Skip to main content

Full text of "Socialism in theory and practice"

See other formats


Google 



This is a digital copy of a book that was preserved for generations on Hbrary shelves before it was carefully scanned by Google as part of a project 

to make the world's books discoverable online. 

It has survived long enough for the copyright to expire and the book to enter the public domain. A public domain book is one that was never subject 

to copyright or whose legal copyright term has expired. Whether a book is in the public domain may vary country to country. Public domain books 

are our gateways to the past, representing a wealth of history, culture and knowledge that's often difficult to discover. 

Marks, notations and other maiginalia present in the original volume will appear in this file - a reminder of this book's long journey from the 

publisher to a library and finally to you. 

Usage guidelines 

Google is proud to partner with libraries to digitize public domain materials and make them widely accessible. Public domain books belong to the 
public and we are merely their custodians. Nevertheless, this work is expensive, so in order to keep providing this resource, we liave taken steps to 
prevent abuse by commercial parties, including placing technical restrictions on automated querying. 
We also ask that you: 

+ Make non-commercial use of the files We designed Google Book Search for use by individuals, and we request that you use these files for 
personal, non-commercial purposes. 

+ Refrain fivm automated querying Do not send automated queries of any sort to Google's system: If you are conducting research on machine 
translation, optical character recognition or other areas where access to a large amount of text is helpful, please contact us. We encourage the 
use of public domain materials for these purposes and may be able to help. 

+ Maintain attributionTht GoogXt "watermark" you see on each file is essential for informing people about this project and helping them find 
additional materials through Google Book Search. Please do not remove it. 

+ Keep it legal Whatever your use, remember that you are responsible for ensuring that what you are doing is legal. Do not assume that just 
because we believe a book is in the public domain for users in the United States, that the work is also in the public domain for users in other 
countries. Whether a book is still in copyright varies from country to country, and we can't offer guidance on whether any specific use of 
any specific book is allowed. Please do not assume that a book's appearance in Google Book Search means it can be used in any manner 
anywhere in the world. Copyright infringement liabili^ can be quite severe. 

About Google Book Search 

Google's mission is to organize the world's information and to make it universally accessible and useful. Google Book Search helps readers 
discover the world's books while helping authors and publishers reach new audiences. You can search through the full text of this book on the web 

at |http : //books . google . com/| 







I 



r 



i 



SOCIALISM IN THEORY AND 

PRACTICE 



THE BCACMILLAN COMPANY 

MKW YORK • BOSTON • CHICAGO 
ATLANTA • SAN FSANOSCO 

MACMILLAN & CO., Limitbd 

LONDON • BOMBAY • CALCUTTA 
MBLBOURNB 

THE MACMILLAN CO. OF CANADA, Ltd. 

TORONTO 



SOCIALISM IN THEORY 
AND PRACTICE 



BV 

MORRIS HILLQUIT 

AUTHOR OF ** HISTORY OF SOCIAUSM IN THX UNTTBD STATES" 









JNtlD gont 

THE MACMILLAN COMPANY 

1909 



Copyright, 1909, 
By the MACMILLAN COMPANY. 



Set np and electrotyped. Published February, 1909. Reprinted 
March. x,o, I20*i99 









•• i • • • 

• • •• • • 

• • • • • • • 

• • • • *• • 



• • • • 






.•% 



• • 



• • • 
• • • • 



• • » • 



• « • 

• •• 

• • » 

• • • • 

• • • 



• • • 

• « « 









• • •! 






• • • « 1 



'• « 



• • •• • • 

• • • 

• • • • • i 
' • • •• 

• • • • • 



• • • 
• • • 



• • I 

• • • 



Carina oti ^rtffS 

J. S. Cashing Co. —Berwick & Smith Co. 

Norwood, Mass., U.S.A. 



PREFACE 

The socialist movement has grown immensely within 
the last decade, and its growth still continues unabated 
in all civilized countries of the world. What is the 
secret of that growth ; what are the aims and methods 
of the movement; and what does it portend for the 
future of the human race ? These are questions which 
persons of intellect can ignore no longer, and they are 
questions which cannot be answered without much 
thought and study. 

In this book I have endeavored to present to the 
public a brief summary of the socialist philosophy in its 
bearing on the most important social institutions and 
problems of our time, and a condensed account of the 
history, methods, and achievements of the socialist 
movement of the world. 

Socialism is a criticism of modem social conditions, 
a theory of social progress, an ideal of social organiza- 
tion, and a practical movement of the masses. To be 
fully understood it must be studied in all of these phases, 
and the fact that this book is probably the first attempt 
to accomplish that task, inadequate as that attempt may 
be, is sufficient justification for its publication. 

Grateful acknowledgment is hereby made for many 
valuable suggestions which I have received from Mr. 
W. J. Ghent, who has carefully read the proofs, and from 
Mr. Rufus W. Weeks, who has read the manuscript. 

MORRIS HILLQUIT. 
New York, January zo, 2909. 






» ■ 



• /'-i', 



CONTENTS 
PART I 

THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

CHAPTER I 

PAGS 

iMTRODUCnON 3 

CHAPTER 11 

Socialism and Individualism 

The SjTStem of Individualism 12 

The Individual and Society 18 

Individualism in Industry 24 

The Individual under Socialism 29 

CHAPTER III 

Socialism and Ethics 

The Essence and Scope of Ethics 36 

The Evolution of the Moral Sense 46 

Class Ethics 52 

The Ethical Ideal and Socialist Morality . • . • 58 

CHAPTER IV 

Socialism and Law 

The Law 66 

The Feudal System of Law 72 

The Modem System of Law 78 

Social Legislation and Socialist Jurisprudence ... 84 

• • 

Vll 



vm 



CONTENTS 



CHAPTER V 

Socialism and the Stats 

FAGS 

Nature and Evolation of the State 89 

The Transitional State 100 

The Socialist State 105 

Production and Distribution of Wealth under Socialism • .111 
Incentive under Socialism • . . . • • .119 
The Political Structure of the Socialist State . . • • 131 



CHAPTER VI 

Sociausm and Politics 

Politics, Representative Government and Political Parties 

Classes and Class Strug^es in Modem Society 

The Class Struggles in Politics 

The Socialist Party in Politics 

Electoral Tactics of the Socialist Party . 

Parliamentary Tactics of the Socialist Party 

Political Achievements of Socialism 



144 

153 
161 

168 

174 
181 

190 



PART II 



SOCIAUSM AND REFORM 



CHAPTER I 
Introduction — Socialists and Social Reformers 

CHAPTER II 

The Industrial Reform Movements 

Industrial Reform 

Factory Reform 

Shorter Workday 

Child Labor . 

Woman Labor 

The Trade Union Movement 

Codpetative Societies of Workingmen 




^ 



214 
215 
218 
224 
231 
236 
242 



CONTENTS IX 
CHAPTER in 

PAGB 

WORKINGMEN^S INSURANCE 254 

CHAPTER IV 

The Political Reform Movements 

Political Reform 269 

UDiversal Suf&age 272 

ProportioDal RepresentatioD 274 

Referendum, Initiative and Right of Recall . . • . 277 

Socialism and Woman Suffrage 281 

CHAPTER V 

Administrative Reforms 

Government Ownership 284 

Tax Reforms 288 

The Single Tax 291 

Abolition of Standing Armies 296 

CHAPTER VI 

Social Reform 

Crime and Vice 303 

Intemperance 309 

The Housing of the Poor 314 

APPENDIX 

Historical Sketch of the Socialist Movement 

Early History 320 

Germany 335 

France . . 337 

Russia .•..•••... 340 

Austria 345 

England 346 

Italy 348 

Belgium and Holland 349 

The Scandinavian Countries ...... 350 

United States 351 

The New International 354 

Index 357 



PART I 

THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



CHAPTER I 

INTRODUCTION 

The history of our civilization presents one unbroken 
chain of social changes. The interval between the primi- 
tive tribe of cave-dwellers and modem industrial society 
is filled with a variety of intermediate social types. 

Each of these types constitutes a separate phase of 
civilization. Within the same civilization each type is 
superior to the one preceding it, and inferior to the one 
succeeding it. Each phase of civilization is evolved from 
the preceding phase and gives birth to the succeeding phase. 
Each phase of civilization passes through the stages of 
formation, bloom, and decay. 

The present phase of our civilization forms no excep- 
tion to this inmiutable rule of social development. We 
have reached a state vastly superior to all conditions of the 
past. Men in modem society on the whole enjoy more 
individual freedom and security, more physical comforts 
and intellectual and aesthetic pleasures than did the sav- 
ages and members of societies based on slavery or serf- 
dom. 

But we have not reached perfection. We never shall 
reach perfection. A state of perfection in society would 
imply the arrest of all hmnan endeavors and progress, the 

3 



' death of civilization. It is improvement, not perfection, 
ifor which we are striving, and our contemporary social 
lorganization is capable of improvement just as all societies 
of the past were. 

Our social order of to-day did not spring into existence 
suddenly and full-fledged. It developed gradually from 
preceding social conditions, and it is still in process of 
evolution. It has had its period of formation, and the 
socialists contend that it has passed its period of bloom. 
It has entered on the stage of decay and must be followed 
by a new phase of civilization of a more advanced type. 

The all-important factor in modem society is industry. 
In former ages industry — that is, production of goods for 
exchange — played a rather subordinate part in the lives 
of the nations. Agriculture was the basis of the com- 
munity. 

But recent times, and pari:icularly the last century, have 
witnessed a stupendous industrial growth. The modest 
workshop of former ages has been superseded by the huge 
modem factory; the simple, almost primitive tool of the 
old-time mechanic has developed into the gigantic machine 
of to-day; and the power of steam and electricity has 
increased the productivity of labor a hundred fold. New 
objects of use have been invented, new needs have been 
created, while the railroads, steamships and other im- 
proved means of communication and distribution have 
united the entire civilized world into one intemational 
market. 

This industrial revolution has brought in its wake a 
radical change of social institutions. It has created new 
classes of society. The privileged type of former ages, 
the landowning and titled nobleman, the courtier and 




i 



mTRODUCTION 

traxrior, has been relegated to the background, and in his 
place has arisen the captain of industry — the modem 

capitalist. 

With the ancient aristocracy have also disappeared the 
ancient types of the dependent class, the slave and the 
serf, and their place has been tai^en by the modem wage 
worker. 

In the earlier stages of its career the capitalist class was 
revolutionary and useful. It abolished absolute monarch- 
ies and introduced modem representative government, it 
rooted out old prejudices and beliefs, it tore down the arti- 
ficial barriers between nations, it gave to the world the 
most marvelous inventions, and ushered in a distmctly 
superior system of society. ' 

But these achievements belong largely to the pioneer 
days of capitalism, to the period when the modem indus- 
tries were in process of formation. To-day our prin- 
cipal industries are fully organized. They have largely 
been reduced to mere routine and their progress depends 
but little on individual initiative. - - — 

The typical capitalist of to-day has long ceased to be 
the manager of the industries. He is "engaged" in what- 
ever industry the vicissitudes of the stock market and the 
tricks of stock Jobbery may thrust upon him. It may 
happen to be a railway system or a gas plant, a mine or a 
steel foundry, a rubber factory or water works, or all of 
them in turn. He need not know, and as a rule he does 
not know, the intimate workings of the mdustry he controls. 
The actual work of management and operation is done by 
hired labor, whether such labor be that of the high-priced 
superintendent or that of a common laborer employed 
at starvation wages. There is hardly a capitalist to-day 



I 



■whose existence is necessary to the continuance of any 
essential industry. The days of the actual usefulness of 
the capitalist class in the social economy of the nation are 
rapidly passing. And like so many other classes in history 
under similar conditions, the capitalists have become 
reactionary, and the regime developed by them has be- 
come irrational, unjust and oppressive. 

In the merciless war of competition the big capitalist 
enterprises are gradually extinguishing the smaller inde- 
pendent concerns. Our "national" wealth and principal 
industries concentrate in the hands of ever fewer combines. 
Trusts and monopolies are becoming the modem form of 
industrial organization. A new capitalist type is thus de- 
veloped, the type of the trust magnate and multi-million- 
aire. 

But the large masses of the people share but little in 
the benefits of this imprecedentcd growth of wealth. 
While a certain portion of the working class, the trained 
or skilled laborers, probably enjoy to-day larger material 
comforts than did their ancestors in the past, the increase 
of then- comforts does not keep pace with the increase of 
the general productivity and wealth. The condition of 
this favored class of the working population is one of 
absolute improvement but of relative deterioration. And 
side by side with the more fortunate strata of the working 
class there are the large masses of laborers whose conditions 
of life have greatly deteriorated, absolutely as well as 
relatively. Millions of workingmen maintain themselves 
with difficulty above the bare margin of starvation, while 
large masses of the population, rendered "superfluous" 
by the invention of improved machinery, are driven to 
vagabondage and forced into the paths of vice and crime. 



The boundless luxuries of the few find their logical coun- 
terpart in the dire misery of the many. 
^- In the mad capitalist race for profits, morals are useless 
_. and cumbersome ballast. (The— earlier merchant and|/-_ 
manufacturer had some sense of commercial pcobity, -Thcj- ] 
"mipdem trust magnate has JioRe:! To him all m'eans are ' 
fair so long as they satisfy his greed. His ideal is to in- 
crease his power, to get possession of all the sources of 
wealth of his coimtry, to own his fellow-men, body and 
soul. — 

To reach this aim he corrupts legislatures, buys courts 
of justice, bribes public officials and pollutes the public 
press, 

The "interests of industry" — his interests — shape the 
entire life of modem nations. They influence our laws, 
dominate our politics, direct our public opinion, determine 
our internal and external policy, and decide upon war and 
peace between nations. The trust magnate is a more 
dangerous potentate than any political despot. — 

And these conditions are not mere accidental abuses; 
they are the necessai-y results of our industrial institutions. 
Even the beneficiaries of these institutions are without 
power to change them. The capitalists are driven into 
the fatal course by the inexorable laws of industrial de- 
velopment. We may well foresee a time, if the present 
order lasts long enough, when practically all of our most 
important industries will have become trusts, when the 
entire wealth of the nations and all the powers of govern- 
ment will be in the hands of a small number of monopolists, 
and when the people will depend upon them absolutely 
for their physical, inteUeclual and moral existence. 

Such conditions are not unparalleled in history. The 



^^iSuch 



i 

I 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AMD MOVEMENT 

P 110111311 Empire found itself in such a situation in the 
fourth and fifth centuries of our era, and Roman civihza- 
tion succumbed. France faced a similar crisis thirteen 
hundred years later, but the French nation suppressed the 
dangerous order and built a better and more vigorous 
society on its ruins. 

Will the modem nation share the fate of Rome, or fol- 
low the example of France? 

I y" The answer to this momentous question is contained in 

l^jhe question itself. 

Rome perished for the lack of a class to save it. The 
'slaves were beyond the pale of Roman society, and the 
proletarians of the capital and the provinces were too 
ignorant, demoralized and feeble to combat the greedy and 
profligate patricians. The degenerate Roman population 

I fell an easy prey to the advancing barbarian hordes. 
In France, on the other hand, the haughty and parasitic 
nobility was confronted by the men of science, industry, 
commerce and labor, the vigorous and intelligent "third 
estate." The "third estate" saved France, even thoughj 
the salvation was accomplished at the cost of a revolution. 
Modem society has developed a new "third estate, " — 
the industrial working class. The working class to-day is 
the principal social power operating against the formation 
of a capitalist oligarchy. And it is a power to be reckoned 
with. The modem workingmen are not the helots of 
ancient Greece, nor the proletarians of ancient Rome, nor 
the serfs of mediaeval ages. They are more intelligent 
and better organized than any dependent class in the past : 
their conditions of existence and instinct of self-preserva- 
tion naturally array them against the present system -of 
exploitation of labor, and force them into active resistance 



INTRODUCnON 



igainst it. As capitalism grows more acute and menac- 
ing, the cohorts of labor become more unified, powerful 
and aggressive, and more fully able and determined to 
carry their struggles to victory. 

Only half a century ago the labor movement was barely 
in its inception, weak in numbers, inefficient in organiza- 
tion and uncertain in its aims. To-day the working- 
men are organized in legions of powerful trade unions, 
trained and drilled in the everyday battles for the advance- 
ment of their conditions of life. In a large number of 
countries they have created immense cooperative estab- 
lishments successfully competing with the capitalist enter- 
prises in the same industries. In all civilized countries of 
the world they have developed a socialist movement, so 
uniform in its aims and methods, so persistent in its 
struggles, so inspiring in its propaganda and so irresistible 
in its spread, that with perhaps the single exception of 
early Christianity the movement stands unparalleled in the 
s of written history. 
The trade unions fight the immediate and particular 

lattles of the workers in the factories, mills, mines and 
^ops, and educate their members to a sense of their 
economic rights. The cooperative labor enterprises train 
their members in the collective operation and democratic 
management of industries. The socialist parties emphasize 
the general and ultimate interests of the entire working 
class, and train their members in political action and 
in the administration of the affairs of government and 
_ state. 

Marching over different routes, operating with different 

Methods and conscious or unconscious of the effects of 

^eir own activity, all these forms of the labor movement 



TO THE SOCXALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

make for one inevitable goal : the building up of a new 
and regenerated society, 

And the workingmen are not alone in this movement. 
They receive large and ever larger accretions from all 
other classes — from the small business men displaced 
by the trust, the professionals reduced to the state of 
"intellectual proletarians"; the farmers, exploited less 
directly but not less effectively by trustified capital, and 
even from the ranks of the capitalist class itself. The 
number of men of the "belter classes" who embrace the 
cause of the people from motives of enlightened self- 
interest or from purely ethical motives grows as the evils 
of the decaying capitalist system become more apparent. 
These "desertions"from the ranks of the dominant classes 
into the camp of the subjugated class, are an infallible sign 
of the approaching collapse of the rule of the former. 

The economic development which has thus furnished 
the conditions for a radical transformation of society and 
produced the forces to accomplish it, is also building up 
the basis of that transformation. 

The great modem trust organizes industry on a national 
scale; it regulates the production and distribution of 
commodities, and brings all workers of the country under 
one administration, A trustified industry is in its essence 
a nationalized industry. It would be Just as easy to-day 
for a governmental agency to run such an industry as it is 
for the individual trust magnates or their agents. 

And it would be much more just. Our highly effective 
system of industry is the achievement of many generations, 
the heritage of all mankind ; our marvelous tools of pro- 
duction and distribution are the fruit of the collective 
industry and intellect of the laboring population ; they are 



INTRODUCTION 1 1 

operated collectively by the whole working class, and they 
are indispensable to the life of the entire nation. In equity 
and justice the capitalist has no better title to the modem 
social tools than the slaveholder had to his chattel slaves. 
Socialism advocates the transfer of ownership in the 
social tools of production — the land, factories, machinery, 
railroads, mines, etc. — from the individual capitalists 
to the people, to be operated for the benefit of all. 

This program has been denounced as confiscatory and 
revolutionary, but it is no more so than was the abolition 
of chattel slavery^ It has been ridiculed as Utopian and 
fantastic, but it is no more so than the demands of the 
eighteenth century capitalist for the abolition of the privi- 
leges of birth were to his contemporaries. 

Our social progress is a movement towards perfect 
democracy. The successive stages of our civilization mark 
the disappearance of one class privilege after another. 
Why should mankind halt in reverence and awe before the 
privilege of wealth? When an heir to millions is bom 
to-day, he has the same exceptional position in society and 
the same power over thousands of his fellow-men that the 
newborn duke or marquis had in times past; and the 
justice and logic of the situation are the same in both cases. 
A true democracy is one in which all babes are bom alike, 
and all human beings enjoy the same rights and oppor- 
timities. 




Socialism and individualism are the two main contend- 
ing principles underlying all modern social theories and 
movements. Both ideas are, comparatively speaking, 
new in the history of human thought, and the social 
philosophy based on individualism is the older of the two, 
Some writers discern the origin of the idea of individualism 
in the movement of the Reformation, and its first practical 
application in the demand for liberty of the conscience, 
i.e., the religious self-determination of the individual. 
The idea of religious liberty according to the noted Russian 
scholar, Peter Struve, led to the broader conception of the 
liberty of the individual, and the latter to the theory of 
political self-government of the nations. 

"In connection with the idea of the self-determination 
of the individual," he observes, "the idea of the self- 
government of society originates in the same surround- 
ings and under the same conditions and becomes a mov- 
ing force. In the study of the events and ideas of the 
English revolution of the seventeenth century, nothing is 
more striking than the fact that that wonderful period 
produced, as with one blow and in quite finished form, the 
idea of individual liberty, liberalism, as well as the idea 
of political self-government, democracy." ' 

The theory is no doubt historically true, but it utterly 

"Individualism i Socialism," Polyarnaya Zvesda, No. ii. 



fails to account for the causes of the phenomenon. The 
religious movement of the Reformation was one of the 
manifestations of the struggle for individualism, but not its 
cause. The Reformation and the nascent idea of indi- 
vidualism involved in it were but the symptoms and results 
of a deeper and more material process — the birth of the 
modem social and industrial system. 

The modem philosophy of individualism came into life 
as a reaction against the excessive centralization of the 
feudal state and church, and as a protest against the un- 
checked powers of the crown, nobility and clergy over the 
population, and especially over the growing class of in- 
dustrials. "Individual Liberty" was the battle cry with 
which the young bourgeoisie (the industrial and trading 
class) entered the arena of political struggle. That 
battle cry meant for it freedom of competition — Industrial 
Liberty; the right to use the powers of the state for the 
advancement of manufacture and commerce — Political 
Liberty ; the freedom from interference by the church with 
the political and industrial management of the people — 
Religious Liberty ; and above aU it meant the freedom and 
sacredness of private property. "What they (the liberal; 
bourgeois) meant by the freedom of the individual," says > 
Mr. E. Belfort Bax, "was, first and foremost, the liberty 
of private property as such, to be controlled in its operation 
by naught else than the will of the individual possessing it. 
What was cared for was not so much the liberty of the 
individual as the liberty of private property. The liberty 
of the individual as such was secondary. It was as the 
possessor and controller of property that it was specially 
desired to assure his liberty." ' 
J"Socialismand Individualism," London, PetsooalRiglitsSeries, p. la 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



The idea of individual liberty thus conceived animates 
all phases of the struggle of the bourgeoisie against feudal 
society. It is at the bottom of Rousseau's "Social Con- 
tract" and the social philosophy of the Encyclopedists; 
it asserts itself in the principle of non-interference pro- 
claimed by Adam Smith and the founders of classical 
political economy ; and it is the true meaning of the ra- 
tionalistic criticisms of Voltaire and his followers. 

Individual liberty with or without other verbal adorn- 
ments was the motto that inspired the battles of the English 
middle classes under Cromwell towards the end of the 
seventeenth century, and those of the French "third estate" 
and the American colonists a century later. 

"All men are bom and continue free," ' and "All men 
are endowed by their Creator with the 'inalienable right' 
of liberty," * were the maxims adopted as the foundation 
of all political constitutions by the victorious bourgeoisie 
of all countries. 

The battles fought by the pre-Revolutionary bourgeoisie 
in the name of Individual Liberty have given to civiliza- 
tion a few great acquisitions. They have to a large extent 
emancipated man in the purely individual sphere of his 
life, and rendered into his own keeping his beliefs, views 
and tastes, his individual mind and soul. The freedom 
of press, speech, conscience and person are such acquisi- 
tions, and they are of everlasting benefit to mankind. 

But the historical watchword had an altogether different 
fate in the field of politics and industry. 

In the revolutionary period of the career of our ruling 
"Individual Liberty" in those fields stood princi- 

' French Dec1ara.tioa of the Rights of Man. 
* American Declaration of IndepcDdeace. 



SOCIALISM AND INDIVIDUALISM 



IS 




I mg 



.ly for freedom from arbitrary political, industrial and 
restraint, but with the fall of feudalism and the 
loval of feudal restraints, the phrase lost its original 
:cance. The manufacturing and trading classes, as ' 
the struggling and subjected bourgeois of the seventeenth 
and eighteenth centuries, appealed to the sacred right of 
^individual freedom as a means to deiiver them from the 
ppression of the ruling classes of their time ; but the pos- i 
;ing classes of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, 
lemseives in power and confronting a new dependent 

the class of wage workers, invoke the old god of their , 
ithers only in order to strengthen their own rule. The 
[dividual Liberty" of the modern capitalist has come 
largely to stand for the right to deal with his employees i 
BS he pleases, the unrestricted right to exploit men, women I 
and children of the working class, and to be free from the 
interference of the state in his process of exploitation. An. 
economic order based entirely on the principles of " laissez- 
faire," and a political organization of the type characterized i 
by Huxley as "Administrative Nihilism" are the ideals of 
the modem priests of the god "Individual Liberty." 
In the hands of the capitalist individual liberty has de- 
generated into individual license, its philosophy is that of 
shortsighted egoism. The most consistent and logical 
representative of that philosophy is probably Max Stirner, 
whose work, "The Ego and His Own," has only recently, 
more than sixty years after its first appearance, been placed 
before the English-reading bourgeois to be acclaimed by 
them with unbounded delight. The views of that philoso- 
pher of individualism may be summed up in the follow- 
ing two brief quotations from the work mentioned : — 
"Away then with every concern that is not altogether 



l6 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

my concern! You think at least 'the good cause' must 
be my concern. What's good and what's bad I Why, I 
myself am my concern, and I am neither good nor bad. 
Neither has meaning for me. 

"The divine is God's concern; the human man's. 
My concern is neither the divine nor the human, not the 
true, good, just, free, etc., but solely what is mine, and it 
is not a general one, but is unique, as I am unique. 

" Nothing is more to me than myself." ' 

And again: — 

"Every state is a despotism, be the despot one or (as 
one is likely to imagine about a republic), if all be the lords, 
i.e., despotize one over the other." ' 

And in this extreme view of individual freedom the liberal 
capitalists find themselves entirely in accord with the 
radical anarchists. Both would rob society of all its 
social functions. Both base their philosophy on individual 
competition and the brutal struggle for existence rather 
than on the prindple of human cooperation, both make an 
idol of individual liberty, both suffer from a morbid exag- 
geration of the Ego, and both sanction all means to attain 
the end of individual happiness. 

The only difference between the conservative and patri- 
1 otic capitalist and the violent anarchist is that the former 
' represents the "individualism" of the rich, and the latter 
that of the poor. 

The philosophy of individualism supplies a moral and 
pseudo-scientific sanction for the economic struggle be- 
tween man and man, and appeals to the different classes of 
the population favorably or imfavorably according to their 

' Mai Stirncr, "The Ego and His Own," New York, 1907, p. 5. 



SOCIAUSM AND INDIVIDUAUSM 17 

chances and position in that struggle. The ruling classes 
with their overwhelming economic powers are best 
equipped for the uneven struggle of existence; they are 
bound to prevail in it and to reap all the advantages ol 
the victory if not interfered with — they are, therefore, 
naturally inclined to individualism. 

The dependent and non-possessing classes, on the other '■ 
band, are powerless in the individual struggle for existence 
under prevailing conditions. They stand in need of social 
protection against the abuses of the dominant class, and 
thus their strength lies in concerted action and cooperation. 
To the intelligent workingmen, individualism is as repel- 
lent as it is hostile to their interests — they naturally lean 
towards the opposite philosophy. Socialism is the mani- 
festation of the working class revolt against the excessive 
individualism of the capitalists, just as individualism 
appeared originally as the expression of the revolt of 
the bourgeoisie against the excessive centralization of the 
ancient regime. 

The frequent and heated modern discussions on the 
merits and demerits of the "systems" of individualism 
and socialism are, therefore, at bottom only the theoretical 
and somewhat veiled expression of the practical struggles 
between the ruling and dependent classes of our times. 

In the words of Sidney Ball, "Socialism and Individual- 
ism, when contrasted, have an economic cormotation," ' 
but in ordinary discussion they assume, as a rule, the guise 
• of purely abstract political or philosophical issues. 

These issues between the "individualists" and the 
socialists are many in number and multiform in character, 



i 



fl8 THE SoaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

but for the convenience of treatment they may all be 
under the following three main heads : — 
The Relations of the Individual to Society. 
The Mutual Relations of Individuals in Production, 
3. The Fate of Individual Liberty under a System 
Socialism. 

We shall consider the points presented by each of these 
three subjects separately. 



L The Individual and Society 

I At the bottom of the individualist philosophy in politics 
lies the conception that organized society is a mere aggre- 
gation of individuals freely and deliberately associating 
for certain common purposes ^ a sort of business part- 
nership which may be formed, shaped and dissolved by 
the contracting parties at will. In this view of our social 
organization every member of modern society is an inde- 
pendent party to the "social contract" who has entered 
into contractual relations with society in order to gain 
some individual advantages and who may cancel these 
relations if the sacrifices imposed on him should exceed 
such advantages. The logical result of these views is an 
attitude of jealousy and suspicion towards organized 
society or the "state," ' an apprehension that the latter 
may strive to exact from the individual more than he has 
bargained to give, that it may "exceed the sphere of its 
legitimate functions." ' 

• For the puqxses of the present discussion the terms are here em- 
ployed interchangeably. 

' M. Yvea Guyot, the leading apostle ot individualism in France, 
_ would limit the activities of the state to the following functions; — 
. To guarantee e»tetior and interior security. 



SOCIAUSM AND INDIVIDUALISM 19 

This somewhat crude social philosophy found its clearest 
expression in the French pre-Revolutionary " literature of 
enlightenment"; it was the key to the social theories of 
the English Utilitarian school of Locke, Bentham and 
Mill, and it held practically undisputed sway of the human 
mind until about the middle of the last century. The 
doctrine is most naively asserted in the Massachusetts 
Bill of Rights, in the following language: "The body 
politic is formed by a voluntary association of individuals; 
it is a social compact by which the whole people covenants 
with each citizen and each citizen with the whole people, 
that all shall be governed by certain laws for the common 
good." 

But the discoveries in the domain of organic evolution 
and the growing recognition of the laws which are oper- 
ating to shape individual life everywhere, finally caused 
the students of social life and phenomena to subject their 
views to a critical examination. Conditions of social 
existence, past and present, were carefully investigated 
and collated, and laws of social development were gradu- 
ally established. 

In the light of the newly acquired knowledge the d priori \ 
social theories of the early thinkers had to be abandoned ; 
one by one, and to-day it is quite generally accepted that • 
organized society is not an arbitrary invention, but the ' 
result of a definite and logical process of historical de- 
velopment. 

It is probable that men never were purely individual 

"2. To secure to each individual the freedom to dispose of his per- 
son and the freedom of the environment in which he must act. 

'3. Not to intervene in contracts except to enforce their performance." 
Le Socialisme et L'Individualisme/' Journal des EconomisteSf June, 
1898. 



It 



' beings, but that they evolved from gregarious or social 
ancestors in the kingdom of animal life. "As far as we 
can go back in the palaeo-ethnology of mankind," observes 
Kropotkin, " we find men living in societies — in tribes 
simOar to those of the higher mammals." And further: 
"The earliest traces of man, dating from the glacial or the 
early post-glacial period, afford unmistakable proofs of 
man having lived even then in societies. Isolated finds of 
stone implements, even from the old stone age, are very 
rare; on the contrary, wherever one flint implement is 
I discovered, others are sure to be found, in most cases in 
r very large quantities. At a time when men were dwelling 
in caves, or under occasionally protruding rocks, in com- 
pany with mammals now extinct, and hardly succeeded in 
making the roughest sorts of flint hatchets, they already 
knew the advantages of life in societies." ' 

The entire history of man's progress has been one of 
increasing growth and importance of his social organiza- 
tion. According to Lewis H. Morgan,' whose studies of 
social development are among the most complete and 
reliable contributions to modern sociology, the first definite 
form of social organization is the primitive family or Gens, 
which still prevails among certain savages. This is a 
rather loose form of organization, consisting of a body of 
human beings descended from a common ancestor. The 
next step in social development is the Association of 
Several Genies or Phratry, which is followed by the 
closer and more complex organization of the Tribe, 
a union of many genks speaking a common dialect and 
occupying a common territory. From the Tribe to the 

* P. Kropotkin, "Mutual Aid a Factor of Evolution," London, 190a, 
Lpp> 79, So. ' "Ancient Society," 



AND INDIVIDUALISM ■ Vt ' 

Confederacy of Tribes, which is formed for mutual 
defense, and gradually and naturally develops into the 
Nation, there is but one step. 

This in brief is the history of social growth in ancient 
society. With the development of property in goods and 
land, the social organization gradually transformed itself 
into a political society based on territorial relations. The 
Township, the County and the National Domain or State, 
are the successive steps of that development. 

Thus mankind has imperceptibly evolved from an aggre- 
gation of loosely connected social units to the present state 
of society, in which the entire globe is divided politically 
into a very small number of governments compacUy and 
closely organized. 

The process took countless ages for its accomplishment 
and was in all its phases determined by the instinctive needs 
of mankind. The successive types of social organization, 
ever stronger and more compact, were evolved in the in- 
cessant struggle for existence as efficient weapons in that 
struggle. " The state," says Professor Ward, " is a natural 
product, as much as an animal or plant, or as man him- 
self." ' Whatever progress has been made by mankind in 
its long career has been made through its social organiza- 
tions. There is no civilization and there is no liberty out- 
side of organized society, and in this sense the individual 
man is the child and creature of the state and tied to it 
with every fiber of his existence.' 

' Lester F. Ward, "Pure Sociology," New Yoik, 1903, p. S49. 

' "There never was and there never can be any liberty upon tbit 
eartb among human beings outside of state organizacioru . . . Liberty 
is as tru!y a creation of the state as is governmenl." — Psoi'UiaB 
J. W. Bt:aGKSS, "Political Science and Constitutional Law," BoMoo, 
1690, p. 88. 



The historical and uniform course of the evolution of 
the state and its overwhelming importance as a factor in 
human civilization have led the school of thinkers of which 
Auguste Comte, Saint-Simon and Hegel are the typical 
representatives, to the opposite extreme— the conception of 
the state as an organism. The "historical" or "organic" 
school sees in the abstract phenomenon of the state a 
concrete and independent being with a life, interests and 
natural history of its own. To these thinkers human so- 
ciety is a social organism very much like the biological 
organism. The social institutions are so many of its 
organs performing certain vital functions required for the 
life and well-being of the organism itself, while the indi- 
vidual members of society are but its cells, Mr, M. J. 
Novicov,' probably the most ingenious exponent of the 
"organic" school of sociology, carries the parallelism be- 
tween the social organism and the biological organism 
to the point of practical identity, and Mr. Benjamin Kidd, 
criticising the utilitarian motto, "The greatest happiness 
of the greatest number," says : " The greatest good which 
the evolutionary forces operating in society are working 
out, is the good of the social organism as a whole. The 
greatest number in this sense is comprised of the members 
of generations yet unborn or tmthought of, to whose in- 
terests the existing individuals are absolutely indifferent. 
And, in the process of social evolution which the race is 
imdergoing, it is these latter interests which are always 
in the ascendant." * 

In short, the state is the end, the citizen is only the 

' "ConBcicDce et Votontfi Sociales," Paris, 1897; "La Th&rie Or- 
ganique des Soci£t£s," in Annaies dt L'lnililut International de Socioio- 
gie, Vol. V. ' "Social Evolution," p. 31a. 



SOCIALISM AND INDIVIDUALISM 23 

means. It is the old parable of the shrewd Mucius Sce- 
vola presenting itself before us in the fashionable garb 
of modem science. 

And here again the two extremes meet. The extreme 
individualist deprecates all attempts on the part of the 
state to regulate the affairs of the citizens, on the plea that 
the state shotdd not interfere with the liberty of the in- 
dividual; the extreme sociocrat discountenances all at- 
tempts on the part of the citizens to model the state in their 
interests, on the ground that the individual cannot shape 
the life of the social organism. One bases his objections 
on the ground of expediency, the other on scientific neces- 
sity ; but the practical results are the same in both cases — 
the separation of the state and the individual. 

Although the ultra "organic" theory of the state has 
found some adherents among socialist writers,* contem- 
porary socialism has, on the whole, as little sympathy with 
the extreme sociocratic view as it has with that of the 
extreme individualist. 

It is always dangerous to engraft a ready-made principle 
of any branch of scientific research on an entirely dif- 
ferent branch, notwithstanding apparent analogies between 
the two, and the fallacy of that method is probably best 
illustrated by the introduction of purely biological laws 
into the domain of sociology. The social organization of 
men is a phenomenon vastly different from the biological 
organism. In the case of the latter it is the organism as 
such which is endowed with sensation, reflection and life 
— the individual cell has no conscious life of its own, and 
serves only to support the existence of the organism. In 

* For example, the well-known Marxian scholar, F. v. d. Goes, in 
"Organische Ontwikkeling der Maatschappij," Amsterdam, 1894. 



THE SOOAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

^tiie case of the "social organism," on the other hand, it 
is the individual members of it who are endowed with 
conscious life, and it is the so-called organism that serves 
to support their individual existences. 

The state is not the voluntary and arbitrary creation of 
man, but it is just as little a factor imposed on man by 
some power outside of him. The state is a product of 
logical historical development, but that only as an accom- 
paniment of the logical historical development of man. 
The individual cannot dissociate himself from society, 
nor can society have any existence outside of the individuals 
composing it. The state represents the collective mind 
and attainments of all past generations, but also the col- 
lective intellect, will and powers of its present living, 
feeling and thinking members. The state has the 
power to regulate the conduct of its individual citizens, but 
its citizens have the power to determine the scope and 
nature of such regulations, and the higher mankind 
ascends in the scale of intellectual development, the more 
effective is its direction of the functions of the state. Man 
to-day is in a position to employ the state not merely for 
the good of the abstract "social organism as a whole," 
nor yet merely for the good of remote generations to come, 

« but for his own present concrete good. 

This is the view from which all socialist political ac- 
tivity proceeds, and this view is steadily gaining practical 
recognition in all spheres of society, as is eloquently attested 
by the ever greater extensions of the social functions of the 

[ modem state. 

Individualism in Industry 
K the tendency of political development of mankind 
m the whole, been in the direction of socialization, 



1 



SOCIAIISM AND INDIVIDUALISM 



25 



the same tendency asserts itself even more strongly in the 
process of industrial development. 

Individualism in production is a mark of economic 
immaturity. 

The primitive man, without experience, tools, weapons 
or arts, living in trees or in caves, and subsisting on the 
wild fruit of the tropical forest, may to a large extent be 
economically independent of his fellow-man in the neigh- 
boring tree. But the succeeding fishing, hunting, agri- 
cultural and pastoral occupations already presuppose the 
existence of certain uniform tools, a certain common ex- 
perience, common methods of work, and even the possi- 
bility of occasional exchanges of products. 

But these early institutions are, on the whole, too un- 
certain and unexplored to enable us to build any sober 
conclusions upon them. To ascertain the real tendency of 
industrial development, we must take a more recent and 
better-known period, — a period, besides, which has uncov- 
ered the laws of industrial evolution more clearly than the 
entire history before it, — the period of the last century. And 
if there is any doubt in our minds as to the tendency of 
our industrial life, the examination of this period will 
rapidly dispel it. 

In the beginning of the nineteenth century, the produc- 
tion and distribution of goods was in the main operated 
on an individualist basis. The artisan worked as an indi- 
vidual either at his home or in his shop, generally alone and 
sometimes with the aid of a helper or apprentice. His 
simple tool was owned and operated by him individually. 
His product was in most cases due entirely to his indi- 
vidual labor and skill, and was rightly and properly his 

[dividual possession. 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

But with the development of the simple tool into a 
variety of huge, steam-propelled machines, specialized for 
the mass production of minute parts of commodities, the 
little workshop grew into the enormous modem factory 
in which hundreds and thousands of men are brought 
together from all parts of the country, organized into a 
complex hierarchy of labor, each one doing one small 
thing, each working into the hands of the other, all of them 
collectively producing one article which may have to go 
through numerous similar operations in other immense 
and complex factories before it turns into a commodity 
for direct consumption. The modern machine is a social 
tool, the modem factory is a social workshop, the modem 
workingman is a social servant, and the modem goods are 
_;£Ocial products. 

' Let us take the most simple articles of use : the coat we 

!ar, the chair we sit on, the bed we sleep in, and ask our- 
* selves, Wlio produced these articles? To answer that 
question we shall have to consider the unknown thousands 
who contributed to the work of their immediate design 
and manufacture, to the production and transportation of 
the material contained in them, to the work of constructing 
the wonderful machinery employed at the coimtless steps 
of the process, and to the work of operating the machinery 
of transportation, etc. In modern production the indi- 
vidual laborer is practically obliterated ; what is before us 
is a world-wide community of socially organized labor of 
all gradations, from the highest and most skillful to the 
lowest and most common, working together collectively 
for the needs of our race. 

And it is this collective labor of our times that sustains 
lodem comforts and modem civilization. Were it pos- 



sck;ialism and individualism 27 

sible for us to return to the regime of absolute individ- 
ualism in production, to prepare oiu: own food, make our 
own clothing, build our own dwellings, without taking 
advantage of the material prepared by others, without 
accepting the cooperation of our fellow-men, we should 
relapse into a state of savagery in less than a generation. 

While the feature of individualism has been almost 
eliminated from the field of production by the last century, 
it has, during that period, shown much greater vitality in 
the sphere of management of our industries. 

The management of our industries by individual capi- 
talists for their own private benefit and in rivalry with 
each other — industrial competition — has for decades 
been the favorite topic of controversy between the ad- 
herents of the individualist philosophy and the partisans 
of the socialist school of political economy. To the 
sturdy individualist the competitive system of industry is 
the source of all blessings of civilization : he never tires of 
extolling the merits of that system as an incentive to in- 
dustrial enterprise, inventiveness and efficiency, as a char- 
acter builder and lever of all social and individual progress. 
The socialist, on the other hand, points a warning finger 
to the evils of competition: the anarchy in management 
and waste in production which the system entails, and the 
tremendous social, economic and ethical losses which it 
imposes on the producers, the consumers and the com- 
munity at large.* 

But while the discussion on the merits and demerits of 
competition is assuming ever more intense forms, the mute 

^ A most notable contribution to that phase of the discussion is the 
recent work of Mr. Sidney A. Reeve, "The Cost of Competition," 
McClure, Phillips & Co., 1906. 



28 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

forces of economic evolution, unconcerned by theories and 
abstractions, are rapidly working towards a practical 
solution of the problem. The individual capitalist stead- 
ily yields his place in the industrial world to the corpora- 
tion and the trust, and the latter combine and consolidate 
the independent managements of numerous individual 
concerns under one corporate direction, and reorganize 
the management of industries, frequently on a national and 
even international scale. The irresistible growth of trusts 
and monopolies is the central fact of all recent economic 
development, and it sounds the death knell of individual 
competition. 

The only sphere of our industrial life in which the prin- 
ciple of individualism has survived in all its pristine vigor, 
is that of the appropriation or distribution of the products. 

Although the instruments of production have become 
social in their character and use, and indispensable to the 
entire working community, they are still owned and con- 
trolled by the individual capitalists, Ahhough the pro- 
duction of goods is a collective process, and its management 
and direction are fast becoming so, it is still conducted 
principaliy for the benefit of the individual captains of 
industry. Although all useful members of the community 
collectively contribute to the so-called national wealth, 
only a comparatively small number of individuals share 
in it. In short, although the production of wealth is prac- 
tically socialistic, its distribution is entirely individualistic. 

And this contradiction between the modem methods 
of production and distribution is the only real issue be- 
tween the individualist and the socialist in the domain of 
economic discussion. 

The beneficiaries of the present system of wealth dis- 



SOOALISH AND INDIVIDUAUSU 



29 



^_ ad 

^^ of . 

Il 



tribntion have a very obvious material interest in main- 
taining it, and there never was a ruling class that did not 
have the abundant support of scientific and ethical theories 
to justify it in the continued enjoyment of its privileges, 
In the present case this function is being performed by 
the school of "individuaUstic" philosophers and mo ralizers. 

The socialists, on the other hand, consider the present 
system of individual appropriation of social wealth as 
hronism, a survival of a past economic order, and 
a disturbing factor in the process of social, economic and 

.ical progress. 

The main object of socialism is to adjust the principles 
of wealth distribution to those of production — to make 
the one as social and general in function and effect as the 
other already is. 



Tke Individual under Socialism 



The commonest of all objections to the socialist ideal 
is that a state of socialism would endanger mdividual 
liberty. From such unimaginative novelists as Eugen 
Richter ' and David M. Parry ,^ whose conceptions of the 
socialist commonwealth are those of the modem factory 
regulations extended to the scope of a national order, up 
to the thinker of the keenness of mind and universality 
of knowledge of Herbert Spencer who asserts that "all 
socialism implies slavery," * all bourgeois philosophers 
seem to take it for granted that mankind is to-day enjoy- 
ing a large measure of individual freedom and that social- 
ism would greatly curtail if not entirely suppress it. 

' "Sozialdemokratische Zukunftsbilder," 
' "The Scarlet Empire," Indianapolis, igo6. 
• "The Coming Slavery." 



30 TTIE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

The socialists deny both assertions with equal emphasis. 

Under our present system of economic dependence and 
struggles, individual liberty is but a fiction. The very 
small "leisure class," i.e., the class of persons enjoying 
a workless and ample income and entirely removed from 
active participation in the industrial, professional, com- 
mercial and financial strife, no doubt enjoy considerable 
individual liberty, but for all other strata of modem society 
that liberty does not exist. 

The workingmen, the largest class of the population, 
are anything but free : their work and their pleasures, 
their dress and their dwellings, their mode of life and their 
habits, are forced on them by their economic condition. 

"Not as an exception, but universally," says Mr. H, D. 
Lloyd,' "labor is doing what it does not want to do, and 
not getting what it wants or needs. Laborers want to 
work eight hours a day; they must work ten, fourteen, 
eighteen. , , . They want to send their children to school ; 
they must send them to the factory. They want their 
wives to keep house for them; but they too must throw 
some shuttle or guide some wheel. They must work 
when they are sick; they must stop work at another's 
will ; they must work life out to keep life in. The people 
have to ask for work, and then do not get it. They have 
to take less than a fair share of the product ; they have to 
risk life, limb or health — their own, their wives', their 
children's — for others' selfishness or whim." 

Nor is the workingman alone deprived of individual 
liberty under present conditions. The toiling farmer bur- 
dened by mortgages and oppressed by the railroad com- 

' Quoted in Richard T. Ely's "Socialiam and Social Reform," pp. 



SOCIALISM AND INDIVIDUALISM 3 1 

panics, the professional man dependent on private and 
unregulated calls for his services, and the small business 
man struggling against odds to maintain his "independ- 
ence," they are all tied to a routine of life and action not 
volimtarily chosen, but inexorably imposed on them by 
the economic exigencies of their business piursuits and 
callings. 

And even the "powerful" and wealthy, the heads of 
the modem industrial structure, are anything but free: 
their wealth as live, active, investment-seeking capital, 
dominates them and suppresses their individual volition ; 
they are the slaves of their wealth rather than its masters. 

All these purely economic checks on individual liberty 
must of necessity be greatly palliated, if not entirely re- 
moved, in a socialist community, for the system of socialism 
implies primarily a state of greater economic security and 
industrial equality. 

"But," it is asked, "assuming that socialism would 
remove some of the elements operating to-day against the 
full exercise of the freedom of the individual, would it not 
create new and more formidable restraints upon liberty? 
Under the present regime the individual has some say in 
the choice of his occupation and the mode of exercising 
his trade or calling; imder socialism, on the other hand, 
the state would be the sole employer, and would determine 
for every citizen what, where and how he should work; 
would not the citizen thus become the slave of the 
state?" 

This argument, so frequently urged against socialism, 
contains two fundamental errors: it assumes that a so- 
cialist state may be a power independent of and opposed 
to the body of individuals composing it, and that in a sys- 



r32 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

tem of socialism, all industries must be concentrated in 
I and controlled by the national government or " state." 
The basic principle of every socialist community must 
be its democratic administration : the socialist state will 
assume such concrete form, powers and functions as the 
majority of citizens, unbiased by conflicting class interests, 
will freely choose to confer on it, and it is not at all reason- 
able to suppose that these citizens will deliberately encase 
E themselves in an iron cage of rigid laws and rules of their 
own making. 
Much more likely the men who will have the framing of 
the political and industrial system of a socialist common- 
wealth, will take ample care of their own individual free- 
dom. 
Nor is there any reason to suppose that under socialism 
"the state" would be the sole employer. Socialism im- 
plies the collective ownership of the social tools of produc- 
tion, and the collective management of industries based 
upon the use of social tools. Does that necessarily 
imply state ownership and management? By no means. 
Certain industries are even to-day organized on a national 
scale, and may be best managed or controlled as state 
functions; others come more appropriately within the 
scope of the municipal administration, others still may be 
most efficiently managed by voluntary cooperative asso- 
ciations with or without state control, while a variety of 
industries of an individual nature, such as the various 
arts and crafts, must of necessity remain purely individual 
pursuits. The phantom of the "despotic state" has taken 
such a strong hold of the minds of our social philosophers 
trained in the individualistic school of thought, that even 
writers like Professor Richard T. Ely, of whose candor 



SOCIALISM AND INDIVIDUAUSM 33 

and analytical powers there can be no doubt, and who is by 
no means unsympathetic to socialism) is not quite free from 
the fear of it. "Even," says Professor Ely, "if the func- 
I tions of government should be reduced to the lowest forms 

I compatible with socialism, those in whose hands were 

centered political and economic control would have tre- 
mendous power, however they might be selected or ap- 
I pointed. Nor can we forget the possibilities of combina- 

l; tions between different parties for certain purposes. It 

would, under socialism, be quite possible for two or three 
parties to act together as sometimes they do now. The 
frequent assertion that the Democratic and Republican 
parties have acted together in New York City to control 
'■' the civil service, seems to be well founded; and it is quite 

I conceivable that two or three parties might act together 

to promote the interests favorable to a few leaders, and to 
keep down, if not persecute, obnoxious persons." ' 

In voicing these apprehensions Professor Ely uncon- 
sciously transfers present conditions into an order of things 
in which the very causes of such conditions are altogether 
lacking. Political parties are the creatures and tools of 
class interests, and "the interests favorable to a few 
leaders" which he mentions, are the economic interests of 
the class or group of men represented in politics by those 
! leaders. Modern party politics is, as we shall attempt 

to show in a later chapter, a manifestation of the capital- 
ist mode of production and of the economic struggle of the 
classes, and must disappear with the abolition of the present 
economic order. 

Under socialism there can be no party politics, in the 
present sense, and whatever abuses may develop in the 
^^^^ ' Richatd T. Ely, "Socialiam and Social Reform," pp. 311, 313. 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

administration of the state or the industries, can be only 
casual, based on inexperience or error of judgment of the 
community or on personal incompetence, malice or am- 
bition of the responsible officers, and in either case they 
be more readily remedied than in a state in which such 
ibuses have their roots in the very foimdation of the in- 
dustrial organization of society. 

On a par with the assertion that socialism would be fatal 
to individual liberty is the kindred claim that socialism 
would destroy the individuality of man. The "dead level 
of intellectual equality and homogeneity" under socialism 
is a specter almost as terrifying to the good " individualist" 
as the phantom of socialist slavery. And it is fully as 
unreal. For if any industrial system tends to destroy 
the individuality of men, it is not the proposed system of 
socialism, but our present economic order. The aggre- 
gation of millions of workingmen in the modern industrial 
centers, employed under similar conditions, tied everlast- 
to the same monotonous machine work, dweliing in 
£ same uniform tenements and leading the same stereo- 
typed bleak existence, tends to turn them into one undis- 
tinguishable, homogeneous mass, dressing, talking, looking 
and thinking substantially alike. The men of our active 
upper classes, ail engaged in the same all-absorbing pursuit 
of wealth by the same methods and tmder the same con- 
ditions, and our leisure classes sorely tried by the rigid rules 
of conventional etiquette, and tied to a blas^ life of uniform 
and tiring social functions, fashionable sports and pre- 
scribed recreations, develop a different but not less homo- 
geneous nor more attractive type. This natural uniform- 
ity of type within the different social classes is accompanied 
by a sort of artificial uniformity produced by the present 



SOCIALISM AND INDIVIDUALISM 35 

economic conditions operating in a more indirect manner. 
" One has only to look on whilst the sons of the nouveaux 
riches spend their money," remarks Mr. Macdonald, "or 
whilst the crowds which our industrial quarters have dis- 
gorged enjoy themselves, to appreciate the meaningless 
monotony of our pleasure. From our furniture, made by 
the thousand pieces by machine, to our religion, stereo- 
t)rped in set formulae and pursued by clockwork methods, 
individuality is an exceptional characteristic." * 

"Our standard of decency in expenditure," observes 
Professor Veblen, " as in other ends of emulation, is set by ! 
the usage of those next above us in reputability; imtil, in 
this way, especially in any community where class distinc- 
tions are somewhat vague, all canons of respectability and 
decency, and all standards of consumption, are traced 
back by insensible gradations to the usages and habits 
of thought of the highest social and pecuniary class — the 
wealthy leisure class." ^ 

And Mr. Vail expresses the same idea when he says: 
"The tendency toward imiformity is due to the lack of 
equality in economic conditions. The inferior classes 
strive to imitate the superior classes in order to avoid an 
apparent social inferiority. The result is, society is con-; 
tinually rim in the same groove. On the other hand, any( 
system which would tend to decrease economic inequality 
would tend to kill imitation. Just in proportion as men 
become equal, they cease to gain by imitating each other. 
It is always among equals that we find true independence."' 

* J. Ramsay Macdonald, "Socialism and Society," London, 1905, 
p. 7. 

' Thorstein Veblen, "The Theory of the Leisure Class," New York, 

I905» P- 104. 

» Charles H. Vail, "Principles of Scientific Socialism," p. 227. 



CHAPTER in 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 
The Essence and Scope of Ethics 

The branch of social philosophy known as Ethics pre- 
sents itself to us in a dual aspect. Theoretical or scien- 
tific ethics aims to ascertain the principles and true mean- 
ing of "right and wrong" in human conduct. Practical 
or applied ethics seeks to draw concrete conclusions from 
the knowledge so gained, and to base on it a code of " right " 
conduct for the practical guidance of mankind. Scien- 
tific ethics takes cognizance of actions and relations as they 
are, while practical ethics considers them as they ought to 
be. And it is largely on account of this dual character 
of ethics that the standard definitions of the term present 
such a striking divergence. Some of the writers on the 
subject have attempted to cover both aspects of ethics 
in one definition, while others either give separate defini- 
tions for each, or emphasize only one side, entirely ignoring 
the other.' 

But whether ethics be considered as a science or as an 

* The following are among the betler-known definitions of ethics, 
both as a science and an art; — 

Frofesnv John Dewey in the Encyclopedia Americana: "Ethics is thai 
branch of human conduct which is concerned with ^he furmatiott and use 
t>i judgments of right and wrong, and with the intellectual, emotional, 
and executive or overt phenomena which are associated with such judg- 
ments, either as antecedents or consequents." 

Francis L. Patlon in Syllabus of Ethics: "Ethics is the science that 
rational explanation of Rigktness and Oughtness; and that deals 



h. 



J 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 37 

art, all authorities agree that in either case it is concerned 
with "right" or "good" human conduct. That is, how- 
ever, as fax as the agreement goes. The more fundamental 
problems of the kind of human conduct properly coming 
within the sphere of ethics, and of the adoption of a uni- 
versally valid standard of "right and wrong" or "good 
and bad" in such conduct, is still the subject of much 
discussion. 

It is pretty generally agreed that the conduct of which 
ethics takes cognizance is not the conduct of associated 
human beings acting as such (for that properly belongs to 

with the Life of free personal beings under these conceptions, considering 
it as related to an Ideal or norm of Excellence, conformity to which is 
obligatory." 

Harold Hdffding in Eihik: *'A scientific system of Ethics endeavors 
to discover in accordance with what principles we direct our life, and to 
secure for these, when ascertained, greater clearness and inner harmony." 

Ethics is considered as a critical science only, in the following defini- 
tions: — 

Herbert Spencer in Data of Ethics: "Morality is the science of right 
conduct, and has for its object to determine how and why certain modes 
of conduct are detrimental, and certain other modes beneficial." 

New International Encyclopedia: "Ethics is the voluntary conduct of 
a self-conscious person, in so far as that action is amenable to a standard 
of obligation imposed on him by social influence or by a supreme plan of 
life that draws its material from society." 

The following definitions deal with ethics as a constructive art: — 

Henry Sidgwick in The Methods of Ethics: "By 'methods of ethics* 
is meant any rational procedure by which we determine what individual 
human beings 'ought' or what it is 'right * for them to do, or to seek to 
realize by voluntary action." 

Jeremy Bentham: "Ethics is the art of directing men's action to the 
production of the greatest possible quantity of happiness." 

American Encyclopedia: "Ethics is the principle which prescribes 
what ought to take place in human conduct." 

Webster's Dictionary: "Ethics is a system of rules for regulating the 
actions and manners of men in society." 



rsS THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

the domain of politics), but tlie conduct of the individual. 
At the same time, however, it is not all individual human 
I conduct that falls within the sphere of ethics. " Conduct" 

I has been aptly defined by Herbert Spencer as "acts ad- 

I justed to ends," ' and it is very obvious that within the 

L scope of his biological functions and even in his intellectual 

^^^B life and social relations man performs daily numerous acts 
^^^Bfully adjusted to ends which have no ethical implications. 
^^^FTo be ethical or unethical, human actions must have some 
I bearing on beings other than the actor himself; they must 

be tested by their socid effects. A number of authorities 
extend the operation of ethics to conduct towards one's 
self and one's fellow-men; philosophers of the theological 
I school include conduct towards God within the purview 

of ethics, while the thinkers of the evolutionary biological 
school, with Spencer at the head, classify ethical conduct 
, as conduct towards self, offspring and race. But on closer 
examination, it will be found that the addition of all factors 
other than the purely social factor, is meaningless or con- 
fusing. Ethics remains indifferent to the conduct of the 
individual towards himself, so long as that conduct does 
not directly or indirectly affect the well-being of his fellow- 
men or of the human race. When an individual wastes 
his physical or mental resources in a manner calculated 
to cripple his own life without, however, involving the well- 
being of other individuals, we call his conduct improvident 
or unwise, and only when he abuses his own body in a 
manner likely to injure his offspring or to enfeeble or 
degenerate the race, do we call hira immoral. Similarly, 
we consider an individual immoral if he is in the habit of 
transgressing those religious precepts which happen to be 
' "Data of Ethics," New York, 1893, p. 5. 



SOCIAUSM AND ETHICS 39 

in accord with the generally accepted secular notions of 
"right" or "good" in social conduct, but if he neglects 
to comply with certain prescribed religious observances 
which have no bearing on the well-being of his fellow-men, 
we merely call him irreligious. And finally the conduct 
of the individual towards his oflFspring is no more than a 
special phase of his conduct towards his fellow-men or 
his race. 

Without fear of serious contradiction we may, therefore, 
define ethics as the science or art of "right" individual 
conduct of men towards their fellow-men. 

A much greater uncertainty and divergence of views con- 
front us when we attempt to discover the meaning of the 
term "right" as applied to human conduct in the various 
philosophical systems of ethics. As a matter of fact, 
there is no code of morality universally recognized and 
conformed to by all mankind at all times. Human 
actions which are condemned as atrocious by some 
races under some circumstances, are sanctioned and even 
praised by other races and under other circumstances. 
Under normal conditions civilized men consider the act 
of deliberate murder as the most revolting and heinous of 
crimes, but in war the same act is glorified by them as one 
of greatest virtue, while among the food-lacking tribes of 
cannibals, it is considered as an indiflFerent act of common- 
place household economy. Other oflFenses against the 
person, and still more so oflFenses against property, have 
received even more varying estimates at diflFerent periods 
of human history and from diflFerent portions of the human 
race, while the astounding changes of the social standards 
of sex morality with time and place, are familiar to every 
student of sociology and reader of descriptive travel. 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



I 



And still the fundamental precepts of morality are 
by no means an arbitrary figment of tlie human brain. 
For the epoch and place in which they prevail they have 
universal validity, and even their modifications from time 
to time and variations from place to place will always be 
found to have legitimate reasons and realistic roots in the 
conditions of such times and places. If there are no 
absolute standards of right and wrong, there certainly 
must be relative standards of right and wrong at every 
given time and place, and these relative standards, further- 
more, must have some common principle determining 
their formation. What are those standards, and what is 
that principle? These are the main questions which 
exercised the minds of the early founders of the science of 
ethics and which still constitute the brunt of discussions 
of the modern moral philosophers. And it is largely 
the difference in the answers to these questions which 
separates the numerous existing ethical systems from each 
other. 

The theological school of thinkers, of which St, Augus- 
tine, the mediseval monk Ambrose and especially Thomas 
Aquinas are the classical exponents, and which still has 
numerous and vigorous adherents, assumes that there is 
a universal and supreme standard of right and wrong. 
That standard is the divine command which has been 
given to all mankind and is expressed in the holy scriptures. 
In particular instances that command is to be ascertained 
by revelation or by interpretation and application of the 
genera! rules obtained from texts of scripture and by 
analogical inferences from scriptural examples. Any 
departure from that command as so interpreted by in- 
dividuals or whole races is merely evidence of apostasy. 



In this theory ethics is practically synonymous with 

theology. 

Closely cognate with the theological system of ethics, 
but considerably secularized, is the doctrine of Natural 
Laws first developed into a comprehensive system by 
Hugo Grotius and followed by many modem writers, 
principally in England, That school, like the theological 
school, recognizes an absolute and universal standard of 
right and wrong in human conduct, but in distinction to 
the theological school it bases that standard not on a divine 
command but on "the essential nature of man." Accord- 
ing to Grotius and his followers there are implanted in the 
human being certain notions of right and wrong which 
form a part of his very existence and which are as unalter- 
able and true as the truths of mathematics. The test and 
the proof of such truths is their universal acceptance by 
human societies. In conformity with this conception the 
writers of that school have evolved a code of ethics based 
entirely on the fundamental notions of morality prevailing 
among the civilized nations of their times. 

Barely distinguishable from the juridical school of 
Natural Laws is the philosophical school of Intuitionalism. 
This school, which may claim Socrates and Plato for its 
founders, has in more recent times had many brilliant ex- 
ponents and defenders in the field of philosophic thought, 
chief among them being Kant and Whewell. According 
to the intuitional doctrine the sense of duty is innate in 
every normal human being and its commands and prin- 
ciples are known to them by intuition and without the aid 
of any process of reasoning or demonstration. This doc- 
trine is developed with the greatest elaborateness by Kant, 
pWho distinguishes between the world of " phenomena," or 



THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

objects as they appear to us through our limited senses and 
powers of perception, and the world of "noumena," the 
real world of objects as they exist regardless of our per- 
ception of them (Die Dinge an sich). The sense of duty 
is one of such "noumena," It manifests itself to us in a 
greater or smaller degree according to the development of 
our powers of perception, but it has an absolute and real 
existence outside of our perceptions. 

To all these systems of ethics which may be collectively 
designated as Idealisticj are opposed the so-called Rational- 
istic systemSj which seek to evolve standards of right and 
wrong from reason and experience rather than from reve- 
lation or intuition. 

The earliest of such schools is the Hedonistic or Epi- 
curean, which considers individual happiness as the end of 
life and all conduct conducive to that end as good and 
right. This theory is not grossly materialistic, since it 
recognizes the intellectual and ^esthetic pleasures as the 
ones conducive to greater and more lasting happiness. 
Like the school of Intuitionalism the school of Hedonism 
dates back to Greek antiquity. The philosophers Aris- 
tippus and Epicurus were among its first exponents. 
The theory was revived by Hobbes and considerably 
modified and extended by him and his followers. The 
more recent writers of this school frequently substitute the 
more definite standard of pleasure and pain for the old 
hedonistic test of happiness and unhappiness, and several 
of them see the true application of the principle of hedonism 
not in the happiness of the individual, but in universal or 
social happiness. Hedonism in one form or another was 
the favorite doctrine of the rationalistic philosophers of pre- 
Revolutionary France — Lamettrie, Helvetius and others. 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 43 

The notion of the "social contract," which appeared 
together with the victory of the European industrials and 
the establishment of constitutional government, logically 
led to the formation of the Utilitarian school of ethics. 
The adherents of the "social contract" theory, as stated in 
a previous chapter, assume that organized society was 
formed by its individual members for their mutual benefit 
and protection, and that it is deliberately maintained by 
them for that purpose. Since, however, the rules or acts of ^ 
organized society cannot always benefit all of its members 
alike, each individual member must occasionally sacri- 
fice some right to his fellow-men, upon the theory that in 
the long nm the advantages derived by him from society 
would outweigh the disadvantages suflFered. This is the 
"rational" sanction for the majority rule in all popular 
government, and Bentham only translated the political 
doctrine into ethical terms, when he asserted that "right" 
conduct is such as results in the greatest good to the great- 
est number. 

The Utilitarian school, in the language of Sidgwick, 
"holds that all rules of conduct which men prescribe to one 
another as moral rules, are really — though in part un- 
consciously — prescribed as means to the general happi- 
ness of mankind." * The chief exponents of this school are 
Paley, Bentham and the Mills, father and son, although 
Kant's ethical injunction, "Act only on such a maxim 
as may also be a universal law," may also be considered 
essentially utilitarian, inconsistent as it is with the in- 
tuitional theory of the famous philosopher. 

Finally, the school of social thought which goes to 

* Henry Sidgwick, "The Methods of Ethics," 5th Edition, London, 
1893, p. 8. 



. 44 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

biology for the discovery of rules of human conduct, has 
introduced another and more realistic standard of right 
and wrong in human conduct. According to Darwinian 
conceptions the strongest motives in all organic life are the 
instincts of self-preservation and preservation of the 
species. Applied to men in a social state that theory 
means that the main concern of human beings is the pres- 
ervation of life, and that such conduct of the individual 
will be regarded as good or right as tends to preserve and 
enhance the life of his fellow-men, while conduct which 
tends to curtail or impair such life will be considered bad 
or wrong. 

" Goodness," says Herbert Spencer, "standing by itself, 
suggests, above all other things, the conduct of one who 
aids the sick in re-acquiring normal vitality, assists the 
unfortunate to recover the means of maintaining them- 
selves, defends those who are threatened with harm in 
person, property, or reputation, and aids whatever promises 
to improve the living of all his fellows. Contrariwise, 
badness brings to mind, as its leading correlative, the con- 
duct of the one who, in caring for his own life, damages 
the lives of others by injuring their bodies, destroying 
their possessions, defrauding them, calumniating them.'" 
And Lester F. Ward tersely expresses the same thought 
in the following language: "'Duty' is simply conduct 
favorable to race safety. Virtue is an attribute of life and 
character consistent with the preservation and continuance 
of man on earth. Vice is the reverse of this, and is felt 
as an attack upon the race." ^ 

These, then, are the main theories of right and wrong, 
as conceived by the contending systems of ethical thought. 
L • "Data of Ethics," pp. 34, aj. * "Pure Socblogy," p. 41a 



I^^^Eroa 



But this branch of the subject does not by any means 
exhaust the field of ethical inquiry. For assuming that a 
true standard of right conduct is discovered, there still 
remains the more important question as to the motives 
which impel or ought to impel human beings to conform 
to that standard. The mere fact that we recognize a 
certain mode of action as right and another as wrong does 
not imply that we will in all cases follow the one and shun 
the other. What, then, is the factor that makes or ought to 
make us choose good conduct in preference to bad conduct ? 

To that question the different schools make different 
replies according to their conceptions of the nature of the 
moral obligation. The theological school holds out the 
promise of reward in a life beyond the grave. The in- 
tuitional school declares that no reward is required, since 
the individual is impelled to obey the moral impulse innate 
in him, the irresistible command of nature, or, as Kant 
terms it, the Categorical Imperative. "Thou must always 
fulfill thy destiny," decrees the celebrated German philoso- 
pher Fichte, and the biological school of ethics practically 
makes the same reply except that it substitutes the instinct 
of preservation of the species for the intuitive moral sense. 

The most contradictory and, therefore, the least satis- 
factory explanations of the ethical motives of men are those 
offered by the schools which pride themselves with being 
founded on pure reason, — those of hedonism and utili- 
tarianism. 

Recognizing that mere individual self-interest is en- 
tirely inadequate to account for the acts of altruism which 
chiefly constitute high moral conduct, the hedonists early 
resorted to the theory of "intelligent egoism" as distinct 
from that of shortsighted selfishnes.s. The well-developed 



THE SOCIALIST PHaOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

human being, they argue, is so constituted that he ex- 
periences greater pleasure in serving his fellow-men than in 
gratifying his own narrow desires. In promoting the well- 
being of his fellows he, therefore, primarily procures a 
pleasurable emotion for himself and only incidentally rend- 
ers a service to his neighbor. But this argument carries 
its own destruction, for it makes the basis of right human 
conduct not the self-interest of the actor, but his inner 
consciousness or instinct of duty to his fellow-men, the 
performance of which causes him pleasure. Neither the 
hedonistic theory nor the utilitarian conception, which 
represents man in organized society as engaged in constant 
cold-blooded bargaining with hisfellow-men for advantages, 
can account for such acts as the voluntary sacrifice of one's 
life in the service of society. And on the other hand the 
idealistic theories of ethics do not even attempt to explain 
motives of human conduct, but virtually abandon the 
subject as beyond their ken. 

Within this charmed circle of contradictions the philoso- 
phy of ethics oscillated during almost the entire intellectual 
period of the human race, aJid little, if any, substantial 
progress was made in twenty-five centuries of the career of 
that important branch of thought. It was only when the 
discussion was removed from the domain of metaphysical 
speculation to the field of positive science, that ethics ac- 
quired a realistic basis. This great work was primarily 
accomplished by Charles Darwin and his disciples. 

The Evolution of (he Moral Sense 

The main features of the Darwinian theory of organic 
evolution are, as is generally known, the doctrine of the 
struggle for existence and the resulting natural selection 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 



47 



through the survival of the fittest, the development of 
useful organs and hereditary transmission. 

In a state of nature each individual is engaged in con- 
stant struggle with individuals of its own or different 
species and with surrounding nature. In this universal 
struggle the individuals least equipped for the fight and 
least adapted to their surroundings, perish, while those 
who happen to possess organs or features of particular 
advantage in the struggle, survive, and by the frequent 
application of such useful organs and features, develop 
them ever more and transmit them to their offspring in a 
higher degree of development. Thus results a constant pro- 
cess of increasing adaptation to surroundings and a breed 
of more highly and efhciently organized individuals. The 
struggle for existence is a purely individual struggle in the 
lowest forms of life, and the struggle between individuals 
of the same species predominates in those forms. But in 
the ascending scale of organic existence the struggle be- 
tween individuals of the same species gradually abates and 
is superseded by the collective struggles of such individuals 
against hostile kinds and the adverse forces of nature 
around them. Social organizations thus arise among 
animals, including the progenitors of primitive men, and 
these organizations prove a powerful weapon in the struggle 
for existence against hostile groups or species. The more 
compact and harmonious the organization, the greater its 
efEciency as a weapon in the struggle for existence. Hence- 
forward the process of evolution is one of growing soli- 
darity and cohesion among the individuals of the same 
group or species as against their common enemies, and this 
instinct of solidarity and cohesion is the first germ of the 
jsense of social duty or moral consciousness. 



r 4s THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

"The feeling of pleasure from society," says Darwin, 

' "is probably an extension of the parental or filial affec- 

! tions, since the social instinct seems to be developed by the 

young remaining for a long time with their parents; and 

this extension may be attributed in part to habit, but 

chiefly to natural selection. With those animals which 

were benefited by living in close association, the individuals 

which took the greatest pleasure in society would best 

escape various dangers, whilst those that cared least for 

their comrades, and lived solitary, would perish in greater 

numbers. With respect to the origin of the paternal and 

filial affections, which apparently lie at the base of the 

I social instincts, we know not the steps by which they have 

been gained ; but we may infer that it has been to a large 

[ extent through natural selection."' 

And again: "When two tribes of primeval men, living in 

1 the same country, came into competition (other circum- 

Lstances being equal) if the one tribe included a greater 

■number of courageous, sympathetic and faithful members, 

[who were always ready to warn each other of danger, to aid 

land defend each other, this tribe would succeed better 

9 and conquer the other. . . . Selfish and contentious people 

t will not cohere, and without coherence nothing can be 

cted, A tribe rich in the above qualities would spread 

and be victorious over other tribes ; but in the course of 

time it would, judging from all past history, be in its turn 

overcome by some other tribe still more highly endowed. 

Thus the social and moral qualities would tend to slowly 

advance and be diffused throughout the world." ' 

' "The Descent of Man," Collier Editbo, New York, 1901, pp. J44, 

S- 

' Ibid., pp. 17s, 17S. 



49 

These mental and moral qualities once generated will 

on the whole grow in the course of evolution. The higher a 

tribe of men stands in the scale of civilization, the less will 

its members depend on their purely physical powers and 

-the greater will be the importance of their mental and 

[.moral qualities. 

"In proportion as physical characteristics become less 
I important," says Alfred Russel Wallace, who shares with 
I Darwin the merit of the discovery of the theory of natural 
f selection, " mental and moral qualities will have an in- 
I creasing influence on the well-being of the race." ' 

Thus the moral sense is a product of the process of 

■evolution of man, gained in his early struggle for existence, 

■precisely in the same manner as his intellectual qualities. 

St is a property of man in a state of society just as much as 

my of his physical organs, or as Mr, Baxputs it, "the ethi- 

l1 sentiment is the correlate in the ideal sphere, of the fact 

i social existence itself in the material sphere. The one is 

5 necessarily implied in the other as the man is implied in 

fius shadow."' 

This conception of the nature of morality and its origin 

ind development in the human being overthrows all earlier 

theories of ethics, but at the same time it reconciles all 

dements of truth that are contained in them. 

The primitive men did not deliberately form their first 

I organizations on the strength of such considerations 

e contained in Rousseau's " Social Contract." They 

idid not bargain for advantages or pleasures to be bestowed 

f on them by society. They were forced into organization 

k by the superior powers of struggle. They probably first 

* In "Contributions to Natural Selcttion." 

' E. Belfort Box, "The Ethics of Socialism," p. 4. 



I 
I 



L 



50 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

herded themselves together blindly, unreasoningly. But 
the instinct which impelled them to form such organiza- 
tions was the instinct of self-preservation, the inarticulate 
and unexpressed conviction that in organization lay their 
greater safety and protection, and that by their own de- 
votion to the social aggregation they would help to 
strengthen the weapon upon the efficiency of which their 
lives largely depended. The primitive men or their pro- 
genitors were in that sense unconscious hedonistic and 
utilitarian philosophers. 

But the moral sense once evolved, in the course of time 
became a permanent trait of the human being, an innate or 
intuitive feeling, and in this sense the Idealistic theories 
of ethics have a certain degree of reason and justification. 
"The social instinct," says Ernst Hacckel, "is always a 
physical habit, which was originally acquired, but which, 
becoming in the course of time hereditary, appears at last 
innate," ' 

The conclusion of the foremost Darwinian scholar in 
Germany thus largely coincides with those of the foremost 
German philosopher of Intuitionalism, Immanuel Kant. 

The moral sense once acquired is, like all other properties 
of the human being, subject to growth. The rudimentary 
moral instinct of the primitive man must have undergone 
countless phases of development before it evolved into the 
lofty conceptions of the contemporary moral philosopher. 

But it would be a mistake to consider that growth as a 
continuous, automatic and regular process. The moral 
sentiment in mankind does not grow in the same sense as 
a plant or other physical organism grows, i.e., by steadily 

Quoled by C. M. Williams, "A Review of the Systems of Ethics," 
, New York, 1893. 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 51 

inereasmg in dimensioii with the lapse of time. Different 
races, thou^ perhaps of the same age, exhibit different 
moral parceptions in kind and degree, and even within the 
same society and age different indiWduals presoit the most 
divergent d^rees of the moral sentiment. 

The growth of the moral sense, like the growth 
of the intellect, depends upon a multiplicity of ex- 
ternal conditions which shape its contents and further 
CMT arrest its progress. What is the nature of these con- 
ditions? The theory of natural selection traces the origin 
and reveals the quality of the moral sense in man, but it 
fails to accoimt for the mode and laws of its further de- 
velopment. In fact the foimders of the modern school 
of biological evolution distinctly disclaim the effective- 
ness of that factor as applied to a more advanced state of 
himian society. 

"With civilized nations," declares Darwin, "as far as 
an advanced standard of morality and an increased number 
of fairly good men are concerned, natural selection ap- 
parently effects but little; though the fundamental social 
instincts were originally thus gained," ^ and Mr. Wallace 
is still more emphatic in this view of the limited scope of 
operation of the principle of natural selection. 

What, then, are the factors determining the degree and 
direction of moral development? 

The answer to that momentous question will be found 
in the philosophy of the school of Karl Marx, who alone 
consistently introduced the spirit of Darwinism into the 
study of social phenomena by substituting the economic 
interpretation of history and the resulting doctrine of the 
class struggle in the more modern stages of social develop- 

* "The Descent of Man," p. 185. 



52 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

ment for the instinct of self-preservation and the resulting 
doctrine of the struggle for existence in its lower stages. 

Class Ethics 

The prime concern of men in a state of society is the 
production of the means for the sustenance of the mem- 
bers of that society. A community engaged chiefly in 
hunting, pastoral, agricultural or manufacturing pursuits 
and largely depending on the success of such pursuits for 
its existence, will in all cases arrange its organization and 
regulate its functions primarily with a view of enhancing 
the efficiency of that particular mode of securing the ma- 
terial life of its members. This object determines all 
economic and political forms of society, and in the last 
analysis it also dominates all social motives and notions. 

"In the social production which men carry on," says 
Marx, "they enter into definite relations that are indis- 
pensable and independent of their will; these relations 
of production correspond to a definite stage of development 
of their material powers of production. The sum total 
of these relations of production constitute the economic, 
structure of society — the real foundation, on which rise 
legal and political superstructures and to which correspond 
definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of pro- 
duction in material life determines the general character 
of the social, political and spiritual processes of life. It 
is not the consciousness of men that determines their ex- 
istence, but, on the contrary, their social existence deter- 
mines their consciousness." ' 

Morality, which has been defined by Professor Ward as 

■ Karl Marx, "A Contribution to Ihe Critique of Political Ecouom]'," 
m ''.iigliah Translation, New York, 1904, p. 11, 



SOCIAUSM AND ETHICS 



S3 



^conduct conducive to "race safety," and by Mr. Stephen 
as conduct conducive to the "health of society,'" and 
which in the earlier stages of social evolution stands 
principally for courage and loyalty in combat, in a more 
advanced society comes to a large extent to signify conduct 
favoring the economic efficiency and prosperity of the 
nation. 

The glaring differences which confront us in the codes 
of ethics of different communities, or within the same com- 
munities at different times, mostly reflect the differences 
or changes of the economic conditions of such communi- 
ties, the manner of maintaining the lives of their members. 
A savage tribe suffering from a scarcity of food may have 
its own rudimentary code of ethics, but such a code will not 
extend its ban to the practices of devouring its captives 
in war or slaying its aged and feeble members. When, 
however, the same tribe develops to the point of using 
tools and implements and leams to produce food in greater 
abundance, the practices of man-eating and of killing its 
own members become immoral. A nation like the ancient 
Spartans, whose subsistence largely depends on success 
in war, may have a very definite and strict code of ethics, 
but the virtues recognized by that code will be principally 
those of military worth, physical strength, courage and 
quick-wittedness, whereas honesty will be considered a 
matter of moral indifference, and the practice of killing 
feeble children, even a moral duty. Conversely, peacefiJ, 
pastoral and agricultural communities will rate honesty 
and industry as the highest virtues, and show but little 
llegard for courage and daring. 

' Leslie Stephen, "The Science of Ethics," ad Edition, New York, 



I 



54 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

Thus each community primarily formulates in its code 
of ethics the material or economic welfare of its members, 
while within each community the standard of individual 
morality is the degree to which each member advances 
or impairs the material interests of his fellow-members. 
In the earlier types of social organization in which the 
material interests of all members were practically identical 
and in which the individual member necessarily benefited 
from every advantage accruing to the totality of members, 
and vke versa, there could be no conflict between the 
interests of the individual and those of socie^. The 
material welfare of the community was easily, we may say 
instinctively, ascertainable and readily conformed to. 
The system of morality, such as it was, was perfect. 

But in modern communities the relations of the indi- 
viduals to society and to each other are by no means so 
simple and harmonious. The division of labor or special- 
ization of functions which has marked the social progress 
of man, together with the accumulation of property made 
possible by the ever growing productivity of human labor, 
have split up all more modem societies into different 
groups of members, with distinct economic interests. 
Society or "the nation" no longer represents a homogene- 
ous aggregation of individuals with uniform and harmonious 
material interests, and the standard of individual morality 
as conduct favoring the safety, health or economic interests 
of the " nation " loses much of its force. For in the modem 
class state conduct which is beneficial to certain groups or 
classes of society is very often detrimental to other groups 
or classes, and especially within the most vital sphere of 
economic activity it is almost impossible to conceive of 
any action which would be beneficial to all society alike. 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 55 

The individual wlio invents a labor-saving device may be 
said in the abstract to be benefiting maniiind at large, 
but as society is constituted to-day, his invention also re- 
sults in depriving large numbers of workingmen of a chance 
to earn their living. The legislator who forces the intro- 
duction of safety appliances in dangerous works benefits 
a certain class of workers but at the same time he injures 
the material interests of a number of employers. 

What, then, is the true standard of morality applicable 
to modem society? 

We have mentioned that modern society consists of 
various interest groups or classes. These classes are 
formed by the economic relations of men and are friendly, 
indifl'erent or hostile to each other according to the nature 
of such relations. But between all these divergent social 
classes we may draw one sharp line of demarcation, the 
line that separates the possessing from the non-possessing, 
the dominant from the dependent classes. And while 
the material interests of the several possessing classes 
between themselves may be conflicting at different points 
of contact, they are as a rule fairly harmonious as regards 
their common relations to the dependent classes. And 
whenever the interests of these dominant classes come in 
conflict with those of the dependent classes, the former 
have always understood it to represent their special in- 
terests as the interests of society. This attitude is made all 
the easier for the ruling classes because their interests al- 
ways coincide with the maintenance of the existing order 
and relations, and are, therefore, conservative, while the 
interests of the dependent classes lie in the direction of a 
change of such conditions and are, therefore, revolutionary. 
■ Moral conduct, as ordinarily interpreted, is conduct 



56 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

tending to conserve the existing order. In the modem 

class state such conduct is, therefore, conduct conducive 

to the perpetuation of the advantages of the ruling classes. 

"Ethics," says Mr. La Monte rather forcibly, "simply 

registers the decrees by which the ruHng class stamps with 

approval or brands with censure human conduct solely 

with reference to the effect of that conduct on the welfare 

of their class. This does not mean that any ruling class 

has ever had the wit to devise ab initio a code of ethics 

perfectly adapted to further their interests. Far from it. 

The process has seldom, if ever, been a conscious one. 

By a process akin to natural selection in the organic world, 

the ruling class learns by experience what conduct is 

helpful and what hurtful to it, and blesses in the one case 

and damns in the other. And as the ruling class has 

I always controlled all the avenues by which ideas reach 

[ the so-called lower classes, they have heretofore been able 

\ to impose upon the subject classes just those morals which 

\ were best adapted to prolong their subjection." ^ 

■ It is only on the theory of the class character of modern 

[ ethics that the curious inconsistencies in our moral con- 

I ceptions can be accounted for. The strong man who 

\ should deliberately injure a weak child outside of his busi- 

I ness pursuits, would be considered by his fellow-men as an 

individual of a low moral character, but the powerful and 

wealthy mill owner who daily undermines the health and 

saps the life of hundreds of inoffensive children of tender 

age in the "legitimate" pursuit of his business, i.e., in the 

process of profit making, is regarded by us as a perfectly 

moral being. He may be the superintendent of a Sunday 

' Robert Rives La Monte, "Socialism: Positive and Negative," 
Chicago, 1907, pp. 60, 61. 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 



57 



school, an honored member of an Ethical Culture Society, 
or may be sincerely interested in the missionary task of 
improving the moral conditions of some South African 
tribe of savages. 

Similarly the owners of the factpries, mines and rail- 
roads, who suffer or cause large numbers of their fellow- 
men to lose their lives on account of insufEcient safety 
appliances in their works, and the dealers in food stuffs, 
who poison their fellow-men by adulterated food, meet 
with no particular opprobrium on the part of society, 
while they would have been condemned as immoral 
wretches if they had been guilty of similar conduct outside 
of their business pursuits, and not for the sake of profits. 

The socialists of the Marxian school do not agree with 
thinkers of the type of Mandeville,* who considers moral- 
ity purely artificial and a device of the "politicians" to 
strengthen their rule on their fellow-men. They fully 
recognize that the moral sentiment is implanted in the 
normal human being and capable of very high development 
even under adverse conditions. Instances of men and 
women rising above their class interests and sacrificing 
their material welfare, sometimes even their lives, in the 
service of their fellow-men, are of frequent, almost daily 
occurrence, and cannot be accounted for on any economic 
or materialistic theory. The socialists also recognize 
that outside of the economic sphere of human activity, 
there is a large field of human interest, in which the indi- 
viduals of all classes meet on common ground, and in 
which the moral conceptions correspond to the actual 
welfare of all mankind. But they maintain that as a rule 

' The author of a book entitled "The Fahle of the Bees, or Private 
IS Public Benefits," published in 1724. 



58 THE SCX;iAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

the ethical conceptions dominating the "business" inter- 
ests of modern nations, and the various social activities 
and organs subservient to these interests, such as politics, 
the agencies molding public opinion, etc., are concep- 
tions favoring the interests of the dominant classes only. 
They are the ethics of the ruling classes falsely parading 
as general social ethics. 



k 



The Ethical Ideal and Socialist Morality 



When we speak of a certain degree of development of 
the moral faculty and when we distinguish a rudimentary 
form of morality from a highly evolved form, we must 
necessarily have in mind a standard of comparison. Such 
a standard of comparison is the ethical ideal, which to us 
represents the limit of ali moral conduct and by the ap- 
proach to which we judge a concrete code of morals to be 
high or low. 

An ethical ideal — Absolute Ethics, Spencer terms it — 
does not imply a belief in a code of morality good for all 
times and places and independent of all existing physical 
conditions. It merely represents our view of the last 
phase of moral evolution in civilized society, based upon 
our observation of the course of such evolution in the past. 
Such an ideal is as useful for the purposes of practical 
ethics as general and abstract laws of pure science are 
iiseful for the study of concrete phenomena. 

Most of the modern writers on the subject have, there- 
fore, outlined ideal standards of ethics, and most of these 
outlines agree in their fundamental characteristics. 

According to Spencer's definition ethical conduct is 
such as is conducive to the welfare of self, offspring and 




SOaALlSM AND ETHICS $g 

: best, i.e., most normal conduct is that which 

fulfills all the three conditions simultaneously and most 

efficiently. Such conduct, however, can only be attained 

in a state of society in which the interests of the individual 

and those of society are entirely identical, and in which 

I happiness is to be achieved mainly through the 

; pursuit of their own happiness by individuals, 

while reciprocally, the happiness of the individual is to be 

achieved in part by the pursuit of the general happiness." ^ 

Whether we agree in all parts with this definition or 

^ whether we confine the scope of ethics to conduct towards 

society or one's fellow-men, does not alter the validity of 

the conclusion. The relations of the individual and society 

are those of mutual service, and the progress of morality 

consists in the growth of these relations, or in the words 

Icf Huxley, "in the gradual strengthening of the social 

f bond." ' 

The limit of moral evolution can thus be reached only 

i in a state of society free from material and other antago- 

L nisms between the individuals among themselves and be- 

I tween the individual and society. In such society the 

I question of right and wrong is entirely obviated, since no 

normal conduct of the individual can hurt society, and 

all acts of society must benefit the individual. Organic 

morality takes the place of ethics. 

Such an ideal state of organic morality may be unattain- 
able in its absolute purity, but the trend of evolution is m 
its general direction. All factors which impede the path 
Lto its approximate realization are anti-ethical or immoral ; 

' Herbert Spencer, "Scjcial Staticg." 

'Thoraaa H. Huxley, "EvolulEon and Ethics," New York, 1896, 



6o THE SOCIALIST PtIlLOSOPIIY AND MOVEMENT 

contrariwise, all factors or movements whicii tend in its 
direction are ethical. 

In modern society tiie checlts to the realization of ideal 
morality are numerous. As indicated in the previous 
chapter, the existence of social classes and the resulting 
class struggles are the chief impediments to a true social 
morality. But the direct action of the struggle between 
antagonistic classes in the same society does not by any 
means exhaust the evil. Some of the indirect effects of 
the class state based on individual production are even 
more disastrous to the progress of true morality than its 
direct operations. And chief among such effects are the 
two most anti-social institutions — competition and war. 

"The competitive struggle," says Kautsky, "affects 
the social instincts of the individuals in the same society 
most distinctively. For in this struggle each individual 
maintains himself best the less he permits himself to be 
influenced by social considerations and the more he is 
guided by his own interests. For the member of the capi- 
talist society based on individual competitive production, 
it is, therefore, quite nattyal to consider egoism as the only 
legitimate instinct in man, and to regard the social in- 
stincts as refined forms of egoism or as an invention of 
the priests to fasten their rule on men or as a supernatural 
mystery." ' 

Wars are regarded by Herbert Spencer as the chief ob- 
stacle to the progress of moral development, and in his 
"Data of Ethics," as well as in his later work, "The Deduc- 
tions of Ethics," the theory occurs again and again that a 
"state of war" is incompatible with an ideal morality, and 

' Karl Kautslty, "Eihik und Materialist ische GeschichtsauffaBsung," 
Stultgirl, 1906, pp. 105, 106. 



SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 



6i 



that the latter is only attainable in perfectly peaceful socie- 
ties. Spencer does not take cognizance of the class struggle 
and of the economic interpretation of history. To him "a 
state of war" and "a state of peace" are merely phases of 
moral development in human society. But as a matter 
of fact wars depend but little on the degree of civilization 
attained by the community. The most advanced states 
are frequently also the most warlike states. Wars in mod- 
em times are most often caused by economic motives. 
They are usually the results of the competitive struggles 
of the capitalist classes of the belligerent nations for the 
markets of the world, the logical counterparts of competi- 
tion in the national markets. 

To the industrial individualism which is the leading 
feature of modern society corresponds a gross egoism in all 
spheres of our material existence which sets mdividual 
against individual and throttles all nobler social instincts 
in man. Employer and employee, producer and consumer, 
buyer and seller, landlord and tenant, lender and borrowa-, 
are always arrayed against each other, constantly and 
necessarily meeting in a spirit of antagonism of interests, 
incessantly engaged in conscious or unconscious economic 
struggle with each other. And a!I these forms of economic 
struggle are but single phases of the broader and deeper 
class struggle which is the dominant factor in modem in- 
dustrial life and largely determines all current moral con- 
ceptions. 

But the class struggle is not an unmitigated evil. Just 
as the struggle for existence among individuals in the 
lower forms of human existence led to the improvement of 
the race and eventually matured the conditions of its own 

Btruction, just so the class struggles in advanced societies 




62 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

have often been the instruments for the improvement of the 
social type and will eventually lead to the abolition of all 
classes and class struggles. 

The struggles between the bourgeoisie, the progenitors 
of the modern capitalist class, and the ruling class of land- 
owners, have yielded many valuable acquisitions to modem 
civilization, and have resulted in the establishment of mod- 
em society, which with all its faults and imperfections is 
vastly superior to the feudal order which it displaced. The 
struggles of the dependent classes against the ruling classes 
in modem society have ah-eady produced the rudiments 
of a nobler social morality, and are rapidly preparing the 
ground for a still higher order of civilization. 

The modern working class is gradually but rapidly 
emancipating itself from the special morality of the ruling 
classes. In their common struggles against the oppression 
of the capitalist class the workers are naturally led to the 
recognition of the value of compact organization and 
solidary, harmonious action. Within their own ranks 
they have no motive for struggle or competition; their 
interests are in the opposite direction. And as the struggles 
of their class against the rule of capitalism become more 
general and concrete, more conscious and effective, there 
grows in them a sentiment of class loyalty, class solidarity 
and class consciousness which is the basis of a new and 
distinct code of ethics. The modern labor movement is 
maturing its own standards of right and wrong conduct, 
its own social ideals and morality. Good or bad conduct 
has largely come to mean to them conduct conducive to 
the welfare and success of their class in its struggles for 
emancipation. They admire the true, militant and de- 
voted "labor leader," the hero in their struggles against 



I SOCIALISM AND ETHICS 63 

' the employing class. They detest the " scab," the deserter 
from their ranks in these struggles. 

The two historical slogans given to the modem socialist 
and labor movement by Karl Marx and Frederick Engels, 

:■ "The emancipation of the workingmea can only be ac- 
complished by the workingmen themselves," and "Work- 
ingmen of all countries imite, you have nothing to lose 
but your chains, you have a world to gain ! " — may truly 
be said to be the main precepts of the new morality of the 
working class. They inspire the " lower " classes with the 
consciousness of a great social mission to be performed by 
them in modern society ; they foster the virtues of com- 
radeship and self-reliance in their ranks, and develop the 
qualities of fidelity and devotion to their common cause. 
This new morality is by no means ideal social morality. 
It is the ethics of struggle, class ethics as yet. But Just 
because it is the ethics of a subjugated class engaged m the 
struggle for its emancipation, it is superior to the prevailing 
ethics of the class bent upon maintaining acquired privi- 
leges. The workingmen cannot abolish the capitaUst 
class rule without abolishing all class rule; they cannot 
emancipate themselves without emancipating all mankind. 
Behind the socialist theory of the existing class struggle 
lies the conception of a classless, harmonious society; 
behind the conception of the international solidarity of 
the working class lies the ideal of the world-wide solidarity 
of the human race. The ideals of the modern socialist 
and labor movement thus generally coincide with the 
scientific conceptions of absolute morality. 

Of course, in both cases we are dealing with ideals, 
and ideals only. We must recognize that the realities of 

L Ufe always fall short of social ideals. Socialism does not 



64 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

imply a state of absolute and universal harmony. The 
human mind cannot conceive to-day a state of society free 
from all antagonism and frictions caused by differences in 
temperament, views and even temporary material interests. 
There will probably always be some individual infractions 
of the accepted canons of social morality, but there will be 
no universal economic motive for such infractions, and 
they will necessarily become less flagrant in character and 
less frequent in number, they will cease to be the rule in 
human conduct, and will become the exception. 

"The conflict of the individual with society," says 
Charles Kendall Franklin, "is of two kinds. On the one 
hand, it is carried on by specialized individuals whose 
function is to develop and perfect society by developing 
the moral and social senses; on the other, the conflict is 
between society and the rank individualist who will not 
be subdued by society, who persists in expendmg his 
energies in as wasteful a manner as he sees fit so it benefits 
himself. Civilization is full of such people to-day. They 
are powerful individuals, they head corporations, they 
compose the professions, they constitute the classes. They 
beheve in society for their own benefit and hoot at the 
socialization of the race as the rankest nonsense. . . . 
Their worst representative is the degenerate and criminal; 
individuals who cannot adapt themselves at all to the 
development of society to-day." ' 

Of the two kinds of anti-social individuals so charac- 
terized by Franklin, the "specialized" individual and the 
pathological criminal, the men physically and morally 
constituted above or below their fellow-men, may survive 
forever in larger or smaller numbers, but the " rank indi- 
' "The Socialijation of HumanEty," Chicago, 1904, p. aio. 



SCX:iALISM AND ETHICS 65 

vidualist" who preys upon his fellow-men and tramples 
on social solidarity, mainly from motives of material gain, 
can find but little room in a society based on cooperative 
production and common social enjoyment. With the 
change of his economic interests and motives man will 
necessarily change his conduct. 

"The ethics of socialism," observes Bax on this point, 
." seeks not the ideal society through the ideal individual, 
but conversely the ideal individual through the ideal 
society. It finds in an adequate, a free and harmonious 
social life, at once the primary condition and the end and 
completion of individuality." * 

* "The Ethics of Socialism," p. 19. 



CHAPTER IV 



I 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 

The Law 

In out occasional contact with the law we are but too 
apt to concentrate our attention on the concrete legal 
enactments and rules of procedure, and to lose sight of 
the body of the law as a dynamic system. 

Here we will not concern ourselves with the anatomy of 
the law, but rather with its physiology, and will consider 
the law as a social force in its relation to the general pro- 
cess of social development. 

Under the designation "Law" in the broadest sense of 
the term, we understand the entire body of legislative 
enactments, rules and regulations which prescribe the 
relations of man to man, man to state, state to man and 
state to state. 

The law thus defined is not fixed or universal : it varies 
with the different types of civilization past and present. 
There is a radical difference between the laws of the 
ancient Greek communities, medieval European society, 
and the modem civilized states, and there is as radical a 
difference between the systems of law prevalent in the 
semi-barbaric countries of South Africa, the empire of 
China and the democracy of the United States. 

Nor are the laws of any given country immutable, il 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



feet, nothing is n 



changeable than the system of i 



tional laws in the modem countries. Every year volumes 
of new laws and ordinances are issued from the halls of 
Congress or parliaments, the inferior legislative chambers 
and the councils of thousands of municipalities; every 
year iimumerable old laws are repealed or amended, and 
innumerable new laws are enacted. The thing that is 
legal to-day may be branded as a crime to-morrow, new \ I 
rights may be conferred on or taken from us, and new ■ 
duties may be imposed on us by every legislative session, 
and especially in the Anglo-Saxon countries new laws may 
grow out overnight by the process of judicial "construc- 
tion," 

But these changes m the law are by no means arbitrary. 

Individual measures may at times be needless and illogical, 

but in the long run all changes in a given system of Uw 

mark a development in a certain definite direction. A 

I system of jurisprudence is just as much subject to the 

[ laws of evolution as any other social institution. 

The primitive man has but little use or occasion for 
I laws. But the higher the plane of human civilization, the 
I doser the interrelation of men, the greater becomes the 
need of definite rules of conduct of the members of such 
organization in all matters pertaining to tJie common wel- 
fare. Those of such rules that are more vital to the main- 
tenance of the social fabric are as a rule enacted into formal 
laws, while those of less direct and important bearing are 
left within the domain of ethics, "Normally," says Mr. 
Sidgwick, " in a well-organized society the most important 
and mdispensable rules of social behavior will be legally 
„enforced, and the less important left to be maintained by 
Wcmtive Morality. , . . Law will constitute, as it were. 



THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



i 



the skeleton of social order, clothed by the flesh and blood 
of Morality." ' Law and ethics have thus a common 
origin, and while by no means identical in all respects, they 
present a great similarity in many aspects. 

Law, like ethics, springs from the economic and social ; 
conditions of the nations, and from its very origin it must ■ 
be adapted to and change with those conditions. A tribe, 
race or nation will in each period establish such rules or 
laws as will be most conducive to the successful pursuit 
of its mode of subsistence, and as each of the succeeding 
economic and social orders gradually grow out of the 
preceding systems, new laws are created to meet the 
changed situation. The feudal system gave us the Law 
of Real Property, the development of national and inter- 
national commerce led to the Law of Negotiable Instru- 
ments, the rise of the factory inscribed the Labor Laws in 
our statute book, and practically in our own times the 
introduction of railroads, telegraphs and telephones added 
new and important branches to our body of law, while the 
more recent economic categories of corporations and trusts 
still keep our legislative mills busy. "The evolution which 
led men to an orderly social life did not consist in the dia- 
lectic self -development of juridic ideas," says Arnold 
Lindwurm, "but in the economic development brought 
about by social necessity." ^ 

The law of each civilization, again like its ethics, not 
only reflects the economic and social conditions of the 
times, but is primarily designed to safeguard and maintain 
those conditions. That is why we find such a variance 

' "The Methods of Ethics," p. ig. 

'"Dag Eigenlhumsrecht und die Menschheits ^ Idee im Slaale," 
Leipbic, 1878, p. 139. 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



in the criminal law of different states in its estimate of the 
gra\ity of certain crimes. "Ev ery state," says Dr. Ru- 
dolph von .Ihering,. "gunis hes tho se crimes most severely 
which threaten its. own peculiar condition of existence, 
w hjie it all ows a moderalioiL Ig^prey ail in regard to other 
crimes which, not unfrequently, presents a very striking 
contrast to its severity as against the former. A theocracy 
bran ds blasphemy and idolatry as crimes deserving of 
death, while it looks on a boundary violation as a mere 
misdeme anor (Mosaic Law). The agricultural state, on 
the other hand, \isits the latter with the severest punish- 
ment, while it lets the blasphemer go with the lightest 
punishment {Old Roman Law). The commercial state 
punishes most severely the uttering of false coin; the 
military state, insubordination and breach of official duty; 
the absolute slate, high treason; the republic, the striving 
after regal power; and they all manifest a severity in 
these points which contrasts greatly with the manner in 
which they punish other crimes. In short, the reaction of 
the feeling of legal right, both of states and individuals, 
is most violent when they feel themselves threatened in the 
conditions of existence peculiar to them." ' 

The statement that the law is always designed to safe- 
guard the existing economic conditions of society must, 
however, again as in the case of ethics, be qualified 
by the further statement that the law of each period is 
primarily designed to safeguard and protect the interests 
of the dominant classes within such society. 

The legal systems of antiquity, the Greek and Roman 
Law, made no attempt to disguise that fact. The subject 
^ class, the class of slaves, frequently the overwhelming 
"Struggle for Law," English Translation, Chicago, 1B79, pp. 45, 46. 



I 



70 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

majority of the population, was placed beyond the pale 
of the law. The slave was excluded from the protection 
of the law and left to the arbitrary treatment of his master. 
The institution of serfdom, which lasted throughout the 
Middle Ages and in some instances survived into the nine- 
teenth century, presents a similar state of affairs. 

Prior to the great French Revolution, the nobihty and 
clergy openly enjoyed special legal privileges from which 
the common people were excluded, and while the form of 
legal class favoritism has been abolished in most of the 
enlightened contemporary states, our laws on the whole 
still favor the ruling classes. 

Since the law is the expression of social and economic 
conditions in motion, every improvement in those condi- 
tions leads to a correspondmg improvement m the system 
of law. The course of political and economic improve- 
ment which on the whole marks our social progress, reflects 
itself in the ever-growing tendency towards equity and 
justice in law. Compared with the miquitous laws of 
mediaeval ages, our laws to-day are exceedingly humane, 
and generally speaking, every succeeding phase of a legal 
system is superior to the preceding phase. This applies 
to all domains of the law — private, public and inter- 
national. 

But legal progress does not run parallel with social 
and economic advance. As a rule the law lags somewhat 
behind existing conditions. New factors in our industrial 
life from time to time create new social conditions, and 
produce new conceptions of social rights and obligations. 
These remain abstract and debatable theories until such 
time as they have been incorporated in the statute books, 
and a penalty has been attached to their violation. Then, 



I 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



n 



' and then only, they are transferred from the domain of 
ethics to that of law. 

But the recognition of these rights, as a rule, does not 
occur automatically. Moral rights do not ripen into laws 
^ by a process of natural growth, nor are acquired laws self- 
executing. Reforms in law and legal redress are conquered 
in struggle, and, in most cases, in hard, obstinate struggle'3 
The effort to effect equitable legal reform or secure suci? 
, the " struggle for law," as-Sr. ven— IteriHg-terms 
i different forms in the different provinces of 
the law. In the domain of private law such efforts find 
I daily application in litigation; in the domain of public 
L law, these efforts are expressed in politics, and their realiza- 
tion is sometimes effected by revolutions; in international 
L law the struggle is expressed in the diplomatic dealings of 
the nations, and sometimes culminates in war. ^' All social 
* classes," says the eminent Italian jurist Alfredo Tortori, 
"are impelled to make such laws, to establish such insti- 
tutions and to sanction such customs and beliefs as accord 
with their direct or indirect interests. Hence the perpet- 
ual movement which drives men and groups to change ex- 
isting laws and to adapt them to new social interests." ' 
^nd this struggle for right and law is the key to all social 
Lprogress^l The man who suffers personal wrong without 
Iprotest or opposition, the "peaceful" member of the com- 
l munity, is a demoralizing factor in our social fabric; the 
class that does not struggle for civic and industrial rights 
will eventually lapse into slavery; and the nation that 
passively countenances encroachments upon its rights 
and territory is doomed to dismemberment and national 
bankruptcy. 

' "Sociaiisrae et droEt privi," in Le Devenir Social, 1896, p. asi. 



73 



THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



It is the man who defends his rights, the class that 
battles for political and industrial advancement, and the 
nation that holds its own against the entire world; it is 
the "litigious" person, the "revolutionary" class and the 
" vigilant " nation that keep the world from stagnation 
and force it onward on the path of progress. 

Conservatism and meekness and the pietistic veneration 

for the laws and customs of our forefathers, are not civic 

virtues, but vicious manifestations of mental indolence and 

political reaction. The progress of mankind lies in the 

future, not in the past. 

r — Let us test the truth of these general observations by a 

\ comparison of three systems of law corresponding to three 

I phases of human civilization ; the feudal system, immedi- 

^'l ately preceding our own, the modem or capitalistic system 
/_and the proposed system of socialism. 
The Feudal System of Law 

The system of feudalism was evolved in the period of 
turbulence into which Europe was thrown by the migra- 
tion of nations, and represented the first attempt to reduce 
the general social chaos and confusion of that period to 
some social order. 

The system was based on landownership and agriculture, 
both of which were rendered highly precarious by inces- 
sant wars and pillage, and naturally produced all the 
complex features of the social, political and legal organiza- 
tion of feudal society. 

The tiller of the soil in the early stages of feudal civiliza- 
tion was in constant danger of having his fields devastated 
and crops destroyed by the incursion of hostile hordes of 
marauders, and the protection from this ever present 



SOCIAUSM AND LAW 



73 



^ 



[anger was a necessary part of his agricultural pursuits. 
The man with the sword was as indispensable to the culti- 
vation of the land as the man with the plow, and the first 
division of labor in feudal society is formed on these lines. 
The warrior is a pubhc functionary in the early feudal 
community ; he protects the tillers of the soil from molesta- 
tion in the pursuit of their daily occupations, and in return 
he receives from them his necessary means of subsistence 
in the shape of a portion of their crops. The warrior 
lives among the other members of the community; he is 
part of them, but his dwelling house is the largest in the 
settlement, and is fortified, so as to offer a refuge to the 
villagers and their property and cattle in case of attack. 

In the further progress of feudal civilization the social 
relations become more permanent and fixed. The division 
of social functions develops into class differences. The 
warrior through long years of use and a process of heredi- 
tary transmission of social functions arrogates to himself 
the power over his fellow-men which the monopoly of arms 
places in his hands: the settlement becomes the feudal 
Manor, and the fortified manor house, the Castle; the 
warrior turns into the Noble, the worker into the Villein, 
and the voluntary compensation for military services grows 
into a fixed annual tribute — the Tithe and compulsory 
military service. 

Land was now the principal wealth and source of power 
in feudal society, and pillage and robbery the accepted 
means of its acquisition. War became the industrial 
pursuit of the noble. 

Conquering a strange community, the victorious leader 
frequently reduced its inhabitants to the state of serfdom, 
ippropriated their land, and endowed his retainers with 



; 



74 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

portions of it. But just as frequently the noble " protector" 
would rob his own subjects of large parcels of the commu- 
nal land. The class of the nobles thus became a land- 
owning class, and brute force was the origin of its title. 

The greed for land and the necessity of defending their 
possessions engendered an ever increasing strife among the 
nobles and led to military offensive and defensive alliances 
between them which m^e up the graduated and complex 
political structure of mediaeval society. 

At this stage of development, which we may consider 
the period of bloom of feudal civilization, the social rela- 
tions, notwithstanding their rough appearances, are still 
not altogether based on force. The social order, strange 
as it may seem, still rests very largely on the principle of 
mutual service between the classes, 

"The feudal lord," says Lafargue, "only holds his land 
and possesses a claim on the labor and harvests of his 
tenants and vassals on condition of doing suit and service 
to his superiors and lending aid to his dependants. On 
accepting the oath of fealty and homage the lord engaged 
to protect his vassal against all and sundry by all the means 
at his command; in return for which support the vassal 
was bound to render military and personal service and 
make certain payments to his lord. The latter in his turn, 
for the sake of protection, commended himself to a more 
puissant feudal lord, who himself stood in the relation of 
vassalage to a suzerain, to the king or emperor. 

All the members of the feudal hierarchy, from the serf 
upwards to the king or emperor, were bound by the ties of 
reciprocal duties." ' 

' Paul Lafargue, "The Evolution of Property," English Translation, 
London, 1S94, p. 79. 



I 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



Under the existing conditions of the times the class of 
I, nobility was, therefore, on the whole a socially useful 



But in the succeeding centuries, the onward march of 
I civilization gradually but radically changed the social 
I conditions of Europe. The logical trend of feudal de- 
L velopment led to ever vaster and more powerful alliances 
I based on a hierarchy of power aqd duties, to political con- 
f centration and ultimately to the formation of monarchical 
[states. The natural cHect of this course of development 
F was to limit strife and warfare, and a number of other 
causes served to accelerate that process. The introduc- 
tion of gunpowder was a death blow to knight errantry, 
and the humanizing mfluences of a more enlightened 
civilization, ushered in by the period of the Renaissance as 
well as the rise of commerce and industry, destroyed the 
very foundation upon which the feudal 'order pas built. 
Feudal society was broken up, and the dominant class 
k which it had produced was deprived of all its useful social 
J functions. But not of its power. The nobility ceased to 
render service to the community, but it did not discard the 
I habit of levying tribute upon it. As landowners, courtiers, 
magistrates and high dignitaries of church and state, the 
•noblemen retained themselves in power for centuries after 
the passing of feudal society. 

But in the course of those centuries, a new and formi- 
dable rival for power was slowly developing in the bosom 
r of society — the class of commercial and industrial burgh- 
a*s — the bourgeoisie. 

Manufacture, which in the earlier stages of feudalism 

vas a very subordinate occupation confined to the village, 

[ and exercised by its followers as a sort of public service in 



76 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

return for a scant living, received an ever larger extension 
as society became more settled. The development of 
village markets and the rise of towns encouraged inde- 
pendent production of commodities and stimulated trade, 
which, with the discovery of the sea route to India and the 
discovery of America, received a new and larger impulse. 
The merchants' and manufacturers' guilds soon became 
a power in the state, and the town, a growing factor in 
the political life of the nation. 

Henceforward, the history of Europe is the history of 
the struggle between these two classes for polirical su- 
premacy. The titled descendants of the robber barons 
of every country unite in the eflort to maintain their in- 
herited social, political and economic ascendency, and to 
stem the threatening tide of the rising power of the churl- 
ish newcomers, and in these efforts they are as a rule 
supported by the Catholic clergy, whose social and eco- 
nomic position is very similar to their own. On the other 
hand, the rising bourgeoisie strives everywhere for free- 
dom from the fetters of the feudal order, which impede 
its movement for the establishment of a free competitive 
international market of commerce and manufacture. 

The struggle results uniformly in the victory of the 
young and vigorous bourgeoisie over the enfeebled nobility- 
The last act in this historical drama is the general Euro- 
pean Revolution which formally establishes the rule of the 
industrial bourgeoisie in all countries of Europe, whether 
such revolution is accomplished with little bloodshed, as in 
Great Britain in the seventeenth century, or by spectacular 
acts and carnage, as in France at the end of the eighteenth 
century, or by a slow and almost imperceptible process, as 
in Germany towards the middle of the last century. 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



17 



Such, in brief, is the career of the feudal system, and 
that career with all its phases of development and strug- 
gles is faithfully portrayed in the laws of the period. 

The formative stages of the feudal order are not con- 
ducive to the development of any general system of juris- 
prudence. Society is spht into innumerable separate and 
very loosely connected communities, in each of which the 
arbitrary will of the feudal lord is the supreme law. The 
system of law of that period has been aptly described by 
Stubbs as "a graduated system of jurisprudence based on 
land tenure, in which every lord taxed and commanded 
the class next below him; in which abject slavery formed 
the lowest and irresponsible tyranny the highest grade; 
in which private war, private coinage, private prisons, 
took the place of the imperial institutions of the govern- 
ment." ^ The legal doctrine that the sovereign can do no 
wrong and the more modem doctrine of the immunity of 
the state from legal process, are directly traceable to that 
period of jurisprudence. 

The succeeding phase of feudalism, with its hierarchic 
order of vassalage and the graduated system of reciprocal 
rights and duties, finds its expression in the law of prop- 
erty and inheritance. Land, practically the sole means 
of existence and the source of all social power, is not 
considered private property. The feudal lord holds his 
land and enjoys the right to its income as a sort of trustee 
for his dependants; his title to the land is not one in fee 
simple, or absolute ownership, but is subject to the superior 
rights of his immediate lord as well as to the numerous 
rights and easements of his subjects. The absolute legal 
^tle to all the land vests in the king as the representative 
' "Constitutional History," pp. 955, 256. 



78 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

of the nation, a theory which has left very distinct traces 
in the present-day legal doctrine of the right of Eminent 
Domain. 

The feudal lord is the military officer in command of 
the fief or manor, and that office upon his death descends 
to his oldest son, together with the duties of protection 
which it entaOs. His landownership is merely an inci- 
dent of office and, therefore, descends to his oldest son 
as his successor in office. The entailed estates, the law of 
intestacy and primogeniture are the juridical expression of 
the social order of that epoch of feudal bloom. 

The period of dissolution of feudal society with its 
accompanying struggles between the landowning noble 
class and the industrial class are written in large letters 
in the legal evolution of that period of social transition. 
The doivnfall of feudalism and the triumph of the bour- 
geoisie are signalized by the removal of restrictions upon 
the alienation of land and freedom of trading, the intro- 
duction of the testament, the abolition of guilds and guild 
laws, and the eradication of all legal privileges of nobility 
and clergy. 

The Modern System of Law 

The basis of modem society differs from that of the 
feudal system in every essential. Under feudalism, as 
we have seen, the principal pursuit is agriculture and the 
principal form of wealth is landownership. The ownership 
of land is the basis of all social relations and political 
rights. It creates the hierarchy of rank, the feeling of ter- 
ritorial solidarity, the sense of communal interest, and the 
spirit of conservatism which are characteristic of that 
phase of civilization. 



SOCIAUSM AND LAW 



79 



Contemporary society, on the other hand, rests mainly 
on manufacture and trading. The wealth of modem 
nations is represented principally by movable objects and 
commodities, or personal property, and all our social re- 
lations are based on the ownership of such property. 

The right to produce, consume and dispose of all com- 
modities at will, is a necessary incident of their full en- 
joyment, hence the absolute ownership of all property, 
the freedom of its production and its unrestricted use, 
are the pillars upon which all modern law rests. 

Private Property and its logical corollaries. Competitive 
Industry and Individual Liberty, are the new Trinity 
which the rule of the bourgeoisie has established in modem 
civilization. These three guiding principles find their 
most eloquent and finished expression in the American 
Declaration of Independence and the French Declaration 
of Human Rights, the two instruments framed spon- 
taneously and in their entirety as the expression of violent 
political revolutions; they animate the unwritten con- 
stitution of England and the written constitutions of all 
other parliamentary countries. 

Private property is also the foundation of all modem 
legislation, for all modem systems of law are principally 
designed for its protection. 

"In a general way," says the well-known criminologist, 
Zerboglio, "it may be considered as an established fact 
that the foundation and objects of criminal law are the 
preservation and the defense of that class which has 
constituted the modern system of Jurisprudence for the 
purpose of safeguarding its economic power." ' 

' A. Zerboglio, "Lutte de classe dans la legislatbti," in Le Devtnit 
^SoeM, iSg6, p. 143. 



I 80 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



"Offenses against property" are acts committed in an 
endeavor to acquire properly by means not sanctioned by 
law ,^ crimes committed for gain. But the direct offenses 
against property are not the oniy crimes committed from 
motives of gain. The overwhelming majority of crimes 
against the person, from murder in the first degree to 
simple assault, are most frequently committed with the 
object of material advantages: if they are not crimes 
against property they may be fitly designated as crimes 
for property. 

And what our criminal laws conceal and disguise to 
some extent, our civil laws reveal with the utmost frank- 
ness; the civil codes of every modem nation are chiefly 
a compilation of rules governing the regulation of disputes 
over property rights and regulating relations of property 
owners between themselves. 

"If we examine any ground of civil action," remarks 
Mr. Bax, "ye shall find it almost always turns directly 
or indirectly on a question of property; that is, on what 
individual shall possess certain wealth — the chances be- 
ing invariably on the side of the wealthy litigant."* 

Except for its protection of private property and the 
principle of free competition as instanced by the anti-trust 
and anti-monopoly legislation, the general policy of our 
modem law is one of non-interference. The famous 
watchword, "Laissez-faire," apphes to bourgeois laws as 
well as to bourgeois economics. 

This policy is based on the assumption of equality of . 
all citizens and their ability to adjust their own relations 
without the mterference of the state. And in the period 

' Ernest Belfort Bax, "The Religion of Socialism," London, 1901, 



SOaALISM AND LAW 



8l 



E inception of the present social order this assumption 
was not entirely unwarranted. When manufacture was 
in its infancy, and was carried on by primitive methods 

. and with the aid of simple and inexpensive tools, the in- 

I dustrial field was practically tree to aU artisans. There 
were no fixed lines between "capitalists" and "wage 
workers" as distinct and permanent classes: employer 
and employee met on terms of some equality ; their rela- 
tions were largely created by voluntary and reciprocal 
contract. But with the development of the complex and 
expensive modem instruments of production, these instru- 
ments passed into the hands of the possessing classes, who 
thus acquired a monopoly of the modem industrial pro- 
cess, while the non-possessing classes were reduced to the 
status of wage workers. 

The assumed equality of all men thus became a mere ' 
fiction, at least as far as the economic relations of the 
citizens are concerned, and all social legislation based on 
that assumption henceforward had the effect of sanc- 
tioning the power of the strong to exploit the weak. In a 
society of economic equals the law might properly abstain . 
from mterfering with the industrial relations of the citi- i 
zens, but in a society in which economic supremacy places | 
one class of citizens in an artificial position of advantage 
over their fellow-citizens, the office of just legislation 
should be to protect the weak against the abuses of the 
strong. The failure of modern law to afford such pro- 

-tection to the workingmen in itself shows partiality 'm 
the interests of the ruling classes. 

"Upon this point," observes Loria, "a comparison 
between modem and medieval law is enlightening. 

w)uring the Middle Ages, when capital was weak and 



82 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

labor acquired its strength from the existence of free land, 
the law came to the assistance of capital by regulating 
the labor contract in a manner hostile to the laborer's 
interest. In our times, on the contrary, when capital is 
strong and labor is deprived of its liberty of action, the 
law amply fulfills its office of guardian of property by 
abstaining from regulating the wage contract at all, and 
leaving it to the dictation of capital." ' 

A striking mstance of this rule is to be found in the 
enactment and repeal of the famous English " Statute of 
LaUorers." The epidemic of the "black death" in the 
middle of the fourteenth century had vastly decreased 
the supply of labor, and wages were gomg up rapidly. 
Parliament passed a law making work compulsory on 
all propertyless persons below the age of sixty years at 
wages that had been customary in the year 1347, i.e., 
before the plague, and this law with a number of successive 
amendments and variations remamed in force until the 
beginning of the nineteenth century, when the develop- 
ment of machinery and the modem processes of produc- 
tion had created a superfluity of labor and a rubious com- 
petition among the workers themselves. The laws &dng 
the rate of wages then became useless and embarrassing 
} to the employing classes, and were speedily repealed. 
But the wage contract is not the only instance of the 
; of the workingmen under the law arising 
from the principle of non-interference. Another and per- 
3 more conspicuous illustration of the iniquitous effect 
of that principle is to be found in the employers' liability 
laws of modem nations, particularly the nations whose 

: Foundations of Society," English 




SOCIALISM AND LAW 



83 



systems of Jurisprudence are based on the Anglo-Saxon 
common law. The doctrine of the assumption by the 
workingman of the "obvious risks of employment," and 
his inability to recover damages for injuries where such 

I injuries were caused in whole or in part by his "contribu- 
tory negligence" or by the negligence of a "fellow-ser- 
vaot," have for their theoretical basis the fiction that the 
modern workingman of his own free choice determines 
how, where and with whom he shall work. The practical 

I effect of these doctrines is that m most cases the work- 
ngman remains without remedy agamst his employer. 
The fictitious "equality of all citizens before the law" 

i furthermore favors the possessing classes as against the 

' classes of non-possessors in matters of modem legal pro- 
cedure at least as much as in matters of substantial law. 
The fact that the practice of law is a business pursuit of 
the private practitioner coupled with the complicated, tech- 
nical and expensive nature of litigation, frequently puts 
justice beyond the reach of the poor. "The law," ex- 
claims the eminent Italian jurist already quoted, "is a 
monopoly of wealth, and in the temple of Themis there 
is no place reserved for the laborer." ' 

Nor is the character of modem law as the guardian of 
the possessing classes and the whip of the poor, evidenced 
by its passive attitude alone. The rigid prohibitions 
against labor combinations in the various modem coun- 
tries, the strict penalties for all labor interferences with 
the "rights" of the employing class, and the severe treat- 
ment by the courts of all "transgressions" of workmgmen 
in thehr struggles against their employers, furnish eloquent 
proof of the law's positive partiality for the ruling classes. 
' Loria, "Economic Foundations of Society," p. 114. 



I 





r 84 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



Social Legislation and Socialist Jurisprudence 

As the feudal regime at a certain stage of its develop- 
ment became burdensome on the class of the " bourgeoisie" 
and caused them to revolt against that regime, so has the 
modem industrial order become burdensome upon the 
working classeSj and the latter already show symptoms of 
revolt against it. The more advanced workingmen of all 
countries begin to regard the economic dependence of 
their class and the privileged position of the employing 
classes as a social injustice. They feel that the part of 
the toilers in the process of production entitles them to a 
larger share of the national product, and that they are 
despoiled and deprived of their just due by the classes in 
power. They demand an ever greater consideration and 
protection for labor, and an ever larger curtailment of the 
privileges of wealth. 

These demands of the workingmen assume for them 
the form of social or ethical rightSj and their struggles are 
struggles to realize their rights as laws. The character 
of the legislation which the working class thus advocates 
and strives for, is diametrically opposed to all the funda- 
mental principles of modem or bourgeois law. It is based 
on the right of persons instead of property rights, and on 
social regulation, control and protection, instead of the 
principles of free competition and non-interference. And 
as the working-class movement grows in strength, intelli- 
gence and determination, the ruling classes are forced to 
make concessions to it, either by way of granting or fore- 
stalling its demands. 

This is the secret of the recent reaction against the 
sacred "laissez-faire" principle of modem law, and the 



r SOCIALISM AND LAW 85 

I source of all "social legislation" of the last few decades. 
I In Germany, social legislation was inaugurated at a time 
I ■when the socialist movement had demonstrated that it 
I was strong enough to withstand the assault of the anti- 
I socialist laws. The motive of the government in intro- 
' ducing such legislation was revealed by the Iron Chan- 
cellor with his characteristic frankness in the following 
speech, delivered in the Imperial Diet in :88i: — 

"That the state should take better care of its needy 
members than heretofore is not only a dictate of humane- 
ness and Christianity, but also a necessity of conservative 
politics which should aim to cultivate in the non-possessing 
classes of the population, who are at the same time the 
I most numerous and least instructed, the view that the state 
is not only a necessary but also a beneficent institution. 
To this end they must be led by means of direct advantages, 
derived through legislative enactment, to consider the 
state not as an institution created solely for the protection 
of the possessing classes, but as one serving their own 
needs and interests. The objection that such legislation 
would introduce a socialistic element must not deter us 
from our course." 

In France the first social legislation was introduced by 
Napoleon III as a measure intended to combat the grow- 
ing influence of the International Workingmen's Associa- 
tion, In England, in the United States and in all other 
modem countries, the beginnings of systematic " factory 
legislation" coincide, broadly speaking, with the begm,- 
nings of the organized labor movement, and its extension 
keeps pace with the growth of the labor movement. 
The current of social legislation takes two distinct 
Ldirections, one being designed to protect the workmen, and 



THE SOCIALIST PmLOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



the other to regulate and limit the power of industrial 
capitalism. To the former class belong the laws pro- 
viding for workingmen's insurance in case of sickness 
and disability, the old-age pension laws, and the large 
body of laws popularly known as Factory Legislation, 
i. e., laws limiting the hours of labor.pf women. and chil::-, 
dren, and of men in certain lines of employment, estab- 
lishing rules for the health and safety of the operatives in 
mines, mills, factories and other works, extending the 
liability of employers for injuries sustained by their work- 
men, regulating the payment of wages, and similar meas- 
ures affecting the duties of employer to employed. 

In the second class of legislation must be counted all 
laws which attempt to check the excessive accumulation 
of wealth in the hands of private individuals, such as the 
income and inheritance tax laws, and laws having for their 
object the control and regulation of certain industries, 
such as railroading, banking, insurance, etc. 

The net result of all such social legislation is as yet 
insignificant. On the whole it has had no great effect 
in improving the condition of the poor or limiting the 
power of the wealthy. But the importance of this line 
of legislation lies not in its positive achievements as 
much as in its symptomatic significance. The "social" 
laws of the last few decades mark a growing change in 
the popular conception of the office of legislation — the 
approach of a new legal system expressive of a new social 
era. For the forces that gave birth to the weak rudiments 
of social legislation are still at work, steadily gaining in 
extent and intensity. The struggles of the organized 
workingmen of all countries for a fair distribution of the 
national wealth and for equitable social relations among 



SOCIALISM AND LAW 



87 



Pall men are finding ever stronger support among all classes 
I of the population, and are bound to continue. The 
P logical end of ali legal reforms accompanying these strug- 
gles is the substitution of a system of law based on 
the principle of socialism for the present individualistic 
system. 

An d wh ile it would be folly to attempt at this time a 
comprehensive outline of a socialist sysleni 'of tai^7 WC" 
.iave. sufficient concrete data in the present tendencies of 
social development to enable us to indicate the, funda- 
mental principles and general aspect of that proposed 
system of jurisprudence. 

A socialist society is one based on the system of public 
, or collective ownership of the material instruments of pro- 
duction, democratic administration of the industries, and 
cooperative labor; and the guiding principle of such so- 
ciety must be the recognition of the right of existence and 
enjoyment inherent in every human being. 

The function of law under socialism will of necessity 
b^t^ insure the stability of these principles and insfitii* ' " 
lions, just as it has been its function at all earlier periods 
^of_human civOization to insure the stability of the institu- 
tions of such periods. But in a socialist society the func- 
tion of law will be largely simplified by the disappearance 
of class distinctions. In a society of industrial equals, in 
r which the material interests of all citizens are identical, and 
Ithe interests of every citizen accord with those of the state, 
f the motives for all crimes against property and for many 
crimes against the person are removed, and with their 
removal disappears the necessity of legislating against 
such crimes, while the abolition of private competitive 
industry and trading must have the effect of eradicating 



88 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

from our statute books the major part of all our civil and 
commercial laws. 

In direct opposition to the modem system of law, which 
deals largely with the reciprocal relations and private 
conduct of individual citizens, and pays but scant atten- 
tion to the industrial life of the nation, a socialist system 
of jurisprudence must of necessity occupy itself primarily 
with the regulation of the social processes of wealth pro- 
duction and distribution, and limit its interference with 
the private life and conduct of the citizen to a minimum. 



CHAPTER V 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



Nature and Evolution of the Stale 

One of the most interesting theoretical discussions that 
ever occupied a modem political parliament was that con- 
ducted in the German Diet on the occasion of its delibera- 
tions on the proposed budget of 1893. It was towards 
the close of the session ; the dissolution of the Diet was 
imminent, and the Social Democracy, which in the pre- 
vious elections had polled close to one and a half million 
votes, loomed up large as a menacing factor in the com- 
ing elections. By common accord the subject under im- 
mediate consideration was suspended, the debate of the 
Diet was made the pretext for an electoral campaign and 
the sole topic of discussion was the proposed SociaHst 
State. It was a battle royal which lasted three consecu- 
tive days. The most eloquent speakers of all anti- socialist 
parliamentary parties in Germany took part in the debate, 
mercilessly criticising the socialist aims and ideals, and 
demolishing the structure of the proposed socialist state 
as they conceived it. 

When the turn came to the brilliant socialist leader, 
August Bebel, he rather nonplussed his colleagues in the 
Diet by the somewhat startlmg declaration that the phrase 
"Socialist State" was in itself an absurdity, and that a 
ate" could not possibly exist under a socialist ort" 



90 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

The same idea is expressed by Bebel more explicitly 
in his "Woman," where, in discussing the effects of the 
proposed economic reforms of socialism on the political 
organization of society, he says: — ■ 

"The state organization as such gradually loses its 
foundation. The state is the organization of force for 
the mamtenance of existing relations of property and 
social rule. But as the relations of master and servant 
disappear with the abolition of the present system of 
property, the political expression of the relationship ceases 
to have any meaning. The state expires with the expira- 
tion of the ruling class, just as religion expires when the 
belief in supernatural beings or supernatural reasoning 
ceases to exist. Words must represent ideas; if they 
lose their substance, they no longer correspond to any- 
thing." '■ 

This conception of the state is by no means peculiar 
to Bebcl. It has been expressed by many socialist think- 
ers of prominence before and after him, and its source is 
to be found in the following passage from the writings of 
Frederick Engels, one of the theoretical founders of 
modern socialism: — 

" By reducing the ever greater majority of the population 
to the rank of proletarians, the capitalist mode of pro- 
duction creates the power which is compelled to bring 
about this social transformation under penally of its own 
destruction. By forcing the conversion of the large 
socialized means of production into state ownership, it 
' points itself the way towards the accomplishment of that 
I transformation. The wage workers seize the powers of 

I ' August Bebel, "Woman io the Pasi, Present and Future," San 
I Francisco, 1897, p. isS. 



SOQALISM AND THE STATE 



91 



the state and provisionally turn the means of production 
over to the state. But with this act they aboUsh their 
own existence as proletarians, and with this act they 
also abolish all class differences and class antagonisms 
and the state as a state. Heretofore society was based 
on class antagonisms and needed a ' state,' i.e., an organi- 
zation of the exploiting classes for the preservation of the 
existing -methods of production, and more particularly 
for the purpose of forcibly maintaining the exploited classes 
in the condition of dependence inherent in such methods 
of production (slavery, serfdom, wage labor). The state 
was the ofiicial representative of the whole society; it was 
its union in a visible body, but only inasmuch as it was 
the state of that class which represented to it the entire 
society: in antiquity, the state of the slave-ownmg citizens; 
in the Middle Ages, that of the feudal nobihty; in oitr 
times, that of the bourgeoisie. By actually becoming the 
representative of the whole society, the state becomes 
superfluous. As soon as there is no longer any class in 
society to be held in subjection, as soon as the class rule 
and the struggle for existence based on the modem an- 
archy in production are removed, and with them also 
the resultant struggles and excesses, there is nothing 
more to repress, nothing requiring a special repressing 
power, a state. The first act in which the state appears 
as the representative of entire society — the seizure of the 
instruments of production in the name of society — is at 
the same time its last independent act as a slate. The 
interference of the state with social relations becomes 
superfluous in one field after the other, and the state, 
as it were, falls asleep. The goverrmient of persons is 
replaced by the administration of things and the regula- 



I 



92 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

tion of the process of production. The state is not ' abol- 
ished,' it dies off. The phrase of the 'socialist state' 
may thus be judged for its value as a slogan in the tem- 
porary propaganda of socialism, and for its scientific 
inefficiency." ' 

It will be noticed that the socialist writers quoted see 
in the state a social institution different and apart from 
organized society as such. This is by no means the 
prevalent conception, and in fact there seems to be no 
fixed and generally accepted definition of the term in the 
popular or scientific literature of the subject. Few ex- 
pressions are tised so vaguely and loosely as the term 
"state." A large number of authoritative sociologica] 
writers and lexicographers by implication consider the 
state as a term synonymous with organized society, and 
expressly define it in that sense.* 

The fault of all such definitions is, that they do not 

'Frederick Engds, "Herni Eugen Duhring's Umwalzung der Wis- 
senschaften," 3d Edition, Sruttgait, 1B94. 

' "The whole body of the people united under one government, what- 
ever may be the form of the government." — Webster's Dictionary. 

"The state (iriXii) is an association of human beings — and the 
highest form of human association." ■ — AkietOile. 

"The state (respublica) is the creature of the people, the people united 
by a common sense of right and by a community of interest." — Cicero. 

"The state is organized mankind." — Johann K. Bujntcshli in 
"Lehre vom modernen Staat." 

"The state is an assemblage of persons united under the same gov- 
ernment." — TUBGOT. 

"The state is the people living within certain geographical limits. 
It represents a body of people having, in general, like sentiments, feelings 
and aims, 10 carry out which they originate some organic law which pro- 
vides for ministers or officers, and they constitute the government, which 
is but the agent of the people in eieculing the laws they have ordained." 
— Cabsoll T>. Wright in " Outline of Practical Sociology," New York, 
1899, pp. 88, 89. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



93 



define. All human society in a state of civilization is or- 
ganized, and the term "organized society" applies with 
equal force to the collectivity of contemporary mankind as 
to each separate nation or community. The "state" has 
a more limited and definite significance, and is more 
properly defined as a body of people united under one 
political government.' That the distinction is not a mere 
scholastic quibble, but a very material and weighty dif- 
ferentiation, becomes apparent as soon as we attempt to 
analyze it. Every political government is not only well 
defined territorially, but it also has certain other fixed 
and essential attributes: it must be based on a constitu- 
tion or on the will of an individual sovereign; it must be 
supported by laws that can be enforced ; it must have the 
machinery to enforce such laws and the power to raise 
revenue for the maintenance of such machinery; it must 
I also be represented by a person or class of persons invested 

' "A politiLal communily organized under a distinct government, 
recognized and conformed to by the people as supreme." — Standakd 

DiCTIONAHY. 

"When a number of persons are supposed to be in the habit of paying 
lAedienct to a person, or an assemblage of persons of a known and certain 
description, such persons altogether are said to be in a state of political 
Bociecy." — J. Beniham in "A Fragment of Government." 

"The supreme will of a stale, in whatever mode of sovereignty mani- 
I fested, etpresses itself and achieves its ends in various ways, but chiefly 
through Government, which may be delined as the requisition, direction 
and organization of obedience." ^ — ^ Franklin H. Giddengs in "Read- 
ings in Descriptive and Historical Sociology." 

"The state is an aggregation of individuals living in the same terri- 
I tory under the government of one supreme power." — Anton Mengeh 
B.tn "Neue Staatslehre." 
I "The stale is sovereign, i.e., it has the original, absolute, unlimited 

■ power over the individual subject and over all associations of subjects." 

■ — J. W. Burgess in "Political Science and Constitutional Law," New 
% York, 1900, p. 4. 



t94 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



with the powers of government. In short, the element 
of repression and coercion is essential to the existence of 
every state. 

"When the political community is regarded as ' society, '" 
says Mr. Bal!, "it is looked at as a number of individuals 
or classes or professions — as an aggregate of units. 
When we speak of the 'state,' we understand a single per- 
sonality, as it were, representing all these interests and 
endowed with force which it can exercise against any one 
of them. In other words 'the stale' cannot be reduced to 
'society' or to 'government,' which is only one of its func- 
tions, but is society organized and having force." ^ 

The keen French economist Leroy-Beaulieu observes: 
"The concrete state, as we see it at work in all countries, 
manifests, as an organism, two essential characteristics, 
which it always possesses, and which, moreover, it is alone 
in possessing; the power of imposing by methods of con- 
straint upon all the inhabitants of a territory the observ- 
ance of certain injunctions known by the name of laws 
or administrative regulations, and the power of raising, 
also by methods of constraint, from the inhabitants of that 
territory large sums of money of which it has the free dis- 
posal. The organism of the state is, therefore, essentially 
coercive; the constraint it exercises takes two forms, 
the one of laws, the other of taxes." ' 

Charles Eenoist in his "Politique" ' states the same 
proposition more tersely in affirming that the state may be 
recognized by two signs; it makes laws and levies taxes. 

' Sidney Ball, "The Moial Aspect of Socialism " in " Socialism and 
Individualism," Fabian Socialist Series, No. 3, London, IQ08, pp. 75, 76. 

' Paul Leroy-Beaulieu, "The Modern State," English Translation, 
London, 1891, p. 67. 

' Quoted by Gabriel Deville, "The State and Socialism." 



SOaALlSM AND THE STATE 



95 



If we enlarge the definition somewhat, and say, The state 
makes and enforces laws and levies taxes, we have men- 
tioned the most uniform and indispensable functions of 
every state. 

But the enumeration of these functions alone is quite 
sufficient to convict the state as a product of class strug- ■ 
gles. Law as distinguished from mere custom, law in the i 
sense of a positive command of the state enforceable by 
a penalty, has its inception in an order of things in which 
it is already in the interest of one part of the population 
to act in a manner prejudicial to their fellow-men, and in 
which it becomes necessary for the latter to restrain the 
former by force. Such an order of things, however, is 
only possible in a class society. Primitive society Is a 
society of economic equals. The community produces 
principally articles of immediate consumption, and that 
in quantities barely sufficient for the needs of its members, , 
There is no opportunity for the accumulation of private 
wealth, there are no rich and no poor, and no social classes 
of any kind. There ia neither motive nor chance for any 
man to covet the property or to trespass upon the "rights" 
of his neighbor, and there is no occasion to repress such 
desires by force. The primitive social organizations, the 
gentes and phratries, have no laws and no instruments to i 
enforce laws. Courts, judges, constables, prisons and 
police are entirely unknown to them; they levy no ti 
or compulsory tribute on their members ; they are entirely 
free from the element of coercion — they are not states. , 

It is only when the productivity of human labor has in- | 
creased to a degree beyond that required for the satis- 
faction of his indispensable personal needs, when man has ' 
become a possible object of exploitation, and when the first 



96 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

form of such exploitation has been introduced in the in- 
stitution of slavery, it is only then that repressive laws and 
organized social force become necessary. 

The state thus appears in the social development of 
mankind simultaneously with the institutions of 'private 
property and slavery and as their necessary concomitant. 
In its original form, it was frankly and without disguise 
the organization of the slave-owning class for the purpose 
of maintaining their authority over their slaves. The 
slaves themselves, as stated in the preceding chapter, 
were not members of the state, and there was no pretense 
that the state was "the body of the whole people." "The 
ancient state," says David G. Ritchie, "existed for the 
citizen and not for the unenfranchised multitudes, who 
were mere means to the state's existence and no part of 
the state itself. The Greek state existed for the few; 
the modern state professes to exist for all — and may do 
so some day in reality." ' 

With the gradual change of economic conditions and 
social relations, the state has steadily modified its outward 
garb, but its true functions and inner mechanism have 
largely remained unchanged. The state has at all times 
been the instrument of the possessing classes; its chief 
function has always been to maintain the existing order, i.e., 
the supremacy of the ruling classes and the dependence of 
the non-possessing classes, and even to-day it is the privi- 
lege of the classes in power " to make laws and to levy 
taxes," while it is the duty of the poor to obey the laws 
and to pay the taxes. 

The socialist definition of the state as an organization of 

the ruling classes for the maintenance of the exploited 

' "The Principle of Stale Interference," London, 1902, p. 101. 



SOaALISM AND THE STATE 



97 



N 



classes in a condition of dependence, is thus entirely cor- 
rect in substance. 

But in connection with this definition another factor 
must be considered. The ruling classes of every period 
are created by the prevalent economic conditions of that 
period and they change with the change in these conditions. 
The slave-owning class was superseded in history by the 
class of feudal landlords, and the latter by the modem 
bourgeoisie, and with the accession of every new class of 
rulers the character and constitution of the state assumed 
a different aspect. These changes are rarely distinguish- 
able by definite lines of demarcation. As a rule they take 
place gradually and are accompanied by protracted and 
obstinate struggles between the declining and rising classes, 
and it is not always easy to determine which of the two 
contendmg classes is the ruling class. In such periods of 
transition the state reflects the indefinite character of the 
social and economic conditions, and while in the main it 
always serves the interests of the class temporarily in power, 
it frequently makes important concessions to the rebellious 
classes. Thus the state of the fourteenth century was a 
feudal state, pure and simple, without any admixture of 
foreign elements ; but the state of the seventeenth century, 
while still feudal in its main characteristics, already pre- 
sented many elements of bourgeois power. And similarly, 
the state of a century and even half a century ago was an 
imalloyed bourgeois state, while the present-day state 

- already shows deep inroads made m its substance and 
functions by the rising class of wage workers. 

Under the pressure of the socialist and labor movement 
in all civilized countries, the state has acquired a new sig- 

bi^Ilificance as an mstrument of social and economic reform. 



98 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

Such reforms have already demonstrated the ability of 
the state to curb the industrial autocracy of the ruling 
classes and to protect the workers from excessive exploi- 
tation by their employers. 

The modern state, originally the tool in the hands of the 
capitalist class for the exploitation of the workers, is grad- 
ually coming to be recognized by the latter as a most 
potent instrument for the modification and ultimate aboli- 
tion of the capitalist class rule. In the general scheme 
of socialism, the state has, therefore, the -very important 
mission of paving the way for the transition from present 
conditions to socialism. The state in that r61e is gener- 
ally styled in the literature of socialism the "period of 
transition, " or the " transitional state." Beyond it lies the 
pure socialist order. 

Does that order still admit of the existence of a state, 
or must the state, as the product of class divisions in so- 
ciety, fall with the disappearance of those class divisions 
as asserted by Engels and his followers? 

At the first glance the proposition seems almost axio- 
matic ^ with the removal of the cause, the effect must fail. 
But on closer analysis the question seems by no means free 
from doubt. A social institution may be called into life 
by certain conditions and for certain purposes, but may 
gradually adapt itself to new and entirely different con- 
ditions and purposes. In fact, the history of our civiliza- 
tion is replete with instances of social, political, religious 
and legal institutions which have long survived their origi- 
nal creating causes, and in an altered form have shown 
great vitality imder new conditions. The modern state 
exhibits many features that seem to indicate just such 
adaptability and vitality. The state, which came into being 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



99 



' as an instrument of class repression, has gradually, 
and especially within the last centuries, assumed other 
important social functions, functions in which it largely 
represents society as a whole, and not any particular class 
of it. Instances of such functions of the modern state 
may be found in the system of public education, sanitary 
and healtii regulations, and in the institutions of police and 
criminal justice to the extent to which they secure the per- 
sonal safety and security of all citizens. 

It is true, as Menger ' observes, that these functions con- 
stitute but a very small part of the activity of the state, 
and are as a rule relegated to its subordinate organs, such 
as municipalities, etc. ; but it is equally true that these gen- 
erally useful functions are claiming and receiving ever 
greater attention from the state, and that under a system 
of socialism they are certain to receive an immense ex- 
tension. 

If we realize that the socialist commonwealth must 
of necessity be charged with the direction, regulation or 
control of at least its principal industries, and with the care 
of its old and decrepit, sick, invalid and orphaned mem- 
bers, we shall readily see that the socialist organization will 
have to be something more than a mere " administration 
of things," — it will in all likelihood be a quite definitely 
organized society. 

But, it may be objected, a socialist society will be free 
from the element of coercion ; hence it will not be a state 
in the true sense of the term. 

Let us consider this objection. 

For the purposes of public works, health, safety and 

relief, the socialist commonwealth will need vast material 

' Anion Menger, "Neue Staatalehre," 3d Edition, Jena, 1904, p. 2a 




riOO THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



^ 



resources, probably more than the modern state, and these 
resources, in whatever form and under whatever designa- 
tion, can come only from the wealth-producing members 
of the commonwealth — thus there must be a direct or 
indirect tax on the labor or income of the citizen. The 
collection of this tax, the direction of the industries and 
the regulation of the relations between the citizens, will 
require some laws and some rules or instruments for their 
enforcement; hence even the element of coercion cannot 
be entirely absent in a socialist society, at least not as far 
as the human mind can at present conceive. The socialist 
society as conceived by modern socialists differs, of course, 
very radically from the modern state in form and substance. 
It is not a class state, it does not serve any part of the 
population and does not rule any other part of the popu- 
lation; it represents the interests of the entire community, 
and it is for the benefit of the entire community that it 
levies taxes and makes and enforces laws. It is not the 
slaveholding state, nor the feudal state, nor the state of the 
bourgeoisie, — it is a socialist state, but a state neverthe- 
less, and since little or nothing can be gained by inventing a 
new term, we shall hereafter designate the proposed or- 
ganized socialist society as the Socialist State. 



The Transitional State 



Modern socialists recognize that social institutions axe 
not the results of arbitrary choice, but of historical growth. 
When the ever working forces of industrial evolution have 
created new economic interests and social relations, the 
political forms of society must be modified to meet these 
changes, and when these new interests and relations become 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



r 



incompatible with the very basis of the existing social 
■system, that system is bound to give way to a more ade- 
quate order. The socialists contend that the present 
system of individual ownership in the large and social 
means of production, and the system of industrial com- 
petition based on such individual ownership, have become 
or are fast becoming incompatible with the interests of an * 
ever growing majority of the population and with the prog- 
ress of industry itself. They perceive a tendency in the 
modem industrial development towards the collective 
ownership of these means of production and the socializa- 
tion of industries; they see the public necessity of such 
transformation, and advocate and demand its accomplish- 
ment. 

That is the whole of the socialist program, and it is 
certainly wide enough. The transformation of the means 
of production from private to public ownership is by no 
means a simple task. It is not reasonable to suppose that 
the possessing classes, the owners of the land, the mines, 
railroads and factories, the financiers and capitalists of 
all descriptions, will some fine day voluntarily surrender all 
their privileges and possessions to the people, nor is it 
likely that the transformation will be accomplished by one 
single and simple decree of the victorious proletariat all 
over the civilized world. More likely the process of trans- 
formation will be complicated and diversified, and will be 
marked by a series of economic and social reforms and 
legislative measures tending to divest the ruling classes 
of their monopolies, privileges and advantages, step by 
step, until they are practically shorn of the power to ex- 
ploit their fellow-men ; i.e., until all the important means 
of production have passed into collective ownership and 



ri02 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

all the principal industries are reorganized on the basis 
of socialist cooperation. The proposed measures that 
are expected to eBect this eventual transformation con* 
stitute the "immediate" or "transitional" demands of so- 
cialism, and are part of the general socialist program, each 
socialist party emphasizing those points which are of more 
immediate importance in view of the social and political 
conditions of its own country at any given time. The 
measures thus most generally advocated by the socialists 
are: universal suffrage and equal political rights for 
men and women; the initiative, referendum, proportional 
representation in legislative bodies, and the right of 
recall of representatives by their constituents; greater 
autonomy for the municipalities and limitation of the 
powers and functions of the central government; the 
abolition of standing armies; progressive reduction of the 
hours of labor and increase of wages; state employment 
of the unemployed; state insurance of workingmen in 
case of accidents and sickness; old age pensions for work- 
ingmen; state provisions for all orphans and invalids; 
abolition of all indirect taxes; a progressive tax on prop- 
erty, income and inheritance; municipal ownership of all 
municipal utilities; state or national ownership of all 
mines, means of transportation and communication, and 
of all industries controlled by monopolies, trusts and 
combines, and the gradual assumption by the munici- 
pality or state of all other industries as soon as they reach 
a stage where they become susceptible of socialization. 

The socialists, of course, do not anticipate that these 
measures will in all cases be adopted in their logical order 
and in the pristine purity of their original conception ac- 
cording to program, nor that they will be realized in all 



SOCIAUSM AND THE STATE 



103 



countries with absolute uniformity. More likely the 
course of the social transformation will be different in the 
different countries, slow and methodic in some, rapid and 
tempestuous in others, according to the historic condi- 
tions, the temperament of the people and the respective 
strength and intelligence of the ruling classes and the prol- 
etariat in each case. In the more democratic countries, 
especially those in which the socialist and labor movements 
constitute important political and social factors, the neces- 
sary transitional reforms, or at least a large part of them, 
may be gradually conquered through the direct control 
by the proletariat of important organs of the state, such - 
fls municipalities or legislatures, or through the indirect 
influence of the growing labor movement. In other 
countries the conquest of the public powers by the working 
class may be accomplished by a violent insurrection. The., 
wage workers may, in the words of Engels, "seize the 
powers of the state" and establish a temporary "dictator- 
ship of the proletariat." Thus the transition from the 
system of feudalism to the present order was accomplished 
radically but peacefully in England, slowly and incom- 
pletely in Germany, rapidly and violently in France. But 
violence is but an accident of the social revolution; it is 
by no means its necessary accompanunent, and it has no 
place in the socialist program. 

And similarly silent is the socialist program on the 
question whether the gradual expropriation of the possess- 
ing classes will be accomplished by a process of confisca- 
tion or by the method of compensation. The greater 
number of socialist writers incline towards the latter 
assumption, but in that they merely express their individ- 
■resent preferences. Social development, and espe- 



I 



I04 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AKD MOVEMENT 

cially social revolutions, are not in the habit of consulting 
cut and dried theories evolved by philosophers of past 
generations, and social justice is more frequently a ques- 
tion of social expediency and class power. The French 
clergy was not compensated for the lands taken from h 
by the bourgeois revolution, and the Russian noblemen 
and American slave owners were not compensated upon 
the emancipation of their serfs and chattel slaves. It is 
not unlikely that in countries in which the social transfor- 
mation will be accomplished peacefully, the state will com- 
pensate the expropriated proprietors, while every violent 
revolution will be followed by confiscation. The socialists 
are not much concerned about this issue. Their aim is 
the establishment of a state in which exploitation of man 
by man shall become impossible, and when private wealth 
has been robbed of the character of employing and ex- 
ploiting capital, its possession by a number of individuals 
ceases to be a menacing factor in a socialist state. 

The "transitional state" thus conceived carmot be 
bounded by fixed lines of demarcation either in its incep- 
tion or its termination. As every other period of historical 
development, it is bound to overlap at both ends. A 
number of municipalities and states are already wholly 
or partly under socialist control. Many of the "transi- 
tional" reforms of socialism, political and social, have al- 
ready been realized to some extent in the countries of Eu- 
rope, America and Australia, and the conceded tendency 
of all modem legislation is toward the extension of such 
reforms. In this sense it may well be said that we are in 
the midst, or at any rate at the beginning, of the socialist 
" transitional state," although it would be impossible for us 
to say just when we entered it. And similarly difficult is 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



lOS 



it to fix the line between the so-called transitional state and 
the socialist state proper. Theoretically, the reign of 
pure socialism begins after the entire socialist program 
has been materialized and society has been reorganized 
entirely on the basis of cooperative production. But in 
reality, social ideals are rarely realized in perfect form, 
[ and just as the period of feudalism has left remnants of 
I its institutions in a later order, and in some cases dovra 
to the present day, so, in all likelihood, many features of 
our present individualist order will long survive in a state, 
substantially and preponderatingly socialistic. 

I The Socialist State 

\ The transition from the present order of individual 
wealth and competitive industry to a system of collective 
ownership and cooperative production, by whatever means 
and in whatever manner accomplished, is bound to be 

I accompanied by very thoroughgoing changes in all rela- 

I tions of men, and by a decided remodeling of the entire 
social and political structure of society. These proposed 
changes, with the probable constitution, construction and 
workings of the "socialist state," have always offered an 
exceptionally fertile field for speculation, 

I The modern socialist movement made its first appear- 
ance towards the end of the eighteenth and the beginning 
of the nineteenth centuries, and its philosophy was largely 
influenced by the general ideological conceptions of that 
time. The first apostles of the new creed believed with 
their contemporaries that political and social institutions 
could be arbitrarily devised, tried, chosen, cast away, 
and substituted by others. They regarded the evils and 

■jBhortcomings of modern society as flaws in the social struc- 



Io6 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

ture, due to the carelessness of the "founders" of that 
society, and saw the remedy for these evils in the simple 
expedient of constructing a new society on a more rational 
and equitable plan. The early socialist literature is, 
therefore, replete with detailed and minute descriptions 
of proposed social organizations wherein universal brother- 
hood is the rule, bliss and prosperity are the heritage of 
all, and justice reigns supreme. And as the authors of 
these social Utopias were not bound by material impedi- 
ments and freely drew upon their fertile imaginations, their 
schemes are more or less realistic or fantastic according 
to their individual temperaments and bent of mind. The 
most noteworthy representatives of this early school of 
socialism are MoreUy, Gabriel Mably, Charles Fourier, 
Etieime Cabet, Robert Owen and Wilhclm Weitling. 

But the detailed painting of the society of the future 
or the "socialist state" is by no means confined to the 
pioneers of modern socialist thought. The temptation to 
evolve a ready and complete scheme of a new social order, 
based on socialism, for the purpose of proving or refuting 
the "feasibility" of the socialist ideal is so great, that 
socialists and anti- socialists alike still very frequently 
resort to that expedient. Conspicuous instances of such 
society builders on the socialist side are Edward Bellamy 
("Looking Backward"), William Morris ("News from 
Nowhere") and Laurence Gronlund ("Cooperative Com- . 
monwealth"); while the opposite side is ably represented 
by the merciless destroyers of the "socialist state" of the- 
types of Eugen Richter (" Sozialdemokratische Zukunfts- 
bilder"), William Graham ("Socialism Old and New"), 
Victor Cathrein ("Socialism: Its Theoretical Basis and 
Practical Application"), and those latest valiant con- 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



107 



I querors of the Socialist Dragon, David M. Pany 
1 ("The Scarlet Empire") and W. H. Mallock. Nor can 
I it be said that the drawing of such detailed descriptions 
\ of imaginary forms and workings of a socialist society is 
, altogether a waste of time ; such pictures are not without 
usefulness as food for reflection and interesting speculation, 
and some of them no doubt contain sparks of true genius 
which may perhaps even find practical application in times 
to come. But all such descriptions are nevertheless mere 
guesses for which none but their authors are responsible; 
they are not part of the generally accepted socialist pro- 
gram or philosophy. 

"Never," said the veteran leader of the German Social 
Democracy, Wilhelm Liebknecht, on the occasion of the 
debate in the Diet already alluded to, " never has our party 
told the workingmen about a 'state of the future,' never 
in any way other than as a mere Utopia. If anybody says: 
I picture to myself society after our program has been 
realized, after wage labor has been abolished and the ex- 
ploitation of men has ceased, in such or such a manner, 
well and good ; ideas are free, and everybody may conceive 
the socialist state as he pleases. Whoever beli 
I may do so, whoever does not, need not. These pictures 
I are but dreams, and social democracy has never under- 
stood them otherwise." 

And it is difficult to see how any forecast of future con- 
ditions could be much more than a dream. If we look 
back from the pirmacles of the twentieth century to con- 
ditions of the early part of the nineteenth century, we shall 
be astounded at the unprecedented radical revolution 
accomplished within the last hundred years in all doi 
I of our social, political and industrial life. The old pur- 



"■ / 

es / 




&08 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

' suits, habits and views of our fathers have been mercilessly 
cast aside. New fields of endeavor have been explored, 
new truths discovered, new relations established, new worlds 
created. The globe has a vastly different aspect from 
that of a hundred years ago, and the nations that people 
it are vastly different beings. The modern man differs 
in all his habits and mode of life from his forefathers of 
but a few generation.? ago. 

It will not be seriously contended that these present con- 
ditions could have been more or less accurately forecast 
and divined at the beginning of the present regime even by 
the most sagacious and best-informed social philosopher. 
For even if such a philosopher could reckon with the prob- 
able development of the forces then existing, he could cer- 
tainly not take into account the tremendous effect of the 
new discoveries and inventions since made, the applica- 
tion of steam and electricity in the industrial processes, 
the introduction of the railroads, steamships, telegraphs, 
telephones, and the countless modern machines and con- 
trivances which have served to revolutionize our entire 
system of production and communication and with it 
all our habits of life and thought. To the placid and 
rational philosopher of the beginning of the nineteenth 
century, an account of our present civilization would have 
been a much wilder and more incredible dream than the 
most fantastic socialist Utopia seems to-day to our wise 
bourgeois philosopher. 

And still the task of the man who might have assumed 
a century ago to forecast present conditions would have 
been mere child's play in comparison with that of the 
dreamer who undertakes to-day to describe the details 
of the life Wid organization of the "socialist state." 



SOOALISM AND THE STATE 



109 



The forces of industrial development have by no means 
reached their zenith, they are still multiplying and multi- 
plying in an ever accelerating ratio. The wider the basis 
of existing industrial forces, the greater the rate of economic 
progress; this is the simple working of the theory of geo- 
metrical progression as daily demonstrated in our indus- 
trial life. The last fifty years have witnessed more indus- 
trial progress than the three centuries preceding them, and 
the coming fifty years will perhaps eclipse the last five 
hundred years. 

The task of the would-be socialist forecaster is besides 
greatly complicated by another element. The develop- 
ments of the last century, immense and radical as they have 
been, have not very materially affected the basic principles 
of modern industrial organization. But the industrial 
development of the future, as conceived by socialists, will 
consist not only in the natural increase and multiplication 
of the ]iroductive forces, but also in a radical reorganiza- 
tion of the methods of production and distribution, and the 
resultant changes must thus of necessity be more thorough- 
going and less calculable. 

And finally, all speculation on the nature and aspect of 
the socialist state suffers from another inherent weakness. 
They tacitly assume that the "socialist state" is a fixed 
and definite phase of social development, whereas in fact 
it is anything but that. Socialism stands for an order of 
society in which private ownership in the means of produc- 
tion has substantially given way to a system of collective 
ownership. Such an order of things may quite conceiv- 
ably be established in some of the most progressive coun- 
tries in a short time, say within twenty-five years — our 
era is one of rapid developments. Such a country would iq 



1 



no THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

that case quite properly claim the designation of a "so- 
cialist state." But with the establishment of socialism, 
the general progress of that coimtry would not halt, and 
the succeeding centuries would continue to change its 
institutions, life and customs. The socialist state in its 
maturity will be an entirely diSerent organization from the 
socialist state in its infancy, and similarly the socialist 
organization of one country may be radically different 
from that of the other, and still the social prophet must 
have in mind a fixed and uniform "socialist state." 

Modern socialists indulge but little in fantastic fore- 
casts of the future order of things; they fully realize the 
general futility ofsuchspeculationsfor the practical purposes 
of the socialist movement. The socialist criticism is directed 
against existing evils, the socialist program is a program of 
immediate relief, and the socialist demands are made on the 
present state. The socialists are concerned only with the 
immediate effects of their proposed measures on the welfare 
of the present population, andifthey venture at all to inquire 
mfo the futtu-e, they limit their inquiries entirely to such 
immediate effects, to conditions "on the day after the 
revolution." Such inquiries arc very useful as serving to 
illustrate the constructive sides of the socialist philosophy. 

Much valuable work on such lines has recently been done 
by Karl Kautsky ("The Social Revolution," Second Part), 
and Anton Menger ("Neue Staatslehre"), and very cred- 
itable attempts in the same direction have also been made 
by Annie Besant and G. Bernard Shaw (in the "Fabian 
Essays"), Oswald Koehler (" Der Sozialdemokratische 
Staat"), B, Malon (in "Pr&is de Socialisme"), and the 
American writer, John Spargo ("Socialism"). And as 
the socialist movement gains in power and the socialist 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



ideal becomes more realistic, the socialist thinkers are 
bound to bestow greater and more serious attention to the 
elaboration of that feature of their philosophy. 

The great distinction between the works of these con- 
temporary socialist writers and their Utopian precursors 
is, that while the latter based then- speculations on an 
entirely arbitrary conception of an ideal state, the former 
take for their starting point the present actual state. They 
realize that the so-called " socialist state, " as far as we can 
conceive it to-day, is nothing but the present state with 
such modifications as the realization of the proposed so- 
cialist reforms naturally and necessarily imply, and their' 
forecast is but an analysis of such probable changes. But 
with all this candor and caution it is still impossible to 
arrive at scientific and indisputable conclusions as to con- 
ditions of even the immediate future. The conclusions 
of each author are bound to contain some element of spec- 
ulation and to reflect to a large extent his individual views 
and inclinations. It is in that spirit and with that under- 
standing that the following chapters are c 



Production and Distribution of Wealth Under Socialism 

The organization of wealth production under socialism 
offers but little difficulty. The prevalent methods of pro- 
duction, as indicated in a previous chapter, have already 
. become largely social in many important industries. 

In the modem corporations, trusts and other combines, 

the capitalists have created industrial organizations very 

much akin to the socialist ideal, and have demonstrated 

the feasibility and advantages of cooperative and planful 

L production on a large scale. By the simple process of 



r 112 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



' combining the greater number of plants in a given industry 
under one head, discarding the less efficient of them and 
strengthening the more important, the trusts have largely 
eliminated the element of waste in production; and by 
consolidating the management and supervision of the work, 
and perfecting the specialization and division of labor, 
they have vastly increased the productivity of Ihe latter. 
The state, with its larger powers and resources, will be able 
to increase the advantages of trustified production very 
considerably. 

But a socialist regime, once having assumed the admin- 
istration of the trusts, will be bound to change the nature 
and to extend the benefits of these institutions still further. 
The modem trusts, while social in their methods of work, 
are not public, but private institutions, and are operated 
entirely for the benefit of their individual owners. 

It is not in the interests of the individual trust magnates 
to extend production beyond the limits of the present de- 
mand; the general purchasing power of the consumers 
remaining unchanged, such an increased output could only 
result in a decline of prices. The policy of the trusts is, 
therefore, on the whole, to limit production. A social- 
ist administration, on the other hand, has a vital interest 
in extending production in order to enhance the national 
wealth and to provide employment for a larger number 
of its members. Since it is not producing for profit, the 
effect of an increased output on the price of the commodity 
will not enter in its calculations, and since the purchasing . 
power of the population will be increased in proportion 
to the growth of productivity, there will be no danger of an 
industrial crisis. 

The members of a socialist state, furthermore, will be 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



113 



interested in such trustified industries not only as con- 
sumers, but also as employees, and hence they will naturally 
introduce such reforms in the management of these indus- 
tries as will benefit them in the latter capacity. Under 
capitalism the greater productivity of labor in trustified 
industries is accompanied by loss of work for large portions 
of former employees. Under socialism it will necessarily 
lead to a progressive diminution of their hours of labor. 
Under capitalism the profits of the trust magnates are the 
sole aim and motive of production, and the safety and wel- 
fare of their employees are of but secondary importance. 
Under socialism production will be carried on principally 
for the benefit of the producers themselves, and it is rea- 
sonable to expect that every known device will be applied 
to make industry safe, pleasant and attractive. 

The modem trusts, thus transformed into cooperative 
enterprises on a large scale, will in all likelihood become 
the starting point of the socialist system of industrial 
organization, and the system will be extended from one 
industry to the other as fast as the conditions will permit. 
But this will probably not be, at least for a long time to 
come, the exclusive form of industrial organization. There 
are certain industries dependent on purely personal skill, 
such as the various arts and crafts, that from their very 
nature are not susceptible of socialization, and other indus- 
tries, such as small farming, that will, at least for many years 
to come, not be proper objects for socialization. These 
may contmue to exist in a socialist society as individual 
enterprises side by side with the larger cooperative works. 

On the whole, however, it is safe to assume that by far 
the greater and most important part of wealth production 
will be conducted by cooperative establishnients. In th^ 



I 
I 



114 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

countries of the most advanced industrial development, 
the large plants employ even to-day the greater part 
of the wage-working population, and there are but few 
important industries that are not ripe for concentration 
and consolidation. And since the large cooperative 
establishments, with their natural economies and advan- 
tages, will hold out greater attractions to the workers 
than the majority of the small individual enterprises, there 
will probably be but few who will choose to remain outside 
of the prevalent industrial organization. 

The rational organization of labor, the elimination of 
duplicate plants, of the "middlemen" in industry and 
commerce and of other waste entailed in a system of com- 
petition, the disappearance of all workless "incomes" and 
of all the purely parasitic types who are to-day maintained 
and supported by the competitive system or maintained 
for the special interests and comforts of the ruling and 
leisure classes, — all these changes necessarily involved in 
a system of socialism, will increase the productive forces of 
society and augment the national wealth immensely. 

How will that wealth be distributed ? With this ques- 
tion we have approached what is considered as the cru- 
cial point of socialism by the opponents of that philoso- 
phy. The impracticability or impossibility of the "social- 
ist scheme of wealth distribution" is the burden of most 
of the "scientific" refutations of the socialist theory, and 
curiously enough most of these criticisms are based on a 
careless reading of the great theoretician of modem 
socialism, Karl Marx. 

In common with Smith, Ricardo and other representa- 
tives of the classical school of political economy, Marx 
holds that the value of a commodity is determined by the 



[ SOQALISM AND THE STATE 115 

labor time expended in its production, the labor time in 
question being defined as "the labor time socially neces- 
sary to produce an article under the normal conditions 
of production with the average degree of skill and intensity 
prevalent at that time." ' This simple statement of fact 
has been almost uniformly interpreted by the astute critics 
of Marx as the socialist "plan of distribution," and many 
valuable reams of paper have been consumed in ingenious 
objections to that plan.' 

In fact, however, Marx occupied himself just as little 
with the distribution of wealth in a future socialist state 
of society as Darwin occupied himself with the ultimate 
physical type of man. As a true man of science, he limited 
his researches to the past developments and existing facts 
and tendencies. In formulating the labor theory of value, 
Marx simply stated a fact, a law applicable to the present 
system of producing wealth — ■ nothing else. 

"Marx," says Frederick Engels, his foremost inter- 
preter, "deals only with the determination of the value 
of commodities, that is to say, with the value of 
articles which are produced in a society consisting of 
private producers, by each private producer for his indi- 
vidual account and for the purpose of exchange. Thia 
value in its definite historic meaning is created and meas- 
ured by human labor embodied in the separate com- 
modities. ... It is this simple fact, daily enacted before 
our own eyes in the modern capitalist society, which Marx 
states. . . . Whatever other values may be mentioned. 



I 



' Karl Mars, "Capital," English Edition, Vol. I, p. 11. 

' See William Graham, "Socialism New and Old"; Victor Cathrein, 
"Socialism: Its Theoretical Basis and Practical Application"; Schaefflti 
"Quintessence of Socialism." 



I Il6 THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

this much is certain, that Mars is not concerned with these 
things, but only with the value of commodities ; and that in 
the whole chapter on Value in his 'Capital' there is not the 
slightest hint whether and to what extent this theory of 
value is applicable to other forms of society."^ 

And Karl Kautsky adds : — 

"There could be no greater error than to consider that 
one of the tasks of a socialist society is to see to it that 
the law of value is brought into perfect operation, and that 
only equivalent values are exchanged. The law of value 
is rather a law peculiar to a society of producers for ex- 
change."' 

But what then, may be asked, is the socialist plan of 
distribution of wealth? 

The plain answer to this inquiry is: The socialists 
do not oSer a cut and dried plan of wealth distribution. 

As a proposition of abstract justice and fairness there 
is no reason why any discrimination at all should be made 
in the distribution of the necessaries and material comforts 
of life between the members of the community. The in- 
creased productivity of labor and the consequent augmenta- 
tion of wealth are due to the concerted efforts of men in all 
fields of endeavor, physical and mental, in generations 
past as well as present, and the precise share of each in- 
dividual in the general wealth of the nation is altogether 
insusceptible of measurement. 

It must be granted that some individuals are stronger, 
wiser, more gifted and skillful than others. But what of 
that? Is there any moral ground for punishing the 

' "Herm Eugen DQhring's Umwilzung der Wisaenschaften," pp. 309, 

• Karl Kautsky, "The Social Revolution," Chicago, 1903, p. lag. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



cripple, the invalid, the decrepit, the imbecile, the un- 
fortimate step-children of nature, by reducing their 
rations of food or clothing? Is there any moral sanc- 
tion for rewarding the man of physical strength or mental 
gifts by special allowances from the storehouse of human 
society? Do humane parents discriminate in that manner 
between their strong and weak, their fortunate and un- 
fortimate children ? Is the title of the stronger and "abler" 
to greater material reward based on equity, or is it rather 
a survival of the barbaric " &st right " of the dark ages? 

To the socialists the old communistic motto: "From 
each according to his ability, to each according to his 
needs," generally appears as the ideal rule of distribution 
in an enlightened human society, and quite likely the time 
will come when that high standard will be generally 

I adopted by civilized communities. 

The productivity of labor is increasing with such 
phenomenal rapidity that we may well foresee a time when 
society will, with comparative ease, produce enough to 
afford to all its members, without distinction, all neces- 
saries and even luxuries of life, and when there will be 
just as little justification for a quarrel over the method of 
distribution of material wealth as there is to-day for a 
quarrel over the use of air or water. To the wise skeptics 
the statement may seem extravagant, but when we com- 
pare the wealth and productivity of modem countries to- 
day with those of half a century ago, we shall easily realize 
that we are by no means dealing with pure Utopian dreams. 
But just and feasible as this ideal method of distribu- 
tion may be, it is to-day nevertheless a mere ideal, a hope 
to be realized in the more or less distant future. It is not 

I a part of the present program of the socialist movement. 



Il8 THE SoaALIST PIIILOSOPHV AND MOVEMENT 




Modem socialists recognize that the methods of distribu- 
tion under the new order of things must take for their 
starting point the present methods, i.e., payments of vary- 
ing wages or salaries for services rendered. 

Here again we run counter to a deep-rooted popular con- 
ception or rather misconception of the socialist program. 
One of the pet schemes of the early socialist experimenters 
was the substitution of "labor certificates" or "time certifi- 
cates" for money. By this means they expected to fix the 
value of each commodity with reference to the labor time 
contained in it as it were automatically, to eliminate the 
"unearned increment "of the capitalist and the profit of the 
middleman and to give to each producer the full equivalent 
of his labor. The scheme was on a par with that of the 
"equitable labor exchange banks," the communistic 
societies and the other social experiments of the Utopian 
socialists. They all proceeded from the belief that a 
small group of men could dissociate themselves from the 
rest of society, establish a miniature socialist common- 
wealth, and induce their fellow-men to follow their ex- 
ample by the practical demonstration of its excellence. 
Modem socialists have long discarded all miniature social 
experimentations and arbitrary social devices as Utopian 
1 puerile, and the continued dissertations of many dis- 
tinguished critics of socialism about the "socialist plan" 
of the suppression of money and the abolition of money 
payments for services, only go to demonstrate how little 
they are abreast with the developments of socialist thought. 

Money and wages are both the products of a certain 

phase of economic development. Neither was known 

before the rise of private property, and in all likelihood 

I both will at some time in the distant future lose their use- 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



119 



fulness and disappear. But these reflections again belong 
to the sphere of dreams of the golden future, — -they have 
no room in a sober and reaHstic program of social reform, 

"Money," says Kautsky, "is the simplest means known 
up to the present time which makes it possible in as com- 
plicated a mechanism as that of the modern productive 
process, with its tremendous far-reaching division of labor, 
to secure the circulation of products and their distribution 
to the individual members of society. It is the means 
which make it possible for each one to satisfy his neces- 
sities according to his individual inclination (to be sure 
within the bounds of his economic power). As a means to 
such circulation, money will be found indispensable until 
something better is discovered," ' 



Incentive Under Sociaiism 

Next to the assertion that it would curtail individual 
liberty, the most popular objection to the proposed system 
of socialism is that every such system is bound to paralyze 
social progress by depriving the individual initiative of 
the incentive to exert itself usefully in behalf of society. 
This argument assumes: first, that individual initiative 
is the chief lever of human progress, and second, that the 
love of material gain is the principal, if not the only, 
, motive which impels men to strive for the highest degree 
I of excellence in the various fields of private and public 
Lendeavor. Since socialism is based on a system of more 
is equal and secured incomes, and excludes the pos- 
sibility of large pecuniary rewards, it is argued that under 
such a system the man of genius will have no inducement 
' "The Social Revolution," p, 139. 



^20 THE SOaAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



■ to exert his utmost skill, the common mortal will work 
reluctantly and indifferently, and social stagnation will 
inevitably result. Let us examine this argument. 

What constitutes modem civilization is the sum total of 
all our achievements in industry, in science, in the arts, and 
in the various organs and institutions of public life and 
activities which are comprised under the general designa- 
tion of politics. 

There Is no doubt that a large share of these achieve- 
ments is due to the individual initiative and the creative 
genius of exceptional men. But let us not overestimate 
the importance of this factor in social progress. Our 
civilization owes on the whole much more to the collective 
endeavors of man than to the individual genius of men, 
and the general improvement in our culture, refinement of 
work, and mode of life, is vastly more the result of a process 
of social growth to which the large multitudes of human 
beings have for many generations contributed their un- 
known and imperceptible mites, than the merit of the 
great individual inventors, discoverers or leaders. "So- 
cial achievement," says Professor Ward, "has consisted 
m the establishment of a social order under and withm 
which individual achievement can go on and civilization 
is made possible.'" 

The art of book printing, the use of gunpowder, and the 
application of steam and electricity have alt been invented 
or perfected by individual geniuses, but the more substan- 
tial arts of plowing, cooking, tailoring and housebuilding 
have been invented, developed and perfected by the human 
race as a whole. What is still more significant, however, is 
this, that while the collective inventions belong to an ear- 
' Lester F. Ward, "Applied Sociology," Boston, 1906, p. 38. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



iier age and the individual inventions to a later age, we have 
undoubtedly reached a period which is characterized by the 
process of the gradual passing of the individual inventor, 
initiator or hero, and of the return to a system of social 
progress through collective effort. 

And nowhere is this process more distinctly noticeable 
than in the most vital sphere of human activity, industry. 

' Industrial development depends almost entirely upon the 
efficient organization of the mechanism of production (which 
includes a proper division of labor, organization of manage- 
ment, and use of effective machinery), and of transporta- 
tion and exchange, and in all these domains collective 

I achievements are rapidly supplanting individual enter- 
prise. The modern mass production based on the factory 
system forces the organization and division of labor along 
lines practically indicated by the machine ; and while 
there is still much room left for the exercise of human in- 

i genuity in the arrangement and rearrangement of details, 

I such arrangements and rearrangements are in most cases 
the result of simple experience, almost of mathematical cal- 
culation, and not the work of an exceptional genius. Nor 
are the other modem industrial categories, the cor- 
porations and trusts, the stock exchanges and banks, 
the system of credit and the national and international 
markets, the individual invention of an industrial genius. 
They are the products and forms of gradual industrial 
development ; the entire industrial community, employers 
and employees, have imperceptibly built them up in the 

I course of centuries, and they are still busily engaged in the 
process of developing and perfecting these institutions 

I without marked individual initiative or leadership. And 
in the domain of the invention and perfection of machinery, 




Pl22 THE SOCIALIST PHIlOSOPm' AND MOVEMENT 



this peculiar territory of the individual genius, the element 
of personal initiative is gradually and steadily receding 
to the background, 

The laws of mechanics are being explored with ever in- 
creasing accuracy and planfulness for the practical re- 
quirements of industry, and the new improvements in the 
tools of production are now but rarely in the nature of 
great and unexpected inventions; more often they are 
merely the successful solutions of preconceived problems 
by means of well-defined scientific methods. The hustling, 
up-to-date experimental laboratory is rapidly crowding 
out the dreamy inventive genius. What we call " Edison" 
to-day is not the Thomas A. Edison who early in life made 
the astounding inventions in telegraphy, but the well- 
equipped, well-organized electrical laboratory at West 
Orange, New Jersey, with the number of trained scientific 
workers engaged in it. 

And what has been said of the industrial process applies 
with almost equal force to the domain of science : the fac- 
tory system with its specialization, division of labor, and 
collective production, is the recognized form of modem 
scientific research almost as much as it is the form of the 
modem manufacture of market commodities. Scientific 
work is, as a rule, not done by individuals but by groups 
of workers; not at home, but in laboratories, clinics and 
libraries, and scientific discoveries like mechanical inven- 
tions are most often the results of planned and collective 
labor. Left to his own individual resources, the modem 
scientist would he almost helpless. 

Nor does our public life form an exception to this 

general tendency of our times. The great individual leg- 

I islators, as Moses, Solon, Lycurgus, and even Napoleon, 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



123 



have been superseded by the many-headed bodies of popu- 
lar representatives in the legislative chambers ; the great 
free-lance statesmen have made room for the chosen leaders 
of strong political parties, and the success of a modem 
battle depends not so much on the military genius of the 
individual commander as on the proper organization and 
equipment of his army. In the recent Russo-Japanese 
war the demoralized Russian army and navy did not 
produce a single military or naval " genius," whereas in the 
well -organ! zed and welt-equipped Japanese army and navy 
every general and admiral was a "hero." In one domain 
after the other the individual genius and arbiter of human 
destiny, the "hero" of Carlyle is being dethroned and 
subordinated to the collective human fraternity. The 
domain of the arts is to-day practically the last resting 
place of the "superman," 

Individual initiative and talent thus by no means play 
such a determining part in the world's progress as the 
critics of socialism claim. But on the other hand the 
cialists readily admit that they play some part. There 
always were and probably always will be persons of ex- 
traordinary gifts and abilities who may contribute vastly 
more to the store of human welfare and happiness than the 
average man. Without them the world would probably 
not relapse into a stale of barbarism, but it will fare much 
better with them and their services. But what of it? 
Is there any real danger that under a system of socialism 
these superior individuals would disappear or refuse to 
give the benefit of their special talents to society ? Is the 
striving for wealth actually the most powerful incentive of 
the creative genius? The theory seems plausible enough 
5 regards the leader in industry, the business man, but 



I 



' 124 THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

how about the scientist, the artist, the statesman? This 
is a fruitful source for reflection and comparison. 

The manufacturer, banker or other active capitalist 
undoubtedly strives for material wealth. But wealth is 
for him only secondarily, if at all, a means of procuring 
physical or intellectual enjoyment. To him wealth rep- 
resents power, and above all, it is the test of his success in 
his chosen vocation. To say of a man engaged in industry 
or commerce that he has made a large fortune is to say 
that he has proved himself efficient and successful in his 
career; to say of him that he has lost his fortune is 
equivalent to asserting that he has proved _ himself the 
inferior of his rivals, that he is inefScient, and that his 
life work has been a failure. 

The man of science, on the other hand, would gain or 
lose btit little in the esteem of his contemporaries and in his 
own self-respect by the gain or loss of a fortune. The test 
of his success is not the amount of money he has made, but 
the extent of the recognition accorded to him and his work 
by the learned fraternity. Scholastic honors and aca- 
demic titles are to him what money is to the business man ; 
his incentive is not the love of money but the desire of 
recognition. 

Again, the reward of the artist is neither money nor 
academic titles. As an artist he strives primarily for pub- 
lic applause and glory, for these are the true tests of his 
success and efficiency in the side of his existence which 
he values most, his art. 

So likewise, the statesman cares most for influence and 
authority, the soldier for military honors and preferment, 
and the priest for the respect and reverence of his fellow- 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



125 



Of course, it may wdl happen, and no doubt often does 
happen, that the scientist, the artist, the statesman, the 
soldier and the priest are anything but indifferent to 
material wealth. They may prefer an easy and com- 
fortable existence, they may sometimes be goaded on to 
create by sheer poverty and want, and they may even 
I occasionally be grasping and greedy. But these will 
I then be features entirely independent of their respective 
[ gifts and talents, and by no means a stimulus to their 
best application. "It is not true," again observes Ward, 
I "that men of genius depend upon adversity and dire 
necessity as a spur to activity. This is all a popular illu- 
sion which the entire history of human achievement dis- 
proves and should dispel. The instinct of workmanship, 
if it be in no other form than fear of the hell of ennui, is 
I the great and unremitting spur that drives and goads all 
I men to action." ' "* 

I The real incentive moving all men to bring forth the 
I best that is in them is just that best that is in them : their 
L desu-e is to excel and to earn the recognition of their fellow- 
men in such a form in which such recognition is most fitly 
I esrpressed. And the business man, whose apparently 
sole motive is money making, forms no exception to this 
rule. To-day, when industries are conducted for private 
gain and in competition between the individual capitalists, 
accumulated individual wealth is, as we have seen, the 
only measure of the business man's efficiency and suc- 
cess. But when the industrial organization passes into 
the hands of society and becomes a part of its general 
administration, the distinction between service in that 
branch of the government and any other branch of it 
■ ' "Applied Sociology," p. 345. 



126 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

will naturally cease. The director of industries will be- 
come a "statesman" just as any other public functionary, 
and will be just as much moved by motives of a more 
ideal nature as the latter. Our post office has been 
nationalized, and its operation has become an adminis- 
trative function, while the express business of the country 
has remained the individual enterprise of competing 
capitalists. The salary of the Postmaster-General, who 
is a public officer, is a mere pittance in comparison with 
the revenues of the head of one of our large express com- 
panies, and still the government has been able to secure 
for the administration of its Post-Office Department men 
at least as capable as the highly paid managers of the 
express companies, 

A socialist society will not destroy the individual in- 
centive in mdustrial life ; it will merely change its char- 
acter by substituting a more ideal standard for the present 
standard of pecimiary gain. 

And as for the scientist, artist and statesman, a socialist 
regime caimot possibly affect their creative work adversely 
by cutting down their money reward, since that reward, 
as we have shown, never was their prime incentive. The 
golden age of Athens knew nothing of immense fortunes 
and heavy money rewards, but it produced a sculpture, 
drama, literature and architecture never surpassed in 
history. 

"To undertake to state the influence which the com- 
munistic elements in Athenian life had upon the ex- 
traordinary development of Athenian art and literature 
in the fifth century before our era," says Professor Sey- 
mour, "would be dangerous. But any reader may see 
that the artist and dramatist were not stimulated by any 



SOQAUSM AND THE STATE 



127 



material rewards or prizes. ^^Ischylus had no mcome 
whatever, so far as we know, from his plays, and the 
architect's pay was only twice that of the stonecutter," ' 
Nor, we may add, did the great statesmen and orators 
of that period, as Pericles and Demosthenes, receive large 
pecuniary compensation. 

On the other hand, there is every reason to believe that 
a socialist regime will offer larger opportunities for the 
unfolding and development of true genius and for its pure 
artistic exercise than present society does. 

Our modem capitalist society does all in its power to 
suppress genius and ability, but does not entirely succeed. 
Capitalism reduces one part of the population to the con- 
dition of uncultured, exhausted wage slaves, and forces 
the other into a wild, all-absorbing race for material 
wealth; still the exceptional gifts of some break 
through these formidable obstacles. Capitalism subverts 
all art and science to the worship of the golden calf; it 
subordinates the beautiful to the practical, the true to the 
profitable, and strips life of all poetry and noble inspira- 
tion; still, art and science are not entirely dead. The 
capitalist manufacturer cheats the inventor, the capitalist 
publisher robs the author, the capitalist art dealer exploits 
the painter, — the inventor dies in the poorhouse, the 
author and artist live in beggary; but the inventor con- 
tinues inventing, the scientist continues studying and the 
artist continues creating. 

Under a state of socialism education and culture will 
be equally accessible to all, and the citizens will have more 
leisure to cultivate their gifts. What greater stimulus 

L ' "Socialism and Communism in Greece," by Thomas D. Seymour, 
I liLJi., in Harper"! Monthly Magazine for November, 1907. 



I 



f 128 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



P can human society offer for the full development of the 

f fine arts and true sciences? 

The elaborate and painstaking investigations of Odin, 
Galton, de Candolle and Jacoby, all collated by Mr. 
Ward in his scholarly work on " Apphed Sociology," show 
conclusively that modem economic conditions smother 
scores of native genius for every one they allow to mature. 
Analyzing the economic conditions of 619 well-known 
men of letters between the years 1300 and 1835, de 
Candolle finds that 562 of them had been brought up and 
had Hved in ease and material comfort, while only 57 
had spent their youth in comparative poverty; and M. 
0dm, commenting on the results of this analysis, ob- 
serves: "This means by the sole fact of economic con- 
ditions in the midst of which they grew up the children 
of the famines in easy circumstances had at least forty 
to fifty more chances of making themselves a name in 
letters than those who belonged to poor families or to 
families of insecure economic position." ' 

But, it is argued, all this may be very well as far as the 
men of exceptional genius and abilities are concerned, 
but how about the plain ordinary workingman, the "com- 
mon laborer" who can neither expect the special homage 
or approval of his fellow-men for his obscure work nor, 
under a system of advanced socialism, a commensurate 
pecuniary reward — what will be his incentive to work 
conscientiously and efficiently? 

This question introduces a distinct feature of present 
conditions into a state of society based on an entirely 
different order. To-day our industries are managed by 

' A. Odin, "Genfese des grands hommes," etc., Paris, 1895, p. 5ag, 
oled in Ward's "Applied Sociologj'," p. 304. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



i2g 



I 



individual capitalists for their private profit and with but 
Kttle regard for the health, comfort or needs of the em- 
ployees; work is exhausting, monotonous, repulsive and 
often dangerous. In a system of cooperative labor, the 
workingman will naturally be considered above every- 
thing else; his hours of labor will be shortened as much 
as practicable, his occupation will be more varied, the 
dangers of employment will be reduced to a minimum, 
the workshop will be clean, bright and hygienic ; in a 
word, labor will be made attractive. 

"Because," observes J. Stem, "the workingman con- 
siders as a burden the work which ties him to a mechani- 
cal, monotonous and cheerless occupation in squalid 
workshops during inhumanly long hours and for which 
he receives starvation wages; because the office clerk 
prefers to play truant rather than to busy himself the 
entire day with matters that do not appeal to his mind 
or heart; because men are reluctant in the exercise of 
a calling which was forced on Ihem against their wishes 
and inclinations; because generally the present class state 
imposes on most persons activities which have no charms 
for them and only hold out the promise of pecuniary re- 
ward — because of all that — are we to infer that the 
human being is generally disposed to laziness rather than 
to industry? Does not, on the contrary, even the most 
superficial examination of persons of all ages and classes 
show that love of action, the irresistible desire to unfold 
one's strength, to ' do things ' and to create, is implanted 
in every healthy human individual, and that to the normal 
person nothing is more unbearable than inaction? , . . 
In a million of ways the love of action reveals itself as a 
mighty power in human life, from early childhood even 



I 



THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

to old age. Whence comes the passion for all kinds of 
sports but from the mighty instmct of action? Why 
do people voluntarily choose strenuous and even dangerous 
activities, as is shown by numerous instances in life and 
history ? This fear, that without the whip of poverty or 
force maniiind would lapse into a state of inaction, re- 
minds us of the humorous prophecy upon the advent of 
the bicycle and automobile that men would hereafter have 
little occasion for the use of their legs, and the latter would 
become weak, short and crooked like those of the dachs- 
hund." ' 

And furthermore, one of the chief causes operating 
to-day to make labor disagreeable is the lack of variety in 
occupation. 

"The desire for freedom of choice and for change of 
occupation is deeply implanted in human nature," says 
August Bebel. " Just as constant and regular repetition 
without variation will at length make the best food dis- 
liked, an employment that is daily repeated becomes as 
monotonous as a treadmill; it blunts and relaxes. The 
man performs a given task, because he must, but without 
enthusiasm or enjoyment. Now, every one possesses a 
number of capabilities and inclinations, which only require 
to be roused, developed, and put into action to give the 
most satisfactory results and enable their possessor to 
unfold his whole and real being. The socialistic com- 
munity will offer the fullest opportunity for gratifying 
this need of variety. The enormous increase m produc- 
tive power, combined with growmg simplification in the 

'J. Stern, "Der Zukunffsstaat ^ Thesen Uber dea Soaalismus, 
sein Wesen, seine DurchfiihrbarkeEt und Zweckmaseigbeit," Berlin, 
1906, p. 30. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



131 



process of production, will permit a considerable limita- 
tion in the time of labor, while it facilitates the acquire- 
ment of mechanical skill in a number of different 
Lbranches." ' 



The Political Structure of the Socialist Stale 

We cannot, of course, attempt a detailed forecast of 
[the political organization of the future socialist state with- 
out embarking upon the domain of speculation. But we 
may, nevertheless, profitably endeavor to discern the bold 
outlines of the political structure of the socialist stale, at 
least in the early periods of its existence, provided we 
always bear in mind the following two fundamental 
propositions : — 

The machinery of government of every state must 
' be adapted to the character and objects of such state. 

The modem state is the state of the capitalist extracting 

profits from the working members of the community, and 

the modem government is, in the words of Karl Mane, 

"but a committee for managing the common affairs of 

1 the capitalist class." 

The socialist state, on the other hand, is a classless 
state of cooperative producers, and its government must 
be a "committee for the managing of the common affairs" 
of the members of that state. In other words, the main 
functions of the socialist state will be of an industrial 
character, and since there will be no separate economic 
classes with fixed and conflicting interests, the state will 
represent the citizens. It will be a democratic state. 

2. Every new political organization evolves from the 



133 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

organization immediately preceding it and retains all of 
its features except such as have become useless or in- 
compatible with the new order of things. 

The French Revolution has not done away with the 
entire poUtical structure evolved under the monarchy; it 
has merely modified it in a few substantial points. The 
United States has retained more features of its pre-Revo- 
lutionary political organization than it has introduced 
new ones since the Declaration of Independence. 

The socialist state will probably, on the whole, retain 
the present forms of political organization with such 
changes as will be necessitated by the altered character 
and objects of organized society. 

Most likely the present geographical limits of the 
various states will be left substantially intact. The 
political ideal of the early socialist writers was a globe 
studded with small autonomous communities. Thus 
Fourier's political unit is the Phalanx composed of about 
two thousand inhabitants, and his scheme of political re- 
organization contemplates the division of our planet into 
just two millions of such Phalanxes, each economically 
and politically independent of the rest. It is a note- 
worthy fact that the proposed Utopian communities grow 
in size as the authors come nearer to our present era. 

"The socialist commonwealth," observes Kautsky on 
this point, "is not the product of an arbitrary figment of 
the brain, but a necessary product of economic develop- 
ment, and it is understood more clearly as that develop- 
ment becomes more apparent. Hence the size of that 
commonwealth is also not arbitrary, but is conditioned 
upon the stage of that development at a given time. 
The higher the economic development, the greater the 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 133 

' division of labor, the larger the size of the common- 
wealth. . . . 

" The division of labor is carried on ever further; ever 
more do the several industries apply themselves to the 
production of special articles only, but those for the whole 
world; ever larger becomes the size of these establish- 
ments, some of which count their workmen by the thou- 
sands. Under such conditions a community able to satisfy 
all its needs and embracing all requisite industries must 
have dimensions very different from those of the socialist 
colonies planned at the begiiming of the last century. 
Among the social organizations in existence to-day, there 
is but one that possesses the requisite dimensions, and 
may be used as the framework for the establishment and 
development of the socialist commonwealth, and that is 
the modern state." ' 

The expectation that the proposed socialist common- 
wealth will be co-extensive with the modem state, and the 
assumption that the state will be charged with the man- 
agement and direction of the industries, have led to the 
widespread notion that the socialist state will be highly 
centralized and that the socialist administration will be 
"paternalistic." 

Nothing can be less warranted than these assumptions. 
The modem centralized state is a product of the capitalist 
system, and especially of capitalist trading. 

We again quote that acutest observer and thinker of 
modem socialism, Karl Kautsky: — 

' Karl Kautsky, "Das Erfurter Programm," 81I1 Edition, Stuttgart, 
1907, pp. 117, iiS, ii<). Compare also "The Socialist Republic," by 
Karl Kautsky, translated and adapted to America by Dauiel de Leon, 
New York, igoo, pp. 10, II. 



S"34 THE SOCIAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

" Commerce has always had a tendency towards central- 
ization. It causes the influx of commodities as well as of 
buyers and sellers to certain points favored by their geo- 
graphical location and political conditions. Under the 
capitalist mode of production, which converts all industry 
into production of commodities, and makes it dependent 
on commerce, the centralization of commerce leads to the 
centralization of the entire industrial life. The whole 
country becomes directly or indirectly dependent on the 
metropolis, as it becomes dependent on the capitalist 
class. The metropolis, the center of commerce, also 
becomes the converging point of all surplus value, of all 
superfluity of the country, and luxury lures after it the 
arts and the sciences. 

"The economic centralization leads to political centrali- 
zation, and the center of commerce also becomes the cen- 
ter of government." ' 

Since there is no room in a socialist commonwealth for 
production for sale or for commerce, there is no economic 
need for a strongly centralized government. Moreover, 
the very fact that the socialist state will be charged 
with much larger functions than the present state, and 
will exercise a much larger interference in the economic 
relations of its individual citizens, will make it an almost 
impossible task to direct the most substantial activities of 
the state from one central point and through one set 
of general officers. 

While the state as such will probably retain certain 
general functions, it will no doubt be found more con- 
venient to vest the more vital and direct functions in 
political organizations embracing smaller territories. The 
' "Der Parlamenlarismua," etc., Stuttgart, iSgj, p. 30. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



135 



socialists regard the present city or township as the nucleus 
of such a political unit. 

The city is to-day already charged with many functions 
of prime importance to the welfare of its inhabitants, and 
I those functions could be readily enlarged under a socialist 
' administration. The municipality could well conduct, 
direct or regulate all industries except those that from 
their nature require an organization of national scope, 
such as the posts, telegraphs, railways, mines, and the 
great trustified industries. It could, besides, have the 
sole care of the safety, health, education and amusement 
of its citizens and of the support and maintenance of its 
aged, invalid and other dependent members. 

It is not at all unlikely that these functions may, 
especially in the case of larger municipalities, be further 
subdivided, and apportioned among several organized 
"labor groups" or city districts. 

"The single communes," says August Bebel, "form a 
suitable basis for such an institution, and where they are 
too large to allow of the convenient transaction of busi- 
ness, they can be divided into districts. All adult mem- 
bers of the commune, without distinction of sex, take 
part in the necessary elections, and determine to what 
persons the conduct of affairs shall be intrusted." ' 

And Anton Menger describes his conception of the 
practical workings of such organizations in the following 
language : " At first it will be necessary to divide the larger 
mimic ipalities into local districts in order to facilitate their 
industrial activities. For the same reason every large 
municipality in which the industrial life is very complex, 
will have to organize the members of the same trade 

' "Woman," p. 130. 



' 136 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

or calling into separate ' labor groups.' But these inter- 
mediary organizations are to be considered only as ad- 
ministrative organs. The municipality remains the owner 
and the authority in all industrial activity. Hence the 
members of the group may assert the right of existence as 
against the municipality, but they have no claim to a 
division of the product of the group's labor in any fixed 
proportion. . . . 

"The municipality may establish or dissolve the labor 
group and may assign to it members, work and ma- 
terial. . . , The managers of the labor group are ap- 
pointed and discharged by the municipality. . . . 

"When the socialist state has become firmly established, 
the labor groups may be transformed with great caution 
in the direction of greater democracy." ' 

These ideas are, of course, purely speculative, and there 
seems to be no valid reason why the managers and foremen 
of the "labor group" should not be elected by the group 
members at the very outset as suggested, for instance, by 
Laurence Gronlund.' But the ideas are, nevertheless, 
valuable as indications of one of the possible arrangements 
under socialism. 

The city with or without political and industrial sub- 
divisions will thus absorb the most important govern- 
mental activities under socialism, and the central govern- 
ment will as a result be limited to the management of the 
"national" industries and to the enactment of general 
laws and regulations. 

For while the city will enjoy a much larger measure of 
independence under socialism than it does to-day, it is 

' "Neue Staatslehre," ad Editran, pp. 199, aoo. 

' "The Co6perative Commonwealth," Boston, 18^3, p. 186. 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



137 



not reasonable to suppose that it will be clothed with com- 
plete autonomy or the power to pass legislation of a general 
character. To confer such powers on the municipality 
would mean to weaken the state and to paralyze its 
usefulness as a factor in the industrial life of the nation. 
The state being thus retained under socialism, what 
will be the political form of its administration? Will it be 
republican or monarchic ? 

To the American reader the question may seem idle, 

I but it is, nevertheless, true that it has been the subject of 

\ considerable differences of opinion in the ranks of the 

I socialists of Europe. 

Of the early socialist writers Saint-Simon and Fourier 

' asserted that a constitutional monarchy was not neces- 
sarily incompatible with socialism, Karl Rodbertus, the 
friend of Ferdinand Lassalle, held similar views, and even 
Lassalle himself was not entirely opposed to the notion of 

, a "social kingdom." 

Of the modern writers on socialism Anton Menger seeks 
to solve the problem by the following theory: — 

"Like all great questions of politics between princes 
and nations, this is a question of power. The answer de- 
pends upon the revolutionary strength of the nation and 
upon the power which the monarchy has attained in the 
course of its historical development. Thus the socialist 
state will probably appear in the form of a republic in the 
Latin countries. On the other hand, the dynasties of 
England, Germany and other Germanic countries may 
through a proper policy assure the maintenance of the 
monarchy after the establishment of the socialist regime 
for some time, perhaps even for an indefinite period." '■ 

k ' "Neue Stoalslehre," pp. 171, 171. 



[138 THE SOCIALISr PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

What seems to lend some plausibility to this peculiar 
conception is the fact that the Englishmen, the Germans 
and the other Germanic peoples attribute but a secondary 
importance to the form of government of present society. 
There are no aggressive republicans in England, not even 
among the socialists, and the socialists of Norway, after 
the recent separation of their country from Sweden, sub- 
mitted to the election of another king without violent 
protest. 

The sentiments of the German social-democrats on the 
respective merits of the republic and monarchy were well 
expressed by August Bebel in the International Socialist 
Congress at Amsterdam on the occasion of his famous 
oratorical duel with the eloquent leader of French socialism, 
Jean Jaurfes. 

"As much as we envy you Frenchmen your republic," 
exclaimed he, "and as much as we wish it for otu^eives, 
we will not allow our skulls to be broken for jt : it does not 
deserve it, A capitalist monarchy or a capitalist repub- 
lic, — both are class states, both are necessarily and from 
their very nature made to maintain the capitalist regime. 
Both direct their entire strength in the effort to preserve for 
the capitalist class all the powers of the legislature. For 
the moment that the capitalist class will lose its political 
power, it will lose also its social and economic position. 
The monarchy is not so bad and the capitalist republic is 
not so good as you picture them." ' 

And similarly, A. Labriola, the brilliant young leader 
of the extreme wing of Italian socialism, declares : — 

"Class rule does not express itself in a monarchical 
"Sixttine Congris Socialist International," Compte-ReDduAn&ly- 



tique, Br 



isela, 1904, p 



^ 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 139 

form of government or in a republican form of govern- 
ment, but in the fact that one group of men exercise the 
political powers in their own interests. We must learn 
to understand that there are no political forms which 
exclude class rule, nor such which make it inevitable." ' 

On the other hand, the Frenchman Benoit Malon 
affirms categorically : — 

"Since the republic is the political form of human 
dignity, the states which will be founded by emancipated 
nations, can only be republican. The socialist state must 
be a federated republic, for federalism alone combines the 
respect for local and particular needs and the relative 
autonomy of secondary political organizations (munici- 
palities, etc.) with the great interests of the nations freely 
constituted." ' 

On the whole it is safe to assume that barring per- 
haps some peculiar tricks with which history sometimes 
amtaes itself, the socialist states will be republics, with or 
■without presidents or other individual heads. The affairs 
■of the socialist republics will in all probability continue 
to be conducted by -representative assemblies. 

The modern parliaments owe their origin to the capital- 
ist regime, but the social development of the last centuries 
seems to have made them indispensable for the demo- 
cratic management of the affairs of every large and com- 
plex state, and as far as we can see to-day, a socialist 
regime cannot offer anything better as a substitute. The 
old town meetings and other direct legislative and de- 
iliberative bodies of citizens may be practical for the 

* Artura Labriola, "Kifonne e Rivoluzione Sociale," Milan, i!)04| 
' B. Malon, "Pr&is dc Socialisine," Paris, iBga, p. 297. 



I 140 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

regulation of purely local affairs in small communities, 
but they are entirely inadequate to deai with complex 
problems of national import. Nor can the institutions of 
the popular Initiative and Referendum take the place of 
modem representative assemblies. The process of law- 
making requires even to-day a large measure of skill, 
special knowledge and precision. The enactment of a 
wise law or regulation presupposes a careful deliberation 
over its main object, and the minute and searching ex- 
amination of its separate provisions. In many cases the 
original project is modified and improved before adoption, 
and the law as finally enacted is often the result of a com- 
promise, more or less satisfactory to all. In all pro- 
gressive legislation, furthermore, there must be a certain 
consistency and continuity of idea, — a system; and this 
feature will be more essential to a socialist legislature, 
which will have to deal with the most vital problems of 
the nation, than it is to modem legislative bodies. 

But such systematic, planful and elastic legislation 
cannot be introduced by popular Initiative and cannot 
be enacted by popular Referendum. The Initiative is in 
its nature spasmodic and often inconsistent, and the 
Referendum is too rigid and categorical for a regular 
engine of the popular will. The Initiative and the Ref- 
erendum are excellent institutions in conjunction with 
parliaments. As preventives and correctives of legislative 
abuses they are indispensable to every true democracy; 
they cannot, however, do away with representative gov- 
ernment. 

But if representative assemblies should be retained under 
socialism, they will at the same time probably be modi- 
fied very largely to meet the requirements of greater 



SOCIALISM AND THE STATE 



141 



democracy and to comply with the new needs and func- 
tions of the commonwealth. 

The Initiative and Referendum will probably be 
established in conjunction with all legislative bodies, and 
will be coupled with the right of the constituents to recall 
their representative at all times. The representatives of 

I the people will furthermore be elected by the votes of all 
adult citizens, male and female, and their powers will 

[ naturally be curtailed by the limited functions of a so- 

I cialist parliament. 

What will be these functions, and in what manner will 

I they be discharged ? 

The functions of national government to-day may be 

' roughly divided under two main heads — those of a gen- 
eral administrative or political character, represented by 
the departments of foreign affairs, national defense, treas- 
ury, justice, education, insurance, health, fine arts, etc., 

. and those of a character, prevalently industrial or economic, 
such as the administration of posts, railroads, telegraphs, 
lines and other national industries and the de- 

I partments of agriculture, public works, etc. 

In the modern state the political functions largely pre- 
ponderate, and the economic functions occupy but a sub- 
ordinate position. This is natural in view of the fact that 
the political functions of the present state are largely 
exercised for the benefit of the ruling classes. Under 
socialism the industrial activities of the government are 
bound to increase, and the political activities to diminish. 
The division of the governmental functions into those 

k of a political and those of an economic nature has given 

I rise to the hypothesis that the socialist parliament will re- 

I main bi-cameral — the political chamber taking the place 



I 142 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

of the lower house and the economic chamber that of the 
upper house. 

" Does any one believe that the earth will cease to re- 
volve, if the present upper and lower houses of parliament, 
whose division does not correspond to anything, shall be 
replaced by a political chamber and an economic cham- 
ber?" queries B, Malon, and he continues; "The po- 
litical chamber might be elected by universal suffrage as 
our present representative assemblies; but the economic 
chamber, the larger and more important of the two, 
should be the result of professional elections, with proper 
regard to the special qualifications of the elected, so that 
it should truly represent the producers and workers of all 
categories." ' 

Anton Menger suggests a somewhat similar ar- 
rangement, "It will be expedient," he asserts, "that 
legislation in the socialist state shall be enacted by two 
chambers: one to be elective and to be subject to the 
democratic tendencies of the people, the other to be aristo- 
cratic, but to be composed not of the most useless, but of 
the really best members of the state;" and such "best 
members," according to Menger, are to be the highest 
active or retired state officials and the leading representa- 
tives of the sciences, arts and literature." 

The notion that the industrial affairs of the socialist 
state will not be administered by officers elected by gen- 
eral popular vote, but by men chosen by the members of 
each separate trade and calling for their experience and 
special qualifications, is generally accepted by the socialists. 

Wilhelm Liebknecht suggests that the most important 

' " Precis de Socialisme," pp. 300, 301. 
' "Neue Staatslehre," pp. 179, iSo, 



SOCXAUSM AND THE STATE 143 

work of legislation and administration be performed by 
conmiittees of experts instead of parliaments/ and Annie 
' Besant, in a somewhat vivid flight of imagination, says : 
"One may guess that in each nation all the Boards of 
commxmal authorities will ultimately be represented in 
some central Executive or Industrial Ministry; that the 
Minister of Agriculture, or Mineral Industries, or Textile 
Industries, and so on, will have relations with similar 
officers in other lands; and that thus, internationally as 
well as nationally, cooperation will replace competition." * 

^ "Ueber die politische Stellung der Sozialdemokratie," 9th Edition, 
Berlin, 1893, p. 5. 

' "Industry under Socialism," in Fabian Essays, American Edition, 
Boston, 1894, p. 147. 



CHAPTER VI 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



Politics, Representative Government and Political Parties 

Practical politics may be defined as the art or action 
of guiding or influencing the policy of a government, or 
the effort to obtain control of or influence over the powers 
of government.' 

And it is essential for the first part ot this definition 
that the guidance and influence to which it refers, should 
not be exercised by the organized government itself, but 
by persons or parties outside of it. The difference be- 
tween Administration and Politics is just this, that the 
fonner consists in the direct management of pubUc affairs 
by the persons ofTiciaUy vested with the power and charged 
with the duty to manage them, while the latter is an 
indirect management secured through influence or power 
over the public official. 

In absolute monarchies the powers of government are 
concentrated, at least theoretically, in' the person of the 
autocrat ; hence the political influence and functions of the 
country are confined to the small circle of persons who 

* "In tha nanoner and more usual sense, Politics is tbe act or vocation 
of guiding or influencing the policy of a government thiough the organi- 
zation of a party among its citizens." — CENTimY Dictionary. 

"The administration o£ public affairs or the conduct of political mat- 
ters so as to can; elections and secure public offices." — Stakdabs 
Dictionary. 

144 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



MS 



lalone have the opportunity to come in frequent contact 

I with the person of the monarch — the high nobility and 

■ the dignitaries of the church. Politics in such countries 

i conducted principally tlirough the medium of court 

I cliques; its objects aie usually the personal advantages 

' and preferment of a set of individuals or a caste; its 

methods are those of intrigue and conspiracy, and the 

climax of such politics is a palace or dynastic revolution. 

Countries of a constitutional form of government, on 

the other hand, are bound to evolve politics of an entirely 

different type. The head of a constitutional government, 

whether he be designated king or president, is but one 

wheel in the administrative machinery of the state. His 

I powers are limited by a constitution, and the active and 

' vital functions of government are vested in bodies of 

popular representatives — the national parliaments, state 

legislatures and municipal councils. In order to guide or 

influence the policies of such a government, it is no longer 

sufficient to gain the good graces of the chief executive; 

it becomes necessary to enlist the support or obedience ot 

a majority of the representative assembly. 

This shifting of the field of political operation en- 
tails a chain of radical changes in the methods, aims and 
objects of modem politics. The representative assemblies 
are large bodies of men, frequently of divergent views and 
interests ; their power is temporary, and its continuance de- 
pends upon the confidence of their constituencies; their 
deliberations and actions are public and open to the 
r scrutmy of the people; theu" actions must, therefore, be 
i such as will be reasonably certain to meet with the ap- 
roval of at least that portion of the population whose 
lupport is indispensable to their public careers. 



146 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

Under normal conditions the individual and unsup- 
ported political intriguer, plotting for liis own prefennent 
or for that of the small clique of his friends or confederates, 
is thus obviously powerless to influence a popular govern- 
ment to an appreciable degree. He disappears in politics 
with the disappearance of the absolute state, and his 
place is taken by the large body of citizens, banded to- 
gether perraanently for the purpose of controlling the 
government, ostensibly in the interests of the people as a 
whole according to their views of the needs of the people, 
but actually in the interest of a given class or section of 
the population, as we shall endeavor to show presently. 
The most direct way to control the government which 
naturally suggests itself to such a body of citizens, is to 
place men of then- own midst in the administration, and 
its ultimate aim is, therefore, to elect a majority of the 
representatives in the popular assemblies and of other 
governmental and public functionaries. Thus arises the 
modem political party w^ith its strong and ramified or- 
ganization, its platforms, issues and electoral campaigns. 
And in practice we observe that the origin of organized 
political parties coincides in each country with the estab- 
lishment of a parliamentary regime. "They are a neces- 
sary evil in free government," as De Tocqueville puts 



The British Parliament has largely served as a model 
for all other constitutional countries, and the Hfe of that 
body in its modern form, as the real repository of the 
political power of the country, may be dated from the 
meeting of the Long Parliament in 1640, when the House 
of Commons deprived the crown of its two most essential 

' Alexis de Tocqueville, "Democracy in the United States," p. 186. 



SOaALISM AND POLITICS 



H7 



I' prerogatives — the power to levy taxes and the right to 
i dissolve Parliament indefinitely, and to the Bill of Rights, 
' which practically vested all legislative functions of the 
United Kingdom in Parliament. Prior to the Long 
Parliament there were no fixed political parties in the 
modem sense in England, but the next year already wit- 
nesses the formation of the first two distinct and well- 
defined parties of England, the Cavaliers and the Round- 
heads; and these parties, subsequently known as Whigs 
and Tories, and still later as Liberals and Conservatives, 
gradually changing their aims and methods of warfare 
with the changed conditions of the advancing centuries, 
reappear as the leading factors in all political struggles of 
England, from the stormy days of the Long Parliament 
down to our own time. 

In France there were no organized political parties 
prior to the revolutionary Constituent Assembly of 1789, 
but when the first National Assembly or parliament met 
in 1791, after the adoption of a constitution for the re- 
public, it found itself at once divided into at least four 
distinct political parties — the Royalists, who yearned for 
a return to the old regime; the Feuillants or constitutional 
monarchists, the Girondists or moderate republicans, and 
the Montagnards or radical republicans. 

With the accession of Napoleon and the smothering of 
parliament and constitution, political party life disappears 
in France, but with the restoration and the new grant of a 
constitution and parliament, the new political parties of 
the Moderates and Independents immediately spring into 
being. 
In Germany the modern political parties date partly 
_ from the days of the Frankfort Assembly in 1848, and 



I 



F148 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

I partly from the establishment of the North German Union 
I in 1867. 

The colonies of the United States lioew little of politi- 
cal parties, and held such institutions in scant esteem. 
"Throughout the eighteenth century," remarks Henry 
Jones Ford, " party was regarded as a gangrene, a cancer 
which patriotic statesmen should combine to eradicate." ' 
But immediately following the Declaration of Independ- 
ence, and even before the formal adoption of the national 
constitution of the new republic, the Federalists and 
Anti-Federahsts appeared in the public arena as full- 
I fledged political parties, and while these parties have 
I since repeatedly changed their issues and watchwords, 
I and have finally settled on the party names of Republican 
and Democratic, they rule to-day the poHtics of the 
United States as absolutely and effectively as any political 
parties in the world. 

In Italy the modern political parties appear imme- 
diately after the accomplishment of the unification of 
the country as a constitutional monarchy. In Austria, 
Hungary, Belgium and Holland the grant or conquest of 
a constitution was in every case regularly followed by the 
formation of political parties; in Russia the grant of a 
mere phantom of a constitution was the immediate signal 
for the spontaneous creation of a number of political 
parties. 
I Constitutions, representative government and political 
* parties are thus intimately and indissolubly correlated 
with each other; they have a common origin, and together 
they constitute one historical phase in the development of 

' "The Rise and Growth ol American Politics," New York, 1898, 
p. 90. 



SOaALISM AND POLITICS 



149 



our political institutions — the phase corresponding on the 
whole to the modem or capitalist economic system. 

Just as the fixed absolute state is the most appropriate 
form of government of a rigorous feudal society, so is the 
flexible representative system the ideal form of govern- 
ment of the modem state of free competitive producers. 

The rise of representative government and political 
parties marks in all countries the ascendency of the 
modem industrial classes over the landowning classes 
formerly in power. 

It is true we find in history abundant mention of par- 
liaments and popular assemblies antedating by centuries 
the modem capitalist system, and some of them tracing 
their origin to hoary antiquity. But whOe these institu- 
tions may have had a remote influence on the shaping 
and forms of the modem parliaments, they certainly 
had nothing in common with their present substance and 
function. 

The essential features of every modem representative 
assembly may be summarized as follows: — 

1. It is an independent governmental organ, whose ex- 
istence and permanence are guaranteed by a constitution 
which represents the supreme law of the land. 

2. It meets at regular intervals. 

3. It has the power to grant or veto the taxes or budget 
' of the state. 

4. It is either vested with supreme legislative powers 
or it acts as a check upon the legislative powers of the 
crown. 

5. The cabmet ministers are directly or indirectly under 
its control. 

6. As a rule it is bi-cameral. 



r 150 THE SCOALISr PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

7. The lower house, at least, is representative in char- 
acter, and its members are chosen by and accountable 
to the citizens entitled to vote- 
Neither the medieval English Parliament, nor any 
other popular assembly of the early or middle periods of 
our era possessed these attributes. 

"The mediEEval Parliament," says Edward Jenks, 
"represented the estates of the realm, viz.: nobles, clergy, 
yeomen or peasants, and craftsmen. 

"But two things about it are well worth noticmg; — 
" (a) It was not, in any ordinary sense of the term, a 
popular institution. On the other hand, for many years 
after its appearance, it was intensely impopular, both 
with 'constituencies' and representatives. ... All hated 
it, because a Parliament invariably meant taxation. The 
members themselves disliked the odium of consenting to 
taxes which their constituents would have to pay. Only 
by the most stringent pressure of the Crowti were Parlia- 
ments maintained during the first century of their exist- 
ence; and the best proof of this assertion lies in the fact, 
that in those countries in which the Crown was weak, 
Parliament ultimately ceased to assemble. The notion 
that Parliaments were the result of a spontaneous demo- 
cratic movement can be held by no one who has studied, 
ever so slightly, the facts of history. 

" {b) Parliament, at any rate the representative part of 
it, was, in the origin, concerned solely with the granting of 
money. The nobles were, it is true, hereditary councilors 
of the Crown; but the clerical proctors, and the members 
of the counties and boroughs, could claim no such position. 
There was no pretense of such a thing in the early days of 
Parliament. It was liability, and not privilege, which was 



SOCIAUSM AND POLITICS 



the basis of Parliamentary representation; it was the old 
idea of seizure of the village elders (for ransom), carri^ 
out on a magnificent scale." ' 

These rather humiliating functions of the early Par- 
liaments are by no means peculiar to England. The 
French States-General were convoked by the king when- 
ever he needed money. Their duties consisted in making 
grants, and their riglits in presenting grievances or peti- 
tions, and the king as a rule forced the former and ignored 
the latter. The three Estates of France, the Nobility, the 
Clergy and the Commons or Third Estate, formed three 
independent chambers, deliberating and voting separately, 
the decision of any of the two chambers being binding on 
the third. And as the Nobihty and Clergy were exempt 
from taxation and otherwise mostly united in interest as 
agamst the burgesses and peasantry, the Assembly of 
Estates usually resulted in a heavy tax imposed by the 
first two Estates upon the third. Once in a while the 
rebellious representatives of the "third estate" would re- 
fuse to "register" the royal edict for new taxes. In such 
cases the king would personally appear in the session and 
compel the recalcitrant commons to register his edicts. 
This peculiar procedure was for some reason styled "lit 
de justice" — bed of justice. 

The mediteval German Diet was composed of the per- 
sonal representatives of the numerous reigning princes of 
the empire and a few representatives of the cities. It had 
no important or useful functions to perform and no real 
power over the country. 

The early Polish Diet was merely a council of the nobles, 
and the early Russian Assemblies were convoked on 

' Edward Jenks, "History ot Politics," London, igoo, pp. 133, 133. 



152 THE SOOALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

critical occasion, ordinarily for the purpose of fiomishing 
the government with money and arms. 

As to the ancient Teutonic and Anglo-Saxon assemblies, 
the witenagemotes, they have even less claim to the title 
of parliament in the modern sense than the medieval 
bodies. They were practically nothing but councils of 
elders or chiefs, with little or no bmding powers. 

And just as the pre-capitalistic "parliaments" have 
nothing in common with the modem institution of that 
.name, so have the pre-capitalistic "parties" no affinity 
with the political parties of the modem type. 

Historians sometimes designate as parties the followers 
of hostile princee contending for a throne, or the scattered 
adherents of a religious creed or even a scientUic theory. 
In that rather loose sense, parties have, of course, existed 
at all times. But it requires more than the mere common 
adherence to a person or theory to make a political party. 

No aggregation of individuals can be properly styled a 
political party unless they are bound together by a com- 
mon social and political ideal and by planned and organized 
action aimed at the maintenance or realization of that 
ideal; the two most \'ital features of every political party 
are: unity of principle and unity of action. 

And here we arrive at the most baffling aspect of the 
political party — the mysterious union of principle, which 
lends harmony and continuity to the modem political or- 
ganization, and enables it to survive all changing political 
situations and is.^ues. It cannot be mere casual agreement 
on abstract ideas and theories, for frequently we see a 
party as a whole abandon its original views and adopt 
new and altogether different grounds and issues. The 
history of the last century is replete with instances of 



^^^^B SOaALlSM AND POLITICS 153 

paxhes which were formed for specific political objects, 
and remained intact and active long after those objects 
had been fully accomplished. 

Nor can it be mere compatibility of temper that holds 
vast masses of individuals together in de&nite political 

I parties, for every political party of any significance unites 
within its fold men of all conceivable dispositions and in- 

I dinations. 

The force that cements the members of a political party 
together is obviously not to be looked for in the intellectual 
or psychic world. It must be found in the more realistic 
sphere of our existence — the material interests of the 
special classes of modern society represented by each of 
the political parties. 

Classes and Class Struggles in Modern Society 

One of the cardinal doctrines of modern socialism is 
the doctrine of the "class struggle." 

The inhabitants of every state, as was casually mentioned 
in the preceding chapters, may always be divided into 
several groups of persons with reference to their source of 
income or mode of acquiring the material means of their 
existence. Within each group the single individuals may 
strive for the largest possible share of the common income, 
but as against all the other elements of society, each of 
such groups is interested in the maintenance and increase 
of its special revenue or material wealth. Each of such , 
social groups constitutes a separate "class" of society, 
and the characteristic features of every class are these : 
its individual members are united in their general economic 
t interest with each other, and as a whole they are opposed 



1 54 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

to all other classes contending with them for their share of 
the national wealth. 

The existence of classes thus creates the instincts of 
class solidarity and class antagonism, and the socialists 
contend that the efforts of each class to maintain or improve 
its position, and the resultant conflicts between them, con- 
stitute the politics of the nations and make their histories. 

The doctrine of the class struggle in its present finished 
form was first proclaimed in " The Communist Manifesto," 
which was drafted by the principal theoretical founders of 
modern socialism, Karl Marx and Frederick. Engels, in 
1848, and is there stated in the following terse and cogent 



"The (recorded) history of all hitherto existing society 
is the history of class struggles. 

"Freeman and slave, patrician and plebeian, lord and 
serf, guild master and journeyman, in a word, oppressor 
and oppressed, stood in constant opposition to one another, 
carried on an uninterrupted, now hidden, now open, fight, 
that each time ended either in revolutionary reconstitution 
of society at large, or in the common ruin of the contending 
classes. 

" In the earlier epochs of history we find almost every- 
where a complicated arrangement of society into various 
orders, a manifold gradation of social rank. In ancient 
Rome we have patricians, knights, plebeians, slaves; in 
the Middle Ages, feudal lords, vassals, guild masters, jour- 
neymen, apprentices, serfs; in almost all of these classes, 
again, subordinate gradations. 

" The modern bourgeois society that has sprouted from 
the ruins of feudal society, has not done away with class 
antagonisms. It has but established new classes, new 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



ISS 



conditions of oppression, new forms of struggle in place 
of the old ones. 

" Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeois, possesses, how- 
ever, this distinctive feature; it has simplified the class 
antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more split- 
ting up into two great hostile camps, into two great classes 
directly facing each other: Bourgeoisie and Proletariat." ' 

The principal classes in modern society are thus, accord- 
ing to Marx and Engels, the classes of the "Bourgeoisie" 
and the "Proletariat," and a few words must be said here 
in explanation of these terms very current in the literature 
of socialism. 

"Bourgeois," literally a "townsman," was originally a 
term used in opposition to that of gentle or noble, and signi- 
fied a manufacturer or tradesman. The class of the "bour- 
geoisie," in an economic sense, has come to stand for the 
entire propertied class : it includes the modern manufac- 
turer, money lender, and even the landowner who employs 
his land for industrial or other business purposes. It is 
the entire "third estate," less the wage workers. 

The term "Proletariat" is borrowed from the political 
nomenclature of ancient Rome, where it was used to 
denote the class of free citizens without property or assured 
means of existence. ' In a more restricted and technical 

' "The CornmunLat Manifesto," New York, Socialist Cooperative 
Publisliing Assn., 1901, pp. 10, 11. 

' The etymoiogical derivation of the term is by no means free from j 
doubt. The Roman grammarians, and most of the modern writers after ' 
them, derive it from the word "proles" — descendants, and interpret 
the original meaning of proletariat as a descendant- beget ting or child- 
hearing class. The Austrian philologist, Stowasser, recently suggested 
the derivation of the word from "pro-oletarius," i.e., substitute for ma- 
ture worker, hired slave or common wage laborer. 

"Deutsche Worte," September, 1901, quoted in NeueZeit of October a, 



I 

I 



156 THE SOQALIST PHILOSOPHV AND MOVEMENT * 

sense, the word Proletarian signifies a workingman who 
does not own iiis tools of labor, a wage worker ; but in its 
wider application it embraces the entire propertyless class 
of workers. Thus we speak not only of the "industrial" 
proletarian, but also of the "agricultural" proletarian, 
the farmer who does not own his land, or the hired farm 
hand; and even of the "intellectual" proletarian, the pro- 
fessional who depends upon an unsteady and uncertain 
hiring out of his talents for a living. 

Such then are the main characteristics of the two prin- 
cipal classes of modern society, the Bourgeoisie and Proleta- 
riat, or Capitalists and Workingmen, and the antagonism 
between them to which the authors of "The Communist 
Manifesto" refer, is the conflict of material interests which 
springs from their mutual economic relations. 

The principal wealth of modern society is represented 
by an accumulation of commodities owned by individual 
competing capitalists and used for the purpose of exchange. 
The process of modern industry is a process of manufacture 
and exchange of such commodities. All wealth is created 
in that process, and all profits are derived through it. The 
diEEerent commodities exchange for each other at their 
actual value ; hence, the accumulation of profit and wealth 
must not be looked for in the process of exchange, but in 
the process of production. 

The value of a commodity is determined by the average 
social labor expended on its production, and if the manu- 
facturing capitalist should pay to the laborer a wage 
equivalent to the products of his labor, there would remain 
no margin of profit for hira, and the hoarding up of indi- 
vidual wealth would be impossible. But, as a matter of 
fact, the manufacturing capitalist does not return to the 



SOCIAUSM AND POLITICS 



157 



workingman, in the form of a money wage, commodities 
of a value representing his full hours of labor, but only 
such quantity as will enable him to maintain his existence 
according to the established standard of living and 
to reproduce his species. Thus assuming that the 
quantity of food, clothing and other necessaries of a work- 
ingman's life per day are produced in six hours of average 
social labor time, his wages will represent the portion of 
■ his labor equivalent to six hours, and if he works ten hours 
per day, the product of the remaining four hours of his 
labor is appropriated by his employer. 

Since the individual capitalist owns the tools without 
which no labor can be performed in modern society, and 
the laborer owns nothing but his ability to work — his la- 
bor power, the workingman is compelled to sell that labor 
power to the capitalist for a fixed daily wage. His labor 
power is sold to the capitalist to be used for a day of a 
duration of eight, ten or twelve hours, according to agree- 
ment, and the products of his labor are divided betweea 
him and his employer. The portion of such labor that 
falls to the share of the workingman is his wage, and the 
portion retained by the manufacturing capitalist Marx 
calls "surplus value," 

The "surplus value" of the manufacturing capitalist is 
by no means his clear profit; as a rule, he is forced to di- 
vide it with the landlord, the money lender and the mer- 
chant, "Surplus value" is the source of all profits of the 
manufacturing and trading capitalists, the rents of the 
landowning capitalists, and the interest of the money-lend- 
ing capitalists. Thus the capitalists of all types depend 
upon the production of " surplus value," while the working 
s depends upon wages. Since wages and "surplus 



I 
I 



158 THE SOQALIST PHILOSOPHV AND MOVEMENT 

value" come from the same source, i.e., labor power, 
it is clear that the proportion of the one will be relatively 
larger as the proportion of the other is relatively smaller, 
and vice versa; in other words, the greater the share of 
capital in the created values, the smaller the share of labor. 

The economic interests of capital and labor are, there- 
fore, opposed to each other, and while it is in the interest 
of the class deriving its income from "surplus value" to 
maintain the present system of distribution of wealth, the • 
interests of the working class lie in the abolition of that 
system. 

These are the main lines on which the modem class 
struggles are conducted, but a closer analysis of the process 
will show that they are by no means the sole lines of modern 
class division. 

The capitalists or bourgeoisie constitute but one class 
in their common interest to exploit the working class, but 
among themselves they are separated in many groups 
with reference to the special interests of the respective 
fields of their operation. The three main forms of capi- 
talist revenue, rent, interest and profits, spring, as we have 
seen, from the same source, the "surplus value" of the 
producing capitalists ; and the shares of these three cate- 
gories of income stand in inverse relation to each other. 
It is, of course, conceivable that rent, interest and profits 
may rise simultaneously, at the expense of the working class 
and the consumers, but they need not and do not always 
increase in equal proportions, and the total quantity of 
"surplus value" remaining equal, an increase of rents or 
a rise of the rate of interest will signify a lowering of profits, 
and vice versa. The three main economic divisions of 
capitalists, dependent on the three forms of income men- 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



159 



timed, the rent-gathering landowner, the interest-drawing 
money lender, and the profit-making manufacturer and 
merchant, are thus by no means united in interest between 
themselves. The money lender or banker exploits the 
mortgaged landowner and the borrowing industrial alike, 
while the owner of the factory site and store property ex- 
ploits the manufacturer and merchant with equal thorough- 
ness. Nor is the industrial group of the capitalist class 
always a unit in interests: the interests of the manufac- 
turers usually run counter to those of the sellers, and vice 
versa; and even within the manufacturing class the interests 
of separate trades are frequently opposed to each other — 
for instance, where the producers of one certain commodity, 
a finished article, are the consumers of the products of 
another class of manufacturers, those engaged in the 
production of materials. 

As compared with the divergent interests of the capital- 
ists among themselves, the interests of the working class _ 
are, on the whole, harmonious. The workingmen are 
frequently forced to compete with each other for employ- 
ment, which, as a rule, results in a general reduction of 
wages. But this competition is no evidence of a conflict 
of interest among different groups of workingmen; on 
the contrary, its effect is strong proof of the solidarity of 
their interests; and the recognition of the pernicious eiiects 
of their competition ultimately leads the workers to a more 
compact class organization. No group of workingmen 
benefits by the fall of wages of another group, no class of 
workingmen exploits another class; hence, there exists no 
economic cause for antagonism between the workingmen 
of the different trades. 

We have thus described and analyzed the two main 



I 



l6o THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

classes of modern society and their component parts. But 
between and besides them there are several economic 
groups which cannot properly be classed with the one or 
the other — the groups characterized by the general desig- 
nation of the "middle classes." These consist of small 
merchants, manufacturers and farmers, who, while they 
own their business, implements or land, and sometimes 
employ hired labor, still extract but little " surplus value," 
and chiefly depend for their living upon their own efforts. 
The members of the middle class are engaged in a strenuous 
and losing battle for the maintenance of their economic 
independence against the invading large industries. Their 
hope is to develop some day into large and wealthy capi- 
talists, their fate most commonly is to succumb to the 
superior means and organization of the great industries, 
and to find refuge in the employment of their victorious 
rivals or to be forced down to the ranks of the wage laborer. 
By their sympathies and sentiments, these men mcline 
towards the capitalist class, by their immediate economic 
interests they are arrayed against it, and at times they 
break out in a feeble or more vigorous revolt against om- 
nivorous capitalism. 

Another middle-class group of considerable impor- 
l tance is that of the " intellectuals " in the direct employ of 
the capitalists; the managers, superintendents, foremen, 
engineers, accountants, clerks, etc. The economic posi- 
tion of these is similar to that of the proletarian 
wage worker, inasmuch as they are also hired by their 
employers and paid a fixed remuneration for their 
services, but it is different with respect to the size of that 
remuneration. The average income of the men of this 
class is frequently larger than that of the middle-class 



SOaALISM AND POLITICS 



i6i 



maniJacturers, traders or farmers; they are styled "em- 
ployees," not " workingmen " ; they receive "salaries," 
not " wages," and by their education, social environment, 
tastes and habits, they feel themselves more akin to the 
capitalist class than to the working class. 

And finally we must mention the variety of the mid- 
dle class known as the "professionals," i.e., physicians, 
lawyers, clergymen, teachers, journalists, artists, etc. 
These constitute a class by themselves. They do not 
operate with capital, and their incomes are not derived 
from exploitation of labor, nor, on the other hand, do they 
as a rule sell their labor or talents to a permanent individual 
employer in return for a fixed periodical compensation, 
They are "free" practitioners, who sell their services to 
whomsoever pays for them from time to time. The men of 
this group usually find their most remunerative clientele 
among the possessing class, and place their skill and talent 
at the disposal of that class. It is from among this group 
that the capitalists primarily gather the apologists and 
defenders of their class interests, their "retainers," to 
borrow an expression from W. J. Ghent.' But the pro- 
fessionals are not permanently tied to the dominant classes. 
They are alert in perceiving every coming social change, 
and whenever a new class enters upon a promising cam- 
paign to displace the old order, these professionals desert 
their former patrons in large numbers and place them- 
selves at the head of the new movement. 



Tke Class Struggle in Politics 

In the preceding pages we have attempted to oudine 

the main class divisions in modern society. In the general 

' "Mass and Class," New York, 1905. 



l62 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



k 



struggle for social existence, each of these classes of ne- 
cessity seeks to fortify its economic position by the strong 
arm of the state. The dominant and possessing class as a 
whole needs the protection of the state, its laws, courts of 
justice, police power, and sometimes even its armed force 
to preserve its "vested rights" and privileges and to main- 
tain its power over the working class; and within the capi- 
talist class each interest group needs the special services 
and support of the state against the hostile groups of other 
interests. The transportation industries need charters, 
grants and franchises, the manufacturing industries want 
subsidies and protective import tariffs on manufactured 
articles, while they oppose tariffs on food stuffs; the agri- 
cultural landowning class, on the other hand, demands a 
high tariff on imported food stuffs, but combats the tariff 
on articles of foreign manufacture; the commercial classes 
generally strive for a free trade policy; the debtor classes 
see their salvation in anti-usury laws and debased currency ; 
the money-lending class requires a solid and unchangeable 
monetary standard; the small manufacturers and traders 
endeavor to avert the threatening ruin of their economic 
independence by the enactment of laws against combination 
and concentration of capital, while the workingmen look 
to the government for protection against excessive capi- 
talist exploitation. In short, each class and group strives 
to make the state subservient to its economic interests, to 
retain or capture the powers of government for its own 
special purposes. 

It is this phase of the class struggle which constitutes 
modem politics, and the economic classes and interest 
groups participating in it, correspond, roughly speaking, 
to the political parties or factions in each country. Thus we 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 163 

find in every constitutional country of Europe, whatever 
the elements of its political life may otherwise be, at least 
three definite political parties : the Conservative, the Lib- 
eral and the Socialist. In Germany and Austria, they are 
directly known under those names; in England the politi- 
cal party corresponding in its genera! features to the So- 
cialist Party in continental Europe is known as the Labor 
Party; in Belgium and Holland the Clerical Party prac- 
tically takes the place of the Conservative Party; in France 
the Conservative and Liberal parties sometimes are known 
under the names of the Party of Resistance and the Party 
of Movement, but under whatever name or guise they may 
appear here or there, they uniformly present the distinc- 
tive features of class parties. The Party of the Conserva- 
tives is always in substance the party of the landowning 
class. In countries of feudal antecedents it represents in 
the first instance the descendants of the landowning and 
privileged nobility, and its political ideal is the reconstruc- 
tion of the old regime and the restoration of the political 
powers of the aristocracy of birth — the party is usually 
opposed to all progress and reform. 

The Liberal Party is the party par excellence of the 
modern bourgeoisie. It represents the interests of in- 
dustry and commerce. In most countries it Is the party 
in power, and the aims of its politics are to maintain it in 
power. It favors such moderate and gradual reforms as 
tend to destroy the feudal remnants in modem European 
society without in any way endangering the supremacy 
of the class represented by it. Its political interests and 
ideals coincide on the whole with the present regime, — 
it is the party of the present. 

The Socialist Party is the party of the workingmen who 



r 



164 THE SOCIALIST PIULOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

have drawn the last conclusion from their struggles with 
capitalism. Its ideal is a cooperative commonwealth based 
on the collective ownership of the social instruments of 
wealth production. Its social ideal is not inspired by the 
fabulous "golden age" of the past, but is founded on the 
anticipated results of social progress, — it is the party of 
the future. 

Side by side with these three main parties representing 
the three principal classes of society, there exists in most 
countries of Europe a party generally known as the Radi- 
cal Party. This is the party of the middle class, and its 
political activity is the expression of the last struggles of a 
class doomed to economic annihilation between the upper 
grindstone of capitalist competition and the nether grind- 
stone of proletarian organization and aggressiveness, 

Paul L-ouis characterizes this party in the following 
language : — 

"It is composed of men whose social condition is ill 
defined, who are neither satisfied nor crushed, but who 
feel themselves menaced and strive to fortify their position. 
These men desire to conquer the political power in order 
to break the instruments of the material or moral domina- 
tion of the great industries and properties. . . . They 
demand fiscal reforms which would permit them to tax 
the large revenues and to place artificial fetters on the 
mechanical concentration of capital. . . . Nowhere do 
they constitute a coherent party, for nothing is more fugi- 
tive than its contingent." ' 

In the countries of Europe we thus find all principal 
economic classes and interest groups represented by sep- 
arate and well-defined political parties. The only excep- 
' "L'Avenir du Socialisme," Paris, 1905, pp. 105, 106, 



SOCIALISM AND POUTICS l6$ 

I tion seems to be presented by the money-lending group of 
I capitalists, who, as a rule, do not form parties of their own, 
■ This, however, may perhaps be accounted for by the func- 
tion of money capital, which can become operative only 
in connection with the other forms of capitalistic owner- 
ship, but has no independent productive existence. 

All other permanent political parties of continental Eu- 
rope are but slight variations of the foiir types described. 

In the United States of America, where the economic 
development of the country has not passed through the 
stage of feudalism, and where there exist no remnants of a 
feudal economy or of a class of privileged nobles, there is, 
of course, no room for a Conservative Party in the Euro- 
pean sense, and the parties of the propertied classes are 
formed on different lines. The Republican Party is sub- 
stantially the party of the modem capitalists, correspond- 
ing in its main characteristics to the Liberal parties of 
Europe, while the Democratic Party is largely the party 
of the middle class, the small business man and farmer, 
and bears some resemblance to the Radical parties of 
European countries. 

Such then, generally speaking, are the leading char- 
acteristics and motive forces of the modern political parties, 
but m practice their formative processes and workings 
are by no means so clear-cut and simple. 

In the complex relations of modern society, it is some- 
times exceedingly difficult to determine the exact line of 
class divisions. It is not always easy to determine when 
a man ceases to be workman and becomes a member of 
the middle class, nor whether he is to be classed as a 
"middleman" or capitalist; and within the capitalist class 
especially it becomes more and more dif&cult to divide its 



Fl66 THE SOOAUST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



members into definite interest groups. The extensive de- 
velopment of stock companies within the last decades has 
largely broken down the rigid lines of special interest 
groups within the possessing class, and the typical capitalist 
of to-day may and frequently does own at the same time 
stock in banks, in real estate concerns and in industrial 
and commercial enterprises. 

The economic mainsprings of politics are, besides, as a 
rule deeply hidden below the surface. With the sole 
possible exception of the working class in the countries 
of the most advanced industrial development, there Is not 
a single class or interest group large enough to conquer 
I and hold the modern governmental machinery by its own 
I numbers. Each of the classes contending for the political 
mastery of the country is, therefore, bound to seek the sup- 
port of other classes or their individual members, and this 
it can obviously not receive for the mere and avowed 
advancement of its naked class interests. To overcome 
the difficulty, the dominant political parties are thus in- 
stinctively led to conceal rather than expose their class 
character; they make concessions or hold out promises to 
all classes of the population, and by their official platforms 
and public declarations they pretend to strive for the com- 
mon welfare of the whole population. The interests of 
the classes represented by them are thus generalized into 
the interests of the entire nation, and their striving for 
political power masquerades as a struggle for lofty political 
ideals. These false pretensions are sometimes formulated 
consciously and intentionally by the shrewd party leaders, 
but perhaps more often the active political party workers, 
and especially its passive supporters, fully believe in their 
sincerity ; hence, we find the capitalist and middle-class 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



167 



aU . 



s largely supprorted by working- 
men, and, generally speaking, there is hardly a political 
party whose constituent elements are wholly recruited from 
one homogeneous class. 

"It is not contended," says W. J. Ghent, "that men are 
always, or even generally, conscious of the economic mo- 
tive that impels them. Far less is it to be contended that 
they are aware of the influence laid upon the exercise of 
that motive by the prevailing economic environment. The 
consciousness of their motives is often but dim and vague, 
and that motive which they believe dominant, a mere 
illusion." ' 

And moreover, the economic motive, while it is the domi- 
nant factor, is not the sole factor in politics. In times of 
threatened foreign invasion, the defense of the country 
may become a paramount political issue of equal impor- 
tance to all classes of the population, and when a govern- 
ment represents nothing but the autocratic power of a small 
clique, and becomes equally oppressive on all classes of 
society, as is the case for instance in Russia, all political 
parties may well unite in a common program of opposition. 
In times of special agitation an ideological sentiment may 
become a political issue of great force and break down all 
established party lines. At other times, especially when 
the dominant class is safely intrenched behind the powers 
of government without vital disputes between its dif- 
ferent interest groups and without the menace of a strong 
working class political party, politics degenerates into a 
question of mere individual spoils and patronage. 

"Mass and Clftss," p. 13. 



l68 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



The Socialist Parly in Politics 

In the general political struggles of the classes, the 
Socialist Party, as was stated above, represents the 
working class. This statement, however, requires some 
qualification and explanation. 

The Socialist Party represents in politics primarily the 
general immediate and ultimate interests of the working 
class as a whole. Its program consists of a number of 
planks calculated to strengthen the proletariat in its 
struggles with the dominant classes and to lessen the degree 
of its exploitation by the latter, and it culminates in the 
demand for the complete economic enfranchisement of 
the working class. Since the power of the dominant 
classes over the workingmen is based on the ownership 
by the former of the social tools and instruments of wealth 
production, the cardinal point of the socialist political 
platform is the demand for the abolition of private owner- 
ship in these means of production. 

The socialist ideal is a state of society based on organized 
and cooperative work of all individuals capable of perform- 
ing work, and on an equitable distribution of the products 
of such joint labor among all the members of the coni- 
mimity. The Socialist Party, the only party which frankly 
recognizes the class character of the contemporary state 
and politics, is at the same time the only party which ad- 
vocates the abolition of all class distinctions. All other 
political parties, while they ignore or deny the fact of the 
class struggle, either stand for the preservation of the 
present class relations or strive merely for the shifting of 
power from one of the existing classes to the other. The 



I 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 1 69 

Socialist Party alone has thus a certain right to claim that 
it represents the interests of the whole society. 

The Socialist Party is, however, preeminently a working- 
men's party, for the reason that its ultimate aim coincides 
primarily with the interests of the working class, while it Is 
a menace to the privileges and immediate economic in- 
terests of the possessing classes. Recognizing that the 
vast majority of men are moved by economic motives, 
the socialists make their appeal in the first line to the 
working class, and as a rule the Socialist parties actually 
recruit their adherents mostly from that class. 

But the workingmen are by no means the sole supporters 
of socialism. Its ranks are continually swelled by members 
of the middle classes, and by large numbers of ideologists 
from all classes of society, including those of the capitalists. 
These bourgeois ideologists come into the socialist move- 
ment either because they perceive in its lofty social ideal 
the realization of justice and freedom, or because they 
have become convinced, through a scientific analysis of 
modem tendencies of social and economic development, 
of the inevitability of socialism. The founders of theoret- 
ical socialism were men of that type, and the leaders of 
the socialist movement in all countries recruit themselves 
principally from among that class. 

The socialist movement did not enter the arena of uni- 
versal history as a practical political movement. In its 
inception it was purely a philosophical school indulging 
occasionally in miniature social experiments, and inter- 
fering in concrete political movements only by way of 
exception. In 1848, Marx and Engels stilt proclaimed 
that the "communists (the term then employed for the 
modem word Socialist) do not form a separate party op- 



I 



1 17° THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

posed to other working class parties," and as late as 1867, 
when the German subjects were granted universal suHrage 
in elections to the North German Diet, the socialists of 
that country seriously debated the question whether they 
should take part in these elections, or scornfully reject 
"the gift of Bismarck," and abstain from voting. 

The reasons for the reluctance of the socialists of the 
earlier period to engage in politics are quite obvious. 

In the first place, the movement m its more modem 
phase was only in its inception, and the number of its 
adherents was quite small. But It is numbers more than 
issues that count in political campaigns. 

In the next place, the franchise of the workingmen, the 
class upon whom the socialists primarily relied for their 
support, was in most countries of Europe monstrously 
restricted. In Germany universal manhood suffrage was 
confined to elections to the powerless North German Diet, 
but the more important municipal and state elections were 
then as now based on the "three-class system," ' which 
reduced the working-class vote to a minimum, or on a 
property test, which had the same effect. 

' Elections on the "three-dasa system" are by "categorEes." The 
voters are divided into three classes; the first including the largest tas- 
payers paying together one-third of the taxes; Ihe nert, those paying an- 
other third of the taxes in the second largest amounts; and the last class, 
including the remainder of the people. Each class elects the same num- 
ber of delegates to the conventions that choose the councilors or deputies. 
The result, of course, is always to return an assembly rapresentative of 
the property interests, and quite unrepresentative of the masse?. 

In the elections of 1893 to the Prussian Landtag 5,989,538 voters took 
part. Of these only 210,759 constituted the first class, the second con- 
sisted of 732,633, while the third class embraced all the remaining 
5,056,146. The 933,392 citizens of the first two classes could thus ea- 
L tirely outvote their 5,000,000 fellow-citizens of the poorer classes. 



SCOALISM AND POLITICS 



171 



In Italy and Belgium the right to vote in parliamentary 
elections was restricted to citizens paying direct taxes of 
specified minimal amounts, and qualified by a property 
test, with the result that in the former country there were 
in 1879 only 7.77 electors for each 100 male adults, while 
in the latter the voters constituted but little above 2 per 
cent of the population in 1874, Similar conditions existed 
in Holland, Hungary, Austria, Sweden and Norway. 
In England the expenses of the electoral campaigns were 
borne by the electors, as they still are, and were prohib- 
itively high for the workingmen. (Within the last decades 
the electoral laws in many European countries have been 
somewhat reformed in the direction of greater liberalism.) 

Besides, in most countries it was only the lower house of 
parliament that was elective, membership in the upper 
house was mostly, as it still remains in many cases, heredi- 
tary or appointive, and the composition of these bodies 
was frequently such as to blast all hopes of a progressive 
parliamentary policy. Thus the upper house or senate 
of Italy was composed of princes of the royal family and 
other dignitaries of the rctdm, more than 40 years of age, 
and chosen by the king from among the archbishops, 
bishops, ministers of the, cabinet, admirals, generals and 
very heavy taxpayers. In Hungary, the upper house 
consisted of 3 princes of the reigning house, 31 Roman and 
Greek Catholic prelates, 11 "standard bearers," 57 lord 
lieutenants, 5 dukes, 219 counts and 81 barons. What 
a chance a democratic lower house would have for the 
cooperation of such a chamber ! 

Moreover, the early socialist leaders had serious mis- 
givings about the effects of an electoral activity on the 
morale of the socialist masses. The parliamentary elec- 



I 



■ 172 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

tions, they argued, could result in but little, if any, benefit 
to the working class, but they might tend to divert it from 
the consistent stand of revolutionary opposition, and from 
the straight path of education and economic struggle. 

But still more than the demoralizing effects of electoral 
campaigns upon the movement, the socialists feared the 
corrupting influences of parliamentary life upon the chosen 
representatives of their party. They were inclined to view 
the European parliaments, with their limited powers, as 
assemblies whose principal function was to cultivate in 
their members the fine art of talking; talking not for the 
sake of convincing, but for the purpose of shining, and such 
talk, they reasoned, is calculated to deaden the revolution- 
ary spirit of the orator, to arouse his personal vanity and 
ambition, and to degrade him into a shallow demagogue. 
The views on the efficiency of parliamentary activity prev- 
alent among the socialists of that time were very similar 
to those recently expressed by the French socialist writer, 
Paul Louis, who says: — 

"Never has a great decision capable of briskly accelerat- 
ing the course of history, emanated from a parliament. 
Parliaments, even when elected by universal suffrage, 
occupy a position similar to that of the academies ; they 
regard the past, they defend the existing status; by their 
temperament, their procedure and byzantme exactness, 
they soon paralyze all men of action who may penetrate 
there." * 

Furthermore, they contended, for the socialist move- 
ment parliamentary activity could never be anything but a 
useless farce. As long as the socialist deputies shall 
remain in the minority, they will be powerless to influence 
' "L'Avenir du Socialisine," ParLs, 1905, pp. 71, 73. 



SOaALISM AND POLITICS 



173 



the actions of Parliament, and when the party shall be 
strong enough to elect a clear majority of the members of 
any parliament, the country will be ripe for the social 
revolution, and the cumbersome machinery of Parliament 
will become useless. 

Besides, their strict and rigid interpretation of the class- 
struggle theory made them doubt the wisdom of deliberat- 
ing and cooperating with the representatives of the hostile 
camps in joint council. "Wer mit Feinden parlamentelt, 
parlamenlirt, wer parlamentirt, paktirt !" tersely decreed 
the veteran leader of German Social Democracy, Wilheim 
Liebknecht.' 

But as against these possible disadvantages, the socialists 
were bound to consider the following features of political 
and parliamentary activity as positive advantages for their 
I cause: — 

The times of active electoral campaigns are peculiarly 
propitious for the discussion of social, economic and politi- 
cal theories ; hence they offer an excellent opportunity for 
the propaganda of socialism among the broad masses of the 
people, and that opportunity is largely enhanced, if 
socialism is made one of the direct issues of the campaign. 
And not only are political campaigns important as mediums 
of effective propaganda, they are also useful as periodical 
reviews of the socialist forces. The number of votes which 
the socialists poll at general elections is one of the surest 
gauges of the_ progress made by the movement in each 
country among the masses of the population, and nothing 



"Ueber die polit[scbe Stellung dec Sozial democrat [e," Berlin, 1893, 
a. The sentence is very difficult to render in English. Its mean- 

l'|i% is about as follows: "He who discusses with the eaEmj, negotiates 

t frith him, and he who negotiates, compiomises." 



174 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

stimulates growth so much as the proof of growth. Then, 
again, parliament is a platform from which the popular 
representative addresses not only his colleagues, but prac- 
tically the entire nation, and the socialist deputies thus are 
afforded a rare chance for the propaganda of their party 
principles on a large scale. 

The practical aim of the Socialist Party, moreover, is 
the capture of the powers of government by the working 
class in order that it might transform the state from an 
instrument of class exploitation into a cooperative common- 
wealth. But the working class cannot accomplish these 
tasks unless it is well organized and trained in the art of 
politics and administration, and practical political activity 
is best calculated to give it that organization and training. 

And finally, the socialists by no means disdain all partial 
reforms, and parliamentary activity opens lo them the 
opportunity to urge and the chance to pass reforms of 
actual benefit to the working class. 

These, then, were the doubts and questions, the pros and 
cons which met the socialists at the threshold of their 
political career, and while the leaders were discussing the 
theoretical aspects of the problem, the mass, as usual in 
practical questions, solved it, and, as usual, solved it right. 
The socialists went into politics yielding to the instincts 
^ of the masses, rather than following the reasoned policies 
of the leaders. 



Electoral Tactics of the Socialist Party 

The tactics and policies of every party must necessarily 
I be such as will be best calculated to insure its political 
\ success at a given time and place. They must be shaped 



SOaALISM AND POLITICS 



175 



tomeet the special conditions of each country and period, 
and must change with the change of these conditions. 
Pohtical tactics are never immutable, and they are not even 
as stable as political programs. But while the tactics 
of a political party are variable and changing, such varia- 
tions and changes are as a rule neither very radical nor 
very sudden. The policy of every party must in the last 
analysis be determined by and subordinated to its main 
aims and objects, its political platform, and as long as the 
latter remains in force, the former changes but slightly. 

These general principles of party policy apply to the 
Socialist Party with even greater force than to the other 
parties. The socialist platform is the only political plat- 
form which is practically identical in its main features 
and important details in all civilized countries; the prin- 
cipal aims of socialism are not those of local or temporary 
reform, but of permanent and radical social reconstruction ; 
the socialist methods of warfare were not evolved from 
casual and fleeting conditions, but from general and firmly 
established social and economic relations ; hence the mfun 
points of socialist tactics are bound to be practically uni- 
form and fixed as long as the present social system lasts. 
And as a matter of fact, we observe that while the details 
of socialist policy and tactics vary in every country, and are 
modified with every economic and political change, its 
most salient features are identical everywhere, and have 
undergone but little change since the days when the So- 
cialist Party first established itself in practical politics. 

The most striking characteristic of all socialist tactics 
is the political isolation of the party, its reluctance to fuse 
or combine with other parties in electoral campaigns. 
The Socialist Party usually makes independent nomina- 



I 



1 



176 THE SOaALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

tions for public office regardless of the prospects of imme- 
diate success in the election. As a rule it does not unite 
with other parties on a common electoral list or "ticket," 
it does not nominate non-socialists on its own ticket, it 
does not support candidates of other parties, and its mem- 
bers do not accept nominations or even indorsements from 
other parties. 

This poKcy of isolation has its good reasons. In theory 
it is the logical and inseparable sequel of the class struggle 
doctrine. Viewed from that standpoint there can be no ac- 
tual solidarity of interest, at least under normal conditions, 
between the Socialist Party which strives to overthrow the 
present regime, and the various parties of the propertied 
classes which are interested in upholding it. A political 
union between the Socialist Party and any other party can 
be accomplished, therefore, only on the basis of a compro- 
mise which of necessity entails the concealment or aban- 
donment of the most vital principles of socialism. And 
the Socialist Party is invariably the loser by such combina- 
tion. Experience has abundantly demonstrated that 
whenever a party of the propertied classes has invited 
the political cooperation of the working class, the latter 
has, with few exceptions, been used by it as a cat's paw for 
the furtherance of its own class interests. The working 
class has never derived a substanlial or lasting benefit from 
such an illogical alliance, but the latter has frequently 
served to bring in demoralization and disorganization in its 
ranks. Many young and promising revolutionary move- 
ments have been smothered by such compromises with 
the enemy, and the fate of the numerous short-lived politi- 
cal labor movements in the United States is very strong 
proof of the truth of this assertion. Nor is even the un- 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



177 



solicited support of the bourgeois parties always without 
danger to socialism in politics. The socialist candidates 
elected by non-socialist votes tacitly assume certain moral 

.obligations towards this class of voters, and when elected 

I they can rarely maintain the uncompromising attitude of 
the purely socialist representative. The socialists are, 
therefore, inclined to reject such political support, arguing 
with the Roman poet — "Timeo Danaos et dona ferentes" 

[ — I fear the Greeks even if they bear gifts. 

But with ail that the rule of uncompromising socialist 

[ tactics, like every other rule of human conduct, is not 
entirely free from exceptions. It is apt to be observed 
most rigorously and inflexibly in the earlier days of the 
socialist movement in every country, when that movement 
has not yet passed the phase of pure theoretical propa- 
ganda and has not yet become a real factor in practical 
politics. 

"There is no need of compromising while the entire 
activity of the party is limited to oral and written propa- 
ganda and the purely theoretical defense of party prin- 
ciples, which saves them from contamination by any 
foreign elements," observes S. Kotlyarevski.' 

And, it may be added, not only is there no Justification 
for a compromising policy in the early phases of the social- 
ist movement, but there is every reason against it. While 
scientific theories or social philosophies are new, it is 
always their novel and striking features, the features dis- 
tinguishing them from the accepted theories and philoso- 
phies, that receive the greatest emphasis. And only 
when such new theories or philosophies gain considerable 
currency or following, are their main propositions sub- 
' "Partii i Nauka," in Polyarttaya Svesda for January, 1906. 



I 178 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

jected to a more minute and critical analysis, and their 
qualifications and exceptions noted. The uncompromis- 
ing and uncriticising propaganda of new ideas is useful 
and even necessary in the early stages for their popular 
dissemination. And a practical movement based on such 
new ideas has besides a special interest in guarding its 
pristine purity and complete independence in the critical 
period of its inception or formation, for it is then that it 
can be diverted or absorbed by foreign elements with the 
greatest ease. 

But with the spread of the socialist movement and the 
growth of the Socialist Party, new problems present them- 
selves. When the party becomes so numerous as to con- 
stitute a factor of importance in the politics and parlia- 
ment of any country, but not numerous enough to control 
them by its own strength, the temptation to enlist the co- 
operation of other progressive parties for the purpose of 
accomplishing some immediate practical reforms becomes 
great. Impatient cries are raised within the party urging 
political combinations for such purposes, and are met by 
the warning voices of the more conservative leaders tena- 
ciously adhering to the class- struggle tactics. 

How do the socialists generally meet the new situation ? 

In a preceding chapter we observed that even in our 
present class state there are certain political situations in 
which the immediate interests of classes otherwise hostile 
may occasionally coincide. 

In countries of feudal origin it is generally in the com- 
mon interest of the progressive bourgeoisie and the work- 
ing class to remove the surviving feudal remnants from 
the social and political structure of their countries, since 
I such remnants are often an impediment to all social prog- 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



i;9 



and in the countries of restricted, plural or qualified 
suffrage, the Radical, Liberal and Socialist parties have 
sometimes an equal interest in extending the suffrage. 

The extension of popular suffrage, more especially, is 
of the greatest vital importance to the Socialist Party, since 
the latter can hardly make any poiitica! progress, still 
less conquer the political powers of the country, in the 
absence of equal and universal suffrage. 

This situation is the key to the solution of the problem. 
The socialists often combine with other progressive parties 
for the attainment of these common purposes; they com- 
bine but rarely for any other purposes. 

Thus Ferdinand Lassalle, the founder of the Social 
Democratic Party of Germany, outlined the tactics of the 
proposed party in his famous "Open Letter" addressed 
to the workingmen of Leipsic in 1863, in the following 
langu^e : — 

"The working class must constitute itself into an inde- 
pendent political party, and must make the demand for 
universal, equal and direct suffrage, the watchword and 
motto of that party. ... It must feel and constitute 
itself as a party entirely distinct and separated from the 
Progressive (Liberal) Party; it must nevertheless support 
the Progressive Party in those pomts and questions in 
which the interests of the two parties are identical, but turn 
its back upon it and actively oppose it as often as it aban- 
dons these interests." ' 

When the English Reform League was organized for 
the purpose of securing much- needed reforms in the mode 
of parliamentary elections, Karl Marx and other members 

' Ferdbaod Lassalle's "Reden und Scbriften," Bernstein Rcvisioa, 
, Vol. II, p. 413. 



I80 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



b 



of the General Council of the International Workingman's 
Association took active part in the deliberations of that 
body together with the bourgeois members of other 
progressive political parties, and in Belgium, Denmark 
and Sweden the Socialist Party has at different times for- 
mally entered into political alliances with other parties 
upon the common platform of suffrage extension. 

But all such socialist alliances with bourgeois parties, 
whether made for the purpose of suffrage reform or for 
any other political object, are never permanent. They 
are made for a special purpose and are dissolved as soon 
as that purpose is accomplished. 

"We social democrats," said Bebel at the International 
Socialist Congress of Amsterdam, in 1904, "are broad 
minded enough to accept from our adversaries all con- 
cessions we can obtain from them, when they offer us some 
real benefit in order to secure our support to-day for the 
government, to-morrow for the liberal parties, the day after 
even for the party of the center, which makes a special 
bid for the workingmen's votes. But the hour after we 
combat them all, the center, the government and the 
liberals, as our permanent enemies. The bottomless 
chasm which separates us from the government as well as 
from all parties of the bourgeoisie is not forgotten for a 
minute." ^ 

In the countries where an absolute majority is required 
for election to parliament, and a second ballot thus often 
becomes necessary to determine the choice in certain 
districts, the Socialist parties frequently enter into agree- 
ments with other parties for the support of their mutual 

' "Sixii^me Congr&s Sockliste Inlernatiooal," Compte-Rendu Aiia- 
lytique, Brussels, 1904, p. 88. 



I 

I 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



iSi 



candidates as against the candidates of other parties, on 
the second ballot. While the excuse for this seeming 
digression from non-compromising socialist tactics is 
obvious, the Sociahst parties of Germany and other coun- 
tries have repeatedly endeavored to abolish this practice, 
but with Kttle success; the socialist voters as a rule insist 
on exercising their suffrage on all occasions, and the watch- 
word of abstention in any election has never met with their 
general approval. 

In the United States, in which there are no political or 
economic remains of a feudal system, hardly any restric- 
tions upon universal manhood suffrage, and no second 
ballots in general elections, there seems to be no reason or 
excuse for any deviation from the general socialist prin- 
ciple of absolutely independent poUtics, and the socialists 
of America have in fact on every occasion declared them- 
selves against all forms of pohtical combination or co5pera- 
tion with other parties. 

ParliamentaTy Tactics of the Socialist Party 

The first entry of socialists into parliamentary politics 
was characterized by the same diffidence and misgivings 
that had marked then: early participation in electoral 



Thus, when the first socialists were elected to the old 
North German Diet, so shrewd a party leader as Wilhelm 
Liebknecht advocated a purely negative attitude on the 
part of the socialist deputies towards the positive work of 
Parliament. "My personal opinion," says he, "was that 
our elected representatives should enter Parliament with 
a protest, and withdraw immediately, without, however, 



I 



I 



582 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



surrendering their credentials. With this opinion I re- 
mained in the minority; it was decided that the repre- 
sentatives of democracy could utilize every opportunity 
they might deem appropriate, in order to emphasize in 
the 'Diet' their attitude of negation and protest, but that 
they should keep aloof from all practical parliamentary 
proceedings, because any participation in such proceed- 
ings would imply a recognition of the North German 
Union and of Bismarck's policies, and might tend to obscure 
the fact that the struggles in the 'Diet' are but ^ctitious 
struggles and a mere farce," ' 

These negative tactics were steadfastly adhered to 
during the first two sessions of the North German Diet, 
but already the next session witnessed a spontaneous de- 
parture from the rigid rule, when several socialist deputies 
took the floor in the first parliamentary discussion on the 
subject of governmental labor regulation. And the so- 
cialist tactics of parliamentary abstinence have since 
gradually but definitely given way to the policy of watchful 
and energetic parhamentary activity. The socialist depu- 
ties in the European parliaments have preserved their 
uncompromising attitude of "negation and protest" 
practically on the sole subject of the budgets of their respec- 
tive governments ; they vote almost uniformly against their 
approval, arguing that as representatives of the working 
class they cannot consistently grant to capitalist govern- 
ments the means to maintain a class state, which in almost 
all cases includes a standing army." In all other matters, 

' "Ueber die politische Stellung der Sozial democratic," p. 13. Com- 
pare also, Robert Hunler, "Socialists at Work," New York, 1908, p. an. 

'Recently a strong apposition hasdeveloped in the ran Its of the Social 
Democratic Party of Germany to (he continuance ot the party's tradi- 
I tional attitude of protest against the budget. 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 183 

nowever, the socialist groups in the parliaments of Europe 
are among the most active and alert: the socialist deputies 
are never tired of introducing legislative measures for the 
betterment of the social, political and material conditions 
of the workingmen, for the curtailment of capitalist ex- 
ploitation, and for the advancement of true social progress. 

Thus at the convention of the Socialist Party of France, 
held at Reims in 1903, the parliamentary representatives 
of the party reported that they had introduced during 
the preceding session of parliament no less than forty- 
six legislative bills, the principal provisions of which 
dealt with the following subjects: the guaranty of se- 
crecy and liberty of the ballot; the suppression of the 
religious budget; the old-age pension; the repeal of the 
laws against vagabondage; the right of government and 
municipal employees to strike; the monopoly of sugar 
refineries; the enactment of a labor code; the abolition 
of the trucking system; the abolition of private employ- 
ment bureaus; theamendment of the laws on trade unions; 
the abolition of the standing army; the creation of a 
department of labor; the introduction of the initiative and 
referendum in legislative matters; the freedom of hunting 
and fishing, and the insurance of workingmen against 
accidents/ 

In the session of the German Diet of 1900-1901, the 
representatives of the Social Democratic Party introduced 
bills for the amendment of the industrial courts act ; for 
tenement house regulation and inspection; for the crea- 
tion of a national department of labor and of a national 
factory inspection bureau; for the limitation of the work- 

' "Parti Socialiste de France," Comple-Rendu du Deuw&me CongrtB 
National, Teau i Reims, September 17-39, 1903, p. 38. 



I 



I 184 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

day of all employees in industrial, commercial and other 
occupations and pursuits, to ten hours; for the prohibition 
of employment of children under the age of fourteen 
years; for the extension of legal protection to working- 
women, especially those pregnant or in childbed; for the 
prohibition of the manufacture, import and export of 
matches with white phosphorus; for the extension of 
the rights of assembly, organization and coalition; for 
the extension and guaranty of the liberty of the press; 
for the abolition of the offense of Ifese majesty ; for the 
immunity of members of parliament from arrest during 
parliamentary sessions; for enforcing the responsibility 
of the Imperial Chancellor to the Diet, and for the reap- 
portionment of parliamentary electoral districts in accord- 
ance with the increase of the population.' 

We have chosen these instances of proposed socialist 
legislation from the two countries in which the socialist 
parliamentary groups are the oldest and have had ample 
time to settle down to fixed parliamentary practices, for 
the reason that the wide and varied scope of these pro- 
posed measures is typical of the socialist activity in the 
parliaments of all other European countries. Besides the 
proposed laws of the character of those mentioned, there 
are numerous other radical measures advocated most 
uniformly and persistently by socialists in parliaments, 
among them bemg those providing for a graduated in- 
I come and inheritance tax. 

But the cEfort to initiate legislation does not by any 
means exhaust the parliamentary work of the socialists. 

' " Pratokoll ijber die Verhandlungen cles Parteitages dcr Sozialdcmo- 
kiatischen Fartei Deutstb lands," abgehaltea zu Lilbeck, September 23- 
aS, 1901, p. 77. 



I 



■^H SOaALlSM AND POLITICS 1S5 

The socialist deputies take part in the discussion on all 
legislative measures of social import introduced by the ' 
government or other parties, supporting or opposing or 
urging amendments, according to the nature of the pro- I 
posed measure; they make full and sometimes very ' 
effective use of their right to interpellate the government 
on its actions, attitude or intentions with respect to matters 
or occurrences of public interest; they accept membership 
in the various parliamentary committees, and generally 
participate in all the detailed work of the parliaments. 
Thus the attitude of the socialists towards the positive 
work of parliaments has changed very radically within 
the last few decades, and the change was by no means 
arbitrary, but was brought about by the increased political 
strength of the socialist movement. A movement may 
well maintain a piu^ely negative and criticising attitude 
so long as it is numerically weak and politically insignifi- 
cant. But when the movement grows in strength and 
extension and gradually becomes a recognized social and 
political power, it can no longer remain at a dignified 
distance from the actual and practical struggles of modem 
industrial and political life — it is forced into the very 
center of these struggles and is involved in all their details: 
its progress becomes more persistent and aggressive, its 
program and practical work become more detailed and 
specific. 

In 1867, when Liebknecht and his associates first formu- | 
lated their rigorous program of pariiamentary abstention, 
Germany was the only country that had socialist repre- 
sentatives in parhament, and the total number of these 
representatives was eight. To-day, after just forty years, 
the socialist parties have over four hundred deputies in 



\ l86 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



the national parliaments of sixteen European countries, 
and hosts of representatives in minor legislative assemblies 
and municipal councils all over the world. 

The socialist deputies in every country constitute a 
separate and independent parliamentary group, but they 
freely support other parties in parliaments in such meas- 
ures and actions as they consider to be in the interests of 
the working class or in the furtherance of true social 
progress. The difference between such political co5pera- 
tion in parliament and cooperation or combination in 
electoral campaigns is obvious. In parliaments votes are 
taken upon concrete and single issues from time to time; 
each party determines its stand on a given issue in con- 
formity with its general views and the interests of its 
constituents, and the parties taking a similar stand natu- 
rally vote and act together on the particular issue. No 
compromise or organic fusion is involved in the pro- 
cedure. The socialists in parliament frequently accept 
and support compromise measures, but only in cases 
where the measures contain at least some positive benefit 
to their cause; they do not indulge in the practice of po- 
litical "swapping," by which one party often gives its 
support to a measure which it would otherwise oppose, in 
return for the similar support for its pet measures by the 
other party. 

Nor do the socialist representatives in parliament make 
lasting or permanent alliances with the other parties for 
any purpose. 

When the famous "bloc republicain" was formed in the 
t Parliament of France as a defensive and offensive union 
[, against the monarchists and reactionaries, who were 
I advanced to the foreground by the violent anti-Dreyfus 



SOaALISM AND POUTICS 1S7 

agitation, one wing of the socialist group, the moderates 
or opportunists, joined the " bloc." But that policy proved 
so unsatisfactory to the socialists of France, and met with 
such decided criticism from the socialists of other countries, 
that it was soon abandoned. 

Another and much more mooted point of parliamentary 
tactics presented itself to the socialists of Europe in recent 
years. In 1899, the "radical" French premier, Waldeck- 
Rousseau, conferred the portfolio of Commerce and In- 
dustry on the socialist deputy, Etienne Millerand, and 
thus for the first time in the history of modem politics 
a socialist became a full-fledged cabinet minister. The 
event came as a surprise to the socialists of France as well 
as to the socialists of all other countries, and the wisdom of 
Millerand's entry into the Waldeck-Rousseau cabinet, or, 
stated in terms of the general principle involved, the wis- 
dom of socialist participation in a bourgeois government, 
for a time furnished the foremost subject of discussion in 
the socialist press and in all socialist party circles. 

The defenders of Millerand's course, who came to be 
known as " ministerialists," saw in the entry of a socialist 
into the government of the country a partial attainment 
of that "conquest of the powers of government" which is 
the final political aim of all socialist parties. The offer 
of a cabinet portfolio to a socialist, they argued, is not a 
free gift on the part of the government; it is a concession 
forced from it by the growing strength of the party. It 
is as much a legitimate object of political conquest as is a 
seat in parliament, and the socialists having conquered 
that high position in the administration of the affairs of 
the country, would prove themselves inconsistent and weak- 
kneed if they should shrink from its responsibilities instead 



I l88 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



utilizing its great opportunity for tlie advancement of 
their cause. 

On the other hand, the ultra radical wing of the socialist 
movement in France and other countries was utterly 
opposed to participation of socialists in bourgeois govern- 
ments under any and all circumstances. The powers of 
government in a centralized state, they declared, cannot 
be conquered piecemeal. As long as the dominant inter- 
ests in parliament are those of the capitalist class, the 
government must, on the whole, be a class government, 
administered in the interests of the possessing classes and 
directed against the classes of non-possessors, and a socialist 
member of such a government is bound to become a tool 
of the bourgeoisie in its struggles against the workingmen. 
The socialist party can gain no positive benefit from the 
membership of one of its representatives in a bourgeois 
cabinet, but it may suffer incalculable harm by assuming 
responsibility for the acts of a hostile government. 

The views of the great bulk of socialists outside of 
France on the vexed question were admirably expressed 
by Karl Kautsky in a letter to the "ministerial" French 
newspaper, Pelile Republique : * — 

"The question whether and to what extent the socialist 
proletariat may participate in a bourgeois government," 
writes he, "is a question of tactics, which must be an- 
swered differently in different countries and at different 
times, and which I do not dare to answer in absolute and 
unconditional terms. 

"In Switzerland and in England, such a participation 
would seem to me possible; in Germany, out of the 
question. 

' Reproduced in Die Neue Zeit, igth Year, Vol. I, p. 37, 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



"But just because I cannot give an absolute answer, I 
cannot assert that the principle of class struggle prohibits 
a socialist from entering a bourgeois cabinet under all 
circumstances. 

"Under normal conditions a socialist wiio recognizes 
the class struggle will be as little inclined to enter a 
bourgeois cabinet as an atheist would be inclined to enter 
a clerical cabinet' or a republican a cabinet of Bonapart- 
ists. His activity in such a cabinet could in the long run 
hardly have any other effect than to corrupt and to com- 
promise him and his party. 

"But I do not mean to say that there may not be ex- 
ceptional cases in which it may sometimes be proper for 
socialists to cooperate for a definite purpose with bourgeois 
democrats in the same government against a common 
enemy, without violating the prmciple of class struggle. 
Such experiments will indeed always be dangerous, but 
there may be possible situations which would justify 
them." 

The Millerand experiment has abundantly proved that 
the exceptional situation of which Kautsky spoke did not 
exist in his case, and the official career of the first socialist 
minister has, on the whole, confirmed the apprehensions 
of the "anti-ministerialists." The socialist parties in 
France and other countries have now adopted the definite 
policy of uniformly declining membership in cabinets, 
and while there are to-day two socialist ministers in France 
(Briand and Viviani) and one in England (John Bums), 
the socialist parties of these countries disclaim all connec- 
tion with or responsibility for them. Viviani and Burns 
had ceased to be members of the Socialist Party long before 
they accepted their portfolios, and Eriand was summarily 



I 
I 



h 



1190 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

expelled from membership in his party as soon as he 
entered the cabinet. As showing the prevalence of the 
fashion of appointing socialists to cabinet positions, it is 
amusing to note that even Tsar Nicholas II could not 
abstain from offering to a prominent Finnish socialist, 
Mr, J, K. Karl, a portfolio in the Finnish cabinet. Mr. 
Kari, formerly secretary of the Finnish Socialist Party, 
accepted the offer, and was promptly read out of the party. 
"What a strange pass our bourgeois republic has come 
to at this day," exclaims Jean Jaurfes, " when cabinets can- 
not live without calling in socialists, even when socialists as 
a party deliberately decline to take office; when the repub- 
lican majority not only turns to our model socialists to bring 
about needed reforms, but even has recourse to the rene- 
gades of revolutionary socialism to carry out effective 
measures against the advancing hosts! The Third Re- 
public utilizes our men of energy and even our traitors I" ' 

Political Achievements of Socialism 



The practical political activity of the socialist parties 
is, on the whole, of quite recent date. The social demo- 
crats of Germany entered on their first electoral campaign 
as far back as 1867, but for almost twenty years they 
stood practically alone in the field of socialist politics- 
Sporadic attempts at electoral campaigns were made by 
socialists in Holland beginning in 1S80, in Italy in i88a 
and in Denmark in 18S4; but as well-organized and con- 
tinuous political parties the socialists entered the political 
arena in France in 1885, in Denmark in 1889, In Sweden in 
1890, in Italy in 1892, in Spain in 1893, in Belgium in 

> The Indtpendent, New York, June ao, 1907. 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



191 



^ 



1894, and finally in Austria, Holland and Norway as late 
as 1897. In the United States the socialists nominated 
their first national ticket in 1892. In some of these coun- 
tries the socialists had occasionally engaged in municipal 
and other minor campaigns somewhat earlier, but on the 
whole it may be said that the average period of practical 
and systematic socialist activity in politics does not exceed 
twenty years. 

This comparatively short space of time has by no 
means been barren of positive results for the socialist 
movement and the working class, 

The parliamentary achievements of the socialist parties 
may be divided into such reforms and measures as are 
directly traceable to socialist initiative and such as are the 
indirect results of socialist politics. 

The reforms of the former class are few and rather 
insignificant, as must naturally be expected in view of the 
fact that the socialists as yet constitute but a small minority 
in every parliament, and a minority generally hostile to 
the rest of the house. Moreover, in several European 
parliaments, notably in the German Diet, a fixed and 
rather large number of seconders is required before a 
proposed measure may be considered by the house; and in 
most of such countries the socialist parliamentary groups 
have not been, until recent years, numerous enough to 
comply with such requirements, so that their activity was 
of necessity limited to the support or opposition of measures 
introduced by the government or by other parties. 

Summing up the positive achievements of social demo- 
cratic politics in the German Diet, Hermann Molkenbuhr ' 

' "Positive Leiatungen dei Sozialdemocratie," Die Neue Zeit, aslh 
Year, Not. 37, 39 and 30. 



192 THE SOQALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

claims some direct socialist victories in all the domains 
of parliamentary legislation dealing with workingmen's 
insurance, factory laws, industrial courts, the civil code, 
protective tari£E and taxation. Taking the existing 
German law on accident insurance as an illustration, he 
shows, by an elaborate analysis of the origin of its 
various provisions, that no less than twelve of its most 
substantial amendments have been adopted on motion of 
the social democratic party, while the party of the center, 
which habitually poses as the champion of the working 
class, has only two of such amendments to its credit, 
the party of the government and the liberal union, each 
one, the other parties having contributed nothing at 
all to the amelioration of this important law. In France 
the socialist deputies have initiated or secured the passage 
of several favorable measures, among them laws reducing 
the hours of labor of government employees, extending 
the powers of municipalities, suppressing private employ- 
ment bureaus, and several important amendments to the 
accident insurance law. In Denmark the socialists in 
parliament have, after persistent efforts of twenty years, 
recendy succeeded in securing the passage of a law which 
makes it incumbent on the government and municipalities 
to grant considerable subsidies to labor organizations 
formed for the support of their unemployed members. 
In Italy, Belgium and Switzerland the socialist representa- 
tives in parliament have at one time or another succeeded 
in securing the passage of several measures of social re- 
form, while in Sweden, Norway and Austria the socialist 
parties have within recent years secured largely extended 
suffrage. 
Far more important, however, than the laws du-ectly 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



193 



initiated in parliaments by socialist representatives, are 
those numerous measures of social legislation which have 
within the last two decades been passed by the parliaments 
of almost all civilized countries as the indirect but never- 
theless legitimate result of socialist political action. These 
measures are as a rule taken by the liberal or even con- 
servative parties bodily or with some changes from the pro- 
grams formulated by the socialist parties, and are fathered 
as original proposals of the opponents of socialism in order 
to destroy the effectiveness of the socialist propaganda. 
Far-seeing statesmen sometimes meet such "issues" with 
apparent cheerfulness, even before they have acquired the 
force of popular demands, and shortsighted governments 
grant them grudgingly when the general ciy for them has 
practically become irresistible. Prince Bismarck, as was 
pointed out in a previous chapter,' frankly avowed that the 
object of the broad social legislation inaugurated by him 
was primarily to avert a popular revolution, and the greater 
part of the social and political reforms inaugurated since 
by the several parliaments of Europe clearly owe their 
origin to similar considerations. In those countries of 
Europe in which the socialist movement has attained 
such political strength as to cause alarm to the parties of 
the dominant classes, the latter regularly shape their 
policies with special reference to their probable effect on 
the socialist vote, and the " stealing of the socialist thunder " 
is one of their favorite manceuvers, especially in time of 
approaching electoral campaigns. Chancellor Von Buelow 
has publicly admitted this fact for Germany, and it is 
more than an accident that the golden era of social legisla- 
tion in all other countries coincides quite closely with the 
' "Social Legislfltion and Socialist Jurisprudence." 



I 194 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

period of practical socialist politics; that countries in which 
political socialism is weak, as, for instance, the United 
States, are the most backward in the domain of social 
legislation, and that the few labor laws occasionally passed 
by the American state legislatures are so often nullified 
by court decisions. 

But all the parliamentary victories of socialism, direct 
or indirect, are but a minor part of the political achieve- 
ments of the socialist parties. Socialist politics is not 
restricted to parliamentary elections and activity; it 
extends to all minor divisions of the state in which the 
administration is wholly or partly elective, to the landtags 
of Germany, the cantonal councils of Switzerland, the pro- 
vincial councils of other countries, the state legislatures of 
the United States, and above all, the councils of munici- 
palities. And it is the last- mentioned domain in which 
the socialists have so far achieved their greatest practical 
triumphs. 

The powers of municipalities are, as a very uniform rule, 
largely restricted by the state, and a socialist administra- 
tion never has the opportunity to realize all or even a sub- 
stantial part of its program within the scope of a municipal 
government. But on the other hand the socialists, while 
they have so far not succeeded in a single instance in con- 
quering the government of an entire country, province or 
state, have gained the absolute majority in the councils of 
numerous municipalities in many countries of Europe and 
within the very restricted scope of municipal powers they 
have had the opportunity to experiment in practical 
administrative problems. 

Of the countries with a strong socialist representation 
in the municipal administration, we must mention in the 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



I9S 



first place France, where but one wing of the socialist 
movement, the Parti Ouvrier Franjais, in 1904, had full 
control of the administration of 63 municipalities and a 
grand total of over 1300 municipal councilors in 174 
cities and towns. The unified Socialist Party of France 
has to-day about 3800 representatives and officers in 
about 500 municipalities. The Italian socialists adminis- 
ter over one hundred towns and cities and have represen- 
tation in the councils of more than 1200 municipalities; 
the socialists of Belgium have majorities in the councils of 
22 municipalities and a total of 650 representatives in 193 
towns; those of Austria had, in 1904, 526 representatives 
in 178 municipalities; the socialists of Norway elected in 
1907 over I too representatives in urban and rural com- 
munities; those of Denmark have over 400 municipal 
councilors, and the socialists of England and Sweden 
have strong representations in the municipal administra- 
tion of their countries. Even the Socialist Party of the 
United States has at different times had the control of 
the administration of several towns, and has about three 
hundred mimicipal officers in the different parts of the 
country. 

The work and achievements of these socialist municipali- 
ties vary in each country according to the special condition 
of their inhabitants and the latitude of action allowed to 
them by the centra! governments, but a pretty complete 
picture of such work and achievements may be obtained 
from a brief description of the main features of "municipal 
socialism" in the countries where it is most strongly 
represented. 

From the country in which municipal socialism is 
strongest, France, we have the reports of the mayors of 




igfi THE SOQALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

several cities ' which afford an excellent insight into the 
workings of "socialist" municipalities. 

In Roubaix, a manufacturing town in Northern France, 
of a population of about 125,000, the socialists were in 
control of the municipal government for a number of 
years. The first attention of the socialist council was given 
to the task of properly bringing up the children of the poor. 

"The child and its welfare, its protection against disease, 
against want and against contamination, its training and 
its culture," says Felix Chabrouilland, the socialist secre- 
tary of the Roubaix municipality, in one of the reports 
mentioned, "this has been the constant care of the socialist 
council of Roubaix. 

"The sociaJist officers began their work for the little 
ones by admitting girl-mothers to the relief offered by the 
bureau of charities, which up to that time had been piously 
denied them. For the benefit of infants the socialist 
officers provided a distribution of layettes to needy mothers. 
Moreover, the bureau of medical assistance has been 
reorganized, and the mothers can obtain without cost the 
services of the doctor and the midwife, 

"The child is bom. To whom shail the mother intrust 
it if she must return to the factory? 

" Before the socialists came into power, Roubaix had no 
municipal creches (day nurseries). They contented them- 
selves with subsidizing to a slight extent the work of private 
creches. 

"In 1894 the first municipal creche was started in a 



' The reporta appeared originally in "Le Mouvcmeiit Socialiste" and 
in "Le Socialiste"; they were translated into English and published 
under Ihe title, "Socialists in French Municipalities," by Charles H. 
Keir, Chicago, 1900. 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



197 



rented building in the heart of a populous district. Some 
months later $10,000 was voted for building another 
creche, which, opened in 1896, deserves to be taken as a 
model, A third is now building, and others are under 
construction. Children are received in the municipal 
creches without any charge. 

"The resolution establishing restaurants for school 
children was passed by the socialist council on the first day 
of its official existence. These restaurants, the cost of 
which is borne by the school fund, are open every school 
day of the year. The great majority of children are ad- 
mitted without charge. The children enrolled as paying are 
charged fifteen centimes a meal in the kindergartens and 
twenty centimes in the primary schools. Since 1892 the 
school restaurants of Roubaix have served 2,818,601 meals, 
of which only 20,402 were paid for. The meal consists 
of a soup, a plate of meat with vegetables. So grammes of 
bread and a glass of beer. 

"To give children food of the first quality is an excellent 
thmg. But some of them lack sufficient clothing. Since 
the socialists have replaced the reactionaries in the mayor's 
office, the bureau for clothing school children has distrib- 
uted to the poor children in the secular schools 157,617 
pieces of clothing, — trousers, shirts, dresses, caps, pairs 
of stockings or of shoes, etc. 

"By the terms of an agreement made in 1897 ^^^ ^^~ 
newed in 1900, the city of Roubaix sends to the seaside 
hospital of Saint -Pol -sur-Mer, a little place near Dunkirk, 
the children from its common schools who are enfeebled, 
anemic — in a word, ' candidates for disease,' whose 
delicate constitution may be restored by the good effects 
of a sojourn at the seashore. These children are sent 




t.lgS THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

during the summer season, from April 15 to October 1 
and remain a month at the sanitarium. Each < 
is composed of not less than 100 children nor more than 
160, and their only duty while at the seashore is to take 
deep breaths of fresh air, play in the sunlight and improve 
in health. No classes, no lessons, no discipline other than 
what a parent would impose, but watchful care. Already 
i86g little 'candidates for disease,' boys and girls, have 
been helped by a month at Saint-Pol. There is no doubt 
on the part of any one acquainted with the facts but that 
the benefit to the children, moral as well as physical, has 
been great." 

The socialists of Roubaix also largely extended and im- 
proved the common school system of the town by estab- 
lishing a number of new classes, introducing courses of 
manual training, etc. 

Next to the all-important subject of education, the so- 
cialist administration of Roubaix bestowed the greatest care 
upon the matter of public health and the support of the 
poor. It established municipal bathing houses and dis- 
infecting plants as well as municipal bakeries and kitchens. 
In its bakeries it baked its own bread for the poor of the 
town, and distributed it freely at the homes of the latter, 
while its kitchens provided all needy families with whole- 
some food, at the lowest possible price. 

In addition to this, the socialist municipality paid a 
pension of 120 francs a year to the aged poor of cither sex 
living at home ; it provided a number of cottages for widows 
with little children to care for, established a bureau for 
free legal advice and built a new hospital for the sick. 

The socialist administration of Roubaix largely benefited 
the mimicipal employees, whose hours of labor were re- 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



199 



I 



duced to eight per day and whose wages were substantially 
increased, and it endowed the theaters and the scientific 
and artistic societies of the town more liberally than its 
bourgeois predecessors had done. 

In the still larger city of Lille, which was likewise 
under socialist control for a number of years, the mu- 
nicipal reforms introduced by the socialists bear a 
general resemblance to those of Roubaix, except that 
some of them, particularly those relating to sanitary 
measures and hygienic supervision, were carried out on a 
larger scale, A notable feature of the socialist administra- 
tion of Lille was the promotion of the fine arts and higher 
education among the poor. The school of fine arts was 
reorganized on a higher and more ef5cient plane; the 
municipal theater was frequently opened to the workers, 
and by agreement with the management of the theaters in 
the city, the administration received four hundred free 
seats at each performance, which were distributed among 
the workingmen; popular concerts and lectures were 
periodically arranged at the expense of the city, and liberal 
prizes were awarded to poor students of recognized ability. 

The examples of Roubaix and Lille are typical for all 
other municipalities under socialist control in France. 
In almost all cases the care of the children, the public 
health, the assistance of the poor and the legal protection 
of the workingmen are the prime concern of the admin- 
istration. 

The socialists of France ascribe but a secondary im- 
portance to the municipal ownership of street cars, tele- 
phones, etc., although wherever possible, they regulate the 
rates of such public service concerns and sometimes even 
operate them as municipal enterprises. 



I 
I 
1 



200 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



With all their reforms, the socialist municipalities in 
France are as a rule far from being extravagant or reckless 
in their expenditures, and their balance sheets usually show 
a. substantial surplus. The taxes are shifted, as much as 
possible, from the poor to the wealthy. 

In Belgium the powers of the municipal administration 
are even more limited than in France — the mayor of the 
cily is appointed by the king, and the decisions and ordi- 
nances of the municipal council are subject to the veto of 
the "deputation permanenle," a bureau of the provincial 
parliament and of the king. Under these circumstances 
the socialists in Belgian town and city councils have natu- 
rally not been able to introduce very radical innovations 
in the municipal administration of the country. Thus the 
principle of the progressive income tax for the raising of 
municipal revenues has repeatedly been adopted by the 
councils of socialist municipalities, and has been vetoed 
by the government as often as adopted. Among the first 
tasks of a socialist municipality in Belgium is the improve- 
ment of the conditions of the workingmen in its employ. 
A fixed minimum wage, a fixed maximum workday, and 
insurance against accidents are almost uniformly among 
the first measures adopted by a new socialist administra- 
tion in a Belgian town. The schooling of children with the 
special features of free clothing, free meals and vacation 
colonies plays as important a part in every socialist mimici- 
pal administration in Belgium as in France, but in the 
former somewhat more attention is being paid to the 
mimicipal operation of street cars, gas, electricity, water- 
works, etc. 

The socialist municipal councilors of Belgium have or- 
ganized a tmion for the study of municipal problems and 



SOaALlSM AND POLITICS 201 

the dissemination of information on affairs of municipal 
administration, with a permanent bureau and a salaried 
secretary, and their example has been followed by the 
socialists of Holland. 

The socialist municipalities of Denmark proceed sub- 
stantially along the same lines as those of France and 
Belgium. Speaking for the town of Esbjerg as a typical 
example, the editor of the local socialist paper relates in a 
recent report: " The Socialists hold 12 of the 19 seats in the 
city council. Our first act, after having gained control, 
was to assist the poor, and we have managed to make it 
possible for all poor to avoid public charity. 

"We then helped the hungry school children by giving 
them a free noon-day meal, until the minister of the in- 
terior prohibited the appropriation of the necessary means. 

"We next had the food paid for by the free poor fund and 
in turn appropriated money for the fund. 

"Later, however, we formed a private organization, 
which took charge of the feeding of the school children, 
and strangely enough, the city council was now given 
permission by the department of the interior to appropriate 
the required money for this purpose. 

"We have endeavored to improve the school system, 
until we now have free and uniform education in all 
common schools, 

"However, other things have drawn public attention 
toward Esbjerg more than these. The contractors 
formerly had a solid organization and as a njle always 
agreed on bids for public works, and then divided the 
profits. The socialists soon put a stop to this. We em- 
ployed workmen direct and bought our own lumber and 
brick. We built a school and employed our carpenters 



f.302 THE SCOALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 



direct. Then we were boycotted. We could get no more 
brick at the iiilns, and the team owners were forbidden to 
deliver any material to the building. This strike lasted 
half a day, after which we bought the required brick at the 
contractors' own brick kiln, 

"The employers' association, however, has since at- 
tempted, hitherto without any success, to delay or even 
stop all work undertaken by us, 

"The anti-socialist minority has now resigned in a body, 
in spite of the fact that they have been represented on all 
committees, according to their number in the council." 

The distinctive features of municipal socialism in Italy 
are the reduction of the taxes on articles of food, the 
increase of direct taxes, and the municipal subsidies and 
support of labor exchanges and coSperative enterprises 
conducted by trade unions, although the socialist admin- 
istrations do not neglect any of the customary municipal 
reform measures. 

In the United States Wisconsin is so far the only state 
in which the socialists have of late years had a substantia! 
and growing representation in the legislature and in the 
councils of some municipalities, notably in the city of 
Milwaukee, In the state legislature as well as in the 
Milwaukee City Council, they form minority groups, 
but they have nevertheless been able to influence the actions 
of both bodies in a marked degree, Mr, Carl D. Thomp- 
son, a former socialist member of the Wisconsin State 
Legislature, enumerates a surprisingly large number of 
positive measures initiated by the Socialist Party and 
passed by the city council of Milwaukee or the state 

jislature of Wisconsin.' 
' "The Conatructive Program o£ Socialism," Milwaukee, 1908. 



SOCIALISM AND POLITICS 



203 



The achievements of socialist politics in the field of posi- 
tive reform are thus not insignificant. But the socialists do 
not overestimate them. They consider them as measures 
calculated to brace and strengthen the working class in 
its struggle against capital, but by no means as the be- 
ginnings or installments of a socialist system. 

The work of systematically rebuilding the economic and 
political structure of modern society on the lines of social- 
ism, can begin only when the socialists have the control 
of the entire political machinery of the state, i.e., of 
all the legislative, executive and judicial organs of the 
government. As long as the socialist representatives in 
modem legislative or administrative organs remain in 
the min ority, the more radical and truly socialistic reforms 
advocated by them, the reforms aimed at the dispossession 
of the privileged classes, are bound to founder on the op- 
position of the ruling-class majorities in the government. 
The socialists can expect to carry out their program only 
by a series of gradual and successive, but systematic and 
uninterrupted measures, when they themselves are in 
the majority in the government, either having carried a 
majority of the popular vote in a successful election, or 
having been placed in power fcy a popular rising. The 
chief aim of socialist activity is, therefore, to develop the 
numerical strength and political maturity required for the 
ultimate conquest of the powers of government, and the 
'supreme test of the success of present socialist poUlics is 
the measure in which it realizes that aim. And it is in this, 
their most important function, that socialist politics have 
achieved their highest triumph. 

For whatever might have been the significance of socialist 
politics as a factor in securing immediate social reforms, 



[ 304 THE SOCIALIST PHILOSOPHY AND MOVEMENT 

it certainly has been of transcendent importance in the 
creation of the powerful national organizations of socialism. 
It was the practical political battles of socialism, the 
concrete attacks on the enemy, the definite issues and war 
cries, the common victories and defeats that attracted mul- 
titudes of European workingmen, and it is these that are 
beginning to attract the mass of American workingmen to 
the banner of socialism. If the number of socialist voters 
of the world has grown from about 30,000 in 1867 to 
almost 10,000,000 in 1908; if the socialists have become 
a recognized factor in the public life of 25 modern na- 
tions, having representation in the parliaments and ad- 
ministrative orgajis of 16 of them; if the socialists have 
elaborated a clear, detailed and sober program of social 
transformation, and developed ia their ranks thousands 
of thinkers, orators, statesmen, organizers and leaders, 
the practical poUtics of the modem socialist parties is 
largely responsible for these splendid results. Without 
the unifying and propelling force of political activity, the 
socialist movement tonday might not have advanced much 
beyond the stage of the purely literary significance of the 
early socialist schools or beyond that of a number of inco- 
herent sects. 



PART n 

SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



CHAPTER I 



INTRODUCTION 



Socialists and Social Reformers 



Tot 



e of the ti 



t puzzlin 



s of the 



e outsidei 

socialist movement is its attitude towards the modem move- 
ments for social reform. The socialists are reformers. 
The socialist program contains a large number of concrete 
measures or "demands" for the progressive improvement 
of our industrial, social and political institutions, and much 
of the practical political activity of socialism is directed 
towards the advancement of such reform measures. 

And still socialists are often found reluctant to co- 
operate with non-socialist reformers for the attainment of 
specific reforms. Even when such proposed reforms are 
apparently in line with the demands of socialism, the sepa- 
rate movements for their realization are not seldom met by 
them with indifference, sometimes even with active op- 
position. 

The socialists have on that account been charged with 
narrowness and inconsistency, but these charges are based 
on an entire misconception of the character of socialist 
reforms. There is a vital distinction between the reforms 
advocated by the socialists and those urged by the re- 
formers of all other shades. 

The non-socialist reform movements may be divided into 
' two general groups; those inaugurated distinctly for the 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



benefit of the middle classes, i.e., the small farmers, manu- 
facturers or traders, and those supported by ideologists of 
all classes. 

The movements of the former variety have for their in- 
variable object the strengthening of the position of the 
middle class as against the increasing power of large 
capitalism. The measures advocated by them often con- 
template the arrest of industrial development or even the 
return to conditions of past ages. Among such "reform" 
measures arc the restrictions on combinations of capital 
and the provisions against suppression of competition- 
Measures of this character are reactionary even though 
in their formulation they sometimes coincide with working- 
class demands. 

The ideologists of the "better classes" represent a less 
reactionary but not more efficient type of social reformers. 
These kind-hearted but shortsighted gentlemen are 
thoroughly convinced of the soundness of our social 
system as a whole. They notice occasionally certain 
social evils and abuses, and they endeavor to remove them 
in what seems to them to be the most direct way. They 
happen to encounter an appalling condition of poverty, 
and they seek to allay it by alms. They notice the spread 
of disease among the poor, and tliey build hospitals and 
sanitariums. They are shocked by the tidal wave of crime 
and vice, and they strive to lead the sinners back to the 
path of righteousness by moral sermons and model penal 
institutions. They find their elected representatives in 
public office incompetent and corrupt, and they unite to 
turn them out of office and to elect more efficient and 
honest men. They treat each social abuse and evil as an 
isolated and casual phenomenon. They fail to see the con- 



INTRODUCTION 



20g 



I 



nection between them all. For them, as for the late 
German-American statesman, Carl Schurz, there is no 
social problem, but there are many social problems. 

The aim of all socialist reforms, on the other hand, is to 
strengthen the working class economicaUy and politically 
and to pave the way for the introduction of the socialist 
state. The effect of every true socialist reform must be 
to transfer some measure of power from the employing 
classes. A socialist reform must be in the nature of a 
working-class conquest. 

The socialist reform measures, moreover, are all insepa- 
rably and logically connected \vith each other, and only 
when taken together do they constitute an effective pro- 
gram of social progress. As separate and independent 
measures, they would be trivial, and from the point of view 
of the ultimate aim of the socialist movement, none of 
them is alone of sufficient importance to warrant the con- 
centration of all efforts for its realization. 

The difference between the conceptions and methods 
of the ideological social reformers and those of the social- 
ists may be best shown by an illustration borrowed from 
the domain of pathology. A number of physicians are 
called into consultation on a grave case. The patient 
suffers from spells of coughing, headaches and high fever, 
His appetite is poor, and he is losing weight and color. 

If the physicians are thoughtless and superficial prac- 
titioners, they will regard all these indications as so many 
separate and mdependent diseases. They will treat each 
of the supposed diseases separately or they will have each 
treated by a specialist in that particular branch of medicine, 
Eut if a scientific and experienced practitioner be called into 
the consultation, he will say to his colleagues: "Gentle- 



SOCIAUSM AND REFORM 

men, your diagnosis of the case is wrong. The patient 
does not suffer from a complication of diseases. The 
many supposed diseases which you have discovered are not 
independent casual ailments; they are all but symptoms 
of one grave organic disease — tuberculosis. If you suc- 
ceed in banishing this organic disease from the patient's 
system, the symptoms which you take for independent 
ailments will disappear of themselves, but if you persist in 
treating the symptoms without attacking the root of them 
all, the patient cannot improve." 

And so, likewise, it is with the so-called evils of society. 
Our social conditions are not healthy and normal, our 
social organism is ill. The abject poverty of the masses 
with all its concomitant evils — sickness, ignorance, vice 
and crime — is appalling, while the extravagant luxuries 
of our multi-millionaires only serve to accentuate the utter 
misery of "the other half." 

The gigantic trusts and monopolies which have developed 
within recent years, the periodic crises and chronic strikes 
and lockouts, are proof of the pathological condition of our 
industries, while boss rule, corruption and bribery mark a 
similar condition in our politics. 

To the superficial student of society these conditions 
present so many separate "evils," each one independent 
of the others, each one curable by itself. Hence our 
charity organizations, anti-vice leagues and societies for the 
prevention of crime; hence our "trust busters," single 
taxers, municipal-ownership men and anti-corrupt-prac- 
tices advocates; hence our social and political reformers 
of all types and specialties. 

The socialists, on the other hand, see a clear connection 
and necessary interdependence between these evils. They 



INTRODUCTION 



regard them all as mere symptoms of one deep-rooted 
disease of our social organism and do not believe in curing 
the mere symptoms without attacliing the real disease. 
This disease the socialists find in the imhealthy organiza- 
tion of our industries, based on the private ownership of 
the means of production and distribution. 

Poverty is the direct result of capitalistic exploitation, 
and ignorance, vice and crime are poverty's legitimate 
children. To maintain its rule, capitalism must dominate 
government and public sentiment, hence the constant 
incentive for the ruling classes to corrupt our politics, our 
press, pulpit and schools. 

The ultimate aim of the socialist movement is to convert 
the material means of production and distribution into the 
common property of the nation as the only radical and 
effective cure of all social evils. But this program does 
not imply that the socialists propose for the time being to 
remain inactive, complacently expecting the dawn of the 
millennium. 

The scientific physician in our illustration, after having 
made his diagnosis, does not idly sit by expecting the 
coming of the day when the dread disease shall suddenly 
disappear. He proceeds to the proper course of treat- 
ment forthwith. By a systematic process of strengthening 
his patient's physique, by increasing his powers of resist- 
ance, he gradually restores his patient's health. In the 
course of the treatment he does not disdain palliatives 
calculated to give temporary relief, but all his remedies 
are strictly consistent and coordinate, and are applied 
with the ultimate object constantly in view — the destruc- 
tion of the mortal germs of the organic disease. 

And the socialists proceed in a similar manner. They 



SOaALISM AND REFORM 



seek to prepare the people for the radical change of the 
industrial basis of society, by a systematic and never- 
ceasing course of education, training and organization, 
but in the meantime they do not reject temporary reform. 
They favor every real progressive measure, and work for 
such measures wherever and whenever an opportunity 
offers itself to them. But all the socialist reforms are con- 
sistent parts of their general program; they all tend in one 
direction and serve one ultimate purpose. 

To the ordinary social reformer, on the other hand, each 
evil is an evil by itself to be ciu-ed without change of the 
system which produces it, and hence his "practical" 
reforms are doomed to failure. The charity worker may 
bring temporary relief to a few hundred poor, a mere atom 
in the world of poverty, but he cannot check poverty; 
the moral crusader may "save the souls" of some fallen 
women and men, but as long as the conditions which drive 
them into vice and crime remain unchanged, he cannot 
stamp out vice or crime; the political reformer may suc- 
ceed in a certain campaign, and defeat the corrupt "boss" 
or divorce the legislature from the corrupting lobby, but 
the next campaign will find a new "boss" at the head 
of his party and a new host of capitalist agents in control 
of the legislature as long as the industrial conditions 
which breed corruption in politics continue. Just as the 
middle-class reformers are reactionary and Utopian, the 
ideological reformers are, as a rule, superficial and ineffec- 
tive, and the socialists can, therefore, gain nothing by a 
union with either. 

From this analysis of the aims and nature of socialist 
reforms it will be readily seen that socialism cannot attach 
an equal importance to all the numerous reform measures 



INTRODUCTION 213 

agitated in our days. Its relation to each of such measures 
depends on the special character of that measure and its 
efficiency as a weapon in the class struggle. In the 
following chapters we will endeavor to deal with the 
subject from that point of view. For the convenience of 
treatment, we will group the most popular reforms imder 
five main heads, and we will consider the character, 
achievements, and rdle in the socialist program of each 
reform group in a separate chapter 



CHAPTER n 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



Industrial Reform 

Under this general title we will include all direct efforts 
to improve the present economic conditions of the wage 
laborers, to diminish the degree of their exploitation and 
to strengthen their position in the struggles with their 
employers. 

The specific movements coming under this head are those 
for the improvement of labor conditions and other measures 
commonly designated as factory reform; the reduction of 
the hours of work, the abolition of child labor, the regula- 
tion of woman labor and all other progressive movements 
represented by the trade imions and the cooperative so- 
cieties of workingmen. 

The socialists attach the greatest importance to all 
reforms of this character. They realize that the task of 
transforming the modern capitalist society into a socialist 
commonwealth can be accomplished only by the conscious, 
systematic and persevering efforts of a working class 
physically, mentally and morally fit for the assumption of 
the reins of government, and not by a blind revolt of a 
furious and desperate rabble. Every measure calculated 
to remove from the workingman some of the cares and 
imcertainties of his material existence, to improve his health 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



2IS 



and spirits, to give him some measure of leisure, and some 
time for thought and study, is bound to enhance his general 
intelligence, his interest in social affairs and in the prog- 
ress and welfare of his class. The adherents of socialism 
principally recruit themselves from among the better 
situated classes of the workmgmen, and the socialist efforts 
to raise the economic level of the working class are an 
organic part of the socialist movement, an indispensable 
condition of its progress and ultimate triumph. 



N 



Factory Reform 

The beginnings of factory legislation are to be found in 
the classic country of modem capitalism, England, where 
Parliament as early as 1802 adopted the bill introduced 
by Sir Robert Peel for the protection of the apprentices 
employed in cotton mills. The measure was called forth 
by the inhuman conditions in the English cotton mUls, 
into which thousands of orphans and pauper children of 
the most tender ages were bound out by the parishes under 
the old Elizabethan "Apprenticeship Act," without re- 
striction on their hours of labor and without provisions 
for then: health and education. These unfortunate chil- 
dren were forced to work up to fifteen hours a day, and 
were crowded in penl-up, unsanitary buildings adjoining the 
factory. They were ill-clothed and underfed. They were 
growing up under conditions of physical, mental and 
moral degeneracy, and it was the menace to the future 
of England's laboring population implied in these con- 
ditions which secured the passage of the Peel act. 

Viewed from the standpoint of modem conceptions, the 
act of 1802 was no great achievement. It limited the 



zi6 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



■workday of the cotton mill apprentices to twelve hours, and 
compelled the mill owners to clothe their apprentices and 
to give them a certain limited school instruction. But 
the great significance of the act lies in the fact that it was 
the first to break down the bourgeois doctrine of non-inter- 
ference by the state in the industrial relations of its citizens. 
It created the "precedent," so indispensable to the Anglo- 
Saxon mind; it opened the door to factory legislation. 
And slowly but steadily the principle of state protection 
for factory workers grew in scope and extension. In 
England the law of 1S02 was followed first by the timid 
amendments of 1819, 1835 and 1833, and then by the bolder 
measures of the latter half of the last century, until factory 
laws became a regular and important function of parlia- 
mentary legislation. Starting with the regulation of the 
labor of apprenticed children, they gradually extended their 
operation to the "free" working children, then to working 
women, and finally to all factory workers. 

From England the principle of factory legislation spread 
to the United States, Germany, France and Switzerland, 
and finally it established itself in all industrial coimtries. 

"Looking broadly now to labor legislation as it has 
occurred in this country," says Mr. Carroll D. Wright, 
speaking of factory laws in the United States, " it may be 
well to sum up its general features. Such legislation has 
fixed the hours of labor for women and certain minors in 
manufacturing establishments; it has adjusted the con- 
tracts of labor; it has protected employees by insisting 
that all dangerous machinery shall be guarded; ... it 
has created boards of factory inspectors, whose powers and 
duties have added much to the health and safety of the 
operatives; it has in many instances provided for weekly 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



217 



^ 



pajTnents, not only by municipalities, but by corporations; 
. . . it has regulated the employment of prisoners; pro- 
tected the employment of children; exempted the wages 
of the wife and minor children from attachment; estab- 
lished bureaus for statistics of labor; provided for the 
ventilation of factories and workshops; established indus- 
trial schools and evening schools; provided special trans- 
portation by railroads for workingmen; modified the com- 
mon-law rules relative to the liability of employers for 
injuries of their employees; fixed the compensation of 
railroad corporations for negligently causing the death of 
employees, and has provided for their protection against 
accident and death." ' 

In reading this seemingly large schedule of labor laws it 
must, of course, be borne in mind that it enumerates and 
combines all principal measures enacted in the different 
states of the Union, and that hardly any single state can 
boast of a labor code containing them all. On the other 
hand, however, it must also not be forgotten that the 
United States is one of the backward countries in the 
matter of factory legislation, and that many countriffi of 
Europe have gone considerably farther in that direction. 

But even in the most advanced countries, factory legisla- 
tion is, on the whole, only in its infancy, and its practical 
achievements are insignificant compared with what still 
remains to be done in order to make the work of the factoiy 
hand tolerable and safe. 

The beginnings of factory legislation were thus intro- 
duced by the bourgeoisie at a time when the labor move- 
ment had hardly attained the power to speak for itself. 
The first labor laws were brought about partly as a result 
' "Industrial Evolution of the Uaited States," pp. tgi, 393. 



[aiS 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



of the struggles between the hostile divisions of dominant 
classes, each of whom courted the support of the working- 
men, but probably to a larger extent as a measure of hygiene 
intended to check the physical degeneration of the working 
class, whose misery had become so great as to threaten the 
future of the nation. And it is very significant that Peel's 
pioneer measure in the domain of factory reform was 
entitled, "A bill for the preservation of the health and 
morals of the apprentices employed in cotton mills." 

In some instances, notably in Prussia, the first measures 
of protective labor legislation were introduced by the 
rulers as a military necessity, "Thus," relates Adolf 
Braun, "in an address to Frederick William III in 1836, 
it was reported that the factorj- districts were unable to 
furnish their full quota of soldiers for the army. Shortly 
thereafter the first Prussian Labor Law, that of March 9, 
1839, was enacted. Children under the age of nine years 
were excluded from work in factories and mines; chil- 
dren under sixteen years were forbidden to work nights or 
Sundays or more than 10 hours on workdays." ' 

But with the growth of the labor movement and the 
general improvements in labor conditions brought about 
by it, the dominant classes have no longer any interest in 
the protection of the wage workers against the exploita- 
tion of their employers, and the task of developing and ex- 
tending factory legislation falls entirely on the organized 
workingmen. 

Shorter Workday 

\ Prior to the development of modem factory industry, 

' the normal workday of the artisan was one of compara- 

' Adolf Braun, "Zum Achtstundentag," Berlin, igoi, p. 14. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



219 



lively short duration. Speaking of pre-capitalistic Eng- 
land, Thorold Rogers ' asserts that it was one of eight 
hours, and his assertion is backed by an abundance of 

. proof. 

But with the gradual disappearance of the easy-going 
artisan of media;val times, and the advent of capitalist 
production, the length of the workday and intensity of 
labor grew steadily, reaching the high-water mark to- 
wards the end of the eighteenth and the beginning of the 
inetcenth century. The golden era of machine invention 
stimulated production and developed factory industry with 

' an impetuous suddenness and in immense proportions. 

I The ready urban workmen were totally insufficient for the 
new needs of capitalist industry. Their wives and children 
I their rural cousins were called into requisition, and 
their hours of labor were advanced to the limits of physical 
possibility. At the beginning of the nineteenth century 
the ordinary workday of the English factory worker seems 
to have been one of from twelve to fifteen hours, and in 
seasons of special activity there was no limit to it at all. 
The effects of such overwork on the physical, moral and 
mental condition- of the factory workers were disastrous 
in the extreme, and the demand for a reduction of the 
workday was practically the first manifestation of the 
incipient labor movement in England. The efforts to re- 
duce the length of the workday have ever since remained 
a cardinal part of the modern labor movement. These 
efforts find their expression in the political agitation of the 
working-class parties as well as in the struggles of the in- 
dustrial labor organizations in their special fields, and in 
both domains the labor movement has attained some suc- 
' "Six Centuries of Work and Wages," p. 337. 



SOCIAUSM AND REFORM 



cess during the last century. In England the first law 
limiting the hours of labor to lo per day, was passed in 
1847. The law was loosely framed and poorly enforced, 
and in 1850 it was superseded by a new bill limiting the 
hours of labor to loj on week days and j^ on Saturdays. 
This law originally applied to women, children and men 
employed in the textile mills only, but its operation was 
gradually extended by a series of new enactments to prac- 
tically all factory workers. The hours of labor of textile 
workers and of children in certain industries were subse- 
quently reduced to 10 per day. In France the workday 
of adtih males, when working together with women and 
children, is limited to 10 hours, otherwise to la; in Aus- 
tria, Germany and Switzerland, the normal workday of 
adult male factory workers is fixed at 11 hours by law, 
and several states of the American Union have limited the 
duration of the normal workday by legal enactment. 

Besides these general laws several countries have fixed 
a minimum workday of varying length for certain special 
classes of workmen, principally those engaged in the more 
perilous and taxing occupations and those employed di- 
rectly by the government. 

These, then, are the rather meager results so far achieved 
by this movement in the domain of legislation. But 
far larger and more substantial gains have been made 
in the same field through the efforts of the industrial 
labor organizations in most of the advanced countries of 
Europe, Australia and America. In many industries 
in those coimtries, nine-hour and even eight-hour work- 
days prevail. 

In almost all modern countries the movement of organ- 
ized labor to reduce the hours of work has crystallized in 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



the demand for an eight-hour workday, and the movement 
is, therefore, generally known as the eight-hour movement. 

The English trade unions seem to have advanced the ideal 
1 of a general eight-hour day for workers of all sexes and 
IS soon as their public activity was made possible by 
the repeal of the Combination Laws in 1824; in Australia 
an Eight-Hour League was formed in 1856, and a. similar 
organization was caUed into life in the United States in 
1869 under the leadership of Ira Stewart. 

In the English-speaking coimtries, especially, the eight- 
hour movement has assumed large proportions and impor- 
tance. " Out of it," says William D. P. Bliss, " has grown 
in America a so-called eight-hour philosophy, which is held 
by its adherents to be a complete philosophy of the labor 
movement and to furnish a program not to be looked at as 
simply one plank in a labor program, but as a proposition 
complete in itself, including most socialist propositions and 
furnishing in its outline a solution of the whole labor ques- 
tion." ' 

A shortening of the hours of labor is a measure of im- 
mense importance to the working people, as a factor tend- 
ing to improve their general condition of health and to 
raise the average duration of theh- lives. Long hours o£ 
labor are bound to impair the alertness and vigilance of 
the worker. It is a well-known fact that accidents occur 
most frequently in the industries in which long hours are 
the rule, and that they occur with greater frequency towards 
the end of the workday than at its beginning. But aside 
from accidents the duration of the workday has a very 
direct and important bearing on the sickness and mortal- 
ly of the working class. Dr. J. Zadek, who has made a 

"The Encyclopedia o£ Social Reforms," New York and London, 
^898, p. 3S. 



I 



! SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

special study of this aspect of the problem,' relates many 

striking instances of the effect of a reduced workday on the 
health and life of the workers. Thus, after the lace workers 
of Switzerland had succeeded in reducing their workday to 
II hours, sickness among the employees decreased by 25 
per cent. Up to 1871 the workday of the machine builders 
of Great Britain was excessively long, and the average life 
of the workers in that trade was 38^ years; in 1872 the 
machine builders secured a reduction of the workday to 
nine hours, and seventeen years later the average length of 
their lives had risen to 48^ years I 

The adoption of an eight-hour system of work, it is fur- 
ther argued, would benefit the working class and advance 
the general cause of human civilization in many ways. 
By reducing the hours and quantity of labor of each indi- 
\'idual, it would necessitate the employment of a larger 
number of workingmcn to satisfy the demands of produc- 
tion. The dread army of unemployed, the source of much 
social vice and crime and the cause of much disastrous 
competition in the labor market, would thus disappear. 
A reduction of the hours of labor would result in a material 
increase of wages not only on account of the elimination 
of competition between workingmen, but also because it 
would raise their standard of living. A short workday 
would give to the workingman more leisure, i.e., more time 
to live, think and enjoy, and such leisure would necessarily 
increase his fondness for home and family life, broaden his 
intellectual, social and political interests, and develop in 
him greater needs and requirements. And it is the habit- 
ual requirements of the workingman, his accustomed stand- 
ard of living, that largely determine his wage. A shorter 
' " Der Achtstundentag eine gesundheitliche Forderung," Berlin, 1906. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



223 



I 
I 



workday would, therefore, also increase the consumptive 
powers of tlie worliing classes, and thus stimulate industry 
and largely remove the causes of periodic overproduction 
and underconsumption with the resultant industrial crises 
and panics. 

The formal resolution adopted by the Boston Eight- 
Hour League, and drafted by Ira Stewart, goes so far as to 
claim: — 

"That less hours mean reducing the profits and fortunes 
that are made on labor or its results. 

"More knowledge and more capital for the laborer; 
the wage system gradually disappearing through higher 
wages," 

The socialists do not concede to the eight-hour movement 
all the importance that its most ardent adherents claim for 
it. They do not believe that the wage system upon which 
the entire present order is built can be abolished by a 
gradual reduction of hours and raising of wages, and they 
even do not admit that the general introduction of an eight- 
hour workday would be effective in solving the problem of 
miemployment. The shortening of the hours of labor, 
as a rule, results in the greater intensity and productiveness 
of labor, and it is the testimony of many writers on the sub- 
ject that where a short workday has been introduced, it has 
been found that the ordinary workingman, owing to his 
better health, larger energy and more cheerful spu-its, 
could do in eight hours practically as much work as he pre- 
viously had done in ten. John Rae,' himself an employer 
of labor and one of the most ardent and persuasive advo- 
cates of the eight-hour day, largely bases his argument on 
this observation. But the socialists fully adhere to the 
' "Eighl Hours for Work," London, 1894. 



f224 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

view that a reduced workday would result in an increase 
of wages for the other reasons mentioned above, and they 
attach the utmost importance to the effect of greater leisure 
on the morale and intellect of the working class. Hence 
they are among the most active and enthusiastic promoters 
of the movement. In countries with a strong trade union 
movement they support the eight-hour agitation ; in coun- 
tries where the organizations of the trade unions are weaker 
they lead the agitation. Every socialist platform invariably 
contains the demand for a progressive reduction of the 
hours of labor in keeping with the improved methods of 
production, and the socialist representatives in parliaments 
and other legislative bodies never miss an opportunity to 
urge legislation in that direction. 

One of the first resolutions adopted by the International 
Workingmen's Association, which stood wholly under 
socialist influences, at its first regular convention in 1864, 
was to the effect that " the limitation of the workday is the 
first step in the direction of the emancipation of the working 
class," and that "the congress considers in principle that a 
workday of eight hours' duration is sufficient," And when 
the first of the new series of international socialist con- 
gresses convened in Paris in 1889, it reaffirraed the resolu- 
tion, and set apart the first day of May of every year for 
international labor demonstrations in favor of an eight- 
hour workday. "May Day" parades and "eight-hour 
demonstrations" have since become prominent features in 
the socialist propaganda of Europe and America. 

CkUd Labor 

Child labor as an incident of domestic and agricultural 
pursuits has probably always existed, but child labor as a 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



225 



regtJar and important factor in national industry is an in- 
novation, a blossom of the modern capitalist system of pro- 
duction. It was the machine that made child labor on a 
large scale possible, it was capitalist competition that made 
it desirable, and it was capitalist exploitation of the adult 
workers that made it inevitable. The worst phases of child 
labor are to be found in the classic country of capitalism 
and in the classic period of factory development — in 
England towards the end of the eighteenth and the begin- 
ning of the nineteenth centuries. 

Describing the conditions of child labor of that period, 
Mr. William F. Willoughby says: — 

"Children of all ages, down to three and four, were 
found in the hardest and most painful labor, while babes of 
six were commonly found in large numbers in many fac- 
tories. Labor from 12 to 13 and often 16 hours a day was 
the rule. Children had not a moment free, save to snatch 
a hasty meal, or sleep as best they could. From earliest 
youth they worked to a point of extreme exhaustion, with- 
out open-air exercise or any enjoyment whatever, but grew 
up, if they survived at all, weak, bloodless, miserable, and 
in many cases deformed cripples, and victims of almost 
every disease. Drunkenness, debauchery and filth could 
not but be the result. Their condition was but the veriest 
slavery, and the condition of the serf or negro stood out in 
bright contrast to theirs. The mortality was excessive, and 
the dread diseases rickets and scrofula passed by but few 
in their path. It was among this class that the horror of 
hereditary disease had its chief hold, aided as it was by the 
repetition and accumulation of the same causes that first 
planted its seeds. The reports of all the many investiga- 
tions showed that morality was almost unknown. In the 





P 226 SOaALISM AND REFORM 

coal mines the condition of the children was even worse. 
According to the report of 1842, on child labor, it was 
estimated that fully one third of those employed in the coal 
mines of England were children under eighteen, and of these 
much more than one half were under thirteen. The facts 
revealed in this elaborate report of over 2000 pages, devoted 
chiefly to child labor in coal mines, would be scarcely 
credible if they were not supported by the best of authority, 
so fearful was the condition of the children found to be. 
Down in the depths of the earth they labored from 14 to 16 
hours daily. The coal often lay in seams only 18 inches 
deep, and in these children crawled'on their hands and feet, 
generally naked, and harnessed up by an iron chain and 
band around their waists, by which they either dragged 
or pushed heavily loaded cars of coal through these narrow 
ways. In nearly every case they were driven to work by 
the brutal miners, and beaten, and sometimes even killed. 
Law did not seem to reach to the depths of a coal pit. 
Thus these young infants labored their young lives out as 
if condemned to torture for some crime." * 

And John A. Hobson, commenting on these conditions 
exclaims : — 

"There is no page in the history of our nation so in- 
famous as that which tells the details of the unbridled 
greed of the.'^e pioneers of modem commercialism, feeding 
on the misery and degradation of English children." ^ 

Nor were the conditions in other countries in the periods 
of inception of great capitalist production much better. 
"In the first decades of the last century," relates Dr. 

' William F. Willoughby, "Child Labor," American Ecocamic Asso- 
ciation. March, iSga, 

' "Problems of Poverty," London, 1891, p. 184. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



227 



I wnica c 

^^H twelve ) 
^^^1 children 



Herkner, "children of the most tender ages, some of them 
four years old, were made to work in the industrial centers 
of the Rhenish provinces, for a daily wage of twopence; 
their workday lasted 10, 12 and even 14 hours, and often 
they were made to work in the nighttime," ' 

And even in Switzerland children of six and seven years 
were employed in the spinning mills, working continually 
from midnight to noon or from early in the morning till 
night. 

The evils of child labor early attracted the attention of 
the public-spirited men of all countries, and the first efforts 
of all factory legislation were invariably directed against 
this evil. But the process of legislative reform in this 
field has, on the whole, been slow and quite ineffective. 
It took the English Parliament fully seventeen years after 
the adoption of the Peel law to pass the first act prohibit- 
ing the employment of children below a minimum age in 
factories, and that age as fi.xed by the law of 1819, was — 
nine years ! The minimum age of cJiild workers in Eng- 
land was raised to ten years in 1874, to eleven in 1891, and 
at present it is twelve years. Of the other countries of 
Europe, some have entirely failed to legislate on the 
mini mum age of factory workers, and others have fixed 
it at so low a point that it accentuates rather than relieves 
the horrors of child labor. Thus, in Denmark, the law 
forbids the employment of children under ten years. In 
Belgium, Italy, Russia, Sweden and Holland the age at 
which children are legally set free for factory work is 
twelve years. Germany and France do not allow their 
children to work in factories before the age of thirteen 
4Ch EditioD, Berlin, 1905, 



Heinrich Herkner, "Die Arbciterfrage," 
pp. 34. 3S. 



228 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



years, and Austria and Switzerland before fourteen. In 
the United States we are confronted in this, as in every 
other domain of social legislation, by 46 different sets of 
laws enacted in as many states. The minimum age of 
juvenile factory workers varies from twelve to sixteen 
years, but fovirteen seems to be the favorite point in most 
states. 

Somewhat more satisfactory results in the field of child- 
labor legislation seem to have been achieved in the direc- 
tion of limiting the hours of labor of the youthful factory 
workers. In England children under fourteen years are only 
allowed to be employed half time, and the hours of em- 
ployment of children between fourteen and eighteen years 
are limited to r 2 , with 2 hours' intermission for rest. In Ger- 
many the hours of children under fourteen years of age in 
factories must not exceed 6 a day, with an intermission of 
at least half an hour, and children between fourteen and 
sixteen must not work more than 10 hours a day, with one 
hour's interval in the middle of the day, and half an hour 
in the morning and afternoon. In France children under 
sixteen may work 10 hours a day in factories. Sweden 
limits the work of children under fourteen to 6 hours, 
and under sixteen to 12 hours. In the United States the 
hours of labor for children are variously fixed at from 8 
to 10 per day. 

Yet while the legal restrictions on child labor and on 
the intensity of its exploitation have thus, on the whole, 
been making slow and laborious progress, the evil itself 
ha^ been steadily increasing and spreading. 

Economically, morally and in every other way, child 
labor is one of the heaviest curses upon the working class. 
Originating as a last and desperate resort in the effort to 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



229 



I 



augment the insufficient income of the head of the prole- 
tarian family, child labor has proved in the hands of the 
capitalists one of the most effective methods for cutting 
the wages of the adult workers. Instead of being a help 
to his father, the child has become his competitor in the 
factory. The wages of the factory children are ludi- 
crously low, ranging from 25 or 30 cents a week in some 
countries of Europe to about $2,50 per week in the United 
States, and the total earnings of the working children are 
rarely enough to make up for the losses in wages which 
their competition causes to the adult workers. 

And the moral cost of child labor to the working class is 
incalculable. It robs the working child of all joys and 
privileges of childhood, cripples his body, dwarfs his mind, 
takes the very life out of him, and tlireatens to develop a 
generation of dull, cheerless and resistless workers. 

"The sucking out of the life juice from these helpless 
and defenseless creatures, the destruction of all joys of 
life right at the threshold of life, the consumption of the 
seed of manhood right from the stem — that, more than 
anything else, is the sin of the capitalist rule against the 
present generation; it is also a criminal interference with 
the future!" exclaims the eloquent Rosa Luxemburg, 
speaking on the subject of child labor.' 

Socialism, which ever strives for the highest physical, 
mental and moral development of the working class, and 
centers its hopes on the rising generation of workers, 
naturally sees in child labor one of the greatest obstacles 
to its progress, and combats it by all means at its command. 

The socialists favor all legislation for the restriction of 

' Quoted by Kate Duncker in "Die Kinderarbeit und ihre Bekarap- 
I fiug," Stultgart, 190&. 



230 



SOCLAI.ISM AND REFORM 



' child labor, and consistently support every measure tend- 
ing in that direction. But unlike the ideologist champions 
of the cause of child labor, who are of late developing con- 
siderable activity, especially in the United States and in 
England, they realize that the evil cannot be wholly cured 
by mere laws for the abolition or limitation of child labor. 
The alarming spread of child labor is largely a symptom 
of the dire poverty of the working class. It Is true that in 
some instances children are sent to work by their parents 
out of thoughtlessness or cupidity, but these instances 
may be safely set down as rare exceptions. As a rule the 
parents of the working class feel very keenly the dreadful 
sacrifice involved in the offering of their immature and 
tender-bodied children on the altar of the profit-grinding 
machine, and only the most implacable need will induce 
them to do so. Speaking of the beginnings of child work 
in the English factories, John Spargo remarks: "To get 
children for the cotton mills was not easy at first. Parental 
love and pride were ranged against the new system, deny- 
ing its demands, ■ Accustomed to the old domestic system, 
the association of all members of the family in manufacture 
as part of the domestic life, they regarded the new indus- 
trial forms with repugnance. It was considered a degra- 
dation for a child to be sent into the factories, especially 
for a girl, whose life would be blasted thereby. The 
terra 'factory girl' was an insulting epithet. . . . Not 

' till they were forced by sheer hunger and misery, through 
the reduction of wages to the level of starvation, could the 

' respectable workers be induced to send their chfldren into 
the factories." ' 

It may be argued that if the workingman be deprived 
' "The Bitter Cry o£ the Children," New York, 1906, pp. 130, 131. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



231 



of the earnings of his children by legal enactment, he 
would be compelled in the long rim to force up his wages 
to a higher level, and thus to make up for the impairment 
of the family income. And there is certainly much justice 
in the argument. But its weakness lies in the proviso — 
"in the long run." Few workingmen's families can stand 
a decrease in their meager incomes for any length of time. 

Capitalism holds the workers in the grip of a vicious 
circle: the poverty of the wage-earning father sends his 
child to the factory, and the competition of the child in 
the factory increases the father's poverty and makes it 
ever harder for him to dispense with the scanty additional 
earnings of the child. 

To cope effectively with the evil, it is necessary to attack 
its very root and source, the poverty of the working class. 
The child-labor problem is but one phase of the larger 
labor problem and cannot be solved separately. 

The socialist demand for greater restriction of child 
' labor derives its main strength and effectiveness from its 
; connection with the demands for other industrial reforms 
contained in the socialist program. 



Woman Labor 

In its history, and partly also in its social effects, the 
problem of woman labor is somewhat similar to that of 
child labor, but its solution presents a different and con- 
siderably more complex question. 

With the introduction of the machine and of the factory 

system, the personal training and physical strength of the 

workingman rapidly lost their importance in the process of 

, production. What the capitalist demanded was cheap 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



labor rather than skilled labor, and next to the labor of 
the child that of the woman was and is the cheapest j 
commodity in the labor market. 

The working woman is in the majority of cases not 
called upon to support a family, as is the workingman. 
As a rule her earnings are but a subsidiary source of the 
family income; her wages are intended only to add some- 
what to those of her husband or father. The position of 
the working woman in industry is furthermore not as per- 
manent as that of the man or even the boy — the woman 
often, though by far not as a rule, quits the factory on her 
marriage. And finally, the work of the married woman 
is not as steady as that of the man ; it is necessarily inter- 
rupted by the periods of pregnancy and childbed. The 
wants of the working woman are thus comparatively small 
and her power of resistance is weak. Women rarely 
organize into compact and permanent trade unions, they 
seldom strike or revolt, and they are for that reason better 
objects of capitalist exploitation than men. 

"It is," observes Mr. Hobson, "the general industrial 
weakness of the condition of most women workers, and not 
a sex prejudice, which prevents them from receiving the 
wages which men might get, if the work the women do 
were left for male competition alone." ' 

In the earlier part of the nineteenth century, the ex- 
ploitation of factory women grew so unbridled and their 
treatment so brutal that the parliaments and legislatures 
of the most advanced countries found themselves impelled 
to take official cognizance of the situation, and to attempt 
to cure some of the worst evils of woman labor by legis- 
lative enactments. 

' "Problems of Poverty," p. 158. 



I 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



233 



^ 



The first measure in that direction was the English act 
of 1843, which prohibited underground work for women 
as well as for children, and that act was followed by several 
other measures at long intervals, the effect of which was 
to limit and regulate to some extent the labor of women 
in industries. Similar laws were also enacted in other 
countries, but on the whole these laws are even less radical 
and effective than those dealing with child labor. 

The wages of women workers were hardly affected by 
these measures. They are still much below those of their 
male companions in the factories, even though their work 
may be equally efficient. Out of 782 instances selected at 
random by the United States Commissioner of Labor in 
1897, in which men and women worked at the same occu- 
pation and performed their work with the same degree of 1 
efficiency, men received greater pay in 595, or 76.1 per 
cent of the instances, and their pay in these instances was 
50.1 per cent greater than that of the women. 

The average wage of the factory woman in the United 
States is about S5 per week, while in Great Britain the 
working woman earns about 11 shillings per week. But 
it must be remembered that these averages are greatly 
swelled by the higher pay of women in exceptional posi- 
tions, and also that they apply to factory work only. The 
female sweatshop and house workers receive much more 
wretched pay. 

It is, therefore, not to be wondered at that the number 
of women employed in the industries is growing steadily 
and rapidly. In the United States, in which the woman 
engaged m industry was a rare exception at the beginning 
of the last century, the number of women engaged in 
gainful occupation rose to almost 4,000,000 in 1890. In 



234 SOaALISM AND REFORM 

France there were 6,382,658 women engaged in the dif- 
ferent industries of the country as against 12,061,121 men, 
and in Germany the rapid growth of the number of women 
engaged in the factories alone is shown by the following 
eloquent figures : — 

1895 664,116 

1899 884,239 

1904 1,119,713 

1905 1,180,894 

1906 1,244,964 

These figures include the female children. In England 
half of the grown-up women are, according to Mr. John 
A. Hobson, wage laborers. 

The socialists are not opposed to woman labor as such. 
They recognize that woman occupies a legitimate and 
lasting position in industry and that the growing im- 
portance of her r61e in all spheres of the social, political 
and economic life of modem nations is fully in keeping 
with the march of social progress. But they combat the 
special evils and abuses of woman labor. And these 
abuses are many. 

The woman, when not burdened with a family of young 
children depending on her care and guidance, is just as 
fit to work as the man ; but the woman with a large family, 
and the woman in a condition of pregnancy, or immediately 
after childbirtli, has enough useful and necessary work to 
perform at home. Her work in the factory under such 
conditions is not a proud assertion of the rights of woman, 
but a pitiful and tragic surrender of her maternal duties 
and feelings to tJie cruel exigencies of dire poverty. And 
her work under such conditions causes incalculable physi- 
cal and moral harm to her and her progeny. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



235 



I 



The small pay of the working women, furthermore, con- 
stantly tends to drag down the wages of their husbands, 
fathers and brothers to an even lower level. 

The efforts of the socialists are, therefore, directed 
primarily towards raising the wages of the adult male 
worker, the father of the workingman family, to a point 
where they would be sufficient to meet the necessary re- 
quirements of all members of his family, including those of 
his young children and their mother. Only thus can the 
inhuman evils of forced woman labor be effectively cured. 

For the remaining female workers in industry, the social- 
ists demand equal pay for equal work, and they strive to 
interest the working women in the organizations of the 
workingraen, and to secure their cooperation in the strug- 
gle for the improvement of the conditions of labor of both 
sexes. 

The abuses of woman labor and the exploitation of 
child labor are logical and necessary accompaniments of 
the competitive system of industry. It lies in the nature 
of capitalism to stimulate competition in the labor market 
by opposing sex to sex, age to age and nationality to 
nationality, and as long as the system endures, its inherent 
abuses cannot be entirely removed. Socialism alone 
offers a complete cure for the evils of woman and child 
labor. But even such imperfect and partial remedies as 
may be secured under the present system will be effect- 
ive only if obtained in pursuance of a consistent pro- 
gram of labor reform in all of its branches and as a 
result of a strong and planful movement on the part of 
the workers organized industrially and politically. 



136 SOOALISM AND REFORM 

Tke Trade Union Movement 

In their eEforts to secure radical and lasting industrial 
reform, and we may add, in their expectations of the ulti- 
mate realteation of their entire program, the socialists 
thus rely not on their own strength, but also on the co- 
operation of the industrial organization of the working 
class. This industrial organization is represented chiefly 
by the trade union movement, and the r61e of that move- 
ment in the progress of industrial reform and the reciprocal 
relations between it and the socialist movement, are ques- 
tions of large moment in the practical work of socialism. 

Trade unionism and socialism have a common origin, 
I and are both the products and expression of an advanced 
I stage of the class struggle between capitalism and labor. 

In England, France, Italy, Australia and the United 
States, the modern trade union movement preceded the 
socialist movement; in Germany, Austria and Russia, 
the trade unions are largely the creation of socialists, while 
in Sweden, Norway, Denmark, Belgium and Holland, both 
movements developed almost simultaneously. In the 
Anglo-Saxon countries the trade unions have developed 
a greater numerical strength than the socialist parties, 
while in the countries of continental Europe the reverse 
is true. On the whole, however, the total strength of the 
two movements is approximately equal, as the following 
figures taken from the leading countries will show ; ' — 

' The figures for the trade union membership are taken from the 
paper of Ijiuis de Brouckfere on Socialism and Trade Unionism sub- 
mitted to the Stuttgart Internationa.] Congress, 1907, and those for the 
socialist vote are largely compiled from the official reports of the varmua 
socialist parties to th? same Congress. The Belgian socialist vote has, 
k fince June, 1908, substantially increased. The figures for England, 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



c™ 


s^^y^ 


Tk«k Ub.o« 


Great Britain 

Belgium 

Denmark 

Sweden 

Norway 

German}' 

Austria 

Servia 

Bulgaria 

Italy 

Spain 

Holland 

France 

United States 


342,10 

500,000 
76,612 
26,083 
24,744 

1^41,948 
30,000 
10,000 
30 1 -52s 
9,000 
65.743 

I,I2opOO 

423.09 


1,866,75s 
148,483 
92,091 

"4.935 

18,600 

1,822,343 

322,049 

5,°74 

8,300 

347.839 

36,557 

30,000 

800,000 

2,500,000 


Total 


7,222,82s 


8.1.3,026 



Stating the proposition in general and broad terms, the 
trade unions fight the special and economic battles of the 
workingmen, while the Socialist Party represents the gen- 
eral interest of the wage earners in the field of politics. 
But on closer examination the distinction is by no means 
as clear and definite as it seems at first sight. 

Every trade union represents primarily the interest of 
the employees in its special trade, but under a highly 
developed state of factory production the modem trades 

Spain and Servia are estimated. Owing to the chaotic electoral system 
of Russia the strong socialist vote of that country cannot be estimated. 
Neither the socialist vote nor the trade-union strength are fully shown in 
the above table, since a number of countries have had to be omitted 
from it for lack of sufficient data. The total socialist vote is estimated 
as exceeding 10,000,000; the total membership of the trade un 
the world is about 11,000,000. 



:a38 sociAUSM akd reform 

' and industries have come to be so closely allied and inter- 
woven, that the workingmen in any trade can rareiy suc- 
ceed in their struggles unless they are supported by their 
comrades in the allied trades and sometimes by organized 
labor as a whole. The growing practice of "sympathy 
strikes" is evidence of this fact, and the trade unions 
tacitly recognize it by forming local, national, and even 
international central bodies for the purpose of cooperation 
and mutual support on a large scale. The interests repre- 
sented by the whole body of trade unions thus gradually 
become the general interests of the working class rather 
than the special interests of the employees of particular 

r trades. 

I With the enlargement of the scope of the trade union 
movement, the very character of the movement is trans- 
formed : its economic battles partake of the nature of po- 
litical struggles. 

For the distinction between economic and political ac- 
tion is one of degree and method rather than of kind and 
substance. The efforts of the organized employees of a 
given shop or craft to secure and maintain a reduction of 
their hours of labor by the strength of their own organiza- 
tion, are classed as economic struggles. The efforts of 
the entire organized working class or a specific and uni- 
form portion of it to secure and maintain the same reduc- 
tion of work hours through legislative enactment, con- 
stitute political action. As the trade unions in every 
country grow in numbers and power, they pay ever greater 
attention to the more general phases of the labor problem 
and are thus drawn into ever closer contact with pohtics. 
The trade unions of every advanced country are actively 
engaged in the effort to secure legislation for the limitation 



k 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



239 



of child labor, the regulation of woman labor, the improve- 
ment of the employers' liability laws, the safeguarding of 
dangerous machinery and for the abatement of the count- 
less other e\ils of modem factory work. And whenever 
legislation is threatened which may be detrimental to the 
interests of labor or tend to curtail the rights or the effi- 
ciency of its organizations, the unions engage in an active 
campaign of opposition to such measures. 

"The distinction between the industrial and the political 
struggles of the proletariat was only temporary," says the 
well-known socialist theoretician writing under the nam 
de plume of Parvus; "it was always rather superficial and 
often fictitious; with the extension of the scope and power 
of the strikes, it disappears entirely. Whoever tries to 
exclude politics from the trade unions, must retard the 
very development of the trade unions." * 

The trade unions of continental Europe fully recognize 
this political phase of their movement, and they frankly 
ally themselves with the sociaHst parties of their coun- 
tries in all political campaigns. In England the trade 
organizations stubbornly maintained the attitude of non- 
interference in politics until such time as they found their 
very existence menaced by the legislative and judicial 
powers of the realm. Then they constituted themselves 
into a political Labor Party, which declared for inde- 
pendent working-class politics and adopted a radical pro- 
gram of political labor reform. 

The only large body of trade unions which, at least to 
some extent, still upholds the fiction of political indifference, 
is that represented by the American Federation of Labor, 
and that fiction is becoming so incongruous as to involve 
' Parvus, "Der GcwerJiSchaltliche Kampf," Berlin, 1908. 



r 240 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



the organization in the most ludicrous contradictions. 
Thus, while a special clause in its constitution prohibits 
any afElialion with political parties, and the favorite slogan 
of the Federation is "No politics in the union," one of the 
principal objects of the organization, as likewise stated in 
its constitution, is "to secure national legislation in the 
interests of the working people," and every one of its 
conventions devotes entire days to the discussion of politi- 
cal problems and demands. In the election of 190S, the 
Federation unofficially supported the Democratic Party. 
The American Federation of Labor is in politics just as 
much as are the labor unions of all other countries, but it 
is the only large labor body that has failed to organize 
and concentrate its forces in one consistent pohtical labor 
party, and prefers to scatter and waste them in the sup- 
port of the political parties of the empioymg class. 

Another distinction frequently drawn between the trade 
union and the socialist movements is that the former stands 
for mere improvements of the conditions of labor within 
the frame of the present system, while the latter strives for 
the entire abolition of the wage system. This distinction 
is also more imagmary than real. 

The object of all trade unions is directly or indu-ectly 
to enhance the worker's share of the product, thus cor- 
respondingly decreasing the share of the employer. No 
limit is set to this process, and its logical conclusion, at 
least in abstract theory, is the entire elimmation of the 
capitalist's prolits — the socialization of industries. The 
only difference between the socialists and the trade union- 
ists on the point is that while all of the former clearly 
realize this ultimate goal of the class struggle, many of the 
latter do not. But even that is rapidly ghangmg. The 



THE INDUSTRJAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



241 



e unionists of Europe are as a rule permeated with the 
I of socialism, and the understanding of that 
philosophy gives them a clearer vision of their task and 
makes their struggles more effective. In the United States 
sociahsm is makmg its way among the trade unionists 
slowly but steadily. 

Thus the fields of socialism and trade imionism largely 
encroach on each other, and the line of demarcation be- 
tween the two movements is often blurred. Still it would 
be a mistake to consider them as synonymous. Socialism 
and trade unionism constitute together the body of the 
modem labor movement, and the separation of the two 
merely signifies a division of functions. But that division 
is essential for the success of the movement as a whole. 
The activity of the socialist parties lies primarily in the 
poKtical field : they translate the economic struggles of the 
working class into political action, formulate its general 
demands, coordinate its special needs, and always em- 
phasize its ultimate aim, while supporting the immediate 
economic battles of the unions. 

The functions of the trade unions, on the other hand, 
are primarily directed to the sphere of industrial struggle. 
They protect the individual worker in the factory against 
the excessive exploitation of the employer, and they ad- 
vance the general poKtical interests of their members 
through the medium of the socialist parties. Beyond 
these separate provinces there is, moreover, a large field of 
action in which the labor movement can achieve success 
only by the spontaneous cooperation of both of its 
■wings. 

The most striking instance of such joint action is the 
political mass strike which has of late been resorted to by 



I 
I 



|'24Z 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



I few extraordinary occa- 



k 



the workingmen of Europe c 
sions to good purpose. 

From this sketch of the objects and methods of opera- 
tion of the two movements, it will be readily seen that their 
relations to each other must be of the closest and most 
cordial character. In Belgium, Denmark, Sweden and 
Norway, the membership of the socialist parlies and the 
trade unions is practically identical, and the two organiza- 
tions may be considered as separate committees of the 
same body created for the performance of different func- 
tions. In Germany, Austria, Holland, Italy and Russia, 
the two movements are very closely allied in all their 
struggles. In England the Independent Labor Party, one 
of the leading socialist organizations of the country, forms 
a constituent part of Ihe political Labor Party in the same 
way as do the trade unions. In France the party and 
the trade unions sometimes quarrel, but it is always the 
passing quarrel of lovers. In the United States alone the 
great body of organized workingmen, the American Feder- 
ation of Labor, has so far kept aloof from the socialist 
movement. 

Coaperative Societies of Workingmen 

Another movement that has of late years developed 
great strength, and is coming to be regarded as a factor of 
growing importance in the struggles between capital and 
labor, is the movement represented by the cooperative 
societies of workingmen. 

The origin of cooperative enterprises for joint produc- 
tion, purchase, distribution and consumption of commod- 
ities, may be traced back to the eighteenth century, but 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



243 



the modem coSperative societies have as Httie in common 
with their earlier prototypes as the trade unions have with 
the old institutions of the masters' or helpers' guilds. 

The cooperative movement of our day is a part of the 
general labor movement, one of the manifestations, con- 
scious or unconscious, of the general effort on the part of 
the workingmen to lessen the exploitation of their class 
by capitalism. The movement has developed within the 
last fifty years, and it has attained general extension only 
within the last two decades. 

In this, as in many other practical labor reform 
movements, England led the procession. The famous 
society of the Rochdale Pioneers, the oldest of its kind, 
was founded in November, 1843, when twelve poor weav- 
ers met in the back room of a miserable inn, and agreed 
to pay 20 pence a week into a common fund until they 
should accumulate enough to start in business for their 
Joint benefit. In a year their number had increased to 28 
and their capital had grown to ;^2S. They rented a store 
and stocked it with £15 worth of flour, and from these 
modest beginnings the enterprise rapidly grew to one of 
the most prosperous and powerful business institutions of 
the country. In 1876 the Rochdale Society of Equitable 
Pioneers numbered 8892 members, and had an invested 
capital of £254,000; the year's business amounted to 
;£305,ooo, and the society's net profits were ^£50,500. 

Membership in the society is acquired by the purchase 
of a share of stock of the denomination of ^^5, but that 
amount may be paid in small weekly installments. Each 
individual member may hold as many as 20 shares, but 
no member has more than one vote in the meetings of the 
society. Out of the net profits a dividend of 5 per cent 



I 
I 



244 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



per annum is paid on the stock, 2J per cent is set apart for 
an education fund, and the balance is distributed among 
the members in proportion to the amount of their purchases. 

In 1863 the great Cooperative Wholesale Society, 
Limited, was founded as a sort of central agency for a 
number of cooperative enterprises. In 1872 the year's 
sales of that society already reached the enormous sum 
of ;£i,iS3,i32. The society originally confined itself to 
purchasing commodities at wholesale and sellmg them to its 
members (individual associations) at retail, but gradually 
it embarked in the field of independent manufacture, 
and with its ready market and large capital its efforts in 
that direction have been signally successful. To-day the 
society operates extensive biscuit, soap, boot and clothing 
factories, woolen and com mills, cocoa works and jam 
canneries; it runs a large printing establishment, conducts 
building operations, and has a fleet of its own in connection 
with its shipping department. It has branches in several 
of the principal cities of England and maintains purchas- 
ing agencies in several other countries. It is on the whole 
one of the largest establishments of the world. In 1905 
its capital exceeded £3,300,030; its sales amotmted to 
;£ao,785,469, and its net profits were £368,309. 

The Scottish Cooperative Wholesale Society is an 
enterprise of almost similar magnitude, and a large num- 
ber of other independent cooperative societies exist in 
England, Scotland and Ireland. In 1907 the Central 
Board of the Cooperative Union of the United Kingdom 
received reports from 1566 societies having a total mem- 
bership of 2,434,085, The aggregate sales of these socie- 
ties exceeded £105,000,000, and their net profits were 
over £12,000,000. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



24S 



But notwithstanding its enormous business success, the 
cooperative movement is less of a factor in the labor 
struggles of Great Britain than in most other countries of 
Europe. The British cooperatives are honeycombed 
with middle class elements and middle-class notions. 
They are conspicuously devoid of large class ideals, and 
are held together principally by the paltry material bene- 
fits of the movements. 

In all these features the cooperative societies of Great 
Britain stand in marked contrast to those of Belgium, 
which are closely allied with the socialist and trade union 
movements. 

The oldest of the modem cooperative societies in Bel- 
gium is the famous Vooruit (Forward) of Ghent. It was 
organized in 1880 at the initiative of the socialist leader, 
Edouard Anseele, and its first enterprise was a bakery in 
a cellar equipped and operated with a capital of 84 francs 
and 95 centimes. The undertaking was an immediate 
success, and was enlarged and extended from year to year. 
At this writing the amount of its annual business exceeds 
3,000,000 francs, and its yearly profits are over 400,000 
francs. The bakery produces over 100,000 kilos of bread 
per week. In 1903 the Vooruit conducted four drug 
stores, seven groceries, a bookbmdmg shop, a cigar fac- 
tory, a foundry and one of the largest dry goods stores in 
the city. 

Its Feestlokaal, or assembly hall, is located in Rue des 
Baguettes, in the most aristocratic quarters of Ghent. "It 
was once the property of the most select bourgeois club of 
the town," relate Destr^e and Vandervelde, "When the 
members of the club found that it was too expensive for 
I them, the workingmen of Ghent purchased it through the 



I 



11^6 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

intermediary of a dummy, and rents in Rue de Baguettes 
at once dropped 50 per cent. In the gardens in which the 
ladies of high bourgeois society had formerly promenaded, 
hundreds of factory giris are now dancing on Sundays, 
In the concerts the Marseillaise has replaced the Bra- 
ban^onne; the red flag supplanted the tricolor, and 
on the holidays of labor the peaceful bourgeois, looking 
from behind their curtains, see the black columns of work- 
ingmen marching through the quiet street like the torch- 
bearers of the revolution," ' 

The next cooperative society of import^ce to be or- 
ganized in Belgium was the Maison du Peuple {House of 
the People) of Brussels, founded in 1882. 

Of the history of this society Louis Bertrand relates the 
following : " A group of worldngmen of all trades decided 
to create a cooperative bakery. Each member promised 
to contribute 10 francs in weekly payments of 25 to 50 
centimes. In a few months Ihe society had 80 members 
on its list and 700 francs in its treasury. These So mem- 
bers needed about 120 loaves of bread of one kilogram 
each per day. They hired a cellar containing a bake oven 
at a rental of 35 francs per month. . . , Only one baker 
was employed. In the morning he would bake his bread 
and in the afternoon he would carry it to the houses of the 
members. This was not an easy matter, for the mem- 
bers lived in all parts of the city and in the suburbs. . , . 
Gradually the number of members rose from 80 to 250. 
At the end of four years it had 400 members. It was 
necessary to rent a larger place and to install modem bake 
ovens and a mechanical kneading trough. 

' "Le Socialisme en Belgique," par Jules Destr^e et Emile Vander- 
|. veldc, 2d EdilLon, Paris, 1903, p. 47. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



24; 



I 



■'In 1886 the cooperative hired a large hall for 5000 
francs per year, and placed it at the disposal of the labor 
organizations and socialists of Brussels. In less than ten 
years the hall had become too small, and the cooperative 
decided to buUd a new one." ' 

To-day the society counts about 31,000 members, which 
an the basis of 5 persons to the family, makes about 
105,000 consumers. 

The Maison du Feuple operates the largest baking 
establishment in Belgium, and sells over ten million kilos 
of bread per year. The society besides conducts various 
other enterprises, and its building, the new Maison du 
Peuple, is a veritable palace of labor, costing r, 200,000 
francs. 

The cooperative society Progrhs, founded in 1886, is in 
some respects even more influential than either of the two 
described. Its region extends over the entire industrial 
district between Charleroi and Mons, and its four mag- 
nificent buildings erected in different parts of the district 
axe the principal gathering points of the socialists and 
organized workingmen of the neighborhood. 

AH told, the number of cooperative societies in 
Belgium m 1907 was 2582, Of these 630 were so- 
cieties for distribution, 209 were productive societies, 
31 were societies for cooperative dwellings, 52 were in- 
dustrial and 1302 were agricultural credit associations. 
The membership of the distributive societies consisted of 
119,581 families, their aggregate sales for the year 1906 
amounted to 31,174,552 francs, and their net profits for 
that year were 3,035,940 francs. 

The workingmen's cooperatives of Belgium are all 

' "Histoiie de la Cooperative en Belgique," BiusseU, 190a, 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



affiliated with the Federation of Belgian Socialist Coop- 
eratives, founded in 1900 principally for the purpose of 
wholesale purchases. The rules of all societies thus 
affiliated with the Federation are practically uniform, and 
the constitutions of the societies expressly declare "that 
the society is above all a political socialist group, and that 
the members by subscribing to the constitution signify 
their adherence to the program of the Labor Party." 
The members of the cooperatives and their families form 
the basis of the Belgian Labor Party, and in times of elec- 
toral campaigns they constitute themselves into poHtical 
committees. Around the cooperatives and in their spa- 
cious halls are grouped the trade unions, the socialist or- 
ganizations, the social and educational clubs of working- 
men, and the editorial rooms of the socialist papers. The 
cooperatives expend a considerable portion of their profits 
on socialist propaganda in all forms and in the support of 
the struggles of trade unions. In a word, the cooperatives 
in Belgium are the center of the socialist and labor move- 
ment. In the electoral campaign of 1900 they printed 
and distributed at their own expense two million socialist 
booklets. 

The development of the cooperative movement in Ger- 
many has followed a somewhat peculiar course owing to 
special historical and political conditions. In the period 
of the beginnings of the socialist and labor movement in 
Germany, the problem of cooperative enterprises played 
a very important rfile, Schulze-Delitsch, one of the heads 
of the Liberal Party and an ardent apostle of the doctrine 
of "self-help," headed a large movement for the organiza- 
tion of voluntary cooperative societies chiefly for produc- 
tion, as a complete solution of the labor question. It was 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



249 



^ 



a middle-class movement, its theoretical foundation was 
unsound and reactionary, and the design of its promoters 
seemed to be to deter the working class from independent 
labor politics. To this movement Ferdinand Lassalle 
opposed his famous plan of cooperative productive asso- 
ciations with state credit, a plan which involved the con- 
quest of universal suffrage by the workingmen and the 
democratization of the state, i.e., working-class political 
action. The struggle between Lassalle and Schulze on 
the issue of state credit as against self-help, assumed the 
form of a struggle between socialism and liberalism. The 
socialists concentrated their forces on politics, while the 
liberals gained control of the voluntary cooperative move- 
ment. Under the leadership of Schulze-Delitsch and his 
successors the latter grew up, large in size, but weak and 
inefficient in spirit. It laid the greatest stress on pro- 
ductive associations, and encouraged associations for 
credit, but regarded societies for distribution and con- 
sumption with a certain degree of suspicion. 

The socialists had but little esteem for the cooperative 
movement under those circumstances. 

But in the meanwhile the expiration of the ant i -socialist 
laws in 1890 set free a large quantity of stored-up energy in 
the radical workingmen of Germany. They inaugurated 
a vigorous activity in all domains of the labor movement, 
and among others they entered the ranks of cooperative 
societies for consumption in large numbers. This influx 
of socialists so perturbed the leaders of the conservative 
cooperative movement that in 1902 they expelled by a 
coup d'ilat 99 societies for consumption on the ground of 
their social democratic tendencies. In May of the next 
year these called a convention at Dresden which was at- 



f 250 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

tended by representatives of 6zi associations for con- 
sumption, largely composed of workingmen with socialist 
tendencies. At that convention was organized the Cen- 
tral Union of German Societies for Consumption, which 
is now the leading organization in that field. Towards 
the end of 1907 there were in Germany 2110 societies for 
consumption, with a total membership of about 1,131,453. 
Of these the Central Union represented 959 societies, with 
a total of 879,221 members. The societies afiiliated with 
it thus represented 77 per cent of the entire membership 
of the German consumptive organizations. They em- 
ployed 12,783 persons and conducted about 2500 stores, 
with a total invested capital of 25,000,000 marks. Their 
business for the year was 303,794,452 marks, and their 
profits were more than 20,000,000 marks. 

With the separation of the radical societies for con- 
sumption from the liberal cooperative movement, the re- 
lations between the former and the socialists grew closer 
and more cordial, and to-day both work in complete har- 
mony. 

The cooperative movements in the other countries have 
developed various degrees of strength and usefulness, and 
their period of greatest growth lies almost invariably 
within the last two decades. 

In Italy a special feature of the movement is presented 
by the cooperatives of the day laborers, who hire out their 
joint work under contract, and subdivide it among them- 
selves in separate g£ings, supplying the necessary tools 
out of the common fund and sharing the contract price. 
The effect of such cooperation is to eliminate the profit of 
the padrone. In 1906 Italy had 2793 cooperative socie- 
ties, doing a total business of over 600,000,000 francs. 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 251 

Eight hundred and fifty-one of these societies were purely 
consumptive, 454 were productive societies, 350 were 
cooperative societies for credit, while the remainder con- 
sisted of labor, agricultural and mixed societies. 

In Sweden the object of cooperative societies is almost 
exclusively joint farming and building. Out of the 2524 
I cooperative societies reporting in 1906, all but 382 be- 
I longed to that class. The character of the cooperative 
F organizations in Finland and Holland is very similar to 
I the organization of Sweden. 

France had in 1904 about 5500 co6perative societies, of 
which more than 3000 are agricultural associations. Aus- 
tria, Switzerland, Holland and Denmark have also de- 
veloped noteworthy cooperative movements. The United 
States is the most backward country in this field. 

Victor Serwy, at that time Secretary of the Internationa! 
Socialist Bureau, computed that in 1901 there were 56,623 
known cooperative societies in the world. 

Cooperative societies may be divided into a large num- 
ber of distinct groups according to the objects pursued 
and methods employed by them, but we are concerned 
with those of them only that may be fairly said to form a 
part of the labor movement. These may be divided into 
enterprises for cooperative production and enterprises for 
cooperative consumption or distribution. 

The productive societies are of special value for trade 
unions m conjunction with their struggles against their 
employers, and they often do good service in oEEering 
a refuge to blacklisted strike leaders or other active 
union members. But as a rule they attain a measure of 
business success only when conducted in conjunction with 
L societies for consumption. As independent enterprises 



1852 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

they generally fail. A manufacturing establishment in 
modern times cannot succeed unless it is provided with the 
capital which its large competitors command, and employs 
the same methods as they. And the workingmen -found- 
ers of productive associations as a rule do not possess the 
required capital nor can they employ the countless cus- 
tomary methods of labor exploitation. 

The cooperative societies for consumption, on the other 
hand, have proved themselves almost uniformly successful 
from the point of view of business. 

The socialists do not foster the illusion that voluntary 
cooperative societies of labor, either for production or for 
consumption, could gradually and by the strength of their 
own development, supersede the prevalent capitalist 
methods of production and distribution. They do not 
even attach great importance to the cooperatives as factore 
in the general improvement and elevation of the material 
conditions of the workers. But they regard them as use- 
ful auxiliaries in the struggles of the working class as soiu-ces 
of ammunition in those struggles, and as effective schools 
for the training of the workingmen in the administration 
of industries and in the sense of the solidarity of their 
class. 

Thegeneral attitude of socialism towards the cooperative 
movement of the workingmen was defined by the social 
democrats of Germany in a resolution adopted at the 
convention of their party at Hanover in 1899, in the fol- 
lowing language : — 

" The attitude of the party towards the cooperative in- 
dustrial associations is one of neutrality. It considers the 
organization of such associations, when the necessary con- 
dhions of their success are present, as calcidated to Intro- 



THE INDUSTRIAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 253 

duce improvements in the economic situation of their 
members, and it also sees in such associations, as in every 
organization of 'the workingmen for the protection and 
promotion of their interests, a proper medium for the 
education of the working class in the independent direc- 
tion of its aflfairs. The party does not attribute to such 
associations a determining importance for the liberation 
of the working class from the chains of wage slavfery." 



CHAPTER III 



woeeingmen's insurance 



One of the greatest evils of the modern system of wage 
labor is tlie uncertainty of the woriser's existence under it. 
So long as the wage earner is in normal good health and 
his employment is tolerably steady, he 'manages to eke out 
a precarious living for himself and those dependent on him. 
In times of prosperity the laborer, and especially the 
skilled mechanic, may even save up a modest sum for a 
rainy day. 

But suddenly his work is interrupted and his earnings 
cease. A dull season may throw him out of employment 
for weeks, or a general industrial depression may close the 
doors of the factory against him for months. His scanty 
savings, if he has any, dwindle and disappear with frightful 
rapidity, and in a short time the worker finds himself con- 
fronted with the menace of actual starvation. Or he sud- 
denly falls sick in the midst of great industrial activity, and 
is rendered physically incapable for a protracted period of 
time. To the workingman health means not only well- 
being and happiness, it means his bread and the bread of 
his family; sickness for him is not only physical discom- 
fort, it is often helpless, bottomless destitution. 

But the sick workingman in the midst of his distress is 
at least comforted with the hope of recovery, with the hope 
of eventual resumption of his work and life. How much 



WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 



2SS 



more desperate is the lot of the man crippled in his em- 
ployment. The workingman whose principal, if not sole 
claim, to life lies in the deftness of his fingers, in the 
strength of his arm or in the muscles of his leg, is in con- 
stant danger of being robbed of his limbs and strength by 
his perfidious and bloodthirsty shopmate, the iron monster 
:nachine, ever on the alert for a sign of weariness or re- 
laxation on his part, ever ready to assail him unawares. 
And when the hapless worker has been maimed and in- 
validated in the service of his fellow-men, our Chrbtian 
I society does not reward him for his sacrifice, does not in- 
' demnify him for his loss, does not even extend a pitying 
hand to comfort him in his misfortune, but casts him aside 
mercilessly and unfeelingly, and quietly lets him perish, 
passing on to the next victim. 

And if this cruel fate may accidentally overtake any 
workingman in the prime of his life and strength, a similar 
lot is almost certain to befall all workingmen at a more 
advanced age. 

"Not less tragic than the position of the unemployed 
workman," observes Mr. George Turner, "is that of the 
aged craftsman. The man who does not give the fullest 
measure of work for his weekly wage is promptly dis- 
carded by an economic system depending upon alert 
competition for its existence. Fortunate it is that sixty 
per cent do not live to be replaced by active, able-bodied, 
hopeful young workmen, and to be left destitute. But a 
large minority meets this fate. Wages of men from forty- 
five years upwards show a gradual and persistent decline. 
The roughest forms of labor are the first to suffer ; but in 
skilled trades where deftness of handiwork is the first 
I condition of eiKciency and of continued employment, the 



256 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

attainment of fifty-five years of age is usually accompanied 
by a reduction of earnings." ' 

This uncertainty of existence, the constant menace of 
unemployment, of sicitness, accidents and old age, which 
hangs over the head of every modem wage earner like the 
sword of Damocles, is intimately linked with the system of 
private competitive industries and "free" wage labor, and 
as the system unfolds itself, it tends to aggravate the pre- 
cariousness of the workingman's life. With the develop- 
ment and perfection of machinery and the growing in- 
tensity of work and competition, the "reserve army of the 
unemployed" is constantly on the increase, industrial 
accidents are more common, the worker is exhausted and 
enfeebled earlier in life, and the aged mechanic is rendered 
more useless. 

The problem of providing against these contingencies 
has, therefore, naturally engaged the attention of the 
workingmen ever since the rise of the wage system, and 
it has become a matter of ever greater concern to them 
as that system has developed. 

The first practical efforts for the relief of workingmen 
in cases of unemployment, sickness, accidents and old age, 
assumed the form of private and voluntary enterprises, 
undertaken by workingmen, and sometimes by employers 
of labor. To the former class belong the trade unions and 
other labor organizations which furnish relief to their 
members out of work from funds raised among themselves 
by means of regular periodical contributions or assess- 
ments, and the numerous fraternal and mutual societies 
which insure their members in cases of sickness and acci- 

' "The Case for State Pensions in Old Age," Fa.biaD Society, London, 
1899. 



WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 



257 



1 old 



dents, and sometimes even provide for annuities i 
age. Among tlie latter class must be counted the special 
funds of large employers of labor, notably the mining and 
railroad companies, established for the purpose of aiding 
their employees in cases of sickness and accidents or of 
providing them with pensions after a continuous employ- 
ment of specified duration. These funds are as a rule 
created with a view of attracting a better grade of work- 
ers to the more dangerous and strenuous trades and insur- 
ing their steadiness of work. In the United States they 
have gained but little extension. In some countries of 
Europe, notably in France, Belgium and England, they 
play a much more important rfile, but on the whole the 
practice is so rare, and the benefits of the system are so 
restricted and insignificant, that they can hardly be con- 
sidered a serious factor in the movement for the relief of 
the workingmen against the uncertainties of their existence. 

Of much greater value than the employers' funds, are 
the cooperative societies of workingmen, such as the 
various Benefit Orders of the United States, the Friendly 
Societies of Great Britain, the SocieHs de Secours Mutuels 
of France, Belgium and Switzerland, the Kranken-Kassen 
of Germany and Austria, and the mutual aid associations 
of almost all other countries. 

Beginning on a modest scale in the early part of the last 
century, these societies soon proved themselves so essential 
to large masses of the working population, and spread with 
such rapidity that they almost attained the importance of 
a social institution. Towards the middle of last century 
the governments of the most advanced countries of Europe 
found themselves impelled to take official cognizance of 
, their existence and activity. 



[258 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

I In England the first legislative act affecting the friendly 
societies dates back to 1793, but that act and the amend- 

• atory legislation following it during more than half a cen- 
tury, did not materially advance the standing or powers 
of these societies, and left the application of such laws 
optional with the societies. The first laws which under- 
took not only to regulate but also in some degree to aid 

I and strengthen the mutual insurance societies of working- 
men, were the laws passed in Prussia in 1849 ^^d ^ France 
and Belgium in 1850. And similar laws have since been 
adopted by almost every country of Europe and by most 
of the states in the United States. 

I From government regulation to government manage- 

I ment is but one step, and in the matter of workingmen's 
insurance this step was readily taken in several countries 
of Europe. In France a state department for old-age in- 
surance ■ — the Caisse Nationale des Retrailes pour la 
Vieillesse — was established in 1850, and it was followed 
in 1868 by a similar state institution for accident insur- 
ance—the Caisse Nationale d' Assurance en cas d'Ac- 
cidents. 

In Belgium a National Old Age Pension Bank was 
established by the government in 1850. In Italy a semi- 
governmental Bank for the Insurance of Workingmen 
Against Accidents — the Cassa Nazimiak di Assicura- 
zione per gli inforluni degli operai, was created by the law 
of July 8, :883. 

AH these instances of workingmen's insurance institu- 
tions managed by the government are those of voluntary 
state insurance, i.e., institutions conducted by the state as 
a branch of the government for the benefit of those of its 
citizens who may desire to take advantage of them. The 






WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 259 

state does not contribute to the insurance funds, and the 
amount of insurance is determined on the basis of pre- 
mium payments. The superiority of such state insurance 
over that of the ordinary insurance companies lies in the 
greater safety of the investment and in the fact that it 
excludes the element of profit. 

The institutions of voluntary state insurance have no- 
where become very effective or popular for the reason that 
they leave the entire burden of financing them on the class 
least capable of carrying it — the working class. Volun- 
tary state insurance is, after all, but another form of self- 
telp in insurance, and such insurance has, on the whole, 
proved entirely inadequate to relieve the needs of the 
vast masses of wage earners of our day. Comparing the net 
results of the various forms of workingmen's insurance, 
voluntary and involuntary, at the close of the nineteenth 
century, M. Maurice Bellom remarks : " It is impossible 
to refrain from an exclamation of astonishment and ad- 
miration in reviewing the social results of compulsory in- 
surance, . . , The diffusion of insurance which the 
compulsory organization has caused, the pecuniary ad- 
vantages which it has secured for the workers, the ease 
with which it has enabled employers of labor to discharge 
their liability, and finally the benefits of a better hygiene 
which it has conferred on the entire community, have won 
for the system of compulsory insurance the general recog- 
nition of the numerous beneficiaries of that system." ^ 
Within the last few decades the conviction has grown in 
some of the most advanced countries that the provision of 
workingmen's insurance against unemployment, sickness, 

' Journal de la SociiU de Siaiisligue de Paris, 19Q1, for June, July and 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

accidents and old age, is not a matter to be left to the m- 
clinations or abilities of individuals, but a task to be 
assumed by organized society as such ; that it is the duty 
of the state to guarantee the existence of the invalids and 
veterans of its industrial army at least as much as the 
existence of the invalids and veterans of its military army 
is now guaranteed. 

The first official proclamation of this principle is prob- 
ably that contained in the French constitution of 1848, 
which declared "that the Republic should by fraternal 
assistance assure the existence of its needy citizens." 
"But," observes Edouard Vaillant,' "the victorious reac- 
tion knew how to guard itself against all practical conse- 
quences of its republican affirmations and declarations." 

It was left to the imperial government of Germany to 
inaugurate and enforce a general system of compulsory 
state insurance with direct state aid. This revolutionary 
measure in the domain of workingmen's insurance was 
first announced in a famous message of Wilhelm I to the 
German Diet, on November 17, 1881, and we quote from 
it the following passage bearing on the subject : — 

"Already in February of this year we expressed our con- 
viction that the cure of our social maladies is not to be 
found in the repression of the social democratic excesses 
alone, but also in the promotion of the welfare of the work- 
ing class. We consider it our Imperial duty once more to 
urge the accomplishment of this task on the Diet. , . . 

"In this sense the united governments will first re- 
submit to the Diet the bill for insurance of workingmen 
against accidents with such amendments as have been 
1 in the discussions on the subject at your last 
"Assurance Sociale," Paris, 1901, p. 7. 



WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 



261 



» 



Supplementary thereto a bill will be introduced 
which has for its object the uniform organization of in- 
dustrial insurance institutions in cases of sickness. But 
also those who are incapacitated for work by reason of 
old age or invalidity, have a well-founded claim on the 
community to a higher degree of state aid than has here- 
tofore been accorded them." 

The first institution of compulsory state insurance of 
workingmen established in Germany in pursuance of the 
imperial message, was the insurance against sickness 
created by the law of 1883 and repeatedly amended since. 
Almost all industrial workers whose yearly earnings do 
not exceed 2000 marks, and certain classes of commercial 
and agricultural workers are brought under the provisions 
of this law. The institution operates through the agency 
of local sick benefit societies. The employers contribute 
one third of the insurance funds and pay the expense of 
administration, the employees pay the remaining two 
thirds, the contributions in each case being proportionate 
to the wages paid or earned. 

The minimum aid fixed by law includes tree medicine 
and medical attendance; a money indemnity equal to 
three fourths of the daily wage, or half of the wage and 
free hospital treatment; in case of death a cash benefit to 
the widow or family of the deceased equal to twenty times 
his daily wage; and sick relief to working women during 
six weeks after confinement. 

The German system of state insurance against accidents 
was inidated by the law of 1884, That act is a radical 
advance over the sick insurance law in that it specifically 
recognizes the loss occasioned by accidents in the indus- 
trial process as a legitimate part of the employer's operating 




262 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



h 



expenses, and places the entire burden of the insurance 
against accidents on the employing class. Tlie affairs of 
the institution are administered by the joint representatives 
of the employers and employees, and the rates of insurance 
are fixed with reference to the degree of the danger of the 
several trades, and the efficiency of the safeguards adopted 
by each particular employer. One of the most substantial 
benefits of this system has been the greater care developed 
by the employers of labor and the general decrease of acci- 
dents to workingmen. 

The system of accident insurance embraces practically 
all wage workers whose yearly earnings do not exceed 3000 
marks. The compensation includes free medical attend- 
ance and a fixed allowance during the period of disability. 
In cases of total disability the injured man receives an 
annuity equal to two thirds of his wages, and in cases of 
death an indemnity is paid to the surviving family. 

The third measure of workingmen's insurance mentioned 
in the imperial message, that of insurance against old age 
and invalidity, was not realized till iSSg. The system dif- 
fers from the two other forms of workingmen's insurance 
in that it has been made a more distinct function of the 
state as such. The old-age pension fund is administered 
directly by the government, and the latter contributes 50 
marks per year for each insured entitled to an annuity. 
The remaining funds are contributed in equal portions 
by the employers and employees. This form of insurance 
is compulsory on every wage earner, sixteen years of age 
and over, whose annual wages do not exceed 2000 marks. 
The fund insures an annuity to each workingman after 
he has become incapacitated for work, or has reached the 
^e of seventy years. The amount of the pension is de- 



WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 263 

termined with reference to the average wages of the in- 
sured, the minimum being 115 marks, and the maximum 
about 450 marks per year. 

All the three forms of workingmen's insurance are oper- 
ated in conjunction with each other, and the main object 
of the copious amendatory legislation on the subject has 
been to combine them all into a harmonious and com- 
plete system. 

In comparison with the crude methods of voluntary in- 
surance, the compulsory state insurance of Germany, 
insufficient as it is, has proved a decided success. 

In 1904 the number of German workingmen insured 
against sickness was 11,418,446, and relief in that branch 
of insurance was given in 4,642,679 cases, involving a total 
expenditure of about 240,000,000 marks. 

No less than 20,000,000 German workers were insured 
against accidents in 1906, and about 14,000,000 persons 
were insured against invalidity and old age in 1905. 
The total amount of accident indemnity paid in the year 
mentioned was 142,436,844 marks, while almost 160,000,- 
000 marks were paid out in workingmen's pensions, 
On January i, 1906, 934,983 invalid and aged working- 
men were drawing pensions, and the receipts for that 
year and purpose exceeded 210,000,000 marks, of which 
the government had contributed about 38,000,000 marks. 

In aU, the German empire has spent in the twenty-year 
period, 1885-1905, the sum of about 5,000,000,000 marks 
on workingmen's insurance. 

The example of Germany has been partly followed by 
Austria, which enacted laws for the insurance of its work- 
ingmen against sickness in 1888, and against accidents in 
1887. In Hungary the system of compulsory insurance 



r 364 SOaALISM AND REFORM 

against sickness was introduced in 1891. In Switzerland 
the principle of compulsory state insurance of workingmen 
was adopted in the form of an amendment to the federal 
constitution. That amendment was adopted in 1890 on a 
popular referendum, and read as follows: — 

"The Confederation shall provide, by legislative en- 
actment, for insurance against sickness and accidents, 
account being taken of existing aid societies. It may 
declare participation in insurance compulsory on all or on 
certain specified categories of citizens." 

When, however, a concrete legislative bill on compulsory 
sick insurance was submitted to the referendum of the 
people, it was rejected by a vote of 330,000 against 143,000, 
on account of certain unpopular provisions, principally 
with respect to the proportion of the contributions of the 
insured. 

In Norway a system of compulsory state insurance 
against accidents was inaugurated in 1894, in Finland in 
1895, in Italy in 1898, and in Holland and Sweden in 1901, 
France has had a system of accident insurance since 1898, 
and has very recently adopted a law providing for the 
compulsory insurance of workingmen against invalidity 
and old age. Similar institutions are in force in the colo- 
nies of New Zealand, New South Wales and Victoria, In 
Great Britain Parliament has recently established a gov- 
ernment system of old-age pensions. 

The main principles and methods of operation of these 
institutions in the countries enumerated are substantially 
similar to those of Germany, but some of them, notably 
that of Austria, are more liberal in the amounts of the 
benefits. 

Denmark has the distinction of having the only national 



■ WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 265 

system which somewhat approaches the ideal of state in- 
surance against unemployment. It has recently adopted 
a law regulating the methods of trade unions in the manage- 
ment of funds for the relief of their members out of work, 
and providing for regular state contributions toward such 
funds. In Belgium, Switzerland and France, several mu- 
nicipalities have introduced similar measures for the as- 
sistance of unemployed working men. 

In Belgium and Denmark, the subject of compulsory 
state insurance of workingmen in one form or another is 
of late being very strongly agitated, and the indications 
are that these countries wiU soon fall into line with the 
general progress of "social legislation." 

The practical plan- of workingmen's insurance was first 
formulated by the well-known Austrian statesman and 
sociologist. Dr. Schaeffle, in 1867,' and was elaborated by 
Professors Wagner, SchmoUer and the other representa- 
tives of the school of social science known in Germany by 
the general designation of "socialism of the chair" (Katke- 
dersozialismus). But its practical realization and the 
steady extension of its application is distinctly due to the 
propaganda of modern socialism. The message of Em- 
peror Wilhelm I quoted above, plainly admits that the 
fear of the socialist movement was one of the government's 
motives in inaugurating the era of social legislation, and 
Prince Bismarck, the prime mover of the measure, was even 
franker in his public utterances on the subject, as shown in 
a previous chapter (Socialism and Law). 

Factory legislation involves merely reforms in the rela- 
tions between the individual employers and employees, but 
social insurance is based on the recognition of the duties of 
k ' Adolph Schaeffle, " Kapitalismua und Sozialismus." 



I 266 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



I 



the state as such towards its working-class citizens, ani 
distinctly a socialistic idea. Factory legislation, there- 
fore, may be forced from the government by a strong labor 
movement, even if that movement has not reached the 
consciousness of socialism; but social insurance can be 
achieved, directlyor indirectly, only through the presence of 
a well-defined and aggressive socialist movement. Ger- 
many, the classical country of modern socialism, is also 
the home of social insurance; in the United States, where 
the trade-union movement is old and strong and the socialist 
movement is new and comparatively weak, we have a con- 
siderable number of factory laws, but not even the first 
rudiments of social legislation. England was in this 
respect similarly situated with the United States, until its 
workingmen turned to socialism and socialist politics. 
The English old-age pension system has been among the 
first results of the change. 

The socialists do not overrate the value of workingmen's 
insurance. They do not consider it as a solution of the 
social problem, nor even as a measure of adequate relief of 
the more pressing needs of the working class. But they 
see in it a potent lever for the elevation of the physical and 
moral standard of the masses. 

The uncertainty of the workingmen's life has probably a 
more deteriorating effect on the morale of their class than 
any other feature of their existence; it tends to make 
them timid and conservative and inaccessible to the 
movement for the elevation of then- class on a broad and 
bold plane. 

The effect of a comprehensive system of state insurance 
is to remove from the minds of the workingmen the haunt- 
mg dread born of uncertainty, and to develop in them a 



WORKINGMEN'S INSURANCE 267 

r certain sense of material security and intellectual independ- 
ence. 
The socialists, moreover, regard the system of compul- 

, sory state insurance as a large step in the direction of the 

social transformation of the modern individualistic state. 

"In a socialist society," Edouard Vaillant predicts, 

"social insurance will in its turn disappear in the higher 

I forms of the social institutions based on equality and 
solidarity, as they are tonday absorbing and transforming 
the old institutions of public assistance and the partial 
and incomplete experiments of private insurance. Charity, 
public assistance and social insurance are the three suc- 
cessive stages through which we have to pass before the 
emancipation of the working class and the social republic 
will render them useless. 

" Under the capitalist regime it is only through social 
insurance that the dignity of the workingman and the poor 
can be safeguarded, and his legal rights, his guaranty 
against all social risks and all misery, can be established 
and maintained. And it is because of this, because the 
time for the complete realization of the plan has arrived, 
that we must concentrate all our eSorts on its establish- 



And the socialists have never relaxed theu- efforts to 



' "Assurance Sociale." 

For detailed descriptions of the kinds, methods and results ot Work- 
ingmen's Insurance, consult:^ 

William Franklin Willoughby, " Workingmen's Insurance," New 
York. 1898. 

John Graham Brooks, "Compulsory Insurance in Germany," Special 
Report of United Stales Commissioner of Labor, Washington, 1B95. 

Dr. Heiotich Herkner, "Die Arbeiterfrage," 4th revised and enlarged 
I edition, Berlio, 190^. 



268 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

improve and extend the existing system of state insurance. 
In Germany and other countries in which the system has 
been wholly or partly established, they work for the elimina- 
tion of the workingmen's contributions to the insurance 
funds on the theory that it is the duty of the state to insure 
the life and existence of the worker, without curtailing his 
wages for that purpose; they demand the raismg of the 
benefits to an extent sufficient to meet the actual needs of 
the sick, disabled and aged workers, and they urge the 
extension of the system to cover the entire wage-earning 
class. 

In countries in which the system of compulsory state in- 
surance for workingmen has not yet been introduced, the 
socialists are its most ardent, often its sole advocates. 



CHAPTER IV 



THE POIITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 
Political Reform 

In theory representative government is govemmraf 
"of, for and by the people," and the modern politicaJ 
machinery is an instrument for the expression and en- 
forcement of the popular will. 

But in most of the advanced modem countries the po- 
litical actualities accord but poorly with these theoretical 
ideals of democracy. As a rule it is not the great masses, 
but the small privileged groups who dominate the govern- 
ment. A large portion of the people are openly excluded 
from all direct participation in politics, and for many of 
those who nominally enjoy political rights, the exercise of 
those rights is a mere illusion. The elected or appointed 
public officials are but rarely the disinterested "servants" 
of their constituents. More often they are the rulers of the 
nation, exercising the fimctions of oflice for the promotion 
of their own interests or those of their special class and in 
hostility to the people. The constituents have but little 
control over their "representatives," and the general 
tendency of modem political development has been to 
alienate the government from the people, 

Mr. M. Ostrogorski, who has probably made the most 
searching and exhaustive investigation of political institu- 
tions and conditions in the two greatest democracies of our 



270 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



day, England and the United States,' makes the alarming 
but well -substantiated statement that in both countries the 
political parties, which were originally devised for the reali- 
zation of the wiil of the voting masses, have turned into ef- 
fective instruments for the defeat of that very will. Politi- 
cal parties have become political machines run by political 
"bosses" on the principle early announced by a prominent 
American politician, "To the victors belong the spoils." 
The "victors," within the meaning of that maxim of 
modern political ethics, are always the party bosses and 
their henchmen, and the "spoils" are the public ofSces of 
trust and confidence, the powers of popular government 
and all its departments. 

The professional politicians in the United States, in- 
cluding officeholders and party bosses of all grades, have 
developed into a distinct class. Mr. Ostrogorski estimates 
their number at about 900,000^ i.e., about 6,5 per cent 
of the voting population, and that class practically controls 
the politics of the country and constitutes its government. 
Only from one to ten per cent of the voters take part in the 
primaries, and the large bulk of the votes in popular 
elections is manipulated by the professional politicians, 
either by means of the stultifying clap-trap methods of 
modern American campaigning, or by direct personal 
promises and influence, or by the still more direct method 
of purchase. Mr. Ostrogorski makes the startling asser- 
tion that more than 11 per cent of the American voters 
sell their votes. 

It is this perversion of popular government that has 
given rise to the many modern movements of political re- 

' M. Ostrogorski, "Democracy aad Political Parties," New York, 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



form, and as the vices of prevailing political conditions and 
methods become more acute and apparent, these move- 
ments grow in extension and intensity. 

The main currents of all such political reform movements 
may be said to proceed along three distinct lines. 

The first of these is directed against the personal in- 
competence or corruption of individual officeholders or 
politicians. This is the so-called "good government" 
movement, which sees the remedy for all political evils in 
"putting good men into office." The movement by its 
very nature is bound to be sporadic and ineffective. It is 
most common in the large American cities, which are the 
chronic prey of organized gangs of unscrupulous politi- 
cians. When these political marauders, intoxicated with 
power, become too shameless and aggressive, the decent 
citizens, mostly of the "better classes," periodically rise 
in revolt, and inaugurate a "good government" campaign. 
If successful, they oust the corrupt officials, and elect men 
of their own ranks in their stead. As a rule they do not 
attempt any radical changes of the conditions which breed 
and maintain corrupt political gangs in the cities, and 
as a result their reform regimes are short lived, and soon 
succumb to a new and more appalling state of political 
I corruption. The recent histories of New York, Chicago, 
' Pittsburg, Philadelphia, Minneapolis and St. Louis offer 
abundant instances of such movements, and the pathetic 
struggles and failures of the shortsighted good government 
reforms of these cities have been graphically described by 
Mr. Lincoln Steffens.' 

The more important movements of political reform are 
those concerned m the permanent improvements of politi- 
» "The Shame of Che Cities," New York, 1904. 



f 272 



SOCIAUSM AND REFORM 



cal institutions and methods. These movements have 1^^ 
their object the extension of the suffrage to classes still 
excluded from it, or they aim to increase the political 
powers of the people and to strengthen their control over 
their chosen representatives. To the former class belong 
the movements for the abohtion of all forms of restrictions 
on adult manhood suffrage, and for the introduction of 
woman suffrage; to the latter, the movements for the 
direct election of all public officials, for the introduction 
of the principle of initiative and referendum in legislation, 
the system of proportional representation in government, 
and the right of the constituents to recall their represent- 
atives. 

All these movements have of late made very consider- 
able gains. 



Universal Suffrage 

The general principle of universal suffrage of all adult 
male citizens has been pretty definitely established in 
several countries, such as the United States, England, 
France and Switzerland, for all political elections; in other 
countries, such as Germany and Austria, it is limited to 
parhamentary elections, while in the local elections in 
these countries, and in ail elections in some other countries, 
such as Belgium and Holland, the suffrage is qualified by 
the age, property, education or social condition of the voter. 
The domain of imiversal manhood suffrage is steadily 
extending, and the struggles for the removal of all qualifica- 
tions on such suffrage are assuming ever larger proportions, 
especially in Belgium, Holland, Germany and Hungary. 

As part of the general movement for suffrage exten- 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



273 



^^ sta 
^^H ' cia 



sion, the movement for the enfranchisement of women has 
also made large strides within the last generation. Not 
only has that movement to-day numerous and energetic 
adherents of both sexes all over the civilized world, but in 
many countries it has already realized complete or partial 
practical victories. The women of Finland enjoy the 
"active" and the "passive" franchise (the right to vote 
and to hold elective office) in all elections ui the same 
manner as the men, and out of the 200 deputies in 
the Finnish Diet, 19 are women. In Norway the tax- 
paying or propertied women have votes in all parliamen- 
tary and local elections. Women are completely enfran- 
chised in New Zealand and in the Austrahan colonies of 
South and West Australia, New South Wales, Tasmania and 
Queensland. In the fittle Isle of Man, which has its own 
local parliament, women are likewise allowed to vote on 
equal terms with men. In the other parts of Great Britain 
and Ireland woman suffrage is restricted to certain elec- 
tions for local offices. The Frenchmen have conferred on 
their women the right to vote in elections for school trus- 
tees, charity inspectors and members of the industrial 
courts. In Germany, Sweden, Denmark and Switzerland 
women are permitted to vote in certain local elections. 

In the United States four states, Wyoming, Colorado, 
Utah and Idaho, have extended to their female citizens the 
rights of unrestricted suffrage, while most of the other 
states allow their women to participate in the elections of 
local school boards and other minor oEBcials. 

Wyoming has had the longest experience with the insti- 
tution of woman suffrage, which was introduced in that 
state in 1868. In 1893 its legislature attested its appre- 
ciation of the beneficial and ennobling effect of the instltu- 



I 274 SOCIALISM AND REFORM ^^H 

tion on the public life of the citizens of the state, in a con- 
I current resolution, which among other things recited: 
"That the possession and exercise of suffrage by the 
women in Wyoming for the past quarter of a century has 
wrought no harm and has done great good in many ways; 
that it has largely aided in banishing crime, pauperism 
and vice from the state, and that without any violent and 
oppressive legislation; that it has secured peaceful and 
orderly elections, good government and a remarkable 
degree of civilization and good order," 

Of the remaining electoral reform movements, the first 
in order of importance is probably that advocating the 
I system of 

Proportional Represenialian 

Under the prevailing systems of election, the majority 
party may sometimes monopolize all public offices while 
the minority parties may have no representation at all. 
Theoretically we may conceive of a situation where a 
party representing a bare majority of the voters, say 
51 per cent, evenly distributed aU over the country, may 
carry every election and fill every seat in the state and 
national legislatures and all other public offices of the coun- 
try, while the remaining 49 per cent may have no represen- 
tation and no voice in the administration at all. But 
this applies only to countries in which an absolute ma- 
jority of the votes cast is required for election. In countries 
in which a mere plurality determines the elections, as in 
■ the United States, we may well conceive a situation where 
the voters are divided into three or more parties of ap- 
prox,iniate]y equal strength, and the strongest of them, 



I 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 2^$ 

representing perhaps 35 per cent of all voters, may control 
the entire government. In actual practice, of course, 
the party voters are never so evenly distributed, and a 
strong minority party as a rule has some representation 
in the government. But this representation is uncertain, 
and the smaller parties are often left without any repre- 
sentation. In the general national elections in the United 
States in 1908, the total number of votes cast for all 
parties was 14,882,132, Of these the Republican Party 
received 7,677,544, the Democratic Party, 6,405,707, the 
Socialist Party, 420,464, the Prohibition Party, 251,660, 
the Independence Party, 83,628, the People's Party, 
29,108, and the Socialist Labor Party, 14,021. 

In the same elections 391 members of the House of 
Representatives were chosen. Under a system of pro- 
portional representation these members would have been 
apportioned among the various parties as follows: — 

Republicans 
Democrats 
Socialists 
Prohibitionists 
Independence Party 
People's Party 

391 

As a matter of fact the House was composed of 219 
Republicans and 172 Democrats, and none of the min or 
parties had any representation whatever on it. 

There are several methods by which the principle of pro- 
portional representation may be applied to elections. The 
one known as the "free list" or "quota plan" is the 
r simplest and most commonly employed. This system 



3^6 SOOALISM AND REFORM 

presupposes large electoral districts and party nominations. 
To illustrate its practical working let us take the case of a 
city with 100,000 voters entitled to elect ten members of 
Congress or other_ legislative body. Every ten thousand 
voters of any political faith will thus be entitled to one 
representative, and no political party polling at least that 
number of votes will be entirely excluded from representa- 
tion. Let us assume that there are four parties in the field. 
Each of the parties may nominate ten candidates, but it 
will serve the purpose if they nominate one or two more 
than they expect to elect. The electoral ticket and the 
votes cast for the different parlies will be as follows: — 




This illustration presupposes a straight party vote, and 

in that case candidates will be declared elected in the order 

of their positions on the ballot, the positions having been 

fixed by the respective parties. This is known as the 

" block-vote." But the plan of proportional representation 

i does not preclude the voter from expressing his preference 

I for specific candidates of his party. The voter may be al- 

I lowed to vote for the individual candidates of his choice, 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 277 

and his vote will count both for the candidate and the party, 
and he may be even allowed to vote on the cumulative sys- 
tem, i.e., cast all of his ten votes for one candidate or distrib- 
ute them among several candidates in such proportions as 
he may choose. Where votes are counted for the candi- 
date as well as for the party, each party will receive the 
representation to which the total number of votes cast for 
its ticket entitles it, and the candidates receiving the high- 
est individual votes on the ticket will be declared elected. 

The system of proportional representation has been 
introduced in the parliamentary elections of Sweden, Fin- 
land and Japan; it is being strongly urged in several other 
countries for national elections, and is frequently applied 
in local elections. Belgium has the curious system of 
proportional representation based on the "single vote 
plan" and combined with plural voting. The system is 
the same as shown in our illustration, except that every 
voter casts one vote which counts for the candidate des- 
ignated by him on the ballot and for his party, and 
except also that persons of property or college education 
have the privilege of voting three separate ballots instead 
of the one ballot allowed to the other citizens. 



I The Referendum, Initiative and Right of Recall 

If proportional representation is designed to give to 
each political group of citizens a representation in govern- 
ment in accordance with its numbers, the Referendum 
seeks to maintain the representatives under the constant 
control of their electors. By the "Referendum" is meant 
the right to compel the legislature to submit to the vote 
fii the entire people any law, ordinance or other question 



r 278 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



P 



to be adopted, ratified or rejected at the polls. Where 
the referendum is in vogue, it is usually set in motion by 
the petition of a certain number of voters, ordinarily from 
five to ten per cent. If such petition is presented to the 
legislature within a specified time after the passage of a 
certain act or measure, say within two or three months, the 
act or measure in question is submitted to a popular vote, 
and the decision of the voters seals its fate. The Referen- 
dum was introduced in Switzerland in the early part of the 
nineteenth century, it was largely extended by the constitu- 
tion of 1874, and has since become an established feature 
in that progressive little republic. It has also been adopted 
in four states of the Union, and it is the uniform method of 
amending state constitutions in ail states but one. It is 
also often resorted to in the local politics of many cities in 
America, Europe and Australia. 

The benefits of the Referendum as practiced in Switzer- 
land are stated by Mr. John A. Hobson in this lan- 
guage:— 

"i. It provides a remedy for intentional or uninten- 
tional misrepresentation on the part of elected legislatures 
and secures laws conformable to the actual will of the 
majority. 

"2. It enhances the popular confidence in the stability 
of law. 

"3. It eliminates much waste of political energy by 
enabling proposals of unknown value to be submitted 
separately to a quantitative test." 

Yet the greatest service of all is the training in the art 
of self-government which the referendum gives. Says Mr. 
Hobson : — 

"It may indeed be questioned whether a people whose 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 



279 



f direct contribution to self-government consists in a single 
vote cast at intervals of several years, not for a policy or 
even for a measure, but for a party or a personality, can 
be or is capable of becoming a genuinely self-governing 
people. Some amount of regular responsibility for con- 
crete acts of conduct is surely as essential to the education 
of a self-reliant people as of a self-reliant individual." ' 
L And Mr. Curti, for many years a member of the Swiss 
' Parliament, sums up his own experience as follows : — 
"I am certain that the Referendum has prevented but 
little of the good we might have done, but it has averted 
many evils if only by the fact that it always stood wamingly 
fc before us. I should say that it does not condemn democ- 
I racy to a standstill, despite its occasional retrogressive 
I movements, but that it lends steadiness to progress itself." ' 
[ The Referendum, beneficial as its operations may be, 
I is not eSective to secure the dommion of the popular will 
I over the representative legislatures without the aid of 
i another modem political weapon — the Popular Initia- 
tive. 

The Initiative is "the right of a certain percentage of 
the voters, usually five to ten per cent, to propose a law, 
ordinance or constitutional amendment for action by the 
legislature or decision at the polls or both." * If the 
proposed measure is acted upon favorably by the legisla- 
ture, that disposes of it, but if the legislature fails to enact 
it, it must be submitted to a popular vote for adoption or 
rejection. 

' Quoted from Equity, Philadelphia, for January, igoS. 

' TliBodor Curti, "Die Resultate dcs Schweizerischen Referendums," 
Stuttgart, 1898, p. 48, 
I ' "A Primer of Direct Legislation," The Arena, Trenton, New 
kjersey, 1906, p. S. 



S8o 



SOaALISM AND REFORM 



The Referendum alone is merely designed to prevent 
mischievous legislation, for its workings are negative; the 
Initiative enables the people to force positive legislation. 
The Referendum and Initiative complement each other, 
and in a majority of cases they have been adopted together 
and as parts of the same political system. 

The Right of Recall is the right of the constituents of 
any public oflicial to withdraw him from office before the 
expiration of his elective or appointive term. This right 
is based on the theory that in a democracy every public 
official is the agent of the people, and may be discharged 
by the latter at any time and for any reason. 

The Eight of Recall is usually exercised by a petition 
for the removal of the objectionable representative or offi- 
cial, signed by a large number of voters within the district 
from which he has been elected. Upon stich petition new 
elections are ordered, and the name of the objectionable 
incumbent is submitted to the voters together with the 
names of any new candidates, so as to give to the voters 
the opportunity to retain him in office or to recall him. 

The system has been introduced in Switzerland, in 
several municipalities of the state of California, and re- 
cently in the city of Seattle, Washington. It is not as 
popular as the Referendum and the Initiative, and the 
adoption of the latter often tends to make the measure 
superfluous, at least so far as regards legislative repre- 



The socialists advocate all political reforms which have 
for their object the democratization of the modem state, 
and that not only on account of their general desire for 
political progress, but also for the special reason that such 
reforms are indispensable for the progress and success of 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 28 1 

the socialist movement. All restrictions on popular suf- 
frage are primarily designed to disfranchise the property- 
less working class, the main source of the political strength 
of socialism, and all methods of disproportionate repre- 
sentation work most disastrously on minority parties and 
new political movements. 
The social democrats of Germany under Lassalle's 
I leadership entered the political arena with the motto of un- 
restricted suSrage for all adult citizens, and that motto has 
remained the battle cry of militant socialism in all coun- 
tries of restricted suffrage. In Austria, Russia, Belgium 
and Sweden, the socialists have been the leading spirits 
of all movements for suffrage extension, and in other coun- 
tries they have often been its sole champions. 

Socialism and Woman Suffrage 

A similarly unmistakable stand have the socialists 
always maintained on the subject of woman suffrage. 
"As soon as the Socialist Party was bom," attests Mrs. 
Zetkin, " it adopted the demand of equal rights for man and 
woman in its pohtical program. The social democracy 
is the organization of woman suffrage par excellence in 
Germany. In the many thousands of meetings in which 
the party year after year proclaims its theories and explains 
its program, the justice of woman suffrage is always em- 
phasized. The proletarian movement of women especially 
has repeatedly unfolded all over the empire an exclusive 
propaganda in favor of the fullest and highest political 
rights of the female sex. Bebel, von Vollmar and other 
socialist representatives have time and time again made 
earnest pleas for woman suffrage in the General German 



' 382 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



Diet and in the different provincial diets. And t&e 
democracy has not satisfied itself with mere talk in 
of woman suffrage. It has repeatedly proposed pc 
legislation on that subject. As the first and, up to the 
present, the only political party of Germany, the Social 
Democrats already in 1S95 offered a resolution in the Ira- 
perial Diet which declared that all elections to Parliament 
and to the provincial diets should be based on the universal, 
equal, direct and secret vote of all adult citizenSj without 
distinction of sex." ' 

For the socialist movement the demand for woman 
suffrage is not a mere sentimental proposition of abstract 
justice. The working woman has become so large and 
important a factor in modem industrial life that the work- 
ingman can hardly carry on his economic and politicaJ 
struggles without her cooperation. For the upper and 
middle class woman suffrage is a convenience and an 
advantage; for the woman of the working class it is an 
immediate material necessity. 

It is for this reason that the breach between the bour- 
geois "suffragists" and the working women advocates of 
suffrage is constantly deepening. The suffragists of the 
upper and middle classes favor woman suffrage qualified 
by a property test because such test would not exclude them 
from voting, and also because they regard such limited 
suffrage as a partial victory for the general principle of 
woman suffrage. 

The proletarian suffragettes, on the other hand, see in 
such qualified woman suffrage only a means of strengthen- 
ing the political power of the possessing classes, thus cor- 

' Clara Zetkin, "Zur Frage des Frauenwahlrecht?," Berlin, 1907, 



THE POLITICAL REFORM MOVEMENTS 2S3 

respondingly diminishing the political strength of the 
property less working class. 

The question of woman suffrage was thoroughly ex- 
amined by the last International Socialist Congress held 
at Stuttgart in 1907, and the resolution adopted on the 
subject thus defines the socialist attitude towards the gen- 
eral movement for woman suffrage : — 

"It is the duty of socialist parties of all countries to 
agitate most energetically for the introduction of imiversal 
womanhood suffrage. The socialist parties repudiate 
limited woman's suffrage as an adulteration of, and a 
caricature upon, the principle of political equality of the 
female sex. It fights for the sole living concrete expression 
of this principle ; namely, universal womanhood suffrage, 
which should belong to all women of age and not be con- 
ditioned by property, taxation, education, or any other 
qualification which would exclude members of the laboring 
classes from the enjoyment of this right. The socialist 
women should not carry on this struggle for complete equal- 
ity of right of vote in alliance with the middle-class women 
suffragists, but in common with the socialist parties, which 
insist upon woman suffrage as one of the fundamental 
and most important reforms for the full democratization 
of political franchise in general." 



ADUmiSTSATIVE HEFOKUS 

In the last chapter we dealt with such reforms as affect 
' primarily the character of government. Here we will con- 
sider some reforms bearing on the functions of government 
and the manner of their discharge, and for lack of a more 
expressive term, we wilt designate these by the common 
title of " administrative reforms." 

Under this head we will examine three significant move- 
ments of recent times: the movements for government 
ownership of certain industries, for the shifting of the 
burden of taxation on the possessing classes, and for the 
abolition of standing armies. The three movements are 
but loosely related among themselves, and the socialist 
attitude to them is different in each case. 

Government Owmrship 

The movement for the transfer of ownership in certain 
industries of a public or quasi-public nature, such as rail- 
roads, telegraphs, telephones, street cars, waterworks and 
gas works, to the central government or to municipal 
governments, has made very substantial progress within 
the last few decades, and its ideas have found very extended 
application. Switzerland, Belgium and the Australian 
colonies, Prussia and Russia own the greater part of the 
railroads of those countries ; in Saxony all railroading 
284 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 285 

is government monopoly, and in Austria, Holland and 
Norway the governments are gradually and steadily absorb- 
ing the private lines. All of these countries began with 
private ownership of the roads, and gradually transferred 
such ownership to the government. 
Still more marked is that process in the case of the tele- 
I graph, "With the exception of the sale of the experimen- 
I tal line from Washington to Baltimore," says Professor 
Parsons, "no country has changed from public to private 
I ownership, but every country in the world that began with 
I private telegraphs has changed to public ownership, except 
Bolivia, Canada, Cuba, Cyprus, Hawaii, Honduras and 
I the United States." ' 

Germany, Bulgaria and some of the Australian colonies 
introduced their first telephones as government monopolies, 
and have retained them as such, while Great Britain, 
Belgium, Austria, France, Switzerland, Sweden and 
I Norway have acquired all or portions of the telephone 
I systems of their country from the original private owners. 
The field of municipal ownership is even more ex- 
I tensive than that of national ownership. Municipal 
I ownership of water and gas works is practically the rule 
in most countries of Europe, and in the United States more 
than half of the cities and towns own their own water- 
works, and several cities have acquired their gas works. 

Municipal street railways have received the largest 
extension in Great Britain, where the municipalities own 
and operate more than 40 per cent of the total mileage. 
The movement for the transfer of all privately owned street 
cars to the municipal governments has of late met with 

' Frank Parsooa, "The City (or the People," Equity Series, Phila- 
delphia, 19D1, p. 207. 



286 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



more or less substantial success in all modem coun? 

except the United States. 

From the fact that socialism advocates the public owner- 
ship of all means of production, and that its political pro- 
gram demands the national ownership of railways and 
telegraphs, and the municipal ownership of street cars 
and gas and water works, the inference is often drawn that 
the growth of government ownership as here described is a 
direct or indirect achievement of the socialist movement. 
This notion is as erroneous as it is widespread and popu- 
lar. The socialists do not claim any credit for the pres- 
ent-day institutions of government ownership, nor have 
they any illusions as to their significance and benefits. 
Government ownership under the present regime does not 
represent an advanced phase of industrial development 
or the climax of industrial concentration. It is in no sense 
an installment of the socialist cooperative republic. 

National ownership of railroads, telegraphs and tele- 
phones has been in most cases introduced by the govern- 
ments for reasons of military expediency or for the sake 
of revenue. In other cases it was brought about as a con- 
cession to the interests of the middle classes. 

Similarly, municipal ownership, where not brought 
about by a socialist administration, is as a rule but a de- 
vice for municipal revenue. Government ownership, both 
national and municipal, has some very decided advantages 
over private ownership, and on the whole, it assures better 
service to the public and better treatment of the employees. 
But these advantages are to a large extent offset by the 
fact that government ownership tends to strengthen the 
powers of the modern class state, and to curtail the freedom 
of combination and coalition on the part of the e 



■ ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 287 

What the socialists demand is not government owner- 
ship, but public ownership, and the distinction is very 
material under present conditions, as pointed out by 
Professor Parsons, who says ; ~- 

"Public ownership and government ownership are by 
no means synonymous. Where legislative power is per- 
verted to private piu-poses — where the spoils system 
prevails and the offices are treated as private property — 
where government is managed in the interests of a few 
individuals or of a class, anything that is in the control of 
the government is really private property, although it 
may be called public property. If councils and legisla- 
tures are masters instead of the people, they are likely to 
use the streets and franchises for private gain instead of the 
public good. If the government is a private monopoly, 
everything m the hands of the government is a private 
monopoly." ' 

In fact, the movement for the national or municipal 
ownership of public utilities is the most striking illustra- 
tion of a reform movement which may be revolutionary 
or retrogressive according to the source from which it 
emanates. 

The socialists of all countries favor the municipaliza- 
tion or nationalization of public utilities, but that only as 
a measure to be carried out by an administration controlled 
or at least strongly influenced by the working class. 
Their demand for municipal or national ownership of the 
industries mentioned is coupled with the further demand 
for the democratic administration of those industries, and 
for their management in the interests of the employees 
and the public- On the other hand, the most reactionary 
I ' "The City for the People," p. 17. 



SOCULISM AND REFORM 



capitalist governments may utilize it for the purpose oi 
strengthening their grip on the pieople, and the middle-class 
apostles of municipal or national ownership of the type 
of Hearst or Bryan in the United States or the "radical" 
bourgeois parties of Europe, see in it primarily a means of 
decreasing the taxes of property owners and reducing the 
rates of freight, transportation and communication for 
the smaller business men. 

In Germany, where the socialists have had ample oppor- 
tunity to watch the practical workii^ of government 
ownership, th^ passed judgment on the institution in the 
following terse resolution adopted at their annual con-J 
vention of 1 892 : — I 

" State socialism, so-called, inasmuch as it aims at statel 
ownership for fiscal purposes, seeks to substitute the state 
for the pri\ate capitalist, and to confer on it the power to 
subject the people to the double yoke of economic e^loi- 
tation and political slavery." 



Tax Reforms 



The support of the modern state in all its branches, civfl 
and military, involves the expenditure of immense funds, 
and the problem of raising these funds has ever been the 
hardest bone of contention between the governments and 
the governed. All moneys tor the support of the govern- 
ment necessarily come from the people in the form of taxes, 
and the distribution of the burden of taxation among the 
various classes of the population always depends on the 
methods employed in its levying. 

The two main contending methods of taxation are the 
direct and the indirect. A direct tax is a tax imposed 



1 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 289 

the very person of the citizen who is expected to pay it, 
and one that cannot be shifted by him; an indirect tax 
is a tax on real estate or commodities, formally imposed on 
the owner, manufacturer or merchant, but actually borne 
by the tenant or consumer. Instances of the first class 
are the poll tax, the income tax and the inheritance tax; 
instances of the latter class are the real property tax, the 
import duties on raw material or manufactm-ed goods of 
foreign importation, and the excise duties on articles of 
domestic manufacture, such as tobacco, liquors, etc. 

The ruling classes and the modern state as a rule favor 
the indirect tax, while the socialists have always been 
strongly opposed to it. 

"The indirect tax is the instrument through which the 
bourgeoisie brings about the complete exemption from 
taxation of capital, and burdens the poorer classes of 
society with all the expenses of the state government," 
asserted Ferdinand Lassalle in his famous " Workingraen's 
Program" hi 1862, and this conception is still the generally 
accepted socialist view on the subject. The socialists have 
always consistently advocated the system of direct taxa- 
tion, and among the most universal planks of their practical 
political programs are the demands for a progressive in- 
come tax and a progressive inheritance tax. 

A progressive income tax is a direct tax levied upon the 
excess income of each citizen above a certain minimum, 
and progressively graded according to the size of the in- 
come. The tax has the merit of placing the onus of main- 
taining the government upon the classes who derive the 
greatest benefits from it and who can bear the burden with 
the greatest ease. 

In England the progressive income tax was first Intro- 



l29o 



SOaALlSM AND REFORM 



duced in the period of the Napoleonic wars as a temporary 
makeshift, but the system has since established itself in 
the country firmly, and the revenue from that source was 
almost ;£36,ooo,ooo in 1902. From England the progres- 
sive income tax has spread to Italy, Switzerland, Germany, 
Austria, Hungary, Denmark, Holland and Australia. 
France at present taxes only the incomes of corporations 
and business associations, but a general and rather high 
income tax is now proposed by the government. In the 
United States a progressive income tax was in force, and 
yielded excellent results during the closing years of tiie 
Civil War, and until 1S72, when it was repealed. In 1S94, 
a new income tax law was passed by Congress, but the 
law was declared unconstitutional and void by the Supreme 
Court, the far-reaching decision having been rendered by 
a vote of 5 to 4, after one of the justices had changed his 
expressed views on the question. Several states of the 
Union, however, levy an income tax on their citizens. 

A progressive inheritance tax is a tax on those acquiring 
property by inheritance or by will. The tax is sometimes 
levied only on collateral heirs, and usually it is progres- 
sively graded either in accordance with the size of the in- 
heritance or with the degree of remoteness of the relation- 
ship between the deceased and the heir, or both. 

The progressive inheritance tax, and especially the col- 
lateral inheritance tax, furnish large parts of the state 
revenues in most of the Australian colonies and in Switzer- 
land, where the tax is in some cases as high as twenty per 
cent of the estate. England, Germany, France, Austria, 
Italy, Spain, Belgium, Holland, Denmark, Switzerland, 
Russia, Roumania, Australia, Canada, and most of the 
states of the Union, all have inheritance taxes, but in most 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 



291 

, the tax 



of these countries except France and Australia 
rate is rather insignificant. 

Socialism does not consider the direct income and inher- 
itance taxes within the frame of modern capitalist society 
as a means of equalizing the distribution of wealth, but it 
favors them as effective mstruments for the abolition of 
indirect taxes, which diminish the purchasing power of 
the working class and lower its standard of life. 



The "Single Tax" 

Another movement of tax reform which has developed 
considerable strength within the last quarter of a century, 
especially in the English-speaking countries, is that based 
on the so-called Single-Tax theory. 

The theory was first fully and clearly formulated by 
Henry George in his famous work " Progress and Poverty," 
published in 1879, and it has since been elaborated and 
restated in numerous books, pamphlets and periodicals. 

The principal features of the proposed reform are tersely 
stated by the originator of the movement himself in the 
following language: — 

"We propose to abolish all taxes save one single tax 
levied on the value of land, irrespective of the value of 
improvements in or on it. 

"What we propose is not a tax on real estate, for real 
estate includes improvements. Nor is it a tax on land, for 
we would not tax all land, but only land having a value 
irrespective of its improvements, and would tax that in 
proportion to that value. 

" Our tax involves the imposition of no new tax, since 
we already tax land values in taxing real estate. To carry 



SOCIAUSM AND REFORM 



it out we have only to abolish all taxes save the tax on real 

estate and to abolish all of that which now falls on build- 
ings or improvements, leaving only that part of it whicfi 
now falls on the value of the bare land. This we would 
increase so as to take as nearly as may be the whole of the 
economic rent, or what is sometimes styled the ' unearned 
increment of land values.' " ' 

This single tax on land values is proposed by Mr. George 
and his followers not merely as an improvement on the pre- 
vailing methods of taxation, but as a cure of all social 
evils of our times. 

The root and source of all human poverty and misery, 
" according to the conception of the single taxers, lies in the 
fact that the valuable land in all civilized countries is 
monopolized by a comparatively small class of landowners, 
who appropriate all benefits derived from it, and impose a 
high tax for its use and occupation in the form of rent. 

This system makes it possible for a number of men to 
hold large areas of land for speculative purposes, thus with- 
drawing it from actual use. And as land is in the last 
analysis the source of all wealth, the withholding of any 
part of it results in the curtailment of wealth production 
for the nation. 

Furthermore, so long as land was free to all, everybody 
could gain his subsistence by agriculture or by industrial 
pursuits on a small scale, but so soon as land becomes 
private property, it is only the man who can afford to pay 
a high rent — the capitalist — who can engage in any 
industry, while the poor man is compelled to sell his labor 
for the best price obtainable. 

t' Henry George in "Financial Reform Almanach" of England tor the 
year 1891. 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 



293 



And lastlyj 1 



, bein 



1 arbib 



1 produ( 



auction, 

it draws from the profits of capital and wages of labor 
alike, impoverishes both, gives rise to industrial crises, 
and produces an unjust distribution of wealth which is 
building up immense fortunes in the hands of a few while 
the masses grow relatively poorer and poorer. 

"The taxation of the processes and products of labor 
on the one hand," says Mr. George, in the article already 
mentioned, " and the insufficient taxation of land values 
on the other, produces an unjust distribution of wealth 
which is building up, in the hands of a few, fortunes more 
monstrous than the world has ever before seen, while the 
masses of our people are steadily becoming relatively 
poorer. These taxes necessarily fall on the poor more 
heavily than on the rich; by increasing prices, they neces- 
sitate larger capital in all business, and consequently give 
an advantage to large capitals ; and they give, and in some 
cases are designed to give, special advantages and mo- 
nopolies to combinations and trusts. On the other hand, 
the insufficient taxation of land values enables men to 
make large fortunes by land speculation and the increase 
in ground values — fortunes which do not represent any 
addition by them to the general wealth of the community, 
but merely the appropriation by some of what the labor 
of others creates. 

"This unjust distribution of wealth develops on the one 
hand a class idle and wasteful, because they are too rich, 
and on the other band a class Idle and wasteful, because 
they are too poor — it deprives men of capital and oppor- 
tunities which would make them more efficient producers." 

It is the conviction of the disciples of Henry George 
that a single tax on land values as advocated by them would 



294 



SOCULISM AND REFORM 



gradually lead to the abolition of private ownership 
land. 
The only country in which some general application of ■ 

the tax on land values has been attempted is New Zealand, 
and while it is claimed by the friends of the reform that the 
system has on the whole had a stimulating and beneficial 
effect on the industries of the country and has succeeded 
in curbing wild land speculation, predicted benefits of a 
fundamental character have so far failed to materialize. 
It must be added, however, in justice to the advocates o£ 
the measures, that the New Zealand system of land taxa- 
tion is by no means a full application of the single-tax 
theory. On the other hand, at least one of its principli 
that of taxing vacant and unused land most heavily, has 
of late found direct or indirect recognition in the systems 
of taxation of several countries, states and municipalities. 

The socialists have but little sympathy for the single- 
tax theory. They do not agree with the economic premises 
on which it is based, and they consider the proposed reform 
as entirely impotent to cope with the evils which it seeks 
to combat, and in some respects even as distinctly reac- 
tionary. 

The single-tax philosophy was evolved by Henry George 
a generation ago in the then little developed far West, 
and it is entirely adapted to the industrial conditions 
which surrounded him at the time. It presupposes a 
system of industry based mainly on agriculture and small 
manufacture, and is sadly out of place in a system o£ 
gigantic factories. 

Land values occupy but a secondary position in modem 
industrial wealth. If the up-to-date large capitalist were 
to be taxed on the value of his factory site to the full extent 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 29S 

of its rental income, but be relieved from all taxes on the 
factory buildings, implements, stock and other property 
and income, he would practicaUy escape taxation. On 
the other hand, an accessible or even free factory site would 
not enable the propertyless wage worker to equip a costly 
modern plant and to set up in business on his own account 
in competition with his present employer. It is the private 
ownership of the machine, even more than the private 
ownership of land, that holds the working class in bondage. 

The single taxer recognizes but one form of economic 
exploitation — rent. The socialist, on the other hand, 
asserts that the source of all exploitation is the "surplus 
value" (the unpaid part of the workingman's labor) from 
which all rent as well as interest and profit are derived. 

The single taxer would abolish the landlord, the monop- 
ohst of "land values," but continue the existence of the 
capitalist and wage worker ; the socialist strives to wipe 
out all class distinction and to introduce complete economic 
equality. The single-tax theory professes to be an ab- 
solute and scientific truth applicable to all ages and con- 
ditions alike, while socialism professes to be a theory grow- 
ing out of modern economic conditions, and expecting its 
realization from the steadily growing concentration and 
socialization of industry. The single taxer, lastly, is an 
earnest supporter of the competitive system of industry, 
while the socialist is as ardent a coHectivist. 

Thus the two social theories difier very materially in 
their views, aims, and methods.' 

' Compare, Morris Hillquit, "HiEtory of Socialism in Ihe United 
Stales," 4th Edition, New York, 1906, pp. 373, etc.; also A. M. Simons, 
"Single Tai vs. Socialism," Chicago, 1899. 



SOQALISM AND REFORM 



Abolition of Standing Armies 

One of the greatest evils of the modem state is the 
standing army. Capitalist society cannot be maintained 
without a host of soldiers. In their world-wide competi- 
tive struggles, the capitalists of each coimtry strive not 
only to preserve and extend their own markets, but also 
to invade those of the rival nations and to conquer new 
markets. This feature of the modern capitalist system 
of production and exchange inevitably leads to clashes I 
between competing nations, and the specter of war is ever 
hovering among them. The modern capitalist state is 
powerless without a strong army or navy. It must always 
be ready for offensive and defensive military action, and it 
must always make a display of military strength to curb 
the bellicose designs of its neighbors. It must prepare for 
war, if it wants war ; it must prepare for war, if it wants ' 
peace. 

A strong army moreover has within recent times become j 
essential to the maintenance of capitalist government for ' 
another reason and for another purpose. With the in- 
creasing intensity of capitalist exploitation, the outbreaks 
of revolt on the part of the working masses tend to become 
more violent and frequent, and where these outbreaks are 
of such a character that the local authorities are either 
powerless to cope with them, or disinclined to interfere 
with them, the army is the most effective instrument for 
their suppression. To the capitalist government the army 
is an organization for the protection of the ruling classes 
from "all enemies, foreign and domestic," and the pro- 
tection from "the domestic enemy" is often its more im- 
portant function. 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 



Russia 


1,500,000 


France 


746,000 


Germany . 


650,000 


Great Britain 


550,000 


Austria 


470,000 


Italy .... 


290,000 



The vast dimensions of the standing armies of the most 
powerful countries of Europe are shown by the following 
figures : — 

^^^* And even in the United States, which up to recent times 
has been practically free from the curse of militarism, the 
development of industry and foreign commerce and the 
growth of the class struggles have of late years given rise 
to a movement on the part of the ruling classes to increase 
and strengthen the army and navy. The recent military 
law of the United States Congress aims to consolidate the 
federal troops and the various state militia organizations 
into a standing army of 250,000 soldiers, while the agita- 
tion for a huge navy is steadily increasing. 

The military and naval organizations of the modem 
states are an intolerable economic drain upon the nation. 
The "Nouveau Manuel du Soldat," taking the statistics 
of the year 1899 as the basis of calculation, figures the 
loss of productive value caused by militarism in Europe 
as follows : — 

The total military expenses of the European powers for 
1899 were $1,436,864,218. In the same year those coun- 
tries had in the field 4,i69,32r men, who, if employed 
at productive work, would produce every day, at an 
average of only 60 cents per day per man, a total of 
$2, 501, 592,6a Europe had in its armies 710,342 horses 



SOaALISM AND REFORM 



which could produce $284,136,80 per day at an aVa 
production of 40 cents per day. The expenditures and 
wasted productive values of the army upon that basis thus 
amounted to $2,272,533,038 per year on the basis of 300'J 
worliing days ! 

This burden hasvasUy grown since 1899. In Germany! 
alone the military budget has increased from about ' 
920,000,000 marks in 1899 to i ,300,000,000 in 1906-1907. 
Karl Liebknecht estimates the present total military cost of J 
Europe at 13,000,000,000 marks, or about $3,250,000,0001 
per year.' 

The standing armies and the navies are besides a pro 
li&c source of general bnitalization and demoralization c 
the people. 

By drafting the young men of the nation into the army, I 
the state withdraws from tJic productive ranks of the pop- I 
ulation its most vigorous and useful members, compels the I 
rest of the people to support them in useless idleness during J 
their protracted term of service, and at the expiration of tlie I 
term it sets them adrift, often with crippled minds, cor- I 
rupted morals and impaired social usefulness. 

" When, after a satisfactory test, the young man becomes I 
a soldier in the standing army," observes Vaillant, "he ' 
ceases to be a citizen. In order that he may become a 
passive instrument in the hands of his superior, he is de- 
prived of all civil functions and political rights upon enter- 
ing the miUtary life. For him there is no right and no- 
law. He is merely a thing of the military state. It is the 
rule without exception, the rule established in order that it 
may not be tempered by the possible humaneness of the 



' Dr. Karl Liebknecht, ' 
08, p. 43. 



lilitaiismus uad Antimilitarismus," Zurich, 



ADMINISTRATIVE REFORMS 



299 



superior officer. The military rule takes possession of the 
young man and arbitrarily disposes of his actions, his 
liberty, his life. If the brutality and arrogance of the 
officer do not break his resistance and wOl, he is tried, con- 
victed, sent to prison or to death by a court martial. This 
is 'justice' for him, these are the tribunals where his 
superiors, constituting themselves his judges and exe- 
cutioners, take their revenge for his lack of discipline. In 
fact, it is necessary that the army be entirely separated from 
the people, so that it may serve against it, against the work- 
ing class, as the police force and bodyguards of the capi- 
talist class and the government. For this purpose, es- 
pecially in an army through which all the children of the 
working class pass, it is necessary that a discipline of terror 
and of death steady the arm of the soldier in civil as well 
as in foreign war." ' 

The rapid lempo of technical progress in all matters of 
military organization and equipments leads to constant 
revolutions in the system of armament and forces upon the 
nations burdens which exhaust their material strength. 
The governments of the principal countries of Europe 
seem almost to have the sole function of securing and feed- 
ing their soldiers, and the tremendous growth of the national 
debts and indirect taxes necessitated by the standing armies 
has brought many countries to the verge of national 
bankruptcy. It was this state of affairs which compelled 
the youthful czar of Russia in 1898 to emit his desperate 
cry for universal limitation of armament, which was eu- 
phemistically styled a "peace message," and it is this con- 
dition of things which accounts for the modem "peace 
conferences" of the governments. 
! Edouard Vaillinl, "Suppression de I'Amiee Permanente," Paris, p. 12. 



I 300 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



i 



The working class, which furnishes the large bulk ofl 
army and contributes the greater part of the funds for its 
support, is naturally opposed to all wars and standing 
armies, and the socialists, as the political spokesmen of 
that class, have always carried on a strenuous propaganda 
against wars and standing armies. But socialists have 
but little enthusiasm for the official "peace conferences" 
held under the auspices of the present governments. 
The object of these conferences is not to abolish stand- 
ing armies, but merely to decrease their size, and that not 
below the point required for the suppression of the "do- 
mestic enemy," the working class. 

Socialism stands for the abolition of all wars and all 
armies, but it recognizes that within the modem social sys- 
tem this is an unattainable ideal. The practical socialist 
program, therefore, advocates what the socialists consider 
the next best step, — introduction of a national demo- 
cratic militia system instead of that of the standing army. 

There is but one country in the world in which that 
system has found almost complete application, and that 
Gjuntry naturally is the one that may be called the experi- 
mental laboratory of all social reforms — Switzerland. 

The militia system was introduced in Switzerland in 
1874. Subsequently that system was supplemented by 
the institutions of the Landwekr and Landslurm. 

The militia proper, or the Elite, consists of all able-bodied 
male citizens between the ages of twenty and thirty-two 
years ; the Landwekr is composed of all men between the 
ages of thirty-two and forty-four years, while all citizens, 
between the ages of eighteen and fifty years, who for one 
cause or another do not belong to either of the two classes, 
constitute the Landsturm. J 



ADMINISTFATIVE REFORMS 



301 



The cavalry exercises every year, all other corps of the 
Elite, or active army, every two years, while the members 
of the Landwehr are called under arms for the purpose of 
military exercise and maneuvers once in four years. The 
Federal Council of the republic is the head of the army. 

In 1902 the total military forces of the Swiss militia 
were as follows : 153,649 in the Elite, 88|8r3 in the Land- 
wehr, and in the Landsturm, 43,368 soldiers under arms, 
and 237,275 in the non-armed or auxiliary service. In 
other words, the little republic with a population of about 
3,000,000 had an active army of 285,830 trained men, 
and in case of emergency could rely on 523,105 citizens for 
its defense. And the total military budget of Switzerland 
is less than thirty million francs per year. 

The militia system of Switzerland is the socialist model 
of existing military organization, though the socialists do 
not consider it perfect, and strongly advocate certain im- 
provements, especially the election of ofEicers and the mili- 
tary education and training of the youth as part of the 
general educational system. 

The militia system has been criticised as too cumber- 
some, irregular and scattered for offensive action, but in 
the eyes of the socialists this feature is one of its greatest 
merits. The militia is primarily an instrument for eelf- 
defense, Just as the standing army is mainly an insllru- 
ment of aggression. 

But the principal virtue of a true democratic militia is 
that it leaves the military power in the hands of the people 
and prevents the ruling classes from turning it into a tool 
of oppression and despotism. The only people that is 
really free is an armed people, and the people as such can 
be properly armed only under a general militia system. 



SOaALlSM AND REFORM 



P 



' I ask you to observe," said Edouard Vaillant, speaking 
in support of his bill for the introduction of the Swiss 
militia system in France, before the Chamber of Deputies, 
"that when we advocate the institution of militia, we do 
not pretend to propose a measure of socialism. The militia 
is the military organization of the city, which without dis- 
tinction between military and civi! functions, has become 
at once military and civil. It is the present city trans- 
ferred to the camp, it is the citizen-soldier, and the soldier- 
citizen, always a citizen in all his functions, be they mili- 
■tary or civil." And again: — 

"The armament of the people is the necessary comple- 
ment to universal suffrage and to the development of a true 
democracy. The militia has in all history been the in- 
stitution of democracy, appearing with its victories, dis- 
appearing with its defeats." '■ 

This positive side of the militia system, the arming and 

training of all male citizens, makes the reform of almost 

as great importance to the working class of the countries 

free from standing armies as to the workingmen in the 

, most military states. 

' "Suppression de I'Arm^e Permanente," pp. aj, a6. 




^^■sch 



The alarming growth of crime and vice in modem times 
has advanced a problem which society can no longer 
ignore. Up to very recent years the views of the good and 
virtuous people on the criminal and the prostitute were 
exceedingly definite and simple. The one was a mali- 
cious enemy of law and order, to be mercilessly run down 
and punished for his deliberate malefactions ; the other was 
a shameless creature, an outcast of society, to be loathed 
and despised. And it is only within the last decades that 
more sober views on the subject have begun to assert 
themselves. The application of scientific methods to the 
investigation of social phenomena was gradually extended 
to the domain of crime and vice. Attempts were made to 
discover their true nature, origin and causes and to devise 
rational methods for checking their growth. The new 
science of criminology was thus bom, and as is the case 
with every social science, especially during the period of its 
inception, several divergent schools of thought were soon 
developed within it. 

Of such modern schools of criminology the most popu- 
larly known and most sensational is that established by 
the famous Italian criminologist, Cesare Lombroso, the 
school of "criminal anthropology." The main doctrine 



304 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

of this school is that the criminal is distinguishable from 
the normal human being by certain physical and psychic 
peculiarities, which stamp him as an uotho deliquenle, 
delinquent man or bom criminal. 

These peculiarities are of an atavistic nature, and are 
either inherited or gradually acquired through a, definite 
process of physical degeneration. The proof of this 
theory rests on the results of extensive investigations into 
the family histories of numerous criminals, on physical 
measurements and autopsies of delinquents, and on fine 
observations of the general mental traits and moral con- 
ceptions of the criminal classes. The habitual criminals, 
according to these observations, as a rule spring from an 
ancestry tainted with drunkenness, epilepsy and insanity; 
they have no conception of right and wrong, and their 
physical construction and appearance show a reversion 
to the peculiarities of primitive men. 

Lombroso's theories were extended by the brilliant 
coterie of his disciples, and finally Dr. B. Tamowsky, of 
the St. Petersburg Military Medical Academy, transferred 
them from the field of crime to that of vice. To the type 
of the "bom criminal" was added that of the "born pros- 
titute," both possessing largely the same characteristics. 

The conception of the born criminal leads necessarily 
to that of the incurable criminal, and the school of criminal 
anthropology thus practically proclaims the hopelessness 
and futility of all social attempts to curb crime and vice. 
The doctrines of that school bear a close resemblance to 
the pseudo-scientific arguments of the old-time advocates 
of slavery and the modern opponents of woman's rights 
— all of them seek a sanction for revolting social conditions 
in the alleged physical inferiority of the vjctinqs of those 



SOaAL REFORM 



305 



conditions, and all of them fail to take into account the 
social and historical influences which contribute so largely 
to the development and modification of the physical, 
mental and moral type. 

A substantial improvement on the one-sided views of 
the school of Lombroso was introduced by the well-known 
Italian criminologist and socialist leader, Enrico Ferri.' 
Ferri admits the existence of a criminal type to be dis- 
tinguished by physical symptoms, but he regards such 
symptoms merely as evidence of pathological traits, in- 
herited or acquired, which predispose the subject to a 
career of crime. In his view such criminal inclinations are 
by no means irresistible — they may be overcome by other 
agencies. Ferri recognizes three main factors as causes of 
crime; the physico-psychical constitution of the individual, 
his natural environment, and his social environment. 
He distinguishes five different classes of criminals : — 

Born criminals, or persons with a hereditary taint 

I predisposing them to crime; 

. Insane criminals, or such who commit crimes while 

f insane; 

3. Criminals through passion; 

4. Criminals through circumsiances, whose crimes are 
I accidental and are due to their social surroundings, and 

5. Habitual criminals, who have become such after the 
first offense, through prison life and associations, and 
through the relentless persecutions of organized society. 

The last two classes, according to Ferri, embrace about 
75 per cent of all criminals. But the criminals through 
passion are also largely the products of the conditions of 
the modem struggle for existence, and even the bom a 
' "Crime as a Social PheriorDenon." 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



the insane criminal types are to a large extent developed 
by social conditions. 

"The anthropologist who recognizes the hereditary or 
acquired biological anomalies of these criminals," says he, 
"does not thereby deny the indirect social origin of the 
greater part of these anomalies themselves." ' 

Similar views are held by many eminent criminolo- 
gists, especially of the Italian school. The social cause of 
crime is still more emphasized by the "positive school of 
criminology," whose leading exponent is the well-known 
German criminologist, Franz von Liszt. That school 
does not ignore the individual characteristics of the crimi- 
nal as a factor in the commission of crime, but it attributes 
to them a secondary importance only, 

"The individual conditions of crime are often the 
direct products of its social conditions," observes von 
Liszt. "The misery of the masses is the fertile soil not 
only for the growth of crime itself, but also of that degen- 
eration based on hereditary taint which in its turn again 
leads to crime. . . . Every crime is the product on the 
one hand of the peculiarities of the individual criminal, 
and on the other, of the social conditions which surround 
the criminal at the time of the deed — in other words, 
it is the product of only one individual factor and of count- 
less soc'iai factors." 

And again : — 

"It is an established fact that a protracted industrial 
depression always results in the increase of crime generally, 
and especially of offenses against property, principally 
theft ; in the decrease of marriages and births of legitimate 

' Enrico Ferri, "Kriminelle Anthropologje und Soiialismua," Neue 
Zfit, 14th Year, Vol. II, No. 41, 



1 



SOaAL REFORM 



307 



children with a corresponding increase of illegitimate 
births ; in the rise in the infantile death-rate, the increase 
of suicides, the lowering of the average life and in a series of 
other disquieting phenomena. A close examination would 
show that the influence of industrial conditions on crimi- 
nality is more far-reaching than commonly supposed. 
Thus the geographical distribution of criminality in each 
country is largely based on the industrial conditions of 
the different sections of the country. . , . Thus also the 
strong increase of offenses against property in December, 
January and February may be accounted for by the de- 
creased opportunities for work in the cold season and the 
greater need of food, clothing and fuel. . , . The 'indus- 
trial conditions,' whose favorable or unfavorable influence 
on criminality must be primarily considered to-day, are the 
general condition of the working classes, not only their 
financial, but also their physical, mental, moral and politi- 

I cal condition." ' 

I The socialists most generally adhere to the views of 
von Liszt and the positive school of criminology. 

Crime and vice do not owe their existence to the modem 
capitalist society. Crimes against the person arc as old 
as human passion, and crimes against property and the vice 
of prostitution are probably as old as the institution of 
private property. But if capitalism has not created crime 
and vice, it has created the conditions for their wholesale 
development and ever increasing extension. For if the 
misery of the masses is the fertile soil of crime and vice, 
capitalism is the hothouse of popular misery. 

Whether crime and vice in their devastating triumphal 

' Quoted by Paul Hirsch in "Verbrechen und Prostitution als soiiale 
idtserscheinungen," ad Edition, Berlin, 1907, pp. la, 23. 



308 SOaALISM AND REFORM 

march brand the bodies and souls of their victims with 
visible marks of infamy, and whether they choose their 
victims in the prime of their lives, in their cradles or in 
their mothers' wombs, is a matter of liltie moment: the 
modern social relations are such that they cannot fail to 
produce destitution and physical and mental degeneracy 
and crime and vice as specific expressions of such destitu- 
tion and degeneracy. All conditions surrounding the 
modern workingman's family, and especially the family 
of the most poorly paid workingman, tend to drive its 
members to break the established social canons of law and 
morality. The exhausting labor of the workingmen and 
working women sap their physical and moral strength; 
their helpless and hopeless condition in cases of unem- 
ployment, sickness or physical disability render them des- 
perate ; their repulsive " homes " rob them of the sustaining 
influences of family life and drive them to drink and to the 
rude life of the street ; the heartless treatment of their em- 
ployers and of "organized society" as a whole makes them 
morose and embittered; their misery is so deep, their 
temptations are so strong, and their powers of resistance 
so weak, that it should be a matter of surprise that so many 
of them escape the clutches of crime or vice. 

And just as the heartless system of exploitation breeds 
crime and vice in the classes of the exploited, so does the 
senseless system of competition and the headlong race 
for profits breed the crimes so prevalent and growing in the 
ranks of the exploiters themselves : fraud, bribery, corrup- 
tion and numerous similar offenses. 

Crime and vice cannot be entirely eliminated from the 
capitalist system of society. They may be diminished, but 
not by police measures nor by prison methods, not by 



SOCIAL REFORM 



309 



"supervision nor by segregation, not by any system of 
punishment or moral preaching, but by removing the worst 
features of those social conditions that breed crime and 
vice. The socialists are by no means indifferent to the 
efforts to check the growth of crime and vice, but they recog- 
nize the absolute impotency of purely penal reforms to 
accomplish that end, and they see the only remedy against 
the dreadful double scourge of human society in the 
realization of their general program of industrial and 
social reform. 



I Intemperance 

* Intemperance as such is not a modem problem. The use 
and abuse of alcoholic drinks are as old as written history, 
and the movement to combat the evil dates back several 
centuries. 

The first temperance society is said to have been founded 
by Margrave Frederick V in 1600, and it is instructive to 
learn that the noble members of that society were bound 
by a pledge, good for two years, not to drink more than 
seven bumpers of wine with any meal, nor more than four- 
teen bumpers a day. They were, however, permitted to 
quench any surplus of thirst with beer and to drink one 
glass of whisky on the side. By this ideal of abstention 
may be gauged the ordinary drinking habits of our fore- 
fathers in the good old times when knighthood was in 
flower. 

But on the whole, drinking in those times seems to have 
been the sport of the nobles rather than the vice of the 



1 whisky 



It was only with the advent of the cheap c 



SOCIALISM AKD KOOSM 



I 



in the sixteenth century thaX_ Etrong alcobolir -^hi' n' 1 4|y S- 
'becajnc accessible to the rising class of the jupletariat, 
and since that time the dnnk habit among tbcworking 
people has grown so enormously that alcohotism h^s be- 
come a [.foblem of the modern labor movcmEnt. 

The use of alcohol affects the poor much more injuri- 
ously than the men of the wealthier classes, cvea tbougfa^ie 
latter may be addicted lo it no less than the former, The^ 
ni-nourtshcd and weak organism of the workingman offeis 
but little resistance to the ravishing eSects of alcohoL The 
workingman will often succumb to a quantity of tbeLbo'££-r 
age which will not disturb the equilibrium of a maJl.Q£ t**" 
better-situated classes. ■ 

Moreover, the workingman's income is as a rule barej ^ ■ 
■nfficient to cover the necessaries of Bis IiTeT He can pro- ■ 
cure his drink only by depriving himself of more sub- ■ 
atanlial nourishment, thus undermining his body in two I 
directions. I 

On the whole it may be truthfully said that int^eper- I 
ancc is one of the heaviest scourges of the working class ■ 
and one of the greatest obstacles to all progressive labor I 
movements and to socialism. I 

"^The excessive use of alcohol enfeebles and brulalizes I 
large masses of the workingmen. It renders them incap- ■ 
able of study, training and organization, indifferent to I 
the struggles of their class, and inaccessible to its aspira- I 
tions and ideals. I 

The alcoholic habits of the working class are deeply I 
rooted in the material condition's of their lives. They are M 
largely caused and stimulated by their industrial and social I 
surroundings. fl 

Mr. Emanuel Wurm, in an able report on Alcoholism I 



^ ' 

w 



SOCIAL REFORM 31 1 

before the German Social Democratic Convention of 1907,' 
mentions the following causes which combine to stimulate 
drinking among the workers : — 

1. The dwelling conditions of the poor. 

Says Frederick Engels on this point : " Rctummg from 
the factory, the workingman finds a home without any 
comforts, damp, unattractive and filthy; he stands in 
need of exhilaration ; he must have something to make his 
work worth while, to make the prospects of the morrow 
tolerable. . . . His social instinct can find satisfaction 
only in the liquor saloon ; he has no other place to meet 
his friends." 

2. Mental exhaustion caused by overwork. 

Modem factory work with its monotonous operations is 
bound to produce a condition of mental fatigue from which 
the worker is but too apt to seek refuge in alcoholic stimu- 
lants. 

3. Conditions of work creating an abnormal thirst. 

Under this head come the industries in which the em- 
ployees are forced to work under a high temperature, or in 
which the shops are constantly filied with line particles 
of dust, or in which the nature of the work generates offen- 
sive fumes and gases. 

4. Insufficient and unwholesome nourishment. 

"The whisky habit is not the cause but the result of 
misery," said Justus v, Liebig, as early as in 1860. " It is 
an exception to the rule when a well -nourished man be- 
comes addicted to whisky. But when a man earns less 
than is required for the quantum of food necessary in 

"Protokoll Ubec die Verhandlungen des Parteitaga der Sozialderao- 
kratischen Parte! Deulschlands," abgehalten zu Essen, September, 1907, 
pp. 345. olc. 



312 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



order to restore his labor power, he is compelled by rigid 
and inexorable necessity to seek refuge in whisky," ' 

The insufBcient nourishment of the workingman is due 
to low wages, high food prices, and also to the unskillful 
preparation of his food. The workingman's wife has as a 
rule never bad an opportunity to cultivate the household 
arts, and seldom has the time to practice them. 

Various other causes contribute to develop the drink 
habit among workingmen, most of them having their roots 
in the modem industrial conditions. And as is the case 
with almost all social evils of the day, the cause and effect 
of alcoholism move in a seemingly unbreakable vicious 
circle — misery causes drunkenness, drunkenness increases 
misery. 

For a long time the socialists of all countries were rather 
indifferent to the temperance movement. They were fully 
alive to the dangers of the evil habit for the working 
class, but they had little faith in the cures offered by the 
ideological temperance advocates. High taxes on spiritu- 
ous liquors, wherever tried, have failed to check the drink- 
ing evil and have only resulted in greater inroads on the 
meager budget of the working families. Prohibition has 
proved as impotent to cope with the evil, and as a rule 
has only served to encourage smugglhig and illicit stills. 
Nor were the socialists inclined to expect substantial 
results from a purely moral crusade against alcoholism. 
The generally accepted socialist view was that the evils 
of alcoholism could be lessened only by the betterment 
of the material conditions of the workers, and could be 
removed only with the abolition of the wage system. 

" As every other evil of the capitalist mode of production, 
' Quoted by Wurin in report mentioned. 



SOCIAL REFORM 



313 



alcoholism can be checked only to a certain extent through 
the class struggle. It can disappear totally only with the 
disappearance of the system which has created it and which 
always reproduces it," declared Kautsky in 1891. 

But of late the socialists of many countries have con- 
siderably changed their views on the problem of alcoholism 
and on the value of the modem temperance movements. 
They have gradually come to realize that in the matter of 
abstinence from or temperance in the use of alcoholic 
drinks, the purely moral factors of will power and de- 
termination play a large part. In their campaigns against 
the drink evil they still lay the greater stress on the better- 
ment of the material conditions of the workers, but they 
also recognize the value of a purely educational propa- 
ganda against the abuses of alcohol. 
To the Social Democratic Party of Austria belongs the 
. merit of having stated the proposition most clearly and 
I tersely in a resolution adopted in 1903, and from which 
I -we quote the following portion : — 

[ " This convention declares that alcoholism has a disas- 
trous effect on the physical and mental powers of the work- 
' ing class, and that it is a strong obstacle to the organizing 
I work of socialism. No means to remove the evils arising 
I from alcoholism should, therefore, be neglected. . . . 
I " The principal means in this struggle will always be the 
I elevation of the material conditions of the proletariat, but 
I a necessary supplement to this is the task of enlightening 
I the workers on the effects of alcohol and of shattering their 
1 prejudices in favor of the drinking habit." 
I The socialists of Germany declare it to be the duty of 
I organized labor to see to'it that theworkingmen, and espe- 
[ cially their children, be enlightened by oral and written 



314 



SOCIALISM AND REFORM 



propaganda on the dangers arising from the use of alcolud ' 
and the drink-treating habit. 

A similar stand has been taken by the socialists of 
Switzerland and Holland. In Sweden the socialist pro- 
gram contains a plank demanding that the public schools 
include in their curriculum a regular study course on the 
evils of alcoholism. In Norway the Socialist Party de- 
mands the imposition of heavy taxes on all alcoholic 
beverages. In England the Labor Party favors the local 
option system. In Belgium the socialists have banished 
all alcoholic drinks from their numerous meeting places 
and recreation halls, while the socialists of Finland demand 
the imconditional prohibition of all manufacture and sale 
of alcoholic drinks. 

The socialists of the United States for the first time took 
official notice of the alcohol problem at their national 
convention of 1908, and expressed their views on the 
subject in the following resolution : — 

" We recognize the evils arising from the manufacture and 
sale of alcoholic liquors, especially those which are adtil- 
terated, and we declare that any excessive use of such 
liquors by the working class postpones the day of the final 
triumph of our cause. But we do not believe that alcohol- 
ism can be cured by an extension of police powers under tfei 
capitalistic system. Alcoholism is a disease, and it can be 
cured best by the stopping of underfeeding, overwork and 
underpay, which result from the present wage system." 



The Housing of the Poor 

The dwelling conditions of the working people, especially 
a the large cities and in factory towns, present a problem 



SOQAL REFORM 



315 



of growing importance. Herded together like sheep, large 
families of human beings of all ages and sexes live in one 
or two small squalid rooms, without sufficient air or Hght. 
Here they cook, wash, dress, eat, sleep, quarrel and curse, 
make merry and make love in the constant company of 
each other and in an atraos])here of filth, irritation, cruelty 
and misery. The congested tenements are not only pro- 
lific sources of drunkenness, but also veritable breeding 
places of sickness, and of all species of vice and crime. 
The foul air of the "slum" dwellings is surcharged with the 
germs of death; the dread white plague and all other 
infectious diseases feed principally on the unfortunate 
inhabitants of the tenements, and the mortality of the 
children of this nether world is appalling. The miserable 
surroundings of these "homes" drive the children into the 
streets, the men into the liquor saloons and the women 
into the arms of vice. Tenement life in the slums de- 
moralizes the present generation of the workingmen, and 
breeds a race of feeble, apathetic and cheerless men and 
women which is the greatest menace to our progress and 
civilization. 

With the concentration of industries and the massing of 
ever larger numbers of workingmen in the manufacturing 
centers, the menace of popular congestion has within the 
last generation become particularly apparent and acute. 
Many movements for the reform of the housing conditions 
of the poor have sprung up, many measures of relief have 
been proposed. 

The first impulse of the tenement-house reformers is to 
go at the solution of the problem in what seems to be the 
most direct way. They wish to physically destroy the 
slum or to eradicate its worst evils ; to wash, sweep and 



3l6 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

air the squalid rooms; to break through windows in their 
dark walls to let in air and sunshine, and finally to dis- 
tribute the uniortunate tenement dwellers over a wider 
area by removing many of them from the congested spots 
into the more cheerful, healthy and sunny suburbs. 

These purely mechanical reforms have been tried and 
I are being tried to-day in all of the worst slum centers of the 
i world. 

More than forty years ago Miss Octavia Hill of London 
inaugurated a movement which has for its object the train- 
ing of tenement dwellers in the habits of cleanliness, order 
and decency in their households, and the movement has 
found many enthusiastic adherents in some of the large 
industrial cities of England, Scotland and the United 
States. 

Laws providing for the construction of tenement houses, 
with better provisions for air, light and sanitary arrange- 
ments, have of late been enacted in numerous countries. 

" Model " tenements have been built in large numbers. 
The Peabody fund and the Guinness trust in England, as 
well as numerous other philanthropic institutions in almost 
aJl advanced countries, have erected many thousands of 
such "model" tenements. 

Several great municipalities of England and Scotland 
have attempted to provide for the housing of their poor 
directly. They have purchased and torn down their 
worst tenements and have erected in their stead sanitary 
"dwelling houses, and let them to the poor at cost. 

Finally, the movement for suburban development as a 

cure for city congestion has also assumed large and ever 

growing proportions. Almost every large industrial city is 

■irteadily extending the radius of its surrounding rural 



SOCIAL REFORM 



317 



II 



territory as an outlet for its crowded population, and multi- 
plying and improving its transit facilities. 

All these measures have had a certain beneficial effect 
on the housing conditions of the city poor. Separately and 
collectively they have probably served to relieve the con- 
gestion of the working population to some degree and to 
make their conditions of life somewhat more tolerable, or 
rather, without them these conditions might have grown 
even more intolerable than they are to-day. 

But weighing the positive achievements along these 
lines of tenement-house reform, we caimot help being 
disappointed at the meagemess of the results. The slums 
of the world have not disappeared, nor have they on the 
whole been appreciably improved anywhere. In compari- 
son with the benefits derived, the time, energy and money 
expended on those measures seem an almost unproductive 
waste. 

Sermons on household cleanliness and sanitation, as a 
rule, fall on deaf ears where crowding and poverty me- 
chanically produce filth and indifference. 

The "model" tenements have on the whole proved a 
great success for their philanthropic or commercial found- 
ers, a success equal to from 5 to 10 per cent per annum on 
their investments. But to the masses of the poor they 
have brought but little rehef. The rents in new "model" 
tenements are as a rule a trifle higher than those in the 
ordinary ones, just high enough to allow the class of clerks 
and other better-paid employees to take advantage of them 
and to shut out those who most stand in need of dwelling 
reform — ■ the poorest classes of workingmen. 

The municipal experiments of demolishing the most 
jdisreputable tenements and erecting new and better ones, 



3l8 SOCIALISM AND REFORM 

have also largely failed to accomplish the results hoped for. 
But too often it has been found that the procedure resulted 
only in the transfer of the slum center from one spot to 
another. The evicted slum dwellers as a rule have settled 
down among their nearest slum neighbors. 

And as for suburban development — it also did not 
and could not materially relieve the evil of congestion. 
Suburban development means, in the first place, increased 
means of communication between. the city and the suburb, 
more lines of street cars and railways, and in the second 
place, more buildings and business in the suburbs. The 
principal beneficiaries of such reforms under present condi- 
tions are, as a rule, the railroad companies, the property- 
owners along the new lines of travel, the land speculators 
dealing in suburban property, and incidentally also our 
upper and lower middle classes, who furnish the bulk of 
all suburban population. 

The slum dwellers do not move to the suburbs, they 
cannot move to the suburbs. The slum dwellers are the 
hardest worked and poorest paid o£ the working class. 
They have not the money to pay the fares to and from their 
places of work, and they have not the time to spend on 
travel. Mr. Jacob A. Riis has observed that the housing 
problem is a transportation problem. That may be true 
for the middle classes, for tke workingmen the housing 
problem is not a transportation problem, but a wage 
problem. 

The trouble with the movement for tenement-house re- 
form, as with all current reform movements, is that it 
touches the surface, but not the root of the problem. 
Under our system of civilization, the "slum" is not a 
local or accidental abuse, but a social institution. Pov- 



^M SOaAL REFORM 319 

erty is the inevitable result of our industrial system, and 
the slum is poverty's logical place of abode. 

The first condition for the development of a slum district 
is its proximity to the factory. The workingman, and 
the poorer-paid workingman especially, is compelled to 
live within walking distance of his place of work. The 
price of land in such favored districts, then, naturally rises, 
and the landowners find it to their best advantage to build 
huge and cheap buildings occupying every available inch 
of ground, and containing many small rooms. These 
they let for exorbitantly high rent, and the workingman 
tenant is compelled to crowd his family into as few rooms 
as physically possible, and to secure one or more roomers 
besides to help him pay the rent. Then an entire industry 
adapted to the needs and means of the population develops 
in the district. In the streets of the, slum, in its groceries, 
eating houses and dry goods stores, the vilest and cheapest 
of food stuffs and of other commodities converge from all 
parts of the city and country. The slum is adjusted to the 
entire household economy of its inhabitants and holds 
them in its iron grip. It must persist as long as exploi- 
tation and poverty continue. 

The various reforms heretofore tried have some value as 
temporary palliatives, and the socialists heartily favor them 
as such. They advocate municipal construction of model 
tenements to be let to workingmen at cost, and they advo- 
cate suburban development through improved transit lines 
to be built and operated by the city in the interest of the 
traveling public and the employees. But they do not 
expect substantial relief from such measures, 

The slum evil can be relieved only by better wages and 
shorter hours, it can be cured only by socialism. 



APPENDIX 



HISTORICAL SKETCH OF THE SOCIALIST MOVEMENT 

Early History 

Some writers on the subject include in the history of the 1 
socialist movement all ancient and mediaeval manifesta- 
tions of communistic thought and institutions. But as i 
matter of fact the modem socialist movement has nothing 
in common with the Utopias of Plato, Campanella and 
More, or with the prehistoric tribal institutions, early I 
Christian practices or the various sectarian communities 
of the Middle Ages. 

The political socialist movement of our day is primarily 
a movement of the working class, and has for its object the 
reconstruction of the present-day system of industry on the 
basis of collective ownership of the tools of production. 

The movement thus presupposes the existence of a 
competitive individualist system of industry and of a wage- 
earning class. In other words, modern socialism is 
unthinkable without its antithesis — capitalism. Social- 
ism is the child of the modern or "capitalist" system of 
production. And more than that, it is the product of that 
system at a certain advanced stage. The socialist move- 
ment is a protest against the present industrial system, 
hence it presupposes a state of development of that system 
to a point where it has become oppressive; it involves a 
criticism of the system, hence it implies a dissatisfaction 



^ 



^m APPENDIX 321 

with it; and finally, it offers a substitute for the present 
system, hence it is predicated on the assumption of a state 
of decline of the capitalist regime. 

Thus while the beginnings of the present industrial 
system may be traced back to the fifteenth or sixteenth 
century of our era, the modern socialist movement is barely 
more than a century old. 

Socialism, like most other social theories and movements, 
has passed through several stages of development before 
reaching its modem aspect. 

In its first phases it was primarily a humanitarian move- 
ment, and its political rflle was but secondary and ind- ■ 
dental. 1 

The early socialists saw only the evils of the new system \ 
of production; they did not penetrate into its historical I 
significance and tendencies. The evils of the system ap- | 
peared to them as arbitrary deviations from the "eternal 
principles" of "natural law," justice and reason, and the 1 
social system itself as a clumsy and malicious contrivance ' 
of the dominant powers in society. i 

To the "unreasonable" and "unjust" social systems of 
their times they opposed more or less fantastic schemes 
of social organization of their own invention supposed to be ■ 
free from the abuses of modem civilization, and thereupon i 
they appealed to humanity at large to test those schemes. 

These social schemes were, as a rule, unfolded by their 
authors by means of description of a fictitious country with 
a mode of life and form of government to suit their own 
ideas of justice and reason. The happy country thus de- 
scribed was the Utopia (Greek for "Nowhere"), hence 
the designation of that phase of the socialist movement 
as " Utopian." 



322 



APPENDIX 



I 



One of the fruits of these theories was the organization 
of the numerous communistic societies of the early part of 
the last century. The Utopian socialists knew of no 
reason why their plans of social organization should not^ 
work in a more limited sphere just as satisfactorily as c 
a national scale, and they fondly hoped that they wouldj 
gradually convert the entire world to their system by f 
practical demonstration of its feasibility and benefits ii 
a miniature society. 

Another practical application of the Utopian socialist \ 
philosophy is to be found in the conspiratory revolutionary 
societies which accompanied the socialist agitation of 
several European countries, notably France, in the thirties 
and forties of the nineteenth century. The object of these 
societies was to capture the organs of government and to . 
decree a socialist state of society, a perfectly sane and J 
logical procedure from the point of view of men who be- I 
lieved that systems of society could be created and altered I 
at will. 

As with every other movement it is, of course, impos- 
sible to locate the exact starting point of modem social- 
ism. In a general way, however, it may be said that the I 
beginning of the modern socialist movement coincides 
with the period of the great French Revolution. 
' The first gleams of socialist philosophy appear in the 
^orks of the pre-Revolutionary French philosophers of the 
School of the Encyclopedists, notably in those of Jean i 
Jacques Rousseau, who as early as in 1754 denounced 
private property as the cause of all crimes. 

But a much more definite and elaborate expression of the 
Utopian socialist creed we find in the two works of Morelly: 
" Naufrage des lies Flottantes ou la Basiliade" (The Ship-' ' 



APPENDIX 323 

""wreck of the Floating Islands or Baailiade), 1753, and 
"Code de la Nature" {Code of Nature), 1753. The 
former is an Utopian novel in metrical form, and the latter 
is a philosophic essay. Morelly is a keen and farseeing 
critic of the industrial system of individualist competition, 
and advocates a somewhat loose form of communism. 

Next to Morelly, Gabriel Mably (1709-1785) must be', 
mentioned among the early French socialist writere. Like ' 
Morelly, Mably advocated a social system based on the , 
community of property, with the difference, however, that 
the state of Mably is highly centralized, both in the system 
of production and distribution. 

A more realistic note in the literature of the young 
socialist speculation is introduced by the French lawyer, 
Francois Boissel (1728-1807), whose "Catechisme du , 
Genre Humain" (Catechism of Mankind), which appeared , 
in 1789, the year of the French Revolution, contains the 
first attempt at a scientific analysis of the modem mode 
of production. 

These three authors arc the principal exponents of 
socialism in pre-RevoIutionary France. Their works are 
purely theoretical, and they did not result in any socialist 
activity. 

The first direct step toward an active revolutionary 
and socialist movement was made by Francois Noel 
Babeuf (1760-1796). Babeuf, himself an active factor 
in the great French Revolution, was by no means satisfied 
with its accomplishments. "The Revolution," he argued, 
"has proclaimed Liberty, Fraternity and Equality, but 
equality is a mere sham unless it is social and economic as 
well as political," With the aim of capturing the govern- 
ment of France and establishing social and economic 



324 APPENDIX 

equality, he organized the famous Conspiracy of Equals. 
The movement is said to have attained considerable 
dimensions in Paris when it was detected in 1796- 
\ Babeuf was convicted on the charge of treason, and be- 
headed. Years later, Filippo Buonarotti, a friend and 
disciple of Babeuf, published the history of the conspiracy 
I and the program of the conspirators, and the work played 
■ a large part in the movement of the secret socialist societies 
of later years. _ 

/ Babeuf was the last representative of the eighteenth-J 
century socialism. The beginning of the nineteenth cen-4 
tury produced a series of socialist thinkers and workers 
who have influenced the shaping of the present-day 
socialist movement more directly than their predecessors. 
■Of these, two are always mentioned together. They are J 
Charles Henri Saint-Simon and Charles Fourier. I 

' Saint-Simon is a teacher rather than a practical social I 
reformer. The keynote to his philosophy is the demand'! 
(that society be organized not on a political but on an in- I 
pustrial basis. His last work, "Nouveau Christianisme" I 
y{New Christianity) is the most complete exposition of I 
(his social views, and contains the germs of the theory of I 
I economic determinism which in the hands of Karl Marx I 
subsequently became one of the most powerful weapons in I 
' the arsenal of contemporary socialist philosophy, I 

After the death of Saint-Simon his work was continued I 
by a talented coterie of his disciples, prominent among 1 
whom were Oiinde Rodrigue (1794-1851), Barthel^my I 
P. Enfantin (1796-1864), Armand Bazard (1791-1S32), 1 
I Auguste Comte, the father of positive philosophy, and I 
L Terdinand de Lesseps, of the Suez Canal fame. The I 
I iSaint-Simonian school at one time gained considerable 1 



APPENDIX 325 

influence in the intellectual circles of France, its organ, " Le 
Globe," had a large circulation, and in the revolution of 
1830 the Saint-Simonians played a not unimportant part. 
But the movement ultimately split, principally on the 
question of woman's rights. Under the leadership of 
Enfantin the Saint-Simonian school developed a mystic 
religious cult with certain unconventional practices in the 
relation of the sexes, which led to the arrest of Enfantin 
and his followers on the charge of immorality, and to the 
inglorious end of the Saint-Simonian movement. 

If Saint-Simon was the preacher of order and system, 
Fourier may be called the apostle of harmony, 

God created the entire universe on a harmonious plan, 
reasons Fourier, hence there must be harmony between 
everything in existence. Endowing human beings with 
certain instincts and desires, God intended their free and 
untrammeled exercise, and not their suppression, ^11 
human instincts and desires are legitimate and useful 
if existing society curbs the right of the citizen to fol 
those instincts and desires, it is evidence of a defect 
social system, not in the individual. Fourier advocates 
the reorganization of society on the basis of autonomous 
communities of from 1500 to 2000 members. These com- 
munities, styled by him" phalanxes," are voluntary associ- 
ations of citizens for the purpose of cooperative labor 
and collective enjoyment, with ample provisions for the 
choice of associates and occupations, variety of pursuits 
and attractive surroundings of industries. The phalanxes 
are not communistic enterprises, but rather partake of 
the nature of modem joint-stock associations, in which 
capital receives its reward as well as labor and "talent," 
it-Simon emphasizes the rights and importance of 




326 APPENDIX 

society, Fourier dwells principally on the rights of the 
individual citizens as against organized society. The two 
great Utopians may be said to be the prototypes of the two 
dominant tendencies in the social theories of our times — 
collectivism and individualism. 

Chief among the French disciples of Fourier is Victor 
Consid^rant, under whose leadership the Fourierist move- 
ment attained some importance years after the master's 
death. But even more influence than in France, the 
philosophy of Fourier exercised in the United States of 
America, where it counted among its most enthusiastic 
adherents men like Albert Brisbane, Horace Greeley, 
Parke Godwin, George Ripley, Charles A. Dana, Mar- 
garet Fuller and other men and women prominent in 
the world of letters. 

In France, the home of Fourierism, but few attempts at 
the practical realization of the system were made, but in 
the United States over forty phalanxes were established 
between 1840 and 1850, among them the famous Brook 
Farm and the North American Phalanx. Of the socialist 
writers and reformers of that period who have largely con- 
tributed to the development of the modem socialist move- 
ment, we must mention fitienne Cabet (1788-1856), 
Louis Blanc (1S11-1882), Jean Lamennais (1782-1854) 
and Pierre J. Proudhon {1809-1865). 

Cabet's Utopian novel "Voyage en Icarie" (Voyage to 
Icaria), published in 1842, gave rise to a popular movement 
in favor of communism which at one time was said to 
number several hundred thousands of adherents. The 
movement resulted in the establishment of the "Icarian 
communities" in the United States. The first of these 
communities was established in Texas in 184S, and the 



I 



APPENDIX 327 

last of the series perished in California almost half a cen- 
tury later. 

Louis Blanc, who first achieved fame through his work 
"Organization du Travail" {Organization of Labor), 
published in 1840, played an important part ip the French 
revolution of 1848 as a member of the Provisional Com- 
mittee. He was chiefly instrumental in bringing about the 
famous decree of that committee recognizing the "right 
to labor," and was indirectly responsible for the establish- 
ment of the National Workshops, which under the post- 
revolutionary administration of the French government 
turned into a disastrous failure. 

Lamennais is the father of Christian Socialism in France. 
He early advocated the union of the Catholic church with 
the growing socialist movement of the workingmcn. His 
views were condemned by Pope Gregory XVI, and Lamen- 
nais thereafter addressed his appeals directly to the people. 
His "Paroles d'un Croyant" (Words of a Believer), 
published in 1854, contains a burning indictment of the 
selfish rich, and is full of tender sympathy for the disin- ,' 
herited of the world. It was widely read by the working- ! 
men of his generation, and made a deep and lasting im- 
pression on his countrymen. 

Proudhon, the author of the famous "Qu'est-ce que la 
Propri^te ?" (What is Property?) and "Contradictions 
ficonomlques" (Economic Contradictions), may be said to 
be the father of modem "communistic anarchism." 

This review of early French socialism would not be 
complete without a brief reference to the secret societies 
which made their appearance immediately after the rev- 
olution of 1830, and continued with varying degree of 
strength and success for about ten years. The principal 



328 APPENDIX 1 

organizations of that cycle are the Sociiti des amis du 
Peuple (Society of the Friends of the People), SociSti \ 
des droits de I'homme {Society of Human Rights), Soci6l4 j 
des families (Society of Families), and SociitS des saisons 
(Society of Seasons), and the most prominent leaders of 
the movement were Louis Blanqui (1805-1S81), Armand j 
1 Barbfes (1809-1870), Voyer d'Argcnjon (1771-1842) and ] 
\ Filippo Buonarotti mentioned above. 1 

■ j While the socialism of France during the first half of the ] 
/last century was thus replete with various movements, 
^schools and thinkers, the movement in England during ] 
/ the corresponding period is practically represented by one | 
\ name — Robert Owen, 

The socialism of Owen differed from that of his French I 
contemporaries just as much as the political and industrial J 
conditions and national temperament and genius of Eng- i 
land differed from those of France. I 

Owen was primarily a practical business man, not a 1 
philosopher, and still less a conspirator. His socialist 
views were developed by his contact with actual industrial 1 
conditions, more highly developed in England than in any 
other European country, and they always bore the imprint 
of that origin. 

Owen's early activity in the field of social reform was 
more of a philanthropic than revolutionary character: it 
consisted in the long and patient work of improving the ] 
conditions of his own employees in the Scotch manufactur- | 
ing village of New Lanark, and in this he succeeded so 1 
well that within one generation (from 1800 to 1824) the 
former miserable village, with a degenerate and wretched 
population, had become a model community of healthy, 
mdustrious and happy men and women. j 



I 



APPENDIX 329 

His revolutionary career may be said to date from 1817, 
when upon the invitation of the committee of the As- 
sociation for the Rehef of the Manufacturing and Laboring 
Poor, he unfolded his views on the causes of poverty and 
the needed social reforms. The gist of his views is that 
widespread pauperism and popular misery are inseparable 
from an industrial system based on free competition, and 
that under such a system the increased productivity of 
labor inevitably leads to the deterioration of the condition 
of the working class. 

He was a great believer in the influence of environment 
on the formation of human character, and predicted that 
improved material conditions of the laboring population 
would result in the physical, intellectual and moral regen- 
eration of the masses. 

His activities as a socialist propagandist and experi- 
menter extend over forty years, and are as variegated as in- 
tense. He organized the famous New Harmony communi- 
ties in the United States (1826-1828), and several similar 
communities in England, Scotland and Ireland. In 1832 
he established the Equitable Banks for Labor Exchange, 
a contrivance for the exchange of commodities by their 
producers without the intervention of the profit-making 
merchant and manufacturer, and several years later he 
formed the Association of all Classes and Nations whose 
members first applied the appellation of "socialists" to 
themselves. He was indefatigable in the propaganda of 
his creed m the United States as well as in England. He 
delivered several lectures in the Hall of Representatives 
at Washington, called an mtemational socialist congress in 
New York, and presided over the first national convention 
of English trade unions. He was largely responsible for 



[330 



APPENDIX 



the introduction of the infant-school system, aiia 
sidered the father of factory legislation. 

Owen's influence was, however, mainly personal, and he 
left no school or movement behind him. 

In Germany the first manifestations of socialist thought 
and activity are connected with the names of the cele- 
brated philosopher Johann Gottlieb Fichte (1762-1S14), 
who in his " Geschlossener Handelstaai" (Closed Trading 
State) advocates the state regulation of production and 
distribution of goods, and the tailor Wilhelm Weitling 
(1808-1871), who may be considered the connecting link 
between present-day socialism and its earlier forms. 

Weitling seems to have imbibed the theories of French 
commimism in his early traveling days, but he instilled into 
them the life and faith of the active propagandist and en- 
thusiastic apostle. Like Owen he extended his activity to 
all spheres of radical social reform known in his day, or- 
ganizing cooperative enterprises, workingmen's study clubs, 
a communistic settlement, trade-union organizations, etc. 
His main theoretical works are : " Die Welt wie sie ist und 
sein soUte" (The World as It is and as It Should Be), 1838, 
"Die Garantien der Harmonic und Frciheit" (The Guar- , 
anties of Harmony and Freedom), 1842, and "Das Evan- 
gelium des Armen Siinders" (Evangel of a Poor Sinner), 
1846. 

Weitling is the first socialist to make a more direct 
appeal to the working class, although the modem socialist 
conception of class struggle is still foreign to him. Weit- 
ling's fields of activity were Switzerland and the United 
States, but his influence also extended to Germany, Austria 
and the colonies of German emigrants in other coun- 
tries, i 



APPENDIX 331 

In tfie meantime, the industrial development of Europe 
had proceeded with giant strides, and with it also the 
scientific study of the character and tendencies of the exist- 
ing industrial regime. The fantastic theories and hypoth- 
eses of early socialism, liite those of so many other young 
sciences, had to be greatly modified. Socialism had to 
be given a new, more realistic and sounder foundation, 
and this task was accomplished towards the middle of the 
last century by the twin founders of modem socialism, 
Karl Marx (1818-1883) and Frederick Engels (1820- 
1895)- 

The socialism of the new school, known as Marxian or 
Scientific socialism, proceeds on the theory that the social 
and political structure of society at any given time and 
place is not the result of the free and arbitrary choice of 
men, but the logical outcome of a definite process of his- 
torical development, and that the underlying structure of 
such foundation is at all times the economic system upon 
which society is organized. 

As a logical sequence from these views it follows that 
a form of society cannot be changed at any given time un- 
less the economic development has made it ripe for the 
change, and that the future of mankind must be looked 
for, not in the ingenious schemes of mventive social 
philosophers, but in the tendencies of economic develop- 
ment. 

The Marxian socialists base their hopes on the tendency 
of modern industries towards centralization and socializa- 
tion, the inadequacy and wastefulness of the individual 
and competitive system of production, and the growing 
revolt of the working classes against J 
hardships involved in that system, 






1332 APPENDIX 

Modem socialists address themselves not so muci^ to the 
humane sentiments of society at large as to the self-interests 
of the working class, as the class primarily concerned in the 
impending social change. They do not indulge in minia- 
ture social experiments or in political conspiracies, but di- 
rect their efforts towards the education and political and 
industrial organization of the working class, so as to enable 
that class to steer the ship of state from individualism into 
collectivism, when the time shall be ripe for it, and to hasten 
that time. I 

This phase of the socialist movement may be said to date I 
from the publication of the celebrated " Communist Mani- 
festo." The "Manifesto" is a brief pamphlet written con- 
jointly by Marx and Engels. It has since been translated 
into almost all modern languages, and has remained to 
this day the classical exposition of modern socialism. 

The "Communist Manifesto" appeared in 184S. The 1 
great revolutionary movement of that year and the long 
period of European reaction following upon its defeat, 
temporarily paralyzed the young socialist movement 
inaugurated by Marx and his comrades. For almost 
fifteen years the movement was confined to a few scattered 
circles of "intellectuals" in the different countries of Eu- 
rope and did not penetrate into the masses anywhere. 
The general political and social awakening which marks 
the beginning of the sixties of the last century in all princi- 
pal countries of Europe and in the United States of Amer- 
ica, did not pass without affecting the working classes. 
A strong labor movement grew up in the most advanced 
countries of Europe, and a large portion of it fell, under the 
spiritual leadership of the socialists. 

The first fruit of these renewed socialist and labor ac- 



APPENDIX 333 

tivities was the organization of the International Working- 
men's Association {commonly styled the International) 
in 1864. The International was organized in London by 
some representative English trade unionists in conjunction 
with a number of political refugees of various nationalities 
with whom the capital of England was fairly teeming just 
then. Its constitution and declaration of principles were 
drafted by Karl Marx, and the latter instrument was a 
concise exposition of the socialist philosophy winding up 
with the declaration — " No rights without duties; no duties 
without rights." 

The International extended over England, France, 
Germany, Austria, Belgium, Holland, Denmarti, Spain, 
Portugal, Italy, Switzerland, Poland, Australia and the 
United States of America, and at one time was considered 
a great power in European politics. Its active career em- 
braced a period of about eight years, from 1864 to 1872, 
during which time it held six conventions. These con- 
ventions were largely devoted to the discussion of social 
and labor problems, and served to impress the socialist 
movement of the world with a uniform and harmonious 
character. 

The dissolution of the organization was brought about 
by a number of factors, not the least of which was the fate 
of the Paris Commune. 

The Commune, proclaimed in Paris on March 18, 187T, 
in its inception had no connection whatever with the In- 
ternational or the socialist agitation of the time. Its name 
was not intended to imply any sympathy with the doctrines 
of communism, but was merely meant to signify the com- 
munal or municipal autonomy of Paris. The proclamation 
of the Commune was a result of the revolt of the Parisians 



334 APPENDIX 

' i^inst the excessive centralization of government 
France. 

Originally the movement was rather conservative, but 
in the course of the struggles between the Parisian Com- 
munards and their Versaillian adversaries it became more 
and more radical in character. The Parisian populace, 
after the Prussian siege of 1870, consisted largely of work- 
ingmen and small shopkeepers reduced to a state of extreme 
poverty and suffering, while many of the wealthier citizens 
fled from Paris after the proclamation of the Commune, to 
seek protection from the national troops stationed at Ver- 
sailles, The Commune, therefore, assumed the character 
of a struggle between the Parisian proletariat and the 
French bourgeoisie, and the International threw its entire 
moral influence to the support of the former. When the 
Commune was defeated, after a stormy existence of about 
two months, the defeat and the general European moral 
opprobrium which attached to the memory of the Parisian 
revolt, strongly affected the standing of the International. 

But the deciding blow to the life of the International 
was dealt by the growing spirit of anarchism within its 
ranks. 

Up to about 1869 the Tnternational was under the undis- 
puted control of the Marxian wing of socialism, but in the 
later years of its existence the school of " communistic 
anarchism " steadily gained ground in the councils of the 
society under the leadership of the apostle of the new creed, 
Michael Bakounin (1814-1876). Bakounin, a Russian by 
birth and a revolutionist by temperament, had passed 
through a very picturesque revolutionary career before . 
he joined the International. He abominated the evolu- 
tionary doctrines and "tame" methods of Marxian social- 



APPENDIX 335 

ism, and revolted against organization and discipline. 
He advocated the immediate rising against tlie obnoxious 
powers of modern civilization, and proclaimed the principle 
of "complete individual liberty restrained only by natural 
laws." He was eloquent, enthusiastic and magnetic, 
and the desperate conditions of the laboring population 
of Europe, especially in the Southern countries, furnished 
a large and very receptive audience for his promises of 
quick and easy salvation. 

Anarchism threatened to become a power in the Inter- 
national, and Marx and his friends decided to avert the 
danger by sacrificing the organization. In 1S72 the seat 
of its general council was transferred to New York, and 
three years later the International was formally dissolved. 

The International, however, had accomplished its 
purpose, and during its activity the socialist movement of 
Europe had developed to such dimensions that it became 
impossible to confine it within the bounds of one central 
organization. From this point we shall have to follow 
the varying fortunes of the movement in the different 
countries in which it has developed. 

Chief among such countries is, of course, 



Germany 

In Germany the present-day socialist movement runs I 
an unbroken chain from the days of the agitation of Ferdi- 
nand Lassalle (1825-1864). Of extraordinary eloquence, 
profound learning and indomitable energy, Lassalle was 
probably the most powerful popular tribune produced by 
the nineteenth century. 
|.Hi5 active work in the cause of socialism is practically 



I 



confined to the last two years of his life. But during 
short period he succeeded in thoroughly rousing the phleg- 
matic working class of his country by his ringing speeches 
and powerful writings. In his social views he was a dis- 
ciple of Marx, but the principal issues of his agitation were 
the demands for universal suffrage and for the establish- 
ment of cooperative workshops with state credit. 

In 1863 he organized the General Workingmen's As- 
sociation, which at the time of its founder's death numbered 
only 4610 members, but grew considerably in later years, 
notwithstanding one serious schism within its ranks. 

In the meanwhile a new socialist party, more stricdy 
Marxian, was organized in 1869, under the leadership of 
Wilhelm Liebknecht and August Bebel, and the six years 
following are marked by a bitter feud between the rival 
organizations. The feud was terminated in 1875 by the 
amalgamation of all socialist organizations at the Gotha 
convention, and the present Social Democratic Party of 
Germany was thus born. Since then the progress of the 
socialist movement has been rapid and steady, and even 
the imrelenting government persecution under the Excep- 
tion Laws did not succeed in checking its growth. These 
laws were designed to suppress all forms of socialist prop- 
aganda, and their enforcement was attended by the im- 
prisonment and exile of large numbers of the most active 
socialists. They were enacted in 1878 after two attempts 
by irresponsible individuals on the life of the Emperor, and 
were abandoned in 1890 after their futility had been dem- 
onstrated in practice. The growth of socialism in Ger- 
many can be best appreciated by a comparison of the 
socialist vote in the parliamentary elections of that country, 
l-was 101,927 in 1871 and over three and one quarter 



I 



APPENDIX 337 

millions in 1906. The Social Democratic Party of Ger- 
many is to-day numerically the strongest political organi- 
zation in the country. 



France 

If the socialist movement of Germany may be considered 
a model of orderly and methodical growth, that of France 
has had, on the contrary, a most bewildering and stormy 
career. 

With the fall of the Paris Commune the movement in 
France had received a blow from which it recovered but 
very slowly. For a number of years after 1871 the only 
manifestation of socialist activity was to be found in the 
students' circles organized by Gabriel Deville and Jules 
Gufesde, and the main efforts of these circles were di- 
rected towards the propaganda of socialism among the 
trade unions. In these efforts they gained a partial suc- 
cess in 1878 when the general trade-union congress of 
Lyons pledged its support to some socialist candidates, 
and several large trade organizations indorsed the entire 
socialist program. The arrest of Gufesde and thirty-three 
other labor leaders in 1879 for participation in a political 
labor conference, and the brilliant defense of Gufesde on 
that occasion, largely served to increase the sympathies 
of the working population for socialism, and the general 
trade-union congress of Marseilles, held in the same year, 
unreservedly declared itself in favor of the movement. 

But this declaration, made by the delegates under the 
influence of the events immediately preceding the conven- 
tion, did not seem to have the unanimous support of their 
constituents. At the following convention, held in Havre in 



338 APPENDIX I 

1880, the discussion was resumed, and resulted in a split 
The organized workingmen divided themselves into two 
separate organizations distinguished from each other as 
" collect! vists" and "cooperativists" respectively. And 
the socialist movement in France has ever thereafter pro- 
gressed through a process of alternate fusions and divisions, 
The first schism in the ranks of the socialist movement 
proper took place in 1882, when the strict adherents of 
Marxian socialism, led by Jules Gu^sde, Paul Lafargue and 
Gabriel Deville, separated from the Possibilisl or oppor- 
tunist sociahsts, headed by Paul Brousse and Benoit 
Malon. The former organized the Parti Ouvrier 
(Labor Party), and the latter, the Federation Frangaise 
des Travailleurs Socidisks Revolutionaires (French 
Federation of Socialist Revolutionary Workingmen). 
To these must be added the Parti Revolutionaire founded 
by the veteran of the French Revolution, Blanqui, upon his 
release from his last term of imprisonment in 1879, and J 
after his death dkected by the well-known communard, ~ 
Edouard Vaillant. 

The number of socialist parties was further augmented I 
by a split within the ranks of the Possibilists, the more ] 
radical wing of which organized an independent party in 
1891 under the name of Parti Ouvrier Revolutionaire \ 
Sociatiste, and under the leadership of Allemane, and also 
by the formation of numerous local groups of "independ- j 
ent socialists" whose membership included such promi- 
nent socialists as Etienne Millerand and Jean Jauifts. 

The period between 1898 and igor is marked by efforts 
to bring about the union of socialist forces. These efforts 
were partly realized in 1900, when a national congress of all 
French socialist parties and organizations was held in Paris. , 



APPENDIX 339 

But in the meanwhile a new issue presented itself to the 
socialists of France. The events attending the Dreyfus 
agitation had forced sociaUsts to the front in national poli- 
tics, and one independent socialist, fitienne Millerand, 
was given a portfoUo in the cabinet of the new premier, 
Waldeck-Rousseau. MiUerand's entry into the "bour- 
geois" cabinet had the approval of the more liberal or 
"opportunist" wing of the socialist movement under the 
leadership of the eloquent Jean Jaurfes, but was strongly 
condemned by the more orthodox faction headed by Jules 
Gufesde. And on this new issue the socialist organizations 
of France now grouped themselves. The "ministerialists" 
combined into the Parti Socialisle Franfais, while the 
"anti-ministerialists" united into the Parli Socialisle de 
France. Both parties continued a separate though not 
always antagonistic existence until 1905, when they united 
into one, largely through the good services of the Inter- 
national Socialist Congress held in Amsterdam in 1904. 
The new party is the first in France to bring together all 
of the more important socialist organizations under one 
administration, although some minor groups of "inde- 
pendent" socialists still remain in existence. 

The first socialist campaign in parliamentary elections 
in France was made in 1885, when the combined socialist 
parties polled about 30,000' votes. The successive growth 
of the socialist parliamentary vote is shown by the follow- 
ing round figures : — 

47,000 
120,000 



L 



Russia 



While the modem socialist movements in Germany and ' 
France, as well as in all other European countries, are 
primarily economic in their character, and are supported 
principally by the industrial working classes, the movement 
in Russia was in its inception preponderatingly political 
and ethical, and was represented principally by men and 
women of the better-situated and cultured classes. This . 
difference in the character of the movement is accounted | 
for by the difference between the social and economic -I 
conditions of that country and the rest of Europe at the 
period of the birth of socialism in Russia. At a time when 
the modem industrial riigime was fully developed, and the 
system of representative government firmly established 
in the other principal countries of Europe, Russia was a 
purely agricultural country with a population of peasants 
just liberated from serfdom, with no manufacturing class . 
or industrial proletariat worth mentioning, and with an I 
almost Asiatic form of autocratic government. The i 
cialism of Russia was not the du-ect result of economic de- I 
velopment, not a form of class struggle between the classes 
of capitalists and workingmen : it was partly an expressioa 
of poUtical revolt against absolute czarism, and partly a 
reflex of the economic socialist theories with such modi- 
fications as comported with the peculiar conditions of j 
, Russia. 

The first expressions of socialist thought in Rus^a | 
coincide with the agitation for the emancipation of the 
serfs, and its best-known representatives of that period 
are a famous coterie of publicists and critics among whom 
we must mention Alexander Herzen, an expatriated noble- 



APPENDIX 341 

man of considerable wealth, who conducted an active 
agitation for Russian freedom from London principally 
by means of his magazine Kolokol (Bell), and Nicholas 
Chemyshefsky, the editor of the influential magazine 
Sovremennik (Contemporary), who was deported to Si- 
beria in the prime of his life, to return thence an old man 
and a physical and mental wreck. 

The next phase of the socialist movement in Russia is 
that designated as "Nihilism," The word was coined by 
the well-known novelist Ivan Turgenief as a term of ridicule 
of the new current of Russian thought which developed 
strongly around i860 to 1870, and whose main characteris- 
tics were a crude materialism and the negation of all 
established beliefs. 

"Nihilism" was an intellectual rather than a political 
or social movement, but its effect was to promote socialism 
in two ways; it created a negative attitude towards the old 
order of things in Russia, and it developed a thirst for posi- 
tive knowledge among the youth of both sexes, driving 
large numbers of them into the universities of Western 
Europe, principally those of Switzerland, since they could 
not quench that mtellectual thirst at home. These young 
and receptive Russian students were powerfully attracted 
by the awakening socialist movement of Western Europe, 
and also came under the influence of their own exiled 
countrymen, Michael Bakounin, Alexander Herzen and 
Peter LavTofl', the foremost Russian representative of 
scientific sociahsm at that time. The socialist sympathies 
of these Russian students were so manifest that their 
government finally took alarm, and in 1873 summarily 
recalled them to their fatherland under pain of exile. The 
eSect of the order was hardly gratifying to the government: 



342 APPENDIX 

the students returned in large numbers, but they returned; 
as active socialist propagandists. I 

At this stage of the movement Russian socialism was' 
perfectly peaceful. The activities of the young propa- 
gandists were principally educational ; their main effort was 
to raise the intellectual level of the illiterate peasantry 
composing the great bulk of the population. They spread 
in the villages, settled among the peasants, whose habits, 
language and even dress they tried to imitate, and con- 
ducted the work of socialist propaganda side by side with 
that of general education. But their activity provoked 
severe government persecutions; the "political offenders" 
were hounded down, executed, imprisoned or exiled to 
Siberia, frequently without so much as the formality of 
trial. Within five years the young movement found itself 
practically checked: the socialist propagandists, reduced 
in numbers and rendered desperate by the relentless and 
cruel police persecution, abandoned the peaceful methods 
of propaganda. A seeming accident determined the suc- 
ceeding phase of Russian socialism. 

In 1878 a young woman named Vera Sassulich shot at 
General Trcpoff, the military commandant of St. Peters- 
burg, as an act of revenge for his brutal treatment of a 
political prisoner. Vera Sassuhch was placed on trial for 
the offense, but was triumphantly acquitted by the jury 
amid the plaudits of the better part of the population. 
Encouraged by the success of Sassulich, deprived of all 
means of peaceful activity, and rendered desperate by the 
relentless police persecutions, the socialists turned to 
methods of force and conspiracy. 

A sudden and radical change took place in the Russian 
revolutionary movement. The old type of peaceful propa- 



I 



APPENDIX 343 

gandist and dreamer disappeared, and instead of him there 
arose the sullen and determined terrorist. The Russian 
socialists engaged in mortal combat with the autocratic 
government, and the embodiment of that government, the 
czar, in person. The struggle lasted but a few years, and 
it was the strangest ever witnessed in history. A mere 
handful of ideaJists, without substantial support on the part 
of any class of the population, was arrayed against the 
rulers of Russia, supported by a powerful police, a vast 
army and unlimited resoiyces; and still the struggle was 
fierce, just as fierce on the one side as on the other. The 
"white terror" of the government was fully balanced by 
the "red terror" of the revolutionists. The enthusiasm, 
courage and ingenuity displayed by the Russian socialists, 
men and women, during that period, defy comparison. 
The annals of these few years of the movement are the 
most romantic in the history of international sociahsm, 
and are characterized by numerous political assassinations, 
and by the imprisonment and execution of the most gifted 
leaders of Russian socialism. The movement culminated 
in the assassination of Czar Alexander II, and this triumph 
of the first period of revolutionary terrorism in Russia 
was also its end. The Russian revolutionists had expected 
that the killing of the czar would be the signal for a general 
revolt, but in this expectation they found themselves sorely 
disappointed. The population of Russia was not ready 
for a revolution at that time, and had but little sympathy 
or understanding for the youthful socialists. 

The Will of the People, the famous fighting organiza- 
tion of the revolutionary terrorists, survived the assassi- 
nation of Alexander II only a few years. 

In the meanwhile, modem industrial conditions rapidly 



344 APPENDIX 

developed in Russia, and with them developed a new social 

power, the class of factory workers. 

Thus was prepared in Russia the soil for a socialist 
movement after the pattern of Western Europe, and the 
soil rapidly produced a plentiful harvest. Already in the 
days of revolutionary terrorism a small group of Russian 
socialists, headed by George Plekhanoff, Paul Axelrod and 
Vera Sassulich, had based their hopes for the future of 
Russian socialism in the nascent class of industrial workers, 
and their propaganda kept pace with the growth and spread 
of that class. In the early nineties of the last century, 
official Russia, greatly to its surprise 'and dismay, found 
itself confronted in all industrial centers by a well-organized ■ 
and radical labor movement, which refused to yield to 
persecution or to be side tracked by governmental ruses. 
The organized labor movement gave a new impetus to the 
political socialist movement. The Social Democratic 
Party, originally organized by Russian political exiles in 
Switzerland, soon had a number of local committees in 
various parts of Russia, and was reenforced by the organiza- 
tions of the Jewish, Polish, Lettish and Armenian social 
democrats. At the begirming of the present century, the 
Social Democratic Party, secret and persecuted as it was, 
had developed into a power of no mean proportions, and 
during the most agitated days of the overt outbreak of the 
Russian revolution, towards the end of 1905 and the be- 
ginning of 1906, it was this party that led the movement. 

With the revival of the socialist movement in Russia, 
revolutionary terrorism, the natural child of unbridled 
autocracy, gradually reappeared. This movement was at 
first represented by a number of scattered groups, but in 
1901 the large majority of them combined their forces and 



k 



APPENDIX 345 

created the party of Socialist Revolutionists, which is re- 
sponsible for the numerous political assassinations preced- 
ing and accompanying the present war between the govern- 
ment and the people of Russia, It is impossible at this 
time to estimate the number of Russian subjects enhsted in 
the ranks of socialism of one shade or another, but the fact 
that the second Duma, elected on a restricted suffrage and 
under government surveillance, had about one hundred 
socialist members (social democrats, socialist revolutionists 
and representatives of the Group of Toil), is eloquent 
testimony to the immense spread and power of socialism 



Austria 

The socialist movement in Austria is closely linked with 
that of Germany, so much so that in their earlier stages 
the two movements are hardly differentiated. In the 
famous convention of Eisenach, held in 1868, the Austrian 
socialists were represented as well as their German com- 
rades. But notwithstanding the common beginnings and 
intellectual identity of socialism in the two countries, the 
movement in Austria soon fell behind that of Germany. 
There were many reasons for this phenomenon, chief 
among them being the industrial backwardness of Austria, 
and the difficulty of carrying on a systematic and uniform 
propaganda of socialism among the many heterogeneous 
nationalities constituting the Austrian Empire. 

The beginnings of the socialist movement in Austria 
appear In. 1867, when the Imperial Council granted a partial 
right of assembly and association to the people of Austria. 
.Two years later the movement was strong enough to force 



the government to revoke its ban against socialist prop; 
ganda by a most remarkable and unexpected demonstra- 
tion on the streets of Vienna (December 13, 1869). The 
r succeeding period (1870-1888) is principally noteworthy 
I for the dissensions within the movement. The prac- 
tical disfranchisement of the working class and the 
brutal government persecution had bred among the more 
radical workingmcn a spirit of embittered pessimism which 
made them unusually susceptible to the propaganda of 
anarchism, then in its prime all over Europe, and the main 
work of Austrian social democracy during that period was 
to combat the anarchist movement. The turning point 
of the socialist movement in Austria may be considered the 
Hainsfeld Congress {1888), which marked the final victory 
of social democracy over anarchism in the Austrian labor 
movement, and created a unified and well -organized party 
which has since been making rapid and steady progress. 
In the parliamentary elections of 1907, for the first time 
held on the basis of universal suffrage, the Social Demo- 
cratic Party polled over 1,000,000 votes, electing no less 
than 87 deputies to the Reichsrat. 



I 
I 



Notwithstanding the fact that England is the most in- 
dustrial country of Europe, its socialist movement was 
rather tardy in appearing and in its growth. 

The organized socialist movement of England may be 
dated from the formation of the Democratic Federation in 
1881. The Federation, called into life by H. M. Hynd- 
man, Herbert Burrows and a few other well-known social- 
ists, was originally not of outspoken socialist views, but 



■ APPENDIX 347 

became so in 1883, when it was reorganized under the name 
of Social Democratic Federation. The Federation has 
ever since continued a somewhat uneventful existence, and 
is to-day the orthodox representative of Marxian socialism 
in England, 

In 1893 another political party of socialism was founded, 
principally through the efforts of Keir Hardie. The or- 
ganization assumed the name of Independent Labor Party, 
adopted a somewhat broader platform than that of the 
Social Democratic Federation, and laid more stress on the 
political side of the movement. But contrary to the 
expectations of its founders, it did not acquire a much 
larger following among the working classes of England 
than the older organization. 

Besides these two parties, the socialist movement of 
England is also represented by the well-known Fabian 
Society, founded in 1883, principally for the purpose of 
educational propaganda along socialist lines. The society 
has published a number of popular tracts on the main 
aspects of theoretical socialism and has achieved consider- 
able success in the field of municipal reform- The out- 
spoken socialist organizations in England are not a factor 
of great importance in the political life of the country, 
but it would be a mistake to measure the strength of the 
socialist movement in England only by its organized 
portions. 

The socialist sentiment in England largely expresses 
itself in the radical or "new" trade unions. These trade 
unions together with the Independent Labor Party and 
the Fabian Society constitute the Labor Party, which has 
32 representatives in the House of Commons. The Labor 

■ Party has recently adopted a very radical declaration of 



principles, and it Is the masses behind that party which 
to-day must be considered as the main factor making for 
socialism in England. i 



lidy 

The socialist movement in Italy antedates the Interna- 
tional. When the latter split between the adherents of 
Karl Marx and Michael Bakounin, the socialists of Italy, 
like those of almost all southern and economically back- 
ward countries, sided with Bakounin. 

The first manifestation of socialist political activity 
occurred in 1882, when several scattered socialist groups 
united for the ensuing parliamentary elections and nomi- 
nated candidates. The elections gave to the socialist 
candidates about 50,000 votes, 4 per cent of the total vote 
cast, and secured the return of two of them to parliament. 
Encouraged by this success, the socialists of Italy organ- 
ized a national Socialist Party in 1885, but the party made 
little progress, and between government persecutions and 
internal dissensions, it led a very precarious existence. 

It was only in 1892 that a socialist party, after the 
general European model, was organized in Italy, and since 
that time the socialist movement in Italy has made large 
and steady gains. In 1907 the party consisted of more 
than I200 local groups with a total dues- paying member- 
ship of over 38,000; it had 25 representatives in the 
Chamber of Deputies, and had control of about 100 
municipalities, besides having representatives in almost 
all other of the most important cities and towns of the 
kingdom. In 1904 the party polled 320,000 votes, about 
one iifth of the total number of votes cast in the country. 



k 



K 



APPENDIX 349 

hae of the most remarkable features of the socialist 
movement in Italy is its strength among the rural popula- 
tion of the country, principally the farm laborers; the 
membership of the Socialist Party is largely made up of 
them. The Socialist Party also took the initiative in 
organizing these laborers into an independent national 
organization. In 1900 that organization numbered over 
200,000 members. The organized socialist movement of 
Italy is divided into several camps on questions of policy 
and methods, but that does not seem to interfere with its 
, work or progress. 



Belgium and Holland 

The history of socialism in Belgium and in Holland is so 
much alike in many respects, that it may well be reviewed 
together. In both countries the movement had its incep- 
tion during the last years of the International ; in both 
coimtries the split of the International in 1872 divided the 
local movement into two hostile camps — the Marxists 
and Bakuninists, or Social Democrats and Anarchists — 
and in both the former finally prevailed. 

Belgium possesses the stronger movement. The first 
distinctly socialist political organization was founded in 
1885 under the name of Socialist Labor Party of Belgium. 
Notwithstanding the frequent dissensions and heated dis- 
putes among the Belgian socialists, the movement has 
made rapid progress. It has a large and influential press, 
and a strong organization. In 1908 the party polled 
about half a million votes and had 33 out of the 166 
members of the Belgian Parliament, 

The activity of the Belgian socialists is principally 



marked by their repeated and embittered struggles fiar 

universal suffrage, and by their successful organization of 
cooperative enterprises. 

The first political organization of socialism in Holland 
was the Social Democratic Union, founded in 1878 ; but it 
made but little progress until 1893, when the anarchistic 
elements under the leadership of the eloquent Domela 
Nieuvenhuis withdrew from it. The party is represented 
in parliament by seven deputies, and its methods and 
activity are practically those of the socialist movement of 
Belgium, though on a smaller scale. 

The Scandinavian Countries 



Another group of countries whose socialist history may 
be reviewed together, is that of Denmark, Sweden and 
Norway. Of these, the movement of Denmark is the 
oldest. It dates back to the days of the International, but 
the present socialist organization of the country, the Social 
Democratic Union, was founded in 1878. In 1889 the 
Danish socialists elected one deputy to the Folkething 
(parliament), out of a total of 114, and in 1907 the num- 
ber of their representatives rose to 28. In that year the 
party had over 35,000 dues-paying members and no less 
than 25 daily papers; it was also very successful in local 
politics, having elected over 850 councilors in different 
towns and villages. 

The movement in Sweden was initiated under Danish 
influence, and grouped itself around three socialist papers, 
the Social Democrat, published in Stockholm since 1885, 
the Arbetel (Worker), established in Malmo hi 1887, and 
the Ny Tid (New Times), founded in Gotheburg in 



APPENDIX 351 

1889, As in the case of Belgium and Holland, the main 
activity of the Socialist Party was for years directed to- 
wards the conquest of universal suffrage, and its cam- 
paign in that behalf was as picturesque as it was ener- 
getic and effective. The party has 15 representatives in 
Parliament. 

The socialist organization of Norway, the Norwegian 
Labor Party, was organized in 1887, but it constituted 
itself as a socialist political party only two years later. In 
the elections to the Storthing in 1906, the party polled 
about 45,000 votes and elected ten deputies; it also has 
several hundred representatives in the various municipal 
councils, a number of them being women. 

The distinguishing feature of the socialist movement in 
the three Scandinavian countries is its complete fusion 
and unity with the trade-union organizations. In fact, 
the organized working men of each of these countries up to 
a very few years ago constituted but one party, operating 
simultaneously or alternately on the economic and political 
fields. The types and methods of the socialist movement 
in the three countries are similar to such a point that joint 
conferences or conventions of the socialists of Denmark, 
Sweden and Norway are quite frequent. 



United Slates 

In the early part of the last century, the United States 
was the chief theater of communistic experiments. The 
disciples of Owen, Fourier, Weill ing and Cabet alike 
sought the realization of their Utopian ideals on Ameri- 
can soil, and during the decade 1840-1850, Fourierism in 
America developed great strength, both as an intellectual 



I 



movemcDt and as a practical experiment. Among its ad- 
herents were many persons of national reputation, such as 
Horace Greeley, Nathaniel Hawthorne, Charles A. Dana, 
Albert Brisbane, Margaret Fuller, George Ripley, John 
S. Dwight and William E. Channing. Among its ex- 
periments the famous Brook Farm and the North American 
Phalanx each lasted a number of years. 

But modern political socialism made its first appearance 
in the United States years after the Fourierist and other 
Utopian socialist movements had died out, and there 
seems to be no direct connection between that move- 
ment and its early Utopian precursors. The present 
socialist movement in America may be dated from 1868, 
when the Social Party of New York and Vicinity was 
organized. That party immediately after its formation 
nominated an independent ticket, but its vote was very 
insignificant, and the organization collapsed with its 
failure at the polls. The Social Party of New York and 
Vicmity was succeeded by the General German Labor 
Association, which in 1869 became the first local organi- 
zation or section of the International Workingmen's 
Association. Between 1869 and 1872, additional "sec- 
tions" of the International were organized in almost all 
the principal industrial centers of the United States from 
New York to San Francisco. The socialist movement 
thus organized by the International at the time seemed so 
promising, that the latter transferred its general council 
to the United States, but after a few years, and especially 
during the industrial crisis inaugurated by the collapse of 
the Northern Pacific in 1873, the organization rapidly 
disintegrated. 
g^^ first socialist political party on a national scope 



I 



APPENDIX 3S3 

oi^anized on American soil, was the Social Democratic 

Workingmen's Party, called into life on the 4th day of 
July, 1874. This party, together with several other then 
existing socialist organizations, merged into the Working- 
men's Party o( the United States in 1876. It was this 
party, which had in the meanwhile changed its name to 
Socialist Labor Party of North America, which main- 
tained the undisputed hegemony in the socialist movement 
during twenty-three years, and was largely instrumental 
in laying the foundation of the present socialist movement 
in this country. In 1892 the socialists of the United 
States for the first time nominated a presidential ticket, 
and they have since that time invariably adhered to the 
policy of independent politics, steadfastly refusing to ally 
themselves with any other political parties. 

But notwithstanding the untiring efforts and persistent 
propaganda of the Socialist Labor Party, the growth of 
the socialist movement in the United States was exceed- 
ingly slow and entirely out of keeping with that of the 
movement in other countries. As a matter of fact, the 
movement was largely borne by foreign workingmen, 
principally Germans, and until the end of the last century 
it did not succeed in acquiring a foothold in the broad 
masses of the native population ; but during the last decade 
a number of circumstances have combined to insure a 
more favorable reception to the gospel of socialism in the 
United States. The rapid industrial development of the 
country, accompanied by the growth of gigantic trusts and 
powerful labor unions, the growing intensity of the overt 
struggles between capital and labor, and the collapse of 
the populist and other reform movements, all served to 
prepare the soil for the socialist seed. Alongside of the 



^54 APFENDDC 

Socialist Labor Party, largely built on the narrow lines of 
a mere propaganda club, a new party, the Socialist 
Party, sprang up, absorbing the greater part of ttie 
members o£ the Socialist Labor Party, and attracting 
large numbers of new converts, Americans of all parts of 
the country, recruited principally from among the working 
class. The Socialist Party has at this time (1909) about 
3200 local organizations in the different states and terri- 
tories of the Union, with a dues-paying membership of 
I about 50,000. It polled a vote of 423,969 in the presi- 1 
[ dential election of 1908. Its press consists of more I 
I than fifty periodical publications in almost all languages I 
i spoken in America. The socialists have no representation I 
1 in the United States Congress, but they have lately con- 
quered a number of seats in several state legislatures 
and municipal councils. 

The New International j 

When the International Workingmen's Association was I 
formally dissolved at Philadelphia on July 15, 1876, the I 
last members of the expiring organization issued a proc- I 
lamation of which the following is a part: — 1 

'"The International is dead!' the bourgeoisie of all | 
countries will again exclaim, and with ridicule and joy it j 
will point to the proceedings of this convention as docu- 
mentary proof of the defeat of the labor movement of the 
world. Let us not be influenced by the cry of our ene- 
mies I We have abandoned the organization of the In- 
ternational for reasons arising from the present political 
situation of Europe, but as a compensation for it we see 
the principles of the organization recognized and defended 
_ by the progressive workingmen of the entire civilized 



^^b 



APPENDIX 355 

world. Let us give our fellow-workers in Europe a little 
time to strengthen their national affairs, and they will 
surely soon be in a position to remove the barriers between 
themselves and the workingmen of other parts of the 
world." 

The statement was prophetic. Only thirteen years later 
the first of the new series of international socialist and 
labor congresses was held in Paris, and it was followed by 
six more as follows; Brussels, 1891; Zurich, 1893; Lon- 
don, i8g6; Paris, 1900; Amsterdam, 1904, and Stuttgart, 
1907. And as the socialist movement grew and extended 
steadily during that period, so did each succeeding congress 
excel its predecessors in point of representation and gen- 
eral strength. The first Paris congress was attended by 
391 delegates (221 of them Frenchmen), representing 17 
countries of Europe and the United States; the Stuttgart 
congress was attended by about 1000 delegates, represent- 
ing 35 distinct countries of all parts of the world. 

At the London congress of 1896, it was resolved to try 
the experiment of establishing a permanent International 
Socialist Bureau with a responsible secretary, but the 
practical realization of the plan was left to the succeeding 
congress of 1900, which definitely created the Bureau and 
prescribed its functions. 

The International Socialist Bureau is now composed of 
two representatives of the organized socialist movement in 
each affiliated country. Its headquarters are located in 
Brussels, Belgium, and are in charge of a permanent secre- 
tary. The Bureau is the executive committee of the in- 
ternational congresses, and meets at such times as its 
business requires. In the intervals between its sessions it 
transacts its business by correspondence. 



356 APPENDIX 

During the experimental period of its existence the In- 
ternational Socialist Bureau seemed to hold out but scant 
promise of accomplishing practical results for the socialist 
movement. But within the last few years, the Inter- 
national Socialist Bureau has rapidly adapted itself to the 
needs of the movement, and to-day it is a useful and im- 
portant factor in the socialist movement of the world. It 
obtains and publishes from time to time valuable informa- 
tion on the progress and conditions of the socialist and 
labor movements of all countries; it advises on matters of 
socialist legislative activity, and it organizes the interna- 
tional congresses. The Bureau has established an archive 
of the socialist movement and has collected a library of 
socialist works, both of which are of the utmost impor- 
tance to the students of socialism; and finally the Bureau 
has often served as a medium for mutual assistance 
between the socialist and labor movements of the dif- 
ferent countries. 



n 



^H ^^^ 


Alcoholism ai a labor problem, 310. 


Cathrein, Victor, 106, iij. 


American Federation 1^ Labor, 339. 


Central Union of Germui Societies 


Anarchism, 16, 334, 3iS- 




Anacele, Edouard, a^s- 




Argenijon, Voyer d', 318. 


Chsnning, William E., 351. 


Army, uses of, 396. 


Chemyshefsky, Nicholas. 341. 


Aielrod, Paul, 344. 


Cbild labor, 334, >3i- 




City, the, under socialism, 13s. 


Babeuf, Franfois Noel, 333. 


Civiliiation, factors of, lao. 




"Class," definition of, 153. 




Class ethics, 53. 


Ball, Sidney, 17, 94. 


Class lines, vagueness of, 165, 1^7, 


Barbts, Armand, 358. 


Class struggle, the, S4. 60, 76, gsi 


Bai, E. Bdfort, 13, 49, 65, 80. 


doctrine of, 151; economic basis 


Baiard. Ajmand, 334. 


of. .57. 


B^bel, August, 89, 90, .30, 131, 13s, 


Commune, the. of Paris, 333, 337. 


138, 180, a8i. 336. 




Bellamy, Edward, .06. 




Bellom, Maurice, 359. 


passing of. a 8. 


Bcnoist. Charles. 94. 


Comte. Auguste, 33, 314. 


Bentham, Jeremy, 37, 43. 93' 


Conduct, human, 38. 


Bettrand, Louis, 346, 347. 


ConservatiTe Party, nature of, 163. 


Besant, Annie, no, 143. 


Considirant, Victor. 336. 


Bismarck, Prince, 183, ig^. 163. 


Cooperative Wholesale Sodely, Lim- 


Blanc, Louis, 3J6, 317. 


ited, 344. 


BUnqui, Louis, 338, 338. 


Crime and vice, 303. 


BUss, William D. P., 33r. 


Culture under socialism, 137. 


Bluntschli, Johann K^ 93. 


Curti, Theodor, 379. 


Boissel, Fransms. 323. 






Dana, Charles A., 316, 353. 


Braun, Adolf, »i8. 


Darwin, Charles, 46, 51. 


Briand, Aristide, 1S9. 


Darwin's theory of organic evolulioo. 


Brisbane, Albert, 336, 353. 


46. 47. 


British Parliament, origin of, 150. 


De leon, Daniel, 133. 


Brooks, John Graham, 367. 


Destrfe, Jules, 345. 346. 


Brousse, Paul, 338. 


Deviile, Gabriel, 94, 337. 338. 


Buelow, Chancellor voo, r93. 


Dewey, John, 36. 


Buonarotti, Fitippo, 314, 3^8. 


Dunckcr. Kale, 3:19. 


Burgess, J. W., 31,93. 


Dwight, John S., 353, 


Bunis. John, 189. 




Burrows. Herbert, 346. 


Economic basis of party politics, 161, 

163. 
Edison, Thomas A., isi. 


Cabet, Etiennc^ 336. 351. 


Candolie, de, i»8. 


Ely, Richard T., 30, 31, 33. 


3 


7 







358 



INDEX 



Emi^oyers' funds for the relief of 

workingmen, 257. 
Enfantin, Bartheldmy P., 324, 325. 
Engels, Frederick, 90, 91, 93, 98, 103, 

IIS, 154, 155. 3". 331- 
Esbjerg, municipal experiments in, 

301. 

Ethical ideal, 58, 65. 

Ethical motive, 45. 

Ethics, definitions of, 36, 37; bio- 
logical school, 43; hedonistic or 
Epicurean school, 4a, 45; intui- 
tional school, 41, 45; school of 
''natural laws," 41; theological 
school, 40, 45; utilitarian school, 
43; and law compared, 67, 69; 
and socialism, 36, 65. 

Factory reform, 215, a 18. 

Ferri, Enrico, 305, 306. 

Feudal laws, 77. 

Feudal society, the, development of, 
72, 76; nature of, 72, 75; class 
struggles in, 76; dissolution of, 75. 

Fichte, Johann Gottlieb, 330. 

Ford, Henry Jones, 148. 

Fourier, Charles, 106, 132, 137, 324, 
325. 326, 351. 

Franklin, Charles Kendall, 64. 

French parliament, origin of, 151. 

French Revolution, 8. 

Fuller, Margaret, 326, 352. 

Genius, place of, in social progress, 

121; fate of, imder capitalism, 

127. 
George, Henry, 291, 292, 293, 294. 
Germany, Social Democratic Party of, 

183. 
Ghent, W. J., 161, 167. 
Giddings, Franklin H., 93. 
Godwin, Parke, 326. 
Goes, F. V. d., 23. 
"Good Government" movement, 

271. 
Government ownership, 284, 288. 
Graham, William, 106, 115. 
Greeley, Horace, 326, 352. 
Gronlund, Laurence, 106, 136. 
Grotius, Hugo, 41. 
Gufesde, Jules, 337, 338, 339. 
Guyot, Yves, 18. 



Haeckel, Ernst, 50. 

Hardie, Keir, 347. 

Hawthorne, Nathaniel, 359. 

Herkner, Heinrich, 226, aay, 267. 

Herzen, Alexander, 340, 341. 

Hill, Octavia, 316. 

Hirsch, Paul, 307. 

Hobson, John A., 226, 339, 234, 278, 

279. 
HofiFding, Harald, 37.. 
Housing problem, the, 3x4. 
Hunter, Robert, 192. 
Huxley, Thomas, 15, 59. 
Hyndman, H. M., 346. 

Ihering, Rudolph von, 69, 71. 

Incentive in art, 124; in science^ 124; 
to work, 128. 

Indirect results of the socialist propa- 
ganda, 193. 

Indirect taxes, definition of, 289. 

Individual genius as a factor of social 
progress, 120; in public life, 123; 
in science, 122; in industry, 121. 

Individual initiative, scope of, 123. 

Individual the, and society, 18, 24; 
under socialism, 29. 

Individualism, the system of, 12; in 
industry, 24. 

Industrial reforms, 214. 

Initiative, definition of, 279. 

Insurance of workingmen against 
accidents, 261; sickness, 261. 

Intellectuals, economic position of, 
160. 

Intemperance, 309. 

International Workingmen's Associa- 
tion, 85, 333, 334, 335. 

Jaur^, Jean, 138, 190, 338, 339. 
Jenks, Edward, 150, 151. 

Kant, Immanuel, 41, 43, 45, 50. 

Kari, J. K., 190. 

Kautsky, Karl, 60, no, 116, 119, 132, 

133, 188, 189, 313. 
Kerr, Charles H., 196. 
Kidd, Benjamin, 22. 
Koehler, Oswald, no. 
Kotlyarevski, S., 177. 
Kropotkin, P., ao. 



^H|^H^ INDEX 3S9 ^1 


^^^•Labor Groups," 135- 


Money under socialism, 118. 


Labor mnvcmeDt, functions of, 9. 


Moral conduct, meanizig oE, 54. 


Labriola, Arturo, 13B, 139. 


Moral sense, evolution of, 46. 


Latargue, Paul, 74, 338. 


Morelly, loS, 3aj. 323. 


Lamennaig, Jean, 318, 317. 


Morgan, Lewis H.. jo. 


La Monte. Robert Rives, 56. 


Morris, William, 106. 


LassaUe, Ferdinand, 137, 179, 349. 


"Municipal Sodaliam," 194, 


=■8., =189, 335, 336. 




Lavraff, Peter, 341- 


Nieuvenhuis, Domcla, 350. 


Lan, the substance of, 66; and ethics 


"Nihilism," definition of, 341, 


compared, S7. 


Novikov, M. J., 22. 


Letoy-Beaulieu, Paul, 94. 




Lesseps, Ferdinand de, 334. 


Odin, A„ isa. 


Liberal Patty, nature of. 163. 


Old-age pensions, 262, 


Liebig, Justus Von, 311, 3H. 


Ostrogorski, M., 269, 270. 


Licbknecht, Karl, agS. 


Owen, Robert, loS, 33S, 329, 330, 351, 


Liebicnecht, WUhelm. 107, 14J, 143, 




173, '»'' ■8". 185. 336- 


Parliaments under socialism, 139. 


Lille, municipal eiptriraeats in, 199. 


Parry, David M,, 29, 107. 


Lindwurm, Arnold, 68. 


Parsons, Frank, 283, 287. 


Liszt, Frani von, 306, 307. 


Parvus, 239. 


Lloyd, Henry D., 30. 


Patton, Francis L., 36. 




Peel, Robert, 315, 218. 


Loria, Achillc, Si, 8a, B3. 


Phitosophy, socialist, 3. 


Louis, Paul, 164, 171, 


Plekhanoff, George, 344. 


Luiemburg, Rosa, 229. 


Political action, objections to, 171; 






Mably, Gabriel. 106, 313. 


Political alliances with the old parties 


Macdonald, J. Ramsay, 35. 


as a danger to the working dass, 


Machinery, social effects of, aj. 


176. 


Maison du Peuple of Brussels, 246. 


Political centralization, 133. 


Mallock, W. H., 107. 


Political parties, origin of. 146; in 


Malon, Benoil, ..0, 139, ,4a. 338. 


France, 1471 in Great Britain, 146; 


Marx, Karl, ji, ja, 114, 115, '3', '34, 


in the United States, 148, 165. 


'55, 157. 179. 3=4, 331. 33", 333. 


Political party, attributes of, 152. 


335. 348. 


Political reform movements, 140. 




Politics, definition of, 144; in autoc- 


Massachusetts Bill of Rights. 19. 


racy, 144; in countries of consti- 


"May Day" celebration, origin of, 


tutional government, 145- 






Menger, Anton, 93, 99. no. 135, 136, 


140. 


'37. '*'• 


Production under socialism, mi. 


"Middle Classes," economic position 




of, 160. 




Militarism, evils of, 297. 299. 


Progrfe, cooperalive society, 247- 


Militia, system of. in Switzerland, 300. 


Progrpssive income lax, definition of. 


MiUerand. Etienne, 187, 338. 335- 




"Ministerialism" in socialist politics. 


Progressive inheritance tax, defini- 


'87. 190. 


tion of, a9°- 


ModemUw, nature of, 81. 


"Proletariat," definition of, 155. 






Monaichy. socialist view of, 137. 


Proudhon. Pierre J., 326, 327. 



^^Kjte ^^^I^^^^H 


I TUdicol Patty, nature of, 164- 


Socialism and the afcohud proUem, 


Kae, John, 213. 


313; and the cooperative move- 


Reeve, SEdncy A„ 17. 


ment, 353; and individualism, 19; 


Referendum, deGnition of, ijj; Ini- 


and single tai compared, 394. 


tiative and Right of RecaU, 377, 


Socialist ethics, 63. ^_ 


1 3S1 i limitatioos oi, 14s. 


Socialist jurisprudence S7 ^^^| 


Socialist Puty, composition of, 169; ^H 






of, M9- 




Republic, socialist view of, 137. 


parliamenlary tactics, 181; politi- | 


Kichtcr. Eugen, jg, 106. 


cal tactics of, 174; poUtical £so- 






"Right" and "Wrong" conduct. 


wilh other parties, 179; political 


meaning of, 6a, 63. 


achievements of, 190. 


' Right of Recall, definition of. >&>. 




1 Hiis, JacobA., 3t8. 


187. 


Ripley, Geotge, 336, 35a. 


Socialist reforms, and ''middle class" 


' Ritchie, David G.. 96. 


reforms compared, aoB; nature ol, ' 


Rocbdale Pioneeis, society of, 143- 


ao7, 309. ^m 


1 Sodbertus, Karl, 137. 


Socialist state, the. 89, 98, 100, 105; ^^M 


Rodrigue, Olindc, 334. 


143; functions of. i4>; probatdB ^H 


1 Rogers, Thorold,>i9. 


^^1 


Roman Empire, fall of, S. 


Socialist working program, iqb, ^^M 


Roubaii, mucicipia eiperiments in, 


Society and the individual, 18. ^H 


166. 


Spargo, John, no, 330. ^H 


Rouiseau, Jean Jacques, 14. 313. 


Spencer, Herbert, 39, 37. 38, 44, 58, ^M 

59, 60. 6r. ^m 

Standing armies in Europe, 397. ^H 


1 Saint-Simon, Charle* Henri. la, 137. 


3»4, 3'5- 




Sassulich, Vera, 343. 344- 


attributes of, 93; functions of, iS. ^H 


Scevola. Mudus. 33. 


Steffens. Lincoln, 271. ^H 


Schaeffle, Adolph, 115, 365. 


Stephen, Leslie. 53. ^H 


School children, feeding and clothing 


Stem. J., rag. ^H 


of. 197. 30I. 


Stewart, Ira, iii, 333. ^^M 


Schulze-Dditsch, 148. »49. 


Slimer, Man. 15. 16. ^H 


Scburi, Carl. 3og. 


Struve, Peter, la. ^^M 


Scottiah Co6peratiTe Wholesale So- 


Suffrage, restrictions on, 170. ^^M 


ciety. 344. 


"Surplus Value," 157. ^H 


Serwy. Victor, 351. 




Seymour, Thomas D., nS. 137. 


Tamowsky, B.. 304. ^^M 


Shaw, G. Bernard, 110. 


Tax reforms, 388. ^^^^^H 


Shorter workday, aiS. 


Thompson. Carl D„ loa. ^^^^^^M 


1 Sidgwick, Henry, 37, 43, 6?. 


Toiiueville, Alexis de, r46. ^^^^^^H 


1 Simons. A. M.. 395. 


Tortori. Alfredo. 71. ^^^^^H 


"Single Tax," the, 391. 


Trade-union movement, 336. ^^^^^H 


1 Smith, Adam, 14, ii4- 


Trade unions, function of, 337, >7^^^^| 


1 Social classes in feudal society, 73. 




Social development, laws of, 30. 


pared. 336. ^M 


L Soda) legislation, cause of, Sj ; na- 


Transitional state, the, 98. 100. ^H 


' ture of. 85. 


Trusts, social effects of. id. ^^M 




Turgenief, Ivan, 341. ^^M 


^^^L Sodal utolaai, 106. 


Turner, George, asj. ^H 



INDEX 



361 



Universal Suffrage movement, 272. 
Uomo deliquente, description of, 304. 
"Utopian socialism," origin of, 321; 
forms of, 333. 

Vail, Charles H., 35. 

Vaillant, Edouard, 260, 267, 298, 299, 

302, 338. 
Vollmar, Georg von, 281. 
Value, socialist theory of, 156. 
Vandervelde, ^mil, 245, 246. 
Veblen, Thorstein, 35. 
Viviani, 189. 

Voluntary state insurance, 258. 
Voaruii, the, 245. 

Waldeck-Rousseau, 187, 339. 
Wallace, Alfred Russel, 49, 51. 
Ward, Lester F^ ax, 44, 5a, 120, 125, 
128, 



Wars, causes of, 61 ; moral effects of, 

60. 
Wealth as incentive to exertion, 124; 

distribution of, 28, 116. 
Weitling, Wilhdm, 106, 330, 351. 
Williams, C. M., 50. 
Willoughby, William F., 225, 226, 

267. 
Woman labor, 231; growth of, 233. 
Woman Suffrage movement, 273, 

281. 
Workingmen's insurance, 254. 
Working women, wages of, 233. 
Wright, Carroll D., 92, 216, 217. 
Wurm, Emanuel, 3x0, 3XX, 3x2. 

Zadek, Dr. J., 221, 222. 
Zerboglio, A., 79. 
Zetkin, Clara, 281, 282. 



j • 

i 

I 
5 
I 1 






3- I 



m 




I 



i 







w 

r 



I 'A f. 



».\ 



/