incompatible ;  and  this,  I  think,  is  implied 
in  the  foregoing  arguments.  But  the  point  is  of  such  critical 
importance  that  I  must  try  to  bring  out  the  contrast  more 
clearly. 

33.  The  problem,  as  I  have  said,  is  shortly,  What  is  the 
"  law  "  of  motive  ?  May  it  always  be  described  as  a  desire 
for  the  greatest  happiness  of  the  agent?  Let  us  ask  first 
whether  it  can  ever  be  so  described.  The  unreasoning 
animal  acts  from  blind  instinct;  his  judgments,  so  far  as  he 
judges,  are  limited  to  the  immediate  facts ;  he  judges  or  sees 
this  to  be  a  fire,  that  to  be  a  devouring  animal,  and  so  forth  ; 
but  he  has  no  prevision  of  the  remoter  consequences,  and  is 
therefore  neither  selfish  nor  unselfish,  for  we  can  only  predi- 
cate selfishness  where  there  is  at  once  a  knowledge  and  a 
disregard  of  the  feelings  of  others.  A  distinction,  however, 
may  already  be  made  in  so  far  as  he  possesses  instincts  which 
are  in  consequence,  though  not  in  intention,  profitable  to 
others.  Animals,  as  I  have  sufficiently  said,  possess  instincts, 
such  as  motherly  love,  non-essential,  and  in  many  cases,  and 
even  in  the  average  case,  prejudicial  to  the  individual,  and 
yet  essential  to  the  race.  These  instincts,  therefore,  must  be 
developed  as  the  race  thrives,  and  since  the  animal  has  no 
prevision  or  only  the  most  rudimentary  prevision  of  conse- 
quences, he  will  act  without  conscious  regard  to  the  con- 
sequences. If,  in  the  next  place,  we  suppose  the  animal  to 
become  enlightened  so  far  as  to  be  able  to  trace  remoter 
consequences — or,  in  other  words,  to  contemplate  the  distant 
and  the  future  as  well  as  the  immediate — but  without  any 
correlative  extension  of  sympathies,  the  result  would  be  a 
limitation  of  these  instincts.  The  instinct,  indeed,  would 
not  be  abolished ;  pleasure  might  still  be  derived,  for  example. 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  249 

from  the  exercise  of  the  maternal  functions ;  but  such  a 
pleasure  would  be  in  the  same  category  as  any  of  the  purely 
sensual  pleasures.  A  perception  that  drinking  brandy  is 
mischievous — that  is,  productive  of  future  suffering — does 
not  annihilate  the  pleasure  of  brandy-drinking,  but  it  tends 
to  limit  the  indulgence  by  introducing  the  foretaste  of  misery 
to  come.  The  instincts  of  the  non-sympathetic  agent  would 
in  the  same  way  be  limited  so  far  as  their  operation  was 
normally  productive  of  unpleasant  consequences  ;  and,  as 
a  matter  of  fact,  we  may  observe  frequent  exemplifications 
of  this  principle.  In  some  societies  the  unwillingness -of 
women  to  accept  the  burdens  of  maternity  is  proportioned 
to  their  intelligence ;  the  more  thoughtless  continue  to  act 
upon  animal  instincts  which  involve  ultimate  self-sacrifices, 
\vhilst  the  more  thoughtful  restrain  the  instinct  from  purely 
selfish  considerations. 

^^.  That  this,  indeed,  cannot  be  the  normal  case  follows 
from  what  has  been  said ;  for,  if  I  am  right,  the  intellectual 
development  must  normally  coincide  with  a  development  of 
the  sympathies,  and  whatever  deflections  from  this  coinci- 
dence may  be  possible  will  be  limited  by  the  operation  of 
our  general  principle ;  for  if  the  increased  reasoning  power 
meant  a  diminution  of  social  qualities,  the  intellect  would 
exercise  a  disintegrating  and  enfeebling  influence.  The 
more  reasoning  society  would  tend  to  be  supplanted  by  that 
which  may  be  called  lower  so  far  as  less  intelligent,  but 
which  would  be  superior  in  so  far  as  better  fitted  for  the 
conditions  of  life.  The  perception  of  utility  would  in  such 
a  case,  as  I  have  said,  be  in  conflict  with  the  general  con- 
ditions of  utility.  If  cleverness  carried  with  it,  or  so  far  as 
it  carries  with  it,  inferior  sociability,  it  is  or  would  be  a 
mischievous  factor,  and  would  tend  to  be  eliminated :  the 
world  would  be  to  the  stupid.  We  may  say,  therefore,  that 
the  intellectual  development  must  at  least  carry  with  it 
somethino;  which  counterbalances  this  anti-social  tendency. 
In  some  way,  then,  this  anti-social  tendency  must  be 
counterbalanced,   and    this    may   be    done    to    some   extent 


250  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

without  assuming  any  increase  of  sympathy,  for  the  enhght- 
ened  instinct  would  reveal  not  merely  the  disadvantages  but 
the  advantages  of  acting  for  others,  and,  though  it  would 
discourage  self-sacrifice,  would  encourage  such  action  for  the 
good  of  others  as  would  bear  fruit  in  good  for  the  agent. 
The  difficulty  of  the  question  depends  upon  the  intricate 
intermixture  of  these  intrinsic  and  extrinsic  motives  to 
altruistic  conduct,  and  we  must  of  course  admit  with  the 
egoist  that  the  extrinsic  motives  to  social  conduct  exist,  and 
are  of  great  importance,  though  we  deny  that  they  explain 
the  whole  phenomenon ;  and  this  is  the  point  which  has  to 
be  made  clear. 

34.  Now  the  general  principle,  which  may  be  called  the 
fundamental  axiom  of  prudence,  the  rule,  namely,  ''Act  so  as 
to  obtain  the  maximum  of  happiness,"  does  not,  as  we  see, 
hold  strictly  even  of  those  actions  in  which  there  is  no  admix- 
ture of  altruistic  motive.  It  cannot,  therefore,  have  that 
absolute  or  a  priori  character  which  is  sometimes  claimed  for 
it.  In  order  that  it  may  be  approximately  verified,  a  con- 
dition is  requisite  which  may  or  may  not  be  fulfilled.  The 
conduct  must  always  be  determined  in  this,  as  in  all  cases,  by 
the  actually  existing  feelings.  These  feelings,  again,  may 
include  a  foretaste  of  future  pleasures  and  pains.  But,  as 
a  general  rule,  the  influence  of  the  future  pleasure  is  less 
than  the  influence  of  the  immediate  pleasure,  the  degree  in 
which  it  is  less  depending  upon  the  constitution  of  the  agent. 
For  the  unreasoning  agent  the  future  is  simply  non-existent; 
but  even  for  the  reasoning  agent  it  does  not  necessarily 
follow  that  conduct  will  correspond  to  calculation.  If  he 
knows  to  a  certainty  that  a  present  sacrifice  of  pleasure  will 
be  repaid  in  kind  by  pleasures  to  come,  he  may  still  be 
unwilling  to  make  the  sacrifice — a  case  which  is  daily  ex- 
emplified. He  does  not  care,  we  may  say,  for  the  future  self 
as  nmch  as  for  the  present  self.  It  is  true,  however,  that,  so 
far  as  he  reasons,  he  tends  to  regard  the  future  as  well  as  the 
present,  and  therefore,  we  may  say,  approximates  to  an  adop- 
tion of  the  prudential  axiom.    71ie  more  reasonable  he  is,  the 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  251 

closer  he  comes  to  it ;  but  it  still  represents  an  ideal  limit 
never  actually  realised,  and  implying  a  corresponding 
balance  of  passions  which  may  be  more  or  less  perfectly 
achieved.  And  even  the  approximation  is  possible  in  virtue 
of  the  normal  conditions  of  life.  It  is  only  in  rare  cases  that 
we  have  to  make  the  kind  of  choice  suggested  between  an 
isolated  pleasure  in  the  future  or  one  in  the  present.  If  I 
had  a  fixed  number  of  cakes,  I  might  ask  whether  I  should 
obtain  the  maximum  pleasure  by  eating  all  to-day  or  leaving 
part  for  to-morrow.  The  answer  would  be  determined  by 
the  relative  power  of  the  immediate  appetite  and  the  fore- 
taste ;  and  the  stronger  my  reasoning,  the  greater  the  proba- 
bility that  the  perception  of  the  maximum  happiness  would 
represent  the  governing  motive.  As  a  rule,  however,  the  case 
is  simpler.  What  is  pleasantest  now  is  also  most  productive 
of  pleasure.  To  eat  my  dinner  to-day  is  normally  a  condition 
towards  eating  a  dinner  to-morrow.  My  appetites  have 
already  been  regulated  when  I  set  up  as  a  reasoning  being. 
Each  had  a  place  in  my  system,  and  a  force  proportioned  to 
its  normal  utility.  The  appetite  for  food  already  approxi- 
mately corresponds  to  the  need  for  food ;  that  is,  to  the 
importance  of  the  function  in  the  whole  system  of  life.  To 
satisfy  the  appetite  is  therefore  to  satisfy  the  conditions  of 
health,  and  therefore  of  maximum  enjoyment.  The  reason 
finds  the  problem  already  approximately  solved,  and  has 
only  to  work  out  a  closer  approximation.  It  starts  with 
instincts  already  harmonised,  not  antagonistic;  and  there- 
fore in  fulfilling  the  dictates  of  pleasure  I  am  already  act- 
ing with  an  unconscious  reference  to  the  needs  of  my  whole 
life.  The  instincts  have  been  moulded  by  the  conditions, 
though  they  do  not  consciously  attend  to  them.  What  is 
true  (as  I  may  note  in  passing)  of  the  balance  between  the 
primary  instincts  which  do  not  involve  sympathy  holds  true 
equally  when  sympathy  is  introduced.  Normally  it  is  prudent 
to  be  virtuous,  a  point  which  will  have  to  be  considered  more 
fully  hereafter. 

^^.  Meanwhile  we  may  say  that,  as  a  rule — leaving  the 


252  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

question  of  sympathy  out  of  account — an  increase  of  reason 
implies  an  approximation  to  the  prudential  maxim  ;  that  is 
to  say,  that,  as  a  fact,  the  working  of  the  instincts  or  feelings 
which  dictates  conduct  approximately  coincides  with  the 
prevision  as  to  the  maximum  of  happiness  obtainable  by  the 
agent.  This,  however,  is  not  an  a  priori  principle,  depen- 
dent or  incapable  of  being  denied  without  contradiction, 
but  a  deduction  from  the  general  conditions  of  life  and  the 
mode  of  development  of  the  faculties ;  and  the  closeness  of 
the  approximation  depends  upon  extrinsic  conditions.  The 
bare  foresight  that  I  am  sacrificing  the  maximum  of  pleasure 
to  an  immediate  pleasure  certainly  does  not  make  yielding 
to  temptation  impossible.  It  only  makes  it  unreasonable 
in  a  sense  in  which  unreason  is  thoroughly  possible.  I  may 
know  that  I  should  gain  a  greater  amount  of  happiness  if 
the  door  of  a  public-house  were  locked ;  but  the  knowledge 
is  not  equivalent  to  locking  the  door.  Still,  so  far — that  is, 
excluding  all  question  of  sympathy — we  accept  the  maxim  as 
expressing  the  general  law  of  the  operative  motive  in  reason- 
able beings  in  proportion  as  they  are  reasonable.  In  all 
cases  the  conduct  depends  upon  the  actual  mechanism  of 
motive,  but  that  mechanism  is  so  arranged  that  it  is  possible 
for  the  immediate  conduct  to  act  in  conformity  with  the 
formula. 

;^6.  We  now  have  to  introduce  the  sympathetic  motives, 
and  to  inquire  whether  the  same  formula  is  applicable  or 
approximately  applicable.  The  sympathetic  feeling,  again, 
is  one  of  which  it  is  the  law  that  your  pain  is  therefore  pain- 
ful to  me.  The  reasoning  agent,  in  so  far  as  not  altruistic, 
suffers  from  the  knowledge  that  he  will  suffer  hereafter,  and, 
so  far  as  altruistic,  he  suffers  from  the  knowledge  that  some 
one  else  is  suffering  or  is  about  to  suffer.  And,  again,  I  have 
already  remarked  that  sympathetic  motives  are  not  necessarily 
contrasted  with  others  in  respect  cither  of  their  consequences 
or  of  the  fact  that  they  are  still  feelings  of  the  agent.  The 
sympathetic  motives,  so  to  speak,  always  develop  within  the 
framework  already  provided  by  the  other  motives^  and  the 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  253 

two  arc  often  inextricably  blended.  The  external  bond  of 
maternity,  implying  no  affection  of  the  feelings  of  the 
spring,  develops  into  the  closer  union  in  which  the  sympa- 
thetic feeling  becomes  predominant,  and  both  forms  may 
persist  at  any  stage  of  development.  The  mother  may  still 
admire  the  child  as  she  admires  a  flower,  independently,  that 
is,  of  any  recognition  of  its  consciousness,  and  this  sentiment 
may  blend  indissolubly  with  the  same  maternal  love ;  and, 
again,  the  non-sympathetic  feeling  may  prompt  to  a  virtual 
self-sacrifice.  A  passion  for  beauty  regarded  as  a  purely 
external  quality  may  lead  to  imprudence  as  well  as  the 
higher  motive  of  personal  affection  ;  and,  in  both  cases,  again, 
self-sacrifice  is  impossible  in  the  sense  of  action  against  the 
predominant  motive.  Maternal  love  is  still  a  feeling  of  the 
mother,  and  therefore  we  have  only  to  suppose  it  strong 
enough  to  make  self-sacrifice  in  a  given  case  impossible.  For 
the  pang  of  inflicting  injury  upon  the  child  might  be  so  great 
that  no  other  pleasure  of  which  the  mother  is  capable  could 
repay  it.  In  this  case,  then,  it  might  be  urged  that  the 
highest  self-devotion  was  no  devotion  at  all,  for  it  is  still 
obedience  to  the  mother's  own  feelings.  In  other  words,  if  we 
regard  consequences,  the  least  sympathetic  action  may  imply 
self-sacrifice,  whilst  the  most  sympathetic  may  apparently  be 
still  selfish.  This  confusion  follows  if  we  attempt  to  base 
our  distinction  upon  the  bare  fact,  common  to  all  actions, 
that  they  have  both  subjective  and  objective  conditions. 

37.  Let  us  return,  then,  to  the  other  problem,  what  is  the 
law  of  the  two  classes  of  motives  ?  Omitting  the  sympa- 
thetic emotions,  we  have  seen  that  the  reasonable  agent 
approximates  to  an  acceptance  of  the  prudential  axiom. 
Supposing,  then,  a  case  in  which  the  sympathetic  feelings  do 
not  come  into  play — as,  for  example,  a  case  in  which  we  are 
concerned  with  lifeless  objects  alone — the  maxim  can  be 
applied  without  difficulty.  No  conflicting  motive  opposes 
itself  to  the  rejection  of  any  course  from  which  we  antici- 
pate a  balance  of  unhappiness.  We  may  calculate  badly  or 
we  may  be  misled  by  association.     We  sometimes  acquire  a 


254  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

kind  of  sentiment  in  regard  even  to  inanimate  objects,  mis- 
led,  it  may  be,  by  a  kind  of  childish  anthropomorphism  which 
leads  us  to  treat  them  as  though  they  had  feehngs,  and  to 
preserve  them  even  at  some  cost  of  happiness  to  ourselves. 
But  so  far  as  our  action  implies  any  assumption  of  this  kind, 
we  feel  it  to  be  unreasonable,  and  it  tends  to  disappear  as  we 
become  more  reasonable.     We  suppress  it  if  we  wish  to  act 
consistently.     We  approach  more  closely  to  the  only  assign- 
able rule  of  conduct  in  such  cases,  that  which  prescribes  action 
for  a  maximum  of  happiness.     Since  by  hypothesis  we  are 
the  only  persons  concerned,  we  are  the  only  persons  whose 
happiness  can  be  reasonably  taken  into  account.      If  the 
maxim    applies    unreasonably,    we  must    treat    every    case 
in  the  same  way.     The  mother  must  be  ready  to  abandon 
her    child    whenever    she    anticipates    more    misery   than 
happiness  from  the  connection.     This  is  not  only  the  sole 
rule  when  we  have  to   deal   with  material   objects,  but  it 
is    also    the    rule    in    so    far    as    we   treat    sentient    beings 
without    regard   to  their  feelings.     We  throw   aside  shoes 
which  hurt  our  feet  as  soon  as  we  can  get  better  shoes. 
We  may  consider  human  beings  as  tools,  and  treat  them  in 
the  same  way.     We  may  discharge  an  old  servant  who  can 
no  longer  do  his  work  without  regard  to   his    consequent 
starvation.     If  we  had  no  sympathy,  this  w^ould  be  the  sole 
rule  of  action.     The  same  rule,  again,  is  possible  in  regard 
to  objects  (if  we  may  call  them  objects)  to  which  we  do  not 
attribute  actual  existence.     We  derive  much  pleasure  from 
sharing  in  imagination   the  sorrows  and  joys  of   fictitious 
persons.     We  may  follow  the  histories  of  Juliet  or  of  Jeanie 
Deans  with  an  interest  not  differing  in  kind  from  that  which 
we  feel  for  real  human  beings ;  and  in  this  case  (assuming  this 
pleasure  to  be  our  sole  motive  for  reading)  the  only  rational 
principle  will  be  to  dismiss  the  fictitious  persons  from  our 
thoughts,  so  far  as  we  are  able  to  do  it,  directly  the  imagina- 
tion gives  us  more  pain  than  pleasure.    The  more  reasonable 
we  are,  the  more  consistently  we  shall  obey  this  principle, 
though,  of  course,  habit  and  accidental  associations  often 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT. 


-33 


make  our  observance  of  it  uncertain.  And  here,  again,  it  is 
possible  and  common  to  act  in  the  same  way  in  regard  to 
human  beings — to  treat  them  as  mere  dreams  which  pass 
from  existence  as  soon  as  they  pass  beyond  our  sphere  of 
observation.  We  read  habitually  of  events  in  a  distant 
country  as  we  read  of  events  in  a  novel,  with  little  more 
belief  in  their  objective  existence,  that  is,  in  their  existence 
independently  of  our  consciousness.  Too  often  we  treat  even 
our  friends  as  old  kings  treated  their  fools — as  sources  of 
amusement,  to  be  annihilated  for  us  as  soon  as  they  cease  to 
be  amusing.  To  do  so  is  to  treat  the  object  as  though  it 
were  unreal  or  existed  solely  in  relation  to  us. 

38.  The  difference,  then,  between  the  two  cases  is,  in  this 
respect,  sharply  marked,  and  corresponds  to  the  principles 
already  laid  down.     To  believe  in  the  objective  existence  of 
anvthing  is  to  believe  that  it  exists  independently  of  my 
feelings — to  believe  that  it  is  still  there  when  I  shut  the  eyes 
of  my  body  or  of  my  mind.     To  believe  in  the  existence  of 
a  sentient  being  is  to  believe  that  it  has  feelings  which  may 
persist  when  I  am  not  aware  of  them.     A  real  belief,  again, 
implies  that  at  the  moment  of  belief  I  have  representative 
sensations  or  emotions  corresponding  to  those  which  imply 
the  actual  presence  of  the  object.     Again,  a  material  object 
has  an  interest  only  so  far  as  it  is  a  condition  of  some  kind 
of  feeling,  and,  when  the  sympathies  are  not  concerned,  of 
some  feeling  of  my  own,  whether  implying  or  not  implying 
any  foretaste  of  the  future.     To  take  any  interest  in  any 
material  object,  therefore,  except  in  this  relation,  is  unrea- 
sonable, as  it  is  unreasonable  to  desire  food  which  cannot 
nourish   or    fire  which  cannot  warm.       I  want   something 
which  has  by  hypothesis  no  relation  to  my  wants.     The  same 
is  true  of  the  sentient  object  so  long,  and  only  so  long,  as  I 
do  not  take  its  sentience  into  account.     But  to  take    the 
sentience   into  account  is  to    sympathise,    or    at    least  the 
svmpathy  is   implied   in   the   normal  or  only  possible  case. 
The  only  condition  necessary  for  the  sympathy  to  exist,  and 
to  be  capable  therefore   of   becoming  a  motive,  is   that  I 


256  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

should  really  believe  in  the  object,  and  have,  therefore, 
representative  feelings.  To  believe  in  it  is  to  feel  for  it,  to 
have  sympathies  which  correspond  to  my  representations, 
less  vivid  as  the  object  is  more  distant  and  farther  from  the 
sphere  of  my  possible  influence,  but  still  real  and  therefore 
effective  motives.  Systematically  to  ignore  these  relations, 
then,  is  to  act  as  I  should  act  if  I  were  an  egoist  in  the  ex- 
tremest  sense,  and  held  that  there  was  no  consciousness  in 
the  world  except  my  own.  But  really  to  carry  out  this 
principle  is  to  be  an  idiot,  for  an  essential  part  of  the  world 
as  interesting  to  me  is  constituted  by  the  feelings  of  other 
conscious  agents,  and  I  can  only  ignore  their  existence  at 
the  cost  of  losing  all  the  intelligence  which  distinguishes  me 
from  the  lower  animal. 

39.  What,  then,  is  the  law  of  the  motives  when  the  in- 
fluence of  sympathy  is  admitted  ?  Can  it  still  be  said  that 
I  shall  always  act  for  my  own  greatest  happiness  ?  That,  as 
we  have  seen,  must  be  approximately  the  law  of  motive  for 
the  non-sympathetic  animal,  inasmuch  as  his  conduct  is 
governed  by  his  feelings,  and  those  feelings  can  only  be  dis- 
tino-uished  bv  includins:;  or  excluding;  a  foretaste  of  feelings 
to  come,  but  still  of  his  own.  The  only  elements  in  the 
problem  are  therefore  the  feelings  of  the  agent  himself, 
including  the  anticipations  of  his  future  state,  and  I  have 
suggested  reasons  for  thinking  that  the  correlation  must  be 
such  that  his  perceptions  of  maximum  happiness  will  natur- 
ally coincide  with  the  strongest  motive.  When  we  intro- 
duce the  sympathetic  feelings,  it  still  remains  as  true  as 
before  that  the  agent  is  governed  by  his  own  feelings,  but 
the  law  is  no  longer  stateable  in  the  same  way.  It  is  true, 
in  mathematical  phrase,  that  the  conduct  of  the  agent  is  a 
function  of  his  feelings,  but  some  of  the  feelings  are  them- 
selves functions  of  independent  variables,  namely,  the  feelings 
of  others,  and  we  therefore  cannot  deduce  the  law  of  conduct 
from  the  agent  considered  by  himself.  The  colour  of  a 
reflecting  body  depends  upon  the  intimate  structure  of  the 
body,  as  much  as  the  colour  of  the  non-reflecting  body,  but 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  257 

the  law  of  the  colour  will  in  one  case  necessarily  include, 
and  in  the  other  necessarily  exclude,  a  reference  to  the  sur- 
rounding bodies.  This,  as  I  take  it,  gives  the  true  and  only 
tenable  line  of  distinction.  The  sympathetic  being,  that  is, 
becomes,  in  virtue  of  his  sympathies,  a  constituent  part  of  a 
larger  organisation.  He  is  no  more  intelligible  by  himself 
alone  than  the  limb  is  in  all  its  properties  intelligible  w^ith- 
out  reference  to  the  body.  Each  part  of  the  body  must  of 
course  be  governed  by  its  own  properties,  but  they  work  in 
such  intimate  connection  with  the  whole  organism,  that  they 
are  only  intelligible,  or,  in  other  words,  we  can  only  obtain 
the  law  of  their  action,  when  we  take  the  whole  body  into 
account.  This  is  equally  true  of  the  being  which  has  become 
part  of  the  social  organism.  It  is  true,  we  may  say,  in 
respect  of  the  direct  sympathies  which  bind  him  to  some 
other  person,  so  that  his  friend's  joys  and  sorrows  are  also 
his  own.  It  is  true,  again,  whenever  such  sympathies  give 
rise  to  a  corporate  spirit,  to  the  domestic  bonds  which  unite 
families,  the  patriotism  of  states,  or  the  military  spirit  of  an 
army.  It  is  equally  true  of  those  instincts,  the  sense  of  hon- 
our, and  so  forth,  which  are  generated  by  the  social  factor,  and 
which,  though  they  do  not  imply  the  presence  of  any  special 
organisation,  are  essential  to  the  constitution  of  the  social 
tissue.  All  such  instincts  are  products,  we  must  suppose,  of 
sympathy;  their  growth  and  strength  imply  a  capacity  in 
each  of  feeling  for  others ;  and  being  accessible  to  impulses 
not  implying  changes  in  the  physical  organisation,  they  are 
so  worked  into  the  most  essential  modes  of  thought  and 
feeling  that  they  must  count  as  underlying  and  primary  in- 
stincts, and  any  personal  element  has  been  eliminated  by  the 
very  process  of  propagation.  Though  feelings  of  the  indi- 
vidual, their  law  can  only  be  determined  by  reference  to  the 
general  social  conditions. 

40.  This,  again,  enables  us  to  state  in  what  sense  the 
prudential  axiom  must  now  be  limited.  To  become  reason- 
able is  (to  my  mind,  at  least)  to  act  on  general  principles, 
and  to  act  consistently;  and  this,  as  I  have  said,  includes 

R 


258  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  condition  that  a  statement  of  the  real  cause  of  my  action 
should  equally  assign  the  reason  of  my  actions.  The  law 
which  my  feelings  actually  follow  must  coincide  with  the 
principle  which  commends  itself  to  my  reason.  In  order, 
then,  that  a  being  provided  with  social  instincts  should  act 
reasonably,  it  is  necessary,  not  that  he  should  take  that 
course  of  conduct  which  gives  the  greatest  chances  of  happi- 
ness, but  that  which  gives  the  greatest  chance  of  happiness 
to  that  organisation  of  which  he  forms  a  constituent  part. 
Certain  external  conditions  were  necessary,  as  I  have  said, 
to  the  adoption  even  of  the  prudential  axiom — the  condition, 
namely,  that  the  immediate  pleasure  should  not  be  normally 
inconsistent  with  the  greatest  sum  of  pleasure ;  and  it  is  of 
course  still  more  obvious  that  in  the  other  case  the  weak 
and  intermittent  sympathies  of  the  less  social  man  should 
not  be  naturally  out  of  harmony  with  the  purely  non- 
sympathetic  instincts.  As  a  rule,  the  instincts  of  the  social 
organism  must  be  closely  coincident  with  those  of  the 
individual ;  in  fighting  for  his  tribe  the  savage  must  be 
fighting  for  himself.  Even  in  the  highest  societies  both 
reason  and  sympathy  are  feeble  enough,  but  every  extension 
of  reasoning  power  implies  a  wider  and  closer  identification 
of  self  with  others,  and  therefore  a  greater  tendency  to  merge 
the  prudential  in  the  social  axiom  as  a  first  principle  of  con- 
duct. In  the  highest  conceivable  stage,  a  large  part  of  con- 
duct is  still  prompted  by  motives  in  which  the  sympathies  are 
not  concerned,  just  as  in  the  highest  organisms  each  organ 
has  some  properties  which  have  no  reference  to  the  organic 
union.  But  this,  as  has  been  sufficiently  said,  implies  no  in- 
compatibility except  in  particular  cases,  and  it  is  equally  true 
that  so  soon  as  I  become  sympathetic,  even  in  the  slightest 
dco:ree,  and  thcrebv  accessible  to  the  social  instincts,  the 
purely  prudential  maxim  ceases  to  give  the  true  law  of 
motive,  and  therefore  of  conduct,  in  all  the  cases  in  which 
the  sympathies  or  the  derivative  instincts  are  called  into 
action. 

41.  The  explanation  may  be  completed  by  considering  the 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  259 

prudential  turn  given  to  the  facts  upon  the  egoistic  hypo- 
thesis. That  hypothesis  starts  from  the  theory,  which  I  have 
criticised  upon  different  grounds,  that  reasoned  action  means 
action  for  an  end.  I  admit,  of  course,  the  truth  impHed  in 
this  statement,  that  in  reasoned  conduct  every  action  is 
regarded  not  merely  in  isolation  but  as  part  of  a  system, 
and  therefore  includes  more  or  less  conscious  reference  to 
the  future  as  well  as  to  the  present ;  but  I  have  further 
remarked  that  this  must  not  be  so  interpreted  as  to  imply 
that  the  subjective  condition  of  conduct  can  ever  be  any- 
thing else  than  the  present  feeling.  As  soon  as  we  slide 
into  that  fallacious  statement,  we  adopt  the  egoistic  formula, 
for  in  that  case  the  dependent  or  identical  proposition  that 
the  conduct  of  an  agent  is  determined  by  his  own  feelings, 
since  otherwise  it  would  not  be  his  own  conduct,  is  expressed 
by  saying  that  his  end  must  be  his  own  happiness.  Even 
when  we  have  to  do  with  the  sympathetic  feelings,  of  which 
it  is  the  primary  characteristic,  from  their  most  elementary 
form,  that  they  reflect  the  feelings  of  others,  they  have  to  be 
forced  into  conformity  with  this  formula ;  and  we  therefore 
have  to  assume  that  in  all  cases  of  sympathetic  feeling  there 
is  an  egoistic  end,  which  is  dropped  from  consciousness 
at  the  moment  of  action.  This,  upon  my  theory,  is  to 
admit  that  all  such  conduct  is  unreasonable,  or  that  it  would 
tend  to  become  impossible  in  proportion  as  our  reason, 
and  therefore  our  prevision  of  future  consequences,  became 
stronger.  This  argument,  however,  is  sometimes  met  by 
accepting  the  apparent  paradox,  and  declaring  that  a  man 
may  be  the  happier  by  taking  for  his  "end^'  that  which  is 
not  the  ultimate  end.  This,  indeed,  would  still  leave  any 
case  of  real  self-sacrifice  unreasonable ;  for  the  advantage, 
whatever  it  may  be,  of  attending  exclusively  to  the  imme- 
diate end  cannot  make  it  reasonable  to  pursue  that  end  at 
the  expense  of  the  ultimate  end ;  but  it  may  be  taken  to 
explain  why,  in  point  of  fact,  men  may  find  pleasure  in 
pursuing  the  good  of  others  when  they  anticipate  no  ultimate 
good  to  themselves. 


26o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

42.  Now  this  statement  certainly  expresses  an  important 
psychological  truth,  which  may  be  worth  considering  in  many 
cases.     It  is  no  doubt  true  that  the  pleasure  of  any  emo- 
tional state  is  in  proportion  to  its  intensity,  and  therefore  to 
the  exclusion  of  all  other  emotions  for  the  time.     We  may 
put  this  into  a  paradoxical  shape  if  we  say  that  our  know- 
ledge of  any  feeling  is  proportional  to  its  intensity,  and  yet 
that  the  greater  the  intensity  the  less  we  can  know  of  it. 
This  is  only  a  way  of  putting  the  fact  that  the  presentative 
knowledge  excludes  for  the  time  the  representative,    I  know 
anything  the  more  I  know  its  relations  to  other  things,  and 
I  know  a  feeling  as  I  know  the  conditions  under  which  it 
arises.     I  know  it,  again,  the  better  as  I  have  felt  it  more 
keenly,  but  at  the  moment  the  intense  feeling  excludes  all 
reflection,  and  therefore  its  intensity  suppresses  knowledge 
at  the  instant,  though  it  is  a  condition  of  knowledge  when 
I  come  to  reflect.     In  the  same  way  we  may  hold  that  when 
a  man  is  acting  for  any  end  whatever,  he  may  gain  it  more 
effectually  by  not  thinking  about  it  at  the  time.     If  I  aim 
at  a  mark  in  order  to  win  a  prize,  I  must  not  think  of  the 
prize  whilst  I  am  aiming,  for  to  think  of  the  prize  is  to  allow 
a  number  of  distracting  representations  to  interfere  with  my 
absorption  in  the  immediate  action,  and  they  may  be  equally 
distracting  at  the  moment,  whether  they  are  in  some  way 
connected  or  not  connected  with  the  action,  whether  they 
are  thoughts  of  the  cheers  which  are  to  greet  my  success,  or 
thoughts  of  some  entirely  different  character.     Exclusion  of 
everything  irrelevant  and  extrinsic,  absolute  concentration 
upon  a  single  end,  is  a  general  condition  of  successful  action, 
even  when  that  special  end  is  part  of  a  larger  whole,  and 
would  not  be  desired  unless  it  contributed  to  something  else. 
43.  This  is  clear  enough,  and  it  holds  good  of  course  of 
many  altruistic  actions.     I  may  do  good  to  a  man  in  order 
to  attain  a  reward ;  I  shoot  at  a  mark  to  gain  the  prize ; 
I  cure  a  patient  to  get  the  fee.     And,  in  point  of  fact,  I 
think  that,  as  a  rule,  the  mind  generally  "flickers" — that  it 
runs  along  a  chain  of  consequences,  stopping  sometimes  at 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  261 

one  point,  sometimes  at  another,  dwelling  upon  the  final 
success  or  the  intermediate  struggle,  and  therefore  taking 
various,  though,  so  far  as  it  is  reasonable,  consistent  or 
mutually  dependent  ends.  But  this  statement  does  not  in 
the  least  aflfect  the  reality  of  each  of  the  motives  called  into 
play.  I  have  no  right  to  select  the  last  state  anticipated, 
and  to  say  that  this  alone  is  the  essential  motive,  even  though 
other  motives  taken  by  themselves  may  be  insufficient  with- 
out it.  Every  part  of  the  foreseen  consequences  has  its  effect 
as  much  as  the  ostensible  end.  I  aim  at  the  mark  to  get  the 
prize;  that  is,  if  it  were  not  for  the  prize  I  should  not 
aim.  But  it  is  equally  true  that  the  desire  for  the  prize 
would  not  make  me  aim  if  the  act  of  aiming  were  itself 
disagreeable  in  a  certain  degree.  Nor,  again,  could  I  dismiss 
from  my  mind  all  thoughts  of  the  end,  and  therefore  I  could 
not  fulfil  the  necessary  condition  of  success  unless  the  action 
were  agreeable  up  to  a  certain  point.  It  must  be  in  itself 
tolerable,  or  I  should  have  to  call  up  a  thought  of  extrinsic 
consequences,  and  so  far  to  distract  my  mind;  and  there- 
fore the  necessity  of  "disengagement"  proves  nothing  against 
the  reality  of  each  motive,  which  has  for  the  moment  to  be 
(if  I  may  say  so)  self-supporting.  On  the  contrary,  in  order 
that  it  may  be  self-supporting,  the  motive  must  be  real. 

44.  This  is  equally  true  in  the  case  of  the  benevolent 
action.  The  physician  is  not  benevolent  enough  to  cure  me 
unless  he  expects  a  fee ;  but  unless  he  is  really  kind,  unless, 
that  is,  he  has  a  real  sympathy  for  my  suffering,  he  must  be 
always  thinking  of  his  fee,  which  is  a  very  different  thing. 
He  cannot  be  really  benevolent  so  long  as  he  regards  his 
patient  simply  as  an  instrument  upon  which  he  is  to  operate 
for  the  sake  of  pay,  without  real  interest  in  its  feelings.  I 
need  not  ask  whether  he  will  or  will  not  be  a  better  physician 
for  being  benevolent  or  not;  though  one  may  perhaps  admit 
that  on  some  occasions  he  will  do  well  to  suspend  both  his 
sympathies  and  his  desire  of  fees,  and  to  full  back  upon  the 
simple  pleasure  of  skilful  energy.  But  in  any  case,  if  he  has 
to  forget  his  fee  for  the  time,  some  other  genuine  motive 


262  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

must  take  its  place;  and  though  the  desire  to  reheve  is  only 
one  of  the  possible  substitutes^  it  must  be  real  so  far  as  it 
has  to  produce  any  influence.  And  a  real  sympathy,  so  far 
as  it  exists,  is  at  once  a  feeling  which  does  not  conform  to 
the  purely  prudential  axiom.  He  cannot  be  so  good  even 
as  a  physician  unless  he  is  accessible  to  motives  which  may 
carry  him  beyond  the  area  of  professional  success.  The 
whole  argument,  in  fact,  merely  comes  to  this,  that  in  the 
complex  system  of  actions  which  constitute  the  active  life  of 
any  reasonable  being,  the  suppression  of  any  one  motive  would 
clearly  involve  the  alteration  of  others;  our  sympathies  would 
often  be  stifled  if  it  were  not  for  the  co-operation  of  motives 
of  a  diff'erent  kind,  and  our  non-sympathetic  feelings  would 
be  equally  limited  in  their  range  if  such  modes  of  action 
would  not  operate  by  motives  which  rest  essentially  upon 
sympathetic  feeling. 

45.  And  this  suggests  a  remark  which  will  have  to  be 
developed  hereafter.  The  difference  between  the  sympathetic 
and  the  non-sympathetic  feelings  is  a  difference,  as  we  have 
seen,  in  their  law  or  in  the  fundamental  axiom  which  they 
embody.  When  the  egoist,  therefore,  maintains  that  it  is 
paradoxical  to  say  that  a  man  can  be  the  happier  for  aiming 
at  something  which  is  not  his  own  happiness,  he  means  that 
a  man  cannot  be  the  happier  for  sensibility  to  motives  which 
obey  a  different  law  from  that  of  the  simple  desire  for  his 
own  happiness.  Now,  from  what  has  gone  before,  it  is  plain 
that  this  paradox  has  really  no  meaning  for  us.  It  is  true 
that  the  man  acquires  sympathies  which  may  deviate  from 
the  law  of  prudence,  and  which  may  therefore  involve 
self-sacrifice.  Even  the  non- sympathetic  instincts  may, 
as  I  have  argued,  involve  self-sacrifice,  and  self-sacrifice  is 
clearly  not  essential  to  the  sympathetic  instincts ;  it  is  only 
an  incident  which  has  more  or  less  importance  according  as 
the  interests  of  the  society  conflict  more  or  less  with  those 
of  the  individual.  If  and  in  so  far  as  this  conflict  does  not 
exist,  there  is  no  paradox  in  supposing  that  the  sympathetic 
is  happier  than  the  non-sympathetic  being.     He  differs  in 


THE  RULE  OF  CONDUCT.  263 

having  acquired  new  sensibilities ;  he  is  not  the  same  man 
acting  from  different  motives,  which  is,  in  fact,  a  contradic- 
tory assumption,  but  a  diflferent  being  with  a  difflirent  set  of 
faculties  ;  he  has  gained  a  fresh  capacity  which  has  fresh 
advantages  as  well  as  fresh  dangers.  It  has  indeed  this  plain 
advantage,  that  he  cannot  develop  as  a  reasonable  agent 
without  it.  To  be  reasonable,  he  must  be  sympathetic ;  to 
be  thoroughly  and  systematically  selfish,  he  must  be  an  idiot; 
or,  in  other  words,  we  may  say  that  he  has  made  a  bargain, 
in  virtue  of  which  he  makes  a  common  stock  of  pains  and 
pleasures  with  the  whole  society  to  which  he  belongs,  and 
acquires  all  the  new  advantages  which  are  dependent  upon 
the  social  union.  We  shall  have  to  consider  more  fully 
whether  the  bargain  be  a  good  one  or  a  bad  one ;  but  we 
have  at  least  no  a  prioi'i  right  to  say  that  it  is  bad ;  for  if  it 
carries  with  it  an  obligation  to  occasional  self-sacrifice,  we 
cannot  tell  whether  the  obligation  is  or  is  not  oppressive  on 
the  whole  till  we  can  tell  how  it  operates  in  fact  and  what 
are  the  correlative  advantages  which  it  implies. 


(    264    ) 


CHAPTER  VII. 

MERIT. 
I.    The  Conception  of  Merit. 

I.  Altruism  is,  as  I  have  argued,  the  faculty  essentially 
necessary  to  moral  conduct.     Were  it  not  a  reality,  virtue 
would  be  a  name  and   society  an  impossibility.     But,  as  I 
have  also  said,  the  altruistic  sentiment  is  not  to  be  identified 
with  morality.     I  can  only  be  an  efficient  member  of  any 
society  so  far  as  I  can  identify  myself  with  others.     As  altru- 
istic, I  can  imbibe  the  corporate  spirit  of  any  social  organism, 
and  become  absorbed  in  my  regiment,  my  church,  my  family, 
or  my  club;  but  the  sentiment  itself  thus  generated  is  some- 
thino-  different  from  the  altruism  of  which  it  is  a  product. 
The  elementarv  sympathy  must  be  regulated  and  disciplined 
in  order  that  it  may  give  rise  to  the  truly  moral  sentiments. 
Virtues  which  belong  to  the  type  of  truthfulness  and  justice 
generally  implv  a  severe  restraint  of  the  immediate  sympa- 
thetic impulses.     A  hatred  of  lying  is  a  virtue,  because  the 
typical  character,  as  determined  by  the  conditions  of  social 
vitality,  includes  thorough  trustworthiness.    But  at  any  given 
moment  the  love  of  truth  may  dictate  conduct  which,  at  first 
sight,  at  any  rate,  is  contrary  to  that  dictated  by  the  love 
of  our  neighbours.     Hence  virtue  implies  more  than  simple 
altruism  or  benevolence,  namelv,  the  elaboration  and  regula- 
tion of  the  sympathetic  character  which  takes  place  through 
the  social  factor. 

2.  The  recognition  of  this  leads  to  a  corresponding  recogni- 
tion of  another  aspect  of  the  same  process.  As  altruistic  or 
sympathetic,   we   arc   not    only  sensitive   to   the    pains    and 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  265 

pleasures  of  other?,  but  we  catch  the  contagion  of  their 
complex  sentiments.  We  share  their  prejudices  and  passions, 
their  love?,  hatreds,  and  modes  of  estimating  men  and  things. 
We  come  to  love  and  hate  our  own  qualities,  with  a  love 
and  hatred  reflected  from  the  feelings  of  our  neighbours, 
and  transmuted  in  this  case  into  remorse  or  self-complacency. 
As  altruistic  we  are  fitted  into  the  social  medium  and  inoc- 
culated  with  its  characteristic  sentiments.  Hence  we  have, 
amongst  other  things,  the  complex  sentiment  of  moral  ap- 
proval and  disapproval.  If  virtue  were  identical  with  altru- 
ism, we  might  identify  moral  approval  with  gratitude.  It 
would  be  simply  a  case  of  loving  the  man  who  does  us  a 
good  turn,  because  his  action  implies  love  for  us  or  for  our 
fellows.  But  this  seems  to  be  an  inadequate  account  of  the 
peculiar  sentiment  which  is  elaborated  in  any  complex  social 
structure.  The  approval  of  which  virtue  is  the  object  requires 
to  be  explained,  as  well  as  the  motives  of  which  virtue  is  the 
fruit.  In  both  cases  we  have  to  consider  sentiments  which 
imply  the  existence  of  a  true  altruism,  but  which  also  imply 
some  modification  of  the  altruistic  feelings. 

3.  Hence  arise  certain  problems  which  require  discussion, 
and  which  take  various  forms  according  to  the  aspect  under 
which  we  regard  them.  The  moral  code  itself,  according  to 
the  principles  hitherto  expounded,  is  briefly  a  statement  of 
the  conditions  of  social  vitality.  A  man  is  said  to  do  his  dufi/ 
when  he  obeys  this  code.  He  has  mei'lt  in  so  far  as  he  obeys 
the  law;  or,  according  to  some  theories,  he  has  merit  if  he 
exceeds  it,  and  demerit  if  he  falls  short  of  it.  He  is  under  an 
obligation,  again,  to  obey  the  law,  as  merit  implies  the  fulfil- 
ment of  the  obligation.  He  is  virtuous  so  far  as  his  character 
secures  that  his  conduct  shall  be  invariably  in'  conformity 
with  the  law;  and  the  conscience  is  the  feeling  or  group  of 
feelings  which  make  conformity  pleasant  and  a  want  of  con- 
formity painful  to  him.  He  is  morally  responsible  for  the 
duties  which  he  is  able  to  perform.  These  various  phrases 
are  of  course  closely  connected.  To  explain  one,  therefore, 
is,  in  fact,  necessarily  to  explain  the  other.    In  some  cases  we 


266  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

think  primarily  of  the  social  sentiment  of  approval  and  dis- 
approval, and  in  the  others  of  the  motives  by  which  the  agent 
is  actuated  in  virtuous  conduct.  Conduct  is  meritorious 
when  regarded  as  giving  a  claim  upon  the  approval  of  others, 
and  is  virtuous  when  we  think  of  it  as  implying  a  disposition 
of  spontaneous  conformity  to  the  moral  law.  There  is  the 
same  kind  of  difference  between  the  words  virtue  and  merit 
as  there  is  between  the  words  reason  and  argument.  A  reason 
is  an  argument  when  it  is  applied  to  convince  others,  and 
an  argument  is  a  reason  when  it  supplies  the  ground  of  the 
individual  conduct.  But  there  are  certain  difficulties  which 
are  specially  connected  with  each  aspect;  they  are  so  far  dis- 
tinct that  they  can  be  separately  discussed,  and  perhaps  it  does 
not  much  matter  in  what  order  we  take  them.  I  propose 
first  to  discuss  the  problems  connected  with  the  theory  of 
merit,  and  by  showing  how  the  conception  of  merit  depends 
upon  that  of  virtue  we  shall  clear  the  ground  for  the  final 
question  as  to  the  nature  of  virtuous  motive  and  conscience. 
I  take  for  granted  for  the  present,  that  intrinsically  virtuous 
motive  is  possible ;  that  is,  that  a  man  may  be  so  constituted 
as  to  obey  the  moral  law  unconditionally.  I  say,  then,  that 
he  is  meritorious  in  so  far  as  he  is  thus  constituted,  and  I  shall 
try  to  explain  certain  fallacies  which  obscure  this  part  of  the 
subject. 

4.  Merit,  in  the  first  place,  clearly  implies  a  close  con- 
nection with  virtue.  We  may  assume  that,  ceteris  paribus,  it 
is  proportioned  to  virtue.  That  man  is  the  most  meritorious 
who,  under  the  same  conditions,  is  most  virtuous,  and  that  con- 
duct the  most  meritorious  which  requires  the  greatest  virtue  for 
its  performance.  Merit,  in  the  next  place,  seems  to  carry  a 
reference  to  some  reward.  So  far  as  meritorious,  a  man  has 
a  claim  upon  the  approval  of  his  fellows  or  (upon  some 
systems)  a  claim  upon  the  justice  of  his  Maker.  It  is  even 
supposed,  in  some  superstitions,  that  he  can  obtain  a  claim 
which  may  be  passed  to  the  credit  of  others,  llie  genesis, 
then,  of  the  theory  seems  to  be  simple.  So  far  as  we  share 
the  moral  sentiment,  we  wish  that  virtue  should  be  stimu- 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  267 

lated,  and  therefore  that  it  should  be  rewarded.  The  moral 
rule  begins,  as  I  have  argued,  in  the  external  form  ;  it  is 
stated,  "  Do  this,"  instead  of,  "  Be  this."  So  long  as  it  is  in 
this  form  we  need  not  attend  to  the  motives  of  the  agent. 
The  conduct  is  approved  simj)ly  because  it  is  useful,  and  it 
is  equally  useful  whatever  his  motives.  I  desire  that  a  man 
should  not  cut  my  throat,  and  may  care  little  whether  he  is 
restrained  by  a  fear  of  the  gallows  or  of  hell,  or  by  a  desire 
of  pavment,  or  by  sympathy  for  me.  As  the  moral  senti- 
ment develops,  I  come  to  approve  of  the  motives  which  imply 
true  morality,  or  of  such  a  dislike  to  cutting  my  throat  as 
is  founded  not  upon  the  extrinsic  and  separable  motive,  but 
upon  the  intrinsic  and  inseparable  motives  of  humanity  and 
good  will.  But  this  development  does  not  imply  that  the  old 
motive  is  superseded,  only  that  it  is  less  prominent.  The 
fear  of  punishment  may  be  operative  or  capable  of  being 
called  into  activity.  I  still  desire  that  my  throat  should  not 
be  cut,  and  therefore  that  the  gallows  should  remain  appli- 
cable in  case  of  need,  though  I  desire  also  that  the  case  may 
occur  as  seldom  as  possible,  and  that  men  may  be  actuated  as 
much  as  possible  by  the  motives  which  are  opposed  to  murder 
as  such,  irrespectively  of  possible  penal  consequences,  and  so 
far  as  I  make  this  distinction,  I  recognise  a  difference  in 
the  merit  of  the  two  classes  of  persons.  The  man,  I  say,  is 
meritorious  who  does  from  an  intrinsic  motive  what  another 
man  will  do  only  from  an  extrinsic  motive.  The  villain 
onlv  dislikes  hantrino;  and  murder  so  far  as  it  leads  to  hano:- 
ing;  the  benevolent  man  objects  to  murder  whether  it  has  or 
has  not  bad  consequences  to  himself.  I  consider,  therefore, 
that  he  has  a  certain  claim  upon  me  and  upon  society  at  large, 
inasmuch  as  he  has  done  for  nothino:  what  another  man 
will  only  do  for  pay,  or  has  refrained  spontaneously  from 
doing  something  from  which  another  man  can  only  be  re- 
strained by  threats  and  coercion. 

5.  The  principle  so  far  seems  to  be  simple  enough,  though, 
like  many  simple  principles,  it  leads  to  some  intricate  questions. 
If  we  wish  well  to  virtue,  it  is  suggested,  we  must  wish  virtue 


268  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

to  be  rewarded,  and  vet  with  the  certaintv  of  reward  virtue 
disappears.  A  inau  saves  my  life  out  of  sheer  benevolence, 
and  I  reward  him  out  of  sheer  gratitude.  But  if  he  had  a 
right  to  be  rewarded,  or  could  count  upon  reward  as  a 
certainty,  he  would  so  far  cease  to  be  virtuous.  He  would 
be  saving  my  life  from  avarice  instead  of  benevolence.  So  far 
as  I  stimulate  the  extrinsic,  I  deduct  from  the  intrinsic  motive. 
The  contrast  of  course  appears  in  many  theological  contro- 
versies. If  virtue  is  to  be  rewarded  by  heaven  and  vice  by 
hell,  do  they  not,  it  has  been  asked,  cease  to  be  virtuous  and 
vicious?  One  difficulty  which  applies  to  human  laws  can  of 
course  be  avoided.  A  human  legislator  cannot  secure  the 
coincidence  of  the  extrinsic  with  the  intrinsic  motive.  If  he 
pays  for  virtue,  a  love  of  pay  takes  the  place  of  a  love  of 
virtue,  and  love  of  pay  may  be  pressed  into  the  service 
of  vice ;  a  svstem  of  rewards  may  suggest  a  system  of  bribes, 
and  thus  no  external  sanction  can  be  uniformly  annexed 
to  the  moral  law.  The  divine  legislator  is  of  course  bound 
by  no  such  restrictions;  he  may  secure  the  absolute  coin- 
cidence of  the  two  classes  of  motive,  and  may  affix  to 
virtuous  and  vicious  conduct  consequences  which  are  not  the 
necessary  outcome  of  the  conduct  itself.  The  purely  self- 
regarding  motive  may  thus  always  operate  in  the  same  direc- 
tion with  the  altruistic.  The  question  remains  (with  which 
I  have  nothing  to  do  here),  whether  such  a  theory  does  not 
destroy  the  essence  of  virtue  by  making  the  appearance  of 
altruism  a  mere  illusion?  In  anv  case,  it  illustrates  the  fact 
that  merit  represents  the  claim  of  the  virtuous  person  upon 
the  universe.  In  so  far  as  he  desires  no  reward  here,  he  is 
held  to  deserve  a  reward  hereafter;  and  we  need  not  here 
inquire  how,  upon  this  hypothesis,  a  satisfactory  distinction 
can  be  drawn  between  prudence  which  aims  at  an  immediate, 
and  virtue  which  aims  at  a  remote  advantage. 

6.  Merit,  then,  is  a  function  of  the  social  forces  by  which 
our  characters  are  moulded.  It  is  attributed  to  any  one  in  so 
far  as  he  dispenses  with  any  extrinsic  stimulus,  or,  in  other 
words,  with  motives  which  are  equally  available  for  other  pur- 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  269 

poses.  Thus  we  find  that  the  wants  of  mankind  in  particular 
social  stages  generate  a  particular  respect  for  certain  virtues, 
which  under  different  conditions  cease  to  be  valued  so  highly, 
because  the  wants  can  be  supplied  without  calling  the  virtue 
into  plav.  In  sparsely  settled  countries,  for  example,  hospi- 
tality is  stimulated  bv  its  obvious  convenience.  A  man  is 
forced,  on  penalty  of  forfeiting  the  esteem  of  himself  and 
his  neio;hbours,  to  render  services  for  nothing  which  would 
elsewhere  be  rendered  for  pay.  He  is  regarded  as  a  churl 
if  he  turns  away  a  stranger  from  his  door.  The  senti- 
ment is  developed  wherever  the  conditions  occur  which 
make  the  practice  obviously  convenient,  and  may  be  de- 
scribed by  saving  that  in  such  regions  a  man  is  induced  to 
do  what  an  innkeeper  does  elsewhere,  not  by  the  prospect  of  a 
bill,  but  bv  dread  of  incurring  contempt,  or  by  the  correspond- 
ing sentiment  which  has  become  a  part  of  his  own  character. 
It  does  not  of  course  follow  that  when  the  social  demand  is 
lowered,  the  creneral  level  of  virtue  is  lowered.  A  man  who 
lives  in  London  may  be  called  upon  to  approach  a  higher 
standard  of  benevolence  in  general  than  an  Arab  in  the  desert 
or  a  backwoodsman  in  America.  But  this  particular  kind  of 
benevolence  is  not  demanded  from  him  to  the  same  extent, 
and  we  do  not  censure  him  for  a  want  of  hospitality  when 
he  sends  a  foreigner  to  a  hotel  or  passes  on  a  tramp  to  the 
casual  ward.  A  similar  change  takes  place  in  regard  to 
many  duties  which  in  a  rude  state  of  society  depend  upon 
the  voluntary  public  spirit  of  individuals,  and  which  are  pro- 
vided for  in  more  civilised  conditions  by  a  regular  part  of  the 
social  machinery.  The  demand  for  certain  manifestations  of 
virtue  becomes  less  when  society  is  so  constituted  that  the 
corresponding  kind  of  conduct  can  be  commanded  without 
callimz;  for  self-sacrifice.  Whenever  society  finds  sacrifice  of 
the  individual  necessary,  it  pays  for  it,  we  may  say,  in  terms 
of  merit.  The  deserving  person  has  a  blank  form  of  credit 
upon  the  world  at  large,  not  to  be  filled  up  in  terms  of  hard 
cash.    The  whole  demand  for  benevolence  may  increase  whilst 


270  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

special  modes  of  benevolence  are  less  necessary,  and  therefore 
regarded  with  less  respect. 

7.  The  conception  of  merit  has  thus  a  close  analogy  to 
the  economical  conception  of  value.  We  may  define  merit 
as  the  value  set  upon  virtue.  We  have  to  distinguish  between 
the  merit  and  the  intrinsic  virtue  of  an  action  as  economists 
distinguish  between  the  value  of  any  commodity  as  equiva- 
lent to  its  intrinsic  utility  and  what  is  called  the  value  in 
exchange.  Water,  as  the  economists  tell  us,  has  a  certain 
utility,  which  is,  of  course,  independent  of  the  abundance  or 
the  scarcity  of  the  supply.  It  has  the  same  effect  upon  my 
thirst  whether  I  live  upon  the  borders  of  a  river  or  can  only 
obtain  an  occasional  bucket  from  a  well.  But  the  value 
in  exchange  depends  upon  the  difficulty  of  attainment,  and, 
in  the  ordinary  case,  gravitates  towards  a  certain  average 
standard,  dependent  upon  the  various  processes  which  con- 
stitute the  industrial  life  of  a  community.  The  same  state- 
ments may  be  made  in  regard  to  virtue  and  merit.  Benevo- 
lence, we  may  say,  is  always  benevolence,  and  truthfulness, 
truthfulness  ;  but  the  estimate  set  upon  these  may  vary  within 
wide  limits.  The  moral  law  may  remain  in  a  sense  unaltered, 
whilst  the  price  necessary  to  secure  obedience  may  rise  or 
fall,  the  merit  of  obedience  being  greater  in  proportion  to 
the  quantity  of  extrinsic  motive  necessary  to  enforce 
obedience  upon  the  average  mind.  An  action  is  highly 
meritorious  in  one  country  which  in  another  is  a  mere 
matter  of  course.  That  was  regarded  as  an  act  of  heroic 
self-restraint  in  Scipio  which  would  be  so  natural  to  a  modern 
general  that  to  praise  him  for  it  would  be  an  insult.  We 
scarcely  thank  a  mother  for  a  devotion  to  her  child  which, 
if  shown  to  a  stranger,  would  imply  the  most  unusual 
benevolence,  and  therefore  the  highest  merit.  In  all  societies 
some  degree  of  maternal  affection  is  necessary  ;  but  in  some, 
a  mother  would  be  praiseworthy  for  attentions  to  her  child, 
the  neglect  of  which  in  others,  even  for  the  sake  of  her  own 
health  and  comfort,  would  involve  the  severest  censure.  Thus, 
we  may  suppose  that  whilst  the  scale  of  duty  remains  fixed, 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  271 

the  zero  point  of  merit  may  shift  upwards  or  downwards 
according  to  circumstance.  Of  two  courses  of  conduct,  the 
same  may  be  regarded  in  all  cases  as  the  best,  but  the  degree 
of  approval  which  it  invites  may  change  like  the  price  of 
a  commodity.  You  are  no  more  obliged  to  a  man,  it  is 
said,  for  being  commonly  honest  or  decently  civil  than  you 
have  to  pay  for  air  in  the  open  fields  or  for  water  on  the 
banks  of  the  Nile.  Merit  thus  carries  with  it  a  reference  to 
an  assumed  averao;e  standard  of  conduct,  and  accrues  to  the 
agent  in  proportion  as  he  reaches  that  standard.  Absolute 
merit,  if  the  phrase  may  be  used,  means  a  man's  virtue, 
considered  abstractedly  from  the  social  state  and  the  diffi- 
culty of  attaining  it,  whilst  merit,  in  the  more  ordinary  sense, 
takes  those  conditions  into  account.  The  sober  man  is  in  the 
first  sense  equally  meritorious  everywhere,  because  he  every- 
where shows  the  same  quality ;  but  sobriety  may  be  called 
more  meritorious  in  England  than  in  a  temperate  country, 
because  the  average  standard  of  temperance  is  lower. 

8.  It  is  clear,  again,  from  this  that  merit  can  only  belong 
to  voluntary  actions.  A  man  is  meritorious  in  so  far  as  he 
acts  in  a  way  which  the  average  man  will  only  act  under  from 
the  stimulus  of  some  extrinsic  motive.  The  act,  therefore 
must  spring  from  his  character ;  it  must  be  the  fruit  of  some 
motive  which  we  regard  as  excellent ;  and  if  it  did  not  arise 
from  a  motive — or,  in  other  words,  were  not  voluntary — it 
would  not,  properly  speaking,  be  his  conduct  at  all.  The 
meritorious  disposition  must  be  capable  of  a  stimulus  from 
the  approval  or  disapproval  of  the  society.  There  is  no 
price  for  commodities  the  supply  of  which  is  entirely  beyond 
the  influence  of  demand,  and  we  do  not  praise  or  blame  a 
man  for  qualities  incapable  of  being  altered  by  our  praise 
or  blame.  We  may  like  or  dislike  a  man  for  qualities  which 
w^e  recognise  as  being  entirely  beyond  control,  but  the  senti- 
ment only  becomes  praise  or  blame  uhen  we  conceive  it  as 
having  a  certain  power  of  modifying  its  objects.  Moral 
approval  is  the  name  of  the  sentiment  developed  through 
the  social  medium  which  modifies  a  man's  character  in  such 


272  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

a  way  as  to  fit  him  to  be  an  efficient  member  of  the  social 
'^tissue."  It  is  the  spiritual  pressure  which  generates  and 
maintains  morality.  The  whole  man  is  moulded  by  the 
beliefs  and  sentiments  which  he  imbibes  from  the  surround- 
ing medium.  He  may  be  forced  to  obey  the  external  law 
both  by  intrinsic  and  extrinsic  motives ;  but  so  far  as  he  is 
really  and  intrinsically  moral^  his  character  is  regulated  and 
stimulated  by  the  organised  opinions  of  the  society  to  which 
he  belongs.  It  is  plain,  therefore,  that  his  merit,  which 
corresponds  to  the  degree  in  which  he  has  been  thus  regu- 
lated, can  only  accrue  in  respect  of  the  qualities  capable  of 
being  thus  influenced,  and  these  are  the  qualities  implied  in 
all  voluntary  conduct. 

9.  In  saying,  then,  that  a  man  has  merit,  we  mean  that  he 
has  virtue,  whilst  we  implicitly  recognise  the  fact  that  virtue 
is  the  product  of  a  certain  social  discipline.  The  individual 
of  course  may  be  a  more  or  less  favourable  subject  of  such 
discipline  ;  his  innate  qualities  may  be  such  as  spontaneously 
mould  themselves  upon  the  moral  code,  or  such  as  are  only 
forced  into  it  with  great  difficulty.  They  are,  in  any  case, 
qualities  which  are  modifiable,  and  susceptible  of  the  social 
discipline.  When  a  man  obeys  the  moral  law  from  some 
extrinsic  motive,  he  is  not,  properly  speaking,  moral  at  all ; 
so  far  as  he  can  properly  be  called  virtuous,  it  is  because  the 
outward  has  become  an  inward  law ;  it  is  no  longer  a 
law  in  the  juridical  but  in  a  scientific  sense ;  it  is  not  a  rule 
enforced  by  external  sanctions,  but  the  "law"  of  his  charac- 
ter, or  the  formula  which  expresses  the  way  in  which  he 
spontaneously  acts.  Society  does  not  force  him  to  act 
against  his  will ;  it  has  annexed  and  conquered  his  will 
itself;  the  obligation  is  internal,  and  the  action  supplies  its 
own  motive.  The  man,  if  we  choose  to  say  so,  enforces 
upon  himself,  which  is  the  same  thing  as  to  say  that  he  does 
without  force  that  which  others  can  only  be  made  to  do  by 
some  external  force.  We  imply,  therefore,  that  in  this  case 
virtue  is  intrinsically  desirable,  or,  in  the  common  phrase, 
becomes  its  own  reward. 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  273 

10.  One  other  source  of  possible  ambiguity  must  be 
noticed.  We  speak,  perhaps,  more  commonly  of  the  merit 
of  an  action  than  of  the  merit  of  the  agent.  What  is  meant 
by  such  a  phrase  ?  Obviously  the  moral  quality,  whatever 
it  may  be,  cannot  be  attributed  to  an  action  as  distinguished 
from  the  agent.  By  a  kind  action  we  mean  the  action 
which  is  done  by  a  man  because  of  his  kindness,  or  in  so 
far  as  he  is  kind.  In  other  words,  it  is  an  action  which 
proves  him  to  be  kind,  or  which  would  not  be  done  unless 
he  were  kind.  And  in  the  same  way,  a  meritorious  action 
is  the  action  which  proves  a  man  to  have  merit,  or,  in  other 
words,  to  be  virtuous.  Upon  this  showing — and  it  is,  I  think, 
the  only  consistent  statement  of  the  case — an  action  is  meri- 
torious in  so  far  as  it  is  a  manifestation  of  certain  qualities 
already  existing.  But  we  speak  of  the  action  rather  than 
the  agent  as  meritorious  for  obvious  reasons.  For,  in  the 
first  place,  we  can  only  know  a  man's  character  through  his 
actions.  We  could  not  know  for  certain  that  Leonidas  was 
a  brave  man  until  he  had  fallen  at  Thermopylae,  for  we 
cannot  see  a  man's  bravery.  We  therefore  may  fall  into  the 
confusion  of  speaking  as  though  a  quality  were  more  real 
because  it  is  more  clearly  established.  We  are  quite  right 
for  honouring  a  man  more  who  has  given  proofs  of  courage 
by  his  behaviour  under  danger  than  one  whose  courage  is 
only  inferred  from  more  indirect  inferences.  If,  then,  we 
mean  by  merit  proved  virtue,  we  may  admit  that  of  two 
equally  virtuous  men  one  may  have  more  merit  than 
another.  We  mean,  not  that  he  has  more  virtue,  but  that 
he  has  shown  more.  The  case,  again,  is  complicated  by  the 
reflection  that  action  strengthens  habit,  and  therefore  that 
a  man  may  become  actually  more  virtuous  by  giving  greater 
proofs  of  virtue.  This  being  understood,  however,  it  is  only, 
a  question  of  words.  A  man  may  be  equally  virtuous  whether 
he  has  or  has  not  had  opportunities  of  showing  his  good 
qualities;  his  intrinsic  merit,  therefore,  is  unaffected.  But  if 
by  merit  we  mean  the  established  claim  upon  our  respect, 
his   merit   will,   of   course,   be    increased   according  to   the 

s 


274 


THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 


opportunities  of  manifestation.  There  may  have  been  a 
hundred  men  in  the  EngUsh  fleet  as  brave  as  Nelson,  but 
honour  could  only  be  paid  to  the  one  who  had  shown  his 
valour.  That  only  shows  that  honour  in  the  world  cannot 
be  proportioned  to  the  merit  absolutely,  but  only  to  the 
merit  which  has  become  known. 

II.  The  distinction  sometimes  gives  rise  to  other  difficulties. 
Moralists  have  spoken  of  the  goodness  of  an  action  as  being 
independent  of  the  motive.     Persecution,  it  has  been  said, 
is  equally  bad,  whether  it  proceeds  from  a  religious  motive 
associated  with  a  mistaken  view  of  duty,  or  from  some  worse 
motive— say,  a  simple  love  of  despotic  power.     If  we  judge 
morality  by  "consequences,"  it  is  equally  wrong  in  both  cases, 
and  therefore  equally  condemnable;  and  hence,  if  the  merit 
follows  the  morality,  we  must  condemn  the  good  man  who 
persecutes  from  misguided  love  of  truth,  and  admire  the  bad 
man  who  tolerates  out  of  sheer  indifference  to  truth.     The 
case  is   interesting  because    it    suggests    some   troublesome 
problems  of  actual  occurrence,  but  we  may  answer  it  suffi- 
ciently  for    our    present    purpose   without   much    trouble. 
According  to  the  previous  argument,  it  is  the  same  thing 
whether  I  say,  "This  is  right,"  or,  "This  is  commanded  by  the 
moral  law,"  or,  "This  is  what  all  good  men  will  do."   The  good 
man  is  one  who  does  what  is  right  or  what  the  moral  law 
prescribes,  and  the  moral  law  prescribes  that  which  is  right 
and  which  all  good  men  do ;  and  therefore  it  is  a  contradic- 
tion to  say,  "  This  is  right,"  and  to  add  that  it  may  be  done 
cither  by  a  good  man  or  a  bad  man.    But  I  have  tried  to  show 
how  such  an  impression  arises.     The  moral  law,  "  Do  not 
persecute,"  is  one  of  late  growth,  and  for  the  simple  reason 
that  the  evil  of  persecution  was  not  perceived  until  recently; 
it  therefore  presented  itself  in  the  first  instance  in  the  shape 
of  an  external  law  or  a  law  of  expediency;  that  is  to  say, 
some  people  saw  that  persecution  was  mischievous  but  could 
not  convince  others  that  it  was  mischievous.     Whilst  that 
was  the  case,  a  man  might  persecute  from  a  good  motive, 
say,  a  love  of  truth,  not  seeing  that  he  was  doing  more  harm 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  275 

than  good.  Just  so,  as  I  have  said,  good  men  may  still  advocate 
protection  as  well  as  free  trade.  If  protection  were  recognised 
as  mischievous^  an  advocacy  of  it  would  necessarily  imply 
selfishness,  as  at  present  it  may  imply  either  selfishness  or 
intellectual  error.  But  whilst  a  proposed  rule  is  in  this  state, 
whilst  its  good  or  evil  results  are  still  disputed,  and  a  con- 
viction of  its  advantage  has  not  forced  itself  into  the  accepted 
moral  standard,  it  is  not  properly  a  moral  rule  at  all,  or  it  is 
a  moral  rule  only  for  the  more  enlightened,  who  understand 
its  true  nature.  In  saying,  then,  that  it  is  wrong  to  persecute, 
the  early  advocates  of  toleration  meant  that  persecution  was 
mischievous,  and  therefore  wrong  for  those  who  recognised 
the  mischief:  but  thev  misfht  admit  that  a  "good"  man 
might  still  persecute  if  he  did  not  see  the  mischief,  meaning 
by  a  good  man  a  man  of  benevolence  and  love  of  truth,  but 
of  a  certain  degree  of  stupidity. 

12.  Hence  we  may  see  what  is  the  true  criterion  and  the 
cause  of  difficulty  in  its  application.  A  given  action,  as 
defined  by  its  external  relations,  may  always,  as  I  have  said, 
be  brought  under  various  principles ;  or,  in  other  words,  the 
conduct  may  be  the  result  of  various  motives.  Heretics 
may  be  burnt  from  religious  or  political  motives,  or  spared 
from  religious  indifference  or  out  of  respect  for  veracity ; 
money  may  be  given  to  the  poor  from  ostentation  or  from 
true  charity.  The  inference,  therefore,  from  the  action  to 
the  motive  is  always  more  or  less  precarious  :  it  is  precarious, 
in  particular,  in  the  case  of  a  growing  morality,  when  the 
true  character  of  a  given  rule  of  conduct  is  not  yet  fully 
recognised,  and  may  be  judged  differently  by  different 
people.  Whatever  we  may  think  of  the  ultimate  ground  of 
morality,  we  must  all  admit  that  the  normal  consequences 
of  any  rule  of  conduct  are  relevant  in  determining  its 
moralitv.  When  we  know  that  certain  modes  of  indulo^ence 
are  injurious  to  health,  the  indulgence  proves  imprudence ; 
and  when  we  know  that  any  mode  of  conduct  is  injurious 
to  our  fellows,  such  conduct  proves  selfishness.  So  long  as 
the  consequences  remain  uncertain,  the  implication  as  to 


276  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

character  depends  upon  the  state  of  mind  of  the  agent — that 
is,  upon  his  genuine  belief  as  to  the  nature  of  his  conduct. 
Very  difficult  problems  occur  when  ''  material "  is  not  iden- 
tified with  formal  morality ;   when,  that  is,  we  as  lookers- 
on  are  supposed  to  know  that  certain  conduct  is  mischievous 
in  fact,  but  when  at  the  same  time  the  agent  may  be  igno- 
rant, or  doubtful,  or  deluded  by  some  sophistical  argument. 
The  criterion,  however,  of  merit  seems  to  be  clear,  whatever 
the  difficulty  of  applying  it.     We  assume,  in  the  first  place, 
that  the  conduct  springs  from  a  certain  motive;  the  man 
gives  money  from  charity  or  from  ostentation,  he  is  tolerant 
from  indifference  to  truth  or  from  love  of  truthfulness.    His 
particular  action,  whatever  it  may  be,  is  one  case  of  a  general 
rule,  which,  again,  expresses  his  character  in  a  certain  rela- 
tion.    In  the  next  place,  this  rule  coincides  or  diverges  from 
a  given  moral   code,  and    the   character  of  which  it  is  a 
partial  expression  is  or  is  not  virtuous  as  judged  by  that 
code.     Hence,  again,  follows  the  merit  of  the  action.     It  is 
more  or  less  meritorious  according  to  the  degree  of  virtue 
implied.     Where  the  moral  code  is  still  doubtful,  there  may 
of  course  be  many  difficulties  in  deciding  the  proper  inference. 
But,   given    the   moral    standard,   we   simply  have   to    ask 
wdiether  the  character  implied  does  or  does  not  correspond 
to  that  type  which  spontaneously  and  invariably  obeys  the 
moral   law?     The  more  closely  it  does  so,  the  higher  the 
merit,   which   is,   as   I   have   said,   nothing    but  the  virtue 
regarded  from  a  particular  point  of  view. 

13.  I  have  already  argued  that  a  true  moral  law  can  only 
exist  when  it  includes  a  definition  of  character.  It  is  at  most 
an  approximate  statement  of  the  moral  law  to  say  that  we 
should  give  money  to  the  poor.  The  man  who  gives  money 
from  ostentation  is  not  really  acting  morally  at  all,  though, 
in  the  particular  case,  his  conduct  coincides  with  that  which 
morality  prescribes.  His  conduct  may  be  regarded  as  moral 
so  long  as  we  attend  only  to  the  external  rule;  but  it  is  a 
sham  morality  which  he  obeys,  for  the  character  indicated 
is  not  that  which  docs  what  really  belongs  to  the  best  social 


THE  CONCEPTION  OF  MERIT.  277 

type,  and  therefore  not  that  which  is  prescribed  by  a  tenable 
moral  code.  A  i2:enuine  moral  law  distino-uishes  classes  of  con- 
duct  not  according  to  external  circumstances,  but  according  to 
the  motives  involved  ;  and  therefore,  when  the  conformity  to 
the  law  is  only  external,  it  is  more  proper  to  say  that  it  is  not 
conformity  at  all.  Vanity  or  avarice  may  often  prompt  the 
actions  which  are  equally  commanded  by  a  sense  of  duty  or 
by  genuine  love  of  my  neighbours.  The  question  whether 
such  actions  are  or  are  not  virtuous  is  only  intelligible  as  a 
question  as  to  the  motives  from  which  they  spring.  We  may 
or  may  not  be  able  to  answer  that  question  decisively  in  any 
particular  case,  but  till  it  is  answered  we  cannot  say  how 
far  the  conduct  is  strictly  meritorious.  The  test  would  be 
given  by  placing  a  man  in  such  a  position  that  the  only 
motives  operative  are  the  intrinsic  motives  to  virtue.  If  he 
acts  rightly  when  he  can  have  no  other  motive  for  action 
except  those  w^hich  we  hold  to  be  virtuous,  he  is  really 
virtuous ;  if  not,  we  must  suppose  that  his  conformity  to  the 
moral  law  was  simply  accidental.  And  this,  it  may  be  added, 
is  independent  of  any  hypothesis  as  to  the  ultimate  nature 
of  the  intrinsically  virtuous  motive.  If  there  be  such  a  thing 
as  love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake,  the  virtuous  man  must  obey 
the  rule  when  all  other  motives,  including  those  derived  from 
the  happiness  of  his  fellows,  make  the  other  way.  If,  on  the 
other  hand,  virtue  is  merely  a  form  of  selfishness,  it  is  absurd 
to  suppose  that  virtue  can  ever  command  conduct  which  is 
on  the  whole  opposed  to  the  interests  of  the  individual. 
But  on  that  hypothesis  we  should  consider  a  man  to  be  in- 
trinsically virtuous,  and  therefore  meritorious,  who,  though 
systematically  selfish,  never  allowed  immediate  interests 
to  overpower  a  proper  attention  to  his  total  interests.  In 
any  case,  his  character  must  be  such  as  to  imply  invariable 
obedience  to  the  moral  code ;  or,  as  we  may  safely  say  that 
no  one  is  virtuous  up  to  this  point,  we  should  rather  say 
that  he  is  virtuous  or  meritorious  in  proportion  as  he  reaches 
this  ideal  standard. 

14.  We  have  said,  then,  that  a  man's  intrinsic  merit  is 


278  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

not  merely  proportioned  to  his  virtue,  but  is  his  virtue  con- 
sidered   under  a  particular  aspect,  namely,  as  causing  the 
moral   approval  of   his  fellows,  and   that  the  merit  of  an 
action  means  simply  his  proved  virtue,  that  virtue,  namely, 
which  he  must  possess  in  order  to  do  the  action  in  question ; 
and,  in  saying  this,  we  have  assumed  certain  very  simple 
principles,  which  hav^e  nevertheless  produced  libraries  of  con- 
troversy.    We  assume,  in  fact,  that  merit  can  only  attach 
to  voluntary  conduct;  for  that  is  the  same  thing  as  to  say 
that  it  attaches  to  the  character.     Conduct  which  does  not 
spring  from  motives  or  from  character  is  not,  properly  speak- 
ing, conduct  at  all,    A  man  is  not  truly  an  agent  in  matters 
in  which  he  is  passive.    In  the  next  place,  merit,  as  we  have 
seen,  has  a  reference  to  a  certain  assumed  standard  :  a  man 
is  more  or  less  meritorious  as  he  is  above  or  below  the  ordi- 
nary standard  in  respect  of  virtue.     Therefore  conduct  has 
positive  merit  only  in  so  far  as  it  is  more  or  less  difficult  for 
the  average  man.     Thirdly,  the  criterion  of  merit  is  that  the 
motive  implied  should  be  truly  virtuous;    that  is,  that  its 
agent  is  so  far  in  conformity  with  the  moral  type.     Now 
these    conditions    are    frequently  expressed    by  saying  that 
merit  implies   free-will,  that  it  implies  effort,  and  that  it 
implies  a  love  of  right  for  the  sake  of  right.     A  man  can 
have  no  merit  so  far  as  he  acts  under  compulsion,  or  without 
difficulty,  or  from  some  other  motive  than  a  love  of  virtue. 
Other  conceptions,  especially  that  of  ^'  moral  responsibility," 
are  equally  involved  in  the  controversies  which  have  arisen 
upon  these  points  ;  but  it  will  be  sufficient  if  I  state  the 
bearing  of  my  own  theories  upon  the  main  points  at  issue. 


II.  Free- Will. 

15.  I  have  already  said  in  a  sunmiary  way  that  I  reject 
the  free-will  theory,  so  far,  at  least,  and  only  so  far,  as  it 
implies  a  negative  of  the  "universal  postulate"  in  regard  to 
human  conduct.  I  would  willingly  pass  by  the  whole  con- 
troversy with  this  statement.     But  it    seems    necessary    to 


FREE-WILL.  279 

traverse  expressly  the  contention  that  a  ^^  a  determinist " 
must  logically  be  a  disbeliever  in  merit.  In  one  sense,  in- 
deed, that  contention  is  admissible.  I  admit  that  there  can 
be  no  question  of  merit  as  between  man  and  his  Maker. 
The  potter  has  no  right  to  be  angry  with  his  pots.  If  he 
wanted  them  different,  he  should  have  made  them  differ- 
ent. The  consistent  theologian  must  choose  between  the 
Creator  and  the  Judge.  He  must  abandon  the  conception 
of  merit  or  the  conception  of  absolute  dependence.  The 
free-will  argument,  as  understood  by  the  school  which  seri- 
ously maintains  it,  is  an  illogical  attempt  to  reconcile  two 
conceptions  which  are  radically  contradictory  by  the  device 
of  substituting  the  word  '^mystery"  for  the  plainer  word 
''  nonsense."  Admitting  the  inherent  difficulty  of  the  ques- 
tion, I  must  still  admit  frankly  that  to  my  mind  the  one 
insuperable  difficulty  is  the  difficulty  of  reconciling  deter- 
minism with  the  ordinary  theology.  That  difficulty,  how- 
ever, ceases  to  trouble  us  when  we  admit  (with  many  theo- 
logians) that  the  ordinary  theology  is  erroneous.  If  any  one 
denies  this,  I  must  be  content  to  refer  him  to  the  many 
metaphysicians  who,  from  the  days  of  Hobbes  and  Jona- 
than Edwards,  have  fully  discussed  the  question.  I  proceed 
to  argue  that  not  only  is  determinism  consistent  with  a 
belief  in  merit  and  moral  responsibility,  but  that  it  is  im- 
plied at  every  step  by  that  belief. 

16.  Let  us  start  from  a  particular  case.  I  sign  what  I 
know  to  be  a  malicious  libel.  I  am,  then,  a  malevolent 
liar.  My  conduct  proves  that  I  am  neither  benevolent  nor 
truthful.  I  deserve  blame,  and  my  conduct  is  de-meritorious. 
But  it  is  proved  that  my  hand  was  held  by  overpowering 
force.  My  action,  then,  was  not  wrong,  or  rather  it  was 
not  my  action.  My  body  was  employed  by  somebody  else,  as 
my  pen  was  employed.  My  character,  then,  had  no  influence 
upon  the  result.  I  may  have  been  the  most  truthful  and 
benevolent  of  men.  The  moral  law  applies  to  my  character, 
and  not  to  the  mechanical  movements  of  my  limbs  when 
impelled  by  another  man's  will.       Suppose  it  now  proved 


2 So  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

that  a  pistol  was  held  to  my  head  or  a  bribe  offered  to  me. 
How  am  I  now  to  be  judged?  From  the  whole  operative 
motive  and  the  total  implication  as  to  character.  The  new 
motives^  fear  of  death  and  love  of  money,  are  not  in  them- 
selves bad^  for  they  may  be  shared  by  the  best  of  men.  The 
implication  as  to  my  malevolence  or  falseness  is  not  so  strong 
as  before^  as  the  new  motive  counts  for  something.  If  the 
temptation  was  very  great  and  the  injury  to  my  victim  very 
trifling,  it  may  perhaps  be  thought  that  my  conduct  was 
such  as  an  average  man  would  adopt  under  the  circum- 
stances. If  so^  I  am  not  thought  bad,  though  I  should  un- 
doubtedly be  better  if  I  had  enough  courage,  sense  of  hon- 
our, and  benevolence  to  resist  the  temptation.  It  may  be 
thought  that  resistance  would  have  required  heroic  virtue, 
or  possibly  that  my  yielding  to  a  bribe  implies  a  greed 
which  is  still  more  contemptible  than  malevolence.  Hence 
arise  many  difficult  psychological  and  moral  problems :  what 
is  the  implication  as  to  character  ?  what  is  the  right  morality? 
and  so  forth.  But  the  criterion  remains  the  same,  namely, 
what  was  the  quality  of  the  motive  indicated,  and  how  far 
is  it  indicative  of  a  certain  constitution  of  my  character  in 
respect  of  morality  ? 

17.  This  is,  I  think,  the  argument  sanctioned  by  common 
sense,  and  to  my  mind  it  is  perfectly  sound  and  satisfactory. 
The  principle  assumed  is  simple.  I  infer  motive  from  con- 
duct :  so  far  as  other  causes  do  not  account  for  the  conduct, 
my  inference  stands ;  so  far  as  other  causes  are  assignable, 
the  inference  must  be  modified  accordingly;  and  the  strength 
of  the  motive  is  measured  by  the  resistance  which  it  over- 
comes. So,  in  the  case  suggested,  we  only  infer  malevolence 
in  so  far  as  the  conduct  is  determined  by  the  character  of 
the  agent,  and  we  infer  that  degree  of  malevolence  which  is 
necessary  to  account  for  the  action  when  the  influence  of 
other  motives  is  deducted.  I  reason  precisely  as  I  reason 
in  determining,  for  example,  the  motion  of  a  body  when  I 
set  down,  say,  to  the  tension  of  a  particular  rope  all  the 
share  in  supporting  a  given  weight  which  is  not  otherwise 


FREE-WILL.  281 

explained.  At  every  step  in  tlic  process  I  assume  that  there 
is  a  causal  connection  between  character  and  conduct,  so 
that  I  may  infer  motives  from  actions,  and  reciprocally 
actions  from  motives.  I  assume  freedom,  in  the  sense  of 
freedom  from  external  force,  wherever  I  assume  merit,  because 
the  internal  force  accounts  and  must  account  for  all  that 
part  of  the  phenomenon  for  which  the  external  force  does 
not  account.  Coercion  or  external  force  makes  motive 
irrelevant,  and  therefore  annihilates  the  inference  to  motive. 
But  the  inference  would  equally  break  down  if  I  denied  this 
causal  relation  between  action  and  motive.  If,  that  is, 
conduct  did  not  imply  motive  when  there  was  no  coercion, 
I  could  make  no  inference  as  to  motive  from  the  fact  of 
freedom.  If,  therefore,  by  assuming  freedom,  I  mean  to  imply 
that  motive  does  not  determine  conduct,  or  that,  given  the 
character,  the  man  may  either  act  or  abstain  from  acting,  I 
so  far  destroy  the  inference  as  to  virtue  and  merit.  But, 
upon  my  assumptions,  this  is  to  assume  an  absurdity,  if  not 
a  contradiction  in  terms.  It  is  to  destroy  the  sole  postulate 
in  virtue  of  which  reasoning  is  possible  at  all,  or  to  make 
the  very  essence  of  reasoning  impossible. 

18.  Let  us  suppose,  in  fact,  that  my  inference  is  uncertain, 
or,  as  it  is  sometimes  put,  that  the  agent  and  all  the  relevant 
circumstances  being  constant,  the  conduct  varies.  The  same 
man  will  in  one  case  give  and  in  another  refrain  from  giving. 
What  is  the  legitimate  inference  ?  Since  the  action  varies, 
I  infer  that  some  of  the  conditions  must  vary.  Now  in 
many  cases  this  is  apparently  an  accurate  statement  of  the 
facts.  The  same  man  is  liberal  at  one  moment,  stingy  at 
another.  I  infer  that  his  character  has  varied,  and  that  he 
has  seen  one  beggar  before  dinner  and  another  after,  or 
that  some  accidental  association  of  ideas  {''  accidental "  in 
the  sense  that  it  is  due  to  some  combination  not  dependent 
either  upon  his  character  or  the  assumed  facts)  has  for  the 
moment  modified  his  disposition.  This,  of  course,  is  possible 
upon  any  hypothesis.  So  far  as  this  explanation  is  hypo- 
thetic, the  merit  or  the  virtue  is  diminished  in  proportion 


282  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

to  the  uncertainty.  The  man  is  less  liberal  than  I  supposed, 
for  his  liberality  is  limited  by  a  previously  unknown  con- 
dition. He  is  only  liberal  when  his  temper  is  unruffled,  or 
when  he  is  under  the  influence  of  a  particular  association. 
But  this  is  not  enough  for  the  advocate  of  free-will,  for  I 
have  still  assumed  that  some  variation  of  character  or  cir- 
cumstance accounts  for  the  varvino-  conduct.  He  asserts 
that,  all  conditions  down  to  the  minutest  remaining  constant, 
there  is  still  a  possibility  of  variation  in  conduct.  I  deny 
the  possibility ;  but,  assuming  it  for  the  sake  of  argument, 
I  deny  that  the  inference  is  legitimate.  If  the  conduct 
varies,  and  if  no  assignable  change  of  conditions  can  account 
for  it,  I  cannot  assume  the  intervention  of  some  inscrutable 
or  unassignable  condition  which,  as  independent  both  of 
character  and  circumstances,  can  only  be  described  in  nega- 
tive terms.  We  are  virtually  postulating  a  blind  fatality. 
Some  unknown  and  unknowable  power  must  have  governed 
the  action.  But  so  far  as  that  is  the  case,  all  inferences  as 
to  merit  and  virtue  are  as  illegitimate  as  in  the  case  of 
external  coercion.  Whatever  determines  conduct  inde- 
pendently of  character  so  far  destroys  the  moral  value  of 
conduct.  To  say  that  a  man  is  benevolent  means  that  he 
will  always  be  benevolent ;  to  say  that  an  action  is  bene- 
volent means  that  it  proves  the  man  to  be  benevolent.  What- 
ever diminishes  the  certainty  that  a  man  is  benevolent  now 
and  will  be  benevolent  hereafter  must  so  far  diminish  his 
virtue,  and  makes  the  whole  theory  contradictory.  By  con- 
founding coercion  with  internal  determination  we  fall  into 
endless  perplexities ;  for  whereas  we  must  admit  that  a  man 
is  more  truthful  in  proportion  as  he  is  certain  always  to 
speak  the  truth,  we  make  it  an  essential  condition  of  his 
virtue  that  it  is  intrinsically  uncertain  whether  he  will  speak 
the  truth  or  lie.  Indeed,  if  free-will  be  essential,  then  the 
more  free-will  the  better,  and  the  smaller  the  certainty  of 
truth  the  greater  the  virtue. 

19.  The  same  argument  of  course  applies  to  the  correlative 
theory  of  responsibility.     A  man  is  responsible  for  that  alone 


FREE-WILL.  2S3 

which  he  can  do  or  leave  undone.  Obviously  so  if  we  mean 
for  that  the  doing  or  the  not  doing  of  which  depends  upon 
his  character ;  for  otherwise  there  is  no  inference  as  to 
character.  I  am  not  responsible  for  dying  when  my  throat 
is  cut,  for  I  shall  die  equally  whether  I  am  a  saint  or  a 
sinner  ;  but  I  am  responsible  for  cutting  my  throat,  for  I 
shall  not  do  so  (assuming  the  immorality  of  suicide)  if  I  am 
a  saint,  but  only  if  I  am  a  sinner.  If  it  is  urged  that,  being 
a  saint,  I  am  still  free  to  cut  my  throat  or  leave  it  alone, 
that  is  true  in  the  sense  in  which  it  is  true  that,  being  a 
saint,  I  may  become  a  sinner.  But  the  more  saintly  I  am 
the  smaller  is  the  possibility.  If  a  fate  called  free-will  or 
anything  else  intervenes,  and  causes  me  to  cut  my  throat 
whilst  I  am  still  a  saint,  I  am  not  the  more  but  the  less 
responsible  for  an  action  which  does  not  spring  from  my 
character. 

20.  But,  it  is  said,  admitting  the  relation  between  char- 
acter and  conduct,  it  is  true  that  each  man  can  form  his  own 
character.  Undoubtedly  every  man  is  always  forming  his 
own  character.  Every  act  tends  to  generate  a  habit  or  to 
modify  character,  and  consciously  to  form  character  is  an 
act  like  any  other,  and  subject  to  the  conditions  already 
stated.  Nothing  but  fresh  confusion  is  introduced  by 
attempting  to  draw  the  old  distinction  upon  these  lines. 
We  say,  for  example,  that  a  man  is  less  •  responsible  for 
licentiousness  who  has  been  brought  up  in  a  corrupt  society. 
The  argument  is  sound  if  reasonably  interpreted.  It  is  true 
that  a  man  who  is  now  a  drunkard  may  have  been  originally 
as  sober  as  another  man  who  owes  his  sobriety  to  the  absence 
of  temptations.  The  moral  worth  of  the  two  men  was 
originally  the  same,  and  the  difference  is  due  to  the  differ- 
ence of  circumstance.  Again,  it  is  true  that  the  whole  in- 
ference as  to  character  is  often  very  different  according  to 
the  different  mode  in  which  it  has  been  formed.  The  man 
who  has  been  seduced  to  drinking  by  strong  temptations  is 
as  much  a  drunkard  as  the  man  who  has  taken  to  drink 
without  them^  but    he   has    not   given  the   same  proof  of 


284  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

weakness  of  character,  and  may  probably  be  more  estimable 
in  other  ways.  When  everybody  drank,  drunkenness  was 
more  consistent  with  a  sense  of  honour  than  it  now  is. 
Such  considerations  show  the  necessity  of  guiding  our  judg- 
ment by  very  complex  inferences,  and  show  that  the  merit 
— in  the  sense  of  the  proved  virtue — of  given  conduct  may 
vary  widely  when  the  particular  action  alone  is  given.  But 
it  is  impossible  to  make  this  the  ground  for  a  distinction 
between  qualities  due  to  circumstance  and  others  due  to  the 
man  himself.  In  all  actions,  as  in  the  whole  of  our  lives, 
there  is  a  constant  action  and  reaction  between  the  external 
and  internal  conditions.  We  cannot  disentangle  them  into 
two  separate  series  of  events,  any  more  than  we  can  say 
whether  breathing  depends  more  upon  the  air  or  the  lungs. 
Every  character  is  developed  under  circumstances,  and  the 
development  depends  upon  the  continuous  adjustment  of 
the  relations.  If  we  suppose  that  every  man's  "self"  is  a 
separate  entity  of  precisely  the  same  qualities,  then  the 
difference  between  the  developed  characters  is  due  entirely 
to  circumstances,  and  therefore  can  have  no  merit  on  the 
free-will  theory,  or  to  a  mysterious  act  of  choice  which  is  due 
neither  to  circumstance  nor  to  a  difference — for  such  differ- 
ence is  supposed  not  to  exist — in  the  choosing  subject.  If, 
again,  the  difference  is  due  to  some  distinction  between  the 
original  selves,  we  come  back  to  the  determinist  hypothesis; 
for  this  difference  is  the  condition  of  all  subsequent  differ- 
ences, and  must  be  itself  due  to  previous  growth,  or  to  the 
absolute  will  of  the  Creator.  Or,  finally,  we  come  back  to 
the  unintelligible  theory  of  "  accident"  or  "fatality"  as  the 
foundation  of  merit,  though  merit  is  only  intelligible  as 
excluding  accident. 

21.  This  argument  has  been  so  frequently  and  forcibly 
stated  that  further  insistence  is  needless.  Identify  free-will 
with  the  occurrence  of  chance,  and  the  conception  of  merit 
becomes  contradictory  and  repulsive.  Exclude  chance,  and 
you  are  virtually  a  determinist.  From  this  dilemma  I  can 
sec  no  escape,  and  I  am  not  aware  of  a  plausible  answer. 


FREE-WILL.  285 

The  advocates  of  free-will  theories  are  frequently  content  to 
admit  the  force  of  the  argument^  but  retort  it  by  suggesting 
equal  difficulties  in  the  opposing  theory,  and  asserting  this 
to  be  one  of  the  speculations  which  lead  to  inevitable  anti- 
nomies. The  practical  reason  is  therefore  left  to  choose  the 
most  edifvinsf  alternative.  Though  I  am  far  from  admitting 
this  assertion,  I  think  that  it  is  true  in  this  as  in  many  other 
cases,  that  each  party  to  the  controversy  is  most  effective 
when  assailing  the  position  of  its  antagonists.  I  must 
therefore  give  my  reply  to  that  which  I  take  to  be  the  most 
telling  argument  of  my  opponents.  The  pith  of  it  seems 
to  be  as  follows: — Moral  responsibility,  it  is  said,  implies 
freedom.  A  man  is  only  responsible  for  that  which  he 
causes.  Now  the  cmisa  causce  is  also  the  causa  causaii.  If 
I  am  caused  as  well  as  cause,  the  cause  of  me  is  the  cause  of 
my  conduct;  I  am  only  a  passive  link  in  the  chain  which 
transmits  the  force.  Thus,  as  each  individual  is  the  product 
of  something  external  to  himself,  his  responsibility  is  really 
shifted  to  that  something.  The  universe  or  the  first  cause 
is  alone  responsible,  and  since  it  is  responsible  to  itself  alone, 
responsibility  becomes  a  mere  illusion. 

22.  I  admit,  of  course,  the  first  statement.  I  am  respon- 
sible for  that,  and  for  that  alone,  which  I  cause.  But  does 
the  fact  that  I  am  also  "  caused  "  relieve  me  of  responsibility  ? 
This  I  deny.  A  man's  character  is  what  it  is ;  it  makes  no 
difference  that,  like  everything  in  the  universe,  it  has  grown 
according  to  assignable  laws  instead  of  springing  into  being 
miraculously.  Certain  qualities  of  character  are' virtuous, 
and  not  the  less  so  because  their  existence  depends  upon 
conditions.  The  criterion  of  merit  or  responsibility  is  the 
dependence  of  conduct  upon  character,  and  this  remains 
unaffected  so  long  as-  the  character  is  the  true  proximate 
cause  of  conduct.  A  man  is  not  responsible  when  his  hand 
is  another  man's  tool ;  he  is  responsible  whenever  it  is  moved 
by  his  will.  I  do  not  diminish  a  man's  responsibility  when 
I  '^ cause"  him  to  act,  but  only  when  I  cause  him  to  '^act" 
involuntarily.     So  far  as  I   know  a  man's  character,  and 


286  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

apply  the  motives  which  induce  him  to  act^  I  may  be  said 
to  cause  his  conduct,  but  I  do  not  diminish  his  responsibihty. 
If  I  give  a  man  half-a-crown  to  shoot  my  enemy,  he  is  not 
the  less  a  brutal  murderer.  His  responsibility  is  measured 
by  the  guilt  of  committing  murder  for  half-a-crown.  I  have 
only  brought  out  the  fact  that  he  is  a  brute,  and  of  course 
encouraged  the  growth  of  his  brutal  habits.  My  guilt  in  the 
murder  is  the  same  as  if  I  had  myself  used  the  knife ;  his 
cruWt  is  the  same  as  if  his  motive  had  been  the  plunder  of 
the  victim  instead  of  the  bribe  from  me. 

23.  In    this    sense    conduct    may   be   '^caused"    without 
lessening  the  agent's  responsibility;   and  this  suggests  the 
inquiry  which,  if  fully  cleared  up,  would  do  more  than  any- 
thing to  remove  the  obscurities  of  these  problems.     I  can 
only  touch  upon  it  so  far  as  it  is  relevant  to  the  immediate 
purpose.    What  is  the  meaning  of  the  word  ''  cause  "  ?    We 
are  apt  to  think  of  cause  and  effect  as  of  two  separate  things, 
one  of  which  somehow  governs  or  coerces  the  other.     If  we 
carefully  restrict  ourselves  to  the  necessary  implications  of  the 
word,  and  consider  the  cause  as  a  constituent  part  of  the  total 
process  which  is  called  the  effect,  many  illusory  associations 
vanish.     Thus,  in  the  familiar  phrase,  a  man  is  said  to  be 
enslaved  by  his  passions,  as  though  he  and  his  passions  were 
separable  entities,  and  he  could  still  be  the  same  man  without 
them.     All  that  can  really  be  meant  is  that  certain  instincts 
are  unusually  potent ;  and  to  say  what  he  would  have  done 
without  them  is  to  say  what  a  different  man  would  have  done. 
They  are  not  external  fetters  capable  of  being  removed  or 
added  without  altering  the  man,  but  parts  of  the  man  him- 
self.     Yet   this  metaphorical    phrase  leads  to  a  confusion 
between  strong  will  and  absence  of  will,  and  we  declare  a 
man  incapable  of  choice  just  because  he  chooses  so  strongly. 
In  the  same  way  we  might  speak  of  an  assembly  as  being 
enslaved  by  the  majority,  as  though  the  assembly  were  an 
entity  separate  from  the  majority ;  and  thus  wc  should  con- 
fuse a  condition  of  energetic   action   with  a   condition  of 
impotence;  such,  for  example,  as  one  in  which  the  assembly 


FREE-WILL.  287 

is  controlled  by  a  foreign  body.  So^  if  we  state  that  a  man's 
conduct  is  determined  by  his  character,  we  identify  a  state- 
ment which  implies  the  highest  degree  of  volitional  energy 
with  one  in  which  volition  has  no  influence.  A  lover  is  a 
slave  to  his  passion  only  in  the  sense  that  a  part  of  himself 
prompts  him  to  vigorous  activity,  and  his  will  is  not  sus- 
pended but  intensified.  The  case  exemplifies  the  obvious 
absurdity  of  confounding  external  with  internal  coercion,  or 
rather  of  using  such  a  phrase  as  internal  coercion  at  all.  Self- 
coercion  can  only  mean  determination  in  the  logical  sense. 
Every  conceivable  object  has  certain  qualities,  and  we  are  in- 
dulging in  a  meaningless  figure  of  speech  if  we  speak  of  the 
quality  as  something  separate  from  the  thing,  and  ^'forcing" 
it  to  act  in  such  and  such  a  way.  To  say  every  material  body 
has  weight  is  of  course  the  same  thing  as  to  say  that  it  is 
heavy,  and  does  not  imply  that  weight  is  like  a  chain  pulling 
at  the  body  and  separable  from  it ;  but  some  such  feeling 
seems  to  be  always  creeping  in  when  we  speak  of  the  causa- 
tion of  conduct  or  of  character. 

24.  Let  us  look  at  this  a  little  more  closely.  What  is 
implied  in  the  statements  with  which  we  are  here  concerned? 
A  man  is  an  organism,  and  may  be  considered  from  without 
as  built  up  of  mutually  dependent  organs,  or  from  within 
as  consisting;  of  certain  faculties  or  instincts.  When  we 
say  that  his  conduct  is  caused  by  one  of  those  instincts,  we 
do  not  mean  that  there  is  a  man  plus  the  instinct,  but  that 
the  whole  man,  regarded  as  a  unit,  including  this  instinct, 
acts  in  a  certain  way  in  which  a  man  (if  such  a  man  be 
possible)  without  the  instinct  would  not  act;  or,  again,  if 
the  instinct  be  an  essential  part  of  the  man,  that  the  conduct 
varies  according  to  some  variation  in  this  instinct,  or,  in 
other  words,  in  the  character  considered  in  the  corresponding 
relation.  "The  cause  of  charity  is  benevolence,"  means 
simply  that  benevolent  men  are  charitable ;  malevolent  men 
are  not.  ''The  cause  of  eating  is  hunger,"  means  that  a 
man  eats  more  or  less  as  he  is  more  or  less  hun2:rv.  If, 
again,  we  speak  of  self-caused  conduct,  we  use  words  inac- 


288  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

curately^  as  when  we  speak  of  self-coercion ;  but  the  mean- 
ing is  clear  enough.     Briefly,  we  mean  that  the  conduct  in 
question  arises  from  an  internal  and  not  from  an  external 
variation ;  that  it  depends   upon  certain  organic  processes 
which  take  place  whilst  the  medium  or  external  set  of  condi- 
tions remains  constant.     I  go  to  sleep  because  I  am  tired, 
and  my  fatigue  arises  from  my  own  activity,  not  from  any 
change  in  the  surrounding  conditions.      A   certain  set  of 
external  conditions  is  always  necessary  for  my  existence,  and 
therefore  for  my  existence  in  any  particular  state,  and  I  may, 
if  I  please,  consider  them  as  a  "cause"  of  my  conduct.    But 
the  cause  is,  so  to  speak,  latent.     It  remains  a  constant,  and 
therefore  is  not  relevant  in  determining  the  particular  action 
wdiich  depends    immediately    upon    processes   taking   place 
within  the  sphere  of  my  own  organisation.     In  these  cases, 
then,  to  speak  of  my  conduct  as  caused,  is  clearly  not  to 
assert  that  there  is  something  besides  me  and  my  surround- 
ings  which  coerces    me,    but    simply   that   I   have  certain 
qualities  which  display  themselves  in  certain  ways,  and  are 
the  manifestation  of  my  character.     But  we  now  have  to 
deal  with  external  causes.     My  conduct  at  a  given  moment 
is  determined  by  my  surroundings.     I  read  because  a  book 
is  present,  run  away  because  there  is  danger,  and  so  forth. 
Am  I  therefore,  as  is  sometimes  said,  the  creature  of  circum- 
stances ?     Undoubtedly  my  conduct  depends  upon  circum- 
stances, but  it  is  just  equally  true  that  it  depends  upon  my 
character.     Both  factors  are  essential,  and  neither  at  any 
given  moment  is  simply  the  product  of  the  other.      I  am 
now   repeating  the  same  set   of   intellectual   operations  as 
before  upon  a  larger  whole.     Instead  of  considering  a  man 
as  a  separate  organism,  I  include  the  whole  set  of  processes 
of  which  he  forms  a  part,  and,  as  before,  there  is  a  mutual 
dependence,  and  no  one  part  is  to  be  regarded  more  than 
another  as  determining  or  creating  the  other  part.     If,  in 
fact,  I  could  analyse  the  whole  universe  (so  far  as  is  necessary 
for  the   problem   under  consideration)   into   its  constituent 
factors,  one  of  these  factors  would  be  the  a<2;ent  with  certain 


FREE-WILL.  2S9 

qualities.  If  the  surroundings  are  all  known,  I  can  infer 
various  conditions  by  which  the  agent  is  limited,  but  there 
would  still  remain  an  indeterminate  factor,  namely,  the 
character  of  the  man  himself.  So,  again,  given  the  man,  I 
could  infer  a  great  part  of  the  surroundings,  namely,  all  the 
conditions  necessary  for  his  existence  in  his  actual  state.  This 
merely  states  that  wherever  there  is  a  complex  whole  with 
mutually  dependent  parts,  I  can,  so  far  as  my  knowledge 
goes,  infer  either  the  parts  from  the  whole  or  one  part  from 
another;  but  it  does  not  imply  that  besides  all  the  constituent 
parts  there  is  a  something  else  corresponding  to  a  coercive 
force.  And  this  is  equally  true  if  I  go  back  to  what  is  called 
the  historical  cause.  The  universe  is  a  continuous  system;  no 
abrupt  changes  suddenly  take  place.  We  could  not  suppose 
them  to  take  place  without  supposing  that  identical  processes 
might  suddenly  become  different,  which  is  like  supposing  that 
a  straight  line  may  be  produced  in  two  different  directions. 
Hence  every  agent  is  a  continuation  of  some  preceding  pro- 
cess. He  has  not  suddenly  sprung  into  existence  from 
nowhere  in  particular ;  the  man  has  grown  out  of  the 
child.  We  might  (though  the  language  would  be  somewhat 
strained)  call  the  child  in  this  sense  the  "cause"  of  the  man. 
But  for  the  child  the  man  would  not  exist.  But  there  is  not 
a  child  pli/s  a  man,  in  which  case  there  might  be  a  coercion 
of  the  man  by  the  child.  The  child  and  man  form  a  con- 
tinuous whole,  with  properties  slowly  varying  according  to 
its  character  and  the  external  circumstances.  A  man,  atrain. 
has  of  course  qualities  which  he  has  inherited;  but  this  is 
not  to  be  understood  as  if  there  were  a  man  plus  inherited 
qualities,  which,  therefore,  somehow  diminish  his  respon- 
sibility. The  whole  man  is  inherited,  if  we  may  use  such  a 
phrase.  He  starts  at  his  birth  with  qualities  dependent  of 
course  upon  the  qualities  of  his  parents,  for  their  character- 
istics and  condition  are  the  sole  relevant  conditions.  The 
fact  that  he  inherits  a  particular  temper  no  more  implies  that 
he  is  one  thing  and  the  temper  another  thing  superimposed, 
than  the  fact  that  he  inherits  the  general  characteristics  of 

T 


290  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

humanity  would  imply  that  the  man  is  something  in  addi- 
tion to  all  his  essential  qualities.  From  the  child^  again^  we 
may  (within  certain  limits)  infer  the  man.  It  is  equally 
true  that  from  the  man  we  may  infer  the  child.  It  is  true 
that  the  man  must  have  certain  qualities  which  he  would  not 
have  had  the  child  been  different^  and  it  is  equally  true  that 
the  child  must  have  had  certain  qualities  which  he  would 
not  have  had  if  the  man  were  different.  In  both  cases  we  are 
looking  at  a  continuous  process  from  varying  points^  and  we 
can  infer  either  backwards  or  forwards.  The  latter  attitude  is 
more  customary^  owing  to  the  conditions  of  human  conduct. 
But  it  is  not  implied  that  something  survives  from  the  earlier 
stage  which  is  additional  to^  and  capable  therefore  of  limit- 
ing or  coercing^  the  later  stage.  Our  power  of  inferring 
simply  expresses  the  fact  of  continuity  and  nothing  more ; 
and  I  may  observe  in  passing  that,  even  if  we  denied  this 
axiom,  and  supposed  that  men  could  spring  into  existence 
out  of  nothing,  it  is  impossible  to  see  how  their  "  responsi- 
bility" or  "free-will"  would  be  affected. 

25.  The  whole  illusion  in  this  part  of  the  question  seems 
to  rest  upon  a  simple  principle.  Philosophers  tell  us  (and 
with  undeniable  truth)  that  "chance"  is  a  mere  name  for 
ignorance.  It  is  a  chance  whether  a  penny  will  fall  heads 
or  tails  uppermost ;  that  is,  we  do  not  know  which  way  it 
will  fall.  I  say  equally  when  I  am  crossing  a  mountain 
that  it  is  a  chance  whether  the  other  side  of  a  rido-e  is  a 
precipice  or  a  slope.  In  this  case,  then,  I  assert  nothing  as 
to  the  thing  itself,  for  that  is  already  there ;  there  is  already 
either  a  precipice  or  a  slope ;  but  only  assert  that  I  do  not 
know  which.  And  this,  which  is  admittedly  true  of  chance, 
is  equally  true  of  the  necessity  which  is  the  negation  of 
chance.  It  is  simply  a  name  for  certainty,  as  chance  for 
absence  of  certainty.  Thus,  if  I  say  you  will  "necessarily" 
act  in  such  a  way,  I  mean  that  I  know  that  you  will  act  in 
that  way,  and  I  mean  nothing  more.  My  knowledge  may 
be  founded  upon  a  knowledge  of  your  character,  and  upon 
a  knowledge  of  certain  physical  limitations  which  make  your 


FREE-WILL. 


291 


character  irrelevant.  In  this  sense,  conduct  or  action  de- 
pendent upon  character  can  rarely  be  certain  or  "  necessary" 
beyond  a  certain  point,  because  we  have  rarely  any  accurate 
knowledge  of  character.  The  data  are  more  complex,  but 
they  are  not  in  themselves  less  determinate.  An  indeter- 
minate thing  is  a  non-existent  thing,  for  it  would  be 
something  which  is  at  once  one  thing  and  another  thing. 
The  same  applies  to  all  such  words  as  "necessary,"  "^^ pro- 
bable," "potential,"  "possible,'*  and  so  forth.  They  arc 
simply  names  of  the  observer's  state  of  mind,  which,  by 
one  of  the  most  familiar  of  all  fallacies,  are  supposed  to 
denote  qualities  of  the  thing  observed.  What  I  see  to  exist 
"  necessarily,"  may  be  only  probable  for  you,  but  the  thing 
itself  either  exists  or  does  not  exist,  and  by  saying  "necessary" 
I  add  nothing  except  a  statement  as  to  my  knowledge.  The 
use  of  the  word  "  necessary  "  in  regard  to  conduct  has  given 
offence  from  this  common  confusion  of  ideas.  If  I  sav.  for 
example,  that  a  man  will  necessarily  commit  murder  under 
given  circumstances,  I  mean  that  I  am  quite  certain  that  he 
will.  Why  am  I  certain  ?  Because  I  know  him  to  have  the 
murderous  character.  I  do  not  assert  the  existence  of  a  neces- 
sity as  of  something  external  to  his  character,  which  will  make 
him  commit  murder  whether  he  likes  it  or  not,  but  simply 
that  I  know  that  he  will  like  it.  And  thus  the  only  meaning\\ 
of  the  necessity  of  conduct  is  that  people  have  fixed  qualities  \\ 
of  character,  which  do,  as  a  matter  of  fact  (not  determine  ) 
their  conduct  from  without),  but  manifest  themselves  m// 
conduct;  in  other  words,  that  people  have  characters.  If 
they  have  not,  I  do  not  see  how  they  can  be  virtuous,  and 
meritorious,  and  responsible. 

26.  Finally,  let  us  return  to  the  causa  causce  argument. 
The  statement  is,  that  if  action  is  caused,  the  original  cause 
alone  can  be  responsible.  If  this  is  interpreted  bv  the 
hypothesis  of  a  Creator  separate  from  the  universe,  who 
has  yet  moulded  it  as  the  seal  moulds  the  wax,  and  who  at 
every  instant  sustains  and  supports  it,  I  admit  that  it  is  im- 
possible to  conceive  of  responsibility  to  such  a  being.     It  is 


292  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  case  of  a  man  bribing  me  to  a  crime  and  then  punish- 
ing me  for  committing  it.  I  may  be  equally  responsible^  as 
I  have  said^  to  others,  but  I  do  not  see  how  I  can  be  re- 
sponsible to  him.  But  the  bare  fact  that  an  omniscient,  or 
even  a  highly  intelligent  being  could  foresee  my  actions  with 
certainty,  would  not  destroy  my  responsibility.  Such  fore- 
knowledge, it  used  to  be  argued,  implied  predestination,  and 
therefore  an  incapacity  of  the  individual  to  act  otherwise. 
But  the  determination  implied  would  not  be  an  external 
fate  coercing  the  character,  but  simply  the  character  itself. 
I  know  that  a  man  will  remain  motionless,  not  because  I 
know  him  to  be  in  fetters,  but  because  I  know  that  he  is 
indolent.  In  one  case,  I  should  infer  that  he  will  be  motion- 
less whatever  his  character ;  in  the  other,  that  he  will  be 
motionless,  assuming  his  character.  The  two  cases  are  really 
mutually  exclusive,  though  they  are  so  often  confounded. 
Prediction,  in  short,  does  not  imply  a  man  plus  a  fate,  but  a 
man  alone. 

27.  I  am  not,  however,  properly  concerned  with  the  so- 
called  transcendental  causes.  Within  the  sphere  of  scientific 
thought,  the  case  is  as  I  have  argued  it.  A  man  is  respon- 
sible, I  have  said,  for  those  actions  which  are  caused  by  his 
moral  character.  The  fact  that  he  is  himself  "  caused,"  or 
that  his  actions  are  caused  by  circumstances,  is  only  relevant 
in  so  far  as  this  statement  means  that  his  character  ceases  to 
be  a  cause  at  all ;  in  other  words,  as  the  same  phenomena 
would  result  whatever  his  character  might  be.  If  my 
benevolence  causes  my  action,  if,  that  is,  a  person  not 
benevolent  would  act  differently,  then  I  have  the  merit  of 
benevolence.  The  fact  that  my  action  depends  upon  circum- 
stances— that  is,  would  be  different  if  circumstances  differed 
— is  irrelevant  if  it  also  depends  upon  my  character.  My 
character  is  still  a  true  cause.  The  fact  that  my  character 
has  been  developed  under  the  action  of  circumstances  is 
equally  irrelevant  so  long  as  it  is  my  character.  The  two 
factors  are  implied  at  every  stage  of  the  process,  and  the 
so-called  "  dependence  "  of  one  upon  the  other  means  simply 


FREE-WILL.  293 

that  T  cannot  infer  the  whole  phenomenon  from  either  taken 
separately.  Finally^  if  I  refer  to  the  origin  or  the  historical 
cause  of  my  character,  it  is  of  course  true  that  the  man's 
character  would  be  different  if  the  character  of  the  child's 
character  had  been  different,  or  the  child's  if  the  parents'  had 
been  different.  If  the  child  had  certain  instincts,  the  man 
will  have  corresponding  iristincts ;  as  also  if  the  parents 
were  monkeys  instead  of  men,  the  child  would  be  a  monkey. 
But  there  are  not  separate  qualities  which  are  left  behind  by 
the  parents  or  the  child  to  hamper  the  man ;  the  whole  of 
the  man's  qualities  are  continuous  with  the  qualities  existing 
in  any  previous  stage  of  the  same  person.  There  is  not  a 
common  something  which  becomes  either  monkey  or  man 
as  a  different  form  is  imposed  upon  it.  If  we  could  suppose 
a  sudden  appearance  of  the  man  out  of  nothing  or  by  the 
fiat  of  a  Creator,  we  should  still  only  shift  the  responsibility  to 
the  Creator  or  to  chance.  We  may  infer  the  child  from  the 
man  as  well  as  the  man  from  the  child,  and  there  is  no  more 
necessity  in  the  one  case  than  the  other,  except  in  the  sense 
which  means  certainty.  When  we  know  from  one  pheno- 
menon that  another  exists,  it  is  simply  that  we  can  (for  some 
reason)  identify  the  two  as  parts  of  a  whole  of  mutually 
dependent  parts.  From  an  eye  we  infer  an  ear  or  a  leg  ;  it  is 
not  because  the  eye  has  a  power  to  make  ears  and  legs  out  of 
formless  matter,  or  because,  besides  eyes  and  ears  and  legs 
and  every  part  of  the  organism,  there  is  some  additional 
coercive  force  which  holds  them  together,  but  simply  that 
each  part  carries  with  it  a  reference  to  the  rest.  The  diffi- 
culty is  dispelled  so  far  as  it  can  be  dispelled  when  we  have 
got  rid  of  the  troublesome  conception  of  necessity  as  a  name 
for  something  more  than  the  certainty  of  the  observer. 
When  we  firmly  grasp  and  push  to  its  legitimate  conse- 
quences the  truth  that  probability,  chance,  necessity,  deter- 
mination, and  so  forth,  are  simply  names  of  our  own  states 
of  mind,  or,  in  other  words,  have  only  a  subjective  validity; 
that  a  thing  either  exists  or  does  not  exist,  and  that  no 
fresh  quality  is  predicated  when  we  say  that  it  exists  neces- 


294  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

sarily;  and  that  all  dependence  of  one  thing  upon  another 
implies  a  mutual  relation  and  not  an  abolition  of  one  of  the 
things — we  have  got  as  far  as  we  can  towards  removing  the 
perplexity  now  under  consideration.  But  it  is  not  likely  to 
disappear  to-day  or  to-morrow. 


TIL  Efort. 

28.  I  pass,  therefore,  to  a  further  condition  of  morality, 
which  involves  some  similar  ambiguities.  The  free-will 
condition  implies  (upon  my  view)  a  misunderstanding  of  the 
undeniable  proposition  that  a  man  can  be  virtuous  or  meri- 
torious in  respect  of  those  actions  alon^  which  are  con- 
ditioned by  his  character,  or  which  are  really  his  actions. 
The  agent  must  be  really  an  agent^  not  a  bit  of  mechanism, 
or  a  transmitter  of  internal  force.  But,  in  the  next  place,  as 
I  have  said,  the  qualities  in  respect  of  which  a  man  is  meri- 
torious must  be  those  which  are  amenable  to  discipline. 
The  moralised  man  is  the  trained  savage ;  he  helps  a  stranger 
instead  of  attacking  him ;  and  this  modified  instinct  which 
he  has  acquired  through  the  social  factor  distinguishes  him 
from  the  immoral  man,  in  whom  the  instinct  is  deficient. 
Thus,  again,  it  seems  that  merit  implies  an  effort.  Those 
actions,  I  have  said,  are  regarded  as  meritorious  which  the 
average  man  would  not  do  without  extrinsic  reward,  and 
that  character  is  meritorious  which  implies  the  modification 
necessary  to  such  conduct.  Hence,  again,  it  is  often  said, 
with  more  or  less  propriety,  that  a  man  deserves  nothing 
for  conduct  which  is  pleasant  or  purely  "  natural."  As  these 
statements  involve  various  perplexities,  I  must  seek  to  give 
at  least  the  clue  by  which  they  may  be  unravelled. 

39.  I  observe,  then,  that  (as  already  stated)  a  judgment 
of  merit  implies  reference  to  some  standard  ;  and  this  implies, 
again,  that  the  person  is  supposed  to  belong  to  a  certain 
class,  and  to  have  the  essential  properties  of  that  class. 
When  I  say  "  a  good  "  or  "  a  bad  "  man,  I  of  course  use  the 
words  in  a  diflcrcnt  sense  from  those  in  which  I  should  speak 


EFFORT.  295 

of  a  good  or  bad  horse.  I  mean  that  the  man  is  better  or 
worse  than  the  average  man,  and  I  take  for  granted  that 
he  has  all  the  qualities  essential  to  humanity.  This  already 
involves  one  ambiguity,  for  it  becomes  a  question  how  far 
certain  qualities  which  may  be  absent  should  put  a  man 
outside  the  class  to  which  we  are  in  all  cases  making  a  tacit 
reference.  What  are  the  characteristics,  one  might  ask, 
which  bring  a  man  within  the  sphere  of  morality  ?  It  is 
not  "fair,"  we  often  say,  to  judge  a  man  in  one  age  by  the 
moral  standard  of  another  age.  It  is  not  fair  to  judge  a 
man  exposed  to  temptation  by  the  standard  applicable  to 
one  who  is  not  tempted.  And  with  these  difficulties  may 
be  classed  the  more  practical  difficulties  which  so  frequently 
occur  in  criminal  law,  when  we  have  to  decide  how  far  a 
child  or  a  madman  can  be  considered  as  responsible  for  his 
actions.  The  difficulty  results  to  a  great  extent  from  a 
confusion  between  different  classes  of  questions.  When  we 
speak  of  the  merit  of  an  action,  we  really  speak,  as  I  have 
said,  of  the  qualities  which  it  implies.  If  we  have  solved 
that  question,  which  may  be  one  of  extreme  difficulty,  we 
have  next  to  ask  how  far  and  in  what  way  the  man  who  has 
those  qualities  differs  from  the  moral  man,  and  how  far, 
therefore,  they  imply  morality  or  the  reverse?  Keeping 
these  problems  apart,  we  shall  see,  I  think,  that  though  they 
involve  great  difficulties  of  application,  the  governing  prin- 
ciple is  sufficiently  clear. 

30.  A  man  tortures  a  prisoner,  but  torture  is  not  con- 
demned by  the  morality  of  the  time.  Is  the  torturer  wicked? 
Clearly  not  wicked  according  to  one  standard,  and  clearly 
wicked  accordino;  to  ours.  Which  standard  should  we 
apply  ?  That,  I  should  say,  depends  upon  the  problem 
which  we  are  considering.  He  is  not  proved  to  be  a  bad 
man  according  to  the  morality  of  the  day.  The  action, 
therefore,  does  not  imply  the  same  degree  of  cruelty  which 
would  be  implied  by  a  similar  action  now.  We  should  not 
be  justified  in  inferring  that  he  was  cruel  in  other  relations 
of  life,  as  we  should  now  be  justified  in  a  similar  inference. 


296  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Suppose  that  we  have  made  our  inferences  correctly,  and 
discovered  that  the  man  was  up  to  the  average  standard  of 
his  time,  our  judgment  is  complete.  He  was  not  in  advance 
of  his  time,  and  we  do  not  respect  him  so  much  as  we  should 
respect  one  who  was  in  advance.  He  is  not  so  good  a  man, 
again,  as  a  man  who  is  up  to  an  improved  moral  standard; 
that  is,  he  is  not  so  uniformly  merciful  or  benevolent. 
Possibly  his  innate  qualities  were  as  good ;  and  had  he  been 
born  under  the  improved  standard,  he  would  have  been 
as  good.  That,  as  it  seems  to  me,  is  all  that  we  can  say. 
"Merit"  does  not  mean  a  separable  quality  which  is  the 
same  at  all  periods,  but  carries  with  it  a  statement  of  rela- 
tion to  a  varying  standard,  and  therefore  cannot  be  definitely 
valued  apart  from  the  circumstances  without  a  sophistry. 
Each  of  the  two  men,  we  must  reply,  is  equally  good, 
measured  by  his  own  standard ;  their  innate  qualities  may 
have  been  equally  good  also;  but  one  man  is  absolutely 
better  in  so  far  as  he  represents  a  more  advanced  type  of 
humanity.  We  cannot  sum  up  these  various  statements  by 
a  single  statement  about  "  merit."  That  can  only  be  done 
satisfactorily  when  we  assume  that  both  agents  belong  to 
the  same  class,  and  are  to  be  judged  by  a  single  standard. 
We  fall  into  the  same  kind  of  perplexity  as  if  we  were  to 
compare  the  wealth  of  a  man  of  to-day  with  the  wealth  of 
his  ancestor.  We  may  compare  the  amount  of  gold  which 
each  man  possesses,  or  the  amount  of  actual  enjoyment 
which  it  purchases,  or  the  position  in  the  society  which  it 
confers;  but  to  answer  definitely  the  question  which  is  in- 
volved, we  must  distinguish  the  sense  in  which  the  question 
is  asked.  Then  the  ambiguity  disappears,  though  the  diffi- 
culty of  answering  may  be  immense. 

31.  The  question  is  more  perplexing  when  we  have  to  do 
with  cases  such  as  the  child  or  the  madman,  when  the  indi- 
vidual has  qualities  (or  an  absence  of  qualities)  which  seem 
to  take  him  out  of  the  class.  But  the  same  mode  of  answer- 
ing applies  equally.  Thus,  for  example,  children  and  some 
adults  are  without  the  passions  which  are  regulated  by  one 


EFFORT.  297 

important  part  of  the  moral  law.  What  are  we  to  think  of 
them  ?  Simply  this,  that  they  are  without  these  passions. 
If^  then,  they  refrain  from  certain  vices,  their  abstinence 
does  not  prove  chastity.  It  simply  shows  that  in  respect 
of  this  quality  they  are  neutral,  neither  good  nor  bad.  It 
would  be  a  clear  mistake  in  logic  to  identify  the  case  of  the 
man  who  has  certain  passions  under  control  and  the  man 
who  has  not  the  passions  at  all.  But  a  man  is  neither  moral 
nor  immoral  in  so  far  as  he  has  the  passions,  for  in  them- 
selves they  are  neither  good  nor  bad.  The  man  who  has 
them  not  will  indeed  be  so  far  disqualified  for  certain  social 
relations,  as,  on  the  other  hand,  he  will  be  free  from  certain 
temptations.  The  ordinary  inferences  as  to  character,  and 
therefore  our  judgment  of  his  virtue  or  merit,  will  be  falla- 
cious. But  he  will  still  have  a  character,  which  may  be 
either  virtuous  or  the  reverse  in  the  highest  degree  in  all 
other  respects,  and  we  shall  judge  him,  if  we  judge  rightly, 
according  to  the  conformity  of  his  character  to  the  type,  so 
far  as  it  goes.  He  cannot  be  a  perfect  man  in  the  full  sense, 
for  he  is  without  qualities  which  are  essential  to  the  race, 
but  then  the  defect  is  not  such  as  to  imply  any  moral 
defect  in  any  of  the  relations  which  he  is  capable  of  fulfilling. 
It  would  therefore  be  absurd  to  call  him  either  moral  or 
immoral  in  respect  of  this  defect.  We  can  only  say  that  he 
is  defective,  but  that  the  defect  is  morally  neutral.  There 
may  be  a  liability  to  error  in  our  ordinary  inferences  as  to 
the  facts  of  character,  and,  when  the  facts  are  known,  in 
saying  what  degree  of  deflection  is  implied ;  but  the  prin- 
ciple seems  to  be  simple. 

33.  Thus,  again,  we  have  the  case  of  the  madman,  with 
all  the  ever-recurring  difficulties  of  deciding  what  is  meant 
by  madness.  It  is  agreed,  of  course,  that  a  madman  is  not 
responsible  so  far  as  he  is  under  actual  illusions,  and  supposes 
himself  to  be  beheading  a  cabbage  when  he  is  really  killing 
a  man.  The  test  and  the  ordinary  inferences  as  to  character 
would  fail.  But  madness  shades  into  sanity  by  imperceptible 
degrees,  and  we  are  asked  to  pronounce  a  moral  judgment 


298  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

upon  such  cases  as  that  of  the  "homicidal  mania."  A  mad- 
man, it  is  suggested,  is  not  responsible,  because  he  cannot 
help  it  or  has  lost  his  free-will ;  the  sane  man  can  help 
himself,  and  is  therefore  responsible.  As  I  consider  free-will 
to  be  an  illusion,  I  cannot  accept  this  theory,  nor  can  I  see 
why  the  madman  should  be  supposed  to  be  without  it.  The 
more  unaccountable  a  man's  actions,  the  more  one  would 
be  inclined  to  admit  the  presence  of  some  arbitrary  agent. 
A  man  who  possessed  free-will  in  a  large  degree,  whose 
actions  obeyed  no  assignable  rule,  would  certainly  appear 
to  be  mad.  The  argument,  however,  points  to  the  obvious 
explanation.  No  one  would  consider  a  man  to  be  less 
responsible  for  a  murder  in  proportion  to  the  strength  of  his 
malice.  The  more  malicious  he  is,  the  more  certain  he  is  to 
commit  murder ;  the  less  is  his  malice  restrainable  by  fear, 
or  conscience,  or  any  other  motive ;  and  therefore,  in  the 
judgment  of  every  man^  the  greater  is  the  crime.  We  hold 
the  madman  to  be  not  responsible  for  precisely  the  opposite 
reason,  namely,  that  in  him  murder  does  not  imply  malice, 
but  some  different  impulse;  he  is  not  accessible  to  the 
ordinary  motives.  ''  Homicidal  mania,"  if  used  simply  to 
imply  a  high  degree  of  cruelty  or  malice,  would  not  take  the 
sufferer  out  of  the  ordinary  moral  code ;  it  can  only  do  so 
when  it  means  that  his  mental  machinery  is  out  of  gear,  so 
that  the  ordinary  motives  do  not  have  their  normal  effect. 
His  mind,  we  say,  is  deranged.  He  deviates  from, the  type, 
not  as  a  man  deviates  in  whom  certain  passions  are  unusually 
strong,  but  by  some  undefined  and  undefinable  organic  dif- 
ference, which  prevents  him  from  being  amenable  to  the 
natural  motives.  Murder  is  in  him  not  the  manifestation  of 
malice,  but  a  proof  that  his  brain  is  in  an  abnormal  condition, 
due  perhaps  to  an  accident  or  to  some  obscure  constitutional 
defect  entirely  unconnected  with  his  moral  character,  and 
therefore  not  justifying  the  ordinary  inference.  This,  as  it 
seems  to  mc,  is  more  or  less  explicitly  assumed  in  all  cases  of 
madness.  We  do  not  call  a  man  mad  uuless  we  assume  a 
deflection  in  his  psychological  organisation  from  that  of  the 


EFFORT.  299 

type  which  prevents  him  from  being  amenable  to  the  moral 
motives,  and  such  a  deflection  as  implies  disease  and  a  dis- 
integration of  the  faculties  necessary  for  a  due  discharge  of 
the  vital  functions.  The  difficulty  of  saying  in  a  given  case 
what  constitutes  this  deflection  is  enormous;  but  in  any  case 
we  do  not  judge  that  the  actions  of  the  sane  man  are 
independent  of  motives  whilst  those  of  the  madman  are  de- 
pendent, but  that  whilst  both  have  motives,  the  madman's 
motives  are  ^'irrational"  or  abnormal. 

^^.  The  perplexity  which  thus  intrudes  itself  into  our 
conceptions  of  merit  is  a  difficulty  in  judging  of  facts. 
What  character  does  a  given  action  imply?  What  is  the 
value  of  a  given  character  ?  What  is  the  class  to  which  a 
man  is  to  be  referred,  and  how  far  should  our  judgment  be 
affected  by  his  passions  or  qualities  which  distinguish  him 
from  other  members  of  the  class  ?  All  such  questions  are 
very  difficult  in  themselves,  and  in  our  rough  daily  estimates 
of  merit  we  have  to  solve  them  after  a  very  summary  fashion, 
and  often  with  very  inconsistent  results.  We  apply  one 
measure  of  merit  in  particular,  which,  though  perfectly 
rational  in  itself,  has  led  to  various  perplexities.  Conduct, 
I  have  said,  is  meritorious  so  far  as  it  proves  merit ;  it  can 
only  prove  merit  so  far  as  it  implies  difficulty  for  the  average 
man.  Leonidas  was  as  brave  before  Thermopylae  as  after ; 
he  was  only  known  to  be  brave  when  he  had  proved  his 
courage  by  accepting  a  fate  from  which  cowards  shrank. 
Hence,  it  is  argued,  merit  only  accrues  in  respect  of  difficult 
performance;  whilst  again  it  is  said  the  greater  the  difficulty 
the  greater  the  merit,  and  thus  that  whatever  a  man  does 
simply  to  please  himself  is  no  credit  to  him. 

34,  The  fallacy  which  is  sometimes  involved  in  this  state- 
ment is  too  simple  to  require  a  long  examination ;  the  full 
statement  of  the  case  is  enough  to  expose  it.  The  man  is 
most  meritorious  who  has  most  virtue;  consequently,  if  we 
assume  that  a  certain  task  has  to  be  performed,  the  man 
who  performs  it  most  easily  is  the  most  virtuous.  Leonidas 
was  braver  in  proportion  as  he   had   no   tendency  to    run 


300  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

away ;  I  am  honester  in  proportion  as  T  feel  less  disposition 
to   pocket  my  neighbour's   spoons.      A   man  who   felt   no 
disposition  whatever  to   commit   any  sin  would   so   far  be 
absolutely  perfect,  and   such  a   character  is  attributed    by 
Christians  to  a  divine  man.     Christ  was  not  the  less  perfect 
if  he  never  felt  the  least  velleity  to  do  wrong;  on  the  con- 
trary, such   a   character  represents  the  unattainable  moral 
ideal.    For  the  same  reason  it  is  true  that,  if  we  suppose  the 
task  to  increase  in  difficulty,  the  man  is  most  honest  who 
overcomes  the  greatest  difficulty — that  is,  the  greatest  diffi- 
culty for  a  given  strength.     The  less  the  difficulty  for  him, 
the  greater    the   difficulty  which   he   can  overcome.      The 
greater  the  danger,  the  greater  the  bravery ;  the  heavier  the 
bribe  offiired,  the  greater  the  honesty  displayed  in  resisting 
it,  and  so  forth.     The  principle  is  precisely  the  same  as  in 
the  case  of  a  mechanical  exertion ;  the  man  is  the  strongest 
who  can  lift  the  heaviest  weight,  or  who  can  lift  a  given 
weight  with  the  greatest  ease.     But  (and  it  is  a  proof  of  the 
loose  argument  which  has  often   been   accepted  in  ethical 
disputes)   the  two  cases  have  sometimes  been  confounded. 
It  would  plainly  be  absurd  to  say,  "  The  man  is  strongest  who 
lifts  the  greatest  v»^eight ;  therefore  the  man  who  makes  the 
greatest  effort ;  therefore  the  man  who  makes  the  greatest 
struggle  to  lift  a  given  weight."      But  it  has  occasionally 
been  said   that   the   man   is  most  virtuous  who   resists   the 
greatest  temptation ;  therefore  the  man  who  has  the  greatest 
struggle;  therefore  the  man  who  has  the  greatest  difficulty 
in    resisting   a    given    temptation.       Though    the    fallacy 
docs  not  occur  in   this   bare  form,  it   is  not   unfrequently 
implied  in  the  assumption  that  the  effort,  taken  absolutelv, 
is  the  measure  of  merit ;  we  are  occasionally  tempted,  that 
is,  to  confound  the  difficulty  which  arises  from  an  extrinsic 
or  morally  neutral  motive  with  that  which  arises  from  the 
moral   (or  immoral)    impulse  itself.      We  are  thus   led   to 
excuse  a  man  for  the  very  qualities  which  make  him  wicked. 
True  he  committed  a  murder,  but  he  was  so  spiteful  that  he 
could  not  help  it ;  or  he  was  exceedingly  kind,  but  he  is  so 


EFFORT.  301 

good-natured  that  it  cost  him  no  efTort.  Obviously  such 
reasoning  is  absurd,  but  it  suggests  the  necessity  of  guarding 
our  statement. 

'^^.  The  man,  I  have  said,  is  most  virtuous  who  performs 
a  given  virtuous  act  with  the  least  effort ;  but  on  looking 
closer,  we  see  that  this  statement  might  lead  to  the  mis- 
understanding already  explained.  We  might  argue,  in  fact, 
that  temperance  showed  greater  virtue,  when,  in  truth,  it 
merely  shows  a  defect  in  some  faculty  of  enjoyment.  If  a 
man  resists  any  inducement  because  it  has  no  charms  for 
him,  his  act  does  not  prove  virtue,  unless  the  inducement  be 
such  as  to  appeal  only  to  the  wicked.  Our  formula  really 
involves  an  assumption  which  must  be  explicitly  stated.  The 
man  is  most  meritorious  who  is  virtuous  with  least  effort, 
provided  always  that  he  has  the  normal  passions  of  a  man. 
We  virtually  assume  as  the  basis  of  our  comparisons  that  two 
men  are  constituted  in  the  same  way  so  far  as  their  moral 
qualities  are  not  involved ;  that  each  of  them  is  equally  sen- 
sitive to  certain  modes  of  enjoyment  so  long  as  the  enjoy- 
ment is  not  opposed  by  any  moral  motive.  Then  we  say, 
and  are  justified  in  saying,  that  the  man  is  most  virtuous 
who  is  so  constituted  that  virtuous  conduct  is  easiest  to  him. 
If,  for  example,  two  men  enjoy  the  taste  of  wine  equally, 
the  man  is  most  temperate  to  whom  abstinence  from  exces- 
sive use  of  wine  costs  the  least  exertion.  But  if  one  man 
abstains  because  he  dislikes  wine,  we  cannot  argue  as  to  his 
moral  superiority;  for,  in  the  first  place,  his  abstinence  in 
that  case  affords  no  presumption  that  he  will  refrain  in  other 
cases ;  and,  in  the  next  place,  a  man  is  so  far  the  worse  as 
he  is  wanting  in  any  capacity  not  intrinsically  bad.  A  taste 
for  wine  exposes  a  man  to  certain  temptations,  but  it  is  also 
presumably  a  symptom  of  certain  organic  advantages  which 
make  him  so  far  a  more  eflective  being  than  the  man  in 
whom  it  is  deficient. 

'^6.  This  brings  us  to  a  very  important  point.  The  infer- 
ence from  a  particular  act  is  always  precarious,  and  part  of 
our  perplexity  arises  from  deciding  what  is  or  is  not  implied 


302  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

in  any  given  line  of  conduct.  Conduct,  which  is  the  same 
so  far  as  the  external  circumstances  are  concerned,  may  be  a 
manifestation  of  very  diiferent  qualities  of  character  acci- 
dentally coinciding  upon  this  particular  point.  The  man 
with  strong  but  disciplined  passions  may  act  in  the  same 
way  upon  a  given  occasion  as  the  man  without  passions, 
though  he  would  on  other  occasions  act  differently.  Hence 
the  "merit"  of  the  action  is  indeterminate,  inasmuch  as 
it  may  result  from  different  motives.  Putting  this  aside,  or 
assumins;  the  motive  to  be  ascertained,  we  have  therefore  a 
further  question  of  facts.  We  may  ask,  in  fact,  whether  the 
primitive  instincts  of  which  a  man's  nature  is  composed  are 
to  be  regarded  as  morally  indifferent,  or  whether  there  are 
various  primitive  instincts,  some  of  which  are  morally  good, 
whilst  others  are  morally  bad?  In  the  latter  case,  the  suppres- 
sion of  a  bad  instinct  would  of  course  imply  a  higher  pitch 
of  virtue ;  and  this  doctrine  seems  to  be  assumed  in  ascetic 
systems,  and  is  sometimes  even  pushed  to  the  degree  of 
maintaining  (in  words  at  least)  that  all  the  natural  instincts 
are  bad.  It  w^ould  be  superfluous  for  me  to  assign  the 
grounds  upon  which  I  reject  this  theory.  The  whole  doc- 
trine of  evolution  seems  to  imply  that  absolutely  pernicious 
instincts  are  eliminated  in  the  struggle  for  existence,  and  to 
fall  in  with  the  other  assumption  that  virtue  implies  a  cer- 
tain organisation  of  the  instincts,  and  not  the  extirpation  of 
any  existing  instincts.  Assuming  this  for  the  present,  the 
inference  as  to  the  particular  question  before  us  seems  to  be 
simple. 

37.  Every  new  sensibility  or  faculty  is  so  far  an  advantage 
to  the  agent.  A  man  is  a  completer  being  or  at  a  higher 
stage  of  development  in  so  far  as  he  has  acquired  any  faculty 
not  shared  by  his  fellows.  (I  assume,  of  course,  that  it  also 
implies  a  total  increase  of  power.)  Again,  every  such  faculty, 
so  far  as  it  is  morally  indifferent,  exposes  its  possessor  to  fresh 
temptations,  as  well  as  gives  him  fresh  capacities  for  virtue. 
Cultivated  tastes  often  encourage  indolence,  as  they  also 
enable  us  to  confer  fresh  services  upon  our  fellows.     If  even 


EFFORT.  303 

a  sensual  appetite,  such  as  a  love  of  wine,  exposes  a  man 
to  temptation,  it  also  helps  materially  to  save  him  from  a 
sour  and  unsociable  temper.  A  man  so  far  as  he  possesses 
greater  faculties  is  not  necessarily  more  moral  or  less  moral ; 
he  is  only  capable  of  a  more  extensive  virtue  or  a  wider 
deviation  from  virtue.  He  is  moral  in  the  highest  sense 
when  he  possesses  the  most  richly  endowed  nature,  and  when 
it  is  also  so  disciplined  that  he — that  is,  when  his  instincts — 
are  so  correlated  and  organised  that  he  spontaneouslyobeys  the 
moral  law.  To  be  defective  in  any  faculty  is  to  be  on  a  lower 
platform,  and  to  come  under  the  moral  law  at  a  smaller 
number  of  points.  An  action  which  proves  such  a  defect 
proves  nothing  as  to  the  morality  of  the  agent  in  the  cases 
where  morality  is  possible  for  him.  But  it  is  also  true,  of 
course,  that  such  a  defect  saves  a  man  from  certain  tempta- 
tions, as  it  also  removes  some  opportunities  for  moral  excel- 
lence. He  is  without  a  faculty  which  may  lead  him  into 
moral  ruin,  as,  if  properly  disciplined,  it  may  enrich  and 
strengthen  his  morality. 

38.  Hence,  therefore,  we  may  say  that,  in  one  sense,  effort 
is  essential  to  merit.  A  man,  that  is,  must  possess  the 
"  natural"  instincts  in  order  to  become  a  proper  subject  for 
morality  at  all.  If  he  possess  them  in  any  given  degree, 
he  is  the  more  moral  in  proportion  as  they  are  so  disciplined 
that  moral  action  is  easy  for  him.  But  inasmuch  as  the 
instincts  are  themselves  neutral,  this  always  implies  a  certain 
accessibility  to  temptation,  and  therefore  a  certain  struggle. 
He  cannot  be  properly  temperate  unless  he  is  capable  of 
enjoying  the  pleasures  which  tempt  to  excess.  If  he  has  no 
such  capacity,  he  is  not  in  this  respect  a  moral  agent  at  all. 
So  far  therefore  as  the  effort  is  taken  as  a  symptom  that  he 
is  accessible  to  the  temptation,  it  is  certainly  essential  to 
virtue.  But  assuming  a  certain  strength  of  the  appetites, 
the  more  virtuous  he  is,  the  less  will  be  the  effort  in  a  given 
case,  for  the  more  thoroughly  they  will  be  harmonised  and 
disciplined.  No  human  being,  we  may  add,  can  be  absolutely 
or  infinitely  virtuous.     Every  motive  in  a  finite  being  must 


304  '  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

have  a  finite  strength.  We  may  therefore  say  with  the  cynic 
that  every  man  has  his  price.  Some  conceivable  strength  of 
temptation  would  overpower  any  human  virtue.  Thus  a 
capacity  for  sinning  is  implied  in  a  capacity  for  doing  right, 
for  both  imply  the  existence  of  passions  which  may  be 
enlisted  on  either  side  of  the  struggle.  We  may  even  say  in 
this  sense  that  the  more  a  man  is  capable  of  sinning,  the 
more  he  is  capable  of  virtue,  for  the  virtuous  and  the  vicious 
character  are  different  modifications  of  the  same  primitive 
instincts,  and  the  man  is  on  a  higher  stas;e  the  more  thev 
are  developed.  But  given  the  instincts,  the  temptation  to 
sin  and  the  disposition  to  sin  can  no  more  prove  a  man  to  be 
virtuous  than  the  actual  sin. 


IV.  Knowledge. 

39.  This  brings  us  to  the  third  consideration.  The  doctrine 
that  virtue  implies  effort  is  associated  with  the  doctrine  that 
the  primary  instincts  are  either  corrupt  or  neutral.  Some 
theological  systems,  starting  from  the  dogma  of  the  corruption 
of  human  nature,  are  logically  drawn  to  the  conclusion  that 
virtue  represents  a  supernatural  influence  governing  and 
subduing  the  natural  instincts.  The  philosopher  who  rejects 
this  domia  and  denies  the  validitv  of  this  division  between 
the  natural  and  the  supernatural  so  far  admits  the  method 
as  to  assign  to  reason  the  functions  of  divine  grace.  Reason 
thus  dominates  and  controls  the  passions,  though  they  are 
not  regarded  as  positively  bad,  but  rather  as  neutral  or 
morallv  indifferent.  So  far  as  a  man  acts  from  instinct  he  acts 
"  irrationally,^'  and  therefore  not  morally.  Every  instinct, 
as  I  have  said,  may  be  the  ally  or  the  opponent  of  the  moral 
motives.  A  mother's  love  makes  her  sacrifice  herself  to  her 
children,  but  it  may  also  lead  her  to  cruelty  to  others  for 
their  fjood.  It  is  onlv  virtuous  then,  or  meritorious,  insofar 
as  it  implies  a  love  of  virtue  and  a  principle  of  action  which 
will  guide  her  when  her  passions  are  on  the  wrong  side. 
Conduct,   it  is   inferred,  is  truly  virtuous  when,  and  only 


KNOWLEDGE.  '  305 

whcn^  the  action  is  done  because  it  is  virtuous.  The  motive 
must  be  the  pure  love  of  virtue  or  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake. 
Otherwise,  since  conduct  dictated  by  the  emotions  alone  is 
morally  neutral,  or  even,  as  it  is  sometimes  said,  arbitrary, 
it  cannot  be  regarded  as  properly  speaking  virtuous. 

40.  The  principle  involved  in  this  reasoning  is  implied  in 
all  that  I  have  said.  To  say  that  an  action  is  virtuous  is  to 
say  that  it  is  a  manifestation  of  a  virtuous  character.  It  is 
perfectly  true,  therefore,  that  we  cannot  infer  virtue  from 
an  action  which  springs  from  a  motive  conmion  to  all  men 
or  to  all  animals,  such  as  hunger  or  fear.  An  action  which 
only  proves  that  a  man  has  an  appetite  or  dislikes  pain 
does  not  prove  him  to  be  either  good  or  bad.  A  man's 
virtue  or  intrinsic  merit  depends  upon  his  whole  character, 
and  his  character  is  a  complex  of  many  instincts  connected 
by  laws  inscrutable  to  our  imperfect  methods,  and  acting 
and  reacting  in  a  vast  variety  of  most  delicate  and  intricate 
ways.  The  question  as  to  virtue  or  merit  is  the  question  as 
to  whether  the  whole  character  does  or  does  not  imply  action 
in  conformity  with  the  moral  law.  The  question,  then, 
may  be  asked,  how  far  such  conformity  is  possible  without 
an  explicit  recognition  of  the  law.  If  it  is  possible  for  a 
man  to  act  as  the  law  directs  without  so  acting  because  the 
law  directs,  then  his  conduct  is  said  to  be  "materially"  but 
not  "formally"  moral.  Now  there  can  be  no  a  priori  objec- 
tion to  such  a  conformity.  It  is  not  true  (as  some  language 
seems  to  imply)  that  conduct  dictated  by  instinct  or  emo- 
tion is  arbitrary.  Nothing  is  arbitrary.  Every  instinet 
has  its  own  law,  though  it  may  not  consciously  recognise 
the  law.  And  though  each  instinct,  taken  separately,  may 
be  morally  indifierent,  it  does  not  follow  that  the  complex 
character  built  up  of  those  instincts  is  morally  indifferent. 
An  instinct  is  not  a  separate  entity,  but  expresses  the  reac- 
tion of  the  whole  character  under  a  special  stimulus;  and 
the  whole  must  have  laws  of  its  own,  which  express  more  or 
less  approximation  to,  or  deviation  from,  the  moral  type. 

How  far  that  conformity  involves  an  explicit  recognition  of 

u 


3o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  law  is  a  question  of  facts^  of  great  complexity  doubtless, 
upon  which  a  few  words  must  here  be  sufficient. 

41.  It  is  clear^  in  the  -first  place^  that  reason  is  in  some 
sense  essential  to  virtue.  I  deny  the  possibility  of  separating 
the  reason  from  the  feelings  as  two  distinct  faculties^  and 
hold,  on  the  contrary,  that  in  every  act  of  an  intelligent 
being  both  reason  and  emotion  are  necessarily  involved. 
Morality  proper  becomes  possible  at  the  point  at  which 
sympathy  is  possible ;  and  sympathy  involves  reason,  for  it 
involves  the  recognition  of  other  centres  of  consciousness. 
The  germs  of  morality  may  be  present  at  an  earlier  stage, 
but  the  germ  is  not  the  developed  product.  The  moral  law, 
again,  involves  the  knowledge  of  many  facts,  and  often  of 
very  complex  facts.  Cruelty  and  kindness  cannot  emerge 
until  we  recognise  the  existence  of  other  sentient  beings, 
nor  truthfulness  or  justice  till  we  can  understand  general 
rules,  nor  chastity  and  temperance  till  we  can  distinguish 
between  the  cases  of  legitimate  and  illegitimate  indulgence. 
The  growth  of  any  of  the  social  relationships,  of  the  state  or 
the  family,  imposes  obligations  which  cannot  be  appreciated 
until  those  relationships  are  intelligible;  and  in  the  higher 
stages  of  life  this  involves  very  complex  conceptions.  Every 
development  of  intelligence  implies  an  extension  of  the 
emotional  range,  and  consequently  of  the  sphere  of  duty. 
Conversely,  every  extension  of  the  moral  code  implies  a  deve- 
lopment both  of  intelligence  and  feeling.  A  man  who  could 
feel  without  thinking  or  think  without  feeling  is  an  incon- 
ceivable being,  and  we  have  no  more  to  do  with  him  than 
an  ordinary  geometer  with  space  of  four  dimensions. 

42.  Consistently  with  this,  it  still  remains  such  that  a  man 
may  (and  indeed  must)  act  regularly  though  he  does  not  act 
by  rule ;  or  again,  that  he  may  act  in  conformity  with  a 
moral  rule  without  an  explicit  regard  to  its  moral  character. 
He  may  become  aware  that,  in  fact,  it  expresses  his  character, 
though  he  has  not  referred  to  it  as  the  reason  of  his  actions. 
The  moral  law  is  the  ^'objective"  law  of  his  conduct,  but 
not  the '''subjective"  law  or  "  reason."    I  eat  when  I  am 


KNOWLEDGE.  307 

hungry ;  so  far  I  act  temperately,  though  I  may  not  think  of 
the  rule.     I  help  a  man  in  distress  because  distress  always 
affects  me,  though  I  never  think  of  the  general  principle  ; 
and  so  far  I  am  charitable  without  recoo-nisino;  the  dutv  of 
charity.     The  more  spontaneous  the  kindly  feeling,  the  less 
the  need  for  reference  to  a  moral  rule;  and  accordingly  we 
regard  a  man  with  some  suspicion  who  has  always  to  remind 
himself  of  the  moral  obligation  in  order  that  he  may  do  what 
others  do  spontaneously.     This  indeed  follows  if  we  regard 
morality  as  the  product  of  a  character  which  allows    the 
various  instincts  to  operate  in  their  proper  places  instead  of 
superseding  them  by  some  different  faculty,  and  it  suggests 
the  answer  to  our  difficulty.      Maternal  love,  it  is  said,  is 
not  virtuous  so  far  as  it  is  a  mere  natural  instinct.     This 
(upon  our  hypothesis)  means  that  it  is  not  virtuous  because 
it  is  consistent  with  many  bad  qualities,  and  may  prompt  to 
injustice  on  behalf  of  the  children;   but  no  one  can  deny 
that   it  is  so  far  virtuous   that  it  is  implied  in  a  virtuous 
character.     We  should  condemn  a  mother  in  whom  it  was 
deficient,  and  condemn  her  expressly  on  the  ground  that  she 
would  be  ''wanting  in  natural  feeling."     The  feeling  does 
not  constitute  positive  merit,  because  it  is  assumed  in  the 
average  standard ;  but  for  the  same  reason  its  absence  is  a 
positive  demerit,  or  a  conclusive  proof  of  inferiority  to  the 
moral  type.     The  mother  who  had  no  affection  for  her  child 
would  be  so  far  a  bad  woman ;  she  would  be  without  the 
emotions  which  are  the  very  groundwork  of  all  the  virtues. 
It  is  of  course  true  that  the  affection  is  not  sufficient  bv 
itself  to  make  her  virtuous,  and  that  even  then,  in  many 
cases,  it  may  lead  her  astray.     Still  it  is  essential  to  virtue, 
and,  in   the    vast   majority  of  cases,  favourable  to  virtue; 
whilst,  in  the  rare  cases  in  which  it  leads  to  wrongdoino-, 
it  may  be  held  in  check  by  other  sympathetic  feelings  which 
spring  from  the  same  root  without  any  conscious  reference 
to  a  moral  law.     It  is  true  that  so  long  as  that  conscious 
reference  is  absent  we   are  without  the   full  guarantee  for 
a  regular  observance  of  the  moral  law.     A  recognition  of 


3o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

that  law  is,  on  every  hypothesis,  the  crown  and  final  outcome 
of  the  moralised  character ;  but  a  close  approximation  to 
morality  may  exist  previously,  just  because  it  is  a  product, 
and  not  a  precedent  condition.  If  this  be  the  true  state  of 
the  case  or  an  approximation  to  it,  if  morality  may  exist 
in  fact  without  a  previous  reference  to  the  moral  law,  we 
are  quarrelling  over  words  if  we  deny  the  name  "  virtuous  " 
to  such  characters. 

43.  What  is  true  of  the  maternal  affections  is  true  of  all 
the  instincts  by  which  conduct  is  determined.  A  man  is 
virtuous,  not  so  far  as  he  is  without  passions,  nor  so  far  as 
they  are  dominated  by  some  external  force,  but  so  far  as  they 
constitute  a  harmonised  whole,  determining  the  approxima- 
tion of  character  to  the  best  social  type.  The  main  and 
essential  condition  of  morality  is  the  altruism  which  enables 
a  man  to  appropriate  the  feelings  of  others^  and  so  to  acquire 
instincts  with  a  reference  to  the  social  good.  That  quality, 
which  is  not  a  separate  organ,  but  an  inseparable  incident  of 
the  development  of  the  reasoning  and  feeling  agent,  supplies 
the  necessary  leverage  upon  which  the  social  sentiments 
operate.  Its  bare  existence,  even  in  a  high  degree,  does  not 
suffice  to  make  a  man  thoroughly  moral,  but  it  capacitates  him 
for  morality,  and  renders  immorality  proportionately  difficult. 
A  man  is  moral  because  and  in  so  far  as  his  instincts  are 
correlated  according  to  a  certain  type.  He  cannot  become 
thoroughly  moral,  especially  in  a  society  in  which  the  moral 
law  has  been  distinctly  formulated,  without  becoming  con- 
scious of  the  law  of  his  own  action,  and  the  recognition  be- 
comes of  great  importance  as  a  guide  for  his  conduct  in  cases 
where,  without  such  a  rule,  he  might  fail  to  perceive  the  true 
nature  of  his  conduct.  He  may  be  brave,  temperate,  and 
truthful  without  ever  reflecting  upon  the  law  which  com- 
mands the  corresponding  actions;  his  sympathies  may  be  so 
strong  as  to  guard  him  against  most  kinds  of  wrongdoing ; 
and  if  so,  I  should  certainly  call  him  virtuous,  though  he 
should  never  think  of  right  and  wrong  as  such,  but  be 
always  guided  by  his  immediate  feelings.     Undoubtedly  such 


KNOWLEDGE.  309 

a  man  would  still  be  defective,  as  a  man  would  be  defective 
who  trusted  to  his  immediate  perceptions  for  the  knowledge 
that  two  sides  of  a  triangle  were  greater  than  the  third  in 
every  particular  case,  instead  of  recognising  the  general 
principle.  But  upon  my  theory,  the  recognition  of  the 
general  rule  follows  from  the  specific  intuitions  instead  of 
preceding  them.  Upon  a  different  philosophical  theory  the 
facts  would  be  differently  expressed.  Meanwhile  I  can  only 
say,  that,  upon  my  showing,  it  is  simply  a  question  of  fact 
how  far  the  actual  observance  of  the  law  involves  a  recogni- 
tion of  the  law,  and  one  which  cannot  be  solved  by  a  priori 
considerations. 

44.  This  brings  us  to  the  question  which  must  be  more 
fully  considered  in  the  next  chapter.  What  is  the  nature  of 
conscience,  or  the  intrinsic  motives  to  right-doing?  The 
question  is  obviously  of  the  highest  importance,  and  the 
answer  to  it  will  clench  this  part  of  the  inquiry.  At  pre- 
sent I  have  only  tried  to  show  that,  whatever  it  may  be, 
intrinsic  merit  is  properly  a  name  for  the  virtuous  character 
considered  in  a  special  relation,  and  that  the  perplexities 
arise  in  great  measure  from  a  confusion  between  merit  in 
this  sense  and  that  merely  relative  merit  which  means  not 
the  actual  virtue,  but  the  virtue  proved  by  any  given  action; 
or,  again,  between  the  qualities  considered  in  themselves  and 
the  estimate  placed  upon  them  at  different  periods.  Clear- 
ing away  these  difficulties,  there  remain  difficulties  which  I 
have  considered,  and  of  which  I  need  only  remark  in  con- 
clusion, that  they  are  all  more  or  less  associated  with  the 
familiar  illusion  sanctioned  by  the  double  sense  of  the  word 
'Maw."  A  scientific  law,  as  has  been  so  often  said,  is  nothing 
but  a  generalised  statement  of  facts ;  but,  in  spite  of  all  that 
has  been  said,  it  is  difficult  to  avoid  the  impression  that  it 
corresponds  in  some  way  to  an  external  something  impressed 
upon  the  facts.  In  this  way  true  if  not  self-evident  state- 
ments lead  to  inextricable  labyrinths  of  confusion.  If  we 
speak  of  a  man's  character  as  obeying  a  law,  we  mean  only 
that  he  has  a  fixed  character.     We  are  taken  to  mean  that 


3IO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

besides  this  character  there  is  a  law  which  governs  the  cliar- 
acter^  and  thus  external  coercion  is  confounded  with  internal 
determination,  and  freedom,  in  the  sense  of  freedom  of  the 
character  from  itself  as  well  as  freedom  from  an  outward 
restraint,  is  made  a  condition  of  moral  conduct.  Again,  if 
we  take  the  rule  as  a  something  forced  upon  a  set  of  bad  or 
neutral  instincts,  we  assume  that  an  effort  corresponding  to 
this  process  is  essential  to  virtue.  Virtue  is  not  simply  the 
expression  of  a  certain  harmony  between  the  instincts,  but 
a  constraining  power  opposed  to  instinct  and  emotion  in 
general.  And  so,  finally,  this  abstraction  becomes  the  sole 
principle  of  virtuous  conduct,  and  virtue  is  only  possible  in 
so  far  as  it  is  recognised.  Thus,  according  to  my  theory, 
the  various  conditions  of  merit  which  we  have  been  con- 
sidering are  distortions  of  some  perfectly  simple  principles. 
The  simple  fact  is,  that  when  we  speak  of  a  man's  conduct 
as  virtuous,  we  assume  that  it  is  really  conduct,  that  is,  really 
determined  by  his  character;  that  it  is  the  conduct  of  a  real 
man,  that  is,  of  one  who  has  the  normal  instincts,  appetites,  and 
emotions ;  and  really  virtuous,  that  is,  the  manifestation  of  a 
character  which  conforms  to  the  type  and  implies  a  uniform 
obedience  to  the  law.  This  is  distorted  into  the  assumption 
that  a  man  must  be  free,  not  only  from  outward  restraint, 
but  from  his  own  character  ;  that  his  feelings  must  not  only 
be  regulated  by  each  other,  but  entirely  suppressed  by  some 
external  power;  and,  finally,  that  he  must  not  only  act 
rationally,  but  act  from  abstract  principles  of  reason  instead 
of  regulated  emotion. 


(     311     ) 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

THE      CONSCIENCE. 

I.   Theories  of  Conscience. 

1.  Having  thus  attempted  to  clear  away  the  ambiguities 
connected  with  the  word  "  merit/'  and  to  show  that  merit 
means  simply  the  value  set  upon  virtue^  we  have  still  to  ask, 
What  is  the  quality  valued  ?  A  man,  I  have  said,  can  only 
be  virtuous  when  he  obeys  the  moral  law  "spontaneously," 
"  unconditionally,"  or  from  the  intrinsic  motives  implied  in 
the  law  itself.  A  man  gives  money  to  the  poor ;  is  he 
charitable  ?  The  question  can  only  be  answered  if  I  know 
the  motive,  or,  which  is  the  same  thing,  know  how  the  man 
will  act  when  circumstances  vary.  If  he  acts  from  direct 
sympathy,  he  is  charitable ;  if  from  ostentation,  he  is  only 
acting  from  a  desire  of  praise.  His  action  conforms  externally 
in  this  particular  case  to  the  rule  which  would  be  dictated  by 
charity,  but  it  is  not  therefore  charitable.  The  truly  chari- 
table man  would  give  wherever  he  could  relieve  distress, 
whether  he  received  praise  or  failed  to  receive  it ;  the  osten- 
tatious man  would  do  whatever  gained  praise,  whether  his 
action  did  or  did  not  relieve  his  nei2;hbour.  If  we  make  a 
similar  statement  in  regard  to  virtuous  conduct  generally, 
we  must  say  that  a  man  is  truly  virtuous  only  when  he  acts 
from  an  intrinsically  virtuous  motive — when  his  action  is 
therefore  a  guarantee  that  he  will  always  be  virtuous,  or 
when  the  simple  fact  that  conduct  of  a  certain  kind  is  com- 
manded by  the  moral  law  is  a  sufficient  motive  with  him  for 
adopting  that  mode  of  conduct. 

2.  What,    then,    is    the    intrinsic    motive    to    virtue  ? 


312  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Various  explanations  may  be  adopted  according  to  our 
moral  theory.  In  any  case,  it  may  be  admitted  that  con- 
duct is  only  virtuous  in  so  far  as  it  is  the  manifestation 
of  a  truly  virtuous  character — that  is,  of  a  character 
such  that  the  agent  will  always  act  in  conformity  to  the 
moral  law.  Obedience  to  a  law  is  sometimes  explained 
most  simply  from  the  analogy  of  the  positive  law  as  im- 
plying respect  for  some  external  authority.  The  motive, 
then,  common  to  all  virtuous  conduct  is  the  motive  (what- 
ever it  may  be)  which  prompts  obedience  to  this  rule. 
With  theological  utilitarians,  for  example,  it  is  taken  to  be 
the  fear  of  supernatural  penalties.  The  difficulty  which 
then  occurs  is  that  the  motive  appears  to  be  extrinsic ;  it  is 
fear  of  a  god  or  devil  which  makes  us  moral ;  and  though 
we  may  say  that,  as  a  fact,  the  Deity  affixes  penalties  to 
conduct  of  a  certain  kind,  the  connection  seems  to  be  arbi- 
trary. We  cannot  say  why  this  or  that  particular  kind  of 
conduct  should  be  punished  or  rewarded,  and  morality  is 
thus  explained  by  explaining  it  away.  This,  again,  may  be 
avoided  by  saying,  with  the  ordinary  utilitarians,  that  moralitv 
means  that  conduct  which  produces  a  maximum  of  happi- 
ness. The  difficulty  presents  itself  that  the  test  seems  to  put 
all  kinds  of  happiness  on  a  level,  and  therefore  to  affiard  no 
apparent  means  of  explaining  the  specific  feeling  attached 
to  moral  conduct,  or  the  difference  between  the  propositions 
"This  is  right"  and  "This  is  useful."  Another  answer  is 
therefore  adopted,  and  we  are  told  that  the  essential  motive 
to  morality  is  not  the  fear  of  a  deity  simply,  but  the  fear  of 
a  good  deity,  or  that  there  is  a  specific  feeling,  different 
from  all  others,  to  which  we  give  the  name  of  Conscience, 
and  which  supplies  its  own  credentials.  The  obvious  diffi- 
culty is  that  such  an  explanation  explains  nothing.  We 
cannot  tell  what  a  good  deity  will  approve  unless  we  know 
what  is  meant  by  goodness ;  and  if  goodness  is  explained  to 
us  by  a  faculty  of  which  it  is  the  sole  function  to  declare 
what  is  good,  we  fall  into  a  vicious  circle.  Another  answer 
is,  therefore,  to  say  that  the  law  gives  its  own  authority  in 


THEORIES  OF  CONSCIENCE.  313 

the  same  sense  as  a  logical  proposition ;  it  is  ])incling  because 
reasonable;  we  cannot  deny  its  validity  without  falling  into 
a  contradiction  in  terms.  Conduct  is  virtuous  only  when  it 
implies  a  love  of  virtue  "for  its  own  sake;"  and  this  is 
interpreted  to  mean  that  the  rule,  when  apprehended  by 
the  reason,  compels  our  assent  by  its  inherent  reasonable- 
ness, like  the  rule  that  things  which  are  equal  to  a  third  are 
equal  to  each  other.  But  here  we  assume  that  conduct  can 
be  determined  without  reference  to  feeling,  and  we  explain 
the  uniformity  of  action  by  an  assumption  which  makes 
action  unintelligible, 

3.  How  are  these  various  difficulties  to  be  met?  The 
method  which  resolves  morality  into  reason  is,  from  my 
point  of  view,  unacceptable  upon  grounds  sufficiently  indi- 
cated in  the  whole  course  of  my  argument.  I  have,  in  fact, 
assumed  all  along  that  conduct  is  determined  by  feeling,  and 
this,  which  appears  to  me  to  be  true,  so  far  as  we  can  push 
our  analysis,  is  certainly  true,  I  think,  within  the  sphere  of 
science.  It  is  true,  that  is,  that  we  are  determined  to  act 
by  our  desires,  appetites,  or  emotions,  even  if  the  metaphy- 
sician and  the  outologist  can  by  some  means  explain  a  desire 
as  a  process  of  the  individual  or  the  universal  reason.  The 
statement  that  I  eat  because  I  am  hungry  expresses  a  fact 
with  which  we  are  concerned,  even  if  it  be  not  the  ultimate 
form  of  expression.  Any  rule,  again,  which  is  deduced  from 
the  pure  reason  seems  to  me  to  have  too  wide  an  application. 
Formal  rationality  has  no  special  relation  to  ethics.  No 
moralist  has  succeeded  in  any  plausible  deduction  of  the 
moral  code  without  tacitly  introducing  an  appeal  to  specific 
facts  properly  irrelevant  to  his  doctrine.  If  general  logical 
rules  can  be  deduced  in  this  way,  moral  rules  can  only  be 
deduced  by  some  dexterous  sleight  of  hand.  "  Ought"  and 
"ought  not"  (as  Hume  somewhere  says)  are  suddenly  in- 
serted in  the  place  of  "  is  "  and  "  is  not,"  Nor,  again,  can 
such  a  method  decide  between  different  codes  of  morality  so 
long  as  they  satisfy  the  general  condition  of  logical  coher- 
ence.    "  Let  every  one  care  for  one,"  is  as  good  a  rule  in 


314  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  sense  of  formal  logic  as  the  rule,  "  Let  every  one  love 
his  neighbour  as  himself."  We  can  only  decide  which  is 
the  best  rule  by  appealing  to  facts  given  by  experience,  but 
not  deducible  from  any  d  priori  canon  of  logic.  Not  only 
so,  but  the  law,  as  generally  stated,  seems  to  me  to  give  a 
wrong  rule  in  many  cases.  In  some  senses  it  tends  (as  I 
shall  have  to  observe  hereafter)  to  make  the  external  rule 
unconditional  instead  of  the  internal,  and  to  substitute 
"  Do  this  "  for  "  Be  this."  And,  finallv,  I  think  that  it  is 
at  bottom  an  inadequate  statement  of  the  undeniable  truth 
that  not  only  is  logical  consistence  implied  in  the  moral 
law,  but  that  the  emotional  development  implies  at  every 
step  a  corresponding  development  of  the  reason.  It  may  be 
maintained  that  as  men  are,  to  be  perfectly  reasonable  is 
also  to  be  perfectly  moral.  But  we  cannot  omit  the  con- 
dition "as  men  are,"  or  infer  morality,  without  taking  into 
account  the  specific  constitution  of  men  and  human  society, 
and  we  shall  have  perhaps  further  to  affix  a  special  sense  to 
the  words  "  perfectly  reasonable." 

4.  The  theory,  again,  of  an  autonomous  or  independent 
conscience,  of  a  faculty  which  exists  as  a  primitive  and  ele- 
mentary instinct,  and  which  is  therefore  incapable  of  further 
analysis,  appears  to  be  equally  untenable.  I  agree,  indeed, 
that  here  too  we  have  an  inaccurate  statement  of  a  highly 
important  truth.  The  theory  needs  the  less  discussion  be- 
cause it  is  part  of  an  obsolete  form  of  speculation.  Nothing 
is  easier  than  to  make  out  a  list  of  separate  faculties  and  to 
call  it  a  psychology.  The  plan  had  its  negative  advantages 
so  far  as  it  was  in  useful  antithesis  to  an  easy-going  analysis, 
which  was  too  quickly  satisfied  with  explanations  of  complex 
mental  phenomena.  At  the  present  day  no  one  will  deny 
the  propriety  of  rigidly  cross-examining  the  claims  of  anv 
instinct  to  be  an  ultimate  factor  in  the  orcjanisation.  The 
difliculties  which  apply  to  all  such  speculations  (as,  for  ex- 
ample, to  the  phrenological  theory  of  separate  organs)  are 
not  diminished  in  the  case  of  conscience.  When  we  take 
into    account    any    theory    of    evolution    they   arc    greatly 


THEORIES  OF  CONSCIENCE.  315 

increased.  The  conscience  appears  historically  as  a  develop- 
ment of  simpler  instincts.  The  broad  fact  must  be  admitted 
that  "material  morality"  makes  its  appearance  long  before 
any  conscious  recognition  of  a  moral  law.  We  may  pro- 
bably trace  the  germs  of  the  moral  instincts  down  to  the 
associations  of  animals ;  and  we  may  at  least  assume  that 
men  live  together  and  obey  certain  rules,  of  which  the  exist- 
ing moral  law  is  a  continuous  development,  long  before  they 
have  any  distinct  conception  of  such  a  law,  as  distinguished 
from  other  rules  with  which  it  is  originally  identified,  and 
from  which  it  is  slowly  disengaged  as  civilisation  advances. 
It  would  require  a  very  forced  interpretation  of  the  pro- 
cess to  see  in  it  the  introduction  of  an  entirely  new  factor 
instead  of  a  gradual  development  of  previously  existing 
sensibilities. 

5.  Without  appealing  to  the  evolutionist,  we  need  not 
hesitate  to  say  that  the  theory  of  conscience  as  an  elementary 
faculty  is  untenable  or  superfluous.  Conscience  in  any  case 
means  the  pain  felt  by  the  wrongdoer,  or  rather  the  sen- 
sibility implied  by  that  pain.  It  is  exerted  when  we  judge 
that  we  have  deserved  blame,  and  we  deserve  blame  when 
we  display  some  moral  deficiency.  Now  a  separate  instinct 
— a  physical  appetite,  for  example,  such  as  hunger  or  lust — 
mav  give  us  pain  when  its  dictates  are  suppressed  by  some 
conflicting  impulse.  It  corresponds  to  a  particular  function 
of  the  organism ;  it  is  excited  by  the  appropriate  stimulus, 
and  is  the  sole  instinct  directly  interested  in  a  given  class  of 
actions.  It  is  supreme  within  its  own  province,  but  it  has 
to  struggle  because  it  is  part  of  a  complex  whole  which  can 
only  act  in  one  way  at  once,  though  accessible  to  a  variety 
of  stimuli.  But  it  is  impossible  to  conceive  of  the  conscience, 
in  accordance  with  this  analogy,  as  a  particular  faculty 
co-ordinate  with  others,  or  as  possessing  a  separate  province 
within  which  alone  it  is  applicable.  We  may  indeed  say, 
in  a  sense  already  explained,  that  some  conduct  is  morally 
indiflerent,  and  therefore,  if  we  will,  outside  the  sway  of  the 
conscience.     That  is  merely  to  say  that  many  actions  do 


3i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

not  justify  any  inference  as  to  the  moral  character^  and  are 
therefore  neither  meritorious  nor  demeritorious  in  the  sense 
of  proving  virtue  or  vice.  From  the  fact  that  a  man  is 
hungry  or  obeys  hunger  we  can  only  infer  that  he  has  a 
quality  common  to  the  virtuous  and  the  vicious.  No  moral 
judgment  arises.  But  this  does  not  mean  that  the  instinct 
itself  has  no  moral  quality;  only  that  the  quality  cannot  be 
inferred  from  the  particular  action.  A  man's  appetite  for 
food  has  certain  determinate  relations  to  his  other  instincts 
and  affections  ;  and  according  as  it  exerts  a  certain  influence^ 
the  man  is  either  greedy  or  temperate,  and  so  far  vicious 
or  virtuous.  Hence  a  man's  intrinsic  merit  or  his  virtue  is 
always  a  function  of  his  character  considered  as  a  whole, 
and  is  affected  by  every  variation  of  the  elementary  instincts, 
though  his  merit,  in  the  sense  of  his  manifested  or  proved 
virtue,  is  not  inferable  from  the  simple  fact  that  he  has 
some  instinct  which  may  be  exerted  either  for  or  against  the 
moral  law.  Conscience,  in  short,  always  implies  a  judgment 
of  the  whole  character,  although,  as  a  rule,  it  considers  only 
some  special  manifestation,  and  a  defect  or  fitness  in  some 
special  relation.  If  it  were  an  instinct  co-ordinate  with 
others,  we  should  then  require  a  further  judgment  to  say 
whether  it  was  in  excess  or  defect  relatively  to  the  whole 
of  which  it  forms  a  part ;  and  this  other  faculty  would  have 
a  better  claim  to  be  called  conscience. 

6.  In  this  sense,  it  may  be  remarked,  the  love  of  virtue 
"  for  its  own  sake "  is  sometimes  used  so  as  to  convey 
an  absurdity.  I  may  love  eating  for  its  own  sake,  because 
there  is  a  specific  appetite  which  corresponds  to  a  particular 
stimulus,  and  I  mean  simply  to  say  that  the  act  of  eating 
is  pleasant  because  it  gratifies  this  appetite,  whilst  no  other 
appetite  is  directly  interested.  But  it  is  impossible  to  con- 
ceive of  a  love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake  as  implying  a  state 
of  mind  in  which  the  conscience  was  gratified  whilst  no 
other  instinct  was  interested.  If  conduct  is  such  as  to  give 
no  direct  stimulus  to  anv  of  the  other  instincts,  to  my 
love  or  hate,  or  hope  or  fear,  or  my  physical  appetites  or 


THEORIES  OF  CONSCIENCE.  317 

feelings,  then  the  conscience  cannot  be  stimulated.  Tt  is 
awakened  whenever  the  agent  perceives  that  his  appetites 
are  excessive  or  his  emotions  distorted  ;  but  it  has  nothing 
to  act  upon  when  none  of  his  appetites  or  emotions  are 
concerned.  By  the  love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake,  we 
can  only  mean  that  the  fact  that  an  action  is  moral,  with 
all  the  necessary  implications  of  that  statement,  whatever 
they  may  be,  is  enough  to  determine  to  that  action ;  and  not 
that  it  has  absolutely  no  other  implications,  which  would, 
in  fact,  be  to  make  it  inconceivable  as  conduct  at  all. 

7.  If  we  still  speak  of  the  conscience  as  a  separate  faculty, 
but  admit  that  it  is  stimulated  only  when  other  emotions 
are  stimulated,  the  proposition  seems  to  evade  our  grasp. 
If  we  consider  it  as  a  simple  feeling,  excited  through  the 
perception  of  other  emotions,  its  law  must  be  dependent 
upon  them.  The  specific  emotion  will  be  produced  when 
certain  conditions  arise  which  can  be  stated  independently 
or  in  terms  of  the  other  instincts.  It  is  a  kind  of  parasi- 
tical or  dependent  sensibility,  which  gives  its  responses  in 
obedience  to  the  impinging  forces.  It  varies  as  they  vary; 
and  therefore,  whether  we  admit  or  reject  the  hypothesis,  it 
cannot  give  its  own  law  directly.  We  must  inquire  else- 
where what  are  the  conditions  under  which  it  produces  a 
painful  or  a  pleasurable  emotion.  If,  on  the  other  hand,  we 
conceive  of  conscience  as  a  something  which  judges  of 
an  action  by  some  inherent  power,  we  see  that  we  really 
have  to  attribute  to  it  reasoning  and  feeling,  a  power  of 
estimating  an  action,  comparing  it  with  a  rule,  of  weighing 
and  sympathising  with  all  the  various  passions  concerned;  and, 
in  short,  we  find  (as  is  generally  the  case  with  the  separate 
faculties  of  psychologists)  that  we  are  not  really  speaking  of 
a  conscience  as  one  amongst  various  powers  of  an  individual, 
but  of  a  conscientious  man,  who  is  somehow  a  spectator  of 
the  agent  from  within, 

8.  Without  further  expanding  considerations  which  are 
sufficiently  obvious,  and  which  refer  to  a  rather  anti- 
quated   form    of    theory,   I    must    come    to    the    question, 


3i8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

What,  then,  Is  the  conscience?  If  it  be  neither  a  distinct 
emotion  nor  a  purely  intellectual  judgment,  how  are  we  to 
account  for  it?  I  admit,  of  course,  that  there  is  such  a 
feeling — or  rather,  my  theory  rests  upon  the  admission  that 
it  exists.  Conduct  is  determined  by  feeling,  and  virtuous 
conduct  by  the  particular  kind  of  feeling  which  we  call  the 
conscience.  I  consider  it,  indeed,  to  be  not  a  primary  attri- 
bute of  the  agent  (to  borrow  Spinoza's  language),  but  a  mode 
of  the  attributes.  It  is  not  the  less  important.  Remorse 
for  crime  is  clearly  amongst  the  most  poignant  of  emotions. 
It  has  driven  some  men  mad ;  it  has  blighted  the  whole 
lives  of  others ;  it  has  in  all  ages  been  one  great  source  of 
the  power  of  the  classes  who  were  able  to  regulate  its  action 
and  alleviate  its  pangs.  Its  existence  is  as  undeniable  as  the 
existence  of  hunger  or  cold  or  heat.  Yet  I  feel  bound  to 
add  that  well-meaning  moralists  are  much  given  to  exaggerate 
the  sorrow  which  it  actually  excites.  In  almost  every  case 
the  pain  which  we  feel  for  a  bad  act  is  complex,  and  due 
only  in  part  to  our  conviction  that  we  have  broken  the 
moral  law.  The  sorrow  which  I  feel  for  having  injured  a 
friend  is  made  up  in  part,  but  only  in  part,  of  the  sorrow 
which  I  feel  for  having  injured  him  wrongfully.  We  may 
frequently  observe  how  faint  is  the  purely  conscientious 
emotion.  I  kill  a  man,  let  us  suppose,  by  an  accident — by 
carelessly  handling  a  loaded  gun,  or  when  really  trying  to 
do  him  a  service,  as  by  mistaking  him  in  the  dark  for  a  wild 
beast,  whose  attack  might  be  fatal  to  us  both.  Or,  again,  I 
mean  to  kill  him,  and  take  every  step  in  my  power,  but  he 
escapes  by  some  entirely  unforeseen  circumstance.  I  give 
him  what  I  believe  to  be  poison,  and  it  turns  out  to  be  a 
wholesome  drink ;  or,  vice  versa,  I  poison  him  meaning  to 
do  him  good.  Now  my  guilt  is  obviously  proportioned  in 
such  cases  to  my  intention :  the  carelessness  is  precisely  the 
same  whether  it  produces  fatal  effects  or  none;  the  malice 
is  equal  whether  the  object  docs  or  docs  not  happen  to 
escape.  But  it  cannot  be  doubted,  I  think,  that  as  a  rule 
the  remorse  felt  by  most  men  depends  almost  entirely  upon 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  319 

the  event.  Men  arc  made  wretched  for  life  when  they  have 
killed  a  friend  by  pure  accident^  even  where  the  carelessness 
has  been  most  trifling;  they  speedily  acquit  themselves  for 
the  ffuilt  of  an  action  dictated  bv  a  malevolent  intention, 
and  completed  so  far  as  depended  upon  them,  when  by  some 
accident  the  intention  has  not  been  realised.  These  facts 
may  show,  as  indeed  I  think  they  do  show,  that  men  reason 
very  loosely  in  such  matters,  and  often  receive  pain  or 
pleasure  from  mere  illusions  of  the  imagination.  But  this 
comes  to  the  same  thing — namely,  that,  as  a  matter  of 
fact,  the  purely  conscientious  feeling,  the  pain  resulting 
from  the  consciousness  of  my  wickedness,  is  often  very 
feeble,  and  that  much  of  what  we  call  by  that  name  is 
the  simpler  feeling  of  regret  for  the  mischief  caused,  irre- 
spectively of  the  wickedness  of  causing  it.  Deduct  from 
repentance  all  that  is  not  purely  moral,  and  we  must  admit 
that  conscience  is  not  so  strong  de  facto  as  perhaps  it  ought 
to  be  de  jure.  Indeed  I  should  say  that  most  men  find 
nothing  easier  than  to  suppress  its  stings,  when  some  imme- 
diately bad  consequence,  or  the  contempt  and  abhorrence 
of  their  neighbours,  does  not  constantly  instil  the  venom. 
This  is  as  far  as  possible  from  proving  that  an  increased 
strength  of  conscience  is  not  highly  desirable,  and  that,  even 
in  the  existing  state  of  things,  its  influence  is  not  of  the  last 
importance.  The  force  of  gravitation,  as  physicists  tell  us, 
is  intrinsically  very  feeble  compared  with  many  others,  but 
it  keeps  the  planets  in  their  orbits ;  and  so  the  sense  of  duty, 
faint  and  flickering  as  it  is  in  the  great  mass  of  men,  is  suffi- 
cient to  keep  the  social  order  from  disruption. 


II.   The  Sense  of  Shame. 

9.  To  explain  fully  what  is  meant  by  conscience,  or  by 
any  other  mode  of  feeling,  would  require  a  complete  psycho- 
logy, such  as  is  not  at  present  in  existence.  It  is  enough  for 
my  purpose  if  I  can  show  that  it  is  explicable  in  conformity 
with  the  theory  already  laid  down.     We  have  to  ask  how 


320  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  conduct  forbidden  by  the  moral  law  comes  to  excite  a 
specific  sentiment^  which  we  interpret  as  disapproval  when  the 
agent  is  some  one  else^  as  a  pang  of  conscience  when  he  is  our- 
self  ?  The  difficulty  seems  to  be,  that  if  we  interpret  it  as  a 
simple  emotion,  it  appears  to  be  more  or  less  arbitrary ;  if  as 
an  intellectual  perception,  it  is  difficult  to  see  how  it  can  affect 
conduct ;  whilst  the  theory  which  makes  conscience  an  inde- 
pendent faculty,  invested  both  with  intellectual  and  emotional 
attributes,  seems  only  to  evade  the  difficulty  by  help  of  an 
unjustifiable  assumption.  In  any  case,  it  seems  clear,  how- 
ever, that  there  must  be  both  an  intellectual  and  an  emotional 
side  to  the  process.  The  old  moralists  distinguished  between 
the  conscience  which  declared  the  law  and  that  which 
punished  a  breach  of  the  law.  Each  process,  in  fact,  seems 
to  imply  the  other.  If  I  perceive  that  conduct  is  wrong 
because  forbidden  by  law,  the  sense  that  I  am  breaking  the 
law  must  be  painful,  in  order  that  the  law  may  have  any 
binding  force.  If,  again,  we  suppose  that  every  wrong  act  is 
attended  by  a  specific  feeling,  I  could  construct  the  law  by 
generalising  from  my  experience  of  the  feeling.  This  or  that 
act  causes  the  specific  pain  called  remorse;  these  actions, 
therefore,  are  forbidden  by  the  moral  law;  or  the  moral  law 
is  a  statement  of  the  actions  which  cause  remorse.  A  wrong 
action  would  be  definable  as  a  remorse-causing  action.  The 
function  of  conscience  would  be  similar  to  that  of  hearing 
in  regard  to  music.  The  ear  decides  authoritatively  that 
certain  sounds  are  discordant  and  others  harmonious.  The 
scientific  observer  notes  these  cases,  and  proceeds  to  determine, 
with  the  help  of  his  reason  and  his  other  senses,  what  are  the 
conditions  which  produce  disagreeable  sounds.  If  the  con- 
science were  in  fact  as  distinct  and  separable  a  faculty  as  the 
hearing,  we  should  be  able  to  decide  by  a  similar  process  what 
were  the  conditions  which  caused  painful  and  pleasurable 
emotions  of  this  particular  class.  It  might,  of  course,  turn 
out  that  the  conscience  varied  indefinitely  from  one  man  to 
another,  or  that  it  gave  uniform  decisions  in  all  men.  In 
the  former  case,  we  should  again  have  to  inquire  what  were 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  321 

the  laws  of  its  variation,  and  then  to  inquire  whether,  and  if 
so,  in  what  sense,  one  conscience  could  be  regarded  as  better 
than  another.  We  have,  however,  the  prehminary  difficulty 
already  stated,  that  the  conscience  is  not  in  this  way  marked 
off  from  all  other  modes  of  feeling  or  reasoning,  and  that 
the  law  is  given  much  more  distinctly  than  the  feelino;  by 
which  it  is  enforced. 

10.  There  is,  indeed,  a  sensibility  which  seems  to  have 
as  good  a  claim  as  any  other  to  be  regarded  as  elementary, 
and  which  is  clearly  concerned  in  most  of  our  moral  judg- 
ments. The  sense  of  shame  appears  to  me,  so  far  as  one 
can  judge  by  the  direct  introspective  method,  to  be  one  of  the 
most  distinctive  of  our  feelings,  and  the  presumption  seems 
to  be  confirmed  by  its  having  a  distinct  physical  manifestation 
of  blushing.  If  we  assume  that  this  emotion  is  really  some- 
thing distinct  in  itself,  we  may  ask,  as  we  ask  in  the  case  of 
music,  what  are  the  conditions  under  which  it  arises?  It  is 
clearly  excited  by  breaches  of  the  moral  law,  and  especially 
by  detected  breaches.  A  man  is  ashamed  of  himself  for  con- 
duct which  is  actually  condemned  by  the  moral  judgment  of 
his  neighbours,  so  far  at  least  as  he  sympathises  with  the 
general  morality,  and  he  is  ashamed  of  conduct  which  would 
be  condemned  if  known.  In  most  men,  however,  and  indeed 
in  all  but  exceptionally  sensitive  men,  the  shame  is  enor- 
mously increased  by  the  actual  condemnation,  and,  in  many 
cases,  seems  to  be  exclusively  due  to  the  consciousness  of  this 
condemnation.  Again,  so  far  as  I  can  guess,  it  does  not  appear 
to  me  that  the  sense  of  shame  is  proportioned  to  the  moral 
gravity  of  the  offence.  There  is  a  difficulty  in  speaking  posi- 
tively upon  such  a  matter,  because  the  relative  importance  of 
different  kinds  of  offences  is  very  differently  estimated  by 
different  moralists,  and  it  is  hard  to  sunu'est  any  assionable 
measure  of  the  gravity.  Some  moralists,  for  example,  attach  a 
preponderating  importance  to  veracity  and  others  to  chastity  ; 
some  think  more  of  the  virtue  of  justice,  and  others  of  the 
virtue  of  benevolence ;  but  it  is  not  possible  to  define  in  any 
way  the  weight  assigned  to  difierent  considerations,  especially 

X 


322  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

as  there  is  no  agreement  as  to  the  irrelevancy  of  particular 
considerations.  Speaking  roughly,  however,  one  would  say 
that  a  sense  of  shame  is  more  excited  bv  offences  of  sensuality 
than  by  offences  of  cruelty.  We  say,  indeed,  "What  a  shame ! " 
when  we  hear  of  a  gross  act  of  oppression ;  but  a  man  con- 
victed of  tvrannv  seems  hardly  to  be  liable  to  shame  in  the 
same  way  as  a  man  convicted  of  some  offence  against  purity. 
This  tvrant  may  excite  more  abhorrence  but  less  disgust;  he 
is  not  regarded  with  contempt,  and  the  sense  of  being  con- 
temptible is  peculiarly  connected  with  shame. 

II.  Thus,  again,  we  find  that  the  conduct  enforced  by 
the  sense  of  shame  seems  to  extend  beyond  the  sphere  of 
morality  proper.  We  may  perhaps  say,  in  a  general  way, 
that  indecency  is  wrong;  but  there  are  a  great  many  acts 
which  we  call  indecorous,  if  not  actually  indecent,  to  which 
we  should  scruple  to  give  so  grave  a  name.  A  want  of  com- 
pliance with  the  regulations  of  the  society  in  which  we  live 
excites  shame,  often  very  acutely  and  painfully,  and  yet  we 
should  hesitate  to  describe  it  as  immoral.  This,  of  course, 
comes  in  partly  under  a  familiar  principle.  If  it  is  right  to 
obey  a  ruler,  it  is  right  to  obey  his  particular  commands  in 
cases  where  the  conduct  would  otherwise  be  indifferent ;  and 
so,  in  many  cases,  it  is  right  to  do  at  Rome  as  Rome  does ; 
it  is  right  to  cover  parts  of  the  body  in  England  which  it 
may  be  right  to  leave  bare  in  Abyssinia.  But  it  seems  also 
to  be  true  that  the  emotion  of  shame  extends  beyond  the 
actions  which  would  be  regarded  as  in  any  sense  wicked. 
Nobody  would  call  a  man  immoral  for  appearing  at  a 
dinner-party  in  a  shooting-coat,  but  a  young  man  would 
probably  feel  more  ashamed  of  himself  for  such  an  action 
than  for  many  offences  which  he  would  admit  to  be  far 
graver.  Many  sensitive  people  would  feel  far  less  shame 
if  detected  in  a  crime  than  in  connnitting  an  indecent 
action,  even  though  the  breach  of  decency  were  involuntary, 
and  therefore  not  in  any  sense  immoral.  So  women  may 
cease  to  be  virtuous  without  ceasing  to  be  modest,  and  some 
might  possibly  prefer  a  loss  of  virtue  to  a  loss  of  modesty. 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  323 

12.  The  same  may  be  said  in  cases  which  arc  less  ambi- 
guous. Decency  may  always  be  regarded  as  a  kind  of  minor 
morality;  but  the  sense  of  shame  is  often  most  powerfully 
excited  in  cases  where  there  is  no  question  of  morality  at 
all.  There  are  few  things  which  a  man  remembers  with  a 
more  hearty  and  ineffaceable  sense  of  shame  than  his  having 
— in  the  vulgar  phrase — made  a  fool  of  himself.  A  youth 
who  has  tried  to  say  something  witty,  and  whose  luckless 
joke  has  fallen  flat  or  provoked  ridicule,  has  a  memory 
which  will  revisit  him  in  dreams,  and  make  him  blush  in 
private  whenever  it  recurs  to  him.  Even  a  grave  moralist 
may  often,  I  suspect,  suffer  more  pain  for  such  slips  than  is 
visited  upon  him  for  indisputable  moral  offences.  And  not 
only  thus,  but  in  many  cases  the  sense  of  shame  operates 
against  the  moral  code.  The  boy  who  thinks  it  right  to 
say  his  prayers  is  ashamed  when  his  practice  is  detected  by 
unsympathetic  observers.  In  some  cases  a  young  man  is 
ashamed  of  chastity  and  sobriety  when  his  companions  act 
upon  different  principles,  even  though  they  do  not  explicitly 
deny  the  validity  of  the  moral  code.  We  call  this,  of  course,  a 
false  shame,  and  doubtless  it  is  "  false  "  in  the  sense  that  it 
can  only  be  justified  by  false  reasoning;  but  it  is,  whilst  it 
lasts,  as  real  as  any  other  feeling,  and  therefore,  whatever 
the  cause  of  its  being  enlisted  in  the  service  of  the  enemy, 
it  is  clear  that  it  is  not  invariably  to  be  found  as  an  ally  of 
conscience. 

13.  Now  the  general  principle  which  appears  to  be  in- 
volved in  this  case  is  simply  that  a  sense  of  shame  is  somehow 
involved  in  a  state  of  heightened  self-consciousness.  The 
bare  fact  that  we  are  the  objects  of  attention  is  sufficient  to 
produce  the  painful  seiisation  of  shyness,  and  that  even  when 
we  are  the  objects  of  admiring  attention.  We  see  ourselves 
through  the  eyes  of  others;  we  attend  to  ourselves  out  of 
sympathy  with  their  attention  to  us,  and  are  at  once  object 
and  subject  of  our  own  feelings.  When,  in  addition  to  this, 
the  attention  is  of  a  hostile  kind,  or  the  self-consciousness  a 
consciousness  of   defects;    when  we  are  the  objects  of  our 


324  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

own  hatred^  contempt^  disgust,  or  ridicule,  we  have  some  of 
the  most  disagreeable  emotions  of  which  our  nature  is  cap- 
able. If  this  be  the  general  law  of  the  feeling,  it  is  intelli- 
gible that  it  should  be  closely  connected  with,  and  yet  in 
many  respects  diverge  from,  the  conscientious  feeling.  So 
far  as  we  break  the  moral  law  we  are  acting  in  opposition 
to  the  general  sentiment,  and  therefore  incurring  disapproval. 
But  the  law  of  shame  does  not  coincide  precisely  with  the 
moral  code;  for,  in  the  first  place,  our  feeling  in  regard  to 
different  moral  offences  seems  to  differ  in  quality,  and  our 
abhorrence  of  crueltv,  though  it  may  be  in  some  senses 
stronger,  is  less  keen,  and  therefore  less  provocative  of  the 
sense  of  shame,  than  the  spasm  of  physical  disgust  which  we 
feel  for  some  kinds  of  sensuality ;  and,  in  the  next  place, 
the  code  extends  beyond  the  moral  code,  inasmuch  as  many 
things  are  exquisitely  ridiculous  which  are  not  immoral ; 
and,  finally,  it  may  even  conflict  with  morality,  in  that  case, 
at  least,  in  which  a  kind  of  spurious  moral  code  is  formed  by 
a  special  section  of  society,  or  in  cases  where  the  conduct 
deflects  from  the  average  standard,  not  by  falling  short,  but 
by  exceeding  it  in  a  way  which  seems  to  imply  a  tacit 
reproach  to  others. 

14.  The  sense  of  shame,  then,  is  in  some  sense  implicated 
in  conscientious  feeling.  It  is  clearly  a  part  of  the  emotion 
which  restrains  me  from  wrongdoing.  I  shrink  from  detec- 
tion in  shameful  conduct,  and  from  conduct  which  would  be 
shameful  if  detected.  The  motive,  whether  I  call  it  con- 
scientiousness or  not,  acts  on  behalf  of  any  accepted  moral 
code ;  but  we  cannot  identify  it  with  the  conscience,  because 
it  operates  fitfully,  affects  conduct  which  is  not  moral,  and  is 
sometimes  even  opposed  to  morality;  as  also  because  it  con- 
demns crimes  which  are  found  out  much  more  emphatically 
than  the  same  crimes  when  they  are  not  found  out.  The 
question  therefore  arises  how  such  an  emotion  can  supply  an 
intrinsic  motive  to  virtue.  Has  it  not  rather  a  dangerous  and 
disturbino;  influence  ?  So  far  as  I  am  accessible  to  shame,  shall 
I  not  be  inclined  to  over-estimate  the  judgment  of  the  special 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  325 

class  in  which  T  live,  to  regard  decorum  as  of  more  importance 
than  real  virtue,  to  make  respectability  the  measure  of  my 
conduct,  to  prefer  the  infliction  of  a  real  injury  upon  one 
who  cannot  complain  to  showing  the  least  disregard  in  public 
to  the  slightest  fancies  of  a  conspicuous  ruler,  to  obey  codes 
which  I  disapprove  in  my  heart,  such  as  that  which  enforces 
duellin(r,  and  to  break  throujrh  moral  laws  which  are  {generally 
neo-lected,  such  as  that  which  condemns  bribery ;  and,  above 
all,  shall  I  not  feel  a  much  greater  fear  of  being  found  out 
than  of  beinc-  g-uJltv?  To  this  I  should  replv:  Undoubtedlv 
shame  often  acts  in  this  undesirable  way.  It  is  not  identical 
with  conscience,  and  when  badly  informed  or  regulated  it 
may  even  put  obstacles  in  the  way  of  moral  progress,  and 
account  for  the  fitful  and  apparently  arbitrary  fluctuations  in 
the  moral  standard.  But  I  should  also  find  it  impossible  to 
say  that  the  shame  felt  by  a  sinner  is  not  part  of  the  con- 
scientious feeling  or  of  the  intrinsic  sanction  of  morality. 
The  difficulty  is,  that  if  we  admit  it  as  part  of  the  conscien- 
tious feeling,  we  admit  an  element  of  feeling  which  may  vary 
from  one  man  to  another,  and  which  does  not  account  for 
the  specific  character  of  conscience.  This  requires  a  little 
further  consideration. 

15.  Shame,  in  the  first  place,  is  the  name  of  a  certain  state 
of  consciousness.  I  know  that  I  am  ashamed  as  I  know  that 
I  have  the  toothache,  or  as  I  know  that  I  am  amused — by 
direct  feeling.  It  is  so  far  an  ultimate  fact,  which  cannot 
be  explained  any  more  than  any  other  immediate  feeling  or 
emotion ;  we  feci,  and  therefore  we  know  that  wc  feel,  and 
no  more  can  be  said.  But  we  may,  of  course,  proceed  to 
ask,  What  are  the  conditions  under  which  this  feeling  is 
generated?  It  involves,  we  say,  a  certain  intellectual  per- 
ception ;  we  have  only,  then,  to  say  what  is  this  perception 
in  order  to  assign  the  law  of  the  feeling.  So,  for  example,  it 
would  be  easy  to  suggest  that  shame  arises  when  we  perceive 
our  inferiority  to  others,  and  then  to  infer  that  shame  is  the 
perception  of  inferiority.  This  method,  however  tempting  it 
may  be,  leads  in  fact  to  endless  confusion.    Nothing  is  really 


326  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

more  difficult  than  to  discover  the  law  of  a  feeling.  Philo- 
sophers dispute  endlessly  as  to  the  definitions  of  such  words 
as  "  beautiful,"  "  ludicrous/'  or  "  shameful."  Although 
every  one  may  understand  what  is  the  emotion  which  arises 
when  we  see  a  beautiful  object,  or  are  moved  to  laughter  by 
the  ludicrous,  or  to  blushing  by  the  shameful,  it  is  at  least  as 
difficult  to  discover  the  law  of  these  emotions  as  to  discover 
the  law  of  any  physical  phenomena,  and  the  only  satisfactory 
method  is  in  either  case  by  a  systematic  interrogation  of 
experience;  we  should,  in  fact,  have  to  discover  all  the  cases 
in  which  we  do,  in  fact,  feel  the  emotion  in  question.  When 
we  are  ashamed  we  are  ashamed,  and  we  are  often  ashamed 
when  our  preconceived  formula  seems  to  be  inapplicable. 
We  feel,  and  in  each  particular  case  we  know  our  feeling,  or 
in  other  words  we  are  conscious ;  but  we  are  not  by  any  means 
directly  conscious  of  the  law  of  the  feeling,  or  able  to  say  in 
what  other  cases  it  will  arise.  So  soon  as  we  begin  to  gene- 
ralise we  are  liable  to  indefinite  error,  and  we  are  just  as  apt 
to  go  wrong  about  the  phenomena  of  our  own  consciousness 
as  about  any  other  phenomena.  The  reason  is,  as  I  should 
say,  that  the  perception,  for  example,  of  our  inferiority  is  not 
a  bare  logical  process,  but  is  also  a  mode  of  feeling:  it  involves 
a  comparison  of  immediate  and  represented  states  of  feeling; 
and  the  compound  emotion  which  arises  will  vary  as  they 
vary,  and  cannot  be  deduced  from  the  simple  statement  of 
the  identity  or  diversity  of  two  conceptions.  In  fact, 
nothing  is  more  common  than  to  find  that  the  philosophical 
definition  hopelessly  breaks  down,  and  that  we  do  not  feel 
wdiat  our  theorists  tell  us  that  we  shall  feel  when  the  case 
actually  occurs.  In  short,  to  find  the  law  of  any  of  these 
modes  of  feeling  requires,  not  a  simple  generalisation  of 
a  formal  loi2;ical  statement,  but  a  verifiable  and  scientific 
psychology. 

i6.  The  feeling  of  shame,  then,  appears  as  a  positive  datum 
in  our  theories.  It  represents  a  matter  of  fact  which  can 
only  be  explained  and  its  laws  determined  through  careful 
observation.     In  this  sense  it  seems  to  irive  rise  to  direct  and 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  327 

unassailable  intuitions.  In  any  given  case,  at  least,  I  am 
conscious  of  feeling  or  of  not  feeling  shame,  and  I  may,  if  I 
please,  state  this  as  an  intuitive  perception,  that  the  condition 
in  which  I  am  placed  is  shameful.  Nor,  again,  am  I  much 
further  advanced  if  I  admit  that  shame  arises  whenever  I  am 
conscious  of  doimr  something  disgustins;,  ridiculous,  or  even 
strongly  provocative  of  the  attention  of  others;  for  I  must 
ask  what  are  the  conditions  which  make  conduct  ridiculous, 
disgusting,  and  so  forth.  This  is  no  easier  than  to  say  what 
makes  it  shameful.  And  not  only  so,  but  it  would  seem 
that  the  relation  is  reciprocal ;  that  is  to  say,  that  a  man  in 
whom  a  sensibility  to  shame  is  keen  will  find  things  ludicrous 
or  disgusting  which  are  not  so  to  his  less  sensitive  neighbour; 
and  thus,  again,  we  seem  to  be  falling  into  a  vicious  circle,  or 
to  have  an  insoluble  problem. 

17.  The  case,  however,  so  far  as  we  are  concerned,  may 
be  sufficiently  solved.  In  the  first,  shame,  considered  as  a 
mode  of  feeling,  has  a  certain  and  conceivably  determinable 
function  in  the  moral  constitution.  It  is  not  arbitrary  except 
in  the  sense  that  it  is  a  datum  which  is  given  by  experience, 
but  cannot  be  deduced  by  any  a  priori  process.  It  is  not 
arbitrary  in  the  sense  of  being  susceptible  of  indefinite  varia- 
tion, which  seems  to  be  the  impression  of  those  who  would 
say  that  to  admit  such  a  feeling  as  determining  the  conscience 
is  to  make  morality  a  mere  "matter  of  taste."  Even  taste 
or  fashion  is  not  "  arbitrary  "  in  the  full  sense  of  the  word, 
for  in  that  sense  nothing  is  arbitrary;  it  has  its  laws,  though 
thev  are  laws  consistent  with  a  very  wide  variation  from  one 
individual  to  another.  The  emotion  is  of  course  limited  by 
the  physiological  and  psychological  laws  of  the  individual 
structure.  It  may,  as  I  have  said,  vary  very  widely  in  some 
respects.  A  degree  of  nudity  which  is  excusable  in  one 
region  is  disgusting  in  another ;  and,  generally  speaking, 
the  emotion — as  follows  from  its  general  nature — is  of  course 
very  amenable  to  custom.  As  a  medical  student  soon  loses 
the  sense  of  horror  at  surgical  operations,  a  child  brought  up 
in  a  degraded  social  state  feels  no  instinctive  revolt  against 


328  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

impurity,  dishonesty,  falsehood,  or  cruelty.  But  the  variation, 
though  it  is  impossible  to  assign  its  limits,  because  we  have 
not  the  necessary  experience  for  deciding  such  a  problem,  is 
clearly  not  indefinite,  llie  instinctive  repugnance  to  sights 
of  blood  and  mangled  flesh  may  be  suppressed,  but  it  could 
not  be  generated  at  pleasure  in  regard  to  any  other  objects. 
So,  as  I  have  suggested,  the  feeling  of  shame  is  specially 
stimulated  where  certain  passions  are  concerned,  and  this 
implies  the  existence  of  physiological  laws  which  cannot  be 
altered  so  long  as  the  most  fundamental  properties  of  human 
nature  remain.  We  may  doubt  how  far  it  would  be  possible, 
by  any  course  of  training,  to  invert  the  sense  of  shame  in 
particular  cases,  and  to  make  those  actions  disgraceful  which 
are  now  honourable  or  vice  versa.  But  in  any  case,  it  is 
clear  that  the  variation  is  limited  and  forced  to  take  place 
along  certain  lines,  if  we  may  so  speak,  by  the  constitution 
of  our  nature.  It  can  no  more  be  arbitrarily  changed  at  the 
will  of  some  other  person  than  a  legislator  could  order  men 
to  be  seasick  on  land  and  comfortable  at  sea,  or  force  our 
gorge  to  rise  at  wholesome  food  and  make  carrion  appetising. 
The  organism  is  not  the  less  subject  to  precise  laws  because  it 
is  capable  of  responding  in  a  vast  variety  of  ways  to  different 
stimuli. 

1 8.  Undoubtedly,  however,  the  possible  variation  is  great 
enough  to  conform  to  the  observed  variability  of  moral 
codes.  If  men  are,  in  fact,  shameless  in  certain  respects  in 
one  country  and  ashamed  in  another ;  if  the  standards  of 
courage,  purity,  truthfulness,  and  benevolence  vary  widely, 
and  without  any  corresponding  variation  in  the  innate 
powers  of  the  individual,  it  follows  of  course  that  the  deter- 
mining condition  must  be  the  social  medium.  What  is  not 
explained  by  the  individual  organism  must  be  explained  by 
the  social  organism.  If  modern  Englishmen  are  disgusted 
by  conduct  which  did  not  disgust  Socrates,  we  must  explain 
the  difference  by  the  whole  social  development  which  has 
taken  place  in  the  interval ;  and,  if  my  theory  of  morality 
be  correct,  this  shows  in  what  sense  variation  is  possible. 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  329 

The  existence  of  a  social  order  or  a  certain  stage  of  develop- 
ment implies  a  corresponding  development  in  the  individual, 
considered  as  a  constituent  part  of  the  society.  This  develop- 
ment implies  on  the  one  hand  the  attainment  of  a  certain 
moral  standard,  which,  again,  implies  obedience  to  and 
respect  for  the  primary  moral  laws;  and,  on  the  other,  it 
implies  that  the  whole  character  of  the  individual,  including 
the  sense  of  shame,  which  is  one  of  the  most  powerful  factors 
in  determining  his  conduct,  must  be  so  modified  as  to  imply 
an  acceptance  of  the  standard.  The  fixed  element  which 
causes  the  sense  of  shame  to  develop,  so  to  speak,  along 
certain  lines,  is  simply  the  social  necessity.  I  have  tried  to 
show  in  what  sense  morality  is  essential  to  social  vitality, 
and  in  that  sense  and  within  these  limits  the  sense  of  shame 
must  be  so  moulded  as  to  maintain  the  moral  standard, 
unless  the  society  is  not  to  deteriorate,  and  to  raise  it  if  the 
society  is  to  make  progress. 

19.  This  is  enough  to  show  that  there  are  narrow  though 
not  easily  assignable  limits  to  a  possible  variation  of  the 
instinctive  feeling.  Social  development  implies  moral  deve- 
lopment, but  it  of  course  implies  much  more.  It  implies  the 
development  of  a  certain  type  of  character,  which  includes 
as  essential  certain  moral  qualities.  It  implies,  that  is,  the 
growth  of  mutual  confidence,  peacefulness,  the  restraint  of 
antisocial  passions,  and  so  forth.  But  though  a  certain 
moral  conformation  is  implied,  and  is  essential  to  the  social 
efficiency  of  the  agent,  his  possession  of  these  qualities  does 
not  define  his  character.  We  may  have  an  indefinite  variety 
of  talents  and  sensibilities  not  directly  concerned  in  this 
morality.  Consistently  with  moral  excellence,  he  mav  be 
an  artist,  a  philosopher  or  a  poet,  a  statesman  or  an  artisan, 
a  priest  or  a  lawyer,  and  in  each  case  his  character  and  his 
intellect  will  be  stimulated  in  different  ways  and  have  differ- 
ent excellences.  The  morality  is  an  attribute  of  the  core  or 
nucleus  of  character,  separable  only  by  an  abstraction,  not 
as  a  concrete  entity :  it  defines  the  qualities  necessary  in 
every  relation  ;  it  imposes  certain  limits  upon  every  instinct, 


330  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

and  is  itself  strengthened  or  weakened  by  the  reaction  of 
every  part  of  our  natures.  There  is  no  reason  therefore  to 
suppose  that  it  has  any  faculty  peculiar  to  itself.  A  given 
instinctj  such  as  the  sense  of  shame^  may  be  so  developed 
that  the  whole  character  conforms  to  the  moral  type;  but  it 
may  be  called  into  play  in  many  cases  where  morality  is  not 
immediately  concerned^  and  every  other  instinct  must  also 
have  a  part  along  with  it  in  enforcing  the  moral  law.  The 
qualities  implied  by  morality  do  not  correspond  to  any 
separate  instinct  any  more  than  moral  actions  constitute  a 
separate  class  amongst  other  qualities.  They  only  define  cer- 
tain modes  of  reaction  of  the  whole  organism  in  particular 
relations. 

20.  It  follows  that  the  dictates  of  an  instinct  such  as 
shame  are  not  arbitrary  in  the  sense  sometimes  assumed. 
If,  in  fact,  some  conduct  were  condemned  simply  as  offensive 
to  a  separate  instinct  which  might  or  might  not  be  present, 
there  would  be  a  difficulty  in  obtaining  a  fixed  rule.  This 
disgusts  me  and  that  disgusts  you;  who  is  to  say  which  is  in 
the  right?  To  this  it  may  be  answered  that  he  is  right  who 
is  disgusted  by  really  mischievous  things.  The  answer  is 
satisfactory  as  far  as  it  goes,  but  it  leaves  a  difficulty  un- 
solved. If  the  instinct  which  forbids  certain  conduct,  say  a 
sense  of  decency,  were  something  separate  and  unsociable, 
we  must  ask  whether  it  has  a  rio;ht  to  be  considered  in  the 
matter.  Indecent  conduct  is  no  doubt  mischievous  so  far 
as  it  gives  pain,  but  we  can  get  rid  of  the  sense  of  decency, 
and  then  the  conduct  will  not  give  that  kind  of  pain.  The 
objection,  then,  to  the  indecent  action  is  extrinsic;  it  is  not 
bad  simply  because  indecent,  but  because  it  has  some  other 
ill  effect;  and  if  the  sense  of  decency  could  be  abolished 
without  any  other  alteration  in  character,  we  might  propose 
to  get  rid  of  it  as,  on  the  whole,  a  troublesome  and  illusory 
quality.  We  should  then  object  only  to  those  indecent 
actions  which  appeared  to  be  mischievous  upon  other  grounds, 
and  judge  directly  by  their  utility  as  so  measured,  without 
considering  their  superfluous  or  supplementary  inconvenience. 


THE  SENSE  OF  SHAME.  331 

When,  however,  we  consider  the  whole  problem,  this  is 
obviously  inadequate.  Undoubtedly  the  evil  of  indecent 
actions  is  not  confined  to  the  simple  pain  inflicted  upon  that 
particular  sensibility.  The  sense  of  decency  is  closely  con- 
nected with  the  virtue  of  purity,  and  it  is  desirable  to  main- 
tain it  as  a  kind  of  outpost  which  defends  a  virtue  most 
essential  to  society.  But  this,  as  we  have  seen,  does  not 
exhaust  the  utility  of  the  instinct,  when  we  consider  it  not  as 
a  separate  mode  of  feeling,  but  as  a  sensibility  implied  in  the 
whole  development  of  character.  A  man,  that  is,  who  is  not 
endowed  with  a  capacity  for  such  feeling,  must  be  made 
throutrhout  of  coarser  fibre.  A  society  in  which  some  code 
of  decency  is  not  developed  must  be  entirely  wanting  in  a 
refinement  and  delicacy  which  is  an  essential  symptom,  and 
reciprocally  an  essential  condition,  of  any  but  the  lowest  stages 
of  barbarism.  The  penal  code  may  vary  widely;  some  code 
is  necessary  if  men  are  to  be  more  than  a  herd  of  brutes. 
We  must,  in  short,  as  I  have  previously  said,  consider  the 
whole  oriranisation  of  man  in  society.  We  cannot  measure 
the  value  of  a  sense  of  decency  by  simply  considering  a 
particular  set  of  bad  consequences  resulting  from  indecent 
actions  other  than  the  shock  to  decency,  but  the  whole 
difference  between  a  state  of  society  which  possesses  and  one 
which  does  not  possess  such  a  code.  That  difference  would 
probably  turn  out  to  be  the  difference  between  a  thoroughly 
brutalised  and  a  really  refined  and  intelligent  social  state,  in 
which  the  moral  qualities  were  in  harmony  with  the  general 
advance  in  the  scale  of  civilisation.  To  ask  what  is  the  use 
of  a  sense  of  decency  is  to  ask  how  far  any  tolerable  social 
order  could  be  constructed  without  stimulating  the  various 
emotive  sensibilities  which  are  concerned  in  generating  that 
sense  and  forming  a  corresponding  code,  and  no  mode  of 
inquiry  can  be  satisfactory  which  omits  a  full  consideration 
of  all  the  implied  conditions. 


332  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 


III.  Esthetic  Judgments. 

2T.  The  value,  therefore,  of  any  particular  instinct  depends 
upon  its  place  in  the  whole  character,  and  is  thus  not  arbi- 
trary in  the  sense  in  which  it  would  be  arbitrary  if  we  could 
speak  intelligibly  of  men  as  made  up  of  different  faculties, 
any  one  of   which   could   be  removed   without   implying  a 
chano-e  of  the   whole  organisation.     The   question   remains 
how  it  comes  to  pass  that  the  conscientious  feeling,  which  is 
thus  a  function  of  the  whole  character  and  not  a  specific 
faculty,  comes  to  have  so  distinctive  a  quality  as  is  at  least 
frequently  attributed  to  it?    This  difficulty,  as  I  may  observe 
in  the  first  place,  is  not  peculiar  to  ethical  judgments.    When 
we  say,  "  This  is  beautiful  or  ugly,"  we  refer  to  a  set  of  feel- 
ings which,  in  the  judgment  of  common  sense,  are  quite  as 
distinctive  in  respect  of  quality  as  those   to  which  we  refer 
when  we  say,  "This  is  right  or  wrong,"  if  by  those  words 
we  mean  agreeable  or  offensive  to  the  moral  feeling.     In  the 
latter  case,  it  is  true,  there  is  also  a  reference  to  a  fixed  rule, 
which  is  supposed  to  be  the  same  for  every  one,  whilst  the 
aesthetic  judgment  has  little  or  no  reference  to  any  such  rule. 
This,  however,   only  means  that   the   laws   of  the   aesthetic 
feelings  are  much  more  dependent  upon  the  idiosyncrasies  of 
the  individual  than  the  laws  of  the  ethical  feelings.     I  will 
consider  directly  what  is  implied  in  this.     It  is  not  incon- 
sistent with  the  statement,  which  seems  in  any  case  to  be 
true,  that  we  know  as  well  what  is  meant  by  the  sense  of  the 
beautiful  as  by  the  sense  of  the  morally  right,  just  as  we  know 
what  is  meant  by  the  sensual  appetite  for  food,  although  one 
man  likes  one  food  and  one  another.     The  class  to  which  the 
feelings  belong  is  as  distinctly  marked  off  from  other  classes, 
thou2:h  it  is  more  variable  in  its  dictates. 

23.  Now  the  aesthetic  feelings,  whatever  else  they  may 
be,  are  not  a  set  of  separate  emotions,  distinct  from  others 
as  one  physical  appetite  is  distinct  from  another.  On  the 
contrary,  it  is  the  prerogative  of  art  to  call  into  play  every 


ESTHETIC  JUDGMENTS.  333 

possible  variety  of  emotion.     We  say  that  a  woman,  a  sun- 
set, a  picture,  a  tunc,  or  a  simple  colour  or  form,  is  beautiful. 
We  mean  that  some  of  our  passions  are  agreeably  stimulated, 
not  that  a  set  of  passions  distinct  from  those  which  affect  us 
in  other  relations  is  stimulated.     In  one  case,  it  is  the  direct 
pleasure  of  the  senses;  in  others,  moods  which  call  into  play 
an  indefinite  variety  of  intellectual  processes;  as  in  reading 
a  fine  poem,   our  pleasure  may  be  derived  from  the  tender 
melancholy  of  old  associations  or  from  thoughts  of  the  sorrows 
and  joys  of  the  whole  human  race.    To  decide  what  consti- 
tutes the  aesthetic  mood  would  be  to  enter  upon  a  very  thorny 
problem,  for  which  I  am  not  competent,  and  which  does  not 
appear  to  be  relevant  to  the  present  question.     One  point, 
however,  is  sufBcient  for  my  purpose.    We  may  assume,  that 
is,  the  truth  of  the  general  statement  that  the  end  of  all  truly 
ffisthetic  indulgence  is  the  immediate  pleasure ;  and  this  state- 
ment would  be  sufficient  if  it  could  be  made  quite  accurate 
for  my  present  purpose. 

23.  I  find,  indeed,  a  certain  difficulty  in  stating  this 
criterion  to  my  satisfaction,  and  the  difficulty  arises,  I  think, 
from  the  fact  that  the  distinction  is  not  so  absolute  as  is 
frequently  assumed.  All  conduct  whatever  is  determined 
in  the  sense  already  explained  by  the  pleasantness  or  painful- 
ness  of  the  corresponding  feeling;  and  conduct  in  this  sense 
must  include  both  aesthetic  and  other  modes  of  activity.  The 
proposition,  for  example,  must  be  equally  true  whether  I  am 
composing  or  listening  to  music,  or  painting  pictures,  or  fight- 
ing, or  labouring  in  the  fields.  It  must  be  equally  true,  again, 
that  the  immediate  pleasure  is  the  sole  determining  condition, 
whether  I  am  drinking  a  glass  of  wine  or  listening  to  a  song; 
and  we  should  be  stretching  the  definition  of  aesthetic  enjoy- 
ment too  widelv  if  we  used  it  to  include  the  former  kind  of 
pleasure.  The  distinction  seems  to  correspond  to  the  distinc- 
tion between  play  and  work.  Certain  activities  are  con- 
sciously intended  to  procure  some  future  pleasure  and  to 
modify  the  conditions  of  my  existence ;  in  others,  I  have  no 
thouo-hts  of  anything  beyond  the  present,  and  I  find  pleasure 


334  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

in  the  simple  utterance  of  my  emotions  and  their  direct 
stimulation  without  reference  to  future  consequences.  If  I 
hunt  to  get  food,  I  am  at  work ;  if  I  hunt  without  caring  for 
any  ulterior  results,  I  am  at  play.  When  I  read  a  storv  or 
see  a  play,  the  same  emotions  are  stimulated  which  would  be 
affected  if  I  were  reading  history  or  witnessing  a  scene  in 
real  life :  the  sense  of  the  unreality  of  the  objects  presented 
to  my  eyes  or  my  imagination  converts  my  feelings  into  the 
aesthetic  state  as  it  deprives  them  of  the  normal  influence 
upon  conduct.  In  Dryden's  Ode,  Alexander  passes  through 
all  the  emotions  in  turn  of  pride,  ambition,  love,  pitv,  and 
anger,  till  one  happens  to  coincide  with  an  opportunity  for 
action,  and  the  emotional  force  which  had  previously  expended 
itself  in  vague  excitement  suddenly  discharges  along  a  fixed 
channel  and  propels  him  to  energetic  action.  In  one  case,  it 
seems,  we  are,  so  to  speak,  merely  discharo^ino-  feelino-  or  blow- 
ing  off  steam ;  in  the  other,  applying  it  to  the  purpose  of 
doing  mechanical  work. 

24.  The  difference,  then,  between  aesthetic  and  other 
pleasures  depends  upon  the  form  of  the  gratification,  not 
upon  the  instincts  gratified.  The  poet  or  the  artist  appeals 
to  my  love,  hate,  or  sympathy  as  much  as  the  preacher  or 
the  philosopher,  though  he  does  not  direct  them  to  any 
specific  practical  end ;  and  hence  we  have  the  variability  of 
the  aesthetic  canons  of  taste  which  seems  to  distincruish  them 
from  the  rule  of  conscience.  Whatever  gives  pleasure  may 
give  aesthetic  pleasure,  and  there  seems  to  be  in  some  direc- 
tions hardly  any  limits  to  the  divergence  of  individual  tastes. 
If  I  like  this  colour  or  taste  and  you  like  that,  we  are  equally 
pleased,  and  there  is  no  criterion  for  deciding  our  difference. 
So  treacherous  and  fluctuatino-  a  mode  of  feelino-  should  there- 
fore,  it  is  said,  be  excluded  from  moral  judgments  if  morality 
is  not  to  be  regarded  as  a  mere  fashion.  The  answer,  so  far 
as  the  moralist  is  concerned,  is  not  difficult.  However  vari- 
able the  taste  may  be,  it  is  not — for  nothing  is — absolutely 
variable.  Even  in  the  simple  case  of  a  direct  pleasure  of  the 
senses — a  love  of  bright  colours,  for  example — the  scientific 


ESTHETIC  JUDGMENTS.  335 

observer  may  show  that  certaui  sensibiHties  are  essentially 
connected  with  certain  organic  conditions,  and  thus  that 
some  imply  healthy  and  others  morbid  conditions.  The 
sense  of  the  beautiful,  again,  implies  the  presence  of  an 
intellectual  element,  and  the  development  of  the  intellect 
thus  imposes  certain  conditions  on  the  development  of  the 
taste.  So,  for  example,  the  pleasure  which  we  derive  from 
the  sight  of  a  fine  figure  or  a  perfect  statue  implies  a  power 
of  judging  of  certain  relations  of  form,  a  capacity  for  recog- 
nising that  a  given  conformation  corresponds  to  the  best 
possible  combination  of  strength  and  activity.  It  is,  indeed, 
another  question  to  ask  why  such  a  combination  should  give 
us  pleasure;  and  we  need  not  attempt  to  decide  whether  the 
recognition  is  explicit  or  implicit,  whether  we  feel  or  reason, 
or  judge  by  an  instinct,  or  in  any  degree  by  a  recognised 
formula.  In  any  case  the  taste  must  conform  to  the  facts, 
and  will  be  more  or  less  the  same  whenever  the  conditions  of 
strength  and  activity  are  the  same,  and  a  perception  that  they 
are  fulfilled  gives  pleasure;  and  this  is  equally  true  where 
the  perception  which  gives  pleasure  involves  some  condition 
of  the  intellectual  emotions. 

25.  This,  I  think,  explains  the  sense  in  which  we  must 
admit  that  the  conscience  includes  an  aesthetic  element,  and 
in  which  we  may  properly  speak  of  a  moral  sense.  Any 
pleasurable  emotion  whatever  may  be  involved  in  what  is 
called  aesthetic  pleasure.  We  derive  pleasure,  therefore,  from 
a  vast  variety  of  perceptions  which  have  no  assignable  rela- 
tion to  moral  feeling.  Anything  which  stimulates  the  emo- 
tions agreeably  may  give  rise  to  an  aesthetic  pleasure,  the 
only  conditions  being  that  the  mode  of  feeling  must  be 
agreeable,  and  must  not  be  expended  on  what  we  call  prac- 
tical effort.  One  kind  of  aesthetic  pleasure,  therefore,  is  that 
which  we  derive  from  the  contemplation  of  certain  characters 
or  the  play  of  certain  emotions  in  our  fellows.  Moral 
approval  includes  the  pleasure  derived  from  the  contemplation 
of  virtuous  character,  and  may  therefore  give  rise  to  an 
aesthetic    pleasure.      If   we    admire    heroism,    unselfishness. 


33^    '  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

simplicity,  and  other  moral  qualities  iu  real  life,  the  artist 
may  appeal  to  that  emotion  as  well  as  to  any  other:  he  may 
set  before  us  imaginary  ideals,  from  the  contemplation  of 
which  we  may  derive  a  very  keen  as  well  as  very  elevating 
pleasure,  or  he  may  provide  us  with  a  means  of  uttering  the 
emotions  which  are  habitually  stimulated  by  such  contem- 
plation^ or  by  the  directly  moral  emotions  themselves.  So 
far  as  there  is  any  emotional  element  in  our  approval  of 
moral  conduct,  it  may  take  the  aesthetic  form.  According 
to  me,  it  would  be  impossible  that  morality  itself  should  be 
maintained  if  it  did  not  excite  these  pleasurable  emotions. 
The  conception  of  merit  implies,  as  I  have  argued,  the  social 
pressure  which  consists  in  a  general  approval  and  admiration 
of  certain  qualities  and  a  disapproval  and  contempt  of  their 
opposites.  The  emotion  may  pass  from  one  phase  to  the 
other  according  to  circumstances.  It  is  in  the  aesthetic  phase 
when  we  simply  enjoy  the  contemplation  of  some  beautiful 
moral  tvpe  set  before  us  in  history  or  fiction,  and  passes^into 
the  practical  phase  as  soon  as  it  begins  to  have  a  definite 
relation  to  the  conduct  of  our  lives.  If^  for  example,  I  admire 
the  simplicity  and  tenderness  of  the  "  Vicar  of  Wakefield  " 
whilst  I  am  reading  Goldsmith's  masterpiece,  I  am  simply  in 
the  aesthetic  frame  of  mind.  If  an  analogous  case  presents 
itself  at  the  moment,  the  emotion  kindled  by  the  artist  may 
prompt  me  to  charitable  and  so  far  moral  action.  The  strains 
of  military  music  may  produce  aii  ardent  excitement  which 
expends  itself  in  mere  feeling,  or  may  stimulate  a  regiment  to 
mount  a  dangerous  breach. 

26.  But  admitting  the  existence  of  the  feeling,  how  far 
does  it  bring  any  guarantee  of  conformity  to  the  moral  law  ? 
How  far  are  the  dictates  of  the  moral  sense  infallible  or 
authoritative?  The  bare  fact  that  the  contemplation  of 
certain  emotions  or  types  of  character  is  pleasurable  does  not 
prove  that  they  are  morally  good  or  bad,  for,  in  the  first 
place,  no  moral  cjuestion  mav  be  raised.  I  may  simply  be 
sympathising  with  emotions  common  to  the  good  and  the 
bad ;  but  if  a  moral  sentiment  be  involved,  the  bare  fact  that 


mSTIIETIC  JUDGMENTS.  337 

you  and  I  approve  is  clearly  not  conclusive  as  to  its  Tightness. 
Nor  does  it  always  follow  that  a  conviction  of  the  moral 
excellence  of  certain  character  or  conduct  will  suffice  to  make 
the  contemplation  agreeable.  This,  indeed,  is  obvious  from 
a  consideration  of  the  way  in  which  we  suppose  the  moral 
law  to  arise.  When  I  say  that  I  know  an  action  to  be  right, 
I  mav  mean  simplv  that  it  is  in  conformity  with  a  law  which, 
for  whatever  reason,  I  respect.  So  long  as  the  moral  law  is 
stated  in  the  external  form,  and  is  obeved  from  some  extrinsic 
motive,  such  as  respect  for  the  authority  of  the  supposed 
legislator,  I  may  approve  obedience  without  feeling  any 
vivid  and  spontaneous  pleasure.  I  admit  this  or  that  to  be 
right — that  is,  commanded — and  on  the  whole,  therefore,  I 
wish  to  see  it  done;  but  I  do  not  feel  that  spontaneous  and 
instinctive  sympathy  which  is  necessary  to  generate  aesthetic 
pleasure.  It  is  only  in  so  far  as  the  moral  law  has  become 
the  law  of  my  character,  and  expresses  the  way  in  which  my 
emotions  act  previously  to  reflection  upon  any  abstract  prin- 
ciple, that  I  can  be  said  to  have  a  moral  sense.  Undoubtedly 
this  moral  instinct  may  be  exceedingly  powerful  and  sensitive 
in  some  characters,  and  give  indications  more  delicate  than 
anv  process  of  deliberate  calculation.  A  man  of  fine  moral 
sensibility  mav  perceive  emotional  discords  as  a  man  of  fine 
musical  ear  mav  be  sensitive  to  differences  of  sound  too  slight 
to  be  measured  by  scientific  observers.  So  we  may  in  certain 
cases  accept  the  judgment  of  a  man  who  is  remarkable  for  a 
keen  sense  of  honour.  The  fact  that  certain  conduct  does 
not  shock  him  is  evidence  that  it  cannot  be  dishonourable  : 
we  hold  that  his  instinctive  perceptions  supply  a  more  delicate 
test  than  can  be  embodied  in  any  cut-and-dried  formula. 

37.  We  may  admit,  then,  that  the  thorough  assimilation 
of  the  moral  law  implies  the  growth  of  a  sensibility  which 
may  be  called  aesthetic — a  capacity  for  receiving  delight  from 
the  bare  contemplation  of  high  moral  qualities,  abstractedly 
from  any  special  advantages  expected  from  them,  or  from 
any  extrinsic  consequences.  We  may  agree  that  to  some 
extent  this  sensibility  must  be  developed  in  every  truly  virtu- 


338  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

ous  person^  that  is,  in  any  person  in  whom  the  instincts 
which  dictate  obedience  to  the  moral  law  have  become  de- 
finitely organised;  and,  further,  that  this  aesthetic  pleasure 
implies  a  corresponding  sentiment  as  governing  practice,  and 
that  in  the  more  finely  constituted  natures  it  implies  a  deli- 
cacy of  discrimination  beyond  that  which  can  be  formulated 
in  any  of  the  accepted  moral  commonplaces.  Unless,  in- 
deed, the  moral  sense  is  cultivated  up  to  this  pitch,  so  that 
we  take  a  spontaneous  delight  in  the  spectacle  of  heroic  or 
philanthropic  energy,  we  can  hardly  say  that  a  society  has 
become  tolerably  moralised.  But  we  still  have  to  admit 
that  there  is  an  apparently  arbitrary  or  indeterminate  ele- 
ment in  such  feeling.  It  varies  from  one  man  to  another, 
and  it  is  difficult  to  suggest  any  test  for  distinguishing'be- 
tween  the  healthy  and  the  morbid  sensibility ;  between  that 
exquisite  perception  which  outruns  the  more  tangible  tests 
and  the  perverted  perception  which  is  biassed  by  some  in- 
dividual peculiarity.  A  man  of  a  high  sense  of  honour,  for 
example,  may  be  Quixotic ;  he  may  attach  undue  value  to 
certain  considerations,  and  sanction  a  retro2;rade  instead  of 
an  advanced  moral  code. 

28.  What  then  is  the  fixed  element?  The  instinctive 
feeling  always  includes,  we  may  say,  an  intellectual  judg- 
ment. But  what  is  this  implicit  judgment?  It  is  prima 
facie  a  judgment  that  this  or  that  conduct  gives  pleasure. 
But  as  different  things  may  please  different  people,  two  diver- 
gent judgments  may  be  equally  right.  It  is  still,  after  all,  a 
question  of  taste,  and  therefore  comes  within  the  proverbial 
exclusion  from  a  possibility  of  logical  decision.  It  is  clear, 
however,  that  even  a  question  of  taste  may  often  admit  of 
being  brought  to  an  issue  of  facts.  So,  in  the  analogy 
already  suggested,  two  sculptors  may  prefer  two  different 
ideals,  yet  both  of  them  may  agree  in  preferring  that  form 
which  represents,  say,  the  most  perfect  combination  of 
strength  and  agility.  There  is  therefore  a  clear  objective 
test.  One  of  the  two  forms  represented  will  in  fact  perform 
a  given  feat  with  the  least  effort,  or  with  a  given  effort  pro- 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  339 

dace  the  greatest  results.  The  process  of  educating  the 
taste  is  virtually  a  process  of  learning  to  solve  such  problems 
instinctively,  and  we  may  say  that  the  taste  is  best  which 
solves  them  most  accurately.  The  question  is  therefore  a 
question  of  fact,  though  it  may  be  one  of  such  complexity 
that  it  is  impossible  to  obtain  more  than  an  approximate 
solution. 

29.  Now,  if  we  apply  this  analogy,  we  have  to  say  what 
is  the  problem  presented  to  the  moralist.  Every  moral 
judgment,  as  I  have  argued,  is  an  implicit  (if  not  an  explicit) 
approval  of  a  certain  type  of  character.  It  includes,  there- 
fore, an  assertion  that  the  highest  type  includes  certain 
qualities  of  character,  which,  of  course,  imply  corresponding 
modes  of  conduct.  The  highest  type,  again,  must,  according 
to  our  theory,  be  that  which  is  on  the  whole  best  fitted  for 
the  conditions  of  social  welfare.  The  problem  is  just  as 
precise  as  the  problem  which  physical  conformation  is  best 
adapted  to  satisfy  the  conditions  of  health,  strength,  and 
activity.  The  fact,  so  far  as  it  is  a  fact,  that  we  cannot 
obtain  an  accurate  solution  does  not  prove  that  there  is  no 
such  solution  to  be  found,  but  only  that  the  solution  requires 
longer  observation  and  a  more  elaborate  set  of  experiments 
before  we  can  hit  upon  it.  The  experiment,  in  fact,  is  that 
which  is  being  always  carried  on  by  the  collective  experience 
of  the  race;  and  though  we  have  established  beyond  a 
possibility  of  doubt  certain  general  principles  which  are  the 
basis  of  the  accepted  moral  code,  there  is  still  a  considerable 
margin  of  uncertainty  in  details.  Upon  this  assumption, 
the  problem  for  the  moralist  is  analogous  to  the  problem  for 
the  artist ;  each  is  virtually  trying  to  discover  a  certain  type 
which  has  definite  conditions  to  satisfy — briefly  spcakino-, 
that  of  bodily  vigour  in  one  case  and  of  social  vitality  in  the 
other. 

IV,  The  Consciejice. 

30.  But  it  must  also  be  admitted  that,  although  I  have 
argued  that  this  gives  a  correct  definition  of  morality,  or  a 


340  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

description  of  the  function  actually  discharged  by  the  moral 
sentiments,  I  have  not  maintained^  nor  does  it  seem  to  be 
in  fact  maintainable,  that  it  is  a  description  of  the  explicit 
aim  of  moral  conduct.     I  have  considered  what  is.the  ground 
or  cause  of  morality,  what  is  the  explanation  of  its  existence 
to  an  independent  observer ;  but  I  have  not  considered  what 
is  the  reason  which  is  consciously  admitted  by  moral  agents. 
The  society  is  moral  up  to  a  certain  standard  "  because  "  the 
society  could  not  reach  a  certain  stage  of  development  without 
being  so  far  moral.     But  this  does  not  imply  that  the  end  of 
every  man,  so  far  as  moral,  is  the  elevation  of  society  or 
the  preservation  of  its  vigour.     On  the  contrary,  it  may  be 
true  that  though  the  moral  man  contributes  to  that  end,  he 
may  never  think  about  it.     So  far  as  the  units  are  moral,  the 
social  organism  which  they  constitute  is  healthy  ;  but  a  man's 
reason  for  being  moral  need  not  include  any  reference  to  that 
fact,  nor  need  the  reasons  always  be  identical.     A  man  may 
act  from  a  given  instinct  without  asking  how  he  comes  to 
have  that  instinct,  nor  whether  it  is  original  or  derivative, 
permanent  or  destructible,  useful  in  any  sense  to  himself  or  to 
others.     Indeed,  the  plausibility  of  rival  systems  of  ethics  is 
partly  due  to  the  fact  that  men  may  be  moral,  that  is,  may 
obey  certain  external  rules  of  conduct,  from  different  motives  ; 
with  some   the  motive   may  be  fear  of  hell,  an  association 
with  certain  accidental  circumstances,  or  some  instinct  which 
has  been  generated  thev  know  not  how;  or,  again,  the  im- 
mediate  motive   may  be  a  desire  of  consistency,   or  direct 
sympathy  with  their  surrounding  neighbours;  and  although 
it  is  true  that,  in  each  of  these  cases,  there  .corresponds  a 
certain  type  of  character,  and  the  difference  might  be  revealed 
by  the  occurrence  of  special  conditions,  still,  under  the  average 
circumstances  of  life,  the  resulting  rule  of  conduct  may  be 
approximately  the  same.     How  far  one  motive  or  system  of 
motives  is  more  strictly  entitled  to  be  called  conscientious  than 
another  is  a  question   to  be  considered  directly;    and    thus 
we  have  to  ask  how  the  different  modes  of  reorardinir  morality 
can  all  lead  to  the  same  result,  or  how  men  should  obtain  the 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  341 

answer  to  one  problem  when  they  are  apparently  aiming  at 
another  ? 

31.  The  answer,  as  I  take  it,  follows  from  the  facts  alreadv 
stated.     Tq  any  particular  association  of  human  beings  there 
must    correspond  a  certain    corporate    sentiment.     A    state 
implies  the  existence  of  feelings  of  loyalty  or  patriotism;  a 
church,  a  certain  religious  sentiment  which  carries  with  it 
attachment  to  the  ecclesiastical  order;  an  armv  implies  dis- 
cipline ;  a  college,  a  school,  and  a  club  imply  certain  sentiments 
of  mutual  goodwill  and  readiness  to  accejit  the  conditions  of 
common  action  for  the  purposes  of  the  particular  association. 
Whatever  ma.y  be  the  cause  of  the  existing  sentiments,  what- 
ever may  be  the  end  of  the  association  or  the  function  of  the 
social  organ,  the  corporate  sentiment  which  holds  it  together 
must  always  imply  conformity  to  certain  rules  necessary  to 
the  welfare  of  the  body ;  and  as  the  sentiment  is  vigorous  or 
feeble,  the  body  will  so  far  tend  to  flourish  or  decay.     More- 
over, the  sentiment  which  springs  up  and  binds  men  together 
implies  something  which  it  is  often  very  hard  to  distinguish 
from  a  moral  sentiment.     The  spirit  of  loyalty  to  some  special 
association  sometimes  conflicts  with  the  ordinary  moral  law, 
and    is  often  strong;    enoutrh   to    overcome  it.      A  thief  is 
bound  to  his  gang  by  a  sentiment  which  we  call  immoral, 
because  it  implies  conduct  condemned  by  the  prevailing  moral 
code  ;  but  so  far  as  it  implies  a  genuine  identification  of  him- 
self with  the  gang,  and  a  sacrifice  of  his  private  interests  to 
those  of  the  community,  it  is  rather  a  kind  of  spurious  or 
class  morality,  implying  obedience  to  a  rival  moral  code.    So 
the  member  of  a  particular  class  acquires  a  sense  of  oblifration 
to  the  class  even  where  its  interests  conflict  with  those  of  the 
organism  at  large.     The  proverbial  noblesse  oblige  may  imply 
a  more  refined  sense  of  honour,  but  it  also  frequently  implies 
a  regard  for  the  privileges  of  the  class  abstractedly  from  the 
question  of  their  utility  to  the  whole  communitv.    When  we 
take  the  wider  associations,  the  state,  for  example,  it  becomes 
diflicult  to  distinguish  between  the  sphere  of  conscience  and 
that  of  the  more  specific  sentiment.     Patriotism,  we  sav,  is 


342  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

a  dutv;  and  of  course  It  is  a  duty  in  every  man  to  promote 
the  welfare  of  the  nation  to  which  he  belongs.  But  there 
are  cases — unfortunately  of  not  infrequent  occurrence — in 
which  the  duty  of  patriotism  seems  to  diverge  from  the  duty 
in  a  wider  sense.  Even  intelligent  people  are  not  ashamed 
to  limit  their  obligations  by  the  supposed  interests  of  their 
country — to  declare  that  it  is  a  man's  "  duty"  to  be  for  his 
country  "right  or  wrong" — to  promote  the  happiness  of 
Englishmen  even  at  the  expense  of  the  general  welfare  of  the 
world,  or  even  to  extend  the  British  empire  at  the  expense  of 
the  happiness  of  all  its  constituent  members.  The  sense  of 
duty  or  obligation  to  any  class  to  which  we  may  happen  to 
belong  seems  to  have  very  much  the  same  quality,  so  to 
speak,  as  the  moral  sense,  though  we  only  use  the  word  "  duty  " 
when  we  are  not  considering  the  class,  or  when  it  is  so  large 
that  our  intellectual  horizon  does  not  practically  extend 
beyond  it. 

32.  Now,  upon  my  showing,  the  sense  of  duty  or  the  purely 
moral  oblio-ation  has  the  same  relation  to  the  "  social  tissue  " 
as  the  various  special  sentiments  corresponding  to  each  organ 
or  association  have  to  the  body  to  which  they  correspond. 
I  am  patriotic  so  far  as  Englishman,  and  moral  so  far  as 
human  being,  or  rather  as  a  constituent  member  of  a  certain 
social  order.  The  difficulty,  then,  with  which  we  are  now  con- 
cerned is  simply  that  in  the  one  case  there  is,  and  in  the  other 
there  is  not,  a  certain  definite  and  rounded  body  which  may 
serve  as  the  concrete  object  of  my  devotion.  It  would  be 
hopeless  to  attempt  an  analysis  of  all  the  sentiments  which 
go  to  form  patriotism,  and  it  is  enough  to  say  that  at  times 
they  include  the  most  unselfish  emotions  and  the  widest 
intellectual  culture,  as  in  the  case  of  our  best  statesmen, 
whilst  sometimes  the  sentiment  may  exhibit  itself  in  the 
grotesque  form  of  the  aversion  of  a  clown  for  a  race  of  which 
he  only  knows  that  it  uses  strange  words,  and  includes  such 
a  sentiment  in  its  composition  many  unamiable  and  selfish 
feelings.  And  yet  there  is  so  much  similarity  that  the  clown 
and  the  statesman  may  be  equally  ready  to  die  for  the  flag,  or 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  343 

uphold  what  is  generally  supposed  to  be  the  honour  of  their 
nation.  Now  if  the  nation  were  something  formless  and 
indefinite,  something  which  had  no  definite  internal  symbols 
and  could  issue  no  definite  orders,  how  could  any  devotion 
be  either  generated  or  displayed  ?  And  this  seems  to  be  the 
case  with  that  extremely  indefinite  entity  the  "  social  tissue," 
which  can  neither  give  rules  nor  be  regarded  as  an  object  of 
devotion. 

^^.  The  answer  seems  to  bs  twofold.  In  the  first  place, 
every  possible  form  of  association  implies  some  moral  training. 
So  far  as  a  man  is  a  member  of  any  larger  organisation,  the 
qualities  which  fit  him  for  social  action  are  stimulated  and 
disciplined.  As  a  citizen,  as  a  member  of  a  church,  and  in 
everv  other  capacity  in  life,  he  learns  subordination,  self- 
restraint,  consideration  for  others,  and  so  forth.  The  quality 
of  every  particular  organ  depends  upon  the  qualities  of  the 
tissue  from  which  it  is  constituted,  and  have  invariably  an 
influence  upon  it.  The  character  of  each  unit  is  affected 
in  some  degree  by  his  position  as  a  member  of  the  larger 
body,  and  the  modification  thus  impressed  affects  him  in  all 
other  capacities.  If  I  learn  obedience  as  a  soldier  or  self- 
restraint  as  a  member  of  a  club,  I  shall  be  so  far  adapted 
to  display  the  same  characteristics  in  any  other  relation  in 
which  I  may  be  placed.  And  further,  as  a  general  rule,  the 
conditions  of  vitality  of  the  society  at  large  must  be  also 
conditions  for  the  vigour  of  any  particular  association  formed 
from  it.  Anvthino:  which  contributes  to  a  man's  health  in 
general  is  also  useful  in  any  particular  employment.  There 
is  not  one  set  of  sanitary  rules  for  a  peasant  and  another  for 
an  artisan,  though  each  occupation  has  its  special  conditions, 
which  may  be  regarded  as  modifications  of  the  more  general. 
This  is  equally  true  of  the  conditions  of  social  health.  So 
far  as  a  man  is  morally  better,  he  is  better  fitted  for  the 
particular  duties  imposed  upon  him  by  his  special  position 
in  the  general  organisation.  In  fact,  if  an  association  were 
so  constituted  as  to  require  a  set  of  rules  different  from  the 
general  rules,  or,  in  other  words,  if  immorality  were  a  condi- 


344  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tion  of  membership^  it  would  correspond  to  a  morbid  growth 
instead  of  a  normal  organ.  The  society  would  so  far  be  in 
a  condition  of  decay,  and  the  elimination  of  the  association 
in  question  would  be  necessary  for  its  vitality.  The  general 
condition,  in  short,  of  social  vigour  implies  an  approximate 
identity  of  interests  between  the  whole  and  every  constituent 
part.  It  is,  of  course,  true  indeed  that  the  special  interests 
of  a  particular  part  of  the  community  may  conflict  with 
those  of  the  whole,  and  it  is  the  chief  duty  of  a  statesman 
to  guard  against  such  deviations  on  pain  of  revolution  or 
social  decay.  The  devotion  of  the  soldier  may  tell  in  favour 
of  despotism,  and  patriotic  spirit  may  lead  to  the  most 
atrocious  conduct  towards  outsiders.  In  such  cases,  of 
course,  we  have  imperfect  or  one-sided  moral  systems,  but 
they  are  still  moral.  That  is  to  say,  qualities  are  stimulated 
which  are  so  far  moral  as  they  imply  an  identity  between 
the  individual  and  some  larger  organism,  although  the 
interests  of  that  organism  diverge  from  those  of  society  at 
large.  In  order  that  a  man  may  be  an  effective  member  of 
any  society,  he  must  have  certain  moral  qualifications,  and 
what  is  required  is  an  enlargement  of  his  perceptions  which 
shall  force  him  to  take  into  account  wider  considerations  of 
a  similar  kind ;  to  sympathise  with  men  even  though  they 
use  different  symbols  for  communication,  and  to  respect  other 
claims  upon  his  loyalty  than  those  which  are  associated  with 
military  leadership.  The  morality  impressed  upon  a  man  is 
not  always,  perhaps  it  is  never,  absolutely  right — that  is,  it  is 
never  an  absolutely  correct  impression  of  the  ideal  qualities; 
but  it  must  be  almost  always  an  approximate  expression, 
and  capable  generally  of  reconciliation  by  a  simple  widen- 
ing of  the  field  of  view. 

34.  In  the  next  place,  the  true  school  of  morality  is  the 
family,  which  represents  a  mode  of  association  altogether 
closer,  more  intimate  than  any  other,  and  in  which  there  is 
not  the  same  possibility  of  deviation  from  the  moral  code. 
The  moral  quality  of  every  man  is  determined  to  a  very  great 
extent  in   his  infancy.     We  learn   our  morality,  not  from 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  345 

books  and  lessons,  but  in  the  nursery,  or  at  our  mother's 
knee,  or  from  intercourse  with  our  brothers  and  sisters. 
There  it  is  that  the  core  of  character  is  fixed,  and  that  the 
deepest  organic  quaHties  are  permanently  stamped  upon  us. 
The  essential  part  of  our  education,  we  may  say,  is  that 
which  we  receive  in  the  stage  of  absolute  dependence  upon 
others.  The  adult,  it  is  true,  acquires  passions  of  which 
the  infant  was  incapable,  but  it  is  still  through  the  family  rela- 
tions that  they  are  principally  disciplined.  The  purity  of  the 
domestic  relations  is  the  essential  guarantee  for  a  most  im- 
portant class  of  virtues,  and  the  family  is  moulded  and  deter- 
mined by  the  discipline  to  which  thev  are  subject.  The 
sympathies,  again,  receive  their  chief  stimulus  through  the 
domestic  relations,  and  it  is  in  the  sphere  of  the  family  that 
we  normally  find  a  degree  of  altruism  which  is  scarcely  to  be 
expected  elsewhere.  The  love  of  a  mother  is  the  typical  and 
central  virtue  of  which  all  others  seem  to  be  faint  reflections. 
It  is,  as  I  have  said,  in  the  family  that  the  binding  forces 
which  hold  society  together  come  as  it  were  to  the  surface, 
and  are  directly  visible  without  admixture  of  any  ties  of  an 
inferior  order  of  intimacy ;  and  therefore  the  family  is  the 
main  organ  of  morality. 

^^.  This  familiar  fact  gives  the  historical  explanation  of 
the  moral  sense  in  so  far  as  it  shows  how  the  development  of 
the  conscience  naturally  takes  place.  It  shows  further,  I 
think,  what  is  to  be  regarded  as  the  true  form  of  moralitv. 
The  child  has  become  a  moral  agent  as  it  has  learned  self- 
restraint,  sympathy,  truthfulness  in  the  special  concrete  case. 
It  knows  nothing  whatever  of  society  at  large,  or  of  the 
formulas  sanctioned  by  moral  philosophers.  It  is  a  good 
child  because  it  loves  its  parents  and  has  imbibed  certain 
organic  instincts  around  which  all  later  developments  of 
feeling  group  themselves  spontaneously.  The  assumed  end 
of  moral  conduct  has  never  been  presented  to  it,  and  cannot 
supply  it  with  a  motive.  It  has  never  thought  of  the  greatest 
happiness  of  the  greatest  number,  nor  is  it  capable  of  a  priori 
deductions  or  categorical  imperatives.    If  the  morality  taught 


346  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

is  avowedly  based  upon  some  theological  dogma,  the  child 
can  only  conceive  of  the  Deity  as  an  invisible  father,  or  per- 
haps as  an  invisible  being  who  always  approves  the  paternal 
commands.  What  jxives  the  real  force  to  the  moral  teachino- 
which  it  may  receive  is  the  stimulus  given  to  its  affections 
by  its  actual  intercourse  with  the  little  microcosm  which 
bounds  its  intellectual  vision.  In  what  sense,  then,  is  the 
morality  of  the  child  determined  by  conditions  of  social 
welfare?  Obviously  not  by  any  conscious  appreciation  of 
those  conditions.  As  obviously  the  conditions  may  be  called 
operative  in  this  sense,  that  as  the  social  tissue  is  composed 
of  human  beings,  whose  most  intimate  bond  is  the  family 
relation,  the  conditions  of  social  welfare  are  necessarily  coin- 
cident with  the  general  conditions  of  family  welfare.  So  far 
as  men  are  better  husbands,  fathers,  and  sons,  and  women 
better  wives,  mothers,  and  daughters,  society  is  in  a  more 
wholesome  condition.  Every  variation  in  the  strength  and 
purity  of  the  family  relations  implies  a  corresponding  variation 
in  the  stability  of  the  society  at  large.  As  the  cohesion  of  a 
whole  tissue  depends  upon  the  cohesion  of  the  compound 
molecules  of  which  it  is  built  up,  so  the  society  depends  upon 
the  family ;  whatever  qualities  are  useful  in  one  relation  are 
useful  in  the  other.  The  good  child  becomes  the  good  man 
by  simply  widening  its  sphere  of  svmpathy,  exerting  the  same 
qualities  under  a  new  stimulus,  and  generalising  in  its  other 
relations  the  same  principles  which  it  has  applied  in  the 
nurserv. 

36.  This  statement,  indeed,  requires  to  be  guarded.  It  is 
obvious,  and  I  certainly  should  not  seek  to  evade  the  admission, 
that  the  family  affections,  like  those  which  are  generated  in 
any  wider  association,  may  lead  to  a  kind  of  compound  selfish- 
ness. As  a  man's  patriotism  may  make  him  a  bad  cosmo- 
politan, or  his  attachment  to  a  particular  church  may  make 
him  intolerant  of  other  religions,  so  his  love  to  his  family 
may  make  him  a  corrupt  judge  or  an  avaricious  tradesman. 
Fathers  of  families  are  capable,  it  is  said,  of  anything;  that  is, 
of  any  amount  of  injustice  to  others.     And,  again,  it  is  of 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  347 

course  a  commonplace  that  the  domestic  relations  incapacitate 
a  man  for  heroic  action  either  of  the  good  or  bad.  A  man's 
fondness  for  his  children  may  make  him  less  disposed  to  run 
risks  for  the  good  of  his  race.  It  follows  that  the  domestic 
virtues  are  not  a  sufficient  condition  of  virtue  in  general. 
This,  of  course,  is  undeniable,  but  it  does  not  conflict  with 
the  principle  as  properly  understood.  For,  in  the  first  place, 
though  domestic  virtue  does  not  of  necessity  imply  public 
virtue  in  a  corresponding  degree,  it  implies  some  moral 
qualities.  What  is  essentially  bad  in  other  social  relations  is 
bad,  if  not  permanently  bad,  in  the  family  relations.  To  be 
a  good  member  of  a  family,  a  man  must  practise  the  duties 
of  chastity,  temperance,  truthfulness,  and  of  kindliness  and 
justice  to  at  least  his  immediate  surroundings.  He  must  have 
taken  the  great  step  of  crossing  the  tremendous  gulf  which 
separates  each  man  from  the  rest  of  the  universe ;  and  that 
gulf  once  crossed,  all  further  advance  is  a  question  of  time  and 
cultivation  of  the  sympathies.  The  question  remains,  What 
will  be  the  law  of  the  sympathies?  The  purely  egoistic  form 
may  of  course  observe  the  external  law  of  domestic  virtue  as 
of  other  virtues ;  he  may  be  kind  to  his  wife  as  to  his  horse, 
with  an  exclusive  view  to  his  own  comfort;  but  in  that  case 
his  virtue  is  an  outside  sham  which  will  disappear  when 
accident  divides  the  interests  of  the  persons  related  to  liini. 
But  admitting  the  reality  of  altruism,  we  must  also  admit 
that  it  is  naturally  stimulated  in  the  family  case  at  the  earliest 
period  of  life,  and  that  family  affections  are  both  the  type  and 
the  root  of  all  truly  altruistic  feeling.  As  soon  as  we  are 
affected  by  the  sorrow  of  our  brothers,  we  can  be  really  moved 
by  the  sorrow  of  any  other  human  being  who  comes  into 
any  relation  to  us.  We  have  the  raw  material  of  the  moral 
sense,  which  will  afterwards  be  developed  and  regulated  by 
our  position  in  the  whole  social  organism.  The  development 
in  different  cases  of  course  varies  greatly.  Some  men  have 
very  strong  affections  for  those  whom  they  see,  and  very  weak 
sympathies  for  the  distant,  because,  perhaps,  the  imaginative 
faculty  is  weak ;  whilst  in  other  cases  the  relation  is  reversed. 


348  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

The  affection  In  the  particular  case  does  not  of  itself  deter- 
mine the  law  of  the  affection  in  other  cases^  and  that  will 
vary  according  to  individual  idiosyncrasies.  If  my  affection 
for  my  family  rests  upon  genuine  altruism,  then  so  far  as  I 
am  reasonable  I  shall  sympathise  with  others  in  so  far  as  I 
am  able  to  realise  their  feelings,  and  to  my  power  of  being 
useful  to  them,  that  is,  of  giving  a  practical  effect  to  mv  feel- 
ings. That  is,  as  I  love  my  brother  I  shall  love  others,  and 
discharge  whatever  duties  arise  from  other  relations.  If  I 
love  him  only  in  name,  and  am  kind  to  him  only  to  gain  some 
advantage  to  myself,  then,  of  course,  I  am  a  good  brother  and 
a  good  friend  only  in  name.  To  ask  how  far  the  domestic 
affection  will  prompt  to  others  is  to  ask  how  far  it  is  real. 

37.  Thus  we  may  say  that,  if  we  start  from  the  general 
point  of  view,  the  organisation  of  society  implies  a  certain 
distribution  of  functions  which  has  been  gradually  elaborated 
in  obedience  to  the  general  conditions  of  welfare.  As  a  cer- 
tain constitution  of  the  family  is  bound  up  in  the  very  struc- 
ture of  the  social  tissue,  all  other  relations  have  been  developed 
with  reference  to  these  primary  relations.  And  therefore, 
if  a  man  acted  with  an  explicit  reference  to  the  welfare  of 
the  whole  organisation,  he  would  necessarily  acquire  the 
characteristics  essential  to  the  good  son,  husband,  and  father, 
as  well  as  those  essential  to  the  good  citizen,  soldier,  or 
craftsman.  The  whole  problem  has  been  worked  out  by  a 
single  process,  and  therefore  every  part  of  the  organism  has 
been  developed  with  reference  to  the  rest.  But  if  we  start 
from  the  opposite  or  individual  point  of  view,  which  neces- 
sarily corresponds  to  the  historical  development  in  each  par- 
ticular case,  the  character  is  developed  through  the  immediate 
surroundings;  the  man  learns  to  be  affectionate,  truthful, 
and  so  forth  through  his  relation  to  his  own  little  world, 
without  being  even  able  for  a  long  time  to  apprehend  the 
general  principle,  and  so  acquires  the  qualities  which  fit  him 
for  other  relations  as  he  comes  to  be  sensible  of  them  and 
required  to  act  on  them.  Whether  we  start  from  the  whole 
and  argue  to  the  constituent  part  or  reverse  the  process,  we 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  349 

come  to  the  same  conclusion,  though  what  is  laid  down  as 
an  explicit  principle  in  one  case  is  implicitly  assumed  in  the 
other,  and  gradually  ev^olved  in  the  process  of  life. 

38.  And  further,  it  must  of  course  be  admitted  that  in 
many  particular  cases  the  duties  may  conflict.  The  general 
qualities  which  fit  a  man  for  excellence  in  the  v^arious  rela- 
tions of  life  are  identical,  so  far  as  the  moralist  can  take 
notice  of  them,  but  he  cannot  say  what  weight  is  to  be 
given  to  special  considerations  in  given  cases.  It  is  plain 
that  so  far  as  a  man  acts  as  a  judge,  he  must  not  be  moved 
by  the  interests  of  his  family  ;  and  the  same  character  which 
causes  a  man  to  act  justly  as  a  father  will  make  him  act 
justly  as  a  judge,  for  he  will  feel  that  such  conduct  is  im- 
posed upon  him  by  the  claims  of  the  wider  organism,  and 
he  will  not  wish  that  his  children  more  than  himself  should 
be  helped  by  corrupt  actions.  But  it  is  not  possible  to  lay 
down  a  general  moral  principle  which  shall  decide  whether 
a  man  should  devote  himself  to  a  domestic  or  a  public  career. 
For,  in  the  first  place,  it  involves  the  difficult  question  of 
facts  as  to  which  career  will  be  the  most  useful,  and,  in  the 
next  place,  the  answer  must  partly  depend  upon  the  indivi- 
dual character.  If  a  man's  affections  are  strong  but  narrow, 
he  will  be  better  fitted  for  one  position;  if  diffusive  and 
lively,  better  fitted  for  another;  and  we  cannot  say  which 
man  is  the  most  moral.  Such  discussions  really  take  us 
beyond  the  sphere  of  morality  into  questions  of  prudence, 
which  can  generally  be  decided  by  nothing  but  instinctive 
tact. 

39.  For  my  immediate  purpose  I  have  gone  far  enough. 
The  moral  law  being,  in  brief,  conformity  to  the  conditions 
of  social  welfare,  conscience  is  the  name  of  the  intrinsic 
motives  to  such  conformity.  So  far  as  we  feel  ourselves  to 
be  members  of  any  social  organisation  and  identify  ourselves 
with  it,  we  are,  in  virtue  of  that  sentiment,  prompted  to  this 
conformity  and  feel  a  sense  of  obligation.  In  this  way  a 
kind  of  subordinate  conscience  is  formed  in  regard  to  even 
the  more  cursory  forms  of  association,  and  still  more  in  re- 


350  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

gard  to  the  more  permanent  and  conspicuous,  through  which 
our  stronger  instincts  are  gratified.  When  pubHc  spirit  im- 
poses upon  us  sacrifices  to  our  country,  we  are  actuated  by 
a  feeUng  which  is  of  the  same  kind  as  conscience,  and  is 
often  indistinguishably  blended  with  it.  But  it  is  the 
pecuHarity  of  the  moral  law  that  it  belongs  to  us,  not  in 
any  special  capacity,  but  as  belonging  to  the  indefinite  and 
formless  organisation  of  the  race  at  large.  On  the  other 
hand,  although  this  organisation  has  no  form  or  definite 
limits,  we  are  in  the  closest  possible  contact  with  it,  and  it  is 
the  underlying  substance  of  all  other  associations,  and 
especially  as  the  main  bonds  which  hold  it  together  are 
those  of  the  family  relations.  Our  whole  character  is 
moulded  from  our  earliest  infancy  by  the  family  tie,  and 
the  conformation  of  character  so  impressed  upon  us  carries 
with  it  the  wider  moral  sensibilities.  The  conscience,  there- 
fore, is  not  a  separate  faculty  which  responds  only  to  a 
special  set  of  stimuli,  but  is  a  compound  feeling  to  which  all 
the  strongest  instincts  of  our  nature  contribute.  Through 
our  affections  for  our  friends  and  our  brothers  our  feelings 
are  stamped  and  moulded,  and  prepared  to  be  developed 
under  the  action  of  all  the  other  relations  into  which  we  are 
brought,  as  our  intellects  and  sympathies  expand  and  our 
passions  come  into  play.  In  this  way  the  primary  instincts 
undergo  modifications,  causing  them  to  act  in  certain  ways, 
and  to  obey  certain  rules  which  have  necessarily  a  moral 
quality,  or,  in  other  words,  a  definite  relation  to  the  condi- 
tions of  social  welfare.  The  perception  that  this  rule  is 
formed  bv  somethino;  outside  us,  that  we  imbibe  it  from  the 
medium  in  which  we  live,  gives  the  sense  of  obligation, 
though  we  may  become  conscious  of  it  as  the  expression  of 
instincts  which  have  grown  up  before  distinct  reflection, 
and  are  involved  in  all  our  modes  of  thought  and  feeling. 
And  as  the  process  of  working  it  into  our  character  is  always 
more  or  less  imperfect,  we  have,  as  a  rule,  plenty  of  oppor- 
tunities for  finding  that  obedience  costs  an  eflbrt,  though 
disobedience  may  bring  with  it  a  pang.      The  conscience  is 


THE  CONSCIENCE.  351 

the  utterance  of  the  public  spirit  of  the  race,  ordering  us  to 
obey  the  primary  conditions  of  its  welfare,  and  it  acts  not 
the  less  forcibly  though  we  may  not  understand  the  source 
of  its  authority  or  the  end  at  which  it  is  aiming. 

40.  I  will  conclude  by  applying  this  to  the  particular  case 
of  maternal    love,    which    seems    to  be    as  well   the   purest 
type  as  an  original  germ  of  virtue.     It  has  been  denied  by 
sage  philosophers  that  it  is  a  virtue  at  all,  and  this  because 
it  is  an  instinct,  which  therefore  implies  at  most  a  compound 
selfishness,  and  involves  no  explicit  recognition  of  the  general 
principle  of  morality.    A  mother  is  not  good  because  she  loves 
her  children,  but  would  be  virtuous  if  she  deduced  the  dutv  of 
doing  good  to  them  from  some  abstract  principle — from  the 
doctrine  that  you  must  act  so  that  your  rule  may  be  a  rule 
for  all.  or  again  from  the  belief  that  by  doing  them  good  she 
was  actino-  from  a  wise  calculation  of  her  own  greatest  inte- 
rest,  or  of  the  greatest  happiness  of  the  greatest  number.     I 
hold,  on  the  contrary,  that  a  mother  who  loves  her  children 
is  so  far  good,  though  happily  she  has  not  much  merit,  as 
the  virtue  is  a  very  common  one,  and  therefore  that  it  is 
more  accurate  to  say  that  a  mother  who  does  not  love  her 
children  is  very  bad.     But  how  is  this  admission  of  the  in- 
stinctive character  of  the  virtue  to  be  reconciled  with  the 
doctrine  that  it  is  reasonable  as  the  embodiment  of  a  general 
principle  in  a  particular  case?     My  answer  is  that  we  must 
distinguish  two  closely  allied  questions.     If  you  ask,  "  Why 
is  maternal  love  a  virtue?"  the  answer  is,  "Because  it  is 
essential    to    social   virtue ; "    because,   in    other   words,   the 
vitality  of  every  society  from  the  earliest  period  is  dependent 
upon  the  vigorous  action  of  this  instinct.     The  same  con- 
sideration shows  that,  though  an  essential,  it  is  not  a  sufficient 
condition  of  virtue.     The  love  for  infants  must  be  controlled 
by  some  interest  in   others.     It  can    be   controlled   by  the 
wider  instinct  generally  because  the  instinct  springs  from  the 
same  root,  and  the  sympathy  excited  in  the  mother  by  the 
dependent  infant  is  homogeneous  with  her  sympathy  for  other 
infants,  and  for  all  to  whom  she  can  render  services.     The 


352  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

altruism,  again,  which  is  thus  generated  becomes,  in  a  mind 
capable  of  reflection,  the  conscious  acceptance  of  the  general 
principle,  which  of  course  receives  additional  strength  when 
it  is  explicitly  announced  as  part  of  the  fundamental  convic- 
tion of  the  society.  It  is  reinforced  by  all  the  other  motives, 
which  are  enabled  to  co-operate  with  it  because  society  is  so 
developed  as  to  secure  their  normal  coincidence.  In  this 
sense,  then,  the  general  condition  may  be  stated  as  deter- 
minins;  the  moral  character  of  the  instinct :  it  is  essential, 
and  perceived  to  be  essential,  to  social  welfare,  and  therefore 
(for  this  is  the  only  reason  we  can  give)  it  is  a  virtue,  and  a 
recoc^nised  virtue.  But  if  we  look  at  the  case  from  the 
opposite  side,  and  ask  for  the  mother's  reason  of  action,  we 
must  invert  the  order  of  the  deduction.  The  mother  loves 
because  she  is  so  constituted  as  to  be  capable  of  loving,  and 
because  she  is  part  of  a  society  in  which  the  instinct  is  stimu- 
lated and  fostered.  For  her  the  love  is  its  own  justification; 
she  has  the  sentiment,  and  need  look  no  further.  The  wider 
love  which  she  comes  to  feel  for  others  is  not  the  cause  of 
the  narrower  instinct,  but  the  product  whea  it  comes  to  be 
enlin-htened  and  extended ;  and  the  conscientious  feeling  itself 
which  sanctions  and  strengthens  the  primary  instinct  is  not 
something  which  exists  independently,  but  which  springs 
from  the  instinct  as  developed  through  the  emotions  and  the 
imbibation  of  the  social  instincts.  The  cause,  in  other  words, 
must  be  found  in  the  social  utility ;  the  reason  in  the  indi- 
vidual constitution  as  developed  by  the  social  life. 

41.  And  this  leads  to  a  new  division  of  the  subject.  I 
have  started  from  the  condition  of  social  welfare,  and  tried  to 
show  how  this  implies  the  growth  of  a  sense  of  obligation  in 
its  constituent  members;  but  now  we  must  start  from  the 
opposite  pole;  each  man  has  to  be  regarded  as  acting  from  his 
instincts,  however  it  may  have  come  to  pass  that  he  has  those 
instincts,  and  therefore  as  acting  with  an  immediate  reference 
to  his  happiness.  Whence  we  have  to  inquire  what  is  the 
relation  between  morality  and  happiness,  which  I  shall  proceed 
to  do  in  the  next  two  chapters. 


(     353     ) 


CHAPTER  IX. 

HAPPINESS     AS    A    CRITERION. 

I.   Utilitarianism. 

I.  The  phrase  "utility,"  I  have  remarked,  has  a  double 
sense.  Conduct  mav  be  called  "  useful  "  as  it  contributes  to 
the  preservation  of  the  agent,  or  as  it  contributes  to  his 
happiness ;  and  it  is  an  essential  part  of  the  evolution  theory 
that  these  two  characteristics  must  approximately  coincide ; 
that  is,  that  there  must  be  a  correlation  between  the  per- 
nicious and  the  painful  on  the  one  hand,  and  on  the  other 
between  the  beneficial  and  the  agreeable.  By  applying  this 
principle  to  the  social  organism,  we  have  come  to  the 
conclusion  that  the  development  of  the  society  implies  the 
development  of  certain  moral  instincts  in  the  individual,  or 
that  the  individual  must  be  so  constituted  as  to  be  capable 
of  identifying  himself  with  the  society,  and  of  finding  his 
pleasure  and  pain  in  conduct  which  is  socially  beneficial  or 
pernicious.  The  necessary  condition  for  morality  is  altruism. 
The  altruistic  person  is  moulded  and  modifiejd  by  the  society 
of  which  he  forms  a  part,  and  acquires  the  moral  sense  which 
implies  a  certain  intellectual  and  emotional  constitution.  But 
the  facts  may  be  equally  regarded  from  the  opposite  point 
of  view.  Conduct,  we  say,  is  a  function  of  character  and 
circumstance.  If  we  ask,  "  Why  does  a  man  act  in  such  a  way 
under  given  circumstances?"  the  immediate  answer  must 
always  be  in  the  form,  "  Because  it  is  pleasant,"  or,  in  other 
words,  because  it  gratifies  some  of  the  instincts  which  toiiether 
form  his  character.     This  must  in  all  cases  give  the  reason 

of  his  conduct.    But  if  we  choose  to  go  further  and  ask,  "  Whv 

z 


354  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

is  it  pleasant  ?  "  the  answer  must  be  given  by  showing  how  his 
character  comes  to  be  constituted  in  this  particular  way;  and 
the  only  explanation  that  can  be  given  is  the  exposition  of 
the  relations  which  the  agent  bears  to  the  whole  system  of 
which  he  forms  a  part.  "  Why  do  I  eat  ?  "  To  satisfy  hunger. 
"Why  do  I  hunger?"  Because  I  am  constituted  in  such  a 
way  that  the  consumption  of,  and,  therefore,  the  desire  for, 
food  is  essential  to  my  life.  In  this  case  I  assign  (so  far  as 
it  can  be  assigned)  the  cause  of  my  conduct.  The  problem 
hitherto  considered  has  corresponded  to  this  last  question.  We 
have  asked  what  is  the  cause  of  the  development  of  morality, 
and  we  have  answered  by  reference  to  the  social  organism. 
We  have  still  to  ask  what  is  the  reason  of  morality,  or  what 
are  the  motives  which  operate  upon  the  individual. 

2.  A  moral  agent  must  have  a  reason  for  moral  action, 
and  the  reason  must  clearly  have  some  relation  to  his  happi- 
ness. The  conduct  must  be  always  that  in  which  he  finds 
happiness  at  the  time,  and  the  "  end "  must  always  be 
either  his  own  happiness  or  the  happiness  of  others.  If,  in 
fact,  the  preservation  of  the  race  meant  the  continuance  of 
misery;  if,  like  Milton's  devils,  we  were  kept  in  existence  in 
order — 

"  Strongly  to  suffer  and  endure  our  woes," 

we  could  not  reasonably  desire  existence.  We  have,  therefore, 
to  justify  morality  both  as  happiness-giving  and  as  life-pre- 
serving. If  the  ends  necessarily  diverged,  we  should  get  into 
considerable  difficulties;  but,  as  I  have  urged,  the  very  principle 
of  evolution  implies  that  there  must  be  at  least  an  approximate 
coincidence,  and  there  is  no  apparent  a  priori  reason  why 
the  coincidence  should  not  be  indefinitely  close.  The  pessi- 
mist indeed  may  regard  life  as  essentially  miserable.  He 
escapes  from  the  conclusion  that  annihilation  is  desirable 
by  declaring  that  it  is  impossible.  All  that  is  left  for  us 
tipon  his  showing  is  to  minimise  the  misery  which  cannot 
be  annulled.  His  morality,  therefore,  aims  at  what  is 
equivalent  to  a  maximum  of  happiness,  although  he  states  it 


UTILITARIANISM.  355 

in  the  opposite  form  of  a  minimum  of  misery.  With  this 
question,  at  any  rate,  I  am  not  for  the  present  concerned.  I 
assume  that,  in  any  case,  we  are  invariably  determined  by 
pain  and  pleasure,  though  it  is  equally  true  that  our  pain 
and  pleasure  have  a  necessary  relation  to  the  tendency  of 
the  corresponding  conduct  to  our  preservation  or  destruction. 
We  have  now  to  ask  how  the  moral  rule  can  be  constructed 
from  this  secondary  point  of  view,  always  bearing  in  mind 
the  condition  defined  by  the  primary.  The  rules  which 
formerly  appeared  as  conditions  of  maintaining  the  vigour  of 
the  race  will  now  appear  as  conditions  of  securing  its  happi- 
ness. We  have  to  inquire  how  the  two  are  related;  whether 
the  rule  constructed  on  the  one  principle  coincides  necessarilv, 
and  how  far  it  coincides,  with  that  constructed  on  the  other; 
and  under  what  condition  that  which  is  the  cause  of  moral 
conduct  will  or  will  not  supply  an  adequate  reason  or  motive 
for  such  conduct  to  the  agent.  This,  in  the  utilitarian  phraseo- 
logy which  now  becomes  appropriate,  is  to  inquire  into  the 
criterion  and  the  sanction  of  morality ;  and  in  this  chapter 
I  shall  speak  of  the  first  of  these  problems. 

3.  Utilitarianism  is  the  system  which  endeavours  to  con- 
struct the  moral  rule  exclusively  from  the  principle  of  happi- 
ness, and  I  propose  to  ask  briefly  what  modification  must 
be  imposed  upon  this  system  in  order  to  make  it  square  with 
the  theory  here  adopted.  The  general  assumption  upon  which 
it  proceeds  may  be  easily  laid  down.  Happiness  is  the  sole 
end  of  conduct;  the  '^utility"  of  an  action  is  its  tendency  to 
produce  happiness;  its  morality  is  measured  by  its  utility; 
that  conduct  is  right  which  produces  most  happiness,  and 
by  this  we  must  be  understood  to  mean  which  produces 
most  happiness  on  the  average;  for  since  we  can  seldom 
calculate  more  than  a  small  part  of  the  consequences  of  any 
action,  we  are  forced  to  act  upon  rules  correspondino-  to  the 
general  limits  of  observation.  We  find  that,  on  an  average, 
certain  kinds  of  conduct  increase  and  others  diminish  happi- 
ness. We  have  to  act  upon  this  probability,  and  thus  we 
attain  the  moral  law.     "  This  action  is  wrong,"  means  that. 


356  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

on  an  average,  this  action  causes  a  balance  of  misery.  Further, 
the  motive  to  morality  must  be  the  motive,  whatever  it  may 
be,  which  makes  us  desire  to  promote  the  general  happi- 
ness. Here  utilitarians  divide,  according  as  they  do  or  do  not 
admit  the  reality  of  unselfish  impulses.  The  egoistic  utili- 
tarian holds  that  we  desire  to  promote  the  happiness  of  others 
because  we  shall  in  some  way  promote  our  own  happiness; 
the  altruistic  holds  that  the  desire  of  happiness  to  others  may 
be  an  ultimate  motive. 

4.  Although  this  doctrine  is,  as  I  shall  presently  argue, 
unsatisfactory  as  a  complete  account  of  morality,  it  contains, 
as  I  think,  a  core  of  inexpugnable  truth.  A  great  deal  is 
said  about  the  vagueness  of  the  word  "  happiness  "  and  the 
impossibility  of  devising  a  calculus  for  determining  the  effect 
of  conduct  upon  happiness.  The  criticism  would  be  con- 
clusive if  utilitarianism  required  any  such  calculus.  If  I 
attempted  to  lay  down  rules  for  the  whole  conduct  of  life, 
and  to  say  whether  in  any  given  case  this  or  that  course  will 
give  a  maximum  of  pleasure,  I  should  be  hopelessly  at  a  loss. 
On  the  one  side  the  vast  complexity  of  consequences,  on  the 
other  the  vast  variety  of  tastes,  would  make  it  impossible  to 
give  trustworthy  rules.  There  is  no  hope  that  we  shall  ever 
construct  a  pocket  calculating  machine  which  will  tell  us  by 
a  short  and  easy  method  what  is  the  path  to  happiness.  But, 
then,  this  very  uncertainty  is  an  essential  part  of  the  utili- 
tarian contention.  It  is  just  because  the  calculation  is  so 
hopelessly  intricate  that  we  are  forced  to  trust  to  rules  formed 
from  an  average,  and  that  we  can  obtain  so  very  few  of  such 
rules.  The  moral  law  can  only  give  us  a  few  very  simple  in- 
dications, because  our  powers  of  calculating  happiness  are  so 
limited.  In  order,  therefore,  to  make  the  objection  valid,  it 
must  be  shown  that  our  uncertainty  is  so  great  as  to  extend 
to  the  consequences  of  moral  behaviour.  We  must  show 
that  there  is  such  a  thing  as  a  law,  admitted  to  be  moral,  and 
yet  of  doubtful  effects  upon  happiness.  If  there  be  such  a 
thing,  we  shall  hardly  hear  of  it  from  the  other  schools  of 
morality,  for  they  are  at  least  as  anxious  as  their  opponents 


UTILITARIANISM.  357 

to  show  that  morality  produces  happiness.  Nobody,  indeed, 
will  seriously  profess  any  doubt  that  cruelty,  lying,  sensuality, 
and  so  forth,  do  diminish  the  stock  of  happiness.  Many 
people  deny  that  the  mischief  is  the  ground  or  the  sole  ground 
of  our  condemnation,  but  they  do  not  denv,  or  rather  they 
solemnly  assert,  the  reality  of  the  mischief.  If,  then,  they  admit 
the  fact  that  wickedness  causes  misery  and  virtue  happiness, 
thev  cannot  attack  the  utilitarian  for  holdino;  that  the  fact  is  as- 
certainable.  If  we  can  know  for  certain  that  morality  produces 
happiness,  the  utilitarian  who  makes  it  consist  in  producing 
happiness  cannot  be  accused  of  placing  morality  upon  an  un- 
certain base.  The  truth  upon  which  he  rests  is  admitted  by 
his  antagonist,  and  they  cannot  consistently  argue  that  it  is 
a  truth  which  cannot  be  known.  Yet  more,  if  it  can  be 
ascertained  that  any  class  of  conduct  increases  or  diminishes 
the  general  sum  of  happiness,  all  moralists  admit  that  it  is 
so  far  right.  If  it  were  proved  that  certain  conduct  did  no 
harm  to  anybody,  that  conduct  could  hardly  be  wrong.  The 
duty  of  benevolence  orders  us  to  increase  happiness,  and  happi- 
ness is  per  se  a  good  thing,  though  there  may  be  contingent 
objections  upon  other  grounds  to  particular  kinds  of  happiness. 
The  question,  therefore,  of  the  tendency  of  actions  to  pro- 
duce happiness  cannot  be  irrelevant  to  its  morality,  nor  can 
we  deny  that  moral  conduct  has  that  tendency,  or  that  con- 
duct proved  to  possess  it  thereby  becomes  moral.  So  far  as 
this  is  the  substance  of  a  good  many  attacks  upon  the  utili- 
tarian, I  think  that  he  is  perfectly  capable  of  holding  his 
own,  and  has  a  good  solid  basis  of  fact  from  which  it  would 
be  rash  to  attempt  to  dislodge  him.  Crime  is  mischievous; 
it  causes  bodily  and  mental  agony;  it  is  the  great  source  of 
all  human  suffering,  and  it  is  bad  for  that  plain  and  undeni- 
able reason.  If  you  could  get  rid  of  the  reason  you  would 
find  it  very  hard  to  substitute  any  other  of  equal  cogency. 
And,  indeed,  the  utilitarian  argument  appears  from  a  certain 
point  of  view  to  be  so  cogent,  that  one  is  half  disposed  to 
regard  all  the  argumentation  about  morality  as  grotesque. 
Can  it  be  necessary  to  go  into  such  elaborate  reasoning  to 


358  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

account  for  the  fact  that  men  have  generally  agreed  to  con- 
demn the  practice  of  cutting  each  other's  throats  ?  Why- 
should  not  they  ? 

5.  Yet,  when  we  try  to  answer  more  explicitly  the  various 
criticisms  that  have  been  so  frequently  and  forcibly  expressed, 
we  become  sensible  that  the  utilitarian  position  requires  at 
least  re-statement  or  reconstruction.  The  system  has  been 
attacked  as  giving  an  inadequate  account  of  all  the  most 
essential  characteristics  of  the  moral  law.  It  is  said,  in  the 
first  place,  that  since  morality  depends  upon  the  calculus  of 
happiness,  since  men's  conceptions  of  happiness  vary  within 
almost  indefinite  limits,  and  since  the  tendency  of  actions 
to  produce  particular  kinds  of  happiness  is  only  to  be  dis- 
covered by  examining  a  vast  variety  of  complex  phenomena 
which  elude  all  scientifie  inquiry,  the  rules  which  result  must 
necessarily  be  arbitrary  or  indefinitely  fluctuating.  If  at  a 
given  moment  they  take  one  shape,  there  is  no  assignable 
reason  why  they  should  not  take  another  at  any  other  time 
or  place.  Since,  again,  we  start  from  individual  conceptions 
of  happiness,  and  we  have  no  more  reason  for  assigning 
special  importance  to  the  judgment  of  one  man  than  to  that 
of  any  other,  or  of  preferring  the  estimate  of  the  saint  to  the 
estimate  of  the  sinner,  the  standard  which  results  from  the 
average  judgment  must  be  an  inferior  or  debasing  standard. 
Further,  since  on  this  hypothesis  the  morality  of  conduct  is 
essentially  dependent  upon  its  consequences,  that  is,  upon 
something  different  from  the  action  itself,  we  must  always  be 
led  to  an  external  moral  code.  Evil  cannot  be  objectionable 
as  evil  or  good  desirable  as  good,  but  we  must  always  con- 
sider morality  as  a  means  to  some  ulterior  end;  and  thus  the 
very  essence  of  virtue  is  destroyed ;  a  conscience  becomes 
superfluous;  and  hence,  finally,  the  moral  law  of  the  utili- 
tarian can  never  get  beyond  expediency.  There  is  always 
some  other  condition  by  reference  to  which  we  must  decide 
upon  any  particular  line  of  conduct,  and  therefore  the  moral 
rule,  though  it  may  serve  as  a  useful  indication  of  what  is  to 
be  done  in  average  cases,  cannot  be  a  supreme  and  absolute 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  359 

rule,  deciding  what  is  to  be  done  in  all  cases.  Hence  all 
the  specific  characteristics  of  which  we  took  account  in 
framing  our  theory  of  morality  are  more  or  less  destroyed ; 
for  though  the  utilitarian  can  provide  a  kind  of  substitute  for 
the  various  qualities  described,  he  can  only  make  an  outward 
show  of  morality,  and  run  up  an  edifice  which  looks  like  the 
everlasting  structure,  but  falls  to  pieces  at  the  first  touch. 
He  may  call  his  code  moral,  but  in  fact  it  is  a  code  which 
has  neither  permanence  nor  supremacy,  nor  uniformity  nor 
unconditional  validity. 


H.  The  Evolutionist  Criterion. 

6.  I  have  already  given  by  anticipation  my  answers  to 
these  charges,  if  applied  to  the  moral  system  which  I  am 
defending.  The  svstem,  however,  according  to  many  thinkers, 
is  simply  the  old  dog  in  a  new  doublet.  I  propose,  therefore, 
to  consider  more  precisely  how  far  the  evolutionist  morality 
can  meet  the  theories  which  have  some  cogency  as  against  the 
older  utilitarianism.  Utilitarianism,  let  us  note  in  the  first 
place,  springs  from  the  mode  of  speculation  which  renounces 
as  much  as  possible  every  a  priori  method,  and  rejects  all 
"intuitions^'  or  supposed  logical  necessities  of  thought,  in 
order  to  base  morality  upon  pure  experience.  The  tendency 
of  the  utilitarian  is  therefore  to  consider  knowledge  in  general 
as  conforming  to  the  type  of  that  purely  empirical  know- 
ledge in  which  the  experience  of  a  former  coincidence  of  two 
distinct  phenomena  is  the  sole  basis  for  our  expectation  of  a 
future  coincidence.  Carrying  out  this  principle  as  far  as 
possible,  reasoning  is  essentially  a  process  of  associating  ideas, 
and  the  association,  though  practically  indissoluble  in  some 
cases,  is  regarded  as  always  potentially  dissoluble.  The  logical 
result  is  atomism,  or  the  reduction  of  every  kind  of  organised 
system,  whether  of  "  ideas,"  regarded  as  existing  in  the 
mind,  or  of  the  objects  external  to  the  mind  and  represented 
by  the  ideas,  to  an  aggregate  of  independent  luiits,  capable 
of  indefinite  analysis  in  the  mind,  or  of  being  taken  to  pieces 


36o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

and  reconstructed  in  reality.  All  a  priori  truths,  therefore, 
disappear;  and  as  so-called  a  priori  truths  may  be  unverified 
and  erroneous  assumptions,  the  application  of  a  thoroughgoing 
analysis  is  at  least  useful  provisionally,  even  if  the  scepticism 
to  which  it  leads  should  not  be  ultimately  justifiable.  Further, 
as  it  is  the  tendency  of  thinkers  of  this  class  to  account  for 
all  differences  between  two  organisms  as  in  some  sense  due 
to  "  circumstance,"  they  are  forced  by  a  logical  necessity  to 
assume  the  existence  of  uniform  atoms  upon  which  the 
circumstances  operate.  The  difference,  for  example,  between 
two  men  being  due  to  the  various  associations,  and  not  to 
those  innate  tendencies  of  character  which  are  suspected  of  an 
affinity  to  "  innate  ideas,"  we  must  suppose  that  there  is  a 
uniform  man — a  colourless  sheet  of  paper  or  primitive  atom 
— upon  whom  all  qualities  are  imposed  by  the  circumstances 
under  which  he  is  placed.  This  assumption,  in  fact,  plays  a 
considerable  part  in  some  utilitarian  theories. 

7.  The  existence  of  assumptions  more  or  less  explicitly 
accepted  explains  the  general  tendency  of  the  school,  as  it 
may  help  to  render  intelligible  some  of  their  shortcomings. 
Society,  according  to  that  doctrine,  is  an  aggregate  built 
up  of  the  uniform  atoms  called  men.  The  only  primitive 
property  which  can  be  attributed  to  man  is  the  desire  for 
happiness ;  and  we  must  conceive  of  happiness  as  a  kind  of 
emotional  currency,  capable  of  being  calculated  and  distri- 
buted in  "  lots,"  which  have  a  certain  definite  value  indepen- 
dent of  any  special  taste  of  the  individual.  Conduct,  then,  is 
moral  or  immoral  according  as  it  tends  to  swell  or  diminish 
the  volume  of  this  hypothetical  currency.  Pains  and  pleasures 
can  be  handed  about  like  pieces  of  money,  and  we  have  simply 
to  calculate  how  to  gain  a  maximum  of  pleasure  and  a  mini- 
mum of  pain.  I  have  certainly  no  desire  to  fix  down  the 
utilitarian  to  any  extreme  form  of  his  theory,  or  to  pursue 
some  grotesque  consequences  to  which  it  is  occasionally 
applied.  The  criticisms  which  I  shall  consider  are  those 
which  seem  to  me  to  be  applicable  to  the  essence  of  the 
doctrine. 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  361 

8.  The  criterion  thus  suggested  is,  in  fact,  Hable  to  one 
criticism  which  appears  to  me  to  be  decisive  so  far  as  it 
appHes,  and  to  show  the  real  Hmitations  of  the  method;  I 
mean  that  it  fails  to  take  into  account  an  essential  condition 
of  any  tenable  theory,  and  that  precisely  because  it  refuses 
to  take  into  account  the  true  nature  of  the  social  organism, 
and  considers  it  a  simple  combination  of  independent  atoms. 
The  utilitarian  argument  would  be  perfectly  relevant  if  we 
could  take  each  action  by  itself,  sum  up  its  consequences,  and 
then  generalise  as  to  the  actions  of  the  class.  So,  for  example, 
I  find  that  eating  green  fruit  is  always  followed  by  a  painful 
sensation.  I  resolve  to  abstain;  and  if  all  other  men  made 
the  same  remark,  they  would,  if  wise,  follow  my  resolution  ; 
assuming,  of  course,  that  the  subsequent  pain  was  clearly 
greater  than  the  immediate  pleasure,  and  that  no  counter- 
balancing advantages  were  observable.  VVe  may  argue  in 
the  same  way  about  murder,  stealing,  lying,  drunkenness, 
and  so  forth.  They  do  infinite  mischief,  and  mischief  which 
clearly  overbalances  the  pleasure.  We  judge  that  thev 
diminish  the  sum  of  happiness,  and  I  have  no  doubt  that  our 
judgment  of  utility  is  so  implicated  in  the  moral  judgment 
that  one  could  not  change  without  a  corresponding  change  in 
the  other.  But  it  is  also  true  that  our  judgment  as  to  the 
effects  of  immoral  conduct  are  very  inadequately  represented 
by  this  simple  and  direct  process.  The  primary  evil  of  murder 
thus  estimated  is  the  pain  suffered  by  the  victim,  against 
which,  if  we  take  happiness  as  good  per  se,  we  must  set  off 
the  pleasure  of  the  murderer.  If  morality  is  to  be  defined  by 
happiness,  we  must  of  course  allow  all  kinds  of  happiness  to 
count,  and  to  count  equally  so  far  as  they  are  actually  equal. 
We  must  reckon  the  pleasures  of  malevolence  as  well  as  those 
of  benevolence.  Allowing  that  the  balance  inclines,  even 
upon  this  showing,  against  the  practice,  the  calculation  seems 
insufScient  to  justify  the  strength  of  the  general  prejudice. 
We  amend  our  argument,  therefore,  by  taking  into  account 
the  secondary  or  ulterior  consequences,  and  especially  the 
shock  to  the  general  sense  of  security.     We  may  possibly 


^62  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

object,  again,  to  allowing  the  murderer's  pleasure  to  count, 
because  a  motive  which  implies  pleasure  in  the  infliction  of 
pain  is  a  mischievous  motive,  and  therefore  whatever  pleasure 
it  may  produce  is  bought  at  a  ])rice  to  society  at  large.  But  it 
is  now  evident  that  we  must  take  into  account  a  consideration 
hitherto  neglected,  namely,  the  existence  of  a  certain  social 
order,  and  of  a  corresponding  character  in  the  individual 
constituents;  for  as  the  shock  to  the  sense  of  security  is 
undoubtedly  an  important  item  in  the  account,  the  shock  is 
proportioned  to  the  existence  of  a  certain  standard  of  mutual 
confidence.  Murder  means,  speaking  brieflv,  killing  by 
private  persons.  The  executioner  and  the  soldier  may  kill 
under  certain  circumstances;  and  though  war  may  be  de- 
nounced by  hasty  theorists  as  wholesale  murder,  the  distinction 
is  important,  for  war  does  not  in  the  same  way  imply  a  disin- 
tegration of  a  social  order,  but  is,  on  the  contrary,  an  essential 
part  of  the  process  by  which  that  order  has  been  built  up. 
It  is  easy  to  propose  the  summary  abolition  of  war,  and  we 
all  hope  that  it  may  be  abolished ;  but  all  men,  except  a  few 
enthusiasts,  can  see  that  to  propose  its  abolition  is  to  propose 
a  complete  social  and  moral  reconstruction.  It  is  not  an 
excrescence  which  can  be  simply  dropped,  but  the  result  of 
processes  essential  to  the  growth  of  society  in  certain  stages. 
What  is  true  of  war  is  equally  true  of  murder.  At  an  early 
period  the  distinction  between  public  and  private  killing  is 
unintelligible,  and  for  want  of  an  organisation  fitted  to 
suppress  individual  conflicts,  men  must  be  allowed  to  fight 
out  their  own  quarrels,  and  to  act  in  the  way  which  we  should 
afterwards  (that  is,  when  a  law  has  been  developed)  describe 
as  "  taking  the  law  into  their  own  hands."  Again,  it  is  quite 
true  that  the  murderer  in  the  present  day  is  a  malevolent  and 
therefore  mischievous  individual,  whose  gratification  is  not 
desirable  because  it  inflicts  more  evils  than  are  compensated 
by  his  pleasure.  But  this,  again,  is  virtually  to  assert  that  a 
social  development  has  been  evoked  in  which  the  pugnacious 
instincts  are  so  mischievous  that  they  can  be  placed  under 
certain  restraints.     At  an  earlier  period,  when  there  was  not 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  363 

a  residentiary  police,  the  calculus  of  happiness  would  be 
materially  different.  The  murderer  would  not  be  injuring 
a  sense  of  security  which  did  not  in  fact  exist — perhaps 
would  even  be  dischartrino;  a  necessary  function :  nor, 
again,  would  the  pain  of  the  sufferer  be  the  same,  nor  the 
pleasure  derived  from  the  killing  be  indicative  of  so  mis- 
chievous a  character. 

9.  It  follows,  then,  that  the  direct  application  of  the 
calculus  omits  a  most  essential  element  in  the  calculation. 
Let  us  note — for  the  point  is  one  of  vital  importance — what 
are  the  tacit  assumptions  involved.  The  utilitarian  or  indi- 
vidualist considers  society  to  be  formed  of  an  aggregate  of 
similar  human  beings.  The  character  of  each  molecule  is 
regarded  as  constant.  The  only  difference  which  he  considers 
to  be  relevant  in  a  moral  sense  consists  in  a  more  or  less 
exhaustive  and  accurate  calculation  of  the  consequences  of 
actions.  That  society,  therefore,  will  enjoy  the  greatest 
happiness  which  has  the  clearest  perception  of  these  conse- 
quences,'and  consequently  enforces  the  corresponding  rule; 
for  we  at  present  assume  that  a  perception  of  the  evil  leads 
to  its  suppression.  Now  at  any  given  moment,  as  character 
varies  slowly  and  the  social  relations  may  be  taken  as  approxi- 
mately fixed,  this  gives  an  approximately  accurate  test;  that 
is  to  say,  the  consequences  of  immoral  conduct  generally 
involve  misery,  and  the  further  we  trace  them  the  more 
evident  is  the  fact.  But  when  we  try  to  frame  something 
like  a  scientific  criterion  from  such  considerations,  w^e  become 
sensible  of  the  inadequacy  of  the  statement.  For  the  conse- 
quences can  only  be  traced  when  we  recognise  the  nature  of 
the  social  structure,  which  again  implies  the  existence  of  a 
certain  stage  of  individual  development,  and  neither  of  these 
is  deducible  from  the  properties  of  the  assumed  unit.  Human 
nature  is  not  a  constant,  but,  on  the  contrary,  a  variable,  and 
the  aim  of  the  moralist  is  precisely  to  modify  it.  The  problem 
changes  in  our  hands  as  we  consider  it.  If,  in  f^ict,  we  ask 
what  are  to  be  considered  as  the  consequences,  it  is  plain  at 
once  that  we  cannot  make  an  arbitrary  selection  of  the  most 


364  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

obvious  and  prominent.  What  are  the  consequences  of  a 
murder?  Evervthing  which  isimphed  in  the  murder  not  hap- 
pening, including  the  consequences  to  the  victim,  to  societv 
at  larsie,  and  all  that  follows  from  the  implied  change  in 
the  character  of  the  murderer.  What  are  the  consequences 
of  a  certain  frequency  of  murder?  All  that  is  implied  in  the 
difference  between  a  society  where  murder  is  frequent  and 
one  in  which  it  is  not  frequent.  This,  again,  implies  a  com- 
plete structural  change,  the  consequences  of  which  reach  inde- 
finitely beyond  this  particular  mischief.  To  suppress  murder 
is  to  civilise  a  societv  ;  and  unless  we  take  into  account  the 
laws  of  social  growth,  it  is  impossible  to  say  what  is  included 
in  civilisation. 

10.  The  utilitarian  criterion,  again,  is  frequently  presented 
in  the  form  of  a  maximum.  Morality  is  conduct  tendinc;  to 
produce  the  greatest  happiness  of  the  greatest  number.  But 
a  maximum  is  meaningless  unless  we  assume  certain  fixed 
conditions.  Here  we  must  mean  the  greatest  happiness 
possible,  and  therefore  possible  on  a  certain  assumption.  But 
on  what  assumption?  The  assumption  of  the  fixity  ofhuman 
nature.  But  that  alone  is  insufficient.  It  would  lead  to 
such  conclusions  as  this:  that  the  society  was  happiest  in 
which  there  were  fewest  murders,  whatever  the  cause  of  their 
rarity.  But  this  is  at  least  a  doubtful  truth,  since  violence 
may  be  diminished  as  well  by  diminution  of  energy  as  by  an 
increase  of  peaceful ness,  and  the  bare  elimination  of  particular 
practices  gives  a  totally  inadequate  measure  of  social  welfare. 
Doubtless  a  diminution  of  certain  evils  will  be  a  symptom  of 
social  progress  after  a  certain  stage,  but  it  is  not  a  measure 
of  the  whole  complex  process.  If,  then,  we  suppose  that  a 
given  stage  has  in  fact  been  reached,  and  that  on  comparing 
two  societies  at  that  stage,  that  will  be  the  happiest  in  which 
there  are  the  fewest  murders,  we  are  making  a  tenable  pro- 
position, and  one  which  is  undoubtedly  of  vast  importance. 
But  it  has  an  appearance  of  being  arbitrary,  because  we  take 
for  granted  the  existence  of  certain  instincts  as  an  ultimate 
fact;  and  therefore,  though  excluding  intuitions,  we  are  vir- 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  365 

tuallv  assuming  the  existence  of  a  certain  disposition,  whilst 
we  make  no  attempt  to  justify  our  assumption.  We  prove 
that,  under  given  circumstances,  murder  is  on  the  average 
objectionable,  but  we  do  not  attempt  to  state  what  is  the 
cause  of  its  badness,  or  to  state  the  general  principle  upon 
which  we  are  proceeding.  It  may  always  be  argued  that  we 
are  biassed  by  certain  prejudices  which  are  more  or  less  arbi- 
trary, or  which,  in  other  words,  might  be  changed  without 
injury  to  the  general  happiness.  We  object  to  murder  be- 
cause in  the  existing  state  of  society  it  does  more  harm  than 
good.  But  suppose  we  get  rid  of  some  of  the  feelings  con- 
cerned, might  we  not  be  the  happier  on  the  whole  ?  To 
answer  this  we  are  thrown  back  upon  the  previous  case,  and 
have  to  compare  the  amount  of  happiness  in  two  societies 
agreeing  only  in  the  circumstance  that  both  are  composed  of 
men,  which  seems  to  render  the  whole  problem  too  intricate 
and  indeterminate  for  practical  application. 

II.  Consider  for  a  moment  what  is  perhaps  something 
more  than  an  analogous  case.  So  far  as  our  physical  con- 
stitution is  concerned,  the  only  conceivable  motive  is  the 
attainment  of  pleasure.  We  may  say,  therefore,  that  a  man 
acts  most  wisely — considered  simply  as  an  animal — who  acts 
so  as  to  obtain  the  maximum  of  pleasure.  But  if  we  should 
seek  to  frame  a  rule  of  life  directly  from  this  consideration, 
we  should  fall  into  infinite  perplexity.  We  must  obviously 
say,  in  fact,  that  he  must  act  with  reference  to  his  constitu- 
tion. Pleasure  is  not  a  separate  thing  independently  of  his 
special  organisation.  The  bare  rule,  "  Get  as  much  pleasure  as 
you  can,"  is  unintelligible  unless  we  proceed  further  and  point 
out  some  of  the  conditions  which  must  be  observed.  Each 
instinct,  for  example,  must  have  its  turn,  and  their  respective 
provinces  must  be  determined  by  the  general  organic  balance. 
We  can  undoubtedly  point  out  that  certain  modes  of  con- 
duct produce  pain  and  others  pleasure,  and  this  is  a  primd 
facie  reason,  at  least,  for  avoiding  one  and  accepting  the 
other.  But,  again,  some  pains  imply  a  remedial  process, 
whilst  others  imply  disease;  and  the  conduct  which  increases 


366  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

them  may  therefore  be  either  wise  or  foolish  in  the  highest  de- 
gree. For  the  simple  rule,  therefore,  "  Get  the  most  pleasure," 
we  must  substitute  the  general  rule,  "  Preserve  health."  The 
two  rules  plainly  coincide  very  closely.  The  healthiest  man 
is  generally  the  happiest,  and  therefore  the  best  and  only 
general  rule  for  securing  physical  pleasure  is,  "Be  healthy." 
No  doubt  some  kind  of  rule  might  be  constructed  by  aimino- 
at  happiness.  We  may  recommend  temperance,  for  ex- 
ample, because  we  observed  as  a  truth  that  intemperance  is 
generally  followed  by  a  headache,  and  the  practice  of  intem- 
perance by  all  the  pains  of  various  diseases.  But  we  are  then 
tacitly  referring  to  the  organic  conditions  which  are  summed 
up  by  saying  that  intemperance  is  inconsistent  with  health. 
This,  therefore,  whether  explicitly  or  implicitly  stated,  is  a 
necessary  element  in  our  statement,  and  gives  the  only  o-eneral 
criterion.  We  wish  for  health,  it  may  be,  only  as  a  condition 
of  pleasure,  but  the  only  general  rule  for  obtaining  pleasure 
is  to  secure  this  general  condition.  If  we  tried  directlv  to  sum 
up  the  various  kinds  of  pleasure,  to  compare  the  value,  to 
discover  how  far  they  were  compatible,  and  to  decide  how 
much  we  should  take  of  each,  we  should  embark  upon  a 
hopelessly  complicated  undertaking,  which  is  made  needless 
by  the  single  consideration  that  the  process  is  in  all  cases 
conditioned  by  the  maintenance  of  the  organic  condition 
called  health.  The  organism  has  solved  the  problem  for  us 
approximately.  It  has  come  to  be  so  constituted  that  what 
is  pleasant  is  approximately  wholesome.  We  start  with  that 
assumption,  and  correct  the  errors  by  the  inverse  conclusion 
that  what  is  wholesome  is  in  the  long  run  also  productive  of 
most  pleasure. 

13.  This,  as  it  seems  to  me,  represents  the  real  difference 
between  the  utilitarian  and  the  evolutionist  criterion.  The  one 
lays  down  as  a  criterion  the  happiness,  the  other  the  health  of 
the  society.  The  two  are  not  really  divergent;  on  the  con- 
trary, they  necessarily  tend  to  coincide;  but  the  latter  satisfies 
the  conditions  of  a  scientific  criterion  in  a  sense  in  which 
the  former  fails.    I  desire  happiness.    I  discover  by  experience 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  367 

that  this  or  that  particular  set  of  conditions  makes  me  happy, 
and  by  degrees  I  learn  how  to  divide  myself  amongst  different 
impulses,  and  so  to  obtain  certain  general  rules  of  happiness. 
But  to  obtain  any  germ  of  a  scientific  theory  I  must  turn 
from  without  to  within  ;  the  law  of  happiness  will  appear  as 
simple  only  when  it  is  regarded  as  a  law  in  terms  of  the  state 
of  the  single  individual  who  goes  through  all  these  v^arious 
experiences.  The  external  conditions  of  happiness  are  multi- 
tudinous and  incapable  of  summation,  but  they  must  all  agree 
in  this,  that  they  stimulate  me  in  a  manner  consistent  with 
the  laws  of  my  being,  in  the  unity  of  which  they  are  com- 
bined and  correlated.  Therefore  the  general  rule  must  be  a 
rule  relative  to  my  state,  and  briefly  the  law  of  my  health. 
What  is  true  of  the  individual  is  true  in  proportion  of  the 
much  valuer  and  less  coherent  social  oro;anism.  We  obtain 
unity  of  principle  when  we  consider,  not  the  various  external 
relations,  but  the  internal  condition  of  the  organism.  The 
conditions  might  conceivably  be  laid  down  either  by  saying 
that  the  various  social  functions  are  discharged  and  the  rela- 
tion between  the  social  organs  maintained  in  a  certain  equili- 
brium, or  by  trying  to  sum  up  all  the  various  modes  of  conduct 
which  produce  happiness  to  its  various  members ;  but  we  only 
get  a  tenable  and  simple  law  when  we  start  from  the  structure, 
which  is  itself  a  unit. 

13.  Hence,  again,  we  obtain  a  rule  which  is  fixed  and 
elastic  in  the  right  place.  An  organism  may  be  healthy  or 
diseased  at  any  period  of  its  growth,  and  the  laws  of  health 
or  disease  will  be  continuous,  although  varying  within  limits 
as  the  organism  itself  varies.  But  if  we  take  the  direct 
utilitarian  criterion,  it  seems  to  be  rigid  and  yet  indefinitely 
variable  in  different  directions.  For  as  human  nature  is  taken 
as  a  constant,  we  should  always  have  the  same  rule  of 
conduct;  and  yet  as  men's  thoughts  and  feelings  are  sup- 
posed to  be  indefinitely  variable  in  obedience  to  accidental 
association,  we  seem  to  have  no  guarantee  for  the  permanence 
of  any  moral  criterion.  In  fact,  utilitarian  moralists  have 
dwelt  upon  the  variations  of  the  moral  standard  in  order  to 


368  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

prove  the  necessity  of  resting  morality  upon  experience  and 
to  get  rid  of  a  priori  intuitions.  They  have  dwelt  upon  the 
same  facts  in  order  to  justify  a  belief  in  human  perfectibility. 
Yet  surely  if  human  nature  is  in  this  sense  so  modifiable, 
we  have  no  guarantee  for  expecting  amelioration  rather  than 
deterioration.  And  if,  as  I  have  said,  human  nature  is  re- 
garded as  in  some  sense  a  constant,  the  science  of  morality, 
which  should  be  rigidly  deducible  from  its  properties,  can 
hardly  be  realised  when  the  human  material  is  capable  of 
being  worked  up  into  indefinitely  varying  forms.  It  is  in 
substituting  for  these  contradictory  examples  the  conception 
of  a  slowly  developing  social  organism  that  the  evolution 
philosophy  has  rendered  the  greatest  service  to  ethics,  as  the 
variations  become  themselves  reducible  under  a  fixed  rule,  and 
the  necessity  of  recognising  the  social  organism  as  something 
not  formed  by  simple  mechanical  combination  restores  the 
due  authority  to  social  instincts  without  elevating  them  into 
transcendental  intuitions. 

14.  Briefly,  then,  I .  regard  utilitarianism  as  giving  what 
may  be  called  instantaneous  morality.  It  corresponds  to  the 
way  in  which  men  actually  reason  and  are  justified  in  reasoning 
provisionally  as  to  moral  questions.  We  see  that  a  certain 
social  arrangement  or  regulation  produces  bad  and  good 
effects.  We  try  roughly  to  sum  them  up,  and  to  regulate  or 
repeal  accordingly.  Our  moral  judgments  are  in  all  cases  de- 
termined by  these  observations,  or  must  be  in  conformity  with 
them.  Any  class  of  conduct  which  clearly  produces  a  balance 
of  misery  is  so  far  bad,  and  that  which  produces  a  balance  of 
happiness  is  so  far  good.  A  constant  and  steady  attempt  to 
get  rid  of  the  misery-causing,  and  to  encourage  the  happiness- 
causing  activities  is  the  condition  of  all  moral  progress.  In 
order  to  modify  any  moral  law  or  any  social  arrangement,  we 
try  to  show  that  it  actually  causes  some  misery,  and  that  its 
modification  would  produce  more  happiness.  I  do  not  see 
that  any  other  mode  of  argument  has  ever  any  real  efficiency. 
The  actual  progress  in  morality  is  always  determined  at  every 
point  by  utilitarian    considerations.      But  when  we   try  to 


THE  EVOLUTIONIST  CRITERION.  369 

generalise  from  this,  and  to  sav  that  the  form  of  morality  or 
the  criterion  of  moral  conduct  is  the  tendency  to  produce 
happiness,  we  get  into  difficulties.  The  reason  is  that  already 
civen.  We  are  generalising  in  such  a  wav  as  to  omit  an 
essential  condition  of  an  accurate  statement.  We  are  taking 
constants  for  variables  and  variables  for  constants.  If  v^'e 
compare  anv  two  organisms,  we  assume  a  certain  organic 
identity.  Both  of  them,  we  suppose,  have  a  certain  fixed  core 
of  instincts,  and  corresponding  habits  which  define  their 
essential  character.  It  is  also  capable  of  varying  in  a  sub- 
ordinate degree  compatibly  with  the  uniformity  of  these 
fundamental  organic  relations.  Now  we  may  say  that  any 
conduct  which  produces  pain  is  so  far  bad.  So  far  as  the 
being  is  capable  of  intelligent  observation,  it  may  classify  the 
various  kinds  of  conduct  as  they  lead  to  painful  or  pleasurable 
conditions,  and  its  action  will  be  determined  accordingly.  On 
the  other  side,  pain  implies  a  certain  condition  of  the  organ- 
ism itself  which  we  may  call  morbid  as  depending  upon  a 
deviation  from  the  normal  equilibrium.  The  being  itself 
must  be  so  constituted  that  the  conditions  of  pleasure  coin- 
cide closely  with  the  conditions  of  health.  So  far,  therefore, 
that  is,  whilst  we  assume  an  identity  of  organic  relations, 
the  two  rules  will  coincide ;  those  which  cause  pain  are  bad, 
and  those  which  cause  morbid  action  are  bad.  The  internal 
and  the  external  law  approximately  coincide.  The  external 
rule  assumes  indeed  the  existence  of  a  certain  internal  con- 
stitution, but  as  that  is  fixed  it  does  not  require  to  be  ex- 
pressly stated.  But  now  we  suppose  a  new  instinct  to  be 
required  ;  we  perceive  that  certain  conduct  produces  pain 
on  an  average,  and  we  therefore  propose  to  eliminate  it.  It 
cannot  be  simply  left  out,  because  we  are  dealing  with  an 
organism,  and  every  such  change  involves  an  action  upon  the 
whole  constitution.  The  organic  relations,  therefore,  are 
themselves  changed,  and  we  substitute  virtually  a  new  organ- 
ism for  the  old.  The  new,  we  may  assume,  is  on  the  whole 
more   efficient   than   its  predecessor,   and  represents  a  more 

complete   solution  of   the   general   problem  of  life.      As  it 

2  A 


370  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

has  new  sensibilities,  it  no  longer  estimates  happiness  in  the 
same  way  as  the  old.  If  we  compare  the  two,  we  must  not 
suppose  that  we  have  an  identical  being  placed  in  different 
circumstances  and  making  different  estimates  of  happiness, 
but  two  different  beings,  with  different  measures  of  happiness. 
The  difference  is  not  represented  by  a  more  complete  attain- 
ment of  the  same  ends,  but  by  a  change  in  the  end  itself,  and 
a  greater  total  efficiency  of  the  whole  new  system.  The 
common  rule  is  that  each  oro-anism  is  better  as  it  obeys  the 
conditions  of  health,  but  we  cannot  found  any  common  rule 
upon  the  happiness,  the  standard  of  which  changes  as  the 
organism  itself  changes. 

15.  In  this  sense  the  growth  of  the  social  organism  is 
precisely  analogous  to  that  of  the  individual.  The  devel- 
opment of  the  animal  implies  the  slow  acquisition  of  new 
instincts,  which  in  time  become  part  of  its  organic  constitu- 
tion. Whilst  they  are  not  fully  organised  they  determine  its 
conduct  more  or  less  by  the  pain  and  pleasure  with  which 
they  are  associated,  and  they  tend  to  become  fixed  as  they 
imply  on  the  whole  a  superior  or  more  efficient  form  of 
organisation.  The  moral  instincts  of  the  society  correspond 
in  the  same  way  to  the  social  development,  and  express  at 
every  instant  the  judgment  formed  of  the  happiness  and 
misery  caused  by  corresponding  modes  of  conduct.  As  they 
become  organised  the  whole  society  becomes  more  efficiently 
constituted,  and  its  standard  of  happiness  is  also  modified. 
We  may  therefore  say  that  at  any  period  the  vitilitariau 
judgment  must  be  satisfied.  Given  a  certain  stage  of  social 
development,  the  society  will  be  in  a  healthier  state  and  the 
general  happiness  greater  in  proportion  as  it  is  moral.  But 
since  the  happiness  itself  changes  as  the  society  develops,  we 
cannot  compare  the  two  societies  at  different  stages  as  if  they 
were  more  or  less  efficient  machines  for  obtaining  an  identical 
product. 

16.  The  importance  of  the  distinction  is  illustrated  in 
almost  every  important  social  discussion.  We  notice  certain 
bad  results  from  a  particular  economical  or  social  arrange- 


VARIABILITY  OF  MORALITY.  371 

ment.  The  indissolubility  of  marriage  inflicts  hardship 
upon  many  individuals ;  let  it  be  dissoluble  in  those  cases. 
The  importation  of  foreign  products  ruins  certain  manu- 
facturers ;  let  it  be  prohibited.  We  remedy  the  immediate 
evil  by  suppressing  more  obvious  symptoms ;  but  we  often 
forget  that  we  are  dealing  with  a  complex  organism,  and 
that  the  real  problem  involves  innumerable  and  far-reaching 
actions  and  motives  due  to  its  constitution.  We  may  be 
remedying  the  grievances  of  individual  husbands  and  wives 
l)y  lowering  the  general  sanctity  of  family  relations,  and 
helping  a  particular  class  at  the  expense  of  the  general 
efficiency  of  the  nation.  I  need  not  say  how  constantly 
such  omissions  vitiate  plausible  arguments  and  involve  the 
accomplishment  of  the  chimerical  hopes  of  reformers.  A 
similar  practical  conclusion  may  be  drawn  from  this  part  of 
the  argument,  namely,  that  to  prove  that  a  rule  of  conduct 
involves  pain  in  many  cases  is  not  a  sufficient  reason  for 
abolishing  it,  though  it  is  a  presumption  for  modifying  it. 
We  are  also  bound  to  show  that  all  the  consequences  involved 
in  the  change,  including  the  changes  in  the  individual 
character  and  in  the  social  structure,  will  produce  a  more 
efficient  social  organism.  It  is  true  that,  as  a  rule,  we  have 
to  work  out  such  changes  by  actual  experiment ;  but  it  is  well 
to  note  beforehand  the  need  of  conforming  our  expectations 
to  the  complexity  of  the  problem. 


III.   Variahillty  of  Morality. 

17.  The  evolution  theory  necessarily  assumes  a  variation 
of  morality,  but  not  an  indefinite  or  arbitrary  variability. 
And  this  may  lead  us  to  a  further  question.  We  must 
admit,  of  course,  that  the  calculus  of  happiness  will  give 
different  results  at  different  periods.  Qualities  will  be  re- 
garded as  virtuous  amongst  savages  which  cease  to  be  virtu- 
ous amongst  civilised  men.  Revenge  is  sometimes  regarded 
as  a  duty,  and  in  a  rude  social  state  we  may  say  that  it 
may  conceivably  cause  more  happiness  than  misery.     As, 


372  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

according  to  Bacon,  revenge  is  a  kind  of  wild  justice,  it  may 
to  a  certain  extent  discharge  the  functions  of  justice  before 
a  settled  system  of  law  has  been  developed.  To  weaken 
the  motive  without  corresponding  development  of  the 
virtues  of  order,  would  be  to  remove  a  penalty  upon  wrong- 
doing, and  might  imply  rather  a  deficiency  in  energy  of 
feeling  than  a  defect  of  sympathy.  Of  two  societies  at  the 
corresponding  stage  of  development,  the  one  which  had  it 
least  might  be  in  a  morbid  condition,  and  therefore  in  one 
less  favourable  to  the  average  happiness  than  the  other  in 
which  the  sentiment  was  vigorous.  This  inconclusiveness  of 
the  utilitarian  standard  if  no  reference  be  made  to  the  social 
state  follows  from  the  previous  argument,  and  it  presents 
another  difficulty  which  frequently  occurs.  The  variability 
of  different  estimates  of  happiness  is  pointed  out  as  one 
of  the  main  difficulties  of  the  utilitarian  creed.  One  man 
prefers  sensual,  another  intellectual  pleasures.  Which  is 
right,  and  why  ?  The  question  is  one  of  importance  in 
regard  to  the  sanction  of  morality — that  is,  in  assigning  the 
general  motive  to  which  moralists  may  appeal — and  I  shall 
return  to  it  in  the  next  chapter.  Meanwhile  let  us  ask 
how  far  it  affects  the  criterion  of  morality.  If  the  moral 
criterion  resulted  from  taking  an  average  of  different  esti- 
mates of  happiness,  there  would  be,  doubtless,  a  difficulty. 
But  then  I  deny  that  this  gives  in  any  case  the  true  theory 
of  morality.  The  moral  sense  is,  indeed,  according  to  me, 
a  product  of  the  social  factor.  It  is  the  sum  of  certain 
instincts  which  have  come  to  be  imperfectly  organised  in 
the  race,  and  which  are  vigorous  in  proportion  as  the  society 
is  healthy  and  vigorous.  Undoubtedly,  again,  they  fall  in 
with  the  general  belief  as  to  the  effects  upon  happiness  of 
certain  modes  of  conduct.  This,  again,  is  equally  true 
whether  we  suppose  that  the  society  has  thriven  because  it 
had  useful  instincts — that  is,  because  its  judgments  of  happi- 
ness were  in  fact  such  as  to  make  it  thrive — or  whether 
we  suppose  that  the  instinct  has  been  consequent  upon  an 
observation  of  certain  bad  consequences.    In  the  earlier  stages 


Variability  of  morality.  373 

of  development  the  first  method  will  presumably  be  the 
dominant,  and  in  later  stages  the  second,  whieh  implies 
a  certain  power  of  distinct  reasoning.  But  in  any  case,  there 
can  be  no  doubt  that  the  judgment  that  conduct  is  im- 
moral will  coincide  with  the  judgment  that  it  diminishes 
happiness ;  and  therefore  a  race  which  has  low  concep- 
tions of  happiness  will  have  a  low  view  of  morality.  If  the 
sensual  pleasures  play  a  great  part  in  the  general  estimate  of 
happiness,  it  is  probable  that  the  virtue  of  temperance  will 
not  be  hi2;hlv  estimated. 

18.  This,  I  imagine,  can  hardly  be  disputed;  but,  on  the 
other  hand,  it  is  not  true  that  the  moral  judgment  preva- 
lent in  a  race  amounts  implicitly  or  explicitly  to  the  asser- 
tion that  the  average  standard  of  happiness  is  that  which  a 
moral  agent  will  desire,  or  which  it  is  desirable  to  secure  for 
society  at  large.  In  fact,  as  I  have  argued,  the  general  pro- 
cess in  any  progressive  state  of  society  implies  something 
materially  different.  The  moral  law  first  appears,  as  I  have 
said,  in  the  external  form.  People  come  to  recognise,  that 
is,  that  certain  lines  of  conduct  do  harm  irrespectively  of 
the  motives  of  the  agent.  They  observe,  more  or  less  clearly, 
that  certain  breaches  of  the  law  of  temperance  produce  inju- 
ries to  men  in  various  relations;  that  the  attempt  to  enforce 
particular  beliefs  causes  war,  misery,  endless  discord,  and 
the  suppression  of  intellectual  activity.  When  this  opinion 
has  been  established  we  have  what  may  be  called  a  purely 
utilitarian  law  of  morals.  There  is  a  general  conviction 
that  a  certain  class  of  conduct  causes  suffering,  but  it  is  not 
yet  clearly  realised  that  such  conduct  is  in  itself  wicked. 
It  may  be  adopted  by  good  men  or  from  good  motives — if 
goodness  is  measured  by  conformity  to  the  existing  standard. 
But  if  society  improves,  the  external  law  must  become  an 
internal  law;  the  conduct  which  produces  the  bad  effects 
must  be  intrinsically  repugnant,  and  there  is  therefore  a 
demand  for  the  true  virtues  of  temperance  and  toleration, 
with  all  the  necessary  implications  as  to  the  whole  char- 
acter.     The    purely    utilitarian    rule    proposes    a    problem 


374  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

which  Is  solved  by  generating  a  type  of  character  so  con- 
stituted that  the  evils  perceived  are  intrinsically  hateful  to  it. 
19.  It  is,  in  fact,  plain  that  the  moral  judgment  does  not 
correspond  exactly  to  the  individual  estimate  of  happiness. 
A  man,  for  example,  may  be  sensual:  w^hen  a  gross  pleasure 
is  within  his  grasp,  he  may  prefer  it  to  a  refined  pleasure; 
but  in  his  judgment  of  his  neighbours  he  sees  that  the  sensual 
person  incurs  diseases  and  inflicts  injuries  upon  his  neighbour. 
Even  the  most  sensual  of  mankind  wishes  his  daughters  to 
grow  up  chaste,  and  would  try  to  prevent  his  sons  from  be- 
coming drunkards.  A  man  may  be  intolerant  in  the  sense  of 
desiring  to  impose  his  own  opinions  by  downright  force,  or  by 
other  modes  than  pure  reason,  but  he  may  recognise  the  fact 
that  the  general  admission  of  this  principle  leads  to  innume- 
rable evils.  It  is  a  common  observation  that  persecution  has 
been  attacked  by  men  who  had  a  full  share  of  the  persecuting 
spirit.  They  objected  to  being  persecuted  themselves,  not  to 
persecution  in  general ;  but  in  order  to  secure  themselves  they 
were  forced  to  appeal  to  principles  common  to  all,  and  there- 
fore to  insist  upon  the  bad  consequences  of  persecution  in 
general,  and  to  become,  in  spite  of  themselves,  advocates  of 
the  genuine  virtue  of  toleration.  This  process  is  the  typical 
one.  In  attacking  particular  evils  we  become  sensible  to  the 
general  underlying  principle,  and  by  pointing  out  the  mischie- 
vous results  of  certain  kinds  of  conduct  we  are  virtually  prepar- 
ing a  higher  type  of  character,  to  which  not  only  that  kind 
of  conduct  is  repugnant,  but  all  such  conduct  as  springs  from 
similar  qualities  of  character.  We  object  to  the  sensual  con- 
duct, not  primarily  as  sensual,  but  as  mischievous  in  some 
other  way;  we  come  to  object  to  the  sensuality  itself  when 
we  recoi^nise  it  as  the  source  of  these  and  of  other  evils.  The 
process  is  possible  because  at  every  instant  we  start  from  an 
approximate  solution  of  the  problem,  and  with  instincts  so 
far  balanced  and  correlated  as  to  be  consistent  with  the  con- 
ditions of  existence :  the  process  is  slow  because  the  redress 
of  any  evil  involves  a  readjustment  of  the  whole  character; 
and  it  is  endless,  because  from  each  point  we  have  reached  we 


VARIABILITY  OF  MORALITY.  375 

develop  new  faculties,  and  have  to  attack  new  and  wider 
problems.  The  whole  process  corresponds,  not  to  the  sum- 
mary solution  of  a  problem  from  fixed  data,  but  to  an  inces- 
sant series  of  approximations,  in  which  we  start  from  one 
organisation  which  works  tolerablv  to  another  which  will  on 
the  whole  work  better. 

20.  In  this  sense  it  is  true,  as  I  should  say,  that  the  actual 
character  of  men,  and  therefore  their  estimate  of  happiness, 
must  always  provide  the  basis  for  every  further  improvement. 
The  new  rule  of  morality  can  only  be  introduced  by  making 
them  sensible  to  evils  appreciable  at  the  lower  stage.  But  at 
any  given  point  of  the  process  the  moral  law  implicitly  com- 
mands conduct  for  the  realisation  of  which  an  improvement  of 
the  whole  order,  and  therefore  an  elevation  of  the  moral  sense 
itself,  is  commanded.  The  lower  natures  can  only  be  reached 
by  motives  suitable  to  their  application ;  but  in  commanding 
conduct  upon  the  lower  ground  the  moralist  is  already  favour- 
ing the  introduction  of  the  higher  motive,  and  the  actual 
moral  sense  is  thus,  in  a  progressive  society,  always  in  advance 
of  the  actual  standard  of  the  average  individual.  He  can 
see,  even  from  his  own  point  of  view,  the  advantages  of  a 
better  morality,  though  it  has  not  yet  become  a  principle  of 
his  own  character. 

21.  The  general  condemnation  of  utilitarian  morality  as 
degrading  springs  partly  from  another  cause.  I  mean  that 
the  utilitarian  is  naturally  the  man  who  is  beyond  all  things 
anxious  to  have  his  feet  on  solid  earth,  and  to  assign  definite 
and  tangible  grounds  for  every  conclusion.  He  is  a  realist 
as  opposed  to  an  idealist,  prosaic  rather  than  poetical,  or 
belongs  to  the  school  which  has  more  affinity  for  the  mater- 
ialist than  the  idealist  conclusions.  This  is,  of  course,  unde- 
niable, and  utilitarian  codes  of  morality  are  spun  of  coarser 
if  more  enduring  materials  than  those  of  the  antagonistic 
systems.  But  this  follows  from  the  temperament  rather 
than  from  the  principles  of  the  moralist.  The  same  disposi- 
tion which  makes  him  a  utilitarian  leads  him  to  assign  com- 
paratively little  importance  to  the  kinds  of  happiness  which 


376  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

imply  a  poetic  imagination  or  a  delight  in  the  ideal  world. 
But  though  he  is  liable  to  this  error^  it  is  an  error  upon  his 
own  principles.  In  whatever  degree  the  poetic  faculties  give 
real  pleasure^  he  must  admit  that  pleasure  into  his  calculus ; 
in  whatever  degree  they  are  really  conducive  to  the  eleva- 
tion or  development  of  the  race,  he  must  admit  that  they 
are  as  "useful"  as  the  humbler  instincts.  The  facts  must 
decide,  and  there  is  no  a  priori  reason  for  assuming  that 
they  will  give  a  humiliating  decision,  though  it  is  easy  enough 
to  see  why  the  intellectual  temperament,  favourable,  as  specu- 
lation has  hitherto  been  conducted,  to  the  less  idealist  view, 
should  also  incline  a  man  to  put  what  we  may  simply  call  a 
lower  interpretation  upon  the  facts.    But  this  is  parenthetical. 

IV.  Extrinsic  Morality. 

32.  The  argument  thus  brings  us  to  another  set  of  criti- 
cisms upon  utilitarian  theories.  The  utilitarian  takes  what 
I  have  called  the  external  view  of  morality;  he  judges 
from  consequences  conclusively,  and  says  that  conduct  is 
good  or  bad  conclusively  as  it  produces  a  balance  of  happi- 
ness or  misery,  and  this  irrespectively  of  the  motives  of  the 
agent.  The  motive,  therefore,  to  moral  conduct  is  always 
extrinsic.  It  is  not  in  itself  bad,  but  bad  as  producing  some 
other  effect.  This  doctrine  takes  various  shapes  with  differ- 
ent utilitarian  moralists,  and  if  it  were  my  purpose  to  criti- 
cise their  doctrine  exhaustively,  I  should  have  to  consider 
precisely  the  meaning  of  some  of  the  terms  employed — as, 
for  example,  of  the  distinction  between  an  act  and  its  con- 
sequences— for  the  meaning  seems  to  fluctuate  considerably. 
I  have,  however,  virtually  given  my  answer  in  defending  mv 
own  view,  and  I  will  therefore  be  content  with  indicating 
the  general  nature  of  the  divergence.  I  have  said,  in  the 
first  place,  that  a  law  becomes  truly  moral  when  it  can  be 
stated  in  the  internal  form.  Morality  is  the  conduct  of  the 
truly  moral  man,  and  immorality  the  conduct  which  is 
intrinsically  repugnant  to  him.     But  here  is  the  ambiguity 


EXTRINSIC  MORALITY.  377 

which  I  have  already  tried  to  explain.  The  utilitarian 
asserts  that  there  is  no  such  thing  as  a  love  of  virtue  "for 
its  own  sake."  In  one  sense  of  the  words  I  entirely  agree 
with  him ;  in  another,  I  should  say  that  there  is  no  real 
virtue  at  all  unless  it  imply  a  love  of  virtue  for  its  own  sake. 
I  agree  with  the  utilitarian  in  so  far  as  I  deny  that  con- 
science is  a  separate  facultv,  instead  of  a  mode  of  reaction  of 
the  whole  character.  If,  therefore,  there  is  any  class  of  con- 
duct which  has  no  relation  whatever  to  happiness  of  any 
other  kind,  which  does  not  gratify  or  repel  other  instincts 
than  the  conscience,  it  can  have  no  interest  for  the  con- 
science either.  Virtuous  actions  are  not  a  separate  class  of 
actions,  and  actions  which  have  no  effect  upon  happiness 
are  for  that  reason  morally  indifferent.  On  the  other  hand, 
it  is  equally  true  that  a  man  is  virtuous  only  if  the  bare  fact 
tnat  an  action  is  right  is  to  him  a  motive  for  acting  in  that 
way,  and  he  is  virtuous  in  proportion  as  it  is  always  a  suffi- 
cient motive.  This,  again,  is  possible  because  the  virtuous 
man  means  simply  the  man  who  corresponds  to  the  best 
social  type,  and  will  therefore  act  on  all  occasions  in  con- 
formity with  the  character  so  defined.  It  is  not  because  all 
virtuous  actions  have  one  definite  end,  which  end  is  itself 
something  different  from  virtue,  but  because  all  virtuous 
action  implies  action  in  conformity  with  certain  instincts 
which  have  become  organic  in  the  virtuous  man.  To  say, 
then,  to  such  a  man,  "  This  is  right,"  is  the  same  thing  as  to 
say,  "This  satisfies  your  instincts;"  or,  in  other  words,  it 
states  a  sufficient  inducement  to  the  corresponding  action. 

23.  The  utilitarian  statement  represents  this  by  defining 
moral  conduct  as  that  which  has  for  its  end  the  production 
of  happiness,  irrespectively  of  its  quality.  To  love  virtue 
for  its  own  sake  would  be  to  love  the  means  irrespectively 
of  the  end,  which  would  be  clearly  irrational,  though  not 
impossible.  But  upon  the  view  of  the  egoistic  utilitarian, 
it  seems  that  all  truly  virtuous  conduct  must  be  placed  in 
this  predicament.  He  explains  the  origin  of  the  benevolent 
impulses  through  association  in  such  a  way  as  to  destroy 


378  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

their  reality.  The  typical  example  is  that  of  the  miser,  who, 
from  loving  money  as  a  means  for  promoting  pleasure,  comes 
to  love  it  as  an  end,  and  even  when  possession  implies  a 
sacrifice  of  pleasure.  Similarly,  it  is  suggested,  we  associate 
pleasant  sensations  with  certain  persons,  and  we  love  them 
as  the  cause  of  those  sensations.  If,  however,  love  thus 
explained  should  prompt  us  to  act  in  such  a  way  as  to 
sacrifice  our  pleasure  for  the  good  of  others,  we  should  be 
unreasonable  in  the  same  sense  as  the  miser.  We  should  be 
applying  a  rule  in  a  case  where  it  was  plainly  inapplicable, 
and  using  means  for  an  end  in  a  case  where  we  knew  that 
they  would  not  produce  that  end.  Association  in  this  sense 
implies  illusion ;  and  the  more  reasonable  we  become,  the 
more  we  should  deliver  ourselves  from  the  bondage  of  such 
errors. 

24.  This  view  seems  to  include  an  imperfect  statement  of 
one  side  of  the  truth.  I  cannot  admit  its  accuracy,  indeed, 
even  in  regard  to  our  old  friend  the  miser.  As  a  rule,  it 
seems  to  me,  the  man  who  really  desires  money  as  a  means 
to  enjoyment  is  more  likely  to  become  a  spendthrift  than  a 
miser.  He  will  be  so  eager  for  present  enjoyment  as  to 
neglect  provisions  for  future  enjoyment.  The  miser,  as  I 
should  say,  is  in  the  normal  case  a  man  who  desires  money 
in  order  to  guard  against  the  misery  of  poverty  and  depend- 
ence. His  motive  is  not  the  positive  desire  for  pleasure,  but 
its  negative  side,  the  dread  of  actual  suffering.  When  his 
desire  for  money  becomes  excessive,  he  is  still  guarding 
against  the  same  evil,  though  he  is  taking  exaggerated  pre- 
cautions. He  resembles  a  man  who  is  afraid  of  falling  over  a 
cliff',  and  who  therefore  will  not  go  within  a  hundred  yards, 
though  in  fact  he  would  be  equally  safe  within  a  yard  of  the 
edge.  He  reasons  badly,  therefore,  in  so  far  as  his  terrors  are 
extravagant.  But  the  motive  is  not  necessarily  changed  in 
character.  There  is  always  a  danger  of  loss  and  poverty,  though 
the  danger  may  be  so  small  that  a  wise  man  would  not  consider 
it.  The  motives  of  the  miser  may  be  changed  in  other  direc- 
tions.    He  loses  all  relish  for  pleasures  which  he  has  never 


EXTRINSIC  MORALITY.  379 

allowed  himself  to  ciijoy,and  many  tastes  havetbus  been  stifled 
in  the  germ.  And,  on  the  other  side,  the  various  activities 
necessary  for  the  acquisition  and  preservation  of  money 
have  become  pleasant  to  him,  as  any  mode  of  activity  v^hich 
gives  room  for  skill,  forethought,  and  a  discharge  of  energy 
may  be  really  pleasant.  There  is,  for  example,  a  pleasure  in 
skilful  speculation,  as  there  is  a  pleasure  in  the  game  of  chess, 
abstractedly  from  any  consideration  whatever  of  an  ^^end." 
It  is  only  when  we  assume  that  all  activity  is  conditioned  by 
the  prospect  of  the  pleasure  attainable  at  the  end  that  we 
are  forced  into  the  supposition  of  a  confusion  between  means 
and  ends.  Every  kind  of  activity  has  its  own  pleasure,  as 
affording  a  means  for  the  discharge  of  energy  or  escape  from 
ennui.  The  miser  who  finds  pleasure  in  the  act  of  money- 
making  need  not  be  unreasonable  even  if  he  proposes  to 
make  no  use  of  the  money.  The  money-making  is  in  itself 
pleasant,  and  pleasant  because  it  is  a  regulated  mode  of 
activity  which  gives  occupation  to  a  variety  of  faculties. 

35.  Now  if  we  compare  this  case  with  that  of  benevolent 
action,  we  may  see  what  is  really  implied.  It  is  doubtless 
true  that  we  may  learn  to  love  our  neighbours  because  they 
have  contributed  to  our  pleasures.  The  child,  in  whom  sympa- 
thy and  intelligence  is  still  dormant,  may  thus  regard  its  mother 
as  the  source  of  a2:reeable  sensations.  More  ffenerallv,  as  I 
have  argued,  moral  progress  may  proceed  in  an  analogous  way. 
We  mav  become  interested  in  the  welfare  of  our  neio-hbours 

O 

because  our  interests  are  identical ;  and  this  observation  mav 
convince  us  that  the  identity  extends  to  cases  in  which  the 
direct  sympathy  would  not  dictate  benevolent  action.  When 
this  community  of  action  has  once  been  established  in  any 
degree,  there  is  room  for  the  play  of  sympathy.  The  happi- 
ness of  others,  so  soon  as  we  can  appreciate  it,  becomes  an 
end  in  itself;  but  this  sympathy  is  enabled  to  expand  because, 
previously  to  its  existence,  the  rule  of  conduct  which  it  pre- 
scribes has  already  been  adopted  from  different  motives.  The 
external  rule  then  passes  into  the  internal,  and  genuine  and 
intrinsic  moral  motives  become  possible.     Hence  the  associa- 


38o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tion  theory  has  a  certain  truth  within  its  province,  but  it 
does  not  by  any  means  account  for  the  whole  phenomenon, 
and  it  fails  just  at  the  point  where  true  morality  begins:  it 
may  explain,  that  is,  why  we  first  take  a  pleasure  in  the 
welfare  of  others;  it  may  in  some  cases  even  explain  why, 
though  still  selfish,  we  act  unselfishly,  and  so  far,  in  this  case, 
unreasonably.  It  is  possible,  too,  that,  as  in  the  case  of  avarice, 
the  various  kinds  of  activity  called  forth  by  conduct  which 
does  good  to  others  becomes  in  itself  pleasant.  A  man,  for 
example,  may  learn  to  take  pleasure  in  surgical  operations, 
though  without  any  genuine  sympathy  for  his  patients;  he 
may  even  be  externally  unselfish  to  the  point  of  heroism,  and 
sacrifice  his  life  to  his  pursuit,  as  another  man  might  sacrifice 
his  in  the  pursuit  of  some  purely  selfish  and  even  degradino; 
pleasure.  The  conditions  of  life,  which  force  every  member 
of  a  society  to  conform  in  some  degree  to  the  interests 
of  others,  and  which  therefore  involve  a  considerable  con- 
formity between  the  egoistic  and  altruistic  sentiments,  may 
for  that  reason  generate  a  kind  of  fictitious  benevolence,  a 
pleasure  in  conduct  which  has  in  fact  good  results  to  others, 
even  though  the  contemplation  of  those  results  affords  no 
pleasure.  Upon  this  view,  however,  sympathy  is  so  far 
unreasonable.  Directly  it  prompts  to  self-sacrifice  we  are  the 
slaves  of  sophistry  or  a  misleading  association.  Upon  my 
theory,  on  the  contrary,  sympathy  is  a  real  motive  implied  in 
all  true  morality,  though  it  can  only  operate  as  some  germ  of 
reason  becomes  developed,  and  begins  to  operate  within  the 
line  already  laid  down  by  the  non-sympathetic  customs. 


V.  Expedienaj. 

26.  The  utilitarian,  therefore,  who  is  also  an  egoist,  docs,  as 
I  hold,  deprive  morality  of  its  essential  meaning,  and  the  as- 
sumption that  the  principle  of  association  explains  all  modes  of 
thought  and  feeling  lends  itself  to  that  mode  of  regardino;  the 
facts.  The  utilitarian,  however,  is  more  naturally  a  genuine 
believer  in  altruism  :  that  belief  fulls  in  with  the  theory  that 


EXPEDIENCY.  381 

the  criterion  of  morality  is  the  tendency  of  conduct  to  promote 
happiness,  for  this  tendency  then  corresponds  to  a  genuine 
motive.     We   have,   however,   still   to   inquire   whether  the 
morality  thus  constructed  has  sufficient  stability,  or  whether 
it  may  not  be  rijihtlv  condemned  as  encourao"ina:  mere  "ex- 
pediency."     This  is  perhaps  the  most  frequent  line  of  attack 
upon  utilitarian  systems.     Tiie  force,  indeed,  of  the  criticism 
depends  to  a  great  extent  upon  the  assumption  that  expe- 
diency is  another  name  for  selfishness.     When  a  man  breaks 
a  particular  moral  rule — that  of  truthfulness,  for  examj)le — 
because  he  thinks  that  a  lie  will  do  more  good  than  harm,  we 
accuse   him  of  acting  upon  principles  of  expediency.     But 
there  is  certainly  a  wide  moral  difference  between  the  cases 
in  which  the  lie  is  prompted  simply  by  the  consideration  that 
a  lie   will   be   useful   to   the   agent,   or  that  in  which  it  is 
prompted   by   the   genuine   belief   that   it    will    increase    the 
general  happiness.     We  are  apt  to  confound  the  two  cases, 
and  to  saddle  the  man  who  breaks  the  rule  upon  any  con- 
sideration with  all  the  blame  due  to  the  selfish  consideration. 
The  inference  may  be  frequently  correct  in  fact;  expediency 
may,  in  point  of  fact,  be  generally  used  as  a  cloak  for  selfish- 
ness;  or,  which  is  probably  nearer  the  truth,  a  man  who 
allows  himself  to  break  rules  for  the  good  of  others  may  be 
strongly  tempted  to  break  them  for  his  own  private  good  at 
the  expense  of  others.     Still,  a  man  who  should  really  act 
upon  the  altruistic  version  of  the  utilitarian  criterion  might 
be  shifty  and  unreliable  in  his  conduct,  but  could  not  pro- 
perly  be   called    selfish.      His  conduct   would    generally   be 
moral,  thou<rh   he  mioht  diverge  in  certain  cases  from  the 
moral  law. 

27.  What,  then,  is  implied  by  the  supremacy  of  the 
moral  law,  or  autonomy  of  the  conscience?  If  there  is  any 
rule  of  conduct  which  can  be  laid  down  as  absolute,  it  must 
at  once  decide  the  morality  of  the  conduct  affected  in  every 
conceivable  case.  If  we  admit  of  any  criterion  outside  of 
morality,  it  must  limit  the  sway  of  the  moral  law.  If  the 
true  test  be  the  utilitarian,  then  we  nmst  either  admit  that 


382  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

lying,  for  example,  is  right  when  it  increases  happiness,  or  we 
must  prove  that  lying  never  increases  happiness.     The  utili- 
tarian   admits    that   any   such    proof  is  impossible.     There 
may  be  cases  in  which  a  lie  will  do  more  good  than  harm  ; 
therefore  "  Lie  not"  cannot  be  an  absolute  law.      He  says, 
indeed^  that  we  are  forced   to  act  for  the  most   part   upon 
probabilities,  and   that   experience   shows  probability  to   be 
enormously  in  favour  of  truth-telling.    But  the  question  occurs, 
Why  should  we  act  upon  this  general  probability  without 
reference  to  the  particular  circumstances  ?     The  general  rule 
is  not  properly  "  supreme"  over  the  particular,  and  it  is  hard  to 
see  how  it  can  be  said  to  override  it.     Take  any  ordinary  case 
of  prudence.     I  know  that,  as  a  rule,  it  is  imprudent,  sav,  to 
trust  monev  to  a  stranger.     That  is  a  sufficient  guide  for  me 
if  the  only  thing  that  I  know  about  a  man  is  the  bare  fact 
that  he  is  a  stranger.     It  holds,  ao-ain,   so  lonf  as  I  know 
nothing  to  take  him  out  of  the  class  as  an  exceptional  person. 
But  directly  I  do  know  something  which  takes  him  out  of 
that  class,  I  must,  if  I  am  reasonable,  modify  my  judgment 
accordingly.     The  only  rule  that  can  be  given  is  to  act  upon 
the  whole  probabilities  of  the  case.     This,  of  course,  includes 
a  reference  to  the  general  probability  which  arises  from  the 
fact  that  the  man  is  a  stranger,  but  it   does   not  give  any 
absolute  predominance  to  the   rule.      I   must  take  it  into 
council,  but  not  obey  it  as  a  master.    My  ground  of  action  in 
any  particular  case  must  be  my  judgment  of  the  probability, 
which  will  be  guided  partly  by  reference  to  the  general  rule 
that  strangers  are  not  to  be  trusted,  but   also  by  reference 
to  any  other  rule  which  may  tend  to  show  that  this  particular 
strano-er  is  trustworthy.     I  have  then  said  evervthino;  when 
I  have  said,  "Act  upon  the  probabilities,"  for  that  of  course 
includes  a  reference  to  every  applicable  principle  of  judgment. 
Why  should  I  not  say  the  same  in  moral  questions  ?     Should 
not  the  rule  be,  "  Act  in  that  way  which  will  probably  pro- 
duce the  greatest  happiness,"  where  the  "  probably  "  of  course 
includes  a  reference  to  general  induction  from  similar  cases 
already  observed,  but   regards  it  only  as  an   induction,   not 


EXPEDIENCY.  383 

as  an  infalible  test?  And  if  this  be  so,  how  can  the  moral  law- 
be  regarded  as  absolute  and  supreme?  It  is  nothing  but  a 
useful  collection  of  precedents  tending  to  guide  our  judgment 
in  particular  cases. 

28.  This,  it  is  felt,  is  a  dangerous  principle.  7"he  utilitarian, 
however,  diminishes  the  importance  of  his  attack  upon  the 
supremacy  of  the  moral  rule  by  obvious  considerations;  that 
is  to  say,  he  insists  upon  the  extent  of  our  ignorance  as  to  the 
consequences,  and  upon  the  danger  of  trusting  ourselves. 
The  pleas  must  be  admitted  to  have  considerable  force ;  but 
they  seem  to  leave  the  difficulty  in  some  undefined  degree. 
For,  in  the  first  place,  however  great  the  importance  of  trust- 
ing to  the  general  rule,  it  cannot  be  denied  that  we  are  able  to 
make  some  estimate  of  the  consequences,  or  otherwise  we 
could  not  make  the  necessary  induction ;  and  thus,  again,  it 
must  be  admitted  that,  after  making  all  allowance  for  our 
ignorance,  the  question  is  still  essentially  one  of  probabilities, 
and  the  presumption  in  favour  of  the  beneficial  consequences 
of  certain  particular  lies  may  be  enormous.  And,  in  the  next 
place,  the  danger  of  trusting  ourselves  is  undoubtedly  very 
great;  and  yet  it  is  a  danger  from  which  we  cannot  shrink. 
The  danger  is,  in  fact,  a  danger  of  misinterpreting  the  prece- 
dents which  we  have  set.  The  general  rule  must  be,  not  that 
lies  are  immoral,  but  that  mischievous  lies  are  immoral.  Why, 
then,  should  it  be  supposed  that  we  should  be  more  in  danger  of 
tellins;  a  mischievous  lie  because  we  have  told  a  beneficial  lie? 
If  we  do  so,  we  are  fallina;  into  an  error  of  reasoninc;.  We 
are  holding  fast  to  the  accident  and  dropping  the  substance. 
Why  should  not  the  fact  that  we  have  acted  for  the  best  in 
one  case  determine  us  to  act  for  the  best  in  another,  although 
in  one  case  the  best  action  accidentally  involved  a  lie,  and  in 
the  other  accidentally  involved  truth-speaking?  Generally,  if 
the  promotion  of  the  general  happiness  is  the  sole  criterion, 
why  should  not  the  desire  for  general  happiness  be  the  sole 
motive  for  moral  conduct?  If  so,  can  we  properly  consider 
moral  rules  as  anything  more  than  formulae,  useful  in  calcula- 
ting the  probable  consequence  of  conduct  to  happiness,  but 


384  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

always  liable — like  any  other  empirical  formulae — to  be  over- 
ridden by  special  circumstances  ? 

29.  I  cannot,  upon  my  own  hypothesis,  meet  this  by  de- 
claring the  particular  moral  laws  to  be  absolute  and  supreme. 
The  attempt  to  do  so  only  leads  to  casuistry  of  the  objection- 
able kind.     Make  the  rule  against  Iving  absolute,  and  vou 
find    yourself  obliged  to  bring  the  particular  cases  under  a 
different  rule  by  some  device  analogous  to  a  legal  fiction,  and 
more  demoralising  than  an  open  declaration  that  the  moral 
law   is  not  to  be  always  observed.     Nor    can   I  accept  the 
statement  in  the  form  that  the  contingent  consequences  of 
an  action  must  always  be  set  aside.     It  seems  to  me  that  the 
known  consequences  of  an  action  must  always  be  relevant  to 
its  morality.     If  I  were  absolutely  certain  that  a  lie  would  do 
goodj  I  should  certainly  hesitate  before  speaking  the  truth, 
and  the  certainty  might  be  of  such  a  kind  as  to  make  me 
think  it  a  dutv  to  lie.     It  has  been  said  bv  moralists  that  a 
good  man  would  not  commit  the  most  venial  sin,  even  though 
the  consequences  of  his  virtuous  action  were  the  perishing  of 
all  mankind  in  torture.     The  statement  is  either  shockino-  or 
meanino-less.     I  can  conceive  of  no  action  which  would  not 
become  an  abominable  crime  by  the  simple  fact  of  its  entail- 
ing such  consequences,  and  of  no  crime  which   would  not 
become  an  imperative  dutv  if  it  evaded  them.      A  man  who 
saved  his  dirty  soul  at  such  a  price  would  deserve  damnation 
ten  times  over;  and  if  he  did  not  get  it,  I  should  not  regard 
his  deity  as  a  truly  moral  agent.     If,  on  the  other  hand,  the 
act   still    remained   virtuous,   it   could    only    be    because    we 
assume,  for  some  reason  or  other,  that  the  moral  action  has 
other  good  consequences — say   the  eternal  happiness  of  the 
agent — which    overbalance  the  evil  consequences.     In  that 
case  the  utilitarian  position  is  not  really  denied. 

30.  The  assertion  that  the  particular  moral  rules  are  not 
absolute  is  a  repetition  of  a  principle  already  laid  down.  It 
is  impossible  to  secure  more  than  an  approximate  coincidence 
between  the  external  and  the  internal  law.  However  closclv 
they  may,  and  frequently  do,  coincide,  it  is  always  (or  almost 


EXPEDIENCY.  385 

always)  possible  to  suggest  cases  in  which  they  diverge. 
Wherever  such  a  deviation  occurs,  the  true  moral  rule  must 
be  the  internal  rule.  Morality  is  essentially  a  determination 
of  character,  and  hence  wherever  adherence  to  a  fixed  rule 
implies  a  change  of  character,  or,  inversely,  the  persistency 
of  character  implies  a  breach  of  the  rule,  the  virtuous  man 
will  break  the  rule.  Hence,  again,  the  attempt  to  secure  an 
absolute  and  immutable  moral  law  in  its  external  shape 
must  be  illusory.  The  moral  law  can  be  stated  uncondition- 
ally when  it  is  stated  in  the  form  "Be  this,"  but  not  when 
stated  in  the  form  "Do  this."  We  may  say  without  any 
qualification  whatever  that  the  good  man  must  be  merciful, 
just,  truthful,  temperate,  courageous,  and  so  forth  ;  but  for 
the  very  reason  that  the  law  is  in  this  sense  absolute,  it  can- 
not be  absolute  as  prescribing  external  modes  of  conduct. 
Hence,  again,  whatever  the  difficulty  of  deciding  in  particular 
cases  what  is  the  rio;ht  sense  of  conduct,  we  have  a  definite 
principle,  and  therefore  a  fixed  rule,  though  not  always  an 
easily  discoverable  rule.  The  truly  virtuous  man  is  the  typical 
man  whose  character  conforms  to  the  conditions  of  social 
vitality.  The  question  what  is  right  is  in  all  cases  equivalent 
to  the  question  what  the  right-minded  man  would  do,  sup- 
posing him  of  course  to  be  fully  informed,  and  to  reason  cor- 
rectly from  the  facts.  In  nine  hundred  and  ninety-nine  cases 
out  of  a  thousand  he  will  act  in  conformity  with  the  ordinary 
moral  rule,  say,  of  speaking  the  truth.  We  may  say  absolutely 
that  the  moral  man  must  be  thoroughly  trustworthy.  Wher- 
ever trustworthiness  implies  truth-telling,  he  will  tell  the  truth ; 
but  if,  in  any  particular  case,  the  same  character  implies 
lying,  he  will  lie,  and  will  lie  like  a  man,  that  is,  without 
trying  to  conceal  from  himself  by  any  shuffle  of  casuistry 
the  true  nature  of  his  conduct.  If  in  this  sense  morality  in- 
cludes an  element  of  expediency,  not,  that  is,  in  the  sense  of 
denying  that  there  is  a  rule  of  conduct  in  this  case  as  in  all 
others,  but  in  the  sense  that  the  rule  may  fail  in  certain 
cases  definable  in   principle,    but  not  precisely  ascertainable 

by  any  definite  external  indications.     Normally,  any  deflec- 

a  B 


386  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

tion  from  the  rule  implies  a  deficiency  in  some  good  quality. 
In  certain  very  rare  cases  it  implies  the  presence  of  good 
qualities.  In  the  latter  case  the  conduct  is  right,  as  in  the 
former  it  is  wrong. 

31.  To  apply  this  more  specifically  to  the  problems  which 
actually  present  themselves  would  be  to  write  a  treatise  upon 
casuistry ;    but  one  or  two  remarks  may  clear  the  general 
principle.     It  must  be  observed,  in  the  first  place,  that  many 
so-called  problems  of  casuistry  are  not  properly  moral  pro- 
blems at  all.      In  many  cases  we  must  admit  that  the  mor- 
ality of  a  given  course  of  conduct  depends  upon  its  tendency 
to  produce  happiness.      Ceteris  paribus,  I  must  do  that  which 
will  give  most  pleasure  to  others.     But,   again,   to   decide 
what  will  give  most  pleasure  to  others  is  often  a  very  diffi- 
cult quci^tion,  which  admits  of  being  decided  only  by  tact 
or  instinct.     We  must  judge  in  most  practical  cases  of  any 
difficulty  by  probability,  or,   in  other  words,   by  guessing. 
When  we  really  believe  that  we  shall  do  most  good  by  a 
certain  course  of  conduct,  that  conduct  is  so  far  right ;  and 
here  the  moral  rule  is  plain,  however  difficult  the  application. 
Again,  many  casuistical  problems  turn  upon  such  questions 
as  the  nature  of  some  implied  contract.     It  is  a  question  of 
law  what  rights   I  have  created  by  marrying,  or  accepting 
an  office,  or  making  some  commercial  bargain.     Morality  in 
such  cases  may  simply  order  me  to  keep  my  contract,  what- 
ever it  may  be,  and  the  "  whatever  "  is  to  be  decided  by  the 
lawyers.     And  this,  again,  leads  to  another  distinction  often, 
as  I  have  said,  overlooked.     The  problem  is  frequently  stated 
ambiguously,  and  may  either  be,  "  Does  the  actually  existing 
standard  of  morality  forbid  a  certain  action? "  or  it  maybe,  "Is 
it  desirable  that  the  action  should  be  forbidden  by  morality?  " 
The  moralist,  like  the  lawyer,  is  apt  to  conceal  the  fact  that 
he  is  reallv  making  new  laws  under  the  pretext  of  enlarging 
the  old.     In  reality,  he  is  trying  to  frame  a  more  precise  rule 
than  the  one  which  has  hitherto  been  accepted.     It  would 
be  better  frankly  to  admit  the  clear  nature  of  the  case,  be- 
cause it  would  then  be  easier  to  argue  upon  the  principles  to 


EXPEDIENCY.  387 

be  applied.  Upon  my  theory,  the  method  is  dcfmcd  by  the 
doctrine  already  laid  down.  A  certain  kind  of  conduct,  we 
suppose,  has  hitherto  been  regarded  as  indifferent.  There  is 
no  established  rule  for  assuming  whether  a  good  man  would 
or  would  not  act  in  that  way.  To  decide,  then,  whether  the 
conduct  is  right  or  wrong  is  virtually  to  add  a  new  moral 
precept;  and  that  is  implicitly  to  inquire  whether  the  adop- 
tion of  the  new  principle  would,  on  the  utilitarian  showing, 
do  more  good  or  harm  ;  or,  more  accurately,  according  to  me, 
to  ask  whether  the  incorporation  of  this  rule  in  the  moral 
system  would  imply  a  closer  approximation  to  the  solution 
of  the  great  problem  of  social  utility.  Of  course,  the  ques- 
tion of  the  affinity  of  this  proposed  rule  to  previously  accepted 
principles  will  throw  light  upon  the  whole  problem;  but  we 
need  not  conceal  the  fact  that  we  are  really  trvin"-  to  extend 
and  amend  these  principles,  and  not  sim pi v  judging  new  cases 
by  the  old  principle.  Here,  therefore,  the  ultimate  difficulty 
is  still  a  question  of  fact — whether,  namely,  social  develop- 
ment implies  the  adoption  of  the  new  rule  sugcrested  ? 

32.  We  may  now  come  to  the  proper  casuistical  questions 
where  there  is  a  real  difficulty  in  interpreting  the  law.  If  it 
is  ever  right  to  tell  a  lie,  when  is  it  right?  What  are  the 
principles  by  which  we  must  judge?  The  utilitarian  prin- 
ciple seems  to  suggest  the  answer,  Whenever  the  probabilities 
are  in  favour  of  a  lie  doing  more  good  than  harm.  The 
morality  of  this  answer  depends  partly  upon  the  question, 
What  are  the  "consequences"  to  be  admitted  as  relevant? 
May  I  take  into  account  in  my  calculation  the  pain  which 
the  bare  telling  of  a  lie  gives  to  a  man  accustomed  to  speak 
the  truth  ?  Or  shall  we  say  that  as  this  pain  depends  upon 
a  fallacy  of  association,  we  ought  to  accustom  ourselves  to  lie, 
and  so  to  find  lying  painless,  whenever  we  see  a  balance  of 
good  consequences  in  its  favour?  There  can  be  no  doubt 
that  such  a  principle  strikes  most  people  as  immoral.  The 
actual  standard  of  morality,  whatever  its  justification,  con- 
demns lying  in  almost  all  cases,  and  only  admits  of  doubtful 
exceptions  w^here  the  balance  is  seen  to  be  overpoweringly  in 


388  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

favour  of  a  lie,  such  as  the  famous  case  of  giving  informa- 
tion to  a  murderer.  It  seems,  then,  that  in  this  case  the 
average  moral  judgment  does  not  conform  precisely  to  the 
utilitarian  standard.  It  condemns  useful  lies,  though  we 
may  admit  that  there  is  a  distinction  between  the  cases  of  a 
lie  which  is  useful  to  the  ao-ent  and  that  which  is  useful  to 

O 

the  world  at  large.  The  former  kind  of  lie  would,  of  course, 
be  condemned  by  the  utilitarians,  in  cases  at  least  where  the 
good  to  the  agent  is  counterbalanced  by  evil  to  others; 
whilst,  in  regard  to  the  latter,  the  moral  standard  would  seem 
to  be  rather  unsettled,  and  people  are  generally  inclined  to 
evade  a  solution  by  denying  that  the  case  ever  occurs,  or  by 
saying  that  it  occurs  so  rarely  as  not  to  be  worth  '  consi- 
deration. There  is  a  strons;  feeling  that  it  is  dancrerous  to 
consider  such  facts  closely,  as  an  admission  of  a  possibility 
of  exceptions  tends  to  increase  the  freedom  of  making 
exceptions, 

^^.  Now  I  certainly  think  that  the  utilitarian  principle 
does  not  explain  the  whole  case.  The  moral  rule  is  formed 
in  a  great  degree,  as  I  have  argued,  by  a  utilitarian  method; 
that  is,  by  observing  the  bad  and  good  consequences  of  certain 
kinds  of  conduct.  But  morality  includes  more  than  this,  as 
the  moral  sense  is  the  product  of  the  whole  social  development, 
and  therefore  of  the  development  of  social  instincts  by  other 
processes  than  that  of  direct  calculation.  The  whole  system 
of  instincts  must  be  such  as  are  implied  in  a  healthful  social 
growth,  but  the  sentiment  may  justify  itself  by  being  actually 
useful  instead  of  being  generated  from  a  perception  of  utility. 
Hence,  as  I  think,  the  true  analogv  must  be  found  elsewhere. 
A  kind  of  moral  sentiment,  as  I  have  said,  grows  up  in  every 
social  organisation.  The  patriotic  spirit  of  a  citizen  or  the 
military  spirit  of  the  soldier  is  closely  related  to  the  moral 
sentiments  which  discharge  a  similar  function  in  tlie  "  social 
tissue."  Let  us  take,  for  example,  the  striking  case  of  the 
soldier's  devotion  to  his  regiment  or  army.  The  essential 
condition  of  military  excellence  is  the  spirit  of  subordination. 
The  ideal  soldier — the  man  who  realises  most  fully  the  condi- 


EXPEDIENCY.  389 

tions  of  military  life — is  one  who  obeys  orders  implicitly.  The 
code  of  mllltarv  duty  includes,  therefore,  as  Its  first  principle, 
the  great  rule,  "Do  as  you  are  bid."  In  almost  every  case, 
disobedience  to  orders  proceeds  from  laziness,  cowardice,  want 
of  patriotic  spirit,  or  some  quality  which  so  far  makes  a  man 
a  worse  soldier.  And  hence,  again,  the  rule  is  put  forth 
absolutely;  and  no  commander  would  endeavour  to  Impress 
upon  the  mind  of  a  subordinate  the  importance  of  sometimes 
disobeying  orders.  And  yet  it  is  plain  that  questions  may 
arise  in  this  capacity  which  are  precisely  analogous  to  the 
ordinary  problems  of  casuistry.  No  one  will  deny  that  the 
importance  of  implicit  obedience  is  founded  upon  the  directly 
utilitarian  consideration  that  obedient  soldiers  make  a  better 
armv ;  but  cases  occur  in  which  the  implicit  obedience 
produces  a  bad  effect.  When,  for  example,  the  Roman 
soldier  stood  at  his  post  at  Pompeii  to  be  overwhelmed  by 
the  eruption,  his  heroic  devotion  was  so  far  a  source  of  weak- 
ness to  the  armv.  Had  he  been  less  devoted,  the  army  would 
have  had  one  brave  soldier  (though  not  quite  so  brave  a 
soldier)  the  more.  Or  if  we  call  him  stupid,  we  must  then 
admit  that  superior  Intelligence  would  lead  him  In  this  instance 
to  break  a  law  unconditionally  laid  down.  Take,  again,  the 
opposite  case.  Nelson  won  several  victories  by  direct  insub- 
ordination, and  is  therefore  a  rather  awkward  precedent  for 
the  people  who  like  to  tell  us  that  to  learn  to  command 
we  should  first  learn  to  obey.  Nelson  clearly  failed  in  his 
dut)'-,  and  had  he  failed  in  his  venture  would  probably  have 
been  punished.  Was  he  right  or  wrong?  If  wrong,  it  is 
plain  that  he  would  in  fiict  have  been  a  less  efficient  com- 
mander for  having  a  stronger  sense  of  duty;  and  if  right, 
we  must  admit  that  a  man  may  be  right  sometimes  to  take 
the  law  into  his  own  hands.  The  most  reasonable  view 
is  probably  that  Nelson,  being  really  a  man  of  genius  and 
conscious  of  his  genius,  was  justified  in  acting  as  he  did.  He 
was  "justified,"  that  is,  in  this  sense,  that  his  action  proved 
him  to  be  a  more  efficient  commander  on  the  whole,  although 
his  case  cannot  be  made  into  a  precedent,  because  we  cannot 


390  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

say  what  constitutes  a  man  of  genius  or  suggest  any  satis- 
factory test  of  the  presence  of  genius. 

34.  Such  cases  may  of  course   be  multiphed  indefinitely, 
and  they  pass  imperceptibly  into  moral  problems.     The  prin- 
ciple upon  which  they  rest  is  apparently  simple.     It  is  essen- 
tial, that  is,  to  the  welfare  of  the  army,  that  a  certain  spirit 
of  discipline  should  be  generated.     The  stronger  it  is,  within 
certain  limits,   the  more   efficient  is   the  army.     An   army 
usually   composed   of  such   men   as   the    Pompeian   sentinel 
would  be  invincible  by  any  ordinary  foe.     In  certain  special 
cases  the  sentiment  thus  stimulated  produces  the  very  result 
against  which  it  is  a  safeguard  in  the  normal  case.     A  good 
soldier  sticks  to  his  post  or  his  colours  when  the  post  is  useless 
and  the  colours  represent  nothing  but  so  much  rag.     Still, 
as  a  rule,  the  danger  is  entirely  on  the  other  side,  and  we 
strengthen   the  motives  to   obedience  as  much  as   possible, 
leaving  it  to  the  occasional  man  of  genius  to  break  rules  on 
his  own  responsibility.     We  tacitly  admit  that  a  breach  of 
rules  mav  be  right  in  certain  very  rare  cases,  but  they  are 
cases  which  it  is  impossible  to  define  by  any  sufficient  criterion. 
They  must  spring  from  zeal,  not  from  the  absence  of  zeal, 
but  they  are  only  justifiable  by  self-conscious  genius,  w^hich 
unfortunately   has    a    strong   outward    resemblance    to    self- 
deceiving  folly.     Finally,  if  we  can  reckon  upon  more  intel- 
ligence In  the  man,  we  may  allow  a  greater  latitude.     We 
recoo-nlse  the  danger  of  maklmr  the  soldier  too  much  of  a 
machine,  and  we  try  to  allow  for  a  greater  latitude  of  indi- 
vidual action.     This,  indeed,  does  not  alter  the  general  prin- 
ciple of  obedience,  but  only  makes  the  particular  rules  less 
precise;    still,  as  stimulating  the   tendency  of  independent 
judgment,  it  probably  lowers  the  absolute  character  of  the 
disciplinary    rules;    the    obedience    is   no   longer    blind,   but 
includes  a  more  or  less  explicit  reference  to  the  end  for  which 
it  was  imposed. 

^^.  It  seems  to  me  that  the  same  principle  really  governs 
the  moral  case.  The  absoluteness  of  the  moral  law  does  in 
fact  rest  upon  the  principle  alleged  by  the  utilitarian,  namely, 


EXPEDIENCY.  391 

that  men  cannot  be  trusted,  and  should  not  trust  themselves. 
They  could  trust  themselves,  perhaps,  if  thev  always  reasoned 
rightly;  but  then  people  do  not  reason  rightly,  and  still  less, 
if  we  may  use  the  phrase,  do  our  emotions  reason  rightly. 
The  fact  may  be  regretted,  but  it  is  a  fact  which  it  is  idle  to 
neglect  in  morality,  which  is  meant  to  bind  men  as  they  are, 
not  for  men  of  some  ideal  but  hitherto  unapproachable  state. 
The  utilitarian  principle  of  acting  in  every  case  from  a  judg- 
ment of  the  probable  consequences  might  answer  at  a  time 
when  we  could  also  allow  every  soldier  in  our  army  to  act 
upon  his  own  judgment  as  to  running  away  and  fighting, 
because  we  could  trust  each  man  to  see  when  the  good  of 
the  army  required  him  to  run,  and  to  run  only  when  required 
by  the  good  of  the  army.  Till  that  time  arrives  we  cannot 
grant  a  liberty  which  is  liable  to  abuse.  There  are  moral 
precepts  which  clearly  await  such  a  process.  Why,  for 
example,  do  we  not  allow  life  to  be  taken  when  life  means 
continued  agony?  We  cannot  allow  it  because  we  cannot 
trust  the  persons  who  would  have  to  apply  it.  The  physician 
makes  it  an  absolute  rule  to  preserve  life  as  much  as  he  can, 
because,  if  he  once  admitted  any  other  consideration,  he  would 
open  the  door  to  innumerable  abuses.  That  is  a  plain,  and, 
as  I  think,  an  amply  sufficient  reason  for  maintaining  the 
rule,  and  so  far  deviating  from  the  utilitarian  method,  whicli 
would  prescribe  calculation  of  the  probabilities  for  each  par- 
ticular case.  We  cannot,  in  fact,  keep  up  the  value  of 
human  life  without  fostering  what  is  in  some  sense  a  super- 
stitious regard  for  life — a  tenderness  for  life  when  the  desira- 
bility of  life  has  disappeared,  and  so  far  a  kind  of  conduct 
which  may  be  called  unreasonable.  I  do  not  inquire  whether, 
as  a  matter  of  fact,  this  sentiment  is  not  encouraged  to  excess 
at  the  present  day;  but  the  justification  depends  upon  this 
principle,  and,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  upon  this  principle  alone, 
unless  we  resort  to  arbitrary  hypotheses  to  cover  an  unrea- 
soned prejudice. 

;^6.  If,  now,  we  suppose  that  a  man,  knowing  that  life 
meant  for  him  nothing  but  agony,  and  that  moreover  his  life 


392  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

could  not  serve  others,  and  was  only  giving  useless  pain  to 
his  attendants^  and  perhaps  involved  the  sacrifice  of  health  to 
his  wife  and  children,  should  commit  suicide,  what  ought  we 
to  think  of  him  ?  He  would,  no  doubt,  be  breaking  the 
accepted  moral  code;  but  why  should  he  not  break  it? 
Because  he  is  setting  a  bad  example?  Undoubtedly  that 
must  be  allowed  to  have  some  weight.  If  his  conduct  tended 
to  depress  the  general  estimate  of  the  value  of  life  below  the 
point  which  is  necessary  to  social  welfare,  he  is  so  far  setting 
a  bad  precedent — bad,  that  is,  in  so  far  as  it  is  likely  to  be 
abused.  In  conforming  to  the  law  he  is  making  himself  a 
martyr  to  the  general  welfare,  and  deserves  the  praise  of 
unselfishness.  But  if,  again,  he  knew  that  his  conduct 
could  not  have  this  effect,  as  in  a  case  where  he  might 
be  quite  certain  that  his  action  would  remain  unknown, 
what  harm  would  he  be  doing?  May  we  not  say  that  he  is 
acting  on  a  superior  moral  principle,  and  that  because  he  is 
clearly  diminishing  the  sum  of  human  misery?  It  is  impos- 
sible to  settle  the  case  in  concrete  instances,  because  there  is 
no  fixed  external  test.  The  conduct  may  spring  either  from 
cowardice  or  from  a  loftier  motive  than  the  ordinary,  and  the 
merit  of  the  action  is  therefore  not  determinable ;  but,  assu- 
ming the  loftier  motive,  I  can  see  no  ground  for  disapproving 
the  action  which  flows  from  it. 

37.  Briefly,  then,  if  conduct  be  such  as  to  increase  the 
actual  sum  of  happiness,  if  it  does  not  imply  a  defect  of 
altruism  in  the  agent,  and  if  it  be  such  as  not  to  set  a  bad 
precedent  either  to  ourselves  or  to  others,  I  do  not  see  in 
what  sense  it  is  morally  blameworthy.  To  adhere  to  the 
rule,  when  the  rule  clearly  does  not  apply,  is  not  to  be  moral, 
but  to  be  a  moral  pedant.  The  truth  is  simply  that  the  race 
must  form  its  moral  code  in  the  same  way  as  we  have  to 
stimulate  the  sense  of  discipline  in  an  army;  that  is,  we  have 
to  deal  with  human  beings  who  cannot  be  trusted  ;  we  have 
to  encourage  modes  of  feeling  which,  though  generally  of  the 
highest  value,  do  not  point  infallibly  to  that  kind  of  conduct 
which  is  most   productive   of  happiness;  we    have   to    take 


EXPEDIENCY.  393 

human  nature  in  the  rough,  and  to  give  external  rules  which 
do  not  formally  and  at  all  points  correspond  to  the  judgment 
which  would  be  passed  by  the  most  intelligent  and  sensitive 
of  the  species.  So  far  as  the  utilitarian  mode  of  reasoning 
tends  to  obscure  this  essential  fact,  it  may  be  rightly  con- 
demned because  liable  to  abuse;  but  it  is  possible  to  interpret 
the  utilitarian  principle  differently,  and  I  regard  it  as  in  any 
case  an  approximation  to  the  truth,  though  tending  perhaps 
to  a  certain  laxity  in  practice,  in  so  far  as  it  assumes  an  im- 
practicable nicety  in  the  application  of  the  criterion. 

38.  In  what  sense,  however,  can  the  theory  here  stated  be 
properly  stigmatised  as  a  doctrine  of  expediency  ?  To  act 
rightly,  I  say,  is  to  act  as  the  truly  moral  man  would  act; 
the  truly  moral  man  being  defined  by  his  fulfilment  of  the 
conditions  of  social  welfare.  He  has,  therefore,  certain 
qualities  which  may  be  called  absolutely  good ;  that  is,  that 
they  are  good  on  the  sole  assumption  of  a  certain  social  and 
individual  organisation.  They  imply,  again,  obedience  to 
the  established  moral  standard  in  almost  every  case.  The 
thoroughly  trustworthy  man  will  speak  the  truth  all  but  in- 
variably. But  in  certain  rare  cases,  the  internal  and  external 
laws  cease  to  coincide  absolutelv.  Now  in  such  cases  the 
ideal  or  thoroughly  moral  man  will  break  the  external  law, 
and  break  it  in  obedience  to  his  instinct.  He  must  trust  his 
instincts,  for  he  has  nothing  else  to  which  he  can  trust.  If, 
in  fact,  the  exceptions  to  the  law  admitted  of  being  definitelv 
formulated,  we  should  have  the  case  of  a  new  moral  law.  The 
rule  would  no  longer  be,  "  Speak  the  truth,"  but  "  Speak  the 
truth  under  such  and  such  circumstances."  We  miirht  then 
have  some  difficult  questions  as  to  the  rightness  of  obeying 
the  recognised  law,  or  obeying  the  law  which  is  still  strug- 
gling for  recognition.  On  our  hypothesis,  the  difficulty  is 
that  the  problem  has  to  be  solved  without  any  fixed  test  to 
go  by.  Still  the  difficulty  is  essentially  the  same.  The  man 
has  to  act  upon  his  instinctive  perception  that  in  this  case 
the  moral  law  is  defective.  But  to  say  that  he  must  trust 
his  instinct  is  not  to  say  that  whatever  his  instinct   tells 


394  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

him  will  be  right.     It  is  simply  that  in  certain  cases  the 
refined  and  well-informed  instinct  outruns  the  definite  and 
assignable  formula.     He  is  the  final  court  of  appeal,  but  not, 
therefore,  above  the  law.     The  ear  of  the    musician  may- 
judge  of  discords  and  harmonies  too  fine  to  be  measured  by 
mathematical  instruments.     He  will  accept  the  general  rules, 
but  will  apply  them  with  greater  severity  than  any  mechani- 
cal contrivance  can  sufficiently  test.     In  the  same  way,  the 
man  of  fine  moral  taste  has  to  solve  problems  too  delicate 
for  the  coarser  rules  which  serve  for  everyday  life ;  not  be- 
cause he  despises  those  rules,  but  because  he  has  a  keener 
sense  of  their  true  value.     Some  of  the  noblest  actions  re- 
corded have  generally  been  where  a  man  has  broken  with 
the  accepted  code  of  steadygoing  respectable  moralists ;  but 
the  Tightness  or  wrongness  of  his  conduct  is  still  amenable 
to  a  test,  which,  though  only  implicit,  is  as  valid  and  fixed 
as  any  other.     The  exception  to  the  law  must  always  itself 
imply  a  law.     It  must  embody  some  general  principle,  though 
the  principle  cannot  be  absolutely  laid  down  in  particular 
cases  j  for  the  general  principle,  briefly  stated,  must  be  this, 
namely,  that  the  conduct  in  question  would  be  commanded 
by  a  higher  code  of  morality,  and  by  ''  higher"  I  mean  such 
a  code  as  would  be  obtained  by  a  general  increase  of  social 
efficiency,  and  a  closer  approximation  to  an  adequate  solu- 
tion of  the  great  problem  of  life.     The  problem,  therefore, 
just  noted  must  always  occur,  namely,  whether  I  ought  to 
act  upon  a  code  which  is  not  yet  recognised  by  the  accepted 
morality,  and  which   cannot  be  recognised  on    account  of 
human   stupidity  and   insensibility.     That  question,  again, 
can    only    be  answered    by  taking   into   account  the  total 
effect,  and  asking  whether  I  am  doing  more  good  by  my 
action    or  more    harm    by   setting  a  precedent  capable   of 
misinterpretation. 

39.  There  is,  then,  only  one  test  for  such  problems.  Does 
a  given  deviation  from  the  law  imply  an  advance  or  a  decline 
in  the  stage  of  moral  development?  Does  it  mean  that  the 
qualities  which  imply  conformity  to  the  moral  law  have  not 


EXPEDIENCY.  395 

been  sufficiently  organised  in  the  individual,  or  that  they 
have  become  a  part  of  his  nature  so  thoroughly  that  a  still 
finer  instinct  has  been  generated  which  transcends  him  ? 
That  is  a  question  of  fact,  which  it  is  generally  pretty  easy 
to  answer.  Most  conduct  which  offends  the  average  standard 
proceeds  from  some  vicious  motive.  But  we  cannot  deny 
that  there  are  examples  to  the  contrary;  and  we  must  admit 
this  freely  in  spite  of  any  taunts  as  to  expediency,  which 
really  confound  the  two  cases  or  overlook  the  undoubted 
importance  of  the  great  fact  upon  which  the  importance  of 
every  kind  of  general  rule  of  conduct  really  rests,  namely, 
that  men  are  in  fact  too  stupid,  too  wilful,  and  too  skilful 
in  self-deception  to  be  trusted  to  act  from  more  refined 
considerations. 

40.  The  answer  suggests  one  other  difficulty.  Let  us 
grant  that  the  moral  man  will  sometimes  break  a  law 
which  it  is  vitally  important  to  impress  upon  the  ordinary 
man.  Is  not  this  to  make  two  rules,  one  for  the  good  and 
one  for  the  bad  ?  Rather  it  is  to  assert  that  the  ordinary  man 
cannot  perform  the  same  action  as  the  good.  If  the  same 
internally,  it  is  not  really  the  same  because  it  does  not  imply 
the  same  motive.  But  to  make  a  general  rule  of  conduct  is  to 
make  a  law  which  can  be  brought  to  bear  upon  everybodv. 
A  moral  law,  as  here  stated,  seems  to  be  simply  a  description 
of  the  way  in  which  certain  people  will  act,  and  therefore 
to  have  no  meaning  for  others.  This  introduces,  therefore, 
the  problem  which  we  now  have  to  consider.  What  is  the 
relation  between  morality  and  happiness?  What,  in  the 
utilitarian  language,  is  the  general  sanction  of  morality  ?  A 
man  may  say,  "That  is  doubtless  'right,'  or,  in  other  words,  it 
is  what  a  virtuous  man  would  do ;  but  I  happen  not  to  be  a 
virtuous  man;  why  should  I  do  it?  "  How  are  we  to  answer 
him  ? 


(     396    ) 


CHAPTER  X. 

MORALITY   AND    HAPPINESS. 

I.   The  Sanction. 

I.  I  HAVE  thus  considered  the  problem,  What  is  the  cri- 
terion which,  upon  the  evolutionist  theory,  must  be  substi- 
tuted for  the  greatest-happiness  criterion  of  the  utilitarian  ? 
And  this  leads  naturally  to  the  problem  how,  upon  the  same 
theory,  must  the  utilitarian  sanction  be  modified?  Why 
should  a  man  be  virtuous?  The  answer  depends  upon  the 
answer  to  the  previous  question,  What  is  it  to  be  virtuous? 
If,  for  example,  virtue  means  all  such  conduct  as  promotes 
happiness,  the  motives  to  virtuous  conduct  must  be  all  such 
motives  as  impel  a  man  to  aim  at  increasing  the  sum  of 
happiness.  These  motives  constitute  the  sanction,  and  the 
sanction  may  be  defined  either  as  an  intrinsic  or  an  extrinsic 
sanction;  it  may,  that  is,  be  argued  either  that  virtuous  conduct 
invariably  leads  to  consequencee  which  are  desirable  to  every 
man,  whether  he  be  or  be  not  virtuous ;  or,  on  the  other 
hand,  that  virtuous  conduct  as  such,  and  irrespectively  of  any 
future  consequences,  makes  the  agent  happier.  Some  mo- 
ralists say  that  a  good  man  will  go  to  heaven  and  a  bad  man 
to  hell.  Others,  that  virtue  is  itself  heaven  and  vice  hell. 
Now,  I  have  already  said  that  an  answer  which  assigns  a 
really  extrinsic  motive  is,  to  my  mind,  a  virtual  evasion  of 
the  question.  Yet  the  line  between  extrinsic  and  intrinsic 
motives  is  perhaps  not  clearly  drawn,  and  there  are  diffi- 
culties in  the  assignment  of  a  purely  intrinsic  motive  which 
require  explicit  consideration.  The  criterion  which  I  have 
accepted  is,  briefly,  that  a  man  is  virtuous  or  the  reverse  so 


THE  SANCTION.  397 

far  as  he  does  or  does  not  conform  to  the  type  defined  by  the 
healthy  condition  of  the  social  organism.  We  have,  there- 
fore, to  consider  what  advantages  are  implied  in  the  possession 
or  the  acquirement  of  such  a  character,  or  the  observance  of 
the  corresponding  rules  of  action. 

2.  The  problem  is  thus  to  find  a  scientific  basis  for  the  art 
of  conduct.  The  "sanction"  must  supply  the  motive  power 
by  which  individuals  are  to  be  made  virtuous.  It  is  for  the 
practical  moralist  the  culminating  point  of  all  ethical  theory. 
Now,  according  to  my  argument,  the  primary  and  direct  incid- 
ence, if  I  may  say  so,  of  moral  sanctions  is  upon  the  social 
organism,  whilst  the  individual  is  only  indirectly  and  second- 
arily affected.  There  is  (as  I  hold)  a  necessary  and  immediate 
relation  between  social  vitality  and  morality.  We  may  say 
unconditionally  that  healthy  development  implies  an  efficient 
moral  code,  and  that  social  degeneration  implies  the  reverse. 
But  it  does  not  follow  that  there  is  the  same  intimate  con- 
nection in  the  individual  case.  As,  indeed,  the  society  has 
no  existence  apart  from  the  individual  by  which  it  is  con- 
stituted, there  must  be  a  close  connection  ;  but  it  must  be 
subject  to  various  limitations,  in  so  far  as  the  conditions  of 
health  and  happiness  of  any  particular  person  are  not  ex- 
haustively defined  by  those  of  the  society  to  which  he 
belongs.  We  cannot  transfer  to  each  member  of  the  society 
what  we  can  say  of  the  society  regarded  as  a  whole.  It  is 
at  least  conceivable  that  the  sacrifice  of  some  of  its  members 
may  be  essential  to  the  welfare  of  the  society  itself.  The 
virtuous  men  may  be  the  very  salt  of  the  earth,  and  yet  the 
discharge  of  a  function  socially  necessary  may  involve  their 
own  misery.  A  great  moral  and  religious  teacher  has  often 
been  a  martyr,  and  we  are  certainly  not  entitled  to  assume 
either  that  he  was  a  fool  for  his  pains,  or,  on  the  other  hand, 
that  the  highest  conceivable  degree  of  virtue  can  make 
martyrdom  agreeable. 

3.  Here,  in  short,  we  come  to  one  of  the  multiform  and 
profound  problems  which  has  tortured  men  in  all  ages. 
Virtue — no  one  denies  it — does  good  to  somebody,  but  how 


398  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

often  to  the  agent?  A  belief  in  justice  as  regulating  the 
universe  has  been  held  to  imply  (I  do  not  ask  whether 
rightly  held)  that  happiness  should  somehow  go  along  with 
virtue.  To  give  up  the  belief  in  such  a  supreme  regulation 
seemed,  again^  to  be  an  admission  that  virtue  was  folly. 
Yet  how  can  this  doctrine  be  reconciled  to  the  plainest  facts 
of  experience  ?  The  lightning  strikes  the  good  and  the  bad  ; 
the  hero  dies  in  the  ruin  of  his  cause ;  the  highest  self-denial 
is  repaid  by  the  blackest  ingratitude ;  the  keenest  sympathy 
with  our  fellows  implies  the  greatest  liability  to  suffering; 
the  cold,  the  sensual,  and  the  systematically  selfish  often 
seem  to  have  the  pleasantest  lots  in  life.  Great  men  in 
despair  have  pronounced  virtue  to  be  but  a  name ;  philoso- 
phers have  evaded  the  difficulty  by  a  verbal  denial  of  the 
plainest  truths ;  theologians  have  tried  to  console  their 
disciples  by  constructing  ideal  worlds  which  have  served 
for  little  more  than  a  recognition  of  the  unsatisfactory 
state  of  the  actual  world.  The  problem,  so  often  attacked, 
will  perhaps  be  solved  when  we  know  the  origin  of  evil. 
Meanwhile,  we  have  only  to  consider  in  what  way  it  is 
related  to  ethical  theories. 

4.  One  preliminary  remark  may  help  to  clear  the  way. 
Any  sound  proposition  whatever  about  happiness  must  in- 
clude some  reference,  tacit  or  explicit,  to  the  constitution  of 
the  agent.  Happiness,  whatever  else  it  may  imply,  implies 
a  state  of  some  conscious  being;  it  must  be  conditioned  by, 
or,  in  the  mathematical  phrase,  be  a  function  of,  the  organic 
state.  We  may,  of  course,  discover  conditions  of  happiness 
common  to  large  classes  of  organised  beings,  or  even  to 
organised  beings  in  general.  Such  a  condition,  for  example, 
would  be  asserted  in  the  proposition  (true  or  false)  that 
happiness  implies  a  state  of  heightened  vitality.  Other 
more  special  conditions  apply  only  to  particular  classes.  The 
intellectual  pleasures  imply  a  certain  degree  of  mental  culture; 
the  pleasure  of  music  implies  a  certain  specific  sensibility. 
Such  pleasures  imply  a  faculty  which  is  not  common  to  all 
men,  but  to  all  intellectual  or  to  all  musical  men.     Unless 


THE  SANCTION.  399 

therefore^  virtue  cand  happiness  are  related  as  merely  different 
modes  of  regarding  the  same  quality,  it  is  idle  to  attempt  to 
assign  their  relations  by  a  simple  inspection  of  the  concepts 
themselves.  Whatever  relation  they  may  have  must  be 
dependent  upon  the  constitution  of  the  agent.  And  though 
it  might  conceivably  turn  out  that  the  relation  was  such  as 
to  be  independent  of  any  possible  variations  in  the  individual 
constitution,  we  cannot  make  any  such  assumption  at  start- 
ing. The  presumption  is  in  this,  as  in  every  other  case,  that 
the  relation  of  happiness  and  virtue  will  be  dependent  upon 
the  character  of  the  agent.  It  may  be  true  that  the  happi- 
ness of  a  given  class  depends  upon  virtue,  and  that  class  may 
be  a  very  large  one ;  but  we  have  no  right  to  assume  that 
the  class  is  identical  with  the  whole  human  race;  nor  can 
any  such  theory  be  established  without  an  investigation  suffi- 
cient to  rebut  the  natural  presumption  that  some  of  the 
class  qualities  are  necessary  for  its  existence.  In  fact,  the 
most  obvious  answer  to  the  question,  "^Does  virtue  coincide 
with  happiness  ?  "  would  probably  be,  "Yes,  for  the  virtuous 
man."  As  music  gives  pleasure  only  to  men  who  have  a 
M  musical  ear,  so  it  may  be  virtue  gives  pleasure  to  men  with 
.  a  conscience.  If  the  answer  is  not  generally  given,  it  is  not 
because  it  is  destitute  of  considerable  plausibility,  and,  as  I 
think,  of  a  great  degree  of  accuracy ;  but  because  it  is  calcu- 
lated to  shock  many  respectable  people.  But  this  is  not  a 
philosophical  consideration. 

5.  The  remark  is  enough  to  exhibit  the  fallacy  of  a  familiar 
short  cut  to  the  desired  conclusion.  When  attempting  to 
estimate  the  happiness  of  the  virtuous,  we  may,  it  has  been 
said,  confine  ourselves  to  the  judgment  of  the  virtuous.  The 
intellectual  man  alone  can  judge  of  the  value  of  intellectual 
pleasures,  whilst  he  can  judge  as  well  as  the  sensual  of  the 
value  of  sensual  pleasures ;  he  alone,  therefore,  can  make  a 
comparison ;  and  as  every  one  which  can  thus  compare  does 
in  fact  (so  it  is  asserted)  prefer  the  intellectual,  we  are  justi- 
fied in  accepting  this  authoritative  decision.  The  argument, 
like  many  other  formally  unsound  arguments,  has,  I  think, 


400  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

some  force  in  a  shape  to  be  presently  noticed ;  but  in  this 
shape  it  appears  to  be  hopelessly  untenable.  For,  in  the 
first  place,  no  judgment  of  pleasure  proceeding  by  this 
method  of  direct  inspection  alone  can  have  much  authority. 
We  are  very  bad  judges  even  of  our  own  pleasures,  and  we 
have  innumerable  temptations  to  give  a  coloured  judgment. 
We  may,  therefore,  always  appeal  from  a  man's  avowed 
sentiments  to  his  practice ;  and  it  can  hardly  be  said  that 
men  of  the  highest  intellectual  qualities  always  display  a 
relative  indifference  to  the  pleasures  of  the  senses.  Solomon 
the  preacher  must  be  compared  with  Solomon  the  king. 
Nor  does  it  follow  that  if  I  can  judge  of  my  own  pleasures 
I  can  therefore  judge  of  other  men's  pleasures.  The  fallacy 
inherent  in  all  such  inferences  is  one  of  the  most  familiar 
topics  of  experience.  If  I  prefer  Shakespeare  to  a  mutton-chop, 
I  may  say  that  I  so  far  judge  the  pleasures  of  imagination 
to  be  preferable  for  me  to  those  of  the  senses.  But  how  can 
I  leap  from  that  proposition  to  the  proposition  that  they  are 
preferable  for  others  ?  They  are  clearly  not  preferable  for 
the  pig,  or  to  the  Patagonian,  or  even  to  those  civilised  men 
who  are  in  this  matter  of  the  pig's  way  of  thinking.  At 
most,  I  may  infer  that  certain  cultivated  minds  find  m.ore 
pleasure  in  poetry  than  in  eating,  but  still  it  does  not 
follow  that  the  cultivated  man  finds  more  pleasure  in  poetry 
than  the  sensual  man  finds  in  eating.  The  two  men  are 
differently  constituted  throughout,  and  it  may  be  that  the 
intellectual  man  has  lost  in  one  kind  of  sensibility  what  he 
has  gained  in  another.  To  assert  positively  that  he  gains  on 
the  whole  is  to  make  an  assumption  often  disputed,  and  of 
which  either  side  may  be  taken  without  self-contradiction, — 
the  assumption,  namely,  that  an  increased  intellectual  sensi- 
bility necessarily  carries  with  it  increased  power  of  enjoy- 
ment on  the  whole;  or,  in  other  words,  that  it  always  answers 
to  cultivate  your  brain  at  the  expense  of  your  stomach. 

6.  There  is  yet  another  decisive  objection.  It  is  not  even 
true  that  any  man  absolutely  prefers  Shakespeare  to  a  mutton- 
chop.     Rather,  the  phrase  is  nonsensical.     Only  an  infant 


THE  SANCTION.  401 

compares  his  lov^e  for  his  cousin  with  his  love  for  jam-tart. 
Shakespeare  himself  would  at  the  right  moment  have  pre- 
ferred a  cup  of  sack  to  the  sweetest  music  or  the  loftiest 
poetry.  A  starving  saint  might  choose  to  eat  a  crust  of 
bread  rather  than  listen  to  the  most  edifying  sermon.  Briefly, 
a  pleasure  is  not  a  separate  thing,  which  has  a  certain  con- 
stant value,  but  a  state  of  feeling  which  varies  both  accord- 
ing to  the  permanent  constitution  and  the  varying  condition 
of  that  constitution.  Each  desire  has  a  certain  force,  de- 
pending upon  the  circumstances  and  character  of  the  agent, 
and  there  are  conditions  under  which  any  particular  desire 
may,  for  the  moment  at  least,  become  predominant.  We 
can  only  obtain  absurd  propositions  when  we  attempt,  in 
discussing  pains  and  pleasures,  to  abstract  from  the  agent 
who  feels  them.  Nor  can  we  evade  the  force  of  this  argu- 
ment by  making  a  distinction  between  the  quantity  and 
quality  of  pleasure.  It  is  doubtless  possible  to  give  some 
meaning  to  such  phrases.  We  may,  for  example,  distinguish 
between  pleasures  as  they  affect  different  sensibilities,  and 
call  those  pleasures  highest  which  require  activity  of  the 
intellect  or  the  sympathetic  emotions,  and  those  lower  which 
excite  only  the  senses.  Or,  again,  it  may  be  true  that  some 
pleasures  are  massive  and  others  acute;  that  some  imply  a 
state  of  the  whole  organism,  and  others  only  the  excitement 
of  a  particular  organ.  But  though  this  and  much  more 
may  be  true,  and  for  some  purposes  important,  it  does  not 
affect  our  present  argument ;  it  does  not  enable  us  to  say, 
that  is,  that  one  pleasure  is  absolutely  preferable  to  another. 
Pleasures  may  indeed  be  compared  in  respect  of  pleasantness; 
that  is,  we  may  say  that,  under  given  conditions,  the  desire 
for  one  will  overpower  the  desire  for  another.  But  each  will 
be  alternately  strongest  as  the  conditions  vary,  and  therefore 
the  formula  which  expresses  their  relations  must  always  take 
those  conditions  into  account,  and  can  never  yield  the  state- 
ment that  one  is  always  preferable  to  the  other.  This  is 
equally  true  whether  we  mean  by  preferable  that  which  is 

actually  preferred,  or  that  which  ought  to  be  preferred ;  for, 

3  c 


402  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

upon  any  moral  theory  worth  discussing,  every  natural 
desire  has  its  turn  not  only  of  preference  but  of  rightful 
preference. 

7.  I  return,  then,  to  the  problem,  which  cannot  be  solved 
by  any  such  summary  method,  What  is  the  relation  between 
virtue  and  happiness  ?  and  I  have  to  admit  that  it  may  be 
a  relation  dependent  upon  the  character  of  the  agent.     And 
here  we  have  to  notice  at  once  that  there  is  an  apparent 
difficulty  in  our  assumptions  which  necessitates  a  re-statement 
of  the    question.     Given    the   character,   I   have    said,   the 
conduct    follows ;    the    virtuous    man   acts    virtuously   and 
the  vicious  man  viciously.     If  we  suppose,  then,  that  the 
character  remains  constant,  there  is  apparently  no  sense  in 
asking  whether  it  would  make  the  vicious  man  happier  to 
act  virtuously,  for   by  acting  virtuously  he  would   become 
virtuous,  and  this,  by  the  hypothesis,  does  not  happen.     So 
long,   therefore,   as   we  assume   character    to   be   fixed,   the 
question  resolves  itself  into  this,  whether  the  virtuous  man 
is  happier  than  the  vicious  man  ?     Assuming  the  external 
circumstances  to  be  the  same  for  both,  we  have  to  ask  how 
far  virtue  is  under  all  or  under  what  circumstances  a  guaran- 
tee for  happiness  ?     But,  in  the  next  place,  the  assumption 
of  the  fixity  of  character  is  of  course  arbitrary.     A  man's 
character  is  in  all  cases  the  product  of  all  the  influences  to 
which  he  has  been  subjected  from  his  infancy  acting  upon 
his  previously  existing  character ;  and  though  more  variable 
in  early  life  than  afterwards,  it  is  in  every  case  undergoing 
a  continuous  process  of  development.     We  have  therefore 
to  ask  whether  the  acquisition  of  a  virtuous  character — of 
those  instincts  and  modes  of  conduct  which  are  prescribed 
by  the  moral  law — be  in  all  cases  conducive  to  happiness^ 
or  whether  (as  is  conceivable)  there  are  natures  which  are 
made  happier  and  others  which  arc  not  made  happier  by 
such  discipline  ?    We  have,  on  the  former  hypothesis,  to  ask 
whether  a  man  with  eyes  is  happier  than  a  man  without ; 
and  upon  this,  whether,  supposing  a  man  to  have  eyes,  it  is 
always  worth  his  while  to  cultivate  the  art  of  seeing.     And, 


THE  SANCTION.  403 

thirdly^  we  have  to  observe  that  conduct  is  not  fixed,  even 
when  character  and  circumstances  are  givcn^  unless  we  in- 
chide  under  "circumstances"  the  particular  set  of  thoughts 
and  feelings  which  are  present  in  the  agent's  mind.  Hence 
we  have  to  consider  the  problem  (which^  indeed,  seems  to 
be  the  most  frequently  discussed)  whether  we  can  discover 
any  sanction  for  the  observance  of  the  moral  law  as  such 
which  would  be  equally  operative  upon  all  men  irrespectively 
of  their  moral  character.  To  exhibit  to  a  selfish  man  the 
pleasures  of  sympathy  is  to  suggest  to  him  a  motive  for  be- 
coming virtuous ;  we  are  virtually  telling  him  to  cultivate  a 
taste  which  he  has  neglected ;  and  this  falls  under  the  pre- 
vious case.  But  we  may  also  try  to  persuade  him  that  even 
upon  purely  selfish  or  prudential  grounds  he  ought  to  do 
good  to  his  neighbour.  In  short,  we  may  try  to  prove  that 
obedience  to  the  outward  rule  answers,  whatever  the  internal 
motive.  We  have  thus  to  ask  three  questions  :  first,  whether 
the  virtuous  man  as  such  is  happier  than  the  vicious ; 
secondly,  whether  it  is  worth  while  on  prudential  grounds 
for  the  vicious  to  acquire  the  virtuous  character;  thirdly, 
whether  it  can  be  worth  while  in  the  same  sense  for  the 
vicious  man  to  observe  the  external  moral  law  ? 

8.  Before  applying  myself  to  the  argument  directly,  I  will 
make  one  remark.  I  think  it  altogether  superfluous  to  dilate 
upon  the  old  test  that  honesty  is  the  best  policy.  The  point 
has  been  so  much  laboured,  that,  although  there  is  abundant 
room  for  rhetoric,  there  is  little  need  of  argument.  Con- 
sidering how  closely  we  are  dependent  upon  our  neighbours 
and  upon  their  good  opinion,  and  the  enormous  difficulty  of 
retaining  that  good  opinion  without  deserving  it,  there  can  be 
no  serious  doubt  that,  on  the  average,  every  man  will  find  his 
account  in  observing  the  accepted  moral  code  and  acquiring 
the  corresponding  instincts.  To  be  on  good  terms  with  vour 
family,  to  avoid  picking  and  stealing,  to  be  decently  sober,  in- 
dustrious, and  good-natured,  are  rules  of  conduct  so  obviously 
expedient  upon  all  grounds,  that  I  will  not  burn  daylight  by 
insisting  upon  them.    I  assume  a  general  coincident  between 


404  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  dictates  of  morality  and  of  prudence,  and  refer  readers  in 
need  of  further  argument  to  the  Hbraries  of  excellent  treatises 
extant  upon  this  familiar  topic,  I  will  add  that  in  the  follow- 
ing remarks  I  shall  content  myself,  for  the  same  reasons,  with 
pointing  out  what  I  take  to  be  the  true  issues,  without  seeking 
to  estimate  the  weight  of  the  appropriate  evidence  which  may, 
as  a  rule,  be  taken  for  granted. 

II.  Happiness  and  Virtue. 

9.  Assuming,  then,  that  virtue  and  prudence  approxi- 
mately coincide,  whilst,  on  the  other  hand,  we  cannot  assume 
that  they  are  absolutely  coincident,  how  much  farther  can 
we  go  ?  Can  we  fix  with  any  greater  precision  the  limits 
of  possible  duration?  Does  the  new  form  into  which  the 
old  aro;uments  must  be  cast — for  a  change  of  form  is  all  that 
can  be  regarded  as  possible — help  us  to  discuss  the  question 
more  effectively?  Every  writer  is  tempted  to  recommend 
his  own  scheme  by  showing  that  it  establishes  a  closer  con- 
nection between  virtue  and  morality  than  the  scheme  of  his 
rivals,  and  there  is  therefore  a  very  natural  tendency  to  pass 
too  lightly  over  the  less  solid  parts  of  ethical  theory.  We 
feel  that  what  is  wanting  in  reason  will  be  made  up  by  the 
goodwill  of  our  audience.  But  if  our  aim  is  the  discovery 
of  the  truth,  we  must  be  more  upon  our  guard  against  the 
plausibilities  of  writers  who  wish  to  combine  edification  with 
argument.  It  would  be  highly  agreeable  to  find  sound  reasons 
for  holding  virtue  and  prudence  to  be  identical ;  it  would  be 
both  wrong  and  foolish  to  make  sham  reasons  where  we  have 
not  got  real  ones. 

10.  If  any  man  outside  of  a  pulpit  were  to  ask  himself 
frankly  what  were  the  main  conditions  of  human  happiness, 
the  answer  would  certainly  include  one  proposition.  The 
first,  most  essential,  and  most  sufficient  condition  of  happi- 
ness is  health — health,  of  course,  inclusive  of  cerebral,  and  so 
far  of  mental  health ;  or,  in  the  opposite  phrase,  an  absence 
of  every  disease  of  mind    or    body.     This,   again,    remains 


HAPPINESS  AND  VIRTUE.  405 

equally  certain^  whatever  the  difficulty  of  giving  a  satisfactory 
definition  of  health  or  disease.  We  can  only  say  vaguely 
that  health  corresponds  to  the  maintenance,  and  disease  to 
the  disturbance  of  a  certain  organic  balance.  But  though 
we  may  not  know  precisely  what  they  are,  we  cannot  doubt 
their  importance.  A  sound  digestion,  an  active  liver, 
strong  nerves — briefly,  all  the  qualities  that  go  to  a  perfect 
physical  machinery — form  the  best  of  all  outfits  for  the 
voyage  of  life,  so  far  as  "best"  means  most  productive  of 
happiness. 

II.  The  question  then  arises.  Can  we  push  this  theory  any 
farther  ?  Can  we  use  the  w^ord  "health"  in  such  a  way  as  to 
include  the  right  working  of  all  the  functions — including 
the  intellectual  and  the  emotional,  as  well  as  the  purely 
animal — and  then  assert  that  health  in  this  wide  acceptation, 
including  the  normal  constitution  of  the  "moral  sense,"  is 
the  most  general  and  essential  condition  of  happiness  ? 
Common  sense  seems  to  sanction  some  such  doctrine.  The 
viejis  Sana  in  corpore  sano  is  still  the  truest  possible  definition 
of  the  general  condition  of  happiness,  and  we  have  no  hesita- 
tion in  applying  the  words  "healthy"  and  "morbid"  to  purely 
mental  phenomena.  But  it  may  be  urged  that  the  phrase 
implies  a  metaphor  too  vague  to  bear  much  argumentative 
stress.  We  are  making  an  awkward  transition  from  ob- 
jective to  subjective  considerations,  from  the  comparatively 
firm  land  of  physiology  to  the  treacherous  morasses  of 
psychology.  We  may  assume,  in  virtue  of  the  general 
principle,  that  health  of  brain  is  a  condition  of  happiness 
at  least  as  much  as  health  of  stomach ;  and  more  vaguely 
we  may  assume  that  health  of  brain  has  some  correlation 
with  health  of  mind.  In  extreme  cases  it  is  plain  enough 
that  a  diseased  brain  implies  madness  and  misery ;  but  we 
are  certainly  unable  to  say  what  state  of  brain  is  correlated 
with  those  good  and  bad  qualities  which  constitute  the 
virtuous  or  vicious  character,  but  which  may  vary  from  one 
pole  to  the  other  without  exceeding  the  limits  of  perfect 
sanity.     It  is  possible  that  we  may  be  justified  in  inferring 


4o6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

that  some  correlation  exists,  but  our  inference,  even  if  well 
established,  gives  us  next  to  no  help.  It  asserts  a  relation 
between  two  things,  one  of  which,  the  state  of  the  brain, 
is  hopelessly  inaccessible,  and  can  therefore  afford  no  inde- 
pendent information.  If  vice,  like  some  physical  diseases, 
were  due  to  the  presence  of  a  parasite  in  the  tissues,  the 
fact  might  help  us  to  define  its  effects  upon  the  organic  state 
generally,  and  therefore  upon  the  happiness  of  the  agent. 
But  as  the  existence  of  any  physical  condition  is  a  hypothesis 
which  cannot  be  confirmed  by  any  direct  test,  and  the  con- 
dition is  not  likely  to  be  of  this  definite  and  assignable  kind, 
any  such  hypothesis  would  seem  to  be  a  mere  curiosity. 
And  yet  I  think  that  the  analogy  has  a  real  force,  and  may 
be  of  use — not  so  much  in  suggesting  new  arguments  as 
in  giving  more  coherence  and  fulness  to  the  old  familiar 
argument.  And  this  is  as  much  as  we  can  expect  in  ethical 
inquiries. 

12.  That  health  implies  happiness  may  be  asserted  on 
purely  empirical  grounds.  A  simple  induction  may  con- 
vince us  that  all  states  which  imply  the  disturbance  of  the 
normal  equilibrium  are  also  states  of  misery.  The  convic- 
tion of  this  truth  may  not  be  much  intensified,  but  it  seems 
to  be  more  or  less  "  explained," — that  is,  shown  to  be  not 
merely  a  fact,  but  a  necessary  consequence  of  a  wider  prin- 
ciple,— when  we  take  into  account  the  evolutionist  doctrine, 
which  I  have  everywhere  assumed.  The  whole  process  of 
nature,  upon  that  doctrine,  implies,  speaking  briefly,  a 
correlation  between  the  painful  and  the  pernicious,  and 
thus  (as  I  have  argued  at  sufficient  length)  the  elaboration 
of  types  in  which  this  problem  is  solved  by  an  ever-increas- 
ing efficiency  and  complexity  of  organisation.  This  holds 
equally  from  the  simplest  up  to  the  highest  species.  And 
hence  we  may  infer  that  the  typical  or  ideal  character  at 
any  given  stage  of  development,  the  organisation  which,  as 
we  may  say,  represents  the  true  line  of  advance,  corresponds 
to  a  maximum  of  vitality ;  to  a  maximum  power  of  pre- 
serving the  equilibrium  or  resisting  morbid  conditions,  and 


HAPPINESS  AND   VIRTUE.  407 

therefore  of  a  maximum  accuracy  in  the  correlation  between 
painful   and   pernicious  states.      It  seems,  again,  that  this 
typical  form,  as  it  is  the  healthiest,  must  represent  not  only 
the  strongest — that  is,  the  most    capable  of  resisting   un- 
favourable influences — but  also  the  happiest ;  for  every  de- 
viation from  it  affords  a  strong  presumption,  not  merely  of 
liability  to   the   destructive  processes  which    are    distinctly 
morbid,  but   also  to  a  diminished  efficiency  under  normal 
conditions.     The  man  who  has  the  weakness  which  predis- 
poses to  disease  may  not  suff'er  so  long  as  the  disease  is  not 
actuallv  generated,  but   he   has   presumably  less    power  of 
enjovment    under    any    circumstances,      A    defect    in    the 
machinery  will  imply  defective  working,  though  actual  decay 
may  not  take  place  in  the  absence  of  a  special  strain.    What 
is  true  of  the  elaborate  machinery  of  the  physical  organisa- 
tion is  also  presumably  true  of  the  less  accessible  and  definable 
machinery  of  that  which  is  called  the  spiritual  organisation. 
13.  The   argument,   again,    whatever  its   weight,   is    not 
affected  so  far  by  the  consideration  that  the  phrase  "per- 
nicious "  must  be  supposed  to  include  conditions  primarily 
injurious  to  the  society  instead  of  the  individual.     So  long 
at  least  as  we  are  speaking  of  the  type,  such  an  argument  is 
irrelevant.     For,  as  I  have  said  at  sufficient  length,  the  type 
always  and  from  the  earliest  period  is  moulded  with  an  equally 
essential,  though  not  an  equally  permanent,  reference  to  the 
needs  of  the  race.     The  typical  or  most  effective  form  is  the 
most  effective  relatively  to  the  whole  conditions,  and  the  so- 
called  social  qualities  are  no  less  essential  than  those  which 
immediately  refer  to  the   fixed    material    conditions.     The 
reproductive  and  maternal  functions  of  the  animal  are  just  as 
much  a  part  of  its  nature  as  the  digestive  or  the  respiratory, 
and  they  must,  therefore,  have  their  proper    place  in  the 
oro-anisation.     The    same   is   equally  true  of  the   affections 
which  become  prominent  in  the  rational  animal  capable  of 
true  social  life.     To  the  type,  though  not  so  fully  to  every 
individual,  capacity  for  society  is  just  as  essential  as  capacity 
for  breathing  air.     The  whole  organisation  is  moulded,  we 


4o8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

may  say,  with  a  view  to  this  social  function,  and  a  defective 
constitution  in  this  respect  carries  with  it  an  impHcation  of 
unfitness  for  the  presumed  conditions  of  hfe  just  as  much  as 
defects  in  any  other  direction. 

14.  This  may  suggest  the  bare  outline  of  an  argument 
w^iich  might  be  carried  out  and  illustrated  in  much  greater 
detail  by  those  who  have  the  necessary  knowledge.  How- 
ever fully  set  forth,  it  would  still,  I  suspect,  remain  exceed- 
ingly vague,  and  probably  would  have  some  logical  gaps.  It 
is  scarcely  to  be  regarded  as  an  independent  argument,  but 
as  affording  a  presumption  that  some  generally  admitted 
truths  may  be  manifestations  of  a  general  scientific  principle, 
and  thus  necessary  under  the  known  conditions  of  life. 
Whatever  its  vagueness,  I  have  briefly  stated  it,  because  I 
think  that  it  will  enable  us  to  suggest  the  best  method  of 
viewing  the  ordinary  reasonings  as  to  the  relation  between 
virtue  and  happiness. 

15.  And,  in  the  first  place,  it  is  to  be  noted  that  upon  this 
showing — as  indeed  upon  any  intelligible  ground — the  con- 
nection of  morality  and  virtue  is  conditional  rather  than 
absolute.  For  the  true  statement  is,  so  far  as  we  have  gone, 
that  the  typical  man  is  so  far  the  happiest.  But  the  typical 
man,  though  he  is,  on  my  theory,  the  virtuous  man,  is  also 
much  more  than  is  generally  understood  by  that  name. 
Happiness  is  the  reward  offered,  not  for  virtue  alone,  but  for 
conformity  to  what  I  have  called  the  law  of  nature ;  that 
law,  namely,  of  which  it  is  the  great  commandment,  "Be 
strong."  If  the  problem  at  which  the  whole  race  is  perpe- 
tually, even  when  unconsciously,  labouring,  is  the  production 
of  the  most  vigorous  type,  and  if  pain  and  pleasure  be  the 
great  incentives  to  labour,  then  we  must  admit  that  the  prizes 
must  be  won  by  those  who,  on  the  whole,  and  considering 
all  their  relations,  are  the  most  efficiently  constituted.  As 
individual  excellence  assumes  fitness  for  the  social  functions, 
so  the  social  excellence  clearly  assumes  fitness  for  the  non- 
social  functions ;  and  therefore  we  must  expect  to  find  that 
happiness   is  correlated  not  only  with  the  qualities  which 


HAPPINESS  AND  VIRTUE.  409 

involve  approval,  but  those  also  which  excite  admiration. 
Beauty,  strength,  intellectual  vigour,  aesthetic  sensibility, 
prudence,  industry,  and  so  forth,  are  all  implied  in  the  best 
type,  and  are  so  far  conducive  to  happiness. 

16.  This  remark,  obvious  enough,  seems  to  be  implicitly 
disregarded  in  some  of  the  attempts  to  prove  that  virtue 
brings  happiness.  For  if  virtue  be  taken  in  its  narrower 
sense,  and  as  implying  chiefly  the  negative  quality  of  habi- 
tual abstinence  from  forbidden  actions,  there  is  no  reason  to 
suppose  that  it  coincides  with  happiness.  It  marks  only  a 
partial,  and  perhaps  a  subordinate,  conformity  to  the  essential 
conditions  of  life.  Nature — if  I  may  use  that  convenient 
personification  for  things  considered  as  part  of  a  continuous 
system — wants  big,  strong,  hearty,  eupeptic,  shrewd,  sensible 
human  beings ;  and  would  be  grossly  inconsistent  if  she 
bestowed  her  highest  reward  of  happiness  upon  a  billions, 
scrofulous,  knockkneed  saint,  merely  because  he  had  a  strong 
objection  to  adultery,  drunkenness,  murder,  and  robbery,  or  an 
utter  absence  of  malice,  or  even  highly  cultivated  sympathies. 
You  can  only  raise  a  presumption  that  moral  excellence 
coincides  closely  with  a  happy  nature  if  you  extend  "moral  " 
to  include  all  admirable  qualities,  whether  they  are  or  are 
not  the  specifically  moral  products  of  altruistic  feeling.  The 
attempt  to  evade  this  conclusion  is,  of  course,  exceedingly 
natural.  The  practical  moralist  holds  that  the  non-social 
qualities  may  be  left  to  take  care  of  themselves.  The  moral 
progress  is  dependent  upon  the  extension  of  the  sympathies, 
and,  at  any  given  period,  the  huge  dead  weight  of  selfishness 
is  the  great  obstructive  force.  This  is  reflected  in  the  theory 
of  desert  assumed  by  the  ordinary  morality  of  common  sense. 
No  man  acquires  a  claim  upon  his  neighbours  by  attending 
to  his  own  wants.  If,  indeed,  men  were  differently  consti- 
tuted— if,  as  is  sometimes  the  case  in  individual  cases,  sym- 
pathy meant  a  morbid  state  of  mind,  a  neglect  of  a  man's 
own  affairs,  and  a  useless  expenditure  of  emotion  upon  affairs 
which  he  could  not  control; — if,  in  short,  men  erred  in  the 
direction  of  being  sentimental  busybodics,  it  might  become 


4IO  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

necessary  to  preach  the  opposite  doctrine.  We  should  then 
feel  '^  obliged  "  to  the  man  who  strenuously  minded  his  own 
business  and  cultivated  his  own  corner  of  the  world,  and 
might  even  come  to  think  him  the  most  '^meritorious/' 
For  the  present,  there  is  no  appreciable  risk  in  this  direction. 
There  is  an  inexhaustible  supply  of  selfishness  and  a  most 
plentiful  lack  of  public  spirit;  and  therefore  the  aim  of  all 
moralists — rather  of  all  moral  human  beings — will  be  to 
develop  the  side  of  human  nature  now  most  defective.  Only 
when  this  essentially  relative  conception  of  merit  is  made 
absolute  we  get  into  all  the  perplexities  which  warn  us  that 
we  are  flying  in  the  face  of  facts.  If  from  the  doctrine  that 
virtue  is  meritorious  we  infer,  not  that  the  development  of 
certain  qualities  is  a  necessary  element  of  social  progress, 
but  that  the  ultimate  end  of  the  universe  is  to  stimulate, 
and  therefore  to  reward  virtue,  we  get  into  the  region  of 
unrealities.  If  we  can  speak  of  an  "  end "  at  all  in  that 
sense,  it  must,  so  long  as  we  are  in  the  scientific  region,  be 
the  end  towards  which  we  can  perceive  some  progress, 
namely,  the  development  of  a  higher  type — higher  in  respect 
of  the  general  efficiency  of  the  whole  organism,  and  certainly 
not  the  production  of  virtuous  beings  simply  ;  especially  if  by 
virtue  we  mean  conformity  to  that  narrower  moral  code  which 
is  only  a  part  of  the  "  law  of  nature."  To  make  any  such 
theory  square  with  the  facts,  we  must  either  overlook  the 
most  palpable  and  undeniable  phenomena  of  life,  or  we 
must  take  refuge  in  a  world  of  arbitrary  fancies. 

17.  We  have  still,  however,  to  consider  the  bearing  of 
this  doctrine  upon  the  relations  between  virtue  and  happi- 
ness; for  it  is  possible,  consistently  with  the  theory,  to 
regard  that  relation  as  approaching  absolute  coincidence. 
If,  in  fact,  we  are  justified  in  assuming  that  the  typical  man 
is  the  happiest,  and  further  that  he  is  also  the  most  virtuous, 
we  may  say  that  the  connection  is  of  a  very  intimate  kind. 
It  is  true,  indeed,  that  a  limit  is  suggested,  for  it  is  only  upon 
condition  of  an  alliance  with  the  other  useful  qualities  that 
we  suppose  virtue  to  imply  happiness.     Now  as  most  men 


HAPPINESS  AND   VIRTUE.  41 1 

are  very  far  from  possessing  the  other  qualities  in  perfection, 
it  may  be  that  their  virtues  should  be  diminished  in  propor- 
tion in  order  to  produce  a  maximum  of  happiness.  This, 
for  example,  is  sometimes  insinuated  in  the  cynical  maxim 
which  recommends  us ,  to  keep  our  hearts  cold  and  our 
stomachs  warm,  for  this  seems  to  be  an  epigrammatic  asser- 
tion of  the  theory  that  warm  affections  are  apt  to  be  injurious 
to  the  digestion.  Perhaps,  indeed,  its  author  meant  to  go 
further;  he  meant,  it  may  be,  to  assert  that  the  affections 
were,  on  the  whole,  sources  of  more  misery  than  happiness, 
and  he  was  probably  one  of  the  people  who  consider  that 
your  heart,  like  vour  liver,  must  be  out  of  order  whenever 
YOU  become  distinctly  conscious  of  its  existence.  But  omitting 
this,  which  will  be  presently  noticed,  the  doctrine  may  be 
interpreted  as  an  assertion  that  the  pleasures  of  sympathy  are 
worth  having,  but  only  on  condition  of  their  not  interfering 
with  sanitary  considerations.  And  this,  true  or  not,  leaves 
a  vague  but  very  wide  sphere  for  their  possibly  agreeable 
activity;  and,  in  fact,  it  seems  impossible  to  deny  that  a 
man's  capacity  for  emotional  excitement  may  be  too  great 
for  his  constitutional  power ;  that  he  carries  too  m.uch  sail  for 
his  prudential  ballast,  and  that  he  has,  in  this  sense,  too  much 
virtue  for  happiness. 

18.  The  same  thing  indeed  may  be  stated  in  a  less  offensive 
way.  We  may  either  say  that  the  man  has  too  much  virtue 
for  his  prudence,  or  that  he  has  too  little  prudence  for  his 
virtue.  We  mean  in  either  case  that  he  deviates  from  the 
type  by  a  relative  excess  of  those  qualities  which  are,  on  an 
average  of  cases,  defective.  He  is  so  far  a  less  efficient  being 
on  the  whole,  and  therefore  less  calculated  for  happiness,  as 
his  nature  is  ill  balanced  ;  and  the  balance  might  be  redressed 
either  by  strengthening  the  weaker  or  weakening  the  stronger 
side.  But  it  is  not  true  in  an  absolute  sense  that  he  is  too 
virtuous  for  happiness;  for  by  our  assumption  the  virtue  is 
the  typical  character  considered  under  one  aspect  or  in 
certain  definite  relations.  The  typical  man  represents  the 
best  kind  of  man  who  can  be  made  out  of  given  materials ; 


412  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

and  this  Involves  both  the  quahties  which  excite  admiration 
and  those  which  excite  moral  approval.  It  is  possible,  indeed, 
that  the  supposed  man  may  represent  an  altogether  higher 
type  than  that  implied  in  the  actual  moral  standard ;  and 
we  shall  ask  presently  whether  we  have  any  right  to  suppose 
that  such  a  being  is  presumably  happier.  In  the  ordinary 
case,  the  answer  already  given  is  sufficient.  The  assertion 
that  a  man  has  too  fine  feelings  means  equaliv  he  has  too 
weak  a  fibre.  He  is  deficient  in  one  kind  of  excellence, 
though  not  in  the  moral  kind ;  and  any  deficiency  so  far  tells 
against  his  happiness.  This,  in  fact,  seems  to  be  true  of  many 
of  the  men  who  have  been  made  miserable  by  qualities  which 
w^e  rightly  call  good,  because  they  are  implied  in  the  highest 
type,  but  which,  taken  by  themselves,  are  an  insufficient 
guarantee  for  happiness.  Virtue,  in  the  sense  of  benevolence 
or  quick  sympathies,  will  not  supply  the  place  of  strong 
nerves  and  high  vitality.  The  whole  man  does  not  represent 
the  best  type,  for  a  race  which  developed  its  sympathies  at 
the  expense  of  its  vitality  as  a  whole  would  be,  for  that  reason, 
an  inferior  race,  and  represent  not  progress  but  deterioration. 
19.  The  general  argument  might  be  confirmed  by  going 
again  over  the  chief  virtues,  considered  in  their  individual 
instead  of  their  social  aspect,  and  showing  how  they  implied 
greater  fitness  for  the  normal  conditions  of  life.  To  do  so 
would  be  to  repeat  much  that  I  have  said,  and  to  insist  upon 
some  of  the  familiar  arguments,  which  I  am  content  rather 
to  take  for  granted ;  and  it  will  be  sufficient  to  indicate  here 
a  few  obvious  points,  w^ithout  fuller  elaboration.  Thus,  in 
the  first  place,  we  might  dwell  upon  the  direct  connection 
between  the  prudential  and  the  moral  aspect  of  sanitary 
rules.  Excesses  of  sensuality  may  be  forbidden  for  purely 
prudential  reasons ;  a  man  may  be  temperate  to  avoid  the 
pains  of  delirium  tremens.  The  higher  character  is  certainly 
not  insensible  to  this  motive,  but  he  has  the  additional 
motives  that  by  injuring  his  health  he  is  injuring  his  power 
of  discharging  every  social  function,  and  that  sensuality 
implies  the  dulling  of  his  intellect  and  the  deadening  of  his 


HAPPINESS  AND  VIRTUE,  413 

emotions;  and  thus,  as  I  have  said,  it  matters  not  whether 
some  rules  forbidding  conduct  which  in  its  first  incidence 
is  "self-regarding"  be  regarded  as  prudential  or  as  moral. 
They  are  properly  both.  The  same  rule,  "  Be  temperate,"  is 
applicable  from  the  lowest  to  the  highest  stage  ,of  develop- 
ment, though  the  details  of  the  code  would  vary  as  the  con- 
stitution. The  typical  being  at  each  stage  would  be  tempe- 
rate, whether  from  mere  instinct,  or  from  a  reasoned  obser- 
vation of  consequences,  or  from  the  wider  considerations 
operative  upon  the  being  capable  of  genuine  morality.  It  is 
not  less  important  at  the  highest  than  at  the  lowest  stages 
that  the  bodily  health  should  be  preserved  ;  and  a  regard  for 
sanitary  rules  is  therefore  implied  in  the  typical  being,  and 
in  the  consistent  code  of  rules  expressing  his  mode  of  conduct, 
and  embodying  both  the  moral  and  the  prudential  law.  Of 
course,  there  are  special  occasions  on  which  the  virtuous  man 
will  have  to  sacrifice  health  to  other  considerations ;  but  the 
whole  law  must  be  so  constructed  as  to  harmonise  with  the 
sanitary  code  under  normal  conditions ;  for  qualities  which 
could  only  be  acquired  at  the  expense  of  health  would  not 
be  useful  to  the  society,  and  would  therefore  not  represent 
the  true  line  of  moral  advance.  Saints,  like  poets,  are  subject 
to  certain  morbid  tendencies;  but  the  saintliness  which 
necessarily  promotes  sickliness  is  the  kind  of  saintliness 
which  diverges  from  sound  morality. 

20.  From  this  one  might  proceed  to  show  how  the  qualities 
more  specifically  moral  fall  in  with  the  same  principle.  So, 
for  example,  the  so-called  intellectual  virtues,  the  virtues  of 
which  truth  and  justice  are  the  specifically  moral  expression, 
are  also  the  product  of  what  we  naturally  call  a  thoroughly 
sound  mind ;  that  is  to  say,  a  mind  which  works  normally 
undisturbed  by  prejudice  and  passion,  which  has  that  couraQ-e  to 
face  disagreeable  facts  and  to  draw  painful  conclusions  which 
does  not  imply  absence  of  the  emotions,  but  a  power  of  re- 
straining that  irregular  action  which  distorts  and  colours  the 
intellectual  vision.  This  would  be  followed,  ao:ain,  bv  reckon- 
ing up  the  vast  internal  advantages  which  result  to  the  man 


414  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

whose  intellect  is  thus  healthy  ;  for  health  implies  a  fitness  for 
the  normal  conditions  of  life.  And  here  I  might  expatiate  upon 
the  immense  advantages  to  every  man  of  imperturbable  sound- 
ness of  sense,  and  the  undeviating  honesty,  justice,  and  trust- 
worthiness which  are  its  natural  fruit  in  a  man's  intercourse 
with  his  neighbours.  It  would,  again,  be  equally  easy  to 
dilate  upon  the  advantage  of  a  healthy  emotional  nature,  one 
which  is  neither  morbidly  overwrought  nor  deficient  in  strength 
and  sensibility;  for,  in  spite  of  the  advantages  attributed  to 
a  cold  heart,  or,  more  moderately,  to  a  calculated  selfishness, 
it  must  be  admitted  that  some  warmth  of  affection  is  neces- 
sary to  happiness.  So  it  may  be  doubted  whether  any  consider- 
able intellectual  development  is  possible  without  a  correspond- 
ing emotional  development.  Without  it  a  man  is  a  hog  in 
mind  as  well  as  in  heart.  Of  all  conditions  of  health,  again, 
one  of  the  most  obvious  is  steady  and  regulated  exercise  of 
the  various  faculties.  To  weaken  the  affections  is  to  weaken 
all  the  motives  to  action  which  are  capable  of  dominating  and 
giving  continuous  interest  to  life.  These  supply  the  springs 
of  all  actions  which  can  really  satisfy  a  man's  whole  nature. 
Nobody  will  doubt  that  domestic  peace  is  the  most  important 
of  all  conditions  of  happiness  after  bodily  health;  and  next 
to  it  we  may  place  the  possession  of  interests  which  give 
motives  for  continuous  though  not  exhausting  labour.  The 
great  bulk  of  mankind  is  absorbed  in  bodily  or  other  labour, 
which  has  little  interest  except  as  a  means  of  support  to 
themselves  and  their  families;  and  its  pleasantness  or  other- 
wise must  depend  chiefly  upon  its  healthiness  or  the  reverse. 
The  happiness  of  the  whole  life  in  such  cases  depends  gene- 
rally upon  the  domestic  interests  round  which  it  centres;  but 
beyond  this,  a  man's  happiness  may  be  said  to  depend  chiefly 
upon  his  power  of  associating  agreeably  with  his  fellow-men, 
and  of  devoting  himself  to  some  of  those  pursuits  which  imply 
public  spirit,  and  therefore  a  capacity  for  sympathy  in  some 
of  its  multitudinous  forms. 

21.  This  hint  at  a  famiHar  line  of  argument  must  suffice, 
except  that  I  must  once  more  take  brief  notice  of  an  opinion 


HAPPINESS  AND  VIRTUE.  415 

which  has  encountered  us  in  various  forms.  Here  it  declares 
that  there  is  something  of  paradox  in  our  fundamental 
theory.  That  theory  asserts  that  a  man  is  the  happiest  who 
does  not  aim  at  his  own  happiness.  In  order,  then,  to  be 
happy  we  must  not  aim  at  happiness.  We  have,  as  it  were, 
to  keep  a  secret  from  ourselves,  and  to  hit  the  mark  by  pre- 
tending to  look  in  the  opposite  direction.  I  deny,  however 
(not  to  go  into  other  questions),  that  the  argument  is  here 
relevant.  Sympathetic  feelings  are  just  as  much  feelings, 
and,  of  course,  feelings  of  the  agent  himself,  as  any  other 
feelings.  They  cause  real  pains  and  pleasures;  and  there 
can  be  no  a  priori  reason  for  supposing  that  a  man  endowed 
with  sensibility  to  such  pains  and  pleasures  may  have, 
on  the  whole,  more  happiness  than  the  man  without.  If, 
indeed,  a  man  retaining  precisely  the  same  character  could 
act  either  selfishly  or  unselfishly,  it  might  seem  strange  to 
assert  that  he  would  get  more  happiness  for  himself  when 
pursuing  the  happiness  of  others.  But  this  involves  a  con- 
tradictory assumption.  Unless  a  man  be  really  altruistic 
his  actions  are  really  selfish,  even  when  they  aim  incidentally 
at  good  to  others.  If  he  be  altruistic,  he  is  a  different 
man  from  the  purely  selfish.  The  comparison,  therefore,  is 
not  really  between  the  happiness  of  the  same  man  acting 
from  one  or  the  other  motive,  but  between  the  happiness  of 
two  differently  constituted  people,  one  of  whom  has  the 
capacity  for  a  whole  set  of  pains  and  pleasures  which  are 
denied  to  the  other.  Experience  alone  can  tell  us  which 
constitution  is  the  best  suited  for  happiness ;  and  I  have 
indicated  the  line  of  argument  which,  as  I  think,  is 
conclusive  in  favour  of  the  sympathetic  character.  The 
fact  that  the  sympathetic  man  aims  at  the  happiness  of 
others  can  only  appear,  at  first  sight,  to  be  an  argument 
against  him.  For,  in  the  first  place,  it  makes  him  happv  to 
aim  at  the  happiness  of  others;  and  if  this  happiness  has  the 
awkward  quality  that  it  may  lead  to  an  actual  sacrifice  of  his 
own  future  happiness,  that  is  not  less  true  of  the  selfish  forms 
of  enjoyment.    Love  of  drink  causes  a  good  deal  more  "self- 


4i6  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

sacrifice"  in  this  sense  than  love  of  family.  Gin  is  a  more 
potent  source  of  imprudence,- even  in  the  moderate  sense, 
than  family  affection.  The  happiness  which  results  from 
aiming  at  something  different  from  our  own  future  happiness 
calls  no  doubt  for  conspicuous  calls  of  self-abnegation,  where- 
as the  purely  selfish  motives  always  promise  payment  in 
kind  to  the  agent  himself.  But  the  sympathetic  motives 
have  on  their  side  the  far  greater  intrinsic  advantage  that  they 
promote  ends  more  permanent,  far  richer  in  interest,  and  giving 
a  proper  employment  to  all  the  faculties  of  our  nature,  besides 
the  intrinsic  advantages  which  spring  from  friendly  relations 
with  the  society  of  which  we  form  a  part.  Nobody  can  doubt 
but  a  man  would  on  an  average,  that  is,  if  he  has  the  necessary 
faculties,  have  an  incomparably  greater  guarantee  for  happiness 
who  was  a  devoted  member,  say  of  some  political  or  religious 
body,  than  if  he  were  exclusively  bent  upon  satisfying  one  of 
the  sensual  appetites. 

32.  The  arguments  upon  which  I  have  touched,  when 
duly  expanded  and  enforced  by  appropriate  evidence,  may 
convince  us  of  the  truth  of  the  proposition  laid  down. 
There  is,  namely,  a  necessary  connection  between  virtue  and 
happiness,  inasmuch  as  there  is  a  necessary  connection  be- 
tween virtue  and  total  efficiency  (to  put  it  briefly),  and  as 
virtue  forms  a  necessary  part  of  efficiency.  Therefore  in  so 
far  as  a  man  is  not  virtuous  he  deflects  from  the  type,  and 
is  less  calculated  for  happiness.  And  this  is  quite  consistent 
with  the  admission  that  he  may  deflect  from  the  type  in 
other  ways,  which  do  not  entitle  us  to  call  him  vicious,  but 
which  are  equally  fatal  to  happiness.  But  there  is  an  obvious 
gap  in  the  argument,  for  at  every  step  of  the  argument  it  is 
clear  that  we  virtually  assume  a  certain  state  of  social  deve- 
lopment; for  the  "  typical "  man  is,  roughly  speaking,  the 
best  that  can  be  made  out  of  existing  materials,  and  by  the 
"  best,"  again,  we  have  meant  the  best  raw  material  for  the 
formation  of  a  vigorous  society.  But,  again,  it  is  plain  that 
the  type  gradually  changes,  and  though  the  change  is  for  the 
most   part  slow,  it  becomes  considerable  by  accumulation. 


HAPPINESS  AND  VIRTUE.  417 

Now  if  we  suppose  a  man  to  be  distinctly  in  advance  of  his 
age,  we  must  say  that  he  is  more  moral,  or  represents  a 
superior  type;  but  for  that  reason  he  is  out  of  harmony 
with  his  social  medium,  and  loses,  therefore,  all  that  part  of 
the  advantages  of  virtue  which  depends  upon  such  harmony. 
In  fact,  it  seems  that  the  argument  tends  to  show  the  advan- 
tage of  the  '^type,"  considered  as  representing  the  best 
instantaneous  development.  Happiness  will  be  the  reward 
of  fitness  for  the  actual  conditions,  and  therefore  of  an  em- 
bodiment of  the  code  of  virtues  actually  recognised  and 
possessing  authority.  Admitting  that  it  is  worth  while,  say, 
to  be  respectable,  we  may  doubt  whether  it  answers  to  be  a 
moral  hero.  Or,  again,  we  may  say  that  as  the  advantages 
depend  upon  a  certain  agreement  amongst  men,  I  have  com- 
paratively small  inducement  to  respect  the  agreement  until 
other  people  can  be  brought  to  respect  it  also.  In  fact,  it  is 
plain  that  in  many  ways  this  is  a  very  important  consideration. 
A  fine  ear  for  music  is  said  to  be  a  source  of  torture  to  a  man 
condemned  to  live  amongst  organ-grinders;  delicate  tastes  un- 
fit us  for  living  amongst  the  coarse ;  even  intellectual  activity 
exposes  a  man  to  much  discomfort  if  he  has  to  live  amongst 
the  stupid.  We  may  say  summarily  that,  though  the  intrinsic 
advantages  of  the  higher  organisation  are  not  changed,  the 
extrinsic  disadvantages  due  to  life  in  an  uncongenial  medium 
go  far  to  neutralise  them. 

33.  It  seems  impossible  to  deny  that  this  holds  good  of  the 
moral  qualities.  Temperance  is  no  doubt  directly  useful  in 
so  far  as  it  is  sanitary,  and  this  will  be  equally  true  wherever 
man  lives;  but  in  a  gross  society,  where  the  temperate  man 
is  an  object  of  ridicule,  and  necessarily  cut  off  from  participa- 
tion in  the  ordinary  pleasures  of  life,  he  may  find  his  moral 
squeamishness  conducive  to  misery.  The  just  and  honour- 
able man  is  made  miserable  in  a  corrupt  society  where  the 
social  combinations  are  simply  bands  of  thieves  and  his  high 
spirit  only  awakens  hatred ;  and  the  benevolent  is  tortured 
in  proportion  to  the  strength  of  his  sympathies  in  a  society 
where  they  meet  with  no  return,  and  where  he  has  to  witness 

a  D 


41 8  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

cruelty  triumphant  and  mercy  ridiculed  as  weakness.  The 
domestic  affections  are  the  greatest  sources  of  happiness,  but 
if  a  man's  wife  be  faithless  and  his  children  "  unnatural/' 
they  are  so  many  possibilities  of  exquisite  torture  ;  and  similar 
truths  hold  of  the  wider  social  circles.  All  this  tends  to  show, 
not  only  that  a  civilised  man  among  savages,  a  gentleman 
amongst  rogues,  and  so  forth,  is  exposed  to  misery  by  reason 
of  his  superiority,  but  even  that,  every  reformer  who  breaks 
with  the  world,  though  for  the  world's  good,  must  naturally 
expect  much  pain,  and  must  be  often  tempted  to  think  that 
peace  and  harmony  is  worth  buying  even  at  the  price  of 
condoning  evil.  ''  Be  good  if  you  would  be  happy,"  seems  to 
be  the  verdict  even  of  worldly  prudence  ;  but  it  adds  in  an 
emphatic  aside,  ^^Be  not  too  good." 


III.  Moral  Discipline. 

24.  If  we  admit  (as  I  think  that  we  must  admit)  this  limi- 
tation upon  the  general  principle,  we  virtually  admit  that  an 
excessive  virtue  cannot  be  recommended  to  the  selfish  person 
upon  grounds  intelligible  to  him.  And  there  is  another,  and, 
for  most  purposes,  more  important  exception.  Saints  are 
rare,  and  will  probably  be  little  affected  by  prudential  argu- 
ments. But  there  are  plenty  of  selfish  and  sensual  people 
to  whom  we  may  be  unwilling  to  admit  that  they  will  not 
find  it  worth  their  while  to  be  virtuous;  and  yet,  may  they 
not  uree  very  forcibly  that  a  hio;her  strain  of  virtue  is  a 
questionable  advantage  to  the  lofty  nature,  and  even  an  aver- 
age degree  of  virtue  may  be  a  doubtful  gain  for  lower  natures  ? 
Granting,  they  may  say,  for  the  sake  of  argument,  that  the 
virtuous  are  generally  the  happier  for  their  virtue,  is  that 
equally  true  for  people  with  small  aptitudes  in  that  direction  ? 
Why  should  they  undergo  the  necessary  discipline  ?  You 
would  not  advise  a  man  to  try  to  learn  music  unless  he  had 
a  rudimentary  perception  of  the  difference  between  harmony 
and  discord ;  and  if  a  man's  appetite  be  gross  and  sensual 


MORAL  DISCIPLINE.  419 

and  his  sympathies  slow,  can  you  suggest  to  him  any  adequate 
motives  for  cultivating  his  moral  sense  ? 

25.  This  brings  us  to  the  second  of  the  problems  which 
I  proposed  to  consider ;  and  the  general  remark  may  be 
made,  that  the  argument  of  a  coincidence  between  happiness 
and  virtue  (so  far  as  it  exists)  docs  not  depend  upon  the 
mode  in  which  a  man  becomes  virtuous.  I  have  assumed 
that-  moral  progress  (speaking  roughly)  does  not  imply  an 
advance  in  the  innate  qualities,  but  a  development  through 
the  social  factor.  Children,  no  doubt,  start  with  infinitely 
varying  aptitudes  for  moral  culture,  as  they  start  with 
stomachs  of  varying  strength  of  digestion ;  but  in  every 
case  the  action  of  the  social  medium  is  an  essential  factor 
in  the  result;  and  therefore  the  bare  fact  that  the  qualities 
have  to  be  developed  is  not  more  peculiar  to  one  individual 
than  another,  and  can  afford  no  presumption  as  to  their 
connection  with  his  happiness.  If  a  man  has  the  normal 
constitution,  he  will  presumably  be  the  happier  for  a  moral 
development,  as,  if  he  has  the  normal  intellect,  he  will 
derive  the  normal  benefits  from  education,  or,  if  he  has  a 
normal  stomach,  he  will  derive  the  normal  benefits  from 
observance  of  sanitary  rules.  The  foregoing  reasons  are 
therefore  equally  applicable,  though  in  particular  cases  moral 
culture  may  be  thrown  away  upon  uncongenial  natures. 
Briefly^  so  far  as  a  man  is  the  happier  for  being  virtuous,  he 
is  presumably  the  happier  for  a  virtuous  training.  Still  some- 
thing too  must  presumably  depend  upon  his  aptitude  for  receiv- 
ing it ;  and  we  may  therefore  ask  the  question,  What  are  the 
inducements  to  a  cultivation  of  virtue  which  exist  indepen- 
dently of  and  antecedently  to  the  virtue  itself?  What  pur- 
chase have  we  in  the  list  of  the  character  for  stimulating  a 
man  to  the  development  of  his  latent  good  qualities  ?  To 
answer  that  would  be  to  say  whether  it  is  worth  while  for 
the  man — reckoning  the  ''worth  while ^'  in  terms  already 
intelligible  to  him — to  become  a  new  man. 

26.  We  may  still  rely  to  some  extent  upon  the  old  prin- 
ciple.    The  process  of  moralisation  is  part  of  a  complex  pro- 


420  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

cess ;  and  whether  we  consider  the  race^  or  the  individual 
who  repeats  the  race-experience^  it  depends  upon  the  total 
intellectual^  emotional,  and  physical  growth.  It  follows 
that,  although  the  undeveloped  man  may  be  blind  to  some 
of  the  advantages  of  the  moral  character,  he  may  have  an 
eye  for  the  advantages  of  development  in  general,  or  of  some 
particular  kind  of  development  with  which  the  moral  is 
necessarily  bound  up.  He  is  accessible  to  all  the  ordinary 
prudential  arguments  as  to  the  superior  fitness  for  society 
of  the  moral  character,  even  if  he  has  himself  a  very  slight 
appreciation  of  the  more  intellectual  pleasures.  And  here 
comes  in  the  true  bearing  of  an  argument  which  we  have 
had  to  reject  in  a  different  shape.  I  see  no  use  in  asking 
whether  Shakespeare  or  a  pig  is  the  best  judge  of  the  relative 
merits  of  pigwash  and  poetry,  but  it  may  be  worth  the  pig's 
W'hile  to  aim  at  making  some  approach  to  Shakespeare.  The 
stupidest  lad  may  see  some  of  the  advantages  of  sharpening 
his  faculties ;  he  will  not  see — for  it  is  not  true — that  poetry 
is  absolutely  pleasanter  than  dinner,  but  he  may  easily  see 
that  he  would  be  the  happier  if  he  had  such  an  education 
as  would  make  intellectual  pleasure  determine  a  much 
greater  share  of  his  total  activities.  He  may  see  that 
stupidity  is  in  a  thousand  ways  a  disadvantage ;  that  it 
makes  him  inferior  to  competitors,  despised  by  his  equals, 
incapable  of  many  enjoyments,  and  so  forth.  Even  a  prize- 
fighter or  a  foxhunter  finds  a  good  brain  useful  up  to  a 
certain  point,  and  has  sometimes  capacity  enough  to  infer 
that  a  more  vigorous  brain  would  be  still  more  useful.  And 
putting  the  same  remark  generally,  we  may  say  that  there 
is  something  like  a  general  (though  clearly  not  a  universal) 
consent  as  to  the  advantage  of  a  full  development  of  our 
faculties.  It  is,  I  think,  hopeless  to  produce  a  balance-sheet 
of  pains  and  pleasures  which  would  prove  that  the  virtuous 
man  gets  a  greater  sum  of  pleasant  emotions  or  a  sum  of 
emotions  superior  in  (juality ;  but  it  may  be  proved  that  a 
man  gains  by  growing  as  much  as  it  is  in  him  to  grow,  and 
that  this  necessarily  involves  moral  growth. 


MORAL  DISCIPLINE.  421 

37.  The  argument  thus  sug:2;cstccl  dilTcrs  from  the  ancient 
and  famihar  arguments   of  all  practical   moralists  only  by 
laying  rather  more  stress  than  they  generally  do  upon  the 
intrinsic  as  distinguished  from  the  extrinsic  considerations. 
The  ordinary  arguments,  "Be  industrious,  and  you  may  come 
to  be  Lord  Mayor ; "  "^Ee  sober  and  steady,  and  your  master 
may  allow  you  to  marry  his  daughter,"  are  very  good  argu- 
ments, so  far  as  they  go ;  and  the  practical  moralist  who 
scorned  to  make  use  of  them  would,   I  think,  be  very  ill 
advised.      I   am   only   pointing  out  that  such  a  statement 
does   not   exhaust  the    purely   prudential   argument.      It   is 
equally  possible  to  prove  to  a  man  upon  purely  prudential 
grounds  the  advantage   of  cultivating  such  germs  of  good 
feeling  as  he  may  possess,  and  make  him  see  that  besides  the 
direct  pleasure  derivable  from  their  exercise  and  the  inci- 
dental advantages  derivable  from  the  respect  of  his  fellows, 
such  culture  is  a  necessary  element  in  the  full  development 
of  his  nature,  and  therefore  in  his  excellence  in  other  facul- 
ties.     The  general  statement  has   already  been  sufficiently 
indicated  to   show  the  advantages   of  a  moralised  nature. 
I  have  had  to  speak  of  this  essential  connection  between  the 
qualities  embodied  in  the  type,  and  what  I  am  now  saying  is 
merely  an  application  of  the  same  principle.    A  one-sided  deve- 
lopment is  always  a  disadvantage,  as  a  defect  in  one  faculty 
has  some  reaction  upon  those  which  form  part  of  the  same 
nature.      We  may   undoubtedly   find    cases    enougli   of  an 
apparent  divergence  between  different  excellences.      There 
are  men  of  vast  intellect  who  have  been  thoroughly  selfish 
and   unscrupulous ;  or,  again,  men  of  fine  sensibilities  and 
rich   emotional   natures  who  have  become  prophets  of  the 
baser  elements   in  our  nature;  and,  in  such  cases,  it  may 
seem  as  if  eminence  were  the  reward,  not  simply  of  indifl:er- 
ence  to,  but  of  downright  contempt  for,  moral  considerations. 
Yet  a  fair  examination  would  rather  prove,   I  think,  that 
this  is  an  erroneous  view.     The  statesman  who  is  wanting 
in  genuine  moral  feeling  or  sympathy  for  his  kind  is  under 
one   of  the   greatest   disadvantages    possible ;    and   a  great 


422  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

man,  even  though  the  moraUst  may  feel  bound  to  condemn 
him,  is  generally  in  a  kind  of  tacit  alliance  with  morality, 
simply  because  the  intellect  which  makes  him  perceive  the 
realities  of  life  reveals  to  him  the  advantage  of  being  on  the 
side  of  the  strongest  forces,  and  therefore,  even  in  his  own 
despite,  of  progress.  But  he  is  more  powerful  if  he  is  impelled 
by  more  spontaneous  sympathies.  So,  on  the  other  side,  we 
may  be  inclined  to  say  that  the  highly  emotional  nature 
is  at  once  a  source  of  power  over  the  sympathies  of  others 
and  of  many  moral  weaknesses ;  but  it  is  as  true  to  say 
that  a  development  of  the  counterbalancing  faculties  will 
improve  his  morality  without  weakening  his  power  over 
others.  Incontinence  of  feeling  is  a  source  of  weakness, 
though  it  may  at  times  cause  a  superficial  appearance  of 
vigour.  In  proportion  to  the  development  of  a  man's  intellect 
is  not  only  his  power  but  his  need  of  sympathy.  As  he  is 
able  to  identify  himself  with  a  larger  part  of  the  social 
organism,  an  identity  between  his  own  interests  and  the 
deepest  interests  of  his  fellows  becomes  more  essential  to 
his  life. 

28.  This,  again,  falls  in  with  the  doctrine,  which  may  be 
presented  in  various  lights,  of  the  unity  of  virtue,  or  of  the 
statement  that  virtue  has  a  positive,  and  vice  only  a  negative 
meaning.  This,  in  fact,  is  one  way  of  putting  the  truth  that 
virtue  is  one  aspect  of  the  development  of  a  single  type, 
whereas  vice  means  any  tendency  towards  disintegration. 
Consistency  and  harmony  of  conduct  is  therefore  one 
characteristic  of  the  virtuous,  whilst  vice  is  by  its  nature 
heterogeneous  and  leads  to  discord.  If,  for  example,  a  man 
has  a  lofty  intellect,  and  has  yet  overpowering  sensual 
impulses,  his  nature  is,  as  we  say,  at  war  with  itself.  For  as, 
on  the  one  hand,  he  is  fitted  for  the  pursuit  of  abstract  truth 
and  capable  of  wide  sympathies  and  lofty  ideals,  he  is,  on 
the  other  hand,  attracted  by  the  lower  kind  of  pleasure 
which  can  only  be  attained  at  the  expense  of  the  higher. 
He  is  a  great  scholar  or  statesman  by  fits,  and  at  other 
times  the  slave  of  the  bottle  or  of  women.     This  kind  of 


MORAL  DISCIPLINE.  423 

inconsistency  or  irrationality  is  in  fact  the  expression  of  an 
ill-balanced  character^  and  by  "  ill-balanced  "  wc  mean  that 
which  deflects  from  the  type  actually  worked  out  by  con- 
formity to  the  condition  of  maximum  efficiency. 

29.  And  here  we  come  upon  a  fresh  form  of  the  old  diffi- 
culty ;  for  we  see  that  the  discord  of  which  we  are  speak- 
ing is  the  mark,  as  it  were,  of  a  hybrid  nature — of  a  man 
who  belongs  in  some  respects  to  the  higher,  and  in  others  to 
a  lower  type.  And  thus  we  have  still  to  ask  whether  a  man 
may  not  be  also  harmonious  with  himself  if  he  belongs  to  a 
lower  type,  by  some  innate  defect  which  unfits  him  for 
receiving  the  normal  development,  and  whether  in  that  case 
we  can  suppose  that  he  will  be  the  happier  for  moral  dis- 
cipline? Are  there  not,  in  fact,  men  whose  sympathies  are 
so  dull  and  whose  intellects  are  so  torpid  that  a  pursuit  of 
sensual  pleasure  will  always  be  more  congenial  to  them,  and 
that  they  will  only  derive  misery  for  themselves,  if  not  for 
others,  by  being  forced  into  conformity  with  moral  rules? 
Are  there  not  idiots,  and  beings  at  every  point  of  the  scale 
between  absolute  idiocy  and  the  loftiest  genius  ?  and  if  so,  is  it 
possible  to  say  that  all  of  them  will  be  the  happier  for  accept- 
ing the  same  law  ?  A  man  with  a  capacity  for  sympathy  may 
be  the  happier  for  having  it  fully  developed.  But  suppose 
that  he  has  none  ?  If  by  any  process  you  can  persuade  him 
to  act  like  a  benevolent  man,  will  this  fictitious  benevolence 
repay  him  for  abstinence  from  gin  ? 

30.  I  can  certainly  see  no  reason  to  doubt  the  existence  of 
human  brutes — of  men  who  not  only  do  nOt  possess,  but  can- 
not be  made  to  possess,  the  instincts  characteristic  of  the 
higher  type.  There  are,  I  fully  believe,  men  capable  of  intense 
pleasure  from  purely  sensual  gratification,  and  incapable  of 
really  enjoying  any  of  the  pleasures  which  imply  public 
spirit  or  private  affection  or  vivid  imagination.  It  is  true, 
generally,  that  each  man  has  certain  capacities  for  moral  as 
for  every  other  kind  of  development,  and  capacities  which 
vary  from  the  top  to  the  bottom  of  the  scale.  No  process 
of  education  or  discipline  whatever  would  convert  a  Judas 


424  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Iscariot  into  a  Paul  or  a  John.  And  therefore,  too,  as  a 
plain  matter,  we  must  admit  that  the  ends  which  men  pursue 
vary  indefinitely,  and  that  some  men,  possibly  the  mass  of 
men,  are  fitted  for  those  positions  in  the  social  organism 
which  do  not  demand  any  great  activity  of  the  higher 
faculties,  or  make  any  strain  upon  a  man's  devotion  to  the 
race  or  to  truth.  So  far,  again,  as  a  man  cannot  be  made 
moral,  there  is  very  little  use  in  asking  whether  he  would  be 
the  happier  for  being  made  moral.  That  is  really  to  ask, 
as  before,  whether  a  different  kind  of  man  is  happier.  And 
thus,  when  we  speak  of  the  morality  of  the  lower  type,  we 
must  mean  that  the  habit  of  obedience  to  the  moral  law  may 
be  impressed  upon  it,  although  the  normal  instincts  which 
make  such  obedience  the  spontaneous  fruit  of  his  charac- 
ter may  be  very  imperfectly  developed,  and  therefore,  as  a 
general  rule,  that  to  some  extent  other  instincts,  such  as  the 
fear  of  punishment  or  of  the  contempt  of  his  fellows,  have 
been  called  into  play,  so  as  to  make,  as  it  were,  a  substitute 
for  genuine  morality.  Is  such  a  process  likely  to  make  him 
happier  ? 

31.  To  this  we  must  reply,  that  the  external  and  prudential 
sanctions  must  generally  remain  in  force  for  all  men  inde- 
pendently of  their  character.  The  evils  of  drunkenness,  so 
far  as  they  consist  in  disease  or  poverty,  are  applicable  to 
and  appreciable  by  the  most  sensual  man,  though  he  is  not 
equally  sensitive  to  the  injury  to  his  intellect.  The  objec- 
tions to  a  want  of  honesty  which  depend  upon  the  action 
of  the  policeman  or  the  victims  of  fraud  are  applicable  to 
every  one  in  a  civilised  country.  And  generally  the  human 
hog  as  well  as  the  genuine  man  will  find  his  account  in 
being  on  tolerable  terms  with  the  society  in  which  he  lives. 
But  it  certainly  does  not  appear  that  this  is  equally  true 
of  the  intrinsic  sanctions.  The  sensualist  who  has  enough 
prudence  to  avoid  disease  or  general  disgrace  may  get  a 
quantity  of  pleasure  from  immoral  practices.  If  by  any 
device,  by  persuading  him  that  he  will  go  to  hell  for  such 
indulgence,  or  by  so  strictly  drilling  him  till  abstinence  has 


MORAL  DISCIPLINE.  425 

become  a  custom,  and  the  sensuality  has  thus  lost  some  of 
its  power  without  making  room  for  the  development  of  the 
nobler  feelings,  it  is  hard  to  say  why  such  restraints  should 
make  a  man  happier  any  more  than  physical  restraints.  The 
drunkard  in  a  jail  who  cannot  get  his  bottle  is  probably  less 
happy  than  when  he  is  at  large ;  and  if  his  jail  be  made  of 
prejudices  forced  upon  his  nature,  and  justifiable  by  motives 
which  he  cannot  understand,  it  does  not  seem  to  make  much 
difference.  So,  again,  when  a  man  has  no  real  benevolence, 
but  is  forced  into  the  outward  practice  of  benevolence  by 
custom  and  dread  of  public  opinion,  he  is  probably  less  at 
ease  than  if  he  were  systematically  cold-blooded.  So  the 
man  who  goes  to  church  because  he  has  always  been  taught 
to  do  so,  without  possessing  the  instincts  which  are  gratified 
by  religious  worship,  is  probably  more  uncomfortable,  even 
though  he  may  not  be  a  conscious  hypocrite,  than  if  he  were 
frankly  a  "  worldling."  And  thus,  though  it  is  very  hard 
to  sum  up  such  considerations,  our  argument  would  seem  to 
point  to  the  conclusion,  that,  as  a  very  general  rule  at  least, 
obedience  to  the  external  moral  law  is  a  matter  of  prudence 
for  everybody ;  that  it  can  be  proved  to  almost  any  man 
that  it  is  safer  for  him  not  to  be  at  war  with  his  fellows  or 
indulge  his  appetites  to  excess;  but  that,  on  the  other  hand, 
it  cannot  be  said  with  any  confidence  that  if  we  were  to 
consult  the  happiness  of  the  agent  exclusively,  we  should 
always  try  to  infuse  into  him  habits  of  virtue  which  tran- 
scend this  rather  moderate  limit.  It  is  possible  to  make  a 
man  less  fitted  for  enjoyment  under  normal  circumstances 
by  trying  to  put  too  high  a  polish  upon  his  moral  nature,  as 
it  is  possible  to  achieve  the  same  result  by  cultivating  tastes 
for  art  or  intellectual  study  in  those  who  have  no  natural 
aptitude. 

32.  It  may  be  necessary  to  add,  that  this  is  no  sufficient 
reason  for  not  trying  to  do  it.  Happily,  as  I  have  already 
said,  the  moral  standard  of  society  does  not  depend  upon 
each  man's  estimate  of  what  will  be  most  for  his  own  happi- 
ness, but  much  more  upon  the  general  conviction  of  every 


426  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

man  that  it  is  his  interest  to  Hve  in  a  moral  world.  We 
may,  indeed,  desire  to  see  this  conviction  a  great  deal 
stronger  than  it  is.  Yet  even  the  sensualist,  who,  for  his 
own  part,  expects  to  get  the  greatest  amount  of  enjoyment 
out  of  life  by  indulging  his  appetites,  is  generally  anxious 
that  the  world  at  large  should  be  guided  by  different  prin- 
ciples. Doubtless  the  estimate  which  every  man  forms  of 
the  general  conditions  of  happiness  is  greatly  biassed  by  his 
character,  and  the  Utopia  of  the  drunkard  is  very  different 
from  that  of  the  philosopher.  Still  the  moral  standard  is 
not  formed  by  a  simple  generalisation  of  each  man  from  his 
own  experience,  and  a  desire  for  the  greatest  possible  divi- 
dend of  such  pleasure  as  he  can  appreciate,  but  is  worked 
out  by  the  general  social  process,  which  virtually  decides  the 
observance  of  certain  rules  to  be  essential  to  the  general 
welfare,  which,  again,  may  imply  conduct  and  character  very 
different  from  the  private  standard  of  the  man  who  honestly 
accepts  the  general  estimate.  And,  finally,  whatever  doubts 
we  may  have  as  to  the  possibility  of  making  any  given  person 
moral,  and  of  contributing  to  his  private  happiness  by  doing 
so,  we  can  have  no  scruples  in  making  him  as  moral  as  we 
can.  For  we  cannot  know  till  we  have  tried  what  capa- 
bilities of  development  there  may  be  in  him,  and  the  general 
principle  that  moral  development  involves  good  to  him  and 
still  more  to  the  society,  is  sufficiently  demonstrated  to  com- 
pel us  to  do  what  we  can.  The  danger  of  failing  on  the 
other  side  is  the  only  one  worth  notice  in  any  given  case. 


IV.   Self- Sacrifice. 

33.  This  brings  us  to  the  last  question  proposed,  which 
has  indeed  been  more  or  less  answered  by  anticipation. 
Have  we  any  right  to  say,  not  merely  that  the  good  are 
happier  than  the  bad,  or  that  moral  development  is  calcu- 
lated to  make  a  man  happy,  but  that  in  every  particular  case 
a  man,  whether  good  or  bad,  will  be  the  happier  for  acting 
rightly  ?     After  the  conditional  answer  which  we  have  been 


SELF-SACRIFICE.  4^7 

forced  to  give  even  to  the  more  general  questions,  it  is 
impossible  that  we  should  expect  to  answer  this  more  con- 
fidentlv.  I  am,  for  my  part,  convinced  that  there  are 
occasions  upon  which  we  have  to  choose  between  two 
masters.  This  way  is  the  path  of  duty;  that  is  the  path  of 
happiness.  We  shall  at  times  have  to  choose,  and  to 
choose  wuth  our  eyes  open.  Let  us  take  as  illustration  any 
of  the  famous  cases  of  moralists.  Regulus  preferred  death 
by  torture  to  dishonour.  Was  he  acting  for  his  own  happi- 
ness ?  To  make  the  question  intelligible,  w^e  must  suppose 
that  Regulus  could  have  acted  differently ;  and  this  may  be 
taken  to  mean  either  that  he  could  have  declined  martyr- 
dom if  his  character  had  been  different,  or  that  he  could 
have  declined  it,  his  character  remaining  unaltered.  On 
the  first  hypothesis  I  must  first  remark,  that  the  greater  the 
virtue  the  less  the  sacrifice  in  acting  virtuously — a  doctrine 
which  has  a  paradoxical  sound  only  if  we  understand  the 
''self"  in  self-sacrifice  to  be  the  man  without  his  virtue, 
and  his  virtue  to  be  something  external.  The  stronger  the 
virtuous  impulse,  the  greater  the  force  of  other  motives 
which  it  can  override,  and  so  far  the  greater  the  "sacrifice" 
which  it  can  impose.  But  the  less,  for  the  same  reason,  is 
the  sacrifice  of  the  whole  nature  implied  in  a  given  act,  for 
the  gratification  of  that  impulse  counts  for  more  in  the 
whole  nature.  Now,  we  may  suppose  a  man  so  constituted 
that  death  by  torture  would  imply  less  misery  than  life  in 
disgrace ;  and  still  more  easily,  so  constituted  that  a  certainty 
of  speedy  death  would  imply  a  less  prospect  of  evil  than  the 
certainty,  not  of  life,  for  life  is  always  precarious,  but  of  an 
escape  from  death  with  disgrace  for  the  indefinite  remainder 
of  life.  Would,  then,  a  man  in  the  position  of  Regulus  have 
greater  chance  of  happiness  for  possessing  such  a  sense  of 
honour  as  would  determine  him  to  martyrdom  ?  I  think  that 
it  is  impossible  to  answer  in  the  affirmative.  Many  men  live 
"  infamous  and  contented  "  after  saving  life  at  the  expense  of 
honour.  Even  if  we  suppose  Regulus  to  have  had  so  strong 
a  sense  of  honour  as  to  make  his  martyrdom  a  "  bed  of  roses," 


428  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

T  do  not  see  my  way  to  deny  that  a  man  of  less  virtue  might 
have  easily  complied^  and  have  passed  a  very  agreeable  old 
age  at  Capua  as  a  retired  general  officer,  deriving  an  amount 
of  pleasure  out  of  life  greater  than  any  which  fell  to  Regulus. 
In  this  sense,  Regulus's  virtue  was,  under  the  given  circum- 
stances, a  disadvantage  to  him  personally.  A  less  virtuous 
man  would  have  been  in  that  sense  better  adapted  to  the 
position.  But  the  question  generally  has  a  different  sense. 
We  assume  in  asking  it  that  Regulus  might  have  acted  in 
either  way  consistently  with  his  character.  His  state  of 
health,  the  excitement  of  seeing  his  home  or  his  family,  the 
presence  of  some  symbol  associated  with  patriotic  sentiment 
or  vividly  recalling  the  pangs  of  torture — briefly,  that  intri- 
cate play  of  varying  and  conflicting  emotions  which  gives 
rise  to  the  illusion  of  '^  free-will " — mi2;ht  cause  him  to  act  in 
either  way.  Again,  I  do  not  see  my  way  to  any  definite 
answer.  The  answer  would  really  depend  upon  qualities  of 
character  not  assigned  in  our  assumed  data.  A  lapse  from 
a  high  standard  may  embitter  the  whole  life  of  an  honour- 
able man.  It  may  embitter  it  so  keenly  as  to  make  such  a 
life  worse  than  death ;  and  in  that  case,  a  choice  of  death 
would  be  a  choice  of  happiness.  But  the  opposite  hypothesis 
is  certainly  conceivable.  I  see  nothing  contrary  to  the  recog- 
nised laws  of  human  nature  in  supposing  that  Regulus 
might  commit  himself  to  martyrdom  in  a  moment  of  en- 
thusiasm, and  be  afterwards  overcome  by  a  weakness  which 
would  double  the  pangs  of  death  ;  whilst,  on  the  other  hand, 
had  he  given  way,  he  might  have  made  the  discovery — not  a 
very  rare  one — that  remorse  is  amongst  the  passions  most 
easily  lived  down.  Briefly,  then,  I  admit  in  both  senses  that 
Regulus  may  have  acted  in  defiance  of  a  calculation  of  happi- 
ness ;  and  I  may  add  that  upon  my  principles  the  fullest 
recognition  of  the  fact  might  be  quite  compatible  with  such 
action.  It  may  be  true  both  that  a  less  honourable  man 
would  have  had  a  happier  life,  and  that  a  temporary  fall 
below  the  hitrhest  strain  of  heroism  would  have  secured  for 
him  a  greater  chance  of  happiness. 


SELF-SACRIFICE.  429 

34.  All  this,  again,  may  be  applied  to  much  more  ordinary 
cases.     It  is  true,  so  far  as  I  can  see,  that  not  merely  heroic 
virtue,  but  even  virtue  of  the  ordinary  kind,  demands  real 
sacrifices  on  some  occasions.    When  we  say  to  a  man,  "  This 
is  right,"  we  cannot  also  say  invariably  and  unhesitatingly, 
"  This  will  be  for  your  happiness. "     The  cold-hearted  and 
grovelling  nature  has  an  argument  which,   from    its    own 
point  of  view,  is  not  only  victorious  in  practice,  but  logically 
unanswerable.     Not  only  is  it  impossible  to  persuade  people 
to  do  right  always — a  matter  of  fact  as  to  which  there  is  not 
likely  to  be  much  dispute— but  there  is  no  argument  in  exis- 
tence which,  if  exhibited  to  them,  would  always  appear  to 
be  conclusive.     A  thoroughly  selfish  man  prefers  to  spend 
money  on  gratifying  his  own  senses  which  might  save  some 
family  from  misery  and  starvation.     He  prefers  to  do  so,  let 
us  sav,  even  at  the  cost  of  breaking  some  recognised  obli- 
gation— of  telling  a  lie  or  stealing.     How  can  we  argue  with 
him  ?     By  pointing  out  the  misery  which  he  causes  ?     If  to 
point  it  out  were  the  same  thing  as  to  make  him  feel  it,  the 
method  might  be  successful,  and  we  may  hold  that  there  is 
no  reasonable  being  who  has  not  at  least  the  germs  of  sym- 
pathetic feeling,  and   therefore   no   one  who   is  absolutely 
inaccessible  to  such  appeals.     But  neither  can  we  deny,  with- 
out flying  in  the  face  of  all  experience,  that  in  a  vast  number 
of  cases  the  sympathies  are  so  feeble  and  intermittent  as  to 
supply  no  motive  capable  of  encountering  the  tremendous 
force  of  downright  selfishness  in  a  torpid  nature.     Shall  we 
then  appeal  to  some  extrinsic  motive,  to  the  danger  of  being 
found  out,  despised,  and  punished  ?     Undoubtedly  that  will 
be  effective  as  far  as  it  goes.     But  if,  for  any  reason,  the 
man  is  beyond  the  reach  of  such  dangers ;  if  he  is  certain  of 
escaping  detection,  or  so  certain  that  the  chance  of  punish- 
ment does  not  outweigh  the  chance  of  impunity,  he  may 
despise  our  arguments,  and  we  have  no  more  to  offer.     He 
may  say — and,  as  it  appears  to  me,  may  say  with  truth — ''  I 
shall  personally  get  more  pleasure  from  doing  wrong  than 
from  doing  rioht,  and  I  care  for  nothing  but  my  personal 


430  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

pleasure."  The  first  statement  may  be — it  often  is — un- 
deniably true.  Of  the  second  he  is  the  only  judge,  and 
though  we  may  prove  that  he  ought  to  be  differently  con- 
stituted, or  that  a  virtuous  man  would  be  differently  con- 
stituted, we  do  not  thereby  alter  his  nature,  or  even  prove 
by  any  arguments  accessible  to  him  that  it  is  worth  his 
while  to  alter  it.  Against  some  people,  in  short,  the  only 
effective  arguments  are  the  gallows  or  the  prison.  Unluckily 
they  are  arguments  which  cannot  be  brought  to  bear  with  all 
the  readiness  desirable,  and  therefore  I  think  it  highly  pro- 
bable that  there  will  be  bad  men  for  a  long  time  to  come. 

^;;^.  I  see  no  use  in  shutting  or  trying  to  shut  our  eyes  to 
so  plain  a  truth.  As  regards  the  world  with  which  alone 
scientific  reasoning  can  have  any  concern,  it  is  a  simple 
statement  of  undeniable  facts,  or  of  facts  which  can  only  be 
denied  in  some  potential  sense,  that  is  to  say,  not  really 
denied  at  all.  The  theologian  and  the  philosopher  are,  in- 
deed, willing  to  admit  it  so  far  as  the  world  of  experience 
goes,  and  sometimes  inclined  to  insist  upon  it  as  affording  a 
presumption  in  favour  of  a  better  constituted  world  beyond 
or  underlying;  and  I  have  here  nothing  to  say  to  their  solu- 
tions. But  the  attempt  to  evade  the  truth  as  regards  the 
existing  state  of  things  is  often  made,  and  leads,  as  I  fancy, 
to  a  weary  waste  of  sophistry.  The  attempt  to  establish  an 
absolute  coincidence  between  virtue  and  happiness  is  in 
ethics  what  the  attempting  to  square  the  circle  or  to  dis- 
cover perpetual  motion  are  in  geometry  and  mechanics.  I 
think  it  better  frankly  to  abandon  the  hopeless  endeavour. 
Indeed,  this  admission,  true  or  false,  would  seem  to  be  but 
the  inverse  side  of  a  doctrine  which  most  moralists  have 
laboured,  and,  as  I  think,  successfully  laboured  to  establish. 
When  we  listen  to  the  careful  demonstrations  of  the  reality 
of  benevolence,  when  we  are  told  aijain  and  aeain  that  a 
man  may,  and  in  fact  does,  sacrifice  his  own  happiness  to 
the  good  of  his  fellows,  we  are  edified  and  convinced.  But 
we  receive  something  of  a  shock  when  the  edifying  moralist 
suddenly  turns  round  and  tells  us  that  the  sacrifice  is  only 


SELF-SACRIFICE.  431 

temporary,  that  is  to  say,  that  it  is  after  all  unreal.  It  is  still 
more  surprising  when  this  is  presented,  and  precisely  by  the 
moralists  who  profess  to  take  the  loftiest  theory,  not  merely  as 
expressing  the  fact,  but  as  an  a  priori  truth  deducible  from  the 
very  nature  of  things.  For  what  can  this  be  but  to  fall  back 
upon  the  purely  egoistic  doctrine  ?  Self-sacrifice,  says  the 
egoist,  is  impossible.  Yes,  agrees  his  opponent,  it  is  impos- 
sible. The  only  distinction  is  that  the  egoist  denies  that  a 
man  can  ever  take  anything  but  his  own  happiness  for  an 
ultimate  reason.  The  lofty  moralist  denies  that  anything 
but  his  own  happiness  can  ever  be  the  ultimate  result.  He 
thus  comesto  recommend  a  game  of  self-deceit  like  that  already 
noticed — selfishness,  not  abolished,  but  banished  to  the  uncon- 
scious motives.  "  You  are  to  act,"  he  says,  "  at  every  given 
moment  from  a  genuine  desire  for  the  good  of  others,  but 
vou  are  also  to  be  intimatelv  convinced  that  whatever  is  for 
their  good  is  also  for  your  own  happiness.  When  acting, 
you  are  to  ignore  this  esoteric  doctrine;  when  philosophising, 
vou  are  to  hold  to  it  as  a  necessarv  truth."  Nothino-  can 
exhibit  the  plausibility  of  the  egoistic  theory  more  forcibly 
than  this  process,  by  which  its  professed  antagonists  manage 
quickly  to  sidle  round  into  adopting  its  fundamental  tenet. 

^6.  For  my  part,  I  accept  the  altruist  theory,  and  I  accept 
what  I  hold  to  be  its  legitimate  and  inseparable  conclusion — 
the  conclusion,  namely,  that  the  path  of  duty  does  not 
coincide  with  the  path  of  happiness.  I  should  meet  the 
objection  (so  far  as  it  can  be  met  at  all)  that  this  is  an 
immoral  doctrine,  not  by  trying  to  prove  that  in  some  way 
the  immediate  loss  will  be  repaid,  but  by  reasserting  the 
doctrine  of  altruism.  By  acting  rightly,  I  admit,  even  the 
virtuous  man  will  sometimes  be  making  a  sacrifice;  and  I 
do  not  denv  it  to  be  a  real  sacrifice ;  I  onlv  denv  that  such 
a  statement  will  be  conclusive  for  the  virtuous  man.  His 
own  happiness  is  not  his  sole  ultimate  aim,  and  the  clearest 
proof  that  a  given  action  v  ill  not  contribute  to  it  will  there- 
fore not  deter  him  from  the  action.  To  a  great  extent  this 
is  true  of  everv  man  who  has  the  normal  faculties.     There 


432  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

is  scarcely  any  man,  I  believe,  at  all  capable  of  sympatby  or 
reason,  who  would  not  in  many  cases  unhesitatingly  sacrifice 
his  own  happiness  for  a  sufficient  advantage  to  others.  Almost 
every  mother  would  die  or  expose  herself  to  sufferings  which 
can  never  be  repaid  for  the  good  of  her  infant ;  and  though 
maternal  love  affords  the  most  perfect  example  of  devotion 
to  others,  and  is  of  course  much  stronger  than  most  other 
benevolent  feelings,  I  think  that  the  same  principle  is  illus- 
trated even  in  those  commonplace  acts  of  good  nature  of 
which  almost  every  man  is  capable. 

37.  I  do  not  wish  to  exaggerate  any  more  than  to  extenuate 
the  extent  of  this  fundamental  discord,  I  believe  it  to 
exist,  but  I  do  not  believe  that  it  materially  modifies  the 
ordinary  statement.  I  take  for  granted  that  as  a  rule  it  is 
prudent  to  be  moral,  and  still  more  unequivocally  that  it  is 
prudent  to  encourage  the  morality  of  our  neighbours.  But 
I  also  admit  that  this  argument  in  favour  of  morality  cannot 
be  rightly  put  in  the  form.  Morality  is  always  and  necessarily 
coincident  with  prudence.  In  exhorting  a  man  to  be  virtuous, 
we  really  exhort  him  to  develop  his  nature  upon  the  lines 
which  the  experience  of  the  race  has  conclusively  proved  to 
coincide  with  the  general  conditions  both  of  social  and  indi- 
vidual welfare.  This  is  to  exhort  him  to  acquire  a  quality 
of  character  which,  under  normal  conditions,  and  in  the  vast 
majority  of  particular  cases,  will  make  him  the  happier  be- 
cause better  fitted  for  the  world  in  which  he  lives,  capable  of 
wider  and  more  enduring  aims,  and  susceptible  to  motives 
which  will  call  out  the  fullest  and  most  harmonious  play  of 
all  the  faculties  of  his  nature  ;  but  it  is  also  to  exhort  him 
to  acquire  a  quality  which  will  in  many  cases  make  him  less 
fit  than  the  less  moral  man  for  getting  the  greatest  amount 
of  happiness  from  a  given  combination  of  circumstances.  I 
advise  a  man  to  acquire  habits  of  temperance  on  a  simple 
calculation  of  pleasure,  from  wider  prudential  considerations, 
and  upon  purely  moral  grounds.  In  each  case  the  argument 
is  conclusive,  but  in  each  case  it  admits  of  certain  exceptions. 
Temperance  will,  as   a   rule,   procure   him   most  pleasure, 


SELF-SA  CRIFICE.  433 

because  it  will  make  him  healthy ;  but  if  he  were  certain  to 
die  to-morrow,  he  might  get  most  pleasure  by  being  drunk 
to-night.  It  will  make  him  fitter  for  work,  and  therefore, 
as  a  rule,  secure  him  a  more  comfortable  position ;  but,  in 
particular  cases,  it  might  lose  him  the  favour  of  some  immoral 
person  who  could  do  him  a  service.  It  will,  again,  make 
him  more  virtuous,  and  so  far  a  better  husband  and  father ; 
but  it  is  still  as  before  easy  to  imagine  particular  cases 
in  which  the  very  strength  of  the  feelings  which  form  the 
best  guarantee  for  happiness  may  cause  the  most  exquisite 
pain,  and  make  him  miserable  in  proportion  to  their  strength. 
If,  indeed,  life  were — as  seems  to  be  implied  in  the  theories 
of  some  moralists — a  series  of  detached  acts,  in  each  of  which 
a  man  could  calculate  the  sum  of  happiness  or  misery  attain- 
able by  different  courses,  and  calculate  them  without  reference 
to  his  character,  the  whole  argument  would  be  different. 
But  this  is  precisely  what  it  is  not.  Every  man  starts  with 
an  inborn  set  of  qualities  which  are  gradually  moulded, 
developed,  or  suppressed  by  the  circumstances  in  which  he 
is  placed,  and  by  the  inherent  processes  of  growth  and  decay. 
The  happiness  or  misery  due  to  any  set  of  external  condi- 
tions depends  essentially  upon  the  disposition  upon  which 
they  operate.  Therefore  it  may  be,  or  rather  it  plainly  is, 
necessary  for  a  man  to  acquire  certain  instincts,  amongst 
them  the  altruistic  instincts,  which  fit  him  for  the  general 
conditions  of  life,  though  in  particular  cases  they  may  cause 
him  to  be  more  miserable  than  if  he  w-ere  without  them. 
And  thus,  again,  the  acquisition  of  altruistic  feeling  may 
be  recommended  on  purely  prudential  grounds,  although 
these  grounds  can  never  supply  an  exhaustive  statement  of 
the  motives ;  and  some  power  of  altruistic  feeling  is  pre- 
supposed in  the  very  capacity  to  become  moral.  But  it  does 
not  follow  that  on  special  occasions  prudence  and  virtue 
will  coincide ;  and,  as  a  matter  of  fact,  I  think  that  they 
often  emphatically  differ. 


a  E 


(    434     ) 


CHAPTER  XI. 

CONCLUSION. 

1.  I  HAVE  reached  a  conclusion  which  suggests  further 
controversy.  What  is  it  that  I  have  done,  supposing  my 
arguments  to  be  satisfactory ;  and  what  is  it  that,  even  upon 
that  hypothesis,  still  remains  to  be  done  ?  These  are  questions 
to  which,  for  reasons  to  be  immediately  assigned,  I  cannot 
give  a  full  answer.  Yet  some  answer  is  required,  so  far  at 
least  as  an  indication  of  my  own  view  of  the  case  can  be 
regarded  as  an  answer. 

2.  I  concluded  my  statement  by  expressly  admitting  that 
one  great  difficulty  must  remain  unsolved.  Rather,  I  assert 
that  it  is  intrinsically  insoluble.  There  is  no  absolute  coin- 
cidence between  virtue  and  happiness.  I  cannot  prove  that 
it  is  always  prudent  to  act  rightly  or  that  it  is  always  happiest 
to  be  virtuous.  My  inability  to  prove  those  propositions 
arises,  as  I  hold,  from  the  fact  that  they  are  not  true.  This 
admission  does  nothing  to  diminish  our  belief  in  the  sur- 
passing importance  of  morality  and  of  its  essential  connec- 
tion with  social  welfare ;  and  further,  it  does  not  diminish 
the  intrinsic  motives  to  virtue,  inasmuch  as  those  motives 
are  not  really  based  upon  prudence.  But  I  cannot  go  further. 
I  do  not  think  that  any  one  has  really  gone  further  except 
in  words ;  nor  do  I  see  any  reason  to  expect  that  any  one 
will  go  further.  The  problem  is  bound  up  in  the  old  one  of 
the  origin  of  evil.  Given  the  existence  of  misery  or  vice, 
you  may  conceivably  ^^ explain"  them  by  showing  what  are 
the  general  conditions  under  which  they  exist ;  but  you 
cannot,  without  contradiction,    explain  them  away.     Yet^ 


CONCLUSION.  435 

until  you  have  explained  them  away^  your  explanation  is 
pronounced  to  be  insufficient.  If  so,  all  explanation  will  be 
insufficient,  so  long  as  vice  and  misery  exist,  or  rather  so 
long  as  it  can  be  truly  said  that  they  ever  have  existed.  The 
problem  of  the  association  between  misery  and  virtue  is 
really  part  of  this  ancient  puzzle ;  and  when  one  enigma  is 
solved,  perhaps  the  other  may  be  clear.  This,  however,  will 
appear  more  clearly  as  we  proceed  ;  for  we  may  still  ask 
whether  we  cannot  attempt  some  solution  or  modifica- 
tion of  our  difficulties  by  going  beyond  the  limits  hitherto 
accepted. 

3.  One  distinction  must  be  made  at  starting.  Whatever 
more  may  be  said,  it  is  perfectly  clear  that  there  is  a  great 
deal  more  to  be  done.  To  expound  the  nature  of  any  evil 
is  not  the  same  thing  as  to  cure  it.  A  physiologist  has  ful- 
filled his  duty  when  he  has  stated  what  are  the  actual  pro- 
cesses of  life,  and  therefore  what  are  the  conditions  of 
healthy  or  diseased  life.  The  physician  applies  these  laws 
when  he  cures  diseases,  and  the  sanitary  reformer  when  he 
secures  the  observation  of  healthful  modes  of  life.  It  would 
be  manifestly  absurd  to  condemn  the  physiologist  because 
he  does  not  make  disease  impossible  or  induce  men  to  live 
healthily.  He  has  done  all  that  is  proper  to  him  in  his 
scientific  capacity  when  he  has  said,  for  example,  "Such  and 
such  are  the  processes  implied  by  drunkenness,  and  such 
and  such  are  the  necessary  and  probable  consequences."  He 
shows  what  are  the  appetites  gratified  by  drunkenness  as 
well  as  the  evils  which  it  causes.  So  long  as  he  is  a  man  of 
science,  he  has  simply  to  observe  facts  and  formulate  laws; 
he  is  successful  in  so  far  as  his  observations  and  generalisa- 
tions correspond  to  the  fact,  and  he  has  nothing  to  do  with 
consequences  or  applications.  If,  after  hearing  all  that  he 
has  to  say,  I  prefer  drink  and  delirium  tremens,  that  is  not 
his  concern  in  his  scientific  capacity.  His  aim  is  the  dis- 
covery of  truth,  and  his  success  is  proportionate  to  the  truths 
which  he  discovers.  With  the  physician  or  reformer  the 
case  is  of  course  differentk     One  has  to  cure  disease  and  the 


436  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

Other  to  suppress  bad  customs.  The  end  of  each  is  to  pro- 
duce a  given  result^  and  his  success  is  measured  by  the  attain- 
ment. And  therefore,  though  one  chief  aim  of  physiology 
is  to  furnish  means  for  suppressing  disease,  yet  the  theory  is 
"  right "  as  it  most  exactly  reflects  the  truth,  as  the  conduct 
is  "right"  which  most  accurately  attains  the  end.  The 
theory  would  be  useless  unless  it  led  to  conduct,  and  the 
conduct  could  not  succeed  unless  it  were  guided  by  the 
theory;  but  we  do  not  expect  the  theory  to  cure  diseases  by 
itself,  and  therefore  the  correctness  of  his  theories  does  not 
excuse  the  physician  who  fails  to  effect  a  cure. 

4.  The  same,  as  I  take  it,  is  the  relation  between  the  scien- 
tific and  the  practical  moralist.  The  scientific  moralist  has 
fulfilled  his  task  when  he  has  explained  what  virtue  and  vice 
actually  are,  what  are  their  normal  consequences  to  society 
and  the  individual,  and  what  are  the  conditions  under  which 
they  are  generated.  He  has  done  all  that  he  can  do  if  he 
has  laid  down  true  propositions  upon  such  matters.  He 
tries  to  discover  what  is  the  "  form  "  of  morality,  what  is  its 
intrinsic  or  essential  character,  how  good  or  bad  men  act, 
what  are  their  motives,  and  what  the  normal  consequences 
of  their  actions.  The  physiologist,  as  I  have  said,  may  ask 
similar  questions  in  regard  to  health  and  disease.  But  the 
effect  of  a  belief  in  conclusions  attained,  whether  in  ethics 
or  in  physiology,  wdll  depend  upon  the  character  of  the 
believer.  "  This  is  wrong,  and  I  choose  to  act  wrongly ; " 
"  This  is  unwholesome,  and  I  choose  to  risk  my  health," 
represent  states  of  mind  not  only  possible  but  common.  It 
is  part  of  the  ethical  problem  to  determine  what  character  is 
implied  in  them.  We  should  contradict  the  commonest  ex- 
perience if  we  denied  their  possibility.  The  practical  moralist 
who  tries  to  raise  the  standard  of  morals  or  to  influence  a 
particular  man  must  start  from  the  science ;  and  his  success 
will  be  measured  by  the  degree  in  which  he  affects  conduct. 
But  it  is  an  error  to  try  the  scientific  moralist  by  the  test 
applicable  to  the  practical  moralist.  His  theory  is  sound, 
like  every  other  theory,  so  far  as  it  explains  the  facts ;  and 


CONCLUSION.  437 

it  must  explain,  and  therefore  admit,  the  existence  of  vice  as 
well  as  virtue.  And  this  seems  to  l^e  overlooked  when  an 
ethical  theory  is  condemned  because  it  does  not  of  itself 
constrain  the  will  as  well  as  convince  the  intellect.  That  is 
to  confound  the  art  with  the  science,  or  practice  with  theory. 
A  theory  is  a  systematic  statement  of  belief,  and  the  only 
question  about  a  belief  is  in  any  and  every  case  whether  it 
is  true  or  fiilse,  not  whether  it  does  or  does  not  produce  any 
assumed  effect  upon  conduct.  In  this  respect  the  analogy 
is  complete  between  the  scientific  and  practical  moralist  and 
the  scientific  and  practical  physiologist.  It  is  as  idle  to 
suppose  that  an  ethical  theory  will  show  vice  to  be  impossible 
as  to  suppose  that  a  physiological  theory  will  show  disease 
to  be  impossible.  If  that  were  the  case,  we  should  happily 
be  able  to  dispense  with  theories  altogether. 

5.  Philosophers  have  attempted  to  evade  this  diflficulty  in 
many  ways.  They  have  laboured  indefatigably  so  to  state 
the  ethical  principle  that  disobedience  may  be  "  unreason- 
able "  in  the  same  sense  as  refusal  to  believe  in  a  mathe- 
matical demonstration.  Every  such  attempt  is  doomed  to 
failure  in  a  world  which  is  not  made  up  of  working  syllogisms 
and  where  the  w^ill  and  the  reason  mean  different  things.  But 
the  difHculty  recurs  so  often,  that  I  may  attempt  to  explain 
my  opinion  by  some  further  considerations.  It  is  some- 
times said  that  the  moralist  has  to  treat  of  what  ^"^ ought" 
to  be,  not  of  what  "is."  To  which  I  might  reply  that 
there  is  no  real  disjunction,  and  that  it  would  be  just  as 
reasonable  to  say  that  the  medical  writer  treats  of  the  health- 
ful and  the  morbid,  and  not  of  the  actual.  The  moral  in- 
stincts are  realities,  and  in  treating  of  them,  I  treat  of 
morality.  But  the  intention  of  the  remark  seems  to  be 
different.  The  implied  assertion  (if  I  understand  it  rightly) 
is  to  this  effect :  The  man  of  science  aims  in  all  cases  at  the 
discovery  of  "  laws,"  where  by  "  law  "  we  mean  nothing  but 
generalised  statements  of  fact.  But  the  moralist  has  to  do 
something  different  from  this;  he  has  to  establish  "  laws"  in 
the  juridical  sense ;  meaning,  therefore,  commands,  or  at 


438  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

least  formulce  of  some  kind  which  have  a  "coercive"  action 
upon  the  will.  Hence  there  is,  it  is  said^  a  real  difference 
between  the  cases.  The  physicist  proves  (say)  that  the 
planets  attract  each  other  ;  and  the  fact  so  summarised  takes 
place  by  a  mechanical  necessity,  or  independently  of  the 
human  rule.  The  sociologist  again  (if  the  possibility  of  such 
a  science  be  admitted)  obtains,  or  would  obtain,  formulae  of 
the  same  kind ;  that  is  to  say,  "  All  men  do  so  and  so," 
"Good  men  do  this,"  "Bad  men  do  that,"  and  so  forth. 
This  can  never  amount  to  more  than  a  statement  of  facts. 
The  forces  at  play  now  include  desires  and  volitions  ;  but  the 
man  of  science  lays  down  social  rules  as  the  physicist  lays 
down  his  formulae,  as  statements  of  what  will  invariably  or 
"  necessarily "  happen.  Assuming,  therefore,  that  he  can 
obtain  such  formulae,  they  cannot  be  moral  laws ;  for  the 
moral  law  says,  not,  "  This  and  this  is  true,"  but,  "  This  and 
this  is  to  be  done."  It  is  a  command  or  a  law  proper,  not  a 
law  in  the  derivative  or  scientific  sense.  But  the  moralist 
has  to  discover  laws  proper,  not  laws  metaphysical,  and 
therefore  has  to  do  with  the  "  ought,"  not  with  the  "  is." 

6.  To  this  I  must  reply,  so  far  as  I  dissent,  by  giving 
my  own  view.  The  statement  just  given  seems  to  me  to 
be  accurate,  but  leads  to  an  apparent  difficulty  only  when 
we  confound  the  spheres  of  practice  and  theory,  or  confound 
the  meanino;s  of  "  fact "  and  "  truth."  When  dealing  with 
beliefs,  we  can  only  ask  whether  they  are  true  or  false. 
When,  on  the  contrary,  we  are  dealing  with  commands,  it 
is  nonsense  to  ask  whether  they  are  true  or  false ;  we  can 
only  ask  whether  they  do  or  do  not  operate,  that  is,  compel 
obedience.  So  I  do  not  properly  "believe"  or  "disbelieve" 
in  a  command :  I  simply  obey  or  disobey  it ;  though  I  may, 
of  course,  believe  or  disbelieve  that  the  command  has  been 
given  or  that  certain  consequences  will  follow  disobedience. 
But  although  it  is  not  proper  to  use  the  words  "fact"  and 
"  truth  "  as  though  they  were  synonymous,  every  truth  is, 
of  course,  concerned  with  facts ;  and  there  are  truths  and 
beliefs  which  are  concerned  with  commands  as  with  facts  of 


CONCLUSION.  439 

every  kind.  And  further,  a  belief  may  be  necessarily  im- 
plied in  a  command,  and  in  such  a  way  that  a  command 
may  be  the  necessary  result  of  a  belief,  which,  indeed,  must 
generally  be  the  case  where  the  belief  is  a  belief  about  con- 
duct. The  "  law,"  in  the  case  of  physical  inquiries,  may  be 
accepted  without  any  effect  upon  the  character.  The  accept- 
ance of  the  law  of  universal  gravitation  has  no  bearing  what- 
ever upon  the  ends  of  the  believer.  It  will  sometimes  affect 
his  means,  as  in  the  case  of  calculations  founded  upon  the 
assumption  of  its  truth;  it  will  not  affect  his  principles. 
But  the  case  is  different  when  conduct  is  the  subject- 
matter  of  the  science.  The  belief,  then,  is  inseparably 
united  with  a  feeling.  The  belief  that  all  good  men  act  in 
a  certain  w^ay  must  have  a  reaction  upon  my  character  if  I 
have  any  feeling  in  regard  to  goodness  and  to  good  men. 
The  effect  will  depend  upon  my  previous  character,  but  in 
really  accepting  it  my  character  will  also  be  modified. 

7.  Let  us  apply  this  more  closely  to  the  case.  There  is 
a  law,  using  the  word  in  the  strict  sense  of  "  positive  law," 
against  murder.  From  a  scientific  point  of  view  this  is 
simply  a  statement  of  facts.  The  sociologist  asserts  the 
existence  of  a  certain  social  order  with  appropriate  customs 
and  instincts,  one  result  of  which  is  that  detected  murderers 
are  liable  to  hanging.  The  psychologist  recognises  and  tries 
to  explain  the  effect  produced  by  this  knowledge  upon  the 
mind  of  an  intending  murderer.  Their  conclusions  are 
expressible  as  statements  of  general  fact  or  scientific  "  laws  ; " 
murderers  are  hanged  at  certain  stages  of  social  develop- 
ment ;  all  men  of  a  certain  character  are  deterred  by  the 
fear  of  hanging,  and  so  forth.  The  effect,  again,  which  is 
produced  in  a  given  case  is  a  special  instance  of  these  laws. 
When  the  scientific  observer  has  laid  them  down,  he  has 
done  all  that  he  can  do.  The  man,  again,  who  is  about  to 
commit  a  murder  knows  the  facts  and  has  to  choose.  The 
choice  is  determined  not  merely  by  the  recognition  of  the 
scientific  truth  but  by  the  man's  character.  He  hates  his 
enemy,  and  is  aware  that  by  gratifying  his  hatred  he  runs 


440  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

a  risk  of  the  gallows.  His  action  is  the  correlative  of  the 
struggle  between  fear  and  hatred.  His  conduct  is  one  of 
the  facts  with  which  the  man  of  science  has  to  deal.  But 
in  any  case^  the  bare  intellectual  recognition  of  the  general 
proposition,  ^'Murderers  are  liable  to  hanging,"  is  not 
sufficient  to  determine  them.  The  recognition  will  operate 
differently  according  to  his  character.  If  it  is  a  genuine 
recognition,  involving  a  realisation  of  all  the  facts  implied,  it 
is  but  the  logical  aspect  of  an  emotional  process,  which  is 
symbolised  by  the  words.  He  must  have  a  foretaste  of  the 
various  horrors  connected  with  hanging;  and  the  painful 
foretaste  of  an  appearance  on  the  gallows  will  strug-gle  with 
the  pleasurable  foretaste  of  gratified  revenge  and  determine 
his  conduct.  For  him,  the  terror,  the  hatred,  are  facts ; 
actual  forces  which  move  him  one  way  or  the  other,  and 
which  are  rendered  possible  by  means  of  the  intellectual 
foresight,  as  it,  again,  is  only  possible  through  them;  that 
is,  neither  of  them  could  exist  separately. 

8.  We  may  say  the  same  of  the  moral  law.  The  socio- 
logist and  the  psychologist  have  to  describe  the  nature  and 
laws  of  action  of  the  moral  instincts,  as  in  the  other  case  of 
the  instincts  which  support  the  political  order.  And  in  the 
same  way,  the  agent  who  recognises  the  fact  that  murder  is 
wicked  as  well  as  criminal  will  act  according  to  the  resul- 
tant of  the  various  emotions  set  in  play  through  his  recog- 
nition of  that  accepted  principle.  These  emotions,  again,  it 
must  be  repeated,  may  vary  widely.  The  moral  sense  may, 
perhaps  generally  does,  correspond  simply  to  an  unreasoning 
instinct,  and  the  recognition  that  murder  is  wrong  may 
involve  nothing  but  the  action  of  this  unexplained  feeling. 
It  means  that  the  hatred  of  the  victim  is  checked  by  the 
awakening  of  the  acquired  instinct  which  makes  bloodshed 
hateful.  The  thought,  again,  that  murder  is  wrong  may 
call  into  play  other  emotions,  according  to  the  moral  theories 
accepted  by  the  agent.  It  may  bring  to  his  mind  the  wrath 
of  his  God,  or  the  injury  to  society,  or  the  hatred  which 
others  would  feel  for  him,  or  the  prospect  of  lasting  remorse, 


CONCLUSION.  441 

or  various  other  associated  emotions.  In  any  case,  it  means 
the  perception  of  other  modes  of  contemplating  the  pro- 
posed action  besides  that  which  suggested  the  murderous 
impulse,  and  the  bringing  into  play  of  the  various  emotions 
bound  up  with  these  perceptions.  The  command  is  only  a 
moral  command  so  far  as  it  appeals  to  the  intrinsically  moral 
motives,  whatever  they  may  be.  It  represents  a  force  in  so 
far  as  the  recoirnition  of  its  truth  involves  the  action  of  the 
strictly  moral  instincts. 

9.  We  may  now  return  to  the  difficulty.  It  is  quite  true 
that  the  simple  scientific  statement  does  not,  upon  my  show- 
ing, necessarily  carry  with  it  a  governing  principle.  That 
is  to  say  that  a  theory  of  motives  is  not  itself  a  motive.  The 
admission  that  the  moral  laws  are  statements  of  essential 
conditions  of  social  welfare  will  not  even  tend  to  make  me 
moral,  if  I  care  nothing  for  society.  If  I  am  incapable  of 
sympathy,  no  proof  of  the  adv^antages  of  good  actions  to 
others  will  induce  me  to  sacrifice  myself.  This,  however,  is 
merely  to  say,  with  every  moralist  who  ever  wrote,  that  the 
bare  moral  maxims  will  do  nothing  without  a  thorough 
training  of  the  emotional  nature.  We  must  not  merely 
learn  that  our  actions  affect  the  happiness  of  others,  but 
must  acquire  the  habit  of  feeling  for  them.  It  may,  indeed, 
be  said  that  a  nominal  acceptance  of  the  formula  can 
scarcely  be  called  a  real  belief  in  it,  unless  the  meaning  of 
the  symbols  is  realised  ;  and  so  far  to  teach  me  that  my 
conduct  hurts  others  is  to  make  me  feel  for  others  if  I  am 
capable  of  the  sympathy,  whilst  it  has  no  proper  meaning 
for  me  unless  I  am  capable  of  sympathy.  And  this  is  so  far 
true  that  a  genuine  assimilation  of  the  moral  precepts  may 
be  assumed  to  imply  a  growth  of  moral  sentiment.  To  learn 
really  to  appreciate  the  general  bearings  of  moral  conduct 
is  to  learn  to  be  moral  in  the  normally  constituted  man, 
though  we  must  always  make  the  condition  that  a  certain 
aptitude  of  character  exists.  But  in  saying  this  I  have  only 
recognised  the  fact  that  beyond  the  science  of  morality  there 
is  the  art  which  depends  upon  it. 


442  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

lo.  This,  however,  is  regarded  as  an  insufficient  statement. 
After  all,  it  is  said,  the  moral  system  remains  insufficiently 
clenched.  All  that  it  comes  to  is,  "  If  I  am  wicked,  I  shall 
commit  murder;  if  I  am  not  wicked,  I  shall  not."  The 
agent,  therefore,  simply  recognises  his  motives,  but  cannot 
alter  them  or  properly  approve  or  condemn  them.  The 
judge  can  say,  "  I  will  force  you  to  refrain  from  crime."  The 
moralist  can  only  say,  "  I  will  give  you  reasons  for  refraining 
ifyovL  are  already  good."  Hence  arises  the  desire  of  moral- 
ists to  prove  that  there  is  some  reason  binding  every  man 
simply  as  reasonable.  The  search,  if  I  am  right,  is  hopeless ; 
as  all  motives  in  every  case  involve  another  element.  In  any 
and  every  case,  the  compulsion,  legal  and  moral,  must 
depend  upon  the  character.  The  legal  sanction  appeals  to 
feelings  more  universal  than  the  moral,  though  the  moral 
has  the  advantage  of  covering  actions  which  the  legal  can- 
not touch;  but  even  the  legal  sanction  may  cease  to  be 
effective  in  conceivable  cases.  Its  highest  penalty  depends 
for  efficacy  upon  the  love  of  life ;  and  there  are  many  cir- 
cumstances under  which  a  man  may  cease  to  care  for  life, 
and  so  far  be  beyond  the  power  of  the  legislator.  The 
moralist,  undoubtedly,  can  only  appeal  to  people  who  have 
certain  instincts ;  for  an  appeal  to  extrinsic  motives  is  merely 
a  cutting  of  the  knot.  Unless  a  man  has  certain  sensibilities 
the  moralist  has  absolutely  no  leverage.  This  I  take  to  be 
a  simple  fact,  undeniable  in  practice,  and,  so  long  at  least 
as  we  have  to  deal  with  science,  a  fact  which  must  be  recog- 
nised like  any  other.  But  I  must  guard  against  one  misinter- 
pretation which  seems  to  be  implied  in  the  above  statement. 
It  is  true  (as  I  hold)  that  if  a  man  is  without  any  conscience 
you  cannot  move  him  by  speaking  of  right  and  wrong ; 
but  it  seems  to  be  inferred  that  this  is  in  some  way  a  justi- 
fication of  his  acting  wrongly.  This  is  a  sophistry.  It  is 
capable  of  proof — scientific  proof,  if  you  will — that  murder 
is  wrong — "  wrong"  as  opposed  to  the  rules  actually  accepted 
and  regarded  with  reverence  in  every  civilised  society,  and 
wrong,  again,  as  being  opposed  to  that   underlying  moral 


CONCLUSION.  443 

code  to  which  actual  morality  is  an  approximation,  and 
which  expresses  the  conditions  of  social  welfare.  I  may, 
therefore,  prove  to  the  murderer  that  he  is  acting  wickedly. 
But  he  says,  '^  I  have  no  conscience."  If  he  adds,  '^  There- 
fore I  shall  commit  murder,"  his  reasoning  is  perfectly 
sound.  If  he  goes  on,  "Therefore  I  am  right  in  committing 
murder,"  he  is  contradicting  himself.  The  true  inference 
is,  therefore,  "  I  am  wrong  by  my  own  confession."  Right 
conduct  is  the  conduct  dictated  by  a  conscience,  or  the 
conduct  (as  I  have  put  it)  of  the  ideal  man.  To  allege  the 
absence  of  good  motive  as  a  justification  is  nonsense,  because 
justification  means  the  proof  of  good  motives.  It  is,  there- 
fore, a  simple  "objective"  fact  that  a  man  acts  rightly  or 
wrongly  in  a  given  case,  and  a  fact  which  may  be  proved 
to  him  ;  and,  further,  though  the  proof  will  be  thrown  away 
if  he  is  a  moral  idiot,  that  is,  entirely  without  the  capacities 
upon  which  morality  is  founded,  the  proof  is  one  which 
must  always  affect  his  character,  if  we  suppose  the  truth 
to  be  assimilated,  and  not  the  verbal  formula  to  be  merely 
learnt  by  rote. 

II.  Here  we  are  approaching  the  inevitable  free-will 
puzzle.  I  am  content  to  say  once  more  that,  so  long  as  we 
are  in  the  region  of  science,  it  is  idle  to  evade  the  plain 
facts.  Many  men  are  wicked  ;  no  man  is  perfect.  No  dex- 
terous logic  will  make  the  wicked  man  good,  nor,  so  long 
as  it  appeals  to  motives  which  they  cannot  appreciate,  will  it 
convince  them  that  it  is  well  to  be  good.  The  man  of 
science,  indeed,  sometimes  tries  to  evade  this  painful  con- 
clusion. He  points  out  that  although  men  are  now  so 
constituted  that  right  conduct  is  often  painful  and  virtue 
itself  not  unconditionally  desirable,  this  discord  may  be  re- 
solved in  some  better  state.  Progress  means  approximation 
to  some  Utopia  in  which  our  natures  will  be  so  improved 
that  we  shall  always  sympathise  with  each  other,  and  society 
be  so  happily  constituted  that  the  conduct  which  gives  to 
any  man  the  greatest  chance  of  happiness  will  give  it  an 
equal  advantage  to  his  neighbours.     Such  speculations  are 


444  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

legitimate.  They  may  be  useful  in  defining  an  end  towards 
which  all  w^ell-wishers  to  their  fellows  may  desire  to  act, 
and  they  may  serve  also  to  bring  out  the  fact  that  altruistic 
emotion  does  not  involve  self-sacrifice  in  essence,  but  only  by 
accident.  Yet  it  does  not  solve  the  difficulty  for  us.  Specu- 
lations about  the  future  of  society  are  rash ;  and  the  know- 
ledge— if  we  could  attain  the  knowledge — that  our  descend- 
ants would  be  better  off  than  ourselves  would  not  disprove 
the  existence  of  the  present  evil.  Moreover,  various  doubts 
suggest  themselves.  We  cannot  tell  that  progress  will  be 
indefinite.  It  seems  rather  that  science  points  to  a  time  at 
which  all  life  upon  the  planet  must  become  extinct ;  and 
the  social  organism  may,  according  to  the  familiar  analogy, 
have  its  natural  old  age  and  death.  In  any  case  there  is 
one  obvious  difficulty.  Progress  means  a  stage  of  evolution. 
Evolution  from  the  earliest  to  the  latest  sta2;es  means  a  con- 
tinuous  process  of  adjustment,  which  is  always  determined 
by  the  fact  that  at  any  existing  stage  the  adjustment  is 
imperfect.  Complete  equilibrium,  or  an  elimination  of 
this  discordant  element,  would  therefore  mean,  ndt  perhaps 
stagnation,  but  a  cessation  of  progress,  an  attainment  of  the 
highest  arc  of  the  curve,  after  which  we  would  only  expect 
descent. 

12.  Consider,  in  fact,  what  is  meant  by  moral  progress. 
It  is  an  essential  part  of  a  development  in  virtue  of  which 
the  society  is  more  vigorous,  the  individual  is  bound  by 
further-reaching  sympathies  with  his  fellows,  and  thus  a 
more  comprehensive  code  of  conduct  is  recognised.  The 
member  of  the  higher  society  is  more  fully  conscious  of  the 
nature  and  consequences  of  his  actions  than  the  member  of 
the  lower  society.  In  this  sense,  therefore,  he  is  more  moral. 
The  higher  man  is  affected  by  sufferings  to  which  the  lower 
man  is  indifferent.  And  thus,  again,  conduct  which  would 
require  abnormal  excellence  at  the  lower  stage  has  become 
normal  as  the  corresponding  instincts  have  become  definitely 
organised  in  the  higher.  But,  in  another  sense,  the  moral 
progress  is  less   clear;   that  is  to  say,  the  savage  deviates 


CONCLUSION.  445 

less  frequently  than  the  civilised  man  from  the  code  recog- 
nised in  each  case.  The  savage  law  is  lower,  but  it  is  more 
regularly  observed.  So,  if  we  go  back  to  the  animals,  in 
whom  morality  proper  does  not  exist,  the  obedience  to  instinct 
is  more  regular  still.  Sin  comes  throuu;h  the  law,  as  it  is  only 
when  the  agent  is  capable  of  laying  down  general  rules  that 
be  begins  to  be  sensible  of  deviations  from  them.  If  we 
measure  both  stages  of  development  by  the  same  law,  we 
may  say  that  the  higher  is  more  moral  than  the  lower.  If 
we  measure  each  by  its  own  law,  the  observance  is  more 
uniform  in  the  lower  than  the  higher;  as,  in  fact,  a  greater 
mobility  and  flexibility  of  character  seems  to  be  necessarily 
implied  in  the  higher  type.  Moral  progress  involves  a  con- 
stant laying  down  of  new  problems.  Old  evils  are  avoided, 
old  hostilities  reconciled,  the  whole  life  is  fuller  and  more 
vigorous ;  but  the  process  implies  at  the  same  time  that  the 
new  capacities  and  sensibilities  developed  constantly  bring 
with  them  new  evils  or  difficulties  which  again  require  to  be 
reconsidered.  A  nation  acquires  new  mechanical  powers, 
but  it  has  not  yet  the  habits  necessary  to  turn  them  to 
account,  and  they  are  so  many  temptations  to  immoral  in- 
dulgence. Sympathy  expands,  but,  as  not  guided  by  know- 
ledge, leads  to  rash  changes  productive  of  evil  as  well  as  good. 
To  improve,  whether  for  the  race  or  the  individual,  whether 
in  knowledge  or  sympathy,  is  to  be  put  in  a  position  where  a 
new  set  of  experiments  has  to  be  tried,  and  experience  to 
be  bought  at  the  price  of  pain.  And  as  this  seems  to  be 
esssentially  implied  in  all  progress  that  we  can  imagine,  I 
see  no  reason  to  suppose  that  pain  will  be  eliminated,  or  that 
it  will  be  so  distributed  that  there  shall  never  be  a  diver2;ence 
between  the  painful  and  the  pernicious  either  to  man  or 
society.  From  the  scientific  point  of  view  we  may  hold  that 
evolution  implies  progress — progress  at  any  rate  to  a  point 
beyond  our  present  achievements ;  and,  further,  progress  im- 
plies a  solution  of  many  discords,  and  an  extirpation  of  many 
evils  J  but  I  can  at  least  see  no  reason  for  supposing  that  it 


446  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

implies  the  extirpation  of  evil  in  general  or  the  definitive 
substitution  of  harmony  for  discord. 

13.  We  may,  however,  and,  according  to  many  thinkers, 
we  must,  go  beyond  this  point  of  view.  We  may  find  in 
metaphysical  speculation  or  in  the  transcendental  world 
which  it  reveals  to  us  an  answer  to  the  doubt  and  a  solution 
of  the  discord.  Here,  indeed,  I  might  stop;  for  I  started  at 
the  outset  with  a  disavowal  of  any  desire  to  go  beyond  the 
scientific  boundary.  I  should  have  to  conclude  by  challenging 
the  metaphysician  to  dispute  the  truth  of  my  conclusions, 
and  should  urge  that  they  would  have  to  be  recognised  upon 
any  metaphysical  theory,  although  different  schools  would 
interpret  them  in  different  ways.  And  I  might  further 
decline  to  follow  the  metaphysician  into  his  own  ground. 
This,  I  might  say,  is  the  meaning  to  be  attached  to  morality 
so  long  as  we  remain  in  the  world  of  experience ;  and  if,  in 
the  transcendental  world,  you  can  find  a  deeper  foundation 
for  morality,  that  does  not  concern  me.  I  am  content  to 
build  upon  the  solid  earth.  You  may,  if  you  please,  go  down 
to  the  elephant  or  the  tortoise.  I  think  it  better,  however, 
to  indicate  my  own  view  in  the  briefest  way  possible.  For, 
in  the  first  place,  many  thinkers  consider  that  it  is  necessary 
to  begin  at  the  very  beginning ;  and  to  solve  the  whole 
problem  of  the  universe  before  they  get  down  to  morality. 
A  discussion  which  does  not  try  to  settle  the  issues  between 
materialism  and  idealism,  and  between  theism,  pantheism, 
and  atheism,  and  investigate  the  nature  of  the  ego,  is  from  their 
point  of  view  simply  frivolous.  It  touches  the  barest  outside 
of  the  question.  And,  in  the  next  place,  T  feel  that  I  may 
be  accused  of  unfair  reticence;  unless  I  proceed  further,  my 
antagonists  will  hold  that  my  dismissal  of  certain  problems 
to  the  metaphysician  is  a  juggle,  and  that  my  real  meaning 
is  that  the  problems  in  question  are  barren  logomachies, 
which  may  be  left  to  the  manufacturers  of  intellectual  cob- 
webs for  their  amusement,  but  not  for  the  instruction  of 
mankind.     In  which,  indeed,  there  seems  to  me  to  be  a  great 


CONCLUSION.  447 

deal  of  truth  ;  only  I  do  not  wish  to  conceal  my  opinions,  so 
far  as  I  have  any  settled  opinions. 

14.  To  ffive  a  satisfactory  answer,  I  should  have  to  write 
a  metaphysical  treatise;  for  without  such  a  discussion  I  could 
not  define  accurately  the  boundaries  between  metaphysics 
and  science.  And  I  must  add,  that  one  difficulty  which  I 
feel  is  that  mv  own  mind  is  not  as  clear  as  I  could  wish  upon 
these  questions.  I  can,  however — or  so  I  hope — indicate 
briefly  certain  crucial  points.  And  first  of  all,  I  will  say  that  I 
utterly  disbelieve  in  any  so-called  ontology.  I  regard  it  as  a 
barren  region  haunted  by  shadowy  chimeras,  mere  spectres, 
which  have  not  life  enough  in  them  even  to  be  wrong,  non- 
entities veiled  under  dexterously  woven  masses  of  verbiage. 
I  don't  believe  that  any  one  can,  by  any  device  whatever, 
spin  out  of  his  own  mind  a  demonstration  of  the  ultimate 
nature  of  things  in  general;  and  that  is  what  the  ontologist 
substantially  tries  to  do.  The  direct  arguments  against  such 
systems  are  not  more  conclusive  than  the  futility  of  the 
supposed  conclusions.  The  ontologist  proves  something  with 
infinite  display  of  logic;  and  if  you  admit  it  to  be  proved, 
you  find  that  the  admission  leaves  you  exactly  where  you 
were  before.  And  if  this  has  an  arrogant  sound,  I  can  only 
say  that  it  is  the  only  conclusion  compatible  with  a  due  re- 
spect for  philosophers.  For  when  1  look  at  the  vast  systems  set 
forth  and  supported  by  arguments  devised  by  the  most  famous 
thinkers,  and  consider  their  instability,  their  helpless  incapa- 
city to  withstand  assaults  or  to  solve  real  difficulties,  I  can 
only  infer  either  that  their  authors  were  fools — which  would  be 
the  height  of  arrogance — or  that  they  were  attempting  pro- 
blems beyond  the  reach  of  reason.  The  greatest  athlete  can- 
not get  off  his  own  shadow. 

15.  The  desired  consummation  of  some  approximation  to 
unity  is,  therefore,  as  I  hold,  to  be  sought  by  distinguishing 
the  metaphysical  from  the  scientific  problem.  Ethical  in- 
vestio-ations,  like  others,  will  have  some  definite  results 
when  we  turn  to  what  are  called  historical  methods  of 
inquiry.     This  is  true,  I  think,  of  the  allied  inquiries  into 


448  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

social,  and  political,  and  aesthetic  inquiry.  The  tendency  of 
modern  speculation  to  take  that  form,  and  to  look  into  the 
history  of  the  past  for  an  answer  to  problems  which  were 
once  attacked  by  looking  simply  into  our  own  minds,  im- 
plies a  recognition  of  this  principle.  And  I  believe  that  we 
may  look  for  some  approximation  to  agreement  as  the 
method  is  more  generally  adopted  and  more  systematically 
carried  out.  I  need  not  dwell  upon  the  nature  of  the 
advantage  thus  gained.  It  is  enough  to  say  that  when  we 
cease  to  ask  '^What  is  the  beautiful  or  the  moral?"  and  ask 
"  What  have  men  actually  admired  ? "  we  get  rid  of  the  many 
illusions  generated  by  mistaking  our  own  special  tastes  for 
universal  tastes ;  that  we  take  into  account  that  "  social 
factor,"  without  a  recognition  of  which  no  tenable  theory 
can  be  put  together,  and  that  we  have  an  advantage  com- 
parable to  that  gained  when  we  see  a  large  arc  of  a  curve 
instead  of  the  infinitesimal  fraction  perceptible  at  a  given 
moment.  To  this  it  is  often  replied  that  an  account  of  how 
things  come  to  be  is  after  all  radically  different  from  an 
account  of  what  they  are.  I  do  not  quite  admit  the  radical 
difference,  for  I  think  that  the  true  nature  of  a  thing  may 
reveal  itself  only  when  we  see  it  on  a  large  scale.  But  I 
admit  that  there  is  something  more  to  be  done,  and  that, 
after  all  that  can  be  said  by  the  man  of  science,  we  must 
still  come  upon  the  old  metaphysical  problems.  In  what 
form,  then,  do  they  enter  our  investigation  ? 

1 6.  When  we  have  taken  leave  of  ontology,  is  there  any- 
thing left  for  the  metaphysician?  Metaphysics  has  been 
described  as  a  theory  of  knowledge,  a  systematic  account  of 
all  that  can  be  said  about  knowledge  as  knowledge.  This 
must  not  be  understood  as  though  we  could  explain  what  is 
meant  by  knowledge  in  terms  of  something  different  from 
knowledge.  To  attempt  to  give  an  answer  of  that  kind 
would  be  to  attempt  to  get  outside  ourselves,  and  to  fall  into 
the  sham  philosophy  of  the  ontologists.  We  may  still,  it  is 
said,  be  able  to  understand  the  intimate  nature  of  knowledge, 
to  regard  it  as  a  vast  process  in  which  every  particular  de- 


CONCLUSION.  449 

partment  is  organically  connected  with  the  rest,  as  the 
special  manifestation  of  some  universal  principles.  To  try  to 
define  this  vague  suggestion  would  be  to  discuss  the  most 
thorny  metaphysical  problems.  It  is  enough  in  this  place 
if  I  endeavour  to  suggest  certain  conclusions.  It  is  much 
easier  to  say  what  metaphysics  are  not  than  to  say  what  they 
are.  And  I  say,  in  the  first  place,  that  though  it  may  be 
conceivably  possible  to  exhibit  the  most  general  forms  of 
knowledge  and  understand  their  relations,  no  such  theory 
would  enable  us  to  get  from  theory  of  knowledge  to  theory 
of  facts.  We  may  twist  and  turn  as  long  as  we  please,  but 
the  theory  of  knowledge  will  not  in  the  least  help  us  to  dis- 
cover the  actual  constitution  of  the  world.  We  cannot 
make  the  slightest  approach  to  explaining  why  human  beings 
should  be  constituted  as  they  are,  why  they  should  have 
such  and  such  senses  and  faculties,  and  no  more,  or  why 
matter  should  be  distributed  in  the  actual  combinations ;  and 
therefore,  as  it  seems  to  me,  wherever  there  is  a  question  of 
facts,  we  must  find  some  ground  of  knowledge  outside  of 
metaphysical  inquiries.  And  if,  in  the  next  place,  we  ask 
What  can  metaphysics  do  for  us?  I  can  only  reply  indirectly: 
A  man  is  a  sound  reasoner  when  his  thoughts  accurately 
reflect  the  external  world.  And  this,  as  we  come  to  see, 
implies  not  merely  correct  performance  of  logical  opera- 
tions, but  the  elimination  of  certain  fundamental  illusions 
generated  in  earlier  stages  of  thought.  Sound  metaphysics 
consist,  in  Berkeley's  phrase,  in  the  laying  of  the  dust  which 
we  have  ourselves  raised,  in  the  removal  of  certain  scaffold- 
ings which  have  been  useful  in  the  building  up  of  the  edifice, 
and  the  perception  that  they  are  not  essential  parts  of  the 
structure;  briefly,  in  becoming  distinctly  conscious  of  our 
own  mental  operations,  and  therefore  destroying  fallacies 
which  lie  at  the  base  of  all  logical  procedure.  If  this  be  any- 
thing like  the  accurate  statement — and  I  can  only  speak  in 
the  roughest  way — we  may  say  that  metaphysical  inquiry  is 
of  the  highest  importance  in  this  sense,  that  our  reasoning 
cannot  be  thoroughly  sound  unless  we  are  sound  metaphysi- 

2  F 


450  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

cians^  but  that  we  must  not  expect  from  metaphysics  any 
system  of  definite  statement  of  fact.  And  further^  we  must 
infer  that  legitimate  metaphysical  investigations  affect  know- 
ledge in  general,  but  have  no  special  relation  to  any  par- 
ticular department  of  knowledge. 

17.  My  view,  therefore,  is  that  the  science  of  ethics  deals 
with  realities  ;  that  metaphvsical  speculation  does  not  help  us 
to  ascertain  the  relevant  facts;  and,  therefore,  that  it  has  no 
more  relation  to  ethical  science  than  to  any  other  branch  of 
knowledge.  Our  statement  of  the  facts  will  be  modified  as 
our  metaphysical  creed  changes;  the  approximation  to  precise 
and  lasting  truth  will  be  made  closer,  and,  so  far,  the  science  of 
ethics  will  be  improved  by  metaphysical  progress.  But  ethical 
principles  are  onlv  affected  as  the  principles  of  all  other 
sciences  are  affected.  Though  I  cannot  offer  any  proof  of 
this  doctrine,  I  shall  try  briefly  to  show  how  it  bears  upon 
certain  cardinal  points;  and  why,  in  my  opinion,  it  is  useless 
to  look  for  any  further  light  from  metaphysical  inquiries. 
This  is  virtually  to  challenge  the  metaphysician  to  show  that 
he  is  of  anv  use  in  the  matter. 

18.  The  first  principle  which  I  have  sought  to  establish  is, 
briefly,  that  a  moral  rule  is  a  statement  of  a  condition  o^ 
social  welfare.  Temperance,  according  to  me,  is  proved  to 
be  immoral  by  the  same  methods  which  prove  it  to  be  un- 
wholesome. Scientific  observation  shows  that  it  is  productive 
of  diseased  states  either  of  the  individual  or  of  society.  In  great 
part  the  arguments  are  identical,  and  though  the  moralist 
has  to  go  into  questions  not  considered  by  the  physioloo-ist, 
he  still  uses  the  same  methods.  Moreover,  it  is  by  scientific 
observation  alone  that  the  facts  can  be  proved  ;  for  by  the 
purely  metaphysical  method  you  cannot  even  approach  the 
relevant  questions,  or  prove  even  the  advantages  of  drinkinsr, 
much  less  of  moderate  drinking.  What  is  true  in  this  case 
is  true,  according  to  me,  of  all  moral  problems.  They  can 
only  be  examined  when  we  have  some  knowledge  of  the 
organisation  of  man  and  of  society  which  is  unattainable  by 
any  other  than  the  scientific  method.     And  I  have  further 


CONCLUSION.  451 

urged  that  moral  systems  have  actually  grown  up  through  a 
recognition,  more  or  less  explicit,  of  these  truths.  Morality 
has  been  regarded  as  imposed  by  the  will  of  a  deity;  but  then 
it  is  taken  to  be  the  will  of  a  good  deity;  that  is,  of  a  deity  who 
wishes  well  to  mankind.  From  the  purely  utilitarian  point 
of  view,  it  is  regarded  as  a  statement  of  the  conditions  of 
happiness;  but  the  happiness  is  that  of  beings  whose  character 
is  already  determined  at  all  points  by  their  being  part  of  the 
social  organism,  and  the  sentiment  can  only  become  part  of 
the  social  instinct  when  it  is  purified  from  any  individual 
aberration. 

19.  If  this,  which  it  has  been  my  purpose  to  prove,  be 
admitted,  what  is  the  relation  of  the  ethical  to  the  meta- 
physical theory?  The  metaphysician,  as  I  take  it,  has  a 
locus  standi  only  so  far  as  he  can  throw  light  upon  the  general 
conditions  of  belief,  or,  again,  upon  the  nature  of  certain  ulti- 
mate distinctions,  such  as  that  of  object  and  subject,  taken 
for  granted  in  the  scientific  statement.  The  ontologist, 
indeed,  and  the  theologian  claim  to  do  more;  for  ontology, 
as  I  believe,  is  but  the  spectre  of  theology,  the  caput  mortuum 
to  which  it  is  reduced  when  the  attempt  is  made  to  purify  it 
from  all  sensuous  and  anthropomorphic  elements.  But  what 
more  is  required  ?  If  you  assert  that  morality  does  not  coin- 
cide with  the  conditions  of  social  welfare,  you  have  not  only 
to  meet  the  direct  aro;umentsalle2;ed  in  favour  of  the  identitv, 
but  to  give  some  other  criterion  of  morality.  If,  for  ex- 
ample, the  criterion  be  conformity  to  the  will  of  a  deitv 
who  commands  men  to  transgress  the  conditions  of  social 
welfare,  we  have  to  meet  the  reply  that  the  deity  is  malevolent 
and  commands  a  false  morality,  or  rather  imposes  an  im- 
moral rule.  Even  the  most  ascetic  system,  according  to  me, 
carries  with  it  a  tacit  reference  to  social  welfare,  and  the 
deviations  are  due  to  errors  of  judgment  as  to  the  facts.  In 
any  case,  if  the  criterion  be  rejected,  morality  is  arbitrary 
until  some  further  criterion  be  suggested.  The  impossibility 
of  any  such  attempt  is  so  clear,  that  it  may  be  almost  taken 
for  granted  that  the  coincidence  between  morality  and  the 


452  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

conditions  of  social  welfare  is  admitted.  But  if  so,  the  rule  is 
given  by  the  conditions.  If  it  be  admitted  tliat  this  coin- 
cidence exists  in  fact ;  if,  again,  it  be  admitted  that  the 
social  utility  of  certain  kinds  of  conduct  and  character  can 
be  proved,  and  that,  if  proved,  they  become  for  that  reason 
"right"  and  "virtuous,"  then  it  seems  to  follow  that  the 
moral  law  is  actuallv  established  in  the  way  suggested,  namelv, 
by  observation  of  the  facts.  You  may  perhaps  prove  that 
the  deity  approves  obedience  to  the  law  thus  established ; 
but  for  the  mere  fact  of  ascertaining  the  law,  the  observation 
is  the  sole  and  sufficient  method.  Nor  can  vou  know  that 
the  deity  approves  otherwise  than  by  knowing  that  he  is  good, 
that  is,  desires  the  welfare  of  mankind. 

20.  The  same  arguments  take  a  different  form  in  the  case 
of  metaphysical  discussion.  The  ontologist  insists  that 
morality  cannot  be  established  until  "materialism"  be  con- 
futed. To  this  I  should  answer,  that  for  scientific  purposes 
the  discussion  is  irrelevant,  I  can  prove  that  unselfishness 
and  all  the  qualities  which  require  intellectual  development 
are  essential  conditions  of  social  welfare.  If  the  materialist 
can  prove  that  the  emotions  and  the  intellect  are  in  some 
sense  mere  dances  of  atoms,  I  can  only  reply  that  in  that 
case  atoms  have  more  in  them  than  I  should  have  supposed, 
but  that  the  phenomena  which  I  take  into  account  remain 
the  same.  And  meanwhile,  from  the  scientific  point  of 
view,  I  can  obtain  a  solution  of  the  real  problem,  which  the 
ontologist  cannot  approach.  For  as  the  organism  has  both 
physical  appetites  and  intellectual  emotions,  and  as  the  condi- 
tions of  social  welfare  require  a  certain  balance  between  the 
faculties,  and  not  the  abolition  of  either  class  of  faculties, 
the  study  of  those  conditions  gives  a  measure  of  the  degree 
in  which  the  intellect  should  be  developed;  so  far,  namely,  as 
is  consistent  with  the  health  of  the  whole  organism  ;  whereas 
any  absolute  conclusion  as  to  the  merit  of  intellectual 
and  physical  parts  of  our  nature  abstractedly  from  the 
conditions  of  life,  would  be  futile  because  absolute.  The 
metaphysician,  however,  more  frequently  takes  a  position 


CONCLUSION.  453 

corresponding  to  that  of  the  theologian  who  allows  the 
coincidence  between  morality  and  social  welfare,  and  only 
disputes  as  to  the  mode  of  proof.  The  metaphysician  dis- 
tinguishes between  the  form  and  the  contents  of  duty.  He 
does  not  deny  that  in  any  special  case  we  must  discover 
what  is  right  by  observing  the  facts,  and  that  the  fact  that 
a  given  action  will  make  men  happier  is  so  far  a  proof  that 
it  is  a  right  action ;  but  he  argues  that  the  conception  of 
"  duty/'  of  "  ought,"  or  of  "  right  and  wrong,"  must  be 
independently  obtainable.  The  question,  which  involves  the 
basis  of  a  whole  metaphysical  system,  cannot  be  adequately 
argued  here.  But  I  may  answer  briefly,  first,  that  even 
upon  this  assumption,  the  science,  if  there  be  a  science,  of 
the  conditions  of  social  welfare  must  be  of  essential  impor- 
tance to  morality;  for,  if  it  leads  to  any  conclusions,  those 
conclusions  will  immediately  determine  the  morality  of  some 
classes  of  conduct.  If  I  can  prove  drunkenness  to  be  socially 
mischievous,  I  shall  certainly  prove  it  to  be  wicked.  The  blank 
concept  "  right  and  wrong"  will  be  of  no  use  till  I  can  pro- 
vide it  with  contents  upon  which  to  operate  ;  and  therefore 
the  science  of  ethics  will  still  be  of  paramount  importance 
if  it  can  be  established.  And,  secondly,  I  answer  that,  upon 
my  showing,  this  is  really  a  perversion  of  a  plain  principle. 
In  the  metaphysical  region  you  may  come  across  ultimate 
canons  of  truth,  but  by  no  conceivable  ingenuity  upon  prin- 
ciples of  action.  And,  in  fact,  we  find  accordingly  that 
thinkers  who  accept  this  position  have  to  make  the  most 
desperate  efforts  to  twist  the  "  ought "  out  of  the  "  is."  The 
ultimate  principles  which  they  propose  are  simply  logical 
principles  in  a  thin  disguise.  So,  for  example,  the  famous 
theorem  that  you  are  to  act  so  that  your  rule  of  conduct  may 
be  a  rule  for  all  men  is  a  transfigured  bit  of  logic.  To  think 
so  that  my  thoughts  may  be  true  for  everybody,  is  perhaps  a 
description  of  thinking  that  is  objectively  true.  But,  as  I 
have  already  argued,  the  theorem  as  stated  is  strictly  true  of 
all  conduct  whatever.  I  cannot  help  acting  in  the  way  in 
which  every  one  would  act  with  my  character  and  under 


454  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

the  same  circumstances ;  nor,  upon  my  showing,  has  this 
proposition  more  to  do  with  moral  conduct  than  with  any 
other  kind  of  conduct ;  nor  has  it  more  to  do  with  the 
narrowest  and  most  prudential  than  with  the  most  sym- 
pathetic and  self-sacrificing  principles.  And  this  is  only 
what  we  must  expect,  if,  in  fact,  metaphysical  inquiry  has, 
as  I  maintain,  no  special  relation  to  ethics,  and  can  only  be 
forced  into  relation  with  it  by  ingenious  sophistry. 

21.  Let  us  pass  to  the  next  head  under  which  I  have  con- 
sidered morality.  It  is  argued  that  without  some  transcen- 
dental principle  there  is  no  adequate  foundation  for  morality; 
and  this,  not  in  the  sense  just  considered,  that  the  moral  law 
remains  indeterminate,  but  in  the  sense  of  our  having  no 
security  for  its  permanence,  I  have  already  explained  at 
full  length  my  own  theory.  Morality,  I  have  said,  is  a. 
product  of  the  social  factor;  the  individual  is  moralised 
through  his  identification  with  the  social  organism ;  the 
conditions,  therefore,  of  the  security  of  morality  are  the 
conditions  of  the  persistence  of  society ;  and  if  we  ask  from 
the  scientific  point  of  view  what  these  conditions  are,  we  can 
only  reply  by  stating  that  the  race  is  dependent  upon  the 
environment;  by  tracing,  so  far  as  we  are  able,  the  conditions 
under  which  it  has  been  developed,  and  trying  to  foresee  the 
future  from  the  past.  We  may,  again,  appeal  to  the  meta- 
physician if  we  want  to  examine  into  the  validity  and  the 
various  implications  of  the  ultimate  principles  involved  in  our 
argument.  Only  from  science,  if  from  science,  can  we  learn 
anything,  however  trifling,  as  to  the  order  of  actual  existence 
in  the  present  or  the  future.  Our  hopes  and  our  fears  must 
be  alike  based  upon  our  experience,  and  upon  nothing  else. 
The  theologian  who  pronounces  this  procedure  to  be  in- 
sufficient has  to  meet  the  dif^culty  after  his  own  fashion. 
We  can  only  feel  confidence  in  the  existence  of  that  which 
rests  upon  a  transcendental  basis.  Morality  has  a  pre- 
carious position,  therefore,  unless  we  believe  in  a  moral 
governor  of  the  universe.  But  here  immediately  arise  the 
whole  array  of  insuperable  difficulties  over  which  theologians 


CONCLUSION.  455 

have  vainly  struggled  since  theology  existed.  It  is  enough 
to  hint  at  them.  What  is  a  moral  governor?  A  governor 
who  makes  his  subjects  moral  ?  No,  for  many  men  are 
wicked.  Could  he  prevent  their  being  wicked  ?  If  he  could 
and  did  not,  we  have  no  security  for  his  willing  them  to  be 
moral.  If  he  did  not  because  he  could  not,  his  willing  them  to 
be  moral  will  not  secure  the  existence  of  morality.  He  can, 
however,  secure  the  punishment  of  the  wicked;  and  therefore, 
if  moral  government  does  not  mean  the  immediate  morality 
of  the  universe,  it  means  the  ultimate  rule  of  justice.  What, 
then,  is  justice?  It  means,  in  brief,  that  punishment  should 
be  impartial,  and  should  be  proportioned  to  the  offence. 
Now,  if  the  wicked  are  to  be  punished  impartially,  they  must 
be  punished  in  proportion  to  their  wickedness;  that  is,  for 
the  wickedness  due  to  their  own  character,  not  to  the  acci- 
dental circumstances.  But  their  own  character  means  their 
innate  qualities,  that  is,  the  qualities  with  which  they 
were  created ;  or,  in  other  words,  the  Creator  as  governor 
punishes  them  exactly  for  being  what  he  made  them.  Again, 
the  punishment  is  "  proportioned  "  to  the  offence.  How  is 
the  proportion  to  be  determined?  Surely  the  perfection  of 
human  justice  is  measured  by  its  efficiency.  That  system  is 
best  which  most  diminishes  crime.  But  if  we  apply  this  rule 
to  divine  justice  we  get  into  hopeless  difficulties.  We  must 
suppose  that  the  Creator  wishes  to  diminish  wickedness  as 
much  as  possible,  for  otherwise  he  would  inflict  useless  suf- 
fering. Yet  we  have  to  suppose  that  he  inflicts  punishments 
— infinite  and  eternal,  according  to  the  most  logical  theo- 
logians— in  such  a  wav  that  the  reforming  influence  is  a 
minimum  and  the  sufferino-  a  maximum.  If  a  human  ruler 
admitted  that  the  punishments  inflicted  by  his  laws  had  very 
little  deterrent  effi^ct,  but  argued  as  a  set-off  that  he  kept  the 
greatest  part  of  his  subjects  in  perpetual  confinement  and 
incessant  torture,  we  should  certainly  say  that,  whether 
by  his  misfortune  or  fault,  he  had  a  very  ill-regulated  king- 
dom. Yet,  when  we  try  to  reconcile  ourselves  to  the  exist- 
ing  evils   by  assuming   the  existence  of   this   supernatural 


456  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

balance,  we  necessarily  present  the  universe  after  this 
fashion.  Whether  it  is  an  edifying  theory  or  not  I  can- 
not say.  I  do  not  see  how  it  helps  to  strengthen  our 
belief  in  the  safeguards  of  morality.  The  explanation  is 
simple  enough.  The  world  is  what  we  see  it,  abounding  in 
misery  and  wickedness.  If  you  believe  in  a  moral  governor, 
you  are  bound  to  put  extraordinary  limitations  upon  his 
power  to  vindicate  his  benevolence,  or  to  limit  his  benevo- 
lence in  order  to  vindicate  his  power;  and,  in  either  case, 
you  take  away  with  one  hand  that  safeguard  to  morality 
which  you  give  with  the  other.  Meanwhile^  in  any  case, 
you  have  to  stop  all  logical  gaps  by  talking  about  mystery. 
It  is  simpler  to  admit  that  the  whole  is  a  mystery,  and  to 
cease  the  effort  to  play  ourselves  with  words. 

23.  The  ontolon;ist  sees  the  weakness  of  the  theolocrical  arsxu- 
ment  and  tries  to  remedy  it.  The  puzzle  is  that  virtue  may  be 
painful  and  vice  pleasant.  You  cannot  really  get  rid  of  this 
difficulty  by  adding  extrinsic  considerations,  by  assuming  that 
virtue  will  always  meet  with  a  reward  either  from  man  or 
God,  and  so  the  initial  error  be  made  up  by  a  subsequent 
compensation.  The  hypothesis  cannot  be  made  to  work,  and 
makes  a  fresh  breach  with  every  attempted  repair.  The 
ontologist  therefore  cuts  at  the  very  root  of  the  difficulty, 
not  by  saying  that  the  balance  will  be  redressed,  or  by  admit- 
ting the  mystery — for  to  him  there  is  no  mystery — but  by  boldly 
asserting  that  evil  is  merely  a  negative  term,  a  privation,  not 
a  positive  existence,  or,  in  short,  that  in  some  way  or  other  it 
does  not  exist  at  all.  If  it  is  any  satisfaction  to  anybody  to 
repeat  such  phrases,  it  would  be  a  pity  to  deprive  them  of  it, 

23.  I  come  to  the  final  question  about  morality,  and  the 
most  difficult.  Must  we  not  go  to  transcendental  considera- 
tions in  order  to  find  a  sufficient  motive  for  moral  conduct  ? 
This  brings  us  back  to  the  previous  argument.  To  say  what 
morality  is — I  repeat  the  statement  once  more — is  by  no 
means  the  same  thing  as  to  enforce  morality.  It  is  not 
when  one  is  approaching  the  last  page  of  an  ethical  essay 
that    one   can   have  any   illusions    upon    that    point.     Un- 


CONCLUSION.  457 

doubtedly  a  man  may  have  very  clear  conceptions  about 
the  nature  of  morahty,  and  yet  may  receive  from  that 
cireumstance  a  very  sHght  impulse  towards  being  himself 
moral.  Beyond  the  science,  I  have  said,  lies  the  art ;  when 
we  have  admitted  the  truth,  it  has  still  to  become  an  operative 
influence  in  moulding  our  characters.  The  abstract  formula 
may  be  admitted  without  producing  any  vivid  representa- 
tion of  concrete  facts ;  the  imagination  has  to  be  stimu- 
lated as  well  as  the  intellect  to  be  convinced  ;  and  there  is 
still  much  to  be  done  before  the  character  is  moulded,  so  that 
the  actual  impulse  shall  in  each  case  represent  the  general 
principle.  A  man  may  be  forced  to  comply  with  external 
morality  by  some  appeal  to  extrinsic  motives ;  but  to  make 
him  really  moral  we  must  stimulate  the  intrinsic  motives; 
and  this  must  be  in  all  cases  the  product  of  the  pressure  put 
upon  him  in  gradually  imbibing  the  principles  developed  by 
the  social  factor.  This  is  recognised  in  the  statement  that  a 
religion  is  always  more  than  a  morality.  It  is  not  a  mere 
statement  that  certain  rules  of  conduct  are  desirable,  but  it 
is  such  an  embodiment  of  some  theory  of  the  universe  as 
may  impress  the  imagination  and  govern  the  emotions. 

24.  Here,  in  fact,  arises  a  vast  problem  or  series  of  pro- 
blems at  which  only  the  briefest  glance  is  possible.  The  rela- 
tion between  morality  and  religion  suggests  at  once  whole 
libraries  of  controversy  and  lifetimes  of  investigation.  A 
religion  implies  a  theory  of  the  universe.  It  rests  upon  some 
doctrine  as  to  the  ultimate  facts  ascertainable  about  human 
life  and  the  world  in  which  we  live ;  and  therefore,  of 
course,  every  moral  theory  is  based  upon,  or  at  least  closely 
implicated  in,  the  religious  doctrines  of  the  persons  who  hold 
it.  Whatever  is  meant  by  "  best,"  we  can  only  say  what  is 
best  for  man  as  man  by  considering  him  as  part  of  the 
general  system.  But  many  relations  are  equally  possible. 
The  theory,  for  example,  that  the  universe  is  governed  by 
some  inscrutable  and  invisible  power  may  be  worked  out 
with  little  reference  to  morality  j  the  gods  may  be  conceived 


438  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

as  indifferent  to  moral  considerations,  and  when  a  moral 
system  is  evolved  they  may  take  up  very  different  attitudes 
in  regard  to  it ;  whilst,  again,  in  some  systems  the  supreme 
power  may  be  regarded  as  essentially  moral,  and  perhaps  as 
revealed  to  us  through  the  conscience.  In  any  case,  where 
there  is  a  philosophical  religion  the  ethical  doctrine  will 
doubtless  be  vitally  connected  with  the  religious,  and  will 
be  stated  partly  in  religious  language ;  and  therefore  every 
srreat  relio-ious  crisis  has  a  moral  reaction.  Sometimes  it  is 
due  to  a  moral  revolt:  the  gods  are  opposed  to  the  interests 
of  morality,  and  are  punished  by  being  abolished.  In  other 
cases,  they  may  be  on  the  side  of  morality,  and  a  disbelief  in 
their  existence,  due  to  some  other  cause,  may  weaken  the 
respect  entertained  for  the  moral  rule.  To  examine  into  the 
complex  processes  of  thought  and  feeling  thus  set  up  must 
always  be  a  task  of  immense  difficulty.  I  only  hint  at  such 
questions  to  draw  one  conclusion.  A  religion,  so  far  as  it 
is  moral  (for,  of  course,  many  religions  have  a  very  question- 
able relation  to  morality),  must  act  by  stimulating  the  intrin- 
sic motives  to  morality.  Further,  it  can  act  only  through 
the  genuine  belief  which  it  embodies  ;  and  thus  when  we 
wish  to  estimate  the  effect  of  a  religion  upon  morality,  we 
come  at  once  to  a  further  problem. 

25.  In  what  sense,  we  have  to  ask,  is  a  belief  the  ultimate 
condition  of  conduct?  We  may,  as  it  is  easy  to  see,  fall 
into  great  diff  culties,  unless  we  can  say  also  what  governs 
the  belief.  So  long,  indeed,  as  a  man  has  a  certain  belief, 
we  may  say  that  it  does  not  matter  what  was  the  origin  of 
the  belief,  nor  whether  it  were  true  or  false.  A  man  will 
refrain  from  conduct  if  he  fears  to  be  punished,  whether  the 
punishment  dreaded  is  to  come  from  a  real  or  an  imaginary 
being.  The  fear  of  hell,  so  long  as  people  believe  in  hell, 
may  be  a  genuine  restraint  just  as  much  as  the  fear  of  the 
o-allows.  But  there  is  an  obvious  difference  between  the 
cases.  The  fear  of  a  real  enemy  may  be  due  to  actual  ex- 
perience.    We  explain  the  belief  sufficiently  by  supposing 


CONCLUSION.  459 

the  enemy  to  exist  and  to  be  perceived.  But  when  wc 
have  to  deal  with  the  imae:inarv  enemy,  we  have  alwavs  a 
possible  explanation  of  a  different  kind.  There  must  have 
been  some  cause  for  the  imagination ;  and  that  cause  may 
be  something  which  is  not  removed,  and  which  is  still  opera- 
tive when  the  existence  of  the  imaginary  enemy  is  disproved. 
If  the  fear  of  the  enemy  be  the  sole  cause  of  abstinence  from 
the  conduct,  the  conduct  will  cease  to  be  disagreeable  when 
the  enemy  is  no  longer  feared.  But  the  case  may  be  entirely 
diflferent.  Perhaps  the  conduct  was  found  to  produce  dis- 
agreeable consequences  ;  they  were  erroneously  explained  as 
due  to  the  hostility  of  an  imaginary  being;  and  though  the 
being  is  proved  not  to  exist,  the  same  consequences  will 
result,  and  will,  as  soon  as  recognised,  still  dictate  abstinence 
from  the  conduct. 

26.  This,  of  course,  applies  to  the  case  of  so-called  religious 
sanctions.  Is  the  dread  of  hell  the  cause  of  abstinence  from 
vice  ?  It  may  no  doubt  be  the  immediate  cause  for  the  in- 
dividual. If  a  man  believe  that  drunkards  will  be  damned, 
that  is  for  him  a  sufficient  cause  for  abstainino-  •  and  if  vou 
prove  to  him  that  hell  is  a  fiction,  he  may  become  a  drunkard. 
But  this  is  an  obviously  inadequate  account  of  the  whole 
phenomenon.  If  this  belief  in  hell  were  the  result  of  scientific 
inquiry,  if  the  tendency  of  drunkenness  to  produce  damna- 
tion were  proved  like  its  tendency  to  produce  delirium 
tremens,  the  explanation  would  be  sufficient.  We  should 
say  simply  that  the  existence  of  a  known  place  of  torment 
was  one  of  the  causes  which  limited  drunkenness.  But  if 
hell  be  an  imaginary  place  we  must  necessarily  go  further. 
People  are  afraid  of  being  damned  for  drunkenness,  and 
therefore  they  do  not  drink.  But  why  do  they  anticipate 
damnation  as  a  consequence  of  drunkenness?  Obviously 
they  must  think  it  hateful  for  some  independent  reason. 
They  think  that  drunkards  will  be  damned  because  they 
think  drunkenness  hateful ;  or  at  any  rate,  the  belief  in  the 
damnation  of  drunkards  has  arisen  from  a  perception  of  its 


46o  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

other  evil  consequences.  The  supposed  ultimate  ground, 
therefore,  of  the  dislike  is  itself  a  corollary  from  the  dis- 
like. We  must  distinguish  between  the  social  and  the 
individual  creed.  A  given  person  may  be  influenced  solely 
by  the  belief  which  he  has  accepted  from  his  neighbours, 
whether  it  be  true  or  false.  But  the  belief  has  been  developed 
in  the  society  from  a  perception  of  the  evil,  and  is  a  product 
of  that  perception,  not  the  determining  cause. 

27.  Thus  the  true  statement  of  the  case  will  be,  upon  my 
theory,  that  the  limiting  and  determining  cause  of  the  moral  . 
objection  to  vice  is  in  all  cases  measured  by  the  percept i^ui 
of  the  social  evils  which  it  causes.  Whilst  the  society  is 
permeated  by  a  belief  in  the  supernatural,  this  perception 
has  to  express  itself  in  terms  of  the  supernatural  sanction ; 
and  to  a  man  who  is  a  member  of  such  a  society,  who  really 
explains  the  phenomena  in  general  as  significant  of  the  action 
of  a  supernatural  being,  it  is  the  same  thing  to  say  that 
conduct  is  harmless,  and  to  say  that  it  is  not  punished  super- 
naturally.  But  as  the  belief  in  such  interference  decays, 
the  perception  of  the  pernicious  consequences  which  expressed 
itself  in  terms  of  hell  may  use  a  difterent  language  without 
being  therefore  less  efficacious.  The  motive  alleged  in  the 
old  dialect  was  nominally  indeed  of  infinite  weight,  but  the 
effect  upon  conduct  was  entirely  disproportionate,  because, 
in  the  first  place,  it  did  not  correspond  to  a  genuine  belief, 
and,  in  the  second  place,  the  imaginary  penalty  would  always 
be  supposed  capable  of  evasion  by  imaginary  remedies.  The 
difference  upon  this  showing  is  not  in  the  strength  of  the 
motive,  but  in  the  dialect  which  has  to  be  used  to  accommodate 
it  to  the  prevailing  system  of  belief.  The  ethical  sentiment 
becomes,  however,  stable  and  demonstrable  when  that  which 
is  the  real  cause  of  its  development  is  recognised  as  being 
also  its  sufficient  reason,  and  when  people  find  in  the  various 
motives  which  command  a  conformity  to  the  social  interest 

a  sufficient  ground  of  conduct. 

28.  I  cannot  expand  this  further  at  present.    I  conclude  by 


CONCLUSION.  461 

one  remark  which  it  suggests,  and  which  seems  to  require 
explicit  statement.  It  is  sometimes  said  that  science  cannot 
provide  a  new  basis  of  morality  j  and  this  is  urged  as  though 
it  were  an  objection.  I  at  least  must  thoroughly  accept  the 
statement.  What  science  proves,  according  to  me,  is  pre- 
cisely that  the  only  basis  of  morality  is  the  old  basis ;  it 
shows  that  one  and  the  same  principle  has  always  determined 
the  development  of  morality,  although  it  has  been  stated  in 
different  phraseology.  And,  moreover,  this  principle  is  not 
the  suggestion  of  any  end  distinct  from  all  others.  The 
great  forces  which  govern  human  conduct  are  the  same  that 
they  always  have  been  and  always  will  be.  The  dread  of 
hunger,  thirst,  and  cold  ;  the  desire  to  gratify  the  passions ; 
the  love  of  wife  and  child  or  friend ;  sympathy  with  the 
sufferings  of  our  neighbours;  resentment  of  injury  inflicted 
upon  ourselves — these  and  such  as  these  are  the  great  forces 
which  govern  mankind.  When  a  moralist  tries  to  assign 
anything  else  as  an  ultimate  motive,  he  is  getting  beyond 
the  world  of  realities.  If  a  theologian  tells  me  to  love  my 
mother  because  God  commands  me  to  love  her,  he  is  invert- 
ing the  true  order  of  thought.  My  love  of  those  who  are 
nearest  to  my  sympathies  must  be  the  ultimate  ground  of 
any  love  that  I  can  have  for  anybody  else.  My  desire  for 
the  welfare  of  my  race  grows  out  of  my  desire  for  the  wel- 
fare of  my  own  intimates;  and  that  exists  independently 
of  any  ethical  theory  whatever.  A  theoloirical  basis  of 
morality  is  conceivable  so  far  as  the  supreme  being  is  repre- 
sented as  knowable  and  lovable;  but  to  order  morality  in 
the  name  of  logical  consistency  is  reasonable  only  when 
I  can  stir  men's  blood  by  assuming  that  two  and  two  make 
four.  On  my  theory,  then,  the  moralist  assigns  no  new 
motives ;  he  accepts  human  nature  as  it  is,  and  he  tries  to 
show  how  it  may  maintain  and  improve  the  adv^antages 
already  acquired.  His  influence  is  little  enough ;  but, 
such  as  it  is,  it  depends  upon  the  fact  that  a  certain  har- 
mony has  already  come  into  existence ;  and  that  men  are 


462  THE  SCIENCE  OF  ETHICS. 

therefore  so  constituted  that  they  desire  a  more  thorougli 
solution  of  existing  discords.  A  sound  moral  system  is 
desirable  in  order  to  give  greater  definiteness  to  the  aims 
and  methods ;  and  it  is  doubtless  important  to  obtain  one 
in  a  period  of  rapid  decay  of  old  systems.  But  it  is  happy 
for  the  world  that  moral  progress  has  not  to  wait  till  an 
unimpeachable  system  of  ethics  has  been  elaborated. 


THE    END. 


I'RINTED  BV  BALLANTYNE,  HANSON  AND  CO. 
EDINbURGH  ANU  LONDON 


^ 


university  ol  California  ^ 

SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  L1BRABV_FAC,L^33, 

^°=  tls'ANGELls,  c'uf'oRNIA  90095-1388 


L 


Form  L9-11 


UC  SOUTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY 


/ 


t 


PLEA?5:  DO    NOT    REMOVE 
THIS    BOOK  CARDz!] 


^ILIBRARY(9/C 


^ 


lo  - 


University  Research  Library 


"^8  01205  2428 


_;3 

_J 

.J 

J 

J 

1 


J3 

C 

o 
o 


0) 

CD 

1\J 


;t 


> 

c 
-1 

X 

o 

70 


V 


■1'^' ■''■!!»'' Will  1  "I  ft#K'nTO'P'»«T^^ 


<  r.  If  . 


Ifr  '4 


n:>i 


«  « 


%*-• 


\  n  Iff  *i  ;f  tw  ,*v  i 


M      ?vlSr      J6     ^    ^      r?       '      ^     *^     St      - 


m:m  I 


if:.  W 


Ir  *