Skip to main content

Full text of "Sevem theistic philosophers : an historico-critical study"

See other formats


ALVMNVS  BOOK  FYND 


Seven  Theistic   Philosophers 


Seven 
Theistic     Philosophers 

An  Historico-Critical  Study 


BY 


JAMES   LINDSAY, 

M.A.,  D.D.,  B.Sc.,  F.R.S.E.,  &c., 

AUTHOR   OF 

A   PHILOSOPHICAL   SYSTEM   OF  THEISTIC   IDEALISM, 
'STUDIES   IN   EUROPEAN   PHILOSOPHY,'   ETC. 


William   Blackwood   &   Sons 

Edinburgh  and  London 

1920 


ALL  RIGHTS  RESERVED 


PREFACE. 


THE  modern  world,  in  its  awakened  interest  in  Per- 
sonality, alike  in  God  and  in  man,  owes  a  greater 
debt  to  the  "  Seven  Theistic  Philosophers  "  treated  of 
in  this  work,  than  has  been  at  all  realised.  They 
belong,  for  most  philosophical  students,  to  the  "  illus- 
trious unknown."  But  no  enlightened  theist  can 
afford  to  be  indifferent  to  their  historic  place,  work, 
and  influence.  They  belong  to  that  School  of  Spec- 
ulative Theology,  or  Theistic  School  of  Philosophers, 
whose  wrk  and  influence  in  the  mid -nineteenth 
century  will  be  found  described  in  the  text.  Prof. 
Flint,  in  his  '  Theism,'  named  the  chief  thinkers  of 
this  philosophic  group,  but  gave  no  exposition  or 
criticism  of  their  "  profound  theories  "  (p.  433).  Dr 
Merz,  in  his  massive  work  on  the  '  History  of  Euro- 
pean Thought  in  the  Nineteenth  Century/  makes 
but  a  passing  mention  of  only  three  of  them.  Since 
they  have  never  been  dealt  with  by  any  British 
writer,  it  seemed  to  me  that  some  account  of  them 

43252S 


VI  PREFACE. 

was  long  past  due,  for  the  credit  of  British  philoso- 
phical knowledge  and  interest.  I  have  only  sought 
to  present  the  quintessence  of  their  thought,  but  the 
account  is  as  extended  as  the  interest  of  most 
English  readers  seemed  likely  to  require.  The 
study  here  presented  is  an  historico-critical  one,  and 
this  has  made  it  of  more  vital  interest,  because  it 
has  afforded  me  opportunity  to  bring  the  discussion 
at  many  points  into  critical  contact  with  the  discus- 
sions of  to-day.  It  has  in  many  ways  not  been  an 
easy  or  auspicious  time  in  which  to  do  the  work, 
but  this  has  not  deterred  me  from  its  execution. 
The  sources  have,  of  course,  had  to  be  all  German, 
by  which  I  do  not  mean  merely  works  of  these 
philosophers  themselves,  but  a  large  number  of 
German  works  that  seemed  likely  to  have  a  bearing 
on  one  or  another  of  them.  In  the  case  of  most  of 
these  works,  the  help  derived  has  been  infinitesimal, 
but  there  have  been  one  or  two  exceptions.  What- 
ever the  defects  of  the  work  may  be,  I  am  sanguine 
enough  to  believe  that  there  are  many  who  will  be 
grateful  for  it,  and  for  such  it  has  been  written. 


JAMES    LINDSAY. 


ANNICK  LODGE,  IRVINE, 
SCOTLAND,  29th  March  1920. 


CONTENTS. 


CHAP.  PAGE 

I.   IMMANUEL   HERMANN  PICHTE 1 

II.    CHRISTIAN   HERMANN  WEISSE 27 

III.  KARL   PHILIPP  FISCHER 50 

IV.  HEINRICH   MORITZ   CHALYBAUS               ....  69 
V.    FRANZ   HOFFMANN 79 

VI.    HERMANN   ULRICI 90 

VII.    FRIEDRICH   ADOLF   TRENDELENBURG  .  .  .110 

VIII.   CONCLUSION 122 

INDEX   OF  AUTHORS  AND    SUBJECTS   .  135 


SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHEKS. 


CHAPTER  I. 

I.   H.   FICHTE. 

I.  H.  FICHTE  (1797-1879)  was  the  recognised  head 
and  leader  of  the  School  of  Speculative  Theology 
or  the  Theistic  School,  mentioned  in  our  Preface. 
This  School,  in  the  mid-nineteenth  century,  sought 
with  conspicuous  ability  to  defend  the  interests  of 
Christian  speculation  against  Hegelian  pantheism, 
and  to  bring  to  validity  the  idea  of  personality 
in  all  parts  of  philosophy.  I  propose  to  confine 
myself  to  the  main  members  of  the  philosophic 
group,  without  now  considering  the  services  to 
theistic  philosophy  of  Protestant  speculative  theo- 
logians like  Rothe  and  I.  A.  Dorner,  or  of  Catholic 
speculative  theologians  like  Sengler,  Deutinger, 
Gunther,  and  others,  though  the  work  of  all  of 
them  is  interesting  and  valuable. 

A 


2  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

it  is  an  egregious  mistake  to  suppose,  as  is 
often  done,  that  this  group  of  philosophers  were 
mere  critics  of  Hegel ;  their  critical  assaults  were, 
it  is  true,  in  conjunction  with  other  causes,  instru- 
mental in  overthrowing  the  sway  of  Hegelianism 
in  Germany ;  but  their  most  significant  work  was — 
not  the  attempt  to  get  away  from  Hegel's  abstract 
idealism  but — to  win  the  true  idealism,  and  to 
formulate  Theism  as  a  thoroughgoing  philosophical 
system  or  World -View.  For  they  had  no  idea 
of  treating  Theism  as  the  paltry  magnitude  it 
has  often  become  in  the  hands  of  philosophical 
and  theological  thinkers  of  our  time.  And,  for  my 
own  part,  I  should  not  have  thought  it  worth  while 
now  to  treat  of  them  because  of  their  assaults  on 
Hegel,  since  enough  has  been  done  in  that  direction 
for  all  time,  one  might  almost  say;  and  besides, 
the  years  have  brought  me  a  heightened  sense  of 
admiration  of  Hegel's  philosophical  power  and 
ability,  albeit  I  stand  no  nearer  an  acceptance  of 
his  system. 

Fichte's  earliest  efforts  were  directed  against 
pantheism  in  general,  and  the  views  embodied  in 
them  he  distinguished  later  as  "concrete  theism." 
We  shall  see  that  what  he  contended  for  was  a 
theism  with  an  essentially  physico  -  teleological 
grounding.  By  1829  he  wrote  energetically  and 
specifically  against  the  Hegelian  form  of  pantheism, 
and  sought  to  show  its  untenableness  in  every 


IMMANUEL   HERMANN   FICHTE.  3 

part  of  the   system,   in   view   of   the   deliverances 
of  the  religious  consciousness.     In  the  'Zeitschrift 
ftir   Philosophic,'  Fichte  wrote  :   "  The  fundamental 
fallacy     of    Hegel's     philosophy    consists     in    his 
identifying  abstract  human  thought  with  absolute 
thought,  a  purely  arbitrary  and  groundless  hypo- 
thesis."    Among  Fichte's  allies  were  C.  H.  Weisse, 
who  is  generally  regarded   as   the   most  profound 
thinker  of  the  group,  J.   Sengler,  K.   Ph.  Fischer, 
H.  M.  Chalybaus,  Fr.  Hoffmann,  H.  Ulrici,  A.  Tren- 
delenburg,  J.  U.  Wirth,  and  others.     But  they  were 
not  without  influences   received   from   Baader  and 
Schelling,  as  we  shall  see.     I.  H.  Fichte  constituted 
it   his    own    life -task    to   demonstrate    Theism  to 
be  the  final  solving  word  of  all  world -riddles,  and 
the   inescapable   end   of  all   inquiry.      As   he   puts 
it  in  the  Vorwort  of  his  work  on  '  Theistic  World- 
View,'   "It  is  the   ultimate   solution  of  all  world- 
problems,  the    unavoidable    goal   of    investigation, 
silently  effective  in  that  which  externally  denies  it." 
There  are  those  works  in  which  Fichte   treated 
of  the  theistic  world -view   and   its  justification — 
viz.,  the  '  Ontology '  (1836),  c  Speculative  Theology  ' 
(1846),    and    'The    Theistic    View    of    the    World ' 
(1873) — and   sought  with   great  comprehensiveness 
to  find  proper  grounding  for  the  idea  of  the  person- 
ality of  God,  no  less  than  for  his  Being-in-and-for 
Himself,  and  His  comprehensibility  to   man.     For 
he  can  speak  of  "  the  speculative  comprehensiveness 


4  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

of  God."  But  Fichte  also  published  important 
works  on  '  Anthropology '  (1856),  and  '  Psychology ' 
(1864),  whereby  he  became  the  psychologist,  and 
also  the  anthropologist,  of  the  whole  theistic  system, 
a  far  more  significant  achievement  than  if  he  had 
merely  led  the  way  as  an  incisive  critic  of  Hegel. 
Moreover,  he  was,  as  Dr  Merz  in  a  footnote  remarks, 
"  the  first  among  German  philosophers  of  the  nine- 
teenth century  to  take  in  hand  a  historical  and 
systematic  study  of  Ethics " — no  small  merit  in 
itself.  And  Paulsen,  in  a  footnote  of  his  'Ethics' 
(by  Thilly,  p.  179),  remarks  that  in  its  first  or 
historico-critical  part,  Fichte  has  given  "  an  elaborate 
and  thorough  exposition  of  the  history  of  Ethics  and 
jurisprudence  in  the  eighteenth  and  nineteenth  cen- 
turies." In  this  'System  of  Ethics'  (1850-53),  it 
may  be  remarked,  Fichte,  who  seeks  to  unite  morals 
and  religion,  said ;  "  Religion  is  conscious  morality, 
a  morality  which,  in  virtue  of  that  consciousness, 
is  mindful  of  its  origin  from  God."  Fichte  already 
strongly  emphasised,  too,  the  social  question,  saying 
that  "the  whole  future  of  the  world  lies  in  the 
social  question,  not  in  the  political." 

But  my  concern  now  is  with  his  speculative 
theism,  not  with  his  ethics.  So  long  ago  as  1897 
I  wrote :  "  I.  H.  Fichte  was  able,  in  treating  of 
speculative  theism,  to  postulate  a  rational  and 
immanent,  yet  independent  Creator,  and  to  speak  of 
personality  as  the  only  real  existence,  the  one  true 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  5 

reality  (das  allein  wahrhaft  existirende)  "  ('  Recent 
Advances  in  Theistic  Philosophy  of  Religion,"  p. 
288).  Yet  it  is  less  the  aim  of  Fichte  to  propound 
a  new  system  of  his  own,  than  to  make  insistence  on 
the  fact  that  the  objective,  universally  valid  world  - 
system  is  already  contained  in  the  Divine  thought. 
Thus,  in  his  view,  it  is  less  something  absolutely 
new  that  we  come  to  or  discover  by  our  own 
thought,  than  that,  by  the  highest  self-renunciation, 
we  follow  the  thoughts  of  that  Divine  world-system, 
in  our  own  understanding.  This  was,  I  think,  a 
mistaken  view  on  the  part  of  Fichte.  Human 
minds  are  so  diversified  and  varied  in  their  modes  of 
approach,  that  there  will  always  be  need  and  room 
for  our  different  theistic  systems  or  presentations. 
These  may  be  idealistic,  or  may  assume  realistic 
forms.  He  himself  says  that  "philosophy  never 
loses  the  character  of  human,  finite  inquiry" 
('Anthropology/  p.  14  of  the  3rd  or  1876  edn.). 
Fichte  himself  did  not  even  act  on  his  own  view  of 
the  matter. '  He  supposed  himself  to  find  his  point 
of  departure  in  the  later  form  of  his  father's 
doctrine  of  science  or  knowledge.  But,  besides 
Hegel's  immanent  teleology,  the  Leibnizian- 
Herbartian  doctrine  of  monads  earlier  exercised  a 
decisive  influence  upon  him.  This  was  certainly 
not  a  finding  of  the  original  objective  Divine 
thought.  Also,  an  insistence  on  the  need  for  the 
highest  forms  of  speculative  activity  would  have 


6  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

been   more   in   place,   in  this  connection,  than   the 
inculcation  of  self-renunciation. 

Fichte  is  not  wrong  in  speaking,  in  his  work  on 
'  Speculative  Theology,'  of  his  own  metaphysics,  as 
a  union  of  Hegel  and  Herbart,  but  without  their 
one-sidedness ;  but  this  again  was  not  finding  the 
original  Divine  thought.  He  claimed  for  Herbart, 
that  he  had  for  ever  secured,  in  behoof  of 
psychology,  the  principle  of  individuality.  Fichte 
has,  however,  in  methodological  respects  wholly 
freed  himself  from  Hegel.  Fichte  reached,  through 
his  study  of  Kant,  the  insight  that  not  by  the 
dialectical  method  could  philosophical  truth  be  won  ; 
that  this  is  opened  up  to  the  spirit  only  through 
experience,  with  the  self -observation  that  should 
accompany  it.  This  constituted  one  of  the  most 
essential  divergences  of  Fichte  from  his  friend  and 
associate,  the  deep-thinking  Weisse,  whose  dialectic 
method,  whereby  a  knowledge  of  God  was  to  be 
spun  out  of  pure  concepts,  Fichte  was  unable  to 
accept.  Weisse  followed  a  more  deductive  method 
than  Fichte,  who  thought  it  can  never  be  the 
problem  of  theistic  speculation  to  deduce  the  finite 
from  the  absolute,  or  even  to  determine  the  mode  of 
its  first  coming  into  existence.  Weisse  thought 
Fichte  laid  a  too  exclusive  stress  on  immortality,  in 
the  contest  with  materialism,  and  should  have  laid 
like  stress  on  creational  idea.  Fichte  had,  as  we 
shall  see,  his  own  conception  of  creation,  and  held 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  7 

every  pantheistic  philosophy  to  be  quite  incom- 
patible with  the  idea  of  creation.  He  related 
Weisse's  view  only  to  the  past,  and  regarded  it  as 
pure  Scholasticism,  preferring  as  his  own  point  of 
departure  the  anthropological  and  anthropocentric 
starting-point  of  Kant.  In  this  case,  Fichte  will  be 
generally  regarded  as  having  shown  the  more 
correct  judgment. 

When  it  comes  to  his  work  on  '  Speculative 
Theology,'  however,  Fichte  follows  not  self- 
observation  as  his  immediate  point  of  departure,  as 
in  the  case  of  the  doctrine  of  knowledge,  but  seeks 
the  world-view  to  which  experience  is  guide.  He 
begins  with  the  finite,  whose  reality  he  must  prove 
by  reason  of  the  pantheistic  atmosphere  that  existed, 
as  that  which  has  the  ground  of  its  existence  in  and 
through  another.  The  finite  being  knows  he  has 
a  Ground  beyond  himself,  and  he  seeks  a  primal 
Ground,  an  eternal  Ground,  but,  not  as  before  or 
outside  him,  does  he  conceive  this  Ground,  but  as 
present  in  and  to  him.  He  seeks  in  the  '  Speculative 
Theology/  in  short,  to  maintain  a  moral  idea  of 
God,  and  to  base  our  comprehension  of  God,  man, 
and  the  universe,  on  the  moral  and  religious  facts 
of  human  nature.  And  in  his  work  on  'Theistic 
World-View,'  Fichte  says  (p.  3)  that  "the  idea  of 
the  unconditioned,  rising  irrepressible  in  the  back- 
ground of  our  consciousness,  is  the  first  ground- 
premiss  from  which  all  thought  is  set  in  action  and 


&  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

driven  on  over  all  conditioned  and  presented  reality, 
to  find  rest  only  in  the  certainty  of  an  Infinite 
and  All-conditioning."  And,  in  the  same  work,  he 
urges,  as  a  universal  fact  of  the  world,  an  inner 
drawing  of  beings  to  one  another,  a  harmonious 
fitting  of  all  finite  things  into  one  another. 

But  his  speculative  theology  finds  the  finite 
not  merely  finite,  or  only  a  quantitatively  deter- 
mined personality,  but  views  it  as  at  the  same 
time  qualitatively  determined,  and  permanent  in 
the  midst  of  change.  And  the  finites — as  what  he 
calls  primary  positions  or  monads  —  constitute  a 
perpetually  existing  system,  in  which  they  are 
complementary  one  of  another,  for  such  an  inner 
active  relation  amongst  them  must  be  presupposed. 
The  one  Absolute  is  real  and  effective  in  them  all. 
For  Fichte's  universe  is  a  reason  -  system,  perfect 
unity  realised  through  means  and  ends.  But  this 
Absolute,  as  unity,  is  not  only  immanent  in  the 
world,  but  transcends  it.  Not  as  mere  unity, 
however,  but  as  comprehending,  in  its  specific  range 
or  grasp,  world  -  order  and  world  -  law,  must  this 
Absolute  be  grasped.  The  Absolute  is  not  only 
purpose-positing  but  purpose-preserving.  All  space 
and  time  distinctions  fall  together  in  this  Absolute, 
in  whom  they  are  overthrown  or  transcended,  but 
this  can  only  be  thought  of  in  an  infinitely  ideal 
manner.  The  Absolute  is  to  be  conceived  as  infinite 
and  all-present  Thought,  but  at  the  same  time  as 
world-creative  Thought. 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  9 

Fichte  expends  a  good  deal  of  discussion  on 
whether  the  Absolute  is  a  mere  World- Soul,  with 
"  unconscious "  and  "  instinctive  "  action.  He 
believes  himself  to  have  reached  not  only  an  all- 
consciousness  of  the  Absolute,  but  a  self  -  con- 
sciousness of  the  same.  It  is  a  difficulty,  however, 
that  he  and  others  hold  the  Divine  self -consciousness 
to  be  effective  only  through  the  world-idea — or  the 
ideal  world — for  then  the  world -idea  cannot  be 
derived  from  self  -  conscious  Deity.  This  was  an 
influence  that  ran  back  to  Bohme — whom  Baader 
so  largely  followed — and  it  was  indeed  Bohme's 
main  defect  that  he  ranked  nature  so  highly  as  to 
make  it  a  necessary  condition  of  God's  self-con- 
sciousness. Bohme  says  of  God  and  Nature  that 
"there  is  nothing  prior,  and  either  is  without 
beginning,  and  each  is  a  cause  of  the  other,  and 
an  eternal  bond"  (J.  R.  Earle's  work  on  'Bohme,' 
p.  143).  Has  it  ever  really  been  shown,  one  must 
ask,  that  God  must  first  think  something;  different 

O 

from  Himself  ?  I  believe  not ;  the  Divine  self - 
consciousness  had  no  need  of  any  Anstoss  from  the 
outside,  in  order  to  its  rise,  as  we  shall  see  later, 
since  he  is  the  Absolute  Being,  and  is  the  Unity  of 
the  modes  of  existence  —  the  subjective  and  the 
objective,  the  ideal  and  the  real. 

Weisse,  whom  we  shall  presently  consider,  made 
God  the  Father  the  primary  essence  or  foundation, 
Who  thinks  Himself ;  this  does  not  yet  go  beyond 
Deism,  if  communicability  be  supposed  wanting. 


10  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Fichte  finds,  at  any  rate,  the  climax  of  his  thought 
in  the  conception  of  God  as  Absolute  Spirit  and  the 
Absolute  Personality.  Thus  Fichte,  like  those 
other  philosophers,  K.  Ph.  Fischer  and  Weisse,  runs 
the  concept  of  God  up  to  absoluteness,  so  that  it 
completes  itself,  whereas,  the  world  of  Hegel  and  of 
Schelling  was  only  in  process,  but  not  perfected. 
These  first-named  philosophers  held  that  God  is 
eternally  in  Himself  perfect,  and  that  absolutely, 
apart  from  the  existing  world.  Fichte  thought 
that  the  world -creation  did  not  affect  the  Divine 
essence,  it  was  so  wrought  in  freedom;  and  that 
the  idea  of  God  remained  the  same,  apart  from  all 
world-reference.  The  "  many  ness  "  of  the  world  is, 
to  Fichte,  only  the  inner  manifoldness  of  the 
unified  act  of  positing  by  the  Absolute.  But  Fichte 
thinks  the  world  is  not  redeemed  by  thought,  as 
Hegel  supposed,  without  there  being  a  residue,  for 
Fichte  finds  more  than  an  objectified  thought  in  the 
creature. 

Besides  thought,  Fichte  thinks,  there  must  have 
been  much  more  a  creative  power  of  will  in  God's 
fashioning  the  creature.  He  thinks  the  purest  or 
most  sublimated  in  God  is  thought,  but  will  is  the 
deepest,  and  the  prius  of  thought  itself.  This 
absurd  Voluntarism  Fichte  had  obviously  carried 
over  from  his  father's  system.  The  primacy  of 
idea  or  reason  is  much  more  to  be  maintained,  as  I 
have  shown  elsewhere  ("Rationalism  and  Volun- 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  11 

tarism  "  in  'The  Monist,'  1918).  Over  against  the 
position  of  Fichte  here,  I  should  like  to  place  some 
words  of  Leibniz :  "  Propterea  intellectus  Dei  est 
regio  veritatum  aeternarum  aut  idearum  unde 
dependent,  et  sine  ipsis  nihil  realitatis  foret  in 
possibilitatibus,  et  nihil  non  modo  existeret,  sed 
nihil  etiam  possibile  foret."  Nay,  I  should  like  to 
cite  Fichte  against  himself,  when  he  says  in  the 
small  work,  'On  the  Question  of  the  Soul,  a 
Philosophical  Confession,'  as  against  bare  will  or 
blind  Schopenhauerian  impulse,  that  "intelligence 
ever  remains  as  a  distinctive  agent,  a  hidden 
principle,  nay,  as  the  Alpha  and  the  Omega,  the 
starting-point  and  the  aim  of  the  mind's  whole 
development."  Consciousness  is  to  him  a  "  rational 
power  from  the  very  first." 

Fichte  goes  on  to  distinguish  a  real  or  objective 
side  and  an  ideal  or  subjective  aspect — nature  and 
spirit — in  the  Divine  essence.  But  these  two  aspects 
he  supposes  to  be  harmonised  or  combined  in  a 
higher  principle  of  volition  or  of  love.  Bohme  also, 
I  may  observe,  had  an  ideal  or  spirit  side  and  a  real 
or  nature  side  in  his  conception  of  God,  so  that 
Fichte's  postulation  is  not  entirely  novel.  But  we 
should  still  have  to  inquire  whether  spirit  came  to 
proper  independence  in  Bohme's  treatment.  This 
objective  or  real  side  of  the  Divine  Life  is  to  be 
taken  as  its  first  moment;  it  is  the  sphere  of 
potential  life.  There  is,  in  Fichte's  thought,  some 


12  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

consideration  of  the  most  original  ground  of  Being 
at  all,  but  it  does  not  seem  very  satisfactory, 
influenced  as  it  too  much  ib  by  the  Ungrund  of 
Bohme  and  the  "  Indifference "  of  Schelling.  Dr 
H.  L.  Martensen's  fine  study  of  Bohme  is  worthy 
of  remembrance  in  this  connection. 

The  reality  of  God,  Fichte's  objective  life  or  "real 
side,"  is  found  in  the  "  eternal  universe  "  of  monads, 
which  form  "  nature  in  God,"  and  whose  infinity  and 
absolute  unity  He  is.  In  this  conception  of  what  he 
calls  the  primary  positions  or  monads,  which  are 
inner  determinations  of  Divine  self-conscious  will, 
Fichte  finds  not  only  the  essential  foundation  of  his 
speculative  theology  and  the  basis  for  his  philosophy 
of  religion,  but  a  means  of  warding  off  pantheistic 
and  deistic  modes  of  representation.  Theory  of 
knowledge  may,  in  Fichte's  view,  ground  a  know- 
ledge of  the  truth,  and  prove  the  agreement  of  being 
and  knowing.  But  it  still  remains  for  metaphysics 
to  inquire  into  the  primal  Being  and  Ground,  beyond 
all  individual  beings  and  particular  grounds.  Fichte 
further  holds  that  such  an  inquiry  already  involves 
the  presupposition  of  the  existence  of  such  a 
Primal  Being  and  Ground.  The  preservation  of  the 
monadistic  universe  means  to  him  an  eternal  new- 
creating  on  the  part  of  God — a  life-process  of  self- 
generation  by  the  Deity.  In  this,  Fichte  had  really 
taken  up  a  Baader- Hoffmann  conception,  as  we  shall 
see  later. 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  13 

But  it  would  be  interesting  to  know  how,  in  this 
talk  of  life  and  of  process,  Fichte  meant  to  keep  the 
concept  of  time  out  of  the  matter.  At  one  time  he 
speaks  as  though  time  and  space  were  forms  of  the 
specification  of  all  the  real,  whether  absolute  or 
finite.  Empiric  time,  he  yet  elsewhere  says,  does 
not  exist  for  God,  and  has  no  truth  or  reality ;  but 
though  he  speaks  of  "true"  time  and  "true"  space, 
Fichte  does  not  work  out  his  time  conceptions,  in 
connection  with  his  descriptions  of  process,  any  too 
consistently  or  satisfactorily.  But  he  holds  to  the 
objectivity  of  time  and  space,  though,  in  the  out- 
working, space  and  time  relations  tend  to  become 
mere  subjective  appearances  in  his  hands.  And  the 
sense -world  is  to  him  a  mere  phenomenon.  In  that 
case,  all  empiric  reality  would  become  a  mere  Schein 
of  the  Absolute,  and  all  talk  of  life  and  process  in 
the  Absolute  would  be  at  an  end.  Fichte  was  afraid 
of  falling  into  pantheism — which  he  aimed  to  ex- 
clude— if  he  made  process  in  the  being  of  the 
Absolute  a  purely  temporal  real.  Yet  the  demand 
of  the  religious  consciousness  is  at  once  for  the 
reality  of  the  Absolute  and  the  reality  of  the  empiric 
being. 

Fichte  holds  that  the  Divine  essence  is  subject 
to  no  development,  but  does  not  think  that  that 
is  to  posit  a  dead  lack  of  variety,  and  a  rigid 
unchangeableness  in  God.  And  yet  he  also  speaks 
of  God's  eternity  as  all-duration,  and  as  in  some 


14  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

sense  without  change.  It  is  not  easy  to  harmonise 
these  insistences  with  all  Fichte  has  advanced  about 
the  self-generation  of  the  Deity.  Time  is  bound 
up  with  change,  but  change  cannot  remain  only 
change  —  with  no  unchangeable  being.  These 
positions  as  to  change  can,  I  think,  be  quite  har- 
monised, in  ethical  ideas  of  God,  whose  immutability 
does  not  consist  in  unethical  fixedness,  without 
adopting  the  crude  proposals  of  some  philosophical 
and  theological  writers  to  resolve  progress  under 
Deity  into  a  progress  of  Deity,  for  which  there  is 
no  real  or  proper  warrant.  We  know  how  great 
are  the  difficulties  that  attach  to  the  time-problem  ; 
Fichte  seems  to  me  to  have  been  keenly  conscious 
of  them  ;  he  was,  I  think,  influenced  a  good  deal  by 
Baader,  who,  in  seeking  to  combat  pantheism,  which 
draws  the  Deity  into  the  temporal  course,  placed 
God  in  eternity. 

One  of  his  German  critics  appears  to  think  that,  to 
do  so,  lands  Fichte  in  insuperable  difficulty.  I  do  not 
think  so.  We  may  regard  time  and  eternity  as 
opposites  or  incommensurables,  but  we  are  not 
entitled  to  treat  them  as  contradictory  or  exclusive. 
They  are  no  more  exclusive,  I  think,  than  God 
and  man  are  exclusive.  Rothe  was  right  when 
he  said  that  "the  words  temporal  and  eternal  do 
not  in  any  way  exclude  each  other."  The  temporal 
stands  in  the  eternal,  and  presupposes  it,  which 
the  critic  fails  to  realise.  Timelessness  and  univer- 


IMMANUEL   HERMANN   FICHTE.  15 

sality  are  just  the  lack  of  a  good  deal  of  our  phil- 
osophy. And  even  timelessness  is  but  the  negative 
idea  of  eternity ;  the  positive  idea  of  it  is  not  yet 
ours.  If  God  in  His  absoluteness  were  conceived 
as  existing  above  all  world-oppositions,  there  would 
be  no  way  of  explaining  His  self-communications 
to  man  and  the  world,  which  are  not  to  be  doubted. 
But,  though  immanent  in  the  world,  God  is  yet 
above  the  space  and  time  forms  of  the  finite  world, 
and  His  unified  action  is  not  split  by  them ;  although 
He  may  not  enter  into  the  forms  of  space  and  time, 
it  does  not  follow  that  what  goes  on  under  these 
forms  has  no  reality  for  Him.  But  not  even  for 
us  are  they  ultimate,  as  we  learn  to  view  the 
world  sub  specie  aeternitatis ;  while  as  yet  all  things 
are  for  us  quantitatively  determined  in  the  finite 
world.  The  full  significance  of  the  temporal  is 
found  only  under  the  eternal  aspect,  so  that  there 
is  here  a  heightening,  and  not  a  lessening,  of  the 
value  of  temporal  reality.  The  temporal  is  thus  no 
mere  appearance  for  God.  There  is  no  need,  there- 
fore, so  to  conceive  the  timeless  being  of  the 
Eternal  as  to  preclude  His  every  entrance  into  time. 
This,  without  losing  Himself  in  the  time-relations. 
Certainly  "  the  finite  is  within  God,"  and  has  a 
real  value  for  Him,  but  I  could  not  bring  myself 
to  say,  with  Laurie,  that  "  God  leads  a  finite  life — 
a  life  in  Time"  (' Synthetica,'  ii.  p.  142). 

But  at  least  Fichte  appears  to  me  to  deserve  not 


16  SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHEKS. 

a  little  speculative  credit  for  the  way  in  which,  at 
that  period,  he  sought  to  grapple  with  the  problem. 
If  I  do  not  dwell  further  on  the  time  and  eternity 
problems  and  relations,  that  is  because  I  have  else- 
where dealt  with  them  in  a  way  that  appears  to 
me  less  open  to  objection  than  any  views  propounded 
on  the  subject  by  any  one  of  these  philosophical 
thinkers  (in  my  'Philosophical  System  of  Theistic 
Idealism,'  ch.  iv.).  There  I  have  shown  how  the 
eternal  may  enter  into  relations  with  time,  may 
penetrate  and  exalt  it;  and  how  the  time-process 
is  not  to  be  treated  as  unreal,  since  it  has  more  than 
merely  temporal  character  and  import,  but  is  yet  not 
the  ultimate  reality,  being  grounded  in  the  eternal. 
We  shall  have  the  time  question  again,  presently, 
in  connection  with  Weisse  and  with  Fischer. 

Corresponding  to  the  "real"  side  in  the  Divine 
essence  is,  for  Fichte,  the  "ideal"  side,  the  original 
ego,  the  unifying  moment  of  the  Divine  Spirit, 
whereby  what  was  real  and  living  exists  in  self- 
conscious  unity.  For  Fichte  postulates  that  the 
real  and  the  ideal  universes  form  a  unity.  What 
Fichte  calls  the  second  moment  in  the  Divine  Being 
or  Essence,  is  the  All-consciousness  of  God.  This 
corresponds  to  the  real  infinity  of  His  self-generating 
Life.  But  God  not  only  lives  in  all  the  universe, 
but  knows  Himself  therein.  So  we  are  brought 
up  to  the  Divine  self -intuition  or  self -consciousness. 
This  Divine  Self-consciousness  is  taken  by  Fichte 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  17 

to  be  the  third  moment,  as  he  terms  it,  in  the  Divine 
Being  or  essence,  and  by  it  the  Divine  self-generation 
and  self -knowing  first  became  perfected.  But  it 
cannot  be  said  that  Fichte  always  keeps  this  self- 
consciousness  in  rigid  distinctness  from  the  All- 
consciousness.  For  the  creation  of  the  world, 
Fichte  postulates  in  God  a  peculiar  form  of  will, 
which  he  calls  will  ad  extra,  in  distinction  from  will 
ad  intra,  by  which  latter  he  means  the  will  whereby 
God  realises  in  Himself  His  own  thought  of  the  in- 
finite universe.  But  the  distinction  in  the  activity 
of  the  divine  attributes,  as  ad  intra  and  ad  extra, 
though  it  may  be  of  speculative  service,  is  not,  in 
my  judgment,  of  any  special  value.  For,  if  we 
except  aseity,  all  the  divine  attributes  or  qualities, 
conceived  in  any  living  form,  are  active  in  relation  to 
God  and  in  relation  to  the  world.  The  distinction  of 
the  attributes  as  metaphysical  and  moral  is,  method- 
ologically, a  more  fruitful  one. 

Fichte  rightly  asserts,  as  against  pantheism,  that 
God  had  no  need  of  the  willed  and  finite  world 
in  order  to  His  own  perfection  or  reality.  He  even 
declares,  none  too  reflectively,  that  the  world  could 
as  well  not  have  been.  The  difficulty  is  to  keep 
such  an  unqualified  statement  from  running  up  too 
far  in  a  Deistic  direction.  Creation  does  not,  he 
thinks,  follow  from  the  idea  of  God,  and  cannot  be 
proved  in  an  a  priori  manner  or  as  having  arisen 
from  dialectical  necessity.  But  Fichte  does  not 

B 


18  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

realise  the  need  to  keep  creation  free  from  being 
arbitrary  or  accidental,  or  due  to  anything  but  God 
Himself.  The  world's  creation  is  the  free,  self-deter- 
mined act  of  the  Divine  Will,  but  in  the  light,  it 
should  have  been  said,  of  what  has  just  been  pointed 
out.  And  in  respect  of  our  knowledge  of  the  world, 
Fichte  wrote  in  the  '  Zeitschrift  fiir  Philosophic,' 
that  "objectivity  can  only  be  known  by  being  re- 
cognised as  originally  rational,  since  the  laws  of 
reason  which  govern  our  mind  show  themselves  to 
be  exactly  the  same  as  the  objective  reason  existing 
in  it — i.e.,  external  objects." 

Between  his  theory  of  Nature  as  in  God,  and  his 
theory  of  the  particular  creation  of  finite  being,  in 
which  it  is  distinguished  from  the  eternally  real 
universe,  Fichte  was  able  to  overcome  pantheism. 
But  one  cannot  think  his  method  always  happy. 
His  two  wills  for  God  become  a  proposition  diffi- 
cult of  acceptance  when  we  find  that  it  carries,  for 
him,  two  consciousnesses  in  God.  He  distinguishes 
God's  eternal  All-Consciousness,  in  which  is  no 
before  and  after,  from  God's  knowledge  of  the 
World-all,  with  which  it  is  not  identical,  and  for 
which  past,  present,  and  future  do  exist,  though 
these  are  comprehended  in,  and  carried  over  into, 
the  eternal  All-Consciousness  of  God.  It  has  been 
said  by  an  able  German  critic,  A.  Drews,  a  follower 
of  Hartmann,  that  such  a  double  consciousness  in 
God  as  Fichte  postulated  is  a  justifiable  and  even 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN  FICHTE.  19 

necessary  result  in  every  consequent  theism  ('Die 
deutsche  Spekulation  seit  Kant,'  vol.  i.  pp.  378- 
379). 

Now,  the  internal  complexity  of  consciousness  is 
not  to  be  doubted,  but  while  a  distinction  between 
the  absolute  and  the  relative  may  exist  as  internal 
in  the  All-consciousness,  such  a  cleavage  as  is  pos- 
tulated in  the  theory  of  a  double  consciousness  in 
God  cannot,  I  think,  be  held  as  justified.  The  All- 
Consciousness  must  be  held  to  be  one,  and  the 
double-consciousness  theory,  in  any  such  pronounced 
form  at  least,  does  not  appear  to  me  a  characteristic 
of  theism.  A  distinction  within  consciousness  is  not 
a  separation  of  consciousness.  To  separate  the 
''relative  consciousness"  of  God  —  His  objective 
activities  —  from  the  absolute  consciousness,  as 
some  thinkers  have  proposed,  is,  in  fact,  to  set  up 
the  absoluteness  of  the  relative,  which  should  always 
be  grounded  in  the  absolute.  I  cannot  admit  that 
God's  consciousness  of  the  relative  means  a  "  relative 
consciousness  "  in  Him,  for  that  would  be  to  fasten 
a  finite  consciousness  to  an  infinite  being.  The 
two  forms  of  consciousness  in  God  I  take  to  be  un- 
necessary. What  is  required  is  to  recognise  the 
outer  or  relative  form  of  consciousness  as  already 
inherent  in  the  nature  of  consciousness ;  the  absolute 
consciousness  is  consciousness  of  the  outer  or  rel- 
ative, as  the  relative  that  it  is.  Besides,  the  outer 
or  relative,  to  wit,  all  being  or  reality,  is,  as 


20  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

dependent,  internal  to  the  absolute  rather  than 
external,  as  it  is  to  us.  No  consciousness  of  relation 
annuls  or  cancels  God's  consciousness  of  absolute 
being.  Fichte,  in  postulating  a  double-consciousness 
in  God,  seems  to  me  to  have  relaxed  his  hold  of  the 
personality  of  God,  for  which  in  its  unity  he  had 
so  strongly  contended.  Personality  rests  on  con- 
sciousness, has  consciousness  for  its  indispensable 
presupposition.  Personality  must  be  unitary  in  its 
root-significance,  and  its  consciousness  one,  however 
its  complex  nature  may  admit  diverse  modes  of 
expression. 

Fichte  grounds  philosophy  in  experience.  He 
thinks  that,  the  better  we  know  the  world,  the 
more  do  we  know  of  its  original  Ground.  He 
opines  that  this  setting  out  from  experience  will 
be  the  inauguration  of  a  new  epoch.  It  is,  then, 
from  the  world-fact  Fichte  sets  out,  and  for  the 
solution  of  its  inner  contradictions  he  is  led  to 
seek  a  purpose-positing  Will.  He  laid  new  and  de- 
served stress  on  teleological  conception,  the  world- 
order  being  to  him  one  of  purpose — the  purpose 
of  the  thinking  and  willing  Absolute.  In  the 
'Zeitschrift  fiir  Philosophic/  Fichte  wrote  that 
"  a  reciprocal  relation  between  the  end  and  the 
means  cannot  exist  apart  from  consciousness  imagin- 
ing and  realising  this  relation.  Now,  such  relation 
to  an  end  is  universally  found  in  the  actual  world ; 
thus,  the  Absolute  in  the  realisation  of  the  world 


IMMANUEL   HEKMANN   FICHTE.  21 

must  be  an  Absolute  that  imagines  the  world  and 
consciously  penetrates  it."  The  World- Whole,  in 
Fichte's  view,  is,  like  all  experience,  teleological 
throughout.  God  is,  for  him,  working  everywhere 
in  the  world,  as  the  real  and  absolute  background 
of  nature's  laws.  Nor  is  the  world  of  phenomena 
and  their  appearances  or  developments  to  be  viewed 
as  anywhere  outside  the  Divine  working.  Fichte 
is,  of  course,  justified  in  so  postulating  a  real 
immanence  for  God  in  the  world,  though  it  is 
another  question  whether,  in  working  out  the 
correlative  positions  of  God  and  man,  he  has  always 
sufficiently  preserved  the  Divine  independence  and 
self-possession  which  he  theoretically  maintained. 
It  may  be  doubted  whether,  on  a  strict  view,  his 
theism  has  always  been  able  to  emancipate  itself 
perfectly  from  pantheistic  associations. 

Fichte  holds  a  purposeful  connection  in  the  fact 
of  the  world  to  have  been  "eternally  real  in  the 
nature  of  God,"  and  so  in  His  All- Consciousness. 
But  I  think  one  may  doubt  whether,  in  this  talk 
of  what  is  "eternally  real  in  the  nature  of  God," 
he  is  in  very  strict  consistency  with  his  own 
attribution  of  creation  to  the  will  of  God,  and 
whether,  in  speaking  of  what  is  so  "  eternally  real " 
in  that  nature,  he  is  making  creation  really  the 
free  work  of  Divine  love.  And  if  the  world,  and 
all  that  concerns  it,  is  already  so  "  eternally  real " 
in  God,  it  becomes  a  question  whether  human 


22  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

freedom  is  so  provided  for  as  it  should  be  in  a  real 
theism.  Yet  he  proclaims  that  the  foundation  of 
man  is  not  a  "  universal  world -spirit,"  in  the 
pantheistic  sense.  In  this  he  was  clearly  right, 
for  it  is  only  in  a  theistic  world-view  that  the 
fulfilment  or  perfection  of  personality  can  be  posited 
as  transcendent  -  positive  end.  Pantheism,  I  must 
observe,  cannot  really  recognise  realities  within  the 
world-process,  but  must  run  everything  back  into 
identity  with  God.  It  conduces  not  to  life-affirma- 
tion, but  rather  tends  to  denial  of  the  will  to  live. 
Pantheism,  says  Fichte  (in  the  '  Zur  Seelenfrage '), 
"  is  wholly  incapable  of  laying  the  foundations  of 
a  true  objective  psychology."  Fichte  yet,  in  his 
work  on  'Theistic  World-View/  says,  quite  con- 
sistently, that  "the  more  a  being  fulfils  its  end  in 
reference  to  the  all,  the  higher  does  it  advance  its 
own  well-being,"  for  that  is  in  reference  to  the  moral 
system. 

On  the  question  of  the  soul,  Fichte  holds  that 
the  soul  is  at  once  "  the  real  ground  of  our  individ- 
uality, and  the  great  formative  principle."  And 
the  main , object  of  psychology  is,  in  his  view,  to 
show  what  "  within  the  consciousness  "  is  the  work 
of  the  soul  itself,  and  what  is  contributed  by 
experience.  In  controversy  with  Lotze  on  the 
question  of  the  seat  of  the  soul,  while  Lotze  was 
inclined  to  place  it  in  a  fixed  portion  of  the  brain, 
Fichte,  opposed  to  dualistic  interpretation  of  the 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  23 

human  constitution,  claimed  for  its  seat  the  whole 
nervous  system,  and  assumed  at  the  same  time  what 
he  termed  an  invisible  pneumatic  body,  inseparable 
from  the  soul,  and  through  which  the  soul,  as  a 
dynamical  but  not  physical  existent,  could  maintain 
communication  with  the  body.  It  was  a  con- 
troversial time,  and  Rud.  Wagner,  the  great  physi- 
ologist, had  issued  in  1857  his  small  treatise  'The 
Controversy  about  the  Soul'  ('Der  Kampf  um  die 
Seele').  His  position  was  that  physiology  could 
only  go  half-way,  in  explanations  that  concerned 
the  assumption  of  an  immaterial  soul,  and  that 
other  means  must  be  used  for  a  great  region  beyond 
this.  He  claimed  to  speak  thus  in  the  interest 
of  religion  and  morality,  and  was  bitterly  opposed 
by  Vogt,  who,  at  a  scientific  assembly  in  1854, 
where  Wagner  stated  his  dualistic  view  of  nature, 
as  mechanism  and  spiritualism,  contemptuously 
called  it  "book-keeping  by  double  entry." 

Man  alone  is,  for  Fichte,  minted  for  individuality, 
and,  as  such,  immortal.  He  postulated  a  real 
connection  of  the  human  spirit  with  the  Divine 
spirit  in  prayer  and  pious  inspiration.  It  was  by 
the  attribution  of  feeling  and  love,  besides  know- 
ledge and  will,  to  the  Deity,  that  Fichte  reached 
his  "concrete"  or  "ethical"  theism.  To  him,  it  is 
confirmed  by  all  experience  that  God  is  Love.  He 
thinks  optimism  susceptible  of  empirical  proof. 
But  such  an  optimism  can  only  be  grounded,  I  think, 


24  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

in  the  inward  man,  its  inner  perceptions  of  the 
character  and  purpose  of  God,  its  personal  attitude, 
in  short,  to  life,  not  in  a  survey  of  and  outlook  upon 
the  world,  which,  by  itself,  would  probably  make 
such  optimism  less  possible  than  ever.  Yet  many 
higher  considerations  make  such  an  optimistic  faith 
reasonable  and  possible,  albeit  it  cannot  be  un- 
attended with  pain  and  difficulty.  Even  these  dis- 
appear in  the  quest  and  vision  of  the  eternal  God. 
In  his  '  Anthropology,'  Fichte  favoured  the  doctrine 
(pp.  347-352)  of  a  non  -  corporeal  soul,  although 
thinking  that  the  soul  is  never  to  be  found  without 
its  corresponding  body.  The  relations  of  body  and 
soul  are  fully  discussed  in  its  chapters.  His  view 
of  life  was  that  it  meant  the  self-sustentation  of 
the  organism.  He  posits  an  active  organic  force, 
mere  mechanism  being  unable  to  explain  the  fact 
of  organic  life. 

It  must  be  said  that  Fichte  has  not  received  any 
very  skilful  or  adequate  appreciation  from  the 
accredited  historians  of  philosophy.  This  is  not 
surprising,  for  it  has  been  too  much  their  way  to 
sacrifice  theistic  systems  and  values,  with  a  strange 
lack  of  sense  of  proportion,  to  all  kinds  of  pan- 
theistic, positivistic,  and  materialistic  thought. 
Prof.  Campbell  Fraser  says  of  pantheism,  that  "its 
history  is  in  a  manner  the  history  of  philosophy  "  > 
yes,  in  the  manner  in  which  the  historians  have, 
with  blind  custom,  written  it.  But  it  should 


IMMANUEL  HERMANN   FICHTE.  25 

never  be  forgotten  that,  in  the  history  of  philosophy, 
theistic  world- view  has  the  longest  list  of  names 
attached  to  it.  It  should  be  said,  however,  that 
in  the  '  Ueberweg-Heinze-Oesterreich '  '  History  of 
Philosophy'  (vol.  iv.,  Berlin,  1916),  distinctly  im- 
proved notices  of  Fichte  and  Weisse  appear. 

But  to  return  to  Fichte ;  historians  notwithstand- 
ing, there  are  abounding  proofs  in  German  philo- 
sophical literature  of  the  high  esteem  in  which 
not  only  Fichte,  but  all  the  members  of  this  philo- 
sophical group,  were  held,  and  Fichte  has  not  gone 
without  high  and  deserved  praise  for  his  speculative 
power  and  insight,  even  from  philosophers  not 
belonging  to  his  own  School.  C.  Schwarz,  for 
instance,  singles  out  Fichte  and  Weisse  for  particular 
and  appreciative  treatment  ('  Zur  Geschichte  der 
neuesten  Theologie,'  pp.  310-324).  They  have 
known — as  Hoffding  has  not — that  it  is  a  conspicuous 
merit  in  Fichte  that,  as  a  philosopher,  he  keeps  to 
a  purely  speculative  standpoint,  and  eschews  every- 
thing of  theological  or  supranaturalistic  character. 
Hence  we  find  Rothe,  in  his  '  Dogmatik '  (footnote, 
p.  83),  disclaiming  sympathy  with  Fichte  on  this 
score,  as  was  to  be  expected  from  the  more  theo- 
logical standpoint  of  the  former.  Fichte's  services 
to  philosophy  must  be  judged  by  what  he  did  for 
the^formulation  of  theistic  world-view,  as  philosophy 
stood  in  his  own  time.  Dull  indeed  would  be  the 
critical  insight  that  should  fail  to  accord  his  system 


26  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

a  high  place  from  this  point  of  view.  If  in  his 
own  time  he  was  criticised,  now,  for  his  trans- 
cendentalism, and  now  for  his  dualism ;  the  world 
to-day  discards  these  forgotten  criticisms,  and  forms 
its  own  appreciative  estimate  of  his  work.  His  sub- 
sequent influence  on  philosophical  thought  has  been 
very  considerable,  as  is  known  by  those  who  take 
the  trouble  to  know  the  course  it  has  really  followed 
outside  as  well  as  inside  Germany. 


27 


CHAPTER  II. 

C.   H.   WEISSE. 

C.  H.  WEISSE  (1801-1866),  to  whom  I  now  turn, 
was  the  most  powerful  representative  of  this  group 
of  philosophers.  He  was  more  permeated  with  the 
Hegelian  spirit,  and  more  in  command  of  the 
fundamental  truths  of  that  system  than  any  of 
the  theistic  philosophers  of  his  period,  having  been 
for  a  time  an  adherent  of  that  system,  from  which 
he  only  gradually  and  slowly  broke  away.  There 
have  been  those,  among  capable  German  thinkers, 
who  have  regarded  Weisse  as  not  behind  Hegel 
and  Schelling  in  intellectual  power,  and  as  the 
superior  of  both  in  philosophical  and  theological 
learning;  and  it  may  at  any  rate  be  doubted  if 
there  has  been  any  speculative  mind  since  Hegel 
more  worthy  to  rank  with  his,  than  Weisse.  Lotze, 
of  course,  has  been  more  popular  and  better  known, 
which  is  quite  a  different  matter.  And  Lotze 
frankly  owned  that  the  circle  of  ideas  which  had 
been  his,  and  which  he  had  never  felt  any  desire 


28  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

to  change,  had  been  primarily  derived  from  Weisse. 
That,  of  course,  must  not  be  taken  to  mean  either 
that  Lotze  was  not  greatly  influenced  by  Leibniz, 
or  that  Lotze  has  not  advanced  at  points  to  im- 
portant positions  of  his  own,  beyond  the  insight 
of  Weisse. 

Weisse  formed  a  connecting  link  between  Hegel 
and  Lotze.  It  has  even  been  claimed  by  R.  Seydel 
for  Weisse  that  he  had  more  influence  on  philo- 
sophical development  after  Hegel  than  any  other 
thinker.  But  that  seems  true  only  in  a  restricted 
sense,  and  the  direction  which  Weisse's  philosophical 
energies  took,  together  with  the  heaviness  of  his 
style,  was  not  the  most  favourable  to  his  services 
for  philosophy  being  duly  remembered.  One  could 
almost  wish  that  Weisse  had  concerned  himself  a 
little  less  in  his  philosophical  work  with  theological 
matters,  and  the  reconciliation  of  philosophy  and 
theology,  and  of  faith  and  knowledge. 

As  a  critic,  Weisse  thought  the  Hegelian  system 
both  contradicted  the  facts  of  reality  and  left  the 
needs  of  the  heart  and  of  feeling  unsatisfied.  He 
thought  it  left  the  world  a  mere  system  of  ob- 
jectified thoughts ;  there  was  always  a  dark  residue 
belonging  to  another  than  the  stuifless  shadow- world 
of  the  absolute  idea,  so  that  Hegel  never  got  beyond 
mere  rationalism.  Weisse  did  valuable  but  greatly 
neglected  work  in  'Metaphysics'  (1835),  and  in 
'Aesthetics'  (1830),  the  latter  warmly  praised,  and 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN  WEISSE.  29 

largely  followed,  by  Lotze,  who,  however,  super- 
added  the  idea  of  worth  or  value.  Weisse  was  a 
contributor  to  Fichte's  "  Zeitschrif t,"  in  which  his 
essays  on  Bonnie  (1845-6)  contained  the  just  state- 
ment that  Bohme  "is  not  a  speculative  philosopher, 
but  a  religious  seer  pointing  the  way  to  speculative 
philosophy."  Bohme  was  a  bold  and  vigorous 
thinker,  whose  speculation  was  mainly  concerned 
with  God,  whom  He  sought  in  the  differences  and 
contrasts  wherein  He  manifests  His  nature.  But 
his  speculative  mysticism  is  lacking  in  system,  as 
might  be  expected.  In  the  Vorrede  of  his  'Meta- 
physics,' Weisse  said — "The  formal  truth  and  the 
material  untruth  of  Hegel's  philosophy,  the  solid 
excellence  of  its  method,  and  the  wretched  baldness 
of  its  results,  obtrude  themselves  with  equal  evidence 
upon  my  spirit." 

In  his  book  on  '  The  Idea  of  the  Godhead '  (1833), 
which  is  a  purely  philosophical  work,  Weisse  sought 
to  derive  in  a  dialectical  manner  the  absolute  per- 
sonality of  God  from  the  idea  of  truth  and 
perfection.  Leibniz,  I  may  point  out,  had,  long 
before,  in  his  own  way  based  the  being  of  God 
upon  the  reality  of  eternal  truth  and  infinite  per- 
fection. Weisse's  great  three  -  volumed  work  on 
'Philosophical  Dogmatics'  (1855-1862)  was  as  rich 
in  theological  learning  as  it  was  powerful  in  spec- 
ulative thought.  Indeed,  Erdmann  remarks  that 
"  its  extensive  and  intensive  wealth  of  matter "  was 


30  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

such  that  it  "  frightened  away  many  readers."  He 
would  prove  no  disunion  to  exist  between  dogma, 
rightly  understood,  and  true  philosophy.  The  work 
contained,  in  fact,  the  whole  system  of  Weisse  in 
outline.  But  it  did  not  adopt  the  pure  dialectical 
method  of  the  self-development  of  the  notion,  but 
took  more  account  of  religious  experience,  which 
it  would  treat  in  a  speculative  manner.  Weisse's 
movement  is  thus  away  from  abstract  idealism, 
and  into  his  deductive  method  he  manages  to 
weave  much  that  is  empirical,  with  fruitful  results, 
a  fact  that  was  too  often  overlooked.  The  concept 
of  God  is  for  Weisse  no  immediate  or  presupposi- 
tionless  one ;  it  is  not  given  through  experience 
as  such.  The  concept  of  absolute  spirit  he  takes 
to  be  first  fully  realised  in  the  trinity  of  reason, 
feeling  or  phantasy,  and  will.  Scientific  knowledge 
must  bring  to  consciousness,  out  of  pure  reason- 
speculation  and  universal  philosophic  world- view, 
those  knowledge  -  determinations  which  justify  it, 
and  attribute  to  it  objective  validity. 

I  do  not  propose  to  concern  myself  here  with  what 
Weisse  advances  as  to  the  so-called  proofs  for  the 
being  of  God :  I  only  remark  what  is  a  striking 
feature  in  Weisse,  the  emphasis  with  which  he 
insists  that  the  original  possibility  of  God  — "  in 
whose  possibility  is  included  every  other  possi- 
bility"— is  the  sole  content  of  thought-necessity. 
In  this  thought  of  the  possibility  of  God  he  finds 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN  WEISSE.  31 

the  absolute  of  pure  reason;  it  is  for  him  the 
truth  of  pure  thought-necessity.  Thus  for  Weisse's 
ontology  the  concept  of  the  possible  may  be  said 
to  count  for  more  than  that  of  being.  He  holds 
that  the  logical  and  mathematical  laws  of  the 
possible  are  valid  for  Deity,  who  moves  freely 
within  these,  just  as  the  artistic  genius  is  free 
within  the  laws  of  his  art.  The  category  of  the 
possible  is  important,  I  may  remark,  because  of 
the  way  it  relates  the  ideal  to  the  actual.  Thus, 
in  the  case  of  the  Godhead,  the  logical  Absolute 
furnishes,  for  Weisse,  only  the  forms  of  the  possi- 
bility of  being  or  existence,  as  a  last  background. 
The  real  and  personal  life  of  God,  however,  rests 
on  inner  freedom,  phantasy,  and  will.  The  concept 
of  freedom  is  here  the  spring  or  fountain  for  the 
outworking  of  Weisse's  doctrine,  But  no  abstract 
necessity  of  reason  can  give  more  than  empty  forms 
of  possibility,  says  Weisse,  and  for  knowledge  of 
the  real,  experience  is  everywhere  necessary.  But 
the  fundamental  error  of  the  Hegelian  philosophy 
is,  in  his  view,  its  thinking  to  advance  from  the 
concept  over  to  being  itself.  He  thinks  Hegel  has 
only  given  us  a  negative  prius  —  a  negative 
Absolute — while  claiming  to  have  given  a  positive 
one. 

This  thought  of  the  original  possibility  of  God, 
or  of  the  negative  Absolute — may  be  said  to  be 
the  basal  thought  of  Weisse's  system.  It  recalls 


32  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

for  me  Leibniz,  who  laid  great  stress  on  the 
possibility  of  God,  with  this  difference,  however, 
that  Leibniz  always  went  further  than  the  abstract 
possibility  in  which  Weisse  rests,  and  said  that 
God,  if  He  be  possible,  exists.  And  this,  again, 
reminds  one  of  the  saying  of  Aquinas,  "Deus  est 
actualitas  totius  possibilitatis."  But  if  that  original 
possibility  should  ever  become  actuality,  Weisse 
holds  that  it  can  only  be  thought  as  doing  so  as 
the  self-conscious  Primal  Subject,  or  the  Primal 
Personality.  With  fine  speculative  power  and 
ability,  Weisse  shows  how  the  absolute  idea,  the 
possibility  of  pure  being  or  existence,  is  in  a  peculiar 
sense  the  prius  of  tl  e  whole  Godhend — the  first 
member  (Glied),  in  fact,  of  the  Divine  triunity, 
which  has  been  known,  in  all  the  ages,  as  the 
Godhead  of  the  Father.  In  such  ways  Weisse 
reached  the  positive  in  his  Absolute.  The  Father 
is,  to  Weisse,  the  primary  Essence,  the  primary 
Foundation,  who  thinks  Himself.  The  Son  is,  to 
him,  Wisdom,  and  is  the  intellectual  cause  of  the 
Divine  world  of  feeling  or  phantasy.  The  Spirit 
is  the  moral  Will  or  Love,  and  ethically  wills  the 
ideal  world.  But  here,  as  we  shall  again  find  in 
Fischer,  the  Son  and  the  Spirit  are  distinguished 
only  as  attributes. 

Weisse  held  that  to  the  divine  Reason  and  its 
necessary  thoughts  must  be  added  the  divine  Heart 
and  the  divine  Will,  and  these  three  he  identified 


CHRISTIAN    HERMANN   WEISSE.  33 

with  the  Persons  of  the  Trinity.  Weisse  did  well 
in  the  way  he  brought  out  the  becoming  real  of 
the  original  possibility  or  thought  necessity  of  God 
to  mean  a  real  thinking  absolute  subject.  But 
he  unfortunately  begged  the  whole  question,  when 
he  introduced  this  absolute  Thinker  under  the 
conditions  of  subject  and  object,  because  he  mis- 
takenly supposed  this  necessary  to  the  idea  of 
personality.  This  was  to  fail  to  realise  that  person- 
ality has  its  ground  within  itself,  not  external 
to  it  —  in  the  realisation  of  the  ego,  not  in  the 
difference  of  the  ego  and  the  non-ego.  Such  a 
psychological  determination  of  human  thought  he 
had  clearly  no  right  to  carry  over  and  attach  to 
absolute  thought.  He  failed  to  see,  as  some 
philosophers  amongst  us  still  fail  to  see,  that  such 
real  oppositions  as  subjective  and  objective  prove 
for  human  thought,  do  not  exist  for  pure  absolute 
thought,  which  indeed  is  Absolute  Thought  precisely 
because  it  is  free  from  these  limitations.  No  good 
or  valid  reason,  I  maintain,  has  ever  been  adduced 
why  the  Absolute  Being  should  not  have,  perfectly 
unified  in  Himself,  subject  and  object  and  their 
relating  activity.  The  notion  that  self -conscious- 
ness in  God  is  like  finite  self -consciousness  in  its 
dependence  on  a  not-self  outside,  is,  to  use  a  term 
of  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison,  who  holds  this  position, 
an  "  exploded  "  one.  There  can  be  no  self -modifying 
term  to  assert  itself  as  a  not-self  to  the  Absolute 

c 


34  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Consciousness.  That  consciousness  has  no  non- 
ego  either  outside  or  within  its  own  infinite 
content,  which  embraces  the  totality  of  all  the 
real.  The  Ego  here,  and  the  non-ego,  are  only 
different  forms  of  being  contained  in  the  Absolute 
Ego.  The  Absolute,  if  really  taken  as  the  Absolute, 
can  in  no  wise  have  a  non-ego ;  for  that  is  possible 
only  to  a  finite  being.  We  cannot  take  Him  as 
the  Absolute  and,  at  the  same  time,  make  Him 
non  -  absolute,  as  is  sometimes  attempted.  This, 
although  it  is  still  useful  and  necessary  in  our 
relative  thought,  to  retain  the  distinction  of  subject- 
consciousness  and  object -consciousness  in  speaking 
of  the  Absolute  Experience;  but  it  cannot  be  as 
real  oppositions,  such  as  exist  in  human  thought. 
That  is  to  say,  for  Dr  Pringle  -  Pattison's  co- 
ordination of  the  object,  there  is  its  clear  and 
necessary  subordination,  in  the  case  of  the  Absolute. 
In  its  need  of  a  hyper-cosmic  principle,  the  world 
is  certainly  less  than  Being-in-and-of -itself. 

An  American  philosopher  has  remarked  that  "  it  is 
said  that  all  consciousness  involves  the  distinction 
of  subject  and  object,  and  hence  is  impossible  to 
an  isolated  and  single  being."  "But  this  claim 
mistakes  a  mental  form  for  an  ontological  distinc- 
tion. The  object  in  all  consciousness  is  always 
only  our  presentations,  and  not  something  ontologi- 
cally  diverse  from  the  mind  itself.  These  presenta- 
tions may  stand  for  things,  but  consciousness  extends 


CHRISTIAN  HERMANN  WEISSE.  35 

only  to  the  presentations.  In  self -consciousness 
this  is  manifestly  the  case.  Here  consciousness 
is  a  consciousness  of  our  states,  thoughts,  &c.,  as 
our  own.  The  Infinite,  then,  need  not  have  some- 
thing other  than  Himself  as  His  object,  but  ma,y 
find  the  object  in  His  own  activities,  cosmic  or 
otherwise."  But  Hegel  said  substantially  the  same 
thing  as  to  God  being  His  own  object,  that  it 
was  God  "to  distinguish  Himself  from  Himself, 
to  be  object  to  Himself,  &c."  The  failure  to 
recognise  all  that  I  have  now  advanced  makes 
the  necessity — once  more  assumed,  in  his  recent 
able  work  on  '  The  Idea  of  God,'  by  Prof.  Pringle- 
Pattison — of  the  world  to  the  Divine  self-conscious- 
ness, a  very  ill-founded  and  unconvincing  affair. 
The  Absolute  Being  sums  in  Himself  the  unity 
of  the  real  and  the  ideal,  and  has  no  need  of 
such  means  to  His  self-realisation.  It  is  a  gratui- 
tous anthropomorphism  to  think  otherwise. 

It  is  precisely  the  objection  to  Prof.  Pringle- 
Pattison's  whole  treatment  of  the  Absolute  Being 
or  Universal  Subject,  "just  as"  (p.  314)  the  finite 
is  done,  that  it  is  perfectly  untenable,  because, 
in  his  own  phrase,  "  ultimately  unmeaning."  God 
is,  to  him,  no  more  separable  from  the  universe  than 
finite  subjects  have  independent  subsistence  outside 
the  universal  life  in  which  they  are  set.  The 
analogy  is  to  be  rejected.  He  himself  recognises, 
in  another  connection,  that  we  have  no  analogy 


36  SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHERS. 

in  our  experience  to  the  Absolute  Experience 
(p.  293).  Of  it  I  say,  in  se  est,  et  per  se  concipitur. 
It  is  he  himself  who  says  of  Dr  Rashdall  (p.  389), 
that  it  is  "ultimately  unmeaning  to  treat  the 
universal "  as  the  particulars  are  done.  Dr  Pringle- 
Pattison  is  never  weary  of  insisting  that  the  Infinite 
is  "  in  and  through  the  finite  "  (pp.  254,  315).  What 
is  the  value  of  this  insistence  ?  Not  true  in  any 
sense  that  makes  it  of  any  more  value  here  than 
the  merest  truism.  The  finite  may  posit  or  affirm 
the  absolute  or  infinite,  no  doubt,  but  it  does  not, 
as  suggested,  constitute  it;  in  fact,  so  little  does 
the  finite  really  posit  the  absolute  or  infinite, 
that  it  much  more  has  the  absolute  or  infinite  for 
its  presupposition.  This  dependence  of  the  finite 
he  is  himself  compelled  to  acknowledge  (pp.  250-1). 
It  is  in  its  necessity  to  the  finite  that  we  know  the 
Infinite.  It  is  interesting  to  recall  the  terms  in 
which  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison,  earlier,  spoke  of  the 
position  which  he  now  adopts,  that  "the  strange 
thing  would  rather  seem  to  be  that  man  should  ever 
forget  his  position  as  a  finite  incident  in  the  plan 
of  things  "  ;  that  it  is  "  both  absurd  and  blasphemous 
to  suppose"  that  "it  is  reserved  for  man  to  bring 
the  Absolute  as  it  were  to  the  birth";  and  "that 
the  Absolute  exists,  so  to  speak,  by  the  grace  of 
man,  and  lives  only  in  the  breath  of  his  nostrils  " 
('Two  Lectures  on  Theism/  p.  50).  It  is  no  new 
thing,  in  the  history  of  philosophy,  for  a  thinker's 
second  thoughts  not  to  be  his  best. 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN   WEISSE.  37 

No  sound  theism  regards  Deity  as  a  being 
conditioned  by  environment,  "just  as"  a  man  is,  not 
even  if,  in  this  apotheosis,  man  be  proclaimed 
"the  one  perpetual  miracle."  I  reject  the  talk 
of  a  metaphysic  of  experience  in  this  connection, 
for  it  is  experience  only  in  a  narrow,  cramped,  and 
positivistic  sense,  with  deadening  effect  on  specula- 
tive impulse.  A  true  metaphysic  of  experience 
must  be  interpreted  in  so  large  a  sense  as  to  include 
not  merely  what  we  know  of  God  through  the 
"objective  creation,"  but  God's  self-revealings  in 
our  mental  constitution  and  our  spiritual  conscious- 
ness, wherein  are  given  to  us  much  of  the  best  we 
know  of  Him.  There  are  realms  of  truth  and  being, 
the  knowledge  of  which,  whether  reached  as  con- 
ceived, that  is,  logically  discriminated,  or  as  dis- 
cerned through  rational  and  spiritual  intuition, 
is  gained  through  what  are  properly  experience- 
forms.  No  one  who  has  shed  a  merely  positivist 
cast  of  thought  would  talk  of  "  proof "  in  such  a 
connection,  since  the  truths  that  so  come  to  us 
appear  as  necessary  truth.  There  is  no  higher 
"  proof "  of  the  truth  of  a  concept  than  thought- 
necessity.  Not  God  simply  as  the  World-Subject, 
but  as  the  free  Absolute  Personality,  not  God  as 
creative  only,  but  as  the  sole  self-existent  Being, 
do  we  thus  come  to  know.  But  Dr  Pringle-Pattison, 
having  started  out  with  the  correlation  of  God 
as  World-Subject  and  the  World-Object,  never  does, 
or  can,  rise  above  this  correlation,  or  eternal 


38  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

dualism,  which  is  to  me  a  most  unsatisfactory 
position.  I  am  certainly  of  those  who  reject  such 
a  "  Siamese-twin  "  connection,  as  it  has  been  styled, 
between  God  and  the  world,  as  one  that  derogates 
from  the  Deity,  never  allows  Him  to  come  to  His 
own  as  Lord  of  all  being,  and  dogmatically  repre- 
sents this  eternal  minorship  as  an  improvement 
in  the  idea  of  God!  God  is  the  Absolute  Self 
or  Being,  self-existent,  and  distinct  from  the  world- 
process,  as  the  primary  absolutely  Given  and  Real. 

It  is  easy  to  understand  why  Weisse  will  not  have 
the  personality  of  God  taken  "  immediately  "  as  the 
Absolute,  nor  the  Absolute  taken  "  immediately  "  as 
Personality.  This  is  because  between  the  Absolute 
of  pure  reason  or  the  infinite  possibility  of  God, 
on  the  one  hand,  and  the  living,  personal  God  of 
religious  experience,  there  is,  in  his  view,  a  great 
difference.  It  cannot  be  denied,  I  think,  that  there 
were  thinkers  of  that  time,  Rothe,  for  example,  who 
started  at  once,  and  too  soon,  from  the  representation 
that  God  is  the  Absolute.  It  seems  to  me  that  this 
position  is  reached  only  through  reflection :  we  must 
begin,  I  think,  with  the  pure  concept  of  the  Absolute, 
and  only  finally  do  we  come  to  identify  the  Absolute 
which  we  have  thought,  with  the  God  of  religious 
experience.  To  me  it  is  by  no  means  unimportant 
that  our  thought  as  pure  thought  should  prove  a 
philosophical  working  up  to  our  more  concrete  repre- 
sentation. Many  thinkers,  I  may  add,  have  debated 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN   WEISSE.  39 

whether  the  Absolute  is  a  positive  or  a  merely 
negative  conception.  If  we  think  the  absolutely 
Unconditioned,  negative  in  a  verbal  form  but  not  in 
idea,  we  shall,  I  believe,  be  left  in  the  end  with  the 
most  positive  of  all  concepts,  that,  namely,  of  the 
absolutely  self-determined  and  all-conditioning  Being. 
But,  though  we  may  and  must  distinguish  with 
Weisse  the  Absolute  of  pure  thought  or  reason- 
possibility  from  the  God  of  religious  experience,  yet 
the  former  Absolute  does  most  surely  come  to  be 
taken  at  last  as  a  personal  Absolute,  really  or  ulti- 
mately identical  with  the  latter.  Two  Absolutes 
there  cannot  be,  without  the  grossest  absurdity,  yea, 
the  uttermost  inconceivability. 

Also,  for  Weisse  the  Triune  God  is  personal,  for 
what  we  have  seen  to  be  the  commonplace  and  un- 
satisfactory reason  that  God  cannot  be  a  person 
without  other  persons.  As  if  the  case  were  not  that 
of  the  Absolute  Who  is  the  Universal  Personality. 
God  is  the  Absolute  Individual,  the  self-subsistent 
Being,  the  infinite  plentitude  of  Being  and  of  Ration- 
ality, and,  as  such,  is  not  anthropomorphic,  albeit  He 
has  all  the  notes  of  Personality.  And  when  I  speak 
of  Him  as  the  Universal  Personality,  I  do  not,  of 
course,  mean  it  in  the  vulgar  quantitative  sense,  but 
that  He  is  the  metaphysical  reason  of  all  beings,  and 
that  nothing  exists  but  by  Him.  I  do  not  follow 
Weisse  in  this  matter,  and  I  remain  unconvinced  by 
recent  discussions  of  any  philosophical  necessity  to 


40  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

drag  in  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity  in  order  to 
establish  the  personality  of  God.  Theism,  in  the 
philosophical  sense,  takes  God  to  be  a  single  personal 
Being.  That  is  its  view  of  the  "one  form  with 
many  names,"  to  use  a  phrase  of  ^Eschylus,  in  the 
worship  of  mankind  ("  Prom.  Vinct."  1.  212).  But  it 
is  to  me  a  perfectly  gratuitous  assumption  that  such 
a  Being  as  God,  of  infinite  internal  complexity  and 
distinction,  could  not  be  eternally  active  within  His 
own  absolute  Being.  At  any  rate,  the  absoluteness 
of  being  is  to  me  the  first  determination,  and  it  is 
not  yet  trinitarian  I  must  not  be  supposed,  in 
what  has  already  been  said,  not  to  hold  the  simplicity 
of  God's  being,  its  entire  freedom  from  composition 
of  any  kind,  but  I  am  not  unmindful  of  Rothe's 
word  that  there  is  a  way  of  thinking  God  as  an 
entirely  simple  being  that  brings  with  it  a  strong 
temptation  "  to  form  a  pantheistic  conception  of  Him 
as  particularising  Himself  in  the  world."  Weisse 
also  favoured  modal  and  relational  forms  of  Divine 
manifestation  under  a  trinity  of  nature,  man,  and 
art,  and  of  the  ideas  of  the  true,  the  beautiful,  and 
the  good. 

Of  course,  I  have  not  here  been  denying  the  value 
of  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity,  when  it  comes  to 
developing  the  riches  of  Divine  Personality.  An 
eminent  Catholic  writer  has  said  that  "the  Three 
Persons  in  God  are  not  as  human  persons,  each  of 
whom  has  a  separate  being ;  but  they  are  the  three 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN   WEISSE.  41 

Divine  terms  or  perfections  of  One  infinite  and 
Eternal  Life."  Or,  as  an  illustrious  German  thinker 
once  put  it,  "  this  one  Divine  Personality  is  the  unity 
of  the  three  modes  of  subsistence  which  participate 
in  itself."  That  oneness  of  personal  Life,  at  any  rate, 
so  sums  all  we  know  of  God  as  to  afford  reason  for 
our  speaking  of  the  Personality  of  God.  But  I 
would  explicitly  remark  that  Weisse,  like  Fichte, 
calls  in  the  aid  of  the  world-idea  in  order  to  set  up 
the  self-consciousness  of  God,  a  procedure  whose 
philosophical  necessity,  I  maintain,  has  not  been 
shown,  and  which  in  the  end  defeats  itself,  leaving 
the  world -idea  no  longer  the  product  of  free  self- 
conscious  Deity.  But  the  pure  internal  product  of 
the  Divine  Mind  the  world-idea  must  be,  and,  as 
such,  it  cannot  be  identified  with  God,  a  fact  which, 
as  we  shall  see  later,  Ulrici  failed  adequately  to 
realise.  That  inner  logical  distinction  must  be 
clearly  kept  in  mind.  It  is  not  my  purpose  now  to 
set  out  the  lengthy  argumentations  of  Weisse  on 
these  and  other — theological  and  mythological — 
matters :  it  is  enough  for  my  purpose  to  note  that 
his  speculative  theism  makes  its  way  round  to  the 
necessary  conception  of  the  unity  in  the  manifoldness 
of  the  products  of  the  Divine  generation  or  begetting. 
But  Weisse's  whole  argumentation  rests  essentially 
upon  the  idea  of  a  process  wherein  God  raises 
Himself  to  actuality  out  of  the  pure  possibility  of 
being.  And  with  all  this  process  of  self-realisation 


42  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

in  God  in  pre-creational  time,  there  comes  to  be 
associated  a  cosmogonic  process  later,  in  time.  Crea- 
tion is,  for  him,  through  free  resolution  of  God's  will, 
and  consists  in  a  series  of  acts  that  begin  and 
continue  in  time.  First  of  these  is  the  formation  of 
matter,  from  whose  nature  Weisse  derives  the  meta- 
physical necessity  of  evil,  since  he  conceives  matter, 
so  externalised,  as  having  put  itself  into  opposition 
to  the  Divine  personal  Will.  But  this  does  not  seem 
to  me  a  position  for  which  there  is  any  proper 
philosophical  warrant  or  substantiation.  Not  only 
so,  but  Weisse  even  presupposes  a  Divine  or  infinite 
space,  which  he  takes  to  be  the  fundamental  form  of 
the  life  of  the  inner  Divine  nature.  The  Divine 
Will  contains  the  immediate  that  of  reality ;  the 
divine  Nature  its  what ;  and  the  Divine  Will  is  free 
and  self-conscious.  But  such  a  becoming  of  God,  as 
has  just  been  spoken  of,  out  of  potentiality,  and  by 
means  of  developmental  process,  is  obviously  philo- 
sophically objectionable  in  many  ways,  to  any  one 
at  least  who,  like  Weisse,  would  avoid  pantheistic 
tendency  and  suggestion.  Rothe,  too,  showed  like 
traces  of  the  influence  of  pantheistic  speculation  in 
his  talk  of  the  process  of  self-generation,  wherein 
Deity  passes  from  potentiality  to  actuality.  For  he 
felt,  in  fact,  the  after  effects  of  the  Schleiermacherian 
pantheism.  But  the  Absolute  Being  stands  above 
time,  growth,  change,  succession,  and  but  for  this 
changeless  Absolute  we  could  not  even  know  the  flux 


CHKISTIAN   HERMANN   WEISSE.  43 

of  time — a  fact  which  many  present-day  philosophers 
fail  to  realise. 

In  striking  contrast  with  the  Augustinian  view  of 
time,  Weisse  posited  time  as  eternally  in  God.  He 
thought  infinite  time  and  infinite  space  to  be  powers 
of  the  Divine  Life,  for  to  him  the  forms  of  time 
and  space  were  eternal  truths  or  original  forms  of 
the  absolute  possibility  of  being.  Not  powers  above 
God,  since  Weisse  supposed  them  to  be  eternally 
overcome  by  the  Divine  eternity  and  perfection.  In 
the  form  in  which  they  exist  in  God,  however,  they 
have  for  him  nothing  in  common  with  space  and 
time,  as  we  know  them.  Still  the  fact  remains 
that  number,  time,  and  space,  were  all  three  forms 
taken  by  Weisse  to  be  real  and  objective,  alike  for 
God  and  for  the  world.  The  immanent  presup- 
positions of  space  and  time  were  made  by  Weisse 
with  a  view  to  the  Divine  creative  activity,  but 
his  theory  does  not  seem  to  me  to  be  free  of 
inherent  difficulties,  although  some  important 
German  thinkers  have  found  it  maieutic  or  sug- 
gestive. Instead  of  so  postulating  time  and  space 
eternally  in  God,  it  is  surely  enough  for  us  to  pos- 
tulate them  as  possibilities,  not  in  any  actual,  but 
merely  in  a  logical  sense.  I  hold  eternity  to  be 
that  which  cannot  not-l)Q,  and  that  it  is  a  necessary 
presupposition  of  time.  For  it  must  hold  within 
it  the  perpetual  possibility  of  time.  And  there  is 
only  one  Eternity,  which  is  thus  an  All,  and  must, 


44  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

I  believe,  in  the  last  analysis,  be  identified  with  God. 
The  problem  occurs  again  in  Fischer. 

Divine  Revelation  was,  to  Weisse's  "  Philosophical 
Dogmatics,"  history,  and  revelation  was  for  the  race, 
not  for  that  part  which  lives  in  the  midst  of  it. 
But  it  does  not  belong  to  our  present  task  to  follow 
his  eindringenden  Bemerkungen,  as  they  have  been 
termed,  on  this  subject.  He  thought  the  foreknow- 
ledge of  God  involved  what  he  calls  positive  and 
glaring  (klare  und  helle)  determinism,  wherein  the 
freedom  of  created  beings  was  annulled.  He  failed 
to  realise  that  such  foreknowledge  by  no  means 
carried  with  it  causal  efficiency  and  will-determin- 
ation. As  I  am  touching  now  on  the  freewill 
problem,  I  remark  that  no  thinker  of  that  time 
thought  out  the  freewill  problem  more  deeply  than 
did  Deutinger,  of  whom  I  am  not  to  treat.  He  was 
greatly  influenced  by  Schelling,  the  lack  in  whose 
speculation  he  yet  clearly  perceived,  but  also  by 
Baader.  The  freedom  of  the  will  was,  for  him,  the 
central  core  of  personality;  without  it,  he  thinks 
there  is  no  morality;  and  no  being  for  ones  self; 
and  where  there  is  no  free  ground  of  determination, 
there  is  no  personality.  Any  philosophy,  Deutinger 
shows,  that  knows  no  true  personality,  knows  also 
no  revelation.  "  Revelation  emphasises  the  personal 
element  in  God,"  says  an  American  writer,  "and 
gives  it  a  position  not  otherwise  attainable  by  it" 
(J.  Bascom,  'Philosophy  of  Religion/  p.  206). 


CHRISTIAN   HERMANN  WEISSE.  45 

On  the  problem  of  Immortality,  Weisse  saw  the 
advantage  of  the  personal  Absolute,  as  securing 
the  real  immortality  of  man.  Weisse  reserved  im- 
mortality, however,  for  the  regenerate.  With  his 
interesting  interpretations  of  eschatological  matters 
we  are  not  here  concerned,  though  I  do  not  mean  that 
they  do  not  belong  to  theism,  but  a  word  may  be 
said  on  the  question  of  immortality,  as  developed 
subsequently  to  Fichte  and  Weisse.  Lotze  made 
no  serious,  or  at  least  no  successful,  attempt  to 
harmonise  the  ethical  and  the  metaphysical  aspects 
of  the  subject.  He  thought  we^  should  be  "  content 
to  retain  the  general  idea  of  a  continued  life" 
without  "that  intimate  acquaintance"  which  had 
been  claimed  for  it.  That  he  had  nothing  better 

o 

to  say  is  not  surprising,  when  writers  on  the  idea 
of  immortality  in  our  own  time  still  fail  to  ap- 
preciate the  fact  that  neither  the  ethics  of  immor- 
tality, nor  any  other  ethic,  is  secured  against  the 
fictitious,  the  illusory,  the  merely  provisory,  until 
metaphysical  grounding  has  been  reached.  The 
ethical  "  argument "  for  immortality  may,  of  course, 
be  formulated  independently  of  metaphysics,  but 
an  "illusory  belief  in  immortality"  was  precisely 
what  Prof.  Sidgwick  ('Memoir/  p.  472)  held  to 
be  current,  and  this  may  still  be  charged,  when 
no  metaphysical  grounding  has  been  sought  or 
reached  (Cf.  my  '  Philosophical  System  of  Theistic 
Idealism/  ch.  xi.). 


46  SEVEN   THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

It  is  to  another  type  of  mind  than  that  of  either 
Royce  or  M'Taggart  we  should  look  for  appreciation 
of  the  metaphysical  implications  of  immortality. 
Royce  makes  everything  "depend  upon  the  meta- 
physical interpretation  and  foundation  of  the  com- 
munity" (cThe  Problem  of  Christianity,'  vol.  ii.  p. 
11).  A  metaphysician  may  carry  through  this 
"corporate"  inquiry,  and  miss  a  great  deal  of  the 
metaphysical  implications  essential  to  a  satisfying 
theory  of  personal  immortality.  There  can  be  no 
talk  of  "proofs"  here,  any  more  than  in  the  case 
of j  the  being  of  God,  in  the  old  formal  logic  sense 
of  "proof,"  but  only  in  a  dialectical  sense,  as  de- 
scribing the  way  of  spirit — an  inner  way.  If  there 
is  immortality,  it  is  that  of  the  soul  or  self  as  a 
thinking,  willing,  and  feeling  being  or  essence, 
whose  immortality  must  have  metaphysical  aspects 
or  relations,  for  the  ontological  sense. 

The  ethical  presentation  must  lack  in  depth  and 
solidity  of  treatment,  cannot,  in  fact,  be  well  founded, 
so  long  as  the  unescapable  metaphysical  aspects  and 
relations  have  been  shirked  or  ignored.  More  sug- 
gestive than  Lotze's  are  the  positions  of  Feuerbach 
on  immortality.  For,  even  with  his  absurd  tendency 
to  run  theology  back  into  anthropology,  there  has 
yet  not  been  a  more  original  psychological  critic  of 
religion  since  Hume's  time  than  he.  In  what  has 

o 

been  termed  the  "  rich  "  and  "  delicate  "  psychology 
of  his  best  period,  there  is  much  that  is  suggestive, 


CHKISTIAN   HERMANN  WEISSE.  47 

and  not  least  on  the  subject  of  immortality,  despite 
his  putting  logical  reasoning  before  spiritual  reality, 
and  the  too  great  identity  that  marked  his  whole 
system.  The  need  here,  for  metaphysicians  and  still 
more  for  ethicists,  is  of  a  deeply  grounded  theistic 
metaphysic,  capable  of  applying  to  this  connection 
the  words  of  Troeltsch,  —  "  Only  the  personality 
which  arises,  out  of  man,  to  beyond  him  as  a  mere 
natural  product,  through  a  union  of  his  will  and 
deepest  being  with  God — this  alone  is  raised  above 
the  finite,  and  alone  can  defy  it.  Without  this 
support,  every  individualism  evaporates  into  thin 
air."  This  will  take  us  to  a  higher  metaphysical 
plane  than  Dr  M'Taggart's  metaphysic  of  immor- 
tality. I  find  finer  and  more  explicit  recognition  of 
the  metaphysical  aspects,  values,  and  implications,  of 
immortality  in  theological  writing,  thirty  or  more 
years  ago,  than  in  that  of  to-day ;  surely  not  much 
of  our  vaunted  development  there  !  Happily,  things 
have  fared  better  in  philosophy,  to  some  real  extent 
at  least,  especially  when  philosophy  is  not  taken  as 
limited  to  our  own  country. 

I  think  it  would  be  a  legitimate  criticism  to  say 
that,  so  far  as  speculative  theology  is  concerned, 
both  Weisse  and  I.  H.  Fichte,  working  after  Hegel, 
were  inclined  to  use  too  abstract  categories.  They 
both  recognised  the  dialectic  of  Hegel,  so  far  as  the 
supply  of  the  necessary  forms  was  concerned,  but 
they  both  thought  (each  in  his  different  way)  it 


48  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

called  for  supplementing  from  the  experiential  side. 
Fichte's  '  Ontology '  manifested  dialectic  dependence 
on  Hegel's  'Logic/  but  he  did  not  escape  Trendel- 
enburg's  sharp  criticism  for  his  procedure  ('Log. 
Unter.'  I.  p.  103).  Trendelenburg  was  inclined  to 
view  Weisse's  and  Fichte's  result  as  a  doubtful  go- 
between,  in  respect  of  dialectic  and  experience. 
Philosophy  may,  I  think,  rightly  enough,  develop  all 
its  categories  out  of  the  differences  of  self -conscious- 
ness, but  speculative  theology  is  not  concerned  with 
the  impossible  task  of  developing  the  Divine  self- 
consciousness  out  of  abstract  categories,  but  rather 
with  the  attempt  to  deal  with  the  empirico-historical 
God-consciousness,  and  the  questions  that  naturally 
spring  therefrom. 

This  does  not  mean,  of  course,  that  there  will  not 
follow,  for  speculative  theology  also,  a  resultant 
system  or  systematic  unfolding.  But,  in  what  I 
have  just  said,  I  should  not  admit  that  speculative 
theology  ever  need,  or  should,  be  less  rigidly  philoso- 
phical in  its  procedure  than  philosophy  of  the  most 
rationalist  or  agnostic  or  positivist  type.  In  both 
cases,  self -consciousness  is  in  reality,  I  hold,  the  first 
starting-point ;  even  if,  in  the  former,  a  consciousness 
of  the  Divine  should  be  superadded,  self-consciousness 
is  still  preserved  therein,  and  indeed  in  heightened 
form.  Speculative  theology,  in  my  view,  begins,  no 
less  than  philosophy  in  general,  with  man  and  the 
phenomenal  world,  and  reaches  God  only  as  the 


CHEISTIAN    HERMANN   WEISSE.  49 

result  of  experience  and  reflection.  This  should  not 
be  overlooked,  if  ever  speculative  theology  puts  God, 
as  a  matter  of  logical  concern,  in  the  forefront  of  its 
system.  Some  of  these  considerations  were  too 
much  overlooked,  in  my  judgment,  by  K-othe,  for 
example.  The  only  difference,  then,  is  that  phil- 
osophy or  general  speculation  does  not  proceed  from 
the  religious  consciousness,  which,  as  the  more  in- 
clusive, is  followed  by  speculative  theology,  but  they 
are  both,  and  equally,  valid. 

Weisse  and  Fichte  both  sought  to  build  up  an 
ethical  theism  in  opposition  to  the  pantheistic 
idealism  of  Hegel.  The  immediate  influence  of 
Weisse  and  Fichte  was  conspicuous,  among  other 
ways,  on  both  the  ethics  and  the  dogmatics  of  Rothe, 
of  whom  I  am  not  to  treat,  nor  was  the  influence 
wholly  wanting  on  Rothe  of  Chalybaus,  of  whom  J 
have  still  to  speak.  But  Rothe  had  also  been  in- 
fluenced by  Oetinger  and  by  Baader.  Of  Weisse's 
important  philosophical  influence  I  have  already 
spoken,  in  the  beginning  of  this  chapter,  in  connec- 
tion with  Seydel's  view  of  it.  His  potent  influence 
is  not  surprising,  since,  as  Pfleiderer,  whose  '  Phil- 
osophy of  Religion'  does  so  poorly  by  our  group 
(omitting  most  of  them),  remarks  elsewhere  of 
Weisse,  that  "  his  system  is  not  without  the  origin- 
ality of  genius,  and  contains  an  abundance  of 
profound  and  fertile  thoughts"  ('The  Development 
of  Theology  in  Germany  since  Kant,'  p.  145). 


50 


CHAPTER   III. 

K.   P.   FISCHER. 

K.  PH.  FISCHER  (1807-1885),  another  member  of 
this  group  of  philosophers,  was  largely  influenced 
by  Baader,  by  Oken,  and  by  Schelling;  the  last- 
named  was  his  point  of  departure,  rather  than  Fichte 
(the  elder),  as  in  the  case  of  Fichte  the  younger,  or 
Hegel  as  in  the  case  of  Weisse.  Fischer  was  an 
energetic  critic  of  Hegel,  and  opposed,  like  Fichte 
and  Weisse,  an  impersonal  logical  God,  but  even 
his  statements  of  the  measure  of  truth  contained 
in  absolute  idealism  were  valuable  and  interesting. 
His  work  on  'The  Idea  of  the  Godhead '  (1839) 
claims  to  be  an  attempt  to  ground  and  develop 
Theism  in  a  speculative  manner.  He  does  not 
profess  it  to  be  purely  philosophical,  and  without 
theological  tendency,  for  he  thinks  philosophical  and 
theological  truth  must  come  into  essential  agree- 
ment. This,  although  he  was,  at  the  time  of  his 
death,  professor  of  philosophy  in  Erlangen.  It 
might  be  objected,  however,  as  a  German  critic  has 


KARL   PHILIPP   FISCHER.  51 

pointed  out,  that  he  makes  philosophy  dependent 
on  theology,  when  he  goes  on  to  assume  Christianity 
to  be  the  absolute  religion,  with  which  the  phil- 
osophy of  religion  has  to  do,  with  the  Christian 
consciousness  as  its  inner  presupposition.  It  must 
certainly  be  agreed  that  it  is  the  business  of  phil- 
osophy to  take,  without  presuppositions,  appearances 
as  it  finds  them,  and  try  to  explain  them,  without 
the  warping  influence  of  preconceived  notions.  At 
the  same  time,  I  should  not  admit  that  a  speculative 
thinker  was  less  philosophic  because,  to  bare  self- 
consciousness,  as  such,  he  added  religious  conscious- 
ness, for  in  what  we  may  call  his  religious  self- 
consciousness,  his  self -consciousness  is  still  present, 
and,  in  fact,  realises  itself  more  truly  than  before. 
For  then,  in  being  conscious  at  the  same  time  of  his 
relation  to  God,  the  thinker  grows  more  certain  of 
himself — gains  deepened  self -consciousness,  and  is 
better  fitted  for  philosophic  inquiry. 

In  the  work  on  '  The  Idea  of  the  Godhead '  already 
mentioned,  Fischer  seeks  by  use  of  the  historical 
development  to  bring  out  that  Theism  is  no  resultant 
of  arbitrary  and  subjective  thinking,  but  is  the 
scientifically  ascertained  truth  of  the  history  of 
speculative  theology.  He  lays  especial  stress  on  the 
notion  of  the  absolute  Unity  or  the  absolute  Idea, 
as  one  to  which  thought,  of  inner  necessity,  raises 
itself.  This  idea  of  an  absolute  unity  is  a  presup- 
position to  which  we  are  thus  immediately  brought 


52  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

by  the  inward  becoming  of  reason.  I  may  remark 
that,  like  Fischer  here,  Wirth  and  some  others  set 
out  from  the  concept  of  pure  unity.  Sengler  was 
one  of  these,  and  he  leant  to  metaphysical  philosophy, 
under  the  influence  of  Schelling,  as  Fischer  did  to 
theory  of  knowledge,  not  without  influence  from 
Leibniz.  It  is  with  the  help  of  this  ideal  unity  that 
Fischer  hopes  to  prove  that  the  Being,  whom  this 
unity  represents,  must  be  personal.  Particular  specu- 
lative systems  are  to  Fischer  but  so  many  different 
forms  of  the  absolute  Idea.  The  Absolute  can  be 
thought  merely  as  the  principle  or  the  unity  of  the 
world,  as  in  pantheism.  Or,  it  may  be  conceived  as 
self-conscious  principle  or  a  unity  of  being-in-and- 
for-itself,  with  inner  determinations  and  qualities, 
as  in  theism.  Fischer  reviews  the  forms  of  historic 
pantheism  from  the  abstract  pantheism  of  the 
Eleatics,  through  the  substantial  pantheism  of 
Spinoza,  the  realistic  pantheism  of  Oken  and 
Schleiermacher,  on  to  the  idealistic  pantheism  of 
Hegel,  in  which  he  finds  the  highest  and  most 
perfect  form  of  pantheism.  But  he  finds  the  type 
of  unity  provided  by  theism  to  be  the  higher  one. 
In  this  work  Fischer  says  that  being  presupposes 
a  becoming,  that  is,  self-determination.  But  I  think 
it  might  be  asked  whether  being  does  not  before 
all  presuppose  self-possession — a  self -having — an 
important  point  for  these  discussions,  as  we  shall 
see  later. 


KARL   PHILIPP  FISCHER.  53 

Though  I  do  not  mean  to  traverse  what  Fischer 
says  on  the  proofs  for  the  Being  of  God,  yet  I  wish 
to  note  that,  in  connection  with  the  Ontological 
argument,  he  looks  favourably  on  the  contention 
that  the  essentially  unescapable  need  of  a  Supreme 
Being  is  of  a  kind  that  carries  with  it  the  corre- 
sponding reality  of  the  same.  This  maintenance,  I 
may  remark,  was  metaphysically  grounded  by 
Fechner  in  his  work,  entitled  'The  Three  Motives 
and  Grounds  of  Faith/  and  explicitly  made  to 
enclose  the  personality  of  God.  The  truth  of  the 
thought,  Fischer  says,  encloses  the  reality  in  itself. 
It  would,  he  thinks,  be  an  inner  contradiction  to 
hold  a  thought  as  true,  and  yet  count  it  unreal. 
In  this  work  on  the  Godhead,  and  in  his  most 
notable  work  still  to  be  spoken  of,  Fischer  holds 
that  the  absolute  principle  of  all  things  cannot  be 
conceived  otherwise  than  as  having  existence ; 
human  reason  were  else  radically  deceptive  and 
illusive;  the  objective  truth  of  rational  knowledge 
would  be  done  away.  Of  the  whole  Kantian  scepti- 
cism on  the  question  of  the  existence  of  God,  Fischer 
says  that  "the  conceit  of  having  put  a  complete 
end  to  the  scientific  investigation  of  objective  truth 
really  involves  the  haughty  presumption  of  pro- 
nouncing judgment  on  the  systems  of  all  the  phil- 
osophers who  have  honestly  and  truly  followed  in 
the  footsteps  of  Plato,  as  well  as  a  renunciation  of 
that  knowledge  of  the  truth  which  is  the  end  and 


54  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

aim  of  all  true  culture,  and  should  by  no  means  be 
regarded  as  humility  and  self-restraint/' 

In  all  this,  Fischer  is  contrastive  with  the  non- 
speculative  spirit  of  a  religious  writer,  who  tells  us 
that  "if"  the  ontological  argument  has  "a  shadow 
of  validity,  it  is  useless  in  a  religious  interest " 
(G.  Galloway,  'Mind,'  July  1919,  p.  366).  Both 
philosophical  and  religious  writers  have  shown  a 
singular  capacity  for  forgetting  that  both  the 
Monologion  and  the  Proslogion  of  Anselm  were 
as  far  as  possible  from  purely  intellectual  per- 
formances ;  what  we  have  in  both  is,  fides  quaerens 
intellectum.  The  Proslogion,  in  which  the  Anselmic 
form  of  the  ontological  argument  occurs,  is  a  lifting 
up  of  the  soul  to  God,  and  I  am  not  without  doubt 
whether  Anselm's  Greatest,  conceived  by  him  in 
such  a  setting,  was  to  him  the  purely  metaphysical, 
and  morally  qualityless,  magnitude,  which  it  has 
commonly  been  assumed  to  be.  Anselm,  however, 
helped  to  give  this  impression,  when,  in  his  con- 
troversy with  Gaunilo,  he  sacrificed  the  moral  to 
giving  his  argument  supposed  scientific  form. 

The  ontological  argument,  however,  is  to  be 
reckoned  with  in  its  many  fine  formulations  in 
modern  thought,  wherein  a  background  of  infinite 
and  necessary  Being  or  Reality  is  seen  to  be  involved 
in  our  thought  or  knowledge ;  the  appreciation  of  it, 
however,  depends  on  speculative  insight.  Religion 
will  win  no  respect  by  a  too  ready  application  of  the 


KARL  PHILIPP   FISCHER.  55 

yardstick  of  "  interest "  or  value  to  such  high,  specu- 
lative matters.  And  it  should  be  the  last  to  flout 
the  immanence  of  God  in  human  ideals.  In  this 
connection,  one  thinker  has  said,  "  imperfect  as  may 
be  the  form  in  which  it  has  often  been  presented,  the 
principle  of  this  argument  is  that  on  which  our 
whole  religious  consciousness  may  be  said  to  rest." 
What,  on  such  a  view,  becomes  of  the  "  uselessness," 
as  a  religious  "interest,"  which  has  been  so  lightly 
affirmed  ?  Anselm,  with  his  quantitativeness,  and 
Descartes,  with  his  predicativeness,  busied  them- 
selves too  much  about  establishing  existence,  instead 
of  pursuing  the  ideality  on  which  the  proof  really 
rests,  and  rising  to  assert  the  actuality  of  the  Being 
Who  is  the  infinite,  prevenient,  and  necessary  ideal 
of  the  human  spirit.  Such  an  ideal  cannot  be  merely 
subjective.  That  Being  is  Spirit,  not  mere  existence ; 
is  before  and  beyond  all  thought  and  all  things ;  is, 
in  fact,  by  underlying  presupposition,  self -existent 
Being.  Such  a  Being  as  this  latter  cannot  be  proved, 
but  must,  on  rational  grounds,  be  assumed,  and  may 
be  rightfully  asserted  as  the  prevenient,  but  also 
the  actual  and  infinite  ideal  of  our  spirit.  But  the 
reality  of  the  idea  of  God  is  discernible  only  as 
the  reality  itself  is  present  to  the  idea  in  experience, 
that  is  to  say,  religious  experience.  The  validating 
of  the  idea  of  God  does  not  belong  to  mere  thought, 
as  such.  "  God  transcends  all  conception,"  said 
Anselm,  and,  if  so,  He  cannot  be  a  mere  conception 


56  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

of  the  human  intellect.  Our  speculative  conceptions 
of  God,  which  have  their  place  and  value,  are  clearly 
to  be  distinguished  from  the  position  of  those  who 
hold  that  God  is  as  much  a  matter  of  empirical 
knowledge  as  any  other  reality.  Anselm  compares 
the  mode  of  thought  which  makes  God  a  product 
of  the  mind  with  that  which  conceives  Him  as 
existing.  He  did  not  offer  to  prove  God's  exist- 
ence, but  said  that  He  is,  and  cannot  be  conceived 
not  to  exist.  No  more  does  Hegel  allow  any 
formal  demonstration  of  God's  existence;  to  him 
the  idea  of  God  means  the  unity  of  thought 
and  existence.  An  interesting,  if  not  convincing, 
criticism  of  them  both  is  given  by  Kleutgen 
('La  Phil.  Scolastique,'  vol.  iv.  pp.  340-355). 

Dr  James  Ward  has  spoken  very  incautiously 
of  what  Kant  has  effected  here.  Kant  missed  this 
aspect  of  ideality  in  the  proof,  and  his  criticism 
remained  inconclusive  against  it,  although  he  was 
right,  of  course,  so  far  as  our  voluntary  and 
assertive  part — the  deplorable  "  dollar  "  part — of  the 
argument,  is  concerned.  No  wonder  Hegel  said 
nothing  could  be  "pettier  in  knowledge  than  this," 
for  it  was  quite  unworthy  of  Kant's  genius.  These 
imperfect  apprehensions  and  treatments  do  not 
touch  the  essential  worth  and  validity  of  the 
ontological  argument  itself,  as  deeper  reflection 
shows:  it  is  still  the  case  that  the  highest  essence, 
when  thought,  must  be  thought  as  absolute  and 


KARL   PHILIPP   FISCHER.  57 

self  -  existing.  As  Prof.  Pringle  -  Pattison  rightly 
remarks,  "  the  possibilities  of  thought  cannot  exceed 
the  actuality  of  being."  And  it  should  be  remem- 
bered that  no  conception  possible  to  the  mind  can 
equal  the  God-idea  in  universality,  wealth,  compass, 
and  ultimateness.  His  attempted  destruction  of  the 
ontological  argument  was  Kant's  main  blow  at 
speculative  theology ,  Hegel's  support  and  defence 
of  it  was  one  of  the  finest  things  he  did — for  which 
I  honour  him  more  than  did  any  member  of  our 
philosophic  group,  in  all  probability.  Right  well 
had  Hegel  understood  that  the  existence  of  those 
non-empirical  ideas  which  are  necessary  to  thought 
proves  that  the  kingdom  of  reason  is  not  of  this 
world.  It  was  something  for  Hegel's  time  to  have 
vindicated  the  depth  and  subtlety  of  Anselm. 

Dr  Pringle-Pattison  has  here  delightfully  emanci- 
pated himself,  with  whatever  consistency,  from  the 
cramped  metaphysics  in  which  we  found  him,  and 
has  gone  far  in  the  way  of  the  self -existent  Being, 
Whom  he  is  over -anxious  to  exclude  from  his 
work,  so  leaving  it  a  torso.  Without  such  absolute 
and  unconditioned  Being,  known  through  rational 
intuition,  no  rational  theory  of  being  is  possible. 
But  I  have  not  meant  to  suggest  that  the  concept 
of  self -existence  is  already  the  concept  of  God,  for 
an  agnostic  might  say  there  may  possibly  be  many 
self-existing  beings.  It  is  only  material  for  the 
working  out  of  the  judgments  of  reason  towards 


58  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

the  infinite  and  necessary  existence  of  God.  In 
this  outworking,  reason  will  severely  track  and 
trace  the  deep  implications  of  being  or  existence 
up  to  this  great  height,  quite  unheeding  of  the 
peremptory  voices  that  would  proscribe  reason, 
and  dwarf  her  results  to  that  only  which  is 
contained  in  a  hard,  positivistic  round  of  thought. 
And  yet  we  have  our  own  solid,  positivistic  basis, 
in  that  we  set  out  from  the  perceived  fact  of  being, 
whence  we  rise  to  being  as  conceived,  or  logically 
discriminated.  I  return  to  add  that  the  '  Proslogion  ' 
of  Anselm  itself  (c.  14)  shows  that  more  of  "  religious 
interest "  and  ethical  value  was  included,  in  connec- 
tion with  the  argument,  than  is  usually  remembered 
or  credited  to  it,  though  it  is  so  intellectually 
coercive  in  its  appeal.  Indeed,  we  shall  not  talk 
of  intellectualism,  if  the  activity  of  the  Absolute 
itself  in  the  thinking  spirit  is  here  remembered, 
as  Baader  insisted.  One  is  almost  tempted  to  say 
that  Anselm  did  in  philosophy,  what  Victor  Hugo 
did  in  poetry,  when  he  brought  to  men  the  shudder 
of  the  infinite. 

"  The  self-conscious  unity  of  subjective  existence  " 
agrees,  in  Fischer's  view,  through  the  self-existent 
Primal  Spirit,  "with  the  infinity  of  knowing  and 
working"  realised  in  the  objective  universe,  where 
the  Idea  is  found  "in  its  absolute  truth  and 
totality."  In  the  attempt  of  Fischer,  to  which  I 
have  referred,  at  an  historical  proof  of  the  truth 


KARL   PHILIPP   FISCHER.  59 

of  theism,  a  German  critic  (Drews)  has  objected 
that  the  trouble  is  that,  though  the  argument 
appears  to  be  worked  out  by  a  real  temporal 
development  of  things,  yet  what,  in  this  critic's 
view,  we  really  come  to  is  the  idea  in  the  subjective 
spirit  of  the  theistic  philosopher  regarded  and 
treated  too  much  as  though  it  were  the  idea  of 
God  Himself.  That  is  to  say,  the  danger  is  of 
the  representation  being  a  too  subjective  one.  I 
do  not  think  the  criticism  should  be  too  readily 
accepted:  there  need  be  no  lack  of  objectiveness 
in  the  historical  treatment  of  the  theistic  idea,  and 
Fischer  is  not  only  a  sober  and  careful  inquirer, 
but  an  able  defender  of  the  objectivity  of  truth. 
But  it  is  not  always  easy  to  find  le  mot  juste  in 
such  matters,  and  it  is  better  to  lean  to  generosity's 
side.  Fischer  is  philosophically  more  sound  than 
his  critic  when,  unlike  the  latter,  he  makes  finite 
existence  "only  the  revelation  or  the  spiritual 
creation,  but  not  the  self-realisation  of  the  Absolute 
Spirit." 

Fischer's  most  notable  work  was  the  very  large 
one,  entitled  '  Outlines  of  the  System  of  Philosophy/ 
4  vols.  (1848-1855),  which,  as  encyclopaedia  of  the 
philosophical  sciences,  rightly  understood,  he  carried 
through  with  independence  and  originality.  Logic, 
and  the  philosophy  of  nature,  are  first  treated; 
then  anthropology,  or,  in  subjective  aspect,  the 
theory  of  spirit;  next  ethics,  speculatively  treated; 


60  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

and  finally,  speculative  theology  or  the  phil- 
osophy of  religion.  Fischer  also  wrote  on  'Meta- 
physics' (1834),  and  on  freedom,  and  the  sensual  - 
istic  philosophy.  He  contributed,  too,  to  Fichte's 
Zeitschrift. 

Fischer  lays  down  what  he  conceives  to  be  the 
principles  of  the  immanent  self-determination  of  the 
Divine  Personality,  though  his  positions  have  not 
been  made,  at  all  points,  clear.  He  does  not,  as  we 
saw  Weisse^  did,  use  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity  for 
his  philosophical  reconstructions,  but  only  speaks  of 
different  principles  or  qualities  or  determinations  of 
the  Absolute  Personality.  That  does  not  keep  him, 
of  course,  from  admitting  three  forms  in  which  we 
recognise  the  Divine  working,  as  Primal  Being. 
Primal  Will,  and  Primal  Spirit.  Through  "these 
three  relations "  the  Absolute  Personality  is,  in  his 
view,  known  "  in  its  inner  principles."  The  Godhead 
is  in  itself  the  absolute  identity  of  its  principles, 
according  to  Fischer.  The  Divine  Personality  is  an 
absolute  Whole,  in  which  God  is  the  universal  unity 
of  each  and  every  particular  principle.  Fischer  does 
not  attain,  however,  to  the  Christian  doctrine  of  the 
Trinity,  with  its  three  independent  persons.  He 
takes  the  divine  Son  as  primary  Will,  or  as  the 
intellectual  love  of  God  to  Himself.  The  Spirit  he 
regards  as  Intelligence  or  the  primary  Spirit.  But 
it  is  merely  as  attributes  that  he  distinguishes  the 
Son  and  the  Spirit.  But  I  do  not  pursue  these 


KARL  PHILIPP  FISCHER.  61 

theological  aspects,  as  it  is  his  work  as  a  theistic 
philosopher  which  now  concerns  us. 

There  is  an  inner  self  -  objectifying  of  God,  a 
grounding  of  His  eternal  nature,  which  funda- 
mentally conditions  His  return  into  Himself.  His 
subjectivity  is  God's  soul  or  heart.  His  "heart  is 
His  eternal  Will,"  whose  unity  with  itself  is  His 
absolute  Love,  through  which  God  distinguishes 
Himself  from  Himself.  In  His  objective  relation  to 
Himself,  God  is,  in  Fischer's  view,  the  absolute 
object  of  His  own  eternal  knowing.  A  drawback  of 
this  whole  representation,  it  must  be  admitted,  is  the 
carrying  over,  in  this  trinal  way,  only  the  concepts 
of  human  personality  to  God,  in  a  kind  of  anthropo- 
morphised  manner.  This  seems  a  legitimate  criticism, 
even  though  one  holds,  with  Rothe,  that  "as  we 
cannot  truly  understand  the  idea  of  man  without 
possessing  the  true  idea  of  God,  so  the  converse  is 
also  true."  Still,  I  think  Fischer's  representation 
has  its  own  place  and  value,  albeit  not  without 
defects  and  difficulties.  Hence  the  Divine  relations, 
with  regard  to  Nature,  are  not  in  all  respects  made 
clear  and  explicit.  His  representation  is  likely  to 
appear  to  many  so  difficult  that  it  may  bear  a  little 
further  phrasing  in  somewhat  different  terms.  The 
self-objectivisation  of  God  means  that  eternal  return 
into  Himself  which,  as  Drews  puts  it, "  is  the  termimis 
ad  quern  of  His  immanent  self-determination."  In 
the  infinite  unity  of  this  eternal  Will,  God  returns. 


62  SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHERS. 

says  Fischer,  from  every  outgoing  of  His  existence, 
into  Himself,  that  unity  "  eternally  to  affirm."  This 
subjective  self-affirmation  of  God  is,  as  Drews  says, 
the  eternal  mediation  of  His  objective  relation  to 
Himself,  in  which,  as  I  have  already  remarked,  He  is 
the  absolute  object  of  His  own  eternal  knowledge. 
The  foregoing  positions  as  to  God's  self-affirmation 
are  found  both  in  his  work  on  'The  Idea  of  the 
Godhead/  and  in  that  with  his  'System  of  Phil- 
osophy,' but  in  forms  which  supplement  each  other, 
and  are  therefore  better  taken  together.  But  in  all 
such  contentions  Fischer  will  have  it  that  God  does 
not  "exist  abstractly,"  and  the  "immanent  presup- 
positions of  His  absolute  truth"  are  not  "abstract 
determinations"  (abstrakte  Bestimmungen). 

It  seems  to  me  a  merit,  on  the  part  of  Fischer — 
and  one  for  which  he  has  not  always  received  credit 
at  the  hands  of  German  thinkers — that,  like  I.  H. 
Fichte  and  Weisse,  he  allows  God  to  have  absolute 
and  eternal  completeness  or  perfectness  in  Himself. 
This,  we  saw,  neither  Hegel  nor  Schelling  attained, 
and  I  may  add  that  Hartmann's  Unconscious  is  mere 
potentiality,  and  so  is  Schopenhauer's  World -Will. 
But  an  unconscious  Deity  could  not  be  free,  in 
respect  of  the  world,  and  could  not  be  distinct  from 
it,  since  he  could  not  know  Himself  to  be  active  in 
it.  Hartmann's  unconscious  Absolute  is  a  complete 
self-contradiction,  since  it  is  all -knowing  and  all- 
wise,  only  does  not  know  itself.  Hoffding  does  not 


KAKL   PHILIPP  FISCHER.  63 

even  desire  such  completeness  for  Deity,  but  appar- 
ently prefers,  in  speaking  of  I.  H.  Fichte,  a  God  who 
is  developing  or  evolving  to  One  whom  he  is  pleased 
to  term  "ready-made."  A  not  very  philosophical 
term  to  apply  to  the  ens  a  se  or  necessary  Being. 
He  does  not  reflect  that  such  an  undeveloped  Deity 
does  not  fulfil  the  conception  of  God  at  all,  at  least 
not  to  theistic  view.  Hoffding  does  not  realise  that 
a  God  of  growth,  effort,  and  unrealised  ideals,  is  a 
God  dragged  down  to  the  regions  of  anthropomor- 
phism, and  that  a  Deity  not  raised  above  these 
limitations  will  never  satisfy  the  rational  nature  of 
man.  God  is  to  Fischer  not  only  a  self-determined 
eternal  principle  in  Himself,  but  is  at  the  same  time 
eternal  Ground  of  the  world,  in  which  relation  He  is 
the  self-conscious  Primal  Subject,  to  all  the  objectivity 
so  grounded  by  and  known  to  Him.  The  world  of 
possibility  is  thus  eternal,  but  this  eternal  grounding 
of  the  world — the  mere  presupposition  of  its  creation 
— is  not  to  be  confused  with  its  successive  and 
temporal  realisation.  So  far  as  the  world  of 
possibility  is  concerned,  Fischer's  emphasis  is  upon 
the  moment  of  "essential"  Will  in  God,  but 
when  it  comes  to  the  creative  or  temporal  realisa- 
tion, it  is  His  "  real "  Will  that  is  concerned.  This 
recalls  the  double  Will  aspect  which  we  noted  in 
Fichte. 

Fischer,  like  Baader  and  Fichte,  postulates  a  pre- 
temporal  and  supra-temporal  eternity  for  God.     But 


64  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

he  also  postulates  a  beginning  of  creation  and  of 
time,  and  thus,  having  already  placed  Deity  in 
Eternity,  he  has  had  ascribed  to  him  the  same 
sort  of  difficulty,  as  had  Baader  and  Fichte,  in  re- 
lating the  Life  of  the  Eternal,  in  which  is  no  before 
and  after,  to  the  concept  of  the  after.  But  I  think 
the  Absolute  as  self -originative,  and  free  to  objec- 
tive activity.  And  the  temporal  cannot,  I  insist,  be 
conceived  save  as  with  the  eternal  as  its  positive 
ground ;  nor  is  eternity  to  be  thought  in  terms  of 
time;  and  it  is  quite  a  mistake  to  treat  the  matter 
so  abstractly,  without  reference  to  the  Divine  mode 
of  existence  (eternity),  which  does  not  contradict  the 
human  mode  of  existence  (time),  else  there  could  be 
no  communion  between  them.  Nor  is  the  idea  of 
an  eternal  Now,  in  which  so  many  philosophers 
think  they  have  the  idea  of  eternal  existence,  any 
more  adequate  than  the  notion  of  past  and  future; 
for  the  Now,  in  a  time  sense,  really  presupposes 
a  not-now,  in  the  past  and  future  sense.  Fischer's 
pre- existent  God — or  God  of  eternity — could  not, 
according  to  the  same  German  critic's  objection,  have 
any  inner  life ;  this,  however,  is,  to  me,  to  conceive 
Eternal  Deity  too  abstractly,  and  to  forget  that  He 
is,  as  such,  eternal  self-realisation,  eternal  self -related 
activity,  not  passivity,  nor  nothingness.  The  world- 
idea,  present  in  God's  eternal  self-consciousness,  can 
certainly  not,  in  my  view,  be  allowed  to  precede 
that  self -consciousness.  That  world-idea  must  have 


KARL   PHILIPP   FISCHER.  65 

included,  I  presume,  possible  time,  succession,  and 
progress.  Fischer  thinks  God  would  not  be  the 
Absolute  Personality  were  the  creation  not  effected 
by  an  act  of  His  free  will.  Fischer  was  right  in 
so  holding  God  to  be  absolutely  free  and  purely 
self-determined  in  His  creative  activity.  It  has  its 
ethical  ground  and  purpose,  in  his  view,  in  God's 
free  love  and  self -revelation.  Fischer  did  well  so  to 
emphasise  the  free  character  of  the  Divine  love  in 
Creation,  and  avoid  the  error  of  those  who  made 
it  a  necessary  step  in  God's  own  self-determination, 
or  a  means  to  His  own  self-conscious  perfection. 
It  is  enough  that  the  unconditioned  Being,  whose 
nature  is  love,  should  know  the  good  of  love -de- 
termined being,  which  is  no  aimless,  accidental  affair. 
It  will  thus  be  seen  that  I.  H.  Fichte,  Weisse,  and 
Fischer,  all  stood  out  against  the  system  of  the  im- 
personal logical  Deity,  and  against  the  extreme  specu- 
lative tendencies  connected  therewith.  One  great 

O 

— perhaps  the  greatest — reason  why  the  personality 
of  God  for  which  they  contended  was  denied,  was 
that,  from  the  crass  way  in  which  personality  and 
individuality  were  conceived — I  mean,  as  connected 
with  earthly  environment  and  sense — men  could  not 
endure  to  have  personality  attributed  to  the  Abso- 
lute Being.  Can  we  doubt  that  this  has  still  to 
do  with  the  like  repugnance — which  in  this  respect 
one  can  well  sympathise  with — of  some  philosophers 
in  our  own  time  ?  But  only  lack  of  speculative 

E 


66  SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHERS. 

imagination  could  keep  one  from  conceiving  Divine 
Personality,  as  pure  personality  in  its  completeness 
and  integrity,  stripped  of  the  accidents  and  limita- 
tions of  personality  in  man.  All  that  we  can  expect 
of  human  personality,  under  material  and  clogging 
conditions,  imposed  by  no  thought  or  choice  or  will 
of  our  own,  is  that  it  should  yield  us  some  power 
to  understand  and  conceive  what  Personality,  in  its 
highest  and  perfect  realisation,  must  mean.  And 
this  it  can  very  well  do,  as  personality  becomes 
developed  in  us.  But  it  argues  some  lack  of  power 
to  discriminate  if  we  fail  to  perceive  that  our  self- 
constituted  personality  has  followed  our  being  con- 
stituted — -  by  nature  and  by  others ;  whereas  the 
Absolute  Personality  is  a  pure  and  sole  self-con- 
stituting, with  nothing  before  it  and  nothing  beyond 
it.  Rightly  conceived,  neither  finite  existences  nor 
anything  else  can  annul  or  derogate  from  the  abso- 
luteness of  His  self-constituting.  It  is  a  complete 
fallacy  to  suppose  that  Personality  in  its  idea  must 
include  finiteness,  must  necessarily  be  anthropo- 
morphic, due  to  the  haunting  error  of  making 
personality  quantitative. 

Though  I  am  not  to  treat  of  Sengler,  yet  his 
position  is  in  this  connection  so  interesting  that  it 
may  be  briefly  referred  to.  Sengler,  we  saw,  was 
influenced  by  Schelling,  whose  last  philosophical 
standpoint  Sengler  sought  to  bring  out  in  his  work 
on  'The  Idea  of  God'  (1845).  But  Sengler,  unlike 


KAKL   PHILIPP   FISCHER.  67 

many  others,  was  critical  of  Baader.  Setting  out, 
like  Fischer,  from  the  concept  of  unity,  he  sought 
to  bring  it  to  a  determination  as  self-conscious 
Primal  Spirit.  Planting  himself  thus  on  the  concept 
of  being,  Sengler  sought  then  to  educe  the  Absolute 
Personality.  There  is  no  lack  of  independence  in 
Sengler's  work,  as  he  sought  to  grasp  the  concept 
of  unity  in  its  full  depth.  He  thought  that  if  the 
personality  of  God  has  not  been  philosophically 
established,  that  is  because  the  being  or  essence  of 
spirit  has  not  been  properly  distinguished,  as  to 
its  chief  difference,  from  nature.  He  held  the  being 
of  personality  to  be  determined  in  and  for  itself. 
God  must  be,  independent,  and  absolutely  free  of 
the  nature-world.  He  consists  through  and  in  Him- 
self and  His  own  essential  determinations.  Other- 
wise, he  would  only  be  Nature-form  or  Nature-spirit 
— its  highest  stuff,  but  not  its  very  principle.  Ideal- 
ised naturalism,  not  true  idealism,  would  be  the 
result.  God  is  mere  impersonal  World-spirit,  in  his 
view,  so  long  as  He  is  mere  Nature  -  spirit.  The 
true  concept  of  God,  Sengler  opines,  is  to  be  found 
in  the  true  concept  of  spirit.  Sengler  reaches  these 
positions  only  through  historico  -  critical  inquiry. 
He  made  much  use  of  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity 
for  his  world-interpretation. 

The  teachings  of  Fischer  I  cannot  now  further 
pursue.  It  only  remains  to  say  of  Fischer's  notable 
achievement  that,  though  he  is  less  known  outside 


68  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Germany  than  Fichte  and  Weisse,  yet  there  is  evi- 
dence enough  that  his  influence  in  Germany  on 
philosophy  and  higher  theology  was  very  consider- 
able, as  a  list  of  influenced  writers  might  easily  be 
given  to  prove.  It  must  suffice  now  to  say  that 
C.  I.  Nitzsch,  I.  A.  Dorner,  C.  Eichhorn,  C.  Schwarz, 
would  be  among  them. 


CHAPTER  IV. 

H.   M.   CHALYBAUS. 

H.  M.  CHALYBAUS  (1796-1862),  who  was  professor 
in  Kiel,  is  another  philosopher  of  this  group.  He 
sought  to  prove  the  Absolute  Personality  in  his 
'  Outlines  of  a  System  of  the  Theory  of  Knowledge  ' 
(1846),  with  which  I  am  mainly  concerned.  He 
was  already  well  known,  especially  by  his  work  on 
'Historical  Development  of  Speculative  Philosophy 
from  Kant  to  Hegel'  (1837).  At  the  close  of  this 
work,  Chalybaus  had  found  Hegel  "assuming  a 
pantheistic  identity  of  man  and  God,  in  which, 
at  least  if  strictly  and  conscientiously  carried  out, 
the  Deity  only  attains  consciousness  by  means  of 
human  agnition — a  solution  which  indeed  perfectly 
accounts  for  absolute  knowledge  in  us,  but  comes 
up  so  much  the  less  to  the  religious  representations, 
and,  let  us  add,  to  the  philosophical  idea  of  the 
Deity."  His  other  works  I  need  not  enumerate, 
unless  perhaps  to  mention  his  'System  of  Specu- 
lative Ethics '  (1850),  in  which  he  emphasises  man's 


70  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

freedom  of  choice  as  dependent  on  the  Divine  law, 
and  his  'Philosophy  and  Christianity'  (1853),  in 
which  Chalybaus  maintains  that  the  Spirit  is  proved 
through  the  Word,  the  Word  through  the  Spirit, 
but  the  sacred  history  is  an  "  incredible  narration  " 
without  the  Idea  —  the  new  idea  of  God  which 
Christianity  brings. 

Philosophy  was  to  him  essentially  theory  of 
knowledge  (Wissenschaftslehre),  as  it  had  been  to 
the  elder  Fichte.  Philosophy  had  its  starting-point 
in  self -consciousness,  whereas  speculative  theology 
had,  in  his  view,  God-consciousness  for  its  point 
of  departure  (so  his  'Fundamental  Philosophy,' 
1861).  My  remarks  on  this  position  in  chap.  ii. 
must  suffice.  Chalybaus  thought  philosophy  must 
win  anew  experience  as  self -active  (in  his  '  Wissen- 
schaftslehre').  In  his  view  also,  the  formal  and 
the  material  principles  in  philosophy  reciprocally 
condition  each  other;  and  the  practical  reason  he 
ranked  as  prior  to  the  theoretic.  His  conception 
of  philosophy  laid  stress  on  striving  after  truth 
or  wisdom,  and  not  mere  theoretic  knowledge.  His 
attitude,  like  that  of  Tennyson's  "  Ulysses,"  was — 
"  To  strive,  to  seek,  to  find,  and  not  to  yield."  But 
truth  for  him  dwelt,  one  may  say,  "  in  interiore 
homine,"  not  in  the  intellect  alone.  And  so  he 
expressly  says  that  so  long  as  man  strives,  he 
believes,  and  so  long  as  he  believes,  he  strives.  He 
distinguished  his  own  position  in  this  respect  from 


HEINRICH  MORITZ  CHALYBAUS.  71 

that  of  Hegel,  who,  he  thought,  had  robbed  phil- 
osophy of  teleological  or  ethical  character.     Human 
thought  was  to  Chalybaus  an  after-thinking  of  the 
Absolute  Thought.     His  thought  is  here  somewhat 
near   of    kin  to   what   we    noted    in   Fichte.     The 
Absolute  can  only  will  absolute  truth.     The  Absolute 
is   the  all-embracing  one— the    All-One   which,   in 
thinking  and  willing  the  All,  can  at  the  same  time 
only  think  and  will  itself.     It  comprehends  itself 
as  the  absolute  Truth,  and  at  the  same  time  as  the 
absolute    principle.      Because    it    knows    itself,    it 
comprehends  itself  as  a  self-conscious   spirit.     The 
Absolute,  as  self-conscious,  knows  all  being  as  its 
being,  but  it  is  an  abstract  Absolute,  in  whose  being 
all  other  being  is  contained.     As  will  of  truth,  the 
Absolute  seeks  after  real  truth  objective  to  itself, 
hence  the  existence  of  the  real  world,  to  which  it 
is  First  Subject.     To  him,  therefore,  the  world  was 
not  an  emanation   from   God,   not  produced   from 
Him,  but  created  by  the  objective  exertion  of  His 
power  as  just  indicated.     His  position  recalls  that  of 
Glinther,  to  whom  the  world  was  posited  by  the 
Absolute,   as   something    essentially    different  from 
Him,  and  not  necessary  to  His  existence.     But,  for 
Chalybaus,    God   knows   Himself  as    sole    or    only 
God  after  creation,  just  as  before  it.     But  He  then 
knows  Himself  as  a  God  Who  is  no  longer  alone. 
Two   moments   are   to    be    distinguished   in   the 

t     Absolute,  by  means  of  which  the  process  of  raising 


72  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

the  abstract  unity  is  mediated.  This  belongs  to 
his  important  discussion  of  the  "principles"  of 
Ontology.  The  first  is,  the  substantial  or  soulish 
moment,  which  is  the  real  foundation  of  the 
Absolute,  and  of  the  objective  truth  to  be  created. 
It  is  undetermined  materia  prima,  an  eternal 
aether  or  matter,  but  is  as  yet  only  the  negative 
condition  or  real  possibility  of  the  world,  not  the 
productive  principle  of  its  creation.  Chalybaus 
says  one  cannot  suppose  "an  eternal  and  self- 
dependent  matter ;  that  would  be  the  principle  of 
materialism  and  deism — an  independence  of  God  on 
the  world's  part."  But  he  thinks  we  should  also 
hesitate  "to  constitute  God  mere  thought,  because 
that  would  lead  to  idealistic  pantheism — Acosmism." 
He  thinks  "  there  exists  externally  a  materia 
prima"  but  prefers  to  view  it  as  "the  element  in 
absolute  Being  itself  co-existent "  with  thought  or 
the  ideal.  But  it  is  real,  not,  however,  "  as  matter 
beside  God,  or  in  determinate  form,"  that  is,  not 
"  as  a  corporeal  world,"  but  also  "  not  simply  as 
matter  thought."  Rather,  as  "the  substantially 
psychical,  as  the  basis  of  the  Divine  Will."  These 
can  hardly  be  called  easy  conceptions,  and 
Chalybaus  has  perhaps  left  something  to  be  desired 
in  the  way  of  clearness.  For  what  do  we  really 
know  of  a  soul  -  aether,  with  space,  time,  and 
number,  as  its  forms,  all  on  an  infinite  scale  ? 
His  materia  prima  is,  all  things  considered,  a 


HEINRICH  MORITZ  CHALYBAUS.  73 

rather  too  wonderful  presupposition,  in  my  judg- 
ment. It  contains  the  possibility  of  all  sub- 
stantiality, causality,  corporeality,  and  soul,  which 
are  all  comprehended  within  the  range  of 
ontological  category.  We  know  what  difficulties 
have  attended  scientific  theories  of  an  aether  in 
the  explanation  of  phenomena,  but  this  philosophical 
theory  of  a  soul -aether,  so  wondrously  dowered, 
does  not  seem  to  me  one  easy  of  acceptance.  It 
only  falls  short  of  the  "  aether  "  of  Euripides,  which 
was  "father  of  men  and  gods."  In  this  way; 
however,  Chalybaus  eschews  materialism,  matter 
being  the  thing  determined;  he  also  avoids  the 
futility  of  a  mere  thought  idealism.  His  materia 
prima  seems  meant  to  express  the  realistic  side  of 
creation,  an  endeavour  still  marked  by  strange 
gropings  of  thought  to-day.  But  if  we  are  to 
talk  of  a  natura  in  God,  we  should  need  to  bring 
out  more  clearly,  I  think,  than  does  Chalybaus 
that  His  will  harmoniously  moves  and  directs,  if 
one  may  so  speak,  His  natura,  so  that  passivity 
shall  nowise  be  ascribed  to  it.  Chalybaus  has, 
however,  avoided  any  idea  of  matter  as  drawn 
from  any  natura  pertaining  to  God's  essence.  But 
the  talk  of  some  thinkers  of  that  time  about  a 
nature  in  God  which  became  the  basis  of  the  matter 
of  the  universe  —  something  not  God  which  was 
posited  in  God — was  an  influence  derived  from 
Schelling.  When  intelligible,  it  was  apt  to  run 


74  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

into  a  pantheistic  form  or  tendency,  but  it  often 
remained  a  mere  form  of  speech,  and  ultimately 
unmeaning. 

The  positive  or  ideal  moment  is  found  rather  in 
the  second  moment,  of  which  I  now  come  to  speak, 
namely,  the  Divine  thought,  which  seizes  upon  the 
world  -  thought  or  possibility,  and  supplies  the 
necessary  impulse  to  the  process  of  creation,  though 
not  of  itself  capable  of  effecting  the  reality  of  the 
world.  It  makes,  however,  for  the  concrete  unity 
of  the  two  moments,  soul  and  thought.  The 
purpose  of  the  creative  process  is  the  being  of 
objective  truth;  the  process  is  an  act  of  positive 
love,  which  produces  the  objective  truth  of  the 
creaturely  subjects.  This  means  a  plurality  of 
thinking  monads.  This  is  a  concession  to 
Herbartian  realism,  which  Chalybaus  considers  in 
eingehend  manner,  but  less  frequently  opposes 
than  the  idealism  of  Hegel,  to  which  he  ascribed 
articular  disease,  in  a  quaint  expression. 

Regarding  the  already  mentioned  view  of 
Chalybaus,  that  God  knew  Himself  to  be  the 
only  God,  before  the  world's  creation,  some  German 
and  other  thinkers  have  regarded  such  a  view  as 
untenable,  on  the  ground  that  there  was  no 
existent  being  whereby  the  Divine  self -con- 
sciousness could  be  enkindled.  No  better  reason 
has  been  adduced  for  this  than  the  anthropomorphic 
assumption  that  the  world  must  have  existed, 


HEINRICH  MORITZ  CHALYBAUS.  75 

and  that  eternally,  for  this  purpose.  But  that  is 
not  to  show  any  valid  reason  why  God  must  first 
think  something  different  from  Himself.  No 
philosopher,  of  the  galaxy  belonging  to  the  time  of 
our  group,  more  emphatically  rejected  the  op- 
position of  subject  and  object  in  the  Deity  than 
Steudel,  who  says  that  God  is  subject  and  object  in 
one,  as  the  Fulness  of  the  All.  He  holds  that  in 
God  is  no  such  duality  or  difference,  as  is  found  in 
the  human  subject.  I  am  not  concerned,  however, 
to  express  agreement  with  the  way  in  which 
Steudel  further  develops  his  position  in  these 
matters.  The  contention  that  there  cannot  be 
personality  without  a  contra  -  posited  world  or 
object  Lotze  has  overthrown  even  for  the  human 
subject,  in  which  the  non-ego  does  not  constitute 
the  ego,  but  only  calls  out  its  powers;  but  it  is 
infinitely  more  untenable  in  the  case  of  the  sole 
self-existing  Being  of  theism.  God  is  not  to  be 
thought  as  so  thirled  to  the  world. 

Chalybaus  rightly  perceived  that  if  the  Divine 
self  -  consciousness  first  rose  in  this  way,  namely, 
through  the  thought  and  real  being  of  the  world,  the 
issue  would  be  pantheism.  And  this  leads  me  to  say 
that  the  objective  existence  of  the  universe  is  where 
pantheistic  thought  fails.  Pantheism  is  the  neces- 
sary and  eternal  consubstantiality  of  God  and 
Nature.  Pantheism  cannot  posit  a  universe  con- 
sciously other  than  itself.  Such  a  universe,  non- 


76  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

objective  to  the  Unconditioned  Being,  remains  an 
ego.  Chalybaus  was  also  right  in  pointing  out  the 
difference  of  the  absolute  self  -  consciousness  from 
the  becoming  human  consciousness,  that  in  God 
there  was  a  knowledge  of  the  not-being  of  the  real 
world  (that  is,  pre-ereationally),  while  in  man  what 
goes  before  is  a  not-knowing  of  its  being.  But  he 
enters  ground  where  I  am  not  prepared  to  follow 
him,  when  he  makes,  not  being,  but  the  knowledge 
of  the  not-being  of  the  world — its  possibility  through 
eternal  matter — the  reason  of  its  creation,  by  en- 
kindling the  Divine  creative  will :  this  is  absurd 
as  making  creation  rest  on  a  mere  abstraction. 
Creation  must  be  positively  motived  —  by  free, 
ethical  love,  which  is  not  to  say  that  it  can 
be  motived  by  any  desire  of  addition  to  His  own 
nature  or  good  by  the  Infinite  Being.  Lotze  and 
others  have  spoken  of  God  becoming  enriched  by 
our  love  to  Him  in  ways  that  suggest  the  need 
for  care  that  we  do  not  attribute  susceptibilities 
to  God  that  might  appear  to  impair  or  destroy 
His  absoluteness.  God's  nature  as  Love  does  not 
depend  on  objective  creation  for  development:  His 
nature  is  directly  self-determined.  That,  of  course, 
is  not  to  say  that  God's  relation  to  the  finite  being  is 
no- wise  conditioned,  but  without  self-detriment,  by 
the  creaturely  attitude  towards  Him. 

Nor,  again,  should  I  follow  Chalybaus  if  he  really 
thought  that  it  was  from  the  knowledge  of  the  not- 


HEINRICH   MORITZ  CHALYBAUS.  77 

being  of  the  world  that  the  Divine  self -consciousness 
originated,  since  it  would  be  absurd  to  derive  the 
Divine  self -consciousness  from  any  such  negative 
consideration.  But  Chalybaus  did  not  seem,  as  we 
saw,  to  hold  that  in  creation  God  became  conscious 
of  Himself,  and  he  should  have  found  less  ground, 
I  think,  to  hold  it  because  of  its  not -being.  He 
seems  to  me,  however,  in  these  abstract  reasonings 
to  have  lost  sight  too  much  of  the  identity  of 
thought  and  being  in  God.  He  in  these  positions 
leads  me  again  to  recall  Giinther,  who  distinguished 
clearly  the  absolute  self  -  consciousness  from  the 
human  self  -  consciousness,  and  made  the  absolute 
self -consciousness  an  immediate  intuition  of  its 
own  essence,  without  need  of  any  external  medi- 
ation. Such  outer  mediation  cannot  obtain,  he 
holds,  in  the  case  of  One  Who  is  the  All  in  All. 
But  Giinther  I  cannot  pursue  at  length  now. 

One  feature  in  the  thought  of  Chalybaus  which 
deserves  attention,  since  it  has  place  both  in  his 
'  Theory  of  Knowledge '  and  in  his  '  Ethics,'  is,  that 
he  thinks  an  existential  proof  for  the  existence  of 
God  is  yielded  through  reflection  on  the  genesis 
of  the  immediate  God  -  consciousness :  this  proof, 
through  an  immediate  self -seizure  or  self -appre- 
hension of  the  fact  in  consciousness,  ties  it  up  to 
existence.  The  theory  is  not  without  its  suggestive 
side,  but  I  do  not  dwell  upon  it  now.  I  rather  note 
the  stress  of  Chalybaus  on  ethical  personality 


78  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

and  ethical  categories,  in  his  desire  to  found  an 
ethical  theism.  There  is  also  to  be  noted  the  fact 
that  he  was  a  contributor  to  Fichte's  '  Zeitschrif t,' 
which  occupied  such  an  important  place  during 
that  time — and  indeed  ever  since. 

I  have  been  occupied  mainly  with  the  teaching 
of  Chalybaus,  as  a  theistic  philosopher,  on  God : 
one  important  point  relative  to  man,  in  the  course 
of  his  discussion,  may  be  noticed.  He  says  those 
who  make  the  supposition  of  different  human  species, 
instead  of  races  with  like  rational  destination,  are 
seeking  "a  transformation  of  men  into  a  physical 
order."  Whereas,  as  he  elsewhere  remarks,  "man 
is  himself  a  self,  and  hence  he  seeks  after  certitude 
of  himself,  which  again  he  cannot  attain  without 
certitude  of  the  Deity." 

If  we  take  the  subjects  here  so  briefly  outlined, 
in  conjunction  with  the  other  philosophical  work 
of  Chalybaus,  we  shall  find  no  need  in  this  instance 
to  differ  from  the  judgment  of  Erdmann,  who 
declared  the  discussions  of  Chalybaus  to  be  "pro- 
found and  searching"  in  respect  of  religio-ethical 
questions,  but  will  extend  its  reference  to  his 
treatment  of  metaphysical  and  epistemological  pro- 
blems as  well.  His  influence  as  an  historian  of 
philosophy  was,  however,  wider  than  that  which 
he  exerted  as  an  independent  philosopher,  which  is 
not  to  say  that  this  latter  was  by  any  means  incon- 
siderable. 


79 


CHAPTER  V. 

F.   HOFFMANN. 

F.  HOFFMANN,  who  was  professor  in  Wiirzburg  when 
he  died  in  1881,  is  a  member  of  our  philosophic 
group,  albeit  less  known  out  of  Germany  than 
most  of  the  others.  Of  the  potent  influence  of 
Hoffmann  on  German  philosophical  literature,  how- 
ever, there  can  be  no  doubt  to  any  one  whose 
knowledge  reaches  below  the  surface.  Hoffmann 
was  the  most  distinguished  adherent  of  Baader, 
whose  valuable  work  and  thought  he  presented  with 
great  skill  and  care.  Hoffmann  has  sought  to  give 
Baader's  thought  a  more  scientific  form,  to  free  it 
of  phantasy,  and  of  anything  it  might  have  suffered, 
philosophically,  from  Baader's  aphoristic  style  of 
writing,  and  the  disconnectedness  of  its  form. 

Hoffmann's  reading,  especially  in  historical  direc- 
tions, was  so  wide  that  Erdmann  says  it  may 
"almost  be  called  fabulous."  Baader's  thought 
upon  God  was  serviceably  issued  by  Hoffmann 
under  the  title,  'Speculative  Development  of  the 


80  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Eternal  Self  -  Generation  of  God'  (1835).  A  more 
ordered  and  comprehensive  presentation  of  the  same 
theme  was  Hoffmann's  '  Vestibule  to  the  Speculative 
Theology  of  Franz  Baader '  (1836),  though  the  work 
is  not  entirely  confined  to  pure  Baaderian  positions. 
"The  eternal  Self -Generation  of  God,"  as  Hoffmann 
calls  it,  was,  in  Baader's  view,  the  life  of  the 
Absolute  as  something  to  be  strictly  distinguished 
from  the  act  of  Creation,  and  from  the  life  and 
existence  of  the  created  world  itself. 

I  have  noted,  earlier,  how  this  Baader-Hoffmann 
conception  of  an  eternal  Self -Generation  of  the 
Deity  was  taken  up  and  fully  endorsed  by  I.  H. 
Fichte.  It  is  the  insistence  of  Baader,  however, 
that,  in  view  of  this  self -generative  process  of  Deity, 
the  world  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  inner  life  of 
God,  which  is  in  no  way  dependent  upon  the  world 
for  its  own  self-realisation.  The  self -generative 
conception,  however,  is  one  which  runs  back  to 
Bohme,  who  describes  the  process  whereby  the 
Deity,  from  the  dark  ground  of  Being  within  Him, 
reaches  out,  by  means  of  will  or  Drang,  to  attain 
self -revelation  in  the  Divine  wisdom.  Yet  "the 
essence  of  the  deepest  Deity"  is  "without  and 
beyond  Nature."  Bohme  leaves  us,  however,  with 
more  of  will-struggle  than  of  intellectual  clearness 
and  consistency.  Baader,  in  criticising  the  current 
philosophical  tendencies  of  his  time  in  his  work, 
'  Fermenta  Cognitionis  '  (1822  -  24),  recommended 


FRANZ  HOFFMANN.  81 

the  study  of  Bohme.  Baader  says  expressly  that 
while  God  generates  Himself,  He  knows  Him- 
self, and,  knowing  Himself,  He  generates  Himself. 
Though  the  Ideal  world-creation,  through  love's  free 
act,  is  something  which  thus  cannot  be  deduced,  yet 
Baader  views  the  theogonic  process  in  the  light  of 
a  necessary  event,  in  which  God  returns  to  unity. 
There  is  here  a  double  strain  in  Baader's  thought, 
amounting  to  an  esoteric  (ideal  or  immanent  or 
logical)  and  an  exoteric  (real  or  emanant  or  essen- 
tial) view  of  Divine  process. 

Hoffmann,  in  the  *  Vorhalle '  work,  says  of  God,  as 
the  absolute  Spirit,  that  "  the  Spirit "  is  in  the 
Divine  "tri -personality"  the  means  or  medium  of 
"His  esoteric  and  exoteric  Being."  "For  what 
is  there  merely  internal  is  in  Him  at  the  same  time 
internal  and  external :  "  the  "one -being  of  the  inner 
and  the  outer"  is  the  living  means  or  medium. 
The  tri-personal  spirit  is  taken  to  be  comprehended 
"  in  the  constant  movement  or  shifting  of  the  inner 
in  the  outer,  and  of  the  outer  in  the  inner,"  so  that 
it  is  to  be  viewed  as  "identical  in  both."  One 
recalls  in  this  connection  Hegel's  nature -view,  in 
which  the  outer  is  only  a  determinate  mode  of  being 
of  the  inner,  the  Kantian  dualism  of  outer  and  inner 
being  thereby  transcended.  All  the  moments  alike 
in  the  esoteric  and  the  exoteric  process,  pass,  in  the 
spiritual  process,  "  out  of  their  abstractness "  into 
"concreteness,"  "truth,  and  livingness."  To  Baader, 

F 


82  SEVEN   THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHERS. 

as  Hoffmann  represents  him,  the  being  of  the  world 
is  different  from  that  of  God,  and  has  therefore 
of  necessity  a  beginning.  "  As  eternal  as  God  is,  so 
eternal  is  the  possibility,  the  thought,  the  idea,  the 
archetype,  of  the  world  in  the  spirit  of  God,  but 
this  eternally  possible  is  not  at  the  same  time 
eternally  realised."  When,  however,  God  seeks  to 
create,  the  two  principles  of  Nature — or  rather  will 
— and  intelligence  co-operate  to  this  end,  the  former 
as  the  material,  and  the  latter  as  the  formal 
principle.  This  idea  Baader  took  over  from  Bohme, 
who  had  made  God  at  once  the  rational  ground 
(Urgrund)  and  the  efficient  cause  (Ursache)  of  the 
world,  and  regarded  the  world,  with  entire  dis- 
regard of  the  pantheistic  issue,  as  only  "  the  essen- 
tial nature  of  God  Himself  made  creatural."  But 
the  idea  of  the  two  principles  is  one  which,  as  is 
well  known,  is  present  in  Leibniz,  Schelling,  and 
Hartmann,  and  it  is  hoped  to  reach  by  it  a  realistic 
side  in  idealism.  It  is  obvious  that  Baader  greatly 
excels  Schopenhauer  in  this  matter,  in  his  clear 
insight  into  the  necessity  of  thought  or  intelligence 
to  will  or  power,  while  urging  the  creative  power 
and  necessity  of  will. 

Our  concern  with  Hoffmann  here,  however,  is  not 
mainly  with  the  way  in  which  Hoffmann  set  out  the 
Neo  -  Schellingian  positions  of  Baader,  as  it  is 
sometimes  put,  although  in  Baader  elements  that 
had  been  conjoined  in  Schelling  really  appear 


FRANZ   HOFFMANN.  83 

divided.     Our  concern  rather  is  with  the  fact  that 
Hoffmann   was  associated  as  one  of  the  group  of 
theistic  philosophers  now  occupying  our  attention, 
and  furthered  the  cause   in   the   '  Zeitschrif t,'  and 
other  important  ways.      Hoffmann's  own  position 
is    well    brought   out,   among   other   ways,   in   the 
Vorrede  to  Baader's  minor  writings  (1850),  where 
the    untenableness    of    Schelling's    personality-pan- 
theism—  in   which  God   is  a  personal  Being,  and 
the   universe   is  at  the   same    time    His    actuality 
or  realisation  —  is  shown.     "If  God  is  personality, 
the  world  cannot  be   His  actuality  or   realisation, 
because,   whilst    a    person    may   work    and    bring 
works  into  existence  ad  extra,  he  cannot  have  his 
own  actuality  outside  Himself;     and  if  the  world 
is  the  actuality  of  God,  God  cannot  be  personality, 
because   a   personal    being    cannot    be    constituted 
by    an    infinitude    of    transient    unconscious    and 
conscious   existences."      Another    significant    state- 
ment  of   Hoffmann's   position   is   that   given   in   a 
footnote  near  the  beginning  of  the  second  volume 
of   Baader's  works :  —  "  Nothing  has  given  to  pan- 
theism   a    greater    appearance    of    reasonableness, 
and  consequently  of  truth,  than  the  idea  that  every 
theistic    theory     proceeds     necessarily     upon     the 
supposition  of   a   certain   contingency   of    creation, 
and  that  the  affirmation — Creation  is  a  free  act  of 
God,    is    identical    with    the    affirmation — it    is   a 
contingent  or  accidental  act  of  God.     But  whoever 


84  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

attributes  contingency  to  God  subjects  Him,  only 
in  a  manner  exactly  the  opposite  of  the  pantheistic, 
to  blind  fate." 

Hoffmann,  I  may  observe,  doughtily  contested 
Kant's  view  of  the  character  of  formal,  a  priori 
knowledge.  Hoffmann  maintained  that  if  there 
is  such  a  thing  as  a  priori  knowledge,  it  cannot  be 
merely  formal,  but  must  necessarily  have  deter- 
minate content,  and  therefore  be  knowledge  with  a 
content.  If  mind  had  not  a  content  of  its  own,  it 
never  could,  he  says,  comprehend  a  content  outside 
itself.  I  do  not  dwell  now  on  this,  but  remark 
that  his  opposition  to  Kant  here  was  due  to  the 
fact  that  he  would  oppose  empiricism,  sensualism, 
and  materialism.  As  a  critic  of  materialism, 
Hoffmann  said  that  it  hazards  the  most  senseless 
theories  of  all  kinds;  such  as  time  without 
beginning  or  end,  endless  space,  an  absolutely 
infinite  number  of  atoms,  as  if  these  base  infinities 
were  not  self  -  contradictory.  And  he  maintained 
that  it  would  be  hard  to  find,  in  any  theory  of 
Creation,  such  a  mass  of  contradictions  as  were  to 
be  found  in  the  theory  of  materialism. 

Baader,  in  view  of  his  influence,  not  merely  on 
Hoffmann  and  certain  other  members  of  our 
philosophic  group,  but  on  many  thinkers  outside  it, 
may  well  bear  some  further  remark.  Baader,  too, 
opposed  materialism,  as  might  be  expected  from 
one  whom  E.  A.  von  Schaden  called  "philosophus 


FRANZ   HOFFMANN.  85 

christianus."  He,  too,  opposed  a  priori  knowledge 
as  a  mere  formal  and  subjective  principle.  Baader 
found  in  self  -  consciousness  the  essence  of  spirit, 
not  a  mere  property  of  it.  Our  self -consciousness 
is  to  Baader  a  consciousness  of  being  known  by 
God.  For  our  being — and  indeed  all  being — is  a 
being  known  by  God.  He  further  asserted  of 
Kant's  doctrine  that  we  can  know  nothing  of  that 
which  lies  beyond  the  world  of  sense,  that  the 
reason  of  its  being  so  well  received  as  it  was,  lay 
mainly  in  the  fact  of  that  constitutional  God- 
blindness,  on  the  part  of  man,  which  Kant  himself 
proclaimed.  Of  the  understanding  which  is  averted 
from  the  divine,  Baader  says  that,  "  separated  from 
Unity,  it  loses  the  very  power  to  unite  and  truly  to 
understand;  and  instead  of  simply  distinguishing 
in  order  to  unify,  and  unifying  in  order  to  dis- 
tinguish, all  it  can  do  is  in  separating  to  confound, 
and  in  confounding  to  separate."  And,  in  the  view 
of  Baader,  it  is  really  God  Himself  Who  enables  us 
to  know  God,  since  God  is  Reason,  and  enables  us 
to  participate  in  the  Divine  act  of  reason.  That  is 
to  say,  Baader  made  God  the  subject  of  knowledge, 
and  not  merely  its  object.  God  is  to  him  at  once 
subject  and  object.  But  he  opposes  pantheistic 
identification  of  Divine  and  human  thought. 

It  is,  to  Baader,  a  deep-seated  error  of  rational 
philosophy  to  think  that  we  can  know  God,  or  even 
rightly  about  Him,  apart  from  or  without  God, 


86  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

that  is,  by  or  from  human  reason  alone.  Baader's 
is  a  profoundly  religious  nature;  he  holds  that 
all  thought  must  begin  with  God.  All  problems 
are,  in  his  view,  related  to  God,  as  the  last  ground 
of  all  thought  and  being.  Consequently,  true  phil- 
osophy must  be  religious  philosophy.  And  in  our 
knowledge  of  God,  he  contends,  God  is  at  once 
knower  and  known.  But  our  cognition  is  not  com- 
plete, and  takes  threefold  form.  If  God  merely 
pervades  the  creature  —  dwells  through  him  is 
Baader's  conception — there  is  not  enough  of  the 
free  co-operative  working  of  the  knower.  If  God 
dwells  with  him,  a  better  state  of  things  is  reached. 
But  knowledge  is  only  free  and  perfect  when  God 
dwells  in  the  man,  so  that  the  Divine  reason  speaks 
in  him  as  his  own.  There  is  to  be  no  abstract 
dividing  between  faith  and  knowledge,  between 
knowledge  and  love,  or  between  thought  and  voli- 
tion. Religion,  in  Baader's  view,  belongs  to  man 
as  man,  and  carries  with  it  a  certain  original  cer- 
titude of  Deity  springing  from  the  natural  and 
necessary  rapports  between  the  Creator  and  the 
creature. 

In  his  endeavours  to  reconcile  theism  and  monism, 
Baader  did  a  great  deal  to  prepare  the  way  for  the 
panentheism  of  Krause,  with  whom  he  is  in  many 
ways  contrastive,  and  whom  he  may  be  said  to  excel 
in  profundity,  though  not  in  methodic  and  system- 
atic excellence.  Baader's  treatment  of  philosophy 


FRANZ   HOFFMANN.  87 

is  a  broad  one,  embracing  all  that  concerns  God — 
logic  or  theory  of  knowledge  and  theology :  all 
that  concerns  Nature — cosmology  and  physics:  all 
that  concerns  Man — ethics  and  sociology.  It  will 
be  already  evident  how  theocratic  his  whole  phil- 
osophy was.  But,  like  Kant,  he  holds  man  to  be 
practically  autonomous.  He  views  him,  however^ 
as  working  only  under  the  exercise  of  reason  in 
matters  theoretic.  Man,  as  the  real  image  of  God, 
can  acquire  a  wider  knowledge  of  Him.  Baader 
thinks  man  is  in  space  and  time,  as  a  result  of 
the  Fall,  which  has  a  very  important  place  in  his 
system.  He  holds  moral  and  physical  evil  to  be 
indissolubly  united,  and  thinks  it  absurd  to  trace 
the  world's  evil  and  misery  to  physical  causes.  The 
true  time  is  eternity,  which  man  must  seek.  Matter 
is  not  the  ground  of  evil,  but  rather  its  consequence. 
Matter,  like  time,  will  cease. 

Baader's  system  really  attempted  a  religio-phil- 
osophical  synthesis  of  Neo-Platonism,  Scholastic 
philosophy,  post-Mediaeval  Mysticism,  and  German 
transcendentalism,  largely  under  the  influence  of 
Schelling,  whom  he,  in  his  turn,  greatly  influenced. 
But  this  statement  of  a  reciprocal  relation  between 
them,  though  it  is  usually  all  we  get,  does  not  meet 
the  case,  and  a  more  exact  determination  is  required, 
since  we  are  sometimes  left  with  the  impression 
that  Baader  owed  a  great  deal  more  to  Schelling 
than  was  the  case.  We  owe  it  to  Hoffmann  more 


88  SEVEN   THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

than  any  other,  that  we  know  Baader  to  be  far 
less  indebted  to  Schelling  than  Schelling  was  to 
Baader.  Baader,  who  was  ten  years  older  than 
Schelling,  had  his  own  main  positions  well  in  hand, 
there  is  good  reason  to  believe,  while  Schelling  was 
still  fast  bound  in  pantheism,  with  its  dead  and 
abstract  God  -  concepts,  whence  he  was  extricated  by 
the  bright  persuasive  powers  of  Baader.  Baader 
had  no  inconsiderable  influence  on  Schelling's  philos- 
ophy of  nature,  and  a  greatly  determining  influence 
on  the  upbuilding  of  Schelling's  theosophic  teachings. 
Baader,  admittedly  a  profound  speculative  thinker, 
was  fortunate  not  only  in  having  so  able  an  ex- 
ponent as  Hoffmann,  but  in  the  excellent  represen- 
tations of  Anton  Lutterbeck  and  Jul.  Hamberger, 
who,  like  Hoffmann,  were  at  the  same  time  both 
capable  thinkers  on  their  own  account.  A  feature 
common  to  Baader  and  Hamberger  is  the  concep- 
tion of  Nature  in  God  as  an  opposition,  and  even 
contradiction,  to  be  overcome,  to  the  Divine  glory. 
Hamberger,  in  a  work  entitled  '  Physica  Sacra ' 
(1869),  deals  with  the  eternal  and  celestial  cor- 
poreality. In  it  he  speaks  of  Nature  as  not  only 
an  opposition,  but  much  more  a  contradiction,  to 
spirit,  both  of  these  being  powerful  forms  or 
energies,  capable  of  the  sharpest  outward  contrast. 
I  may  remark  that  this  idea  of  opposition  or  war- 
fare in  things  is  as  old  as  Heraclitus,  as  the  dis- 
cussions of  Bywater,  Burnet,  and  Adam,  have  finely 


FRANZ  HOFFMANN.  89 

shown.  But  if  we  speak  of  Nature  in  God,  I  think 
we  must  remember  that  there  can  be  no  real  or 
enduring  opposition  in  God's  harmonious  unity; 
that  matter  is  no  part  of  the  Divine  natura;  that 
spirit  is  the  prius  of  every  natura,  and  that  God, 
as  personal  Spirit,  is  the  power  above  Nature. 
Because  these  things  are  so,  there  is  meaning,  I 
think,  in  the  words  of  an  Eastern  poet  who  says 
that  "all  that  is  not  One  must  ever  suffer  with 
the  wound  of  absence." 


90 


CHAPTER    VI. 

H.   ULRICI. 

H.  ULRICI  (1806-1884),  professor  in  Halle,  is  the 
next  member  of  this  philosophic  group  to  claim 
our  attention.  In  his  contentions  for  the  truth  of 
Theism,  he  had  the  materialism  of  the  time,  no  less 
than  its  pantheism,  in  his  view.  This  did  not  keep 
him  from  severely  criticising  alike  the  principle  and 
the  method  of  the  Hegelian  system.  He  thought 
it  was  not  to  be  blamed  for  its  pantheism,  if  only 
that  pantheism  could  be  shown  accordant  with 
reason.  He  is  like  Chalybaus  in  viewing  that 
system  of  idealism  as  one-sided,  but  is  without  those 
leanings  to  Herbartian  realism  which  we  saw  to 
be  characteristic  of  Chalybaus.  Ulrici  aims  at  an 
idealism  founded  on  a  realistic  basis  of  his  own, 
based,  in  his  later  works,  on  empiric  science.  To 
philosophise  is,  in  his  view,  to  seek  principles. 

Ulrici  was  a  more   independent  thinker  than   is 
always  realised;  like  Fechner  and  Lotze,  he   bore 


HERMANN  ULRICI.  91 

his  part  in  leading  his  age  to  see  that  the  results, 
newly  won  and  increasing,  of  science,  were  as  capable 
of  interpretation  in  the  sense  of  a  theistic  idealism, 
as  in  that  of  an  atheistic  materialism.  Among  the 
works,  of  which  Ulrici  was  the  author,  were  his 
discussions  'On  the  Principle  and  Method  of  the 
Hegelian  Philosophy'  (1841),  in  which,  I  may 
remark,  he  complains  of  the  way  Hegel  subsumes 
Art  under  Religion,  so  that  every  determinate 
difference  between  them  is  done  away,  and  there  is 
posited  instead  a  vague  flowing  into  each  other. 
Also,  his  'System  of  Logic'  (1852),  in  which  he 
stood  for  the  derivation  of  the  categories.  He 
held  that  thought  is  activity;  that  all  thought 
consists  in  differentiation;  and  that  thought  dis- 
tinguishes itself  in  itself,  and  becomes  consciousness 
and  self  -  consciousness.  His  somewhat  neglected 
work  on  'Faith  and  Knowledge'  (1858)  aimed  to 
harmonise  the  interests  of  philosophy,  religion,  and 
science.  He  says : — "  Always  in  science,  knowledge 
and  belief,  far  from  a  severe  separation,  are  in  the 
closest  connection  even  in  the  exactest  sciences;  a 
great  part  of  our  scientific  knowledge  really  belongs 
not  to  knowledge,  but  to  the  sphere  of  belief." 
Much  as  we  should  take  this  for  granted  now,  it 
was  very  important  for  Ulrici's  time.  After  having 
dealt  with  the  part  played  by  personality,  he  argues 
that  scientific  faith  rests  on  the  preponderating 
weight,  objectively,  of  reasons.  Among  his  other 


92  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

philosophical   services,   Ulrici   was   for  many   years 
editor  of  the  '  Zeitschrift  fiir  Philosophie/ 

But  I  now  come  to  deal  with  the  thought  of  his 
two  chief  works,  which,  it  should  be  observed,  are 
closely  connected,  and  approach  the  same  problem 
from  two  different  sides.  In  Ulrici 's  work  on  '  God 
and  Nature'  (1862),  there  is  outlined  a  philosophy 
of  nature.  He  thinks  philosophical  inquiry  into 
the  final  grounds  of  being  and  event  must  concern 
itself  with  the  knowledge  of  Nature.  He  therefore 
sets  out  from  the  study  of  Nature  and  the  results 
of  science,  in  its  principles,  fundamental  conceptions, 
and  presuppositions.  He  aims  to  show,  by  the 
result,  that  God  is,  to  use  his  own  words,  "the 
creative  author  of  Nature,  and  the  absolute  pre- 
supposition of  nature -science  itself."  Mr  Balfour 
has  adopted  a  like  position  that  theism  is  an 
assumption  "not  only  tolerated,"  but  "actually 
required,  by  science"  ('Foundations  of  Belief,' 
p.  321).  The  scientific  ideas  involved,  —  atoms, 
forces,  laws,  &c.  —  make  the  assumption  of  the 
Divine  existence,  for  Ulrici,  absolutely  necessary  t 
He  argues  to  God  as  the  necessary  presupposition 
of  science ;  the  distinguishing  creative  power  of  God 
is  necessary,  and  our  distinguishing  activity  is  but 
a  distinguishing  after  God.  On  this  our  know- 
ledge depends.  Ulrici  admits  the  title  should  rather 
have  been  "Nature  and  God,"  since  the  point  of 
departure  is,  as  we  have  seen,  found  in  the  results 


HERMANN   ULRICI.  93 

of  modern  science.  He  contends  that  many  of  the 
improved  hypotheses  of  science  are  not  necessarily 
anti-religious,  but  quite  as  susceptible  of  a  theistic 
interpretation.  He  thinks  scepticism  is  "  not  a  legit- 
imate result"  of  scientific  research  and  criticism, 
but  "  the  product  of  a  subjective  spirit  and  temper  " 
indicative  of  interest  in  science  "beginning  to 
wane."  Ulrici  seeks  to  mediate  between  theism 
and  pantheism.  He  lays  stress  on  the  need  of  an 
Unconditioned  as  Ground  of  the  conditioned  atoms. 
And  nature  powers  and  effects  have  need  of  an 
unconditioned  Cause  of  all  events  in  the  world. 
Ulrici's  position  is  that  the  Absolute  is  not  condi- 
tioned by  anything  else,  and  so  far  is  the  Uncon- 
ditioned, but  yet  only  because  it  is  itself  the  positive 
condition  of  everything  else.  Ulrici  is  in  such  ways 
led  to  consider  the  proofs  of  the  Divine  existence, 
which  I  do  not  now  propose  to  follow.  I  only  note 
his  position  that  "the  proofs  for  the  existence  of 
God  coincide  with  the  grounds  for  the  belief  in 
God,"  are  simply  "the  real  grounds  of  the  belief 
established  and  expounded  in  a  scientific  manner." 
He  maintains  that  discussion  of  "  the  existence  and 
essence  of  God"  must  be  founded  on  "a  definite 
and  determinate  theory  of  knowledge."  Ulrici 
thinks  that  modern  theology,  in  so  readily  abandon- 
ing, at  Kant's  bidding,  the  proofs  of  the  Divine 
existence,  not  only  renounces  its  claims  to  be  a 
science,  but  uproots  the  foundations  of  the  religion 


94  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

on  which  it  rests.  More  could  be  said  for  this  view, 
at  any  rate,  than  is  often  thought  by  those  who  take 
Kant  a  deal  too  finally.  It  is  enough  for  my  present 
purpose  that,  in  the  ways  already  indicated,  Ulrici 
arrives  at  the  need  for  a  self-conscious  Being  or 
the  Absolute  Spirit.  The  idea  of  God,  for  him, 
implies  not  only  the  possibility  of  an  immediate 
Divine  influence  upon  the  soul,  but  the  fact  of  such 
an  operation.  The  Absolute  is  for  Ulrici  the  uncon- 
ditioned creative  power  through  which  all  con- 
ditioned being  is  posited,  and  in  this  act  of  positing 
it,  He  is  necessarily  distinguished  from  it. 

When  it  comes  to  the  working  out  of  the  evolu- 
tionary world -process,  Ulrici,  like  Lotze,  recognises 
both  a  mechanical  and  a  teleological  process  as 
involved.  But  the  primary  Cause  of  things  he 
found,  not  in  the  affinity  of  atoms,  like  the  mate- 
rialists, but  in  the  principle  which  produced  that 
affinity.  Says  Ulrici, — "  Everything  which  is  con- 
ditional presupposes  a  condition,  which,  as  such,  is 
necessarily  unconditioned  and  absolute."  The  re- 
ciprocal conditionality  of  atoms  cannot,  he  argues, 
be  "in  the  atoms  themselves,"  or  they  would  be 
"  at  once  conditioned  and  unconditioned."  "  Conse- 
quently the  existence  of  atoms  presupposes  some- 
thing absolute  and  unconditional,  which,  as  it  is 
the  cause  of  their  conditionality,  must  necessarily 
be  also  the  cause  of  their  existence." 

Ulrici  rejects  all  pantheistic  theories  of  creation, 


HERMANN  ULRICI.  95 

wherein  the  world  figures  as  a  self -development,  or 
unfolding,  or  self -partitioning,  of  Deity;  for  him 
the  Absolute  is  bound  to  no  condition,  not  even 
to  an  already  existing  stuff.  But  it  is  his  position, 
for  all  that,  in  one  of  his  writings,  that  "  a  universe 
which  remains  the  same  in  the  eternal  change  of 
phenomena  is  a  contradictio  in  adjecto,  for  that 
which  changes  does  not  remain  the  same,  and  a 
changing  manifestation,  without  an  essence  mani- 
fested in  it,  and  changing  with  it,  is  no  mani- 
festation, but  an  illusion."  As  for  Creation  out  of 
nothing,  he  prefers  to  say  that  through  something, 
to  wit,  God,  the  not-being  of  the  world  disappears 
as  the  world  is  posited.  For  there  is  in  the 
absolute  Divine  Spirit  a  producing  and  dis- 
tinguishing activity.  Moritz  Carriere,  like  Ulrici 
here,  rested  the  Divine  self  -  consciousness  on  this 
original  distinguishing  activity.  In  our  own  time 
we  find  much  made  of  activity  by  certain  philos- 
ophers who  make  nothing  of  causality :  it  seems 
strange  to  forget  that  in  every  activity  there  is 
causality. 

The  first  great  thought  is  to  Ulrici  the  positing 
of  the  world,  as  a  possibility  —  a  necessary, 
non  -  arbitrary  act  that  flows  from  the  "  inner 
necessity "  of  the  spiritual  nature  of  God.  I 
cannot  now  dwell  on  the  difficulties  with  which 
this  first  thought  is  beset,  as  Ulrici  expounds  it, 
especially  in  respect  of  such  an  untenable 


96  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

abstraction,  in  the  case  of  God ;  in  Him  thought  and 
realisation,  and  this  as  in  the  second  thought, 
cannot  be  distinguished  in  Ulrici's  way  ;  nor  is  such 
a  negative,  undetermined  mode  of  thought  (as  in 
this  first  thought)  ascribable  to  God.  The  second 
thought  is  concerned  with  the  reality  of  the 
world  —  a  free,  spontaneous  resolution,  with  the 
plan  of  the  world's  realisation,  its  law,  norm,  end, 
and  purpose.  What  Ulrici  hoped  by  separating 
this  thought  from  the  first  was  to  save  the 
freedom  of  God  in  creating,  but  he  did  not  see  the 
difficulty  he  had  created  in  already  insisting  on 
its  springing  out  of  "inner  necessity."  This  has 
the  objectionable  air  of  a  sort  of  Divine  deter- 
minism, even  ethical  necessitation  may  be  presented 
in  such  objectionable  form.  The  standpoint  of 
freedom  is  to  be  absolutely  maintained  for  God, 
in  respect  of  Creation.  But  it  does  not  follow 
from  this  freedom  of  God  in  creating,  that  creation 
is  the  accidental  or  contingent  thing  it  has  often 
been  taken  to  be. 

Prof.  Pringle  -  Pattison  thinks  the  result  of 
creation  being  by  God's  will,  rather  than  grounded 
in  His  nature  (pp.  303-4),  is  to  make  His  relation  to 
the  world,  "  external,"  "  almost  accidental,"  "  merely 
incidental,"  "  almost  an  afterthought."  But  this 
profusion  of  characterisation  is  grounded  in  some 
lack  of  knowledge  and  understanding.  Neither 
philosophy  nor  theology  denies  the  world-idea  to 


HERMANN    ULRICI.  97 

be  eternal  —  nothing  merely  "  incidental,"  nor  of 
the  nature  of  an  "afterthought."  And  if  there  is 
to  be  no  "externality,"  no  otherness,  how  is  the 
world  to  realise  any  manner  of  objective  existence 
as  God's  creation  ?  We  should  then  have  a 
monistic  pantheism  incapable  of  realising  altruism 
at  all.  The  creative  act  is  no  more  "external"  or 
"almost  accidental"  than  is  the  free,  deliberate  act 
of  my  will,  whose  resolution,  carried  out,  is,  in  fact, 
the  most  real  and  intimate  expression  of  my  con- 
sciousness or  mind.  This  revealing  character  of 
will,  in  its  deed,  was  finely  brought  out  by  Schelling. 
Infinitely  less  externality  is  there  in  the  case  of 
immanent  creative  Deity.  That  Divine  will  is 
no  blind,  unconscious  force,  is  not  "  bare  "  will,  but 
is  one  with  eternal,  immanent,  and  purposeful 
Reason.  It  is  quite  groundless  to  say  that,  because 
the  world  is  willed,  the  nature  of  God  cannot  be 
expressed  in  and  through  it.  What  else,  indeed, 
has  it  been  willed  for  ?  It  would  be  a  complete 
mistake  to  put  God's  will  and  His  nature  into  any 
kind  of  opposition.  As  pure,  absolute  Spirit,  there 
can  only  be  perfect  equilibrium  between  them.  We 
cannot  say  that  His  will  dominates  His  nature, 
any  more  than  we  can  say  that  His  nature 
dominates  His  will ;  what  we  can  and  do  say  is, 
that  they  perfectly  and  mutually  condition  each 
other,  so  that  the  absolute  harmony  of  His  being  is 
eternally  maintained. 

G 


98  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

We  cannot  acquiesce  in  the  sureness  of  Eternal 
Love,  finding  expression  in  creation,  being  converted 
into  a  quasi-pantheistic  necessity  to  create.  If  we 
seek  in  the  conception  of  ethicised  Deity,  to  adjust 
and  correct  the  notion  of  contingency  or  acci- 
dentalism, no  less  must  we  correct  and  reject  the 
notion  of  any  sort  of  abstract  pantheistic  necessity, 
in  speaking  of  Deity  as  determined  by  love.  For 
we  know  only  too  well  the  pantheistic  type  of 
thought  which  makes  creation  His  necessary  act, 
and  regards  the  world  as  identical  with  His 
essence.  His  unconditioned  love  knows  neither 
necessity  nor  compulsion.  The  love  that  issues  in 
Creation  is  a  free,  spontaneous  giving — a  love  which 
is  the  transitive  element  in  the  immanent  being  of 
God  that  Rothe  declared  it  to  be — and  is  rightly 
conceived  in  terms  of  spontaneity  and  freedom, 
not  of  necessity.  And  thus,  to  the  einheitliche 
view  of  life  and  of  the  world  which  constitutes 
theistic  world-view,  in  the  fine  thought  of  the  poet 
of  the  "  Paradiso,"  "all  the  scattered  leaves  of  the 
universe  are  bound  by  love  into  a  single  volume." 

"  Legato  con  amore  in  un  volume, 
Ci6  che  per  1'universo  si  squaderna." 

(Canto  XXXIII.  86-7). 

God  is  to  Ulrici  not  first  God  and  then  world 
Creator,  but  as  God  is  He  world  Creator,  and  only 


HERMANN   ULRICI.  99 

as  world  Creator  is  He  God.  This  last  statement 
falls  short  of  true  Theism,  which  allows  God  Being- 
in- and -for -Himself,  and  not  for  the  world  only. 
The  personality  of  God  is  to  be  posited  before  all, 
although  Ulrici  fails  of  that.  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison, 
however,  gives  Ulrici's  passage  unqualified  support. 
But  if  the  distinction  of  the  world  is,  as  Ulrici 
maintains,  one  which  is  necessary  to  God,  then 
Ulrici  contradicts  himself  in  making  God  the  ground 
of  all  freedom;  this  He  cannot  be,  after  having 
been  so  put  under  necessity.  For  Ulrici  creation  is 
eternal,  but  the  world,  he  holds,  is  not  eternal  in 
itself.  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison  says  (p.  310),— "As 
Ulrici  put  it,  God  is  known  to  us  as  Creator  of  the 
world,"  a  statement  I  accept,  but  it  is  not  quite 
accurately  put,  for  Ulrici  speaks  of  what  God  "  is," 
not  of  God's  being  "known."  Ulrici's  statement 
that  "only  as  Creator  of  the  world  is  He  God,"  I 
repudiate,  as  making  God  subservient  to  the  activity 
of  world-making.  God's  real  freedom,  the  internal 
perfection  of  His  Being,  and  His  complete  self- 
possession,  are  to  be  maintained.  And  I  may  remark, 
in  passing,  and  with  a  general  reference,  that  phil- 
osophers who  allow  themselves  to  treat  slightingly 
His  eternal  dignity  (gloria  Dei)  pay  the  penalty  in 
their  own  work,  since  that  eternal  dignity  is  "the 
absolute  fundament  of  worthiness,"  the  sole  founda- 
tion of  all  true  adoration,  and  the  absolute  basis  of 


100  SEVEN  THEISTTC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

all  true  subjective  dignity,  honour,  and  worth.  It  is 
as  if  a  new  and  exalted  application  were  made  of  the 
words  in  Shakespeare's  sonnet, — 

"  I  am  that  I  am  !  and  they  that  level 
At  my  abuses,  reckon  up  their  own." 

The  religious  interest  calls  for  clear  discrimination 
of  God  from  the  world.  Being  that  exists  of  and 
for  itself  exists  necessarily,  and  does  not  by  world 
determination  become  God.  There  are  affinities 
with  pantheism,  as  well  as  with  theism,  in  Ulrici's 
statements.  Neither  Ulrici  nor  Dr  Pringle-Pattison 
claims  aseity  for  matter  or  the  world,  and  their  in- 
culcation that  we  must  not  "  separate  the  two  ideas  " 
is  not  justified:  the  distinction  of  God  from  the 
world  is  precisely  what  theistic  thought  and  the 
religious  consciousness  have  always  demanded.  And, 
as  Bradley  says,  "the  man  who  demands  a  reality 
more  solid  than  the  religious  consciousness,  knows 
not  what  he  seeks." 

If  the  world  is  "  not  eternal  in  itself,"  then  it  has 
received  Dasein  or  existence  from  Another,  and 
ought  to  be  distinguished  from  Him.  When  it  is 
said  that  we  must  not  separate  the  two  ideas,  is  it 
a  pantheistic  identity  we  are  offered  ?  But  if  we 
separate  them  in  thought  in  order  to  distinguish 
them,  that  is  not  separation  in  any  absolute  sense. 
No  one  proposes  such  a  thing,  because,  for  us,  these 
are  complementary  of  each  other.  If  we  separate  or 


HERMANN  ULRICI. 


..101 


isolate  the  idea  of  God,  it  is  that  we  may  view  Him 
as  the  Unconditioned,  but  the  Unconditioned  does 
not  necessarily  mean  the  unrelated.  Absoluteness 
itself  carries  the  possibility  of  relation.  And  if  we 
separate  the  idea  of  the  world,  it  is  to  view  it  in  its 
dependence,  as  a  system  of  conditioned  activities,  not 
to  claim  for  it  an  independence  of  the  Deity.  The 
world  is  to  be  distinguished  from  God,  and  is  not 
a  mere  function  of  God,  as  the  votaries  of  an  evolv- 
ing deity  assume ;  but,  while  a  divine  product  and 
dependent  manifestation  of  God,  it  has  an  existence, 
a  relative  independence,  of  its  own,  with  a  corre- 
spondingly relative  imperfection.  If  the  independ- 
ence of  the  world  were  other  than  thus  relative,  and 
grounded  in  God,  the  whole  metaphysics  of  the 
Absolute  would  be  superfluous.  If,  however,  as 
Ulrici  holds,  God  is  not  God  but  as  He  creates  the 
world — which  He  must  do  eternally — then  I  agree 
with  those  who  think  His  action  is,  in  such  case, 
necessary,  and  talk  of  His  freedom  is  vain.  Vain, 
too,  is  talk  of  His  free,  ethical  motives  of  love  in 
creating,  which  Ulrici  emphasises,  if  His  creative 
action  is  thus  necessary. 

I  feel  bound  to  say  that  I  think  Hegel  and  Janet 
— both  of  whom  Prof.  Pringle-Pattison  criticises — 
had  at  least  both  grasped  the  fact  that  creative 
action,  on  the  part  of  God,  presupposed  His  in- 
teriorly perfect  being,  and  full  self-possession,  in  a 
way  that  their  critic  has  missed.  Elsewhere  Dr 


1 02  SEVES    THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Pringle-Pattison  said  that  in  Hegel's  hands  "the 
analysis  of  the  structure  of  thought  is,  in  his  own 
daring  phrase,  '  the  exposition  of  God  as  He  is,  in  His 
eternal  essence,  before  the  creation  of  nature  or  a 
single  human  spirit'"  ('Two  Lectures  on  Theism,' 
p.  20).  On  this  and  its  connections  Dr  H.  Stirling 
speaks  in  '  What  is  Thought  ? '  (pp.  384-386).  What 
Hegel  here  expressly  proposed  to  do — consider  God 
"  in  His  eternal  essence "  —  is  precisely  what  Prof. 
Pringle-Pattison  disallows  throughout  his  work.  So, 
on  the  logical  position  involved,  I  prefer  to  stand 
with  Hegel  and  Janet,  rather  than  with  their  critic. 
For,  in  failing,  logically,  to  regard  God  "in  His 
eternal  essence,"  before  viewing  Him  as  Creator, 
Prof.  Pringle-Pattison  fails  to  ontologise  in  the  right 
place,  and  has  in  consequence  lost  or  neglected  some- 
thing in  the  Divine  attributes.  Even  now,  thought 
can  project  itself  behind  the  universe  (whereby  we 
have  come  to  know  God)  and  can  conceive  Him  in 
His  selfness  —  His  freedom  and  independence  —  as 
distinct  from  the  world,  and  as  Lord  of  all  being. 
Certainly  we  know  God  only  in  His  manifestations 
in  the  world,  but  does  that  mean  that  our  knowledge 
of  God  must  be  confined  to  these  ?  Certainly  not ; 
for  these  suggest  as  well  as  declare,  and,  as  has  been 
rightly  said,  "suggest  more  than  they  declare." 
Thus  we  can  pass  behind  them  to  the  Person- 
ality expressed  in  and  through  them,  can  know 
something  of  God  in  Himself,  not  merely  in  His 


HERMANN  ULKICI.  103 

manifestations  To  deny  this  were  to  go  flatly 
in  the  face  of  the  myriad -voiced  religious  con- 
sciousness. 

It  is  a  complete  fallacy  to  treat  God's  nature  as 
subject  to  modification  by  His  objective  deeds,  and 
make  Him  dependent  upon  them,  "just  as "  our 
dependent  natures  are  developed  by  interaction  with 
external  forces.  There  is  only  one  clear  and  correct 
way  to  think  God's  nature,  and  that  is  as  the  one 
self-existent,  and  absolutely  self-determined,  Being. 
I  venture  to  assert,  that  only  as  such  eternally 
perfect,  and  perfectly  self-determined  Being,  is  He 
God.  Absolute  self-determination  means  Absolute 
Personality.  But  to  the  full  height  of  this  concep- 
tion— the  full- orbed  personality  of  God — Ulrici  has 
not,  in  my  judgment,  risen,  great  as  were  his 
services  to  theistic  philosophy.  I  must  make  clear 
in  what  sense  I  have  spoken  of  self-determination 
as  applied  to  God.  Rothe,  after  the  manner  of 
Weisse,  took  this  conception,  as  applied  to  the 
Absolute,  to  involve  the  distinction  of  potentiality 
and  actuality.  I  mean  nothing  of  the  sort.  There 
is  no  ideal  or  possible  state,  into  which  He  may,  by 
will  or  effort,  come,  as  into  actuality  out  of  poten- 
tiality. He  knows  Himself,  but  it  is  as  actuality, 
never  potentiality,  since  He  is  the  eternally  per- 
fect existence.  I  mean,  therefore,  by  the  term 
that  God  is  determined  only  from  within — by  His 
own  being,  not  by  the  world  or  anything  outside 


104  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

Him.     He  wills   Himself,  His  own   nature.     Thus, 
and  thus  only,  does  He  determine  Himself. 

Prof.  Pringle-Pattison's  defect  appears  to  me  to 
be  that  his  hold  of  God  as  a  self  -  communicating 
Life  has  prevented  his  adequate  seizure  of  God's 
dignity  (essentia  essendi),  His  complete  self-posses- 
sion, His  self  -  containment,  without  world  -  depend- 
ence or  world  -  subordinationism.  But  this  is  the 
proper  presupposition  of  His  self  -  communicating 
Life,  so  that  the  self -communicative  process  may  not 
lead  to  His  losing  Himself,  pantheistically,  in  what 
is  different  from  Himself.  To  say  that  the  Divine 
Life  is  essentially  the  "process  of  self -communica- 
tion "  is  but  a  half-truth,  unless  and  until  properly 
grounded  in  the  perfection  of  His  Being,  and  its 
independence  of  objective  action  or  relation,  so  far 
as  His  consciously  absolute  and  self  -  determined 
nature  is  concerned.  No  theistic  philosopher,  I 
venture  to  assert,  fully  realises  his  position  who 
has  not  the  intellectual  and  moral  courage  to  stand 
for  the  infinite  egoistic  consciousness  or  perfection, 
as  that  whereon  Divine  or  perfect  altruism  depends. 
Self -communication,  sundered  from  self-affirmation, 
were  not  love  at  all  in  any  worthy  and  proper  idea 
of  the  term,  but  a  self-destructive  laying  waste  of 
its  own  powers. 

I  now  pass  to  Ulrici's  work  on  '  God  and  Man ' 
(1866),  in  which  is  outlined  a  psychology  of  man. 
It  has  for  aim  "to  demonstrate,"  he  says,  "on  the 


HERMANN  ULRICI.  105 

basis  of  firmly  established   facts,  that  to  the   soul 
as   distinguished   from   the   body,  to   the   spirit  as 
distinguished  from  nature,  not  simply  independence, 
but  supremacy  belongs  of  right  and  of  fact."     Force, 
organism,  the  body,  the  soul  and  psychical  forces,  are 
all  discussed.     Ulrici  does  not  contest  the  Darwinian 
theory  of  descent,  but  only  the  Darwinian- Haeckelian 
purely  mechanistic  conception,  with  its  exclusion  of 
all  governing  plan  and  purpose.     On  the  contrary, 
Ulrici  believes  in  a  universally  ruling  principle  of 
development,   in   the   inorganic   as    in   the   organic 
region,  which   is  immanent  in  all   things  from  the 
beginning,  and  is  in  result  seen  in  harmonious  form 
and   purpose  (vol.  i.  p.  118   of   2nd  or  1874  edn.). 
I.    H.    Fichte   says   he   is   in   full   agreement   with 
Ulrici's    view,    in    which    the    realisation    of    this 
principle  of  development  is  taken  to  have  constituted 
the  struggle  for  existence.      Ulrici  comes  at  length 
(vol.  i.  2)  to  treat  of  the  soul — an  insoluble  centralised 
union  of  powers — in  its  relation  to  God,  ethical  and 
religious  questions  receiving  much  attention.     It  has 
always  seemed  to  me  a  significant  thing  that  Ulrici 
should  have  contended  that  the  idea  of  truth  is  an 
ethical  category,  especially  in  view  of  the  develop- 
ment so  long  after,  of   Rickert's   system,  in  which 
truth  of  the  logical  conscience  is  subsumed   under 
the  ethical  (see  my  Art.  on  "  The  Greatest  Problem 
in  Value,"  in  '  The  Monist/  1919).     In  a  lengthy  and 
valuable  discussion,  Ulrici   argues  that  the  ethical 


106  SEVEN  THEISTIC  PHILOSOPHERS. 

ideas  are  not  derivable  from  experience;  they  are 
not  derived  through  experience,  but  yet  not  without 
experience  (vol.  ii.  pp.  68-131).  Another  point  in 
Ulrici's  ethical  position  worth  noting,  is  that  "  man 
is  not  born  with  rights,  but  only  with  duties,"  from 
which  his  rights  follow.  Otherwise,  he  thinks,  the 
idea  of  right  would  have  ethical  obligation  taken 
from  it,  That,  however,  I  do  not  now  discuss,  as 
I  wish  to  note  his  religious  position.  I  may  remark, 
however,  that  the  opposite  view  was  held  by  Stahl, 
who  contended  for  an  objective  order  of  right,  in 
which  rights  are  not  consequent  on  duty. 

Ulrici  thinks  "  the  inmost  life  of  the  human  soul 
has  its  root  in  God  Himself,  while  rooted  in  the 
man's  own  religious  and  moral  feeling."  Both  in 
this  work,  and  in  the  work  on  'God  and  Nature,' 
Ulrici  deals  with  the  immediate  manifestation  of 
God  to  the  soul,  using  the  analogy  of  sense-percep- 
tion. Lotze,  it  need  hardly  be  added,  does  so  also,  in 
his  '  Mikrokosmos,'  and  philosophy  of  religion.  Only 
the  subjective  ground  of  faith  in  God  can  psychology 
find  in  the  nature  of  the  human  soul,  and  with  this 
must  be  connected  the  objectively  given  grounds  for 
faith  in  God.  But  the  objective  truth  cannot  be 
grasped  without  a  subjective  ground  of  its  certainty. 
The  ethical  and  the  religious  feelings  are  not 
identical,  but  are  closely  related,  and  are  com- 
plementary of  each  other.  The  religious  feeling  is, 
for  Ulrici,  the  necessary  condition  of  all  knowledge 


HERMANN  ULBICI.  107 

that  will  raise  us  above  brute-level.  He  thinks  it 
"clear  that  the  moral  feeling  stands  in  original 
unity  with  the  religious,  and  is  of  one  and  the 
same  origin."  He  says  that  "  the  religious  and  the 
moral  feeling,  the  subjective  grounds  of  religion 
and  morality,  are  indeed  not  absolutely  identical," 
but  he  thinks  they  hold  together  as  immediately 
and  inseparably  as  do  the  metaphysical  and  the 
ethical  being  of  God.  He  views  the  idea  of  God 
as  lying  implicitly  in  moral  feeling  -  perception, 
unmediated  by  reasonings  from  nature  ('Gott  und 
der  Mensch,'  vols.  i.-ii.  pp.  448-450). 

It  may  also  be  noted  that  Ulrici  does  not  regard 
conscience  as  the  voice  of  God,  and  thinks  freewill 
impossible  if  a  command  of  God  is  imprinted  on 
man's  constitution.  In  this  Ulrici  seems  to  me 
mistaken.  No  imprinting  on  man's  constitution, 
making  him  capable  of  obedience,  takes  away  the 
necessity  for  his  acceptance  of  the  true  law  of  life 
of  his  own  free  choice  or  self-determination.  And 
Ulrici's  rejection  of  conscience  as  the  voice  of  God 
calls  for  explanation,  since  it  is — taken  as  the  voice 
of  God — not  the  whole  truth  of  the  matter,  for 
conscience  is  the  voice  of  our  own  inner  nature  too, 
and  God's  voice  would  be  vain,  if  we  had  not  a 
faculty  of  moral  perception  of  our  own.  Moreover, 
I  do  not  think  that,  speaking  in  a  general  sense 
at  least,  we  can  say  that  God  is  given  in  conscience  ; 
what  is  given  rather  is  only  right  and  wrong.  It 


108  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

works  in  connection  with  this  rather  than  as  relat- 
ing the  person  to  God.  Schenkel  and  others  have 
held  a  high  theory  that  God  is  immediately  given 
in  conscience,  so  making  conscience  in  an  extreme 
way  the  peculiar  organ  of  religion,  rather  than  the 
voice  of  our  moral  nature.  Kant,  too,  made  it  the 
source  of  subjective  religion,  holding  it  to  reveal 
the  law  of  reason  as  the  law  of  God.  But,  as 
a  general  theory  for  mankind,  conscience  cannot 
be  said  to  have  God  for  its  object,  as  religion  has, 
but  the  Tightness  or  wrongness  of  the  action.  But 
the  moral  and  the  religious  aspects,  though  distinct, 
are  not  opposed,  but  are  complementary  of  each 
other,  and  conscience  is  so  deep  and  important  a 
factor  of  the  soul  that  without  it,  religion  could  not 
be.  For,  in  its  final  and  highest  form,  conscience 
carries  in  itself  the  ideal  of  the  perfect  life.  Ulrici's 
position  calls  for  criticism  only  where  the  religious 
view  of  conscience  is  taken,  that  it  is  only  through 
God  that  we  come  to  know  what  is  good,  only  in 
His  light  that  we  see  light,  whether  we  consciously 
realise  this  fact  or  not. 

Ulrici  is,  under  any  deductions,  a  noble  and 
capable  expounder  and  defender  of  philosophical 
truth,  as  he  saw  it.  He  is  less  known  in  Britain 
than  in  America,  and  far  less  known  in  Britain  than 
might  have  been  expected  from  Erdmann's  reproach- 
ful and  somewhat  narrow-minded  references  to 
Ulrici's  interest  in  British  thought.  An  admirable 


HERMANN  ULRICI.  109 

philosophical  scholar,  and  a  man  of  rare  accomplish- 
ments, Ulrici  is  also,  in  the  construction  of  his 
system  of  real -idealism,  a  far  more  original  and 
systematic  philosopher — besides  being  an  incisive 
critic — than  is  sometimes  supposed  by  those  whose 
criticism  might  be  said,  in  the  stock  phrase  of 
Hegelians  to  all  criticism,  to  be  external. 


110 


CHAPTER  VII. 

F.   A.   TRENDELENBURG. 

A.  TRENDELENBURG  (1802-1872),  professor  of  philos- 
ophy in  the  University  of  Berlin,  is  the  last  of  our 
philosophic  group  whom  I  shall  now  mention. 
Among  the  many  influences  exerted  upon  him  were 
the  Kantian  Reinhold,  Von  Berger,  and  K.  F. 
Becker,  author  of  works  on  the  philosophy  of 
language.  Trendelenburg  is  especially  famed  for 
his  'Logical  Investigations'  (1840,  I  use  the  1862 
edn.),  a  fact  which  has  sometimes  been  obscured 
because  of  the  fame  he  won  as  a  commentator  on 
Aristotle.  His  '  Elements  of  the  Aristotelian  Logic ' 
(1837)  went  through  several  editions.  Trendelen- 
burg was  the  leader  in  the  revival  of  Aristotelian 
studies,  and  he  laid  emphasis,  in  the  Preface  to  his 
'  Logical  Investigations,'  on  "  that  organic  conception 
of  the  universe  which  has  its  foundation  in  Plato 
and  Aristotle,  and  which,  continuing  from  them, 
will  have  to  complete  itself  in  a  profounder  exam- 
ination of  fundamental  ideas  and  through  an  inter 


FRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  Ill 

change  with  the  science  of  reality."  Dr  Merz  says 
that  when  "  the  exclusively  critical  task  of  deciding 
as  to  the  powers  and  limits  of  the  human  intellect 
and  the  nature  of  scientific  knowledge  was  taken  up 
as  a  definite  problem,"  it  was  "  partly  as  a  continua- 
tion and  confirmation  of  Kant's  views,  partly  also 
in  opposition  to  them.  The  solution  of  this  problem 
was  very  much  assisted  and  influenced  by  two 
independent  lines  of  research.  The  first  of  these 
was  the  analysis  of  the  methods  of  science,  of 
which  John  Stuart  Mill  was  the  great  representa- 
tive ;  the  second  was  the  revival  of  Aristotelian 
studies,  in  which  Trendelenburg  of  Berlin  was  the 
principal  leader"  (' History  of  European  Thought/ 
vol.  iii.  p.  125). 

Philosophy,  Trendelenburg  says,  must  take  up 
the  problems  historically,  and  unfold  them.  His 
'  Historical  Contributions  to  Philosophy '  (3  vols. 
1846,  1855,  and  1867)  proved  very  notable,  his 
historical  work  being  marked  by  almost  unique 
learning  and  scientific  objectiveness.  Philo'sophy 
was  to  him  the  "science  of  the  Idea."  He  deeply 
discussed  the  ultimate  differences  of  systems,  and  in 
the  second  volume,  found  these  in  their  attitudes 
or  preferences  towards  thought  (Gedanke)  or  force 
(Kraft).  In  this  volume  he  also  has  valuable  critical 
comments  on  Herbart's  attitude  to  supposed  contra- 
dictions in  the  universal  concepts  of  experience.  He 
devoted,  in  the  first  volume,  great  attention  to  the 


112  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

doctrine  and  development  of  the  categories.  In  the 
third  (1867)  volume,  Trendelenburg  says  that  "an 
ethical  philosophy  which  would  exclude  pleasure 
would  be  contrary  to  nature ;  and  one  which  would 
make  a  principle  of  it  would  be  contrary  to  spirit." 
I  may  also  observe  that  some  critical  remarks  on 
Trendelenburg's  positions,  in  this  volume,  relative  to 
Kant's  views  on  the  World-concept  and  its  time  rela- 
tions, will  be  found  in  H.  Cohen's  work,  '  Kant's 
Theorie  der  Erfahrung,"  (pp.  260-270),  but  these 
need  not  occupy  us  here,  where  we  are  mainly  con- 
cerned with  Trendelenburg's  own  positions  as  a 
theistic  philosopher.  Certain  other  works  of  his 
were  widely  studied,  and  many  of  the  best  German 
thinkers  were  influenced  by  him,  among  whom  may 
be  instanced  Dilthey,  Eucken,  Brentano,  Teichmiiller, 
Kym ;  and  there  were  many  others. 

Trendelenburg  showed  what  he  considered  the 
inconclusive  and  unhistorical  character  of  Hegel's 
dialectic  method,  and  its  adaptability  to  prove  any- 
thing or  everything.  That  is  to  say,  Trendelenburg 
held  Hegel's  logical  contradictories  to  be  real  con- 
traries. Thus  pure  Being,  ever  self -identical,  is 
rest;  pure  Nothing,  also  ever  self-identical,  is  also 
rest.  Trendelenburg  asks  how  out  of  these  two 
admitted  abstractions  (ruhenden  Vorstellungen'), 
Becoming  shall  suddenly  arise  ?  Yes,  Becoming, 
this  concrete  perception,  which  presides  over  life  and 
death  ('  Log.  Unter.,'  i.  p.  38).  Of  Hegel's  making 


FRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  113 

pure  being  signify  pure  nothing,  Trendelenburg  said 
that  in  it,  the  pure  is  the  empty,  and  the  empty 
is  the  pure.  And,  after  dealing  with  the  "una- 
voidable dilemma  "  of  the  dialectic  of  pure  thought, 
Trendelenburg  concludes,  —  "  Whoever,  therefore, 
sees  deeply  into  the  so-called  negative  movement 
of  dialectic  will  discover  in  most  cases  of  its  appli- 
cation something  ambiguous"  ('Log.  Unter./  i.  pp. 
56-57).  Trendelenburg  goes  on  to  point  out  that, 
in  the  dialectical  process,  there  is  a  constant  in- 
fusion of  elements  really  empirical,  even  saying — 
"  Das  Meiste  ist  von  der  Erfahrung  aufgenommen." 
Chalybaus,  I  may  remark,  in  the  concluding  chapter 
of  his  '  Historical  Development  of  Speculative 
Philosophy/  expressly  indicates  his  sympathy  with 
Trendelenburg  in  this  claim  for  the  place  and  power 
of  empiricism. 

Space,  time,  and  the  categories,  were,  to  Trendel- 
enburg, forms  of  thought  as  well  as  of  being.  The 
logical  form  he  would  not  separate  from  the  content. 
Besides  Hegel,  Trendelenburg  devoted  much  atten- 
tion to  Schelling  and  'Schopenhauer.  Against  the 
platonising  Kant  and  all  one-sided  Idealism,  Tren- 
delenburg sought  to  vindicate  the  rights  of  reality 
(Realitdt),  real  existence  (Wirklichkeit),  and  objects 
(Gegenstdnde).  He  stood  opposed  to  Kant's  time- 
space  theory  as  a  subjectivist-phenomenalist  con- 
ception. Martineau  agrees  with  him,  saying,  —  "I 
hold,  with  Trendelenburg,  that  the  subjectivity  of 

H. 


114  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

space  and  time — the  fundamental  characteristic  of 
the  critical  philosophy  —  does  not  prejudice  their 
claim  to  objectivity,  and  requires  no  surrender  of 
the  reliance  which  we  inevitably  place  on  the 
veracity  of  our  own  faculties"  ('The  Study  of 
Religion/  vol.  i.  p.  73).  Trendelenburg  and  Kuno 
Fischer,  however,  were  at  variance  upon  the  subject. 
Trendelenburg  thought  that  if  one  should  grant 
space  and  time  to  be  subjective  conditions,  and 
precedent  to  perception  and  experience  in  us,  there 
would  still  not  be  a  shred  of  proof  to  show  that  they 
cannot,  at  the  same  time,  also  be  objective  forms. 
It  is  their  being  only  (nur)  subjective  forms  that  he 
holds  ill-grounded,  and  he  thinks  space  and  time  are 
not  to  be  denied  to  things,  because  Kant  found  them 
in  thought.  Trendelenburg  is  opposed,  generally, 
to  the  eliminating  and  phenomenalising  of  the  thing- 
world.  Lotze  is  like  him  in  this  emphasis  on  the 
realistic  side,  in  modification  of  the  idealistic  stress 
of  the  elder  Fichte,  Schelling,  and  Hegel.  But  this 
did  not  keep  Lotze  from  occupying  the  subjectivist 
position  on  space,  of  which  I  have  just  spoken. 
Trendelenburg  thus  pursues  an  empiric -inductive 
method,  rather  than  a  purely  speculative  one,  in 
matters  metaphysical. 

Trendelenburg  sought  a  form  of  activity  that 
should  be  common  at  once  to  thought  and  being,  and 
this  he  found  in  motion,  instead  of  Hegel's  thought, 
motion  to  him  being  fundamental  and  undefinable. 


FRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  115 

Movement  is  the  most  extended  activity  in  being. 
What  appears  as  rest,  is,  more  deeply  inquired  into, 
seen  to  be  movement.  All  rest  in  nature  is  only  the 
counterpoise  of  movements.  Movement  is  the  funda- 
mental phenomenon  in  all  Nature.  He  says,  with 
Aristotle,  that  he  who  does  not  know  movement, 
does  not  know  Nature.  But  he  extends  movement 
to  the  world  of  spirit  also;  spiritual  movement  is 
the  great  organ  of  knowledge.  His  "constructive 
movements,"  both  in  our  inner  thought,  genetically 
developed  as  constructive  movement  out  of  our  self- 
activity,  and  in  external  or  objective  movements  of 
being,  cannot  here  be  discussed  in  all  their  Hera- 
clitean  aspects  and  bearings,  but  it  must  be  noted 
how  fundamentally  he  posits  everywhere  the 
concrete  intuition  of  "constructive  movement."  I 
observe,  in  passing,  that  some  critical  remarks  on 
Trendelenburg,  having  relation  to  this,  will  be  found 
in  the  appendix  (pp.  336-337)  to  the  work  of  E.  Laas, 
'  Kant's  Analogien  der  Erfahrung/  Trendelenburg 
takes  this  "constructive  movement"  to  be  that 
which  philosophy  has  in  common  with  mathematics, 
setting  the  latter  as  a  speculative  science  in  opposi- 
tion to  the  empirical.  Speculative  method  is,  it  may 
perhaps  be  allowed,  related  to  experience  as  mathe- 
matics is  to  the  material  world.  But  in  respect  of 
the  spiritual  potency  of  "constructive  movement," 
Trendelenburg  is  not  always  allowed  to  have 
sufficiently  considered  the  free  potency,  over  against 


116  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

an  overweighted  objective  movement,  of  the  subject 
as  a  first  posited  spiritual  substantiality  ('Log. 
Unter.,'  i.  ch.  viii. ;  ii.  ch.  xi.).  This  view  has  been 
taken,  for  example,  by  P.  Gloatz,  in  his  '  Speculative 
Theologie/  Erster  Band,  p.  11.  I  think,  too,  the 
treatment  was  perhaps  not  all -sided  enough,  and 
moved  too  much  on  the  lines  of  contrast  merely 
between  machine  and  organism,  but  his  insistences 
on  purpose  were,  for  that  time,  admirable  in  their 
way  and  serviceable,  and.  I  shall  speak  of  them 
presently,  but  critically.  A  more  comprehensive  and 
systematic  use  of  the  idea  of  potency,  although  his 
potencies  are  too  abstractly  conceived,  is  found,  for 
example,  in  Schelling,  for  whom  possibility  is  itself 
something  real — a  real  potency. 

Besides  much  acute  criticism  of  Kant  and  Herbart, 
Trendelenburg  discusses  causality  and  substance, 
and,  in  the  first  volume  of  his  '  Logical  Investigations,' 
the  real  categories,  in  the  second,  the  modal  categories. 
He  takes  causality,  that  is,  efficient  cause,  to  be  as 
extended  as  motion  itself.  From  the  creative  act  of 
motion  springs  causality,  wherein,  from  the  efficient 
cause,  the  effect  follows.  As  movement  is  at  the 
bottom  of  all  thought,  he  takes  causality  to  be 
necessary  to  thought;  movement  in  thought  corre- 
sponds exactly  to  real  movement ;  causality  is 
equally  necessary  to  being,  since  movement,  in 
another  form,  is  at  the  base  of  being.  His  emphasis 
is  on  efficient  cause  as  the  main  category.  Dr  E. 


FRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  117 

Konig,  devotes  some  critical  attention  to  Trendelen- 
burg's  position  on  the  causal  problem,  on  constructive 
movement,  and,  as  a  Kantian,  to  Trendelenburg's 
criticism  of  Kant.  Konig  thinks  that  just  as  little 
in  being  as  in  thought,  does  all  causality  mean 
continuously  connected  movement ;  he  takes  all  cau- 
sal connections  to  be  cases  of  mechanical  causality. 
He  takes  a  purely  natural  science  view  of  causal 
working,  and  is  more  free  of  speculative  postulation 
than  Trendelenburg  (c  Die  Entwickelung  des  Causal- 
problems  in  der  Philosophic  seit  Kant/  vol.  ii.  75-84). 
With  substance,  Trendelenburg  says,  is  associated  the 
notion  of  the  independent — of  what  is  grounded  in 
itself,  and  not  in  another.  But  he  cannot  find,  in 
strict  sense,  place  for  such  a  conception  in  the  whole 
territory  of  the  finite,  hence  he  goes  on  to  speak  of 
the  relative  and  finite  use  of  the  term.  Substance  is, 
to  Trendelenburg,  the  permanent  (angehaltene)  pro- 
duct of  causality.  He  has  much  to  say  also  of 
quality  and  quantity  in  these  connections.  As  to 
necessity,  Trendelenburg  says  the  "  ultimate  point " 
on  which  all  necessity  is  made  to  rest,  is  "a  com- 
munity of  thought  and  being.  What  is  an  element 
of  thought  must  be  conversely  an  immediate  element 
of  being.  We  could  call  this  ultimate  point,  if  the 
expression  were  not  used  in  manifold  senses,  the 
identity  of  thought  and  being."  And  he  adds,  later, 
that  Hegel  calls  the  ego  universal  because  the 
particular  objects  fall  into  his  consciousness,  and  he 


118  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

calls  the  man  universal,  because  the  man  thinks  the 
universal  (ii.  pp.  178-184). 

When  he  comes  to  consider  the  question  of  End, 
Trendelenburg  gives  much  attention  to  final  cause, 
which  he  treats  as  an  a  priori  principle  on  the  level 
of  efficient  cause.  He  shows  its  bearing  on  the 
doctrine  of  organic  life,  of  which  the  ethical  was  a 
higher  stage.  In  fact,  he  regards  his  philosophy  as 
"organic  world -view,"  and  it  has  kinship  with 
speculative  theism.  He  says  it  is  a  simple  and 
pregnant  conclusion  that,  so  far  as  design  is  realised 
in  the  world,  thought  as  its  ground  has  preceded  it. 
Yet  the  teleological  argument,  says  an  American 
writer,  "  instead  of  showing  thought  as  antecedent, 
shows  it  as  pervading  the  whole,  and  in  a  process 
whose  apparent  mode  of  operation  is  that  of  neces- 
sity" (E.  Mulford,  'The  Republic  of  God,'  p.  9). 

A  blind  and  unconscious  adaptation  of  means  to 
ends  Trendelenburg  regards  as  inconceivable.  But 
this  seems  hardly  in  keeping  with  his  view  of  the 
universe  as  itself  organic,  and  the  drawback  of  the 
intelligence  presumed  in  the  teleological  argument 
is,  I  think  it  may  be  allowed,  its  association  with 
blind  agents,  and  its  apparently  so  remote  connection 
with  consciousness.  For  the  Deity  is  supposed  to  be 
at  one  with  the  intelligence  involved  in  a  sphere 
where  the  voluntary  and  the  spontaneous  are  so 
jealously  excluded  by  science.  But  these  are  mere 
obiter  dicta,  and  the  subject  in  its  full  bearings 


PRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  119 

cannot  here  be  discussed.  The  world  is  reasonable, 
Trendelenburg  says,  and  reason  is  real.  He  distin- 
guishes real  opposition  from  logical  contradiction, 
and  says  a  contradiction  "is  the  expression  of  the 
utterly  incompatible,  which  of  itself  mocks  at  all 
mediation."  Realised  purpose  is  only  comprehensible 
through  the  prius  of  thought.  Trendelenburg  saw 
the  practical  reason  of  Kant  to  rest  upon  the  prac- 
tical reason  of  Aristotle,  and  he  did  much  for  teleo- 
logical  thought  through  his  wide  and  far-reaching 
influence.  To  him,  the  fixed  action  of  the  forces  of 
nature,  and  their  conformity  to  purpose,  argue  the 
existence  of  a  Cause  which  has  determined  this  fixity 
and  conformity  (ii.  p.  24).  Purpose,  like  motion,  is 
for  him  fundamental  fact,  and  common  to  both 
thinking  and  being. 

He  does  not  regard  the  Unconditioned  as  a  nega- 
tive notion.  We  reach  it  by  a  negative  process, 
removing  everything  that  limits  it.  But  the  notion 
itself  is  positive,  the  most  positive  of  all  notions. 
This  result  is  in  harmony  with  the  view  which  I 
have  myself  taken  of  the  matter,  earlier  in  this 
work.  Trendelenburg  says, — "The  so-called  proofs 
of  the  existence  of  God  have  worth  only  as  points 
of  view,  which  cannot  be  understood  without  the 
Absolute.  They  are  indirect  proofs,  which  have  for 
their  peculiar  function  to  develop  the  ground-theme 
of  the  Unconditioned."  "They  indicate  what  con- 
fusion (Zwiespalt)  must  arise,  if  we  do  not  posit  God. 


120  SEVEN   THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

In  this  thought  they  have  their  constraining  power  " 
(ii.  p.  427).  The  restless  movement  of  the  spirit, 
thinks  Trendelenburg,  finds  rest  only  in  the  notion 
of  the  "Whole";  to  this  we  are  led  by  the  organic 
and  ethical  view  of  the  world;  knowledge  is  per- 
fected only  in  the  presupposition  of  one  spirit,  whose 
thought  is  the  source  of  all  being ;  this  is  Idealism, 
but  of  a  kind  that  does  not  block  the  way  to  reality 
(ii.  chaps,  xxii.-xxiii.).  Trendelenburg  concludes  that 
there  is  no  pure  thought,  for  there  is  no  life  without 
intuition  and  the  possibility  of  the  same.  Else  there 
were  no  community  between  thought  and  things.  It 
is  in  this  significance  that  motion,  the  category  of 
which  he  makes  so  much,  appears.  This  original 
activity,  constructive  movement,  is  the  key  to  the 
greatest  results  of  human  knowledge.  He  shows  in 
detailed  form  its  working  in  the  spheres  of  matter 
and  of  spirit. 

Both  the  activity  and  the  influence  of  Trendelen- 
burg were  great.  He  was  not  only  member  of  the 
Royal  Academy,  but  secretary  of  the  History  of 
Philosophy  section,  for  many  years.  Royce  says 
that  since  "  Trendelenburg's  keen  criticism  of  the 
dialectic  method,"  "the  Hegelian  doctrine  has  re- 
ceived less  and  less  attention  in  Germany,  although 
its  indirect  and  unconsciously  effective  influence  has 
been  great"  ('Spirit  of  Modern  Philosophy/  p.  479). 
In  our  own  country,  Martineau  was  much  influenced 
by  Trendelenburg ;  in  America,  many — among  them 


FRIEDRICH   ADOLF  TRENDELENBURG.  121 

Noah  Porter,  F.  E.  Abbot,  G.  S.  Morris  ('Life'  by 
Professor  R.  M.  Wenley) ;  in  Italy,  the  distinguished 
philosopher,  F.  Bonatelli  (who  was  not  without  in- 
fluence from  Ulrici  also);  in  Denmark,  the  cele- 
brated thinker,  S.  Kierkegaard.  Dr  Merz  remarks,  in 
a  footnote,  that  Trendelenburg's  merits  "are  being 
more  and  more  acknowledged  in  the  present  day" 
(op.  cit.,  vol.  iv.  p.  607).  His  wholly  exceptional 
strength  as  an  historical  philosopher  is  universally 
acknowledged,  but  this  was  conjoined  with  great 
insight,  acuteness,  and  systematic  grasp,  as  an  in- 
dependent philosopher. 


122 


CHAPTER  VIII. 

CONCLUSION. 

BEFORE  speaking  of  these  seven  theistic  philoso- 
phers, we  must  glance  for  a  moment  at  the  times  in 
which  their  work  was  set.  The  nineteenth  century 
came  in  with  the  speculation  of  the  great  quadri- 
lateral, Kant,  Fichte,  Schelling,  Hegel.  It  went  out 
with  the  dominance  of  the  empirical  sciences.  The 
idealistic  philosophy  encountered  three  sources  of 
hostility,  all  of  them  of  empiric  character  and 
tendency. 

There  was,  firstly,  Pessimism,  developed  out  of 
Romanticism,  and  finding  expression  in  Schopen- 
hauer (1788-1860),  and  his  quiescence  of  the  will. 
His  influence  became  specially  powerful  after  his 
death,  and  might  have  been  less  if  Lotze's  (1817- 
1881)  position  had  been  a  more  defined  one.  But  in 
Lotze  little  "  wool "  was  too  often  the  result  of  much 
critical  "  cry." 

Then  there  was,  secondly,  the  Sensualistic  An- 
thropologism  of  Feuerbach  (1804-1872),  in  which 
man  was  the  "  superlative."  He,  in  reaction  from  the 


CONCLUSION.  123 

idealistic  dogmatism  of  the  Hegelians,  turned,  as  he 
supposed,  from  abstractions  to  reality,  to  life,  and 
landed  finally  in  materialism.  The  influence  of  the 
materialistic  writers,  chief  among  whom  were  Vogt, 
Moleschott,  and  Biichner,  was  particularly  strong, 
and  endangering  to  Idealism,  in  Germany  in  the 
forties  and  after.  This  natural  science  temper 
found  expression  in  Lange's  'History  of  Material- 
ism' (1866),  in  which  he  took  our  physical  organi- 
sation as  the  only  theoretic  ground  of  explanation 
in  all  human  inquiry,  yet  idealistically  invoked,  on 
the  practical  side,  the  aid  of  poetry,  and  of  religion 
as,  vaguely,  elevation  above  the  actual.  A  some- 
what lame  and  impotent  conclusion  for  the  expen- 
diture of  so  great  an  amount  of  knowledge  and 
acuteness.  The  Positivism  of  Comte  (1798-1857), 
and  the  sensationalist  philosophy  of  Mill  (1806- 
1873)  are  not  now  quoted,  for  they  had  no  influence 
in  Germany  in  the  first  half  at  least  of  the  century. 
Later,  Agnosticism  and  Positivism  were  effective 
enough.  For  then  Positivism  and  Agnosticism 
"claimed  all  man's  interest  and  strength  for  his 
immediate  existence  in  nature  and  society,  and 
relegated  the  world  of  faith  to  an  unknown  Beyond, 
degrading  it  even  to  a  tissue  of  mere  illusions  "  (R. 
Eucken,  '  Hauptprobleme  der  Religionsphilosophie 
der  Gegenwart,'  p.  111).  Or,  to  view  the  matter 
more  from  the  philosophical  point  of  view,  after  the 
idealism  of  Hegel  had  "raised  the  world  to  the 


124  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

plane   of   ideas,"  Positivism   came   along   and   "de- 
stroyed ideas  in  the  facts." 

Then,  thirdly,  there  were,  in  the  second  half  of 
the  century,  the  exact-sciences,  with  their  demands 
for  nature -inquiry,  their  presupposition  of  the  un- 
breakableness  of  mechanical  nature-connection,  and 
their  application  of  Darwinism  in  the  spheres  of 
evolutionary  thought  and  process.  Much  natural 
science  scepticism  had  a  loosening  effect  on  theistic 
conviction.  The  empirical  disintegration  of  person- 
ality was  a  natural  result  of  this  empirical  or 
positivist  reaction.  The  exclusively  empirical  view 
or  conception  of  the  world — a  somewhat  superficial 
one,  it  must  be  said — led  to  complete  forgetfulness 
of  the  great  idealistic  truth  that  Nature  is,  after  all, 
but  a  representation  of  the  ego.  Since  the  human 
mind  "  finds  reason  and  order  in  nature,"  "  it  may 
fairly  conclude  that  nature  itself  is  orderly,  that 
perhaps  after  all,  in  some  faint  way,  natural  law 
has  points  of  likeness  to  legal  ordinance,  and  may 
denote  a  lawgiver.  This  is  not  science,  it  is  meta- 
physics once  more  calling  on  science  to  witness " 
(Whetham's  'Science  and  the  Human  Mind,"  p.  276). 
I  must  be  content  here  to  indicate  these  three 
sources  of  empiric  influence,  without  expanding 
or  dwelling  upon  them,  or  showing  what  philosophy 
has  done,  in  the  return  to  idealism,  in  the  way  of 
freeing  itself  from,  and  raising  itself  above,  any 
prejudicial  results  from  these  empirical  sources  of 


CONCLUSION.  125 

influence.  It  was  just  this  later  bent  towards 
"  empirical  deduction,"  says  Pfleiderer,  that  militated 
against  the  influence  of  Weisse,  for  example,  being 
greater  than  it  was  ('  Development  of  Theology  in 
Germany  since  Kant,'  p.  145).  But  we  have  already 
seen  what  powerful  influence  our  philosophic  group 
exerted  in  countering  deleterious  influences  of  the 
kind,  so  far  as  these  had  developed  in  their  own 
time,  which  was  well  into  the  first  two-thirds  of  the 
century,  and  we  shall  glance  presently  at  the  con- 
tinuation and  expansion  of  the  philosophic  work 
and  influence  inaugurated  by  them.  Such  continu- 
ation and  expansion  were  sorely  needed,  for  the 
times  continued  to  be  impregnated  with  empiricism 
and  scepticism,  influences  from  which  our  own  age 
is  by  no  means  completely  free. 

Not  only  had  all  these  members  of  the  mid- 
nineteenth  century  School  of  Speculative  Theology, 
or  the  Theistic  School  of  Philosophers,  rid  themselves 
of  subservience  to  Hegel — which  is  not  to  say  that 
any  or  all  of  them  had  escaped  influence  by  the  type 
of  idealism  that  had  been  so  dominant — but  every 
one  of  them  made  meritorious  contribution  to  theistic 
world- view,  a  fact  of  great  philosophical  importance 
for  their  period,  and  after.  They  had  clearly  per- 
ceived that  the  differences  between  theistic  and 
pantheistic  world- views  centred  around  the  concept 
or  idea  of  personality,  in  God  and  in  man,  and  the 
personality -concept  they  made  the  corner-stone  of 


126  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

their  theistic  speculation.  Yet  it  is  strange  to  find 
how  very  inadequately  some  leading  philosophical 
writers,  in  our  own  time,  realise  that  the  personality 
of  God  and  the  personality  of  man  must  stand  or 
fall  together.  So  long  ago  as  Lessing,  it  was  said, — 
"  If  I  am,  God  is  also ;  He  may  be  separated  from 
me,  but  not  I  from  Him."  But,  as  has  been, 
conversely,  remarked  on  this,  "  if  God  is  not,  then  I 
am  not ;  if  He  is  no  person,  I  can  no  longer  maintain 
my  personality.  The  man  who  denies  the  personality 
of  God,  undermines  the  foundation  of  His  own. 
Pantheism,  in  doing  this,  swallows  up  God  in  man 
and  man  in  God."  In  a  similar  spirit  to  Lessing, 
W.  Archer  Butler  said, — " '  Cogito  ergo  sum '  was  the 
well-known  postulate  of  Descartes;  to  those  who 
can  reflect,  '  Cogito,  ergo  Deus  est,'  will  not  appear  a 
less  cogent  conclusion  "  ('  Ancient  Philosophy,'  vol.  i. 
p.  57).  The  freedom  and  the  moral  strength  of  man, 
it  cannot  be  too  clearly  realised,  have  their  founda- 
tion in  the  personality  of  God. 

Theistic  world -view,  however,  has  owed  not  a 
little,  in  the  sharpening,  deepening,  defining,  and 
enlarging  of  its  positions,  to  the  influence  of  pan- 
theistic world-views,  while  never  abating  its  claim 
to  occupy  the  higher  ground.  Although  I  have  felt 
obliged  to  confine  myself  to  these  seven  philosophers, 
I  must  note  what  a  plethora  of  representatives — 
many  of  them  theological,  both  Catholic  and  Pro- 
testant— Theism  had  in  their  time,  some  grounding 


CONCLUSION.  127 

their  theistic  philosophy  in  manner  speculative, 
some  in  mode  better  termed  rational,  some  ethical, 
some  supernatural,  and  some  inductive,  but  all  com- 
bining to  prove  the  richness  and  inexhaustible 
vitality  of  Theism,  and  constituting  the  greatest 
movement  in  favour  of  the  personality  of  God  that 
modern  times  have  witnessed.  These  efforts  also 
significantly  made  for  harmony  between  knowledge 
and  faith,  for  profounder  ethical  treatment  of  the 
problems,  and  for  their  elucidation  from  many  sides 
or  points  of  view,  so  advancing  the  philosophy  of 
theism,  and  dispensing  deepening  influences  to 
theology  by  the  way.  Yet  such  are  the  insularity 
and  the  ingratitude  observable,  in  various  ways  and 
at  different  times,  in  much  British  philosophy,  that 
Mr  Clement  Webb,  for  example,  has  felt  able,  in  his 
recent  work  on  '  God  and  Personality/  to  dispense, 
amid  much  historical  reference,  with  even  a  single 
allusion  to  this  very  notable  movement.  Such  a 
significant  omission  adds  nothing  to  the  competency 
of  the  discussion.  I  find  much  in  his  work  with 
which  to  agree,  and  not  a  little  to  admire,  but  from 
his  main  thesis  that  we  must  not  speak  of  the 
personality  of  God,  but  only  of  personality  in  God, 
I  am  in  deep  and  radical  dissent.  Living  and  pro- 
gressive thought  will  never  again  rest  in  this  re- 
actionary attitude ;  his  position  is  as  unsatisfactory 
as  all  half-way  houses  are.  It  is  none  of  the 
business  of  a  philosopher,  when  dealing  with  great 


128  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

problems  like  the  freedom  and  personality  of  God, 
to  move  timidly  along,  under  the  shadowing  influ- 
ence of  past  Confessional  monuments  or  documents, 
but  to  allow  free  and  living  philosophic  thought  to 
solve  the  problems  in  its  own  independent  and  self- 
reliant  way.  Thus  it  will,  in  the  end,  best  serve  the 
interests  of  spiritual  religion.  No  more  will  the 
philosopher,  who  would  satisfactorily  treat  of  "  God 
and  Personality/'  allow  his  thought  to  be  so  com- 
pletely dominated  by  Bradley  and  Bosanquet,  since 
on  this  point  these  eminent  thinkers  are  eminently 
unsatisfactory. 

In  this  connection  I  take  occasion  to  say,  with  a 
broader  reference,  that,  in  my  considered  judgment, 
the  main  peril  and  hindrance  to  British  theistic 
philosophy  to-day  lies  in  the  fact  that  we  have 
systems,  often  loosely  regarded,  even  by  those  who 
ought  to  know  better,  simply  as  theistic,  but  which 
in  reality  consist  of  a  theistic  head  grafted  on  to 
a  pantheistic  body.  As  there  have  always  been 
pantheists  who  were  almost  theists,  and  theists  who 
were  almost  pantheists,  a  philosopher  should  make 
clear  to  himself  and  others  whether  he  is  one  or  the 
other,  if  he  is  to  be  regarded  as  a  consistent  and 
thoroughgoing  thinker.  I  do  not  suggest  that  any, 
or  indeed  all,  of  the  seven  philosophers  here  treated, 
furnished  a  complete,  and,  in  all  respects,  satisfying 
theistic  world- view,  but  they  outlined  the  programme, 
and  went  far  towards  supplying  the  materials  of 


CONCLUSION.  129 

such  a  world-view.  They  would  have  spurned,  as 
palpably  absurd,  the  suggestion  that  rigorous  philo- 
sophical thinking  must  needs  take  pantheistic  form, 
or  be  found  in  pantheistic  systems,  for  it  was 
precisely  their  merit  as  thinkers  that  they  perceived, 
with  varying  clearness  and  correctness,  the  intrinsic 
philosophical  superiority  of  theistic  world-view.  If 
Hegelian  pantheism  is  to  be  forced  upon  us,  as  the 
only  form,  and  necessary  result,  of  rigorous  thinking, 
we  shall  be  compelled  to  ask  if  what  a  once  noted 
English  philosophical  writer  called  "  the  consummate 
trimming  of  Hegel"  has  no  grounds  or  meaning? 
The  truth  is,  Theism  is  the  religious  and  the  philo- 
sophic norm ;  pantheism  is  in  some  sort  a  perversion 
of  it. 

Pantheism  can,  of  course,  be  made  coherent,  con- 
sistent, even  attractive,  but  it  is  and  remains  only 
denaturalised  theism.  Its  Absolute  is  merely  quan- 
titative, the  Absolute  of  Theism  is  qualitative.  For 
the  Infinite  of  pantheism  is  merely  the  All,  but  the 
Infinite  of  theism  is  the  Absolute  Being,  the  perfect 
form  of  Being,  unlimited  in  its  divine  perfections — 
a  notion  perfectly  distinct  from  that  of  the  mere 
totality  of  being.  The  theistic  Absolute  knows  the 
totality  of  all  the  real  to  be  contained  within  Him- 
self. There  cannot  be  anything  outside  the  con- 
sciousness of  the  Absolute;  whatever  is  in  Him; 
of  that  He  is  conscious.  What  is  first  in  the  theistic 
Absolute  comes  last  in  the  God  of  evolutionary 

I 


130  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

pantheism,  a  sufficiently  strong  contrast,  when  it 
has  the  courage  to  declare  itself.  To  the  former, 
God  is  the  Absolute  Personality  from  the  outset, 
and  is  not  conceived  after  the  manner  of  any 
evolving  germ  or  nucleus  analogies,  which  last  make 
far  more  impossible  demands  on  reason  than  any- 
thing to  be  found  in  Theism. 

Theistic  world -view  holds  the  world  to  be 
grounded  in  God,  but  also  grounded  through  God, 
Who  lives  in  it,  but  is  not  measured  by  it.  Pan- 
theistic world -view,  on  the  other  hand,  oscillates 
in  unclear  fashion  between  a  mere  appearance-world 
and  a  rising  of  the  fundamental  essence  in  the  world. 
But  it  does  not  allow  this  essence  to  rule  over  the 
world  as  free  Absolute  Subject  or  Lord  of  all 
being,  but  leaves  Him  to  exist  only  in  the  totality 
of  the  world's  being.  God  appears  not  in  His 
actuality  suffused  with  the  warmth  of  a  Personality 
with  living  content,  but  is  a  mere  schema,  so  far  as 
real  self-determination  is  concerned.  Pantheistic 
thought,  in  its  glorification  of  the  world,  tends  to 
suppress  God,  whose  metaphysical  attributes  it 
takes  to  be  of  no  importance  for  morality.  And,  in 
its  fundamental  presupposition,  the  identification  of 
God  and  the  world,  it  makes,  as  Siebeck  shows,  the 
world  in  its  outstanding  quality  finally  incom- 
prehensible ('Religions -philosophic/  p.  374). 

The  superiority  of  theistic  world-view  is  also 
evidenced  in  its  personal,  or  "I"  and  "Thou," 


CONCLUSION.  131 

relation,  whereby  the  relative  independence  of  the 
self  is  maintained,  and  an  active — not  merely  con- 
templative— attitude  is  engendered.  Theistic  world- 
view  also  stands,  in  its  direction  of  the  whole 
creation  towards  an  end,  for  the  conservation  and 
perpetuation  of  values,  in  a  way  which  pantheism 
does  not,  since  pantheism  excludes  the  universality 
of  value,  or  the  purposiveness  of  the  whole  course 
of  events.  Pantheistic  world -view  concerns  itself 
with  reality  in  general,  rather  than  with  what  is 
concretely  given.  It  thus  comes  into  conflict  with 
this  latter,  which  it  is  prone  to  make  proceed  as  by 
necessity  from  the  grounding  principle.  Theistitf 
world- view,  on  the  other  hand,  in  its  knowledge  of 
the  universe,  rises  from  our  knowledge  of  the 
particular  realities  to  their  ultimate  ground  or 
reason  in  God.  It  "  ascends  into  the  empyrean,  and 
communes  with  the  eternal  essences."  Thus  with 
a  great  poet — 

"  In  contemplation  of  created  things, 
By  steps  we  may  ascend  to  God." 

Such  is  the  path  to  unity  and  totality  in  our  views. 
Thus  is  gained  a  real  Creator  and  Ruler,  not  a 
determinationless  One,  nor  a  mere  necessitated  unity 
of  the  All.  The  pantheistic  view  was  set  out  by 
Strauss,  when  he  entirely  denied  the  existence  of  a 
Divine  consciousness  separate  from  the  human ;  and 
the  copestone  was  laid  on  by  Feuerbach,  when  he 


132  SEVEN   THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

asserted  that,  in  imagining  a  Deity,  man  is  only 
deifying  his  own  nature.  But  it  was  the  superior, 
idealistic  type  of  pantheism  with  which  our  phil- 
osophers were  mainly  concerned. 

When  it  is  said  that  philosophical  influence  passed 
from  the  philosophers  here  treated  to  Lotze,  because 
of  his  being  a  more  systematic  philosopher,  that  can 
be  granted  only  in  a  very  limited  sense.  It  must 
not  be  forgotten  how  much  Lotze,  whose  greatness 
is  not  denied,  occupied  himself  with  individual 
problems,  rather  than  with  the  working  out  of  a 
system,  clear  -  cut,  coherent,  self  -  consistent.  His 
spirit  was  essentially  critical,  and  to  him  a  system, 
as  such,  meant  a  tyranny  over  its  component  parts. 
His  appeal  is  rather  to  experience  than  to  system. 
His  philosophy  is  largely  syncretistic,  and  is  acute 
rather  than  profound.  Nor  should  it  be  overlooked 
how  much  Lotze  owed  to  our  group,  to  Weisse  in 
particular,  and  how  much  he  held  in  common  with 
them — in  the  Personality  of  God  for  example,  and, 
on  evolutionary  and  teleological  process  with  Fichte, 
Ulrici,  and  Trendelenburg.  It  would  be  a  great 
mistake  to  suppose  that  Lotze's  discussion  of  the 
Personality  of  God  made  any  less  necessary  bourdon 
the  discussions  of  that  theme  by  the  thinkers  we 
have  treated,  or  by  other  theistic  thinkers  of  that 
time  who  have  not  come  within  the  scope  of  our 
consideration.  Valuable  as  Lotze's  discussion  is,  it  is 
by  no  means  certain  that  he  felt  the  difficulties  of 


CONCLUSION.  133 

the  subject  more  than  some  others  did,  and  he 
appears  not  to  have  realised  some  of  the  serious 
difficulties  attendant  on  his  own  representations. 
He  also  failed  to  do  full  justice  to  personality  in 
man,  when  he  made  it  a  weak  imitation  or  pale 
semblance  of  personality  in  God,  for  human  per- 
sonality is  indeed  most  real,  albeit  it  may  not 
be  compared  with  personality  in  God. 

He  displayed  a  distinct  lack  of  speculative  depth  in 
respect  of  the  doctrine  of  the  Trinity.  His  system 
suffers  from  his  display  of  the  same  lack  in  his 
performances  on  the  territory  of  the  philosophy  of 
religion,  which  are  marked  by  grave  gaps,  inade- 
quacies, and  superficialities.  Nor  can  one  forget  the 
fatally  subjective  character  of  Lotze's  theory  of 
knowledge.  Scarcely,  then,  does  one  find  a  com- 
pletely satisfactory  theistic  world -view  in  Lotze, 
any  more  than  in  the  group  of  philosophers  just 
considered.  Theistic  world -view  has  advanced  in 
many  respects  since  Lotze's  time  and  theirs,  while 
agreeing  with  him  and  them  in  leaving  behind  the 
mischievous  and  untenable  procedure  of  those  phil- 
osophers who  identified  the  actual  relation  of  God 
to  the  universe  with  the  mental  processes  whereby 
we  come  to  know  Him. 

The  truth  is,  the  personality  -  philosophy  passed 
not  simply  into  the  hands  of  Lotze,  but  broadened 
out  into  influences  like  Schwarz,  Busse,  Wentscher, 
Eucken,  Martineau,  James,  S.  Harris,  B.  P.  Bowne, 


134  SEVEN  THEISTIC   PHILOSOPHERS. 

and  others.  And  of  theistic  world-view,  of  vital 
and  thoroughgoing  character,  I  will  only  now  say 
that  it  is  well  able  to  hold  its  own  against  all  world- 
theories  that  philosophically  come  its  way ;  it  needs 
only  the  full  possession  of  its  own  principles,  as 
grounded  in  eternal  and  immutable  Reason,  to  ensure 
its  sway  over  the  mind  of  the  world  in  its  best  mani- 
festations. For,  as  James  said,  in  what  was  certainly 
not  one  of  his  "brilliant  irresponsibilities,"  but  a 
sober  and  well-grounded  expectation,  we  await  "  that 
ultimate  Weltanschauung  of  maximum  subjective  as 
well  as  objective  richness,  which,  whatever  its  other 
properties  may  be,  will  at  any  rate  wear  the  theistic 
form"  ('Will  to  Believe,'  p.  129). 


INDEX. 


Abbot,  F.  E.,  121 

Absolute,  the,  8-10,  13,  20-21,  32, 

33-34,  38,  39,  42,  57,  64,  71,  94, 

103,  129 
Acosmism,  72 
Adam,  J.,  88 
^Eschylus,  40 
Aesthetics,  28 
Agnosticism,  123 
Anselm,  54-57 

Anthropology,  4,  5,  7,  24,  59,  122 
Anthropomorphism,  35,  39,  61,  66, 

74 

Aquinas,  32 
Aristotle,  110,  119 
Art,  40,  91 
Aseity,  17,  100 
Attributes,  the  Divine,  17,  32,  60, 

102,  130 
Augustine,  43 

Baader,  3,  9,  12,  14,  44,  49,  50,  58, 

63,  64,  67,  79-80,  81-83,  84,  85, 

87-88 

Balfour,  A.  J.,  92 
Bascom,  J.,  44 
Becker,  K.  F.,  110 
Being,  12, 17,  40,  53,  55,  57,  67,  82, 

94,  100,  103,  112,  113,  114,  115, 

129 

Berger,  v.,  110 
Bohme.  9,  11,  12,  29,  80,  82 
Bonatelli,  F.,  121 
Bosanquet,  B.,  128 
Bowne,  B.  P.,  133 
Bradley,  F.  H.,  100,  128 
Brentano,  112 
Buchner,  123 
Burnet,  J.,  88 
Busse,  L.,  133 
Butler,  W.  A.,  126 
Bywater,  I.,  88 


Carriere,  M.,  95 

Causality,  116-118 

Chalybaus,  H.  M.,  3,  49  ;  estimate 
of,  69,  78  ;  system,  69-78  ;  works, 
69-70 

Change,  13-14,  42-43,  95 

Cohen,  H.,  112 

Comte,  123 

Conscience,  107-108 

Consciousness,  20,  34-35 ;  the  Ab- 
solute, 18-20,  33-34,  104,  131  ; 
the  religious,  13,  48-49,  51,  100, 
103 

Cosmology,  87 

Creation,  6,  17-18,  37,  42,  64,  65, 
71,  74,  83,  84,  96,  98-102,  131 

Dante,  98 
Darwin,  105, 124 
Deism,  12,  17,  72 
Descartes,  55,  126 
Determinism,  44,  96 
Deutinger,  1,  44 
Dilthey,  W.,  112 
Dorner,  I.  A.,  1,  68 
Drews,  A.,  18,  59,  61,  62 

Earle,  J.  K,  9 

Eichhorn,  C.,  68 

Eleatics,  the,  52 

Empiricism,  84,  113,  115,  124-125 

Erdmann,  29,  78,  79,  108 

Eternity,  14-16,  43-44,  63-64 

Ethicism,  46-47,  105-106 

Ethics,  4,  59,  69,  77-78,  87,  112 

Eucken,  R.,  112,  123,  133 

Euripides,  73 

Evil,  87 

Experience,  7,  20,  37,  48,  70,  105- 

106,  111,  132 ;  the  Absolute,  34- 

36 


136 


INDEX. 


Fechner,  53,  90 

Feuerbach,  46,  122,  131 

Fichte,  I.  H.,  41,  45,  47,  43,  49,  50, 
62,  63,  64,  65,  68,  71,  80,  105, 
132;  estimate  of,  1-3,  24-26; 
system,  4-24  ;  works,  3-4,  11,  22 
24,  48 

Fichte,  J.  G.,  5,  50,  70,  114,  122 

Fischer,  K.  Ph.,  3,  10,  16,  52; 
estimate  of,  50,59,67-68  ;  system, 
50-67  ;  works,  50,  59-60,  62 

Fischer,  Kuno,  114 

Fraser,  A.  C.,  24 

Freewill,  44,  65,  96,  99,  101,  126 

Galloway,  G.,  54-55,  58 
Gloatz,  P.,  116 
Giinther,  1,  71,  77 

Haeckel,  105 
Hamberger,  J.,  88 
Harris,  S.,  133 
Hartmann,  18,  62,  82 
Hegel,  2,  3,  5,  6,  10,  27,  28,  29,  31, 
35,  47,  48,  49,  50,  52,  56,  57,  62, 

69,  71,  74,  90-91,  101,  102,  112, 
114,  117,  122,  123,  125 

Heraclitus,  88 

Herbart,  5,  6,  74,  111,  116 

History  of  Philosophy,  the,  24-25, 

58-59,  t>9 

Hoffding,  H.,  25,  62-63 
Hoffmann,  Fr.,  3,  12;  estimate  of, 

79-80,  88  ;  system,  80-84,  87-88 ; 

works,  79-80,  83 
Hugo,  Victor,  58 

Idealism,  2,  30,  67,  74,  91,   113, 

120,  123,  124 
Immortality,  6,  12,  45-47 
Individuality,  6,  23,  39,  65 

James,  W.,  133,  134 
Janet,  P.,  101,  102 

Kant,  6,  7,  49,  53,  56,  69,  84,  85, 
87,  93-94,  108,  111,  112,  113, 
114,  115,  116,  119,  122,  125 

Kierkegaard,  S.,  121 

Kleutgen,  56, 

Knowledge,  theory  of,  7,  52,  69, 

70,  93,  133 
Konig,  E.,  117 
Krause,  86 


Kym,  112 

Laas,  E.,  115 

Lange,  F.  A.,  123 

Laurie,  S.  S.,  15 

Leibniz  5,  11,  28,  29,  32,  52,  82 

Lessing,  126 

Lindsay,  J.,  works  by,  5,  16,  45  ; 

articles  by,  11,  105 
Logic,  48,  59,  87,  91 
Lotze,  22,  27,  28,  45,  75,  90,  106, 

114,122,132-133 
Lutterbeck,  A.,  88 

Martensen,  12 

Martineau,  J.,  113,  120,  133 

Materialism,  72,  73,  84,  123 

Mathematics,  31,  115 

Matter,  42,  72,  87 

Merz,  J.  T.,  4,  111,  123 

Metaphysics,  6,  12,  28-29,  37,  39, 

45-47,  124 
Mill,  J.  S.,  Ill,  123 
'Mind, '54 
Moleschott,  123 
'  Monist,  The,'  11,  105 
Morris,  G.  S. ,  121 
M'Taggart,  J.  E.,  46-47 
Mulford,  E.,  118 
Mysticism,  87 

Nature,  18,  40,  73,  75,  80,  88,  89, 

92,124 

Neo-Platonism,  87 
Nitzsch,  C.  I.,  68 

Oetinger,  49 

Oken,  50,  52 

Ontological  argument,  the,  53-fi8 

Ontology,  3,  31.  34,  48,  72,  102 

Optimism,  23-24 

Panen theism,  86 

Pantheism,  1,  7,  13,  14,  17,  18,  22, 
24,  40,  42,  52,  69,  72,  75,  83,  85, 
88,  90,  93,  97,  98,  126,  129,  130, 
131,  132 

Paulsen,  F.,  4 

Personality,  20,  22,  33,  44,  65,  66, 
75,  124,  125;  of  God,  1,  3,  20, 
32,  37,  38,  39,  41,  60,  65-66,  67, 
83,  99,  102,  103,  125,  126,  127, 
128,  130,  132  ;  of  Man,  20,  22, 
66,  124,  125,  126,  133 


INDEX. 


137 


Pessimism,  122 

Pfleiderer,  0.,  49,  125 

Physics,  87 

Physiology,  23 

Plato,  53,  110 

Porter,  Noah,  121 

Positivism,  123-124 

Pringle-Pattison,  A.  S.,  33-38,  57, 

96-97,  99-104 
Psychology,  4,  6,  22,  104,  106 

Bashdall,  H.,  36 

Rationalism,  10-11,  18 

Realism,  74,  82,  90,  114 

Reinhold,  110 

Relativity,  19,  101,  117 

Religion,  philosophy  of,  12,  44,  48- 

49,  60,  106,  123,  130,  132 
Revelation,  44 
Rickert,  H.,  105 
Romanticism,  122 
Rothe,  R.,  1, 14,  25,  38,  40,  42,  49, 

61,  98,  103 
Royce,  J.,  46,  120 

Schaden,  E.  A.,  v.,  84 

Schelling,  3,  10,  12,  27,  44,  50,  52, 

62,  66,  73,  82,  83,  87-88,  97,  113, 
114,  116, 122 

Schenkel,  107 

Schleiermacher,  42,  52 

Scholasticism,  87 

Schopenhauer,  62,  82,  113,  122 

Schwarz,  C.,  25,  68 

Schwarz,  H.,  133 

Science,  73,  91-93,  111,   115,  118, 

123,  124 
Self-consciousness,  Divine,  9,   16- 

17,  18-19,  33,  48,  64,  75,  76,  95, 

131  ;  human,  33,  35,  48,  51,  70, 

76,  85,  131 

Sengler,  J.,  1,  3,  52,  66 
Seydel,  R.,  28,  49 
Shakespeare,  100 
Sidgwick,  H.,  45 
Siebeck,  H.,  130 
Sociology,  87 
Soul,  the,  11,  22-26,  73,  74,  104, 

105,  106 

Space,  13,  42-43,  113,  114 
Speculative  School,  1,  125 
Speculative  Theology,  3,  6-21,  48- 

49,  51,  57,  60  70,  79-80,  125 
Spinoza,  52 


Stahl,  106 
Steudel,  75 
Stirling,  J.  H.,  102 
Strauss,  131 
Substance,  116-117 

TeichmUller,  112 

Teleology,  2,  20-21,  116,  118-119 

Tennyson,  70 

Theism,  2,  3,  6,  19,  23,  25,  40,  49, 

50,  51,  52,  59,  75,  78,  86,  90,  92- 

93,  103,  104,  118,  125-128,  129, 

130,  133,  134 
Thilly,  F.,  4 
Thought,  8,  53,  55,  56,  71,  74,  85, 

86,  91,  111,  113,  114,  115,  120, 

127 

Time,  13-16,  42-43,  64,  65, 113, 114 
Transcendentalism,  87 
Trendelenburg,  F.  A.,  3,  48,  132  ; 

estimate   of,    110-112,    120-121; 

system,  110-120  ;  works,  110-112 
Trinity,  the,  33,  39,  40-41,  60,  67, 

133 
Troeltsch,  47 

Ueberweg  -  Heinze  -  Oesterreich, 
:  Hist,  of  Philosophy,'  25 

Ulrici,  H.,  3,  41,  121,  132;  esti- 
mate of,  90-91,  108-109  ;  system, 
91-108  ;  works,  91-92,  104,  107 

Value,  55,  58,  105,  131 
Vogt,  123 
Voluntarism,  10-11 

Wagner,  R.,  23 

Ward,  J.,  56 

Webb,  C.  C.  J.,  127 

Weisse,  C.  H.,  3,  6-7,  9,  10,  16,  25, 
50,  60,  62,  65,  68,  103,  132 ;  esti- 
mate of,  27-28,  49 ;  system,  28- 
49 ;  works,  28-29 

Wenley,  R.  M.,  121 

Wentscher,  133 

Whetham,  124 

Wirth,  J.  U.,  3,  52 

World,  the,  18,  21,  24,  75,  82,  98- 
99,  101, 102,  130 

World-Ground,  7,  12,  20,  63 

World-View,  Theistic,  2,  3,  7,  22, 
25,  98,  125,  128-131,  133,  134 

'Zeitschrift  fur  Philosophic,"  3. 
18,  20,  29,  60,  78,  83,  92 


PRINTED    BY   WILLIAM    BLACKWOOD   AND   SONS. 


RETURN  TO  the  circulation  desk  of  any 
University  of  California  Library 

or  to  the 

NORTHERN  REGIONAL  LIBRARY  FACILITY 
Bldg.  400,  Richmond  Field  Station 
University  of  California 
Richmond,  CA  94804-4698 

ALL  BOOKS  MAY  BE  RECALLED  AFTER  7  DAYS 

•  2-month  loans  may  be  renewed  by  calling 
(510)642-6753 

•  1  -year  loans  may  be  recharged  by  bringing 
books  to  NRLF 

•  Renewals  and  recharges  may  be  made  4 
days  prior  to  due  date. 

DUE  AS  STAMPED  BELOW 


SEP  2  5 1997 


12,000(11/95) 


YC136274 


UNIVERSITY  OF  CALIFORNIA  LIBRARY 


:    •'    •.->;#: