Skip to main content

Full text of "Spinoza, his life and philosophy"

See other formats


HANDBOUND 
AT  THE 


UNIVERSITY  OF 
TORONTO  PRESS 


7*!**- 


7t^^ 


> 


SPINOZA 


/ 


1 


Benedictus   de  Spikoza 


Cui  na±ura.,T>tMs.reruxn  cui  coe"nxius   ordo. 
Hoc  Spinola  ftalru  conlpiciencius    erat: 

Hxpreflere  viri  laciem.feci  pine-ere  xnentem 
Z^uxiJis   artifices  .  not!  valuere  tnanus  . 

Ilia  vi^^i:     Tcrrplris  :  Jiic  fuDlimia  tractat: 
Hiuicauicunquecupis  nolcere.fcripta  leg-e . 


-A 


\ 


\ 


.^d?^ 


SPINOZA 


HIS     LIFE     AND     PHILOSOPHY 


BY 


FREDERICK    POLLOCK 

BARRISTER-AT-LA\V  :    LATE  FELLOW  OF  TRINITY  COLLEGE,   CAMBRIDGE,   AND 
HONORARY  DOCTOR  OF   LAWS  OF  THE   UNIVERSITY  OF  EDINBURGH 


'  WeUseele,  komm,  uns  z:t  durcJidringen  ! 
Datin  7nit  detn  Weligeist  sclbst  zu  ringen, 

Wird  nnsrer  Krcifie  Hochheruf. 
Tkeilnehmend filkre ii  gute  Geister, 
Gclinde  leitetui,  tiSchste  Meister, 

Zit  detn,  der  alles  schafft  und  schnf 

Goethe  ;  Eins  und  Alles. 


LONDON 
C.  KEGAN  PAUL  &  CO.,  i  PATERNOSTER  SQUARE 

1880 


s 

91 


v5 


YTIie  rights  of  translation  and  of  rcprodiulion  are  reset  ved) 


A 


TO     THE    MEMORY     OF 
MY    FRIEND 

WILLIAM    KINGDOM    CLIFFORD 

HOMO    LIBER 

DE    NULLA    RE    MINUS 

QUAM     DE     MORTE     COGITAT 


i 


CONTENTS. 


[Note. —  Throughout  this  Table  and  the  Index  the  abbreviation  Sp.  is 
used  for  Spinoza,  except  where  it  might  be  ambiguous^ 

INTRODUCTION. 

PAGE 

Preliminary      . .         .         .  xv 

Sp.'s  Works  ;  original  publications     .......  xvi 

Editions xvii 

Translations xix 

Authorities  for  Sp.'s  life xxii 

Portraits  of  Sp xxvi 

Early  literature  relating  to  Sp. xxvii 

English  books xxxi 

*  Modern  accounts  of  Sp.'s  philosophy xxxv 

Special  monographs xxxix 

CHAPTER   I. 

THE   LIFE   OF    SPINOZA. 

Birth  of  Sp I 

The  Jewish  Settlement  at  Amsterdam 3 

Their  leaders  :  Manasseh  ben  Israel 6 

Uriel  da  Costa 8 

State  of  Jewish  education .     .  10 

Sp.'s  training  in  youth  :  Van  den  Ende 11 

Story  of  Clara  van  den  Ende 13 

Difficulties  with  the  synagogue 16 

Attempt  on  Sp.'s  life  :  excommunication 17 

Change  of  name  :  lawsuit  with  sisters 20 

Changes  of  residence 22 

Friendship  and  correspondence  with  Simon  de  Vries         .        .        .23 

Friendship  with  Oldenburg 25 


Vlll 


CONTENTS. 


Correspondence  as  to  publication  of  his  works   . 

The  '  Principles  of  Descartes'  Philosophy '  published     . 

The  '  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus  '  published 

Controversy,  and  prohibition  of  the  book 

Invitation  to  Heidelberg  declined       .... 

French  invasion  of  1672  :  Sp.'s  visit  to  Conde's  quarters 

Plan  of  publishing  '  Ethics '  abandoned 

Death  of  Sp 

Publication  of '  Opera  Posthuma '       .        .        .        . 
Sp.'s  manner  of  life 


PAGE 
26 

30 
31 

33 
34 
36 
38 
39 
,  40 
,     41 


CHAPTER    II. 
Spinoza's  correspondence. 

Letters  not  strictly  philosophical  the  subject  of  this  chapter       .         .  44 

Sp.  questioned  by  Blyenbergh  on  origin  of  evil 46 

His  reply,  and  further  correspondence 47 

Reason  and  Scripture 50 

Anthropomorphism  of  theology 53 

Close  of  the  correspondence   ...                 .        .                 .     .  56 

Letter  to  Peter  Balling  on  omens 56 

Anonymous  correspondent  on  ghosts 59 

Sp.  on  perfections  of  divine  nature 63 

Letter  on  an  alchemical  experiment 64 

Reply  to  Van  Velthuysen's   criticism   on  '  Tractatus   Theologico- 
politicus  ' 65 

Sp.'s  general  view  of  religion 69 

Later  correspondence  with  Van  Velthuysen  as  to  publication     .        .  70 

Correspondence  and  acquaintance  with  Leibnitz 71 

With  Tschirnhau  :;n 72, 

Letter  from  Albert  Burgh  on  his  conversion  to  Church  of  Rome  .     .  75 

Sp.'s  answer 77 

CHAPTER    III. 

IDEAS   AND    SOURCES   OF    SPINOZA's    PHILOSOPHY. 


'^  Pari  I. — Judaism  and  Nco-Platonisni. 

Philosophy  must  renounce  finality 80 

Ideas  permanent,  not  systems 83 

Leading  ideas  of  Sp.  :  uniformity  (pantheism) 84 

Identity  of  body  and  mind  (monism) 85 

Self-preserving  effort  (natural  law) 86 


CONTENTS. 


IX 


General  view  of  sources  of  these  ideas 
Uniformity  :  the  Essay  on  God  and  Man 
Not  Cartesian  in  metaphysics  . 
Sp.'s  metaphysics  developed  from  theology 
Jewish  theologico-philosophical  authors    . 

Maimonides 

Chasdai  Creskas 

Alleged  influence  of  Kabbalah  on  Sp.  . 

Possible  allusions  to  it  in  Sp.     . 

Giordano  Bruno  and  Avicebron    . 

Points  of  resemblance  in  Bruno  and  Sp.   .... 

Part  II. — Descartes. 

Influence  on  Sp.  most  important  in  physics .         .         .         , 
Sp.'s  '  things  immediately  produced  by  God '    . 

Motion  and  Rest  treated  as  things 

Descartes'  axiom  of  conservation  oi  quantity  of  nioiion    . 
His  consequent  errors  ........ 

Aim  of  his  physical  speculations        ..... 

Sp.'s  criticism  of  Descartes 

Derivation  of  principle  of  self-conservation  from  Descartes 
Sp.'s  gradual  divergence  from  Descartes  in  psychology 


87 

89 

90 

92 

93 

94 

95 

97 

100 

102 

104 


107 
108 
109 
no 
III 
112 
114 
116 
118 


CHAPTER    IV. 


THE    DOCTRINE    OF    METHOD. 

*  Sp.'s  treatise  '  De  Intellectus  Emendatione' 

Search  for  the  Chief  Good    . 

Contrast  with  Descartes'  object 
,    The  good  to  be  aimed  at 
'  Knowledge  and  its  degrees 

The  test  of  truth    . 

Double  use  of  idea  by  Sp. . 

Reflective  knowledge    . 

Problems  of  method  stated 

Fiction  and  error  . 

Sp.'s  conception  of  truth    . 

Sp.'s  '  most  perfect  being '    . 
'  Doubt  and  imagination 
0  Discipline  of  the  reason 

Theory  of  definition  . 

Sp.'s  definition  includes  explanation 

'  Eternal  things '         .        .         . 

Identified  with  '  infinite  modes  '  of  Ethics 


121 

122 
123 

125 
126 
128 

131 
133 
i35 

139 
141 

143 
145 
146 

147 
150 
152 


CONTENTS. 
CHAPTER    V. 

THE   NATURE    OF   THINGS. 


PAGE 


State  of  philosophical  ideas  and  terms  in  Sp.'s  time         .         .         .  156 

Sp.'s  geometrical  method 157 

Definitions  of  ^////tj',  Part  i      .         .        .        ,        .        .        .        .159 

Sp.'s  causa  sui  and  conception  of  Cause 160 

Substance 162 

Attributes 163 

Modes 165 

Infinity  of  Attributes .166 

Parallehsm  of  Attributes 168 

Difficulties  of  Sp.'s  theory 171 

Implicit  ideahsm  of  the  system 175 

Kant's  approximation 176 

Summary 178 

Sp.  on  infinity '.         .     .  179 

On  notions  of  time,  measure,  and  number 181 

Sp.'s  '  aids  of  the  imagination '  not  Kantian 185 

Note  on  the  Infinite  Modes 187 


CHAPTER   VI. 

»  BODY   AND    MIND.    *> 

The  doubleness  of  experience 189 

Subject  and  Object,  Mind  and  Matter 190 

Theories  of  relation  between  Mind  and  Matter  — .        .         .        .     .  192 

Sp.'s  account 193 

Complexity  of  human  mind 195 

Doctrine  of  association 196 

Coufased  knowledge  and  error 198 

Universals. .  200 

Degrees  of  knowledge 201 

Sp.'s  determinism     v 202 

No  distinct  faculties  of  mind 205 

Will  and  judgment 206 

Automatism  of  body 207 

Advantages  of  necessarianism  according  to  Sp 210 

No  distinct  theory  of  perception  in  Sp. 212 


CONTENTS.  xi 
.   ^  ''^             CHAPTER   VII. 

THE   NATURE   OF    MAN. 

PACE 

Preface  to  Part  3  of  £'//;/Vj- 214 

Self-preservation 216 

Sp.'s  use  of  conatus 218 

_What  is  a //////o- ? 219 

Self-preservation  and  desire 221 

Self-preservation  as  incident  to  life 222 

Pleasure  and  pain 224 

Love,  hatred,  &c 226 

Extension  of  emotions  by  sympathy 228 

Active  emotions     . 230 

The  definitions  of  the  emotions 233 

CHAPTER   VIII. 

THE    BURDEN    OF    MAN. 


Introduction  to  Part  4  of  Ethics    . 
Remarks  on  the  argument  from  design 
Perfection  and  imperfection,  good  and  evil 
Emotion  controllable  only  by  emotion 
The  life  according  to  reason  . 
Agreement  of  Sp.  with  the  Stoics 
Development  of  ethical  doctrine  . 
Virtue  as  intelligence         .... 
Element  of  common-sense  morality  in  Sp. 

Society  and  law 

What  things  are  useful .... 

Enjoyment  of  life       ..... 

Returning  good  for  evil 

Some  passions  relatively  good  . 

The  reasonable  or  free  man  . 

Sp.'s  appendix  of  maxims  .... 


245 
246 
250 
252 
253 
255 
257 
258 
260 
261 
262 
264 
265 
266 
268 
271 


CHAPTER    IX. 

THE    DELIVERANCE    OF    MAN. 


The  power  of  reason 

Criticism  of  Descartes'  physical  theory  of  will 
Division  of  Part  5  of  Ethics 
The  government  of  the  passions 


278 
279 
280 
283 


xii  CONTENTS. 

PAGE 

The  use  of  moral  precepts 285 

The  love  of  God 287 

The  eternity  of  the  mind       .........  288 

Aristotelian  and  Averroist  doctrines  of  immortality  :  Gersonides     .  289 

Sp.'s  argument 292 

Discussion  of  his  meaning 295 

•  The  mind's  knowledge  '  under  the  form  of  eternity '     .         .        .     .  296 

The  '  intellectual  love  of  God ' 300 

Return  to  physical  aspect  :  concurrent  development  of  body  and 

mind 303 

Morahty  independent  of  eternity  of  mind 305 

Virtue  its  own  reward ,  306 

Conclusion  of  the  Ethics 30S 

CHAPTER   X. 

THE   CITIZEN    AND    THE   STATE. 

Sp.  as  publicist  belongs  to  English  school 310 

Relation  to  Hobbes 313 

Theory  of  sovereignty  as  compared  with  Hobbes          .         .         •     •  315 

Sovereignty  never  absolute 317 

Special  revelations  not  to  hold  against  law 319 

Review  of 'Tractatus  Pohticus  ' 321 

Scientific  treatment  of  subject 323 

General  ideas 325 

'  Natural  right ' 327 

The  State  and  its  power 328 

Can  the  State  do  wrong  ? 330 

Ideal  of  government 332 

Ideal  of  special  forms  of  government  :  Monarchy        .         .         .     .  333 

Aristocracy         . 233 

Federal  government 334 

Democracy 336 

The  treatise  broken  off 338 


^    CHAPTER   XL 

/^    SPINOZA    AND    THEOLOGY. 

Theology  and  philosophy 340 

Sp.'s  personal  position  ..........  341 

Criticism  of  theological  doctrines  in  Ethics,  Part  i  :  necessity  of 

God's  action 343 

Things  could  not  have  been  otlierwise 344 


CONTENTS. 


xm 


Deity  and  moral  law 
Final  causes  .... 
God  as  conceived  by  Sp.    . 
The  'infinite  understanding' 
*  Personality         .... 
Sp.'s  pantheism 
Sp.  on  historical  revelations 
The  voice  from  Sinai     . 
Revelation  in  general 
Religion  and  morality   . 
Sp.  on  pre-eminence  of  Christ   . 
Sp.'s  letters  to  Oldenburg  on  the  Resurrection 
Religion  as  guide  of  life  for  the  unlearned 


346 
348 
352 
353 
354 
355 
357 
360 

361 
363 
365 
366 
368 


CHAPTER   XII. 


SPINOZA   AND    MODERN    THOUGHT. 


Nature  of  Sp.'s  influence        .... 

Early  controversy  in  Netherlands 

Spinozistic  heresies  in  the  Reformed   Church 

X  Leenhof 

XIartesian  opposition  ;  attitude  of  Leibnitz 

Slight  notice  by  English  philosophers  . 

English  theological  criticism 

French  writers  on  Sp 

Voltaire 

Boulainvilliers        ..... 

Montesquieu's  knowledge  of  Sp. 

Lessing's  vindication  of  Sp.  . 

Conversation  with  Jacobi  . 

Goethe  ....... 


van  Hattem  and 


Later  recogition  of  Sp.  in  Germany  . 

Post-Kantian  philosophers    . 

Study  of  Sp.  in  England  :  Coleridge 

Shelley's  intended  translation 

Later  English  criticism 

Study  of  Sp.  in  France .... 

Bicentenary  commemoration  in  Holland 


373 

375 

376 

379 
381 

383 
386 

387 
388 

389 
390 
391 
394 
397 
397 
400 

403 
404 

405 

405 


xiN'  COXTENTS. 

APPENDIX   A. 

PAGE 

The  Life  of  Spinoza  by  Colerus         .......     409 

APPENDIX   B. 

Ordinance  of  July  19,  1674,  condemning  the  *  Tractatus  Theologico- 

politicus ' 444 

APPENDIX   C. 

1.  Dutch  originals  of  certain  letters  of  Sp.         ...  .     446 

2.  Unpublished  letter  of  Sp.  to  Dr.  Meyer  (in  V.  Cousin's  library)  .     447 

APPENDIX   D. 
Circular  of  the  Spinoza  Committee 45 1 

APPENDIX   E. 
Table  showing  Sp.'s  position  in  the  history  of  Philosophy  456 

INDEX ....     457 


Erratum. 
Page  45,  )iote  i,  the  first  essendi  should  be  existendi 


INTRODUCTION, 


The  purpose  of  this  book  is  to  put  before  English  readers  an 
account,  fairly  complete  in  itself  and  on  a  fairly  adequate 
scale,  of  the  life  and  philosophy  of  Spinoza.  It  aims,  in  the 
first  instance,  at  being  understood  by  those  who  have  not 
made  a  special  study  of  the  subject  ;  but  I  hope  that  it  may 
also  be  not  useless  to  some  who  already  know  Spinoza  at  first 
hand,  and  even  to  critical  students  of  philosophy.  In  order 
to  reconcile  these  objects  as  far  as  possible,  I  have  thought  it 
well  to  collect  once  for  all  in  this  introductory  chapter  a 
certain  amount  of  critical  and  bibliographical  matter,  which 
the  reader  who  is  interested  in  it  will  thus  find  ready  to  his 
hand,  while  the  less  curious  may  with  equal  ease  pass  it  over. 
I  propose  here,  not  to  enter  at  large  on  the  bibliography  and 
literature  of  Spinoza,  but  to  give  sufficient  indications  to  any 
one  who  desires  to  go  further  on  his  own  account.  This  will 
involve  some  partial  repetition  of  matters  elsewhere  touched 
upon  in  the  course  of  the  book.  But  I  prefer  repetition  to 
obscurity. 

First  let  me  premise  that  a  most  useful,  one  may  indeed 
say  an  indispensable,  companion  to  anything  like  a  critical 
study  of  Spinoza  is  Dr.  A.  van  der  Linde's  Bencdictus  Spiuoaa  : 
Bibliografie  (the  Hague,  1871).  This  is  a  classified  catalogue 
of  the  literature  of  the  subject,  which,  if  not  absolutely  com- 
plete, is  as  complete  down  to  its  date  as  the  learning  and 
industry  of  one  man  could  in  the  nature  of  things  make  it. 
While  I  am  mentioning  the  work  of  a  Dutch  scholar,  I  may 
at  the  same  time  gratefully  acknowledge  my  personal  obliga- 
tions to  several  members  of  the  Spinoza  Memorial  Committee 

a 


xvi  INTRODUCTION. 

in  the  Netherlands  for  help  and  information  freely  given  on 
various  points.  Herein  I  am  specially  bound  to  Dr.  Betz,  the 
Secretary  of  the  Committee,  Dr.  Campbell,  of  the  Royal 
Library  at  the  Hague,  and  Professor  Land,  of  Leyden. 

What  has  to  be  said  here  may  be  distributed  under  the 
following  heads  : — 

L  Editions  and  translations  of  Spinoza's  works. 
IL  Authorities  for  Spinoza's  life. 
III.  The  early  or  controversial  stage  of  Spinoza  literature. 
VL  Modern  writings  on  Spinoza's  philosophy  as  a  whole. 
V.  Monographs  and  special  discussions  treating  of  parts 
(especially  the  De  Deo  et  Honiine)  and  particular 
aspects  of  Spinoza's  work. 
Dr.  van  der  Linde's  work  is  referred  to  as  Bibliogr.  simply. 
It  brings  us  down,  as  I  have  said,  to  1871.     Much  more  has 
appeared  since  that  time,  as  to  which  I  can  only  call  attention 
to  the  more  important  of  the  publications  with  which  I  have 
become  acquainted.     In  some  few  particulars  I  am  able  to 
supplement  Dr.  van  der  Linde's  information  as  to  writings  of 
earlier  date. 

I.  The  Works  of  Spinoza. 

These,  in  the  original  order  of  publication,  are  as  follows  : — 

1.  Renati  des  Cartes  Principiorum  Philosophiae  pars  I  &  II, 
more  geometrico  demonstratae  per  Benedictum  de  Spinoza 
Amstelodamensem.  Accesserunt  ejusdem  cogitata  meta- 
physica,  &c.     Amsterdam,  1663. 

2.  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus,  continens  dissertationes 
aliquot,  quibus  ostenditur  libertatem  philosophandi  non 
tantum  salva  pietate  et  reipublicae  pace  posse  concedi :  sed 
eandem  nisi  cum  pace  reipublicae  ipsaque  pietate  tolli  non 
posse.  Hamburg  (really  Amsterdam),  1670.  Some  notes  of 
Spinoza's  own  to  this  treatise  came  to  light  later.  See  Bruder's 
preface,  and  Ed.  Bohmer  :  Ben.  de  Sp.  Tractatus  de  Deo  et 
Homine  &c.  atque  Adnotationes  ad  Tractatum  Thcologico- 
politicum.     Halle,  1852. 

3.  B.  d.  S.  Opera  Posthuma.  Amsterdam,  1677.  The  con- 
tents arc : 


INTRODUCTION.  xvii 

Ethica  ordine  geometrico  demonstrata. 

Tractatus  politicus. 

Tractatus  de  intcllectus  emendatione. 

Epistolae    doctorum    quorundam  virorum  ad  B.  d.  S. 

et  auctoris  responsiones. 
Compendium  grammatices  linguae  hebrasae. 

4.  (Tractatus  de  Iride.)  Stelkonstige  reeckening  van 
den  Regenboog.     The  Hague,  1687.     {Bibliogr.  no.  -^6) 

This  work  was  long  lost  sight  of  and  supposed  to  have 
perished.  It  was  recovered  and  reprinted  by  Dr.  van  Vloten 
in  his  Supplementum  (see  below). 

5.  Letter  of  Spinoza  to  Dr.  Lambert  van  Veldhuysen. 
1844.  Published  by  Prof  Tydeman,  and  given  in  ed.  Bruder 
as  Ep.  75.     {Bibliogr.  no.  35.) 

6.  Ad  Benedicti  de  Spinoza  opera  quae  supersunt  omnia 
supplementum.     Amsterdam,  1862. 

By  Dr.  J.  van  Vloten.  Uniform  with  Bruder's  ed.  (see 
below),  so  as  to  make  a  supplementary  volume  to  it.  Contains 
Spinoza's  early  Essay  on  God  and  Man,  the  Treatise  on  the 
Rainbozi',  and  some  letters  and  parts  of  letters  not  before 
published. 

7.  Li  1705  two  letters  written  in  Dutch  by  Spinoza,  and 
including  a  paragraph  not  given  in  the  Opera  Posthuma,  ap- 
peared in  a  periodical  called  Boekzaal  der  Geleerde  Wen'elt. 
They  seem  to  have  been  forgotten  till  Prof  Land  quite 
recently  lighted  upon  them  :  see  his  paper  reprinted  from  the 
proceedings  of  the  Dutch  Academy  of  Sciences,  '  Over  de 
eerste  uitgaven  der  brieven  van  Spinoza,'  Amsterdam,  1879; 
and  Appendix  C  to  this  book, 

8.  Letter  of  Spinoza  to  Dr.  Meyer  of  Aug.  3,  1663.  French 
translation  given  by  Saisset,  Q^uvrcs  de  Spino.ca,  iii.  458.  The 
original  is  printed  for  the  first  time  in  this  book  (Appendix  C). 
This  letter  might  conveniently  be  cited  as  Ep.  xxix.  a. 

Three  collected  editions  of  Spinoza's  works  have  been 
published  :  by  Paulus  (Jena,  1802,  2  vols.),  Gfrorer  (Stuttgart, 
1830),  and  Bruder  (Leipzig,  1843-6,  3  vols.).  Full  titles  and 
particulars  in  Bibliogr.  38,  39,  41.  The  edition  by  Paulus  is 
still  useful  to  the  student,  as  all  the  authorities  then  known 
for  the  life  of  Spinoza  are  conveniently  brought  together  in 

a  2 


xviii  INTRODUCTION. 

the  Collectanea  at  the  end  of  vol.  ii.  Unfortunately  the  text 
is  by  no  means  free  from  misprints ;  and  more  unfortunately 
this  edition  seems  to  have  been  used  to  print  from  in  both 
Gfrorer's  and  Bruder's,  and  some  serious  errors,  though  not 
all,  thus  remain  uncorrected.  I  have  noted  the  following  in 
the  Ethics : — 

Part  I,  Prop.  22  :  '  Quicquid  ex  altquo  Dei  attributo,'  &c. 
So  6?//.  Post/i.,  as  the  sense  requires.  All  the  modern  editions 
give  alio. 

Part  3,  Prop.  2i,  Demonst. :  '  Deinde  quatenus  res  aliqua 
tristitia  afficitur,'  &c.     Modern  editions  have  re. 

Part  5,  Prop.  33,  Schol.  :  '.  .  .  nisi  quod  mens  easdem 
has  perfectiones  .  .  .  aeternas  habuerit,'  &c.  Modern  editions 
(except  Gfrorer)  have  metus.  Errors  in  the  original  edition  of 
the  Opera  PostJuuna  have  likewise  remained  uncorrected. 
See  Ed.  Bohmer,  Spinozana,  in  Fichte's  Zeitschrift  fur  Philo- 
sophic und  philosophische  Kritik,  i860,  vol.  xxxiii.  p.  153.  But 
as  to  two  of  the  remarks  there  made,  see  ib.  vol.  xlii.  1863, 
p.  97,  n.  where  they  are  retracted  by  the  author. 

Gfrorer's  edition  has  a  Latin  preface  of  considerable  merit, 
in  which  the  argument  for  determinism  is  put  with  a  certain 
freshness  of  topics  and  instances.  In  this  preface  there  is 
also  a  misprint  or  lapsus  calami  odd  enough  to  deserve  special 
notice.  In  the  part  relating  to  Spinoza's  letters  we  read : 
*  Penultima  a  iuvene  nobili  Edmundo  Biirk  [Alberto  Burgh] 
conscripta  est.' 

Bruder's  edition  is  the  handiest  and  altogether  best 
equipped  of  the  three,  and  the  most  convenient  for  reference. 

Dr.  Hugo  Ginsberg  has  more  lately  undertaken  a  new 
edition,  in  which  I  have  seen  the  Ethics,  the  Letters,  and 
Tractatus  Theologico-politicus.  (Leipzig,  1875,  &c.)  A  fourth 
volume,  apparently  completing  the  edition,  is  announced  this 
year.  The  introductions  contain  much  useful  matter  carefully 
brought  together.  The  text  professes  to  be  an  improvement 
on  Bruder's  ;  but  as  regards  the  Ethics  and  Letters  the 
editor's  intention  of  collating  the  original  text  of  the  0pp. 
Posth.  has  not  been  thoroughly  carried  out  by  those  entrusted 
with  the  work.  All  the  errors  above  noted  are  repeated  ; 
besides  which  the  number  of  new  misprints  can  only  be  called 


INTRODUCTION.  xix 

enormous.  The  additions  to  the  Letters  first  published  in 
Dr.  van  Vloten's  Supplementum  are  also  not  fully  given. 
See  Mind,  vol.  ii.  p.  273. 

As  to  translations  : — 

Dutch. — A  version  of  the  '  Principles  of  Descartes'  Philo- 
sophy '  (Renatus  des  Cartes  beginzelen  der  wysbegeerte,  &c.) 
was  published  at  Amsterdam  in  1664.  The  translator,  named 
only  as  P.  B.,  is  stated  to  have  been  Peter  Balling,  one  of 
Spinoza's  correspondents  {Bibliogr.  no.  2).  The  TractaUis 
TJieologico-politicus  was  translated  into  Dutch  as  early  as  1673, 
and  again  in  1694  {Bibliogr.  nos.  17,  18);  and  the  Opera 
Posthiima  appeared  in  Dutch  almost  as  soon  as  in  Latin  {De 
nagelate  ScJiriften  van  B.  d.  S.  &c.  Bibliogr.  23).  This  last 
work  is  well  and  carefully  executed.  The  purity  of  the 
language  contrasts  remarkably  with  the  Latinisms  which  in- 
fested the  current  writing  of  the  time,  and  some  errors  in  the 
Latin  text  of  the  0pp.  Posth.  are  tacitly  corrected.  There  do 
not  seem  to  be  any  modern  Dutch  versions. 

English. — There  is  no  complete  English  translation  of 
Spinoza,  nor  any  trustworthy  one  of  his  most  important 
philosophical  works.  The  Tractatiis  Theologico-politicus  was 
translated  in  1689,  and  again  (a  reprint .'')  in  1737.  The  trans- 
lation of  1689  is,  like  the  original,  anonymous  ;  neither  is 
Spinoza's  name  mentioned  by  the  translator.  So  far  as  I 
have  looked  at  it,  the  rendering  is  pretty  accurate,  but  it  has 
no  great  literary  merit.  Lastly,  in  1862,  and  in  a  second 
edition,  1868,  there  appeared  a  version  which  was  on  the 
face  of  it  anonymous,  but  was  known  to  be  the  work  of  the 
late  Dr.  R.  Willis,  and  afterwards  acknowledged  by  him. 
The  same  writer  published  some  years  later  a  translation  of 
the  Ethics  and  Letters.  {Benedict  dc  Spinoza ;  his  Life,  Cor- 
respondence, and  Ethics.  Trubner  &  Co.,  London,  1870.)  Of 
this  book  Professor  Flint  has  lately  said,  with  perfect  judgment 
and  discretion,  that  it  may  be  recommended  to  the  merely 
English  reader.  I  should  be  glad  to  imitate  his  reserve,  but 
silence  might  be  misunderstood.  The  fact  is  that  Dr.  Willis, 
with  extensive  reading,  a  fair  knowledge  of  philosophy,  and 
great  interest  in  his  subject,  had  not  either  scholarship  adequate 
to  his  task,  or  that  habit  of  an  exact  use  of  language  which  is 


XX  INTRODUCTION. 

almost  as  needful  to  the  translator  as  knowledge  of  the  original 
tongue.  The  result  (though,  for  many  reasons,  it  is  painful  to 
have  to  say  it)  is  that  this  version  is  far  too  inaccurate  to  be 
of  any  serious  use.  Not  only  shades  of  meaning  are  missed, 
and  Spinoza's  terse  Latin  spread  into  loose  paraphrase,  but 
there  are  constant  errors  in  the  rendering  of  perfectly  common 
Latin  particles,  idioms,  and  constructions.  The  same  remarks 
apply  to  the  translation  of  the  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus. 
There  is  a  still  later  anonymous  translation  of  the  Ethics  (New 
York  and  London,  1876).  Unfortunately  the  writer  looked 
upon  Dr.  Willis  as  an  authority,  and  copied  nearly  all  his 
mistakes.  In  1854  there  appeared  a  translation  of  the  Trac- 
tatus  Politicus  by  W.  Maccall  {Bibliogr.  no.  32,  in  Corrigenda), 
a  small  book  in  an  apparently  obscure  series  called  The 
Cabinet  of  Reason.  It  is  in  the  British  Museum,  but  has 
escaped  the  libraries  of  both  Oxford  and  Cambridge  Uni- 
versities. The  translator  speaks  with  enthusiasm  of  Spinoza  ; 
why  this  particular  work  was  chosen  for  translation  does  not 
plainly  appear. 

It  appears  from  a  diary  kept  by  Shelley's  friend  Williams 
at  Pisa  and  Lerici  in  182 1-2,  that  Shelley  not  only  planned 
but  executed  to  some  extent  a  new  translation  of  the  Trac- 
tatus  Theologico-politicus :  '  to  which  Lord  B.  [Byron]  has 
consented  to  put  his  name,  and  to  give  it  greater  currency, 
will  write  the  life  of  that  celebrated  Jew  to  preface  the  work.' 
This  passage  was  first  published  in  Mr.  R.  Garnett's  article, 
'Shelley's  Last  Days,'  FortnigJitly  Revieiv,  June  1878  (vol. 
xxiii.  N.S.,  p.  858).  A  fragment  of  the  first  chapter,  written 
it  would  seem  in  England,  and  accidentally  preserved,  and  a 
fac-simile  of  the  MS.,  may  be  seen  in  Mr.  C.  S.  Middleton's 
'  Shelley  and  his  Writings  '  (London  1858).  See  p.  403,  below. 
No  other  trace  of  Shelley's  design  remains. 

The  treatise  De  Intellechis  Emendatione,  the  Principia 
Philosophic^  and  Cogitata  Metaphysica,  and  the  book  De  Deo 
et  Honiine,  have  never  to  my  knowledge  been  done  into 
English. 

French. — The  TractaUis  Theologico-politicus  was  translated 
in  1678,  and  appeared  under  several  false  titles  at  once  {La 
clef  du  sanctiiaire  .  .  .  Reflexions  curienses  d'nn  esprit  desin- 


INTRODUCTION.  xxi 

te'resse   .    .    .    Traitd  des  Ceremonies  supcrstitieuses  des  Jiiifs. 
Bibliogr.  nos.  lo,  ii,  12).     More  recently  the  principal  works 
of  Spinoza  have  been  translated  by  E.  Saisset  {CEuvres  de 
Spinoza.    Paris,  1842  ;  2nd  ed.  1861,  3  vols.  :  reprinted  without 
alteration,  1872).     The  first  volume  is  a  critical  introduction. 
The  translation  is  faithful,  but  the  Principles  of  Descartes' 
PJiilosopJiy  and  a  good  many  of  the  letters  are  omitted.     The 
critical  and  bibliographical  information  has  to  some  extent 
become  obsolete  since  Dr.  van  Vloten's  publication  of  new 
matter.     Another  version,  intended  to  be  complete,  has  been 
begun  by  M.  J.  G.  Prat,  and  is  still  in  progress  {CEuvres  com- 
plies de  B.  de  Spinoza.     Premiere  serie  :  '  Vie  de  Spinoza, 
par  Lucas  ; '  '  Vie  de  Spinoza,  par   Colerus  ; '  '  Principes  de 
la  Philosophic  de  Descartes  et   Meditations  metaphysiques.* 
Paris,   1863.     Deuxieme  serie:    Traite   Theologico-politique, 
1872.      Ethique,   Premiere  Partie,    1880).     A  version  of  the 
Tractatus  Politicns,  by  the  same  hand,  appeared  separately  in 
i860.     In  1878  M.  Paul  Janet  gave  for  the  first  time  a  French 
version  of  the  De  Deo  et  Homine,  of  which  more  presently. 

German. — There  have  been  several  German  translations 
of  the  Ethics  and  other  works  of  Spinoza.  It  will  suffice  to 
mention  here  Auerbach's  (last  edition  entitled  B.  de  Spinoza's 
sanuntliche  Werke,  Stuttgart,  1871,  2  vols.),  and  a  yet  more 
recent  one  in  J.  H.  von  Kirchmann's  PJiilosopJiiscJie  Bib- 
liotJiek,  Berlin,  1868-72,  which  since  its  completion  is  also  to 
be  had  in  a  collected  form.  Auerbach's  version  contains  the 
whole  philosophical  works  of  Spinoza,  including  in  the  last 
edition  the  essay  De  Deo  et  Homine^  and  is  wonderfully  close 
to  the  original.  The  preface  and  life  of  Spinoza  prefixed  to 
the  first  volume  contain  in  a  short  compass  nearly  all  the  ex- 
traneous information  which  the  reader  is  likely  to  want,  and 
form  an  excellent  introduction  to  fuller  study.' 

Italian. — The   Tractatus    TJicologico-politicus  has  recently 
appeared  in  an  Italian  version,  namely : 

Trattato  Teologico-politico  di  Benedetto  de  Spinoza,  &c. 

'  I  may  here  mention  that  Auerbach's  novel  Spinoza :  cin  Doderlcl'iii,  is  still 
practically  inaccessible  to  English  readers  who  do  not  know  German.  A  French 
version  appeared  some  time  ago  in  the  Revue  Gervianiqiie,  but  has  not  been  sepa- 
rately published.  There  are  two  Dutch  translations,  the  latest  dated  1875  ; 
&nd  a  Spanish  one  by  Gonzales  Serrano  {11. d.). 


xxii  INTRODUCTION. 

(translating  full  title  of  original),  tradotto  dal  testo  latino  per 
Carlo  Sarchi.  Milan,  1875.  Pp.  xlii  and  368.  Preface  by 
way  of  dedication  to  S.  Cesare  Correnti,  At  p.  xxxiii  the 
translator  says :  '  Non  solamente  concorda  lo  Spinoza  colla 
metafisica  del  Vico,  di  cui  non  fu  mai  incolpata  la  cattolica 
ortodossia,  ma  sono  consentanei  i  suoi  principii  con  quelli  di 
S.  Tommaso,  del  Dottore  angelico,  siccome  se  ne  puo  accertare 
chiunque  voglia  meditare  le  Quest,  ii,  iii,  iv,  v,  e  seguenti 
della  Somjua  Teologica.' 

Spanish. — Still  more  lately  there  has  appeared  the  first 
instalment,  containing  the  Tract atiLS  TJieologico-politicus,  of  a 
Spanish  version  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  works  : 

Obras  filosoficas  de  Spinoza  vertidas  al  castellano  y  pre- 
cedidas  de  una  introduccion  por  Don  Emilio  Reus  y  Baha^ 
monde,  &c.     Madrid,  1878,  8vo.  pp.  cxvi  and  16^, 


II.  Authorities  for  Spinoza's  Life. 

I.  Colerus. — First  and  chiefly  we  have  the  life  of  Spinoza 
by   Johannes    Colerus    (Kohler),    German    minister   of    the 
Lutheran  congregation  at  the    Hague.     This   congregation, 
existing  side  by  side  with  the  Dutch   Reformed  Church  in 
freedom    and  security    much    beyond    any    rights    officially 
allowed  to  it,  was  to  some  extent  under  the  protection   of 
German  Lutheran  princes ;  and,  for  the  convenience  of  Ger- 
mans residing  at  the  Hague  in  the  service  of  the  States  or 
otherwise,  there  was  a  German  minister  as  well  as  a  Dutch 
one.     This  office  was  filled   by  Colerus  from   1693   to   1707. 
The  usage  of  a  bihngual  ministry  was  kept  up  till  1832,  when 
the  last  German  pastor  died.     Colerus  first  published  his  life 
of  Spinoza  in  Dutch,   together  with  a  controversial  sermon 
against  Spinozism  (Amsterdam,    1705.     Bibliogr.   Z'S).     This 
original  edition    is   extremely  rare.       Only  two    copies    are 
known,  one  of  which  is  in  the  Royal   Library  at   the  Hague 
and  the  other  at  Halle  {Bibliogr.  p.  vii).     It  was  almost  im- 
mediately followed,  and  for  all  practical  purposes  supplanted, 
by  a  French  version  (La  verite  de  la  resurrection  de  Jesus 
Christ  defendue  centre  B.  de  Spinoza  et  ses  spectateurs  [secta- 


I 


INTRODUCTION.  xxiii 

teurs].  Avec  la  vie  de  ce  fameux  philosophe,  tir^e,  tant  de  ses 
propres  Ecrits,  que  de  la  bouche  de  plusieurs  personnes  dignes 
de  foi  qui  I'ont  connu.  Par  Jean  Colerus,  Ministre  de  I'Eglise 
Lutherienne  de  la  Haye.  The  Hague,  1706.  Bibliogr.  90.) 
This  French  version  of  the  life  has  been  several  times  re- 
printed ;  it  is  to  be  found  in  Paulus'  edition  of  Spinoza,  in 
Saisset's  and  Prat's  translations,  and  at  the  end  of  Dr.  Gins- 
berg's edition  of  the  Letters.  An  English  translation  of  it 
appeared  in  the  same  year,  which  is  reprinted  at  the  end  of 
this  book  (Appendix  A),  and  a  German  one  in  1723,  remark- 
able for  a  portrait  of  Spinoza,  in  the  lettering  of  which  he  is 
described  as  '  characterem  reprobationis  in  vultu  gerens.' 
There  was  a  later  German  translation  from  the  original 
Dutch,  1734  {Bibliogr.  91-93).  Many  details  have  been 
added  or  cleared  up  since,  but  Colerus  remains  the  principal 
authority.  What  gives  his  witness  a  singular  value  is  its 
freedom  from  all  suspicion  of  designed  panegyric.  He  detests 
the  philosophy  of  Spinoza,  but  is  too  honest  to  slander  his 
character  as  a  man,  or  even  to  conceal  his  admiration  for  it. 

2.  Opera  PostJuima-dSidi  Supple^nentum. — Some  biographical 
information  is  given  in  the  editors'  preface  to  the  Opera 
Posthnma,  and  something  may  be  gathered  from  various 
passages  in  Spinoza's  correspondence,  notably  in  the  portions 
first  made  known  by  Dr.  van  Vloten,  who  has  also  given  other 
documentary  evidence  bearing  on  Spinoza's  life  both  in  the 
Siipplemcntinn  and  in  his  Dutch  work  on  Spinoza  (see 
below). 

3.  Leibnitz. — A  few  personal  recollections  of  Spinoza  are 
preserved  in  Leibnitz's  writings.  They  will  be  specially 
mentioned  in  their  place  in  the  biographical  part  (Paulus, 
Collectanea  ;  Foucher  de  Careil,  Leibniz,  Descartes,  et  Spifioza). 

The  remaining  sources  of  information  are  of  less  weight. 

4.  Lucas. — Early  in  the  eighteenth  century,  we  cannot 
say  when  first,  but  it  seems  before  171 2  at  all  events 
(see  extract  from  Brit.  Mus.  MS.  below),  there  became  cur- 
rent in  MS.  a  biography  of  Spinoza,  attributed  in  the  preface 
to  one  Lucas,  a  physician  of  the  Hague.  It  was  often  asso- 
ciated, under  the  common  title  La  vie  et  Vesprit  de  Mr. 
Benoft  de  Spinosa,  with  a  certain  Traitc  des  trots  iuiposteurs, 


xxii  INTRODUCTION. 

(translating  full  title  of  original),  tradotto  dal  testo  latino  per 
Carlo  Sarchi.  Milan,  1875.  Pp.  xHi  and  368.  Preface  by 
way  of  dedication  to  S.  Cesare  Correnti.  At  p.  xxxiii  the 
translator  says :  '  Non  solamente  concorda  lo  Spinoza  colla 
metafisica  del  Vico,  di  cui  non  fu  mai  incolpata  la  cattolica 
ortodossia,  ma  sono  consentanei  i  suoi  principii  con  quelH  di 
S.  Tommaso,  del  Dottore  angelico,  siccome  se  ne  puo  accertare 
chiunque  voglia  meditare  le  Quest,  ii,  iii,  iv,  v,  e  seguenti 
della  Sonima  Teologica' 

Spanish. — Still  more  lately  there  has  appeared  the  first 
instalment,  containing  the  Tractatiis  Theologico-politiais,  of  a 
Spanish  version  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  works  : 

Obras  filosoficas  de  Spinoza  vertidas  al  castellano  y  pre- 
cedidas  de  una  introduccion  por  Don  Emilio  Reus  y  Baha- 
monde,  &c.     Madrid,  1878,  8vo.  pp.  cxvi  and  368. 


II.  Authorities  for  Spinoza's  Life. 

I.  Colents. — First  and  chiefly  we  have  the  life  of  Spinoza 
by   Johannes    Colerus    (Kohler),    German    minister   of    the 
Lutheran  congregation  at  the    Hague.     This   congregation, 
existing  side  by  side  with  the  Dutch   Reformed   Church  in 
freedom    and  security    much    beyond    any    rights    officially 
allowed  to  it,  was  to  some   extent  under  the  protection   of 
German  Lutheran  princes ;  and,  for  the  convenience  of  Ger- 
mans residing  at  the  Hague  in  the  service  of  the  States  or 
otherwise,  there  was  a  German  minister  as  well  as  a  Dutch 
one.     This  office  was  filled  by  Colerus  from   1693   to  1707. 
The  usage  of  a  bilingual  ministry  was  kept  up  till  1832,  when 
the  last  German  pastor  died.     Colerus  first  published  his  life 
of  Spinoza  in  Dutch,   together  with  a  controversial  sermon 
against  Spinozism  (Amsterdam,    1705.     Bibliogr.   ^Z).     This 
original  edition    is    extremely  rare.       Only  two   copies    are 
known,  one  of  which  is  in  the  Royal   Library  at   the  Hague 
and  the  other  at  Halle  {Bibliogr.  p.  vii).     It  was  almost  im- 
mediately followed,  and  for  all  practical  purposes  supplanted, 
by  a  French  version  (La  verite  de  la  resurrection  de  Jesus 
Christ  defendue  contre  B.  de  Spinoza  et  ses  spectateurs  [secta- 


\ 


INTRODUCTION.  xxiii 

teurs].  Avec  la  vie  de  ce  fameux  philosophe,  tiree,  tant  de  ses 
propres  Ecrits,  que  de  la  bouche  de  plusieurs  personnes  dignes 
de  foi  qui  I'ont  connu.  Par  Jean  Colerus,  Ministre  de  I'Eglise 
Lutherienne  de  la  Haye.  The  Hague,  1706.  Bibliogr.  90.) 
This  French  version  of  the  life  has  been  several  times  re- 
printed ;  it  is  to  be  found  in  Paulus'  edition  of  Spinoza,  in 
Saisset's  and  Prat's  translations,  and  at  the  end  of  Dr.  Gins- 
berg's edition  of  the  Letters.  An  English  translation  of  it 
appeared  in  the  same  year,  which  is  reprinted  at  the  end  of 
this  book  (Appendix  A),  and  a  German  one  in  1723,  remark- 
able for  a  portrait  of  Spinoza,  in  the  lettering  of  which  he  is 
described  as  *  characterem  reprobationis  in  vultu  gerens,' 
There  was  a  later  German  translation  from  the  original 
Dutch,  1734  {Bibliogr.  91-93).  Many  details  have  been 
added  or  cleared  up  since,  but  Colerus  remains  the  principal 
authority.  What  gives  his  witness  a  singular  value  is  its 
freedom  from  all  suspicion  of  designed  panegyric.  He  detests 
the  philosophy  of  Spinoza,  but  is  too  honest  to  slander  his 
character  as  a  man,  or  even  to  conceal  his  admiration  for  it. 

2.  Opera  PostJnimaz.n6.  Supplementimi. — Some  biographical 
information  is  given  in  the  editors'  preface  to  the  Opera 
Postkuma,  and  something  may  be  gathered  from  various 
passages  in  Spinoza's  correspondence,  notably  in  the  portions 
first  made  known  by  Dr.  van  Vloten,  who  has  also  given  other 
documentary  evidence  bearing  on  Spinoza's  life  both  in  the 
Supplemciitiun  and  in  his  Dutch  work  on  Spinoza  (see 
below). 

3.  Leibnitz. — A  few  personal  recollections  of  Spinoza  are 
preserved  in  Leibnitz's  writings.  They  will  be  specially 
mentioned  in  their  place  in  the  biographical  part  (Paulus, 
Collectanea  ;  Foucher  de  Careil,  Leibniz,  Descartes,  et  Spinoza). 

The  remaining  sources  of  information  are  of  less  weight. 

4.  Lucas, — Early  in  the  eighteenth  century,  we  cannot 
say  when  first,  but  it  seems  before  171 2  at  all  events 
(see  extract  from  Brit.  Mus.  MS.  below),  there  became  cur- 
rent in  MS.  a  biography  of  Spinoza,  attributed  in  the  preface 
to  one  Lucas,  a  physician  of  the  Hague.  It  was  often  asso- 
ciated, under  the  common  title  La  vie  et  Vesprit  de  Mr. 
Benoit  de  Spinosa,  with  a  certain  Traitc  des  trois  imposteurs, 


xxiv  INTRODUCTION. 

which  has  nothing  to  do  with  Spinoza,  and  is  again  distinct 
from  the  Latin  book  De  tribiis  iuipostoribus,  though  it  pre- 
tends to  be  from  a  Latin  original.  In  this  form  the  Hfe  was 
printed  at  Amsterdam  in  17 19,  in  a  publication  called 
Nonvcllcs  Litteraires,  and  also  in  a  sepai"ate  book.  The  book 
was  almost  immediately  called  in  ;  the  life  was  reissued  alone 
at  Hamburg  [i*],  1735,  and  this  edition  also  became  very  scarce 
(the  British  Museum  has  a  copy).^  Meanwhile  the  Count  de 
Boulainvilliers,  who  possessed  an  early  MS.  copy,  had  worked 
it  up  with  the  life  by  Colerus  into  a  not  very  coherent  whole 
{La  vie  de  Spinosa  ecrite  par  M.  Jean  Colerus  .  .  .  auginefitee 
de  beaiicoiip  de  particularites  iirees  d'line  vie  manuscrite  de  ce 
philosophe,  faite  par  U7i  de  ses  amis)  in  his  book  called  a  refu- 
tation of  Spinoza,  but  really  a  popular  exposition,  which  was 
published  after  the  author's  death  (Brussels  [.?],  173 1.  Bibliogr. 
107,  where  the  date  is  given  as  1726  by  the  misprint  of  XXVL 
for  XXXL). 

The  additions  in  Boulainvilliers,  and  some  passages  of 
Lucas  omitted  by  him  (these  from  a  MS.  copy),  are  given  in 
Paulus'  edition  as  footnotes  to  Colerus  ;  and  Lucas  is  reprinted 
at  large  from  ed.  1735  by  M.  Prat  (he  does  not  mention 
whence  he  obtained  the  use  or  a  transcript  of  the  book)  in  his 
Qiuvres  completes  de  B.  de  Spinoza,  ire  serie.  The  history  of 
this  work,  and  the  connexion  of  the  different  forms  in  which 
it  has  existed,  were  first  unravelled  by  Paulus  (preface  to 
vol.  ii.  of  his  edition).  One  could  wish  it  were  better  worth 
so  much  trouble.  It  is  the  production  of  an  ardent  and 
undiscriminating  panegyrist,  confused  in  its  narrative,  and  not 
always  consistent  with  what  is  known  from  other  quarters. 
As  Auerbach  justly  says,  Lucas'  enthusiasm  prevents  him 
from  telling  his  story  clearly  or  soberly.  His  unsupported 
evidence  is,  in  my  opinion,  worth  very  little,  and  at  best  we 
can  only  use  him  as  a  witness  auxiliary  and  subordinate  to 
Colerus.  The  authorship  of  this  biography  has  been  called  in 
doubt  on  the  ground  that  Lucas  (of  -whom,  by  the  way,  very 
little  seems  to  be  known,  save  that  he  was  the  author  of  a 

'  At  the  foot  of  p.  47  is  the  catchword  L'ESPRIT,  belonging  to  the  title 
'  L'Esprit  de  M.  de  Spinosa, '  which  followed  on  p.  49  in  the  original  issue  of 
1719,  p.  48  being  blank. 


INTRODUCTION.  .  xxv 

satirical  work  called  Les  Quintessences)  was  not  capable  of  it 
(Prosper  Marchand,  Diet.  Historiqne,  article  '  Impostoribus  '). 
But  the  question  is  not  worth  discussing, 

5.  Bayle,  Kortholt,  ^e. — The  remaining  evidences  may  be 
taken  in  the  lump.     A  few  touches  are  contributed  by  the 
article  on  Spinoza  in  Bayle's  Dictionary  (reprinted  as  appendix 
to  Dr.  Ginsberg's  edition  of  the  Tractatns  Thcologico-politicns), 
which  however  is  very  loose  in   its  facts,   and  by  a  notice 
prefixed  by  Sebastian   Kortholt  to  a  second  edition  of  his 
father's  hook  De  irib?is  im/>ostoridns  ma^-uis  (Hamburg,  1700. 
Bibliogr.  ^2  :  the  passages  about  Spinoza  are  given  in  Paulus' 
Collectanea).     The  '  three  great  impostors '  of  the  last-named 
book  are  Lord   Herbert  of  Cherbury,  Hobbes,  and  Spinoza. 
What  is  said  of  Spinoza  personally  in  the  preface  is  remark- 
able as  the  testimony  of  a  very  unwilling  witness  to  the  sim- 
plicity and  blamelessness  of  his  life.     Colerus  had  Bayle  and 
Kortholt  before  him  when  he  wrote  his  life  of  Spinoza.     Then 
we  have  a  little  book  by  one  Stoupe,'  a  Swiss  officer  in  the 
French  service,  La  religion  des  hollandois,  162^  {Bibliogr.  6^^, 
where  the  passages  in  question  are  given),  containing  a  rather 
confused  account  of  Spinoza,  who  was  then  living,  and  of  the 
Tractatns    Theologico-politicus.     The    Dutch   theologians  are 
accused  of  lukewarmness,  or  worse,  for  not  coming  forward 
more  strongly  to  refute  Spinoza  ;  this  piece  of  evangelical 
zeal  is  not  unlikely,  as  Paulus  suggests,  to  have  had  a  political 
motive.     Dutch  writers  presently   replied    to  these  charges. 
One  of  them,  described  as  '  Jean  Brun,  Ministre  du  Roy  des 
Armees,'    expresses   astonishment   at    Stoupe's   zeal    against 
Spinoza ;  for  Stoupe,  he  says,  himself  sought  Spinoza's  ac- 
quaintance, and   made  much  of  him  on   the  occasion  of  his 
visit  to  Conde's  head-quarters  at  Utrecht  {Bibliogr.  6y).     In 
1847  there  appeared  in  the  Berlin  Allgemeine  Zeitschrift  fiir 
GcschicJite  some  notes  of  travel  made  in    1703   by   Gottlieb 
Stolle,  aftenvards  a  professor   at   Jena    {Bibliogr.   ?>6).      At 
Amsterdam  he  picked  up  some  gossip  about  Spinoza  from  an 
old  man  who  professed  to  have  known  him  well.     This  com- 
munication is  of  no  importance,  and  in  part  manifestly  absurd. 

'  The  name  is  variously  spelt.     Dr.  van  Vloten,  in  his  recent  address  on  the 
unveiling  of  the  Spinoza  statue  (see  p.  xxxvi.  below),  prints  it  SioJ>pa, 


xxiv  INTRODUCTION. 

which  has  nothing  to  do  with  Spinoza,  and  is  again  distinct 
from  the  Latin  book  De  tribus  iuipostoribus,  though  it  pre- 
tends to  be  from  a  Latin  original.  In  this  form  the  hfe  was 
printed  at  Amsterdam  in  17 19,  in  a  publication  called 
Noni'dles  Litteraircs,  and  also  in  a  separate  book.  The  book 
was  almost  immediately  called  in  ;  the  life  was  reissued  alone 
at  Hamburg  [.?],  1735,  and  this  edition  also  became  very  scarce 
(the  British  Museum  has  a  copy).^  Meanwhile  the  Count  de 
Boulainvilliers,  who  possessed  an  early  MS.  copy,  had  worked 
it  up  with  the  life  by  Colerus  into  a  not  veiy  coherent  whole 
{La  vie  de  Spinosa  ecrite  par  M.  Jean  Colerus  .  .  .  augmentee 
de  heaiicoiip  de  particidarites  tirees  d'lme  vie  manuscrite  de  ce 
philosopJie,  faitc  par  an  de  ses  amis)  in  his  book  called  a  refu- 
tation of  Spinoza,  but  really  a  popular  exposition,  which  was 
published  after  the  author's  death  (Brussels  [.''],  173 1.  Bibliogr. 
107,  where  the  date  is  given  as  1726  by  the  misprint  of  XX VL 
for  XXXL). 

The  additions  in  Boulainvilliers,  and  some  passages  of 
Lucas  omitted  by  him  (these  from  a  MS.  copy),  are  given  in 
Paulus'  edition  as  footnotes  to  Colerus  ;  and  Lucas  is  reprinted 
at  large  from  ed.  1735  by  M.  Prat  (he  does  not  mention 
whence  he  obtained  the  use  or  a  transcript  of  the  book)  in  his 
Qiitvres  coinplHcs  de  B.  de  Spinoza,  ire  serie.  The  history  of 
this  work,  and  the  connexion  of  the  different  forms  in  which 
it  has  existed,  were  first  unravelled  by  Paulus  (preface  to 
vol.  ii.  of  his  edition).  One  could  wish  it  were  better  worth 
so  much  trouble.  It  is  the  production  of  an  ardent  and 
undiscriminating  panegyrist,  confused  in  its  narrative,  and  not 
always  consistent  with  what  is  known  from  other  quarters. 
As  Auerbach  justly  says,  Lucas'  enthusiasm  prevents  him 
from  telling  his  story  clearly  or  soberly.  His  unsupported 
evidence  is,  in  my  opinion,  worth  very  little,  and  at  best  we 
can  only  use  him  as  a  witness  auxiliary  and  subordinate  to 
Colerus.  The  authorship  of  this  biography  has  been  called  in 
doubt  on  the  ground  that  Lucas  (of  whom,  by  the  way,  very 
little  seems  to  be  known,  save  that  he  was  the  author  of  a 

'  At  the  foot  of  p.  47  is  the  catchword  L'ESPRIT,  belonging  to  the  title 
'  L'Esprit  de  M.  de  Spinosa, '  which  followed  on  p.  49  in  the  original  issue  of 
1 719,  p.  48  being  blank. 


INTRODUCTION.  .  xxv 

satirical  work  called  Les  Quintessences)  was  not  capable  of  it 
(Prosper  Marchand,  Diet.  Historigue,  article  '  Impostoribus  '). 
But  the  question  is  not  worth  discussing, 

5.  Bayle,  Kortholt,  &c. — The  remaining  evidences  may  be 
taken  in  the  lump.  A  few  touches  are  contributed  by  the 
article  on  Spinoza  in  Bayle's  Dietionary  (reprinted  as  appendix 
to  Dr.  Ginsberg's  edition  of  the  Tractatiis  Thcologico-politieus)^ 
which  however  is  very  loose  in  its  facts,  and  by  a  notice 
prefixed  by  Sebastian  Kortholt  to  a  second  edition  of  his 
father's  book  De  tribus  irnpostoribus  magnis  (Hamburg,  1700. 
Bibliogr.  82  :  the  passages  about  Spinoza  are  given  in  Paulus' 
Collectanea).  The  '  three  great  impostors '  of  the  last-named 
book  are  Lord  Herbert  of  Cherbury,  Hobbes,  and  Spinoza, 
What  is  said  of  Spinoza  personally  in  the  preface  is  remark- 
able as  the  testimony  of  a  very  unwilling  witness  to  the  sim- 
plicity and  blamelessness  of  his  life,  Colerus  had  Bayle  and 
Kortholt  before  him  when  he  wrote  his  life  of  Spinoza.  Then 
we  have  a  little  book  by  one  Stoupe,'  a  Swiss  officer  in  the 
French  service,  La  religion  des  hoUandois,  i6y^  {Bibliogr.  63, 
where  the  passages  in  question  are  given),  containing  a  rather 
confused  account  of  Spinoza,  who  was  then  living,  and  of  the 
Tractatus  TJieologico-politiciis.  The  Dutch  theologians  are 
accused  of  lukewarmness,  or  worse,  for  not  coming  forward 
more  strongly  to  refute  Spinoza  ;  this  piece  of  evangelical 
zeal  is  not  unlikely,  as  Paulus  suggests,  to  have  had  a  political 
motive.  Dutch  writers  presently  replied  to  these  charges. 
One  of  them,  described  as  '  Jean  Brun,  Ministre  du  Roy  des 
Armees,'  expresses  astonishment  at  Stoupe's  zeal  against 
Spinoza ;  for  Stoupe,  he  says,  himself  sought  Spinoza's  ac- 
quaintance, and  made  much  of  him  on  the  occasion  of  his 
visit  to  Conde's  head-quarters  at  Utrecht  [Bibliogr.  6y).  In 
1847  there  appeared  in  the  Berlin  Allgemeine  Zeitsclirift  fiir 
Gesehichte  some  notes  of  travel  made  in  1703  by  Gottlieb 
Stolle,  aftenvards  a  professor  at  Jena  {Bibliogr.  ^6).  At 
Amsterdam  he  picked  up  some  gossip  about  Spinoza  from  an 
old  man  who  professed  to  have  known  him  well.  This  com- 
munication is  of  no  importance,  and  in  part  manifestly  absurd. 

'  The  name  is  variously  spelt.     Dr.  van  Vloten,  in  his  recent  address  on  the 
xmveiling  of  the  Spinoza  statue  (see  p.  xxxvi,  below),  prints  it  Stoppa. 


xxvi  INTRODUCTION. 

But  StoUe  likewise  made  the  acquaintance  of  Rieuwerts 
(or  Riewerts,  as  the  name  appears  on  the  title-page  of  the 
Priiicipia  PJiilosophice),  the  publisher  of  the  0pp.  Posth.,  and 
got  from  him  some  interesting  particulars  ;  he  also  visited 
Bayle,  and  spoke  with  him  of  Spinoza.  See  Ginsberg's  In- 
troduction to  his  edition  of  the  Ethics,  pp.  20-25,  where  these 
passages  are  reprinted. 

Some  other  miscellaneous  publications  of  the  eighteenth 
century  contain  statements  or  allusions  touching  Spinoza's 
life  ;  but,  so  far  as  I  know,  these  are  either  copied  from  the 
authorities  already  mentioned,  or  were  idle  tales  contradicted 
by  the  known  facts  (e.g.  Bibliogr.  98,  1 10). 

I  may  here  say  a  word  of  the  portraits  of  Spinoza.  Three 
only  that  I  know  of  (if  so  many)  may  be  reasonably  considered 
authentic : — 

1.  Engraving  found  in  some  copies  of  the  0pp.  Posth.  It 
is  not  described  as  rare  in  Bibliogr.,  but  is  difficult  to  meet 
with  in  this  country.  After  searching  without  result  in  public 
libraries,  we  found  an  example  in  the  copy  of  the  0pp.  Posth, 
belonging  to  the  London  Institution,  of  which  the  frontispiece 
to  this  book  is  a  reproduction. 

2.  Miniature  belonging  to  the  late  Queen  of  the  Nether- 
lands, in  the  Summer  Palace  at  the  Hague.  A  chromo- 
lithographic  copy  is  given  as  frontispiece  to  Schaarschmidt's 
edition  of  De  Deo  et  Honiinc. 

3.  Painting  formerly  belonging  to  Professor  Paulus,  the 
editor  of  Spinoza,  since  to  Dr.  van  Vloten,  and  by  him  pre- 
sented to  the  Town  Museum  at  the  Hague.  Comparison  of 
the  three  suggests  that  No.  i  may  be  to  some  extent  idealised. 
On  the  other  hand,  No,  i  is  by  far  the  most  artistic  and  lifelike. 
Cf.  Ed.  Bohmer,  Spinozana,  i.  p.  144,  ii.  pp.  86,  Z'j  (in  Zeitschr. 
fiir  Philosophic  und  philosophische  Kritik,  Halle,  vol.  xxxvi. 

i860,  vol.  xlii.  1863).' 

'  No.  1  also  occurs  without  the  inscription,  but  in  that  state  is  very  rare.  No. 
2  was  bought  at  Leyclen  in  1866,  with  some  sort  of  tradition  of  Spinoza  being  the 
person  represented.  Opinions  differ  as  to  the  value  to  be  attached  to  it.  No.  3 
has  been  engia%-ed  as  frontispiece  to  Paulus'  edition  of  .Spinoza.  Recent  inspection 
of  the  original  has  led  me  to  suspect  that  it  may  be  only  a  fancy  picture  by  some 
painter  who  had  no.  i  before  him  :  if  this  were  so,  it  would  of  course  be  of  no 
authority. 


INTRODUCTION.  xxvii 


III,  Early  Literature  relating  to  Spinoza. 

Andala. — The  following  book,  not  without  curiosity  for 
the  elaborate  comparison  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  with  Stoi 
cism,  is  not  in  Bibliogr.  : — 

Apologia  I  pro  |  vera  &  saniore  |  philosophia  [  quatuor 
partibus  comprehensa,  |  auctore  |  Ruardo  Andala,  |  Phil,  et 
SS.  Theol.  Doctore  &  Professore  |  ordinario.  |  Franequerae,  | 
Ex  Officina  Wibii  Bleck,  Bibliopolje  |  MDCCXIX.  4to. 
pp.  3  unnumbered  (title-page  and  preface)  and  210. 

Parts  I.  and  II.  relate  to  Spinoza  ;  the  pages  of  Part  I. 
are  headed  :  '  Philosophia  R.  Descartes  |  Spinosismo  opposita.* 
Those  of  Part  II. :  '  Spinosus  Stoicismus  fons  Spinosismi  |  et 
puritas  philosophise  R.  Descartes.'  The  Stoic  philosophy  is 
compared  with  Spinoza's  in  parallel  columns  through  a  series 
of  numbered  heads. 

For  my  acquaintance  with  this  book  (as  for  the  references 
to  some  of  the  others  hereafter  mentioned)  I  am  indebted  to 
the  kindness  of  Mr.  I.  Bywater,  of  Exeter  College,  Oxford, 
the  owner  of  the  copy  I  have  seen.  It  is  not  in  the  British 
Museum,  the  Bodleian,  or  the  Cambridge  University  library. 

The  full  title  of  the  same  author's  book  described  in 
Bibliogr.  303  is  : — 

Cartesius  |  verus   Spinozismi  |  eversor,  |  et  |  physicae   ex- 
perimentalis  |  architectus,  |  auctore  |  Ruardo  Andala,  |  Phil, 
et  SS.  Theol.  Doctore  et  Professore  |  ordinario.  |  Franequeree  | 
Ex  officina  Wibii  Bleck,  Bibliopolae,  MDCCIX.     4to. 

Pp.  1-282,  headed  :  '  Cartesius  verus  Spinozismi  eversor.* 

New  title  :  Dissertatio  physica  |  qua  repra^sentatur  |  Car- 
tesius I  physics  experimentalis  architectus,  |  vcntilata  public^ 
A.D.  21.  Jun.  MDCCXIX,  |  Defendente  |  Georgio  Szobo:^- 
zlai,  I  Transylvano-Hungaro. 

Pp.  1-44,  headed:  'Cartesius  physicae  experimentalis  ar- 
chitectus.' 

The  same  author's  Dissertationuui  pJiilosopJiiairuvL  Iicptas 
(Franeq.  MDCCXI)  contains  at  least  one  incidental  attack 
on  Spinoza,  of  whom  it  is  said,  among  other  amenities,  in  the 


xxviii  INTRODUCTION 

fifth  dissertation,  De  voluntatis  libcrtate  (p.  190)  :  '  Hsec  et  alia 
ostendunt  Atheum  avTOKaraKpirov.^ 

Bontckoe. — Dr.  Cornelius  Bontekoe's  unexecuted  intention 
of  refuting  Spinoza  is  noticed  in  the  text  further  on  (ch.  xii.). 

Boiilainvillicrs. — Spinoza's  name  was  strangely  mixed  up, 
as  above  mentioned,  with  a  certain  Traite  des  trots  imposteiirs 
which  had  a  half-occult  circulation  in  MS.  in  France  and  the 
Low  Countries ;  a  performance,  for  the  rest,  of  no  particular 
merit,  and  itself  a  clumsy  imposture  as  regards  its  pretended 
origin  and  date.  Later  in  the  eighteenth  century  it  ,was 
printed,  but  without  the  use  of  Spinoza's  name  in  any  way. 
See  for  detailed  bibliography  of  this  work  Ed.  Bohmer,  Spino- 
zana,  i860  {ubi  supra),  pp.  156  sqq.  I  now  add  my  contribu- 
tion for  what  it  may  be  worth.  In  an  eighteenth  century 
MS.  in  the  British  Museum  (Add.  12064)  there  occurs,  after 
a  copy  of  this  treatise,  a  note  which  maybe  worth  transcribing. 
It  is  as  follows  (I  modernize  the  spelling  and  accents,  and 
correct  one  or  two  words)  : 

'  J'ai  vu  une  copie  MS.  de  I'ouvrage  de  Monsieur  le  comte 
de  Boullainvilliers  touchant  la  doctrine  de  Spinoza  faite  sur 
I'original  de  I'auteur  au  mois  d'aout  171 2,  in-4to.  Ce  MS. 
contient  la  Metaphysique  et  I'Ethique  de  Spinoza,  son  Esprit 
[i.e.  the  Traite  dcs  trois  itnposteiirs]  et  sa  vie,  comme  il  \sic\ 
porte  le  titre.  II  commence  par  la  vie  de  Spinoza,  qui  est  fort 
abregee,  et  dont  le  plus  essentiel  et  remarquable  a  ete  ajoute 
a  la  vie  de  Spinoza  ecrite  par  Colerus,  et  a  ete  imprime  depuis 
peu  dans  le  livre  de  la  Refutation  des  erreurs  de  Benoit 
Spinoza,  a  Bruxelles  chez  Francois  Foppens  en  1731,  in-8vo, 
comme  porte  Ic  titre,  mais  veritablement  en  HoUande. 
[Bibliogr.  107,  and  see  above.] 

'  Aprcs  la  vie  de  Spinoza  est  place  I'ouvrage  de  Monsieur 
Boullainvilliers  avec  ce  titre  : 

'  Essai  de  Metaphysique  dans  les  Principes  de  B  .  .  .  de 
Sp  .  .  .  compose  par  M.L.C.D.C.D.B.,  c'est-a-dire — 

'  II  y  precede  un  avertissement  qui  fait  la  preface  de 
rimprime  dans  la  Refutation  de  Spinoza,  mais  au  commence- 
ment, oil  il  est  dit :  J'entrcprends  de  faire  parler  dans  les  trois 
traites  suivans — on  a  retranche  le  mot  trois — parce  qu'on 
n'a  pas  osc  d'imprimer  i'Esprit  de  Spinoza,  qui  fait  le  troisieme 


INTRODUCTION.  xxix 

traite.  .  .  .  Le  troisieme  traite  est  intitule :  L'Esprit  de  Mon- 
sieur de  Spinoza,  c'est-a-dire  ce  que  croit  la  plus  saine  partie 
du  monde.' 

It  would  be  rash  to  infer  anything  from  this  memorandum 
as  to  the  authorship  of  the  Traite  des  trois  iuiposteurs,  which 
is  indeed  quite  beneath  Boulainvilliers'  ability,  particularly  as 
shown  in  the  so-called  Refutation,  with  which  it  was  associated 
in  the  MS.  of  17 12  seen  by  the  annotator.  But  it  does 
appear  to  connect  Boulainvilliers  with  the  affixing  of  Spinoza's 
name  to  the  work.  It  is  not  surprising  that  the  writer  of  the 
MS.  now  cited  did  not  know  (as  he  obviously  did  not)  that  it 
had  been  printed  in  1719.  The  'copie  MS.'  mentioned  by 
him  would  seem  to  be  that  in  the  library  of  the  Arsenal  at 
Paris,  described  ex  relatione  by  Bohmer,  Spinosana,  ii.  p.  157. 
The  British  Museum  possesses  another  MS.  copy  of  the 
Traite,  which,  however,  does  not  offer  any  peculiar  feature. 

In  Paris  MSS.  have  apparently  been  searched  for  by 
Bohmer.  One  would  think,  however,  there  must  yet  be 
several  unexamined  copies  in  French  libraries  {cf.  Spinosana, 
ii.  89,  90). 

LangenJiert. — Arnoldi  Geulincx  |  compendium  physicae  [ 
illustratum  |  a  |  Casparo    Langenhert.     |  |    Franequerse,  |  Ex 
Officina   Leonardi   Strick  Bibliopolae  |  Anno    MDCLXXXVlli, 

At  p.  116:  '  Quomodo  autem  Philosophi  nonnulli  atque 
Theologi,  liberrimum  hoc  arbitrium  cum  Deo  non  competere 
vaferrimo  Spinosae  (qui  libertatem  banc,  ut  suo  tempore 
dante  Deo  demonstrabimus,  ne  quidem  per  somnium  novit) 
largiantur,  ex  ejus  sese  liberent  tricis,  id  ego  me  ignorare 
profiteor,' 

Langenhert's  intention,  like  Dr.  Bontekoe's,  appears  to 
have  remained  unperformed. 

Rijcke. — Theodori  Ryckii,  etc.  ad  diversos  epistolae 
ineditae.     Ed.  G.  D.  J.  Schotel.     Hagae  Comitum,  1843. 

At  p.  6,  in  letter  to  Adrian  BIyenburg,  Aug.  14,  1675  : — 

'  Inter  nos  rumor  est  auctorcm  Tractatns  Theologieo-politici 
in  promptu  habere  librum  de  Deo  ct  Mcnte  multo  priore  isto 
periculosiorem.* 

Compare  Spinoza's  Ep.  19,  of  about  the  same  date. 

Ryssel  (J.  J.  a)  gives  a  short    account    of   Spinoza    and 


XXX  INTRODUCTION. 

his  philosophy  in  his  edition  of  Vossius  de  philosophorum 
sectis,  Lips.  1690,  4to.  p.  203. 

Wittc  (Henning). — Diarium  biographicum,  in  quo  scrip- 
tores  seculi  post  natum  Christum  xvii.  prsecipui  .  .  .  concis^ 
descripti  magno  adducuntur  numero.  Gedani  [Danzig]  1688, 
4to.  At  sig.  Nnnn,  fo.  4,  verso  (the  book  is  unpaged)  sub  ann. 
1677,  is  the  name  of  Spinoza  and  a  list  of  his  works:  the 
exact  date  of  his  death  is  added  in  a  supplement. 

An  anti-Spinozist  bibliography  was  attempted  as  early 
as  1725  by  Joh.  Albert  Fabricius  in  his  wordily  entitled  book  : 

Delectus  argumentorum  et  syllabus  scriptorum  qui  'veri- 
tatem  religionis  Christianae  adversus  atheos,  Epicureos,  Deistas 
seu  naturalistas,  idololatras,  Judaeos  et  Muhammedanos  lu- 
cubrationibus  suis  asseruerunt.     Hamburg  1725,  4to. 

Cap.  XIII.,  p.  355: 

Adversus  Spinosam  et  alios  mundum  aeternum  confin- 
gentes. 

At  p.  357  is  a  list  of  writers  against  Spinoza :  some  names 
of  authors  and  books  are  given  which  I  do  not  find  in 
Bibliogy.  Besides  Brampton  Gurdon  (as  to  whom  see  below 
among  English  writers)  the  following  are  referred  to,  if  re- 
ference it  can  be  called. 

Gerardus  de  Vries  in  exercitationibus  rationalibus  de  Deo.' 

D.  Jo.  Jachimi-  Weidneri  Homo  Spinosae  religionem  exer- 
cens  :  qu.  whether  a  separate  work  from  '  Numen  Spinozae  in 
refutationem  erroris  atheistici,'  &c.  {Bibliogr.  394),  the  title 
of  which  is  inaccurately  cited  by  Fabricius. 

Petrus  van  Mastricht  in  Gangraena.  (Novitatum  Car- 
tesianarum  Gangraena,  s.  Theologia  Cartesiana  detecta. 
Amstclod.  1677.  In  University  Libraries  of  Cambridge  and 
Lcydcn,  and  in  the  Bodleian :  not  in  Brit.  Mus.  The  author 
was   Professor  of  Theology   at    Utrecht,    1677- 1706).       The 

'  Gerardi  de  Vries  exercitationes  rationales  de  Deo,  divinisque  peifectionibus, 
necnon  philosophemata  miscellanea,  &c.  Trajecti  ad  Rhenum,  MDCXCV,  410. 
At  p.  34  is  a  pious  wish  for  unhappy  persons  who  may  be  '  istis  Spinis  suffocati  '  : 
at  p.  43  the  Ethics  are  named  :  '  consonant  hrec  per  omnia  eis,  quae  occurrunt  in 
ipso  limine  profana.'  Ethica:  ordinegeometrico  demonstrate.'  The  book  is  mainly 
anti-Cartesian.     The  author  was  a  Professor  at  Utrecht. 

'  Read  Jo.  Joachimi.     The  D.  apparently  stands  for  'Domini.' 


INTRODUCTION.  xxxi 

full  title  is  :  Novitatum  Cartesianarum  Gangrasna,  nobiliores 
plerasque  corporis  theologici  partes  arrodens  &  exedens. 
Seu  theologia  Cartesiana  detecta  auctore  Petro  van  Mastricht, 
S.  literarum  in  ecclesia  &  academia  Duisburgensi  doctore 
&  professore.  Prostant  Amstelodami :  apud  Janssonio- 
Waesbergios.     Anno  MDCLXXVII. 

In  cap,  3,  De  Philosophia  non  ancilla  Theologiae,  occurs 
criticism  of  the  'Tractatus  Theologico-politicus.'  Spinoza  is 
described  as  '  Athens  quidem,  sed  Cartesianus  tamen  '  on  p. 
35,  and  on  p.  44  we  find  an  early  instance,  perhaps  the  earliest, 
of  a  pun  which  afterwards  became  current  (see  citations  from 
Andala  and  De  Vries  above)  :  *  Spinosam  Spinoss  argutiam 
prolixius  obtundere  visum.'  '  Van  Mastricht  shared  the  mis- 
take, not  uncommon  at  the  time,  of  attributing  to  Spinoza  the 
anonymous  book  '  Philosophia  Scripturae  interpres,'  really  by 
Dr.  Meyer.  '  Idem  (et  forte  etiam  ipse  idem)  aliis  licet 
verbis,  habet  Exercitator  paradoxus  de  P kilos.  Interp.  Script! 

&c.  (p.  35)- 

Jo.  van  de  Weyen  (read  van  der  Waeyen)  in  Summa 
Theologise  (Pars  Prior,  Franeq.  1689). 

The  following  English  works  of  the  late  seventeenth  and 
eighteenth  century,  more  or  less  concerned  with  Spinoza,  are 
not  in  Bibliogr. 

Cudworth  (Ralph,  D.D.). — True  Intellectual  System  of 
the  Universe,  book  i.  c.  5,  p.  707  (the  pagination  is  the  same 
in  ed.  pr.  1678,  fo.,  and  ed.  1743,  2  vols.  4to.)  : 

'As  for  that  late  theological  politician,  who,  writing 
against  miracles,  denies  as  well  those  of  the  former  [by 
natural  power  of  angels,  &c.]  as  of  this  latter  [supernatural] 
kind  ...  we  find  his  discourse  every  way  so  weak,  ground- 
less, and  inconsiderable,  that  we  could  not  think  it  here  to 
deserve  a  confutation.' 

Blackmore, — Creation.  A  philosophical  poem.  In  seven 
books.  By  Sir  Richard  Blackmore,  Knt.  M.D.,and  P^cllow  of  tlic 
College  of  Physicians  in  London.     London  :  INIDCCXII.  8vo. 

'  Such  ornaments  of  argument  were  then  in  fashion,  and  Spinoza  is  here  in  no 
less  orthodox  company  than  Hildebrand's,  of  whom  our  author  speaks  thus  (p.  3) 
'  Gregorius  septimus,  Hildebrandus  (Hellebrandum  sue  nomine  dixeris'). 

b 


xxxii  INTRODUCTION. 

Also  to  be  found  in  the  collection  of  English  Poets  edited  by 
Johnson.  It  is  a  didactic  poem  on  natural  theology  ;  in  the 
course  of  which,  as  the  author  announces  (Preface,  p.  xviii.) 
'  the  modern  atheists,  Vaninus,  Hobbs,  and  Spinosa '  are 
spoken  of  in  their  turn.  Again  he  says  in  the  Preface 
(p.  xlv)  :- 

'Will  they  [the  irreligious  gentlemen  of  the  age]  derive 
their  certainty  from  Spinosa  }  Can  such  an  obscure,  perplext, 
unintelligible  Author  create  such  Certainty,  as  leaves  no  Doubt 
or  Distrust .-'  If  he  is  indeed  to  be  understood,  what  does  he 
alledge  more  than  the  ancient  Fatalists  have  done,  that  should 
amount  to  Demonstration  .' ' 

The  confutation  of  Spinoza  in  the  body  of  the  work  is  in 

Book  3,  V.  742.     It  is  not  without  curiosity  as  a  specimen  of 

what    then    passed    muster    in    England    as  philosophy  and 

poetry : — 

Spinosa  next,  to  hide  his  black  design, 

And  to  his  Side  th'  unwary  to  indine, 

For  Heavn  his  Ensigns  treacherous  displays, 

Declares  for  God,  while  he  that  God  betrays  : 

For  whom  he's  pleas'd  such  Evidence  to  bring, 

As  saves  the  Name,  while  it  subverts  the  Thing. 

Now  hear  his  labour'd  Scheme  of  impious  Use  ; 
No  Substance  can  another  e'er  produce. 
Substance  no  Limit,  no  Confinement  knows, 
And  its  Existence  from  its  Nature  flows. 
The  Substance  of  the  Universe  is  one, 
Which  is  the  Self-existent  God  alone. 

The  Spheres  of  Ether,  which  the  World  enclose, 
And  all  th'  Apartments,  which  the  Whole  compose  ; 
The  lucid  Orbs,  the  Earth,  the  Air,  the  Main, 
With  every  diff'rent  Being  they  contain, 
Are  one  prodigious  Aggregated  God, 
Of  whom  each  Sand  is  part,  each  Stone  and  Clod. 
Supream  Perfections  in  each  Insect  shine, 
Each  Shrub  is  Sacred,  and  each  Weed  Divine. 

Sages,  no  longer  Egypt's  Sons  despise. 

For  their  cheap  Gods,  and  Savoury  Deities  ! 

No  more  their  course  '  Divinities  revile  I 

To  Leeks,  to  Onions,  to  the  Crocodile, 

You  might  your  humble  Adorations  pay. 

Were  you  not  Gods  your  selves,  as  well  as  thej. 


INTRODUCTION.  xxxiii 

As  much  you  pull  Religion's  altars  down, 
By  owning  all  Things  God,  as  owning  none. 
For  should  all  Beings  be  alike  Divine, 
Of  Worship  if  an  Object  you  assign, 
God  to  himself  must  Veneration  shew, 
Must  be  the  Idol  and  the  Vot'ry  too  ; 
And  their  assertions  are  alike  absurd. 
Who  own  no  God,  or  none  to  be  ador'd. 

Colliber.  An  Impartial  Enquiry  into  the  Existence  and 
Nature  of  God  &c.  The  third  edition.  By  Samuel  Colliber. 
London,  1735.  8vo,  pp.  276.  Spinoza  is  several  times  cited 
in  order  to  be  contradicted  ;  in  some  places  the  words  of  the 
original  are  given. 

Brampton  Giirdon.  A  Defence  of.  Natural  and  Revealed 
Religion  :  Being  a  collection  of  the  sermons  preached  at  the 
lecture  founded  by  the  Honourable  Robert  Boyle,  Esq.  ;  (from 
the  year  1691  to  the  year  1732).  3  vols.  Lond.  1739,  fo. 

At  p.  277.  The  Pretended  Difficulties  in  Natural  or 
Reveal'd  Religion  no  Excuse  for  Infidelity.  Sixteen  Ser- 
mons preached  in  the  church  of  Saint  Mary  le  Bow,  London  ; 
in  the  years  1721  and  1722.  At  the  lecture  founded  by  the 
Honourable  Robert  Boyle,  Esq.  By  Brampton  Gurdon,  A.JVI. 
Chaplain  to  the  Right  Honourable  Thomas  Earl  of  Maccles- 
field, Lord  High  Chancellour  of  Great  Britain. 

Criticism  of  Spinoza  occurs  at  pp.  297,  299-308,  329-30, 

345>  358,  363-5- 
■  Ramsay.     The  ]  philosophical  ]  principles  |  of  \  natural  and 

revealed  |  religion.  |  Unfolded  |  in  |  a  geometrical  order  |  by  the 
Chevalier  Ramsay  |  author  of  the  travels  of  Cyrus.  |  Glas- 
gow :  I  printed  and  sold  by  Robert  Foulis.  |  MDCCXLVIII. 
2  vols.  4to.  Vol.  I.  (pp.  viii  and  541)  contains  frequent  cri- 
ticism on  Spinoza.     At  p.  497 : 

Appendix  '.  to  the]  foregoing  work  :  |  containing  |  a  |  refuta- 
tion I  of  the  first  book  of  |  Spinosa's  Ethics ;  |  by  which  |  the  whole 
structure  |  is  undermined.     At  pp.  539~54i  • 

'  From  all  this  it  appears  that  Spinosa's  monstrous  system 
is  composed  of  Cabbalism,  Cartesianism,  and  Predestinarian- 
ism  differently  conjoined  and  interwoven.  .  .  .  With  regard 
to  moral  actions,  the  Spinosian  errors  arc  not  so  much  abuses, 

b2 


xxxiv  INTRODUCTION. 

as  natural  and  necessary  consequences  of  the  Predestlnarian 
scheme.  If  this  be  so,  then  it  is  possible  that  Spinosa  did 
not  think  himself  an  Atheist.  ... 

'  Those  who  have  undertaken  the  confutation  of  this  philo- 
sopher have  not  as  yet  succeeded.  All  that  Bayle  says 
against  Spinosa  is  unworthy  of  our  notice.  That  ingenious 
author  scarce  ever  dipt  beyond  the  surface  of  things.  .  .  . 

'  We  have  endeavoured  to  disclose  the  mysterious  jargon  of 
this  dark  system,  represent  it  in  its  true  light,  and  confute  it  in 
two  different  manners,  by  demonstrating  truths  diametrically 
opposite  to  its  principles,  and  by  proving  that  all  its  demonstra- 
tions are  sophistical.  We  conclude  with  this  sole  remark, 
that  till  Predestlnarian  and  Cartesian  principles  be  ban- 
ished from  the  Christian  schools,  Spinosism  can  never  be 
solidly  confuted.' 

Vol.  ii.  (pp.  462)  is  on  ancient  religions  and  mythology, 
and  appears  to  contain  no  further  mention  of  Spinoza, 

Dugald  Stewart.  In  the  First  Preliminary  Dissertation  of 
the  Encyclop(2dia  Britannica  (vol.  i,  p.  144  in  7th  ed.)  a  few 
pages  are  given  to  Spinoza.  They  are  of  no  value  at  the  pre- 
sent day. 

Gibbon.  In  the  Critical  Observations  on  the  Sixth  Book  of 
the  j^Eueid  {Misc.  Works,  ii.  510),  Gibbon  speaks  of 'the  prin- 
ciples which  the  impious  Spinoza  revived  rather  than  invented.' 
The  context  sufficiently  shows  that  '  the  impious  Spinoza '  was 
for  Gibbon  merely  a  stick  to  beat  Warburton  with. 

One  other  book  may  be  noticed  under  this  head,  merely 
to  save  trouble  to  other  students  of  Spinoza  literature  who 
may  come  across  it.  It  is :  '  APETH-AOFIA,  or  An  En- 
quiry into  the  Original  of  moral  Virtue  ;  wherein  the  false 
Notions  of  Machiavel,  Hobbes,  Spinoza,  and  Mr.  Bayle,  as 
they  are  collected  and  digested  by  the  Author  of  the  Fable  of 
the  Pees,  are  examined  and  confuted,  and  the  eternal  and  un- 
alterable Nature  and  Obligation  of  moral  Virtue  is  stated  and 
vindicated.  To  which  is  prefixed  a  prefatory  Introduction,  in 
a  Letter  to  that  Author.'  By  Alexander  Innes,  D.D.,  &c. 
Westminster,  MDCCXXVIIL,  8vo.,  pp.  xlii  and  333. 

There  is  not  a  word  in  the  body  of  the  book  about  Spinoza, 
nor  yet  about  Ilobbes  and  Bayle.     Machiavclli   is  once  cited 


INTRODUCTION.  xxxv 

as  an  authority.  The  argument  against  Mandeville,  who  is 
the  sole  object  of  attack,  proceeds  on  hedonistic  principles, 
and  there  is  even  an  attempt  at  what  late  writers  have  called 
a  hedonic  calculus  (p.  199),  so  that  I  fancy  the  work  may  be 
of  some  interest  for  the  history  of  utilitarianism. 

IV.  Not  as  a  matter  of  bibliography,  but  for  the  reader's 
general  convenience,  I  shall  here  mention  some  of  the  modern 
accounts  of  Spinoza. 

It  will  be  generally  admitted,  I  believe,  by  competent 
persons  that  Kuno  Fischer's  {Geschickte  dcr  neueren  Philoso- 
phies vol.  i.  part  2)  is  on  the  whole  the  fullest  and  best.  The 
author  has  the  merit,  too  rare  in  philosophical  literature,  of 
combining  thorough  analysis  with  clear  exposition  and  an 
admirable  style. 

In  English  the  best  general  view  is  still  given  by  Mr. 
Froude's  essay  reprinted  from  the  '  Westminster  Review  '  in 
Short  Studies  on  Great  Subjects.  The  chapter  on  Spinoza  in 
Lewes'  History  of  Philosophy  is  good  for  the  biographical 
part ;  as  to  the  philosophy,  it  excites  an  interest  which  it 
hardly  does  enough  to  satisfy.  There  is  a  good  article  in 
Blunt's  Dictionary  of  Sects,  Heresies,  &c.  (London,  1874),  s.  v. 
'  Spinoza,'  showing  careful  study  and  great  familiarity  with 
the  Ethics  ;  but  it  is  of  necessity  much  condensed.  Com- 
pare '  Spinozism  '  in  the  same  editor's  Diet,  of  Doctrinal  and 
Historical  Theology.     London,  1871. 

Hallam's  account  must  be  mentioned  as  occurring  in  a 
work  classical  in  its  own  line  ('  Literature  of  Europe,'  part  iv. 
ch.  iii.,  ss.  71-96,  ch.  iv.  ss.  9-12).  It  is  painstaking  and 
perhaps  as  free  from  material  inaccuracy  as  a  mere  abstract 
can  be.  A  more  popular  one,  candid  and  careful  as  far  as  it 
goes,  is  in  Milman's  *  History  of  the  Jews,'  vol.  iii.  p.  374,  sqq. 
(3rd  ed.  1863). 

Dr.  van  Vloten's  Bencdictus  de  Spinoza  naar  Leven  en 
Werken  (2nd  ed.,  Schiedam,  1871)  is  a  work  more  addressed 
to  non-philosophical  readers  than  Kuno  Fischer's,  but  his 
account  is  thus  far,  unfortunately,  accessible  only  to  those 
who  can  read  Dutch.  Spinoza's  doctrines  are  stated,  as  far 
as  possible,  in  his  own  language,  so  that  the  book  has  a  value 


xxxvi  INTRODUCTION. 

independent  of  Dr.  van  Vloten's  interpretation,  which  on 
many  points  is  open  to  discussion.  I  am  bound  to  say,  how- 
ever (the  more  so  as  divers  philosophers  by  profession,  both 
in  the  Netherlands  and  in  Germany,  have  unduly  slighted  his 
work),  that  in  the  main  I  agree  with  his  results.' 

The  most  determined  adversary  of  Dr.  van  Vloten  is  Dr. 
Spruyt,  now  a  professor  of  philosophy  at  Amsterdam  (Van 
Vloten's  Benedictus  de  Spinoza  beoordeeld  door  C.  B. 
Spruyt.  Utrecht,  1876.  8vo.,  pp.  xi.  and  lOo).  His  work, 
though  short,  has  three  distinct  aims  :  vindication  of  Descartes, 
especially  as  to  his  services  to  physical  science  ;  criticisrh  of 
Dr.  van  Vloten's  treatment  of  Spinoza ;  and  criticism  of 
Spinoza  himself.  As  to  the  first  topic,  I  do  not  know  that 
Dr.  van  Vloten  would  really  have  much  to  say  to  the  contrary, 
and  I  certainly  have  nothing.  As  to  the  second,  Dr.  van 
Vloten  is  well  able  to  take  care  of  himself,  and  moreover  Mr. 
Lotsy  has  come  to  support  him.  But  it  is  curious  that,  not- 
withstanding Dr.  Spruyt's  vehement  and  supercilious  criticism 
of  most  parts  of  Dr.  van  Vloten's  work,  his  own  remarks  on 
Spinozism  amount  to  a  virtual  admission  that  Dr.  van  Vloten's 
view  of  the  general  effect  and  tendency  of  Spinoza's  philo- 
sophy is  correct.  The  real  difference  is  on  the  question  how 
far  Spinoza  was  himself  aware  of  its  tendency,  and  a  question 
of  this  kind  is  seldom  so  free  from  doubt  as  to  justify  one  in 
treating  with  absolute  contempt  an  opinion  different  from 
one's  own.  As  to  Spinoza  himself,  there  is  only  one  thing  to 
be  said  of  Dr.  Spruyt's  criticism.  Haeret  in  cortice.  It  is  the 
kind  of  criticism  that  naturally  occurs  to  a  reader  instructed 
in  modern  philosophy  who  looks  into  Spinoza  without  any 
serious  endeavour  to  discover  what  was  really  in  his  mind. 
It  makes  verbal  points  effectively,  but  adds  no  more  to  our 
understanding  of  Spinoza  than  the  abundant  criticism  of  the 
same  kind  that  has  gone  before  it.  One  point  of  substance  is 
well  seen,  namely,  that  Spinoza's  philosophy  is  not  the  flawless 
miracle  of  consistency  imagined   by  many  writers.     But  Dr. 

'  On  the  unveiling  of  the  statue  of  Spinoza  at  the  Hague  on  September  14, 
1880,  Dr.  van  Vloten  delivered  an  address,  which  is  printed  in  the  form  of  a 
pamphlet  (Spinoza  de  blijde  boodschapper  der  mondige  menschheid.  's  Graven- 
hage,  1880). 


'     INTRODUCTION.  xxxvii 

Spruyt  runs  into  the  other  extreme,  and  seems  to  think  no 
inconsistency  too  gross  to  ascribe  to  him.  Dr.  Spruyt  is  espe- 
cially scandalised  at  Spinoza's  theory  of  politics  (which, 
according  to  him,  is  quite  irreconcilable  with  the  Ethics),  and 
has  devised  for  it  the  neat  phrase  '  brutale  machtsvergoding  ;  * 
which  has,  I  believe,  been  a  source  of  great  comfort  to  anti- 
Spinozistic  clergymen  and  journalists. 

In  the  last  year  or  two  there  have  appeared  Herr  Theodor 
Camerer's  Die  Lehre  Spinoza  s  (Stuttgart,  1S77),  and  Mr. 
Lotsy's  Spinoza  s  Wijsbegeerte  (Amsterdam,  1878).  Hei-r 
Camerer's  book  is  a  minute  analysis  of  the  philosophy  of  the 
Ethics,  which  has  the  merit  of  never  shirking  a  difficulty, 
though  the  difficulties  are  sometimes  exaggerated.  Those 
who  know  Spinoza  already  may  find  it  suggestive  ;  and  for 
such  only  it  appears  to  be  written.  The  total  absence  of  his- 
torical criticism  is  a  rather  serious  defect.  Some  things  in 
Spinoza  are  naturally  obscure  if  one  does  not  look  back  at 
least  as  far  as  Descartes.  Mr.  Lotsy  takes  much  the  same  line 
as  Dr.  van  Vloten,  but  even  more  emphatically.  The  book 
is  vigorous,  clear-headed,  and  often  original  in  treatment.  It 
is  noticed  more  at  length  in  a  review  contributed  by  myself 
to  Mind  {]u\y  i?>7(),  p.  431). 

Then  there  is  a  class  of  writings  which  may  be  described 
as  mixed  exposition  and  criticism,  with  criticism  predominat- 
ing. Among  these,  which  are  very  numerous,  a  chief  place  is 
held  by  Trendelenburg's  essays,  Ueber  Spinoza's  Grund- 
gedanken  und  dessen  Erfolg  and  Ueber  die  aufgefnndenen 
Ergdnzungen  zu  Spinoza's  Werken  und  deren  Ertrag  fiir 
Spinoza! s  Leben  und  Lehre  {Historische  Beitrdge  zur  Philoso- 
phie,  vol,  ii.  p.  31,  and  vol.  iii.  p.  277).  The  later  of  the  two 
essays  is  occasioned  by  the  publication  of  De  Deo  et  Homine, 
but  is  by  no  means  confined  to  points  immediately  raised 
thereby. 

H.  C.  W.  Sig wart's  Der  Spinozismus  historisch  und  pJiilo- 
sophisch  erldutert,  drc.,  Tubingen,  1839  {Bibliogr.  310),  has 
suffered  the  fate  of  many  good  books  in  being  assimilated  by 
later  ones,  till  there  is  little  actual  need  to  consult  it  in  its 
original  form.     But  a  good  and  valuable  book  it  remains. 

An  elaborate  criticism  is  given  in  the  introductory  volume 


xxxviii  INTRODUCTION. 

to  Saisset's  translation.  It  is  avowedly  polemical,  and  belongs 
to  a  school  of  philosophy  which  may  now  happily  be  consi- 
dered pretty  well  extinct  even  in  its  own  country,  where  till 
quite  lately  it  sat  in  high  places.  But  Saisset  is  an  able  and 
fair  combatant,  and  stands,  I  think,  at  or  near  the  head  of  the 
distinctly  adverse  writers  on  Spinoza.  In  English  it  has  not 
been  my  fortune  to  meet  with  anything  of  the  kind  (save  Prof. 
Flint's  work  mentioned  below)  showing  competent  acquaint- 
ance with  the  subject. 

One  or  two  recent 'works  are  on  the  line  between  general 
and  special  monographs.     I  will  name  here : — 

Busolt  (Dr.  Georg) :  Die  Grundzuge  der  Erkenntnisz- 
Theorie  und  Metaphysik  Spinoza's  dargestellt,  erlautert  und 
gewijrdigt.  Von  der  Universitat  zu  Konigsberg  gekronte 
Preisschrift.     Berlin,  1875. 

Turbiglio  (Sebastiano)  :  Benedetto  Spinoza  e  letrasforma- 
zioni  del  suo  pensiero.      Libri  tre.     Rome,  1874. 

Signor  Turbiglio  seems  to  hold  that  Spinoza  never  fully 
developed  his  own  thought ;  he  distinguishes  between  '  lo 
Spinoza  reale,'  and  '  lo  Spinoza  fenomenico.'  Of  Spinoza's 
influence  he  says,  ad  fin. :  '  In  qualunque  punto  dell'  eta 
moderna  voi  interroghiate  il  pensiero  filosofico,  vi  si  revela  la 
presenza  dello  Spinoza.' 

Last,  not  least,  come  M.  Renan's  commemorative  address 
(Spinoza,  Discours  prononce  a  la  Haye  le  21  fevrier  1877,  ^ 
I'occasion  du  200*^  anniversaire  de  sa  mort.  The  Hague,  1877), 
a  masterpiece  in  its  kind  ;  and  Professor  Land's  lecture  Ter 
Gcdachteiiis  vafi  Spinoza  (Leyden,  1877),  which,  with  its 
illustrative  notes,  gives  in  a  small  compass  an  accurate  his- 
torical and  critical  survey  of  Spinoza's  philosophy,  and 
extracts  from  many  authorities  in  the  originals.  I  may  here 
note  that  any  one  who  wishes  to  make  a  special  study  of 
Spinoza  will  find  it  amply  worth  his  while  to  be  able  to  read 
Dutch. 

The  only  formal  commentary  on  Spinoza's  works  which  I 
know  of  is  J.  H.  von  Kirchmann's.  It  has  appeared  in  parts 
in  the  PJiilosopliische  Bibliothek,  and  is  now  to  be  had  as  a 
book  complete  in  itself,  or  together  with  the  translation  {sub 
(it.  Benedict  von  Spinoza's  sammtliche  philosophische  Werke 


INTRODUCTION.  xxxix 

iibersetzt  und  erlautert.  von    J.    H.   v.    Kirchmann    und    C. 
Schaarschmidt). 

It  is  hardly  needful  to  add  that  the  general  histories  of 
philosophy,  such  as  Erdmann's  and  Ueberweg's,  may  also  be 
usefully  consulted. 

V.  Among  special  monographs  and  discussions  those  on 
the  treatise  De  Deo  et  Homine  form  a  class  apart. 

Avenarius  (Dr.  Richard)  :  Ueber  die  beiden  ersten  Phasen 
des  Spinozischen  Pantheismus,  &c.     Leipzig,  1868  {Bibliogr. 

146). 

Schaarschmidt  (Prof  C.) :  Benedicti  de  Spinoza  korte  Ver- 
handelingvan  God,  de  Mensch  en  deszelfs  Welstand,  tractatuli 
deperditi  de  Deo  et  homine  ejusque  felicitate  v^ersio  Belgica. 
Ad  antiquissimi  codicis  fidem  edidit  et  praefatus  est  de  Spi- 
nozae  philosophiae  fontibus  Car.  Schaarschmidt.  Amstelodami 
1869  {Bib Hog K  51). 

Sigwart  (Dr.  Christoph)  :  Benedict  de  Spinoza's  kurzer 
Tractat  von  Gott,  dem  Menschen  und  dessen  Gluckseligkeit, 
&c.  Tubingen,  1870  {Bibliogr.  53).  A  translation  with  com- 
mentary :  cf.  the  same  author's  earlier  monograph  Spinoza  s 
neuentdeckter  Tractat,  drc.  Gotha,  1866  {Bibliogr.  144). 

All  these  are  important,  and  also  Trendelenburg's  essay 
already  mentioned.  I  must  be  allowed  to  express  the  pleasure 
I  have  found  in  Professor  Schaarschmidt's  preface,  apart  from 
its  considerable  philosophical  merits,  as  an  example  of  elegant 
and  unaffected  modern  Latinity.  Quite  lately  M.  Paul  Janet 
has  given  us  the  first  French  version  of  the  treatise,  with  an 
excellent  introduction  : 

Supplement  aux  QEuvres  de  Spinoza  :  Dieu,  I'homme  et 
la  beatitude :  traduit  pour  la  premiere  fois  en  frangais  et 
precede  d'une  introduction.     Paris,  1878. 

IMonographs  on  special  aspects  and  relations  of  Spinoza's 
philosophy  are  too  numerous  to  be  effectively  dealt  with  here. 
Dr.  Joel's  researches  on  the  Jewish  predecessors  of  Spinoza 
{Beit rage  zur  Geschichte  der  Philosophie,  Breslau,  1876,  a  re- 
issue of  several  earlier  published  essays  of  various  dates) 
are  mentioned  in  the  body  of  the  work  (ch.  iv.).  Dr.  Joel's 
inferences  are  criticised  by   Mr.  W.  R.  Sorley  in  Mind,  No. 


xl  INTRODUCTION. 

10,  July  1880,  'Jewish  Mediaeval  Philosophy  and  Spinoza,' 
who  holds  that  Spinoza's  relation  to  these  thinkers  '  was  as 
much  one  of  antagonism  as  Descartes'  relation  to  Christian 
Scholasticism,  and  indeed  much  more  so.' 

Spinoza's  Relation  to  Descartes. — Bouillier,  Histoire  de  la 
Philosophic  Cartesienne,  3rd  ed.,  Paris,  1868,  2  vols.,  chaps. 
xv-xix  in  vol.  i.  being  on  Spinoza  (not  in  Bibliogr.). 

Dr.  F.  G.  Hann  :  Die  Ethik  Spinoza's  und  die  Philosophic 
Descartes,  Innsbruck,  1875. 

Encyclopcedia  Briian?tica,  9th  ed.,  art.  Cariesianisnty  by 
Professor  Caird. 

All  these  writers  adhere  to  the  view  that  Spinoza's  philo- 
sophy is  a  direct  development  from  Descartes,  and  little  or 
nothing  else. 

Bearings  of  Spinoza  on  Moderji  Theology. — Heine  :  Zur 
Geschichte  der  Religion  und  Philosophic  in  Deutschland,  2tes 
Buch.  Samnitl.  Werke,vo\.w.  p.  123  sqq, 

Matthew  Arnold  :  Spinoza  and  the  Bible.  In  Essays  in 
Criticism,  3rd  ed.  London,  1875,  at  p.  357. 

Prof.  Robert  Flint :  Anti-theistic  theories.  Being  the 
Baird  lecture  for  1877.      Edinburgh  and  London,  1879. 

Pp.    358-375    are   on    Spinoza;    also   note   xxxviii.   pp. 

547-552. 

Prof  Flint's  opinions  as  to  the  value,  speculative  and 
practical,  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  belong  to  a  school  from 
which  I  widely  differ  :  he  speaks,  for  example,  of  the  ethical 
and  political  applications  of  Spinoza's  doctrine  as  'immoral 
and  slavish.'  But  his  work  deserves  respect  as  that  of  a 
thoroughly  competent  scholar.  The  note  will  be  found  useful 
by  students. 

Dr.  M.  M.  Kalisch:  Path  and  Goal.  London,  1880:  see 
pp.  377-405,  in  title  '  Pantheism.' 

Relations  of  Spinoza  to  Modern  Philosophy  a?id  Literature. 
— Conrad  von  Orelli :  Spinoza's  Leben  and  Lchre,  &c.,  2nd 
cd.     Aarau,  iS^o  {Bibliogr.  130). 

The  specific  object  of  this  work  is  to  defend  Spinoza 
against  the  critici.-^.ms  of  Schelling,  Hegel,  and  their  followers. 
It  contains  a  careful  discussion  of  Spinoza's  philosophy,  and 
collects  many  opinions  and  sayings  of  modern  writers  on  him. 


INTRODUCTION.  xli 

Nourrisson :  Spinoza  et  le  naturalisme  contemporain. 
Paris,  1866  {Bibliogr.  141). 

In  this  little  book  literary  and  bibliographical  notices  of 
real  interest  are  strangely  associated  with  superficial  and  de- 
clamatory criticism.  Cf.  M.  Paul  Janet's  article  in  Revue  des 
Deux  Mondes,  July  15,  1867. 

Dr.  S.  E.  Lowe'nhardt :  Benedictus  von  Spinoza  in  seinem 
Verhaltnisz  zur  Philosophie  und  Naturforschung  der  neueren 
Zeit.     Berlin,  1872. 

An  able  vindication  of  the  harmony  of  Spinoza's  doctrine 
with  modern  physiology  and  psychology.  Several  modern 
criticisms  of  Spinoza  are  considered  in  detail. 

Paul  Janet :  French  Thought  and  Spinozism.  In  Contem- 
porary Review,  May  1877, 

Dr.  Karl  Rehorn :  G.  E.  Lessing's  Stellung  zur  Philoso- 
phie des  Spinoza.     Frankfurt  am  Main,  1877. 

Guyau :  La  morale  d' Epicure  et  ses  rapports  avec  les 
doctrines  contemporaines.     Paris,  1878. 

Pp.  227-237  are  on  Spinoza.  '  Le  vaste  systeme  de 
Spinoza,  ou  ceux  d'Epicure  et  de  Hobbes  sont  absorbes,  con- 
tient  d'avance  les  theories  fondamentales  de  I'ecole  utilitaire 
frangaise  et  anglaise.' 

Jellinek  (Dr.  Georg)  :  Die  Beziehungen  Gothes  zu 
Spinoza.  Vortrag  gehalten  im  Vereine  der  Literaturfreunde 
zu  Wien.     Wien,  1878. 

Frohschammer  (Prof  J.) :  Ueber  die  Bedeutung  der 
Einbildungskraft  in  der  Philosophie  Kant's  und  Spinoza's. 
Munchen,  1879.  The  part  concerned  with  Spinoza  (pp. 
1 18-172)  is  an  ingenious  attempt  to  read  into  Spinoza,  or 
exhibit  as  necessary  for  the  completeness  of  Spinoza's  system, 
an  approximation  to  the  author's  own  point  of  view. 

In  conclusion,  it  may  be  proper  to  say  a  word  of  the 
method  I  have  myself  followed.  While  I  have  endeavoured 
to  make  myself  acquainted  as  far  as  practicable  with  the 
modern  literature  of  the  subject,  my  opinions  of  the  meaning 
and  value  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  have  been  formed  by  the 
study  of  Spinoza  at  first  hand  ;  and  if  this  book  induces  even 
a  few  readers  to  do  the  same  thing  for  themselves,  and  to 


xlii  INTRODUCTION. 

forget  as  far  as  possible,  in  so  doing,  what  they  may  have 
read  about  Spinoza  here  or  elsewhere,  I  shall  desire  no 
other  success.  The  only  way  to  understand  a  great  philoso- 
pher is  to  meet  him  face  to  face,  whatever  the  apparent  diffi- 
culties. A  certain  amount  of  historical  preparation  is  indeed 
at  least  advisable  ;  for  to  apprehend  rightly  the  speech  of  a 
past  time  one  must  know  something  of  its  conditions.  Apart 
from  this,  the  author  is  his  own  best  interpreter,  and  it  has  been 
my  aim  rather  to  make  Spinoza  explain  himself  than  to  dis- 
cover explanations  from  the  outside.  As  Herder  says,  '  Einen 
Schriftsteller  aus  sich  selbst  zu  erklaren  ist  die  honestas  jedem 
lionesto  schuldig.' 


SPINOZA: 

HIS    LIFE    AND    PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER   I. 

THE   LIFE   OF   SPINOZA. 

Quae  cum  magna  modis  multis  miranda  videtur 
gentibus  humanis  regio  visendaque  fertur, 
rebus  opima  bonis,  multa  munita  virum  vi, 
nil  tamen  hoc  habuisse  viro  praeclarius  in  se, 
nee  sanctum  magis  et  mirum  carumque  videtur. 

Lucretius,  i.  726. 

Baruch  de  Spinoza  was  born  at  Amsterdam  on  November 
24,  1632.^  His  parents,  of  whose  circumstances  and  position 
in  life  nothing  certain  is  known,  were  members  of  the  com- 
munity of  Jewish  emigrants  from  Portugal  and  Spain  which 
had  then  been  established  in  the  Netherlands  for  something 
more  than  a  generation.  Before  we  enter  on  Spinoza's  life, 
it  may  be  not  amiss  to  let  our  attention  rest  for  a  while  on 
the  society  in  which  he  was  brought  up,  the  vicissitudes  of 
its  foundation  and  growth,  and  the  tone  of  thought  and  in- 
struction which  prevailed  in  it.'^     Something  we  may  there 

'  The  house  has  been  identified  with  great  probability  within  the  last  few 
years.  Certainty  is  to  be  attained,  however,  only  by  the  inspection  of  documents 
which  the  owner  of  the  house  refuses  to  produce. 

'^  My  chief  authority  on  this  subject  is  Gratz,   Geschichte  der  Juden,  vols.  ix. 
and  X.      I  have  also  consulted   Koenen,    Geschiedenis  der  Joden  in   Nederland 
(Utrecht,  1843). 

B 


2  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

find  to  throw  light  on  the  manner  in  which  the  early  signs  of 
Spinoza's  philosophical  genius  were  received  by  his  own 
people,  though  we  shall  assuredly  be  disappointed  if  we  look 
in  external  circumstances  of  education  or  study,  in  the  in- 
fluence of  masters  or  companions  either  Jewish  or  Gentile, 
for  an  explanation  of  that  genius  itself.  It  was  well  said  of 
an  Indian  poet  :  '  Of  mighty  men  and  of  great  rivers  the 
springs  are  obscure.'  The  enlarged  and  purified  vision  of 
modern  science  may  perceive  much,  and  guess  more,  of.  the 
conditions  that  make  the  appearance  of  genius  possible.  But 
the  conditions  which  fix  it  at  the  very  time  and  place,  the 
secret  workings  of  nature  which  bring  it  to  pass  that  an 
i^schylus,  a  Lionardo,  a  Faraday,  a  Kant,  or  a  Spinoza  is 
born  upon  the  earth,  are  as  obscure  now  as  they  were  a  thou- 
sand years  ago.  The  power  of  these  men  still  bears  with  it 
the  reverence  and  awe  that  belong  to  great  things  unaccount- 
able. 

The  result  of  the  persecutions,  banishments,  and  forcible 
conversions  which  had  earned  for  the  sovereigns  of  Spain  the 
title  of  Catholic,  and  laid  the  foundation  of  their  country's  ruin 
at  the  very  height  of  its  prosperity,  had  been  to  leave  in  Spain 
and  Portugal  a  large  class  of '  new  Christians,'  nominally  con- 
verted and  openly  conforming  Jews  who  in  many  cases  kept 
up  in  secret,  from  generation  to  generation,  some  remnant  of 
Jewish  usages.  Their  tendencies  to  covert  persistence  in  the 
faith  and  customs  of  their  fathers  were*  watched  by  the  In- 
quisition with  an  evil  and  sleepless  eye.  Persecutions,  autos  da 
_/"/,  and,  notwithstanding  all  the  vigilance  of  the  Spanish  govern- 
ment, flights  from  the  land  of  the  oppressor  were  constant. 
Towards  the  close  of  the  sixteenth  century  it  seemed  as  if  the 
precarious  state  of  the  Marranos — so  these  unacknowledged 
Jews  were  called — was  about  to  become  hopeless.  The  power 
of  Spain  still  waxed  in  Europe  ;  where  Spain  went,  there  the 
Inquisition  followed  ;  and  where  the  Inquisition  came,  there 
justice  and  mercy  ceased  to  be. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  3 

The  Italian  States,  which  had  formerly  offered  a  refuge  to 
the  exiles,  were  no  longer  safe  for  them.  England,  now  the 
chief  Protestant  country,  had  driven  out  the  Jews  three 
centuries  before,  and  they  did  not  again  find  admission  till 
the  last  days  of  the  Commonwealth.  It  was  out  of  the 
dominion  of  Spain  herself  that  the  light  of  deliverance  first 
shone.  The  fury  of  the  Inquisition  defeated  its  own  purpose. 
The  Netherlands  revolted  from  the  intolerable  combination  of 
secular  with  spiritual  tyranny ;  and  from  the  desperate  rising, 
as  it  at  first  seemed,  of  a  handful  of  subjects  in  a  corner  of  the 
Spanish  Empire  there  sprang  a  commonwealth  which  for  the 
greater  part  of  a  century  was  the  most  free,  the  most  pro- 
sperous, and  the  most  tolerant  in  Europe. 

No  sooner  was  the  independence  of  the  Netherlands 
practically  secure  than  the  new  Christians  of  Spain  and 
Portugal  began  to  look  thither  for  a  refuge.  In  or  about 
1 591  overtures  were  made  to  the  magistrates  of  Middelburg 
for  a  settlement  of  Marranos,  which  would  have  secured  to 
the  province  of  Zealand  the  first  advantages  of  Jewish 
industry  and  commerce.  The  civil  authorities  were  disposed 
to  enter  into  the  plan,  but  theological  prejudice  stood  in 
the  way.  The  Reformed  clergy  set  themselves  against  the 
proposal,  and  nothing  came  of  it.  But  in  the  spring  of  1593 
a  vessel  sailed  in  secret  from  Portugal  with  a  small  company 
of  Marranos,'  determined  to  adventure  themselves  on  the 
Dutch  coasts,  and  trust  their  fortunes  to  the  principles  of 
toleration  that  had  been  proclaimed  by  William  of  Orange. 
After  a  not  uneventful  voyage  they  landed  at  Emden,  and 
found  assistance  at  the  hands  of  German  Jews  already  settled 
some  time  past  in  East  Friesland.  By  their  advice  the  fugitives 
made  their  way  to  Amsterdam,  where  they  arrived  on  April  23. 
This  little  nucleus  of  a  colony  soon  received  accession.  In  1 596 
the  English  fleet  under  Essex,  returning  from  the  sack  of  Cadiz, 
brought  a  number  of  new   Christians,  presumably   not  un- 

'  Griitz,  ix.  492,  and,  as  to  the  exact  date,  ib,  note  10, 

B  2 


4  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

willing  prisoners,  who  openly  returned  to  Judaism  as  soon  as 
they  were  safe  in  Holland.  It  was  some  time  before  any 
official  notice  was  taken  of  the  new  community,  and  its 
recognition  was  hastened  by  a  curious  accident.  The 
celebration  of  the  Day  of  Atonement  attracted  the  suspicion 
of  the  citizens,  who  knew  that  the  immigrants  came  from 
Popish  lands,  and  guessed  that  their  mysterious  meeting 
could  be  nothing  else  than  a  Popish  plot.  The  congregation 
was  surprised  by  armed  force,  and  the  leaders  arrested. 
These,  once  in  the  presence  of  the  magistrates,  speedily 
convinced  them  that  the  Pope  and  the  Inquisition  were  as 
odious  to  themselves  as  to  the  Protestants  of  the  United 
Provinces.  Being  thus  made  known  to  the  civil  powers,  the 
Jews  were  emboldened  to  ask  leave  to  build  a  synagogue. 
After  some  discussion  this  was  granted,  and  the  first  syna- 
gogue of  Amsterdam  was  opened  in  1598.  Ten  years  later 
the  numbers  of  the  colony  had  so  much  increased  that  a  new 
synagogue  was  needed.  This  was  itself  only  temporary.  In 
1675,  when  the  Jewish  community  of  Amsterdam  had  reached 
the  height  of  its  prosperity,  the  present  Portuguese  synagogue 
was  completed,  amidst  the  felicitations  not  only  of  Jewish  but 
of  Christian  theologians  and  poets. 

Meanwhile  some  years  more  seem  to  have  passed  before 
the  Jews  acquired  a  distinct  legal  status.  They  were  ex- 
posed to  inconvenience  from  an  unexpected  quarter  ;  for  in 
the  battle  of  Remonstrants  and  Contra-Remonstrants  the 
worsted  Remonstrants  took  the  line  of  complaining  that 
various  strange  sects,  including  Jews,'  enjoyed  a  freedom  of 
worship  which  was  denied  to  themselves.  These  complaints 
did  the  Remonstrants  no  good,  but  they  did  the  Jews  some 
little  harm.  Mixed  marriages  were  forbidden ;  the  Jews 
were  once  threatened,  if  not  more,  with  the  closing  of  the 

'  'Ja  de  Joden  zelfs,  die  Chiistus  verzaken,  welke  zij  supplianten  {i.e.  your 
petitioners)  houden  voor  hun  eenigen  Heiland.' — Remonstrant  Petition,  1617,  ap. 
Koenen,  p.  145. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  5 

synagogue  ;  and  it  seems  that  in  other  parts  of  the  Nether- 
lands they  were  not  always  sure  even  of  personal  liberty.  In 
1619  an  ordinance  was  made  by  the  States  of  Holland,  on  the 
report  of  a  commission  appointed  some  time  before,  by  which 
provision  was  made  for  the  regular  admission  and  government 
of  the  Jews.^  After  this  the  Hebrew  colony  waxed  and 
throve  apace.  We  have  still  a  living  record  of  their  prosperity 
in  Rembrandt's  grave  and  majestic  portraits  of  Jewish 
merchants  and  rabbis.  And  they  increased  and  multiplied 
with  every  fresh  act  of  persecuting  folly  in  the  Spanish 
peninsula.  Had  the  Catholic  rulers  intended  to  impoverish 
their  own  countries  and  enrich  the  heretical  provinces,  they 
could  not  have  done  it  better.  The  exiles,  though  they  pre- 
served among  themselves  (as  their  descendants  still  preserve 
for  official  purposes)  the  use  of  the  Portuguese  and  Spanish 
languages,  and  even  in  their  ceremonies  and  manners  had 
some  remnants  of  their  old  outward  conformity  to  the  Church 
of  Rome,  soon  repaid  the  hospitality  of  their  adopted  country 
with  faithful  attachment,  as  well  as  with  the  material  advan- 
tages that  accompanied  their  settlement.  Spinoza  was  a  good 
citizen  if  not  an  active  one  ;  and  several  passages  of  his  writings 
show  that  the  free  institutions  of  the  Dutch  Republic  were  to 
him  the  object  not  merely  of  esteem  but  of  patriotic  affection. 
Yet  he  has  been  accused  even  in  our  own  time  of  preaching 
maxims  of  despotism.  But  for  the  present  let  us  return 
from  his  critics  to  his  immediate  ancestors  and  contemporaries. 
The  occasion  was  a  great  one  for  the  rising  Jewish 
community,  the  New  Jerusalem,  as  it  was  already  called  in 
Spinoza's  generation.  The  leaders  of  the  Amsterdam  syna- 
gogue might,  in  the  opinion  of  the  latest  and  most  exact 
historian  of  the  Jewish  nation,  have  done  wonders  if  they  had 
been  capable  of  making  the  most  of  their  fortune.     But  they 

'  Koenen,  147.  Each  Province  was  to  make  its  own  rules,  subject  to  tlie 
condition  that  no  distinctive  dress  or  badge  (such  as  was  usual  in  Catholic 
countries)  should  be  imposed.  Koenen  gives  no  particulars  of  what  was  done  at 
Amsterdam. 


6  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

were  not  men  of  that  stamp.  Ability,  industry,  and  fortitude 
they  possessed  :  the  renovating  power  of  genius  was  wanting. 
Their  learning  was  rather  of  that  formaHst  kind  which  is  dis- 
concerted by  genius,  and  forces  a  quarrel  on  it.  And  so  it 
was  when  genius  appeared  among  them  in  the  person  of 
Spinoza.  The  conjecture  which  deals  with  lost  possibilities 
might  amuse  itself  worse  than  with  the  contemplation  of  what 
the  author  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  '  and  friend 
of  De  Witt  might  have  done  for  his  people  in  civil  and  political 
matters  if  he  had  remained  in  their  community. 

Saul  Levi  Morteira,  said  to  have  been  Spinoza's  instructor, 
was  a  man  who  had  no  claim  to  original  powers.  He  was 
not  specially  remarkable  for  eloquence,  nor  did  he  stand  in 
the  first  rank  of  Jewish  learning  ;  altogether  he  was  of  those 
who  care  not  to  commit  themselves  out  of  beaten  paths. 
His  colleague,  Isaac  Aboab  de  Fonseca,  presided  over  the 
synagogue  of  Amsterdam  for  nearly  seventy  years.  Eloquence 
was  his  chief,  it  would  seem  his  only  gift.  His  discourses 
commanded  admiration,  but  he  was  neither  eminent  in 
learning  nor  fitted  to  deal  with  .questions  of  practical  moment. 
His  character  was  lacking  in  force,  his  perceptions  in  width 
and  comprehension  ;  he  was  not  capable  of  firm  and  clear- 
sighted action. 

A  better  known  personage  than  either  of  these  two  was 
Manasseh  ben  Israel.  His  father,  like  others  of  the  first 
founders  of  the  colony,  had  escaped  from  the  pious  cares  of 
the  Holy  Office,  shattered  in  body  and  ruined  in  estate,  to 
find  his  last  resting-place  among  his  own  people.  The  son 
has  a  place  in  the  social  history  of  England  by  his  unsparing 
efforts  to  procure  from  Cromwell  the  readmission  of  the  Jews. 
He  had  to  encounter  much  opposition,  including  an  extra- 
ordinary polemic  from  Prynne,  in  which  a  great  deal  of  curi- 
ous learning  was  mixed  up  with  repetition  of  all  the  mediaeval 
stories  of  Jewish  child-murder,  cannibalism,  and  sacrilege. 
Nor  did  he  live  to  see  his  purpose  effected  :  he  died  in  1657, 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  7 

and  the  Jews  found  their  way  back  into  England  on  a  footing 
of  informal  but  unquestioned  liberty  only  after  the  Restora- 
tion. But  the  way  had  none  the  less  been  made  for  them  by 
Manasseh  ben  Israel's  endeavours.  It  may  be  (as  Dr.  Gratz 
suggests)  that  the  very  foibles  of  his  character,  his  turn  for 
mystical  interpretations  of  theology,  and  his  credulity  as  to 
prophetic  signs  and  seasons,  were  additions  to  his  strength 
for  that  particular  work,  and  that  a  stronger  man  would  not 
have  done  it  so  well.  His  credulity  was  indeed  nothing 
singular :  about  the  same  time  a  deputation  of  Asiatic  Jews 
came  to  England  to  inquire  if  Cromwell  were  not  the  Messiah. 
For  his  learning,  it  was  ample  and  various,  and  extended  to 
European  as  well  as  Hebrew  literature.  But  it  did  not  save 
him  from  giving  himself  over  to  superstition  and  letter- 
worship  which  often  ran  into  puerilities.  He  was  a  voluminous 
writer,  but  wrote  with  an  undiscerning  hand,  mixing  up  in 
his  compilation  things  wise  and  foolish.  Yet  he  had  one 
power  which  may  at  times  almost  fill  the  place  of  genius — 
the  power  of  winning  men's  friendship.  He  was  of  an  open 
and  generous  nature,  which  showed  itself  in  that  frank 
urbanity  and  polished  conversation  which  is  wont  everywhere 
to  draw  confidence  to  it. 

At  the  time  when  the  congregation  of  Amsterdam  con- 
demned Spinoza,  Manasseh  ben  Israel  was  absent  on  his 
mission  to  England.  .  It  may  be  doubted  whether  his  presence 
would  have  ensured  any  more  rational  course  of  action. 
A  believer  in  the  verbal  inspiration  of  the  Talmud  could 
have  had  nothing  to  urge  for  moderation,  unless  on 
grounds  of  secular  policy  ;  and  in  this  case  it  is  by  no  means 
clear  that  policy  was  not  for  once  on  the  side  of  the 
fanatics. 

In  the  generation  before  Spinoza  the  Jewish  common- 
wealth of  Amsterdam  did  not  enjoy  unbroken  peace  within 
itself  For  many  years  there  was  a  schism  in  the  synagogue, 
arising  out  of  the  scandal  caused  to  the  stricter  members  b}- 


8  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

the  survival  of  Spanish-Catholic  practices  and  manners  ;  and 
in  Spinoza's  first  years  the  congregation  was  troubled  by  the 
strange  career  of  Uriel   da  Costa.     He  too,  deserves   brief 
mention  here  ;  not  that  he  was  a  person  of  any  weight  or  in- 
fluence, much  less  a  precursor  of  Spinoza  ;  but  his  fate  illus- 
trates the  temper  of  the  times,  and  his  excommunication  may 
have  served  as  a  precedent  in  Spinoza's  case.     He  was  born 
of  a  New  Christian  family  in  Oporto  ;  his  parents  were,  how- 
ever, orthodox  in  conviction  as  well  as  in  name,  and  he  re- 
ceived a  learned  education  under  Jesuit  instructors.     Dissatis- 
fied with  their  formal  dogmatism,  he  betook  himself  to  the 
study  of  the  prophets  of  the  Old  Testament  ;  and  the  result 
was  that  he  fled  to  Amsterdam,  together  with  his  mother  and 
brothers,  joined  the  synagogue,  and  changed  his  former  Chris- 
tian name  Gabriel  for   the  purely  Jewish  one  of  Uriel.     But 
here  also  disappointment  awaited  him.     He  was  perplexed 
and  shocked  by  the  discrepance  between  Judaism  such  as  he 
found  it,  or  thought  to  find  it,  in  the  Scriptures,  and  such  as 
it  had  been   made  by  Rabbinical  gloss  and  tradition.     He 
denounced  the  modern  teachers  and  rulers  as  Pharisees,  and 
set  their  ceremonies  at  naught  ;  they  replied  to  his  criticism 
by  excommunicating  him.     He  went  on  to  publish  a  contro- 
versial tract  against  the  immortality  of  the  soul ;  upon  this  the 
chiefs  of  the  synagogue  denounced  him  to  the  civil  authorities, 
and  he  was  fined  and  imprisoned,  and  his  book  publicly  burnt. 
For  fifteen  years  he  endured  the  social  penalties  of  excom- 
munication, but  at  length  his  patience  gave  way,  and  he  was 
formally  reconciled.     But  he  seems  to  have  made  no  secret  of 
the  purely  outward  character  of  his  conformity.'     At  this  very 
time  his   course  of  unregulated  speculation   was  leading  him 
on  from  an  anti-Rabbinical  and  as  it  were  Puritan  Judaism 
to  a  doctrine   of  bare  natural  Deism.     Nor  did  he  observe 
ordinary  caution  in  his  conversation.     There  followed  a  new 
and    more  stringent  excommunication,  to  be  taken  off  only 

'  Er  woUte,  wie  er  sagte,  '  unter  Afifen  auch  ein  Affe  sein. '     Gratz,  x.  137. 


THE  LIFE  OF  SPINOZA.  9 

on  condition  of  a  solemn  and  public  act  of  penance.  Da  Costa 
held  out  this  time  for  seven  years,  and  then  again  submitted. 
He  underwent  a  humiliating  ceremony,  modelled  on  those  of 
the  Inquisition,  which  were  probably  known  by  bitter  personal 
experience  to  some  of  those  present. 

It  is  a  general  fact  in  human  history,  and  one  of  the  sad- 
dest, that  no  sooner  has  a  persecuted  community  secured  its 
freedom  than  it  takes  to  persecuting  in  its  turn.  This  was 
shown  at  the  very  same  time  by  the  Reformed  Church  of  the 
Netherlands :  '  Those  who  but  a  few  years  before  had  com- 
plained of  the  cruelty  of  the  Church  of  Rome  were  no  sooner 
delivered  from  that,  than  they  began  to  call  for  the  same  ways 
of  persecuting  those  who  were  of  the  other  side.' '  And  it  was 
not  far  from  this  time  that  the  Puritan  colonists  of  New 
England  set  up  an  ecclesiastical  tyranny  far  more  oppressive 
and  searching  than  that  from  which  they  had  fled.  Da  Costa's 
penance  was  completed  by  his  lying  down  athwart  the  thresh- 
old of  the  synagogue,  so  that  the  whole  congregation  stepped 
over  him  as  they  passed  out.  Humiliation  he  must  have  ex- 
pected, but  the  reality  was  too  much  for  his  pride.  He  deter- 
mined to  live  only  so  long  as  was  needful  to  commit  to  writ- 
ing, in  the  form  of  an  autobiography,  a  fierce  denunciation  of 
his  enemies  and  persecutors.  Having  completed  this  writing, 
he  shot  himself  in  his  own  house. 

It  does  not  seem  that  Da  Costa's  speculations  had  any 
value,  and  his  character  cannot  be  said  to  call  for  admiration. 
Martyrs  and  confessors  in  the  cause  of  free  thought  have  not 
been  so  few  or  so  weak  that  one  who  was  twice  excommuni- 
cated, and  twice  recanted,  can  claim  a  high  place  among  them  ; 
and  there  was  at  least  a  large  element  of  personal  pique  and 
resentment  in  Da  Costa's  later  courses.  But  we  cannot  refuse 
our  pity  to  a  life  cast  among  such  untoward  surroundings,  nor 
can  we  acquit  the  chiefs  of  the  synagogue  of  excessive  and 
ill-judged  harshness  throughout  their  dealings  with  this  un- 
'  Burnet,  History  of  his  oxvn  'fiiitc,  i.  315. 


lo  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

happy  man.     His  story  prepares  us  to  hear  with  much  less 
surprise  of  Spinoza's  treatment  sixteen  years  later. 

As  to  the  general  state  of  education  among  the  Jews  of 
Amsterdam,  they  were  exceedingly  well  provided  with  the 
appliances  of  learning  and  literature  then  current.  So  much 
would  sufficiently  appear  from  Spinoza's  works  and  corre- 
spondence alone.  His  writing  is  that  of  a  man  who  has  been 
brought  up  among  scholars  and  has  mastered  betimes  all  the 
knowledge  that  a  scholar  is  expected  to  possess.  But  high 
literary  culture  and  great  literary  facility  are  compatible  vvith 
great  feebleness  of  intellectual  grasp.  Scholarship  is  in  itself 
no  warranty  of  sound  thinking.  And  so  it  was  that  the 
Hebrew  scholars  who  exchanged  more  or  less  elegant  Latin 
verses  with  European  scholars  of  the  stamp  of  Grotius  or 
Barlaeus  were  ready  and  even  eager  to  give  ear  to  the  wildest 
and  most  idle  fancies  in  matters  of  theology  and  philosophy. 
The  doctrine  of  the  Kabbalah,  likened  by  the  historian  to 
whom  I  am  so  much  indebted  to  a  fungus  growth  creeping 
over  the  body  of  the  Law  and  the  Traditions,  was  almost  uni- 
versally received.  A  generation  filled  with  the  east  wind  of 
mystical  ravings  hungered  after  signs  and  wonders,  and  signs 
and  wonders  came  without  stint.  Demoniacs,  exorcisms, 
miracles,  false  prophets,  even  false  Messiahs,  fed  the  credulity 
of  the  Levantine  Jews,  and  deceived  not  a  few  elsewhere. 
The  most  singular  appearance  of  this  kind,  the  career  of 
Sabbatai  Zevi,  belongs  however  to  a  somewhat  later  date. 
Accounts  of  the  dreams,  revelations,  and  supernatural  feats  of 
the  new  prophets  were  published  and  eagerly  read  ;  and 
besides  these  the  epidemic  of  superstition  produced  a  specu- 
lative literature  of  its  own.  One  of  these  works,  composed 
by  a  Polish  Jew,  Naphtali  ben  Jakob  Elchanan,  who  had 
caught  the  Kabbalistic  contagion  in  Palestine,  and  published 
at  Amsterdam  in  1648,  is  described  by  Dr.  Gratz '  as  not 
containing  a  single   rational  sentence  :  '  yet  leading  rabbis  of 

'  Griitz,  X.   131. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  it 

Germany  and  Poland  accepted  this  puddle  of  nauseous 
blasphemy  as  a  fountain  of  divine  wisdom.'  If  these  were  the 
studies  in  favour  among  Spinoza's  teachers  and  companions, 
we  can  hardly  wonder  at  the  tone  of  something  like  contempt 
in  which  he  generally  speaks  of  current  Jewish  opinion. 

Such,  then,  was  the  society  into  which  Spinoza  was  born. 
The  accustomed  course  of  education  was  almost  if  not  alto- 
gether confined  to  the  Hebrew  language  and  literature.  With 
these,  therefore,  Spinoza  was  early  made  familiar,  and  at  the 
age  of  fifteen  he  had  gone  so  far  in  the  study  of  the  Talmud  as 
to  be  one  of  Rabbi  Morteira's  most  promising  pupils.  In  the 
advanced  classes  of  the  Amsterdam  school  he  had  the  oppor- 
tunity of  mastering  the  philosophical  writings  of  the  golden  age 
of  modern  Jewish  learning,  the  commentaries  of  Maimonides 
and  Ibn  Ezra.  The  probable  effect  of  these  on  the  develop- 
ment of  his  thought  will  be  more  fully  spoken  of  in  a  later 
place.  Enough  to  say  here  that  he  found  in  the  hints  and 
questionings  of  these  men  much  more  than  his  teachers 
expected  him  to  find  or  were  themselves  capable  of  find- 
ing. 

Secular  learning  and  accomplishments  had  to  be  sought 
in  other  quarters.  The  elements  of  Latin  were  imparted  to 
Spinoza  by  a  German  master  whose  name  is  not  known  ;  he 
continued  the  study  with  Francis  van  den  Ende,'  a  physician 
as  well  as  a  man  of  letters,  whose  high  reputation  as  a  teacher 
was  qualified  by  the  suspicion  that  he  taught  his  pupils  free- 
thinking  as  well  as  Latin.  The  charge  may  have  been  true, 
but  it  may  just  as  well  have  been  a  mere  popular  inference 
from  the  known  fact  that  he  was  a  proficient  in  the  natural 
sciences.  So  much  is  certain,  and  it  is  probable  that  he 
communicated  this  part  of  his  knowledge,  no  less  than  that 
which  he  specially  professed  to  teach,  to  those  who  showed 

'  llis  name  is  given  in  Ihe  documents  relating  to  tlie  Clievalicr  de  Rohan's 
plot  as  Francis  Affinius  van  den  Enden.  Sc«  Clement,  Episodes  de  I'Histoiie  de 
France,  Paris,  1859. 


12  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

themselves  apt  for  it :  for  Spinoza's  works  afford  unmistak- 
able evidence  of  thorough  and  sound  instruction  in  physical 
science,  and  more  especially  physiology,  which  cannot  well 
have  been  acquired  at  a  later  time  of  his  life  ;  not  that  he 
makes  any  great  display  of  knowledge,  but  that  with  many 
occasions  for  mistakes  he  commits  few  or  none.  As  to  Latin, 
at  all  events.  Van  den  Ende's  charge  was  efficiently  per- 
formed. Spinoza  mastered  it  completely,  not  indeed  accord- 
ing to  the  fine  and  exacting  standards  of  later  scholarship, 
but  more  completely  in  one  sense,  for  he  made  it  a  living 
instrument  of  thought.  His  language  is  not  what  we  call 
classical,  but  it  is  handled  with  perfect  command  and  per- 
fectly adapted  to  its  ends.  At  the  same  time  it  appears  by 
quotations  and  allusions  that  he  was  fairly  well  at  home  with 
the  Latin  classics.  His  knowledge  of  Greek  was  more 
limited,  and  by  his  own  account  not  critical.'  Of  modern 
languages  he  knew  French,  German,  and  Italian,  besides 
Portuguese  and  Spanish,  one  or  both  of  which  were  native  to 
him.  It  appears  from  evidences  made  public  early  in  the  last 
century,  but  afterwards  lost  sight  of  until  quite  recently,  that 
he  always  regarded  Dutch  as  a  foreign  language,  and  wrote 
it  only  with  difficulty.  Such  little  circumstances  help  us  to 
realize  the  self-contained  isolation  in  which  the  Hebrew  com- 
munity must  have  dwelt  even  among  well-wishers. 

It  was  perhaps  through  his  intercourse  with  Van  den 
Ende  that  Spinoza  became  acquainted  with  the  writings  of 
Giordano  Bruno  and  Descartes.  As  to  Descartes,  indeed, 
explanation  may  be  dispensed  with  ;  no  young  man  with  a 
philosophical  turn  of  mind  could  help  reading  him.  But  as 
to  Giordano  Bruno,  if  one  assumes  (on  the  grounds  to  be 
mentioned  hereafter)  that  Spinoza  had  read  him,  one  may  be 
fairly  called  on  to  assign  the  occasion  for  it.  Giordano  Bruno 
would  not  otherwise  have  come  naturally  in  Spinoza's  way  ; 
his  theories  were  scarcely  less  abhorrent  to  Jews  and  Pro- 

'   Tract.  Theol.-Pol.  cap.  x.  ad  fin. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  13 

testants  than  to  Catholics.  But  it  is  quite  possible  that  Van 
den  Ende  may  have  more  or  less  cherished  Bruno  in  private, 
and  discussed  him  with  a  select  few  of  his  learners.  This 
would  have  been  just  the  kind  of  study  to  procure  for  Van 
den  Ende  the  alarming  reputation  handed  down  to  us  by 
Colerus.  Besides  his  graver  pursuits  Spinoza  contrived  to 
acquire  considerable  skill  in  drawing  :  he  filled  a  book  with 
portrait  sketches,  many  of  them  being  of  distinguished  per- 
sons. This  book  was  at  one  time  in  the  possession  of  Colerus, 
but  there  is  no  further  trace  of  it. 

There  is  a  story  that  Van  den  Ende  was  assisted  in  his 
teaching  by  a  daughter,  of  singular  wit,  learning,  and  accom- 
plishments.    Spinoza,  the  story  goes,  was  among  her  pupils, 
and  from  a  pupil  became  a  lover.     But  he  had  a  rival  in  a 
fellow-pupil    named    Kerkering,  who  finally  won  the   lady's 
hand  by  the  help  of  a  valuable  pearl  necklace.     Now  it  is  true 
that  Van  den  Ende  had  a  daughter  named  Clara  Maria,  who 
married  Theodore  Kerkkrinck  (such  is  the  authentic  form  of 
the  name).     The   date  of  the  marriage,  however,    has  been 
ascertained  by  Van  Vloten  to  be  1671   (the  year  when  Van 
den  Ende  left  Holland),  and  it  appears  by  the  register  that  the 
bride  was  twenty-seven  years  old.     Now  Spinoza  was  excom- 
municated and  left  Amsterdam  in   1656.     Clara  Man'a  van 
den  Ende  was  therefore  eleven  or  twelve  years  old  at  the  latest 
time  when  Spinoza  could  have  been  her  father's  pupil,  and  the 
tale  of  the  students'  rivalry  and  the  pearl  necklace  must  be 
dismissed.     Kerkkrinck  was  a  physician,  who  published  works 
on  medicine,  anatomy  and  chemistry,  and  earned  a  consider- 
able scientific  reputation,  so  that  the  match  was  in  itself  a 
natural    one   enough    for   Van    den    Ende's   daughter.     The 
question  remains  whether  the  tale  of  Spinoza's  love  for  her  is 
absolutely  without  foundation.     There  is  no  reason  whatever 
to  suppose  that  Spinoza  did   not  keep  up  his  acquaintance 
with  Van  den   Ende  in    the  visits  which  we   know  that  he 
made  from  time  to  time  to  Amsterdam  ;  and  thus  we  have 


H  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

occasion  and  room  enough  for  a  friendship  extending  into 
Klaartje's  riper  years,  which  may  have  passed  into  a  serious 
inchnation.  A  romantic  affection  we  cannot  ascribe  to 
Spinoza  at  this  time :  it  would  be  too  much  out  of  keeping 
with  all  his  habits  and  character;  and  one  may  shrewdly 
suspect  that  his  inclination  never  in  truth  got  beyond  a 
hypothetical  stage.  He  was  likely  enough  to  be  rallied  by 
host  or  friends  on  his  hermit  life,  and  not  unlikely  to  put  them 
off  with  some  such  answer  as  that,  if  he  married  a  wife,  it 
should  be  Van  den  Ende's  daughter.  A  speech  or  two  of 
this  kind  would  be  ample  foundation  for  the  story  given  by 
Colerus,  and  a  simple  confusion  of  dates  would  do  the' rest. 

Yet  there  is  one  chance  left  if  we  are  minded  to  hold  fast 
to  the  solitary  piece  of  romance  that  can  be  suggested   in 
Spinoza's  life.     Nothing  forbids  us  to  suppose   that   at   the 
earlier  time  there  sprang  up  some  half  ideal,   half  childish 
affection  between  Spinoza  and  Clara  van  den  Ende  ;  there  is 
no   violation  of  possibility  in  conceiving  her  as  standing  to 
him  in  a  relation  like  that  of  Beatrice  to  Dante.     As  far  as 
ages  go  the  probability  is  even  greater  than  in  Dante's  case  ; 
so  that,  unless  we  join  ourselves  to  those  over-curious  persons 
who  Avould  allegorize  away  the    Vita  Niiova,  we  have  a  fair 
precedent  enough.     Beatrice  was  nine  years  old,  Dante  him- 
self only   ten,    when    the    '  glorious  lady  of   his    soul '  first 
showed  herself  to  his  eyes,  and  the  word  came  to  him,  Ecce 
dens  fortior  me,  qui  veniens  dominabitur  mihi.     Spinoza  was 
not  a  poet,  some  one  will  say.     No,  but  he  was  a  mystic  at 
the  time  in  question,  which  for  this  purpose  will  do  at  least  as 
well.     But  I  throw  out  this  merely  for  the  chance  of  anyone 
finding  comfort  in  it.     As  a  hypothesis  it  seems  to  me  much 
less  probable  than  the  other  ;  and  even  if  the  facts  had  been  as 
suggested,  Spinoza  was  not  the  man  to  be  very  communicative 
about  them.     The  truth  is  that  we  have  no  positive  evidence 
at  all.     We  have  only  a  story  which,    as    it   stands,    cannot 
possibly  be  true,  and  which  does  not  rest  on  any  satisfactory 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  15 

authority.  The  absence  of  any  apparent  motive  for  inventing 
the  whole  of  it  raises  a  certain  presumption  that  it  contains  in 
a  more  or  less  distorted  form  elements  of  genuine  fact, 
derived  from  statements  made  by  Spinoza  himself.  But  what 
those  elements  may  be  we  have  no  means  of  determining. 

As  to  Van  den  Ende  himself,  one  is  sorry  to  know  that 
he  came  to  a  bad  end.     In  his  old  age  he  settled  in  France, 
and  had  been  there  only  a  few  years  when  he  was  drawn  into 
the  conspiracy  of   the   Chevalier  de  Rohan  and  La  Treau- 
mont,  partly  by  working  on  his  patriotism  with  hopes  that  the 
affair  would  turn  to  the    profit  of  the    Netherlands,  partly 
by  flattering  his  speculative  fancy  with  dreams  of  a   Utopian 
republic    to   be    established    on    the    ruins    of    the    French 
monarchy.      A    general    rising    in    Normandy    was   to    be 
supported  by  a  descent    of  the  Dutch    fleet :    the   admiral, 
Cornelius  Tromp,  was  fully  prepared  to  take   his  part,  and 
long  hovered  on  the  French  coast  awaiting  the  signal,  which 
never  came.     But  the  conspiracy,  though  carefully  planned, 
was  hollow  from  the  first ;  it  was  a  venture  of  disappointed 
and  desperate  personal  ambitions.     It  was  discovered  before 
any  part  of  it  could  be  put  in  execution,  and  its  leaders  paid 
the  usual  penalty  of  unsuccessful  conspirators.  Van  den  Ende 
was  hanged  at  Paris  on  November  27,  1674. 
^       So  much  is  known  of  Spinoza  for  the  first  twenty-three 
years  of  his  life.     Not  long  after  he  had  fully  attained  man's 
estate  the  elders  of  his  people  began  to  remark  in  him  an 
unwonted  freedom  of  discourse,  and  pos.sibly  some  laxity  in 
ceremonial  observances  which  would  of  itself  have  sufficed  as 
an  ostensible  ground  of  censure.     One  anecdote  of  this  time, 
plausible  enough  to  be  worth  repeating,  has  come  down  to 
us.'      Two  fellow-students,    it    is   said,    questioned    Spinoza 
closely  on  theology ;  he  put  them  off  with  general  reference 
to  the  authority  of  Moses  and  the  Prophets  as  sufficient  for  all 

'  This  is  from  Lucas  ;  in  other  words  we  may  give  ic  just  so  mucli  credit  as 
it  appears  on  the  face  of  it  to  deserve. 


1 6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

true  Israelites.  But  as  far  as  their  authority  goes,  answered 
one  of  his  companions,  I  cannot  find  any  such  thing  as  that 
God  is  incorporeal,  the  soul  immortal,  or  angels  real  beings. 
What  say  you,  then,  to  these  matters  }  Spinoza  replied  that 
he  could  see  no  objection  in  point  of  orthodoxy  to  holding 
that  God  has  a  body,^  or  that  angels  are  mere  apparitions 
created  for  the  special  occasion  of  their  ministry  (for  which, 
indeed,  or  for  something  very  like  it,  there  is  Talmudic 
authority  :  a  circumstance  likely  enough  to  be  known  to 
Spinoza  and  overlooked  by  his  questioners),  and  that  the 
Scriptures  use  soul  as  a  pure  synonym  of  life,  without  saying 
anything  about  immortality.  The  two  friends  were  only  half 
satisfied  ;  but  Spinoza,  while  he  promised  to  give  them  fuller 
explanations  another  time,  contrived  not  to  find  any  oppor-. 
tunity  of  renewing  the  discourse.  We  have  no  trustworthy 
or  distinct  account  of  the  events  that  led  to  Spinoza's  rupture 
with  the  congregation  ;  but  certain  it  is  that  in  the  early  part  of 
the  year  1656  it  was  considered  by  Morteira  and  his  colleague 
that  action  of  a  decided  kind  must  be  taken. 

It  has  already  been  remarked  that  the  persecuted  of  Spain 
and  Portugal  had  brought  a  leaven  of  persecuting  zeal  to  their 
new  asylum.  But  in  this  case  reasons  of  secular  policy  were 
potent  counsellors  to  the  same  effect.  The  Jewish  community 
was  a  kind  of  state  within  a  state,  a  society  foreign  in  religion, 
language,  and  manners  to  its  hosts.  To  expose  themselves 
to  the  charge  of  fostering  novelties  in  speculation  might  well 
have  been  a  serious  danger  to  them.  As  prudent  governors 
of  their  household,  it  behoved  the  chief  men  to  suffer  no 
more  scandals  within  it  like  that  of  Da  Costa.  And  Spinoza's 
particular  novelties  might  be  thought  eminently  fitted  to 
bring  them  into  trouble.  He  busied  himself  with  Descartes, 
and  the  Synod  of  Dort  (not  the  first  and  famous,  but  a  second 
one)  had  just  condemned  Cartesianism.  The  best  way  would 
be  to  make  things  quiet  while  it  was  yet  time ;  the  next  best, 
■  Compare  Hobbes's  arguments  on  this  point. 


THE  LIFE  OF  SPINOZA.  \j 

if  the  erratic  member  could  not  be  brought  to  take  the  fitting 
measure  of  heed,  at  least  in  his  public  ways,  was  to  cut  him 
off  at  once  and  disclaim  all  responsibility  for  him.  Accord- 
ingly the  way  of  compromise  was  first  tried,  and  an  annuity 
of  looo  florins  was  offered  to  Spinoza  as  the  price  of  apparent 
conformity.  This  however  was  positively  declined.  The 
next  step  '  was  to  summon  Spinoza  before  the  congregation 
and  inflict  on  him  the  first  degree  of  ecclesiastical  censure,  the 
lower  excommunication,  which  excluded  the  offender  for 
thirty  days  from  the  society  of  the  faithful,  and  was  intended 
to  operate  as  a  serious  invitation  to  repentance. 

During  the  period  of  suspense  which  followed,  Spinoza's 
life  was  aimed  at  by  an  unknown  enemy,  presumably  some 
fanatic  outrunning  the  zeal  of  his  masters,  or  thinking  himself 
a  divinely  appointed  messenger  to  rebuke  their  tardiness  in 
defending  the  faith  by  a  striking  example.  This  man  set 
upon  Spinoza  with  a  dagger  one  evening  as  he  was  leaving 
the  Portuguese  synagogue.^  But  he  avoided  the  blow  in 
time,  and  it  pierced  only  his  coat,  which  he  afterwards  kept 
in  the  same  condition  as  a  memorial.  Being  warned  by  this 
attack  that  Amsterdam  was  no  longer  a  safe  place  for  him, 
he  betook  himself  to  the  hospitality  of  a  friend  who  dwelt  a 
little  way  out  of  the  city,  on  the  Ouwerkerk  road.  His  host 
belonged  to  the  small  dissenting  community  of  Remonstrants 
or  Collegiants.  Here,  under  the  roof  of  heretics  anathe- 
matized by  the  Synod  of  Dort,  he  learnt  the  final  decision  of 
the  Jewish  congregation  on  the  charge  of  heresy  against 
himself.  The  sentence  was  pronounced  on  July  27,  1656,  in 
the  Portuguese  language,  and  its  effect  is  as  follows : — 

'  Our  data  for  these  events  are  still  meagre,  and  their  order  in  time  uncertain : 
but  we  cannot  doubt  that  a  lesser  excommunication  preceded  the  final  one.  See 
Gratz,  X.  175.  Lucas  gives  what  purport  to  be  details  of  the  earlier  proceedings, 
but  in  his  usual  confused  manner  and  with  improbable  circumstances. 

*  I  follow  Colerus's  account  as  the  best  supported  and  most  probable.  Diffi- 
culties have  been  raised  about  the  incident  :  they  are  discussed  in  Van  VIoten's 
Levefisbode ,  ix.  419. 

C 


1 8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

'  The  chiefs  of  the  council  do  you  to  wit,  that  having  long 
known  the  evil  opinions  and  works  of  Baruch  de  Espinoza, 
they  have  endeavoured  by  divers  ways  and  promises  to  with- 
draw him  from  his  evil  ways,  and  they  are  unable  to  find  a 
remedy,  but  on  the  contrary  have  had  every  day  more  know- 
ledge of  the  abominable  heresies  practised  and  taught  by  him, 
and  of  other  enormities  committed  by  him,  and  have  of  this 
many  trustworthy  witnesses,  who  have  deposed  and  borne 
witness  in  the  presence  of  the  said  Espinoza,  and  by  whom  he 
stood  convicted  ;  all  which  having  been  examined  in  the 
presence  of  the  elders,  it  has  been  determined  with  their 
assent  that  the  said  Espinoza  should  be  excommunicated 
and  cut  off  from  the  nation  of  Israel  ;  and  now  he  is  hereby 
excommunicated  with  the  following  anathema  : — 

'  With  the  judgment  of  the  angels  and  of  the  saints  we 
excommunicate,  cut  off,  curse,  and  anathematize  Baruch  de 
Espinoza,  with  the  consent  of  the  elders  and  of  all  this  holy 
congregation,  in  the  presence  of  the  holy  books  :  by  the  613 
precepts  which  are  written  therein,  with  the  anathema  where- 
with Joshua  cursed  Jericho,  with  the  curse  which  Elisha  laid 
upon  the  children,  and  with  all  the  curses  which  are  written 
in  the  law.  Cursed  be  he  by  day  and  cursed  be  he  by  night. 
Cursed  be  he  in  sleeping  and  cursed  be  he  in  waking,  cursed 
in  going  out  and  cursed  in  coming  in.  The  Lord  shall  not 
pardon  him,  the  wrath  and  fury  of  the  Lord  shall  henceforth 
be  kindled  against  this  man,  and  shall  lay  upon  him  all  the 
curses  which  are  written  in  the  book  of  the  law.  The  Lord 
shall  destroy  his  name  under  the  sun,  and  cut  him  off  for  his 
undoing  from  all  the  tribes  of  Israel,  with  all  the  curses  of  the 
firmament  which  are  written  in  the  book  of  the  law.  But  ye 
that  cleave  unto  the  Lord  your  God,  live  all  of  you  this  day. 

'  And  we  warn  you,  that  none  may  speak  with  him  by  word 
of  mouth  nor  by  writing,  nor  show  any  favour  to  him,  nor  be 
under  one  roof  with  him,  nor  come  within  four  cubits  of  him, 
nor  read  any  paper  composed  or  written  by  him.' 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA. 


19 


From  the  terms  of  the  excommunication  something,  but 
not  much,  may  be  gathered  as  to  the  form  which  the  accusa- 
tion had  assumed.  It  is  not  on  the  face  of  it  a  condemnation 
for  mere  speculative  opinions  ;  indeed  such  a  condemnation 
would  not  be  warranted  by  Jewish  law.  The  *  heresies  practised 
and  taught  '  ('  horrendas  heresias  que  praticava  e  ensinava ') 
point  at  some  active  attempt  to  spread  his  opinions,  and  the 
mention  of  '  other  enormities  '  on  Spinoza's  part  ('  ynormes 
obras  que  obrava ')  probably  refers  to  breaches  of  ceremonial 
rules,  and  is  not  (though  to  an  English  reader  it  looks  so  at 
first  sight)  a  meaningless  addition  like  the  alia  enormia  of 
old-fashioned  English  pleadings. 

Thus  was  Baruch  de  Spinoza  made  an  outcast  from 
Israel,  and  cut  off  from  his  own  people  and  from  his  father's 
house.  The  ties  of  kindred,  ties  which  for  that  people  have  ever 
been  of  exceeding  strength  and  sanctity,  were  for  him  severed 
beyond  recall.  The  bond  of  fellowship  among  Israelites  is  of 
strength  and  sanctity  only  less  than  that  of  actual  kindred  ; 
and  this  also  was  at  once  and  irrevocably  dissolved.  The 
excommunicated  Jew  became  as  it  were  a  masterless  man  ; 
he  had  no  title  by  which  he  could  call  upon  either  Jew  or 
Christian  to  stand  by  him  or  answer  for  him.  If  it  is  a  good 
preparation  for  philosophy  to  be  alone  in  the  world,  the  need- 
ful discipline  came  upon  Spinoza  with  terrible  completeness. 
It  is  hardly  possible  for  men  at  this  time,  either  in  Spinoza's 
country  or  in  our  own,  to  realize  the  full  effect  of  such  a  blow. 
But  Spinoza  never  faltered  under  it :  the  passionate  weakness 
of  Uriel  da  Costa  was  far  from  his  nature.  '  This  compels  me/ 
he  said  on  receiving  the  news,  '  to  nothing  which  I  should  not 
otherwise  have  done.'  Thus  it  would  seem  that  he  held  him- 
self to  have  renounced  the  synagogue  of  his  own  motion  rather 
than  to  have  been  driven  from  it ;  and  the  title  of  a  defence 
which  he  wrote  in  Spanish  and  sent  to  the  elders  points  the 
same  way.     This  paper  itself  has  never  been  found  ;  Mt  is 

'  Unless  it  was  identical  with  or  developed  into  the  polemic  against  the  Jews 

c  2 


20  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

supposed,  however,  to  have  contained  some  foreshadowing  of 
the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  It  is  said  that  the  chiefs 
of  the  synagogue  were  not  content  with  inflicting  their  utmost 
ecclesiastical  penalty.  They  represented  to  the  civil  authori- 
ties that  Spinoza  was  a  dangerous  person  ;  their  request  was 
backed  by  the  Reformed  clergy,  and  a  sentence  of  banishment 
for  a  short  time  was  pronounced  against  Spinoza,  who  must 
have  already  left  the  city.  But  sentences  of  this  kind  against 
men  who  have  forestalled  them  by  absence  are  common 
enough  in  history.  The  incident  does  not  rest  on  good  autho- 
rity,' but  the  fact  that  similar  proceedings  had  been  taken  in 
the  case  of  Da  Costa  renders  it  not  improbable  in  itself. 
From  this  time  forth,  in  any  case,  we  have  to  think  of  Spinoza 
as  removed  from  Amsterdam  and  the  associations  of  his 
youth.  He  marked  the  severance  himself  by  disusing  his 
Hebrew  name  Baruch,  and  substituting  for  it  the  Latin  equi- 
valent Benedict.  Only  once  more  in  his  lifetime  do  we  hear 
anything  of  dealings  with  his  family.  Spinoza  became  en- 
titled upon  the  death  of  his  father  to  share  the  inheritance 
with  his  two  sisters.  The  sisters  disputed  his  title,  presum- 
ably under  the  belief  that  an  excommunicated  heretic  would 
have  no  part  in  the  estate  of  a  faithful  Israelite.  Spinoza  has 
left  on  record  his  opinion  that  in  a  state  where  just  laws  are 
in  force  it  is  not  only  the  right  of  every  citizen,  but  his  duty 
towards  the  common  weal,  to  resist  injustice  to  himself,  lest 
peradventure  evil  men  should  find  profit  in  their  evil-doing. 
In  his  own  case,  then,  he  acted  on  this  principle  :  the  civil 
law  was  just,  whether  on  the  high  ground  of  indifference  to 


mentioned  by  Rieuwertz,  the  publisher  of  the  Opera  Posthuvia,  to  the  German 
traveller  StoUe  as  existing  in  MS.  and  having  been  in  his  possession.  See 
Ginsberg's  edition  of  the  Ethics,  p.  20. 

'  It  is  in  Lucas,  with  confusion  of  time  and  circumstance,  as  usual.  Colerus 
knows  nothing  of  it,  and  Spinoza's  tone  of  admiration  and  deference  for  the  civil 
powers  of  his  countiy  (in  the  Tradatiis  TJieologico-Polit'uus)  is  likewise  against 
it.  The  precedent  of  Da  Costa  turns  the  scale  in  favour  of  giving  it  a  place  in 
the  text. 


I 


/  THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  21' 

theological  strife,  or,  as  is  more  likely,  because  Judaism  was 
only  a  tolerated  religion  ;  and  Spinoza's  claim  to  share  with 
his  sisters  was  made  good.  But,  having  established  his  rights, 
he  did  not  choose  to  take  any  material  advantage  by  them. 
When  the  partition  came  to  be  efifected  he  gave  up  to  his 
sisters  everything  but  one  bed  :  '  qui  etait  en  verite  fort  bon,' 
says  Colerus  in  the  French  version. 

Spinoza  was  now  dependent  on  his  own  work  for  a  liveli- 
hood.    In    compliance    with  the    Rabbinical    precept  which 
commands  every  man  to  learn  some  handicraft,  and  guided 
by  his  philosophical  and  scientific  temper,  he  had  acquired 
the  art  of  making  and  polishing  lenses  for  optical  instruments. 
Perhaps  a  desire  to  imitate  the  example  of  Descartes,  who 
had   likewise  made   himself  a    practical  optician,  may  have 
entered  into  Spinoza's  motives.     At  this  time  his  admiration 
of  Descartes  was  probably  at  its  height.     The   art  enabled 
him  to  earn  an  income,  slender  indeed,  but  sufficient  for  his 
limited  wants,  and  a  reputation  for  skill  and  knowledge  of 
optics  which  preceded  his  fame  as  a  philosopher.     The  lenses 
made  by  him  were  sought  after,  and  those  left  undisposed  of 
at  his  death  fetched  a  high  price.     It  was  as  an  optician, 
moreover,  that  he  made -the  acquaintance  of  Huygens  and 
Leibnitz.    Jn  1671    Leibnitz  wrote  to  consult   him  on  certain 
optical  questions,  and  his  letter  addresses  Spinoza  as  a  critic 
of  recognized  authority.     It  was  believed  by  Spinoza's  friends 
that  but  for  his  early  death  he  would  have  made  some  con- 
siderable   contribution    to    the   science ;  as  it   was,  the  only 
work  of  that  kind  which  he  completed  was  a  small  treatise  on 
the  Rainbow,  long  supposed  to  have  been  lost.     It  was  in 
truth   published  at  the  Hague  in  1687,  and  has  been  found 
and  reprinted  in  our  own  time  by  Dr.  Van  Vloten.'     Wc  are 
also  told  that  Spinoza   had   formed    the  plan    of  writing    a 
concise  treatise  on    Algebra   ('  breviori   et  magis  intelligibili 
methodo '),  and  other  unspecified  works. 

'  The  original  copy,  believed  to  be  unique,  is  in  the  Royal  Library  at  the  Hague. 


22  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

It  appears  that  Spinoza  stayed  with  his  Remonstrant  friend 
till  the  end  of  1660  or  beginning  of  1661,  when  they  removed 
together  tothevillageof  Rijnsburg,  near  Leyden,then  the  head- 
quarters of  the  sect.  The  house  where  they  lived  is  still  stand- 
ing, and  the  road  bears  to  this  day  the  name  of  '  Spinoza  Lane.' 
The  Remonstrants  were  by  this  time  practically  tolerated, 
but  had  no  regular  clergy  or  public  ministrations.  There 
could  therefore  be  no  outward  evidence  that  a  person  living 
among  them,  and  not  being  a  member  of  any  other  religious 
community,  was  not  one  oF  themselves.  Hence  the  report 
that  Spinoza  had  become  a  Christian  would  very  naturally 
arise.  It  gained  currency  enough  to  be  thought  by  Colerus 
worth  an  express  contradiction. 

The    meagre    information  given   by   Colerus  and    others 

of  the  philosopher's  movements  and  occupations  in  after  years 

is  partly  filled  in  by  his  letters,  of  which  we  possess  only  the 

selection    made,  unhappily  with  a  far  too  sparing  hand,  by 

the  editors  of  his  posthumous  works,  and  a  few  more  which 

have  been  discovered  in  the  orphan  asylum  at  Amsterdam 

formerly  belonging  to  the  Collegiants.    Spinoza  paid  frequent 

visits  to  the  Hague,  where  he  became  well  known  in    the 

society  of  men  of  letters  ;  and  it  is  clear  that  as  time  went 

on  he  found   more  and    more  content    in  his  entertainment 

there,  for   in    1664  he  moved  again   to  Voorburg,  which  is 

a  suburb  of  the  Hague,  and  in    1670  to  the  Hague   itself, 

where  he  spent  the  rest  of  his  life. 

In  1663  we  find  that  Spinoza  had  already  sketched  out 
some  of  the  leading  ideas  of  his  metaphysical  system,  sub- 
stantially in  the  same  form  in  which  they  eventually  appeared 
in  the  '  Opera  Posthuma,'  and  had  entrusted  his  papers  to  a 
number  of  his  younger  friends  at  Amsterdam.  They  had 
formed  a  sort  of  philosophical  club,'  at  whose  meetings  the 

'  Perhaps  a  section  or  ofTshoot  of  the  society  Nil  volcntibiis  ardititm  (it  was  and 
is  the  practice  in  Holland  for  the  motto  of  a  society  to  be  used  as  the  name  of  the 
society  itself),  of  which  Dr.  L.  Meyer  is  known  to  have  been  an  active  member. 
(Van  Vlutcn,  Bcned.  de  Spinoza,  p.  29.) 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  2j 

members  took  it  in  turns  to  read  out  and  comment  on 
Spinoza's  manuscript.  If  after  discussion  any  point  re- 
mained obscure,  a  note  was  made  of  the  difficulty,  and  one  of 
the  company  would  write  to  Spinoza  for  explanation.  Such 
a  letter  is  extant,  written  by  Simon  de  Vries,  a  young  student 
of  medicine,  and  of  much  promise,  who  had  conceived  for 
Spinoza  an  intellectual  attachment  which  grew  into  a  warm 
friendship.  He  would  willingly  have  shown  his  gratitude  to 
his  master  by  substantial  benefactions ;  we  are  told  of  a  gift 
of  2000  florins  offered  by  him  to  Spinoza  and  declined, 

Spinoza's  life,  as  we  shall  see,  was  not  a  robust  one  ;  but 
that  of  his  young  disciple  seems  to  have  been  yet  frailer,  for 
he  died  in  Spinoza's  lifetime,  and  not  so  unexpectedly  but 
that  he  had  time  to  form  the  design  of  making  Spinoza  his 
heir,  and  to  be  dissuaded  from  it  by  his  friend's  own  entreaties. 
De  Vries  had  a  brother  living,  and  Spinoza  pressed  upon  him 
the  duty  of  thinking  first  of  his  own  kindred.  The  master 
prevailed  with  the  disciple  against  his  own  interest,  and  the 
bulk  of  the  estate  was  left  by  De  Vries  to  his  brother,  charged 
however  with  a  sufficient  annuity  for  Spinoza's  maintenance. 
Even  this  was  accepted  only  in  part.  The  heir  offered  to  fix 
the  amount  at  500  florins  ;  but  Spinoza  pretended  that  it  was 
too  much,  and  refused  to  take  more  than  300.  De  Vries's 
letter  to  Spinoza  shows  all  the  generous  enthusiasm  of  a 
learner  in  presence  of  a  beloved  teacher. 

*  I  have  long  desired,'  he  says,  '  an  occasion  to  be  with  you,  but 
weather  and  the  hard  winter  have  not  allowed  me.  Sometimes  I 
complain  of  my  fate  in  being  removed  from  you  by  a  distance  that 
keeps  us  so  much  apart.  Happy,  most  happy,  is  that  companion  who 
dwells  with  you  under  the  same  roof,  and  who  can  at  all  times,  dining, 
supping,  or  walking,  hold  discourse  with  you  of  the  most  excellent 
matters.  But  though  we  are  so  widely  separated  in  the  body,  yet  you 
have  constantly  been  present  to  my  mind,  especially  when  I  apply 
myself  to  your  writings.' 

Spinoza's  answer  approves  the  plan  of  the  society,  and 


24  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

gives  the  desired  explanations.     To  De  Vries's  complaint  of 
their  long  separation  he  replies  as  follows  : — 

'  Your  long  continued  absence  has  been  no  less  disagreeable  to 
me  than  to  you  ;  but  meanwhile  I  am  glad  that  my  exercises  (liictibra- 
tiioiculae)  are  of  use  to  you  and  our  friends.  For  thus  I  speak  with 
you  while  we  are  away  from  one  another.  As  to  my  fellow-lodger, 
you  need  not  envy  him.  There  is  no  one  I  like  less,  or  with  whom  I 
have  been  more  cautious  ;  so  that  I  must  warn  you  and  all  our 
friends  not  to  communicate  my  opinions  to  him  till  he  has  come  to 
riper  years.  He  is  still  too  childish  and  inconstant,  and  cares  for 
novelty  more  than  truth.  Yet  I  hope  he  will  amend  these  youthful 
failings  some  years  hence  ;  indeed  I  am  nearly  sure  of  it,  so  far  as  I 
can  judge  from  his  disposition  ;  and  so  his  general  character  moves 
me  to  be  friendly  with  him.' 

It  appears  that  Spinoza's  expectations  of  this  young  man 
were  too  sanguine.  He  is  identified  by  plausible  conjecture 
with  one  Albert  Burgh,  who  many  years  afterwards  was  re- 
ceived into  the  Church  of  Rome,  and  on  that  occasion 
favoured  Spinoza  with  an  extraordinary  letter,  of  which  a 
specimen  will  come  before  us  hereafter. 

A  solitary  letter  of  1665  containing  some  personal  details 
has  been  lately  discovered.'  An  allusion  to  the  fleet  then 
fitting  out  against  England,  and  the  mention  of  a  journey  of 
Spinoza's  to  Amsterdam,  of  which  we  have  other  indications, 
fix  the  date  towards  the  end  of  May,  or  in  the  first  days  of 
June.  The  person  addressed  is  supposed  to  be  the  '  J.  B.,' 
to  whom  a  letter  of  the  following  year  (Ep.  42)  was  written, 
and  who  is  identified  with  the  Dr.  J.  Bresser  mentioned  else- 
where in  Spinoza's  correspondence.  Spinoza  complains  of 
having  missed  him  both  when  he  went  to  Amsterdam  and 
when  he  came  back  to  Voorburg.  He  then  begs  his  friend 
to  be  diligent  in  philosophy  while  he  is  young  and  has  time, 
and   not  to  be  afraid  of  writing  to  him  freely. 

'  I  have  before  now  suspected,  and  I  am   pretty  sure,  that  you 
'  Ep  42a.  Van  Vloteii,  Suppl.  p.  303. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  25 

have  some  unreasonable  distrust  of  your  own  parts,  and  fear  to  ask 
or  propound  something  unworthy  of  a  scholar.  It  is  not  fit  for  me 
to  praise  your  talents  to  your  face ;  but  if  you  fear  my  showing  your 
letters  to  others  who  may  ridicule  you,  I  give  you  my  promise  on 
this  point  that  I  will  scrupulously  keep  them,  and  will  communicate 
them  to  no  mortal,  unless  with  your  leave.  On  these  terms  you  may 
begin  your  correspondence  with  me,  unless  indeed  you  doubt  my 
good  faith,  which  I  do  not  suppose  possible.  I  trust  to  hear  your 
opinion  of  the  matter  by  your  first  letter,  and  to  have  with  it  some  of 
the  conserve  of  red  roses,  as  you  promised,  though  I  am  now  much 
better.  After  I  left  this  [for  Amsterdam]  I  once  let  myself  blood, 
yet  the  fever  did  not  cease  (though  I  was  somewhat  brisker  even 
before  the  blood-letting,  I  think  by  the  change  of  air),  but  I  was 
twice  or  thrice  troubled  with  a  tertian  ;  but  by  dint  of  good  diet  at 
last  1  drove  it  out  and  sent  it  packing ;  where  it  has  gone  I  know 
not,  but  I  am  taking  care  that  it  shall  not  come  back.' 

He  then  proinises  to  send  '  the  third  part  of  my  philo- 
soph}','  or  a  considerable  part  of  it,  as  far  as  the  8oth  proposi- 
tion or  thereabouts.  As  the  third  part  of  the  '  Ethics,'  as  it 
now  stands,  contains  nothing  like  that  number,  the  third  and 
fourth  parts  must  in  the  first  draft  have  formed  but  one. 
He  ends  by  asking  for  news  of  the  fleet. 

This  is  the  only  letter  preserved  to  us  in  which  Spinoza 
says  anything  about  himself  as  distinct  from  his  works,  and  it 
is  preserved  only  by  chance  :  the  editors  of  the  '  Opera  Post- 
huma,'  adhering  rigidly  to  the  principle  of  selecting  only  what 
illustrated  the  philosophy,  had  put  it  aside  as  'of  no  value.'  ' 
Ten  years  later  we  hear  of  Dr.  Bresser  as  returned  to  Amster- 
dam from  a  journey  to  Cleves,  and  having  brought  a  cask  of 
beer  as  a  present  for  Spinoza.^ 

Another  constant  friend  of  Spinoza's  was  Henry  Olden- 
burg, well  known  in  the  .scientific  history  of  England  as  the 
first  secretary  of  the  Royal  Society  and  the  intimate  friend  of 
Robert  Boyle.  He  had  settled  in  this  country,  where  he  spent 
the  best   part  of  his   life,  in    1653';  and   in  the  course  of  a 

*  Adscripseiunt  enim  :   'is  van  geender  w^iarde. '     (Van  Vloten,  /.  c.) 

-  Ep.  65a,  Supp.  p.  316. 


26  SPINOZA:    HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

journey  on  the  Continent  he  visited  Spinoza  at  Rijnsburg  and 
formed  an  acquaintance  with  him,  which,  though  opportunities 
of  meeting  were  few,  was  assiduously  kept  up  by  correspond- 
ence. Oldenburg  had,  within  discreet  limits,  a  lively  interest 
in  philosophy,  and  in  the  earlier  years  of  his  intercourse  with 
Spinoza  was  always  pressing  him  not  to  keep  back  his  know- 
ledge from  the  world.  In  the  same  letter  in  which  he  informs 
Spinoza  of  the  incorporation  of  the  Royal  Society,  Oldenburg 
thus  exhorts  him  to  boldness  : — 

'  I  would  by  all  means  advise  you  not  to  begrudge  to  men  of 
letters  the  ripe  fruits  of  your  learning  in  philosophy  and  theology,  but 
let  them  go  forth  into  the  world,  whatever  grumblings  may  proceed 
from  petty  theologians.  Your  commonwealth  is  most  free,  and 
therein  the  philosopher  should  work  most  freely.  Your  own  prudence 
will  counsel  you  to  publish  your  thoughts  and  opinions  with  as  little 
ostentation  as  may  be ;  I  would  have  you,  for  the  rest,  commit  the 
issue  to  fortune.  Come,  then,  my  friend,  cast  out  all  fear  of  stirring 
up  against  you  the  pigmies  of  our  time  ;  too  long  have  we  made 
sacrifices  to  their  ignorance  and  trifling  scruples  ;  let  us  spread  our 
sails  to  the  wind  of  true  knowledge,  and  search  out  the  secrets  of 
nature  more  thoroughly  than  has  yet  been  done.  In  your  country 
it  will  be  safe,  I  should  think,  to  print  your  reflections  ;  nor  is  any 
offence  from  them  to  be  feared  among  men  of  learning.  If  such 
are  your  patrons  and  promoters — and  such,  I  answer  for  it,  you  will 
find — why  should  you  fear  the  detraction  of  the  ignorant  ? ' ' 

Writing  some  little  time  afterwards,  in  the  spring  of  1663, 
Oldenburg  presses  Spinoza  yet  more  urgently  to  complete  his 
work  then  in  hand. 

*  Permit  me  to  ask  you,'  he  says,  '  whether  you  have  finished  that 
important  essay  in  which  you  treat  of  the  origin  of  things  and  their 
dependence  from  their  first  cause,  as  well  as  of  the  amendment  of  our 
understanding  ?  Surely,  my  excellent  friend,  I  believe  that  nothing 
can  be  published  more  pleasant  or  acceptable  to  men  of  learning  and 
discernment  than  such  a  treatise  as  yours.  This  is  what  a  man  of 
your  wit  and  temper  should  regard,  more  than  what  pleases  theo- 
logians of  the  present  age  and  fashion,  for  by  them  truth  is  less 

'  Ep.  7. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  '  27 

regarded  than  their  own  advantage.  I  adjure  you,  therefore,  by  the 
bond  of  our  friendship,  by  every  duty  of  multiplying  and  spreading 
abroad  the  truth,  not  to  withhold  from  us  your  writings  on  those 
subjects.  But  if  there  is  any  reason  more  grave  than  I  perceive 
which  hinders  you  from  setting  forth  the  work,  I  heartily  beseech 
you  to  be  at  the  pains  to  give  me  a  summary  of  it  by  letter  ;  and 
by  this  service  you  shall  know  that  you  have  earned  a  friend's 
gratitude.' ' 

In  the  following  letters  these  requests  and  exhortations 
are  repeated  in  even  stronger  terms.  We  collect  that  Olden- 
burg had  some  knowledge,  though  it  was  by  no  means  exact, 
of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  of  the  treatise  '  De 
Intellectus  Emendatione,'  which  was  never  finished,  and  has 
come  down  to  us  as  a  fragment,  and  perhaps  of  an  early  draft 
of  the  '  Ethics.'  Oldenburg's  language  seems  to  mix  up  the 
different  works,  and  his  later  conduct  still  more  plainly  shows 
that  he  did  not  at  this  time  know  much  of  their  contents. 

He  was  abundantly  valiant  in  counsel  before  he  had 
measured  the  risk  ;  but  after  the  publication  of  the  '  Tractatus 
Theologico-Politicus'  we  find  that  his  valour  has  all  evaporated. 
In  1675,  when  Spinoza  thought  of  publishing  the  '  Ethics,' 
Oldenburg's  talk  was  no  longer  of  spreading  all  sail  and 
defying  the  malice  of  theologians.  Now  he  is  all  for  caution 
and  conformity  ;  he  again  invokes  friendship,  but  this  time  to 
warn  Spinoza  against  giving  any  sort  of  ground  for  attacks 
upon  religion  and  virtue.  Not  that  he  refuses  to  take  some 
copies  of  the  book  ;  they  may  be  consigned  to  a  Dutch  friend 
in  London  for  him,  and  he  can  doubtless  find  purchasers  for 
them  ;  but  he  would  rather  not  have  it  talked  about.  And 
when  he  learnt  from  Spinoza  that  the  publication  was 
indefinitely  put  off,  his  expression  of  regret  was,  to  say  the 
least,  but  lukewarm.^ 

In  the  earlier  days  of  which  we  are  now  speaking  Olden- 
burg was  not   unaided   in  his  encouragement   to    Spinoza's 

1  Ep.  8.  -  Epp.  18-20. 


28  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

philosophical  work.  Boyle's  name  is  joined  once  and  again  in 
his  messages  of  greeting  and  exhortation,  and  considerable 
parts  of  these  letters  are  taken  up  with  communications  on 
questions  of  chemistry  and  pneumatics,  conveyed  through 
Oldenburg,  which  amount  in  effect  to  a  scientific  correspond- 
ence between  Spinoza  and  Boyle.  They  obviously  knew  and 
esteemed  one  another's  work  ;  but  there  is  no  trace  of  any 
more  direct  intercourse. 

The  miseries  of  the  great  plague  and  of  the  war  between 
England  and  Holland  are  brought  before  us  by  a  letter  of 
Oldenburg's  in  the  autumn  of  1665.  He  has  no  news  yet  of 
a  book  about  which  Spinoza  had  asked  him,  '  because  the 
plague  forbids  almost  all  traffic  ;  besides  which,  this  cruel  war 
brings  in  its  train  a  very  Iliad  of  mischiefs,  and  is  like  to  leave 
but  little  civility  in  the  world.'  The  public  meetings  of  the 
Royal  Society,  he  adds,  are  suspended  by  the  danger  of  the 
times  ;  but  the  individual  fellows  are  not  unmindful  of  their 
quality,  and  pursue  their  experiments  in  private.  Indeed 
meetings  were  shortly  afterwards  held  at  Oxford,  whither 
several  of  the  members  had  followed  the  Court.  •  But  the  war 
did  not,  for  some  time  at  least,  interrupt  the  correspondence, 
nor  abate  Oldenburg's  curiosity  for  information. 

In  December  1665  he  writes  of  a  wide-spread  report  that 
the  dispersed  nation  of  Israel  was  about  to  return  to  its  own 
country.  The  news  not  having  been  confirmed  from  Con- 
stantinople, Oldenburg  refuses  credit  to  it,  but  would  like  to 
know  how  it  has  been  received  in  the  Jewish  society  of 
Amsterdam.  The  allusion  is  to  the  stir  produced  throughout 
the  Jewish  world  by  the  impostor  Sabbatai  Zevi,  of  Smyrna, 
who  proclaimed  himself  as  the  Messiah  or  something  more, 
and  obtained  a  large  following  not  only  in  the  Levant  but  in 
all  the  synagogues  of  Europe.  In  London  the  believers  in 
his  mission  were  testifying  to  their  faith  by  laying  heavy 
odds  that  Sabbatai  Zevi  would   be  the  crowned  and  anointed 

'  Epp.  13a,  14. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  29 

king  of  Jerusalem  within  two  years.'  But  within  an  even 
shorter  time,  so  far  from  being  crowned  at  Jerusalem,  he  was 
a  prisoner  at  Constantinople,  and  completed  the  discomfiture 
of  those  who  had  committed  themselves  to  him  by  turning 
Mahometan  :  a  step  which,  decisive  as  it  seemed  against  his 
pretensions,  was  ineffectual  to  sober  a  certain  number  of 
enthusiasts.  The  delusion  survived  in  various  forms  for  at 
least  two  or  three  years  longer.^  One  would  give  something 
to  know  what  were  Spinoza's  reflections  on  seeing  the  ortho- 
dox elders  who  had  excommunicated  him  (for  Isaac  Aboab 
was  carried  away  with  the  rest)  fall  an  easy  prey  to  a  new 
heresy  of  the  most  gross  and  vulgar  kind.  But  his  answer  to 
Oldenburg's  inquiry  is  unluckily  not  preserved  :  we  know  not, 
indeed,  if  any  answer  were  sent,  for  at  this  point  there  ensues  a 
break  of  ten  years  in  the  correspondence  of  the  two  friends. 

In  1663  Spinoza  published  the  only  work  to  which  he 
ever  set  his  name  ;  the  origin  of  it  is  described  by  himself  in 
one  of  his  letters  to  Oldenburg.  He  had  prepared  a  summary 
of  the  second  part  of  Descartes'  '  Principles  of  Philosophy ' 
for  the  use  of  a  pupil  whom  he  did  not  choose  to  make  fully 
acquainted  with  his  own  opinions,  probably  the  young  man 
of  whom  we  have  already  heard.  Certain  of  Spinoza's  friends 
became  curious  about  this  manual,  and  desired  him  to  treat 
the  first  part  of  Descartes'  work  also  in  the  same  manner. 
This  was  done  within  a  fortnight,  and  Spinoza  was  then 
urged  to  publish  the  book,  which  he  readily  agreed  to  do 
upon  condition  that  one  of  his  friends  would  revise  the 
language,  and  write  a  preface  explaining  that  the  author  did 
not  agree  with  all  the  Cartesian  doctrine  set  forth  by  him  in 
the  text. 

'  Gralz,  X.  226,  229. 

2  '  And  yet  most  of  them  affirm  that  Sabatai  is  not  turn'd  Turk,  but  his 
Shadow  only  remains  on  Earth,  and  walks  with  a  white  Head,  and  in  the  habit  of 
a  Mahometan  :  But  that  his  natural  Body  and  Soul  are  taken  into  Heaven, 
there  to  reside  until  the  time  appointed  for  the  accomplishment  of  these  Wonders.' 
— '  The  Counterfeit  Messiah  of  the  Jews  at  Smyrna,  1666'  (in  Two  Journeys  to 
Jerusalem,  &c.,  collected  by  R.  Burton,  London,  1738). 


30  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

This  task  was  undertaken  by  Dr.  Meyer,  and  the  book 
appeared  at  Amsterdam  in  the  same  year  ;  in  the  following 
one  a  Dutch  translation  was  issued  by  the  same  publisher. 
The  contents  were  the  exposition  of  two  parts  of  Des- 
cartes' Principles,  a  fragment  of  a  third  part,  and  an 
appendix  of  '  Metaphysical  Reflections,'  professedly  written 
from  a  Cartesian  point  of  view',  but  often  giving  signifi- 
cant hints  of  the  author's  real  divergence  from  Descartes. 
Spinoza  took  little  trouble  in  the  matter  himself,  and 
attached  no  value  to  the  publication  except  as  a  means 
of  preparing  the  way  for  more  important  things.  '  On  this 
opportunity,'  he  writes  to  Oldenburg,  '  we  may  find  some 
persons,  holding  the  highest  places  in  my  country  ' — meaning 
the  De  Witts,  who  certainly  were  among  Spinoza's  visitors  at 
Rijnsburg  and  the  Hague — '  who  will  be  anxious  to  see  those 
other  writings  which  I  acknowledge  for  my  own,  and  will 
therefore  take  such  order  that  I  can  give  them  to  the  world 
without  danger  of  any  inconvenience.  If  it  so  happens,  I  doubt 
not  that  I  shall  soon  publish  something  ;  if  not,  I  will  rather 
hold  my  peace  than  thrust  my  opinions  upon  men  against  the 
will  of  my  country  and  make  enemies  of  them.'  The  design 
of  Spinoza  and  his  friends  was  but  partly  effected.  The  book 
on  Descartes  excited  considerable  attention  and  interest,  but 
the  untoward  course  of  public  events  in  succeeding  years  was 
unfavourable  to  a  liberal  policy,  and  deprived  Spinoza  of  the 
support  for  which  he  had  looked. 

We  may  here  make  a  note  in  passing  of  two  facts  which 
are  established  by  this  exposition  of  Descartes,  and  which  have 
been  often  overlooked.  One  is  that  if  Spinoza  had  ever  been 
a  disciple  of  Descartes,  he  had  completely  ceased  to  be  so  by 
the  time  when  he  was  giving  lessons  in  philosophy  to  Albert 
Burgh.  The  other  is  that  he  did  not  suppose  the  geometrical 
form  of  statement  and  argument  to  be  an  infallible  method  of 
arriving  at  philosophical  truth  ;  for  in  this  work  he  made  use 
of  it  to  set  forth  opinions  with  which  he  himself  did  not  agree, 


THE  LIFE   OR  SPINOZA.  31 

and  proofs  with  which  he  was  not  satisfied.  We  do  not  know 
to  what  extent  Spinoza's  manual  was  accepted  or  taken 
into  use  by  Cartesians,  but  its  accuracy  as  an  exposition  of 
Descartes  is  beyond  question.  One  of  the  many  perverse 
criticisms  made  on  Spinoza  by  modern  writers  is  that  he  did 
not  understand  the  fundamental  proposition  cogito  ergo  sum} 
In  fact  he  gives  precisely  the  same  explanation  of  it  that  is 
given  by  Descartes  himself  in  the  Meditations. 

The  next  notable  event  in  Spinoza's  life  is  the  publica-* 
tion  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  : '  the  full  title,  as 
Englished  by  an  early  translator  (1689),  runs  thus  : — 

'A  treatise  partly  theological  and  partly  political,  con- 
taining some  few  discourses  to  prove  that  the  liberty  of  phi- 
losophizing (that  is,  making  use  of  natural  reason)  may  be 
allowed  without  any  prejudice  to  piety,  or  to  the  peace  of 
any  commonwealth  ;  and  that  the  loss  of  public  peace  and 
religion  itself  must  necessarily  follow,  where  such  a  liberty 
of  reasoning  is  taken  away.' 

The  scope  of  the  book  is  political  and  practical,  not 
speculative.  The  final  thesis  to  which  all  its  apparatus  of 
criticism  leads  up  is  that  '  in  a  free  commonwealth  it  should 
be  lawful  for  every  man  to  think  what  he  will  and  speak  what 
he  thinks : '  a  proposition  which,  with  due  reservations  in 
behalf  of  decency  and  civil  order — and  the  reservations  were 
in  no  wise  neglected  by  Spinoza — has  now  become  common 
learning  for  the  greater  part  of  the  civilized  world.  It  looks 
to  our  modern  eyes  infinitely  less  bold  than  the  arguments 
by  which  Spinoza  maintained  it.  In  order  to  gain  his  desired 
foundation  for  the  freedom  of  speculative  opinion,  he  plunges 
into  an  investigation  of  the  nature  of  prophecy,  the  principles 
of  Scriptural  interpretation,  and  the  true  provinces  of  theology 
and  philosophy,  anticipating  with  wonderful  grasp  and  insight 
almost  every  principle,  and   not   a  few  of  the  results,  of  the 

'  Foucher  de  Careil,  Leibniz,  Descartes,  et  Spinoza,  Paris,  1862,  p.  75  :  '  il  n'a 
jamais  compris  le  cogito  ergo  sum.'' 


32  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

school  of  historical  criticism  which  has  arisen  within  the  last 
two  or  three  generations  ;  a  school  which,  through  Lessing 
and  his  circle,  is  connected  by  direct  descent  with  Spinoza. 
Taking   the    whole   contents    of    the    treatise    together,    we 
cannot  be  surprised  that  even  in  the  United  Provinces,  then 
the  freest  country  in  the  world,  it  was  thought  needful  to 
issue  it  without   the  name   of  the  author  and  with   that  of 
a  fictitious  printer  at  Hamburg.      The  tone    and    form    are 
conciliatory,  but  with  the  kind    of  high-handed   conciliation 
that  exasperates.     Much  hard  hitting  will  be  taken  without 
complaint  in  downright  argument ;  but  few  men  can  endure 
to  be  confuted  from  their  own  premisses  by  an  adversary  who 
never  fully  shows  his  hand.     It  is  more  tolerable  for  a  dog- 
matist to  be  confronted  with  novelties  in  speculative  opinion 
than  to  be  told  that  speculative  opinions  are  in  themselves 
indifferent  ;  and  the  truth  that  conduct  does  not  depend  on 
speculation,  though  exemplified  abundantly  by  all  generations 
of  men,  is  still  unfamiliar  and  unwelcome  to  most  of  us.     It 
is  just  to  this  unwelcome  truth  that   Spinoza  bears  a  testi- 
mony of  unsurpassed  power  in  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico- 
Politicus  ; '  but  if  anything  more  were  needed  to  explain  the 
storm  of  polemic  that  burst  upon  him,  there  is  yet  more  to 
come.     We  have  said  that  Spinoza  does  not  omit  the  neces- 
sary reservations  in  favour  of  the  civil  power  ;  we  must  add 
that  he  makes  them  not  only  freely  but  amply,  so  amply  that 
he  has  been  charged  by  some  of  his  modern  censors  with 
going  about  to  deify  mere  brute  force.     He  appeals,  more- 
over, from   the    Churches  to   the   State,  as  representing  the 
worldly  common  sense  of  the  lay  mind.     He  looks  to  an 
enlightened  civil  magistrate  to  deliver  men  from  the  barren 
clamour  of  anathemas,  almost  as  an  Indian  heretic  vexed  by 
the  Brahmans  may  look  to  the  impartial  secular  arm  of  the 
British  Government.     *  This  is  the   conclusion  of  the  whole 
matter  for  him  ;  a  fervent  appeal  to  the  State  to  save  us  from 
the  untoward  generation  of  metaphysical  Article-^nakers  ; ' 


THE    LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  2,^ 

so  Mr.  Arnold  sums  it  up  in  his  admirable  essay.'  If  the 
English  translator  had  been  minded  to  give  the  book  a 
second  title,  after  the  manner  of  English  controversialists  of 
that  day,  he  might  fairly  have  called  it  '  Erastianism  not 
Unscriptural.'  Now  it  is  a  great  error  to  suppose  that  the 
metaphysical  Article-makers  are  stupid  or  undiscerning  people. 
Whatever  qualities  may  be  desirable  in  those  who  are  to 
believe  articles  after  they  are  made,  a  great  deal  of  energy 
and  acuteness  have  gone  to  the  making  of  them  ;  and  the 
faculties  thus  employed  are,  as  a  rule,  very  sufficient  to 
perceive  the  drift  of  any  new  ideas  that  may  imperil  their 
finished  handiwork.  In  1670  the  generation  of  Article-makers 
was  mighty  in  the  Netherlands,  and  still  pretty  fresh  from 
its  great  exercise  at  the  Synod  of  Dort.  It  was  fully  on 
the  alert,  and  lost  no  time  in  showing  itself  equal  to  the 
occasion.  And  the  occasion  was  no  common  one,  for  the 
attack  was  not  only  powerful,  but  vital.  If  there  is  anything 
that  ecclesiastical  dogmatists  of  all  parties  are  united  in 
hating  with  a  perfect  hatred,  it  is  the  Erastian  view  of  the 
relation  of  the  State  to  religious  differences. 

Spinoza  probably  never  disguised  from  himself  the  oppo- 
sition he  would  have  to  encounter.  In  1671  he  wrote  thus  to 
his  friend  Jarig  Jellis  : — 

'When  Professor  N.  N.  [Wittichius  ?]  ^  lately  saw  me,  he  told 
me,  among  other  things,  how  he  had  heard  of  my  Theologico- 
political  treatise  being  translated  into  Dutch,  and  that  a  person  whose 
name  he  did  not  know  was  on  the  point  of  printing  the  translatioa 
I  therefore  earnestly  entreat  you  to  inquire  diligently  into  the  matter, 
and  stop  the  printing  if  it  can  be  done.  This  request  is  not  from  me 
alone,  but  also  from  many  of  my  friends  and  acquaintance,  who 
would  be  sorry  to  see  the  book  prohibited,  as  it  certainly  will  be  if  it 
appears  in  Dutch.' 

It  seems  that   Spinoza's  wishes  were  attended  to,  for  no 

•  '  Spinoza  and  the  Bible,'  in  Essays  in  Criticism. 

*  .Van  Vloten,  Betted,  de  Spinoza,  p.  81,  note. 

D 


34  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Dutch  version  appeared  until  1693,'  some  years  after  an 
English  one  had  been  published  in  London.  But  the  Synods 
were  already  up  in  arms,  and  in  the  spring  of  1671  addressed 
a  solemn  complaint  to  the  States-General  concerning  the 
printing  and  publishing  of  divers  '  Socinian  and  blasphemous 
books,  to  wit,  the  books  called  "Bibliotheca  Patrum  Polonorum 
quos  unitarios  vocant,"  the  famous  book  of  Hobbes  called 
"  Leviathan,"  and  moreover  the  book  entitled  "  Philosophia 
Sacrae  Scripturae  interpres,"  ^  as  well  as  that  called  "  Tractatus 
Theologico-Politicus." '  In  1674  effect  was  given  to  this  by 
a  formal  prohibition  of  the  book,  which,  either  in  anticipation 
of  such  a  measure,  or  in  order  to  obtain  a  sale  in  Catholic 
countries,  had  already  been  issued  in  a  second  edition  with 
various  false  title-pages,  as  of  works  on  medicine  or  history,^ 
Rome  was  not  far  behind  the  Reformed  churches  in  dili- 
gence. The  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  '  was  ere  long  put 
on  the  Index,  and  it  still  holds  its  place  in  the  strangely  mixed 
company  of  that  catalogue  with  many  of  the  best  and  some 
of  the  worst  books  of  the  world.  But  the  celebrity  which  came 
to  Spinoza  by  reason  of  this  publication  was  not  altogether  of 
a  disagreeable  kind  even  in  official  quarters.  When  his  treatise 
had  been  some  three  years  before  the  world  he  received  an 
invitation  to  the  Chair  of  Philosophy  at  Heidelberg,  written 
by  Professor  Fabritius  at  the  command  of  the  Elector  Pala- 
tine Charles  Lewis,  and  coughed  in  the  most  honourable 
terms.  The  only  hint  of  a  restriction  was  in  the  following 
^sentence :  '  You  will  have  the  largest  freedom  of  speech  in 
philosophy,  which  the  prince  is  confident  that  you  will  not 
misuse  to  disturb  the  established  religion.'  Now  it  is  hardly 
possible  to  suppose  that  the  Elector  and  his  advisers  were 
unacquainted  with  the  'Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  ;'  and 
if  they   were   acquainted   with   its  general  purport,   one    is 

'  Bibliografic,  No.  17. 

-'  This  was  for  a  time  erroneously  attributed  to  Spinoza. 

s  Bibliografie,  Nos.  4-7.     See  Appendix  B  for  the  text  of  the  ordinance. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA,  35 

tempted  to  suspect  that  a  phrase  of  such  very  mild  caution 
may  have  been  inserted  only  as  a  matter  of  form  ;  especially 
when  we  remember  that  established  religion,  as  such,  is 
treated  by  Spinoza  with  great  respect  in  the  treatise  itself. 
The  test  seems  almost  framed  to  invite  evasion. 

But  even  the  semblance  of  evasion  was  repugnant  to 
Spinoza's  ideal  of  intellectual  truthfulness.  He  answered  the 
invitation  thus  : — 

'  Had  it  ever  been  my  desire  to  occupy  a  chair  in  any  faculty,  I 
could  have  wished  for  no  other  than  that  which  the  Most  Serene 
Elector  Palatine  offers  me  by  your  hands  ;  and  especially  on  account 
of  that  freedom  in  philosophy  which  the  prince  is  pleased  to  grant,  to 
say  nothing  of  the  desire  I  have  long  entertained  to  live  under  the 
rule  of  a  prince  whose  wisdom  is  the  admiration  of  all  men.  But 
since  I  have  never  been  minded  to  give  public  lectures,  I  cannot 
persuade  myself  to  accept  even  this  splendid  opportunity,  though  I 
have  given  long  consideration  to  it.  For  I  reflect,  in  the  first  place, 
that  I  must  give  up  philosophical  research  if  I  am  to  find  time  for 
teaching  a  class.  I  reflect,  moreover,  that  I  cannot  tell  within  what 
bounds  I  ought  to  confine  that  philosophical  freedom  you  mention 
in  order  to  escape  any  charge  of  attempting  to  disturb  the  established 
religion.  Religious  dissensions  arise  not  so  much  from  the  ardour  of 
men's  zeal  for  religion  itself  as  from  their  various  dispositions  and 
love  of  contradiction,  which  leads  them  into  a  habit  of  decrying  and 
condemning  everything,  however  justly  it  be  said.  Of  this  I  have 
already  had  experience  in  my  private  and  solitar}'  life  ;  much  more, 
then,  should  I  have  to  fear  it  after  mounting  to  this  honourable  con- 
dition. You  see,  therefore,  that  I  am  not  holding  back  in  the  hope 
of  some  better  post,  but  for  mere  love  of  quietness,  which  I  think  I 
can  in  some  measure  secure  if  I  abstain  from  lecturing  in  public. 
Wherefore  I  heartily  beseech  you  to  desire  the  Most  Serene  Elector 
that  I  may  be  allowed  to  consider  further  of  this  matter.'  ' 

The  call  to  Heidelberg  was  in  1673.  We  have  anticipated 
the  order  of  events  to  keep  the  philosophic  side  of  Spinoza's 
life  distinct  from  the  one  point  at  which  it  was  visibly  touched 
by  the  turmoil  of  public  affairs.    The  misfortunes  of  the  Nether- 

'  Ep.  54. 

D  2 


36  SPINOZA:   HIS   LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

lands  in  1672  are  the  property  of  general  history.  Then  took 
place  the  sudden  and  overwhelming  invasion  in  which  '  the 
kino-  of  France  came  down  to  Utrecht  like  a  land  flood  ; '  '  and 
this  war  of  insolent  aggression,  so  far  from  uniting  all  parties  in 
resistance  to  the  enemy,  bred  in  the  Commonwealth  a  passion 
of  panic  that  let  loose  the  worst  excesses  of  domestic  faction. 
The  brothers  De  Witt,  after  lives  spent  in  the  service  of  their 
country,  were  massacred  by  a  frantic  mob  at  the  Hague. 
Spinoza  had  been  the  friend  of  John  de  Witt ;  he,  had 
accepted  a  small  pension  from  him,  and  is  said  to  have  been 
consulted  by  him  in  affairs  of  State.  It  was  not  common 
with  Spinoza  to  be  visibly  disturbed  or  angry,  but  by  this 
event  he  was  moved  as  by  no  other  in  his  life.  So  much  was 
his  wonted  self-control  shaken  that  he  was  hardly  restrained 
from  expressing  his  indignation  in  public  at  the  risk  of  his 
life.^  He  was  shortly  afterwards,  as  it  fell  out,  to  be  exposed 
to  a  similar  risk,  and  for  a  not  dissimilar  cause.  While  the 
headquarters  of  the  French  army  were  at  Utrecht  the  Prince 
of  Conde,  then  in  command  of  it,  invited  Spinoza  to  visit  him. 
There  is  no  reason  to  suppose  any  other  motive  than  a  genuine 
desire  to  make  the  philosopher's  acquaintance,  still  less  to  ima- 
gine (as  one  or  two  writers  have  done)  a  secret  political  errand. 
Spinoza  proceeded  to  Utrecht  with  a  safe-conduct,  but  found 
that  Conde  had  been  in  the  meantime  called  away.  He  waited 
some  days,  but  Conde's  absence  was  prolonged,  and  he  finally 
returned  to  the  Hague  without  having  seen  him.  The  French 
officers  who  entertained  Spinoza  suggested  that  if  he  would 
dedicate  some  work  to  Louis  XIV.  he  might  probably  count 
upon  a  pension  ;  but  the  proposal  fell  upon  deaf  ears.    A  man 

*  Burnet,  i.  321. 

^  This  was  communicated  by  Spinoza  himself  to  Leibnitz.  '  J'ay  passe 
quelques  heures  apres  diner  avec  Spinoza  ;  il  me  dit  qu'il  avait  este  porte,  le  jour 
des  massacres  de  MM.  de  Witt,  de  sortir  la  nuit  et  d'afficher  quelque  part,  proche 
du  lieu,  un  papier  oil  il  y  aurait  iiltimi  barbarorum.  Mais  son  hote  luy  avait  ferme 
la  maison  pour  I'empecher  de  sortir,  car  il  se  serait  expose  aetre  dechire.'  MS. 
note  of  Leibnitz,  ap.  Foucher  de  Careil,  Leibniz,  Descartes,  et  Spinoza,  p.  74. 


THE  LIFE  OF  SPINOZA.  yj 

who  could  scarcely  be  prevailed  on  to  accept  favours  from  his 
friends  at  home  was  not  likely  to  sell  the  reputation  of 
patronizing  him  to  the  ruler  of  a  hostile  country.  But  at  the 
Hague,  men's  minds  being  still  in  a  ferment,  sinister  rumours 
about  Spinoza's  journey  had  got  abroad  ;  and  he  found  him- 
self on  his  return  the  object  of  the  most  alarming  and  most 
insidious  charge  that  can  fall  upon  a  citizen  in  time  of  war. 
The  landlord  feared  an  assault,  if  not  the  sack  of  the  house, 
from  the  populace  among  whom  these  reports  were  passing, 
and  who  might  at  any  moment  resolve  to  lay  violent  hands 
upon  Spinoza  as  a  French  spy. 

Spinoza,  however,  comforted  his  host  with  these  words  : — 
'Fear  nothing  on  my  account  ;  I  can  easily  justify  myself; 
there  are  people  enough,  and  of  chief  men  in  the  country  too, 
who  well  know  the  motives  of  my  journey.  But,  whatever 
comes  of  it,  so  soon  as  the  crowd  make  the  least  noise  at  your 
door,  I  will  go  out  and  make  straight  for  them,  though  they 
should  serve  me  as  they  have  done  the  unhappy  De  Witts.  I 
am  a  good  republican,  and  have  never  had  any  aim  but  the 
honour  and  welfare  of  the  State.' 

The  danger  passed  off;  but  Spinoza's  conduct  under  it  is 
none  the  less  worthy  of  admiration,  for  it  was  unquestionably  a 
very  serious  one.  Even  in  our  own  times,  notably  in  France 
during  the  war  of  1870,  many  innocent  persons  have  been  in 
imminent  peril,  or  have  actually  lost  their  lives,  on  far  slighter 
circumstances  of  supposed  evidence  than  appeared  in  this 
case.  The  incident  also  has  its  value  in  the  light  it  throws  on 
the  general  esteem  in  which  Spinoza  then  stood.  For  the  con- 
sciousness, not  merely  of  an  innocent  purpose,  but  of  a  cha- 
racter above  the  possibility  of  rational  suspicion,  was  necessary 
to  make  his  visit  to  the  French  headquarters  prudent  or 
justifiable  ;  and  the  authorities  of  his  own  country  would 
assuredly  never  have  consented  to  it  had  they  not  felt 
absolute  confidence  that  the  public  good  would  in  no  way 
suffer  by  it.     It  is  indeed  almost  surprising  that  Spinoza,  a 


38  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

known  friend  of  John  de  Witt,  was  in  the  existing  state  of 
affairs  allowed  to  go  to  the  French  camp  at  all. 

Meanwhile  Spinoza  had  been  working  at  the  Ethics,  and 
before  the  end  of  1674  manuscript  copies  of  the  finished  work 
were  in  the  hands  of  some  of  his  friends.'  About  the  end  of 
July  1675  he  made  an  excursion  to  Amsterdam  in  order  to 
arrange  for  the  publication  of  the  book.  What  befell  him  there 
is  best  told  in  the  words  of  his  own  letter  to  Oldenburg, 

*  While  I  was  busy  with  this,  the  report  was  spread  everywhere 
that  a  certain  book  of  mine  was  in  the  press,  wherein  I  endeavoured 
to  show  that  there  was  no  God  ;  and  this  report  found  credence  with 
many.  Whereupon  certain  theologians  (themselves  perhaps  the  authors 
of  it)  took  occasion  to  complain  of  me  to  the  prince  and  the  magis- 
trates ;  moreover  the  stupid  Cartesians,  being  supposed  to  side  with 
me  and  desiring  to  free  themselves  from  that  suspicion,  were  diligent 
without  ceasing  in  their  execration  of  my  doctrines  and  writings,  and 
are  as  diligent  still.  Having  knowledge  of  these  matters  from  trust- 
worthy persons,  who  likewise  told  me  that  the  theologians  were  laying 
plots  against  me  on  all  sides,  I  determined  to  put  off  the  publication 
until  I  could  see  the  issue  of  the  affair,  and  then  to  signify  my  designs 
to  you.  But  the  business  inclines,  as  it  seems,  to  the  worse  from  day 
to  day,  and  I  know  not  yet  what  I  shall  do.' 

The  result  was  that  nothing  more  was  done  in  Spinoza's 
lifetime.  He  had  shown  that  he  could  endure  much  in  silence 
rather  than  barter  a  jot  of  his  freedom,  but  he  did  not  choose 
to  be  vexed  with  the  petty  warfare  of  clerical  controversy; 
he  must  have  felt  the  assurance  that  his  work  would  live,  and 
that  a  few  years  sooner  or  later  in  the  date  of  its  appearance 
would  be  indifferent.  Can  he  have  surmised  that  the  few 
years  by  which  the  publication  was  postponed  would  be  a 
mere  fraction  in  comparison  with  the  time  during  which  his 
thoughts  were  in  the  world  but  not  perceived  by  it,  misunder- 
stood by  those  who  took  notice  of  them,  and  unheeded  by 
those  who  might  have  understood  }     Can  he  have  even  dreamt 

'  Epp.  63,  66. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  39 

of  the  splendour  with  which  his  work  was  to  shine  forth  to  a 
newer  world  after  the  period  of  eclipse,  giving  up  its  hidden 
treasures  of  light  and  vital  fire  to  inform  the  philosophy  and 
poetry  of  a  mighty  nation  ?  Such  fame  as  Spinoza's  is  the 
reward  only  of  those  who  are  above  fame  in  their  lives. 

Spinoza  had  now  but  little  more  of  life  before  him.     For 
many  years  he  had  suffered  from  consumption,  aggravated  per- 
haps by  his  work  of  glass-polishing.    On  Sunday,  February  21, 
1677,    the    end    came    unexpectedly,   and    almost   suddenly. 
Spinoza  had  indeed  sent  to    Amsterdam  for  his  friend  and 
physician  Lewis  Meyer  ;  but  on  the  Saturday  he  had  spent  the 
afternoon  in  talk  with  his  hosts  as  usual  ;  and  on  the  Sunday 
he  came  down  again  in  the  morning,  and  spoke  with  them 
before  they  went  to  hear  Dr.  Cordes,  Colerus's  predecessor  in 
the  Lutheran  church  at  the  Hague.     They  were  so  far  from 
any  immediate  apprehensions  that  they  went  out  again  in  the 
afternoon,  leaving  him  alone  with  Meyer.     When  they  came 
home  they  found,  to  their  surprise,  that  Spinoza  was  no  longer 
alive.     Dr.  Meyer,  the  only  person  who  was  with  him  at  the 
last,  returned   forthwith  to   Amsterdam.     He  is  charged  by 
Colerus  with  neglect  of  duty  and  rapacity  ;  or  rather,  in  plain 
terms,  with  making  booty  of  a  silver-handled  knife  and  the 
loose  money  in  the  room.     But  this  is  so  grossly  improbable 
that  we  can  only  disregard  it.     Colerus  may  have  not  been 
sorry  to  compensate  himself  for  the  admiration  his  native 
honesty  compelled  him  to  yield   to  Spinoza's  character  by 
giving  currency  to  a  piece  of  malignant  gossip  about  a  friend 
of  Spinoza's,  known  or  suspected  to  share  Spinoza's  opinions, 
and  who,  as  a  person  only  coming  incidentally  into  the  story, 
had  no  particular  claim  to  be  treated  with  justice.     Rut  credit 
must  be  given  to  Colerus,  on  the  other  hand,  for  his  downright 
contradiction    of    the  tales   concerning   Spinoza's   death-bed 
which  were  circulated,  it  would  seem,  by  persons  who  thought 
it  would  tend  to  edification  to  represent  Spinoza  as  the  blus- 
tering infidel  of  popular  orthodox  polemics,  who  is  invariably 


40  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

assailed  by  doubt  and  disquietude  in  his  last  moments,  and 
as  invariably  strives  to  disguise  them  with  feeble  bravado.' 
Colerus  very  honestly  says  that  the  people  of  the  house,  whom 
he  more  than  once  questioned,  knew  nothing  of  any  such 
matters,  and  did  not  believe  a  word  of  them. 

Spinoza  left  behind  him  but  a  scanty  estate  :  some  thirty 
or  forty  volumes,  a  few  engravings,  the  tools  of  his  trade, 
and  a  certain  number  of  finished  lenses  ;  which  last,  we  are 
told,  fetched  a  good  price  ;  besides  these  a  modest  list  of  per- 
sonal effects,  carefully  enumerated  by  Colerus,  and  in  all  so 
little  more  than  would  cover  debts  and  expenses  that  the  sur- 
viving sister  Rebekah,  who  at  first  was  disposed  to  assert  her 
rights,  concluded  that  the  inheritance  was  not  worth  having. 
Yet  Spinoza  had  one  precious  legacy  to  dispose  of — the  desk 
containing  his  letters  and  unpublished  work.  Van  der  Spijck 
had  been  charged  to  convey  this  after  Spinoza's  death  to  Jan 
Rieuwertz,  a  publisher  at  Amsterdam.  The  trust  was  faithfully 
executed,  and  the  *  Opera  Posthuma '  appeared  in  the  course 
of  the  same  year,  but  without  the  author's  full  name.  The 
editors'   preface  explains  that  this  was  by  his  own  request. 

'  The  writer's  name/  they  say,  '  is  expressed  on  the  title-page  and 
elsewhere  only  by  his  initials  ;  which  is  done  for  no  other  reason 
than  that,  shortly  before  his  death,  he  specially  desired  that  his  name 
should  not  be  prefixed  to  his  Ethics,  while  he  directed  the  printing  of 
them.  The  only  reason  for  this  prohibition  was,  as  we  think,  that  he 
chose  not  that  his  doctrine  should  be  called  after  his  name.  For  he 
says  in  the  Appendix  to  the  fourth  part  of  the  Ethics,  cap.  25,  that 
they  who  desire  to  aid  others  by  counsel  or  deed  to  the  common 
enjoyment  of  the  chief  good  shall  in  no  wise  endeavour  themselves 
that  a  doctrine  be  called  after  their  name.  Moreover  in  the  third 
part  of  the  Ethics,  in  the  nth  definition  of  the  Passions,  where  he 
explains  the  nature  of  ambition,  he  plainly  charges  with  vain -glory 
those  who  do  after  this  sort' 

In  the  following  year  the  States  of  Holland   and  West 

■  One  of  these  stories  is  circumstantially  repea,ted  by  Bayle,  Pensees  Diverses, 
§  1 8 1,  '  Vanite  de  Spinoza  a  I'heure  de  mort.' 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  41 

Friesland,  being  satisfied  that  the  book  entitled  '  B.  D.  S. 
Opera  Posthuma  '  '  labefactated  '  various  essential  articles  of 
the  faith  and  *  vilipended  the  authority  cf  miracles,'  expressed 

*  the  highest  indignation  '  at  the  disseminating  thereof,  declared 
it  profane,  atheistic,  and  blasphemous,  and  forbad  printing, 
selling,  and  dealing  in  it,  on  pain  of  their  high  displeasure.' 

The  framers  of  this  well-meant  enactment  earned  a  per- 
manent remembrance  for  their  work,  but  not  quite  as  they 
desired.     Instead  of  their  ordinance  extinguishing  Spinoza's 

*  Ethics,'  the  '  Ethics'  have  preserved  the  memory  of  the 
ordinance. 

It  remains  to  say  something  of  Spinoza's  manner  of  daily 
life  and  outward  habit ;  which  however,  as  we  know  them 
almost  entirely  through  Colerus's  account,  so  they  are  pre- 
sented by  Colerus  with  a  kind  of  simple  quaintness  more 
impressive  than  any  studied  description  can  be.  The 
effect  of  those  particulars  which  we  possess  is  to  show  us  a 
man  who  was  led  to  a  retired  life  by  choice  and  circum- 
stance, not  by  ostentation  ;  to  an  almost  incredible  frugality 
by  reasons  of  health  and  economy,  not  by  ascetic  pride  ;  who 
could  be  freespoken  and  of  good  will  towards  all  sorts  of  men, 
but  would  be  dependent  on  none.  His  living  and  diet  were 
of  the  simplest,  his  expenses  amounting  sometimes  only  to  a 
few  pence  for  the  whole  day.  But  he  kept  down  his  expenses 
in  this  manner  chiefly,  if  not  wholly,  in  order  to  keep  them 
within  his  means  ;  just  making  both  ends  meet,  as  he  would 
say  of  himself,  like  a  snake  with  its  tail  in  its  mouth.  And 
his  means  remained  slender  to  the  last  because  he  did  not 
choose  to  live  on  patronage,  and  the  studies  to  which  he 
devoted  the  best  of  his  mind  had  even  less  bread-winning  virtue 
then  than  they  have  now.  It  is  reported  that  Spinoza,  on  hear- 
ing that  a  man  who  owed  him  200  florins  had  become  bankrupt, 
said  with  a  smile,  '  I  must  retrench  my  allowance  to  make 

'  June    25,     1678.      Gioot   Placaet    Bock,    3de   deel,    p.    525  :    Bibliografic, 
No.  24. 


42  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

up  for  this  little  matter ;  at  this  price  one  buys  equanimity.' ' 
But  the  story  seems  doubtful. 

Again,  Spinoza  lived  in  a  retirement  which  at  times 
might  be  called  solitude  ;  when  absorbed  in  work  he  would 
hardly  leave  his  chamber  for  many  days  together ;  once  he 
did  not  leave  the  house  for  three  months.^  But  if  on  these 
occasions  he  chose  to  be  alone,  it  was  not  that  he  loved 
solitude  for  its  own  sake.  He  had  none  of  the  shallow  pride 
and  arrogance  which  fancies  that  the  way  to  show  superior 
knowledge  is  to  disdain  the  common  intercourse  of  mankind. 
There  was  no  touch  of  misanthropy  in  the  retirement  from  the 
world  which  he  imposed  upon  himself.  Besides  keeping  up 
a  not  inconsiderable  correspondence,  Spinoza  visited  and  was 
visited  by  not  a  few  men  of  letters  and  learning  ;  there  was 
a  time,  as  we  gather  from  his  own  statements,  when  their 
civilities  left  him  few  hours  to  call  his  own. 

Nor  did  he  limit  his  converse  to  scholars  :  he  knew  how 
to  win  the  esteem  and  affection  of  the  simple  folk  of  the 
household  where  he  dwelt,  an  esteem  which,  as  M.  Renan  has 
well  said,  is  in  truth  the  most  precious  of  all.  He  talked 
freely  and  familiarly  with  his  hosts  the  Van  der  Spijcks,  and 
would  counsel  their  children  to  good  behaviour  and  obedience. 
He  discussed  with  them  the  sermons  of  Dr.  Cordes,  the 
Lutheran  pastor  who  preceded  Spinoza's  biographer  Colerus 
in  the  charge  of  the  Lutheran  congregation  at  the  Hague, 
and  recommended  them  to  give  all  attention  to  the  discourses 
of  so  excellent  a  teacher.  Bold  as  he  was  in  speculative 
thought,  and  detached  in  his  own  person  from  all  sects  and 
doctrines,  Spinoza  was  no  furious  iconoclast  in  private  life. 

'  This  anecdote  is  only  in  Lucas,  and  as  given  by  him  has  a  slightly  theatrical 
air.  He  adds  a  sort  of  apologetic  explanation  :  '  Je  ne  rapporte  pas  cette  action 
comme  quelqiie  chose  d'eclatant,  mais  comma  il  n'y  a  rien  en  quoi  le  genie  paraisse 
davantage  qu'en  ces  sortes  de  petilcs  choses,  je  n'ai  pu  I'omettre  sans  scrupule.' 
I  cannot  but  suspect  that  the  turn  of  the  saying  at  least  is  borrowed  from  Epictctus 
{Man.  c.  12,  2),  t'lriAe^e  on  to  crovrov  TrajXeTTaj  andO  eia,  r  orrovr  ov 
ar  apa^ia. 

*  Pref.  to  Opera  Posthiitiia. 


THE  LIFE   OF  SPINOZA.  43 

He  did  not  seek  to  make  nominal  proselytes  who  would  have 
been  neither  the  wiser  nor  the  happier  for  their  conversion, 
and  when  the  good  woman  of  the  house  attacked  him  with  a 
point-blank  question  as  to  the  sufficiency  of  her  religion  for 
salvation,  he  answered  that  her  religion  was  good  if  it  led  her 
to  a  good  life,  and  she  had  no  need  to  seek  further. 

But  the  strength  of  Spinoza's  social  feelings,  and  the 
importance  he  attached  to  fellowship  among  men  as  the  only 
means  by  which  man  can  live  a  life  worthy  of  his  nature, 
are  most  evidently  shown  in  his  '  Ethics  ; '  and  the  ideal  of 
human  life  Avhich  he  there  sets  forth,  and  to  which  he  himself 
was  faithful  in  action,  will  come  under  our  notice  when  we 
endeavour  to  obtain  a  view  of  his  philosophy. 


44  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER    11. 

SPINOZA'S   CORRESPONDENCE. 

Treu  dem  Gesetz  und  treu 

Dir  selbst— so  bleibst  du  frei. — Proverb. 

He  that  feeds  men  serveth  few  ; 

He  serves  all  who  dares  be  true. — Emerson. 

We  have  already  made  use  of  some  of  Spinoza's  letters  in 
order  to  supplement  the  rather  meagre  outlines  of  his  bio- 
graphy which  we  possess  from  other  sources.  Hereafter  we 
shall  have  to  refer  to  others  as  containing  important  passages 
of  authentic  commentary  on  his  philosophy.  But  we  have  a 
certain  number  of  an  intermediate  character,  which,  while 
their  interest  is  literary  and  speculative  rather  than  personal, 
yet  lie  outside  the  main  lines  of  Spinoza's  systematic  thought. 
They  contain  much  that  is  curious  in  itself,  and  much  that  is 
useful  as  an  introduction  to  Spinoza's  general  manner  of 
thinking  and  discussion  ;  and  we  may  find  it  worth  while  to 
dwell  a  little  upon  them  before  we  finally  quit  the  ground  of 
biography  and  enter  upon  that  of  criticism.  It  is  pleasant  to 
linger  in  a  borderland  where  speculation  is  still  relieved  by  per- 
sonal incidents.  Of  Spinoza's  correspondence  with  Oldenburg 
and  De  Vries  we  have  already  seen  something :  what  remains  in 
those  quarters  is  of  strictly  philosophical  interest.  Another 
friend  of  Spinoza  who  must  have  been  in  constant  intercourse 
with  him  was  Dr.  Lewis  Meyer,  who  undertook  the  publica- 
tion of  the  '  Principles  of  Cartesian  Philosophy,'  and  was  after- 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  45 

wards  joint  editor  of  the  '  Opera  Posthuma.'  What  has 
become  of  the  letters  which  passed  between  these  two  ?  At 
present,  unfortunately,  the  answer  is  that  we  have  one,  and 
only  one,  preserved  in  the  '  Opera  Posthuma,'  this  being  an 
answer  to  a  letter  of  Meyer's,  probably  written  on  behalf  of 
the  philosophical  club  at  Amsterdam,  and  asking  Spinoza  for 
the  result  of  his  speculations  on  the  Infinite.  Here,  again,  we 
must  leave  the  contents  for  the  present  untouched,  only  re- 
marking the  comparatively  early  date  (1663)  of  the  letter. 
It  belongs  to  the  Rijnsburg  time,  and  shows,  together  with 
the  letters  to  De  Vries,  that  the  groundwork  at  least  of 
Spinoza's  system  as  we  now  have  it  was  by  that  time  fully 
formed. 

Oldenburg,  Meyer,  and  De  Vries  naturally  wrote,  as 
scholars,  in  Latin  (De  Vries  not  without  a  touch  of  Batavism), 
and  Spinoza  replied  to  them  in  the  same  language,  writing 
carefully,  and  even  indulging  in  purisms  :  he  will  not  put  the 
scholastic  form  '  essendi '  before  Meyer  without  an  apology.^ 
But  there  were  other  less  learned  correspondents  who  pre- 
ferred the  vernacular. 

The  originals  of  their  letters  are  apparently  preserved 
in  the  Dutch  version  of  the  '  Opera  Posthuma,'  which  was  pub- 
lished almost  simultaneously  with  the  Latin  text.  But  with 
Spinoza's  own  replies  to  them  it  is  not  so.  Two  of  Spinoza's 
Dutch  letters  are  preserved  as  he  wrote  them,  and  the  editors 
of  the  '  Nagelate  Schriften '  found  it  necessary  to  make  con- 
siderable amendments  in  their  composition.  In  one  of  them 
Spinoza  expressly  apologizes  for  not  being  perfect  in  the 
language.  There  is  some  reason  to  think  the  Latin  versions 
of  the  letters  originally  sent  in  Dutch  were  prepared  for  pub- 
lication by  Spinoza  himself  ^ 

The  lion's  share  of  the  miscellaneous  correspondence,  in 

'  '  Infinitam  esiendi  sive  (invita  Latinitate)  essendi  fruitionem. ' — Ep.  29. 
2  See  Prof.  Land's  paper,  Over  de  eerste  uitgaven  der  brieven  van  Spinoza, 
Amsterdam,  1879  ;  and  Appendix  C  below. 


46  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

point  of  bulk  at  least,  belongs  to  William  van  Blyenbergh,  a 
worthy  merchant  and  municipal  officer  of  Dort,  and  a  citizen 
of  good  family,  who  was  mightily  taken,  by  his  own  account, 
with  Spinoza's  '  Principles  of  Cartesian  Philosophy.'  In 
December  1664  he  wrote  to  Spinoza  in  these  terms  : — 

'  Dear  Sir  and  unknown  Friend, — I  have  already  had  the  pleasure 
of  several  times  carefully  reading  over  your  treatise  lately  published, 
together  with  its  Appendix.  It  will  be  more  proper  for  me  to  speak 
to  others  than  to  yourself  of  the  exceeding  solidity  I  found  in  it,  and 
of  the  pleasure  I  derived  from  it.  This  much  I  cannot  forbear  saying, 
that  the  oftener  I  go  over  it  with  attention,  the  more  I  am  pleased 
with  it  ;  and  that  I  constantly  find  something  which  I  had  not 
marked  before.' 

He  proceeds  to  enlarge  (in  a  style  much  improved  by  the 
Latin  translation)  on  his  sincere  love  of  philosophic  truth  as 
the  only  thing  deserving  of  affection  in  this  transitory  life,  on 
his  admiration  for  the  knowledge  and  philosophic  felicity 
shown  in  Spinoza's  work,  and  his  desire  to  make  the  personal 
acquaintance  of  a  man  so  favoured,  and  on  his  disappoint- 
ment in  having  been  prevented,  by  various  causes,  from  intro- 
ducing himself  to  Spinoza  face  to  face  instead  of  by  letter. 
He  had  meant  only  to  ask,  in  a  preliminary  way,  whether  he 
might  trouble  Spinoza  with  some  of  his  difficulties  ;  but,  '  not 
to  leave  the  letter  quite  empty,'  he  states  one  of  them  forth- 
with, which  concerns  the  question  of  creation,  especially  as 
bearing  on  the  origin  of  evil.  If,  according  to  what  is  said  in 
various  places  by  Spinoza,  both  in  his  exposition  of  Descartes 
and  in  his  own  commentary,  God  is  the  immediate  cause,  not 
only  of  the  existence  of  the  human  soul  but  of  its  particular 
operations,  is  not  God  the  immediate  cause  of  evil  volitions, 
for  example,  the  determination  of  Adam  to  eat  the  forbidden 
fruit }  Blyenbergh  professes  himself  puzzled,  but  confidently 
awaits  a  satisfactory  answer,  and  adds  a  sentence  ominous  of 
future  garrulity  :  '  Be  assured,  dear  sir,  that  I  ask  this  for  no 
other  cause  than  desire  for  the  truth,  and  have  no  particular 


SPINOZA'S   CORRESPONDENCE.  47 

interests  ;  I  am  unattachecl,  dependent  on  no  profession ;  I 
live  by  honest  merchandise,  and  spend  my  leisure  on  these 
subjects.  I  humbly  pray  you  not  to  find  my  difficulties 
troublesome.' 

Spinoza  seems  to  have  thought  from  this  first  letter  that 
Blyenbergh  was  a  man  of  some  real  capacity,  and  that  he 
had  gained  a  valuable  acquaintance.  At  any  rate,  he  received 
his  unknown  correspondent  with  a  warm  welcome. 

'Unknown  Friend, — From  your  letter  I  understand  your  exceed- 
ing love  of  truth,  and  how  that  only  is  the  aim  of  all  your  desires  ; 
and  since  I  direct  my  mind  upon  naught  else,  this  constrains  me  to 
determine,  not  only  fully  to  grant  your  request,  which  is  to  answer 
to  the  best  of  my  skill  the  questions  which  you  now  send  or  shall 
send  hereafter,  but  to  perform  all  else  on  my  part  which  may  avail 
for  our  better  acquaintance  and  sincere  friendship.  For  myself,  there 
is  among  things  out  of  my  own  control  none  I  prize  more  than 
entering  into  the  bond  of  friendship  with  men  who  are  sincere 
lovers  of  truth.  For  I  believe  that  nothing  in  the  world,  not  being 
under  our  own  control,  can  be  so  securely  taken  for  the  object  of  our 
love  as  men  of  this  temper  ;  since  'tis  no  more  possible  to  dissolve 
that  love  they  have  for  one  another  (seeing  it  is  founded  on  the  love 
each  of  them  hath  for  the  knowledge  of  truth)  than  not  to  embrace 
the  truth  itself  when  once  perceived.  This  love  is  moreover  the 
most  perfect  and  delightful  which  can  exist  towards  objects  not  in  our 
control,  since  no  other  thing  has  such  virtue  as  truth  to  unite  men's 
minds  and  affections.  I  say  nothuig  of  the  exceeding  conveniences 
that  spring  from  it,  that  I  may  no  longer  detain  you  with  matters 
which  you  doubtless  well  know  ;  I  have  however  done  so  thus  far, 
the  better  to  show  how  pleasant  it  is  to  me  now,  and  will  be  in  future, 
to  find  any  occasion  of  doing  you  service.' 

He  then  takes  up  the  question  proposed  by  Blyenbergh. 
After  observing  that  Blyenbergh  has  not  defined  his  notion  of 
evil,  Spinoza  declares  that  for  his  part  he  cannot  allow  that 
sin  and  evil  have  any  positive  reality,  much  less  that  anything 
happens  contrary  to  God's  will :  nay,  it  is  only  an  inexact 
and  human  fashion  of  speech  to  say  that  man  can  sin  against 
or  offend  God.    For  every  really  existing  thing,  if  we  consider 


48  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

it  apart  from  its  relation  to  other  things,  is  perfect  as  far  as 
its  existence  goes  (this  equivalence  of  reality  and  perfection  is 
one  of  the  key-notes  of  Spinoza's  metaphysic).  Thus,  taking 
Blyenbergh's  example  of  Adam's  determination  to  eat  the 
forbidden  fruit,  there  is  no  imperfection  in  the  act  as  such. 
Approval  or  disapproval  implies  a  standard  of  comparison  ; 
we  are  simply  amused  by  actions  in  animals  which  are  the 
object  of  moral  condemnation  in  men.  Sin  is  a  note  of  im- 
perfection, and  therefore  something  apart  from  the  action 
itself,  in  so  far  as  it  partakes  of  or  '  expresses  reality.' 

Again,  we  cannot  say  that  Adam's  will  was  evil  inasmuch 
as  it  displeased  God.  For  we  cannot  assume  anything  to 
happen  against  God's  will  without  assuming  imperfection  in 
God,  whose  will,  indeed,  being  coextensive  with  his  under- 
standing, an  event  against  God's  will  could  only  be  an  event 
repugnant  to  the  laws  of  understanding.  Adam's  determina- 
tion, then,  was  not  evil  considered  in  itself,  nor  yet,  strictly 
speaking,  contrary  to  God's  will ;  and  there  is  no  difficulty  in 
admitting  God  to  have  been  the  cause  of  it,  so  far  as  it  was  a 
real  action.  Its  evil  consisted  in  Adam's  losing  in  consequence 
of  it  the  state  of  perfection  he  enjoyed  before.  But  loss  is 
merely  negative,  and  the  conception  of  it  a  relative  one  which 
has  no  place  in  absolute  intellect.  Our  notion  of  imperfection 
arises  from  an  individual  not  conforming  to  the  type  of  the 
class  which  we  have  obtained  by  a  process  of  abstraction. 
But  infinite  intellect  has  no  need  of  abstraction  or  definition, 
and  therefore  does  not  and  cannot  regard  anything  as  imper- 
fect. Everything  is  as  real  and  as  perfect  as  the  divine  power 
has  made  it :  in  other  words,  as  perfect  as  it  can  be.  We 
call  things  good  or  bad  in  their  kinds  ;  but  the  divine  intel- 
lect sees  everything  as  perfect  in  itself     This  Spinoza  thinks 

'  Cf.  Cogit.  Met.  pt.  ii.  c.  7,  §  4  :  '  Quum  ergo  mala  et  peccata  in  rebus  nihil 
sint,  sed  tantum  in  mente  humana  res  inter  se  comparante,  sequitur  Deum  ipsa 
extra  mentes  humanas  non  cognoscere.'  And  §5:  '.  .  .  .  Deo  singularium 
cognitionem  tribuimus,  universalium  denegamus,  nisi  quatenus  mentes  humanas 
intelligit,' 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPOhWENCE.  49 

a  sufficient  answer  on  speculative  grounds  ;  but  he  goes  on  -to 
the  practical  bearings  of  the  matter.  As  to  the  language  of  the 
Scriptures,  they  speak  in  a  popular,  not  a  philosophic  manner, 
ascribing  to  God  anger,  jealousy,  and  even  liability  to  error. 
'  Thus  the  precept  given  to  Adam  consisted  only  in  this,  that 
God  revealed  to  Adam  that  eating  of  that  tree  caused  death  ; 
just  as  God  reveals  to  us  through  natural  understanding  that 
poison  is  deadly  to  us.  If  you  ask  for  what  purpose  God 
revealed  this  to  Adam,  I  answer,  in  order  to  make  him  to 
that  extent  more  perfect  in  knowledge.'  '  If  you  ask, 
again,  why  he  did  not  give  Adam  a  more  perfect  will,  it  is 
like  asking  why  God  has  not  endowed  the  circle  with  the 
properties  of  the  sphere. 

Then  as  to  the  objection  that  if  all  men  do  the  will  of 
God,  the  wicked  do  it  no  less  than  the  good  :  they  do  it  in- 
deed in  their  fashion,  but  their  lot  is  nevertheless  very 
different.  Knowing  not  God,  they  serve  him  as  a  blind 
instrument  in  the  workman's  hand,  which  perishes  in  the 
using  ;  the  righteous  do  their  service  with  knowledge,  and  are 
made  more  perfect  therein. 

The  letter  disclpses  only  parts  of  Spinoza's  ethical  theory, 
and  in  language  adapted  to  the  assumptions  of  his  questioner  ; 
but  these  parts  are  characteristic.  Even  in  this  form  they 
may  still  seem  daring  to  many  readers,  and  Blyenbergh 
was  entirely  taken  aback  by  them.  Yet  the  leading  idea  of 
the  letter — namely,  that  the  notions  of  good  and  evil  are  re- 
lative, and  have  place  only  in  finite  intellects — had  been  enun- 
ciated centuries  before  by  Maimohides,  Observe  also  Spinoza's 
complete  Nominalism,  and  the  important  practical  use  he 
makes  of  it  against  the  anthropomorphic  view  of  the  govern- 
ment of  the  world. 

Ten  days  later  Blyenbergh  replied  in  a  very  long  epistle, 
the  contents  of  which  it  is  needless  to  state  further  than  that 

'  Cf.  Trad.   Theol.-Polit,  c.  4,  §§26,  27,  where  it  is  said  that  the  revelation 
was  a  command  or  precept  only  in  respect  of  Adam's  imperfect  knowledge. 

E 


50  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

he  repeats  and  enlarges  on  his  objections.  He  protests  that 
Spinoza's  doctrine  destroys  all  practical  difiference  between 
right  and  wrong,  and  leaves  no  ground  for  preferring  virtue 
to  vice.  As  for  desiring  virtue  for  its  own  sake,  human 
nature  is  far  too  weak  for  that.  '  See  what  ground  we  give 
to  all  godless  men  and  their  impiety  !  We  make  ourselves 
like  stocks,  and  our  actions  no  better  than  the  works  of  a 
watch.'  Blyenbergh  also  explains  to  Spinoza  at  the  begin- 
ning of  the  letter  that  he  has  two  rules  wherewith  to  guide 
himself  in  philosophy,  Reason  and  Scripture  ;  and  that  if  the 
apparently  clear  conclusions  of  his  reason  differ  from  the  re- 
vealed word,  he  can  only  suppose  that  his  reason  is  wrong.^ 

This  disclosure  was  a  surprise  to  Spinoza,  who  answered 
that  on  such  conditions  discussion  would  not  be  very  profit- 
able. 

'  When  I  read  your  first  letter,  I  thought  that  our  opinions  pretty 
well  agreed  ;  but  from  the  second  I  understand  it  is  quite  otherwise, 
and  perceive  that  we  differ  not  only  in  the  consequences  that  may  be 
drawn  from  first  principles,  but  also  in  the  principles  themselves  ;  in- 
somuch that  I  can  scarce  believe  that  we  shall  be  able  to  instruct 
one  another  further  by  letters.  For  I  see  that  no  demonstration, 
however  firm  it  may  be  according  to  the  laws  of  demonstration,  may 
prevail  with  you  unless  it  agree  with  the  interpretation  that  you,  or 
other  theologians  familiar  to  you,  put  upon  Holy  Writ.  If  you  find 
the  light  of  Scripture  clearer  than  the  light  of  reason  (which  also  is 
given  us  by  divine  wisdom),  you  are  doubtless  right  in  your  own 
conscience  in  making  your  reason  yield.  For  my  part,  since  I 
plainly  confess  that  I  do  not  understand  the  Scriptures,  though  I  have 
spent  many  years  upon  them,  and  since  I  know  that  when  once  I 
have  a  firm  proof  I  cannot  by  any  course  of  thought  come  to  doubt  of 
it,  I  rest  wholly  upon  that  which  my  understanding  commends  to  me, 
without  any  suspicion  that  I  am  deceived  therein,  or  that  the 
Scriptures,  even  though  I  do  not  search  them,  can  speak  against  it. 
For  one  truth  cannot  conflict  with  another,  as  I  have  already  clearly 
shown  in  my  Appendix  to  the  "  Principles  of  Descartes  "  (I  Cannot  give 
the  chapter,  as  here  in  the  country  I  have  not  the  book  by  me).' 

'  Ep.  33. 

*  Cogii.  Met.  pt.  ii.  c.  8,  §  5.     '  Veritas  veritati  non  repugnat,  nee  scriptura 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  51 

But  if  in  any  case  I  did  find  error  in  that  which  I  have  collected  from 
my  natural  understanding,  I  should  count  it  good  fortune,  since  I 
enjoy  life,  and  endeavour  to  pass  it  not  in  weeping  and  sighing,  but 
in  peace,  joy,  and  cheerfulness,  and  from  time  to  time  climb  thereby 
a  step  higher.  I  know,  meanwhile  (which  is  the  highest  pleasure  of 
all),  that  all  things  happen  by  the  power  and  unchangeable  decree  of 
the  most  perfect  Being.' 

He  then  turns  to  the  matter  of  Blyenbergh's  objections, 
which  depend  on  his  way  of  regarding  God  in  his  relations  to 
man  as  a  magnified  human  judge  ;  whereas  in  Spinoza's  view 
the  reward  of  serving  God  is  not  as  it  were  a  prize,  but  the 
necessary  consequence  of  the  work  itself.  The  love  of  God, 
which  is  man's  highest  happiness,  follows  from  the  knowledge 
of  God  as  necessarily  as  it  follows  from  the  nature  of 
a  triangle  that  the  sum  of  its  angles  is  two  right  angles. 
*  One  may  easily  give  a  general  proof  of  this,  if  one  will  only 
consider  the  nature  of  God's  decrees,  as  I  have  explained  in 
my  Appendix.^  But  I  confess  that  all  those  who  confound 
the  divine  nature  with  that  of  man  are  very  inapt  to  compre- 
hend this.'  Spinoza  further  shows  how  Blyenbergh  had  mis- 
understood both  himself  and  Descartes,  and  then  replies  with 
some  warmth  to  the  charge  that  his  doctrine  is  likely  to  have 
mischievous  consequences.  '  When  you  say  that  by  making 
men  so  dependent  on  God  I  make  them  like  the  natural 
elements,  herbs,  or  stones,  that  is  full  proof  that  you  take  my 
meaning  much  amiss,  and  confuse  things  which  are  of  the 
understanding  with  things  of  the  imagination.  For  if  you 
had  clearly  conceived  in  your  understanding  what  dependence 
on  God  is,  you  would  never  think  that  things,  forasmuch  as 

nugas,  quales  vulgo  fingunt,  docere  potest.  Si  enim  in  ipsa  inveniremus  aliquid, 
quod  lumini  natural!  esset  contrarium,  eadem  libertate,  qua  Alcoranum  et 
Thalmud  refellimus,  illam  lefellere  possemus.' 

'  Cogii.  Met.  pt.  ii.  c.  9  ;  cf.  c.  7,  §  7  :  Dei  volitiones  et  decreta  =  eius  cognitio 
circa  res  creatas]:  'Dei  idea  sive  decretum.'  Cf.  too  Tract.  TheoL-Pol.  c.  4, 
§§  24,  25:  '  respectu  Dei  unum  et  idem  affirmamus,  quum  dicimus  I^eum  ab 
aeterno  decrevisse  et  voluisse  tres  angulos  trianguli  aequales  esse  duobus  rectis,  vel 
Deum  hoc  ipsum  intellexisse.' 

E  2 


52  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

they  depend  on  God,  are  dead,  corporeal,  and  imperfect  (as 
who  has  ever  dared  speak  so  meanly  of  the  most  perfect 
being  ?) ;  you  would  understand,  on  the  contrary,  that  thereby, 
and  forasmuch  as  they  depend  on  God,  they  are  perfect ;  so 
that  we  best  understand  this  dependence,  and  the  necessary 
operation  of  things  by  God's  decrees,  when  we  look,  not  upon 
stocks  and  herbs,  but  upon  the  most  reasonable  and  perfect 
creatures.  ...  I  cannot  forbear  saying  that  I  am  greatly 
amazed  when  you  say.  If  God  were  not  to  punish  evil  (to 
wit,  as  a  judge  doth,  with  a  punishment  that  the  evil  itself 
brings  not  with  it,  for  that  is  our  only  difference),  what  reason 
is  there  that  I  should  not  run  into  all  manner  of  wickedness  } 
Surely  he  who  abstains  from  such  things  only  for  fear  of  pun- 
ishment (which  I  will  not  think  of  you)  is  in  no  way  moved 
by  love  towards  God,  and  has  mighty  little  affection  for 
virtue.  For  my  part,  I  let  such  things  alone,  or  endeavour  so 
to  do,  because  they  would  be  clearly  at  strife  with  my  proper 
nature,  and  lead  me  astray  from  the  knowledge  and  the  love 
of  God.' 

As  to  the  rule  of  submission  to  the  Scriptures,  Spinoza 
says  that  in  his  opinion  it  is  a  more  respectful  way  of  treat- 
ing the  Scriptures  to  recognize  that  they  speak  in  human 
language  and  in  parables  than  to  put  hasty  and  absurd 
interpretations  upon  them  for  the  purpose  of  contradicting 
natural  reason.  .*  Matters  of  high  speculation  have,  I  think, 
nothing  to  do  with  the  Scriptures.  For  my  part,  I  have  learnt 
none  of  God's  eternal  attributes  from  Scripture,  nor  have  been 
able  to  learn  any.' 

One  would  think  this  answer  not  very  encouraging,  but 
Blyenbergh,  nothing  daunted,  returned  to  the  charge  with 
another  letter  '  nearly  as  long  as  the  former  one.  He  mildly 
complains  of  Spinoza's  censures,  but  makes  a  kind  of  apo- 
logy for  persisting  in  his  objections.  He  asks  many  new 
questions,  most  of  them  unanswerable  and  some  irrational, 

'  Ep.  35. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  53 

and  winds  up  with  this  sage  postscript :  '  Through  haste  I 
have  forgot  to  add  this  question,  whether  we  cannot  by  our 
foresight  prevent  that  which  otherwise  would  befall  us  ? ' 
Spinoza  replied  '  in  courteous  terms,  but  obviously  beginning 
to  lose  patience,  that  his  purpose  had  been  not  merely  to 
criticize,  but  to  point  out  to  Blyenbergh  the  fundamental 
nature  of  their  difference.  '  I  had  thought,'  he  says  in 
substance,  *  that  you  wished  to  discuss  these  matters  in  a 
purely  philosophical  manner,  but  you  showed  me  that  it  was 
otherwise,  and  that  the  foundation  on  which  I  thought  to 
build  our  friendship  was  not  laid  as  I  had  supposed.'  He 
consents  once  more,  however,  to  address  himself  to  Blyen- 
bergh's  objections.  The  leading  passage  is  so  characteristic 
that  it  seems  profitable  to  give  it  nearly  in  full. 

'  In  the  first  place  I  say  that  God  is  perfectly  and  truly  the  cause 
of  everything  whatsoever  that  hath  any  being.  Now  if  you  can 
show  that  evil,  error,  crimes,  and  the  like  are  anything  which 
expresses  real  being,  I  shall  fully  grant  to  you  that  God  is  the  cause 
of  these  things.  I  have  sufficiently  shown,  to  my  mind,  that  that 
which  constitutes  the  nature  of  evil,  error,  crimes,  and  so  forth 
consists  not  in  anything  that  expresses  real  being  ;  and  therefore  we 
cannot  say  that  God  is  their  cause.  For  example,  Nero's  matricide, 
in  so  far  as  it  comprehended  anything  positive,  was  not  a  crime. 
For  the  outward  act,  and  likewise  the  intention  to  slay  his  mother, 
were  the  same  in  Orestes'  case,  and  yet  he  is  not  blamed,  at  least  not 
in  the  same  degree  as  Nero.  What,  then,  was  Nero's  crime? 
Nothing  else  but  that  by  such  a  deed  he  showed  himself  ungrateful, 
unmerciful,  and  disobedient.  'Tis  certain  that  none  of  these  things 
express  real  being,  and  therefore  God  was  not  the  cause  thereof, 
though  he  was  of  Nero's  act  and  intent.  Further,  I  would  here  have 
you  note  that  while  we  speak  in  the  manner  of  philosophy  we  must 
not  use  the  language  of  theology.  For  since  theology  constantly 
represents  God  as  a  perfect  man  (and  that  not  without  reason)  it 
suits  well  enough  in  theology  to  say  that  God  has  desire,  that  he  is 
angered  at  the  works  of  the  ungodly,  or  that  he  takes  pleasure  in 
those  of  the  righteous.     But  in  philosophy,  where  we  clearly  under- 

•  Ep.  36. 


54  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

stand  that  it  is  as  little  fit  to  ascribe  to  God  the  properties  that  make 
a  man  perfect  as  if  one  should  ascribe  to  man  such  as  belong  to  the 
perfection  of  the  elephant  or  the  ass,  there,I  say,  the  forementioned  sort 
of  terms  have  no  place,  and  we  cannot  so  use  them  without  greatly 
confounding  our  conception  of  the  matter.  Therefore,  philosophically 
speaking,  we  may  not  say  that  God  desires  anything  of  any  man,  or 
that  anything  is  displeasing  or  agreeable  to  him  ;  for  all  these  are 
human  qualities,  which  in  God  have  no  place.' 

He  goes  on  to  say,  in  answer  to  specific  questions  of 
Blyenbergh's,  that  however  indifferent  acts  may  be  in  them- 
selves, considered  from  the  philosophic  or  universal  point  of 
view,  this  does  not  afifect  our  moral  judgment  of  the  agents. 
Blyenbergh  asks  whether  homicide  is  equally  acceptable 
to  God  with  almsgiving  t  '  Philosophically  speaking,'  says 
Spinoza,  '  I  do  not  know  what  you  mean  by  acceptable  to  God. 
If  the  question  is  whether  God  hates  the  one  and  loves  the 
other,  and  whether  the  one  has  given  offence  to  God  and  the 
other  done  him  a  favour,  then  I  answer  No.  If  the  question 
is  whether  murderers  are  equally  good  and  perfect  with  those 
who  give  alms,  I  again  say  No.'  The  similar  question, 
whether  stealing  be  in  the  sight  of  God  as  good  as  honesty, 
is  similarly  disposed  of.  The  acts  of  the  thief  and  the  honest 
man,,  so  far  as  they  are  real  actions,  are  equally  perfect. 
Spinoza's  meaning  may  want  illustration  for  modern  readers ; 
suppose,  for  example,  a  thief  putting  forth  his  hand  to  steal, 
and  an  honest  man  laying  hands  on  him  to  stop  him.  The 
motion  of  the  hand,  considered  as  a  natural  event  exhibiting 
the  structure  and  functions  of  human  limbs,  is  in  itself  no  better 
or  worse  in  the  honest  man's  anatomy  than  in  the  thief's.  Or, 
again,  a  thief  may  steal  goods  with  violence,  and  an  officer  of 
justice  may  afterwards  recover  them  from  the  thief,  by  actions 
in  themselves  precisely  similar.  But  the  honest  man  and 
the  thief  are  not  therefore  alike  in  perfection  or  happiness 
of  estate.  '  For  by  an  honest  man  '  (Spinoza  continues)  '  I 
understand  one  who  desires  that  every  one  should  have  his 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  55 

own  ;  and  I  show  in  my  Ethics  (as  yet  unpubHshed)  that  this 
desire  necessarily  arises  in  righteous  men  from  the  clear  know- 
ledge they  have  of  themselves  and  of  God.'  Evil-doers,  not 
having  this  desire,  must  be  without  the  knowledge  of  God, 
and  so  miss  the  great  foundation  of  human  happiness. 

There  was  yet  a  third  question  :  if  there  existed  a  mind 
so  framed  that  vice  and  crime  were  not  repugnant  to  its 
proper  nature  but  agreed  with  it,  could  any  rational  motive 
be  assigned  why  such  an  agent  should  do  good  or  avoid  evil  .■* 
Spinoza  says  that  this  is  to  assume  a  contradiction, 

'  It  seems  to  me  no  otherwise  than  if  one  asked,  supposing 
it  agreed  better  with  his  nature  to  hang  himself,  whether  there 
would  be  any  reason  for  not  hanging  himself.'  Assuming 
that  a  man  could  really  find  hanging  to  agree  better  with 
him  than  eating  and  drinking,  his  only  rational  course  would 
be  to  hang  himself ;  assuming  that  such  a  perverse  human 
being  as  suggested  by  Blyenbergh  could  exist,  vice  would 
with  respect  to  such  a  being  become  virtue. 

'  As  to  the  last  question,  which  you  have  added  at  the 
end  of  your  letter,  since  one  could  put  a  hundred  such  in  an , 
hour  without  coming  to  a  conclusion  in  any  case,  and  you 
do  not  much  press  for  an  answer  yourself,  I  shall  not  answer 
it.'  The  question  was  indeed  a  formidably  vague  one. 
Probably  Blyenbergh  wanted  to  extract  from  Spinoza  some- 
thing capable  of  being  used  as  an  admission  of  free-will, 

Blyenbergh,  still  unabashed,  paid  Spinoza  a  visit  in  person, 
and  finding  that  he  could  not  remember  to  his  own  satisfac- 
tion what  Spinoza  had  said  to  him,  sent  yet  another  epistle, 
asking  a  new  string  of  questions,  which  rambled  pretty  well 
over  the  whole  ground  of  the  '  Principia  Philosophise  '  and 
'  Cogitata  Metaphysica.'  He  concluded  by  asking,  as  a 
favour  necessary  to  his  complete  understanding  of  Spinoza's 
answers,  that  Spinoza  would  furnish  him  with  the  principal 
heads  of  the  '  Ethics.' 

Philosophers  are  men  (though  the  contrary  seems  to  be 


56  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

not  uncommonly  believed),  and  human  long-suffering  has 
limits.  After  some  delay  Spinoza  now  replied  very  shortly/ 
to  the  effect  that  he  really  could  not  undertake  to  answer 
questions  of  such  a  scope,  but  hoped  to  find  an  opportunity 
of  explaining  by  word  of  mouth  that  it  was  impracticable  ; 
the  chief  reason  being  that,  even  if  he  could  do  it,  the  funda- 
mental differences  between  his  views  and  Blyenbergh's  would 
remain  where  they  were  before.  He  hopes  that,  on  further 
consideration  of  the  matter,  Blyenbergh  will  waive  this  last 
request,  and  remain  his  good  friend.  With  this  Blyenbergh 
disappears  from  Spinoza's  correspondence,  but  we  hear  more 
of  him  from  Colerus,  who  speaks  with  much  admiration  of 
a  controversial  treatise  against  the  'Tractatus  Theologico- 
Politicus  '  published  by  Blyenbergh  in  1674.  Notwithstand- 
ing his  former  friendly  intercourse  with  Spinoza,  the  worthy 
merchant  of  Dordrecht  pronounced  the  book  to  be  '  full  of 
curious  but  abominable  discoveries,  the  learning  and  inquiries 
whereof  must  needs  have  been  fetched  from  hell.'  He  under- 
took to  prove  Spinoza's  opinions  ruinous  to  the  welfare  of 
souls  and  of  States,  '  Ziel-  en  Landsverderffelyck.'  But  such 
were  the  usual  amenities  of  controversy  at  the  time.  In 
most  cases  they  probably  implied  no  personal  ill-will.  Eight 
years  later  Blyenbergh  also  published  a  refutation  of  the 
'  Ethics,'  ^  with  the  vc\o\Xo  A  rdu a  quae  pulckra,  probably  meant 
as  a  counterblast  to  Spinoza's  own  concluding  words,  '  omnia 
praeclara  tam  difficilia  quam  rara  sunt.' 

The  curiosity  of  Spinoza's  questioners  was  not  limited  to 
the  proper  field  of  philosophy  ;  they  made  no  scruple  of  con- 
sulting him  on  omens  and  ghosts.  A  friend  named  Peter 
Balling,  of  whom  we  know  very  little,^  but  for  whom,  judging 
from  the  tone  of  the  answer,  Spinoza  must  have  had  a  sincere 
regard,  announced  the  death  of  a  child,  and  at  the  same  time 

'  Ep.  38.  ■'  Bibliografie,  380. 

*  It  appears  that  he  was  the  translator  of  Spinoza's  Pnnciples  of  Descartes' 
Philosophy,  of  which  a  Dutch  version  came  out  not  long  after  the  Latin. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  57 

(seeking  perhaps  distraction  in  a  speculative  question)  desired 
Spinoza's  opinion  of  a  supposed  forewarning  that  had  come 
to  him.  In  other  circumstances  it  is  possible  that  Spinoza 
might  have  dealt  with  such  a  query  rather  summarily.  We 
cannot  suppose  for  instance  that  Blyenbergh  would  have  taken 
much  by  throwing  it  in  among  his  other  difficulties.  But  now 
Spinoza  was  full  of  consideration  for  his  friend's  distress,  and 
whatever  he  may  have  thought  of  the  wisdom  of  the  question 
in  itself,  he  answered  it,'  gently  and  patiently,  though  with 
his  usual  decision.  After  expressing  his  sympathy  and  en- 
treating Balling  to  write  to  him  again  at  length,  he  proceeds 
to  the  matter  of  the  warning. 

'  As  to  the  omen  you  mention,  namely,  that  while  your  child  was 
still  in  good  health  you  heard  it  groan  in  the  same  manner  that  it  did 
when  it  had  fallen  into  the  sickness  whereof  it  soon  after  died  :  I 
should  think  these  were  no  real  groans,  but  mere  imagination,  since 
you  say  that  when  you  rose  up  and  set  yourself  to  listen  for  them, 
you  heard  them  not  so  clearly  as  either  before,  or  afterwards  when 
you  had  fallen  asleep  again.  Surely  this  proves  that  these  groans 
were  nothing  else  than  imagination,  which,  being  detached  and 
free,  could  frame  to  itself  a  sound  of  groans  in  a  more  forcible  and 
lively  manner  than  in  the  time  when  you  rose  up  to  listen  in  a  certain 
direction.  I  can  both  confirm  and  explain  what  I  now  say  by  another 
chance  which  befell  me  last  winter  at  Rijnsburg.  One  morning  as 
I  woke  out  of  a  very  heavy  dream  (it  being  already  day),  the  images 
which  had  come  before  me  in  my  dream  remained  before  my  eyes 
as  lively  as  if  they  had  been  the  very  things,  and  specially  that  of  a 
scurvy  ^  black  Brazilian,  whom  I  had  never  before  seen.  This  image 
vanished  for  the  most  part,  when,  in  order  to  divert  myself  with 
somewhat  else,  I  cast  my  eyes  on  a  book  or  any  other  thing ;  but 
so  soon  as  I  removed  my  eyes  from  their  object,  without  looking 
with  attention  anywhere,  the  image  of  this  same  negro  appeared 
as  lively  as  before,  and  that  again  and  again,  until  it  vanished  even 
to  the  head.  Now  I  say  that  the  same  thing  which  happened  to 
me  in  the  inward  sense  of  sight  happened  in  your  sense  of  hearing. 
But  since  the  causes  were  very  different,  there  was  in  your  case  an 
omen,  and   in    mine    none.      [The  effects  of   the  imagination  are 

'  Ep.  30,  -  Or,  'leprous.' 


58  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

various,  according  to  the  exciting  cause,  which  may  be  either  mental 
or  bodily.'  Where  it  is  bodily,  as  in  the  delirium  of  fever,  there  can 
be  no  question  of  any  relation  to  future  events.]  But  the  effects  of 
imagination,  or  images,  which  have  their  origin  from  the  condition 
of  the  mind,  may  be  omens  of  something  future,  because  the  mind 
can  have  a  confused  presentiment  of  such  a  thing.  It  can  therefore 
frame  to  itself  as  firm  and  lively  an  image  of  such  a  thing  as  if  the 
thing  were  present.  Thus,  to  take  an  example  like  yours,  a  father 
so  loves  his  son  that  he  and  his  beloved  son  are  as  it  were  one  and 
the  same  being.' 

Spinoza  goes  on  to  say,  referring  for  details  to  some 
fuller  exposition  of  the  subject  which  cannot  be  identified 
with  anything  in  his  extant  works,  that  in  so  far  as  the 
father  is  united  by  sympathy  with  the  son,  he  shares  not 
only  in  his  actual  existence,  but  in  the  consequences  de- 
termined by  his  present  state  and  potentially  included  in 
it.  Under  favourable  conditions,  then,  he  may  have  an 
extremely  vivid  imagination  of  something  depending  on 
the  son's  own  constitution  and  likely  to  happen  to  him,  and 
which  does  in  fact  happen  to  him  shortly  afterwards. 

Spinoza's  language  is  not  altogether  clear.  It  seems  to 
assume  a  physiological  theory  of  presentiments  and  other 
similar  occurrences,  designed  to  afford  a  natural  explanation 
not  only  of  the  subjective  facts,  but  of  the  supposed  warnings 
being  verified  in  a  certain  proportion  of  cases.  Some  such 
theory  may  have  been  struck  out  by  Spinoza  in  the  days  when 
he  still  believed  in  animal  spirits  ;  as  indeed  various  physical 
conjectures  of  a  similar  kind  have  been  started  in  our  own 
time  with  much  less  excuse.  Even  very  ingenious  persons 
will  try  the  most  improbable  suppositions  rather  than  resign 
themselves  to  the  incredulity  of  healthy  common  sense. 

It  is  fairly  certain  that  the  '  confused  presentiment '  spoken 
of  in  the  letter  does  not  mean  a  revelation  or  literal  foreseeing 

'  Spinoza  is  here  speaking  in  a  popular  manner.  We  shall  see  hereafter  that 
he  does  not  admit  any  causal  connexion  between  mental  and  material  phenomena, 
but  only  a  parallel  correspondence  excluding  such  a  relation. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  59 

of  a  future  event  as  such,  but  a  sort  of  unconscious  judgment 
of  the  possibilities  involved  in  existing  conditions.  But  the 
exact  nature  of  this  operation  is  not  defined,  still  less  the 
nature  and  extent  of  the  sympathy  which  enables  us  to  form 
a  presentiment  as  to  persons  closely  connected  with  us.  The 
conception  of  love  as  an  impulse  to  union  with  the  beloved 
object,  which  is  here  pressed  to  an  almost  fantastic  conse- 
quence, is  taken  from  Descartes,  who  himself  probably  had  it 
from  some  older  source.  It  plays  an  important  part  in 
Spinoza's  essay  *  On  God  and  Man,' — confided  in  manuscript  to 
a  limited  number  of  friends,  of  whom  perhaps  Balling  was  one 
— but  has  disappeared  in  the  Ethics.  On  the  whole  the  re- 
marks now  in  question  seem  to  belong  to  an  early  stage  of 
Spinoza's  psychology.  Compared  with  other  letters  of  about 
the  same  date  (1664)  they  present  something  like  an  anachron- 
ism. But  such  anachronisms  must  exist  in  the  mind  of  every 
man  whose  thoughts  are  still  maturing  ;  and,  under  the  special 
circumstances,  Spinoza  was  probably  willing  to  strain  a  point 
in  favour  of  treating  Balling's  question  seriously. 

Ten  years  later  another  correspondent,  whose  name  has 
been  charitably  suppressed  by  the  editors  of  the  *  Opera 
Posthuma,'  wrote  to  Spinoza,  without  any  particular  occasion 
that  appears,  to  ask  what  he  thought  about  ghosts.  He  comes 
to  the  point  without  preface  or  preparation.  '  The  reason  of  my 
writing  to  you,'  he  says,  '  is  that  I  desire  to  know  your  opinion 
concerning  apparitions,  and  ghosts  or  goblins  ;  and  if  they 
exist,  what  you  think  of  them,  and  how  long  they  live .''  for 
some  consider  them  mortal  and  some  immortal.'  He  is  quite 
aware,  however,  that  Spinoza  may  entertain  the  preliminary 
doubt  whether  there  be  ghosts  at  all  :  '  but  'tis  certain  the 
ancients  believed  in  them.  .  ,  .  Some  say  they  are  made  of 
a  very  thin  fine  matter,  others  that  they  are  incorporeal.' 
Spinoza's  answer^  begins  with  a  neatly  turned  compliment: — 

'  Ep.  56. 


6o  SriNOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

'  Your  letter,  received  yesterday,  was  most  acceptable  to  me,  as 
well  because  I  desired  some  tidings  of  you,  as  because  I  see  that  you 
have  not  quite  forgotten  me.  And  though  others  might  perhaps  take 
it  for  a  bad  omen  that  ghosts  or  goblins  should  be  the  cause  of  your 
writing  to  me,  I  find  on  the  contrary  something  much  more  to  the 
purpose  ;  for  I  perceive  that  not  only  real  things  but  trifles  of  the 
imagination  may  thus  turn  to  my  profit.' 

He  deals  with  the  question  in  a  tone  of  perfect  courtesy, 
but  with  a  touch  of  banter.  '  I  esteem  you  too  much,'  he-says, 
*  to  contradict  you  ;  much  less  can  I  flatter  you  with  a  feigned 
assent.  As  a  middle  course  I  will  beseech  you  to  produce 
one  or  two  thoroughly  authenticated  ghost  stories  of  your  own 
choice.  To  be  plain  with  you,  I  am  so  far  from  having  met 
with  a  satisfactory  account  of  any  ghost,  that  I  cannot  even 
make  out  what  a  ghost  is.  If  the  philosophers  choose  to 
name  those  things  ghosts  which  we  do  not  know,  I  will  not 
contradict  them,  for  there  are  an  infinity  of  things  whereof  I 
have  no  knowledge.'  He  lastly  observes  that  all  the  ghosts 
he  ever  heard  of  were  at  best  very  foolish  creatures,  and 
seemed  to  have  nothing  better  to  do  than  to  make  dull  prac- 
tical jokes. 

The  questioner  replies '  that  he  expected  some  such 
answer,  as  from  a  friend  not  sharing  his  opinion  (so  it  would 
seem  his  original  purpose  was  to  start  a  discussion) ;  but 
friends,  he  adds,  may  well  differ  in  things  indifferent  and  yet 
preserve  their  friendship. 

Before  proceeding  to  give  reasons  for  his  belief  he  notes, 
with  a  judicial  gravity  which  need  not  surprise  us,  seeing  that 
it  is  maintained  at  the  present  day  by  believers  in  table- 
moving,  slate-writing,  funipotent  and  other  goblins,  that 
preconceived  opinions  hinder  the  investigation  of  truth.  He 
does  not  meet  Spinoza's  challenge,  but  gives  a  priori  reasons 
why  there  must  be  disembodied  or  semi-material  spirits— such 

-    '  Ep.  57. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  6i 

•creatures  being,  in  his  opinion,  indispensable  for  the  com- 
pleteness of  the  universe.  On  their  natural  history  he  is 
a  little  uncertain.  '  I  think  there  are  spirits  of  all  sorts, 
though,  perhaps,  none  of  the  female  sex.'  Being  aware, 
however,  that  these  reasons  will  not  be  convincing  to 
people  who  think  the  world  was  made  by  chance,  he  passes 
to  evidence.  He  does  not  accept  the  stories  of  demons  and 
magicians  ;  but  for  ghosts  in  general  he  cites  Plutarch,  Pliny 
the  Younger,  Suetonius,  Lavater,  and  others  ;  the  experience 
of  a  burgomaster  of  his  own  acquaintance,  '  a  learned  and  wise 
man,  yet  living,  who  told  me  that  a  noise  of  working  was 
heard  all  night  in  his  mother's  brewhouse,  just  like  that 
which  brewing  made  in  the  day  time,'  and  some  similar  and 
never-to-be-forgotten  experience  of  his  own — of  which  no 
particulars  are  disclosed. 

After  a  while  Spinoza  replied,'  still  in  the  tone  of  his  first 
answer.  He  had  been  able  to  consult  only  Pliny  and  Sueto- 
nius among  the  list  of  authorities  given  by  his  friend  ;  but  he 
found  these  quite  enough,  for  they  convinced  him  that  the 
historians  who  report  ghost  stories  do  so  merely  for  the  sake 
of  astonishing  their  readers.  '  I  confess  that  I  am  not  a 
little  amazed,  not  at  the  stories  that  are  told,  but  at  those 
who  set  them  down.'  The  suggestion  that  there  are  male  but 
not  female  ghosts  is  presumably  not  serious,  '  otherwise  I 
could  only  compare  it  to  the  imagination  of  the  common  sort, 
who  take  God  to  be  masculine  and  not  feminine.'  He  explains 
that  he  entirely  repudiates  the  notion  of  the  world  having 
been  made  by  chance,  but  he  nevertheless  cannot  admit  his 
friend's  assertion  that  ghosts  are  necessary  to  its  perfection. 
For  perfection  and  beauty  are  terms  relative  to  the  observer. 
'  He  who  says  that  God  has  made  the  world  beautiful  must 
needs  assert  one  of  two  propositions  :  either  that  God  has 
framed  the  world  according  to  the  desire  and  the  eyes  of  men, 
or  the  desire  and  eyes  of  men  according  to  the  world.     Now, 

'  Ep.  58. 


62  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

whether  you  assert  the  former  or  the  latter,  I  see  not  why 
God  must  have  made  goblins  and  ghosts  to  attain  either  of 
these  two  ends.     For  perfection  and  imperfection,  they   are 
terms   not    much    different  from  beauty   and  ugliness.     So, 
not  to  be  tedious,  I  only  ask,  is  the  existence  of  ghosts  more 
necessary  to  the  adornment  and  perfection  of  the  world  than 
that  of  various  other  monsters  like  Centaurs,  Hydras,  Harpies, 
Satyrs,  Griffins,  Argus,  and  other  like  vanities  ?     A  pretty 
world  it  should  have  been,  indeed,  had   God  adorned, and 
beautified  it  after  the  good  pleasure  of  our  fancies  with  such 
things  as  any  man  may  easily  imagine  and  dream,  but  none 
have  yet  been  able  to  understand.'     Having  disposed  of  the 
other  reasons,  Spinoza  regrets  that  his  friend  has  not  been 
able  to  furnish  him  with  any  better  example  than  the  burgo- 
master's ghost  in  the  brewhouse,  which  he  considers  laughable. 
*  To  cut  the   matter  short,   I   take   for  my  authority  Julius 
Caesar,  who,  as  Suetonius  reports,  made  sport  of  such  things 
and  yet  prospered.     And  so  must  all  do  who  consider  the 
effects  of  human  imagination  and  passions,  whatever  Lavater, 
and  others  who  in  this  matter  dream  in  company  with  him, 
may  say  to  the  contrary.' 

The  rejoinder '  was  delayed  by  a  passing  indisposition  of 
the  writer.  It  was  mostly  taken  up  with  a  theological 
digression.  Spinoza's  friend  asks,  among  other  things,  as  a 
retort  to  his  demand  for  a  clearer  definition  of  ghost  or  spirit, 
whether  he  has  so  clear  an  idea  of  God  as  of  a  triangle.  As 
to  the  main  point,  he  takes  refuge  in  the  general  consent  of 
ancient  and  modern  philosophers.  '  Plutarch  bears  witness  of 
this  in  his  treatises  of  the  Opinions  of  the  Philosophers,  and 
of  the  Daemon  of  Socrates  ;  as  do  all  the  Stoics,  Pythago- 
reans, Platonists,  Peripatetics,  Empedocles,  Maximus  Tyrius, 
Apuleius,  and  others.' 

Spinoza  must  have  had  reasons  of  private  friendship  for 
being    indulgent   to   this    correspondent ;    for    he    not   only 

'  Ep.  59. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  63 

answered  him  again,  but  took  up  his  remarks  on  points  quite 
collateral  to  the  existence  of  ghosts.  Part  of  this  letter  '  is 
of  some  importance.  Spinoza  points  out  that  he  conceives 
freedom  as  opposed,  not  to  necessity,  but  to  external  com- 
pulsion. Every  one  admits,  for  example,  that  God's  know- 
ledge of  himself  is  both  free  and  necessary.  So,  again,  man's 
love  of  life  is  necessary,  but  not  compelled.  The  correspon- 
dent had  expressed  surprise  at  Spinoza's  refusal  to  ascribe 
human  qualities  to  God.  To  this  Spinoza  replies :  '  When 
you  say  that,  if  I  allow  not  in  God  the  operations  of  seeing, 
hearing,  observing,  willing,  and  the  like,  nor  that  they  exist 
eminently  in  him,  you  know  not  what  sort  of  God  mine  is :  I 
thence  conjecture  that  you  believe  there  is  no  greater  perfection 
than  such  as  can  be  explained  by  the  attributes  aforesaid.  I 
do  not  wonder  at  it ;  for  I  believe  that  a  triangle,  if  it  could 
speak,  would  in  like  manner  say  that  God  is  eminently  tri- 
angular, and  a  circle  that  the  divine  nature  is  in  an  eminent 
manner  circular ;  and  thus  should  every  one  ascribe  his  own 
attributes  to  God,  and  make  himself  like  God,  counting 
everything  else  as  misshapen.^  .  .  .  When  you  ask  me 
whether  I  have  so  clear  an  idea  of  God  as  of  a  triangle,  I 
answer  Yes.  But  if  you  ask  me  whether  I  have  such  a  clear 
image  of  God  as  of  a  triangle,  I  shall  answer  No :  for  we 
cannot  imagine  God,  but  we  can  understand  him.'  This 
distinction  between  imagination  and  understanding  runs 
through  the  whole  of  Spinoza's  philosophy.  He  repeats  that 
nothing  has  been  advanced  to  make  the  existence  of  ghosts 
even  probable,  and  altogether  declines  to  submit  to  the 
authority  of  the  ancients. 

*  The  authority  of  Plato,  Aristode,  and  Socrates  does  not  count 

'  Ep.  60. 

*  Cf.  the  fragment  of  Xenophanes  : — 

'  If  oxen  and  horses  had  hands  like  ours,  and  fingers. 
Then  would  horses  like  unto  horses,  and  oxen  to  oxen, 
Paint  and  fashion  their  gods.' — (G.  H.  Lewes's  trans.). 


64  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

for  much  with  me.  I  should  have  been  surprised  if  you  had  cited 
Epicurus,  Democritus,  Lucretius,  or  any  of  the  Atomic  school.  For 
it  is  nothing  strange  that  the  inventors  of  occult  qualities,  intentional 
species,  substantial  forms,  and  a  thousand  other  vanities,  should  have 
also  devised  goblins  and  ghosts,  and  given  credence  to  old  wives,  in 
order  to  destroy  Democritus'  reputation,  whose  good  name  they  so 
envied  that  they  burnt  all  the  books  he  had  published  with  so  much 
renown.  If  you  choose  to  believe  them,  what  reason  have  you  for 
denying  the  miracles  of  Our  Lady  and  all  the  saints?  which  are 
described  by  so  many  philosophers,  theologians,  and  historians  of 
renown  that  I  can  produce  a  hundred  of  them  for  one  of  the  others,' 

This  last  passage  is  material,  as  disclosing  how  very  im- 
perfectly Spinoza  was  acquainted  with  Greek  philosophy.  It 
would  seem  that  he  thought  Aristotle  responsible  for  all  the 
developments  of  the  schoolmen  and  knew  Plato  only  by 
name.  His  sympathy  with  the  Epicureans  is  no  doubt 
founded  on  the  fact  that  their  system  was  a  genuine  attempt 
at  a  scientific  explanation  of  the  world,  and  was  in  its  day 
the  solitary  protest  against  the  contempt  of  physics  which 
prevailed  in  the  other  post-Aristotelian  schools.  But  he 
obviously  did  not  know  Lucretius  except  by  hearsay ;  for 
Lucretius  and  his  masters,  so  far  from  venturing  to  deny  the 
objective  reality  of  apparitions,  provided  an  elaborate  physical 
hypothesis  to  account  for  them. 

Alchemy  was  a  kindred  topic  which  still  exercised  men's 
minds  in  Spinoza's  time,  and  we  have  some  evidence  of  the 
manner  in  which  he  regarded  it.  In  1667  he  wrote  to  Jarig 
Jellis  on  an  alleged  conversion  of  silver  into  gold  effected  by 
an  unknown  stranger  in  the  presence  of  the  naturalized  Ger- 
man chemist  Helvetius  (Schweizer),  who  had  by  this  time 
taken  up  alchemy  with  full  belief. 

He  made  inquiries  of  both  the  goldsmith  who  had  assayed 
the  gold  and  Helvetius  himself;  and  though  he  expresses 
no  opinion,  he  was  obviously  disposed  to  think  seriously  of 
the  matter  at  that  time.'     But  in  1675,  when  Dr.  Schaller  had 

»  Ep.  45.     See  Lewes,  Hist.  Phil.  2.  l8o.     Helvetius  published  his  Vittilus 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  65 

sent  him  an  account  of  some  similar  experiment,  he  simply 
replied  that  he  did  not  care  to  repeat  it,  and  that  the  more  he 
considered  it  the  more  sure  he  felt  that  no  gold  was  produced 
which  was  not  there  already.' 

We  have  also  letters  more  nearly  connected  with  Spinoza's 
philosophical  work,  and  attached  to  particular  landmarks  of 
it.  In  1673  the  Jewish  physician  Isaac  Orobio  de  Castro' 
forwarded  to  Spinoza  a  long  letter,  written  nominally  to  him, 
but  for  Spinoza's  perusal,  by  a  certain  Dr.  Lambert  van  Velt- 
huysen  of  Utrecht.  This  critic  went  through  all  the  common 
topics  of  censure  against  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,' 
and  concluded  that  the  principles  of  that  treatise  destroy  the 
foundations  of  religion,  '  introduce  atheism,  or  set  up  a  God 
himself  subject  to  destiny,  whom  men  can  have  no  reason  for 
worshipping  ;  leave  no  room  for  divine  government  or  pro- 
vidence, and  abolish  all  dispensations  of  reward  and  punish- 
ment.' In  short,  the  author  of  such  a  work  has  no  injury  to 
complain  of  if  he  is  denounced  as  teaching  mere  atheism  in  a 
disguised  form.^ 

Spinoza  thought  the  criticism  not  only  wrong  but  perverse  ; 
so  perverse,  indeed,  as  to  be  hardly  consistent  with  good  faith  : 
and  he  replied  with  a  sharpness  beyond  his  wont.  The  original 
draft  of  the  letter  has  been  found,  and  contains  even  stronger 
expressions,  which  on  consideration  he  struck  out.     The  tone 

Aureus  in  this  same  year,  1667.  His  family  is  a  remarkable  example  of  hereditary 
talent  ;  his  son  and  grandson  were  both  eminent  as  physicians  in  France,  where 
the  son  settled  early  in  life  ;  his  great  grandson  (1715-1771)  was  the  philosopher 
by  whom  the  name  is  best  known. 

•  Ep.  75  b.     Van  Vloten,  Suppl.  p.  318. 

-  Balthasar,  afterwards  Isaac  Orobio  de  Castro  (circ.  1620-1687)  was  of  a  New 
Christian  family,  and  had  lived  many  years  in  Spain,  where  he  was  a  distinguished 
physician.  He  fell  into  suspicion  of  Judaism,  and  was  imprisoned  and  tortured 
by  the  Inquisition,  and  finally  banished  from  Spain.  A  ter  spending  some  time 
in  France,  he  settled  in  Amsterdam  and  professed  himself  a  Jew.  He  became 
well  known  as  a  controversial  writer,  and  was  the  author  of  a  critique  on  one  of 
Spinoza's  critics,  whom  he  charged  with  being  himself  a  Spinozist.  {Cerlamen 
Philosophicum,  etc.  Bibliogr.  loS,  209).     Gratz,  x.  202. 

»  Ep.  48. 

F 


66  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

of  this  letter  shows  us  an  aspect  of  Spinoza's  character  which 
we  could  ill  afford  to  miss.  His  indignation  is  not  the  mere 
intellectual  disgust  of  a  philosopher  at  the  stupidity  of  an  un- 
reasonable critic,  it  is  the  moral  resentment  of  a  man  loving 
truth  and  righteousness  at  the  imputation  of  teaching  what  he 
abhors.  It  seems  well  to  give  here  a  considerable  part  of 
the  letter. 

'  He  begins  with  saying  it  concerns  him  little  to  know  what 
is  my  nation  or  way  of  life.  If  he  had  known  it,  he  would 
not  have  so  easily  convinced  himself  that  I  teach  atheism.  It 
is  the  character  of  atheists  to  seek  rank  and  wealth  beyond 
measure,  things  which  I  have  ever  despised,  as  all  know  who 
are  acquainted  with  me.  .  .  .  Then  he  proceeds  :  In  order  to 
avoid  the  reproach  of  superstition^  he  seems  to  me  to  have  cast 
off  religio7i  altogether.  What  this  writer  means  by  religion 
and  what  by  superstition,  I  know  not.  Does  he,  I  would 
ask,  cast  off  all  religion  who  affirms  that  God  is  to  be 
accepted  for  the  chief  good,  and  that  as  such  he  is  to  be  loved 
with  a  free  affection }  that  in  this  only  consists  our  per- 
fect happiness  and  perfect  liberty  ?  more,  that  the  reward  of 
virtue  is  virtue  itself,  and  the  punishment  of  folly  and  vice  is 
folly  itself.''  and,  lastly,  that  every  man's  duty  is  to  love  his 
neighbour  and  to  obey  the  commands  of  the  supreme  power } 
These  things  I  have  not  only  said,  but  proved  by  most  solid 
reasons.  But  methinks  I  see  in  what  mud  this  fellow  sticks.' 
He  finds,  it  should  seem,  nothing  to  please  him  in  virtue  and 
knowledge  by  themselves,  and  he  would  choose  to  live  by  the 
mere  impulse  of  his  passions  but  for  this  one  difficulty,  that 
he  fears  the  penalty.  So  he  abstains  from  ill  deeds  and 
follows  God's  commandments  like  a  slave,  unwilling  and  with  a 
hesitating  mind,  and  for  this  service  looks  to  be  rewarded  by 
God  with  gifts  far  more  grateful  to  him  than  the  love  of  God 
itself;  so  much  the  more,  I  say,  as  he  finds  the  more  distaste 

'   '  Quo  in  luto  hie  homo  haereat.'     Spinoza  was  scholar  enough  to  know  the 
classical  force  of  homo  in  controversial  usage,  and  I  think  he  intended  it. 


SPINOZA'S   CORRESPONDENCE.  67 

and  repugnance  in  well-doing.  And  thus  it  comes  about  that 
in  his  conceit  all  men  who  are  not  restrained  by  this  fear 
must  live  without  discipline  and  cast  off  all  religion.  But  I 
leave  this,  and  pass  to  his  conclusions  where  he  would  fain 
show  that  I  teach  atheism  by  covert  and glozing  arguments. 

'  The  foundation  of  his  reasoning  is  this,  that  he  thinks  I 
take  away  God's  freedom,  and  make  him  subject  to  fate  : 
which  is  manifestly  false.  For  I  have  affirmed  that  all  things 
follow  of  inevitable  necessity  from  God's  nature  no  otherwise 
than  all  affirm  that  it  follows  from  God's  nature  that  he 
understands  himself.  This  surely  no  one  denies  to  follow 
necessarily  from  God's  nature,  and  yet  no  one  conceives  that  God 
understands  himself  under  any  compulsion  of  fate,  but  rather 
that  he  does  so  with  entire  freedom,  tliough  necessarily.  .  .  . 

'  This  inevitable  necessity  of  things  destroys  neither  divine 
nor  human  law.  For  moral  precepts,  whether  they  have  the 
form  of  law  from  God  himself  [i.e.  by  direct  revelation]  or  not, 
are  yet  divine  and  wholesome  ;  and  the  good  which  ensues 
from  virtue  and  the  love  of  God,  whether  we  take  it  from 
God  as  a  judge  [a  political  superior  issuing  distinct  com- 
mands] or  as  flowing  from  the  necessity  of  God's  nature,  will 
be  neither  mere  nor  less  desirable ;  as  on  the  other  hand  the 
evil  which  ensues  from  evil  deeds  is  not  therefore  less  to  be 
feared  because  it  so  comes  of  necessity :  in  short,  whether 
our  actions  be  necessary  or  free,  our  motives  are  still  hope 
and  fear.  Therefore  his  assertion  is  false,  that  /  zvonld  leave 
no  room  for  precepts  and  commands,  or,  as  he  says  later,  that 
there  is  no  expectation  of  retuard  or  pnnisJiment  when  every- 
thing is  ascribed  to  fate,  and  it  is  settled  that  all  things  proceed 
from  God  by  inevitable  necessity.  .  .  . 

'  It  were  too  long  to  review  all  the  passages  which  show  that 
he  was  in  no  sober  mood  when  he  formed  his  judgment  of 
me.  Wherefore  I  pass  to  his  conclusion,  where  he  says  that 
/  /iave  left  myself  no  argument  to  prove  that  MaJiomet  was  not 
a  true  trotJiet.     And  this  he  endeavours  to  show  from  my 

F  2 


68  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

principles,  whereas  it  plainly  follows  from  them  that  Mahomet 
was  an  impostor.  For  that  liberty  which  is  granted  by  the 
catholic  religion,  as  revealed  by  the  light  of  both  nature  and 
prophecy,  and  which  I  have  shown  is  most  fit  to  be  granted, 
is  by  him  wholly  done  away.  But  if  this  were  not  so,  am  I 
concerned,  I  pray  you,  to  show  that  such  and  such  a  prophet 
is  a  false  one  ?  On  the  contrary,  the  burden  lay  on  the 
prophets  to  show  that  they  were  truly  such.  If  he  should  reply 
that  Mahomet  also  taught  God's  law,  and  gave  sure  tokens 
of  his  mission,  as  the  other  prophets  did,  then  I  grant  there 
will  be  no  cause  for  him  to  deny  that  Mahomet  was  a  true 
prophet. 

'  For  the  Turks  themselves  and  heathens  in  general,  if 
they  worship  God  by  justice  and  charity  to  their  neighbours, 
I  believe  that  they  have  the  spirit  of  Christ  and  are  saved, 
whatever  persuasion  they  may  entertain  through  ignorance 
concerning  Mahomet  and  their  oracles. 

'You  see,  my  friend,  how  far  from  the  truth  your  corre- 
spondent has  wandered.  Nevertheless  I  admit  that  he  has 
done  no  injury  to  me,  but  much  to  himself,  when  he  scruples 
not  to  affirm  that  /  teacJi  atheism  with  covert  and  glosing 
argimients. 

'  I  do  not  think  you  will  find  anything  in  this  that  you 
can  judge  too  harsh  in  its  terms  towards  this  writer.  But  if 
you  light  on  any  such  thing  I  beg  you  to  strike  it  out,  or  else 
amend  it  as  you  shall  think  fit.  I  have  no  mind  to  anger  him, 
whoever  he  may  be,  or  make  myself  enemies  by  my  work ,; 
and  because  this  commonly  happens  in  disputations  of  this 
sort,  I  could  scarce  bring  myself  to  answer  him,  nor  could  I 
have  done  so  unless  I  had  promised  you.' ' 

This  protest  is  strong  and  even  vehement  in  its  terms,  and 
there  is  not  the  least  reason  to  doubt  its  sincerity.  It  has  an 
important  bearing  on  that  part  of  Spinoza's  sentiments  of 
which  it  is  peculiarly  difficult  to  form  an  exact  estimate,  I 

'  Ep.  49. 


sriXOZA'S   CORRESPONDENCE.  69 

mean  his  relation  to  religious  belief  in  general.  We  shall 
have  to  consider  in  another  place  the  effect  of  his  philoso- 
phical systenn,  taken  in  itself,  on  religion  as  usually  under- 
stood. His  own  interpretation  of  his  philosophy  is  on  that 
question  material  but  not  conclusive  :  here  it  comes  before  us 
as  a  point  in  his  personal  character.  It  is  evident  that  he 
considered  religion  as  something  very  real  in  man's  life,  and 
the  charge  of  irreligion  or  atheism  as  the  grossest  and  most 
wicked  of  calumnies.  But  this  religion,  as  he  understands  it, 
is  not  the  religion  of  churches  and  sects.  It  is  independent 
of  dogmatic  theology,  independent  of  any  particular  know- 
ledge or  belief  as  to  revelation,  independent  even  of  the 
so-called  natural  theology  which  holds  to  the  conception  of 
God  as  a  Person  after  all  other  definitions  of  his  nature  have 
been  renounced,  and  to  the  expectation  of  another  life  which 
shall  redress  the  balance  of  the  present  one  in  some  manner 
of  which  all  specific  knowledge  is  disclaimed.  Tbe__essence  of 
religion  is  in  Spinoza's  mind  a  cheerful  and  willing  co-operation 
with  the  order  of  the  world  as  manifested  in  the  nature  of 
man  and  of  society.  Irreligion  is  the  self-seeking  spirit  to 
which  the  love  that  is  its  own  reward  is  unknown.  The 
atheist  is  the  man  who  has  nothing  better  to  pursue  than  the 
satisfaction  of  his  own  vulgar  appetites,  whose  only  plan  of 
life  is  '  honores  et  divitias  supra  modum  quaerere.'  Xlia  true 
and  saving  worship  is  to  do  justice  and  love  one's  neighbour. 
And  observe  that  Spinoza  does  not  put  this  as  something 
beside  or  opposed  to  religion  ;  he  speaks  of  it  as  religion 
itself,  and  regards  definite  religious  beliefs  (in  the  popular 
sense)  as  things  in  themselves  comparatively  indifferent,  but 
good  in  so  far  as  they  serve  as  a  vehitle,  so  to  speak,  for  the 
essential  virtues  of  love  and  well-doing. 

His  attitude  towards  Christianity— not  the  dogmas  of 
Catholic  or  Reformed  divines,  but  the  '  spirit  of  Christ '  which 
men  may  have  in  intellectual  and  historical  ignorance — 
is   one  of  respect    and    even  reverence.     In  the  '  Tractatus 


70  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Theologico-Politicus '  one  is  not  absolutely  safe  in  relying  on 
expressions  of  this  kind,  as  the  treatise  is  framed  throughout 
on  an  accommodating  and  hypothetical  plan,  which  gives 
occasion  for  a  certain  vein  of  irony.  But  in  this  letter  he  is 
writing  to  the  Jew  Orobio,  an  escaped  and  living  witness  of 
the  tender  mercies  of  the  Inquisition,  who,  even  if  he  shared 
the  liberal  tendencies  of  many  members  of  the  Amsterdam 
synagogue,  would  not  be  specially  pleased  by  compliments 
to  Christianity.  And  it  is  very  certain  that  Spinoza  did  not  go 
out  of  his  way  to  please  Van  Velthuysen,  for  whose  reading 
the  reply  was  ultimately  intended. 

The  tone  of  the  Tractatus  and  of  Spinoza's  remarks  in 
divers  passages  of  other  writings  is  indeed  strongly  anti- 
clerical. Spinoza  regards  clerical  influence  as  a  bad  thing, 
not  so  much  on  the  ground  that  it  is  wrong  to  teach  with 
authority  and  as  absolutely  certain  that  which  is  false  or 
doubtful,  as  because  such  influence  tends  to  disturb  the  order 
of  society  and  diminish  respect  for  the  civil  law.  Hence  the 
peculiar  hostility  with  which  Spinoza  has  been  pursued  by 
professional  theologians.  Rut  as  regards  individual  belief 
there  is  nothing  irreligious  or  anti-religious  to  be  found  in 
him.  He  would  never  have  consented  to  his  name  being 
inscribed  on  the  banner  of  a  materialist  crusade. 

Notwithstanding  the  sharpness  of  this  first  passage  of 
arms,  Van  Velthuysen  and  Spinoza  came  into  direct  commu- 
nication afterwards,  and  on  terms  of  mutual  respect,  if  not 
friendship.  There  is  a  letter^  from  Spinoza  to  Velthuysen 
concerning  his  intention  of  publishing,  together  with  some 
explanatory  notes  to  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,' 
certain  papers  which  appear  to  be  no  other  than  the  corre- 
spondence we  have  just  had  before  us.  The  letter  seems  to 
be  one  of  a  series  of  at  least  two  or  three,  and  to  have  been 
preserved  only  by  accident.  I  give  it  here,  however,  for  the 
fine  sense  of  literary  courtesy  which  it  shows. 

'  Ep.  75. 


SPINOZA'S   CORRESPONDENCE.  71 

'  I  am  surprised  at  our  friend  Neustadt  having  told  you 
that  I  thought  of  replying  to  the  writings  against  my  treatise 
which  have  been  published  for  some  time  past,  and  intended 
to  include  your  MS.  in  the  number.  I  am  sure  I  nev^er 
intended  to  refute  any  of  my  opponents,  so  little  did  any  of 
them  seem  to  me  worth  an  answer.  All  I  remember  to 
have  said  to  Mr.  Neustadt  is  that  I  purposed  to  publish  some 
notes  explaining  the  more  difficult  passages  of  the  treatise, 
and  to  add  to  these  your  MS.  and  my  answer,  if  I  had  your 
leave  for  so  doing.  This  I  desired  him  to  ask  of  you,  and  added 
that  in  case  you  should  be  unwilling  to  grant  it  on  the  score 
of  certain  expressions  in  the  answer  being  rather  severe,  you 
should  be  at  full  liberty  either  to  amend  or  to  cancel  them. 
Meanwhile  I  have  no  cause  of  offence  against  Mr.  N.  ;  but  I 
thought  it  well  to  show  you  the  real  state  of  the  case,  so  that, 
if  I  cannot  obtain  your  leav^e,  I  might  at  least  make  it  clear 
that  I  had  no  manner  of  design  to  publish  your  MS.  against 
your  will.  I  believe,  indeed,  it  may  be  done  without  any  risk 
to  your  reputation,  provided  your  name  is  not  affixed  to  it  ; 
but  I  will  do  nothing  unless  you  grant  me  leave  and  licence 
to  publish  it.  But  I  am  free  to  confess  you  would  do  me 
a  far  greater  favour  if  you  would  set  down  the  arguments 
with  which  you  think  you  can  attack  my  treatise,  and  add 
them  to  your  MS. ;  and  this  I  most  heartily  beseech  you  to 
do.  There  is  no  one  whose  arguments  I  should  be  more 
willing  to  consider,  for  I  am  aware  that  your  only  motive  is 
affection  for  the  truth,  and  I  know  the  candour  of  your  mind  ; 
in  the  name  of  which  I  again  entreat  you  not  to  decline 
giving  yourself  this  trouble.' 

The  scheme  here  mentioned  was  not  carried  out,  and  a 
year  or  two  afterwards  Van  Velthuysen  published  his  argu- 
ments as  an  independent  work.  It  is  one  of  the  polemics 
against  Spinoza  mentioned  with  approbation  by  Colerus. 

Leibnitz,  who  after  Spinoza's  death  joined  the  popular  cry 
against  him,  appears  in  his  lifetime  among  the  list  of  his 


72  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

correspondents.  In  167 1  he  wrote  to  him,  enclosing  for  his 
opinion  a  note  on  the  improvement  of  lenses.  He  addresses 
him  as  an  expert  of  well-known  standing  and  authority  : 
'  Among  your  other  merits  known  to  fame,  I  understand  that 
you  have  excellent  skill  in  optics,  which  persuades  me  to 
address  to  you  my  essay,  such  as  it  is,  as  I  shall  not  easily 
find  a  better  critic  than  yourself  in  this  kind  of  inquiry.' 
Spinoza  replied  courteously,  and  offered  to  send  Leibnitz 
a  copy  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  if  he  had, not 
one  already.', 

In  1675  we  hear  that  Tschirnhausen  (of  whom  presently) 
had  met  in  Paris  '  a  man  of  excellent  learning,  accomplished 
in  many  sciences,  and  likewise  free  from  vulgar  theological 
prejudice,  byname  Leibnitz,'  who  thought  very  highly  of  the 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  and  had  (if  he  remembered 
right)  written  about  it  to  Spinoza.^  Tschirnhausen  thought 
he  might  safely  be  trusted  with  Spinoza's  writings  {i.e.,  the 
Ethics  in  MS.),  and  that,  for  reasons  he  could  explain  on 
occasion,  it  would  be  well  worth  Spinoza's  while.  The 
answer  to  this  overture  was  however  more  cautious  than 
might  have  been  expected.  Spinoza  wrote  to  the  friend 
through  whom  it  had  been  communicated  that  he  thought  he 
already  knew  this  Leibnitz  by  correspondence,  but  could  not 
tell  what  he  was  doing  in  Fran:e,  From  his  letters  he  judged 
him  to  be  an  accomplished  and  liberal-minded  man,  but  he 
thought  it  imprudent  to  trust  him  with  the  unpublished  work 
without  knowing  more  of  him.  On  the  whole  he  would  await 
a  further  report  from  Tschirnhausen.^ 

Leibnitz  afterwards,  on  his  way  home  from  Paris,  paid  a 
visit  to  Spinoza.  Whether  they  talked  philosophy  does  not 
appear.  Leibnitz  himself  represented  the  conversation  as 
having  been  an  ordinary  if  not  trifling  one,  in  which  Spinoza 

'  Epp.  51,  52. 

*  There  is  no.  such  matter  in  Leibnitz's  one  extant  letter  to  Spinoza. 

'  Ep.  d^b  (to  Dr.  Schaller  of  Amsterdam),  Suppl.  p.  317. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  73 

told  him  some  amusing  stories  about  the  poHtics  of  the  time.' 
He  doubtless  thought  it  necessary  to  avoid  the  suspicion  of 
having  had  too  much  to  do  with  the  heretic  Spinoza, 
and  prudent  to  make  a  sort  of  apology  for  "having  visited 
him  at  all.  Leibnitz's  depreciation  of  Spinoza's  merits  in 
philosophy  was  such  as  to  speak  ill  either  for  his  penetration 
or  for  his  candour. 

In  the  last  two  years  of  Spinoza's  life  we  have  a  series  of 
important  philosophical  letters  which  bring  him,  as  we  now 
know,  into  relation  with  one  of  the  men  who  in  the  following 
generation  were  diligent  in  extending  the  domain  of  science. 
Ehrenfried  Walter  von  Tschirnhausen  (165  1-1708)  was  of  a 
noble  Bohemian  family,  and  later  in  life  attained  high  distinc- 
tion in  mathematics  and  physics,  and  was  at  a  comparatively 
early  age  admitted  to  the  French  Academy  of  Sciences.  He 
became  especially  known  by  his  improvements  in  the 
construction  of  lenses  and  burning  glasses,  with  which  he 
produced  extraordinary  effects,  and  his  name  has  left  a  per- 
manent place  in  mathematics  by  his  investigation  of  the  class 
of  curves  known  as  caustics.  The  foundation  of  his  scientific 
taste  was  laid  during  his  studies  at  the  university  of  Leyden, 
and  we  may  well  suppose  that  it  was  on  the  special  ground  of 
optics  that  he  first  sought  Spinoza's  acquaintance.  When  we 
meet  with  him  in  the  letters  he  is  already  on  the  footing  of  an 
old  friend.  His  name  was  suppressed  by  the  editors  of  the 
'  Opera  Posthuma,'  like  those  of  several  other  of  Spinoza's 
correspondents,  and  his  part,  formerly  attributed  by  conjecture 
to  Dr.  Meyer,  has  only  been  restored  to  him  since  the  full 
text  of  these  letters  was  published  by  Van  Vloten.  He  did 
not,  like  Leibnitz,  turn  against  Spinoza's  memory  ;  but 
neither  did  he  make  any  open  attempt  to  vindicate  it.  The 
work  by  which  he  is  best  known,  '  Medicina  Mentis  '  (Amster- 
dam, 1687),  draws  largely  and  tacitly  on  Spinoza's  treatise 

'   '  Anecdota  non  contemnenda  de  rebus  illius  temporis.'     See  Spin.  Oj>.  ed. 
Paulus,  2.  672  sqq.  ;  and  cf.  Van  Vloten,  Supp.  p.  307. 


74  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

on  the  *  Amendment  of  the  Understanding.'  The  borrowing 
is  of  an  extent  which  in  our  more  scrupulous  age  would  amply 
warrant  a  charge  of  plagiary  ;  but  when  we  consider  the  lax 
habits  of  the  time  in  this  respect,  and  the  prejudice  which 
any  open  reference  to  Spinoza  would  certainly  have  excited 
against  Tschirnhausen's  work,  we  should  be  at  least  cautious 
in  blaming  him.  If  his  object  was  to  gain  a  hearing  for 
Spinoza's  ideas  among  the  respectable  public,  there  can  be  no 
doubt  that  the  course  he  adopted  was  the  most  plausible  if  not 
the  only  practicable  one.  At  the  same  time  it  is  certain  that 
Tschirnhausen,  without  any  such  excuse,  gave  some  offence 
to  both  Huygens  and  Leibnitz  by  his  use  of  unpublished 
matter  which  they  had  communicated  to  him.^ 

Tschirnhausen  was  an  eager  student  of  Descartes,  and 
also  of  Spinoza's  yet  unpublished  writings.  In  1675-6  he 
made  a  journey  to  London,  where  he  exerted  himself  with 
success  to  remove  an  ill  opinion  which  Boyle  and  Oldenburg 
had  formed  of  the  'Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  '  and  of 
Spinoza  himself;  and  on  his  way  back  he  stayed  in  Paris, 
and,  as  we  have  seen,  made  the  acquaintance  of  Leibnitz. 
During  this  time  he  exchanged  letters  with  Spinoza  on 
several  metaphysical  points.  His  questions  and  objections 
were  the  most  deserving  of  attention  of  any  that  Spinoza 
had  received.  They  are  always  intelligent,  and  one  or  two 
are  so  acute  and  forcibly  put  that  it  would  be  difficult  for  a 
modern  critic  to  improve  upon  them.  Even  an  uncritical 
reader  may  perceive  strong  evidence  of  their  aptness  in  the 
fact  that  Spinoza  himself  found  considerable  difficulty  in 
meeting  them.  Tschirnhausen's  power  of  appreciation  and 
criticism  does  not  seem  however  to  have  been  accompanied 
by  much  capacity  for  original  work  in  philosophy.  He  en- 
tertained an  exaggerated  notion  of  the  advances  in  physical 
discovery  which  might  be  secured  by  an  a  priori  doctrine  of 
method.     We  already  see  traces  of  this  in  his  correspondence 

'  Van  Moten,  Benedict  us  de  Spinoza^  App.  III. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  75 

with  Spinoza,  and  at  a  later  time  his  too  sanguine  expecta- 
tions were  gently  rebuked  by  Huygens.'  But  with  all  allow- 
ances for  errors  of  judgment  and  other  human  infirmities,  his 
career  was  a  useful  and  honourable  one,  and  to  have  been 
Tschirnhausen's  master  is  no  contemptible  addition  to 
Spinoza's  memory. 

There  is  yet  one  correspondent  to  be  recorded  who  stands 
alone.  In  the  autumn  of  1675  Spinoza  received  a  strange 
epistle  ^  dated  from  Florence,  and  written  by  one  Albert 
Burgh,  now  believed  to  be  the  same  pupil  and  companion 
whose  facilities  of  intercourse  with  Spinoza  were  so  much 
envied  by  Simon  de  Vries,  and  of  whose  temper  and  capacities 
Spinoza,  in  writing  to  De  Vries,  expressed  a  very  doubtful 
opinion.  He  now  announced  that  he  had  been  received  into 
the  fold  of  the  Catholic  Church  ;  the  particular  circumstances 
of  his  conversion  might  be  seen  in  a  letter  he  had  written  to 
Professor  Craane  of  Leyden ;  his  present  purpose  was  to  offer  a 
few  remarks  important  for  Spinoza's  own  welfare.  And  with 
that  he  launched  forth  at  no  small  length  into  denunciation 
of  Spinoza's  profane  and  chimerical  philosophy,  mixed  with 
compassion  (of  the  right  ecclesiastical  sort)  for  the  wretched 
estate  of  his  soul  if  he  should  persist  in  his  damnable  errors. 
He  marvels  how  a  man  of  Spinoza's  abilities,  eager  in  the 
pursuit  of  truth,  could  let  himself  be  so  deceived  by  the  devil. 
'  You  assume,'  he  asks  with  delightful  simplicity,  '  that  you 
have  at  last  found  the  true  philosophy.  How  do  you  know 
that  your  philosophy  is  the  best  of  all  those  which  have  ever 
been  taught  in  the  world,  are  now  taught,  or  shall  ever  be 
taught  hereafter.''     To  say  nothing  of  what  may  be  devised 

'  See  their  correspondence  in  Van  Vloten's  Supplement,  which  is  in  many 
respects  curious.  Tschirnhausen's  statements  as  to  an  expected  pension  from  the 
Academy  of  Sciences,  and  the  amount  of  assistance  he  required  '  ad  studia  bona 
excolenda,'  show  that  the  endowment  of  research  is  no  new  invention.  Huygens' 
just  estimate  of  the  amount  of  inevitable  labour  still  lying  before  science  is  also 
worth  noting. 

'  Ep.  73. 


76  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

in  the  future,  have  you  examined  all  those  philosophies  both 
ancient  and  modern  which  are  taught  here,  in  India,  and  all 
the  world  over  ?  And  even  supposing  you  have  duly  ex- 
amined them,  how  do  you  know  that  you  have,  chosen  the 
best?  .  .  . 

'  Do  not  flatter  yourself,'  cries  the  triumphant  proselyte, 
*  with  the  reflection  that  the  Calvinists  or  so-called  Reformed 
divines, the  Lutherans,  the  Mennonites,  the  Socinians,  or  others 
cannot  refute  your  doctrines.  All  those  poor  creatures  are  as 
wretched  as  yourself,  and  sitting  along  with  you  in  the  shadow 
of  death.  How  dare  you  set  yourself  up  above  all  the 
patriarchs,  prophets,  apostles,  martyrs,  doctors,  and  confessors 
of  the  Church }  Miserable  man  and  worm  upon  the  earth 
that  you  are,  yea,  ashes  and  food  for  worms,  how  can  you 
confront  the  eternal  wisdom  with  your  unspeakable  blasphemy? 
What  foundation  have  you  for  this  rash,  insane,  deplorable, 
accursed  presumption  ?  What  devilish  pride  puffs  you  up  to 
pass  judgment  on  mysteries  which  Catholics  themselves  de- 
clare to  be  incomprehensible  ? '  This  and  much  more  of  the 
same  fashion  is  enforced  with  arguments  which  it  would  be 
intolerably  tedious  to  repeat.  One  of  them  however  may 
deserve  to  be  singled  out  :  it  is  that,  because  Julius  Caesar 
would  probably  have  laughed  at  a  prophecy  of  gunpowder,  it 
is  unreasonable  to  disbelieve  in  the  divining  rod,  alchemy, 
magic,  and  demonologj'.  Burgh  protests  that  he  has  written 
to  Spinoza  '  with  a  truly  Christian  intention  ;  first  that  you 
may  understand  the  love  I  bear  to  you,  though  a  heathen  ;  and 
next,  to  beseech  you  not  to  persist  in  perverting  others.' 
Finally  he  threatens  Spinoza  with  eternal  damnation  if  he 
does  not  repent  of  his  wicked  and  abominable  errors.  It  will 
be  remembered  that  the  immortal  discourse  of  Brother  Peter 
in  the  '  Tale  of  a  Tub '  ends  with  invoking  similar  consequences 
on  the  hearers  if  they  ofier  to  believe  otherwise ;  but  the 
I  genuine  crudity  of  Albert  Burgh's  effusion  hardly  leaves 
I    room  for  even  a  Swift  to  add  any  touch  of  caricature. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  77 

Spinoza  was  at  first  unwilling  to  make  any  answer  to  such 
an  attack.  But  some  common  friends,  who  had  known  Burgh 
and,  with  Spinoza,  hoped  better  things  of  him,  represented  that 
it  was  but  due  to  their  old  friendship  to  try  the  effect  of  re- 
monstrance. Being  once  prevailed  upon  to  write,  Spinoza  could 
not  but  show  his  sense  of  the  extreme  folly  and  insolence 
displayed  in  Burgh's  letter.  The  arrogance  of  it  would  have 
been  sufficiently  gross  if  addressed  to  a  Protestant ;  to  one 
who  had  never  professed  himself  a  Christian  at  all  it  was  ex- 
travagant. The  answer  is  far  the  sharpest  ever  written  by 
Spinoza.^  For  serious  argument  he  had  little  occasion  ;  the 
convert's  attack  on  what  he  called  chimerical  philosophy  was 
easily  answered  out  of  his  own  mouth. 

'  You  who  assume  that  you  have  at  last  found  the  best 
religion,  or  rather  the  best  teachers,  and  fixed  your  credulity 
on  them,  hozu  do  yoic  know  that  they  are  the  best  among  these 
who  have  taught  other  religions,  or  now  teach  or  shall  hereafter 
teach  them  ?  Have  you  examined  all  those  religions  both  ancient 
and  modern  which  are  taught  here  and  in  India  and  all  the  world 
over?  And  even  stipposing you  have  duly  examined  them,  hou 
do  you  know  that  you  have  chosen  the  best?  ' 

Spinoza  recalls  to  the  hot-headed  proselyte,  who  fancies 
that  Rome  has  a  monopoly  of  all  the  virtues,  that  in  Alva's 
persecution  his  own  ancestors  had  suffered  valiantly  for  the 
Protestant  religion.  The  historical  claims  of  the  Church  of 
Rome  are  met  not  with  direct  criticism  but  with  an  un- 
expected counter-attack. 

*As  for  what  you  add  touching  the  common  consent  of 
multitudes  of  men,  the  uninterrupted  continuance  of  the 
Church,  and  the  like,  that  is  the  very  same  old  tale  as  the 
Pharisees'.     They  bring  forward  their  myriad  witnesses  with 


'  Some  remarks  of  Leibnitz's  on  this  letter,  of  no  great  importance,  may  be 
found  at  the  end  of  M.  Foucher  de  Carcil's  Leibniz,  Descartes,  ei  Spinoza  ; 
and  some  sufficiently  absurd  reflections  by  the  admiring  editor  at  the  end  of  the 
•  Premier  Memoire '  in  the  same  volume. 


78  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

no  less  confidence  than  the  devotees  of  Rome,  and  those 
witnesses  repeat  their  traditions,  as  if  they  were  facts  within 
their  own  knowledge,  no  less  stoutly  than  the  Roman  ones. 
Their  lineage  they  carry  back  to  Adam.  They  boast  as 
proudly  as  any  that  their  Church  has  been  continued  to  this 
day,  and  stands  unshaken  in  spite  of  the  enmity  of  heathens 
and  Christians.  They  have  more  antiquity  for  them  than 
any  other  sect.  They  proclaim  with  one  voice  that  their 
tradition  comes  direct  from  God,  and  that  they  alone  possess 
the  word  of  God  both  written  and  unwritten.  It  cannot  be 
denied  that  all  heresies  have  branched  off  from  them,  while 
they  have  remained  firm  during  several  thousand  years  with 
no  political  power  to  compel  them,  but  in  the  mere  strength  of 
fanaticism.  The  miracles  they  report  would  weary  a  thousand 
nimble  tongues.  But  their  most  notable  claim  is  that  they 
count  far  more  martyrs  than  any  other  nation,  and  they  daily 
increase  the  number  of  those  who  have  with  .singular  con- 
stancy suffered  for  the  faith  they  profess  ;  and  this  is  no  fable. 
I  know  myself,  among  others,  of  one  Judah,  called  the  Believer, 
who  in  the  midst  of  the  fire,  when  he  was  supposed  already 
dead,  began  to  sing  the  psalm,  To  thee,  O  God,  I  commit  my 
souly  and  so  expired  singing  it.' 

'  The  discipline  of  the  Roman  Church,  which  you  so  much 
praise,  is,  I  confess,  politic  and  brings  gain  to  many.  I  should 
think,  indeed,  that  there  was  none  more  convenient  for 
deceiving  the  vulgar  and  subduing  men's  minds,  were  it  not 
for  the  discipline  of  the  Mahometan  Church,  which  far  excels 

'  This  was  Don  Lope  de  Vera  y  Alarcon  de  San  Clemente,  a  Spanish  nobleman 
who  was  converted  to  Judaism  through  the  study  of  Hebrew,  and  was  burnt  at 
Valladolid  on  the  25th  of  July,  1644.  Gratz,  Gesch.  derjudcn,  x.  loi.  Dr.  Gratz 
supposes  that  Spinoza  here  speaks  as  an  eye-witness,  and  must  consequently  have 
been  born  and  passed  his  youth  in  Spain.  But  the  sense  of  Spinoza's  words  is  amply 
satisfied  by  referring  them  to  the  notoriety  which  the  event  doubtless  had  among  the 
Jewish  congregation  of  Amsterdam.  It  cannot  be  suggested  that  in  §  3  Spinoza 
means  to  say  that  Burgh  had  witnessed  the  sufferings  of  his  own  ancestors  under 
the  Duke  of  Alva.  But  the  phrase  (parentes  tuos  nosti,  qui  .  .  .  ipse  quendam 
Judam  .  .   .  novi,  qui  .   .  .  )  is  exactly  the  same  in  both  cases. 


SPINOZA'S  CORRESPONDENCE.  79 

it.     For  since  that   superstition  had  its  rise,  no  schism  has 
taken  place  in  their  Church.' 

Spinoza  means,  I  suppose,  that  in  the  history  of  Islam 
there  is  no  great  doctrinal  rupture  comparable  to  the  Reforma- 
tion in  Europe.  He  must  have  known  from  his  study  of  the 
Jewish  philosophers,  who  abound  in  allusions  to  the  Arabic 
schools,  that  Mahometanism  has  no  lack  of  sects  to  show. 
It  shares  with  Judaism,  however,  the  advantage  of  never 
having  complicated  its  fundamental  formula.  But  under  the 
circumstances  Spinoza  could  not  be  expected  to  write  with 
minute  exactness,  even  if  he  were  capable  of  it.  A  broad  and 
rapid  presentation  of  things  was  the  only  instrument  that 
could  possibly  have  any  effect  on  Albert  Burgh's  sublime 
ignorance. 


8o  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER    III. 

IDEAS   AND   SOURCES   OF   SPINOZA'S   PHILOSOPHY. 

Laudemus  viros  gloriosos,  et  parentes  nostros  in  generatione  sua. — EcCLUS. 
xliv.  I. 

Lo,  thou  hast  learned  that  whosoever  tells  a  thing  in  the  name  of  him  that  said 
it  brings  redemption  to  the  world.— Pereq  R.  Meir  (in  C.  Taylor's  '  Sayings  of  the 
Jewish  Fathers'). 

Part  I. — Judaism  and  Neo-Platonism. 

The  time  has  passed  when  systems  of  philosophy  could  be 
regarded  as  final  and  absolute.  It  is  not  so  very  long  since 
it  was  assumed  as  a  matter  of  course  that  the  key  to  all  the 
secrets  of  the  universe  was  in  man's  hands,  and  that  only 
culpable  perversity  could  fail  to  find  it.  In  our  own  day  the 
nearest  approach  to  a  dogmatic  philosophy  of  the  old  pattern 
has  been  a  dciine  which  proceeds  on  the  systematic  assump- 
tion that  the  problems  of  philosophy  are  insoluble.  There 
are  some  who  find  in  this  state  of  things  the  death-warrant  of 
philosophy  itself,  and  thereupon  exult  or  revolt,  according  to 
their  temper,  as  at  a  matter  irrevocably  judged.  But  such  are 
over-hasty,  forgetting  that  the  change  which  has  come  over 
men's  view  of  the  great  problems  of  the  world  is  not  single  or 
casual,  but  is  the  last  step  in  a  vast  movement  of  human 
thought  which  has  profoundly  modified  our  whole  conception 
of  the  nature  and  limits  of  knowledge.  Science  has  for  good 
and  all  abandoned  the  dream  of  finality.  The  discoverer 
well  knows  that  his  discovery,  while  it  brings  new  certainty 
and  new  power  over  things,  will  also  throw  open  a  new  series 
of  questions.     In  the  first  flush  of  conquering  advance,  armed 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  8i 

with    instruments    whose    power    seemed    unbounded,    and 
mighty  in  their  new-born  freedom  of  mind,  the  leaders  of  the 
great  revival   saw  visions  of  a  goal   near  at  hand.     Let  the 
right  method  be  once  obtained,  and  a  few  simple  principles 
might  suffice  to  explain    the  Avhole   course    of  nature.     So 
thought  Descartes  and  his  ardent  followers,  among  whom  we 
have    already    seen    Spinoza's    friend    Tschirnhausen.       So 
thought  Leibnitz  even  after  the  warning  of  their  failures.     A 
few  more  cautious  workers,  with  the  prescience  which  only 
practical  experience   gives,  refused   to  be  dazzled   by  these 
magnificent  and  facile  promises.     Thus    Huygens  perceived 
that  the  course  which  lay  before  scientific  explorers  was  at 
best  a  long  and  arduous  one.     Thus  Newton  taught  the  world 
the  lesson  of  patient  exactness  by  his  great  example  of  self- 
denial.     But  the  world  is  slow  to  learn,  and  as  the  work  of 
science  grew  and  multiplied  it  admired  with  imperfect  know- 
ledge,   accepting   provisional    or   even    erroneous    results   as 
absolute  truth.     At  last  the  various  paths  of  science  were 
seen  to  converge  into  a  broad  road.    The  atomic  theory  brought  f^ 
chemistry  into  relation  with  general  physics,  and  the  ideas  of 
correlation  and  continuity  drew  together  the  several  branches 
of  physical  knowledge,  while  the  undulatory'  Irfeory  of  light 
opened  to  the  scientific  imagination  a  new  world  coextensive 
with  the  sensible  universe.     But  it  was  also  seen  that  this  was 
not  the  end  of  questionings,  but  the  beginning  of  new  and 
higher   questionings.     A    fresh    problem    arose  in  the  place 
of  every  one  that  had  been  solved  or  set  aside  :  and,  so  far 
from  resting  on  her  conquests,  science  only  girded  herself  for 
a  more  strenuous  continuance  of  the  campaign.     We  stand 
face  to  face  with  infinite  mysteries  in  the  things  we  see  and 
handle  ;  we  have  to  do  no  longer  with  inert  masses  pushed 
and  pulled  through  space  by  a  convenient  something  called 
Force,    but   myriadfold   complexities   of    rushing,    vibrating, 
pulsating  units,  each  of  them  endowed  with  a  definite  charac- 
ter and  persisting   in  it   against  the    assaults   of  the   whole 

G 


82  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.  . 

universe  ;  endless  motion,  shock  and  counter-shock,  taken  up 
and  reverberated  by  the  all- pervading  ether  ;  everywhere 
restless  activity,  and  changes  rapid  beyond  our  conception, 
though  numbered  and  measured  in  our  calculations ;  a  new 
and  immense  variety  in  the  manifestations  of  nature,  a 
boundless  and  unexplored  wealth  in  her  powers.  The  very 
elements  of  our  physical  knowledge  are  transformed.  Only  a 
few  years  ago  we  talked  of  Matter  and  Force  as  if  they  were 
things  obvious  and  within  our  grasp.  The  doctrine  of  Energy 
has  come  to  tell  us  that  even  in  the  elements  we  must  always 
be  learning  afresh.  Descartes,  and  Spinoza  after  him,  spoke^ 
of  Motion  as  if  it  were  a  real  thing.  Down  to  the  present 
time  we  have  been  brought  up  to  speak  of  Force  as  if  it  were 
a  real  thing.  Now  Force  has  become  either  a  mere  compen- 
dious symbol  in  the  description  of  motion,  or  a  worse  than  idle 
name  to  hide  our  ignorance ;  and  matter  is  almost  reduced  to 
a  vehicle  for  Energy.  Yet  the  certainty  of  the  natural  sciences 
is  not  shaken,  nor  is  the  ardour  of  research  abated.  We  still 
seek  knowledge,  knowing  that  when  we  have  found  it  we  shall 
have  to  seek  still  farther. 

Was  it  any  wonder,  then,  that  philosophy,  having  not  only 
the  difficulties  of  scientific  inquiry  to  contend  with,  but  other 
peculiar  ones  differing  in  kind  from  those  encountered  in  the 
natural  sciences,  should  be  slower  to  enter  into  the  critical 
period  in  which  knowledge  becomes  conscious  of  its  provi- 
sional character  .•'  Is  it  surprising,  on  the  other  hand,  that 
philosophy  also  should  at  last  conform  to  the  conditions 
that  science  has  already  recognized  .'*  And  if  it  does  submit 
to  those  conditions,  why  should  its  work  become  fruitless  or 
worthless  any  more  than  the  work  of  science .''  We  can  see, 
indeed,  that  it  is  not  so.  There  are  no  longer  Platonist  and 
Aristotelian  schools,  but  Plato  and  Aristotle  are  more  exactly 
studied,  more  truly  honoured  and  revered,  than  they  ever 
were  in  the  days  when  men  blindly  worshipped  them. 
The  same  is  true,  though  less  conspicuously  true,  of  the  great 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  83 

names  of  more  modern  times.  Kant  certainly  has  disciple 
who  may  be  called  after  his  name  ;  but  that  would  be  a  very 
shallow  estimate  which  should  reckon  the  power  of  Kant  in 
philosophy  by  the  number  of  professed  Kantians  in  the  world. 
For  the  work  done  by  Kant  was  not  that  he  established  this 
and  that  proposition  about  the  mental  mechanism  of  percep- 
tion and  thought,  but  that  he  announced  the  entry  of  philo- 
sophy into  her  critical  age.  His  own  application  of  the  critical 
method  may  or  may  not  be  correct,  it  may  or  may  not  be 
complete  ;  but  his  work  stands  nevertheless.  Ardent  and 
strenuous  thinkers  began  to  strive  against  it  when  it  was 
barely  finished  ;  they  have  striven  ever  since  to  find  some 
form  in  which  dogmatic  philosophy  could  be  revived,  and 
they  have  all  striven  in  vain.  The  harvest  of  the  '  Critique  of 
Pure  Reason '  is  reaped  by  hundreds  and  thousands  who 
know  nothing  of  the  Categories  and  Antinomies.  It  is  not 
systems  that  make  the  life  of  philosophy,  but  the  ideas  of 
which  systems  are  the  perishable  framework  ;  and  the  phi- 
losopher's place  among  his  fellows  is  determined  not  by 
counting  the  heads  of  those  who  accept  his  system  as  a  whole, 
but  by  the  strength  and  fruitfulness  of  the  ideas  which  he 
sets  astir  in  men's  minds. 

In    every  scheme  of  philosophy,    then,  which    is  worth 
serious  consideration,  there  is  a  vital  core  of  ideas  embodied 
in  a  frame  of  more  or  less  artificial  construction.     It  is  the 
task  of  the  history  of  philosophy  to  trace  from  generation  to 
generation  the  life  and  growth  of  these  underlying  ideas  ;  to 
disengage  them   from  their  local  and  temporary  incidents  ; 
and  thereby  to  keep  a  clear  pathway  for  the  work  of  philoso- 
phy itself    This  is  the  spirit  in  which  we  would  fain  approach 
that  splendid  effort  of  constructive  genius  which  Spinoza  has 
left  us  in  his  '  Ethics  ; '  not  with  a  minute  curiosity  seeking 
for   mere    curiosity's  sake  to  retrace  each    individual   stone 
of  his  building  to  the  quarry  whence  he  may  have  hewn  it, 
nor   yet  with    the   incurious    and    barren    admiration   which 


G  2 


84  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

forgets  that  even  the  loftiest  genius  is  conditioned  by  the 
materials  given  to  the  workman's  hand.  It  has  been  said  of 
Spinoza  that  his  theory  was  after  all  but  a  system,  and  that 
like  all  other  systems  it  has  passed  away  never  to  come  back. 
Such  a  charge,  if  a  charge  it  be,  M'^e  can  freely  afford  to  admit. 
Spinoza  did  not  seek  to  found  a  sect,  and  he  founded  none. 
Nay,  we  will  go  farther  ;  it  is  at  least  doubtful  whether  a 
single  person  can  be  named  who  has  accepted  the  system  of 
the  '  Ethics '  in  all  points  as  it  stands.  But  that  is  because 
Spinoza's  mind  is  abc(ve  the  level  of  the  people  who  hunger 
and  thirst  after  systems  ;  and  for  that  very  reason  the  thought 
of  Spinoza's  '  Ethics '  has  slowly  but  surely  interpenetrated 
the  thought  of  the  world,  and  even  now  works  mightily  in  it, 
while  other  systems  welcomed  in  their  own  day  as  new  reve- 
lations are  now  in  very  truth  past  and  forgotten.  Or  are 
we  to  go,  perchance,  in  search  of  systems  which  have  not 
passed  away }  Assuredly  such  are  to  be  found  :  they  drag 
on  their  barren  life,  a  fixed  monotony  of  centuries,  in  the 
schools  of  Brahmans  and  Buddhists  and  Confucians,  who 
have  drained  off  the  life-giving  words  of  their  ancient  masters 
into  labyrinthine  canals  and  stagnant  pools.  There  in  the- 
overteemed  East  is  the  limbo  of  unchangeable  systems,  pre- 
served from  the  fertilizing  breath  of  change  by  a  universal 
inertia.  If  Spinoza's  philosophy  were  identical,  as  not  a  few 
shallow  critics  have  fancied,  with  Indian  pantheism  or  indif- 
ferentism,  then  Spinozism  would  be  an  existing,  unchanged, 
and  unshaken  system  ;  but  such  an  existence  and  such 
security  are  the  death  of  philosophy. 

In  order  to  consider  the  origin  and  growth  of  Spinoza's 
philosophical  ideas,  it  will  be  necessary  to  anticipate  to  some 
extent  our  account  of  his  finished  doctrine.  The  first  and 
leading  idea  in  Spinoza's  philosophy— the  only  part  of  it,  in 
^  fact,  which  has  at  all  entered  into  the  notion  commonly  formed 
of  his  system— is  that  of  the  unity  and  uniformity  of  the 
world.     Nature,  as  conceived  by  him,  includes  thought  no  less 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  85 

than  things,  and  the  order  of  nature  knows  no  interruption. 
Again,  there  is  not  a  world  of  thought  opposed  to  or  inter- 
fering with  a  world  of  things  ;  we  have  everywhere  the  same 
reality  under  different  aspects.  Nature  is  one  as  well  as  uni- 
form. Now  there  is  a  thing  to  be  well  marked  about  this 
conception  of  Spinoza's  ;  it  is  itself  two-sided,  having  an  ideal 
or  speculative,  and  a  physical  or  scientific  aspect.  On  the 
one  hand  we  find  a  line  of  reasoning  derived  from  the  meta- 
physical treatment  of  theology  ;  in  other  words,  a  philosophy 
starting  from  the  consideration  of  the  nature  and  perfection  of 
God.  On  the  other  hand,  we  find  a  view  of  the  existing  universe 
guarded  by  the  requirements  of  exact  natural  science,  so 
that  the  philosopher  who  follows  this  track  is  bound  over  to 
see  that  his  speculation,  whatever  flights  it  may  take,  shall  at 
all  events  not  contradict  physics.  The  combination  of  these 
two  elements  is  one  of  the  most  characteristic  features  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy.  No  one  had  before  him  attempted 
such  a  combination  with  anything  like  the  same  knowledge 
of  the  conditions  of  the  task.  Few  have  even  after  him  been 
so  courageous  and  straightforward  in  the  endeavour.  The 
pantheist  or  mystical  element,  as  we  may  call  it  (though 
both  terms  are  ambiguous  and  liable  to  abuse),  is  not  merely 
placed  beside  the  scientific  element,  but  fused  into  one  with 
it.  Here,  then,  is  a  twofold  root  of  Spinoza's  conception  of 
the  universe,  and  each  branch  of  it  calls  for  an  account  of  the 
soil  that  nourished  it. 

The  greater  part  of  Spinoza's  '  Ethics '  is  occupied  with 
the  application  of  his  general  ideas  to  investigating  the  nature 
of  man.  The  body  and  the  mind  are  not  treated  as  two  se- 
parate entities  working  upon  one  another,  much  less  is  the 
one  allowed  to  be  the  product  of  the  other.  Mind  and  body 
are  in  truth  one  and  the  same.  That  which  is  mind  to  the 
inner  sense  is  (or  if  accessible  would  be)  body  to  the  outer 
sense.  There  is  no  mind  without  body  ;  but  also  there  is  no 
body  without  mind.     Physical  and  mental  events  run  exactly 


86  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

parallel  to  one  another  ;  the  physical  sequence  cannot  inter-t 
fere  with  the  mental  sequence,  or  the  mental  with  the  phy- 
sical, just  because  they  are  two  sides  of  the  same  thing.  Such 
is  the  metaphysical  theory  which  determines  Spinoza's  psy- 
chology. It  is  implied  in,  and  directly  deduced  from,  his 
general  view  of  the  world ;  but  it  is  convenient  to  speak  of  it 
separately,  for  reasons  which  will  appear,  as  the  monistic 
element. 

When  he  comes  to  human  actions,  Spinoza  regards  them 
as  a  particular  case  of  the  operation  of  universal  causes. 
Every  living  thing  has  appetite,  an  impulse  making  for  certain 
ends  and  determined  by  the  tendency  or  effort  {coiiatiis)  of  all 
things  towards  self-preservation,  which  effort  is  given  by  the 
very  fact  that  the  individual  thing  does  exist  as  such.  When 
appetite  as  thus  understood  is  conscious,  it  becomes  desire. 
With  this  fundamental  idea  Spinoza  works  out  an  account  of 
the  passions  which  is  by  general  consent  his  masterpiece, 
and  which  even  now  may  be  said  to  stand  unsurpassed.  In 
the  ethical  field  of  action  also  the  self-preserving  effort  is  the 
ultimate  fact  of  life.  '  The  foundation  of  virtue  is  no  other 
than  the  effort  to  maintain  one's  own  being,  and  man's  hap- 
piness consists  in  the  power  of  so  doing.'  ^  That  is  the  first 
law  of  our  moral  nature  in  the  scientific  sense  of  law  ;  it  is  a 
universal  fact  which  must  be  faced  and  reckoned  with.  But 
this  does  not  lead  to  a  system  of  selfishness.  For  man  is 
known  by  experience  to  be  a  social  animal,  and  this  is  no  less 
a  law  of  his  being.  Thus  he  can  maintain  his  being  only  in 
society.  As  an  individual  living  in  society,  and  unable 
to  be  solitary  if  he  would,  he  must  preserve  society  in  order  to 
preserve  himself;  or  rather  the  preservation  and  welfare 
of  society  are  his  only  true  preservation  and  welfare.  Thus 
the  foundation  of  morality  is  essentially  social.  To  this  element 
of  Spinoza's  doctrine  we  shall  refer  as  the  idea  of  natural 
law.     The  choice  of  that  term  will  explain  itself  hereafter. 

'  Eth.  4.  18,  Schol. 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA S  PHILOSOPHY.  87 

We  need  not  say  anything  thus  early  of  Spinoza's  follow- 
ing out  of  this  idea  in  politics.  Of  the  last  part  of  the 
'  Ethics  '  we  shall  only  say  here  that,  notwithstanding  its  place 
in  the  finished  work,  it  is  in  the  main  to  be  assigned  to  what 
we  have  called  the  mystical  element  in  the  principles  of  Spi- 
noza's philosophy,  and  is  to  be  explained,  so  far  as  it  may  be 
capable  of  historical  explanation,  by  reference  to  the  same 
sources.  The  interpretation  is,  however,  difficult  at  best : 
the  result  I  have  myself  arrived  at  after  much  doubt  Avill  be 
submitted  to  the  reader  in  its  due  order. 

This  division  enables  us  to  give  at  once  in  a  summary 
way  some  kind  of  introductory  general  notion  of  what  is  at 
present  knoM^n  or  surmised  about  the  birth  and  growth  of 
Spinoza's  philosophical  ideas. 

The  pantheist  or  mystical  element  is  traced  to  the  medi- 
aeval Jewish  philosophers,  with  whose  works  we  know  that 
Spinoza  was  familiar.  This  is  to  some  extent  matter  of  direct 
evidence.  A  claim  has  also  been  put  in,  and  with  likelihood 
practically  amounting  to  certainty,  for  Giordano  Bruno.  Now 
Bruno  himself  was  subject  in  certain  ways  to  Oriental  influ- 
ences, while  the  Jewish  and  Arabic  schools  of  the  Middle 
Ages  were  again  strongly  imbued  with  Neo-Platonism,  and 
Neo-Platonism  in  turn  has  a  semi- Oriental  character.  It 
seems  impossible,  even  if  it  were  worth  while,  to  disen- 
tangle all  the  details.  But  it  remains  sufficiently  clear,  what- 
ever theory  we  may  adopt,  that  the  East  has  a  considerable 
share  in  this  portion  of  Spinoza's  materials. 

The  scientific  element  may  be  assigned  without  hesitation 
to  Descartes,  though  Spinoza  carried  out  the  scientific  view  of 
the  world  farther  and  more  vigorously  than  Descartes  himself 
But  as  regards  its  union  with  the  mystical  element  it  is  ma- 
terial to  remark  that  a  nascent  scientific  impulse  runs  through 
the  naturalism  of  the  Renaissance  philosophy  as  represented 
by  Bruno  and  others  ;  and  thus  the  line  of  contact  was  in  a 
manner  already  traced. 


88  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  monistic  element  is  given  by  reaction  from  the  ^ 
duahsm  of  Cartesian  philosophy,  and  determined  chiefly,  as 
I  think,  by  considerations  of  a  scientific  order.  The  pantheist 
idea  may  also  have  its  part.  But  we  can  strike  no  exact 
account  between  the  two,  for  Spinoza  had  completed  the 
fusion  of  the  mystical  and  the  scientific  principles  before  he 
settled  his  monism  in  its  final  form.' 

The  idea  of  natural  law  remains,  and  is  the  most  inde- 
pendent work  of  Spinoza's  genius.  Ideas  and  suggestions  of 
a  general  kind  he  had  from  Descartes,  and  a  good  deal  of  more 
definite  material  from  Hobbes,  who  is  in  fact  his  master  in 
politics  ;  and  there  is  an  extraordinary  amount  of  resemblance 
to  Stoic  doctrine,  suggestive  at  the  first  glance  of  imitation.; 
But  closer  attention  will  show  that  such  a  supposition  presents 
greater  difficulties  than  that  of  coincidence. 

It  would  seem,  if  the  foregoing  statement  can  be  accepted, 
that  the  really  practical  part  of  Spinoza's  philosophy,  that 
by  which  it  is  now  operative  and  keeps  hold  on  men's  living 
interests,  is  also  the  part  which  is  most  peculiarly  his  own.  I 
am  aware  that  such  a  conclusion  may  not  be  free  from  uncon- 
scious bias,  nor  is  it  to  be  assumed  that  historical  criticism 
has  said  its  last  word.  It  is  certain  that  critics  have  hitherto 
busied  themselves  much  more  with  the  metaphysical  than 
with  the  ethical  part  of  Spinoza's  system  ;  and  it  is  yet  to 
be  seen  whether  the  revival  of  interest  in  ethical  problems 
which  has  lately  shown  itself  may  not  be  fruitful  in  this 
region.  It  may  be,  though  such  is  not  my  own  judgment, 
that  if  little  has  been  found  here,  it  is  because  there  has  been 
little  search.  In  the  meantime  I  can  only  beg  the  reader  to 
use  his  own  diligence  in  verifying  whatever  is  advanced. 

First  let  us  take  in  its  purely  speculative  aspect  the  idea 
of  the  nature  of  things  as  one  and  uniform.  Much  light 
has  been  thrown  on  the  growth  of  this  idea  in  Spinoza's  mind 

'  This  appears  from  the  advance  of  the  Ethics  on  the  Tractatulus  de  Deo  et 
Hoinine  (see  next  note)  in  that  respect. 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  89 

by  the  discovery  of  his  unpublished  '  Essay  on  God  and 
Man.'  '  The  date  of  its  composition  is  only  approximately 
known,  nor  is  the  work  itself  a  uniform  whole.  On  the  one 
hand  it  must  be  earlier  than  any  of  Spinoza's  other  writings, 
and  the  absence  of  any  mention  of  it  in  the  letters  goes  to  show 
that  by  1661  at  latest  it  was  for  Spinoza  himself  a  superseded 
work.  On  the  other  hand  it  was  written  originally  in  Latin, 
and  therefore  after  he  had  mastered  the  language  under  Van 
den  Ende,  and  it  shows  familiarity  with  Descartes,  We  shall 
probably  not  be  far  wrong  in  placing  it  about  the  time  of 
Spinoza's  excommunication.  Possibly  the  essay  or  some 
portions  of  it,  privately  circulated  among  friends,  may  have 
been  the  *  abominable  heresies  which  he  taught.'  Compared 
with  the  *  Ethics '  or  even  with  the  earlier  treatise  on  the 
Amendment  of  the  Understanding,  it  is  a  brilliant  but  im- 
mature performance.  Inasmuch  as  we  possess  the  '  Ethics,' 
the  essay  has  only  a  historical  value,  but  that  value  is  very 
great.  It  shows  us  the  ferment  and  conflict  of  elements o 
received  from  different  quarters  and  not  yet  subdued  to  their 
places  and  proportions  in  a  new  structure.  As  to  the  matter 
now  in  hand,  it  gives  positive  proof  that  Spinoza  really  0 
worked  out  his  metaphysic  by  starting  in  the  first  instance 
from  theology,  and  did  not  first  conceive  his  metaphysic  and 
then  clothe  it  in  theological  terms.  In  psychology  and 
everything  that  has  a  scientific  bearing  he  was  still  dominated 
by  Descartes  when  he  wrote  the  essay.  Not  that  he  even 
then  adopted  the  Cartesian  doctrines. 

He  was  struggling,  but  as  yet  without  a  perfectly  fixed 
aim,  to  work  out  for  himself  the  reconciliation  of  Cartesian'' 
analysis  with  a  priori  speculation.  The  leaders  of  mediaeval 
Jewish  thought  had  endeavoured  to  recast  their  theology  in 

'  See  the  account  of  Spinoza's  works  in  the  Introduction,  and  the  monographs 
on  this  essay  there  cited.     It  is  preserved  only  in  an  indifferently  executed  Dutch 

version,  which  seems  to  have  been  made  in  the  early  part  of  the  eighteenth  century. 
The  original  title,  rendered  by  '  Korte  Verhandeling  van  God,  den  mensch,  en 
deszelfs  \\'elstand,'  was  probably  Tractatulus  de  Deo  et  Homine  ciusquc  Felicitate. 


\ 


\ 


90  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

an  Aristotelian  mould  given  them  by  the  philosophic  culture 
of  their  time.  Spinoza  in  turn,  beginning  where  they  had 
left  off,  set  himself  to  refashion  their  handiwork  with  the 
instruments  furnished  by  Descartes.  But  he  took  up  the 
work  with  the  resolve  to  carry  it  through  at  all  costs,  and  the 
result  was  that  both  matter  and  method  became  transformed 
in  his  hands.  It  must  remain  doubtful,  I  think,  whether 
Spinoza  himself  was  ever  fully  aware  of  the  amount  of  the 
transformation  he  had  effected,  especially  as  regards  his  theo- 
logical premisses.  He  could  not  have  been  what  he  wasc 
without  the  Jewish  doctors  or  without  Descartes,  but  his 
philosophy  is  neither  Cartesian  nor  Jewish. 

The  essay  likewise  gives  to  my  mind  strong  reasons 
against  holding  (though  it  is  commonly  assumed  as  if  it  were 
certain)  that  Spinoza  was  ever  actually  a  Cartesian.  For 
though  as  to  certain  parts  it  is  Cartesian  in  language  and 
arrangement,  in  those  very  parts  the  essay  enunciates  anti- 
Cartesian  doctrine  even  more  pointedly  than  the  '  Ethics ' 
afterwards  did.  Not  only  is  it  denied  that  sorrow  and  the 
passions  derived  from  it  can  ever  be  useful — whereas  Descartes 
says  that  sorrow  is  in  a  manner  even  more  necessary  for  men 
than  joy — but  all  passions  whatever,  except  the  divine  love,' 
and,  in  a  qualified  sense,  one  or  two  others  of  the  more 
active  kind,  are  repudiated  as  unworthy  of  the  philosophic 
life.  If  Spinoza  was  a  Cartesian  at  any  time  it  must  have 
been  before  the  essay  was  written ;  and  moreover  he  could 
not  have  become  a  Cartesian  without  utterly  breaking  with 
the  Jewish  philosophic  traditions,  on  whose  lines,  however,  or  at 
any  rate  from  out  of  them,  he  is  working  in  the  essay.  We 
should  be  driven  to  suppose,  then,  that  Spinoza  broke  with 
Jewish  literature  to  take  up  Descartes,  and  becoming  dis- 
satisfied with  Descartes,  turned  back  again  to  the  Jewish 
authors.^     But   violent   oscillations    of  this  kind  are  not  in 

'  In  treating  this  as  a  passion  the  Essay  differs  from  the  Ethics. 

*  This  is  in  fact  the  theory  of  Dr.  Joel.     He  puts  the  supposed    return  to 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  91 

Spinoza's  character,  to  say  nothing  of  the  time  between 
Spinoza's  introduction  to  Descartes  and  his  composition  of 
this  essay  being  too  short  to  afford  room  for  them.  And 
even  so  the  essay  should  present  to  us,  not  a  juxtaposition  of 
non-Cartesian  metaphysic  and  Cartesian  psychology,  but 
modified  Cartesian  doctrine  throughout.  And  this  it  certainly 
does  not.  I  conclude,  therefore,  not  only  that  Spinoza  was 
not  solely  dependent  on  Descartes,  but  that  he  was  never  a 
Cartesian  at  all.^ 

The  argument  of  the  essay  starts,  in  a  purely  a  priori 
manner,  from  the  nature  and  attributes  of  God.  The  absolute 
uniformity  of  nature,  and  the  implied  rejection  of  final  causes, 
are  deduced  from  the  consideration  of  his  freedom  and  per- 
fection. The  universe  is  governed  by  divine  laws,  which, 
unlike  those  of  man's  making,  are  immutable,  inviolable,  and 
an  end  to  themselves,  not  instruments  for  the  attainment  of 
particular  objects.  The  love  of  God  is  man's  only  true  good. 
From  other  passions  we  can  free  ourselves,  but  not  from  love, 
'  because  for  the  weakness  of  our  nature  we  could  not  subsist 
without  the  enjoyment  of  something  that  may  strengthen  us 
by  our  union  with  it.'  Only  the  knowledge  of  God  will  enable 
us  to  subdue  the  hurtful  passions.  This,  as  the  source  of  all 
knowledge,  is  the  most  perfect  of  all ;  and,  inasmuch  as  all 
knowledge  is  derived  from  the  knowledge  of  God,  we  may 
know  God  better  than  we  know  ourselves.  This  knowledge  in 
turn  leads  to  the  love  of  God,  which  is  the  soul's  union  with 
him.  The  union  of  the  soul  with  God  is  its  second  birth,  and 
therein  consist  man's  immortality  and  freedom. 

The  detachment  from  ordinary  cares  and  interests  in 
which  the  essay  makes  man's  happiness  to  consist  is  carried 
so  far  as  to  approach  quietism.  A  great  contrast  is  presented 
to  Spinoza's  later  manner  in  such  passages  as  the  following, 

Jewish    philosophy  as    late   as   the   composition    of  the    Tractatus     Theologico- 
Foliticus,  in  which  he  finds  the  occasion  for  it. 

'  The  same  conclusion  has  been  arrived  at  by  Dr.  Avenarius  in  his  very  care- 
ful discussion  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  development. 


92  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

which  occur  in  the  description  of  Hate.     It  is  said  to  be  pro- 
duced, in  common  with  other  passions,  by  false  opinion. 

'  Hate  is  the  right  contrary  to  love,  and  ariseth  from  the 
delusion  that  is  begotten  of  mere  opinion.  For  when  a  man 
hath  concluded  concerning  such  and  such  a  thing  that  it  is 
good,  and  another  comes  and  doth  somewhat  to  the  prejudice 
of  the  same,  then  the  first  conceives  hate  against  him  so  doing. 
The  which  should  have  no  place  in  him  if  the  true  good  were 
known,  as  we  shall  show  hereafter.  For  all  that  is  or  may  be 
thought  of  is  in  comparison  with  the  true  good  [the  love  of  God] 
nothing  but  mere  wretchedness,  and  is  not  he  that  so  affects 
wretched  things  much  more  worthy  of  pity  than  of  hate  .'' ' ' 

In  the  '  Ethics  '  the  ordinary  pleasures  and  amenities  of 
life,  though  not  exclusive  or  sufficient  objects  of  a  reasonable 
man's  pursuit,  nor  to  be  lamented  for  when  they  are  not 
attainable,  are  treated  as  something  very  different  from  '  mere 
wretchedness.'  And  we  shall  see  that  the  love  of  God, 
though  still  presented  as  the  crown  and  perfect  state  of  the 
human  mind,  acquires  a  much  more  intellectual  character,  if 
indeed  it  can  be  at  all  distinguished  from  pure  speculative 
knowledge. 

It  appears  therefore  that  the  theological  element,  however 
transformed  subsequently,  may  claim  the  right  of  primogeni- 
ture among  Spinoza's  ideas.  We  shall  be  pursuing  an  order 
not  only  historical  in  point  of  actual  chronology,  but  just  and 
fitting  with  regard  to  the  probable  history  of  Spinoza's  thought, 
if  we  first  turn  our  attention  to  the  Jewish  doctors  of  the  middle 
ages  who  brought  a  philosophical  treatment  to  bear  upon 
theological  problems. 

Partly  coinciding  in  time  with  Catholic  scholasticism,  but 
with  their  rise  and  culminating  period  nearly  a  century  earlier, 
a  series  of  Jewish  philosophers  in  Spain,  Provence,  and  the 
East,  did  work  which  has  a  far  more  important  place  in  the 
general  history  of  philosophy  than  has  commonly  been  allowed 

'  Kortc  VerhanJeling,  part  ii.  cap.  3, 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  93 

to  it.  The  task  they  set  themselves  was  the  same  in  kind  as 
that  of  the  schoolmen,  Avho,  in  spite  of  religious  difference, 
joined  hands  with  them  on  the  common  ground  of  Aristotle, 
and  used  their  work  with  open  acknowledgment  and  respect. 
They  strove,  in  one  word,  to  systematize  theology  on  an 
Aristotelian  footing.  For  this  purpose  it  was  necessary 
to  embark  on  a  critical  and  philosophical  interpretation  of 
Scripture ;  and  in  this  undertaking  the  comparatively 
undefined  character  of  Jewish  orthodoxy  secured  them  a 
certain  amount  of  freedom.*  Or  rather  philosophy  presented 
itself  to  Jewish  speculation  as  an  enlightened  interpretation 
of  the  hidden  meaning  of  the  law.  Thus  Moses  ben  Maimon 
and  Ibn  Ezra  were  leaders  in  biblical  criticism  no  less  than  in 
philosophy.  The  ideas  they  put  forward  in  this  field  weie  lo 
be  carried  out  to  their  full  development  in  the  '  Tractatus 
Theologico-Politicus.'  Spinoza's  object  is  indeed  opposite  to 
that  of  Maimonides.  So  far  from  finding  philosophy  in  the 
Scriptures,  he  maintains  that  it  is  idle  to  seek  it  there ;  and 
the  sharpness  of  his  criticism  on  Maimonides'  artificial  system 
of  interpretation  has  probably  distracted  attention  from  that 
which  they  really  have  in  common.  Maimonides'  work  was  con- 
tinued by  Levi  ben  Gerson,  or  Gersonides  (born  at  Bagnal  in 
Provence  in  1288,  living  in  1340),  who,  professing  to  be  a  mere 
interpreter  of  the  Scriptures  and  to  rely  on  them  as  the  source 
of  every  kind  of  knowledge,  was  at  the  same  time  more 
thoroughly  Aristotelian  than  his  predecessors.  His  dis- 
covery of  Aristotelian  metaphysics  in  the  Song  of  Solomon 
was  probably  the  extreme  feat  of  the  Jewish  theologico- 
philosophical  dialectic. 

•  The  Mahometan  schools  enjoyed  the  same  advantage.  Strictly  speaking, 
neither  Judaism  nor  Islam  have  any  dogmatic  theology  at  all.  At  the  same  time 
there  must  have  been  in  practice  a  good  deal  of  restraint.  Maimonides  expressly 
warns  his  readers  that  on  many  points  he  will  be  deliberately  obscure  ;  and  Ibn 
Ezra  could  only  hint  with  elaborate  mystery  that  '  the  Canaanite  was  then  in  the 
land '  could  not  have  been  the  language  of  Moses'  generation.  The  intervals  o( 
absolute  silence  in  his  commentary  on  Isaiah  are  even  more  significant. 


94  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  influence  of  these  writers  is  most  marked  in  the 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  with  which  we  are  not 
immediately  concerned  in  this  place.  In  the  purely  philo- 
sophical part  of  Spinoza's  work  it  was  comparatively  slight : 
it  is  perhaps  not  too  much  to  say  that  there  are  only  traces  of 
it  in  the  '  Ethics,'  apart  from  the  doctrine  of  the  mind's  eter- 
nity in  the  fifth  part,  which  I  believe  comes  from  the  Averro- 
ists  through  Gersonides.  Still  the  pointsof  affinity  are  notable. 
The  following  are  specimens  of  those  which  may  be  found  in 
Maimonides'  great  work,  the  '  More  Nebuchim.'  ' 

The  will  and  the  wisdom  of  God  are  regarded  as  insepar- 
able. And  not  only  is  there  no  real  distinction  between  the 
divine  attributes,  but  no  attribute  whatever  can  be  predicated 
of  God  in  the  ordinary  sense.  Even  eternity  and  existence, 
as  applied  to  him,  are  not  jr;/;w;/;//«^z^j,  but  mitrely  homonymous 
with  the  same  terms  in  any  other  application.^  This,  however, 
is  by  no  means  peculiar  to  Maimonides  ;  it  is  a  common 
possession  of  the  scholastic  writers,  and  is  distinctly  enounced 
in  the  treatise  on  mystical  theology  which  bears  the  name  of 
Dionysius  the  Areopagite.  Probably  it  might  be  traced  much 
farther  back  by  any  one  conversant  with  Neo-Platonism.  The 
application  of  theprinciple  to  God's  knowledge  as  distinguished 
from  man's  was  strenuously  disputed  by  Levi  ben  Gerson. 

The  existence  of  God  is  involved  in  his  essence  ;  other- 
wise of  the  existence  of  any  finite  creature,  which  may  be 
considered  as  an  accident  in  the  logical  sense.^ 

God  coexists  with  the  creation  as  its  cause  /;/  actu,  not  as 
a  cause  in  potentia,  which  precedes  the  effect  in  time.* 

'  Edited  by  Dr.  Muak,  sub  (it.  Le  Guide  des  Egarh,  with  literal  French  trans- 
lation. I 

^  Cap.  56,  and  elsewhere. 

'  Capp.  57,  58. 

^  Cap.  69.  One  may  be  allowed  to  note  (though  not  here  relevant) 
I\Iaimonides'  answer  to  the  standing  question  why  the  world,  if  created  in  time, 
was  created  at  one  time  rather  than  another.  He  says  it  is  just  like  asking  why 
there  exists  a  certain  number,  neither  more  nor  less,  of  individuals  of  any  kind — 
e.g.  the  fixed  stars. 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  95 

Perfect  intellect  forms  no  conception  of  good  and  evil,  only 
of  true  and  false.  Such  was  the  first  state  of  Adam.  Good 
and  evil  belong  to  the  region  of  probable  opinion,' 

Dr.  Joel  also  calls  attention  to  Maimonides'  reflections  on 
final  causes  as  being  fitted  to  prepare  the  way  for  Spinoza's 
entire  rejection  of  them.^  Maimonides  holds  that  the  con- 
ceptions of  design  and  final  cause  have  no  intelligible  applica- 
tion except  as  regards  things  created  in  time. 

Chasdai  Creskas  of  Barcelona,  and  afterwards  of  Saragossa, 
who  lived  in  the  latter  part  of  the  fourteenth  and  early  part 
of  the  fifteenth  century,  was  a  more  daring  and  original 
thinker  than  his  predecessors,  though  to  a  certain  extent 
in  the  interest  of  orthodoxy.  He  broke  with  the  Peripatetic 
tradition  to  strike  out  an  independent  line  of  his  own,  and 
Dr.  Joel's  research  has  shown  that  he  stands  in  a  closer  rela- 
tion to  Spinoza  than  any  other  of  the  Jewish  philosophers. 
His  principal  work,  the  '  Light  of  the  Lord  '  (Or  Adonai), 
finished  in  1410,  contains  many  things  which  come  near  to 
characteristic  points  of  Spinoza's  philosophy.  Some  of  these 
points  are  already  well  developed. 

He  censures  as  fallacious  the  notion  of  infinite  extension 
being  made  up  of  measurable  parts  (cf.  Spinoza,  Eth.  i.  15 
schoL,  Ep.  29)  :  he  also  holds  matter  to  be  eternal,  the  act 
of  creation  consisting  only  in  the  ordering  of  it  ;  and  maintains 
that  the  material  world,  being  good  in  its  kind  (which  he 
takes,  I  presume,  as  a  truth  known  by  revelation),  participates 
in  the  Divine  nature.  The  contrast  of  this  with  the  Cartesian 
theory  of  substances  distinct  in  genere  ^yrohahXy  had  something 
to  do  with  Spinoza's  conception  of  extension  as  an  attribute 
coequal  with  thought. 

Again,  the  perfection  of  God  consists  not  in  knowledge,  as 
the  Aristotelians  say,  but  in  love.  This  love  is  what  deter- 
mines God  to  creation,  as  at  the  same  time  a  necessity  of  his 

'  Cap.  2. 

*  Zur  Genesis  der  Lehre  Spinoza's  (in  Bcitrdge  zur  Gesch.  der  Philos. ). 


96  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

nature  and  an  act  of  will.  Love  being  the  chief  attribute  of 
God,  the  perfection  of  any  creature  depends  on  the  extent  to 
which  it  shares  therein  :  thus  the  love  of  God  (for  its  own  sake, 
not  as  a  means  of  salvation)  is  the  chief  end  of  man.  We  have 
already  had  occasion  to  see  what  an  important  part  is  assigned 
to  this  in  the  essay  '  On  God  and  Man '  which  preceded 
Spinoza's  Ethics. 

Most  remarkable  of  all,  perhaps,  is  Chasdai's  thorough 
determinism.  He  explicitly  denies  that  any  event,  whether 
depending  on  human  choice  or  not,  can  be  called  possible  or 
contingent  in  an  absolute  sense.  It  is  inconceivable,  he  says, 
'  that  two  men,  being  themselves  of  like  temper  and  character, 
and  having  before  them  like  objects  of  choice  in  like  circum- 
stances, should  choose  differently.'  Volitions  are  determined 
by  motives  as  much  as  anything  else  in  nature  is  determined. 
An  act  of  free  will  is  free  in  so  far  as  it  is  not  compelled,  but 
necessary  in  so  far  as  it  is  not  iincaiised.  The  argument  on 
this  topic  seems  to  be  fully  worked  out,  and  to  deal  with  most 
of  the  points  that  have  been  made  in  later  controversy  on  the 
subject.  The  fallacy  of  fatalism,  for  example,  is  clearly 
enough  exposed.  The  objector  who  says,  If  all  things  that 
happen  are  necessary,  why  do  men  take  pains  to  compass 
their  ends .-'  forgets  that  things  are  necessary  only  with  refer- 
ence to  their  conditions,  and  that  in  the  case  of  human 
undertakings  forethought  and  labour  are  among  the  conditions. 

Reward  and  punishment,  as  the  consequences  of  good  and 
bad  actions,  are  themselves  part  of  the  necessary  order  of 
things.  If  it  is  asked,  How  is  it  just  that  the  wicked  should 
be  punished,  if  their  wickedness  is  necessary?  Chasdai  an- 
swers, with  Zeno  before  him  and  Spinoza  after  him,  that  their 
punishment  is  necessary  too.  Reward  and  punishment, 
commands  and  prohibitions,  are  nevertheless  ordained  by 
Providence  as  means  to  lead  men  to  salvation.  The  love  of 
God  is  man's  chief  good,  even  as  love  is  God's  own  perfection  : 
and    therefore  the  fore-ordained    sanctions  are   attached    to 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  97 

those  actions  and  thoughts  which  are  free  in  the  popular 
sense,  that  is,  which  are  determined  by  a  state  of  mind  in- 
volving the  lov^e  of  God  or  its  contrary. 

Chasdai  holds  fast,  it  must  be  remembered,  to  the  idea  of 
designed  order  in  the  universe,  though  final  causes  in  the 
ordinary  sense  are  as  it  were  swallowed  up  in  the  absolute, 
self-sufficient  necessity  by  which  God's  love  manifests  itself. 
He  likewise  holds  fast  to  the  necessity  of  revelation,  and  goes 
so  far  as  to  say  that  the  fundamental  doctrine  of  the  unity  of 
God  could  not  be  otherwise  known.  Thus  he  cannot  be 
regarded  as  a  forerunner  of  Spinoza's  system.  Spinoza  took 
the  suggestions  in  detail  and  worked  them  into  a  systematic 
connexion  of  his  own  which  would  probably  have  found  little 
favour  in  Chasdai's  eyes. 

Chasdai  Creskas  deserves  to  be  remembered,  apart  from 
his  probable  influence  on  Spinoza,  as  one  of  the  first  who 
ventured  to  attack  the  prevalent  Aristotelian  dogmatism.  His 
motives  appear  to  have  been  purely  theological  ;  the  artificial 
constructions  forced  on  Scripture  by  the  school  of  Ben  Maimon 
and  Ben  Gerson  were  repugnant  both  to  his  reason  and  to  his 
faith.  When  theologians  fall  out  philosophy  sometimes  comes 
by  her  own.  For  Spinoza's  knowledge  of  Chasdai's  work  we 
have  the  direct  evidence  of  one  express  quotation  •  (Ep.  29, 
ad  fin  ^j. 

A  word  must  also  be  said  of  the  mystical  literature  which 
qxercised  an  even  greater  influence  on  modern  Judaism  than 
the  Aristotelian  philosophy,  and  whose  later  development  was 
due,  according  to  one  high  authority,'^  to  a  reaction  against 
the  rationalism  of  the  philosophic  writers.  The  possible 
influence  of  the  Kabbalah  on  Spinoza   has    been    discussed 

'  '  Verum  hie  obiter  adhuc  notari  velim,  quod  Peripatetici  recentiores,  ut  quidem 
puto,  male  intellexerunt  demonstrationem  veterum,  qua  ostendere  nitebantur  Dei 
existentiam.  Nam  ut  ipsam  apud  Judaeum  quendam,  Rab  Ghasdai  vocatum, 
reperio,  sic  sonat.'  ....  The  passage  is  identified  by  Dr.  Joel  {Don  Chasdai 
Creskas'  Religionsphilosophische  Lehren,  etc.,  p.  9). 

-  Dr.  Gratz,  in  Gesch.  der  Juden,  vol.  vii. 

II 


98  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

from  time  to  time  ever  since  Spinoza's  writings  have  been  an 
object  of  notice  to  the  learned  world.  One  of  his  earliest 
critics,  J.  E.  Wachter,  endeavoured  to  trace  his  principal 
doctrines  to  that  quarter  :  ^  and  others  in  later  times,  without 
going  so  far  as  to  ascribe  to  the  Kabbalists  the  chief  share  in 
Spinoza's  philosophical  genealogy,  have  claimed  for  them  a 
more  or  less  considerable  one.  In  order  to  put  this  question 
on  a  rational  footing  it  is  very  necessary  to  distinguish  between 
the  Kabbalah  properly  so  called,  which  dates  from-  the 
thirteenth  century,  and  the  older  mystical  traditions  which 
the  Kabbalists  deliberately  confounded  with  their  own  fan- 
tastic speculations  in  order  to  give  themselves  an  apparent 
sanction  of  antiquity.  The  later  Kabbalah,  starting  from 
an  idealist  theology  and  cosmology  expressed  in  highly 
symbolic  language,  rapidly  became  overwhelmed  by  its  own 
anthropomorphic  symbolism,  and  overran  all  Jewry  with 
demonolog}^,  thaumaturgy,  and  other  wild  fancies  beyond 
measure  ;  for  all  which  the  professors  of  this  so-called  philo- 
sophy found  warrant  in  Scripture  by  trifling  and  wearisome 
schemes  of  non-natural  interpretation,  anagrammatic  readings, 
arbitrary  transpositions  and  substitutions  of  letters,  allegorical 
and  other  occult  meanings,  virtues  of  numbers,  and  the  like. 
The  greatest  play  was  made  with  the  numerical  values  of 
words  and  letters,  a  method  which  has  to  some  extent  found 
its  way  into  Christian  theology  also.  The  metaphysical 
foundations  of  the  system  appear  to  have  been  derived  by 
some  road  not  fully  known  from  Neo-Platonism,  and  it  is  said 
by  the  best  authorities  that  the  very  terms  bear  marks  of 
imitation  from  the  Greek.  The  doctrine  of  emanations  and 
intermediate  powers  between  God  and  the  world  was  laid 
hold  of  in  order  to  have  a  philosophic  standing-ground  against 
Maimonides  and  the  rationalists,  and  at  the  same  time  to 
preserve  tradition  and  ritualism  in  their  literal  significance. 

'  Dcr  Sphiozistmcs  im  yndenthunib,  1699,     Elucidarius  Cabbalisticus,    1706. 
See  Van  der  Linda,  Bibliogr.  No.  274. 


SOURCES  OF  SFIXOZAS  PHILOSOPHY. 


99 


In  Spinoza's  generation  this  system  had  attained  its  fullest 
and  most  extravagant  development :  and  it  seems  to  have 
become  by  that  time  the  most  unmitigated  nonsense  ever  put 
together  by  the  perverted  ingenuity  of  man,  except  perhaps 
the  English  law  of  real  property.  In  its  application  to  cere- 
monial observances  it  was  little  else  than  a  mass  of  ludicrous 
or  disgusting  puerilities.  Its  fruits  were  seen  in  the  outbreaks 
of  delusion  and  imposture  culminating  in  the  exploits  of  the 
false  Messiah,  Sabbatai  Zevi,  of  which  mention  has  already 
been  made  in  a  former  chapter.  Such  a  doctrine,  we  may 
be  sure,  had  little  attraction  for  Spinoza  ;  and  in  an  age  when 
historical  criticism  did  not  exist  he  would  scarcely  have  had 
the  patience  to  search  the  rubbish-heap  for  the  jewels  that 
might  be  buried  in  it.  He  has  indeed  left  us  in  no  doubt  as 
to  his  opinion  of  the  Kabbalists  of  his  time.  For  he  says  in 
the  ninth  chapter  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  : '  '  I 
have  read  and  moreover  known  some  Kabbalistic  triflers,  at 
whose  follies  I  was  astonished  beyond  description.' 

It  is  hardly  worth  while  to  insist  on  the  differences  between 
Spinoza  and  the  Kabbalah.  The  doctrines  of  emanation  and 
the  transmigration  of  souls  are  both  fundamental  in  the 
Kabbalistic  account  of  the  world,  and  are  both  utterly  in- 
compatible with  Spinoza's  metaphysic. 

But  on  the  other  hand  Spinoza  twice  refers,  in  passages  of 
marked  importance  and  in  a  tone  of  respect,  though  in  vague 
terms,  to  ancient  Hebrew  opinions  and  traditions  ;  and  these 
references  may  with  some  plausibility  be  assigned  to  the  earlier 
mysticism  which  undoubtedly  preceded  the  modern  Kabbalah, 
and  was  afterwards  confused  with  it.  Only  an  accomplished 
Orientalist  can  be  entitled  to  a  positive  opinion  on  the  sources 
and  antiquity  of  these  speculations.  But  all  mysticism  is 
Eastern  in  its  ultimate  origin,  and  the  choice  would  seem  to 
be  substantially  between  holding  that  the  Jewish  mysticism  was 
indirectly  derived  from  the  East  through  Neo-Platonism  and  the 
Alexandrian  schools,  or  that  it  came,  as  we  know  that  modern 

H  2 


loo  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

Jewish  theology  came,  earlier  and  more  directly  from  the  old 
Persian  religion,  in  which  case  Jewish  and  Alexandrian 
mysticism  would  be  related  to  one  another,  not  in  a  direct 
line  of  descent,  but  as  parallel  and  partly  intermixed  streams 
from  the  same  fountain-head.  The  question  is  hardly  a  pro- 
per one  to  be  pursued  here,  even  if  I  were  qualified  for  the 
undertaking.  But  it  is  easy  to  see  that,  apart  from  the  evi- 
dence of  actual  coincidences,  which  in  a  case  of  this  kind  is 
difficult  to  fix  at  its  true  value,  the  last  mentioned  opinion  has 
a  strong  antecedent  probability  in  its  favour :  and  even  a 
stranger  to  Oriental  literature  may  be  permitted  to  appreciate 
the  weight  of  M.  Franck's  arguments  for  it. 

The  allusions  in  Spinoza  are  the  following. 

In  the  Scholium  to  the  seventh  Proposition  of  the  Second 
Part  of  the  Ethics  he  says  :  '  A  mode  of  extension  [i.e.  a  finite 
material  thing]  and  the  idea  of  that  mode  are  one  and  the 
same  thing,  but  expressed  in  two  ways  ;  which  certain  of  the 
Hebrews  seem  to  have  seen  as  through  a  cloud,  when  they 
say  that  God,  the  understanding  of  God,  and  the  things 
understood  by  him  are  one  and  the  same.'  Now  this  is  dis- 
tinctly said  in  the  commentary  of  Moses  of  Cordova  on  the 
Kabbalistic  book  Zohar,  '  It  is  to  be  known  that  the  know- 
ledge of  the  Creator  is  not  as  that  of  his  creatures.  For  in 
these  knowledge  is  distinct  from  the  subject  of  knowledge,  and 
is  directed  upon  objects  which  in  their  turn  are  distinguished 
from  the  subject.  This  is  denoted  by  these  three  terms  : 
thought,  that  which  thinks,  and  that  which  is  thought  of  But 
the  Creator,  on  the  contrary,  is  himself  at  once  knowledge 
and  that  which  knows  and  that  which  is  known.  His  manner 
of  knowledge  consists  not  in  applying  his  thought  to  things 
outside  him  ;  in  the  knowledge  of  himself  he  knows  and 
perceives  all  that  exists.  Nothing  exists  which  is  not  united 
to  him  or  which  he  finds  not  in  his  own  substance. '  ^     The 

'  Franck,    La    Kabbah,     pp.    27,    194 ;    Sigwart,    Spinoza's    Netuntdeckto- 
Tractat,  &c.,  ]).  100.     The  book  Zohar  itself,  the  great  armoury  of  the  Kabbalists, 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  loi 

coincidence  is  striking,  and  it  is  quite  possible  that  Spinoza 
had  read  Moses  of  Cordova.  But  then  it  is  quite  certain 
that  Spinoza  had  read  and  digested  the  Kabbalist's  far  greater 
namesake  Moses  ben  Maimon.  And  the  same  thought  is 
even  more  fully  and  distinctly  expressed  in  a  chapter  of  Mai- 
monides'  masterpiece,  to  which  Spinoza  makes  on  another 
point  an  unmistakable  reference  elsewhere.'  The  chapter 
opens  thus  :  '  Thou  knowest  the  famous  proposition  laid  down 
by  philosophers  concerning  God,  to  wit  that  he  is  intellect, 
the  intelligent,  and  the  intelligible,  and  that  these  three  things 
in  God  make  but  one  and  the  same  thing,  wherein  is  no  mul- 
tiplicity.' And  again  at  the  end  of  the  chapter  :  '  Hence  (from 
God  being  intellect  always  in  actii,  never  in  potentia  like  the 
knowledge  of  finite  minds)  it  follows  that  he  is  constantly  and 
perpetually  intelligent,  intellect,  and  intelligible  ;  it  is  his  very 
essence  that  is  intelligent,  it  is  the  same  that  is  the  intelligible, 
and  still  the  same  that  is  intellect,  as  must  be  the  case  with 
all  intellect  in  act.'  Maimonides  himself  is  here  following 
Ibn-Si'na,  and  the  idea  is  ultimately  derived  from  Aristotle. 
Thus  we  have  a  warning  of  some  significance  against  jumping 
at  simple  coincidences  in  matters  of  this  kind.  It  is  practi- 
cally certain  that  Spinoza  had  in  his  mind  the  passage  of 
Maimonides  ;  he  may  or  may  not  have  also  had  before  him 
the  adaptation  of  it  by  Moses  of  Cordova  to  a  purpose 
superficially  like  Spinoza's  own. 

The  other  passage  to  be  considered  is  in  a  letter  to  Olden- 
burg (Ep.  2l). 

'  I  hold  God  for  the  immanent  cause,  as  they  say,  of  all 
things,  not  tHe  transient.  That  all  things  have  their  being 
and  move  in  God,  I  affirm  with  Paul,  and  perhaps  I  may  say 
with  all  the  ancient  philosophers,  though  in  another  form  ;  I 


is  finally  ascertained  by  recent  criticism  to  be  a  forgery  of  the  thirteenth  century. 
Gratz,  op.  cit.  vol.  vii.  note  12. 

'  More  Nebuchim,  part  i.  c.  68  (vol.  i.  p.  301   in  Munk's  translation,  and  see 
his  note)  ;  Spinoza,  Collate  Meiaphysica,  pt.  ii.  c.  6,  §  3. 


I02  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

might  even  make  bold  to  say,  with  all  the  ancient  Hebrews, 
so  far  as  one  may  guess  from  certain  traditions,  though  they 
be  in  many  ways  corrupted.'  The  traditions  here  mentioned 
might  well  belong  to  the  metaphysical  kernel  of  the  Kabbalah, 
which  Spinoza  must,  in  common  with  all  scholars  of  the  time, 
have  believed  to  be  of  great  antiquity ;  and  the  manifold  cor- 
ruptions of  which  he  speaks  would  also  fit  very  well  with  the 
vagaries  of  the  later  Kabbalists,  and  the  opinion  expressed  of 
them  in  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.'  But  such-a  re- 
ference is  too  vague  to  be  much  relied  upon  by  itself ;  and  we 
have  seen  that  the  passage  in  Eth.  ii.  7  gives  it  very  little 
support. 

It  is  further  to  be  observed  that  the  Kabbalah  was  taken 
up  with  great  ardour  by  Raymond  Lull  within  the  century 
of  its  birth,  and  thus  obtained  a  partial  currency  in  Christen- 
dom ;  and  that  it  was  eagerly  studied  by  Pico  de  Mirandola, 
Reuchlin,  and  other  scholars  of  the  Renaissance,  who,  enter- 
taining no  doubt  of  the  antiquity  alleged  for  it,  thought  to  find 
in  it  a  venerable  and  authoritative  confirmation  of  the  Platonic 
or  Neo-Platonic  philosophy  that  prevailed  among  them. 

Giordano  Bruno,  whose  relation  to  Spinoza  w^ill  im- 
mediately be  considered,  was  probably  not  free  from  this  in- 
fluence. At  all  events  the  work  of  the  Jewish  NeorPlatonist 
Avicebron  (Ibn-Gebirol)  was  known  to  him  and  freely  used  by 
him  ;  and  thus  we  have  yet  another  road  by  which  the  Neo- 
Platonic  ideas  may  have  found  their  way  to  Spinoza.  Solomon 
Ibn-Gebirol,  born  at  Cordova  or  Malaga  about  1020,  came  at 
an  unfortunate  time  for  his  philosophical  reputation  among 
his  own  people.  His  speculative  writings,  in  which  he  closely 
followed  Plotinus,  were  overwhelmed  in  the  Peripatetic  flood 
that  was  already  rising  before  his  death,  and  while  he  lived 
and  still  lives  as  a  religious  poet,'  he  was  entirely  forgotten  as 

'    '  Den  Gabirol,  diesen  treuen 
Gottgeweihten  Minnesangcr, 
Diese  fromme  Nachtigall, 
Jjeren  Rose  C.ott  gewescn.'  — Hfixf,,  Ilcbydische  McIoJien. 


SOURCES   OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  103 

a  philosophical  writer.  But  his  principal  work  had  been 
translated  into  Latin  under  the  name  of  '  Fons  Vitae,'  and 
was  current  among  the  schoolmen.  The  author's  name  was 
disguised  under  the  Latinized  form  Avicebron,  and  he  was  set 
down  without  further  inquiry,  by  a  sort  of  unreasoned  mental 
attraction,  as  belonging  to  the  Arabic  school  headed  by 
Averroes  and  Avicenna,  The  identity  of  Avicebron  with  Ibn- 
Gebirol  was  rediscovered  only  in  our  own  day  by  the  saga- 
cious industry  of  the  late  Dr.  Munk.  The  '  Fons  Vitae,'  well 
known  to  the  leaders  of  mediaeval  philosophy,  fell  into  the 
hands  of  Giordano  Bruno,  who  as  a  Platonist  of  the  Renais- 
sance naturally  received  it  in  a  much  more  kindred  spirit  than 
the  Aristotelians.  Bruno  repeatedly  cites  Avicebron  with  ap- 
proval, and  there  is  much  likeness  in  tne  general  strain  of 
their  speculations,  which  however  may  be  due  to  the  use  of 
common  sources.  . 

We  have  no  direct  evidence  that  Spinoza  was  acquainted 
with  Giordano  Bruno's  writings  ;  but  the  want  of  such  evi- 
dence counts  for  very  little.  But  for  his  reply  in  a  letter  to  a 
friend's  passing  question,  we  should  be  in  the  same  case  as  to 
Spinoza's  knowledge  of  Hobbes  ;  yet  his  political  theory  is 
so  evidently  founded  on  that  of  Hobbes  that  the  letter  adds 
nothing  to  our  certainty.  At  that  time  it  was  still  the  con- 
stant practice  for  writers  to  make  in  silence  such  use  of  their 
predecessors'  work  as  in  our  day  would  be  thought  to  demand 
the  most  ample  acknowledgment.  And  in  this  particular 
case  there  was  a  special  reason  for  silence,  the  same  reason 
which  probably  accounts  for  Tschirnhausen's  later  omission  of 
all  reference  to  Spinoza  himself.  Any  avowed  following  of 
Bruno  would  have  been  sure  to  excite  the  most  violent  pre- 
judice even  among  Protestant  readers.  It  was  by  no  means  at 
Catholic  orthodoxy  alone  that  Giordano  Bruno  had  struck  in 
his  daring  and  unconfined  speculations.  We  are  free,  then,  to 
take  at  its  full  worth  the  internal  evidence  for  Spinoza's  know- 
ledge of  Bruno  ;  and  it  is  of  such  strength  as  to  carry  all  but 


104  SPINOZA  :  HIS  IJFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

irresistible  conviction.  Whether  Spinoza  had  actually  read 
Bruno's  dialogues,  or  had  become  acquainted  with  their 
substance  in  some  other  way  (for  example,  through  Van  den 
Ende),  it  is  impossible  with  our  present  materials  to  decide. 

One  is  tempted  to  linger  on  the  singular  career  and  tragic 
fate  of  the  man  whose  fame,  crushed  for  awhile  but  not  con- 
sumed, has  revived  in  our  own  day  for  the  eternal  dishonour 
of  his  persecutors.  They  who  curse  liberty  and  the  advance- 
ment of  man's  estate  in  our  own  day  are  true  and  worthy 
successors  of  those  who  burnt  Giordano  Bruno  and  were 
ready  to  torture  Galileo.  The  philosopher  and  martyr  of- 
whom  we  now  speak  is  at  last  fitly  celebrated  in  the  verse  of  one 
of  our  own  poets,  himself  full  of  the  spirit  of  the  Renaissance, 
its  ideal  ardour  for  freedom,  its  impatience  of  authority  in  all 
forms,  its  height  of  speculative  ambition,  and  its  passionate 
love  of  beauty.  But  my  task  forbids  me  to  enter  on  digressions, 
and  I  must  proceed  to  notice  the  points  of  Bruno's  philosophy 
which  bear  on  the  matter  in  hand. 

'  '^  Bruno  admits  only  one  first  principle,  cause,  or  sub- 
stance, in  the  universe.  He  is  never  tired  of  dwelling  on  the 
unity  of  all  things,  which  he  regards  as  a  multiform  unity 
embracing  the  whole  and  present  in  every  part.  He  rejects 
the  notion  of  formless  matter,  and  maintains  that  matter  and 
form  are  inseparable.  Finite  things  differ  from  one  another 
not  in  their  being,  but  only  in  their  mode  of  being,  so  that  in 
them  the  one  substance  is  not  diverse,  but  only  diversely 
fashioned  and  figured  ;  all  things  are  in  the  universe,  and  the 
universe  in  all  things.  The  study  of  nature  seems  to  disclose 
two  substances  of  mind  and  body,  but  further  contemplation 
reduces  them  to  one  ;  and  the  ultimate  object  of  all  philoso- 
phy and  science  is  declared  (with  an  ironical  reservation  as  to 
supernatural  knowledge)  to  be  the  perception  of  this  unity. 
In  one  dialogue  the  speaker  who  represents  Bruno's  own 
opinions  asserts  that  the  'first  principle'  is  infinite  in  all  its 
attributes,  and  that  one  of  those  attributes  is  extension  {mw 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  105 

aviplissimo  dimensionale  infinito).  Again,  it  is  animated,  in- 
asmuch as  it  includes  all  life  as  part  of  one  and  the  same 
being  :  all  particular  lives  are  effects  of  the  divine  life  present 
in  all  things,  '  Natura  est  deus  in  rebus.'  We  find  in  Bruno 
the  terms  attribute  and  mode,  used  in  a  manner  which,  though 
it  has  not  anything  like  Spinoza's  precision,  may  very  well 
have  suggested  Spinoza's  adoption  of  the  words.  The  con- 
stant polemic  against  Aristotle  is  likewise  worth  noting ;  if 
Spinoza  was  a  reader  of  Bruno,  his  almost  contemptuous  view  • 
of  Aristotle  (p.  6-"^  above)  might  be  partly  accounted  for  by 
this. 

In  some  of  Bruno's  writings  much  prominence  is  given  to 
the  identification  of  the  highest  kind  of  speculative  knowledge 
with  the  love  of  God,  or  the  one  perfect  object ;  and  the  power 
and  surpassing  excellence  of  this  ideal  and  intellectual  love 
are  dwelt  upon  with  exuberant  poetic  fancy.  Notwithstand- 
ing the  wide  difference  between  Bruno's  manner  and  Spinoza's, 
the  thought  and  even  the  expressions  are  often  strikingly 
Tke  those  of  the  '  Essay  on  God  and  Man.'  At  the  same  time 
this  topic  is  so  much  the  common  property  of  all  mystic  and 
mystically  inclined  writers  that  I  can  hardly  think  these  re- 
semblances add  very  much  to  the  evidence  of  a  specific  con- 
nexion between  the  two  thinkers.  It  would  be  no  great 
matter  for  surprise  if  an  equally  good  parallel  could  be  pro- 
duced from  the  Persian  Sufis,  whom  Spinoza  certainly  had 
not  studied.  Still,  when  the  general  probability  of  Spinoza's 
relation  to  Bruno  is  once  established,  all  points  of  coincidence 
have  a  certain  cumulative  value,  though  each  may  in  itself  be 
capable  of  a  different  explanation. 

It  has  been  suggested  that  Descartes  also  may  have  been 
indebted  to  Giordano  Bruno,  and  there  is  nothing  unlikely  in 
it.  Leaving  this  question  aside  as  too  remote,  we  must  now 
turn  to  Descartes  as  the  master  who  gave  the  most  powerful 
and  immediate  impulse  to  Spinoza's  thought  in  another 
direction.     By  him  were   nourished   the  exact   method,  the 


io6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

close  analysis,  the  spirit  of  scientific  curiosity,  which  we  find 
in  Spinoza's  earliest  writing  side  by  side  with  the  ardour  of 
universal  contemplation,  and  in  the  '  Ethics '  interpenetrating 
and  transforming  it. 

Part  II. — Descartes. 

The  real  merit  of  Descartes  is  not  to   be  found   in   the 
particular   novelties  which    he   started    in  either   natural    or 
universal  philosophy.     His  fundamental  axiom  in  psychology,— 
though  first  brought   into  full  prominence  by  him,  was  not 
altogether  new.     His  physical  principles  were  unsatisfactory- 
not    only  in  themselves,  but  as  compared  with  the   results 
already  arrived  at  by  other  workers  to  whom  Descartes  failed 
to  do   justice.     They  were   indeed   absolutely  erroneous    in 
many  respects,  as  we  shall  presently  have  occasion  to   see. 
The  amount  of  direct  edification  which  a  modern  reader  can 
get  out  of  Descartes'  '  Principia  Philosophiae  '  is  in  truth  ex- 
ceedingly small.     It  is  only  in  pure  mathematics,  where,  as  ""• 
the  undoubted  creator  of  analytical  geometry,  he  can  claim 
his  part  in  all  its  later  achievements  and  extensions,  that  his 
contributions  to   man's  positive  knowledge  have  retained   a 
permanent  value.     Yet  the  name  of  Descartes,  notwithstand- 
ing all  the  shortcomings  of  his  actual  performance,  marks  an 
epoch  in  the  history  of  science  and  philosophy.     His  fame  .. 
is  great  and  justly  won  because  he  made  a  serious  attempt  to 
give  an  account  of  the  world  on  a  scientific  plan,  to  apply  the 
same  method  to  the  problems  of  outward  and    inward    ex- 
perience, and  to  combine  the  results  into  a  consistent  whole. 
He  saw,  with  clearness  and  boldness  then  without  parallel, - 
that  physiology  was  a  branch  of  physical  knowledge,  and  to 
be  investigated  on  just  the  same  principles  as  every  other 
branch.     He  saw  that  philosophy  must  leave  science   alone 
with  the  things  which  pertain  to  science  ;  that  the  business  of 
philosophy  is  not  with  the  particulars  which  fall  within  the 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  107 

province  of  scientific  inquiry,  but  with  the  interpretation  of 
the  facts  of  experience  which  for  science  are  ultimate.  We 
have  no  right  to  be  offended  or  even  surprised  when  his 
execution  falls  short  of  his  intentions.  He  knew  that  he 
ought  not  to  be  imposed  upon  by  words  or  dogmatic  fictions, 
but  it  was  only  natural  that  he  should  in  many  cases  be  un- 
consciously led  away  by  them.  There  is  another  disturbing 
influence,  unfortunately,  which  has  to  be  allowed  for  in  con- 
sidering Descartes'  work  as  a  whole ;  I  mean  his  attitude  of 
extreme  caution  towards  the  Church.  It  is  certain  that  he  , 
was  much  hampered  by  the  danger  of  an  open  conflict  with 
orthodoxy,  which  he  was  determined  to  avoid  at  almost  any 
cost.  As  it  was,  all  his  astuteness  was  too  little  to  save  him- 
self or  his  immediate  followers  from  ecclesiastical  hostility 
which  was  even  more  bitter  in  the  Protestant  Netherlands 
than  in  any  part  of  the  Catholic  world,  and  which,  though  it 
never  rose  to  the  importance  of  a  persecution,  was  able  in 
various  ways  to  inflict  considerable  inconvenience.  It  would 
be  neither  generous  nor  wise  to  ascribe  Descartes'  hesitation 
and  reticence  in  the  face  of  these  difficulties  to  mere  personal 
timidity.  He  had  a  sincere  aversion  to  controversies  of  this 
kind  and  a  sincere  dread  of  violent  changes.  He  would  have 
liked  the  Church  to  adopt  modern  science  and  philosophy  ; 
failing  that,  he  was  content  that  they  should  be  left  unmo- 
lested, and  thought  it  no  harm  to  secure  immunity,  if 
necessary,  by  silence  on  some  points  and  transparent 
dissimulation  on  others.  Certain  apologetic  passages  in 
Descartes'  physical  writings  are  as  manifestly  ironical  as 
anything  in  Hume.  Open  defiance  must  have  appeared  to 
him  an  impracticable  policy,  and  disastrous,  if  it  had  been 
practicable,  both  for  society  and  for  science  itself.  These j 
questions,  however,  do  not  touch  the  physical  side  of  Des-| 
cartes'  teaching,  as  to  which  there  is  no  suspicion  of  reserve. 
And  it  was  on  this  side,  as  I  conceive,  that  Spinoza  first 
approached   him   and   felt   his  power.      In   Spinoza's  earliest 


io8  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

essay  the  psychology  shows  a  reader  of  Descartes,  but  a  reader 
very  far  from  being  a  disciple  ;  the  physics,  on  the  other  hand, 
are  simply  and  solely  Cartesian. 

Yet,  while  the  influence  of  Descartes'  philosophical  con- 
ceptions on  Spinoza  has  over  and  over  again  been  discussed, 
sometimes  with  exaggeration,  sometimes  with  depreciation, 
the  not  less  important  and  certainly  more  persistent  influence 
of  his  physical  conceptions  has  passed,  so  far  as  I  am  aware, 
almost  without  notice.'  The  very  peculiar  account  of  motion 
given  by  Descartes  was  not  only  repeated  by  Spinoza,  as  in 
duty  bound,  in  his  'Principles  of  Cartesian  Philosophy,'  but 
occurs  in  the  '  Essay  on  God  and  Man,'  and  has  left  its  traces 
in  the  *  Ethics.'  I  venture  to  say  that  without  going  back  to 
the  Cartesian  theory  of  dynamic  Spinoza's  account  of  the 
material  world  is  not  intelligible. 

We  read  in  Spinoza  of  '  certain  things  immediately  pro- 
duced by  God,'  which,  though  individual  things,  are  infinite 
in  their  kind,  and  necessary  in  an  eminent  manner,  as  being 
coextensive  with  the  attribute  or  aspect  of  existence  to  which 
they  belong.  What  these  things  are  is  not  stated  in  the 
Ethics  ;  the  explanation  must  be  sought  partly  in  one  of  the 
later  letters,  partly  in  the  early  essay  which  has  already 
come  before  us.^  In  this  last  the  following  explanation  is 
given. 

'As  concerning  Natiira  nahirata  in  general,  that  is,  the 
modes  or  creatures  which  immediately  depend  on  God  or  are 
created  by  him,  of  such  we  know  two  and  no  more  ;  namely, 
motions  in  matter,  and  understanding  in  the  thinking  thing.. 
Of  these  we  say  that  they  have  been  from  all  eternity,  and  to 
all  eternity  shall  remain  unchangeable,  a  work  verily  as  great 
as  beseemed  the  greatness  of  the  master-worker.' 

'  Professor  Sigwart,  however,  has  indicated  the  point  here  discussed  and  its 
significance.   Spinoza's  Neuentdeckter  Ti-adat,  &c.  Gotha,  1 866,  p.  49. 

2  Eth.  I,  propp.  21,  23,  and  28,  schol.  ;  Ef.  66,  §  8  ;  Korte  Verhandeling, 
part  i.  cap.  9,  to  which  there  is  an  odd  note,  presumably  by  a  transcriber,  stating 
that  the  author  really  thought  motion  itself  to  be  capable  of  further  e.xplanation. 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  109 

The  subject  of  motion  is  not  pursued,  as  more  properly- 
belonging  to  a  treatise  on  natural  science.  Motion  and 
understanding,  the  eternal  and  immutable  creatures,  are  called 
by  a  startling  Hebraism  Sons  of  God.  Indications  of  this 
kind  have  their  value  as  showing  that  Spinoza  was  really 
striving  to  find  a  scientific  interpretation  for  mystical  con- 
ceptions. Not  less  significant  is  the  disappearance  of  such 
language  from  the  Ethics.  We  find  it  stated,  again,  that 
extended  bodies  differ^jVom  one  another  only  in  'proportion 
ofjlggLgil^  motion  ;'  and,  what  is  still  more  extraordinary, 
we  hear  of  a  body  being  set  in  motion  by  the  impact  of  an- 
other body '^iii'/;/^  ;;/^//^«^rrrt/t'r  than  its  jrst}  In  the  '  Trac- 
tatus  Theologico-Politicus '  {c.  vii.  §  27)  we  read  of  'res  max- 
ime  universales  et  toti  naturae  communes,  videlicet  motum  et 
quietem,  eorumque  leges  et  regulas,'  which,  though  it  might 
excite  little  attention  by  itself,  is  significant  in  connexion  with 
other  passages.  And  in  a  letter  as  late  as  1675  he  gives 
Motion  and  Rest  as  examples  of  the  '  things  immediately 
produced  by  God.'     Motion  and  Rest,  then,  were  for  Spinoza 

not  relative  terms  describing  the  state  of  bodies  with  regard ^_ 1., 

to  eacTi  other,  but  in  some  sense  and  for  some  purposes  real_^      ||f/v»l 
things.      Indeed   he   all  but  defined    Matter    as   Extension 
modified  by  Rest  and  Motion. 

For  the  key  to  these  ideas  we  must  look  to  the  second 
part  of  Descartes'  '  Principia  Philosophiae,'  closely  followed  by 
Spinoza  himself  in  the  professed  exposition  cf  Cartesian  doc- 
trine which  was  his  first  published  work.  Descartes  tells  us 
that  the  nature  of  matter,  or  body  generally  considered^  does^  . 


not  consist  m  hardness,  weight,  or  aiiy^omex., sensible  quality, 
but  onlv  in  extension  in  three  dimensions  :  and  that  all  matter 
is  ultimately  homogeneous  ('  in  toto  univcrso  una  et  cadcm 
existit '),  and  all  the  differences  in  its  sensible^ropH^ics  dc- 
pend  ori"~3rfferences  oT"  motion  ('omnis  materiae  variatio,  sive 


.mil  iw^nw**^'"'  '""' 


'  Koite  Verk.,  part  ii.  note  ad  init.  (I  have  no  doubt  tliat  tliis  note  is  Spinoza's 
own),  and  cap.  19  (pp.  49,  99  in  Schaaisclunidt's  ed.).     Cf,  E/liics,  4,  39. 


no  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

omnium  eius  formarum  diversitas,  pendet  a  motu  ').  The  re- 
lative nature  of  motion  is  clearly  enough  pointed  out  ('nullum 
esse  permahente'ifr  lillius  rei  loeum,  nisi  quafeTius'arcogitatione 
nostra  determinatur  '),  and  the  same  illustration  of  it  is  given 
which  has  (no  doubt  independently)  been  repeated  by  Mr. 
Herbert  Spencer  "('  First  Principles,'  c.  3,  §  17). 

Thus  far  the  modern   reader  may  follow  Descartes  with 
admiration  ;  but  then  it  is  laid    down  that_the  quantity  of 
motion  in  the  universe  is  constant,  a  pfgposttion  whictt'''t3*ae-  ' 
monifrated  2?7^mrr'Tfdm"thrp^^ 

presunie  that" God "oMetveT^tKe"'!^^^  in  all  his 

operations,  and  we  muSt~frst'§uppo'sFany"clTahges  in  his  works 
which  are  not  actually  known  by  experience  or  revelation. 
Hence  we  are  to  "believe  that'  in  'the  begmnjn^Jhecreateda 
certam^uantity  of  motion  and  rest,  and  preserves  them_.un-^_ 
changedT'nnaferiani  siifiuraIm"moUriet"q  in  principio 

creavit,  iamque  per  solum  suum  concursum  ordinarium  tan- 
tundem  motus  et  quietis  in  ea  tota,  quantum  tunc  posuit,  con- 
servat.'   The  addition  of  rest,  as  if  that  also  were  a  real  thing, 
is  shown  by  the  context  to   be  merely  rhetorical.     Spinoza 
may  have  been  misled  by  it,  or  his  own  language  may  be 
nothing  but  an  excessive  imitation  of  Descartes.     It  would 
seem,  indeed,  that  Descartes  himself  was  not  free  from  con- 
fusion on  this  point  ;  for  some  paragraphs  later  he  speaks  of 
motion  as  contrary  to  rest,  and  of  speed  as  contrary  to  slow- 
ness, '  in  so  far  as  such  slowness  partakes  of  the  nature  of 
rest.'      Spinoza,  again,  speaks  elsewhere  of  finite  existence  as 
'  de  nihilo  participans,'  partaking  of  nullity  ('  Cogit.  Met'  pt.  ii. 
c.  3,  §  I)  ;  but  he  certainly  did  not  regard  Nothing  as  a  real 
thing.     Here,  then,  we  have  tjie  conservation  of  motiojojajd 
Idown    by    Descartes   as   a    first    principle    of    phvsks_-attd 
taken  over  by  Spinoza  without  question.      The  first  remark 
/that  occurs  on  it  is  that,  however  we  take  the  supposed  prin- 
|ciple,  it  is  not  true ;  and  it  is  almost  impossible  to  believe 
that  the  supposed  proof  of  it  was  satisfying  to  the  inventor 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  in 

himself.  Yet  Descartes  had  a  perfectly  distinct  and  right 
intention,  and  one  may  even  say  that  he  came  near  to  a  de- 
finite truth.  But  unhappily  he  had  not  the  patience  to  abstain 
from  premature  generalization  ;  he  violated  all  the  rules  of 
sound  scientific  method,  including  his  own  maxims,  and  his 
haste  led  him  into  deep  and  irreparable  error.  He  was  added 
to  the  number  of  those  mighty  ones  who  in  their  search  for 
the  truth  of  things  have,  as  Lucretius  says,  mightily  fallen  : 
'  graviter  magno  magni  cecidere  ibi  casu.' 

By  quantity  of  motion  Descartes  meant  what  is  now  called 
mofnentu'm^^qua.n tify  measure^Hby  mass  aad  velocity  jointly. 
The"^term  'quantity  of  motion '  Has  indeed  been  p/eserved  as 
a  synonym' Tor  inomentum  In  several  modern  books.  Now 
velocityT^aiKf  therefore  momEifurii^"^ 
direction  as  weiras^magnttude.  It  seems  unaccountable  that 
Descartes  should  have  neglected  to  consider  this,  but  he  did 
neglect  it.  He  took  a  sum  of  directed  quantities  all  over  the 
universe,  in  all  directions  indiscriminately,  and  asserted  that 
it  was  constant :  his  proposition  would  symbolically  be  ex- 
pressed thus — X  (mv)  =  C.  This  is  not  only  untrue  but 
unintelligible.  For,  motion^  and  velocity  being  relative  (as 
Descartes  himself,  strange  to  say,  well  knew),  w£_arejiQL.tald. 
how  the  velocity  is  to  be  estimated.  Descartes  took  no  ac- 
count whatever  of  direction,  holding  the  nature  of  motion  in 
itself  to  be  something  apart  from  its  direction,  which  he  calls 
'  the  determination  of  motion  towards  this  or  that  part  ; '  and 
this  is  further  made  clear  by  the  application  of  his  principle 
which  immediately  follows.  He  considers  various  cases  of  the 
collision  of  two  bodies  on  the  assumption  that  the  total  quan- 
tity of  motion  must  remain  the  same  after  the  collision  as 
before 7  andlHOr^^^^  quantity  as  still  being  the  same 

when  the  direction  is  reversed.  The  most  curious  confusion 
of  all  is  that,  after  duly  warning  us  that  the  two  bodies  in 
question  must  be  regarded  as  an  independent  system  (*  a 
reliquis  omnibus  sic  divisa  ut  eorum  motus  a  nullis  aliis  cir- 


112  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE   AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

cumiacentibus  impedirentur  nee  iuvarentur '),  he  proceeds  to 
speak  of  cases  in  which  one  of  them  is  absolutely  at  rest, 
and  other  cases  in  which  they  are  moving  with  different  velo- 
cities. The  results  he  obtains  are  in  part  wholly  wrong,  in 
part  such  as  might  be  theoretically  true  in  a  limiting  and 
physically  impossible  case.  Spinoza  was  apparently  satisfied 
with  all  Descartes'  rules  except  one.     (Ep.  I5,§  lo). 

Had  Descartes  attended  to  the  truth  that  direction  is  in- 
separable from  momentum,  he  might  have  lighted  upon -Jthe 
perfectlyjtrue  proposition  that  momentum  in  a  given  dityction 
js  conserved.  ..This  is  a  corollary  from  Newton's  Third  Law 
of  Motion,  that  action  and  reaction  are  equal  and  opposite. 
For,  if  any  change  took  place  in  the  momentum  of  a  system 
resolved  along  any  particular  direction  whatever,  such  change 
would  be  due  to  an  inequality  between  action   and   reaction 
measured   in   that  direction,  which   is  what  the  third  law  of 
motion  excludes.'     But  Newton's  third  law  was  unknown  to 
Descartes  ;  and  in  truth  its  scope  and  importance  have  only 
in  late  years  been  redeemed  from  general  neglect.    Descartes, 
however,  had  a  grand  object  in  his  speculations  on   the  first 
principles  of  physics.     He  could  not  be  expected  to  know 
that  it  was  unattainable  with  the  means  at  his  command,  and 
the   importance  of  the  conception    may  almost  excuse  his 
rashness  in  clutching  at  it  and  seizing  a  phantom.     He  was 
I  in  search  of  a  principle  which  should  enable  him  to  deal  with 
i,^|  the  material  universe  as  a  machine  self-acting  and  complete 
in'itself.     Given  a  certain  disposition  of  matter  and  motion, 
the  whole  future  series  of  phenomena  was  to  be  involved  in 
I  it,  and  was  to  follow  without  any  necessity  for  a  renewal  of 
1  interference  from  outside.     Theological  criticism  was  met,  if 
'  not  disarmed,  by  postulating  an  original  creative  act  to  endow 
the  matter  of  the  universe  with  its  fixed  '  quantity  of  motion.' 
Descartes  was  in  truth  feeling  about,  without  sufficient  light, 

'  The   proposition  was  also  correctly  enounced  by  Leibnitz  :    O/era  Philo- 
sophica  (ed.  Erdmann,  Berlin,  1840),  pp.  108,  133. 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY. 


113 


?  .<  { 


1 


for  some  such  general  doctrine  as  that  which  is  now  known  as 
the-Conservation  of  Energ}^  ;  and"  if IthaTBeeiTin  tlie~nature     , 
of  things  that  the  Conservation  of  Energy,  or  anything  equi-     : 
valent  to  it,  should  be  either  discovered  or  proved  a  priori,    I 
Descartes  would  in  all  probability  have  done  it.     His  con-    1 
temporaries  were  too  much  dazzled  by  the  brilliance  of  his    ; 
system  to  perceive  its  scientific  weakness.     Spinoza,  full  ofoi 
the    Hebrew  conviction  of  the  perfect  unity  of  the  divine    ■ 
nature  and  of  its  manifestations  in   the  sensible  world,  and    i 
determined  to  carry  that  principle  to  its  utmost  consequences, 
found  in   Descartes  a  seeming  demonstration,  on  grounds  of 
scientific  evidence,  of  that "iliiity'ahd  uiiiformity  m  th'e  piy- 
sical  world  which  specufation  had  already  led  him  to  expect, 
and  it  must  have  come  upon  liim  almost  as  a  revelation. 

It  is  curious  that  Spinoza's  language  about  Motion  and 
Rest,  derived  as  we  have  seen  from  the  most  confused  and 
erroneous  part  of  the  Cartesian  physics,  is  nevertheless  in  a 
manner  capable  of  a  rational  interpretation.  He  is  asked  to 
name  the  particular  things  which  are  infinite  in  their  kind,  and 
necessary  to  the  existence  of  finite  things  of  the  same  kind. 
Matter  he  does  not  count  as  such  (at  least  not  in  the  first 
rank),  though  Tn  his  view' the"  material  universe  ~may  be 
considered  as  an  individual  whole  no  less  than  any  part  of  it. 
Probably  he  regarded  matter  as  nothing  but  figured  exten- 
sion;  and  the  visible  universeV  'Tacies  totius  universi,'  in- 
volves change  and  motion.  ' He "fiames  accordingly  '  motus  et 
quies,'  as  being,  in  the  attribute  of  extension,  the  examples  A 
desired.  Now  if  for  motus  we  might  read  energy  of  motion,  cL 
and  for  quies  energy  of  position,  we  should  have  a  fairly  P^A'^'^^ 
plausible  result.  Energy  is,  according  to  the  notions  of  J 
modern  physics,  the  most  fundamental  property  of  the  sen- 
sible universe,  coextensive  with  it,  and  necessary  to  every- 
thing that  happens  in  it.  Every  physical  event  may  be 
regarded  as  a  transference  of  energy.  Again,  though  kinetic 
energy  and  potential  energy,  taken  separately,  are  not  con- 

I 


114  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY.' 

stant,  the  sum  of  them  is  constant  ;  so  that,  if  anything  iny 
the  physical  world    is  to  be  called  infinite  and  immutable, 
Energy,  taken  as  this  sum,  appears  to  have  a  good  enough 
claim    to   the   title.     And   thus   (if  we   chose   to   disregard 
historical   facts   and  conditions)  we  might  find  in  Spinoza's 
dark  saying  a  kind  of  prophetic  vision,  and  assign  to  him 
the  glory  of  having  pointed  the  way  to  the  latest  generaliza- 
tion  of  science.     But  this  fancy  would  of  course  be  wholly 
untenable  ;  first,  because  it  was  no  more  possible  for  Spinoza 
than  for  Descartes  to  arrive  at  the  modern  conception  of  the 
Conservation  of  Energy  ;  secondly,  because  we  have   fixed 
Spinoza's  phrase  to  its  only  admissible  meaning  by  tracing  it 
to  its  Cartesian  origin.     Why  then,  it  may  be  asked,  do  I  go 
out  of  the  way  to  suggest  the  possibility  of  such  a  fancy }     I 
reply  that  the  example  is  not  uninstructive  as  showing  what 
caution    must    be   used    in  assigning   a  meaning  to  obscure 
language   in  the  philosophy  of  past   generations,   and    how 
ini^ortant  it  is,  where  practicable,  to  ascertain  the'history  of 
ytfie  ideas  and  terms  we  have  to  do  with. 
^        At  the  same  time  we  have  indications  that  towards  the 
end  of  his  life  Spinoza  had  become  deeply  dissatisfied  with 
the  physical  conceptions  of  Descartes.     This  appears  by  his 
last  letters  to  Tschirnhausen  (in  the  year  1676).     Tschirn- 
hausen  asks  (Ep.  69)  how  Spinoza  would  proved  priori  the 
existence  of  bodies  figured  and   in   motion,  extension  in  the 
abstract  being  conceivable  without  any  such  thing.     Spinoza 
makes    answer    thus :    '  From    extension    as    conceived    by 
Descartes,  that  is,  an  inert  mass  (molem  quiescentem),  it  is  not 
only,  as  you  say,  difficult,  but  altogether  impossible  to  prove  the 
"Existence  of  bodies.    For  matter  at  rest  will,  so  far  as  in  it  lies, 
persist  in  its  rest,  and  will  not  be  impelled  to  motion  unless 
by  a  more  powerful  external  cause,  and  for  this  reason  I  long 
ago  did  not  hesitate  to  affirm  that  the  Cartesian  principles  of 
natural  philosophy  are  useless,  not  to  say  absurd.'^  Tschirn- 
hausien  replied  that  Descartes  did  not,  in  his  opinion,  profess  to 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  115 

account  for  the  existing  material  universe  as  a  product  of  inert 
matter,  since  he  supposes  matter  to  have  been  animated  with 
motion  by  a  creative  act.     Spinoza  was  unable,  probably  by 
reason  of  increasing  ill  health,  to  keep  up  the  discussion  at  any 
length.    His  rejoinder  is  in  these  terms  :  '  As  to  your  question 
whether  the  variety  of  existing  things  can  be  proved  a  priori 
from  the  mere  conception  of  extension,  I  think  I  have  already 
sufficiently  shown  that  it  is  impossible  ;  and  that  therefore 
matter  is  ill  defined  by  Descartes  as  identical  with  extension 
(materiam  a  Cartesio  male  definiri  per  extensionem),  but  must 
necessarily  be  explained  by  an  attribute  which  expresses  an 
eternal  and  infinite  nature.     But  perhaps  I  will  discourse  of 
this  more  clearly  with  you  some  day,  if  life  suffices  me.     For 
hitherto  I  have  not  been  able  to  set  down  anything  orderly  on 
the  matter.'  The  opportunity  for  fuller  explanation  never  came, 
and    the   passage  as  it  stands  is,   like  others  in    the    same 
correspondence,   somewhat  obscure.     One  would  expect  theo 
meaningf  to  be  that  matter  without  motion  is  as  inconceivable 
as  matter  without  extension,  so  that  Descartes'  assumption 


that  matter  was  there  first,  as  anTnert  lump,  and  motion  was^ 
"ptrt~TTTtO"it  afterwards,  is"  illegitimate  and  irrational.     But  if 
Spinoza  meant  this,  I  cannot  see  why  he  should  not  have  said 
it  with  his  usual  distinctness. 

At  any  rate  it  is  pretty  clear  that  the  Cartesian  conception 
of  material  substance  as  consisting  merely  in  extension — the 
confusion  of  matter  with  space,  as  Professor  Clerk  Maxwell 
lias'called  it' — which  leaves  the  fact  and  the  idea  of  mass  in- 
explicable, and  leads  to  motion  being  incbnsistehtly  regarded, 
now  as  an  ens  rationis  like  the  configuration  of  a  system  or 
part'  of  space,... Jio.w  as  a  kind  of  thing-in -itself,  was  not 
accepted  by  Spinoza  in  his  later  days.  This  alone  would  not 
show  that  he  did   not  accept  it  when  he  wrote  the  '  Ethics,' 

'  Clerk  Ma.\well  was  living  when  these  lines  were  written  :  I  cannot  let  them 
pass  through  the  press  without  adding  a  word  of  tribute  to  a  man  of  profound  and 
original  genius,  too  early  lost  to  England  and  to  science. 

1  2 


ii6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

but  it  is  enough   to  make  us  wary  in  reading  those  propo- 
sitions which  involve  physical  ideas. 

Another  physical  proposition  given  by  Descartes,  and 
included  in  Newton's  first  law  of  motion,  appears  to  have 
furnished  the  groundwork  of  the  more  general  proposition 
used  by  Spinoza  as  the  starting  point  of  human  psychology 
and  ethics.    Descartes  says  ('  Princ.  Phil.'  2,  c.  37)  th^t'every- 

thing,  in  so  far  as  it  is  simple  and.undivi^ed,  remainSj^a.s  much 

«~"  ,      ,  ^  .-- -. — ...-.-.  .—  -■-  ■~         —^ 

as^in  jt  lies,  in  the  same  condition,,  and  suffers  no  change 
unless  from  external  causes.'  Spinoza,  in  his  manual  of 
Cartesian  philosophy,  repeats  the  proposition  in  almost  the 
same  words.  '  Unaquaeque  res,  quatenus  simplex  et  indivisa 
est,  et  in  se  sola  consideratur,  quantum  in  se  est,  semper  in 
eodem  statu  perseverat'  The  demonstration  he  gives  is 
framed  in  such  general  terms  as  to  show  that  he  regarded  the 
proposition  as  not  merely  physical  ;  Descartes  having  already 
treated  it  as  the  most  general  law  of  physical  action  ('  Princ. 
Phil.'  2,  c.  43).  And  in  the  '  Cogitata  Metaphysica,'  published 
as  an  appendix  to  this  work,  wc  find  the  general  idea  of  the 
i seTT-presSvl rig' efr6rt~'6F  things,  '  conatus  quo  res  in  statu  suo 
pefs'evef are  "conantu'r.'  This  effort,  Spinoza  says,  is  in  truth 
Tiothing  else  than  the  thing  itself;  or,  as  we  should  now  say, 
the  fact  of  the  thfhg "being' there.  And  he  gives  the  first  law 
of  rnotion  as  a  simple  example."''  Motion  has  the  power  of 
persisting  in  its  actual  condition.  Now  this  power  is  nothing 
else  than  the  motion  itself,  that  is,  the  fact  that  such  is  the 
nature  of  motion'  ^  ('  Cogit.  Met.'  pt.  i.  c.  6,  §  9).  In  the  '  Essay 
on  God  and  Man '  is  a  curious  chapter  (pt.  i.  c  .5)  in  which  Provi- 
dence is  explained  as  identical  with  the  self-preserving  effort. 
Let  us  now  turn  to  the  sixth  and  seventh  propositions  in 
the  third  book  of  the  '  Ethics.'  '  Unaquaeque  res,  quantum 
in  se  est,  in  suo  esse  perseverare  conatur : '  every  particular 
thing,  so  much  as  in  it  lies,  endeavours  to  persist  in  its   own 

J  Or  perhaps,  '  of  the  particular  motion  : '  but  if  that  had  been  the  meaning 
Spinoza  would  probably  have  written  tstiits  motus. 


SOUJ^CES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  117 

being.  '  Conatus,  quo  unaquaeque  res  in  suo  esse  perseverare 
conatur,  nihil  est  praeter  ipsius  rei  actualem  essentiam  :  *  the 
endeavour  wherewith  everything  strives  to  persist  in  its  being 
--is  nothing  else  than  the  fact  of  the  thing  being  what  it  is. 
The  physical  aspect  of  the  proposition  may  be  stated  in 
modern  language  by  saying  that  no  change  of  configuration 
takes  place  without  work  being  done ;  this  gets  rid  of  the 
objectionable  term  conatus,  and  dispenses  with  the  auxiliary 
proposftion  which  Spinoza  required  to  guard  against  the 
illusions  it  might  lead  to.  Both  the  conception  and  the 
name  of  the  self-preserving  endeavour  are  older,  possibly 
much  older,  than  Descartes ; '  but  the  connexion  between 
Spinoza's  proposition  and  Descartes'  so-called  first  law  of  | 
nature  appears  to  be  sufficiently  made  out  by  comparison  of  \\ 
the  passages  above  given.^ 

Here  again  we  are  led  to  remark  the  importance  of  histor- 
ical criticism.  It  would  be  easy,  notwithstanding  Spinoza's 
own  warning,  to  find  in  the  conatus  an  inkling  of  the  struggle 
for  existence,  as  we  now  call  it,  which  is  so  important  in  the 
modern  scientific  account  of  the  world.  It  has  even  been 
suggested  that  Spinoza  here  anticipates  the  doctrine  of  evo- 
lution. But  the  facts  are  inexorable.  There  is  no  more  of 
evolution  in  Spinoza  than  in  Descartes  ;  there  is  in  one  sense 
the  general  idea  of  evolution  in  both,  namely,  that  the  whole 
physical  universe,  animate  as  well  as  inanimate,  is  to  be  ac- 

'  Giordano  Bruno  speaks  of  a  '  desio  di  conservarsi '  as  common  to  all 
creatures.  In  Dante,  De Monarchia,  i,  §  15,  we  find  it  assumed  as  a  principle  that 
'  omne  quod  est  appetit  suum  esse.'  A  similar  maxim  was  familiar  to  the  Stoics. 
'  They  say  that  the  first  impulse  of  every  living  thing  is  directed  to  self-preservation 
(fTrJ  rb  Tr)pe7v  eavT6  ),  .  .  .  and  the  proposition  is  thus  stated  by  Chr)'sippus  in 
his  first  book  on  Ends,  that  the  first  property  of  every  living  creature  is  the  con- 
scious maintenance  of  itself  (rijv  avrov  crvcrracriv  kuI  Ti]v  ravT-rfs  (TvvfiStitnv).  Diog. 
L.  vii.  85  (ap.  Ritter  and  Preller,  §  420).  I  have  not  been  able  to  trace  the  idea 
much  farther  back.  So  far  as  I  can  learn  (though  I  speak  with  difhdence)  it  is 
not  in  Aristotle  ;  but  it  is  discoverable  in  the  later  Peripatetics.  See  the  frag- 
ment on  the  Stoics  in  Grote's  Aristotle. 

"^  It  is  briefly  noticed  by  Trendelenburg,  Historische  Beitrdge  zur  Philosophie, 
ii.  82. 


U 


ii8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

counted  for  by  physical  causes.  What  the  doctrine  of  evolu- 
tion has  done  is  to  put  this  idea  into  forms  whereby  it  becomes 
capable  of  definite  scientific  treatment,  and  leads  to  definite 
results.  The  point  is  not  to  see  that  there  is  in  nature  a  con- 
stant endeavour,  or  even  competition,  of  individuals  and  kinds 
to  preserve  their  existence,  but  to  see  that  the  competition  is 
itself  an  orderly  process,  and  that  existing  forms  are  worked 
out  by  it  in  ways  which  may  be  investigated  and  reduced  to 
law.  This  belongs  to  natural,  not  to  speculative  philosophy  ; 
the  most  the  speculative  philosopher  can  do  is  to  know  his 
own  business  and  leave  the  road  clear  for  natural  history. 
And  this  is  the  credit  I  would  claim  for  Spinoza,  not  the  gift 
of  prophecy  but  the  gift  of  discernment.     But  we  shall  return 

j  to  this  hereafter. 

I  Thus  much  of  Descartes'  physical  doctrines  in  their  rela- 
tion to  Spinoza.  As  to  his  philosophy  in  general,  there  is  no 
X  doubt  that  Spinoza  was  profoundly  influenced  by  his  doctrine 
of  method  and  by  his  manner  of  approaching  metaphysical 
and  psychological  questions.  Indeed  it  could  not  have  been 
otherwise.  At  the  time  when  Spinoza's  mind  was  opening  to- 
philosophy,  and  his  powers  ripening  for  independent  work, 
Descartes  was  still  in  the  first  flush  of  his  renown.  Every 
student  who  meant  to  think  for  himself  would  turn  eagerly  to 
Descartes  as  the  liberator  who  had  set  reason  on  a  new  footing. 
Spinoza  necessarily  dAvelt  in  a  Cartesian  atmosphere  and 
drew  his  life  from  it.  But,  however  much  Spinoza  must  have 
admired  the  height  and  range  of  Descartes'  genius,  and  been 
fascinated  by  the  brilliance  of  his  invention,  he  found  the 
actual  performance  wanting.  Reasons  have  been  given,  in 
the  foregoing  notice  of  the  '  Essay  on  God  and  Man,'  for  believ- 
ing that  Spinoza  was  never  a  Cartesian  in  metaphysics  ;  it  is 
certain  that  in  psychology  he  came,  though  more  gradually, 
to  a  marked  divergence  from  Cartesian  opinions  ;  and  we  have 
just  seen  that  even  in  physics,  where  until  the  advent  of  New- 
ton Descartes  seemed  to  reign  without  a  rival,  Spinoza  did 


SOURCES  OF  SPINOZA'S  PHILOSOPHY.  119 

not  give  him  unreserved  allegiance.  When  he  wrote  his  early 
essay,  Spinoza  had  already  made  up  his  mind  to  reject  the 
metaphysical  dualism  of  Descartes  ;  the  conception  of  spirit 
and  matter  as  two  distinct  substances  is  entirely  put  aside. 
On  the  other  hand  he  still  so  far  adhered  to  Cartesian  psy- 
chology as  to  hold  that  interaction  took  place  between  the 
mind  and  the  body  by  means  of  the  *  animal  spirits,'  the 
direction  of  whose  motion,  tHoiigh  not  the  motion  itself,  could 
be  changed  by  a  purely  mental  act.  This  was  tfie  philoso- 
phical use  of  the  fallacious  distinction  made  by  Descartes 
between  motion  and  its  direction  or  'determination  towards 
this  or  that  part*  It  enabled  Kim  to  assign,  as  he  thought,  a 
point  of  contact  for  the  material  and  the  immaterial  worlds, 
and  not  only  to  leave  room  for  the  operation  of  free  will  but 
to  give  a  scientific  explanation  of  it.  The  will  could  impress 
as  much  change  as  might  be  required  on  the  direction  of  the 
animal  spirits  without  violating  the  axiom  of  the  conservation 
of  motion.'  Spinoza,  as  his  own  work  advanced,  perceived  the 
weakness  of  the  Cartesian  theory,  and  not  only  ceased  to  fol- 
low it  but  explicitly  controverted  it  in  the  '  Ethics.' 

Spinoza's  doctrine  of  the  unity  of  Substance  was  held  by 
him,  I  believe,  without  interruption  from  the  first  days  of  his 
philosophic  activity.  He  was  only  strengthened  in  it  by  ex- 
amination of  the  Cartesian  dualism  ;  and,  so  far  as  we  think 
of  his  opinion  on  this  point  in  relation  to  Descartes,  we  must 
think  of  it  as  a  critical  reaction  rather  than  a  development. 
It  is  true  that  philosophy  could  not  in  any  case  have  rested 
content  with  the  form  of  dualism  propounded  by  Descartes  ; 
the  school  of  Descartes  himself  did  not  so  rest.  He  had  drawn 
a  sharp  line  of  separation  between  the  subjective  and  objec- 
tive aspects  of  the  world,  the  mental  and  the  material  series 
of  phenomena,  without  making  any  distinct  attempt  to  show 
how  they  came  into  relation   and   correspondence  with  one 

'  Attempts  have  been  made  quite  lately  to  revive  this  invention  in  a  form 
adapted  to  modern  physical  knowledge .    ,      / 


I20  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

another.     The   gap   was  filled  up    by   the  ingenuity   of  his 
immediate  followers  with  the  doctrine  of  Occasional  Causes ; 
which  however  is  really  equivalent  to  giving  up  the  problem 
as  hopeless,  and  taking  refuge  in  a  perpetual  miracle.     Yet 
no   other   way  is    possible  so  long  as  the  fundamental  dis- 
(tinction  of  substances  is  retained.     Spinoza  saw  that  the  ap- 
parent explanation  was  no  explanation  at  all,  and  took  up 
the  question  again  from  the  beginning.     If  it  can  be  said, of 
him  that  he  only  continued  the  work  of  Descartes,  it  can  with 
equal  justice  be  said  of  Kant  that  he  only  continued  the  work 
3f  Hume.     Both  found  new  difficulties  probed  and  laid  bare, 
new  lines  of  search  indicated  by  their  great  precursors  ;  but 
the  problems  thus  started  had  in  the  one  case  been  solved 
imperfectly  or  erroneously,  in  the  other  they  were  conspicu- 
ously and  of  set  purpose  left  unsolved.     Kant  and  Spinoza,© 
men  of  widely  different  genius  and  considering  the  questions 
of  philosophy  under  widely  different    forms,  both  produced 
j  results  which  have  struck   deep   root  and    brought    forth    a 
manifold   harvest   in  the  subsequent    course   of  philosophic 
inquiry. 

Every  new  step  in  philosophy  is  a  continuation  of  the  ° 
last,  in  so  far  as  its  character  and  direction  are  determined  by 
that  which  has  been  found  wanting  in  the  account  of  things 
obtained  in  the  last  preceding  stage.  But  it  can  properly  be 
called  a  continuation  only  when  it  pushes  on  in  the  same 
direction,  not  when  it  comes  back  from  it  as  leading  nowhere 
and  strikes  out  a  distinct  one.  This  last  was  the  case  with 
Spinoza  as  regards  Descartes  ;  and  to  speak  of  his  philosophy 
as  a  branch  of  the  philosophy  of  Descartes  appears  to  me 
nothing  short  of  a  paradox. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  121 


CHAPTER   IV. 

THE   DOCTRINE   OF   METHOD. 

Et  j'avais  toujours  un  extreme  desir  d'apprendre  a  distinguer  le  vrai  d'avec  le 
faux,  pour  voir  clair  en  mes  actions  et  marcher  avec  assurance  en  cette  vie. — Des- 
cartes, Discours  de  la  Methode. 

The  best  general  introduction  to  the  philosophy  of  Spinoza 
is  perhaps  that  which  he  has  himself  given  us  in  his  unfinished 
work,  '  On  the  Amendment  of  the  Understanding.'  It  Avas 
begun  some  considerable  time  before  the  '  Ethics,'  probably 
on  the  suggestion  of  Descartes'  '  Discourse  on  Method,'  but 
on  a  much  larger  scale  ;  it  seems  to  aim  at  nothing  less  than<? 
a  complete  analytical  account  of  the  objects,  nature,  and 
instruments  of  philosophic  inquiry.  Thus  it  was  to  prepare 
the  way  for  a  constructive  exposition  which  is  now  represented, 
so  far  as  Spinoza  was  able  to  carry  it  out,  by  the  '  Ethics.' 
At  the  time  of  writing  this  treatise  his  designs  were  probably 
more  extensive  ;  and  changes,  though  not  fundamental  ones, 
had  come  over  his  opinions  in  some  points  before  the  '  Ethics  * 
assumed  their  present  form.  But  on  the  whole  the  '  De  In- 
tellectus  Emendatione'  stands  so  much  nearer  to  the  'Ethics' 
than  to  the  '  Essay  on  God  and  Man  '  that  it  may  be  fairly 
regarded  as  the  analytical  preface  to  Spinoza's  latest  work, 
bearing  to  it  some  such  relation  as  Descartes'  '  Discourse '  to 
his  '  Principles  of  Philosophy,'  or  Kant's  '  Prolegomena  '  to  the 
*  Kritik.'  Spinoza  himself,  if  we  may  trust  the  statement  of  his 
editors,  had  not  dropped  the  work  as  out  of  harmony  with 
his  later  views,  but  always  intended  to  take  it  up  and  finish 
it.     Several  of  the  foot-notes   attached   to  it  in  its  present 


122  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

shape  look  as  if  they  had  been  made  by  Spinoza  on  a  re- 
perusal  some  time  after  the  text  was  written,  and  were  meant 
as  memoranda  for  his  own  use  in  the  subsequent  revision  and 
completion  which  was  never  executed. 

The  treatise  begins  by  considering  the  futility  of  the 
common  objects  of  human  desire,  which  are  reduced  to  the 
heads  of  wealth,  power,  and  pleasures  of  sense.  All  these  are 
vain  and  precarious  in  themselves,  and  distract  the  mind 
from  the  pursuit  of  the  true  good.  But  is  not  that  pursuit 
also  precarious  t  and  if  for  its  sake  we  renoimce  that  which 
men  commonly  seek  after,  may  we  not  lose  the  substance  of 
life  for  a  shadow  ? 

The  answer  gives  in  a  few  sentences  the  whole  aim  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy.  '  After  I  had  somewhat  thought  over 
the  matter,  I  found,  in  the  first  place,  that  by  abandon- 
ing these  objects  and  undertaking  a  new  course  of  life  I 
should  abandon  a  good  uncertain  in  its  own  nature,  as  we 
may  plainly  gather  from  what  I  have  said,  for  one  uncer- 
tain, not  in  its  own  nature  (for  it  was  a  constant  good  I  was 
in  search  of)  but  only  as  to  the  attainment  of  it.  Further, 
I  came  by  persevering  reflexion  to  see  that  by  so  doing,  if 
only  I  could  thoroughly  weigh  the  question,  I  should  abandon 
certain  evils  for  a  certain  good.  For  I  perceived  that  I  was 
encompassed  by  the  utmost  danger,  and  drove  myself  to  seek 
a  remedy  with  all  my  power,  uncertain  as  it  might  be  ;  as 
one  sick  of  a  mortal  disease,  when  he  foresees  certain  death 
unless  a  remedy  be  applied,  is  driven  to  seek  that  remedy 
with  all  his  power,  uncertain  though  it  be,  and  his  whole  hope 
is  set  thereon.  Now  all  those  things  which  the  multitude 
pursue  not  only  provide  no  remedy  for  the  maintenance  of 
our  being,  but  actually  hinder  it,  and  are  oftentimes  the  occa- 
sion of  ruin  to  such  as  possess  them,  always  to  such  as  are 
possessed  by  them.'  .  .  .  Happiness  or  unhappiness  depends 
on  the  nature  of  the  object  whereon  we  fix  our  affection. 
Strife,    envy,  hatred,   and   .^ear  are  the  constant  penalty  of 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  123 

loving  perishable  things.  '  But  love  towards  a  thing  eternal 
and  infinite  feeds  the  mind  with  pure  joy,  and  is  wholly  free 
from  sorrow ;  this  is  to  be  greatly  desired  and  strenuously 
sought  for.' 

Spinoza,  like  Descartes,  tells  the  story  of  his  own  search  o 
for  truth,  taking  us  along  with  him  in  the  path  which  he 
struck  out,  and  retracing  with  us  the  steps  by  which  at  last 
he  found  himself  in  the  right  way.  But  the  difference  of  their  I 
ambitions  is  remarkable.  Descartgs  is  in  search,  not  of 
blessedness,  not  of  the  supreme  good,  but  of  certainty  for  the 
conduct  of  man's  action.  '  I  ever  had  an  exceeding  desire  to 
learn  how  to  distinguish  truth  from  falsehood,  that  I  might 
see  the  way  clearly  in  my  actions  and  walk  with  confidence 
in  this  life.'  There  was  no  ardent  disquietude  in  his  pursuit 
of  truth.  He  found  literature  instructive  and  agreeable  ; 
mathematics  admirable  and  useful  ;  theology  a  guide  to 
heaven  (whither  he  meant  to  go  no  less  than  any  other  man), 
but  too  lofty  for  terrestrial  uses  ;  philosophy  an  art  of  support- 
ing many  diverse  opinions  with  equally  plausible  reasons  ; 
and  special  branches  of  learning  appeared  to  him  in  the 
same  case  with  philosophy,  save  that  they  were  practical  roads 
to  wealth  and  honourable  employments.  From  the  pursuit 
of  these  he  could  stand  apart ;  he  knew  enough  of  vulgar 
imposture  and  delusion  to  be  proof  against  them  ;  and  having 
found  the  school  of  books  a  failure,  he  went  forth  into  the 
school  of  men.  It  was  only  after  some  years  that  in  the 
leisure  of  a  long  winter  he  turned  back  upon  himself  to  find 
some  better  foundations  of  knowledge  and  belief.  Meanwhile 
active  life  was  well  enough  ;  every  man  finds  at  least  some 
truth  in  attending  to  his  own  business,  for  therein  error 
brings  its  own  speedy  punishment.  As  for  the  common 
objects  of  men's  desires  and  undertakings,  their  vanity  is 
passed  over  with  the  briefest  mention.  What  may  be  the  real 
object  of  life  is  not  discussed,  not  even  glanced  at.  Know-  / 
ledge  is  enough   for  our  present  search,  Descartes  seems  to 


124  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

say.     Let  us  know  where  we  are,  and  then  there  will  be  time 
enough  for  the  rest. 

It  is  otherwise  with  Spinoza.  Following  a  more  ancient 
course  of  thought  than  that  struck  out  by  Descartes,  he  is 
impelled  by  the  futility  of  earthly  desires  to  set  forth  on  the 
quest  of  man's  true  and  perfect  good.  It  is  not  enough  foro 
him  to  satisfy  the  practical  need  of  '  walking  with  confidence 
in  this  life  ; '  he  would  fain  understand  the  consummation  of 
the  journey,  and  the  purpose  to  which  all  particular  know- 
ledge and  actions  are  subordinate.  The  life  of  courts  and 
camps,  the  field  of  varied  activity  and  observation  where 
Descartes  could  leave  his  questionings  aside  for  a  season,  was 
not  open  to  him.  He  set  himself,  without  delay  or  remission, 
to  attack  the  problem  of  life,  not  in  and  through  the  world, 
but  apart  from  it.  Descartes  assumes  tacitly  that  human  life 
is  good  to  a  reasonable  man  ;  Spinoza  assumes  that  there  is 
some  human  good  so  sure  and  so  permanent  that  by  find- 
ing it  the  reasonable  man  can  make  life  good  for  himself, 
and  help  others  to  find  it  good  also.  The  alternative  of  pes-o 
simism  does  not  occur  to  them  in  any  form.  Descartes 
certainly  had  no  reason  to  complain  of  the  world  ;  Spinoza, 
so  far  as  outward  circumstances  went,  had  as  little  reason  to 
praise  it.  But  for  each  of  them  it  was  equally  impossible  to 
devise  that  sort  of  stimulant  for  jaded  philosophical  appetites. 
They  lived  in  too  fresh  and  stirring  an  air. 

Spinoza's  early  mention  of  'love  towards  a  thin^  eternal 
and  infinite '  reminds  us  in  a  manner  of  the  '  Essay  on  God 
and  Man.'  But  the  following  paragraphs  no  less  foreshadow 
the  '  Ethics.'  He  does  not  rush  off  to  take  the  Chief  Good  by 
storm,  but  prepares  to  make  sure  of  it  by  artificially  conducted 
approaches.  But  for  the  glimpse  he  first  gave  us  we  should 
not  know  what  he  had  in  sight.  In  considering  what  is  the 
true  or  the  chief  good,  it  is  to  be  observed,  he  says,  that  good 
and  evil  are  only  relative  terms.  *  Nothing  regarded  in  its 
own    nature    is    to   be   called   either   perfect   or    imperfect  ; 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  125 

especially  when  we  are  satisfied  that  eveiything  which 
happens  does  so  according  to  an  eternal  order  and  fixed  laws 
of  nature.'  But  man  can  form  the  conception  of  a  human 
character  more  constant  than  his  own,  and  sees  that  it  is  pos- 
sible for  his  existing  character  to  be  improved  by  approach  to 
this  ideal.  He  casts  about  therefore  for  means  which  may 
help  him  towards  this  perfection  ;  everything  that  may  so 
help  him  is  a  true  good.  '  And  the  chief  good  is  to  bring  it 
to  pass  that  he,  together  with  other  persons,  if  so  it  may  be, 
may  be  endowed  with  such  a  character.  What  that  character 
is  we  shall  show  in  its  proper  place,  namely,  that  it  consists  in 
knowledge  of  the  union  which  the  mind  has  with  the  whole 
of  nature.  This  then  is  the  end  for  which  I  make,  to  acquire 
such  a  character,  and  to  labour  that  many  acquire  it  with  me  ; 
that  is,  it  belongs  to  my  happiness  to  endeavour  myself  that 
many  others  may  understand  the  same  that  I  do,  that  their 
understandings  and  desires  may  wholly  agree  with  mine.' 
Here  is  announced  the  essentially  social  nature  of  all  human 
morality  and  improvement,  which  we  afterwards  find  deve- 
loped in  the  '  Ethics.'  To  be  wise  alone  is  only  half  the 
battle,  and  the  lesser  half;  the  triumph  of  the  seeker  for 
wisdom  is  to  find  for  his  fellow-men  as  well  as  for  himself 
An  instructed  and  enlightened  society  must  be  formed  if  its 
members  are  to  attain  wisdom.  For  this  end  moral  philosophy 
and  the  science  of  education  must  be  cultivated  (and  how  far, 
two  centuries  after  Spinoza,  we  still  are  from  a  science  of 
education) ;  and  health  being  an  important  condition  of  our 
undertaking,  medicine  in  every  branch  is  to  be  perfected  ;  ^ 
nor  are  the  mechanical  arts  to  be  omitted  which  multiply  the 
convenience  of  life.  '  But  before  all  is  to  be  devised  a  method 
of  curing  the  understanding,  and  purifying  it  so  far  as  we  are 


'  Cf.  DescSiVtes,  Disc,  de /a  Mei/iode,  part  vi.  whose  hngutxgc  is  stronger.  .  .  . 
'  S'il  est  possible  de  trouver  quelque  moyen  qui  rende  communement  les  homtnes 
plus  sages  et  plus  habiles  qu'ils  n'ont  ete  jusqu'ici,  je  crois  que  c'est  dans  la 
medecine  qu'on  doit  le  cheicher.' 


126  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

able  at  this  stage,  that  it  may  succeed  in  understanding  things 
as  well  as  possible  and  without  error.'     Thus  the  scope  of  alio 
i    knowledge  is  the  same,  the  perfection  of  man's  nature  ;  and 
by  its  tendency  to  promote  that  end  its  usefulness  is  to  be 
judged. 

Some  provisional  rules  are  laid  down  for  the  conduct  of  life 
during  the  period  of  inevitable  ignorance,  but  they  are  of  nu 
great  moment.  One  of  them  looks  as  if  Spinoza  thought  it 
possible  at  one  time  that  a  guarded  and  judicious  introduc- 
tion of  his  opinions  would  save  them  from  being  unpopular. 
Then  we  come  to  the  degrees  of  perception,  or  as  we  should 
.  now  say,  knowledge. 

Four  kinds  are  enumerated.  We  may  learn  things  (i)by 
hearsay  or  on  authority  {ex  auditii)  ;  (2)  by  the  mere  sugges- 
tion of  experience  {ab  experientia  vaga  •)  ;  (3)  by  reasoning 
{essentia  rei  ex  alia  re  concluditiir)  ;  and  (4)  by  immediate  and 
complete  perception  {res  percipitur  per  solam  suam  essentiam). 
Thus  a  man's  birthday,  the  names  and  condition  of  his 
ancestors,  and  the  like,  are  known  to  him  by  hearsay ;  such 
matters  as  that  oil  increases  fire,  and  water  puts  it  out,  and  most 
things  that  make  up  the  common  knowledge  of  life,  he  knows 
by  unreasoned  experience  ;  while  by  reasoning  from  the 
known  properties  of  light  and  optical  instruments  we  correct 
the  illusions  of  our  sight  as  to  the  size  of  heavenly  bodies,  or 
from  our  peculiar  experience  of  our  own  bodies,  we  infer  that 
there  is  a  peculiar  relation  of  some  "kind  between  the  mind 
and  the  body.  We  know  immediately,  or  by  the  nature  of 
the  thing  alone,  a  few  of  the  simplest  and  most  general  truths. 
A  single  example,  however,  will  serve  to  illustrate  all  the 
kinds  of  knowledge  ;  and  this  example  alone  is  retained  in 
the  '  Ethics,'  where  the  classification  is  repeated,  but  tradition 
and    loose    experience    are    taken    together    as    sources   of 

'  This  is  a  Baconian  phrase.  A^'ov.  Org.  Aph.  lOO.  Sigwart,  Spinoza's 
Neuentdeckter  Tractat,  &c.  p.  157.  Prof.  Sigwart  s  other  evidences  of  Baconian 
influence  in  Spinoza's  treatise  are  not  so  clear ;  the  influence,  at  all  events,  was  a 
transitory  one. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  127 

knowledge  of  the  first  kind  ;  reasoning  forming  the  second 
kind,  and  intuition  the  third  and  highest.  The  example 
chosen  is  that  of  a  simple  arithmetical  proportion. 

'  Let  three  numbers  be  given  in  order  to  find  a  fourth,  which 
shall  be  to  the  third  as  the  second  to  the  first.  Tradesmen  have 
no  hesitation  in  multiplying  the  second  by  the  third  and  dividing  the 
product  by  the  first ;  either  because  they  have  not  forgotten  the  rule 
they  once  heard  from  a  master  without  any  proof  [knowledge 
ex  audiiii],  or  because  they  have  often  made  trial  of  it  with  simple 
numbers  [experietitia  vagd],  or  by  virtue  of  the  proof  in  the  nineteenth 
proposition  of  the  seventh  book  of  Euclid,  that  is,  by  the  general 
property  of  proportionals  [rafio  or  seaindi  gejieris  cogfiitio].  But  with 
very  simple  numbers  there  is  no  need  of  this.  For  example,  if  the 
given  numbers  be  i,  2,  3,  no  one  fails  to  see  that  the  fourth  pro- 
portional is  6  ;  and  this  much  more  clearly,  because  we  at  once 
infer  the  fourth  number  from  the  ratio  which  we  see  by  a  single 
intuitive  act  that  the  first  has  to  the  second.'  ' 

We  have  to  choose  between  these  modes  of  acquiring  in- 
formation as  the  means  of  arriving  at  exact  knowledge,  and 
thereby  at  the  greatest  possible  perfection  of  man's  nature. 
Tradition  and  loose  experience  are  obviously  uncertain  and 
untrustworthy.  It  was  Spinoza's  intention,  as  we  learn  by  his 
marginal  note,  to  discuss  in  this  place  the  whole  subject  of 
experimental  knowledge  and  research.  Reasoning  will  lead 
us  to  certainty,  if  rightly  carried  out  ;  '  yet  by  itself  it  will  not 
be  a  means  of  attaining  our  perfection.'  The  fourth  mode  of 
perception  alone  (the  third  kind  of  knowledge  in  the  nomen- 
clature of  the  '  Ethics  ')  is  the  only  one  which  is  both  adequate, 
as  giving  us  the  whole  nature  of  the  thing  perceived,  and  free 
from  risk.  Our  task  is  therefore  to  find  the  best  and  shortest 
way  for  bringing  things  at  present  unknown  to  us  within  its 
grasp.^ 

'  Now  that  we  have  learnt  what  knowledge  is  needful  for  us,  we 
have  to  deliver  a  way  and  method,  whereby  the  things  to  be  known 
sharfbeknown  with  that  kind  of  knowledge.     To  which  end  it  is 

'  Eth.  2,  40,  schol.  2.  -  Dc  Int.  Emend,  c.  5. 


128  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

first  to  be  considered,  that  there  shall  not  be  here  an  infinite  search  : 
that  is,  in  order  that  the  best  method  of  discovering  the  truth  may 
be  found,  we  do  not  need  another  method  to  discover  that,  and  to 
discover  the  second  method  we  do  not  want  yet  a  third,  and  so  on 
without  end.  Jor  in  this  manner  we  should  never  arrive  at  know- 
ledge of  the  truth,  nor  at  any  knowledge  at  all.  The  matter  stands 
indeed  in  the  same  way  as  that  of  material  instruments,  where  one 
might  argue  in  like  manner.  For  to  work  iron  one  must  have  a 
hammer,  which  hammer  must  be  made  ;  for  which  yet  another 
hammer  and  other  tools  are  needful,  and  to  produce  these  again  we 
shall  need  other  tools,  and  so  on  without  end  :  ^  and  in  this  fashion 
one  might  vainly  endeavour  to  prove  that  men  have  no  power  of 
working  iron.' 

Man  has  in  fact  succeeded  in  making  tools  and  machines  > 
by  many  progressive  steps.  At  first  he  used  his  hands  to 
obtain,  by  rough  and  toilsome  processes,  a  few  of  the  simplest 
instruments.  By  the  help  of  these  he  made  other  and  better 
ones  with  less  labour,  and  from  stage  to  stage  arrived  at  his 
command  of  mechanical  arts.  So  too  the  human  mind,  using 
\  its  native  strength  to  procure  instruments  for  its  work,  pro- 
ceeds from  one  undertaking  to  another  till  it  attains  consum- 
ij  mate  wisdom.  What  then  j,re  jLbe_.Lnstrum  with  which  the 
\mind.isequipped"by^  nature,  and  \yhich  suffice  it  for  the  con- 
struction of  other  and  more  finished  ones.-*  They  are  true 
ideas,  and  the  sole  and  sufficient  proof  of  their  truth  is  fur- 
nished by  themselves. ,  Accordingly  the  doctrine  of  method  . 
is  not  concerned  to  assign  a  test  of  truth  to  be  applied  to  our 
ideas  after  we  have  got  them  ;  the  problem  is  to  find  the  due 
order  in  which  truthj  the  representations  of  the  nature^  of^_ 
things,^  or  true  ideasj[;^l  which  terms  are  synonymous)  are  to 

'  Cf.  the  Rabbinical  list  of  '  things  created  between  the  suns,'  in  which  '  some 
say,  tongs  also,  made  with  tongs.' — C.   Taylor,  Sayings  of  the  Jewish  Fathers, 

V.  9. 

^  '  Essentiae  obiectivae  rerum. '  In  Spinoza's  usage  obiectivus  means  repre- 
sented in,  or  taken  as  the  object  of  thought,  and  is  often  equivalent  to  the  modern 
subjective.  The  correlative  term,  where  the  thing  is  considered  in  itself,  or  as  we 
should  now  say  objectively,  \sformalis  ;  so  that  true  knowledge  in  the  mind  is  said 
refer  re  obiective  formalitatem  naturae. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  129 

be  sought  for.     This  naturally  appears  to  a  modern  reader  at 
first  sight  as  the  most  absolute  dogmatism.     The  author  seems 
to  be  claiming  an  arbitrary  right  to  accept  anything  he  pleases 
as  self-evident.     But  this  is  not  really  the  case.     Spinoza's 
drift  in  this  passage,  when  freed  from  the  technical  form  of  his 
argument,  is  that  by  no  logical  device  whatever  can  we  escape  « 
the  necessity  of  starting  from  something  or  other  as  self-evident,  I 
ajTdJhxQiiiigjsn^ Jts.j,elf-eYidence  t^he  w^ 
subseguentj<npwledge  we  on  our  leading  assump- 

tions. 

Let  us  take  Spinoza's  own  explanation  in  the  more  concise 
and  finished  form  which  it  assumes  in  the  '  Ethics.'  In  the 
second  part  (Prop.  43)  he  asserts  that  '  whoever  has  a  true 
idea,  knows  at  the  same  time  that  he  has  a  true  idea,  and 
cannot  doubt  the  truth  of  the  thing  perceived.' 

After  the  regular  demonstration,  which  is  very  artificial, 
these  remarks  are  added  by  way  of  Scholium  : — 

'  It  is  to  be  noted  that  the  foregoing  proposition  is  pretty  manifest 
of  itself.  For  no  man  who  has  a  true  idea  is  unaware  that  a  true  idea 
involves  the  utmost  degree  of  certitude.  For  to  have  a  true  idea 
signifies  nothing  else  than  to  know  the  thing  perfectly  or  as  well  as 
possible  ;  nor  can  any  one  possibly  doubt  of  this  unless  he  thinks  an 
idea  to  be  a  lifeless  thing  like  a  picture  on  a  panel,  and  not  a  mode 
of  thought,  to  wit  the  very  act  of  understanding.  Who  can  know,  I 
ask,  that  he  understands  anything,  unless  he  do  first  understand  the 
thing?  in  other  words,  who  can  know  that  he  is  sure  of  anythino- 
unless  he  is  first  indeed  sure  of  that  thing  ?  Again,  what  can  be 
found  more  clear  and  certain  than  a  true  idea,  which  may  be  the 
test  of  truth  ?  Even  as  light  makes  manifest  both  itself  and  dark- 
ness, so  is  truth  the  measure  of  itself  and  of  falsehood.' 

Spinoza  does  not  say,  be  it  observed,  that  every  apparent 
certainty  is  true  knovvledge,^t  thatjthere  js^o  true  knovv- 
jedge^^without  certainty,  and^the   certaintY.-la_.givcn'  in    thej 
knowledge    itself.     In    other   words,    there   is  ultimately  no 
external  test  of  truth  j^we  must  be  content  jji_the  last  resortj 
with  the  clear  and  gersisten.t.„witacs^.of  consciQusjiess^    This  i 

K 


I30  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

doctrine  is  not  necessarily  transcendental  or  dogmatic.     It  is 
i  compatible  with  a  purely  empirical  account  of  the  origin  of 
all  our  knowledge,  and  indeed  is  adopted  in  that  connexion 
by  one  of  the  leading  philosophical  authors  of  our  own  time 
and  country.     Mr.  Herbert  Spencer's  view  of  the  final  test  of  o 
truth,  though  he  puts  it  in  the  negative  form  as  the  inconceiv- 
ableness  of  the  contrary,  is  substantially  not  distinguishable 
from   Spinoza's.     Rightly  understood,  the  doctrine  is  not  an 
assumption  of  infallibility,  but  a  warning  against  any  such  as- 
sumption.    When  a  man  is  once  in  possession  of  the  truth,  he 
cannot  doubt  it ;  but  he  may  well  be  deceived  into  supposing 
himself  in  possession  of  it  when  he  is  not.     To  take  an  illus- 
tration used  elsewhere  by  Spinoza  himself,  a  man  dreaming 
often  fancies  himself  sure  that  he  is  awake ;  but  a  man  really 
, awake  can  never  think  he  is  dreaming.     The  things  I  see  and 
feel,  my  phenomena,  are  ultimate  certainties  to  me  so  far  as 
fthey  go.     The  difficulty  is  to  ascertain  how  far  thej^  really  do 
go;  to  separate  the  phenomena  from  my  interpretation  of  them, 
which  experience  has  shown  to  be  in   many  ways  liable  to 
error.     Again,    when    I    have   clearly  grasped    the    relations 
between  the  parts  of  a  geometrical  diagram,  I  can  entertain 
no  doubt  concerning  them.     Yet  before  I  had  sufficiently  con- 
sidered them  I  might  be  uncertain,  or  even  entertain  a  wrong 
conception  of  the  geometrical  relations  and  imagine  it  to  be 
-    certainly  right.     No  one  knew  better  than  Spinoza  how  easy 
it  is  to  hold  confused  and  erroneous  beliefs  with  absolute  con- 
fidence.    Some  of  the  current  notions  in  philosophy  and  psy- 
chology which  he  makes    the   objects  of  his  most  unsparing 
attack  are  precisely  those  which  have  been  most  commonly 
maintained  on  the  ground  that  they  are  principles  given  by 
consciousness  as  clear,  ultimate,  and  self-evident. 
;        At  the  same  time  there  is  no  reason  to  doubt  that  Spinoza 
(did  underrate   (as  almost   all  constructive  philosophers  have 
[underrated)  the  difficulty  of  ascertaining  what  the  ultimate 
jdata  of  sense  and  thought  really  are  ;  he  nowhere  undertakes 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  131 

the  analysis  of  these  data,  nor  does  he  separate  it  from  the 
business  of  ascertaining  concrete  truth  in  particular  cases. 
Descartes'  own  testimony  is  express  that  he  thought  \hec 
whole  body  of  possible  knowledge  to  lie,  generally  if  not  in 
detail,  within  a  moderate  compass,  and  to  be  deducible  from 
principles  which  might  be  finally  settled  in  a  single  generation, 
when  once  the  problem  of  method  was  solved.  Spinoza  is  not 
so  explicit,  but  it  seems  probable  that  his  expectations  were 
of  the  same  kind.  For  men  in  this  sanguine  frame  of  mind 
it  was  natural  also  to  underrate  the  difficulty  of  procuring  ac- 
ceptance among  mankind  for  the  conceptions  which  to  them 
appeared  to  shine  with  the  light  of  evident  and  self-justifying 
truth.  This  kind  of  excessive  hope,  however,  is  capable  of 
being  dashed  by  experience  in  all  but  incorrigible  visionaries  ; 
and  while  it  appears,  though  not  extravagantly,  in  the  fragment 
'  De  Intellectus  Emendatione,'  no  sign  of  it  is  left  in  the 
'  Ethics.' 

So  far  I  have  put  the  matter  in  my  own  way,  to  avoid  the 
difficulties  of  Spinoza's  vocabulary :  but  his  use  of  the  term 
idea  calls  for  some  consideration  in  this  place,  the  point  being 
too  important  for  the  understanding  of  Spinoza's  psychology 
to  be  omitted  or  evaded.  In  the  passage  now  before  us  '  ideac 
is  a  conscious  state  of  the  knowing  mind,  in  which  the  object 
known  is  represented.  This  again  may  become  the  subject 
of  another  representation,  and  so  on.  '  The  man  Peter  is  an 
existing  thing  {quid  reale).  The  U'lie  idea  of  Peter  is  the 
nature  of  Peter  represented  in  thought  {essentia  Petri  obiec- 
tiva),  and  is  itself  an  existing  object  wholly  distinct  from 
Peter.' 

This  idea  of  Peter  may  then  be  the  object  of  another  idea 
which  will  contain  by  representation  {obiective)  all  that  the 
idea  of  Peter  contains  actually  iformaliter)  ;  and  again  the  idea 
thus  formed  of  the  idea  of  Peter  has  its  own  nature  which 
may  likewise  be  the  object  of  another  idea,  and  so  on.     Thus 

'  Dc  Int.  E»i.  c.  6,  §  T,},. 
K  2 


^ 


n 


132  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

,   to  know  the  idea  of  Peter  is  not  a  previous  condition  of  know- 

I   ing  Peter  himself;  in  other  words,  knowing  that  I  know  is  not  "^ 

a  condition  of  knowledge,  but  on  the  contrary  the  reflective 

knowledge  is  a  consequence  of  the  direct.     And  the  certainty 

I  ©f  knowledge  is  nothing  else  than  the  nature  of  the  thing  itself 

f  i"epresented  in  thought  ;  whence  we  see  again  that  there  is  no 

S  'ultimate  mark  of  truth  outside  the  truth  itself. 

So  far,  then,  and  as  far  as  the  treatise  on  the  '  Amendment 
-j  of  the  Understanding '  goes,  Spinoza's  idea  seems  equivalent 
1  to   what   we    now  call  a  concept.     But  v/e   shall   find  else- 
y  where  that  it  has  a  wider  significance.     It  always  denotes  a 
mode  of  thought  considered  as  corresponding  to  an  object,  but 
the  nature  of  the  correspondence  may  be  very  difi'erent  from 
that  which  is  here  dealt  with.     The  most  important  case  is 
that  of  the  human  mind,  which  is  spoken  of  as  the  idea  of  the 
body  associated  with  it.     Now  a  man  can  easily  think  of  his 
own  body,  but  he  is  not  always  doing  so,  and  when  he  does 
his  thought  will  not  be  accurate  unless  he  has  learnt  some- 
thing of  physiology.     And  even  if  every  human  being  were 
an  accomplished   physiologist,   the  constant   relation  of  the 
mind  as  a  whole  to  the  body  as  a  whole  would  still  be  something 
different  from  the  relation  of  the  knowing  to  the  known.     Theo 
organic  sensations  which  furnish  the  groundwork  for  a  large - 
part  of  our  conscious  life  are  not  knowledge  or  concepts.     But 
Spinoza  makes  use  of  the  one  term  idea  to  denote  the  two  kinds 
of  relation,  and  we  have  to  find  out  by  the  context  which  he 
means.'     If  I  think  of  Peter,  the  state  of  my  consciousness  is  an 
idea  of  Peter  according  to  Spinoza's  first  usage  of  the  term.  But 
according  to  his  other  usage,  it  is  the  idea,  not  of  Peter,  but  of 
the  corresponding  state  of  my  own  brain  and  nerves,  or  such 
parts  of  them  as  are,  in  modern  language,  the  organs  of  that 

'  The  corresponding  German  term  Vorstellung  is  capable  of  the  same  latitude. 
Hence  we  find  the  ambiguity  of  Spinoza's  own  language  to  some  extent  reproduced 
even  by  the  best  of  his  German  expounders.  Spinoza  himself  once  calls  attention 
to  the  distinction  :  Eth.  2,  17,  schol. 


■    THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  133 

particular  phase  of  conscious  thought.     In  the  one  sense  the 
object  of  the  idea  is  Peter,  in  the  other  it  is  the  bodily  organism 
correlated  to  the  thinking  mind.  And  it  is  important  to  observe 
that  in  this  other  sense  idea  has  a  far  wider  application  than  in 
the  first  and  more  familiar  sense.     The  material  correlate  which 
is  called  the  object  of  the  idea  may  be  a  living  organism,  but 
also  it  may  not.     The  idea  may  coincide  with  a  concept  in  a 
conscious  mind,  or  with  a  conscious  mind  forming  concepts, 
but  also  it  may  not.     Considering,  for  example,  the  whole  : 
material  universe  as  the  object,  we  have  a  corresponding  idea 
which,  whatever  it  may  be,  is  not  part  of  any  human  con- 
sciousness.    In  this  sense,  accordingly,  there  can  be  only  one 
idea  of  any  given  object  ;  in  the  former  sense,  in  which  idea 
was  equivalent  to  concept,  we  might  have  a  distinct  and  in- 
dividual idea  of  the  object  in  every  finite  mind  capable  of 
thinking  about  it. 

Taking  idea  in  the  narrower  sense  of  concept,  it  is  obvious,  j 
as  Spinoza  points  out,  that  the  process  denoted  by  it  may  be 
repeated  on  the  idea  itself ;  and  this  either  in  the  conceiving  • 
mind  itself  or  in  another.     When  this  takes  place  in  the  same 
mind,  we  have  a  thought  thinking  upon  itself,  or  reflective 
knowledge.     The   mind's   operation  thus  taking   account  of 
itself  is  in  Spinoza's  language  idea  idcae.     Now  Spinoza  was 
firmly  minded  to  hold  fast  the  unity  and  continuity  of  mental 
processes.     He  would  have  nothing  to  do  with  separate  facul- 
ties, much  less  with  an  ascending  scale  of  them.     When  the 
mind  knows  itself,  the  knowing  and  the  known  are  one  and 
the  same.     In  order  to  enforce  this  he  carries  over  the  term 
idea  ideae,  naturally  framed,  as  we  have  seen,  on  his  first  sense 
of  the  word  idea,  to  a  new  employment  in  the  second  sense. 
Reflective  knowledge  is  idea  mentis  or  idea  ideae  (where  idea 
is  the  concept).    The  mind  itself,  as  united  with  the  body,  is  idea 
corporis   (where   idea  =  correlate    in  the   world    of  thought). 
Spinoza  tacitly  substitutes  correlate  for  concept  in  the  inter- 
pretation of  idea  ideae,  and  concludes  that  the  idea  vieniis  is 


7  34  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

\  united  with  the  mind  as  the  mind  is  with  the  body.  But  the 
!  mind  and  the  'idea  of  the  mind'  are  both  modes  of  thought. 
If  therefore  they  correspond  exactly  they  must  be  one  and  the 
same  thing  ;  not  the  same  thing  under  different  aspects,  as  the 
mind  and  body,  but  the  same  thing  under  the  same  aspect,  and 
identical  to  all  intents,'  The  blending,  logically  not  to  be 
justified,  of  the  two  meanings  of  idea,  seems  to  give  us  the 
key  to  some  of  the  difficulties  we  must  hereafter  face  in  the 
/    'Ethics.' 

Spinoza   goes   on   to  jay_tIial.jdie..,£bJ£Ct.,o£._niethadJs 
neither  tolTn3~a"'special  test  of  truth  (which  has  been  shown 


C 


mi 


to  be  needless)  nor  the^  actual  acquisitioii^  of  k^^ 
the  guidance  j3fj:iifi,sgarch  for  kn^^  'jnothing 

else  than  reflective  knowledge  or  the  idea  of  an  idea.'^     Now 
,^i  ftHe  reflective  knowledge  which  has  for  its  object  the  idea  of 

^Ithe  most  perfect  being   is   more  excellent  than  any  other. 

t  This  idea^then,  is  the  ultimate  object  of  the  mind's  pursuit. 
Here,  again,  the  two  senses  of  idea  are  not  separated.  It  is 
by  no  means  evident  that  the  mind's  knowledge  of  its  own 
operations  is  more  or  less  perfect  as  knowledge  by  reason  of 
those  operations  being  concerned  with  a  more  or  less  perfect 
subject-matter.  To  make  the  assumption  intelligible  we  have 
to  suppose  a  correlation  as  well  as  a  relation  between  the  mind 
which  knows  in  the  first  instance  and  the  object  which  is 
known.  What  is  meant  by  the  idea  of  the  most  perfect  being 
is  not  further  explained  in  this  place ;  except  that  true  ideas 
in  the  mind  should  be  produced  from  '  that  which  represents 
the  origin  and  source  of  all  nature,'  as  the  reality  of  things  is 
derived  from  that  origin  itself  Once  more  the  two  distinct 
conceptions    of    representation    and    correlation    are    thrown 

'■:  together  under  the  term  idea. 

The  road  by  which  the  human  mind  is  to  attain  its  goal 

'   r.th.  2,  22. 

2  De  Int.  Em.  c.  J,  ad  fn.  Cf.  Descartes,  Disc,  de  la  Methode,  part  ii.  ;  hut 
the  resemblance  is  not  close. 


THE  DOCTRINE  OF  METHOD.  135 

is  practically  to  be  found  in  the  knowledge  of  its  own  powers 
and  of  the  order  of  nature.     Were  the  true  method  once  found 
and  followed,  advance  would  be  certain.     But  it  is  in  truth 
seldom   found,  by  reason  of  men's  prejudices,  the  toil  and 
clearness  of  thought  needed  for  the  work,  and  other  causes. 
Even  if  the   method,  being  found,  were  exhibited  in   action 
without  any  previous  warning,  it  would  probably  fail  to  carry 
conviction  :  for  it  might  well   happen  to  lead  to  unexpected 
results,  which  men  would  be  prone  to  reject  without  examina- 
tion.    It  is  therefore  not  reasonable  to  call  for  an  immediate 
production  of  results  to  test  the  value  of  the  method  by.     As 
for  absolute  sceptics,  if  any  such  there  be,  they  are  by  their 
own  showing  beyond  the  pale  of  reasonable  discourse.    A  man 
who  will  admit  nothing  cannot  be  certain  even  of  his  own 
doubt,  although  he  cannot  live  without  acting  on   a  great 
number  of  assumptions  as   to  the  reality  of  himself  and  the 
world. 

The  inquiry,  so  far  as  it  has  gone,  is  now  summed  up. 
We  have  ascertained,  firstly,  what  is  the  ultimate  object  of 
our  search  ;  secondly,  through  what  kind  of  knowledge  we 
may  best  attain  perfection  ;  thirdly,  what  course  we  must 
follow  to  think  rightly  from  the  beginning,  or  how  we  may 
enlarge  our  stock  of  '  true  ideas.'  To  provide  for  this  demand 
is  the  special  task  of  method,  and  its  problems  are  the 
following : — 

1.  To  distinguish  a  true  idea  from  all  other  conceptions, 
and  restrain  the  mind  from  others : 

2.  To    deliver   rules   whereby   things    unknown    may   be 
brought  into  knowledge  according  to  this  distinction  : 

3.  To  establish  an  order  of  inquiry  whereby  we  may  be 
saved  useless  labour : 

4.  And  to  arrive  at  the  '  idea  of  the  most  perfect  being,' 
as  the  surest  way  to  the  perfection  of  our  method. 

This    may  not  look   very  promising  at  first  sight  to  a 
student  of  modern  science  :  especially  the  fourth   canon  of 


136  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

method  has  an  air  of  hopelessly  unpractical  mysticism.     But 

reflexion  will  alter  this  view.     The  first  three  rules  are  open, 

in  our  day  at  least,  only  to  the  objection  that  they  savour  of 

J commonplace.lU Clearness    of   conception  ancl,^oidance  of 

<  <"  ^  ''•-'  ""^ 

I  confused  thought-jr-S'procedure  step  by  step  from  the  known 

^^    I  ' '  • "."'' . 

%  ;  to  the  unknowri^^^^d  an  arrangement  of  the  whole  work  such 

li  that  every  step  has  its  value,  and  no  labour  is  spent  in  vain, 
I  are  beyond  question  among  the  most  essential  conditions  for 
Ithe  successful  conduct  of  all  scientific  inquiry.  Every  one 
seriously  concerned  with  the  investigation  of  truth  in  philoso- 
phy, law,  natural  science,  or  the  practical  affairs  of  life,  does 
in  fact  endeavour  to  fulfil  those  conditions  in  his  own  busi- 
ness, and  the  success  of  the  body  of  his  enterprise  will  be  in 
proportion  to  his  success  in  fulfilling  them. 

The  fourth  rule  is  in   appearance   a  harder  saying.     But 

we  have  already  seen  that  for  Spinoza,  attached  by  race  and 

tradition  to  the  Hebrew  sentiment  of  a  one  and  only  supreme 

power,  and  by  an  intellectual  passion  to  the  pursuit  of  exact 

science,  the  perfection  of  God,  conceived  as  the  most  perfect 

being,  '  constant  in  all  his  works,'  meant  above  all  things  unity 

and  uniformity.     Thus  the  '  idea  of  the  most  perfect  being ' 

includes,  if  it  is  not   equivalent  to,  the  belief  that  the  whole 

nature  of  things  is  one  and  uniform.     Now  this  is  the  very 

first  principle  of  all  science.     The  uniformity  of  the  course  of 

nature  is  that  to  which  all  lesser  uniformities  converge,  and  by 

which  they  are  all  supported.     If  we  do  not  call  it  a  law  of 

nature,  it  is  because  there  could  be  no  laws  of  nature  and  no 

science  without  it.     And  Spinoza  will  have  no  exceptions 

from  it.     In  knowing  the  'most  perfect  being,'  the  mind  also 

knows  itself  as  part  of  the  universal  order  and  at  one  with  it : 

therein  finding,  as  we  have  to  learn  elsewhere,  the  secret  of 

man's  happiness  and  true  freedom.     What  more  Spinoza  may 

have  meant  is  doubtful  :  that  he  meant  this  much  is  certain. 

Such  is  not  the  mind  of  a  dreamer  of  dogmatic  dreams. 

Spinoza  proceeds  to  work  out  the  several  departments  of 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  137 

method  ;  an  operation  interesting  to  us  not  because  it  is  more 
likely  to  lead  any  one  to  the  actual  discovery  of  truth  than 
other  expositions  of  the  same  kind,  but  because  it  throws 
light  on  Spinoza's  theory  of  knowledge  and  helps  to  make  us 
familiar  with  the  conceptions  afterwards  more  closely  handled 
in  the  '  Ethics.'     The  first  part  of  method  was  to  distinguish 
true  ideas  from  all  others :  the  nature  of  fiction,  error,  and 
doubt,  has  therefore  to  be  considered./    Fiction  or  fancy  in  its 
most  common  shape  deals  with  things  considered  as  possible 
but  undetermined.     We  make  a  supposition  which  we  know 
or  assume  to  be  consistent  in  itself,  but  without  knowing  the 
facts  on  which  its  actual  truth  depends.    An  omniscient  mind 
would  be  incapable  of  making  suppositions  of  this  kind  ;  ^  nor 
can  we  make  them  as  to  matters  of  which  we  are  certain.     In 
another  sense,  however,  -we  can  imagine  the  contrary  of  what 
is  well  known  to  us  ;  for  instance,  that  the  sun  goes  round 
the  earth.     This  is  the  mental  representation  of  an  erroneous 
idea  which  we  may  have  ourselves  formerly  entertained,  or 
which  might  be  entertained  by  others.  Again,  we  make  supposi- 
tions contrary  to  our  immediate  perceptions  ;  as  that  a  candle 
burning  before  us  is  not  burning.     This  is  nothing  but  an 
effort  of  memory  or  abstraction  ;  the  recollection  of  unlighted 
candles  we  have  seen,  or  the  image  of  the  candle  before  us 
apart  from  its  flame.     Spinoza  gives  in  a  note  the  important 
remark  that  the  mind  can  really  create  nothing  by  way  of 
'fiction,'  but  can  only  recall  and  combine  the  elements  already 
given  in  experience.      We   remember   spoken  words  and  a 
tree;  and  if  attention  is  directed  'confusedly  and  without 
distinction '  to  these  mental  representations,  we  can  form  the 
notion  of  a  tree  speaking.     As  to  the  fictions  which  involve 
the  nature  of  things  apart  from  or  in  addition  to  particular 

'  Reading  with  Sigwart  emu  or  id  for  nos  in  §  54,  ad  hiit.  The  correction 
had  already  been  made  by  the  cont'jmporary  Dutch  translator  :  '  Hier  uit  volgtdat, 
zo'  er  enig  God,  of  iets  alweetcnd  is,  hy  gantschelijk  niets  kan  verdichlen.'— 
Nagdatc  Schriftcn,  p.  423. 


138  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

facts,  they  depend  simply  on  ignorance.  The  less  we  know 
of  nature,  the  more  absurdities  can  we  accept  from  the  work- 
shop of  unregulated  fancy  ;  such  as  talking  trees,  magic  and 
apparitions,  transformations  of  men  into  stones,  and  the  like. 
On  the  whole,  then,  the  mere  fictions  of  the  imagination  are 
always  confused,  and  will  never  impose  on  us  if  we  trace  out 
their  consequences,  which  if  they  are  absurd  will  show  the 
absurdity  of  the  assumption,  or  analyse  them  into  elements 
so  simple  as  to  exclude  that  confused  representation  of 
several  things  at  once  which  is  the  essence  of  baseless  fancies. 
Positive  error  {idea_falsd)  ^  is  of  the  same  nature  as  fiction, 
differing  from  it  only  in  the  addition  of  intellectual  assent. 
The  remedy  is  the  same  as  in  the  last  case,  namely,  the  reduc- 
tion of  our  ideas  to  a  degree  of  simplicity  that  shall  ensure 
I  their  being  clear  and  distinct.  A  perfectly  simple  idea  cannot 
),'■  be  false,  provided  we  understand  truth  and  falsehood  in  the 
sense  which  Spinoza  now  proceeds  to  explain.  The  truth  or 
falsehood  of  an  idea  does  not,  in  higLview,  depend  so  much  ori^ 
external  things  as  upon  the  constitution  and  operation  of  the_ 
mind  itself  An  architect  conceives  in  his  mind  a  building  of 
a  new  design,  which  may  peradventure  never  be  executed. 
If  the  plan  is  not  repugnant  to  the  laws  of  construction,^  he 
has  an  idea  vera.  If  a  man  makes  a  reckless  assertion  without 
means  of  knowledge,  his  judgment  is  with  regard  to  him  not 
true,  though  it  may  turn  out  to  be  in  accordance  with  fact. 
'  The  affirmation  that  Peter  exists  is  true  only  with  regard  to 
him  who  has  assured  knowledge  of  Peter's  existence.'  Again, 
even  a  fiction  may  be  idea  vera  when  it  is  used  consistently 
and  limited  to  the  purpose  for  which  it  was  made.  Thus  we 
may  imagine  a  sphere  to  be  generated  by  the  revolution  of  a 
semicircle  ;  and  this  conception,  though  we  know  that  it  does 
not  correspond  to  any  physical  fact,  is  perfectly  legitimate  and 
true  for  the  purpose  of  defining  our  conception  of  a  sphere. 
If  we  took   it  as  the  statement  of  a  physical  event  it  would 

'  Cap.  9.  -  '  Si  quis  faber  ordine  concepit,'  &c.  §  69. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  139 

> 

become  false.     So  the  mathematical  ideas  of  imaginary  quan- 
tities and  loci,  the  circular  points  at  infinity,  and  the  like,  are 
'  true  ideas  '  in  Spinoza's  meaning,  for  they  are  consistently 
worked  out  and  lead  to  intelligible  results.     Probably  Spinoza 
would  have  said  the  same  of  the  non-Euclidean  systems  of 
geometry  which  have  been  the  subject  of  modern  speculations. 
Truth,  in  short,  is  not  the  correspondence  of  the  concept  with'    / 
an  external  object,  but  the  result  of  the  nqrrnal  operation  of 
the  mind  on    elements  given  by  clear   and  distinct  concep- 
tion.    '  Error  \falsitas)  consists  only  in  this,  that  somewhat 
is  affirmed  of  a  thing  which  is  not  contained  in  the  concept  \ 
we  have  formed  of  it ;    as   motion  or    rest   \i.e.  as    physical    'i 
facts]  of  a  semicircle.'     When  we  make  such  an  affirmation,    \f\  f^AA^ 
'  it  shows  a  defect  in  our  conception,  or  that  our  thought  or    ;. 
idea  is  as  it  were  maimed  and  cut  short.' '  \ 

Spinoza's  definition  of  truth  may  seem  to  verge  on  para- 
dox. But  his  estimate  of  the  value  of  truth  coincides  with 
that  which  we  derive  both  from  common  sense  and  from 
science.  Not  the  bare  possession  of  a  fact,  but  the  possession 
of  it  in  connexion  with  other  fatcts  which  enable  us  to  make 
thej2ght^  use-jof  it^s  the  object  we  seek  in  every  particular 
inquiry.  Disjointed  and  accidental  knowledge  is  for  the  most 
part  little  better  than  none,  and  may  be  even  worse.  On  the 
other  hand  we  may  and  constantly  do  use  fictitious  conceptions 
as  the  most  convenient  way  of  arriving  at  real  results  ;  and 
there  is  no  harm  in  this  if  we  confine  the  fiction  to  its  proper 
use.  Thus  the  corpuscular  theory  of  light,  though  known 
to  be  false  as  a  physical  hypothesis,  may  still  be  used  as  a 
legitimate  fiction  in  geometrical  optics  :  and  the  language  and 
conceptions  of  the  Ptolemaic  system  are  still  employed  in  astro- 
nomy for  many  purposes.  Even  the  formal  part  of  Spinoza's 
exposition  is  less  alien  to  our  ways  of  thinking  than  it  appears. 

'  Cf.  Ep.  42,  where  Spinoza  says  even  more  positively  that  the  chain  of 
'clear  and  distinct  perceptions'  is  independent  of  external  circumstances.  See 
especially  §  3. 


/ 


I40  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

When  he  makes  truth  consist,  in  the  last  resort,  in  the  identity 
ofjdeas  clearly  seen  to  be  equivalent,  falsehood  in  the  juxta- 
position of  incongruous  ones,  he  is  really  on  the  same  ^line 
of  thought  as  more  than  one  recent  inquirer.     The  position 
becomes    dogmatic  only  on   the   assumption    that   we  have 
ideas   antecedent   to  experience  ;  but  of  such  ideas  Spinoza 
knows  nothing.     He  does  not  dwell,  it  is  true,  on  the  practicalo 
necessity  of  testing  our  work,  in  all  departments  where  it  can 
be  so  tested,  by  fresh  appeals  to  experience.     But  this  belongs 
to  the  art  of  conducting  research  in  the  particular  subject- 
matter,  whatever  it  may  be ;  and  Spinoza  does  not  profess  to 
give  rules  extending  so  far.     At  the  same  time  it  is  hardly 
I  open  to  doubt   that  Spinoza  very  much   underrated  the  diffi-D 
^  culty  of  making  sure  of  '  clear  and  distinct  ideas '  at  the  out- 
I  set.     With  all  philosophers  of  all  times  down  to  his  own,  he  ■: 
supposed  that  the  ultimate  elements  of  things  and  of  know- 
ledge were  comparatively  few  and  simple  ;  and  that  when  the 
fundamental  principles  were  once  ascertained,  everything  could 
be  explained  by  deduction  from  them  with  very  little  need  for 
external  verification.     Previous  inquirers,  he  says,  have  fallen 
into    error   by  not  understanding  the  first  principles  of  the 
universe  ;  '  whereby,  proceeding  without  due  order,  and  con- 
founding the  nature  of  things  with  rules  which,  though  true, 
are  abstract ' — in  modern  language,  by  applying  general  rules 
or  definitions  without  first   ascertaining  whether  they  were 
really  applicable  to  the  particular  class  of  facts — 'they  con- 
found themselves  and  distort  the  order  of  nature.'     He   in- 
stances the  materialism  of  the  Stoics,  who  identified  the  soul 
with  the  subtlest  kind  of  matter  by  mixing  up  a  physical  con- 
ception which  was  clear  as  far  as  it  went  with  a  confused 
notion  of  mind.     *  But  we,'  he  continues,  '  if  we  proceed  with 
as  little  abstraction  as  may  be,  and  begin  from  first  principles 
at  the  earliest  possible  point,  that   is,  from  the  source  and 
origin  of  nature,  shall  be  free  from  all  fear  of  such  illusion.' 
The  reason  why  the  danger  of  abstractions  disappears  is  thatC 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  141 

(as  we  are  to  learn  hereafter)  the  idea  of  the  first  prhiciple  of 
nature  is  not  and  cannot  be  an  abstraction.  '  This  is  in  fact  a 
being  single  and  infinite,  that  is,  it  is  the  whole  of  being, 
beside  which  no  being  is  found.'  ^ 

This  '  being  single  and  infinite '  is  that  which  has  been 
already  proposed  as  the  final  object  of  all   knowledge,  the 
knowledge  of  it  being  man's  only  durable  good.     And  we 
may  fitly  observe  here  the  reason  why  the  idea  of  this  being 
is  justly  denied  by  Spinoza  to  be  abstract.     We  may  arrive  b 
at  an  abstract  idea  of  being  by  forming  more  and  more  general    j 
notions  which,  as  we  proceed  from  one  to  another,  shall  com-  \ 
prise  a  greater  number  of  subordinate  kinds  and  individuals  ||V^^'^ 
agreeing  in  fewer  attributes  ;  until   at  length  we  arrive  at  a  r 
bare  notion   of  being  in  which   no  distinct  attribute  is  left. 
This   is   the   vanishing-point    of   logical   classification,  where 
there  is  no  longer  a  handle  for  the  dividing  mind  to  lay  hold 
of     But  this  abstraction  is  quite  different  from  our  conception 
of  the  sum  of  things  as  a  whole,  which  is  the  conception  not 
of  a  class  or  genus  but  jjfjexisting  things,  and  is  no  more 
abstract  tlian  the  conception  of  any  object  or  assemblage  of 
objects  which  cannot  be  directly  presented  to  sense.     To  a 
certain  extent  this  may  be  illustrated  by  simpler  examples. 
We  have  the  general  name  army,  and  a  corresponding  general 
or  abstract  idea.     But  the  name  of  the  British  army,  and  the 
idea  called  up  by  it,  stand  for  no  abstraction,  but  for  a  certain 
real  aggregate  of  men,  together  with  their  arms,  horses,  and 
various  munitions  of  war,  all  which  are  definite  existing  things. 
In  our  idea  of  the  British  army  as  it  exists  at  a  given  moment, 
as  when  the  Mutiny  Act  for  next  year  comes  into  operation, 
there  is  no  abstraction  at  all.     There  is  a  sort  of  abstraction 
when  we  regard  ihe  a'-my  as  a  body  which  retains  an  histori- 
cal and  moral  continuity  notwithstanding  the  changes  of  men, 
material,  and  organization  which  are  constantly  taking  place 
in  it  :  but  this,  as  may  easily  be  seen,  has  no  analogy  in  the 

'  Ccp.  9.  I§  74-76. 


142  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

course  of  nature  as  a  whole.  For  changes  of  this  kuid  are 
from  without,  or  with  regard  to  something  outside  the  subject 
of  change  :  "but  there  is  nothing  outside  the  whole  of  nature. 
I  "^^^l^^^^S.  J^?S--OL!l^e  J^^o^^  of  being,  as  Spinoza  calls  it,  is 
the  idea  of  the  whole  actual  sum^  of  existence  anXof  alflts 
consequences:  and  it  differs  from  the  abstract  idea7of "being 
iS^fe^^P^^  way  tliat  our  thoughl^c^^^  army  differs 

from  our  thought  of  an  army  in   general,  but  in'  an  even 
greater  degree.     Ij  is  not  a  vanishing  conception  which  eludes 
the  understanding  by  having  no  real  contents,  but  it  baffles 
the  imagination  because  its  contents  are  too  rich  and  mani- 
fold to  be  grasped.     And  it  has  the  singular  property  that  no 
abstraction  can  be  formed  from  it.    The  universe,  as  including- 
everything,  is  manifestly  sui  generis,  or  rather  above  all  genera 
V  and  species  :  we  cannot  speak  of  this   or  that  universe,  for 
^  then  it  would  be  a  universe  no  longer.     But  all  this  may  so 
far  seem  to  be  mere  trifling  with  words.     For  suppose  we  have 
an  idea  of  the  universe  or  whole  sum   of  being,  which,  em- 
bracing as  it  does  all  particular  existence,  is  necessarily  single 
and  all-containing,  what  then  }     Where  is  the  mighty  profit 
which,  according  to  Spinoza,  we  are  to  derive  from  the  con- 
templation of  it }     Nothing  is  more  certain  than  that  no  man 
ever  made  or  will  make  a  discovery  of  any  moment  in  art  or 
science  by  dint  of  thinking  on  the  nature  of  things  at  large. 
But  it  is  no  less  an  assured  fact  that  discoveries  are  not  made 
without  belief  in  the  nature  of  things,  by  which  I  mean  the 
sure  trust  that  under  all  diversity  of  appearances  there  is  a 
certain  and  sufficient  order,  that  there  is  no  maze  which  has 
not  somewhere  a  clue.     Belief  in  the  nature  of  things  is  the  < 
mainspring  of  all  science  and  the    condition   of  all   sound 
thinking,  unless  there  be  some  kind  of  sound  thmkmg  which 
diverges  from  sound  reason.     Now  Spinoza's  philosophy  is 
the  enthronement  of  reason,  and  it  is  this  belief  that  he  re- 
quires^   Thp  truth  is  that  his  idea  of  the  sum  and   source  of 
all  being,  or  the  most  perfect  being,  in  other  words,  of  God, 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  14J 

as  he  afterwards  explained  that  name  in  the  '  Ethics,'  in- 
cludes the  idea  of  uniformity  as  ruling  all  events  whatever, 
and  this  uniformity  is  regarded  as  inseparable  from  the  unity 
of  the  only  and  all-embracing  whole.  '  Deus  est  summe 
constans  in  suis  operibus.*  The  Mosaic  conception  of 
the  one  God  of  Israel  wedded  to  the  Lucretian  concep- 
tion, revived  though  with  bated  breath  by  Descartes,  of 
the  one  and  inflexible  nature  of  things  ;  such  is  the  mood 
Spinoza  would  have  us  bring  to  the  questioning  of  the  world, 
such  the  majesty  and  gravity  of  nature  in  his  eyes.  Here 
we  have  no  matter  of  verbal  definitions,  but  a  fundamental 
principle ;  and  whoever  would  enter  into  Spinoza's  mind 
must  first  feel  himself  at  home  in  this  the  central  point  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy. 

Let  us  return  for  the  present  to  the  fragment  on  Method 
which  is  our  text  in  this  chapter.     Having  spoken  of  true  and 
false  ideas,  Spinoza  goes  on  to  the  nature  of  doubt,  which 
can  take  placQ,  he  says,  only  in  the  case  of  ideas  which  are 
confused   or  imperfect.     We  know  by  past  experience  that 
error  is  possible,  but  have  not  the   means  of  ascertaining  or 
removing  the  possible  sources  of  it  in  the  particular  case. 
Ignorant  people  are  confident  because  they  know  nothing  of 
their  liability  to  mistake  ;  thus  a  rustic  stares  and  disbelieves 
when  he  is  told  that  the  sun  is  much  bigger  than  a  clod  of 
earth.     So  that  doubt  may  be  said  always  to  arise  from  our\ 
inquiries  not  being  pursued  in  a  due  order.     Here  again  there  f-:, 
is  the  tacit  assumption  that  it  is  possible  to  conform  to  an  \ 
ideal  type  of  orde;r  in  every  kind   of  investigation,  so  as  to 
ensure   demonstrative    certainty   for    every   step ;    in    other 
words,  that  a  general  and  infallible  theory  of  method  can  be 
found.'     What  Spinoza  says  of  memory  in  the  next  chapter 
is    more    fully  repeated   in   the    '  Ethics,'  and   may  be  here 
passed  over  :  but  his  summary  of  the  results  thus  far  obtained 
is  important.     He  dwells  on  the  point  that  error  has  been 

'  Dc  III/.  Em.,  cap.  10. 


("ruN 


SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


shown  to  be  a  product  not  of  the  understanding  but  of  the 
imaginatioi'u 

*  As  to  a  true  idea,'  he  proceeds,  '  we  have  shown  that  it  is  simple 
or  compounded  of  simple  ideas  ;  that  it  shows  how  and  why  something 
is  or  has  become  what  it  is  ;  and  that  the  effects  of  the  object  as 
represented  in  the  mind  correspond  to  the  reaUty  of  the  object  itself 
Which  was  indeed  the  meaning  of  the  ancients  when  they  said  that 
true  knowledge  proceeds  from  the  cause  to  the  effects  ;  save  that  they 
never  to  my  knowledge  conceived,  as  we  do  here,  the  mind  as  acting 
conformably  to  fixed  laws  and  like  an  immaterial  automaton. 
Hence  we  have  gained,  so  far  as  we  might  at  the  outset,  the  descrip- 
tion of  our  understanding,  and  such  a  rule  of  true  ideas  as  leaves  us 
in  no  fear  of  confounding  true  things  with  false  or  feigned  ;  neither 
shall  we  wonder  why  we  understand  sundry  things  that  are  in  no  wise 
subject  to  the  imagination,  while  others  are  in  the  imagination  which 
are  wholly  repugnant  to  the  understanding,  and  others  again  agree 
therewith.  For  we  know  that  the  operations  by  which  the  works  of 
imagination  are  produced  have  place  according  to  laws  of  their  own 
wholly  diverse  from  those  of  the  understanding,  and  that  the  mind, 
as  regards  the  imagination,  is  in  a  merely  passive  condition.  Whence 
it  also  appears  how  easily  those  may  fall  into  great  error  who  have 
not  been  careful  to  distinguish  between  the  acts  of  imagination  and 
of  understanding.' 

This  distinction  is  one  of  the  corner-stones  of  Spinoza's 
psychology  :  and  the  conception  of  knowledge  as  an  activity 
of  the  mind — which,  as  we  may  remember,  is  not  found  in  the 
early  treatise  '  Of  God  and  Man  ' — is  of  hardly  less  importance 
in  his  mature  work.  He  now  applies  his  doctrine  of  the  ima- 
gination to  illustrate  the  fallacies  of  common  language.  The 
passage  is  remarkable. 

'  Since  words  belong  to  the  imagination  (that  is  to  say,  we  form 
many  notions  according  as  the  words  expressing  them  are  confusedly 
put  together  in  the  memory  by  reason  of  particular  bodily  conditions), 

1  '  Quod  ipsius  effectvis  obiectivi  in  anima  procedunt  ad  rationem  formalitatis 
ipsius  obiecti. '  One  might  be  tempted  to  xt.'aA  affect  us  ^ox  effechis.  But  effectns 
obiectivi  is  probably  equivalent  to  the  ordo  ct  connexio  idcariuii  of  EtJi.  2,  7.  As  to 
'automaton  spirituale,'  which  occurs  immediately  below,  cf.  what  Descartes  says 
of  the  body  in  the  Treatise  of  die  Passions,  §§6,  16. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  145 

we  cannot  doubt  that  words,  no  less  than  imagination,  may  be 
the  source  of  many  grievous  errors,  unless  we  are  very  watchful 
against  them.  Besides,  they  are  framed  after  the  fancy  and  capacity 
of  the  common  sort,  so  that  they  are  but  signs  of  things  as  they  are 
in  the  imagination,  not  as  they  are  in  the  understanding.  Which 
is  evident  from  this,  that  on  all  such  things  as  lie  in  understanding 
only  and  not  in  imagination  they  have  fixed  names  that  are  often- 
times negative,  as  are  incoi-poi-eal,  infinite,  and  the  like.  Many  other 
things  which  are  in  truth  affirmative  they  express  in  negative  terms, 
and  conversely,'  because  in  each  case  the  contrary  is  far  easier  to  be 
imagined  :  thus  the  names  occurred  in  that  easier  form  to  the  men 
who  first  framed  them,  and  they  used  positive  terms  for  negative 
ideas.  There  is  much  that  we  affirm  and  deny  because  the  nature 
of  language  allows  us  so  to  do,  and  yet  the  nature  of  things  doth  not ; 
so  that,  not  knowing  this  last,  we  might  well  take  falsehood  for  truth.' 

Spinoza  proceeds  ^  to  the  second  part  of  the  doctrine  of 
method,  which  prescribes  as  the  ends  to  be  sought,  first  the 
possession  of  clear  and  distinct  ideas  '  produced  by  the  pure 
operation  of  the  mind,  not  by  casual  bodily  motions  ; '  next 
the  reduction  of  these  to  unity.  For  this  purpose  we  must 
endeavour  so  to  connect  and  order  our  ideas  '  that  our  mind, 
so  far  as  possible,  may  represent  in  thought  the  reality  of 
nature  both  as  a  whole  and  in  its  parts.'  Finite  things  must 
be  understood  through  their  immediate  causes;  'for  the 
knowledge  of  an  effect  is  in  truth  nothing  else  than  acquiring 
a  more  perfect  knowledge  of  the  cause,'  Hence  it  appears, 
adds  Spinoza  in  a  note,  that  we  can  understand  no  part  of 
nature  without  at  the  same  time  increasing  our  knowledge  of 
the  first  cause  or  God  ;  in  modern  language,  every  true  expla- 
nation of  a  particular  fact  gives  us  a  particular  piece  of  the 
single  and  universal  order  of  nature,  and  thereby  adds  to  our 
knowledge  of  that  order.     '  Therefore,'  the  text  continues,  '  so 

'  The  Latin  here  repeats  instances  of  terms  negative  in  form,  but  gives  none 
of  terms  affirmative  in  form  but  negative  in  meaning.  There  seems  to  be  some 
confusion  or  omission  in  the  text.  In  the  first  sentence  of  the  paragraph  here 
translated,  it  is  not  clear  whether  the  siibject  of  cornpomnitur  is  verba  or  coticeptus 
\  have  assumed  the  former. 

•  Cap.  12. 

L 


146  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

long  as  our  business  is  inquiry  concerning  actual  things,  we 
may  never  form  any  conclusion  from  abstract  notions  ;  and 
■  we  shall  use  exceeding  care  not  to  confound  that  which  is 
only  in  the  understanding  with  that  which  is  in  the  thing 
itself.' 

To  appreciate  the  significance  of  this  we  must  bear  ino 
mind  that  Spinoza  was  a  thorough-going  nominalist.     And 
further  on   he  says  that  our  chief  aim  should  be  to  acquire 
knowledge  of  particulars.     Such  an  outspoken  abjuration  of 
all  figments  and  preconceived  notions  might  almost  be  ex- 
jpected  to  introduce  without  more  ceremony  an  exhortation 
*f  :  -to  practical   observation.     But  Spinoza  proceeds  otherwise : 
■|he  tells  us  that  the  best  way  is  to  work  from  the  true  defini- 
tion of  the  thing  investigated,  and  that  the  next  problem  is 
lo  fix  the  conditions  of  such,  a  definition. 

What  he  says  on  this  topic  ^  is  very  characteristic.  *  A 
definition,  if  it  is  to  be  called  perfect,  must  explain  the  very 
nature  of  the  thing,  and  beware  of  using  instead  thereof  only 
some  of  its  properties.'  He  gives  as  an  example  the  defini- 
tion of  a  circle,  which  he  chooses  merely  for  convenience  ;  a 
circle  being,  like  all  geometrical  figures,  an  abstraction,  so 
that  it  really  matters  not  which  of  the  possible  definitions  we 
take.2  If  we  define  a  circle  as  a  figure  such  that  the  radii 
from  the  centre  to  the  circumference  are  equal,  we  get  only  a 
particular  property  of  the  circle,  and  have  not  accounted  for 
the  circle  itself  And  if  we  were  dealing  with  a  real  thing 
this  would  be  serious.  The  true  definition  of  a  created  (which 
practically  means  finite  ^)  thing  should  satisfy  two  conditions. 
I.  It  must  include  the  immediate  cause  {causa  proximo)  of 
the  thing,     2,  It  must  be  such  that  all  the  properties^  of  the 

'  Cap.  13. 

"^  '  Figura  non  aliud  quam  determinatio,  et  determinatio  negatio  est.'  Ep.  50, 
§  4.  Modern  readers,  however,  will  have  no  difficulty  in  admitting  that  a  circle  or 
hyperbola  is  not  a  physically  existing  thing. 

3  Not  exactly,  for  res  creata  here  must  =  modus  in  the  'Ethics,'  and  Spinoza 
sx>tik%  o^  infinite  modes.     (See  above,  p.  108.) 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  147 

thing,  so  far  as  it  is  considered  apart  from  everything  else, 
can  be  deduced  from  it.     In  the  case  of  the  circle  these  con- 
3ifT6lTs"w6illd  be  fulfitle'd  by  defining  it  as  the  figure  described 
by  the  free  extremity  of  a  straight  line  whose  other  end  is 
fixed.     As  to  the  definition  of  an  uncreated  thing,  it  must 
show  that  the  thing  is  not  explained  by  reference  to  anything 
outside  itself,  which  Spinoza  calls  the  exclusion  of  a  cause  ;  it   , 
must  make  the  existence  of  the  thing  evident  ;  the  explana-  j  J 
tion  must  involve  no  abstract  notions  ;  and  all  the  properties  ]/ 
of  the  thing  must  be  deducible  from  the   definition,  which  / 
however  is  not  so  material  in  this  case. 

All  this  is  at  first  sight  perplexing,  and  if  we  take  the 
terms  in  their  common  meaning  it  is  hardly  intelligible.     We 
have  then  to  consider  what  Spinoza  really  meant  by  a  defini- 
tion, and  what  was  the  causa  proxhna  which,  wherever  a  cause 
is  admissible,  the  definition  must  include.     He  requires  of  a    \ 
definition,  as  it  appears  to  me,  a  great  deal  more  than  logicians 
require  ;  so  much  that  it  may  fairly  be  suggested  that  what 
he  calls  a  definition  would  now  be  called  a  scientific  explana- 
tion.    It  is  not  merely  an  equation  of  names,  but  an  equation 
of  ideas  corresponding  to  a  constant  relation  between  facts, 
and  expressing  the  reduction  of  something  unknown  to  terms 
of  known  elements.     If  this  be  so,  the  '  immediate  cause  '  is 
the  known  condition  or  set  of  conditions  in  terms  of  which  the 
unknown  thing  can  Be  expressed.     Definition  is  the  same  pro-        • 
cess,  considered  with  regard  to  the  observer's  mind,  which  is    / 
explanation  when  we  consider  it  with  regard  to  the  object,   f  s ;  .  ^ 
As  the  object  is  to  our  idea  of  it,  so  is  explanation  to  defini-    \^ 
tion  ;  explanation  resolves  the  given  phenomenon  into  better 
known  or  more  familiar  elements  of  fact,  definition  resolves 
the  idea  of  it  into  better  known  or  more  familiar  elements  of 
thought.  On  this  view  it  is  quite  natural  that  where  there  is  no 
real  physical  sequence,  as  in  the  case  of  geometrical  figures,  the 
causa  pro xivta  should  be  different  as  we  approach  the  subject 
from  one  or  another  direction,  and  that,  as  Spinoza  says,  it 

L  2 


148  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

should  matter  little  which  direction  we  take.  The  causa pvoxinia 
of  a  circle,  if  we  confine  ourselves  to  pure  geometry,  is  the 
revolution  of  a  straight  line.  But  in  analytical  geometry  it  is 
otherwise.  Although  it  is  easy  to  show  that  this  process  will 
give  a  circle,  the  '  immediate  cause '  of  a  circle  will  not  be  any 
such  graphical  process,  but  the  existence  of  a  certain  relation 
among  the  coefficients  of  the  general  equation  of  the  second 
degree.  For  in  analytical  geometry  the  general  notion  of  a 
curve  of  the  second  order  is  prior  to  that  of  any  particular  kind 
such  as  circle  or  ellipse  :  and  from  this  general  conception  can 
be  deduced  not  only  the  familiar  geometrical  properties  of  the 
circle,  but  others  which  are  neither  demonstrable  nor  intelli- 
gible except  from  the  more  general  point  of  view. 

We  may  also  find  more  practical  examples  of  that  which 
(as  I  venture  to  suggest)  Spinoza  means  to  require  in  a  defini- 
tion. A  chemical  formula  will  give  us  a  fairly  good  illustra- 
tion. In  this  case  the  formula  describes  the  thing  exactly 
and  in  terms  of  its  '  immediate  cause,'  namely,  the  elements 
hi/  whose  combination  in  definite  proportions  it  is  formed. 
And  the  definition  itself  leads  to  a  scientific  knowledge  of  the 
thing  defined  which  is  incomplete  only  by  reason  that  our 
knowledge  of  the  simple  elements  and  of  the  dynamical  laws 
according  to  which  combination  takes  place  is  not  complete. 
Or;  to  take  another  example  from  a  science  which  is  not 
physical,  Savigny's  definition  of  Agreement  ( Vertrag)  as  a 
legal  term  furnishes  us  with  a  perfect  instance  of  what  is 
sought  by  Spinoza.  Most  of  the  definitions  found  in  our 
law  books,  and  not  least  the  definitions  of  Contract,  are  loose 
and  unsatisfying.  They  are  vague,  insufficient,  and  redun- 
dant ;  they  assume  knowledge  of  other  matters  that  have 
never  been  explained  ;  they  fail,  in  Spinoza's  language,  to 
expound  the  thing  defined  in  terms  of  its  causa proxivia.  But 
Savigny  goes  to  the  root  of  the  matter  and  gives  us  a  clear 
statement  of  the  simple  elements  that  make  up  the  legal 
Idea.     His  definition  is  accurate  and  exhaustive,  and  therefore 


7 HE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  149 

fruitful.  Or  take,  again,  the  minuter  analysis  by  which  the 
first  chapter  of  the  Indian  Contract  Act  arrives  at  the  more 
specific  conception  of  contract.  It  builds  up  the  causa 
proxima  step  by  step  in  a  series  of  elements,  none  of  which, 
taken  alone,  would  have  any  legal  effect,  but  which  combine 
to  form  the  complex  event  whose  legal  significance  is  denoted 
by  the  technical  term. 

The  last  chapter  of  Spinoza's  treatise  now  in  hand,  which 
however  breaks  off  abruptly,  shows  that  the  way  to  a  defini- 
tior>,  as  understood  by  him,  was  not  to  discuss  the  application 
of  a  word,  but  to  consider  what  we  know  alDOUt  the  thing 
denoted  by  it.     True  it  is  that  the  greater  part  of  the  words 


and  ideas  in  ordinary  use  are  in  the  present  state  of  our  know- 
ledge not  capable  of  being  defined  at  all  in  this  sense.  The 
definition  of  any  '  natural  kind,'  to  use  J.  S.  Mill's  term,  would 
have  to  give  us  not  only  the  specific  characteristics  of  the 
kind  in  question,  but  their  '  immediate  cause,'  in  other  words, 
to  show  how  they  come  to  be  what  they  are  :  and  it  is  barely 
conceivable  that  in  this  region  of  natural  history  we  shall 
ever  get  beyond  more  or  less  probable  conjecture.  We  have 
verae  causae  in  natural  selection,  adaptation,  and  the  like,  but 
to  assign  the  proxima  causa  of  any  existing  type  we  should 
have  to  know  exactly  in  what  manner  and  proportions  their 
effects  took  place  in  the  particular  instance.  There  is  no 
reason  to  suppose,  however,  that  Spinoza  would  have  been 
afraid  of  saying  that  very  few  perfect  definitions  had  been 
found  or  could  be  expected.  The  statement  made  earlier  in 
the  treatise  (c.  4,  §  22)  that  he  had  as  yet  been  able  to  com- 
prehend but  very  few  things  with  the  fourth  or  most  perfect 
kind  of  knowledge,  '  ubi  res  percipitur  per  solam  suam  es-  | 
sentiam  vel  per  cognitionem  suae  proximae  causae,'  is  indeed 
equivalent  to  this.  I  have  little  doubt  that  Spinoza  believed 
his  own  definition  of  God,  the  sum  and  origin  of  all  existence 
(to  which  we  shall  come  afterwards)  to  satisfy  the  conditions 
here  laid  down  by  him  ;  I  am  by  no  means  sure  that  he  did 


I50  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

not  consider  it  the  only  perfect  definition  attainable,  except 
those  of  geometrical  and  other  abstract  conceptions,  and 
possibly  of  the  '  infinite  modes.'  It  is  impossible  to  see  how  o 
his  requirements  can  be  strictly  complied  with  in  the  case  of 
any  finite  thing  whatever  :  and  it  is  equally  impossible  to  sup- 
pose that  he  overlooked  so  manifest  a  difficulty. 

Spinoza's  next  topic  is  '  the   means  of  knowing  eternal 
things.' '     We  must  constantly  derive  our  ideas,  he  says,  fromc 
physical  or  really  existing  things,  proceeding  according  to  the 
series  of  causes  from  one  really  existent  thing  to  another,  and 
so  as  never  to  pass  over  into  abstract  and  universal  notions. 
So  far  there  is  not  much  difficulty  in  accepting  his  counsel ; 
but  we  come  upon  an  explanation  which  seems  to  unsettle 
everything.     We  are  bidden  to  note  that  the  series  of  causes 
and  realities  here  mentioned  is  not  a  series  of  particular  and 
mutable  things  '  but  only  of  constant   and  eternal  ones.'     It 
is  beyond  human  powers  to  follow  up  the  innumerable  and 
complicated    sequences    of  particular  things  :  but  it  is  also 
needless,  for  the  actual  train  of  events  or  '  order  of  existence ' 
among  finite  things  depends   on  external  circumstances,  and 
the  '  very  nature '  {mtima  essentia)  of  things  is  to  be  sought 
in  the  '  constant  and   eternal  things,'  and  the  laws  whereof 
those   things  are  as  it  were  the  tables,  and  by   which  the 
{course  of  all   mutable  things  is  governed.     These  '  constant 
i  and    eternal '    things    are  themselves   particular  {smgularia), 
\lbut,  as  they  are  present  and  operative  everywhere,  we  must 
^l  regard  them  as  universal  with  regard  to  all  mutable  things, 
and  as  being  the  '  immediate  causes  '  of  all  other  particular 
existence. 

What  can   these  eternal  things  be  .-*     The  interpretation^ 
that  lies  nearest  at  hand  for  a  modern  reader  is  to  identify 
them  with  the  constant  relations  among  phenomena  which 
we  now  call  the  laws  of  nature.     But  this  is  evidently  not 
admissible.     Spinoza,  the  downright   enemy  of  abstractions' 

'  Cap.  14. 


n  THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD.  151 

I        and  universals,   knew   the  difference   between   relations  and 
j        things  far  too  well  to  confuse  them  in  this  way.     Besides,  he 
I         wanted   no  artificial   way  of  describing  laws  of  nature  ;  the 
name  was  already  familiar  in  his  time,  and  he  could  speak  of 
I         them,  when  he  thought  fit,  just  as  we  do.     In  fact,  he  does 
(  speak  of  the  '  eternal  things  '  as  having  laws  of  their  own  in 

some  way  attached  to  or  involved  in  them,  which  pervade 
j  the  whole  world  of  phenomena.     Clearly,  therefore,  the  things 

li  in  question  are  not  themselves  laws.     Another  explanation 

is  offered  by  a  writer  who  has  done  excellent  work  for  the 
history  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  ideas.  Professor  Sigwart  of 
Tubingen.  He  says  with  some  confidence,  on  the  strength 
of  certain  resemblances  in  language  between  our  treatise  and 
the  '  Novum  Organum,'  that  the  '  eternal  things '  of  Spinoza 
are  identical  with  the  Forms  of  Bacon's  doctrine  of  Method. 
But  surely  this  will  not  serve  either.  For  the  Baconian 
Forms  are  not  things  at  all,  certainly  would  not  be  recognized 
as  such  by  Spinoza :  and  if  we  are  to  find  a  parallel  in  this 
treatise  to  what  Bacon  meant  by  the  Form  of  a  thing,  it 
seems  to  me  that  it  would  be  more  hopefully  sought  in 
Spinoza's  causa  proxima.  And  Spinoza's  nominalism,  which 
we  have  always  to  bear  in  mind,  is  a  sufficient  warning 
against  assuming  that  the  '  eternal  things  '  have  anything  to 
do  with  kinds,  qualities,  or  classification. 

My  own  opinion  is  perhaps  too  simple  to  be  accept- 
able.^ We  have  just  found  in  the  chapter  treating  of  defini- 
tion that  Spinoza,  for  whatever  reason,  sometimes  used 
general  terms  when  his  description  was  really  meant  to 
apply  to   very   few    instances   or   even    to   a    solitary    one. 

'  It  is  not  far  removed  from  Trendelenburg's,  Histor.  Beitrdge  zur  PhilosophU, 
iii.  387.  But  he  seems  to  identify  Spinoza's  '  eternal  things  '  not  with  the  infinite  , 
modes  themselves,  but  with  their  laws  or  relations.  See,  too,  Leibnitz's  marginal 
note  on  this  passage,  ap.  Foucher  de  Careil,  Leibniz^  Descartes,  et  Spinoza,  p.  123, 
It  consists  of  this  list  :  Deus,  spatitan,  materia,  tnotus,  potentia  universi,  intel- 
lectus  agens,  mundus.  The  words  in  italics  are  cancelled.  The  others,  I  suspect, 
were  meant  by  Leibnitz,  not  for  an  interpretation  of  Spinoza,  but  for  an  improve- 
ment on  him. 


152  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

Accordingly  we  need  not   expect  to  find  any  great   number 
of   '  eternal    things,'    if  we   succeed    in  finding  them  at    all. 
There    would   be    nothing   repugnant   to  Spinoza's  habit  of 
^thought  and  discourse  if  there  turned  out  to  be  very  few  of 
j     them.     But  when  the  illusory  expectation  of  a  large  class  of 
things,  representing  some  such  higher  order  of  existence  as 
the  Platonic  Ideas,  is  once  done  away  with,  the  true  solution 
presents    itself,  as    I    think,   readily   enough.     The   '  eternal 
things '  are  simply    the    '  infinite   modes '    which    afterwards 
occur  in  the  'Ethics,'  and  which^we  have  had  occasion  to  men- 
tion in   speaking  of  the   influence  exercised  on  Spinoza  by 
^the  physical  conceptions    of  Descartes.'     These  are,  in    the 
/material  world,  in  the   first  place  Motion,  which  to  a  disciple 
iof  the   Cartesian  physics  was  a  real,  eternal,   and  constant 
%  \  thing  ;  in  the   second    place,    as    presupposing   Motion,    the 
material    universe  itself,  taken   as  a  sum  of  existence  which 
is  constant    under   all    its    changing  aspects.     In   the    world 
of  thought    we  have,    corresponding   to    Motion,    a   fact   or 

process     called    '  infinite intellect ; '    what    should    answer 

in  thought  to  the  sum  of  material  things,  the  'facies  totius 
universi,'  we  are  not  told.^  We  must  also  assume  other  cor- 
responding facts  without  limit  in  other  aspects  of  existence 
capable  of  being  related  to  minds  associated  with  them  in 
ways  analogous  to  the  relation  of  the  material  universe  to 
human  thought ;  but  these  could  be  no  part  of  human 
experience,  nor  imaginable  by  human  faculties.  This  results 
from  the  theory  of  the  Infinite  Attributes,  of  which  there  is 
no  mention  in  the  present  treatise. 

The  assertion  that  all  particular  things  happen  according? 
to  the  laws  of  the  *  eternal  things  '  are  on  the  view  here  taken 
equivalent,  so  far  as  concerns  the  material  world,  to  saying 
that  all  physical  events  are  ultimately  explicable  by  dyna- 
mical laws.  And  to  what  could  Spinoza  more  appropriately 
ascribe  'presence  in  all  parts  and  unbounded  operation  '  than 

'     P.  io8,  above.  *  Ep.  66,  ad  fin. 


THE  DOCTRINE   OF  METHOD. 


'5j 


to  Matter  and  Motion  ?  Again,  a  certain  configuration  of 
matter  under  dynamical  conditions  would  be  most  naturally- 
described  in  Spinoza's  language  as  iki^  causa  proxima  oi  ^v&xy 
individual  object.'  But  we  are  left  without  any  farther  light 
by  Spinoza,  for  he  goes  into  an  auxiliary  discussion  of  the 
nature  and  powers  of  the  understanding :  and  Avith  the 
chapter  containing  this  the  work  breaks  off.  He  enumerates 
the  properties  of  the  understanding,  as  the  only  practicable 
way  of  arriving  at  the  full  knowledge  or  definition  of  its 
nature.  He  speaks  not  of  human  understanding,  but  of  the 
operations  of  human  thought  (nostras  cogitationes)  as  depend- 
ing on  the  nature  of  understanding  in  general :  and  I  think 
there  is  room  for  more  than  a  suspicion  that  the  object  of  the 
definition  which  was  never  completed  was  to  be  not  the 
human  understanding  as  such,  but  '  intellectus  absolute 
infinitus.'  We  shall  here  take  note  of  only  one  of  the  propo- 
sitions laid  down  as  to  the  properties  of  intellect,  which  throws 
light  on  Spinoza's  distinction  between  understanding  and 
imagination,  and  is  the  first  occasion  of  his  using  a  phrase  on 
which  the  difficulties  of  the  last  Part  of  the  Ethics  may  in 
great  measure  be  said  to  turn.  '  It  perceives  things  not  so  F 
much  under  the  head  of  duration,  as  under  a  cert  am  form  of 
eternity  and  without  finite  number  ;  or  rather  it  attends  to  the 
perception  itself  and  not  to  number  or  duration.  But  when 
it  imagines  things,  it  perceives  them  as  certain  in  number, 
and  with  a  definite  duration  and  quantity.' 

This  appears  to  mean  that  acts  of  pure  intellect  (such  as 
the  perception  of  a  general  truth  in  physics)  are  of  universal^ 
validity  and  have  no  reference  to  particular  events  as  such. 

For  example,  the  theoretical  statement  of  the  flight  of  a 
projectile  in  a  resisting  medium  under  the  influence  of  gravity, 


'  What  Spinoza  actually  says,  however,  is  that  the  '  fixa  et  aeterna '  (instead 
of  the  particular  configurations)  are  themselves  the  causae  proximae.  This  is  not 
exact,  and  the  comparison  of  this  passage  with  EtJi.  i.  28  goes  to  show  that  he 
afterwards  perceived  the  inaccuracy. 


154  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

and  of  the  energy  transferred  to  other  bodies  by  its  impact, 
is  equally  applicable  at  all  times,  everywhere,  and  to  one  or 
a  thousand  experiences,  assuming  the  laws  of  matter  and 
motion  to  suffer  no  change.  It  is  an  affirmation '  sub  quadam 
specie  aeternitatis  et  numero  infinito.'  On  the  other  hand 
the  observation  of  the  course  and  effects  of  a  projectile  in  a 
particular  experiment  is  the  record  of  a  specific  event  which 
happened  at  a  given  time  and  place,  and  otherwise  und^r 
defined  conditions :  so  much  initial  velocity,  so  much  less  at 
the  end  of  successive  seconds,  so  many  foot-tons  of  striking 
energy,  such  and  such  fractures  and  displacements  in  the 
target.  The  facts  are  found  'sub  certo  numero,  determinata 
duratione  et  quantitate.'  I  am  not  unconscious  that  interpre- 
tations of  this  kind  are  perilous  ;  but  I  believe  that  the  present 
one  is  near  enough  to  the  substance  of  Spinoza's  meaning  to 
be  of  some  assistance  until  a  better  is  found. 


THE  NATURE    OF   THINGS  155 


CHAPTER   V. 

THE   NATURE   OF   THINGS. 

Know  in  thyself  and  the  world  one  selfsame  soul  : 
Banish  the  dream  that  sunders  the  part  from  the  whole. 

Sankara  AchXrya. 
I  am  that  which  began  ; 

Out  of  me  the  years  roll ; 
Out  of  me  God  and  man  ; 
I  am  equal  and  whole  ; 
God  changes,  and  man,  and  the  form  of  them  bodily  ;  I  am  the  soul. 

Swinburne,  Hertha. 

Having  in  foregoing  chapters  learnt  to  know  something  of 
Spinoza's  habit  of  thought,  we  are  now  prepared  to  go  up  into 
the  heart  and  citadel  of  his  philosophy  as  we  find  it  set  forth 
in  the  '  Ethics.'  I  have  endeavoured  to  make  the  philosopher 
himself  in  some  measure  smooth  the  reader's  path  to  the  dif- 
ficulties of  his  great  work :  but  it  is  not  to  be  supposed  that 
these  difficulties  can  be  wholly  done  away.  Spinoza  has  cast  his 
thought  in  singular  and  even  startling  forms,  and  we  must  be 
content  to  grapple  with  the  form  if  we  mean  to  grasp  the 
substance.  Yet  it  may  not  be  useless  to  give  at  one's  own 
risk  a  sort  of  free  translation  of  the  thought  which,  according 
to  the  view  here  taken  of  Spinoza's  general  purpose,  may  be 
apprehended  as  underlying  the  elaborate  construction  of  his 
metaphysic.  It  seems  to  me  that  in  modern  language  it  may 
be  rendered  somewhat  as  follows. 

Europe  had  for  centuries  been  filled  with  the  noise  of 
scholastic  discussion  over  questions  incomprehensible  to  ordi- 
nary sense,  of  which  the  staple  was  furnished  by  such  terms  as 
substance,  attribute,  essence,  existence,  eternity.     And  these  terms 


156  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

were  the  established  stock  in  trade,  as  it  were,  not  only  of 
philosophical  language  but  of  philosophical  thought.  Such 
as  they  were,  these  were  the  tools  with  which  Spinoza  had  to 
work.  Even  if  he  could  have  conceived  the  notion  of  dis- 
carding them  altogether  and  inventing  new  ones,  which  how- 
ever was  in  his  circumstances  not  possible,  it  was  only  by 
keeping  them  in  use  that  he  had  any  prospect  of  inducing 
students  of  philosophy  to  listen  to  him.  But  the  powerful^ 
and  subtle  minds  which  had  exercised  themselves  on  these 
ideas  had  troubled  themselves  but  little  as  to  their  relation  to 
actual  things  and  man's  knowledge  of  them.  It  was  assumed 
that  the  foundations  had  been  settled  once  for  all,  while  the 
flood  of  new  ideas,  unseen  and  irresistible,  was  in  truth  ad- 
vancing to  break  them  up.  The  cunningly  wrought  structure 
of  mediaeval  philosophy  was  doomed  ;  and  now  that  it  has 
crumbled  away  philosophy  goes  houseless,  though  not  des- 
pairing ;  for  after  all  it  is  better  to  be  a  wanderer  than  to 
dwell  in  castles  in  the  air. 

But  meanwhile  what  was  a  man  in  Spinoza's  place  to  do  } 
The  terms  were  there  to  his  hand,  still  the  only  currency  of 
scholars  ;  the  ideas  for  which  they  had  been  framed  were 
dead  or  dying,  and  the  great  scientific  conception  of 
the  unity  and  uniformity  of  the  world,  often  seen  as  in 
visions,  but  now  unveiled  in  all  its  power  by  Descartes, 
had  already  begun  to  spread  abroad,  subduing  everything 
to  its  dominion.  A  sincere  and  unflinching  eye  could 
already  see  that  in  the  end  nothing  would  escape  from  it,  not 
even  the  most  secret  recesses  of  human  thought.  Only  in 
the  light  of  this  conquering  idea  could  the  old  words  live,  if 
they  were  to  live  at  all.  If  any  vital  truth  lay  hidden  in  them 
from  of  old,  it  would  thus  be  brought  out  and  bear  its  due 
fruit  ;  and  what  new  life  was  wanting  must  be  breathed  into  <d 
them  through  the  new  conception  of  the  nature  of  things. 
This,  I  believe,  was  in  effect  the  task  Spinoza  took  upon  him- 
self.    It  cannot  be  maintained  that  it  was  altogether  a  pos- 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  157 

sible  one  ;  and  it  is  at  least  doubtful  whether  Spinoza  himself 
was  fully  aware  of  its  magnitude.  I  do  not  think  he  realized 
the  extent  of  the  revolution  which  was  really  involved  in  his 
use  of  philosophical  terms.  He  seems  to  have  been  in  perfect 
good  faith  shocked  and  surprised  at  the  vehemence  of  the 
opposition  excited  by  his  opinions,  though,  from  the  point  of 
view  of  the  objectors,  nothing  could  be  more  natural.  He 
thought  he  was  correcting  erroneous  interpretations  when  he 
was  in  truth  abrogating  the  text.  Thus  we  find  almost^ 
everywhere  in  his  work  scientific  and  essentially  modern 
thought  clothed  in  the  semblance  of  scholastic  forms  ;  and 
this  creates  for  a  modern  reader  an  illusion  which  it  is  ex- 
tremely difficult  to  shake  off.  It  seems  at  first  sight  a  mere 
paradox  to  say  that  Spinoza  is  not  only  more  scientific  than 
his  predecessors,  but,  allowing  for  the  unavoidable  defects  of 
his  physical  knowledge,  as  scientific  as  any  modern  philo- 
sopher whatever  ;  that,  so  far  from  his  metaphysical  principles 
being  repugnant  or  foreign  to  scientific  thinking,  it  is  just 
the  thoroughly  scientific  cast  of  Spinoza's  thought  which  has 
made  his  work  a  stumbling-block  to  the  greater  part  of  his 
readers ;  and  that  when  he  has  been  misunderstood,  it  has 
generally  been  because  his  interpreters  have  not  had  enough 
of  scientific  training  or  temper  to  understand  him  rightly. 
Nevertheless  I  hope  to  show  that  this  apparent  paradox  is 
true. 

In  the  exposition  of  his  philosophy  Spinoza  follows  a 
suggestion  made  by  Descartes,  and  throws  it  into  a  highly 
artificial  form  borrowed  from  the  usage  of  geometry.  There 
is  the  same  array  of  definitions,  axioms,  propositions,  and 
corollaries,  as  in  Euclid  ;  and  every  step  in  the  argument 
p\irports  to  be  definitely  warranted  by  something  already 
demonstrated  or  claimed  as  self-evident.  Only  the  diagrams 
are  wanting  to  complete  the  external  resemblance.  Few 
readers  will  at  the  present  time  be  found  to  doubt  that  this 
proceeding    was   on    the    whole    unfortunate.     It    gives    to 


158  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE   jumu   rnii.Kj^unix. 

Spinoza's  work,  in  addition  to  its  real  difficulties,  a  needless 
air  of  abstruseness  and  technicality. 

Probably  many  students  have  been  thus  frightened  away 
before  they  had  made  any  real  acquaintance  with  his  thought. 
The  geometrical  form  of  exposition  has  also  led  to  much  ex- 
aggerated language  about  the  rigid  consistency  of  Spinoza's 
system.  Admirers  have  pushed  their  enthusiasm  on  this 
point  into  hyperbole,  and  critics,  taking  them  at  their  word, 
have  assumed  that  the  whole  system  would  be  disposed  of  if 
they  could  succeed  in  picking  holes  in  a  few  of  the  definitions. 
Again,  critics  have  been  misled  in  another  way  by  the  sup- 
position that  Spinoza's  doctrines  were  intimately  connected 
with  the  form  in  which  they  were  stated  ;  and  no  small  in- 
genuity has  been  wasted  on  tracing  his  real  or  supposed 
mistakes  to  his  reliance  on  the  geometrical  method.  This 
oversight,  though  perhaps  natural,  might  have  been  avoided 
by  more  careful  consideration  of  Spinoza's  other  works,  as  we 
have  already  had  occasion  to  point  out.  Lastly,  it  is  very 
possible  that  in  some  ways  this  artificial  mode  of  exposition 
had  an  unfavourable  influence  on  Spinoza  himself.  I  am<3 
disposed  to  think,  in  particular,  that  it  materially  disguised 
from  him  the  nature  and  extent  of  the  assumptions  on  which 
his  work  was  really  founded,  and  of  the  tacit  appeals  to  ex- 
perience contained  in  them.  In  geometry  these  appeals  rest 
on  a  ground  so  broad  and  secure  that,  except  for  the  higher 
geometry  which  involves  discussion  of  the  nature  of  geometri- 
cal truth  itself,  it  does  not  matter  whether  they  are  recognized 
or  not :  but  in  philosophy  it  is  otherwise. 

It  seems  therefore  not  only  permissible  but  desirable  to 
depart  considerably  from  the  strict  order  of  the  original  in  the 
endeavour  to  give  a  generally  intelligible  outline  of  the  '  Ethics.' 
But  we  cannot  altogether  leave  the  peculiar  form  out  of  sight: 
for  much  that  is  important  and  characteristic  depends  on 
Spinoza's  use  of  particular  expressions,  which  cannot  be 
understood  without  reference  to  his  definitions.     And  before 


ITU  RE   OF  THINGS.  159 

we  go  farther  it  will  be  convenient  to  translate  once  for  all  the 
Definitions  of  the  First  Part.     They  are  as  follows  : — 

Definitions. 

1.  By  self -caused  (causa  sui)  I  understand  that  of  which  the 
essence  involves  existence,  that  is,  whose  nature  cannot  be  conceivecj 
otherwise  than  as  existing. 

2.  A  thing  is  called  finite  in  its  kind,  which  can  be  limited  by 
another  of  the  same  nature.  For  example,  a  body  is  called  finite, 
because  we  may  always  conceive  another  as  greater.  So  a  thought 
is  limited  by  another  thought.  But  a  body  is  not  limited  by  thought, 
nor  a  thought  by  body. 

/.S'3-'!By  substafice  I  understand  that  which  is  in  itself  and  is  con- 
jceive<i  by  itself ;  that  is,  whose  concept  needs  not  the  concept  of 
/another  thing  for  it  to  be  formed  from. 

j     1 4-  By  attribute  I  understand  that  which  intellect  perceives  con- 
cerning Substance,  as  constituting  the  essence  thereof.^ 

1  5.  By  mode  I  understand  the  affections  of  Substance,  or  that 
which  is  in  somewhat  else,  through  which  also  it  is  conceived. 

"6.  By   God   I  understand   a  being   absolutely   infinite,  that  is, 

V Substance  consisting  of  infinite  attributes,  whereof  each  one  expresses 
eternal  and  infinite  being. 

Explanation.  I  say  infinite  absolutely,  not  in  its  own  kind.  For 
whatever  is  infinite  only  in  its  own  kind  may  have  infinite  attributes 
denied  of  it;  but  if  it  is  absolutely  infinite,  there  belongs  to  its  nature  ^ 
whatever  expresses  reality,''  and  involves  no  denial. 

7.  A  thing  is  caWed/ree,  which  exists  by  the  mere  necessity  of  its 
own  nature  and  is  determined  to  action  by  itself  alone  :  but  necessary, 
or  rather  constrained,  if  it  is  determined  by  something  else  to  exist 
and  operate  in  a  certain  determined  manner. 

8.  By  eternity  I  understand  existence  itself,  so  far  as  it  is  con- 
ceived to  follow  necessarily  from  the  mere  definition  of  the  eternal 

thing. 

Explanation.  For  such  existence  is  conceived  as  an  eternal 
truth,  as  well  as  the  essence  of  the  thing,  and  therefore  cannot  be 

•  An  earlier  form  of  this  definition  is  given  in  Ep.  27  :  '  I  understand  the 
same  by  attribute,  except  that  it  is  called  attribute  with  respect  to  the  under- 
standing, which  attributes  to  substance  such  a  determined  nature  as  aforesaid. ' 

*  The  Latin  has  essentiam  in  both  places. 


i6o  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

explained  in  terms  of  duration  or  time,  though  its  duration    be  con- 
ceived as  without  beginning  or  end. 

Of  these   definitions    the   third,  fourth,  fifth,    and    sixth 
contain    the    fundamental    ideas    of    Spinoza's    metaphysic. 
The  others  may  go  without  comment  for  the  present  except 
the  first,  which  is  remarkable  rather  for  what  it  does  not  say 
than    for  what   it  says.     Spinoza    takes  the  current  phrase 
causa  sui,  and  defines  it  in  a  manner  which  leaves  causation 
wholly  out  of  account.     In  fact,  his  definition  implies  that 
the  use  of  the  word  cause  in  this  sense  is  really  inappropriate  : 
and  except  so  far  as  we  are  left   to  assume  the   converse, 
namely,  that  everything  which  can  '  be  conceived  otherwise 
than  as  existing '  must,  if  it  does  exist,  be  said  to  be  caused 
by  something  else,  he  does  not  tell  us  what  he  understands 
by  the  word  Cause  in  any  other  use.     In  the  axioms,  indeed 
(ax.  4)  he  says  '  the  knowledge  of  an  effect  depends  on  the 
knowledge  of  the  cause  and  involves  it.'     This  must  mean,  if 
it  is  to  give  any  acceptable  sense,  the  knowledge  of  the  effect 
as  suck;  in  that  sense  it  is  obviously  true,  but  throws  no  direct 
light  on  Spinoza's  conception  of  causation.     Yet,  when  we 
couple   it  with  the  absence  of  any  further  definition,  it  does 
appear  to  suggest  something  very  much  at  variance  with  the 
notions  commonly  formed  about  Spinoza's  philosophy.     This  0 
is  that,  so  far  from  regarding  causation  as  a  kind  of  mysterious 
power  which  keeps   together   the  order  of  nature,   Spinoza 
regarded  Cause  and  Eftect  as  correlated  terms  framed  by  us 
to  detach  parts  of  the   order  of  nature  from  the  whole  for 
more  convenient  examination,  and   nothing  else.     We  know 
that  he  believed  with   an  intense  and  vivid  belief  in  the  con- 
tinuity of  all    natural    phenomena   and    processes.     Several 
modern  thinkers  have  independently  come  to  the  conclusion 
that  this  same  continuity  does  not  suffer  us  to  look  upon  the 
notion  of  Cause  and  Effect  as  other  than  a  convenient  artifice 
to  keep  our  materials  within  manageable  bounds.     It  is  the 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  i6i 

separation  of  that  which  i's  separable  only  in  thought.' 
Spinoza  calls  time  and  space,  considered  as  measurable  o 
quantities,  '  aids  of  the  imagination  : '  on  this  view  causation 
would  be  an  '  aid  of  the  imagination  '  too.  But  if  we  assume 
a  real  causal  power  or  nexus,  the  law  of  causation  becomes 
the  most  universal  law  of  nature,  prior  even  to  that  of  uni- 
formity ;  for  we  might  conceive  the  causal  power  to  be 
universal  but  capricious  in  its  operation.  Had  Spinoza  held 
this  opinion,  we  might  surely  expect  to  find  causality  promi- 
nent among  the  '  constant  and  eternal  things '  which  gave  us 
some  trouble  to  explain  in  the  treatise  on  the  Amendment  of 
the  Understanding  (p.  150,  above).  It  would  indeed  hold  a 
unique  and  supreme  position  among  laws  of  nature  on 
Spinoza's  system  :  for  it  would  not  only  be  universal  in  each 
Attribute,  but  common  to  all  the  Attributes.  But  of  all  this 
there  is  no  hint,  so  far  as  I  know,  in  any  part  of  Spinoza's 
writings. 

If  the  inference  now  suggested  is  correct,  Spinoza  would 
have  said  that  infinite  intellect  forms  no  idea  of  cause  and 
effect,  except  as  being  an  idea  present  in  finite  minds.^  For 
a  mind  possessing  infinite  capacity  and  means  of  knowledge 
would  perceive  all  things  at  once  as  being,  and  necessarily 
being,  what  they  are  and  not  otherwise  ;  but  would  not 
perceive  the  necessity  as  distributed,  so  to  speak,  over  the 
particular  states  and  operations  of  nature.  //To  perceive 
things  as  necessary  is  to  perceive  them  as  they  are,  and  the  \ 
necessity  of  each  thing  is  no  other  than  the  necessity  of  the  ' 

'  G.  II.  Lewes,  in  Problems  of  Life  and  Mind,  vol.  ii.  ;  Mr.  Shadwortli  Hodg- 
son, in  his  Philosophy  of  Reflection,  1878  ;  cf.  Mr.  Carveth  Read's  remarks  in  his 
Essay  on  the  Theory  of  Logic,  1878  ;  and  see  W.  K.  Clifford,  Aims  and  Instru- 
ments of  Scientific  Thought,  m  Lectures  and  Essays,  Lond.  1879,  vol.  i.  p.  149. 
Cf.  also  Trendelenburg's  suggestion  [Histor.  Beitrdge,  iii.  275),  that  Causation 
in  general  (die  abstracte  Causalitiit)  may  be  resolved  into  the  idea  of  Motion  ; 
Motion  being  considered  as  equally  real  on  the  subjective  and  the  objective  side. 

*  The  position  suggested  might  be  expressed  in  Spinoza's  language  thus  :  'In 
Dei  infinito  intellectu  non  dari  obiective  ideam  causae  singularis  ;  sivc  tanluin 
eatenus  dari,  quatenus  humanae  mentis  naturam  conslituit.' 

M 


i62  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

universal  order.^//  If  it  had  occurred  to  any  correspondent  to 
put  to  Spinoza  the  particular  question  here  proposed,  we 
should  possibly  have  had  a  decisive  answer.  As  it  is,  we  are 
left  to  conjecture,  but  not  without  probability  to  guide  us. 
Spinoza  does  actually  say  that  infinite  intellect  forms  no 
general  ideas.  Therefore,  in  addition  to  what  has  been 
already  said,  there  seems  to  be  no  alternative  between  hold- 
ing that  Spinoza  regarded  cause  and  effect  as  merely  the 
machinery  of  finite  conceptions,  and  that  he  thought  causa- 
tion as  much  a  real  thing  as  matter  and  motion. 

What  is  it  that  Spinoza  regards  as  '  self-caused '  within 
the  meaning  of  his  first  definition  .■'     The  reply  is  given  by 
the  definition  of  Substance  and  by  the  chain  of  propositions 
formally  showing  that  the  two  coincide.     Substance  is  that 
which  is  '  in  itself  or  self-subsistent,  and  is  conceived  by  or 
through  itself,  that  is,  without  assuming  anything  else  to  exist. 
In  other  words,  it  can  be  conceived  as  existing  v/ithout  any 
'  external  reason   for  its  existence.     But  we  cannot  seriously  •- 
['  apply  such  a  conception  to  anything  short  of  the  whole  sum 
's/i\A  t%,  I  of  being,  within  which  we  may  seek  for  the  reason  of  particular 
things,  but  outside  which  we  cannot  go.     ExplanatiorLjs^  of 
the  relations  between   particular  things  ;  the  universe  in  its 
entirety  is  inexplicable.     And  to  say  of  the  universe,  in  the 
scholasticTariguage 'retained  by  Spinoza,  that  its  essence  in- 
volves existence,  does  not  really  import  any  greater  assump- 
tion than  that  something  does  exist.     It  may  indeed  be  asked 
what  we  mean  by  existence  ;  and  the  question  is  not  only  a 
reasonable  but  an  important  one.     But  this  way  of  consider- 
ing the  general  problem  of  knowledge  belongs  to  a  later  age 
than  Spinoza's,  and  it  is  useless  to  complain  of  him  for  not 
having  formally  anticipated  it.     Anything,  then,  which  is  sus- 
ceptible of  explanation,  derivation,  or  subordination  to  some- 
thing outside  it,  is  not  Substance  in  Spinoza's  meaning. 

Attribute  is  that  which   is  perceived   as  constituting  the 

'  Eth.  ii.  44. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  163 

nature  of  Substance  ;  and  to  understand  Spinoza's  view  we 
must  dismiss  from  our  mind  the  common  use  of  the  term.  If 
we  think  of  Spinoza's  Substance  as  distinct  from  and  under- 
lying the  Attributes,  as  being,  so  to  speak,  at  the  back  of  the 
Attributes  and  guarded  by  them  against  any  closer  approach, 
we  shall  certainly  go  wrong.  Attribute  is  perceived,  not  as 
merely  belonging  to  Substance,  but  '  as  constituting  its  nature.' 
Substance  is  indeed  manifested  in  the  Attributes,  but  there 
is  not  an  inaccessible  reality  behind  the  manifestations.  The 
manifestations  are  themselves  the  reality  ;  Substance  consists 
of  the  attributes  and  has  no  reality  other  thajTrteifsT'^Asfor 


the  sug;ge5ttomhafThe  perception  oT^the  understanding  in 
this  respect  may  be  illusory,  in  other  words  that  the  reality  of 
things  is  unknowable,  it  is  one  which  Spinoza  was  incapable 
of  entertaining  :  it  is  wholly  foreign  to  his  thought,  and  I 
submit  that  it  ought  so  to  be  to  all  sound  thinking.  This  is 
not  the  place  to  enter  on  a  general  metaphysical  discussion  ; 
but  I  may  be  permitted  to  say  here  shortly,  by  way  of  clear- 
ing the  ground,  that  to  me  it  amounts  to  a  contradiction  in 
terms  to  speak  of  '  unknowable  existence '  or  '  unknowable 
reality '  in  an  absolute  sense.  I  cannot  tell  what  existence 
means,  if  not  the  possibility  of  being  known  or  perceived. 
This  position,  implicitly  contained  in  Spinoza's  definitions,  was 
explicitly  taken  up,  and,  as  I  venture  'o  think,  in  the  main 
conclusively  established,  by  Berkeley.  Since  his  time  philo- 
sophy has  done  something,  and  science  much,  to  confirm  his 
w'ork.  But  I  do  not  know  that  the  point  will  bear  much 
labouring  ;  it  is  too  fundamental.  One  accepts  it,  or  one  does 
not,  and  the  whole  view  of  the  character  and  possibilities  of 
metaphysic  depends  on  this  primary  decision.  For  the  pre- 
sent, however,  our  chief  concern  is  not  to  defend  Spinoza's 
conception,  but  to  ascertain  what  it  actually  was.  And  I 
think  there  can  hardly  be  a  reasonable  doubt  that  for  Spinoza 
to  exist  and  to  be  intelligible  were  all  one.  Substance  is  not 
an    Unknowable,    Noumenon,  or  Biug  an  sick,  nor  arc  the 

M   2 


i64  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Attributes  forms  imposed   on  it  by  the  human  mind.     Yet, 
when  we  have  settled  what  the  Attributes  are  not,  there  is  no 
small  difficulty  in  finding  an  unexceptionable  term  to  describe 
what  they  are.     They  are  not  forms  of  Substance,  as  we  have 
seen  ;  neither  are  they  operations  or  energies,  for  that  also 
would  make  Substance  prior  to  and  distinct  from  them  ;  and 
much  less  are  we  to  be  misled  by  any  false  analogy  to  Neo- 
Platonic  fancies  of  emanations  and  the  like.     The  least  un- 
satisfactory word   I  can  suggest  is  aspect,  which  has  already 
been  used  by  modern  writers  with  virtually  the  same  meaning. 
Attribute,  as  Spinoza  himself  said  in  the  earlier  form  of  the 
definition,  is  Substance  itself  as  known  and  identified  by  the 
\  understanding.     The  division  of  attributes,  as  far  as  human 
knowledge  goes,  is  the  ultimate  division  of  experience  into 
subjective  and  objective,  or  mental  and  material.     We  know 
a  world  of  things  extended  in  space,  to  the  understanding  of 
which,  so  far  as  we  can  understand  them,  the  laws  of  matter 
and  motion  are  our  sole  and   sufficient   guide.     This  is,  in 
Spinoza's  language,  Substance  perceived  under  the  Attribute 
of  Extension.     Again,  we  know  a  world  of  thoughts,  feelings, 
mental  events,  or  however  we  may  call  its  elements,  to  which 
the  notions  of  space  and  extension  are  wholly  inapplicable  ; 
we  cannot  ascribe  mass  to  a  sensation,  or  resolve  a  thought 
into  atoms.     And  this  is  the  domain  of  Substance  perceived 
under  the  Attribute  of  Thought. 

It  is  to  be  observed  that,  inasmuch  as  Attribute  is  defined 
/  by  reference  to  intellect,  and  Thought  is  itself  an  attribute, 
Thought  appears  to  be  in  a  manner  counted  twice  over. 
Likewise  Extension  and  Thought,  although  they  are  the  only 
Attributes  we  have  anything  to  do  with,  are  in  Spinoza's  view 
only  two  out  of  an  infinite  number.  But  the  difficulties  that 
arise  on  both  these  points  are  better  postponed  for  a  while. 
,  As  for  the  modes  or  affections  of  Substance,  they  are 
nothing  else  than  particular  things.  Ever>'  material  object  is 
a  mode  of  Extension,  and  every 'feeling  is  a  mode  of  Thought. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  165 

It  will  as  a  rule  be  found  a  help  to  the  apprehension  of 
Spinoza's  meaning  to  read  thing  for  mode  ;  remembering  that 
any  aggregate  whatever,  within  the  limits  of  the  same  Attri- 
bute, may  be  taken  as  a  single  thing  ;  and  that  this  extends 
even  to  the  whole  material  universe,  and  to  the  sum  of  all 
thought.  The  whole  contents  of  any  Attribute  are  regarded 
by  Spinoza  as  an  infijiite  mode.  But  his  acceptance  of  motion 
as  a  real  thing  of  constant  quantity  compelled  him  to  regard 
Motion  as  an  infinite  Mode  by  itself,  and  more  '  immediately 
produced  by  God,'  or  dependent  on  the  very  nature  of  the 
attribute  of  Extension,  than  Matter ;  since  the  sensible  world, 
'  facies  totius  universi,'  is  not  matter  alone,  but  matter  diver- 
sified by  motion.  This  peculiarity  has  no  sensible  effect  on 
the  general  bearings  of  Spinoza's  philosophy.' 

The  definition  of  God  as  '  substance  consisting  of  infinite 
attributes,  whereof  every  one  expresses  eternal  and  infinite 
being,'  brings  us  face  to  face  with  Spinoza's  metaphysical  im- 
agination in  the  full  extent  of  its  daring.  In  the  eleventh 
proposition  of  the  First  Part  of  the  '  Ethics '  he  formally  de- 
monstrates that  this  *  absolutely  perfect  being '  exists.  Most 
people  are  content  nowadays,  when  they  set  about  explaining 
the  nature  of  things,  to  assume  that  there  is  something  to  be 
explained  ;  and  if  that  were  all,  Spinoza's  proof  that  the 
universe  exists  might  be  left  aside  as  an  historical  curiosity. 
But  there  is  more  than  one  reason  for  dwelling  on  it.  Spinoza 
follows  in  form,  and  even  in  language,  the  examples  made 
familiar  by  theologians,  and  philosophers  under  theological 
influence  or  pressure,  who  had  undertaken  to  prove  the  exist- 
ence of  a  being  apart  from  and  above  the  universe.  He  does 
not  simply  break  off  from  theological  speculation  and  seek  to 
establish  philosophy  on  an  independent  footing  ;  he  seems 
intent  on  showing  that  theological    speculation    itself,  when 

'  The  doctrine  of  the  Infinite  Modes  is  given  in  Eth.  i.  21-23,  but  in  such 
general  language  that  it  would  be  unintelligible  without  the  parallel  passages  in 
Ep.  66  and  elsewhere.      See  ]\  108,  152  .^hnve. 


i66  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

reason  is  once  allowed  free  play,  must  at  last  purge  itself  of 
anthropomorphism  and  come  round  to  the  scientific  view. 
Spinoza  does  not  ignore  theology,  but  provides  an  euthanasia 
for  it;  and  there  is  every  reason  to  believe  that  in  so  doing 
he  faithfully  reproduces  the  development  of  his  system  in  his 
own  mind.  Hence  his  work  has  a  peculiar  fascination  for 
liberal-minded  theologians,  and  from  the  very  first  has  excited 
the  violent  abhorrence  of  the  more  orthodox  ones.  There 
were  similar  grounds,  as  was  remarked  in  our  first  chapter, 
for  the  exceeding  bitterness  of  the  opposition  encountered  by 
the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.' 

If  Spinoza  swallows  up  speculative  theology  in  philosophy, 
he  is  equally  determined  not  to  confine  the  range  of  philoso- 
phical construction  within  the  bounds  of  human  experience. 
Rejecting  the  theological  conception  of  the  universe  as  created 
and  governed  by  a  magnified  human  despot,  which  indirectly 
makes  man  the  measure  of  all  things,  Spinoza  w^as  not  more 
willing    to   accept    the    contrary  form   of  anthropomorphism 
which  admits  no  reality  of  things  outside  what  is  known  to 
ourselves.     And  he  was  determined  withal  not  to  give  up  the 
substance  and  reality  of  the  knowledge  we  have  in  the  search 
for  some   other  imagined  reality  which   might   peradventure 
turn    out    a  shadow.     Thus   encompassed    with   dangers,  he 
escaped  from  them  by  a  flight  of  speculation  as  daring  and 
splendid  as  any  that  human  intellect  has  achieved.     The  God 
of  Spinoza  is  not  merely  Substance,  but  '  Substance  consisting 
I  of  infinite  attributes.'     The  infinity  of  attributes  is  deduced 
I  from  the  perfection  and  reality  of  Substance.     Perfection  and 
1  reality  are  with  Spinoza  synonymous  terms.'     Whatever  exists 
.  I  must  exist  as  much  as  it  can  ;  and  that  whose  nature  is  to 
I  exist,  or  which  exists  of  itself,  is  under  no  possible  restraint 
leither  internal  or  external  which  could  set  bounds  to  its  exist- 
lence.     Therefore  it  will  exist  with  infinite  reality,  in   every 
possible  way,  and  we  must  ascribe  to  it    infinite  attributes. 
\  '  ElJi.  2,  def.  6. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  1^7 

The  existent  universe,  though  not  the  world  accessible  to  a 
particular  order  of  finite  minds,  must  include  every  possible 
consequence  of  infinite  being,  and  there  is  no  real  distinction 
between  the  actual  and  the  possible. 

Let  us  endeavour  to  put  this  in  a  shape  more  congenial 
to  modern    habits  of  thought.     \Vp  Vnnw  fhp  v,jnr\r\  under 

f[]p    Afl-ri'hiif-pc    f^r    pqpprts    t^i'   pytprK^inn    anrl  thnnglit,  and  in 

each  kind  the  sum  of  reality  appears  to  be  inexhaustible. 
Our  world  consists  of  modes  of  extension  associated  with 
modes  of  thought :  the  two  orders  of  events  being,  as  Spinoza 
sets  forth  later,  strictly  correlated  and  parallel.  But  we  have 
no  right  to  assume  that  this  is  the  only  world :  for  this  would 
be^to  setltQuiids  to  infinite  being.  How  can  we  tell  what 
other  ac;j2Pri;^  pyi-^tprire  may  pot  have  to  intelligence  other 
thari_ours  .^  We  can  conceive,  though  not  imagine,  relations 
of  thought  to  other  worlds  analogous  to  those  which  we  per- 
ceive between  thought  and  extension.  For_aU  we  ran  ever 
kn^MjMjig^fljTTfij^p  pndlpt^s  asperfc;  of  pyi'stence  unimaginabjfi 
to  us.  That  :a:.lw?h-4o-thc  modeyH-4hhiker,appears  as  a  specy- 
lative^posMbility^Jbrbidding  us  to  affirm^  thaL^himmnJkxio^- 
ledge^is.everytlamg,  appeared^to  Spinozaas, a  positiyejiecessit^^ 
and  jie  ^aifirmed-  the_infi-nity^f  Attri^ute^- as  requir€4-by-t]ie 
perfection  of  Substance.  //  Things-jnust^xistujot  only  after  the 
manner_in_jyhir,h  they  are- jnanife.sted  to  us.  but  in._,eYery 
m ajiner  which  infinite  understanding  can  conceive.  Yet  that 
uJTJch  v^e-do-perreive  is  not  a  part  or  fraction  of  the  realit^^  ; 
forjthe^ttribules  unknown  to  us  express,  as  Spinoza  says,  in 
infinitp  ways  the  very  same  r£ality-£)£-tliings_MJlich  we  kno\v, 
or_niay  .conceivably  know,  mider  the  Attribiiiies  of  Thought 
and^Extension.  In  each  Attribute  the  same  order  and 
«;pqnpnrg_J3_]:pppafprl  in  the— aspgct  ^onexpression  proper  to 

that  A^rjbute^__DifferingjnJd^ 

and^parallel^  in  form.  A  geometrical  illustration  may  help 
us  to  understand  Spinoza's  conception.  Let  anyioiie  of  the 
At*^"ibutes  be  likened  to  an  infinite  plane,  and  lej  figures  be 


1 68  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

d mwn  all  over  fli(^  plane.  The  figures  mav-tliea-stami  for  the 
Modes,  or  pprfrmlar  l-hing^,  rnmpng;pr1    nnrjpr   that   Attribute: 

and.--ih€-4\diole  plane  itself,  considered  as  a -.figured  surface, 
will  represent  an  infinite  Mode.  Now  let  us  suppose  an  in^ 
finite  number  of  other  planes  to  be  taken,  and  figures  to  be 
drawn  on  them  similar  and  similarly  situated  to  those  dra\vn 
upon  the  first.  Further,  we  suppose  the  figures  to  vary  con- 
tinuously,  and  the  variations  to  be  similar  and  correspondent 
in  all  the  planes,  so  that  at  all  times  the  configuratioa-of, all  the 
planes  is  identical.  Tntelligent  beings  living:_Dn_one  .of  these 
planes^and  confined  to.J:wo- dimensions  could  have  no  imagina^ 
tion  of  any_surface  outside  their  plane^  which  however  is  to 
observers  furnished  with  normal  organs  of  sense  in  three  di- 
mensions_only  one  plane  arbitrarily  selected  out  of  an  infinite 
number  as^  the  '  plane  of  JJie_pape.r.'  Yet  suchbeings  rnight 
conceiv£^_tliQjjgh-lh£y  could  not-imagine,  the  configuratioiis^of 

vuhirh  thpy_Jiad-gJs:pp-rienrf^-ai;-J:ieing-i:eppa fprl  on  JrifinJl^J^ibr^ 

plan£sJn_aixe5siM£jjO-tbeir-4acuLties.  This  is  the  sort  of  cor- 
respondence- assumed-by^Spinoza  to  hold  good  between  all 
thfi_Attribut€S,  But  the  illustration  is  imperfect  in  this,  that 
there  is  no  reason  in  the  nature  of  the  supposed  case  why  the 
figures  on  dift'erent  planes  should  not  be  dissimilar:  whereas 
in  Spinoza's  view  of  the  universe  the  corresponding  modes  in 
different  attributes  are  not  different  things  at  all,  but  the  same 
thing  '  differently  expressed.'  Thus  there  is  no  room  for  diver- 
gence ;  there  are  not  infinite  and  similar  orders  of  things 
running  parallel  to  one  another,  but  one  order  in  infinite  ma- 
nifestations. The  order  itself  is  the  same  in  every  aspect, 
somewhat  as  in  the  symbolical  operations  of  mathematics  the 
development  of  a  function  remains  constant  in  form,  whatever 
values  we  may  give  to  the  variables. 

The  parallelism  of  the  Attributes  includes  as  a  particular 
case  the  exact  correspondence  of  body  and  mind,  to  which 
the  Cartesian  school  was  already  committed,  though  its 
founder  tried  to  effect  a  compromise  with  prevailing   notions 


THE  NATURE   OF   THINGS.  169 

by  means  of  the  doctrine  of  animal  spirits  :  a  doctrine  which, 
as  we  have  seen,  was  followed  by  Spinoza  himself  in  his  earlier 
essay  '  Of  God  and  Man.'  By  the  time  he  wrote  the  '  Ethics ' 
he  was  convinced  that  such  a  compromise  was  untenable  ;  and 
there  can  be  little  doubt  that  his  final  and  complete  accept- 
ance of  the  correlation  of  mind  and  body  rested  on  grounds 
which  we  should  now  call  scientific,  the  same  in  fact  on 
which  the  most  eminent  of  recent  and  living  psychologists 
have  come  to  the  same  conclusion.  Hence,  while  the  infinity 
of  the  Attributes  was  determined  by  a  supposed  necessity 
of  speculation,  the  parallelism  which  constitutes  the  original 
and  peculiar  feature  of  this  part  of  Spinoza's  system  appears 
to  be  an  extension  of  the  parallelism  already  fixed  in  Spinoza's 
view  of  the  world  of  human  experience  as  a  necessity  of 
scientific  thought.  It  is  to  be  observed  that  without  this 
feature  the  Infinite  Attributes  would  be  a  mere  formless  vision 
of  unseen  worlds,  such  as  have  abounded  both  before  and 
since  the  time  of  Spinoza.  So  that  even  when  Spinoza  goes 
farthest  in  overleaping  the  bounds  of  experience,  it  is  still 
the  scientific  element  that  gives  consistence  and  definition  to 
his  work. 

We  may  now  see  that  although  nothing  outside  Extension 
and  Thought  can  affect  human  knowledge  or  impeach  its 
reality,  the  Infinite  Attributes  arc  not  merely  ornamental. 
Spinoza's  purpose  is  to  keep  a  clear  course  between 
materialism  on  the  one  hand  and  subjective  idealism  on  the 
other.  He  makes  extension  and  thought  equally  real,  and 
co-ordinate  not  only  with  one  another  but  with  infinite 
other  aspects  of  existence.  Thus  the  system  is  obviously  not 
materialism.'  It  is  no  less  remote  from  the  subjective 
idealism  which    turns  the   universe    into  a  phantom.     It   is 

'  Except  in  the  nomenclature  of  certain  modern  writers,  who  signify  by 
viatcrialist  (as  appears  by  their  usage,  though  they  do  not  give  themselves  the 
pains  so  to  define  it)  any  one  who  does  not  admit  some  dogma,  generally  that  of 
free-will,  affirmed  by  the  particular  writer  to  be  essential  to  religion  and  morality. 


170  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

proof  even  against  the  objections  to  which  Berkeley's  idealism 
is  exposed.  Professor  Huxley,  in  his  essay  on  Berkeley,  sup- 
poses a  piano  to  be  conscious  of  sound  and  of  nothing  else. 
*  It  would  become  acquainted  with  a  system  of  nature  entirely 
composed  of  sounds,  and  the  laws  of  nature  would  be  the 

laws  of  melody  and  of  harmony  ; '  and,  having  no  conception 

VV/ 


rv^ 


of  any  other  sort  of  existence,  it  might  reason  thus  :  '  All  my  '  ^-, 
knowledge  consists  of  sounds  and  the  perception  of  the 
relation  of  sounds  ;  now  the  being  of  sound  is  to  be  heard  ; 
and  it  is  inconceivable  that  the  existence  of  the  sounds  I 
know  should  depend  upon  any  other  existence  than  that  of 
the  mind  of  a  hearing  being.'  But  we  know  that  the  exist- 
ence of  these  sounds  requires,  besides  the  mind  of  a  hearing 
beinsT,  the  structure  of  wood  and  metal  which  makes  the 
visible  and  tangible  piano,  and  a  musician  to  play  upon  it.' 
So  that  the  Berkeleian  piano  would  be  mistaken,  though  by 
the  hypothesis  it  could  never  have  proof  of  its  error.  Now 
let  us  vary  the  supposition  and  make  it  reason  after  Spinoza's 
manner.  It  would  then  say  something  of  this  kind  :  Existenee 
is  manifest  to  me  in  Thought  and  Sound  :  these  are  the  At- 
tributes  under  which  I  perceive  the  reality  of  things,  and  each 
is  infinite  and  perfectly  real  in  its  own  kind.  But  I  may  not 
assume  that  these  are  the  only  possible  aspects  of  existence, 
though  they  are  the  only  ones  that  fall  within  my  apprehen- 
sion. The  fulness  of  things  must  be  infinite  in  infinite  kinds, 
and  must  be  expressed  in  infinite  ways  besides  these  two  of 
Thought  and  Sound,  '  The  auditory  consciousness  of  our 
speculative  piano  '  would  thus  vindicate  the  reality  of  its  per- 
ceptions as  far  as  they  went,  or  the  identity  of  ^j-j-^  2lX\^  percipi 
within  the  supposed  limits  of  its  faculties,  and  yet  its  specu- 
lation would  leave  ample  room  for  the  existence  of  the 
material  piano,  the  musician,  and  the  world  in  general. 
Substitute  Extension  for  Sound  in  Professor  Huxley's  parable 

'   Critiques  and  Addresses,  \i.  },\^. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  171 

as  thus  varied,  and  we  have  Spinoza's  view  of  the  relation  of 
human  knowledge  to  the  totality  of  existence. 

The  first  remark  on  Spinoza's  hypothesis  that  occurs  to  a 
modern  reader,  being  probably  the  last  that  would  have 
occurred  to  any  of  his  contemporaries,  is  that  by  the  nature 
of  the  case  it  is  incapable  of  verification.  But  perhaps  that 
objection  is  not  conclusive  ;  for  it  is  at  least  open  to  grave 
doubt  whether  any  metaphysical  h}'pothesis  can  be  brought 
to  this  test,  or  can  have,  to  use  the  Kantian  phrase,  any 
other  than  a  regulative  value.  Leaving  this  point  aside,  we 
have  to  see  whether  Spinoza's  theory  is  consistent  in  itself, 
and  gives  a  consistent  interpretation  of  our  actual  experience. 
And,  notwithstanding  its  apparent  symmetry,  closer  inspec- 
tion shows  that  the  difficulties  are  insuperable.  Spinoza 
found  himself,  indeed,  unable  to  resolve  the  doubts  pro- 
pounded by  Tschirnhausen,  whose  letters  will  compare  very 
favourably  with  most  of  the  modern  criticism  on  the  '  Ethics.' 
Man  is,  as  we  know  by  all  our  experience,  an  extended  and  , 
thinking  being,  and  nothing  else.  But,  according  to  Spinoza, 
the  reality  of  everything  is  expressed  in  infinite  ways.  Mind 
and  body  are  only  two  expressions  or  aspects  out  of  an  in- 
finite number:  how  then  do  these  two  come  to  be  exclusively 
associated  1  Why  are  the  other  Attributes  unknown  to  us  } 
And  are  we  to  suppose  those  Attributes  to  constitute  other 
worlds  [jerceived  by  finite  creatures  .who  have  no  notion  of 
Extension  } '  Such  is  the  effect  of  Tschirnhausen's  first  set 
of  questions.  The  answer  he  received  -  failed  to  satisfy  him  ; 
and  in  truth  it  is  not  only  obscure,  but  seems  to  evade  the 
main  difficulty.  Spinoza  says  that  the  human  mind  knows  / 
only  thought  and  extension,  because  it  is  nothing  else  than  a 
mode  of  thought  associated  with  a  particular  body  or  mode 
of  extension  (idea  corporis  actu  existentis).  But  the  difficulty 
is  just  to  see  how  this  dual  association  is  to  be  reconciled  with 

>  Ep.  65,  -  i:p.  66. 


172  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

the  symmetrical  co-ordination  of  all  the  Attributes.     Tschirn- 
hausen  returned,  courteously  but  stoutly,  to  the  attack. 

'  I  well  perceive,'  he  says,  '  that  in  your  system  the  universe  is 
one,  and  not  many ;  but  it  is  no  less  clear  from  the  very  passage 
to  which  you  refer  me '  that  it  is  expressed  in  infinite  ways,  and  there- 
fore that  the  being  of  every  single  thing  is  so  expressed. 

'Whence  it  seems  to  follow  that  though  the  modification  con- 
stituting my  mind  and  the  modification  constituting  my  body  be  one 
and  the  same,  yet  that  modification  is  expressed  in  infinite  ways  ;  once 
under  thought,  again  under  extension,  thirdly  under  an  attribute  of 
God  to  me  unknown,  and  so  on  to  infinity  ;  for  the  attributes  of  God 
are  infinite,  and  the  order  and  connexion  of  the  modifications  is,  as 
I  understand,  the  same  in  all.  Hence  arises  this  question  :  why  the 
mind— which  embodies  (repraesentat)  a  certain  modification,  which 
modification  is  expressed,  not  only  in  extension,  but  in  infinite  other 
ways — why,  I  say,  the  mind  perceives  that  modification  only  as  ex- 
pressed in  extension,  (that  is,  the  human  body)  and  no  other  expression 
of  it  under  other  attributes  ? '  ^ 

Spinoza's  reply,  apparently  only  a  part  of  the  letter  in 
which  it  was  given,  is  so  brief  that  it  may  be  translated  in 
full. 

'In  answer  to  your  objection  I  say  that,  although  every  particular 
thing  is  expressed  in  infinite  ways  in  the  infinite  understanding  of 
God,  yet  those  infinite  ideas  whereby  it  is  expressed  cannot  constitute 
one  and  the  same  mind  of  a  particular  thing,  but  constitute  infinite 
minds ;  inasmuch  as  these  infinite  ideas  have  severally  no  connexion 
among  themselves,  as  I  have  explained  in  the  aforesaid  scholium  to 
Prop.  7,  Part  2  of  the  Ethics,  and  appears  from  Prop.  10,  Part  i.  If 
you  will  sufficiently  apply  yourself  to  these,  you  will  see  that  no 
difficulty  remains.'  ^ 

Spinoza  seems  to  say  that  every  Mode  of  every  Attribute 
other  than  Thought  has  a  several  mind  or  modification  of 
thought  to  itself.  Even  the  iniellectus  absolute  infitiittcs  appears 
to  be  manifold,  so  that  each  infinite  mode  of  thought  is  appro- 
priated to  one  Attribute  only,  and  they  are  infinite  in  number. 

'  Elh.  ii.  7,  schol.  2  Y.Y..  67.  ^  pp   ^g^ 


THE  NATURE  OF  THINGS. 

The  result  is  that  the  modes  of  Thought  are    numerically 
equal  to  the  modes  of  all  the  other  Attributes  together ;  in 
other   words,   Thought,    instead  of  being  co-equal  with  the 
infinity  of  other  Attributes,  is  infinitely  infinite,  and  has  a  pre- 
eminence which  is  nowhere  explicitly  accorded  to  it.^     But  if 
we  go  back  to  the  definition  we  find  that  this  pre-eminence 
has  all  the  while  been  implied.     For  Attribute  is  '  tJiat  which 
uiidcrstajiding  perceives  concerning  substajice  as  constituting 
the  essence  thereof.'     Thus  the  ground  is  cut  from  under  the      ■ 
apparent  equality  of  the  Attributes  ;  and,  though  the  system     ; 
escapes  the  snares  of  subjective  idealism,  it  does  not  escape     ' ' 
idealism    altogether.     In  order   to   judge  Spinoza's  attempt      ,..  ■  i^ 
rightly,  we  must  face  the  question  whether  such  an  escape       :■) 
was  possible  at  all.     If,  as  I  think,  his  failure  was  due  not  to 
any  want    of  philosophical   power   or  ingenuity,  but  to  the 
nature  of  the  problem  itself,  it  will  be  no  mere  exercise  of 
historical  curiosity  to  undertake  a  narrower  scrutiny  of  his 
conception.     Before  we  do  this,  one  or  two  other  difficulties 
may  be  mentioned.     In  a  continuation  of  the  correspondence 
already  referred  to,  Tschirnhausen  calls   on  Spinoza  to  show  ' 
how  the  existence  and  variety  of  extended  things  is  to  be  : 
deduced  a  priori  from  the  Attribute  of  extension.     It  is  not  < 
very  clear  whether  Spinoza  thought  himself  bound  to  meet 
such  a  challenge  or  not  ;  at  all  events  he  was  not  ready  with 
an  answer.^     If  we  regard  his  metaphysic  as  an  ajttempt  not 
only  to  interpret  Jbuman   experience  as  it  is,  but  to  demon- 
strate that  it  must  be  what  it  is,  Tschirnhausen's  question 
was,  as  Tre^iidelenburg^^says,  a  shot  into  the  Avhjte.     But  it 
loses  all  significance  if  we  treat  the  system  as  in  truth  rest- 
ing on  a  foundation  of  empirical  facts,  and  professing  not  to 
construct  the  world  a  priori,  but  only  to  make  the  world  in- 
telligible.    And  this  we  are  entitled   to  do  for  our  present 

'  Cf.   Erdmann,    Grundriss  der  Gcsch.   dcr  Dnlosophie,  §  272,  5,  6  (vol.    ii. 

PP-  55-61)- 

2  Epp.  71,  72. 


174  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

purposes,  though  Spinoza  himself  might  not  have  been  con- 
tent to  accept  such  a  limitation  of  his  aims.  There  are  still, 
however,  other  stumbling-blocks.  It  is  part  of  Sjginoza's  theory 
that  everything  possible  must  actually  exist:'  and  the  objec- 
tion  that  it  ought  all  to  exist  at  once,  or  else  it  must  be 
sKown  why  one  tfiing  should  exist  before  another,  is  not  ade- 
quately  met  by  saying  that  duration  in  time  is  only  a  relative 
conception  in  fiiiite  minds.  The  same  principle  has  yet 
another  strange  consequence.  Spinoza  had,  of  course,  'no 
suspicion  that  the  properties  of  Extension  could  be  conceiv- 
ably different  from  those  assumed  in  ordinary  geometry,  and 
verified  in  all  our  experience  as  far  as  verification  has  gone. 
But  modern  geometers  have  shown  that  such  differences  are 
perfectly  conceivable,  and  that  an  indefinite  number  of  con- 
sistent geometrical  systems  may  be  framed  with  axioms 
contradicting  in  various  ways  those  of  Euclid  :  and  this  in 
the  range  of  three  dimensions,  without  any  reference  to  the 
more  knotty  question  whether  space  of  more  than  three 
dimensions  is  conceivable  or  not.  So  that  a  thoroughgoing 
Spinozist,  could  such  an  one  be  found  at  the  present  day, 
would  have  to  believe  that  all  conceivable  geometries  are 
realized  in  as  many  worlds  of  extension  in  three  dimensions, 
presumably  with  varied  dynamical  laws  to  match  ;  and  if  he 
believed  space  of  more  than  three  dimensions  to  be  conceiv- 
able, he  would  also  have  to  believe  in  infinite  worlds  of  in- 
finite dimensions  as  actually  existing.  Besides  all  this,  he 
would  have  to  suppose  corresponding  modifications  running 
through  the  infinite  parallel  series  of  all  the  other  Attributes. 
One  may  doubt  if  even  the  boldest  metaphysician  of  modern 
times,  or  the  thinker  most  eager  to  find  room  for  the  free 
play  of  a  constructive  philosophy  untrammelled  by  the  con- 
ditions of  experience,  would  care  to  take  upon  himself  such  a 
burden  of  unseen  worlds  as  this. 

^    Let  us  now  turn  to  the  main  point  of  Spinoza's  implicit 

'  Etk.  i.  i6. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  175 

idealism.     What  is  the  conclusion  to  which  it  really  points? 
What  would  Spinoza  have  done  if  he  had  not  been  uncon- 
sciously hampered  by  a  remnant  of  Cartesian  dualism?     We<^ 
have  to  observe  that  each  Attribute  is  complete  in  itself :  the ' 
possibility  of  niutualinterference  is  rig;orouslv  excluded.    The 
perception  of  things  as  extended  is  not  a  relation  between 
the  extended  thing  and  the  perceiving  mind,  for  they  are  in- 
commensurable.    Every  extended  thing  has  its  correlate  in 
Thought,  whether  that  correlate  is  part  of  a  conscious  mind 
or  not ;  arid  when    it   is  a  perception  in  a  conscious  mind, 
the  perception  is  a  mode  of  Thought  and  nothing  else.     And  "' 
the  thing  correlated  to  the  perception  is  not  the  object  per-, 
ceived,    but  the   organism   of  the    perceiving   subject.     The 
series  of  ideas  or  modes  of  Thought  is  whole  and  continu- 
ous  ;  no  other.  Attribute  has  any  part  in  it.     How  then  can 
we  say  that  Thought  perceives  Extension  .''  or  what  ground 
have  we    for   making    Extension  co-ordinate  with  Thought, 
and    in    some   way,    which    nevertheless    is    not    causation, 
necessary  to  its  manifestations  .-'     Putting  out  of  sight   the 
supposed  a  priori  necessity  for  an  infinity  of  Attributes,  let 
us  assume  Extension  and  all  its  modes  to  be  blotted  out  of 
existence.     Thought  and  its  modes  will  by  the  hypothesis 
remain  unaffected ;  every  mental  correlate  of  a  material  fact 
will  be  precisely  what  it  was  before  ;  the  psychical  order  of 
things,  ordo  et  connexio  idearum,  will  be  unaltered.     In  other 
words,  there  will  be  no  effect  on  the  perceptions  which  take 
place  in  any  mind,  and  though  Extension  be  annihilated  as 
an  independent  Attribute,    no    thinking   being   will   miss  it. 
The  diff"erence  would  be  sensible  only  to  an  infinite  intelli- 
gence placed  as  a  spectator  outside  the  universe  and  all  its 
Attributes  ;    but    such    an    intelligence  we  are   forbidden  to 
suppose,  for  the  universe  can  have  nothing  outside  it.     The 
same  reasoning  applies  to  all  the  other  unknown  Attributes. 
Hence ^^  the  Attributes  except  Thought  are  really  super- 
fluous :    and    Spinoza's  doctrine,  when    thus  reduced   to   its 


n 


\ 


176  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

/it 
rJj^   \    simplest  terms,  is  that  nothing  exists  but   thought  and  its 

^  -^  '     modifications.     Feeling,  or   something    commensurable  with 

Feeling,  is  the  only  unit  and  measure  of  reality.  The  ulti- 
mate elements  of  thought  are  not  merely  correlated  with  the 
ultimate  elements  of  things  ;  they  are  the  elements  of  things 
themselves.  For,  when  the  principle  of  continuity  is  once 
admitted,  there  is  no  need  to  assume  any  other.  And  this 
view,  strange  as  it  may  seem  at  first  sight,  may  be  arrived  at  by 
divers  ways.  It  may  be  reached  even  through  the  notion  of  a 
thing-in-itself  or  substratum  of  phenomena;  and  Kant  was  on 
the  very  point  of  thus  reaching  it,  but  left  it  aside.  Accept-  ^ 
ing  the  alleged  necessity  for  a  substratum,  noumenon,  or 
whatever  else  it  may  be  called,  to  support  our  phenomenal 
experience,  we  must  admit  that  of  the  nature  of  this  substra- 
tum, as  it  is  in  itself,  we  know  nothing  whatever.  Therefore 
the  substratum  may  as  well  be  of  the  nature  of  mind  as  any- 
thing else.  But  mind  is  the  one  sort  of  real  existence  of 
which  we  have  direct  experience ;  it  is  that  which  is  known 
in  conscious  feeling.  And,  seeing  that  a  known  kind  of 
existence  will  satisfy  the  conditions  required  of  the  suDstra- 
tum,  we  have  no  occasion  to  postulate  other  unknown  kinds. 
Indeed,  the  law  of  economy  forbids  us  thus  to  multiply 
entities  without  need.  Kant's  authority,  no  doubt,  is  against  . 
this  last  conclusion  ;  for  he  deliberately  refused  to  proceed  to  it.' 
His  reasons,  however,  were  not  strictly  scientific,  as  they  are 
inseparable,  historically  if  not  formally,  from  his  determina- 
tion to  reserve  an  inaccessible  world  of  things-in-themselves 
as  a  field '  for  the  exercise,  assumed  to  be  indispensable,  of  a 
Practical  Reason  whose  demands  could  not  be  satisfied  in  the 
region  of  real  knowledge.  But  Kant's  own  language  on  the 
subject  is  too  important  to  be  omitted  :  I  give  it  accordingly 
in  a  free  translation  : —  * 

'  It  has  been  proved  that  bodies  are  only  phenomena  of  our  out- 
'  Or  might  one  izy  playground ?     Spielraum,  at  any  rate,  is  an  innocent  term. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  177 

ward  sense,  not  things  in  themselves.  Accordingly  we  may  affirm 
that  our  thinking  self  is  not  bodily  in  this  sense,  that,  being  conceived 
as  an  object  of  the  inner  sense,  it  cannot,  so  far  as  it  is  a  thinking 
thing,  be  an  object  of  outward  sense  or  a  phenomenon  in  space.  In 
other  words,  thinking  things  as  such  can  never  occur  among  outward 
phenomena  ;  we  can  have  no  outward  perception  of  their  thoughts, 
consciousness,  desires,  &c.  ;  for  all  this  is  the  domain  of  the  inward 

sense 

'  But  though  extension,  impenetrability,  cohesion  and  motion,  in 
short  everything  we  obtain  exclusively  through  the  outward  sense, 
cannot  be  or  contain  thought,  feeling  or  the  like,  which  in  no  case  can 
be  objects  of  outward  perception;  yet  the  i-<?w^//««^  which  underlies 
the  outward  phenomena,  and  so  affects  our  sense  as  to  furnish  it  with 
the  notions  of  space,  matter,  form,  &c. — this  something,  I  say,  con- 
sidered as  noumenon,  might  well  be  the  subject  of  thoughts,  though 
we  obtain  from  it  through  the  outward  sense  no  perception  of  ideas, 
wll  or  the  like,  but  only  of  space  and  its  modifications.  This  some- 
thing, whatever  it  be,  has  in  itself  none  of  the  qualities  of  matter,  such 
as  extension,  impenetrability  and  the  like;  for  statements  about  these 
qualities  are  statements  about  our  perceptions.  But  the  qualities 
proper  to  the  inner  sense,  namely,  ideas  and  thought,  may  be  ascribed 
to  it  without  contradiction.  .  .  .  Matter  is  complex  as  a  phenomenon, 
but  only  as  a  phenomenon  :  and  I  am  free  to  assume  that  it  is  in 
itself  simple,  and  that  the  substance  which  to  our  outward  sense  is 
extended  is  in  itself  accompanied  by  thoughts  capable  of  being  re- 
presented in  consciousness  by  an  inward  sense  of  its  own.  In  this 
way  the  same  thing  that  in  one  aspect  is  called  bodily  would  in 
another  be  a  thinking  being,  of  which  we  could  not  perceive  the 
thought,  but  could  perceive  the  signs  of  it  in  the  phenomenon.  Then 
we  should  no  longer  say  that  only  souls  think,  assuming  soul  to  be  a 
special  kind  of  Substance  ;  we  should  say,  with  common  speech,  that 
men  think,  in  other  words  that  the  same  thing  ivhich  as  an  out^vard 
phenomenon  is  extended  is  inwardly  or  in  itself  a  Subject,  which  is  not 
composite,  but  which  is  simple  and  thinTcs.' ' 

Kant,  however,  threw  out  this  hypothesis  only  for  a  special 
purpose,  and  did  not  pursue  it.  The  closeness  of  the  approach 
to  Spinoza,  of  which  Kant  was  probably  not  aware,  is  most 
striking  ;  and   the  suggestion  differs  only  in  one  point  from 

'  Kritikderr.  V.  ist  ed.  Kr.des  zweiten  Paralogismus  deriranssc.  Psychologie, 
pp.  287-8,  Rosenkr.,  304-6,  Kehrbach  (in  Univfrml-Bibliothek). 

N 


178 


SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE   AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


^V^ 

'S 


the  result  which  follows,  as  above  pointed  out,  from  develop- 
ing the  implicit  idealism  of  Spinoza's  theory  of  the  Attributes. 
The  difference  is   that  Kant  assumes  the  ideal  or  psychical 
thing-in-itself,  or  rather  substitute  for  the  thing-in-itself,  to  be 
a  simple  subject  or  monad.     In  Spinoza's  system,  on  the  other 
hand,  as  well  as  in  the  simplified  form  of  it  here  proposed,  the 
ultimate  fact  is  not  only  represented,  but  adequately  repre- 
sented, by  the  phenomenon.     The   inward  fact,  or  mode  of  c 
■thought,  corresponds  point  for  point  with  the  outward  fact,  or 
mode  of  extension,  and  is  complex  in  the  same  proportion.    We 
must  remember,  however,  that  the  inner  and  the  outer  world 
are  not  really  different  and  parallel,  but  one  and  the  same  world 
under  two  aspects.     This,  indeed,  is  expressly  and  repeatedly 
stated  by  Spinoza.     The  process  of  criticism   we  have  just 
gone  through,  supposing  it  to  be  legitimate,  does  not  affect 
the  substantial  and  working  value  of  Spinoza's  metaphysic. 
The  effect  is  only  to  strip  it  of  brilliant  but  dangerous  orna-o 
ments,  and  lay  open  the  speculative  ground  on  which  it  really 
stands.     How  Spinoza  uses  his  metaphysical  conception  as  a 
groundwork  for  psychology,  and  with  what  success,  we  shall 
see  in  due  time. 

Jacobi,  who  only  half  understood  Spinoza,  made  the  ex- 
traordinary statement  that  no  man  may  profess  to  understand 
him  so  long  as  he  finds  a  single  line  of  the  '  Ethics '  obscure. 
The  saying  is  one  of  those  which  produce  a  cheap  effect  by 
reckless  disregard  of  the  real  difficulties.  Lessing  and  Goethe 
knew  better.  And  as  to  more  recent  philosophers  and  critics,c 
it  is  hardly  too  much  to  say  that  no  two  of  them  have  under- 
stood the  metaphysical  principles  of  the  '  Ethics '  in  precisely 
the  same  manner.  This  being  so,  I  am  far  from  claiming  or  ex- 
pecting general  acceptance  for  the  interpretation  above  given  ; 
I  am  content  if  I  have  made  it  intelligible.  On  the  other  hand 
the  bearing  of  Spinoza's  principles  in  their  application  to  human 
nature  is  clear  enough,  and  I  do  not  know  that  his  practical 
results  have  ever  been  found   obscure  except  by  those  who 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  179 

were  determined  not  to  understand,  though  opinions  differ  as 
widely  as  possible  as  to  their  correctness  and  value.     Whether 
the  criticism  of  the  purely  speculative  part  be  found  interest- 
ing depends  on  one's  belief  or  taste  as  to  metaphysics  in 
general.     The  reader  who  thinks  metaphysics  an  impossibility 
or  a  useless  luxury  will  probably  have  quitted  me  several 
pages  back.     For  those  who  remain  it  may  be  worth  while  to 
sum  up  the  criticism  in  a  more  technical  form  than  I  have  yet 
allowed  myself     Spinoza's  Attributes  are  in  effect  defined  as     I 
objects,  or  rather  as  objective  worlds.     But  the  general  form 
of  the  definition  disguises  the  all-important  fact  that  the  world 
of  Thought,  and  that  alone,  is  subjective  and  objective  at  once. 
The  intellect  which  perceives  an  Attribute  as  '  constituting   \ 
the  essence  of  Substance,'  itself  belongs  to  the  Attribute  of 
Thought     Thus,  if  we  push  analysis    further,  we  find    that 
Thought  swallows  up  all  the  other  Attributes  ;  for  all  conceiv- 
able Attributes  turn  out  to  be  objective  aspects  of  Thought 
itself     Spinoza  does  indeed  return,  but  too  late,  to  the  double 
aspect  of  Thought : '  and  the  formal  part  of  his  system  re- 
mains a  magnificent  attempt  at  an   impossible  symmetry  of 
the  universe,  in  which  thought  vainly  struggles  to  escape  from 
its  own  fundamental  conditions,  and  to  conquer  new  worlds  _ 
beyond  the  inexorable  boundaries  of  experience.  ^^ 

It  has  been  seen  how  great  a  part  is  played  hy  infinity  in 
the  system ;  we  have  Attributes,  infinite  in  number  and  in  their 
several  kinds,  infinite  Modes,  and  the  like.  It  is  evidently 
material  to  know  what  precise  meaning  was  attached  by 
Spinoza  to  the  term.  The  explanation  is  partly  given  in  the 
'  Ethics  : '  but  we  have  to  look  chiefly  to  the  letter  to  Dr. 
Meyer  where,  in  answer  to  his  friend's  inquiries,  Spinoza  dis- 
cusses the  problem.  He  incidentally  sets  forth  his  view  of 
other  metaphysical  conceptions  which,  though  secondary  and 
auxiliary,  are  of  great  importance.  After  a  complimentary 
introduction  Spinoza  proceeds  thus  (Ep.  29) ; — 

•  Eth.  ii.  20,  21,  43. 
N  2 


:ph>^ 


l8o  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

*  The  question  of  the  infinite  has  always  been  considered  very 

:   difficult,  nay  inexplicable,  by  those  who  have  handled  it,  because 

,;   they  have  not  distinguished  between  that  which  is  concluded  to  be 

\    infinite  by  its  own  nature,  that  is,  by  virtue  of  its  definition,  and  that 

^    which  is  without  limits  by  virtue  not  of  its  essence  but  of  its  cause  " 

I   (in  modern  language,  between  that  which  cannot  be  conceived  as 

finite,  and  that  which  as  a  matter  of  fact  is  indefinite  in  quantity)  ; 

'  again  they  have  not  distinguished  between  a  thing  called  infinite 

from  having  no  limit,  and  a  thing  whose  parts  cannot  be  measured 

or  expressed  by  any  number,  though  a  greatest  and  a  least  magnitude 

of  the  thing  itself  can  be  assigned  ;  finally,  because  they  have  not 

distinguished  between  that  which  we  can   only  understand  but  not 

imagine,  and  that  which  we  can  as  well  imagine  as  understand.     Had 

i    they  attended,  I  say,  to  these  points,  they  would  never  have  beeti 

^    overwhelmed  by  such  a  crowd  of  difficulties.     For  then  they  would 

-,   have  clearly  understood  what  kind  of  infinite  quantity  is  not  capable 

I  of  having  or  being  divided  into  parts,  and  what  without  any  contradic- 

I  tion   is   so.     They   would  likewise    have  understood   what  kind  of 

\  infinite  may  without  any  repugnance  be  greater  than  another  infinite, 

\  and  what  kind  may  not  be  so  conceived,  as  will  plainly  appear  from 

%  what  I  shall  presently  say.' 

I  He  shortly  recapitulates  his  technical  use  of  the  terms 
substance,  mode,  eternity,  and  duration.  Duration,  he  says,  is 
a  term  applicable  only  to  the  existence  of  particular  things 
or  modes.  To  substance  belongs  eternity,  'that  is,  infinite 
faculty  (fruitionem)  of  existence  or  being.'  When  we  con- 
sider the  existence  and  duration  of  particular  things  with 
regard  to  those  things    only,   and   apart  from   the  order  of 

,  nature,  we  may  freely  conceive  it  as  bounded,  greater  or  less, 
and  divided  into  parts,  without  in  any  way  contradicting 
our  conception  of  the  thing.  But  eternity  and  substance 
cannot  be  conceived  as  limited  ;  therefore  if  we  seek  to  apply 
the  conceptions  of  limit  and  measure  to  them  the  principal 
conception  is  already  gone. 

'  Wherefore  they  talk  idly,  not  to  say  madly,  who  think  extended 
substance  to'be  made  up  of  parts  or  bodies  really  distinct  from  one 
another,  .  .  .  and  all  that  heap  of  arguments  with  which  philosophers 
commonly  go  about  to  show  that  extended  substance  is  finite  falls  to 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  ^S^)' 

pieces  of  itself.     In  the  same  case  are  others  who,  having  persuaded 
themselves  that  a  line  is  made  up  of  points,  have  succeeded  in  find-  \ 
ing  many  arguments  to  show  that  a  line  is  not  infinitely  divisible.'         1 

*  Now  if  you  ask  why  we  are  by  nature  so  prone  to  treat  extended 
substance  as  divisible,  I  answer,  because  quantity  is  conceived  by  us    | 
in  two  manners  :  to  wit,  by  abstraction  or  superficially,  as  it  is  present    \ 
to  us  in  imagination  through  the  senses,  or  in  its  quality  of  substance, 
which  can  be  done  only  by  the  understanding.     So  that  if  we  con- 
sider quantity  as  it  is  in  the  imagination  (which  is  the  common  and 
easy  way),  it  will  be  found  divisible,  finite,  made  up  of  parts,  and    | 
manifold.     But  if  we  consider  substance  as  it  is  in  the  understanding,     • 
and  the  thing  is  considered  as  it  is  in  itself  {i.e.  as  Substance  ;  for  only    i 
Substance  is  /«  itself) '  which  is  exceedingly  difiicult,  then,  as  I  have     \ 
at   former   times  sufficiently  shown  you,  it   will   be  found  infinite, 
indivisible,  and  single. 

'  Again,  from  the  fact  that  we  can  assign  bounds  to  duration  and 
quantity  at  our  pleasure  (that  is,  when  we  conceive    quantity  ab-        \ 
stractedly,  apart  from  Substance,  and  separate  duration  in  our  thought 
from  the  manner  of  its  derivation  from  eternal  things),  there  arise  time 
and  7neasure ;  time  being  conceived  in  order  to  determine  duration, <- 
measure  in  order    to   determine  quantity,   so   that   we    may    most 
conveniently  represent  them  in  imagination.     Then  from  the  fact  that  ^ 
we   separate  the  affections  of  substance  from  substance  itself  and 
reduce  them  to  classes  for  the  like  convenience  of  our  imagination, 
there  arises  number,  whereby  we  determine  the  same.     Whence  it  is  ^ 
plainly  to  be  seen  that  measure,  time,  and  number  are  nothing  else  J 
than  ways  of  thinking,  or  rather  of  imagining.^     Therefore  it  is  no 
wonder   that  all  who  have  attempted  to  understand  the  course  of 
nature  by  means  of  notions  of  this  kind,  and  those  too  ill  under- 
stood, have  so  marvellously  entangled  themselves  that  at  last  they 
could  find  no  escape  but  by  breaking  all  bounds  and  committing 
themselves  to  absurdities  beyond  measure.' 

Hence  the   attempt   to  explain    the  ideas  of  substance, 
eternity,  or  the  like,  which  belong  purely  to  the  understand- 

•  Cf.  Eth.  i.  15,  schol. 

*  Cf.  Cogit.  Met.  part  i.  c.  I,  §  4.  *  Ad  rem  deinde  explicandam  etiam  modos 
cogitandi  habemus,  determinando  scilicet  earn  per  comparationem  ad  aliam.  Modi 
cogitandi  quibus  id  efficimus  vocantur  tempus,  numerus,  tnensura,  et  si  quae 
adhuc  alia  sunt.  Horum  autem  tempus  inservit  durationi  explicandae,  numerus 
quantitati  discretae,  mensura  quantitati  continuae  :  '  and  part  ii.  c.  4. 


1 82  SPINOZA  :   HIS  IJFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY, 

ing,  by  means  of  conceptions  which  are  mere  'aids  of  the 
imagination/  is  necessarily  futile.  It  is  like  applying  the  in- 
tellectual tests  of  sanity  and  insanity  to  acts  of  pure  imagina- 
tion (nihilo  plus  agit  quam  si  det  operam  ut  sua  imaginatione 
insaniat).  Even  finite  things  cannot  be  rightly  understood  if 
we  confound  their  reality  with  these  'aids  of  the  imagination,' 
For  instance,  if  one  confounds  duration  with  measurable 
time,  and  goes  about  to  divide  it  into  parts,  it  is  impossible  to 
understand  the  lapse  of  time.  To  bring  an  hour  to  an  end, 
half  the  hour  must  first  pass,  then  half  of  the  residue,  then 
half  of  the  next  remainder,  and  so  on  without  end  : — 

'  Wherefore  many  who  are  not  used  to  distinguish  abstractions 
from  reality  have  made  bold  to  assert  that  duration  is  compounded 
of  instants,  and  so  have  fallen  into  Scylla  in  flying  from  Charybdis. 
For  it  is  all  one  to  compound  duration  out  of  instants  and  to  make 
number  by  adding  up  noughts.' 

We  have  here,  it  will  be  observed,  Spinoza's  answer  to  the 
standing  puzzles  as  to  the  impossibility  of  motion,  the  difficulty 
jt^\\  of  conceiving  matter  as  either  being  or  not  being  infinitely 
divisible,  the  contradictions  implied  in  assuming  time  to  have 
had  or  not  to  have  had  a  beginning,  and  other  catches  of  that 
sort.  They  are  for  the  most  part  as  old  as  philosophy  itself. 
Some  were  brought  into  new  prominence  by  Kant,  who  used 
them  with  extreme  ingenuity  to  set  an  impassable  barrier  to 
the  legitimate  operations  of  human  reason,  and  leave  a  world 
beyond  the  barrier,  not  accessible  to  reason  and  yet  not 
inaccessible  altogether.  In  our  own  time  an  elaborate  mis- 
understanding of  Kant  has  led  to  the  waste  of  great  powers 
on  the  invention  of  the  so-called  Philosophy  of  the  Con- 
ditioned, which,  having  barely  survived  its  inventor  and  first 
promoters,  may  be  dismissed  as  past  criticism. 

Spinoza's  meaning  is  clearly  expressed,  but  in  his  own 
peculiar  vocabulary,  and  it  seems  to  call  for  a  modern  inter- 
pretation.    The  nature  of  things   is  really  continuous  ;  the 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  183 

further  we  push  our  inquiries  the  more  we  are  compelled  so  to  \ 
regard  it.     But  in  the  common  uses  of  life  our  imagination    \ 
parcels  it  out  for  convenience.     What  we  call  things  are  per-     \ 
sistent    groups    of  our  sensations  and   of  relations  betAveen    ' 
them :  and  the  conception  of  a  thing  varies  according  to  our  , 
knowledge  and   the  purpose  for   which  the  conception  is  re-  ;. 
quired.     The   identity  and  individuality  of  things  is  nothing  , 
but  the  persistence  and  similarity  of  relations,  and  is  different  I 
as  we  take  one  or  another  set  of  relations.     A  living  body  is  \ 
the  same  from  day  to  day  in  one  sense,   not  the  same  in  j  , 
another.  > 

To  common  apprehension  the  common  objects  of  sight  and  f 
touch  are  unities  complete  in  themselves  and  marked  off  from 
the  rest  of  the  world  ;  they  are  conceived  as  whole  until  they 
are  visibly  divided.     To  the  scientific  apprehension  they  are 
composite  structures  built  up  of  molecules,  which  again  are  ; 
built  up  of  atoms.     For  common  purposes  and  many  scientific  / 
purposes  we  regard  the  internal  parts  of  inanimate  bodies  as  fi 
at  rest ;  for  other  scientific  purposes  we  regard  them  as  in  con-'' 
stant  motion.     If  we  take  the  separate  things  into  which  we 
have  thus  parcelled  out  the  world,  and  try  to  reconstruct  the  : 
unity  of  the  world  out  of  them,  we  shall  naturally  fail.     For/ 
the  unity  was  broken  up  in  the  act  of  imagining  each  thing; 
as  separate,  and  for  the  purpose  of  dealing  with  it  separately] 
We  cannot  restore  the  unity  without  undoing  the  dividing f 
work  of  the  imagination. 

As  we  divide  the  unity  of  the  world  materially  by  the  con 
ception  of  separate  things,  so  we  also  divide  it  formally  by 
those  of  measurable  space  and  time.  Extension  Is  one  and 
mdivisiblcj,  but  we  measure  out  space  by  feet  and  inches,  or  by 
fractions  of  a  millimetre,  or  by  diameters  of  the  earth's  orbit, 
as  may  serve  the  matter  in  hand.  Duration  is  continuous,  but 
we  first  conceive  time,  as  Newton  said,  to  be  something  con- 
stantly and  equably  flowing,  and  then  we  take  lengths  of  it,  as 
it  were,  and  mark  them  off  into  years,  days,  hours,  and  minutes. 


i84  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Number  is  involved  in  the  possibility  of  things  being  conceived 
as  separate.'  If  we  perceive  or  conceive  things  and  classes  of 
things  as  persistent,  we  can  range  them,  in  fact  or  in  mental 
representation,  side  by  side.  And  we  find  that  they  still  per- 
sist, however  we  may  alter  the  arrangement.  As  Sir  James 
■  Stephen  has  excellently  said,  we  are  able  to  measure  and  count 
things  because  they  stay  to  be  measured  and  counted.  We 
take  matter  occupying  a  definite  part  of  space,  and  consider 
its  motions  and  the  transformations  of  energy  therein  involved 
apart  from  the  general  sum  of  matter  and  energy  :  in  Spinoza's 
words,  '  a  modo,  quo  a  rebus  aeternis  fluit,^  separamus,' 

That  things  do  thus  cohere   and  persist,   so  as  to  make 
measure  and  number  possible,  is  a  universal  fact  of  experi- 
ence ;  indeed  there  could  be  no  experience  without  it.     Why 
I     it  should  be  so  is  an  impracticable  and  barren  inquiry  (except 
f     so  far  as   physical  research  may  succeed   in  expressing  the 
j     more  complex  properties  of  matter  in  terms  of  less  complex 
I     ones),  and  Spinoza  seems  to  pass  it  over.     But  he  also  seems 
»     to  assume  that  it  is  not  of  the  nature  of  understandmg~as  such 
to  perceive  things  by  the  '  aids  of  the  imagination.'     Extension, 
r    as  we  have  seen,  is  for  Spinoza  only  one  of  innumerable  aspects 

f 

of  existence.  Intelligences  knowing  Substance  under  other 
attributes  would  presumably  have  their  own  'aids  of  the 
imagination,'  corresponding  to  our  spatial  measurements. 
But  we  also  find  indications  that  existence  and  knowledge 
out  of  time  were  conceived  by  Spinoza  as  possible ;  in  fact, 
he  regards  all  scientific  knowledge,  the  knowledge  of  things 
as  necessary  or  '  sub  specie  aeternitatis,'  as  independent  of 
time.  Everything  is  eternal  in  its  necessary  aspect,  or  as 
part  of  the  universal  order,  and  the  knowledge  of  it  is  eternal 
also.     An  unexpected  use  is  made  of  this  conception  in  the 

'  Cf.  Cogit.  Met.  part  i.  cap.  6,  §  i  :  '  Nos  autem  dicimus  unitatem  .... 
tantum  modum  cogitandi  esse,  quo  rem  ab  aliis  separamus,  quae  ipsi  similes  sunt, 
vel  cum  ipsa  aliquo  modo  conveniunt.' 

*  Res  aeternae  =  infinite  modes  =  in  extension,  Motion  and  Matter.  See 
p.  152,  above. 


THE  NATURE   OF  THINGS.  185 

last  part  of  the  '  Ethics,'  of  which  there  is  more  to  be  said  here- 
after. In  this  point,  I  think,  Spinoza  was  again  striving  to 
transcend  experience.  The  knowledge  that  something  is  true 
at  all  times  and  in  all  places  is  not  a  knowledge  out  of  time : 
for  the  act  of  knowing  or  feeling  involves  change,  and  change 
involves  time.  Without  risking  any  transcendental  proposi- 
tion we  may  safely  affirm  that  to  the  human  mind,  or  to  any 
mind  similarly  organized  in  the  world  we  live  in,  existence 
out  of  time  is  not  intelligible. 

It  is  material  to  note  that  the  'aids  of  the  imagination '~^ 
are   not  represented    by  Spinoza  as  forms  imposed   by  the 
mind  upon  things.     They  arise  out  of  the  relation  between  the 
reality  of  things  and  the  finite  mind  which  is  unable  to  graspi 
it  in  imagination  as  an  unbroken  whole.    Only  the  division  and 
measuring  is  the  work  of  the  mind  ;  that  which  we  represent  \ 
'as  divided  "and  measured  is  perfectly  real.     We  do  not  per-  \ 
ceive  things  as  extended  in  space  because  such  is  the  constitu-  ! 
tioh  of  our  minds  ;  we  perceive  them  as  extended  because  our  \ 
bodies  are  extended,  and  we  measure  and  divide  extension  for ( 
the  purpose  of  comparing  our  perceptions.     Thus  Spinoza's  { 
doctrine  of  time  and  space  cannot  be  called  an  anticipation  of 
Kant's.     He  would  never  have  admitted  that  the  material 
world  is  extended  only  in  respect  of  our  perception.     Kant 
assumes  real  existences   which  are  unperceivable  and  unin- 
telligible.    Spinoza  denies  that  any  kind  of  existence  is  unin- 
telligible, and  also  denies  that  the  understanding  makes  exist- 
ence what  it  is.     The  inner  and  outer  aspects  of  the  world  are 
for  him  correlated,  co-equal,  and  co-ordinate.     Extension  is   | 
made  known  to  consciousness,  Thought  is  made  known  in 
consciousness,  but  neither  is  derived  from  it.    On  the  contrary,  o 
the  conscious  mind  is  a  highly  complex  mode  of  thought, 
organized  as  the  body,  which  is  its  outward  aspect,  is  organized. 
Unorganized  matter  is  correlated  with  proportionately  simpler  c 
groupings  of  the  ultimate  elements  of  thought  or  feeling  ;  and 
unorganized   things  are,   in  accordance    with    both    common 


|W 


1 86  SPINOZA:   HIS    LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

language  and  the  inferences  of  science,  regarded  as  uncon- 
scious. At  the  same  time,  thought  being  no  less  continuous 
than  extension,  or  rather  their  continuity  being  the  same,  it 
is  impossible  to  fix  the  point  where  life  begins  or  leaves  off. 
Why  thought  should  become  conscious  and  capable  of  re-t 
flexion  when  it  attains  a  particular  kind  and  degree  of  organized 
complexity  is  a  question  we  have  no  means  of  answering,  and 
Spinoza  does  not  attempt  to  deal  with  it. 

We  are  here  partly  anticipating  Spinoza's  psychology-; 
but  it  may  conduce  to  clearness  to  exhibit  its  principles  in 
immediate  connexion  with  their  metaphysical  foundation 
before  we  trace  their  application  in  the  following  chapter.  It 
may  also  be  permitted  to  anticipate  the  results  so  far  as  to 
observe  that  they  show  a  remarkable  coincidence  with  those 
of  the  modem  English  or  empirical  school.  Spinoza  starts 
from  premisses  which  are  in  appearance  dogmatic  and  trans- 
cendental, and  yet  his  conclusions  are  the  same  that  have  been 
independently  reached  by  inquirers  who  acknowledged  no 
source  of  knowledge  but  experience.  At  first  sight  the  coin- 
cidence is  perplexing,  but  it  is  not  really  very  difficult  to 
explain.  The  psychology  of  the  '  Ethics '  is  founded  in  part  on 
tacit  assumptions  of  an  empirical  kind,  in  part  on  express 
ones  which  are  in  form  universal  and  unqualified.  But,  in 
one  way  or  another,  much  the  same  positions  are  assumed  by 
Spinoza  that  are  accepted  by  modern  science  and  psychology 
as  the  basis  of  their  work.  And  since  a  working  hypothesis 
must  be  treated,  so  long  as  one  works  with  it,  as  if  it  were 
absolutely  true,  there  is  no  reason  why  the  results  and  even 
the  processes  should  not  in  great  measure  coincide.  Thus 
we  may  well  hold  that  all  human  knowledge  is  provisional, 
and  yet  receive  as  real  additions  to  knowledge,  and  valid  for 
practical  purposes,  doctrines  arrived  at  and  asserted  in  the 
first  instance  without  any  thought  of  such  reservations. 


THE  NATURE   OF   THINGS.  187 


NOTE    rO    CHAPTER   V. 

The  doctrine  of  the  Infinite  Modes,  one  of  the  most  difficult 
points  in  Spinoza's  system,  has  been  discussed  piecemeal  as  it  came 
up  under  one  and  another  aspect.  It  may  be  useful  to  give  a  summary 
view  of  the  results. 

According  to  the  explanation  here  proposed,  the  Infinite  Modes 
are  as  follows  : — 

1.  In  Extension. 

a.  Motion,  conceived   after  the  Cartesian   theory  as   a  real 

thing  and  constant  in  quantity  :  '  quantity  of  motion ' 
being  the  '  momentum '  of  modern  usage. 

b.  The  material  universe  or  sum  of  extended  things  taken 

together  as  one  Mode,  'facies  totius  universi.'      This, 
being  extension  modified  by  motion  and  rest,  is  said  to  be 
produced    by   God  not   immediately  but   through    the  !/ 
operation  of  motion  ('  mediantibus  his  primis,'  Eth.  i.  28, 
Schol.). 

2.  In  Thought. 

a.  The  sum  of  all  the  psychical  facts  or  events  correspond- 

ing to  physical  motion,  '  intellectus  absolute  infinitus.' 

b.  There    should    be    a    sum    of   all   particular    modes    of,. 

Thought  taken  as  making  up  one  Mode,  to  correspond  to 
the  'facies  totius  universi.'  But  this  is  not  specified  by 
Sphioza.  It  might  be  the  '  idea  Dei  in  cogitatione  '  of 
Eth.  i.  21,  but  there  it  seems  not  to  be  distinguished 
from  '  intellectus  absolute  infinitus.' 


We  have  then  : — 

A.  Deus  {causa  absolute proxima). 
Extensio.  Cogitatio. 

B.  Res  a  Deo  immediate  produciae. 

t,        ,  r  Motus.  Intellectus  absolute  infinitus. 

Res  aeternae 

seu  modi  infi-  J        B'.  Modi  qui  et  nccessario  et  infiniti  existimt,  median- 
"[tjjcausae       j  tibus  his  primis. 

t  Faeies  totius  universi.  (.?)  Idea  Dei  in  cogitatione. 

C.  Res  siugulares  quae  Jiniiae  sunt. 


proximae) 


1 88  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

There  would  also  in  theory  be  modes  answering  to  these  in  eacho 
of  the  numerically  infinite  Attributes  to  us  unknown. 

This  matter  is  fully  and  ably  discussed  by  Ed.  Bohmer  {Spinozana 
ii.,  Zeitschr.  fiir  Philosophie  u.  philos,  Kritik,  vol.  42,  pp.  107-116, 
Halle  1863) ;  his  results  agree  to  a  considerable  extent  with  mine, 
at  which  I  had  arrived  before  seeing  his  work.  He  takes  Spinoza's 
'  facies  totius  universi '  to  cover  Thought  as  well  as  Extension  :  a 
possible  but,  as  it  seems  to  me,  not  very  probable  interpretation. 


i 


BODY  AND  MIND.  189 


CHAPTER   VI.         ^'V^-.s 

BODY    AND     MIND. 

Pensiti  aver  tu  solo  provvidenza, 

E  '1  ciel,  la  terra,  e  I'altre  cose  belle, 

Le  quali  sprezzi  tu,  starsene  senza? 
Sciocco,  d'onde  se'  nato  tu  ?  da  quelle, 

Dunque  ci  e  senno  e  Dio.     Muta  sentenza. 

Mai  si  contrasta  a  chi  guida  le  stelle. — Campanella. 

oin  PpoToTs  ytpas  aWo  ri  iii(7^oy 
otre  0fo7s  ^  KOiyhv  ail  v6fiov  ^v  S'ik^  vfxvelf. 

Cleanthes,  Hymn  to  Zeus. 

Our  experience  manifests  to  us  a  series  of  events  in  time. 
But  we  no  sooner  begin  to  reflect  upon  it  than  we  find  that 
the  series  is  not  single  but  double.  We  commonly  speak  of 
time  and  space  as  if  they  were  on  exactly  the  same  footing  ; 
yet  there  is  a  distinction  of  some  importance.  Whatever 
happens  in  space  can  be  perceived  by  several  observers  at 
once,  so  far  as  the  conditions  admit  of  their  being  conveniently 
placed.  On  the  other  hand,  every  one  of  us  is  aware  of  an 
immense  number  of  events  which  can  be  perceived  by  nobody 
but  himself,  namely,  his  own  thoughts  and  feelings.  When  I 
move  my  hand  to  write  on  this  paper  the  motion  can  be  seen 
by  another  person  in  the  room^fuU  as  well  as  by  myself.  The 
event  is  as  much  a  part  of  his  experience  as  of  mine.  But 
my  will  and  sensations  that  accompany  the  act  belong  to  me 
and  to  my  experience  alone.  My  companion  can  see  my  fingers 
on  the  pen,  but  he  cannot  feel  the  pressure  which  the  pen 
exerts  on  them  ;  he  can  follow  the  movements,  but  not  the 
desires  which  direct  them.     He  can  form  a  notion  of  my  feel- 


I90  SPINOZA:  HIS  IIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

ings  only  by  inference  from  what  his  own  feelings  have  been 
in  similar  circumstances;  immediate  experience  of  them  is 
wholly  beyond  his  reach. 

If  we  desire  to  use  the  word  unknowable,  we  may  find  a 
harmless  use  for  it  by  saying  that  the  feelings  of  any  one 
mind  are  in  this  sense  unknowable  for  every  other  mind. 

Each  of  us  has  a  world  of  inner  experience  reserved  to 
himself  alone,  and  a  world  of  outer  experience  which  he  can 
share  with  other  men.     What  is  known  by  inward  experience 
we  call  mind,  or  mental ;  what  is  known  by  outward  experience 
I  I  is  named    matter,  or   material.     Modern    philosophers   have 
%  I  stated  the  distinction  in  another  form  by  the  use  of  the  terms 
Subject  and  Object.     This  has  the  advantage  of  fixing  the 
attention  upon  the  individual  and  incommunicable  character 
of  the  mind's  experience.    The  adjective  derived  from  Subject, 
when  taken  in  this  technical  sense,  has  passed  into  common 
use  as  an  epithet  for  feelings  or  opinions  resting  on  personal 
grounds,  as  distinguished  from  such  as  are  due  to  causes  found 
to  operate  in  a  similar  way  on  great  numbers  of  men  Imder 
similarconditions.  Its  correlated  term  objective  is  not  so  familiar 
in  England,  but  is  freely  used  by  German  writers  to  denote 
absence  of  prejudice  and  distortion,  faithfulness  in  reproduc- 
tion, and  the  like.     In  this  meaning  it  almost  comes  round  to 
the  earlier  usage,  where,  as  we  have  already  seen  in  Spinoza's 
treatise  on  Method,  a  true  idea  is  said  to  '  repeat  objectively ' 
the  reality  of  the  thing  signified.     Whether  the  terms  have 
really  done  much  good  in  philosophy  is,  I  think,  an   open 
question.     They   have    certainly   led  to  much  inelegance  of 
language  and  some  confusion  of  thought. 

I  have  assumed  that  the  division  of  Subject  and  Object  is 
identical  with  that  of  Mind  and  Matter;  but  it  may  -be 
needful  to  show  cause  for  this,  though  it  is  in  truth  rather  a 
matter  of  verbal  definition  than  anything  else.  Let  it  be 
supposed  that  the  two  divisions  do  not  coincide.  Then 
Matter  can  be  part  of  the  Subject,  or  Mind  part  of  the  Object. 


\ 


BODY  AND  MIND.  191 

The  former  is  obviously  impossible  :  for  Matter,  whatever  it 
may  be,  is  not  part  of  my  feeling.  It  is  assumed  to  exist 
expressly  as  something  outside  my  feeling.  My  own  body 
and  organs  of  sense  belong  to  the  objective  world  no  less  than 
any  other  bodies.  Nor  does  it  fare  any  better  with  the  latter 
alternative.  It  is  true  I  can  reflect  upon  my  own  feelings, 
but  that  will  not  make  them  something  outside  me.  Like- 
wise I  can  think  of  other  persons  and  their  feelings  ;  but  that 
will  not  make  their  minds  objects  to  me  :  for  I  think  of  their 
minds  as  trains  of  consciousness  and  feeling  analogous  to  my 
own,  but  inaccessible  to  my  direct  knowledge.  They  are  re- 
presented, in  fact,  as  imaginary  states  of  my  own  mind  which 
it  might  assume  under  those  other  conditions  which  are 
actually  present  in  the  case  of  the  other  persons  I  think  of. 
Therefore  no  part  of  Mind  can  be  part  of  the  Object.  Thus 
we  see  that  the  division  of  individual  experience  by  the 
conceptions  of  subject  and  object  is  the  same  which  was 
applied  to  existence  by  the  conceptions  of  mind  and  matter. 
Now  this  reasoning  tends  to  show  that  the  divisions  are  in 
themselves  unsatisfactory.  And  we  need  not  be  surprised  at 
it,  having  seen  in  the  last  chapter  the  metaphysical  grounds 
for  holding  the  ultimate  distinction  between  mind  and  matter 
to  be  illusory. 

The  distinction  in  human  experience  is  however  quite 
real ;  and  mankind,  taking  their  experience  as  the  measure  of 
existence,  have  conceived  the  world  of  mind  and  the  world  of 
matter  as  two  sharply  defined  regions  set  over  against  one 
another.  But  the  same  experience  which  suggested  the  divi- 
sion also  shows  us  a  constant  connexion.  The  feelings  which 
I  cannot  show  to  my  fellow-man  in  any  but  a  symbolic  and 
representative  manner,  namely,  by  signs  that  he  can  interpret 
in  terms  of  his  own  feelings,  are  paired  with  outward  events 
which  are  parcel  of  our  common  experience.  The  gulf  between 
the  two  worlds  is  bridged.  How  the  bridge  is  possible  is  a 
problem  which  has  exercised  philosophers  of  all  ages  ;  and  all 


V^ 


192  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

their  endeavours  have  failed  so  long  as  they  have  not  perceived 
that  the  gulf  itself  is  the  creature  of  our  own  thought.  It  is 
an  irrational  and  hopeless  task  to  inquire  how  mind  acts  upon 
matter,  or  matter  upon  mind.  We  are  trying  to  find  a  rela- 
tion between  things  which  have  no  common  measure.  The 
strength  of  an  emotion  cannot  be  expressed  in  foot-pounds, 
nor  will  our  sensations  of  warmth  help  us  to  fix  the  mechanical 
equivalent  of  heat.  Either  we  must  give  up  the  problem  as  a 
mystery,  or  we  must  invent  another  mystery  to  explain  it,  or 
we  must  say  plainly  that  the  common  way  of  stating  it  is 
wrong,  and  that  the  distinction  on  which  it  is  founded  is 
wrong  also. 

The  Cartesian  school  saw  the  difficulty,  but  still  held  to 
the  conception  of  mind  and  matter  as  entities  or  substances 
distinct  in  themselves.  The  notion  of  mutual  action  was  very 
nearly,  but  not  quite,  rejected  by  Descartes.  He  supposed  a 
communication  by  means  of  the  '  animal  spirits,'  the  soul 
being  able  to  change  the  direction  though  not  the  amount 
of  their  motion.  His  followers  went  further,  and  devised 
the  theory  of  Occasional  Causes,  first  propounded  in  its 
completeness  by  Arnold  Geulinx.  The  correspondence  ofo 
body  and  mind  was  kept  up  at  ever}^  instant  by  a  special 
operation  of  God's  power.  Material  fire  could  have  no 
effect  of  itself  on  the  immaterial  mind,  but  was  the  occasion 
of  God's  producing  in  the  mind  the  sensations  of  light 
and  heat.  This_w3j_jiQthing_ds£_than^j^ost^^ 
petual  miracle  '^  and  the  Cartesians  not  only  admitted  as 
much,  but  made  it  a  reason  for  recommending  the  opinion. 
Leibnitz  put  forward  a  simpler  but  not  less  arbitrary  supposi- 
tion. His  famous  doctrine  of  Pre-established  Harmony,  as  c 
applied  to  this  particular  question,  likens  mind  and  matter  to 
two  clocks  constructed  with  absolute  perfection  of  mechanism 
and  set  going  at  the  same  rate,  so  that,  while  each  goes 
independently  of  the  other,  they  keep  exact  time  together. 
The  metaphor  of  the  two  clocks  is  also  found  in  Cartesian 


BODY  AND  MIND.  193 

literature ; '  and  we  might  perhaps  Hken  the  communication 
through  the  '  animal  spirits  '  which  is  admitted  in  the  earlier 
Cartesian  theory  to  an  electrical  connexion  such  as  is  now 
sometimes  used  to  regulate  a  distant  clock  by  a  standard 
timekeeper. 

Spinoza's  psychology  takes  the  same  view  of  the  facts  ; 
but  instead  of  seeking  an  artificial  explanation  for  the  corre- 
spondence of  two  such  different  things  as  body  and  mind,  lie_ 
boldly  says  that  they  are_the  same  thing,  and  differ  onIy_as 
aspects.  Their  parallelism  and  mutual  indepgjidpnre  isjiuis. 
not  a  mystery  but  an  elementary  __fact.  To  ask  why  mind 
should  correspond  with  matter  is  like  asking  why  the  con- 
vexity of  a  curve  should  answer  to  the  concavity.  Let  us 
now  proceed  to  con.sider  Spinoza's  work  more  in  detail,  giving 
to  the  reader  who  may  not  be  acquainted  with  it  the  warning 
that  the  second  part  of  the  '  Ethics '  is  very  difficult  in  form, 
and  that  many  of  the  propositions  become  clear  only  by 
repeated  consideration.  The  preliminaries  however  are  less 
formidable  in  appearance  than  those  of  the  first  part,  and  we 
need  not  dwell  much  upon  them.  The  specific  assumptions  as 
to  the  nature  of  man  are  simple  appeals  to  common  experience.^ 
'  Man  thinks  ; '  '  we  are  aware  of  a  particular  body  '■ — that  is, 
each  man  is  aware  of  his  own  body — '  as  affected  in  many  ( 
ways  ; '  'we  are  not  aware,  nor  have  we  perceptions,  of  any 
individual    things    besides    bodies    and    modes    of    thought. 


'\ 


'  '  Sicut  duobus  horologiis  rite  inter  se  et  ad  solis  cursum  quadratis  propter 
nieram  dependentiam  qua  utrumque  ab  eadem  arte  et  simili  industria  constitutum 
est.'  Editor's  note  to  Geulinx's  posthumous  Ethics  (ap.  Bouillier,  Hist,  dc  la 
Philosophie  Cartesicnne,  i.  305,  3rd  ed.).  With  Leibnitz  there  is  a  universal 
harmony  between  the  independent  activities  of  the  infinite  monads  or  'simple  sub- 
stances '  which  make  up  the  sentient  universe.  Of  this  harmony  the  correspon- 
dence between  the  soul  and  the  bodily  organism  is  a  particular  case  :  Moiiadologie, 
§§78-81.  '  Ce  systeme  fait  que  les  corps  agissent  comme  si  (par  impossible)  il 
n'y  avoit  point  d'ames,  et  que  les  ames  agissent  comme  s'il  n'y  avoit  point  dc 
corps,  el  que  tous  deux  agissent  comme  si  Tun  influoit  sur  I'autre. '  Leibnitz,  like 
Spinoza,  calls  the  mind  a  '  spiritual  automaton.'    [TJiiv.iic.  §  403,  and  elsewhere.) 

-  Spinoza  himself  attaches  some  importance  to  this  ;  '  Omnia  ilia  quae  sumjisi 
postulata  vix  quicquam  continent  quod  non  constct  experientia  dc  qua  noliis  non 
licet  dubitare. ' — Prop.  17,  Schol. 

O 


1 


194  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Some  further  postulates  are  introduced  at  a  later  stage  (after 
Prop.  1 3)  concerning  the  composite  nature  of  the  human  frame 
and  the  component  parts  themselves,  and  its  powers  of  acting 
on  and  receiving  impressions  from  external  bodies. 

The  human  mind,  or  man  as  a  thinking  being,  is  a  mode° 
of  thought,  and  '  part  of  the  infinite  intellect  of  God  '  (Prop.  1 1, 
Coroll.).  As  such  it  must  have  its  correlate  or  *  object '  in 
extension  ;  for  the  same  reality  of  Substance  is  expressed  in 
extension  as  in  thought.'  This  object  is  nothing  else  than 
the  human  body,  the  existence  of  which  is  made  known  to  us 
by  our  experience  of  its  affections  (Prop.  13).  At  this  point 
occurs  a  note  of  great  importance,  the  substance  of  which  is 
best  given  in  Spinoza's  own  words  : — 

*  Hence  we  understand,  not  only  that  the  human  mind  is  united 
to  the  body,  but  what  is  to  be  understood  by  this  union.  But  no 
one  can  understand  this  adequately  or  distinctly  unless  he  first  has 
adequate  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  our  body.  For  the  propositions 
hitherto  established  are  very  general,  and  apply  no  more  to  man 
than  to  all  other  individual  things  ;  which  indeed  are  all  endowed 
with  mind,  though  in  various  degrees.  For  of  every  thing  soever^ 
there  is  necessarily  in  God  an  idea,  whereof  God  is  the  cause,  in 
like  manner  as  there  is  an  idea  of  the  human  body  :  and  thus  what- 
ever we  have  said  of  the  idea  of  the  human  body  must  also  be  said 
of  the  idea  of  everything  else.  At  the  same  time  we  cannot  deny 
that  ideas  differ  among  themselves  as  their  objects  do '  (the  relations 
among  modes  of  thought  are  parallel  to  those  among  the  correspond- 
ing modes  of  extension)  '  and  that  one  is  more  excellent  than 
another,  and  comprehends  more  reality  ;  and  therefore  in  order 
to  determine  wherein  the  human  mind  differs  from  others,  and 
how  it  excels  them,  it  is  needful  for  us  to  know  the  nature  of  its 
object,  that  is,  the  human  body.  This  however  I  cannot  here 
explain,  nor  is  it  necessary  for  the  purpose  of  my  demonstration. 
But  this  much  I  will  generally  say,  that  the  more  any  body  surpasses 
others  in  its  fitness  for  manifold  actions  or  impressions,  the  more 
doth  its  mind  surpass  others  in  capacity  for  manifold  perceptions  j 

'  Prop.  7.  What  becomes  of  the  corresponding  modes  of  the  other  Attributes  ? 
This  difficuUy,  which  is  insohil^le  on  Spinoza's  principle  of  p(pi3l  cQ-nrdinAlIi^i, 
has  already  been  discussed  in  the  last  chapter. 


/ 


BODY  AND  MIXD.  195 

and  the  more  the  actions  of  a  given  body  depend  upon  itself  alone, 
and  the  less  other  bodies  concur  with  it  in  its  actions,  the  more 
capable  is  its  mind  of  distinct  understanding.  Hence  we  can  obtain 
knowledge  of  the  excellence  of  one  mind  above  others  ;  and  more- 
over see  why  we  have  but  a  very  confused  knowledge  of  our  own 
body,  and  several  other  matters  which  I  shall  in  the  sequel  deduce 
from  these  principles.' 

There  could  not  be  a  more  distinct  or  positive  declaration 
of  the  necessity  that  psychology,  if  it  is  to  be  a  serious  branch 
of  scientific  inquiry,  should  go  hand  in  hand  with  physio- 
logy, and  verify  its  results,  as  far  as  possible,  by  physiological 
observation.  Persons  who  describe  Spinoza  as  a  mere  dog- 
matic metaphysician  have  obviously  never  read  as  far  as  this 
Scholium.  But  to  proceed  to  Spinoza's  consequences.  One 
of  the  first  is  that  '  the  idea  constituting  the  human  mind,  as 
it  is  in  itself,  is  not  simple,  but  compounded  of  very  many 
Ideas.'  For  the  human  mind  is  the  idea,  or  correlate  in 
thought,  of  an  extended  body  which  is  known  to  be  very 
complex  ;  and  every  part  of  the  body  must  have  its  corre- 
sponding idea  ;  so  that  the  mind  is  composed  of  the  ideas  of 
the  manifold  parts  that  make  up  the  body.  In  oth^r  words, 
the  mindjs  complex  precisely  as  the^adxls  compjex.  Here 
at  all  events  there  is  no  metaphysical  assumption  in  the 
popular  sense  of  the  term  ;  nothing  about  a  soul,  or  an  Ego, 
or  a  simple  substance,  or  an  inward  assurance  of  personality. 
We  must  complain  of  Spinoza,  if  we  complain  of  him  at  all, 
for  not  being  metaphysical  enough.  From  this  we  are  led 
on  to  the  association  of  ideas,  a  topic  in  which  Spinoza  has 
T^uticipated  not  only  the  propositions  laid  down  by  modern 
ps)'chologists,  but  the  modern  manner  of  handling  them. 

The  perception  of  an  external  object  is  the  state  of  mind 
corresponding  to  the  modification  of  the  bodily  organism 
produced  by  that  object.  Sj  long  as  that  modification  lasts, 
so  long  will  the  corresponding  idea  ;  in  other  words,  the 
external   body  will   be  perceived  or  thought  of  as  present. 

o  2 


»^ 


i 


196  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

And  this  will  be  repeated  if  the  parts  of  the  organism  con- 
cerned are  again  placed  in  the  same  disposition,  whether  by 
the   presence  of  the  same  object  or  by  any  other  accident. 
Hence  we  may  imagine  things  as  present  when  they  are  not.      V 
Here  likewise  it  is  observed  that  our  notion  of  an  external 
^  I  ■  body  is  a  function  of  our  own  organism,  and  has  more  to  do 
'  ' ;  with  the  nature  of  our  own  body  than  with  that  of  the  external 
one.     Thus  'we  understand  what  is  the  difference  between' 
,  that  idea  of  Peter  which  constitutes  the  reality  of  Peter's  own 
mind,  and  the  idea  of  Peter  which  is  in  another  man,  say  in 
Paul.      For  the  former   directly    answers   to    (explicatj    the 
reality  of  Peter's  own   body,  and  does   not   imply  existence 
except  while  Peter  exists  ;  the  latter  indicates  rather  the  dis- 
position of  Pauls  body  than  the  nature  of  Peter,  and  therefore 
while  that  disposition   lasts  Paul's  mind,  though   Peter  may 
not  exist,  will  }-et  regard  him  as  present  to  it.'     Spinoza  is 
fully  conscious  in  this  place  of  his  doubl,e__iLi£.  of  the  over- 
worked term  idea  ;  yet    elsewhere,  as  we  pointed    out    in  a 
former  chapter,  he  appears  to  mix  up  the  two  meanings;  and  in 
a  later  proposition  (Part  2,  Pr.  ^2)  the  verbal  confusion  reaches 
its  climax.       The  proposition  amounts  to  saying  that  every 
mental  state  is  in  one  sense  true,  inasmuch  as  it  really  exists. 
But  to  return  to  the  passage  immediately  before    us:  it  is 
further  noted  that  imagination  is  in  itself  not  capable  of  error. 
If  the  mind  imagines  a  non-existent  thing  as  present,  but  also 
knows  it  not  to  exist,  there  is  no  error,  but  a  pure  activity  of 
the  imaginative  power.'     Again.  '  if  the  human  body  has  once 
been  affected  at  the  same  time  by  two  or  more  bodies,  then  when  " 
'ithe  mind  afterwards  imagines  any  one  of  them,  it  v/ill  there-- 
'4upon  remember    the    others    also.'  -     This  is  the   ground  of 
'""Ifiiemory  and  association.     Memory  is  defined  as  'An associa- 
tion (concatenatio)   of  ideas  involving  the  nature  of  things 
outside  the  human  body,  which  arises  in  the  mind  according 

'  Prop.  17,  Scho"  -  riop.  18. 


BODY  AXD  MIND.  197 

to  the  order  and   association  of  the  affections  of  the  human 
body.' 

*  And  hence  we  further  understand  why  the  mind  should  upon  the 
thought  of  one  thing  fall  into  the  thought  of  anotlier  thing  which  hath 
no  likeness  with  the  first.  As  for  example,  from  thinking  upon  the  word 
pomum  a  Roman  will  fall  to  thinking  upon  the  fruit  apple,  which  hath 
no  likeness  to  that  articulate  sound,  nor  anything  common  with  it, 
save  that  the  man's  body  has  often  been  affected  by  these  two  ;  that 
is,  that  the  man  often  heard  the  word  pomum  when  he  saw  the  fruit 
itself ;  and  thus  every  man  '"ill  fall  from  one  thought  into  another,  as 
the  habit  of  each  has  ordered  the  images  of  things  in  his  body.  A 
soldier  when  he  sees  the  footprints  of  a  horse  in  sand  wui  thcreiipon 
fall  to  thinking  of  a  horseman,  and  thence  into  thoughts  of  warfare 
and  the  like.  But  a  farmer  will  fall  from  thinking  of  the  horse  to 
thinking  of  ploughs,  fields,  and  the  like  ;  and  thus  will  every  man 
fall  into  this  or  that  course  of  thought,  as  he  has  been  accustomed  to 
join  and  associate  the  ideas  of  things  in  this  or  that  manner.' 

This  contains,  though  only  in  outline,  all  the  essentials  of 
the  modem  doctrine  on  the  subject. 

The  nature  and  limitations  of  human  knowledge  are  then 
further  discussed  on  the  same  psychological  method.  We 
know  our  own  bodies  only  through  our  '  ideas  of  the  affections 
wherewith  the  body  is  affected  ; '  and  we  also  have  a  reflective 


knowledge  of  these  ideas,  and  this  is  the  milyJ<nowledge  which 
the  mind  has_of  itself.'  Even  in  the  most  abstruse  act  of  re- 
flexion the  mental  operation  is  accompanied  by  the  material 
series  of  changes  in  the  organism  ;  we  cannot  by  any  cffort„ 
whateve.r  transcend  the  organic  conditions  of  thought,  for  they 
are  the  other  .side^  thought  itself.  All  our  perceptions  of  ^' 
external  things  consist  in  perceptions  of  our  own  body  as 
modified  by  them  ;  but  this  does  not  give  us  accurate  know- 
ledgeof  the  constitution  either  of  our  own  bodies  or  of  the  objects 
affecting  them.  For  the  things  we  actually  perceive,  whether 
due  to  the  internanunctions_ofour  organism  or  to  impressions 

'  Eth.  ii.  19-23.     As  to  Spinoza's   peculiar  way  of  stating  the  doctrine  of 
'idea  ill eae,' cf.  p.  i33aoove. 


\ 


198  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

on  it  from  without,  are  but  limited  parts  of  extremely  complex 
pHysical  events  extending  far  beyomi^our  '"sen!Tent~Qrgang,__ 
And  on  the  whole,  'the  human  mind,  whenever  it  perceives  0 
things  after  the  common  order  of  nature,  has  not  an  adequate 
knowledge  either  of  itself  or  of  its  own  body,  or  of  external 
bodies,  but  only  a  confused  and  fragm.entary  one.'  The  mind 
is  said  to  '  perceive  things  after  the  common  order  of  nature ' 
when  itsjthought^are.determined  by  externalcircumstancesj 

i   which  with  regard  to  the  mind  may  be  called  accidental,  and 

;  not  by  its_pwn  operation  ^^fxeasojiing. 

'         Hence  we  have  but    a  confused  notion  of  the  duration 

-  either  of  our  own  body  or  of  external  things,  for  this  depends 
on  the  'common  order  of  nature;'  and  thus  we  regard  all 
particular  things  as  contingent  and  perishable  ;  for  to  call  a 
thing  contingent  and  perishable^is  as  much  as  to  say  that  we 
have  no  adequate  knowledge  of  its  duration.  Error  in  general 
is  explained  as  the  privation  of  knowledge  which  accompanies 
inadequate  or  confused  ideas. 

'  For  example,  men  are  mistaken  m  their  opinion  of  their  own 
freedom  ;  which  opinion  consisteth  only  in  this,  that  they  are  con- 
scious of  their  own  actions,  and  ignorant  of  the  causes  whereby  they 
are  determined.  So  that  their  idea  of  freedom  is  nothing  else  than 
their  not  knowing  any  cause  of  their  actions.  For  when  they  say 
that  human  actions  depend  on  the  will,  these  are  words  for  which 
they  have  no  idea  to  answer  them.  What  the  will  is,  or  how  it 
moves  the  body,  thereof  they  all  know  nothing  ;  the  pretensions  of 
those  who,  feigning  to  know  somewhat,  devise  houses  and  dwelling- 
places  for  the  soul,  are  either  ludicrous  or  disgusting.' ' 

Again,  our  visual  impression  of  the  sun's  apparent  distance 
is  not  altered  by  knowledge  of  the  real  distance.  The  error 
of  the  common  sort  is  not  in  the  visual  impression  itself,  but 
in  the  ignorance  that  accompanies  it.  '  We  imagine  the  sun 
as  near  us,  not  because  we  know  not  its  true  distance,  but 
because  the  present  affection  of  our  body  involves  the  nature 

'  Prop.  35,  Suhol. 


BODY  AND  MIND. 


199 


of  the  sun  only  in  so  far  as  the  same  body  is  thereby  affected.' 
It  is  to  be  observed  that  imagination  here  stands  for  the 
acquired  interpretations  of  sensation  which  in  ordinary  adult 
perceptions  are  not  distinguished  from  the  sensation  itself, 
but  which  really  depend  on  the  representation  of  many  sensa- 
tions experienced  in  the  past  and  their  various  associations  and 
consequences.  The  erroneous  ideas  in  a  finite  mind,  however 
are  in  themselves  as  necessary  as  the  true  ones,  being  part  of 
the  general  order  of  nature.  On  the  other  hand  there  are 
ideas  in  the  human  rnind  which  are  necessarHyLadequaiieL 
"namely  ideas  of  those  elements  which  are  common  to  all 
perceptions,  or,  taking  it  from  the  objective  side,  to  the  human 
body  and  all  bodies  affecting  it.  '  Hence  it  follows  that  a 
mind  will  be  fitted  to  perceive  more  things,  and  to  perceive 
them  adequately,  as  its  body  has  more  in  common  with  other 
bodies  : '  in  other  words,  the  power  of  gaining  knowledge  from 
the  outer  world  depends  on  the  variety  of  the  organs  of  sen- 
sation, and  their  adaptation  to  the  physical  influences  by 
which  they  can  be  affected  ;  a  conclusion  which  must  be 
admitted  as  very  just,  whatever  we  may  think  of  Spinoza's 
Avay  of  demonstrating  it.  In  modern  language,  his  position 
amounts  to  the  now  familiar  statement  that  sensation  is  a 
function  of  the  organism  as  affected  by  some  external  body^ 
But  the  condition  of  the  affected  organism  does  not  necessarily 
resemble  the  condition  of  the  affected  body,  except  so  far  as 
they  are  both  material  systems  in  which  motion  and  trans- 
ferences of  energy  are  going  on.  Thus  neither  our  sensations 
nor  the  physical  events  in  the  organism  immediately  correlated 
with  them  can  be  said  in  any  proper  sense  to  resemble  the 
external  objects  and  events  indicated  by  them.  Spinoza's 
argument  seems  to  imply  further  that  all  men  have  an 
adequate  idea  of  matter  and  motion  ;  for  these  are  on  his 
physical  principles  the  only  constituents  common  to  all  bodies. 
This  appears  to  be  another  consequence  of  the  ambiguous  use 
of  the  word  '  idea.'     That  which  is  feeling  in  itself,  or  to  the 


200  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

inward  sense,  would  be  to  the  outward  sense,  if  it  were 
accessible,  a  series  of  motions  in  a  material  organism.  And 
motion,  as  such,  is  everywhere  the  same,  whether  occurring  in 
the  organism  or  outside  it.  But  this  carries  us  no  farther  as  to 
the  correctness  of  the  information  we  derive  from  our  senses 
concerning  the  outer  world,  much  less  of  the  conceptions  of 
matter  and  motion  which  we  may  form  by  reflexion  on  our 
,  experience.  Because  my  idea,  in  the  general  sense  of  mental 
state,  corresponds  exactly  to  a  series  of  physical  events  in  my 
brain,  it  follows  not  that  I  shall  frame  an  adequate  idea,  in 
the  sense  of  a  consciously  held  conception,  when  I  try  to 
think  what  matter  and  motion  are.  All  that  I  can  directly 
know  is  a  state  of  my  own  feeling.  It  is  only  through  a  long 
course  of  education  and  experiment  that  I  can  interpret  any 
such  state  in  terms  of  other  people's  possible  feelings,  or,  in 
other  words,  proceed  from  it  to  a  statement  about  the 
accompanying  condition  of  my  own  organs  or  the  dispositions 
of  external  bodies  determining  that  condition. 

Spinoza,  however,   does  not  here  explain   what  are  the 
notions  common  to  all  men,  or  the    secondary  maxims  de- 
ducible    from    them.     He    refers   us  for  all   this  to    another 
treatise,  probably  the  unfinished  work  on  the  Amendment  of 
the  Understanding,  of  which  an  account   has   already  been 
given,  and  he  goes  on  to  his  explanation  of  universals.'     The 
limited  resources  of  our  organism  permit  us  to  form  only  a 
limited  number  of  images.     There  is  a  point  beyond  which 
our  senses  become  incapable  of  perceiving  minute  differences  ; 
the  various  organs  of  the  human  body,  with  all  its  delicacy  of 
adaptation,  are  but  rough  instruments  to  observe  the  bound- 
less variety  of  nature  withal.     We  may  observe  in  passing 
j  that  Spinoza's  statement,  which  is  here  partly  modernized  in 
form,  is  confirmed  to  the  full  by  the  results  of  modern  phy- 
a  siology.     The    overlapping   and  confusion    of  many  similar 
\  perceptions  and  the  representations  of  them  beget  our  generic 

'  Prop.  40,  Schol.  2. 


c 


BODY  AND  MIND.  201 

or  so-called  universal  notions.  We  have  seen,  for  example, 
a  great  number  of  human  beings  in  the  course  of  life,  and 
cannot  remember  all  the  differences  of  stature,  complexion, 
features,  and  other  matters.  Every  one  carries  a  strong 
though  not  very  distinct  impression  of  the  points  in  which 
all  or  most  of  the  several  perceptions  have  agreed,  and  the 
aggregate  of  these  is  called  by  the  generic  name  of  man. 
Thus  one  man's  general  ideas  are  not  exactly  like  another's  ; 
they  depend  in  each  case  on  the  individual's  aptitude  for 
perceiving  and  remembering  this  or  that  common  feature  in  a 
multitude  of  objects.  The  crystallographer's  idea  of  diamofid 
is  different  from  the  chemist's,  and  that  again  from  the 
jeweller's. 

'  Those  who  have  often  admired  the  stature  of  men  understand  by 
the  name  of  ??ian  an  animal  of  upright  stature  ;  while  those  who  are 
accustomed  to  consider  some  other  attribute  will  form  some  other 
general  imagination  of  men,  as,  that  man  is  an  animal  capable  of 
laughter,  two-legged,  without  feathers,  or  rational;  and  thus  in  other 
cases  every  one  will  form  universal  images  of  things  after  the  habit  of 
his  body.  Wherefore  it  is  no  wonder  that  so  many  controversies 
have  arisen  among  philosophers,  who  have  been  minded  to  explain 
things  as  they  are  in  nature  by  mere  images  of  things.' ' 

This  leads  to  a  classification  of  knowledge  in  three  de-' 
grees.  The  first  is  opinion  or  imagination,  proceeding  from 
one's  own  confused  experience  or  the  report  of  others.  In  this 
class  are  noAV  included  the  first  and  second  kinds  of  know- 
ledge which  we  met  with  in  the  treatise  on  the  Amendment 
of  the  Understanding  (p.  126  above). 

The  second  or  reasonable  kind  is  obtained  by  the  posses- 
sion of  common  notions  (which  are  necessarily  adequate)  and 
adequate  ideas  of  particularTproperties  of  things. 

The  third,  or  intuitive  kind,  '  proceeds  from  an  ade- 
quate idea  of  the  absolute  nature  of  some  attribute  of  God 

'  Prop.  40,  Schol.  I.  Compare  Mr.  F.  Gallon's  recent  paper  on  'Generic 
Images,'  N^inelcenlh  Century,  July  1S79. 


202  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

to  an  adequate  knowledge  of  the  nature  of  things.'  Our 
immediate  perception  that  6  is  to  3  as  2  to  i  is  given  as  an 
instance  of  it ;  but  the  formidable  language  of  the  general 
statement  is  not  otherwise  explained. 

Knowledge  of  the  first  kind  is  precarious  ;  the  second  and 
third  kinds  are  certain,  and  are  our  only  means  of  distinguish- 
ing truth  from  error.  Then  comes  the  proposition  as  to  the 
ultimate  test  of  truth  which  we  have  cited  in  a  foregoing 
chapter  (p.  129). 

The  rest  of  the  second  Part  of  the  Ethics^  is  mainly  devoted 
to  working  out  the  theory  of  determinism./ '  It  is  of  the  nature  of 
reason  to  consider  things  not  as  contingent,  but  as  necessary:'^ 
it-is-tlie  wodc  oi-the  imagination  toj^gardlhern  as  contingent, 
and  our  notion  of  contingency  arises  from  the  confusion  of  many 
associations,  in  somewhat  the  same  way  that  general  notions 
arise  from  the  confused  impression  of  many  particular 
experiencesTf  Let  a  child  on  a  given  day  see  Peter  in  the 
morning,  Paul  at  noon,  and  Simon  in  the  evening ;  then  at 
the  beginning  of  the  next  day  he  will  expect  the  day  to  run 
its  course,  and  will  also  expect,  if  nothing  occurs  to  counteract 
it,  the  sight  of  Peter,  Paul,  and  Simon  to  be  repeated  in  the 
same  order  ;  and  the  expectation  will  be  strengthened  by 
repetition  of  the  experience.  But  if  one  evening  James  comes 
instead  of  Simon,  the  next  morning's  expectations  of  evening 
wall  bring  with  it  conflicting  images  of  Simon  and  James. 

'  For  the  boy  is  assumed  to  have  seen  at  eventide  only  one  or 
the  other  of  them,  not  both  together.  With  the  coming  eventide  he 
will  imagine  now  the  one,  now  the  other  ;  that  is,  he  Avill  imagine 
neither  of  them  as  certainly,  l)ut  both  as  contingently  about  to  be 
present.  Moreover  the  wavering  of  the  imagination  will  be  the  same 
if  it  is  an  imagination  of  things  which  we  consider  in  the  same 
manner  with  reference  to  time  past  or  present,  and  accordingly  we 
may  equally  regard  things  as  contingent,  whether  they  be  refeiTed  to  a 
time  present,  past,  or  future.' 

'  Prop.  44. 


BODY  AND  MIND,  203 

This  passage  suggests  that  determinists  may  turn  the  tables 
on  the  maintainers  of  free-will  in  its  popular  sense  of  cause- 
less choice  by  their  own  favourite  device  of  an  appeal  to  the 
common  use  of  language.  It  is  said  that  determinism  reduces 
to  an  absurdity  our  ordinary  feelings  and  forms  of  speech  with 
regard  to  future  events :  but  it  is  overlooked  that  we  habitually 
apply  the  very  same  feelings  or  forms  of  speech  to  events 
which  at  the  time  are  unquestionably  determined.  Nay,  we  may 
believe  or  positively  know  that  they  are  determined,  so  long 
as  we  do  not  know  which  of  the  conceivable  determinations 
is  the  one  that  has  occurred.  While  we  await  the  disclosure 
of  a  parliamentary  division  list,  the  result  of  an  examination, 
the  return  of  casualties  in  an  action,  the  account  of  a  friend's 
arrival  in  a  distant  country,  or  a  hundred  other  things  no  less 
easily  called  to  mind,  our  emotions  of  curiosity,  hope,  and  fear 
are  but  little  allayed  by  the  thought  that  the  matter  itself  is 
already  decided  ;  for  the  source  of  those  emotions  is  not  in 
the  facts  but  in  our  ignorance  of  them,  and  we  wonder, 
speculate,  and  form  provisional  imaginations  of  what  we  shall 
do  in  this  or  that  event,  just  as  if  the  event  were  still  in  the 
future.  In  familiar  language  we  do  not  hesitate  to  couple 
hope  or  fear  with  the  present  and  even  the  past  tense.  '  I 
hope  you  have  enjoyed  yourself  ; '  '  I  fear  you  have  got  wet : ' 
it  were  mere  pedantry  to  replace  these  by  more  accurate 
phrases.  Again,  the  historian  who  investigates  the  actions 
and  motives  of  men  in  the  transactions  of  a  past  made  obscure 
by  distance,  by  the  conflict  of  evidence,  by  the  flattering  or 
violence  of  partisans,  or  by  the  machinations  of  wrongdoers,  is 
constantly  driven  to  deal  in  surmise,  contingency,  and  conjec- 
ture. Probably,  he  will  say,  this  was  the  course  of  events  ;  this 
was  perhaps  the  reason  for  such  or  such  a  singular  action; 
possibly  this  commonly  received  account  is  true,  notwith- 
standing the  difficulties  attaching  to  it  ;  now  and  then  he  will 
confess  (unless  he  is  a  historian  of  the  confident  sort,  who  has 
a  complete  explanation  for  everything)  that  with  his  existing 


y 


204  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

means  of  information  he  can  only  suspend  his  judgment. 
All  statements  of  this  kind  are  statements  about  our  imperfect 
knowledge  of  matters  which  in  truth  have  been  settled  once 
for  all.  The  fact  that  events  happened  somehow  and  are 
past  we  know ;  the  manner  of  it  we  do  not  know.  Yet  we 
constantly  speak  of  them  as  uncertain,  finding  it  useful  and 
indeed  necessary  to  do  so.  We  say,  for  example,  that 
Alcibiades  was  possibly  concerned  in  the  mutilation  of  the 
Hermae,  though  it  is  most  certain  that  either  he  was  or  he 
was  not. 

There  does  not  appear  to  be  anything  in  the  nature  of 
reason  or  of  language  that  should  compel  one  to  suppose  the 
notion  of  contingency  as  regards  future  events  to  be  anything 
else  than  what  it  undoubtedly  is  as  regards  past  and  present 
events  ;  that  is  to  say,  a  fiction  imposed  on  us  by  our  limited 
m.eans  of  knowledge.    /We  hope  and  fear,  not  because  the 
events  are  uncertain,  butbecause  we  are  uncertain  ;  nor  would 
a  general  belief  that  future  events  are  as  certain  as  past  ones, 
at  least  if  intelligently  held,  alter  the^expectations  or  conduct 
of  mankind  for  any  practical  purpose,  f  Assuredly  it  does  not^^ 
lead  to  the  indifference  of  fatalism :  for  a  little  consideration  ' 
will  show  that  fatalism  consists,  not  in  believing  all  events_to 
be  the  definite  results  of  definite  conditions,  but  in  holding 
that  the  course  of  events  is  overruled  by  an  arbitrary  power 
which  so  constantly. ba^,£5-dil  man's  forethought  as  to  make 
/^^  "']t'^rth  while  to  take  thought  for  the^  future.     Philoso- 
j^hical  determinism  is  the  opposite  of  this.    ;The  determinist 
holds,  in  accordance  with  common  experience,  that  the  de- 
1  iberate  action  of  men  is  among  the  conditions  that  shape  the 
course  of  events,  and   is  often  the  most  important  condition. 
If  particular  men  or  societies  are  foolish  enough  to  think  that 
their  own  acts  or  omissions  count  for  nothing,  that  is  a  con- 
dition too,  and  its  results  will  be  greatly  to  their  disadvantage. 
Determinism,  in  short,  if  only  one  applies  it  thoroughly,  leaves 
all  the  common  uses  of  life  exactly  where  they  were.     For  my 


( 


BODY  AND  MIND.  205 

own  part,  I  hold  that  the  choice  I  exercise  in  writing  these 
lines  is  determined  and  in  nowise  arbitrary.  But  the  sense 
of  power  involved  in  the  conscious  exercise  of  choice  is  none 
the  less  pleasurable  for  that.  The  schoolboy  who  runs,  leaps, 
or  swims  knows  mighty  little  of  the  complex  mechanism 
that  governs  every  action  of  his  body.  For  all  that  English 
schoolboys  could  learn  from  their  appointed  teachers  till 
within  a  few  years  past,  he  might  fancy  that  his  will  acted 
immediately  on  his  hands  and  feet.  The  student  of  riper 
years  who  seeks  recreation  in  active  exercise  well  knows  that 
this  is  not  so.  He  is  aware  that  he  cannot  lift  his  foot  from 
the  ground,  or  adjust  the  balance  of  his  oar,  or  shift  the  grasp  of 
his  ice-axe,  without  calling  into  play  an  apparatus  exceeding  in 
its  intricate  variety  the  staff  and  transport  of  a  modern  army. 
He  knows  that  innumerable  parts  must  work  harmoniously 
together  in  their  several  functions  to  produce  the  desired 
motion.  Yet  the  physical  delight  of  putting  forth  strength 
or  skill  is  no  less  in  the  man  than  in  the  boy.  This,  as 
regards  the  body,  is  matter  of  common  observation.  I  know 
not  why  it  should  be  otherwise  in  the  mind.  But  perhaps  a 
much  shorter  answer  should  sufficiently  meet  the  common 
objection  that  determinism  robs  life  of  its  interest ;  for  it  is 
the  experience  of  a  reasonable  number  of  persons  who  hold 
the  doctrine,  and  who  are  not  less  competent  than  other  men 
to  bear  witness  to  their  own  feelings,  that  it  does  nothing  of 
the  sort.  In  any  case,  it  is  time  to  return  to  Spinoza's  own 
exposition. 

The  mind,  he  says,  is  a  particular  and  determined  mode 
of  thought,  and  as  such  can  have  no  absolute  or  uncon-j 
ditioned  power  of  volition.  Its  state  at  a  given  moment,  to 
whatever  so-called  faculty  we  may  refer  it,  is  the  effect  of 
some  definite  cause,  which  itself  is  the  cft'ect  of  a  preceding! 
cause,  and  so  on  withQiii.£iui-'  The  supposed  faculties  of 
the  mind,  and  the  will  among  them,  are  abstract  terms  having 

'  Elh.  ii.  48. 


2o6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

a  merely  verbal  existence.  '  Understanding  and  will  have  the 
same  relation  to  this  and  that  idea,  or  this  and  that  volition, 
as  lapideity  to  this  and  that  stone,  or  man  to  Peter  and  Paul' 
Spinoza  does  not  mean  to  say  that  the  desire  which  begets 
will  is  not  a  real  and  individual  fact.  How  he  treats  desire 
/  we  shall  see  later  ;  here  he  explains  that  he  distinguishes 
will  from  desire,  and  regards  it  as,  in  the  abstract,  a  faculty, 
or,  in  the  concrete,  an  act  of  affirmation  or  negation,  or,  as  we 
should  now' say,  of  judgment.  This  appears  to  a  modern 
reader  to  be  a  needless  complication  of  his  case.  It  is 
coupled  with  the  doctrine  that  every  idea  involves  a  judg- 
ment,i  which,  if  we  take  idea  in  Spinoza's  larger  sense  as  in- 
cluding all  states  of  consciousness,  is  a  paradox,  and  if  we 
take  idea  in  the  restricted  sense  of  conception,  still  remains 
difficult  of  digestion.  Spinoza  gives  the  affirmation  that  the 
angles  of  a  triangle  are  together  equal  to  two  right  angles  as 
an  example  of  a  volition.  Most  people  would  deny  that 
there  is  any  volition  concerned  in  such  a  judgment.  What  is 
implied  in  Spinoza's  choice  of  such  an  example  is  that  in  his 
view  the  mind  is  quite  as  active  in  the  formation  of  a  neces- 
sar}'  inference  .as  in  fixing  on  one  conclusion  or  course  of 
action  out  of  several  which  may  appear  plausible.  And  who- 
ever admits  this  cannot  well  refuse  the  corollary  that  '  will 
and  understanding  are  one  and  the  same.'  In  like  manner 
perception  is  inseparable  from  judgment :  to  perceive  a  winged 
horse  is  to  affirm  that  a  horse  has  wings.  So  long  as  a  winged  ^ 
horse  or  anything  else  is  present  to  the  imagination,  and  no 
other  perception  is  present  which  contradicts  its  reality,  we 
shall  believe  in  the  real  existence  of  the  object.  This  is  the 
common  experience  of  dreams,  when  the  imagination  is  active 
and  unchecked.  And  thus,  if  the  objection  is  made  that  will 
differs  in  nature  from  understanding,  because  we  have  it  in  our 
free  choice  to  suspend  our  judgment  whether  we  shall  or  shall 
not  assent  to  a  given  perception   as  corresponding  to  reality, 

'  I'rop.  49,  and  Schol. 


BODY  AND  MIND. 


207 


the  answer  is  that  what  we  call  suspense  of  judgment^  is  our 
consciousness  that  the  given  perception  is  inadequate  ;  in 
other  words,  it  is  itself  a  perception  and  belongs  to  the  intel- 
lect. All  this,  it  must  be  confessed,  is  a  rather  barren  dis- 
cussion, and  at  this  day  serves  chiefly  to  show  with  what 
poverty  of  language,  both  in  extent  and  in  definition, 
psychology  had  to  labour  in  Spinoza's  time.  But  the 
manner  in  which  he  explains  the  strength  of  the  common 
notions  as  to  the  rel_atijoa_pfjninji_arid_bady^  of  which  the 
popular  doctrine  of  free-will  is  really  parcel,  is  of  lasting 
interest.  It  occurs  in  a  later  glace,^  but  it  will  be  convenient 
to  translate  part  of  it  here.  [,  After  giving  as  a  separate  pro- 
position the  doctrine  that  the  body  can  g^-Jve  rise  to  no 
operation  .pf  though i-  in  the  mind,  nor  the  mind  to  any 
phenomenon  of  motion  or  otherwise  in  the  body,  he  proceeds 
to  the  difficulties  of  common  sense  on  the  subject : — 

*  I  scarce  believe,  until  I  shall  have  assured  myself  of  it  by  ex- 
perience, that  men  can  be  brought  to  consider  this  matter  impartially  : 
so  firmly  are  they  persuaded  that  'tis  from  the  mere  decree  of  the 
mind  that  their  bodies  now  move,  now  are  at  rest,  and  perform  much 
else  that  flows  from  the  purewillandfaculty  of  invention  in  the  mind. 
Certainly  no  man  hath  yet  determined  what  are  the  powers  of  the 
body  :  I  mean  that  none  has  yet  learnt  from  exj^erience  what  the 
body  may  perform  by  mere  laws  of  nature,  considering  it  only  as  a 
material  thing,  and  what  it  cannot  do  without  the  mind's  determina- 
tion of  it.  For  nobody  has  known  as  yet  the  frame  of  the  body  so 
thoroughly  as  to  explain  all  its  operations  ;  not  to  say  that  in  brutes 
much  is  noted  which  doth  far  surpass  human  cunning,  and  that  men 
Avalking  in  their  sleep  often  perform,  so  sleeping,  that  which  they 
would  never  dare  Avaking  ;  which  is  proof  enough  that  the  body  may, 
merely  by  the  laws  of  its  own  constitution,  do  much  that  its  own 
mind  is  amazed  at.  Again,  there  is  none  can  tell  how  and  in  what 
manner  the  mind  moves  the  body,  what  measure  of  motion  it  can 
impart  to  it,  or  with  what  velocity.' 

To  say,  therefore,  that  a  particular  action  of  the  body  is 
caused  by  the  mind  is  only  a  grudging  confession  of  ignorance 

•  '  Eth.  iii.  2,  Schol. 


) 


w 


208  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

as  to  its  real  cause.  As  for  the  appeal  to  common  experience, 
it  cuts  both  ways.  If  the  body  is  helpless  without  the  mind, 
so  is  the  mind  subject  to  be  disabled  by  sleep,  and  otherwise 
limited  in  its  operation  by  bodily  conditions.  If  it  be  saidc' 
that  the  existence  of  material  works  of  art,  such  as  houses, 
pictures,  and  statues,  is  inexplicable  on  the  supposition  that 
the  human  body  is  governed  only  by  the  physical  laws  of 
its  constitution,  and  that  the  body  could  never  perform  such 
feats  if  it  were  not  guided  by  the  mind;  the  answer  is, -as 
before,  that  the  objector  knows  not  what  the  powers  of  the 
body  really  are.  Moreover,  the  human  body  itself  is  infi- 
nitely more  artificial  than  any  work  of  human  art.  Men  say 
they  have  experience  that  it  is  in  the  absolute  power  of  the 
mind  either  to  speak  or  to  keep  silence,  and  the  like  ;  to 
which  Spinoza  replies  that  if  it  were  indeed  as  much  in 
man's  power  to  be  silent  as  to  speak,  the  world  would  be 
much  happier.  The  argument  is  a  little  more  fully  illustrated 
in  a  letter  (Ep^_62},  which  is  partly  identical  with  the  passage 
in  hand. 

'  I  call  a  thing  free  if  it  exists  and  acts  merely  from  the  necessary 
laws  of  its  own  nature,  but  constrained  if  it  is  determined  by  some- 
thing else  to  exist  and  act  in  a  certain  determinate  way.     Thus  God 
exists  necessarily,  and  yet  freely,  because  he  exists  by  the  necessity  of 
his  own  nature  alone.     So  God  freely  understands  himself  and  every-  c 
thing  else,  because  it  follows  solely  from  the  necessity  of  his  own^ 
nature   that  he  must  understand  everything.     You  see  then  that  I 
make  freedom  consist  not  in  a  free  decision  of  the  will,  but  in  free 
necessity.  .  ,  . 

'  Imagine,  if  you  can.  that  a  stone,  while  its  motion  continues,  is 
conscious,  and  knows  that  so  far  as  it  can  it  endeavours  to  persist  in 
its  motion.  This  stone,  since  it  is  conscious  only  of  its  own  endeavour 
and  deeply  interested  therein  {minivie  indifferens),  will  believe  that  it 
is  perfectly  free  and  continues  in  motion  for  no  other  reason  than 
that  it  so  wills.  Now  such  is  this  freedom  of  man's  will  which  every 
one  boasts  of  possessing,  and  which  consists  only  in  this,  that  men 
are  aware  of  their  own  desires  and  ignorant  of  the  causes  by  which 
those  desires  are  determined.     So  an  infant  thinks  his  appetite  for 


;H 


t 


BODY  AND  MhYD.  209 

milk  is  free  ;  so  a  child  in  anger  thinks  his  will  is  for  revenge,  in  fear 
that  it  is  for  flight.  Again,  a  drunkard  thinks  he  speaks  of  his  free 
will  things  which,  when  sober,  he  would  fain  not  have  spoken.' 

That  which  we  call  choice  in  the  mind  is  in  truth  exactly 
correlated,  or  rather  identical,  with  some  determined  physical 
event  in  the  body.  Again,  it  must  be  conceded  that  our 
freedom  of  action  depends  on  memory  ;  we  must  remember 
a  particular  word,  for  example,  before  we  can  will  to  speak  or 
not  to  speak  it  ;  and  memory  is  not  subject  to  the  will.  At 
best,  therefore,  the  alleged  power  of  volition  can  be  exercised 
only  within  the  limits  fixed  by  the  range  of  memory, 

'  But  when  we  dream  of  speaking,  we  believe  ourselves  to  speak 
from  a  free  decision  of  the  mind,  and  yet  we  speak  not,  or  if  we  do, 
it  is  by  an  independent  motion  of  the  body.  We  dream,  again,  of 
doing  by  the  like  decision  sundry  things  which  as  waking  men  we 
dare  not ;  and  hereon  I  would  fain  know  if  there  be  in  the  mind  two 
sorts  of  decisions,  the  one  merely  fantastic  and  the  other  truly  free. 
But  if  we  choose  not  to  go  that  length  in  folly,  it  must  needs  be 
allowed  that  this  decision  of  the  mind  which  is  believed  to  be  free. 
is  not  in  truth  distinguishable  from  the  imagination  or  memory  pre- 
cedmg  it,  and  is  nothing  else  than  that  affirmation  which  an  idea,  in- 
sonmch  as  it  is  an  idea,  doth  of  necessity  include.  So  that  these 
decisions  of  the  mind  arise  therein  by  the  same  necessity  as  its  ideas 
of  really  existing  things.  And  they  who  believe  themselves  to  speak  \ 
or  keep  silence  or  do  aught  else  by  the  free  decision  of  their  minds 
are  men  dreaming  with  their  eyes  open,'  i  \ 

So  ends   this   characteristic    and  uncompromising  expo- 
sition, which  is  too  clear  to  need  much  commentary.    Spinoza 
seems   to    assume    rather   confidently  that    no   advocate    of       ^: 
free-will  would  go  so  far  as  to  maintain  that  there  is  a  real  '! 
operation  ofthat  excellent  faculty  in  dreaming.     As  a  matter  T 
of  pure  psychological  argument,  it  is   not  easy  to  see  what 
should  prevent  it.     But  the  doctrine  of  free-will  is  never,  so 
far  as  I  know,  maintained  on  a  purely  scientific  footing  :  it  is 
always  rested,  at  least  in  great  part,  on  the  supposed  necessity 


-n 


2IO  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

of  having  it  as  a  foundation  of  moral  responsibility.  There- 
fore a  disputant  who,  defending  free-will  on  the  usual  grounds, 
should  assert  that  free-will  is  really  exercised  in^reams, 
would  find  himself  in  an  awkward  position.  For  he  must 
admit  either  that  free-will  and  moral  responsibility  are  not 
inseparable,  or  that  we  are  morally  responsible  for  all  the 
crimes  and  follies  which  the  best  and  wisest  of  us,  as  common 
experience  abundantly  shows,  are  liable  to  commit  in  our 
dreams.  The  first  alternative  deprives  the  volitionist  of  his 
principal  interest  in  his  cause  ;  the  second  is  too  repugnant 
to  common  sense  to  be  entertained,  though  something  not 
unlike  it  was  held  by  St.  Augustine, 

Let  us  return  to  the  conclusion  of  the  Second  Part  of  the 
'  Ethics,'  where  Spinoza  sets  forth  the  advantages  of  the  phil- 
osophical doctrine  of  necessity.  It  gives  a  marked  foretaste  -> 
of  the  manner  in  which  the  practical  side  of  his  teaching 
coincides  with  that  of  the  Stoics.  The  attainment  of  happi- 
ness by  man  through  realizing  his  intimate  union  with  the 
whole  nature  of  things ;  the  distinction  between  things  in  our 
power  and  things  not  in  our  power  ;  the  avoidance  of  all  dis- 
turbing passions,  and  the  performance  of  social  duties  from 
rational  desire  for  the  common  good  :  all  these  points  occur 
in  the  paragraph  I  shall  now  translate,  and  all  are  not  only 
present  but  conspicuous  in  the  Stoic  theory  of  morals. 
Spinoza's  words  are  as  follows  : — 

'  It  remains  to  show  how  much  is  gained  for  the  uses  of  life  by  the 
knowledge  of  this  doctrine,  which  we  shall  easily  perceive  from  these 
considerations. 

'  First,  it  teaches  us  that  we  act  only  by  the  decree  of  God,  and  arc 
partakers  of  the  divine  nature,  and  that  it  proportion  as  we  are  more 
perfect  in  our  actions  and  more  advanced  in  the  understanding  of 
God.  Wherefore  this  doctrine,  besides  that  it  begets  an  absolute 
content  in  the  mind,  excels  also  in  this,  that  it  teaches  us  wherein  our 
highest  happiness  or  blessedness  doth  consist ;  that  is,  in  the  know- 
ledge of  God  only,  which  leadeth  us  to  do  only  such  things  as  be 
commended  by  love  and  duty.     Hence  we  clearly  understand  how 


BODY  AND  MIND.  211 

far  they  go  astray  from  a  right  judgment  of  virtue  who  look  to  be 
ilhistrated  by  God  with  extreme  rewards  for  virtue  and  perfect  actions, 
as  for  some  extreme  hardship  of  service  ;  as  if  virtue  and  the  service 
of  God  were  not  themselves  very  happiness  and  the  extreme  height 
of  freedom. 

'  Secondly,  it  teaches  us  how  to  carry  ourselves  as  concerning  the 
gifts  of  fortune  or  things  which  are  not  in  our  power,  I  mean  such 
things  as  depend  not  on  our  own  nature  ;  that  is,  that  we  should  with 
an  equal  mind  await  and  bear  either  countenance  of  fortune,  seeing 
that  all  things  follow  from  the  eternal  ordinance  of  God  with  the 
same  necessity  whereby  it  follows  from  the  nature  of  a  triangle  that 
its  three  angles  are  equal  to  two  right  angles. 

'  Thirdly,  this  doctrine  is  good  for  civil  conversation,  insomuch  as 
it  teaches  us  to  hold  no  man  in  hatred,  contempt,  or  derision,  and 
not  to  be  angered  or  envious  at  any  one.  Further,  because  it  teaches 
that  every  man  should  be  content  with  his  own  and  helpful  to  his  neigh- 
bour ;  not  from  womanish  pity,  favour,  or  superstition,  but  merely  at 
the  bidding  of  reason,  according  to  the  time  and  matter,  as  I  shall 
show  in  the  third  part.^ 

*  Lastly,  this  doctrine  is  of  no  small  profit  for  the  commonwealth 
in  that  it  shows  how  citizens  are  to  be  governed  and  led,  that  is,  not 
to  make  them  do  service,  but  to  cause  them  to  do  freely  whatsoever 
is  best.  And  herewith  I  have  finished  that  of  which  I  purposed  to 
treat  in  this  Scholium,  and  so  I  make  an  end  of  this  our  second  part  ; 
conceiving  that  therein  I  have  explained  the  nature  and  qualities  of 
the  human  mind  at  sufficient  length,  and  as  clearly  as  the  difficulty  of 
the  thing  admits  ;  and  that  from  that  which  I  have  delivered  many 
conclusions  may  be  drawn  of  excellent  use  and  very  necessary  to  be 
known,  as  in  the  sequel  shall  partly  appear.' 

With  the  second  book  of  the  '  Ethics '  the  general  part,  as 
we  may  call  it,  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  comes  to  an  end. 
The  rest  is  concerned  with  the  application  to  definite  pro- 
blems of  the  principles  already  laid  out.  Before  we  pass 
on  to  these  we  cannot  but  notice  the  one  extraordinary 
defect  which  is  conspicuous  in  Spinoza's  psychology.  One 
of  the  first  things  we  expect  from  a  psychologist  nowadays 

'  Or  rather  the  fourth.     It  appears  from  Spinoza's  letters  that  the  third  and 
fourth  part  of  the  Ethics  were  originally  meant  to  form  one. 

P  2 


212  SPINOZA:  HIS   LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Is  a  systematic  account  of  the  processes  of  perception  and 
knowledge.  BuJ  Spinoza  does  not  appear  to  have  any  theory 
of  perception  at  all.  He  assumes,  as  we  all  assume,  that 
there  is  some  kind  of  correspondence  between  sensations  in 
consciousness  and  things  in  the  external  world.  But  of  the 
nature  of  that  correspondence  he  has  very  little  to  say.  We 
find  the  important  proposition,  which  had  already  been  given 
by  Descartes,  that  sensation,  being  a  function  of  the  organism, 
depends  not  simply  on  the  external  object,  but  on  the  organ- 
ism as  affected  by  the  object  ;  we  find  also  a  marked  appre- 
ciation of  the  advantages  to  be  derived  from  studying  the 
phenomena  of  sensation  and  thought  under  their  physiolo- 
gical aspect.  We  do  not  find,  however,  any  explicit  hand- 
Hng  of  the  problems  which  are  started  by  the  old  Platonic 
question :  What  is  Knowledge .-'  The  omission  may  be 
ascribed  to  several  reasons.  First,  the  aim  of  Spinoza's 
treatise  is  not  to  give  a  complete  system  of  philosophy  or 
psychology,  but  to  show  the  way  to  human  happiness.  The 
philosophical  introduction,  elaborate  as  it  appears,  is  sub- 
ordinate to  the  ethical  purpose.  Next,  these  questions  were 
not  prominent  in  Spinoza's  time.  They  were  put  in  the  front 
rank  of  discussion  by  Locke,  Spinoza's  contemporary  by  birth, 
but  in  philosophy  standing  wholly  apart  from  him  and  be- 
longing to  another  generation.  And  I  conceive  that  the 
psychological  problem  of  knowledge  was  obscured  to  Spinoza's 
own  mind  by  that  ambiguous  and  distracting  use  of  the  word 
idea  which  has  already  been  more  than  once  noticed.  Not 
that  his  metaphysical  principles  are  in  themselves  unable  to 
furnish  means  of  dealing  with  the  problem  :  on  the  contrary 
they  very  much  simplify  it.  The  puzzle  of  sensation,  when 
considered  in  the  usual  way,  is  that  there  is  a  relation  between 
the  heterogeneous  terms  of  consciousness  and  motion.  Some- 
thing happens  in  my  optic  nerves,  physiology  may  or  may 
not  be  able  to  say  exactly  what,  and  thereupon  I  see.  Can 
my  sensation  of  sight  be  said  to  resemble  the  thing  seen,  or 


BODY  AND  MIND.  213 

the  images  on  my  two  retinae,  or  the  motions  in  the  optic 
nerves,  and  if  so,  in  what  sense  ?  These  questions  are 
essentially  insoluble  on  the  common  supposition  that  body 
and  mind  are  distinct  substances  or  orders  in  nature.  If  body 
artd  mind  are  really  the  same  thing,  the  knot  is  cut,  or  rather 
vanishes.  The  problem  of  making  a  connexion  between  the 
inner  and  the  outer  series  of  phenomena  becomes  a  purely 
scientific  one.  It  is  no  longer  a  metaphysical  paradox,  but 
the  combination  of  two  methods  of  observing^  the  same  facts, 
or  facts  belonging  to  the  same  order :  and  the  science  of 
physiological  psychology  can  justify  itself  on  philosophical 
grounds,  besides  making  good  its  claims  by.  the  practical  test 
of  results.  But  the  people  who  cry  materialism  at  everything 
they  disagree  with  or  cannot  understand  Will  doubtless  cry 
out  that  this  also  is  materialism.  And  they  are  very  welcome 
to  any  good  it  can  do  them. 


214  SPINOZA:   HIS   LIFE   AND   PHILOSOPHY. 


k 


CHAPTER   VII. 

THE   NATURE   OF   MAN, 

Behold,  I  show  you  truth  !     Lower  than  hell, 
Higher  than  heaven,  outside  the  utmost  stars, 
Farther  than  Brahm  doth  dwell, 

Before  beginning,  and  without  an  end, 

As  space  eternal  and  as  surety  sure, 
Is  fixed  a  power  divine  which  moves  to  good, 

Only  its  laws  endure. 

Out  of  the  dark  it  wrought  the  heart  of  man. 
Out  of  dull  shells  the  pheasant's  pencilled  neck  ; 

Ever  at  toil,  it  brings  to  loveliness 
All  ancient  wrath  and  wreck. 

It  slayeth  and  it  saveth,  nowise  moved 

Except  unto  the  working  out  of  doom  ; 
Its  threads  are  Love  and  Life  ;  and  Death  and  Pain 

The  shuttles  of  its  loom. 

Edwin  Arnold,  The  Light  of  Asia. 

Spinoza's  inquiry  concerning  the  Passions,  which  forms  the 
Third  Part  of  the  Ethics,  is  best  introduced  in  his  own 
words. 

'THE  PREFACE. 

'  Most  of  those  who  have  writ  concerning  the  passions  and  man's 
way  of  Ufe  appear  as  if  they  handled  not  such  things  as  belong  to 
nature,  and  follow  her  common  laws,  but  things  outside  nature  ;  in- 
somuch that  they  conceive  man  to  be  in  nature  as  a  kingdom  with- 
in a  kingdom.  For  they  suppose  that  man  rather  confounds  than 
follows  the  order  of  nature,  and  has  an  absolute  power  over  his  own 
actions,  being  no  otherwise  determined  than  by  himself     As  con- 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN,  215 

cerning  men's  weakness  and  unsteadfastness,  they  attribute  these  not 
to  the  common  power  of  nature,  but  to  some  defect  in  the  nature  of 
man  ;  which  therefore  they  bewail,  mock,  despise,  or  (which  for  the 
most  part  happens)  vituperate  ;  and  he  passes  for  the  best  prophet 
who  can  most  eloquently  and  shrewdly  rebuke  the  human  mind  for 
its  weakness.  Not  that  most  renowned  authors  have  been  wanting  (to 
whose  labour  and  ingenuity  we  do  confess  ourselves  much  indebted) 
who  have  written  much  and  excellently  on  the  right  way  of  life,  and 
have  given  to  mankind  precepts  full  of  wisdom.  But  none  of  these, 
to  my  knowledge,  hath  determined  the  nature  and  strength  of  the 
passions,  or  what  on  the  other  part  the  mind  can  do  in  restraining 
them.  I  well  know  that  the  admirable  Descartes  (though  he  supposed 
the  mind  to  have  an  absolute  power  over  its  own  actions)  yet  en- 
deavoured both  to  explain  human  passions  by  their  immediate  causes, 
and  to  show  the  road  whereby  the  mind  could  come  to  a  perfect 
mastery  thereof  But,  in  my  judgment,  he  hath  shown  nothing  but 
the  exceeding  sharpness  of  his  own  wit,  as  I  shall  prove  in  the 
fitting  place.  But  to  return  to  those  who  choose  rather  to  abhor  or 
deride  the  passions  and  actions  of  men  than  to  understand  them  ; 
this  sort  will  no  doubt  be  amazed  that  I  go  about  to  treat  of  human 
defects  and  follies  after  the  geometrical  manner,  and  would  fain 
demonstrate  by  certain  reasoning  that  which,  as  they  so  loudly 
protest,  is  against  all  reason,  idle,  absurd,  and  abominable.  But 
such  is  my  way.  Nothing  happens  in  nature  that  can  be  ascribed  to  o 
a  defect  of  nature ;  for  nature  is  always  and  everywhere  one  and  the 
same,  and  her  virtue  and  power  of  operation  is  the  same  :  that  is,  the 
laws  and  rules  of  nature,  according  to  which  all  things  are  made  and 
change  from  one  form  into  another,  are  everywhere  and  always  the 
same  ;  and  therefore  there  should  be  but  one  and  the  same  way  of 
understanding  things  of  whatsoever  kind,  to  wit,  by  the  universal  laws 
and  rules  of  nature.  Thus  the  passions  of  hatred,  anger,  envy  and 
the  like,  when  considered  in  themselves,  follow  from  the  like  necessity 
and  virtue  of  nature  as  all  other  individual  things ;  and  accordingly 
they  obey  fixed  causes,  whereby  they  may  be  understood,  and  have 
their  fixed  properties,  equally  worthy  of  our  knowledge  as  the  pro- 
perties of  any  other  thing  in  the  mere  contemplation  whereof  we  take 
delight.  I  shall  treat  therefore  of  the  nature  and  strength  of  the 
passions,  and  the  power  of  the  mind  over  them,  by  the  same  method 
as  I  have  treated  of  God  and  the  mind  in  the  foregoing  parts  ;  and  I 
shall  consider  human  actions  and  desires  after  the  same  sort  as  if  the 
inquiry  were  concerned  with  lines,  surfaces,  or  solids.' 


2i6  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

This  passage  throws  light,  among  other  things,  on  the 
true  significance  of  Spinoza's  geometrical  method.  It  is  noto 
that  he  thinks  the  geometrical  method  of  exposition  an  in- 
fallible engine  of  discovery  ;  but  he  is  determined  to  conduct 
the  investigation  of  human  nature  in  a  purely  scientific  spirit, 
and  he  chooses  the  geometrical  form  as  the  most  perfect  and 
striking  type  of  scientific  method.  The  scientific  value  of  his 
results  in  this  part  of  his  work  is  not  only  recognized  by 
modern  criticism,  but  may  be  described  as  the  one  point  on 
which  almost  all  expounders  and  critics  have  agreed.  Spi- 
noza's account  of  the  passions  is  universally  spoken  of  as  his 
masterpiece.  I  shall  quote  only  one  scientific  testimony, 
which  has  a  peculiar  value  as  coming  from  a  leading  authority 
in  physiology,  being  given  in  the  course  of  his  proper  scientific 
work,  and  acted  upon  by  him  in  an  unmistakable  manner. 
This  witness  is  Johannes  Miiller. 

'  With  regard  to  the  relations  of  the  passions  to  one  another,  apart 
from  their  physiological  conditions,  it  is  impossible  to  give  any  better 
account  than  that  which  Spinoza  has  laid  down  with  unsurpassed 
mastery.  In  the  following  statement  I  shall  therefore  confine  myself 
to  giving  the  propositions  of  Spinoza  on  that  subject.' ' 

And  this  he  proceeds  to  do  without  further  criticism  or 
comment.  We  shall  find  that  his  view  is  indirectly  con- 
firmed by  the  work  of  more  recent  inquirers  in  both  natural 
science  and  psychology. 

The  first  spring  of  action,  common   to   man  with  every  o 
creature,  is  self-preservation.     We  must  not  say  the  desire  of 
self-preservation,  for  desire,  as  conceived  by  Spinoza,  comes 
later.     His  leading  propositions  on  the   subject  are  thus  ex- 
pressed : — 

'  Physiologie  dcs  Menschen,  ii.  543.  Dr.  Diihring's  remarks  on  this  are 
curious  :  '  In  neuester  Zeit  hat  auch  ein  Physiolog  von  einigem  Professorruf 
Johannes  Miiller,  ungeachtet  seiner  engherzigen,  religios  und  politisch  riicklautigen 
Denkweise,  von  seinem  Standpunkt  aus  die  von  Spinoza  gelieferte  Slatik  der 
Leidenschaften  flir  so  gelungcn  erachtet, '  &c. 


THE   NATURE   OF  MAN.  217 

'  Each  individual  thing,  so  fir  as  in  it  Hes,  endeavours  to  persist 
in  its  own  being. 

The  effort  wherewith  everything  endeavours  to  persist  in  its  own 
being  is  nothing  else  than  that  thing's  being  what  it  is'  (praeter  ipsius 
rei  actualem  essentiani). ' 

In  a  former  chapter  we  traced  this  fundamental  proposition 
from  its  Cartesian  use  as  a  physical  axiom  or  law  of  motion 
through  Spinoza's  repetition  and  extension  of  it  in  the  ex- 
position of  Descartes  which  was  his  first  published  work.  We  0 
also  noticed  that  in  a  more  extensive  application  it  was 
current  in  the  post-Aristotelian  schools  of  Greek  philosophy, 
and  notably  among  the  Stoics,  In  the  middle  ages,  too,  it 
appears  to  have  been  familiar  in  a  scholastic  form.  Spinoza, 
hovvever,  probably  knew  nothing  of  its  earlier  history  and 
meaning,  and  certainly  did  not  concern  himself  with  them. 
He  took  the  statement  from  Descartes  as  a  general  law  ofc 
physics  ;  and,  as  he  extended  without  limit  the  scientific 
view  of  the  world  propounded  by  Descartes,  so  he  extended 
the  range  of  those  principles  from  which  the  Cartesian  system 
undertook  to  explain  all  sensible  phenomena,  or  at  least  to 
show  that  they  were  explicable. 

It  is  important  to  bear  in  mind  the  interpretation  and 
warning  given  by  Spinoza  himself  The  statement  that 
everything  endeavours  to  persist  in  its  own  being  might  seem 
to  imply  some  notion  that  the  effort  or  tendency  to  self-pre- 
servation is  a  mysterious  power  implanted  in  things  and 
antecedent  to  their  existence.  Such  a  power  has  been  con- 
ceived in  both  ancient  and  modern  philosophies.  Varieties  of 
it  are  the  karma  of  Buddhism,  which  performs  the  singular 
feat  of  keeping  up  a  chain  of  transmigration  when  there  is  no 
soul  to  transmigrate  ;  -  the  supposed  ultimate  activity  sym- 
bolically called  Will  by  Schopenhauer  ;  and  the  more  ela- 
borate version  of  it  given  as  the  Unconscious  in  Hartmann's 

'  Eth.  iii.  pr.  6,  7  ;  cf.  Cogit.  Met.  pt.  i.  cap.  7,  §  8. 
^  Rhys  Davids,  Buddhism,  p.  loi. 


2i8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

system.  But  Spinoza  most  carefully  excludes  all  assump- 
tions of  this  kind.  The  self-preserving  effort  is  nothing  else  o 
than  the  thing's  being  what  it  is.  Whatever  the  thing  in 
question  may  be,  the  mere  fact  of  its  existence  means  that  it 
must  be  reckoned  with.  Great  or  small,  there  it  is,  and  you 
cannot  get  it  out  of  the  way  without  doing  work  upon  it 
Destruction  is  only  a  name  for  processes  of  change  which  areo 
peculiarly  conspicuous  to  our  senses  or  important  in  their 
results.  Every  change  implies  motion,  and  every  motion 
implies  work,  and  signifies  resistance  overcome.  This  resist-o 
ance,  as  we  call  it  from  the  point  of  view  of  the  worker  over- 
coming it  from  the  outside,  is  persistence  or  *  effort  of  self- 
preservation  '  if  we  shift  the  adjustment  of  the  mind's  eye,  and 
fix  the  centre  of  the  field  of  imagination  in  the  thing  operated 
upon.  The  use  of  the  word  effort  {conattis)  belongs  to  the- 
realistic  habits  of  scientific  language  in  Spinoza's  time.  He 
speaks  of  effort  in  this  relation,  just  as  long  afterwards  mathe- 
maticians were  accustomed  to  speak  of  a  force  or  power  of 
inertia,  which  is  indeed  the  same  thing  in  its  simplest  physical 
aspect.  It  might  be  rash  to  affirm  that  even  now  vis  inertice 
and  other  terms  of  the  same  kind  do  not  survive  in  books 
which  may  be  put  into  the  hands  of  students.  But  at  that 
time  the  usage  went  farther.  Not  only  inertia  was  a  force, 
but  velocity  was  spoken  of  as  the  cause  of  a  body's  changing 
its  place.  Nay,  in  our  own  time  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer  has 
called  momentum  the  cause  of  motion.  We  need  not  be 
surprised,  then,  that  elsewhere  Spinoza  speaks  of  this  self- 
preserving  endeavour  as  a  force  (vis  qua  unaquaeque  [res]  in 
existendo  perseverat).'  In  the  case  of  living  creatures  heo 
identifies  it  with  life.  In  the  less  complex  relations  of  the^ 
material  world  it  would  appear  (as  we  have  just  seen)  in  the 

'  Eth.  ii.  45,  Schol.,  with  which  cf.  Cogit.  Met.  pt.  ii.  cap.  6,  §  3  ;  but  he 
there  says,  '  Ilia  vis  a  rebus  ipsis  est  di versa,'  which  is  contradicted  not  only  by 
the  Ethics,  but  quite  as  strongly  by  a  passage  which  stands  earlier  in  the  same 
work  (pt.  i.  c.  6,  §§  8,  9).  I  have  already  suggested  that  the  Cogitata Metaphysial 
may  be  made  up  of  notes  written  at  various  dates. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  219 

fundamental  properties  of  matter — inertia,  mass,  and  impene- 
trability. But  the  fact  now  assumed  as  ultimate  for  ordinary- 
scientific  purposes,  that  every  atom  of  every  element  succeeds 
in  preserving  itself,  would  in  Spinoza's  view  be  no  more  than 
a  striking  illustration.  The  conatiis  is  equally  present  in  the 
most  unstable  as  in  the  most  stable  of  combinations.  A 
molecule  of  water  endeavours,  in  the  peculiar  sense  here  ex- 
plained, not  to  be  decomposed  ;  and  not  less  so,  while  it  holds 
together,  does  the  molecule  of  some  of  those  transitory  com- 
pounds which  explode  at  a  touch  or  vibration. 

It  will  perhaps  help  us  to  understand  Spinoza's  meaning 
if  we  invert  the  order  of  his  terms.  Instead  of  considering 
whether  things  can  be  said  to  exercise  a  self-preserving  effort, 
let  us  ask  ourselves  what  we  mean  by  a  thing.'  The  question 
is  not  as  easy  as  it  seems  ;  yet  an  answer  may  be  given  in 
few  words.  We  take  it  from  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer :  exist- 
ence, he  tells  us,  means  persistence.  A  thing  is  a  group  of 
phenomena  which  persists.  Herein  is  its  individuality,  its 
title  to  be  counted  apart  from  the  surrounding  medium.  We 
shall  find  that  persistence  for  an  appreciable  time,  in  a  manner 
obvious  to  sense,  and  against  appreciable  external  force,  is 
the  test  applied  by  the  unconscious  philosophizing  of  language. 

The  first  requisite  of  a  tJmig  is  that  it  should  be  appa- 
rently continuous  in  itself  and  not  continuous  with  things 
outside  it.  It  must  be  definite,  or  we  should  not  want  to 
name  it  ;  still  more  must  it  be  persistent,  or  we  could  not 
name  it  at  all.  What  is  more,  the  persistence  must  be  con- 
ceived as  depending  on  the  thing  itself,  and  not  as  a  pre- 
carious result  of  external  conditions.  Take  a  cubical  vessel 
full  of  water.  The  vessel  is  beyond  question  a  thing.  Is 
the  water  also  a  thing }  Every  molecule  of  it  is  assuredly 
represented  as  a  real  thing  in   the  duly  trained  imagination, 

'  Spinoza  gives  a  physical  definition  in  Cartesian  terms  of  unum  corpus  size 
individuum  in  Part  ii.  of  the  Ethics  (excursus  after  Schol.  to  Pr.  13).  But  it  is 
not  exactly  to  the  present  purpose,  nor  is  it  very  lucid  to  the  modern  reader. 


220  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

though  it  cannot  be  separately  observed.  But  the  body  of  water 
is  not  regarded  as  a  thmg  either  by  a  scientific  or  an  unscien- 
tific observer.  It  is  sensibly  continuous,  and  it  is  persistent  so 
long  as  it  is  confined  by  the  walls  of  the  vessel  ;  but  it  will 
persist  no  longer.  When  the  external  restraint  is  removed  it 
will  flow  away,  assume  other  forms,  and  be  dispersed.  We 
refuse  it  the  name  of  a  thing  because  it  is  manifestly  held 
together  only  by  external  forces.  Take  a  cubic  inch  of  water 
inside  this  vessel,  or  a  cubic  foot  of  air  in  the  atmosphere: 
these  again  are  not  things  in  common  speech,  and  for  the  like 
reasons.  Cases  may  be  put,  however,  so  as  to  present  all 
degrees  of  doubt.  For  example,  is  a  pile  of  cannon-balls  a 
thing }  More  work  is  required  to  dislodge  one  of  the  shot 
than  to  sever  or  destroy  many  things  of  undoubted  reality,  if 
we  may  use  the  term  in  a  strictly  scholastic  sense  ;  and  the 
pile  is  not  less  continuous  to  the  eye  than  many  a  rough  stone 
wall  or  cairn  which,  like  itself,  is  kept  together  merely  by 
friction  and  gravity.  Nevertheless,  while  nobody  would 
hesitate  to  speak  of  the  wall  or  cairn  as  a  thing,  I  doubt 
whether  any  one  would  so  speak  of  the  pile  of  shot,  unless  as 
an  object  confusedly  seen  in  the  distance.  I  conceive  that 
here  we  are  determined  by  considerations  of  human  use  and 
intention.  The  normal  use  of  stones  is  to  be  built  into  walls, 
and  the  possible  uses  of  the  individual  stones  are  too  trifling  to 
be  much  thought  of.  Cannon-balls  are  made  to  be  separately 
fired  off,  and  the  pile  is  in  itself  of  no  use  whatever.  In  the 
case  of  the  wall  or  cairn  the  parts  are  there  for  the  sake  of  the 
whole,  and  are  merged  in  it :  in  the  case  of  the  pile  of  shot 
the  whole  is  there  for  the  sake  of  the  parts.  Hence  we 
regard  the  heap  of  stones  as  meant  for  one  permanent  thing, 
and  the  heap  of  shot  as  meant  for  a  provisional  arrangement  of 
many  things.  In  fine,  the  conception  of  individual  things  as 
such  is  an  affair  of  our  perceptions,  and  to  some  extent  of  our 
convenience.  That  such  was  Spinoza's  view  is  pretty  mani- 
fest from  what  he  says  in  various  places  in  the  First  and 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  221 

Second  Parts  of  the  Ethics,  and  this  goes  to  support  the  read- 
ing now  offered  of  his  principle  of  self-preservation. 

So  understood,  the  principle  is  simple  enough.     How  then 
does  Spinoza  connect  it  with  the  world  of  life  and  action  .''  or 
what    light    can  it  throw    on   the    intricate    play    of  human 
passions  .-*     The  connexion  is  made  out  by  affirming  that  the  o 
impulse  or  desire  of  self-preservation  which  we  know  in  our"^ 
own  feeling  is  a  special  manifestation  of  the  universal  principle 
involved    in    existence    itself.       The    mind    '  endeavours    to 
persist  in  its  being  with  a  certain  undetermined  duration,  and  ' 
is  conscious  of  this  its  endeavour.' '     Such  endeavour,  consi- 
dered with  regard  to  the  mind  alone,  is  called  will  ;  consi- 
dered with  regard  to  mind  and   body  together,  it   is   called 
appetite  ;  '  which  is  nothing  else  than  the  very  being  of  the 
man,   from    whose    nature   those  things  of  necessity  follow 
which  make  for  his  preservation  ;  and  thus  the  man  is  deter- 
mined to  the  doing  of  such  things.     Then  betwixt  appetiteo 
and  desire  there  is  no  difference,  save  that  for  the  most  part 
desire  is  ascribed  to  men  in  so  far  as  they  be  conscious  of 
their  appetite  ;  and  therefore  it  may  be  thus  defined,  that  is 
to  say  :  desire  is  appetite  ivitJi  consciousness  thereof.     From  all » 
which  it  appears  that  we  have  not  endeavour,  will,  appetite, 
or  desire  for  anything,  because  we  deem  it  good  ;  but  con- 
trariwise deem  a  thing  good,  because  we  have  an  endeavour, 
will,  appetite,  or  desire  for  it.' 

Whether  this  bold  and  far-reaching  thought  of  Spinoza's 
can  be  justified  in  its  whole  extent  I  do  not  venture  to  say. 
But  I  entertain  no  doubt  that,  after  all  possible  deductions,  it 
contains  profound  and  vital  truth.  It  seems  probable  that 
the  extreme  complexity  and  the  late  development  of  distinct 
consciousness,  and  consequently  of  the  emotions  as  they  are 
known  in  the  adult  experience  of  mankind,  were  underrated 
by  Spinoza.  It  may  be  that  they  were  very  much  under- 
rated,  though    we    have    already    seen   that    the    composite 

'  Eth.  iii.  9,  and  Schol.  kA.-^'.  le^  kMX*/  ^ 


222  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE   AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

character  of  mind  was  most  clearly  asserted   by  him.     He 
appears  to  jump  from  unconscious  organic  processes — which, 
let  us  again  repeat  it,   are   in  his  view   mental    as    well    as 
material,  or  rather  both  in  one — to  the  facts  of  vivid   con- 
sciousness.    The  love  of  life  in  man  is  more  than  an  organic 
feeling  ;  the  finished  ideas  of  memory   and   expectation,  and 
even  the  highly  wrought  conceptions  of  our  ethical  and  social 
nature,  have  their  part  in  it.     And  in  our  active  consciousness 
these  more  refined  elements  are   predominant.     But  in  ihe 
main  it  is  enough  for  Spinoza's  purpose  that  the  organic  feel- 
ing is  there  ;  and  that  such  a  feeling  is  in  truth  deeply  rooted 
in  us  is    a    proposition  which    we    need    not  waste  time  in 
establishing.      We    have    already    called    in     Mr.     Herbert 
Spencer  to  help  us  to  a  modern  reading  of  Spinoza's  thought. 
We  shall  now  for  a  like  purpose  appeal  to  his  definition  of  life, 
which  is  especially  valuable  as  an  interpretation   of  scientific 
results  framed  in  perfect  independence  of  Spinoza's  work,  and 
proceeding  on  different  lines. 

According  to  this  definition,  life  is  '  the  continuous  adjust- 
ment of  internal  relations  to  external  relations  ;'  it  '  consists 
in  maintenance  of  inner   actions  corresponding  with  outer 
actions.'     Now  this  adjustment  or  maintenance  is  precisely 
what  Spinoza  means  by  a  thing's  persistence  in  its  own  being. 
The  organism  endeavours  to  persist  in  the  face  of  external 
conditions,  converting  them  to  its  use  when  it  can,  or  resisting 
them  at  need  ;  and  the  success  of  this  endeavour  is  life.     It  is 
observed  by  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer  himself  that  the  definition 
in  this  form  is  too  wide  ;  but,  to  whatever  extent  this  may  be 
a  defect  for  the  purposes  of  natural  history  or   biology,  from 
Spinoza's  point  of  view  it  is  a  merit.    The  correlation  of  mind 
and  matter  being  universal,  and   all  things  endowed  with  life 
in  various  degrees,  philosophy  is  not  concerned  to  draw  a  line 
anywhere  to  mark  where  life  begins.     Philosophically  speak- 
ing, the  attempt  to  draw  one  is  illusory  ;  and  it  is  a  question 
whether  science  itself  may  not  ere  long  bring  us  the   same 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  223 

report.     We  may  confine  ourselves  for  the  present,  however, 
to  the  undoubted  manifestations  of  life.     Spinoza  does   not 
profess  to  give  a  particular  account  of  nature,  or  even  the 
whole  of  animated  nature,  but  of  man.     As  regards  life  in  its 
common  acceptation,  it  will  be  seen  that  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer 
takes  in  a  factor  of  great  importance  which  is  not  marked  by- 
Spinoza.     He  speaks  of  continuous  adjustment,  thus  implying 
that  external  relations  are  constantly  changing  and  requiring 
adjustments  to  be  effected.     Nature  commands  the  adjust- 
ment under  the  penalty  of  extinction.     Now  the  striving  of 
every  creature  to  keep  its  own  nature  in  harmony  with  the 
world  around  it  is  the  fundamental  fact  whose  consequences 
are   traced    in   the   modern    doctrine   of  evolution.     Natural 
history,  as  Mr.  Darwin  and  Mr.  Spencer  have  taught  us  to 
see,  is  the  history  of  the  never-ceasing  effort  of  individuals 
and  races   to    maintain    a    certain    correspondence    between 
the  organism  and  its  environment.     The  nearer  this  corre- 
spondence approaches  to  completeness,  the  more  perfect  and 
secure    is   the    existence    of    the    individual   and    the   kind. 
Spinoza  pointed  to  the  law  of  persistence,  but  could  not  trace 
its  working.     We  now  know  that  in  operation  it  becomes  a 
law  of  development.     Older  by  countless  ages  than  conscious  o 
desire,  older  than  anything  to  which  we  now  grant  the  name 
of  life,  the  primeval  and  common   impulse — 'the  will  to  live, 
the  competence  to  be' — is  at  length  in  the  sight  of  all  men,  as 
it  was  for  Spinoza's  keener  vision,  the  root  of  all  action  and  of 
all  that  makes  the  world  alive.     Not  that  we  claim  Spinoza 
as  a  forerunner  of  the  theory    of  evolution.       He   had    no 
materials  for  anticipating  it ;  and  even  if  he  had  seemed  to 
prophesy  it,  the  prophecy  would   have  been   a  guess   in  the 
dark.     His  merit  is  rather  to  have  abstained,  with  a  singular 
philosophical  tact  or  instinct,  from  any  prematurely  ambitious 
construction.     As  his  work  stands,  one   does  not  see  that  on  ^ 
the  face  of  it  his  principle   of  self-conservation   is  sufficiently 
connected  with  the  real  world  :  there  is  a  void  space  between 


224  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND    PHILOSOPHY. 

the  idea  and  the  facts.  But  one  also  sees  that  the  required 
connexion  is  wonderfully  supplied  by  Mr.  Darwin.  The  gap 
has  been  left  open  at  exactly  the  right  place,  and  Spinoza 
had  the  wisdom  to  leave  it  open  rather  than  fill  it  up  in- 
adequately, and  the  courage  to  stand  by  the  idea  with  such 
light  as  he  had. 

The  practical  value  of  Spinoza's  analysis  of  the  passions 
is,  however,  to  a  great  extent  independent  of  the  general 
axiom  from  which  he  starts.  All  that  is  really  necessary  to 
be  granted  is  that  man  has  the  impulse  or  instinct  of  self- 
preservation,  and  desires  power  and  fulness  of  life  :  and  this 
much  it  would  need  some  boldness  to  dispute,  however  the 
fact  itself  may  be  explicable.  Let  us  see  how  Spinoza 
reaches  the  cardinal  definitions  of  Pleasure  and  Pain  ;  car-c 
dinal  because  with  him  Pleasure,  Pain,  and  Desire  are  the 
primary  elements  of  which,  according  to  the  variety  of  objects 
exciting  them,  all  human  passions  are  compounded.  It  is 
stated  as  a  direct  consequence  from  the  correspondence  of 
body  and  mind  that  '  whatsoever  increases  or  diminishes,  helps 
or  hinders,  the  active  power  (agendi  potentiam)  of  our  body  ; 
the  idea  thereof  likewise  increases  or  diminishes,  helps  or 
hinders,  the  sentient  power  (cogitandi  potentiam)  of  our 
mind.'  '  Thus  we  see,'  adds  the  Scholium,  '  that  the  mind 
may  undergo  great  variations,  and  pass  now  to  a  greater,  now 
to  a  lesser  perfection  ;  which  effects  explain  to  us  the  .states 
of  pleasure  and  pain.  Vty  pleasure  I  shall  therefore  hereafter 
understand  an  affection  whereby  the  mind  passes  to  a  greater 
perfection  ;  and  by  pain  an  affection  whereby  it  passes  to  a 
lesser  perfection.'  •  Here  again  there  is  a  singular  coincidence 
with  modern  scientific  speculation.  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer  is 
led,  on  the  one  hand  by  the  evidence  of  the  actual  conditions 
of  pleasure  and  pain  in  their  most  conspicuous  and  regular 
manifestations,  on  the  other  hand  by  deduction  from  the 
hypothesis   of    evolution,    to    conclude    that    '  pains   arc   the 

'   Kth.  iii.    II. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  225 

correlativ'es    of    actions    injurious    to    the    organism,    while 
pleasures   are   the    correlatives  of  actions  conducive    to    its 
welfare.'     But  an  action  or  event  conducive  to  the  welfare  of 
the  organism  is  precisely  what   Spinoza  means  by  '  transition 
to  a  greater  perfection  ; '  conversely,  an  action  injurious  to  the 
organism  is  in   Spinoza's   language  a  transition   to   less  per- 
fection.    Pleasure  marks  the  raising,  pain  the  lowering,  of  the  0      ) 
vital  energies,  and  consequently  the  advance  or  depression  of 
the  creature  in  the  scale  of  being,  to  a  corresponding  extent      \ 
and  in  so    far   as   the  particular  event    is   concerned.     The      / 
results  of  the  philosopher  who  still  passes  for  a  mere  dog- 
matist agree  in  their  full    extent    with    those    of   the    latest 
inquirer    working    by    induction  from   the    facts  of  biology, 
Spinoza's  definition,  it  will  be   seen,   implies  that  pleasure  is 
not  only  normally  but  invariably  beneficial  in  itself,  and  pain 
hurtful.     Not  that  the  normal  indications  of  pain  and  pleasure 
may  not  be  disturbed,  so  as  to  make  them  in  particular  cases 
blind  or  worse  than  blind  guides.     Experience  of  this  kind  is 
only  too  common  ;  and  the  explanation  of  it  is  briefly  touched 
on  by  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer,  and   has  been   more  lately  con- 
sidered by  others.     But  the  pleasure  which  leads  to  ultimate 
harm  is  yet  not   an  evil    in   itself,  but  a  partial  good   bought 
at  a  ruinous  price  :  the   pain   which  brings  healing  is  not  by 
itself  a  good,  but  an  evil  submitted   to  that  greater  evil  may 
be  avoided.     And  we  here  use  the  terms  good  and  evil  as 
denoting  the  quality,  not  of  the  sensation  as  such  (for  that 
would  only  be  to  say  that  pleasure  is   pleasure  and   pain   is 
pain),  but  of  the  events  and   relations  in  the  organism  imme- 
diately indicated  by  the  sensation.    Anaesthetics,  for  example, 
are  useful  not  merely  because  pain  is  escaped  for  the  moment, 
but  because  the  shock  and  exhaustion  which  are  the  direct 
consequences  of  pain  are  escaped  with  it.     This  view  of  the 
intrinsic  utility  of  pleasure  and  hurtfulness  of  pain  has  been 
ingeniously  maintained  by  Mr.  Grant  y\llen,  who  thus  com- 
pletes the  accordance  between  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer's  doctrine 

Q 


226  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

and  that  of  Spinoza.  Accepting  this  view,  we  shall  say  that 
the  action  beneficial  to  the  organism  which,  in  Mr.  Spencer's 
language,  is  correlated  with  pleasure,  is  not  the  antecedent  or 
concomitant  of  the  pleasurable  sensation,  but  the  corporeal  or 
objective  aspect  of  the  sensation  itself.  The  importance  of 
the  remoter  consequences,  and  the  weight  of  Mr.  Spencer's 
argument  therefrom,  remain,  of  course,  unchanged.  The  in- 
dividuals and  races  whose  nervous  system  has  been  trained 
by  experience  to  forecast  impending  good  or  ill  at  an  early 
stage,  and  to  report  them  by  means  of  pleasure  and  pain  to 
the  centres  of  voluntary  action,  have  an  advantage  in  the 
struggle  for  life  precisely  like  that  of  the  prudent  over  the  un- 
thinking man,  or  of  an  army  where  sentinel  and  outpost  duties 
are  carefully  performed  over  one  in  which  they  are  neglected. 
But  we  must  return  to  following  Spinoza. 

The  special  forms  of  Pleasure  and  Pain  on  which  most  of  c 
the  passions  depend  are  Love  and  Hatred.  In  Spinoza's 
language  these  include  like  and  dislike  ;  in  fact  the  English 
language  is  alone,  or  nearly  so,  in  marking  a  difference  of 
degree^in  these  emotions  so  sharply  as  it  does.  The  mind 
seeks  to  retain  in  consciousness  whatever  increases  its  power, 
and  to  recall  whatever  may  counteract  the  impression  of  such 
things  as  hurt  or  hinder  it  ;  these  being  simple  manifestations 
of  the  self-preserving  tendency.  Hence  arise  Love,  which  is 
Pleasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  an  external  cause  ;  and 
Hatred,  which  is  Pain  with  the  like  accompaniment.  And,  by 
the  law  of  association  of  ideas  already  given  in  the  Second 
Part,  objects  in  themselves  indififerent  may  excite  pleasure, 
pain,  and  desire  by  their  casual  association  with  other  things 
which  are  of  themselves  apt  to  excite  those  emotions.  Hence 
the  obscure  likings  and  dislikings  which  are  commonly  referred 
to  an  unknown  cause  called  sympathy  or  antipathy.  They 
depend  on  some  association  by  resemblance  which  is  known 
only  in  its  effects.'     Through  association,  again,  a  conflict  of 

'  Eth,  iii.  12-15. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  227 

emotions  is  possible  ;  for  something  which  affects  us  with  pain 
may  at  the  same  time  call  up  memories  of  equal  or  greater 
pleasure.     But  conflicts  may  be  more  directly  produced,  foro 
the  human  body  is  exceedingly  complex,  and  therefore  may 
be  variously  affected  at  the  same  time  and  by  the  same  object. 
External  objects,  too,  are  themselves  complex,  and  may  have 
complex  effects  on  the  same  bodily  organs.     The  emotions  of  t> 
hope,  fear,  confidence,  despair,  joy,  and  disappointment,  are 
accounted  for  by  the  imagination  working  on  the  conception 
of  pleasurable  or  painful  events  as  future  or  past.'     The  effects 
of  love  and  hatred  in  inducing  emotions  of  pleasure  and  pain 
by  sympathy  are  then  set  forth.     We  have  pleasure  in  theo 
welfare  of  a  beloved  object,  and  pain  in  its  destruction  ;  its 
pleasure  and   pain  give  rise  to  the  like  affections  in  us  ;  we 
love  that  which  we  conceive  as  giving  pleasure  to  it,  and  hate 
that  which  we  conceive  as  giving  pain  ;  and   hatred  on  the 
other  hand  produces  the  contrary  effects  (Eth.  3,  19-26).     But'^ 
the  range  and  power  of  sympathy  are  yet  wider.     In  addition 
to  these  causes  the  mere  conception  of  anything  as  like  our- 
selves is  a  source  of  induced  emotion. 

'  When  it  happens  that  we  imagine  a  thing  like  ourselves,  and 
whicli  we  have  not  regarded  with  any  particular  emotion,  to  be 
affected  with  any  emotion,  we  are  thereupon  affected  with  the  like 
emotion '2  (Pr.  27). 

For,  in  so  far  as  an  external  object  conceived  by  us  as 
affected  in  a  particular  way  resembles  our  own  body,  so  far 
\A\\  our  representation  of  its  condition  include  a  representation 
or  faint  repetition  of  similar  states  of  our  own  consciousness : 
or,  under  the  physiological  aspect,  as  Spinoza  puts  it,  '  the  idea 
of  the  external  body  imagined  by  us  will  imply  an  affection 
of  our  body  like  to  that  of  the  external  body  ;  and  accordingly 

•  Propp.  17,18.   I  translate  r^wj-rj^fw^zo^worjMj  by 'disappointment,' as  Spinoza 
warns  us  at  the  end  of  the  book  that  his  terms  do  not  always  bear  their  common 

meaning.      Remorse  is  described  later  as  poenitentia. 

■  The  original  Affcctus  is  a  wider  lerm  ;  not  being  confined  to  consciousness 

Q  2 


228  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

if  we  imagine  any  one  like  ourselves  to  be  afifected  with  any 
emotion,  this  imagination  will  be  the  expression  in  conscious- 
ness of  an  affection  of  our  body  like  the  said  emotion.'  Here, 
as  often  in  Spinoza,  the  complexity  and  difficulty  of  the  physio- 
logical side  of  the  inquiry  are  apparently  slurred  or  underrated. 
But  the  psychology  is  thoroughly  sound  in  its  main  features, 
and  we  must  never  forget  that  it  was  by  keeping  the  physio- 
logical side  constantly  in  view  that  Spinoza  escaped  the  count- 
less fallacies  from  which  not  even  Kant  has  been  able  wholly 
to  deliver  us. 

Varieties  of  these  induced  or  imitative  emotions  of  sym- 
pathy are  pity,  emulation  or  the  pursuit  of  similar  objects  of 
desire,  and  benevolence,  which  is  defined  as  a  desire  arising 
from  pity,  and  seeking  to  liberate  the  object  of  pity  from  the 
evils  of  its  condition.'  Another  result  of  this  extended  sym- 
pathy (which  in  modern  language  we  may  call  the  sympathy 
of  race,  or  more  shortly  and  exactly  kindliness)  is  that  '  we 
shall  endeavour  to  do  whatever  we  conceive  men  to  look  upon 
with  pleasure,  and  shun  the  doing  of  that  which  we  conceive 
them  to  shun  '  (Pr.  29).  If  we  think  we  have  succeeded  in 
pleasing  other  men  by  our  actions,  the  result  is  complacency ; 
if  we  seem  to  have  displeased  them,  it  is  shame.  The  belief'^/ 
that  our  affection  towards  any  object  is  shared  by  others  will 
strengthen  that  affection  ;  if  the  disposition  of  another  towards 
an  object  liked  or  disliked  by  us  is  contrary  to  our  own,  there 
ensues  a  fluctuation  or  conflict  of  emotion  in  us.  Hence  we 
endeavour  to  associate  others  with  us  in  our  emotions.  This 
desire  that  others  should  agree  with  us  has  in  its  crude  form 
the  nature  of  ambition,  and  begets  mutual  hindrance  and  dis- 
cord. Hence  also  arises  envy :  for  another's  enjoyment  ex- 
cites in  us  an  appetite  for  the  like  enjoyment ;  and  if  it  is 
such  that  it  cannot  be  shared  with  our  neighbour,  we  shall 
wish  to  deprive  him  of  it.'^     How  these  effects  of  sympathy 

'  Benevolentia  .  .  .  nihil  aliud  estquam  cupiditas  e  commiseratione  orta.     (Pr. 
27,  Schol.  2.) 
»  Pr.  .^o--;2. 


1/ 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  229 

may  be  controlled  to  rational  and  social  uses  is  not  considered 
in  the  present  part  of  the  '  Ethics,'  but  will  appear  in  due 
course.  Spinoza  throws  out  here,  but  without  dwellinj^  on  it, 
the  important  hint  that  the  psychology  of  the  passions  may  be 
studied  to  advantage  in  children,  their  tender  organism  being 
as  it  were  in  a  state  of  unstable  equilibrium,  and  offering 
slight  resistance  to  external  impressions.  We  see  that  the 
laughing  or  weeping  of  others  in  their  presence  will  make 
them  laugh  or  weep  ;  that  they  seek  to  imitate  whatever  they 
see  others  doing,  and  desire  for  themselves  whatever  seems  to 
give  pleasure  to  others.^ 

Other  combinations  and  effects  of  the  master  passions  of'' 
love  and  hatred  are  worked  out  in  a  series  of  propositions 
which  we  shall  not  follow  in  detail.  But  it  may  be  useful  to 
translate  a  few  of  them  as  specimens  of  Spinoza's  manner. 
The  omitted  demonstrations  involve  reference  to  other  pro- 
positions without  which  they  are  not  intelligible. 

'  Prop.  43.  Hatred  is  increased  by  mutual  hatred,  and  contrariwise 
may  be  abolished  by  love. 

Demonstration.  Whenever  one  conceives  a  person  hated  by  him 
to  be  affected  with  hatred  towards  him,  thereupon  a  new  hatred 
arises  while  the  first,  by  the  supposition,  is  yet  in  being.  But  if  on 
the  other  hand  he  conceive  this  person  to  be  affected  with  love 
towards  him,  in  so  far  as  he  conceives  this  he  will  regard  himself  with 
pleasure,  and  to  that  extent  will  endeavour  to  please  that  other ;  that 
is,  to  that  extent  he  endeavours  not  to  hate  him  and  to  do  no  dis 
pleasure  to  him.  And  this  endeavour  will  be  greater  or  less  in  pro- 
portion to  the  emotion  whence  it  arises.  Therefore  if  it  be  greater  than 
that  which  arises  from  hatred,  and  through  which  the  man  endeavours 
to  do  displeasure  to  the  thing  he  hates,  it  will  prevail  over  it,  and 
abolish  the  hate  from  his  mind  ;  which  was  to  be  proved. 

Prop.  44.  When  hatred  is  wholly  overcome  by  love,  it  passes  into 
love  ;  and  this  love  is  greater  than  if  hatred  had  not  gone  before  it. 

Scholhitn.  Though  this  be  so,  yet  no  man  will  endeavour  to  hate 
anything  or  undergo  displeasure  that  he  may  enjoy  this  greater 
pleasure  ;  that  is,  no  one  will  desire  harm  to  be  done  to  himself  for 

'  Pr.  32,  Schol. 


230  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

the  hope  of  making  it  good,  nor  long  to  be  sick  for  the  hope  of 
growing  whole.  For  every  man  will  always  endeavour  to  preserve 
his  being  and  to  keep  off  pain  as  far  as  he  can.  But  if  it  can  be 
supposed  that  a  man  may  desire  to  hate  some  one  that  he  may  after- 
wards be  affected  with  greater  love  towards  him,  then  he  will  con- 
stantly desire  to  hate  him.  Fc  r  the  greater  the  hatred  has  been,  the 
greater  the  love  shall  be,  and  therefore  he  will  constantly  wish  the 
hate  to  be  more  and  more  augmented  ;  and  for  the  like  reason  a 
man  will  endeavour  to  be  more  and  more  sick,  that  he  may  enjoy 
greater  pleasure  afterwards  in  the  return  of  health  ;  which  is  absurd. 

Prop.  49.  Love  and  hatred  towards  a  thing  which  we  conceive  as 
free  must  both  be  greater,  the  occasion  being  otherwise  the  same, 
than  towards  a  thing  conceived  as  necessary. 

Schol.  Hence  it  follows  that  men,  because  they  deem  themselves 
free,  are  moved  toward  one  another  with  greater  love  and  hate  than 
other  creatures  ;  besides  which  is  to  be  considered  the  imitation  of 
emotions  above  mentioned  (Prop.  27,  34,  40,  and  43  of  this  Part).' 

A  little  farther  on  we  have   an  important  group  of  pro- 
positions concerning  the  active  powers  of  the  mind.     Whenr 
the  mind  contemplates  itself  and  its  own  power,  this  gives 
rise  to  pleasure  ;  while  the  contemplation  of  one's  own  weak- 
ness gives  rise  to  pain.' 

'  This  displeasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  our  own  weakness 
is  called  dejection  {humilitas)  ;  the  pleasure  that  arises  from  the  con- 
templation of  oneself  is  named  self-love  or  self-complacency.  Ando 
seeing  this  is  renewed  every  time  that  a  man  contemplates  his  own 
faculties  or  active  power,  it  likewise  follows  that  every  one  is  eager  to 
recount  his  own  doings  and  display  his  strength  both  of  body  and 
mind,  and  for  this  reason  men  are  troublesome*  to  one  another. 
Also  this  oftentimes  leads  men  to  be  enviously  disposed,  that  is,  to 
rejoice  at  the  infirmity  of  their  fellows,  and  be  displeased  at  their 
excellence.  For  so  often  as  this  or  that  man  conceives  his  own 
actions,  he  is  affected  with  pleasure,  and  the  more  so  as  he  conceives 
them  more  distinctly  and  as  expressing  a  greater  perfection  ;  or  in 
other  words,  the  more  he  can  distinguish  them  from  others  and 
contemplate  them  as  individual  things.  Wherefore  every  one  will 
most  rejoice  in  the  contemplation  of  himself  when  the  quality  con- 

'  Propp.  53,  54,  55.    Prop.  54  is  a  curious  example  of  Spinoza's  most  artificial 
manner. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  231 

templated  in  himself  is  somewhat  he  allows  not  in  other  creatures. 
But  if  that  which  he  affirms  of  himself  be  ascribed  by  him  to  man  or 
animals  in  general,  he  mil  not  be  so  much  delighted  ;  contrariwise 
he  will  be  displeased  if  he  conceives  his  own  actions  as  infirm  in 
comparison  of  other  men's.  And  this  displeasure  he  will  strive  to 
put  off,  namely,  by  perversely  construing  the  actions  of  his  fellows,  or 
dressing  out  his  own  as  best  he  may.  Thus  'tis  plain  that  men  are 
naturally  prone  to  hate  and  envy,  which  last  is  also  favoured  by  their 
bringing  up.  For  it  is  the  way  of  parents  to  urge  their  children 
towards  excellence  with  the  spur  of  ambition  and  envy.  But  per- 
adventure  some  doubt  remains,  because  we  often  admire  men's 
excellence  and  do  them  honour.  To  remove  this  I  shall  add  this 
following  corollary. 

No  man  is  envious  of  excellence  unless  in  one  supposed  his 
equal. 

Demonstration.  Envy  is  of  the  nature  of  hate  or  displeasure,  that 
is,  an  affection  whereby  man's  active  power  or  endeavour  is  hindered. 
But  man  doth  not  endeavour  or  desire  to  do  anything  but  what  can 
follow  from  his  own  nature  as  he  finds  the  same.  Therefore  a  man 
will  not  desire  any  active  power  or  excellence  (for  'tis  all  one)  to  be 
attributed  to  him  which  belongs  to  some  other  nature  and  is  foreign 
to  his  own.  So  his  desire  cannot  be  hindered,  that  is,  the  man 
cannot  suffer  displeasure,  from  his  contemplation  of  some  excellence 
in  one  unlike  himself,  and  by  consequence  he  cannot  envy  such  an 
one.  But  his  equal  fellow  he  can  envy,  since  he  is  assumed  to  be  of 
like  nature  with  him.' 

So  that  when  we  admire  men  for  singular  foresight, 
courage,  or  other  qualities,  this  is  because  we  conceive  their 
qualities,  at  least  in  that  degree,  as  singular  and  above  the 
common  fortune  of  men.  The  hero  is  conceived  as  not  of  one  b 
mould  with  ourselves,  and  we  no  more  entertain  envy  with 
respect  to  him  than  against  the  lion  for  his  courage  or  against 
a  tree  for  its  height.' 

It  is  to  be  observed  that  Spinoza  is  in  this  book  concerned  ° 
only  with  the  play  of  the  emotions  when  left  to  themselves. 
He    does    not    mean    to    deny   that    rational    and    unselfish 
admiration    of  human    excellence   as   such    is  possible   and 

'  Scholia  to  Prop.  51^. 


232  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

practicable.  But  this  is  the  effect  of  right  knowledge  and  the« 
discipline  of  society,  which  have  not  yet  been  considered.  Ito 
is  next  pointed  out  that  pleasure,  pain  and  desire,  and  there- 
fore all  the  emotions  derived  from  them,  are  of  as  many  kinds 
and  varieties  as  the  external  objects  which  are  the  occasion 
of  them  ;  and  also  that  the  emotions  differ  in  every  individual  o 
according  to  the  difference  of  the  internal  conditions  of  his 
constitution.  Thus  the  desires  and  appetites  of  animals  are 
specifically  different  from  the  analogous  desires  and  appetites 
in  man,  and  the  pleasure  of  a  drunkard  is  by  no  means  the 
same  as  the  pleasure  of  a  philosopher.  Spinoza  here  ap- 
proaches the  question  whether  all  pleasures  are  commensurable, 
which  is  prominent  in  modern  discussions  of  the  theory  of 
ethics  :  but  he  does  not  pursue  it.  From  his  point  of  view  it 
is  at  best  superfluous,  and  I  cannot  help  suspecting  that, 
either  m  Spinoza's  way  or  in  some  other  not  very  far  from  it, 
we  shall  finally  acquiesce  in  the  same  conclusion. 

So  far  the  discourse  has  been  of  the  emotions  considered  ^ 
as  passions,  or  '  ascribed  to  man  in  so  far  as  he  is  acted  upon ; ' 
but  there  are  also  emotions  of  an  active  kind.  Pleasure  arises 
from  the  mind's  contemplation  of  its  own  power  ;  but  such 
contemplation  is  present  whenever  the  mind  has  a  true  or 
adequate  idea  (because  true  knowledge  includes  certitude  or 
the  consciousness  of"  its  truth,  Eth.  2,  43,  see  p.  129  above). 
Therefore  the  conception  of  adequate  ideas  is  a  pleasurable^ 
activity  of  the  mind  ;  and  activity  as  such  includes  the  effort 
or  desire  of  self-maintenance.  Hence  there  is  a  desire  which 
is  purely  active.  This  active  and  reasonable  desire  is  the  «> 
source  of  virtue  ;  which  has  two  main  branches  according  as 
desire  is  directed  by  reason  to  the  welfare  of  the  agent  him- 
self, or  to  doing  good  to  other  men  and  seeking  their  friend- 
ship. (Prop.  59,  Schol.)  Having  thus  brought  the  third  part 
of  the  Ethics  to  an  end,  Spinoza  recapitulates  his  definitions  of 
the  emotions  with  some  few  additions  and  new  explanations. 
I  shall  make  no  apology  for  translating  this  piece  at  length. 


l^HE  NATURE   OF  MAN. 


-jj 


THE   DEFINITIONS   OF  THE   EMOTIONS. 

I.  Desire  is  the  being  of  man  itself,  in  so  far  as  we  conceive  it  as  o 
determined  to  a  particular  action  by  any  given  affection  of  it. 

Explanation.  We  have  said  above,  in  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  9 
of  this  part,  that  desire  is  appetite  with  consciousness  thereof ;  and 
that  appetite  is  the  being  itself  of  man,  in  so  far  as  it  is  determined 
to  such  actions  as  make  for  his  preservation.  But  in  that  scholium 
I  likewise  noted  that  in  truth  I  acknowledged  no  difference  between 
the  appetite  and  the  desire  of  men.  For  whether  a  man  be  conscious 
of  his  appetite  or  not,  yet  the  appetite  is  still  one  and  the  same  ;  and 
thus,  lest  I  should  seem  to  fall  into  tautology,  I  would  not  explain 
desire  by  appetite,  but  have  sought  so  to  define  it  as  to  comprise  in 
one  word  all  those  efforts  of  human  nature  which  we  signify  by  the 
name  of  appetite,  will,  desire  or  impulse.  I  might  well  have  said 
that  desire  is  the  being  of  man  itself,  so  far  as  we  conceive  it  as 
determined  to  a  particular  action  ;  but  from  this  definition  it  would 
not  follow  (by  Prop.  23,  Part  2)  •  that  the  mind  could  be  conscious 
of  its  own  appetite  or  desire.  Therefore,  in  order  to  mclude  the 
cause  of  this  consciousness,  it  was  needful  to  add  :  by  any  given 
affection  of  it.  For  by  an  affection  of  human  being  or  nature  weo 
understand  every  disposition  thereof,  whether  it  be  innate,  whether 
it  be  conceived  purely  under  the  attribute  of  thought  or  purely  under 
that  of  extension,  or  be  ascribed  to  both  together.  Here  therefore  I 
understand  by  desire  man's  efforts,  impulses,  appetites  and  volitions 
whatsoever,  which  after  the  manifold  disposition  of  the  same  man  be 
themselves  manifold  and  not  seldom  contrary  to  one  another,  so 
that  the  man  is  dragged  this  way  and  that  and  knows  not  where  to 
turn. 

2.  Pleasure  is  the  passage  of  a  man  from  less  to  greater  perfec- 
tion. 

3.  Pain  is  the  passage  of  a  man  from  greater  to  less  perfection. 
Explanation.   I  say  passage  :  for  pleasure  is  not  perfection  itself.  ^ 

For  if  the  man  were  born  with  that  perfection  whereto  he  passes,  he 
would  possess  the  same  without  the  emotion  of  pleasure  ;  as  more 
plainly  appears  from  the  contrary  emotion  of  pain.     For  no  man  can 

'   '  The  mind  knows  not  itself,  save  so  far  as  it  perceives  ideas  of  tlie  affections 
of  the  body. ' 


234  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

deny  that  pain  consists  in  a  passage  to  less  perfection,  and  not  in 
lesser  perfection  itself,  since  a  man  cannot  have  pain  in  that  he  par- 
takes of  some  degree  of  perfection.  Neither  can  we  say  that  pain 
consists  in  being  deprived  of  a  greater  perfection  ;  for  deprivation  is 
nothing.  So  the  emotion  of  pain  is  an  act,  which  can  be  no  other 
than  that  of  passing  to  a  less  perfection,  that  is,  an  act  whereby  the 
active  power  of  man  is  diminished  or  hindered.  See  the  Scholium 
to  Prop.  1 1  of  this  Part.  For  the  definitions  of  cheerfulness,  merri- 
ment, melancholy  and  grief,  I  pass  them  over,  because  they  have 
rather  the  nature  of  bodily  affections,  and  are  but  kinds  of  pleasure 
or  pain. 

4.  Wonder  is  the  imagination  of  somewhat  whereon  the  mind 
remains  fixed  because  that  particular  imagination  hath  no  sensible 
connexion  with  others.     See  Prop.  52  with  the  Scholium. 

Explanation.  In  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  18,  Part  2,  we  have  shown 
what  is  the  cause  that  the  mind  from  contem.plating  one  thing  straight- 
way falls  into  thinking  of  another ;  namely  because  the  images^  of  those 
things  are  mutually  linked  together  in  such  order  that  one  follows  on 
the  other.  Which  cannot  be  supposed  where  the  image  of  the  thing 
is  novel ;  so  that  in  such  case  the  mind  will  be  holden  in  the  con- 
templation of  the  same  thing  till  it  be  determined  by  other  causes  to 
think  on  other  matters.  Thus  the  imagination  of  a  new  object,  if  we 
consider  it  in  itself,  is  of  like  nature  with  others  :  and  for  this  reason 
I  do  not  reckon  wonder  among  the  emotions,  nor  see  any  ground 
why  I  should,  since  this  distraction  of  the  mind  ariseth  from  no 
positive  cause  that  should  draw  the  mind  off  from  other  things,  but 
only  from  this,  that  a  cause  is  wanting  for  which  the  mind  should 
be  determined  to  think  on  other  things.  Therefore  I  admit  (as  I  •=* 
have  noted  in  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  11)  only  three  primitive  or 
primary  emotions,  namely,  of  pleasure,  pain,  and  desire  ;  and  I 
have  mentioned  wonder  for  no  other  reason  than  that  it  is  our 
custom  to  call  certain  emotions  derived  from  the  three  primitive 
ones  by  different  names  when  they  have  regard  to  objects  of  our 
wonder.  And  for  the  same  reason  I  am  minded  to  add  here  a 
definition  of  contempt. 

5.  Contempt  is  the  imagination  of  a  thing  which  so  little  moves 
the  mind  that  by  the  presence  of  the  thing  it  is  inclined  rather  to 
imagine  the  qualities  which  are  not  in  the  thing  than  those  which  are 
in  it.     See  the  scholium  to  Prop.  52.  . 

'    In  modern  language  we  should  say  ideas  or  concepts. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  235 

The  definitions  of  worship  and  scorn  {vefierationis  ei  didignaiionis) 
I  here  leave  alone,  since  no  emotions  are  to  my  knowledge  named 
after  them. 

6.  Love  is  pleasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  an  external 
cause. 

ExplanatioJi.  This  definition  clearly  explains  wherein  love  consists. 
But  that  of  the  authors  who  define  it  as  the  will  of  the  lover  to  unite 
himself  to  the  thing  loved  expresses  not  the  nature  of  love  but  a 
particular  property  thereof  And  since  the  nature  of  love  was  not 
well  understood  by  these  authors,  they  could  not  so  much  as  form  a 
clear  notion  of  that  property ;  and  hence  their  definition  hath  been 
generally  esteemed  pretty  obscure.  But  it  is  to  be  observed  that 
when  I  say  that  this  property  is  in  love,  to  have  a  will  for  union  with 
the  thing  loved,  I  mean  by  will  not  an  assent  or  conclusion,  nor  a  free 
resolve  of  the  mind  (for  this  I  have  shown  to  be  a  fiction  in  Prop.  48, 
Part  2) ;  nor  yet  the  desire  of  being  united  to  the  thing  loved  when 
it  is  away,  or  of  continuing  in  its  presence  when  it  is  by  ;  for  love 
may  be  conceived  without  either  of  these  desires  ;  but  by  this  ^\^ll  I 
understand  the  content  which  arises  in  him  that  loves  upon  the 
presence  of  the  thing  loved,  whereby  the  pleasure  of  the  lover  is 
strengthened  or  at  least  encouraged.' 

7.  Hate  (or  dislike)  is  pain  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  an 
external  cause. 

Explanation.  Whatever  is  to  be  observed  here  is  easily  collected 
from  the  explanation  to  the  foregoing  definition,  and  see  the  Scholium 
to  Prop.  13. 

8.  Inclination  is  pleasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  something 
which  is  a  casual  occasion  {per  accidens  causa)  of  pleasure. 

9.  Aversion  is  pain  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  something 
which  is  a  casual  occasion  of  pain.  See  as  to  these  the  Scholium  to 
Prop.  15. 

ID.  Devotion  is  love  towards  one  whom  we  admire. 
Explanation.  Admiration  or  wonder  ariseth  from  the  novelty  of 
the  thing,  as  we  showed  in  Prop.  52.     If  therefore  it  happen  that  we 

'  Remembering  that  Spinoza's  amor  is  taken  in  the  widest  possible  sense,  we 
may  doubt  if  the  property  in  question  is  universal.  A  statesman  or  philanthropist 
may  do  good  to  people  hundreds  or  thousands  of  miles  away  who  never  heard  of 
his  existence.  \\Tien  he  thinks  of  the  good  he  has  done  them  collectively,  his 
feeling  will  be  '  laetitia  concomitante  idea  causae  externae  ;  '  but  their  individual 
presence  may  be  indifferent  or  even  disagreeable  to  him.  Spinoza  would  say  that 
even  here  there  is  some  pleasure,  but  that  it  is  overpowered  by  dislike  arising 
from  other  causes. 


236  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

often  imagine  something  we  admire,  we  shall  cease   to  admire  it ; 
and  thus  we  see  that  devotion  is  apt  to  reduce  itself  to  mere  love. 

11.  Derision  is  pleasure  arising  from  our  imagination  that  some- 
thing we  contemn  is  present  in  something  which  we  hate. 

Explanation.  So  far  as  we  contemn  a  thing  which  we  hate,  we 
deny  existence  of  it  (see  Prop.  52,  Scliol.)  and  therefore  (by  Prop. 
20)  we  are  pleased.  But  since  we  assume  that  the  man  who  derides 
a  thing  also  hates  it,  it  follows  that  such  pleasure  is  unsubstantial. 
See  the  Schol.  to  Prop.  47. 

12.  Hope  is  an  unconstant  pleasure  bred  of  the  idea  of  a  future 
or  past  thing,  of  the  issue  '  whereof  we  are  to  some  extent  in  doubt. 
See  as  to  this  Prop.  18,  Schol.  2. 

13.  Fear  is  an  unconstant  pain  bred  of  the  idea  of  a  future  or 
past  thing,  of  the  issue  whereof  we  are  to  some  extent  in  doubt. 
See  as  to  these  Prop.  18,  Schol.  2. 

Explanatmi.  From  these  definitions  it  follows  that  there  is  no  hope 
without  fear,  nor  fear  without  hope.  For  whoever  is  in  hope  and 
doubts  of  the  issue  of  the  matter,  the  same  is  assumed  to  imagine 
somewhat  that  excludes  the  existence  of  the  thing  hoped  for  ;  and 
so  far,  therefore,  to  receive  pain  (Prop.  19)  and,  while  he  is  in  hope, 
to  fear  that  the  desired  thing  may  not  happen.  Again,  he  who  is  in 
fear,  that  is,  doubts  of  the  issue  of  a  thing  he  dislikes,  also  imagines 
somewhat  that  excludes  the  existence  of  that  thing  ;  and  therefore  is 
pleased  (Prop.  20),  and  so  to  that  extent  has  hope  that  the  thing  may 
not  happen. 

14.  Confidence  is  pleasure  bred  of  the  idea  of  a  future  or  past 
thing  concerning  which  our  cause  of  doubt  is  removed. 

15.  Despair  is  pain  bred  of  the  idea  of  a  future  or  past  thing  con- 
cerning which  our  cause  of  doubt  is  removed. 

ExpIanatio7i.  Thus  there  ariseth  of  hope  confidence,  and  of  fear 
despair,  when  our  cause  of  doubt  as  to  the  issue  of  the  thing  is  taken 
away  ;  which  happens  because  a  man  imagines  a  past  or  future  thing 
as  present  to  him,  and  as  such  contemplates  it ;  or  because  he 
imagines  other  matters  which  exclude  the  existence  of  those  things 
which  threw  him  into  doubt.  For  although  we  can  never  be  truly 
certain  of  the  issue  of  particular  things  (by  the  Corollary  to  Prop.  31, 
Part  2),^^  yet  it  may  so  be  that  we  have  no  doubt  thereof     For  we 

'  Or  '  happening. ' 

-  '  Omnes  res  particulares  contingentes  et  corruptibiles  esse.'  The  Proposition 
itself  seems  more  in  point  :  '  Nos  de  duratione  rerum  singularium  quae  extra  nos 
sunt  nullam  nisi  admodum  inadaequatam  cognitionem  habere  possumus.' 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  237 

have  shown  (see  the  Scholium,  Prop.  49,  Part  2)  that  it  is  one  thing 
to  have  no  doubt  of  a  matter,  another  to  have  the  certainty  of  it  ; 
and  thus  it  may  come  to  pass  that  the  imagination  of  a  past  or  future 
thing  may  affect  us  with  the  same  emotion  of  pleasure  or  pain  as  the 
imagination  of  the  thing  when  present :  as  we  have  proved  in  Prop. 
18  of  this  Part,  which  see,  as  well  as  its  second  Scholium. 

16.  Joy  is  pleasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  something  past 
which  happened  beyond  our  expectation. 

17.  Disappointment  or  grief  (conscientiae  morsns)  is  pain  accom- 
panied by  the  idea  of  something  past  which  happened  beyond  our 
expectation. 

18.  Pity  {commisa'atio)  is  pain  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  evil 
happening  to  another  whom  we  conceive  to  be  like  ourselves.  See 
the  Scholia  to  Prop.  22  and  27  of  this  Part. 

Explanation.  Between  pity  and  mercy  {j?itsericordiam)  there 
seems  to  be  no  difference,  unless  perhaps  that  pity  has  regard  to 
the  emotion  in  particular,  mercy  to  the  disposition  thereto.' 

19.  Approval  {favor)  is  love  toward  some  one  who  has  done  good 
to  another. 

20.  Indignation  is  hate  towards  some  one  who  has  done  ill  to 
another. 

Explanation.  I  know  that  these  terms  have  a  different  meaning© 
in  common  use.  But  my  purpose  is  not  to  explain  the  meaning  of 
words  but  the  nature  of  things,  and  to  signify  the  things  by  words 
whose  accustomed  meaning  is  not  wholly  repugnant  to  that  in  which 
I  desire  to  use  them.  And  so  let  it  suffice  to  note  this  once  for  all. 
As  to  the  causes  of  these  emotions,  see  CoroU.  i.  Prop.  27,  and  the 
Schol.  to  Prop.  22  of  this  Part. 

21.  Over-esteem  {existimatio)  is  to  think  too  highly  of  a  man  for  " 
love's  sake. 

22.  Disparagement  {despectus)[?,  to  think  too  meanly  of  a  man  for 
hate's  sake. 

Explanation.  Over-esteem  is  thus  an  effect  or  property  of  love, 
and  disparagement  of  hate  •;  and  so  over-esteem  may  likewise  be 
thus  defined,  that  it  is  love,  so  far  forth  as  it  moves  a  man  to  think  too 
highly  of  the  thing  loved,  and  on  the  other  part  disparagement 
may  be  defined  as  hate,  so  far  forth  as  it  moves  a  man  to  think  too 
meanly  of  one  whom  he  hates.  See  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  26  of 
this  Part. 

'  It  is  even  more  difficult  to  find  in  English  the  difference  indicated  by  Spinoza. 
Auerbach  uses  Mitleid  and  Miigefuhl. 


238  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE   AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

23.  Envy  is  hate,  in  so  far  as  it  disposeth  a  man  to  be  sorry  at 
another's  happiness,  and  contrariwise  rejoice  in  his  misfortune. 

Explanation.  To  Envy  we  commonly  oppose  Mercy,  which 
accordingly  may  be  thus  defined,  though  against  the  usual  meaning 
of  the  word  : 

24.  Mercy  (or  Good  Will)  is  love,  in  so  far  as  it  disposeth  a  man 
to  rejoice  in  another's  good  fortune  and  contrariwise  be  sorry  at  his 
ill  fortune. 

Explanation.  See  more  of  envy,  Prop.  24,  Schol.  and  32,  Schol. 
in  this  Part.  Now  these  be  the  emotions  of  pain,  which  the  idea  of 
somewhat  outside  us  doth  accompany  as  being  their  cause,  whether  of 
its  own  nature  or  by  casual  association  {per  accidens.)  Hence  I  pass  to 
those  which  are  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  somewhat  within  us  as  a 
cause.  * 

25.  Self-contentment  is  pleasure  bred  of  a  man's  contemplating 
himself  and  his  own  active  power. 

26.  Humility  is  pain  bred  of  a  man's  contemplating  his  own 
im[)Otence  or  infirmity. 

Explanation.  Self-contentment  is  opposed  to  humility,  so  far  as 
we  understand  by  it  a  pleasure  that  arises  from  contemplating  our 
own  active  power.  But  so  far  as  we  also  understand  by  it  a  pleasure 
accompanied  by  the  idea  of  some  act  which  we  conceive  ourselves 
to  have  performed  by  a  free  resolve  of  the  mind,  then  it  is  the 
opposite  of  repentance,  which  we  define  thus  : 

27.  Repentance  is  pain  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  some  act 
which  we  conceive  ourselves  to  have  performed  by  a  free  resolve  of 
the  mind. 

Explanation.  We  have  shown  the  causes  of  these  emotions  in  the 
Schol.  to  Prop.  51  of  this  Part,  and  Propp.  53,  54,  and  55  and  its 
Scholium.  As  to  the  free  resolve  of  the  mind,  see  Prop.  35,  Part  2, 
Schol.  But  here  it  is  also  to  be  observed  that  'tis  no  wonder  that  all 
acts  in  general  which  by  custom  are  called  wrong  are  followed  by 
pain,  and  those  which  are  called  right  by  pleasure.  For  we  may 
easily  comprehend  from  what  has  been  above  said  that  this  chiefly 
depends  on  education.  Parents  have  so  ordered  it  by  reproving  the 
one  sort  of  actions  and  often  rebuking  their  children  therefor,  and 
contrariwise  commending  and  praising  the  other,  that  passions  of  pain 
are  joined  with  the  one,  but  of  pleasure  with  the  other.  And  this  is 
likewise  confirmed  by  actual  experience.  For  custom  and  religion  c 
be  not  for  all  men  the  same  ;  but  what  is  holy  with  some  is  profane 
with  others,  and  what  is  honourable  with  some  is  base  with  others. 


THE  NATURE  OF  MAN.  239 

So  that  according  as  every  man  is  brought  up,  he  repenteth   of  a 
particular  deed  or  maketh  boast  of  the  same. 

28.  Pride  is  to  think  too  highly  of  oneself  by  reason  of  self-love. 
Explanation.  The  difference  of  pride  and  over-esteem  is  that  the^ 

latter  hath  regard  to  an  outward  object,  but  pride  to  the  man  himself, 
esteeming  himself  overmuch.  Now  as  over-esteem  is  an  effect  or 
property  of  love,  so  is  pride  of  selfishness,  and  may  therefore  be  also 
thus  defined,  that  it  is  self-love  or  self-contentment,  in  so  far  as  it 
disposeth  one  to  think  too  highly  of  himself  See  Prop.  26,  Schol. 
To  this  emotion  there  is  none  contrary.  For  no  man  thinks  too 
meanly  of  himself  through  hating  himself ;  nay  there  is  no  man 
thinks  too  meanly  of  himself,  so  far  as  he  conceives  that  he  cannot 
do  this  or  that  thing.  For  whatever  a  man  conceives  he  cannot  do, 
that  he  necessarily  conceives,  and  by  that  notion  he  is  so  disposed 
that  in  truth  he  cannot  do  that  which  he  conceives  he  cannot  do. 
For  so  long  as  he  conceives  that  he  cannot  do  a  thing,  so  long  is  his 
action  not  determined  to  that  thing  ;  and  therefore  so  long  is  it 
impossible  that  he  should  do  it.  But  now  if  we  consider  such  things 
as  depend  merely  on  opinion,  we  can  conceive  how  it  may  be  that  a 
man  should  think  too  meanly  of  himself.  It  may  happen  that  a 
man  in  sorrow,  while  he  considers  his  own  infirmity,  imagines  that  he 
is  despised  by  everybody  ;  and  this  while  other  men  have  nothing 
less  in  their  thoughts  than  despising  him.  Again,  a  man  may  think 
too  meanly  of  himself  if  he  deny  somewhat  of  himself  with  regard 
to  a  future  time  whereof  he  is  uncertain  ;  as  if  he  should  suppose 
that  he  can  have  no  certain  conceptions,  or  can  desire  and  perform 
nothing  but  wicked  and  base  things,  and  the  like.  Again  we  may  say 
that  a  man  thinks  too  meanly  of  himself  when  we  see  that  for  exceed- 
ing fear  of  shame  he  will  not  adventure  what  others  being  his  equals 
will.  Thus  we  have  an  emotion  fit  to  be  opposed  to  pride,  which  I 
shall  call  dejection.  For  as  pride  is  bred  of  self-contentment,  so  is 
dejection  of  humility  ;  and  accordingly  we  define  it  thus  : 

29.  Dejection  {abiecHo)  is  to  think  too  meanly  of  oneself  by 
reason  of  displeasure. 

Explanation.  Nevertheless  pride  is  wont  to  be  opposed  to 
humility  :  but  then  we  consider  the  effects  of  them  rather  than  their 
nature.  We  call  that  man  proud,  who  boasts  exceedingly  (see  Prop. 
30,  Schol.),  who  talks  of  nothing  but  excellence  in  himself  and  faults 
in  others,  who  would  fain  have  precedence  of  all  others,  and  who 
affects  the  dignity  and  apparel  used  by  those  whose  estate  is  much 
above  his  own.     Whereas  we  call  him  humble,  who  often  blushes,  who 


240  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

confesses  his  own  faults  and  tells  of  other  men's  excellence,  who  gives 
place  to  all  men,  and  who  is  of  a  downcast  carriage  and  negligent 
of  his  apparel.  Howbeit  these  emotions,  I  say  humility  and  dejec-- 
tion,  are  very  scarce.  For  man's  nature,  considered  in  itself,  strives' 
against  them  with  all  its  power  (see  Propp.  15  and  54) ;  and  hence 
those  who  pass  for  being  most  downcast  and  humble  are  oftentimes 
the  most  self-seeking  and  envious. 

30.  Honour  (gloria)  is  pleasure  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  some 
action  of  our  own  which  we  suppose  to  be  praised  by  others. 

31.  Shame  is  pain  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  some  action  which 
we  suppose  to  be  blamed  by  others. 

Explanation.  As  to  these  see  the  Scholium  to  Prop.  30  of  this 
Part.  I  shall  here  observe  the  difference  between  shame  and 
modesty.  Shame  is  the  pain  following-a  deed  whereof  one  is  ashamed  ; 
but  modesty  is  the  apprehension  or  fear  of  shame,  whereby  a  man  is 
restrained  from  any  disgraceful  action.  To  modesty  is  commonly 
opposed  shamelessness,  which  is  in  truth  not  an  emotion,  as  I  shall 
show  in  due  place.  But  the  names  of  the  emotions,  as  I  have^* 
already  noted,  go  more  to  their  application  than  to  their  nature. 
Thus  much  of  the  emotions  of  pleasure  and  pain,  which  I  have  now 
expounded  as  I  purposed  :  and  I  go  on  to  those  which  I  ascribe  to 
Desire. 

32.  Regret  is  the  desire  or  appetite  of  possessing  something,  which 
is  nourished  by  the  remembrance  of  that  thing,  and  at  the  same 
time  checked  by  the  remembrance  of  other  things  which  exclude  the 
existence  of  the  thing  so  desired. 

Explanation.  When  we  remember  anything,  (as  we  have  often 
said  before),  this  of  itself  disposeth  us  to  regard  the  thing  with  the 
same  emotion  as  if  it  were  actually  present.  But  this  disposition  or 
effect,  at  least  in  waking  hours,  is  mostly  constrained  by  ideas  of 
things  which  exclude  the  existence  of  the  thing  remembered  by  us. 
When  therefore  we  remember  a  thing  which  affects  us  with  any  sort 
of  pleasure,  we  at  once  endeavour  to  regard  it  with  the  same  emotion 
of  pleasure  as  if  it  were  present  ;  and  this  endeavour  is  thereupon 
restrained  by  the  remembrance  of  things  which  exclude  its  existence. 
Wherefore  regret  is  in  truth  a  pain  opposite  to  that  pleasure  which 
arises  from  the  absence  of  a  thing  we  hate,  as  to  which  see  Prop. 
47,  Schol.  But  since  the  name  of  regret  seemeth  to  have  regard  to 
desire,  I  reckon  this  emotion  among  those  of  desire. 

33.  Emulation  is  the  desire  of  something  excited  in  us  by  our 
conception  that  others  have  the  like  desire. 


iHt.   NATURJi.    OF  MAN  241 

Explanation.  When  one  runs  away  at  seeing  others  run  or  fears 
at  seeing  others  fear,  or  on  seeing  that  another  hath  burnt  his  hand, 
draws  in  his  own  hand  and  moves  as  if  his  own  hand  were  burnt,  we 
say  that  he  imitates  the  emotion  of  the  other,  but  nob  that  he 
emulates  him  :  not  because  we  know  of  any  difference  between  the 
causes  of  emulation  and  of  imitation,  but  because  use  will  so  have  it 
that  v/e  speak  of  emulation  only  in  him  who  imitates  what  he  deems 
honourable,  useful,  or  agreeable.  As  for  the  cause  of  emulation,  see 
Prop.  2  7  of  this  Part  and  the  Scholium.  And  why  this  emotion  doth 
mostly  go  in  couples  with  envy,  see  Prop.  32  with  the  Scholium 
thereto. 

34.  Thankfulness  or  gratitude  is  a  desire  or  bent  prompted  by 
love,  whereby  we  endeavour  to  do  good  to  him  who  has  conferred 
benefit  on  us  in  the  like  disposition.  See  Prop.  39,  with  the  [first] 
Scholium  to  Prop.  41  of  this  Part. 

35.  Benevolence  is  the  desire  of  doing  good  to  one  whom  we 
pity.     See  Prop.  27,  Schol.  [2].^ 

36.  Anger  is  a  desire  whereby  we  are  impelled  through  hatred  to 
do  ill  to  one  whom  we  hate.     See  Prop.  39. 

37.  Revenge  is  a  desire  whereby  we  are  stirred  up  through  mutual 
hatred  to  do  ill  to  one  who  hath  done  ill  to  us  with  the  like  disposi- 
tion.    See  Prop.  40,  Coroll.  2,  and  the  Scholium  thereon. 

38.  Cruelty  or  barbarity  (saevitia)  is  the  desire  whereby  any  one 
is  impelled  to  do  evil  to  one  whom  we  love  or  pity. 

Explanation.  To  cruelty  is  opposed  clemency,  which  is  not  a 
passion,  but  the  power  of  the  mind  whereby  a  man  restrains  anger 
and  revenge. 

39.  Fear  is  the  desire  of  avoiding  at  the  cost  of  a  lesser  evil  a 
greater  one  which  we  apprehend.     See  Prop.  39,  Schol. 

40.  Daring  is  a  desire  whereby  one  is  impelled  to  do  somewhati" 
attended  with  a  danger  which  his  peers  are  afraid  to  undergo. 

41.  Cowardice  is  ascribed  to  him  whose  desire  is  checked  by  the 
fear  of  a  danger  which  his  peers  dare  to  undergo. 

Explanation.  Cowardice  therefore  is  naught  else  than  the  fear  of 
an  evil  which  most  men  are  not  wont  to  fear  ;  for  which  cause  I 
reckon  it  not  with  the  emotions  of  desire.  Yet  I  have  chosen  to 
explain  it  here,  because,  in  so  far  as  we  attend  to  the  desire,  there 
is  a  true  opposition  betwixt  it  and  daring. 

42.  Consternation  is  ascribed  to  him  whose  desire  to  avoid  evil 
is  checked  by  amazement  at  the  evil  he  fears. 

'  Quoted  above,  p.  228,  note. 
R 


242  SPINOZA  :   HTS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Explanation.  Consternation  is  therefore  a  kind  of  cowardice. 
But  since  consternation  is  bred  of  a  double  fear,  it  may  be  more  con- 
veniently defined  as  fear  whicli  holds  a  man  in  such  bewilderment  or 
distraction  that  he  cannot  remove  the  evil  from  him.  I  say  bewilder- 
ment, so  far  as  we  understand  his  desire  to  remove  the  evil  to  be 
checked  by  amazement.  And  I  say  distraction,  in  so  far  as  we  con- 
ceive the  same  desire  to  be  checked  by  the  fear  of  another  ill  which 
equally  vexeth  him  :  whereby  it  comes  to  pass  that  he  knows  not 
against  which  of  the  two  to  defend  himself.  See  the  Scholia  to 
Propp.  39  and  52.     As  to  cowardice  and  daring,  see  Prop.  5i,Schol. 

43.  Civility  or  deference  {Jmmanitas  seu  modestia)  is  the  desire  of 
doing  what  pleaseth  men  and  omitting  what  displeaseth  them. 

44.  Ambition  is  an  immoderate  desire  for  honour,  o^^ 
Explanation.  Ambition  is  a  desire  whereby  all  the  emotions  are 

nourished  and  fortified  (by  Prop.  27  and  31  of  this  Part)  ;  and  there- 
fore this  emotion  can  scarce  be  overcome.  For  so  long  as  a  man  is 
holden  by  any  desire,  he  is  of  necessity  holden  by  this  withal.  '  The 
more  a  man  excels,'  saith  Cicero,  '  the  more  is  he  led  by  honour  :  yea 
the  philosophers  write  books  of  despising  honour  and  glory,  and  set 
their  names  to  them.' 

45.  Luxury  is  unrestrained  desire  or  love  (which  you  will)  of 
feasting. 

46.  Drunkenness  is  unrestrained  desire  and  love  of  drinking. 

47.  Avarice  is  unrestrained  desire  and  love  of  wealth. 

48.  Lust  is  in  the  like  manner  desire  and  love  in  bodily  inter- 
course. 

Explanation.  Whether  this  last  desire  be  restrained  or  not,  it  is 
commonly  called  lust.  And  these  five  emotions  as  noted  in  the 
Schol.  to  Prop.  56)  have  no  contraries.  For  deference  is  itself  a  kind 
of  ambition,  as  to  which  see  Prop.  29,  Schol.  For  temperance,  sober-^ 
ness,  and  chastity,  I  have  already  noted  of  these  also  that  they  express 
not  a  passion  but  a  power  of  the  mind.  And  though  it  may  be  that  an 
avaricious,  ambitious,  or  timid  man  shall  abstain  from  excess  in  these 
kinds,  yet  avarice,  ambition,  and  fear  are  not.contraries  to  luxury,  drunk- 
enness, or  lust.'  For  an  avaricious  man  is  oftentimes  eager  to  stuft' 
himself  with  food  and  drink  at  another  man's  charges.  An  ambitious 
man,  so  long  as  he  hopes  it  may  be  hid,  will  stint  himself  in  nothing  ; 
indeed,  if  he  live  in  drunken  and  debauched  company,  his  ambition 
will  but  make  him  the  more  prone  to  those  vices.     As  for  the  timid 

'    Castitati  in  tlie  Latin  text  by  an  obvious  slip. 


THE  NATURE   OF  MAN.  243 

man,  he  doth  what  he  would  not.  For  though  a  miser  should  cast 
his  wealth  into  the  sea  to  escape  death,  yet  he  is  a  miser  still  ;  and 
so  if  a  lustful  man  is  grieved  that  he  cannot  follow  his  bent,  he  ceases 
not  thereby  to  be  lustful.  And  in  general  these  emotions  regard  noto 
so  much  the  acts  of  feasting,  drinking,  and  so  forth,  as  the  inward 
appetite  and  liking.  So  that  nothing  can  be  opposed  to  these 
emotions  but  high-mindedness  and  valour  {generosiiafem  et  animosita- 
tem),  whereof  more  presently.' 

The  definitions  of  jealousy  and  other  perturbations  of  the  mind  I 
pass  over  in  silence,  as  well  because  they  spring  from  the  compound- 
ing of  the  emotions  already  defined,  as  because  they  mostly  have  no 
special  names  ;  which  is  a  sign  that  for  the  uses  of  life  it  sufficeth  to 
have  a  general  knowledge  of  them.  And  it  is  established  from  those 
definitions  of  the  emotions  which  we  have  expounded  that  they  all 
have  their  rise  from  Desire,  Pleasure,  or  Pain  ;  or  rather  that  there 
be  none  beside  these  three,  every  one  whereof  is  wont  to  be  called  by 
divers  names  after  the  divers  presentments  and  tokens  of  them  in 
outward  operation.  Considering  these  primitive  emotions  and  that 
which  we  have  above  said  of  the  nature  of  the  mind,  we  may  now 
thus  define  the  emotions,  so  far  as  they  have  regard  to  the  mind 
alone. 

GENERAL   DEFINITION    OF   THE   EMOTIONS. 

Emotion,  which  is  called  a  passion  {pathema)  of  the  soul,  is  a  con- 
fused idea  whereby  the  mind  affirms  a  greater  or  less  faculty  of  exist- 
ence ^  in  its  body  or  some  part  thereof  than  it  had  before,  and  on 
the  occurrence  of  which  the  mind  itself  is  determined  to  think  on  one 
thing  more  than  another. 

Explanation.  First,  I  say  that  emotion  or  passion  in  the  soul  is  a  o 
confused  idea.  For  we  have  shown  (Prop.  3  of  this  Part)  that  the  mind 
suffers  only  so  far  as  it  hath  inadequate  or  confused  ideas.  Next,  I 
say  '  whereby  the  mind  affirms  a  greater  or  less  power  of  existence  in 
its  body  or  some  part  thereof  than  it  had  before.'  For  all  ideas  of 
[other]  bodies  which  we  have  denote  rather  the  existing  disposition 

'  Cp.  Prop.  59  of  this  Part,  Scliol.  Animositas  zt\A  generositas  s.re  the  Uvo 
npecies  of /ortifudo.  'Per  animositatem  intelligo  ciipiditatem  qua  unusquisqiie 
conatur  suum  esse  ex  solo  rationis  dictamine  conservare.  Per  generositatem  autcm 
cupiditatem  intelligo  qua  unusquisque  ex  solo  rationis  dictamine  conatur  reliijuos 
homines  iuvare  et  sibi  amicitia  iungcre.' 

-  lixistcndi  vis  really  vncans  neither  mure  nor  less  than  e.\i^lcnlia.  Sec  p.  218, 
above. 

R  2 


244  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

of  our  own  body  than  the  nature  of  the  external  body  (Part  2,  Prop. 
16,  Cor.  2).  But  the  idea  wherein  an  emotion  really  consists  must 
denote  or  express  the  disposition  of  the  body  or  some  part  there- 
of, because  the  body's  active  power  or  faculty  of  existing  is  increased  or 
diminished,  forwarded  or  hindered.  It  is  to  be  observed  that  when  Ic 
say  '  a  greater  or  less  faculty  of  existence  than  before,'  I  intend  not 
that  the  mind  compares  the  present  disposition  of  the  body  with  a 
past  one,  but  that  the  idea  wherein  the  being  of  the  emotion  doth 
consist  affirms  of  the  body  something  which  in  fact  involves  more  or 
less  of  reality  than  before.  And  since  the  nature  of  the  mind  consists 
in  this,  that  it  affirms  the  real  present  existence  of  its  body  (Part  2, 
Prop.  II  and  13)  and  we  mean  by  perfection  the  nature  of  the  thing 
itself;  hence  it  follows  that  the  mind  passes  to  a  greater  or  less  perfec- 
tion when  it  happens  to  it  to  affirm  somewhat  of  its  body  or  some  part 
thereof  which  involves  more  or  less  of  reality  than  before.  When 
therefore  I  said  above  that  the  mind's  power  of  thinking  is  increased 
or  diminished,  I  desired  to  have  only  this  meaning,  that  the  mind 
formed  an  idea  of  its  o\vn  body  or  some  part  thereof  which  expressed 
more  or  less  reality  than  it  had  formerly  affirmed  of  the  same  body. 
For  the  dignity  of  ideas  and  the  present  power  of  thinking  are 
measured  by  the  dignity  of  the  object.  Lastly  I  have  added  :  '  and 
on  the  occurrence  of  which  the  mind  itself  is  determined  to  think  on 
one  thing  more  than  another,'  that  besides  the  nature  of  pleasure  and 
pain,  which  the  first  part  of  the  definition  explains,  I  might  also 
express  that  of  desire. 


THE  BURDEN   OE  MAN.  245 


CHAPTER  VIII. 
THE   BURDEN    OF    MAK. 

Denn  alle  Kraft  dringt  vorwarts  in  die  Weite, 

Zu  leben  iind  zu  wirken  hier  und  dort  ; 
Dagegen  engt  und  hemmt  von  jeder  Seite 

Der  Strom  der  Welt  und  reisst  uns  mit  sich  fort  ; 
In  diesem  innern  Sturm  und  aussem  Streite 

Vernimmt  der  Geist  ein  schwer  verstanden  Wort : 
Von  der  Gewalt,  die  alle  Wesen  bindet, 
Befreit  der  Mensch  sich,  der  sich  iiberwindet. 

Goethe,  Die  Geheimnisse. 

Once  read  thy  own  breast  right, 

And  thou  hast  done  with  fears  : 
Rfan  gets  no  other  light. 
Search  he  a  thousand  years. 
Sink  in  thyself!  there  ask  what  ails  thee,  at  that  shrine. 

Matthew  Arnold,  Empedocles  on  Etna, 

Having  concluded  his  purely  scientific  analysis  of  the  springs^ 
of  action  and  passion,  Spinoza  proceeds  to  expound  in  the 
fourth  Part  of  the  Ethics  '  the  slavery  of  man,  or  the  power  of 
the  emotions.'     In  a  short  preface  he  explains  the  notions  of 
good  and  evil,  as  he  conceives  them. 

'  When  a  man  hath  determined  to  make  something  and  brought 
the  same  to  pass,  not  only  that  man  himself  will  call  his  work  perfect, 
but  also  every  one  that  rightly  knows  or  conceives  himself  to  know 
the  mind  and  aim  which  the  author  of  that  work  had.  For  example, 
if  a  man  shall  see  a  particular  work  (which  I  ^assume  to  be  not  yet 
finished)  and  knows  that  the  aim  of  its  author  is  to  build  a  house,  he 
will  call  the  house  imperfect,  but  contrariwise  perfect  whenever  he 
sees  the  work  brought  to  the  end  which  its  author  proposed  to  make 
of  it.     But  if  a  man  sees  a  work  the  like  whereof  he  hath  never  seen, 


246  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

nor  knows  the  mind  of  the  workman,  'tis  plain  he  cannot  tell  whether 
that  work  be  perfect  or  not.' 

A  sentence,  one  may  remark  in  passing,  which  deserves 
much  meditation  on  the  part  of  those  who  discuss  natural 
theology,  but  has  been  before  the  world  these  two  centuries 
without  producing  much  lesult :  and  if  we  pause  awhile  to 
discuss  the  idea  contained  in  it  the  digression  will  be  less  than 
it  seems.  For  on  this  depends  Spinoza's  view  of  ethical  good*^ 
and  evil,  and  consequently  his  whole  theory  of  ethics. 

The  argument  from  design  in  all  its  common  forms,  and 
most  of  the  obvious  objections  to  it,  proceed  on  the  assump- 
tion that  we  have  some  independent  knowledge  of  what  the 
designs  of  nature  are  or  m'ay  be  expected  to  be.     What  we 
find  in  nature,  e.specially  animated  nature,  is  fitness  in  various 
degrees  for  various  purposes  ;  organs  of  sense  for  example, 
ranging  from  a  rudimentary  state  in  the  lower  animals  to  the 
delicate  and  complex  apparatus  posse.ssed  by  the  highest.     To 
say  that  this  comes  of  design,  and  that  the  particular  degree  of 
fitness  was  designed  in  each  case,  is  a  pure  assumption  as  far 
as  the  evidence  of  nature  goes.     I  speak  of  degrees  of  fitness  ; 
for  to  talk  of  absolute  fitness  in  nature,  as  popular  teleology 
does  or  recently  did,  is  merely  to  disregard  the  facts.     Every- 
thing that  exists  is  indeed  in  one  sense  the  fittest  possible  ; 
since  if  it  were  not  so,  it  would  not  be  the  thing  existing  then 
and  there,  but  the  place  would   be  filled   by  something  else 
which  was  fitter  under  the  given  conditions.     In  other  words, 
existence  is  not  a  bare  fact  but  a  continuing  process,  and  at 
every  moment  of  the  process  the  particular  set   of  conditions 
lias  one  and  only  one  possible  result.     This  was  long  ago  seen 
in   a  general  way  by  Hume,  and  has  been  fixed  as  a  distinct 
scientific  conception  by  Mr.  Darwin's  discovery  of  it  in  a  most 
important  and  striking  concrete  form.     But  if  we  assume  a  par- 
ticular designed  purpose,  as  seeing  in  the  case  of  the  eye,  and 
inquire  if  the  means  are  as  perfect  as  they  conceivably  might 
be,  we  shall  generally  if  not  always  find  that  they  are  not. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  247 

Thus  the  human  eye,  considered  as  an  optical  instrument,  has 
more  than  one  grave  defect :  and  the  human  ankle-joint  is 
inconveniently  weak  in  proportion  to  the  strain  thrown  upon  it 
by  man's  erect  attitude  in  standing  and  walking.  If,  again,  we 
say  that  the  greatest  fitness  under  given  conditions  is  equiva- 
lent to  absolute  fitness,  and  is  in  fact  the  standard  of  perfec- 
tion in  human  workmanship,  it  must  be  observed  that  in  the 
case  of  human  workmanship  we  know  that  the  workman  did 
not  make  his  conditions  :  or,  if  there  be  conditions  as  to  which 
we  are  uncertain  how  far  they  were  within  his  control,  we 
suspend  our  judgment  as  to  the  part  of  his  work  affected 
by  them.  Now  in  the  case  of  the  universe  we  have  not  this 
knowledge,  and  the  suspense  of  judgment  must  needs  be  in- 
definite. We  cannot  separate  the  work  from  the  conditions. 
In  order  to  arrive  at  any  final  judgment  we  ought  to  know 
whether  the  conditions  themselves  were  given  with  any  and 
what  design,  and  if  so,  whether  or  not  subject  to  other  condi- 
tions. And  thus  the  inquiry  would  become  endless,  and  we 
should  never  have  anything  solid  to  show  for  it.  In  short, 
the  frame  of  nature  is  what  it  is,  neither  more  nor  less.  If  we 
believe  it  to  be  the  work  of  an  extremely  powerful  being,  of 
intelligence  and  activities  more  or  less  analogous  to  our  own, 
then  we  must  also  believe  that  it  was  and  is  intended  to  be 
just  what  it  is.  What  inferences  of  any  practical  value  could 
be  drawn  from  that  conclusion  is  rather  too  wide  a  question 
to  be  taken  in  the  course  of  a  digression.  Some  of  those  which 
might  be  drawn  by  an  observer  confining  himself  strictly  to 
the  evidence  would  be  as  follows  :  that  if  the  being  in  question 
took  any  pleasure  in  his  operations,  it  could  only  be  the  purely 
intellectual  pleasure  of  working  out  a  set  of  fixed  rules,  which 
he  might  possibly  be  supposed  to  have  fixed  by  his  own  choice 
with  that  pleasure  in  view  ;  that  he  had  no  conception  of  pain, 
and  was  therefore  regardless  of  the  amount  of  it  that  might 
be  involved  in  executing  the  grand  scheme  of  the  universe 
(for  one  would  not  gratuitously  ascribe  malice  to  him)  ;  and 


248  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

that  if  that  scheme  had  any  ulterior  object,  it  was  not  the 
happiness  of  Hving  creatures  generally  or  of  any  particular 
species  of  them.  These  inferences,  however,  are  not  such  as 
expounders  of  natural  theology  either  desire  or  profess  to 
arrive  at ;  and,  as  I  do  not  myself  attach  any  particular  validity 
to  the  assumptions  on  which  they  would  depend,  it  seems 
needless  to  dwell  on  them. 

But  now   let  us   assume   that  we    believe    in    design    on 
independent  grounds.     Will  this  take  us  much  farther  .-*     We 
still  cannot  criticize  the  works  of  nature  by  the  analogy  of  the 
productions  of  human  art  without   knowing  to  what  extent 
the  objects  and  conditions  are  similar :  we  shall  therefore  still 
find  ourselves  in  the  same  condition  of  absolute  suspense.     If 
we  take  it  as  known  from  other  sources  that  the  universe  is  a 
work  of  perfect  wisdom  and  goodness,  and  perfectly  adapted 
to  fulfil  some  purpose  which  does  not  appear  on  the  face  of 
things,  and  which  we   can   only  partly  understand,  then  we 
have  after  a  sort  an  account  of  the  whole  matter.     But  it  is 
an  account  which  the  witness  of  nature   itself  cannot  either 
add    to    or    confirm    in    any    way.       Detailed    criticism    and 
detailed   apologies — for  such  is  the  tone   of  modern  natural 
theology  at  times — are  alike  in   the  air,  or   rather   /;/  vacuo. 
It  is  not  uncommon  to  speak  of  the  wastefulness  of  nature  as 
if   it   were   something  requiring    an  excuse.     But    why   is  it 
esteemed  a  merit  in  human  operations  to   effect  the  desired 
result    with    the    least    possible    expenditure    of    work    and 
materials  }     Plainly  because  the  available  work  and  materials 
are  limited.     If  the  resources  of  the  universe   were  at  one's 
disposal,  there  would  be  no  occasion  for  economy.     So  far  as 
\\e    can     form    any    expectation    in    the    matter,    we    might 
reasonably  expect  a  magnified  human  intelligence  command- 
ing all  the  powers  of  nature  to  be  at  least   as  wasteful  as 
nature  actually  is.     The  stability  or   instability  of  the  exist- 
ing order  of  nature  cannot,  in  like  manner,  be  judged  perfect 
or  imperfect  unless  we  know  whether  or  not  the  order  was 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  249 

intended  to  be  permanent.  It  was  an  accepted  opinion  till 
very  lately  that  the  solar  system  was  a  self-maintaining  and 
self- compensating  machine  which,  if  left  to  itself,  would  go 
on  for  ever.  And,  strangely  enough,  it  was  commonly  held 
by  the  same  persons  who  extolled  this  as  a  perfection  that 
the  solar  system,  or  at  any  rate  the  part  of  it  inhabited  by 
mankind,  was  intended  to  last  only  a  few  thousand  years, 
and  at  the  end  of  that  time  to  be  destroyed.  On  their 
assumptions  the  designer  of  the  solar  system  acted  like  a 
builder  who  should  put  a  stone  house  where  a  wooden  shed 
would  have  done  as  well :  unless,  indeed,  it  were  a  mere 
display  of  magnificence  like  that  of  a  barbaric  prince  at 
whose  command  whole  palaces  rise  for  the  service  of  a  day's 
festival,  and  are  swept  away  with  all  their  ornaments  when 
the  feast  is  over.  For  precisely  the  same  reasons,  it  would  be 
absurd  to  say  that  the  instability  now  discovered  by  science 
in  the  constitution  of  the  solar  system  is  any  mark  of  imper- 
fection. And  if  we  believe  that  we  have  evidence  or  pre- 
sumption from  other  quarters  of  a  design  tending  to  the 
dissolution  of  the  present  state  of  nature,  then  it  is  quite  fair 
to  speculate  on  the  physical  means  (imperfect  vortex-atoms 
or  the  like)  by  which  it  might  be  carried  out.  Again,  a 
designer  may  be  limited  in  his  choice  of  means  either  by 
external  conditions  or  by  some  reason  of  his  own ;  and  of 
these  conditions  or  reasons  the  spectator  may  know  nothing. 
In  the  case  of  the  sensible  world  and  its  order  it  is  certain 
(apart  from  supernatural  information)  that  we  know  nothing 
of  them  whatever.  All  our  ideas  of  design  and  perfection  areo 
derived  from  the  efforts  of  man,  a  finite  being,  working  for 
definite  objects  and  with  such  instruments  as  he  can  procure : 
and  the  attempt  to  find  something  answering  to  them  in  the 
constitution  of  the  universe  leads  to  nothing  but  insoluble 
perplexities.  All  this  was  most  clearly  seen  by  Spinoza,  and 
the  mastery  of  his  conceptions,  whether  learnt  from  himself 
or  from  some  other  teacher,  is  the  first  condition  of  any  free 


250  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

and  rational  treatment  of  the  questions  which  beset  the 
boundaries  of  our  positive  knowledge.  I  do  not  mean  that  it 
is  necessary  to  accept  Spinoza's  ideas,  but  that  it  is  necessary 
to  know  of  their  existence  and  to  understand  them. 

The  primary  meaning  of  such  terms  2.?>  perfect  and  impcr--: 
feet  is  according  to  Spinoza  not  only  relative,  but  relative  to 
the  accomplishment  of  some  particular  design.  But  the 
formation  of  general  ideas  leads  men  to  take  their  general 
idea  of  a  species  or  kind  as  a  standard,  and  regard  every  de- 
parture from  it  as  an  imperfection.  And  this  way  of  think- 
ing and  speaking  is  applied  indiscriminately  to  natural  and  to 
artificial  productions,  though  we  cannot  ascribe  design,  or 
therefore  apply  any  test  of  perfection  in  this  sense,  to  nature 
as  a  whole. 

'  For  that  eternal  and  infinite  being  which  we  call  God  or  naturee 
acts  by  the  same  necessity  wherewith  it  exists  .  .  .  so  that  the  reason 
or  cause  why  God  or  nature  acts,  and  why  he  exists,  is  one  and  the 
same.  As  therefore  he  exists  not  for  the  sake  of  any  end,  so  he  acts 
for  the  sake  of  none  ;  but  hath  as  well  of  existing  as  of  acting  no 
beginning  nor  end.  That  which  is  called  a  final  cause  is  nothing  but 
the  desire  of  man  itself,  considered  as  the  origin  or  primary  cause 
of  anything.  As  when  we  say  that  to  be  inhabited  was  the  final 
cause  of  this  or  that  house,  then  'tis  plain  we  understand  merely  this, 
that  a  man  having  conceived  in  his  mind  the  conveniency  of  dwelling 
in  a  house,  was  thereupon  desirous  to  build  it." 

Perfection  and  imperfection,  then,  are  relative  notions  or 
ways  of  thinking,  dependent  on  our  classification  and  com- 
parison of  things.  If  we  try  to  apply  them  on  a  universal^- 
scale,  the  only  class-notion  remaining  with  us  for  the  purpose  ' 
is  the  genus  generalissi7num  of  mere  being,  and  we  must  mea- 
sure perfection  by  amount  of  being  or  reality.  Thus  Spinoza 
explains  his  own  former  definition  of  perfection  as  identical 
with  reality.'  And  apparently  he  regards  it,  or  tends  in  this 
place  to  regard   it,  as  only  a   particular  aspect  of  things  to 

'  Eth.  ii.  def.  6. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  251 

finite  minds  that  one  should  appear  to  have   '  pkis  entitatis 
seu  realitatis  '  than  another.     But  on  this  he  is  not  explicit. 

The  ethical  notions  of  good   and  evil  are  the  notions  of^ 
perfection  and  imperfection,  as  applied   to  human  character 
and  conduct  by  means  of  a  normal  idea  or  standard  of  man. 
That  the  terms  are  in  themselves  relative  is  obvious. 

'  Music  is  good  for  a  melancholic  patient,  bad  for  a  man  in  grief ; 
for  a  deaf  man  it  is  neither  good  nor  bad.  But  though  this  be  so, 
yet  these  words  are  to  be  kept  in  use.  For  since  we  desire  to  form 
an  idea  of  min  as  a  type  of  human  nature  to  be  set  before  us,  it 
will  be  convenient  to  keep  these  words  in  the  sense  I  have  mentioned. 
By  good  I  shall  therefore  understand  hereafter  that  which  we  are-' 
assured  is  a  means  for  approaching  more  and  more  nearly  to  the 
pattern  of  human  nature  we  set  before  ourselves  ;  and  by  evil  that 
which  we  are  assured  is  a  hindrance  to  our  copying  of  the  same  pattern. 
Further,  we  shall  speak  of  men  as  more  or  less  perfect,  as  they 
approach  this  pattern  more  or  less  nearly.' 

Some  definitions  follow,  of  which  we  need  only  say  that, 
by  a  distinction  now  first  introduced,  a  contingent  thing  is 
defined  as  that  which  is  not  known  to  be  necessary  or  impos- 
sible in  respect  of  itself,  or  which  we  can  equally  well  conceive 
to  exist  or  not  to  exist ;  3. possible  thing  as  one  not  known  to 
be  necessary  or  impossible  in  respect  of  its  conditions,  or  as 
to  which  we  do  not  know  if  the  conditions  required  for  its 
production  are  fulfilled.  There  is  a  single  axiom  :  *  No  par- 
ticular thing  is  found  in  nature  which  is  not  exceeded  in 
power  and  strength  by  some  other  :  but  whatsoever  thing  be 
taken,  another  more  powerful  can  be  found,  whereby  the  first 
may  be  destroyed.' 

Man  is  a  part  of  nature  ;  his  powers  are  limited  and  sub-° 
ject  to  be  overmastered   by  external  causes.     On    external 
causes,  too,  depends  the  strength  of  human  passions  ;  for  pas-      / 
sion  is  the  modification  of  the  mind  under  an  external  cause       ^ 
Hence  flows  a  proposition  of  the  first  practical  importance, 
that    *  emotion  cannot  be  controlled  or  removed,  .save  by  a 


V 


252  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

contrary  emotion  stronger  than  that  which  is  to  be  controlled.'  ^ 
Repeatedly  one  is  led  to  marvel  at  Spinoza's  critics,  and  ask 
oneself  if  they  really  have  read  him  :  and  here  one  stops  to 
doubt  whether  this  most   true  and  pregnant  statement  can 
ever  have  been  considered  by  those  who  represent  Spinoza  as 
a  framer  of  mere  intellectual  puzzles,  having  no  root  in  the 
deeper  part  of  man's  feelings.     It  is  not  insignificant  that  the 
proof,  which  however  would  not  add  much  to  the  conviction 
of  a  modern  reader,  is  in  form  physiological.     Hence  know- 
ledge, as  such,   is  incompetent  to   restrain  the  passions  :  it 
can  have   that    effect   only   in    so  far  as    it  is    an    emotion.- 
And   in    fact  knowledge  of  good  or  evil   is   in  the  nature  of 
pleasure  or  pain  ;  for  it  is  by  reference  to  supposed  utility^ 
which  involves  reference  to  pleasure  and  pain,  that  we  deter- 
mine any  particular  thing  to   be   good   or  evil.     Thus   '  the 
knowledge  of  good  and  evil  is  nothing  else  than  an  emotion 
of  pleasure  or  pain,  in  so  far   as   we  are  conscious  thereof.' 
Observe  that  this  knowledge,  or  in  English  it  would  be  better 
to  say  judgment,  is  not  as  yet  assumed  to  be  correct.     Or,  if 
we  say  that  pleasure  as  such  is  always  good,  and  pain  as  such 
always  bad,  which  Spinoza  does  say  later  (Pr.  41  of  this  Part), 
we  may  affirm  that  an  immediate  judgment  of  good  or  evil  is 
correct  in  itself,  but  not  necessarily  so  with  regard  to  concomi- 
tants and  consequences.     But  even  if  we  have  a  true  judgment 
{vera  boni  et  inali  cognitio)  the  emotion  produced  by  it  may 
not  prevail  over  other  emotions  conflicting  with  it.     For  emo- 
tion  due  to  a  present  exciting  cause  is,  other  things  being 
equal,  stronger  than  that  which  proceeds  from  contemplation 
of  something  distant  in  time  or  place:  and   so  memory  and 
expectation  are  themselves  more  intense  in  proportion  to  the 
nearness  of  their  objects  ;  unless  indeed  the  remoteness  in 
time  of  the  different  objects  compared  be  such  that  for  our 
imagination  both  are  practically  infinite.^     Again,  that  which 
we  conceive  as  necessary  affects  us  more  strongly  than  that 

'  Elh.  iv.  7.  2  Prop.  14.  '  Prop.  9,  lo. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  253 

which  is  conceived  as  possible  or  contingent.  In  this  and 
other  ways  the  desires  arising  from  a  true  knowledge  of  good 
and  evil  may  be  restrained  or  suppressed  by  others  arising 
from  divers  contrary  emotions.  And  in  particular  '  the  desire 
arising  from  the  knowledge  of  good  and  evil,  so  far  as  this 
knowledge  has  regard  to  the  future,  may  easily  be  constrained 
or  extinguished  by  the  desire  of  things  which  are  agreeable 
in  the  present'  ^  Hence  the  weakness  of  human  nature  and 
the  difficulty  of  obeying  the  dictates  of  reason  ;  hence  the 
danger  of  wrong-doing  in  the  face  of  knowledge,  whereof  the 
Preacher  said.  He  that  increaseth  knowledge  increaseth  sorrow. 
We  see  that  Spinoza  felt  profoundly  and  acutely  the  need  of 
understanding  being  'touched  with  emotion'  before  it  can 
bring  forth  the  fruit  of  good  living.  But  his  purpose  is  not  to 
discourage  men  from  well-doing. 

'  This  I  say  not  for  any  such  purpose  as  to  conclude  that  ignor- 
ance is  to  be  chosen  before  knowledge,  or  that  a  fool  and  a  man  of 
understanding  differ  nothing  as  to  the  control  of  their  passions  ;  but 
because  it  is  needful  to  know  as  well  the  power  as  the  weakness  of 
our  nature,  that  we  may  determine  what  reason  can  and  cannot  do 
in  controlling  the  passions.  And  in  this  part,  as  I  have  promised, 
I  shall  treat  only  of  human  weakness.  For  of  the  power  of  reason 
over  the  passions  I  am  minded  to  treat  apart.'  ^ 

Leaving  it,  then,  for  future  consideration  how  the  power 
of  following  reason  is  to  be  acquired,  Spinoza  proceeds  to  set^ 
forth  what  the  precepts  of  reason  are.     He  begins  with  a  sum- 
mary introduction  which  gives  the  leading  ideas  of  his  ethical 
system  in  a  wonderfully  short  compass. 

'  Since  reason  demands  nothing  against  nature,  it  therefore  0 
demands  that  every  man  do  love  himself,  seek  his  own  interest  (I 
mean  that  which  is  truly  so),  and  desire  whatsoever  truly  leads  a  man 
to  greater  perfection  ;  and  generally  that  every  man  endeavour,  so  far 
as  in  him  lies,  to  maintain  his  own  being.  And  this  is  as  necessary  a 
truth  as  that  the  whole  is  greater  than  its  part.  Then  forasmuch  as 
virtue  is  nothing  else  than  acting  by  the  proper  laws   of  one's  own 

•  Prop.  16.  =  Prop.  17,  Schol. 


254  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

nature,  and  no  man  endeavours  to  maintain  his  own  being  otherwise 
than  by  those  laws  :  it  follows  in  the  first  place  that  the  foundation 
of  virtue  is  this  very  endeavour,  and  that  happiness  doth  consist  in 
a  man's  having  power  to  maintain  his  own  being.  Secondly  it  follows 
that  virtue  is  to  be  desired  for  its  own  sake,  and  nothing  prefer- 
able or  more  useful  can  be  found  for  whose  sake  it  should  be  desired. 
And  thirdly,  it  follows  that  men  who  kill  themselves  are  infirm  of 
mmd,  and  merely  overcome  by  external  causes  repugnant  to  their 
OAvn  nature. '  Again,  it  follows  from  the  fourth  postulate  of  the  second c 
Part  ^  that  we  never  can  bring  it  to  pass  that  we  need  nothing  outsidfe 
us  to  maintain  our  being,  or  live  without  any  conversation  with 
things  that  are  outside  us  ;  and  if  moreover  we  consider  our  own 
mind,  our  understanding  would  surely  be  less  perfect  if  the  mind 
were  alone  and  understood  not  anything  beyond  itself.  Thus  there  be 
many  things  outside  us,  which  are  useful  for  us  and  therefore  to  be  de- 
sired. Among  these  none  more  excellent  can  be  thought  of  than  such 
as  wholly  agree  with  our  own  nature  :  since  if  two  individuals  of  the 
same  nature  are  joined  together,  they  make  a  new  individual  twice  as 
powerful  as  either.  Nothing,  therefore,  is  so  useful  to  man  as  man  ; 
nothing  more  excellent,  I  say,  can  be  sought  by  men  towards  main- 
taining their  being  than  that  all  should  so  agree  in  all  things  as  that 
the  minds  and  bodies  of  all  should  make  up  as  it  were  one  mind  and 
one  body,  and  all  together  striVe  to  maintain  their  being  to  the  best 
of  their  power,  and  all  together  seek  the  common  interest  of  all. 
Hence  it  follows  that  men  who  are  governed  by  reason,  or  who  seejc 
their  own  interest  after  the  guidance  of  reason,  desire  nothing  for 
themselves  which  they  desire  not  for  other  men  ;  and  therefore  also 
they  be  just,  faithful,  and  honourable.' 

This  is  given  expressly  as  a  short  preliminary  sketch,  in 
order  to  obviate  the  prejudices  of  those  who  might  be  disposed 
to  think  '  that  this  principle,  namely,  that  every  man's  duty  is 
to  seek  his  own  interest,  is  the  beginning  of  wickedness,  and 
not  of  virtue  and  righteousness.'  But  the  outlines  of  an 
ethical  system  are  quite  distinctly  laid  down;  and  we  mayo 
conveniently  pause  here  to  notice  the  singular  resemblance  to 

'  It  is  difficult  to  see  why  a  point  of  detail  like  this  should  be  made  so  pro- 
minent.    Can  Spinoza  have  been  thinking  of  Uriel  Da  Costa  ? 

-  '  The  human  body  has  need  for  its  maintenance  of  many  other  bodies, 
whereby  it  is  constantly  as  it  were  refashioned. ' 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  255 

Stoic  doctrine.  A  life  according  to  reason,  which  consists  in*" 
following  out  the  law  of  one's  own  nature,  or  self-preservation 
in  the  fullest  sense,  was  precisely  that  which  the  Stoics  aimed 
at.  What  they  meant  by  following  nature,  however  vague 
the  phrase  appears  in  itself,  is  the  same  that  Spinoza  means 
by  sumn  esse  conservare.  It  is  the  putting  forth  and  main- 
tenance of  the  activities  proper  to  the  individual  and  the  species. 
With  them  no  less  than  with  Spinoza  self-conservation  was 
the  ultimate  spring  of  action. 

For  them,  likewise,  it  is  a  fundamental  axiom  that  only 
in  the  society  of  his  fellow-men  can  man  effectually  preserve 
his  being,  fulfil  the  law  of  his  specific  welfare,  or,  as  they  said, 
*  follow  nature.'  Both  the  Stoics  and  Spinoza  seem  to  treat 
the  social  character  of  man  as  a  fact  of  common  experience 
not  open  to  contradiction  and  requiring  no  proof.  Their 
morality  is  so  far  egoistic  that  they  admit  as  a  first  principle 
that  every  man  must  seek  his  own  welfare.  But  it  is  not 
selfish  ;  for  the  very  first  of  their  mediate  axioms  is  the  con- 
tradiction of  selfishness.  The  first  condition  of  a  man's  wel- 
fare is  the  welfare  of  the  society  of  which  he  is  a  part,  or,  as 
the  Stoics  said,  a  limb.  Practical  morality  is  therefore  not 
individual  but  social,  and  the  reasonable  man  can  find  his 
own  weal  only  by  pursuing  the  common  weal  and  doing  good 
to  his  fellow-men. 

There  are  other  points  of  coincidence,  for  example  the 
determinism  which  is  hardly  less  prominent  in  the  Stoics 
than  in  Spinoza,  and  the  stress  laid  on  the  active  nature  of 
virtue.  On  the  other  hand  there  are  great  differences  in  the 
general  philosophical  bases  of  the  two  systems.  The  Stoics 
were  devoted  adherents  of  teleology,  which  Spinoza  wholly 
rejects  ;  and  to  follow  nature  was  to  them  the  same  thing  as 
to  follow  reason,  because  they  held  nature,  both  in  its  general 
constitution  and  in  specific  forms,  to  be  eminently  reasonable. 
Spinoza  could  not  speak  of  'following  Nature'  as  they  did, 
though   he  speaks  with    them  of  following  reason,  and  coin- 


256  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

cides  with  Stoic  language  even  in  the  detail  of  ascribing  free- 
dom as  a  special  honourable  attribute  to  the  wise  or  reason- 
able man.     '  The  wise  man  alone   is  free,  and  the  fool  is  a 
slave '  was  one  of  the  famous   Stoic   paradoxes  :  a  paradox 
for  this  reason,  that  wisdom   in  the   Stoic   sense  is   an   ideal 
state  of  passionless  perfection  which  hardly  anyone  attains, 
and  whoever  has  not  attained  this  wisdom  is  yet  in  the  outer 
darkness  of  folly.     A  form   of  speech   like  this  might  easily 
have  been  picked  up  by  Spinoza  from  Horace  or  Cicero  ;  but 
as  to  the  deeper  resemblances,  I  do  not  think  they  are  to  be 
ascribed  to  imitation,  for  the  very  reason  that  they  go  so  far 
down.     It  is  certain  that  Spinoza's  acquaintance  with  Greeko 
philosophy  was  superficial  ;  anything  he  knew  of  the  Stoics 
must  have  been  at  second-hand,  and    the    resemblances    in 
question  have  much  more  the  air  of  being  due  to  independent 
work  on  parallel  lines  than  of  being  derived  from  second-hand 
information.     One    very   characteristic    point    of    Spinoza'sc 
ethical  theory,  the  doctrine  that  emotion  can  be  controlled 
only  by  emotion,  is  entirely  absent  from  the  teaching  of  the 
Stoics.     They  trust  to  pure  reason  to  furnish  not  only  light 
but  heat  and   motive  power,  thus  ignoring  the  strength  and 
bondage  of  the    passions,    the    '  affectuum    vires '   on    which 
Spinoza  so  minutely  and   pitilessly  dwells.     The   difference 
may  not  be  of  great  practical  importance  if  we  compare  the 
two  systems  as  working  systems  of  morality,  in  which  point 
of  view   they  seem  almost  identical.     For  the  mental  disci- 
pline and  contemplation  recommended  by  the  Stoics  are  of  a 
kind  well  fitted   to  produce  the   moral  emotion  required  by 
Spinoza  and   all   the   best  modern   moralists  as  a  necessary 
condition  of  righteousness,  or  rather  the  constant  reserve  of 
moral  emotion  which  we  call   a  moral  temper.     And,  if  the 
disposition  be  produced,  it  matters  little  for  practical  purposes 
whether  it  finds  its  due  place  in  the  scientific  account  of  the 
process  given  by  the  teachers.     This  temper  of  moral  devo- 
tion, if  one  may  so  call  it,  and  the  means  of  maintaining  it, 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN,  257 

were  indeed  recognized  as  of  importance ;  for  example,  they 
are  not  unfrequently  considered  by  Marcus  Aurelius  ;  but 
these  reflexions  go  side  by  side  with  positive  statements  that 
the  mere  knowledge  of  good  and  evil  suffices  to  overcome 
evil  impulses  ;  or  in  other  words  that  vice  is  nothing  but 
ignorance. 

The  scientific  advance  of  Spinoza's  doctrine  upon  this  is 
very  great,  and  is  of  itself  enough  to  establish  his  independent 
merit.' 

The  following  propositions,  in   which  Spinoza  works  out  a 
the  doctrines  briefly  sketched  in  the  passage  last  translated, 
fall  into  four  groups. 

The  first  deals  with  self-maintenance  as  the  foundation  of 
virtue  (Prop.  19-25)  :  the  second  with  intelligence  as  the 
foundation  of  ethical  judgment  (26-28)  :  the  third  w^ith  the 
common  nature  and  interests  of  men  as  the  ground  of  social 
ethics  (29-37)  :  the  fourth  considers  in  detail  what  bodily  and 
mental  affections  are  good  or  bad  with  reference  to  man's 
common  weal,  and  herein  of  the  conduct  and  duties  of  the 
reasonable  man  (38-73)  :  lastly,  the  ethical  maxims  arc 
collected  and  restated  in  an  Appendix. 

First,  the  self-maintaining  activity  is  the  foundation  of 
virtue.  For  virtue  is  active  power,  and  power  is  the  affirma- 
tion of  the  agent's  existence.  Living  must  come  before  living 
well,  and  no  man  can  desire  a  virtuous  life  without  also 
desiring  life  itself.  '  Virtuous  action,  as  such  {ex  virttite 
absolute  agere),  is  in  us  nothing  else  than  to  act,  live,  or  main- 
tain one's  own  being  (these  three  are  all  one)  according  to 
reason  and  on  the  footing  of  seeking  our  own  interest'  "^ 

Now  the   self-affirmation  of  the  mind   is   understanding, ^^ 
since  the  proper  nature  of  the  human  mind  is  to  understand  : 
so    that  the  self-maintaining  endeavour  which  is  the  begin- 

'  On  the   resemblance  and  contrast  between  Spinoza  and  the  Stoics,  comp.Tre 
Trendelenburg,  Hislor.  Beit!  age,  iii.  396-397. 
^  Prop.  24. 

S 


258  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

I 
ning  of  virtue  is  an  endeavour  after  understanding.       Hence 

)  good  is  whatever  help?  the  understanding,  evil  whatever 
hinders  it  ;  and  the  highest  good  is  the  knowledge  of  God, 
the  most  complete  object  of  knowledge  and  the  condition  of 
all  other  knov/ledge  and  existence.  To  know  God  (in  other 
words  to  know  the  order  of  nature  and  regard  the  universe 
as  orderly)  is  the  highest  function  of  the  mind  :  and  know- 
ledge, as  the  perfect  form  of  the  mind's  normal  activity,  is 
good  for  its  own  sake  and  not  as  a  means. 

The  attempt  to  reduce  the  proper  nature  and  function  of 
the  mind  to  pure  intelligence,  which  is  made  in  Pr.  26,  is  open 
to  much  criticism.  It  depends  on  the  doctrine  that  all  real 
action  is  a  function  of  intellect  (Part  3,  Pr.  3)  :  but  even 
assuming  this,  the  self-maintaining  effort  of  the  mind  '  qua- 
tenus  ratiocinatur '  is  briefly  taken  as  equivalent  to  and  in- 
volving the  maintenance  or  welfare  of  the  whole  man.  Theo 
supremacy  of  reason  is  insufhciently  explained  and  not 
proved  at  all.'  Spinoza's  position  here  is  no  doubt  connected 
with  the  Peripatetic  theory  of  the  active  intellect,  and  pre- 
pares the  way  for  the  peculiar  developments  of  the  fifth  Part 
of  the  Ethics. 

The  next  group  of  propositions  leads  up  to  the  social 
grounds  of  morality  by  a  chain  of  formal  proof  which  is  more 
ingenious  than  convincing,  and  seems  not  even  formally  invul- 
nerable. For  instance,  '  commune  aliquid  nobiscum  '  in  Prop. 
29  appears  to  be  used  in  a  different  sense  from  'cum  nostra 
natura  commune '  in  Prop.  30 :  and  Prop.  30  is  difficult  to  follow. 
It  is  easy  to  understand  the  position  of  Prop.  29,  that  we  can- 
not be  affected  for  good  or  harm  by  anything  which  has  not 
'  commune  aliquid  nobiscum  : '  e.g.  bodily  hurt  must  be  in- 
flicfed  by  a  material  body.  But  how  then  can  we  say  with 
Prop.  30  that  a  thing  is  never  hurtful  '  per  id  quod  cum  nos- 
tra natura  commune  habet .'' '  One  human  body  may  hurt 
another  very  much,  by  knocking  it  down  or  otherwise.  If 
we  say  that  this  depends  not  on   the  assailing  body  being 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN. 


259 


human,  but  on  its  being  a  solid  body,  the  common  properties 
of  matter  still  remain:  A  runs  against  B  and  hurts  himself: 
it  is  true  he  might  have  hurt  himself  as  much  or  more  by 
running  against  a  post.  But  in  any  case  the  properties  of 
mass  and  impenetrability  are  common  to  A's  body  and  B's, 
and  are  of  the  essence  of  the  hurt  that  follows.  For  if  parts 
of  A's  body  and  B's  could  be  in  the  same  place  at  once,  there 
would  be  no  resistance,  no  violent  compression  of  the  collid- 
ing parts,  and  no  hurt.  Or  if  natura  includes,  as  it  probably 
does,  the  amount  and  distribution  of  energy  in  the  particular 
material  system  affected  (cp.  Prop.  39),  still  the  difference  or 
incongruousness  between  the  disturbed  system  and  the 
external  body  is  not  of  kind  but  of  degree.  There  is  still 
'  aliquid  commune.'  I  think  it  must  be  allowed  that  Spinoza's 
way  of  talking  of  «rt:/;^r^  in  this  and  similar  passages  is  not 
free  from  residual  entanglements  of  scholasticism. 

Spinoza's  object  is  to  show  that  men  disagree  only  in  so 
far  as  they  are  swayed  by  passion,  and  agree  in  so  far  as  they 
are  governed  by  reason.  Passion  being  an  infirmity  or  nega- 
tion, men  cannot  be  said  to  agree  in  it ;  just  as  it  is  an  abuse 
of  language  to  say  that  white  and  black  are  similar  in  not 
being  red.  The  counter-proposition  that  '  in  so  far  as  men 
live  according  to  reason,  they  always  and  necessarily  agree,' 
is  supported  by  an  appeal  to  experience  which  is  more  satis- 
factory than  the  formal  reasoning. 

'  Experience  likewise  bears  witness  to  our  proposition  every  day, 
so  clearly  and  abundantly  that  it  is  a  common  speech,  that  man  is 
as  a  God  to  man.  Yet  it  seldom  happens  that  men  live  according 
to  reasoa  ;  but  such  is  their  fashion  that  they  mostly  bear  ill  will  and 
do  mischief  to  one  another.  Nevertheless  they  cannot  endure  a  life 
of  solitude,  so  that  the  definition  of  man  as  a  social  animal  hath  been 
in  general  approved  :  as  indeed  it  is  the  truth  of  the  matter  that  far 
more  convenience  than  hurt  arises  from  the  common  fellowship  of 
men  '  {i.e.  even  when  they  do  not  live  according  to  reason).  '  Where- 
fore let  the  satirists  make  sport  of  human  affairs  as  much  as  they  will ; 
let   theologians  decry  them  ;  let   misanthropes  do  their  utmost  to 

•  s  2 


26o  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

extol  a  rude  and  churlish  life,  despising  men,  and  admiring  the 
brutes  :  yet  men  shall  find  that  their  needs  are  much  best  satisfied 
b}'  mutual  help,  and  that  only  by  joining  their  strength  they  can 
escape  the  dangers  that  everywhere  beset  them  ;  not  to  say  how  much 
more  excellent  it  is  and  worthy  of  our  knowledge  to  consider  the 
actions  of  men  than  of  beasts.'  ^ 

Passages  of  this  kind  give  to  Spinoza's  system— strange 
as  this  may  appear  to  such  as  know  it  only  at  second-hand — 
the  character  of  a  morality  of  common  sense  :  and  herein  he 
shows  an  affinity  to  Aristotle's  cast  of  thought  which  in  this 
particular  place  is  conspicuous.  The  position  that  good  men  ' 
are  naturally  friends,  and  that  theirs  is  the  best  and  only 
durable  friendship,  is  dwelt  upon  with  some  fulness  in  the 
Eighth  Book  of  the  Nicomachean  Ethics.^  And  Aristotle 
calls  to  witness  the  ordinary  experience  of  reasonable  men  in 
very  much  the  same  way  as  Spinoza.  In  this  case  imitation 
or  derivation  is  wholly  out  of  the  question  :  Spinoza  knew 
Aristotle  only  in  the  distorted  version  given  by  so-called 
Aristotelian  philosophy.  The  work  of  restoring  Aristotle 
to  his  true  place  has  hardly  been  effected  even  yet :  in  Spi- 
noza's time  it  had  not  been  begun. 

Spinoza  goes  on  to  show  that  the  highest  good  aimed  at 
by  virtuous  or  reasonable  men  is  common  to  all  and  may  be 
equally  enjoyed  by  all,  and  that  the  virtuous  man  desires  the 
same  good  for  his  fellows  as  for  himself  :  ^  and  he  lays  down 
in  outline  the  foundations  of  civil  society  and  law.  His  posi-L> 
tion,  expressed  in  modern  language,  would  be  that  society  is 
antecedent  to  law  ;  that  legal  right  and  wrong  can  exist  only 
with  reference  to  a  government,  and  moral  right  and  wrong 
only  with  reference  to  a  community.  The  form  in  which  he  o 
states  it,  however,  is  that '  every  one  exists  by  an  absolute 
natural  right,'  and  pursues  by  the  same  right  whatever  he 
supposes  to  be  his  own  interest.     If  all  men  lived  according 

'   Pr.  35,  Schol. 

*  Cap.  3,  sqq.      I  am  indebted  for  this  parallel  to  Prof.  Land. 

3    p..      -.A      '.■' 


THE   BURDEN  OF  MAN.  261 

to  reason,  their  desires  and  pursuits  would  never  clash,  and 
the  *  summum  naturae  ius'  would  suffice  them  without  further 
definition.  But,  since  in  fact  men  are  subject  to  passions, 
and  one  man's  desires  are  incompatible  with  another's,  they 
can  live  together  and  form  a  society  only  on  the  footing  of 
mutual  concession.  This  concession  is  guaranteed  by  the 
common  authority  of  the  society,  operating  not  by  reason 
(for  the  passions  can  be  restrained  only  by  stronger  passion) 
but  by  the  fear  of  penalties.  The  course  of  living  prescribed 
by  the  community  under  the  sanction  of  a  penalty  is  law  : 
'  and  the  community  thus  established  by  laws  and  the  power 
of  self-maintenance  is  called  a  state,  and  those  who  are  within 
its  protection  citizens.'  Good  and  ill  desert,  justice  and 
injustice,  depend  on  the  political  order  and  exist  only  in  the 
political  or  social  state,  '  where  it  is  ordained  by  common  con- 
sent what  is  good  and  bad,  and  every  man  is  bound  to  obey 
the  civil  authority.' 

'  In  the  state  of  nature  no  man  is  owner  of  anything  by  common 
consent,  nor  does  anything  exist  which  can  be  said  to  be  one  man's 
more  than  another's  ;  but  all  things  are  all  men's,  and  thus  in  the 
state  of  nature  we  cannot  conceive  any  purpose  of  giving  every  man 
his  own,i  nor  yet  of  depriving  any  one  of  that  which  is  his  :  that  is, 
nothing  done  in  the  state  of  nature  can  be  called  either  just  or  unjust. 
This  becomes  possible  only  in  the  civil  state,  where  it  is  ordained  by 
conmion  consent  what  belongs  to  this  and  to  that  man.' 

Here  we  have  a  first  sketch  of  Spinoza's  theory  of  law  and 
politics,  which  coincides  in  the  main  with  that  of  Hobbes,  and 
so  anticipates  in  its  broad  features  the  analysis  adopted  and 
developed  by  the  later  English  school  of  jurisprudence.  In 
this  place  however  it  is  meagrely  and  not  quite  opportunely 
presented,  and  is  not  seen  to  advantage.  One  is  struck  by 
the  capital  omission  to  distinguish  in  any  way  between  posi- 
tive civil  law,  custom,  and  what  we  now  call  positive  morality. 

'  Voluntas  unicuique  suum  tribuendi  :  alluding  to  the  familiar  definition  of 
justice  in  the  civil  law  (iustitia  est  constans  ct  perpetua  voluntas  ius  suum  cuique 
tribuens,  I.  i.  \). 


262  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE   AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

The  obvious  fact  that  moral  wrong-doing  extends  far  beyond  =: 
disobedience  to  the  civil  law,  which  leaves  untouched  many- 
things  commonly  judged  worthy  of  the  strongest  moral  disap- 
probation, appears  to  be  simply  ignored.  In  order  to  make 
Spinoza's  account  complete  even  in  outline  on  its  own  ground 
and  from  its  own  point  of  view,  we  need  the  conception  of 
positive  morality  as  a  kind  of  informal  law  which  aims  at 
governing  conduct  in  a  particular  society,  and  acts  through 
the  sanctions  of  collective  approbation  and  disapprobation, 
being  administered  not  by  any  set  tribunal  or  officers,  but  by 
the  members  of  the  community  at  large.  But  on  these  points 
we  need  not  dwell  at  present. 

Next  comes  the  consideration  in  detail  of  what  things  are 
useful  and  hurtful  to  man's  common  estate.  In  the  first  place,/-, 
everything  is  useful  which  tends  to  preserve  life,  or,  as  Spinoza 
puts  it  in  the  language  of  his  Cartesian  physics  and  phy- 
siology, '  whatever  tends  to  preserve  the  proportion  of  motion 
and  rest  subsisting  betwixt  the  parts  of  the  human  body  is 
good  ;  and  contrariwise  that  is  bad  which  tends  to  alter  the 
same  proportion  : '  •  the  specific  and  individual  character  of 
any  body  whatever  being  considered  as  resulting  from  the 
mutual  communication  of  motion  among  its  particles  in  a  cer- 
tain definite  proportion.  The  destruction  or  change  of  cha- 
racter consequent  on  the  disturbance  of  this  proportion  in  a 
living  body  is  however  not  necessarily  equivalent  to  death  in 
the  ordinary  sense. 

'  I  am  not  so  bold  as  to  deny,'  adds  Spinoza  in  the  Scholium, '  that 
a  human  body,  keeping  the  circulation  of  the  blood  and  other  pro- 
perties which  are  esteemed  the  marks  of  life,  may  nevertheless 
receive  another  nature  wholly  different  from  its  former  one.  For  no 
reason  compels  me  to  hold  that  the  body  dies  not  unless  it  become 
a  corpse ;  nay  experience  would  seem  to  suggest  the  contrary.  It 
sometimes  befalls  a  man  to  suffer  such  change  as  that  I  would  scarce 
call  him  the  same,  as  I  have  heard  tell  of  a  Spanish  poet,  who  having 
been  seized  with  great  sickness  and  recovered  therefrom,  yet  was  left 

'  Pr.  39,  referring  to  Def.  in  the  Excursus  after  Pr.  13,  part  2. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  263 

so  forgetful  of  his  past  life  that  he  believed  not  the  plays  he  had  writ 
to  be  his  own,  and  might  indeed  have  been  held  for  a  grown-up  child 
if  he  had  forgotten  his  mother-tongue  as  well.  And  if  this  appear 
incredible,  what  shall  we  say  of  infants,  whom  a  man  of  ripe  age 
thinks  to  be  so  unlike  himself  in  kind  that  he  could  never  be  per- 
suaded he  had  been  such  himself,  did  he  not  apply  to  himself  the 
analogy  of  other  men  ?  But  lest  I  should  afford  occasion  to  super- 
stitious persons  for  raising  novel  questions,  I  shall  leave  these  matters 
alone.' 

This  is  the  whole  of  Spinoza's  contribution  to  the  vexed  «> 
question  of  personal  identity,  which  he  seems  to  regard  (and 
rightly  so  from  the  scientific  point  of  view)  as  at  best  merely 
curious.  In  an  equally  general  but  simpler  proposition  which 
immediately  precedes  this  one  •  it  is  laid  down  that  such  '^. 
things  are  good  as  increase  the  capacity  of  the  human  body 
to  receive  impressions  from  without  and  to  impress  its  own 
action  on  outward  things.  For  the  manifold  and  various 
adaptation  of  the  body  is  likewise  an  adaptation  of  the  mind 
and  increases  its  power  of  knowledge.  Pleasure  as  such  is 
good,  since  it  tends  to  increase  of  active  power,  and  pain  as 
such  is  bad.^  But  localized  pleasure  {titillatio)  may  be  bad 
as  interfering  unduly  with  the  activity  of  other  parts  and 
of  the  body  as  a  whole  ;  and  a  pain  which  serves  to  control 
this  local  excess  of  pleasure  may  be  good.  Love  and  desire 
may,  for  the  same  cause,  be  excessive  and  unreasonable. 
Hatred  is  never  good  ;  for  it  aims  at  the  destruction  of  our  ^' 
fellow-man  ;  and  the  same  consequence  holds  of  all  the  emo- 
tions derived  from  it,  such  as  envy,  derision,  contempt,  anger. 
Here  a  very  interesting  Scholium  is  added. 

'  Between  derision  and  laughter  I  mark  a  great  difference.  For 
laughter,  hke  jesting,  is  mere  pleasure  ;  and  therefore  is  in  itself 
good,  so  it  be  not  excessive.  Surely  'tis  but  an  ill-favoured  and  sour 
superstition  that  forbids  rejoicing.  For  why  is  it  a  better  deed  to 
quench  thirst  and  hunger  than  to   drive  out  melancholy?     This  is 

>  Pr.  38. 

-  Laetitia  directe  mala  non  est,  sed  bona  ;  tristitia  autem  contra  directe  est 
mala.     Pr.  41. 


264  SPINOZA  :   HIS   LIFE   AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

my  way  of  life,  and  thus  have  I  attuned  my  mind.  No  deity,  nor 
any  one  but  an  envious  churl,  hath  delight  in  my  infirmity  and  incon- 
venience, nor  reckons  towards  our  virtues  weeping,  sobs,  fear,  and 
other  such  matters  which  are  tokens  of  a  feeble  mind  ;  but  con- 
trariwise the  more  we  are  moved  with  pleasure,  the  more  we  pass  v 
to  greater  perfection,  that  is,  the  more  must  we  needs  partake  of  the 
divine  nature.  Therefore  it  is  the  wise  man's  part  to  use  the  world 
and  delight  himself  in  it  as  he  best  may,  not  indeed  to  satiety,  for 
that  is  no  delight.  A  wise  man,  I  sa}^,  will  recruit  and  refresh  him- 
self with  temperate  and  pleasant  meat  and  drink,  yea  and  -Avith 
perfumes,  the  fair  prospect  of  green  woods,  apparel,  music,  sports 
and  exercises,  stage-plays  and  the  like,  which  every  man  may  enjoy 
without  any  harm  to  his  neighbour.  For  the  human  body  is  com- 
pounded of  very  many  parts  different  of  kind,  which  ever  stand  in 
need  of  new  and  various  nourishment,  that  the  whole  body  alike  may 
be  fit  for  all  actions  incident  to  its  kind,  and  that  by  consequence 
the  mind  may  be  equally  fit  for  apprehending  many  things  at  once.'  ' 

If  at  a  former  passage  we  were  tempted  to  call  Spinoza  a 
Stoic,  we  shall  perhaps  be  tempted  now  to  call  him  an  Epi- 
curean. Here  is  none  of  the  Stoic  disdain  for  the  common 
amenities  of  life,  no  artificial  striving  to  visit  them  with  indif- 
ference or  discredit,  no  attempt  to  make  a  virtue  of  dispensing 
with  them.  Let  us  remember  that  the  speaker  is  one  who  did 
in  his  own  person  largely  dispense  with  them,  and  whose  life 
was  not  only  temperate,  but  quiet  and  frugal  in  the  extreme. 
This  is  not  the  apology  of  a  man  of  the  world  for  his  careless 
living,  but  the  grave  unrepining  approval  of  innocent  pleasures 
by  a  student  debarred  by  his  own  circumstances  from  sharing 
in  many  of  them.  Nor  does  he  approve  them  simply  because o 
they  are  pleasant,  but  as  tending  to  a  high  purpose,  the  many- 
sided  culture  of  body  and  mind.  Yet  the  pursuits  and  enjoy- 
ments he  mentions  are  simple  and  familiar  ones,  such  as  are 
more  or  less  within  the  reach  of  every  one  above  absolute 
poverty,  and  such  as  at  this  day  naturally  present  themselves 
to  an  observer  in  most  civilized  countries.  England,  unhap- 
pily, is  the  ane  land  where  Spinoza's  lesson  falls  most  strangely 

'  Prop.  45,  Schol. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  265 

on  the  ears  of  good  and  well-meaning  men  and  is  most  sorely- 
needed.  In  truth  the  need  is  a  crying  one,  and  we  are  only 
beginning  to  learn  that  rational  recreation  is  a  thing  worth 
studying.  But  perhaps  we  shall  hardly  give  ear  to  Spinoza 
in  this  matter  while  we  refuse  to  profit  by  the  living  example 
of  our  nearest  neighbours  and  kinsfolk.  After  all  it  may  be 
best  that  we  should  go  farther  back  yet  and  learn  of  the 
Greeks,  who  first  and  most  perfectly  discovered  the  worth  and 
dignity  of  human  life.  We  can  say  nothing  better  or  greater 
of  Spinoza's  doctrine  in  this  passage  than  that  he  unconsciously 
Atticizes. 

There  is  something  touching  in  the  thought  of  this  man, » 
weak  in  body,  of  slender  estate,  living  by  sedentary  toil  and 
giving  his  leisure  to  philosophy,  thus  reconstructing  for  him- 
self the  Athenian  ideal  of  a  free  and  joyous  life,  in  which  the 
pursuit  of  beauty  is  chastened  by  wisdom  and  temperance, 
while  wisdom  itself  is  informed  with  the  delight  of  a  fine  art, 
and  contemplation  goes  hand  in  hand  with  the  manhood  and 
active  fellowship  of  citizens.  If  it  be  said  that  this  ideal  fails 
to  include  the  strenuous  and  self-denying  aspects  of  virtue, 
the  proposition  is  at  least  doubtful  ;  but  for  the  present  it 
suffices  to  say  that  Spinoza  at  all  events  prescribes  a  canon 
of  conduct  as  lofty  and  unselfish  as  any  moral  teacher  of 
ancient  or  modern  times.  Not  that  in  Spinoza's  view  any  o 
virtue  is  really  self-denying  ;  for  the  denial  and  restraint  of 
the  unruly  passions  and  of  all  that  we  call  selfish  is  the 
strengthening  and  affirmation  of  man's  true  self  But  let  us 
hear  his  next  precept. 

'  He  who  lives  according  to  reason  endeavours  to  the  utmost  of 
his  power  to  outweigh  another  man's  hate,  anger  or  despite  against 
him  with  love  or  high-mindedness.  .  .  .  He  who  chooses  to  avenge 
wrong  by  requiting  it  with  hatred  is  assuredly  miserable.  But  he 
who  strives  to  cast  out  hatred  by  love  may  fight  his  fight  in  joy  and 
confidence  ;  he  can  withstand  many  foes  as  easily  as  one,  and  is  in 
nowise  beholden  to  fortune  for  aid.     As  for  those  he  doth  conquer. 


266  SPINOZA  :  HIS  IIFE   AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

they  yield  to  him  joyfully,  and  that  not  because  their  strength  faileth, 
but  because  it  is  increased/  ' 

The  ethical  value  of  the  specific  emotions  is  assigned  on  " 
the  principle  that  only  those  are  good  which  spring  from  the 
active  and  rational  part  of  man's  nature.  Hope  and  fear,  since 
they  involve  pain,  are  good  only  so  far  as  they  may  check  the 
excess  of  other  passions  (Pr.  47).  Pity,  for  the  same  reason, 
is  in  itself  worse  than  useless,  and  will  be  shunned  by  the 
reasonable  man  (Pr.  50).  Spinoza  is  careful  to  explain  in 
what  sense  he  means  this,  which  in  fact  is  the  sense  in  which 
the  Stoics  laid  down  similar  rules. 

'A  man  who  rightly  knows  that  everything  follows  from  the  o 
necessity  of  God's  being  and  happens  according  to  the  eternal  laws  i 
of  nature  will  in  truth  find  nothing  worthy  of  hate,  mocker}',  or 
contempt,  nor  will  he  pity  any  one  ;  but,  so  much  as  human  power 
admits,  he  will  endeavour  to  do  well,  as  they  say,  and  be  of  good 
clieer.  Moreover  it  is  to  be  noted  that  he  who  is  lightly  touched 
with  the  passion  of  pity  and  moved  by  the  distress  or  tears  of  another 
often  doth  somewhat  of  the  which  he  afterwards  repents  ;  because  as 
well  we  do  nothing  out  of  passion  Avhich  we  surely  know  to  be  good, 
as  we  are  easily  deceived  by  feigned  lamentations.  But  ^  in  this 
place  I  particularly  intend  a  man  who  lives  according  to  reason. 
For  one  who  is  moved  neither  by  reason  nor  by  pity  to  help  others 
is  justly  called  inhuman,  since  he  acts  as  if  he  had  no  likeness  to 
man.' 

In  like  manner  humility  and  repentance,  though  not 
part  of  the  reasonable  man's  character,  are  relatively  useful, 
and  necessary  for  the  government  of  mankind.  Since  men 
must  err,  it  is  better  they  should  err  on  the  side  of  submission 
than  on  that  of  pride  and  violence.  This  admission  of  a  scale 
of  relative  merit  as  between  passions  and  motives  which  in 
themselves  are  all  alike  unworthy  of  the  reasonable  man  may 
remind  us  of  certain  features  in  the  Stoic  system,  though  the 

'  Prop.  46,  and  Schol. 

•^  Perhaps  we  should  read  aiqin  for  atque.     The  Dutch  version  omits  the  con 
junction  altogether. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  267 

analogy  is  not  exact.  On  the  other  hand  the  emotions  which'^' 
can  be  purely  active,  as  goodwill  (favor),  self-contentment 
{acqniescejitia  in  se  ipso),  honour  {gloria),  may  have  a  reason- 
able origin  and  be  positively  good.  And  generally  'every 
activity  to  which  we  are  determined  by  an  emotion  in  the 
nature  of  passion  may  be  determined  in  us  by  reason  without 
such  emotion  '  (Pr.  59).  No  particular  action  is  in  itself  either 
good  or  bad,  and  therefore  every  particular  action  may  in  some 
conceivable  circumstances  be  induced  by  reason.  The  act  of 
striking,  for  instance,  is  in  itself  the  lifting  of  the  arm,  closing 
of  the  fist,  and  forcible  bringing  down  of  the  arm  ;  and,  consi- 
dered as  a  physical  action,  it  is  a  manifestation  of  the  power 
or  excellence  proper  to  the  human  body  {virtus  quae  ex 
corporis  hicinani  fabrica  concipitur).  But  the  act  may  be 
performed  for  an  infinite  variety  of  purposes,  lawful  or  un- 
lawful, wise  or  foolish.  The  attitude  and  movements  of 
Hamlet  playing  in  good  faith  are  the  same  as  those  of  Laertes 
with  his  poisoned  rapier.  Cicero's  hand  wrote  consummate 
prose  with  the  same  motion  and  characters  as  worthless  verse. 

'  So,  if  a  man  that  is  moved  with  anger  or  hate  is  thereby  deter- 
mined to  close  his  fist  or  move  his  arm,  this  happens  (as  we  showed 
in  the  second  part)  because  one  and  the  same  action  may  be  joined 
with  any  sort  of  images  of  things  ;  and  thus  we  may  be  determined 
as  well  by  images  of  things  we  conceive  confusedly,  as  by  those  we 
conceive  clearly  and  distinctly,  to  one  and  the  same  action.  It 
appears  therefore  that  every  desire  arising  from  an  emotion  of  the 
passionate  kind  would  be  of  no  utility  if  men  could  be  led  by  reason.' 

In  other  words,  reason  and  the  active  emotions  related  to  it 
afford  an  adequate  motive  for  every  reasonably  desirable  act  : 
but  such  motives  will  be  effective  only  so  far  as  the  man  to 
whom  they  are  presented  is  reasonable. 

One  reason  of  desire  being  irrational,  or  not  regarding  the  o 
interest  of  the  agent  as  a  whole,  is  its  proceeding  from  local  '• 
pleasure  or  pain  ;  and   '  since  pleasure  is  mostly  referred  to 
some  one  part  of  the  body,  we  mostly  exercise  the  desire  to 


268  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE   AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

maintain  our  being  without  taking  any  thought  of  our  health  j 
as  a  whole.'  Another  reason  is  the  undue  preponderance  of 
the  present  over  the  future  in  our  most  common  desires.' 
This  however  does  not  occur  when  the  mind  is  guided  by 
reason  in  its  judgments  ;  for  then  it  conceives  things  '  under 
the  form  of  eternity  or  necessity,'  and  facts  are  regarded  in 
their  true  relations  and  independent  of  their  being  past, 
present  or  future.  Hence,  in  so  far  as  we  act  reasonably,  we 
choose  not  only  the  greater  of  two  goods  and  the  lesser  of 
two  evils,  but  a  greater  good  in  the  future  before  a  lesser  in 
the  present,  and  a  lesser  evil  in  the  present  which  is  to  be 
outweighed  by  a  greater  good  in  the  future.^  In  this  group 
of  propositions  it  is  also  pointed  out  that  reasonable  action  is 
never  produced  by  fear  :  '  under  reasonable  desire  we  seek  the 
good  directly  and  avoid  evil  indirectly.  .  .  .  This  is  illus- 
trated by  the  case  of  a  sick  and  a  healthy  man.  The  sick 
man  eats  what  he  dislikes  for  fear  of  death  ;  but  the  whole 
man  enjoys  his  food  and  so  hath  better  use  of  life  than  if  he 
feared  death  and  had  an  immediate  desire  of  avoiding  it.  So 
the  judge,  when  he  sentences  a  criminal  to  death  not  from 
hate  or  anger,  but  merely  for  love  toward  the  public  weal,  is 
led  by  reason  alone.'     (Pr.  6}^,  schol.  2). 

This  part  of  the  Ethics  is  now  brought  to  a  close  by  anc 
enunciation  of  the  qualities  of  the  reasonable,  or,  as  Spinoza 
now  puts  it  with  the  Stoics,  the  free  man.  Here  his  proposi- 
tions assume  the  nature  of  aphorisms  ;  they  cannot  be  con- 
sidered strictly  capable  of  proof,  and  that  which  stands  first, 
one  of  the  noblest  and  most  weighty  sayings  ever  uttered, 
seems  to  foreshadow  the  more  daring  flights  of  the  succeeding 
book.  Yet,  if  we  regard  it  as  a  precept  for  use  in  life,  it  is  on 
a  scientific  view  of  man's  nature  as  just  and  reasonable  as  it  is 

'  Pr.  60,  and  Schol. 

-  Pr.  62,  65,  66.  In  Pr.  66,  '  malum  prassens  minus  quod  causa  est  fuluri 
[futitra  ed.  Bruder  by  misprint]  alicuius  mali '  is  obviously  corrupt.  The  con- 
temporary Dutch  translator  appears  to  have  read  maioris  boni,  which  may  be  ac- 
cepted as  a  practically  certain  correction  {Magcl.  ScJtrifleii,  p.  244). 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  269 

morally  elevating ;  and  the  demonstration  offered  by  Spinoza 
is  extremely  simple. 

'  A  free  man  thinks  of  death  least  of  all  things,  and  his  wisdom  is 
a  meditation  not  of  death  but  of  life. 

Demonstr.  A  free  man,  that  is,  one  who  lives  only  by  the  bidding 
of  reason,  is  not  led  by  the  fear  of  death,  but  immediately  desires 
good  ;  that  is,  to  act,  to  live,  and  maintain  his  own  being  on  the 
footing  of  seeking  his  true  interest.  And  therefore  he  thinks  of  no- 
thing less  than  of  death,  and  his  wisdom  is  a  meditation  of  life  ; 
which  was  to  be  proved.'  {Pr.  67.) 

Again, 

'  If  men  were  born  free,  they  would,  so  long  as  they  were  free, 
form  no  notion  of  good  and  evil.'  (Pr.  68.) 

This  depends  on  a  foregoing  proposition  (64)  that  the 
knowledge  of  evil  is  necessarily  inadequate ;  and  it  seems  to 
be  a  direct  reminiscence  of  Maimonides,  who  says  (More 
Nebuchim,  c.  2)  that  Adam  before  the  Fall  had  a  true 
'  intellectual  comprehension '  and  knew  nothing  of  probable 
opinion,  to  which  the  categories  of  good  and  evil  belong.  By  o 
the  unfallen  intellect  things  were  distinguished  not  as  good 
and  evil,  but  only  as  true  and  false.  Spinoza  gives  in  a 
Scholium  a  not  dissimilar  interpretation  of  the  Mosaic 
history,  and  endeavours  incidentally  to  find  authority  in  it 
for  various  points  of  his  psychology.  To  what  extent  he  was 
serious  in  this  must  be  left  to  every  reader's  conjecture  ;  but 
it  is  quite  possible  that  he  was  really  disposed,  after  the 
example  abundantly  set  by  Maimonides  and  others,  to 
regard  the  legends  of  Genesis  as  elaborate  philosophical 
allegories. 

The  statement  that  '  only  free  men  are  perfectly  grateful  " 
to  one  another,'  which  has  already  been  thrown  out  in 
general  terms,  is  now  given  as  a  formal  proposition  (Pr.  71): 
there  seems  to  be  a  play  on  the  meaning  of  the  adjective 
which  is  rather  more  natural  in  Latin  than  in  English.  On 
the  other   hand  (Pr.  70),  a  free  man  whose  conversation  is 


270  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

among  the  ignorant  will  avoid  receiving  favours  from  them  ; 
for  he  cannot  please  them  except  by  requiting  them  after 
their  own  manner  with  such  things  as  are  good  in  their 
conceit.  But  the  desire  of  the  free  man  is  to  seek  both  for 
himself  and  for  other  men  only  that  which  is  pointed  out  as 
good  by  reason.  '  Therefore  the  free  man,  that  he  may 
neither  come  into  ill  repute  with  the  ignorant,  nor  follow  their 
appetites  instead  of  holding  to  reason  only,  will  endeavour, 
so  far  as  he  may,  to  eschew  favour  from  them.'  But  Spinoza 
is  careful  to  add  a  word  of  explanation  to  show  that  he  does 
not  counsel  a  cynical  and  unsociable  reserve.  'Isayj'C'y^r 
as  he  may.  For  though  men  be  ignorant,  yet  they  are  men, 
and  in  our  necessary  occasions  can  give  a  man's  help,  than 
which  nothing  is  more  excellent.  And  therefore  it  often 
happens  to  be  of  necessity  to  receive  some  favour  from  them, 
and  by  consequence  to  return  thanks  to  them  after  their  own 
fashion.  Moreover  a  certain  caution  must  be  observed  in  the 
act  of  declining  favours,  lest  we  seem  to  despise  men,  or  to 
be  so  avaricious  that  we  fear  having  to  recompense  them, 
and  thus  fall  into  giving  ground  of  offence  by  our  very  care 
to  avoid  it.  So  that  in  declining  favours  regard  must  be  had 
to  expediency  and  good  manners.' 

Again  '  the  free  man  never  acts  fraudulently,  but  always  ino 
good  faith  ; '  and  this  is  laid  down  as  an  universal  proposition 
applicable  even  to  extreme  cases  (Pr.  72).  Lastly  the  reason-o 
able  man  finds  true  and  perfect  freedom  not  in  a  solitary 
independence  but  in  living  in  society  and  under  a  comnion 
law  with  his  fellow-men  (Pr.  'Ji).  It  is  considered  unneces- 
sary to  follow  out  in  detail  the  character  of  the  wise  or,  as  he 
is  now  called,  the  strong  man.  That  he  will  hate  no  man, 
have  no  anger,  envy,  or  contempt  for  any  one,  and  be  free 
from  pride,  easily  follows  from  the  general  propositions 
already  given  as  to  the  conditions  of  social  and  reasonable 
life.  Spinoza  now  proceeds  to  collect  the  precepts  of  right 
living    already    stated    or    implied    in    various    parts    of    his 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  271 

argument  into   a  more  compact  form.     This  appendix  is  as 
follows. 

*  Cap.  I.  All  our  endeavours  or  desires  so  follow  of  necessity  from 
our  nature  that  they  may  be  understood  either  by  that  nature  alone 
as  their  immediate  cause,  or  only  by  regarding  ourselves  as  a  part  of 
nature,  which  cannot  be  adequately  conceived  by  itself  apart  from 
other  particular  things. 

C.  2.  The  desires  which  follow  from  our  nature  in  such  wise  thafj 
they  may  be  understood  by  it  alone  are  those  which  are  ascribed  ^ 
to  the  mind  in  so  far  as  it  is  conceived  as  consisting  of  adequate 
ideas ;  but  other  desires  are  ascribed  to  the  mind  only  in  so  far  as  it 
conceives  things  inadequately,  and  their  strength  and  increase  must 
be  defined  not  by  the  power  of  man  but  by  the  power  of  things  out- 
side us.  And  therefore  the  former  are  justly  called  actions^  the  latter 
passions.  For  the  former  ever  denote  our  power,  the  latter  our  im- 
potence and  maimed  knowledge. 

C.  3.  Our  actions  (that  is,  those  desires  which  be  determined  by 
man's  power  or  by  reason)  are  always  good  ;  the  rest  may  be  either 
good  or  bad 

C.  4.  It  is  therefore  of  exceeding  use  in  life  to  perfect,  so  far  as^ 
we  can,  the  understanding  or  reason,  and  herein  alone  consisteth  the'' 
highest  happiness  or  blessedness  of  man.  Blessedness,  indeed,  is 
nothing  else  than  the  contentment  of  mind  arising  from  the  intuitive 
knowledge  of  God.  And  to  perfect  the  understanding  is  nothing 
else  than  to  understand  God  and  the  attributes  of  God,  and  the  actions 
that  necessarily  follow  from  his  nature.  Wherefore  the  final  aim  of  a 
man  led  by  reason,  that  is,  the  chief  desire  whereby  he  seeks  to 
govern  all  others,  is  that  which  makes  for  the  adequate  conception 
both  of  himself  and  of  all  things  which  be  subjects  of  his  intelli- 
gence. 

C.  5.  There  is  therefore  no  reasonable  life  without  intelligence,  and 
things  are  good  only  in  so  far  as  they  help  man  to  enjoy  that  spiritual 
life  which  the  name  of  intelligence  doth  signify.  And  those  things 
which  hinder  man  from  perfecting  his  reason  and  enjoying  the 
rational  life  are  alone  by  us  called  evil. 

C.  6.  Now  because  all  things  whereof  man  is  the  sole  efficient 
cause  are  necessarily  good,  no  evil  can  happen  to  man  save  by  out- 
ward causes  ;  to  wit,  inasmuch  as  man  is  a  part  of  nature,  whose 
laws  his  nature  is  bound  to  obey,  and  he  to  accommodate  himself  to 
her  in  almost  infinite  ways. 


272  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

C.  7.  And  it  cannot  be  otherwise  than  that  man  should  be  a  part 
of  nature  and  follow  her  common  order  ;  but  if  his  conversation  be  o 
with  such  creatures  as  agree  with  his  own  nature,  thereby  man's 
active  power  will  be  holpen  and  fostered.  Contrariwise  if  he  be 
among  those  whose  nature  agrees  not  with  his  own,  he  will  scarce  be 
able  to  accommodate  himself  to  them  without  some  great  change  in 
himself. 

C.  8.  Whatsoever  is  found  in  nature  which  we  judge  to  be  evil, 
or  to  be  capable  of  hindering  our  existence  and  enjoyment  of  life  in 
reason,  that  we  may  repel  from  ourselves  by  whatever  way  seems  the 
safer.  And  whatever  is  found  on  the  other  hand  which  we  judge 
s^ood  ox  useful  for  the  maintenance  of  our  being  and  enjoyment  of 
life  in  reason,  that  we  may  take  and  convert  to  our  own  use  as  we 
will.  And  generally  every  one  hath  an  absolute  natural  right  of 
doing  what  he  judgeth  to  make  for  his  own  advantage. 

C.  9.  Nothing  can  agree  better  with  the  nature  of  any  particular 
thing  than  other  individuals  of  the  same  kind.  Therefore  (by  cap.  7) 
there  is  nothing  more  useful  to  man  for  the  maintenance  of  his  beingo 
and  enjoyment  of  rational  life  than  a  man  who  governs  himself  by 
reason.  Again,  since  among  particular  things  we  know  of  none  more 
excellent  than  a  man  who  governs  himself  by  reason,  therefore  a  man 
can  in  no  way  better  show  the  power  of  his  skill  and  understanding 
than  in  so  training  up  men  that  at  last  they  may  live  as  true  subjects 
under  che  dominion  of  reason. 

C.  10.  So  far  as  men  bear  to  one  another  envy  or  any  emotion 
derived  from  hate,  they  are  contrary  to  one  another  ;  and  are 
therefore  to  be  feared  in  proportion  to  the  excess  of  their  power  over 
that  of  other  creatures. 

C.  T  I.  Yet  minds  are  conquered  not  by  force  of  arms,  but  by  lovec 
and  highmindedness. 

C.  12.  It  is  of  exceeding  use  to  men  to  enter  upon  acquaintance 
and  so  bind  themselves  together  that  they  may  the  better  make 
tliemselves  all  one  power,  and  generally  to  do  such  things  as  are 
fitted  to  establish  friendship. 

C.  13.  But  for  this  they  need  skill  and  vigilance.  For  men 
be  of  many  minds  (seeing  few  of  them  live  as  reason  prescribes),  and 
yet  are  mostly  envious  and  more  prone  to  revenge  than  to  pity.  So 
that  to  endure  every  man's  humour  and  restrain  oneself  from  copy- 
ing their  passions  is  a  matter  of  no  small  resolution.  Yet  those  who 
rather  chide  men  and  rebuke  their  faults  than  teach  them  virtue,  and 
can  break  their  spirits,  but  not  strengthen  them,  are  grievous  both 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  273 

to  themselves  and  others.  Thus  many  have  been  driven  by  their 
overmuch  impatience  or  misguided  zeal  for  religion  to  live  with 
brutes  rather  than  men  ;  as  boys  and  lads  who  cannot  quietly  bear  to 
be  scolded  by  their  parents  will  go  for  soldiers,  and  choose  the  hard- 
ships of  war  and  a  tyrannical  discipline  rather  than  convenience  at 
home  and  a  father's  counsel  withal,  and  suffer  any  burden  to  be  put 
upon  them  if  only  they  may  spite  their  parents, 

C.  14.  Therefore  although  men  for  the  most  part  carry  every- 
thing after  their  own  fancies,  yet  from  their  common  fellowship  there 
ensues  far  more  convenience  than  harm.  So  it  is  the  better  part  to 
bear  wTong  from  them  with  an  even  mind,  and  be  diligent  in  whatever 
is  fitted  to  bring  about  concord  and  friendship. 

C.  15.  That  which  begetteth  concord  is  that  which  belongs  to 
justice,  equity,  and  good  report.  For,  besides  what  is  unjust  and 
iniquitous,  men  are  also  displeased  with  what  is  in  ill  repute,  or  when 
a  man  doth  reject  the  usage  received  in  their  commonwealth.  And 
for  winning  their  love  those  things  be  chiefly  necessary  which  have 
regard  to  religion  and/zV/y. 

[Reference  is  made  to  previous  propositions  as  to  these  terms. 
Religion  is  the  sum  of  desires  and  actions  proceeding  from  the  idea  ore 
knowledge  of  God,  i.e.  from  the  conception  of  the  order  of  nature 
as  one  and  uniform.     Piety  is  the  desire  of  well-doing  produced  by 
living  according  to  reason.  Pr.  37,  Schol.  i.] 

C.  16.  Concord  is  also  commonly  produced  by  fear ;  but  this  is 
treacherous.  Also  fear  ariseth  from  a  weakness  of  the  mind  and 
therefore  belongs  not  to  the  exercise  of  reason  ;  and  the  same  holds 
of  compassion,  though  it  hath  on  the  face  of  it  a  certain  show  of 
piety. 

C.  17.  Men  are  likewise  overcome  by  liberality,  chiefly  those 
who  have  not  wherewithal  to  buy  the  necessaries  of  life.  But  help- 
ing every  one  in  need  is  far  beyond  the  means  and  convenience  of 
any  private  person.  For  a  private  man's  wealth  is  no  match  for  such 
a  demand.  Also  a  single  man's  opportunities  are  too  n:irrow  for  him 
to  contract  friendship  with  all.  Wherefore  providing  for  the  poor  is  a 
duty  that  falls  on  the  whole  community  and  has  regard  only  to  the 
common  interest. 

C.  18.  In  receiving  favours  and  the  return  of  gratitude  there  is  a 
material  distinction,  as  to  which  see  the  Scholia  to  Pr.  70  and  71. 

[That  is,  the  reasonable  man  endeavours  to  decline  favours  from 
the  ignorant  which  would  place  him  under  embarrassing  obligations  \ 

T 


274  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

but  between  free  men  there  is  a  free  and  unrestrained  affection,  apart 
from  and  above  any  question  of  returning  or  recompensiiig  favours.] 
C.  19.  Meretricious  love,  that  is,  the  lust  of  generation  which 
ariseth  from  outward  beauty,  and  in  general  every  kind  of  love  that 
hath  any  cause  beside  freedom  of  mind,  doth  easily  pass  into  hate, 
unless  (which  is  worse)  it  be  a  kind  of  madness  ;  and  then  more 
discord  than  concord  grows  of  it.  See  the  CoroU.  to  Pr.  31,  Part  3. 
C.  20.  As  concerning  marriage,  'tis  certain  that  it  agrees  with 
reason  if  the  desire  of  bodily  union  is  bred  not  merely  of  outward 
sense  but  of  the  desire  to  beget  children  and  bring  them-  up  in 
wisdom  ;  and  also  if  the  love  of  both  parties,  namely  the  man  and 
the  woman,  has  not  outward  sense  alone  for  its  cause,  but  freedom 
of  mind  in  the  chief  place. 

C.  21.  Concord  is  also  produced  by  flattery  ;  but  this  is  at  the  cost 
of  vile  slavishness  or  falsehood.  None  are  more  easily  taken  with 
flattery  than  the  proud  ones,  who  fain  would  be  first,  and  are  not. 

C.  22.  Dejection  hath  a  false  show  of  piety  and  religion.  And 
though  dejection  be  contrary  to  pride,  yet  is  the  downcast  man  very 
near  being  proud.     See  Schol.  to  Pr.  57. 

C.  23.  Likewise  concord  is  advanced  by  shame,  but  only  in 
things  which  cannot  be  hid.  Also  because  shame  is  in  itself  a  kind 
of  pain  it  belongs  not  to  the  exercise  of  reason. 

C.  24.  The  other  emotions  of  pain  towards  men  are  plainly 
against  justice,  equity,  good  report,  piety  and  religion.  And  though 
indignation  hath  on  the  face  of  it  a  show  of  equity,  yet  life  is  but  law- 
less where  any  man  may  pass  judgment  on  another's  deeds  and  vindi- 
cate his  own  or  another's  right. 

C.  25.  Civility  {?>wdestia),  that  is,  a  desire  of  pleasing  men  which 
is  determined  by  reason,  is  referred  (as  we  said  in  the  Schol.  to  Pr. 
37)  to  piety.  But  if  it  arise  from  passion  ^  it  is  ambition,  a  desire 
whereby  men  do  mostly  stir  up  strife  and  tumults  under  the  pretence 
of  piety.  A  man  who  desires  to  help  others  by  counsel  or  deed,  so  '- 
as  they  may  together  enjoy  the  chief  good,  will  be  very  forward  to 
win  their  love  to  him,  but  not  to  draw  them  into  admiration  of  him, 
that  a  doctrine  may  be  called  after  his  name,  nor  in  any  manner  to 
give  cause  of  offence.  Also  in  common  talk  he  ^vill  eschew  telling 
of  men's  faults,  and  will  speak  but  sparingly  of  human  weakness. 
But  he  will  speak  at  large  of  man's  virtue  and  power,  and  the  means 
of  perfecting  the  same,  that  thus  men  may  endeavour,  not  from  fear 

'  AJfectu  :  but  Spinoza  must  mean  affccUt  qui passio  est. 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  275 

or  disgust,  but  wholly  in  joyfulness,  to  live,  so  far  as  in  them  lies, 
after  the  commandment  of  reason. 

C.  26.  Except  men,  we  know  of  no  particular  thing  in  nature,  in 
twhose  mind  we  may  take  pleasure  and  which  we  may  join  to  our- 
selves by  friendship  or  any  manner  of  society  ;  and  therefore  what- 
ever there  is  beside  men  in  the  world  the  reason  of  our  convenience 
doth  not  require  us  to  preserve,  but  persuades  us  according  to  the 
divers  uses  thereof  to  preserve,  destroy,  or  adapt  it  to  our  own  use 
as  we  will. 

C.  27.  The  utility  we  derive  from  things  outside  us  is  (besides 
the  experience  and  knowledge  we  acquire  i\  om  observing  them  and 
changing  them  from  one  form  into  another)  in  the  first  place  the  con- 
servation of  our  body.  And  in  this  regard  those  things  are  chiefly 
useful  which  can  so  feed  and  nourish  the  body  as  to  make  all  its 
parts  fit  for  their  proper  offices.  For  the  better  fitted  the  body  is  to-^ 
be  impressed  and  to  impress  outward  bodies  in  divers  ways  the  more  fit 
is  the  mind  for  thinking.  {See  Propp.  38  and  39.)  But  of  this  kind 
there  seem  to  be  very  few  things  in  nature.  Wherefore  for  nourish- 
ing the  body  as  it  needs  we  must  use  many  foods  of  different  kinds  : 
the  human  body  being  indeed  made  up  of  very  many  parts  of 
different  kinds,  which  be  in  need  of  constant  and  manifold  nourish- 
ment, that  the  body  may  be  equally  fit  for  performing  all  things  which 
are  within  its  natural  power,  and  consequently  that  the  mind  may 
also  be  equally  fit  for  perceiving  many  different  things. 

C.  28.  Now  for  achieving  this  the  strength  of  every  man  would 
scarce  avail  unless  men  lent  one  another  their  help.  But  money  has 
given  us  a  token  for  everything.  Whence  it  happens,  that  the 
imagination  thereof  doth  mainly  busy  the  minds  of  the  common 
sort  ;  for  they  can  scarce  imagine  any  kind  of  pleasure  without 
having  withal  the  idea  of  money  as  its  cause. 

C.  29.  This  is  the  fault  only  of  them  who  seek  money  not  from 
poverty  nor  for  their  needs,  but  because  they  have  learnt  arts  of  gain 
and  make  a  mighty  show  with  them.  'Tis  true  they  tend  their  bodies 
by  habit ;  but  scantily,  since  they  esteem  themselves  to  be  losing  so 
much  of  their  goods  as  they  spend  on  maintaining  their  own  bodies. 
But  they  who  know  the  right  use  of  money  and  fix  the  measure  of  ^ 
wealth  only  according  to  need  can  live  contented  with  a  litde. 

C.  30.  Since  then  those  things  are  good  which  assist  the  mem- 
bers of  the  body  to  perform  their  oftice,  and  pleasure  consists  in 
this,  that  the  power  of  man,  in  so  far  as  he  is  composed  of  body  and 
mind,  is  advanced  or  increased  ;  therefore  all  things  be  good  which 

T  2 


2/6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

bring  us  pleasure.  Yet  since  things  operate  not  for  any  such  purpose 
as  to  give  us  pleasure,  nor  is  their  power  of  action  limited  according 
to  our  convenience,  and  also  because  pleasure  is  mostly  related  to 
some  one  part  of  the  body  above  the  rest  -,  therefore  most  emotions 
of  pleasure  are  subject  to  excess,  unless  reason  be  on  guard,  and 
consequently  so  are  the  desires  engendered  of  them.  Besides  all 
which  emotion  leads  us  to  count  that  first  which  is  agreeable  in  the 
present,  and  we  cannot  consider  things  future  with  a  proportionate 
liveliness.     See  the  Scholia  to  Pr.  44  and  Pr.  60. 

C.  31.  But  superstition  seemeth  contrariwise  to  hold  that  for 
good  which  brings  pain,  and  that  for  evil  which  brings  pleasure. 
But,  as  we  have  said,  (Schol.  to  Pr.  45)  only  an  envious  man  can 
take  any  delight  in  my  weakness  and  inconvenience.  For  the 
greater  is  our  pleasure  the  more  do  we  pass  to  greater  perfection,  and 
therefore  the  more  do  we  partake  of  the  divine  nature  ;  nor  can 
pleasure  ever  be  bad,  when  it  is  governed  by  a  just  regard  for  our 
interest  as  a  whole.  But  he  who  is  led  by  fear  and  doth  good  only 
to  avoid  toil  is  not  led  by  reason. 

C.  32.  Now  man's  power  is  very  much  confined,  and  is  infinitelyo 
surpassed  by  the  power  of  external  causes ;  and  therefore  we  have-' 
not  any  absolute  power  of  converting  to  our  own  use  things  outside 
us.  Yet  we  shall  bear  with  an  even  mind  that  which  happens  to  us 
against  the  conditions  of  our  own  advantage  if  we  are  aware  that  we 
have  done  our  part  of  the  business,  and  that  the  power  we  possess 
could  not  have  gone  so  far  as  to  avoid  those  evils  ;  and  that  we  are 
a  part  of  the  whole  order  of  nature  and  bound  thereby.  Which  if  we 
clearly  and  distinctly  understand,  that  part  of  us  which  is  described 
as  intelligence^  that  is,  our  better  part,  will  therein  be  wholly  contented 
and  will  endeavour  to  persist  in  that  content.  For  so  far  as  we 
understand,  we  can  desire  nothing  but  what  is  necessary,  nor  can  we 
rest  content  in  aught  but  the  truth  ;  and  therefore  so  far  as  we  under- 
stand these  things  rightly,  the  endeavour  of  our  better  part  agrees 
with  the  universal  order  of  nature.' 

This  summary  docs  not  appear  to  call  for  any  particular 
explanation.  The  equivalence  of  action,  intelligence,  and 
virtue,  which  stands  out  in  the  leading  enunciations,  has 
already  been  remarked  on  ;  the  description  of  intelligence  as© 
'  our  better  part '  at  the  conclusion  is  of  some  importance  as 
leading  up  to  the  doctrine  of  the  following  Part.     Attention 


THE  BURDEN  OF  MAN.  277 

may  be  called  to  the  moral  elevation  of  the  precept  given  in 
cap.  25.  It  is  a  lofty  refinement  of  the  fundamental  duty  of 
good  will  to  men  which  is  not  to  be  found,  so  far  as  I  know, 
in  any  other  moralist.  The  tone  is  very  like  that  of  Marcus 
Aurelius,  but  I  have  not  met  with  an  exact  parallel  to  the 
matter  either  in  M.  Aurelius  or  elsewhere. 


!78  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER   IX. 

THE   DELIVERANCE   OF   MAN. 

Nee  pietas  ullast  velatum  saepe  videri 
vertier  ad  lapidem  atque  omnis  accedere  ad  aras 
nee  procumbere  humi  prostratum  et  pandere  palmas 
ante  deum  delubra  nee  aras  sanguine  multo 
spargere  quadrupedum  nee  votis  nectere  vota, 
sed  mage  pacata  posse  omnia  mente  tueri. 

Lucretius  :  v.  1198. 

Je  eroi,   dist   Pantagruel,    que  toutes   ames   intelleetives   sont   exemptes   des 
ciseaulx  d'Atropos. — Rabelais  :  Pantag7-uel,  book  iv.  ch.  xxvii. 

La  raison  triomphe  de   la  mort,    et  travailler  pour  elle,   e'est  travailler  pour 
I'etemite. — E.  Renan  :  Disccmrs  de  reception,  3  avril,  1879. 

With  the  fourth  Part  of  the  '  Ethics  '  it  might  appear  at  first 
sight  that  Spinoza's  task  was  ended.  He  has  laid  bare  the 
constituents  of  human  motives  and  passions  ;  he  has  explained 
the  working  of  these  passions  in  the  various  circumstances  of 
life  ;  he  has  contrasted  the  slave  of  passion  with  the  reason- 
able or  free  man,  and  has  declared  the  precepts  of  righteous- 
ness and  goodwill.  But  he  esteems  his  work  only  half  done, 
and  goes  on  to  that  which  remains  as  to  something  he  has 
been  longing  to  take  in  hand. 

'  At  length,'  he  says  in  the  Preface  to  Part  V.,  'I  pass  on  to  the 
other  division  of  my  Ethics,  concerning  the  method  or  path  which - 
leads  us  to  freedom.  [And  in  this  I  shall  treat  of  the  power  of  reason, 
and  show  what  is  its  native  strength  against  the  emotions,  and  thence 
what  is  the  freedom  or  blessedness  of  the  mind.  Whence  we  shall 
see  in  liow  much  better  case  is  the  wise  man  than  the  ignorant. 
But  by  what  means  and  method  the  understanding  is  to  be  perfected, 
and  by  what  skill  the  body  is  to  be  tended  that  it  may  truly  do  its 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  279 

office,  pertains  not  to  this  inquiry ;  for  the  latter  of  these  is  the  con- 
cern of  medicine,  the  former  of  logic. 'J 

The  fact  is  that  Spinoza's  aim  has  throughout  been  prac-: 
tical.     He  has  undertaken  the  scientific  analysis  of  thepas- 
sions.  not  without  the  pure  curiosity  of  the  man  of  science,  but 
niainly  to  the  end  of  showing  ho^^•  the}-  may  be  mastered,  and 
the  conditions  of  man's  happiness  assured.      In  this  he    is 
at  one  with  the  Greeks,  and  particularly,  as  in  many  points 
before,  with  the  Stoics.     But  Spinoza  explicitly  denies  the<^' 
Stoic  assumption  that  the  will  has  an  absolute  power  over  the 
emotions :  a  denial  which;  on  comparison  of  his  express  con- 
tradictions of  Descartes,  might  be  taken  to  imply  an  admis- 
sion that  in  other  ways  the  Stoic  doctrine  appeared  to  him 
profitable  and  worthy  of  respect.     In  the  same  passage  he  ■ 
goes  on   to  controvert  the  Cartesian  theory  of  a  connexion  \ 
between  the  mind  and  the  body  through  the  pineal  gland,  by  \ 
which  Descartes  endeavoured  to  show  *  that  there  is  no  soul    \ 
so  feeble  but  that,  being  rightly  trained,  it   may  acquire  an 
absolute    dominion    over   its    passions.'     Spinoza    points  out 
that  the  hypothesis  of  the  pineal  gland  being  the  seat  of  con- 
sciousness, transmitting  impressions  to  the  mind  from  without, 
and  receiving  orders  from  the  mind  which  are  sent  on  to  the     j 
nerves  of  motion  by  means  of  the  animal  spirits,  is  contrary 
to  Descartes'  own  principles  of  scientific  work  ;|  introducing 
as  it  does  assumptions  more  baseless  and  occult  than  any  of 
the  scholastic  occult  qualities  which  Descartes  rejected.     He 
also  remarks  that  Descartes  did  not  and  could  not  assign  any 
mechanical  measure  of  the  alleged  power  of  the  mind  to  ini- 
tiate or  control  the  motions  of  this  gland  / '  in  truth,  will  and 
motion  being  incommensurable,  there  is  no  comparison  betwixt  c 
the  power  or  force  of  the  mind  and  the  body  :  and  therefore 
the  force  of  the  latter  can  in  no  wise  be  determined  by  that  of 
the  former.'     The  physiological  difficulties  of  the  hypothesis 
are  lightly  touched  on,  but  so  as  to  show  that  Spinoza  did  not 
overlook  them.     In  its  actual  form  this  preliminary  discussion 


28o  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

is  now  chiefly  interesting  as  a  monument  of  the  extraordinary- 
hold  the  Cartesian  philosophy  must  have  acquired  on  that 
generation  to  make  Spinoza  thus  go  out  of  his  way  to  re- 
fute the  most  fantastic  and  untenable  point  of  it.  But  the 
substance  of  Spinoza's  argument  remains  applicable  to  the 
various  quasi-materialist  attempts  that  from  time  to  time  have 
been  made,  in  the  supposed  interest  of  spiritual  truth,  to  esta- 
blish or  make  plausible  some  kind  of  physical  communica- 
tion between  the  mind  and  the  brain. 

1  When  we  examine  in  detail  what  Spinoza  has  to  say  '  of 
the  power  of  the  understanding,  or  of  Man's  freedom,' '  we  o 
find  that  it  consists  of  two  independent  parts.  The  first  :' 
(Part  V.  of '  Ethics  '  to  Prop.  20)  is  a  consistent  following  out 
of  the  psychological  method  we  have  already  become  familiar 
with.  [The  condition  of  mastering  the  emotions  is  shown  to 
be  a  clear  and  distinct  understanding  of  their  nature  and 
causes  ;  and  the  love  of  God — which  is  nothing  else  than  the 
rational  contemplation  of  the  order  of  the  world,  and  of 
human  nature  as  part  thereof — is  described  as  the  greatest 

1  happiness  of  man  in  this  life,  and  the  surest  way  of  establish; 

<  ing  the  rule  of  the  understanding  over  the  passions.  Here 
again  one  might  suppose,  and  with  more  reason  than~before, 
that  nothing  more  remained  to  be  set  forth.  But  it  is  not  so  : 
Spinoza  proceeds  to  lay  before  us  a  theory  of  intellectual  im- ' 
mortality,  or  rather  eternity,  the  perfection  whereof  consists  in 
an  intellectual  love  of  God  which  is  likewise  eternal,  and  '  is 
part  of  the  infinite  love  wherewith  God  loves  himself  This 
exposition,  which  takes  up  the  fifth  Part  of  the  '  Ethics '  from 
Prop.  21  onwards,  presents  great  difiiculties.  It  is  by  no' 
means  obvious,  in  the  first  place,  what  is  Spinoza's  real  mean- 
ing ;  nor  can  we  feel  sure  that  any  explanation  is  the  right  one 
until  we  have  some  probable  account  of  the  manner  in  which 
Spinoza  reconciled  the  doctrine,  as  we  may  propose  to  read 

»  Title  of  Part  V, 


THE  DELIVERANCE  OF  MAN.  281 

it,  with  the  rest  of  his  own  philosophy.     And  this  latter  pro- 
blem is  a  yet  harder  one. 

The  question  has  been  evaded,  as  it  seems  to  me,  by  most 
of  those  who  have  written  on  Spinoza.     Critics  who  regard 
him  as  a  transcendental  dogmatist  naturally  feel  no  particular 
difficulty  at  this  point :  why  should  not   Spinoza  dogmatize 
about  the  eternity  of  the  mind  as  well  as  about  Substance  and 
Attributes  }     So  they  are  content  to  give  some  abridgment  or 
paraphrase  of  Spinoza's  argument  which  in    truth  explains 
nothing.     Others,  led  by  their  own  prepossessions  to  disregards 
all  the  rules  of  historical  and  critical  probability,  have  sought, 
in  the  face  of  Spinoza's  express  and  repeated  warnings,  to  make 
out  that  his  theory  is  a  doctrine  of  personal  immortality  in  the 
ordinary  sense,  or  some  sense  practically  equivalent  to  it,  only 
stated  in  an  unusual  way  and  supported  by  artificial  reason- 
ing.    Some  few,  taking  a   view  of  the  general  meaning  of 
Spinoza's  philosophy  similar  to  that  which  has  been  main- 
tained in  the  foregoing  chapters,  have  manfully  striven  to  re- 
duce this  apparently  eccentric  part  into  scientific  conformity 
to  the  main  body.     But  they  are  forced  to  say  either  that 
Spinoza  did  not  clearly  know  his  own  meaning,  or  that  he  did 
not  succeed  in  saying  what  he  meant,  or  that  he  deliberately 
said  things  he  did  not  mean  :  none  of  which  suppositions  can 
^be  entertained  by  any  serious  and  impartial  reader  of  the 
*  Ethics '  except  as  a  desperate    remedy.      For  my   part,   I 
would  rather  confess  myself  baiifled  than  help  myself  out  by 
any   one  of  them,   especially   the  last :    and  in  fact  I    long 
thought  the  obscurity  of  the  last  portion  of  the  '  Ethics '  all 
but  hopeless. 

The  explanation  I  shall  now  put  forward  with  the  hope 
of  throwing  some  light  upon  the  historical  affinities  of  this 
speculation,  and  its  logical  connexion  with  Spinoza's  psy- 
chology, is  one  that  has  occurred  to  me  almost  at  the  last 
moment,  and  after  repeated  consideration. 

It  may  be  observed  here,  as  a  matter  independent  of  any 


282  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

particular  interpretation  of  Spinoza's  thought,  that  there  is 
some  reason  to  beheve  that  he  was  himself  conscious  of  not 
standing  on  the  firmest  ground  in  this  place.  The  proposi- 
tions concerning  the  eternity  of  the  mind  seem  to  be  carefully 
isolated  from  the  rest :  the  love  of  God  arising  from  clear  and 
distinct  self-knowledge  (Prop.  15)  is  kept  apart  from  the  in- 
tellectual love  which  is  the  privilege  of  the  mind  in  its  eternal 
quality  (Prop.  33),  though  on  almost  any  possible  reading  of 
Spinoza's  theory  the  two  must  coincide  ;  and  at  the  end 
Spinoza  guards  himself  by  showing  that  the  validity  of  ethical 
motives  and  precepts  is  independent  of  the  exalted  doctrine 
he  has  just  been  setting  forth  (Prop.  41).  In  a  writer  so  care- 
ful and  subtle  indications  of  this  kind  are  not  to  be  neglected. 
I  believe  that  Spinoza's  argument  was  to  himself  satisfactory  ; 
but  it  hangs,  as  I  read  it,  on  a  very  special  point  in  his  theory 
of  knowledge,  and  it  may  well  be  that  he  sa^A;  the  danger  of 
its  not  being  satisfactory  to  other  people,  j  Moreover  I  am 
inclined  to  think  that  Spinoza  wished  emphatically  to  dis- 
claim any  intention  of  relying  on  a  supernatural  or  super- 
sensible world  for  the  foundations  of  ordinary  virtue  and 
morality.  He  puts  his  eternity  of  the  mind  as  a  kind  of  sup- 
plemental speculation  ;  if  we  accept  it,  so  much  the  better  ;  if 
not,  the  rest  of  his  work  will  not  be  impaired.  (  It  might  per- 
haps be  suggested  that  this  series  of  propositions  was  in  fact 
an  afterthought.  But  conjectures  of  this  kind  are  too  uncer- 
tain to  be  worth  pursuing. 

Let  us  now  turn  to  a  connected  survey  of  the  book ; 
taking  first  in  order,  as  it  comes,  the  practical  and  fairly 
obvious  part.  The  opening  propositions,  in  which  the  con- 
ditions of  the  mind's  power  of  self-control  are  laid  down,  run 
as  follows  : 

I.  As  particular  thoughts  and  ideas  of  things  are  arranged 
and  connected  in  the  mind,  exactly  so  are  bodily  modifica- 
tions or  images  of  things  arranged  and  connected  in  the 
body. 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  283 

(This  is  an  immediate  inference  from  the  complete  paral- 
lelism of  mind  and  body.) 

2. /if  we  separate  a  disturbance  or  emotion  of  the  mind 
from  the  thought  of  its  outward  cause,  and  associate  it  with 
other  thoughts,  then  love  or  hatred  towards  that  outward 
cause,  as  likewise  the  agitations  arising  from  those  emotions, 
will  be  destroyed.  ^ 

(For  love  and  hate  depend  on  the  idea  of  the  external 
cause  being  present.) 

3.  That  emotion  which  is  a  passion  ceases  to  be  passion 
as  soon  as  we  form  a  clear  and  distinct  idea  thereof. 

(For  passion  as  such  is  a  confused  idea.) 

4.  There  is  no  modification  of  the  body  whereof  we  cannot 
form  some  clear  and  distinct  conception. 

(For  all  bodies  and  affections  of  bodies  have  some  proper- 
ties in  common,  and  our  conceptions  of  these  are  adequate.) 

Hence  it  appears  that  it  is  more  or  less  in  every  one's 
power  to  attain  a  clear  understanding  of  his  own  nature,  and 
to  that  extent  to  be  superior  to  passion.  So  that  the  first  c 
precept  of  freedom  may  be  thus  expressed  :  Understand  the' 
passions  that  you  may  be  master  of  them.  Nay,  the  very 
emotions  and  desires  that  otherwise  would  be  pernicious  are 
converted  to  beneficial  uses  by  the  government  of  the  under- 
standing. For  example,  '  we  have  found  man's  nature  to  be 
such  that  he  desires  others  to  live  after  his  own  plan.  And 
in  a  man  not  governed  by  reason  this  desire  is  the  passion 
called  ambition,  which  is  little  removed  from  pride  ;  whereas 
in  the  man  who  lives  according  to  reason  it  is  a  virtue  or 
activity,  and  is  called  piety.'  Such  is  the  nature  of  the 
mind's  power  over  the  emotions.  Of  course  it  might  equally 
be  expressed  in  terms  of  the  attribute  of  Extension,  as  a^ 
power  of  the  body  over  the  particular  modifications  of  the 
organism  which  correspond  to  the  emotions  in  consciousness. 
But,  as  Spinoza  is  here  considering  the  emotions  in  their 
mental  aspect  as  states  of  feeling,  he  naturally  follows  both 


\ 


284  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

convenience  and  common  use  in  regarding  the  facts  on  the 
psychical  rather  than  the  physical  side.  This  does  not  the  least 
imply,  as  a  hasty  reader  might  think,  that  he  loses  sight  of 
the  physical  side.  If  there  is  one  canon  of  interpretation 
more  important  than  another  for  the  right  understanding  of 
Spinoza,  it  is  that  the  physiological  correlations  of  mental 
action  are  never  overlooked  by  him  for  a  moment,  whatever 
his  language  may  be.  i^--^'- f^*^- '-= 

Next,  how  may  this  power  of  the  mind.^^be  strengthened?'^ 
By  conceiving  all  things  as  necessary  ;  for  the  knowledge  of 
a  thing  as  determined  by  definite  causes  tends  to  prevent  us 
from  fixing  any  emotion  upon  it  (Pr.  5,  6). 

'  The  more  this  knowledge  of  things  as  necessary  is  applied  to 
particular  things  where  of  we  have  a  distinct  and  lively  imagination, 
the  greater  is  this  power  qf^the  mind  over  the  emotions,  as  experience 
also  doth  bear  witness.  For  we  perceive  sorrow  for  any  possession 
that  is  lost  to  be  abated  t^enever  the  man  who  hath  lost  it  adviseth 
with  himself  that  this  possession  could  in  no  manner  have  been  saved. 
So  likewise  we  see  that  no  man  pities  a  child  because  it  cannot  speak, 
walk,  or  reas^,  or  because  for  so  many  years  its  life  is  in  a  manner 
unconscious.  <  But  if  the  more  part  of  us  were  bom  groAvn  up,  and 
one  here  and  there  as  a  child,  then  who  but  would  jjity  children  ? 
since  then  we  should  regard  the  state  of  infancy  not  as  a  thing  natural 
and  necessary,  but  as  a  defect  or  fault  in  nature.  And  after  this  sort 
we  might  mark  several  other  instances.'  (Pr.  6,  Schol.) 

I  It  is  further  pointed  out  that  an  emotion  arising  from 
rational  contemplation,  since  it  depends  on  constant  and  ever 
present  facts  in  the  order  of  nature,  will  be  stronger,  other 
things  being  equal,  than  emotions  directed  towards  a  par- 
ticular absent  object ;  and  that  emotion  is  stronger  in  propor- 
tion to  the  number  of  distinct  exciting  causes  acting  together 
to  produce  it.  Then  comes  a  proposition  in  the  nature  of 
practical  application : — 

,"    '  So  long  as  we  are  not  disturbed  by  emotions  contrary '  to  ouro 

'  Contrarii  is  omitted  in  the  text  of  the  0pp.  Posth.  It  is  tacitly  supplied  by 
the  Dutch  translator,  and  replaced  in  the  text  of  Gfrorer's  and  Bruder's  edd. 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  285 

nature,  we  have  the  power  of  ordering  and  connecting  the  affections    I 
of  the  body  in  pursuance  of  the  intellectual  order.'  (Prop.  10.) 

Spinoza  comments  on  this  in  a  Scholium,  which  seems  to 
mark  a  period  in  the  discussion.  It  is  of  a  very  practical 
kind,  and  may  strike  the  reader  as  not  being  original  :  in 
which  case  I  would  ask  him  to  reflect  that  we  have  much 
reason  to  be  thankful  that  in  moral  precepts  intended  for  real 
use  no  great  originality  is  either  needful  or  practicable.  The 
scientific  discussion  and  explanation  of  morality  is  the  task 
of  philosophers.  But  morality  itself  is  made  by  the  commu- 
nity of  right-minded  men,  whether  they  happen  to  be  philo- 
sophers or  not :  and  when  we  come  to  speak  of  the  actual 
contents  of  morality  and  the  conduct  of  life,  the  philosopher 
has  little  or  no  advantage  over  any  other  right-minded  man 
beyond  the  habit  of  expressing  himself  in  accurate  language. 
No  system  of  ethics  can  do  more  than  organize  the  common 
moral  sense  of  good  men.  Let  us  hear  Spinoza,  therefore,  as 
one  speaking  to  us  in  the  name  of  us  all.  That  which  is 
spoken  with  the  common  voice  and  in  the  common  name  of 
man's  conscience  may  w^ell  be  common  ;  if  it  is  not,  we 
should  strive  to  make  it  so.  But  it  can  never  be  common- 
place. 

'  By  this  power  of  duly  ordering  and  linking  together  the  affections/ 
of  our  body  we  may  bring  it  to  pass  that  we  be  not  easily  wrought  on 
by  evil  passions.     For  greater  force  is  needed  to  control  emotions/o 
ordered  and  linked  according  to  the  intellectual  order  than  those 
which  are  uncertain  and  loose.     Wherefore  the  best  we  can  compass, 
so  long  as  we  have  not  a  perfect  knowledge  of  our  emotions,  is  to  lay 
out  a  method  and  settled  rules  of  life,  to  commit  these  to  memory 
and  constantly  '  to  apply  them  to  such  particular  cases  as  do  com 
monly  meet  us  in  life,  that  so  our  imagination  may  be  penetrate 
therewith,  and  we  may  ever  have  them  at  hand.     \\'e  laid  down,  fo 
example,  among  the  precepts  of  life,  that  hatred  should  be  conquered 
by   love   or  high-mindedness,  not  repaid   in  kind.     Now  that  this 

'  Continito  :  Spinoza  was  probably  not  ignorant  of  the  classical  usage  of  the 
word,  but  it  would  not  suit  this  context. 


286  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

command  of  reason  may  always  be  ready  for  us  at  need,  we  should 
often  think  upon  and  consider  the  wrongs  commonly  done  by  men, 
and  in  what  manner  they  are  warded  off  by  a  noble  mind.  For  thus 
we  shall  knit  the  image  of  a  wrong  done  us  to  the  imagination  of 
this  precept,  and  the  precept  will  always  be  at  hand  when  a  wrong  is 

offered  us But  we  shall  note  that  in  ordering  our  thoughts 

and  imaginations  we  are  ever  to  attend  to  that  which  is  good  in  a 
particular  thing,  that  we  may  always  be  determined  to  action  by  an 
emotion  of  pleasure.  For  example,  if  one  sees  that  he  exceedeth  in 
the  pursuit  of  honour,  let  him  think  of  the  right  use  thereof,  and  for 
Avhat  purpose  it  is  to  be  pursued,  and  by  what  means  to  be  acquired  ; 
not  of  the  misuse  and  vanity  of  it,  the  inconstancy  of  mankind  and 
the  like,  of  which  no  man  thinks  except  for  infirmity  of  spirit.  For 
with  such  thoughts  do  ambitious  men  most  plague  themselves,  when 
they  despair  of  attaining  the  station  they  are  bent  upon;  and  so 
venting  their  anger  they  would  fain  be  thought  philosophers.  'Tis 
certain  that  they  are  most  greedy  of  honour  who  are  loudest  concern- 
ing the  misuse  of  it  and  the  vanity  of  the  world.  Nor  is  this  peculiar 
to  the  case  of  ambition,  but  it  is  common  to  all  who  meet  with  ill 
fortune  and  lack  strength  of  mind.  ...  So  he  who  endeavours  to 
govern  his  emotions  and  desires  purely  by  the  love  of  freedom  will 
strive,  as  best  he  may,  to  know  the  virtues  and  their  causes,  and  to 
fill  his  mind  with  the  joy  which  arises  from  the  true  knowledge  of 
them  ;  but  in  no  wise  to  study  men's  faults,  nor  to  flatter  them  and 
make  merry  with  a  false  show  of  liberty.  And  whoever  will  dili- 
gently observe  and  use  these  precepts  (for  they  are  not  difficult), 
assuredly  in  a  short  space  of  time  he  will  be  able  for  the  most  part  to 
guide  his  actions  after  the  rule  of  reason.' 

We  are  next  introduced   to  the  exercise  of  contemplative o 

reason  described  as  the  love   of  God,  which  consists  in  the 

distinct  understanding  of  one's  own  nature.     There  is  no  form 

k  or  mode  of  knowledge  which  cannot  be  made  to  some  extent 

Iclear  and  distinct ;  in  other  words,  '  referred   to  the   idea  of 

IGod,'  since  without  God  nothing  exists  or  can  be  conceived. 

Clear  and  distinct  understanding  of  one's  own  nature  involves^ 

/pleasure,  and  this  is  accompanied   by  the  idea  of  God  ;  and 

therefore  the  resulting  emotion  is  love  of  God,  and,  being 

associated  with   every  act  of  understanding,  must  hold  the 

chief  place  in  the  mind  that  entertains  it.     God,  on  the  other- 


THE  DELIVERANCE _  OF  MAN.  287 

hand,  is  not  subject  to  passion,  not  capable  of  pleasure  or 
pain,  and  cannot  properly  be  said  to  love  or  hate  any  one. 
Therefore,  since  we  cannot  desire  that  God  should  contradict 
his  own  nature  and  perfections,  '  he  who  loves  God  cannot 
endeavour  that  God  should  love  him  in  return.'  And_this 
love  of  God  is  the  chief  good  which  men  can  seek  under  the 
guidance  of  reason  ;  it  may  be  common  to  all  men,  and  we 
can  wish  it  for  otHers  as  much  as  for  ourselves.  Thus  it  is 
not  liable  to  be  marred,  like  the  common  affections  of  men, 
by  envy  or  jealousy.' 

Here  again  there  is  a  pause  and  a  summing  up. 

'  I  have  now  collected,'  we  read,  '  all  the  remedies  against  the 
emotions,  that  is,  everything  that  the  mind  considered  in  itself  is 
capable  of  doing  against  them.     Whence  it  appears  that  the  power  ofc 
the  mind  over  the^  emotions  consists, — i.   In  actual  knowledge  of 
the  emotions  (see  Schol.  to  Pr.  4  of  this  Part).     2.  In  the  separation  ; 
of  the  emotions  from  the  thought  of  the  external  cause  of  whjjch  we  j 
have  a  confused  imagination.     3.  In  respect  of  time,  wherein  those  I 
affections  which  have  regard  to  things  we   understand   overmatch 
those  that  have  regard  to  things  we  conceive  confusedly  or  brokenly 
(Prop.  7).     4.  In  the  number  of  causes  by  which  those  affectioiis  are  j 
fostered  that  have  regard  to  the  universal  properties  of  things  or  to  ' 
God.  (Prop.  9  and  11.)     5.   Finally  in  that  order  in  which  the  min^ 
can  arrange  and  link  together  its  own  emotions.' 

Spinoza  goes  on  to  say  that  the  mind's  power  consists 
in  knowledge,  considered  not  as  freedom  from  error  but  as 
its  natural  and  proper  activity.  1  Not  absence  of  inadequate  c^ 
ideas,  but  preponderance  of  adequate  ones,  is  the  condition  of 
mental  health.  Clear  and  distinct  knowledge,  more  especially 
the  third  or  intuitive  kind,  gives  us  the  means  of  controlling 
the  passions  to  such  an  extent  that  they  have  but  an  insigni-i 
ficant  part  in  the  mind  \—\ 

'  Likewise  it  engenders  love  towards  an  immutable  and  eternal 
being,  truly  within  our  reach  ;  which  therefore  can  be  sullied  by  none 
of  the  defects  common  to  other  kinds  of  love,  but  may  constantly 

'  Propp.  11-20. 


288  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  A  ND   PHILOSOPHY. 

increase,  and  may  possess  the  best  part  of  the  mind  and  thoroughly 
penetrate  it.  And  herewith  I  have  finished  what  concerns  this 
present  life.  .  .  .  And  so  it  is  time  for  me  to  pass  on  to  other 
matters  which  belong  to  the  duration  of  the  mind  without  regard 
to  the  body.' 

We  are  now  on  the  threshold  of  the  singular  and  difficult 
part  of  Spinoza's  exposition.  I  shall  begin  by  stating  as 
clearly  as  I  can  what  I  conceive  his  meaning  to  have  been. 
Next  I  shall  point  out  what  I  believe  to  be  the  histbrical' 
ancestry  of  his  doctrine.  Then  I  shall  give  the  leading 
points  of  the  argument  in  Spinoza's  own  words,  or  as  nearly 
so  as  may  be,  and  at  the  same  time  exhibit  in  detail,  for  any 
reader  who  cares  to  follow  me  so  far,  the  manner  in  which  I 
justify  my  interpretation. 

Whatever  is  known  as  part  of  the  necessary  order  of" 
nature,  in  other  words  exactly  or  scientifically,  is  said  by 
Spinoza  to  be  known  '  under  the  form  of  eternity.'  And  this 
is  eminently  true  of  the  immediate  knowledge  which  he  calls 
the  third  kind.  Now  in  every  act  of  knowledge  the  mind  is 
(in  Spinoza's  technical  sense)  the  idea  of  a  certain  state  of  its 
own  body  ;  and  if  we  regard  this  as  a  knowledge  of  its  own 
body  (which  I  shall  show  that  Spinoza  does),  the  mind  in 
contemplating  things  as  necessary  knows  its  own  body  '  under 
the  form  of  eternity.'  But  the  knowing  mind  has  a  conscious- 
ness or  knowledge  of  itself  which  exactly  corresponds  to  its 
knowledge  of  the  body;  in  Spinoza's  language,  it  is  the  idea 
of  itself  as  well  as  of  the  body.  Therefore  in  all  exact  know- 
ledge the  mind  knows  itself  '  under  the  form  of  eternity : ' 
that  is  to  say,  in  every  such  act  it  is  eternal,  and  knows  itself 
as  eternal.  This  eternity  is  not  a  persistence  in  time  after  the 
dissolution  of  the  body,  for  it  is  not  commensurable  with  time 
at  all.  And  there  is  associated  with  it  a  state  or  quality  of 
perfection  called  the  intellectual  love  of  God.  This  is  not  an 
emotion,  since  the  emotion  of  pleasure  involves  transition 
to  greater  perfection,  and  therefore  a  finite  time  ;   but  it  is 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAM.  289 

related  to  the  emotion  of  love  as  the  eternity  of  the  mind  is 
related  to  its  existence  in  time   in  a  particular  act  of  know- 
ledge.    The  intellectual  love  of  man  for  God  is  part  of  the 
infinite  intellectual  love  wherewith  God  loves  himself;  and 
the  mind,  together  with  whatsoever  it  knows  '  under  the  form 
of  eternity,'  is  a  link  in  an  infinite  chain  of  eternal  beings, 
which  all  together  make  up  the  infinite  mind  of  God.     Reser- 
ving the  discussion  of  difficulties  and  the  critical  analysis  of 
Spinoza's   argument,    let   us    endeavour   to  seize  the   points 
which  stand  out  most  distinctly  in  this  daring  flight  of  specu- 
lation.    The  eternity  of  the  human  mind  is  a  function  of  pure 
intellect,  and  depends  on  the  mind's  power  and  habit  of  exact 
:    knowledge.     Its  perfection  goes  along  with  the  attainment  of 
^  the  most  perfect  kind  of  knowledge,  and  its  degree  is  different 
I  in  different  individuals.     It  has  no  relation  to  time,  and  there- 
(  fore  is  not  a  future  life  or  continuance  of  personal  conscious- 
'  ness  in  the  ordinary  sense.     At  the  same  time  it  is  in  some 
sense  individual  ;  the  active  and   understanding  mind  is  an 
'  eternal  mode  of  thought '  which  is  part  of  the  infinite  intel- 
lect, but  is  not  lost  in  it. 

It  seems  to  me  that  we  cannot  but  trace  in  this  a^ 
direct  connexion  with  the  Aristotelian  doctrine  of  immortality 
taken  up  and  developed  by  the  Averroists  in  the  middle  ages. 
M.  Kenan's  warning  is  before  my  eyes  : '  but  it  is  M.  Renan 
himself  who  supplies  us  with  the  links  that  complete,  as  I 
submit,  a  sufficient  chain  of  evidence. 

In  various  passages  of  Aristotle  a  doctrine  of  intellectual 
immortality  is  indicated  rather  than  worked  out.  The  passive 
or  receptive  elements  of  the  mind  are  perishable  ;  only  the 
active  intellect  {vovs  ttolijtlkos),  and  the  individual  mind  so 
far  as  it  partakes  thereof,  are  eternal  and  immortal.     Whether 

'  '  Rechercher  si  Averroes  peut  revendiquer  quelquc  cliose  clans  le  systeme  du 
penseur  d'Amsterdam,  ce  serait  depasser  la  limite  ou  doit  s'arreter,  dans  les 
questions  de  filiation  de  systemes,  une  juste  curiosite  :  ce  serait  vouloir  retrouver 
la  trace  du  ruisseau  quand  il  s'est  perdu  dans  la  prairie. ' — Averroes  et  l' Averroisme, 
2d  ed.  p.  199. 

U 


290  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

this  active  intellect  is  only  the  sum  of  similar  elements  in 
individual  minds,  that  by  virtue  of  which  the  mind  is  rational 
in  each  case,  or  is  to  be  regarded  as  having  a  permanent 
existence  beside  and  beyond  the  minds  of  individual  men,  is 
a  point  not  altogether  free  from  doubt  in  Aristotle  himself. 
The  commentators  resolved  and  developed  the  question  in 
various  ways.  Ibn-Roshd  (Averroes)  appears  to  have  consi-^ 
dered  the  active  intellect  as  being  independent  of  this  and 
that  man's  individuality,  and  of  one  substance  in  all  men, 
but  existing  only  in  individual  men  :  a  unity  realized  and  re- 
flected in  the  multiplicity  of  finite  minds.  In  any  case,  the 
personal  immortality  of  the  individual  is  excluded  by  the 
Averroistic  doctrine.  The  active  intellect  is  immortal,  either 
in  itself  or  as  embodied  in  the  human  race  which  is  mortal 
only  as  regards  individuals  :  this  and  that  soul  can  be  im- 
mortal only  so  far  as  they  have  part  in  the  active  intellect ; 
not  as  individual,  but  as  rational  and  belonging  to  universal 
reason.' 

When  the  Mussulman  fanaticism  which  took  alarm  even 
in  Averroes'  lifetime  had  effectually  suppressed  the  cultivation 
of  philosophy  within  the  bounds  of  Islam,  the  light  was  kept 
alive  by  a  series  of  Jewish  scholars  of  whom  Moses  ben  Mai- 
mon,  the  contemporary  of  Averroes,  was  first  in  time  and  in 
renown.  The  various  problems  of  the  Peripatetic  system,  and 
this  particular  one  among  them,  were  taken  up  and  eagerly 
discussed.  It  was  not  fully  entered  upon  by  Maimonides, 
but  he  inclined  to  go  with  Ibn-Roshd  in  holding  that  im- 
mortality was  not  individual.  Levi  ben  Gerson  dealt  with  it  '^ 
at  length,  and  after  elaborately  criticizing  the  opinions  of 
Ibn-Roshd  and  others,  concluded  in  favour  of  an  immortality 
Avhich  was  intellectual  but  also  individual.  Rejecting  the 
notion  of  union  with  the  universal  reason,  and  retaining  the 
Aristotelian  theory  that  contemplative  knowledge  is  the  only 
proper  function  of  an  eternal  mind,  he  held  that  the  indi- 

'  Rcnan,  op.  cil.  pp.  122-158, 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  291 

vidual  mind  is  immortal  in  respect  of  the  knowledge  possessed 
by  it  at  the  time  of  its  emancipation  from  the  body.  It  has 
a  fuller  and  freer  possession  of  this  knowledge,  but  not  having 
the  organism  and  senses  by  which  alone  new  experience  can 
be  acquired,  it  cannot  in  any  way  extend  it.^ 

We  are  fairly  entitled  to  assume  that  Spinoza  was  not  un- 
acquainted with  the  writings  of  Gersonides ;  through  them  he 
would  have  become  acquainted  with  the  Peripatetic  doctrine 
of  intellectual  immortality  as  understood  by  the  commen- 
tators, and  with  the  Averroist  modification  of  it,  as  well  as 
with  Gersonides'  own  speculations.  And  if  this  knowledge 
is  admitted,  no  supposition  is  more  natural  than  that  Spinoza's'^ 
own  doctrine  was  suggested  to  him  from  this  quarter.  The 
leading  ideas  are  the  same,  only  worked  into  formal  agree- 
ment, as  we  shall  presently  see,  with  Spinoza's  metaphysics 
and  psychology.  His  insistance  on  the  eternity  of  the  mind 
being  wholly  independent  of  time,  and  incommensurable  with 
existence  determined  in  time,  appears  to  be  peculiar  to  him- 
self ;  and  in  the  transfiguration  of  contemplative  knowledge  as 
the  '  intellectual  love  of  God '  there  is  perhaps  a  reminiscence 
of  the  Neo-PIatonic  influence  which  was  still  predominant 
when  he  wrote  the  'Treatise  of  God  and  Man.'  In  that  work, 
it  may  be  not  amiss  to  observe  here,  we  find  little  or  nothing 
to  throw  light  on  the  part  of  his  mature  system  now  under 
consideration.  The  theory  of  immortality  is  but  vaguely 
.sketched  out,  and,  so  far  as  we  can  assign  it  to  any  generic  type, 
is  decidedly  Neo-Platonic  rather  than  Aristotelian  ;  the  soul's 
capacity  for  immortality  being  represented  as  depending  on 
its  detachment  from  the  body  and  union  with  God.  But  it  is 
worth  noting  that  in  the  '  Cogitata  Metaphysica '  some  space 
is  given  to  denouncing  the  error  of  those  who  '  consider  eter- 
nity as  a  form  of  duration.'     And   on   the  point  of  eternity 

'  Joel,  Levi  ben  Geison  (Gersonides),  als  Religions-philosoph  (in  Bcitriige 
zur  GcscJu  d.  Philosophic)  :  '  Der  von  Seele  und  Leib  befieite  Geist  denkt  alle 
seine  Erkenntnisse  auf  einmal  und  als  Einhcit.  Nur  iicuc  ErkonnUiissc  zu 
enverben  ist  cr  ausser  Stande,'  p.  45. 

U  2 


292  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

having  to  do  with  essentia  not  existentia,  it  is  said  :  '  Nobody- 
will  ever  say  that  the  being  of  a  circle  or  a  triangle,  so  far  as 
it  is  an  eternal  truth,  hath  endured  longer  at  this  day  than  it 
had  in  Adam's.' — '  Cogitata  Metaphysica,'  Part  2,  c.  i. 

I  proceed  to  the  fuller  statement  of  Spinoza's  argument. 
The  leading  propositions  are  as  follows. 

Prop.  21.  The  viiiid  cannot  imagine  any  tiling  or  remember 
tilings  past  except  while  the  body  endures. 

It  will  be  sufficient  to  observe,  without  reproducing 
Spinoza's  proof  and  references,  that  in  the  Second  Part 
memory  has  been  treated  as  dependent  on  association,  which 
involves  a  material  mechanism  in  the  brain  ;  and  in  like  man- 
ner imagination  cannot  be  exercised  without  a  material  organ 
of  thought  and  storehouse  of  impressions. 

Prop.  22.  There  nevertheless  necessarily  exists  in  God  an 
idea  ivhich  expresses  the  being  of  the  individual  human  body 
under  the  form  of  eternity. 

Again  let  us  pass  over  the  formal  demonstration,  and  look 
back  to  Prop.  44  of  Part  2.  There  wc  find  that  '  it  is  of  the 
nature  of  reason  to  perceive  things  under  a  certain  form  of 
eternity,'  which  is  the  same  thing  as  perceiving  them  as  part 
of  the  necessary  order  of  nature.  The  human  body,  like 
everything  else,  is  part  of  the  necessary  order  of  nature,  and 
can  therefore  be  thought  of  '  under  the  form  of  eternity,'  as 
determined  by  natural  laws  whose  operation  is  always  and 
everywhere  the  same.  The  essentia  of  a  result  of  given  con- 
ditions, or  what  it  shall  be,  has  nothing  to  do  with  the  tract 
of  time  or  portion  of  space  in  which  the  conditions  are  found  : 
for  Spinoza,  like  most  if  not  all  writers  down  to  our  own  time, 
assumes  that  the  laws  of  nature  can  be  exactly  known,  and  are 
known  to  be  absolutely  and  universally  valid.  The  existentia 
of  a  particular  result — when  and  where  it  shall  be,  if  at  all — 
the  fact  that  it  does  occur  at  a  given  time  and  place — this 
cannot  be  expressed  in  terms  of  the  eternal  laws  of  nature 
alone,  and  therefore  cannot  be  determined  in  thought  by  pure 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  293 

intellect,  but  only  with  the  help  of  the  imagination.  Thus 
the  '  idea  which  expresses  the  essence  of  this  and  that  human 
body  under  the  form  of  eternity  '  would  seem  to  be  nothing 
else  than  the  knowledge  of  the  human  body  as  a  neces- 
sary part  of  the  order  of  nature.  Further,  it  seems  a  fair  ex- 
tension of  Spinoza's  language  to  say  that  everything  known 
'  under  the  form  of  eternity '  is  to  that  extent  eternal.  We 
shall  presently  see  that  he  all  but  says  it  in  so  many  words. 
What  Spinoza  has  really  arrived  at,  then,  is  that  in  a  certain^ 
sense  the  human  body  may  be  called  eternal.  We  must  care- 
fully observe  that  this  eternity  has  nothing  to  do  with  the 
persistence  in  time  of  the  ultimate  elements  of  the  organism 
after  the  organism  is  dissolved.     Let  us  now  see  what  follows. 

'Prop.  23.  The  hwnan  vimd  cannot  be  wholly  destroyed  7vith  the 
body,  but  somexvhat  of  it  remains  which  is  eternal. 

Demonstr.  There  is  necessarily  in  God,  by  the  foregoing  proposi- 
tion, a  concept  or  idea  which  doth  express  the  being  of  the  human 
body.  This  accordingly  must  needs  be  something  which  pertains  to 
the  being  of  the  human  mind  (by  Prop.  13,  Part  2).'  But  we  do 
not  assign  to  the  human  mind  any  duration  that  can  be  described  by 
time,  except  so  far  as  it  doth  express  the  actual  existence  of  the  body, 
which  is  explained  by  duration  and  may  be  described  by  time  ;  that 
is  {by  Coroll.  Prop.  8,  Part  2)^  we  assign  not  existence  to  it  except 
M'hile  the  body  endures.  But  seeing  there  is  nevertheless  somewhat^ 
which  by  a  certain  eternal  necessity  is  conceived  through  the  being 
of  God,  this  somewhat  which  belongs  to  the  being  of  the  mind  will 
necessarily  be  eternal . 

Schol.  This  idea  which  doth  express  the  being  of  the  body  under 
the  form  of  eternity  is,  as  we  said,  a  determined  mode  of  thought 

'   '  The  object  of  the  idea  which  makes  up  the  human  mind  is  a  body  or  certain 
actually  existing  mode  of  extension,  and  nothing  else.' 

-  '  So  long  as  particular  things  do  not  exist,  save  so  far  as  they  are  contained' 
in  the  attributes  of  God  \i.c.,  so  long  as  they  exist  potentially  but  not  actually], 
the  objective  being  or  ideas  of  them  do  not  exist,  save  in  so  far  as  the  infinite  idea 
of  God  exists.'  This  is  a  case  of  the  universal  parallelism.  Whatever  can  be  said 
to  exist  potentially  in  the  order  of  extension  must  also  be  said  to  exist  potentially 
in  the  order  of  thought.  The  universe  as  a  whole,  which  on  the  side  of  thought 
is  'infinita  Dei  idea,'  involves  the  whole  history  of  things  and  every  possible  con- 
sequence of  the  laws  of  nature. 


294  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE    AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

which  belongs  to  the  being  of  the  mind  and  is  necessarily  eternal. 
Yet  it  cannot  come  to  pass  that  we  remember  anything  of  an  exist- o 
ence  before  the  body,  since  neither  can  there  occur  any  traces  thereof' 
in  the  body,  nor  can  eternity  be  described  by  time,  nor  have  unto 
time  any  proportion.  But  none  the  less  we  do  feel  and  are  aware 
that  we  are  eternal.  For  the  mind  feels  not  less  those  things  which 
it  conceives  by  the  understanding  than  those  which  it  doth  hold  in 
memory.  The  eyes  of  the  mind,  wherewith  she  sees  and  observes 
things,  are  no  other  than  demonstrations.  So  that  although  we 
remember  not  that  we  existed  before  our  body,  yet  we  feel  that  our 
mind,  in  so  far  as  it  involves  the  being  of  the  body  under  the  form 
of  eternity,  is  eternal ;  and  that  this  manner  of  its  existence  cannot 
be  described  by  time  or  explained  in  terms  of  duration.  Thus  our 
mind  can  only  so  far  be  said  to  endure,  and  its  existence  be  described 
by  a  determined  time,  as  it  involves  the  actual  existence  of  the  body ; 
and  it  hath  only  so  far  the  power  of  limiting  the  existence  of  things 
by  time,  and  conceiving  them  under  the  category  of  duration.' 

Observe,  again,  how  distinctly  the  notion  of  persistence  inf 
time  is  cut  off  from  that  of  eternity.  Spinoza's  eternal  life  is 
not  a  continuance  of  existence  but  a  manner  of  existence  ; 
something  which  can  be  realized  here  and  now  as  much  as  at 
any  other  time  and  place ;  not  a  future  reward  of  the  soul's 
perfection  but  the  soul's  perfection  itself.  In  which,  it  is  almost 
needless  to  remind  the  reader,  he  agrees  with  the  higher  and 
nobler  interpretation  of  almost  all  the  religious  systems  of  the 
world.  Whether  it  is  called  the  life  eternal,  the  kingdom  of' 
God,  wisdom,  liberation,  or  nirvana,  the  state  of  blessedness 
has  been  put  forward  by  the  great  moral  teachers  of  mankind 
as  something  not  apart  from  and  after  this  life,  but  entering  into 
and  transforming  it.'  The  after-coming  generations  of  dull 
and  backsliding  disciples  have  degraded  these  glories  of  the 
free  human  mind  into  gross  mechanical  systems  of  future 
rewards  and  punishments. 

But  we  must  return  to  the  critical  study  of  the  argument. 
A  difficulty  presents  itself  at  first  sight,  which  has  weighed 

'  I  fear  this  cannot  be  said  of  Mahomet,  and  moral  enthusiasm  is  precisely 
what  the  religion  founded  liy  him  seems  to  be  most  wanting  in. 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  295 

much  with  those  who  have  thought  that  Spinoza's  only  real 
meaning  (notwithstanding  his  express  declaration  that  eternity 
is  out  of  relation  to  time)  must  be  that  the  ultimate  elements 
of  body  and  mind  alike  persist  in  other  forms  after  the  living 
organism  is  broken  up.  It  looks  as  if  too  much  had  been 
proved,  though  not  stated  ;  as  if  what  is  asserted  of  the 
human  mind  were  by  implication  asserted  of  all  things  what- 
ever. Spinoza  would  then  be  saying  aloud  :  '  The  human 
mind  is  in  a  certain  sense  eternal ' — and  adding  in  a  whisper, 
for  the  few  who  could  penetrate  his  secret : — '  and  everything 
else  too.'  This  reading  was  long  ago  put  forward  (still  with 
a  certain  amount  of  reserve)  by  Boullainvilliers  in  his  so-called 
'  Refutation  of  Spinoza,'  173 1,  a  title  which  thinly  disguises  a 
popular  exposition  ;  and  it  has  been  suggested  in  our  own 
day  in  Holland  by  Dr.  Van  Vloten,  and  lately  propounded 
with  some  confidence  by  Mr.  Lotsy.  The  objections  are 
however  insuperable.  Either  Spinoza  gratuitously  gives  an 
involved  and  obscure  demonstration  of  a  consequence  which 
on  his  metaphysical  principles  is  perfectly  simple,  or  his  argu- 
ment is  from  beginning  to  end  a  piece  of  deliberate  duplicity. 
The  first  alternative  is  repugnant  to  Spinoza's  intellectual 
character,  the  second  to  his  moral.  And  then,  even  if  he 
were  capable  of  throwing  dust  in  his  readers'  eyes,  what  pos- 
sible motive  had  he }  To  save  appearances,  it  is  suggested. 
If  that  were  so,  it  would  be  a  curious  thing  that  he  began  to 
think  of  saving  appearances  after  he  had  written  nine-tenths 
of  the  Ethics  without  the  slightest  regard  to  any  such  pru 
dential  economy.  There  is  nothing  of  the  kind  in  his  treat- 
ment of  popular  theology,  of  final  causes,  of  free-will,  of  current 
ethical  notions,  of  dominant  Cartesian  theories.  Nay,  the  allu- 
sions to  common  opinion  in  this  very  series  of  propositions  are 
as  far  from  disguise  and  conciliation  as  anything  in  the  earlier 
Parts.  If  Spinoza's  design  was  to  save  appearances,  he  has 
gone  about  the  work  with  incredible  clumsiness  and  want  of 
tact.     Besides  all  this,  it  is  hopeless  to  reconcile  the  proposed 


296  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

interpretation  with  Spinoza's  express  words.  In  short,  I  do 
not  see  how  any  careful  reader  can  on  full  consideration  so 
understand  him,  unless  he  is  steadfastly  minded  not  only  to 
find  in  the  Ethics  a  complete  modern  doctrine  of  physiological 
psychology,  but  to  find  nothing  else. 

Let  us  consider  Spinoza's  reasoning  more  narrowly.  Thep 
human  body  may  be  known  as  part  of  an  eternal  order,  '  under 
the  form  of  eternity,'  and  so  may  any  other  body  ;  that  must 
be  allowed.  The  human  mind,  as  strictly  corresponding  to 
the  body,  point  for  point  and  element  for  element,  may  be 
known  in  like  manner ;  and  so  may  the  mind  or  complex  of 
mental  facts  corresponding  to  any  other  aggregate  of  matter. 
Is  there  nothing  more  to  be  said  then  }  and  is  there  no  prero- 
gative left  for  man  }  Yes,  and  a  great  one,  the  prerogative  of 
knowledge.  If  the  atom  of  matter  and  the  primitive  cell  of 
organic  life  may  be  called  eternal,  yet  their  eternity  is  only  in 
the  thought  of  the  higher  intelligence  which  knows  them  as 
part  of  the  immutable  order.  The  knowledge  of  the  material 
atom  '  under  the  form  of  eternity '  is  not  in  the  mind-atom 
that  is  paired  with  it.  But  the  knowledge  of  the  human  body 
'  under  the  form  of  eternity '  need  not  be  in  some  separate 
thinking  being  :  it  may  be  in  the  mind  of  that  body  itself. 
The  mind  can  know  its  own  body  '  under  the  form  of  eternity ' ; 
and  in  knowing  the  body  it  knows  itself.  The  knowing  and 
self-conscious  mind  is,  as  we  saw  in  the  Second  Part,  idea  ideae 
as  well  as  idea.  Thus  it  is  eternal  in  the  strength  of  its  own 
knowledge,  and  is  conscious  of  its  eternity.  It  is  the  clear 
consciousness  accompanying  every  act  of  knowledge,  not  any 
such  vague  sentiment  or  presentiment  as  is  relied  on  by  the 
popular  doctrine  of  immortality,  that  Spinoza  calls  to  witness 
when  he  says  :  Sentimus  experimiirqiie  nos  aeternos  esse. 

But  what  is  the  mind's  knowledge  of  the  body  '  under  the 
form  of  eternity  ' }  'To  know  under  the  form  of  eternity  is  to 
know  rationall)'  or  exactly.  ;  In  modern  language  what  we 
mean  by  having  a  rational  knowledge  of  our  own  body  is  being 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  297 

able  to  give  a  scientific  account  of  its  structure  and  functions : 
and  if  we  carried  this  conception  into  Spinoza's  propositions 
we  should  make  the  eternity  of  the  mind  depend  on  one  o 
special  kind  of  knowledge,  and  reduce  the  way  of  salvation  to 
a  course  of  human  physiology- — a  conclusion  too  grotesque  to 
dw^ell  upon.  In  fact  the  mind's  eternal  knowledge  of  the  body, 
as  understood  by  Spinoza,  is  not  a  knowledge  of  the  human 
body  generically,  but  a  relation  between  the  particular  mind 
and  the  particular  body  which  we  should  not  now  think  of 
calling  knowledge  at  all.  The  key  to  this  part  of  his  argu-o 
ment  is  the  ambiguous  use  of  the  word  idea  on  which  we  have 
already  commented  in  the  Second  Part  of  the  Ethics.  The 
word  is  sometimes  used  in  the  common  sense,  as  meaning  a 
concept  in  the  mind  referred  to  some  object  of  knowledge 
outside  it :  sometimes  in  the  sense  peculiar  to  Spinoza's  meta- 
physical system,  as  meaning  the  mode  of  thought  (which  may 
or  may  not  be  in  a  conscious  mind)  corresponding  to  a  given 
mode  of  extension.  In  the  first  sense  idea  is  the  image  or 
concept,  idcatiun  the  thing  perceived  or  conceived  ;  in  the 
second  idea  and  ideatum  are  one  and  the  same  thing  'ex- 
pressed '  in  the  attributes  of  Thought  and  of  Extension.  To 
take  a  concrete  instance,  Peter  thinks  of  Paul.  The  thought 
in  Peter's  mind  is  in  the  first  sense  idea  Pauli ;  in  the  second 
sense  it  is  idea  affectionis  corporis  Petri,  that  is,  Peter's  thought 
about  Paul  is  strictly  parallel  to  a  certain  definite  state  of  the 
material  machinery  of  imagination  in  Peter's  brain.  So  if  I 
think  of  a  geometrical  proposition,  the  ideate  of  my  idea  is  in 
the  one  sense  a  set  of  geometrical  relations  in  space,  in  the 
other  sense  my  own  body  (and  especially  my  brain)  as  modi- 
fied in  that  particular  act  of  thought.  Now  Spinoza,  as  we 
have  already  pointed  out,  habitually  carries  over  statements 
and  inferences  from  the  one  meaning  of  the  term  idea  to  the 
other,  apparently  v/ithout  the  least  suspicion  that  his  pro- 
cedure is  open  to  any  objection.  When  I  know  an  external 
fact,  the  state  of  my  mind  which  is  my  knowledge  is  the  idea 


298  SPINOZA  :   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

of  the  external  fact  in  one  sense.  But  it  is  the  idea  of  a  cer- 
tain state  of  my  own  body  in  the  other  sense.  Accordingly 
-^Spinoza  affirms  that  the  mind  in  every  act  of  knowledge  also 
knows  its  own  body  ;  though  so  long  as  it  perceives  things 
'  after  the  common  order  of  nature '  its  knowledge  of  itself  and 
the  body  is  not  adequate.^  Now  when  the  mind  is  in  the  act 
of  rational  or  scientific  knowledge  of  anything  whatever — in 
other  words,  when  it  perceives  things  '  under  the  form  of 
eternity,' — Spinoza  says,  transferring  to  the  relation  between  the 
mind  and  its  own  body  what  belongs  to  the  relation  between 
the  mind  and  the  object  of  knowledge,  that  the  mind  knows 
its  own  body  '  under  the  form  of  eternity.'  So  knowing  its 
own  body  and  consequently  itself,  it  is  eternal,  and  depends 
only  on  its  own  activity  for  this  eternity.  As  Spinoza  says  o 
farther  on,  '  the  mind  conceives  nothing  under  the  form  of 
eternity,  save  so  far  as  it  conceives  the  being  of  its  own 
body  under  the  form  of  eternity,  that  is,  save  so  far  as  it 
is  eternal.'  (Eth.  V.  Pr.  31,  Demonstr. ;  cp.  Pr.  29).  The  verbal 
confusion  involved  in  Spinoza's  way  of  stating  his  doctrine  is 
no  doubt  surprising  at  the  present  day.  But  it  has  not  been 
assumed  here  to  explain  this  particular  doctrine ;  we  could 
not  help  taking  note  of  it,  on  quite  independent  grounds, 
in  going  through  the  Second  Part.-  And  when  we  remember 
that  in  Spinoza's  time  psychology  was  really  in  its  infancy, 
and  hardly  any  serious  attempt  had  been  made  to  work  out 
the  theory  of  perception,  our  surprise  may  be  considerably 
abated. 

Apart  from  the  peculiar  form  of  his  argument,  vSpinoza 

falls  in  this  place  into  a  metaphysical  difficulty  of  which  he 

was  so  far  aware  that  he  made  a  distinct  effi^rt  to  escape  it. 

;  The  eternity  of  which  the  mind   is  conscious  in  the  act  of  j 

\  rational  knowledge  is  w'.olly  out  of  relation  to  time.     Also  it 

is  distinctly  stated  to  be  a  kind  of  existence.^     Here,  then,  we 

'  Eth.  2,  Pr.  24-29.  -  P.  196,  above. 

^  Hanc   eius  existentiam  tempore  definiri  sive  per  durationem  explicari  non 
posse.     Prop.  2^,  Schol. 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  299 

have  existence  out  of  time,  and  a  knowledge  or  perception  of 
it  in  consciousness.  Now  it  is  at  least  a  serious  question 
whether  existence  out  of  time  is  conceivable.  We  cannot 
think  of  existence  except  in  terms  of  actual  or  possible  ex- 
perience. But  experience  involves  consciousness  or  at  least 
feeling.  And  it  is  not  a  metaphysical  speculation,  but  an  es- 
tablished fact  of  science,  that  change  of  some  kind  is  the 
necessary  condition  of  all  feeling  and  experience.  Every  feeling 
of  which  we  know  anything  or  can  form  a  notion  is  a  feeling  of 
transition,  of  an  event,  of  something  happening  :  which  on  the 
physical  side  is  motion  of  some  kind  in  the  sentient  organism. 
Even  an  apparently  continuous  sensation  is  a  series  of 
many  rapidly  succeeding  nervous  shocks.  The  more  we 
analyse  feeling,  the  more  we  find  change  and  motion  to  be  its 
constant  form  :  and  these  involve  time.  It  would  seem,  there- 
fore, that  without  making  any  transcendental  or  universal 
affirmation,  but  as  a  matter  of  human  experience  as  far  as  it 
has  gone,  we  must  say  that  existence  out  of  time  is  a  combi- 
nation of  words  to  which  we  can  attach  no  real  meaning.  The 
position  involves  more  consequences  than  can  be  here  dis- 
cussed ;  as  for  instance  the  total  rejection  of  all  attempts, 
however  powerful  and  ingenious,  to  set  up  an  Absolute,  Uncon- 
ditioned, Unknowable,  or  any  form  of  unapproachable  reality 
supposed  to  be  somehow  more  real  than  the  things  we  feel 
and  know.  For  the  present  it  is  enough  to  beg  the  reader  to 
believe  that  such  a  position  is  philosophically  tenable,  not- 
withstanding that  (as  he  can  see  for  himself)  it  is  in  no  way 
repugnant  to  common  sense.  If,  being  valiant  in  speculation 
and  disregarding  objections  of  this  kind,  we  begin  to  talk 
about  something  alleged  to  exist  without  relation  to  time,  the 
objection  will  be  forced  upon  us  in  a  practical  shape  by  the 
extreme  difficulty  we  shall  soon  find  in  pursuing  our  discourse 
without  manifest  contradictions.  Probably  the  objection  did 
not  occur  to  Spinoza  in  the  shape  in  which  it  is  here  put :  for 
that  shape  is  the  result  of  modern  inquiries.     But  he  felt  the 


300  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

logical  difficulty  of  discussing  eternity  in  the  language  of  time ; 
and  he  endeavoured  to  secure  himself  by  the  following  char- 
acteristic remark. 

'  We  shall  here  note  that,  although  we  be  now  certain  that  the 
mind,  so  far  as  it  doth  conceive  things  under  the  form  of  eternity,  is 
eternal ;  yet,  in  order  that  our  ensuing  exposition  may  be  the  easier 
and  the  better  understood,  we  shall  consider  the  mind  (like  as  we 
have  done  thus  far)  as  if  at  a  given  moment  it  began  to  be,  and 
to  understand  things  under  the  form  of  eternity  ;  and  this  we  may 
safely  do  without  any  risk  of  error,  so  that  we  use  care  to  conclude 
nothing  except  from  evident  premisses.' ' 

Having  laid  down  this  caution,  Spinoza  sets  forth  the 
'  intellectual  love  of  God  '  which  is  the  crown  of  the  mind's 
perfection.  It  has  already  been  stated  that  the  most  perfect 
activity  and  excellence  of  the  mind  is  to  understand  things 
with  the  third  or  intuitive  kind  of  knowledge  ;  and  that  this 
begets  the  highest  degree  of  contentment  attainable  by  human 
nature.^  Again,  this  knowledge  implies  the  knowledge  of' 
God  ;  hence  the  delight  of  the  highest  intellectual  activity  is 
a  pleasure  accompanied  with  the  idea  of  God  as  its  cause. 
That  is,  it  is  love  of  God  ;  '  not  in  that  we  conceive  him '  adds 
Spinoza  '  as  now  present,  but  in  that  we  understand  God  as 
eternal,  and  this  is  what  I  call  the  intellectual  love  of  God.' ' 
Like  the  knowledge  from  which  it  springs,  it  is  eternal  ;  on 
which  there  is  another  curious  remark. 

*  Although  this  love  toward  God  hath  had  no  beginning,  yet  it 
hath  all  the  perfections  of  love  in  the  same  manner  as  if  it  had  arisen 
in  time,  as  we  feigned  in  the  corollary  to  the  foregoing  proposition. 
And  herein  there  is  no  difference  but  that  the  mind  hath  eternally 
had  the  same  perfections  which  (as  we  feigned)  accrued  to  it  at  a  par- 
ticular time,  and  that  accompanied  by  the  idea  of  God  as  the  eternal 
cause  thereof  And  since  pleasure  consisteth  in  a  passage  to  greater 
perfection,  'tis  plain  blessedness  must  consist  in  this,  that  the  mind 
hath  perfection  in  full  possession.' 

Here,  the  reader  will  observe,  we  are  required  to  form  the 

'  Prop.  31,  Schol.  ^  Propp.  25,  27.  '  Pr.  32,  Coroll. 


THE  DELIVERANCE  OF  MAX.  301 

idea  of  an  eternal  causation  ;  and  this  lands  us  in  an  impossi- 
bility if  we  regard  the  cause  as  an  antecedent  of  the  effect,  as 
in  that  case  we  have  to  conceive  a  relation  which  is  in  time 
and  out  of  time  at  once.  But  this  difficulty  would  probably 
not  touch  Spinoza.  There  is  nothing  to  show  that  he  con- 
ceived cause  and  effect  as  being  necessarily  antecedent  and 
consequent  ;  on  the  contrary,  it  is  pretty  clear  from  the  First 
Part  of  the  Ethics  that  he  did  not.  God,  as  the  absolute 
first  cause,  is  the  immediate  cause  of  motion  and  matter,  and 
they  of  all  material  things  ;  and  similar  relations  hold  in  the 
other  Attributes.  But  there  is  here  no  question  of  priority  in 
time. 

Freedom  from  the  passions,  though  not  itself  perfection, 
is  a  condition  of  perfection :  hence  the  mind,  so  far  as_it 
partakes  of  eternity,  must  enjoy  this  freedom,  and  Spinoza 
naturally  proceeds  to  show  that  '  the  mind  is  not  exposed, 
except  while  the  body  endures,  to  those  emotions  which 
are  reckoned  as  passions.'  Whence  it  follows  that  none 
but  the  intellectual  love  is  eternal.  And  here  for  the  first 
time  Spinoza  takes  distinct  notice  of  the  common  opinion  of 
immortality. 

'  If  we  consider  the  general  opinion  of  mankind,  we  shall-' 
find  that  they  are  indeed  aware  of  the  eternity  of  their  own 
mind  ;  but  confound  the  same  with  duration,  and  ascribe  it  to 
the  imagination  or  memory,  which  they  suppose  to  remain 
after  death.' '  This  explains  why  Spinoza  throughout  this 
part  of  his  work  avoids  the  use  of  the  term  immortality,  and  it 
exposes  more  fully  than  an}^  comment  could  do  the  hopeless- 
ness of  attempting  to  represent  him  as  maintaining  the 
immortality  of  the  soul  in  the  ordinary  sense  :  yet  the  attempt 
has  been  made. 

One  more  surprise  remains  :  the  philosopher  is  determined 
to  outdo  the  theologians  with  their  own  vocabulary.  '  God 
loves  himself  with  an  infinite  intellectual  love  : '  the  intellec- 

'  Pr.  34,  CoroU.  and  Schol. 


y>2  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

tual  love  of  human  minds  towards  God  is  part  of  this  infinite 
love,  and  in  it  God  may  be  said  to  love  men  ;  in  which  there 
is  no  contradiction  of  the  foregoing  statement  that  God 
neither  loves  nor  hates  any  one,  since  this  intellectual  love  is 
not  an  emotion.  It  is  perhaps  difficult  to  remember  that  the 
substance  of  the  propositions  thus  expressed  is  still  purely 
and  simply  the  human  mind's  contemplation  of  itself  and  its 
own  certain  knowledge  as  part  of  the  infinite  and  necessary 
order  of  the  universe  ;  that  for  Spinoza  the  divine  love  is  ^ 
nothing  else  than  conscious  acceptance  of  universal  law,  the 
'welcoming  every  event'  of  the  Stoics  ;  and  that  the  secret  of 
blessedness  and  glory  (for  those  titles  are  expressly  claimed 
and  justified)  is  none  other  than  a  mind  steadfastly  bent  on 
the  truth. 

It  seems  a  poor  and  barren  conclusion  to  bear  up  the 
solemnity  of  language  :  so  strong  is  the  prejudice  bred  of  our' 
inveterate  custom  of  hungering  after  dreams  and  neglecting 
the  realities  under  our  hands.  After  all,  if  we  turn  Spinoza's 
thought  into  a  guide  for  action,  if  we  translate  his  speculative 
propositions  into  a  practical  imperative,  what  is  the  outcome.'* 
Even  that  which  true  and  fearless  men  have  preached  through? 
all  the  generations  to  unheeding  ears.  Seek  the  truth,  fear 
not  and  spare  not  :  this  first,  this  for  its  own  sake,  this  only ; 
and  the  truth  itself  is  your  reward,  a  reward  not  measured  by 
length  of  days  nor  by  any  reckoning  of  men.  This  lesson 
assuredly  is  not  an  idle  one,  or  unworthy  to  be  set  forth  with 
fervent  and  solemn  words.  And  if  any  man  ever  had  a 
special  title  so  to  repeat  the  lesson,  that  man  was  Spinoza, 
whose  whole  life  was  an  example  of  it. 

On  the  strength  of  these  passages  Spinoza  has  been  called 
a  mystic ;  and,  while  they  have  perplexed  philosophical 
inquirers,  they  have  exercised  a  sort  of  fascination  on  many 
readers.  As  to  the  actual  contents  of  them,  their  author  is 
no  more  a  mystic  than  Aristotle,  if,  as  I  have  endeavoured  to 
show,  the  groundwork   of  his   doctrine  is   the   Aristotelian 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  303 

theory  that  contemplative  knowledge  is  the  highest  and  most ' 
proper  function  of  the  mind,  in  respect  of  which  alone  it  can 
be  said  to  partake  of  eternity.  Moreover  the  form  chosen 
by  Spinoza  may  be  partly  due,  as  I  have  already  hinted, 
to  the  desire  of  encountering  theologians  with  their  own 
weapons.  But  there  is  unquestionably  something  of  an  ex-  o 
alted  and  mystical  temper  in  his  expressions  ;  and  it  seems 
possible  enough  that,  but  for  his  scientific  training  in  the 
school  of  Descartes,  he  might  have  been  a  mystic  indeed.  If 
this  be  so,  Descartes  has  one  claim  the  more  to  the  gratitude 
of  mankind. 

But  these  seemingly  transcendental  propositions  are  not 
left  without  practical  application.  The  intellectual  love, 
being  a  quality  of  the  mind  '  inasmuch  as  it  is  regarded  as  an 
eternal  truth  depending  on  the  nature  of  God,'  is  indestruc- 
tible. And  the  greater  is  the  activity  in  a  particular  mind  of 
the  clear  understanding  described  as  the  second  and  third 
kinds  of  knowledge,  the  more  does  the  man  partake  of 
eternity,  the  less  is  he  exposed  to  evil  passions,  and  the  less 
does  he  fear  death  (Pr.  38,  39).  And  then  there  is  a  sudden 
return  to  the  physical  aspect  of  things,  as  if  to  show  that  it 
has  never  been  forgotten.  '  He  that  hath  a  body  of  most 
various  capacities  hath  also  a  mind  whose  greatest  part  is 
eternal '  (Prop.  39).  For  the  '  power  of  ordering  and  con-c 
necting  the  affections  of  the  body  according  to  the  intellec- 
tual order '  is  a  perfection  of  the  body.  Naturally  the  body  o 
includes  the  special  organs  of  thought  and  reflexion  ;  the 
outward  and  apparent  excellence  of  the  human  body  is  not 
asserted  to  be  the  necessary  index  of  contemplative  power. 
At  the  same  time  Spinoza  would  no  doubt  have  said  that, 
other  things  being  equal,  the  commonly  recognized  qualities 
of  health,  strength,  comeliness,  activity,  and  the  like,  are  all  in 
themselves  good  and  desirable  ;  and  that  whatever  makes  for 
the  health  of  the  body  must  in  some  degree  make  for  the 


304  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

health  of  the  mind.     In  this  place  his  meaning  is  defined  by 
himself  in  a  Scholium. 

'  Since  human  bodies  possess  various  capacities,  there  is  no  doubt 
they  may  be  of  such  a  character  as  to  be  attached  to  minds  that  have 
much  knowledge  of  themselves  and  of  God,  and  whose  greatest  or 
chief  part  is  eternal,  and  this  to  such  a  point  that  they  scarce  fear  death. 
But  for  the  better  understanding  of  this  it  shall  be  observed  that  we 
live  in  perpetual  mutation,  and  are  called  happy  or  unhappy  accord- 
ing as  we  change  for  the  better  or  the  worse.  Thus  one  who  from 
being  a  child  or  a  youth  becomes  a  corpse  is  said  to  be  unhappy,  and 
contrariwise  it  is  accounted  happiness  if  we  have  been  able  to  run  the 
full  course  of  life  with  a  sound  mmd  in  a  sound  body.  And  in  truth  he  ^ 
who  (like  a  child)  hath  a  body  of  very  few  capacities  and  largely 
subject  to  outward  influences,  hath  a  mind  which,  if  we  take  it  in  itself, 
is  little  or  not  at  all  aware  of  itself,  or  God,  or  the  nature  of  things  ; 
and  contrariwise  he  that  hath  a  body  of  many  capacities  hath  a  mind 
which,  if  we  take  it  in  itself,  is  very  well  aware  of  itself,  of  God,  and 
of  the  nature  of  things.  Therefore  it  is  our  chief  endeavour  in  this 
life  to  change  the  infant's  body,  so  far  as  its  nature  admits  and  is 
convenient,  into  another  which  shall  have  many  capacities,  and  shall 
belong  to  a  mind  as  fully  aware  as  may  be  of  itself,  of  God,  and  of 
the  nature  of  things  \  and  so  that  everything  that  belongs  to  its 
memory  or  imagination  shall  in  comparison  of  the  understanding  be 
of  hardly  any  weight.' 

Here  Spinoza  seems  to  regard  education,  both  physical 
and  mental,  as  a  process  of  organic  development  not  dififering 
in  kind  from  the  purely  natural  processes  of  growth  ;  a  guid- 
ing and  training  of  the  possibilities  of  variation  already  given 
in  the  organism.  Though  the  point  is  but  slightly  touched, 
there  is  enough  to  show  a  striking  approximation  to  our  most 
recent  discoveries  in  this  branch  of  the  science  of  human 
nature,  the  most  important  and  perhaps  the  most  neglected 
of  its  practical  applications. 

It  has  already  been  incidentally  stated  that  the  eternal  o 
part  of  the  mind  is  greater  in   some  individuals  and  less  in 
others.     But  however  this  proportion  may  be,  the  eternal  part 
is  in  every  case  the  more  perfect :  for  this  is  the  only  truly 


THE   DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  305 

active  part  of  the  mind,  and  perfection  consists  in  and  is 
measured  by  active  power.  And  here  Spinoza  adds,  rather  o 
abruptly,  a  final  metaphysical  conclusion  :  namely,  '  that  our 
mind,  so  far  as  it  understands,  is  an  eternal  mode  of  thought, 
which  is  determined  by  another  eternal  mode  of  thought, 
and  that  again  by  another,  and  so  on  to  infinity ;  so  that  all 
together  make  up  the  eternal  and  infinite  understanding  of 
God.'  The  other  eternal  mode  of  thought  by  which  the  mind 
is  immediately  determined  would  seem  to  be  the  thing  known 
by  the  mind  '  under  the  form  of  eternity,'  and  the  infinite 
chain  in  which  these  are  links  to  be  the  whole  order  of  the 
universe  under  the  attribute  of  Thought.  But,  it  may  be 
said,  this  will  be  only  the  order  as  existing  at  a  given 
moment,  since  the  thing  known  '  under  the  form  of  eternity  ' 
must  be  a  particular  thing.  Spinoza  might  reply  that  it  is 
only  the  infirmity  of  human  imagination  that  compels  us  to 
conceive  the  order  of  things  as  fixed  at  a  particular  time,  and 
even  as  it  is  we  can  conceive  that  the  state  of  the  universe  at 
a  given  moment  includes  potentially  the  whole  history  for  an 
infinite  past  and  future.  This  would  involve  holding  that  the 
difference  between  potential  and  actual  existence  is  only  in 
respect  of  human  imagination,  besides  the  assumption  (made 
as  a  matter  of  course  by  Spinoza)  that  our  knowledge  of  the 
laws  of  nature  is  or  may  be  exact  and  universal.  However, 
the  speculation  is  not  pursued,  and  we  are  brought  back  to  a 
more  practical  ground, 

'  Though  we  knew  not  that  our  mind  is  eternal,  we  should 
still  put  in  the  first  place  piety  and  religion,"  and  generally 
everything  which  in  the  Fourth  Part  we  showed  to  belong  to 
valour  and  high-mindedness  '  (Pr.  41). 

The  proof  is  simply  that  the  virtues  and  the  reasons  for 
practising  them  have  already  been  established  on  a  footing 
independent  of  the  mind's  eternity. 

'  These  terms  have  been  defined  in  Eth.  4.  37,  Schol.  i.  Religion  is  all 
desire  and  action  prompted  by  knowledge  of  God,  i.e.,  by  rational  knowledge  : 
piety  is  the  desire  of  well-doing  produced  by  a  life  according  to  reason 

X 


N 

306  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

'  But  theJjelief  of  the  common  sort,'  it  is  added,  '  seemeth  to  be 
^.  otherwise.  [For  they  mostly  seem  to  hold  themselves  to  be  free  in 
proportion  as  they  may  do  after  their  own  lusts,  and  to  be  deprived 
of  their  right  in  proportion^  as  they  are  bound   to  live  after  the 
commandment  of  God's  law.  5  So  they  hold  piety  and  religion,  and 
generally  everythmg  that  belongs  to  firmness  of  mmd,  to  be  burdens, 
and  hope  after  death  to  cast  them  off  and  have  the  reward  of  their 
service,  that  is  of  piety  and  religion.     But  not  merely  this  hope,  but 
likewise  (and  chiefly)  fear,  to  wit  of  being  punished  with  grievous 
torments  after  death,  doth  move  them  to  live  after  God's  law,  so  far 
as  their  poverty  and  weakness  of  spirit  doth  admit.     And  if  men  had 
not  this  hope  and  fear,  but  held  that  the  mind  perishes   with  the 
body,  and  no  longer  life  remains  for  poor  mortals  (worn  out  forsooth 
with  the  burden  of  pious  living),  they  would  go  back  to  their  own 
desires,  guide  their  actions  by  the  desire  of  the  moment,  and  be-' 
ruled  rather  by  hazard  than  by  themselves.     Which  to  me  seemeth 
-    no  less  absurd  than  if  a  man,  because  he   knows  he  cannot  with 
wholesome  food  sustain  his  body  for  all  time,  should  choose  to  cram 
himself  with  poison  and  deadly  things  ;  or  because  he  perceives  that 
the  mind  is  not  eternal,  I  mean  not  immortal,  would  therefore  live  as 
one   demented   and   without   aid  of  reason.     But   things   of   such 
absurdity  are  scarce  fit  to  be  mentioned.' 

The  vulgar  notion  of  virtue  having  a  reward  to  claim  is  » 

i 

further  contradicted  in  the  ij^ext  and  final  proposition. 

'  Blessedness  is  not  the  prize  of  virtue,  but  virtue  itself ; 
nor  have  we  the  gifts  of  virtue  through  controlling  our 
desires,  but  we  can  control  our  desires  because  we  have  the 
gifts  of  virtue. 

' ,  ,  .  Herewith  I  have  finished  all  that  I  purposed  to  set 
forth  of  the  power  of  the  mind  over  the  emotions,  and  of  her 
freedom.  Whence  it  is  evident  how  great  is  the  wise  man's 
power  and  his  advantage  over  the  ignorant  man  who  is  driven 
by  blind  desire.  For  such  a  man  is  distracted  by  external 
influences  and  in  many  other  ways  besides,  and  doth  never 
attain  true  contentment  in  his  soul  ;  he  lives  as  it  were  with- 
out sense  of  himself  and  God  and  the  nature  of  things,  and 
no  sooner  ceases  to  sufier  than  he  ceases  to  be.  Whereas  the 
wise  man,  if  wc  take  him  as  such,  is  of  a  constant  mind,  and, 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  307 

being  aware  of  himself  and  God  and  the  nature  of  things  in  a 
way  of  eternal  necessity,  doth  never  cease  to  be,  but  is  ever 
in  possession  of  true  contentment.  And  if  the  way  I  have 
shown  to  lead  hither  seems  exceedingly  hard,  yet  it  may 
be  discovered.  That  truly  must  be  hard  which  is  so  seldom 
found.  For  if  salvation  were  so  easy  and  could  be  found 
with  little  trouble,  how  should  it  come  to  pass  that  nearly  all 
mankind  neglect  it }  But  every  excellent  work  is  as  difficult 
as  it  is  rare.' 

These  are  the  last  words  of  Spinoza's  Ethics  ;  words  of 
gravity  but  not  of  discouragement.      In  their  literal  sense 
they  are  not  quite  consistent  with  what  he    has  said   in  a 
former  proposition  ;    for  we  have  there  read   that  it  is   not 
difficult  to  pursue  the  life  of  reason  and  freedom  :  and  sucli  a 
life  must  lead  ere  long,  on   Spinoza's  principles,  to  wisdom 
and  true  knowledge.     Perhaps  he    contemplated  a  practical 
standard    of  righteous   living  and    happiness    attainable   by 
ordinary  men  with  a  good  will,  and  a  higher  kind  of  satis- 
faction accessible  only  by  strenuous  thinking  and  the  habit  of  • 
contemplative  science.     He  seems  to  have  thought  it  at  least  q 
improbable  that  the  great  bulk  of  mankind  should  ever  be 
able  to  dispense  with  the  external  coercion  of  human  laws 
and  ordinances,  or  even  with  the  belief  in    supernatural  re- 
wards and  punishments,  as  a  guide  of  conduct.     Once  more 
we  note  how  near  he  comes  to  the  Stoics.     The  wise  man  is 
thoroughly  possessed   of  the  knowledge  that  virtue  is  self- 
sufficient,    and    therein    finds    his    happiness,   whatever   his 
external   conditions  :     but  the  perfect  ideal  of  wisdom   can 
scarcely  be  realized   by  man.     The  philosopher  nevertheless 
makes  this  his  aim,  and  comes  as  near  it  as  he  can.     The  way 
is  open  to  everyone  alike  :  but    as  it  is,   the  bulk  of  man- 
kind are  governed  by  the  coarser  motives  which  alone  they 
appreciate,  and  which  experience  has  shown  to  be  necessary 
for  the  maintenance  of  society.     Such  is  the  Stoic  position  as 

well  as  Spinoza's.     In  so  far  as  this  is  a  statement  of  fact,  wc 

X  2 


So6  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

have  no  right  to  ask  whether  it  is  agreeable  or  flattering  to 
human  pride,  but  only  whether  it  is  true ;  and,  whether  we 
consider  Spinoza's  time  or  our  own,  we  shall  find  it  not  easy 
to  deny.  So  far  as  it  implies  the  absence  of  hope  that  the  - 
description  may  some  day  cease  to  be  true,  at  least  as  regards 
the  commonwealth  of  civilized  nations,  we  may  regret  that 
Spinoza  did  not  see  his  way  to  believing  in  the  improvement 
of  mankind.  But  before  we  pass  any  intellectual  or  moral 
censure  upon  him  for  this,  we  should  ask  ourselves  whether, 
his  circumstances  and  his  knowledge  of  history  and  institutions 
being  such  as  they  were,  he  had  reasonable  grounds  for  ex- 
pecting any  continuous  improvement.  He  wrote  in  a  time 
which  on  the  whole  was  one  of  reaction,  and  in  which  the 
blessings  of  a  far  distant  past,  partly  by  the  legendary  bias 
common  to  all  ages,  partly  under  the  special  influence  of  the 
Renaissance,  were  vastly  exaggerated.  The  movement  of 
free  thought  seemed  arrested  ;  in  politics  everything  was 
confusion  ;  the  growth  of  science  was  only  beginning. 
Spinoza  was  not  the  man  to  win  a  cheap  reputation  for  large- 
heartedness  by  facile  promises  of  a  golden  age. 

In  this  last  Part  of  the  Ethics  we  have  traced  a  curiously 
involved  and  artificial  argument,  and  have  tried  to  show  to 
what  extent  it  turns  on  Spinoza's  peculiar  use  of  language 
which  modern  criticism  cannot  allow  to  pass  current.  Yet 
his  doctrine  of  the  eternity  of  the  mind  must  remain  one  of 
the  most  brilliant  endeavours  of  speculative  philosophy,  and 
it  throws  a  sort  of  poetical  glow  over  the  formality  of  his 
exposition.  We  have  already  said  that  it  has  a  sufficiently 
certain  practical  lesson.  But  still  we  linger  over  it,  seekingo 
for  some  expression  which  may  so  give  us  the  central  idea 
that  we  can  accept  and  use  it  for  ourselves,  some  concentra- 
tion of  the  commanding  thought  without  the  precarious 
dialectical  form  in  which  it  is  clothed.  If  the  task  were  still 
to  attempt,  it  might  be  a  hard  one  ;  but  there  is  no  need  for 
any   such    attempt.     The    essence   of   Spinoza's   thought   is 


THE  DELIVERANCE   OF  MAN.  309 

already  secured  for  us  by  a  master  who  combines  delicacy  of 
perception  and   the  intellectual   tact  which  is  the  flower  of 
criticism  with  consummate  power  over  language.     M.  Renane 
has  expressed  it  in  the  perfectly  chosen  words  which  I  have 
placed  at  the  head  of  this  chapter,  and  with  which,  so  far  as  I 
can  preserve  them  in  translation,  I  shall  now  end  it :  Reason 
leads  Death  in  trimnpJi,  and  the  work  done  for  Reason  is  done 
for  eternity. 


3IO  SPINOZA:   HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER   X. 

THE  CITIZEN  AND   THE  STATE. 

Ond'  egli  ancora  :  Or  di' ;  sarebbe  il  peggio 
Per  I'uomo  in  terra,  se  non  fosse  cive  ? 
Si,  rispos'  io  :  e  qui  ragion  non  clieggio. 

Dante  :  Paradise,  8,  115. 

Whatsoever  therefore  is  consequent  to  a  time  of  war,  where  every  man  is 
enemy  to  every  man  ;  the  same  is  consequent  to  the  time  wherein  men  live 
without  other  security  than  what  their  own  strength  and  their  own  invention  shall 
furnish  them  withal.  In  such  condition,  there  is  no  place  for  industry,  because  the 
fruit  thereof  is  uncertain  :  and  consequently  no  culture  of  the  earth  ;  no  navigation, 
nor  use  of  the  commodities  that  may  be  imported  by  sea ;  no  commodious  building  ; 
no  instruments  of  moving,  and  removing,  such  things  as  require  much  force ;  no 
knowledge  of  the  face  of  the  earth  ;  no  account  of  time  ;  no  arts  ;  no  letters  ;  no 
society ;  and  which  is  worst  of  all,  continual  fear,  and  danger  of  violent  death  ; 
and  the  life  of  man,  solitary,  poor,  nasty,  brutish,  and  short. 

HoBBES  :  Leviathan,  ch.  13. 

The  metaphysical  parts  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  are  expressed, 
it  must  be  allowed,  in  a  manner  not  congenial  to   English 
habits  of  thought :  and  in  studying  his  '  Ethics '  the  English 
reader  may  be  at  some  disadvantage  as  compared  with  those 
who  have  been  trained   in  a  Continental  school.     When  we 
come  to  Spinoza's  theory  of  politics  the  balance  is  redressed. 
Though  not  actually  a  disciple  of  Hobbes,  Spinoza  so  closely 
follows  him  that  the  philosophy  of  law  and  government  which 
appears  in  the  *  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  is  just  indi- 
cated in  the  '  Ethics,'  and  is  worked  out  in  the   '  Tractatus 
Politicus,'  distinctly  belongs  to  the  general  doctrine  character- 
istic of  the   English  school  of  jurisprudence.     This  doctrine 
was  first  clearly  given  out  by  Hobbes,  then  taken  up  after  a 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  311 

long  interval  by  Bentham,  then  carried  on  with  additions 
into  a  new  generation  by  Austin  ;  it  has  in  our  own  time  been 
endowed  by  the  work  of  Sir  Henry  Maine  and  others  with 
the  breadth  and  flexibility  that  were  wanting  in  its  earlier 
stages,  and  is  now  accepted,  with  more  or  less  development  and 
modification,  by  nearly  all  English  writers  who  pay  any  serious 
attention  to  the  scientific  study  of  law. 

Hence  the  leading  ideas  of  Spinoza's  treatise  on  Politics 
ought  to  have  for  an  English  reader  nothing  very  strange  in 
them.  The  treatise  was  the  latest  work  of  his  life,  and  is  un- 
finished ;  but  that  which  remained  to  be  added  would  have 
been  concerned  mostly  with  points  of  detail.  The  editors  of 
the  '  Opera  Posthuma '  have  given  in  the  preface  an  extract 
from  a  letter  of  Spinoza's  written  while  he  was  engaged  on 
this  work. 

*  I  should  not  miss  this  opportunity  were  I  not  already  engaged  by 
a  matter  I  judge  more  to  the  purpose,  and  which  I  think  will  also  please 
you  better,  that  is,  the  composition  of  a  treatise  on  Politics,  which 
on  your  persuasion  I  began  some  time  ago.  Of  this  treatise  there 
are  six  chapters  now  finished.  The  first  contains  a  kind  of  introduc- 
tion to  the  body  of  the  work.  The  second  treats  of  the  law  of  nature  ; 
the  third,  of  the  right  of  the  supreme  magistrate  ;  the  fourth,  what 
affairs  of  state  be  in  the  supreme  magistrate's  discretion  ;  the  fifth, 
what  is  that  last  and  chief  good  which  a  society  may  contemplate  ; 
and  the  sixth,  by  what  method  a  monarchic  il  government  ought  to 
be  established  that  it  may  not  slide  into  a  tyranny.  At  present  I 
am  on  the  seventh  chapter,  wherein  I  formally  prove  all  the  heads  of 
the  foregoing  sixth  chapter  touching  the  institution  of  a  well  ordered 
monarchy.  After  this  I  shall  proceed  to  aristocracy  and  popular 
government,  lastly  to  legislation  and  other  particular  questions 
regarding  political  science.' 

Neither  the  date,  the  occasion  alluded  to  in  the  first  sen- 
tence, nor  the  correspondent's  name  is  disclosed.  The 
chapters  on  aristocracy  were  afterwards  added,  and  one  on 
democracy  was  begun,  in  the  middle  of  which  the  treatise 
breaks  off.     There  is  another  letter  of  Spinoza's  to  Jarig  Jellis 


312  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

(Ep.  47),  dated  February  17,  1671,  which  seems  to  throw  some 
more  light  on  the  matter.     In  this  he  says : — 

'  A  friend  of  mine  sent  me  a  while  ago  a  book  entitled  "  Homo 
Politicus,"  '  whereof  I  had  heard  much  talk.  On  perusal  of  it  I 
found  it  as  mischievous  a  book  as  can  be  devised  or  composed  by 
man.  To  this  author's  mind  the  chief  good  is  rank  and  wealth,  and 
thereto  he  directs  his  teaching.  .  .  ,  For  the  rest,  he  mightily  re- 
commends deceit,  promising  and  breaking  one's  promise,  lying, 
false  swearing,  and  much  else  of  the  same  kind.  When  I  had  read 
all  this  I  fell  to  thinking  how  I  might  indirectly  controvert  this  author 
by  a  book  in  wliich  I  should  treat  of  the  chief  good,  then  show  the 
distracted  and  wretched  state  of  those  who  seek  office  and  fortune, 
and  lastly  prove  by  convincing  reasons  and  abundant  examples  that 
commonwealths  must  needs  perish,  and  have  perished,  through  men's 
insatiable  appetite  for  these  thmgs.' 

It  is  possible  that  we  have  here  the  germ  of  the  *  Tractatus 
Politicus,'  though  the  plan  sketched  out  is  very  different  from 
that  which  Spinoza  began  to  execute.  All  that  is  left  of  it  is 
the  problem,  treated  in  a  purely  scientific  manner,  of  deter- 
mining the  conditions  of  stability  in  political  institutions. 
Spinoza's  unfinished  treatise  cannot  be  said  to  hold  a  place 
in  political  science  at  all  comparable  to  that  which  is  held  by 
the  '  Ethics  '  in  philosophy.  So  far  as  I  know,  it  has  been  but 
little  studied  and  has  had  no  marked  influence  on  Continental 
thought.  In  England,  where  it  might  have  had  a  better 
chance,  the  general  prejudice  against  Spinoza  prevented  it 
from  obtaining  the  attention  it  deserved.  Thus  the  political 
theory  of  Spinoza  has  been  left  as  it  were  stranded  between 
the  two  main  currents  of  speculation.  We  shall  find,  however, 
that  the  examination  of  it  is  no  waste  of  time.  The  '  Tracta- 
tus Politicus  '  is  much  more  than  what  it  appears  to  be  at 
first  sight,  a  mere  adaptation  of  Hobbes  to  the  terminology  of 
the  'Ethics.'     Hobbes    is    nowhere  expressly  mentioned  by 

'  Presumably  the  work  catalogued  by  Barbier  in  his  Dictioitnaire  dcs  ouvrages 
anonynies  (No  20,602  in  ed.  1824).  '  Homo  politicus,  hoc  est,  consiliarius  novus, 
officiarius  et  aulicus  secundum  hodiernam  praxin,  auctore  Pacifico  a  Lapide 
(Christophoro  Rapp,   Cancellario  Electorali  Borussise).      CosvwpoH,   1665,  in-4.* 


THE   CITIZEN  AND   THE  STATE.  313 

Spinoza,  save  once  in  answer  to  a  correspondent,  and  once  in 
a  note  to  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico  -Politicus.'  •  But  the  depar- 
tures from  his  method  and  conclusions  involve  a  good  deal  of 
tacit  criticism ;  and  this  implied  criticism  takes  a  strikingly- 
modern  line  on  some  points.  For  substantial  anticipation  of 
modern  constitutional  doctrines  it  would  be  unreasonable  to 
look  in  a  writer  of  Spinoza's  time.  Occasional  remarks  occur, 
however,  which  make  us  regret  that  Spinoza  never  wrote  his 
chapter  on  the  theory  of  legislation.  He  points  out  with  per- 
fect clearness  the  futility  of  sumptuary  laws,  and  assigns  the 
true  ground  of  it,  namely,  that  society  has  no  interest  in  en- 
forcing them.  '  Laws  which  can  be  broken  without  any  wrong 
to  one's  neighbour  are  made  light  of ;  and  so  far  from  such 
laws  restraining  the  appetite  and  lusts  of  mankind,  they  rather 
heighten  them.  Nitimiir  in  vetituni  semper,  aipvnusqne  negata? 
Men  who  have  the  leisure  will  always  find  the  wit  to  evade  laws 
made  to  regulate  such  matters  as  cannot  be  wholly  forbidden, 
banquets,  games,  apparel,  and  the  like  ;  wherein  excess  only  is 
evil,  and  that  to  be  measured  by  the  particular  citizen's  for- 
tune ;  so  that  it  cannot  be  defined  by  statutes  of  general  ap- 
plication,'^ Spinoza  has  been  charged,  and  still  is  charged  by 
some  of  his  critics,  with  preaching  absolutism.  The  whole 
scope  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  which  is  an  ela- 
borate plea  for  liberty  of  thought  and  expression,  is  a  refuta- 
tion of  this  :  and  there  also  occur  in  the  '  Tractatus  Politicus' 
many  sentences  and  maxims  which  show  a  very  different  tem- 
per. Such  are  the  following : — '  It  makes  for  slavery,  not 
peace,  to  deliver  all  power  to  one  man.'  '  It  is  better  that  the 
just  counsels  of  a  realm  should  be  laid  open  to  enemies,  than 

'  Cap.  16,  §  34,  «.  '  In  whatever  commonwealth  a  man  is,  he  may  be  free. 
For  certainly  a  man  may  be  so  far  free  as  he  is  governed  by  reason.  But  reason 
every  way  persuadeth  to  peace  (N.B.  Hobbes  is  otherwise)  ;  but  this  cannot  be 
secured  unless  the  laws  of  the  commonwealth  are  kept.'  There  is  an  oversight 
here,  for  Hobbes  makes  peace  the  first  object  of  rational  desire.  Leviathan, 
C.  13,  ad  fin.  and  c.  14. 

-  'We  spurn  at  rule,  and  seek  forbidden  ioys.' — Ovid,  Amor.  iii.  4.  17. 

'   Tract.  Polit,  c.  lO,  §  5. 


314  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

that  the  wicked  secrets  of  tyrants  should  be  concealed  from 
citizens.'  With  this  last  saying  we  may  contrast  one  of 
Hobbes : — '  In  deliberations  that  ought  to  be  kept  secret, 
whereof  there  be  many  occasions  in  public  business,  the 
counsels  of  many,  and  especially  in  assemblies,  are  danger- 
ous.' ' 

It  may  be  convenient,  before  entering  upon  details,  to  give 
a  general  view  of  Spinoza's  plan,  and  of  the  extent  to  which 
he  agrees  with  and  differs  from  Hobbes.  They  both  aim  at 
the  construction  of  a  science  of  politics  on  the  basis  of  the 
known  facts  of  human  nature  ;  and  the  assumptions  they 
make  about  average  human  nature  are  much  the  same.  But 
Hobbes,  writing  with  a  view  to  immediate  controversies,  does 
not  adventure  himself  to  any  length  on  the  path  of  speculative 
construction.  The  practical  bearing  of  his  argument  may  be 
summed  up  in  one  sentence :  Every  monarch  ought  to  be  ab- 
solutely supreme  in  matters  both  spiritual  and  temporal  ; 
England  is  a  monarchy  ;  therefore  the  king  of  England  is  ab- 
solute. Spinoza,  on  the  other  hand,  undertakes  the  ideal  con- 
struction of  the  most  stable  types  of  institutions  for  monarchy, 
aristocracy,  and  democracy  respectively.  He  goes  nearly  as 
far  as  Hobbes,  but  not  quite,  in  his  dislike  and  distrust  of  re- 
volutions ;  and,  probably  taking  from  Hobbes  his  notions  of 
the  English  Constitution  and  of  contemporary  English  history, 
gives  the  English  civil  war  as  an  instance  of  a  rebellion  which 
had  ended  in  complete  failure.  He  thinks  it  must  be  almost 
always  a  fatal  mistake  to  attempt  a  fundamental  change  in  an 
existing  government,  of  whatever  type  it  may  be.  But  in  the 
abstract  his  preference  is  for  democracy,  a  preference  more 
distinctly  expressed  in  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  ' 
than  anywhere  else.  Democracy  is  defined,  however,  in  such 
a  way  as  to  include  most  of  the  governments  commonly 
called  aristocratic  or  constitutional.  It  is  also  remarkable 
that  Spinoza's  ideal  monarchy  is  on  the  whole  a  more  popular 

'  Leviathan,  c.  25. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  315 

government  than  his  ideal  aristocracy.     His  theory  of  sove- 
reignty is  essentially  the  same  as  that  of  Hobbes.     But  he 
does  not  carry  it  out  into  the  same  unqualified  consequences. 
According  to  Hobbes  the  origin  of  the  State  is  a  covenant 
of  mutual  concession  prompted  by  the  mutual  fear  of  men  in 
a  lawless  condition,  and  by  the  rational  desire  of  peace  which 
is  the  first  law  of  nature  ;  where  a  law  of  nature  means  a  rule 
discovered  by  reason  as   a  means  toward   self-preservation. 
The  sovereign,  whether  he  be  one  man  or  an  assembly  of  men, 
bears  the  person  of  the  united  multitude  who  '  reduce  all  their 
wills,  by  plurality  of  voices,  unto  one  will,'  and  in  this  union 
become  a  commonwealth.     The  collected  power  and  authority 
of  every  citizen  is  transferred  to  him  by  the  common  man- 
date, to  be  used  at  his  discretion  for  their  peace  and  common 
defence.     Further,  the  mandate  is  irrevocable,  since  it  is  not 
several  from  each  citizen  to  the  sovereign,  but  depends  on  the 
social  covenant  of  all  the  citizens.     Every  subject  has  cove- 
nanted with  every  other  that  their  natural  right  shall  be  and 
remain  transferred  to  the  sovereign.     Hobbes  admits  that  the 
unanimous  assent  of  the  sovereign  and  all  the  subjects  (not 
of  the    subjects   without  the  sovereign)  may  determine  the 
sovereign's  right  ;  the  result  of  which  would  be  a  total  disso- 
lution of  government  and  return  to  the  natural  state  of  war. 
Whether  the  whole  commonwealth,  including  the  sovereign, 
might  change  the  form  of  government  without  passing  through 
anarchy  is  a  question  which,  so  far  as  I  know,  he  left  untouched. 
At  all  events,  the  sovereign  is  an  agent  whose  powers  cannot 
be  effectually  recalled  or  renounced  in  any  practically  possible 
circumstances  :  and  no  subject  can  complain  of  acts  of  state 
done  by  the  sovereign,  because  every  such  act  has  been  autho- 
rized by  the  subject  and  must  be  deemed  his  own.     Modern 
readers  cry  out,  of  course,  that  all  this  scheme  of  covenants 
and  mandates  is  the  purest  fiction.     But  Hobbes  is  not  alto- 
gether unprepared  even  for  this.     He  catches  the  objecting 
individual  in  a  dilemma.     Either  you  have  agreed,  he  says,  to 


3i6  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

transfer  your  power  to  the  sovereign  or  you  have  not.  If  you 
have,  then  you  are  estopped  from  disputing  the  acts  of  the 
sovereign.  If  you  have  not,  you  declare  yourself  a  stranger 
to  the  State,  and  therefore  the  State  has  no  duties  towards 
you  and  may  treat  you  as  an  enemy.  Apart  from  these  par- 
ticular turns  of  dialectic,  Hobbes'  argument  always  comes 
round  to  offering  the  choice  between  submission  and  war  ;  and 
war  is  for  him  so  clearly  the  worst  of  evils  that  the  choice 
cannot  be  doubtful.  Whether  the  argument  is  not  equally 
good  to  establish  (as  Dante  long  before  had  actually  sought 
to  establish)  the  necessity  of  an  universal  monarch  to  keep 
the  peace  between  sovereign  states,  as  the  sovereign  in  each 
state  between  individuals,  is  another  question  to  which  Hobbes 
does  not  seem  to  have  applied  himself 

In  Spinoza  we  do  not  find  these  rigorous  extremes.  He 
describes  government  as  founded  on  the  common  consent  of 
the  governed,  but  there  is  no  elaborate  analysis  of  the  sup- 
posed contract.  Again,  he  regards  the  power  of  the  State 
not  as  swallowing  up  the  natural  power  or  right  of  the  indi- 
vidual to  act  as  he  thinks  best  for  his  own  interest,  but  as 
holding  out  effectual  motives  to  the  citizens  to  agree  in  exer- 
cising that  right  or  power  in  a  particular  way,  namely,  by 
living  peaceably  under  the  laws.  Further,  although  he  no- 
where expressly  says  that  rebellion  is  right  even  in  an 
extreme  case,  he  does  say  quite  plainly  that  no  government 
is  really  absolute,  since  in  the  last  resort  its  power  is  limited 
by  the  endurance  of  its  subjects,  and  there  are  some  things 
which  no  community  will  endure.  Thus  a  supreme  govern- 
ment, though  it  cannot  offend  against  its  own  civil  laws,  may 
in  a  certain  sense  offend  against  the  law  of  nature.  Rulers 
who  so  carry  themselves  as  to  invite  the  contempt  or  hatred 
of  their  subjects  run  the  risk  of  committing  political  suicide. 
'  Such  deeds  turn  fear  into  indignation,  and  the  state  of  civil 
society  into  a  state  of  war.'  As  far  as  the  theory  of  the 
English  constitution    goes,  Parliament    might   pass  an    Act 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  317 

forbidding  people  to  perforin  their  contracts.  But  in  that 
case  Parliament  would  cease  to  be  obeyed,  and  Englishmen 
would  have  to  find  some  other  form  of  government.  More- 
over Spinoza  holds  it  competent  to  the  sovereign  power  not 
only  to  interpret  but  to  alter  the  fundamental  laws  of  the 
commonwealth,  provided  that  it  can  be  done  without  provok- 
ing a  revolution  that  would  in  fact,  not  only  by  the  construc- 
tive dissolution  of  a  supposed  covenant,  dissolve  civil  society  ; 
which  Hobbes  does  not  seem  to  contemplate.  There  is 
indeed  one  natural  right  which  Hobbes  holds  to  be  inalien- 
able, the  right  of  personal  self-defence  ;  and  consequently  the 
right  of  inflicting  punishment  '  is  not  grounded  on  any  con- 
cession or  gift  of  the  subjects,'  but  is  part  of  the  natural  right 
of  self-preservation  exercised  by  the  sovereign  on  behalf  of 
the  commonwealth.  '  For  the  subjects  did  not  give  the  sove- 
reign that  right ;  but  only  in  laying  down  theirs,  strengthened 
him  to  use  his  own,  as  he  should  think  fit,  for  the  preservation 
of  them  all :  so  that  it  was  not  given,  but  left  to  him,  and  to 
him  only.'  '  Spinoza's  exceptions  are  much  larger.  His 
language  on  this  point  in  the  17th  Chapter  of  the  '  Tractatus 
Theologico-Politicus '  is  particularly  explicit.  In  the  fore- 
going chapter  he  has  laid  down  the  theory  of  absolute 
sovereignty  as  founded  on  a  concurrent  cession  of  individual 
rights,  without  even  Hobbes'  reservation  of  self-defence. 
But  he  now  points  out  that  absolute  sovereignty  is  an  ideal 
never  completely  realized.  No  man  can  ever  put  himself 
wholly  at  another's  discretion ;  nor  have  there  ever  been 
rulers  who  did  not  stand  in  some  fear  of  their  subjects. 

'In  truth,  if  men  could  so  far  lose  their  natural  right,  that 
for  time  to  come  they  might  do  nothing  without  the  will  of  them 
that  held  sovereign  right,  then  governors  might  without  remedy  use 
all  extremities  of  violence  towards  their  subjects  :  which  opinion  I 
think  no  man  can  entertain.     Wherefore  it  must  be  allowed  that 

'  Leviathan,  ch.  28. 


3i8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

every  man  reserveth  to  himself  much  of  his  own  right,  which  there- 
fore dependeth  on  no  other  man's  resolution,  but  on  his  own  alone.'' 

In  fine,  the  right  of  a  government  over  its  subjects  is 
really  its  power  of  commanding  their  obedience  :  but  this 
does  not  mean  only  commanding  by  force  or  threats,  for  it  is 
the  fact  of  obedience,  not  the  motive,  that  makes  men 
subjects.  The  subject  fulfils  the  law  whether  he  obeys  from 
hope,  fear,  both  together,  or  any  other  cause. 

'  A  man  is  then  most  under  another's  government  when  he 
determines  of  full  consent  to  observe  all  that  other's  orders  ;  and  it 
follows  that  the  prince  who  hath  most  dominion  is  he  that  reigns 
over  his  subjects'  minds.  But  if  they  had  most  dominion  who  be 
most  feared,  then  that  eminence  would  manifestly  belong  to  the 
subjects  of  despots,  who  by  their  despots  are  most  greatly  feared.' 

And  though  governments  cannot  control  men's  thoughts 
and  afiections  directly,  they  may  do  it  indirectly.  This  again 
looks  like  a  reflection  on  Hobbes,  who  is  emphatic  on  the 
point  that  governments  can  control  nothing  but  overt  acts. 

We  may  now  understand  Spinoza's  answer  to  his  corre- 
spondent in  Ep.  50 : — 

'  As  concerning  the  politics,  the  difference  betwixt  Hobbes  and 
myself  of  which  you  ask  consists  in  this,  that  I  ever  save  natural 
right  harmless,  and  hold  that  the  sovereign  magistrate  in  any  state 
hath  no  more  right  over  his  subjects  than  is  measured  by  the  excess 
of  his  power  over  the  subject ;  which '  {i.e.  the  identity  of  right  and 
power)  '  always  takes  place  in  the  state  of  nature.' 

It  would  appear  that  altogether  Spinoza  attached  de- 
cidedly less  importance  than  Hobbes  to  the  question  of 
the  origin  of  government.  What  he  regarded  as  the  main 
thing  was  the  fact  of  a  government  existing  and  being  able 
to  maintain  itself.  In  Hobbes'  view  it  is  difficult  to  see  how 
a  government  once  established  can  ever  lose  its  title  :  the 
Leviathan   once  framed  not  only  exists  de  jure,  but  is  knit 

'  Cf.  Hume,  in  the  Essay  on  the  Origin  of  Government.  '  In  all  govern- 
ments there  is  a  i)cipetual  intestine  struggle,  open  or  secret,  between  Authority 
and  Liberty,  and  neither  of  them  can  ever  absolutely  prevail  in  the  contest. ' 


THE   CITIZEN  AND   THE   STATE.  319 

together  by  a  vincuhiin  juris  which  nobody  can  undo.  He 
is  driven  to  admit  in  some  measure  the  principle  of  allegiance 
to  de  facto  governments  :  but  all  he  will  say  is  that,  if  the 
rightful  government  becomes  unable  to  protect  any  of  its 
subjects,  these  subjects  are  remitted  to  their  natural  right  of 
self-preservation,  and  may  give  their  allegiance  to  any  power 
from  which  protection  can  be  had.  His  greatest  aversion 
and  contempt  is  for  the  doctrine  of  mixed  government ;  and 
his  logical  triumph  over  the  fallacy  of  divided  sovereignty  is 
hardly  distinguishable  from  his  practical  dislike  of  all  attempts 
to  shift  the  centre  of  power  or  divide  the  substance  of  it  from 
the  form.  While  Hobbes  expressly  admits  that  an  aristocracy 
or  democracy  may  exist  under  monarchical  appearances,  he 
utterly  refuses  to  consider  whether  there  is  anything  to  be 
said  for  holding  the  constitution  of  England  to  be  of  this 
kind.  The  name  of  monarchy  seems  enough  to  dazzle  his 
judgment  when  he  comes  to  the  specific  case.  Spinoza 
does  not  share  this  temper.  His  theoretical  analysis  does 
not  prevent  him  from  having  regard  to  the  convenience  of 
mankind,  and  he  is  no  more  an  absolutist  than  Bentham.  In 
his  ideal  commonwealths  he  makes  elaborate  provision  for 
checks  and  balances,  which  in  their  spirit  almost  anticipate 
the  constitutional  publicists  of  the  eighteenth  century. 

The  point  on  which  Hobbes  and  Spinoza  are  most 
thoroughly  in  accord  is  the  total  rejection  of  all  claims,  on 
grounds  of  religion  or  otherwise,  to  set  up  a  jurisdiction  equal 
or  superior  to  that  of  the  civil  power.  They  both  denounce 
ecclesiastical  pretensions  at  every  opportunity ;  and,  while 
they  both  admit  that  if  a  private  man  has  a  special  revelation 
he  must  obey  it  even  against  the  State,  they  give  it  to  be 
understood,  in  almost  identical  terms,  that  the  possibility  of  a 
special  revelation  need  not  be  practically  considered.  No 
man  can  have  immediate  assurance  of  its  truth  except  him  to 
whom  it  is  actually  revealed,  and  therefore  no  private  citizen 
is  bound  to  take  notice  of  an)  thing  alleged  for  revealed  truth 


320  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

by  another,  '  who,  being  a  man,  may  err,  and,  which  is  more, 
may  lie.' '  One  who  sets  up  for  a  prophet  is  at  the  very  least 
bound  to  prove  his  office  by  miracles  ;  Hobbes  adds  as  a  no 
less  indispensable  test  of  a  true  prophet  that  he  must  not 
preach  any  religion  but  the  established  one.  Spinoza  sug- 
gests that  even  if  a  real  prophet  appeared  in  a  modern  com- 
monwealth there  would  be  no  strict  obligation  to  receive  him. 
So  that  '  in  a  commonwealth,  a  subject  that  has  no  certain 
and  assured  revelation  particularly  to  himself  concerning  the 
will  of  God  is  to  obey  for  such  the  command  of  the  common- 
wealth.' ^  The  State  is  supreme  over  all  persons  and  in  all 
causes,  ecclesiastical  and  temporal,  except  in  hypothetical 
events  which  cannot  happen. 

We  have  seen  that  Spinoza  first  gives  the  theory  of 
sovereignty  in  unqualified  terms,  and  then  states  in  another 
chapter  the  qualifications  which  he  sees  to  be  needful  in 
applying  it  to  existing  facts.  This  deserves  a  word  of 
special  notice.  The  faculty  of  clearly  grasping  an  abstract 
doctrine,  and  withal  remembering  that  it  is  an  abstraction, 
and  not  a  complete  account  of  the  actual  phenomena,  is 
by  no  means  a  common  one.  In  our  own  day  it  has  been 
reserved  for  Sir  Henry  Maine  ^  to  point  out  with  accuracy  the 
ideal  character  of  the  conception  of  sovereignty  and  positive 
law  developed  by  Hobbes  and  his  followers,  and  thus  to 
furnish  the  means  of  assigning  its  real  philosophical  and  prac- 
tical value.  That  Spinoza  should  have  seriously  attempted 
a  similar  process,  and  to  a  certain  extent  succeeded,  is 
perhaps  not  the  least  of  the  circumstances  that  show  the  in- 
dependence of  his  thought  even  where  there  is  the  strongest 
appearance  of  his  following  others. 

Having  thus  indicated  the  general  nature  of  Spinoza's 
political  theory,  we  may  proceed  to  a  more  detailed  view  of 

'  Leviathan,  ch.  32. 

*  Leiiathan,  ch.  26;  cp.  Spinoza,  Tract.  Polit.  c.  3,  §  10  ;   Tract.  TInol.-Pol. 
C.  16,  §§  61  sqcj.  and  19,  passim. 

'  Lectures  on  Sovereignty  in  The  Early  History  of  Institutions. 


THE  CITIZEN  AND   THE  STATE.  321 

the  '  Tractatus  Politicus.'  In  the  introductory  chapter 
Spinoza  announces  his  intention  of  deahng  with  the  subject 
in  a  purely  scientific  manner.  On  this  point  he  repeats 
in  substance  what  he  had  said  in  the  Preface  to  the  Third 
Part  of  the  Ethics.  One  remarkable  passage  betrays  how 
strangely  he  underrated  the  extent  and  complexity  of  the 
problem. 

'  I  am  firmly  convinced  that  all  the  kinds  of  commonwealths 
which  can  be  devised  for  men's  living  together  in  harmony,  and 
likewise  the  means  whereby  a  multitude  should  be  guided  and  kept 
within  settled  bounds,  have  been  shown  by  experience  ;  so  that  I  do 
not  think  there  is  anything  not  repugnant  to  experience  and  practice 
which  we  can  discover  by  meditation  on  this  topic,  but  hath  before 
now  been  known  and  put  to  trial.  For  such  is  the  temper  of  men 
that  they  cannot  live  except  in  some  common  bond  of  laws ;  and 
the  laws  of  commonwealths  and  affairs  of  state  have  been  founded 
and  considered  by  men  of  the  greatest  wit  (whether  by  policy  or  by 
craft) ;  wherefore  'tis  hardly  credible  that  we  should  be  able  to 
devise  anything  fitted  to  be  of  use  to  society  which  opportunity  or 
accident  hath  never  off'ered,  and  which  men  busied  on  public  affairs 
and  mindful  of  assuring  their  own  interest  have  not  discerned.' 
(c.  I,  §  3)- 

Yet  this  only  seems  strange  to  the  eyes  of  us  who  have 
learnt  by  fairly  trying  scientific  methods  how  complex  the 
world  is.  We  have  already  seen  that  Spinoza's  belief  in  a 
comparatively  short  road  to  certain  and  complete  knowledge 
of  everything  was  the  belief  of  almost  all  the  aspiring  minds 
of  his  time.  Not  only  Descartes  before  him,  but  Leibnitz 
after  him,  sought  and  expected  to  find  universal  methods, 
and  looked  forward  to  the  consummation  of  the  sciences 
within  a  few  generations.  And  here  we  may  be  allowed  to 
put  in  a  word  for  Bacon,  who  has  been  both  praised  and 
blamed  more  inconsiderately  than  almost  any  philosophical 
writer.  Bacon's  belief  in  a  general  art  of  scientific  discovery 
which  would  go  near  to  equalize  men's  intellects  is  now  easilj^ 
seen  to  have  been  erroneous.     But  it  was  not  a  singular  or 

Y 


3l2  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

a  perverse  belief  at  the  time.  If  we  ridicule  Bacon  on  this 
score,  we  must  ridicule  him  for  not  having  known  more  than 
Leibnitz  did  a  century  later.  So  too  in  the  present  case  of 
politics,  Spinoza's  opinion  that  no  experiment  of  importance 
remained  to  be  tried  was  the  opinion  generally  held  by  the 
most  competent  persons  of  his  time.  The  variety  of  constitu- 
tions then  existing  in  the  remaining  Italian  republics,  the  free 
cities  of  the  Empire,  and  the  Swiss  cantons,  appears  to, have 
suggested  that  all  possible  variety  was  exhausted  rather 
than  to  have  stimulated  curiosity.  Certainly  Hobbes  never 
dreamt  of  the  great  experiment  impending  in  England, 
which  has  been  directly  and  indirectly  the  parent  of  so  many 
more. 

Again,  the  writers  of  the  eighteenth  century  treated  the 
English  constitution  as  having  reached  its  final  development ; 
and  they  regarded  a  state  which  Hobbes  would  have  called 
anarchy  as  the  highest  actual  and  theoretical  perfection  of 
government.  Nor  had  they  any  clear  notion  of  the  distinc- 
tion between  the  outlines  of  positive  constitutional  law  and 
the  great  body  of  informal  constitutional  usage  which  clothes 
the  legal  skeleton  with  full  and  various  life.  Hume's  politi- 
cal essays,  though  full  of  brilliant  remarks,  are  still  in  the 
main  unfruitful.  His  '  Idea  of  a  Perfect  Commonwealth  '  is 
not  unlike  the  '  Tractatus  Politicus  '  in  design  and  arrange- 
ment, allowance  being  made  for  the  difference  of  scale,  and  it 
has  about  as  much  or  as  little  practical  value.  In  Montes- 
quieu we  find  the  true  forerunner  of  the  modern  historical 
method.  But  to  pursue  this  here  would  be  to  go  too  far 
astray. 

It  may  be  well  to  translate  the  next  following  paragraph 
of  the  introductory  chapter  of  the  '  Tractatus  Politicus,'  as  it 
contains  a  phrase  (italicized  in  the  translation)  which  is  often 
and  deservedly  quoted  by  modern  writers  on  Spinoza. 

'  In  applying  myself  therefore  to  the  science  of  politics,  I  pre- 
tended nothing  new  or  unknown,  but  only  to  prove  by  certain  and 


THE  CITIZEN  AND   THE  STATE.    '  323 

undoubted  reasons,  or  to  deduce  from  the  constitution  of  man  itself, 
the  propositions  most  agreeable  to  practical  use.  And  in  order  to 
inquire  of  the  matters  of  this  science  with  the  same  freedom  of  mind 
we  are  wont  to  use  in  the  mathematics,  I  have  made  it  my  especial 
care  neither  to  mock,  to  beiaail,  nor  to  denounce  men's  actions,  but  to 
understand  them  :  and  to  this  end  I  have  considered  men's  emotions, 
such  as  love,  hate,  anger,  envy,  honour,  pity,  and  other  agitations  of 
the  mind,  not  as  defects  of  human  nature,  but  as  properties  which 
belong  to  it  in  like  manner  as  to  the  nature  of  air  there  belong  heat, 
cold,  storms,  thunder,  and  the  like  ;  which  though  they  be  incon- 
venient, yet  are  necessary  and  have  constant  causes  whereby  we 
endeavour  to  understand  their  nature,  and  the  mind  rejoices  in  the 
right  contemplation  of  them  no  less  than  in  the  knowledge  of  such 
things  as  are  pleasing  to  the  senses.' 

Political  science  is  to  concern  itself  with  human  nature  not 
as  it  ought  to  be,  but  as  it  is.  It  must  not  be  assumed  that  men 
will  act  in  public  affairs  according  to  the  true  dictates  of  reason 
unless  it  is  made  their  obvious  interest  not  to  do  otherwise. 
For  the  welfare  of  the  State  it  is  all  one  from  what  motive 
men  obey  the  law  and  perform  the  duties  of  their  station,  so 
that  good  government  be  secured.  '  Freedom  and  strength 
of  mind  are  virtues  in  private  men  ;  but  the  virtue  of  govern- 
ments is  safety.'  Spinoza  proceeds  to  consider  the  funda- 
mental principles  of  government,  starting  from  the  facts  of 
average  human  nature  (cap.  2).  We  translate  the  paragraph 
in  which  the  philosophical  grounds  of  his  theory  are  laid  down. 

'  Any  particular  thing  in  nature  may  be  adequately  conceived, 
whether  it  existeth  or  no.  And  as  the  beginning  of  existence  of 
particular  things  in  nature  cannot  be  deduced  from  their  definition, 
so  neither  can  their  continuance  in  existing.  For  the  thing  itself,  as 
it  is  in  our  conception,'  remains  the  same  after  it  has  begun  to  exist 
as  before.  As  therefore  the  beginning  of  their  existence  cannot 
follow  from  their  essence  '  {i.e.  the  knowledge  of  what  a  thing  is 
differs  from  the  knowledge  that  such  a  thing  is),  '  so  neither  doth 
their  continuance  in  existence  :  but  to  go  on  existing  they  need  the 
same  power  which  they  need  for  beginning  to  exist.     Whence  it 

'  Essentia  idcalis  ;  a  tevm  which  docs  nol,  T  ihink,  occur  in  the  Ethics. 

\  1 


324  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

follows  that  the  power  of  all  things  in  nature,  whereby  they  exist, 
and  therefore  whereby  they  have  effects,  can  be  no  other  than  the 
eternal  power  of  God  himself  For  if  it  were  any  other  created 
power,  it  could  not  maintain  itself,  nor  by  consequence  other  things, 
but  would  need  for  its  own  continuing  in  existence  the  same  power 
that  was  needed  to  create  it. 

'  Now  from  this  conclusion,  that  the  power  of  things  in  nature, 
whereby  they  exist  and  work,  is  identically  the  power  of  God,  we 
easily  understand  what  is  natural  law  or  right.  ^  For  since  God  hath 
right  to  everything,  and  the  right  of  God  is  nothing  else  than  the 
power  of  God,  so  far  as  it  is  regarded  as  absolutely  free,  it  follows  that 
everything  in  nature  hath  of  nature  so  much  right  as  it  hath  power  to 
exist  and  work  ;  seeing  the  power  of  each  several  thing  in  nature, 
whereby  it  doth  exist  and  work,  is  no  other  than  the  free  and 
absolute  power  of  God.  Therefore  I  understand  by  the  law  of 
nature  the  statutes  or  rules  of  nature  according  to  which  all  things 
happen,  that  is,  merely  the  power  of  nature.  And  thus  the 
natural  right  of  the  whole  of  nature,  and  by  consequence  of  each 
several  individual,  doth  extend  so  far  forth  as  its  power;  conse- 
quently whatever  every  man  does  by  the  rules  of  his  own  nature, 
that  he  does  by  perfect  natural  right,  and  hath  right  over  nature  so 
far  as  by  his  power  he  prevails.' 

This  statement  of  Spinoza's,  and  the  corresponding 
passages  in  Hobbes,  appear  to  us  at  this  day  far-fetched  if 
not  perverse.  It  is  so  much  easier  to  say  at  once  that  such 
phrases  as  law  of  nature,  natural  right,  have  no  meaning  in 
jurisprudence  and  political  science ;  that  laws  conferring 
rights  can  exist  only  in  a  society  ;  and  that,  so  far  as  we 
can  conceive  man  as  not  a  member  of  society,  we  must  con- 
ceive him  as  not  subject  to  any  law.  But  a  dominant  set  of 
phrases,  however  inappropriate  to  a  particular  writer's  purpose, 
is  not  thrown  aside  without  struggles.  In  Spinoza's  time  the 
Law  of  Nature  was  not  only  still  commonly  spoken  of  and 
appealed  to,  but  the  idea  had  received  an  important  revival 
and  extension  at  the  hands  of  Grotius  and  his  contemporaries. 
To  discard  the   term  would    have   been    simply  impossible. 

'  Spinoza  uses  the  one  term  ins  naturae.     The  double  meaning  cannot  be 
given  by  any  single  word  in  English. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  325 

Both  Hobbes  and  Spinoza  could  only  strive  to  fix  a  new  mean- 
ing of  their  own  upon  it.  It  may  help  us  to  understand  the 
meaning  sought  by  Spinoza  if  we  here  shortly  recapitulate 
the  position  assumed  by  his  philosophy  with  regard  to  the 
fundamental  ideas  of  ethics  and  law. 

The  notions  of  good  and  bad  arise  as  soon  as  we  consider 
an  individual  whose  existence  and  welfare  are  distinguishable 
from  the  existence  of  the  universe  as  a  whole.  For  every 
creature  some  things  are  good  and  others  bad.  But  the 
same  things  need  not  be  good  and  bad  for  different  indivi- 
duals, or  for  the  same  individual  in  different  circumstances. 

When  we  have  a  society  composed  of  individual  men 
capable  of  independent  action,  that  which  is  good  or  bad  for 
the  society  becomes  r-iglit  or  wrong  for  the  individuals  com- 
posing it.  What  is  esteemed  good  or  bad  by  the  society  at 
large,  or  by  the  opinion  prevailing  in  it,  is  prescribed  or  for- 
bidden to  the  individual  members  as  being  right  or  wrong. 
This  is  what  modern  English  writers  have  called  Positive 
Morality. 

When  in  a  particular  society  there  has  been  formed 
an  organized  government  provided  with  definite  means  of 
making  itself  obeyed,  and  that  government  prescribes,  per- 
mits, and  forbids  particular  kinds  of  conduct,  then  conduct 
falling  under  these  rules  acquires  further  special  qualities. 
What  is  prescribed  is  legal  duty  or  just  ;  what  is  allowed  is 
legally  right  ;  what  is  forbidden  is  legally  wrong  or  unjust. 
This  is,  in  modern  language.  Positive  Law. 

Again,  certain  rules  of  conduct  may  be  discovered  by 
reflection  on  the  general  conditions  of  human  nature,  and 
these  rules  are  independent  of  particular  social  systems. 
They  may  be  regarded  either  as  scientific  statements  about 
the  conduct  men  actually  pursue,  in  so  far  as  their  reason  is 
not  disturbed  by  passion,  error,  and  prejudice,  or  as  moral 
precepts  setting  forth  an  ideal  to  which,  as  reasonable  men, 
we  shall  endeavour  to  conform    in  our  way  of  life.      Such 


326  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

propositions  or  precepts  are  given  in  the  fourth  part  of 
Spinoza's  '  Ethics,'  and  answer  in  a  general  way  to  the  rules 
of  conduct  given  by  Hobbes  as  laws  of  nature.'  So  far  as  a 
man  follows  these  precepts,  he  is  said  to  live  according  to 
reason. 

It  is  true  that  Spinoza  does  not  clearly  recognize  the  dis- 
tinction between  Positive  Morality  and  Positive  Law,  or 
rather  omits  to  take  note  of  the  existence  of  Positive 
Morality.  Indeed  the  conception  is  a  modern  one.  But  it 
fits  well  enough  into  Spinoza's  scheme,  and  the  statement 
would  have  been  so  incomplete  without  it  that  I  have  felt 
justified  in  adding  it.  Now  it  will  be  observed  that  in  this 
scheme  right  and  wrong  are  terms  of  civil  or  social  morality, 
not  of  the  natural  morality  which  is  concerned  with  the  self- 
maintenance  of  the  individual.  For  the  individual,  as  such, 
there  is  only  good  and  bad.  Nevertheless  most  things  which 
are  good  or  bad  for  the  individual  are  also  right  or  wrong,  in 
other  words  good  or  bad  for  society.  Hence  most  things 
which  are  first  regarded  as  simply  good  or  bad  come  to 
acquire  a  certain  value  in  the  social  scale  of  rightness  and 
wrongness  ;  and  ethical  associations  derived  from  the  com- 
munity are  at  last  carried  over  to  the  general  notions  of 
goodness  and  badness  themselves.  A  similar  association 
takes  place,  but  to  a  less  extent,  between  the  ethical  and 
legal  notions  of  right  and  wrong.  Hence  the  intellectual 
analysis  is  difficult,  and  is  apt  to  excite  in  the  moral  sense  a 
kind  of  jealousy  bordering  on  repugnance. 

On  the  other  hand  there  are  elements  of  possible  conflict. 
We  have  at  least  two  distinct  sources  of  rules  of  conduct,  or, 
according  to  the  developed  statement  here  presented,  three. 
One  set  of  rules  is  propounded  by  reason  as  good  ;  another  by 
the  community  as  right;  another  by  the  civil  power  as  imv. 

'  Leviathaji,  c.  14.  Hobbes  distinguishes  between  itis  and  lex,  and  defines 
lex  naturalis,  in  effect,  as  a  rule  of  conduct  discovered  by  reason,  and  tending  to 
the  self-preseivalion  of  the  agent. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE   STATE.  327 

Now  it  may  be  that  all  these  rules  coincide,  so  far  as  they 
cover  the  same  ground  ;  but  we  are  not  entitled  to  assume 
that  they  will.     Indeed  there  could  not  be  a  complete  and 
universal  coincidence  unless  all  societies  and  all  governments 
were  guided  by  right  reason  ;  which  is  not  the  case.    Positive 
Law  may  conflict  with  Positive  Morality  ;  both  Positive  Law 
and  Positive  Morality  may  conflict  with  the  dictates  of  reason. 
If  this  happens,  which  are  we  to  follow  }     Spinoza  does  not 
explicitly  discuss  questions  of  this  kind.    All  he  has  to  say  on 
the  matter  is  that  reason  bids  man  to  live  sociably  with  his 
fellow-men,  and  prescribes  obedience  to  the  civil  law  as  being, 
in  general,  the  surest  way  to  that  end.     And  when  reason 
says,  '  obey  the  law,'  we  follow  reason  in  obeying   the  law, 
though  the  particular  law  may  be  one  that  we  disapprove. 
This  general  indication  of  the  relation  of  Ethics  to  Politics  is 
perhaps  as  much  as  can  be  expected   in  a  political  treatise. 
It  is  also  proper  to  observe  that  although  Spinoza  constantly 
implies  that  the  ethical  conceptions  of  right  and  wrong  are 
of  a  quasi-legal   character,  and  are  not  applicable  except  to 
men  living  in  society,  this  is  not  necessary  to  his  political 
theory  as  such.     Having  premised  this   nmch,  we  resume  the 
order  of  the  treatise. 

Every  man  does  what  he  thinks  most  for  his  own  interest  : 
and  whatever  he  actually  does,  whether  reasonably  or 
foolishly,  he  has,  in  Spinoza's  terminology,  a  natural  right  to 
do.  Men  have  conflicting  interests  in  so  far  as  they  are 
subject  to  passion  ;  and  man  is  more  formidable  to  man  than 
any  other  creature.  But  men  are  subject  to  passions  ;  there- 
fore men  left  to  themselves  would  be  in  frequent  conflict,  or 
in  other  words  the  state  of  nature  is  a  state  of  war.  On  the 
other  hand,  a  state  of  life  in  which  every  man  must  fight  for 
his  own  hand  is  too  precarious  to  be  tolerable,  Man  cannot 
exercise  his  faculties  with  any  pleasure  or  convenience  except 
in  society,  where  his  strength  is  multiplied  by  union  :  and  in 
this  sense  it  may  justly  be  said  that   man  is  a  social  animal. 


328  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

When  a  multitude  of  men  live  together  in  society,  each 
individual,  being  powerless  as  against  the  united  will  of  the 
rest,  has  no  more  right  than  the  society  chooses  to  leave  him. 
The  right  which  arises  from  and  is  determined  by  the  power 
of  the  society  over  the  individual  is  called  government  or 
dominion  {iviperium),  and  is  vested  in  the  person  or  persons, 
be  they  many,  few,  or  one,  who  are  appointed  to  the  supreme 
charge  of  public  affairs. 

The  body  of  men  subject  to  one  government  is  a  State.' 
Its  members  are  called  citizens  in  respect  of  their  franchises 
and  privileges,  subjects  in  respect  of  their  duties.  No  citizen 
can  be  free  to  do  whatever  he  pleases ;  for  if  he  were,  he 
would  be  above  the  State.  Neither  can  the  citizens  be  free 
to  interpret  the  laws  of  the  State  as  they  please  ;  for  this 
would  make  every  man  judge  in  his  own  cause,  and  virtually 
independent  of  the  State.  It  is  for  the  State  to  determine 
what  is  just  and  unjust,  and  for  the  citizen  to  obey  the  law  ; 
the  will  of  the  State  must  be  the  will  of  every  citizen.  If  it 
be  said  that  it  is  against  reason  thus  to  give  up  one's  own 
judgment,  the  answer  is  that  reason  exhorts  to  peace  and 
a  secure  life,  which  cannot  be  had  except  in  a  well-ordered 
State.  The  advantage  of  living  under  settled  laws  is  far 
greater  than  any  hardship  which  we  may  feel  in  a  particular 
case  from  having  to  obey  a  law  which  we  think  unreasonable. 
This  leaves  it  quite  open  to  citizens  to  suggest  amendments 
in  existing  laws,  and  endeavour  by  all  peaceable  means  to 
procure  them  ;  which  is  expressly  mentioned  in  the  'Tracta- 
tus  Theologico-Politicus '  as  not  only  allowable  but  com- 
mendable. 

Next  the  limits  to  the  power  of  the  State  are  considered. 
As  the  free  or  reasonable  man  is  the  strongest  among  men, 
so  that  State  is  strongest  whose  institutions  are  most  accord- 
ing to  reason.  For  the  strength  of  the  State  depends  on  the 
union  of  the  citizens  ;  and  union  cannot  be  unless  the  laws  of 

'  Cap.  3. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  329 

the  State  are  directed  to  the  general  good.  Again,  the  sub- 
jection of  the  citizen  to  the  State  consists  either  in  fear  of  the 
power  of  the  State  or  in  love  of  civil  society  and  order. 
Therefore  the  State  has  no  jurisdiction  over  things  to  which 
men  cannot  be  induced  by  reward  or  compelled  by  punish- 
ment. No  man  can  abandon,  for  example,  his  own  power  of 
judgment.  Nobody  can  be  compelled  to  believe  that  the 
whole  is  not  greater  than  its  part ;  that  God  does  not  exist ; 
that  a  finite  body  before  his  eyes  is  infinite,  and  the  like. 
Further,  there  are  matters  so  repugnant  to  human  nature  in 
other  ways  that  no  power  can  compel  obedience  in  them ;  as, 
to  produce  evidence  against  oneself,  to  kill  one's  parents,  not 
to  attempt  saving  one's  life,  and  the  like.  *  If  we  say  not- 
withstanding that  the  commonwealth  hath  right  or  power  to 
command  such  things,  we  can  no  otherwise  conceive  this  than 
as  one  might  say  that  a  man  has  a  right  to  be  mad.  For 
what  else  than  madness  would  be  a  rule  of  law  to  which  no 
man  can  be  bound  .•* '  In  applying  this  test,  however,  we 
must  consider  the  ordinary  temper  of  men.  There  may 
always  be  some  perverse  or  insane  persons  inaccessible  to  the 
motives  upon  which  most  men  in  most  circumstances  obey 
the  law.  But  this  does  not  prevent  the  law  from  being  in 
general  efficacious.  As  for  the  particular  individual  who  sets 
himself  against  the  State,  as  one  having  nothing  to  hope  or 
fear  from  it,  Spinoza  says  (in  this  point  agreeing  with  Hobbes) 
that  he  may  be  considered  as  an  enemy.  Again,  the  power 
of  the  State  is  limited  by  public  opinion  ;  '  such  matters  are 
not  within  the  right  of  the  State  as  excite  a  general  opposi- 
tion.' For  if  a  government  issues  commands  which  provoke 
many  citizens  to  resistance,  it  thereby  deprives  itself  at  once 
of  a  certain  measure  of  its  power. 

As  for  the  rights  of  independent  States  against  one 
another,  they  are  the  same  as  those  of  individuals  in  the 
imaginary  state  of  nature.  Peace  between  States  corresponds 
to  society  between  individuals  in  so  far  that  it  rests  upon  con- 


330  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND   PHILOSOPHY. 

sent.  The  obligation  of  treaties  lasts  as  long  as  the  reasons 
for  which  they  were  made,  and  no  longer :  a  proposition 
which  may  be  unacceptable  to  some  theorists,  but  which  has 
been  abundantly  verified  in  the  history  of  Europe,  and  not 
less  since  Spinoza's  time  than  before  it.  Indeed  it  seems 
impossible,  on  any  political  or  ethical  principles  whatever,  to 
lay  it  down  as  an  absolute  proposition  that  the  obligation  of 
treaties  is  perpetual.  Whence  can  governments  derive  the 
right  of  binding  their  subjects  and  successors  for  all  time  by 
improvident  undertakings  .'' 

It  follows  from  the  view  already  given  of  the  functions  of 
a  commonwealth  that  the  sovereign  authority  alone  has  the 
direction  of  public  affairs,  and  that  for  any  one  to  meddle 
with  them  unauthorized  is  a  usurpation  of  government.'  If 
it  be  asked  whether  the  sovereign  power  in  a  commonwealth 
is  bound  by  law,  and  capable  of  doing  wrong,  the  answer  is 
that  civilly  it  is  not  so,  but  naturally  it  is.  '  For  if  a  common- 
wealth were  bound  by  no  law  or  rule,  without  which  it  would 
not  be  a  commonwealth,  then  we  should  have  to  regard  a 
commonwealth  not  as  a  thing  existing  in  nature  but  as  a 
chimaera.  Thus  a  commonwealth  does  wrong  when  by  action 
or  sufferance  it  brings  in  causes  of  its  own  destruction.' 
Power  is  always  limited  by  the  capacities  of  the  thing  acted 
upon  as  well  as  the  faculties  of  the  agent.  '  If  I  say,  for 
instance,  that  I  may  of  right  do  as  I  will  with  this  table,  I 
suppose  not  thereby  that  I  have  a  right  to  make  the  table  eat 
grass.'  So  the  commonwealth  cannot  compel  its  citizens, 
being  men,  to  a  kind  or  extent  of  submission  contrary  to 
human  nature.  '  Therefore  that  the  commonwealth  may 
maintain  its  right,  it  is  bound  to  maintain  the  motives  of  fear 
and  respect  ;  otherwise  it  ceases  to  be  a  commonwealth.' 
Nevertheless  fundamental  changes  can  be  regularly  effected 
only  by  the  sovereign   authority  itself     Revolutions  may  in 

'  Cap.  4. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  331 

extreme  cases  be  necessary,  but  they  are  extra-legal  and  in 
the  nature  of  acts  of  war. 

Spinoza  then  considers  what  is  the  best  condition  or  ideal, 
as  we  should  now  say,  of  a  government,'  without  regard  to  its 
particular  form.  This  is  a  question  of  fact,  not  of  right ;  it  is 
one  thing  to  govern  by  law,  another  to  govern  well.  The 
object  of  a  commonwealth  is  peace  and  protection  ;  the 
excellence  of  a  commonwealth  consists  therefore  in  men's 
living  in  amity  and  observing  the  law.  For  since  men  are  by 
nature  much  the  same  everywhere,  habitual  discord  and  law- 
breaking  are  more  the  fault  of  institutions  than  of  the  particu- 
lar offenders.  And  the  peace  here  meant  is  a  cheerful  and 
rational  acquiescence  in  the  law,  not  a  submission  compelled 
by  force. 

*  A  commonwealth  whose  subjects  rise  not  in  arms  because  they 
are  overcome  by  terror  is  rather  to  be  spoken  of  as  being  without 
war  than  as  enjoying  peace.  For  peace  is  not  mere  absence  of  war, 
but  an  excellence  proceeding  from  highmindedness  ;  since  obedience 
is  the  constant  will  to  perform  that  which  by  the  common  ordinance 
of  the  State  ought  to  be  done.  Moreover  a  commonwealth  whose 
peace  depends  on  the  dulness  of  its  subjects,  and  on  their  being 
driven  like  cattle,  to  learn  nothing  but  slavery,  is  more  fitly  called  a 
wilderness  than  a  commonwealth.'^  \\hen  therefore  we  say  that  the 
government  is  best  under  which  men  lead  a  peaceable  life,  I  mean 
that  life  of  man  which  consisteth  not  only  in  the  circulation  of  the 
blood  and  other  properties  common  to  all  animals,  but  whose  chief 
part  is  reason  and  the  true  life  and  excellence  of  the  mind.' 

In  the  same  spirit  he  says  again  in  the  following  chapter : 

'  If  slavery,  rudeness,  and  desolation  are  to  be  called  peace,  then 
is  peace  the  most  wretched  state  of  mankind.  Truly  there  are  more 
and  sharper  disputes  between  parents  and  children  than  between 
masters  and  slaves  ;  and  yet  it  were  no  good  housekeeping  to  make 
the  father  into  a  master,  and  hold  the  children  for  slaves.  It  makes 
for  slavery,  not  for  peace,  to  confer  unlimited  power  on  one  man.' 

'  Cap.  5,  De  optimo  imperii  statu. 

-  '  Rectius  solitndo  qiiam  civitas  dici  potest  : '  with  obvioiif;  allusion  to  the  well- 
known  '  solitudinem  faciunt,  pacem  appellant.' 


332  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Reference  is  made  to  Machiavelli  in  terms  of  great  re- 
spect, and  Spinoza  conjectures  that  his  real  purpose  in  elabo- 
rately showing  '  what  means  a  prince  who  has  no  other  motive 
than  the  lust  of  power  should  use  to  strengthen  his  govern- 
ment '  may  have  been  to  point  out  the  futility  of  removing  a 
despot  when  the  causes  are  left  untouched  which  impel  the 
ruler,  whoever  he  may  be,  to  reign  despotically  ;  and  perhaps 
also  to  warn  free  communities  against  putting  themselves  in 
the  power  of  any  one  man.  The  true  intention  of  Machia- 
velli's  treatise  has  been  a  standing  puzzle  to  modern  critics, 
and  Spinoza's  guess  is  perhaps  as  good  as  any  other. 

Before  we  leave  the  general  part  of  the  treatise,  we  may 
observe  that  if  there  be  anything  illiberal  or  tending  to  an 
apology  for  despotism  in  Spinoza's  marked  dislike  to  violent 
changes  in  affairs  of  State,  the  fault  is  shared  by  him  with  one 
of  the  most  thoughtful  of  English  Liberal  statesmen  of  recent 
times.  At  the  end  of  his  '  Dialogue  on  the  best  form  of  govern- 
ment' Sir  George  Cornewall  Lewis  puts  the  following  sentiment 
in  the  mouth  of  Crito,  an  impartial  bystander  whose  opinions 
may  fairly  be  taken  as  corresponding  with  those  of  the  author 
himself 

'  Looking  back  upon  the  course  of  revolutionary  movements  and 
upon  the  character  of  their  consequences,  the  practical  conclusion 
which  I  draw  is  that  it  is  the  part  of  wisdom  and  prudence  to 
acquiesce  in  any  form  of  government  which  is  tolerably  well  adminis- 
tered and  affords  tolerable  security  to  person  and  property.' 

And  we  may  add  that,  as  matter  of  fact,  the  most  success- 
ful revolutions  have  been  either  re-assertions  of  ancient  rights 
(as  in  England  in  1688),  or  not  merely  domestic  revolutions, 
but  risings  against  a  dominion  which  was  actually  or  virtually 
foreign  ;  as  in  the  struggle  for  the  independence  of  the  Nether- 
lands, and  the  liberation  of  Italy  in  i860.  Cases  of  this  kind 
are  not  considered  by  Spinoza,  and,  though  not  uncommon  in 
history,  scarcely  belong  to  the  theory  of  municipal  politics. 

In  the  remainder  of  the  '  Tractatus  Politicus,'  as  far  as  it 


THE   CITIZEN  AND   THE   STATE.  '333 

goes,'  the  ideal  institutions  appropriate  for  the  different  forms 
of  government  are  sketched  out  and  justified.     It  is  not  worth 
while  to  follow  Spinoza  minutely  through  this  part  of  his 
work  ;  wc  may  be  content  with  fixing  our  attention  on  a  few 
salient  points.     Under  the  head  of  Monarchy  it  is  repeated 
with  some  emphasis  (and  it  would  seem  with  implied  criticism  of 
Hobbes)  that  no  one  man  can  really  be  sovereign.    A  monarch 
must  in  practice  be  guided  by  counsellors,  and  thus  a  nomin- 
ally absolute  monarchy  is  a  covert  and  therefore  bad  form  of 
aristocracy.     Accordingly  Spinoza's  ideal  monarchy  is  limited 
in  various  ways.     There  is  a  great  council  roughly  corres- 
ponding to  the  Parliament  of  a  modern  constitutional  system  : 
it  is  however  not  elective,  but  appointed  by  the  Crown,  sub- 
ject to  fixed  conditions  as  to  age  and  otherwise.     The  Crown 
must  take  the  advice  of  this  assembly,  but  is  free  to  act  upon 
any  opinion    supported    by  a  certain  number  of  votes.     A 
smaller  standing  Council  is  to  take  charge  of  executive  busi- 
ness and  the  routine  of  administration.     The  army  is  to  con- 
sist only  of  citizens,  and  to  receive  pay  only  in  time  of  war  ; 
and  military  commands  are  to  be  annual.     Although  this  is 
to  modern  eyes  one  of  the  most  unpractical  points  in  Spinoza's 
scheme,  it  probably  did  not  seem  so  at  the  time.     Not  only 
then,  but  throughout  the  eighteenth  century,  a  standing  army 
was  the  bugbear  of  constitutional  theorists  :  and  to  this  day 
the  forms  of  the  English  constitution  treat  it  as  a  temporary 
necessity  rather  than  a  constant  part  of  the  appliances  of  an 
independent  State.     As  to  ecclesiastical  affairs,  no  particular 
religion  is  to  be  established  by  law,  but  the  king  may  have  a 
private  chapel. 

Next  comes  the  ideal  aristocratic  constitution,  which  is 
not  unlike  the  monarchical  in  its  general  features ;  the  pre- 
cautions and  checks  being  however  more  elaborate.  Aristo- 
cracy is  defined  as  the  government  in  which  the  sovereign 
power  belongs  to  a  select  number  of  the  citizens  who  thcm- 

'  Capp.  6-1 1  :  cap.  11  is  unfinished. 


334  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

selves  fix  the  terms  of  admission  to  the  governing  body.  The 
number  may  be  either  small  or  large :  indeed  according  to 
Spinoza's  definitions  the  governing  body  might  bear  a  larger 
proportion  to  the  whole  adult  population  in  some  aristocracies 
than  in  some  democracies.  There  must  be  an  established 
religion,  for  the  sake  of  unity  among  the  governing  body,  but 
of  the  simplest  possible  kind  as  to  doctrine.  Others  are  to 
be  tolerated,  but  may  not  compete  with  the  established  one 
in  public  display.  A  conjecture  is  made  as  to  the  historical 
origin  of  aristocracies  (c.  8,  §  12)  which  comes  remarkably 
near  what  is  now  known  or  presumed  to  be  the  truth  from  the 
results  of  later  researches.  We  have  originally  a  homogeneous 
community  of  free  men  founding,  let  us  suppose,  a  new  city. 
As  between  themselves  they  are  equal,  and  willingly  recognize 
their  equality.  But  strangers  will  gather  round  the  original 
stock,  attracted  by  various  motives  :  and  to  these  strangers 
equal  rights  will  not  be  allowed,  nor  indeed  will  they  seek 
them  in  the  first  instance.  In  course  of  time  the  new  comers 
increase,  and  become  assimilated  to  the  original  stock  of  the 
founders  in  everything  but  civil  status  and  rights  :  till  at  last 
the  difference  between  them  appears  conventional,  and  the 
community  of  free  men  with  its  outskirt  of  dependents  has 
become  a  people  governed  by  a  favoured  class.  A  few  words 
are  given  by  Spinoza  to  the  subject  of  public  instruction  ; 
with  a  promise,  unhappily  not  fulfilled,  of  resuming  it  in  a 
future  chapter.  He  expresses  a  decided  opinion  against 
official  endowments,  holding  that  State  universities  '  are  estab- 
lished not  for  the  cultivation  but  for  the  repression  of  under- 
standing '  and  that  every  citizen  should  be  free  to  teach  in 
public  at  his  own  charges  and  his  own  risk. 

The  polity  for  which  an  aristocratic  government  is  best 
adapted  is  that  which  consists  of  several  confederated  cities  of 
approximately  equal  power  (c.  9)  ;  and  further  rules  are  given 
for  this  special  case.  One  of  them,  namely,  that  the  perma- 
nent seat  of  the  federal  government  must  not  be  in  any  one 


THE   CITIZEN  AND    THE  STATE.  335 

of  the  united  commonwealths,  is  in  effect  identical  with  the 
precaution  observed  by  the  founders  of  the  United  States  in 
providing  a  seat  of  government  exempt  from  the  jurisdiction 
of  any  particular  State,  and  subject  to  the  exclusive  authority 
of  Congress. 

The  general  aim  of  all  institutions,  as  well  those  expressly 
recommended  as  others  '  which  may  be  devised  in  each  several 
government  agreeably  to  the  nature  of  the  country  and  the 
temper  of  the  inhabitants,'  should  be  to  lead  men  to  obedience 
rather  than  compel  them. 

*  A  government  which  aims  at  nothing  else  than  to  guide  men  by 
fear  will  be  rather  free  from  defects  than  possessed  of  merit.  Men 
are  to  be  so  guided  as  that  they  may  deem  themselves  not  to  be 
guided,  but  to  live  after  their  own  mind  and  of  their  own  free 
resolve  ;  and  that  they  be  kept  to  allegiance  by  love  of  freedom,  care 
for  increasing  their  substance,  and  the  hope  of  attaining  honourable 
places  in  the  government.  But  for  statues,  triumphs  and  other  such 
whets  to  valour,  they  be  tokens  rather  of  slavery  than  of  freedom. 
Rewards  are  ordained  for  the  valour  of  servants,  not  of  free  men. 
I  do  confess  that  by  spurs  of  this  kind  men  are  extremely  quickened ; 
but  such  things,  which  at  first  are  awarded  to  notable  men,  yet 
afterwards,  as  envy  increaseth,  are  given  to  worthless  fellows  that  are 
puffed  up  with  wealth,  whereby  all  honest  people  are  in  great  indig- 
nation. Likewise  those  who  can  make  a  show  of  their  ancestors' 
triumphs  and  statues  think  themselves  to  be  wronged  if  they  have 
not  precedence  over  others.  And  lastly,  to  say  no  more,  'tis  certain 
that  equality  (which  once  being  cast  off,  the  liberty  of  a  society  must 
needs  perish)  can  by  no  means  be  preserved  when  especial  honours 
'  are  awarded  as  of  common  right  to  any  one  inan  of  illustrious 
excellence.' 

Passages  like  this  arc  interesting  as  showing  how  very 
modern  a  good  deal  of  our  political  experience  is.  Spinoza 
does  not  seem  to  contemplate  the  possibility  of  a  social  aris- 
tocracy being  combined  with  a  system  of  equality  before  the 
law,  and  coinciding  only  in  part  with  political  eminence  :  nor 
does  it  occur  to  him  that  evils  which  now  appear  to  us  obvious 
cnoun-h  arc  likely  to  result  from   concentrating  human  ambi- 


336  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

tion  and  vanity  on  the  one  object  of  official  power  and  dis- 
tinction. 

Having  explained  his  federal  aristocracy,  Spinoza  declares 
with  some  confidence  that  a  State  framed  on  this  model 
would  be  as  stable  as  it  is  possible  for  a  government  to  be, 
and  could  be  dissolved  only  by  some  overwhelming  external 
violence.  He  then  passes  on  to  democracy  (c.  ii).  The  de- 
finition of  democracy  is  peculiar;  the  criterion  of  a  democratic 
government,  as  understood  by  Spinoza,  being  a  franchise 
fixed  by  law.  By  franchise  we  do  not  mean  a  representative 
franchise  in  the  modern  sense  (for  of  representative  govern- 
ment Spinoza  seems  to  have  no  notion)  but  simply  the  right 
to  take  part,  in  some  way  or  other,  in  the  government  of  the 
country,  which  however  would  include  the  voting  power  of 
modern  constitutions.  Thus  there  may  be  a  qualification  by 
age,  by  primogeniture,  or  by  payment  of  taxes  to  a  certain 
amount,  and  it  matters  not  whether  the  actual  governing  body 
thus  constituted  be  large  or  small  in  proportion  to  the  whole 
number  of  inhabitants.  Even  though  the  qualified  citizens  be 
fewer  than  the  sovereign  council  might  be  in  an  aristocratic 
commonwealth  of  the  same  size,  the  government  is  still  to  be 
classed  as  democratic,  '  because  the  citizens  appointed  to  rule 
the  commonwealth  are  not  thereto  chosen  by  a  sovereign 
council  as  the  fittest,  but  are  appointed  merely  by  the  law.' 
This  definition  includes,  it  is  obvious,  the  most  widely  difi"erent 
political  systems.  To  begin  with,  every  form  of  representative 
government  is  a  democracy  in  Spinoza's  sense  ;  the  French 
monarchy  under  Louis  Philippe,  with  its  restricted  pays  legal, 
no  less  than  England  since  the  Reform  Act  of  i  ^Gj,  or  the 
French  Republic  since  1871  with  universal  suffrage.  But 
Spinoza  announces  it  as  his  intention  to  treat  only  of  one 
form  of  democracy,  that  namely  '  in  which  all  men  indiffer- 
ently who  owe  undivided  allegiance  to  the  State,  are  in  other 
respects  of  legal  capacity,  and  are  of  good  conversation,  are 
entitled  to  vote  in  the  sovereign  assembly  and  to  undertake 


THE  CITIZEN  AND  THE  STATE.  337 

the  offices  of  ^  government'  This  is  intended  to  exclude,  as 
Spinoza  explains,  aliens,  women,  infants,  serfs,  and  criminals. 
On  the  point  of  excluding  women  from  political  power  he 
gives  reasons  in  a  separate  paragraph,  the  last  of  the  unfinished 
chapter.  He  puts  it  simply  on  the  ground  that  men  are  the 
stronger ;  not  merely  with  their  physical  strength  as  indi- 
viduals, but  intellectually  and  in  social  combination. 

*If  women  were  by  nature  the  equals  of  men,  and  equally 
endowed  with  firmness  of  mind  and  intellect,  wherein  chiefly  consists 
human  power,  and  consequently  right,  then  surely  among  so  many 
and  various  nations  there  should  be  found  some  where  both  sexes 
ruled  equally,  and  others  where  men  were  ruled  by  women  and  so 
brought  up  as  to  be  inferior  to  them  in  intellect.' 

(This  anticipates  the  topic  much  insisted  on  by  some  re- 
cent advocates,  that  the  general  inferiority  of  women  to  men 
is  entirely  the  result  of  education.) 

'  And  seeing  this  hath  nowhere  come  to  pass,  we  may  clearly 
affirm  that  women  have  not  by  nature  an  equal  right  with  men,  but 
must  needs  give  place  to  them  ;  and  hence  that  it  is  not  possible  the 
two  sexes  should  bear  rule  equally,  much  less  that  men  should  be 
ruled  by  women.' 

Further,  a  little  consideration  of  human  passions  and 
jealousies  will  show  that  'equal  rule  of  men  and  women  can- 
not have  place  without  great  prejudice  to  peace.'  It  is  open  to 
supporters  of  female  suffrage  either  to  disregard  Spinoza's  ob- 
jections as  frivolous,  and  dismiss  him,  like  other  opponents,  as 
a  narrow-minded  person,  or  to  distinguish  him  on  the  ground 
that  he  was  considering  the  question,  not  of  a  vote  for  repre- 
sentatives, but  of  a  direct  and  active  participation  in  public 
affairs.  It  is  more  to  our  present  purpose  to  remark  that  the 
objections,  whatever  may  be  thought  of  their  merits,  are  not 
at  all  of  the  kind  we  should  expect  from  a  man  answering  to 
the  popular  notion  of  Spinoza.  They  are  far  from  being  ap- 
propriate to  a  man  who  sits  in  a  garret  and  spins  metaphysical 
Cobwebs.     Indeed,  with  the  exception  of  a  reference  to  the 

z 


JJ 


8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


fable  of  the  Amazons  in  the  pedantic  manner  of  the  time 
(which  I  have  thought  it  needless  to  translate),  they  are  such 
as  might  well  be  used  at  this  day  in  the  House  of  Commons. 
Here  the  treatise  comes  to  an  untimely  end.  It  is  not 
probable  that  Spinoza's  account  of  an  ideal  democratic  State 
would  have  contributed  much  to  the  science  of  politics,  but 
we  may  still  regret  not  having  it.  Some  light  might  have 
been  thrown  on  the  question,  at  present  obscure,  what  was  the 
extent  of  Spinoza's  familiarity  with  the  public  affairs  of  his 
own  country.  In  dealing  with  a  subject-matter  more  apt  to 
be  illustrated  by  domestic  examples  and,  it  would  seem,  more 
after  his  own  heart  than  the  discussion  of  monarchical  and 
aristocratical  institutions,  he  would  have  had  a  better  occasion 
of  showing  his  knowledge  and  opinions  on  matters  of  present 
interest.  That  he  did  not  neglect  the  political  writings  of  the 
time  we  know  from  a  reference  in  the  discussion  of  aristocracv 
(c.  8,  §31)  to  an  author  mentioned  by  Spinoza  as  '  prudentissi- 
musBelgaV.H.'  This  V.H.isPieter  de  laCourti(i6i8-i685), 
an  eminent  publicist  who  wrote  under  the  initials  D.C.  (De  la 
Court)  V.H.  (Van  den  Hove,  the  Dutch  equivalent).  He  was 
a  friend  of  John  de  Witt,  and  opposed  to  the  party  of  the 
Stadtholders.  The  terms  in  which  Spinoza,  who  is  not  lavish 
of  praise,  refers  to  De  la  Court  are  not  without  significance  as 
to  his  own  political  sympathies.  If,  as  divers  excellent  persons 
have  maintained,  Spinozism  is  in  politics  a  doctrine  of  abso- 
lutism, we  are  diiven  to  conclude  that  Spinoza  did  not  under- 
stand his  own  philosophy,  and  in  fact  that  he  was  the  first  anti- 
Spinozist.  But  the  reader  will  now  be  in  a  position  to  judge 
this  question  even  without  referring  to  Spinoza's  text.  It 
sufficiently  appears,  I  venture  to  think,  not  only  that  Spinoza 
was  a  firm  and  consistent  supporter  of  political  liberty,  but 
that  he  w^as  disposed  to  go  much  farther  in  letting  individual 
thought,   habits,  and   enterprise  alone  than    the  majority  of 

'  I   owe  this  identification  (so  far  as  I  know  hitherto  unpublished)  to  Dr. 
Campbell. 


THE   CITIZEN  AND   THE   STATE.  339 

statesmen  of  his  own  time.  His  condemnation  of  sumptuary- 
laws  must  have  appeared  rash,  his  mistrust  of  State  endow- 
ments pedantic  if  not  suspicious,  and  his  notions  of  religious 
toleration  wildly  extravagant.  Even  his  contention  that  in 
a  monarchical  State  the  monarch  should  be  subject  to  the 
law  was  likelv  to  be  received  with  doubtful  favour  in  some 
quarters.  For  various  reasons  his  work  has  been  eclipsed  by 
that  of  Hobbes  ;  and  in  the  actual  history  of  the  theory  of 
politics  it  can  hold  only  a  rank  subordinate  to  the  'Leviathan.' 
But  the  judgment  of  history  is  not  always  the  judgment  of 
pliilosophy.  Hobbes'  power  of  reasoning  and  mastery  of 
English  command  and  deserve  an  admiration  which  it  would 
be  difficult  to  exaggerate.  But  Spinoza's  doctrine  rests  on  a 
wider  and  more  generous  view  of  human  life  ;  it  is  less  en- 
cumbered with  fictions  ;  it  aims  at  a  higher  mark.  It  is  the 
work,  not  of  a  powerful  mind  which  has  espoused  the  cause 
of  a  party  and  makes  philosophy  a  partisan,  but  of  a  philo- 
sopher who  is  proud  of  being  a  free  citizen. 


z  a 


340  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 


CHAPTER  XI. 

SPINOZA   AND    THEOLOGY. 

One  knocked  at  the  Beloved's  door  ;  and  a  voice  asked  from  within,  '  Who  is 
there?'  and  he  answered,  'It  is  I,'  Then  the  voice  said,  'This  house  will  not 
hold  me  and  thee.'  And  the  door  was  not  opened.  Then  went  the  Lover  into 
the  desert,  and  fasted  and  prayed  in  solitude.  And  after  a  year  he  returned  and 
knocked  again  at  the  door.  And  again  the  voice  asked,  '  Who  is  there  ?  '  and  he 
said,  '  It  is  Thyself !  '  and  the  door  was  opened  to  him. 

E.  Fitzgerald,  from  Jelaladdin. 

Rends-toi  compte  de  Dieu.  Comprendre,  c'est  aimer. — Victor  Hugo  :  Les 
Contemplations,  livre  3me,  no.  8, 

In  various  parts  of  Spinoza's  work  there  are  incidental  dis- 
cussions of  prevailing  theological  conceptions,  not  so  much  by 
way  of  direct  attack  as  for  the  purpose  of  explaining  Spinoza's 
own  different  point  of  view.     We  have  hitherto  not  noticed 
these  passages.    Their  interest  is  perhaps  more  historical  than 
philosophical,  and  moreover   the   consideration  of  Spinoza's 
metaphysical  theory  gave  us  quits  enough  to  do  without  at- 
tending at  the   time  to   his    controversial    digressions.     But 
Spinoza's  bearing  towards  the  current  theology  of  his  time  is 
an  element  of  some  importance  in  our  knowledge  of  the  man, 
and  his  position  as  regards  religion  in  a  wider  sense  excites 
questions  which,  even  if  it  be  impossible  to  answer  them  to  our 
satisfaction,  it  is  impossible  to  leave  untouched.    It  has  already 
been  pointed  out  that   Spinoza  nowhere  professes  to  attack 
theology  in  general,  but  only  to  refute  the  erroneous  philoso- 
phical doctrines  attached  to  theology  by  particular  Churches 
and  theologians.     He  leaves  no  room,  however,  for  a  technical 
system  of  theology  standing  side  by  side  with  philosophy, 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  341 

whether  as  claiming  to  control  it  or  merely  to  belong  to  a 
distinct  and  independent  sphere  of  thought.  Natural  religion 
is  identical  with  philosophy,  and  the  power  of  revealed  religion 
consists  not  in  adding  new  philosophical  truth,  or  systematic 
truth  of  any  kind,  to  that  which  reason  can  discover,  but  in 
showing  men  a  way  of  salvation  independent  of  philosophy. 
So  far  as  theology  is  distinct  from  philosophy  it  is  not  a  body 
of  doctrine  but  a  rule  of  life.  Obedience  is  within  every 
man's  power,  but  not  wisdom.  This  is  the  burden  of  the 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  and  the  severance  of  faith 
from  philosophy  there  spoken  of  does  not  mean  that  what  is 
disbelieved  as  matter  of  reason  may  be  believed  as  matter  of 
faith,  but  that  when  the  distinct  objects  of  the  two  are  rightly 
understood  no  collision  is  possible.  The  whole  scope  of 
revelation  is  practical,  and  the  claims  of  revealed  religion  to 
be  accepted  by  mankind  rest  not  on  demonstrative  but  on 
moral  certainty.  We  further  collect  that,  apart  from  specu- 
lative questions  as  to  the  actual  truth  of  particular  doctrines, 
it  was  in  Spinoza's  view  a  practical  necessity  that  the  great 
majority  of  mankind  should  have  a  dogmatic  religion  of  some 
sort,  but  that  he  also  thought  it  possible  and  desirable  that 
the  fundamental  dogmas  should  be  very  few  and  simple.^ 
Similar  assumptions  are  made  in  the  treatise  on  Politics,  as 
we  saw  in  the  last  chapter. 

Now  we  cannot  expect  to  learn  the  whole  mind  of  Spinoza 
from  the  writings  in  which  these  statements  occur.  In  the 
*  Tractatus  Politicus '  he  professes  to  take  men  as  he  finds 
them  ;  in  the  '  Theologico-Politicus  '  he  is  to  a  great  extent 
conducting  a  hypothetical  argument  on  premisses  which  he 
is  content  to  assume  by  way  of  concession.  He  is  addressing 
himself  as  a  citizen  to  citizens  and  statesmen,  not  as  a  philo- 
sopher to  philosophers.  On  the  other  hand  we  cannot  assume 
that  the  position  taken  by  him  for  this  purpose  is  to  be  set 
aside  as  merely  occasional  and   hypothetical.     The   philoso- 

»   Trad.  Thcol.-PoU  cc.  13-15. 


342  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

phical  criticism  of  the  '  Ethics '  does  not  justify  us  in  disre- 
garding it :  for,  as  Spinoza  himself  would  have  been  the  first 
to  point  out,  the  subject-matter  of  the  two  arguments  is  not 
the  same.  The  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus '  affirms  that 
a  plain  man  who  does  not  enter  upon  philosophy  may  without 
harm,  or  even  with  profit,  believe  whatev^er  he  finds  most 
edifying,  provided  that  he  believes  it  sincerely  and  allows  the 
like  freedom  to  others.  But  it  is  clear  enough  that  the  author 
himself  does  not  accept  popular  theology  or  the  popular 
interpretation  of  Scripture  ;  and  the  discussion  of  current 
theological  philosophy  in  the  '  Ethics '  is  only  the  develop- 
ment of  what  is  already  suggested  in  the  earlier  work.  Then 
we  have  a  curious  correspondence  with  Oldenburg  on  special 
points,  belonging  to  the  last  year  or  two  of  Spinoza's  life. 
Here,  again,  one  cannot  tell  exactly  how  much  allowance  is 
to  be  made  for  Spinoza's  desire  to  accommodate  his  expres- 
sions of  unwelcome  opinions  to  his  friend's  habits  of  thought 
and  language. 

There  are  two  distinct  things  to  be  considered.  The 
general  discussion  of  propositions  in  theology,  or  in  mixed 
theology  and  metaphysics,  has  a  speculative  value  indepen- 
dent of  the  conclusions  we  may  form  about  Spinoza's  exact 
personal  relations  to  historical  theology.  But  the  place 
which  religion  and  the  religious  sentiment  held  in  Spinoza's 
individual  life  cannot  be  estimated  without  some  endeavour 
to  ascertain  those  relations,  however  difficult  it  may  be.  It 
will  be  best  to  take  first  that  branch  of  the  subject  where  we 
are  on  firmer  ground,  and  the  matter  is  of  wider  interest. 
,  We  turn  back,  then,  to  the  First  Part  of  the  '  Ethics.' 

Spinoza  maintains,  as  we  have  seen,  the  doctrine  of  a"? 
universal  necessity  which  is  identical  with  freedom  when  we 
consider  the  universe  as  a  whole.  And  he  says  {Pr.  17)  that 
'  God  acts  merely  by  the  laws  of  his  own  nature  and  without 
constraint  ; '  and  in  this  sense  God  alone  can  rightly  be  called 
a  free  cause.     In   other  words,  the  order  of  the  universe  as  a 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  343 

whole    is    self-contained    and   self-determined.      Discussion 

follows  in  a  Scholium. 

'  Others  hold  that  God  is  a  free  cause,  forasmuch  as  (in  their 
opinion)  he  can  bring  it  to  pass  that  the  things  which,  as  we  have 
said,  follow  from  his  nature  or  are  in  his  power,  do  not  happen  or 
be  not  produced  by  him.     But  this  is  as  if  they  should  say  that  God 
could  make  it  not  to  follow  from  the  nature  of  a  triangle  that  its 
three  angles  should  be  equal  to  two  right  angles  ;  or  that  from  a 
given  cause  its  effect  should  not  follow,  which  is  absurd.     Also  I 
shall  prove  below,  without  the  help  of  this  proposition,  that  neither 
understanding  nor  will  belong  to  the  nature  of  God.     I  know  there 
are  many  who  think  they  can  prove  that  free-will  and  the  height  of 
understanding  belong  to  the  nature  of  God  ;  since,  as  they  say,  they 
know  no  greater  perfection  which  they  can  attribute  to  God  than 
that  which  is  the  highest  perfection  in  ourselves.     Again,  though 
they  conceive  God  as  having  in  act  the  perfection  of  understanding,  yet 
they  believe  not  that  he  can  make  all  those  things  to  exist  which 
he  doth  in  act  understand  ;  for  thus  they  conceive  the  power  of  God 
would  be  taken  away.     If,  they  say,  he  had  created  all  things  that 
were  in  his  understanding,  then  he  could  have  created  nothing  more, 
which  they  hold  repugnant  to  God's  omnipotence.     And  so  they  have 
chosen  to  describe  God  as  every  way  indifferent,  and  creating  no- 
thing else  but  what  by  a  supposed  absolute  will  he  hath  determined  to 
create.' 

But  we  have  shown,  Spinoza  continues,  that  all  things 
follow  by  the  same  necessity  from  the  infinite  nature  or  power 
of  God ;  so  that  the  omnipotence  of  God  is  always  and  eter- 
nally in  act :  whereas  the  other  opinion  really  denies »  his 
omnipotence,  for  it  is  assumed  that  God  cannot  or  must  not 
create  everything  he  has  conceived,  lest  he  should  *  exhaust 
his  omnipotence  and  make  himself  imperfect.' 

""  *  Therefore  in  order  to  affirm  God's  perfection  these  men 
are  driven  to  affirm  at  the  same  time  that  he  cannot  bring 
about  everything  to  which  his  power  extendeth  ;  than  which 
I  see  not  what  can  be  devised  more  absurd,  or  more  repug- 
nant to  the  omnipotence  of  God.'  As  for  understanding  and 
will  in  God,  they  must  be  wholly  different  from  ours,  and 
resemble  them  only  in  name.     Human  understanding  is  con- 


344  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

ditioned  by  the  things  understood  ;  the  divine  understanding 
is  the  cause  and  origin  of  them.  It  is  also  the  cause  of 
human  understanding,  and  for  that  very  reason  must  be 
different  from  it,  as  Spinoza  proves  by  a  curious  piece  of 
formal  argument.  But  this  is  not  all.  Farther  on  he  points 
out  that  both  understanding  and  will  are  in  every  case  parti- 
cular determined  modes  of  thought,  having  particular  finite 
causes.  They  belong  to  natura  natiirata,  not  to  iiatiira  natu- 
rans.  And  accordingly  '  will  and  understanding  are  related 
to  the  nature  of  God  in  the  same  way  as  motion  and  rest ' 
and  generally  all  things  in  nature,  which  must  be  determined 
by  God  to  exist  and  act  in  a  particular  manner.  For  will, 
like  all  other  things,  needs  a  cause  to  determine  it  to  exist 
and  act.  And  though  any  particular  act  of  will  or  under- 
standing hath  infinite  consequences,  yet  God  cannot  therefore 
any  more  be  said  to  act  out  of  freedom  of  will  than  because 
of  the  consequences  of  motion  and  rest  (which  be  likewise 
infinite)  he  can  be  said  to  act  out  of  freedom  of  motion  and 
rest.  Wherefore  will  belongeth  not  to  the  nature  of  God 
more  than  other  things  in  nature,  but  standeth  with  respect 
to  it  no  otherwise  than  motion  and  rest  and  all  other  things, 
which  we  have  shown  to  follow  from  the  necessity  of  God's 
nature,  and  thereby  to  be  determined  to  exist  and  act  in  a 
particular  manner'  (Pr,  32,  Coroll.  2). 

The  next  proposition  affirms  that  'things  could  not  have 
been  produced  by  God  in  any  other  manner  or  order  than 
they  have  been  produced.'  And  it  is  maintained  (Schol.  2) 
that  this  doctrine,  so  far  from  detracting  from  the  perfection 
of  God,  as  many  persons  may  hastily  suppose,  is  required  by 
it.  Assume  with  the  objectors  that  will  belongs  to  the 
nature  of  God  :  it  will  be  admitted  that  all  things  depend  on 
his  will  for  being  what  they  are,  and  that  his  decrees  are 
eternal ;  for  his  mind  cannot  be  supposed  variable.  '  But 
since  in  eternity  there   is  not  any  when,  or  before,  or  after,  it 

•  As  to  Spinoza's  theory  about  '  motus  el  quies,'  see  pp.  108-I15  above. 


SPINOZA  AND    THEOLOGY.  345 

follows  merely  from  the  perfection  of  God  that  God  never 
can  or  could  decree  otherwise  than  he  doth  ;  or  that  God  was 
not  before  his  decrees,  nor  can  be  without  them.'  To  say 
that  God  might  have  made  things  otherwise  than  he  did  is  to 
say  that  his  will  and  understanding  might  have  been  other- 
wise than  they  are.  But  this  leads  to  inadmissible  conse- 
quences. It  is  agreed  by  all  philosophers  (Spinoza  possibly 
is  thinking  of  the  Schoolmen  as  well  of  the  Jewish  Aristote- 
lians) that  the  divine  understanding  is  never  in  potentia  but 
always  in  actii.  But  since  the  will  and  understanding  of  God 
are  indistinguishable  from  God  himself,  as  is  likewise  ad- 
mitted, it  follows  that  if  God's  will  and  understanding  had 
not  been  what  they  are,  he  must  have  been  other  than  he  is. 
That  is,  in  order  to  make  things  otherwise  than  they  are  God 
himself  must  have  been  other  than  he  is.  But  some  will  say 
that  perfection  itself  depends  on  the  will  of  God,  and  that 
what  is  now  perfection  might  have  been  imperfection  if  he 
had  thought  fit  so  to  make  it.  But  this  would  amount  to  the 
assertion  '  that  God,  who  must  needs  understand  that  which 
he  wills,  can  by  his  will  bring  it  to  pass  that  he  shall  under- 
stand things  otherwise  than  he  doth  understand  them. 
Which  (as  above  shown)  is  an  exceeding  absurdity.'  '  Then 
follows  a  very  characteristic  remark. 

*I  confess  this  opinion,  which  doth  subject  all  things  to  an 
alleged  indifferent  will  of  God  and  holdeth  everything  to  depend  on 
his  pleasure,  is  less  wide  of  the  truth  than  the  opinion  of  those  who 
hold  that  all  God's  actions  have  regard  to  a  rule  of  good  (Deum 
omnia  sub  ratione  boni  agere).  For  such  men  seem  to  affirm  some- 
what outside  God,  and  not  dependent  on  him,  which  God  keeps 
before  him  as  a  pattern  in  his  works,  or  at  which  he  aims  as  at  a 
fixed  mark.  This  plainly  is  naught  else  than  to  make  God  subject  to 
fate  ;  than  which  nothing  more  absurd  can  be  propounded  of  God, 
whom  we  have  shown  to  be  the  first  and  singular  free  cause  of  all 
things,  both  as  to  their  essence  and  as  to  their  existence.' 

'  AVith  the  whole  passage  compare  and  contrast  St.  Thomas  Aquinas,  Sumvm 
Theologi(€   Part  i,  Quaest.  19,  artt.  2-5. 


h; 


346  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Spinoza  here  repudiates  two  popular  conceptions  of  theo 
Deity  in  one  breath  ;  one  which  makes  him  an  absolute  ruler 
whose  only  law  is  his  own  will,  and  another  which  regards 
him  as  constantly  fulfilling  a  moral  law  conceived  as  in  some 
way  independent  of  him.  In  the  one  view  he  is  a  despotic 
monarch,  in  the  other  a  governor  bound  by  an  unchangeable 
constitution.  The  world  is  his  plaything,  or  an  inscrutable 
something  is  his  master.  In  the  latter  case,  the  only  evidence 
we  have  of  the  ultimate  sovereignty  of  the  moral  law  is  in 
the  human  conscience :  and  hence  it  would  seem  that  con- 
science must  be  the  judge  of  God  as  well  as  of  man.  And 
this  may  really  be  the  view  obscurely  held  by  a  large  number 
of  the  right-minded  persons  who  accept  theology  in  its  ordi- 
nary forms,  even  those  who  would  verbally  assert  the  other 
opinion,  namely,  that  the  moral  law  is  what  it  is  because  God 
has  chosen  to  make  it  so.  For  though  many  say  that  moral 
commandments  are  binding  because  they  express  the  will  of 
God,  few  of  those  who  say  so  would  not  also  say  that  the  will 
of  God  is  always  good  ;  where  the  meaning  of  good  might 
indeed  be  vague,  but  at  any  rate  would  be  something  more 
than  the  name  of  that  which  God  wills. 

A  more  philosophical  variety  of  this  opinion  is  to  go  so<> 
far  with  Spinoza  as  to  say  that  the  order  of  nature,  and  the 
moral  law  as  part  thereof,  belongs  to  the  nature  of  God  itself ; 
and  then  to  add  that  the  moral  law  appertains  in  some 
peculiar  and  eminent  way  to  the  nature  of  God,  so  as  to 
make  him  the  proper  object  of  a  feeling  similar  in  kind  to 
that  which  we  entertain  for  good  men,  but  infinitely  magnified 
in  degree.  This  position,  or  something  like  it,  is  adopted  by 
divers  modern  theologians.  It  is  free  from  the  metaphysical 
absurdity  pointed  out  by  Spinoza  in  the  cruder  form  of  moral 

.  theology,  but  raises  difficulties  of  another  kind.  The  objects 
of  morality  being  particular  and  relative  to  man,  there  appears 
to   be    no    convenient    mean    between    refraining    from    the 

\  application  of  moral  ideas  to  the  order  of  nature  as  a  whole, 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  347 

and  asserting  that  the  universe  exists  for  the  sake  of  man. 
This  last  position  was  formerly  thought  acceptable  or  even 
obvious,  but  for  several  reasons  there  is  a  growing  disinclina- 
tion to  defend  it.    Again,  it  is  not  impossible  to  deny  in  terms 
that  morality  is  relative  to  human  society.     But  those  who 
do  this  must  be  prepared  to  show  us  the  universal  morality 
of  which  human  morality  is  only  a  particular  case,  or  at  least 
to  bring  forward  some  probable  evidence  of  it.     They  should 
be  able  to  explain,  for  instance,  in  what  sense  morality  existed 
in  the  world  before  any  human  society  was  formed.     So  far, 
however,  from  feeling  any  difficulty  on  this  score,  they  would 
in  general  be  the  first  to  proclaim  the  dignity  of  man  as  the 
only  moral  creature,  and  to  exalt  him  above  all  other  finite 
beings  precisely  on  that  ground.     On  this    point  also   it  is 
hard  to  be  sure  whether  people  really  accept  everything  they 
pjofess.    The  universality  of  the  moral  law  may  be  asserted  in 
words,  while  the  real    meaning  is  only  that  there  are  per- 
manent elements  in  human  nature  and  society  to  which  there 
correspond    permanent    moral    relations,  or   that  the    broad 
groundwork  of  morality  could  not  be  different  from  what  it  is 
unless  human  nature  were  also  different.     But  this  is  a  pro- 
position which  at  the  present  day  nobody  will  dispute,  least 
of  all  anyone  who  has  apprehended  the  lessons  of  Spinoza's 
*  Ethics.'     In  the  same  way  the  principles  of  right  and  wrong  6 
may  be  called  eternal  and  immutable  in  a  sense  to  which  no 
serious  exception  can  be  taken,  namely,  that  these  principles 
are  necessary  consequences  of  the  constitution  of  man,  which 
itself  is  part  of  the  universal  order  of  nature,  and  that  they 
are  as  permanent  as  mankind  itself     It  is  possible  that  some 
of  those  who  speak  as  if  they  thought  the  scientific  discussion 
of  ethical  theories  dangerous  to  morality  may  imagine  that 
these  last-mentioned  propositions  are  attacked,  and  may  wish 
only  to  defend  them  when  they  put  forward  statements  of 
apparently  wider  scope.     Certainly  it  is  not  an  uncommon 
mistake  to  fancy  that  everyone  who   does  not   accept  some 


348  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

transcendental  theory  of  ethics  must  regard  morahty  as 
casual  and  conventional,  and  variable  in  every  new  set  of  cir- 
cumstances :  whereas  if  it  were  possible  to  regard  morality  as 
casual  and  conventional,  it  would  be  by  means  of  the  assump- 
tion that  moral  law  is  nothing  but  the  commandment  of  a 
being  who  gives  no  reason  for  his  commands,  but  will  crush 
us  if  we  disobey. 

But  we  cannot  here  attempt  to  pursue  this  topic  farther, 
and  indeed  the  task  might  prove  endless.  There  are  no 
harder  illusions  to  get  rid  of  than  anthropomorphic  ones  (or 
perhaps  it  would  be  better  to  say  anthropocentric) ;  and  there 
is  no  reason  to  suppose  that  the  possible  and  more  or  less 
plausible  forms  of  such  illusion  are  either  exhausted  or 
exhaustible.  As  to  the  modern  transcendental  theories  of 
superhuman  morality  which  claim  to  be  founded  on  a  strictly 
philosophical  method,  it  may  be  a  sufficient  excuse  for  saying 
nothing  of  them  that  they  have  no  point  of  contact  with 
Spinoza.  But  one  may  observe  that  a  transcendental  theory 
is  by  its  very  nature  a  kind  of  deiis  ex  machina.  Disproof 
may  be  impossible  ;  in  fact,  I  should  be  disposed  to  say 
that  if  any  transcendental  theory  is  capable  of  actual  dis- 
proof, it  can  only  be  the  result  of  bad  workmanship.  But 
the  burden  of  proof  lies  on  the  transcendentalist  to  show  that 
his  deus  ex  machina  is  necessary  ;  at  least  that  is  the  opinion 
of  people  who  have  not  the  transcendental  faculty. 

We  have  now  seen  that  according  to  Spinoza  the  actions  o 
of  God  are  not  directed  by  a  will  that  can  even  be  supposed" 
mutable,  by  anything  that  can  be  called  choice,  or  towards  a 
moral  end.  But  he  further  say§,.that  thgy  are .  not  directed 
towards  ends  at  all.  In  more  technical  words,  he  wholly 
rejects  Final  Causes.  To  most  English  minds  it  may  possibly 
seem  that  the  exclusion  of  deliberation  and  choice  from  the 
order  of  the  universe  would  of  itself  imply  the  exclusion  of 
j  final  causes.  But  recent  speculation  in  Germany  has  shown 
»  that  it  does  not :  and  Spinoza's  appendix  to  the  First  Part  of 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  349 

the  *  Ethics '  is  not  only  a  vigorous  piece  of  controversial  ex- 
position which  as  a  work  of  art  one  would  be  sorry  to  lose,  but 
it  is  by  no  means  philosophically  superfluous.  His  professed^ 
object  is  to  expose  the  prejudices  which  lie  at  the  root  of  most 
confused  thinking  about  the  order  of  nature.  'All  the  preju- 
dices,' he  says,  '  which  I  here  mean  to  lay  bare  depend  on  this 
point  only  ;  to  wit,  that  men  commonly  suppose  all  things  in 
nature  to  act  as  themselves  do  for  a  purpose  ;  insomuch  that 
they  make  sure  that  God  himself  orders  all  things  for  some 
fixed  end  (for  they  say  that  God  made  all  things  for  man's 
sake,  and  man  to  worship  him).'  The  origin  and  the  ground- 
lessness of  this  belief  are  accordingly  to  be  explained.  Men 
think  themselves  free,  and  act  with  a  view  to  some  desired 
end.  Thus  they  come  to  regard  the  purpose  of  an  action  as 
a  necessary  and  sufficient  explanation  of  the  action.  If  in  a 
particular  case  they  can  get  no  positive  information  of  the 
purpose,  they  form  a  conjecture  from  the  analogy  of  the 
motives  by  which  they  have  themselves  on  other  occasions 
been  determined  to  actions  of  the  same  kind.  Then,  find- 
ing so  many  things  in  nature  useful  for  man's  life,  they 
regard  all  things  as  instruments  for  man's  use  ;  and  know- 
ing that  they  found  and  did  not  make  these  conveniences, 
they  infer  that  some  ruler  of  the  world,  having  freedom  like 
that  of  human  agents,  must  have  made  them  of  set  purpose 
for  the  benefit  of  mankind.  Proceeding  to  guess  at  this 
ruler's  motives  from  the  analogy  of  their  own,  they  form  the 
opinion  that  the  Gods  ordered  the  world  for  man's  use  that 
so  they  might  acquire  men's  gratitude  and  have  honour  and 
worship  of  them. 

'And  so  this  prejudice  hath  grown  to  a  superstition 
and  struck  root  deep  in  their  minds  ;  which  was  a  reason 
moving  every  one  to  extreme  diligence  in  considering  and 
explaining  the  final  causes  of  all  things.  But  whereas  they 
sought  to  show  that  nature  doth  not  anything  in  vain  (that 
is,  without  regard  for  the  use  of  mankind)  they  have  shown 


3SO  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

nothing,  as  it  seems,  but  that  nature  and  the  Gods,  if  this 
were  so,  should  be  as  distraught  as  themselves.  Mark,  I  pray 
you,  to  what  a  pass  the  matter  comes  at  last.  Among  so 
many  conveniences  of  nature  they  must  needs  find  not  a  few 
things  contrary,  as  storms,  earthquakes,  plagues  and  the  like, 
and  these  they  affirmed  to  happen  for  that  the  Gods  were 
angered  for  wrongs  done  them  by  men,  or  faults  in  performing 
their  rites  ;  and  though  experience  did  every  day  protest, 
showing  by  numberless  examples  that  good  and  ill  turns  be- 
fall the  obedient  and  the  disobedient  indifferently,  nevertheless 
they  ceased  not  from  their  confirmed  prejudice.'  For  it  was 
easier  to  assume  that  mischievous  things  had  unknown  uses 
than  to  reconstruct  their  habits  of  thought  :  and  so  the 
further  assumption  was  made  that  the  counsels  of  the  Gods 
were  beyond  human  understanding  :  '  which  cause  would  o 
have  alone  sufficed  to  hide  the  truth  for  ever  from  mankind,' 
had  not  the  mathematics,  which  are  concerned  not  with 
designed  ends,  but  only  with  the  nature  and  properties  of 
figures,  made  manifest  to  them  another  pattern  of  truth.' 

Spinoza  then  argues,  in  his  usual  concise  manner,  that  the 
I?  doctrine  of  final  causes  is  in  itself  untenable  :  among  other 
|:  reasons,  it  is  inconsistent  with  the  perfection  of  God  :  '  for  if 
t%  God  acts  for  a  designed  end,  it  must  needs  be  that  he  desireth 
f  something  which  he  hath  not.'     And  it  is  observed  that  a 
I  common  way  of  defending  final  causes  is  by  a  method  other- 
wise   unknown    of  *  reduction,  not   to    impossibility   but   to 
ignorance.'     For  example,  a  tile  falls  from  a  roof  on  a  man's 
head  and  kills  him.     It  shall  be  proved  by  this  method  that 
it  fell  on  purpose  to  kill  him  :  for  if  that  had  not  been  God's 
design,  how  could  all  the  conditions  for  the  event  concur  then 
and  there  }     You  may  answer,  it  happened  because  the  wind 
blew  and  the  man  was  passing  that  way.     They  will  stand  to 
it  with  another  question  :  why  did  the  wind  blow,  and  why 
was  the  man  going  by  just  then.^    If  you  assign  fresh  reasons, 
they  will  again  ask  new  questions,  as  they  always  can,  since 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  351 

of  questioning  there  is  no  end  :  *  and  so  they  will  never  cease 
asking  for  the  causes  of  causes,  until  you  take  flight  to  that 
sanctuary  of  ignorance  which  they  call  the  will  of  God.' 
And  thus  it  happens  that  to  seek  out  the  causes  of  what  seemsS- 
wonderful,  and  to  aim  at  understanding  the  operations  of 
nature  instead  of  staring  in  dull  amazement,  is  to  incur  the 
suspicion  of  heresy.  For  those  who  are  commonly  esteemed 
the  sole  expounders  of  divine  truth  well  know  that  the 
destruction  of  ignorance  is  the  destruction  of  fear,  on  which 
their  power  is  built. 

It  is  then  explained  how  current  notions  of  beauty, 
ugliness,  and  the  like,  are  relative  to  men's  organs  and  dis- 
positions. This  part  of  the  appendix  is  a  rapid  sketch  in 
anticipation  of  what  is  given  at  large  in  the  following  books 
of  the  '  Ethics,'  and  we  therefore  need  not  dwell  upon  it : 
some  expressions,  however,  are  remarkable  for  their  affinity 
to  recent  psychological  theories  independently  worked  out 
from  the  side  of  physical  science.  *  If  the  motion  impressed 
on  the  optic  nerves  by  the  objects  that  the  eyes  perceive  be 
such  as  promotes  health,  the  objects  which  cause  it  are  named 
beautiful  ;  those  which  excite  the  opposite  kind  of  motion 
are  called  ugly.'  Hence  appears  the  answer  to  the  common 
difficulties  touching  the  perfection  of  the  world.  If,  it  is 
asked,  everything  is  the  result  of  God's  perfection,  whence 
come  the  many  imperfections  of  nature,  corruption,  ugliness, 
disorder,  evil,  sin  .''  But  this  is  to  confuse  the  nature  of  things 
with  human  imaginations  of  them. 

« The  perfection  of  things  is  to  be  reckoned  only  from  their  own 
nature  and  power  ;  and  things  are  not  therein  more  or  less  perfect 
that  they  delight  or  offend  the  sense  of  men,  or  that  they  are  con- 
venient for  the  nature  of  man  or  repugnant  thereto.  If  any  ask,  why 
God  hath  not  so  created  all  men  that  they  sliould  be  governed  only 
by  reason  ?  I  give  them  no  answer  but  this  :  Because  he  lacked  not 
matter  for  creating  all  things,  even  from  the  highest  degree  of  per- 
fection unto  the  lowest.  Or  more  exactly  tluis  :  Because  the  laws 
of  his  own  nature  were  so  vast  as  to  suffice  for  producing  all  things 


352  SPINOZA:    HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

which  can  be  conceived  by   an  infinite  understanding'  {ab  altquoo 
ififinito  intellectu  :  a  hypothetical  infinite  mind  which  must  be  dis-  '^ 
tinguished  from  the  infinite  intellect  which  we  have  met  with  as  one 
of  the  things  '  immediately  produced  by  God.' ) 

From  the   universal  point  of  view  perfection  is  fulness  ofo 
being,  and  hasnothing  to  do  with  the  perfection  that  is  rela- 
tive to  man's  use  or  convenience,  y^ 

So  far  Spinoza's  general  criticism  of  theological  ideas.     It 
enables  us  to  say  with  reasonable   certainty,  up  to  a  certain 
pointy  what  the   God  of  Spinoza  is  not.     He  is  free,  but  noto 
exercising_choi(;e  j  for  all  his  works  are  necessary,  and_the  * 
law  of  their  necessity  is  the  law  of  his  own  being.     His  acts 
do  not  spring  from  design  ;  where  there  is  no  choice  there  can 
be  no  deliberation,  and  a  being  which  embraces  tli'eljniverse" 
is  sufficient  to  itself.     He  is  not  a  moral  being  in  the  sense  of 
having  preferences  ;  for  with  respect  to  God  all  things  are 
perfect  in  their  kind.     Even  understanding  and^will  cannot 
be  said  to  belong  to  his  nature.     In,sii£)rt,  the  God  of  Spinoza 
is  not  the  personal  God  often  said  to  be   required  by  the 
innate  religious  sentiment  of  man.     But  if  he  is  thus  imper- 
sonal, it  would  be  misleading,  and  not  in   accordance  with 
Spinoza's  turn  of  thought,  to  say  that  he  is  unconscious.     It 
is  true  that  understanding,  as  a  determined  mode  of  thought, 
belongs  only  to  determined  things.     Even  the  infinite  intellect 
which  includes  all  thought  and  consciousness  is  a  particular 
thing.     The  object  of  these  distinctions,  however,  is  partly  to 
/  secure  the   equality  of  all  the  Attributes,  of  which  we   have 
i  already  spoken.     It  remains  a  cardinal  point  of  the  system 
j  ;   that  God  is  a  thinking  being  who  can  think  infinitely  in  infi- 
^^nl    nite  ways  (Eth.  2,  Pr.  3).     This  does  not  involve,  it  is  true, 
I    the  supposition  of  a  consciousness  analogous  to  human  con- 
sciousness.    Such  a    supposition    is   quite    inadmissible    on 
Spinoza's  principles  ;  for  human  consciousness  is  a  state  of  a 
mental  organism,  answering  in  the  Attribute  of  thought  to  a 
state  of  the  human  body  in  the  Attribute  of  extension.     And 


SPINOZA   AND    THEOLOGY.  353 

God's  consciousness  could  be  like  man's  only  if  the  material 
universe  were  organized  like  a  human  body ;  which  some 
enthusiasts  have  indeed  in  later  times  been  found  to  affirm. 
It  is  stated  however  in  one  of  the  latest  propositions  of  the 
Ethics,  already  cited  (Pt.  5,  Pr.  40),  that  the  human  mind  '  so  far^* 
as  it  understands'  is  an  eternal  mode  of  thought  which  together 
with  endless  other  such  modes  *  makes  up  the  eternal  and 
infinite  understanding  of  God.'  All  human  knowledge,  then,; 
is  not  only  contained  but  in  some  manner  united  and  "as  it 
were  incorporated  in  this  '  infinite  understanding.'  The  mind 
of  God  gathers  up  into  an  eternal  unity  the  true  ideas  of  all 
finite  minds  in  all.time.  And  also,  since  every  idea  or  mode 
of  thought  is  said  to  be  '  true  with  respect  to  God,'  in  that  it 
really  exists  and  corresponds  to  a  really  existing  mode  of  Ex- 
tension,' it  would  seem  that  every  finite  mode  of  thought  what- 
ever, whether  in  a  conscious  finite  mind  or  not,  must  have  its 
due  place  somewhere  in  the  infinite  chain.  All  this  will  doubt- 
less appear  obscure.  I  can  only  say  that  Spinoza  has  left  it 
so,  and  that  it  does  not  seem  to  me  worth  while  to  attempt  to 
force  an  illusory  definiteness  upon  that  which  is  incapable 
of  definition.  The  difficulties  of  Spinoza's  theory  of  the 
eternity  of  the  mind,  which  of  course  would  recur  here,  have 
already  been  pointed  out. 

(It  is  clear,  on  the  whole,  that  the  real  difference  between 
Spinoza  and  the  common  forms  of  orthodox  philosophy  is 
not  that  he  denies  consciousness  to  God,  for  this  he  never 
does  ;  or  that  he  denies  God's  consciousness  to  be  like  man's, 
for  this  many  orthodox  philosophers  would  also  deny,  and 
theologians  of  the  weightiest  authority  have  in  fact  denied  it 
as  strongly  as  Spinoza  himself  The  point  of  his  heterodoxy-^' 
is  that  he  will  not  call  God  exclusively  or  eminently  a  think- 
ing being.  To  say  that  God  is  a  spirit  is  in  Spinoza's  view 
just  as  inadequate  and  misleading  as  to  say  that  man  is  a 
spirit.     Man  is  a  thinking  being,  but  he  is  also  a  corporeal  or 

'  See  p.  196,  above. 
A  A 


354  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

extended  being  ;  and  thought  is  only  one  of  the  infinite 
Attributes  of  God.  But  here  there  recurs  another  point  of  o 
which  we  have  already  treated,  namely  the  latent  idealism 
of  Spinoza's  metaphysical  system,  which  may  have  coloured 
his  thought  on  this  subject  almost  without  his  knowing  it. 
Perhaps  he  regarded  the  infinite  variety  of  the  universe 
(including  as  it  does  in  his  view  countless  forms  of  existence 
to  us  wholly  unimaginable)  as  reflected  and  redoubled,,  and  at 
the  same  time  grasped  as  a  single  whole,  in  the  '  infinite  in- 
tellect of  God.'  But  all  this,  again,  comes  perilously  near  to 
a  mere  playing  with  words. 

The  discussion  of  Spinoza's  metaphysic  in  its  bearing  on 
theology  is  much  complicated  by  his  having  no  philosophical 
term  equivalent  to  the  modern  consciousness,  and  generally 
not  regarding  things  from  that  point  of  view.  In  one  passage 
of  his  early  work,  the  '  Cogitata  Metaphysica '  (Part  2,  c.  8,  §  i) 
he  does  mention  the  term  Personality  as  being  used  by  theo- 
logians to  explain  their  distinction  of  qualities  or  attributes 
(in  the  common  sense)  in  God.  He  adds  that  the  term  is  as 
mysterious  to  him  as  the  mystery  it  is  intended  to  explain, 
and  that  further  light  is  to  be  hoped  for  only  in  the  beatific 
vision  ( '  quamvis  constanter  credamus  in  visione  Dei  bea- 
tissima  quae  fidelibus  promittitur  Deum  hoc  suis  revelatu- 
rum '). 

Now  an  appeal  to  revelation,  either  here  or  hereafter,  fw 
enlightenment  on  a  philosophical  question  is  a  thing  utterly 
contrary  to  Spinoza's  later  principles,  as  abundantly  appears 
from  the  *  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.'  And  this  passage- 
occurs  in  a  work  where  Spinoza  is  not  expressing  his  own 
opinions,  except  so  far  as  he  can  suggest  them  in  a  pro- 
fessedly Cartesian  commentary  without  actually  contradicting 
Descartes.  Either  the  passage  is  ironical,  hinting  to  the  dis- 
ciple of  Descartes  that  his  master  has  brought  him  to  a  theo- 
logico-philosophical  deadlock  whence  nothing  but  a  revelation 
will  help  him   out :  or  (as   I   think  more   probable)    it   was 


SPINOZA   AND    THEOLOGY.  355 

written  by  Spinoza  at  a  very  early  time,  when  he  was  still 
disposed  to  believe  in  mysteries.  At  the  date  of  the  '  Essay 
of  God  and  Man  '  he  seems  to  have  thought  it  possible  that 
new  Attributes  might  become  known  to  man  by  revelation  ; 
for  in  one  place  (Part  i,  c.  7,  note)  he  speaks  of  Thought 
and  Extension  as  the  only  Attributes  as  yet  known  to  us. 

It  is  remarkable  that  the  theological  colouring  of  Spinoza's 
philosophy  becomes  fainter  as  we  proceed   in  the   '  Ethics,' 
and  in  the  third  and  fourth  Parts  Dcus  appears  more  and 
more  like  a  bare  synonym  for  natura.     But  then,  just  as  one 
might  begin  to  think  that  the  verbal  disguise  has  been  com- 
pletely thrown  off,  we  come  upon  the  intellectual  love  of  God 
in  the  fifth  Part.     After  all   God  has  not  been  reduced  to''^ 
Nature,  but   Nature   exalted  to  God.     Spinoza  begins  and 
ends  with  theological  terms  ;  and  yet,  when  we  translate  his 
doctrines  into  modern  language,  we  find  a  view  of  the  world 
standing  wholly  apart   from    those    which    have    been  pro- 
pounded   or   seriously  influenced  by  theology.     His  earlier 
writings   help    us   to    understand    the   seeming   riddle.     He 
started  with  the  intention  of  making  theology  philosophical, 
but  with  the  determination  to  follow  reason  to  the  uttermost. 
Reason  led  him  beyond  the  atmosphere  of  theology  altogether, 
but  his  advance  was  so  continuous  that  the  full  extent  of  itt 
was  hardly  perceived  by  himself.  ^^ 

"^  Those  to  whom  names  are  important  may  be  left  to  settle 
as  best  they  can  by  what  name  Spinoza's  doctrine  shall  be 
called.  Most  people  call  it  Pantheism.  There  is  no  particu-'' 
lar  harm  in  this,  except  that  Pantheism  is  so  vague  a-  term  as 
to  be  applicable  and  applied  to  diametrically  opposite  theories. 
For  example,  the  Hindu  philosophers  of  the  orthodox  Brah- 
manical  schools  are  in  a  general  way  pantheists,  and  are 
commonly  so  named.  But  they  hold  that  all  finite  existence 
is  an  illusion,  and  life  mere  vexation  and  mistake,  a  blunder 
or  sorry  jest  of  the  Absolute.  We  need  hardly  repeat  that 
Spinoza  holds  nothing  of  the  kind.     So  that  when  somebody 

A  A  2 


3S6  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

talked    a   while    ago   of    '  Pantheism    from    the    Vedas    to 
Spinoza,'  he  might  as  well  have  talked  of  the  law  of  evidence 
from  Manu  to  the  Indian  Evidence  Act,  as  far  as  any  logical 
connexion  went :  to  say  nothing  of  the  circumstance  that  the 
Vedas  are   many   centuries  earlier   than   systematic    Hindu 
philosophy,  and  the  earliest  parts  of  them  are  not  pantheistic. 
Again,  the  Stoics  were  also  pantheists  :  only  they  went  to  the 
other  extreme  and  held  that  the  universe  was  the  product  of 
perfect  reason  and  in  an  absolute  sense  good.     A  descrfption 
which  includes  these  opinions  as  well  as  Spinoza's  cannot  be 
of  much  use  for  conveying  exact  information.     And  then  it 
is  difficult  to  say  how  far  Theism  does  or  does  not  overlap 
Pantheism.     Lately  Mr.  Fiske  of  Harvard  has  written  a  very 
lucid  and  systematic  work,  setting  forth  a  view  of  the  nature 
of  things  identical  in  the  main  with  Mr.  Herbert  Spencer's, 
and  he  calls  his  view  Cosmic  Theism.     Now  it  is  certain  that 
Mr.  Spencer's  and  Mr.  Fiske's  doctrine  excludes  the  belief  in 
a  so-called  Personal  God,  and  the  particular  forms  of  religious 
emotion  dependent  on   it.     Whether   any  large   number  of 
people  will  agree  to  use  the  name  of  Cosmic  Theism  for  the 
doctrine  I   do  not  know,  and   cannot  pretend  to  care  very 
much.     But   it   is   evident   that    Spinoza   must  be  called  a 
Theist  by  such  persons,  be  they  many  or  few ;  since  his  ideas 
are  not  less  theological  than  Mr.  Fiske's,  and  his  language 
more  so.     Then  there  is  the  facile  and  once  frequent  name  ot 
Atheism,  which  however  polite  and  intelligent  persons  have 
lately  shrunk  from  using.     This  is  just  as  well,  as  it  is  not 
only  an  ugly  name,  but  has  no  intelligible  meaning.     At  least 
the  nearest  approach  to  a  definition  that  I  can  suggest   is 
that  an  atheist  means  anybody  who  disagrees  with  one  on  any 
theological  question  of  importance ;  the   speaker   being,    of 
course,  the  judge  both  of  what  questions  are  theological,  and 
whether  they  are   important   enough  to   call  names   about. 
Probably  the  historical  meaning  is  definite  enough,  namely,  a 
citizen  who  refuses  to  worship   the  Gods  appointed    to   be 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  357 

worshipped  by  the  authorities  of  his  city.  But  to  apply  this 
in  England  at  the  present  day  would  obviously  lead  us  into 
great  incivility  towards  classes  of  persons  who  are  not  only 
respectable  and  influential,  but  quite  orthodox  as  orthodoxy 
has  been  understood  ever  since  the  Act  of  Toleration.^  As 
for  Agnosticism,  we  may  be  allowed  to  put  off"  any  discussion 
of  this  last  addition  to  the  vocabulary  of  sects  and  persuasions 
till  some  one  has  called  Spinoza  an  Agnostic.  In  fine,  we 
conclude  that  to  dwell  on  these  matters  of  nomenclature  is 
unprofitable  :  and  we  decline,  for  similar  reasons,  to  enter  on 
the  question,  on  which  chapters  if  not  volumes  might  be 
spent,  whether  Spinoza's  way  of  looking  at  the  world  and 
man  is  to  be  called  a  religion  or  not.  If  it  is  fitted  (with 
allowances  and  additions  according  to  the  state  of  knowledge 
for  the  time  being)  for  the  use  of  reasonable  men  in  the  con- 
duct of  life,  sooner  or  later  reasonable  men  will  find  it  out 
and  use  it,  under  whatever  name.  If  it  is  not,  reasonable 
men  will  not  be  persuaded  to  use  it  by  the  most  positive  and 
formal  proof  that  it  satisfies  at  all  points  the  best  possible 
definition  of  a  religion. 

We  may  now  go  on  to  consider  Spinoza's  utterances  as  to 
the  particular  revelations  on  which  the  claims  of  Judaism  and 
Christianity,  the  only  historical  religions  with  which  he  was 
acquainted,  are  commonly  made  to  stand.  It  is  needless  to 
say  that  the  materials  for  a  comparative  study  of  religions 
were  not  accessible  in  Spinoza's  time.  The  religions  of  the 
East  were  known  only  by  loose  and  superficial  report,  and  this 
was  especially  the  case  with  Buddhism,  the  most  important  of 
all.  Spinoza  probably  knew  of  its  existence  (in  his  letter  to 
Albert  Burgh  he  specifies  India  as  the  seat  of  divers  re- 
ligions) ;  but  of  its  origin,  its  fundamental  doctrines,  and  the 
personal  character  of  its  founder  as  preserved  by  tradition,  he 
can  have  known  nothing.    Indian  Buddhism,  indeed,  remained 

'  Yet  the  term  atheist  appears  to  include  even  now,  in  the  borough  of  Chelsea 
and  at  the  time  of  a  general  election,  a  member  of  the  Society  of  Friends. 


358  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

a  sealed  book  to  European  scholars  long  after  his  time.'  This 
has  to  be  borne  in  mind  if  we  undertake  to  reduce  Spinoza's 
judgments  to  the  measure  of  our  own  time.  In  the  first 
chapter  of  the  'Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  where  the 
nature  of  prophecy  is  discussed,  the  revelation  of  the  Deca- 
logue occurs  as  a  question  to  be  specially  dealt  with.  It  is  the 
opinion  of  some  Jewish  authors,  Spinoza  says,  that  the  words 
of  the  commandments  were  not  actually  pronounced  by  God, 
but  the  Israelites  heard  an  inarticulate  noise,  while  at  the  same 
time  the  commandments  were  inwardly  perceived  by  them. 

'  And  this '  (he  proceeds)  '  I  myself  once  thought,  since  I  found 
the  words  of  the  decalogue  in  Exodus  different  from  those  in 
Deuteronomy;  whence  it  seems  to  follow  (since  God  spoke  but 
once)  that  the  decalogue  was  to  lay  down  not  the  very  words  of 
God  but  only  the  meaning.  However,  if  we  are  not  to  do  violence 
to  Scripture,  it  must  certainly  be  allowed  that  the  Israelites  heard  a 
real  voice.' 

This  voice  we  must  suppose  to  have  been  created  for 
that  occasion.  But  this  supposition  is  by  no  means  free  from 
difficulty  :  for  how  cdtild  this  finite  and  created  voice  give  the 
Israelites  any  rational  certainty  of  the  existence  or  nature  of 
God  beyond  what  they  had  before  1  And  moreover  the  whole 
narrative  suggests  not  only  that  there  was  a  real  voice,  but 
that  God  himself  spoke  in  the  fashion  of  a  man.  '  Wherefore 
I  doubt  not,'  Spinoza  concludes,  '  that  herein  lies  a  mystery, 
of  which  we  will  speak  more  at  large  afterwards.'  Are  we  to 
infer  that  Spinoza  thought  it  proper  on  this  point  to  follow 
the  example  set  by  Ibn  Ezra  on  other  points  of  historical  cri- 
ticism .''  By  talking  of  a  mystery  does  he  simply  mean,  as  Ibn 
Ezra  meant  beyond  question,  that  he  does  not  choose  to  ex- 
plain himself  further  }  Certainly  he  has  brought  together 
precisely  the  kind  of  evidence,  and  suggested  precisely  the 
kind  of  considerations,  which  a  modern  critic  would  bring  for- 

'  The  Buddha  appears  in  Montesquieu  (doubtless  through  Jesuit  accounts  of 
Chinese  Buddhism)  as  'Foe,  legislateur  des  Indes.'  Esprit  des  Loi^,  book  14,  c. 
5.     Cp.  note  B  to  Bayle's  article  on  Spinoza, 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  359 

ward  to  show  that  the  whole  narrative  is  an  anthropomorphic 
myth.  The  hypothesis  he  actually  gives  is  a  sort  of  ration- 
alized miracle  :  since  God  does  not  speak  like  men,  he  must 
have  specially  ordained  that  the  Israelites  should  hear  certain 
words  pronounced  as  by  a  magnified  human  voice.  It  is  ex- 
tremely difficult  to  believe  that  this  really  commended  itself 
to  Spinoza.  Again,  it  sufficiently  appears  from  other  parts  of 
the  treatise  that  in  Spinoza's  eyes  the  pre-eminence  of  the 
Jews  as  the  chosen  people  was  a  fact  to  be  studied  and  ex- 
plained on  the  ordinary  principles  of  historical  and  political 
reasoning.  The  divine  election  of  the  Hebrew  nation  is  iden- 
tified, as  we  should  now  say,  with  natural  selection.  Again, 
the  whole  and  only  scope  of  revelation,  in  the  view  set  forth 
by  Spinoza  in  various  parts  of  the  treatise,  is  to  assure  men 
that  there  is  a  way  of  salvation  by  obedience  without  specula- 
tive knowledge.  And  this  obedience  does  not  consist  in  fol- 
lowing any  particular  set  of  precepts,  but  in  the  exercise  of 
justice  and  charity.  The  only  necessary  and  really  catholic 
faith  is  summed  up  in  this  :  *  that  there  is  a  supreme  being, 
loving  justice  and  charity,  whom  all  men  are  bound  to  obey 
that  they  may  be  saved,  and  to  worship  by  showing  justice 
and  charity  to  their  neighbours.'  (c.  14,  §  24).  Philosophical 
questions  as  to  the  nature  and  attributes  of  God  are  indifferent 
to  faith: 

J 

'Whether  he  be  fire,  spirit,  light,  thought,  or  otherAvise,  is  of  no 
account  to  faith  ;  nor  yet  in  what  manner  he  is  the  type  of  the  right 
life,  for  example,  whether  because  he  hath  a  just  and  merciful  mind, 
or  because  by  him  is  the  being  and  operation  of  all  things,  and 
through  him  therefore  we  also  have  understanding,  and  through  him 
perceive  that  which  is  true,  just,  and  good  :  to  faith  it  is  all  one  what 
every  man  holds  touching  these  things.  So  again  it  is  indifferent  to 
faith  whether  one  believe  that  God  is  everywhere  essentially  or 
potentially  ;  that  he  governs  nature  freely  or  by  the  necessity  of  his 
own  nature  ;  that  he  dictates  laws  as  a  prince,  or  shows  them  as 
eternal  truths  ;  that  men  obey  God  from  absolute  free  will,  or  by 
necessity  of  the  divine  ordinance  ;  that  the  reward  of  good  and 
punishment  of  wicked  men  is  natural  or  supernatural.' 


^ 


36o  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Thus,  too,  it  is  not  the  business  of  revelation  to  give 
rational  demonstrations  but  to  move  men  to  obedience.  And 
here  is  the  answer  to  the  difficulties  formerly  raised  about  the 
voice  from  Sinai. 

*  Although  the  voice  which  the  Israelites  heard  could  not  have 
given  them  any  philosophical  or  mathematical  certainty  of  the  exist- 
ence of  God,  yet  it  sufficed  to  ravish  them  with  amazement  at  God's 
power  (such  as  they  already  knew  him),  and  to  impel  them  to 
obedience  ;  which  was  the  purpose  of  that  display.  For  God's  will 
was  not  to  show  the  Israelites  the  attributes  of  his  nature  as  they  are 
in  themselves  (seeing  he  did  not  as  then  reveal  any),  but  to  break 
their  stubborn  mind  and  draw  it  to  obedience ;  and  so  he  went  to 
work  with  them  not  with  arguments,  but  with  the  blast  of  trumpets, 
thunder,  and  lightnings.' 

This,  it  will  be  observed,  removes  only  half  the  difficulty. 
The  other  half  is  not  touched  either  in  the  chapter  on  miracles 
or  elsewhere.  Remembering  that  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico- 
Politicus '  is  a  work  of  conciliation,  we  may  conclude  without 
much  hesitation  that  Spinoza  did  not  himself  regard  the  cir- 
cumstances of  the  Mosaic  revelation  as  historical. 

When  in  the  following  chapter  he  speaks  of  the  necessity 
and  authority  of  revelation,  he  passes  over  the  thunders  of 
Sinai,  and  only  adduces  in  general  terms  the  testimony  of  the 
prophets.  And  the  prophets  he  regards  (herein  pretty  much 
following  Maimonides)  as  men  gifted  with  a  particularly  strong 
and  vivid  imagination,  which  became  the  instrument  of  a  kind 
of  special  insight ;  the  prophet's  individual  character,  educa- 
tion and  habits  colouring  all  his  visions  and  determining  the 
form  in  which  they  were  recorded.  On  this  point  also  the  o 
question  occurs  whether  Spinoza  is  giving  his  own  opinion,  or 
only  aims  at  giving  the  most  rational  theory  within  the  limits 
of  certain  assumptions  he  has  imposed  on  himself  for  a  special 
purpose.  It  is  almost  impossible  to  draw  the  line  between 
these  two  positions  in  the  'Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,' 
and  I  doubt  whether  Spinoza  always  drew  it  himself, 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  361 

The  passage  on  the  general  necessity  of  revelation  to 
which  attention  has  just  been  callecT  deserves  further  con- 
sideration. It  has  been  seen  that  the  foundation  of  theology 
and  the  sum  of  faith  is  that  men  can  be  saved  by  mere 
obedience  without  knowledgej  Not  that  obedience  is  the 
only  way  ;  for  knowledge  leads  to  the  same  life  and  the  same 
salvation,  as  Spinoza  is  careful  to  explain.  But  this  efficacy 
of  obedience  is  not  demonstrated  :  it  may  be  asked  then,  why 
do  we  believe  it  .-*  If  blindly  and  without  reason,  then  we  act 
foolishly ;  if  on  the  other  hand  we  say  it  is  capable  of  proof^ 
theology  is  absorbed  in  philosophy. 

'  Now  to  this  I  answer,  I  clearly  hold  that  this  fundamental  doctrine 
of  theology  cannot  be  discovered  by  natural  reason,  at  least  there 
hath  no  man  been  found  to  demonstrate  it,  and  therefore  revelation 
was  highly  necessary ;  but  nevertheless  we  may  so  use  our  judg- 
ment as  to  accept  the  revelation  once  made  with  at  least  a  moral 
certainty.  I  say  moral  certainty  :  for  we  cannot  look  to  have  greater 
certainty  herein  than  the  prophets  themselves  to  whom  it  was  first 
revealed,  and  whose  certainty  was  yet  but  moral,  as  we  have  already 
shown.  Wherefore  those  go  clean  astray  who  endeavour  to  prove 
the  authority  of  Scripture  by  arguments  of  the  mathematical  kind. 
....  And  we  may  reasonably  embrace  this  fundamental  position  of 
theology  and  Scripture,  though  it  cannot  be  mathematically  proved. 
It  is  folly  to  reject  merely  for  this  cause  that  which  is  confirmed  by 
the  witness  of  so  many  prophets,  from  which  flows  great  comfort  to 
men  who  do  not  excel  in  understanding,  and  to  the  commonwealth 
ensues  no  small  advantage  ;  and  which  we  may  believe  without  any 
hurt  or  danger  ;  as  if  for  the  rational  conduct  of  life  we  could  admit 
nothing  as  truth  which  on  any  plausible  ground  may  be  called  in 
doubt,  or  as  if  the  greater  part  of  our  actions  were  not  uncertain  and 
hazardous.' 

Once  more,  at  the  end  of  the  chapter  Spinoza  repeats  that 
he  attaches  the  highest  value  to  revealed  religion  in  the  sense 
we  have  just  explained. 

'Since  we  cannot  perceive  by  the  light  of  nature  that  mere 
obedience  is  a  way  to  salvation,  but  only  revelation  teaches  that  this  is 
brought  to  pass  by  the  singular  grace  of  God,  which  our  reason  can- 


3r^2        SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

not  attain,  it  appears  by  consequence  that  the  Scriptures  have 
brought  exceeding  comfort  to  mankind.  All  men  without  exceptions 
can  obey,  and  there  be  but  a  very  few,  compared  with  the  whole  of 
human  kind,  who  acquire  a  virtuous  disposition  by  the  guidance  of 
reason  :  so  that  if  we  had  not  this  witness  of  Scripture,  we  should 
doubt  of  the  salvation  of  nearly  all  men.' 

Two  points  of  some  interest  are  left  unexplained  by  this 
statement,  namely,  the  precise  meaning  of  salvation  or  being 
saved,  and  how,  if  at  all,  the  facts  of  revelation  or  the  truth 
revealed  can  be  expressed  in  philosophical  language.  In  the 
first  question  there  is  nothing  to  detain  us.  For  -Spinoza  o 
salvation  cannot  mean  anything  else  than  that  deliverance 
from  the  passions  to  which  the  other  way,  the  clear  but 
arduous  way  of  reason,  is  shown  in  the  '  Ethics.'  But  of 
revelation  what  are  we  to  understand  t  How  can  God  as  con- 
ceived by  Spinoza,  the  being  in  whom  is  the  infinite  reality  of 
infinite  worlds,  whose  freedom  is  the  necessity  of  the  universe, 
to  whose  nature  neither  understanding  nor  will  must  be  specially 
ascribed,  reveal  particular  truths  or  duties  to  men  by  particular 
acts  of  grace  .-•  Again,  the  alleged  contents  of  revelation  are 
hardly  adequate  to  the  machinery.  It  seems  paradoxical,  or 
at  least  not  consistent  with  Spinoza's  general  v/ay  of  think- 
ing, to  call  in  the  Law  and  the  Prophets  to  assure  us  that  the 
reward  of  a  tranquil  mind  may  be  earned  by  righteousness 
and  goodwill  without  philosophy:  for  this  is  what  the  mes- 
sage of  Scripture  seems  to  come  to,  when  we  substitute  for  the 
term  salvation  the  meaning  almost  certainly  attached  to  it  by 
Spinoza.  Is  this  a  matter  to  learn  from  signs  and  wonders  .-' 
or,  thinking  and  saying  what  he  does  of  signs  and  wonders  in 
general,  can  Spinoza  really  mean  to  assert  the  supernatural 
communication  of  this  one  point  of  practical  knowledge  .'* 
On  the  other  hand,  the  words  are  express  and  even  emphatic: 
and  we  have  no  right  to  sacrifice  Spinoza's  good  faith  to  the 
dogma  of  his  rigid  consistency,  which  has  arisen,  as  I  have 
already  had  occasion  to  point  out,  from  attaching  exaggerated 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  363 

importance  to  the  geometrical  form  used  in  the  *  Ethics.' 
Perhaps  we  are  free  to  suppose  that  Spinoza  regarded  revela- 
tion as  the  manifestation  of  a  particular  kind  of  human 
genius,  the  disclosure  of  moral  truth  by  an  insight  natural  in 
its  presence  and  operation,  but  occurring  only  in  a  few  men. 
But  if  prophecy  be  simply  a  kind  of  genius,  why  should  it 
have  ceased  .-*  And  why  does  Spinoza  lay  so  much  stress  on 
the  necessity  of  the  true  prophet's  doctrine  being  confirmed 
by  a  sign  1  In  order  to  dispose  of  modern  impostors,  one 
might  think  at  first  sight.  But  he  must  have  well  known 
that  professing  prophets  are  never  at  a  loss  for  a  sign  ;  and 
moreover  he  has  a  much  shorter  way  with  new  propounders  of 
revelations,  as  we  saw  in  considering  his  theory  of  politics. 
Altogether  the  difficulty  remains  considerable.  There  is  an 
unexplained  gap  between  the  rationalizing  criticism  of  the 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  which  goes  a  long  way, 
but  refuses  to  go  all  lengths,  and  the  thorough-going  specula- 
tion of  the  '  Ethics.'  Difference  of  dates  will  not  account  for 
it,  since  we  know  that  Spinoza's  philosophy  was  matured  long 
before  the  Theologico-political  Treatise  was  published. 

The  difficulty,  however,  applies  only  to  our  estimate  of 
Spinoza's  personal  opinions.  For  philosophical  criticism  the 
*  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus'  may  be  taken  by  itself,  and 
anything  propounded  or  suggested  by  it  may  be  adopted  or 
left  aside  on  its  own  merits.  And  the  view  of  revelation 
there  put  forward  seems  to  contain  at  least  this  truth  :  that 
the  appearance  of  a  religion  which  puts  a  moral  law  before 
ceremonies,  and  organizes  morality  instead  of  merely  organiz- 
ing sacrifices,  processions,  penances,  miracles,  indulgences,  is  a 
capital  fact  in  the  history  of  the  world.  The  religion  which 
reaches  this  height,  whether  gradually  or  by  the  first  impulse 
of  a  founder,  is  vital  and  has  the  means  of  victory.  Judaism, 
Buddhism,  Christianity,  to  some  extent  Mahometanism, 
possess  or  have  possessed  this  power.  It  is  true  that  religion 0 
always  tends,  in  the  hands  of  its  ordinary  ministers  (who  can-* 


364  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

not  as  a  rule  be  more  than  ordinary  men),  to  revert  to  the 
ceremonial  stage.  It  is  also  true  that  the  opposite  danger  of 
mysticism  is  ever  present.  But  when  a  religion  has  once  been 
or  become  moral,  there  is  always  room  for  men  of  moral 
genius  to  arise  within  it  and  revive  the  latent  power.  This 
they  do  at  the  risk  of  being  misunderstood  and  disowned  ;  in 
some  cases  they  find  themselves  cut  off  altogether,  and  found 
a  new  religion  or  communion ;  in  others  the  Church  is  wise 
in  time,  and  their  work  is  openly  or  tacitly  accepted.  Thus 
Judaism  underwent  a  great  moral  transformation  in  the  hands 
of  the  prophets,  but  not  without  great  struggles ;  and  again, 
at  the  very  time  when  the  Jewish  polity  was  doomed  to  final 
destruction,  the  moral  side  of  Jewish  religion  received  a 
further  development  the  results  of  which  have  never  been  lost. 
On  the  other  hand  Buddhism  owes  its  independent  existence 
to  Brahman  jealousy  and  exclusiveness  ;  it  appears,  at  least, 
that  the  Buddha  had  for  himself  no  intention  of  going  out- 
side the  very  large  bounds  of  Hindu  orthodoxy.  In  our  own 
country  Wesley,  who  elsewhere  might  have  become  the 
founder  of  a  new  cosmopolitan  order,  was  driven  to  leave  his 
name  to  a  sect.  And  in  Christianity  we  have  the  greatest  oi 
all  examples  (though  as  to  its  actual  scale  and  extent  not 
greater  than  Buddhism)  of  a  religious  movement  not  origin- 
ally aggressive  assuming  an  entirely  new  character  under  the 
stress  of  opposition,  and  becoming  at  last  a  power  of  the  first 
magnitude.  It  is  curiously  parallel  with  Buddhism  in  the 
circumstances  that  it  has  been  reduced  to  insignificance  in 
the  scenes  of  its  early  conquests,  and  has  found  its  strength 
in  distant  lands  and  among  men  of  alien  races  and  traditions. 
What  has  Spinoza  to  say  of  the  power  of  Christianity  and 
the  person  of  its  founder }  His  own  words  shall  presently  be 
given.  But  we  must  attempt  to  find  an  equivalent  for  them 
in  the  language  of  our  own  time  :  and,  leaving  aside  the 
question  of  revelation  in  the  abstract,  I  think  we  may  say  (5 
that  Spinoza  looked  on  Jesus  as  a  man  of  transcendent  and 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  365 

unique  moral  genius,  standing  out  above  Moses  and  the 
prophets  in  some  such  way  as  Moses  was  conceived  by  the 
Jewish  doctors  to  stand  above  all  other  prophets.^  But  he 
did  not  regard  him  as  otherwise  of  a  different  mould  from 
mortal  men.  The  mysteries  propounded  by  Christian  theo- 
logians appeared  to  him  scarcely  to  deserve  express  contradic- 
tion :  they  were  not  so  much  untrue  as  unintelligible.  In 
discussing  the  nature  of  prophetic  vision  (Tract.  Theol.- 
Polit  c.  I,  §§  22-24)  Spinoza  says  : — 

'Though  we  clearly  understand  that  God  can  communicate 
immediately  with  men  (for  he  communicates  his  nature  to  our  mind  ^ 
without  any  bodily  instrument)  ;  yet  that  a  man  should  purely  in  his 
mind  perceive  matters  which  be  not  contained  in  the  first  principles 
of  our  knowledge,  nor  can  be  deduced  therefrom,  his  mind  must  be 
of  surpassing  excellence  and  beyond  man's  capacity.  Wherefore  I 
believe  not  that  any  man  ever  came  to  that  singular  height  of  per- 
fection but  Christ,  to  whom  the  ordinances  of  God  that  lead  men  to 
salvation  were  revealed,  not  in  words  or  visions,  but  immediately  :  so 
that  God  manifested  himself  to  the  apostles  by  the  mind  of  Christ,  as 
formerly  to  Moses  by  means  of  a  voice  in  the  air.  And  therefore 
the  voice  of  Christ  may  be  called,  like  that  which  Moses  heard,  the 
voice  of  God.  In  this  sense' we  may  Hkewise  say  that  the  wisdom 
of  God,  that  is,  a  wisdom  above  man's,  took  man's  nature  in  Christ, 
and  that  Christ  is  the  way  of  salvation.  But  here  it  is  needful  to  ex- 
plain that  of  those  things  which  sundry  churches  determine  concerning 
Christ  I  have  naught  to  say,  neither  do  I  deny  them  ;  for  I  am  free 
to  confess  I  comprehend  them  not.  What  I  have  now  said  I 
collect  from  Scripture  alone.' 

And  again  in  the  chapter  on  God's  laws  (c.  4)  it  is  said 
that  even  Moses  received  and  understood  his  revelations  not 
as  declarations  of  eternal  truth  but  as  positive  laws  or  pre- 
cepts, and  regarded  God  under  the  human  attributes  of  a 
prince  and  lawgiver. 

*  This,  I  say,'  adds  Spinoza,  *  is  to  be  affirmed  only  of  the  prophets 
who  deliver  laws  in  the  name  of  God  ;  but  not  of  Christ.  Of  Christ, 
though  he  too  appears  to  have  delivered  laws  in  the  name  of  God, 

'  Cp.  Trad  Theol.-Pol.  c.  I,§  21.  -  That  is,  in  our  ordinary  knowledge. 


/ 


366  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

we  are  yet  to  think  that  he  perceived  things  truly  and  adequately. 
For  Christ  was  rather  the  very  mouth  of  God  than  a  prophet ;  since 
(as  we  showed  in  the  first  chapter)  God  gave  revelations  to  mankind  by 
the  mind  of  Christ,  as  aforetime  by  angels,  that  is,  by  particular 
voices  and  visions.' 

And  if  Christ  ever  declared  after  the  fashion  of  a  lawgiver 
the  truths  which  he  perceived  in  their  eternal  necessity,  it 
must  have  been  from  regard  to  the  ignorance  of  his  hearers. 
Spinoza  thus  appears  to  ascribe  to  Christ  not  only  a  sur- 
passing power  of  moral  intuition,  but  a  corresponding  strength 
and  clearness  of  understanding  in  relation  to  the  truths  thus 
V  perceived.    The  reader  may  already  have  observed,  what  is  still 

more  plain  in  reading  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus '  at 
large,  that  Spinoza  takes  no  account  of  the  historical  develop- 
ment either  of  morality  or  of  religion.  It  was  hardly  possible 
that  he  should  ;  the  omission  is  simply  to  be  noted  and  borne 
in  mind. 

These  opinions  of  Christ's  office  and  character  were  natur- 
ally unacceptable  even  to  moderately  orthodox  readers.  In 
1675  Oldenburg  asked  Spinoza  (Ep.  20)  to  explain  himself 
farther  on  this  and  other  points.  The  answer  on  this  head  is 
as  follows  (Ep.  21) : — 

'  I  say  that  it  is  by  no  means  necessary  to  salvation  to  know 
Christ  after  the  flesh ;  but  of  the  eternal  Son  of  God,  that  is,  the 
eternal  wisdom  of  God,  which  has  shown  itself  forth  in  all  things,  and 
chiefly  in  the  mind  of  man,  and  most  chiefly  of  all  in  Jesus  Christ, 
we  are  to  think  far  otherwise.  For  without  this  no  one  can  attain 
the  state  of  blessedness  ;  since  this  alone  teaches  what  is  true  and 
false,  good  and  evil.  And  because,  as  I  have  said,  this  wisdom  was 
chiefly  shown  forth  through  Jesus  Christ,  his  disciples  preached  the 
same  as  by  him  it  was  revealed  to  them,  and  showed  that  in  that 
spirit  of  Christ  they  could  exalt  themselves  above  others.  As  for- 
the  proposition  added  by  sundry  churches,  that  God  took  on  himself 
the  nature  of  man,  I  have  distinctly  stated  that  I  know  not  what  they 
mean.  To  speak  plainly,  they  seem  to  me  to  speak  as  improperly 
as  if  one  should  tell  me  that  a  circle  had  assumed  the  nature  of  a 


/ 


\ 


square. 


SPINOZA  AND   THEOLOGY.  367 

Oldenburg  is  unsatisfied,  and  insists  on  the  necessity  of 
keeping  a  certain  amount  of  miracle  and  mystery  as  the 
foundation  of  Christianity  (Ep.  22).  This  leads  to  an  answer 
where  Spinoza  comes  very  near  to  the  specific  conclusions  of 
modern  theological  criticism,  and  (what  is  more  remarkable) 
by  much  the  same  road  (Ep.  23). 

'  As  to  my  opinion  of  miracles,  I  have  sufficiently  expounded  it, 
if  I  mistake  not,  in  the  theologico-political  treatise.  I  now  add  but 
this  much  :  if  you  consider  these  matters,  to  wit  that  Christ  appeared 
not  to  the  Sanhedrin,  not  to  Pilate,  nor  to  any  of  the  unbelieving, 
but  only  to  the  saints  ;  that  God  hath  no  right  or  left  hand,  nor  is 
naturally  in  any  one  place,  but  everywhere ;  that  matter  is  everywhere 
the  same,  and  that  God  cannot  display  himself  outside  the  world  in 
the  imaginary  space  men  feign  ;  lastly,  that  the  fabric  of  the  human 
body  is  restrained  by  the  mere  weight  of  the  air  within  certain 
bounds  :  you  will  then  easily  perceive  that  the  appearance  of  Christ 
after  his  death  was  not  unlike  that  in  which  God  appeared  to 
Abraham,  when  Abraham  saw  men  and  asked  them  to  dine  with 
him.  You  will  say,  surely  all  the  Apostles  believed  that  Christ  had 
risen  from  the  dead  and  in  truth  ascended  into  heaven  ;  which  I  deny 
not.  For  Abraham  likewise  believed  that  God  had  dined  with  him, 
and  all  Israel  believed  that  God  had  come  down  from  heaven  in  fire 
to  Mount  Sinai  and  spoken  to  them  in  his  proper  person  ;  whereas 
these  and  sundry  other  matters  of  the  like  sort  were  appearances  or 
revelations  adapted  to  the  capacity  and  conceit  of  the  men  to  whom 
God  was  minded  thereby  to  reveal  his  counsel.  I  conclude  there- 
fore that  the  resurrection  of  Christ  from  the  dead  was  in  truth  spiritual, 
revealed  only  to  the  faithful,  and  to  them  after  their  capacity  ;  con- 
sisting in  this,  that  Christ  was  gifted  with  eternity  and  rose  from  the 
dead  (the  dead,  I  mean,  in  that  sense  in  which  Christ  said  :  let  the 
dead  bury  their  dead),  in  that  by  his  life  and  death  he  gave  a  singular 
example  of  holiness ;  and  he  raises  his  disciples  from  the  dead  in  so 
much  as  they  follow  this  example  of  his  life  and  death.  And  it  were 
no  hard  matter  to  explain  the  whole  doctrine  of  the  Gospel  accord- 
ing to  this  hypothesis.  Nay,  the  fifteenth  chapter  of  the  first  Epistle 
to  the  Corinthians  can  be  explained  by  no  other,  or  Paul's  arguments 
understood,  for  on  the  common  hypothesis  they  are  evidently  weak 
and  may  be  confuted  with  little  pains  \  not  to  mention  that  in 
general  the  Christians  have  interpreted  spiritually  what  the  Jews  have 
interpreted  materially.' 


368  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Oldenburg  again  rejoins  that  the  narrative  of  the  passion 
and  resurrection  is  continuous,  lively,  and  circumstantial,  and 
cannot  be  taken  otherwise  than  literally  throughout.  Spinoza 
replies  (Ep.  25)  by  repeating  his  opinion  yet  more  explicitly. 

'With  you  I  take  the  passion,  death  and  burial  of  Christ 
literally,  but  his  resurrection  I  take  allegorically.  I  admit  that  this 
also  is  told  by  the  Evangelists  with  such  circumstances  as  that  we 
cannot  deny  that  the  Evangelists  themselves  believed  Christ's  body  to 
have  risen  and  ascended  into  heaven,  there  to  sit  on  the  right  hand 
of  God ;  and  that  he  might  have  been  seen  by  unbelievers,  had  any 
such  been  in  the  places  where  Christ  appeared  to  his  disciples  :  but 
in  this  they  might  well  be  mistaken  without  prejudice  to  the  Gospel 
doctrine,  as  happened  to  other  prophets  also,  whereof  I  have  given 
instances  in  my  former  letters.  But  Paul,  to  whom  also  Christ 
appeared  afterwards,  boasts  that  he  knows  Christ  not  according  to 
the  flesh  but  according  to  the  spirit.' 

Oldenburg  was  not  content  with  this,  but  once  more  pro- 
tested (exactly  as  an  English  Broad  Churchman  might  now 
protest  if  he  fell  into  a  similar  correspondence  with  a  Dutch 
theologian  of  the  liberal  school)  that  the  literal  historical  fact 
of  the  Resurrection  is  the  indispensable  foundation  of  Chris- 
tianity. So  far  as  we  know,  he  had  the  last  word.  It  is  need- 
less to  dilate  on  the  wonderfully  modern  character  of  Spinoza's 
criticism  ;  it  speaks  for  itself. 

As  regards  the  practical  problem  of  religion  considered  as 
a  guide  of  life,  Spinoza  seems  to  make  a  distinction  between 
philosophers  and  the  majority.  For  Jthe  philosopher  religion 
is  acquiescence  in  the  order  of  nature,  with  the  delight  in 
knowledge  thereby  engendered,  and  living  a  righteous  life  at 
the  bidding  of  reason.  Questions  about  particular  revelations 
and  supernatural  narratives  are  for  him  nothing  else  than  his- 
torical and  critical  questions  of  more  or  less  interest  in  them- 
selves, but  not  affecting  the  conduct  of  life.  God  and  the 
world  stand  sure  for  him  without  miracles  or  prophecies.  But 
for  the  majority  religion  is  obedience  to  a  revealed  rule  ;  a 
rule  which  can  and  ought  to  be  reduced  to  the  simplest  terms, 


SPINOZA   AND   THEOLOGY.  369 

and  almost  or  entirely  freed  from  requirements  of  belief  in 
specific   supernatural    events.     And    it   is   pretty    clear   that 
Spinoza  is  not  only  describing  what  he  deems  practicable  for 
his  own  time,  but  deems  that  it  must  be  so  for  all  time.     Now 
that  we  have  come  to  regard  human  thought  as  the  result  of 
a  continuous  process  of  growth,  we  cannot  think  distinctions 
of  this  kind  maintainable.     We  cannot  hold  it  a  permanent 
necessity  of  human  nature,  however  inevitable  it  may  seem  for 
a  long  time  to  come,  that  there  should  be  one  creed  for  the 
few  and  another  or  others  for  the  many.     The  state  of  things 
contemplated  by  Spinoza  is  an  artificial  compromise  which 
could  not  last  even  in  the  most  favourable  conditions.    In  what 
manner  religion  will  be  transformed  in  the  future  we  cannot 
tell ;  whether  by  the  gradual  widening  and  purifying  of  exist- 
ing forms,  or  by  some  new  manifestation  of  individual  genius, 
or  by  the  diffused  working  of  strong  and  subtle  thought,  dis- 
solving forms  and  leaving  no  vocation  for  prophets.     It  has  ^ 
hitherto  been  the  aim  of  religions  to  fix  man's  ideal  in  life  once 
for  all.     We  now  find  that  man's  life  and  thought  will  not 
be  fixed,  that  our  ideals  themselves  are  shifting  and  changing 
shapes,  figures  of  '  the  shade  cast  by  the  soul  of  man.'     One 
after  another  the  advancing  tide  reaches  them,  rises  above 
them,  and  they  disappear.     Must  we  simply  acquiesce  in  this 
perpetual  flux  of  our  aspirations }  or  may  we  suppose  that 
some  new  form  will  emerge  which,  if  not  absolutely  permanent, 
may  be  as  constant  for  us  and  our  children  as  the  ideals  of 
bygone  generations  were  for  them  .-*     It  is  conceivable,  as  it 
once  seemed  in  a  kind  of  vision  to  the  clear-headed  and  truth- 
loving  friend  to  whose  memory  I  have  dedicated  this  book, 
that  the  sense  of  natural  law  might  become  an  organic  intui- 
tion and  fill  the  world  with  a  new  beauty  that  would  leave  no 
room  for  questioning  ;  or,  to  express  it  in  Spinoza's  language, 
that  the  '  intellectual  love  of  God  '  should  become  a  constant 
power  and  delight  in  the  daily  life  of  our  successors.     It  is 
not  long  since  a  leader  in  science  uttered  in  a  scientific  meet- 

B  B 


370  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

ing  the  hope  that  one  day,  through  the  continued  evolution 
of  human  powers,  '  hght  may  stream  in  upon  the  darkness, 
and  reveal  to  man  the  great  mystery  of  thought.'  Of  this  also, 
if  we  may  not  now  say  that  it  will  be,  we  must  not  say  that  it 
will  not  be.  Difficulties  one  can  see  with  ease  ;  and  it  is  al- 
vvays  unlikely  that  the  first  expression  of  a  great  hope  should 
closely  correspond  to  the  fulfilment.  But  difficulties  are  made  ^ 
to  beget  daring,  not  to  nourish  despair.  Such  visions  and 
hopes  as  these  are  not  to  be  lightly  deemed  of,  shadowy 
though  they  may  appear.  For  men  will  not  seek  without  high 
longings  ;  and  if  seeking  they  find  not  what  their  imagination 
longed  for,  still  they  find,  and  the  search  itself  is  worthy. 

But  howsoever  light  is  to  come,  or  we  are  to  be  enlightened 
to  see  it,  no  cry  or  complaint  will  hasten  it :  we  must  work 
and  wait,  but  above  all  work.  Least  of  all  must  we  listen  to 
those  who  would  entreat  or  command  us  to  go  backward  in- 
stead of  forward.  Neither  the  stars  in  their  courses  nor  the 
working  of  man's  thought  will  go  back  for  any  man's  word, 
or  for  prayers,  or  for  threatenings.  To  those  who  have  not 
the  temper  of  intellectual  enterprise,  whose  feelings  are  indis- 
solubly  entwined  with  the  traditions  of  the  past,  and  who 
would  fain  recall  for  the  world  the  days  of  peaceful  belief,  we 
can  only  say,  sorrowing  for  them  but  steadfast  and  hopeful  for 
ourselves,  that  so  it  must  be.  But  to  those  who  chide  and  re- 
proach we  shall  show,  if  need  be,  a  bold  and  even  a  warlike 
front,  answering  to  their  denunciations  with  Haeckel :  Lnpavidi 
progrediaimir.  Science,  they  cry,  is  irreverent ;  she  has  laid 
hands  on  mysteries  and  made  the  world  profane  and  common. 
In  the  face  of  such  language  it  is  not  for  those  who  bear  the 
lamp  of  knowledge  to  apologize  and  speak  humbly.  They 
need  no  excuse  and  have  no  occasion  to  do  their  work  by  the 
good  leave  of  the  letter-worshippers  and  article-makers.  Nay, 
*  but  it  is  the  makers  of  articles  and  dogmas  who  are  irreverent. 
They  have  desecrated  the  glory  of  the  world  with  dark  habi- 


SPINOZA  AND   THEOLOGY.  371 

tations  and  dwellings  of  idols,  not  enduring  to  live  in  the  open 
light ;  and  when  their  tabernacles  are  broken  down,  and  the 
sun  in  his  strength  quells  at  last  the  unclean  fumes  of  their 
censers  and  their  sacrifices,  their  eyes  are  blinded  with  that 
splendour,  and   they  cry   out  that   the  world    is   darkened. 
Coittaininata  est  in  operibtis  eoriim,  et  fornicati  sunt  in  adinven- 
tionihis  siiis.     Reverence  will  never  be  wanting  from  those 
who  study  nature  with  a  whole  heart  ;  reverence  for  the  truth 
of  things,  and  for  all  good  work  and  love  of  the  truth  in  man. 
And  for  the  great  leaders  of  men  who  have  conquered  them 
not  with  the  sword  but  with  the  spirit,  who,  seeing  above  their 
fellows  what  man's  life  is  and  might  be,  have  given  their  own 
lives  to  make  it  worthier,  for  these  chiefly  shall  our  reverence 
be  unfailing.     Whether  such  an  one  was  named  among  his 
people  Socrates  the  son  of  Sophroniscus,  or  Gautama  who  is 
called  the  Buddha,  or  Jesus  who  is  called  the  Christ,  he  shall 
have  endless  honour  and  worship  of  free  men,  and  not  least  of 
those  who  have  learnt  most  from  Spinoza  for  their  thoughts 
of  man  and  the  world. 

Forward,  then,  we  must  ever  go,  finding  what  light  we 
may  ;  and  he  that  most  surely  finds  will  be  he  that  least  fears 
danger  and  loss.  The  old  Northern  tale  tells  how  Brynhild 
lay  on  the  enchanted  mountain,  cast  in  a  deep  sleep  and  clad 
in  mail  of  proof,  with  a  wall  of  fire  round  about  her.  But 
Sigurd  came  and  rode  through  the  fire,  and  cut  through  the 
armour,  and  delivered  her ;  for  he  was  fearless  of  heart,  and 
rode  Odin's  horse,  and  bare  Odin's  sword,  wherewith  he  had 
slain  the  worm  that  guarded  the  great  treasure.  And  now 
men,  being  afraid  to  look  on  the  living  face  of  truth,  have 
charmed  her  asleep  and,  for  that  she  was  not  strong  enough 
by  herself,  have  imprisoned  her  in  a  grievous  weight  of  armour, 
clothing  her  with  creeds,  and  confessions,  and  articles.  And 
the  great  and  deadly  serpent  Superstition,  bred  of  fear  and 
ignorance,  keeps  watch  on  the  treasure  of  knowledge.     Only 

b  15  2 


V 


372  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

he  who  has  slain  the  serpent  and  knows  not  fear  can  bestride 
Odin's  horse  and  ride  through  the  wall  of  fire  ;  only  he  who 
wields  Odin's  sword  can  draw  near  to  that  sleeping  might  and 
beauty,  and  sunder  the  stifling  links  of  mail,  and  show  the 
divine  face  to  men. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  373 


CHAPTER   XII. 

SPINOZA  AND   MODERN   THOUGHT. 

For  such  men  as  these  death  is  not  the  end  of  life.  They  live  on  in  our  remem- 
brance of  them  and  in  their  works.  Their  thought  animates  others  who  come  after 
them,  and  again  others  who  come  after  these.    Were  not  that  the  true  immortality  ? 

P.  A.  S.  VAN  LiMBURG  Brouwer  :  Akhar. 

I  saw  the  body  of  Wisdom,  and  of  shifting  guise  was  she  wrought, 

And  I  stretched  out  my  hands  to  hold  her,  and  a  mote  of  the  dust  they  caught ; 

And  I  pra)'ed  her  to  come  for  my  teaching,  and  she  came  in  the  midnight  dream  — 

And  I  woke  and  might  not  remember,  nor  betwixt  her  tangle  deem  : 

She  spake,  and  how  might  I  hearken  ?  I  heard,  and  how  might  I  know  ? 

I  knew,  and  how  might  I  fashion,  or  her  hidden  glory  show  ? 

WiLLiA.M  Morris  :  Sigurd  the  Vohimg. 

To  give  an  account  of  the  reception  and  fortunes  of  Spinoza's 
thought ;  to  trace  the  signs  of  its  acceptance  by  a  few  in  the 
time  when  it  was  for  the  most  part  rejected  with  indignation 
or  contempt  ;  to  follow  its  working  in  the  various  fields  of 
literature  and  speculation  where,  having  at  last  risen  to  the 
due  height  of  its  worth,  it  has  more  lately  made  itself  felt : — 
this  would  be  an  undertaking  equivalent,  if  fully  performed, 
to  writing  the  history  of  modern  philosophy.  We  should  not 
go  beyond  the  truth  in  saying  with  Auerbach,  one  of  those 
who  have  in  our  own  time  done  most  to  make  Spinoza's  work 
better  known  and  understood,  that  Spinoza's  mind  has  fed 
the  thoughts  of  two  centuries.  And  we  should  much  err  if  in 
considering  Spinoza's  influence  in  Europe  we  confined  our 
view  to  the  marks  which  his  system  has  left  in  the  formal 
theories  or  discussions  of  later  philosophers.  It  has  more 
than  once  been  remarked  that,  while  much  recent  philosoph}- 
is    in   divers  manners  and  degrees  pervaded  by  Spinozism, 


374  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

there  has  never  been  a  Spinozist  school  as  there  has  been  a 
Cartesian  and  a  Kantian  school.  The  truth  is  that  the 
strength  of  Spinozism  is  not  in  the  system  as  such,  but  in  its 
method  and  habit  of  mind.  Hostile  critics  have  attacked  the 
system  ever  since  it  was  made  known,  some  with  real  power, 
some  with  desperate  captiousness  ;  but  even  when  they  are 
successful  the  spirit  eludes  them.  Not  only  will  it  not  be 
driven  from  philosophy,  but  in  like  manner  it  works  its  way 
into  regions  where  formal  philosophy  is  unwelcome  or'  un- 
known. Religion  and  poetry  become  its  carriers  unawares, 
and  it  might  not  be  too  fanciful  to  trace  its  presence  even  in 
the  fine  arts.  It  is  more  or  less  true  of  every  great  philo- 
sopher, but  it  is  eminently  true  of  Spinoza,  that  the  history 
of  his  philosophy  is  interwoven  with  the  general  history  of 
culture.  What  has  been  written  about  Spinoza  or  directly 
adopted  from  him  represents  but  a  part  of  his  power  in  the 
world,  and  a  still  less  part  of  the  activity  and  power  of  the 
ideas  which  Spinoza  clearly  discerned  and  firmly  grasped 
when  they  were  as  yet  too  hard  even  for  strong  men. 

All  that  I  can  attempt  here  is  to  show  in  outline  how  it 
has  fared  with  Spinoza's  philosophy  in  the  world  of  science 
and  letters  down  to  our  own  time.  The  reader  who  is  curious 
enough  in  the  matter  to  wish  for  critical  and  bibliographical 
information  will  find  references  in  the  introductory  chapter 
which  may  help  him  to  seek  further  for  himself.  We  may 
conveniently  begin,  as  we  shall  have  to  end,  with  Spinoza's 
own  country.  The  first  effect  of  his  writings  in  Holland  was 
to  raise  a  storm  of  controversial  indignation,  chiefly  against 
the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  ; '  not  that  it  was  more 
obnoxious  to  orthodox  criticism  than  the  'Ethics,'  but  it  had 
more  general  and  practical  interest.  Books  and  pamphlets 
were  poured  forth  in  abundance  by  writers  of  various  degrees 
of  notoriety  and  ability,  and  were  esteemed  at  the  time — so 
at  least  we  are  told  by  Colerus,  who  gives  the  titles  of  several 
of  them — to  have  accomplished  the  refutation  of  Spinoza  with 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  375 

all  the  success  that  could  be  desired.     I  suppose  there  is  no- 
body now  living  who  has  read  them  ;  and  perhaps  there  is  no 
enormous  presumption  in  suspecting  that  the  reading  of  them 
would  not  now  be  found  profitable,  though  it  might  possibly 
be  amusing  now  and  then.     This  zeal  for  refuting  the  blasphe- 
mous, atheistic,  deceitful,  soul-destroying  works  of  Spinoza — 
such  were  the  epithets  with  which  the  authors  garnished  their 
arguments,  in  the  usual  taste  of  the  time — was  by  no  means 
confined  to  the  theological  faculty.     Several  of  these  writers 
were  laymen  ;  at  least  one,   Spinoza's   correspondent  Blyen- 
bergh,  had  no  pretension  to  be  a  scholar.     Medicine  produced 
its  champions  too.     The  Jewish  physician  Isaac  Orobio  was 
in  the  field  in  good  time  with  a  tract  against  Spinoza  and  his 
apologists  ;  and  Dr.  Bontekoe,  in  the  course  of  an  extremely 
quaint  work  on  the  numberless  virtues  of  tea,  published  only 
two  years  after  Spinoza's  death,  took  occasion  emphatically 
to    renounce    Spinozism.     Some    one   had    accused    him,    it 
appears,  of  atheism.     *  I  will  one  day  show  the   world,'   he 
exclaims,  '  what  sort  of  an  atheist  I  am,  when   I  refute  the 
godless  works  of  Spinoza,  and  likewise  those  of  Hobbes  and 
Machiavelli,  three  of  the  most  cursed  villains  that  ever  walked 
this  earth.' '     The  variety  of  Dr.  Bontekoe's  other  pursuits 
and  quarrels  (which  were  many)  appears  to  have  prevented 
him  from  fulfilling  this  rather  comprehensive   promise.     It 
happened  afterwards,  curiously  enough,  that  the  career  of  the 
greatest  of  Dutch   physicians,  and  the  leader  of  European 
medicine  in  his  time,  was  in  a  manner  determined   by  the 
blind  fury  of  orthodox  company  against  Spinoza.     Blind  it 
was  in  the  particular  case  at  least,  as  the  story  will  show. 
Boerhaave  was  in  his  youth  intended  for  the  ministry.     While 
he  was  a  theological  student,  he  was  travelling  one  day  with 
a  person  who  abused  Spinoza  in  violent  language,  something 
like  Dr.  Bontekoe's,    we  may  suppose.     Boerhaave,  though 

•  Tractaat  van  het  excellenste  Kruyd  Thee  &c.    In's  Gravenhage,  mdci.xxix, 
P-  349,  cp.  p.  199. 


376  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

himself  no  follower  of  Spinoza,  could  not  refrain  from  asking 
the  speaker  if  he  had  read  any  of  Spinoza's  writings.  This 
was  enough  to  fasten  on  Boerhaave  the  name  of  Spinozist : 
and  accordingly  he  betook  himself  to  medicine,  seeing  him- 
self cut  off  from  all  prospect  of  advancement  in  the  Church.' 
Only  one  writer,  so  far  as  we  know,  Abraham  Cuffeler,  had 
the  courage  to  stand  forth  in  open  defence  of  the  '  Ethics.'  ^ 

So  many  were  the  refuters  of  Spinoza  that  before  long 
they  fell  out  among  themselves,  and  two  or  three  of  them 
incurred  the  suspicion  of  being  no  better  than  Spinozists  in 
disguise.     Such  accusations  are  familiar  in  theological  con- 
troversy, the  more  zealous  champions  seeing  an  enemy    in 
every  one  who   fails  to  go  all  lengths  with  them  ;  and  the 
grounds  were  probably  as  slight  in  this  case  as  they  generally 
are.     At  the  same  time  undoubted  manifestations  of  Spino- 
zism  arose  within   a  generation  after  Spinoza's  death  in  the 
most  unexpected  quarter,  the  Reformed  Church  of  the  Nether- 
lands itself.     The  local  disturbance  produced  by  the  move- 
ment was  considerable  ;  and  it  is  said  that  traces  of  it  remain 
even  now   in  small  isolated  societies  who  find  their  spiritual 
comfort  in  mystical  doctrines  once  formally  condemned  by 
the  church  as  Spinozistic  heresies.     One  of  the  first  leaders 
was  Pontiaan  van  Hattem  of  Bergen-op-Zoom,  whose  works 
soon  acquired  fame  enough  for   Hattemist  and    Hattemism 
to  become  current  terms  of  vituperation.     Van  Hattem  had 
several  disciples  of  more  or  less  note,  among  whom  we  may 
here  mention  the  female  enthusiast  Dinah  Jans,  and  Jacob 
Bril,  who  pushed  his  master's  mysticism  to  extremes.     Pro- 
bably the  movement  came  at  this  stage  under  the  influence 
of  Bohme  and    the    earlier  German  mystics ;    and  we  must 
remember,    as    M.    Janet  has  pointed  out,  that  apart   from 

'  H.  J.  Betz,  Lcvensschc/s  van  Baruch  dc  Spinoza,  (The  Hague,  1876),  p.  25; 
Van  der  Aa,  Biographisch  Woordenboek  der  Nederlanden,  s.v.  Boerhaave.  It 
appears  that  he  had  actually  disputed  against  Spinoza  in  an  academical  thesis. 

=  Specimen  artis  ratiocinandi,  (S;c.,  1684,  \'an  der  Linde,  Bibliograjie, 
nos.  151a,  151/',  \^\c. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  377 

Spinoza's  writing  a  certain  mystical  and  pantheistic  tendency 
already  existed  in  the  theology  of  the  Low  Countries.  Car- 
tesianism,  too,  had  its  mystical  developments.  But  the 
original  connexion  of  Hattemism  with  Spinoza  seems  to  be 
free  from  doubt.  Hattemism,  in  fact,  was  an  exaggeration  of 
Spinozism  on  its  apparently  mystical  side.  Faith  was  defined 
as  the  knowledge  of  man's  absolute  union  with  Christ,  who  is 
God  conceived  in  his  full  perfection,  to  which  this  union  be- 
longs ;  while  the  foundation  of  sin  is  the  error  of  regarding 
God's  being  as  separate  from  or  opposed  to  that  of  man. 
The  true  Christian  is  the  man  who  has  attained  beatitude 
by  the  consciousness  of  this  identity.  Evil  is  regarded,  with 
Spinoza,  as  a  negative  and  relative  conception  ;  nay,  the  sin 
against  the  Holy  Ghost  is  explained  to  consist  in  attributing 
any  positive  existence  to  evil  and  sin.  Van  Hattem's  only 
criticism  on  Spinoza  was  that  he  arrived  at  his  results  by 
speculation  instead  of  finding  them  in  Scripture.  His  doc- 
trines were  elaborately  condemned  in  a  kind  of  official 
syllabus  by  the  ecclesiastical  authorities  of  Middelburg. 
Part  of  the  declaration  required  of  suspected  persons  ran  as 
follows :  *  Especially  I  renounce  the  doctrine  taught  by  P. 
van  Hattem  in  his  writings,  and  account  the  same  blasphe- 
mous and  soul-destroying.  I  testify  that  I  hold  in  abomina- 
tion these  Spinozistic  opinions,  in  what  words  or  language 
soever  they  may  be  expressed.'  At  the  same  place,  and  I 
presume  at  or  about  the  same  time,  a  number  of  anonymous 
works  were  burnt  by  order  of  the  authorities  of  Middelburg  as 
being  '  full  of  the  abominable  and  blasphemous  sentiments 
of  the  Libertines,  modern  Spinozists,  Hattemists,  and  Free- 
thinkers.' ^  Another  conspicuous  figure  in  this  episode  ap- 
pearing somewhat  later  than  Van  Hattem  is  Frederick  van 
Leenhof,  a  minister  of  Zwolle.  His  offence  consisted  in  the 
publication  of  a  book  entitled  '  Heaven  on  Earth  ;  or  a  short 
and  clear  account  of  true  and  constant  blessedness '  (1703)  ; 
'  Van  der  Linde,  no.  169,  note.     This  was  in  1714. 


378  SPINOZA  :'  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

which  was  in  fact  an  attempt  to  construct  a  rationalized  system 
of  Christian  ethics  embodying  most  of  Spinoza's  doctrines- 
Leenhof  accepts  from  Spinoza  not  only  determinism  (in  itself 
an  orthodox  doctrine  enough)  but  the  ethical  condemnation  of 
sorrow  and  all  passions  involving  it.  He  expressly  adopted 
Spinoza's  definition  of  pleasure,  and  justified  this  in  an  apolo- 
getic work  on  the  ground  that  Spinoza's  ethical  definitions  were 
an  improvement  on  those  of  Descartes.  He  also  set  forth 
in  language  closely  copied  from  Spinoza's  the  doctrine  that 
painful  feelings  cease  to  be  painful  in  so  far  as  we  form 
adequate  ideas  of  them  and  contemplate  them  as  part  of  the 
eternal  order  of  the  world.  Withal  he  steadily  protested  that 
his  opinions  were  not  amenable  to  the  charge  of  heterodoxy  ; 
but  the  authorities  of  the  Reformed  Church  thought  other- 
wise, and  continued  to  denounce  the  Leenhoffian  heresy  all 
through  the  eighteenth  century. 

For  the  rest,  this  theological  strife  in  the  Netherlands  had 
no  effect,  so  far  as  appears,  on  the  knowledge  or  criticism  of 
Spinoza's  doctrine  elsewhere  :  and  it  was  soon  so  much  for- 
gotten that  it  escaped  the  notice  even  of  historians  of  philo- 
sophy till,  towards  the  beginning  of  the  most  recent  period  of 
Spinozistic  criticism,  it  was  opportunely  brought  to  light  by  Dr. 
van  der  Linde  in  a  monograph  which  he  has  since  corrected  and 
completed  in  certain  particulars  in  his  Bibliography  of  Spinoza. 
The  light  he  now  throws  upon  this  episode  makes  no  direct 
addition  to  our  understanding  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  ;  but 
it  is  interesting  to  know  that  the  immediate  effect  of  his  work 
was  so  much  greater  than  had  been  supposed.  I  do  not  know 
how  far  Spinoza  may  have  been  similarly  taken  up  by  readers 
of  a  mystic  turn  at  other  times  and  places.  An  attempt  has 
been  made  to  show  that  Swedenborg,  the  most  illustrious  of 
modern  mystics,  borrowed  considerably  from  him.  On  this 
ground,  however,  nothing  is  more  deceptive  than  general  re- 
semblances.' 

'  See  Van  der  Linde,  no.  331  ;  R.  Willis,  Benedict  dc  SfincTO,  p.  187, 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT,  379 

Let  us  turn  to  the  reception  of  Spinoza's  work  by  the 
larger  world  of  European  thought.     It  is  quite  possible  to  ex- 
aggerate the  neglect  of  it  which  prevailed  for  about  a  century 
after  his  death  ;  it  is  quite  possible  also  to  exaggerate  the 
misunderstanding  which  accompanied  and  partly  caused  this 
neglect.     Spinoza  was  rejected,  but  never  forgotten ;  and  re- 
jected not  so   much  because  his  ideas  were  wrongly  appre- 
hended as  because  few  of  his  readers  were  educated  up  to 
the  point  of  tolerating  them.     The  rejection,  however,  was 
complete.     Spinoza   was  for  the  time  thrown  clean  out  of 
the  stream  of  European  speculation,  and  philosophers  in  all 
countries  went  their  way  without  taking  any  serious  account 
of  him.     A  variety  of  circumstances  combined  to  produce  this 
result.    First  and  most  obvious  is  the  enmity  of  orthodox  theo- 
logians of  all  denominations.     But  Spinoza  had  also  incurred 
the  hatred  of  the  philosophical  pai:ty  which,  itself  recently 
under  the  ban  of  the  churches,  had   now  won  for  itself  a  re- 
spectable position,  and  in  many  seats  of  learning  was  supreme. 
The  Cartesians  could  never  forgive  Spinoza  for  his  indepen- 
dence.    To  have  improved  on  Descartes  and  gone  the  length 
of  openly  contradicting  him  was  in  their  eyes  the  worst  heresy 
of  all.     On  the  other  hand,  the  affinities  of  Spinozism  were 
plain  enough  to  give  a  handle  for  ugly-sounding  accusations 
of  Descartes'  teaching  in  its  tendency  if  not  in  its  actual  con- 
tents :  and  thus  it   became  almost  necessary  for  Cartesians, 
anxious  to  vindicate  their  new-fledged  orthodoxy,  to  be  zealous 
in  denouncing  this  strange  growth  which  seemed  to  many  to 
be  of  their  own  stock.     Spinoza's  philosophy  had  to  contend 
with  the  whole  weight  of  the  Cartesian  school  as  well  as  with 
the  power  of  the  churches.     There  was  one  man  who  perhaps 
had  the  power,  if  the  will  had  been  present,  of  doing  justice 
to  Spinoza  and  seeing  it  done  by  others.     Leibnitz  was  cer- 
tainly capable  of  understanding   Spinoza  ;  he  had  held  cor- 
respondence with  him,  seen  and  talked  with  him.     We  know 
that  he  read  his  writings  with  some  care.     His  own  philoso- 


38o  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

phical  conceptions  were  probably  fixed  before  they  could  have 
been  much  affected  by  anything  in  Spinoza's  :  but  a  seri- 
ous recognition  of  Spinoza's  importance  by  Leibnitz,  however 
much  criticism  had  accompanied  it,  would  have  made  it  im- 
possible for  Spinoza  to  be  treated  with  contempt. 

Leibnitz,  however,  not  only  failed  to  do  justice  to  Spinoza, 
but  encouraged  injustice.  It  is  difficult  to  believe  that  his  con- 
duct in  this  matter  was  sincere.  The  references  to  Spinoza  in 
his  published  works  are  in  a  tone  of  systematic  deprecia- 
tion. It  was  Leibnitz  who  started  the  shallow  dictum,  since 
repeated  and  expanded  by  many  imitators,  that  Spinoza  did 
nothing  but  cultivate  some  of  the  seed  sown  by  Descartes. 
His  personal  intercourse  with  Spinoza,  which  could  not  be 
denied,  is  extenuated  as  much  as  possible.  But  in  general 
Spinoza  is  simply  ignored,  even  where  one  would  most  expect 
to  find  reference  to  him,  as  in  the  theory  of  pre-established 
harmony.  Not  that  I  can  regard  the  pre-established  harmony 
of  Leibnitz  as  borrowed  from  Spinoza.^  But  when  Leibnitz 
is  professedly  reviewing  the  various  attempts  already  made 
to  explain  the  relation  of  mind  and  matter,  it  is  surprising  to 
find  all  mention  of  Spinoza's  theory  omitted.  There  would 
be  no  great  cause  for  surprise  if  the  theory  vv^ere  mentioned 
without  Spinoza's  name  ;  that  would  be  only  in  the  manner 
of  the  time.  But  the  omission  is  total,  and  cannot  well  be 
an  accident.  Then  Leibnitz's  saying  already  quoted,  and  still 
more,  his  other  epigrammatic  judgment  that  '  Spinoza  begins 
where  Descartes  ends,  in  naturalism,'  have  very  much  the  air 
of  being  ingeniously  contrived  to  disparage  in  one  breath 
Spinoza  for  having  only  developed  the  philosophy  of  Descartes, 
and  the  philosophy  of  Descartes  for  being  capable  of  such  a 
development.  They  point  the  way  to  the  charitable  senti- 
ment uttered  in  perfect  good  faith  by  a  modern  French  writer 
after  a  careful  study  of  both  systems :  '  Let  us  forgive  Descartes 
for  having  raised  up  Spinoza ! '     Whether  Leibnitz  had  the 

'  See  p.  192  above. 


SPINOZA  AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  381 

deliberate  intention  of  exalting  his  own  originality  at  Spinoza's 
expense,  or  was  misled  by  an  unconscious  bias,  it  is  certain 
that  his  action  had  a  considerable  share  in  keeping  Spinoza 
out  of  his  rightful  place.  So,  as  we  have  said,  philosophy 
went  its  way  without  giving  ear  to  Spinoza,  and  sunk  in  the 
hands  of  Leibnitz's  successors  into  dogmatic  formalism. 

Meanwhile  a  new  school  was  arising  in  England  who 
might  possibly  have  recognized  in  Spinoza's  teaching  the 
voice  of  a  friend  if  not  of  a  master.  But  it  fell  out  otherwise. 
The  English  philosophical  school  grew  up  in  perfect  inde- 
pendence, and  perhaps  it  was  better  so.  Locke,  Berkeley, 
Hume  all  make  some  little  mention  of  Spinoza  ;  but  in  every 
case  it  is  so  slight  and  desultory  as  to  show  plainly  that  they 
had  never  thought  of  Spinoza  as  a  writer  deserving  to  be 
seriously  considered.  Locke  brackets  him  with  Hobbes  in 
loose  condemnation  as  'those  justly  decried  authors.'  Berkeley 
speaks  of  '  those  wild  imaginations  of  Vanini,  Hobbes,  and 
Spinoza  ; '  and  of  '  modern  Atheism,  be  it  of  Hobbes,  Spinoza, 
Collins,  or  whom  you  will : '  and  he  seems  to  have  accepted 
the  popular  view  of  Spinozism  as  a  merely  formal  system. 
The  following  passage  from  '  Alciphron  '  (Seventh  Dialogue, 
§  29,  Works,  ii.  334,  ed.  Eraser)  is  worth  quoting : — 

*  I  have  heard,  said  I,  Spinosa  represented  as  a  man  of  close 
argument- and  demonstration. 

*  He  did,  replied  Crito,  demonstrate  ;  but  it  was  after  such  a 
manner  as  one  may  demonstrate  anything.  Allow  a  man  the 
privilege  to  make  his  own  definitions  of  common  words,  and  it  will 
be  no  hard  matter  for  \\\m.  to  infer  conclusions  which  in  one  sense 
shall  be  true  and  in  another  false,  at  once  seeming  paradoxes  and 
manifest  truisms.  For  example,  let  but  Spinosa  define  natural  right 
to  be  natural  power,  and  he  will  easily  demonstrate  that  '  whatever  a 
man  can  do  '  he  hath  a  right  to  do.  Nothing  can  be  plainer  than  the 
folly  of  this  proceeding  :  but  our  pretenders  to  the  lumen  siccum  are 
so  passionately  prejudiced  against  religion,  as  to  swallow  the  grossest 
nonsense  and  sophistry  of  weak  and  wicked  writers  for  demonstra- 
tion.' 


382  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

It  appears,  however,  that  Berkeley  had  really  read  Spinoza ; 
which  is  more  than  can  be  said  of  either  Locke  or  Hume.  It 
is  possible  that  Locke,  taking  the  general  Continental  estimate 
on  trust,  set  down  Spinoza  as  a  kind  of  erratic  Cartesian  ; 
and  we  know  that  from  Cartesianism  in  any  form  he  expected 
no  solid  profit.  As  to  Hume,  Professor  Huxley  has  pointed 
out  that  he  was  pretty  uniformly  indolent  in  making  himself 
acquainted  with  philosophical  literature  even  on  points  that 
immediately  concerned  his  work.  If  he  ever  did  take  up 
Spinoza,  it  is  unlikely  that  he  had  the  patience  to  pierce 
through  the  rind  of  definitions  and  axioms.  Indeed  it  has 
been  the  common  fate  of  many  readers  and  critics  of  Spinoza 
to  stick  fast  in  the  First  Part  of  the  Ethics.  But  it  is  also 
possible  that  if  Hume  had  looked  far  enough  into  Spinoza  to 
find  other  things  more  to  his  mind,  as  would  have  been,  for 
example,  the  appendix  on  Final  Causes,  and  the  pitiless  on- 
slaughts made  in  various  places  of  the  Ethics  on  the  current 
logical  doctrines  of  universals  and  the  like,  he  would  not  have 
cared  to  leave  any  evidence  of  it  in  his  work.  The  open 
defence  of  opinions  commonly  reprobated  was  not  at  all  con- 
sistent with  his  attitude  of  pure  scepticism.  Besides,  to  profess 
any  particular  interest  in  Spinoza  was  at  that  time  equivalent 
to  throwing  oneself  into  the  troubled  waters  of  theological  and 
sectarian  polemics,  which  was  exactly  what  Hume  wanted  to 
avoid. 

For  the  misapprehension  of  Spinoza's  philosophical  im- 
portance was  not  only  consistent  with  his  making  a  great  stir 
in  the  theological  department  of  the  world  of  letters,  but  was 
to  a  great  extent  the  natural  consequence  of  the  repulsion 
excited  by  the  theological  bearings  of  his  doctrine.  Divines 
filled  with  horror  at  the  impious  writer  who  denied  an  extra- 
mundane  Deity,  final  causes,  and  free  will,  Iwd  not  the  time  or 
temper  to  examine  his  contributions  to  the  science  of  human 
nature.  Moreover,  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  '  had 
already  made  it  impossible  for  the  '  Ethics  '  to  be  fairly  dealt 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN   THOUGHT.  383 

with.     We  have  already  seen  how  it  was   received  in  the 
Netherlands  when  it  first  appeared.     In  England  it  does  not 
seem  to  have  been  much  known  till  some  time  after  Spinoza's 
death;  though  as  early  as  1678  Cudworth  gave  a  contemp- 
tuous paragraph  to  it  in  his  '  True  Intellectual  System  of  the 
Universe  '  (p.  707).     Cudworth  declares  that  '  as  for  that  late 
theological  politician  '  who  contended  that  '  a  miracle  is  no- 
thing but  a  name  which  the  ignorant  vulgar  gives  to  opus 
iiatiircB  insolituni,  any  unwonted  work  of  nature,  or  to  what 
themselves   can  assign  no   cause  of,'  he  finds   his  discourse 
'  every  way  so  weak,  groundless,  and  inconsiderable,  as  not 
to  deserve  a  confutation.'       A  translation  was  published  in 
1689,  not  very  elegantly  written,  and   not  disclosing  either 
the  translator's  or  the  author's  name.     Either  in  this  form 
or  in  the  original  Latin  the  treatise  must  have  obtained  a 
good   deal   of   currency,  as  in  1697  we   find    one    Matthias 
Earbery  coming  forward  to  demolish    it  with   more   valour 
than  wisdom  ('  Deism  examin'd  and  confuted  in  an  answer 
to  a  book  intitled,  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  ').    Earbery 
admits  with  a  sort  of  apology  that  Spinoza  had  some  scholar- 
ship.    '  Nor  am  I  ignorant,'  he  says  in  his  Preface,  '  that  the 
author  of  this  book  was  very  well  versed  (pardon  the  expres- 
sion) in  the  writings  of  Moses  and  the  Prophets.'     But  he 
soon  makes  up  for  any  excess  of  civility  he  may  have  been 
guilty  of :  '  I  thought  it  would  be  at  least  some  punishment, 
as  it  were,  to  the  very  shades  and  Manes  of  this  author  to 
show  the  world  that  he,  who  so  long  has  found  a  place  in 
the  libraries  and  hands  of  very  learned  men,  has  scarce  for 
his  stupidity,  and  trifling  way  of  arguing,  merit  to  obtain  a 
place   amongst  the   lowest   forms    of  inferior   animals.'     In 
course  of  time  other  champions  of  weightier  metal  attacked 
the  '  Ethics  '  also,  but  still  in  distinctly  theological  interests. 
John  Howe,  a  great  light  of  English  nonconformity,  devoted 
a  chapter  of  his  book,  '  The  Living  Temple,'  to  '  animadver- 
sions on  Spinoza.'    His  refutation  of  Spinoza's  metaphysical 


384  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

principles  is  a  fair  specimen  of  the  dry  and  windy  jangling 
over  verbal  definitions  which  then  passed  muster  for  philoso- 
phical discussion  with  the  help  of  the  reader's  foregone  con- 
clusion.    No  doubt  it  was  much  esteemed  at  the  time,  and 
maybe  so  still  by  readers  who  are  able  to  reproduce  in  them- 
selves the  mental  condition  of  Howe's  original  audience.     He 
never  gets  beyond  the  definitions  of  Substance  and  Attribute, 
and  shows  no   sign    of  really  understanding  Spinoza.     My 
own  impression  is  that  he  had  not  so  much  as  read  beyond 
the  First  Part.     But  the  most  serious  and  capable  polemic 
against  Spinoza  was  that  of  Clarke  in  his  Boyle  Lectures, 
otherwise  known  as  the  Discourse  concerning  the  Being  and 
Attributes  of  God.     He  is  little  more  courteous,  if  at  all, 
than    Earbery   and    Howe.     Spinoza   is    described    as   '  the 
most  celebrated  patron  of  atheism  in  our  time  ; '  his  *  vanity, 
folly,  and  weakness  '  are  exposed  ;  and  his  argument  against 
final  causes  is  dismissed  as  hardly  fit  to  be  gravely  refuted  : 
'  I    suppose  it  will    not  be  thought  that  when   once  a  man 
comes  to  this  he  is  to  be  disputed  with  any  longer.'     It  is 
nevertheless  clear  from  the  prominence  given  to  Spinoza,  as 
to  Hobbes,  that  Clarke  practically  thought  both  of  them  more 
formidable  than  he  was  willing  to  admit.     Clarke's  criticism 
turns  on  the  conception  of  Substance,  the  doctrine  of  final 
causes  (on  which,  as  just  mentioned,  he  is  curt  and  super- 
cilious), and    free  will.'     The  Discourse  was  translated  into 
French  in   17 17,  and  into  Dutch  as  late  as  1793,  I  presume 
as  a  counterblast  to  the  German  revival  of  Spinozism.^     A 
less    famous    divine,    by    name    Brampton    Gurdon,  likewise 
formally  attacked  Spinoza  in  a  later  series  of  Boyle  Lectures, 
in  1 72 1  and  1722.     '  Spinoza,' says  Mr.  Gurdon,  'is  the  only 
person  among  the  modern  Atheists,  that  has  pretended  to  give 
us  a  regular  scheme  of  Atheism  ;  and  therefore  I  cannot  act 

'  Cp.  L.  Stephen,  English  Thought  in  the  Eighteenth  Century,     120  ;  and  as 
to  Toland,  ib.  104. 

'  Van  der  Linde,  Bibliogr.  nos.  292,  293. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  385 

unfairly  in  making  him  the  representative  of  their  party.'  Two 
whole  sermons  and  several  passages  in  others  are  given  to 
demolishing  so  much  of  Spinoza's  philosophy  as  is  supposed 
by  the  preacher  to  be  still  in  need  of  demolition. 

Unorthodox  writers,  as  a  rule,  either  neglected  or  affected 
to  neglect    Spinoza   for   reasons   which    may   easily   be   di- 
vined.    Toland,  however,  speaks  of  him  with  considerable 
respect,    and    justifies    himself    for    so   doing.       Criticizing 
Spinoza's    physics,    which    he    seems    to   have    understood 
very  superficially,  as  '  undigested  and  unphilosophical,'  Toland 
maintains  his  right  to  say  that  '  yet  Spinoza  was  for  all  that 
a  great  and  good  man  in  many  respects,  as  may  not  only  be 
seen  by  his  works,  but  also  by  the  account  of  his  life  since 
that  time  publish'd  by  Colerus,  a  Lutheran  minister,  though  as 
contrary  to  some  of  his  sentiments  as  any  man  breathing.' 
Such  language  from  Toland  would  only  confirm   Spinoza's 
general  reputation  as  an  atheist  of  the  worst  kind,  or  perhaps 
a  deist  (it  mattered  little  which),  among  orthodox   readers. 
The  popular  judgment  of  the  religious  world  on  him  is  given 
with  amusing  crudeness  in  a  little  dictionary  of  religions  and 
sects,  for  the  most  part  written  with  fairness  and  moderation, 
which  was  published  about  the  beginning  of  this  century  and 
went  through  many  editions.     In  this  book  we  read   under 
the  head  of  Atheism,  that  '  Spinoza,  a  foreigner,  was  its  noted 
defender.'     So  far  as  I  know,  there  was   no  serious  philoso- 
phical  consideration    of  Spinoza    in    England    until    it   was 
brought   in    by    Coleridge    along  with    his  general  stock    of 
German  literature  and  philosophy.     Thus  the  modern  study 
of  Spinoza  in  England  depends  ultimately  on  the  restoration 
of  his  fame    by    Lessing   in    Germany,   of  which    wc   have 
presently  to  speak. 

Meanwhile  we  must  turn  to  the  fortunes  of  Spinoza  in 
France  ;  on  which  ground  the  reader  who  wishes  for  more 
detail  than  we  can  here  give  will  find  an  excellent  guide  in 
M.  Paul   Janet.     Refutations  of  Spinoza  were  prepared    by 

C  C 


336  SPIiXOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

theologians    in    France  even  before  the  appearance    of  the 

*  Opera  Posthuma.'     Afterwards  Massillon  declaimed  against 
him  as  a  monster  of  impiety,  and  two  Cardinals,  De  Polignac 
and  De  Bernis,  published  versified  refutations  of  him,  the  one 
in  Latin,  the  other  in  French  : '  De  Bernis's  performance  is 
commended  by  Ste.-Beuve  as  combining  vigour  with  discre- 
tion.    But  perhaps  the  two  cardinals  should  rather  count  as 
showing  that  the  name  of  Spinoza  was  the  centre  of  a  certain 
excitement  in  the  general  world   of  letters.     It  appears  on 
the  whole  that  Spinoza  was  more  written  and  talked  about  in 
France  than  in  England  during  the  eighteenth  century  ;  but 
he  was  no  less  completely  excluded  from  the  order  of  seriously 
recognized  philosophers.     As  in  this  country,  he  was  rejected 
v»dth  abhorrence  by  the  orthodox,  and,  with  few  exceptions, 
slighted  by  freethinking  writers.     Bayle  gave  a  long  article  to 
Spinoza  in  his  Dictionary,  which  is   a  curious   and  unequal 
mixture  of  anecdote,  gossip,  and  criticism.     Little  of  it  is  now 
of  any  value  ;  but  it  was  for  a  long  time  the  only  accessible 
and  comparatively  readable  account  of  Spinoza's  system.  The 
alleged  affinities  of  Spinozism  with  other  ancient  and  modern 
systems,  including  Sufism  and  Chinese  Buddhism  (known  to 
Bayle  and  his  authorities  as  Foe  Kiad)  are  traced  with  an 
enormous  display  of  learning.      Spinoza  is  called  an  atheist 
all  through,  and  the  philosophy  of   the  '  Opera  Posthuma ' 
"described  as  a  most  absurd  and   monstrous  theory,  contra- 
dictinsf  self-evident  truths.     It  is  surmised  that  most  French 
philosophers  of  the   eighteenth  century  had  no  other  know- 
ledge of  Spinoza  than  they  could  derive  from  this  article, 
which  was  closely  copied  by  Diderot  in  the  Encyclopaedia. 
Condillac,  in  his  '  Traite  de  Systemes,'  first  published  in  1749, 
criticizes  in  some  detail  the  First  Part  of  the  Ethics.     He 
thinks  Bayle's  criticism  superficial,  but   arrives    at   a  result 
quite  as  unfavourable  to  Spinoza.     He  writes  from  an  anti- 
metaphysical  point  of  view  and  under  the  geometrical  fallacy, 

•  Specimens  of  botli  are  quoied  in  Voltaire's  notes  to  his  poem,  Lcs  Systcvics, 


SPINOZA  AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  387 

if  I  may  so  call  it,  which  has  misled  so  many  of  Spinoza's  critics. 
Spinoza  is  treated  as  a  dogmatic  trifler  who  deceives  himself 
with  an  unintelligible  scholastic  jargon.  What  Condillac 
undertook  to  do  and  thought  he  had  done  was  (nearly  in  his 
own  words)  to  show  that  Spinoza  talked  about  things  of  which 
he  had  no  clear  conception,  that  his  definitions  are  loose,  his 
axioms  far  from  being  true,  his  propositions  fantastic  and 
barren.  He  challenges  the  followers  of  Spinoza — as  if  there 
was  at  that  time  supposed  to  be  some  considerable  number  of 
them — to  choose  between  abandoning  the  system  as  having 
no  real  meaning,  and  providing  a  distinct  explanation  of  the 
meaning  they  profess  to  find  in  it. 

Voltaire  discusses  Spinoza  more  or  less  deliberately  in 
various  places.  Of  his  person  he  speaks  with  high  respect ; 
in  the  criticism  of  his  philosophy  he  goes  in  the  main  with 
Bayle,  though  his  language  is  not  wholly  consistent.  Like 
Bayle,  he  seems  to  find  a  certain  pleasure  in  the  paradoxical 
contrast  between  Spinoza's  supposed  impious  doctrines  and 
his  moral  life.  '  II  renversait  tous  les  principes  de  la  morale, 
en  etant  lui-meme  d'une  vertu  rigide.'  Again,  he  speaks  of 
'  le  sophiste  gdometrique  Spinosa,  dont  la  moderation,  le 
desinteressement,  et  la  generosite  ont  ete  dignes  d'Epictcte.' 
Elsewhere  Spinoza  is  used  by  Voltaire  as  an  example  of 
virtue  apart  from  belief  in  supernatural  dogmas.  The 
mixture  of  personal  generosity  with  philosophical  narrowness 
in  Voltaire's  estimate  is  at  first  sight  strange,  but  ceases  to 
be  so  when  we  bear  in  mind  that  the  form  of  pure  theism 
strongly  and  even  vehemently  maintained  by  Voltaire  made 
him  a  champion  of  natural  theology  and  final  causes.  The 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus,'  where  Spinoza's  opinions  on 
these  points  are  not  developed,  seems  to  have  been  read  by 
Voltaire  with  attention  and  something  like  approval ;  at  least 
his  expressions  of  dissent  are  of  the  most  faint  and  formal 
kind,  and  coupled  with  marked  and  specific  praise. •     As  to 

'  Ldln  sitr  Spinosa,  in  Mctaiiges  Litteraires  :    '  Cet  ouvrage  est  trcs-profond 

c  e  3 


383  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

the  '  Opera  Posthuma,'  Voltaire  had  probably  not  read  them  ; 
he  calls  Spinoza's  Latin  dry,  obscure,  even  bad  ;  and  when 
he  wants  to  discuss  Spinoza's  metaphysics  he  quotes  from 
the  so-called  refutation  by  the  Count  de  Boulainvilliers. 

This  work  is  curious  enough  to  deserve  special  mention, 
and  may  be  introduced  by  Voltaire's  significant  remark  that 
under  the  title  of  '  Refutation  of  Spinoza '  Boulainvilliers 
gave  the  poison  and  forgot  to  give  the  antidote.  The  book 
is  a  popular  exposition  of  the  '  Ethics,'  in  which  little  is  pre- 
served of  the  arrangement  or  the  language  of  the  original. 
Some  passages  appear  to  be  inserted  from  the  '  De  Intellectus 
Emendatione,'  and  occasionally  we  meet  with  terms  and  lines 
of  argument  which  are  not  in  Spinoza  at  all.  It  was  not 
published  till  after  Boulainvilliers'  death  ;  but  he  left  with 
it  an  apologetic  preface  which  thinly  disguises  the  real  pur- 
pose. He  professes  to  have  met  with  the  '  Opera  Posthuma  ' 
quite  by  accident,  and  bought  the  book  for  the  sake  of  the 
Hebrew  grammar :  then,  he  says,  having  nothing  else  to  do 
in  the  country,  he  made  acquaintance  with  the  philosophical 
writings,  and,  thinking  it  of  high  importance  that  they  should 
be  properly  refuted,  conceived  the  plan  of  expounding  their 
contents  in  a  more  generally  intelligible  form  :  '  afin  que  le 
systeme  rendu  dans  une  langue  commune,  et  reduit  a  dcs 
expressions  ordinaires,  put  etre  en  etat  d'exciter  une  indig- 
nation pareille  a  la  mienne,  et  procurer,  par  ce  moyen,  de 
veritables  ennemis  a  de  si  pernicieux  principes.'  The  volume 
also  contains,  I  presume  to  save  appearances,  reprints  and 
extracts  of  sundry  controversial  publications  relating  to  Spi- 
noza and  Spinozism.  It  further  includes  the  life  of  Spinoza 
by  Colerus,  with  large  interpolations  from  the  untrustworthy 
work  of  Lucas,  which  Boulainvilliers  knew  only  in  manu- 
script. In  that  form  Lucas's  biography  appears  to  have  had 
some   currency    in    freethinking   society    on    the    Continent, 

et  le  meillcur  qu'il  ait  fait  ;  j'en  condamne  sans  doute  les  sentimens,  'mais  je  ne 
puis  m'empecher  d'en  estimer  renidition,'  &c. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  389 

and  it  oddly  enough  became  associated  with  a  certain 
*  Traite  des  trois  imposteurs,'  which  occurs  together  with 
Lucas,  and  also  alone,  under  the  title  '  L'Esprit  de  Monsieur 
Benoit  de  Spinoza,'  or  '  L'Esprit  de  Spinoza.'  ^  As  for  this 
last-mentioned  production,  it  has  nothing  whatever  to  do  with 
Spinoza,  nor  yet  is  it  a  translation  of  the  Latin  book  *  De 
tribus  impostoribus,'  of  which  the  true  date  and  origin  have 
long  been  a  standing  puzzle  of  bibliographers.  For  us  the  only 
interest  of  it  is  that  the  circumstances  show  Spinoza's  name 
to  have  become  a  sort  of  catch-word  for  anti-theological  as 
well  as  theological  polemics,  and  with  about  equal  ignorance 
on  both  sides  of  what  his  philosophy  really  was. 

It  would  be  difficult  to  say  to  what  extent  Spinoza  may 
have  been  read  in   a   more  judicial    spirit   by    people   who 
kept  themselves  clear  of  polemics  altogether.     Montesquieu, 
having  ventured  to  treat  historical  and  political  problems  in 
a  scientific  manner,  was  accused  as  a  matter  of  course  of  Spi- 
nozism.      He  had  no  difficulty  in  showing  that  the  charge 
was  absurd.^     There  is  pretty  strong  internal  evidence,  how- 
ever, that  Montesquieu  had  read  the  '  Opera  Posthuma  ; '  not 
in  his  great  work  indeed,  but  in  the  '  Lettres  Persanes,'  a  place 
at  first  sight  less  likely.     In  the  fifty-ninth  Letter  the  follow- 
ing sentence  occurs  :  *  On  a  dit  fort  bien  que,  si  les  triangles 
faisoient  un  dieu,  ils  lui  donneroient  trois  cotes,'     This  ap- 
pears to  be  an  unmistakable  allusion  to  a  passage  we  have 
already  quoted  in  a  former  chapter  from  Spinoza's   letters.^ 
For  the  rest,  the  *  Lettres  Persanes  '  are  much  less  guarded 
in  other   respects  than    the  '  Esprit    des    Lois.'     To  discuss 
what  they  entitle  us  to  conclude  as    to    Montesquieu's  real 
opinions  would  take  us  too  far. 

'  jNISS.  in  the  Royal  Library  at  the  Hague.  Tlie  combination  had  been 
printed  in  17 19,  but  was  shortly  afterwards  called  in.  See  Van  der  Linde, 
Bihliogr.  nos.  99-104.  The  MSS.  are  in  neat  P'rench  handwriting  of  the  first 
half  of  the  eighteenth  century.  There  is  another  in  the  British  Museum.  See 
Introduction  for  more  detail. 

-  Defense  de  V Esprit  des  Lois,  ad  init.  '  P.  6'^,  above. 


390  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

While  Voltaire  and  the  Encyclopaedists  were  still  at   the 
head  of  European  thought,  and  happy  in  the  conviction  that 
Spinoza  might  be  left  alone  as   an  enthusiast  who  had  the 
personal  merit  of  being   a  virtuous  heretic  and    odious    to 
orthodox  authorities,  but  was  philosophically  quite  hopeless, 
the  movement  had  begun  in  Germany,   as  yet  unobserved, 
which  was  to  restore  him  to  his  true  place.     If  a  date  is  to  be 
fixed  for  the  birth  of  modern  Spinozism,  it  must  be  Lessing's 
conversation  with  Jacobi  in  1780.    But  many  years  before  that 
time  Lessing  had  been  in  correspondence  with  Moses  Mendels- 
sohn about  Spinoza,  and,  Vv^hat  is  of  more  importance,  had 
thoroughly  assimilated  Spinoza's  ideas  and  used  them  in  his 
own  work.     Still  earlier  he  had  written  thus  of  Mendelssohn, 
then  quite  a  young  man,  to  another  friend  :  '  His  sincerity  and 
philosophic  turn  of  mind  make  me  look  on  him  as  one  that 
will  be  a  second  Spinoza.    To  make  him  altogether  like  the  first 
nothing   but  his  errors  will  be  wanting.'  ^     It  is  clear  that 
Lessing  had  carefully  studied   Spinoza,  and  understood  him 
better  than  many  later  philosophers  and  critics  ;  it  is  also 
clear  that  Lessing  never  fully  accepted   Spinoza's  point  of 
view  as  applicable  to  the  theory  of  human   nature  and  the 
conduct  of  life.     Not  only  do  the  words  just  quoted  show  this, 
but  it  appears  from  Lessing's  statement  and  indications  of 
his   own    philosophical    opinions,  unsystematic  as  they  are. 
There   were  points  on  which  he  came  nearer  to  Leibnitz, 
But  his  intellectual  sympathies  were  all  with  Spinoza,  both  as 
against  the  common  orthodox  denunciation   and  as  against 
the    half-intelligent    criticism    of  the    free-thinking    French 
school.     A  man  thus  disposed,  and  standing  at  the  head  of 
German  literature,  if  indeed  he  may  not  be  called  the  founder 
of  modern  German  culture,  was  eminently  fitted  to  render  to 
Spinoza's  memory  the  justice  that  had  been  so  long  delayed. 

'  Letters  to  J.  D.  Michaelis,  Oct.  16,  1754  ;  to  Mendelssohn,  April  17,  1763. 
Cp.  Dr.  Karl  Rehorn,  G.  E.  Lessing''s  Stelhmg  zur  Philosophie  dcs  Spinoza, 
Frankfurt-am-Main,  1S77;  J.  Simc,  Lessing,  vol.  ii.  p.  296,  &c. 


SPINOZA  AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  391 

It  was  not  done,  it  is  true,  by  openly  preaching  Spinoza's 
merits.  That  was  left  by  Lessing  to  the  coming  generation 
who  had  learnt  from  him  ;  and  he  taught  them  much  better 
than  he  would  have  done  by  direct  preaching.  It  is  but  one 
example,  if  I  mistake  not,  of  the  characteristic  method  of  his 
work. 

After  Lessing's  death  a  discussion   arose  between  Jacob! 
and  Moses  Mendelssohn  as  to  what  Lessing's  opinions  had 
been.     Mendelssohn  was  preparing  a  memoir  of  Lessing,  and 
Jacobi  communicated  to  him,  as  a  matter  of  interest  he  might 
perhaps  not  know,  that  Lessing  had  been  a  Spinozist.     Men- 
delssohn declined  to  accept  the  statement,  and  there  ensued 
a  correspondence,  long,  desultory,  and  now  sufficiently  tedious 
to  follow,  which  ended  in  a  personal  controversy.     The  part  of 
it  which  is  still  interesting  is  Jacobi's  account  of  his  talk  with 
Lessing  about  Spinoza.     He  wrote  it  down  for  Mendelssohn, 
apparently  from  memory,  three  years  after  it  took  place  :  but 
the  impression  it   had    made   was   obviously  deep,  and  his 
report  may  be  taken  as  in  substance  correct.     It  was  on  the 
5th  of  July,  1780,  that  Jacobi  paid  a  long  desired  visit  to 
Lessing :  they  talked  much  and  of  many  things,  and  the  next 
morning  they  fell  into  more  talk  over  Goethe's  '  Prometheus,' 
which  Jacobi  had  with  him,  and  Lessing  saw  for  the  first 
time.     '  You  have  shocked  so  many  people,'  said  Jacobi  as  he 
gave  it  him  to  read,  '  that  you  may  as  well  be  shocked  for  once 
yourself.'     '  Not  at  all,'  replied  Lessing  after  reading  the  lines  : 
'  I  know  all  that  at  first  hand.'     Let  us  interpose  a  warning 
before  we  follow  up  the  dialogue  as  given  in   dramatic  form 
by  Jacobi.     Judicious  readers  have  before  now  observed  that 
Lessing  seems  to  have  had  a  mind  to  disport  himself  with 
Jacobi,  to  put  things  paradoxically,  to  shock  him  a  little,  and 
never  to  let  him  fully  see  if  he  were  serious  or  not.     Jacobi, 
however,  took  it  all  seriously  and  solemnly.     The  conversa- 
tion proceeds  thus : — 

Jacobi.  You  know  the  poem? 


392  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Lessbig.  I  never  read  the  poem  before,  but  I  like  it. 

Jacobi.  So  do  I  in  its  way,  or  I  would  not  have  shown  it  you. 

Lessing.  That  is  not  what  I  mean.  The  point  of  view  of  that 
poem  is  my  own.  The  orthodox  conceptions  of  Deity  will  do  no 
longer  for  me ;  I  cannot  stomach  them  ;  tv  kui  ttciv — I  know  no  more 
than  that.  Such  is  the  drift  of  this  poem  too ;  and  I  am  free  to  con- 
fess it  is  much  to  my  mind, 

Jacobi.  Why,  that  makes  you  pretty  much  in  accord  with  Spinoza. 

Lessing.  If  I  am  to  call  myself  after  any  master,  I  know  of  no 
other. 

Jacobi  Spinoza  is  good  enough  for  me  :  but  'tis  a  sorry  kind  of 
salvation  one  can  find  in  his  name. 

Lessing.  Well,  so  be  it.  But,  after  all,  do  you  know  of  any 
better? 

Before  Jacobi  had  time  to  recover  from  his  astonishment, 
they  were  interrupted.  Lessing  renewed  the  conversation 
the  next  morning.  Jacobi  explained  that  he  had  rather 
hoped  to  get  some  help  against  Spinoza  from  Lessing. 

Lessing.  Then  it  seems  you  know  him. 

jfacobl.  I  think  I  know  him  as  very  few  can  have  done. 

Lessing.  Then  there  is  no  help  for  you  :  you  had  better  make 
friends  with  him  for  good  and  all.  There  is  no  other  philosophy  than 
the  philosophy  of  Spinoza. 

Jacobi  is  then  drawn  into  a  pretty  full  exposition,  Lessing 
only  putting  in  a  stimulating  question  every  now  and  then. 
At  one  point  Lessing  suggests  that  the  eminently  respect- 
able Leibnitz  was  in  truth  a  Spinozist.  'Do  you  mean 
it  seriously  }  '  cries  Jacobi.  '  Do  you  doubt  it  seriously  .? ' 
answers  Lessing.  Presently  Jacobi  comes  back  to  the  sug- 
gestion and  develops  it  at  some  length. 

Lessing.  I  shall  leave  you  no  peace  till  you  come  out  with 
that  parallel— to  think  that  people  go  on  talking  of  Spinoza  as  if  he 
were  a  dead  dog  ! 

yacobi.  They  would  do  just  the  same  afterwards.  To  grasp 
Spinoza  requires  a  mental  effort  too  long  and  too  stubborn  for  them. 
And  no  one  has  grasped  him  to  whom  a  single  line  in  the  '  Ethics '  has 
remained  obscure. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  393 

Notwithstanding  this  brave  saying,  Lessing  appears  to 
have  had  his  doubts  whether  Jacobi  really  understood 
Spinoza,  and  modern  critics  have  certainly  not  taken  his 
mastery  of  the  '  Ethics  '  at  his  own  valuation.  The  general 
purport  of  Jacobi's  rather  long-winded  observations  is  that 
Spinoza's  philosophy  is  logically  unanswerable  but  morally 
unacceptable  ;  Spinozism,  he  says,  is  atheism.  For  practical 
purposes  he  takes  refuge  in  an  act  of  faith,  salto  mortale  as  he 
calls  it  in  the  conversation  with  Lessing,  who  with  a  certain 
irony  declined  at  his  age  to  follow  in  any  such  adventures ; 
being  unable,  he  said,  to  trust  his  old  limbs  and  heavy  head 
for  such  a  leap. 

The  strife  of  Jacobi  and  Mendelssohn  over  Lessing's  body 
could  not  fail  to  concentrate  attention  on  Spinoza  and  his 
doctrines.  Some  notion  of  the  effect  that  was  produced 
is  given  by  Herder's  preface  to  the  second  edition  of  his 
dialogues  on  Spinoza's  system,  published  in  1800.  It  is  there 
said  that  the  edition  might  have  been  ready  several  years 
earlier,  but  was  delayed  for  various  reasons.  In  particular, 
Spinoza  had  become  so  popular  (being  taken  up  by  some 
even  with  extravagance)  that  an  unpretending  attempt  to 
remove  the  common  misapprehensions  about  him  seemed  to 
have  lost  its  point. 

'Since  1787,  when  these  dialogues  were  first  printed,  much  had 
been  changed  in  the  philosophical  outlook  of  Germany.  The  name 
of  Spinoza,  which  used  to  be  mentioned  with  a  shudder  of  abhorrence, 
had  since  then  risen  so  high  with  some  persons  that  they  could 
never  name  it  except  for  the  disparagement  of  Leibnitz  and  other 
excellent  authors.' 

We  may  take  it,  then,  that  some  ten  or  twelve  years  after 
Lessing's  death  the  tone  of  educated  German  society  with 
regard  to  Spinoza  had  undergone  a  complete  change. 
Herder's  dialogues  themselves  give  a  version  of  Spinoza's 
doctrine,  or  rather  of  what  it  might  have  been,  which  may  be 
described  as  a  sort  of  idealized  naturalism.     Their  general  aim 


394  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

is  curiously  like  that  of  some  writers  of  our  own  day  who, 
accepting  the  theory  of  evolution  as  established  by  science, 
but  not  content  with  its  purely  scientific  aspect,  have  en- 
deavoured to  make  it  the  vehicle  of  new  and  refined  forms  of 
teleology.  Some  of  Herder's  points  and  phrases  might  still  be 
found  suggestive,^  The  general  tendency  of  his  reading  of 
Spinoza  is  thus  opposed  to  Jacobi's,  and  not  unlike  that  which 
has  on  the  whole  prevailed  among  later  German  critics.  An 
undercurrent  of  anti-Kantian  polemic  is  traceable  in  many 
parts  of  the  dialogues. 

Kant  himself  was  unaffected  by  the  rising  influence  of 
Spinoza.  Either  he  never  considered  Spinoza  seriously,  or  he 
came  to  the  consideration  of  him  too  late.  What  mention 
there  is  of  Spinoza  in  Kant's  philosophical  writings  is  but 
slight  and  occasional.  In  one  place  he  is  criticized  on  the 
one  point  of  final  causes,  but  not  lucidly  or  adequately.'^  The 
reader  of  Kant  may  indeed  find  here  and  there  curious  ap- 
proximations to  Spinoza's  lines  of  thought.  One  such  has 
been  pointed  out  in  a  former  chapter.  But  these  are  on  the 
face  of  them  accidental  ;  they  are  such  that  if  Spinoza's  corre- 
sponding work  had  been  present  to  Kant's  mind  the  resem- 
blance must  have  been  less  or  more.  It  is  hardly  needful  to 
add  that  Kant's  way  of  approaching  the  problems  of  philo- 
sophy is  entirely  different  from  Spinoza's.  Only  the  genera- 
tion succeeding  Kant  felt  the  full  power  of  the  revived 
Spinozism  in  philosophy ;  for  the  time  its  work  was  more  in 
the  semi-philosophical  regions  of  literature  and  poetry.  Les- 
sing's  mantle  fell  in  a  great  measure  upon  Goethe  ;  and  for 

*  For  example,  he  meets  the  objection  that  Spinoza  does  not  account  for  the 
individuality  of  things  by  saying  that  when  Spinoza  is  rightly  understood  this  is 
a  specially  strong  point  in  his  system.  Tlie  principium  individiiatioiiis  is  iden- 
tified with  life,  and  is  capable  of  degrees  which  depend  on  the  degree  of  organiza- 
tion attained.  'Je  mehr  Leben  und  Wirklichkeit,  d.  i.  je  eine  verstiindigere, 
machtigere,  voUkommnere  Energie  ein  \\'esen  zur  Erhaltung  eines  Ganzen  hat, 
das  es  sich  angehorig  fiihlt,  dem  es  sich  innig  und  ganz  mittheilet,  desto  mehr  ist 
es  Individuum,  Selbst.' 

2  Kritik  der  Urlhdlskraft,  §  73. 


SPINOZA  AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  39$ 

Goethe,  as  for  Lessing,  Spinoza  was  a  living  and  eloquent 
guide.  By  Goethe  even  more  richly  and  variously  than  by 
Lessing  the  ideas  put  forth  by  Spinoza  were  refashioned  in  less 
technical  forms,  endowed  with  new  life,  and  spread  abroad 
among  the  educated  public.  Goethe  too,  like  Lessing,  was 
not  altogether  in  speculative  agreement  with  Spinoza,  but 
nevertheless  assimilated  and  used  him.  The  direct,  one  may 
indeed  say  decisive,  influence  of  Spinoza  on  his  mind — for 
it  is  his  own  word — is  no  matter  of  conjecture :  it  is  told  by 
Goethe  himself  He  had  long  sought  unsatisfied  for  guidance 
and  sustenance ;  at  last  he  came  on  the  '  Ethics '  of  Spinoza, 
and  there  found  something  he  could  repose  in. 

'  What  the  book  may  have  given  to  me,  or  what  I  may  have 
put  into  it  of  my  own,  it  is  impossible  for  me  to  say  :  enough  that  I 
found  here  that  which  stilled  the  emotions  :  a  wide  and  free  prospect 
over  the  physical  and  moral  world  disclosed  itself  before  me.  But 
what  chiefly  drew  me  to  Spinoza  was  the  boundless  unselfishness 
that  shone  forth  in  every  sentence.  That  marvellous  saying  :  '  Whoso 
truly  loves  God  must  not  expect  God  to  love  him  in  return,'  with  all 
the  propositions  that  support  it,  all  the  consequences  that  flow  from  it, 
was  the  burden  of  all  my  thoughts.  To  be  unselfish  in  everything, 
most  of  all  in  love  and  friendship,  was  my  highest  pleasure,  my  rule 
of  life,  my  exercise,  so  that  my  foolhardy  saying  of  a  later  time,  If  I 
love  you,  what  is  that  to  you  ? — was  truly  felt  by  me  when  I  wrote  it. 
I  must  not  forget  to  acknowledge  in  this  case  as  in  others  the  truth 
that  the  closest  unions  are  the  result  of  contrast.  The  serene  level 
of  Spinoza  stood  out  against  my  striving  endeavour  in  all  directions  ; 
his  mathematical  method  was  the  complement  of  my  poetical  way 
of  observation  and  description,  and  his  formal  treatment,  which  some 
could  not  think  appropriate  to  moral  subjects,  was  just  what  made 
me  learn  from  him  with  eagerness  and  admire  him  without  reserve.' 

In  another  passage,  less  quoted  but  not  less  remarkable, 
Goethe  tells  how  the  sight  of  an  old  attack  on  Spinoza  (it 
seems  to  have  been  Kortholt 's  '  De  tribus  impostoribus 
magnis')  led  him  to  take  up  the  'Opera  Tosthuma'  again, 
after  a  long  interval.  He  well  remembered  the  effect  of 
the  first  reading,  and  this  time  again  he  seemed  to  attain  an 


396  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY, 

extraordinary  clearness  of  intellectual  vision.^  He  goes  on  to 
say  what  was  the  lesson  he  found  in  Spinoza.  The  whole  of 
our  education  and  experience  bids  us  to  renounce  and  resign : 
'  Dass  wir  entsagen  sollen,'  The  problem  of  man's  life  is  to' 
reconcile  himself  to  this.  One  ready  way  is  the  superficial 
way  of  the  many,  to  proclaim  that  all  things  are  vanity.  But 
the  path  of  wisdom,  sought  only  by  a  few,  is  to  cut  short  the 
pains  of  resignation  in  detail  by  a  resignation  once  for  all  ;  to 
rest  one's  mind  on  that  which  is  eternal,  necessary,  and  uni- 
form, and  possess  ideas  which  remain  undisturbed  by  the 
contemplation  of  a  transitory  world.  This  was  the  secret  of 
Spinoza  for  Goethe.  Not  that  he  ever  assented  in  detail  to 
the  letter  of  his  doctrine.  He  knew  too  well  how  difficult 
it  is  for  one  man  to  enter  into  another's  thoughts,  how 
easy  misunderstandings  are,  even  to  flatter  himself  that  he 
thoroughly  understood  Spinoza.  For  some  time  he  meant 
to  introduce  a  visit  to  Spinoza  into  his  unfinished  poem  on 
the  Wandering  Jew.  The  scene  was  much  thought  over,  but 
never  written. 

Against  Jacobi's  reading  of  the  Ethics  Goethe  protested  in 
emphatic  language.  *  My  own  way  of  looking  at  nature/  he 
wrote,  *  is  not  Spinoza's  ;  but  if  I  had  to  name  the  book  that 
of  all  I  know  agrees  best  with  my  view,  I  could  only  name 
the  Ethics.  I  hold  more  and  more  firmly  to  worshipping 
God  with  this  so-called  atheist,  and  gladly  leave  to  you 
and  your  allies  everything  to  which  you  give,  as  you  needs 
must,  the  name  of  religion.'  He  returned  again  and  again 
to  Spinoza  for  spiritual  light  and  strength,  and  the  '  Ethics ' 
continued  to  be  the  companion  of  his  old  age. 

But,  though  Goethe's  purpose  of  paying  an  express 
poetical  tribute  to  Spinoza  was  not  executed,  the  place 
filled  by  Spinoza  in  his  thoughts  makes  itself  known  in  his 

'  '  Ich  ergab  mich  diaser  Lektiire  unci  glaubte,  indem  ich  in  mich  selbst  schaute, 
die  Welt  niemals  so  deutlich  erblickt  zu  haben.' — Aus  7neinem  Leben,  book  xvi. 
ad  init.    The  passage  above  U'anslated  is  towards  the  end  of  book  xiv. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  397 

writings  in  manifold  ways.     In  dramatic  and  lyrical  poetry, 
in  romance  and  in  proverbs,  in  '  Faust '  and  in  epigrams,  the 
same  presence  meets    us.     In    fact  Spinozism    is  so   widely 
spread  and  pervading  an  element  in  Goethe's  works,  that  for 
that  very  reason  it  is  useless  to  give  specific  instances  :  if  one 
were  to  begin,  one  would  be  launched  into  a  commentary  on 
Goethe.     The  series  of  poems  entitled  *  Gott  und  Welt '  may 
be  referred  to  as  showing  Goethe's  speculative  tendencies  in  a 
concentrated  form.     It  was  Lessing  and  Goethe  more  than 
the  philosophers    by   profession    who    secured    the   place    of 
Spinoza   in    modern    German  thought   and    literature.     The 
work  of  tracing  his  influence    and    recognition  down  to  the 
present  time  would    need    a  monograph  to  itself.     Novalis, 
Schleiermacher,   and  Heine    may  be    mentioned   as   leading 
names  among  those  who  from  divers  quarters  and  on  divers 
occasions   have   celebrated    Spinoza's    memory.       Heine    in 
particular  has  given  to  Spinoza  some  of  his  most  charming 
pages.     More  lately,  a  thorough  philosophic  study  of  Spinoza 
has,  in  one  remarkable  instance,  been  united  with  great  powers 
of  literary  expression.     Auerbach,  the  translator  of  Spinoza's 
works,  also    stands    in    the  first  rank    of  German  novelists. 
One  book  ('  Spinoza,  ein  Denkerleben  ')  he  has  given  expressly 
to  a  story  of  Spinoza's  early  life,  in  which  the  outlines  of  fact 
we  possess  are  filled  in  by  a  skilled  and  sympathetic  hand. 
For  those  who  can  read  German,  but  fear  to  attack  technical 
works  on   philosophy,  there  can   be  no  better  introduction  to 
Spinoza.     More  than   this,  Auerbach's  other  work   is   full  of 
SpinozisTn^-/and  at  least  one  of  his  books  carries  on  the  face 
of  it  the  purpose  of  showing  the  value  of  Spinoza's  philosophy 
as  a  working  view  of  life. 

In  philosophy  Spinozism,  to  which  Kant  remained  a 
stranger,  was  largely  taken  up  by  his  successors.  Fichte's 
teaching  is  widely  different  from  Spinoza's  in  its  method  and 
conclusions,  but  it  is  evident  that  he  had  studied  Spinoza  and 
felt  his  power.     Some  of  Fichte's  metaphysical  interpretations 


398  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

of  theology  have  all  the  appearance  of  being  taken  from 
Spinoza  with  but  little  alteration.  We  find  in  him  also  a 
short  criticism  on  Spinoza's  theory  of  Substance,^  Hegel  and 
Schelling  were  more  explicit.  They  both  spoke  of  Spinoza 
with  high  admiration.  To  be  a  philosopher  you  must  first 
be  a  Spinozist ;  if  you  have  not  Spinozism  you  have  no 
philosophy  at  all :  such  were  Hegel's  repeated  sayings.  To 
the  same  effect  Schelling  said  that  no  one  can  attain  true 
and  full  knowledge  in  philosophy  who  has  not  at  least  once 
plunged  into  the  depth  of  Spinozism.  But  when  Schelling 
and  Hegel  had  occasion,  in  expounding  their  own  systems,  to 
show  how  much  they  had  improved  on  Spinoza,  they  not  only 
became  critical,  but  their  criticism  was  hardly  respectful. 
Hegel  even  allowed  himself  a  bad  pun  on  the  manner  of 
Spinoza's  death.^  Their  chief  objection  to  Spinoza's  philo- 
sophy, so  far  as  it  can  be  made  briefly  intelligible,  is  that  his 
system  of  the  world  is  lifeless,  rigid,  motionless.  Schelling 
compares  it  to  Pygmalion's  statue  before  life  had  been 
breathed  into  it.  Nevertheless  it  is  admitted  that  Spinoza 
was  the  founder  of  modern  philosophy ;  and  this  has  been 
confirmed  by  the  general  voice  of  German  criticism  ever 
since.  The  continuance  of  philosophical  interest  in  Spinoza 
among  German  thinkers  down  to  this  time  is  sufficiently 
shown  by  the  amount  of  discussion  which  has  been  specially 
given  to  him.  One  school,  indeed,  which  just  now  is  popular, 
regards  Spinoza  with  considerably  less  favour.  This  is  the 
school  of  Pessimism,  founded  on  the  brilliant  extravagances  of 
Schopenhauer  and  the  more  methodical  system  of  Hartmann. 
Schopenhauer  could  not  abide  Spinoza,  first,  it  would  seem, 
for  being  a  Jew,  and  next  for  being  an  optimist ;  the  charge 

'  Wcrkc,  i.  121,  ed.  1845.  Fur  resemblances  see  especially  Rdigionslehrc, 
lote  Vorlesung. 

-  '  Abgrundder  Substanz  .  .  .  in  dem  Allcs  niir  dahin  schwindet,  alios  Lei  en 
in  sich  selbst  verkommt ;  Spinoza  ist  selbst  an  der  Schwindsucht  gestorbcn.' 
Hegel's  and  Schelling's  criticisms  are  collected  and  discussed  in  C.  von  Orelli's 
Spinoza^ s  Lcben  jind  Lchrc,  Aarau,  1S50. 


SPINOZA  AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  399 

of  optimism  being  established  by  the  simple  assertion  that 
*  pantheism  is  essentially  and  necessarily  optimism.'  Yet 
Spinoza  neither  maintains  that  the  universe  as  a  whole  is  to 
be  called  good  or  the  best  possible  (for  these  with  him  are 
purely  relative  conceptions),  nor  does  he  anywhere  commit 
himself  to  any  opinion  as  to  the  actual  balance  of  pain  and 
pleasure  in  the  world.  Schopenhauer  does  not  trouble  him- 
self with  these  distinctions.  He  makes  an  end  of  Spinoza  in 
three  or  four  pages  of  dashing  criticism,  calls  him  an  uncon- 
scious materialist,  among  other  names,  and  goes  out  of  his 
way  to  cast  a  gross  insult  on  Spinoza's  race.'  Hartmann 
deals  with  Spinoza  much  more  soberly,  neither  vituperates 
nor  misrepresents  him,  and  sometimes  quotes  him  with 
approval.  But  Spinoza's  general  habit  of  mind  is  of  course 
as  entirely  opposed  to  dogmatic  pessimism  as  to  dogmatic 
optimism  ;  and  those  who  find  their  philosophic  satisfaction 
in  pessimism  cannot  be  expected  to  have  much  sympathy 
for  him.  On  the  other  hand,  this  estrangement,  whatever  its 
amount  may  be,  seems  likely  to  be  compensated  or  more 
than  compensated  by  increased  appreciation  of  Spinoza  from 
the  scientific  side.  Muller's  testimony  as  to  his  account  of 
the  passions  has  already  been  quoted.  Even  more  important 
is  the  striking  likeness  between  Spinoza's  results  and  those 
reached  in  our  time  by  workers  who,  like  Wundt  and  Haeckel 
in  Germany,  and  Taine  in  France,  have  come  to  psychological 
questions  through  physiology,  or  taken  the  equivalent  precau- 
tion of  informing  their  philosophic  judgment  with  competent 
physiological  instruction.  It  may  be  safely  affirmed,  I  think, 
that  Spinoza  tends  more  and  more  to  become  the  philosopher 
of  men  of  science. 

The  German   restoration  of  Spinoza  was  yet  new  when 
Coleridge,  foremost  in  transplanting  hither  the  fruits  of  the 

'  Dk  rhil'JsophU  dcr  A'^iiemt,  in  Fragincnle  znr  Gcsch.  dcr  rhilosophic  (vol. 
V.  of  works,  ed.  Frauenstadt).  The  al;nost  incredible  piece  of  bad  taste  referred 
to,  wliich  I  do  not  care  to  repeat,  is  on  p.  78. 


400  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

great  revival  of  German  culture,  began  to  speak  and  write  of 
him    in   England.     The    immediate   effect,    it    is    true,    was 
nothing  conspicuous;  nevertheless    the   present  appreciation 
of  Spinoza  in  this  country  must  be  ascribed  to  Coleridge  more 
than  to  any  other  one  man.     For  the  bulk  of  readers  he  spoke 
in  parables  ;  but  (in  this  resembling  Lessing)  he  did  some- 
thing even  better  than  teaching  the  public  ;  he  taught  their 
teachers.     His  written  and  spoken  words  were  treasured  by  a 
select  circle  of  those  who  formed  the  literature  and  literary 
habits  of  the  next  generation.     At  one  time  he  talked  much 
of  Spinoza  with  Wordsworth,  as  we  know  from  a  droll  anec- 
dote told  by  Coleridge  himself     It  was  in  the  first  fever  of 
the  great  war  with  France,  when  the  minds  of  loyal  subjects 
were  haunted  by  red  spectres    of  Jacobin  clubs  and  corre- 
sponding societies.     Coleridge  and  Wordsworth  were  staying 
peaceably  enough  in  Somersetshire,  with  no  manner  of  treason 
in  their  thoughts.     But  at  that  time  whoever  was  not  a  Tory 
was  held  little  better  than  a  Jacobin,  and  they  fell  under  sus- 
picion.    The  rest  shall  be  told  in  Coleridge's  own  words. 

'  The  dark  guesses  of  some  zealous  Quidnunc  met  with  so  con- 
genial a  soil  in  the  grave  alarm  of  a  titled  Dogberry  of  our  neighbour- 
hood, that  a  spy  was  actually  sent  down  from  the  government  pour 
siwveillaiice  of  myself  and  friend.  There  must  have  been  not  only 
abundance  but  variety  of  these  "  honourable  men  "  at  the  disposal  of 
Ministers  ;  for  this  proved  a  very  honest  fellow.  After  three  weeks' 
truly  Indian  perseverance  in  tracking  us  (for  we  were  commonly 
together)  during  all  which  time  seldom  were  we  out  of  doors  but  he 
contrived  to  be  within  hearing  (and  all  the  while  utterly  unsus- 
pected ;  how  indeed  could  such  a  suspicion  enter  our  fancies  ?)  he 
not  only  rejected  Sir  Dogberry's  request  that  he  would  try  yet  a 
little  longer,  but  declared  to  him  his  belief  that  Ijotli  my  friend  and 
myself  were  as  good  subjects,  for  aught  he  could  discover  to  the  con- 
trary, as  any  in  His  Majesty's  dominions.  He  had  repeatedly  hid  him- 
self, he  said,  for  hours  together  behind  a  bank  at  the  sea-side  (our 
favourite  seat)  and  overheard  our  conversation.  At  first  he  fancied 
that  we  were  aware  of  our  danger ;  for  he  often  heard  me  talk  of  one 
Spy  Nozy,  which  he  was  inclined  to  interpret  of  himself,  and  of  a 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT,  401 

remarkable  feature  belonging  to  him ;  but  he  was  speedily  convinced 
that  it  was  the  name  of  a  man  who  had  made  a  book  and  lived  long 
ago.'  1 

What  Coleridge  thought  of  Spinoza's  importance  as  a 
philosopher  is  to  be  gathered  from  various  scattered  notices. 
A  pencil  note  made  by  him  in  a  copy  of  Schelling's  philoso- 
phical works  runs  as  follows  : — 

'  I  believe  in  my  depth  of  being  that  the  three  great  works  since 
the  introduction  of  Christianity  are — Bacon's  "Novum  Organum,"  and 
his  other  works,  so  far  as  they  are  commentaries  on  it  j  Spinoza's 
"  Ethics,"  with  his  letters  and  other  pieces,  as  far  as  they  are  comments 
on  his  Ethics  ;  and  Kant's  "Critique  of  the  Pure  Reason,"  and  his 
other  works  as  commentaries  on  and  applications  of  the  same.'^ 

At  the  same  time  Coleridge  was  neither  a  Spinozist  nor  a 
Kantian.  His  position  as  regards  Spinoza  was  not  altogether 
unlike  Jacobi's,  though  he  would  never  have  expressed  him- 
self so  crudely  as  Jacobi  did  on  the  consequences  of  the 
system.  While  he  admired  Spinoza  both  intellectually  and 
morally,  he  could  not  fully  accept  his  way  of  thinking. 
Even  at  a  time  when  he  was  all  but  convinced  by  Spinoza, 
he  was  not  satisfied.  '  For  a  very  long  time,  indeed,'  he 
writes,  '  I  could  not  reconcile  personality  with  infinity  ;  and 
my  head  was  Avith  Spinoza,  though  my  whole  heart  remained 
with  Paul  and  John.'^  Crabb  Robinson  tells  in  his  Diary"*  of 
an  interview  with  Coleridge  at  which  he  spoke  of  the  '  Ethics ' 
as  a  book  that  was  a  gospel  to  him,  explaining  at  the  same 
time  that  he  nevertheless  thought  Spinoza's  philosophy  false. 
'  Spinoza's  system  has  been  demonstrated  to  be  false,  but  only 
by  that  philosophy  which  has  demonstrated'  the  falsehood  of 
all  other  philosophies.  Did  philosophy  commence  with  an  it 
is  instead  of  an  /  am,  Spinoza  would  be  altogether  true.' 
But  somehow  this  particular  utterance  of  Coleridge's  does 
not  seem  quite  so  genuine  as  the  others.     It  is  difficult  to  think 

'  Biogyaphia  Litemria,  ch.  x.  *  lb.,  note  17  to  ch.  ix.  ed.  1 847. 

lb.  ch.  X.  *  Vol.  i.  p.  208,  3rd  ed. 

D  D 


402  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

the  little  scene  reported  by  Crabb  Robinson  altogether  free 
from  affectation.  There  is  a  touch  of  deliberate  display  in 
Coleridge's  kissing  the  frontispiece  of  the  '  Opera  Posthuma; ' 
it  is  almost  theatrical.  The  occasion  was  his  borrowing  the 
book  of  Crabb  Robinson.  Had  he  then  no  copy  of  his  own  ? 
However,  there  can  be  no  doubt  that  Coleridge's  feeling 
about  Spinoza  was  in  itself  deep  and  constant.  We  may  be 
sure  that  when  he  spoke  of  him  to  Wordsworth,  it  was  with 
earnestness  and  eloquence.  And  this,  when  we  consider 
Wordsworth's  position  in  English  literature,  is  a  matter  not 
without  importance.  It  seems  not  too  fanciful  to  suppose 
that  Coleridge's  expositions  of  Spinoza  may  have  counted  for 
something  in  the  speculative  strain  that  runs  through  so  much 
of  Wordsworth's  works,  and  thence,  at  one  more  remove,  in  the 
study  and  reverence  of  nature  which  most  cultivated  persons 
now  accept  as  a  matter  of  course,  but  which  in  Wordsworth's 
time  was  new,  and  to  not  a  iew  of  his  critics  appeared 
ridiculous.  The  impulse  of  artistic  nature-worship,  derived 
mainly  from  Wordsworth,  has  been  the  source,  in  one  way  or 
another,  of  nearly  everything  that  has  had  real  life  and  power 
in  the  English  art  and  poetry  of  this  century.  Let  it  not  be 
supposed  that  in  saying  this  we  claim  Wordsworth  as  a 
Spinozist.  The  views  of  man  and  the  world  more  or  less 
systematically  expressed  by  him  are  wholly  different  from 
Spinoza's,  though  it  would  not  be  difficult  to  find  apparent 
parallels  in  detail ;  ^  and  on  the  other  hand,  there  are  only  the 
slightest  hints  in  Spinoza  himself  of  the  possible  artistic 
bearings  of  Spinozism.  But  here  we  are  considering  not 
opinions  or  propositions  which  can  be  followed  or  discarded, 
nor  even  an  intellectual  habit,  but  an  aesthetic  temper  which 
may  be  induced  in  imaginative  minds  by  contact  with  forms 
and  systems  of  thought  aiming  in  the  first  instance  at  quite 
other  ends.     This  kind  of  influence  is  consistent  with  indif- 

'  Compare,  for  instance,  Spinoza's  'omnia,  diversis  tanien  gradibus,  animata 
sunt,'  with  ^Yordb\vorth's  Lities  ivyiitcn  in  Early  Spring. 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  463 

ference  or  even  opposition  in  other  regions.  And,  whatever 
may  be  thought  of  the  influence  on  Wordsworth  of  Coleridge's 
modified  Spinozism,  it  is  certain  that  Coleridge  and  Words- 
worth, above  all  others,  so  transformed  the  intellectual  at- 
mosphere of  England  as  to  make  it  possible  that  Spinoza 
should  in  due  time  be  studied  with  care  and  intelligence  even 
by  those  who  did  not  go  with  him  in  his  conclusions. 

Another  foremost  poet  of  that  time  is  now  known  to  have 
been  an  eager  student  of  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus,' 
if  not  of  the  metaphysical  part  of  Spinoza's  work.  A  quota- 
tion from  the  Tractatus  appears  in  the  notes  to  the  original 
edition  of  Shelley's  '  Queen  Mab,'  and  he  began  an  English 
translation  of  it.  A  fragment  of  the  MS,  came  by  some 
means  into  the  hands  of  Mr.  C.  S.  Middleton,  the  author 
of  a  book  on  '  Shelley  and  his  Writings  '  (London,  1858).  Mr. 
Middleton  took  this  for  an  original  work  of  Shelley's,  one  of 
the  *  school-boy  speculations  alluded  to  by  Medwin,'  and  con- 
sidered it  '  too  crude  for  publication  entire ' !  ^  In  the  winter 
of  1 82 1-2  Shelley  was  at  work  on  this  translation,  and  ob- 
tained a  promise  from  Byron  to  write  a  life  of  Spinoza  by 
way  of  preface  to  it.^  The  '  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus  ' 
translated  by  Shelley  and  introduced  by  Byron  would  have 
been  a  striking  addition  to  the  philosophizing  of  poets.  But 
the  plan  was  soon  cut  short  by  Shelley's  death  ;  and  though 
he  seems  to  have  made  some  way  in  the  translation,  none  of 
it  has  been  found,  save  the  fragment  above  mentioned  (perhaps 
a  rough  draft),  which  he  had  probably  left  with  other  papers 
in  England. 

Nearly    half    a   century   passed    from    the    time    when 

'  The  true  source  of  the  fragment  was  pointed  out  by  Mr.  J.  Oxenford.  Mr. 
Middleton,  in  acknowledging  the  correction,  suggested  that  Shelley  had  used  not 
Spinoza's  Latin,  but  a  French  version  [A/Jiciuridn,  Jan. -June,  1S58,  pp.  211-243). 
But  Shelley  cites  the  Latin  in  his  notes  to  Queen  Mab ;  and  I  find  his  English 
distinctly  nearer  to  the  Latin  than  to  the  old  French  translation  of  167S,  the  only 
one  then  in  existence. 

"^  See  Iiitroduclion,  p.  xx. 

D  D  2 


404  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

Coleridge  was  overheard  talking  of  the  mysterious  '  Spy 
Nozy'  before  Spinoza  was  taken  up  in  a  serious  way  by 
English  philosophical  criticism.  Among  the  first  to  draw 
attention  to  him  were  two  men  of  extremely  different  habits 
of  thought,  F.  D.  Maurice  and  G.  H.  Lewes.  They  ap- 
proached Spinoza  from  their  diverse  points  of  view,  the  one 
holding  a  transcendental  philosophy  which  almost  merged  in 
theology,  the  other  thinking  (at  least  when  he  first  wrote  of 
Spinoza)  that  philosophy  was  impossible.  They  naturally 
criticized  Spinoza's  system  on  widely  different  grounds  ;  but 
they  nevertheless  agreed  in  something  really  more  important, 
for  they  vied  with  one  another  in  appreciating  his  moral  and 
intellectual  grandeur.  Lewes's  work  on  this  subject  ranges 
over  a  long  time,  and  in  its  latest  form  is  still  recent ;  many 
English  readers  must  owe  to  it  their  first  conception  of 
Spinoza's  worth,  and  have  been  determined  by  it  to  study 
him  at  first  hand.  Two  English  writers  who  are  still  living, 
and  distinguished  in  other  fields  of  literature,  Mr.  Matthew 
Arnold  and  Mr.  Froude,  have  made  brilliant  contributions  to 
the  knowledge  of  Spinoza  in  this  country.  But  as  to  Mr. 
Arnold's  essay  on  the  '  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus,'  I 
find  one  serious  ground  of  complaint,  that  he  has  not  written 
another  on  the  '  Ethics.' 

In  France  the  study  of  Spinoza  was  taken  up  from 
Germany  by  the  school  of  philosophical  criticism  of  Avhich 
Victor  Cousin  was  the  chief.  The  tendency  of  the  school 
was  hostile  to  Spinoza's  philosophy  and  all  ways  of  thinking 
allied  to  it,  and  remains  so  to  this  day  so  far  as  its  traditions 
have  been  kept  up.  Nothing  else  could  be  expected  from 
a  philosophy  which  was  in  effect  a  revival  of  French  Car- 
tesianism  and  was  proud  of  its  ancestry.  But  if  Spinoza  met 
with  little  sympathy  from  French  philosophers  of  the  official 
school— which,  as  a  school,  may  be  now  considered  extinct — 
he  met  with  careful  discussion,  The  introduction  to  Saisset's 
translation  of  his  works  is  about  the  best  adverse  criticism  of 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  405 

Spinoza  with  which  I  am  acquainted.  More  lately  Spinoza 
has  been  handled  by  M.  Paul  Janet  in  the  candid  and  im- 
partial spirit  of  the  scientific  historian,  and  by  M.  Renan 
with  delicate  insight  and  sympathy,  and  the  eloquence  of 
which  he  is  an  unrivalled  master.  Meanwhile  philosophy  is 
being  more  and  more  followed  in  France,  as  well  as  elsewhere, 
in  a  spirit  of  disinterested  earnestness  and  with  a  faithfulness 
to  scientific  method  of  which  much  may  be  expected  in  no 
distant  future.  In  this  movement  there  is  yet  another  assur- 
ance that  Spinoza  will  not  fail  to  receive  his  due  from  the 
best  and  most  vigorous  thought  of  modern  France. 

M.  Taine,  who  stands  at  the  head  of  the  French  scientific 
school,  has  given  in  his  principal  work,  '  De  I'lntelligence,'  a 
discussion  of  the  relations  of  mind  and  matter  which  is 
thoroughly  in  accordance  with  the  spirit  of  Spinoza's  doctrine. 
I  refer  especially  to  his  development  of  the  thesis,  '  la  nature 
a  deux  faces,'  where  the  coincidence  is  complete,  or  all  but 
complete.^ 

Turning  our  eyes  again  to  Spinoza's  own  land,  we  find  in 
the  last  twenty  years  a  revival  of  interest  in  him  which, 
though  late  in  its  beginning,  has  already  obtained  consider- 
able importance.  The  way  was  led  by  Dr.  van  Vloten,  to 
whom  is  due  the  first  publication  of  Spinoza's  *  Essay  of  God 
and  Man,'  and  of  several  letters  and  parts  of  letters  which  had 
been  withheld  by  the  original  editors  of  the  'Opera  Posthuma.' 
Other  scholars  and  critics  have  followed  him  with  good  effect, 
and  the  two-hundredth  anniversary  of  Spinoza's  death,  which 
fell  in  1877,  g^ve  occasion  for  a  sort  of  concentration  of  their - 
activity.  It  was  decided  to  invite  subscriptions  from  all 
civilized  countries  in  order  to  erect  a  statue  of  Spinoza  at  the 
Hague,  in  sight  of  the  spot  where  he  passed  the  latter  years 
of  his  life.  This  project  could  not  be  carried  out  in  time 
for  the  anniversary  itself,  which  was  nevertheless  fitly 
celebrated,    M.    Renan  contributing    a  discourse    of    which 

'  De  rintcUigcnce,  Part  I.  Bk.  4,  ch.  ii.,  and  Part  II,  Bk.  2,  ch.  i. 


4o6  SPINOZA  :  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

something  has  already  been  said.  At  the  same  time  Pro- 
fessor Land  of  Leyden  gave  a  special  lecture  on  Spinoza's 
philosophy  in  the  regular  academic  course,  which  has  been 
printed  with  illustrative  and  critical  notes,  and  in  this 
form  constitutes  one  of  the  most  valuable  monographs  we 
now  possess  on  the  subject.  Altogether,  Spinoza  has  fared 
better  in  his  own  country  in  the  last  few  years  than  he  ever 
did  before.  Neither  has  reaction  been  wanting  to  prove  the 
solidity  of  the  movement,  if  more  proof  were  needed.  There 
was  a  pretty  sharp  recrudescence  among  orthodox  journal- 
ists, critics,  and  theologians  of  the  old  polemic  against 
Spinoza.  Some  of  these  criticisms  were  able  and  digni- 
fied, but  the  greater  part  copied  with  little  alteration  the 
violence  and  ignorance  exhibited  by  their  predecessors  two 
centuries  ago.  I  had  the  advantage  of  seeing  a  set  of 
articles  from  a  certain  Flemish  ultramontane  journal,  which 
not  only  pronounced  Spinoza  a  second-rate  sophist,  but 
would  not  allow  M.  Renan  to  be  capable  of  writing  French. 
His  style  was  gravely  described  as  '  flasque  et  enerve.' 
It  would  be  difficult  to  decide  whether  this  remarkable  judg- 
ment proceeded  from  the  imbecility  of  impotent  rage,  or  from 
the  impudence  of  a  dogmatist  assured  that  his  audience 
would  accept  anything. 

However,  the  plan  formed  by  a  committee  of  Dutch 
scholars  to  do  honour  to  Spinoza  in  his  dwelling-place  met 
with  no  serious  obstacle  beyond  a  certain  amount  of  un- 
avoidable delay.  Subscriptions  came  in  gradually  indeed, 
but  in  sufficient  amount  to  ensure  ultimate  success ;  and  it  is 
worth  noting  that,  next  to  the  Netherlands,  Great  Britain 
bore  the  chief  part  in  this  work.  But  of  the  designs  for  a 
statue  which  were  furnished  by  several  competitors,  that  of 
M.  Frederic  Hexamer,  a  young  Parisian  sculptor,  was  chosen 
by  the  Committee.  The  bronze  casting  was  completed  in 
the  course  of  the  present  year,  and  on  September  14  the 
monument  was  unveiled  and  handed  over  to  the  municipal 


SPINOZA   AND  MODERN  THOUGHT.  407 

authorities  of  the  Hague.     Meanwhile,  by  a  happy  coinci- 
dence,   the    house    in    the    Paviljoensgracht   where    Spinoza 
lodged    had    been     identified    beyond    doubt,    though    the 
fabric    has  been   rebuilt  since  his  time.      The  spot  is  now 
marked  by  a  tablet  let   into  the  wall,  and   inscribed  with  a 
short  record.     But  a  word   must  be   said  of  M.   Hexamer's 
work  :    it  presents  the  philosopher  in  a  s'tting  posture,  his 
head  bending  down  on  one  hand  as  if  making  a  pause  in  his 
writing  to  think  over  some  new  question.     The  figure,  as 
befits  the  subject,  is  dignified,  not  by  idealised  features  or 
any  conventional  pose,  but   simply    by  being    natural    and 
unafi"ected.     The  pedestal  bears  for   all  inscription  the  one 
word  :    SPINOZA.     This  is  as  it  should  be,  for  thus  the  be- 
holder has  no  particular  gloss  on  Spinoza's  teaching  thrust 
upon  him,  and  may  rest  undisturbed  in  that  way  of  regarding 
Spinoza's  worth  which  suits  him  best.     Thus,  too,  it  is  made 
manifest,  as  was  from  the  first  the  earnest  desire  of  all  con- 
cerned, that  the  homage  paid  to  Spinoza  is  not  that  of  any 
particular  school  or  sect.      There  have  appeared  as  fellow- 
workers    in    this    cause    men    whose    general    philosophical 
opinions,   whose  readings  of  Spinoza's  doctrine,   and  whose 
estimate  of  its  value  as  a  finished  system  of  thought,  are 
widely  different.     For  like  reasons  the  assistance  of  students 
of  philosophy  in  other  lands   was  invited,  not  so  much  in 
the  hope  of  obtaining  large  contributions  as  for   the    sake 
of  showing  that  Spinoza's  fame  belongs  not  to  one  country, 
but  to  every  place  where  men  are  found  to  think  seriously 
on  the  deepest  problems  of  life.     The  names  of  men  illus- 
trious in  philosophy  and  literature  in  England,  France,  and 
Germany,  men  otherwise  separated  from  one  another  in  their 
occupations,  pursuits,  and  beliefs,  were  inscribed  side  by  side 
on  the  roll  of  supporters.      And   thus   the  nature  and    the 
power  of  Spinoza's  work  are  most  fitly  symbolized  ;  thus  he 
would  himself  have  desired  to  be  commemorated.     His  aim 
was  not  to  leave  behind  him  disciples  pledged  to  the  letter  of 


4o8  SPINOZA:  HIS  LIFE  AND  PHILOSOPHY. 

his  teaching,  but  to  lead  men  to  think  with  him  by  teaching 
them  to  think  freely  and  rightly  for  themselves.     We  said  at  ^ 
the  beginning  of  this  chapter  that  Spinozism,  as  a  living  and 
constructive  force,  is  not  a  system  but  a  habit  of  mind.     And, 
as  science  makes  it  plainer  every  day  that  there  is  no  such 
thing  as  a  fixed  equilibrium  either  in  the  world  without  or  in 
the  mind  within,  so  it  becomes  plain  that  the  genuine  and 
durable  triumphs  of  philosophy  are  not  in  systems  but  in  ideas. 
Wealth  in  vital  ideas  is  the  real  test  of  a  philosopher's  great- ^ 
ness,  and  by  this  test  the  name  of  Spinoza  stands  assured  of 
its  rank  among  the   greatest.     We  who  have  thus  far  en- 
deavoured, however  imperfectly,  to   follow   the   working  of 
Spinoza's  mind,  and  to  explain  his  thoughts  in  the  language  of 
our  own  time,  honour  him  even  more  for  that  which  he  sug- 
gested, seeing  the  far-off  dawn  of  new  truths  as  in  a  vision, 
than  for  that  which  his  hands  made  perfect.     Not  even  from 
those  whom  we  most  reverence  can  we  accept  any  system  as 
final.    A  speculative  system  is  a  work  of  art ;  it  is  an  attempts 
to  fix  an  ideal,  and  in  the  very  act  of  thought  which  marks  it 
off  with  individual  form  the  ideal  is  transformed  and  drawn 
up  into  a  still  unexplored  region.     Experience  and  science 
combine  to  warn  us  against  putting  our  faith  in  symbols  which 
should  be  but  aids  to  thought.     The  word  that  lived  on  the 
master's  lips  becomes  a  dead  catchword    in  the  mouth  of 
scholars  who  have  learnt  only  half  his  lesson.     And  therefore 
it  will  still  be  in  time  to  come  that  when  men  of  impatient 
mind  cry  out  for  systems  and  formulas,  demanding  to  possess 
the  secret  of  all  wisdom  once  for  all,  there  will  be  no  better 
answer  for  them  than  was  given  long   ago  by  the  son  of 
Sirach  :   The  first  man  knew  her  not  perfectly  ;  no  moi'e  shall 
the  last  find  her  out.     For  her  thoughts  are  nioi'e  than  the  sea, 
and  her  counsels  profonnder  than  the  great  deep. 


APPENDIX    A. 


THE    LIFE    OF    SPINOZA. 

By  COLERUS. 


The  English  version  of  Colerus  is  an  indifferently  printed  small  octavo 
of  92  pages.  I  do  not  know  that  it  has  ever  been  reprinted.  In  the  present 
reprint  obvious  errors  and  misprints  in  English  words,  such  as  absta-'d  for 
absurd,  Jttgdment,  Preson,  for  Judgment,  Person,  and  the  like,  as  well  as 
obvious  errors  of  the  press  in  punctuation,  have  been  tacitly  corrected  ;  but  all 
genuine  peculiarities  of  spelling,  punctuation,  &c.,  have  been  preserved,  even 
to  such  blunders  as  essensually  for  essentially.  These  things  belong  to  the 
character  of  the  time  no  less  than  the  style  of  the  writing  itself. 

Another  little  book,  entitled  'An  Account  of  the  Life  and  Writings  of 
Spinosa '  &c.  (London,  1720,  8vo.  Bibliogr.  no,  105)  is  a  servile  abridgment  of 
this  translation,  pp.  1-27,  followed  by  an  epitome  of  the  Tractatus  Theologico- 
politicus,  pp.  28-96. 


i 


THE 

LIFE 

OF 


BENEDICT 


DE 


S  P  I  N  O  S  A. 


Written  b)^  John  Colerus,  Minister 

of  the  Lutheran  Church,  at  the 

Hague. 


DoJie  out  of  French. 


LONDON. 

Printed  by  D.  L.  And  Sold  by  Benj.  Bragg, 
at  the  Raven  in  Pater-Nosier  Roiv,  1706. 


THE 

LIFE 

OF 

B.     D  e     S  p  ino  s  a, 

C^FINOSA,  that  Philosopher,  whose  name  makes  so  great  noise  in 
*^  the  World,  was  originally  a  Jew.  His  parents,  a  little  while 
after  his  birth,  named  him  Baruch.  But  having  afterwards  forsaken 
/udaism,  he  changed  his  Name,  and  call'd  himself  Benedict  in  his 
Writings,  and  in  the  Letters  which  he  subscrib'd.  He  was  Born  at 
Ajnsterdain  the  24th-  of  November,  in  the  Year  1632.  What  is  com- 
monly said,  that  lie  was  Poor  and  of  a  very  mean  Extraction,  is  not 
true.  His  Father,  a  Portuguese  Jew,  was  in  very  good  Circumstances, 
and  a  Merchant  at  Amsterdam,  where  he  lived  upon  the  Burgwal,  in 
a  good  House  near  the  Old  Portuguese  Synagogue.  Besides,  his  civil 
and  handsome  behaviour,  his  Relations,  who  lived  at  ease,  and  what 
was  left  to  him  by  his  Father  and  Mother,  prove  that  his  Extraction, 
as  well  as  his  Education,  was  above  that  of  the  Common  People. 
Samuel  Carceris,  a  Portuguese  Jew,  married  the  Youngest  of  his  two 
Sisters.  The  name  of  the  Eldest  was  Rebeckah,  and  that  of  the 
Youngest  Miriam,  whose  Son  Daniel  Carceris,  Nephew  to  Benedict 
de  Spinosa,  declared  himself  one  of  his  Heirs  after  his  Decease  :  As  it 
appears  by  an  Act  past  before  Libcrtus  Loef,  a  Notary,  the  30th  of 
March  1677,  in  the  form  of  a  Procuration  directed  to  Henry  Vander 
Spyck,  in  whose  House  Spinosa  Lodged  when  he  died. 

Spinosa's  first  Studies. 

Spinosa  shewed  from  his  Childhood,  and  in  his  younger  years, 
that  Nature  had  not  been  unkind  to  him.  His  quick  fancy,  and  his 
ready  and  penetrating  Wit  were  easily  perceived.  Because  he  had  a 
great  Mind  to  learn  the  Latin  Tongue,  they  gave  him  at  first  a 
German  Master.     But  afterwards  in  order  to  perfect  himself  in  that 


414  APPENDIX. 

Language,  he  made  use  of  the  famous  Fi-ancis  Vandcn  Ende,  who 
taught  it  then  in  Avistcrdam,  and  practis'd  Physick  at  the  same  time: 
That  Man  taught  with  good  Success  and  a  great  Reputation  ;  so  that 
the  Richest  Merchants  of  that  City  intrusted  him  with  the  instruction 
of  their  Children,  before  they  had  found  out  that  he  taught  his 
Scholars  something  else  besides  Latin.  For  it  was  discovered  at 
last,  that  he  sowed  the  first  Seeds  of  Atheism  in  the  Minds  of  those 
Young  Boys.  This  is  a  matter  of  fact,  which  I  cou'd  prove,  if  there 
was  any  necessity  for  it,  by  the  Testimony  of  several  honest  Gentle- 
men, who  are  still  living,  and  some  of  whom  have  been  Elders  of  the 
Lutheran  Church  at  Amsterdam.  Those  good  men  bless  every  day 
the  Memory  of  their  Parents,  who  took  care  in  due  time  to  remove 
them  from  the  School  of  so  pernicious  and  so  impious  a  Master. 

Vanden  Ende  had  an  only  Daughter,  who  understood  the  Latin 
Tongue,  as  well  as  Musick,  so  perfectly,  that  she  was  able  to  teach 
her  Fathers  Scholars  in  his  absence.     Spinosa  having  often  occasion 
to  see  and  speak  to  her,  grew  in*  Love  with  her,  and  he  has  often 
confest  that  he  design'd  to  marry  her.     She  was  none  of  the  most 
Beautiful,  but  she  had  a  great  deal  of  Wit,  a  great  Capacity  and  a 
jovial  Humour,  which  wrought  upon  the  Heart  of  Spinosa,  as  well  as 
upon  another  Scholar  of  Vanden  Ende,  whose  name  was  Kerkering,  a 
Native  of  Llambnrgh.     The  latter  did  soon  perceive  that  he  had  a 
Rival,  and  grew  Jealous  of  him.     This  moved  him  to  redouble  his 
care,  and  his  attendance  upon  his  Mistress  :  which  he  did  with  good 
success  :  But  a  Neck-lace  of  Pearls,  of  the  value  of  two  or  three 
hundred  Pistoles,  which   he   had  before  presented  to  that  Young 
Woman,  did  without  doubt  contribute  to  win  her  Affection.     She 
therefore  promised  to  Marry  him  :  Which  she  did  faithfully  perform, 
when  the  Sieur  Kerkering  had  abjured  the  Lutheran  Religion,  which 
he  profest,  and  embraced  the  Roman  Catholick.     See  the  preface  of 
Kortholt  de  trihus  Lmpostoribus,  of  the  2nd  Edition. 

As  for  Vanden  Ende,  being  too  well  known  in  Holland,  to  find 
any  Employment  there,  he  was  obliged  to  look  for  it  somewhere  else. 
He  went  into  France,  where  he  had  a  Tragical  end,  after  he  had 
maintained  himself  for  some  years  with  what  he  got  by  practising 
Physick.  Some  say  that  he  was  Condemn'd  to  be  hanged,  and 
Executed,  for  having  attempted  upon  the  Dauphins  Life  ;  but  others, 
who  knew  him  particularly  in  France,  own  indeed  that  he  was  hanged, 
but  they  give  another  reason  for  it.  They  say  that  Va?iden  Ende 
endeavour'd  to  cause  an  Insurrection  in  one  of  the  Provinces  of 
France^  the  Lihabitants  whereof  hoped  by  that  means  to  be  restored 


APPENDIX.        '  415 

to  their  Ancient  Priviledges  ;  and  that  he  designed  thereby  to  free 
the  United  Provinces  from  the  oppression  they  were  under,  by 
giving  so  much  work  to  the  King  of  France  in  his  own  Country,  as 
to  obUge  him  to  keep  a  great  part  of  his  Forces  in  that  Kingdom. 
That  in  order  to  facilitate  the  Execution  of  that  design,  some  Ships 
were  fitted  out,  but  that  they  arrived  too  late.  However  it  be,  Van- 
dcn  Ende  was  executed,  but  if  he  had  attempted  upon  the  Dauphin's 
Life,  'tis  likely  that  he  wou'd  have  expiated  his  crime  in  another 
manner,  and  by  a  more  rigorous  Punishment. 

He  applies  Himself  to  the  Study  of  Divinity,  and  then  to 

Natural  Philosophy. 

Spinosa  having  learn'd  the  Latin  Tongue  well,  applied  him- 
self to  the  Study  of  Divinity  for  some  years.  In  the  mean  time 
his  Wit  and  Judgment  encreased  every  day  :  So  that  finding  himself 
more  disposed  to  enquire  into  Natural  Causes,  he  gave  over  Divinity, 
and  betook  himself  altogether  to  the  Study  of  Natural  Philosophy. 
He  did  for  a  long  time  deliberate  about  the  choice  he  shou'd  make 
of  a  Master,  whose  Writing  might  serve  him  as  a  Guide  in  his  design. 
At  last,  having  light  upon  the  Works  of  Descartes,  he  read  them 
greedily ;  and  after^vards  he  often  declared  that  he  had  all  his 
Philosophical  Knowledge  from  him.  He  was  charmed  with  that 
Maxim  of  Descartes,  Which  says.  That  nothing  ought  to  be  admitted  as 
True,  but  what  has  been  proved  by  good  arid  solid  Reasons.  From 
whence  he  drew  this  Consequence,  that  the  ridiculous  Doctrine  and 
Principles  of  the  Rabbins  cou'd  not  be  admitted  by  a  Man  of  Sense ; 
because  they  are  only  built  upon  the  Authority  of  the  Rabbins  them- 
selves, and  because  what  they  teach,  does  not  proceed  from  God, 
as  they  pretend  without  any  ground  for  it,  and  without  the  least 
appearance  of  Reason. 

From  that  time  he  began  to  be  very  much  reserved  amongst  the 
Jewish  Doctors,  whom  he  shunned  as  much  as  he  cou'd  :  He  was 
seldom  seen  in  their  Synagogues,  whither  he  went  only  perfunctorily, 
M-hich  exasperated  them  against  him  to  the  highest  degree ;  for  they 
did  not  doubt  but  that  he  wou'd  soon  leave  them,  and  make  himself 
a  Christian.  Yet,  to  speak  the  trutli,  he  never  embraced  Christianity, 
nor  received  the  Holy  Baptism  :  And  tho  he  had  frequent  conversa- 
tions with  some  learn'd  Mennonites,  as  well  as  with  the  most  eminent 
Divines  of  other  Christian  Sects,  yet  he  never  declared  for,  nor 
profest  himself  to  be  a  Member  of  any  of  them. 


41 6  APPENDIX. 

Francis  Halma  says,  in  the  Account  of  Sptnosa,  which  he 
published  in  Dutch ^  that  the  Jeivs  offered  him  a  Pension  a  Uttle 
while  before  his  Desertion,  to  engage  him  to  remain  amongst  'em,  and 
to  appear  Jiow  and  then  in  their  Synagogues.  This  Spinosa  himself 
affirmed  several  times  to  the  Sieur  Vander  Spyck,  his  Landlord,  and 
to  some  other  Persons  ;  adding,  that  the  Pension,  which  the  Rabbins 
design'd  to  give  him,  amounted  to  looo  Florins.  But  he  protested 
at  the  same  time,  that  if  they  had  offered  him  ten  times  as  much,  he 
wou'd  not  have  accepted  of  it,  nor  frequented  their  Assemblies  out 
of  such  a  motive  ;  because  he  was  not  a  Hypocrite,  and  minded 
nothing  but  Truth.  Monsieur  Bayle  tells  us.  That  he  happen'd  one 
day  to  be  assaulted  by  a  Jew,  as  he  was  coming  out  of  the  Play- 
house, who  wounded  him  in  the  Face  with  a  Knife,  and  that  Spinosa 
knew  that  the  yew  design'd  to  kill  him,  tho  his  wound  was  not  danger- 
ous. But  Spinosa^s  Landlord  and  his  Wife,  who  are  still  living,  give 
me  quite  another  account  of  it.  They  had  it  from  Spinosa  himself, 
who  did  often  tell  them,  that  one  evening  as  he  was  coming  out  of  the 
Old  Portuguese  Synagogue,  he  saw  a  Man  by  him  with  a  Dagger  in 
his  Hand  ;  whereupon  standing  upon  his  guard,  and  going  back- 
wards, he  avoided  the  blow,  which  reached  no  farther  than  his 
Cloaths.  He  kept  still  tlie  Coat  that  was  run  thro'  with  the  Dagger, 
as  a  Memorial  of  that  event.  Afterwards,  not  thinking  himself  to  be 
safe  at  Amsterdam,  he  resolved  to  retire  somewhere  else  with  the 
first  opportunity.  Besides,  he  was  desirous  to  go  on  with  his  Studies 
and  Physical  Meditations  in  a  quiet  Retreat. 

He  was  excommunicated  by  the  Jews. 

He  had  no  sooner  left  the  Communion  of  the  Jews,  but  they  pro- 
secuted him  Juridically  according  to  their  Ecclesiastical  Laws,  and 
Excommunicated  him.  He  himself  did  very  often  own  that  he  was 
Exconniiunicatecl  by  them,  and  declared,  that  from  that  time  he 
broke  all  Friendship  and  Correspondence  with  them.  Some  Je^us 
of  Amsterdam,  who  knew  Spinosa  very  well,  have  also  confirmed  to 
me  the  truth  of  that  fact,  adding,  that  the  Sentence  of  Excom- 
munication  was  publickly  pronounced  by  the  Old  Man  Chacham 
Ahuabh,  a  Rabbin  of  great  Reputation  amongst  'em.  1  have 
desired  in  vain  the  Sons  of  that  old  Rabbin  to  communicate  that 
Sentence  to  me;  they  answered  me,  that  they  could  not   find    it 

'  [This  was  a  translation  from  Bayle's  Dictionary,  as  Colerus  himself  afterwards 
says.] 


APPENDIX.  417 

amongst  the  Papers  of  their  Father,  but  I  cou'd  easily  perceive  that 

they  had  no  mind  to  impart  it  to  me.^ 

******* 


Spinosa  learns  a  Trade  or  a  Mechanical  A  rt. 

The  Law  and  the  antient  Jrivish  Doctors  do  expressly  say,  that 
it  is  not  enough  for  a  man  to  be  learned,  but  that  he  ought  besides  to 
learn  a  Profession  or  a  Mechanical  Art,  that  it  may  be  a  help  to  him 
in  case  of  necessity,  and  that  he  may  get  wherewith  to  maintain  him- 
self. This  Rabbin  Gamaliel  does  positively  say  in  the  Treatise  of 
the  Talmuel  Pirke  avoth  Chap.  2.  where  he  teaches,  that  the  study  of 
the  Law  is  a  very  desirable  thing,  when  it  is  attended  with  a  Profession 
or  a  Mechanical  Art  :  For,  says  he,  a  continual  application  to  those 
two  exercises  keeps  a  Man  from  doing  Evil,  and  makes  him  forget  it  ; 
and  every  Learned  Man  who  neglects  to  learn  a  Profession,  will  at 
last  turn  a  loose  Man.  And  Rabbi  Jelmda  adds,  that  every  Man,  who 
does  not  take  care  that  his  children  shou'd  learn  a  Trade,  does  the 
same  thing  as  if  he  taught  them  how  to  become  High-way-men. 

Spinosa  being  well  versed  in  the  Study  of  the  Law,  and  of  the 
Customs  of  the  Ancients,  was  not  ignorant  of  those  Maxims,  and  did 
not  forget  them,  tho  he  was  separated  from  the  Jews,  and  excommu- 
nicated by  them.  Because  they  are  wise  and  reasonable  Maxims  he 
made  a  good  use  of  'em,  and  learned  a  Mechanical  Art  before  he 
embraced  a  quiet  and  a  retir'd  Life,  as  he  was  resolv'd  to  do.  He 
learned  therefore  to  make  Glasses  for  Telescopes,  and  for  some 
other  uses,  and  succeeded  so  well  therein,  that  People  came  to  him 
from  all  Parts  to  buy  them  ;  which  did  sufficiently  afford  him  where- 
with to  live  and  maintain  himself  A  considerable  number  of  tliose 
Glasses,  which  he  had  polished,  were  found  in  his  Cabinet  after  his 
death,  and  sold  pretty  dear,  as  it  appears  by  the  Register  of  the 
Publick  Cryer,  who  was  present  at  the  Sale  of  his  Goods. 

After  he  had  perfected  himself  in  that  Art,  he  apply'd  himself  to 
Drawing,  which  he  learn'd  of  himself,  and  he  cou'd  draw  a  Head  very 
well  with  Ink,  or  with  a  Coal.  I  have  in  my  Hands  a  whole  Ilook  of 
such  Draughts,  amongst  which  there  are  some  Heads  of  several  con- 
siderable Persons,  who  were  known  to  him,  or  who  had  occasion  to 

'  Colerus  proceeds  to  discuss  the  Jewish  law  and  practice  of  excommunication, 
and  inserts  a  form  communicated  to  him  by  Surenhusius.  The  shorter  form 
actually  used  in  Spinoza's  case,  and  first  made  known  by  Van  Vloten,  has  already 
been  given  in  the  text,  p.  18  above.  A  revised  version  of  that  set  out  by 
Colerus  may  be  seen  in  G.  II.  Lcwes's  Ilisl.  of  P/iiloso/'Iiy,  ii.  165  (3rded.). 


41 2  APPENDIX. 

visit  him.  Among  those  Draughts  I  find  in  the  4th  Sheet  a  Fisher- 
man having  only  his  Shirt  on,  with  a  Net  on  his  Right  Shoulder,  whose 
Attitude  is  very  much  like  that  of  Massanello  '  the  famous  Head  of 
the  Rebels  of  Naples,  as  it  appears  by  History,  and  by  his  Cuts.^ 
Which  gives  me  occasion  to  add,  that  Mr.  Va/tder  Spyck,  at  whose 
House  Spinosa  lodged  when  he  died,  has  assured  me,  that  the  Draught 
of  that  Fisherman  did  perfectly  resemble  Spinosa,  and  that  he  had 
certainly  drawn  himself  I  need  not  mention  the  considerable 
Persons,  whose  Heads  are  likewise  to  be  found  in  this  Book,  amongst 
his  other  Draughts. 

Thus  he  was  able  to  maintain  himself  with  the  work  of  his  Hands, 
and  to  mind  his  Study,  as  he  design'd  to  do.  So  that  having  no 
occasion  to  stay  longer  in  Amsterdam,  he  left  it,  and  took  Lodgings 
in  the  House  of  one  of  his  Acquaintance,  who  lived  upon  the  Road 
from  Amsterdam  to  Ainverkerke.  He  spent  his  time  there  in  study- 
ing, and  working  his  Glasses.  When  they  were  polished,  his  Friends 
took  care  to  send  for  them,  to  sell  'em,  and  to  remit  his  Money  to 
him. 

He  zvent  to  live  at  Rynsburg,  afterwards  at  Voorburg,  a7id  at 

last  at  the  Hague. 

In  the  year  1664  Spinosa  left  that  place,  and  retired  to  Rynsburg 
near  Leyden,  where  he  spent  all  the  Winter,  and  then  he  went  to 
Voorburg,  a  league  from  the  Hague,  as  he  himself  says,  in  his  30th 
Letter  written  to  Peter  Balling^^  He  lived  there,  as  I  am  informed, 
three  or  four  years  ;  during  which  time,  he  got  a  great  many  Friends 
at  the  Hague,  who  were  all  distinguisht  by  their  Quality,  or  by  Civil 
and  Military  Employments.  They  were  often  in  his  Company,  and 
took  a  great  delight  in  hearing  him  discourse.  It  was  at  their  re- 
quest that  he  settl'd  himself  at  the  Hague  2X  last,  where  he  boarded  at 
first  upon  the  Veerkaay,  at  a  Widow's  whose  Name  was  Va?t  Velde/i,  m 
the  same  House  where  I  lodge  at  present.  The  Room  wherein  I  study, 
at  the  further  end  of  the  House  backward,  two  pair  of  Stairs,  is  the 
same  where  he  lay,  and  where  he  did  work  and  study.  He  wou'd 
very  often  have  his  ]\Ieat  brought  into  that  Room,  where  he  kept 
sometimes  two  or  three  days,  without  seeing  any  Body.  But  being 
sensible  that  he  spent  a  little  too  much  for  his  Boarding,  he  took  a 

'    Sic. 

'  Fr.  'comme  il  est  reprcsente  clans  rHistoirc  Gt  en  Taille-douce.' 
'  Misprinted  Kallin^  in  llic  En^libh  \xr.sion. 


APPENDIX.  419 

Room  upon  the  Pavi'Iioengrachf,  behind  my  House,  at  Mr.  Hejtry 
Vatider  Spyck's,  whom  I  have  often  mention'd,  where  he  took  care  to 
furnish  himself  with  Meat  and  Drink,  and  where  he  lived  a  very 
retired  Life,  according  to  his  fancy. 

He  was  very  Sober,  and  very  Frugal. 

It  is  scarce  credible  how  sober  and  frugal  he  was  all  the  time.  Not 
that  he  was  reduced  to  so  great  a  Poverty,  as  not  to  be  able  to  spend 
more,  if  he  had  been  willing ;  he  had  Friends  enough,  who  offered 
him  their  Purses,  and  all  manner  of  assistance  :  But  he  was  naturally 
very  sober,  and  could  be  satisfied  with  little ;  and  he  did  not  care 
that  People  shou'd  think  that  he  had  lived,  even  but  once,  at  the 
expence  of  other  Men.  "What  I  say  about  his  Sobriety  and  good 
Husbandry,  may  be  proVd  by  several  small  Reckonings,  which  have 
been  found  amongst  his  Papers  after  his  death.  It  appears  by  them, 
that  he  lived  a  whole  day  upon  a  Milk-soop  done  with  Butter,  which 
amounted  to  three  pence,  and  upon  a  Pot  of  Beer  of  three  half  pence. 
Another  day  he  eat  nothing  but  Gruel  done  with  Raisins  and 
Butter,  and  that  Dish  cost  him  fourpence  half  penny.  There  are 
but  two  half  pints  of  Wine  at  most  for  one  Month  to  be  found 
amongst  those  Reckonings,  and  tho  he  was  often  invited  to  eat  with 
his  Friends,  he  chose  rather  to  live  upon  what  he  had  at  home,  tho 
it  were  never  so  little,  than  to  sit  down  at  a  good  Table  at  the  expence 
of  another  Man. 

Thus  he  spent  the  remaining  part  of  his  life  in  the  House  of  his 
last  Landlord,  which  was  somewhat  above  five  years  and  a  half. 
He  was  very  careful  to  cast  up  his  Accounts  every  Quarter ;  which 
he  did,  that  he  might  spend  neither  more  nor  less  than  what  he  could 
spend  every  year.  And  he  would  say  sometimes  to  the  people  of  the 
House,  that  he  was  like  the  Serpent,  who  forms  a  Circle  with  his 
Tail  in  his  Mouth  ;  to  denote  that  he  had  nothing  left  at  the  years 
end.  He  added,  that  he  design'd  to  lay  up  no  more  Money  than 
what  would  be  necessary  for  him  to  have  a  decent  Bur}dng ;  and 
that,  as  his  Parents  had  left  him  nothing,  so  his  Heirs  and  Relations 
should  not  expect  to  get  much  by  his  Death. 

His  Person,  and  his  zvay  of  Dressing  himself. 

As  for  his  Person,  his  Size,  and  the  features  of  his  Face,  there 
are  still  many  people  at  the  Hague,  who  saw  and  knew  him  par- 
ticularly.    He  was  of  a  middle  size,  he  had  good  features  in  his  Face, 

*  E  E  2 


420  APPENDIX. 

the  Skin  somewhat  black,  black  curl'd  Hair,  long  Eye-brows,  and  of 
the  same  Colour,  so  that  one  might  easily  know  by  his  Looks  that 
he  was  descended  from  Portugicese  Je^vs.  As  for  his  Cloaths,  he  was 
very  careless  of  'ern,  and  they  were  not  better  than  those  of  the 
meanest  Citizen.  One  of  the  most  eminent  Councellors  of  State 
went  to  see  him,  and  found  him  in  a  very  slovenly  Morning-Gown, 
whereupon  the  Councellor  blam'd  him  for  it,  and  offer'd  him  another. 
Spinosa  answer'd  him,  that  a  Man  was  never  the  better  for  having  a 
finer  Gown.  To  which  he  added,  //  is  unreasonable  to  wrap  up  things 
of  little  or  no  value  in  a  precioics  Cover.  • 

His  Maimers f  his  ConversatioUy  mid  his  Uniiiterestedness. 

If  he  was  very  frugal  in  his  way  of  living,  his  Conversation  was 
also  very  sweet  and  easy.  He  knew  admirably  well  how  to  be 
master  of  his  Passions  :  He  was  never  seen  very  melancholy,  nor 
very  merry.  He  had  the  command  of  his  Anger,  and  if  at  any  time 
he  was  uneasy  in  his  mind,  it  did  not  appear  outwardly  ;  or  if  he 
happen'd  to  express  his  grief  by  some  gestures,  or  by  some  words,  he 
never  fail'd  to  retire  immediately,  for  fear  of  doing  an  unbecoming 
thing.  He  was  besides,  very  courteous  and  obliging,  he  would 
very  often  discourse  with  his  Landlady,  especially  when  she  lay  in, 
and  with  the  people  of  the  House,  when  they  happen'd  to  be  sick  or 
afflicted  \  he  never  fail'd  then  to  confort  ^  'em,  and  exhort  them  to 
bear  with  Patience  those  Evils,  which  God  assigned  to  them  as  a 
Lot.  He  put  the  Children  in  mind  of  going  often  to  Church,  and 
taught  them  to  be  obedient  and  dutiful  to  their  Parents.  When  the 
people  of  the  House  came  from  Church,  he  wou'd  often  ask  them 
what  they  had  leam'd,  and  what  they  cou'd  remember  of  the  Sermon. 
He  had  a  great  esteem  for  Dr.  Cordes,  my  Predecessor ;  who  was  a 
learned  and  good  natured  Man,  and  of  an  exemplary  Life,  which 

'  But  see  the  Treatise  of  God  and  Man,  part  ii.  cap.  12,  where  Spinoza  says 
that  it  is  fit  for  us  to  take  notice  of  men's  common  feelings  and  prejudices,  and 
that  sometimes  we  are  even  bound  to  abridge  our  otherwise  lawful  freedom  :  thus 
it  is  wrong  to  wear  costly  apparel  for  mere  show  and  selfish  pride  :  '  but  if  a  man 
sees  that  his  wisdom.,  whereby  he  might  profit  his  neighbours,  is  despised  and 
trodden  under  foot  because  he  is  ill  clad,  then  he  does  well  to  furnish  himself 
from  desire  to  help  his  neighbours)  with  such  clothing  as  offends  them  not.'  We 
may  therefore  believe  Lucas  when  he  tells  us  that  Spinoza,  so  far  from  being 
habitually  careless  of  his  appearance,  was  scrupulously  neat  :  '  il  ne  sortoit  jamais 
qu'on  ne  vit  paroitre  en  ses  habits  ce  qui  distingue  d'ordinaire  un  honnete  Homme 
d'un  Tedant.' 

2  Sic. 


APPENDIX.  421 

gave  occasion  to  Spinosa  to  praise  him  very  often.  Nay,  he  went 
sometimes  to  hear  him  preach,  and  he  esteem'd  particularly  his 
learned  way  of  explaining  the  Scripture,  and  the  solid  applications 
he  made  of  it.  He  advised  at  the  same  time  his  Landlord  and  the 
People  of  the  House,  not  to  miss  any  Sermon  of  so  excellent  a 
Preacher. 

It  happen'd  one  day,  that  his  Landlady  ask'd  him  whether 
he  believed,  she  cou'd  be  saved  in  the  Religion  she  profest :  He 
answered,  Your  Religion  is  a  good  one,  you  need  not  look  for  another, 
nor  doubt  that  you  may  he  saved  iti  it,  provided,  whilst  you  apply  your- 
self to  Piety,  you  live  at  the  same  time  a  peaceable  and  quiet  Life. 

When  he  staid  at  home,  he  was  troublesome  to  no  Body ;  he  spent 
the  greatest  part  of  his  time  quietly  in  his  own  Chamber.  When  he 
happen'd  to  be  tired  by  having  applyed  himself  too  much  to  his  Phi- 
losophical Meditations,  he  went  down  Stairs  to  refresh  himself,  and 
discoursed  with  the  people  of  the  House  about  any  thing,  that  might 
afford  Matter  for  an  ordinary  Conversation,  and  even  about  trifles. 
He  also  took  Pleasure  in  smoaking  a  Pipe  of  Tobacco  ;  or,  when  he 
had  a  mind  to  divert  himself  somewhat  longer,  he  look'd  for  some 
Spiders,  and  made  'em  fight  together,  or  he  threw  some  Flies  into  the 
Cobweb,  and  was  so  well  pleased  with  that  Battel,  that  he  wou'd  some- 
times break  into  Laughter.  He  observed  also,  with  a  Microscope, 
the  different  parts  of  the  smallest  Insects,  from  whence  he  drew  such 
Consequences  as  seem'd  to  him  to  agree  best  with  his  Discoveries. 

He  was  no  lover  of  Money,  as  I  have  said,  and  he  was  very  well 
contented  to  live  from  Hand  to  Mouth.  Simon  de  Vries  of 
A)nsterda7n,  who  expresses  a  great  love  for  him.  in  the  26th  Letter, 
and  calls  him  his  most  faithful  Friend,  Amice  integeri?ne,^  presented 
him  one  day,  with  a  summ  of  two  thousand  Florins,  to  enable  him  to 
live  a  more  easie  Life  ;  but  Spinosa,  in  the  presence  of  his  Landlord, 
desired  to  be  excused  from  accepting  that  Money,  under  pretence  that 
he  wanted  nothing,  and  that  if  he  received  so  much  Money,  it  wou'd 
infallibly  divert  him  from  his  Studies  and  Occupations. 

The  same  Simon  de  Vries  being  like  to  die,  and  having  no  Wife 
nor  Children,  design'd  to  make  him  his  general  Heir ;  but  Spinosa 
wou'd  never  consent  to  it,  and  told  him,  that  he  shou'd  not  think  to 
leave  his  Estate  to  any  Body  but  to  his  Brother,  who  lived  at 
Schiedam,  seeing  he  was  his  nearest  Relation,  and  natural  Heir. 

This  was  executed  as  he  proposed  it ;  but  it  was  upon  condition, 
that  the  Brother  and  Heir  of  Simon  de  Vries  shou'd  pay  to  Spinosa 

'  Sic 


422  APPENDIX. 

a  sufficient  Annuity  for  his  maintenance  ;  and  that  Clause  was  like- 
wise faithfully  executed.  But  that  which  is  particular,  is,  that  an 
Annuity  of  500  Florins  was  offered  to  Spinosa  by  virtue  of  that 
Clause,  which  he  would  not  accept,  because  he  found  it  too  consider- 
able, so  that  he  reduced  it  to  300  Florins.  That  Annuity  was 
regularly  paid  him  during  his  Life  ;  and  the  same  de  Vries  of 
Schiedam  took  care  after  his  death  to  pay  to  Mr.  Vander  Spyck  what 
Spinosa  owed  him,  as  it  appears  by  the  Letter  of  John  Rieinvertz, 
Printer  at  Amsterdam,  who  was  employed  in  that  Affair.  It  is  dated 
the  6th  of  March,  1678,^  and  directed  to  Vander  Spyck  himself  - 

Another  instance  of  the  Uninterestedness  of  Spinosa,  is  what 
past  after  the  death  of  his  Father.  His  Father's  Succession  was  to 
be  divided  between  him  and  his  Sisters,  to  which  they  were  con- 
demned in  Law,  tho  they  had  left  no  Stone  unturn'd  to  exclude 
him  from  it.  Yet  instead  of  dividing  that  Succession,  he  gave  them 
his  share,  and  kept  only  for  himself  a  good  Bed,  with  its  furniture. 

He  was  known  to  several  Persons  of  great  Consideration. 

Spinosa  had  no  sooner  published  some  of  his  Works,  but  he  grew 
very  famous  in  the  World,  amongst  the  most  considerable  Persons, 
who  look'd  upon  him  as  a  Man  of  a   noble  Genius,  and  a  great 
Philosopher.     Monsieur  Sfoupe,  Lieutenant-Collonel  of  a  Regiment 
of  Swissers,  in  the  service  of  the  King  of  France,  commanded  in  the 
City   of   Utrecht  in    1673  ;   he   had   been   before    Minister   of  the 
Walloon  Church,'^  in  London,  during  the  Civil  Wars  of  England  in 
Crom7vel's  time  ;  he   was   made  aftenvards  a   Brigadeer,   and   was 
killed  at  the  Battel  of  Steenkirke.     Whilst  he  was  at  Utrecht,  he  writ 
a  Book  entituled,  The  Religion  of  the  Dutch,  wherein  he  upbraids  the 
Reformed  Divines,  amongst  other  things,  for  neglecting  to  confute 
or  answer  a  Book,  which  was  published  under  their  Eyes,  in  the  year 
1670,  entituled  Tractatiis  Theologico-Politicus,  whereof  Spinosa  owned 
himself  to  be  the  Author,  in  his  nineteenth  Letter.     This  is  what 
Monsieur  Stoupe  says.^     But  the  famous  Braiinius,  Professor  of  the 
University  of  Grofiingen,  shewed  the  contrary  in  his  Answer  to  Mon- 
sieur Stoupe' s  Book  :  And  indeed  so  many  Books  published  against  that 
abominable  Treatise,  do  evidently  shew  that  Monsieur  Stoupe  was 
mistaken.     At  that  very  time  he  writ  several  Letters  to  Spinoza,  from 

'  A  mistake  for  1677  ?  ^   '  Ministre  de  la  Savoie.' 

^  Extracts  from  his  book  are  given  in  Paulus's  ed,  of  Spinoza's  works,  vol.  ii. 
p.  670. 


APPENDIX,  423 

whom  he  received  several  Answers ;  and  at  last  he  desired  him  to 
repair  to  Utrecht  at  a  certain  time.  Monsieur  Stoupe  was  so  much 
the  more  desirous  that  he  shou'd  come  thither,  because  the  Prince 
of  Conde,  who  took  then  possession  of  the  Government  of  Utrecht^ 
had  a  great  mind  to  discourse  with  Spinosa  :  And  it  was  confidently 
reported  that  his  Highness  was  so  well  disposed  to  recommend  him 
to  the  King,  that  he  hoped  to  obtain  easily  a  Pension  for  him, 
provided  he  wou'd  be  willing  to  dedicate  one  of  his  Books  to  his 
Majesty.  He  received  that  Letter  with  a  Passport,  and  set  out  from 
the  Hague  a  little  while  after  he  had  received  it.  Frauds  Hahna 
says,  in  his  Dutch  Account  of  Spinosa,'^  that  he  paid  a  Visit  to  the 
Prince  of  Conde  with  whom  he  had  several  Conversations  for 
several  days,  and  with  some  other  Persons  of  note,  particularly  with 
Lieutenant  Colonel  Stoupe.  But  Vander  Spyck  and  his  Wife,  in 
whose  House  he  did  lodge,  and  who  are  still  living,  have  assured  me, 
that  he  told  them  positively  at  his  return,  that  he  cou'd  not  see  the 
Prince  of  Conde,  because  he  set  out  from  Utrecht  some  days  before 
he  arrived  there.  But  that  in  the  discourse  he  had  with  Monsieur 
Stoupe,  that  Officer  had  assured  him,  that  he  wou'd  willingly  use  his 
Interest  for  him,  and  that  he  should  not  doubt  to  obtain  a  Pension  f 
from  the  King's  Liberality,  at  his  recommendation.  Spinosa  added 
that,  because  he  did  not  design  to  dedicate  any  Book  to  the  King  of 
France,  he  had  refused  the  offer  that  was  made  him,  with  all  the 
civility  he  was  capable  of 

After  his  return,  the  Mob  at  the  Hagiie  were  extreamly  incensed 
against  him,  they  look'd  upon  him  as  a  Spy,  and  whispered  in  one 
anothers  Ears,  that  they  ought  to  kill  so  dangerous  a  Man,  who 
treated,  without  doubt,  of  State  affairs,  keeping  so  publick  a  Corres- 
pondance  with  the  Enemies.  Spinosa'?,  Landlord  was  alarm'd  at  it, 
and  was  afraid,  not  without  reason,  that  the  Mob  wou'd  break  into 
the  House,  and  perhaps  plunder  it,  and  then  drag  Spinosa  out  of  it  : 
But  Spinosa  put  him  in  heart  again,  and  remov'd  his  fears  as  well  as 
he  could.  Fear  nothing,  said  he  to  him,  upon  my  account,  I  can  easily 
justify  myself:  There  are  People  efiough,  and  even  some  of  the  most 
considerable  Fersofis  of  the  State,  who  knoiv  very  well  what  put  me 
upon  that  Journey.  But  Junvcvcr,  as  soon  as  the  Mob  make  the  least 
noise  at  your  Door,  Fll  go  and  meet  'em,  tho'  they  were  to  treat  me,  as 

t  The  Kutg  of  France  gave  at  that  'ime  Pensmts  to  all  learned  Mai,  especially 
to  the  Strangers,  ivho  presented  or  dedicated  some  Books  to  him. 

'  Fr.  '  La  Vie  de  notre  Philosophe,  qu'il  a  traduite  et  cxtraite  du  Dictionnaire 
de  Mr.  Bayle.' 


424  APPENDIX. 

they  treated  pool'  Messieurs  de  Wit.     /  am  a  good  Republican,  and  I 
aliuays  aimed  at  the  Glory  and  Welfare  of  the  State. 

In  that  same  year  Charles  Lewis,  Elector  Palatine,  of  glorious 
Memory,  being  informed  of  the  capacity  of  that  great  Philosopher, 
was  desirous  that  he  shou'd  come  to  Heydelbeig  to  teach  Philosophy 
there,  knowing  nothing,  without  doubt,  of  the  Venom  concealed  in 
his  Breast,  and  which  was  more  openly  manifested  afterwards.  His 
Electoral  Highness  ordered  the  famous  Dr.  Fabritius,  Professor  of 
Divinity,  a  good  philosopher,  and  one  of  his  Councellors,  to  propose 
it  to  Spinosa.  He  offered  him  in  the  Prince's  Name,  with  that  JPro- 
fessorship,  a  full  Liberty  of  Reasoning  according  to  his  Principles,  as 
he  shou'd  think  fit,  cum  amplissima  Philosophandi  libertate.  But 
that  Offer  was  attended  with  a  Condition,  which  Spinosa  did  not  like 
at  all.  For  tho'  the  Liberty  granted  to  him  was  never  so  great,  yet 
he  was  not  allowed  in  any  manner  whatsoever  to  make  use  of  it,  to 
the  prejudice  of  the  Religion  established  by  the  Laws  :  As  it  appears 
by  Dr.  Fabritius' 's,\,t\X^x  ^dXQ^{xo\y\  Heydelberg  \}(\t  i6th  oi  February. 
See  Spinosd's,  Opera  Posthuma  Epist.  53.  pag.  561.  He  is  honoured 
in  that  Letter,  with  the  Title  of  most  Acute  and  most  Famous  Philo- 
sopher, Philosophe  actitissime  ac  celeberrime. 

This  was  a  Mine,  to  which  he  easily  gave  Vent,  if  I  may  be  allowed 
to  use  such  an  Expression  :  He  perceived  the  difficulty,  or  rather  the 
impossibility  of  reasoning  according  to  his  Principles,  without  ad- 
vancing anything  that  shou'd  be  contrary  to  the  established  Religion. 
He  return'd  an  Answer  to  Dr.  Fabritius  the  30th  of  March  1673,  ^^^ 
refused  civilly  the  Professorship  that  was  offered  him.  He  told  him 
that  The  instruction  of  yotmg  Men  won' d prove  an  Obstacle  to  his  own 
Studies,  and  that  he  never  had  the  thoughts  of  embracing  such  a  Profes- 
sion. But  this  was  a  meer  pretence,  and  he  does  plainly  enough 
discover  his  inward  thoughts  by  the  following  words.  "  Besides,  (says 
"  he  to  the  Doctor)  I  consider  that  you  don't  tell  me  within  what 
"  bounds  that  liberty  of  Philosophizing  must  be  confined,  that  I  may 
"  not  publickly  disturb  the  established  Religion.  Cogito  dcinde  me 
nescire  quibus  limitibjis  libertas  ilia  Philosophandi  intercludi  debeat,  ne 
videar  publice  Stabilitam  Peligionem  perturbare  velle.  See  his  Posthu- 
7nous  Works,  pag.  563  Epist.  54. 

His  Writings,  and  his  Opinions. 

As  for  his  works,  there  are  some,  which  are  ascribed  to  him,  but 
it  is  not  certain  that  he  is  the  Author  of  'em  :  Some  are  lost,  or  at 


APPENDIX. 


425 


least  are  not  to  be  found,  others  are  Printed  and  exposed  to  every 
Body's  view. 

Monsieur  Bayle  tells  us  in  his  Historical  and  Critical  Dictionary, 
that  Spinosa  writ  an  Apology  in  Spanish  for  his  leaving  the 
Synagogue  ;  but  that  it  was  never  Printed.  He  adds,  that  Spifiosa 
inserted  several  things  in  it,  which  were  found  afterwards  in  his 
Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  :  But  I  have  not  been  able  to  hear  any 
thing  concerning  that  Apology  ;  tho  in  my  enquiries  about  it  I  have 
consulted  some  Persons,  who  were  familiarly  acquainted  with  him, 
and  who  are  alive  still. 

He  published  in  the  year  1664,  Descartes'?,  Principles  of  Philo- 
sophy Geometrically  demonstrated  :  Roiati  Descartes  principioritm 
Philosophic  pars  prima  et  seciinda  more  Geometrico  demonstratcB ; 
which  were  soon  followed  by  his  Metaphysical  Meditations,  Cogitata 
Mctaphysica  :  and  had  he  gone  no  farther,  he  might  have  preserved  to 
this  day,  the  deserved  Reputation  of  a  Wise  and  Learned  Philosopher. 
In  the  year  1665  there  came  out  a  little  Book  in  Twelves  entituled, 
Lucii  Antistii  Constantis  de  Jure  Ecclesiasticorum.  Alethopoli  apiid 
Cainni  Valerium  pennatiim.  The  author  of  that  Book  endeavours  to 
prove  that  the  Spiritual  and  Political  Right,  which  the  Clergy  ascribe 
to  themselves,  and  which  is  ascribed  to  them  by  others,  does  not 
belong  to  them  in  the  least ;  that  Clergy-men  abuse  it  in  a  Profane 
manner,  and  that  all  their  Authority  depends  upon  that  of  the 
Magistrates  or  Soveraigns,  who  are  in  the  place  of  God,  in  the  Cities 
and  Commonwealths  wherein  the  Clergy  have  established  themselves: 
And  therefore,  that  the  Ecclesiasticks  ought  not  to  take  upon  them- 
selves to  teach  their  own  Religion,  but  that  which  the  Magistrates 
order  'em  to  Preach.  All  that  Doctrine  is  built  upon  the  Principles, 
which  Hobbes  made  use  of  in  his  Leviathan.  Monsieur  Bayle  tells 
us,  that  the  Style,  Principles  and  Design  of  Antistiiis^  Book  were 
like  that  of  Spinosa,  which  is  entituled,  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus ; 
but  this  does  not  prove  that  Spinosa  was  the  Author  of  it.  Tho'  the 
first  Book  came  out  just  at  the  same  time  that  Spinosa  began  to  write 
his  ;  and  tho'  the  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  was  published  soon 
after  ;  yet  it  is  not  a  proof  neither,  that  the  one  was  the  fore-runner  of 
the  other.  It  may  very  well  be,  that  two  Men  will  undertake  to  write 
and  advance  the  same  impious  things ;  and  tho'  their  Writings  shou'd 
come  out  much  about  the  same  time,  it  cou'd  not  be  inferred  from 
thence,  that  they  were  written  by  one  and  the  same  Author.  Spinosa 
himself  being  asked  by  a  Person  of  great  Consideration,  whether  he 
was  the  Author  of  the  first  Treatise,  denied  it  positively;  I  have  it  from 


426  APPENDIX, 

very  good  Hands.  The  Latin  of  those  two  Books,  the  Style,  and  the 
Expressions  are  not  so  like  neither,  as  'tis  pretended  :  The  former  ex- 
presses himself  with  a  profound  respect,  when  he  speaks  of  God  :  he 
calls  him  often  Deiim  tcr  Optimiiin  Maxi/niim.  But  I  find  no  such 
Expressions  in  any  part  of  the  writings  of  Spiiiosa. 

Several  Learned  Men  have  assured  me,  that  the  impious  Book 
Printed  in  1666  in  Quarto,  and  entituled.  The  Holy  Scripture 
explained  by  Philosophy :  Philosopliia  sacrce  Scriptures,  interpres,  and 
the  above-mentioned  Treatise  were  both  written  by  one  and  the 
same  author,  viz.  L.  AT.  and  tho  the  thing  seems  to  me  very  likely, 
yet  I  leave  it  to  the  judgment  of  those  who  may  be  better  informed. 

It  was  in  the  year  1670  that  Spinosa  published  his  Tractatus 
Theologico-Politicus.  He  who  translated  it  into  Dutch,  thought  fit  to 
entitle  it.  The  judicious  and  political  Divine ;  De  Regtzenninge ' 
Theologant,  of  Godgeleerde  Staatkunde.  Spinosa  does  plainly  say 
that  he  is  the  Author  of  it  in  his  19th  Letter,  directed  to  Mr,  Olden- 
burgh  :  He  desires  him  in  that  same  Letter,  to  send  him  the  Objec- 
tions, which  Learned  Men  raised  against  his  Book  ;  for  he  design'd 
then  to  get  it  Re-printed,  and  to  add  some  Remarks  to  it.  If  we  be- 
lieve the  Title  Page  of  that  Book,  it  was  Printed  at  Hamburg,  by  Henry 
Conrad.  But  it  is  certain  that  the  Magistrates,  and  the  Reverend 
Ministers  of  Hamburg  had  never  permitted,  that  so  many  impious 
things  shou'd  have  been  Printed  and  publickly  sold  in  their  City. 

There  is  no  doubt  but  that  Book  was  Printed  at  Amsterdam  by 
Christopher  Conrad.  Being  sent  for  to  Amstei'dam  in  1679  for  some 
Business,  Conrad  himself  brought  me  some  copies  of  that  Treatise, 
and  presented  me  with  them,  not  knowing  that  it  was  a  very  per- 
nicious Book. 

The  Dutch  Translator  was  also  pleased  to  honour  the  City  of 
Bremen  with  so  noble  a  Production  :  as  if  his  Translation  had  come 
from  the  Press  of  Hans  Jur gel  Vander  Weyl,  in  the  year  1694.  But 
what  is  said  of  those  Impressions  of  Bremen  and  Hamburg  is  equally 
false  :  and  they  would  have  met  with  the  same  difiiculties  in  either  of 
those  Towns,  if  they  had  undertaken  to  Print  and  Publish  such  Books 
therein,  Philopater,  whom  we  have  already  mentioned,  does  openly 
say  in  the  continuation  of  his  Life,  pag.  231,  that  oXd^Johii  Hendrikzen, 
Glasemaker,  whom  I  knew  very  well,  was  the  Translator  of  that 
Book  :  and  he  assures  us  at  the  same  time,  that  he  had  likewise 
Translated  into  Dutch  the  Posthumous  Works  of  Spinosa,  Published 
in  1677:     He  values  and  extols  so  much  that  Treatise  of  Spinosa^ 

'  Sic, 


APPENDIX.  427 

that  one  would  think  the  World  never  saw  the  like.  The  Author,  or 
at  least  the  Printer,  of  the  continuation  of  Philopatcr's  Life,  Aard 
Wolsgryk,  heretofore  a  Bookseller  at  Amstcrdavi  in  the  corner  ot 
Hosmaryji-Stceg,  was  punish'd  for  his  Insolence,  as  he  deserv'd,  and 
confin'd  to  the  House  of  Correction,  to  which  he  was  condemn'd  for 
some  years.  I  wish,  with  all  my  heart,  he  may  have  repented  of  his 
fault  during  the  stay  he  made  in  that  place  ;  I  hope  he  came  out  of 
it  with  a  better  mind,  and  that  he  was  in  such  a  disposition,  when  I 
saw  him  here  (at  the  Hague)  last  Summer,  whither  he  came  to  be 
paid  for  some  Books,  which  he  had  Printed  heretofore,  and  deliver'd 
to  the  Booksellers  of  this  Town. 

To  return  to  Spinosa  and  his  Tractahis  Thcologico-Poliiiais,  I  shall 
say  what  I  think  of  it,  after  I  have  set  down  the  judgment,  which  two 
famous  Authors  made  of  it,  one  whereof  was  of  the  Confession  of 
Atisburg,'^  and  the  other  Reformed.  The  first  is  Spitzeliits,  who 
speaks  of  it  thus,  in  his  Treatise  entituled  Infelix  Literator"^  p.  363. 
"That  impious  author  {Spinosa)  blinded  by  a  prodigious  pre- 
"  sumption,  was  so  impudent  and  so  full  of  Impiety,  as  to  main- 
"  tain  that  Prophecies  were  only  grounded  upon  the  fancy  of  the 
"  Prophets  ;  and  that  the  Prophets  and  the  Apostles  wrote  naturally 
"  according  to  their  own  light  and  knowledge,  without  any  Revelation 
"  or  Order  from  God  :  That  they  accommodated  Religion,  as  well  as 
"they  cou'd,  to  the  Genius  of  those  who  lived  at  that  time,  and 
"  established  it  upon  such  Principles  as  were  then  well  known,  and 
"commonly  received.  Irrdiogissinuis^  Author  stupenda  sui  fdentia 
plane  fascinatus,  eo  progressus  impudentia  et  impidatis  fuit  iit  pro- 
pheiiain  dependisse  dixerit  a  fallad  imaginatione  prop/ida7'um,  eosqiie 
paritcr  ac  Apostolos  non  ex  Revelatione  et  Divino  mandato  Scripsisse, 
sed  tantum  ex  ipsorunimet  naturali  judido;  accommodavisse  insuper 
Religioneni^  quo  ad  fieri potuit,  Jiominum  sui  temporis  ingenio,  illamque 
fmdamcntis  tuni  temporis  maxinie  notis  et  aeceptis  super  ccdificasse. 
Spinosa  pretends  in  his  Tractatus  T/ieoiogico-Poiiticus,  that  the  same 
Method  may  and  ought  to  be  observed  still  for  explaining  the  Holy 
Scripture ;  for  he  maintains,  amongst  other  things,  that,  as  the 
Scripture,  when  it  7vas  first  published,  was  fitted  to  the  established 
opinions,  atid  to  the  capacity  of  the  People,  so  every  Body  is  free  to 
expound  it  according  to  his  Knowledge,  and  make  it  agree  with  his  own 
opinions. 

If  this  was  true,  good  Lord  !     What  respect  cou'd  we  have  for  the 
Scripture?     How  cou'd  we  maintain  that  it  is  Divinely  inspired? 
>  Sic,  "  Van  der  Linde,  Bihlio^r.  no,  358,  ;;,  ^  ^^^.^ 


428  APPENDIX^ 

That  it  is  a  sure  and  firm  Prophecy ;  that  the  Holy  Men,  who  are 
the  Authors  of  it,  spoke  and  wrote  by  God's  order,  and  by  the  inspira- 
tion of  the  Holy  Spirit ;  that  the  same  Scripture  is  most  certainly  true, 
and  that  it  gives  a  certain  Testimony  of  its  Truth  to  our  Consciences  ; 
and  lastly,  that  it  is  a  Judge,  whose  Decisions  ought  to  be  the  constant 
and  unvariable  Rule  of  our  Thoughts,  of  our  Faith,  and  of  our  Lives. 
If  what  Spinosa  affirms  were  true,  one  might  indeed  very  well  say, 
that  the  Bible  is  a  Wax-Nose,  which  may  be  turned  and  shaped  at 
one's  will;  a  Glass,  thro'  which  every  Body  may  exactly  see  what 
pleases  his  fancy ;  a  Fool's  Cap,  which  may  be  turned  and  fitted  at 
one's  pleasure  a  hundred  several  ways.  The  Lord  confound  thee, 
Satan,  and  stop  thy  mouth  ! 

Spitzelius  is  not  contented  to  say  what  he  thinks  of  that  per 
nicious  Book  ;  but  he  adds  to  the  judgment  he  made  of  it,  that  of 
Mr  de  MaJisei'cId  heretofore  Professor  at  Utrecht,  who  speaks  of  it 
thus,  in  a  Book  Printed  at  Amsterdam,  in  1674.  My  opinio7'.  is, 
that  that  Treatise  ought  to  be  buried  for  ever  i?i  an  ceternal  oblivion  : 
Tractatum  hunc  ad  ceternas  damnandum  tenebras,  &c.  \Miich  is  very 
judiciously  said  ;  seeing  that  Wicked  Book  does  altogether  overthrow 
the  Christian  Religion,  by  depriving  the  Sacred  Writings  of  the 
Authority,  on  which  it  is  solely  grounded  and  established. 

The  second  Testimony  I  shall  produce  is,  that  of  Mr,  William 
va7i  Blyenburg  of  Dordrect,^  who  kept  a  long  correspondence  with 
Spinosa,  and  who  in  his  31st  Letter  to  him  (See  Spitiosds  Posthumous 
Works  pag.  476)  says,  speaking  of  himself,  that  he  had  embraced  no 
Profession,  and  that  he  lived  by  an  honest  Trade,  Liber  sum  nulli 
adstrictus professiojii,  honestis  mercaturis  me  alo.  That  Merchant,  \\ho 
is  a  learned  Man,  in  the  Preface  of  a  Book  entituled.  The  truth  of  the 
Christian  Religion,  Printed  at  Leyden,  in  1674,  gives  his  judgment 
about  the  Treatise  of  Spinosa  in  these  words.  //  is  a  Book,  says  he, 
/////  of  curious,  but  abonmiable  discoveries,  the  Learning  and  Lnquiries 
%vhei'eof  must  needs  have  been  fetched  from  Lfell.  Every  Christian,  7iay, 
every  Man  of  Sense,  ought  to  abhor  such  a  Book.  The  Author  en- 
deavours to  overthrow  the  Christiaji  Beligion,  and  baffle  all  our  hopes, 
luhich  are  grounded  upon  it:  Ln  the  room  whereof  he  introduces 
Atheism,  or  at  most,  a  Natural  Religion  forged  according  to  the 
humour  or  interests  of  the  Soveraigns.  The  wicked  shall  be  restrained 
only  by  the  fear  of  Punishment ;  but  a  Man  of  no  Conscience,  who 
neither  fears  the  Executioner  nor  the  Laivs,  may  attempt  atiyihing  to 
satisfy  himself,  Sec. 

'  Sic. 


APPENDIX.  429 

I  must  add,  that  I  have  read  that  Book  of  Spinosa  with  application 
from  the  beginning  to  the  end  ;  but  I  protest  at  the  same  time  before 
God,  that  I  have  found  no  solid  arguments  in  it,  nor  anything  that 
cou'd  shake,  in  the  least,  my  belief  of  the  Gospel.  Instead  of  solid 
reasons,  it  contains  meer  suppositions,  and  what  we  call  in  the 
School,  petitio7ies  principii.  The  things  which  the  Author  advances, 
are  given  for  Proofs,  which  being  denied  and  rejected,  the  remaining 
part  of  his  Treatise  will  be  found  to  contain  nothing  but  Lies  and 
Blasphemies.  Did  he  think  that  the  World  wou'd  believe  him 
blindly  upon  his  word,  and  that  he  was  not  obliged  to  give  good 
reasons  and  good  proofs  for  what  he  advanced  ? 

Lastly,  several  Writings,  which  Spifiosa  left  after  his  death  were 
Printed  in  1677,  in  which  year  he  also  died.  They  are  called  his 
Posthumous  Works,  Opera  Posthuma,  These  three  Letters  B.  D.  S. 
are  to  be  found  in  the  Title  of  the  Book,  which  contains  five  several 
works.  The  first,  is  a  Treatise  of  Morals  demonstrated  Geometrically, 
Ethica  more  Gcomeirico  demo7istrata.  The  second,  is  about  Politicks. 
The  third,  treats  of  the  Understanding,  and  of  the  means  of  rectify- 
ing it,  De  eme7idatio7ie  Intelledns.  The  fourth,  is  a  Collection  of 
Letters,  and  Answers  to  them,  Epistolx  &=  Respo7isio7ies.  The  fifth, 
is  an  Abridgement  of  the  Hebrew  Grammar,  Co7iipe7idiiu7i  Gra77i- 
viatices  Li7iguce.  Hebrsese.  The  Printer's  name  and  the  place  wherein 
that  Book  was  Printed,  are  not  mention'd  in  the  Title-page ;  which 
shews  that  the  Person  who  published  it,  did  not  care  to  be  known. 
But  Mr.  Va7ider  Spyck,  Spwosa's  Landlord,  who  is  alive  still,  tells  me 
that  Spinosa  ordered,  that  immediately  after  his  death,  his  Desk, 
which  contained  his  Letters  and  Papers,  shou'd  be  sent  to  JoJm 
Rieinuertze7i,  a  Printer  at  A7nste7-da77i  :  A\'hich  Vander  Spyck  did  not 
fail  to  perform  according  to  his  Will.  And  JoJm  Riemc'e7izc7i  acknow- 
ledged that  he  had  received  that  Desk,  as  it  appears  by  his  Answer 
dated  from  A>/istc7da77i  the  25th  of  March,  1677.  He  adds  towards  the 
latter  part  of  his  Letter,  that  The  Relations  of  Spinosa  wou'd  fain  k7iow 
to  who7n  it  was  directed,  because  they  fa7icied  that  it  was  full  of  Money 
and  that  they  wou'd  7iot  fail  to  enqui7-e  about  it  of  the  Water/nan,  who 
had  been  i7itrusted  with  it.  But,  says  he,  if  the  Packets,  that  a7-e  s.-nt 
hither  by  zuater,  a7-e  not  rcgist/rd  at  the  Hague,  /  don't  see  how  they 
can  be  i7ifo7-77ied  about  it,  a/id  indeed  it  is  better  they  shou'd  know 
7iothi7ig  of  it,  &c.  He  ends  his  Letter  with  those  words,  and  it  does 
clearly  appear  by  that  Letter,  to  whom  we  are  beholden  for  so 
abominable  a  Production. 

Several  Learned   Men  have  already   sufficiently   discovered  the 


430  APPENDIX, 

impious  Doctrines  contained  in  those  Posthumous  Works,  and  have 
given  notice  to  every  Body  to  beware  of  'em.  I  shall  only  add 
some  few  things  to  what  has  been  said  by  them.  The  Treatise  of 
Morals  begins  with  some  Difinitions '  or  Descriptions  of  the  Deity. 
Who  would  not  think  at  first,  considering  so  fine  a  beginning,  that  he 
is  reading  a  Christian  Philosopher  ?  All  those  Difinitions  are  fine, 
especially  the  sixth,  wherein  Spinosa  says,  that  God  is  an  i?ifinite 
Being ;  that  is,  a  Substance,  which  contains  i?t  it  self  an  infinity  of 
Attributes,  every  one  ^vhej'eof  represents  and  expresses  an  Eternal  and 
infinite  Substance.  But  when  we  enquire  more  narrowly  into  his 
Opinions,  we  find  that  the  God  of  Spinosa  is  a  meer  Phantom,  an 
imaginary  God,  who  is  nothing  less  than  God.  And  therefore  the 
words  of  the  Apostle,  Tit.  i.  i6,  concerning  impious  Men,  may  be 
very  well  applied  to  that  Philosopher :  They  profess  that  they  know 
God,  but  in  Works  they  deny  him.  Wliat  David  says  of  ungodly  Men 
Psalm  14.  I.  does  likewise  suit  him  :  The  Fool  has  said  in  /lis  Heart, 
there  is  ?io  God.  This  is  the  true  Opinion  of  Spinosa,  whatever  he 
might  say. ,  He  takes  the  liberty  to  use  the  word  God,  and  to  take  it  in 
a  sense  unknown  to  all  Christians.  This  he  confesses  himself  in  his 
2ist  Letter  to  Mr,  Oldenburg:  I  acknowledge,  says  he,  that  I  have  a 
notion  of  God  and  Nature,  very  different  from  that  of  the  Modern 
Christians.  I  believe  that  God  is  the  Immanent,  and  not  the  Transient 
Cause  of  all  things:  Deum  rerutn  omnium  Causa jn  immanentem,  non 
vero  transeumtcm  statuo.  And  to  confirm  his  Opinion,  he  alledges 
these  Words  of  St  Paul;  In  him  we  live,  and  move,  and  have  cur 
Being.     Act.  17.  28. 

In  order  to  understand  him,  we  must  consider  that  a  Z/'fl^^j/if^/  Cause 
is,  that^  the  Productions  whereof  are  external,  or  out  of  it  self;  as  a 
Man,  who  throws  a  Stone  into  the  Air,  or  a  Carpenter,  who  builds  a 
House  :  Whereas  the  I>?i7nanent  Cause  acts  inwardly,  and  is  confined 
within  itself,  without  acting  outwardly.  Thus  when  a  Man's  Soul 
thinks  of,  or  desires  something,  it  is  or  remains  in  that  thought  or 
desire,  without  going  out  of  it,  and  is  the  immanent  Cause  thereof 
In  the  same  manner,  the  God  of  Spinosa  is  the  Cause  of  the  Universe 
wherein  he  is,  and  he  is  not  beyond  it.  But  because  the  Universe 
has  some  bounds,  it  wou'd  follow  that  God  is  a  limited  and  finite 
Being.  And  tho  he  says  that  God  is  infinite,  and  comprehends  an 
infinity  of  Perfections ;  he  must  needs  play  with  the  words  Eternal 

'  Sic. 

"•  According  to  modern  practice  the  sense  would  require  the  comma  to  be  after 
that. 


APPENDIX. 


43t 


and  Infinite,  seeing  he  cannot  understand  by  them  a  Being,  which 
did  subsist  before  Time  was,  and  before  any  other  Being  was  created , 
but  he  calls  that  infinite,  wherein  the  Humane  Understanding  can 
neither  find  an  End,  nor  any  Bounds  :  For  he  thinks  the  Productions 
of  God  are  so  numerous,  that  Man,  with  all  the  strength  of  his  Mind, 
cannot  conceive  any  Bounds  in  them.  Besides,  they  are  so  solid, 
and  so  well  settled  and  connected  one  with  another,  that  they  shall 
last  for  ever. 

Nevertheless,  he  says,  in  his  21st  Letter,  that  they  were  in  the 
wrong,  who  charged  him  with  asserting  that  God  and  Matter,  wherein 
God  Acts,  are  but  one  and  the  same  thing.  But  after  all,  he  can't 
forbear  confessing,  that  Matter  is  a  thing  essential  to  the  Deity,  who 
is  and  works  only  in  Matter,  that  is,  in  the  Universe.  The  God  of 
Spinosa  is  therefore  nothing  else  but  Nature,  infinite,  but  yet 
corporeal  and  material,  taken  in  general,  and  with  all  its  Modifica- 
tions. For  he  supposes  that  there  are  two  Eternal  Properties  in 
God,  cogitatio  &=  cxtensio,  Thinking  and  Extension  :  By  the  first  of 
those  Properties,  God  is  contain'd  in  the  Universe ;  by  the  second, 
he  is  the  Universe  itself,  and  both  joyn'd  together  make  up  what  he 
calls  God. 

As  far  as  I  am  able  to  understand  Spinosa,  the  dispute  between 
us  Christians  and  him  runs  upon  this,  viz.  Whether  the  true  God  be 
an  Eternal  Substance,  different  and  distinct  from  the  Universe,  and 
from  the  whole  Nature,  and  whether  by  a  free  Act  of  his  Will  he 
produc'd  the  World,  and  all  Creatures  out  of  nothing  ;  or  whether  the 
Universe,  and  all  the  Beings  it  comprehends,  do  essensually '  belong 
to  the  Nature  of  God,  being  considered  as  a  Substance,  whose 
Thought  and  Extension  are  infinite?  Spinosa  maintains  the  last 
proposition.  The  Antispinosa  of  L}  Vittichius,  pag.  18.  and  seq. 
may  be  consulted.  Thus  he  owns  indeed,  that  God  is  the  general 
Cause  of  all  things ;  but  he  pretends,  that  God  produces  'em 
necessarily  without  freedom  and  choice,  and  without  consulting  his 
Will.  In  like  manner,  everything  that  happens  in  the  World,  Good 
or  Evil,  Virtue  or  Vice,  Sin  or  good  Works,  does  necessarily  proceed 
from  him ;  and  consequently  there  ought  to  be  no  Judgment,  no 
Punishment,  no  Resurrection,  no  Salvation,  no  Damnation.  For 
if  it  were  so,  that  imaginary  God  wou'd  Punish  and  Reward  his  own 

'  Sic. 

^  Sic,  an  error  for  Ch.  (Christophef),  as  rightly  given  in  the  original  and  the 
French.     {Bil>!ioi;r.  384,  often  confounded  with  James  Wittichius,  cf.  254,  «). 


432  APPENDIX. 

Work,  as  a  Child  does  bis  Baby.'  Is  it  not  the  most  pernicious 
Atheism  that  ever  was  seen  in  the  World?  And  therefore  Mr. 
Buriimniis^  a  Reformed  Minister,  at  Enkhuyscn  calls  Spinosa,  with 
great  Reason,  the  most  impious  Atheist,  that  ever  liv'd  upon  the  Face 
of  the  Earth. 

I  don't  design  to  examine  here  all  the  impious  and  absurd 
Doctrines  of  Spiiwsa  ;  I  have  mention'd  some  of  the  most  important 
only  to  inspire  the  Christian  Reader  with  the  aversion  and  horror  he 
ought  to  have  for  such  pernicious  Opinions.  But  I  must  not  forget 
to  say,  that  it  does  plainly  appear  by  the  second  part  of  his  Et/jicks, 
that  he  makes  the  Soul  and  Body  but  one  Being,  the  Properties 
Avhereof  are,  as  he  expresses  it.  Thinking  and  Extension  ;  for  he  ex- 
plains himself  in  that  Manner,  pag.  40.  "  When  I  speak  of  the  Body, 
"  I  mean  only  a  Mode,  which  expresses  the  Essence  of  God  in  a 
"certain  and  precise  manner,  as  he  is  considered  under  the  notion  of 
"  an  extended  thing.  Fcr  corpus  intelligo  modum  qui  Dei  essentiam, 
quatcnus  ut  res  extensa  consideratur,  ccrto  &=  ddcrminato  iiiodo  ex- 
primit.  As  for  the  Soul,  which  is,  and  acts  in  the  Body,  it  is  only 
another  Modification  or  manner  of  being,  produced  by  Nature,  or 
manifested  by  Thought  :  It  is  not  a  Spirit,  or  a  particular  Substance 
no  more  than  the  Body,  but  a  Modification,  which  expresses  the 
Essence  of  God,  as  he  manifests  himself.  Acts  and  Works  by 
Thought.  Did  ever  any  Body  hear  any  such  abominations  among 
Christians  !  At  that  rate  God  cou'd  neither  Punish  the  Soul  nor  the 
Body,  unless  he  would  Punish  and  Destroy  himself  Towards  the 
latter  part  of  his  21st  Letter,  he  overthrows  the  great  Mystery  of 
Godliness,  as  we  find  it  expressed  i.  Tim.  3.  16.  by  maintaining  that 
the  Incarnation  of  the  Son  of  God  is  nothing  else  but  the  Eternal 
^^'isdom,  which  having  appeared  in  all  things,  particularly  in  our 
Hearts  and  Souls,  was  at  last  manifested  in  an  extraordinary  manner 
in  Jesus  Christ  :  he  says  a  little  lower,  that  some  Churches  indeed 
add  to  it,  that  God  made  himself  a  ]\Ian;  but  says  he,  I  have  declared 
in  express  terius,  thai  I  don't  kno7u  ivhat  they  mean  by  it.  Quod 
quiedam  Ecclesicc  hisaddant,  quod  Deus  naturam  humanam  assumpse/it, 
nwnui exprcsse  me  quid  dicant  nescire,  &c.  He  goes  on,  and  says.  That 
Doctrine  seems  to  me  to  be  as  strange,  as  if  any  one  shou'd  teach  that 
a  Circle  has  taken  tlie  nature  of  a  Triangle  or  of  a  Square.  Which 
gives  him  occasion  towards  the  latter  part  of  his  23rd  Letter,  to  ex- 
plain the  famous  passage  of  St  John  The  Word  was  made  Flesh 
Chap.  i.  14.  by  a  way  of  speaking  very  common  amongst  the  Eastern 

'  i.e.  doll.  -  Biblio^r.  492. 


APPENDIX.  433 

Nations,  and  to  render  it  thus,  God  has  manifested  himself  in  Jesus 
Christ,  in  a  most  particular  manner. 

I  have  shewn  plainly,  and  in  a  few  words,  in  my  Sermon,  how  in 
his  23rd  and  24th  Letters,  he  endeavours  to  destroy  the  Mystery  of  the 
Resurrection  of  Jesus  Christ,  which  is  a  Capital  Doctrine  amongst 
us,  and  the  ground  of  our  Hopes  and  Comfort.  I  need  not  spend 
more  time  in  setting  down  the  other  impious  Doctrines,  which  he 
teaches. 

Some  Writings  of  Spinosa,  which  have  not  been  Printed, 

He,  who  took,  care  to  publish  the  Posthumous  Works  of  Spinosa^ 
reckons  amongst  the  Writings  of  that  Author,  which  have  not  been 
Printed,  a  Treatise  concerning  the  Rain-Bow.  I  know  some  Men  of 
great  note  in  this  Town,  (at  the  Hague)  who  have  seen  and  read  that 
Treatise ;  but  they  did  not  advise  Spinosa  to  publish  it  :  Which 
perhaps  gave  him  some  trouble,  and  made  him  resolve  to  burn  it 
half  a  year  before  he  died,  as  I  have  been  informed  by  the  people  of 
the  House,  where  he  lived.  ^  He  had  also  begun  a  Translation  of 
the  Old  Testament  into  Didch,  about  which,  he  often  discoursed 
with  some  Men  learned  in  the  Languages,  and  enquired  into  the  Ex- 
plications which  the  Christians  give  to  several  Passages.  He  had 
finished  the  five  Books  of  Moses,  a  great  while  ago,  when  some  few 
days  before  he  died  he  burnt  the  whole  Work  in  his  Chamber. 

Several  Authors  confute  his  Works. 

His  works  were  scarce  published,  but  God  raised  to  his  Glory,  and 
for  the  defence  of  the  Christian  Religion,  several  Champions  who 
confuted  them  with  all  the  Success  they  cou'd  hope  for.  Dr.  Theoph. 
Spitzelius  names  two  of  'em  in  his  Book  entituled  Infelix  Litcrator, 
viz.  Francis  Kuyper  of  Rotterdam,  whose  Book  printed  in  the  same 
Town,  in  the  year  1676,  is  entituled  Arcana  Atheisini  reveiata,  Szc. 
The  prof oiind  Misteries  of  Atheism  discovered.  ^  The  second  is,  Regnier 
de  Mansveld  Professor,  at  Utrecht,  who  in  the  year  1674  Printed  in 
the  same  place  a  Book  upon  the  same  Subject.^ 

The   next  year   1675,  a  Confutation  of  the    same   Treatise   of 

Spinosa,  entituled,  Enervatio  Tractatus  Theologico-Politici,^  came  out 

of  the  Press  of  Isaac  Nceranns  :  It  was  written  hy  f oh n  Brcdenburg, 

whose  Father  had  been  Elder  of  the  Lutheran  Church  at  Rotterdam. 

'  See  p.  21  above,         -  Bibliogr.  365.         ^  Bibliogr.  363.         «  BMiogr.  208. 

F  F 


434  APPENDIX. 

George  MatJiias  Konig  was  pleased  in  his  Bibliotheque  of  ancient 
and  modern  Authors,  pag.  770,  to  call  him  a  certain  Weaver  of 
Rotterdam^  Texiorein  qiwidam  Rotterodamensem.  If  he  exercised  such 
a  Mechanical  Art,  I  am  sure  that  no  Man  of  his  Profession  did  ever 
shew  so  much  ability,  or  produced  such  a  Work  ;  for  he  does  Geo- 
metrically demonstrate  in  that  Book,  and  in  a  clear  and  unanswerable 
manner,  that  Nature  neither  is,  nor  can  be  God  himself,  as  Spinosa 
pretends.  Being  not  very  well  skill'd  in  the  Latin  Tongue,  he  was 
obliged  to  write  his  Book  in  Dutch,  and  to  make  use  of  another  Man's 
hand  to  Translate  it  into  Latin.  Which  he  did,  as  he  himself  says  in 
the  Preface  to  his  Book,  to  the  end,  that  Spinosa,  who  was  still  alive, 
might  have  no  excuse  or  pretence,  in  case  he  made  no  reply  to  it. 

Nevertheless,  I  don't  find  that  all  the  Arguments  of  that  Learned 
Man  are  convincing.  Besides,  he  seems  to  incline  to  Socinianisin  in 
some  parts  of  his  Book.  This  is  at  least  the  judgment  I  make  of  it, 
and  I  believe  it  does  not  differ  in  that  respect  from  the  judgment  of 
knowing  Men,  to  whom  I  leave  the  decision  of  it.  However,  it  is 
certain,  that  Francis  Kiiyper  and  Bredenbwg  published  several  Writ- 
ings one  against  another,  and  that  Kuyper  in  his  accusations  against 
his  Adversary,  pretended  to  no  less  than  to  convince  him  of  Atheism. 

In  the  year  1676,  Lambert  Veldhuis  of  Utrecht,  published  a  Book, 
entituled,  Tractatus  Moralis  de I'laturali piidore,  cS^  dignitate hominis.^ 
He  overthrows,  in  that  Treatise,  the  Principles  whereby  Spinosa  pre- 
tends to  prove,  that  all  the  Good  or  Evil,  which  INIen  do,  is  produc'd  by 
a  Su]3erior  and  necessary  operation  of  God  or  Nature.  I  have  already 
mention'd  Williafn  Van  Bleyenbiirg,  a  Merchant  of  Dordrecht,  who 
enter'd  into  the  List  in  the  year  1674,^  and  refuted  the  impious  Book 
of  Spinosa,  entitul'd,  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus.  I  cannot  forbear 
comparing  him  with  the  Merchant,  whom  our  Saviour  speaks  of, 
Mat.  XIII.  45,  46.  Seeing  he  does  not  present  us  with  worldly  and 
perishable  Riches,  by  the  publishing  of  his  Book,  but  with  a  Treasure 
of  an  infinite  value,  and  which  shall  never  perish.  It  were  to  be 
wish'd,  that  there  were  many  such  Merchants  upon  the  Exchanges  of 
Amsterdam  and  Rotterdam. 

Our  Divines  of  the  Confession  of  Augsburg  have  also  distinguisht 
themselves  amongst  those,  who  have  refuted  the  impious  Doctrine  of 
Spinosa.  His  Tractatus  Theologico-Politicus  was  scarce  come  out,  but 
they  took  Pen  in  hand  and  wrote  against  him.  We  may  name  first 
Dr  Musceus,  Professor  of  Divinity,  7xX/c?ia,  a  Man  of  a  great  Genius, 
and  who  perhaps  had  not  his  like  in  his  time.  During  the  Life  of 
>  Bibliogr.  358,  n.  «  Bihliogr.  364. 


APPENDIX. 


435 


Spinosa,  viz.  in  the  year  1 704,  he  publish'd  a  Dissertation  of  twelve 
Sheets,  entitul'd,  Tractatiis  Theologico-Politicus  ad  Veritaiis  Lumen 
examinatus.'^  ''The  Theological  and  Political  Treatise  examin'd 
"  by  the  Light  of  Reason  and  Truth.  He  declares,  pag.  2,  3.  his 
aversion  and  horror  for  such  an  impious  Production,  and  expresses 
it  in  these  words.  Jure  merito  quis  dubitct,  num  ex  Wis,  quos  ipse 
Dcenion  adhumana  divinaque  jura  peiverteiida  magno  numero  conduxif, 
repertusfiierit,  qui  in  iis  depravandis  operosior  fuerit  quam  hie  Impostor, 
magno  Ecclesice  malo  &=  Reipublicce  detrimento  natus.  "  One  may  very 
"  well  doubt,  whether,  amongst  the  many  Men,  whom  the  Devil  has 
*'  hir'd  to  overthrow  all  Humane  and  Divine  right,  any  of  'em  has  been 
"more  busy  about  it,  than  that  Impostor,  who  was  born  to  the  great 
"  Mischief  of  Church  and  State.  He  sets  down  (pag.  5,  6,  7.)  with 
great  clearness  the  Philosophical  Expressions  of  Spinosa,  he  explains 
those  which  are  capable  of  a  double  sense,  and  shews  in  what  sense 
Spinosa  made  use  of  'em,  that  one  may  the  better  understand  him. 
He  shews  (pag.  16.  §.  32.)  that  when  Spinosa  published  that  Book,  he 
design'd  to  teach  that  every  Man  has  the  right  and  liberty  of  fixing 
his  Belief  in  point  of  Religion,  and  of  confining  it  only  to  such  things 
as  are  not  above  his  reach,  and  which  he  can  comprehend.  He  had 
already  (pag.  14.  §.  28.)  very  clearly  stated  the  Question,  and  shewn 
wherein  Spinosa  differs  from  the  Christians  :  And  in  the  same  manner 
he  continues  to  examine  that  Treatise  of  Spinosa,  and  confutes  every 
part  of  it  with  good  and  solid  Reasons.  There  is  no  doubt  but 
Spinosa  himself  read  that  Book  of  Dr.  Musceus,  seeing  it  was  found 
amongst  his  Papers  after  his  death. 

Tho'  several  Authors  writ  against  the  Theological  and 
Political  Treatise,  as  I  have,  already  observed  ;  yet  none  in  my 
Opinion  has  done  it  with  more  Solidity  than  that  Learned  Professor ; 
and  my  judgment  of  him  is  confirmed  by  that  of  many  others.  The 
Author,  who,  under  tlie  name  of  TJieodorus  Securus,  published  a  small 
Treatise,  entiluled,  Origo  AtJieismi,  says  in  anotlier  little  Book,  en- 
tituled;  Prudentia  Tlieoiogica.  "  I  do  very  much  wonder  that  tlie  Disser- 
"tation  of  Dr.  Alusceus  shou'd  be  so  scarce,  and  so  little  known  here 
*'  in  Holland.  That  learned  Divine,  who  writ  upon  so  important  a 
"  Subject,  shou'd  have  more  justice  done  him  ;  for  he  has  certainly 
"  had  a  better  Success  than  any  other.  Mr.  Fullerus,  {in  continuatione 
Bibliothcm  Universalis  &c.)  expresses  himself  thus,  speaking  of  Dr. 
Musfeus  :  "  That  most  famous  Divine  of  Jena  has  refuted  the  perni- 
"  cious  Book  of  Spinosa  with  his  usual  solidity  and  learning.     Cele- 

'  Bibiio^r.  362. 
K 


436  APPENDIX. 

berrhnus  ilk  Je/iensiufn  Theologus  Joh.  Musaeus  Spinosae  pestilentissi- 
viumfoetum  acutisstmis,^  queis  solet^  telis  coiifodit. 

The  same  Author  does  also  mention  Frederic  Rapoltus,  Professor 
of  Divinity,  at  Leipsick,  who  in  a  Speech  which  he  pronounced  when 
he  took  Possession  of  his  Professorship,  did  likewise  refute  the 
Doctrine  of  Spinosa.  I  have  read  his  Speech,  and  I  find  that  he 
lias  confuted  him  but  indirectly,  and  without  naming  him  :  It  is 
entituled,  Oratio  contra  JVaturalistas,  habita  ipsis  Kalendis  Junii  ann. 
1670,  and  it  is  to  be  found  in  the  Theological  "Works  of  Rappoltus 
torn.  I.  pag.  1386  and  Seq.  published  by  Dr.  John  Benedict 
Carpzoviiis,  and  Printed  at  Leipsick  in  1692.  Dr.  J.  Conrad 
Diirrius,  Professor  at  Aitorf,  followed  the  same  Plan  in  a  Speech,  ^ 
which  I  have  not  read,  but  I  have  heard  it  highly  commended. 

Monsieur  Aubert  de  Verse  published  in  1681  a  Book,  entituled, 
The  impious  Man  convinced,  or  a  Dissertation  against  Spinosa,  wherein 
the  Grounds  of  his  Atheism  are  confuted?  In  1687  Peter  Y7'on,  a. 
Kinsman  and  a  Disciple  of  Labadie,  and  Minister  of  those  of  his 
Sect  at  Wieiverden  in  Friseland,  writ  a  Treatise  against  Spinosa  which 
he  published  under  this  Title,  Impiety  Vanquished,  (ScC*  In  the 
Supplement  to  Moreri's  Dictionary,  in  the  Article  of  Spinosa, 
there  is  a  Treatise  mentioned,  entituled,  de  concordia  Rationis  &=  Fidei, 
written  by  Monsieur  Huet :  ^  That  Book  was  Reprinted  at  Leipsick  in 
1692,  and  \hQ  /ournalists  of  that  City  gave  a  good  Abstract  of  it,  (see 
Acta  Erudit.  an.  1695,  pag.  395)  wherein  the  Doctrine  of  Spinosa  is 
set  down  with  great  clearness,  and  refuted  with  great  Force  and 
Learning,  The  Learned  Mr.  Simon  ^  and  Mr.  de  la  Motte,^  Minister 
of  the  Savoy  in  London,  have  both  of  'em  writ  upon  the  same 
.subject  :  I  have  seen  the  Works  of  those  two  Authors,  but  I  don't 
understand  French  enough  to  judge  of  'em.  Mr.  Peter  Poiret  who 
lives  now  at  Reinsburg  near  Leyden,  published  a  Treatise  against 
Spinosa  in  the  second  Edition  of  his  Book,  De  Deo,  anima,  c^  malo  : 
That  Treatise  is  entituled,  Fundamenfa  Atheismi  eversa,  sive  specimen 
absurditatis  Spinosiance.''  It  is  a  work  which  very  well  deserves  to 
be  read  with  attention. 

The  last  Work,  I  shall  mention,  is  that  of  Mr  Wittichius,  Pro- 
fessor at  Leyden,  which  was  Printed  in  1690,  after  the   death  of  the 

•  The  printing  of  this  in  the  original  is  ahnost  a  curiosity ;  it  gives  Spinosa, 
pestilcntissium,  accutissiiii  is. 

-  Bibliogr.  358,  11.  ^  Bibliogr.  301.     The  name  should  be  de  Verse. 

'  Bibliogr.  368,  369  (Latin  and  French  edd.).  '"  Bibliogr.  358,  n. 

"  Qiuvre.  ^  Bibliogr.  382. 


U 


APPENDIX,  437 

Author,  with  this  Title,  ChrhtopJiori  Wittichii  Professoris  Leidensis 
^////-Spinosa,  sive  Exa»ie?i  Ethiccs  B.  de  Spinosa.'  It  was  sometime 
after  translated  into  Dutch  ;  and  Printed  at  Amsterdam  by  Wasbergen. ' 
'Tis  no  Wonder  to  see  that  great  Man  defamed,  and  his  Reputation 
stained  after  his  death,  in  such  a  Book  as  the  Continuation  of  the  Life 
of  Philopater,  It  is  said  in  that  Book,  that  Mr.  Wittichius  was  an 
excellent  Philosopher,  and  a  great  Friend  of  Spinosa,  that  he  kept 
correspondence  and  had  a  great  many  private  Conversations  with  him  ; 
in  a  word,  that  they  were  both  of  the  same  Opinion.  That  Mr. 
Wittichius  writ  against  the  Ethicks  of  Spinosa,  for  fear  of  being 
reputed  a  Spiuosist,  and  that  his  Confutation  was  Printed  after  his 
death  only,  that  he  might  not  lose  his  Honour,  and  the  Reputa- 
tion of  an  Orthodox  Christian.  These  are  the  calumnies,  which 
that  insolent  Author  has  advanced  :  I  don't  know  from  whence 
he  had  'em,  nor  upon  what  appearance  of  Truth  he  can  build 
so  many  Lies.  How  came  he  to  know  that  those  two  Philo- 
sophers kept  such  strict  a  Correspondence  together,  that  they 
saw  and  WTit  so  often  to  one  another  ?  We  don't  find  any  Letter 
of  Spinosa  to  Wittichius,  nor  of  Wittichius  to  Spinosa  among  the 
Letters  of  that  Author,  which  have  been  Printed  ;  and  there  is 
none  neither  among  those  which  remain  to  be  Printed  :  So  that  we 
have  all  the  reason  in  the  World  to  believe,  that  this  strict  Corres- 
pondence, and  the  Letters  which  they  writ  to  one  another,  are  a  meer 
fiction  of  that  Calumniator.  I  confess,  I  never  had  occasion  to 
speak  to  Mr.  Wittichius ;  but  I  am  pretty  well  acquainted  with  Mr. 
ZinwiertJian,  his  Nephew,  who  is  now  Minister  of  the  Church  of 
England,  and  who  lived  with  his  Uncle  the  latter  part  of  his  Life. 
What  he  told  me  upon  that  Subject,  is  altogether  contrary  to  what 
has  been  Published  by  the  Author  of  Philopater'' s  Life  :  ^  Nay,  he 
shew'd  me  a  Writing,  which  his  Uncle  had  dictated  to  him,  wherein 
the  Opinions  of  Spinosa  are  both  well  explained  and  confuted. 
What  can  one  desire  more  for  his  justification,  than  the  last  Work 
which  he  writ  ?  There  we  see  what  he  believed,  and  there  he  makes, 
as  it  were,  a  Confession  of  his  Faith  before  he  died.  Will  any  Man, 
that  has  any  sense  of  Religion,  be  so  bold  as  to  think  and  even  to 
publish,  that  it  was  all  meer  Hypocrisy,  that  he  did  it  only  that  he 
might  go  to  Church,  and  to  salve  appearances,  and  avoid  being 
accounted  an  Impious  Man  and  a  Libertine  ? 

If  any  such  thing  cou'd  be  inferred,  when  there  has  been  some 
Correspondence  between  two  Persons  ;  I  shou'd  not  find  my  self  very 

1  Bibliogr.  384,  385.  =   Bibliogr.  72-76. 


438  APPENDIX. 

safe ;  and  few  Ministers  wou'd  be  secure  from  the  Tongues  of 
Calumniators,  seeing  it  is  sometimes  impossible  for  us  to  avoid  all 
manner  of  converse  with  some  Persons,  whose  Belief  is  none  of  the 
most  Orthodox.. 

I  shall  willingly  mention  William  Deurhof,  of  Amsterdam^  and  I 
name  him  with  all  the  distinction  he  deserves.  That  Professor  has 
always  vigorously  assaulted  the  Opinions  of  Spi/iosa  in  all  his  Works, 
but  especially  in  his  Lectures  of  Divinity.  •  Mr.  Francis  Halma  does 
him  justice  in  his  DiitcJi  account  of  Spinosa  ;  ^  when  he  says,  that  he 
has  refuted  the  Opinions  of  that  Philosopher  with  so  much  solidity, 
that  none  of  his  Partisans  durst  hitherto  vye  strength  with  him.  He 
adds,  that  that  subtil  Writer,  is  able  still  to  confute  the  calumnies  of 
Philopater's  Life,  and  to  stop  his  mouth. 

1  shall  say  but  one  word  of  two  famous  Authors,  and  I'll  put 
'em  together,  tho'  they  are  now  set  one  against  the  other.  The  first 
is  Mr  Bayle,  so  well  known  in  the  Common-wealth  of  Learning,  that 
I  need  not  make  his  Encojuiiim  in  this  place.  The  second,  is  Mr 
Jaquelot  heretofore  Minister  of  the  Fi-ench  Church  at  the  Hague,  and 
now  Chaplain  to  the  King  of  Prussia.  They  made  both  of  'em 
learned  and  solid  Remarks  on  the  Life,  Writings,  and  Opinions  of 
Spinosa,  which  have  been  Translated  into  DutcJi  by  Francis  Halma, 
a  Bookseller  at  Amsterdam,  and  a  Scholar.  He  has  added  to  his 
Translation,  a  Preface,  and  some  judicious  Remarks  upon  the  Con- 
tinuation  of  F/iilopater's  Life  ;  which  deserve  to  be  read. 

There  is  no  need  to  mention  here  some  Writers,  who  have  very 
lately  opposed  the  Doctrine  of  Spinosa,  upon  account  of  a  Book, 
entituled,  Hemcl  op  Aarden,  Paradice  on  Earth,  written  by  Mr  va7i 
LeenJwff,  a  Reformed  Minister  of  Zwol,  wherein  'tis  pretended  that 
he  builds  upon  the  same  foundations  with  Spinosa.  Those  things 
are  too  fresh,  and  too  well  known  to  insist  upon  'em  :  I  therefore 
proceed  to  mention  the  Death  of  that  famous  Atheist, 

Of  the  last  Sickness,  and  Death  ^/Spinosa, 

There  has  been  so  many  various  and  false  Reports  about  the 
Death  of  Spinosa,  that  'tis  a  wonder  how  some  understanding  Men 
came  to  acquaint  the  Publick  with  it  upon  Hearsays,  without  taking 
care  to  be  better  informed  of  what  they  published.     One  may  find 

'  BibHogr.  190-207,  see  194,  ;/.,  where  Dr.  van  der  Linde  retracts  his  former 
opinion  as  to  Deurhofs  Spinozist  tendencies, 

2  Bibliogr.  'JO,  p. 


I 


APPENDIX.  439 

a    Pattern    of    those    falsehoods    in    the   Menagiana,    Printed   at 
Amsterdam  in  1695,  where  the  Author  expresses  himself  thus.' 

"  I  have  been  told  that  Spiiiosa  died  of  the  fear  he  was  in,  of 
"  being  committed  to  the  Bastille.  He  came  into  Fratice  at  the 
"  desire  of  two  Persons  of  Quality,  who  had  a  mind  to  see  him. 
."  Mr.  de  Pompone  had  notice  of  it,  and  being  a  Minister,  very  zealous 
"  for  Religion,  he  did  not  think  fit  to  permit  that  Spinosa  shou'd  live 
"  in  France^  where  he  might  do  a  great  deal  of  Mischief;  and  in 
"  order  to  prevent  it,  he  resolv'd  to  send  him  to  the  Bastille.  Spinosa 
"  having  had  notice  of  it,  made  his  escape  in  a  Fryar's  Habit  ;  but  I 
* '  will  not  warrant  this  last  Circumstance.  That  which  is  certain,  is, 
"  that  I  have  been  told  by  several  people,  that  he  was  a  little  Man, 
"  and  of  a  yellowish  complexion,  and  that  he  had  an  ill  Look,  and 
'■ '  bore  a  Character  of  Reprobation  in  his  Face. 

There  is  not  one  word  of  truth  in  this  Account ;  for  it  is  certain, 
that  Spinosa  was  never  in  France  :  And  tho  some  Persons  of  great 
note  endeavoured  to  have  him  there,^  as  he  himself  confest  to  his 
Landlords,  yet  he  assured  them,  at  the  same  time,  that  he  hoped  he 
wou'd  never  be  so  great  a  Fool  as  to  do  such  a  thing.  One  may 
also  easily  judge  from  what  I  shall  say  hereafter,  that  it  is  altogether 
false  that  he  died  of  Fear.  Wherefore  I  shall  set  down  the  Circum- 
stances of  his  Death  without  partiality,  and  I  shall  advance  nothing 
without  proving  it ;  which  I  can  the  more  easily  do,  because  he  died, 
and  was  buried  here  at  the  Hague. 

Spinosa  was  a  Man  of  a  very  weak  Constitution,  unhealthy  and  lean, 
and  had  been  troubled  with  a  Pthysick  above  twenty  years,  which 
oblig'd  him  to  keep  a  strict  course  of  Dyet,  and  to  be  extreamly  sober 
in  his  Meat  and  Drink.  Nevertheless,  his  Landlord,  and  the  people 
of  the  House  did  not  believe  that  he  was  so  near  his  end,  even  a 
little  while  before  he  died,  and  they  had  not  the  least  thought  of  it. 
For  the  22nd  ^  of  February^  which  happen'd  to  be  then  the  Saturday 
before  the  last  week  of  the  Carnaval,  his  Landlord  and  his  Wife  went 
to  the  Sermon  which  is  preach'd  in  our  Church,  to  dispose  every 
Body  to  receive  the  Communion,  which  is  administred  the  next  day 
according  to  a  Custom  established  amongst  us.  The  Landlord  being 
come  from  Church  at  four  a  Clock,  or  thereabouts,  Spinosa  went 
down  Stairs,  and  had  a  pretty  long  Conversation  with  him,  which  did 
particularly   run   upon   the  Sermon  ;  and  having  taken  a  Pipe  of 

'  Bibliogr.  98. 

2  Probably  on  the  occasion  of  his  visit  to  the  French  camp  in  1672. 

3  It  should  be  20th.    Colerus  corrects  himself  afterwards,  ad  fin. 


440  APPENDIX. 

Tobacco,  he  retired  into  his  Chamber,  which  was  forwards,  and  went 
to  Bed  betimes.     Upon  Sunday   ]\Iorning  before  Church-time,  he 
went  down  Stairs  again,  and  discoursed  with  his  Landlord  and  his 
Wife.     He  had  sent  for  a  Physitian  from  Amsterdam^  whose  Name  I 
shall   only   express  by  these  two  Letters,  L.    M.    That    Phisitian 
ordered  'em  to  boil  an  old  Cock  immediately,  that  Spmosa  might 
take  some  Broth  about  noon,  which  he  did,  and  eat  some  of  the  Meat 
with  a  good  Stomach,  when  his  Landlord  and  his  Wife  came  from 
Church.     In   the  afternoon  the   Physitian  L.  M.  staid  alone  with 
Spinosa^  the  people  of  the  House  being  returned  to  Church.'    But 
as     they   were    coming    from   Church,  they   were  very  much   sur- 
prized   to    hear,    that  Spinosa  had  expired    about   three  a    Clock, 
in    the    presence    of    that    Physitian,     who    that    very     Evening 
returned  to  Amsterdam  by  the  Night-boat,  without  taking  any  care 
of  the  Deceased.     He  was  more  willing  to  dispense  himself  from 
that  Duty,  because  immediately  after  the  Death  of  Spinosa  he  had 
taken  a  Ducatoon  and  a  little  Money,  which  the  Deceased  had  left 
upon  the  Table,  and  a  Knife  with  a  Silver  Handle  ;  and  so  retired 
with  his  Booty. 

The  particularities  of  his  Sickness  and  Death  have  been  variously 
reported,  and  have  occasioned  several  Contestations.     'Tis  said,  ist, 
That  during  his  Sickness  he  took  the  necessary  Precautions  to  avoid 
being  visited  by  those  whose  Sight  wou'd  have  been  troublesome  to 
him.     2dly,  That  he  spoke  once  and  even  several  times  these  words, 
O  God  have  mercy  vpon  me  miserable  Sifiner.     sdly,  That  they  heard 
him  often  sigh,  when  he  pronounced  the  Name  of  God.     Which 
gave  occasion  to  those,  who  were  present,  to  ask  him,  whether  he 
believed,  at  last,  the  Existence  of  a  God,  whose  judgment  he  had  great 
Reason  to  fear  after  his  death  ?    And  that  he  answered  'em,  that  he 
had  dropt  that  word  out  of  Custom.      'Tis  said,   4thly,  That  he 
kept  by  him  some  Juice  of  Mandrake  ready  at  hand  which  he  made 
use  of,  ^^'hen  he  perceived  he  was  a  dying,  that  he  drew  the  Curtains 
of  his  Bed  afterwards,  and  then  lost  his  Senses,  fell  into  a  profound 
Sleep,  and  departed  this  Life  in  that  manner.     5thly,  That  he  had 
given  express  orders  to  let  no  Body  come  into  his  Room,  when  he 
shou'd  be  near  his  End  :  And  likewise,  that  finding  he  was  a  dying, 
he  call'd  for  his  Landlady,  and  desired  her  to  suffer  no  Minister  to 
come  to  him ;  because  he  was  willing  to  die  peaceably  and  without 
disputing,  &•€. 

I  have  carefully  enquired  into  the  truth  of  all  those  things,  and 
ask'd  several  times  his  Landlord  and   his  Landlady,  who  are  alive 


APPENDIX.  441 

still,  what  they  knew  of  it :  But  they  answered  me,  at  all  times,  that 
they  knew  nothing  of  it,  and  were  perswaded  that  all  those  Circum- 
stances were  meer  Lies.  For  he  never  forbad  them  to  admit  any 
body  into  his  Room,  that  had  a  mind  to  see  him.  Besides,  when  he 
was  a  dying,  there  was  no  body  in  his  Chamber  but  the  Physitian  of 
Amsterdam,  whom  I  have  mentioned.  No  body  heard  the  words, 
which  'tis  said,  he  spoke,  O  God,  have  mercy  upon  me  miserable 
Simier :  Nor  is  it  likely  that  they  shou'd  come  out  of  his  mouth, 
seeing  he  did  not  think  he  was  so  near  his  Death,  and  the  people 
of  the  House  had  not  the  least  suspicion  of  it.  He  did  not  keep  his 
Bed  during  his  sickness  ;  for  the  very  day  that  lie  died,  he  Avent  down 
Stairs,  as  I  have  observed  :  He  lay  forwards  ^  in  a  Bed  made  accord- 
ing to  the  fashion  of  the  Country,  which  they  call  Bedstead.  His 
Landlady,  and  the  people  of  the  House  know  nothing  of  his  ordering 
to  send  away  the  Ministers,  that  shou'd  come  to  see  him,  or  of  his 
invocating  the  Name  of  God  during  his  Sickness.  Nay,  they  believe 
the  contrary,  because  ever  since  he  began  to  be  in  a  languishing 
condition,  he  always  exprest,  in  all  his  sufferings,  a  truly  Stoical 
constancy ;  even  so  as  to  reprove  others,  when  they  happened  to 
complain,  and  to  shew  in  their  Sicknesses  little  Courage  or  too  great 
a  Sensibility. 

Lastly,  as  for  the  Juice  of  Mandrake,  which,  'tis  said,  he  made 
use  of  when  he  was  a  dying,  which  made  him  lose  his  Senses ;  it  is 
also  a  circumstance  altogether  unknown  to  the  people  of  the  House. 
And  yet  they  us'd  to  prepare  every  thing  he  wanted  for  his  Meat  and 
Drink,  and  the  Remedies  which  he  took  from  time  to  time.  Nor 
is  that  Drug  mention'd  in  the  Apothecary's  Bill,  who  was  the  same  to 
whom  the  Physitian  of  Amsterdam  sent  for  the  Remedies,  which 
Spinosa  wanted  the  last  days  of  his  Life. 

Spifiosa  being  dead,  his  Landlord  took  care  of  his  Burial,  /o/in 
Rieinoertz,  a  Printer  at  Amsterdam,  desired  him  to  do  it,  and 
promised  him,  at  the  same  time,  that  he  shou'd  be  paid  for  all  the 
charges  he  should  be  at,  and  past  his  word  for  it.  The  Letter  which 
he  wrote  to  him  upon  that  Subject  is  dated  from  Amsterdam  the  6th 
of  March  1678.^  He  does  not  forget  to  speak  of  that  Friend  of 
Schiedam,  whom  I  have  mentioned,  who  to  shew  how  dear  and 
precious  the  memory  of  Spinosa  was  to  him,  paid  exactly  to  Vander 
Spyck,  all  that  he  cou'd  pretend  from  his  late  Lodger.     The  Money 

'  Sa  chambre  etoit  celle  de  devant. 

*  A  mistake  of  the  French  version  for  1677  ?  cp.  p.  422  above. 


442  APPENDIX. 

was  at  the  same   time  remitted  to  him,  as  Rieuwettz  himself  had 
received  it  by  the  order  of  his  Friend. 

As  they  were  making  everything  ready  for  the  Burial  of  Spinosa, 
one  Schroder,  an  Apothecary,  made  a  Protestation  against  it,  pretend- 
ing to  be  paid  for  some  Medicines  wherewith  he  had  furnished  the 
Deceased  during  his  Sickness.  His  Bill  amounted  to  sixteen  Florins 
and  two  pence.  I  find  in  it  some  Tincture  of  Saffron,  some  Balsam, 
some  Powders,  &=€.  but  there  is  no  Opium  nor  Mandrake  mentioned 
therein.  The  Protestation  was  immediately  taken  off,  and  the  Bill 
paid  by  Mr.  Vander  Spyck. 

The  dead  Body  was  carried  to  the  Grave  in  the  New  Church 
upon  the  Spiiy,  the  25th  of  February,  being  attended  by  many 
Illustrious  Persons  and  followed  by  six  Coaches.  The  Burial  being 
over,  the  particular  Friends  or  Neighbours,  were  treated  with  some 
Bottles  of  Wine,  according  to  the  custom  of  the  Country,  in  the 
House  where  the  Deceased  lodged. 

I  shall  observe  by  the  bye,  that  the  Barber  of  Spiiiosa  brought  in 
after  his  Death,  a  Bill  exprest  in  these  words  :  "  Mr  Spinosa,  oj 
"  Blessed  Memory,''  owes  to  Abraham  Kernel,  for  having  shaved  him 
"  the  last  Quarter,  the  summ  of  one  Florin  and  eighteen  Pence.  The 
Man,  who  invited  his  Friends  to  his  Burial,  two  Ironmongers,  and 
the  Mercer,  who  furnished  the  Mourning  Gloves,  made  him  the  same 
Complement  in  their  Bills. 

If  they  had  known  what  were  the  Principles  of  Spinosa  in  point  of 
Religion  ;  'tis  likely  that  they  would  not  have  made  use  of  the  word 
Blessed :  Or  perhaps  they  used  that  word  according  to  Custom,  which 
permits,  sometimes,  the  abuse  of  such  Expressions,  even  with  respect 
to  those,  who  die  in  despair,  or  in  a  final  Impenitence. 

Spinosa  being  buried,  his  Landlord  caused  the  Inventory  of  his 
Goods  to  be  made.  The  Notary  he  made  use  of,  brought  in  a  Bill,  in 
this  form  :  William  van  Hove,  Notary,  for  having  made  the  Inventory  of 
the  Goods  a?id  Effects  of  the  late  Sieur  Benedict  de  Spinosa.  His 
Bill  amounts  to  seventeen  Florins  and  eight  pence,  which  he  acknow- 
ledges to  have  received  the  14th  oi  November,  1677. 

Eebekah  of  Spiftosa,  Sister  of  the  Deceased,  declared  her  self 
his  Heir.  But  because  she  refused  to  pay,  in  the  first  place,  the 
charges  of  the  Burial,  and  some  Debts  wherewith  the  Succession 
was  clogged ;  Mr.  Vander  Spyck  sent  to  her  at  Amsterda?n,  and 
summoned  her  to  do  it,  by  Robert  Schmeding^  who  carried  his  Letter 

'  Fr.  'Mr.  Spinosa  de  bienheureuse  memoire;'  in  original  'Spinoza 
Zaliger.' 


APPENDIX.  443 

of  Attorny  drawn  iip  and  signed  by  Libertus  Loef\he  30th  oi  March, 
1677.  But,  before  she  paid  any  thing,  she  had  a  mind  to  know, 
whether  the  Debts  and  Charges  being  paid,  she  might  get  something 
by  her  Brother's  Inheritance.  Whilst  she  was  deliberating  about  it, 
Vaiider  Spyck  was  authoriz'd  by  Law,  to  make  a  publick  Sale  of  the 
Goods  in  question  ;  which  was  executed ;  and  the  Money  arising 
from  the  sale  being  deposited  in  the  usual  place,  the  Sister  of  Spinosa 
made  an  Attachment  of  it.  But  perceiving  that  after  the  payment  of 
the  Charges  and  Debts,  there  wou'd  be  little  or  nothing  at  all  left, 
she  desisted  from  her  pretentions.  The  Attorny,  John  Lukkats,  who 
served  Vander  Spyck  in  that  Affair,  brought  him  a  Bill  of  thirty  three 
Florins  and  sixteen  pence,  for  which  he  gave  his  Receipt  the  ist  of 
June,  1678.  The  Sale  of  the  said  Goods  was  made  here  (at  the 
Hague)  the  4th  of  November,  1677,  by  Rykus  van  Stralen,  a  sworn 
Cryer,  as  it  appears  by  his  Account,  bearing  the  same  Date. 

One  needs  only  cast  one's  Eyes  upon  that  Account,  to  perceive 
that  it  was  the  Inventory  of  a  true  Philosopher  :  It  contains  only 
some  small  Books,  some  Cuts,  some  pieces  of  polished  Glass,  some 
Instruments  to  poHsh  them,  &^c. 

It  appears  likewise,  by  his  Cloaths,  how  good  a  Husband  he  was. 
A  Camlet  Cloak,  and  a  pair  of  Breeches  were  sold  for  twenty  one 
Florins  and  fourteen  pence,  another  grey  Cloak,  twelve  Florins 
and  fourteen  pence,  four  Sheets,  six  Florins  and  eight  pence, 
seven  Shirts,  nine  Florins  and  six  pence,  one  Bed  fiveteen  Florins, 
nineteen  Bands,  one  Florin  and  eleven  pence,  five  Handkerchiefs, 
twelve  pence,  two  red  Curtains,  a  Counter-pain,  and  a  little  Blanket, 
six  Florins  :  And  all  his  Plate,  consisted  of  one  Pair  of  Silver- 
Buckles,  which  were  sold,  two  Florins.  The  whole  Sale  of  the 
Goods  amounted  to  four  hundred  Florins  and  thirteen  Pence  ;  and 
the  charges  of  the  Sale  being  deducted,  there  remained  three 
hundred  ninety  Florins  and  fourteen  pence. 

These  are  all  the  particulars  I  cou'd  learn  about  the  Life  and 
Death  of  Spitiosa  :  He  was  forty  four  years,  two  months  and  twenty 
seven  days  old,  when  he  died;  which  happen'd  the  21st  of 
February,  1677,  and  he  was  buried  the  25th  of  the  same  month. 


FINIS. 


444  APPENDIX. 


APPENDIX    B. 

The  following  is  the  text  of  the  ordinance  condemning  the 
Tractatus  Theologico- Politicus.  That  of  June  25,  1678,  condemning 
the  Opera  Fost/nmia,  is  to  be  found  at  p.  525  of  the  sam.e  book  •  but 
inasmuch  as  it  is  also  reprinted  in  Van  der  Linde's  '  Bibliografie,' 
no.  24,  it  is  not  given  here.  I  have  not  thought  it  needful  to  add  a 
translation. 

Groot  Placaet  Boeck  {in's  Graven  Hage,  1683)  3</<?  Deel,  p.  523. 

Placaet  van  den  Hove  van  Hollandt  tegen  de  Sociniaensche  Boecken 
Leviathan  en  andere.     In  date  den  negenthienden  July,  1674. 

Wilhem  Hendrick,  by  der  gratien  Codes  Prince  van  Orange 
ende  Nassau,  Grave  van  Catzenellebogen,  Vianden,  Diest,  Lingen, 

Mceurs,  Buyren,  Leerdam,  «S:c Midtsgaders  den    President 

ende  Raeden  over  Hollandt  ende  West-Vrieslandt  :  Alsoo  Wy  in 
ervaringe  komen,  dat  t'zedert  eenigen  tijdt  herwaerts  verscheyde 
Sociniaensche  ende  andere  schadelijcke  Boecken,  met  den  Druck  zijn 
gemeen  gemaeckt,  ende  noch  dagelijcx  werden  gedivulgeert  ende 
verkocht,  als  daer  zijn  de  Boecken  genaemt  de  Leviathan,  Bibliotheca 
Fratrum  Folonoriafi,  quos  7aiita?-tos  vocant,  Philosophia  Sacra  Scripturce 
mterpres :  als  mede  Tractatus  Theologico  Politicus,  ende  dat  Wy  naer 
examinatie  van  den  inhouden  van  dien  bevinden,  niet  alleen  dat  de 
selve  renverseren  de  Leere  van  de  ware  Christelijcke  Gereformeerde 
Religie,  nemaer  oock  overvloeyen  van  alle  lasteringen  tegens  Godt, 
ende  syne  Eygenschappen,  ende  des  selfs  aenbiddelijcke  Drie 
Eenigheydt,  tegens  de  Godtheydt  Jesu  Christi,  ende  syne  Ware 
voldoeninge ;  midtsgaders  de  fondamentele  Hooft-Poincten  van  de 
voorschreve  Ware  Christelijcke  Religie,  ende  in  effecte  d'authoriteyt 
van  de  Heylige  Schrifture,  t'eenemael  soo  veel  in  haer  is  in  vilipendie, 
en  de  swacke  ende  niet  wel  gefondeerde  gemoederen  in  twijfelinge 
trachten  te  brengen,  alles  directelijck  jegens  iterative  Resolutien  ende 


APPENDIX.  445 

Placaten  van  den  Lande  daer  jegens  ge-emaneert.  Soo  ist,  Dat  wy 
tot  voorkominge  van  dit  schadelijck  Vergift,  ende  om  soo  veel 
mogelijck  te  beletten,  dat  daer  doorniemant  en  moge  werden  misleyt, 
hebben  geoordeelt  van  Onsen  plicht  de  voorsz.  Boecken  te  verklaren 
soodanigh  als  voorsz.  is,  ende  te  decrieren  voor  Gods-lasterlijcke  en 
Ziel-verdeffelijcke  Boecken,  vol  van  ongefondeerde  en  dangereuse 
stellingen  en  grouwelen,  tot  naedeel  van  de  Ware  Religie  ende  Ker- 
chendienst.  Verliedende  dien-volgende  als  noch  by  desen  alien  ende 
een  yegelijcken,  de  selve  of  dier-gelijcke  te  Drucken,  divulgeeren  ofte 
verkoopen,  op  Auctien  ofte  andersints,  op  peyne  by  de  Placaten  van 
den  Lande,  ende  specialijck  dat  van  den  negenthienden  September 
1653,  daer  toe  ghestatueert :  Lastende  een  yeder  die  dit  aengaet, 
hem  daer  na  te  reguleren,  ende  dat  desen  sal  worden  gepubliceert  en 
alomme  geaffigeert,  daer  het  behoort,  ende  in  gelijcke  saecken  te 
geschieden  gebruyckelijck  is.  Gegeven  onde  het  Zegel  van  Justicie 
hier  onder  opgedruckt,  op  den  negenthienden  Julij,  1674.  Onder 
stondt,  In  kennisse  van  My.     Was  gheteeckent, 

Ad.  Pots. 


» 


446  APPENDIX. 


APPENDIX   C. 

Letters  not  contained  in  Spinozds  published  works. 

T.  Prof.  Land  has  recently  discovered  that  the  Dutch  originals  of 
two  of  Spinoza's  letters  to  Blyenbergh  were  printed  in  an  old 
periodical  {Boekzaal  der geleerde  H^erreid)  as  long  ago  as  1705.  One 
of  these  (Ep.  32  in  Latin  version),  had  been  lost  sight  of  ever  since. 
The  other  (Ep.  38)  had  meanwhile  been  recovered  by  Dr.  van  Vloten 
and  printed  in  his  Supplemcntum.  The  final  paragraph  of  Ep,  32 
was  omitted  in  the  Latin  version  of  the  Opera  Posthuma,  but  is  not 
without  interest,  as  it  shows  conclusively  that  Spinoza  wrote  Dutch 
with  difticulty  and  regarded  it  as  a  foreign  language.^  This  portion  is 
here  reprinted  from  Prof  Land's  paper  '  Over  de  eerste  uitgaven  der 
brieven  van  Spinoza,'  Amsterdam,  1879  • — 

Dit  is  myn  Heer  al  wat  ik  nu  weet  by  te  brenge  om  U.  E.  op  sijn 
vraag  te  aantwoorde.  nu  wensch  ik  niet  hooger,  als  dat  het  U.  E. 
mocht  voldoen.  doch  indien  U.  E.  noch  swaarigheyt  vint ;  so  versoek 
ik  dat  ik  die  00k  mach  weeten,  om  te  sien,  of  ik  die  sow  konnen 
wegh  neemen.  U.  E.  hoeft  van  sijn  kant  niet  te  schroomen,  maar 
so  lang  hem  dunkt  niet  voldaan  te  syn,  so  heb  ik  niet  liever  als  de 
reed  en  daar  van  te  weete,  op  dat  eindelyk  de  waarheit  mocht  blyke. 
ik  wenschte  wel  dat  ik  in  de  taal,  waar  mee  ik  op  gebrocht  ben,  mocht 
schryven.  ik  sow  mogelyk  myn  gedaghte  beeter  konnen  uytdrukke, 
doch  U.  E.  gelieft  het  so  voor  goet  te  neemen,  en  selfs  de  fouten 
verbeetren.  en  my  te  houwe  voor 

U.  E.  toegeneege  Vrient 

En  Dienar 

B.  DE  Spinoza. 

Op  de  Lange  bogait  den  5  Januari  1665. 

Ik  zal  op  dese  boogart  een  drie  a  vier  weeke  noch  blyven,  en 
dan  meen  ik  weer  nae  voorburgh  te  gaan.     ik  geloof  dat  ik  voor  die 

'  This  throws  great  cloubt  on  the  account  given  l:)y  Colerus  of  his  projected 
Dutch  translation  of  the  Old  Testament,  ji.  433,  above.  The  same  statement  is 
made  in  the  '  Catalogue  des  ouvrages  de  Mr  de  Spinosa '  at  the  end  of  the 
Life  by  Lucas. 


APPENDIX.  447 

tyt  aantwoord  van  U  E  sal  krygen.  indien  de  afairen  het  niet  toe  en 
laate,  so  gelieft  U  E  na  voorburgh  te  schiyve,  met  dit  opschrift,  te 
bestellen  in  de  kerk  laan  ten  huyse  van  meester  daniel  tydeman  de 
schilder. 

Translation. 
This,  Sir,  is  all  I  can  now  contribute  to  answering  your  question, 
and  I  have  no  higher  wish  than  that  it  may  satisfy  you.  But  in  case 
you  still  find  any  difficulty,  I  beg  you  to  let  me  know  of  that  also,  to 
see  if  I  may  be  able  to  remove  it.  You  have  nothing  to  fear  on  your 
side,  but  so  long  as  you  are  not  satisfied,  I  like  nothing  better  than 
to  be  informed  of  your  reasons,  so  that  finally  the  truth  may  appear. 
I  could  have  wished  to  write  in  the  tongue  in  which  I  have  been 
brought  up.  I  should  perhaps  have  been  able  to  express  my  thoughts 
better.  But  be  pleased  to  take  it  as  it  is,  amend  the  mistakes  your- 
self, and  believe  me, 

Your  sincere  Friend 

and  Servant 

B.  DE  Spinosa. 
Lange  Boogart  (Long  Orchard,  Amsterdam) 

the  5  th  Jamiary,  1665. 

I  shall  stay  here  three  or  four  weeks  more,  and  then  I  think  of 
going  back  to  Voorburg.  I  believe  I  shall  get  your  ansv/er  before 
that  time.  If  business  prevent  it,  be  pleased  to  write  to  Voorburg, 
addressed  to  be  delivered  in  the  Church  lane  at  the  house  of  Mr. 
Daniel  Tydeman,  painter. 

2.  The  following  autograph  letter  of  Spinoza  is  preserved  in 
Victor  Cousin's  library  at  the  Sorbonne.  It  was  seen  in  Cousin's  life- 
time by  Saisset,  who  gave  a  translation  in  his  (Euvres  de  Spinoza 
(2nd  ed.  vol  iii.  ad  fin.)  but  did  not  publish  the  original  or  even 
mention  in  what  language  it  was  written.  The  Latin  text  is  now 
printed  for  the  first  time.  How  the  MS.  came  into  Cousin's  posses- 
sion is  no  longer  known,  but  there  is  no  reason  to  doubt  its  authen- 
ticity. Being  dated  as  well  as  signed,  the  document  seems  to  be  the 
letter  actually  sent,  not  a  draft  retained  by  Spinoza.  It  is  written  on 
one  leaf,  2i"ixi6-2  centimetres.  The  letter  and  signature  closely 
agree  with  other  known  specimens  of  Spinoza's  writing,  and  are  very 
neat  and  clear. 

The  following  signs  are  used  to  represent  the  state  of  the  MS. 
Italics  denote  interlineations  :  small  capitals,  writing  interlined  over  a 
complete  cancellation  :  square  brackets,  that  the  bracketed  words  or 
letters  are  cancelled  by  drawing  a  line  through  but  remain  legible. 


448  APPENDIX. 


Do.  Liidovico  Majero  S.P.D.  B.  de  Spinoza. 

Amice  suavissime 

Praefationem,  quam  mihi  per  amicum  nostrum  de  Vries 
misisti,  en  tibi  per  eundem  remitto.  Pauca,  ut  ipse  videbis,  in  margine 
notavi.  sed  adhuc  pauca  super  sunt,  quse  tibi  per  literas  significare 
consultius  duxi.  Nempe  i.  ubi  pag.  4  [ubi]  lectorem  mones,  qua 
ocasione '  primam  partem  composuerim,  vellem  ut  simul  ibi,  aut  ubi 
placuerit,  etiam  moneres  me  eam  intra  duas  hebdomadas  compo- 
suisse.  hoc  enim  prjemonito  nemo  putabit,  haec  adeo  clare  propbni,  ut 
[si]  quse  clarius  explicari  non  possent,  adeoque  verbulo  uno,  aut  altero,^ 
quod  forte  hie  ilHc  obscurum  ofendent,^  non  hferebunt.  2°.  vellem 
moneres  me  multa  alio  modo  quam  a  Cartesio  demonstrata  sunt 
demonstrare,  non  ut  Cartesium  corrigam,  sed  tantum,  ut  meum 
ordinem  melius  retineam,  et  numerum  axiomatum  non  ita  az/gerem. 
et  hac  etiam  de  causa  multa,  quse  a  Cartesio  nuda  sine  ulla  demon- 
stratione  proponuntur,  demonstrare,  et  alia,  quae  cartesius  [ojmissa 
fecit,  addere  debuisse.  denique  enixissime  te  rogare  volo,  amice 
charissime,  ut  ilia,  quse  in  fine  scripsisti,  in  ilium  homunculum  missa 
faceres,  [et]  ipsaque  prorsus  deleres.  Et  quamvis  ad  hoc  te  rogan- 
dum  multce  me  moveant  rationes,  unam  tantum  reddam,  vellem 
enim,  ut  omnes  sibi  facile  persuadere  possint,  hsec  in  omnium 
hominum  gratiam  evulgari,  teque  in  hoc  libello  edendo  solo  veritatis 
propagandse  desiderio  teneri,  teque  adeo  maxime  curare,  ut  hoc 
opusculum  omnibus  gratum  sit,  hominesque  ad  verse  philosophise 
studium  benevole,  atque  benigne  invitARE  omniumque  utilitati 
studere.  quod  facile  unusquisque  credet,  ubi  neminem  laedi  videbit. 
nee  aUquid  proponi,  quod  alicui  oftendiculo  esse  potest,  quod  si 
tamen  postea  vir  iste,  aut  alius  suum  malevolum  animum  ostendere 
veUt  :  turn  ejus  vitam,  et  mores  non  sine  applausu  depingere  poteris. 
peto  igitur,  ut  eousque  expectare  non  graveris,  teque  exorare  sinas, 
et  me  tibi  addictissimum  credas,  atque 

omni  studio  tuum 

B.  de  Spinoza. 
Voorburgi  3  augustl  1663. 

»  Sic, 

-  The  last  letter  is  an  0  altered  to  i,  or  i  altered  to  0,  it  is  difficult  to  say 
which  :  uno  aid  altera  makes  a  good  and  classical  construction  :  uni  aut  alteri 
would  possibly  not  be  wrong,  but  there  is  very  little  authority  for  the  dative 
governed  by  haereo  in  this  sense. 

»  Sic. 


APPENDIX.  449 

Written  across  on  inner  margin  : 

amicus   de   Vries  haac   secum   ferre  promisserat,*    sed   quia   nescit 
quando  ad  vos  reversurus  est,  per  alium  mitto. 

On  the  back  of  the  leaf  : 

his  tibi  simul  mitto  partem  schoHi  prop.  27.  partis  2.    sicut  pagina 
75  incipit,  ut  ipsmii  typographo  tradas,  et  denuo  imprimatur. 

Heec  qu^e  hie  mitto  debent  necessario  denuo  imprimi  et  [quamvis] 
14  vel  15  regulse  addi  debent,  quae  commode  possunt  intertexi. 

The  preface  in  question  in  this  letter  is  that  written  by  Meyer  for 
the  'Principles  of  Cartesian  Philosophy'  (see  p.  29  above). 
Spinoza's  directions  were  faithfully  carried  out.  I  can  offer  no 
definite  suggestion  as  to  who  the  homunculus  may  have  been  :  pre- 
sumably it  was  some  stubborn  opponent  of  philosophy  in  general 
and  the  new  Cartesian  doctrines  in  particular,  who  had  already  been 
engaged  in  controversy  with  Meyer. 

The  quarrel  cannot  have  been  with  Spinoza,  who  at  that  time  had 
published  nothing. 

Translation. 

Dear  Friend, — The  preface  you  sent  me  by  our  friend  De  Vries 
I  now  send  back  to  you  by  the  same  hand.  Some  few  things,  as  you 
will  see,  I  have  marked  in  the  margin  ;  but  yet  a  few  remain,  which 
I  have  judged  it  better  to  mention  to  you  by  letter.  First,  where  on 
page  4  you  give  the  reader  to  know  on  what  occasion  I  composed 
the  first  part ;  I  would  have  you  likewise  explain  there,  or  where  you 
please,  that  I  composed  it  within  a  fortnight.  For  when  this  is 
explained  none  will  suppose  the  exposition  to  be  so  clear  as  that  it 
cannot  be  bettered,  and  so  tliey  will  not  stick  at  obscurities  in  this 
and  that  phrase  on  which  they  may  chance  to  stumble.  Secondly,  I 
would  have  you  explain  that  when  I  prove  many  points  otherwise 
than  they  be  proved  by  Descartes,  'tis  not  to  amend  Descartes,  but 
the  better  to  preserve  my  order,  and  not  to  multiply  axioms  over- 
much :  and  that  for  this  same  reason  I  prove  many  things  which  by 
Descartes  are  barely  alleged  without  any  proof,  and  must  needs  add 
other  matters  which  Descartes  let  alone.  Lastly,  I  will  earnestly 
beseech  you,  as  my  especial  friend,  to  let  be  everything  you  have  written 
towards  the  end  against  that  creature,  and  wholly  strike  it  out.  And 
though  many  reasons  determine  me  to  this  request,  I  will  give  but 

'  Sic. 
G  G 


4SO  APPENDIX. 

one.  I  would  fain  have  all  men  readily  believe  that  these  matters  are 
published  for  the  common  profit  of  the  world,  and  that  your  sole 
motive  in  bringing  out  the  book  is  the  love  of  spreading  the  truth  ; 
and  that  it  is  accordingly  all  your  study  to  make  the  work  acceptable  to 
all,  to  bid  men  with  all  courtesy  to  the  pursuit  of  genuine  philosophy, 
and  to  consult  their  common  advantage.  Which  every  man  will  be 
ready  to  think  when  he  sees  that  no  one  is  attacked,  nor  anything 
advanced  where  any  man  can  find  the  least  offence.  Notwithstand- 
ing, if  afterwards  the  person  you  know  of,  or  any  other,  be  minded 
to  display  his  ill  will,  then  you  may  portray  his  life  and  character, 
and  gain  applause  by  it.  So  I  ask  that  you  will  not  refuse  to  be 
patient  thus  far,  and  suffer  yourself  to  be  entreated,  and  believe  me 
wholly  bounden  to  you,  and 

Yours  with  all  affection, 

B.  DE  Spinoza. 

Voorburg,  Aug.  3,  1663. 

Our  friend  De  Vries  had  promised  to  take  this  with  him  ;  but 
seeing  he  knows  not  when  he  will  return  to  you,  I  send  it  by  another 
hand. 

Along  with  this  I  send  you  part  of  the  scholium  to  prop.  27, 
jjart  2,  where  page  75  begins,  that  }OU  may  hand  it  to  the  printer  to 
be  reprinted. 

This  matter  I  send  you  must  of  necessity  be  reprinted,  and  14  or 
15  lines  added,  which  may  easily  be  inserted. 


APPENDIX,  451 


APPENDIX    D. 

Circular  of  the  Spinoza  Cominittce. 

At  the  beginning  of  1876  the  following  circular  was  issued  in 
Dutch,  English,  French,  and  German  by  the  Committee  formed  in 
Holland  for  the  erection  of  a  statue  to  Spinoza  at  the  Hague. 

A    STATUE  TO   SPINOZA. 

The  wish  expressed  among  us  a  short  time  ago  and  assented  to 
from  many  sides,  to  see  a  statue  of  Spinoza  arise  at  the  Hague,  must 
find  an  echo  in  many  minds  as  the  February  of  1877,  the  bicentenary 
of  his  death,  is  drawing  near.  We  have  accordingly  resolved  to 
combine  for  its  realization,  and  to  invite  the  co-operation  of  foreigners 
as  well  as  of  our  own  countrymen. 

While  Germany  has  for  many  years  contemplated  the  bronze 
statue  of  Kant  at  Konigsberg,  Holland  should  no  longer  be  deprived 
of  that  of  Spinoza,  who  was  born  and  bred  on  her  ground,  and  who 
breathed  and  thought  in  her  atmosphere.  She  has  honoured  her 
painting  in  Rembrandt,  her  poetry  in  Vondel,  her  love  of  liberty  in 
William  of  Orange,  her  naval  glory  in  De  Ruyter,  her  literary  culture 
in  Erasmus,  her  medical  science  in  Boerhaave,  and  she  now  seeks 
to  add  to  their  bronze  statues  that  of  the  philosopher,  whose  writings 
— too  long  and  too  often  misunderstood — have  proved  replete  with 
life-giving  wisdom  for  many  countries  and  for  many  times. 

Unlike  Kant  at  Konigsberg,  Spinoza  had  no  academical  chair  at 
his  disposal,  nor  did  he  draw  around  him  a  circle  of  private  pupils, 
but  from  his  humble  apartment  on  ihe  Paviljoensgracht  at  the  Hague, 
where  he  spent  the  last  ten  or  twelve  years  of  his  short  life,  he  com- 
municated the  ripe  productions  of  his  mind  to  humanity  at  large. 
From  there  he  drew  the  attention  of  contemporaries  and  of  posterit} 
to  the  nature  of  man's  material  and  moral  existence,  and  to  tlie 
conditions  of  his  bodily  and  spiritual  welfare.  At  the  Hague  there- 
fore his  statue  ought  to  find  a  place,  by  preference  in  sight  of  that 


G  G  2 


4S2  APPENDIX. 

house  on  the  peaceful  spot  (still  remembered  as  a  canal)  which  by  its 
quiet  surroundings  is  well  worthy  of  the  calm  thinker. 

We  are  rejoiced,  though  scarcely  surprised,  that  so  many  distin- 
guished men  of  science  and  letters  in  different  countries  have  at  once 
expressed  their  willingness  to  join  with  us  in  the  accomplishment  of 
this  design.  They  have  understood  that  Spinoza  is  not  merely  a 
Dutch  but  also  a  world-wide  name,  and  that  his  mem.ory  deserves  to 
be  gratefully  honoured  wherever  civilization  extends.  We  confidently 
leave  to  their  care  the  promotion  of  our  object  in  their  respective 
countries,  and  we  trust  that  their  encouraging  example  may  stimulate 
our  and  Spinoza's  countrymen  to  more  strenuous  exertion. 

We  ask  the  support  not  only  of  the  students  of  philosophy 
who  can  appreciate  his  subtle  and  far-reachmg  thought,  but  also  of 
all  those  who  honour  that  courageous  striving  for  truth  and  for 
intellectual  liberty  in  which  his  moral  greatness  consists. 

Tlie  Hague,  January  1876. 

The  Spinoza-Committee : 

M.   D.  Count  Van  Limburg  Stirum,  Honorary  Chairman,  The  Hague. 

Dr.  M.  F.  A.  G.  Campbell,  Chairman,   The  Hague. 

Dr.  H.  J.  Betz,   Secretary,    The  Hague. 

Dr.  A.  Wm.  Jacobson,  Treasurer,    The  Hague.^ 

Prof.  J.   BosscHA,    The  Hague. 

i'rof.  J.   P.  N.  Land,  Leiden. 

Dr.  A.  Van  Der  Linde,  Arnhem. 

Mart.  Nijuoff,   The  Hague. 

Dr.  A.  Van  Oven,  Dordrecht. 

L.  FiNCOFFS,  Rotterdam. 

Dr.  J.  Rutgers,   The  Hague. 

Dr.  T.  J.   StieltjES,   Rotterdam. 

Prof.  B.  J.  Stokvis,  Amsterdam. 

Dr.  J,  Van  Vloten,  BloemendaaL- 

Dr.  J.  E.  De  Vrij,   The  Hague. 

I  add  the  Dutch  text,  as  being  the  original. 


EEN   STANDBEELD   VOOR  SPINOZA. 

De  wensch,  vdor  korten  tijd  openlijk  ten  onzent  geuit,  en  al 
aanstonds  van  verschillende  zijdeti  beaamd  en  toegejuicht,  om  eerlang 
in  den  Haag  een  standbeeld  voor  Spinoza  te  zien  verrijzen,  moet,  bij 
het  naderen  van   den  tweehonderdsten  jaardag  zijns  overlijdens  in 

'  Since  retired. 

^  Became  Treasurer  on  Mr.  Jacol:)son's  retirement. 


APPENDIX.  453 

Februari  1877,  in  veler  gemoed  te  luider  weerklank  vinden.  Dit 
bracht  ons  tot  het  besluit,  de  handen  tot  zijn  vervulling  ineen  te  slaan, 
en  00k  anderen,  buiten  en  binnen  's  land,  tot  krachtdadige  meewerk- 
ing  uit  te  noodigen. 

Ziet  Duitschland  reeds  sedert  jaren  zijn  Kant  in  brons  te  Kon- 
ingsbergen  prijken,  Nederland  mag  den  op  zijn  boden  geboren  en 
getogen,  en  zijn  dampkring  ademenden  en  denkenden  Spinoza 
niet  langer  derven.  Zijn  schilderkunst  heeft  het  in  Rembrandt, 
zijn  dichtkunst  in  Vondel,  zijn  vrijheidszin  in  Willem  van 
Oranje,  zijn  zeeroem  in  De  Ruiter,  zijn  geletterde  beschaving 
in  Erasmus,  zijn  medische  wetenschap  in  Boerhaave  gehuldigd  : 
het  voege  thans  aan  hunne  bronzen  beelden  dat  van  den  wijsgeer 
toe,  die  voor  landgenoot  en  vreemden  van  zijnen  en  later  tijd  in 
zijn  te  lang  en  te  vaak  miskende  geschriften  zoo  levenwekkende 
wijsheid  boekte. 

Had  hij  daarloe  niet — als  Kant  te  Koningsbergen — een  akade- 
mischen  leerstoel  ter  beschikking,— in  den  Haag,  waar  hij  de 
laatste  tien  of  twaalf  jaren  van  zijn  kortstondig  leven  doorbracht, 
heeft  hij,  van  zijn  kleine  woonvertrek  aan  de  Paviljoensgracht  uit, 
tot  geen  grooter  of  kleiner  tal  van  scholieren,  maar,  in  zijn  rijpste 
denkgewrochten,  tot  de  gansche  menschheid  gesproken.  Van  daar 
maakte  hij  tijdgenoot  en  nakomeling  op  aard  en  wezen  opmerkzaam 
van  's  menschen  stoffelijk  en  zedelijk  bestaan,  en  op  de  voorwaarden 
van  zijn  welstand  naar  hchaam  en  geest.  In  dien  Haag  moet  dan 
ook  dat  standbeeld,  liefst  in  't  gezicht  van  dat  Avoonvertrek,  op  de 
sedert  gedempte  stille  gracht  een  plaats  vinden,  door  haar  kalme 
omgeving  den  kalmen  rustigen  denker  ten  voile  waardig. 

Het  verheugt  ons,  al  behoefde  't  ons  waarlijk  niet  te  bevreemden, 
voor  de  verwezenlijking  van  dat  denkbeeld  al  aanstonds  den  vollen 
bijval  en  welkome  toezegging  hunner  medewerking  erlangd  te  hebben 
van  zooveel  uitheemsche  mannen  van  wetenschap,  als  zich,  blijkens 
hun  onderschreven  namen,  voor  verschillende  landen  bij  ons  hebben 
aanglesloten.  Spinoza  toch  is  geen  uitsluitend  Nederlandsche,  hij  is 
tevens  een  wereldgrootheid,  wiens  nagedachtenis  door  de  gansche 
beschaafde  wereld  dankbaar  moet  worden  gevierd.  Dat  hebben  die 
mannen  begrepen,  en  terwijl  wij  daarom  ook  vertrouwend  aan  hunne 
zorg  de  bevordering  van  ons  plan  in  hun  verschillende  woonstreken 
overlaten,  meenen  wij  te  mogen  verwachten,  dat  hun  opwekkelijk 
voorbeeld  onze  en  Spinoza's  landgenooten  tot  des  te  volvaardiger 
meewerking  zal  aanlokken. 

Wij  verwachten  haar  niet  enkel  van  de  beoefenaars  der  wijsbe- 


454 


APPENDIX. 


geerte,  die  Spinoza's  vernuft  en  denkkracht  roemen,  maar  van  alien, 
die  het  moedig  streven  naar  waarheid,  en  het  voorstaan  der  vrijheid 
van  denken  eeren,  waarin  zijne  zedelijke  grootheid  gelegen  is. 

's  Gravenhage,  Januari  1876, 

The  following  persons  gave  their  support  as  honorary  or  corre- 
sponding members  of  the  Committee.  In  some  cases  local  sub- 
committees were  also  formed,  and  in  this  country  the  London 
Committee  issued  a  somewhat  abridged  and  modified  version  of  the 
circular. 


Argentine  Republic. 

Dr.  D.  F.  Sarmiento. 
Prof.  H.  Weyenbergh. 

Austria. 

Prof.  Ad.  Beer. 
Graf  CoRONlNi. 
Dr.  Ed.  SiJss. 
Dr.  J.  Unger. 

Batavia  {Dutch  East  Indies). 

Dr.  F.  H.  Bauer. 

Mr.  L.  W.  C.  V.  D.  Berg. 

Dr.   P.  A.   Bergsma. 

P.    V,    DlJK. 

W.  P.  Groeneveldt. 

Mr.  T.   H.   der  Kinderen. 

Belgium. 

J.  DE  Gevter. 
Prof  J.   F.  Heremans. 
Prof  F.  Laurent. 
Dr.  A.  Willems. 

France. 

Prof  Claude  Bernard.* 

Prof  M.  Berthelot. 

Prof  Ad.  Franck. 

Prof  Paul  Janet. 

Dr.  Louis  J.  Koenigswarter. 

Dr.   E.  L1TTR6. 


E.  Renan. 

Jules  Simon. 
Prof  H.  Taine. 

Gcr>na}ty. 

Dr.  Berthold  Auerbach. 
Prof  J.  Bergmann. 
Prof  KuNO  Fischer. 
Prof   H.   Helmholtz. 
Prof  M.  Lazarus. 
Prof  C.  V.  Prantl. 
Prof  C.   Schaarschmidt. 
Prof   CiiR.   Sigwart. 
Prof   H.  V.   Sybel. 
Prof   Ed.  Zeller. 

Great  Britain  and  Ireland. 

Matthew  Arnold,  Esq. 

Prof  A.  Bain. 

Sir  B.  C.  Brodie,   Bart. 

Prof  Bryce. 

Prof  W.  K.  Clifford.' 

Prof  G.  Croom  Robertson. 

M.  E.  Grant  Duff,  Esq.,  M.P. 

T.  H.   Farrer,   Esq. 

J.  Fowler,  Esq. 

J.  A.  Froude,  Esq. 

Hon.  Mr.  Justice  Grove. 

Prof  T.  H.  Huxley, 

Prof  B.  Jowett,    Master   of  Ballio 
Coll.,  Oxford. 

W.   E.   H.  Lecky,  Esq. 


'  Since  deceased. 


APPENDIX. 


455 


G.  H.  Lewes,  Esq.' 

Rev.  J.  P.  Mahaffy. 

Sir  Louis  Mallet,  C.B. 

Rev.  Prof.  Marks. 

Rev.  James  Martineau. 

Prof.  Max  Muller. 

F.  Pollock,  Esq. 

The  Hon.  Roden  Noel. 

Lord  Arthur  Russell,  M.P. 

Shadworth  H.  Hodgson,  Esq. 

Herbert  Spenxer,  Esq. 

W.  Spottiswoode,  Esq.* 

J.  Hutchison  Stirling,  Esq. 

James ■'^LLV,  Esq. 

Principal  Tulloch. 

Prof.  J.    T  VXD  ALL. 

Italy. 
Prof.  A.  DE  Gubernatis. 


Prof.  J.  Moleschott, 
Prof.  A.  Vera. 

Russia, 

J.  Addens. 
Prof.  W.  BOLIN. 
Prof.  J.  J.  W.  Lagus, 
Prof.  G.  Teichmuller. 

Sivecfcn. 
Prof.  S.  Ribbing,  Upsala. 

Switzerland. 
Prof.   C.   Hebler,  Bern. 

United  States. 
Pi  of.   E.   L.   YoUMANS,  New- York. 


'  Since  deceased. 


President  of  the  Royal  Society, 


456 


APPENDIX 


w 


ft:! 


Oh 
< 


a, 
Co 

i 

I 

Co 

S 


•^  w 
s  o  o  w  '-' 


INDEX. 


'  Sir,  my  friend  jfohn  Baynes  used  to  say  that  the  man  who  published  a  book 
without  an  index  ought  to  be  damned  ten  miles  beyond  Hell,  zuhere  the  Devil  could 
not  get  for  stinging-nettles.''— Vi.^^^\  B.  Wheatley  :  What  is  an  Index?  p.  27. 


ABO 

A  BOAB,  Isaac,  de  Fonseca,  chief  of 
■^^     the  Amsterdam  synagogue,  6 

—  dehided  by  Sabbatai  Zevi,  29 
Abstraction,    warning   of   Sp.   against 

substitutmg  it  for  reality,  140 
Allen,   Grant,  on  utility  of  pleasure  as 

such,  225 
Amsterdam,  foundation  of  Jewish  set- 
tlement at,  3 

—  building     and     opening    of    syna- 
gogues, 4 

Andala,  Ruardus,  his  writings  against 

Sp.,  xxvii 
Apparitions,  Sp.'s  opinion  of,  59 

—  authorities  cited  for  by  a  correspon- 
dent of  Sp.,  61 

Aristocracy,  Sp.'s  ideal  scheme  of,  333 

—  his  conjecture  as  to  historical  origin 

of,  334 
Aristotle,   his   doctrine   of   intellectual 

immortality,  2S9 
Arnold,   Matthew,  his  essay  on  Tract. 

Theol.-pol.,  xl,  404 
Association,  doctrine  of,  in  Sp.,  196 
Atheism  repudiated  by  Sp.,  69 

—  characters  of,  in  Sp's.  opinion,  66 

—  definition  of,  356 

Attributes,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159,  163 

—  parallelism  of,  167 

—  theory  of,  criticised  by  Tschirnhau- 
sen,  171 

Auerbach,  Berthold,  his  translation  of 
Sp.,  xxi 

—  his  Spinozism  in  literature,  397 
Aiixilia  imaginationis,  i8r,  185 
Avenarius,   Dr.   Richard,    on    Sp.    De 

Deo,  &c.,  xxxix 


BOD 

Avenarius,  Dr.  Richard,  his  essay  on 
Sp.'s  philosophical  development,  91 

Averroes,  on  '  active  intellect '  and  im- 
mortality, 290 

Avicebron  (Ibn-Gebirol),  Jewish  Neo- 
Platonist ;  his  Fons  Vitae,  used  and 
cited  by  Giordano  Bruno,  103 


"D  AGON,  Francis,  Lord  Verulam,  his 
•^     belief  in  an  art  of  discovery,  321 

—  surmised    influence     of,     on     .Sp., 
126,  n. 

Balling,  Peter,  translator  of  '  Principia 
Philosophiac, '  56,  n. 

—  letter  of  Sp.  to  him  on  omens,  57 
Bayle,  Pierre,  his  article  on  Sp.,   xxiv, 

386 
Ben  Israel.     See  Manasseh  ben  Israel 
Berkeley,   George,    Bishop  of  Cloyne, 

his  mention  of  Sp.,  381 
Bernis,  Gardinal  de,  refutes  Sp.,  386 
Blackmore,   Sir  Richard,  his   confuta- 
tion of  Sp.,  xxxi 
Blunt's  Dictionary  of  Sects,  article  in, 

on  Sp.,  xxxv 
Blyenbergh,  William  van,  of  Dort,  his 
correspondence  with  Sjd.,  46 

—  published  refutations  of  Sp.,  56 
Body  and  mind,  identity  of,  and  paral- 
lelism of  phenomena,  in  Sp.'s  system, 

—  correspondence  of,  a  special  case 
of  parallelism  of  Attributes  in  Sp.'s 
system,  168 

Body,  the  human,  in  a  certain  sense 
eternal,  293 


4S8 


INDEX. 


BOE 

Boerhaave,  Hermannus,  Spinozist 
against  his  will,  376 

Bohmer,  Ed.,  his  discussion  of  the  In- 
finite Modes,  188 

Bontekoe,   Dr.  C,  his  intention  ~of-j:^_ 
futing  Sp.,  375 

Bouillier,  F.,  on  Descartes  and  Sp., 
xl 

Boulainvilliers,  Henri  Comte  de,  his 
edition  of  life  of  Sp.,  xxiv 

—  his  professed  refutation  of  Sp.,  xxiv, 
xxviii,  388 

Boyle,     Robert,    his    scientific   corres- 
pondence with  Sp.   through    Olden- 
burg, 28 
Bresser,  Dr.  J.,  letter  of  Sp.  to  him,  24 
Bril,  Jacob,  Hattemist,  376 
Bruder,  C.  H.,  his  ed.  of  Sp.,  xvii 
Bruno,  Giordano,  his  influence  on  Sp., 
87,  103-105 

—  his  use  of  Avicebron's  work,  102 

—  Descartes  perhaps  indebted  to  him, 

105 

—  his  mention  of  desio  di  consetvarsi, 
117,  n. 

Burgh,  Albert,  probably  identical  with 
young  man  mentioned  by  Sp.  in 
letter  to  De  Vries,  24 

—  announces  to  Sp.  his  reception  into 
Roman  Church,  75 

Busolt,  Georg,  his  monograph  on  Sp., 

xxxviii 
Byron,  Lord,  intended  to  write  preface 

to  Shelley's  translation  from  Sp.,  xx 


r^^SAR,  JULIUS,  his  ignorance  of 
gtmpowder  evidence  of  magic  in 
Albert  Burgh's  opinion,  76 

—  his   disregard    of  apparitions,    &c., 
cited  with  approval  by  Sp.,  62 

Camerer,  Theodor,  his  monograph  on 

Sp.,  xxxvii 
Cartesian,  Sp.  never  was,  30,  91 
Causa  proxima,  as  element  of  definition 

with  Sp.,  147 
Causa  sui  (Eth.  part  i.  def.    i),    159, 

160 
Cause,  why  not  defined  by  Sp.,  160 
Causes,  Final,  Sp.'s  attack  on,  349 
Charles    Lewis,    Elector   Palatine,    in- 
vites Sp.  to  chair  of  philosophy  at 
Heidelberg,  34 
Christ,  Sp.  on  his  office  as  compared 
\\-ith  prophets,  365 

—  appearances  of,   after  resurrection, 
367 


DES 

Chrysippus,  principle  of  self-preserva- 
tion stated  by,  117,  n. 

Clarke,  Dr.  Samuel,  his  criticism  on 
Sp.,  384 

Clifford,  W.  K.,  on  causation,  cited,  161 
"Coleridge,  S.  T.,  his  appreciation  and 
exposition  of  Sp.,  400 

Colerus,  Johannes,  his  life  of  Sp.,  xxii, 
and  App.  A 

Colliber,  Samuel,  cites  Sp.,  xxxiii 

Conntns,  meaning  of,  in  Sp.'s  use,  218 

Conde  (Louis  II.  de  Bourbon,  Prince 
de)  invites  Sp.  to  French  headquar- 
ters at  Utrecht,  36 

Condillac,  E.  B.  de,  his  criticism  on 
Sp.,  386 

Conservation  of  Energy.    See  Energy 

Craane,  Theodore,  professor  of  medi- 
cine at  Leyden,  the  circumstances  of 
Albert  Burgh's  conversion  communi- 
cated to  him,  75 

Creskas,  Chasdai,  of  Barcelona,  inde- 
pendent Jewish  philosopher ;  points 
of  resemblance  to  Sp.  ;  a  determinist ; 
quoted  by  Sp.  95,  96,  97 

Cudworth,  Ralph,  his  criticism  on  Sp., 
xxxi,  383 

Cutfeler,  Abraham,  376 


■pjA  COSTA,  Uriel,  his  career,  ex- 
■^-^     communication  by  the  sjmagogtie 

of  Amsterdam,  and  death,  8,  9 
Dante,  self-preserving  effort  of  all  things 

mentioned   in  his    '  De   Monarchia, ' 

117,  M. 

Davids,  T.  Rhys,  on  Buddhism,  cited, 

217 
Decalogue,  Sp.  on  revelation  of,  358 
Definition,  Sp.'s  theory  of,  146 

—  what  he  really  meant  by,  147 

De  la  Court,  Peter,  mentioned  by  Sp., 

Democracy,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  336 
Descartes,     Rene,     handbook    of    his 

Principles  of  Philosophy  prepared  by 

Sp.,  29 

—  the  same  enlarged  and  published 
(Renati  Des  Cartes  Principioi-um 
Philosophiae,  etc.,  Amst.  1663),  30 

—  scientific  element  in  Sp.  mostly  due 
to  him,  87,  106  sqq. 

—  his  doctrine  of  motion,  and  its  use 
by  Sp.,  no 

—  his  conception  of  matter  criticized 
by  Sp.,  115 

—  his  partial  statement  of  First  Law 


INDEX. 


459 


DES 

of  Motion,   and  Sp.'s   philosophical 
extension  of  it,  Ii6 

—  his  search  for  truth  distinguished 
from  Sp.'s  123 

—  his  theory  of  the  passions  criticized 
by  Sp.  215 

—  on  pineal  gland,  criticized  by  Sp., 
279 

—  perhaps  saved  Sp.   from  mysticism. 

Design,  the  argument  from,  246 
Desire,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  221 
Detenninism,  Sp.'s  doctrine  of,  202 

—  distinguished  from  fatalism,  204 

De  Vries,  Simon,  pupil  and  friend  of 
Sp.,  23 

—  his  early  death,  and  intended  bounty 
to  Sp.,  23 

De  Witt,  John  and  Cornelius,  their  rela- 
tions with  Sp.,  30,  36 

Duration,  distinguished  by  Sp.  from 
measurable  time,  182 


pARBERY,  MATTHIAS,  his  criti- 
■^^     cism  on  Sp.,  383 
Education,  hint  of  Sp.'s  view  of,  304 
Emotions,    Sp.'s    definitions  of,    233, 

243 

—  can  be  restrained  only  by  stronger 
emotion,  252 

—  only  the  active  are  good,  266 
Ende  or  Enden,    Francis  Affinius  van 

den,  Sp.'s  master  in  Latin,  12 

—  his  migration  to  France,  implication 
in  De  Rohan's  conspiracy,  and  exe- 
cution, 15 

Ende,  Clara  van  den,  daughter  of 
Francis  V.  d.  E.,  m.  Theodore  Kerck- 
krinck,  1671,  said  to  have  jilted  Sp., 
but  the  tale  improbable,  13,  14 
EndowTTients,  Sp.'s  opinion  of,  334 
Energy,  conservation  of,  not  discover- 
able a  priori,  113 

—  not  anticipated  by  Descartes  or  Sp., 

"3 

English  law  of  real  property,  how  much 

more     reasonable     than    Kabbalah, 

qjunre,  99 
Erastianism  of  '  Tractatus  Theologico- 

politicus,'  32 
Erdmann,  J.  E.,  cited,  173 
Error, 

{De  Int.  Evi.),  138 

—  belongs  to  imagination,  not  under- 
standing, 144 

—  Sp.'s  explanation  of,  198 


how  distinguished  from  fiction 


GAR 

'  Eternal  things '  of  Sp.  {De  Int.  Em.), 

what,  150 
Eternity,    perception   of  things   under 

form  of,  153 

—  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159 

—  distinguished  by  Sp.  from  duration, 
294,  301 

—  knowledge  under  the  form  of,  288, 
292 

—  of  the  mind,  280  sqq. 

'  Ethics  '  of  Sp.,  definitions  of  Part  I. 
translated,  159 

—  preface  to  Part  III.  translated,  214 

—  preface  to  Part  IV.  245 

—  Appendix  to  Part  IV.  translated, 
271 

Evil,  nature  of,  discussed  by  Sp.  in 
letters  to  Blyenbergh,  47,  53 

—  Sp.'s  definition  of,  251 

—  knowledge  of,  inadequate,  269 
Evolution,  theoiy  of,  Sp.'s  relation  to, 

223 

Explanation  included  by  Sp.  in  Defi- 
nition, 147 

Extension,  as  one  of  known  Attributes, 
164,  167,  171 

—  its  relation  to  Thought,  175 


PABRICIUS,  John  Albert,  of  Leip- 
-*■       zig    (1 668-1 736)  ;     his    Ddedtis 

argitmentorum,  etc.,  cited,  xxx 
Fabricius,  John  Lewis,  of  Schaffhausen, 

1 63  2- 1 697  ;  professor  of  theology  at 

Heidelberg,  writes  official   letter  to 

Sp.,  34 
Ficlite,   J.    G.,    traces   of   Sp.    in   his 

work,  397 
Fiction,    Sp.'s  theory  of   (in  De  Int. 

Em.),  137 
—  lawful  use  of,  in  science,  139 
Fischer,    Kuno,    his   account   of    Sp., 

XXXV 

Flint,  Prof.  R.,  on  Sp.,  xl 

Force,  comparative  insignificance  of,  in 

modern  physics,  82 
Freedom,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159 
Free-will,  Sp.  on,  205 
Frohschammer,  Prof.  J.,  on  Sp.,  xli 
Froude,  J.  A.,  his  essay  on  Sp.,  xxxv, 

404 


/^  ALTON,  F.,  on  Generic  Images, 
^^     201 

Garnett,    R.,    publication   by  him    of 
Shelley's  diary,  xx 


460 


INDEX. 


GEO 

Geometrical  method,  Sp. 's  purpose  in 

using,  216 
Geometry,   non-Euclidean,  bearing  of, 

on  Sp.'s  theory  of  Attributes,  174 
Gersonides    (Levi   ben    Gerson),    most 

Aristotelian  of  Jewish  philosophers, 

93 

—  his  doctrine  of  immortality,  291 
Geulinx,  Arnold,  on  occasional  causes, 

193 

Gfrorer,  A.,  his  ed.  of  Sp.,  xvii 
Gibbon,  Edward,  alludes  to  Sp.,  xxxiv 
Ginsberg,   Dr.   Hugo,   his  ed.   of  Sp., 

xviii 
God,  in  what  sense  cause  of  evil,  &c.,  53 

—  human  affections  not  to  be  ascribed 

to,  54 

—  theory  of  knowledge  and  love  of,  in 
the  essay  De  Deo  et  Honine,  91 

—  opinions  of  Maimonides  concern- 
ing, 94 

—  'things  immediately  produced  by,' 
108 

—  Motion  and  Understanding  called 
Sons  of,  by  Sp.  {De  Deo  et  Homine), 
109 

—  perfection  of,  how  understood  by 
Sp.,  136,  142 

—  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159 

—  freedom  and  omnipotence  of,  343 

—  will  and  understanding  not  predic- 
able  of,  344 

■ —  not  subject  to  a  moral  rule,  345 

—  summary  of  Sp.'s  conception  of,  352 

—  '  infinite  understanding  '  of,  what  ? 

353 

—  love  of,  in  self-understanding,  286 

—  the  intellectual  love  of,  300 

—  intellectual  love  of,  cannot  be  de- 
stroyed, 303 

Goethe,  J.  W.  von,  Sp.'s  iniluence  on 

him,  395 
Good,  the   chief,   Sp.'s  conception  of, 

125 

—  Sp.'s  definition  of,  251 

—  distinction  of,  from  right,  325 
Government  as  defined  by  Sp.,  328 

—  Sp.  and  Hobbes  on  origin  of,  315, 
316,  318 

—  perfection  of,  33 1 

—  federal,  Sp.  on,  334 

Gratz,  Dr.  H.,  his  Geschichteder  ynden 
used  and  cited,  ch.  i.  passim 

—  his  opinion  that  Sp.  was  born  in 
Spain,  78,  ;/. 

—  his  remarks  on  history  of  Kabbalah, 
97,   lOI 


IDE 


Gurdon,  Brampton,  Boyle  lecturer,  his 

criticism  on  Sp.,  xxxiii,  384 
Guyau,  M.,  on  Sp.,  xli 


TLTALLAM,  H.,  on  Sp.,  xxxv 

-*■-*-      Hann,  Dr.  F.  G.,  on  Descartes 

and  Spinoza,  xl 
Harmony,  pre-established,   192 
Hartmann,  Eduard   von,  his  criticism 

on  Sp.,  399 
Hate,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  226 

—  and  derived  emotions,  always  Tjad, 
263 

Hattem,    Pontiaan   van,   his  Spinozist 

mysticism,  376 
Hegel,  G.  W.  F.,  his  criticism  on  Sp., 

398 
Heine,   Heinrich,  on  Sp.  and  modern 
theology,  xl 

—  celebrated  Sp.,  397 

Helvetius  (J.  F.  Schweitzer),  (1625- 
1709),  alchemist,  his  supposed  pro- 
duction of  gold,  64 

Herder,  J.  G.,  his  dialogues  on  Sp., 

393 
Hobbes,     Thomas,     of     Malmesbury, 

Sp.'s  master  in  politics,  88 

—  mention  of,  by  Sp.,  313 

—  his  political  system  compared  with 
Sp.'s,  314 

—  agreement  with  Sp.  as  to  supre- 
macy of  State,  319 

Hodgson,  Shadworth  H.,  on  Causa- 
tion, cited,  161 

'  Homo  Politicus  '  (pseudonymous 
book),  312 

Howe,  John,  his  criticism  on  Sp.,  383 

Hume,  David,  his  '  Idea  of  a  Perfect 
Commonwealth,'  322 

—  ignored  Sp.,  382 

Huxley,  T.  H.,  on  Berkeley,  cited,  170 
Hu)-gens,   Christian,   his  just  estimate 

of  the  labour  still  awaiting  scientific 

discoverers,  75 


T  BN  EZRA,  his  biblical  criticism,  93 
—  sometimes  deliberately  reticent 
or  obscure,  ib.  n. 
Ibn-CJebirol.     See  Avicebron. 
Idea,  Sp.'s  use  of  the  word,  131 

—  ideae,  133 

— •  ambiguous  use  of  the  word  by  Sp., 
196,  199 

—  Sp's.   use  of  the   term    in   relation 
to  the  eternity  of  the  mind,  297 


INDEX. 


461 


IDE 

Idealism,   implicit,  of  Sp.,    173,    175, 

179 
Ideas,  some  necessarily  adequate,  199 
Identity  of  person,  Sp.'s  remarks  on, 

263 
Images,  generic,  Sp.  on,  201 
Imagination,  distinguished  from  Under- 
standing, 144 
Immortality,  Peripatetic  and  Averroist 

theories  of,  290 
—  popular  opinion  of,  306 
Iinposteurs,  Traitc  dcs  irois,  xxiii 
Infinite  Modes,  165,  187 
Infinity,  Sp.'s  doctrine  of,  180 
Innes,    Alexander,   professes   on  title- 
page  to  criticize  Sp.,  and  does  not, 
xxxiv 


TACOBI,  F.   H.,  his  statement  as  to 
^      Sp. 's  clearness,  178 

—  his  discussion  of  Sp.  with  Lessing, 

391 
Janet,  Paul,  on  Sp.,  xli,  405 

—  his  translation  of  Sp.  De  Deo,  Sec, 
xxxix 

Jans,  Dinah,  Hattemist,  376 

Jellinek,  Dr.   G.,  on  Goethe  and  Sp.,. 
xli 

Jesus,    son  of    Sirach,    on    finality   in 
philosophy,  408 

Jews,    establishment    of,     in    Nether- 
lands, 3 

—  their  settlement  recognized  by  law, 

5 

—  their  chief  men  at  Amsterdam,  6 

—  censure  and  final  excommunication 
of  Sp.  by  synagogue  of  Amsterdam, 

17 

—  success  of  Sabbatai  Zevi's  impos- 
ture, 28 

Joel,  Dr.  M.,  of  Breslau,  on  Sp.'s 
Jewish  forerunners,  xxxix 

—  his  monographs  on  medieval  Jewish 
philosophy,  cited,  90,  95,  97 

Judah,  the  Believer  (Don  Lope  de 
Vera,  &c.),  Spanish  convert  to 
Judaism,  burnt  1644  ;  his  constancy 
mentioned  by  Sp.,  78 


T<^  Ar.r.ALAII,     prevalence     of,     in 
^      Sp.'s  time,  10 

—  question  of  its  influence  on  .Sp.,  98 

—  ancient  sources  of,  99 

—  supposed  allusions  to,  by  Sp.,  100 


LES 

Kabbalists  of  Sp.'s  time,  his  opinion 

of  them,  99 
Kalisch,  Dr.  M.  M.,  on  Sp.,  xl 
Kant,    Immanuel,     the    value    of    his 

work,  83 

—  on    possible   subjectivity    of    Ding 
an  sich,  cited,  176 

—  difference  of  his  view  of  time   and 
space  from  Sp.s',  185 

—  neglected  Sp.,  394 
Kerckkrinck,  Theodore,  physician,  of 

Amsterdam,    ;;/.    Clara    Maria    van 
den  Ende,  supposed  a  rival  of  Sp., 

13 

Kirchmann,  J.  H.  von,  his  trapslation 
of  Sp.,  xxi 

—  his  commentary  on  Sp.,  xxxviii 
Ivnowledge,  degrees  of,  enumerated  by 

Sp.,  126 

—  organic  limits  of,  197 

—  degrees  of  (Eth.  Pt.  II.),  201 
Knowledge,  power  of,  towards  control- 
ling passions,  287 

—  '  under  the  form  of  eternity, '  288 
Kortholt,  Sebastian,  his  notice  of  Sp    , 

XXV 


J  AND,  Prof.  J.  P.  N.,  his  republica- 
tion  of  Dutch  letters  of  Sp.,  xvii 

—  his  monograph  on  Sp.,  xxxviii,  405 
Langenhert,  Caspar,  on  Sp.,  xxix 
Lavater,    Lewis,  of  Zurich,  author   of 

(inter  ah)  a  book  Dc spcdris,  etc.,  d. 
1585,  cited  by  unknown  writer  toSp., 
61 
Law,  general  nature  of,  261 

—  Positive,  325 

—  duty  of  obeying,  328 

Leenhof,  Frederick  van,  his  Spinozistic 

heresy,  377 
Leibnitz,  Gottfried  Wilhelm,   Freiherr 

von,    correspondence    with    Sp.    on 

optics,  72 

—  recommended    to    Sp.    by   Tschirn- 
hausen,  72 

—  visits  Sp. ,  72 

—  thought  an  infallible  scientific  method 
possible,  81 

—  his  correction  of  Descartes'  error  as 
to  motion,  112,  n. 

—  his  note  on   Sp.'s  'eternal   things,' 
151,  ;/. 

—  on  pre-estaljlishod  iiaiiuuny,  193 

—  his  depreciation  of  Sp.,  380 
Lessing,  G.  E.,  his  study  of  Sp.,  390 


462 


INDEX. 


LES 

Lessing,  G.   E.,  his  conversation  with 

Jacobi  on  Sp.,  391 
Lewes,  G.  H.,  on  Sp.,  in  Hist,  of  Phil. 

XXXV 

—  advanced  knowledge  of  Sp.  in  Eng- 
land, 404 

—  on  Causation,  cited,  161 

Lewis,  Sir  Geo.  Cornewall,  on  acquies- 
cence   in    established    governments, 

332 
Life,  Mr.   H.   Spencer's  definition    of, 

222 
Linde,  Dr.  A.  van  der,  his  Bibliography 

of  Sp.,  XV 
Locke,  John,   his  slight  knowledge  of 

Sp.,  381 
Lotsy,  M.  C,  his  monograph  on  Sp., 

XXX  vii 
Love,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  226 

—  of  God  in  self-understanding,  286 
the  intellectual,  300 

Lucas,  biographer  of  Sp.,  his  life  of  Sp., 
xxiii 

—  his  anecdote  of  Sp.  's  equanimity,  qu, 
whether  made  up  from  Epictetus, 
42 


TV/TACCALL,  W.,  translator  of  Tract. 

^^      Pol.  XX 

Machiavelli,  Niccolo,  Sp.'s  remarks  on 

his  Prince,  332 
Mahometanism,  no  schism  in,  according 

to  Sp.,  79 
Maimonides  (Moses ben  Maimon),  Sp.'s 

relation  to  him,  93 

—  philosophical  doctrines  in  his  '  More 
Nebuchim,'  94 

—  on  immortality,  290 

Maine,  Sir  Henry  Sumner,  his  correc- 
tion of  the  theory  of  sovereignty, 
320 

Manasseh  ben  Israel,  his  work  and 
character,  6 

Marranos,  persecution  of,  and  founda- 
tion of  Jewish  settlement  in  Nether- 
lands by,  2,  3 

Mastricht  or  Maestrirht,  Petrus  van, 
early   critic   of   Cartesians   and  Sp., 

XXX 

Materialist,  in  what  sense  Sp.  can  be 

called,  169,  n. 
Matter,  one  of  Sp.  's  '  eternal  things, ' 

—  Cartesian  definition  of,  115 
Maurice,  F.  D. ,  his  admiration  for  Sp., 

404 


MUL 

Maxwell,  James  Clerk,  his  criticism  of 

Cartesian  material  substance,  115 
Memory,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  196 
Mendelssohn,    Moses,    Lessing's    and 
Jacobi 's  correspondence  with,    390, 

391 
Method,  object  and  definition  of,  in  De 

Int.  Em.  134 
Meyer,     Dr.     Lewis,    of    Amsterdam ; 

edits    Sp.'s     Prindpia    Philosophiae 

and  Cogitata  Metaphysica,  30 

—  present  at  Sp.  's  death,  39 
Middleton,  C.    S.,    published  fragment 

of  Shelley's  translation  from  Sp.,  xx, 

403 
Milman,  H.  H.,  on  Sp.,  xxxv 
Mind,  the  only  certain  reality,  176 

—  and  Matter,  the  giilf  betweep  them, 
191 

—  attempts  to  explain  correspondence, 
192 

—  human,  composite,  195 
eternity  of,  280  sqq. 

its     knowledge      of     the     body 

*  under  the  form  of  eternity,'  297 

—  eternity  of,    paired  with  capacity  of 
body,  303 

Mode,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159 
Modes  of  Substance,  164 

—  the  Infinite,  of  Sp.'s  system,    152, 
165,  187 

Monarchy,  Sp.  's  ideal  scheme  of,  333 
Montesquieu,     Charles    de     Secondat, 
Baron  de,  allusion  to  Sp.'s  letters  by, 

389 
Morality,    essentially    social    in    Sp.'s 
\'iew,  86 

—  social  character  of,  255 

—  not  dependent  on  philosophy,  285 

—  Positive,  what,  325 

not  distinctly  recognized  by  Sp., 

326 

—  transcendental,  347 

'More    Nebuchim,'    of    Maimonides, 

cited,  94,  loi 
Morteira,    Saul    Levi,     Sp.'s    reputed 

teacher,  6 
Moses    of    Cordova,    passage    of    his 

Kabbalistic  commentary  supposed  to 

be  referred  to  by  Sp.,  100 
Motion,  Cartesian  theory  of,  109  sqq. 

—  quantity  of,  assumed    constant    by 
Descartes  and  Sp.,  no 

—  one  of  Sp.'s  '  eternal  things,'  152 
Miiller,  Johannes,  on  Sp.'s  account  of 

the  passions,  216 


INDEX. 


463 


NAT 

TsJATURE,  state  of,  261,  327 

-'-^  —  Law  of,  324 

Necessity,  doctrine  of,  its  advantages, 
according  to  Sp.,  210 

Neustadt  i^?),  common  friend  of  Sp. 
and  L.  van  Velthuysen,  71 

New  Christians  :  Jewish  converts  in 
Spain  so  called,  2 

—  persecution  of,  2 

■ —  exodus  to  Netherlands,  3 

Nominalism  of  Sp.,  49,  146,  151 

Nourrisson,  E.,  on  Sp.,  xli 

Novalis  (F.  von  Hardenberg),  cele- 
brated Sp.,  397 

Number,  Sp.'s  account  of,  181 


QBJECTIVE,  meaning  of  term  in 

Sp.'s  time,  128,  n. 
Oldenburg,    Henry,   first  secretary   of 
Royal  Society,  25 

—  his  correspondence  with  Sp.  :  va- 
liant in  exhorting  Sp.  to  publish  his 
works,  26 

—  correspondence  with  Sp.  on  the 
Resurrection,  etc.,  366 

Omens,  letter  of  Sp.  concerning,  57 
Omnipotence,    involves    necessity    ac- 
cording to  Sp.,  343 
'  Opera  Posthuma '  of  Sp. ,  their  publi- 
cation, 40 

—  condemned  by  authority,  41 
Orobio,    Isaac,     de    Castro,    Spanish - 

Jewish  physician  :  forwards  letter  of 
Lambert  van  Velthuysen  to  Sp.,  65 

—  anti-Spinozist  375 


pAIN,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  224 

-•-  —  as  such,  always  bad  ace.  to  Sp., 

252 
Pantheism,  a  vague  term,  355 
Passions,  Sp.'s  theory  of,  214  sijq. 
Paulus,  H.  E.  G.,  his  ed.  of  Sp.,  xvii 
Perception,    no   definite  theory  of,    in 

Sp.,  212 
Perfection,    identified    with    reality  by 

Sp.,  166 

—  Sp.'s  definition  of,  250 
Personality  of  God,  Sp.  on,  354 
Philosophy,  successive  schools  in  what 

sense  continuous,  120 

—  general  aim  of,  according  toSp.,  122 

—  separation  of,  from  faith  by  Sp.,  341 

—  Sp.'s     system    of.         See    Spinoza 
(Philosophy) 

Pleasure,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  224 


SCH 

Pleasure,  as  such,  always  good  ace.  to 

Sp.,  252 
Polignac,  Cardinal  de,  refutes  Sp.,  387 
Politics,  Hobbes'  and  Sp.'s  theory  of, 

314.  &c. 
—     See  Spinoza  (Theoiy  of  Politics). 
Prophecy,  Sp.  's  view  of,  360 
Prat,  J.   G.,  his  translation  of  Sp.   in 

progress,  xxi. 


"D  AMSAY,  Andrew  Michael,  Cheva- 

lier,  on  Sp.,  xxxiii. 
Rapp,  Christopher,  312,  n. 
Read,  Carveth,  cited,  161 
Reason,  the  life  according  to,  255 

—  supremacy  of,  in  Sp.  's  system,  258 

—  source  of  active  emotions,  267 
Rehorn,  Dr.  K.,  on  Lessing  and  Sp  ,  xli 
Religion,  what  Sp.  understood  by  it,  69 

—  consists  in  obedience,  according  to 
Sp.,  341,  368 

Remonstrants,  Sp.  's  life  with,  about  the 
time  of  his  excommunication,  17,  22 
Renan,  Ernest,  on  Sp.,  xxxviii,  405 
Resurrection  of  Jesus  Christ,  Sp.  on,  367 
Reus  y  Bahamonde,  E.,  his  translation 

of  Tract.  Theo..-pol,  xxii 
Revelation,  private,  not  to  be  alleged 
against  the  law,  319 

—  object  of,  according  to  Sp.,  341,359 

—  nature  and  authority  of,  360 

—  difficulty  in  ascertaining  Sp.'s  real 
view  of,  363 

—  to  Christ,  peculiar,  365 
Right,  natural,  what,  260 

—  in  Sp.'s  sense,  324,  327 

Rijcke,  Theodore,  notice  of  Sp.  by,  xxix 
Robinson,  T.  Crabb,  anecdote  of  Cole- 
ridge and  Sp.  reported  by,  401 


CABBATAI      ZEVI,      of     Smyrna, 
pseudo-Messiah,    after    deceiving 
many,  turned  Turk,  28 
Saisset,  E.,  his  translation  of  Sp.,  xxi 
—  on  Sp.,  xxxviii,  404 
Sarchi,  Carlo,  his  translation  of  Tract. 

TItcol.-fol.,  xxii 
Savigny,  Fr.  Carl  von,  cited  for  model 

definition,  148 
Schaarschmidt,  Prof  C,  his  ed.  of  Sp. 

Dc  Deo,  &c.,  xxxix 
Schelling,    F.  W.  J.   von,  his  criticism 

on  Sp.,  398 
Schleiermacher,   F.    E.    D.,  celebrated 

Sp.,  397 


464 


iMdex. 


SCH 

Schopenhauer,  Arthur,  his  criticism  on 

Sp.,  399 
Schweitzer,  J.  F.     See  Helvetius 
Science  and  religion,  370 
Self-conservation,    in    what  sense  first 

law  of  moral  nature  with  Sp. ,  86 

—  as  first  spring  of  action,  216 

—  as  foundation  of  virtue,  253 
Serrano,   Gonzales,  translator  of  Auer- 

bach's  Spinoza,  -xxi 
Shelley,  Percy  Bysshe,   began  transla- 
tion of  Traciatus  Theol.-poL,  xx,  403 
Sigwart,  H.C.  W.,  on  Spinozism,  xxxvii 
Sigwart,   Prof.   Chr.,  his  translation  of 
Sp.  De  Deo,  &c.,  xxxix 

—  his    opinion    as    to    Sp.'s    'eternal 
things'  considered,  151 

Society  necessary  to  man,  259 

—  foundations  of,  260 

Sorley,    W.    R.,    on   Sp.    and  Jewish 

mediteval  philosophy,  xxxix 
Sovereignty,  Hobbes  and  Sp.  on,  315 
Spencer,     Herbert,     coincidence    with 

Descartes  in  illustration  of  relativity 

of  motion,  no 

—  his   view  of  the  test  of  truth  com- 
pared with  Sp.'s,  130 

—  on  meaning  of  existence,  219 

—  his  definition  of  life,  222 

—  on  pleasure  and  pain,  224 

Spiick,  van  der,  Spinoza's  landlord  at 

the  Hague,  40,  42 
Spinoza,  Baruch  or  Benedict  de  : — 
Biography  : 

Portraits  of  Sp. ,  xxvi 

His  birth  and  parentage,  i 

His  early  studies  at  Amsterdam, 

II 
Latin  learnt  from  Van  den  Ende  ; 

knowledge  of  languages,  12 
Story    of    Spinoza's    love    for    his 

daughter,  13 
Censured  by  synagogue,  17 
Attempt  on  his  life,  17 
Excommunication,  17 
Civil  sentence  of  banishment   (?), 

20 
His  conduct  in  partition  of  inlierit- 

ance,  21 
Work    as   optician   and    intended 

scientific  writings,  21 
Friendship  wath  Simon  de  \'ries  ; 
declines  bequest  from  him,  23 

—  with  Dr.  J.  r)resser,  24 

—  with   H.    Oldenburg,  and  cor- 
respondence, 25-29 

Publication  of  the  '  Principia  Phi- 


SPI 

losophiae  '  and  '  Cogitata  Meta- 

physica, '  30 
Publication  of  '  Tractatus  Theolo- 

gico-politicus,'  3  I 
Declines  invitation  to  professorship 

at  Heidelberg,  35 
Visit  to  thi  French  camp  in  the 

invasion  of  1672,  and  danger  on 

return,  36 
Arrangements   for    publication   of 

Ethics  broken  off,  38 
His  last  illness  and  death,  39, 
His  manner  of  life,  41 
Letters  and  Writings  : 
List  o;  works,  xvi 
Modern  editions  of,  xvii 
Translations  of,  xix 
'  Principia  Philosophiae,'  &c.,  pub- 
lished, 30 
'  Tractatus   Theologico  -  politicus ' 

published,  31 
'  Opera  Posthuma '  published,  40 
Correspondence  with  Oldenburg, 

25-29 

—  with  William  van  BIyenbergh, 
46 

—  with  P.  Balling,  57 

—  with  unknown  writer,  on  ghosts, 

59. 

—  with  ^'elthuysen  through  Isaac 
Orobio,  65 

—  with  Velthuysen  directly,  as  to 
publication  of  former  letters,  71 

—  with  Leibnitz,  72 

—  with  Tschirnhausen,  73 

—  with  Albert  Burgh,  75 

Letter  to  J.  Jellis  on  alleged  con- 
version of  silver  into  gold,  64 

The  essay  Of  God  and  A/an,  its 
date  and  character,  how  far  Car- 
tesian, 90 

Contrasts  to  Sp.  's  later  work,  91,92 
Philosophy  : 

Slight  acquaintance  with  ancient 
philosophy,  64 

Reconciliation  of  God's  freedom 
and  moral  law  w'ith  necessity  of 
things,  67 

Leading  ideas  : 

Unity  and  uniformity  of  nature, 

84 
Monism,  86 

Self-maintaining  effort,  86 
Relation  to  Jewish  philosophers  : 
Generally^  87 

INLaimonides,  Ibn-Ezra,  Gerson- 
ides,  93 


INDEX. 


46: 


SPI 

Chasdai  Creskas,  95 
Influence  of  Kabbalah  denied, 
98  sqq. 

Relation  to  Giordano  Bruno,  103 

Adoption  from  Descartes  of  doc- 
trine of  Conservation  of  Motion, 
108  sqq. 

Suggestion  of  modem  physical 
ideas  in  his  language,  113 

Criticism  of  Cartesian  physics,  116 

Does  not  prophesy  theory  of  evo- 
lution, 117 

Derivation  of  the  principle  of  self- 
conservation  from  Descartes, 
117 

Divergence  from  Cartesian  dual- 
ism, 119 

Relation  of  the  '  De  Intellectus 
Emendatione'  to  the  Ethics,  121 

His  conception  of  the  chief  good  in 
De.  Int.  Em.,  125 

The  degrees  of  knowledge,  126 

The  test  of  truth    128-9 

Aims  and  problems  of  doctrine  of 
Method,  135 

Complexity  of  philosophical  pro- 
blems underrated,  140 

Theory  of  definition,  146 

'  Eternal  things,'  150 

Endeavour  to  put  new  life  into  old 
terms,  156 

Geometrical  form  of  exposition,  157 

Choice  of  geometrical  form,  157 

Definitions  of  Part  I.  of  Ethics,  159 

View  of  causation,  160 

Theory  of  causation,  161 

Of  Attributes,  163 

Modes,  what,  165 

Parallelism  of  Attributes,  167  /T 

How  far  idealist  ?  175 

Infinity,  time,  measurable  space, 
181 

Part  II.  of  ^MzVj- considered,  194 
sqq. 

Correspondence  of  human  body 
and  mind,  194 

Association  of  ideas  and  memory, 
196 

Determinism,  202 

Nature  of  free-will,  208 

Absence  of  theory  of  perception, 
212 

The  passions  (Part  III.  oi Ethics)  : 
springs  of  action,  216 

Definition  of  desire,  221 

Of  pleasure  and  pain,  224 

Relation  to  Darwinism,  223 


SPI 

Treatment  of  compound  emotions, 

229 
Definitions  of  the  emotions,  233 
Part   IV.    of  Ethics :    notions  of 

perfection     and      imperfection, 

245,  250  _ 
Leading  ethical  ideas,  253 
Resemblances  to  Stoicism,  255 
Virtue     founded    on    self-mainte- 
nance, 257 
Its  intellectual  character,  258 
Social  grounds  of  morality,  259 
Society  and  law,  260 
Useful  and  hurtful  emotions,  262 
Enjoyment  of  life,  264 
Passive  and  active  emotions,  266 
The  free  man,  268 
Collection  of  maxims,  271 
Part  V.  of  Ethics,  278 
Mastery  of  the  passions,  280,  283 
Power  of  knowledge,  287 
Knowledge     '  under   the   form    of 

eternity,'  288 
Eternity  of  the  mind,  292 
Sp's.  use  of  idea  in  relation  to  this 

doctrine,  297 
Intellectual  love  of  God,  300 
Excellence  of  body  and  mind,  303 
Virtue  and  blessedness,  306 
Theory  of  Politics  : 

Affinity  to  English  school,  310 
Views  on  practical  legislation,  313 
Theory  of  sovereignty  and  govern- 
ment, 316 
Ecclesiastical  claims  against  State 

disallowed,  319 
Scientific    treatment     of    political 

facts,  323 
General  ethico-legal  ideas,  325 
'  Natural     right  '     and    '  state    of 

nature,'  327 
Limits  of  government,  328 
The  best  government,  331 
Ideal  monarchy,  333 
Aristocracy,  333 
Democracy,  336 
Theology  : 

Necessity  of  God's  operations,  344 
Sp.'s  relation  to  popular  notions  of 

Deity,  346 
Rejection  of  Final  Causes,  348 
Difference  in  conception    of  God 

from  orthodox  theolog}',  353 
The  Mosaic  revelation,  358 
Scope  of  revelation,  359 
Distinction  of  Christ  from  Moses 

and  prophets,  365 


n  H 


466 


INDEX. 


SPI 

The    Resurrection     not     literally 
accepted,  367 

Sp.'s  view  of  practical  religion,  368 
Modern  Criticism,  etc.  : 

Early  attacks  on   Sp.   in  Nether- 
lands, 375 

Influence    on    mystical    sects    in 
Reformed  Church,  377 

Cartesians  and  Leibnitz,  380 

England  :    Berkeley  and   English 
school,  381 
Theological  criticism,  383 

Fiance  :  Theologians   and    Ency- 
clopaedists, 3S6 
Voltaire,  387 
Boulainvilliers,  388 

Germany  :  Lessing's  appreciation, 

391 
Goethe,  395 
Auerbach,  397 

^Modern  German  philosophy,  398 
English  revival  :  Coleridge,  400 
Recent     study    in    England    and 

France,  404 
Study     and     commemoration     in 
Holland,  405 
Spruyt,    C.    B.,    his    critique  of    Dr. 

Van  Vloten  and  Sp.,  xxxvi 
Spy  Nozy,  anecdote  of  Coleridge  con- 
cerning, 400 
State,  formation  and  power  of  the,  315, 
316 

—  supremacy  of,  318 

—  limits  of  its  power,  328,  330 
Stewart,  Dugald,  on  Sp.,  xxxiv 
Stoicism,  resemblance  of  Sp.'s  ethical 

doctrine  to,  88,  225 
Stoics,   self-preservation  recognized  as 
first  impulse  by,  117,  n. 

—  materialism  of,  mentioned  by  Sp, ,  140 

—  resemblances  to  Sp.  in  their  ethics, 

255 

—  coincidence  of  Sp.  with,  307 

Stolle,  Gottlieb,  his  information  of  Sp., 

XXV 

Stoupe,  Col.,  his  account  of  Sp.,  xxv 
Subject  and  object,  division  of,  190 
Subjective,   meaning  of  term    in    Sp.'s 

time,  128,  n. 
Substance,  Sp.'s  definition  of,  159 
Swedenborg,  Emanuel,  his  alleged  bor- 
rowing from  Sp.,  378 
Sympathy,  emotions  induced  by,  228 


HTAINE,  Hippolyte-Adolphe,  his  ac- 
cordance  with  Sp. ,  405 


UNS 

Teleology,  difficulties  of,  246 

—  Sp.  differs  from  Stoics  on,  255 
Theology,  natural,  some  difficulties  of 

248 

—  Sp.  on.     Sec  Spinoza  (Theology) 
Thing,  what  we  mean  by,  219 
Thought,  as  one  of  known  Attributes, 

164,  167 

—  really  swallows  up  other  Attributes, 

173,  175.  179 
Time,  Sp.'s  account  of,  iSi 

—  rational  knowledge  independent  of, 
in  Sp.'s  view,  184 

—  eternity  has  no  relation  to,  294 

—  existence  out  of,  an  unmeaning  ex- 
pression, 299 

Toland,    John,    his   remarks    on    Sp., 

385 
'  Tractatus  Theologico-politicus,'  publi- 
cation and  effect  of,  31 

—  Sp.    attempted    to   stop   translation 

of,  33 

—  condemned  by  authority,  34 

—  Sp.'s  position  in,  341 
'Tractatus  Politicus,'  Sp.'s,  account  of, 

liosqq. 
Treaties,  obligation  of,  330 
Trendelenburg,  Adolf,his  essays  on  Sp., 

xxxvii 

—  on  Sp.'s  'eternal  things,'  151 

—  on  Causation,  cited,  161 
Truth,  the  test  of,  128 
Tschirnhausen  (Ehrenfried  Walter  von) 

Bohemian      nobleman,     worker     in 
science  and  optics,  friend  of  Sp. ,  73 

—  borrowed  largely  from  Sp. ,  74 

—  metaphysical   correspondence    with 
Sp.,  74 

—  his  correspondence  with  Sp.  on  Car- 
tesian physics,  114 

—  criticizes  Sp.'s  theory  of  Attributes, 
171 

Turbiglio,   Sebastiano,  his  monograph 
on  Sp.,  xxxviii 


T  TNDERSTANDING,  its  distinction 
^      from    Imagination   fundamental, 

144 
Uniformity  of  nature,  leading  principle 

whh  Sp.,  136,  142 
Universals,  Sp.'s  treatment  of,  201 
Universe,   a    conception    siii   generis. 

Unseen  worlds,  involved  in  Sp.'s  Attri- 


butes, 167,  174 


INDEX. 


467 


V.   H. 

■y.  H.     See  De  la  Court. 
*       Veldhuysen   or  Velthuysen,    Dr. 
Lambert  van,  of  Utrecht ;  his  con- 
troversial letter  on  '  Tractatus  Theo- 
logico-politicus,'  65 

—  subsequent  letter  of  Sp.  to  him  on 
proposed  publication  thereof,  with 
answer,  71 

—  enlarges  and  publishes  his  arguments 
against  '  Tractatus  Theologico-poli- 
ticus  '  independently,  71 

Vera,  Don  Lope  de,  y  Alarcon  de  San 
Clemente  (Judah  the  Believer),  his 
conversion  to  Judaism  and  martyr- 
dom, 78 

Virtue,  essentially  active,  257 

—  its  own  reward,  306 

Vloten,   Dr.  J.   van,  his  work  on  Sp., 

XXXV,  405 
Voltaire,  his  various  remarks  on  Sp., 

387 


ZOH 
Vries,  Gerard  de,  his  allusions  to  Sp., 

XXX 


VyACHTER,  J.   E.,  his  attempt  to 

find  Kabbalism  in  Sp.    98 
Waeyen,  J.  van  der,  stated  to  criticize 

Sp.,  xxxi 
Weidner,  J.  J.,  early  critic  of  Sp.,  xxx 
Willis,  Dr.  R.,  his  book  on  Sp.,  xix 
Witte,  Henning,  his  notice  of  Sp.,  xxx 
Women,  Sp.  on  their  political  capacity, 

337 
Wordsworth,  William,  Coleridge's  talk 

with  him  about  Sp.,  400 
—  influence  of  Coleridge's  Spinozism 

on,  402 


VOHAR,    the    Kabbalistic    book    so 
called,  a  forgery,  100,  ib.  note 


-9 


LONDON  :      PRINTF.D     BY 
SPOTTISWOODE     AND     CO.,      NEW-STUEF.T     SQfARE 
ANP     PAKLIAMENT     STREET 


^ 


BINDING  SECT,   m  S     m 


PLEASE  DO  NOT  REMOVE 
CARDS  OR  SLIPS  FROM  THIS  POCKET 


UNIVERSITY  OF  TORONTO  LIBRARY 


3 

^^ofj    Pollock,  (sir)  Frederick,  bart. 

py        Spinoza